accidie also acedia,
apathy, listlessness, or ennui. This condition is problematic for the
internalist thesis that, necessarily, any belief that one morally ought to do
something is conceptually sufficient for having motivation to do it. Grice
gives the example of Ann. Ann has long believed that she ought, morally, to
assist her ailing mother, and she has dutifully acted accordingly. Seemingly,
she may continue to believe this, even though, owing to a recent personal
tragedy, she now suffers from accidie and is wholly lacking in motivation to
assist her mother. acedia, Fr. acédie,
tristesse, Gr. “ἀϰήδεια,” “ἀϰηδία,” Lat. taedium v. malaise, melancholy,
spleen, dasein, desengano, oikeiosis, sorge, verguenza. Through the
intermediary of monastic Lat., “acedia,” “weariness, indifference” (Cassian, De
institutis coenobiorum, 10.2.3; RT: PL, vol. 49, cols. 363–69), the rich Greek
concept of “akêdeia,” a privative formed on “kêdos” [ϰῆδоς], “care,” and
bearing the twofold meaning of lacking care (negligence) and absence of care
(from lassitude or from serenity), established well in the language —a concept
that belongs simultaneously to the communal and the moral registers. The Greek
was originally associated with social rituals; in philosophical Latin from
Seneca on, it was related to the moral virtue of intimacy, but its contemporary
usage has returned it to a collective dimension. Gr. “akêdeia” is
simultaneously part of the register of the obligations owed to others and part
of the register of self-esteem: this breadth of meaning determines the later
variations. On the social level, the substantive kêdos, “care, concern,” is
specialized as early as Homer in two particular uses: mourning, the honors
rendered to the dead, and union, family relationship through marriage or
through alliance; “ϰήδεια” (adj. “ϰῆδεоς”) is the attention that must be paid
to the dead, as well as the concern and care for allies, characteristic of this
relationship of alliance, which is distinct from that of blood and also contributes
to philia [φιλία], to the well-being of the city-state (Aristotle, Politics,
9.1280b 36; see love and polis); “ὁ ϰηδεμών” refers to all those who protect,
for example, tutelary gods (Xenophon, Cyropaedia, 3.3.21). Akêdês [ἀϰηδής]
qualifies in an active sense, in a positive way, someone who is exempt from
care and anxiety (Hesiod, Theogony, 5.489, apropos of the “invincible and
impassive” Zeus, but also, negatively, the serving woman or negligent man;
Homer, Odyssey, 17.319; Plato, Laws, 913c); in the passive sense, it designates
a person who is neglected (Odyssey, 20.130) or abandoned without burial (like
Hector, Iliad, 24.554). How can the lack of care, “akêdeia,” become a virtue of
the reflexive type? There is a twofold
sense of the term (transitive: care for others; reflexive: care for oneself).
The first movement toward the ethics of intimacy is determined by practical
philosophy’s reflection on the finitude of human life. The event represented by
death produces a sadness that seems to have no consolation. The moral reaction
to situations in which one finds oneself fearing such a finitude is presented
in an active and critical way in the ethics developed by Seneca in the
Consolations. Grace and purity can temper sadness (“Marcum blandissimum puerum,
ad cujus conspectum nulla potest durare tristitia” [Marcus, this boy, so
gentle, before whom no sadness can last]; De consolatione ad Helviam, 18.4).
But above all, it is the effort of reason and study that can overcome any
sadness (“liberalia studia: illa sanabunt vulnus tuum, illa omnem tristitiam
tibi evellent” [these studies will heal your wound, will free you from any
sadness]; De consolatione ad Helviam, 17.3). This view of internal control is
foundational for a style rooted in the culture of the South: the sober
acceptance of death, and more generally, of finitude. Acedia is conceived as
having a twofold psychological and theological meaning. First of all, it is a
passion of the animus and is therefore one of the four kinds of sadness, the
other three being pigritia, “laziness,” tristitia, “sadness” properly so
called, and taedium, “boredom.” In Christian monasticism of the fourth and
fifth centuries, especially in Cassian and the eastern desert fathers, acedia
is one of the seven or eight temptations with which the monks might have to
struggle at one time or another. Usually mentioned between sadness and
vainglory in a list that was to become that of the “seven deadly sins,” it is
characterized by a pronounced distaste for spiritual life and the eremitic
ideal, a discouragement and profound boredom that lead to a state of lethargy
or to the abandonment of monastic life. It was designated by the expression
“noonday demon,” which is supposed to come from verse 6 of Psalm 91. Thomas
Aquinas opposes acedia to the joy that is inherent in the virtue of charity and
makes it a specific sin, as a sadness with regard to spiritual goods (Summa
theologica, IIa, IIae, q. 35). Some place acedia among the seven deadly sins.
If it is equivalent to the more widespread terms “taedium” and “pigritia”, that
is because it is the result of an excess of dispersion or idle chatter, and of
the sadness and indifference (incuria) produced by the difficulty of obtaining
spiritual goods. Thus “desolation” is supposed also to be a term related to
acedia, and is often employed in spiritual and mystical literature——and it
subsists in the vocabulary of moral sentiments. The secular sense that the word
has acquired can make “acedia” the result of a situation of crisis and social
conflict. Acedia (derivedfrom the adjective “acedo,” from Lat. “acidus,” “acid,”
bitter) may be connected with the deprivation and need to which the poor are
subject. It involves the naturalization or loss of aura discussed by Walter
Benjamin, who draws on Baudelaire’s notion of “spleen” and on the phenomenology
of the consciousness of loss or collective distress that follows the great
upheavals of modernization (Das Passagen-Werk).Refs.: Benjamin, Walter. Das
Passagen-Werk. Vol. 5 of Gesammelte Schriften. Edited by R. Tiedemann.
Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1982. Translation by H. Eiland and K. McLaughlin: The
Arcades Project. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999. Meltzer,
Françoise. “Acedia and Melancholia.” In Walter Benjamin and the Demands of
History. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Achillini: essential
Italian philosopher. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice ed Achillini," per
Il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria,
Italia.
ackrillism: after J. L.
Ackrill, London-born, Oxford-educated tutee of Grice’s. Grice cites him in
“Some reflections on ends and happiness.” The reference is to Ackrill’s
exploration on Aristotle on happiness. Ackrill was Grice’s tutee at St. John’s
where he read, as he should, for the Lit. Hum. (Phil.). Grice instilled on him
a love for Aristotle, which had been instilled on Grice by Scots philosopher
Hardie, Grice’s tutee at THE place to study Lit. Hum., Corpus. Grice regretted that
Ackrill had to *translate* Aristotle. “Of course at Clifton and Corpus, Hardie
never asked me so!” Grice thought that Aristotle was almost being ‘murdered,’
literally, by Ackrill. That’s why Grice would always quote Aristotle in the
Grecian vernacular. An “ackrillism,” then, as Grice used it, is a way to turn
Aristotle from one vernacular to another, “usually with an Ackrillian effect.”
Griceians usually pay respect to Ackrill’s grave, which reads, in a pretty
Griceian way, “Aristotelian.” Grice commented: “A man of words, and not of
deeds…”
aconzio: essential
Italian philosopher. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice ed Aconzio," per
Il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria,
Italia.
Acri: essential Italian
philosopher. Resf.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice ed Acri," per Il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
actum: or ACTVM, as Grice
would spell it. Grice’s theory is
action-oriented. He often used ‘pragmatic’ to that effect. This is most evident
in his account of meaning. In the phrastic, “The door is closed, please,” the
ultimate intention is that the recipient performs the action of closing the
door. Grice saw action theory as the study of the ontological structure of
human action, the process by which it originates, and the ways in which it is
explained. Most human actions are acts of commission: they constitute a class
of events in which a subject the agent brings about some change or changes.
Thus, in moving one’s finger, one brings it about that one’s finger moves. When
the change brought about is an ongoing process e.g., the continuing appearance
of words on a , the behavior is called an activity writing. An action of
omission occurs when an agent refrains from performing an action of commission.
Since actions of commission are events, the question of their ontology is in
part a matter of the general ontology of change. An important issue here is
whether what occurs when an action is performed should be viewed as abstract or
concrete. On the first approach, actions are understood either as
proposition-like entities e.g., Booth’s moving a finger, or as a species of
universal namely, an act-type moving a
finger. What “occurred” when Booth moved his finger in Ford’sTheater on April
14, 1865, is held to be the abstract entity in question, and the entity is
viewed as repeatable: that is, precisely the same entity is held to have
occurred on every other occasion of Booth’s moving his finger. When actions are
viewed as concrete, on the other hand, Booth’s moving his finger in Ford’s
Theater is understood to be a non-repeatable particular, accidental property
action theory 6 4065A- 6 and the
movement of the finger counts as an acttoken, which instantiates the
corresponding acttype. Concrete actions are time-bound: each belongs to a
single behavioral episode, and other instantiations of the same act-type count
as distinct events. A second important ontological issue concerns the fact that
by moving his finger, Booth also fired a gun, and killed Lincoln. It is common
for more than one thing to be accomplished in a single exercise of agency, and
how such doings are related is a matter of debate. If actions are understood as
abstract entities, the answer is essentially foregone: there must be as many
different actions on Booth’s part as there are types exemplified. But if
actions are viewed as particulars the same token can count as an instance of
more than one type, and identity claims become possible. Here there is
disagreement. Fine-grained theories of act individuation tend to confine
identity claims to actions that differ only in ways describable through
different modifications of the same main verb
e.g., where Placido both sings and sings loudly. Otherwise, different
types are held to require different tokens: Booth’s action of moving his finger
is held to have generated or given rise to distinct actions of firing the gun
and killing Lincoln, by virtue of having had as causal consequences the gun’s
discharge and Lincoln’s death. The opposite, coarse-grained theory, however,
views these causal relations as grounds for claiming Booth’s acts were
precisely identical. On this view, for Booth to kill Lincoln was simply for him
to do something that caused Lincoln’s death
which was in fact nothing more than to move his finger and similarly for his firing the gun. There
is also a compromise account, on which Booth’s actions are related as part to
whole, each consisting in a longer segment of the causal chain that terminates
with Lincoln’s death. The action of killing Lincoln consisted, on this view, in
the entire sequence; but that of firing the gun terminated with the gun’s
discharge, and that of moving the finger with the finger’s motion. When, as in
Booth’s case, more than one thing is accomplished in a single exercise of
agency, some are done by doing others. But if all actions were performed by
performing others, an infinite regress would result. There must, then, be a
class of basic actions i.e., actions
fundamental to the performance of all others, but not themselves done by doing
something else. There is disagreement, however, on which actions are basic.
Some theories treat bodily movements, such as Booth’s moving his finger, as
basic. Others point out that it is possible to engage in action but to
accomplish less than a bodily movement, as when one tries to move a limb that
is restrained or paralyzed, and fails. According to these accounts, bodily
actions arise out of a still more basic mental activity, usually called
volition or willing, which is held to constitute the standard means for
performing all overt actions. The question of how bodily actions originate is
closely associated with that of what distinguishes them from involuntary and
reflex bodily events, as well as from events in the inanimate world. There is
general agreement that the crucial difference concerns the mental states that
attend action, and in particular the fact that voluntary actions typically
arise out of states of intending on the part of the agent. But the nature of
the relation is difficult, and there is the complicating factor that intention
is sometimes held to reduce to other mental states, such as the agent’s desires
and beliefs. That issue aside, it would appear that unintentional actions arise
out of more basic actions that are intentional, as when one unintentionally
breaks a shoelace by intentionally tugging on it. But how intention is first
tr. into action is much more problematic, especially when bodily movements are
viewed as basic actions. One cannot, e.g., count Booth’s moving his finger as
an intentional action simply because he intended to do so, or even on the
ground if it is true that his intention caused his finger to move. The latter
might have occurred through a strictly autonomic response had Booth been nervous
enough, and then the moving of the finger would not have counted as an action
at all, much less as intentional. Avoiding such “wayward causal chains”
requires accounting for the agent’s voluntary control over what occurs in
genuinely intentional action a difficult
task when bodily actions are held to be basic. Volitional accounts have greater
success here, since they can hold that movements are intentional only when the
agent’s intention is executed through volitional activity. But they must sidestep
another threatened regress: if we call for an activity of willing to explain
why Booth’s moving his finger counts as intentional action, we cannot do the
same for willing itself. Yet on most accounts volition does have the
characteristics of intentional behavior. Volitional theories of action must,
then, provide an alternative account of how mental activity can be intentional.
Actions are explained by invoking the agent’s reasons for performing them.
Characteristically, a reason may be understood to consist in a positive
attitude of the agent toward one or another action theory action theory 7
4065A- 7 outcome, and a belief to the
effect that the outcome may be achieved by performing the action in question.
Thus Emily might spend the summer in France out of a desire to learn , and a
belief that spending time in France is the best way to do so. Disputed
questions about reasons include how confident the agent must be that the action
selected will in fact lead to the envisioned outcome, and whether obligation
represents a source of motivation that can operate independently of the agent’s
desires. Frequently, more than one course of action is available to an agent.
Deliberation is the process of searching out and weighing the reasons for and
against such alternatives. When successfully concluded, deliberation usually
issues in a decision, by which an intention to undertake one of the
contemplated actions is formed. The intention is then carried out when the time
for action comes. Much debate has centered on the question of how reasons are
related to decisions and actions. As with intention, an agent’s simply having a
reason is not enough for the reason to explain her behavior: her desire to
learn notwithstanding, Emily might have
gone to France simply because she was transferred there. Only when an agent
does something for a reason does the reason explain what is done. It is
frequently claimed that this bespeaks a causal relation between the agent’s
strongest reason and her decision or action. This, however, suggests a
determinist stance on the free will problem, leading some philosophers to balk.
An alternative is to treat reason explanations as teleological explanations,
wherein an action is held to be reasonable or justified in virtue of the goals
toward which it was directed. But positions that treat reason explanations as
non-causal require an alternative account of what it is to decide or act for
one reason rather than another. Grice
would often wonder about the pervasiveness of the intentiona idiom in the
description of action. He would use the phrase ‘action verb,’ i. e. a verb
applied to an agent and describing an activity, an action, or an attempt at or
a culmination of an action. Verbs applying to agents may be distinguished in
two basic ways: by whether they can take the progressive continuous form and by
whether or not there is a specific moment of occurrence/completion of the
action named by the verb. An activity verb is one describing something that
goes on for a time but with no inherent endpoint, such as ‘drive’, ‘laugh’, or
‘meditate’. One can stop doing such a thing but one cannot complete doing it.
Indeed, one can be said to have done it as soon as one has begun doing it. An
accomplishment verb is one describing something that goes on for a time toward
an inherent endpoint, such as ‘paint’ a fence, ‘solve’ a problem, or ‘climb’ a
mountain. Such a thing takes a certain time to do, and one cannot be said to
have done it until it has been completed. An achievement verb is one describing
either the culmination of an activity, such as ‘finish’ a job or ‘reach’ a
goal; the effecting of a change, such as ‘fire’ an employee or ‘drop’ an egg;
or undergoing a change, such as ‘hear’ an explosion or ‘forget’ a name. An
achievement does not go on for a period of time but may be the culmination of
something that does. Ryle singled out achievement verbs and state verbs see
below partly in order to disabuse philosophers of the idea that what
psychological verbs name must invariably be inner acts or activities modeled on
bodily actions or activities. A task verb is an activity verb that implies
attempting to do something named by an achievement verb. For example, to seek
is to attempt to find, to sniff is to attempt to smell, and to treat is to
attempt to cure. A state verb is a verb not an action verb describing a
condition, disposition, or habit rather than something that goes on or takes
place. Examples include ‘own’, ‘weigh’, ‘want’, ‘hate’, ‘frequent’, and
‘teetotal’. These differences were articulated by Zeno Vendler in Linguistics
and Philosophy 7. Taking them into account, linguists have classified verbs and
verb phrases into four main aspectual classes, which they distinguish in
respect to the availability and interpretation of the simple present tense, of the
perfect tenses, of the progressive construction, and of various temporal
adverbials, such as adverbs like ‘yesterday’, ‘finally’, and ‘often’, and
prepositional phrases like ‘for a long time’ and ‘in a while’. Many verbs
belong to more than one category by virtue of having several related uses. For
example, ‘run’ is both an activity and an accomplishment verb, and ‘weigh’ is
both a state and an accomplishment verb. Linguists single out a class of
causative verbs, such as ‘force’, ‘inspire’, and ‘persuade’, some of which are
achievement and some accomplishment verbs. Such causative verbs as ‘break’,
‘burn’, and ‘improve’ have a correlative intransitive use, so that, e.g., to
break something is to cause it to break. Grice denies the idea of an ‘act’ of
the soul. In this way, it is interesting to contrast his views to those
philosophers, even at Oxford, like Occam or Geach, who speak of an act of the
soul. And then there’s act-content-object psychology, or ‘act-object
psychology,’ for short, a philosophical theory that identifies in every
psychological state a mental act, a lived-through phenomenological content,
such as a mental image or description of properties, and an intended object
that the mental act is about or toward which it is directed by virtue of its
content. The distinction between the act, content, and object of thought
originated with Alois Höfler’s Logik 0, written in collaboration with Meinong.
But the theory is historically most often associated with its development in
Kazimierz Twardowski’s Zur Lehre vom Inhalt und Gegenstand der Vorstellung “On
the Content and Object of Presentations,” 4, despite Twardowski’s
acknowledgment of his debt to Höfler. Act-object psychology arose as a reaction
to Franz Brentano’s immanent intentionality thesis in his influential
Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt “Psychology from an Empirical
Standpoint,” 1874, in which Brentano maintains that intentionality is “the mark
of the mental,” by contrast with purely physical phenomena. Brentano requires
that intended objects belong immanently to the mental acts that intend
them a philosophical commitment that
laid Brentano open to charges of epistemological idealism and psychologism. Yet
Brentano’s followers, who accepted the intentionality of thought but resisted
what they came to see as its detachable idealism and psychologism, responded by
distinguishing the act-immanent phenomenological content of a psychological
state from its act-transcendent intended object, arguing that Brentano had
wrongly and unnecessarily conflated mental content with the external objects of
thought. Twardowski goes so far as to claim that content and object can never
be identical, an exclusion in turn that is vigorously challenged by Husserl in
his Logische Untersuchungen “Logical Investigations,” 3, 2, and by others in
the phenomenological tradition who acknowledge the possibility that a
self-reflexive thought can sometimes be about its own content as intended
object, in which content and object are indistinguishable. Act-object
psychology continues to be of interest to contemporary philosophy because of
its relation to ongoing projects in phenomenology, and as a result of a
resurgence of study of the concept of intentionality and qualia in philosophy
of mind, cognitive psychology, and Gegenstandstheorie, or existent and
non-existent intended object theory, in philosophical logic and semantics. Grice was fascinated by the metaphysically
wrong theory of agent-causation. He would make fun of it. His example, “The
cause of the death of Charles I is decapitation; therefore, decapitation willed
the death of Charles I. Grice would refer to transeunt causation in “Actions
and events.” In Grice’s terms, agent causation is the convoluted idea that the
primary cause of an event is a substance; more specifically, causation by a
substance, as opposed to an event. Thus a brick a substance may be said to be
the cause of the breaking of the glass. The expression is also used more
narrowly by Reid and others for the view that an action or event is caused by an
exertion of power by some agent endowed with will and understanding. Thus, a
person may be said to be the cause of her action of opening the door. In this
restricted sense Reid called it “the strict and proper sense”, an agent-cause
must have the power to cause the action or event and the power not to cause it.
Moreover, it must be “up to” the agent whether to cause the event or not to
cause it. It is not “up to” the brick whether to cause or not to cause the
breaking of the glass. The restricted sense of agent causation developed by
Reid is closely tied to the view that the agent possesses free will. Medieval
philosophers distinguished the internal activity of the agent from the external
event produced by that activity. The former was called “immanent causation” and
the latter “transeunt causation.” These terms have been adapted by Chisholm and
others to mark the difference between agent causation and event causation. The
idea is that the internal activity is agentcaused by the person whose activity
it is; whereas the external event is event-caused by the internal activity of
the agent. His “Death of Charles I”
example is meant as a reductio ad sbsurdum of ‘agent causation.’ The
philosopher cannot possibly be meaning to communicate such absurdity. The ‘actus’
is less obviously related to the actum, but it should. When Grice says, “What
is actual is not also possible” as a mistake – he is not thinking of HUMAN
rational agency – but some kind of agency, though. It may be thought that
‘actum’ is still phrased after a ‘that’-clause, even if what is reported is
something that is actual, e. g. It is actually raining (versus It is possibly
raining in Cambridge). – potentia -- energeia, Grecian term coined by Aristotle
and often tr. as ‘activity’, ‘actuality’, and even ‘act’, but more literally
rendered ‘a state of functioning’. Since for Aristotle the function of an
object is its telos or aim, energeia can also be described as an entelecheia or
realization another coined term he uses interchangeably with energeia. So
understood, it can denote either a something’s being functional, though not in
use at the moment, and b something’s actually functioning, which Aristotle
describes as a “first realization” and “second realization” respectively On the
Soul II.5. In general, every energeia is correlative to some dunamis, a
capability or power to function in a certain way, and in the central books of
the Metaphysics Aristotle uses the linkage between these two concepts to
explain the relation of form to matter. He also distinguishes between energeia
and kinesis change or motion Metaphysics IX.6; Nicomachean Ethics X.4. A
kinesis is defined by reference to its terminus e.g., learning how to multiply
and is thus incomplete at any point before reaching its conclusion. An energeia,
in contrast, is a state complete in itself e.g., seeing. Thus, Aristotle says
that at any time that I am seeing, it is also true that I have seen; but it is
not true that at any time I am learning that I have learned. In Grecian, this
difference is not so much one of tense as of encrateia energeia 264 264 aspect: the perfect tense marks a
“perfect” or complete state, and not necessarily prior activity. energeticism, also called energetism or
energism, the doctrine that energy is the fundamental substance underlying all
change. Its most prominent champion was the physical chemist Wilhelm Ostwald. In
his address “Die Überwindung des wissenschaftlichen Materialismus” “The
Conquest of Scientific Materialism”, delivered at Lübeck in 5, Ostwald
chastised the atomic-kinetic theory as lacking progress and claimed that a
unified science, energetics, could be based solely on the concept of energy.
Many of Ostwald’s criticisms of materialism and mechanistic reductionism
derived from Mach. Ostwald’s attempts to deduce the fundamental equations of
thermodynamics and mechanics from the principles of energy conservation and
transformation were indebted to the writings of Georg Helm 18749, especially
Die Lehre von Energie “The Laws of Energy,” 7 and Die Energetik “Energetics,”
8. Ostwald defended Helm’s factorization thesis that all changes in energy can
be analyzed as a product of intensity and capacity factors. The factorization
thesis and the attempt to derive mechanics and thermodynamics from the
principles of energetics were subjected to devastating criticisms by Boltzmann
and Max Planck. Boltzmann also criticized the dogmatism of Ostwald’s rejection
of the atomickinetic theory. Ostwald’s program to unify the sciences under the
banner of energetics withered in the
face of these criticisms.” actum: -- behaviourism. Grice
was amused that what Ryle thought was behaviouristic was already pervaded wiith
mentalistic talk! Referred to by H. P. Grice in his criticism of Gilbert Ryle.
Ironically, Chomsky misjudged Grice as a behaviourist, but Chomsky’s critique
was demolished by P. Suppes, broadly, the view that behavior is fundamental in
understanding mental phenomena. The term applies both to a scientific research
Beauvoir, Simone de behaviorism 76 76
program in psychology and to a philosophical doctrine. Accordingly, we
distinguish between scientific psychological, methodological behaviorism and
philosophical logical, analytical behaviorism. Scientific behaviorism. First
propounded by the psychologist J. B.
Watson who introduced the term in 3 and further developed especially by C. L.
Hull, E. C. Tolman, and B. F. Skinner, it departed from the introspectionist
tradition by redefining the proper task of psychology as the explanation and
prediction of behavior where to explain
behavior is to provide a “functional analysis” of it, i.e., to specify the
independent variables stimuli of which the behavior response is lawfully a
function. It insisted that all variables
including behavior as the dependent variable must be specifiable by the experimental
procedures of the natural sciences: merely introspectible, internal states of
consciousness are thus excluded from the proper domain of psychology. Although
some behaviorists were prepared to admit internal neurophysiological conditions
among the variables “intervening variables”, others of more radical bent e.g.
Skinner insisted on environmental variables alone, arguing that any relevant
variations in the hypothetical inner states would themselves in general be a
function of variations in past and present environmental conditions as, e.g.,
thirst is a function of water deprivation. Although some basic responses are
inherited reflexes, most are learned and integrated into complex patterns by a
process of conditioning. In classical respondent conditioning, a response already
under the control of a given stimulus will be elicited by new stimuli if these
are repeatedly paired with the old stimulus: this is how we learn to respond to
new situations. In operant conditioning, a response that has repeatedly been
followed by a reinforcing stimulus reward will occur with greater frequency and
will thus be “selected” over other possible responses: this is how we learn new
responses. Conditioned responses can also be unlearned or “extinguished” by
prolonged dissociation from the old eliciting stimuli or by repeated
withholding of the reinforcing stimuli. To show how all human behavior,
including “cognitive” or intelligent behavior, can be “shaped” by such
processes of selective reinforcement and extinction of responses was the ultimate
objective of scientific behaviorism. Grave difficulties in the way of the
realization of this objective led to increasingly radical liberalization of the
distinctive features of behaviorist methodology and eventually to its
displacement by more cognitively oriented approaches e.g. those inspired by
information theory and by Chomsky’s work in linguistics. Philosophical
behaviorism. A semantic thesis about the meaning of mentalistic expressions, it
received its most sanguine formulation by the logical positivists particularly
Carnap, Hempel, and Ayer, who asserted that statements containing mentalistic
expressions have the same meaning as, and are thus translatable into, some set
of publicly verifiable confirmable, testable statements describing behavioral
and bodily processes and dispositions including verbalbehavioral dispositions.
Because of the reductivist concerns expressed by the logical positivist thesis
of physicalism and the unity of science, logical behaviorism as some
positivists preferred to call it was a corollary of the thesis that psychology
is ultimately via a behavioristic analysis reducible to physics, and that all
of its statements, like those of physics, are expressible in a strictly
extensional language. Another influential formulation of philosophical
behaviorism is due to Ryle The Concept of Mind, 9, whose classic critique of
Cartesian dualism rests on the view that mental predicates are often used to
ascribe dispositions to behave in characteristic ways: but such ascriptions,
for Ryle, have the form of conditional, lawlike statements whose function is
not to report the occurrence of inner states, physical or non-physical, of
which behavior is the causal manifestation, but to license inferences about how
the agent would behave if certain conditions obtained. To suppose that all
declarative uses of mental language have a fact-stating or -reporting role at
all is, for Ryle, to make a series of “category mistakes” of which both Descartes and the logical
positivists were equally guilty. Unlike the behaviorism of the positivists,
Ryle’s behaviorism required no physicalistic reduction of mental language, and
relied instead on ordinary language descriptions of human behavior. A further
version of philosophical behaviorism can be traced to Vitters Philosophical
Investigations, 3, who argues that the epistemic criteria for the applicability
of mentalistic terms cannot be private, introspectively accessible inner states
but must instead be intersubjectively observable behavior. Unlike the previously
mentioned versions of philosophical behaviorism, Vitters’s behaviorism seems to
be consistent with metaphysical mindbody dualism, and is thus also
non-reductivist. behaviorism behaviorism 77
77 Philosophical behaviorism underwent severe criticism in the 0s and
0s, especially by Chisholm, Charles Taylor, Putnam, and Fodor. Nonetheless it
still lives on in more or less attenuated forms in the work of such diverse
philosophers as Quine, Dennett, Armstrong, David Lewis, U. T. Place, and
Dummett. Though current “functionalism” is often referred to as the natural
heir to behaviorism, functionalism especially of the Armstrong-Lewis variety
crucially differs from behaviorism in insisting that mental predicates, while
definable in terms of behavior and behavioral dispositions, nonetheless
designate inner causal states states
that are apt to cause certain characteristic behaviors. -- behavior therapy, a spectrum of behavior
modification techniques applied as therapy, such as aversion therapy,
extinction, modeling, redintegration, operant conditioning, and
desensitization. Unlike psychotherapy, which probes a client’s recollected
history, behavior therapy focuses on immediate behavior, and aims to eliminate
undesired behavior and produce desired behavior through methods derived from
the experimental analysis of behavior and from reinforcement theory. A chronic
problem with psychotherapy is that the client’s past is filtered through
limited and biased recollection. Behavior therapy is more mechanical, creating
systems of reinforcement and conditioning that may work independently of the
client’s long-term memory. Collectively, behavior-therapeutic techniques
compose a motley set. Some behavior therapists adapt techniques from
psychotherapy, as in covert desensitization, where verbally induced mental
images are employed as reinforcers. A persistent problem with behavior therapy
is that it may require repeated application. Consider aversion therapy. It
consists of pairing painful or punishing stimuli with unwelcome behavior. In
the absence, after therapy, of the painful stimulus, the behavior may recur
because association between behavior and punishment is broken. Critics charge
that behavior therapy deals with immediate disturbances and overt behavior, to
the neglect of underlying problems and irrationalities. Behaviourism. Chomsky, a. n. – cites H. P.
Grice as “A. P. Grice” -- preeminent
philosopher, and political activist who has spent his professional
career at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Chomsky’s best-known
scientific achievement is the establishment of a rigorous and philosophically
compelling foundation for the scientific study of the grammar of natural
language. With the use of tools from the study of formal languages, he gave a
far more precise and explanatory account of natural language grammar than had
previously been given Syntactic Structures, 7. He has since developed a number
of highly influential frameworks for the study of natural language grammar
e.g., Aspects of the Theory of Syntax, 5; Lectures on Government and Binding,
1; The Minimalist Program, 5. Though there are significant differences in
detail, there are also common themes that underlie these approaches. Perhaps
the most central is that there is an innate set of linguistic principles shared
by all humans, and the purpose of linguistic inquiry is to describe the initial
state of the language learner, and account for linguistic variation via the
most general possible mechanisms. On Chomsky’s conception of linguistics,
languages are structures in the brains of individual speakers, described at a
certain level of abstraction within the theory. These structures occur within
the language faculty, a hypothesized module of the human brain. Universal
Grammar is the set of principles hard-wired into the language faculty that
determine the class of possible human languages. This conception of linguistics
involves several influential and controversial theses. First, the hypothesis of
a Universal Grammar entails the existence of innate linguistic principles.
Secondly, the hypothesis of a language faculty entails that our linguistic
abilities, at least so far as grammar is concerned, are not a product of
general reasoning processes. Finally, and perhaps most controversially, since
having one of these structures is an intrinsic property of a speaker,
properties of languages so conceived are determined solely by states of the
speaker. On this individualistic conception of language, there is no room in
scientific linguistics for the social entities determined by linguistic
communities that are languages according to previous anthropological
conceptions of the discipline. Many of Chomsky’s most significant contributions
to philosophy, such as his influential rejection of behaviorism “Review of
Skinner’s Verbal Behavior,” Language, 9, stem from his elaborations and
defenses of the above consequences cf. also Cartesian Linguistics, 6;
Reflections on Language, 5; Rules and Representations, 0; Knowledge of
Language, 6. Chomsky’s philosophical writings are characterized by an adherence
to methodological naturalism, the view that the mind should be studied like any
other natural phenomenon. In recent years, he has also argued that reference,
in the sense in which it is used in the philosophy of language, plays no role
in a scientific theory of language “Language and Nature,” Mind, 5.
additum: or, ADDITVM, as
Grice would spell it -- f. addo ,
dĭdi, dĭtum, 3, v. a. 2. do (addues for addideris, Paul. ex Fest. p. 27 Müll.),addition.
Strawson Wiggins p. 520. The utterer implies something more or different from
what he explicitly conveys. Cfr. Disimplicaturum, ‘less’ under ‘different from’
How seriously are we taking the ‘more.’ Not used by Grice. They seem
cross-categorial. If emissor draws a skull and then a cross he means that there
is danger and death in the offing. He crosses the cross, so it means death is
avoidable. Urmson says that Warnock went to bed and took off his boots. He
implicates in that order. So he means MORE than the ‘ampersand.” The “and” is
expanded into “and then.” But in not every case things are so easy that it’s a
matter of adding stuff. Cf. summatum, conjunctum. And then there’s the
‘additive implicaturum.’ By uttering
‘and,’ Russell means the Boolean adition. Whitehead means ‘and then’.
Whithead’s implicaturum is ADDITIVE, as opposed to diaphoron. Grice considers
the conceptual possibilities here: One may explicitly convey that p, and
implicitly convey q, where q ADDS to p (e. g. ‘and’ implicates ‘and then’).
Sometimes it does not, “He is a fine fine,” (or a ‘nice fellow,’ Lecture IV)
implying, “He is a scoundrel.” Sometimes it has nothing to do with it, “The
weather has been nice” implying, “you committed a gaffe.” With disimplicaturum,
you implicate LESS than you explicitly convey. When did you last see your
father? “Yesterday night, in my drams.” Grice sums this up with the phrase,
“more or other.” By explicitly conveying that p, the emissor implicates MORE OR
OTHER than he explicitly conveys.
adornoian implicaturum. Grice enjoyed
Adorno’s explorations on the natural/non-natural distinction; adorno, t. w. a
philosopher of the first generation of the Frankfurt School of critical theory.
With Horkheimer, Adorno gave philosophical direction to the Frankfurt School
and its research projects in its Institute for Social Research. An accomplished
musician and composer, Adorno first focused on the theory of culture and art,
working to develop a non-reductionist but materialist theory of art and music
in many essays. Under the influence of Walter Benjamin, he turned toward
developing a “micrological” account of cultural artifacts, viewing them as
“constellations” of social and historical forces. As his collaboration with
Horkheimer increased, Adorno turned to the problem of a self-defeating
dialectic of modern reason and freedom. Under the influence of the seemingly
imminent victory of the Nazis in Europe, this analysis focused on the
“entwinement of myth and Enlightenment.” The Dialectic of Enlightenment argues
that instrumental reason promises the subject autonomy from the forces of
nature only to enslave it again by its own repression of its impulses and
inclinations. The only way around this self-domination is “non-identity
thinking,” found in the unifying tendencies of a non-repressive reason. This
self-defeating dialectic is represented by the striking image of Ulysses tied
to the mast to survive his encounter with the Sirens. Adorno initially hoped
for a positive analysis of the Enlightenment to overcome this genealogy of modern
reason, but it is never developed. Instead, he turned to an increasingly
pessimistic analysis of the growing reification of modern life and of the
possibility of a “totally administered society.” Adorno held that “autonomous
art” can open up established reality and negate the experience of reification.
Aesthetic Theory develops this idea of autonomous art in terms of aesthetic
form, or the capacity of the internal organization of art to restructure
existing patterns of meaning. Authentic works of art have a “truth-value” in
their capacity to bring to awareness social contradictions and antinomies. In
Negative Dialectics 6 Adorno provides a more general account of social
criticism under the “fragmenting” conditions of modern rationalization and
domination. These and other writings have had a large impact on cultural
criticism, particularly through Adorno’s analysis of popular culture and the
“culture industry.”
adparitum: or ADPARTIVUM, as
Grice would spell it -- apparitio –
Latin for ‘appear’ – ADPARITUM -- theory of appearing, the theory that to
perceive an object is simply for that object to appear present itself to one as
being a certain way, e.g., looking round or like a rock, smelling vinegary,
sounding raucous, or tasting bitter. Nearly everyone would accept this
formulation on some interpretation. But the theory takes this to be a
rock-bottom characterization of perception, and not further analyzable. It
takes “appearing to subject S as so-and-so” as a basic, irreducible relation,
one readily identifiable in experience but not subject to definition in other
terms. The theory preserves the idea that in normal perception we are directly
aware of objects in the physical environment, not aware of them through
non-physical sense-data, sensory impressions, or other intermediaries. When a
tree looks to me a certain way, it is the tree and nothing else of which I am
directly aware. That involves “having” a sensory experience, but that
experience just consists of the tree’s looking a certain way to me. After
enjoying a certain currency early in this century the theory was largely
abandoned under the impact of criticisms by Price, Broad, and Chisholm. The
most widely advertised difficulty theoretical underdetermination is this. What
is it that appears to the subject in completely hallucinatory experience?
Perhaps the greatest strength of the theory is its fidelity to what perceptual
experience seems to be. ap-pārĕo (adp- , Ritschl, Fleck., B. and K.; app- ,
Lachm., Merk., Weissenb., Halm, Rib.), ui, itum, 2, v. n., I.to come in sight, to appear, become
visible, make one's appearance (class. in prose and poetry). I. A.. Lit.: “ego
adparebo domi,” Plaut. Capt. 2, 3, 97: “ille bonus vir nusquam adparet,” Ter.
Eun. 4, 3, 18; Lucr. 3, 25; so id. 3, 989: “rem contra speculum ponas, apparet
imago,” id. 4, 157: unde tandem adpares, Cic. Fragm. ap. Prisc. p. 706 P.; id.
Fl. 12 fin.: “equus mecum una demersus rursus adparuit,” id. Div. 2, 68; so id.
Sull. 2, 5: “cum lux appareret (Dinter, adpeteret),” Caes. B. G. 7, 82: “de
sulcis acies apparuit hastae,” Ov. M. 3, 107: “apparent rari nantes,” Verg. A.
1, 118, Hor. C. S. 59 al.—With dat.: “anguis ille, qui Sullae adparuit
immolanti,” Cic. Div. 2, 30 fin.; id. Clu. 53: “Quís numquam candente dies
adparuit ortu,” Tib. 4, 1, 65.—Once in Varro with ad: quod adparet ad
agricolas, R. R. 1, 40.— B. In gen., to be seen, to show one's self, be in
public, appear: “pro pretio facio, ut opera adpareat Mea,” Plaut. Ps. 3, 2, 60:
“fac sis nunc promissa adpareant,” Ter. Eun. 2, 3, 20; cf. id. Ad. 5, 9, 7:
“illud apparere unum,” that this only is apparent, Lucr. 1, 877; Cato, R. R. 2,
2: “ubi merces apparet? i. e. illud quod pro tantā mercede didiceris,” Cic.
Phil. 2, 34: “quo studiosius opprimitur et absconditur, eo magis eminet et apparet,”
id. Rosc. Am. 41 fin.: “Galbae orationes evanuerunt, vix jam ut appareant,” id.
Brut. 21, 82: “apparet adhuc vetus mde cicatrix,” Ov. M. 12, 444; 2, 734:
“rebus angustis animosus atque fortis appare,” Hor. C. 2, 10, 22: “cum
lamentamur, non apparere labores Nostros,” are not noticed, considered, id. Ep.
2, 1, 224, so id. ib. 2, 1, 250 al.; Plaut. Men. 2, 1, 14; cf. id. Am. 2, 2,
161 and 162.—Hence, apparens (opp. latens), visible, evident: “tympana non
apparentia Obstrepuere,” Ov. M. 4, 391: “apparentia vitia curanda sunt,” Quint.
12, 8, 10; so id. 9, 2, 46.— II. Trop.: res apparet, and far more freq. impers.
apparet with acc. and inf. or rel.-clause, the thing (or it) is evident, clear,
manifest, certain, δῆλόν ἐστι, φαίνεται (objective certainty, while videtur.
δοκεῖ, designates subjective belief, Web. Uebungssch. 258): “ratio adparet,”
Plaut. Trin. 2, 4, 17: “res adparet, Ter Ad. 5, 9, 7: apparet id etiam caeco,
Liv 32, 34. cui non id apparere, id actum esse. etc.,” id. 22, 34; 2, 31 fin.:
“ex quo adparet antiquior origo,” Plin. 36, 26, 67, § 197 al.: “adparet servom
nunc esse domini pauperis,” Ter. Eun. 3, 2, 33: “non dissimulat, apparet esse
commotum,” Cic. Phil. 2, 34: apparet atque exstat, utrum simus earum (artium)
rudes, id. de Or. 1, 16, 72: “quid rectum sit, adparet,” id. Fam. 5, 19; 4, 7:
“sive confictum est, ut apparet, sive, etc.,” id. Fl. 16 fin.; Nep. Att. 4, 1;
Liv. 42, 43: “quo adparet antiquiorem hanc fuisse scientiam,” Plin. 35, 12, 44,
§ 153 al.—Also with dat. pers.: “quas impendere jam apparebat omnibus,” Nep.
Eum. 10, 3; and, by attraction, with nom. and inf., as in Gr. δῆλός ἐστι, Varr.
R. R. 1, 6, 2: “membra nobis ita data sunt, ut ad quandam rationem vivendi data
esse adpareant,” Cic. Fin. 3, 7, 23, ubi v. Otto: “apparet ita degenerāsse
Nero,” Suet. Ner. 1; or without the inf., with an adj. as predicate: “apparebat
atrox cum plebe certamen (sc. fore, imminere, etc.),” Liv. 2, 28; Suet. Rhet.
1.— III. To appear as servant or aid (a lictor, scribe, etc.), to attend, wait
upon, serve; cf. apparitor (rare): “sacerdotes diis adparento,” Cic. Leg. 2, 8,
21: “cum septem annos Philippo apparuisset,” Nep. Eum. 13, 1: “cum appareret
aedilibus,” Liv. 9, 46 Drak.: “lictores apparent consulibus,” id. 2, 55:
“collegis accensi,” id. 3, 33: tibi appareo atque aeditumor in templo tuo,
Pompon. ap. Gell. 12, 10: “Jovis ad solium Apparent,” Verg. A. 12, 850 (=
praestant ad obsequium, Serv.). Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Bradley and the misuses of
‘appearance.’”
ælfric: important English
philosopher, like Grice. Cf. Alcuinus. --.
æqui-pollens: -- from
‘aequipollentia,’ a term used by Grice, après Sextus Empiricus, to express the
view that there are arguments of equal strength on all sides of any question
and that therefore we should suspend judgment on every question that can be
raised.
æqui-probabile: a neuter – as
used by Grice, having the same probability. Sometimes used in the same way as
‘equipossible’, the term is associated with Laplace’s the “classical”
interpretation of probability, where the probability of an event is the ratio
of the number of equipossibilities favorable to the event to the total number
of equipossibilities. For example, the probability of rolling an even number
with a “fair” six-sided die is ½ there
being three equipossibilities 2, 4, 6 favorable to even, and six
equipossibilities 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6 in all and 3 /6 % ½. The concept is now
generally thought not to be widely applicable to the interpretation of
probability, since natural equipossibilities are not always at hand as in
assessing the probability of a thermonuclear war tomorrow.
æqui-valens: -- from
aequi-valentia – i. ee. mutual inferability. The following are main kinds: two
statements are materially equivalent provided they have the same truthvalue,
and logically equivalent provided each can be deduced from the other; two
sentences or words are equivalent in meaning provided they can be substituted
for each other in any context without altering the meaning of that context. In
truth-functional logic, two statements are logically equivalent if they can
never have truthvalues different from each other. In this sense of ‘logically
equivalent’ all tautologies are equivalent to each other and all contradictions
are equivalent to each other. Similarly, in extensional set theory, two classes
are equivalent provided they have the same numbers, so that all empty classes
are regarded as equivalent. In a non-extensional set theory, classes would be
equivalent only if their conditions of membership were logically equivalent or
equivalent in meaning.
æqui-vocalis: A neuter form -- Grice preferred Cicero’s rendition
of ‘synonymia’ (cf. paronymia, and homonympia) --. Grice’s æqui-vocality thesis
-- aequivocation, the use of an expression in two or more different senses in a
single context. For example, in ‘The end of anything is its perfection. But the
end of life is death; so death is the perfection of life’, the expression ‘end’
is first used in the sense of ‘goal or purpose,’ but in its second occurrence
‘end’ means ‘termination.’ The use of the two senses in this context is an
equivocation. Where the context in which the expression used is an argument,
the fallacy of equivocation may be committed.
æstheticum: or AESTHETICVM,
as Grice would spell it – “A hybrid,” – Grice is aware that the old Roman form
is ‘sensus’ – which Cicero uses to translate the rather convoluted Grecian idea
of the ‘aesthesis’ – or ‘aesthetikos’ versus ‘noetikos.’ -- Grice is well aware
that ‘aesthetica,’ qua discipline, was meant to refer to the ‘sensibile,’ as
opposed to the ‘intellectus.’ With F. N. Sibley (who credits Grice profusely),
Grice explored the ‘second-order’ quality of the so-called ‘aesthetic
properties.’ It influenced Scruton. The aesthetic attitude is the appropriate
attitude or frame of mind for approaching art or nature or other objects or
events so that one might both appreciate its intrinsic perceptual qualities,
and as a result have an aesthetic experience. The aesthetic attitude has been
construed in many ways: 1 as disinterested, so that one’s experience of the
work is not affected by any interest in its possible practical uses, 2 as a
“distancing” of oneself from one’s own personal concerns, 3 as the contemplation
of an object, purely as an object of sensation, as it is in itself, for its own
sake, in a way unaffected by any cognition or knowledge one may have of it.
These different notions of aesthetic attitude have at times been combined
within a single theory. There is considerable doubt about whether there is such
a thing as an aesthetic attitude. There is neither any special kind of action
nor any special way of performing an ordinary action that ensures that we see a
work as it “really is,” and that results in our having an aesthetic experience.
Furthermore, there are no purely sensory experiences, divorced from any
cognitive content whatsoever. Criticisms of the notion of aesthetic attitude
have reinforced attacks on aesthetics as a separate field of study within
philosophy. On the other hand, there’s aesthetic formalism, non-iconic, the
view that in our interactions with works of art, form should be given primacy.
Rather than taking ‘formalism’ as the name of one specific theory in the arts,
it is better and more typical to take it to name that type of theory which
emphasizes the form of the artwork. Or, since emphasis on form is something
that comes in degrees, it is best to think of theories of art as ranged on a
continuum of more formalist and less formalist. It should be added that
theories of art are typically complex, including definitions of art,
recommendations concerning what we should attend to in art, analyses of the
nature of the aesthetic, recommendations concerning the making of aesthetic
evaluations, etc.; and each of these components may be more formalist or less
so. Those who use the concept of form mainly wish to contrast the artifact
itself with its relations to entities outside itself with its representing various things, its symbolizing
various things, its being expressive of various things, its being the product
of various intentions of the artist, its evoking various states in beholders,
its standing in various relations of influence and similarity to preceding,
succeeding, and contemporary works, etc. There have been some, however, who in
emphasizing form have meant to emphasize not just the artifact but the
perceptible form or design of the artifact. Kant, e.g., in his theory of
aesthetic excellence, not only insisted that the only thing relevant to
determining the beauty of an object is its appearance, but within the
appearance, the form, the design: in visual art, not the colors but the design
that the colors compose; in music, not the timbre of the individual sounds but
the formal relationships among them. It comes as no surprise that theories of
music have tended to be much more formalist than theories of literature and
drama, with theories of the visual arts located in between. While Austin’s
favourite aesthetic property is ‘dumpty,’ Grice is more open minded, and allows
for more of a property or quality such as being dainty, garish, graceful,
balanced, charming, majestic, trite, elegant, lifeless, ugly, or beautiful. By
contrast, non-aesthetic properties are properties that require no special
sensitivity or perceptiveness to perceive
such as a painting’s being predominantly blue, its having a small red
square in a corner or a kneeling figure in the foreground, or that the music
becomes louder at a given point. Sometimes it is argued that a special
perceptiveness or taste is needed to perceive a work’s aesthetic qualities, and
that this is a defining feature of a property’s being aesthetic. A corollary of
this view is that aesthetic qualities cannot be defined in terms of non-aesthetic
qualities, though some have held that aesthetic qualities supervene on
non-aesthetic qualities. As a systematic philosopher, Grice goes back to the
etymological root of the aesthetic as the philosophy of the sensible. He would
make fun of the specialization. “If at the philosophy department I am
introduced to Mr. Puddle, our man in nineteenth-century continental aesthetics,
I can grasp he is either underdescribed or not good at nineteenth-century
continental aesthetics!’ The branch of philosophy that examines the nature of
art and the character of our adventitious ideas and experience of art and of
the natural environment. It emerged as a separate field of philosophical
inquiry during the eighteenth century in England and on the Continent. Recognition
of aesthetics as a separate branch of philosophy coincided with the development
of theories of art that grouped together painting, poetry, sculpture, music,
and dance and often landscape gardening as the same kind of thing, les beaux
arts, or the fine arts. Baumgarten coined the term ‘aesthetics’ in his
Reflections on Poetry 1735 as the name for one of the two branches of the study
of knowledge, i.e., for the study of sensory experience coupled with feeling,
which he argued provided a different type of knowledge from the distinct,
abstract ideas studied by “logic.” He derived it from the ancient Grecian
aisthanomai ‘to perceive’, and “the aesthetic” has always been intimately
connected with sensory experience and the kinds of feelings it arouses. Questions
specific to the field of aesthetics are: Is there a special attitude, the
aesthetic attitude, which we should take toward works of art and the natural
environment, and what is it like? Is there a distinctive type of experience, an
aesthetic experience, and what is it? Is there a special object of attention
that we can call the aesthetic object? Finally, is there a distinctive value,
aesthetic value, comparable with moral, epistemic, and religious values? Some
questions overlap with those in the philosophy of art, such as those concerning
the nature of beauty, and whether there is a faculty of taste that is exercised
in judging the aesthetic character and value of natural objects or works of
art. Aesthetics also encompasses the philosophy of art. The most central issue
in the philosophy of art has been how to define ‘art’. Not all cultures have,
or have had, a concept of art that coincides with the one that emerged in
Western Europe during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. What justifies
our applying our concept to the things people in these other cultures have
produced? There are also many pictures including paintings, songs, buildings,
and bits of writing, that are not art. What distinguishes those pictures,
musical works, etc., that are art from those that are not? Various answers have
been proposed that identify the distinguishing features of art in terms of
form, expressiveness, intentions of the maker, and social roles or uses of the
object. Since the eighteenth century there have been debates about what kinds
of things count as “art.” Some have argued that architecture and ceramics are
not art because their functions are primarily utilitarian, and novels were for
a long time not listed among the “fine arts” because they are not embodied in a
sensuous medium. Debates continue to arise over new media and what may be new
art forms, such as film, video, photography, performance art, found art,
furniture, posters, earthworks, and computer and electronic art. Sculptures
these days may be made out of dirt, feces, or various discarded and
mass-produced objects, rather than marble or bronze. There is often an explicit
rejection of craft and technique by twentieth-century artists, and the subject
matter has expanded to include the banal and everyday, and not merely
mythological, historical, and religious subjects as in years past. All of these
developments raise questions about the relevance of the category of “fine” or
“high” art. Another set of issues in philosophy of art concerns how artworks
are to be interpreted, appreciated, and understood. Some views emphasize that
artworks are products of individual efforts, so that a work should be
understood in light of the producer’s knowledge, skill, and intentions. Others
see the meaning of a work as established by social conventions and practices of
the artist’s own time, but which may not be known or understood by the
producer. Still others see meaning as established by the practices of the
users, even if they were not in effect when the work was produced. Are there
objective criteria or standards for evaluating individual artworks? There has
been much disagreement over whether value judgments have universal validity, or
whether there can be no disputing about taste, if value judgments are relative
to the tastes and interests of each individual or to some group of individuals
who share the same tastes and interests. A judgment such as “This is good”
certainly seems to make a claim about the work itself, though such a claim is
often based on the sort of feeling, understanding, or experience a person has
obtained from the work. A work’s aesthetic or artistic value is generally
distinguished from simply liking it. But is it possible to establish what sorts
of knowledge or experiences any given work should provide to any suitably
prepared perceiver, and what would it be to be suitably prepared? It is a
matter of contention whether a work’s aesthetic and artistic values are
independent of its moral, political, or epistemic stance or impact. Philosophy
of art has also dealt with the nature of taste, beauty, imagination,
creativity, repreaesthetics aesthetics 12 4065A- 12 sentation, expression, and
expressiveness; style; whether artworks convey knowledge or truth; the nature
of narrative and metaphor; the importance of genre; the ontological status of
artworks; and the character of our emotional responses to art. Work in the
field has always been influenced by philosophical theories of language or
meaning, and theories of knowledge and perception, and continues to be heavily
influenced by psychological and cultural theory, including versions of
semiotics, psychoanalysis, cognitive psychology, feminism, and Marxism. Some
theorists in the late twentieth century have denied that the aesthetic and the
“fine arts” can legitimately be separated out and understood as separate,
autonomous human phenomena; they argue instead that these conceptual categories
themselves manifest and reinforce certain kinds of cultural attitudes and power
relationships. These theorists urge that aesthetics can and should be
eliminated as a separate field of study, and that “the aesthetic” should not be
conceived as a special kind of value. They favor instead a critique of the
roles that images not only painting, but film, photography, and advertising, sounds,
narrative, and three-dimensional constructions have in expressing and shaping
human attitudes and experiences.
agape: Grice would often
contrast ‘self-love’ with ‘agape’ and ‘benevolence.’ Strictly, agape, “a lovely
Grecian word,” is best rendered as the unselfish love for all persons. An
ethical theory according to which such love is the chief virtue, and actions
are good to the extent that they express it, is sometimes called agapism. Agape
is the Grecian word most often used for love in the New Testament, and is often
used in modern languages to signify whatever sort of love the writer takes to
be idealized there. In New Testament Grecian, however, it was probably a quite
general word for love, so that any ethical ideal must be found in the text’s
substantive claims, rather than in the linguistic meaning of the word. R.M.A.
agathon, Grecian word meaning ‘a good’ or ‘the good’. From Socrates onward,
agathon was taken to be a central object of philosophical inquiry; it has
frequently been assumed to be the goal of all rational action. Plato in the
simile of the sun in the Republic identified it with the Form of the Good, the
source of reality, truth, and intelligibility. Aristotle saw it as eudaimonia,
intellectual or practical virtue, a view that found its way, via Stoicism and
Neoplatonism, into Christianity. Modern theories of utility can be seen as
concerned with essentially the same Socratic question.
agitation: or AGITATUM, as
Grice would spell it -- a Byzantine
feeling is a Ryleian agitation. If Grice
were to advance the not wholly plausible thesis that ‘to feel Byzantine’ is
just to have a an anti-rylean agitation which is caused by the thought that
Grice is or might *be* Byzantine, it would surely be ridiculous to criticise
Grice on the grounds that Grice saddles himself with an ontological commitment
to feelings, or to modes of feeling. And why? Well, because, alla Parsons, if a
quantifier is covertly involved at all, it will only be a universal quantifier
which in such a case as this is more than adequately handled by a
substitutional account of quantification. Grice’s situation vis-a-vis the
‘proposition’ is in no way different. In the idiolect of Ryle, “a serious
student of Grecian philosophy,” as Grice puts it, ‘emotion’ designates at least
three or four different kinds of things, which Ryle calls an ‘inclination, or
‘motive,’ a ‘mood’, an ‘agitation,’ or a ‘commotion,’ and a ‘feeling.’ An
inclination or a mood, including an agitation, is not occurrences and doest not
therefore take place either publicly or privately. It is a propensity, not an
act or state. An inclination is, however, a propensity of this or that kind,
and the kind is important. A feeling, on the other hand, IS an occurrence, but
the place that mention of it should take in a description of human behaviour is
very different from that which the standard theories accord to it. A
susceptibility to a specific agitation is on the same general footing with an
inclination, viz. that each is a general propensity and not an occurrence. An
agitation is not a motive. But an agitation does presuppose a motive, or rather
an agitataion presupposes a behaviour trend of which a motive is for us the
most interesting sort. There is however a matter of expression which
is the source of some confusion, even among Oxonian Wilde readers, and that did
confuse philosophical psychologists of the ability of G. F. Stout. An
expression may signify both an inclination and an agitation. But an expression
may signify anything but an agitations. Again, some other expression may signify
anything but an inclination. An expression like ‘uneasy’, ‘anxious’,
‘distressed’, ‘excited’, ‘startled’ always signifies an agitations. An
expression like ‘fond of fishing’, ‘keen on gardening’, ‘bent on becoming a
bishop’ never signifies an agitation. But an expression like ‘love’, ‘want’,
‘desire’, ‘proud’, ‘eager,’ or many others, stands sometimes for a simple
inclination and sometimes for an agitations which is resultant upon the
inclinations and interferences with the exercise of it. Thus ‘hungry’ for
‘having a good appetite’ means roughly ‘is eating or would eat heartily and
without sauces, etc..’ This is different from ‘hungry’ in which a person might
be said to be ‘too hungry to concentrate on his work’. Hunger in this second
expression is a distress, and requires for its existence the conjunction of an
appetite with the inability to eat. Similarly the way in which a boy is proud
of his school is different from the way in which he is speechless with pride on
being unexpectedly given a place in a school team. To remove a possible
misapprehension, it must be pointed out that an agitation may be quite
agreeable. A man may voluntarily subject himself to suspense, fatigue,
uncertainty, perplexity, fear and surprise in such practices as angling,
rowing, travelling, crossword puzzles, rock-climbing and joking. That a thing
like a thrill, a rapture, a surprise, an amusement and an relief is an
agitation is shown by the fact that we can say that someone is too much
thrilled, amused or relieved to act, think or talk coherently. It
is helpful to notice that, anyhow commonly, the expression which completes ‘pang of . . .’ or ‘chill of . . .’ denotes an
agitation. A feeling, such as a man feeling Byzantine, is intrinsically
connected with an agitation. But a feeling, e. g. of a man who is feeling
Byzantine, is not intrinsically connected with an inclination, save in so far
as the inclination is a factor in the agitation. This is no novel psychological
hypothesis; It is part of the logic of our descriptions of a feeling that a
feeling (such as a man feeling Byzantine) is a sign of an agitation and is not
an exercise of an inclination. A feeling, such as a man feeling Byzantine, in
other words, is not a thing of which it makes sense to ask from what motive it
issues. The same is true, for the same reasons, of any sign of any agitation. This
point shows why we were right to suggest above that a feeling (like a man
feeling Byzantine) does not belong directly to a simple inclination. An
inclination is a certain sort of proneness or readiness to do certain sorts of
things on purpose. These things are therefore describable as being done from
that motive. They are the exercises of the disposition that we call ‘a motive’.
A feeling (such as a man feeling Byzantine) is not from a motive and is
therefore not among the possible exercise of such a propensiy. The widespread
theory that a motive such as vanity, or affection, is in the first instance a
disposition to experience certain specific feeling is therefore absurd. There
may be, of course, a tendency to have a feeling, such as feeling Byzantine;
being vertiginous and rheumatic are such tendencies. But we do not try to modify
a tendency of these kinds by a sermon. What a feeling, such as being Byzantine,
does causally belong to is the agitation. A feeling (such as feeling Byzantine)
is a sign of an agitation in the same sort of way as a stomach-ache is a sign
of indigestion. Roughly, we do not, as the prevalent theory holds, act
purposively because we experience a feeling (such as feeling Byzantine); we
experience a feeling (such as feeling Byzantine), as we wince and shudder,
because we are inhibited from acting purposively.
A
sentimentalist is a man who indulges in this or that induced feeling (such as
feeling Byzantine) without acknowledging the fictitiousness of his agitation.
It seems to be generally supposed that ‘pleasure’ or ‘desire’ is always used to
signify a feeling. And there certainly are feelings which can be described as a
feeling of pleasure or desire. Some thrills, shocks, glows and ticklings are
feelings of delight, surprise, relief and amusement; and things like a
hankering, an itche, a gnawing and a yearning is a sign that something is both
wanted and missed. But the transports, surprises, reliefs and distresses of
which such a feeling is diagnosed, or mis-diagnosed, as a sign is not itself a
feeling. It is an agitation or a mood, just as are the transports and
distresses which a child betrays by his skips and his whimpers. Nostalgia is an
agitation and one which can be called a ‘desire’; but it is not merely a
feeling or series of feelings. There is the sense of ‘pleasure’ in which it is
commonly replaced by such expressions as ‘delight’, ‘transport’, ‘rapture’,
‘exultation’ and ‘joy’. These are expressions of this or that mood signifying this
or that agitation. There are two quite different usages of ‘emotion’, in which
we explain people’s behaviour by reference to emotions. In the first usage of
‘emotion,’ we are referring to the motives or inclinations from which more or
less intelligent actions are done. In a second usage we are referring to a
mood, including the agitation or perturbation of which some aimless movement
may be a sign. In neither of these usages are we asserting or implicating that
the overt behaviour is the effect of a felt turbulence in the agent’s stream of
consciousness. In a third usage of ‘emotion’, pangs and twinges are feelings or
emotions, but they are not, save per accidens, things by reference to which we
explain behaviour. They are things for which diagnoses are required, not things
required for the diagnoses of behaviour. Since a convulsion of merriment is not
the state of mind of the sober experimentalist, the enjoyment of a joke is also
not an introspectible happening. States of mind such as these more or less
violent agitations can be examined only in retrospect. Yet nothing disastrous
follows from this restriction. We are not shorter of information about panic or
amusement than about other states of mind. If retrospection can give us the
data we need for our knowledge of some states of mind, there is no reason why
it should not do so for all. And this is just what seems to be suggested by the
popular phrase ‘to catch oneself doing so and so’. We catch, as we pursue and
overtake, what is already running away from us. I catch myself daydreaming
about a mountain walk after, perhaps very shortly after, I have begun the
daydream; or I catch myself humming a particular air only when the first few
notes have already been hummed. Retrospection, prompt or delayed, is a genuine
process and one which is exempt from the troubles ensuing from the assumption
of multiply divided attention; it is also exempt from the troubles ensuing from
the assumption that violent agitations could be the objects of cool,
contemporary scrutiny. One may be aware that he is whistling ‘Tipperary’ and
not know that he is whistling it in order to give tte appearance of a
sang-froid which he does not feel. Or, again, he may be aware that he is
shamming sang-froid without knowing that the tremors which he is trying to hide
derive from the agitation of a guilty conscience.
agnoiologicum: Grice loved a
negative prefix. He was proud that he was never vulgar in publishing, like some
of his tutees – and that the number of his unpublications by far exceed the
number of his publications. To refute Hampshire with this intention and
certainty, he regaled the British Academy with the annual philosophical lecture
on intention and Uncertainty. While Grice thought that ‘knowledge’ was
overreated at Oxford (“Surely an examinee can be said to know that date of the
battle of Waterloo”) he could be agnoiological at times. From Grecian agnoia,
‘ignorance’, the study of ignorance, its quality, and its conditions. And then
there’s ‘agnosticism,’ from Grecian a-, ‘not’, and gnastos, ‘known’, term
invented by Thomas Henry Huxley in 1869 to denote the philosophical and
religious attitude of those who claim that metaphysical ideas can be neither
proved nor disproved. Huxley wrote, “I neither affirm nor deny the immortality
of man. I see no reason for believing it, but on the other hand, I have no
means of disproving it. I have no a priori objection to the doctrine.”
Agnosticism is a form of skepticism applied to metaphysics, especially theism.
The position is sometimes attributed to Kant, who held that we cannot have
knowledge of God or immortality but must be content with faith. Agnosticism
should not be confused with atheism, the belief that no god exists.
alberti: Genova-born
essential Italian philosopher – Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice ed
Alberti," per Il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice,
Liguria, Italia.
albertus magnus: Dominican
Griceian philosopher. As a Parisian master of theology, he served on a
commission that condemned the Talmud. He left Paris to found the first
Dominican studium generale at Cologne. Albert was repeatedly asked to be an
arbiter and peacemaker. After serving briefly as bishop of Regensburg, he was
ordered to preach the crusade. He spent his last years writing in Cologne.
Albert contributed to philosophy chiefly as a commentator on Aristotle,
although he occasionally reached different conclusions from Aristotle.
Primarily, Albert was a theologian, as is evident from his extensive commentary
on Peter Lombard’s Sentences and his commentaries on the Old and New
Testaments. As a theologian, he customarily developed his thought by commenting
on traditional texts. For Albert, Aristotle offered knowledge ascertainable
using reason, just as Scripture, based on God’s word, tells of the
supernatural. Albert saw Aristotle’s works, many newly available, as an
encyclopedic compendium of information on the natural universe; included here
is the study of social and political conditions and ethical obligations, for
Aristotelian “natural knowledge” deals with human nature as well as natural
history. Aristotle is the Philosopher; however, unlike Holy Scripture, he must
be corrected in places. Like Holy Scripture, though, Aristotle is occasionally
obscure. To rectify these shortcomings one must rely on other authorities: in
the case of Holy Scripture, reference is to the church fathers and established
interpreters; in the case of Aristotle, to the Peripatetics. The term
‘Peripatetics’ extends to modern as well as ancient authors al-Farabi, Avicenna Ibn-Sina, and Averroes
Ibn-Rushd, as well as Themistius and Alexander of Aphrodisias; even Seneca,
Maimonides, and “our” Boethius are included. For the most part, Albert saw
Plato through the eyes of Aristotle and Averroes, since apart from the Timaeus
very little of Plato’s work was available in Latin. Albert considered the Liber
de causis a work of Aristotle, supplemented by alFarabi, Avicenna, and
al-Ghazali and tr. into Latin. When he commented on the Liber de causis, Albert
was not aware that this Neoplatonic work
which speaks of the world emanating from the One as from a first cause was based on Proclus and ultimately on
Plotinus. But Albert’s student, Aquinas, who had better translations of
Aristotle, recognized that the Liber de causis was not an Aristotelian work.
Albert’s metaphysics, which is expounded in his commentaries on Aristotle’s
Metaphysics on the Liber de causis, contains profoundly contradictory elements.
His inclination to synthesis led him to attempt to reconcile these
elements as on social and ecclesiastical
questions he often sought peace through compromise. In his Metaphysics and
Physics and in his On the Heavens and On Generation and Corruption, Aristotle
presented the world as ever-changing and taught that an unmoved mover “thought
thinking itself” maintained everything in movement and animation by allowing its
spiritual nature to be seen in all its cold, unapproachable beauty. The Liber
de causis, on the other hand, develops the theory that the world emanates from
the One, causing everything in the world in its pantheistic creativity, so that
the caused world returns in mystic harmony to the One. Thus Albert’s
Aristotelian commentaries culminated with his commentary on a work whose
pseudo-Aristotelian character he was unable to recognize. Nevertheless, the
Christian Neoplatonism that Albert placed on an Aristotelian basis was to exert
an influence for centuries. In natural philosophy, Albert often arrived at
views independent of Aristotle. According to Aristotle’s Physics, motion
belongs to no single category; it is incomplete being. Following Avicenna and
Averroes, Albert asks whether “becoming black,” e.g. which ceases when change ceases and blackness
is finally achieved differs from
blackness essentially essentia or only in its being esse. Albert establishes,
contrary to Avicenna, that the distinction is only one of being. In his
discussions of place and space, stimulated by Avicenna, Albert also makes an
original contribution. Only two dimensions
width and breadth are essential
to place, so that a fluid in a bottle is framed by the inner surface of the
bottle. According to Albert, the significance of the third dimension, depth, is
more modest, but nonetheless important. Consider a bucket of water: its base is
the essential part, but its round walls maintain the cohesion of the water. For
Aristotle, time’s material foundation is distinct from its formal definition.
Materially, the movement of the fixed stars is basic, although time itself is
neither movement nor change. Rather, just as before and after are continuous in
space and there are earlier and later moments in movement as it proceeds
through space, so time being the number
of motion has earlier and later moments
or “nows.” The material of time consists of the uninterrupted flow of the
indivisible nows, while time’s form and essential expression is number.
Following al-Farabi and Avicenna, Albert’s interpretation of these doctrines
emphasizes not only the uninterrupted continuity of the flow of “nows,” but
also the quantity of time, i.e., the series of discrete, separate, and clearly
distinct numbers. Albert’s treatment of time did not lend itself well to later
consideration of time as a dimension; his concept of time is therefore not well
suited to accommodate our unified concept of space-time. The use of the
pseudo-Aristotelian De proprietatibus elementorum in De causis proprietatum
elementorum gave Albert’s worldview a strong astrological flavor. At issue here
is how the planets influence the earth and mankind. Particularly important is
the influence of Jupiter and Saturn on fire and the seas; when increased, it
could produce fiery conflagrations, and when circumscribed, floods. Albert was
encyclopedic: a scientist and scholar as well as a philosopher and theologian.
In addition to the works mentioned, he produced commentaries on
Pseudo-Dionysius, a Summa de creaturis, a Summa Theologica, and many other
treatises. Unlike other commentators, his exposition was continuous, an
extensive paraphrase; he provided a complete Latin and Christian philosophy.
Even in his lifetime, he was a named authority; according to Roger Bacon, his
views were often given as much weight as those of Aristotle, Avicenna, and
Averroes. His students or followers include Aquinas, Ulrich of Strassburg,
Theodoric of Freiberg, Giles of Lessines, Meister Eckhart, Johannes Tauler,
Henry Suso, Jan van Ruysbroeck, and H. P. Grice.
alethic: Grice could not
find a good word for ‘verum,’ and so he borrowed ‘alethic’ from, but never
returned it to, von Wright. Under the alethic modalities, Grice, as
historically, included the four central ways or modes in which a given
proposition might be true or false: necessity, contingency, possibility, and
impossibility. The term ‘alethic’ derives from Grecian aletheia, ‘truth’. These
modalities, and their logical interconnectedness, can be characterized as
follows. A proposition that is true but possibly false is contingently true
e.g., that Aristotle taught Alexander; one that is true and not-possibly i.e.,
“impossibly” false is necessarily true e.g., that red things are colored.
Likewise, a proposition that is false but possibly true is contingently false
e.g., that there are no tigers; and one that is false and not-possibly true is
necessarily false e.g., that seven and five are fourteen. Though any one of the
four modalities can be defined in terms of any other, necessity and possibility
are generally taken to be the more fundamental notions, and most systems of
alethic modal logic take one or the other as basic. Distinct modal systems
differ chiefly in regard to their treatment of iterated modalities, as in the
proposition It is necessarily true that it is possibly true that it is possibly
true that there are no tigers. In the weakest of the most common systems,
usually called T, every iterated modality is distinct from every other. In the
stronger system S4, iterations of any given modality are redundant. So, e.g.,
the above proposition is equivalent to It is necessarily true that it is
possibly true that there are no tigers. In the strongest and most widely
accepted system S5, all iteration is redundant. Thus, the two propositions
above are both equivalent simply to It is possibly true that there are no
tigers.
alexanderian: s.– what Grice
called “A Balliol hegelian,” philosopher, tuteed at Balliol by A. C. Bradley,
Oxford, and taught for most of his career at the of Manchester. His aim, which he most fully
realized in Space, Time, and Deity 0, was to provide a realistic account of the
place of mind in nature. He described nature as a series of levels of existence
where irreducible higher-level qualities emerge inexplicably when lower levels
become sufficiently complex. At its lowest level reality consists of
space-time, a process wherein points of space are redistributed at instants of
time and which might also be called pure motion. From complexities in
space-time matter arises, followed by secondary qualities, life, and mind.
Alexander thought that the still-higher quality of deity, which characterizes
the whole universe while satisfying religious sentiments, is now in the process
of emerging from mind.
alexanderian: related to
Alexander de Aphrodisias: ““Alexander of Aphrodisias” should not be confused
with Samuel Alexander, a fellow of Bradley, even if they are next in your
philosophical dictionary!” – Grice. Grecian philosopher, one of the foremost
commentators on Aristotle in late antiquity. He exercised considerable
influence on later Grecian and Roman philosophy through to the Renaissance. On
the problem of universals, Alexander endorses a brand of conceptualism:
although several particulars may share a single, common nature, this nature
does not exist as a universal except while abstracted in thought from the
circumstances that accompany its particular instantiations. Regarding
Aristotle’s notorious distinction between the “agent” and “patient” intellects
in On the Soul III.5, Alexander identifies the agent intellect with God, who,
as the most intelligible entity, makes everything else intelligible. As its own
self-subsistent object, this intellect alone is imperishable; the human
intellect, in contrast, perishes at death. Of Alexander’s many commentaries,
only those on Aristotle’s Metaphysics Ad, Prior Analytics I, Topics, On the
Senses, and Meterologics are extant. We also have two polemical treatises, On Fate
and On Mixture, directed against the Stoics; a psychological treatise, the De
anima based on Aristotle’s; as well as an assortment of essays including the De
intellectu and his Problems and Solutions. Nothing is known of Alexander’s life
apart from his appointment by the emperor Severus to a chair in Aristotelian
philosophy between and 209.
Algarotti: essential Italian philosopher. Refs.: Luigi
Speranza, "Grice ed Algarotti," per Il Club Anglo-Italiano, The
Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
algorithm: Grice’s term for
‘decision procedure,’ a clerical or effective procedure that can be applied to
any of a class of certain symbolic inputs and that will in a finite time and
number of steps eventuate in a result in a corresponding symbolic output. A
function for which an algorithm sometimes more than one can be given is an
algorithmic function. The following are common examples: a given n, finding the
nth prime number; b differentiating a polynomial; c finding the greatest common
divisor of x and y the Euclidean algorithm; and d given two numbers x, y,
deciding whether x is a multiple of y. When an algorithm is used to calculate
values of a numerical function, as in a, b, and c, the function can also be
described as algorithmically computable, effectively computable, or just
computable. Algorithms are generally agreed to have the following
properties which made them essential to
the theory of computation and the development of the Church-Turing thesis i an algorithm can be given by a finite
string of instructions, ii a computation device or agent can carry out or
compute in accordance with the instructions, iii there will be provisions for
computing, storing, and recalling steps in a computation, iv computations can
be carried out in a discrete and stepwise fashion in, say, a digital computer,
and v computations can be carried out in a deterministic fashion in, say, a
deterministic version of a Turing machine.
allais’s paradox: a puzzle about
rationality, discussed by H. P. Grice, “Aspects of reason,” devised by Maurice
Allais b. 1. Leonard Savage advanced the
sure-thing principle, which states that a rational agent’s ranking of a pair of
gambles having the same consequence in a state S agrees with her ranking of any
other pair of gambles the same as the first pair except for having some other
common consequence in S. Allais devised an apparent counterexample with four
gambles involving a 100-ticket lottery. The table lists prizes in units of
$100,000. Ticket Numbers Gambles 1 2 11
12 100 A 5 5 5 B 0 25 5 C 5 5 0 D 0 25 0
Changing A’s and B’s common consequence for tickets 12100 from 5 to 0 yields C
and D respectively. Hence the sure-thing principle prohibits simultaneously
preferring A to B, and D to C. Yet most people have these preferences, which
seem coherent. This conflict generates the paradox. Savage presented the
sure-thing principle in The Foundations of Statistics 4. Responding to
preliminary drafts of that work, Allais formulated his counterexample in “The
Foundations of a Positive Theory of Choice Involving Risk and a Criticism of
the Postulates and Axioms of the School”
2.
allegedly
‘wayward’ causal chain: Grice: “What
is the antonym of ‘wayward’?’ A causal chain, referred to in a proposed causal
analysis of a key concept, that goes awry. Causal analyses have been proposed
for key concepts e.g., reference,
action, explanation, knowledge, artwork. There are two main cases of wayward or
deviant causal chains that defeat a causal analysis: 1 those in which the
prescribed causal route is followed, but the expected event does not occur; and
2 those in which the expected event occurs, but the prescribed causal route is
not followed. Consider action. One proposed analysis is that a person’s doing
something is an action if and only if what he does is caused by his beliefs and
desires. The possibility of wayward causal chains defeats this analysis. For
case 1, suppose, while climbing, John finds he is supporting another man on a
rope. John wants to rid himself of this danger, and he believes that he can do
so by loosening his grip. His belief and desire unnerve him, causing him to
loosen his hold. The prescribed causal route was followed, but the ensuing
event, his grip loosening, is not an action. For case 2, suppose Harry wants to
kill his rich uncle, and he believes that he can find him at home. His beliefs
and desires so agitate him that he drives recklessly. He hits and kills a
pedestrian, who, by chance, is his uncle. The killing occurs, but without
following the prescribed causal route; the killing was an accidental
consequence of what Harry did. Refs.: H.
P. Grice, “Aetiologica: from Roman ‘causa’ to Anglo-Saxon ‘for’”, Woodfield,
“Be-*cause* he thought she had insulted him,” H. P. Grice, “A philosophical
mistake: ‘cause’ is called for for unusual events only.” Grice: “What is the
antonym of ‘wayward’?” -- a causal chain, referred to in a proposed causal
analysis of a key concept, that goes awry. Causal analyses have been proposed
for key concepts – e.g., reference, action, explanation, knowledge, artwork.
There are two main cases of wayward (or deviant) causal chains that defeat a
causal analysis: (1) those in which the prescribed causal route is followed,
but the expected event does not occur; and (2) those in which the expected
event occurs, but the prescribed causal route is not followed. Consider action.
One proposed analysis is that a person’s doing something is an action if and
only if what he does is caused by his beliefs and desires. The possibility of
wayward causal chains defeats this analysis. For case (1), suppose, while
climbing, John finds he is supporting another man on a rope. John wants to rid
himself of this danger, and he believes that he can do so by loosening his
grip. His belief and desire unnerve him, causing him to loosen his hold. The
prescribed causal route was followed, but the ensuing event, his grip
loosening, is not an action. For case (2), suppose Harry wants to kill his rich
uncle, and he believes that he can find him at home. His beliefs and desires so
agitate him that he drives recklessly. He hits and kills a pedestrian, who, by
chance, is his uncle. The killing occurs, but without following the prescribed
causal route; the killing was an accidental consequence of what Harry did.
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Aetiologica: from Roman ‘cause’ to Anglo-Saxon ‘for’” –
Woodfield, “Be-*cause* she thought he had insulted him.’”
alnwick: English
Franciscan theologian. William studied under Duns Scotus at Paris, and wrote
the Reportatio Parisiensia, a central source for Duns Scotus’s teaching. In his
own works, William opposed Scotus on the univocity of being and haecceitas.
Some of his views were attacked by Ockham. English Franciscan theologian from
Northumbria -- William studied under Duns Scotus at Paris, and wrote the
Reportatio Parisiensia, a central source for Duns Scotus’s teaching. In his own
works, William opposed Scotus on the univocity of being and haecceitas. Some of
his views were attacked by Ockham.
althusserian: a philosopher
Grice called a ‘hegelian’. LouisL Marxist philosopher whose publication in 5 of
two collections of essays, Pour Marx “For Marx” and Lire le Capital “Reading
Capital”, made him a sensation in
intellectual circles and attracted a large international readership. The
English translations of these texts in 9 and 0, respectively, helped shape the
development of Marxist thought in the English-speaking world throughout the 0s.
Drawing on the work of non-positivist
historians and philosophers of science, especially Bachelard, Althusser
proclaimed the existence of an “epistemological break” in Marx’s work,
occurring in the mid-1840s. What preceded this break was, in Althusser’s view,
a prescientific theoretical humanism derived from Feuerbach and ultimately from
Hegel. What followed it, Althusser maintained, was a science of history a
all-things-considered reason Althusser, Louis 23 4065A- 23 development as monumental, potentially,
as the rise of the new sciences of nature in the seventh century. Althusser
argued that the nature and even the existence of this new kind of science had
yet to be acknowledged, even by Marx himself. It therefore had to be reconstructed
from Marx’s writings, Das Kapital especially, and also discerned in the
political practice of Lenin and other like-minded revolutionaries who
implicitly understood what Marx intended. Althusser did little, however, to
elaborate the content of this new science. Rather, he tirelessly defended it
programmatically against rival construals of Marxism. In so doing, he took
particular aim at neo-Hegelian and “humanistic” currents in the larger Marxist
culture and implicitly in the Communist
Party, to which he belonged throughout his adult life. After 8, Althusser’s
influence in France faded. But he continued to teach at l’École Normale
Superieure and to write, making important contributions to political theory and
to understandings of “ideology” and related concepts. He also faced
increasingly severe bouts of mania and depression. In 0, in what the courts deemed an episode of “temporary
insanity,” he strangled his wife. Althusser avoided prison, but spent much of
the 0s in mental institutions. During this period he wrote two extraordinary
memoirs, L’avenir dure longtemps “The Future Lasts Forever” and Les faits “The
Facts”, published posthumously in 2.
altogether nice
girl:
Or Grice’s altogether nice girl. Grice quotes from the music-hall ditty, “Every
[sic] nice girl loves a sailor” (WoW:33). He uses this for his account of
multiple quantification. There is a reading where the emissor may implicate
that every nice girl is such that he loves one sailor, viz. Grice. But if the
existential quantifier is not made dominant, the uniqueness is disimplicated.
Grice admits that not every nominalist will be contented with the
‘metaphysical’ status of ‘the altogether nice girl.’ The ‘one-at-a-time sailor’
is her counterpart. And they inhabit the class of LOVE.
ambrosius: saint. Grice:
“Not to be confused with Ambrose and his orchestra – sweet!” – on altruism.
known as Ambrose of Milan c.33997, Roman church leader and theologian. While
bishop of Milan, he not only led the struggle against the Arian heresy and its
political manifestations, but offered new models for preaching, for Scriptural
exegesis, and for hymnody. His works also contributed to medieval Latin
philosophy. Ambrose’s appropriation of Neoplatonic doctrines was noteworthy in
itself, and it worked powerfully on and through Augustine. Ambrose’s commentary
on the account of creation in Genesis, his Hexaemeron, preserved for medieval
readers many pieces of ancient natural history and even some altruism Ambrose,
Saint 24 4065A- 24 elements of physical
explanation. Perhaps most importantly, Ambrose engaged ancient philosophical
ethics in the search for moral lessons that marks his exegesis of Scripture; he
also reworked Cicero’s De officiis as a treatise on the virtues and duties of
Christian living.
amicus: philia and eros –
Grice on Aristotle’s aporia of friendship -- Eros, the Grecian god of erotic
love. Eros came to be symbolic of various aspects of love, first appearing in
Hesiod in opposition to reason. In general, however, Eros was seen by Grecians
e.g., Parmenides as a unifying force. In Empedocles, it is one of two external
forces explaining the history of the cosmos, the other being Strife. These
forces resemble the “hidden harmony” of Heraclitus. The Symposium of Plato is
the best-known ancient discussion of Eros, containing speeches from various
standpoints mythical, sophistic, etc.
Socrates says he has learned from the priestess Diotima of a nobler form of
Eros in which sexual desire can be developed into the pursuit of understanding
the Form of beauty. The contrast between agape and Eros is found first in
Democritus. This became important in Christian accounts of love. In
Neoplatonism, Eros referred to the mystical union with Being sought by
philosophers. Eros has become important recently in the work of Continental
writers.
ammonius: saccas early
third century A.D., Platonist philosopher. He apparently served early in the
century as the teacher of the philosopher Origen. He attracted the attention of
Plotinus, who came to the city in 232 in search of philosophical enlightenment
Porphyry, Life of Plotinus 3. Ammonius the epithet ‘Saccas’ seems to mean ‘the
bagman’ was undoubtedly a charismatic figure, but it is not at all clear what,
if any, were his distinctive doctrines, though he seems to have been influenced
by Numenius. He wrote nothing, and may be thought of, in E. R. Dodds’s words,
as the Socrates of Neoplatonism.
analyticum: Grice:
Etyologically, a compound – ana-lusis --. Cf. catalysis --. Porphyry couldn’t
find a Latinate for ‘analyticum’ – ‘analyisis’ is like ‘se-paratio.’ But even
in Grecian, ‘analysis’ and synthesis are not real opposite – since ‘synthesis’
neatly comes as ‘compositio’ -- analysis, the process of breaking up a concept,
proposition, linguistic complex, or fact into its simple or ultimate
constituents. That on which the analysis is done is called the analysandum, and
that which does the analysis is called the analysans. A number of the most
important philosophers of the twentieth century, including Russell, Moore, and
the early Vitters, have argued that philosophical analysis is the proper method
of philosophy. But the practitioners of analytic philosophy have disagreed
about what kind of thing is to be analyzed. For example, Moore tried to analyze
sense-data into their constituent parts. Here the analysandum is a complex
psychological fact, the having of a sense-datum. More commonly, analytic
philosophers have tried to analyze concepts or propositions. This is conceptual
analysis. Still others have seen it as their task to give an analysis of
various kinds of sentences e.g., those
involving proper names or definite descriptions. This is linguistic analysis.
Each of these kinds of analysis faces a version of a puzzle that has come to be
called the paradox of analysis. For linguistic analyses, the paradox can be
expressed as follows: for an analysis to be adequate, the analysans must be
synonymous with the analysandum; e.g., if ‘male sibling’ is to analyze
‘brother’, they must mean the same; but if they are synonymous, then ‘a brother
is a male sibling’ is synonymous with ‘a brother is a brother’; but the two
sentences do not seem synonymous. Expressed as a dilemma, the paradox is that
any proposed analysis would seem to be either inadequate because the analysans
and the analysandum are not synonymous or uninformative because they are
synonymous. Analytic philosophy is an
umbrella term currently used to cover a diverse assortment of philosophical
techniques and tendencies. As in the case of chicken-sexing, it is relatively
easy to identify analytic philosophy and philosophers, though difficult to say
with any precision what the criteria are. Analytic philosophy is sometimes
called Oxford philosophy or linguistic philosophy, but these labels are, at
least, misleading. Whatever else it is, analytic philosophy is manifestly not a
school, doctrine, or body of accepted propositions. At Cambridge, analytic
philosophers are the intellectual heirs of Russell, Moore, and Vitters,
philosophers who self-consciously pursued “philosophical analysis” in the early
part of the twentieth century. Analysis, as practiced by Russell and Moore,
concerned not language per se, but concepts and propositions. In their eyes,
while it did not exhaust the domain of philosophy, analysis provided a vital
tool for laying bare the logical form of reality. Vitters, in the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus,
contended, though obliquely, that the structure of language reveals the
structure of the world; every meaningful sentence is analyzable into atomic
constituents that designate the finegrained constituents of reality. This
“Tractarian” view was one Vitters was to renounce in his later work, but it had
considerable influence within the Vienna Circle in the 0s, and in the
subsequent development of logical positivism in the 0s and 0s. Carnap and Ayer,
both exponents of positivism, held that the task of philosophy was not to
uncover elusive metaphysical truths, but to provide analyses of scientific
sentences. Other sentences, those in ethics, for instance, were thought to lack
“cognitive significance.” Their model was Russell’s theory of descriptions,
which provided a technique for analyzing away apparent commitments to
suspicious entities. Meanwhile, a number of former proponents of analysis,
influenced by Vitters, had taken up what came to be called ordinary language
philosophy. Philosophers of this persuasion focused on the role of words in the
lives of ordinary speakers, hoping thereby to escape long-standing
philosophical muddles. These muddles resulted, they thought, from a natural
tendency, when pursuing philosophical theses, to be misled by the grammatical
form of sentences in which those questions were posed. A classic illustration
might be Heidegger’s supposition that ‘nothing’ must designate something,
though a very peculiar something. Today, it is difficult to find much unanimity
in the ranks of analytic philosophers. There is, perhaps, an implicit respect
for argument and clarity, an evolving though informal agreement as to what
problems are and are not tractable, and a conviction that philosophy is in some
sense continuous with science. The practice of analytic philosophers to address
one another rather than the broader public has led some to decry philosophy’s
“professionalization” and to call for a return to a pluralistic,
community-oriented style of philosophizing. Analytic philosophers respond by
pointing out that analytic techniques and standards have been well represented
in the history of philosophy. Analyticity. H. P. Grice, “In defence of a
dogma,” in Studies in the way of words. the analyticsynthetic distinction, the
distinction, made famous by Kant, according to which an affirmative
subject-predicate statement proposition, judgment is called analytic if the
predicate concept is contained in the subject concept, and synthetic otherwise.
The statement ‘All red roses are red’ is analytic, since the concept ‘red’ is
contained in the concept ‘red roses’. ‘All roses are red’ is synthetic, since
the concept ‘red’ is not contained in the concept ‘roses’. The denial of an
affirmative subject-predicate statement entails a contradiction if it is
analytic. E.g., ‘Not all red roses are red’ entails ‘Some roses are both red
and not red’. One concept may be contained in another, in Kant’s sense, even
though the terms used to express them are not related as part to whole. Since
‘biped’ means ‘two-footed animal’, the concept ‘two-footed’ is contained in the
concept ‘biped’. It is accordingly analytic that all bipeds are two-footed. The
same analytic statement is expressed by the synonymous sentences ‘All bipeds
are two-footed’ and ‘All two-footed animals are two-footed’. Unlike statements,
sentences cannot be classified as analytic or synthetic except relative to an
interpretation. analytical jurisprudence analyticsynthetic distinction 26
4065A- 26 Witness ‘All Russian teachers
are Russian’, which in one sense expresses the analytic statement ‘All teachers
that are Russian are Russian’, and in another the synthetic statement ‘All
teachers of Russian are Russian’. Kant’s innovation over Leibniz and Hume lay
in separating the logicosemantic analyticsynthetic distinction from the
epistemological a prioria posteriori distinction and from the modalmetaphysical
necessarycontingent distinction. It seems evident that any analytic statement
is a priori knowable without empirical evidence and necessary something that
could not be false. The converse is highly controversial. Kant and his
rationalist followers maintain that some a priori and necessary statements are
synthetic, citing examples from logic ‘Contradictions are impossible’, ‘The
identity relation is transitive’, mathematics ‘The sum of 7 and 5 is 12’, ‘The
straight line between two points is the shortest’, and metaphysics ‘Every event
is caused’. Empiricists like J. S. Mill, Carnap, Ayer, and C. I. Lewis argue
that such examples are either synthetic a posteriori or analytic a priori.
Philosophers since Kant have tried to clarify the analyticsynthetic
distinction, and generalize it to all statements. On one definition, a sentence
is analytic on a given interpretation provided it is “true solely in virtue of
the meaning or definition of its terms.” The truth of any sentence depends in
part on the meanings of its terms. `All emeralds are green’ would be false,
e.g., if ‘emerald’ meant ‘ruby’. What makes the sentence synthetic, it is
claimed, is that its truth also depends on the properties of emeralds, namely,
their being green. But the same holds for analytic sentences: the truth of ‘All
red roses are red’ depends on the properties of red roses, namely, their being
red. Neither is true solely in virtue of meaning. A more adequate
generalization defines an analytic statement as a formal logical truth: one
“true in virtue of its logical form,” so that all statements with the same form
are true. In terms of sentences under an interpretation, an analytic truth is
an explicit logical truth one whose surface structure represents its logical
form or one that becomes an explicit logical truth when synonyms are
substituted. The negative statement that tomorrow is not both Sunday and not
Sunday is analytic by this definition, because all statements of the form : p
& - p are true. Kant’s definition is obtained as a special case by
stipulating that the predicate of an affirmative subjectpredicate statement is
contained in the subject provided the statement is logically true. On a third
generalization, ‘analytic’ denotes any statement whose denial entails a
contradiction. Subject S contains predicate P provided being S entails being P.
Whether this is broader or narrower than the second generalization depends on
how ‘entailment’, ‘logical form’, and ‘contradiction’ are defined. On some
construals, ‘Red is a color’ counts as analytic on the third generalization its
denial entails ‘Something is and is not a color’ but not on the second ‘red’
and ‘colored’ are logically unstructured, while the rulings are reversed for a
counterfactual conditional like ‘If this were a red rose it would be red’.
Following Quine, many have denied any distinction between analytic and
synthetic statements. Some arguments presume the problematic “true by meaning”
definition. Others are that: 1 the distinction cannot be defined without using
related notions like ‘meaning’, ‘concept’, and ‘statement’, which are neither
extensional nor definable in terms of behavior; 2 some statements like ‘All
cats are animals’ are hard to classify as analytic or synthetic; and 3 no
statement allegedly is immune from rejection in the face of new empirical
evidence. If these arguments were sound, however, the distinction between
logical truths and others would seem equally dubious, a conclusion seldom
embraced. Some describe a priori truths, both synthetic and analytic, as
conceptual truths, on the theory that they are all true in virtue of the nature
of the concepts they contain. Conceptual truths are said to have no “factual
content” because they are about concepts rather than things in the actual
world. While it is natural to classify a priori truths together, the proffered
theory is questionable. As indicated above, all truths hold in part because of
the identity of their concepts, and in part because of the nature of the
objects they are about. It is a fact that all emeralds are emeralds, and this
proposition is about emeralds, not concepts. analyticum-a-priori:
For Grice, an oxymoron, since surely
‘analyticum-a-posteriori’ is an oxymoron. R. A. Wollheim. London-born
philosopher, BPhil Oxon, Balliol (under D. Marcus) and All Souls. Examined by H. P. Grice. “What’s two times
two?” Wollheim treasured that examination. It was in the context of a
discussion of J. S. Mill and I. Kant, for whom addition and multiplication are
‘synthetic’ – a priori for Kant, a posteriori for Mill. Grice was trying to
provide a counterexample to Mill’s thesis that all comes via deduction or
induction.
necessitatum: ananke, when
feeling very Grecian, Grice would use ‘ananke,’ instead of ‘must,’ which he
thought too English! Grecian, necessity. The term was used by early Grecian
philosophers for a constraining or moving natural force. In Parmenides frg. 8,
line 30 ananke encompasses reality in limiting bonds; according to Diogenes
Laertius, Democrianamnesis ananke 27 4065A-
27 tus calls the vortex that generates the cosmos ananke; Plato Timaeus
47e ff. refers to ananke as the irrational element in nature, which reason
orders in creating the physical world. As used by Aristotle Metaphysics V.5,
the basic meaning of ‘necessary’ is ‘that which cannot be otherwise’, a sense
that includes logical necessity. He also distinguishes Physics II.9 between
simple and hypothetical necessity conditions that must hold if something is to
occur.
anaxagoras: Grecian and
pre-Griceian philosopher who was the first of the pre-Socratics to teach in
Athens c.480450, where he influenced leading intellectuals such as Pericles and
Euripides. He left Athens when he was prosecuted for impiety. Writing in
response to Parmenides, he elaborated a theory of matter according to which
nothing comes into being or perishes. The ultimate realities are stuffs such as
water and earth, flesh and bone, but so are contraries such as hot and cold,
likewise treated as stuffs. Every phenomenal substance has a portion of every
elemental stuff, and there are no minimal parts of anything, but matter takes
on the phenomenal properties of whatever predominates in the mixture.
Anaxagoras posits an indefinite number of elemental stuffs, in contrast to his
contemporary Empedocles, who requires only four elements; but Anaxagoras
follows Parmenides more rigorously, allowing no properties or substances to
emerge that were not already present in the cosmos as its constituents. Thus
there is no ultimate gap between appearance and reality: everything we perceive
is real. In Anaxagoras’s cosmogony, an initial chaos of complete mixture gives
way to an ordered world when noûs mind begins a vortex motion that separates
cosmic masses of ether the bright upper air, air, water, and earth. Mind is
finer than the stuffs and is found in living things, but it does not mix with
stuffs. Anaxagoras’s theory of mind provides the first hint of a mindmatter
dualism. Plato and Aristotle thought his assigning a cosmic role to mind made
him sound like “a sober man” among his contemporaries, but they were
disappointed that he did not exploit his idea to provide teleological explanations
of natural phenomena.
anaximander:: Grecian and
pre-Griceian philosopher and cosmologist, reputedly the student and successor
of Thales in the Milesian school. He described the cosmos as originating from
apeiron the boundless by a process of separating off; a disk-shaped earth was
formed, surrounded by concentric heavenly rings of fire enclosed in air. At
“breathing holes” in the air we see jets of fire, which are the stars, moon,
and sun. The earth stays in place because there is no reason for it to tend one
way or another. The seasons arise from alternating periods where hot and dry or
wet and anaphor Anaximander 28 4065A-
28 cold powers predominate, governed by a temporal process figuratively
portrayed as the judgment of Time. Anaximander drew a map of the world and
explained winds, rain, and lightning by naturalistic hypotheses. He also
described the emergence of life in a way that prefigures the theory of
evolution. Anaximander’s interest in cosmology and cosmogony and his brilliant
conjectures set the major questions for later preSocratics.
anaximenes: of Miletus:
Grecian and pre-Griceian philosopher, a
pre-Socratic who, following in the tradition of the Milesians Thales and
Anaximander, speculated about cosmology and meteorology. The source arche of
the cosmos is air aer, originally mist, which by a process of rarefaction
becomes fire, and by a process of condensation becomes wind, clouds, water,
earth, and stones. Air is divine and causes life. The earth is flat and rides
on a cushion of air, while a heavenly firmament revolves about it like a felt
cap. Anaximenes also explained meteorological phenomena and earthquakes.
Although less innovative than his predecessor Anaximander, he made progress in
naturalistic explanations by appealing to a quantitative process of rarefaction
and condensation rather than to mythical processes involving quasi-personal
agents.
ancestry: Studied by H. P.
Grice. Of a given relation R, the relation also called the transitive closure
of R that relates one given individual to a second if and only if the first can
be “reached” from the second by repeated “applications” of the given relation
R. The “ancestor” relation is the ancestral of the parent relation since one
person is an ancestor of a second if the first is a parent of the second or the
first is a parent of a parent of the second or the first is a parent of a
parent of a parent of the second, and so on. Frege discovered a simple method
of giving a materially adequate and formally correct definition of the
ancestral of a given relation in terms of the relation itself plus logical
concepts. This method is informally illustrated as follows. In order for one
person A to be an ancestor of a second person B it is necessary and sufficient
for A to have every property that belongs to every parent of B and that belongs
to every parent of any person to whom it belongs. This and other similar
methods made possible the reduction of all numerical concepts to those of zero
and successor, which Frege then attempted to reduce to concepts of pure logic.
Frege’s definition of the ancestral has become a paradigm in modern analytic
philosophy as well as a historical benchmark of the watershed between
traditional logic and modern logic. It demonstrates the exactness of modern
logical analysis and, in comparison, the narrowness of traditional logic.
andronicus: Grecian
philosopher, a leading member of the Lyceum who was largely responsible for
establishing the canon of Aristotle’s works still read today. He also edited
the works of Theophrastus. At the time, Aristotle was known primarily for his
philosophical dialogues, only fragments of which now survive; his more
methodical treatises had stopped circulating soon after his death. By producing
the first systematic edition of Aristotle’s corpus, Andronicus revived study of
the treatises, and the resulting critical debates dramatically affected the
course of philosophy. Little is recorded about Andronicus’s labors; but besides
editing the texts and discussing titles, arrangement, and authenticity, he
sought to explicate and assess Aristotle’s thought. In so doing, he and his
colleagues initiated the exegetical tradition of Aristotelian commentaries.
Nothing he wrote survives; a summary account of emotions formerly ascribed to
him is spurious.
angst: Grice discusses
this as an ‘implicatural emotion.’ G. term for a special form of anxiety, an
emotion seen by existentialists as both constituting and revealing the human
condition. Angst plays a key role in the writings of Heidegger, whose concept
is closely related to Kierkegaard’s angest and Sartre’s angoisse. The concept
is first treated in this distinctive way in Kierkegaard’s The Concept of
Anxiety 1844, where anxiety is described as “the dizziness of freedom.” Anxiety
here represents freedom’s self-awareness; it is the psychological precondition
for the individual’s attempt to become autonomous, a possibility that is seen
as both alluring and disturbing.
Animatum -- animal: pirotese. Durrell’s
Family Conversations. Durrelly’s family conversation. When H. P. Grice was presented with an ‘overview’ of his
oeuvre for PGRICE (Grandy and Warner, 1986), he soon found out. “There’s something missing.” Indeed, there is a very infamous objection,
Grice thought, which is not mentioned by ‘Richards,’ as he abbreviates Richard
Grandy and Richard Warner’s majestically plural ‘overview,’ which seems to
Grice to be one to which Grice must respond. And he shall! The objection Grice
states as follows. One of the leading strands in Grice’s reductive analysis of
the circumstances or scenario in which an emissor (E) communicates that p is
that the scenario, call it “C,” is not to be regarded exclusively, “or even
primarily,” as a ‘feature’ of an E that is using what philosophers of language (since
Plato’s “Cratylus”) have been calling ‘language’ (glossa, la lingua latina, la
lingua italiana, la langue française, the English tongue, de nederlands taal,
die Deutsche Sprache, etc.). The emissum (e) may be an ‘utterance’ which is not
‘linguistic.’ Grice finds the issue crucial after discussing the topic with his
colleague at Berkeley, Davidson. For Davidson reminds Grice: “[t]here is no such
thing as a language, not if a language is anything like what many philosophers […]
have supposed” (Davidson, 1986: 174). “I’m happy you say ‘many,’ Davidson,”
Grice commented. Grice continues formulating what he
obviously found to be an insidious, fastidious, objection. There are many
instances of “NOTABLY NON-‘linguistic’” vehicles or devices of communication,
within a communication-system, even a one-off system, which fulfil this or that
communication-function. I am using ‘communication-function’ alla Grice (1961:138,
repr. 1989:235).
These vehicles or devices are mostly
syntactically un-structured or amorphous – Grice’s favourite example being a
‘sort of hand-wave’ meaning that it is not the case that the emissor knows the
route or that the emissor is about to leave his addressee (1967:VI, repr. 1989:126).
Sometimes,
a device may exhibit at least “some rudimentary syntactic” structure – as Grice
puts it, giving a nod to Morris’s tripartite semiotics -- in that we may perhaps
distinguish and identify a ‘totum’ or complexum (say, Plato’s ‘logos’) from a
pars or simplex (say, Plato’s ‘onoma’ and ‘rhema’). Grice’s intention-based
reductive analysis of a communicatum, based on Aristotle, Locke, and Peirce, is
designed, indeed its very raison d'être being, to allow for the possibility that a non-“linguistic,” and,
further, indeed a non-“conventional” 'utterance,’ perhaps unrepeatable token,
not even manifesting any degree of syntactic structure, but a block of an
amorphous signal, be within the ‘repertoire’ of ‘procedures,’ perhaps
unrepeatable ones, of this or that organism, or creature, or agent, even if not
relying on any apparatus for communication of the kind that that we may label
‘linguistic’ or otherwise ‘conventional,’ will count as an emissor E ‘doing’
this or that ‘thing,’ thereby ‘communicating’ that p. To provide for this
conceptual scenario, it is plainly necessary, Grice grants, that the key
ingredient in any representation or conceptualization, or reductive analysis of
‘communicating,’ viz. intending that p, for Grice, should be a ‘state’ of the
emissor’s “soul” (Grice is translating Grecian ψυχή the capacity for which does not require what we may label
the ‘possession’ of, shall we say, ‘faculty,’ of what philosophers since
Cratylus have been calling ‘γλῶσσα Ἑλληνίδα,’
‘lingua latina,’ ‘lingua italiana,’ ‘langue française,’ ‘English tongue,’ ‘Nederlands
taal,’ ‘die Deutsche Sprache.’ (Grice always
congratulated Kant for never distinguishing between ‘die Deutsche Sprache’ and
‘Sprache’ as ‘eine Fakultät.’). Now a
philosopher, relying on this or that neo-Prichardian reductive analysis of
‘intending that p,’ (Oxonian Grice will quote Oxonian if he can) may not be
willing to allow the possibility of such, shall we grant, pre-linguistic
intending that p, or non-linguistic intending that p. Surely, if the emissor E
realizes that his addressee or recipient R does not ‘share’ say, what the
Germans call ‘die Deutsche Sprache,” E may still communicate, by doing
so-and-so, that such-and-such, viz. p. E may make this sort of hand wave
communicating that E knows the route or that E is about to leave R. Against
that objection, Grice surely wins the day. There’s nothing in Prichard account
of ‘willing that p,’ itself a borrowing from William James (“I will that the
distant table slides over the floor toward me. It does not.”) which is about
‘die Deutsche Sprache.’
But Grice hastens to declare that
winning ‘the’ day may not be winning ‘all’ day. And
that is because of Oxonian philosophy being what it is. Because, as far as
Grice’s Oxonian explorations on communication go, in a succession of
increasingly elaborate moves – ending with a a clause which closes the succession
o-- designed to thwart this or that scenario, later deemed illegitimate,
involving two rational agents where the emissor E relies on an
‘inference-element’ that it is not the case that E intends his recipient R will
recogise – Grice is led to narrow the ‘intending’ the reductive analysis of ‘Emissor
E communicates that p’ to C-intending. Grice expects that whatever may be the case in general with
regard to ‘intending,’ C-intending seems for some reason to Grice to be
unsophisticatedly, viz. plainly, too sophisticated a ‘state’ of a soul (or ψυχή) to be found in an organism, ‘pirot,’ creature, that we may
not want to deem ‘rational,’ or as the Germans would say, a creature that is plainly
destitute of “Die Deutsche Sprache.” We seem to be needing a pirot to be “very
intelligent, indeed rational.” (Who other than Grice would genially combine
Locke with Carnap?). Some may regret, Grice admits, that his unavoidable rear-guard
action just undermines the raison d'etre of his campaign. However, Grice goes on to provide an admittedly brief reply
which will have to suffice under the circumstances. There is SOME limit for
Oxonian debate! A full treatment that would satisfy Grice requires delving deep
into crucial problems about the boundary between vicious and virtuous conceptual
circularity.
Which is promising. It is not something
UNATTAINABLE a priori – and there is nothing wrong with leaving it for the
morrow. It reduces to the philosopher trying to show himself virtuously
circular, if not, like Lear, spherical. But why need the circle be virtuous.
Well, as August would put it, unless a ‘circulus’ is not ‘virtuosus,’ one would
hardly deem it a ‘circulus’ in the first place. A circle is virtuous if it is not a
bad circle. One may even say, with The Carpenter, that, like a cabbage or a
king, if a circle is not virtuous is not even a circle! (Grice 2001:35). In
this case, to borrow from former Oxonian student S. R. Schiffer, we need the
‘virtuous circle’ because we are dealing with ‘a loop’ (Schiffer, 1988:v) -- a
‘conceptual loop,’ that is. Schiffer is not interested in ‘communicating;’ only
‘meaning,’ but his point can be easily transliterated. Schiffer is saying that
‘U,’ or utterer, our ‘E,’ means that p’ surely relies on ‘U intends that p,’
but mind the loop: ‘U intends that p’ may rely on ‘U means that p.’In Grice’s
most generic, third-person terms, we have a creature, call it a pirot, P1,
that, by doing thing D1, communicates that p. We are talking of Grice qua
ethologist, who OBSERVES the scenario. As it happens, Grice’s favourite pirot
is the parrot, and call Grice a snob, but his favourite parrot was Prince
Maurice’s Parrot. Prince Maurice’s Parrot. Grice reads Locke, and adapts it
slightly. “Since I think I may be confident, that, whoever should see a
CREATURE of his own shape or make, though it had no more reason all its life
than a PARROT, would call him still A MAN; or whoever should hear a parrot discourse,
reason, and philosophise, would call or think it nothing but a PARROT; and say,
the one was A DULL IRRATIONAL MAN, and the other A VERY INTELLIGENT RATIONAL
PARROT. “A relation we have in an author of great note, is sufficient to
countenance the supposition of A RATIONAL PARROT. “The author’s words are as
follows.”““I had a mind to know, from Prince Maurice's own mouth, the account
of a common, but much credited story, that I had heard so often from many
others, of a parrot he has, that speaks, and asks, and answers common questions,
like A REASONABLE CREATURE.””““So that those of his train there generally
conclude it to be witchery or possession; and one of his chaplains, would never
from that time endure A PARROT, but says all PARROTS have a devil in them.””““I
had heard many particulars of this story, and as severed by people hard to be
discredited, which made me ask Prince Maurice what there is of it.””““Prince
Maurice says, with his usual plainness and dryness in talk, there is something
true, but a great deal false of what is reported.””““I desired to know of him
what there was of the first. Prince Maurice tells me short and coldly, that he
had HEARD of such A PARROT; and though he believes nothing of it, and it was a
good way off, yet he had so much curiosity as to send for the parrot: that it
was a very great parrot; and when the parrot comes first into the room where
Prince Maurice is, with a great many men about him, the parrot says presently, ‘What
a nice company is here.’”” ““ One of the men asks the parrot, ‘What thinkest thou
that man is?,’ ostending his finger, and pointing to Prince Maurice.”“The
parrot answers, ‘Some general -- or other.’ When the man brings the parrot
close to Prince Maurice, Prince Maurice asks the parrot, ‘D'ou venez-vous?’”““The
parrot answers, ‘De Marinnan.’ Then Prince Maurice goes on, and poses a second
question to the parrot.””““‘A qui estes-vous?’ The Parrot answers: ‘A un
Portugais.’”““Prince Maurice then asks a third question: ‘Que fais-tu la?’““The
parrot answers: “Je garde les poulles.’ Prince Maurice smiles, which pleases
the Parrot.”““Prince Maurice, violating a Griceian maxim, and being just
informed that p, asks whether p. This is incidentally the Prince’s fourth
question to the parrot – the first idiotic one. ‘Vous gardez les poulles?’”” ““The Parrot answers, ‘Oui, moi; et je scai bien faire.’
Then the parrott appeals to Peirce’s iconic system and makes the chuck four or
five times that a man uses to make to chickens when a man calls them. I set
down the words of this worthy dialogue in French, just as Prince Maurice said
them to me. I ask Prince Maurice in what ‘tongue’ the parrot speaks.””““Prince
Maurice says that the parrot speaks in the Brazilian tongue.””““ I ask Prince
William whether he understands the Brazilian tongue.”” ““Prince Maurice says:
No, but he has taken care to have TWO interpreters by him, the one a Dutchman
that spoke the Brazilian tongue, and the other a Brazilian that spoke the Dutch
tongue; that Prince Maurice asked them separately and privately, and both of them
AGREED in telling Prince Maurice just the same thing that the parrot had
said.””““I could not but tell this ODD story, because it is so much out of the
way, and from the first hand, and what may pass for a good one; for I dare say
Prince Maurice at least believed himself in all he told me, having ever passed
for a very honest and pious man.””““I leave it to naturalists to reason, and to
other men to believe, as they please upon it. However, it is not, perhaps,
amiss to relieve or enliven a busy scene sometimes with such digressions,
whether to the purpose or no.””Locke takes care “that the reader should have
the story at large in the author's own words, because he seems to me not to
have thought it incredible.”“For it cannot be imagined that so able a man as
he, who had sufficiency enough to warrant all the testimonies he gives of
himself, should take so much pains, in a place where it had nothing to do, to
pin so close, not only on a man whom he mentions as his friend, but on a prince
in whom he acknowledges very great honesty and piety, a story which, if he
himself thought incredible, he could not but also think RIDICULOUS.”“Prince
Maurice, it is plain, who vouches this story, and our author, who relates it
from him, both of them call this talker A PARROT.”Locke asks “any one else who
thinks such a story fit to be told, whether, if this PARROT, and all of its
kind, had always talked, as we have a prince's word for it this one did,-
whether, I say, they would not have passed for a race of RATIONAL ANIMALS; but
yet, whether, for all that, they would have been allowed to be MEN, and not
PARROTS?”“For I presume it is not the idea of A THINKING OR RATIONAL BEING
alone that makes the idea of A MAN in most people's sense: but of A BODY, so
and so shaped, joined to it: and if that be the idea of a MAN, the same
successive body not shifted all at once, must, as well as THE SAME IMMATERIAL
SPIRIT, go to the making of the same MAN.”So
back to Grice’s pirotology, or Pirotologia. But first a precis Grice needs a
dossier with a précis, so that he can insert the parrot’s conversational implicatura
– and Prince Maurice’s. PARROT: What a nice company is here.MAN (pointing to
Prince Maurice): What thinkest thou that man is?PARROT: Some general -- or
other. Grice’s gloss: The he parrot displays what Grice calls ‘up-take.’ The
parrot recognizes the man’s c-intention. So far is ability to display
uptake.PRINCE MAURICE: D'ou venez-vous?PARROT: De Marinnan.PRINCE MAURICE: A
qui estes-vous?PARROT: A un Portugais.PRINCE MAURICE: Que fais-tu la?PARROT: Je
garde les poulles.PRINCE MAURICE SMILES and flouts a Griceian maxim: Vous
gardez les poulles?PARROT (losing patience, and grasping the Prince’s implicaturum
that he doubts it): Oui, moi. Et je scai bien faire.Grice’s gloss: The Parrott appeals
to Peirce’s iconic system and makes the chuck five times that a man uses to
make to chickens when a man calls them.According to his “most recent speculations”
about communication, Grice goes on in his ‘Reply to Richards,’ one should
distinguish, as he engages in a bit of legalese, between two sides of the scenario
under conceptual reduction, E communicates that p. One side is the ‘de facto’
side, a side which, as in name implies, in fact contains any
communication-relevant feature which obtains or is present in the
circumstances. But then there is a ‘de jure’ side to the scenario, viz. the
nested C-intending which is only deemed to be present, as a vicious circle with
good intentions may become a virtuous one. By the ‘nesting,’ Grice means the three
sub-intentions, involved in a scenario where Emissor E communicates that (psi*)
p, reducible to the Emissor E c-intending that A recognises that E psi-s that
p.First, there is the ‘exhibitive’ intention, C1. Emissor E intends A to
recognise that A psi-s that p.Second, there is the ‘reflexive’ intention, C2.Emissor
intends that A recognise C1 by A recognising C2Third, there is the ‘openness’
intention, C3. There is no inference-element which is C-constitutive such that
Emissor relies on it and yet does not intend A to recognise.The “de jure” side
to the state of affairs involves self-reference But since this self-referential
circle, a mere ‘loop,’ is meant to BLOCK an utterly vicious circle of a
regressus ad infinitum (or ‘ho eis apeiron ekballon,’ if you must), the
self-referential circle may well be deemed virtuous. The ‘de jure’ side to the
scenario is trying to save state of affairs which in, in Grice’s words,
“infinitely complex,” and such that no reasonable philosopher should expect to
be realised ‘de facto.’ “In which case,” Grice remarks, “it seems to serve
little, if any, purpose” to assume that this very INCONCEIVABLE ‘de facto’
instantiation of a ‘de jure’ ascription of an emissor communicating that p
would only be detectable, as it isn’t, by appeal to something like ‘die
Deutsche Sprache’!“At its most meagre,” to use Grice’s idiom, the ‘de facto’
side should consist, merely, in any pre-rational ‘counterpart’ to the state of
affairs describable by having an Emissor E communicating that p,This might
amount to no more than making a certain sort of utterance – our doing D1 -- in
order thereby to get some recipient creature R, our second pirot, P2, to think
or want some particular thing, our p. This meagre condition hardly involves
reference to anything like ‘die Deutsche Sprache.’Let’s reformulate the
condition.It’s just a pirot, at a ‘pre-rational’ level. The pirot does a thing
T IN ORDER THEREBY to get some other pirot to think or do some particular
thing. To echo Hare,Die Tur ist geschlossen, ja.Die Tur ist geschlossen,
bitte.Grice continues as a corollary: “Maybe in a less straightforward instance
of “Emissor E communicates that p” there is actually present the C-intention
whose feasibility as an ‘intention’ suggests some ability to use ‘die Deutsche
Sprache.’And if it does, Grice adds, it looks like anything like ‘die Deutsche
Sprache’ ends up being an aid to the conceptualizing about communication, not
communication itself! ReferencesDavidson, Donald
1986. A nice derangement of epitaphs, in Grandy and Warner, pp. 157-74.Durrell,
My family and other animals. Grandy, R. E. and R. O. Warner. 1986.
Philosophical grounds of rationality: intentions, categories, ends. Oxford, at
the Clarendon Press. Grice, H. P. 1986. Reply to Richards, in Grandy and Warner,
pp. 45-106Grice, H. P. 1989. Studies in the Way of Words. London and Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press.Grice, H. P. 2001. Aspects of reason. Oxford,
at the Clarendon Press. Locke, J. 1690. An essay concerning humane [sic]
understanding. Oxford: The Bodleian. Schiffer, S. R. 1988. Meaning. Oxford, at
the Clarendon Press. animatum: Grice thinks of communication
as what he calls ‘soul-to-soul transfer.’ Very Aristotelian. Grice was interested in what he called the
‘rational soul’ (psyche logike). In an act of communication, Emissor
communicates that p, there is a psi involved, therefore a soul, therefore what
the Romans called an ‘anima,’ and the Greeks called the ‘psyche.’ For surely
there can be no psi-transmission without a psi. Grice loved to abbreviate this
as the psi, since Lady Asquith, who was a soul, would not have desired any less
from Grice. Grice, like Plato and Aristotle, holds a tripartite theory of the
soul. Where, ‘part’ (Aristotelian ‘meros’) is taken very seriously. Anything
thought. From ‘psyche,’ anima. Grice uses the symbol of the letter psi here
which he renders as ‘animatum.’ Why Grice prefers ‘soul’ to mind. The
immortality of a the chicken soul. By Shropshire. Shropshire claims that the immortality of the soul is proved by
the fact that, if you cut off a chicken's head, the chicken will run round the
yard for a quarter of an hour before dropping. Grice has an an 'expansion' of
Shropshire's ingenious argument.If the soul is not dependent on the body, it is
immortal. If the soul is dependent on the body, it is dependent on that part of
the body in which it is located. If the soul is located in the body, it is
located in the head. If the chicken's soul were located in its head, the
chicken's soul would be destroyed if the head were rendered inoperative by
removal from the body. The chicken runs round the yard after head-removal. It
could do this only if animated, and controlled by its soul. So the chicken's
soul is not located in, and not dependent on, the chicken's head. So the
chicken's soul is not dependent on the chicken's body. So the chicken's soul is
immortal. end p.11 If the chicken's soul is immortal, a fortiori the human soul
is immortal. So the soul is immortal. The question I now ask myself is this:
why is it that I should be quite prepared to believe that the Harvard students
ascribed their expansion of Botvinnik's proof, or at least some part of it, to
Botvinnik (as what he had in mind), whereas I have no inclination at all to
ascribe any part of my expansion to Shropshire? Considerations which at once
strike me as being likely to be relevant are: (1) that Botvinnik's proof
without doubt contained more steps than Shropshire's claim; (2) that the
expansion of Botvinnik's proof probably imported, as extra premisses, only
propositions which are true, and indeed certain; whereas my expansion imports
premisses which are false or dubious; (3) that Botvinnik was highly intelligent
and an accomplished logician; whereas Shropshire was neither very intelligent
nor very accomplished as a philosopher. No doubt these considerations are
relevant, though one wonders whether one would be much readier to accord
Shropshire's production the title of 'reasoning' if it had contained some further
striking 'deductions', such as that since the soul is immortal moral principles
have absolute validity; and one might also ask whether the effect of (3) does
not nullify that of (2), since, if Shropshire was stupid, why should not one
ascribe to him a reconstructed argument containing plainly unacceptable
premisses? But, mainly, I would like some further light on the following
question: if such considerations as those which I have just mentioned are
relevant, why are they relevant? I should say a word about avowals. The
following contention might be advanced. If you want to know whether someone R,
who has produced what may be an incomplete piece of reasoning, has a particular
completion in mind, the direct way to find out is to ask him. That would settle
the matter. If, however, you are unable to ask him, then indirect methods will
have to be used, which may well be indecisive. Indeterminacy springs merely
from having to rely on indirect methods. I have two comments to make. First: it
end p.12 is far from clear to what extent avowals do settle the matter. Anyone
who has taught philosophy is familiar with the situation in which, under
pressure to expand an argument they have advanced, students, particularly
beginners, make statements which, one is inclined to say, misrepresent their
position. This phenomenon is perhaps accounted for by my much more important
second point: that avowals in this kind of context generally do not have the
character which one might without reflection suppose them to have; they are not
so much reportive as constructive. If I ask someone if he thinks that so-and-so
is a consequence of such-and-such, what I shall receive will be primarily a
defence of this supposition, not a report on what, historically, he had in mind
in making it. We are in general much more interested in whether an inferential
step is a good one to make than we are in what a particular person had in mind
at the actual moment at which he made the step. One might perhaps see an
analogy between avowals in this area and the specification of plans. If someone
has propounded a plan for achieving a certain objective, and I ask him what he
proposes to do in such-and-such a contingency, I expect him to do the best he
can to specify for me a way of meeting that contingency, rather than to give a
historically correct account of what thoughts he had been entertaining. This
feature of what I might call inferential avowals is one for which we shall have
to account.Let us take stock. The thesis which we proposed for examination has
needed emendation twice, once in the face of the possibility of bad reasoning,
and once to allow for informal and incomplete reasoning. The reformulation
needed to accommodate the latter is proving difficult to reach. Let us take s
and s′ to be sequences consisting of a set of premisses and a conclusion (or,
perhaps it would be better to say, a set of propositions and a further
proposition), or a sequence (sorites) of such sequences. (This is not fully
accurate, but will serve.) Let us suppose that x has produced s (in speech or
in thought). Let "formally cogent" mean "having true premisses,
and being such that steps from premisses to conclusions are formally
valid". (1) We cannot define "s is a piece of reasoning by x" as
"x thinks s to be formally cogent", because if s is an incomplete
piece of reasoning s is not, and could not reasonably be thought by x to be,
formally cogent. end p.13 (2) We cannot define "s is a piece of reasoning
by x" as "(∃s′)
(s′ is an expansion of s and s′ is formally cogent)" because (a) it does
not get in the idea that x thinks s′ formally cogent and (b) it would exclude
bad reasoning. (3) We cannot define "s is a piece of reasoning by x"
as "x thinks that (∃s′)
(s′ is an expansion of s and s′ is formally cogent)", for this is too
weak, and would allow as reasoning any case in which x believed (for whatever
reason, or lack of reason) that an informal sequence had some formally cogent
expansion or other. (Compare perhaps Shropshire.).” In Latin indeed, ‘animus’
and ‘anima’ make a world of a difference, as Shropshire well knows. Psyche
transliterates as ‘anima’ only; ‘animus’ the Greeks never felt the need for. Of
course a chicken is an animal, as in man. “Homo animalis rationalis.” Grice
prefers ‘human,’ but sometimes he uses ‘animal,’ as opposed to ‘vegetal,
sometimes, when considering stages of freedom. A stone (mineral) displays a
‘free’ fall, which is metabolical. And then, a vegetable is less free than an
animal, which can move, and a non-human animal (that Grice calls ‘a beast’) is
less free than man, who is a rational animal. Grice notes that back in the day,
when the prince came from a hunt, “I brought some animals,” since these were
‘deer,’ ‘deer’ was taken as meaning ‘animal,’ when the implicaturum was very
much cancellable. The Anglo-Saxons soon dropped the ‘deer’ and adopted the
Latinate ‘animal.’ They narrowed the use of ‘deer’ for the ‘cervus cervus.’ But
not across the North Sea where the zoo is still called a ‘deer-garden.’ When
Aelfric studied philosophy he once thought man was a rational deer. animatum – vide: H. P. Grice, “Psychology, folk
psychology, etc.” -- philosophy of psychology, the philosophical study of
psychology. Psychology began to separate from philosophy with the work of the
nineteenth-century G. experimentalists, especially Fechner 180187, Helmholtz
1821 94, and Wundt 18320. In the first half of the twentieth century, the
separation was completed in this country insofar as separate psychology
departments were set up in most universities, psychologists established their
own journals and professional associations, and experimental methods were
widely employed, although not in every area of psychology the first
experimental study of the effectiveness of a psychological therapy did not
occur until 3. Despite this achievement of autonomy, however, issues have
remained about the nature of the connections, if any, that should continue
between psychology and philosophy. One radical view, that virtually all such
connections should be severed, was defended by the behaviorist John Watson in
his seminal 3 paper “Psychology as the Behaviorist Views It.” Watson criticizes
psychologists, even the experimentalists, for relying on introspective methods
and for making consciousness the subject matter of their discipline. He
recommends that psychology be a purely objective experimental branch of natural
science, that its theoretical goal be to predict and control behavior, and that
it discard all reference to consciousness. In making behavior the sole subject
of psychological inquiry, we avoid taking sides on “those time-honored relics
of philosophical speculation,” namely competing theories about the mindbody
problem, such as interactionism and parallelism. In a later work, published in
5, Watson claimed that the success of behaviorism threatened the very existence
of philosophy: “With the behavioristic point of view now becoming dominant, it
is hard to find a place for what has been called philosophy. Philosophy is
passing has all but passed, and unless
new issues arise which will give a foundation for a new philosophy, the world
has seen its last great philosopher.” One new issue was the credibility of
behaviorism. Watson gave no argument for his view that prediction and control
of behavior should be the only theoretical goals of psychology. If the attempt
to explain behavior is also legitimate, as some anti-behaviorists argue, then
it would seem to be an empirical question whether that goal can be met without
appealing to mentalistic causes. Watson and his successors, such as B. F.
Skinner, cited no credible empirical evidence that it could, but instead relied
primarily on philosophical arguments for banning postulation of mentalistic
causes. As a consequence, behaviorists virtually guaranteed that philosophers
of psychology would have at least one additional task beyond wrestling with
traditional mind body issues: the analysis and criticism of behaviorism itself.
Although behaviorism and the mindbody problem were never the sole subjects of
philosophy of psychology, a much richer set of topics developed after 0 when
the so-called cognitive revolution occurred in
psychology. These topics include innate knowledge and the acquisition of
transformational grammars, intentionality, the nature of mental representation,
functionalism, mental imagery, the language of thought, and, more recently,
connectionism. Such topics are of interest to many cognitive psychologists and
those in other disciplines, such as linguistics and artificial intelligence,
who contributed to the emerging discipline known as cognitive science. Thus,
after the decline of various forms of behaviorism and the consequent rise of
cognitivism, many philosophers of psychology collaborated more closely with
psychologists. This increased cooperation was probably due not only to a
broadening of the issues, but also to a methodological change in philosophy. In
the period roughly between 5 and 5, conceptual analysis dominated both and English philosophy of psychology and the
closely related discipline, the philosophy of mind. Many philosophers took the
position that philosophy was essentially an a priori discipline. These
philosophers rarely cited the empirical studies of psychologists. In recent
decades, however, philosophy of psychology has become more empirical, at least
in the sense that more attention is being paid to the details of the empirical
studies of psychologists. The result is more interchanges between philosophers
and psychologists. Although interest in cognitive psychology appears to
predominate in recent philosophy of
psychology, the new emphasis on empirical studies is also reflected in
philosophic work on topics not directly related to cognitive psychology. For
example, philosophers of psychology have written books in recent years on the
clinical foundations of psychoanalysis, the foundations of behavior therapy and
behavior modification, and self-deception. The emphasis on empirical data has
been taken one step further by naturalists, who argue that in epistemology, at
least, and perhaps in all areas of philosophy, philosophical questions should
either be replaced by questions from empirical psychology or be answered by
appeal to empirical studies in psychology and related disciplines. It is
philosophy of psychology philosophy of psychology 695 695 still too early to predict the
fruitfulness of the naturalist approach, but this new trend might well have
pleased Watson. Taken to an extreme, naturalism would make philosophy dependent
on psychology instead of the reverse and thus would further enhance the autonomy
of psychology that Watson desired. animatum -- philosophical psychology, --
vide H. P. Grice: “Method in philosophical psychology: from the banal to the
bizarre” – in “Conception of Value,” Oxford, Clarendon Press. -- philosophy of
mind, the branch of philosophy that includes the philosophy of psychology,
philosophical psychology, and the area of metaphysics concerned with the nature
of mental phenomena and how they fit into the causal structure of reality.
Philosophy of psychology, a branch of the philosophy of science, examines what
psychology says about the nature of psychological phenomena; examines aspects
of psychological theorizing such as the models used, explanations offered, and
laws invoked; and examines how psychology fits with the social sciences and
natural sciences. Philosophical psychology investigates folk psychology, a body
of commonsensical, protoscientific views about mental phenomena. Such
investigations attempt to articulate and refine views found in folk psychology
about conceptualization, memory, perception, sensation, consciousness, belief,
desire, intention, reasoning, action, and so on. The mindbody problem, a
central metaphysical one in the philosophy of mind, is the problem of whether
mental phenomena are physical and, if not, how they are related to physical
phenomena. Other metaphysical problems in the philosophy of mind include the
free will problem, the problem of personal identity, and the problem of how, if
at all, irrational phenomena such as akrasia and self-deception are possible.
Mindbody dualism Cartesian dualism. The doctrine that the soul is distinct from
the body is found in Plato and discussed throughout the history of philosophy,
but Descartes is considered the father of the modern mindbody problem. He
maintained that the essence of the physical is extension in space. Minds are
unextended substances and thus are distinct from any physical substances. The
essence of a mental substance is to think. This twofold view is called
Cartesian dualism. Descartes was well aware of an intimate relationship between
mind and the brain. There is no a priori reason to think that the mind is
intimately related to the brain; Aristotle, e.g., did not associate them.
Descartes mistakenly thought the seat of the relationship was in the pineal
gland. He maintained, however, that our minds are not our brains, lack spatial
location, and can continue to exist after the death and destruction of our
bodies. Cartesian dualism invites the question: What connects the mind and
brain? Causation is Descartes’s answer: states of our minds causally interact
with states of our brains. When bodily sensations such as aches, pains, itches,
and tickles cause us to moan, wince, scratch, or laugh, they do so by causing
brain states events, processes, which in turn cause bodily movements. In deliberate
action, we act on our desires, motives, and intentions to carry out our
purposes; and acting on these mental states involves their causing brain
states, which in turn cause our bodies to move, thereby causally influencing
the physical world. The physical world, in turn, influences our minds through
its influence on our brains. Perception of the physical world with five
senses sight, hearing, smell, taste, and
touch involves causal transactions from
the physical to the mental: what we perceive i.e., see, hear, etc. causes a
sense experience i.e., a visual experience, aural experience, etc.. Thus,
Descartes held that there is two-way psychophysical causal interaction: from
the mental to the physical as in action and from the physical to the mental as
in perception. The conjunction of Cartesian dualism and the doctrine of two-way
psychophysical causal interaction is called Cartesian interactionism. Perhaps
the most widely discussed difficulty for this view is how states of a
non-spatial substance a mind can causally interact with states of a substance
that is in space a brain. Such interactions have seemed utterly mysterious to
many philosophers. Mystery would remain even if an unextended mind is locatable
at a point in space say, the center of the pineal gland. For Cartesian
interactionism would still have to maintain that causal transactions between
mental states and brain states are fundamental, i.e., unmediated by any
underlying mechanism. Brain states causally interact with mental states, but
there is no answer to the question of how they do so. The interactions are
brute facts. Many philosophers, including many of Descartes’s contemporaries,
have found that difficult to accept. Parallelism. Malebranche and Leibniz,
among others, rejected the possibility of psychophysical causal interaction.
They espoused versions of parallelism: the view that the mental and physical
realms run in parallel, in that types of mental phenomena co-occur with certain
types of physical phenomena, but these co-occurrences never involve causal
interactions. On all extant versions, the parallels hold because of God’s
creation. Leibniz’s parallelism is preestablished harmony: the explanation of
why mental types and certain physical types co-occur is that in the possible
world God actualized i.e., this world they co-occur. In discussing the relation
between the mental and physical realms, Leibniz used the analogy of two
synchronized but unconnected clocks. The analogy is, however, somewhat
misleading; suggesting causal mechanisms internal to each clock and intramental
and intraphysical causal transactions. But Leibniz’s monadology doctrine
excludes the possibility of such transactions: mental and physical phenomena
have no effects even within their own realms. Malebranche is associated with
occasionalism, according to which only God, through his continuous activities,
causes things to happen: non-divine phenomena never cause anything.
Occasionalism differs from preestablished harmony in holding that God is
continually engaged in acts of creation; each moment creating the world anew,
in such a way that the correlations hold. Both brands of parallelism face
formidable difficulties. First, both rest on highly contentious, obscure
theological hypotheses. The contention that God exists and the creation stories
in question require extensive defense and explanation. God’s relationship to
the world can seem at least as mysterious as the relationship Descartes posits
between minds and brains. Second, since parallelism denies the possibility of psychophysical
interaction, its proponents must offer alternatives to the causal theory of
perception and the causal theory of action or else deny that we can perceive
and that we can act intentionally. Third, since parallelism rejects intramental
causation, it must either deny that reasoning is possible or explain how it is
possible without causal connections between thoughts. Fourth, since parallelism
rejects physical transactions, it is hard to see how it can allow, e.g., that
one physical thing ever moves another; for that would require causing a change
in location. Perhaps none of these weighty difficulties is ultimately
insuperable; in any case, parallelism has been abandoned. Epiphenomenalism.
Empirical research gives every indication that the occurrence of any brain
state can, in principle, be causally explained by appeal solely to other
physical states. To accommodate this, some philosophers espoused
epiphenomenalism, the doctrine that physical states cause mental states, but
mental states do not cause anything. This thesis was discussed under the name
‘conscious automatism’ by Huxley and Hogeson in the late nineteenth century.
William James was the first to use the term ‘epiphenomena’ to mean phenomena
that lack causal efficacy. And James Ward coined the term ‘epiphenomenalism’ in
3. Epiphenomenalism implies that there is only one-way psychophysical
action from the physical to the mental.
Since epiphenomenalism allows such causal action, it can embrace the causal theory
of perception. However, when combined with Cartesian dualism, epiphenomenalism,
like Cartesian interactionism, implies the problematic thesis that states of an
extended substance can affect states of an unextended substance. An
epiphenomenalist can avoid this problem by rejecting the view that the mind is
an unextended substance while maintaining that mental states and events are
nonetheless distinct from physical states and events. Still, formidable
problems would remain. It is hard to see how epiphenomenalism can allow that we
are ever intentional agents. For intentional agency requires acting on reasons,
which, according to the causal theory of action, requires a causal connection
between reasons and actions. Since epiphenomenalism denies that such causal
connections are possible, it must either maintain that our sense of agency is
illusory or offer an alternative to the causal theory of action. Similarly, it
must explain how thinking is possible given that there are no causal
connections between thoughts. Monism The dual-aspect theory. Many philosophers
reject Descartes’s bifurcation of reality into mental and physical substances.
Spinoza held a dualattribute theory also
called the dual-aspect theory according
to which the mental and the physical are distinct modes of a single substance,
God. The mental and the physical are only two of infinitely many modes of this
one substance. Many philosophers opted for a thoroughgoing monism, according to
which all of reality is really of one kind. Materialism, idealism, and neutral
monism are three brands of monism. Hobbes, a contemporary of Descartes,
espoused materialism, the brand of monism according to which everything is
material or physical. Berkeley is associated with idealism, the brand of monism
according to which everything is mental. He held that both mental and physical
phenomena are perceptions in the mind of God. For Hegel’s idealism, everything
is part of the World Spirit. The early twentieth-century British philosophers
Bradley and McTaggart also held a version of idealism. Neutral monism is the
doctrine that all of reality is ultimately of one kind, which is neither mental
nor physical. Hume was a neutral monist, maintaining that mental and physical
substances are really just bundles of the neutral entities. Versions of neutral
monism were later held by Mach and, for a short time, Russell. Russell called
his neutral entities sensibilia and claimed that minds and physical objects are
logical constructions out of them. Phenomenalism. This view, espoused in the
twentieth century by, among others, Ayer, argues that all empirical statements
are synonymous with statements solely about phenomenal appearances. While the
doctrine is about statements, phenomenalism is either a neutral monism or an
idealism, depending on whether phenomenal appearances are claimed to be neither
mental nor physical or, instead, mental. The required translations of physical
statements into phenomenal ones proved not to be forthcoming, however. Chisholm
offered a reason why they would not be: what appearances a physical state of
affairs e.g., objects arrayed in a room has depends both on physical conditions
of observation e.g., lighting and physical conditions of the perceiver e.g., of
the nervous system. At best, a statement solely about phenomenal appearances is
equivalent to one about a physical state of affairs, only when certain physical
conditions of observation and certain physical conditions of the perceiver
obtain. Materialism. Two problems face any monism: it must characterize the
phenomena it takes as basic, and it must explain how the fundamental phenomena
make up non-basic phenomena. The idealist and neutral monist theories proposed
thus far have faltered on one or both counts. Largely because of scientific
successes of the twentieth century, such as the rebirth of the atomic theory of
matter, and the successes of quantum mechanics in explaining chemistry and of
chemistry in turn in explaining much of biology, many philosophers today hold
that materialism will ultimately succeed where idealism and neutral monism
apparently failed. Materialism, however, comes in many different varieties and
each faces formidable difficulties. Logical behaviorism. Ryle ridiculed
Cartesianism as the view that there is a ghost in the machine the body. He
claimed that the view that the mind is a substance rests on a category mistake:
‘mind’ is a noun, but does not name an object. Cartesianism confuses the logic
of discourse about minds with the logic of discourse about bodies. To have a
mind is not to possess a special sort of entity; it is simply to have certain
capacities and dispositions. Compare the thesis that to be alive is to possess
not a certain entity, an entelechy or élan vital, but rather certain capacities
and dispositions. Ryle maintained, moreover, that it was a mistake to regard
mental states such as belief, desire, and intention as internal causes of
behavior. These states, he claimed, are dispositions to behave in overt ways.
In part in response to the dualist point that one can understand our ordinary
psychological vocabulary ‘belief’, ‘desire’, ‘pain’, etc. and know nothing
about the physical states and events in the brain, logical behaviorism has been
proposed as a materialist doctrine that explains this fact. On this view, talk
of mental phenomena is shorthand for talk of actual and potential overt bodily
behavior i.e., dispositions to overt bodily behavior. Logical behaviorism was
much discussed from roughly the 0s until the early 0s. While Ryle is sometimes
counted as a logical behaviorist, he was not committed to the thesis that all
mental talk can be tr. into behavioral talk. The translations promised by
logical behaviorism appear unachievable. As Putnam and others pointed out, one
can fake being in pain and one can be in pain and yet not behave or be disposed
to behave as if one were in pain e.g., one might be paralyzed or might be a
“super-spartan”. Logical behaviorism faces similar difficulties in translating
sentences about what Russell called propositional attitudes i.e., beliefs that
p, desires that p, hopes that p, intentions that p, and the like. Consider the
following sample proposal similar to one offered by Carnap: one believes that
the cat is on the mat if and only if one is disposed to assent to ‘The cat is
on the mat’. First, the proposed translation meets the condition of being
purely behavioral only if assenting is understandable in purely behavioral
terms. That is doubtful. The proposal also fails to provide a sufficient or a
necessary condition: someone may assent to ‘The cat is on the mat’ and yet not
believe the cat is on the mat for the person may be trying to deceive; and a
belief that the cat is on the mat will dispose one to assent to ‘The cat is on
the mat’ only if one understands what is being asked, wants to indicate that
one believes the cat is on the mat, and so on. But none of these conditions is
required for believing that the cat is on the mat. Moreover, to invoke any of
these mentalistic conditions defeats the attempt to provide a purely behavioral
translation of the belief sentence. Although the project of translation has
been abandoned, in recent years Dennett has defended a view in the spirit of
logical behaviorism, intentional systems theory: belief-desire talk functions
to characterize overall patterns of dispositions to overt behavior in an
environmental context for the purposes of predicting overt behavior. The theory
is sometimes characterized as supervenient behaviorism since it implies that
whether an individual has beliefs, desires, intentions and the like supervenes
on his dispositions to overt behavior: if two individuals are exactly alike in
respect of their dispositions to overt behavior, the one has intentional states
if and only if the other does. This view allows, however, that the contents of
an individual’s intentional states what
the individual believes, desires, etc.
may depend on environmental factors. So it is not committed to the
supervenience of the contents of intentional states on dispositions to overt
behavior.the discussion of content externalism below. One objection to this
view, due to Ned Block, is that it would mistakenly count as an intentional
agent a giant look-up table “a
Blockhead” that has the same
dispositions to peripheral behavior as a genuine intentional agent. A look-up
table is a simple mechanical device that looks up preprogrammed responses.
Identity theories. In the early 0s, Herbert Feigl claimed that mental states
are brain states. He pointed out that if mental properties or state types are
merely nomologically correlated with physical properties or state types, the
connecting laws would be “nomological danglers”: irreducible to physical laws,
and thus additional fundamental laws. According to the identity theory, the
connecting laws are not fundamental laws and so not nomological danglers since
they can be explained by identifying the mental and physical properties in
question. In the late 0s and the early 0s, the philosopher Smart and the
psychologist U. T. Place defended the materialist view that sensations are
identical with brain processes. Smart claimed that while mental terms differ in
meaning from physical terms, scientific investigation reveals that they have
the same referents as certain physical terms. Compare the fact that while ‘the
Morning Star’ and ‘the Evening Star’ differ in meaning empirical investigation
reveals the same referent: Venus. Smart and Place claimed that feeling pain,
e.g., is some brain process, exactly which one to be determined by scientific
investigation. Smart claimed that sensation talk is paraphraseable in
topic-neutral terms; i.e., in terms that leave open whether sensational
properties are mental or physical. ‘I have an orange afterimage’ is
paraphraseable roughly as: ‘There is something going on like what is going on
when I have my eyes open, am awake, and there is an orange illuminated in good
light in front of me, i.e., when I really see an orange’. The description is
topic-neutral since it leaves open whether what is going on is mental or
physical. Smart maintained that scientific investigation reveals that what in
fact meets the topic-neutral description is a brain process. He held that
psychophysical identity statements such as ‘Pain is C-fiber firing’ are
contingent, likening these to, e.g., ‘Lightning is electrical discharge’, which
is contingent and knowable only through empirical investigation. Central state
materialism. This brand of materialism was defended in the late 0s and the
early 0s by Armstrong and others. On this view, mental states are states that
are apt to produce a certain range of behavior. Central state materialists
maintain that scientific investigation reveals that such states are states of
the central nervous system, and thus that mental states are contingently
identical with states of the central nervous system. Unlike logical behaviorism,
central state materialism does not imply that mental sentences can be tr. into
physical sentences. Unlike both logical behaviorism and philosophy of mind
philosophy of mind 687 687 intentional
systems theory, central state materialism implies that mental states are actual
internal states with causal effects. And unlike Cartesian interactionism, it
holds that psychophysical interaction is just physical causal interaction. Some
central state materialists held in addition that the mind is the brain.
However, if the mind were the brain, every change in the brain would be a
change in the mind; and that seems false: not every little brain change amounts
to a change of mind. Indeed, the mind ceases to exist when brain death occurs,
while the brain continues to exist. The moral that most materialists nowadays
draw from such considerations is that the mind is not any physical substance,
since it is not a substance of any sort. To have a mind is not to possess a
special substance, but rather to have certain capacities to think, feel, etc. To that extent, Ryle was
right. However, central state materialists insist that the properly functioning
brain is the material seat of mental capacities, that the exercise of mental
capacities consists of brain processes, and that mental states are brain states
that can produce behavior. Epistemological objections have been raised to
identity theories. As self-conscious beings, we have a kind of privileged
access to our own mental states. The exact avenue of privileged access, whether
it is introspection or not, is controversial. But it has seemed to many
philosophers that our access to our own mental states is privileged in being
open only to us, whereas we lack any privileged access to the states of our
central nervous systems. We come to know about central nervous system states in
the same way we come to know about the central nervous system states of others.
So, against central state materialism and the identity theory, it is claimed
that mental states cannot be states of our central nervous systems. Taking
privileged access to imply that we have incorrigible knowledge of our conscious
mental states, and despairing of squaring privileged access so understood with
materialism, Rorty advocated eliminative materialism, the thesis that there
actually are no mental phenomena. A more common materialist response, however,
is to deny that privileged access entails incorrigibility and to maintain that
privileged access is compatible with materialism. Some materialists maintain that
while certain types of mental states e.g., sensations are types of neurological
states, it will be knowable only by empirical investigation that they are.
Suppose pain is a neural state N. It will be only a posteriori knowable that
pain is N. Via the avenue of privileged access, one comes to believe that one
is in a pain state, but not that one is in an N-state. One can believe one is
in a pain state without believing that one is in an N-state because the concept
of pain is different from the concept of N. Nevertheless, pain is N. Compare
the fact that while water is H2O, the concept of water is different from that
of H2O. Thus, while water is H2O, one can believe there is water in the glass
without believing that there is H2O in it. The avenue of privileged access
presents N conceptualized as pain, but never as neurological state N. The
avenue of privileged access involves the exercise of mental, but not
neurophysiological, concepts. However, our mental concepts answer to apply in virtue of the same properties state types as do certain
of our neurophysiological concepts. The identity theory and central state
materialism both hold that there are contingent psychophysical property and
type identities. Some theorists in this tradition tried to distinguish a notion
of theoretical identity from the notion of strict identity. They held that
mental states are theoretically, but not strictly, identical with brain states.
Against any such distinction, Kripke argued that identities are metaphysically
necessary, i.e., hold in every possible world. If A % B, then necessarily A %
B. Kripke acknowledged that there can be contingent statements of identity. But
such statements, he argued, will employ at least one term that is not a rigid
designator, i.e., a term that designates the same thing in every world in which
it designates anything. Thus, since ‘the inventor of bifocals’ is a non-rigid
designator, ‘Benjamin Franklin is the inventor of bifocals’ is contingent.
While Franklin is the inventor of bifocals, he might not have been. However,
statements of identity in which the identity sign is flanked by rigid
designators are, if true, metaphysically necessary. Kripke held that proper
names are rigid designators, and hence, the true identity statement ‘Cicero is
Tully’ is metaphysically necessary. Nonetheless, a metaphysically necessary
identity statement can be knowable only a posteriori. Indeed, ‘Cicero is Tully’
is knowable only a posteriori. Both ‘water’ and ‘H2O’, he maintained, are rigid
designators: each designates the same kind of stuff in every possible world.
And he thus maintained that it is metaphysically necessary that water is H2O,
despite its not being a priori knowable that water is H2O. On Kripke’s view,
any psychophysical identity statement that employs mental terms and physical
terms that are rigid designators will also be metaphysically necessary, if
true. Central state materialists maintain that mental concepts are equivalent
to concepts whose descriptive content is the state that is apt to produce such-and-such
behavior in such-and-such circumstances. These defining descriptions for mental
concepts are intended to be meaning-giving, not contingent reference-fixing
descriptions; they are, moreover, not rigid designators. Thus, the central
state materialists can concede that all identities are necessary, but maintain
that psychophysical claims of identity are contingent claims of identity since
the mental terms that figure in those statements are not rigid designators.
However, Kripke maintained that our concepts of sensations and other
qualitative states are not equivalent to the sorts of descriptions in question.
The term ‘pain’, he maintained, is a rigid designator. This position might be
refuted by a successful functional analysis of the concept of pain in physical
and/or topic-neutral terms. However, no successful analysis of this sort has
yet been produced. See the section on consciousness below. A materialist can
grant Kripke that ‘pain’ is a rigid designator and claim that a statement such
as ‘Pain is C-fiber firing’ will be metaphysically necessary if true, but only
a posteriori knowable. However, Kripke raised a formidable problem for this
materialism. He pointed out that if a statement is metaphysically necessary but
only a posteriori knowable, its appearance of contingency calls for
explanation. Despite being metaphysically necessary, ‘Water is H2O’ appears
contingent. According to Kripke, we explain this appearance by noting that one
can coherently imagine a world in which something has all the phenomenal
properties of water, and so is an “epistemic counterpart” of it, yet is not
H2O. The fact that we can coherently imagine such epistemic counterparts
explains why ‘Water is H2O’ appears contingent. But no such explanation is
available for e.g. ‘Pain is C-fiber firing’. For an epistemic counterpart of
pain, something with the phenomenal properties of pain the feel of pain is pain. Something can look, smell, taste,
and feel like water yet not be water. But whatever feels like pain is pain:
pain is a feeling. In contrast, we can explain the apparent contingency of
claims like ‘Water is H2O’ because water is not constituted by its phenomenal
properties; our concept of water allows that it may have a “hidden essence,”
i.e., an essential microstructure. If Kripke is right, then anyone who
maintains that a statement of identity concerning a type of bodily sensation
and a type of physical state is metaphysically necessary yet a posteriori, must
explain the appearance of contingency in a way that differs from the way Kripke
explains the appearance of contingency of ‘Water is H2O’. This is a formidable
challenge. The final section, on consciousness, sketches some materialist
responses to it. The general issue of property and state type identity is
controversial. The claim that water is H2O despite the fact that the concept of
water is distinct from the concept of H2O seems plausible. However, property or
state type identity is more controversial than the identity of types of
substances. For properties or state types, there are no generally accepted
“non-duplication principles” to use a
phrase of David Lewis’s. A nonduplication principle for A’s will say that no
two A’s can be exactly alike in a certain respect; e.g., no two sets can have
exactly the same members. It is widely denied, for instance, that no two
properties can be possessed by exactly the same things. Two properties, it is
claimed, can be possessed by the same things; likewise, two state types can
occur in the same space-time regions. Even assuming that mental concepts are
distinct from physical concepts, the issue of whether mental state types are
physical state types raises the controversial issue of the non-duplication
principle for state types. Token and type physicalisms. Token physicalism is
the thesis that every particular is physical. Type physicalism is the thesis
that every type or kind of entity is physical; thus, the identity thesis and
central state materialism are type physicalist theses since they imply that
types of mental states are types of physical states. Type physicalism implies
token physicalism: given the former, every token falls under some physical
type, and therefore is token-token identical with some token of a physical
type. But token physicalism does not imply type physicalism; the former leaves
open whether physical tokens fall under non-physical types. Some doctrines
billed as materialist or physicalist embrace token epiphenomenalism, but reject
type physicalism. Non-reductive materialism. This form of materialism implies token
physicalism, but denies type physicalism and, as well, that mental types
properties, etc. are reducible to physical types. This doctrine has been
discussed since at least the late nineteenth century and was widely discussed
in the first third of the twentieth century. The British philosophers George
Henry Lewes, Samuel Alexander, Lloyd Morgan, and C. D. Broad all held or
thought plausible a certain version of non-reductive materialism. They held or
sympathized with the view that every substance philosophy of mind philosophy of
mind 689 689 either is or is wholly
made up of physical particles, that the well-functioning brain is the material
seat of mental capacities, and that token mental states events, processes, etc.
are token neurophysiological states events, processes, etc.. However, they
either held or thought plausible the view that mental capacities, properties,
etc., emerge from, and thus do not reduce to, physical capacities, properties,
etc. Lewes coined the term ‘emergence’; and Broad later labeled the doctrine
emergent materialism. Emergent materialists maintain that laws correlating
mental and physical properties are irreducible. These laws would be what Feigl
called nomological danglers. Emergentists maintain that, despite their
untidiness, such laws must be accepted with natural piety. Davidson’s doctrine
of anomalous monism is a current brand of non-reductive materialism. He
explicitly formulates this materialist thesis for events; and his
irreducibility thesis is restricted to intentional mental types e.g., believings, desirings, and intendings.
Anomalous monism says that every event token is physical, but that intentional
mental predicates and concepts ones expressing propositional attitudes do not reduce,
by law or definition, to physical predicates or concepts. Davidson offers an
original argument for this irreducibility thesis. Mental predicates and
concepts are, he claims, governed by constitutive principles of rationality,
but physical predicates and concepts are not. This difference, he contends,
excludes the possibility of reduction of mental predicates and concepts to
physical ones. Davidson denies, moreover, that there are strict psychological
or psychophysical laws. He calls the conjunction of this thesis and his
irreducibility thesis the principle of the anomalism of the mental. His
argument for token physicalism for events appeals to the principle of the
anomalism of the mental and to the principle of the nomological character of
causality: when two events are causally related, they are subsumed by a strict
law. He maintains that all strict laws are physical. Given that claim, and
given the principle of the nomological character of causality, it follows that
every event that is a cause or effect is a physical event. On this view, psychophysical
causation is just causation between physical events. Stephen Schiffer has also
maintained a non-reductive materialism, one he calls ontological physicalism
and sentential dualism: every particular is physical, but mental truths are
irreducible to physical truths. Non-reductive materialism presupposes that
mental state event tokens can fall under physical state types and, thereby,
count as physical state tokens. This presupposition is controversial; no
uncontroversial non-duplication principle for state tokens settles the issue.
Suppose, however, that mental state tokens are physical state tokens, despite
mental state types not being physical state types. The issue of how mental
state types and physical state types are related remains. Suppose that some
physical token x is of a mental type M say, a belief that the cat is on the mat
and some other physical token y is not of type M. There must, it seems, be some
difference between x and y in virtue of which x is, and y is not, of type M.
Otherwise, it is simply a brute fact that x is and y is not of type M. That,
however, seems implausible. The claim that certain physical state tokens fall
under mental state types simply as a matter of brute fact would leave the
difference in question utterly mysterious. But if it is not a brute fact, then
there is some explanation of why a certain physical state is a mental state of
a certain sort. The non-reductive materialist owes us an explanation that does
not imply psychophysical reduction. Moreover, even though the non-reductive
materialist can claim that mental states are causes because they are physical
states with physical effects, there is some question whether mental state types
are relevant to causal relations. Suppose every state is a physical state. Given
that physical states causally interact in virtue of falling under physical
types, it follows that whenever states causally interact they do so in virtue
of falling under physical types. That raises the issue of whether states are
ever causes in virtue of falling under mental types. Type epiphenomenalism is
the thesis that no state can cause anything in virtue of falling under a mental
type. Token epiphenomenalism, the thesis that no mental state can cause
anything, implies type epiphenomenalism, but not conversely. Nonreductive
materialists are not committed to token physicalism. However, token
epiphenomenalism may be false but type epiphenomenalism true since mental
states may be causes only in virtue of falling under physical types, never in
virtue of falling under mental types. Broad raised the issue of type
epiphenomenalism and discussed whether emergent materialism is committed to it.
Ted Honderich, Jaegwon Kim, Ernest Sosa, and others have in recent years raised
the issue of whether non-reductive materialism is committed to type
epiphenomenalism. Brian McLaughlin has argued that the claim that an event acts
as a cause in virtue of falling under a certain physical type is consistent
with the claim that it also acts as a cause in virtue of falling under a
certain mental type, even when the mental type is not identical with the
physical type. But even if this is so, the relationship between mental types
and physical types must be addressed. Ernest LePore and Barry Loewer, Frank
Jackson and Philip Pettit, Stephen Yablo, and others have attempted to
characterize a relation between mental types and physical types that allows for
the causal relevance of mental types. But whether there is a relation between
mental and physical properties that is both adequate to secure the causal
relevance of mental properties and available to non-reductive materialists
remains an open question. Davidson’s anomalous monism may appear to be a kind
of dual-aspect theory: there are events and they can have two sorts of
autonomous aspects, mental and physical. However, while Davidson holds that
mental properties or types do not reduce to physical ones, he also holds that
the mental properties of an event depend on its physical properties in that the
former supervene on the latter in this sense: no two events can be exactly
alike in every physical respect and yet differ in some mental respect. This
proposal introduced the notion of supervenience into contem- porary philosophy
of mind. Often nonreductive materialists argue that mental properties types
supervene on physical properties types. Kim, however, has distinguished various
supervenience relations, and argues that some are too weak to count as versions
of materialism as opposed to, say, dual-aspect theory, while other supervenience
relations are too strong to use to formulate non-reductive materialism since
they imply reducibility. According to Kim, non-reductive materialism is an
unstable position. Materialism as a supervenience thesis. Several philosophers
have in recent years attempted to define the thesis of materialism using a
global supervenience thesis. Their aim is not to formulate a brand of
non-reductive materialism; they maintain that their supervenience thesis may
well imply reducibility. Their aim is, rather, to formulate a thesis to which
anyone who counts as a genuine materialist must subscribe. David Lewis has
maintained that materialism is true if and only if any non-alien possible
worlds that are physically indiscernible are mentally indiscernible as well.
Non-alien possible worlds are worlds that have exactly the same perfectly
natural properties as the actual world. Frank Jackson has offered this
proposal: materialism is true if and only if any minimal physical duplicate of
the actual world is a duplicate simpliciter of the actual world. A world is a
physical duplicate of the actual world if and only if it is exactly like the
actual world in every physical respect physical particular for physical
particular, physical property for physical property, physical relation for
physical relation, etc.; and a world is a duplicate simpliciter of the actual
world if and only if it is exactly like the actual world in every respect. A
minimal physical duplicate of the actual world is a physical duplicate that
contains nothing else by way of particulars, kinds, properties, etc. than it
must in order to be a physical duplicate of the actual world. Two questions
arise for any formulation of the thesis of materialism. Is it adequate to
materialism? And, if it is, is it true? Functionalism. The nineteenth-century
British philosopher George Henry Lewes maintained that while not every
neurological event is mental, every mental event is neurological. He claimed
that what makes certain neurological events mental events is their causal role in
the organism. This is a very early version of functionalism, nowadays a leading
approach to the mindbody problem. Functionalism implies an answer to the
question of what makes a state token a mental state of a certain kind M:
namely, that it is an instance of some functional state type identical with M.
There are two versions of this proposal. On one, a mental state type M of a
system will be identical with the state type that plays a certain causal role R
in the system. The description ‘the state type that plays R in the system’ will
be a nonrigid designator; moreover, different state types may play R in
different organisms, in which case the mental state is multiply realizable. On
the second version, a mental state type M is identical with a second-order
state type, the state of being in some first-order state that plays causal role
R. More than one first-order state may play role R, and thus M may be multiply
realizable. On either version, if the relevant causal roles are specifiable in
physical or topic-neutral terms, then the functional definitions of mental
state types will be, in principle, physically reductive. Since the roles would
be specified partly in topic-neutral terms, there may well be possible worlds
in which the mental states are realized by non-physical states; thus,
functionalism does not imply token physicalism. However, functionalists
typically maintain that, on the empirical evidence, mental states are realized
in our world only by physical states. Functionalism comes in many varieties.
philosophy of mind philosophy of mind 691
691 Smart’s topic-neutral analysis of our talk of sensations is in the
spirit of functionalism. And Armstrong’s central state materialism counts as a
kind of functionalism since it maintains that mental states are states apt to
produce a certain range of behavior, and thus identifies states as mental
states by their performing this causal role. However, functionalists today
typically hold that the defining causal roles include causal roles vis-à-vis
input state types, as well as output state types, and also vis-à-vis other
internal state types of the system in question. In the 0s David Lewis proposed
a functionalist theory, analytical functionalism, according to which
definitions of mental predicates such as ‘belief’, ‘desire’, and the like
though not predicates such as ‘believes that p’ or ‘desires that q’ can be
obtained by conjoining the platitudes of commonsense psychology and formulating
the Ramsey sentence for the conjunction. The relevant Ramsey sentence is a
second-order quantificational sentence that quantifies over the mental
predicates in the conjunction of commonsense psychological platitudes, and from
it one can derive definitions of the mental predicates. On this view, it will
be analytic that a certain mental state e.g., belief is the state that plays a
certain causal role vis-à-vis other states; and it is a matter of empirical
investigation what state plays the role. Lewis claimed that such investigation
reveals that the state types that play the roles in question are physical
states. In the early 0s, Putnam proposed a version of scientific functionalism,
machine state functionalism: according to this view, mental states are types of
Turing machine table states. Turing machines are mechanical devices consisting
of a tape with squares on it that either are blank or contain symbols, and an
executive that can move one square to the left, or one square to the right, or
stay where it is. And it can either write a symbol on a square, erase a symbol
on a square, or leave the square as it is. According to the Church-Turing
thesis, every computable function can be computed by a Turing machine. Now
there are two functions specifying such a machine: one from input states to
output states, the other from input states to input states. And these functions
are expressible by counterfactuals e.g., ‘If the machine is in state s 1 and
receives input I, it will emit output O and enter state s2’. Machine tables are
specified by the counterfactuals that express the functions in question. So the
main idea of machine state functionalism is that any given mental type is
definable as the state type that participates in certain counterfactual
relationships specified in terms of purely formal, and so not semantically
interpreted, state types. Any system whose inputs, outputs, and internal states
are counterfactually related in the way characterized by a machine table is a
realization of that table. This version of machine state functionalism has been
abandoned: no one maintains that the mind has the architecture of a Turing
machine. However, computational psychology, a branch of cognitive psychology,
presupposes a scientific functionalist view of cognitive states: it takes the
mind to have a computational architecture. See the section on cognitive
psychology below. Functionalism the view
that what makes a state a realization of a mental state is its playing a
certain causal role remains a leading
theory of mind. But functionalism faces formidable difficulties. Block has
pinpointed one. On the one hand, if the input and output states that figure in
the causal role alleged to define a certain mental state are specified in
insufficient detail, the functional definition will be too liberal: it will
mistakenly classify certain states as of that mental type. On the other hand,
if the input and output states are specified in too much detail, the functional
definition will be chauvinistic: it will fail to count certain states as
instances of the mental state that are in fact such instances. Moreover, it has
also been argued that functionalism cannot capture conscious states since types
of conscious states do not admit of functional definitions. Cognitive
psychology, content, and consciousness Cognitive psychology. Many claim that
one aim of cognitive psychology is to provide explanations of intentional
capacities, capacities to be in intentional states e.g., believing and to
engage in intentional activities e.g., reasoning. Fodor has argued that
classical cognitive psychology postulates a cognitive architecture that
includes a language of thought: a system of mental representation with a
combinatorial syntax and semantics, and computational processes defined over
these mental representations in virtue of their syntactic structures. On this
view, cognition is rule-governed symbol manipulation. Mental symbols have
meanings, but they participate in computational processes solely in virtue of
their syntactic or formal properties. The mind is, so to speak, a syntactic
engine. The view implies a kind of content parallelism: syntaxsensitive causal
transitions between symbols will preserve semantic coherence. Fodor has
mainphilosophy of mind philosophy of mind 692
692 tained that, on this language-of-thought view of cognition the
classical view, being in a beliefthat-p state can be understood as consisting
in bearing a computational relation one that is constitutive of belief to a
sentence in the language of thought that means that p; and similarly for
desire, intention, and the like. The explanation of intentional capacities will
be provided by a computational theory for mental sentences in conjunction with
a psychosemantic theory, a theory of meaning for mental sentences. A research
program in cognitive science called connectionism postulates networks of
neuron-like units. The units can be either on or off, or can have continuous
levels of activation. Units are connected, the connections have various degrees
of strength, and the connections can be either inhibitory or excitatory.
Connectionism has provided fruitful models for studying how neural networks
compute information. Moreover, connectionists have had much success in modeling
pattern recognition tasks e.g., facial recognition and tasks consisting of
learning categories from examples. Some connectionists maintain that
connectionism will yield an alternative to the classical language-of-thought
account of intentional states and capacities. However, some favor a
mixed-models approach to cognition: some cognitive capacities are symbolic,
some connectionist. And some hold that connectionism will yield an
implementational architecture for a symbolic cognitive architecture, one that
will help explain how a symbolic cognitive architecture is realized in the
nervous system. Content externalism. Many today hold that Twin-Earth thought
experiments by Putnam and Tyler Burge show that the contents of a subject’s
mental states do not supervene on intrinsic properties of the subject: two
individuals can be exactly alike in every intrinsic respect, yet be in mental
states with different contents. In response to Twin-Earth thought experiments,
some philosophers have, however, attempted to characterize a notion of narrow
content, a kind of content that supervenes on intrinsic properties of thinkers.
Content, externalists claim, depends on extrinsic-contextual factors. If
externalism is correct, then a psychosemantic theory must examine the relation
between mental symbols and the extrinsic, contextual factors that determine
contents. Stephen Stich has argued that psychology should eschew
psychosemantics and concern itself only with the syntactic properties of mental
sentences. Such a psychology could not explain intentional capacities. But
Stich urges that computational psychology also eschew that explanatory goal.
If, however, psychology is to explain intentional capacities, a psychosemantic
theory is needed. Dretske, Fodor, Ruth Millikan, and David Papineau have each
independently attempted to provide, in physicalistically respectable terms,
foundations for a naturalized externalist theory of the content of mental
sentences or internal physical states. Perhaps the leading problem for these
theories of content is to explain how the physical and functional facts about a
state determine a unique content for it. Appealing to work by Quine and by
Kripke, some philosophers argue that such facts will not determine unique
contents. Both causal and epistemic concerns have been raised about externalist
theories of content. Such theories invite the question whether the property of
having a certain content is ever causally relevant. If content is a contextual
property of a state that has it, can states have effects in virtue of their
having a certain content? This is an important issue because intentional states
figure in explanations not only in virtue of their intentional mode whether
they are beliefs, or desires, etc. but also in virtue of their contents.
Consider an everyday belief-desire explanation. The fact that the subject’s
belief was that there was milk in the refrigerator and the fact that the
subject’s desire was for milk are both essential to the belief and desire
explaining why the subject went to the refrigerator. Dretske, who maintains
that content depends on a causal-historical context, has attempted to explain
how the property of having a certain content can be causally relevant even
though the possession of the property depends on causal-historical factors. And
various other philosophers have attempted to explain how the causal relevance
of content can be squared with the fact that it fails to supervene on intrinsic
properties of the subject. A further controversial question is whether
externalism is consistent with our having privileged access to what we are
thinking. Consciousness. Conscious states such as pain states, visual
experiences, and so on, are such that it is “like” something for the subject of
the state to be in them. Such states have a qualitative aspect, a
phenomenological character. The what-it-is-like aspects of experiences are
called qualia. Qualia pose a serious difficulty for physicalism. Broad argued
that one can know all the physical properties of a chemical and how it causally
interacts with other physical phenomena and yet not know what it is like to
smell it. He concluded that the smell of the chemical is philosophy of mind
philosophy of mind 693 693 not itself
a physical property, but rather an irreducible emergent property. Frank Jackson
has recently defended a version of the argument, which has been dubbed the
knowledge argument. Jackson argues that a super-scientist, Mary, who knows all
the physical and functional facts about color vision, light, and matter, but
has never experienced redness since she has spent her entire life in a black
and white room, would not know what it is like to visually experience red. He
concludes that the physical and functional topic-neutral facts do not entail
all the facts, and thus materialism is false. In response, Lawrence Nemirow,
David Lewis, and others have argued that knowing what it is like to be in a certain
conscious state is, in part, a matter of know-how e.g., to be able to imagine
oneself in the state rather than factual knowledge, and that the failure of
knowledge of the physical and functional facts to yield such know-how does not
imply the falsity of materialism. Functionalism seems unable to solve the
problem of qualia since qualia seem not to be functionally definable. In the
0s, Fodor and Ned Block argued that two states can have the same causal role,
thereby realizing the same functional state, yet the qualia associated with
each can be inverted. This is called the problem of inverted qualia. The color
spectrum, e.g., might be inverted for two individuals a possibility raised by
Locke, despite their being in the same functional states. They further argued
that two states might realize the same functional state, yet the one might have
qualia associated with it and the other not. This is called the problem of
absent qualia. Sydney Shoemaker has argued that the possibility of absent
qualia can be ruled out on functionalist grounds. However, he has also refined
the inverted qualia scenario and further articulated the problem it poses for
functionalism. Whether functionalism or physicalism can avoid the problems of
absent and inverted qualia remains an open question. Thomas Nagel claims that
conscious states are subjective: to fully understand them, one must understand
what it is like to be in them, but one can do that only by taking up the
experiential point of view of a subject in them. Physical states, in contrast,
are objective. Physical science attempts to characterize the world in
abstraction from the experiential point of view of any subject. According to
Nagel, whether phenomenal mental states reduce to physical states turns on
whether subjective states reduce to objective states; and, at present, he
claims, we have no understanding of how they could. Nagel has suggested that
consciousness may be explainable only by appeal to as yet undiscovered basic
nonmental, non-physical properties
“proto-mental properties” the
idea being that experiential points of view might be constituted by protomental
properties together with physical properties. He thus claims that panphysicism
is worthy of serious consideration. Frank Jackson, James Van Cleve, and David
Chalmers have argued that conscious properties are emergent, i.e., fundamental,
irreducible macro-properties; and Chalmers sympathizes with a brand of
panphysicism. Colin McGinn claims that while conscious properties are likely
reductively explainable by brain properties, our minds seem conceptually closed
to the explaining properties: we are unable to conceptualize them, just as a
cat is unable to conceptualize a square root. Dennett attempts to explain
consciousness in supervenient behaviorist terms. David Rosenthal argues that
consciousness is a special case of intentionality more specifically, that conscious states are
just states we can come in a certain direct way to believe we are in. Dretske,
William Lycan, and Michael Tye argue that conscious properties are intentional
properties and physicalistically reducible. Patricia Churchland argues that
conscious phenomena are reducible to neurological phenomena. Brian Loar
contends that qualia are identical with either functional or neurological
states of the brain; and Christopher Hill argues specifically that qualia are
identical with neurological states. Loar and Hill attempt to explain away the
appearance of contingency of psychophysical identity claims, but in a way
different from the way Kripke attempts to explain the appearance of contingency
of ‘Water is H2O’, since they concede that that mode of explanation is
unavailable. They appeal to differences in the conceptual roles of neurological
and functional concepts by contrast with phenomenal concepts. They argue that
while such concepts are different, they answer to the same properties. The
nature of consciousness thus remains a matter of dispute. Animatum --
philosophical psychology – Grice: “Someone at Oxford had the bad idea of
calling the Wilde lecturer the Wilde lecturer in mental philosophy – and the
sad thing is that Ryle did nothing to stop it!” -- Eckhart, Johannes, called
Meister Eckhart c.12601328, G. mystic, theologian, and preacher. Eckhart
entered the Dominican order early and began an academic circuit that took him
several times to Paris as a student and master of theology and that initiated
him into ways of thinking much influenced by Albertus Magnus and Thomas
Aquinas. At Paris, Eckhart wrote the required commentary on the Sentences of Peter
Lombard and finished for publication at least three formal disputations. But he
had already held office within the Dominicans, and he continued to alternate
work as administrator and as teacher. Eckhart preached throughout these years,
and he continued to write spiritual treatises in the vernacular, of which the
most important is the Book of Divine Consolation. Only about a third of
Eckhart’s main project in Latin, the Opus tripartitum, seems ever to have been
completed. Beginning in the early 1320s, questions were raised about Eckhart’s
orthodoxy. The questions centered on what was characteristic of his teaching,
namely the emphasis on the soul’s attaining “emptiness” so as to “give birth to
God.” The soul is ennobled by its emptying, and it can begin to “labor” with
God to deliver a spark that enacts the miraculous union-and-difference of their
love. After being acquitted of heresy once, Eckhart was condemned on 108
propositions drawn from his writings by a commission at Cologne. The
condemnation was appealed to the Holy See, but in 1329 Eckhart was there judged
“probably heretical” on 17 of 28 propositions drawn from both his academic and
popular works. The condemnation clearly limited Eckhart’s explicit influence in
theology, though he was deeply appropriated not only by mystics such as
Johannes Tauler and Henry Suso, but by church figures such as Nicholas of Cusa
and Martin Luther. He has since been taken up by thinkers as different as
Hegel, Fichte, and Heidegger. Philosophical psychology – “soul-to-soul
transfer” – the problem of other minds, the question of what rational basis a
person can have for the belief that other persons are similarly conscious and
have minds. Every person, by virtue of being conscious, is aware of her own
state of consciousness and thus knows she has a mind; but the mental states of
others are not similarly apparent to her. An influential attempt to solve this
problem was made by philosophical behaviorists. According to Ryle in “The
Concept of Mind,”(first draft entitled, “The concept of psyche,” second draft,
“The concept of the soul” -- a mind (Ryle means ‘soul’) is not a ghost in the
physical machine but roughly speaking an aggregate of dispositions to behave
intelligently and to respond overtly to sensory stimulation. Since the behavior
distinctive of these mentalistic dispositions is readily observable in other
human beings, the so-called problem of other minds is easily solved: it arose
from mere confusion about the concept of mind. Ryle’s opponents were generally
willing to concede that such dispositions provide proof that another person has
a “mind” or is a sentient being, but they were not willing to admit that those
dispositions provide proof that other people actually have feelings, thoughts,
and sensory experiences. Their convictions on this last matter generated a
revised version of the otherminds problem; it might be called the problem of
other-person experiences. Early efforts to solve the problem of other minds can
be viewed as attempts to solve the problem of other-person experiences.
According to J. S. Mill’s Examination of Sir William Hamilton’s
Philosophy, one can defend one’s
conviction that others have feelings and other subjective experiences by
employing an argument from analogy. To develop that analogy one first attends
to how one’s own experiences are related to overt or publicly observable
phenomena. One might observe that one feels pain when pricked by a pin and that
one responds to the pain by wincing and saying “ouch.” The next step is to
attend to the behavior and circumstances of others. Since other people are
physically very similar to oneself, it is reasonable to conclude that if they
are pricked by a pin and respond by wincing and saying “ouch,” they too have
felt pain. Analogous inferences involving other sorts of mental states and
other sorts of behavior and circumstances add strong support, Mill said, to
one’s belief in other-person experiences. Although arguments from analogy are
generally conceded to provide rationally acceptable evidence for unobserved
phenomena, the analogical argument for other-person experiences was vigorously
attacked in the 0s by philosophers influenced by Vitters’s Philosophical
Investigations 3. Their central contention was that anyone employing the
argument must assume that, solely from her own case, she knows what feelings
and thoughts are. This assumption was refuted, they thought, by Vitters’s
private language argument, which proved that we learn what feelings and
thoughts are only in the process of learning a publicly understandable language
containing an appropriate psychological vocabulary. To understand this latter
vocabulary, these critics said, one must be able to use its ingredient words
correctly in relation to others as well as to oneself; and this can be ascertained
only because words like ‘pain’ and ‘depression’ are associated with behavioral
criteria. When such criteria are satisfied by the behavior of others, one knows
that the words are correctly applied to them and that one is justified in
believing that they have the experiences in question. The supposed problem of
other-person experiences is thus “dissolved” by a just appreciation of the
preconditions for coherent thought about psychological states. Vitters’s claim
that, to be conceivable, “an inner process stands in need of external
criteria,” lost its hold on philosophers during the 0s. An important
consideration was this: if a feeling of pain is a genuine reality different
from the behavior that typically accompanies it, then so-called pain behavior cannot
be shown to provide adequate evidence for the presence of pain by a purely
linguistic argument; some empirical inductive evidence is needed. Since,
contrary to Vitters, one knows what the feeling of pain is like only by having
that feeling, one’s belief that other people occasionally have feelings that
are significantly like the pain one feels oneself apparently must be supported
by an argument in which analogy plays a central role. No other strategy seems
possible. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Method in
philosophical psychology: from the bizarre to the banal,” repr. in “The
Conception of Value,” Oxford, Clarendon Press. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Method in
philosophical psychology: from the banal to the bizarre,” in The Conception of
Value, Oxford, Clarendon.
annullatum
–Grice: Etymologically, ‘ad-nullatum.’ -- annullability: a synonym for ‘cancellability,’
used in “Causal.” Perhaps clear than ‘cancel.’ The etymology seems clear,
because it involves the negative – “Cancel” seems like a soft sophisticated way
of annulling, render something nix. Short and Lewis has ‘nullus’ as ne-ullus, not any, none, no. which is indeed a diminutive
for ‘unus,’ [for unulus, dim. of unus], any, any one (usu.
in neg. sentences; corresp. with aliquis in affirmations).
anniceris: Grecian and
pre-Griceian philosopher, vide. H. P. Grice, “Pleasure.” A pupil of Antipater,
he established a separate branch of the Cyrenaic school known as the
Anniceraioi. He subscribed to typical Cyrenaic hedonism, arguing that the end
of each action should be one’s own pleasure, since we can know nothing of
others’ experiences. He tempered the implications of hedonism with the claim
that a wise man attaches weight to respect for parents, patriotism, gratitude,
and friendship, perhaps influencing Epicurus in this regard. Anniceris also
played down the Cyrenaic stress on the intellect’s role in hedonistic practical
rationality, taking the Aristotelian view that cultivation of the right habits
is indispensable.
anselmus: “I would call him ‘Canterbury,’ only he was an
Italian!” – H. P. Grice. Saint, called Anselm of Canterbury, philosopher
theologian. A Benedictine monk and the second Norman archbishop of Canterbury,
he is best known for his distinctive method
fides quaerens intellectum; his “ontological” argument for the existence
of God in his treatise Proslogion; and his classic formulation of the
satisfaction theory of the Atonement in the Cur Deus homo. Like Augustine
before him, Anselm is a Christian Platonist in metaphysics. He argues that the
most accessible proofs of the existence of God are through value theory: in his
treatise Monologion, he deploys a cosmological argument, showing the existence
of a source of all goods, which is the Good per se and hence supremely good;
that same thing exists per se and is the Supreme Being. In the Proslogion,
Anselm begins with his conception of a being a greater than which cannot be
conceived, and mounts his ontological argument that a being a greater than
which cannot be conceived exists in the intellect, because even the fool
understands the phrase when he hears it; but if it existed in the intellect
alone, a greater could be conceived that existed in reality. This supremely
valuable object is essentially whatever it is
other things being equal that is
better to be than not to be, and hence living, wise, powerful, true, just,
blessed, immaterial, immutable, and eternal per se; even the paradigm of
sensory goods Beauty, Harmony,
Sweetness, and Pleasant Texture, in its own ineffable manner. Nevertheless, God
is supremely simple, not compounded of a plurality of excellences, but “omne et
unum, totum et solum bonum,” a being a more delectable than which cannot be
conceived. Everything other than God has its being and its well-being through
God as efficient cause. Moreover, God is the paradigm of all created natures,
the latter ranking as better to the extent that they more perfectly resemble
God. Thus, it is better to be human than to be horse, to be horse than to be
wood, even though in comparison with God everything else is “almost nothing.”
For every created nature, there is a that-for-which-it-ismade ad quod factum
est. On the one hand, Anselm thinks of such teleology as part of the internal
structure of the natures themselves: a creature of type F is a true F only
insofar as it is/does/exemplifies that for which F’s were made; a defective F,
to the extent that it does not. On the other hand, for Anselm, the telos of a
created nature is that-for-which-God-made-it. Because God is personal and acts
through reason and will, Anselm infers that prior in the order of explanation
to creation, there was, in the reason of the maker, an exemplar, form,
likeness, or rule of what he was going to make. In De veritate Anselm maintains
that such teleology gives rise to obligation: since creatures owe their being
and well-being to God as their cause, so they owe their being and well-being to
God in the sense of having an obligation to praise him by being the best beings
they can. Since every creature is of some nature or other, each can be its best
by being that-for-which-God-made-it. Abstracting from impediments, non-rational
natures fulfill this obligation and “act rightly” by natural necessity;
rational creatures, when they exercise their powers of reason and will to
fulfill God’s purpose in creating them. Thus, the goodness of a creature how
good a being it is is a function of twin factors: its natural telos i.e., what
sort of imitation of divine nature it aims for, and its rightness in exercising
its natural powers to fulfill its telos. By contrast, God as absolutely
independent owes no one anything and so has no obligations to creatures. In De
casu diaboli, Anselm underlines the optimism of his ontology, reasoning that
since the Supreme Good and the Supreme Being are identical, every being is good
and every good a being. Two further conclusions follow. First, evil is a
privation of being, the absence of good in something that properly ought to
have it e.g., blindness in normally sighted animals, injustice in humans or
angels. Second, since all genuine powers are given to enable a being to fulfill
its natural telos and so to be the best being it can, all genuine
metaphysically basic powers are optimific and essentially aim at goods, so that
evils are merely incidental side effects of their operation, involving some
lack of coordination among powers or between their exercise and the surrounding
context. Thus, divine omnipotence does not, properly speaking, include
corruptibility, passibility, or the ability to lie, because the latter are
defects and/or powers in other things whose exercise obstructs the flourishing
of the corruptible, passible, or potential liar. Anselm’s distinctive action
theory begins teleologically with the observation that humans and angels were
made for a happy immortality enjoying God, and to that end were given the
powers of reason to make accurate value assessments and will to love
accordingly. Anselm regards freedom and imputability of choice as essential and
permanent features of all rational beings. But freedom cannot be defined as a
power for opposites the power to sin and the power not to sin, both because
neither God nor the good angels have any power to sin, and because sin is an
evil at which no metaphysically basic power can aim. Rather, freedom is the
power to preserve justice for its own sake. Choices and actions are imputable
to an agent only if they are spontaneous, from the agent itself. Creatures
cannot act spontaneously by the necessity of their natures, because they do not
have their natures from themselves but receive them from God. To give them the
opportunity to become just of themselves, God furnishes them with two
motivaAnselm Anselm 31 31 tional drives
toward the good: an affection for the advantageous affectio commodi or a
tendency to will things for the sake of their benefit to the agent itself; and
an affection for justice affectio justitiae or a tendency to will things
because of their own intrinsic value. Creatures are able to align these drives
by letting the latter temper the former or not. The good angels, who preserved
justice by not willing some advantage possible for them but forbidden by God
for that time, can no longer will more advantage than God wills for them,
because he wills their maximum as a reward. By contrast, creatures, who sin by
refusing to delay gratification in accordance with God’s will, lose both
uprightness of will and their affection for justice, and hence the ability to
temper their pursuit of advantage or to will the best goods. Justice will never
be restored to angels who desert it. But if animality makes human nature
weaker, it also opens the possibility of redemption. Anselm’s argument for the
necessity of the Incarnation plays out the dialectic of justice and mercy so characteristic
of his prayers. He begins with the demands of justice: humans owe it to God to
make all of their choices and actions conform to his will; failure to render
what was owed insults God’s honor and makes the offender liable to make
satisfaction; because it is worse to dishonor God than for countless worlds to
be destroyed, the satisfaction owed for any small sin is incommensurate with
any created good; it would be maximally indecent for God to overlook such a
great offense. Such calculations threaten certain ruin for the sinner, because
God alone can do/be immeasurably deserving, and depriving the creature of its
honor through the eternal frustration of its telos seems the only way to
balance the scales. Yet, justice also forbids that God’s purposes be thwarted
through created resistance, and it was divine mercy that made humans for a
beatific immortality with him. Likewise, humans come in families by virtue of
their biological nature which angels do not share, and justice allows an
offense by one family member to be compensated by another. Assuming that all
actual humans are descended from common first parents, Anselm claims that the
human race can make satisfaction for sin, if God becomes human and renders to
God what Adam’s family owes. When Anselm insists that humans were made for
beatific intimacy with God and therefore are obliged to strive into God with
all of their powers, he emphatically includes reason or intellect along with
emotion and will. God, the controlling subject matter, is in part permanently
inaccessible to us because of the ontological incommensuration between God and
creatures and our progress is further hampered by the consequences of sin. Our
powers will function best, and hence we have a duty to follow right order in
their use: by submitting first to the holistic discipline of faith, which will
focus our souls and point us in the right direction. Yet it is also a duty not
to remain passive in our appreciation of authority, but rather for faith to
seek to understand what it has believed. Anselm’s works display a dialectical
structure, full of questions, objections, and contrasting opinions, designed to
stir up the mind. His quartet of teaching dialogues De grammatico, De veritate, De libertate
arbitrii, and De casu diaboli as well as his last philosophical treatise, De
concordia, anticipate the genre of the Scholastic question quaestio so dominant
in the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries. His discussions are likewise
remarkable for their attention to modalities and proper-versus-improper
linguistic usage.
antilogismus: Grice: “Not to be
confused with the mere implicatural ‘para-logism.’ -- an inconsistent triad of
propositions, two of which are the premises of a valid categorical syllogism
and the third of which is the contradictory of the conclusion of this valid
categorical syllogism. An antilogism is a special form of antilogy or
self-contradiction.
antinomianism: as a Kantian,
Grice overused the idea of a nomos or law, and then there’s antinominaism, the
view that one is not bound by moral law; specifically, the view that Christians
are by grace set free from the need to observe moral laws. During the Reformation,
antinomianism was believed by some but not Martin Luther to follow from the
Lutheran doctrine of justification by faith alone.
antiochus: Grecian
philosopher and the last prominent member of the New Academy. He played the
major role in ending its two centuries of Skepticism and helped revive interest
in doctrines from the Old Academy, as he called Plato, Aristotle, and their
associates. The impulse for this decisive shift came in epistemology, where the
Skeptical Academy had long agreed with Stoicism that knowledge requires an
infallible “criterion of truth” but disputed the Stoic claim to find this
criterion in “cognitive perception.” Antiochus’s teacher, Philo of Larissa,
broke with this tradition and proposed that perception need not be cognitive to
qualify as knowledge. Rejecting this concession, Antiochus offered new
arguments for the Stoic claim that some perception is cognitive, and hence
knowledge. He also proposed a similar accommodation in ethics, where he agreed
with the Stoics that virtue alone is sufficient for happiness but insisted with
Aristotle that virtue is not the only good. These and similar attempts to
mediate fundamental disputes have led some to label Antiochus an eclectic or
syncretist; but some of his proposals, especially his appeal to the Old
Academy, set the stage for Middle Platonism, which also sought to reconcile
Plato and Aristotle. No works by Antiochus survive, but his students included
many eminent Romans, most notably Cicero, who summarizes Antiochus’s
epistemology in the Academica, his critique of Stoic ethics in De finibus IV,
and his purportedly Aristotelian ethics in De finibus V.
anti-realism: Grice: “Sometimes
I use contra-, sometimes I use anti-.” If Grice was a realist, he hated
anti-realism, the rejection, in one or another form or area of inquiry, of
realism, the view that there are knowable mind-independent facts, objects, or
properties. Metaphysical realists make the general claim that there is a world
of mind-independent objects. Realists in particular areas make more specific or
limited claims. Thus moral realists hold that there are mind-independent moral
properties, mathematical realists that there are mind-independent mathematical
facts, scientific realists that scientific inquiry reveals the existence of
previously unknown and unobservable mind-independent entities and properties.
Antirealists deny either that facts of the relevant sort are mind-independent
or that knowledge of such facts is possible. Berkeley’s subjective idealism,
which claims that the world consists only of minds and their contents, is a
metaphysical anti-realism. Constructivist anti-realists, on the other hand,
deny that the world consists only of mental phenomena, but claim that it is
constituted by, or constructed from, our evidence or beliefs. Many philosophers
find constructivism implausible or even incoherent as a metaphysical doctrine,
but much more plausible when restricted to a particular domain, such as ethics or
mathematics. Debates between realists and anti-realists have been particularly
intense in philosophy of science. Scientific realism has been rejected both by
constructivists such as Kuhn, who hold that scientific facts are constructed by
the scientific community, and by empiricists who hold that knowledge is limited
to what can be observed. A sophisticated version of the latter doctrine is Bas
van Fraassen’s constructive empiricism, which allows scientists free rein in
constructing scientific models, but claims that evidence for such models
confirms only their observable implications.
apagoge:
distinguished by Grice from both ‘epagoge,’ and his favoured ‘diagoge.’ A shifting of the
basis of argument: hence of argument based on a probable or agreed assumption,
Arist.APr.69a20, cf. Anon.in SE65.35; reduction, “ἡ εἰς τὸ ἀδύνατον ἀ.”
reductio per impossibile, APr. 29b6; “ἡ ἀ. μετάβασίς ἐστιν ἀπ᾽ ἄλλου
προβλήματος ἢ θεωρήματος ἐπ᾽ ἄλλο, οὗ γνωσθέντος ἢ πορισθέντος καὶ τὸ
προκείμενον ἔσται καταφανές” Procl. in Euc.p.212F.; τῶν ἀπορουμένων
διαγραμμάτων τὴν ἀ. ποιήσασθαι ib. p.213F. b. reduction of a disputant (cf. ἀπάγω
v. 1c), “ἡ ἐπὶ τὸ ἄδηλον ἀ.” S.E.P.2.234.
apocatastasis: a branch of
Grice’s eschatology -- from Grecian, ‘reestablishment’, the restoration of all
souls, including Satan’s and his minions’, in the kingdom of God. God’s
goodness will triumph over evil, and through a process of spiritual education
souls will be brought to repentance and made fit for divine life. The theory
originates with Origen but was also held by Gregory of Nyssa. In modern times
F. D. Maurice 180572 and Karl Barth 6 8 held this position.
aporia: cf. aporetic, cognate
with porosity. No porosity, and you get an impasse. While aware of Baker’s and
Deutsch’s treatment of the ‘aporia’ in Aristotle’s account of ‘philos,’ Grice
explores ‘aporia’ in Plato in the Thrasymachus on ‘legal justice’ prior to
‘moral justice’ in Republic. in Dialectic, question for discussion, difficulty,
puzzle, “ἀπορίᾳ σχόμενος” Pl.Prt.321c; ἀ. ἣν ἀπορεῖς ib.324d; “ἡ ἀ. ἰσότης ἐναντίων
λογισμῶν” Arist. Top.145b1, al.; “ἔχει ἀπορίαν περί τινος” Id.Pol.1285b28; “αἱ
μὲν οὖν ἀ. τοιαῦταί τινες συμβαίνουσιν” Id.EN1146b6; “οὐδεμίαν ποιήσει ἀ.”
Id.Metaph.1085a27; ἀ. λύειν, διαλύειν, Id.MM 1201b1, Metaph.1062b31; “ἀπορίᾳ ἀπορίαν
λύειν” D.S.1.37.Discussion with the
Sophist Thrasymachus can
only lead to aporia.
And the more I trust you, the more I sink into an aporia of sorts. —Aha!
roared Thrasymachus to
everyone's surprise. There it is! Socratic aporia is back! Charge! neither Socrates' company nor
Socrates himself gives any convincing answer. So, he says, finding himself in a
real aporia, he
visits Thrasymachus as
well, and ... I argue that a combination of these means in form
that I call “provocative-aporetic” better accounts for the means that Plato
uses to exert a protreptic effect on readers. Aporia is a simultaneously
intellectual and affective experience, and the way that readers choose to
respond to aporia has a greater protreptic effect than either affective or
intellectual means alone. When Socrates says he can 'transfer' the use of
"just" to things related to the 'soul,' what kind of conversational
game is that? Grice took Socrates's manoeuvre very
seriously.Socrates relies on the tripartite theory of the soul. Plato, actually -- since Socrates is a drammatis persona! In "Philosophical Eschatology, Metaphysics, and Plato's
Republic," H. P. Grice's purpose is to carry out a provocative-aporetic
reading Book I Grice argues that it is a dispute between two ways of
understanding 'just' which causes the aporia when Socrates tries to analyse
'just.' Although Socrates will not argue for the complexity and
tripartition of the soul until Bk. IV, we can at least note the contrast with
Thrasymachus' “idealize user” theory.For Socrates, agents are complex, and
justice coordinates the parts of the agent.For Thrasymachus, agents are simple
“users,” and justice is a tool for use. (2 - 3) Justice makes its
possessor happy; the function (telos, metier) argument. To make the
argument that justice is an excellence (virtus, arete) of soul (psyche) that
makes its possessor happy, Socrates relies on a method for discovering the
function (ἔργον, ergon, 352e1, cf. telos, metier, causa finalis) of any object
whatsoever. Socrates begins by differentiating between an exclusive
functions and an optimal function, so that we may discover the functions in
different types of objects, i.e., natural and artificial objects. We can
say an object performs some function (ergon) if one of the following conditions
holds.If the object is the only one that can do the work in
question, or If it is the object that does that work best.Socrates
then provides examples from different part-whole complexes to make his
point. The eye's exclusive function is to see, because no other organ is
specialized so as to perform just that function. A horse's work is to
carry riders into battle. Even though this might not be a horse's
EXCLUSIVE function, it may be its “optimal” function in that the horse is best
suited or designed by God to the task. Finally, the pruning knife is best
for tending to vines, not because it cannot cut anything else, but because it
is optimally suited for that task. Socrates' use of the pruning knife of
as an example of a thing's function resembles a return to the technē model,
since a craftsman must make the knife for a gardener to Socrates asks,
“Would you define this as the function of a horse and of anything else, as that
which someone does either through that thing alone, or best?” (...τοῦτο ἄν
θείης καὶ ἵππου καὶ ἄλλου ὁτουοῦν ἔργον, ὅ ἄν ἤ μόνῳ ἐκείνῳ ποιῇ τις ἤ ἄριστα;
352e1-2) Thrasymachus agrees to this definition of function. 91 use.But his use
of the eye — a bodily organ — should dissuade us from this view. One may
use these examples to argue that Socrates is in fact offering a new method to
investigate the nature of justice: 1) Find out what the functions of such
objects are2) determine (by observation, experiment, or even thought
experiment) cases where objects of such a kind perform their functions well and
cases where they perform them poorly; and 3) finally find out the
qualities that enable them to perform such functions well (and in the absence
of which they perform poorly), and these are their virtues.A crucial difference
between this method and technē model of justice lies in the interpretation that
each assigns to the realm of human artifacts. Polemarchus and Thrasymachus
both assume that the technē is unique as a form of knowledge for the power and
control that it offers users. In Polemarchus' case, the technē of justice,
“helping friends and harming enemies,” may be interpreted as a description of a
method for gaining political power within a traditional framework of communal
life, which assumes the oikos as the basic unit of power. Those families
that help their friends and harm their enemies thrive. Thrasymachus, on
the other hand, emphasizes the ways that technai grant users the power to
exploit nature to further their own, distinctively individual ends. Thus,
the shepherd exploits the sheep to make a livelihood for himself. Socrates'
approach differs from these by re-casting “mastery” over nature as submission
to norms that structure the natural world. For example, many factors contribute
to making This points to a distinction Socrates draws in Book X between
producers and users of artifacts. He uses the example of the blacksmith
who makes a bridle and the horseman who uses the bridle to argue that
production and use correspond to two gradations of knowledge (601c). The
ultimate purpose of the example is to provide a metaphor — using the craft
analogy — for identifying gradations of knowledge on a copy-original paradigm
of the form-participant relation. the pruning knife the optimal tool for
cutting vines: the shape of the human hand, the thickness and shape of the
vines, and the metal of the blade. Likewise, in order for horses to
optimally perform their “work,” they must be "healthy" and
strong. The conditions that bring about their "health" and
strength are not up to us, however."Control” only comes about through the
recognition of natural norms. Thus technē is a type of knowledge that
coordinates structures in nature.It is not an unlimited source of
power. Socrates' inclusion of the human soul (psyche) among those things
that have a function is the more controversial aspect of function
argument.Socrates says that the functions (erga) of the soul (psyche)
are “to engage in care-taking, ruling, and deliberation” and, later,
simply that the ergon (or function) of the soul (or psyche) is “to live”
(τὸ ζῆν, "to zen," 353d6). But the difficulty seems to be this:
the functions of pruning knives, horses, and bodily organs are determined with
respect to a limited and fairly unambiguous context that is already defined for
them. But what is this context with respect to the soul (psyche) of a
human individual? One answer might be that the social world — politics —
provides the context that defines the soul's function, just as the needs of the
human organism define the context in which the eye can perform a
function. But here a challenger might reply that in aristocracies,
oligarchies, and democracies, “care-taking, ruling, and deliberation” are
utilized for different ends.In these contexts, individual souls might have
different functions, according to the “needs” that these different regimes
have. Alternatively, one might deny altogether that the human soul has a
function: the distinctive feature of human beings might be their position
“outside” of nature. Thus, even if Socrates' description of the soul's
function is accurate, it is too general to be really informative.Socrates must
offer more details for the function argument to be
convincing. Nonetheless, the idea that justice is a condition that lets
the soul perform its functions is a significant departure from the technē
model of justice, and one that will remain throughout the argument of the
Republic. […] τὸ ἐπιμελεῖσθαι καὶ ἄρχειν καὶ βουλεύεσθαι (353d3). As
far as Bk. I is concerned, “justice” functions as a place-holder for that
condition of the soul which permits the soul to perform its functions
well. What that condition is, however, remains unknown.For this reason,
Plato has Socrates concludes Bk. I by likening himself to a “glutton” (ὥσπερ οἱ
λίχνοι, 354b1), who takes another dish before “moderately enjoying the
previous” serving (πρὶν τοῦ προτέρου μετρίως ἀπολαύσαι, 354b2-3). For
Socrates wants to know what effects the optimal condition of soul brings about
before knowing what the condition itself is. Thus Bk. I concludes in
"aporia," but not in a way that betrays the dialogue's lack of
unity.The “separatist” thesis concerning Bk. I goes back to Hermann in
"Geschichte und System der Platonischen Philosophie." One can
argue on behalf of the “separatist” view as well. One can argue against
the separatist thesis, even granting some evidence in favour of the separatist
thesis. To the contrary, the "aporia" clearly foreshadows the
argument that Socrates makes about the soul in Bk. IV, viz. that the soul
(psyche) is a complex whole of parts -- an implicaturum in the “justice is
stronger” argument -- and that 'just' is the condition that allows this complex
whole be integrated to an optimal degree. Thus, Bk. I does not conclude
negatively, but rather provides the resources for going beyond the
"technē" model of justice, which is the primary cause of
Polemarchus's and Thrasymachus's encounter with "aporia" in Bk.
I. Throughout conversation of "The Republic," Socrates does not
really alter the argument he gives for justice in Bk. I, but rather states the
same argument in a different way. My gratitude to P. N.
Moore. Refs: Wise guys and smart alecks in Republic 1 and 2; Proleptic
composition in the Republic, or why Bk. 1 was never a separate dialogue, The
Classical Quarterly; "Socrates: ironist and moral philosopher."
Strictly an ‘aporia’ in Griceian, is a ‘puzzle’, ‘question for discussion’,
‘state of perplexity’. The aporetic method
the raising of puzzles without offering solutions is typical of the elenchus in the early
Socratic dialogues of Plato. These consist in the testing of definitions and
often end with an aporia, e.g., that piety is both what is and what is not
loved by the gods. Compare the paradoxes of Zeno, e.g., that motion is both
possible and impossible. In Aristotle’s dialectic, the resolution of aporiai
discovered in the views on a subject is an important source of philosophical
understanding. The beliefs that one should love oneself most of all and that
self-love is shameful, e.g., can be resolved with the right understanding of
‘self’. The possibility of argument for two inconsistent positions was an
important factor in the development of Skepticism. In modern philosophy, the
antinomies that Kant claimed reason would arrive at in attempting to prove the
existence of objects corresponding to transcendental ideas may be seen as
aporiai.
applicatum.
Grice: “Etymologically, ad-plicatum. So we have im-plicatum, ex-plicatum,
dis-im-plicatum, and ad-plicatum. While we have implicatum and implicitum, we
also have adplicatum and adplicitum. While Bennett uses the rather ‘abusive’
“nominalist” to refer to Grice, Grice isn’t. It’s all about the ‘applied.’
Grice thinks a rational creature – not a parrot, but a rational intelligent
pirot – can have an abstract idea. So there is this “Communication Device,”
with capital C and capital D. The emissor APPLIES it to a given occasion. Cf.
complete and incomplete. What’s the antonym of applied? Plato’s idea! applied – grice
used ‘applied’ for ‘meaning’ – but ‘applied’ can be used in other contxts too.
In ethics, the domain of ethics that includes professional ethics, such as
business ethics, engineering ethics, and medical ethics, as well as practical
ethics such as environmental ethics, which is applied, and thus practical as
opposed to theoretical, but not focused on any one discipline. One of the major
disputes among those who work in applied ethics is whether or not there is a
general and universal account of morality applicable both to the ethical issues
in the professions and to various practical problems. Some philosophers believe
that each of the professions or each field of activity develops an ethical code
for itself and that there need be no apellatio applied ethics 34 34 close relationship between e.g. business
ethics, medical ethics, and environmental ethics. Others hold that the same
moral system applies to all professions and fields. They claim that the
appearance of different moral systems is simply due to certain problems being
more salient for some professions and fields than for others. The former
position accepts the consequence that the ethical codes of different
professions might conflict with one another, so that a physician in business
might find that business ethics would require one action but medical ethics another.
Engineers who have been promoted to management positions sometimes express
concern over the tension between what they perceive to be their responsibility
as engineers and their responsibility as managers in a business. Many lawyers
seem to hold that there is similar tension between what common morality
requires and what they must do as lawyers. Those who accept a universal
morality hold that these tensions are all resolvable because there is only one
common morality. Underlying both positions is the pervasive but false view of
common morality as providing a unique right answer to every moral problem.
Those who hold that each profession or field has its own moral code do not
realize that common morality allows for conflicts of duties. Most of those who
put forward moral theories, e.g., utilitarians, Kantians, and contractarians,
attempt to generate a universal moral system that solves all moral problems.
This creates a situation that leads many in applied ethics to dismiss
theoretical ethics as irrelevant to their concerns. An alternative view of a
moral theory is to think of it on the model of a scientific theory, primarily
concerned to describe common morality rather than generate a new improved
version. On this model, it is clear that although morality rules out many
alternatives as unacceptable, it does not provide unique right answers to every
controversial moral question. On this model, different fields and different
professions may interpret the common moral system in somewhat different ways.
For example, although deception is always immoral if not justified, what counts
as deception is not the same in all professions. Not informing a patient of an
alternative treatment counts as deceptive for a physician, but not telling a
customer of an alternative to what she is about to buy does not count as
deceptive for a salesperson. The professions also have considerable input into
what special duties are incurred by becoming a member of their profession.
Applied ethics is thus not the mechanical application of a common morality to a
particular profession or field, but an independent discipline that clarifies
and analyzes the practices in a field or profession so that common morality can
be applied.
a priori: Obviously
contrasted to ‘a posteriori,’ but not necessarily in termporal terms -- Grice
was fascinated by the apriori, both analytic but more so the synthetic. He
would question his children’s playmates with things like, “Can a sweater be
green and red all over? No striped allowed.” a priori, prior to or independent
of experience; contrasted with ‘a posteriori’ empirical. These two terms are
primarily used to mark a distinction between 1 two modes of epistemic
justification, together with derivative distinctions between 2 kinds of
propositions, 3 kinds of knowledge, and 4 kinds of argument. They are also used
to indicate a distinction between 5 two ways in which a concept or idea may be
acquired. 1 A belief or claim is said to be justified a priori if its epistemic
justification, the reason or warrant for thinking it to be true, does not
depend at all on sensory or introspective or other sorts of experience; whereas
if its justification does depend at least in part on such experience, it is
said to be justified a posteriori or empirically. This specific distinction has
to do only with the justification of the belief, and not at all with how the
constituent concepts are acquired; thus it is no objection to a claim of a
priori justificatory status for a particular belief that experience is required
for the acquisition of some of the constituent concepts. It is clear that the
relevant notion of experience includes sensory and introspective experience, as
well as such things as kinesthetic experience. Equally clearly, to construe
experience in the broadest possible sense of, roughly, a conscious undergoing
of any sort would be to destroy the point of the distinction, since even a
priori justification presumably involves some sort of conscious process of
awareness. The construal that is perhaps most faithful to the traditional usage
is that which construes experience as any sort of cognitive input that derives,
presumably causally, from features of the actual world that may not hold in
other possible worlds. Thus, e.g., such things as clairvoyance or telepathy, if
they were to exist, would count as forms of experience and any knowledge
resulting therefrom as a posteriori; but the intuitive apprehension of
properties or numbers or other sorts of abstract entities that are the same in
all possible worlds, would not. Understood in this way, the concept of a priori
justification is an essentially negative concept, specifying as it does what
the justification of the belief does not depend on, but saying nothing a priori
a priori 35 35 about what it does
depend on. Historically, the main positive conception was that offered by
proponents of rationalism such as Plato, Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz,
according to which a priori justification derives from the intuitive
apprehension of necessary facts pertaining to universals and other abstract
entities. Although Kant is often regarded as a rationalist, his restriction of
substantive a priori knowledge to the world of appearances represents a major
departure from the main rationalist tradition. In contrast, proponents of traditional
empiricism, if they do not repudiate the concept of a priori justification
altogether as does Quine, typically attempt to account for such justification
by appeal to linguistic or conceptual conventions. The most standard
formulation of this empiricist view a development of the view of Hume that all
a priori knowledge pertains to “relations of ideas” is the claim typical of
logical positivism that all a priori knowable claims or propositions are
analytic. A rationalist would claim in opposition that at least some a priori
claims or propositions are synthetic. 2 A proposition that is the content of an
a priori justified belief is often referred to as an a priori proposition or an
a priori truth. This usage is also often extended to include any proposition
that is capable of being the content of such a belief, whether it actually has
this status or not. 3 If, in addition to being justified a priori or a
posteriori, a belief is also true and satisfies whatever further conditions may
be required for it to constitute knowledge, that knowledge is derivatively
characterized as a priori or a posteriori empirical, respectively. Though a
priori justification is often regarded as by itself guaranteeing truth, this
should be regarded as a further substantive thesis, not as part of the very
concept of a priori justification. Examples of knowledge that have been
classically regarded as a priori in this sense are mathematical knowledge,
knowledge of logical truths, and knowledge of necessary entailments and
exclusions of commonsense concepts ‘Nothing can be red and green all over at
the same time’, ‘If A is later than B and B is later than C, then A is later
than C’; but many claims of metaphysics, ethics, and even theology have also
been claimed to have this status. 4 A deductively valid argument that also
satisfies the further condition that each of the premises or sometimes one or
more particularly central premises are justified a priori is referred to as an
a priori argument. This label is also sometimes applied to arguments that are
claimed to have this status, even if the correctness of this claim is in
question. 5 In addition to the uses just catalogued that derive from the
distinction between modes of justification, the terms ‘a priori’ and ‘a
posteriori’ are also employed to distinguish two ways in which a concept or
idea might be acquired by an individual person. An a posteriori or empirical
concept or idea is one that is derived from experience, via a process of
abstraction or ostensive definition. In contrast, an a priori concept or idea
is one that is not derived from experience in this way and thus presumably does
not require any particular experience to be realized though the explicit
realization of such a concept might still require experience as a “trigger”.
The main historical account of such concepts, again held mainly by
rationalists, construes them as innate, either implanted in the mind by God or,
in the more contemporary version of the claim held by Chomsky, Fodor, and
others, resulting from evolutionary development. Concepts typically regarded as
having this sort of status include the concepts of substance, causation, God,
necessity, infinity, and many others. Empiricists, in contrast, typically hold
that all concepts are derived from experience. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The
synthetic a priori.”
aquino: aquino -- thomism,
the theology and philosophy of Thomas Aquinas. The term is applied broadly to
various thinkers from different periods who were heavily influenced by
Aquinas’s thought in their own philosophizing and theologizing. Here three
different eras and three different groups of thinkers will be distinguished:
those who supported Aquinas’s thought in the fifty years or so following his
death in 1274; certain highly skilled interpreters and commentators who
flourished during the period of “Second Thomism” sixteenthseventeenth
centuries; and various late nineteenth- and twentieth-century thinkers who have
been deeply influenced in their own work by Aquinas. Thirteenth- and
fourteenth-century Thomism. Although Aquinas’s genius was recognized by many
during his own lifetime, a number of his views were immediately contested by
other Scholastic thinkers. Controversies ranged, e.g., over his defense of only
one substantial form in human beings; his claim that prime matter is purely
potential and cannot, therefore, be kept in existence without some substantial
form, even by divine power; his emphasis on the role of the human intellect in
the act of choice; his espousal of a real distinction betweeen the soul and its
powers; and his defense of some kind of objective or “real” rather than a
merely mind-dependent composition of essence and act of existing esse in
creatures. Some of Aquinas’s positions were included directly or indirectly in
the 219 propositions condemned by Bishop Stephen Tempier of Paris in 1277, and
his defense of one single substantial form in man was condemned by Archbishop
Robert Kilwardby at Oxford in 1277, with renewed prohibitions by his successor
as archbishop of Canterbury, John Peckham, in 1284 and 1286. Only after
Aquinas’s canonization in 1323 were the Paris prohibitions revoked insofar as
they touched on his teaching in 1325. Even within his own Dominican order,
disagreement about some of his views developed within the first decades after
his death, notwithstanding the order’s highly sympathetic espousal of his
cause. Early English Dominican defenders of his general views included William
Hothum d.1298, Richard Knapwell d.c.1288, Robert Orford b. after 1250,
fl.129095, Thomas Sutton d. c.1315?, and William Macclesfield d.1303. Dominican Thomists included Bernard of Trilia
d.1292, Giles of Lessines in present-day Belgium d.c.1304?, John Quidort of
Paris d. 1306, Bernard of Auvergne d. after 1307, Hervé Nédélec d.1323, Armand
of Bellevue fl. 131634, and William Peter Godin d.1336. The secular master at
Paris, Peter of Auvergne d. 1304, while remaining very independent in his own
views, knew Aquinas’s thought well and completed some of his commentaries on
Aristotle. Sixteenth- and seventeenth-century Thomism. Sometimes known as the
period of Second Thomism, this revival gained impetus from the early
fifteenth-century writer John Capreolus 13801444 in his Defenses of Thomas’s
Theology Defensiones theologiae Divi Thomae, a commentary on the Sentences. A
number of fifteenth-century Dominican and secular teachers in G. universities
also contributed: Kaspar Grunwald Freiburg; Cornelius Sneek and John Stoppe in
Rostock; Leonard of Brixental Vienna; Gerard of Heerenberg, Lambert of
Heerenberg, and John Versor all at Cologne; Gerhard of Elten; and in Belgium
Denis the Carthusian. Outstanding among various sixteenth-century commentators
on Thomas were Tommaso de Vio Cardinal Cajetan, Francis Sylvester of Ferrara,
Francisco de Vitoria Salamanca, and Francisco’s disciples Domingo de Soto and
Melchior Cano. Most important among early seventeenth-century Thomists was John
of St. Thomas, who lectured at Piacenza, Madrid, and Alcalá, and is best known
for his Cursus philosophicus and his Cursus theologicus. Theravada Buddhism
Thomism 916 916 The nineteenth- and
twentieth-century revival. By the early to mid-nineteenth century the study of
Aquinas had been largely abandoned outside Dominican circles, and in most Roman
Catholic s and seminaries a kind of Cartesian and Suarezian Scholasticism was
taught. Long before he became Pope Leo XIII, Joachim Pecci and his brother
Joseph had taken steps to introduce the teaching of Thomistic philosophy at the
diocesan seminary at Perugia in 1846. Earlier efforts in this direction had
been made by Vincenzo Buzzetti, by Buzzetti’s students Serafino and Domenico
Sordi, and by Taparelli d’Aglezio, who became director of the Collegio Romano
Gregorian in 1824. Leo’s encyclical
Aeterni Patris1879 marked an official effort on the part of the Roman Catholic
church to foster the study of the philosophy and theology of Thomas Aquinas.
The intent was to draw upon Aquinas’s original writings in order to prepare
students of philosophy and theology to deal with problems raised by contemporary
thought. The Leonine Commission was established to publish a critical edition
of all of Aquinas’s writings; this effort continues today. Important centers of
Thomistic studies developed, such as the Higher Institute of Philosophy at
Louvain founded by Cardinal Mercier, the Dominican School of Saulchoir in
France, and the Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies in Toronto. Different
groups of Roman, Belgian, and Jesuits
acknowledged a deep indebtedness to Aquinas for their personal philosophical
reflections. There was also a concentration of effort in the United States at
universities such as The Catholic of
America, St. Louis , Notre Dame, Fordham, Marquette, and Boston , to mention
but a few, and by the Dominicans at River Forest. A great weakness of many of
the nineteenthand twentieth-century Latin manuals produced during this effort
was a lack of historical sensitivity and expertise, which resulted in an unreal
and highly abstract presentation of an “Aristotelian-Thomistic” philosophy.
This weakness was largely offset by the development of solid historical
research both in the thought of Aquinas and in medieval philosophy and theology
in general, championed by scholars such as H. Denifle, M. De Wulf, M. Grabmann,
P. Mandonnet, F. Van Steenberghen, E. Gilson and many of his students at
Toronto, and by a host of more recent and contemporary scholars. Much of this
historical work continues today both within and without Catholic scholarly
circles. At the same time, remarkable diversity in interpreting Aquinas’s
thought has emerged on the part of many twentieth-century scholars. Witness,
e.g., the heavy influence of Cajetan and John of St. Thomas on the Thomism of
Maritain; the much more historically grounded approaches developed in quite
different ways by Gilson and F. Van Steenberghen; the emphasis on the
metaphysics of participation in Aquinas in the very different presentations by
L. Geiger and C. Fabro; the emphasis on existence esse promoted by Gilson and
many others but resisted by still other interpreters; the movement known as
Transcendental Thomism, originally inspired by P. Rousselot and by J. Marechal
in dialogue with Kant; and the long controversy about the appropriateness of
describing Thomas’s philosophy and that of other medievals as a Christian
philosophy. An increasing number of non-Catholic thinkers are currently
directing considerable attention to Aquinas, and the varying backgrounds they
bring to his texts will undoubtedly result in still other interesting
interpretations and applications of his thought to contemporary concerns. : --a strange genitive for “Aquino,” the
little village where the saint was born. while Grice, being C. of E., would
avoid Aquinas like the rats, he was aware of Aquinas’s clever ‘intention-based
semantics’ in his commentary of Aristotle’s De Interpretatione. Saint Thomas
122574, philosopher-theologian, the most
influential thinker of the medieval period. He produced a powerful
philosophical synthesis that combined Aristotelian and Neoplatonic elements
within a Christian context in an original and ingenious way. Life and works.
Thomas was born at Aquino castle in Roccasecca, Italy, and took early schooling
at the Benedictine Abbey of Monte Cassino. He then studied liberal arts and
philosophy at the of Naples 123944 and
joined the Dominican order. While going to Paris for further studies as a Dominican,
he was detained by his family for about a year. Upon being released, he studied
with the Dominicans at Paris, perhaps privately, until 1248, when he journeyed
to a priori argument Aquinas, Saint Thomas 36
36 Cologne to work under Albertus Magnus. Thomas’s own report reportatio
of Albertus’s lectures on the Divine Names of Dionysius and his notes on
Albertus’s lectures on Aristotle’s Ethics date from this period. In 1252 Thomas
returned to Paris to lecture there as a bachelor in theology. His resulting
commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard dates from this period, as do two
philosophical treatises, On Being and Essence De ente et essentia and On the
Principles of Nature De principiis naturae. In 1256 he began lecturing as
master of theology at Paris. From this period 125659 date a series of
scriptural commentaries, the disputations On Truth De veritate, Quodlibetal
Questions VIIXI, and earlier parts of the Summa against the Gentiles Summa
contra gentiles; hereafter SCG. At different locations in Italy from 1259 to
1269, Thomas continued to write prodigiously, including, among other works, the
completion of the SCG; a commentary on the Divine Names; disputations On the
Power of God De potentia Dei and On Evil De malo; and Summa of Theology Summa
theologiae; hereafter ST, Part I. In January 1269, he resumed teaching in Paris
as regent master and wrote extensively until returning to Italy in 1272. From
this second Parisian regency date the disputations On the Soul De anima and On
Virtues De virtutibus; continuation of ST; Quodlibets IVI and XII; On the Unity
of the Intellect against the Averroists De unitate intellectus contra
Averroistas; most if not all of his commentaries on Aristotle; a commentary on
the Book of Causes Liber de causis; and On the Eternity of the World De
aeternitate mundi. In 1272 Thomas returned to Italy where he lectured on
theology at Naples and continued to write until December 6, 1273, when his
scholarly work ceased. He died three months later en route to the Second
Council of Lyons. Doctrine. Aquinas was both a philosopher and a theologian.
The greater part of his writings are theological, but there are many strictly
philosophical works within his corpus, such as On Being and Essence, On the
Principles of Nature, On the Eternity of the World, and the commentaries on Aristotle
and on the Book of Causes. Also important are large sections of strictly
philosophical writing incorporated into theological works such as the SCG, ST,
and various disputations. Aquinas clearly distinguishes between strictly
philosophical investigation and theological investigation. If philosophy is
based on the light of natural reason, theology sacra doctrina presupposes faith
in divine revelation. While the natural light of reason is insufficient to
discover things that can be made known to human beings only through revelation,
e.g., belief in the Trinity, Thomas holds that it is impossible for those
things revealed to us by God through faith to be opposed to those we can
discover by using human reason. For then one or the other would have to be false;
and since both come to us from God, God himself would be the author of falsity,
something Thomas rejects as abhorrent. Hence it is appropriate for the
theologian to use philosophical reasoning in theologizing. Aquinas also
distinguishes between the orders to be followed by the theologian and by the
philosopher. In theology one reasons from belief in God and his revelation to
the implications of this for created reality. In philosophy one begins with an
investigation of created reality insofar as this can be understood by human
reason and then seeks to arrive at some knowledge of divine reality viewed as
the cause of created reality and the end or goal of one’s philosophical inquiry
SCG II, c. 4. This means that the order Aquinas follows in his theological
Summae SCG and ST is not the same as that which he prescribes for the
philosopher cf. Prooemium to Commentary on the Metaphysics. Also underlying
much of Aquinas’s thought is his acceptance of the difference between
theoretical or speculative philosophy including natural philosophy,
mathematics, and metaphysics and practical philosophy. Being and analogy. For
Aquinas the highest part of philosophy is metaphysics, the science of being as
being. The subject of this science is not God, but being, viewed without
restriction to any given kind of being, or simply as being Prooemium to
Commentary on Metaphysics; In de trinitate, qu. 5, a. 4. The metaphysician does
not enjoy a direct vision of God in this life, but can reason to knowledge of
him by moving from created effects to awareness of him as their uncreated
cause. God is therefore not the subject of metaphysics, nor is he included in
its subject. God can be studied by the metaphysician only indirectly, as the
cause of the finite beings that fall under being as being, the subject of the
science. In order to account for the human intellect’s discovery of being as
being, in contrast with being as mobile studied by natural philosophy or being
as quantified studied by mathematics, Thomas appeals to a special kind of
intellectual operation, a negative judgment, technically named by him
“separation.” Through this operation one discovers that being, in order to be
realized as such, need not be material and changAquinas, Saint Thomas Aquinas,
Saint Thomas 37 37 ing. Only as a
result of this judgment is one justified in studying being as being. Following
Aristotle and Averroes, Thomas is convinced that the term ‘being’ is used in
various ways and with different meanings. Yet these different usages are not
unrelated and do enjoy an underlying unity sufficient for being as being to be
the subject of a single science. On the level of finite being Thomas adopts and
adapts Aristotle’s theory of unity by reference to a first order of being. For
Thomas as for Aristotle this unity is guaranteed by the primary referent in our
predication of being substance. Other
things are named being only because they are in some way ordered to and
dependent on substance, the primary instance of being. Hence being is
analogous. Since Thomas’s application of analogy to the divine names
presupposes the existence of God, we shall first examine his discussion of that
issue. The existence of God and the “five ways.” Thomas holds that unaided
human reason, i.e., philosophical reason, can demonstrate that God exists, that
he is one, etc., by reasoning from effect to cause De trinitate, qu. 2, a. 3;
SCG I, c. 4. Best-known among his many presentations of argumentation for God’s
existence are the “five ways.” Perhaps even more interesting for today’s student
of his metaphysics is a brief argument developed in one of his first writings,
On Being and Essence c.4. There he wishes to determine how essence is realized
in what he terms “separate substances,” i.e., the soul, intelligences angels of
the Christian tradition, and the first cause God. After criticizing the view
that created separate substances are composed of matter and form, Aquinas
counters that they are not entirely free from composition. They are composed of
a form or essence and an act of existing esse. He immediately develops a
complex argument: 1 We can think of an essence or quiddity without knowing
whether or not it actually exists. Therefore in such entities essence and act
of existing differ unless 2 there is a thing whose quiddity and act of existing
are identical. At best there can be only one such being, he continues, by
eliminating multiplication of such an entity either through the addition of
some difference or through the reception of its form in different instances of
matter. Hence, any such being can only be separate and unreceived esse, whereas
esse in all else is received in something else, i.e., essence. 3 Since esse in
all other entities is therefore distinct from essence or quiddity, existence is
communicated to such beings by something else, i.e., they are caused. Since
that which exists through something else must be traced back to that which
exists of itself, there must be some thing that causes the existence of
everything else and that is identical with its act of existing. Otherwise one
would regress to infinity in caused causes of existence, which Thomas here
dismisses as unacceptable. In qu. 2, a. 1 of ST I Thomas rejects the claim that
God’s existence is self-evident to us in this life, and in a. 2 maintains that
God’s existence can be demonstrated by reasoning from knowledge of an existing
effect to knowledge of God as the cause required for that effect to exist. The
first way or argument art. 3 rests upon the fact that various things in our
world of sense experience are moved. But whatever is moved is moved by
something else. To justify this, Thomas reasons that to be moved is to be
reduced from potentiality to actuality, and that nothing can reduce itself from
potency to act; for it would then have to be in potency if it is to be moved
and in act at the same time and in the same respect. This does not mean that a
mover must formally possess the act it is to communicate to something else if
it is to move the latter; it must at least possess it virtually, i.e., have the
power to communicate it. Whatever is moved, therefore, must be moved by
something else. One cannot regress to infinity with moved movers, for then
there would be no first mover and, consequently, no other mover; for second
movers do not move unless they are moved by a first mover. One must, therefore,
conclude to the existence of a first mover which is moved by nothing else, and
this “everyone understands to be God.” The second way takes as its point of
departure an ordering of efficient causes as indicated to us by our
investigation of sensible things. By this Thomas means that we perceive in the
world of sensible things that certain efficient causes cannot exercise their
causal activity unless they are also caused by something else. But nothing can
be the efficient cause of itself, since it would then have to be prior to
itself. One cannot regress to infinity in ordered efficient causes. In ordered
efficient causes, the first is the cause of the intermediary, and the
intermediary is the cause of the last whether the intermediary is one or many.
Hence if there were no first efficient cause, there would be no intermediary
and no last cause. Thomas concludes from this that one must acknowledge the
existence of a first efficient cause, “which everyone names God.” The third way
consists of two major parts. Some Aquinas, Saint Thomas Aquinas, Saint Thomas
38 38 textual variants have complicated
the proper interpretation of the first part. In brief, Aquinas appeals to the
fact that certain things are subject to generation and corruption to show that
they are “possible,” i.e., capable of existing and not existing. Not all things
can be of this kind revised text, for that which has the possibility of not
existing at some time does not exist. If, therefore, all things are capable of
not existing, at some time there was nothing whatsoever. If that were so, even
now there would be nothing, since what does not exist can only begin to exist
through something else that exists. Therefore not all beings are capable of
existing and not existing. There must be some necessary being. Since such a
necessary, i.e., incorruptible, being might still be caused by something else,
Thomas adds a second part to the argument. Every necessary being either depends
on something else for its necessity or it does not. One cannot regress to
infinity in necessary beings that depend on something else for their necessity.
Therefore there must be some being that is necessary of itself and that does
not depend on another cause for its necessity, i.e., God. The statement in the
first part to the effect that what has the possibility of not existing at some
point does not exist has been subject to considerable dispute among
commentators. Moreover, even if one grants this and supposes that every
individual being is a “possible” and therefore has not existed at some point in
the past, it does not easily follow from this that the totality of existing
things will also have been nonexistent at some point in the past. Given this,
some interpreters prefer to substitute for the third way the more satisfactory
versions found in SCG I ch. 15 and SCG II ch. 15. Thomas’s fourth way is based
on the varying degrees of perfection we discover among the beings we
experience. Some are more or less good, more or less true, more or less noble,
etc., than others. But the more and less are said of different things insofar
as they approach in varying degrees something that is such to a maximum degree.
Therefore there is something that is truest and best and noblest and hence that
is also being to the maximum degree. To support this Thomas comments that those
things that are true to the maximum degree also enjoy being to the maximum
degree; in other words he appeals to the convertibility between being and truth
of being. In the second part of this argument Thomas argues that what is
supremely such in a given genus is the cause of all other things in that genus.
Therefore there is something that is the cause of being, goodness, etc., for
all other beings, and this we call God. Much discussion has centered on
Thomas’s claim that the more and less are said of different things insofar as
they approach something that is such to the maximum degree. Some find this
insufficient to justify the conclusion that a maximum must exist, and would here
insert an appeal to efficient causality and his theory of participation. If
certan entities share or participate in such a perfection only to a limited
degree, they must receive that perfection from something else. While more
satisfactory from a philosophical perspective, such an insertion seems to
change the argument of the fourth way significantly. The fifth way is based on
the way things in the universe are governed. Thomas observes that certain
things that lack the ability to know, i.e., natural bodies, act for an end.
This follows from the fact that they always or at least usually act in the same
way to attain that which is best. For Thomas this indicates that they reach
their ends by “intention” and not merely from chance. And this in turn implies
that they are directed to their ends by some knowing and intelligent being.
Hence some intelligent being exists that orders natural things to their ends.
This argument rests on final causality and should not be confused with any
based on order and design. Aquinas’s frequently repeated denial that in this
life we can know what God is should here be recalled. If we can know that God
exists and what he is not, we cannot know what he is see, e.g., SCG I, c. 30.
Even when we apply the names of pure perfections to God, we first discover such
perfections in limited fashion in creatures. What the names of such perfections
are intended to signify may indeed be free from all imperfection, but every
such name carries with it some deficiency in the way in which it signifies.
When a name such as ‘goodness’, for instance, is signified abstractly e.g.,
‘God is goodness’, this abstract way of signifying suggests that goodness does
not subsist in itself. When such a name is signified concretely e.g., ‘God is
good’, this concrete way of signifying implies some kind of composition between
God and his goodness. Hence while such names are to be affirmed of God as
regards that which they signify, the way in which they signify is to be denied
of him. This final point sets the stage for Thomas to apply his theory of
analogy to the divine names. Names of pure perfections such as ‘good’, ‘true’,
‘being’, etc., cannot be applied to God with Aquinas, Saint Thomas Aquinas,
Saint Thomas 39 39 exactly the same
meaning they have when affirmed of creatures univocally, nor with entirely
different meanings equivocally. Hence they are affirmed of God and of creatures
by an analogy based on the relationship that obtains between a creature viewed
as an effect and God its uncaused cause. Because some minimum degree of
similarity must obtain between any effect and its cause, Thomas is convinced
that in some way a caused perfection imitates and participates in God, its
uncaused and unparticipated source. Because no caused effect can ever be equal
to its uncreated cause, every perfection that we affirm of God is realized in
him in a way different from the way we discover it in creatures. This
dissimilarity is so great that we can never have quidditative knowledge of God
in this life know what God is. But the similarity is sufficient for us to
conclude that what we understand by a perfection such as goodness in creatures
is present in God in unrestricted fashion. Even though Thomas’s identification
of the kind of analogy to be used in predicating divine names underwent some
development, in mature works such as On the Power of God qu. 7, a. 7, SCG I
c.34, and ST I qu. 13, a. 5, he identifies this as the analogy of “one to
another,” rather than as the analogy of “many to one.” In none of these works
does he propose using the analogy of “proportionality” that he had previously
defended in On Truth qu. 2, a. 11. Theological virtues. While Aquinas is
convinced that human reason can arrive at knowledge that God exists and at
meaningful predication of the divine names, he does not think the majority of
human beings will actually succeed in such an effort SCG I, c. 4; ST IIIIae,
qu. 2, a. 4. Hence he concludes that it was fitting for God to reveal such
truths to mankind along with others that purely philosophical inquiry could
never discover even in principle. Acceptance of the truth of divine revelation
presupposes the gift of the theological virtue of faith in the believer. Faith
is an infused virtue by reason of which we accept on God’s authority what he
has revealed to us. To believe is an act of the intellect that assents to
divine truth as a result of a command on the part of the human will, a will
that itself is moved by God through grace ST II IIae, qu. 2, a. 9. For Thomas
the theological virtues, having God the ultimate end as their object, are prior
to all other virtues whether natural or infused. Because the ultimate end must
be present in the intellect before it is present to the will, and because the
ultimate end is present in the will by reason of hope and charity the other two
theological virtues, in this respect faith is prior to hope and charity. Hope
is the theological virtue through which we trust that with divine assistance we
will attain the infinite good eternal
enjoyment of God ST IIIIae, qu. 17, aa. 12. In the order of generation, hope is
prior to charity; but in the order of perfection charity is prior both to hope
and faith. While neither faith nor hope will remain in those who reach the
eternal vision of God in the life to come, charity will endure in the blessed.
It is a virtue or habitual form that is infused into the soul by God and that
inclines us to love him for his own sake. If charity is more excellent than
faith or hope ST II IIae, qu. 23, a. 6, through charity the acts of all other
virtues are ordered to God, their ultimate end qu. 23, a. 8.
ars: as in ars liberalis, the seven liberal arts –
philosophy is NOT one of them, but the trivium and quadrivium are – So, while
logic or dialectica or witcraft is an art, or technique, philosophy is free
from those constraints. The philosopher is insulted if considered a
craftman! techne Grecian, ‘art’, ‘craft’, a human skill
based on general principles and capable of being taught. In this sense, a
manual craft such as carpentry is a techne, but so are sciences such as
medicine and arithmetic. According to Plato Gorgias 501a, a genuine techne
understands its subject matter and can give a rational account of its activity.
Aristotle Metaphysics I.1 distinguishes technefrom experience on the grounds that
techne involves knowledge of universals and causes, and can be taught.
Sometimes ‘techne’ is restricted to the productive as opposed to theoretical
and practical arts, as at Nicomachean Ethics VI.4. Techne and its products are
often contrasted with physis, nature Physics II.1.
arbitrium: cfr. choose. arminius,
Jacobus 15601609, Dutch theologian who, as a Dutch Reformed pastor and later
professor at the of Leiden, challenged
Calvinist orthodoxy on predestination and free will. After his death, followers
codified Arminius’s views in a document asserting that God’s grace is necessary
for salvation, but not irresistible: the divine decree depends on human free
choice. This became the basis for Arminianism, which was condemned by the Dutch
ReAristotle, commentaries on Arminius, Jacobus 51 51 formed synod but vigorously debated for
centuries among Protestant theologians of different denominations. The term
‘Arminian’ is still occasionally applied to theologians who defend a free human
response to divine grace against predestinationism.
arcesilaus: Grecian,
pre-Griceian, sceptic philosopher, founder of the Middle Academy. Influenced by
Socratic elenchus, he claimed that, unlike Socrates, he was not even certain
that he was certain of nothing. He shows the influence of Pyrrho in attacking
the Stoic doctrine that the subjective certainty of the wise is the criterion
of truth. At the theoretical level he advocated epoche, suspension of rational
judgment; at the practical, he argued that eulogon, probability, can justify
action an early version of coherentism.
His ethical views were not extreme; he held, e.g., that one should attend to
one’s own life rather than external objects. Though he wrote nothing except
verse, he led the Academy into two hundred years of Skepticism.
archytas: Grecian,
pre-Griceian, Pythagorean philosopher from Tarentum in southern Italy. He was
elected general seven times and sent a ship to rescue Plato from Dionysius II
of Syracuse in 361. He is famous for solutions to specific mathematical
problems, such as the doubling of the cube, but little is known about his
general philosophical principles. His proof that the numbers in a
superparticular ratio have no mean proportional has relevance to music theory,
as does his work with the arithmetic, geometric, and harmonic means. He gave
mathematical accounts of the diatonic, enharmonic, and chromatic scales and
developed a theory of acoustics. Fragments 1 and 2 and perhaps 3 are authentic,
but most material preserved in his name is spurious.
aretaic: sometimes
used by Grice for ‘virtuosum’. arete, ancient Grecian term meaning ‘virtue’ or
‘excellence’. In philosophical contexts, the term was used mainly of virtues of
human character; in broader contexts, arete was applicable to many different
sorts of excellence. The cardinal virtues in the classical period were courage,
wisdom, temperance sophrosune, piety, and justice. Sophists such as Protagoras
claimed to teach such virtues, and Socrates challenged their credentials for doing
so. Several early Platonic dialogues show Socrates asking after definitions of
virtues, and Socrates investigates arete in other dialogues as well.
Conventional views allowed that a person can have one virtue such as courage
but lack another such as wisdom, but Plato’s Protagoras shows Socrates
defending his thesis of the unity of arete, which implies that a person who has
one arete has them all. Platonic accounts of the cardinal virtues with the
exception of piety are given in Book IV of the Republic. Substantial parts of
the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle are given over to discussions of arete,
which he divides into virtues of character and virtues of intellect. This
discussion is the ancestor of most modern theories of virtue ethics.
argumentum:
cited
by Grice in “Aspects of reason.” Grice was Strawson’s tutor for the Logic
Paper, and he had to go with him over the ‘boring theory of the syllogism –
Barbara, Celarent, and the reset of them!” -- syllogism, in Aristotle’s words,
“a discourse in which, a certain thing being stated, something other than what
is stated follows of necessity from being so” Prior Analytics, 24b 18. Three
types of syllogism were usually distinguished: categorical, hypothetical, and
disjunctive. Each will be treated in that order. The categorical syllogism.
This is an argument consisting of three categorical propositions, two serving
as premises and one serving as conclusion. E.g., ‘Some students are happy; all students are high school graduates;
therefore, some high school graduates are happy’. If a syllogism is valid, the
premises must be so related to the conclusion that it is impossible for both
premises to be true and the conclusion false. There are four types of
categorical propositions: universal affirmative or A-propositions ‘All S are P’, or ‘SaP’; universal negative
or E-propositions ‘No S are P’, or
‘SeP’; particular affirmative or I-propositions
‘Some S are P’, or ‘SiP’; and particular negative or O-propositions:
‘Some S are not P’, or ‘SoP’. The mediate basic components of categorical
syllogism are terms serving as subjects or predicates in the premises and the
conclusion. There must be three and only three terms in any categorical
syllogism, the major term, the minor term, and the middle term. Violation of
this basic rule of structure is called the fallacy of four terms quaternio
terminorum; e.g., ‘Whatever is right is useful; only one of my hands is right;
therefore only one of my hands is useful’. Here ‘right’ does not have the same
meaning in its two occurrences; we therefore have more than three terms and
hence no genuine categorical syllogism. The syllogistic terms are identifiable
and definable with reference to the position they have in a given syllogism.
The predicate of the conclusion is the major term; the subject of the
conclusion is the minor term; the term that appears once in each premise but
not in the conclusion is the middle term. As it is used in various types of
categorical propositions, a term is either distributed stands for each and
every member of its extension or undistributed. There is a simple rule
regarding the distribution: universal propositions SaP and SeP distribute their
subject terms; negative propositions SeP and SoP distribute their predicate
terms. No terms are distributed in an I-proposition. Various sets of rules
governing validity of categorical syllogisms have been offered. The following
is a “traditional” set from the popular Port-Royal Logic 1662. R1: The middle
term must be distributed at least once. Violation: ‘All cats are animals; some
animals do not eat liver; therefore some cats do not eat liver’. The middle
term ‘animals’ is not distributed either in the first or minor premise, being
the predicate of an affirmative proposition, nor in the second or major
premise, being the subject of a particular proposition; hence, the fallacy of
undistributed middle. R2: A term cannot be distributed in the conclusion if it
is undistributed in the premises. Violation: ‘All dogs are carnivorous; no
flowers are dogs; therefore, no flowers are carnivorous’. Here the major,
‘carnivorous’, is distributed in the conclusion, being the predicate of a
negative proposition, but not in the premise, serving there as predicate of an
affirmative proposition; hence, the fallacy of illicit major term. Another
violation of R2: ‘All students are happy individuals; no criminals are
students; therefore, no happy individuals are criminals’. Here the minor,
‘happy individuals’, is distributed in the conclusion, but not distributed in
the minor premise; hence the fallacy of illicit minor term. R3: No conclusion
may be drawn from two negative premises. Violation: ‘No dogs are cats; some
dogs do not like liver; therefore, some cats do not like liver’. Here R1 is
satisfied, since the middle term ‘dogs’ is distributed in the minor premise; R2
is satisfied, since both the minor term ‘cats’ as well as the major term
‘things that like liver’ are distributed in the premises and thus no violation
of distribution of terms occurs. It is only by virtue of R3 that we can proclaim
this syllogism to be invalid. R4: A negative conclusion cannot be drawn where
both premises are affirmative. Violation: ‘All educated people take good care
of their children; all syllogism syllogism 894
894 who take good care of their children are poor; therefore, some poor
people are not educated’. Here, it is only by virtue of the rule of quality,
R4, that we can proclaim this syllogism invalid. R5: The conclusion must follow
the weaker premise; i.e., if one of the premises is negative, the conclusion
must be negative, and if one of them is particular, the conclusion must be
particular. R6: From two particular premises nothing follows. Let us offer an
indirect proof for this rule. If both particular premises are affirmative, no
term is distributed and therefore the fallacy of undistributed middle is
inevitable. To avoid it, we have to make one of the premises negative, which
will result in a distributed predicate as middle term. But by R5, the
conclusion must then be negative; thus, the major term will be distributed in
the conclusion. To avoid violating R2, we must distribute that term in the
major premise. It could not be in the position of subject term, since only
universal propositions distribute their subject term and, by hypothesis, both
premises are particular. But we could not use the same negative premise used to
distribute the middle term; we must make the other particular premise negative.
But then we violate R3. Thus, any attempt to make a syllogism with two
particular premises valid will violate one or more basic rules of syllogism.
This set of rules assumes that A- and Epropositions have existential import and
hence that an I- or an O-proposition may legitimately be drawn from a set of
exclusively universal premises. Categorical syllogisms are classified according
to figure and mood. The figure of a categorical syllogism refers to the schema
determined by the possible position of the middle term in relation to the major
and minor terms. In “modern logic,” four syllogistic figures are recognized.
Using ‘M’ for middle term, ‘P’ for major term, and ‘S’ for minor term, they can
be depicted as follows: Aristotle recognized only three syllogistic figures. He
seems to have taken into account just the two premises and the extension of the
three terms occurring in them, and then asked what conclusion, if any, can be
derived from those premises. It turns out, then, that his procedure leaves room
for three figures only: one in which the M term is the subject of one and
predicate of the other premise; another in which the M term is predicated in
both premises; and a third one in which the M term is the subject in both
premises. Medievals followed him, although all considered the so-called
inverted first i.e., moods of the first figure with their conclusion converted
either simply or per accidens to be legitimate also. Some medievals e.g.,
Albalag and most moderns since Leibniz recognize a fourth figure as a distinct
figure, considering syllogistic terms on the basis not of their extension but
of their position in the conclusion, the S term of the conclusion being defined
as the minor term and the P term being defined as the major term. The mood of a
categorical syllogism refers to the configuration of types of categorical
propositions determined on the basis of the quality and quantity of the
propositions serving as premises and conclusion of any given syllogism; e.g.,
‘No animals are plants; all cats are animals; therefore no cats are plants’,
‘MeP, SaM /, SeP’, is a syllogism in the mood EAE in the first figure. ‘All
metals conduct electricity; no stones conduct electricity; therefore no stones
are metals’, ‘PaM, SeM /, SeP’, is the mood AEE in the second figure. In the
four syllogistic figures there are 256 possible moods, but only 24 are valid
only 19 in modern logic, on the ground of a non-existential treatment of A- and
E-propositions. As a mnemonic device and to facilitate reference, names have
been assigned to the valid moods, with each vowel representing the type of
categorical proposition. William Sherwood and Peter of Spain offered the famous
list designed to help students to remember which moods in any given figure are
valid and how the “inevident” moods in the second and third figures are
provable by reduction to those in the first figure: barbara, celarent, darii,
ferio direct Fig. 1; baralipton, celantes, dabitis, fapesmo, frisesomorum
indirect Fig. 1; cesare, camestres, festino, baroco Fig. 2; darapti, felapton,
disamis, datisi, bocardo, ferison Fig. 3. The hypothetical syllogism. The pure
hypothetical syllogism is an argument in which both the premises and the
conclusion are hypothetical, i.e. conditional, propositions; e.g., ‘If the sun
is shining, it is warm; if it is warm, the plants will grow; therefore if the
sun is shining, the plants will grow’. Symbolically, this argument form can be
represented by ‘A P B, B P C /, A P C’. It was not recognized as such by
Aristotle, but Aristotle’s pupil Theophrastus foreshadowed it, even syllogism
syllogism 895 895 though it is not
clear from his example of it ‘If man is,
animal is; if animal is, then substance is; if therefore man is, substance
is’ whether this was seen to be a
principle of term logic or a principle of propositional logic. It was the
MegaricStoic philosophers and Boethius who fully recognized hypothetical
propositions and syllogisms as principles of the most general theory of
deduction. Mixed hypothetical syllogisms are arguments consisting of a
hypothetical premise and a categorical premise, and inferring a categorical
proposition; e.g., ‘If the sun is shining, the plants will grow; the sun is
shining; therefore the plants will grow’. Symbolically, this is represented by
‘P P Q, P /, Q’. This argument form was explicitly formulated in ancient times
by the Stoics as one of the “indemonstrables” and is now known as modus ponens.
Another equally basic form of mixed hypothetical syllogism is ‘P P Q, -Q /,
~P’, known as modus tollens. The disjunctive syllogism. This is an argument in
which the leading premise is a disjunction, the other premise being a denial of
one of the alternatives, concluding to the remaining alternative; e.g., ‘It is
raining or I will go for a walk; but it is not raining; therefore I will go for
a walk’. It is not always clear whether the ‘or’ of the disjunctive premise is
inclusive or exclusive. Symbolic logic removes the ambiguity by using two
different symbols and thus clearly distinguishes between inclusive or weak
disjunction, ‘P 7 Q’, which is true provided not both alternatives are false,
and exclusive or strong disjunction, ‘P W Q’, which is true provided exactly
one alternative is true and exactly one false. The definition of ‘disjunctive
syllogism’ presupposes that the lead premise is an inclusive or weak
disjunction, on the basis of which two forms are valid: ‘P 7 Q, -P /, Q’ and ‘P
7 Q, -Q /, P’. If the disjunctive premise is exclusive, we have four valid
argument forms, and we should speak here
of an exclusive disjunctive syllogism. This is defined as an argument in which
either from an exclusive disjunction and the denial of one of its disjuncts we
infer the remaining disjunct ’P W Q, -P
/,Q’, and ‘P W Q, -Q /, P’ modus tollendo ponens; or else, from an exclusive
disjunction and one of its disjuncts we infer the denial of the remaining
disjunct ’P W Q, P /, -Q’, and ‘P W Q, Q
/,-P’ modus ponendo tollens. “Strictly, ‘argumetum’ is ‘what is argued,’
the passive perfect participle – arguens is the present active participle,
‘argumentatio’ the feminine abstract noun, and ‘argumentarus,’ and
‘argumentarum’ the neuter active future participle. – there is the
argumenttaturum, too.”“I thought I saw an argument, it turned to be some soap”
(Dodgson). Term that Grice borrows from (but “never returned” to) Boethius, the
Roman philosopher. Strictly, Grice is interested in the ‘arguer.’ Say Blackburn
goes to Grice and, not knowing Grice speaks English, writes a skull. Blackburn
intends Grice to think that there is danger, somewhere, even deadly danger. So
there is arguing on Blackburn’s part. And there is INTENDED arguing on
Blackburn’s recipient, Grice, as it happens. For Grice, the truth-value of
“Blackburn communicates (to Grice) that there is danger” does not REQUIRE the
uptake.” “Why, one must just as well require that Jones GETS his job to deem
Smith having GIVEN it to him if that’s what he’s promised. The arguer is
invoked in a self-psi-transmission. For he must think P, and he must think C,
and he must think that P yields C. And this thought that C must be CAUSED by
the fact that he thinks that P yields C. -- f. argŭo , ŭi, ūtum (ŭĭtum, hence
arguiturus, Sall. Fragm. ap. Prisc. p. 882 P.), 3, v. a. cf. ἀργής, white; ἀργός,
bright; Sanscr. árgunas, bright; ragatas, white; and rag, to shine (v. argentum
and argilla); after the same analogy we have clarus, bright; and claro, to make
bright, to make evident; and the Engl. clear, adj., and to clear = to make
clear; v. Georg Curtius p. 171. I. A.. In gen., to make clear, to show,
prove, make known, declare, assert, μηνύειν: “arguo Eam me vidisse intus,”
Plaut. Mil. 2, 3, 66: “non ex auditu arguo,” id. Bacch. 3, 3, 65: “M. Valerius
Laevinus ... speculatores, non legatos, venisse arguebat,” Liv. 30, 23:
“degeneres animos timor arguit,” Verg. A. 4, 13: “amantem et languor et
silentium Arguit,” Hor. Epod. 11, 9; id. C. 1, 13, 7.—Pass., in a mid. signif.:
“apparet virtus arguiturque malis,” makes itself known, Ov. Tr. 4, 3, 80:
“laudibus arguitur vini vinosus Homerus,” betrays himself, Hor. Ep. 1, 19, 6.—
B. Esp. a. With aliquem, to attempt to show something, in one's case, against
him, to accuse, reprove, censure, charge with: Indicāsse est detulisse;
“arguisse accusāsse et convicisse,” Dig. 50, 16, 197 (cf. Fest. p. 22: Argutum
iri in discrimen vocari): tu delinquis, ego arguar pro malefactis? Enn. (as
transl. of Eurip. Iphig. Aul. 384: Εἶτ̓ ἐγὼ δίκην δῶ σῶν κακῶν ὁ μὴ σφαλείς)
ap. Rufin. § “37: servos ipsos neque accuso neque arguo neque purgo,” Cic.
Rosc. Am. 41, 120: “Pergin, sceleste, intendere hanc arguere?” Plaut. Mil. 2,
4, 27; 2, 2, 32: “hae tabellae te arguunt,” id. Bacch. 4, 6, 10: “an hunc porro
tactum sapor arguet oris?” Lucr. 4, 487: “quod adjeci, non ut arguerem, sed ne
arguerer,” Vell. 2, 53, 4: “coram aliquem arguere,” Liv. 43, 5: “apud
praefectum,” Tac. A. 14, 41: “(Deus) arguit te heri,” Vulg. Gen. 31, 42; ib.
Lev. 19, 17; ib. 2 Tim. 4, 2; ib. Apoc. 3, 19 al.— b. With the cause of
complaint in the gen.; abl. with or without de; with in with abl.; with acc.;
with a clause as object; or with ut (cf. Ramsh. p. 326; Zumpt, § 446). (α).
With gen.: “malorum facinorum,” Plaut. Ps. 2, 4, 56 (cf. infra, argutus, B.
2.): “aliquem probri, Stupri, dedecoris,” id. Am. 3, 2, 2: “viros mortuos summi
sceleris,” Cic. Rab. Perd. 9, 26: “aliquem tanti facinoris,” id. Cael. 1:
“criminis,” Tac. H. 1, 48: “furti me arguent,” Vulg. Gen. 30, 33; ib. Eccl. 11,
8: “repetundarum,” Tac. A. 3, 33: “occupandae rei publicae,” id. ib. 6, 10:
“neglegentiae,” Suet. Caes. 53: “noxae,” id. Aug. 67: “veneni in se comparati,”
id. Tib. 49: “socordiae,” id. Claud. 3: “mendacii,” id. Oth. 10: “timoris,”
Verg. A. 11, 384: “sceleris arguemur,” Vulg. 4 Reg. 7, 9; ib. Act. 19, 40 al.—
(β). With abl.: “te hoc crimine non arguo,” Cic. Verr. 2, 5, 18; Nep. Paus. 3
fin.— (γ). With de: “de eo crimine, quo de arguatur,” Cic. Inv 2, 11, 37: “de
quibus quoniam verbo arguit, etc.,” id. Rosc. Am. 29 fin.: “Quis arguet me de
peccato?” Vulg. Joan. 8, 46; 16, 8.— (δ). With in with abl. (eccl. Lat.): “non
in sacrificiis tuis arguam te,” Vulg. Psa. 49, 8.—(ε) With acc.: quid
undas Arguit et liquidam molem camposque natantīs? of what does he impeach the
waves? etc., quid being here equivalent to cujus or de quo, Lucr. 6, 405
Munro.—(ζ)
With an inf.-clause as object: “quae (mulier) me arguit Hanc domo ab se
subripuisse,” Plaut. Men. 5, 2, 62; id. Mil. 2, 4, 36: “occidisse patrem Sex.
Roscius arguitur,” Cic. Rosc. Am. 13, 37: “auctor illius injuriae fuisse
arguebatur?” Cic. Verr. 2, 1, 33: “qui sibimet vim ferro intulisse arguebatur,”
Suet. Claud. 16; id. Ner. 33; id. Galb. 7: “me Arguit incepto rerum accessisse
labori,” Ov. M. 13, 297; 15, 504.—(η) With ut, as in
Gr. ὡς (post-Aug. and rare), Suet. Ner. 7: “hunc ut dominum et tyrannum, illum
ut proditorem arguentes,” as being master and tyrant, Just. 22, 3.— II. Transf.
to the thing. 1. To accuse, censure, blame: “ea culpa, quam arguo,” Liv. 1, 28:
“peccata coram omnibus argue,” Vulg. 1 Tim. 5, 20: “tribuni plebis dum arguunt
in C. Caesare regni voluntatem,” Vell. 2, 68; Suet. Tit. 5 fin.:
“taciturnitatem pudoremque quorumdam pro tristitiā et malignitate arguens,” id.
Ner. 23; id. Caes. 75: “arguebat et perperam editos census,” he accused of
giving a false statement of property, census, id. Calig. 38: “primusque
animalia mensis Arguit imponi,” censured, taught that it was wrong, Ov. M. 15,
73: “ut non arguantur opera ejus,” Vulg. Joan. 3, 20.— 2. Trop., to denounce as
false: “quod et ipsum Fenestella arguit,” Suet. Vit. Ter. p. 292 Roth.—With reference
to the person, to refute, confute: “aliquem,” Suet. Calig. 8.—Hence, argūtus ,
a, um, P. a. A. Of physical objects, clear. 1. To the sight, bright, glancing,
lively: “manus autem minus arguta, digitis subsequens verba, non exprimens,”
not too much in motion, Cic. de Or. 3, 59, 220 (cf. id. Or. 18, 59: nullae
argutiae digitorum, and Quint. 11, 3, 119-123): “manus inter agendum argutae
admodum et gestuosae,” Gell. 1, 5, 2: “et oculi nimis arguti, quem ad modum
animo affecti sumus, loquuntur,” Cic. Leg. 1, 9, 27: “ocelli,” Ov. Am. 3, 3, 9;
3, 2, 83: “argutum caput,” a head graceful in motion, Verg. G. 3, 80 (breve,
Servius, but this idea is too prosaic): aures breves et argutae, ears that move
quickly (not stiff, rigid), Pall. 4, 13, 2: “argutā in soleā,” in the neat
sandal, Cat. 68, 72.— 2. a.. To the hearing, clear, penetrating, piercing, both
of pleasant and disagreeable sounds, clear-sounding, sharp, noisy, rustling,
whizzing, rattling, clashing, etc. (mostly poet.): linguae, Naev. ap. Non. p.
9, 24: “aves,” Prop. 1, 18, 30: “hirundo,” chirping, Verg. G. 1, 377: “olores,”
tuneful, id. E. 9, 36: ilex, murmuring, rustling (as moved by the wind), id.
ib. 7, 1: “nemus,” id. ib. 8, 22 al.—Hence, a poet. epithet of the musician and
poet, clear-sounding, melodious: “Neaera,” Hor. C. 3, 14, 21: “poëtae,” id. Ep.
2, 2, 90: “fama est arguti Nemesis formosa Tibullus,” Mart. 8, 73, 7: forum,
full of bustle or din, noisy, Ov. A.A. 1, 80: “serra,” grating, Verg. G. 1,
143: “pecten,” rattling, id. ib. 1, 294; id. A. 7, 14 (cf. in Gr. κερκὶς ἀοιδός,
Aristoph. Ranae, v. 1316) al.—Hence, of rattling, prating, verbose discourse:
“sine virtute argutum civem mihi habeam pro preaeficā, etc.,” Plaut. Truc. 2,
6, 14: “[Neque mendaciloquom neque adeo argutum magis],” id. Trin. 1, 2, 163
Ritschl.— b. Trop., of written communications, rattling, wordy, verbose:
“obviam mihi litteras quam argutissimas de omnibus rebus crebro mittas,” Cic.
Att. 6, 5: vereor, ne tibi nimium arguta haec sedulitas videatur, Cael. ap.
Cic. Fam. 8, 1. —Transf. to omens, clear, distinct, conclusive, clearly
indicative, etc.: “sunt qui vel argutissima haec exta esse dicant,” Cic. Div.
2, 12 fin.: “non tibi candidus argutum sternuit omen Amor?” Prop. 2, 3, 24.— 3.
To the smell; sharp, pungent: “odor argutior,” Plin. 15, 3, 4, § 18.— 4. To the
taste; sharp, keen, pungent: “sapor,” Pall. 3, 25, 4; 4, 10, 26.— B. Of mental
qualities. 1. In a good sense, bright, acute, sagacious, witty: “quis illo (sc.
Catone) acerbior in vituperando? in sententiis argutior?” Cic. Brut. 17, 65:
“orator,” id. ib. 70, 247: “poëma facit ita festivum, ita concinnum, ita
elegans, nihil ut fieri possit argutius,” id. Pis. 29; so, “dicta argutissima,”
id. de Or. 2, 61, 250: “sententiae,” id. Opt. Gen. 2: “acumen,” Hor. A. P. 364:
“arguto ficta dolore queri,” dexterously-feigned pain, Prop. 1, 18, 26 al.— 2.
In a bad sense, sly, artful, cunning: “meretrix,” Hor. S. 1, 10, 40: calo. id.
Ep. 1, 14, 42: “milites,” Veg. Mil. 3, 6.—As a pun: ecquid argutus est? is he
cunning? Ch. Malorum facinorum saepissime (i.e. has been accused of), Plaut.
Ps. 2, 4, 56 (v. supra, I. B. a.).—Hence, adv.: argūtē (only in the signif. of
B.). a. Subtly, acutely: “respondere,” Cic. Cael. 8: “conicere,” id. Brut. 14,
53: “dicere,” id. Or. 28, 98.—Comp.: “dicere,” Cic. Brut. 11, 42.— Sup.: “de re
argutissime disputare,” Cic. de Or. 2, 4, 18.— b. Craftily: “obrepere,” Plaut. Trin.
4, 2, 132; Arn. 5, p. 181. For Grice, an argumentum is a sequence of statements
such that some of them the premises purport to give reason to accept another of
them, the conclusion. Since we speak of bad arguments and weak arguments, the
premises of an argument need not really support the conclusion, but they must
give some appearance of doing so or the term ‘argument’ is misapplied. Logic is
mainly concerned with the question of validity: whether if the premises are
true we would have reason to accept the conclusion. A valid argument with true
premises is called sound. A valid deductive argument is one such that if we
accept the premises we are logically bound to accept the conclusion and if we
reject the conclusion we are logically bound to reject one or more of the
premises. Alternatively, the premises logically entail the conclusion. A good
inductive argument some would reserve
‘valid’ for deductive arguments is one
such that if we accept the premises we are logically bound to regard the
conclusion as probable, and, in addition, as more probable than it would be if
the premises should be false. A few arguments have only one premise and/or more
than one conclusion.
argumentum a
fortiori: According
to Grice, an argument that moves from the premises that everything which
possesses a certain characteristics will possess some further characteristics
and that certain things possess the relevant characteristics to an eminent
degree to the conclusion that a fortiori even more so these things will possess
the further characteristics. The second premise is often left implicit – or
implicated, as Grice prefers, so a fortiori arguments are often enthymemes. A
favourite illustration by Grice of an a fortiori argument can be found in
Plato’s Crito. We owe gratitude and respect to our parents and so should do
nothing to harm them. However, athenians owe even greater gratitude and respect
to the laws of Athens. Therefore, a fortiori, Athenians should do nothing to
harm those laws.
arbor griceiana: When Kant
introduces the categoric imperative in terms of the ‘maxim’ he does not specify which. He just goes,
irritatingly, “Make the maxim of your conduct a law of nature.” This gave free
rein to Grice to multiply maxims as much as he wished. If he was an occamist
about senses, he certainly was an anti-occamist about maxims. The expression
Strawson and Wiggins use (p. 520) is “ramification.”So Grice needs just ONE
principle – indeed the idea of principles, in plural, is self-contradictory.
For whch ‘first’ is ‘first’? Eventually, he sticks with the principle of
conversational co-operation. And the principle of conversational co-operation,
being Ariskantian, and categoric, even if not ‘moral,’ “ramifies into” the
maxims. This is important. While an ‘ought’ cannot be derived from an ‘is,’ an
‘ought’ can yield a sub-ought. So whatever obligation the principle brings, the
maxim inherit. The maxim is also stated categoric. But it isn’t. It is a
‘counsel of prudence,’ and hypothetical in nature – So, Grice is just ‘playing
Kant,’ but not ‘being’ Kant. The principle states the GOAL (not happiness,
unless we call it ‘conversational eudaemonia’). In any case, as Hare would
agree, there is ‘deontic derivability.’ So if the principle ramifies into the
maxims, the maxims are ‘deductible’ from the principle. This deductibility is
obvious in terms of from generic to specific. The principle merely enjoins to
make the conversational move as is appropriate. Then, playing with Kant, Grice
chooses FOUR dimensions. Two correspond to the material: the quale and the
quantum. The quale relates to affirmation and negation, and Grice uses ‘false,’
which while hardly conceptually linked to ‘negation,’ it relates in common
parlance. So you have things like a prohibition to say the ‘false’ (But “it is
raining” can be false, and it’s affirmative). The quantum relates to what Grice
calls ‘informative CONTENT.’ He grants that the verb ‘inform’ already ENTAILS
the candour that quality brings. So ‘fortitude’ seems a better way to qualify
this dimension. Make the strongest conversational move. The clash with the
quality is obvious – “provided it’s not false.” The third dimension relates two
two materials. Notably the one by the previous conversationalist and your own.
If A said, “She is an old bag.” B says, “The weather’s been delightful.” By NOT
relating the ‘proposition’ “The weather has been delightful” to “She is an old
bag.” He ‘exploits’ the maxim. This is not a concept in Kant. It mocks Kant. But
yet, ‘relate!’ does follow from the principle of cooperation. So, there is an
UNDERLYING relation, as Hobbes noted, when he discussed a very distantly
related proposition concerning the history of Rome, and expecting the recipient
to “only connect.” So the ‘exploitation’ is ‘superficial,’ and applies to the
explicatum. Yet, the emissor does communicate that the weather has been
delightful. Only there is no point in informing the recipient about it, unless
he is communicating that the co-conversationalist has made a gaffe. Finally,
the category of ‘modus’ Grice restricts to the ‘forma,’ not the ‘materia.’ “Be
perspicuous” is denotically entailed by “Make your move appropriate.” This is
the desideratum of clarity. The point must be ‘explicit.’ This is Strawson and Wiggins way of putting
this. It’s a difficult issue. What the connection is between Grice’s principle
of conversational helpfulness and the attending conversational maxims. Strawson
and Wiggins state that Grice should not feel the burden to make the maxims
‘necessarily independent.’
The image of the ramification is a good one – Grice
called it ‘arbor griceiana.’ arbor
griceiana, arbor porphyriana: a
structure generated from the logical and metaphysical apparatus of Aristotle’s
Categories, as systematized by Porphyry and later writers. A tree in the
category of substance begins with substance as its highest genus and divides
that genus into mutually exclusive and collectively exhaustive subordinate
genera by means of a pair of opposites, called differentiae, yielding, e.g.,
corporeal substance and incorporeal substance. The process of division by
differentiae continues until a lowest species is reached, a species that cannot
be divided further. The species “human being” is said to be a lowest species
whose derivation can be recaptured from the formula “mortal, rational,
sensitive, animate, corporeal substance.”
ardigò: essential Italian
philosopher. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice ed Ardigò," per Il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
No comments:
Post a Comment