modus: Grice was an expert on mode. There is one mode too many.
If Grice found ‘senses’ obsolete (“Sense are not to be multiplied beyond
necessity”), he was always ready to welcome a new mode – e. g. the quessertive
--. or mode. ἔγκλισις , enclisis, mood of a verb, D.H.Comp.6, D.T.638.7, A.D. Synt.248.14,
etc.Many times, under ‘mode,’ Grice describes what others call ‘aspect.’ Surely
‘tense’ did not affect him much, except when it concerned “=”. But when it came
to modes, he included ‘aspect,’ so there’s the optative, the imperative, the
indicative, the informational, and then the future intentional and the future
indicative, and the subjunctive, and the way they interact with the praesens,
praeteritum and futurum, and wih the axis of what Aristotle called ‘teleios’
and ‘ateleios,’ indefinite and definite, or ‘perfectum, and ‘imperfectum, ‘but
better ‘definitum’ and ‘indefinitum.’ Grice
uses psi-asrisk, to be read asterisk-sub-psi. He is not concerned with
specficics. All the specifics the philosopher can take or rather ‘assume’ as
‘given.’ The category of mode translates ‘tropos,’ modus. Kant wrongly assumed
it was Modalitat, which irritated Grice so much that he echoed Kant as saying
‘manner’! Grice is a modista. He sometimes uses ‘modus,’ after Abbott. The
earliest record is of course “Meaning.” After elucidating what he calls
‘informative cases,’ he moves to ‘imperative’ ones. Grice agreed with Thomas
Urquhart that English needed a few more moods! Grice’s seven
modes.Thirteenthly, In lieu of six moods which other languages have at most,
this one injoyeth seven in its conjugable words. Ayer had said that
non-indicative utterances are hardly significant. Grice had been freely using
the very English not Latinate ‘mood’ until Moravcsik, of all people, corrects
him: What you mean ain’t a mood. I shall call it mode just to please
you, J. M. E. The sergeant is to muster the men at dawn is a perfect
imperative. They shall not pass is a perfect intentional. A version of this
essay was presented in a conference whose proceedings were published, except
for Grices essay, due to technical complications, viz. his idiosyncratic use of
idiosyncratic symbology! By mode Grice means indicative or imperative.
Following Davidson, Grice attaches probability to the indicative, via the
doxastic, and desirability to the indicative, via the
buletic-boulomaic. He also allows for mixed utterances. Probability
is qualified with a suboperator indicating a degree d; ditto for desirability,
degree d. In some of the drafts, Grice kept using mode until Moravsik suggested
to him that mode was a better choice, seeing that Grices modality had little to
do with what other authors were referring to as mood. Probability,
desirability, and modality, modality, desirability, and probability; modality,
probability, desirability. He would use mode operator. Modality is the
more correct term, for things like should, ought, and must, in that order. One
sense. The doxastic modals are correlated to probability. The buletic or
boulomaic modals are correlated to desirability. There is probability to a
degree d. But there is also desirability to a degree d. They
both combine in Grices attempt to show how Kants categorical imperative reduces
to the hypothetical or suppositional. Kant uses modality in a way that Grice
disfavours, preferring modus. Grice is aware of the use by Kant of
modality qua category in the reduction by Kant to four of the original ten
categories in Aristotle). The Jeffrey-style entitled Probability, desirability,
and mode operators finds Grice at his formal-dress best. It predates the Kant
lectures and it got into so much detail that Grice had to leave it at that. So
abstract it hurts. Going further than Davidson, Grice argues that structures
expressing probability and desirability are not merely analogous. They can both
be replaced by more complex structures containing a common element.
Generalising over attitudes using the symbol ψ, which he had used before, repr.
WoW:v, Grice proposes G ψ that p. Further, Grice uses i as a dummy for sub-divisions
of psychological attitudes. Grice uses Op supra i sub α, read: operation supra
i sub alpha, as Grice was fastidious enough to provide reading versions for
these, and where α is a dummy taking the place of either A or B, i. e.
Davidsons prima facie or desirably, and probably. In all this, Grice keeps
using the primitive !, where a more detailed symbolism would have it correspond
exactly to Freges composite turnstile (horizontal stroke of thought and
vertical stroke of assertoric force, Urteilstrich) that Grice of course also
uses, and for which it is proposed, then: !─p. There are generalising movements
here but also merely specificatory ones. α is not generalised. α is a
dummy to serve as a blanket for this or that specifications. On the other hand,
ψ is indeed generalised. As for i, is it generalising or specificatory? i is a
dummy for specifications, so it is not really generalising. But Grice
generalises over specifications. Grice wants to find buletic, boulomaic or
volitive as he prefers when he does not prefer the Greek root for both his
protreptic and exhibitive versions (operator supra exhibitive, autophoric, and
operator supra protreptic, or hetero-phoric). Note that Grice (WoW:110) uses
the asterisk * as a dummy for either assertoric, i.e., Freges turnstile, and
non-assertoric, the !─ the imperative turnstile, if you wish. The operators A
are not mode operators; they are such that they represent some degree (d) or
measure of acceptability or justification. Grice prefers acceptability because
it connects with accepting that which is a psychological, souly attitude, if a
general one. Thus, Grice wants to have It is desirable that p and It
is believable that p as understood, each, by the concatenation of three
elements. The first element is the A-type operator. The second element is the
protreptic-type operator. The third element is the phrastic, root, content, or
proposition itself. It is desirable that p and It is believable that
p share the utterer-oriented-type operator and the neustic or proposition.
They only differ at the protreptic-type operator (buletic/volitive/boulomaic or
judicative/doxastic). Grice uses + for concatenation, but it is best to use ^,
just to echo who knows who. Grice speaks in that mimeo (which he delivers in
Texas, and is known as Grices Performadillo talk ‒ Armadillo + Performative) of
various things. Grice speaks, transparently enough, of acceptance: V-acceptance
and J-acceptance. V not for Victory but for volitional, and J for judicative.
The fact that both end with -acceptance would accept you to believe that both
are forms of acceptance. Grice irritatingly uses 1 to mean the doxastic, and 2
to mean the bulematic. At Princeton in Method, he defines the doxastic in terms
of the buletic and cares to do otherwise, i. e. define the buletic in terms of
the doxastic. So whenever he wrote buletic read doxastic, and vice versa. One
may omits this arithmetic when reporting on Grices use. Grice uses two further
numerals, though: 3 and 4. These, one may decipher – one finds oneself as an
archeologist in Tutankamons burial ground, as this or that relexive attitude.
Thus, 3, i. e. ψ3, where we need the general operator ψ, not just
specificatory dummy, but the idea that we accept something simpliciter. ψ3
stands for the attitude of buletically accepting an or utterance: doxastically
accepting that p or doxastically accepting that ~p. Why we should be concerned
with ~p is something to consider. G wants to decide whether to believe p
or not. I find that very Griceian. Suppose I am told that there is a volcano in
Iceland. Why would I not want to believe it? It seems that one may want to
decide whether to believe p or not when p involves a tacit appeal to value.
But, as Grice notes, even when it does not involve value, Grice still needs trust
and volition to reign supreme. On the other hand, theres 4, as attached to an
attitude, ψ4. This stands for an attitude of buletically accepting an or
utterance: buletically accepting that p, or G buletically accepting that ~p, i.
e. G wants to decide whether to will, now that p or not. This indeed is
crucial, since, for Grice, morality, as with Kantotle, does cash in desire, the
buletic. Grice smokes. He wills to smoke. But does he will to will to smoke?
Possibly yes. Does he will to will to will to smoke? Regardless of what Grice
wills, one may claim this holds for a serious imperatives (not Thou shalt not
reek, but Thou shalt not kill, say) or for any p if you must (because if you
know that p causes cancer (p stands for a proposition involving cigarette) you
should know you are killing yourself. But then time also kills, so what gives?
So I would submit that, for Kant, the categoric imperative is one which allows
for an indefinite chain, not of chain-smokers, but of good-willers. If, for
some p, we find that at some stage, the P does not will that he wills that he
wills that he wills that, p can not be universalisable. This is proposed in an
essay referred to in The Philosophers Index but Marlboro Cigarettes took no
notice. One may go on to note Grices obsession on make believe. If I say, I
utter expression e because the utterer wants his addressee to believe that the
utterer believes that p, there is utterer and addresse, i. e. there are two
people here ‒ or any soul-endowed creature ‒ for Grices squarrel
means things to Grice. It even implicates. It miaows to me while I was in bed.
He utters miaow. He means that he is hungry, he means (via implicaturum) that
he wants a nut (as provided by me). On another occasion he miaowes explicating,
The door is closed, and implicating Open it, idiot. On the other hand, an
Andy-Capps cartoon read: When budgies get sarcastic Wild-life programmes are
repeating One may note that one can want some other person to hold an
attitude. Grice uses U or G1 for utterer and A or G2 for addressee. These are
merely roles. The important formalism is indeed G1 and G2. G1 is a Griceish
utterer-person; G2 is the other person, G1s addressee. Grice dislikes a menage
a trois, apparently, for he seldom symbolises a third party, G3. So, G ψ-3-A
that p is 1 just in case G ψ2(G ψ1 that p) or G ψ1 that ~p is 1. And here the
utterers addressee, G2 features: G1 ψ³ protreptically that p is 1 just in
case G buletically accepts ψ² (G buletically accepts ψ² (G doxastically accepts
ψ1 that p, or G doxastically accepts ψ1 that ~p))) is 1. Grice seems to be
happy with having reached four sets of operators, corresponding to four sets of
propositional attitudes, and for which Grice provides the paraphrases. The
first set is the doxastic proper. It is what Grice has as doxastic,and which
is, strictly, either indicative, of the utterers doxastic, exhibitive state, as
it were, or properly informative, if addressed to the addressee A, which is
different from U himself, for surely one rarely informs oneself. The second is
the buletic proper. What Grice dubs volitive, but sometimes he prefers the
Grecian root. This is again either self- or utterer-addressed, or
utterer-oriented, or auto-phoric, and it is intentional, or it is
other-addressed, or addressee-addressed, or addressee- oriented, or
hetero-phoric, and it is imperative, for surely one may not always say to
oneself, Dont smoke, idiot!. The third is the doxastic-interrogative, or
doxastic-erotetic. One may expand on ? here is minimal compared to the vagaries
of what I called the !─ (non-doxastic or buletic turnstile), and which may be
symbolised by ?─p, where ?─ stands for the erotetic turnstile. Geachs and
Althams erotetic somehow Grice ignores, as he more often uses the Latinate
interrogative. Lewis and Short have “interrŏgātĭo,” which they render as “a
questioning, inquiry, examination, interrogation;” “sententia per
interrogationem, Quint. 8, 5, 5; instare interrogation; testium; insidiosa;
litteris inclusæ; verbis obligatio fit ex interrogatione et responsione; as
rhet. fig., Quint. 9, 2, 15; 9, 3, 98. B. A syllogism: recte genus hoc
interrogationis ignavum ac iners nominatum est, Cic. Fat. 13; Sen. Ep. 87
med. Surely more people know what interrogative means what erotetic means,
he would not say ‒ but he would. This attitude comes again in two varieties:
self-addressed or utterer-oriented, reflective (Should I go?) or again,
addresee-addressed, or addressee-oriented, imperative, as in Should you go?,
with a strong hint that the utterer is expecting is addressee to make up his
mind in the proceeding, not just inform the utterer. Last but not least, there
is the fourth kind, the buletic-cum-erotetic. Here again, there is one varietiy
which is reflective, autophoric, as Grice prefers, utterer-addressed, or
utterer-oriented, or inquisitive (for which Ill think of a Greek pantomime), or
addressee-addressed, or addressee-oriented. Grice regrets that Greek (and
Latin, of which he had less ‒ cfr. Shakespeare who had none) fares better in
this respect the Oxonian that would please Austen, if not Austin, or Maucalay,
and certainly not Urquhart -- his language has twelve parts of speech: each
declinable in eleven cases, four numbers, eleven genders (including god,
goddess, man, woman, animal, etc.); and conjugable in eleven tenses, seven
moods, and four voices.These vocal mannerisms will result in the production of
some pretty barbarous English sentences; but we must remember that what I shall
be trying to do, in uttering such sentences, will be to represent supposedly underlying
structure; if that is ones aim, one can hardly expect that ones speech-forms
will be such as to excite the approval of, let us say, Jane Austen or Lord
Macaulay. Cf. the quessertive, or quessertion, possibly iterable, that
Grice cherished. But then you cant have everything. Where would you put
it? Grice: The modal implicaturum.
Grice sees two different, though connected questions about
mode. First, there is the obvious demand for a characterisation, or
partial characterisation, of this or that mode as it emerges in this or that
conversational move, which is plausible to regard as modes primary habitat)
both at the level of the explicatum or the implicaturum, for surely an
indicative conversational move may be the vehicle of an imperatival implicaturum.
A second, question is how, and to what extent, the representation of mode
(Hares neustic) which is suitable for application to this or that
conversational move may be legitimately exported into philosophical psychology,
or rather, may be grounded on questions of philosophical psychology, matters of
this or that psychological state, stance, or attitude (notably desire and
belief, and their species). We need to consider the second question, the
philosophico- psychological question, since, if the general rationality
operator is to read as something like acceptability, as in U accepts, or A
accepts, the appearance of this or that mode within its scope of accepting is
proper only if it may properly occur within the scope of a generic
psychological verb I accept that . Lewis and Short have “accepto,” “v.
freq. a. accipio,” which Short and Lewis render as “to take, receive, accept,”
“argentum,” Plaut. Ps. 2, 2, 32; so Quint. 12, 7, 9; Curt. 4, 6, 5; Dig. 34, 1,
9: “jugum,” to submit to, Sil. Ital. 7, 41. But in Plin. 36, 25, 64, the
correct read. is coeptavere; v. Sillig. a. h. l. The easiest way Grice finds to
expound his ideas on the first question is by reference to a schematic table or
diagram (Some have complained that I seldom use a board, but I will today. Grice
at this point reiterates his temporary contempt for the use/mention
distinction, which which Strawson is obsessed. Perhaps Grices contempt is due
to Strawsons obsession. Grices exposition would make the hair stand on end in
the soul of a person especially sensitive in this area. And Im talking to you,
Sir Peter! (He is on the second row). But Grices guess is that the
only historical philosophical mistake properly attributable to use/mention
confusion is Russells argument against Frege in On denoting, and that there is
virtually always an acceptable way of eliminating disregard of the use-mention
distinction in a particular case, though the substitutes are usually lengthy,
obscure, and tedious. Grice makes three initial assumptions. He avails
himself of two species of acceptance, Namesly, volitive acceptance and
judicative acceptance, which he, on occasion, calls respectively willing that p
and willing that p. These are to be thought of as technical or
semi-technical, theoretical or semi-theoretical, though each is a state which
approximates to what we vulgarly call thinking that p and wanting that p,
especially in the way in which we can speak of a beast such as a little
squarrel as thinking or wanting something ‒ a nut, poor darling little
thing. Grice here treats each will and judge (and accept) as a primitive.
The proper interpretation would be determined by the role of each in a
folk-psychological theory (or sequence of folk-psychological theories), of the
type the Wilde reader in mental philosophy favours at Oxford, designed to
account for the behaviours of members of the animal kingdom, at different
levels of psychological complexity (some classes of creatures being more
complex than others, of course). As Grice suggests in Us meaning, sentence-meaning,
and word-meaning, at least at the point at which (Schema Of
Procedure-Specifiers For Mood-Operators) in ones syntactico-semantical
theory of Pirotese or Griceish, one is introducing this or that mode (and
possibly earlier), the proper form to use is a specifier for this or that
resultant procedure. Such a specifier is of the general form, For the
utterer U to utter x if C, where the blank is replaced by the appropriate
condition. Since in the preceding scheme x represents an utterance or expression,
and not a sentence or open sentence, there is no guarantee that this or that
actual sentence in Pirotese or Griceish contains a perspicuous and unambiguous
modal representation. A sentence may correspond to more than one
modal structure. The sentence is structurally ambiguous (multiplex in
meaning ‒ under the proviso that senses are not to be multiplied
beyond necessity) and will have more than one reading, or parsing, as every
schoolboy at Clifton knows when translating viva voce from Greek or Latin, as the
case might be. The general form of a procedure-specifier for a modal operator
involves a main clause and an antecedent clause, which follows if. In the
schematic representation of the main clause, U represents an utterer, A his
addressee, p the radix or neustic; and Opi represents that operator whose
number is i (1, 2, 3, or 4), e.g g., Op3A represents Operator 3A, which,
since ?⊢ appears in the
Operator column for 3A) would be ?A ⊢ p. This reminds one of Grandys
quessertions, for he did think they were iterable (possibly)). The
antecedent clause consists of a sequence whose elements are a preamble, as it
were, or preface, or prefix, a supplement to a differential (which is present only
in a B-type, or addressee-oriented case), a differential, and a radix. The
preamble, which is always present, is invariant, and reads: The U U wills
(that) A A judges (that) U (For surely
meaning is a species of intending is a species of willing that, alla Prichard,
Whites professor, Corpus). The supplement, if present, is also
invariant. And the idea behind its varying presence or absence is
connected, in the first instance, with the volitive mode. The difference
between an ordinary expression of intention ‒ such as I shall
not fail, or They shall not pass ‒ and an ordinary
imperative (Like Be a little kinder to him) is accommodated by treating each as
a sub-mode of the volitive mode, relates to willing that p) In the
intentional case (I shall not fail), the utterer U is concerned to reveal to
his addressee A that he (the utterer U) wills that p. In the imperative case
(They shall not pass), the utterer U is concerned to reveal to his addressee A
that the utterer U wills that the addresee A will that p. In each
case, of course, it is to be presumed that willing that p will have its
standard outcome, viz., the actualization, or realisation, or direction of fit,
of the radix (from expression to world, downwards). There is a corresponding distinction
between two uses of an indicative. The utterer U may be declaring or
affirming that p, in an exhibitive way, with the primary intention to get his
addressee A to judge that the utterer judges that p. Or the U is telling
(in a protreptic way) ones addressee that p, that is to say, hoping to get
his addressee to judge that p. In the case of an indicative, unlike that of a
volitive, there is no explicit pair of devices which would ordinarily be
thought of as sub-mode marker. The recognition of the sub-mode is implicated,
and comes from context, from the vocative use of the Names of the addressee,
from the presence of a speech-act verb, or from a sentence-adverbial phrase
(like for your information, so that you know, etc.). But Grice has
already, in his initial assumptions, allowed for such a situation. The
exhibitive-protreptic distinction or autophoric-heterophoric distinction, seems
to Grice to be also discernible in the interrogative mode (?).
Each differentials is associated with, and serve to distinguish, each of
the two basic modes (volitive or judicative) and, apart from one detail in the
case of the interrogative mode, is invariant between autophoric-exhibitive) and
heterophoric-protreptic sub-modes of any of the two basic modes. They are
merely unsupplemented or supplemented, the former for an exhibitive sub-mode
and the latter for a protreptic sub-mode. The radix needs (one hopes) no
further explanation, except that it might be useful to bear in mind that Grice
does not stipulated that the radix for an intentional (buletic exhibitive
utterer-based) incorporate a reference to the utterer, or be in the first
person, nor that the radix for an imperative (buletic protreptic
addressee-based) incorporate a reference of the addresee, and be in the second
person. They shall not pass is a legitimate intentional, as is You shall
not get away with it; and The sergeant is to muster the men at dawn, as uttered
said by the captain to the lieutenant) is a perfectly good
imperative. Grice gives in full the two specifiers derived from the
schema. U to utter to A autophoric-exhibitive ⊢ p if U wills that A judges that U
judges p. Again, U to utter to A ! heterophoric-protreptic p if U wills that A
A judges that U wills that A wills that p. Since, of the states denoted by
each differential, only willing that p and judging that p are strictly cases of
accepting that p, and Grices ultimate purpose of his introducing this
characterization of mode is to reach a general account of expressions which are
to be conjoined, according to his proposal, with an acceptability operator, the
first two numbered rows of the figure are (at most) what he has a direct use
for. But since it is of some importance to Grice that his treatment of
mode should be (and should be thought to be) on the right lines, he adds a
partial account of the interrogative mode. There are two varieties of
interrogatives, a yes/no interrogatives (e. g. Is his face clean? Is the king
of France bald? Is virtue a fire-shovel?) and x-interrogatives, on which Grice
qua philosopher was particularly interested, v. his The that and the why.
(Who killed Cock Robin?, Where has my beloved gone?, How did he fix
it?). The specifiers derivable from the schema provide only for yes/no
interrogatives, though the figure could be quite easily amended so as to yield
a restricted but very large class of x-interrogatives. Grice indicates how
this could be done. The distinction between a buletic and a doxastic
interrogative corresponds with the difference between a case in which the utterer
U indicates that he is, in one way or another, concerned to obtain information
(Is he at home?), and a case in which the utterer U indicates that he is
concerned to settle a problem about what he is to do ‒ Am I to leave the door
open?, Shall I go on reading? or, with an heterophoric Subjects, Is the
prisoner to be released? This difference is fairly well represented in grammar,
and much better represented in the grammars of some other languages. The
hetero-phoric-cum-protreptic/auto-phoric-cum- exhibitive difference may
not marked at all in this or that grammar, but it should be marked in Pirotese.
This or that sub-mode is, however, often quite easily detectable. There is
usually a recognizable difference between a case in which the utterer A says,
musingly or reflectively, Is he to be trusted? ‒ a case in which the
utterer might say that he is just wondering ‒ and a case in which he
utters a token of the same sentence as an enquiry. Similarly, one can usually
tell whether an utterer A who utters Shall I accept the invitation? is
just trying to make up his mind, or is trying to get advice or instruction from
his addressee. The employment of the variable α needs to be
explained. Grice borrows a little from an obscure branch of logic, once
(but maybe no longer) practised, called, Grice thinks, proto-thetic ‒ Why?
Because it deals with this or that first principle or axiom, or thesis), the
main rite in which is to quantify over, or through, this or that connective. α
is to have as its two substituents positively and negatively, which may modify
either will or judge, negatively willing or negatively judging that p is
judging or willing that ~p. The quantifier (∃1α) . . . has to be treated
substitutionally. If, for example, I ask someone whether John killed Cock
Robin (protreptic case), I do not want the addressee merely to will that I have
a particular logical quality in mind which I believe to apply. I want the
addressee to have one of the Qualities in mind which he wants me to believe to
apply. To meet this demand, supplementation must drag back the
quantifier. To extend the schema so as to provide specifiers for a single
x-interrogative (i. e., a question like What did the butler see? rather than a
question like Who went where with whom at 4 oclock yesterday afternoon?),
we need just a little extra apparatus. We need to be able to superscribe a
W in each interrogative operator e.g., together with the proviso that a radix
which follows a superscribed operator must be an open radix, which contains one
or more occurrences of just one free variable. And we need a chameleon
variable λ, to occur only in this or that quantifier. (∃λ).Fx is to be regarded as a way of
writing (∃x)Fx. (∃λ)Fy is a way of writing (∃y)Fy. To provide a specifier for a
x-superscribed operator, we simply delete the appearances of α in the specifier
for the corresponding un-superscribed operator, inserting instead the
quantifier (∃1λ) () at the
position previously occupied by (∃1α) (). E.g. the specifiers for Who
killed Cock Robin?, used as an enquiry, would be: U to utter to A killed Cock Robin if U wills A to judge U to
will that (∃1λ) (A should
will that U judges (x killed Cock Robin)); in which (∃1λ) takes on the shape (∃1x) since x is the free variable within
its scope. Grice compares his buletic-doxastic distinction to prohairesis/doxa
distinction by Aristotle in Ethica Nichomachea. Perhaps his simplest
formalisation is via subscripts: I will-b but will-d not. Refs.: The main
references are given above under ‘desirability.’ The most systematic treatment
is the excursus in “Aspects,” Clarendon. BANC. modus. “The
distinction between Judicative and Volitive Interrogatives corresponds with the
difference between cases in which a questioner is indicated as being, in one
way or another, concerned to obtain information ("Is he at home?"),
and cases in which the questioner is indicated as being concerned to settle a
problem about what he is to do ("Am I to leave the door open?",
"Is the prisoner to be released?", "Shall I go on
reading?"). This difference is better represented in Grecian and Roman.”The Greek word was ‘egklisis,’ which Priscian translates as
‘modus’ and defines as ‘inclinatio anima, affectionis demonstrans.’ The Greeks
recognised five: horistike, indicativus, pronuntiativus, finitus, or definitivus,
prostastike, imperativus, euktike, optativus, hypotaktike (subjunctivus, or
conjunnctivus, but also volitivus, hortativus, deliberativus, iussivus,
prohibitivus anticipativus ) and aparemphatos infinitivus or infinitus. Modus -- odus optativus.
optative enclisis (gre:
ευκτική έγκλιση, euktike enclisis, hence it may be seen as a modus optatīvus.
Something that fascinated Grice. The way an ‘action’ is modalised in the way
one describes it. He had learned the basics for Greek and Latin at Oxford, and
he was exhilarated to be able to teach now on the subtleties of the English
system of ‘aspect.’ To ‘opt’ is to choose. So ‘optativus’ is the deliberative
mode. Grice proved the freedom of the will with a “grammatical argument.”
‘Given that the Greeks and the Romans had an optative mode, there is free
will.” Romans, having no special verbal forms recognized as Optative, had no
need of the designation modus
optativus. Yet they sometimes used it, ad imitationem. Modus -- modality: Grice: “Modality is the manner in
which a proposition (or statement) describes or applies to its subject matter.
Derivatively,’ modality’ refers to characteristics of entities or states of
affairs described by this or that modal proposition. Modalities are classified
as follows. An assertoric proposition is the expression of a mere fact. Alethic
modality includes necessity and possibility. The latter two sometimes are referred
to respectively as the apodeictic modality and the problematic modality – vide
Grice’s category of conversational mode – which covers three categories under
what Kant calls the ‘Funktion’ of Mode – the assertoric, the apodeictic and the
problematic). Grice takes ‘must’ as basic and defines ‘may’ in terms of ‘must.’
Causal modality includes causal necessity or empirical necessity and causal
possibility or empirical possibility. The deontic modality includes obligation
and permittedness. Of course this hardly means that ‘must’ is polysemous. It is
‘aequi-vocal’ at most. There is epistemic modality or modalities such as
knowing that and doxastic modality (what Grice calls ‘credibility,’ as opposed
to ‘desirability’) or modalities ones such as believing that. There is
desiderative modality such as ‘willing that’ (what Grice calls ‘desirability’
as prior to ‘credibility.’) Following medieval philosophers, a proposition can
be distinguished on the basis of whether the modality is introduced via
adverbial modification of the “copula” or verb (“sensus divisus”) – as in
Grice’s “Fido is shaggy” versus “Fido may be shaggy” – (in Roman, “Fidus est
fidelis” versus “Fidus sit fidelis” – Grice: “Not to be confused with “Fido,
sit!” ) or via a modal operator that modifies the proposition (“sensus
compositus” – as preferred by Strawson: “It is the case that,” “It is not the
case that,” “It must be the case that” and “It may be the case that”). Grice
actually calls ‘adverbial modifier’ the external version. The internal version
he just calls, as everybody at Clifton does, ‘conjugation’ (“We are not
Tarzan!”). Grice: "In Gricese, in the instance in which the
indicative occurs after "acsian" here is no doubt in the minds of
those who ask the question, the content of the dependent clause being by them
regarded as a fact.
Mk. X. 2. Da genealsehton him pharisei and hine axodon hwseber alyfS senegum men his wif forlsetan. Interrogabant eum: INTERROGABANT EUM: SI LICET Si licet. L. XII. 36. beo gelice pam mannum be hyra hlaforde abidafr hwsenne he sy fram
gyftum gecyrred.
L. XXII. 24. hi flitun betwux him hwylc hyra wsere
yldest. J. XIX. 24.
uton hleotan hwylces
ures heo sy. Mk. XV. 24. hi hlotu wurpon, hwset
gehwa name.
mittentes sortem
super eis, quis quid tolleret. MITTENTES SORTEM SVPER EIS, QVIS QVID TOLLERET. M. XXVII. 49. Uton geseon hwseber Helias cume and wylle
hyne alysan. Mk. V. 14. hi ut eodon bset hi
gesawon hwset par gedon wsere. L. XIX. 3.he wolde geseon hwylc se hselend
wsere. Mk. IX. 34.hi on wege smeadon hwylc hyra yldost wsere. Mk. IX.
10. L. XI, 38. XXII. 23. L. XIV. 28. Hwylc eower wyle timbrian anne stypel, hu ne sytt he serest and
teleS pa andfengas be him behefe synt, hwseder he hsebbe hine to
full-fremmenne?
L. I. 29. ba wearS heo on his sprsece gedrefed, and pohte
hwset seo greting wsere.
L. Ill, 15. XIV. 31. L.
IX. 46.
bset gepanc eode on hig,
hwylc hyra yldest wsere. Mk. XV. 47. Da com Maria Magdalene and Josepes Maria, and beheoldon hwar he
geled wsere. aspiciebant. ubi poneretur ASPICIEBANT. VBI
PONERETVR.
(Looked around, in order
to discover). The notion of purpose is sometimes involved, the indirect
question having something of the force of a final clause: Mk.
XIII. 11. ne foresmeage ge hwset ge specan. L. XXI. 14. *) Direct rather than indirect question. L. XII. 22. ne beo ge ymbehydige eowre
sawle hwset ge etan, ne eowrum lichaman hwset ge scrydun. M. VI, 25. L. XII. 11. ne beo ge embebencynde hu oSSe hwset ge specon
oSSe andswarian. M. X. 19. ne bence ge hu oSSe hwset ge
sprecun. L. XII. 29.
Nelle ge secean hwset ge
eton oSSe drincon.
J. XIX. 12. and sySSan sohte Pilatus hu he hyne forlete. quaerebat Pilatus dimittere eum. QVAEREBAT PILATVS DIMITTERE EVM 2. When the content of the dependent clause is regarded as an actual
fact, which is the case when the leading verb expresses the act of learning, perceiving,
etc., the indicative is used. M. VI. 28. BesceawiaS secyres Man hu hig weaxaO. M.
XXI. 16.gehyrst bu hwset pas cwseoab? M. XXVII. 13. Ne gehyrst Jm hu fela sagena hig ongen be
secgeaS?
L. XVIII. 6. M. IX.
13.leornigeab hwset is, ic wylle mildheortnesse
nses onssegdnesse. M. XXI. 20. loca nu hu hrsedlice bset fic-treow forscranc. Mk. XV. 4. loca hu mycelum hi be wregea§. M. XII. 4.Ne
rsedde ge hwset David dyde hu he ineode on Godes hus, and set ba
offring-hlafas?
L. VI, 4. Mk. XII. 26. Be bam deadum ■ bset hi arison, ne rsedde ge on Moyses bec hu God
to him cwseb?
Mk. I, 26. Mk. V. 16. hi rehton him ba Se hit gesawon hu hit gedon wses. L.
VIII. 36.
Da cyddon him ba Se
gesawon hu he wses hal geworden. L. XXIII. 55.hig gesawon ba
byrgene and hu his lichama aled wses. J. XX. 14.heo geseah hwar se
hselend stod.
Vidit Jesum
stantem. *)
VIDIT IESVM STANTEM. Not the endeavour to learn, perceive, which
would require the SUBJUNCTIVE. L. XXIV. 6.
gebencao hu he spsec wiS
eow. recordamini.
Mk. VIII. 19.
3.After verbs of knowing both the indicative and subjunctive are used, usually
the indicative. See general statement before § 2. a)
Indicative:*) L. XIII. 27. Ne cann ic hwanon ge
synt. Mk. XIV, 68. M. VI. 8. eower fseder wat hwset eow bearf
ys. M. XX. 22.
Gyt nyton hwset gyt
biddab. L. XIII. 25. nat ic hwanon ge
synt. J. IX. 21. we nyton humete he nu
gesyhb. quomodo autem nunc videat, nescimus. QVOMODO AVTEM NVNC, NESCIMVS. J. IX. 25. gif he synful is, bset ic nat. si peccator est, nescio. SI PECCATOR EST, NESCIO. I know not if he is a sinner. gif he synful is, bset ic nat. "Gif he synful is, ᚦaet ic nat." In Oxonian:
"If he sinful is,
that I know not. M. XXVI. 70. Mk. IX. 6. X, 28. XIII, 33, 35. L. IX,
33. XX, 7. XXII, 60. L. XXIII. 34. J. II. 9. III. 8. V. 13. VII.
27, 27, 28. VIII. 14, 14. J. IX. 29. 30. X. 6. XIII. 18. XIV. 5. XV.
15. b)
Indicative and
subjunctive: L. X. 22. nan man nat hwylc IS se
sunu buton se fseder, ne hwylc SI Se fseder buton se sunu. -- In Latin, both times have subjunctive third person singular,
"sit".)
c)
Subjunctive. a. In the protasis of a conditional sentence: J.
VII. 51.Cwyst bu demS ure se senine man buton hyne man ser gehyre and wite
hwset he do? J. XI. 57. pa pharisei hsefdon beboden gif hwa wiste
hwaer he wsere paet he hyt cydde bset hig mihton hine niman. Translating
the Latin subjunctive in 21 instances, the indic. in 9. As a rule, the mood (or mode, as Grice prefers)
of the Latin (or Roman, as Grice prefers) verb does not determine the O. E. (or
A. S., as Grice prefers) usage. In Anglo-Saxon, Oxonian,
and Gricese, "si" seems to be no more than a literal (mimetic)
rendering of Roman "sit," the correct third person singular
subjunctive.
Ms. A. reads
"ys" with'-sy" above. The Lind. gloss reads
"is". M. XXIV. 43. WitaS bset gyf se hiredes ealdor wiste on hwylcere tide se beof
towerd waere witodlice he wolde wacigean. si sciret paterfamilias qua hora fur
venturus esset vigilaret,
(Cf. J. IV, 10. Gif bu wistest — hwaet se is etc. Si scirest quis est. SI SCIREST QVIS EST. /J. In the apodosis of a conditional sentence: J. VII.
17. gyf hwa wyle his willan don he gecwemo (sic. A.B.C. gecnsewS) be
bsere lare hwseber heo si of Gode hwseber be ic he me sylfum
spece. L. VII. 39. Gyf be man witega wsere
witodlice he wiste hwset and hwylc bis wif wsere be his sethrinb bset heo
synful is.
sciret utique quae et
qualis est mulier. SCIRET VTIQVE QVAE ET QVALIS EST MULIER. y. After a hortatory subjunctive. M. VI.
3. Nyte bin wynstre hwset do bin swybre. 4. After verbs of
saying and declaring. a) Here the indicative is used when the
dependent clause contains a statement rather than a question. L. VIII.
39. cyS hu mycel be God gedon h3efS. L. VIII. 47.Da bset wif
geseah bset hit him nses dyrne heo com forht and astrehte hig to his fotum and
geswutulude beforan eallum folce for hwylcum binge heo hit sethran and hu heo
wearS sona hal. ob quam causam tetigerit eum, indicavit; et quemadmodum
confestim SANATA SIT. Further examples of the indicative are. L. XX.
2.*) Sege us on hwylcum anwalde wyrcst bu Sas
bing oSSe hwset ys se Se be bisne anwald sealde. L. VI. 47. iElc bara be to me cymb and mine sprseca
gehyi*S and pa deb, ic him setywe hwam he gelic is. b) When the subordinate clause refers to the future
both the indicative and subjunctive are used: *) Direct
question, as the order of the words shows. Mk. XIII. 4. Sege us hwsenne bas bing gewurdon (A. geweorSon,
H. gewurSen, R. gewurdon) and hwylc tacen bid
bsenne ealle bas Sing onginnaS beon geendud. (Transition to direct
question.) Dic nobis, quando ista fient? DIC NOBIS, QVANDO ISTA FIENT? et quod signum erit? ET QVOD SIGNVM
ERIT? M. XXIV. 3. Sege us hwsenne bas Sing
gewurbun and hwile tacn si bines to-cymes. J. XVIII. 32. he geswutelode hwylcon deaSe lie swulte. qua
morte ESSET moriturus. c) When the question presents a distinct alternative, so that the
idea of doubt and uncertainty is prominent, the subjunctive in Gricese,
Oxonian, and Anglo-Saxon, qua conjugated version, is used: M. XXVI.
63. Ic halsige be Surh bone lyfiendan God, b*t Su secge us gyf \>u sy
Crist Godes sunu. L. XXII. 67. J. X. 24. d) The following is
hortatory as well as declarative: L. XII. 5. Ic eow setywe
hwsene ge ondredon. Ostendam autem vobis, quem TIMEATIS. 5. In
three indirect questions which in the original are direct, the subjunctive is
used: M. XXIV. 45.Wens (sic. A. H. & R. wenst) \>u
hwa sy getrywe and gleaw BEOW? Quis, putas, EST fidelis
servus? QVIS, PVTAS, EST FIDELIS SERVS. M. XXVI. 25. Cwyst
bu lareow hwseSer ic hyt si? Numquid ego sum? NVMQVID EGO SVM, J. VII. 26. CweSe we hwseber ba ealdras
ongyton ^set bis IS Crist?
Numquid vere cognoverunt
principes, quia hie EST Christus? § 11. RELATIVE CLAUSES. Except
in the relations discussed in the following the indicative is used in relative
clauses. Grice:
"The verb 'to be' is actually composed of three different stems -- not
only in Aristotle, but in Gricese." CONIUGATVM, persona, s-stem
(cognate with Roman "sit"), b-stem, w-stem (cognate with Roman,
"ero") MODVS INFINITVUM, the verb "sīn,” the verb
"bion,” the verb "wesan.” MODVS INDICATIVM PRAESENS prima singularis:
"ik" -- Oxonian "I" "em" Oxonian, "am."
Bium wisu secunda singularis: "thū" -- Oxonian: "thou"
"art" Oxonian "art" bis(t) wisis tertia singularis:
"hē" Oxonian, 'he' "ist" (Cognate with Roman
"est") Oxonian 'is' *bid wis(id) prima, secunda, tertia, pluralis "sindun"
*biod wesad MODVS INDCATIVVM PRAETERITVM prima singularis "was"
Oxonian: "was." seconda singularis ""wāri"
Oxonian "were" tertia singularis "was" Oxonian
"was" prima, secunda, tertia, pluralis "wārun" Oxonian
"were" MODVS SVBIVCTIVVM PRAESENS prima, secunda, tertia,
singularis "sīe" (Lost in Oxonian after Occam) "wese"
(cognate with "was", and Roman, "erat") prima, secunda,
tertia, pluralis "sīen" wesen MODVS SVBIVNCTIVVM
PRAETERITUM prima, secunda, tertia, singularis wāri prima, secunda,
tertia, pluralis wārin MODVS IMPERATIVUM singularis "wis,"
"wes" (Cognate with "was" and Roman "erat")
pluralis wesad MODVS PARTICIPIVM PRAESENT wesandi (cognate with Cicero's
"essens" and "essentia" MODVS PARTICIPIVM PRAETERITVM "giwesan"
The present-tense forms of 'be' with the w-stem, "wesan" are
almost never used. Therefore, wesan is used as IMPERATIVE,
in the past tense, and in the participium prasesens versions of
"sīn" -- Grice: "I rue the day when the Bosworth and
Toller left Austin!" -- "Now the OED, is not supposed to include
Anglo-Saxon forms!") and does not have a separate meaning. The b-stem
is only met in the present indicative of wesan, and only for the first and
second persons in the singular. So we see that if Roman had the
'est-sit" distinction, the Oxonians had "The
'ist'/"sīe"/"wese" tryad). Grice:
"To simplify the Oxonian forms and make them correlative to Roman, I shall
reduce the Oxonian triad, 'ist'/'sīe'/"wese" to the division
actually cognate with Roman: 'ist'/'sīe." And so, I
shall speak of the 'ist'/'sīe" distinction, or the 'est-sit'
distinction interchangeably." Today
many deny the distinction or confine attention just to modal operators. Modal
operators in non-assertoric propositions are said to produce referential
opacity or oblique contexts in which truth is not preserved under substitution
of extensionally equivalent expressions. Modal and deontic logics provide
formal analyses of various modalities. Intensional logics investigate the logic
of oblique contexts. Modal logicians have produced possible worlds semantics
interpretations wherein propositions MP with modal operator M are true provided
P is true in all suitable (e.g., logically possible, causally possible, morally
permissible, rationally acceptable) possible worlds. Modal realism grants
ontological status to possible worlds other than the actual world or otherwise
commits to objective modalities in nature or reality. modus: the study of the
logic of the operators ‘it is possible that’ (or, as Grice prefers, “it may be
that”) and ‘it is necessary that’ (or as Grice prefers, “It must be that…”). For
some reason, Grice used ‘mode’ at Oxford – but ‘manner’ in the New World! The
sad thing is that when he came back to the Old World, to the puzzlmenet of
Old-Worlders, he kept using ‘manner.’ So, everytime we see Grice using
‘manner,’ we need to translate to either the traditional Oxonian ‘modus,’ or the
Gricese ‘mode.’ These operators Grice symbolizes by a diamond and a square
respectively. and each can be defined in terms of the other. □p (necessarily p) is equivalent to ¬◇¬p ("not possible that not-p") ◇p (possibly p) is equivalent to ¬□¬p ("not necessarily
not-p").
To say that Fido may be shaggy is to say that it is not necessarily false. Thus
possP could be regarded as an abbreviation of -Nec-p Equally, to say that Fido
*must* be shaggy is to deny that its negation is possible. Thus Af could be regarded
as an abbreviation of -B-f. Grice prefers to take ‘poss” as primitive (“for
surely, it may rain before it must pour!”). Grice’s ystem G of modality is
obtained by introducing Poss. and Nec. If system, as Grice’s is, is
classical/intuitionist/minimal, so is the corresponding modal logic. Grice
surely concentrates on the classical case (“Dummett is overconcentraating on
the intuitionist, and nobody at Oxford was, is, or will be minimal!”). As with any kind of logic, there are three
components to a system of modal logic: a syntactics, which determines the system
or calculus + and the notion of well-formed formula (wff). Second, a semantics,
which determines the consequence relation X on +-wffs. Third, a pragmatics or
sub-system of inference, which determines the deductive consequence relation Y
on +-wffs. The syntactis of the modal operators is the same in every system.
Briefly, the modal operator is a one-place or unary ‘connective,’ or operator,
strictly, since it does not connect two atoms into a molecule, like negation.
There are many different systems of modal logic, some of which can be generated
by different ways of setting up the semantics. Each of the familiar ways of
doing this can be associated with a sound and complete system of inference.
Alternatively, a system of inference can be laid down first and we can search
for a semantics for it relative to which it is sound and complete. Grice gives
primacy to the syntactic viewpoint. Semantic consequence is defined in modal
logic in the usual classical way: a set of sentences 9 yields a sentence s, 9 X
s, iff if no “interpretation” (to use Grice’s jargon in “Vacuous Names”) I
makes all members of 9 true and s false. The question is how to extend the
notion of “interpretation” to accommodate for “may be shaggy” – and “must be
shaggy”. In classical sentential logic, an interpretation is an assignment to
each sentence letter of exactly one of the two truth-values = and where n % m !
1. So to determine relative possibility in a model, we identify R with a
collection of pairs of the form where each of u and v is in W. If a pair is in
R, v is possible relative to u, and if is not in R, v is impossible relative to
u. The relative possibility relation then enters into the rules for the
evaluating modal operator. We do not want to say, e. g. that at the actual
world, it is possible for Grice to originate from a different sperm and egg,
since the only worlds where this takes place are impossible relative to the
actual world. So we have the rule that B f is true at a world u if f is true at
some world v such that v is possible relative to u. Similarly, Af is true at a
world u if f is true at every world v which is possible relative to u. R may
have simple first-order properties such as reflexivity, (Ex)Rxx, symmetry,
(Ex)(Ey)(Rxy P Ryx), and transitivity, (Ex)(Ey)(Ez)((Rxy & Ryz) P Rxz), and
different modal systems can be obtained by imposing different combinations of
these on R (other systems can be obtained from higher-order constraints). The
least constrained system is the system Ghp, in which no structural properties
are put on R. In G-hp we have B (B & C) X B B, since if B (B & C) holds
at w* then (B & C) holds at some world w possible relative to w*, and thus
by the truth-function for &, B holds at w as well, so B B holds at w*.
Hence any interpretation that makes B (B & C) true (% true at w*) also
makes B B true. Since there are no restrictions on R in G-hp, we can expect B
(B & C) X B B in every system of modal logic generated by constraining R. However,
for G-hp we also have C Z B C. For suppose C holds at w*. B C holds at w* only
if there is some world possible relative to w* where C holds. But there need be
no such world. In particular, since R need not be reflexive, w* itself need not
be possible relative to w*. Concomitantly, in any system for which we stipulate
a reflexive R, we will have C X B C. The simplest such system is known as T,
which has the same semantics as K except that R is stipulated to be reflexive
in every interpretation. In other systems, further or different constraints are
put on R. For example, in the system B, each interpretation must have an R that
is reflexive and symmetric, and in the system S4, each interpretation must have
an R that is reflexive and transitive. In B we have B C Z B B C, as can be
shown by an interpretation with nontransitive R, while in S4 we have B AC Z C,
as can be shown by an interpretation with non-symmetric R. Correspondingly, in
S4, B C X B B C, and in B, B AC X C. The system in which R is reflexive,
transitive, and symmetric is called S5, and in this system, R can be omitted.
For if R has all three properties, R is an equivalence relation, i.e., it
partitions W into mutually exclusive and jointly exhaustive equivalence
classes. If Cu is the equivalence class to which u belongs, then the truth-value
of a formula at u is independent of the truth-values of sentence letters at
worlds not in Cu, so only the worlds in Cw* are relevant to the truth-values of
sentences in an S5 interpretation. But within Cw* R is universal: every world
is possible relative to every other. Consequently, in an S5 interpretation, we
need not specify a relative possibility relation, and the evaluation rules for
B and A need not mention relative possibility; e.g., we can say that B f is
true at a world u if there is at least one world v at which f is true. Note
that by the characteristics of R, whenever 9 X s in K, T, B, or S4, then 9 X s
in S5: the other systems are contained in S5. K is contained in all the systems
we have mentioned, while T is contained in B and S4, neither of which is
contained in the other. Sentential modal logics give rise to quantified modal
logics, of which quantified S5 is the bestknown. Just as, in the sentential
case, each world in an interpretation is associated with a valuation of
sentence letters as in non-modal sentential logic, so in quantified modal
logic, each world is associated with a valuation of the sort familiar in
non-modal first-order logic. More specifically, in quantified S5, each world w
is assigned a domain Dw – the things that exist at w – such that at least one
Dw is non-empty, and each atomic n-place predicate of the language is assigned
an extension Extw of n-tuples of objects that satisfy the predicate at w. So
even restricting ourselves to just the one first-order extension of a
sentential system, S5, various degrees of freedom are already evident. We
discuss the following: (a) variability of domains, (b) interpretation of
quantifiers, and (c) predication. (a) Should all worlds have the same domain or
may the domains of different worlds be different? The latter appears to be the
more natural choice; e.g., if neither of of Dw* and Du are subsets of the
other, this represents the intuitive idea that some things that exist might not
have, and that there could have been things that do not actually exist (though
formulating this latter claim requires adding an operator for ‘actually’ to the
language). So we should distinguish two versions of S5, one with constant
domains, S5C, and the other with variable domains, S5V. (b) Should the truth of
(Dn)f at a world w require that f is true at w of some object in Dw or merely
of some object in D (D is the domain of all possible objects, 4weWDw)? The
former treatment is called the actualist reading of the quantifiers, the
latter, the possibilist reading. In S5C there is no real choice, since for any
w, D % Dw, but the issue is live in S5V. (c) Should we require that for any
n-place atomic predicate F, an n-tuple of objects satisfies F at w only if every
member of the n-tuple belongs to Dw, i.e., should we require that atomic
predicates be existence-entailing? If we abbreviate (Dy) (y % x) by Ex (for ‘x
exists’), then in S5C, A(Ex)AEx is logically valid on the actualist reading of
E (%-D-) and on the possibilist. On the former, the formula says that at each
world, anything that exists at that world exists at every world, which is true;
while on the latter, using the definition of ‘Ex’, it says that at each world,
anything that exists at some world or other is such that at every world, it
exists at some world or other, which is also true; indeed, the formula stays
valid in S5C with possibilist quantifiers even if we make E a primitive logical
constant, stipulated to be true at every w of exactly the things that exist at
w. But in S5V with actualist quantifiers, A(Ex)AEx is invalid, as is (Ex)AEx –
consider an interpretation where for some u, Du is a proper subset of Dw*.
However, in S5V with possibilist quantifiers, the status of the formula, if
‘Ex’ is defined, depends on whether identity is existence-entailing. If it is
existenceentailing, then A(Ex)AEx is invalid, since an object in D satisfies
(Dy)(y % x) at w only if that object exists at w, while if identity is not
existence-entailing, the formula is valid. The interaction of the various
options is also evident in the evaluation of two well-known schemata: the
Barcan formula, B (Dx)fx P (Dx) B fx; and its converse, (Dx) B fx P B (Dx)fx.
In S5C with ‘Ex’ either defined or primitive, both schemata are valid, but in
S5V with actualist quantifiers, they both fail. For the latter case, if we
substitute -E for f in the converse Barcan formula we get a conditional whose
antecedent holds at w* if there is u with Du a proper subset of Dw*, but whose
consequent is logically false. The Barcan formula fails when there is a world u
with Du not a subset of Dw*, and the condition f is true of some non-actual
object at u and not of any actual object there. For then B (Dx)f holds at w*
while (Dx) B fx fails there. However, if we require atomic predicates to be
existence-entailing, then instances of the converse Barcan formula with f
atomic are valid. In S5V with possibilist quantifiers, all instances of both
schemata are valid, since the prefixes (Dx) B and B (Dx) correspond to (Dx)
(Dw) and (Dw) (Dx), which are equivalent (with actualist quantifiers, the
prefixes correspond to (Dx 1 Dw*), and (Dw) (Dx 1 Dw) which are non-equivalent
if Dw and Dw* need not be the same set). Finally in S5V with actualist
quantifiers, the standard quantifier introduction and elimination rules must be
adjusted. Suppose c is a name for an object that does not actually exist; then
- Ec is true but (Dx) - Ex is false. The quantifier rules must be those of free
logic: we require Ec & fc before we infer (Dv)fv and Ec P fc, as well as
the usual EI restrictions, before we infer (Ev)fv. Refs.: H. P. Grice:
“Modality: Desirability and Credibility;” H. P. Grice, “The may and the may
not;” H. P. Grice, “The Big Philosophical Mistake: ‘What is actual is not also
possible’.” modus: Grice: “In Roman,
‘modus’ may have been rendered as ‘way’, ‘fashion’ – but I will not, and use
‘modus’ as THEY did! ‘Modus’ is used in more than one ‘modus’ in philosophy. In
Ariskantian logic, ‘modus’ refers either to the arrangement of universal,
particular, affirmative, or negative propositions within a syllogism, only
certain of which are valid this is often tr., confusingly, as ‘modus’ in
English – “the valid modes, such as Barbara and Celarent.” But then ‘modus’ may
be used to to the property a proposition has by virtue of which it is necessary
or contingent, possible or impossible, or ‘actual.’ In Oxonian scholastic
metaphysics, ‘modus’ is often used in a not altogether technical way to mean
that which characterizes a thing and distinguishes it from others. Micraelius,
in his best-selling “Lexicon philosophicum,” has it that “a mode does not
compose a thing, but distinguishes it and makes it determinate.” ‘Modus’ is also
used in the context of the modal distinction in the theory of distinctions to
designate the distinction that holds between a substance and its modes or
between two modes of a single substance. ‘Modus’ also appears in the technical
vocabulary of medieval speculative ‘grammar’ or ‘semantics’ (“speculative
semantics” makes more sense) -- in connection with the notions of the “modus
significandi,” “the modus intelligendi” (more or less the same thing), and the
“modus essendi.” The term ‘modus’ becomes especially important when Descartes (vide
Grice, “Descartes on clear and distinct perception”), Spinoza (vide S. N.
Hampshire, “Spinoza”), and Locke each take it up, giving it three somewhat
different special meanings within their respective systems. Descartes (vide
Grice, “Descartes on clear and distinct perception”) makes ‘modus’ a central
notion in his metaphysics in his Principia philosophiae. For Descartes, each
substantia is characterized by a principal attribute, ‘cogitatio’ for ‘anima’
and ‘extensio’ for ‘corpus’. Modes, then, are particular ways of being extended
or thinking, i.e., particular sizes, shapes, etc., or particular thoughts,
properties in the broad sense that individual things substances have. In this
way, ‘modus’ occupies the role in Descartes’s philosophy that ‘accident’ does
in Aristotelian philosophy. But for Descartes, each mode must be connected with
the principal attribute of a substance, a way of being extended or a way of
thinking, whereas for the Aristotelian, accidents may or may not be connected
with the essence of the substance in which they inhere. Like Descartes, Spinoza
recognizes three basic metaphysical terms, ‘substania,’ ‘attributum’, and
‘modus’. Recalling Descartes, Spinoza defines ‘modus’ as “the affections of a
substance, or that which is in another, and which is also conceived through
another” Ethics I. But for Spinoza, there is only one substance, which has all
possible attributes. This makes it somewhat difficult to determine exactly what
Spinoza means by ‘modus’, whether they are to be construed as being in some say
a “property” of God, the one infinite substance, or whether they are to be
construed more broadly as simply individual things that depend for their
existence on God, just as Cartesian modes depend on Cartesian substance.
Spinoza also introduces somewhat obscure distinctions between modus infinitus
and modus finitus, and between immediate and mediate infinite modes. Now, much
closer to Grice, Englishman and Oxonian Locke uses ‘mode’ in a way that
evidently derives from Descartes’s usage, but that also differs from it. For
Locke, a ‘modus’ is “such complex idea – as Pegasus the flying horse --, which
however compounded, contain not in them the supposition of subsisting by
themselves, but are considered as Dependences on, or Affections of Substances”
Essay II. A ‘modus,’ for Locke, is thus an idea that represents to us the a ‘complex’
propertiy of a thing, sc. an idea derived from what Locke a ‘simple’ idea that
come to us from experience. Locke distinguishes between a ‘modus simplex,’ like
number, space, and infinity, which are supposed to be constructed by
compounding the SAME simple idea many times, and ‘modus complexum,’ or ‘modus
mixtum,’ a mode like obligation or theft, which is supposed to be compounded of
at least two simple ideas of a different sort.
Refs.: Grice applies Locke’s idea of the modus mixtum in his ‘labour’
against Empiricism, cf. H. P. Grice, “I may care a hoot what the dictionary
says, but it is not the case that I care a hoot what Micraelius’s “Lexicon
philosophicum” says.” Modus – modulus -- Grice
against a pragmatic or rational module: from Latin ‘modulus,’ ‘little mode.’ the commitment to functionally independent and
specialized cognitive system in psychological organizatio, or, more generally,
in the organization of any complex system. A ‘modulus’ entails that behavior is
the product of components with subordinate functions, that these functions are
realized in discrete physical systems, and that the subsystems are minimally
interactive. Organization in terms of a modulus varies from simple
decomposability to what Herbert Simon calls near decomposability. In the
former, component systems are independent, operating according to intrinsically
determined principles; system behavior is an additive or aggregative function
of these independent contributions. In the latter, the short-run behavior of
components is independent of the behavior of other components; the system
behavior is a relatively simple function of component contributions. Gall
defends a modular organization for the mind/brain, holding that the cerebral
hemispheres consist of a variety of organs, or centers, each subserving
specific intellectual and moral functions. This picture of the brain as a
collection of relatively independent organs contrasts sharply with the
traditional view that intellectual activity involves the exercise of a general
unitary ‘faculty’ in a variety of this or that‘domain’, where a ‘domain’ is not
a ‘modulus’ -- a view that was common to Descartes and Hume as well as Gall’s
major opponents such as Flourens. By the middle of the nineteenth century,
Bouillaud and Broca (a French doctor, of Occitan ancestry – brooch, broca –
thorn --) defended the view that language is controlled by localized structures
in the left hemisphere and is relatively independent of other cognitive
activities. It was later discovered by Wernicke that there are at least two
centers for the control of language, one more posterior and one more anterior.
On these views, there are discrete physical structures responsible for communication,
which are largely independent of one another and of structures responsible for
other psychological functions. This is therefore a modular organization. This
view of the neurophysiological organization of communication continues to have
advocates, though the precise characterization of the functions these two
centers serve is controversial. Many more recent views have tended to limit
modularity to more peripheral functions such as vision, hearing, and motor
control and speech, but have excluded “what I am interested in, viz. so-called
higher cognitive processes.” – H. P. Grice, “The power structure of the soul.” Modus -- modus ponendo ponens: 1 the argument
form ‘If A then B; A; therefore, B’, and arguments of this form compare fallacy
of affirming the consequent; 2 the rule of inference that permits one to infer
the consequent of a conditional from that conditional and its antecedent. This
is also known as the rule of /-elimination or rule of /- detachment. modus tollendo tollens: 1 the argument form
‘If A then B; not-B; therefore, not-A’, and arguments of this form compare
fallacy of denying the antecedent; 2 the rule of inference that permits one to
infer the negation of the antecedent of a conditional from that conditional and
the negation of its consequent.
molyneux question: also called Molyneux’s
problem, the question that, in correspondence with Locke, William Molyneux or
Molineux, 1656 98, a Dublin lawyer and member of the Irish Parliament, posed
and Locke inserted in the second edition of his Essay Concerning Human
Understanding 1694; book 2, chap. 9, section 8: Suppose a Man born blind, and
now adult, and taught by his touch to distinguish a Cube, and a Sphere of the
same metal, and nighly of the same bigness, so as to tell, when he felt one and
t’other, which is the Cube, which the Sphere. Suppose then the Cube and Sphere
placed on a Table, and the Blind Man to be made to see. Quære, Whether by his
sight, before he touch’d them, he could now distinguish, and tell, which is the
Globe, which the Cube. Although it is tempting to regard Molyneux’s question as
straightforwardly empirical, attempts to gauge the abilities of newly sighted
adults have yielded disappointing and ambiguous results. More interesting,
perhaps, is the way in which different theories of perception answer the
question. Thus, according to Locke, sensory modalities constitute discrete
perceptual channels, the contents of which perceivers must learn to correlate.
Such a theory answers the question in the negative as did Molyneux himself.
Other theories encourage different responses.
mondolfo: essential Italian philosopher. Like
Grice, Mondolfo believed seriously in the longitudinal unity of philosophy and
made original research on the historiography of philosophy, especially during
the Eleatic, Agrigento, and later Roman periods. Refs.: Luigi Speranza,
"Grice, Mondolfo, e la filosofia greco-romana," per il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
Monte: essential Italian
philosopher. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice e del Monte," per Il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
Montanism, a charismatic, schismatic
movement in early Christianity, originating in Phrygia in the late second
century. It rebuked the mainstream church for laxity and apathy, and taught
moral purity, new, i.e. postbiblical, revelation, and the imminent end of the
world. Traditional accounts, deriving from critics of the movement, contain
exaggerations and probably some fabrications. Montanus himself, abetted by the
prophetesses Maximilla and Prisca, announced in ecstatic speech a new, final
age of prophecy. This fulfilled the biblical promises that in the last days the
Holy Spirit would be poured out universally Joel 2: 28ff.; Acts 2: 16ff. and
would teach “the whole truth” Jon. 14:26; 16:13. It also empowered the
Montanists to enjoin more rigorous discipline than that required by Jesus. The
sect denied that forgiveness through baptism covered serious subsequent sin;
forbade remarriage for widows and widowers; practiced fasting; and condemned believers
who evaded persecution. Some later followers may have identified Montanus with
the Holy Spirit itself, though he claimed only to be the Spirit’s mouthpiece.
The “new prophecy” flourished for a generation, especially in North Africa,
gaining a famous convert in Tertullian. But the church’s bishops repudiated the
movement’s criticisms and innovations, and turned more resolutely against
postapostolic revelation, apocalyptic expectation, and ascetic extremes.
mooreism: g. e. – and his paradox: cited by H. P. Grice. Irish
London-born philosopher who spearheaded the attack on idealism and was a major
supporter of realism in all its forms: metaphysical, epistemological, and
axiological. He was born in Upper Norwood, a suburb of London; did his undergraduate
work at Cambridge ; spent 84 as a fellow of Trinity ; returned to Cambridge in
1 as a lecturer; and was granted a professorship there in 5. He also served as
editor of Mind. The bulk of his work falls into four categories: metaphysics,
epistemology, ethics, and philosophical methodology. Metaphysics. In this area,
Moore is mainly known for his attempted refutation of idealism and his defense
thereby of realism. In his “The Refutation of Idealism” 3, he argued that there
is a crucial premise that is essential to all possible arguments for the
idealistic conclusion that “All reality is mental spiritual.” This premise is:
“To be is to be perceived” in the broad sense of ‘perceive’. Moore argued that,
under every possible interpretation of it, that premise is either a tautology
or false; hence no significant conclusion can ever be inferred from it. His
positive defense of realism had several prongs. One was to show that there are
certain claims held by non-realist philosophers, both idealist ones and skeptical
ones. Moore argued, in “A Defense of Common Sense” 5, that these claims are
either factually false or self-contradictory, or that in some cases there is no
good reason to believe them. Among the claims that Moore attacked are these:
“Propositions about purported material facts are false”; “No one has ever known
any such propositions to be true”; “Every purported physical fact is logically
dependent on some mental fact”; and “Every physical fact is causally dependent
on some mental fact.” Another major prong of Moore’s defense of realism was to
argue for the existence of an external world and later to give a “Proof of an
External World” 3. Epistemology. Most of Moore’s work in this area dealt with
the various kinds of knowledge we have, why they must be distinguished, and the
problem of perception and our knowledge of an external world. Because he had
already argued for the existence of an external world in his metaphysics, he
here focused on how we know it. In many papers and chapters e.g., “The Nature
and Reality of Objects of Perception,” 6 he examined and at times supported
three main positions: naive or direct realism, representative or indirect
realism, and phenomenalism. Although he seemed to favor direct realism at
first, in the majority of his papers he found representative realism to be the
most supportable position despite its problems. It should also be noted that,
in connection with his leanings mood toward representative realism, Moore
maintained the existence of sense-data and argued at length for an account of
just how they are related to physical objects. That there are sense-data Moore
never doubted. The question was, What is their ontological status? With regard
to the various kinds of knowledge or ways of knowing, Moore made a distinction between
dispositional or non-actualized and actualized knowledge. Within the latter
Moore made distinctions between direct apprehension often known as knowledge by
acquaintance, indirect apprehension, and knowledge proper or propositional
knowledge. He devoted much of his work to finding the conditions for knowledge
proper. Ethics. In his major work in ethics, Principia Ethica 3, Moore
maintained that the central problem of ethics is, What is good? meaning by this, not what things are good,
but how ‘good’ is to be defined. He argued that there can be only one answer,
one that may seem disappointing, namely: good is good, or, alternatively,
‘good’ is indefinable. Thus ‘good’ denotes a “unique, simple object of thought”
that is indefinable and unanalyzable. His first argument on behalf of that
claim consisted in showing that to identify good with some other object i.e.,
to define ‘good’ is to commit the naturalistic fallacy. To commit this fallacy
is to reduce ethical propositions to either psychological propositions or
reportive definitions as to how people use words. In other words, what was
meant to be an ethical proposition, that X is good, becomes a factual
proposition about people’s desires or their usage of words. Moore’s second
argument ran like this: Suppose ‘good’ were definable. Then the result would be
even worse than that of reducing ethical propositions to non-ethical
propositions ethical propositions would
be tautologies! For example, suppose you defined ‘good’ as ‘pleasure’. Then
suppose you maintained that pleasure is good. All you would be asserting is
that pleasure is pleasure, a tautology. To avoid this conclusion ‘good’ must
mean something other than ‘pleasure’. Why is this the naturalistic fallacy?
Because good is a non-natural property. But even if it were a natural one,
there would still be a fallacy. Hence some have proposed calling it the
definist fallacy the fallacy of
attempting to define ‘good’ by any means. This argument is often known as the
open question argument because whatever purported definition of ‘good’ anyone
offers, it would always be an open question whether whatever satisfies the
definition really is good. In the last part of Principia Ethica Moore turned to
a discussion of what sorts of things are the greatest goods with which we are
acquainted. He argued for the view that they are personal affection and
aesthetic enjoyments. Philosophical methodology. Moore’s methodology in
philosophy had many components, but two stand out: his appeal to and defense of
common sense and his utilization of various methods of philosophical/conceptual
analysis. “A Defense of Common Sense” argued for his claim that the commonsense
view of the world is wholly true, and for the claim that any view which opposed
that view is either factually false or self-contradictory. Throughout his
writings Moore distinguished several kinds of analysis and made use of them
extensively in dealing with philosophical problems. All of these may be found
in the works cited above and other essays gathered into Moore’s Philosophical
Studies2 and Philosophical Papers 9. These have been referred to as
refutational analysis, with two subforms, showing contradictions and
“translation into the concrete”; distinctional analysis; decompositional
analysis either definitional or divisional; and reductional analysis. Moore was
greatly revered as a teacher. Many of his students and colleagues have paid
high tribute to him in very warm and grateful terms. Moore’s paradox, as first discussed by G. E.
Moore, the perplexity involving assertion of what is expressed by conjunctions
such as ‘It’s raining, but I believe it isn’t’ and ‘It’s raining, but I don’t
believe it is’. The oddity of such presenttense first-person uses of ‘to
believe’ seems peculiar to those conjunctions just because it is assumed both
that, when asserting roughly,
representing as true a conjunction, one
also asserts its conjuncts, and that, as a rule, the assertor believes the
asserted proposition. Thus, no perplexity arises from assertions of, for
instance, ‘It’s raining today, but I falsely believed it wasn’t until I came
out to the porch’ and ‘If it’s raining but I believe it isn’t, I have been
misled by the weather report’. However, there are reasons to think that, if we
rely only on these assumptions and examples, our characterization of the
problem is unduly narrow. First, assertion seems relevant only because we are
interested in what the assertor believes. Secondly, those conjunctions are
disturbing only insofar as they show that Moore’s paradox Moore’s paradox
583 583 some of the assertor’s
beliefs, though contingent, can only be irrationally held. Thirdly,
autobiographical reports that may justifiably be used to charge the reporter
with irrationality need be neither about his belief system, nor conjunctive,
nor true e.g., ‘I don’t exist’, ‘I have no beliefs’, nor false e.g., ‘It’s
raining, but I have no evidence that it is’. So, Moore’s paradox is best seen
as the problem posed by contingent propositions that cannot be justifiably
believed. Arguably, in forming a belief of those propositions, the believer
acquires non-overridable evidence against believing them. A successful analysis
of the problem along these lines may have important epistemological
consequences. Refs.: Grice, “Oxford
seminars.” Grice dedicated a full chapter to the Moore paradox. Mainly, Moore
is confused in lexicological ways. An emisor EXPRESSES the belief that p. What
the emisor communicates is that p, not that he believes that p. He does not
convey explicitly that he believes that p, nor implicitly. Belief and its
expression is linked conceptually with the mode – indicative (‘est’); as is
desire and its expression with the imperative mode (“sit”).
mos,
ethos: ethos:
Grice: “I love Lorenz, and he loved his geese.” -- Grice: “In German, ‘deutsche’ means
‘tribal.’” -- philosophical ethology – phrase used by Grice for his creature
construction routine. ethical constructivism, a form of anti-realism about
ethics which holds that there are moral facts and truths, but insists that these
facts and truths are in some way constituted by or dependent on our moral
beliefs, reactions, or attitudes. For instance, an ideal observer theory that
represents the moral rightness and wrongness of an act in terms of the moral
approval and disapproval that an appraiser would have under suitably idealized
conditions can be understood as a form of ethical constructivism. Another form
of constructivism identifies the truth of a moral belief with its being part of
the appropriate system of beliefs, e.g., of a system of moral and nonmoral
beliefs that is internally coherent. Such a view would maintain a coherence
theory of moral truth. Moral relativism is a constructivist view that allows
for a plurality of moral facts and truths. Thus, if the idealizing conditions
appealed to in an ideal observer theory allow that different appraisers can
have different reactions to the same actions under ideal conditions, then that
ideal observer theory will be a version of moral relativism as well as of
ethical constructivism. Or, if different systems of moral beliefs satisfy the
appropriate epistemic conditions e.g. are equally coherent, then the truth or
falsity of particular moral beliefs will have to be relativized to different
moral systems or codes. -- ethical objectivism, the view that the objects of
the most basic concepts of ethics which may be supposed to be values,
obligations, duties, oughts, rights, or what not exist, or that facts about
them hold, objectively and that similarly worded ethical statements by different
persons make the same factual claims and thus do not concern merely the
speaker’s feelings. To say that a fact is objective, or that something has
objective existence, is usually to say that its holding or existence is not
derivative from its being thought to hold or exist. In the Scholastic
terminology still current in the seventeenth century ‘objective’ had the more
or less contrary meaning of having status only as an object of thought. In
contrast, fact, or a thing’s existence, is subjective if it holds or exists
only in the sense that it is thought to hold or exist, or that it is merely a
convenient human posit for practical purposes. A fact holds, or an object
exists, intersubjectively if somehow its acknowledgment is binding on all
thinking subjects or all subjects in some specified group, although it does not
hold or exist independently of their thinking about it. Some thinkers suppose
that intersubjectivity is all that can ever properly be meant by objectivity.
Objectivism may be naturalist or non-naturalist. The naturalist objectivist
believes that values, duties, or whatever are natural phenomena detectable by
introspection, perception, or scientific inference. Thus values may be
identified with certain empirical qualities of anybody’s experience, or duties
with empirical facts about the effects of action, e.g. as promoting or
hindering social cohesion. The non-naturalist objectivist eschewing what Moore
called the naturalistic fallacy believes that values or obligations or whatever
items he thinks most basic in ethics exist independently of any belief about
them, but that their existence is not a matter of any ordinary fact detectable
in the above ways but can be revealed to ethical intuition as standing in a
necessary but not analytic relation to natural phenomena. ‘Ethical
subjectivism’ usually means the doctrine that ethical statements are simply
reports on the speaker’s feelings though, confusingly enough, such statements
may be objectively true or false. Perhaps it ought to mean the doctrine that
nothing is good or bad but thinking makes it so. Attitude theories of morality,
for which such statements express, rather than report upon, the speaker’s
feelings, are also, despite the objections of their proponents, sometimes
called subjectivist. In a more popular usage an objective matter of fact is one
on which all reasonable persons can be expected to agree, while a matter is
subjective if various alternative opinions can be accepted as reasonable. What
is subjective in this sense may be quite objective in the more philosophical
sense in question above. -- ethics, the
philosophical study of morality. The word is also commonly used interchangeably
with ‘morality’ to mean the subject matter of this study; and sometimes it is
used more narrowly to mean the moral principles of a particular tradition,
group, or individual. Christian ethics and Albert Schweitzer’s ethics are
examples. In this article the word will be used exclusively to mean the
philosophical study. Ethics, along with logic, metaphysics, and epistemology,
is one of the main branches of philosophy. It corresponds, in the traditional
division of the field into formal, natural, and moral philosophy, to the last
of these disciplines. It can in turn be divided into the general study of goodness,
the general study of right action, applied ethics, metaethics, moral
psychology, and the metaphysics of moral responsibility. These divisions are
not sharp, and many important studies in ethics, particularly those that
examine or develop whole systems of ethics, are interdivisional. Nonetheless,
they facilitate the identification of different problems, movements, and
schools within the discipline. The first two, the general study of goodness and
the general study of right action, constitute the main business of ethics.
Correlatively, its principal substantive questions are what ends we ought, as
fully rational human beings, to choose and pursue and what moral principles
should govern our choices and pursuits. How these questions are related is the
discipline’s principal structural question, and structural differences among
systems of ethics reflect different answers to this question. In contemporary
ethics, the study of structure has come increasingly to the fore, especially as
a preliminary to the general study of right action. In the natural order of
exposition, however, the substantive questions come first. Goodness and the
question of ends. Philosophers have typically treated the question of the ends
we ought to pursue in one of two ways: either as a question about the
components of a good life or as a question about what sorts of things are good
in themselves. On the first way of treating the question, it is assumed that we
naturally seek a good life; hence, determining its components amounts to determining,
relative to our desire for such a life, what ends we ought to pursue. On the
second way, no such assumption about human nature is made; rather it is assumed
that whatever is good in itself is worth choosing or pursuing. The first way of
treating the question leads directly to the theory of human well-being. The
second way leads directly to the theory of intrinsic value. The first theory
originated in ancient ethics, and eudaimonia was the Grecian word for its
subject, a word usually tr. ‘happiness,’ but sometimes tr. ‘flourishing’ in
order to make the question of human well-being seem more a matter of how well a
person is doing than how good he is feeling. These alternatives reflect the
different conceptions of human well-being that inform the two major views
within the theory: the view that feeling good or pleasure is the essence of
human well-being and the view that doing well or excelling at things worth
doing is its essence. The first view is hedonism in its classical form. Its
most famous exponent among the ancients was Epicurus. The second view is
perfectionism, a view that is common to several schools of ancient ethics. Its
adherents include Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics. Among the moderns, the
best-known defenders of classical hedonism and perfectionism are respectively
J. S. Mill and Nietzsche. Although these two views differ on the question of
what human well-being essentially consists in, neither thereby denies that the
other’s answer has a place in a good human life. Indeed, mature statements of
each typically assign the other’s answer an ancillary place. Thus, hedonism, as
expounded by Epicurus, takes excelling at things worth doing exercising one’s intellectual powers and
moral virtues in exemplary and fruitful ways, e.g. as the tried and true means to experiencing
life’s most satisfying pleasures. And perfectionism, as developed in
Aristotle’s ethics, underscores the importance of pleasure the deep satisfaction that comes from doing
an important job well, e.g. as a natural
concomitant of achieving excellence in things that matter. The two views, as
expressed in these mature statements, differ not so much in the kinds of
activities they take to be central to a good life as in the ways they explain
the goodness of such a life. The chief difference between them, then, is
philosophical rather than prescriptive. The second theory, the theory of
intrinsic value, also has roots in ancient ethics, specifically, Plato’s theory
of Forms. But unlike Plato’s theory, the basic tenets of which include certain
doctrines about the reality and transcendence of value, the theory of intrinsic
value neither contains nor presupposes any metaphysical theses. At issue in the
theory is what things are good in themselves, and one can take a position on
this issue without committing oneself to any thesis about the reality or
unreality of goodness or about its transcendence or immanence. A list of the
different things philosophers have considered good in themselves would include
life, happiness, pleasure, knowledge, virtue, friendship, beauty, and harmony.
The list could easily be extended. An interest in what constitutes the goodness
of the various items on the list has brought philosophers to focus primarily on
the question of whether something unites them. The opposing views on this
question are monism and pluralism. Monists affirm the list’s unity; pluralists
deny it. Plato, for instance, was a monist. He held that the goodness of
everything good in itself consisted in harmony and therefore each such thing
owed its goodness to its being harmonious. Alternatively, some philosophers
have proposed pleasure as the sole constituent of goodness. Indeed, conceiving
of pleasure as a particular kind of experience or state of consciousness, they
have proposed this kind of experience as the only thing good in itself and
characterized all other good things as instrumentally good, as owing their
goodness to their being sources of pleasure. Thus, hedonism too can be a
species of monism. In this case, though, one must distinguish between the view
that it is one’s own experiences of pleasure that are intrinsically good and
the view that anyone’s experiences of pleasure, indeed, any sentient being’s
experiences of pleasure, are intrinsically good. The former is called by
Sidgwick egoistic hedonism, the latter universal hedonism. This distinction can
be made general, as a distinction between egoistic and universal views of what
is good in itself or, as philosophers now commonly say, between agent-relative
and agent-neutral value. As such, it indicates a significant point of
disagreement in the theory of intrinsic value, a disagreement in which the
seeming arbitrariness and blindness of egoism make it harder to defend. In
drawing this conclusion, however, one must be careful not to mistake these
egoistic views for views in the theory of human well-being, for each set of
views represents a set of alternative answers to a different question. One must
be careful, in other words, not to infer from the greater defensibility of
universalism vis-à-vis egoism that universalism is the predominant view in the
general study of goodness. Right action. The general study of right action
concerns the principles of right and wrong that govern our choices and
pursuits. In modern ethics these principles are typically given a jural
conception. Accordingly, they are understood to constitute a moral code that
defines the duties of men and women who live together in fellowship. This
conception of moral principles is chiefly due to the influence of Christianity
in the West, though some of its elements were already present in Stoic ethics.
Its ascendancy in the general study of right action puts the theory of duty at
the center of that study. The theory has two parts: the systematic exposition
of the moral code that defines our duties; and its justification. The first
part, when fully developed, presents complete formulations of the fundamental
principles of right and wrong and shows how they yield all moral duties. The
standard model is an axiomatic system in mathematics, though some philosophers
have proposed a technical system of an applied science, such as medicine or
strategy, as an alternative. The second part, if successful, establishes the
authority of the principles and so validates the code. Various methods and
criteria of justification are commonly used; no single one is canonical.
Success in establishing the principles’ authority depends on the soundness of
the argument that proceeds from whatever method or criterion is used. One
traditional criterion is implicit in the idea of an axiomatic system. On this
criterion, the fundamental principles of right and wrong are authoritative in
virtue of being self-evident truths. That is, they are regarded as comparable
to axioms not only in being the first principles of a deductive system but also
in being principles whose truth can be seen immediately upon reflection. Use of
this criterion to establish the principles’ authority is the hallmark of
intuitionism. Once one of the dominant views in ethics, its position in the
discipline has now been seriously eroded by a strong, twentieth-century tide of
skepticism about all claims of self-evidence. Currently, the most influential
method of justification consistent with using the model of an axiomatic system
to expound the morality of right and wrong draws on the jural conception of its
principles. On this method, the principles are interpreted as expressions of a
legislative will, and accordingly their authority derives from the sovereignty
of the person or collective whose will they are taken to express. The oldest
example of the method’s use is the divine command theory. On this theory, moral
principles are taken to be laws issued by God to humanity, and their authority
thus derives from God’s supremacy. The theory is the original Christian source
of the principles’ jural conception. The rise of secular thought since the
Enlightenment has, however, limited its appeal. Later examples, which continue
to attract broad interest and discussion, are formalism and contractarianism.
Formalism is best exemplified in Kant’s ethics. It takes a moral principle to
be a precept that satisfies the formal criteria of a universal law, and it
takes formal criteria to be the marks of pure reason. Consequently, moral
principles are laws that issue from reason. As Kant puts it, they are laws that
we, as rational beings, give to ourselves and that regulate our conduct insofar
as we engage each other’s rational nature. They are laws for a republic of
reason or, as Kant says, a kingdom of ends whose legislature comprises all
rational beings. Through this ideal, Kant makes intelligible and forceful the
otherwise obscure notion that moral principles derive their authority from the
sovereignty of reason. Contractarianism also draws inspiration from Kant’s
ethics as well as from the social contract theories of Locke and Rousseau. Its
fullest and most influential statement appears in the work of Rawls. On this
view, moral principles represent the ideal terms of social cooperation for
people who live together in fellowship and regard each other as equals.
Specifically, they are taken to be the conditions of an ideal agreement among
such people, an agreement that they would adopt if they met as an assembly of
equals to decide collectively on the social arrangements governing their
relations and reached their decision as a result of open debate and rational
deliberation. The authority of moral principles derives, then, from the
fairness of the procedures by which the terms of social cooperation would be
arrived at in this hypothetical constitutional convention and the assumption
that any rational individual who wanted to live peaceably with others and who
imagined himself a party to this convention would, in view of the fairness of
its procedures, assent to its results. It derives, that is, from the
hypothetical consent of the governed. Philosophers who think of a moral code on
the model of a technical system of an applied science use an entirely different
method of justification. In their view, just as the principles of medicine
represent knowledge about how best to promote health, so the principles of
right and wrong represent knowledge about how best to promote the ends of
morality. These philosophers, then, have a teleological conception of the code.
Our fundamental duty is to promote certain ends, and the principles of right
and wrong organize and direct our efforts in this regard. What justifies the
principles, on this view, is that the ends they serve are the right ones to
promote and the actions they prescribe are the best ways to promote them. The
principles are authoritative, in other words, in virtue of the wisdom of their
prescriptions. Different teleological views in the theory of duty correspond to
different answers to the question of what the right ends to promote are. The
most common answer is happiness; and the main division among the corresponding
views mirrors the distinction in the theory of intrinsic value between egoism
and universalism. Thus, egoism and universalism in the theory of duty hold,
respectively, that the fundamental duty of morality is to promote, as best as
one can, one’s own happiness and that it is to promote, as best as one can, the
happiness of humanity. The former is ethical egoism and is based on the ideal
of rational self-love. The latter is utilitarianism and is based on the ideal
of rational benevolence. Ethical egoism’s most famous exponents in modern
philosophy are Hobbes and Spinoza. It has had few distinguished defenders since
their time. Bentham and J. S. Mill head the list of distinguished defenders of
utilitarianism. The view continues to be enormously influential. On these
teleological views, answers to questions about the ends we ought to pursue
determine the principles of right and wrong. Put differently, the general study
of right action, on these views, is subordinate to the general study of
goodness. This is one of the two leading answers to the structural question
about how the two studies are related. The other is that the general study of
right action is to some extent independent of the general study of goodness. On
views that represent this answer, some principles of right and wrong, notably
principles of justice and honesty, prescribe actions even though more evil than
good would result from doing them. These views are deontological. Fiat justitia
ruat coelum captures their spirit. The opposition between teleology and
deontology in ethics underlies many of the disputes in the general study of
right action. The principal substantive and structural questions of ethics
arise not only with respect to the conduct of human life generally but also
with respect to specific walks of life such as medicine, law, journalism,
engineering, and business. The examination of these questions in relation to
the common practices and traditional codes of such professions and occupations
has resulted in the special studies of applied ethics. In these studies, ideas
and theories from the general studies of goodness and right action are applied
to particular circumstances and problems of some profession or occupation, and
standard philosophical techniques are used to define, clarify, and organize the
ethical issues found in its domain. In medicine, in particular, where rapid
advances in technology create, overnight, novel ethical problems on matters of
life and death, the study of biomedical ethics has generated substantial
interest among practitioners and scholars alike. Metaethics. To a large extent,
the general studies of goodness and right action and the special studies of
applied ethics consist in systematizing, deepening, and revising our beliefs
about how we ought to conduct our lives. At the same time, it is characteristic
of philosophers, when reflecting on such systems of belief, to examine the
nature and grounds of these beliefs. These questions, when asked about ethical
beliefs, define the field of metaethics. The relation of this field to the
other studies is commonly represented by taking the other studies to constitute
the field of ethics proper and then taking metaethics to be the study of the
concepts, methods of justification, and ontological assumptions of the field of
ethics proper. Accordingly, metaethics can proceed from either an interest in
the epistemology of ethics or an interest in its metaphysics. On the first approach,
the study focuses on questions about the character of ethical knowledge.
Typically, it concentrates on the simplest ethical beliefs, such as ‘Stealing
is wrong’ and ‘It is better to give than to receive’, and proceeds by analyzing
the concepts in virtue of which these beliefs are ethical and examining their
logical basis. On the second approach, the study focuses on questions about the
existence and character of ethical properties. Typically, it concentrates on
the most general ethical predicates such as goodness and wrongfulness and
considers whether there truly are ethical properties represented by these
predicates and, if so, whether and how they are interwoven into the natural
world. The two approaches are complementary. Neither dominates the other. The
epistemological approach is comparative. It looks to the most successful
branches of knowledge, the natural sciences and pure mathematics, for
paradigms. The former supplies the paradigm of knowledge that is based on
observation of natural phenomena; the latter supplies the paradigm of knowledge
that seemingly results from the sheer exercise of reason. Under the influence
of these paradigms, three distinct views have emerged: naturalism, rationalism,
and noncognitivism. Naturalism takes ethical knowledge to be empirical and
accordingly models it on the paradigm of the natural sciences. Ethical
concepts, on this view, concern natural phenomena. Rationalism takes ethical
knowledge to be a priori and accordingly models it on the paradigm of pure mathematics.
Ethical concepts, on this view, concern morality understood as something
completely distinct from, though applicable to, natural phenomena, something
whose content and structure can be apprehended by reason independently of
sensory inputs. Noncognitivism, in opposition to these other views, denies that
ethics is a genuine branch of knowledge or takes it to be a branch of knowledge
only in a qualified sense. In either case, it denies that ethics is properly
modeled on science or mathematics. On the most extreme form of noncognitivism,
there are no genuine ethical concepts; words like ‘right’, ‘wrong’, ‘good’, and
‘evil’ have no cognitive meaning but rather serve to vent feelings and
emotions, to express decisions and commitments, or to influence attitudes and
dispositions. On less extreme forms, these words are taken to have some
cognitive meaning, but conveying that meaning is held to be decidedly secondary
to the purposes of venting feelings, expressing decisions, or influencing
attitudes. Naturalism is well represented in the work of Mill; rationalism in
the works of Kant and the intuitionists. And noncognitivism, which did not
emerge as a distinctive view until the twentieth century, is most powerfully
expounded in the works of C. L. Stevenson and Hare. Its central tenets,
however, were anticipated by Hume, whose skeptical attacks on rationalism set
the agenda for subsequent work in metaethics. The metaphysical approach is
centered on the question of objectivity, the question of whether ethical predicates
represent real properties of an external world or merely apparent or invented
properties, properties that owe their existence to the perception, feeling, or
thought of those who ascribe them. Two views dominate this approach. The first,
moral realism, affirms the real existence of ethical properties. It takes them
to inhere in the external world and thus to exist independently of their being
perceived. For moral realism, ethics is an objective discipline, a discipline
that promises discovery and confirmation of objective truths. At the same time,
moral realists differ fundamentally on the question of the character of ethical
properties. Some, such as Plato and Moore, regard them as purely intellective
and thus irreducibly distinct from empirical properties. Others, such as
Aristotle and Mill, regard them as empirical and either reducible to or at
least supervenient on other empirical properties. The second view, moral
subjectivism, denies the real existence of ethical properties. On this view, to
predicate, say, goodness of a person is to impose some feeling, impulse, or
other state of mind onto the world, much as one projects an emotion onto one’s
circumstances when one describes them as delightful or sad. On the assumption
of moral subjectivism, ethics is not a source of objective truth. In ancient
philosophy, moral subjectivism was advanced by some of the Sophists, notably
Protagoras. In modern philosophy, Hume expounded it in the eighteenth century
and Sartre in the twentieth century. Regardless of approach, one and perhaps
the central problem of metaethics is how value is related to fact. On the
epistemological approach, this problem is commonly posed as the question of
whether judgments of value are derivable from statements of fact. Or, to be
more exact, can there be a logically valid argument whose conclusion is a
judgment of value and all of whose premises are statements of fact? On the
metaphysical approach, the problem is commonly posed as the question of whether
moral predicates represent properties that are explicable as complexes of
empirical properties. At issue, in either case, is whether ethics is an
autonomous discipline, whether the study of moral values and principles is to
some degree independent of the study of observable properties and events. A
negative answer to these questions affirms the autonomy of ethics; a positive
answer denies ethics’ autonomy and implies that it is a branch of the natural
sciences. Moral psychology. Even those who affirm the autonomy of ethics
recognize that some facts, particularly facts of human psychology, bear on the
general studies of goodness and right action. No one maintains that these
studies float free of all conception of human appetite and passion or that they
presuppose no account of the human capacity for voluntary action. It is
generally recognized that an adequate understanding of desire, emotion,
deliberation, choice, volition, character, and personality is indispensable to
the theoretical treatment of human well-being, intrinsic value, and duty.
Investigations into the nature of these psychological phenomena are therefore
an essential, though auxiliary, part of ethics. They constitute the adjunct
field of moral psychology. One area of particular interest within this field is
the study of those capacities by virtue of which men and women qualify as moral
agents, beings who are responsible for their actions. This study is especially
important to the theory of duty since that theory, in modern philosophy,
characteristically assumes a strong doctrine of individual responsibility. That
is, it assumes principles of culpability for wrongdoing that require, as
conditions of justified blame, that the act of wrongdoing be one’s own and that
it not be done innocently. Only moral agents are capable of meeting these
conditions. And the presumption is that normal, adult human beings qualify as
moral agents whereas small children and nonhuman animals do not. The study then
focuses on those capacities that distinguish the former from the latter as
responsible beings. The main issue is whether the power of reason alone
accounts for these capacities. On one side of the issue are philosophers like
Kant who hold that it does. Reason, in their view, is both the pilot and the
engine of moral agency. It not only guides one toward actions in conformity
with one’s duty, but it also produces the desire to do one’s duty and can
invest that desire with enough strength to overrule conflicting impulses of
appetite and passion. On the other side are philosophers, such as Hume and Mill,
who take reason to be one of several capacities that constitute moral agency.
On their view, reason works strictly in the service of natural and sublimated
desires, fears, and aversions to produce intelligent action, to guide its
possessor toward the objects of those desires and away from the objects of
those fears. It cannot, however, by itself originate any desire or fear. Thus,
the desire to act rightly, the aversion to acting wrongly, which are
constituents of moral agency, are not products of reason but are instead
acquired through some mechanical process of socialization by which their
objects become associated with the objects of natural desires and aversions. On
one view, then, moral agency consists in the power of reason to govern
behavior, and being rational is thus sufficient for being responsible for one’s
actions. On the other view, moral agency consists in several things including
reason, but also including a desire to act rightly and an aversion to acting
wrongly that originate in natural desires and aversions. On this view, to be
responsible for one’s actions, one must not only be rational but also have
certain desires and aversions whose acquisition is not guaranteed by the
maturation of reason. Within moral psychology, one cardinal test of these views
is how well they can accommodate and explain such common experiences of moral
agency as conscience, weakness, and moral dilemma. At some point, however, the
views must be tested by questions about freedom. For one cannot be responsible
for one’s actions if one is incapable of acting freely, which is to say, of
one’s own free will. The capacity for free action is thus essential to moral
agency, and how this capacity is to be explained, whether it fits within a
deterministic universe, and if not, whether the notion of moral responsibility
should be jettisoned, are among the deepest questions that the student of moral
agency must face. What is more, they are not questions to which moral
psychology can furnish answers. At this point, ethics descends into
metaphysics. ethnography, an open-ended
family of techniques through which anthropologists investigate cultures; also,
the organized descriptions of other cultures that result from this method.
Cultural anthropology ethnology is based primarily on fieldwork through which
anthropologists immerse themselves in the life of a local culture village,
neighborhood and attempt to describe and interpret aspects of the culture.
Careful observation is one central tool of investigation. Through it the anthropologist
can observe and record various features of social life, e.g. trading practices,
farming techniques, or marriage arrangements. A second central tool is the
interview, through which the researcher explores the beliefs and values of
members of the local culture. Tools of historical research, including
particularly oral history, are also of use in ethnography, since the cultural
practices of interest often derive from a remote point in time. ethnology, the comparative and analytical
study of cultures; cultural anthroplogy. Anthropologists aim to describe and
interpret aspects of the culture of various social groups e.g., the hunter-gatherers of the Kalahari,
rice villages of the Chin. Canton Delta, or a community of physicists at
Livermore Laboratory. Topics of particular interest include religious beliefs,
linguistic practices, kinship arrangements, marriage patterns, farming
technology, dietary practices, gender relations, and power relations. Cultural
anthropology is generally conceived as an empirical science, and this raises
several methodological and conceptual difficulties. First is the role of the
observer. The injection of an alien observer into the local culture unavoidably
disturbs that culture. Second, there is the problem of intelligibility across
cultural systems radical translation.
One goal of ethnographic research is to arrive at an interpretation of a set of
beliefs and values that are thought to be radically different from the
researcher’s own beliefs and values; but if this is so, then it is questionable
whether they can be accurately tr. into the researcher’s conceptual scheme.
Third, there is the problem of empirical testing of ethnographic
interpretations. To what extent do empirical procedures constrain the
construction of an interpretation of a given cultural milieu? Finally, there is
the problem of generalizability. To what extent does fieldwork in one location
permit anthropologists to generalize to a larger context other villages, the dispersed ethnic group
represented by this village, or this village at other times? ethnomethodology, a phenomenological approach
to interpreting everyday action and speech in various social contexts. Derived
from phenomenological sociology and introduced by Harold Garfinkel, the method
aims to guide research into meaningful social practices as experienced by
participants. A major objective of the method is to interpret the rules that
underlie everyday activity and thus constitute part of the normative basis of a
given social order. Research from this perspective generally focuses on mundane
social activities e.g., psychiatrists
evaluating patients’ files, jurors deliberating on defendants’ culpability, or
coroners judging causes of death. The investigator then attempts to reconstruct
an underlying set of rules and ad hoc procedures that may be taken to have
guided the observed activity. The approach emphasizes the contextuality of
social practice the richness of unspoken
shared understandings that guide and orient participants’ actions in a given
practice or activity. H. P. Grice, “The Teutons, according to Tacitus.”
dilemma. Grice: “Ryle overuses the word
dilemma in his popularization, “Dilemmas”.” 1 Any problem where morality is
relevant. This broad use includes not only conflicts among moral reasons but
also conflicts between moral reasons and reasons of law, religion, or
self-interest. In this sense, Abraham is in a moral dilemma when God commands
him to sacrifice his son, even if he has no moral reason to obey. Similarly, I
am in a moral dilemma if I cannot help a friend in trouble without forgoing a
lucrative but morally neutral business opportunity. ’Moral dilemma’ also often
refers to 2 any topic area where it is not known what, if anything, is morally
good or right. For example, when one asks whether abortion is immoral in any
way, one could call the topic “the moral dilemma of abortion.” This epistemic
use does not imply that anything really is immoral at all. Recently, moral
philosophers have discussed a much narrower set of situations as “moral
dilemmas.” They usually define ‘moral dilemma’ as 3 a situation where an agent
morally ought to do each of two acts but cannot do both. The bestknown example
is Sartre’s student who morally ought to care for his mother in Paris but at
the same time morally ought to go to England to join the Free and fight the Nazis. However, ‘ought’ covers
ideal actions that are not morally required, such as when someone ought to give
to a certain charity but is not required to do so. Since most common examples
of moral dilemmas include moral obligations or duties, or other requirements,
it is more accurate to define ‘moral dilemma’ more narrowly as 4 a situation
where an agent has a moral requirement to do each of two acts but cannot do
both. Some philosophers also refuse to call a situation a moral dilemma when
one of the conflicting requirements is clearly overridden, such as when I must
break a trivial promise in order to save a life. To exclude such resolvable
conflicts, ‘moral dilemma’ can be defined as 5 a situation where an agent has a
moral requirement to adopt each of two alternatives, and neither requirement is
overridden, but the agent cannot fulfill both. Another common move is to define
‘moral dilemma’ as 6 a situation where every alternative is morally wrong. This
is equivalent to 4 or 5, respectively, if an act is morally wrong whenever it
violates any moral requirement or any non-overridden moral requirement.
However, we usually do not call an act wrong unless it violates an overriding
moral requirement, and then 6 rules out moral dilemmas by definition, since
overriding moral requirements clearly cannot conflict. Although 5 thus seems
preferable, some would object that 5 includes trivial requirements and
conflicts, such as conflicts between trivial promises. To include only tragic
situations, we could define ‘moral dilemma’ as 7 a situation where an agent has
a strong moral obligation or requirement to adopt each of two alternatives, and
neither is overridden, but the agent cannot adopt both alternatives. This
definition is strong enough to raise the important controversies about moral
dilemmas without being so strong as to rule out their possibility by
definition. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Ryle’s dilemmas: are they?”
epistemology, the discipline, at the intersection
of ethics and epistemology, that studies the epistemic status and relations of
moral judgments and principles. It has developed out of an interest, common to
both ethics and epistemology, in questions of justification and justifiability in epistemology, of statements or beliefs,
and in ethics, of actions as well as judgments of actions and also general
principles of judgment. Its most prominent questions include the following. Can
normative claims be true or false? If so, how can they be known to be true or
false? If not, what status do they have, and are they capable of justification?
If they are capable of justification, how can they be justified? Does the
justification of normative claims differ with respect to particular claims and
with respect to general principles? In epistemology recent years have seen a
tendency to accept as valid an account of knowledge as entailing justified true
belief, a conception that requires an account not just of truth but also of
justification and of justified belief. Thus, under what conditions is someone
justified, epistemically, in believing something? Justification, of actions, of
judgments, and of principles, has long been a central element in ethics. It is
only recently that justification in ethics came to be thought of as an
epistemological problem, hence ‘moral epistemology’, as an expression, is a
fairly recent coinage, although its problems have a long lineage. One
long-standing linkage is provided by the challenge of skepticism. Skepticism in
ethics can be about the existence of any genuine distinction between right and
wrong, or it can focus on the possibility of attaining any knowledge of right
and wrong, good or bad. Is there a right answer? is a question in the
metaphysics of ethics. Can we know what the right answer is, and if so how? is
one of moral epistemology. Problems of perception and observation and ones
about observation statements or sense-data play an important role in
epistemology. There is not any obvious parallel in moral epistemology, unless
it is the role of prereflective moral judgments, or commonsense moral
judgments moral judgments unguided by
any overt moral theory which can be
taken to provide the data of moral theory, and which need to be explained,
systematized, coordinated, or revised to attain an appropriate relation between
theory and data. This would be analogous to taking the data of epistemology to
be provided, not by sense-data or observations but by judgments of perception
or observation statements. Once this step is taken the parallel is very close.
One source of moral skepticism is the apparent lack of any observational
counterpart for moral predicates, which generates the question how moral
judgments can be true if there is nothing for them to correspond to. Another source
of moral skepticism is apparently constant disagreement and uncertainty, which
would appear to be explained by the skeptical hypothesis denying the reality of
moral distinctions. Noncognitivism in ethics maintains that moral judgments are
not objects of knowledge, that they make no statements capable of truth or
falsity, but are or are akin to expressions of attitudes. Some other major
differences among ethical theories are largely epistemological in character.
Intuitionism maintains that basic moral propositions are knowable by intuition.
Empiricism in ethics maintains that moral propositions can be established by
empirical means or are complex forms of empirical statements. Ethical
rationalism maintains that the fundamental principles of morality can be
established a priori as holding of necessity. This is exemplified by Kant’s
moral philosophy, in which the categorical imperative is regarded as synthetic
a priori; more recently by what Alan Gewirth b.2 calls the “principle of
generic consistency,” which he claims it is selfcontradictory to deny. Ethical
empiricism is exemplified by classical utilitarianism, such as that of Bentham,
which aspires to develop ethics as an empirical science. If the consequences of
actions can be scientifically predicted and their utilities calculated, then
ethics can be a science. Situationism is equivalent to concrete case
intuitionism in maintaining that we can know immediately what ought to be done
in specific cases, but most ethical theories maintain that what ought to be
done is, in J. S. Mill’s words, determined by “the application of a law to an
individual case.” Different theories differ on the epistemic status of these
laws and on the process of application. Deductivists, either empiricistic or
rationalistic, hold that the law is essentially unchanged in the application;
non-deductivists hold that the law is modified in the process of application.
This distinction is explained in F. L. Will, “Beyond Deduction.” There is
similar variation about what if anything is selfevident, Sidgwick maintaining
that only certain highly abstract principles are self-evident, Ross that only
general rules are, and Prichard that only concrete judgments are, “by an act of
moral thinking.” Other problems in moral epistemology are provided by the
factvalue distinction and controversies
about whether there is any such distinction
and the isought question, the question how a moral judgment can be
derived from statements of fact alone. Naturalists affirm the possibility,
non-naturalists deny it. Prescriptivists claim that moral judgments are
prescriptions and cannot be deduced from descriptive statements alone. This
question ultimately leads to the question how an ultimate principle can be
justified. If it cannot be deduced from statements of fact, that route is out;
if it must be deduced from some other moral principle, then the principle
deduced cannot be ultimate and in any case this process is either circular or
leads to an infinite regress. If the ultimate principle is self-evident, then the
problem may have an answer. But if it is not it would appear to be arbitrary.
The problem of the justification of an ultimate principle continues to be a
leading one in moral epistemology. Recently there has been much interest in the
status and existence of “moral facts.” Are there any, what are they, and how
are they established as “facts”? This relates to questions about moral realism.
Moral realism maintains that moral predicates are real and can be known to be
so; anti-realists deny this. This denial links with the view that moral
properties supervene on natural ones, and the problem of supervenience is
another recent link between ethics and epistemology. Pragmatism in ethics
maintains that a moral problem is like any problem in that it is the occasion for
inquiry and moral judgments are to be regarded as hypotheses to be tested by
how well they resolve the problem. This amounts to an attempt to bypass the
isought problem and all such “dualisms.” So is constructivism, a development
owing much to the work of Rawls, which contrasts with moral realism.
Constructivism maintains that moral ideas are human constructs and the task is
not epistemological or metaphysical but practical and theoretical that of attaining reflective equilibrium
between considered moral judgments and the principles that coordinate and
explain them. On this view there are no moral facts. Opponents maintain that
this only replaces a foundationalist view of ethics with a coherence
conception. The question whether questions of moral epistemology can in this
way be bypassed can be regarded as itself a question of moral epistemology. And
the question of the foundations of morality, and whether there are foundations,
can still be regarded as a question of moral epistemology, as distinct from a
question of the most convenient and efficient arrangement of our moral ideas.
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Our knowledge of right and wrong: do we have it? Is it
intuitive as Oxonians believe?”
mos: ethos -- meta-ethics:
morality, an informal public system applying to all rational persons, governing
behavior that affects others, having the lessening of evil or harm as its goal,
and including what are commonly known as the moral rules, moral ideals, and
moral virtues. To say that it is a public system means that all those to whom
it applies must understand it and that it must not be irrational for them to
use it in deciding what to do and in judging others to whom the system applies.
Games are the paradigm cases of public systems; all games have a point and the
rules of a game apply to all who play it. All players know the point of the
game and its rules, and it is not irrational for them to be guided by the point
and rules and to judge the behavior of other players by them. To say that
morality is informal means that there is no decision procedure or authority
that can settle all its controversial questions. Morality thus resembles a
backyard game of basketball more than a professional game. Although there is
overwhelming agreement on most moral matters, certain controversial questions
must be settled in an ad hoc fashion or not settled at all. For example, when,
if ever, abortion is acceptable is an unresolvable moral matter, but each
society and religion can adopt its own position. That morality has no one in a
position of authority is one of the most important respects in which it differs
from law and religion. Although morality must include the commonly accepted
moral rules such as those prohibiting killing and deceiving, different
societies can interpret these rules somewhat differently. They can also differ
in their views about the scope of morality, i.e., about whether morality
protects newborns, fetuses, or non-human animals. Thus different societies can
have somewhat different moralities, although this difference has limits. Also
within each society, a person may have his own view about when it is justified
to break one of the rules, e.g., about how much harm would have to be prevented
in order to justify deceiving someone. Thus one person’s morality may differ
somewhat from another’s, but both will agree on the overwhelming number of
non-controversial cases. A moral theory is an attempt to describe, explain, and
if possible justify, morality. Unfortunately, most moral theories attempt to
generate some simplified moral code, rather than to describe the complex moral
system that is already in use. Morality does not resolve all disputes. Morality
does not require one always to act so as to produce the best consequences or to
act only in those ways that one would will everyone to act. Rather morality
includes both moral rules that no one should transgress and moral ideals that
all are encouraged to follow, but much of what one does will not be governed by
morality. H. P. Grice, “Meta-ethics in postwar Oxford philosophy: Hare,
Nowell-Smith, myself, and others!” mos,
ethos – meta-ethical -- meta-ethics:, Grice: “The Romans should have a verb for
‘mos,’ since it’s very nominational!” Surely what we need is something like
Austin’s ‘doing things.’” mos ,
mōris, m. etym. dub.; perh. root ma-, measure; cf.: maturus, matutinus; prop.,
a measuring or guiding rule of life; hence, I.manner, custom, way, usage,
practice, fashion, wont, as determined not by the laws, but by men's will and pleasure,
humor, self-will, caprice (class.; cf.: consuetudo, usus). I. Lit.: “opsequens
oboediensque'st mori atque imperiis patris,” Plaut. Bacch. 3, 3, 54: Grice: “Cicero was
being brilliant when he found that ‘mos’ nicely translates Grecian ‘ethos’ –
cf. Grice’s ethology. Ethologica -- Philosophical
ethology -- 1 the subfield of psychology that traces the development over time
of moral reasoning and opinions in the lives of individuals this subdiscipline
includes work of Jean Piaget, Lawrence Kohlberg, and Carol Gilligan; 2 the part
of philosophy where philosophy of mind and ethics overlap, which concerns all
the psychological issues relevant to morality. There are many different
psychological matters relevant to ethics, and each may be relevant in more than
one way. Different ethical theories imply different sorts of connections. So
moral psychology includes work of many and diverse kinds. But several
traditional clusters of concern are evident. Some elements of moral psychology
consider the psychological matters relevant to metaethical issues, i.e., to
issues about the general nature of moral truth, judgment, and knowledge.
Different metaethical theories invoke mental phenomena in different ways:
noncognitivism maintains that sentences expressing moral judgments do not
function to report truths or falsehoods, but rather, e.g., to express certain
emotions or to prescribe certain actions. So some forms of noncognitivism imply
that an understanding of certain sorts of emotions, or of special activities
like prescribing that may involve particular psychological elements, is crucial
to a full understanding of how ethical sentences are meaningful. Certain forms
of cognitivism, the view that moral declarative sentences do express truths or
falsehoods, imply that moral facts consist of psychological facts, that for
instance moral judgments consist of expressions of positive psychological
attitudes of some particular kind toward the objects of those judgments. And an
understanding of psychological phenomena like sentiment is crucial according to
certain sorts of projectivism, which hold that the supposed moral properties of
things are mere misleading projections of our sentiments onto the objects of
those sentiments. Certain traditional moral sense theories and certain
traditional forms of intuitionism have held that special psychological
faculties are crucial for our epistemic access to moral truth. Particular views
in normative ethics, particular views about the moral status of acts, persons,
and other targets of normative evaluation, also often suggest that an
understanding of certain psychological matters is crucial to ethics. Actions,
intentions, and character are some of the targets of evaluation of normative
ethics, and their proper understanding involves many issues in philosophy of
mind. Also, many normative theorists have maintained that there is a close
connection between pleasure, happiness, or desiresatisfaction and a person’s
good, and these things are also a concern of philosophy of mind. In addition,
the rightness of actions is often held to be closely connected to the motives,
beliefs, and other psychological phenomena that lie behind those actions.
Various other traditional philosophical concerns link ethical and psychological
issues: the nature of the patterns in the long-term development in individuals
of moral opinions and reasoning, the appropriate form for moral education and
punishment, the connections between obligation and motivation, i.e., between
moral reasons and psychological causes, and the notion of free will and its
relation to moral responsibility and autonomy. Some work in philosophy of mind
also suggests that moral phenomena, or at least normative phenomena of some
kind, play a crucial role in illuminating or constituting psychological phenomena
of various kinds, but the traditional concern of moral psychology has been with
the articulation of the sort of philosophy of mind that can be useful to
ethics. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Meta-ethics
in post-war Oxford philosophy: Hare, Nowell-Smith, myself, and others!” H. P.
Grice, “The morality of morality.” H. P. Grice, “Lorenz and the ‘ethologie der
ganse.’”
“practical reason” – Grice: “In ‘practical
reason,’ we have Aristotle at his best: the category is ‘action,’ and the
praedicabile is ‘rational.’ Now ‘action’ is supracategorial: It’s STRAWSON who
acts, not his action!” -- -- “Or ‘to do things,’ as Austin would put it!” -- moral
rationalism, the view that the substance of morality, usually in the form of
general moral principles, can be known a priori. The view is defended by Kant
in Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, but it goes back at least to Plato.
Both Plato and Kant thought that a priori moral knowledge could have an impact
on what we do quite independently of any desire that we happen to have. This
motivational view is also ordinarily associated with moral rationalism. It
comes in two quite different forms. The first is that a priori moral knowledge
consists in a sui generis mental state that is both belief-like and
desire-like. This seems to have been Plato’s view, for he held that the belief
that something is good is itself a disposition to promote that thing. The second
is that a priori moral knowledge consists in a belief that is capable of
rationally producing a distinct desire. Rationalists who make the first claim
have had trouble accommodating the possibility of someone’s believing that
something is good but, through weakness of will, not mustering the desire to do
it. Accordingly, they have been forced to assimilate weakness of will to
ignorance of the good. Rationalists who make the second claim about reason’s
action-producing capacity face no such problem. For this reason, their view is
often preferred. The best-known anti-rationalist about morality is Hume. His
Treatise of Human Nature denies both that morality’s substance can be known by
reason alone and that reason alone is capable of producing action.
Griceian realism: a metaethical view
committed to the objectivity of ethics. It has 1 metaphysical, 2 semantic, and
3 epistemological components. 1 Its metaphysical component is the claim that
there are moral facts and moral properties whose existence and nature are
independent of people’s beliefs and attitudes about what is right or wrong. In
this claim, moral realism contrasts with an error theory and with other forms
of nihilism that deny the existence of moral facts and properties. It contrasts
as well with various versions of moral relativism and other forms of ethical
constructivism that make moral facts consist in facts about people’s moral
beliefs and attitudes. 2 Its semantic component is primarily cognitivist.
Cognitivism holds that moral judgments should be construed as assertions about
the moral properties of actions, persons, policies, and other objects of moral
assessment, that moral predicates purport to refer to properties of such
objects, that moral judgments or the propositions that they express can be true
or false, and that cognizers can have the cognitive attitude of belief toward
the propositions that moral judgments express. These cognitivist claims
contrast with the noncognitive claims of emotivism and prescriptivism,
according to which the primary purpose of moral judgments is to express the
appraiser’s attitudes or commitments, rather than to state facts or ascribe
properties. Moral realism also holds that truth for moral judgments is
non-epistemic; in this way it contrasts with moral relativism and other forms
of ethical constructivism that make the truth of a moral judgment epistemic.
The metaphysical and semantic theses imply that there are some true moral
propositions. An error theory accepts the cognitivist semantic claims but denies
the realist metaphysical thesis. It holds that moral judgments should be
construed as containing referring expressions and having truth-values, but
insists that these referring expressions are empty, because there are no moral
facts, and that no moral claims are true. Also on this theory, commonsense
moral thought presupposes the existence of moral facts and properties, but is
systematically in error. In this way, the error theory stands to moral realism
much as atheism stands to theism in a world of theists. J. L. Mackie introduced
and defended the error theory in his Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, 7. 3
Finally, if moral realism is to avoid skepticism it must claim that some moral
beliefs are true, that there are methods for justifying moral beliefs, and that
moral knowledge is possible. While making these metaphysical, semantic, and
epistemological claims, moral realism is compatible with a wide variety of
other metaphysical, semantic, and epistemological principles and so can take
many different forms. The moral realists in the early part of the twentieth
century were generally intuitionists. Intuitionism combined a commitment to
moral realism with a foundationalist moral epistemology according to which
moral knowledge must rest on self-evident moral truths and with the
nonnaturalist claim that moral facts and properties are sui generis and not
reducible to any natural facts or properties. Friends of noncognitivism found
the metaphysical and epistemological commitments of intuitionism extravagant and
so rejected moral realism. Later moral realists have generally sought to defend
moral realism without the metaphysical and epistemological trappings of
intuitionism. One such version of moral realism takes a naturalistic form. This
form of ethical naturalism claims that our moral beliefs are justified when
they form part of an explanatorily coherent system of beliefs with one another
and with various non-moral beliefs, and insists that moral properties are just
natural properties of the people, actions, and policies that instantiate them.
Debate between realists and anti-realists and within the realist camp centers
on such issues as the relation between moral judgment and action, the rational
authority of morality, moral epistemology and methodology, the relation between
moral and non-moral natural properties, the place of ethics in a naturalistic
worldview, and the parity of ethics and the sciences.
Quinque sense: visum, olfactum, gustum,
tactum, auditum – quinque organa: oculus, etc. Grice: “I am particularly
irritated by Pitcher, of all people, quoting me to refute my idea that a
‘pain-sense’ is an otiosity! Of course
it is!” – “And I used to like Pitcher when he was at Oxford!” -- Some reamarks
about ‘senusus.’ – Grice’s Modified occam’s razor: “Do not multiply senses
beyond necessity – let there be five: visum, auditum, tactum, gustum, and
olfactum --. “Some remarks about the (five?) senses” – Grice: “Grice: “And then
there’s Shaftesbury who thinks he is being witty when he speaks of a ‘moral’
“sense”!” -- moral sense theory, an ethical theory, developed by some British
philosophers notably Shaftesbury,
Hutcheson, and Hume according to which
the pleasure or pain a person feels upon thinking about or “observing” certain
character traits is indicative of the virtue or vice, respectively, of those
features. It is a theory of “moral perception,” offered in response to moral
rationalism, the view that moral distinctions are derived by reason alone, and
combines Locke’s empiricist doctrine that all ideas begin in experience with
the belief, widely shared at the time, that feelings play a central role in
moral evaluation and motivation. On this theory, our emotional responses to
persons’ characters are often “perceptions” of their morality, just as our
experiences of an apple’s redness and sweetness are perceptions of its color
and taste. These ideas of morality are seen as products of an “internal” sense,
because they are produced in the “observer” only after she forms a concept of
the conduct or trait being observed or contemplated as when a person realizes that she is seeing
someone intentionally harm another and reacts with displeasure at what she
sees. The moral sense is conceived as being analogous to, or possibly an aspect
of, our capacity to recognize varying degrees of beauty in things, which modern
writers call “the sense of beauty.” Rejecting the popular view that morality is
based on the will of God, Shaftesbury maintains rather that morality depends on
human nature, and he introduces the notion of a sense of right and wrong,
possessed uniquely by human beings, who alone are capable of reflection.
Hutcheson argues that to approve of a character is to regard it as virtuous.
For him, reason, which discovers relations of inanimate objects to rational
agents, is unable to arouse our approval in the absence of a moral sense.
Ultimately, we can explain why, for example, we approve of someone’s temperate
character only by appealing to our natural tendency to feel pleasure sometimes
identified with approval at the thought of characters that exhibit benevolence,
the trait to which all other virtues can be traced. This disposition to feel
approval and disapproval is what Hutcheson identifies as the moral sense. Hume
emphasizes that typical human beings make moral distinctions on the basis of
their feelings only when those sentiments are experienced from a disinterested
or “general” point of view. In other words, we turn our initial sentiments into
moral judgments by compensating for the fact that we feel more strongly about
those to whom we are emotionally close than those from whom we are more
distant. On a widely held interpretation of Hume, the moral sense provides not
only judgments, but also motives to act according to those judgments, since its
feelings may be motivating passions or arouse such passions. Roderick Firth’s
787 twentieth-century ideal observer theory, according to which moral good is
designated by the projected reactions of a hypothetically omniscient, disinterested
observer possessing other ideal traits, as well as Brandt’s contemporary moral
spectator theory, are direct descendants of the moral sense theory. Refs: H. P. Grice: “Shaftesbury’s moral
sense: some remarks about the ‘senses’ of this ‘expression’!” Refs.: H. P.
Grice, G. J. Warnock, and J. O. Urmson: “The Roman names for the five senses.”
Luigi Speranza, “The senses in iconography.” The Anglo-American Club. --.
MEDIUS
-- mediautum-inmediatum distinction, the: mediatum: Grice is all
about the mediatum. This he call a ‘soul-to-soul’ transfer. Imagine you pick up
a rose, the thorn hurts you. You are in pain. You say “Ouch.” You transmit this
to the fellow gardener. The mediacy means, “Beware of the thorn. It may hurt
you.” “I am amazed that in The New World, it’s all about immediacy (Chisholm)
when there’s so much which is mediately of immediate philosophical importance!”
immediatum: Grice: “Here the ‘in-’
is negative!” – the presence to the mind without intermediaries. The term
‘immediatum’ and its cognates have been used extensively throughout the history
of philosophy, generally without much explanation. Descartes, e.g., explains
his notion of thought thus: “I use this term to include everything that is
within us in a way that we are IMMEDIATELY aware of it” (Second Replies).
Descartes offers no explanation of immediate awareness, but the implicaturum is
“contextually cancellable.” “Only an idiot would not realise that he is
opposing it to mediated experience.” – Grice. Grice is well aware of this. “Check
with Lewis and Short.” “mĕdĭo , 1, v. a. medius, I.to
halve, divide in the middle (post-class.), Apic. 3, 9. — B. Neutr., to be in
the middle: “melius Juno mediante,” Pall. Mart. 10, 32.” “So you see, ‘mediare’
can be transitive, but surely Descartes means it in the intransitive way –
something mediates or something doesn’t – Clear as water!” However, when
used as a primitive in this way, ‘immediatum’ may simply mean that thoughts are
the immediate objects of perception because thoughts are the only things
perceived in the strict and proper sense that no perception of an intermediary
is required for the person’s awareness of them. Sometimes ‘immediate’ means
‘not mediated’. (1) An inference from a premise to a conclusion can exhibit
logical immediacy because it does not depend on other premises. This is a
technical usage of proof theory to describe the form of a certain class of
inference rules. (2) A concept can exhibit conceptual immediacy because it is
definitionally primitive, as in the Berkeleian doctrine that perception of qualities
is immediate, and perception of objects is defined by the perception of their
qualities, which is directly understood. (3) Our perception of something can
exhibit causal immediacy because it is not caused by intervening acts of
perception or cognition, as with seeing someone immediately in the flesh rather
than through images on a movie screen. (4) A belief-formation process can
possess psychological immediacy because it contains no subprocess of reasoning
and in that sense has no psychological mediator. (5) Our knowledge of something
can exhibit epistemic immediacy because it is justified without inference from
another proposition, as in intuitive knowledge of the existence of the self,
which has no epistemic mediator. A noteworthy special application of immediacy
is to be found in Russell’s notion of knowledge by acquaintance. This notion is
a development of the venerable doctrine originating with Plato, and also found
in Augustine, that understanding the nature of some object requires that we can
gain immediate cognitive access to that object. Thus, for Plato, to understand
the nature of beauty requires acquaintance with beauty itself. This view
contrasts with one in which understanding the nature of beauty requires
linguistic competence in the use of the word ‘beauty’ or, alternatively, with
one that requires having a mental representation of beauty. Russell offers
sense-data and universals as examples of things known by acquaintance. To these
senses of immediacy we may add another category whose members have acquired
special meanings within certain philosophical traditions. For example, in
Hegel’s philosophy if (per impossibile) an object were encountered “as existing
in simple immediacy” it would be encountered as it is in itself, unchanged by
conceptualization. In phenomenology “immediate” experience is, roughly,
bracketed experience.
mos, costume – Grice: “Can a single
individual have an idio-mos, a practice? He certainly can device a set of
pratices that nobody ever puts into use, as in my New Hightway Code, or my
Deutero-Esperanto.” moral scepticism, any metaethical view that raises
fundamental doubts about morality as a whole. Different kinds of doubts lead to
different kinds of moral skepticism. The primary kinds of moral skepticism are
epistemological. Moral justification skepticism is the claim that nobody ever
has any or adequate justification for believing any substantive moral claim.
Moral knowledge skepticism is the claim that nobody ever knows that any
substantive moral claim is true. If knowledge implies justification, as is
often assumed, then moral justification skepticism implies moral knowledge
skepticism. But even if knowledge requires justification, it requires more, so
moral knowledge skepticism does not imply moral justification skepticism.
Another kind of skeptical view in metaethics rests on linguistic analysis. Some
emotivists, expressivists, and prescriptivists argue that moral claims like
“Cheating is morally wrong” resemble expressions of emotion or desire like
“Boo, cheating” or prescriptions for action like “Don’t cheat”, which are
neither true nor false, so moral claims themselves are neither true nor false.
This linguistic moral skepticism, which is sometimes called noncognitivism,
implies moral knowledge skepticism if knowledge implies truth. Even if such
linguistic analyses are rejected, one can still hold that no moral properties
or facts really exist. This ontological moral skepticism can be combined with
the linguistic view that moral claims assert moral properties and facts to
yield an error theory that all positive moral claims are false. A different
kind of doubt about morality is often raised by asking, “Why should I be
moral?” Practical moral skepticism answers that there is not always any reason
or any adequate reason to be moral or to do what is morally required. This view
concerns reasons to act rather than reasons to believe. Moral skepticism of all
these kinds is often seen as immoral, but moral skeptics can act and be
motivated and even hold moral beliefs in much the same way as non-skeptics.
Moral skeptics just deny that their or anyone else’s moral beliefs are
justified or known or true, or that they have adequate reason to be moral. moral
status, the suitability of a being to be viewed as an appropriate object of
direct moral concern; the nature or degree of a being’s ability to count as a
ground of claims against moral agents; the moral standing, rank, or importance
of a kind of being; the condition of being a moral patient; moral
considerability. Ordinary moral reflection involves considering others. But
which others ought to be considered? And how are the various objects of moral
consideration to be weighed against one another? Anything might be the topic of
moral discussion, but not everything is thought to be an appropriate object of
direct moral concern. If there are any ethical constraints on how we may treat
a ceramic plate, these seem to derive from considerations about other beings,
not from the interests or good or nature of the plate. The same applies,
presumably, to a clod of earth. Many philosophers view a living but insentient
being, such as a dandelion, in the same way; others have doubts. According to
some, even sentient animal life is little more deserving of moral consideration
than the clod or the dandelion. This tradition, which restricts significant
moral status to humans, has come under vigorous and varied attack by defenders
of animal liberation. This attack criticizes speciesism, and argues that
“humanism” is analogous to theories that illegitimately base moral status on
race, gender, or social class. Some philosophers have referred to beings that
are appropriate objects of direct moral concern as “moral patients.” Moral
agents are those beings whose actions are subject to moral evaluation;
analogously, moral patients would be those beings whose suffering in the sense
of being the objects of the actions of moral agents permits or demands moral
evaluation. Others apply the label ‘moral patients’ more narrowly, just to
those beings that are appropriate objects of direct moral concern but are not
also moral agents. The issue of moral status concerns not only whether beings
count at all morally, but also to what degree they count. After all, beings who
are moral patients might still have their claims outweighed by the preferred
claims of other beings who possess some special moral status. We might, with
Nozick, propose “utilitarianism for animals, Kantianism for people.” Similarly,
the bodily autonomy argument in defense of abortion, made famous by Thomson,
does not deny that the fetus is a moral patient, but insists that her/his/its
claims are limited by the pregnant woman’s prior claim to control her bodily
destiny. It has often been thought that moral status should be tied to the
condition of “personhood.” The idea has been either that only persons are moral
patients, or that persons possess a special moral status that makes them
morally more important than nonpersons. Personhood, on such theories, is a
minimal condition for moral patiency. Why? Moral patiency is said to be
“correlative” with moral agency: a creature has both or neither. Alternatively,
persons have been viewed not as the only moral patients, but as a specially
privileged elite among moral patients, possessing rights as well as
interests.
more grice to
the mill: SOUS-ENTENDU,
-UE, part. passé, adj. et subst. masc. I. − Part. passé de sous-entendre*. A. −
Empl. impers. Il est sous-entendu que + complét. à l'ind. Il est inutile de
préciser que. Synon. il va sans dire que.Elle lui écrivit (...) que (...) elle
aurait enfin, après avoir été si souvent reçue chez eux, le plaisir de les
inviter à son tour. De lui, elle ne disait pas un mot, il était sous-entendu
que leur présence excluait la sienne (Proust,Swann,1913, p. 301). B. − Empl.
ell. à valeur de prop. part. Sous-entendu (inv., le locuteur suppléant ce qui
n'est pas exprimé mais suggéré). Ce qui signifie par là (que). Mon cher Ami,
Encore une! sous-entendu: demande de croix d'honneur (Flaub.,Corresp.,1871, p.
287). II. − Adjectif A. − Synon. implicite, tacite; anton. avoué, explicite,
formulé. 1. Qu'on laisse entendre sans l'exprimer. Le lendemain, à table, mon
mari me dit (je me demandai d'abord s'il n'y avait pas là quelque dessein
sous-entendu): − Sais-tu ce que m'a annoncé Brassy? Gurgine a essayé de se tuer
(Daniel-Rops,Mort,1934, p. 291). 2. Qui reste implicite. Je me rappelle (...)
d'avoir lu dans la déclaration des droits de l'homme cette maxime sous-entendue
dans tous les codes qu'on nous a donnés depuis: « Tout ce qui n'est pas défendu
par la loi ne peut être empêché, et nul ne peut être contraint à faire ce
qu'elle n'ordonne pas » (Bonald,Législ. primit.,t. 1, 1802, p. 152).Toute
mélodie commence par une anacrouse exprimée ou sous-entendue (D'Indy,Compos.
mus.,t. 1, 1897-1900, p. 35). B. − GRAMM. Qui n'est pas exprimé, mais que le
sens ou la syntaxe pourrait suppléer aisément. Observez qu'ainsi est tantôt
adverbe, tantôt conjonction. (...) Il est encore adverbe dans celle-ci [cette
phrase], ainsi que la vertu, le crime a ses degrés; il signifie de la même
manière. C'est que, qui est la conjonction qui lie ensemble la phrase exprimée,
le crime a ses degrés, avec la phrase sous-entendue, la vertu a ses degrés
(Destutt de Tr.,Idéol. 2,1803, p. 140).L'intelligence fait donc naturellement
usage des rapports d'équivalent à équivalent, de contenu à contenant, de cause
à effet, etc., qu'implique toute phrase, où il y a un sujet, un attribut, un
verbe, exprimé ou sous-entendu (Bergson,Évol. créatr.,1907, p. 149). III. −
Subst. masc. A. − Au sing. Comportement de celui qui sous-entend les choses
sans les exprimer explicitement. C'est la plus immense personnalité que je
connaisse [Zola], mais elle est toute dans le sous-entendu: l'homme ne parle
pas de lui, mais toutes les théories, toutes les idées, toutes les logomachies
qu'il émet combattent uniquement, à propos de tout et de n'importe quoi, en
faveur de sa littérature et de son talent (Goncourt, Journal, 1883, p. 251). B.
− P. méton. 1. Parfois péj. Ce qui est sous-entendu, insinué dans des propos ou
dans un texte, ou p. ext., par un comportement. Synon. allusion,
insinuation.Plus libre que ses confrères, il ne craignait pas, − bien
timidement encore, avec des clignements d'yeux et des sous-entendus, − de
fronder les gens en place (Rolland,J.-Chr.,Adolesc., 1905, p. 365). − Au sing.
à valeur de neutre. Henry Céard a passé avec moi toute la journée, causant du
roman qu'il fait, − et qu'il veut faire dans le gris, le voilé, le sous-entendu
(Goncourt,, Journal1878, p. 1276). − En partic. Allusion grivoise. Les
conversations fourmillaient d'allusions et de sous-entendus dont la grivoiserie
me choquait (Beauvoir,Mém. j. fille,1958, p. 165). 2. Ce qui n'est pas exprimé
explicitement. Synon. restriction, réticence.Personne ne dit: « Je suis », si
ce n'est dans une certaine attitude très instable et généralement apprise, et
on ne le dit alors qu'avec quantité de sous-entendus: il y faut parfois un long
commentaire (Valéry, Variété IV,1938, p. 228). REM. Sous-entente, subst.
fém.,vx. a) Action de sous-entendre par artifice; p. méton., ce qui est ainsi
sous-entendu. Il ne parle jamais qu'il n'y ait quelque sous-entente à ce qu'il
dit. Il y a quelque sous-entente à cela (Ac. 1798-1878). b) Gramm. Synon. de
sous-entendu. (Ds Bally 1951). Prononc. et Orth.: [suzɑ ̃tɑ ̃dy]. Ac. 1694:
sousentendu, -ue, 1718: sousentendu, -üe, dep. 1740: sous-entendu, -ue. Fréq.
abs. littér.: 249. Fréq. rel. littér.: xixes.: a) 189, b) 230; xxes.: a) 480,
b) 484. Bbg. Ducrot (O.). Le Dire et le dit. Paris, 1984, pp. 13-31. −
Kerbrat-Orecchioni (C.). L'Énonciation. De la subjectivité ds le lang. Paris,
1980, 290 p., passim. more grice
to the mill: sous-entendu: used by, of all people, Mill. An Examination of
Sir William Hamilton's Philosophybooks.google.com › books ... and speak with
any approach to precision, and adopting into [the necessary sufficient clauses
of a piece of philosophical conceptual analysis] a mere sous-entendu of common
conversation in its most unprecise form. If I say to any one, Cf.
understatement, as opposed to overstatement. The ‘statement’ thing complicates
things, ‘underunderstanding’ seems better, or ‘sub-understanding,’ strictly.
Trust Grice to bring more Grice to the Mill and provide a full essay, indeed
theory, and base his own philosophy, on the sous-tentendu! Cf. Pears, Pears
Cyclopaedia. “The English love meiosis, litotes, and understatement. The French
don’t.” Note all the figures of rhetoric cited by Grice, and why they have
philosophical import. Many entries here: hyperbole, meiosis, litotes, etc.
Grice took ‘sous-entendu’ etymologically serious. It is UNDERSTOOD. Nobody
taught you, but it understood. It is understood is like It is known. So “The
pillar box seems red” is understood to mean, “It may not be.” Now a
sous-entendu may be cancellable, in which case it was MIS-understood, or the
emissor has changed his mind. Grice considers the paradoxes the understanding
under ‘uptake,’ just to make fun of Austin’s informalism. The ‘endendu’ is what
the French understand by ‘understand,’ the root being Latin intellectus, or
intendo.
macaulay: Grice: “Unlike Whitehead, I care
for style; so when it comes to ‘if,’ we
have to please Macaulay – the verbs change, for each mode – and sub-mode!” --
Grice: A curious phenomenon comes to light. I
began by assuming (or stipulating) that the verbs 'judge' and 'will'
(acceptance-verbs) are to be 'completed' by radicals (phrastics). Yet when the
machinery developed above has been applied, we find that the verb 'accept' (or
'think') is to be completed by something of the form 'Op + p', that is, by a
sentence. Perhaps we might tolerate this syntactical ambivalence; but if we
cannot, the remedy is not clear. It would, for example, not be satisfactory to
suppose that 'that', when placed before a sentence, acts as a 'radicalizer' (is
a functor expressing a function which takes that sentence on to its radical);
for that way we should lose the differentiations effected by varying
mode-markers, and this would be fatal to the scheme. This phenomenon certainly
suggests that the attempt to distinguish radicals from sentences may be
misguided; that if radicals are to be admitted at all, they should be
identified with indicative sentences.
The operator '⊢'
would then be a 'semantically vanishing' operator. But this does not wholly
satisfy me; for, if '⊢'
is semantically vacuous, what happens to the subordinate distinction made by
'A' and 'B' markers, which seems genuine enough? We might find these markers
'hanging in the air', like two smiles left behind by the Cheshire Cat. Whatever
the outcome of this debate, however, I feel fairly confident that I could
accommodate the formulation of my discussion to it. Fuller Exposition of the
'Initial Idea' First, some preliminary points. To provide at least a modicum of
intelligibility for my discourse, I shall pronounce the judicative end p.72
operator '⊢'
as 'it is the case that', and the volitive operator '!' as 'let it be that';
and I shall pronounce the sequence 'φ, ψ' as 'given that φ, ψ'. These vocal
mannerisms will result in the production of some pretty barbarous 'English
sentences'; but we must remember that what I shall be trying to do, in uttering
such sentences, will be to represent supposedly underlying structure; if that
is one's aim, one can hardly expect that one's speech-forms will be such as to
excite the approval of, let us say, Jane Austen or Lord Macaulay. In any case,
less horrendous, though (for my purposes) less perspicuous, alternatives will,
I think, be available. Further, I am going to be almost exclusively concerned
with alethic and practical arguments, the proximate conclusions of which will
be, respectively, of the forms 'Acc (⊢ p)' and 'Acc (! p)'; for example, 'acceptable (it is the
case that it snows)' and 'acceptable (let it be that I go home)'. There will be
two possible ways of reading the latter sentence. We might regard 'acceptable'
as a sentential adverb (modifier) like 'demonstrably'; in that case to say or
think 'acceptable (let it be that I go home)' will be to say or think 'let it
be that I go home', together with the qualification that what I say or think is
acceptable; as one might say, 'acceptably, let it be that I go home'. To adopt
this reading would seem to commit us to the impossibility of incontinence; for
since 'accept that let it be that I go home' is to be my rewrite for 'Vaccept
(will) that I go home', anyone x who concluded, by practical argument, that
'acceptable let it be that x go home' would ipso facto will to go home.
Similarly (though less paradoxically) any one who concluded, by alethic
argument, 'acceptable it is the case that it snows', would ipso facto judge
that it snows. So an alternative reading 'it is acceptable that let it be that
I go home', which does not commit the speaker or thinker to 'let it be that I
go home', seems preferable. We can, of course, retain the distinct form
'acceptably, let it be that (it is the case that) p' for renderings of
'desirably' and 'probably'. Let us now tackle the judicative cases. I start
with the assumption that arguments of the form 'A, so probably B' are sometimes
(informally) valid; 'he has an exceptionally red face, so probably he has high
blood pressure' might be informally valid, whereas 'he has an exceptionally red
face, so probably he has musical talent' is unlikely to be allowed informal
validity. end p.73 We might re-express this assumption by saying that it is
sometimes the case that A informally yields-with-probability that B (where
'yields' is the converse of 'is inferable from'). If we wish to construct a
form of argument the acceptability of which does not depend on choice of
substituends for 'A' and 'B', we may, so to speak, allow into the
object-language forms of sentence which correspond to metastatements of the
form: 'A yields-with-probability that B'; we may allow ourselves, for example,
such a sentence as "it is probable, given that he has a very red face,
that he has high blood pressure". This will provide us with the
argument-patterns: “Probable, given A, that B A So, probably, B” or “Probable,
given A, that B A So probably that B” To take
the second pattern, the legitimacy of such an inferential transition will not
depend on the identity of 'A' or of 'B', though it will depend (as was stated
in the previous chapter) on a licence from a suitably formulated 'Principle of
Total Evidence'. The proposal which I am considering (in pursuit of the
'initial idea') would (roughly) involve rewriting the second pattern of
argument so that it reads: It is acceptable, given that it is the case that A,
that it is the case that B. It is the case that A. To apply this schema to a
particular case, we generated the particular argument: It is acceptable, given
that it is the case that Snodgrass has a red face, that it is the case that
Snodgrass has high blood pressure. It is the case that Snodgrass has a red
face. So, it is acceptable that it is the case that Snodgrass has high blood
pressure. end p.74 If we make the further assumption that the singular
'conditional' acceptability statement which is the first premiss of the above
argument may be (and perhaps has to be) reached by an analogue of the rule of
universal instantiation from a general acceptability statement, we make room
for such general acceptability sentences as: It is acceptable, given that it is
the case that x has a red face, that it is the case that x has high blood
pressure. which are of the form "It is acceptable, given that it is the
case that Fx, that it is the case that Gx'; 'x' here is, you will note, an
unbound variable; and the form might also (loosely) be read (pronounced) as:
"It is acceptable, given that it is the case that one (something) is F,
that it is the case that one (it) is G." All of this is (I think) pretty
platitudinous; which is just as well, since it is to serve as a model for the
treatment of practical argument. To turn from the alethic to the practical
dimension. Here (the proposal goes) we may proceed, in a fashion almost exactly
parallel to that adopted on the alethic side, through the following sequence of
stages: (1) Arguments (in thought or speech) of the form: Let it be that A It
is the case that B so, with some degree of desirability, let it be that C are
sometimes (and sometimes not) informally valid (or acceptable). (2) Arguments
of the form: It is desirable, given that let it be that A and that it is the
case that B, that let it be that C Let it be that A It is the case that B so,
it is desirable that let it be that C should, therefore, be allowed to be
formally acceptable, subject to licence from a Principle of Total Evidence. (3)
In accordance with our proposal such arguments will be rewritten: end p.75 It
is acceptable, given that let it be A and that it is the case that B, that let
it be that C Let it be that A It is the case that B so, it is desirable that
let it be that C (4) The first premisses of such arguments may be (and perhaps
have to be) reached by instantiation from general acceptability statements of
the form: "It is acceptable, given that let one be E and that it is the
case that one is F, that let it be that one is G." We may note that
sentences like "it is snowing" can be trivially recast so as (in
effect) to appear as third premisses in such arguments (with 'open'
counterparts inside the acceptability sentence; they can be rewritten as, for
example, "Snodgrass is such that it is snowing"). We are now in
possession of such exciting general acceptability sentences as: "It is
acceptable, given that let it be that one keeps dry and that it is the case
that one is such that it is raining, that let one take with one one's umbrella."
(5) A special subclass of general
acceptability sentences (and of practical arguments) can be generated by
'trivializing' the predicate in the judicative premiss (making it a 'universal
predicate'). If, for example, I take 'x is F' to represent 'x is identical with
x' the judicative subclause may be omitted from the general acceptability
sentence, with a corresponding 'reduction' in the shape of the related
practical argument. We have therefore such argument sequences as the following:
(P i ) It is acceptable, given that let it be that one survives, that let it be
that one eats So (by U i ) It is acceptable, given that let it be that
Snodgrass survives, that let it be that Snodgrass eats (P 2 ) Let it be that
Snodgrass survives So (by Det) It is acceptable that let it be that Snodgrass
eats. We should also, at some point, consider further transitions to: (a)
Acceptably, let it be that Snodgrass eats, and to: (b) Let it be that Snodgrass
eats. end p.76 And we may also note that, as a more colloquial substitute for "Let
it be that one (Snodgrass) survives (eats)" the form "one (Snodgrass)
is to survive (eat)" is available; we thus obtain prettier inhabitants of
antecedent clauses, for example, "given that Snodgrass is to
survive". We must now pay some attention to the varieties of acceptability
statement to be found within each of the alethic and practical dimensions; it
will, of course, be essential to the large-scale success of the proposal which
I am exploring that one should be able to show that for every such variant
within one dimension there is a corresponding variant within the other. Within
the area of defeasible generalizations, there is another variant which, in my
view, extends across the board in the way just indicated, namely, the
unweighted acceptability generalization (with associated singular
conditionals), or, as I shall also call it, the ceteris paribus generalization.
Such generalization I take to be of the form "It is acceptable (ceteris
paribus), given that φX, that ψX" and I think we find both practical and
alethic examples of the form; for example, "It is ceteris paribus
acceptable, given that it is the case that one likes a person, that it is the
case that one wants his company", which is not incompatible with "It
is ceteris paribus acceptable, given that it is the case that one likes a
person and that one is feeling ill, that one does not want his company".
We also find "It is ceteris paribus acceptable, given that let it be that
one leaves the country and given that it is the case that one is an alien, that
let it be that one obtains a sailing permit from Internal Revenue", which
is compatible with "It is ceteris paribus acceptable, given that let it be
that one leaves the country and given that it is the case that one is an alien
and that one is a close friend of the President, that let it be that one does
not obtain a sailing permit, and that one arranges to travel in Air Force
I". I discussed this kind of generalization, or 'law', briefly in
"Method in Philosophical Psychology"1 and shall not dilate on its
features here. I will just remark that it can be adapted to handle 'functional
laws' (in the way suggested in that address), and that end p.77 it is different
from the closely related use of universal generalizations in 'artificially
closed systems', where some relevant parameter is deliberately ignored, to be
taken care of by an extension to the system; for in that case, when the
extension is made, the original law has to be modified or corrected, whereas my
ceteris paribus generalization can survive in an extended system; and I regard
this as a particular advantage to philosophical psychology. In addition to
these two defeasible types of acceptability generalization (each with alethic
and practical sub-types), we have non-defeasible acceptability generalizations,
with associated singular conditionals, exemplifying what I might call
'unqualified', 'unreserved', or 'full' acceptability claims. To express these I
shall employ the (constructed) modal 'it is fully acceptable that . . .'; and
again there will be occasion for its use in the representation both of alethic
and of practical discourse. We have, in all, then, three varieties of
acceptability statement (each with alethic and practical sub-types), associated
with the modals "It is fully acceptable that . . . "
(non-defeasible), 'it is ceteris paribus acceptable that . . . ', and 'it is to
such-and-such a degree acceptable that . . . ', both of the latter pair being
subject to defeasibility. (I should re-emphasize that, on the practical side, I
am so far concerned to represent only statements which are analogous with
Kant's Technical Imperatives ('Rules of Skill').)
more, H: “Not to be confused with the
other More, who was literally beheaded when he refused to swear to the Act of
Supremacy which metaphorically named Henry VIII the head of the C. of E.” -- English
philosopher, theologian, and poet, the most prolific of the Cambridge
Platonists. He entered Christ’s , where he spent the rest of his life after
becoming Fellow . He was primarily an apologist of anti-Calvinist,
latitudinarian stamp whose inalienable philosophico- theological purpose was to
demonstrate the existence and immortality of the soul and to cure “two enormous
distempers of the mind,” atheism and “enthusiasm.” He describes himself as “a
Fisher for Philosophers, desirous to draw them to or retain them in the
Christian Faith.” His eclectic method deployed Neoplatonism notably Plotinus
and Ficino, mystical theologies, cabalistic doctrines as More misconceived
them, empirical findings including reports of witchcraft and ghosts, the new
science, and the new philosophy, notably the philosophy of Descartes. Yet he
rejected Descartes’s beast-machine doctrine, his version of dualism, and the
pretensions of Cartesian mechanical philosophy to explain all physical
phenomena. Animals have souls; the universe is alive with souls. Body and
spirit are spatially extended, the former being essentially impenetrable,
inert, and discerpible divisible into parts, the latter essentially penetrable,
indiscerpible, active, and capable of a spiritual density, which More called
essential spissitude, “the redoubling or contracting of substance into less
space than it does sometimes occupy.” Physical processes are activated and
ordered by the spirit of nature, a hylarchic principle and “the vicarious power
of God upon this great automaton, the world.” More’s writings on natural
philosophy, especially his doctrine of infinite space, are thought to have
influenced Newton. More attacked Hobbes’s materialism and, in the 1660s and
1670s, the impieties of Dutch Cartesianism, including the perceived atheism of
Spinoza and his circle. He regretted the “enthusiasm” for and conversion to
Quakerism of Anne Conway, his “extramural” tutee and assiduous correspondent.
More had a partiality for coinages and linguistic exotica. We owe to him
‘Cartesianism’ coined a few years before the first appearance of the equivalent, and the substantive
‘materialist.’ “But he never coined ‘implicaturum,’” – Grice.
more, Sir Thomas: English humanist,
statesman, martyr, and saint. A lawyer by profession, he entered royal service and
became lord chancellor. After refusing to swear to the Act of Supremacy, which
named (“metaphorically,” – Grice) Henry
VIII the head of the C. of E. h, More was (“ironically, but literally” – Grice)
beheaded as a traitor. Although his writings include biography, poetry,
letters, and anti-heretical tracts, his only philosophical work, Utopia
published in Latin, 1516, is his masterpiece. Covering a wide variety of
subjects including government, education, punishment, religion, family life,
and euthanasia, Utopia contrasts European social institutions with their
counterparts on the imaginary island of Utopia. Inspired in part by Plato’s
Republic, the Utopian communal system is designed to teach virtue and reward it
with happiness. The absence of money, private property, and most social
distinctions allows Utopians the leisure to develop the faculties in which
happiness consists. Because of More’s love of irony, Utopia has been subject to
quite different interpretations. H. P. Grice, “A personal guide to the 39
articles, compleat with their 39 implicatura.”
mosca: Essential Italian
philosopher, who made pioneering contributions to the theory of democratic elitism.
Combining the life of a professor with
that of a politician, he taught such subjects as constitutional law, public
law, political science, and history of political theory; at various times he
was also an editor of the Parliamentary proceedings, an elected member of the
Chamber of Deputies, an under-secretary for colonial affairs, a newspaper
columnist, and a member of the Senate. For Mosca ‘elitism’ refers to the empirical
generalization that a society is ruled by an organised minority. His democratic
commitment is embodied in what he calls juridical defense: the normative
principle that political developments are to be judged by whether and how they
prevent any one person, class, force, or institution from dominating the
others. Mosca’s third main contribution is a framework consisting of two
intersecting distinctions that yield four possible ideal types, defined as
follows: in autocracy, authority flows from the rulers to the ruled. In
liberalism, from the ruled to the rulers. In democracy, the ruling class is
open to renewal by members of other classes; in aristocracy it is not. He was
influenced by, and in turn influenced, positivism, for the elitist thesis
presumably constitutes the fundamental “law” of political “science.” Even
deeper is his connection with the tradition of Machiavelli’s political realism.
There is also no question that he practiced an empirical approach. In the
tradition of elitism, he may be compared and contrasted with Pareto, Michels,
and Schumpeter; and in the tradition of political philosophy, to Croce, Gentile, and
Gramsci. Refs.: H. P. Grice: “Mosca’s liberalism;” Luigi Speranza, "Grice e Mosca," per il Club Anglo-Italiano,
The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
Motus – motivatum – Grice, “Must our
motives be impure?” “Obligation cashes out in motivation.” Motivatum -- motivation,
a property central in motivational explanations of intentional conduct. To
assert that Grice is driving to Lord’s today because she wants to see his
cricket team play and believes that they are playing today at Lord’s is to
offer an explanation of Grice’s action. On a popular interpretation, the
assertion mentions a pair of attitudes: a desire and a belief. Grice’s s desire
is a paradigmatic motivational attitude in that it inclines him to bring about
the satisfaction of that very attitude. The primary function of motivational
attitudes is to bring about their own satisfaction by inducing the agent to
undertake a suitable course of action, and, arguably, any attitude that has
that function is, ipso facto, a motivational one. The related thesis that only
attitudes having this function are motivational
or, more precisely, motivation-constituting is implausible. Grice hopes that the Oxfordshire
Cricket Team won yesterday. Plainly, his hope cannot bring about its own
satisfaction, since Grice has no control over the past. Even so, the hope
seemingly may motivate action e.g., Grice’s searching for sports news on her
car radio, in which case the hope is motivation-constituting. Some philosophers
have claimed that our beliefs that we are morally required to take a particular
course of action are motivation-constituting, and such beliefs obviously do not
have the function of bringing about their own satisfaction i.e., their truth.
However, the claim is controversial, as is the related claim that beliefs of
this kind are “besires” that is, not
merely beliefs but desires as well. Refs.: “Desire, belief, and besire.”
Grice: the explanatory-justificatory
distinction – “To explain” is not to explicate, but to render ‘plain’ – To
justify is hardly to render ‘plain’! Grice is aware of this, because he does
not use the ‘explicatory-justificatory’ distinction. Therefore, the
‘justificatory’ is conceptually prior – a philosopher looks for justification –
hardly to render stuff plain – “Quite the opposite: my claim to fame is to
follow the alleged professional duty of a philosophy professor: to render
obscure what is clear, and vice versa!” -- motivational explanation -- a type
of explanation of goal-directed behavior where the explanans appeals to the
motives of the agent. The explanation usually is in the following form: Smith
swam hard in order to win the race. Here the description of what Smith did
identifies the behavior to be explained, and the phrase that follows ‘in order
to’ identifies the goal or the state of affairs the obtaining of which was the
moving force behind the behavior. The general presumption is that the agent
whose behavior is being explained is capable of deliberating and acting on the
decisions reached as a result of the deliberation. Thus, it is dubious whether
the explanation contained in ‘The plant turned toward the sun in order to
receive more light’ is a motivational explanation. Two problems are thought to
surround motivational explanations. First, since the state of affairs set as
the goal is, at the time of the action, non-existent, it can only act as the
“moving force” by appearing as the intentional object of an inner psychological
state of the agent. Thus, motives are generally desires for specific objects or
states of affairs on which the agent acts. So motivational explanation is
basically the type of explanation provided in folk psychology, and as such it
inherits all the alleged problems of the latter. And second, what counts as a
motive for an action under one description usually fails to be a motive for the
same action under a different description. My motive for saying “hello” may
have been my desire to answer the phone, but my motive for saying “hello”
loudly was to express my irritation at the person calling me so late at
night.
Motus – motivus – “Obligation cashes on
motivation.” Grice, “Must our motives be impure?” -- motivational internalism, the view that moral
motivation is internal to moral duty or the sense of duty. The view represents
the contemporary understanding of Hume’s thesis that morality is essentially
practical. Hume went on to point out the apparent logical gap between
statements of fact, which express theoretical judgments, and statements about
what ought to be done, which express practical judgments. Motivational
internalism offers one explanation for this gap. No motivation is internal to
the recognition of facts. The specific internal relation the view affirms is
that of necessity. Thus, motivational internalists hold that if one sees that
one has a duty to do a certain action or that it would be right to do it, then
necessarily one has a motive to do it. For example, if one sees that it is one’s
duty to donate blood, then necessarily one has a motive to donate blood.
Motivational externalism, the opposing view, denies this relation. Its
adherents hold that it is possible for one to see that one has a duty to do a
certain action or that it would be right to do it yet have no motive to do it.
Motivational externalists typically, though not universally, deny any real gap
between theoretical and practical judgments. Motivational internalism takes
either of two forms, rationalist and anti-rationalist. Rationalists, such as
Plato and Kant, hold that the content or truth of a moral requirement
guarantees in those who understand it a motive of compliance.
Anti-rationalists, such as Hume, hold that moral judgment necessarily has some
affective or volitional component that supplies a motive for the relevant
action but that renders morality less a matter of reason and truth than of
feeling or commitment. It is also possible in the abstract to draw an analogous
distinction between two forms of motivational externalism, cognitivist and
noncognitivist, but because the view springs from an interest in assimilating
practical judgment to theoretical judgment, its only influential form has been
cognitivist.
mystische -- mystical
experience, an experience alleged to reveal some aspect of reality not normally
accessible to sensory experience or cognition. The experience typically characterized by its profound
emotional impact on the one who experiences it, its transcendence of spatial
and temporal distinctions, its transitoriness, and its ineffability is often but not always associated with some
religious tradition. In theistic religions, mystical experiences are claimed to
be brought about by God or by some other superhuman agent. Theistic mystical
experiences evoke feelings of worshipful awe. Their content can vary from
something no more articulate than a feeling of closeness to God to something as
specific as an item of revealed theology, such as, for a Christian mystic, a
vision of the Trinity. Non-theistic mystical experiences are usually claimed to
reveal the metaphysical unity of all things and to provide those who experience
them with a sense of inner peace or bliss. mystische -- ystic -- mysticism, a
doctrine or discipline maintaining that one can gain knowledge of reality that
is not accessible to sense perception or to rational, conceptual thought.
Generally associated with a religious tradition, mysticism can take a theistic
form, as it has in Jewish, Christian, and Islamic traditions, or a non-theistic
form, as it has in Buddhism and some varieties of Hinduism. Mystics claim that
the mystical experience, the vehicle of mystic
knowledge, is usually the result of spiritual training, involving some
combination of prayer, meditation, fasting, bodily discipline, and renunciation
of worldly concerns. Theistic varieties of mysticism describe the mystical
experience as granted by God and thus not subject to the control of the mystic.
Although theists claim to feel closeness to God during the mystical experience,
they regard assertions of identity of the self with God as heretical.
Non-theistic varieties are more apt to describe the experience as one that can
be induced and controlled by the mystic and in which distinctions between the
self and reality, or subject and object, are revealed to be illusory. Mystics
claim that, although veridical, their experiences cannot be adequately
described in language, because ordinary communication is based on sense
experience and conceptual differentiation: mystical writings are thus
characterized by metaphor and simile. It is con 593 troversial whether all mystical
experiences are basically the same, and whether the apparent diversity among
them is the result of interpretations influenced by different cultural
traditions. H. P. Grice, “Vitters and the mystic,” Luigi Speranza, “Vitters und
das mystische,” per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming Pool Library, Villa
Grice, Liguria, Italia.
myth: Grice was aware of Grice, the Welsh philosopher. For Grice
had turned a ‘myth,’ the myth of the compact, into a thing that would justify
moral obligation – When Grice, the Englishman, gives a mythical account of
communication, alla Plato and Paget, he faces the same problem – which he hopes
is “very minor,” compared to others. In this case, it’s not about ‘moral
obligation’ but about “something else.” Grice was possibly motivated by Quine’s
irreverent, “The mth of meaning,” a talk at France, “Le mythe de la
signification.” It’s odd that he gives the example of a ‘social contract’,
developed by G. R. Grice as a ‘myth’ as his own on ‘expressing pain.’ “My
succession of stages is a methodological myth designed to exhibit the
conceptual link between expression and communication. Rather than Plato, he
appeals to Rawls and the myth of the social conpact! Grice knows a little about
Descartess “Discours de la methode,” and he is also aware of similar obsession by
Collingwood with philosopical methodology. Grice would joke on midwifery, as
the philosopher’s apter method at Oxford: to strangle error at its birth. Grice
typifies a generation at Oxford. While he did not socialize with the crème de
la crème in pre-war Oxford, he shared some their approach. E.g. a love affair
with Russell’s logical construction. After the war, and in retrospect, Grice
liked to associate himself with Austin. He obviously felt the need to belong to
a group, to make a difference, to make history. Many participants of the play group
saw themselves as doing philosophy, rather than reading about it! It was long
after that Grice started to note the differences in methodology between Austin
and himself. His methodology changed a little. He was enamoured with formalism
for a while, and he grants that this love never ceased. In a still later phase,
he came to realise that his way of doing philosophy was part of literature
(essay writing). And so he started to be slightly more careful about his style
– which some found florid. The stylistic concerns were serious. Oxonian
philosophers like Holloway had been kept away from philosophy because of the
stereotype that the Oxonian philosophers style is pedantic, when it neednt! A
philosopher should be allowed, as Plato was, to use a myth, if he thinks his
tutee will thank him for that! Grice loved to compare his Oxonian dialectic
with Platos Athenian (strictly, Academic) dialectic. Indeed, there is some
resemblance of the use of myth in Plato and Grice for philosophical
methodological purposes. Grice especially enjoys a myth in his programme in
philosophical psychology. In this, he is very much being a philosopher.
Non-philosophers usually criticise this methodological use of a myth, but they
would, wouldnt they. Grice suggests that a myth has diagogic relevance.
Creature construction, the philosopher as demi-god, if mythical, is an easier
way for a philosophy don to instil his ideas on his tutee than, say, privileged
access and incorrigibility. myth of Er, a tale at the end of Plato’s Republic
dramatizing the rewards of justice and philosophy by depicting the process of
reincarnation. Complementing the main argument of the work, that it is
intrinsically better to be just than unjust, this longest of Plato’s myths
blends traditional lore with speculative cosmology to show that justice also
pays, usually in life and certainly in the afterlife. Er, a warrior who revived
shortly after death, reports how judges assign the souls of the just to heaven
but others to punishment in the underworld, and how most return after a
thousand years to behold the celestial order, to choose their next lives, and
to be born anew. Refs.: The main source is Grice’s essay on ‘myth’, in The H.
P. Grice Papers, BANC.
N
N: SUBJECT
INDEX: NATURA
N: NAME INDEX: ITALIAN
NEGRI
N: NAME INDEX: ITALIAN
NEGRI
NICOLETTI
NOCE
N:
NAME INDEX: ENGLISHMEN (Oxonian philosophy dons)
NOWELL-SMITH
naso del
camello – thing edge of the wedge -- argumentum ad domino: slippery slope argument, an argument that an action
apparently unobjectionable in itself would set in motion a train of events
leading ultimately to an undesirable outcome. The metaphor portrays one on the
edge of a slippery slope, where taking the first step down will inevitably
cause sliding to the bottom. For example, it is sometimes argued that voluntary
euthanasia should not be legalized because this will lead to killing unwanted
people, e.g. the handicapped or elderly, against their will. In some versions
the argument aims to show that one should intervene to stop an ongoing train of
events; e.g., it has been argued that suppressing a Communist revolution in one
country was necessary to prevent the spread of Communism throughout a whole
region via the so-called domino effect. Slippery slope arguments with dubious
causal assumptions are often classed as fallacies under the general heading of
the fallacy of the false cause. This argument is also sometimes called the
wedge argument. There is some disagreement concerning the breadth of the
category of slippery slope arguments. Some would restrict the term to arguments
with evaluative conclusions, while others construe it more broadly so as to
include other sorites arguments.
natura: natura – natura humana -- human nature
– Grice distinguishes very sharply between a human and a person – a human
becomes a person via transubstantiation, a metaphysical routine – human nature
is a quality or group of qualities, belonging to all and only humans, that
explains the kind of being we are. We are all two-footed and featherless, but
‘featherless biped’ does not explain our socially significant characteristics.
We are also all both animals and rational beings (at least potentially), and
‘rational animal’ might explain the special features we have that other kinds
of beings, such as angels, do not. The belief that there is a human nature is
part of the wider thesis that all natural kinds have essences. Acceptance of
this position is compatible with many views about the specific qualities that
constitute human nature. In addition to rationality and embodiment,
philosophers have said that it is part of our nature to be wholly
selfinterested, benevolent, envious, sociable, fearful of others, able to speak
and to laugh, and desirous of immortality. Philosophers disagree about how we
are to discover our nature. Some think metaphysical insight into eternal forms
or truths is required, others that we can learn it from observation of biology
or of behavior. Most have assumed that only males display human nature fully,
and that females, even at their best, are imperfect or incomplete exemplars.
Philosophers also disagree on whether human nature determines morality. Some
think that by noting our distinctive features we can infer what God wills us to
do. Others think that our nature shows at most the limits of what morality can
require, since it would plainly be pointless to direct us to ways of living
that our nature makes impossible. Some philosophers have argued that human
nature is plastic and can be shaped in different ways. Others hold that it is
not helpful to think in terms of human nature. They think that although we
share features as members of a biological species, our other qualities are
socially constructed. If the differences between male and female reflect
cultural patterns of child rearing, work, and the distribution of power, our
biologically common features do not explain our important characteristics and
so do not constitute a nature. Grice -- Grice: beyond the natural/non-natural
distinction ABSTRACT. When we
approach, with Grice, the philosophical question involved in what we may call
the ‘natural’/ ‘non-natural’ distinction, various conceptual possibilities are
open to us. In this contribution, after providing a a historical survey of the
distinction with special focus on its
treatment by Grice, I offer a thesis which, echoing Bennett, I label
‘meaning-naturalism.’ Keywords: H.
Paul Grice, meaning, naturalism, non-natural meaning Introduction
Grice sees his approach to ‘meaning’ (or “meaning that …”, as he would
rather put it) as ‘rhapsody on a theme by Peirce.’ When he presents his “Meaning” to the Oxford
Philosophical Society (only to be published almost a decade later by The Philosophical
Review), Grice endows the philosophical community with a full-blown
‘natural’/‘non-natural’ distinction, for which he has naturally become somewhat
infamously famous, as when a philosopher, exploring the different causes of
death of this or that other philosopher cites Grice as having passed of
‘non-natural causes.’ What is Grice’s
‘natural’/‘non-natural’ distinction about?
As a member of the so-called ‘Oxford school of “ordinary-language”
philosophy’ (he disliked the sobriquet), Grice seems initially to have been
concerned with what at a later stage he calls a ‘pre-theoretical’ exploration
of this or that use of the lexeme ‘mean,’ notably by Peirce. Grice finds Peirce’s attempt to ‘replace’ the
vernacular Anglo-Saxon ‘mean’ with ‘krypto-technical’ jargon as not too
sympathetic to these or those Oxonian ears. So, it is this lexeme, or
‘expression,’ ‘mean,’ to which Grice’s distinction applies. Carefully, as Bennett would point out, using
lower-case ‘x’ and ‘y’ for tokens, Grice attempts to formulate the distinction into two separate
super-expressions, where the sub-expression “means that …” occurs: i. x
meansN that p. ii. x meansNN that q. What is ‘x’? Grice spends some time on this
double-edged elucidation (and indeed, the ‘that’-clause explication is a later
vintage). He grants that his main focus of concern is with (ii). In passing, he
makes some rather intriguing running commentary. It’s clear why Grice feels the need to spend
some time in explicating what he is about to do. Grice’s distinction, as he
formulates it, is supposed to ‘refine’ this or that distinction, made by this
or that philosopher. While ‘ordinary-language’ philosophers are taken as
approaching ‘ordinary-language,’ their underlying motivation is to criticise
this or that philosopher’s mischaracterisation of the linguistic nuance at
hand. Grice’s avowed aim in his talk to
the Oxford Philosophical Society is to shed light on, to use his
characteristically cavalier wording, ‘what people have been thinking,’ which in
that context, means ‘what other philosophers have been thinking’ – including
Ayer -- or even getting at, ‘when they speak of such things as “natural” versus
“conventional” signs.’ Grice thinks
that, by his sticking with ‘meaning that …’ (rather than ‘sign’) and
‘non-natural’ (rather ‘conventional’) he is setting a better scene. Why would
this be a conceptual improvement? Grice gives two reasons. First, and again, Grice presents himself as a
representative of the Oxonian school of ‘ordinary-language’ philosophy, and
exercising what these philosophers referred to this or that adventure in
‘linguistic botany.’ Grice thus sets to explore, introspectively, relying on
his intuitions behind his own usage, philosophical and other: a ‘word,’ for
example, Grice notes, he would not naturally describe as a ‘sign.’ In Grice’s
(but surely not Peirce’s) idio-lect, the expression ‘sign’ is restricted to
things like a traffic signal, say.
Second, and again in this adventure in ‘linguistic-botany,’ x (or
strictly ‘a,’ for ‘agent,’ now) that can ‘mean’ that p, in a way that is
specifically NON-factive (as he’ll later put it, echoing the Kiparskys) but
which need not be ‘conventional.’ Grice gives the example of ‘a gesture,’ which
a few philosophers would associate with Sraffa’s! The historical background Grice’s cavalier reference to ‘what people
are getting at’ sounds charmingly Oxonian. He surely has no intention to
underestimate the knowledge of the fellow members of The Oxford Philosophical
Society. He won’t be seen as ‘going to lecture’ them. This is not a seminar,
but a public occasion. He is allowed to be a cavalier. Had this been a seminar, and being indeed a
Lit. Hum. Oxon., Grice knows he can trace the distinction he is making, as he
refines alternative ones, to Plato’s Cratylus, where we have Socrates and his
dialogical companion playing with various adverbial modifiers, notably,
‘phusei’ and ‘thesei.’ Plato’s ‘phusei,’
surely translates to Grice’s ‘nature’ in ‘natural.’ Plato is carefully in
avoiding the subsantive nominative ‘phusis.’ His ‘phusei’ is meant to modify
the way something may such may be said to ‘mean’ (‘semein’). Possibly the
earliest incarnation of what later will be dubbed as the ‘pooh’ pooh theory of
language. Plato’s ‘thesei’ is slightly
more complicated. It is best to stay lexically conservative here and understand
it to mean, ‘by position,’ i.e. or, in Grice’s freer prose, by convention.
While Plato has to his disposal various other lexemes to do duty for this, he
chooses a rather weak one, and again, not in the nominative “thesis,” but as
applied to something that ‘means’ that p or q. In any case, Plato’s interest,
as indeed Grice’s, is ‘dialectic.’ That x (or a) means that q thesei, by
position, entails (as Plato would say if he could borrow from Moore) that it is
not the case that x (or a) means that q phusei, by nature. The distinction is
supposed to be absolute. The
‘phusis’/‘thesis’ distinction undergoes a fascinating development in the
philosophical tradition, from Greek (or Grecian) into Latin (Roman), and
eventually makes it to scholastic philosophy: ‘per natura’/ ‘per positionem,’
or ‘ad placitum.’ Closer to Grice,
authors partly philosophising in Grice’s vernacular, such as Hobbes, who is
indeed fighting against Latin for the the use of the vernacular in
philosophical discourse, will speak of what Grice knew would be familiar
terminology to his Oxford audience: ‘natural sign’ versus, rather than Grice’s
intentionally rather ugly-sounding ‘non-natural,’ ‘artificial’ or
‘conventional’ sign. Grice does not use
‘scare quotes,’ but perhaps Umberto Eco would have wished he did! (Indeed, it
is best to see Grice as treating ‘a means that p’ as the only ‘literal’ use of
‘mean,’ with ‘natural’ and ‘expression-relative’ uses as ‘derivative, or
transferred, or figurative. While he does NOT use ‘scare quotes’ for his
examples of ‘meanN,’ as in iii. iii.
Smoke means that there is fire. Grice
cares to quote in the talk from just one rather recent philosopher who was being
discussed at Oxford in connection with A. J. Ayer’s approach to ‘moral’ language
as being merely ‘emotive.’ Grice makes
an explicit reference to Stevenson. While Grice finds Stevenson’s account of
the ‘non-natural’ use of “mean” ‘circular’ (in that it relies on conditioning
related to ‘communication,’ Stevenson explores various ‘natural’ uses of
‘mean’, and, to emphasise the figurative status, explicitly employs ‘scare
quotes.’ For Stevenson, (iii) becomes (iv).
iv. Smoke ‘means’ that there is fire.
For surely ‘smoke’ cannot have an intention – and ‘mean’ is too close to
‘intend’ in the Anglo-Saxon vernacular to allow smoke to mean that p or q –
‘mean’ at most. This is crucial (and suggests just one way of the figuration of
‘mean,’ that will go two ways with Grice when he sees this figuration as
applying to ‘expression-relative’ uses of ‘mean,’ as in v.
‘There’s smoke’ ‘means’ that there’s smoke. (Ubi fumus ibi ignis). By carefully deploying
scare-quotes, Stevenson is fighting against ‘animism.’ The root of ‘mean’ is
cognate with Latin ‘mentare’ and ‘mentire,’ and can notably be traced back to
‘mens,’ the mind. Surely smoke cannot really (if we must use one of those
adverbs that Austin called ‘trouser words’) that there is fire – just ‘mean’
it. A careful ‘utterer’ is using the same lexeme in an obviously ‘figurative’
way, and marking this fact explicitly by appealing to an ‘echoic,’ or as Grice
may prefer, ‘trans-categorial,’ use. The
‘fun’ side to this (and for Grice, ‘philosophy need be fun’) is that Grice’s
distinction then becomes now the ‘non-natural’/‘natural’ distinction. Scare
quotes signal that the realm of ‘mean’ is the realm of the ‘mind,’ and not what
Plato might have seen as the realm of nature simpliciter. But back to Hobbes. Indeed, Hobbes may be
drawing on the earlier explorations on this in Latin, by, of all people,
Ockham, who speaks now of scenarios where ‘significare’ is modified by the
adverb ‘naturaliter,’ and scenarios where it is not. For this or that example of what Grice has as
the ‘natural’ use of ‘mean’, Ockham will stick with ‘significare,’ qualified by
‘naturaliter.’ vi. By smiling, Smith
means that he is happy. Or as Ockham
more generically puts it, vii. Risus
‘significat’ naturaliter interiorem laetitiam.
But Ockham can go pretty Griceian too, as when he wonders about a
‘circulus’ – of a wine barrel ‘artificially’ (or not ‘naturaliter’) placed, or
positioned, outside a building, yielding:
viii. Circulus ‘significat’ naturaliter vinum. The circle, even if artificially (or at least
not naturally) placed, is a ‘sign’ or means that wine which is being sold
inside the building (Ockham is playing with the composite nature of
‘significare,’ literally to ‘make sign’). In the Peirceian theme on which Grice
offers his rhapsody, and which he’ll later adopt in his “Retrospective
epilogue,” there is an iconicity involved in the ‘circulus’ scenario, where
this ‘iconicity’ requires some conceptual elucidation. Ockham’s use of the Latin ‘significare’
poses a further question. Strictly, of course, is to ‘make’ (‘ficare’) a sign.
Therefore, Grice feels its Latinate counterpart, ‘signifies that…’ as too
strong a way to qualify a thing like an expression (or ‘word,’) which for him
may not be a sign at all. Grice’s
cavalier attitude and provocative intent is further evidenced by the fact that,
years later, when delivering the William James lectures at Harvard, and
refining his “Meaning,” he does mention that his programme is concerned with
the elucidation of the ‘total signification’ of a remark as uttered by this or
that utterer, into this or that variety of this or that explicit and implicit
component. When Grice refers to “what
people are thinking,” he is aware that Hobbes more or less maintains the Ockham
(or ‘Occam,’ in Grice’s preferred spelling) paradigm, both in his work written
in his late scholastic Latin (“Computatio, sive logica”) and the vernacular
(“Leviathan”) which almost marks the beginning of so-called, by Sorley,
“English philosophy.” With the coming of
empiricism, with Locke’s Essay (1690), and later Mill’s “System of Logic
(mandatory reading at Oxford for the Lit. Hum. degree – “more Grice to the
Mill,” Grice will put it) it seems obvious that the tradition in which Grice is
immersed is not strange to ‘naturalism.’
“Nature” itself, as Plato already knew, need not be hypostasized. It is a
fascinating fact that, for years, Oxford infamously kept two different chairs
for the philosopher: one of ‘natural’ philosophy, and the Waynflete chair of
‘meta-physical philosophy,’ where ‘metaphysical’ is merely an obscure way of
referring to the ‘trans-natural.’ Or is it the other way around? Few empiricist philosophers need to postulate
the ‘unity’ (less so, the uniformity) of “Nature,” even if this or that
Griceians will later will. Witness Nancy Cartwright in the festschrift for
Grice edited by Grandy and Warner for Clarendon, Philosophical Grounds of
Rationality: Intentions, Categories, Ends (or “G. R. I. C. E.,” for short):
‘how the laws of nature lie.’ In its
simplest formulation, which should do for the purposes of this contribution,
the philosophical thesis of ‘naturalism’ may be understood as positing an
ontological continuum between this or that allegation concerning ‘Nature’ and
what is not nature (‘art,’ as in ‘artifice’).
And then, Grice comes to revisit “Meaning.” In 1976, Grice gets invited to a symposium at
Brighton and resumes his 1948 vintage ‘natural’/‘non-natural’ distinction. He
had more or less kept it all through the William James lectures. At Brighton,
Grice adds some crucial elaborations, in terms of what he now calls ‘philosophical
psychology’ (Surely he doesn’t want to be seen as a ‘scientific’ psychologist).
The audience is a different one, and not purely philosophical, so he can be
cavalier and provocative in a different way.
While in his talk on “Meaning” for the Oxford Philosophical Society
Grice had, rather casually, referred to this or that application, collocation,
or occurrence, of the lexeme ‘mean’ as being this or that (Fregeian) ‘sense’ of
the lexeme ‘mean’ -- and thus yielding ‘mean’ as, strictly, polysemous -- he
now feels it’s time to weaken the claim to this or that (Ryleian) ‘use,’ not
(Fregeian) ‘sense,’ of “mean.” His
motivation is obvious, and can be brought back a point he makes in his third
William James lectures, and which in fact underlies his philosophical
methodology regarding other philosophers’ mistakes when dealing with this or
that linguistic nuance. If you are going to be Occamist, ‘senses,’ as specific
entities, are not be multiplied beyond necessity.’ Grice is playing the
etymological game here, concerning ‘mean’ (mens, mind). His example, in
“Meaning revisited,” concerns Smith as ‘being caught in the grip of a
vyse/vice.’ The root in both ‘vice’ and ‘vyse’ – Latin ‘vim’ – is cognate with
‘violence’ and gives two lexemes in Grice’s vernacular: one applies to
something like a carpenter’s tool, and the other to the opposite of a virtue.
Grice wants to explore how the ‘natural’/ ‘non-natural’ distinction may compare
to the ‘vyse’/‘vice’ distinction. With ‘vice,’ Grice suggests, we have, in his
vernacular, as opposed to Latin, two different lexemes (even if ultimately from
a common Latin root, ‘vim,’ which surely mitigates the case for polysemy). But
with ‘mean,’ that’s surely that’s not the case. The ultimate root is that of
‘mens,’ mind, and there’s no spelling difference to deal with. Grice does not reverse the order of the terms
in his ‘natural’/’non-natural’ distinction, though, as Eco would (“a sign is
something you can use to lie”). Rather, he allows for this or that loose, or
figurative, or ‘disimplicatural’ use of “means ….” His craving for a further
philosophical generality justifies his disimplicature. This generality is of
two kinds, one of which he deem thems ‘conceptual,’ or ‘methodological,’ and
the other ‘mythic.’ The ‘conceptual’ or
methodological manoevure is ontological in flavour. If there is a common core
that both our (i) and (ii) above share, it should be rephrasable by a neutral
form for both the ‘natural’ and the ‘non-natural’ scenario: ix. p
is a consequence of x/a ‘Consequentia’
is exactly the term used by Hobbes (some would prefer post-sequentia) when
considering the generic concept of a ‘sign.’ It is thus very apt of Hacking (in
his “Why does language matter to philosophy?”) to see Hobbes as a pre-Griceian
(or is it, Grice as a post-Hobbesian?)
When it comes to ‘naturalism’ proper, we have to be careful in our
exegesis of it as label for this or that philosophical overarching thesis. When
reminiscing about his progress to ‘The City of the Eternal Truth,’ in his
parody of Bunyan’s, pilgrim Grice meets face to face with the monster of
“Naturalism.” One may see this as
Grice’s warning against some trends he found in The New World, ‘the devil of
scientism,’ as he called it, towards ‘reductionism’ and ‘eliminationism,’ as
flourishing in the idea that a ‘final cause’ is ‘mechanistically reducible.’ In
Grice’s philosophical psychology, ‘Naturalism’ for Grice, amounts to rejecting
this or that psychological law when this or that physiological law already
explains the same phenomenon. Grice finds that his Occamism for ‘mean’ is not
enough here and fangles an ‘ontological marxism’: this or that entity (an
autonomous rational soul, say) that seems to go against naturalism may be
justified, ‘provided they help with the house-work’ the philosopher is engaged
in, in this case, and into the bargain, saving the philosopher’s
existence. The spirit, however, if not
the letter, of ‘naturalism’ as a grand philosophical thesis still survives.
Grice regards himself as ultimately a ‘constructivist.’ The realm of his
‘non-natural’ needs to be rooted in a previous realm of the ‘natural.’ He
suggest here a ‘genitorially justified’ ‘myth’ for the ‘natural’/‘non-natural’
distinction: x. a meaninngNN that q derives
from x meaningN that p Grice is
exploring ‘emergence’ as a viable concept in philosophical psychology.
Philosophical psychology is thus rooted in philosophical ethology. This or that
psychological (or souly) state, (or attitude, or stance) may be understood as
emerging from (or supervening on) a mere biological and ultimately physical (i.
e. natural) state. (He is clear about that in his “Intention and uncertainty,”
when, adopting the concept of ‘willing that’ from Prichard, he allows it to be
amenable to a ‘physicalist’ treatment).
In his presidential address to the American Philosophical Association,
Grice feels the need to creates a new philosophical sub-discipline, which he,
echoing Carnap, christens ‘pirotology.’
Grice’s ‘pirotology’ concern Carnap’s ‘pirot,’ that ‘karulises
elatically’ in his “Introduction to Semantics.” Grice adds a nod to Locke’s
reflection on Prince Maurice’s ‘parot’ being “very intelligent, and rational.”
The pirotological justification of the ‘natural’/‘non-natural’ distinction
involves three stages. The first stage
in the sequence or series involves the pirot, P1, as a merely physical (or
purely ‘natural’) entity, P1. The second
stage involves our ‘natural’ pirot giving way to the emergence, pretty much
alla Nicolai Hartmann, of a now bio-logical pirot P2 (a ‘human’), endowed with
the goal of survival and adaptation to its natural environment. The third and last stage sees our P2
‘re-constituting’ itself as now a psycho-logical pirot P3, as a ‘person’, endowed
with a higher type of ‘soul.’ (Grice is following Aristotle’s progression in
“De anima.” Grice carefully avoids the
use of ‘mind,’ in what he felt was an over-use by philosophers in the
discipline of ‘mental philosophy,’ as it is referred to at Oxford in connection
with Wilde. As a Kantotelian, Grice sees the biological pirot P2 as having a
‘soul,’ even if not a rational one. Grice was fascinated by Aristotle’s insight
that, ‘soul,’ like ‘figure’ or ‘number,’ is a concept that cannot be defined by
‘genus,’ but only within this or that ‘series,’ such as the three-stage one he
provides from the ‘natural’ to the ‘non-natural’ pirot. It is thus no easy exegetic task to make
sense of Grice’s somewhat rhetorical antipathy towards ‘Naturalism,’ but I
shall leave that as an open question.
Beyond the distinction? In the
end, for Grice, the key-word is not ‘culture,’ as opposed to ‘nature,’ but
‘rationality,’ as displayed by our ‘non-natural’ pirot P3. Rationality becomes
the philosopher’s main concern, as it is conceptualized to develop from this or
that pre-rational propension, which is biological and ultimately physical, i.e.
natural. Grice’s exploration on the
‘natural’/ ‘non-natural’ distinction thus agrees with a very naturalistic
approaches to things like adaptation and survival in a natural environment, and
the evolution of altruism (a ‘talking pirot’ who transfers his psychological
attitude to another pirot). While his
tone remains distinctively philosophical – and indeed displaying what he
thought as a bit of ‘irreverent, conservative, dissenting rationalism,’ by his
example he has indeed shown that the philosopher’s say has a relevance that no
other discipline can provide. REFERENCES
Grice, H. P. (1948). ‘Meaning,’ repr. in Studies in the Way of Words. Grice, H. P. (1975). ‘Method in philosophical
psychology: from the banal to the bizarre,’ Proceedings and Addresses of the
American Philosophical Association, repr. in Grice, 1991. Grice, H. P. (1976). ‘Meaning revisited,’
repr. in Studies in the Way of Words.
Grice, H. P. (1986). ‘Reply to Richards,’ in Richard Grandy and Richard
Warner, Philosophical Grounds of Rationality: Intentions, Categories, Ends.
Oxord: The Clarendon Press. Grice, H. P.
(1991). The conception of value. Oxford: The Clarendon Press. Hacking, I. M. (1977). Why does language
matter to philosophy? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hobbes, Thomas. Computatio sive logica. Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. Locke, John. A theory concerning humane [sic]
understanding. Mellor, D. H. (n.d.)
‘Causes of deaths of philosophers’ (accessed February 20th, 2020)
https://www.phil.cam.ac.uk/people/teaching-research-pages/mellor/dhm11/deaths-dg.html Mill, J. S. A system of logic. London:
Macmillan. Ockham, William. Theory of
signs. Pietarinen, Ahti-Veikko and
Francesco Bellucci (2016). ‘H. Paul Grice’s Lecture Notes on Charles S.
Peirce’s Theory of Signs,’ International Review of Pragmatics,
8(1):82-129. Sorley, W. R. (1920). A
history of English philosophy. Cambridge. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Natural and
non-natural, and naturalism.”
NECESSE
-- necessitatum: ananke,
when feeling very Grecian, Grice would use ‘ananke,’ instead of ‘must,’ which
he thought too English! Grecian, necessity. The term was used by early Grecian
philosophers for a constraining or moving natural force. In Parmenides frg. 8,
line 30 ananke encompasses reality in limiting bonds; according to Diogenes
Laertius, Democrianamnesis ananke 27 4065A-
27 tus calls the vortex that generates the cosmos ananke; Plato Timaeus
47e ff. refers to ananke as the irrational element in nature, which reason
orders in creating the physical world. As used by Aristotle Metaphysics V.5,
the basic meaning of ‘necessary’ is ‘that which cannot be otherwise’, a sense
that includes logical necessity. He also distinguishes Physics II.9 between
simple and hypothetical necessity conditions that must hold if something is to
occur. necesse – Grice: “The archaic Romans had ‘necessum,’ which they turned
to ‘necessum.’ The etymology is not clear [perh. Sanscr. naç, obtain; Gr. root ἐνεκ-; cf. ἀνάγκη; v. Georg
Curtius Gr. Etym. 424]. ichthyological necessity: topic-neutral:
Originally, Ryle’s term for logical constants, such as “of ” “not,” “every.”
They are not endowed with special meanings, and are applicable to discourse
about any subject-matter. They do not refer to any external object but function
to organize meaningful discourse. J. J. C. Smart calls a term topic-neutral if
it is noncommittal about designating something mental or something physical.
Instead, it simply describes an event without judging the question of its
intrinsic nature. In his central-state theory of mind, Smart develops a
topic-neutral analysis of mental expressions and argues that it is possible to
account for the situations described by mental concepts in purely physical and
topic-neutral terms. “In this respect, statements like ‘I am thinking now’ are,
as J. J. C. Smart puts it, topic-neutral. They say that something is going on
within us, something apt for the causing of certain sorts of behaviour, but
they say nothing of the nature of this process.” D. Armstrong, A Materialist
Theory of the Mind
nicoletti -- paolo di
venezia: philosopher, the son of Andrea Nicola, of Venice – He was born in
Fliuli Venezia Giulia, a hermit of Saint Augustine O.E.S.A., he spent three
years as a student at St. John’s, where the order of St. Augustine had a
‘studium generale,’ at Oxford and taught at Padova, where he became a doctor of
arts. Paolo also held appointments at the universities of Parma, Siena, and
Bologna. Paolo is active in the administration of his order, holding various
high offices. He composed ommentaries on several logical, ethical, and physical
works of Aristotle. His name is connected especially with his best-selling
“Logica parva.” Over 150 manuscripts survive, and more than forty printed
editions of it were made, His huge
sequel, “Logica magna,” was a flop. These Oxford-influenced tracts contributed
to the favorable climate enjoyed by Oxonian semantics in northern Italian
universities. Grice: “My favourite of Paul’s tracts is his “Sophismata aurea” –
how peaceful for a philosopher to die while commentingon Aristotle’s “De
anima.”!” His nom de plum is “Paulus Venetus.”-- Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Paolo
da Harborne, and Paolo da Venezia,”
lecture for the Club Griceiano Anglo-Italiano, Bordighera.
NATURA -- natural intelligence --
artificial (or non-natural) intelligence, also called AI, the scientific effort
to design and build intelligent artifacts. Grice disliked the phrase
“artificial intelligence.” “Strictly, what Minsky means is ‘non-natural’
intelligence.’”Since the effort inevitably presupposes and tests theories about
the nature of intelligence, it has implications for the philosophy of mind perhaps even more than does empirical
psychology. For one thing, actual construction amounts to a direct assault on
the mindbody problem; should it succeed, some form of materialism would seem to
be vindicated. For another, a working model, even a limited one, requires a
more global conception of what intelligence is than do experiments to test
specific hypotheses. In fact, psychology’s own overview of its domain Arouet,
François-Marie artificial intelligence 53
53 has been much influenced by fundamental concepts drawn from AI.
Although the idea of an intelligent artifact is old, serious scientific
research dates only from the 0s, and is associated with the development of
programmable computers. Intelligence is understood as a structural property or
capacity of an active system; i.e., it does not matter what the system is made
of, as long as its parts and their interactions yield intelligent behavior
overall. For instance, if solving logical problems, playing chess, or
conversing in English manifests intelligence, then it is not important whether
the “implementation” is electronic, biological, or mechanical, just as long as
it solves, plays, or talks. Computers are relevant mainly because of their
flexibility and economy: software systems are unmatched in achievable active
complexity per invested effort. Despite the generality of programmable
structures and the variety of historical approaches to the mind, the bulk of AI
research divides into two broad camps
which we can think of as language-oriented and pattern-oriented,
respectively. Conspicuous by their absence are significant influences from the
conditionedresponse paradigm, the psychoanalytic tradition, the mental picture
idea, empiricist atomistic associationism, and so on. Moreover, both AI camps
tend to focus on cognitive issues, sometimes including perception and motor
control. Notably omitted are such psychologically important topics as affect,
personality, aesthetic and moral judgment, conceptual change, mental illness,
etc. Perhaps such matters are beyond the purview of artificial intelligence;
yet it is an unobvious substantive thesis that intellect can be cordoned off
and realized independently of the rest of human life. The two main AI paradigms
emerged together in the 0s along with cybernetic and information-theoretic
approaches, which turned out to be dead ends; and both are vigorous today. But
for most of the sixties and seventies, the language-based orientation dominated
attention and funding, for three signal reasons. First, computer data
structures and processes themselves seemed languagelike: data were
syntactically and semantically articulated, and processing was localized
serial. Second, twentieth-century linguistics and logic made it intelligible
that and how such systems might work: automatic symbol manipulation made clear,
powerful sense. Finally, the sorts of performance most amenable to the
approach explicit reasoning and
“figuring out” strike both popular and
educated opinion as particularly “intellectual”; hence, early successes were
all the more impressive, while “trivial” stumbling blocks were easier to
ignore. The basic idea of the linguistic or symbol manipulation camp is that
thinking is like talking inner
discourse and, hence, that thoughts are
like sentences. The suggestion is venerable; and Hobbes even linked it
explicitly to computation. Yet, it was a major scientific achievement to turn
the general idea into a serious theory. The account does not apply only, or
even especially, to the sort of thinking that is accessible to conscious
reflection. Nor is the “language of thought” supposed to be much like English,
predicate logic, LISP, or any other familiar notation; rather, its detailed
character is an empirical research problem. And, despite fictional stereotypes,
the aim is not to build superlogical or inhumanly rational automata. Our human
tendencies to take things for granted, make intuitive leaps, and resist
implausible conclusions are not weaknesses that AI strives to overcome but
abilities integral to real intelligence that AI aspires to share. In what
sense, then, is thought supposed to be languagelike? Three items are essential.
First, thought tokens have a combinatorial syntactic structure; i.e., they are
compounds of welldefined atomic constituents in well-defined recursively
specifiable arrangements. So the constituents are analogous to words, and the
arrangements are analogous to phrases and sentences; but there is no supposition
that they should resemble any known words or grammar. Second, the contents of
thought tokens, what they “mean,” are a systematic function of their
composition: the constituents and forms of combination have determinate
significances that together determine the content of any wellformed compound.
So this is like the meaning of a sentence being determined by its grammar and
the meanings of its words. Third, the intelligent progress or sequence of
thought is specifiable by rules expressed syntactically they can be carried out by processes
sensitive only to syntactic properties. Here the analogy is to proof theory:
the formal validity of an argument is a matter of its according with rules
expressed formally. But this analogy is particularly treacherous, because it
immediately suggests the rigor of logical inference; but, if intelligence is
specifiable by formal rules, these must be far more permissive,
context-sensitive, and so on, than those of formal logic. Syntax as such is
perfectly neutral as to how the constituents are identified by sound, by
artificial intelligence artificial intelligence 54 54 shape, by magnetic profile and arranged
in time, in space, via address pointers. It is, in effect, a free parameter: whatever
can serve as a bridge between the semantics and the processing. The account
shares with many others the assumptions that thoughts are contentful meaningful
and that the processes in which they occur can somehow be realized physically.
It is distinguished by the two further theses that there must be some
independent way of describing these thoughts that mediates between
simultaneously determines their contents and how they are processed, and that,
so described, they are combinatorially structured. Such a description is
syntactical. We can distinguish two principal phases in language-oriented AI,
each lasting about twenty years. Very roughly, the first phase emphasized
processing search and reasoning, whereas the second has emphasized
representation knowledge. To see how this went, it is important to appreciate
the intellectual breakthrough required to conceive AI at all. A machine, such
as a computer, is a deterministic system, except for random elements. That is
fine for perfectly constrained domains, like numerical calculation, sorting, and
parsing, or for domains that are constrained except for prescribed randomness,
such as statistical modeling. But, in the general case, intelligent behavior is
neither perfectly constrained nor perfectly constrained with a little random
variation thrown in. Rather, it is generally focused and sensible, yet also
fallible and somewhat variable. Consider, e.g., chess playing an early test bed
for AI: listing all the legal moves for any given position is a perfectly
constrained problem, and easy to program; but choosing the best move is not.
Yet an intelligent player does not simply determine which moves would be legal
and then choose one randomly; intelligence in chess play is to choose, if not
always the best, at least usually a good move. This is something between
perfect determinacy and randomness, a “between” that is not simply a mixture of
the two. How is it achievable in a machine? The crucial innovation that first
made AI concretely and realistically conceivable is that of a heuristic
procedure. The term ‘heuristic’ derives from the Grecian word for discovery, as
in Archimedes’ exclamation “Eureka!” The relevant point for AI is that
discovery is a matter neither of following exact directions to a goal nor of
dumb luck, but of looking around sensibly, being guided as much as possible by
what you know in advance and what you find along the way. So a heuristic
procedure is one for sensible discovery, a procedure for sensibly guided
search. In chess, e.g., a player does well to bear in mind a number of rules of
thumb: other things being equal, rooks are more valuable than knights, it is an
asset to control the center of the board, and so on. Such guidelines, of
course, are not valid in every situation; nor will they all be best satisfied
by the same move. But, by following them while searching as far ahead through
various scenarios as possible, a player can make generally sensible moves much better than random within the constraints of the game. This
picture even accords fairly well with the introspective feel of choosing a
move, particularly for less experienced players. The essential insight for AI
is that such roughand-ready ceteris paribus rules can be deterministically
programmed. It all depends on how you look at it. One and the same bit of
computer program can be, from one point of view, a deterministic, infallible
procedure for computing how a given move would change the relative balance of
pieces, and from another, a generally sensible but fallible procedure for
estimating how “good” that move would be. The substantive thesis about
intelligence human and artificial
alike then is that our powerful but
fallible ability to form “intuitive” hunches, educated guesses, etc., is the
result of largely unconscious search, guided by such heuristic rules. The second
phase of language-inspired AI, dating roughly from the mid-0s, builds on the
idea of heuristic procedure, but dramatically changes the emphasis. The earlier
work was framed by a conception of intelligence as finding solutions to
problems good moves, e.g.. From such a perspective, the specification of the
problem the rules of the game plus the current position and the provision of
some heuristic guides domain-specific rules of thumb are merely a setting of
the parameters; the real work, the real exercise of intelligence, lies in the
intensive guided search undertaken in the specified terms. The later phase,
impressed not so much by our problem-solving prowess as by how well we get
along with “simple” common sense, has shifted the emphasis from search and
reasoning to knowledge. The motivation for this shift can be seen in the
following two sentences: We gave the monkey the banana because it was ripe. We
gave the monkey the banana because it was hungry. artificial intelligence
artificial intelligence 55 55 The word
‘it’ is ambiguous, as the terminal adjectives make clear. Yet listeners
effortlessly understand what is meant, to the point, usually, of not even
noticing the ambiguity. The question is, how? Of course, it is “just common
sense” that monkeys don’t get ripe and bananas don’t get hungry, so . . . But
three further observations show that this is not so much an answer as a
restatement of the issue. First, sentences that rely on common sense to avoid
misunderstanding are anything but rare: conversation is rife with them. Second,
just about any odd fact that “everybody knows” can be the bit of common sense
that understanding the next sentence depends on; and the range of such
knowledge is vast. Yet, third, dialogue proceeds in real time without a hitch,
almost always. So the whole range of commonsense knowledge must be somehow at
our mental fingertips all the time. The underlying difficulty is not with speed
or quantity alone, but with relevance. How does a system, given all that it
knows about aardvarks, Alabama, and ax handles, “home in on” the pertinent fact
that bananas don’t get hungry, in the fraction of a second it can afford to
spend on the pronoun ‘it’? The answer proposed is both simple and powerful:
common sense is not just randomly stored information, but is instead highly
organized by topics, with lots of indexes, cross-references, tables,
hierarchies, and so on. The words in the sentence itself trigger the “articles”
on monkeys, bananas, hunger, and so on, and these quickly reveal that monkeys
are mammals, hence animals, that bananas are fruit, hence from plants, that
hunger is what animals feel when they need to eat and that settles it. The amount of search and
reasoning is minimal; the issue of relevance is solved instead by the
antecedent structure in the stored knowledge itself. While this requires larger
and more elaborate systems, the hope is that it will make them faster and more
flexible. The other main orientation toward artificial intelligence, the
pattern-based approach often called
“connectionism” or “parallel distributed processing” reemerged from the shadow of symbol
processing only in the 0s, and remains in many ways less developed. The basic
inspiration comes not from language or any other psychological phenomenon such
as imagery or affect, but from the microstructure of the brain. The components
of a connectionist system are relatively simple active nodes lots of them
and relatively simple connections between those nodes again, lots of them. One important type and
the easiest to visualize has the nodes divided into layers, such that each node
in layer A is connected to each node in layer B, each node in layer B is
connected to each node in layer C, and so on. Each node has an activation
level, which varies in response to the activations of other, connected nodes;
and each connection has a weight, which determines how strongly and in what
direction the activation of one node affects that of the other. The analogy
with neurons and synapses, though imprecise, is intended. So imagine a layered
network with finely tuned connection weights and random or zero activation
levels. Now suppose the activations of all the nodes in layer A are set in some
particular way some pattern is imposed
on the activation state of this layer. These activations will propagate out
along all the connections from layer A to layer B, and activate some pattern
there. The activation of each node in layer B is a function of the activations
of all the nodes in layer A, and of the weights of all the connections to it
from those nodes. But since each node in layer B has its own connections from
the nodes in layer A, it will respond in its own unique way to this pattern of
activations in layer A. Thus, the pattern that results in layer B is a joint
function of the pattern that was imposed on layer A and of the pattern of
connection weights between the two layers. And a similar story can be told
about layer B’s influence on layer C, and so on, until some final pattern is
induced in the last layer. What are these patterns? They might be any number of
things; but two general possibilities can be distinguished. They might be
tantamount to or substrata beneath representations of some familiar sort, such
as sentencelike structures or images; or they might be a kind or kinds of
representation previously unknown. Now, people certainly do sometimes think in
sentences and probably images; so, to the extent that networks are taken as
complete brain models, the first alternative must be at least partly right.
But, to that extent, the models are also more physiological than psychological:
it is rather the implemented sentences or images that directly model the mind.
Thus, it is the possibility of a new genus of representation sometimes called distributed
representation that is particularly
exciting. On this alternative, the patterns in the mind represent in some way
other than by mimetic imagery or articulate description. How? An important
feature of all network models is that there are two quite different categories
of pattern. On the one hand, there are the relatively ephemeral patterns of
activation in various artificial intelligence artificial intelligence 56 56 groups of nodes; on the other, there are
the relatively stable patterns of connection strength among the nodes. Since
there are in general many more connections than nodes, the latter patterns are
richer; and it is they that determine the capabilities of the network with
regard to the former patterns. Many of the abilities most easily and
“naturally” realized in networks can be subsumed under the heading pattern
completion: the connection weights are adjusted
perhaps via a training regime
such that the network will complete any of the activation patterns from
a predetermined group. So, suppose some fraction say half of the nodes in the
net are clamped to the values they would have for one of those patterns say P
while the remainder are given random or default activations. Then the network,
when run, will reset the latter activations to the values belonging to P thus “completing” it. If the unclamped
activations are regarded as variations or deviations, pattern completion
amounts to normalization, or grouping by similarity. If the initial or input
nodes are always the same as in layered networks, then we have pattern association
or transformation from input to output. If the input pattern is a memory probe,
pattern completion becomes access by content. If the output pattern is an
identifier, then it is pattern recognition. And so on. Note that, although the
operands are activation patterns, the “knowledge” about them, the ability to
complete them, is contained in the connection patterns; hence, that ability or
know-how is what the network represents. There is no obvious upper bound on the
possible refinement or intricacy of these pattern groupings and associations.
If the input patterns are sensory stimuli and the output patterns are motor
control, then we have a potential model of coordinated and even skillful
behavior. In a system also capable of language, a network model or component
might account for verbal recognition and content association, and even such
“nonliteral” effects as trope and tone. Yet at least some sort of “symbol
manipulation” seems essential for language use, regardless of how networklike
the implementation is. One current speculation is that it might suffice to
approximate a battery of symbolic processes as a special subsystem within a
cognitive system that fundamentally works on quite different principles. The
attraction of the pattern-based approach is, at this point, not so much actual
achievement as it is promise on two
grounds. In the first place, the space of possible models, not only network
topologies but also ways of construing the patterns, is vast. Those built and
tested so far have been, for practical reasons, rather small; so it is possible
to hope beyond their present limitations to systems of significantly greater
capability. But second, and perhaps even more attractive, those directions in
which patternbased systems show the most promise skills, recognition, similarity, and the
like are among the areas of greatest
frustration for languagebased AI. Hence it remains possible, for a while at
least, to overlook the fact that, to date, no connectionist network can perform
long division, let alone play chess or solve symbolic logic problems. Refs.: H.
P. Grice, “Intelligence: natural and non-natural.”
Natura – natura-ars distinction -- natural
life -- artificial life, an interdisciplinary science studying the most general
character of the fundamental processes of life. These processes include
self-organization, self-reproduction, learning, adaptation, and evolution.
Artificial life or ALife is to theoretical biology roughly what artificial
intelligence AI is to theoretical psychology
computer simulation is the methodology of choice. In fact, since the
mind exhibits many of life’s fundamental properties, AI could be considered a
subfield of ALife. However, whereas most traditional AI models are serial
systems with complicated, centralized controllers making decisions based on
global state information, most natural systems exhibiting complex autonomous
behavior are parallel, distributed networks of simple entities making decisions
based solely on their local state information, so typical ALife models have a
corresponding distributed architecture. A computer simulation of evolving
“bugs” can illustrate what ALife models are like. Moving around in a
two-dimensional world periodically laden with heaps of “food,” these bugs eat,
reproduce, and sometimes perish from starvation. Each bug’s movement is
genetically determined by the quantities of food in its immediate neighborhood,
and random mutations and crossovers modify these genomes during reproduction.
Simulations started with random genes show spontaneous waves of highly adaptive
genetic novelties continuously sweeping through the population at precisely
quantifiable rates.C. Langston et al., eds., Artificial Life II 1. artificial
language artificial life 57 57 ALife
science raises and promises to inform many philosophical issues, such as: Is
functionalism the right approach toward life? When, if ever, is a simulation of
life really alive? When do systems exhibit the spontaneous emergence of
properties? Refs.: Grice: “Life: natural
and non-natural.” naturalism, the twofold view that 1 everything is composed of
natural entities those studied in the
sciences on some versions, the natural sciences
whose properties determine all the properties of things, persons
included abstracta like possibilia and mathematical objects, if they exist,
being constructed of such abstract entities as the sciences allow; and 2
acceptable methods of justification and explanation are continuous, in some
sense, with those in science. Clause 1 is metaphysical or ontological, clause 2
methodological and/or epistemological. Often naturalism is formulated only for
a specific subject matter or domain. Thus ethical naturalism holds that moral
properties are equivalent to or at least determined by certain natural
properties, so that moral judgments either form a subclass of, or are
non-reductively determined by the factual or descriptive judgments, and the
appropriate methods of moral justification and explanation are continuous with
those in science. Aristotle and Spinoza sometimes are counted among the
ancestors of naturalism, as are Democritus, Epicurus, Lucretius, and Hobbes.
But the major impetus to naturalism in the last two centuries comes from
advances in science and the growing explanatory power they signify. By the 1850s,
the synthesis of urea, reflections on the conservation of energy, work on
“animal electricity,” and discoveries in physiology suggested to Feuerbach, L.
Buchner, and others that all aspects of human beings are explainable in purely
natural terms. Darwin’s theory had even greater impact, and by the end of the
nineteenth century naturalist philosophies were making inroads where idealism
once reigned unchallenged. Naturalism’s ranks now included H. Spencer, J.
Tyndall, T. H. Huxley, W. K. Clifford, and E. Haeckel. Early in the twentieth
century, Santayana’s naturalism strongly influenced a number of philosophers, as did Dewey’s. Still other
versions of naturalism flourished in America in the 0s and 0s, including those of
R. W. Sellars and M. Cohen. Today most New-World philosophers of mind are
naturalists of some stripe, largely because of what they see as the lessons of
continuing scientific advances, some of them spectacular, particularly in the
brain sciences. Nonetheless, twentieth-century philosophy has been largely
anti-naturalist. Both phenomenology in the Husserlian tradition and analytic
philosophy in the Fregean tradition, together with their descendants, have been
united in rejecting psychologism, a species of naturalism according to which
empirical discoveries about mental processes are crucial for understanding the
nature of knowledge, language, and logic. In order to defend the autonomy of
philosophy against inroads from descriptive science, many philosophers have
tried to turn the tables by arguing for the priority of philosophy over
science, hence over any of its alleged naturalist implications. Many continue
to do so, often on the ground that philosophy alone can illuminate the
normativity and intentionality involved in knowledge, language, and logic; or
on the ground that philosophy can evaluate the normative and regulative
presuppositions of scientific practice which science itself is either blind to
or unequipped to analyze; or on the ground that phi- losophy understands how
the language of science can no more be used to get outside itself than any
other, hence can no more be known to be in touch with the world and ourselves
than any other; or on the ground that would-be justifications of fundamental
method, naturalist method certainly included, are necessarily circular because
they must employ the very method at issue. Naturalists may reply by arguing
that naturalism’s methodological clause 2 entails the opposite of dogmatism,
requiring as it does an uncompromising fallibilism about philosophical matters
that is continuous with the open, selfcritical spirit of science. If evidence
were to accumulate against naturalism’s metaphysical clause 1, 1 would have to
be revised or rejected, and there is no a priori reason such evidence could in
principle never be found; indeed many naturalists reject the a priori
altogether. Likewise, 2 itself might have to be revised or even rejected in
light of adverse argument, so that in this respect 2 is self-referentially
consistent. Until then, 2’s having survived rigorous criticism to date is
justification enough, as is the case with hypotheses in science, which often
are deployed without circularity in the course of their own evaluation, whether
positive or negative H. I. Brown, “Circular Justifications,” 4. So too can
language be used without circularity in expressing hypotheses about the
relations between language and the prelinguistic world as illustrated by R.
Millikan’s Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories, 4; cf. Post,
“Epistemology,” 6. As for normativity and intentionality, naturalism does not
entail materialism or physicalism, according to which everything is composed of
the entities or processes studied in physics, and the properties of these basic
physical affairs determine all the properties of things as in Quine. Some
naturalists deny this, holding that more things than are dreamt of in physics
are required to account for normativity and intentionality and consciousness. Nor need naturalism be
reductive, in the sense of equating every property with some natural property.
Indeed many physicalists themselves explain how the physical, hence natural,
properties of things might determine other, non-natural properties without
being equivalent to them G. Hellman, T. Horgan, D. Lewis; see J. Post, The
Faces of Existence, 7. Often the determining physical properties are not all
properties of the thing x that has the non-natural properties, but include
properties of items separated from x in space and time or in some cases bearing
no physical relation to x that does any work in determining x’s properties
Post, “ ‘Global’ Supervenient Determination: Too Permissive?” 5. Thus
naturalism allows a high degree of holism and historicity, which opens the way
for a non-reductive naturalist account of intentionality and normativity, such
as Millikan’s, that is immune to the usual objections, which are mostly
objections to reduction. The alternative psychosemantic theories of Dretske and
Fodor, being largely reductive, remain vulnerable to such objections. In these
and other ways non-reductive naturalism attempts to combine a monism of
entities the natural ones of which
everything is composed with a pluralism
of properties, many of them irreducible or emergent. Not everything is nothing
but a natural thing, nor need naturalism accord totalizing primacy to the
natural face of existence. Indeed, some naturalists regard the universe as
having religious and moral dimensions that enjoy a crucial kind of primacy; and
some offer theologies that are more traditionally theist as do H. N. Wieman, C.
Hardwick, J. Post. So far from exhibiting “reptilian indifference” to humans
and their fate, the universe can be an enchanted place of belonging. Refs.: H.
P. Grice: “My labour against Naturalism.” Natura – naturalism -- naturalistic
epistemology, an approach to epistemology that views the human subject as a
natural phenomenon and uses empirical science to study epistemic activity. The
phrase was introduced by Quine “Epistemology Naturalized,” in Ontological
Relativity and Other Essays, 9, who proposed that epistemology should be a
chapter of psychology. Quine construed classical epistemology as Cartesian
epistemology, an attempt to ground all knowledge in a firmly logical way on
immediate experience. In its twentieth-century embodiment, it hoped to give a
translation of all discourse and a deductive validation of all science in terms
of sense experience, logic, and set theory. Repudiating this dream as forlorn,
Quine urged that epistemology be abandoned and replaced by psychology. It would
be a scientific study of how the subject takes sensory stimulations as input
and delivers as output a theory of the three-dimensional world. This
formulation appears to eliminate the normative mission of epistemology. In
later writing, however, Quine has suggested that normative epistemology can be
naturalized as a chapter of engineering: the technology of predicting
experience, or sensory stimulations. Some theories of knowledge are
naturalistic in their depiction of knowers as physical systems in causal
interaction with the environment. One such theory is the causal theory of
knowing, which says that a person knows that p provided his belief that p has a
suitable causal connection with a corresponding state of affairs. Another
example is the information-theoretic approach developed by Dretske Knowledge
and the Flow of Information, 1. This says that a person knows that p only if
some signal “carries” this information that p to him, where information is
construed as an objective commodity that can be processed and transmitted via
instruments, gauges, neurons, and the like. Information is “carried” from one
site to another when events located at those sites are connected by a suitable
lawful dependence. The normative concept of justification has also been the
subject of naturalistic construals. Whereas many theories of justified belief
focus on logical or probabilistic relations between evidence and hypothesis,
naturalistic theories focus on the psychological processes causally responsible
for the belief. The logical status of a belief does not fix its justificational
status. Belief in a tautology, for instance, is not justified if it is formed
by blind trust in an ignorant guru. According to Goldman Epistemology and
Cognition, 6, a belief qualifies as justified only if it is produced by
reliable belief-forming processes, i.e., processes that generally have a high
truth ratio. Goldman’s larger program for naturalistic epistemology is called
“epistemics,” an interdisciplinary enterprise in which cognitive science would
play a major role. Epistemics would seek to identify the subset of cognitive
operations available to the human cognizer that are best from a truth-bearing
standpoint. Relevant truth-linked properties include problem-solving power and speed,
i.e., the abilities to obtain correct answers to questions of interest and to
do so quickly. Close connections between epistemology and artificial
intelligence have been proposed by Clark Glymour, Gilbert Harman, John Pollock,
and Paul Thagard. Harman stresses that principles of good reasoning are not
directly given by rules of logic. Modus ponens, e.g., does not tell you to
infer q if you already believe p and ‘if p then q’. In some cases it is better
to subtract a belief in one of the premises rather than add a belief in q.
Belief revision also requires attention to the storage and computational
limitations of the mind. Limits of memory capacity, e.g., suggest a principle
of clutter avoidance: not filling one’s mind with vast numbers of useless beliefs
Harman, Change in View, 6. Other conceptions of naturalistic epistemology focus
on the history of science. Larry Laudan conceives of naturalistic epistemology
as a scientific inquiry that gathers empirical evidence concerning the past
track records of various scientific methodologies, with the aim of determining
which of these methodologies can best advance the chosen cognitive ends.
Naturalistic epistemology need not confine its attention to individual
epistemic agents; it can also study communities of agents. This perspective
invites contributions from sciences that address the social side of the
knowledge-seeking enterprise. If naturalistic epistemology is a normative
inquiry, however, it must not simply naturalism, biological naturalistic
epistemology 598 598 describe social
practices or social influences; it must analyze the impact of these factors on
the attainment of cognitive ends. Philosophers such as David Hull, Nicholas
Rescher, Philip Kitcher, and Alvin Goldman have sketched models inspired by
population biology and economics to explore the epistemic consequences of
alternative distributions of research activity and different ways that
professional rewards might influence the course of research.
Lockeian ‘sort’ -- natural kind, a
category of entities classically conceived as having modal implications; e.g.,
if Socrates is a member of the natural kind human being, then he is necessarily
a human being. The idea that nature fixes certain sortals, such as ‘water’ and
‘human being’, as correct classifications that appear to designate kinds of
entities has roots going back at least to Plato and Aristotle. Anil Gupta has
argued that sortals are to be distinguished from properties designated by such
predicates as ‘red’ by including criteria for individuating the particulars
bits or amounts for mass nouns that fall under them as well as criteria for
sorting those particulars into the class. Quine is salient among those who find
the modal implications of natural kinds objectionable. He has argued that the
idea of natural kinds is rooted in prescientific intuitive judgments of
comparative similarity, and he has suggested that as these intuitive
classifications are replaced by classifications based on scientific theories
these modal implications drop away. Kripke and Putnam have argued that science
in fact uses natural kind terms having the modal implications Quine finds so
objectionable. They see an important role in scientific methodology for the
capacity to refer demonstratively to such natural kinds by pointing out
particulars that fall under them. Certain inferences within science such as the inference to the charge for
electrons generally from the measurement of the charge on one or a few
electrons seem to be additional aspects
of a role for natural kind terms in scientific practice. Other roles in the
methodology of science for natural kind concepts have been discussed in recent
work by Ian Hacking and Thomas Kuhn. H. P. Grice: “Lockeian sorts: natural and
non-natural.”
Ligatum, lex, -- the natural/non-natural
distinction -- natural law, also called law of nature, in moral and political
philosophy, an objective norm or set of objective norms governing human
behavior, similar to the positive laws of a human ruler, but binding on all
people alike and usually understood as involving a superhuman legislator.
Ancient Grecian and Roman thought, particularly Stoicism, introduced ideas of
eternal laws directing the actions of all rational beings and built into the
very structure of the universe. Roman lawyers developed a doctrine of a law
that all civilized peoples would recognize, and made some effort to explain it
in terms of a natural law common to animals and humans. The most influential
forms of natural law theory, however, arose from later efforts to use Stoic and
legal language to work out a Christian theory of morality and politics. The aim
was to show that the principles of morals could be known by reason alone,
without revelation, so that the whole human race could know how to live
properly. The law of nature applies, on this understanding, only to rational
beings, who can obey or disobey it deliberately and freely. It is thus
different in kind from the laws God laid down for the inanimate and irrational
parts of creation. Natural law theorists often saw continuities and analogies
between natural laws for humans and those for the rest of creation but did not
confuse them. The most enduringly influential natural law writer was Aquinas.
On his view God’s eternal reason ordains laws directing all things to act for
the good of the community of the universe, the declaration of His own glory.
Human reason can participate sufficiently in God’s eternal reason to show us
the good of the human community. The natural law is thus our sharing in the
eternal law in a way appropriate to our human nature. God lays down certain
other laws through revelation; these divine laws point us toward our eternal
goal. The natural law concerns our earthly good, and needs to be supplemented
by human laws. Such laws can vary from community to community, but to be
binding they must always stay within the limits of the law of nature. God
engraved the most basic principles of the natural law in the minds of all
people alike, but their detailed application takes reasoning powers that not
everyone may have. Opponents of Aquinas
called voluntarists argued that
God’s will, not his intellect, is the source of law, and that God could have
laid down different natural laws for us. Hugo Grotius rejected their position,
but unlike Aquinas he conceived of natural law as meant not to direct us to
bring about some definite common good but to set the limits on the ways in
which each of us could properly pursue our own personal aims. This Grotian
outlook was developed by Hobbes, Pufendorf, and Locke along voluntarist lines.
Thomistic views continued to be expounded by Protestant as well as Roman
Catholic writers until the end of the seventeenth century. Thereafter, while
natural law theory remained central to Catholic teaching, it ceased to attract major
new non-Catholic proponents. Natural law doctrine in both Thomistic and Grotian
versions treats morality as basically a matter of compliance with law.
Obligation and duty, obedience and disobedience, merit and guilt, reward and
punishment, are central notions. Virtues are simply habits of following laws.
Though the law is suited to our distinctive human nature and can be discovered
by the proper use of reason, it is not a self-imposed law. In following it we
are obeying God. Since the early eighteenth century, philosophical discussions
of whether or not there is an objective morality have largely ceased to center
on natural law. The idea remains alive, however, in jurisprudence. Natural law
theories are opposed to legal positivism, the view that the only binding laws
are those imposed by human sovereigns, who cannot be subject to higher legal
constraints. Legal theorists arguing that there are rational objective limits
to the legislative power of rulers often think of these limits in terms of
natural law, even when their theories do not invoke or imply any of the
religious aspects of earlier natural law positions. Refs.: N.
Cartwright-Hampshire, “How the laws of phyiscs lie,” in P. G. R. I. C. E.,
without a response by H. P. Grice. (“That will not be feasible.”)
natura – the natural/transnatural
distinction -- natural philosophy – Grice: “It’s funny: there are only three or
four chairs of philosophy at Oxford and one had to be on ‘the trans-natural’
philosophy! Back in the day, I might just as well have to have attended the
‘natural’ philosophy lectures!” -- the
study of nature or of the spatiotemporal world. This was regarded as a task for
philosophy before the emergence of modern science, especially physics and
astronomy, and the term is now only used with reference to premodern times.
Philosophical questions about nature still remain, e.g., whether materialism is
true, but they would usually be placed in metaphysics or in a branch of it that
may be called philosophy of nature. Natural philosophy is not to be confused
with metaphysical naturalism, which is the metaphysical view no part of science
itself that all that there is is the spatiotemporal world and that the only way
to study it is that of the empirical sciences. It is also not to be confused
with natural theology, which also may be considered part of metaphysics. The Sedleian Professor of Natural Philosophy is the name of
a chair at the Mathematical Institute of the University of Oxford. The
Sedleian Chair was founded by Sir William Sedley who, by his will dated 20
October 1618, left the sum of £2,000 to the University of Oxford for purchase
of lands for its endowment. Sedley's bequest took effect in 1621 with the
purchase of an estate at Waddesdon in Buckinghamshire to produce the necessary
income. It is regarded as the oldest of Oxford's scientific chairs.
Holders of the Sedleian Professorship have, since the mid 19th Century, worked
in a range of areas of Applied Mathematics and Mathematical Physics. They are
simultaneously elected to fellowships at Queen's College, Oxford. The
Sedleian Professors in the past century have been Augustus Love (1899-1940),
who was distinguished for his work in the mathematical theory of elasticity,
Sydney Chapman (1946-1953), who is renowned for his contributions to the
kinetic theory of gases and solar-terrestrial physics, George Temple
(1953-1968), who made significant contributions to mathematical physics and the
theory of generalized functions, Brooke Benjamin (1979-1995), who did highly
influential work in the areas of mathematical analysis and fluid mechanics, and
Sir John Ball (1996-2019), who is distinguished for his work in the
mathematical theory of elasticity, materials science, the calculus of
variations, and infinite-dimensional dynamical systems. Refs.: H. P.
Grice: “Oxford and the four Ws: Waynflete, White, Wykeham, and Wilde.”
Natura – nautralism -- natural religion, a
term first occurring in the second half of the seventeenth century, used in
three related senses, the most common being 1 a body of truths about God and
our duty that can be discovered by natural reason. These truths are sufficient
for salvation or according to some orthodox Christians would have been
sufficient if Adam had not sinned. Natural religion in this sense should be
distinguished from natural theology, which does not imply this. A natural
religion may also be 2 one that has a human, as distinct from a divine, origin.
It may also be 3 a religion of human nature as such, as distinguished from
religious beliefs and practices that have been determined by local
circumstances. Natural religion in the third sense is identified with
humanity’s original religion. In all three senses, natural religion includes a
belief in God’s existence, justice, benevolence, and providential government; in
immortality; and in the dictates of common morality. While the concept is
associated with deism, it is also sympathetically treated by Christian writers
like Clarke, who argues that revealed religion simply restores natural religion
to its original purity and adds inducements to compliance. The Faculty of Medicine
appoints an elector for the professorship of Human Anatomy and for the
professorship of Pathology. The Board of Natural Science appoints one elector
for the professorship of Pathology and two for the Lee's Readerships. The Board
of Modern History appoints two electors for the Beit professorship and
lectureship, and three for the Ford lectureship. The Board of Theology appoints
three of the seven electors for the Speaker's lectureship in Biblical Studies.
Three different Boards of Faculty appoint electors for the Wilde lectureship in
Natural Religion. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Natural religion at Oxford
– the Wilde and the Wilde.”
Modus – necessitas -- Necessitarianism:
“An ugly word once used by Strawson in a tutorial!” – Grice. -- the doctrine
that necessity is an objective feature of the world. Natural language permits
speakers to express modalities: a state of affairs can be actual Paris’s being
in France, merely possible chlorophyll’s making things blue, or necessary 2 ! 2
% 4. Anti-necessitarians believe that these distinctions are not grounded in
the nature of the world. Some of them claim that the distinctions are merely
verbal. Others, e.g., Hume, believed that psychological facts, like our expectations
of future events, explain the idea of necessity. Yet others contend that the
modalities reflect epistemic considerations; necessity reflects the highest
level of an inquirer’s commitment. Some necessitarians believe there are
different modes of metaphysical necessity, e.g., causal and logical necessity.
Certain proponents of idealism believe that each fact is necessarily connected
with every other fact so that the ultimate goal of scientific inquiry is the
discovery of a completely rigorous mathematical system of the world.
modus -- necessitas – necessarium -- necessity,
a modal property attributable to a whole proposition dictum just when it is not
possible that the proposition be false the proposition being de dicto
necessary. Narrowly construed, a proposition P is logically necessary provided
P satisfies certain syntactic conditions, namely, that P’s denial is formally
self-contradictory. More broadly, P is logically necessary just when P
satisfies certain semantic conditions, namely, that P’s denial is false, and P
true, in all possible worlds. These semantic conditions were first suggested by
Leibniz, refined by Vitters and Carnap, and fully developed as the possible
worlds semantics of Kripke, Hintikka, et al., in the 0s. Previously, philosophers
had to rely largely on intuition to determine the acceptability or otherwise of
formulas involving the necessity operator, A, and were at a loss as to which of
various axiomatic systems for modal logic, as developed in the 0s by C. I.
Lewis, best captured the notion of logical necessity. There was much debate,
for instance, over the characteristic NN thesis of Lewis’s system S4, namely,
AP / A AP if P is necessary then it is necessarily necessary. But given a
Leibnizian account of the truth conditions for a statement of the form Aa
namely R1 that Aa is true provided a is true in all possible worlds, and R2
that Aa is false provided there is at least one possible world in which a is
false, a proof can be constructed by reductio ad absurdum. For suppose that AP
/ AAP is false in some arbitrarily chosen world W. Then its antecedent will be
true in W, and hence by R1 it follows a that P will be true in all possible
worlds. But equally its consequent will be false in W, and hence by R2 AP will
be false in at least one possible world, from which again by R2 it follows b
that P will be false in at least one possible world, thus contradicting a. A
similar proof can be constructed for the characteristic thesis of S5, namely,
-A-P / A-A-P if P is possibly true then it is necessarily possible. Necessity
is also attributable to a property F of an object O provided it is not possible
that there is no possible world in which O exists and lacks F F being de re necessary, internal or
essential to O. For instance, the non-repeatable haecceitist property of being
identical to O is de re necessary essential to O, and arguably the repeatable
property of being extended is de re necessary to all colored objects. nĕcesse
(arch. nĕcessum , I.v. infra: NECESVS, S. C. de Bacch. l. 4: necessus , Ter.
Heaut. 2, 3, 119 Wagn. ad loc.; id. Eun. 5, 5, 28; Gell. 16, 8, 1; v. Lachm. ad
Lucr. 6, 815), neutr. adj. (gen. necessis, Lucr. 6, 815 ex conj. Lachm.; cf.
Munro ad loc.; elsewhere only nom. and acc. sing., and with esse or habere) [perh.
Sanscr. naç, obtain; Gr. root ἐνεκ-; cf. ἀνάγκη; v. Georg Curtius Gr. Etym.
424]. I. Form necesse. A. Unavoidable, inevitable, indispensable, necessary
(class.; cf.: opus, usus est) 1. With esse. a. With subject.-clause: “edocet
quanto detrimento...necesse sit constare victoriam,” Caes. B. G. 7, 19:
“necesse est eam, quae ... timere permultos,” Auct. Her. 4, 16, 23: emas, non
quod opus est, sed quod necesse est, Cato ap. Sen. Ep. 94, 28: “nihil fit, quod
necesse non fuerit,” Cic. Fat. 9, 17: “necesse est igitur legem haberi in rebus
optimis,” id. Leg. 2, 5, 12; id. Verr 2, 3, 29, § 70. — b. With dat. (of the
person, emphatic): nihil necesse est mihi de me ipso dicere, Cic. Sen. 9, 30:
“de homine enim dicitur, cui necesse est mori,” id. Fat. 9, 17.— c. With ut and
subj.: “eos necesse est ut petat,” Auct. Her. 4, 16, 23: “sed ita necesse
fuisse, cum Demosthenes dicturus esset, ut concursus ex totā Graeciā fierent,”
Cic. Brut. 84, 289; Sen. Ep. 78, 15: “hoc necesse est, ut, etc.,” Cic. de Or.
2, 29, 129; Sen. Q. N. 2, 14, 2: “neque necesse est, uti vos auferam,” Gell. 2,
29, 9: “necesse est semper, ut id ... per se significet,” Quint. 8, 6, 43.— d.
With subj. alone: “haec autem oratio ... aut nulla sit necesse est, aut omnium
irrisione ludatur,” Cic. de Or. 1, 12, 50: “istum condemnetis necesse est,”
Cic. Verr. 2, 2, 18, § 45: “vel concidat omne caelum necesse est,” id. Tusc. 1,
23, 54: “si necesse est aliquid ex se magni boni pariat,” Lact. 3, 12, 7.— 2.
With habere (class. only with inf.): “non habebimus necesse semper concludere,”
Cic. Part. Or. 13, 47: “eo minus habeo necesse scribere,” id. Att. 10, 1, 4:
“Oppio scripsi ne necesse habueris reddere,” id. ib. 16, 2, 5: “non verbum pro
verbo necesse habui reddere,” id. Opt. Gen. Or. 5, 14: “non necesse habeo omnia
pro meo jure agere,” Ter. Ad. 1, 1, 26; Quint. 11, 1, 74; Vulg. Matt. 14, 16:
necesse habere with abl. (= egere; “late Lat.): non necesse habent sani
medico,” Vulg. Marc. 2, 17.—In agreement with object of habere: “non habet rex
sponsalia necesse,” Vulg. 1 Reg. 18, 25.— B. Needful, requisite, indispensable,
necessary: “id quod tibi necesse minime fuit, facetus esse voluisti,” Cic.
Sull. 7, 22.— II. Form necessum (mostly ante-class.). A. With subject.-clause:
“foras necessum est, quicquid habeo, vendere,” Plaut. Stich. 1, 3, 66: quod sit
necessum scire, Afran. ap. Charis. p. 186 P.: “nec tamen haec retineri hamata
necessumst,” Lucr. 2, 468: “externa corpus de parte necessumst tundier,” id. 4,
933: “necessum est vorsis gladiis depugnarier,” Plaut. Cas. 2, 5, 36: “necessum
est paucis respondere,” Liv. 34, 5: “num omne id aurum in ludos consumi
necessum esset?” id. 39, 5: “tonsorem capiti non est adhibere necessum,” Mart.
6, 57, 3.— B. With dat.: “dicas uxorem tibi necessum esse ducere,” Plaut. Mil.
4, 3, 25.— C. With subj.: “unde anima, atque animi constet natura necessum
est,” Lucr. 4, 120: “quare etiam nativa necessum est confiteare Haec eadem,”
id. 5, 377. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The may and the must,” “Ichthyological
necessity.”
need – H. P. Grice, “Need,” cf. D. Wiggins, “Need.” “What Toby
needs” Grice was also interested in the modal use of ‘need’. “You need to do
it.” “ ‘Need,’ like ‘ought’ takes ‘to.’” “It’s very Anglo-Saxon.” “Or, rather
non-Indo-European substratum!” As it is attested only in Germanic,
Celtic, and Balto-Slavic, it might be non-PIE, from a regional substrate
language.
negri: a crucial Italian
philosopher. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice e Negri," per il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
abdicatum: negation: H. P. Grice,
“Negation.” the logical operation on propositions that is indicated, e.g., by
the prefatory clause ‘It is not the case that . . .’. Negation is standardly
distinguished sharply from the operation on predicates that is called complementation
and that is indicated by the prefix ‘non-’. Because negation can also be
indicated by the adverb ‘not’, a distinction is often drawn between external
negation, which is indicated by attaching the prefatory ‘It is not the case
that . . .’ to an assertion, and internal negation, which is indicated by
inserting the adverb ‘not’ along with, perhaps, nature, right of negation
601 601 grammatically necessary words
like ‘do’ or ‘does’ into the assertion in such a way as to indicate that the
adverb ‘not’ modifies the verb. In a number of cases, the question arises as to
whether external and internal negation yield logically equivalent results. For
example, ‘It is not the case that Santa Claus exists’ would seem obviously to
be true, whereas ‘Santa Claus does not exist’ seems to some philosophers to
presuppose what it denies, on the ground that nothing could be truly asserted
of Santa Claus unless he existed. Refs.:
H. P. Grice, “Negation and privation;” H. P. Grice, “Lectures on negation.”
Nemesius: Grecian philosopher. His
treatise on the soul, On the Nature of Man, tr. from Grecian into Latin by
Alphanus of Salerno and Burgundio of Pisa was attributed to Gregory of Nyssa, and
enjoyed some authority. The treatise rejects Plato for underplaying the unity
of soul and body, and Aristotle for making the soul essentially corporeal. The
soul is self-subsistent, incorporeal, and by nature immortal, but naturally
suited for union with the body. Nemesius draws on Ammonius Saccas and Porphyry to
explain the incorruptible soul’s perfect union with the corruptible body. His
review of the powers of the soul (“what I will call ‘the power structure of the
soul,’” – Grice). draws especially on Galen on the brain. His view that
rational creatures possess free will in virtue of their rationality influenced
Maximus the Confessor and John of Damascus.
Ariskant – Kantianism, palaeo-Kantianism,
neo-Kantianism, Ariskantianism! -- neo-Kantianism – as opposed to
‘palaeo-Kantianism’ -- the diverse Kantian movement that emerged within G.
philosophy in the 1860s, gained a strong academic foothold in the 1870s,
reached its height during the three decades prior to World War I, and
disappeared with the rise of Nazism. The movement was initially focused on
renewed study and elaboration of Kant’s epistemology in response to the growing
epistemic authority of the natural sciences and as an alternative to both
Hegelian and speculative idealism and the emerging materialism of, among
others, Ludwig Büchner 182499. Later neo-Kantianism explored Kant’s whole
philosophy, applied his critical method to disciplines other than the natural
sciences, and developed its own philosophical systems. Some originators and/or
early contributors were Kuno Fischer 18247, Hermann von Helmholtz 182,
Friedrich Albert Lange 182875, Eduard Zeller 18148, and Otto Liebmann 18402,
whose Kant und die Epigonen 1865 repeatedly stated what became a neoKantian
motto, “Back to Kant!” Several forms of neo-Kantianism are to be distinguished.
T. K. Oesterreich 09, in Friedrich Ueberwegs Grundriss der Geschichte der
Philosophie “F.U.’s Compendium of the History of Philosophy,” 3, developed the
standard, somewhat chronological, classification: 1 The physiological
neo-Kantianism of Helmholtz and Lange, who claimed that physiology is
“developed or corrected Kantianism.” 2 The metaphysical neo-Kantianism of the
later Liebmann, who argued for a Kantian “critical metaphysics” beyond
epistemology in the form of “hypotheses” about the essence of things. 3 The
realist neo-Kantianism of Alois Riehl 18444, who emphasized the real existence
of Kant’s thing-in-itself. 4 The logistic-methodological neo-Kantianism of the
Marburg School of Hermann Cohen 18428 and Paul Natorp 18544. 5 The axiological
neo-Kantianism of the Baden or Southwest G. School of Windelband 18485 and
Heinrich Rickert 18636. 6 The relativistic neo-Kantianism of Georg Simmel
18588, who argued for Kantian categories relative to individuals and cultures.
7 The psychological neo-Kantianism of Leonard Nelson 27, originator of the
Göttingen School; also known as the neo-Friesian School, after Jakob Friedrich
Fries 17731843, Nelson’s self-proclaimed precursor. Like Fries, Nelson held
that Kantian a priori principles cannot be transcendentally justified, but can
be discovered only through introspection. Oesterreich’s classification has been
narrowed or modified, partly because of conflicting views on how distinctly
“Kantian” a philosopher must have been to be called “neo-Kantian.” The very term
‘neo-Kantianism’ has even been called into question, as suggesting real
intellectual commonality where little or none is to be found. There is,
however, growing consensus that Marneo-Euclidean geometry neo-Kantianism
603 603 burg and Baden neo-Kantianism
were the most important and influential. Marburg School. Its founder, Cohen,
developed its characteristic Kantian idealism of the natural sciences by
arguing that physical objects are truly known only through the laws of these
sciences and that these laws presuppose the application of Kantian a priori
principles and concepts. Cohen elaborated this idealism by eliminating Kant’s
dualism of sensibility and understanding, claiming that space and time are
construction methods of “pure thought” rather than a priori forms of perception
and that the notion of any “given” perceptual data prior to the “activity” of
“pure thought” is meaningless. Accordingly, Cohen reformulated Kant’s
thing-in-itself as the regulative idea that the mathematical description of the
world can always be improved. Cohen also emphasized that “pure thought” refers
not to individual consciousess on his
account Kant had not yet sufficiently left behind a “subjectobject”
epistemology but rather to the content
of his own system of a priori principles, which he saw as subject to change
with the progress of science. Just as Cohen held that epistemology must be
based on the “fact of science,” he argued, in a decisive step beyond Kant, that
ethics must transcendentally deduce both the moral law and the ideal moral
subject from a humanistic science more
specifically, from jurisprudence’s notion of the legal person. This analysis
led to the view that the moral law demands that all institutions, including
economic enterprises, become democratic
so that they display unified wills and intentions as transcendental
conditions of the legal person and that
all individuals become colegislators. Thus Cohen arrived at his frequently
cited claim that Kant “is the true and real originator of G. socialism.” Other
important Marburg Kantians were Cohen’s colleague Natorp, best known for his
studies on Plato and philosophy of education, and their students Karl Vorländer
18608, who focused on Kantian socialist ethics as a corrective of orthodox
Marxism, and Ernst Cassirer 18745. Baden School. The basic task of philosophy
and its transcendental method is seen as identifying universal values that make
possible culture in its varied expressions. This focus is evident in
Windelband’s influential insight that the natural sciences seek to formulate
general laws nomothetic knowledge while the historical sciences seek to
describe unique events idiographic knowledge.
This distinction is based on the values interests of mastery of nature and
understanding and reliving the unique past in order to affirm our
individuality. Windelband’s view of the historical sciences as idiographic
raised the problem of selection central to his successor Rickert’s writings:
How can historians objectively determine which individual events are historically
significant? Rickert argued that this selection must be based on the values
that are generally recognized within the cultures under investigation, not on
the values of historians themselves. Rickert also developed the transcendental
argument that the objectivity of the historical sciences necessitates the
assumption that the generally recognized values of different cultures
approximate in various degrees universally valid values. This argument was
rejected by Weber, whose methodological work was greatly indebted to Rickert. Refs.:
H. P. Grice, “Kantianism: old and new.”
Platone – Platonism – Walter Pater -- Neo-platonism
– as opposed to ‘palaeo-Platonism’ -- that period of Platonism following on the
new impetus provided by the philosophical speculations of Plotinus A.D. 20469.
It extends, as a minimum, to the closing of the Platonic School in Athens by
Justinian in 529, but maximally through Byzantium, with such figures as Michael
Psellus 101878 and Pletho c.13601452, the Renaissance Ficino, Pico, and the
Florentine Academy, and the early modern period the Cambridge Platonists,
Thomas Taylor, to the advent of the “scientific” study of the works of Plato
with Schleiermacher 17681834 at the beginning of the nineteenth century. The
term was formerly also used to characterize the whole period from the Old
Academy of Plato’s immediate successors, Speusippus and Xenocrates, through
what is now termed Middle Platonism c.80 B.C.A.D. 220, down to Plotinus. This
account confines itself to the “minimum” interpretation. Neoplatonism proper
may be divided into three main periods: that of Plotinus and his immediate
followers third century; the “Syrian” School of Iamblichus and his followers
fourth century; and the “Athenian” School begun by Plutarch of Athens, and
including Syrianus, Proclus, and their successors, down to Damascius fifthsixth
centuries. Plotinus and his school. Plotinus’s innovations in Platonism
developed in his essays, the Enneads, collected and edited by his pupil
Porphyry after his death, are mainly two: a above the traditional supreme
principle of earlier Platonism and Aristotelianism, a self-thinking intellect,
which was also regarded as true being, he postulated a principle superior to
intellect and being, totally unitary and simple “the One”; b he saw reality as
a series of levels One, Intelligence, Soul, each higher one outflowing or
radiating into the next lower, while still remaining unaffected in itself, and
the lower ones fixing themselves in being by somehow “reflecting back” upon their
priors. This eternal process gives the universe its existence and character.
Intelligence operates in a state of non-temporal simultaneity, holding within
itself the “forms” of all things. Soul, in turn, generates time, and receives
the forms into itself as “reason principles” logoi. Our physical
three-dimensional world is the result of the lower aspect of Soul nature
projecting itself upon a kind of negative field of force, which Plotinus calls
“matter.” Matter has no positive existence, but is simply the receptacle for
the unfolding of Soul in its lowest aspect, which projects the forms in
three-dimensional space. Plotinus often speaks of matter as “evil” e.g. Enneads
II.8, and of the Soul as suffering a “fall” e.g. Enneads V.1, 1, but in fact he
sees the whole cosmic process as an inevitable result of the superabundant
productivity of the One, and thus “the best of all possible worlds.” Plotinus
was himself a mystic, but he arrived at his philosophical conclusions by
perfectly logical means, and he had not much use for either traditional
religion or any of the more recent superstitions. His immediate pupils, Amelius
c.22590 and Porphyry 234c.305, while somewhat more hospitable to these,
remained largely true to his philosophy though Amelius had a weakness for
triadic elaborations in metaphysics. Porphyry was to have wide influence, both
in the Latin West through such men as Marius Victorinus, Augustine, and
Boethius, and in the Grecian East and even, through translations, on medieval
Islam, as the founder of the Neoplatonic tradition of commentary on both Plato
and Aristotle, but it is mainly as an expounder of Plotinus’s philosophy that
he is known. He added little that is distinctive, though that little is
currently becoming better appreciated. Iamblichus and the Syrian School.
Iamblichus c.245325, descendant of an old Syrian noble family, was a pupil of
Porphyry’s, but dissented from him on various important issues. He set up his
own school in Apamea in Syria, and attracted many pupils. One chief point of
dissent was the role of theurgy really just magic, with philosophical
underpinnings, but not unlike Christian sacramental theology. Iamblichus
claimed, as against Porphyry, that philosophical reasoning alone could not
attain the highest degree of enlightenment, without the aid of theurgic rites,
and his view on this was followed by all later Platonists. He also produced a
metaphysical scheme far more elaborate than Plotinus’s, by a Scholastic filling
in, normally with systems of triads, of gaps in the “chain of being” left by
Plotinus’s more fluid and dynamic approach to philosophy. For instance, he
postulated two Ones, one completely transcendent, the other the source of all
creation, thus “resolving” a tension in Plotinus’s metaphysics. Iamblichus was
also concerned to fit as many of the traditional gods as possible into his
system, which later attracted the attention of the Emperor Julian, who based
himself on Iamblichus when attempting to set up a Hellenic religion to rival
Christianity, a project which, however, died with him in 363. The Athenian
School. The precise links between the pupils of Iamblichus and Plutarch d.432,
founder of the Athenian School, remain obscure, but the Athenians always
retained a great respect for the Syrian. Plutarch himself is a dim figure, but
Syrianus c.370437, though little of his writings survives, can be seen from
constant references to him by his pupil Proclus 412 85 to be a major figure,
and the source of most of Proclus’s metaphysical elaborations. The Athenians
essentially developed and systematized further the doctrines of Iamblichus,
creating new levels of divinity e.g. intelligibleintellectual gods, and
“henads” in the realm of the One though
they rejected the two Ones, this process reaching its culmination in the thought
of the last head of the Athenian Academy, Damascius c.456540. The drive to
systematize reality and to objectivize concepts, exhibited most dramatically in
Proclus’s Elements of Theology, is a lasting legacy of the later Neoplatonists,
and had a significant influence on the thought, among others, of Hegel. Grice:
“The implicaturum of ‘everything old is new again’ is that everything new is
old again.” “It’s the older generation, knock-knock-knocking at the door!” -- Refs.:
H. P. Grice, “Everything old is new again – and vice versa.”
Otiumm -- Schole –scholasticism -- neo-scholasticism:
as opposed to palaeo-scholasticism – Grice: “The original name of Oxford was
‘studium generale’! The mascot was the ox!” --. the movement given impetus
Neoplatonism, Islamic neo-Scholasticism 605
605 by Pope Leo XIII’s encyclical Aeterni Patris 1879, which, while
stressing Aquinas, was a general recommendation of the study of medieval
Scholasticism as a source for the solution of vexing modern problems. Leo
assumed that there was a doctrine common to Aquinas, Bonaventure, Albertus
Magnus, and Duns Scotus, and that Aquinas was a preeminent spokesman of the
common view. Maurice De Wulf employed the phrase ‘perennial philosophy’ to
designate this common medieval core as well as what of Scholasticism is
relevant to later times. Historians like Mandonnet, Grabmann, and Gilson soon
contested the idea that there was a single medieval doctrine and drew attention
to the profound differences between the great medieval masters. The discussion
of Christian philosophy precipitated by Brehier in 1 generated a variety of
suggestions as to what medieval thinkers and later Christian philosophers have
in common, but this was quite different from the assumption of Aeterni Patris.
The pedagogical directives of this and later encyclicals brought about a
revival of Thomism rather than of Scholasticism, generally in seminaries,
ecclesiastical s, and Catholic universities. Louvain’s Higher Institute of
Philosophy under the direction of Cardinal Mercier and its Revue de Philosophie
Néoscolastique were among the first fruits of the Thomistic revival. The studia
generalia of the Dominican order continued at a new pace, the Saulchoir
publishing the Revue thomiste. In graduate centers in Milan, Madrid, Latin
America, Paris, and Rome, men were trained for the task of teaching in s and
seminaries, and scholarly research began to flourish as well. The Leonine
edition of the writings of Aquinas was soon joined by new critical editions of
Bonaventure, Duns Scotus, and Ockham, as well as Albertus Magnus. Medieval
studies in the broader sense gained from the quest for manuscripts and the
growth of paleography and codicology. Besides the historians mentioned above,
Jacques Maritain 23, a layman and convert to Catholicism, did much both in his
native France and in the United States to promote the study of Aquinas. The
Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies at Toronto, with Gilson regularly and
Maritain frequently in residence, became a source of and
teachers in Canada and the United States, as Louvain and, in Rome, the
Jesuit Gregorianum and the Dominican Angelicum already were. In the 0s s took
doctorates in theology and philosophy at Laval in Quebec and soon the influence
of Charles De Koninck was felt. Jesuits at St. Louis began to publish The Modern Schoolman,
Dominicans in Washington The Thomist, and the
Catholic Philosophical Association The New Scholasticism. The School of
Philosophy at Catholic , long the primary domestic source of professors and scholars,
was complemented by graduate programs at St. Louis, Georgetown, Notre Dame,
Fordham, and Marquette. In the golden period of the Thomistic revival in the
United States, from the 0s until the end of the Vatican Council II in 5, there
were varieties of Thomism based on the variety of views on the relation between
philosophy and science. By the 0s Thomistic philosophy was a prominent part of
the curriculum of all Catholic s and universities. By 0, it had all but
disappeared under the mistaken notion that this was the intent of Vatican II.
This had the effect of releasing Aquinas into the wider philosophical
world.
Aquino -- Aquinismo – “If followers of
William are called Occamists, followers of a Saint should surely call
themselves “Aquinistae”! -- neo-Thomism – as opposed to palaeo-Thomism --, a
philosophical-theological movement in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries
manifesting a revival of interest in Aquinas. It was stimulated by Pope Leo
XIII’s encyclical Aeterni Patris 1879 calling for a renewed emphasis on the
teaching of Thomistic principles to meet the intellectual and social challenges
of modernity. The movement reached its peak in the 0s, though its influence
continues to be seen in organizations such as the Catholic Philosophical Association. Among its
major figures are Joseph Kleutgen, Désiré Mercier, Joseph Maréchal, Pierre
Rousselot, Réginald Garrigou-LaGrange, Martin Grabmann, M.-D. Chenu, Jacques
Maritain, Étienne Gilson, Yves R. Simon, Josef Pieper, Karl Rahner, Cornelio
Fabro, Emerich Coreth, Bernard Lonergan, and W. Norris Clarke. Few, if any, of
these figures have described themselves as NeoThomists; some explicitly
rejected the designation. Neo-Thomists have little in common except their
commitment to Aquinas and his relevance to the contemporary world. Their
interest produced a more historically accurate understanding of Aquinas and his
contribution to medieval thought Grabmann, Gilson, Chenu, including a
previously ignored use of the Platonic metaphysics of participation Fabro. This
richer understanding of Aquinas, as forging a creative synthesis in the midst
of competing traditions, has made arguing for his relevance easier. Those
Neo-Thomists who were suspicious of modernity produced fresh readings of
Aquinas’s texts applied to contemporary problems Pieper, Gilson. Their
influence can be seen in the revival of virtue theory and the work of Alasdair
MacIntyre. Others sought to develop Aquinas’s thought with the aid of later
Thomists Maritain, Simon and incorporated the interpretations of
Counter-Reformation Thomists, such as Cajetan and Jean Poinsot, to produce more
sophisticated, and controversial, accounts of the intelligence, intentionality,
semiotics, and practical knowledge. Those Neo-Thomists willing to engage modern
thought on its own terms interpreted modern philosophy sympathetically using
the principles of Aquinas Maréchal, Lonergan, Clarke, seeking dialogue rather
than confrontation. However, some readings of Aquinas are so thoroughly
integrated into modern philosophy that they can seem assimilated Rahner,
Coreth; their highly individualized metaphysics inspired as much by other
philosophical influences, especially Heidegger, as Aquinas. Some of the labels
currently used among Neo-Thomists suggest a division in the movement over
critical, postKantian methodology. ‘Existential Thomism’ is used for those who
emphasize both the real distinction between essence and existence and the role
of the sensible in the mind’s first grasp of being. ‘Transcendental Thomism’
applies to figures like Maréchal, Rousselot, Rahner, and Coreth who rely upon
the inherent dynamism of the mind toward the real, rooted in Aquinas’s theory
of the active intellect, from which to deduce their metaphysics of being.
Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Grice e Aquino: grammatici speculative, per il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
Grecian: Grice: “Much as in London The
Royal Opera only staged operas in Italian, and call itself, The Italian Royal
Opera, at Rome, they only philosophised in Grecian! That is the elite’s way to
separate from the riff raff.” – Grice. Grice: “Similarly, at Oxford, I came
with a knowledge of Grecian and Roman far superior than English – and we always
looked down on those who came down to Oxford just to do what we insultingly
called “Eng. Lit.”!” --.
Academia:
academia vecchia/academia nuova -- accademia nuova – v. Grice,
“Carneades at Rome, and the beginning of Western philosophy.” New Academy, the
name given the Academy, the school founded by Plato in the Athenian suburs, during
the time it was controlled by Academic Skeptics. Its principal leaders in this
period were Arcesilaus and Carneades; our most accessible source for the New
Academy is Cicero’s “Academica.” A master of logical techniques such as sorites
which he learned from Diodorus, Arcesilaus attempted to revive the dialectic of
Plato, using it to achieve the suspension of belief he learned to value from
Pyrrho. Later, and especially under the leadership of Carneades, the New
Academy developed a special relationship with Stoicism: as the Stoics found new
ways to defend their doctrine of the criterion, Carneades found new ways to
refute it in the Stoics’ own terms. Carneades’ visit to Rome in 155 B.C. with a
Stoic and a Peripatetic marks the beginning of Rome’s interest, especially with
the elite, just to be different and to speak in a tongue that the vulgus would
not understand, in what the Romans called “philosophia hellenistica” – Cicero,
“Since I cannot think of a vernacular Roman term for ‘philosophia.’” An
Englishman had the same problem with logic, which he rendered as ‘witcraft.’ –
and ‘witlove.’ His anti-Stoic arguments were recorded by his successor
Clitomachus d. c.110 B.C., whose work is known to us through summaries in
Cicero. Clitomachus was succeeded by Philo of Larisa c.16079 B.C., who was the
teacher of Antiochus of Ascalon c.130c.67 B.C.. Philo later attempted to
reconcile the Old and the New Academy by softening the Skepticism of the New
and by fostering a Skeptical reading of Plato. Angered by this, Antiochus broke
away in about 87 B.C. to found what he called the Old Academy, which is now
considered to be the beginning of Middle Platonism. Probably about the same
time, Aenesidemus dates unknown revived the strict Skepticism of Pyrrho and
founded the school that is known to us through the work of Sextus Empiricus.
Academic Skepticism differed from Pyrrhonism in its sharp focus on Stoic
positions, and possibly in allowing for a weak assent as opposed to belief,
which they suspended in what is probable; and Pyrrhonians accused Academic
Skeptics of being dogmatic in their rejection of the possibility of knowledge.
The New Academy had a major influence on the development of modern philosophy,
most conspicuously through Hume, who considered that his brand of mitigated
skepticism belonged to this school. Grice: “Western philosophy begins with
Carneades lecturing the rough Romans some philosophy; because Greece is EAST!”
– Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The longitudinal history of philosophy from Carneades’s
sojourn at Rome to my British Academy lecture at London.”
Newcomb’s paradox: a conflict, which Grice
finds fascinating, between two widely accepted principles of rational decision,
arising in the following decision problem, known as Newcomb’s problem. Two
boxes are before you. The first contains either $1,000,000 or nothing. The
second contains $1,000. You may take the first box alone or both boxes. Someone
with uncanny foresight has predicted your choice and fixed the content of the
first box according to his prediction. If he has predicted that you will take
only the first box, he has put $1,000,000 in that box; and if he has predicted
that you will take both boxes, he has left the first box empty. The expected
utility of an option is commonly obtained by multiplying the utility of its
possible outcomes by their probabilities given the option, and then adding the
products. Because the predictor is reliable, the probability that you receive
$1,000,000 given that you take only the first box is high, whereas the
probability that you receive $1,001,000 given that you take both boxes is low.
Accordingly, the expected utility of taking only the first box is greater than
the expected utility of taking both boxes. Therefore the principle of maximizing
expected utility says to take only the first box. However, the principle of
dominance says that if the states determining the outcomes of options are
causally independent of the options, and there is one option that is better
than the others in each state, then you should adopt it. Since your choice does
not causally influence the contents of the first box, and since choosing both
boxes yields $1,000 in addition to the contents of the first box whatever they
are, the principle says to take both boxes. Newcomb’s paradox is named after
its formulator, William Newcomb. Nozick publicized it in “Newcomb’s Problem and
Two Principles of Choice” 9. Many theorists have responded to the paradox by
changing the definition of the expected utility of an option so that it is
sensitive to the causal influence of the option on the states that determine
its outcome, but is insensitive to the evidential bearing of the option on
those states. Refs: H. P. Grice, “Why I love Newcomb.”
Grice, “Oxford’s kindly light” -- Newman
(“Lead Kindly light”) -- English prelate and philosopher of religion. As fellow
at Oriel , Oxford, he was a prominent member of the Anglican Oxford Movement.
He became a Roman Catholic in 1845, took holy orders in 1847, and was made a
cardinal in 1879. His most important philosophical work is the Grammar of
Assent 1870. Here Newman explored the difference between formal reasoning and
the informal or natural movement of the mind in discerning the truth about the
concrete and historical. Concrete reasoning in the mode of natural inference is
implicit and unreflective; it deals not with general principles as such but
with their employment in particular circumstances. Thus a scientist must judge
whether the phenomenon he confronts is a novel significant datum, a
coincidence, or merely an insignificant variation in the data. The acquired
capacity to make judgments of this sort Newman called the illative sense, an
intellectual skill shaped by experience and personal insight and generally
limited for individuals to particular fields of endeavor. The illative sense
makes possible a judgment of certitude about the matter considered, even though
the formal argument that partially outlines the process possesses only
objective probability for the novice. Hence probability is not necessarily
opposed to certitude. In becoming aware of its tacit dimension, Newman spoke of
recognizing a mode of informal inference. He distinguished such reasoning,
which, by virtue of the illative sense, culminates in a judgment of certitude
about the way things are real assent, from formal reasoning conditioned by the
certainty or probability of the premises, which assents to the conclusion thus
conditioned notional assent. In real assent, the proposition functions to
“image” the reality, to make its reality present. In the Development of
Christian Doctrine 1845, Newman analyzed the ways in which some ideas unfold
themselves only through historical development, within a tradition of inquiry.
He sought to delineate the common pattern of such development in politics,
science, philosophy, and religion. Although his focal interest was in how
religious doctrines develop, he emphasizes the general character of such a
pattern of progressive articulation. H. P. Grice, “Oxford’s kindly light.”
Res – realism – neo-relaism, New Realism –
or neo-realism – as opposed to “palaeo-realism” -- an early twentieth-century
revival in England of various forms of realism in reaction to the dominant
idealisms inherited from the nineteenth century. In America this revival took a
cooperative form when six philosophers Ralph Barton Perry, Edwin Holt, William
Pepperell Montague, Walter Pitkin, Edward Spaulding, and Walter Marvin
published “A Program and First Platform of Six Realists” 0, followed two years
later by the cooperative volume The New Realism, in which each authored an
essay. This volume gave rise to the designation ‘New Realists’ for these six
philosophers. Although they clearly disagreed on many particulars, they
concurred on several matters of philosophical style and epistemological
substance. Procedurally they endorsed a cooperative and piecemeal approach to
philosophical problems, and they were constitutionally inclined to a closeness
of analysis that would prepare the way for later philosophical tendencies.
Substantively they agreed on several epistemological stances central to the
refutation of idealism. Among the doctrines in the New Realist platform were
the rejection of the fundamental character of epistemology; the view that the
entities investigated in logic, mathematics, and science are not “mental” in
any ordinary sense; the view that the things known are not the products of the
knowing relation nor in any fundamental sense conditioned by their being known;
and the view that the objects known are immediately and directly present to
consciousness while being independent of that relation. New Realism was a version
of direct realism, which viewed the notions of mediation and representation in
knowledge as opening gambits on the slippery slope to idealism. Their
refutation of idealism focused on pointing out the fallacy of moving from the
truism that every object of knowledge is known to the claim that its being
consists in its being known. That we are obviously at the center of what we
know entails nothing about the nature of what we know. Perry dubbed this fact
“the egocentric predicament,” and supplemented this observation with arguments
to the effect that the objects of knowledge are in fact independent of the
knowing relation. New Realism as a version of direct realism had as its primary
conceptual obstacle “the facts of relativity,” i.e., error, illusion, perceptual
variation, and valuation. Dealing with these phenomena without invoking “mental
intermediaries” proved to be the stumbling block, and New Realism soon gave way
to a second cooperative venture by another group of philosophers that came to be known as
Critical Realism. The term ‘new realism’ is also occasionally used with regard
to those British philosophers principal among them Moore and Russell similarly
involved in refuting idealism. Although individually more significant than the group, theirs was not a cooperative effort,
so the group term came to have primarily an
referent.
newton, -- “Hypotheses non fingo.” Grice:
“His surname is a toponymic: it literally means ‘new-town,’ but it implicates,
“FROM new-town.” – “We never knew what ‘old’ town Sir Isaac is implicating,
possibly Oldton, in Cumbria.” -- English physicist and mathematician, one of
the greatest scientists of all time. Born in Woolsthorpe, Lincolnshire, he
attended Cambridge , receiving the B.A. in 1665; he became a fellow of Trinity
in New Realism Newton, Sir Isaac 610
610 1667 and Lucasian Professor of Mathematics in 1669. He was elected
fellow of the Royal Society in 1671 and served as its president from 1703 until
his death. In 1696 he was appointed warden of the mint. In his later years he
was involved in political and governmental affairs rather than in active
scientific work. A sensitive, secretive person, he was prone to
irascibility most notably in a dispute
with Leibniz over priority of invention of the calculus. His unparalleled
scientific accomplishments overshadow a deep and sustained interest in ancient
chronology, biblical study, theology, and alchemy. In his early twenties
Newton’s genius asserted itself in an astonishing period of mathematical and
experimental creativity. In the years 1664 67, he discovered the binomial theorem;
the “method of fluxions” calculus; the principle of the composition of light;
and fundamentals of his theory of universal gravitation. Newton’s masterpiece,
Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica “The Mathematical Principles of
Natural Philosophy”, appeared in 1687. This work sets forth the mathematical
laws of physics and “the system of the world.” Its exposition is modeled on
Euclidean geometry: propositions are demonstrated mathematically from
definitions and mathematical axioms. The world system consists of material
bodies masses composed of hard particles at rest or in motion and interacting
according to three axioms or laws of motion: 1 Every body continues in its
state of rest or of uniform motion in a straight line unless it is compelled to
change that state by forces impressed upon it. 2 The change of motion is
proportional to the motive force impressed and is made in the direction of the
straight line in which that force is impressed. [Here, the impressed force
equals mass times the rate of change of velocity, i.e., acceleration. Hence the
familiar formula, F % ma.] 3 To every action there is always opposed an equal
reaction; or, the mutual action of two bodies upon each other is always equal
and directed to contrary parts. Newton’s general law of gravitation in modern
restatement is: Every particle of matter attracts every other particle with a
force varying directly as the product of their masses and inversely as the
square of the distance between them. The statement of the laws of motion is
preceded by an equally famous scholium in which Newton enunciates the ultimate
conditions of his universal system: absolute time, space, place, and motion. He
speaks of these as independently existing “quantities” according to which true
measurements of bodies and motions can be made as distinct from relative
“sensible measures” and apparent observations. Newton seems to have thought
that his system of mathematical principles presupposed and is validated by the
absolute framework. The scholium has been the subject of much critical
discussion. The main problem concerns the justification of the absolute
framework. Newton commends adherence to experimental observation and induction
for advancing scientific knowledge, and he rejects speculative hypotheses. But
absolute time and space are not observable. In the scholium Newton did offer a
renowned experiment using a rotating pail of water as evidence for
distinguishing true and apparent motions and proof of absolute motion. It has
been remarked that conflicting strains of a rationalism anticipating Kant and
empiricism anticipating Hume are present in Newton’s conception of science.
Some of these issues are also evident in Newton’s Optics 1704, especially the
fourth edition, 1730, which includes a series of suggestive “Queries” on the
nature of light, gravity, matter, scientific method, and God. The triumphant
reception given to Newton’s Principia in England and on the Continent led to
idealization of the man and his work. Thus Alexander Pope’s famous epitaph: Nature
and Nature’s laws lay hid in night; God said, “Let Newton be!” and all was
light. The term ‘Newtonian’, then, denoted the view of nature as a universal
system of mathematical reason and order divinely created and administered. The
metaphor of a “universal machine” was frequently applied. The view is central
in the eighteenth-century Enlightenment, inspiring a religion of reason and the
scientific study of society and the human mind. More narrowly, ‘Newtonian’
suggests a reduction of any subject matter to an ontology of individual
particles and the laws and basic terms of mechanics: mass, length, and time.
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Hypotheses non fingo: Newton e la sua mela,” Luigi
Speranza, per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice,
Liguria, Italia.
Autrecourt, philosopher, unimaginatively born
in Autrecourt, he was educated at Paris (“but I kept Autrecourt as my surname,
Paris being so common” – “Letter to Matthew Parris” --) and earned bachelor’s
degrees in theology and law and a master’s degree in arts. After a list of
propositions from his writings was condemned in 1346, he was sentenced to burn
his works publicly and recant, which he did in Paris the following year. He was
appointed dean of Metz cathedral in 1350. Nicholas’s ecclesiastical troubles
arose partly from nine letters two of which survive which reduce to absurdity
the view that appearances provide a sufficient basis for certain and evident
knowledge. On the contrary, except for “certitude of the faith,” we can be certain
only of what is equivalent or reducible to the principle of noncontradiction.
He accepts as a consequence of this that we can never validly infer the
existence of one distinct thing from another, including the existence of
substances from qualities, or causes from effects. Indeed, he finds that “in
the whole of his natural philosophy and metaphysics, Aristotle had such
[evident] certainty of scarcely two conclusions, and perhaps not even of one.”
Nicholas devotes another work, the Exigit ordo executionis also known as The
Universal Treatise, to an extended critique of Aristotelianism. It attacks what
seemed to him the blind adherence given by his contemporaries to Aristotle and
Averroes, showing that the opposite of many conclusions alleged to have been demonstrated
by the Philosopher e.g., on the
divisibility of continua, the reality of motion, and the truth of
appearances are just as evident or
apparent as those conclusions themselves. Because so few of his writings are
extant, however, it is difficult to ascertain just what Nicholas’s own views
were. Likewise, the reasons for his condemnation are not well understood,
although recent studies have suggested that his troubles might have been due to
a reaction to certain ideas that he appropriated from English theologians, such
as Adam de Wodeham. Nicholas’s views elicited comment not only from church
authorities, but also from other philosophers, including Buridan, Marsilius of
Inghen, Albert of Saxony, and Nicholas of Oresme. Despite a few surface similarities,
however, there is no evidence that his teachings on certainty or causality had
any influence on modern philosophers, such as Descartes or Hume.
Intellectus:
The sensus-intellectus distinction, the: Grice: “Occam’s adage presupposes a
bi-partite philosophical psychology for the credibility realm: the ‘sensus,’ or
perceptual level, and the ‘intellectus,’ or the realm of intellect. nihil est
in intellectu quod non prius fuerit in sensu: a principal tenet of empiricism.
A weak interpretation of the principle maintains that all concepts are acquired
from sensory experience; no concepts are innate or a priori. A stronger
interpretation adds that all propositional knowledge is derived from sense
experience. The weak interpretation was held by Aquinas and Locke, who thought
nevertheless that we can know some propositions to be true in virtue of the
relations between the concepts involved. The stronger interpretation was
endorsed by J. S. Mill, who argued that even the truths of mathematics are inductively
based on experience, as Grice tutored R. Wollheim for his PPE at Oxford: “How
did you find that out?” “Multiplication.” “That proves Mill wrong.”
Activum/passivum distinction: used by
Grice, ‘nous poietikos’ ‘nous – intellectus activus, intellectus passivus --.
Grice thought ‘active’ was misused there, “unless there is a hint that Aquinas
means that the self-conscious soul is the site of personal identity, which
‘does’ things.” --.
Nihil ex nihilo fit – Grice: “an intuitive
metaphysical principle first enunciated by Parmenides, often held equivalent to
the proposition that nothing arises without a cause. Creation ex nihilo is
God’s production of the world without any natural or material cause, but
involves a supernatural cause, and so it would not violate the principle.
Noce: essential Italian
philosopher. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice e del Noce," per Il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
Nous – Grice’s favourite formation from
nous is ‘noetic’, noetic – the opposite of the favourite Griceian sub-disipline
in philosophy, aesthetics -- from Grecian noetikos, from noetos, ‘perceiving’,
of or relating to apprehension by the intellect. In a strict sense the term refers
to nonsensuous data given to the cognitive faculty, which discloses their
intelligible meaning as distinguished from their sensible apprehension. We hear
a sentence spoken, but it becomes intelligible for us only when the sounds
function as a foundation for noetic apprehension. For Plato, the objects of
such apprehension noetá are the Forms eide with respect to which the sensible
phenomena are only occasions of manifestation: the Forms in themselves
transcend the sensible and have their being in a realm apart. For empiricist
thinkers, e.g., Locke, there is strictly speaking no distinct noetic aspect,
since “ideas” are only faint sense impressions. In a looser sense, however, one
may speak of ideas as independent of reference to particular sense impressions,
i.e. independent of their origin, and then an idea can be taken to signify a
class of objects. Husserl uses the term to describe the intentionality or
dyadic character of consciousness in general, i.e. including both eidetic or
categorial and perceptual knowing. He speaks of the correlation of noesis or
intending and noema or the intended object of awareness. The categorial or
eidetic is the perceptual object as intellectually cognized; it is not a realm
apart, but rather what is disclosed or made present “constituted” Nihil est in
intellectu quod non prius fuerit in sensu noetic 617 617 when the mode of appearance of the
perceptual object is intended by a categorial noesis.
euclidean/non-euclideeian
distinction, the:
– as applied to geometry. H. P. Grice, “Non-Euclidean implicatura of space” –
“Non-Euclidean geometrical implicatura – None-euclidean geometry refers to any
axiomatized version of geometry in which Euclides’s parallel axiom is rejected,
after so many unsuccessful attempts to prove it. As in so many branches of
mathematics, Gauss had thought out much of the matter first, but he kept most
of his ideas to himself. As a result, credit is given to Bolyai and Lobachevsky.
Instead of assuming that just one line passes through a point in a plane
parallel to a non-coincident co-planar line, Bolyai and Loachevsky offer a
geometry in which a line admits more than one parallel, and the sum of the
“angles” between the “sides” of a “triangle” lies below 180°. Then Riemann
conceived of a geometry in which lines always meet so no parallels, and the sum
of the “angles” exceeds 180°. In this connection Riemann distinguishes between
the unboundedness of space as a property of its extent, and the special case of
the infinite measure over which distance might be taken which is dependent upon
the curvature of that space. Pursuing the published insight of Gauss, that the
curvature of a surface could be defined in terms only of properties dependent
solely on the surface itself and later called “intrinsic”, Riemann also defines
the metric on a surface in a very general and intrinsic way, in terms of the
differential arc length. Thereby he clarified the ideas of “distance” that his
non-Euclidean precursors had introduced drawing on trigonometric and hyperbolic
functions; arc length was now understood geodesically as the shortest
“distance” between two “points” on a surface, and was specified independent of
any assumptions of a geometry within which the surface was embedded. Further
properties, such as that pertaining to the “volume” of a three-“dimensional”
solid, were also studied. The two main types of non-Euclidean geometry, and its
Euclidean parent, may be summarized as follows: Reaction to these geometries
was slow to develop, but their impact gradually emerged. As mathematics, their
legitimacy was doubted; but Beltrami produced a model of a Bolyai-type
two-dimensional space inside a planar circle. The importance of this model was
to show that the consistency of this geometry depended upon that of the
Euclidean version, thereby dispelling the fear that it was an inconsistent
flash of the imagination. During the last thirty years of the nineteenth
century a variety of variant geometries were proposed, and the relationships
between them were studied, together with consequences for projective geometry.
On the empirical side, these geometries, and especially Riemann’s approach,
affected the understanding of the relationship between geometry and space; in
particular, it posed the question whether space is curved or not the later
being the Euclidean answer. The geometries thus played a role in the emergence
and articulation of relativity theory, especially the differential geometry and
tensorial calculus within which its mathematical properties could be expressed.
Philosophically the new geometries stressed the hypothetical nature of
axiomatizing, in contrast to the customary view of mathematical theories as
true in some usually unclear sense. This feature led to the name ‘meta-geometry’
for them. It was intended as an ironical proposal of opponents to be in line
with the hypothetical character of meta-physics (and meta-ethics) in
philosophy. They also helped to encourage conventionalist philosophy of science
with Poincaré, e.g., and put fresh light on the age-old question of the impossibility
of a priori knowledge.
monotonic/non-monotonice
distinction, the: Grice: “It may be argued that we do not need ‘polytonic,’
just a concept that NEGATES monotone – but since at Clifton I learned about
Grecian polytonicity, I like the idea!” -- “On occasion, the semantics of
implicatura is non-monotonic, i. e. a
logic that fails to be monotonic -- i.e., in proof-theoretic terms, fails to
meet the condition that for all statements u1, . . . un, if f,y, if ‘u1, . . .
un Yf’, for any y, ‘u1 , . . . un, y Y f’. Equivalently, let Γ represent a
collection of statements, u1 . . . un, and say that in a monotonic system, such
as system G (after Grice), if ‘Γ Y f’, for any y, ‘Γ, y Y f’ and similarly in
other cases. A non-monotonic system is any system with the following property:
For some Γ, f, and y, ‘ΓNML f’ but ‘Γ, y K!NML f’. This is what Grice calls a
“weak” non-monotonic system G-w-n-m. In contrast, in a “strong” non-monotonic
system – G-s-n-m, we might have, again for some Γ, f, y, where Γ is consistent
and Γ 8 f is consistent: ‘Γ, y YNML > f’. A primary motivation for Grice for
a non-monotonic system or defeasible reasoning, which is so evident in
conversational reasoning, is to produce a representation for default (ceteris
paribus) reasoning or defeasible reasoning. Grice’s interest in defeasible (or
ceteris paribus) reasoning – for conversational implicatura -- readily spreads
to epistemology, logic, and meta-ethics. The exigencies of this or that
practical affair requires leaping to conclusions, going beyond available
evidence, making assumptions. In doing so, Grice often errs and must leap back
from his conclusion, undo his assumption, revise his belief. In Grice’s
standard example, “Tweety is a bird and all birds fly, except penguins and
ostriches. Does Tweety fly?” If pressed, Grice needs to form a belief about
this matter. Upon discovering that Tweety is a penguin, Grice may have to re-tract
his conclusion. Any representation of defeasible (or ceteris paribus) reasoning
must capture the non-monotonicity of this reasoning. A non-monotonic system
G-s-n-m is an attempt to do this by adding this or that rule of inference that
does not preserve monotonicity. Although a practical affair may require Grice
to reason “defeasibly” – an adverb Grice borrowed from Hart -- the best way to
achieve non-monotonicity may not be to add this or that non-monotonic rule of
inference to System G. What one gives up in such system may well not be worth
the cost: loss of the deduction theorem and of a coherent notion of
consistency. Therefore, Grice’s challenge for a non-monotonic system and for defeasible
reasoning, generally is to develop a rigorous way to re-present the structure
of non-monotonic reasoning without losing or abandoning this or that historically
hard-won propertiy of a monotonic system. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Monotonicity,
and Polytonicity.” G. P. Baker, “Meaning and defeasibility,” in festschrift for
H. L. A. Hart; R. Hall, “Excluders;” H. P. Grice, “Ceteris paribus and
defeasibility.”
nonviolence: H. P. Grice
joined the Royal Navy in 1941 – and served till 1945, earning the degree of captain.
He was involved in the North-Atlantic theatre and later at the Admiralty.
Non-violence is the renunciation of violence in personal, social, or
international affairs. It often includes a commitment called active nonviolence
or nonviolent direct action actively to oppose violence and usually evil or
injustice as well by nonviolent means. Nonviolence may renounce physical
violence alone or both physical and psychological violence. It may represent a
purely personal commitment or be intended to be normative for others as well.
When unconditional absolute 619 norm normative relativism 620
nonviolence it renounces violence in all
actual and hypothetical circumstances. When conditional conditional nonviolence it concedes the justifiability of violence in
hypothetical circumstances but denies it in practice. Held on moral grounds
principled nonviolence, the commitment belongs to an ethics of conduct or an
ethics of virtue. If the former, it will likely be expressed as a moral rule or
principle e.g., One ought always to act nonviolently to guide action. If the
latter, it will urge cultivating the traits and dispositions of a nonviolent
character which presumably then will be expressed in nonviolent action. As a
principle, nonviolence may be considered either basic or derivative. Either
way, its justification will be either utilitarian or deontological. Held on
non-moral grounds pragmatic nonviolence, nonviolence is a means to specific
social, political, economic, or other ends, themselves held on non-moral
grounds. Its justification lies in its effectiveness for these limited purposes
rather than as a way of life or a guide to conduct in general. An alternative
source of power, it may then be used in the service of evil as well as good.
Nonviolent social action, whether of a principled or pragmatic sort, may
include noncooperation, mass demonstrations, marches, strikes, boycotts, and
civil disobedience techniques explored
extensively in the writings of Gene Sharp. Undertaken in defense of an entire
nation or state, nonviolence provides an alternative to war. It seeks to deny
an invading or occupying force the capacity to attain its objectives by
withholding the cooperation of the populace needed for effective rule and by
nonviolent direct action, including civil disobedience. It may also be used
against oppressive domestic rule or on behalf of social justice. Gandhi’s
campaign against British rule in India, Scandinavian resistance to Nazi
occupation during World War II, and Martin Luther King, Jr.’s actions on behalf
of civil rights in the United States are illustrative. Nonviolence has origins
in Far Eastern thought, particularly Taoism and Jainism. It has strands in the
Jewish Talmud, and many find it implied by the New Testament’s Sermon on the
Mount. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “My Royal Navy days: memoirs of a captain.”
normal/non-normal
distinction, the: Grice:
I shall refer to the ‘normal form’ as a formula equivalent to a given formula, but having special properties. The
main varieties follow. A Conjunctive normal form. If D1 . . . Dn are
disjunctions of sentential variables or their negations, such as p 7 -q 7 r, a
formula F is in what I shall call
“conjunctive normal form” provided F % D1 & D2 & . . & Dn. The
following are in conjunctive normal form: -p 7 q; p 7 q 7 r & -p 7 -q 7 -r
& -q 7 r. Every formula of Grice’s predicate calculus – System G, Gricese
-- has an equivalent “conjunctive normal
form.” This fact can be used to prove the completeness of sentential logic.
Disjunctive normal form. If C1 . . . Cn are conjunctions of sentential
variables or their negations, such as p & -q & -r, a formula F is in what I shall call “disjunctive
normal form” provided F % C1 7 C27 . . Cn. The following are thus in
disjunctive normal form: p & -q 7 -p & q; p & q & -r 7 -p &
-q & -r. Every formula of sentential logic has an equivalent disjunctive
normal form. Prenex normal form. A formula of Grice’s predicate calculus –
system G, Gricese -- is in what Grice calls “prenex normal form” if 1 every
quantifier occurs at the beginning of the formula, 2 the scope of the
quantifiers extends to the end of the formula, and 3 what follows the
quantifiers contains at least one occurrence of every variable that appears in
the set of quantifiers. Thus, DxDyFx / Gy and xDyzFxy 7 Gyz / Dxyz are in what
I shall call “prenex normal form.” The formula may contain free variables;
thus, Dxy Fxyz / Gwyx is also in prenex normal form. The following, however,
are not in prenex normal form: xDy Fx / Gx; xy Fxy / Gxy. Every formula of
Grice’s predicate calculus – System G, Gricese -- has an equivalent formula in
prenex normal form. A formula F in predicate logic is in what Grice, as a
tribute to Skolem, calls the “Skolem normal form” provided 1 F is in prenex
normal form, 2 every existential quantifier precedes any universal quantifier,
3 F contains at least one existential quantifier, and 4 F contains no free
variables. Thus, DxDy zFxy / Gyz and DxDyDzwFxy 7 Fyz 7 Fzw are in Skolem
normal form; however, Dx y Fxyz and x y Fxy 7 Gyx are not. Any formula has an equivalent
Skolem normal form. “This has implications for the lack of completeness of my
predicate calculus – but do I worry?”. Refs.: Grice, “Normal and abnormal
forms: a logical introduction.”
notum: Grice was slightly obsessed with “know,” Latin
‘notum – nosco’ -- nosco , nōvi, nōtum, 3 (old form,
GNOSCO, GNOVI, GNOTVM, acc. to Prisc. p. 569 P.; I.inf. pass. GNOSCIER, S. C.
de Bacch.; cf. GNOTV, cognitu, Paul. ex Fest. p. 96 Müll.: GNOT (contr. for gnovit)
οἶδεν, ἐπιγινώσκει; GNOTV, γνῶσιν, διάγνωσιν, Gloss. Labb.—Contr. forms in
class. Lat. are nosti, noram, norim. nosse; nomus for novimus: nomus ambo
Ulixem, Enn. ap. Diom. p. 382 P., or Trag. v. 199 Vahl.), v. a. for gnosco,
from the root gno; Gr. γιγνώσκω, to begin to know, to get a knowledge of,
become acquainted with, come to know a thing (syn.: scio, calleo). I. Lit. 1.
(α). Tempp. praes.: “cum igitur, nosce te, dicit, hoc dicit, nosce animum
tuum,” Cic. Tusc. 1, 22, 52: Me. Sauream non novi. Li. At nosce sane, Plaut.
As. 2, 4, 58; cf.: Ch. Nosce signum. Ni. Novi, id. Bacch. 4, 6, 19; id. Poen.
4, 2, 71: “(Juppiter) nos per gentes alium alia disparat, Hominum qui facta,
mores, pietatem et fidem noscamus,” id. Rud. prol. 12; id. Stich. 1, 1, 4: “id
esse verum, cuivis facile est noscere,” Ter. Ad. 5, 4, 8: “ut noscere possis
quidque,” Lucr. 1, 190; 2, 832; 3, 124; 418; 588; Cic. Rep. 1, 41, 64: deus
ille, quem mente noscimus, id. N. D. 1, 14, 37.—Pass.: “EAM (tabulam) FIGIER
IOVBEATIS, VBEI FACILVMED GNOSCIER POTISIT, S. C. de Bacch.: forma in tenebris
nosci non quita est, Ter Hec. 4, 1, 57 sq.: omnes philosophiae partes tum
facile noscuntur, cum, etc.,” Cic. N. D. 1, 4, 9: philosophiae praecepta
noscenda, id. Fragm. ap. Lact. 3, 14: “nullique videnda, Voce tamen noscar,”
Ov. M. 14, 153: “nec noscitur ulli,” by any one, id. Tr. 1, 5, 29: “noscere
provinciam, nosci exercitui,” by the army, Tac. Agr. 5.— (β). Temppperf., to
have become acquainted with, to have learned, to know: “si me novisti minus,” Plaut.
Aul. 4, 10, 47: “Cylindrus ego sum, non nosti nomen meum?” id. Men. 2, 2, 20:
“novi rem omnem,” Ter. And. 4, 4, 50: “qui non leges, non instituta ... non
jura noritis,” Cic. Pis. 13, 30: “plerique neque in rebus humanis quidquam
bonum norunt, nisi, etc.,” id. Lael. 21, 79: “quam (virtutem) tu ne de facie
quidem nosti,” id. Pis. 32, 81; id. Fin. 2, 22, 71: “si ego hos bene novi,” if
I know them well, id. Rosc. Am. 20 fin.: si Caesarem bene novi, Balb. ap. Cic.
Att. 9, 7, B, 2: “Lepidum pulchre noram,” Cic. Fam. 10, 23, 1: “si tuos digitos
novi,” id. Att. 5, 21, 13: “res gestas de libris novisse,” to have learned from
books, Lact. 5, 19, 15: “nosse Graece, etc. (late Lat. for scire),” Aug. Serm.
45, 5; 167, 40 al.: “ut ibi esses, ubi nec Pelopidarum—nosti cetera,” Cic. Fam.
7, 28, 2; Plin. Ep. 3, 9, 11.— 2. To examine, consider: “ad res suas
noscendas,” Liv. 10, 20: “imaginem,” Plaut. Ps. 4, 2, 29.—So esp., to take
cognizance of as a judge: “quae olim a praetoribus noscebantur,” Tac. A. 12,
60.— II. Transf., in the tempp. praes. A. In gen., to know, recognize (rare;
perh. not in Cic.): hau nosco tuom, I know your (character, etc.), i. e. I know
you no longer, Plaut. Trin. 2, 4, 44: “nosce imaginem,” id. Ps. 4, 2, 29; id.
Bacch. 4, 6, 19: “potesne ex his ut proprium quid noscere?” Hor. S. 2, 7, 89;
Tac. H. 1, 90.— B. In partic., to acknowledge, allow, admit of a reason or an
excuse (in Cic.): “numquam amatoris meretricem oportet causam noscere, Quin,
etc.,” Plaut. Truc. 2, 1, 18: “illam partem excusationis ... nec nosco, nec
probo,” Cic. Fam. 4, 4, 1; cf.: “quod te excusas: ego vero et tuas causas
nosco, et, etc.,” id. Att. 11, 7, 4: “atque vereor, ne istam causam nemo
noscat,” id. Leg. 1, 4, 11.— III. Transf. in tempp. perf. A. To be acquainted
with, i. e. to practise, possess: “alia vitia non nosse,” Sen. Q. N. 4 praef. §
9.— B. In mal. part., to know (in paronomasia), Plaut. Most. 4, 2, 13; id.
Pers. 1, 3, 51.— IV. (Eccl. Lat.) Of religious knowledge: “non noverant
Dominum,” Vulg. Judic. 2, 12; ib. 2 Thess. 1, 8: “Jesum novi, Paulum scio,” I
acknowledge, ib. Act. 19, 15.—Hence, nōtus , a, um, P. a., known. A. Lit.:
“nisi rem tam notam esse omnibus et tam manifestam videres,” Cic. Verr. 2, 3,
58, 134: “ejusmodi res ita notas, ita testatas, ita manifestas proferam,” id.
ib. 2, 2, 34, § “85: fingi haec putatis, quae patent, quae nota sunt omnibus,
quae tenentur?” id. Mil. 28, 76: “noti atque insignes latrones,” id. Phil. 11,
5, 10: “habere omnes philosophiae notos et tractatos locos,” id. Or. 33, 118:
“facere aliquid alicui notum,” id. Fam. 5, 12, 7: “tua nobilitas hominibus
litteratis est notior, populo obscurior,” id. Mur. 7, 16: “nullus fuit civis
Romanus paulo notior, quin, etc.,” Caes. B. C. 2, 19: “vita P. Sullae vobis
populoque Romano notissima,” Cic. Sull. 26, 72: “nulli nota domus sua,” Juv. 1,
7.— (β). With gen. (poet.): “notus in fratres animi paterni,” Hor. C. 2, 2, 6:
noti operum Telchines. Stat. Th. 2, 274: “notusque fugarum, Vertit terga,” Sil.
17, 148.— (γ). With subj.-clause: “notum est, cur, etc.,” Juv. 2, 58.— (δ).
With inf. (poet.): “Delius, Trojanos notus semper minuisse labores,” Sil. 12,
331.— 2. In partic. a. Subst.: nōti , acquaintances, friends: “de dignitate M.
Caelius notis ac majoribus natu ... respondet,” Cic. Cael. 2, 3: “hi suos notos
hospitesque quaerebant,” Caes. B. C. 1, 74, 5; Hor. S. 1, 1, 85; Verg. Cir.
259.— b. In a bad sense, notorious: “notissimi latronum duces,” Cic. Fam. 10,
14, 1: “integrae Temptator Orion Dianae,” Hor. C. 3, 4, 70; Ov. M. 1, 198:
“Clodia, mulier non solum nobilis sed etiam nota,” Cic. Cael. 13, 31; cf. Cic.
Verr. 1, 6, 15: “moechorum notissimus,” Juv. 6, 42.— B. Transf., act., knowing,
that knows: novi, notis praedicas, to those that know, Plaut. Ps. 4, 2, 39.Chisholm:
r. m. influential philosopher whose publications
spanned the field, including ethics and the history of philosophy. He is mainly
known as an epistemologist, metaphysician, and philosopher of mind. In early
opposition to powerful forms of reductionism, such as phenomenalism,
extensionalism, and physicalism, Chisholm developed an original philosophy of
his own. Educated at Brown and Harvard Ph.D., 2, he spent nearly his entire
career at Brown. He is known chiefly for the following contributions. a
Together with his teacher and later his colleague at Brown, C. J. Ducasse, he
developed and long defended an adverbial account of sensory experience, set
against the sense-datum act-object account then dominant. b Based on deeply
probing analysis of the free will problematic, he defended a libertarian position,
again in opposition to the compatibilism long orthodox in analytic circles. His
libertarianism had, moreover, an unusual account of agency, based on
distinguishing transeunt event causation from immanent agent causation. c In
opposition to the celebrated linguistic turn of linguistic philosophy, he
defended the primacy of intentionality, a defense made famous not only through
important papers, but also through his extensive and eventually published
correspondence with Wilfrid Sellars. d Quick to recognize the importance and
distinctiveness of the de se, he welcomed it as a basis for much de re thought.
e His realist ontology is developed through an intentional concept of
“entailment,” used to define key concepts of his system, and to provide criteria
of identity for occupants of fundamental categories. f In epistemology, he
famously defended forms of foundationalism and internalism, and offered a
delicately argued dissolution of the ancient problem of the criterion. The
principles of Chisholm’s epistemology and metaphysics are not laid down
antecedently as hard-and-fast axioms. Lacking any inviolable antecedent
privilege, they must pass muster in the light of their consequences and by
comparison with whatever else we may find plausible. In this regard he sharply
contrasts with such epistemologists as Popper, with the skepticism of
justification attendant on his deductivism, and Quine, whose stranded
naturalism drives so much of his radical epistemology and metaphysics. By
contrast, Chisholm has no antecedently set epistemic or metaphysical
principles. His philosophical views develop rather dialectically, with
sensitivity to whatever considerations, examples, or counterexamples reflection
may reveal as relevant. This makes for a demanding complexity of elaboration,
relieved, however, by a powerful drive for ontological and conceptual
economy. notum per se Latin, ‘known
through itself’, self-evident. This term corresponds roughly to the term
‘analytic’. In Thomistic theology, there are two ways for a thing to be
self-evident, secundum se in itself and quoad nos to us. The proposition that
God exists is self-evident in itself, because God’s existence is identical with
his essence; but it is not self-evident to us humans, because humans are not
directly acquainted with God’s essence.Aquinas’s Summa theologiae I, q.2,a.1,c.
For Grice, by uttering “Smith knows that p,” the emisor explicitly conveys, via
semantic truth-conditional entailment, that (1) p; (2) Smith believes that p;
(3) if (1), (2); and conversationally implicates, in a defeasible pragmatic
way, explainable by his adherence to the principle of conversational
co-operation, that Smith is guaranteeing that p.”Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The
monosemy of ‘know’,” H. P. Grice, “The implicatura of ‘know;’” H. P. Grice, “’I
know’ and ‘I guarantee’;” H. P. Grice, “Austin’s performatory fallacy on ‘know’
and ‘guarantee.’”
conventional/non-conventional distinction, the: “If I were to rename all my taxonomies, I
would say I have always been unconventional, and that it was not convention I’m
interested, but unconventionality --. Grice: “Philosophers and the
unconventional.” “Implicature and the unconventional philosopher.” -- “If I
have to chose, I chose non-conventional, but I don’t have to, so I shall use
‘unconventional.’” -- Unfortunately, Grice never came up with a word or
sobriquet for the non-conventional, and kept using the ‘non-conventional.’
Similarly, he never came up with a positive way to refer to the non-natural,
and non-natural it remained. Luckily, we can take it as a joke. Convention
figures TWICE in Grice’s scheme. For his reductive analysis of communication,
he surely can avoid convention by relying on a self-referring anti-sneaky
clause. But when it comes to the ‘taxonomy’ of the ‘shades’ of implication, he
wants the emissor to implicate that p WITHOUT relying on a convention. If the
emissor RELIES on a convention, there are problems for his analysis. Why? First,
at the explicit level, it can be assumed that conventions will feature (Smith’s
dog is ‘by convention’ called ‘Fido”). At the level of the implied, there are
two ways where convention matters in a wrong way. “My neighbour’s
three-year-old is an adult” FLOUTS a convention – or meaning postulate. And it
corresponds to the entailment. But finally, there is a third realm of the
conventional. For particles like “therefore,” or ‘but.’ “But” Grice does not
care much about, but ‘therefore’ he does. He wants to say that ‘therefore’ is
mainly emphatic.The emissor implies a passage from premise to conclusion. And
that implication relies on a convention YET it is not part of the entailment.
So basically, it is an otiose addition. Why would rational conversationalists
rely on them? The rationale for this is that Grice wants to provide a GENERAL
theory of communication that will defeat Austin’s convention-tied ritualistic
view of language. So Grice needs his crucial philosophical refutations NOT to
rely on convention. What relies on convention cannot be cancellable. What
doesn’t can. I an item relies on convention it has not really redeemed from
that part of the communicative act that can not be explained rationally by
argument. There is no way to calculate a conventional item. It is just a given.
And Grice is interested in providing a rationale. His whole campaign relates to
this idea that Austin has rushed, having detected a nuance in a linguistic
phenomenon, to explain it away, without having explored in detail what kind of
nuance it is. For Grice it is NOT a conventional nuance – it’s a sous-entendu
of conversation (as Mill has it), an unnecessary implication (as Russell has
it). Why did Grice chose ‘convention’? The influence of Lewis seems minor,
because he touches on the topic in “Causal Theory,” before Lewis. The word
‘convention’ does NOT occur in “Causal Theory,” though. But there are phrasings
to that effect. Notably, let us consider his commentary in the reprint, when he
omits the excursus. He says that he presents FOUR cases: a particularized
conversational (‘beautiful handwriting’), a generalised conversational (“in the
kitchen or in the bedroom”), a ‘conventional implicaturum’ (“She was poor but
she was honest”) and a presupposition (“You have not ceased to eat iron”). So
the obvious target for exploration is the third, where Grice has the rubric
‘convention,’ as per ‘conventional.’ So his expansion on the ‘but’ example
(what Frege has as ‘colouring’ of “aber”) is interesting to revise. “plied is that Smith
has been bcating his wifc. (2) " She was poor but she was honcst ",
whele what is implied is (vcry roughly) that there is some contrast between
poverty and honesty, or between her poverty and her honesty. The first cxample
is a stock case of what is sometimes called " prcsupposition " and it
is often held that here 1he truth of what is irnplicd is a necessary condition
of the original statement's beirrg cither true or false. This might be
disputed, but it is at lcast arguable that it is so, and its being arguable
might be enough to distinguish-this type of case from others. I shall however
for convenience assume that the common view mentioned is correct. This
consideration clearly distinguishes (1) from (2); even if the implied
proposition were false, i.e. if there were no reason in the world to contrast
poverty with honesty either in general or in her case, the original statement
could still be false; it would be false if for example she were rich and
dishonest. One might perhaps be less comfortable about assenting to its truth
if the implied contrast did not in fact obtain; but the possibility of falsity
is enough for the immediate purpose. My next experiment on these examples is to
ask what it is in each case which could properly be said to be the vehicle of implication
(to do the implying). There are at least four candidates, not necessarily
mutually exclusive. Supposing someone to have uttered one or other of my sample
sentences, we may ask whether the vehicle of implication would be (a) what the
speaker said (or asserted), or (b) the speaker (" did he imply that . . .
.':) or (c) the words the speaker used, or (d) his saying that (or again his
saying that in that way); or possibly some plurality of these items. As regards
(a) I think (1) and (2) differ; I think it would be correct to say in the case
of (l) that what he speaker said (or asserted) implied that Smith had been
beating this wife, and incorrect to say in the case of (2) that what te said
(or asserted) implied that there was a contrast between e.g., honesty and
poverty. A test on which I would rely is the following : if accepting that the
implication holds involves one in r27 128 H. P. GRICE accepting an
hypothetical' if p then q ' where 'p ' represents the original statement and '
q' represents what is implied, then what the speaker said (or asserted) is a
vehicle of implication, otherwise not. To apply this rule to the given
examples, if I accepted the implication alleged to hold in the case of (1), I
should feel compelled to accept the hypothetical " If Smith has left off
beating his wife, then he has been beating her "; whereas if I accepted
the alleged implication in the case of (2), I should not feel compelled to
accept the hypothetical " If she was poor but honest, then there is some
contrast between poverty and honesty, or between her poverty and her
honesty." The other candidates can be dealt with more cursorily; I should
be inclined to say with regard to both (l) and (2) that the speaker could be
said to have implied whatever it is that is irnplied; that in the case of (2)
it seems fairly clear that the speaker's words could be said to imply a
contrast, whereas it is much less clear whether in the case of (1) the
speaker's words could be said to imply that Smith had been beating his wife;
and that in neither case would it be evidently appropriate to speak of his
saying that, or of his saying that in that way, as implying what is implied.
The third idea with which I wish to assail my two examples is really a twin
idea, that of the detachability or cancellability of the implication. (These
terms will be explained.) Consider example (1): one cannot fi.nd a form of
words which could be used to state or assert just what the sentence "
Smith has left off beating his wife " might be used to assert such that
when it is used the implication that Smith has been beating his wife is just
absent. Any way of asserting what is asserted in (1) involves the irnplication
in question. I shall express this fact by saying that in the case of (l) the
implication is not detqchable from what is asserted (or simpliciter, is not
detachable). Furthermore, one cannot take a form of words for which both what
is asserted and what is implied is the same as for (l), and then add a further
clause withholding commitment from what would otherwise be implied, with the
idea of annulling the implication without annulling the assertion. One cannot
intelligibly say " Smith has left off beating his wife but I do not mean
to imply that he has been beating her." I shall express this fact by saying
that in the case of (1) the implication is not cancellable (without THE CAUSAL
THEORY OF PERCEPTION r29 cancelling the assertion). If we turn to (2) we find,
I think, that there is quite a strong case for saying that here the implication
ls detachable. Thcrc sccms quitc a good case for maintaining that if, instead
of sayirrg " She is poor but shc is honcst " I were to say " She
is poor and slre is honcst", I would assert just what I would havc
asscrtcct ii I had used thc original senterrce; but there would now be no
irnplication of a contrast between e.g', povery and honesty. But the question
whether, in tl-re case of (2), thc inrplication is cancellable, is slightly
more cornplex. Thcrc is a sonse in which we may say that it is non-cancellable;
if sorncone were to say " She is poor but she is honest, though of course
I do not mean to imply that there is any contrast between poverty and honesty
", this would seem a puzzling and eccentric thing to have said; but though
we should wish to quarrel with the speaker, I do not think we should go so far
as to say that his utterance was unintelligible; we should suppose that he had
adopted a most peculiar way of conveying the the news that she was poor and
honesl. The fourth and last test that I wish to impose on my exarnples is to
ask whether we would be inclined to regard the fact that the appropriate
implication is present as being a matter of the meaning of some particular word
or phrase occurring in the sentences in question. I am aware that this may not
be always a very clear or easy question to answer; nevertheless Iwill risk the
assertion that we would be fairly happy to say that, as regards (2), the
factthat the implication obtains is a matter of the meaning of the word ' but
'; whereas so far as (l) is concerned we should have at least some inclination
to say that the presence of the implication was a matter of the meaning of some
of the words in the sentence, but we should be in some difficulty when it came
to specifying precisely which this word, or words are, of which this is true.”
Since the actual wording ‘convention’ does not occur it may do to revise how he
words ‘convention’ in Essay 2 of WoW. So here is the way he words it in Essay
II.“In some cases the CONVENTIONAL meaning of the WORDS used will DETERMINE
what is impliccated, besides helping to determine what is said.” Where
‘determine’ is the key word. It’s not “REASON,” conversational reason that
determines it. “If I say (smugly), ‘He is an Englishman; he is, therefore,
brave,’ I have certainly COMMITTED myself, by virtue of the meaning of my
words, to its being the case that his being brave is a consequence of (follows
from) his being an Englishman. But, while I have said that [or explicitly
conveyed THAT] he is an Englishman, and [I also have] said that [or explicitly
conveyed that] he is brave, I do not want to say [if I may play with what
people conventionally understand by ‘convention’] that I have said [or
explicitly conveyed] (in the favoured sense) that [or explicitly conveyed that]
it follows from his being an Englishman that he is brave, though I have
certainly INDICATED, and so implicated, that this is so.” The rationale as to
why the label is ‘convention’ comes next. “I do not want to say that my
utterance of this sentence would be, strictly speaking, FALSE should the
consequence in question fail to hold. So some implicaturums are conventional,
unlike the one with which I introduce this discussion of implicaturum.”Grice’s
observation or suggestion then or advise then, in terms of nomenclature. His
utterance WOULD be FALSE if the MEANING of ‘therefore’ were carried as an
ENTAILMENT (rather than emphatic truth-value irrelevant rhetorical emphasis).
He expands on this in The John Lecture, where Jill is challenged. “What do you
mean, “Jack is an Englishman; he is, therefore, brave”?” What is being
challenged is the validity of the consequence. ‘Therefore’ is vague enough NOT
to specify what type of consequence is meant. So, should someone challenge the
consequence, Jill would still be regarded by Grice as having uttered a TRUE
utterance. The metabolism here is complex since it involves assignment of
‘meaning’ to this or that expression (in this case ‘therefore’). In Essay VI he
is perhaps more systematic.The wider programme just mentioned arises out of a
distinction which, for purposes which I need not here specify, I wish to make
within the total signification of a remark: a distinction between what the
speaker has said (in a certain favoured, and maybe in some degree artificial,
sense of 'said'), and what he has 'implicated' (e.g. implied, indicated,
suggested, etc.), taking into account the fact that what he has implicated may
be either conventionally implicated (implicated by virtue of the meaning of
some word or phrase which he has used) or non-conventionally implicated (in
which case the specification of the implicaturum falls [TOTALLY] outside [AND
INDEPENDENTLY, i. e. as NOT DETERMINED BY] the specification of the
conventional meaning of the words used [Think ‘beautiful handwriting,’ think
‘In the kitchen or in the bedroom’). He is clearest in Essay 6 – where he adds
‘=p’ in the symbolization.UTTERER'S MEANING, SENTENCE-MEANING, AND WORD-MEANINGMy
present aim is to throw light on the connection between (a) a notion of
‘meaning’ which I want to regard as basic, viz. that notion which is involved
in saying of someone that ‘by’ (when) doing SUCH-AND-SUCH he means THAT
SO-AND-SO (in what I have called a non-natural use of 'means'), and (b) the
notions of meaning involved in saying First, that a given sentence means
'so-and-so' Second, that a given word or phrase means 'so-and-so'. What I have
to say on these topics should be looked upon as an attempt to provide a sketch
of what might, I hope, prove to be a viable theory, rather than as an attempt
to provide any part of a finally acceptable theory. The account which I shall
otTer of the (for me) basic notion of meaning is one which I shall not seek now to defend.I should like its
approximate correctness to be assumed, so that attention may be focused on its
utility, if correct, in the explication of other and (I hope) derivative
notions of meaning. This enterprise forms part of a wider programme which I
shall in a moment delineate, though its later stages lie beyond the limits
which I have set for this paper. The wider programme just mentioned arises out
of a distinction which, for purposes which I need not here specify, I wish to
make within the total signification of a remark: a distinction between what the
speaker has said (in a certain favoured, and maybe in some degree artificial,
sense of 'said'), and what he has 'implicated' (e.g. implied, indicated,
suggested, etc.), taking into account the fact that what he has implicated may
be either conventionally implicated (implicated by virtue of the meaning of
some word or phrase which he has used) or non-conventionally implicated (in
which case the specification of the implicaturum falls [TOTALLY] outside [AND
INDEPENDENTLY, i. e. as NOT DETERMINED BY] the specification of the
conventional meaning of the words used [Think ‘beautiful handwriting,’ think
‘In the kitchen or in the bedroom’). The programme is directed towards an
explication of the favoured SENSE of 'say' and a clarification of its relation
to the notion of conventional meaning. The stages of the programme are as
folIows: First, To distinguish between locutions of the form 'U (utterer) meant
that .. .' (locutions which specify what rnight be called 'occasion-meaning')
and locutions of the From Foundalions oJ Language. 4 (1968), pp. 1-18.
Reprinted by permission of the author and the editor of Foundations oJ
Language. I I hope that material in this paper, revised and re·arranged, will
form part of a book to be published by the Harvard University Press. form 'X (utterance-type) means H ••• "'.
In locutions of the first type, meaning is specified without the use of
quotation-marks, whereas in locutions of the second type the meaning of a sentence,
word or phrase is specified with the aid of quotation marks. This difference is
semantically important. Second, To attempt to provide a definiens for
statements of occasion-meaning; more precisely, to provide a definiens for 'By
(when) uttering x, U meant that *p'. Some explanatory comments are needed here.
First, I use the term 'utter' (together with 'utterance') in an artificially
wide sense, to cover any case of doing x or producing x by the performance of
which U meant that so-and-so. The performance in question need not be a
linguistic or even a conventionalized performance. A specificatory replacement
of the dummy 'x' will in some cases be a characterization of a deed, in others
a characterization of a product (e.g. asound). (b) '*' is a dummy mood-indicator,
distinct from specific mood-indicators like 'I-' (indicative or assertive) or
'!' (imperative). More precisely, one may think of the schema 'Jones meant that
*p' as yielding a full English sentence after two transformation al steps: (i)
replace '*' by a specific mood-indicator and replace 'p' by an indicative
sentence. One might thus get to 'Jones meant that I- Smith will go home' or to
'Jones meant that! Smith will go horne'. (ii) replace the sequence following
the word 'that' by an appropriate clause in indirect speech (in accordance with
rules specified in a linguistic theory). One might thus get to 'Jones meant
that Srnith will go horne' 'Jones meant that Srnith is to go horne'. Third, To
attempt to elucidate the notion of the conventional meaning of an
utterance-type; more precisely, to explicate sentences which make claims of the
form 'X (utterance-type) means "*''', or, in case X is a non-scntcntial
utterancctype, claims of the form 'X means H ••• "', where the location is
completed by a nonsentential expression. Again, some explanatory comments are
required. First, It will be convenient to recognize that what I shall call
statements of timeless meaning (statements of the type 'X means " ...
"', in which the ~pecification of meaning involves quotation-marks) may be
subdivided into (i) statements of timeless 'idiolect-meaning', e.g. 'For U (in
U's idiolect) X means " ... '" and (ü) statements of timeless
'Ianguage meaning', e.g. 'In L (language) X means " ... "'. It will
be convenient to handle these separately, and in the order just given. (b) The
truth of a statement to the effect that X means ' .. .' is of course not
incompatible with the truth of a further statement to the effect that X me ans
'--", when the two lacunae are quite differently completed. An
utterance-type rriay have more than one conventional meaning, and any definiens
which we offer must allow fOT this fact. 'X means " ... '" should be
understood as 'One of the meanings of X is " ... " '. (IV) In view of
the possibility of multiplicity in the timeless meaning of an utterance-type,
we shall need to notice, and to provide an explication of, what I shall call
the applied timeless meaning of an utterance-type. That is to say, we need a
definiens for the schema 'X (utterance-type) meant here " ... "', a
schema the specifications of which announce the correct reading of X for a
given occasion of utterance. Comments. (a) We must be careful to distinguish
the applied timeless meaning of X (type) with respecf to a particular token x (belonging
to X) from the occasionmeaning of U's utterance of x. The following are not
equivalent: (i) 'When U uttered it, the sentence "Palmer gave Nickiaus
quite a beating" meant "Palmer vanquished Nickiaus with some
ease" [rather than, say, "Palmer administered vigorous corporal
punishment to NickIaus."]' (ii) 'When U uttered the sentence "Palmer
gave NickIaus quite a beating" U meant that Palmer vanquished NickIaus
with some ease.' U might have been speaking ironically, in which case he would
very likely have meant that NickIaus vanquished Palmer with some ease. In that
case (ii) would c1early be false; but nevertheless (i) would still have been
true. Second, There is some temptation to take the view that the conjunction of
One, 'By uttering X, U meant that *p' and (Two, 'When uttered by U, X meant
"*p'" provides a definiens for 'In uttering X, U said [OR EXPLICITLY
CONVEYED] that *p'. Indeed, ifwe give consideration only to utterance-types for
which there are available adequate statements of time1ess meaning taking the
exemplary form 'X meant "*p'" (or, in the case of applied time1ess
meaning, the form 'X meant here "*p" '), it may even be possible to
uphold the thesis that such a coincidence of occasion-meaning and applied
time1ess meaning is a necessary and sufficient condition for saying that *p.
But a litde refiection should convince us of the need to recognize the
existence of statements of timeless meaning which instantiate forms other than
the cited exemplary form. There are, I think, at least some sentences whose
‘timeless’ meaning is not adequately specifiable by a statement of the
exemplary form. Consider the sentence 'Bill is a philosopher and he is,
therefore, brave' (S ,). Or Jill: “Jack is an Englishman; he is, therefore,
brave.”It would be appropriate, I think, to make a partial specification of the
timeless meaning of S, by saying 'Part of one meaning of S, is "Bill is
occupationally engaged in philosophical studies" '. One might, indeed,
give a full specifu::ation of timeless meaning for S, by saying 'One meaning of
S, inc1udes "Bill is occupationally engaged in philosophie al
studies" and "Bill is courageous" and "[The fact] That Bill
is courageous follows from his being occupationally engaged in philosophical
studies", and that is all that is included'. We might re-express this as 'One meaning of
S, comprises "Bill is occupationally engaged (etc)", "Bill is
courageous", and "That Bill is
eourageous follows (ete .)".'] It will be preferable to speeify the
timeless meaning of S I in this way than to do so as folIows: 'One meaning of S
I is "Bill is occupationally engaged (etc.) and Bill is courageous and
that Bill is eourageous follows (ete.)" '; for this latter formulation at
least suggests that SI is synonymous with the conjunctive sentence quoted in
the formulation, whieh does not seem to be the case. Since it is true that
another meaning of SI inc1udes 'Bill is addicted to general reftections about
life' (vice 'Bill is occupationally engaged (etc.)'), one could have occasion
to say (truly), with respect to a given utterance by U of SI' 'The meaning of
SI HERE comprised "Bill is oecupationally engaged (ete.)", "Bill
is eourageous", and "That Bill is courageous follows (ete.)"', or
to say 'The meaning of S I HERE included "That Bill is courageous follows
(etc.)" '. It could also be true that when U uttered SI he meant (part of
what he meant was) that that Bill is eourageous follows (ete.). Now I do not
wish to allow that, in my favoured sense of'say', one who utters SI will have
said [OR EXPLICITLY CONVEYED ] that Bill's being courageous follows from his
being a philosopher, though he may weil have said that Bill is a philosopher
and that Bill is courageous. I would wish to maintain that the SEMANTIC
FUNCTION of the 'therefore' is to enable a speaker to indicate, though not to
say [or explicitly convey], that a certain consequenee holds. Mutatis mutandis,
I would adopt the same position with regard to words like 'but' and 'moreover'.
In the case of ‘but’ – contrast.In the case of ‘moreover,’ or ‘furthermore,’
the speaker is not explicitly conveying that he is adding; he is implicitly
conveying that he is adding, and using the emphatic, colloquial, rhetorical,
device. Much favoured by rhetoricians. To start a sentence with “Furthermore”
is very common. To start a sentence, or subsentence with, “I say that in
addition to the previous, the following also holds, viz.”My primary reason for
opting for this partieular sense of'say' is that I expect it to be of greater
theoretical utility than some OTHER sense of'say' [such as one held, say, by L.
J. Cohen at Oxford] would be. So I shall be committed to the view that applied
timeless meaning and occasion=meaning may coincide, that is to say, it may be
true both First, that when U uttered X the meaning of X inc1uded '*p' and Second, that part of what U meant when he uttered X
was that *p, and yet be false that U has said, among other things, that *p. “I
would like to use the expression 'conventionally meant that' in such a way that
the fulfilment of the two conditions just mentioned, while insufficient for the
truth of 'U said that *p' will be suffieient (and neeessary) for the truth of
'U conventionally meant that *p'.”The above is important because Grice is for
the first time allowing the adverb ‘conventionally’ to apply not as he does in
Essay I to ‘implicate’ but to ‘mean’ in general – which would INCLUDE what is
EXPLICITLY CONVEYED. This will not be as central as he thinks he is here,
because his exploration will be on the handwave which surely cannot be
specified in terms of that the emissor CONVENTIONALLY MEANS.(V) This
distinction between what is said [or explicity conveyed] and what is
conventionally meant [or communicated, or conveyed simpliciter] creates the
task of specifying the conditions in which what U conventionally means by an
utterance is also part of what U said [or explicitly conveyed].I have hopes of
being able to discharge this task by proceeding along the following lines.First,
To specify conditions which will be satisfied only by a limited range of
speech-acts, the members of which will thereby be stamped as specially central
or fundamental. “Adding, contrasting, and reasoning” will not. Second, To
stipulate that in uttering X [utterance type], U will have said [or explicitly
conveyed] that *p, if both First, U has 1stFLOOR-ed that *p, where 1stFloor-ing
is a CENTRAL speech-act [not adding, contrasting, or reasoning], and Second, X
[the utterance type] embodies some CONVENTIONAL device [such as the mode of the
copula] the meaning of which is such that its presence in X [the utterance
type] indicates that its utterer is FIRST-FLOOR -ing that *p. Third, To define,
for each member Y of the range of central speech-aets, 'U has Y -ed that *p' in
terms of occasion-meaning (meaning that ... ) or in terms of some important
elements) involved in the already provided definition of occasion-meaning. (VI)
The fulfilment of the task just outlined will need to be supplemented by an
account of this or that ELEMENT in the CONVENTIONAL MEANING of an utterance
(such as one featuring ‘therefore,’ ‘but,’ or ‘moreover’) which is NOT part of
what has been said [or explicitly conveyed].This account, at least for an
important sub-class of such elements, might take the following shape: First,
this or that problematic element is linked with this or that speech-act which
is exhibited as posterior to, and such that their performance is dependent
upon, some member or disjunction of members of the central, first-floor range;
e. g. the meaning of 'moreover' would be linked with the speech-act of adding,
the performance of which would require the performance of one or other of the
central speech-acts. – [and the meaning of ‘but’ with contrasting, and the
meaning of ‘therefore’ with reasoning, or inferring].Second, If
SECOND-FLOOR-ing is such a non-central speech-act [such as inferring/reasoning,
contrasting, or adding], the dependence of SECOND-FLOOR-ing that *p upon the
performance of some central FIRST-FLOOR speech-act [such as stating or
ordering] would have to be shown to be of a nature which justifies a RELUCTANCE
to treat SECOND-FLOOR-ing (e. g. inferring, contrasting, adding) that *p as a
case not merely of saying that *p, but also of saying that = p, or of saying
that = *p (where' = p', or ' = *p', is a representation of one or more
sentential forms specifically associated with SECOND-FLOOR-ing). Z Third, The
notion of SECOND-FLOOR-ing (inferring, contrasting, adding) that *p (where
Z-ing is non-central) would be explicated in terms of the nation of meaning
that (or in terms of some important elements) in the definition of that
notion). When Grice learned that that
brilliant Harvardite, D. K. Lewis, was writing a dissertation under Quine on
‘convention’ he almost fainted! When he noticed that Lewis was relying rightly
on Schelling and mainly restricting the ‘conventionality’ to the
‘arbitrariness,’ which Grice regarded as synonym with ‘freedom’ (Willkuere,
liber arbitrium), he recovered. For Lewis, a two-off predicament occurs when
you REPEAT. Grice is not interested. When you repeat, you may rely on some
‘arbitrariness.’ This is usually the EMISSOR’s auctoritas. As when Humptyy
Dumpty was brought to Davidson’s attention. “Impenetrability!” “I don’t know
what that means.” “Well put, Alice, if that is your name, as you said it was.
What I mean by ‘impenetrability’ is that we rather change the topic, plus it’s
tea time, and I feel like having some eggs.” Grice refers to this as the
‘idion.’ He reminisces when he was in the bath and designed a full new highway
code (“Nobody has yet used it – but the pleasure was in the semiotic design.”).
A second reminiscence pertains to his writing a full grammar of
“Deutero-Esperanto.” “I loved it – because I had all the power a master needs!
I decide what it’s proper!” In the field of the implicatura, Grice uses
‘convention’ casually, mainly to contrast it with HIS field, the
non-conventional. One should not attach importance to this. On occasion Grice
used Frege’s “Farbung,” just to confuse. The sad story is that Strawson was
never convinced by the non-conventional. Being a conventionalist at heart (vide
his “Intention and convention in speech acts,”) and revering Austin, Strawson
opposes Grice’s idea of the ‘non-conventional.’ Note that in Grice’s general
schema for the communicatum, the ‘conventional’ is just ONE MODE OF CORRELATION
between the signum and the signatum, or the communicatum and the intentum. The
‘conventional’ can be explained, unlike Lewis, in mere terms of the validatum.
Strawson and Wiggins “Cogito; ergo, sum”: What is explicitly conveyed is:
“cogito” and “sum”. The conjunction
“cogito” and “sum” is not made an ‘invalidatum’ if the implicated consequence
relation, emotionally expressed by an ‘alas’-like sort of ejaculation, ‘ergo,’
fails to hold. Strawson and Wiggins give other examples. For some reason, Latin
‘ergo’ becomes the more structured, “therefore,” which is a composite of
‘there’ and ‘fore.’ Then there’s the very Hun, “so,” (as in “so so”). Then there’s
the “Sie schoene aber poor,” discussed by Frege --“but,” – and Strawson and
Wiggins add a few more that had Grice elaborating on first-floor versus
second-floor. Descartes is on the first floor. He states “cogito” and he states
“sum.” Then he goes to the second floor, and the screams, “ergo,” or ‘dunc!’”
The examples Strawson and Wiggins give are: “although” (which looks like a
subordinating dyadic connector but not deemed essential by Gazdar’s 16 ones).
Then they give an expression Grice quite explored, “because,” or “for”as Grice
prefers (‘since it improves on Stevenson), the ejaculation “alas,” and in its
‘misusage,’ “hopefully.” This is an adverbial that Grice loved: “Probably, it
will rains,” “Desirably, there is icecream.” There is a confusing side to this
too. “intentions
are to be recognized, in the normal case, by virtue of a knowledge of the
conventional use of the sentence (indeed my account of "non-conventional implicaturum"
depends on this idea).” So here we may disregard the ‘bandaged leg case’ and
the idea that there is implicaturum in art, etc. If we take the sobriquet
‘non-conventional’ seriously, one may be led to suggest that the
‘non-conventional’ DEPENDS on the conventional. One distinctive feature – the
fifth – of the conversational implicaturum is that it is partly generated as
partly depending on the ‘conventional’ “use.” So this is tricky. Grice’s
anti-conventionalism -- conventionalism, the philosophical doctrine that
logical truth and mathematical truth are created by our choices, not dictated
or imposed on us by the world. The doctrine is a more specific version of the
linguistic theory of logical and mathematical truth, according to which the
statements of logic and mathematics are true because of the way people use
language. Of course, any statement owes its truth to some extent to facts about
linguistic usage. For example, ‘Snow is white’ is true in English because of
the facts that 1 ‘snow’ denotes snow, 2 ‘is white’ is true of white things, and
3 snow is white. What the linguistic theory asserts is that statements of logic
and mathematics owe their truth entirely to the way people use language.
Extralinguistic facts such as 3 are not relevant to the truth of such
statements. Which aspects of linguistic usage produce logical truth and
mathematical truth? The conventionalist answer is: certain linguistic
conventions. These conventions are said to include rules of inference, axioms,
and definitions. The idea that geometrical truth is truth we create by adopting
certain conventions received support by the discovery of non-Euclidean
geometries. Prior to this discovery, Euclidean geometry had been seen as a
paradigm of a priori knowledge. The further discovery that these alternative
systems are consistent made Euclidean geometry seem rejectable without
violating rationality. Whether we adopt the Euclidean system or a non-Euclidean
system seems to be a matter of our choice based on such pragmatic
considerations as simplicity and convenience. Moving to number theory,
conventionalism received a prima facie setback by the discovery that arithmetic
is incomplete if consistent. For let S be an undecidable sentence, i.e., a
sentence for which there is neither proof nor disproof. Suppose S is true. In
what conventions does its truth consist? Not axioms, rules of inference, and
definitions. For if its truth consisted in these items it would be provable. Suppose
S is not true. Then its negation must be true. In what conventions does its
truth consist? Again, no answer. It appears that if S is true or its negation
is true and if neither S nor its negation is provable, then not all arithmetic
truth is truth by convention. A response the conventionalist could give is that
neither S nor its negation is true if S is undecidable. That is, the
conventionalist could claim that arithmetic has truth-value gaps. As to logic,
all truths of classical logic are provable and, unlike the case of number
theory and geometry, axioms are dispensable. Rules of inference suffice. As
with geometry, there are alternatives to classical logic. The intuitionist,
e.g., does not accept the rule ‘From not-not-A infer A’. Even detachment ’From A, if A then B, infer B’ is rejected in some multivalued systems of
logic. These facts support the conventionalist doctrine that adopting any set
of rules of inference is a matter of our choice based on pragmatic
considerations. But the anti-conventionalist might respond consider a simple
logical truth such as ‘If Tom is tall, then Tom is tall’. Granted that this is
provable by rules of inference from the empty set of premises, why does it
follow that its truth is not imposed on us by extralinguistic facts about Tom?
If Tom is tall the sentence is true because its consequent is true. If Tom is
not tall the sentence is true because its antecedent is false. In either case
the sentence owes its truth to facts about Tom.
-- convention T, a criterion of material adequacy of proposed truth
definitions discovered, formally articulated, adopted, and so named by Tarski
in connection with his 9 definition of the concept of truth in a formalized
language. Convention T is one of the most important of several independent
proposals Tarski made concerning philosophically sound and logically precise
treatment of the concept of truth. Various of these proposals have been
criticized, but convention T has remained virtually unchallenged and is
regarded almost as an axiom of analytic philosophy. To say that a proposed
definition of an established concept is materially adequate is to say that it
is “neither too broad nor too narrow,” i.e., that the concept it characterizes
is coextensive with the established concept. Since, as Tarski emphasized, for
many formalized languages there are no criteria of truth, it would seem that
there can be no general criterion of material adequacy of truth definitions.
But Tarski brilliantly finessed this obstacle by discovering a specification
that is fulfilled by the established correspondence concept of truth and that
has the further property that any two concepts fulfilling it are necessarily
coextensive. Basically, convention T requires that to be materially adequate a
proposed truth definition must imply all of the infinitely many relevant
Tarskian biconditionals; e.g., the sentence ‘Some perfect number is odd’ is
true if and only if some perfect number is odd. Loosely speaking, a Tarskian
biconditional for English is a sentence obtained from the form ‘The sentence
——— is true if and only if ——’ by filling the right blank with a sentence and
filling the left blank with a name of the sentence. Tarski called these
biconditionals “equivalences of the form T” and referred to the form as a “scheme.”
Later writers also refer to the form as “schema T.”
stuff
and nonsense:
cf. Grice: “P. M. S. Hacker and the nonsense of sense.’ Grice: “One has to be
very careful. For Grice, “You’re the cream in my coffee” involves a category
mistake, it’s nonsense, and neither true nor false. For me, it involves
categorial falsity; therefore, it is analytically false, and therefore,
meaningful, in its poor own ways!” – “”You’re the cream in my coffee” compares
with a not that well known ditty by Freddie Ayer, and the Ambassadors,
“Saturday is in bed – but Garfield isn’t.”” – “ “Saturday is in bed” involves
categorial falsity but surely only Freddie would use it metaphorically – not
all categorial falsities pass the Richards test --. Grice: “ “It is not the
case that you’re the cream in my coffee” is a truism” – But cf. “You haven’t
been cleaning the Aegean stables – because you’ve just said you spent the
summer in Hull, and the stables are in Greece.” Cf. “Grice: “ ‘You’re the cream
in my coffee’ is literally, a piece of nonsense – it involves a categorial
falsity.” “Sentences involving categorial falsity nonsense are the specialty of
Ryle, our current Waynflete!” -- Sense-nonsense -- demarcation, the line
separating empirical science from mathematics and logic, from metaphysics, and
from pseudoscience. Science traditionally was supposed to rely on induction,
the formal disciplines including metaphysics on deduction. In the verifiability
criterion, the logical positivists identified the demarcation of empirical science
from metaphysics with the demarcation of the cognitively meaningful from the
meaningless, classifying metaphysics as gibberish, and logic and mathematics,
more charitably, as without sense. Noting that, because induction is invalid,
the theories of empirical science are unverifiable, Popper proposed
falsifiability as their distinguishing characteristic, and remarked that some
metaphysical doctrines, such as atomism, are obviously meaningful. It is now
recognized that science is suffused with metaphysical ideas, and Popper’s
criterion is therefore perhaps a rather rough criterion of demarcation of the
empirical from the nonempirical rather than of the scientific from the
non-scientific. It repudiates the unnecessary task of demarcating the
cognitively meaningful from the cognitively meaningless. There are cases in which a denial has
to be interpreted as the denial of an implicature. “She is not the cream in my.
Grice: "There
may be an occasion when the denial of
a metaphor -- any absurd utterance when taken literally, e. g., 'You're the
cream in my coffee' -- may be interpreted *not* as, strictly, denying that
you're *literally* the cream in my coffee, but, in a jocular, transferred
-- and strictly illogical -- way, as the denying the implicaturum, or metaphorical
interpretant, viz.'It is not the case that that you're the salt in my
stew,". Grice was interested in how ‘absurdum’ became ‘nonsense’ -- absurdum,
adj. ab, mis-, and Sanscr. svan = “sonare;” cf. susurrus, and σῦριγξ, = a pipe;
cf. also absonus.” Lewis and Short render ‘absurdum’’ as ‘out of tune, hence
giving a disagreeable sound, harsh, rough.’ I. Lit.: “vox absona et absurda,”
Cic. de Or. 3, 11, 41; so of the croaking of frogs: absurdoque sono fontes et
stagna cietis, Poët. ap. Cic. Div. 1, 9, 15.— II. Fig., -- Short and Lewis this
‘absurd’ transferred usage: ‘absurd,’ which is not helpful -- “of persons and
things, irrational, incongruous, absurd, silly, senseless, stupid.” They give a
few quotes: “ratio inepta atque absurda,” – The reason is inept and absurd”
Ter. Ad. 3, 3, 22: “hoc pravum, ineptum, absurdum atque alienum a vitā meā
videtur,” id. ib. 5, 8, 21: “carmen cum ceteris rebus absurdum tum vero in
illo,” Cic. Mur. 26: “illud quam incredibile, quam absurdum!” “How incredible!
How absurd!” -- id. Sull. 20: “absurda res est caveri,” id. Balb. 37: bene
dicere haud absurdum est, is not inglorious, per litotem for, is praiseworthy,
glorious, Sall. C. 3 Kritz.—Homo absurdus, a man who is fit or good for
nothing: “sin plane abhorrebit et erit absurdus,” Cic. de Or. 2, 20, 85:
“absurdus ingenio,” Tac. H. 3, 62; cf.: “sermo comis, nec absurdum ingenium,”
id. A. 13, 45.—Comp., Cic. Phil. 8, 41; id. N. D. 1, 16; id. Fin. 2, 13.—Sup.,
Cic. Att. 7, 13.—Adv.: absurdē . 1. Lit., discordantly: “canere,” Cic. Tusc. 2,
4, 12.— 2. Fig., irrationally, absurdly, Plaut. Ep. 3, 1, 6; Cic. Rep. 2, 15;
id. Div. 2, 58, 219 al.—Comp., Cic. Phil. 8, 1, 4.—Sup., Aug. Trin. 4 fin. Cf.
Tertullian, “Credo quia absurdum est.” – an answer to “Quam incredible, quam
absurdum!” -- Refs.:
H. P. Grice, “Ryle and categorial nonsense;” “The absurdity of ‘You’re the
cream in my coffee.’”
notum – the ‘gnotus’ -- divided line, one
of three analogies with the sun and cave offered in Plato’s Republic VI, 509d
511e as a partial explanation of the Good. Socrates divides a line into two
unequal segments: the longer represents the intelligible world and the shorter
the sensible world. Then each of the segments is divided in the same
proportion. Socrates associates four mental states with the four resulting
segments beginning with the shortest: eikasia, illusion or the apprehension of
images; pistis, belief in ordinary physical objects; dianoia, the sort of
hypothetical reasondispositional belief divided line 239 239 ing engaged in by mathematicians; and
noesis, rational ascent to the first principle of the Good by means of
dialectic. Grice read Austin’s essay on this with interest. Refs.: J. L.
Austin, “Plato’s Cave,” in Philosophical Papers.
noûs: Grice uses ‘nous’
and ‘noetic’ when he is feeling very Grecian. Grecian term for mind or the
faculty of reason. Noûs is the highest type of thinking, the kind a god would
do. Sometimes called the faculty of intellectual intuition, it is at work when
someone understands definitions, concepts, and anything else that is grasped
all at once. Noûs stands in contrast with another intellectual faculty,
dianoia. When we work through the steps of an argument, we exercise dianoia; to
be certain the conclusion is true without argument to just “see” it, as, perhaps, a god
might is to exercise noûs. Just which
objects could be apprehended by noûs was controversial.
nowell-smithianism. “The Nowell is redundant,” Grice would say. P. H.
Nowell-Smith adopted the “Nowell” after his father’s first name. In “Ethics,”
he elaborates on what he calls ‘contextual implication.’ The essay was widely
read, and has a freshness that other ‘meta-ethicist’ at Oxford seldom display.
His ‘contextual implication’ compares of course to Grice’s ‘conversational implicaturum.’
Indeed, by using ‘conversational implicaturum,’ Grice is following an Oxonian
tradition started with C. K. Grant and his ‘pragmatic implication,’ and P. H.
Nowell-Smith and his ‘contextual implication.’ At Oxford, they were obsessed
with these types of ‘implicatura,’ because it was the type of thing that a less
subtle philosopher would ignore. Grice’s cancellability priority for his type
of implicatura hardly applies to Nowell-Smith. Nowell-Smith never displays the
‘rationalist’ bent that Grice wants to endow to his principle of conversational
co-operation. Nowell-Smith, rather, calls his ‘principles’ “rules of
conversational etiquette.” If you revise the literature, you will see that
things like “avoid ambiguity,” “don’t play unnecessary with words,” are listed
indeed in what is called a ‘conversational manual,’ of ‘conversational
etiquette,’ that is. In his rationalist bent, Grice narrows down the use of
‘conversational’ to apply to ‘conversational maxim,’ which is only a
UNIVERSALISABLE one, towards the overarching goal of rational co-operation. In
this regard, many of the rules of ‘conversational etiquette’ (Grice even
mentions ‘moral rules,’ and a rule like ‘be polite’) to fall outside the
principle of conversational helpfulness, and thus, not exactly generating a
‘conversational implicaturum.’ While Grice gives room to allow such
non-conversational non-conventional implicatura to be ‘calculable,’ that is,
‘rationalizable, by ‘argument,’ he never showed any interest in giving one
example – for the simple reason that none of those ‘maxims’ generated the type
of ‘mistake’ on the part of this or that philosopher, as he was interested in
rectifying.
Numenius: Grecian Platonist philosopher of
neoPythagorean tendencies. Very little is known of his life, but his
philosophical importance is considerable. His system of three levels of
spiritual reality a primal god the Good,
the Father, who is almost supra-intellectual; a secondary, creator god the
demiurge of Plato’s Timaeus; and a world soul
largely anticipates that of Plotinus in the next century, though he was
more strongly dualist than Plotinus in his attitude to the physical world and
matter. He was much interested in religion. His most important work, fragments
of which are preserved by Eusebius, is a dialogue On the Good, but he also
wrote a polemic work On the Divergence of the Academics from Plato, which shows
him to be a lively controversialist. J
O
O: SUBJECT INDEX
O: NAME INDEX: ITALIAN
O: NAME INDEX: ITALIAN
OLIVI
O: NAME INDEX – ENGLISHMEN (Oxonian philosophy
dons)
affirmo-nego
distinction, the: O: particularis abdicativa. See Grice, “Circling the Square
of Opposition.”
Oakeshott, M.: H. P. Grice, “Oakeshott’s
conversational implicaturum,” English philosopher and political theorist
trained at Cambridge and in G.y. He taught first at Cambridge and Oxford; from
1 he was professor of political science at the London School of Economics and
Political Science. His works include Experience and Its Modes 3, Rationalism in
Politics 2, On Human Conduct 5, and On History 3. Oakeshott’s misleading
general reputation, based on Rationalism in Politics, is as a conservative
political thinker. Experience and Its Modes is a systematic work in the
tradition of Hegel. Human experience is exclusively of a world of ideas
intelligible insofar as it is coherent. This world divides into modes
historical, scientific, practical, and poetic experience, each being partly
coherent and categorially distinct from all others. Philosophy is the never
entirely successful attempt to articulate the coherence of the world of ideas
and the place of modally specific experience within that whole. His later works
examine the postulates of historical and practical experience, particularly
those of religion, morality, and politics. All conduct in the practical mode
postulates freedom and is an “exhibition of intelligence” by agents who
appropriate inherited languages and ideas to the generic activity of
self-enactment. Some conduct pursues specific purposes and occurs in
“enterprise associations” identified by goals shared among those who
participate in them. The most estimable forms of conduct, exemplified by
“conversation,” have no such purpose and occur in “civil societies” under the
purely “adverbial” considerations of morality and law. “Rationalists” illicitly
use philosophy to dictate to practical experience and subordinate human conduct
to some master purpose. Oakeshott’s distinctive achievement is to have melded
holistic idealism with a morality and politics radical in their affirmation of
individuality. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The Oxbridge conversation,” H. P. Grice,
“The ancient stone walls of Oxford.”
objectivum
– Grice: “Kant thought he was being witty when he speaks of the Copernican
revolution – While I prefer ‘subjectification’ for what he meant, Strawson
likes ‘category shift.’ At Oxford, we never took good care of Number One!” -- Grice reads Meinong on objectivity and finds
it funny! Meinong distinguishes four classes of objects: ‘Objekt,’ simpliciter,
which can be real (like horses) or ideal (like the concepts of difference,
identity, etc.) and “Objectiv,” e.g. the affirmation of the being (Sein) or
non-being (Nichtsein), of a being-such (Sosein), or a being-with (Mitsein) -
parallel to existential, categorical and hypothetical judgements. An “Objectiv”
is close to what contemporary philosophers call states of affairs (where these
may be actual—may obtain—or not). The third class is the dignitative, e.g. the
true, the good, the beautiful. Finally, there is the desiderative, e.g. duties,
ends, etc. To these four classes of objects correspond four classes of
psychological acts: (re)presentation
(das Vorstellen), for objects thought (das Denken), for the objectives feeling
(das Fühlen), for dignitatives desire (das Begehren), for the desideratives.
Grice starts with subjectivity. Objectivity can be constructed as
non-relativised subjectivity. Grice discusses of Inventing right and wrong
by Mackie. In the proceedings, Grice quotes the artless sexism of Austin
in talking about the trouser words in Sense and Sensibilia. Grice tackles all
the distinctions Mackie had played with: objective/Subjectsive, absolute/relative,
categorical/hypothetical or suppositional. Grice quotes directly from Hare:
Think of one world into whose fabric values are objectively built; and think of
another in which those values have been annihilated. And remember that in both
worlds the people in them go on being concerned about the same things—there is
no difference in the Subjectsive value. Now I ask, what is the difference
between the states of affairs in these two worlds? Can any answer be given
except, none whatever? Grice uses the Latinate objective (from objectum). Cf.
Hare on what he thinks the oxymoronic sub-jective value. Grice considered more
seriously than Barnes did the systematics behind Nicolai Hartmanns
stratification of values. Refs.: the most explicit allusion is a specific essay
on “objectivity” in The H. P. Grice Papers. Most of the topic is covered in “Conception,”
Essay 1. BANC. objectivum. Here the
contrast is what what is subjective, or subjectivum. Notably value. For
Hartmann and Grice, a value is rational, objective and absolute, and
categorical (not relative). objectum.
For Grice the subjectum is prior. While ‘subject’ and ‘predicate’ are basic
Aristotelian categories, the idea of the direct object or indirect object seems
to have little philosophical relevance. (but cf. “What is the meaning of ‘of’?
Genitivus subjectivus versus enitivus objectivus. The usage that is more
widespread is a misnomer for ‘thing’. When an empiricist like Grice speaks of
an ‘obble’ or an ‘object,’ he means a thing. That is because, since Hume
there’s no such thing as a ‘subject’ qua self. And if there is no subject,
there is no object. No Copernican revolution for empiricists. the obiectum-quo/obiectum quod distinction: obiectum
quo:
Griceian for “the object by which an object is known.” Grice: “A sort of
meta-object, if you press me.” -- It should be understood in contrast with “obiectum
quod,” -- the object that is known. E. g. when Grice’s son knows WHAT ‘a shaggy
thing’ is, the shaggy thing is the obiectum quod and Grice’s son’s concept of
the shaggy thing is the obiectum quo. The concept (‘shaggy’) is thus instrumental
to knowing a shaggy thing, but the concept ‘shaggy’ is not itself what is
known. A human needs a concept in order to have knowledge, because a human’s
knowledge is receptive, in contrast with God’s which is productive. God creates
what he knows. Human knowledge is mediated; divine knowledge is immediate. J.
C. Wilson famously believed that the distinction between obiectum quod and
obiectum quo exposes the crucial mistake of Bradley’s neo-Hegelian idealism –
“that is destroying the little that’s left of philosophy at Oxford.” According
to an idealist such as Bradley, the object of knowledge, i.e., what Bradley
knows, is an idea. In contrast, the Scholastics maintain that an idealist such
as Bradley conflate the object of knowledge with the *means* (the obiectum quo)
by which human knowledge is made possible. Humans must be connected to the
object of knowledge by something obiectum quo, but what connects them is not
that to which they are connected – “autem natura est terminus ut quo, 3°
Obiectum ut qu9 l esi illud ipsum, ad quod potentia, vel scientia
spectat.Obiectiim ;t quo est propria raiio , propter qnam potentia, vel
scientia circa aliquid versatur. Vel obiectum quod cst illud , quod in scientia
demonstratur.0biectum quo consistit in mediis, quibus probantur conclusiones in
eadem scientia *, 4* l't quod significat subiecium , cui proprie convenit
aliquod attributurn , vel quaedam denominatio: ut quo indicat rationem ,
propter quam subiectum cst, vel denominatur tale ; e. g., hic terminus albus ,
si accipiatur sit quod, significal parietem, vel aliud, quod dicitur album; sin
autem ut quo denotat ipsam albitudinem. Hoc sensu terminus acceptus ut, quod
dicitur etiam usurpari in recto , ut quo, in obliquo *. 5° Denique: Species,
per quam fit cognitio alicuius rei, est obiectum, quo illa cognoscitur; res
antem a specie repraesentata est obiectum quod : « Species visibilis, ait s.
Thomas, non se habet, ut quod videtur, sed ut quo videtur *». Et alibi : «
Species intelligibiles, quibus intellectus possibilis fit in actu, non sunt
obiectum intelleclus, non enim se habent ad intellectum, sicut quod
intelligitur, sed sicut quo intelligit * ». Sane, species non est terminus, in
quem cognitio fertur , sed dumlaxat principium, ex quo facultas cognitrix
determinatur ad I .*, q. n,l;un r m ab ipsa specie repraesentatam, Quarc , etsi
auima cognoseat res pcr species, tamen illas in seipsis cognoscit : « ('ognoscere
res per earum similitudines im cognoscente existentes, est cognoscere eas in
seipsis * ». Et B. Albcrtus M. • Sensus [*r hoc, quod species est sensibilium,
sensibilia imin-diato arripit.” Refs.: H. P. Grice: The obiectum-quo/obiectum
quod distinction: and what to do with it.
objective
rightness. In meta-ethics, an action is objectively right for a person to
perform on some occasion if the agent’s performing it on that occasion really
is right, whether or not the agent, or anyone else, believes it is. An action
is subjectively right for a person to perform on some occasion if the agent
believes, or perhaps justifiably believes, of that action that it is
objectively right. For example, according to a version of utilitarianism, an
action is objectively right provided the action is optimific in the sense that
the consequences that would result from its per624 O 624 formance are at least as good as those
that would result from any alternative action the agent could instead perform.
Were this theory correct, then an action would be an objectively right action
for an agent to perform on some occasion if and only if that action is in fact
optimific. An action can be both objectively and subjectively right or neither.
But an action can also be subjectively right, but fail to be objectively right,
as where the action fails to be optimific again assuming that a utilitarian
theory is correct, yet the agent believes the action is objectively right. And
an action can be objectively right but not subjectively right, where, despite
the objective rightness of the action, the agent has no beliefs about its
rightness or believes falsely that it is not objectively right. This
distinction is important in our moral assessments of agents and their actions.
In cases where we judge a person’s action to be objectively wrong, we often
mitigate our judgment of the agent when we judge that the action was, for the
agent, subjectively right. This same objectivesubjective distinction applies to
other ethical categories such as wrongness and obligatoriness, and some
philosophers extend it to items other than actions, e.g., emotions.
obligatum – Grice: “This has
a deep connection with the Latin idea of ius, cf. iunctum – and lex from ligare
– “Perhaps Hare prefers ‘ought’ because it eye-rymes with ‘obligation.’” Deontology
-- duty, what a person is obligated or required to do. Duties can be moral,
legal, parental, occupational, etc., depending on their foundations or grounds.
Because a duty can have several different grounds, it can be, say, both moral
and legal, though it need not be of more than one type. Natural duties are
moral duties people have simply in virtue of being persons, i.e., simply in
virtue of their nature. There is a prima facie duty to do something if and only
if there is an appropriate basis for doing that thing. For instance, a prima
facie moral duty will be one for which there is a moral basis, i.e., some moral
grounds. This conDutch book duty 248
248 trasts with an all-things-considered duty, which is a duty one has
if the appropriate grounds that support it outweigh any that count against it.
Negative duties are duties not to do certain things, such as to kill or harm,
while positive duties are duties to act in certain ways, such as to relieve
suffering or bring aid. While the question of precisely how to draw the
distinction between negative and positive duties is disputed, it is generally
thought that the violation of a negative duty involves an agent’s causing some
state of affairs that is the basis of the action’s wrongness e.g., harm, death,
or the breaking of a trust, whereas the violation of a positive duty involves
an agent’s allowing those states of affairs to occur or be brought about.
Imperfect duties are, in Kant’s words, “duties which allow leeway in the
interest of inclination,” i.e., that permit one to choose among several
possible ways of fulfilling them. Perfect duties do not allow that leeway.
Thus, the duty to help those in need is an imperfect duty since it can be
fulfilled by helping the sick, the starving, the oppressed, etc., and if one
chooses to help, say, the sick, one can choose which of the sick to help.
However, the duty to keep one’s promises and the duty not to harm others are
perfect duties since they do not allow one to choose which promises to keep or
which people not to harm. Most positive duties are imperfect; most negative
ones, perfect. obligationes, the study of inferentially inescapable, yet
logically odd arguments, used by late medieval logicians in analyzing
inferential reasoning. In Topics VIII.3 Aristotle describes a respondent’s task
in a philosophical argument as providing answers so that, if they must defend
the impossible, the impossibility lies in the nature of the position, and not
in its logical defense. In Prior Analytics I.13 Aristotle argues that nothing
impossible follows from the possible. Burley, whose logic exemplifies early
fourteenth-century obligationes literature, described the resulting logical
exercise as a contest between interlocutor and respondent. The interlocutor
must force the respondent into maintaining contradictory statements in
defending a position, and the respondent must avoid this while avoiding
maintaining the impossible, which can be either a position logically
incompatible with the position defended or something impossible in itself.
Especially interesting to Scholastic logicians were the paradoxes of
disputation inherent in such disputes. Assuming that a respondent has
successfully defended his position, the interlocutor may be able to propose a
commonplace position that the respondent can neither accept nor reject, given
the truth of the first, successfully defended position. Roger Swineshead
introduced a controversial innovation to obligationes reasoning, later rejected
by Paul of Venice. In the traditional style of obligation, a premise was
relevant to the argument only if it followed from or was inconsistent with
either a the proposition defended or b all the premises consequent to the
former and prior to the premise in question. By admitting any premise that was
either consequent to or inconsistent with the proposition defended alone,
without regard to intermediate premises, Swineshead eliminated concern with the
order of sentences proposed by the interlocutor, making the respondent’s task
harder.
recte-obliquum
distinction, the:
casus obliquum -- oblique context. As explained by Frege in “Über Sinn und
Bedeutung” 2, a linguistic context is oblique ungerade if and only if an
expression e.g., proper name, dependent clause, or sentence in that context
does not express its direct customary sense. For Frege, the sense of an
expression is the mode of presentation of its nominatum, if any. Thus in direct
speech, the direct customary sense of an expression designates its direct
customary nominatum. For example, the context of the proper name ‘Kepler’ in 1
Kepler died in misery. is non-oblique i.e., direct since the proper name
expresses its direct customary sense, say, the sense of ‘the man who discovered
the elliptical planetary orbits’, thereby designating its direct customary
nominatum, Kepler himself. Moreover, the entire sentence expresses its direct
sense, namely, the proposition that Kepler died in misery, thereby designating
its direct nominatum, a truth-value, namely, the true. By contrast, in indirect
speech an expression neither expresses its direct sense nor, therefore,
designates its direct nominatum. One such sort of oblique context is direct
quotation, as in 2 ‘Kepler’ has six letters. The word appearing within the
quotation marks neither expresses its direct customary sense nor, therefore,
designates its direct customary nominatum, Kepler. Rather, it designates a
word, a proper name. Another sort of oblique context is engendered by the verbs
of propositional attitude. Thus, the context of the proper name ‘Kepler’ in 3
Frege believed Kepler died in misery. is oblique, since the proper name
expresses its indirect sense, say, the sense of the words ‘the man widely known
as Kepler’, thereby designating its indirect nominatum, namely, the sense of
‘the man who discovered the elliptical planetary orbits’. Note that the
indirect nominatum of ‘Kepler’ in 3 is the same as the direct sense of ‘Kepler’
in 1. Thus, while ‘Kepler’ in 1 designates the man Kepler, ‘Kepler’ in 3
designates the direct customary sense of the word ‘Kepler’ in 1. Similarly, in
3 the context of the dependent clause ‘Kepler died in misery’ is oblique since
the dependent clause expresses its indirect sense, namely, the sense of the words
‘the proposition that Kepler died in misery’, thereby designating its indirect
nominatum, namely, the proposition that Kepler died in misery. Note that the
indirect nominatum of ‘Kepler died in misery’ in 3 is the same as the direct
sense of ‘Kepler died in misery’ in 1. Thus, while ‘Kepler died in misery’ in 1
designates a truthvalue, ‘Kepler died in misery’ in 3 designates a proposition,
the direct customary sense of the words ‘Kepler died in misery’ in 1.
obversum: a sort of immediate inference
that allows a transformation of affirmative categorical A-propositions and
I-propositions into the corresponding negative E-propositions and
O-propositions, and of E- and O-propositions into the corresponding A- and
I-propositions, keeping in each case the order of the subject and predicate
terms, but changing the original predicate into its complement, i.e., into a
negated term. E. g. ‘Every man is mortal’
’No man is non-mortal’; ‘Some students are happy’ ‘Some students are not non-happy’; ‘No dogs
are jealous’ ‘All dogs are non-jealous’;
and ‘Some bankers are not rich’ ‘Some
bankers are not non-rich’. .
occasion:
“I will use ‘occasion,’ occasionally.” The etymology of ‘occasion’ is
fabuluous. It has to do with ‘casus,’ ptosis, fall. Grice struggled with the
lingo and he not necessarily arrived at the right choice. Occasion he uses in
the strange phrase “occasion-meaning” (sic). Surely not ‘occasional meaning.’
What is an occasion? Surely it’s a context. But Grice would rather be seen dead
than using a linguistic turn of phrase like Firth’s context-of-utterance! So
there you have the occasion-meaning. Basically, it’s the PARTICULARISED
implicaturum. On occasion o, E communicates that p. Grice allows that there is
occasion-token and occasion-type. occasionalism: a
theory of causation held by a number of important seventeenth-century Cartesian
philosophers, including Johannes Clauberg, Géraud de Cordemoy, Arnold Geulincx,
Louis de la Forge, and Nicolas Malebranche. In its most extreme version, occasionalism
is the doctrine that all finite created entities are devoid of causal efficacy,
and that God is the only true causal agent. Bodies do not cause effects in
other bodies nor in minds; and minds do not cause effects in bodies nor even
within themselves. God is directly, immediately, and solely responsible for
bringing about all phenomena. When a needle pricks the skin, the physical event
is merely an occasion for God to cause the relevant mental state pain; a
volition in the soul to raise an arm or to think of something is only an
occasion for God to cause the arm to rise or the ideas to be present to the
mind; and the impact of one billiard ball upon another is an occasion for God
to move the second ball. In all three contexts
mindbody, bodybody, and mind alone
God’s ubiquitous causal activity proceeds in accordance with certain
general laws, and except for miracles he acts only when the requisite material
or psychic conditions obtain. Less thoroughgoing forms of occasionalism limit
divine causation e.g., to mindbody or bodybody alone. Far from being an ad hoc
solution to a Cartesian mindbody problem, as it is often considered,
occasionalism is argued for from general philosophical considerations regarding
the nature of causal relations considerations that later appear, modified, in
Hume, from an analysis of the Cartesian concept of matoblique intention
occasionalism 626 626 ter and of the
necessary impotence of finite substance, and, perhaps most importantly, from
theological premises about the essential ontological relation between an
omnipotent God and the created world that he sustains in existence.
Occasionalism can also be regarded as a way of providing a metaphysical
foundation for explanations in mechanistic natural philosophy. Occasionalists are
arguing that motion must ultimately be grounded in something higher than the
passive, inert extension of Cartesian bodies emptied of the substantial forms
of the Scholastics; it needs a causal ground in an active power. But if a body
consists in extension alone, motive force cannot be an inherent property of
bodies. Occasionalists thus identify force with the will of God. In this way,
they are simply drawing out the implications of Descartes’s own metaphysics of
matter and motion. Refs: H. P. Grice, “What’s the case – and occasionalism.”
modified
occam’s razorr:
cf. Myro’s modified modified Occam razor – implicatura non sunt implicanda
praeter implicatura -- see H. P. Grice, “Modified Occam’s Razor” -- known as
the More than Subtle Doctor, English Scholastic philosopher known equally as
the father of nominalism and for his role in the Franciscan dispute with Pope
John XXII over poverty. Born at Occam in Surrey, he entered the Franciscan
order at an early age and studied at Oxford, attaining the rank of a B. A., i.
e. a “baccalarius formatus.” His brilliant but controversial career is cut
short when Lutterell, chancellor of Oxford, presented the pope with a list of 56
allegedly heretical theses extracted from Occam (Grice: “One was, ‘Senses are
not be multipled beyond necessity.’). The papal commission studies them for two
years and find 51 open to censure – “while five are ‘o-kay.’”-- , but none was
formally condemned. While in Avignon, Occam researches previous papal
concessions to the Franciscans regarding collective poverty, eventually
concluding that John XXII contradicted his predecessors and hence was ‘no
pope,’ or “no true pope.” After committing these charges to writing, Occam
flees with Cesena, then minister general of the order, first to Pisa and
ultimately to Munich, where he composes many treatises about church-state
relations. Although departures from his eminent predecessors have combined with
ecclesiastical difficulties to make Occam unjustly notorious, his thought
remains, by current lights, philosophically conservative – or as he would
expand, “irreverent, dissenting, rationalist conservative.” On most
metaphysical issues, Occam fancies himself the true interpreter of Aristotle.
Rejecting the doctrine that the universalse is a real thing other than a name
(‘flatus vocis’) or a concept as “the worst error of philosophy,” Occam
dismisses not only Platonism, but also “modern realist” doctrines according to
which a nature enjoys a double mode of existence and is universal in the
intellect but numerically multiplied in this or that particulare. Occam argues
that everything real is individual and particular. Universality is a property
pertaining only to the expression, sign, or name and that by virtue of its
signification (semantic) relation. Because Occam understands a ‘primary’ name
to be ‘psychological’, and thus a ‘naturally’ significant concept, his own
theory of the universale is best classified as a form of conceptualism. Occam
rejects atomism, and defends Aristotelian hylomorphism in physics and
metaphysics, complete with its distinction between substantial form and
accidental form. Yet, Occam opposes the reifying tendency of the “moderns”
unnamed contemporary opponents, who posited a distinct kind of ‘res’ for each
of Aristotle’s ten categories. Occam agues that from a purely philosophical
point of view it is indefensible to
posit anything besides this or that particular substance and this or that
particular quality. Occam follows the Franciscan school in recognizing a
plurality of substantial forms in living things in humans, the forms of
corporeity, sensory soul, and intellectual soul. Occam diverges from Duns
Scotus in asserting a real, not a formal, distinction among them. Aristotle had
reached behind regular correlations in nature to posit substance-things and
accident-things as primitive explanatory entities that essentially are or give
rise to powers virtus that produce the regularities. Similarly, Occam
distinguishes efficient causality properly speaking from sine qua non
causality, depending on whether the correlation between A’s and B’s is produced
by the power of A or by the will of another, and explicitly denies the
existence of any sine qua non causation in nature. Further, Ocam insists, in
Aristotelian fashion, that created substance- and accident-natures are
essentially the causal powers they are in and of themselves and hence
independently of their relations to anything else; so that not even God can
make heat naturally a coolant. Yet, if God cannot change, He shares with
created things the ability to obstruct such “Aristotelian” productive powers
and prevent their normal operation. Ockham’s nominalistic conceptualism about
universals does not keep him from endorsing the uniformity of nature principle,
because he holds that individual natures are powers and hence that co-specific
things are maximally similar powers. Likewise, he is conventional in appealing
to several other a priori causal principles: “Everything that is in motion is
moved by something,” “Being cannot come from non-being,” “Whatever is produced
by something is really conserved by something as long as it exists.” Occam even
recognizes a kind of necessary connection between created causes and
effects e.g., while God could act alone
to produce any created effect, a particular created effect could not have had
another created cause of the same species instead. Ockham’s main innovation on
the topic of causality is his attack on Duns Scotus’s distinction between “essential”
and “accidental” orders and contrary contention that every genuine efficient
cause is an immediate cause of its effects. Ockham is an Aristotelian
reliabilist in epistemology, taking for granted as he does that human cognitive
faculties the senses and intellect work always or for the most part. Occam
infers that since we have certain knowledge both of material things and of our
own mental acts, there must be some distinctive species of acts of awareness
intuitive cognitions that are the power to produce such evident judgments.
Ockham is matter-of-fact both about the disruption of human cognitive functions
by created obstacles as in sensory illusion and about divine power to intervene
in many ways. Such facts carry no skeptical consequences for Ockham, because he
defines certainty in terms of freedom from actual doubt and error, not from the
logical, metaphysical, or natural possibility of error. In action theory,
Ockham defends the liberty of indifference or contingency for all rational
beings, created or divine. Ockham shares Duns Scotus’s understanding of the
will as a self-determining power for opposites, but not his distaste for causal
models. Thus, Ockham allows that 1 unfree acts of will may be necessitated,
either by the agent’s own nature, by its other acts, or by an external cause;
and that 2 the efficient causes of free acts may include the agent’s
intellectual and sensory cognitions as well as the will itself. While
recognizing innate motivational tendencies in the human agent e.g., the inclination to seek sensory
pleasure and avoid pain, the affectio commodi tendency to seek its own
advantage, and the affectio iustitiae inclination to love things for their own
intrinsic worth he denies that these limit
the will’s scope. Thus, Ockham goes beyond Duns Scotus in assigning the will
the power, with respect to any option, to will for it velle, to will against it
nolle, or not to act at all. In particular, Ockham concludes that the will can
will against nolle the good, whether ignorantly or perversely by hating God or by willing against its own
happiness, the good-in-general, the enjoyment of a clear vision of God, or its
own ultimate end. The will can also will velle evils the opposite of what right reason dictates,
unjust deeds qua unjust, dishonest, and contrary to right reason, and evil
under the aspect of evil. Ockham enforces the traditional division of moral
science into non-positive morality or ethics, which directs acts apart from any
precept of a superior authority and draws its principles from reason and
experience; and positive morality, which deals with laws that oblige us to
pursue or avoid things, not because they are good or evil in themselves, but
because some legitimate superior commands them. The notion that Ockham sponsors
an unmodified divine command theory of ethics rests on conflation and
confusion. Rather, in the area of non-positive morality, Ockham advances what
we might label a “modified right reason theory,” which begins with the
Aristotelian ideal of rational self-government, according to which morally
virtuous action involves the agent’s free coordination of choice with right
reason. He then observes that suitably informed right reason would dictate that
God, as the infinite good, ought to be loved above all and for his own sake,
and that such love ought to be expressed by the effort to please him in every
way among other things, by obeying all his commands. Thus, if right reason is
the primary norm in ethics, divine commands are a secondary, derivative norm.
Once again, Ockham is utterly unconcerned about the logical possibility opened
by divine liberty of indifference, that these twin norms might conflict say, if
God commanded us to act contrary to right reason; for him, their de facto
congruence suffices for the moral life. In the area of soteriological merit and
demerit a branch of positive morality, things are the other way around: divine
will is the primary norm; yet because God includes following the dictates of
right reason among the criteria for divine acceptance thereby giving the moral
life eternal significance, right reason becomes a secondary and derivative norm
there. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Why I love Occam,” H. P. Grice, “Comments on
Occam’s ‘Summa Totius Logicae,’” H. P. Grice, “Occam on ‘significare.’” And
then there’s Occam’s razor. H. P. Grice, “Modified Occam’s Razor.” Also called
the principle of parsimony, a methodological principle commending a bias toward
simplicity in the construction of theories. The parameters whose simplicity is
singled out for attention have varied considerably, from kinds of entities to
the number of presupposed axioms to the nature of the curve drawn between data
points. Found already in Aristotle, the tag “entities should not be multiplied
beyond necessity” became associated with William Ockham although he never
states that version, and even if non-contradiction rather than parsimony is his
favorite weapon in metaphysical disputes, perhaps because it characterized the
spirit of his philosophical conclusions. Opponents, who thought parsimony was
being carried too far, formulated an “anti-razor”: where fewer entities do not
suffice, posit more!
ŒCONOMIA:
Grice: “The end of philosophy at Oxford came with the PPE – I mean, what does a
philosopher to do with the ‘laws’ of the ‘home’?” -- Cf. Grice on the principle
of oeconomia of rational effort. The Greeks used ‘oeconomia’ to mean thrifty.
Cf. effort. There were three branches of philosophia practica: philosophia
moralis, oeconomia and politica. Grice
would often refer to ‘no undue effort,’ ‘no unnecessary trouble,’ to go into
the effort, ‘not worth the energy,’ and so on. These utilitarian criteria
suggest he is more of a futilitarian than the avowed Kantian he says he is.
This Grice also refers to as ‘maximum,’ ‘maximal,’ optimal. It is part of his
principle of economy of rational effort. Grice leaves it open as how to
formulate this. Notably in “Causal,” he allows that ‘The pillar box seems red”
and “The pillar box is red” are difficult to formalise in terms in which we
legitimize the claim or intuition that ‘The pillar box IS red” is ‘stronger’
than ‘The pillar box seems red.’ If this were so, it would provide a rational
justification for going into the effort of uttering something STRONGER (and
thus less economical, and more effortful) under the circumstances. As in “My wife is in the kitchen or in the bedroom, and
the house has only two rooms (and no passages, etc.)” the reason why the
conversational implicaturum is standardly carried is to be found in the
operation of some such general principle as that giving preference to the
making of a STRONGER rather than a weaker statement in the absence of a reason
for not so doing. The implicaturum therefore is not of a part of the meaning of
the expression “seems.” There is however A VERY IMPORTANT DIFFERENCE between
the case of a ‘phenomenalist’ statement (Bar-Hillel it does not count as a
statement) and that of disjunctives, such as “My wife is in the kitchen or ind
the bedroom, and the house has only two rooms (and no passages, etc.).” A
disjunctive is weaker than either of its disjuncts in a straightforward LOGICAL
fashion, viz., a disjunctive is entailed (alla Moore) by, but does not entail,
each of its disjuncts. The statement “The pillar box is red” is NOT STRONGER
than the statement, if a statement it is, “The pillar box seems red,” in this
way. Neither statement entails the other. Grice thinks that he has,
neverthcless a strong inclination to regard the first of these statements as
STRONGER than the second. But Grice leaves it open the ‘determination’ of in
what fashion this might obtain. He suggests that there may be a way to provide
a reductive analysis of ‘strength’ THAT YIELDS that “The pillar box is red” is
a stronger conversational contribution than “The pillar box seems red.”
Recourse to ‘informativeness’ may not do, since Grice is willing to generalise
over the acceptum to cover informative and non-informative cases. While there
is an element of ‘exhibition’ in his account of the communicatum, he might not
be happy with the idea that it is the utterer’s INTENTION to INFORM his
addressee that he, the utterer, INTENDS that his addressee will believe that
he, the utterer, believes that it is raining. “Inform” seems to apply only to
the content of the propositional complexum, and not to the attending ‘animata.’
olivi: philosopher whose
views on the theory and practice of Franciscan poverty led to a long series of
investigations of his orthodoxy. Olivi’s preference for humility, as well as
the suspicion with which he was regarded, prevented his becoming a master of theology
at Paris. He was effectively vindicated and permitted to teach at Florence and
Montpellier. But after his death, probably in part because his remains were
venerated and his views were championed by the Franciscan Spirituals, his
orthodoxy was again examined. The Council of Vienne condemned three unrelated
tenets associated with Olivi. Finally, Pope John XXII condemned a series of
statements based on Olivi’s Apocalypse commentary. Olivi thought of himself
chiefly as a theologian, writing copious biblical commentaries; his philosophy
of history was influenced by Joachim of Fiore. His views on poverty inspired
the leader of the Franciscan Observant reform movement, St. Bernardino of
Siena. Apart from his views on poverty, Olivi is best known for his
philosophical independence from Aristotle, whom he condemned as a materialist.
Contrary to Aristotle’s theory of projectile motion, Olivi advocated a theory
of impetus. He undermined orthodox views on Aristotelian categories. His attack
on the category of relation was thought to have dangerous implications in
Trinitarian theology. Ockham’s theory of quantity is in part a defense of views
presented by Olivi. Olivi was critical of Augustinian as well as Aristotelian
views; he abandoned the theories of seminal reason and divine illumination. He
also argued against positing impressed sensible and intelligible species,
claiming that only the soul, not perceptual objects, played an active role in
perception. Bold as his philosophical views were, he presented them
tentatively. A voluntarist, he emphasized the importance of will. He claimed
that an act of understanding was not possible in the absence of an act of will.
He provided an important experiential argument for the freedom of the will. His
treatises on contracts revealed a sophisticated understanding of economics. His
treatise on evangelical poverty includes the first defense of a theory of papal
infallibility.
omega: the last letter
of the Grecian alphabet w. Following Canto,, it is used in lowercase as a
proper name for the first infinite ordinal number, which is the ordinal of the
natural ordering of the set of finite ordinals. By extension it is also used as
a proper name for the set of finite ordinals itself or even for the set of
natural numbers. Following Gödel 678, it is used as a prefix in names of
various logical properties of sets of sentences, most notably
omega-completeness and omega-consistency. Omega-completeness, in the original
sense due to Tarski, is a syntactical property of sets of sentences in a formal
arithmetic language involving a symbol ‘0’ for the number zero and a symbol ‘s’
for the so-called successor function, resulting in each natural number being
named by an expression, called a numeral, in the following series: ‘0’, ‘s0’,
‘ss0’, and so on. For example, five is denoted by ‘sssss0’. A set of sentences
is said to be omegacomplete if it deductively yields every universal sentence
all of whose singular instances it yields. In this framework, as usual, every
universal sentence, ‘for every n, n has P’ yields each and every one of its
singular instances, ‘0 has P’, ‘s0 has P’, ‘ss0 has P’, etc. However, as had
been known by logicians at least since the Middle Ages, the converse is not
true, i.e., it is not in general the case that a universal sentence is
deducible from the set of its singular instances. Thus one should not expect to
find omega-completeness except in exceptional sets. The set of all true
sentences of arithmetic is such an exceptional set; the reason is the semantic
fact that every universal sentence whether or not in arithmetic is materially
equivalent to the set of all its singular instances. A set of sentences that is
not omega-complete is said to be omega-incomplete. The existence of
omega-incomplete sets of sentences is a phenomenon at the core of the 1 Gödel
incompleteness result, which shows that every “effective” axiom set for
arithmetic is omega-incomplete and thus has as theorems all singular instances
of a universal sentence that is not one of its theorems. Although this is a
remarkable fact, the existence of omega-incomplete sets per se is far from
remarkable, as suggested above. In fact, the empty set and equivalently the set
of all tautologies are omega-incomplete because each yields all singular
instances of the non-tautological formal sentence, here called FS, that
expresses the proposition that every number is either zero or a successor.
Omega-consistency belongs to a set that does not yield the negation of any
universal sentence all of whose singular instances it yields. A set that is not
omega-consistent is said to be omega-inconsistent. Omega-inconsistency of
course implies consistency in the ordinary sense; but it is easy to find
consistent sets that are not omega-consistent, e.g., the set whose only member
is the negation of the formal sentence FS mentioned above. Corresponding to the
syntactical properties just mentioned there are analogous semantic properties
whose definitions are obtained by substituting ‘semantically implies’ for
‘deductively yields’. The Grecian letter omega and its English name have many
other uses in modern logic. Carnap introduced a non-effective, non-logical
rule, called the omega rule, for “inferring” a universal sentence from its
singular instances; adding the omega rule to a standard axiomatization of
arithmetic produces a complete but non-effective axiomatization. An
omega-valued logic is a many-valued logic whose set of truth-values is or is
the same size as the set of natural numbers. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “I know that
there are infinitely many stars.”
one-at-a-time-sailor. Grice’s ‘universale’ – and ‘particulare.’ – the \/x versus
the /\x. For \/x Grice has “one-at-a-time sailor.” For /\x Grice has ‘the
altogether nice girl.” “He is loved by the altogether nice girl. Or grasshopper:
Grice’s one-at-a-time grasshopper. His rational reconstruction of ‘some’ and
‘all.’ “A simple proposal for the treatment of the two quantifiers, rendered
otiosely in English by “all” and “some (at least one),” – “the” is definable in
terms of “all” -- would call for the assignment to a predicate such as that of
‘being a grasshopper,” symbolized by “G,” besides its normal or standard
EXtension, two special things (or ‘object,’ if one must use Quine’s misnomer),
associated with quantifiers, an 'altogether' ‘substitute’, thing or object and
a 'one-at-a-time' non-substitute thing or object.”“To the predicate
'grasshopper' is assigned not only an individual, viz. a grasshopper, but also
what I call ‘The All-Together Grass-Hopper,’
or species-1and ‘The One-At-A-Time Grass-Hopper,’ or species-2. “I now
stipulate that an 'altogether' item satisfies such a predicate as “being a
grasshopper,” or G, just in case every normal or standard item associated with
“the all-to-gether” grasshopper satisfies the predicate in question. Analogously,
a 'one-at-a-time' item satisfies a predicate just in case “SOME (AT LEAST ONE)”
of the associated standard items satisfies that predicate.”“So ‘The
All-To-Gether Grass-Hopper izzes green just in case every individual
grasshopper is green.The one-at-a-time grasshopper izzes green just in case some
(at least one) individual grasshopper izzes green.”“We can take this pair of
statements about these two special grasshoppers as providing us with
representations of (respectively) the statements, ‘Every grass-hopper is
green,’ and ‘Some (at least one) grasshopper is green.’“The apparatus which
Grice sketched is plainly not, as it stands, adequate to provide a comprehensive
treatment of quantification.”“It will not, e. g. cope with well-known problems of
multiple quantification,” as in “Every Al-Together Nice Grass-Hopper Loves A
Sailing Grass-Hopper.”“It will not deliver for us distinct representations of
the two notorious (alleged) readings of ‘Every nice girl loves a sailor,” in
one of which (supposedly) the universal quantifier is dominant with respect to
scope, and in the other of which the existential quantifier is dominant.”The
ambiguity was made ambiguous by Marie Lloyd. For every time she said “a
sailor,” she pointed at herself – thereby disimplicating the default implicaturum
that the universal quantifier be dominant. “To cope with Marie Lloyd’s problem
it might be sufficient to explore, for semantic purposes, the device of
exportation, and to distinguish between, 'There exists a sailor such that every
nice girl loves him', which attributes a certain property to the one-at-a-time
sailor, and (ii) 'Every nice girl is such that she loves some sailor', which
attributes a certain (and different) property to the altogether nice girl.Note
that, as one makes this move, that though exportation, when applied to
statements about individual objects, seems not to affect truth-value, whatever
else may be its semantic function, when it is applied to sentences about
special objects it may, and sometimes will, affect truth-value.”“But however
effective this particular shift may be, it is by no means clear that there are
not further demands to be met which would overtax the strength of the envisaged
apparatus.It is not, for example, clear whether it could be made adequate to
deal with indefinitely long strings of 'mixed' quantifiers.”“The proposal might
also run into objections of a more conceptual character from those who would
regard the special objects which it invokes as metaphysically disreputable –
for where would an ‘altogether sailor” sail?, or an one-at-a-time grasshopper
hop?“Should an alternative proposal be reached or desired, one (or, indeed,
more than one) is available.”“One may be regarded as a replacement for, an
extension of, or a reinterpretation of the scheme just outlined, in accordance
with whatever view is finally taken of the potency and respectability of the ideas
embodied in that scheme.” “This proposal treats a propositional complexum as a
sequence, indeed as ordered pairs containing a subject-item and a
predicate-item.It thus offers a subject-predicate account of quantification (as
opposed to what?, you may wonder). However, it will not allow an individual, i.
e. a sailor, or a nice girl, to appear as COMPONENTS in a propositional
complexum.The sailor and the nice girl will always be reduced, ‘extensionally,’
or ‘extended,’ if you wish, as a set or an attribute.“According to the class-theoretic
version, we associate with the subject-expression of a canonically formulated
sentence a class of (at least) a second order. If the subject expression is a
singular name, like “Grice,” its ontological correlatum will be the singleton
of the singleton of the entity which bears the name Grice, or Pop-Eye.” “The
treatment of a singular terms which are not names – e. g. ‘the sailor’ -- will
be parallel, but is here omitted. It involves the iota operator, about which
Russell would say that Frege knew a iota. If the subject-expression is an
indefinite quantificational phrase, like 'some (at least one) sailor’ ‘or some
(at least one) grasshopper', its ontological correlatum will be the set of all
singletons whose sole member is a member belonging to the extension of the
predicate to which the indefinite modifier “some (at least one)” is attached.So
the ontological correlatum of the phrase ‘some (at least one) sailor’ or 'some (at
least one) grasshopper' will be the class of all singletons whose sole member
is an individuum (sailor, grasshopper). If the subject expression is a universal
quantificational phrase, like ‘every nice girl’ its ontological correlatum will
be the singleton whose sole member is the class which forms the extension of
the predicate to which the universal modifier (‘every’) is attached.Thus, the correlate of the phrase 'every nice girl' will
be the singleton of the class of nice girls.The song was actually NOT written
by a nice girl – but by a bad boy.A predicate of a canonically formulated
sentence is correlated with the classes which form its extension.As for the
predication-relation, i. e., the relation which has to obtain between
subject-element and predicate-element in a propositional complex for that
complex to be factive, a propositional complexum is factive or
value-satisfactory just in case its subject-element contains as a member at least
one item which is a sub-class of the predicate-element.”If the ontological
correlatum of 'a sailor,’ or, again, of 'every nice girl') contains as a member
at least one subset of the ontological correlata of the dyadic predicate ' …
loves … ' (viz. the class of love), the propositional complexum directly
associated with the sentence ‘A sailor loves every nice girl’ is factive, as is
its converse“Grice devotes a good deal of energy to the ‘one-at-a-time-sailor,’
and the ‘altogether nice girl’ and he convinced himself that it offered a
powerful instrument which, with or without adjustment, is capable of handling
not only indefinitely long sequences of ‘mixed’ quantificational phrases, but
also some other less obviously tractable problems, such as the ‘ground’ for
this being so: what it there about a sailor – well, you know what sailors are.
When the man o' war or merchant ship comes sailing into port/The jolly tar with
joy, will sing out, Land Ahoy!/With his pockets full of money and a parrot in a
cage/He smiles at all the pretty girls upon the landing stage/All the nice
girls love a sailor/All the nice girls love a tar/For there's something about a
sailor/(Well you know what sailors are!)/Bright and breezy, free and easy,/He's
the ladies' pride and joy!/He falls in love with Kate and Jane, then he's off
to sea again,/Ship ahoy! Ship ahoy!/He will spend his money freely, and he's generous
to his pals,/While Jack has got a sou, there's half of it for you,/And it's
just the same in love and war, he goes through with a smile,/And you can trust
a sailor, he's a white man (meaning: honest man) all the while!“Before moving
on, however, I might perhaps draw attention to three features of the proposal.”“First,
employing a strategy which might be thought of as Leibnizian, it treats a
subject-element (even a lowly tar) as being of an order HIGHER than, rather
than an order LOWER than, the predicate element.”“Second, an individual name,
such as Grice, is in effect treated like a universal quantificational phrase,
thus recalling the practice of old-style traditionalism.“Third, and most
importantly, the account which is offered is, initially, an account of
propositional complexes, not of propositions; as I envisage them, propositions
will be regarded as families of propositional complexes.”“Now the propositional
complexum directly associated with the sentence “Every nice girl loves a
sailor” (WoW: 34) will be both logically equivalent to and numerically distinct
from the propositional complex directly associated with ‘It is not the case
that no nice girl loves no sailor.’ Indeed for any given propositional complex
there will be indefinitely many propositional complexes which are both
equipolent to yet numerically distinct from the original complexum. Strawson
used to play with this. The question of how tight or how relaxed are to be the
family ties which determine the IDENTITY of propositio 1 with propositio 2 remains to be decided. Such conditions will vary
according to context or purpose. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Every nice girl loves a
sailor: the implicatura.”
occam: Grice: “I hate it when people who wouldn’t know London
from their elbow pretentiously use ‘Ockham’ when Aquinas consistently uses
Occam.” -- a picturesque village in Surrey. His most notable resident is
William. When William left Occam, he was often asked, “Where are you from?” In
the vernacular, he would make an effort to aspirate the ‘h’ Ock-Home.’ His
French friends were unable to aspirate, and he ended up accepting that perhaps
he WAS from “Occam.” Vide Modified Occam’s Razor. occamism – Grice, “I’m not so much interested
in Occam as in the Occam Society, that I endured!” -- Occamism: d’Ailly,
P.: Ockhamist philosopher, prelate, and writer. Educated at the Collège de
Navarre, he was promoted to doctor in the Sorbonne in 1380, appointed
chancellor of Paris in 1389, consecrated
bishop in 1395, and made a cardinal in 1411. He was influenced by John of
Mirecourt’s nominalism. He taught Gerson. At the Council of Constance 141418,
which condemned Huss’s teachings, d’Ailly upheld the superiority of the council
over the pope conciliarism. The relation of astrology to history and theology
figures among his primary interests. His 1414 Tractatus de Concordia
astronomicae predicted the 1789
Revolution. He composed a De anima, a commentary on Boethius’s
Consolation of Philosophy, and another on Peter Lombard’s Sentences. His early
logical work, Concepts and Insolubles c.1472, was particularly influential. In
epistemology, d’Ailly contradistinguished “natural light” indubitable knowledge
from reason relative knowledge, and emphasized thereafter the uncertainty of
experimental knowledge and the mere probability of the classical “proofs” of
God’s existence. His doctrine of God differentiates God’s absolute power
potentia absoluta from God’s ordained power on earth potentia ordinata. His
theology anticipated fideism Deum esse sola fide tenetur, his ethics the spirit
of Protestantism, and his sacramentology Lutheranism.
one-off communicatum. The
condition for an action to be taken in a specific way in cases where the audience
must recognize the utterer’s intention (a ‘one-off predicament’). The
recognition of the C-intention does not have to occur ‘once we have habits of
taking utterances one way or another.’
Blackburn:
one of the few philosohpers from Pembroke that Grice respects! -- From one-off
AIIBp to one-off GAIIB. Surely we have to generalise the B into the
PSI. Plus, 'action' is too strong, and should be replaced by
'emitting'This yields From EIIψp
GEIIψp. According to this
assumption, an emissor who is not assuming his addressee shares any system of
communication is in the original situation that S. W. Blackburn, of Pembroke,
dubbs “the one-off
predicament, and one can provide a scenario where the Griciean conditions, as
they are meant to hold, do hold, and emissor E communicates that p i. e. C1,
C2, and C3, are fulfilled, be accomplished in the "one-off predicament" (in
which no linguistic or other conventional ...The Gricean mechanism with
its complex communicative intentions has a clear point in what Blackburn calls
“a one-off predicament”
- a . Simon
Blackburn's "one-off
predicament" of communicating without a shared language
illustrates how Grice's theory can be applied to iconic signals such as
the ...Blackburn's
"one-off predicament" of communicating without a shared language
illustrates how Grice's theory can be applied to iconic signals such as the
drawing of a skull to wam of danger. See his Spreading the Word. III. 112.Thus S may draw a pic- "one-off predicament"). ... Clarendon, 1976); and Simon Blackburn, Spreading the Word
(Oxford: Clarendon, 1984) ...by
Blackburn in “Spreading the word.” Since Grice’s main motivation is to progress
from one-off to philosophers’s mistakes, he does not explore the situation. He
gets close to it in “Meaning Revisited,” when proposing a ‘rational
reconstruction,’ FROM a one-off to a non-iconic system of communication, where
you can see his emphasis and motivation is in the last stage of the progress.
Since he is having the ‘end result,’ sometimes he is not careful in the
description of the ‘one-off,’ or dismissive of it. But as Blackburn notes, it
is crucial that Grice provides the ‘rudiments’ for a ‘meaning-nominalism,’
where an emissor can communicate that p in a one-off scenario. This is all
Grice needs to challenge those accounts based on ‘convention,’ or the idea of a
‘system’ of communication. There is possibly an implicaturum to the effect that
if something is a device is not a one-off, but that is easily cancellable. “He
used a one-off device, and it worked.”
one-piece-repertoire: of hops and rye, and he told me that in twenty-two years
neither the personnel of the three-piece band nor its one-piece
repertoire had undergone a change.
Unum:
One of the transcendentals – see Achillini -- see: one-many problem: also
called one-and-many problem, the question whether all things are one or many.
According to both Plato and Aristotle this was the central question for
pre-Socratic philosophers. Those who answered “one,” the monists, ascribed to
all things a single nature such as water, air, or oneness itself. They appear
not to have been troubled by the notion that numerically many things would have
this one nature. The pluralists, on the other hand, distinguished many
principles or many types of principles, though they also maintained the unity
of each principle. Some monists understood the unity of all things as a denial
of motion, and some pluralists advanced their view as a way of refuting this
denial. To judge from our sources, early Grecian metaphysics revolved around
the problem of the one and the many. In the modern period the dispute between
monists and pluralists centered on the question whether mind and matter
constitute one or two substances and, if one, what its nature is. Unum – see: one over many, a universale;
especially, a Platonic Form. According to Plato, if there are, e.g., many large
things, there must be some one largeness itself in respect of which they are
large; this “one over many” hen epi pollon is an intelligible entity, a Form,
in contrast with the sensible many. Plato himself recognizes difficulties
explaining how the one character can be present to the many and why the one and
the many do not together constitute still another many e.g., Parmenides
131a133b. Aristotle’s sustained critique of Plato’s Forms Metaphysics A 9, Z
1315 includes these and other problems, and it is he, more than Plato, who
regularly uses ‘one over many’ to refer to Platonic Forms.
ontogenesis.
Grice taught his children “not to tell lies” – “as my father and my mother
taught me.” One of his favourite paintings was “When did you last see your
father?” “I saw him in my dreams,” – “Not a lie, you see.” it is interesting
that Grice was always enquiring his childrens playmates: Can a sweater be red
and green all over? No stripes allowed! One found a developmental account of
the princile of conversational helpfulness boring, or as he said,
"dull." Refs.: There is an essay on the semantics of children’s language,
BANC.
Esse – variations
on ‘esse’ give us Grice’s ontological marxism:
As opposed to ‘ontological laisssez-faire’ Note the use of ‘ontological’
in ‘ontological’ Marxism. Is not metaphysical Marxism, so Grice knows what he
is talking about. Many times when he uses ‘metaphysics,’ he means
‘ontological.’ Ontological for Grice is at
least liberal. He is hardly enamoured of some of the motivations which prompt
the advocacy of psycho-physical identity. He has in mind a concern to exclude
an entity such as as a ‘soul,’ an event of the soul, or a property of the soul.
His taste is for keeping open house for all sorts of conditions of entities,
just so long as when the entity comes in it helps with the housework, i. e.,
provided that Grice see the entity work, and provided that it is not detected
in illicit logical behaviour, which need not involve some degree of
indeterminacy, The entity works? Ergo, the entity exists. And, if it comes on
the recommendation of some transcendental argument the entity may even qualify
as an entium realissimum. To exclude an honest working entitiy is metaphysical
snobbery, a reluctance to be seen in the company of any but the best. A
category, a universalium plays a role in Grice’s meta-ethics. A principles or
laws of psychology may be self-justifying, principles connected with the
evaluation of ends. If these same principles play a role in determining
what we count as entia realissima, metaphysics, and an abstractum would be
grounded in part in considerations about value (a not unpleasant
project). This ontological Marxism is latter day. In “Some remarks,” he
expresses his disregard for what he calls a “Wittgensteinian” limitation in
expecting behavioural manifestation of an ascription about a soul. Yet in
“Method” he quotes almost verbatim from Witters, “No psychological postulation
without the behaviour the postulation is meant to explain.” It was possibly D.
K. Lewis who made him change his mind. Grice was obsessed with Aristotle on
‘being,’ and interpreted Aristotle as holding a thesis of unified semantic
‘multiplicity.’ This is in agreement with the ontological Marxism, in more than
one ways. By accepting a denotatum for a praedicatum like ‘desideratum,’ Grice
is allowing the a desideratum may be the subject of discourse. It is an
‘entity’ in this fashion. Marxism and laissez-faire both
exaggerate the role of the economy. Society needs a safety net to soften the
rough edges of free enterprise. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Ontological Marxism
and ontological laissez-faire.” Engels – studied by Grice for his “Ontological
Marxism” -- F, G. socialist and economist who, with Marx, was the founder of
what later was called Marxism. Whether there are significant differences
between Marx and Engels is a question much in dispute among scholars of
Marxism. Certainly there are differences in emphasis, but there was also a
division of labor between them. Engels, and not Marx, presented a Marxist
account of natural science and integrated Darwinian elements in Marxian theory.
But they also coauthored major works, including The Holy Family, The G.
Ideology 1845, and The Communist Manifesto 1848. Engels thought of himself as
the junior partner in their lifelong collaboration. That judgment is correct,
but Engels’s work is both significant and more accessible than Marx’s. He gave
popular articulations of their common views in such books as Socialism: Utopian
and Scientific and AntiDühring 1878. His work, more than Marx’s, was taken by
the Second International and many subsequent Marxist militants to be definitive
of Marxism. Only much later with some Western Marxist theoreticians did his
influence decline. Engels’s first major work, The Condition of the Working
Class in England 1845, vividly depicted workers’ lives, misery, and systematic
exploitation. But he also saw the working class as a new force created by the
industrial revolution, and he developed an account of how this new force would
lead to the revolutionary transformation of society, including collective
ownership and control of the means of production and a rational ordering of
social life; all this would supersede the waste and disparity of human
conditions that he took to be inescapable under capitalism. The G. Ideology,
jointly authored with Marx, first articulated what was later called historical
materialism, a conception central to Marxist theory. It is the view that the
economic structure of society is the foundation of society; as the productive
forces develop, the economic structure changes and with that political, legal,
moral, religious, and philosophical ideas change accordingly. Until the
consolidation of socialism, societies are divided into antagonistic classes, a
person’s class being determined by her relationship to the means of production.
The dominant ideas of a society will be strongly conditioned by the economic
structure of the society and serve the class interests of the dominant class.
The social consciousness the ruling ideology will be that which answers to the
interests of the dominant class. From the 1850s on, Engels took an increasing
interest in connecting historical materialism with developments in natural
science. This work took definitive form in his Anti-Dühring, the first general
account of Marxism, and in his posthumously published Dialectics of Nature.
AntiDühring also contains his most extensive discussion of morality. It was in
these works that Engels articulated the dialectical method and a systematic
communist worldview that sought to establish that there were not only social
laws expressing empirical regularities in society but also universal laws of
nature and thought. These dialectical laws, Engels believed, reveal that both
nature and society are in a continuous process of evolutionary though
conflict-laden development. Engels should not be considered primarily, if at
all, a speculative philosopher. Like Marx, he was critical of and ironical
about speculative philosophy and was a central figure in the socialist
movement. While always concerned that his account be warrantedly assertible,
Engels sought to make it not only true, but also a finely tuned instrument of
working-class emancipation which would lead to a world without classes. Refs.:
H. P. Grice, “Ontological Marxism.”
Esse – variations
on ‘esse’ give us ‘ontological,’ and thus, ontological commitment: the object or
objects common to the ontology fulfilling some regimented theory a term
fashioned by Quine. The ontology of a regimented theory consists in the objects
the theory assumes there to be. In order to show that a theory assumes a given
object, or objects of a given class, we must show that the theory would be true
only if that object existed, or if that class is not empty. This can be shown
in two different but equivalent ways: if the notation of the theory contains
the existential quantifier ‘Ex’ of first-order predicate logic, then the theory
is shown to assume a given object, or objects of a given class, provided that
object is required among the values of the bound variables, or additionally is
required among the values of the domain of a given predicate, in order for the
theory to be true. Thus, if the theory entails the sentence ‘Exx is a dog’,
then the values over which the bound variable ‘x’ ranges must include at least
one dog, in order for the theory to be true. Alternatively, if the notation of
the theory contains for each predicate a complementary predicate, then the
theory assumes a given object, or objects of a given class, provided some
predicate is required to be true of that object, in order for the theory to be
true. Thus, if the theory contains the predicate ‘is a dog’, then the extension
of ‘is a dog’ cannot be empty, if the theory is to be true. However, it is
possible for different, even mutually exclusive, ontologies to fulfill a theory
equally well. Thus, an ontology containing collies to the exclusion of spaniels
and one containing spaniels to the exclusion of collies might each fulfill a
theory that entails ‘Ex x is a dog’. It follows that some of the objects a
theory assumes in its ontology may not be among those to which the theory is
ontologically committed. A theory is ontologically committed to a given object
only if that object is common to all of the ontologies fulfilling the theory.
And the theory is ontologically committed to objects of a given class provided
that class is not empty according to each of the ontologies fulfilling the
theory.
casus obliquum
– Grice: “A bit of a redundancy: if it is a casus (ptosis), surely it fell
obliquely – the ‘casus rectum’ is an otiosity! Since ‘recte, ‘menans ‘not
oblique’! -- casus rectum (orthe ptosis) vs. ‘casus obliquus – plagiai ptoseis
– genike, dotike, aitiatike. “ptosis” is not
attested in Grecian before Plato. A noun of action based on the radical of
πίπτω, to fall, ptôsis means literally a fall: the fall of a die Plato,
Republic, X.604c, or of lightning Aristotle, Meteorology, 339a Alongside this
basic value and derived metaphorical values: decadence, death, and so forth, in
Aristotle the word receives a linguistic specification that was to have great
influence: retained even in modern Grecian ptôsê πτώση, its Roman Tr. casus allowed it to designate grammatical
case in most modern European languages. In fact, however, when it first appears
in Aristotle, the term does not initially designate the noun’s case inflection.
In the De Int. chaps. 2 and 3, it qualifies the modifications, both semantic
and formal casual variation of the verb and those of the noun: he was well, he
will be well, in relation to he is well; about Philo, to Philo, in relation to
Philo. As a modification of the noun—that is, in Aristotle, of its basic form,
the nominative—the case ptôsis differs from the noun insofar as, associated
with is, was, or will be, it does not permit the formation of a true or false
statement. As a modification of the verb, describing the grammatical tense, it
is distinguished from the verb that oversignifies the present: the case of the
verb oversignifies the time that surrounds the present. From this we must
conclude that to the meaning of a given verb e.g., walk the case of the verb
adds the meaning prossêmainei πϱοσσημαίνει of its temporal modality he will
walk. Thus the primacy of the present over the past and the future is affirmed,
since the present of the verb has no case. But the Aristotelian case is a still
broader, vaguer, and more elastic notion: presented as part of expression in
chapter 20 of the Poetics, it qualifies variation in number and modality. It
further qualifies the modifications of the noun, depending on the gender ch.21
of the Poetics; Top. as well as adverbs
derived from a substantive or an adjective, like justly, which is derived from
just. The notion of case is thus essential for the characterization of
paronyms. Aristotle did not yet have specialized names for the different cases
of nominal inflection. When he needs to designate them, he does so in a
conventional manner, usually by resorting to the inflected form of a pronoun—
τούτου, of this, for the genitive, τούτῳ, to this, for the dative, and so on —
and sometimes to that of a substantive or adjective. In the Prior Analytics,
Aristotle insists on distinguishing between the terms ὅϱοι that ought always to
be stated in the nominative ϰλῆσεις, e.g. man, good, contraries, but the
premisses ought to be understood with reference to the cases of each term—either
the dative, e.g. ‘equal to this’ toutôi, dative, or the genitive, e.g. ‘double
of this’ toutou, genitive, or the accusative, e.g. ‘that which strikes or v.s
this’ τούτο, accusative, or the nominative, e.g. ‘man is an animal’ οὗτος,
nominative, or in whatever other way the word falls πίπτει in the premiss Anal.
Post., I.36, 48b, 4 In the latter expression, we may find the origin of the
metaphor of the fall—which remains controversial. Some commentators relate the
distinction between what is direct and what is oblique as pertains to
grammatical cases, which may be direct orthê ptôsis or oblique plagiai ptôseis,
but also to the grand metaphoric and conceptual register that stands on this
distinction to falling in the game of jacks, it being possible that the jack
could fall either on a stable side and stand there—the direct case—or on three
unstable sides— the oblique cases. In an unpublished dissertation on the
principles of Stoic grammar, Hans Erich Müller proposes to relate the Stoic
theory of cases to the theory of causality, by trying to associate the
different cases with the different types of causality. They would thus
correspond in the utterance to the different causal postures of the body in the
physical field. For the Stoics, predication is a matter not of identifying an
essence ousia οὖσια and its attributes in conformity with the Aristotelian
categories, but of reproducing in the utterance the causal relations of action
and passion that bodies entertain among themselves. It was in fact with the
Stoics that cases were reduced to noun cases—in Dionysius Thrax TG, 13, the
verb is a word without cases lexis aptôton, and although egklisis means mode,
it sometimes means inflection, and then it covers the variations of the verb,
both temporal and modal. If Diogenes Laertius VII.192 is to be believed,
Chrysippus wrote a work On the Five Cases. It must have included, as Diogenes
VII.65 tells us, a distinction between the direct case orthê ptôsis—the case
which, constructed with a predicate, gives rise to a proposition axiôma,
VII.64—and oblique cases plagiai ptseis, which now are given names, in this
order: genitive genikê, dative dôtikê, and accusative aitiatikê. A
classification of predicates is reported by Porphyry, cited in Ammonius
Commentaire du De Int. d’Aristote, 44, 19f.. Ammonius 42, 30f. reports a
polemic between Aristotle and the Peripatetics, on the one hand, and the Stoics
and grammarians associated with them, on the other. For the former, the
nominative is not a case, it is the noun itself from which the cases are
declined; for the latter, the nominative is a full-fledged case: it is the
direct case, and if it is a case, that is because it falls from the concept,
and if it is direct, that is because it falls directly, just as the stylus can,
after falling, remain stable and straight. Although ptôsis is part of the
definition of the predicate—the predicate is what allows, when associated with
a direct case, the composition of a proposition—and figures in the part of
dialectic devoted to signifieds, it is neither defined nor determined as a
constituent of the utterance alongside the predicate. In Stoicism, ptôsis v.ms
to signify more than grammatical case alone. Secondary in relation to the
predicate that it completes, it is a philosophical concept that refers to the
manner in which the Stoics v.m to have criticized the Aristotelian notion of
substrate hupokeimenon ὑποϰειμένον as well as the distinction between substance
and accidents. Ptôsis is the way in which the body or bodies that our representation
phantasia φαντασία presents to us in a determined manner appear in the
utterance, issuing not directly from perception, but indirectly, through the
mediation of the concept that makes it possible to name it/them in the form of
an appellative a generic concept, man, horse or a name a singular concept,
Socrates. Cases thus represent the diverse ways in which the concept of the
body falls in the utterance though Stoic nominalism does not admit the
existence of this concept—just as here there is no Aristotelian category
outside the different enumerated categorial rubrics, there is no body outside a
case position. However, caring little for these subtleties, the scholiasts of
Technê v.m to confirm this idea in their own context when they describe the ptôsis
as the fall of the incorporeal and the generic into the specific ἔϰ τοῦ γενιϰοῦ
εἰς τὸ εἰδιϰόν. In the work of the grammarians, case is reduced to the
grammatical case, that is, to the morphological variation of nouns, pronouns,
articles, and participles, which, among the parts of speech, accordingly
constitute the subclass of casuels, a parts of speech subject to case-based
inflection πτωτιϰά. The canonical list of cases places the vocative klêtikê ϰλητιϰή
last, after the direct eutheia εὐθεῖα case and the three oblique cases, in
their Stoic order: genitive, dative, accusative. This order of the oblique
cases gives rise, in some commentators eager to rationalize Scholia to the
Technê, 549, 22, to a speculation inspired by localism: the case of the PARONYM
743 place from which one comes in Grecian , the genitive is supposed naturally
to precede that of the place where one is the dative, which itself naturally
precedes that of the place where one is going the accusative. Apollonius’s
reflection on syntax is more insightful; in his Syntax III.15888 he presents,
in this order, the accusative, the genitive, and the dative as expressing three
degrees of verbal transitivity: conceived as the distribution of activity and
passivity between the prime actant A in the direct case and the second actant B
in one of the three oblique cases in the process expressed by a biactantial
verb, the transitivity of the accusative corresponds to the division A all
active—B all passive A strikes B; the transitivity of the genitive corresponds
to the division A primarily active/passive to a small degree—B primarily
passive/active to a small degree A listens to B; and the transitivity of the
dative, to the division A and B equally active-passive A fights with The direct
case, at the head of the list, owes its prmacy to the fact that it is the case
of nomination: names are given in the direct case. The verbs of existence and
nomination are constructed solely with the direct case, without the function of
the attribute being thematized as such. Although Chrysippus wrote about five
cases, the fifth case, the vocative, v.ms to have escaped the division into
direct and oblique cases. Literally appelative prosêgorikon πϱοσηγοϱιϰόν, it
could refer not only to utterances of address but also more generally to
utterances of nomination. In the grammarians, the vocative occupies a marginal
place; whereas every sentence necessarily includes a noun and a verb, the
vocative constitutes a complete sentence by itself. Frédérique Ildefonse REFS.:
Aristotle. Analytica priorTr. J.
Jenkinson. In the Works of Aristotle, vol. 1, ed. and Tr.
W. D. Ross, E. M. Edghill, J. Jenkinson, G.R.G. Mure, and Wallace
Pickford. Oxford: Oxford , 192 . Poetics. Ed.
and Tr. Stephen Halliwell.
Cambridge: Harvard / Loeb Classical
Library, . Delamarre, Alexandre. La notion de ptōsis chez Aristote et les
Stoïciens. In Concepts et Catégories dans la pensée antique, ed. by Pierre Aubenque, 3214 : Vrin, . Deleuze,
Gilles. Logique du sens. : Minuit, . Tr.
Mark Lester with Charles Stivale: The Logic of Sense. Ed. by Constantin V. Boundas. : Columbia , .
Dionysius Thrax. Technē grammatikē. Book I, vol. 1 of Grammatici Graeci,
ed. by Gustav Uhlig. Leipzig: Teubner,
188 Eng. Tr. T. D. son: The Grammar. St. Louis, 187 Fr. Tr. J.
Lallot: La grammaire de Denys le Thrace. 2nd rev. and expanded ed. : CNRS
Éditions, . Frede, Michael. The Origins of Traditional Grammar. In Historical
and Philosophical Dimensions of Logic, Methodology, and Phil. of Science, ed. by E. H. Butts and J. Hintikka, 517
Dordrecht, Neth.: Reiderl, . Reprinted, in M. Frede, Essays in Ancient Phil. ,
3385 Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, . . The Stoic Notion of a
Grammatical Case. Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies of the
University of 39 : 132 Hadot, Pierre. La notion de ‘cas’ dans la logique
stoïcienne. Pp. 10912 in Actes du XIIIe Congrès des sociétés de philosophie en
langue française. Geneva: Baconnière, . Hiersche, Rolf. Entstehung und
Entwicklung des Terminus πτῶσις, ‘Fall.’ Sitzungsberichte der deutschen
Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin: Klasse für Sprachen, Literatur und Kunst
3 1955: 51 Ildefonse, Frédérique. La naissance de la grammaire dans l’Antiquité
grecque. : Vrin, . Imbert, Claude. Phénoménologies et langues formularies. :
Presses Universitaires de France, . Pinborg, Jan. Classical Antiquity: Greece.
In Current Trends in Linguistics, ed. by
Th. Sebeok. Vol. 13 in Historiography of Linguistics series. The Hague and :
Mouton, .-- oratio obliqua: The idea of
‘oratio’ is central. Grice’s sentence. It expresses ‘a thought,’ a
‘that’-clause. Oratio recta is central, too. Grice’s example is “The dog is
shaggy.” The use of ‘oratio’ here Grice disliked. One can see a squarrel
grabbing a nut, Toby judges that a nut is to eat. So we would have a
‘that’-clause, and in a way, an ‘oratio obliqua,’ which is what the UTTERER
(not the squarrel) would produce as ‘oratio recta,’ ‘A nut is to eat,’ should
the circumstance obtains. At some points he allows things like “Snow is white”
means that snow is white. Something at the Oxford Philosohical Society he would
not. Grice is vague in this. If the verb is a ‘verbum dicendi,’ ‘oratio
obliqua’ is literal. If it’s a verbum sentiendi or percipiendi, volendi, credendi,
or cognoscenti, the connection is looser. Grice was especially concerned that
buletic verbs usually do not take a that-clause (but cf. James: I will that the
distant table sides over the floor toward me. It does not!). Also that seems
takes a that-clause in ways that might not please Maucalay. Grice had explored
that-clauses with Staal. He was concerned about the viability of an initially
appealing etymological approach by Davidson to the that-clause in terms of
demonstration. Grice had presupposed the logic of that-clauses from a much
earlier stage, Those spots mean that he has measles.The f. contains a copy of
Davidsons essay, On saying that, the that-clause, the that-clause, with Staal .
Davidson quotes from Murray et al. The Oxford English Dictionary, Oxford.
Cf. Onions, An Advanced English Syntax, and remarks that first learned
that that in such contexts evolved from an explicit demonstrative from
Hintikkas Knowledge and Belief. Hintikka remarks that a similar development has
taken place in German Davidson owes the reference to the O.E.D. to Stiezel.
Indeed Davidson was fascinated by the fact that his conceptual inquiry repeated
phylogeny. It should come as no surprise that a that-clause
utterance evolves through about the stages our ruminations have just
carried us. According to the Oxford English Dictionary, the use of that in a
that-clause is generally held to have arisen out of the demonstrative pronoun
pointing to the clause which it introduces. The sequence goes as follows. He
once lived here: we all know that; that, now this, we all know: he once lived
here; we all know that, or this: he once lived here; we all know that he once
lived here. As Hintikka notes, some pedants trying to display their knowledge
of German, use a comma before that: We all know, that he once lived here, to
stand for an earlier :: We all know: that he once lived here. Just like
the English translation that, dass can be omitted in a
sentence. Er glaubt, dass die Erde eine
Scheibe sei. He believes that the Earth is a disc. Er
glaubt, die Erde sei eine Scheibe. He believes the Earth is a disc. The
that-clause is brought to the fore by Davidson, who, consulting the OED,
reminds philosophers that the English that is very cognate with the German
idiom. More specifically, that is a demonstrative, even if the syntax, in
English, hides this fact in ways which German syntax doesnt. Grice needs
to rely on that-clauses for his analysis of mean, intend, and notably
will. He finds that Prichards genial discovery was the license to use
willing as pre-facing a that-clause. This allows Grice to deals with
willing as applied to a third person. I will that he wills that he wins the
chess match. Philosophers who disregard this third-person use may indulge in
introspection and Subjectsivism when they shouldnt! Grice said that Prichard
had to be given great credit for seeing that the accurate specification of
willing should be willing that and not willing to. Analogously, following
Prichard on willing, Grice does not
stipulate that the radix for an intentional (utterer-oriented or
exhibitive-autophoric-buletic) incorporate a reference to the utterer (be in
the first person), nor that the radix for an imperative (addressee-oriented or
hetero-phoric protreptic buletic) or desiderative in general, incorporate a
reference of the addressee (be in the second person). They shall not pass is a
legitimate intentional as is the ‘you shall not get away with it,’either
involves Prichards wills that, rather than wills to). And the sergeant is to
muster the men at dawn (uttered by a captain to a lieutenant) is a perfectly
good imperative, again involving Prichards wills that, rather than wills to. Refs.:
The allusions are scattered, but there are specific essays, one on the
‘that’-clause, and also discussions on Davidson on saying that. There is a
reference to ‘oratio obliqua’ and Prichard in “Uncertainty,” BANC.
No comments:
Post a Comment