metaphoricum implicaturum: Grice made a
dictionary of figures of rhetoric – from A to Z.
accumulation: Grice, “As its
name implies, this is the utterer accumulating arguments in a concise forceful
manner.”
adnomination: Grice: As the
name implies, this is the repetition of words with the same root word.
alliteration: Grice: “As the
name implies, this is a device, where a series of words in a row have the same
first consonant sound. It was quite used by my ancestors – they called it
‘head-rhyme.’” Example: "She sells sea shells by the sea shore".
Adynaton: Grice: “This is
almost like Hyperbole, as in the ditty, “Every nice girl loves a sailor.” It is
an extreme exaggeration used to make a point. It is like the opposite of
"understatement". Example: "I've told you a million times."
anacoluthon: Grice, as the
name implies, this is a Transposition of clauses to achieve an unnatural (or
non-natural) order in a sentence. “Join them, if you can’t beat’em.”
anadiplosis: Repetition of a
word at the end of a clause and then at the beginning of its succeeding clause.
anaphora: Repetition of the same word or set of words in a paragraph.
anastrophe: Grice: As the name
implies this Changing the object, subject and verb order in a clause, as in “Me
loves she,” as uttered by Tarzan.
anti-climax: It is when a
specific point, expectations are raised, everything is built-up and then
suddenly something boring or disappointing happens. Example: "People,
pets, batteries, ... all are dead."
anthimeria: Transformation of
a word of a certain word class to another word class.
antimetabole: A sentence
consisting of the repetition of words in successive clauses, but in reverse
order.
antirrhesis: Disproving an
opponent's argument. antistrophe: Repetition of the same word or group of words
in a paragraph in the end of sentences. antithesis: Juxtaposition of opposing
or contrasting ideas.
aphorismus: Statement that
calls into question the definition of a word. aposiopesis: Breaking off or
pausing speech for dramatic or emotional effect. apposition: Placing of two
statements side by side, in which the second defines the first. assonance:
Repetition of vowel sounds: "Smooth move!" or "Please
leave!" or "That's the fact Jack!"
asteismus: Mocking answer or
humorous answer that plays on a word.
asterismos: Beginning a
segment of speech with an exclamation of a word. asyndeton: Omission of
conjunctions between related clauses. cacophony: Words producing a harsh sound.
cataphora: Co-reference of one expression with another expression which follows
it, in which the latter defines the first. (example: If you need one, there's a
towel in the top drawer.) classification: Linking a proper noun and a common
noun with an article chiasmus: Two or more clauses are related to each other
through a reversal of structures in order to make a larger point climax:
Arrangement of words in order of descending to ascending order. commoratio:
Repetition of an idea, re-worded conduplicatio: Repetition of a key word
conversion (word formation): An unaltered transformation of a word of one word
class into another word class consonance: Repetition of consonant sounds, most
commonly within a short passage of verse correlative verse: Matching items in
two sequences diacope: Repetition of a word or phrase with one or two intervening
words dubitatio: Expressing doubt and uncertainty about oneself dystmesis: A
synonym for tmesis ellipsis: Omission of words elision: Omission of one or more
letters in speech, making it colloquial enallage: Wording ignoring grammatical
rules or conventions enjambment: Incomplete sentences at the end of lines in
poetry enthymeme: An informal syllogism epanalepsis: Ending sentences with
their beginning. epanodos: Word repetition. epistrophe: (also known as
antistrophe) Repetition of the same word or group of words at the end of
successive clauses. The counterpart of anaphora epizeuxis: Repetition of a
single word, with no other words in between euphony: Opposite of cacophony –
i.e. pleasant-sounding half rhyme: Partially rhyming words hendiadys: Use of two
nouns to express an idea when it normally would consist of an adjective and a
noun hendiatris: Use of three nouns to express one idea homeoptoton: ending the
last parts of words with the same syllable or letter. homographs: Words we
write identically but which have a differing meaning homoioteleuton: Multiple
words with the same ending homonyms: Words that are identical with each other
in pronunciation and spelling, but different in meaning homophones: Words that
are identical with each other in pronunciation, but different in meaning
homeoteleuton: Words with the same ending hypallage: A transferred epithet from
a conventional choice of wording.hyperbaton: Two ordinary associated words are
detached. The term may also be used more generally for all different figures of
speech which transpose natural word order in sentences.[13] hyperbole:
Exaggeration of a statement hypozeuxis: Every clause having its own independent
subject and predicate hysteron proteron: The inversion of the usual temporal or
causal order between two elements isocolon: Use of parallel structures of the
same length in successive clauses internal rhyme: Using two or more rhyming
words in the same sentence kenning: Using a compound word neologism to form a
metonym litotes derived from a Greek word meaning "simple", is a
figure of speech which employs an understatement by using double negatives or,
in other words, positive statement is expressed by negating its opposite
expressions. Examples: "not too bad" for "very good" is an
understatement as well as a double negative statement that confirms a positive
idea by negating the opposite. Similarly, saying "She is not a beauty
queen," means "She is ugly" or saying "I am not as young as
I used to be" in order to avoid saying "I am old". Litotes, therefore,
is an intentional use of understatement that renders an ironical effect.
merism: Referring to a whole by enumerating some of its parts mimesis:
Imitation of a person's speech or writing onomatopoeia: Word that imitates a
real sound (e.g. tick-tock or boom) paradiastole: Repetition of the disjunctive
pair "neither" and "nor" parallelism: The use of similar
structures in two or more clauses paraprosdokian: Unexpected ending or
truncation of a clause paremvolia: Interference of speak by speakingparenthesis:
A parenthetical entry paroemion: Alliteration in which every word in a sentence
or phrase begins with the same letter parrhesia: Speaking openly or boldly, in
a situation where it is unexpected (e.g. politics) pleonasm: The use of more
words than are needed to express meaning polyptoton: Repetition of words
derived from the same root polysyndeton: Close repetition of conjunctions pun:
When a word or phrase is used in two (or more) different senses rhythm: A
synonym for parallelism sibilance: Repetition of letter 's', it is a form of
consonance sine dicendo: An inherently superfluous statement, the truth value
of which can easily be taken for granted. When held under scrutiny, it becomes
readily apparent that the statement has not in fact added any new or useful
information to the conversation (e.g. 'It's always in the last place you
look.') solecism: Trespassing grammatical and syntactical rules spoonerism:
Switching place of syllables within two words in a sentence yielding amusement
superlative: Declaring something the best within its class i.e. the ugliest,
the most precious synathroesmus: Agglomeration of adjectives to describe
something or someone syncope: Omission of parts of a word or phrase symploce:
Simultaneous use of anaphora and epistrophe: the repetition of the same word or
group of words at the beginning and the end of successive clauses synchysis:
Words that are intentionally scattered to create perplexment synesis: Agreement
of words according to the sense, and not the grammatical form synecdoche:
Referring to a part by its whole or vice versa synonymia: Use of two or more
synonyms in the same clause or sentence tautology: Redundancy due to
superfluous qualification; saying the same thing twice tmesis: Insertions of
content within a compound word zeugma: The using of one verb for two or more
actions Tropes accismus: expressing the want of something by denying it[16]
allegory: A metaphoric narrative in which the literal elements indirectly
reveal a parallel story of symbolic or abstract significance.allusion: Covert
reference to another work of literature or art ambiguity: Phrasing which can
have two meanings anacoenosis: Posing a question to an audience, often with the
implication that it shares a common interest with the speaker analogy: A
comparison anapodoton: Leaving a common known saying unfinished antanaclasis: A
form of pun in which a word is repeated in two different senses.[20]
anthimeria: A substitution of one part of speech for another, such as noun for
a verb and vice versa.[21] anthropomorphism: Ascribing human characteristics to
something that is not human, such as an animal or a god (see zoomorphism)
antimetabole: Repetition of words in successive clauses, but in switched order
antiphrasis: A name or a phrase used ironically. antistasis: Repetition of a
word in a different sense. antonomasia: Substitution of a proper name for a
phrase or vice versa a: Briefly phrased, easily memorable statement of a truth
or opinion, an adage apologia: Justifying one's actions aporia: Faked or sincere
puzzled questioning apophasis: (Invoking) an idea by denying its (invocation)
appositive: Insertion of a parenthetical entry apostrophe: Directing the
attention away from the audience to an absent third party, often in the form of
a personified abstraction or inanimate object. archaism: Use of an obsolete,
archaic word (a word used in olden language, e.g. Shakespeare's language)
auxesis: Form of hyperbole, in which a more important-sounding word is used in
place of a more descriptive term bathos: Pompous speech with a ludicrously
mundane worded anti-climax burlesque metaphor: An amusing, overstated or
grotesque comparison or example. catachresis: Blatant misuse of words or
phrases. cataphora: Repetition of a cohesive device at the end categoria: Candidly
revealing an opponent's weakness cliché: Overused phrase or theme
circumlocution: Talking around a topic by substituting or adding words, as in
euphemism or periphrasis congeries: Accumulation of synonymous or different
words or phrases together forming a single message correctio: Linguistic device
used for correcting one's mistakes, a form of which is epanorthosis dehortatio:
discouraging advice given with seeming sagacity denominatio: Another word for
metonymy diatyposis: The act of giving counsel double negative: Grammar
construction that can be used as an expression and it is the repetition of
negative words dirimens copulatio: Balances one statement with a contrary,
qualifying statement[22] distinctio: Defining or specifying the meaning of a
word or phrase you use dysphemism: Substitution of a harsher, more offensive,
or more disagreeable term for another. Opposite of euphemism dubitatio:
Expressing doubt over one's ability to hold speeches, or doubt over other
ability ekphrasis: Lively describing something you see, often a painting
epanorthosis: Immediate and emphatic self-correction, often following a slip of
the tongue encomium: A speech consisting of praise; a eulogy enumeratio: A sort
of amplification and accumulation in which specific aspects are added up to
make a point epicrisis: Mentioning a saying and then commenting on it
epiplexis: Rhetorical question displaying disapproval or debunks epitrope:
Initially pretending to agree with an opposing debater or invite one to do
something erotema: Synonym for rhetorical question erotesis: Rhetorical
question asked in confident expectation of a negative answer euphemism:
Substitution of a less offensive or more agreeable term for another
grandiloquence: Pompous speech exclamation: A loud calling or crying out
humour: Provoking laughter and providing amusement hyperbaton: Words that
naturally belong together separated from each other for emphasis or effect
hyperbole: Use of exaggerated terms for emphasis hypocatastasis: An implication
or declaration of resemblance that does not directly name both terms hypophora:
Answering one's own rhetorical question at length hysteron proteron: Reversal
of anticipated order of events; a form of hyperbaton innuendo: Having a hidden
meaning in a sentence that makes sense whether it is detected or not inversion:
A reversal of normal word order, especially the placement of a verb ahead of
the subject (subject-verb inversion). irony: Use of word in a way that conveys
a meaning opposite to its usual meaning.[23] litotes: Emphasizing the magnitude
of a statement by denying its opposite malapropism: Using a word through
confusion with a word that sounds similar meiosis: Use of understatement,
usually to diminish the importance of something memento verbum: Word at the top
of the tongue, recordabantur merism: Referring to a whole by enumerating some
of its parts metalepsis: Figurative speech is used in a new context metaphor:
An implied comparison between two things, attributing the properties of one
thing to another that it does not literally possess.[24] metonymy: A thing or
concept is called not by its own name but rather by the name of something
associated in meaning with that thing or concept neologism: The use of a word
or term that has recently been created, or has been in use for a short time.
Opposite of archaism non sequitur: Statement that bears no relationship to the
context preceding occupatio see apophasis: Mentioning something by reportedly
not mentioning it onomatopoeia: Words that sound like their meaning oxymoron: Using
two terms together, that normally contradict each other par'hyponoian:
Replacing in a phrase or text a second part, that would have been logically
expected. parable: Extended metaphor told as an anecdote to illustrate or teach
a moral lesson paradiastole: Extenuating a vice in order to flatter or soothe
paradox: Use of apparently contradictory ideas to point out some underlying
truth paraprosdokian: Phrase in which the latter part causes a rethinking or
reframing of the beginning paralipsis: Drawing attention to something while
pretending to pass it over parody: Humouristic imitation paronomasia: Pun, in
which similar-sounding words but words having a different meaning are used
pathetic fallacy: Ascribing human conduct and feelings to nature periphrasis: A
synonym for circumlocution personification/prosopopoeia/anthropomorphism:
Attributing or applying human qualities to inanimate objects, animals, or
natural phenomena pleonasm: The use of more words than is necessary for clear
expression praeteritio: Another word for paralipsis procatalepsis: Refuting
anticipated objections as part of the main argument proslepsis: Extreme form of
paralipsis in which the speaker provides great detail while feigning to pass
over a topic prothesis: Adding a syllable to the beginning of a word proverb:
Succinct or pithy, often metaphorical, expression of wisdom commonly believed
to be true pun: Play on words that will have two meanings rhetorical question:
Asking a question as a way of asserting something. Asking a question which
already has the answer hidden in it. Or asking a question not for the sake of
getting an answer but for asserting something (or as in a poem for creating a
poetic effect) satire: Humoristic criticism of society sensory detail imagery:
sight, sound, taste, touch, smell sesquipedalianism: use of long and obscure
words simile: Comparison between two things using like or as snowclone:
Alteration of cliché or phrasal template style: how information is presented
superlative: Saying that something is the best of something or has the most of
some quality, e.g. the ugliest, the most precious etc. syllepsis: The use of a
word in its figurative and literal sense at the same time or a single word used
in relation to two other parts of a sentence although the word grammatically or
logically applies to only one syncatabasis (condescension, accommodation):
adaptation of style to the level of the audience synchoresis: A concession made
for the purpose of retorting with greater force. synecdoche: Form of metonymy,
referring to a part by its whole, or a whole by its part synesthesia:
Description of one kind of sense impression by using words that normally
describe another. tautology: Superfluous repetition of the same sense in
different words Example: The children gathered in a round circle transferred
epithet: A synonym for hypallage. truism: a self-evident statement tricolon
diminuens: Combination of three elements, each decreasing in size tricolon
crescens: Combination of three elements, each increasing in size verbal paradox:
Paradox specified to language verba ex ore: Taking the words out of someone’s
mouth, speaking of what the interlocutor wanted to say.[14] verbum volitans: A
word that floats in the air, on which everyone is thinking and is just about to
be imposed.[14] zeugma: Use of a single verb to describe two or more actions
zoomorphism: Applying animal characteristics to humans or gods. Refs.
Holdcroft: “Grice on indirect communication,” Journal of Rhetoric.”
Fallacia – Grice compilied a
“Fallaciae: A to Z.” Formal fallacies Main article: Formal fallacy A formal
fallacy is an error in logic that can be seen in the argument's form.[4] All
formal fallacies are specific types of non sequitur. Appeal to
probability – a statement that takes something for granted because it would
probably be the case (or might be the case).[5][6] Argument from fallacy (also
known as the fallacy fallacy) – the assumption that if an argument for some
conclusion is fallacious, then the conclusion is false.[7] Base rate fallacy –
making a probability judgment based on conditional probabilities, without
taking into account the effect of prior probabilities.[8] Conjunction fallacy –
the assumption that an outcome simultaneously satisfying multiple conditions is
more probable than an outcome satisfying a single one of them.[9] Masked-man
fallacy (illicit substitution of identicals) – the substitution of identical
designators in a true statement can lead to a false one.[10] Propositional
fallacies A propositional fallacy is an error in logic that concerns compound
propositions. For a compound proposition to be true, the truth values of its
constituent parts must satisfy the relevant logical connectives that occur in
it (most commonly: [and], [or], [not], [only if], [if and only if]). The following
fallacies involve inferences whose correctness is not guaranteed by the
behavior of those logical connectives and are not logically guaranteed to yield
true conclusions. Types of propositional fallacies: Affirming a disjunct
– concluding that one disjunct of a logical disjunction must be false because
the other disjunct is true; A or B; A, therefore not B.[11] Affirming the
consequent – the antecedent in an indicative conditional is claimed to be true
because the consequent is true; if A, then B; B, therefore A.[11] Denying the
antecedent – the consequent in an indicative conditional is claimed to be false
because the antecedent is false; if A, then B; not A, therefore not B.[11]
Quantification fallacies A quantification fallacy is an error in logic where
the quantifiers of the premises are in contradiction to the quantifier of the
conclusion. Types of quantification fallacies: Existential fallacy – an
argument that has a universal premise and a particular conclusion.[12] Formal
syllogistic fallacies Syllogistic fallacies – logical fallacies that occur in
syllogisms. Affirmative conclusion from a negative premise (illicit
negative) – a categorical syllogism has a positive conclusion, but at least one
negative premise.[12] Fallacy of exclusive premises – a categorical syllogism
that is invalid because both of its premises are negative.[12] Fallacy of four
terms (quaternio terminorum) – a categorical syllogism that has four terms.[13]
Illicit major – a categorical syllogism that is invalid because its major term
is not distributed in the major premise but distributed in the conclusion.[12]
Illicit minor – a categorical syllogism that is invalid because its minor term
is not distributed in the minor premise but distributed in the conclusion.[12]
Negative conclusion from affirmative premises (illicit affirmative) – a
categorical syllogism has a negative conclusion but affirmative premises.[12]
Fallacy of the undistributed middle – the middle term in a categorical
syllogism is not distributed.[14] Modal fallacy – confusing possibility with
necessity. Modal scope fallacy – a degree of unwarranted necessity is placed in
the conclusion. Informal fallacies Main article: Informal fallacy Informal
fallacies – arguments that are logically unsound for lack of well-grounded
premises.[15] Argument to moderation (false compromise, middle ground,
fallacy of the mean, argumentum ad temperantiam) – assuming that the compromise
between two positions is always correct.[16] Continuum fallacy (fallacy of the
beard, line-drawing fallacy, sorites fallacy, fallacy of the heap, bald man
fallacy) – improperly rejecting a claim for being imprecise.[17]
Correlative-based fallacies Suppressed correlative – a correlative is redefined
so that one alternative is made impossible (e.g., "I'm not fat because I'm
thinner than him").[18] Definist fallacy – defining a term used in an
argument in a biased manner. The person making the argument expects the
listener will accept the provided definition, making the argument difficult to
refute.[19] Divine fallacy (argument from incredulity) – arguing that, because
something is so incredible or amazing, it must be the result of superior,
divine, alien or paranormal agency.[20] Double counting – counting events or
occurrences more than once in probabilistic reasoning, which leads to the sum
of the probabilities of all cases exceeding unity. Equivocation – using a term
with more than one meaning in a statement without specifying which meaning is
intended.[21] Ambiguous middle term – using a middle term with multiple
meanings.[22] Definitional retreat – changing the meaning of a word when an
objection is raised.[1] Motte-and-bailey fallacy – conflating two positions
with similar properties, one modest and easy to defend (the "motte")
and one more controversial (the "bailey").[23] The arguer first
states the controversial position, but when challenged, states that they are
advancing the modest position.[24][25] Fallacy of accent – changing the meaning
of a statement by not specifying on which word emphasis falls. Persuasive
definition – purporting to use the "true" or "commonly
accepted" meaning of a term while, in reality, using an uncommon or
altered definition. (cf. the if-by-whiskey fallacy) Ecological fallacy –
inferences about the nature of specific individuals are based solely upon
aggregate statistics collected for the group to which those individuals
belong.[26] Etymological fallacy – reasoning that the original or historical
meaning of a word or phrase is necessarily similar to its actual present-day usage.[27]
Fallacy of composition – assuming that something true of part of a whole must
also be true of the whole.[28] Fallacy of division – assuming that something
true of a thing must also be true of all or some of its parts.[29] False
attribution – an advocate appeals to an irrelevant, unqualified, unidentified,
biased or fabricated source in support of an argument. Fallacy of quoting out
of context (contextotomy, contextomy; quotation mining) – refers to the
selective excerpting of words from their original context in a way that
distorts the source's intended meaning.[30] False authority (single authority)
– using an expert of dubious credentials or using only one opinion to sell a
product or idea. Related to the appeal to authority. False dilemma (false dichotomy,
fallacy of bifurcation, black-or-white fallacy) – two alternative statements
are held to be the only possible options when in reality there are more.[31]
False equivalence – describing two or more statements as virtually equal when
they are not. Feedback fallacy - believing in the objectivity of an evaluation
to be used as the basis for improvement without verifying that the source of
the evaluation is a disinterested party.[32] Historian's fallacy – assuming
that decision makers of the past had identical information as those
subsequently analyzing the decision.[33] This should not to be confused with
presentism, in which present-day ideas and perspectives are anachronistically
projected into the past. Historical fallacy – a set of considerations is
thought to hold good only because a completed process is read into the content
of the process which conditions this completed result.[34] Baconian fallacy -
using pieces of historical evidence without the aid of specific methods,
hypotheses, or theories in an attempt to make a general truth about the past.
Commits historians "to the pursuit of an impossible object by an
impracticable method".[35] Homunculus fallacy – using a
"middle-man" for explanation; this sometimes leads to regressive
middle-men. It explains a concept in terms of the concept itself without
explaining its real nature (e.g.: explaining thought as something produced by a
little thinker - a homunculus - inside the head simply identifies an
intermediary actor and does not explain the product or process of
thinking).[36] Inflation of conflict – arguing that, if experts in a field of
knowledge disagree on a certain point within that field, no conclusion can be
reached or that the legitimacy of that field of knowledge is questionable.[37]
If-by-whiskey – an argument that supports both sides of an issue by using terms
that are selectively emotionally sensitive. Incomplete comparison –
insufficient information is provided to make a complete comparison.
Inconsistent comparison – different methods of comparison are used, leaving a
false impression of the whole comparison. Intentionality fallacy – the
insistence that the ultimate meaning of an expression must be consistent with
the intention of the person from whom the communication originated (e.g. a work
of fiction that is widely received as a blatant allegory must necessarily not
be regarded as such if the author intended it not to be so.)[38] Lump of labour
fallacy – the misconception that there is a fixed amount of work to be done
within an economy, which can be distributed to create more or fewer jobs.[39]
Kettle logic – using multiple, jointly inconsistent arguments to defend a
position.[dubious – discuss] Ludic fallacy – the belief that the outcomes of
non-regulated random occurrences can be encapsulated by a statistic; a failure
to take into account that unknown unknowns have a role in determining the
probability of events taking place.[40] McNamara fallacy (quantitative fallacy)
– making a decision based only on quantitative observations, discounting all
other considerations. Mind projection fallacy – subjective judgments are
"projected" to be inherent properties of an object, rather than being
related to personal perceptions of that object. Moralistic fallacy – inferring
factual conclusions from purely evaluative premises in violation of fact–value
distinction. For instance, inferring is from ought is an instance of moralistic
fallacy. Moralistic fallacy is the inverse of naturalistic fallacy defined
below. Moving the goalposts (raising the bar) – argument in which evidence
presented in response to a specific claim is dismissed and some other (often
greater) evidence is demanded. Nirvana fallacy (perfect-solution fallacy) –
solutions to problems are rejected because they are not perfect. Proof by assertion
– a proposition is repeatedly restated regardless of contradiction; sometimes
confused with argument from repetition (argumentum ad infinitum, argumentum ad
nauseam) Prosecutor's fallacy – a low probability of false matches does not
mean a low probability of some false match being found. Proving too much – an
argument that results in an overly-generalized conclusion (e.g.: arguing that
drinking alcohol is bad because in some instances it has led to spousal or
child abuse). Psychologist's fallacy – an observer presupposes the objectivity
of their own perspective when analyzing a behavioral event. Referential
fallacy[41] – assuming all words refer to existing things and that the meaning
of words reside within the things they refer to, as opposed to words possibly
referring to no real object or that the meaning of words often comes from how
they are used. Reification (concretism, hypostatization, or the fallacy of
misplaced concreteness) – treating an abstract belief or hypothetical construct
as if it were a concrete, real event or physical entity (e.g.: saying that
evolution selects which traits are passed on to future generations; evolution
is not a conscious entity with agency). Retrospective determinism – the
argument that because an event has occurred under some circumstance, the
circumstance must have made its occurrence inevitable. Slippery slope (thin
edge of the wedge, camel's nose) – asserting that a proposed. relatively small,
first action will inevitably lead to a chain of related events resulting in a
significant and negative event and, therefore, should not be permitted.[42]
Special pleading – the arguer attempts to cite something as an exemption to a
generally accepted rule or principle without justifying the exemption (e.g.: a
defendant who murdered his parents asks for leniency because he is now an
orphan). Improper premise Begging the question (petitio principii) – using the
conclusion of the argument in support of itself in a premise (e.g.: saying that
smoking cigarettes is deadly because cigarettes can kill you; something that
kills is deadly).[43][44][45] Loaded label – while not inherently fallacious,
use of evocative terms to support a conclusion is a type of begging the
question fallacy. When fallaciously used, the term's connotations are relied on
to sway the argument towards a particular conclusion. For example, an organic
foods advertisement that says "Organic foods are safe and healthy foods
grown without any pesticides, herbicides, or other unhealthy additives."
Use of the term "unhealthy additives" is used as support for the idea
that the product is safe.[46] Circular reasoning (circulus in demonstrando) –
the reasoner begins with what he or she is trying to end up with (e.g.: all
bachelors are unmarried males). Fallacy of many questions (complex question,
fallacy of presuppositions, loaded question, plurium interrogationum) – someone
asks a question that presupposes something that has not been proven or accepted
by all the people involved. This fallacy is often used rhetorically so that the
question limits direct replies to those that serve the questioner's agenda.
Faulty generalizations Faulty generalization – reach a conclusion from weak
premises. Unlike fallacies of relevance, in fallacies of defective induction,
the premises are related to the conclusions yet only weakly support the
conclusions. A faulty generalization is thus produced. Accident – an
exception to a generalization is ignored.[47] No true Scotsman – makes a
generalization true by changing the generalization to exclude a
counterexample.[48] Cherry picking (suppressed evidence, incomplete evidence) –
act of pointing at individual cases or data that seem to confirm a particular
position, while ignoring a significant portion of related cases or data that
may contradict that position.[49] Survivorship bias – a small number of
successes of a given process are actively promoted while completely ignoring a
large number of failures False analogy – an argument by analogy in which the
analogy is poorly suited.[50] Hasty generalization (fallacy of insufficient
statistics, fallacy of insufficient sample, fallacy of the lonely fact, hasty
induction, secundum quid, converse accident, jumping to conclusions) – basing a
broad conclusion on a small sample or the making of a determination without all
of the information required to do so.[51] Inductive fallacy – A more general
name to some fallacies, such as hasty generalization. It happens when a
conclusion is made of premises that lightly support it. Misleading vividness –
involves describing an occurrence in vivid detail, even if it is an exceptional
occurrence, to convince someone that it is a problem; this also relies on the
appeal to emotion fallacy. Overwhelming exception – an accurate generalization
that comes with qualifications that eliminate so many cases that what remains
is much less impressive than the initial statement might have led one to
assume.[52] Thought-terminating cliché – a commonly used phrase, sometimes
passing as folk wisdom, used to quell cognitive dissonance, conceal lack of
forethought, move on to other topics, etc. – but in any case, to end the debate
with a cliché rather than a point. Questionable cause Questionable cause is a
general type of error with many variants. Its primary basis is the confusion of
association with causation, either by inappropriately deducing (or rejecting)
causation or a broader failure to properly investigate the cause of an observed
effect. Cum hoc ergo propter hoc (Latin for "with this, therefore
because of this"; correlation implies causation; faulty cause/effect,
coincidental correlation, correlation without causation) – a faulty assumption
that, because there is a correlation between two variables, one caused the
other.[53] Post hoc ergo propter hoc (Latin for "after this, therefore
because of this"; temporal sequence implies causation) – X happened, then
Y happened; therefore X caused Y.[54] Wrong direction (reverse causation) –
cause and effect are reversed. The cause is said to be the effect and vice
versa.[55] The consequence of the phenomenon is claimed to be its root cause.
Ignoring a common cause Fallacy of the single cause (causal
oversimplification[56]) – it is assumed that there is one, simple cause of an
outcome when in reality it may have been caused by a number of only jointly
sufficient causes. Furtive fallacy – outcomes are asserted to have been caused
by the malfeasance of decision makers. Gambler's fallacy – the incorrect belief
that separate, independent events can affect the likelihood of another random
event. If a fair coin lands on heads 10 times in a row, the belief that it is
"due to the number of times it had previously landed on tails" is
incorrect.[57] Inverse gambler's fallacy Magical thinking – fallacious
attribution of causal relationships between actions and events. In
anthropology, it refers primarily to cultural beliefs that ritual, prayer,
sacrifice, and taboos will produce specific supernatural consequences. In
psychology, it refers to an irrational belief that thoughts by themselves can
affect the world or that thinking something corresponds with doing it.
Regression fallacy – ascribes cause where none exists. The flaw is failing to
account for natural fluctuations. It is frequently a special kind of post hoc
fallacy. Relevance fallacies Appeal to the stone (argumentum ad lapidem) –
dismissing a claim as absurd without demonstrating proof for its absurdity.[58]
Argument from ignorance (appeal to ignorance, argumentum ad ignorantiam) –
assuming that a claim is true because it has not been or cannot be proven
false, or vice versa.[59] Argument from incredulity (appeal to common sense) –
"I cannot imagine how this could be true; therefore, it must be
false."[60] Argument from repetition (argumentum ad nauseam, argumentum ad
infinitum) – repeating an argument until nobody cares to discuss it any
more;[61][62] sometimes confused with proof by assertion Argument from silence
(argumentum ex silentio) – assuming that a claim is true based on the absence
of textual or spoken evidence from an authoritative source, or vice versa.[63]
Ignoratio elenchi (irrelevant conclusion, missing the point) – an argument that
may in itself be valid, but does not address the issue in question.[64] Red
herring fallacies A red herring fallacy, one of the main subtypes of fallacies
of relevance, is an error in logic where a proposition is, or is intended to
be, misleading in order to make irrelevant or false inferences. In the general
case any logical inference based on fake arguments, intended to replace the
lack of real arguments or to replace implicitly the subject of the
discussion.[65][66] Red herring – introducing a second argument in
response to the first argument that is irrelevant and draws attention away from
the original topic (e.g.: saying “If you want to complain about the dishes I
leave in the sink, what about the dirty clothes you leave in the
bathroom?”).[67] See also irrelevant conclusion. Ad hominem – attacking
the arguer instead of the argument. (N.b., "ad hominem" can also
refer to the dialectical strategy of arguing on the basis of the opponent's own
commitments. This type of ad hominem is not a fallacy.) Circumstantial ad
hominem - stating that the arguer's personal situation or perceived benefit
from advancing a conclusion means that their conclusion is wrong.[68] Poisoning
the well – a subtype of ad hominem presenting adverse information about a
target person with the intention of discrediting everything that the target
person says.[69] Appeal to motive – dismissing an idea by questioning the
motives of its proposer. Kafka-trapping – a sophistical and unfalsifiable form
of argument that attempts to overcome an opponent by inducing a sense of guilt
and using the opponent's denial of guilt as further evidence of guilt.[70] Tone
policing – focusing on emotion behind (or resulting from) a message rather than
the message itself as a discrediting tactic. Traitorous critic fallacy (ergo
decedo, 'thus leave') – a critic's perceived affiliation is portrayed as the
underlying reason for the criticism and the critic is asked to stay away from
the issue altogether. Easily confused with the association fallacy ("guilt
by association") below. Appeal to authority (argument from authority,
argumentum ad verecundiam) – an assertion is deemed true because of the position
or authority of the person asserting it.[71][72] Appeal to accomplishment – an
assertion is deemed true or false based on the accomplishments of the proposer.
This may often also have elements of appeal to emotion (see below). Courtier's
reply – a criticism is dismissed by claiming that the critic lacks sufficient
knowledge, credentials, or training to credibly comment on the subject matter.
Appeal to consequences (argumentum ad consequentiam) – the conclusion is
supported by a premise that asserts positive or negative consequences from some
course of action in an attempt to distract from the initial discussion.[73]
Appeal to emotion – an argument is made due to the manipulation of emotions,
rather than the use of valid reasoning.[74] Appeal to fear – an argument is made
by increasing fear and prejudice towards the opposing side[75] Appeal to
flattery – an argument is made due to the use of flattery to gather
support.[76] Appeal to pity (argumentum ad misericordiam) – an argument
attempts to induce pity to sway opponents.[77] Appeal to ridicule – an argument
is made by presenting the opponent's argument in a way that makes it appear
ridiculous (or, arguing or implying that because it is ridiculous it must be
untrue).[78] Appeal to spite – an argument is made through exploiting people's
bitterness or spite towards an opposing party.[79] Judgmental language –
insulting or pejorative language to influence the audience's judgment.
Pooh-pooh – dismissing an argument perceived unworthy of serious
consideration.[80] Wishful thinking – a decision is made according to what
might be pleasing to imagine, rather than according to evidence or reason.[81]
Appeal to nature – judgment is based solely on whether the subject of judgment
is 'natural' or 'unnatural'.[82] (Sometimes also called the "naturalistic
fallacy", but is not to be confused with the other fallacies by that
name.) Appeal to novelty (argumentum novitatis, argumentum ad antiquitatis) – a
proposal is claimed to be superior or better solely because it is new or modern.[83]
Appeal to poverty (argumentum ad Lazarum) – supporting a conclusion because the
arguer is poor (or refuting because the arguer is wealthy). (Opposite of appeal
to wealth.)[84] Appeal to tradition (argumentum ad antiquitatem) – a conclusion
supported solely because it has long been held to be true.[85] Appeal to wealth
(argumentum ad crumenam) – supporting a conclusion because the arguer is
wealthy (or refuting because the arguer is poor).[86] (Sometimes taken together
with the appeal to poverty as a general appeal to the arguer's financial
situation.) Argumentum ad baculum (appeal to the stick, appeal to force, appeal
to threat) – an argument made through coercion or threats of force to support
position.[87] Argumentum ad populum (appeal to widespread belief, bandwagon
argument, appeal to the majority, appeal to the people) – a proposition is
claimed to be true or good solely because a majority or many people believe it
to be so.[88] Association fallacy (guilt by association and honor by
association) – arguing that because two things share (or are implied to share)
some property, they are the same.[89] Ipse dixit (bare assertion fallacy) – a
claim that is presented as true without support, as self-evidently true, or as
dogmatically true. This fallacy relies on the implied expertise of the speaker
or on an unstated truism.[90][91] Bulverism (psychogenetic fallacy) – inferring
why an argument is being used, associating it to some psychological reason,
then assuming it is invalid as a result. The assumption that if the origin of
an idea comes from a biased mind, then the idea itself must also be a
falsehood.[37] Chronological snobbery – a thesis is deemed incorrect because it
was commonly held when something else, known to be false, was also commonly
held.[92][93] Fallacy of relative privation (also known as "appeal to
worse problems" or "not as bad as") – dismissing an argument or
complaint due to what are perceived to be more important problems. First World
problems are a subset of this fallacy.[94][95] Genetic fallacy – a conclusion
is suggested based solely on something or someone's origin rather than its
current meaning or context.[96] I'm entitled to my opinion – a person
discredits any opposition by claiming that they are entitled to their opinion.
Moralistic fallacy – inferring factual conclusions from evaluative premises, in
violation of fact-value distinction; e.g. making statements about what is, on
the basis of claims about what ought to be. This is the inverse of the
naturalistic fallacy. Naturalistic fallacy – inferring evaluative conclusions
from purely factual premises[97][98] in violation of fact-value distinction.
Naturalistic fallacy (sometimes confused with appeal to nature) is the inverse
of moralistic fallacy. Is–ought fallacy[99] – statements about what is, on the
basis of claims about what ought to be. Naturalistic fallacy fallacy[100]
(anti-naturalistic fallacy)[101] – inferring an impossibility to infer any
instance of ought from is from the general invalidity of is-ought fallacy,
mentioned above. For instance, is {\displaystyle P\lor \neg P}P \lor \neg P
does imply ought {\displaystyle P\lor \neg P}P \lor \neg P for any proposition
{\displaystyle P}P, although the naturalistic fallacy fallacy would falsely
declare such an inference invalid. Naturalistic fallacy fallacy is a type of
argument from fallacy. Straw man fallacy – misrepresenting an opponent's
argument by broadening or narrowing the scope of a premise and refuting a
weaker version (e.g.: saying “You tell us that A is the right thing to do, but
the real reason you want us to do A is that you would personally profit from
it).[102] Texas sharpshooter fallacy – improperly asserting a cause to explain
a cluster of data.[103] Tu quoque ('you too' – appeal to hypocrisy,
whataboutism) – the argument states that a certain position is false or wrong
or should be disregarded because its proponent fails to act consistently in
accordance with that position.[104] Two wrongs make a right – occurs when it is
assumed that if one wrong is committed, another wrong will rectify it.[105]
Vacuous truth – a claim that is technically true but meaningless, in the form
of claiming that no A in B has C, when there is no A in B. For example,
claiming that no mobile phones in the room are on when there are no mobile phones
in the room at all.
metaphorical implicaturum -- Grice,
“You’re the cream in my coffee” – “You’re the salt in my stew” – “You’re the
starch in my collar” – “You’re the lace in my shoe.” metaphor, a figure of
speech (or a trope) in which a word or phrase that literally denotes one thing
is used to denote another, thereby implicitly comparing the two things. In the
normal use of the sentence ‘The Mississippi is a river’, ‘river’ is used
literally – or as some would prefer to say, used in its literal sense. By
contrast, if one assertively uttered “Time is a river,” one would be using
‘river’ metaphorically – or be using it in a metaphorical sense. Metaphor has
been a topic of philosophical discussion since Aristotle; in fact, it has
almost certainly been more discussed by philosophers than all the other tropes
together. Two themes are prominent in the discussions up to the nineteenth
century. One is that metaphors, along with all the other tropes, are
decorations of speech; hence the phrase ‘figures of speech’. Metaphors are
adornments or figurations. They do not contribute to the cognitive meaning of
the discourse; instead they lend it color, vividness, emotional impact, etc.
Thus it was characteristic of the Enlightenment and proto-Enlightenment philosophers
– Hobbes and Locke are good examples – to insist that though philosophers may
sometimes have good reason to communicate their thought with metaphors, they
themselves should do their thinking entirely without metaphors. The other theme
prominent in discussions of metaphor up to the nineteenth century is that
metaphors are, so far as their cognitive force is concerned, elliptical
similes. The cognitive force of ‘Time is a river’, when ‘river’ in that
sentence is used metaphorically, is the same as ‘Time is like a river’. What
characterizes almost all theories of metaphor from the time of the Romantics up
through our own century is the rejection of both these traditional themes.
Metaphors – so it has been argued – are not cognitively dispensable decorations.
They contribute to the cognitive meaning of our discourse; and they are
indispensable, not only to religious discourse, but to ordinary, and even
scientific, discourse, not to mention poetic. Nietzsche, indeed, went so far as
to argue that all speech is metaphorical. And though no consensus has yet
emerged on how and what metaphors contribute to meaning, nor how we recognize
what they contribute, nearconsensus has emerged on the thesis that they do not
work as elliptical similes. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Why it is not the case that
you’re the cream in my coffee.” H. P. Grice, “One figure of rhetoric too many.”
“Metanonymy.”
Ariskant
-- Aristkantian metaphysical deduction: cf. the transcendental club. or
argument. transcendental argument Metaphysics,
epistemology An argument that starts from some accepted experience or fact to
prove that there must be something which is beyond experience but which is a
necessary condition for making the accepted experience or fact possible. The
goal of a transcendental argument is to establish the transcendental dialectic truth of this precondition.
If there is something X of which Y is a necessary condition, then Y must be
true. This form of argument became prominent in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason,
where he argued that the existence of some fundamental a priori concepts,
namely the categories, and of space and time as pure forms of sensibility, are
necessary to make experience possible. In contemporary philosophy,
transcendental arguments are widely proposed as a way of refuting skepticism.
Wittgenstein used this form of argument to reject the possibility of a private
language that only the speaker could understand. Peter Strawson employs a
transcendental argument to prove the perception-independent existence of
material particulars and to reject a skeptical attitude toward the existence of
other minds. There is disagreement about the kind of necessity involved in
transcendental arguments, and Barry Stroud has raised important questions about
the possibility of transcendental arguments succeeding. “A transcendental
argument attempts to prove q by proving it is part of any correct explanation
of p, by proving it a precondition of p’s possibility.” Nozick Philosophical
Explanations transcendental deduction Metaphysics, epistemology, ethics,
aesthetics For Kant, the argument to prove that certain a priori concepts are
legitimately, universally, necessarily, and exclusively applicable to objects
of experience. Kant employed this form of argument to establish the legitimacy
of space and time as the forms of intuition, of the claims of the moral law in
the Critique of Practical Reason, and of the claims of the aesthetic judgment
of taste in the Critique of Judgement. However, the most influential example of
this form of argument appeared in the Critique of Pure Reason as the
transcendental deduction of the categories. The metaphysical deduction set out
the origin and character of the categories, and the task of the transcendental
deduction was to demonstrate that these a priori concepts do apply to objects
of experience and hence to prove the objective validity of the categories. The
strategy of the proof is to show that objects can be thought of only by means
of the categories. In sensibility, objects are subject to the forms of space
and time. In understanding, experienced
objects must stand under the conditions of the transcendental unity of
apperception. Because these conditions require the determination of objects by
the pure concepts of the understanding, there can be no experience that is not
subject to the categories. The categories, therefore, are justified in their
application to appearances as conditions of the possibility of experience. In
the second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason (1787), Kant extensively
rewrote the transcendental deduction, although he held that the result remained
the same. The first version emphasized the subjective unity of consciousness,
while the second version stressed the objective character of the unity, and it
is therefore possible to distinguish between a subjective and objective
deduction. The second version was meant to clarify the argument, but remained
extremely difficult to interpret and assess. The presence of the two versions
of this fundamental argument makes interpretation even more demanding.
Generally speaking, European philosophers prefer the subjective version, while
Anglo-American philosophers prefer the objective version. The transcendental
deduction of the categories was a revolutionary development in modern
philosophy. It was the main device by which Kant sought to overcome the errors
and limitations of both rationalism and empiricism and propelled philosophy
into a new phase. “The explanation of the manner in which concepts can thus
relate a priori to objects I entitle their transcendental deduction.” Kant,
Critique of Pure Reason. metaphysical realism, in the widest sense, the view
that (a) there are real objects (usually the view is concerned with
spatiotemporal objects), (b) they exist independently of our experience or our
knowledge of them, and (c) they have properties and enter into relations
independently of the concepts with which we understand them or of the language
with which we describe them. Anti-realism is any view that rejects one or more
of these three theses, though if (a) is rejected the rejection of (b) and (c)
follows trivially. (If it merely denies the existence of material things, then
its traditional name is ‘idealism.’) Metaphysical realism, in all of its three parts,
is shared by common sense, the sciences, and most philosophers. The chief
objection to it is that we can form no conception of real objects, as
understood by it, since any such conception must rest on the concepts we
already have and on our language and experience. To accept the objection seems
to imply that we can have no knowledge of real objects as they are in
themselves, and that truth must not be understood as correspondence to such
objects. But this itself has an even farther reaching consequence: either (i)
we should accept the seemingly absurd view that there are no real objects
(since the objection equally well applies to minds and their states, to
concepts and words, to properties and relations, to experiences, etc.), for we
should hardly believe in the reality of something of which we can form no
conception at all; or (ii) we must face the seemingly hopeless task of a
drastic change in what we mean by ‘reality’, ‘concept’, ‘experience’,
‘knowledge’, ‘truth’, and much else. On the other hand, the objection may be
held to reduce to a mere tautology, amounting to ‘We (can) know reality only as
we (can) know it’, and then it may be argued that no substantive thesis, which
anti-realism claims to be, is derivable from a mere tautology. Yet even if the
objection is a tautology, it serves to force us to avoid a simplistic view of
our cognitive relationship to the world. In discussions of universals,
metaphysical realism is the view that there are universals, and usually is
contrasted with nominalism. But this either precludes a standard third
alternative, namely conceptualism, or simply presupposes that concepts are
general words (adjectives, common nouns, verbs) or uses of such words. If this
presupposition is accepted, then indeed conceptualism would be the same as
nominalism, but this should be argued, not legislated verbally. Traditional
conceptualism holds that concepts are particular mental entities, or at least
mental dispositions, that serve the classificatory function that universals
have been supposed to serve and also explain the classificatory function that
general words undoubtedly also serve. -- metaphysics, most generally, the
philosophical investigation of the nature, constitution, and structure of
reality. It is broader in scope than science, e.g., physics and even cosmology
(the science of the nature, structure, and origin of the universe as a whole),
since one of its traditional concerns is the existence of non-physical
entities, e.g., God. It is also more fundamental, since it investigates
questions science does not address but the answers to which it presupposes. Are
there, for instance, physical objects at all, and does every event have a
cause? So understood, metaphysics was rejected by positivism on the ground that
its statements are “cognitively meaningless” since they are not empirically
verifiable. More recent philosophers, such as Quine, reject metaphysics on the
ground that science alone provides genuine knowledge. In The Metaphysics of
Logical Positivism (1954), Bergmann argued that logical positivism, and any
view such as Quine’s, presupposes a metaphysical theory. And the positivists’
criterion of cognitive meaning was never formulated in a way satisfactory even
to them. A successor of the positivist attitude toward metaphysics is Grice’s
tutee at St. John’s – for his Logic Paper for the PPE -- P. F. Strawson’s
preference (especially in Individuals: an essay in descriptive metaphysics) for
what he calls descriptive metaphysics, which is “content to describe the actual
structure of our thought about the world,” as contrasted with revisionary
metaphysics, which is “concerned to produce a better structure.” The view,
sometimes considered scientific (but an assumption rather than an argued
theory), that all that there is, is spatiotemporal (a part of “nature”) and is
knowable only through the methods of the sciences, is itself a metaphysics,
namely metaphysical naturalism (not to be confused with natural philosophy). It
is not part of science itself. In its most general sense, metaphysics may seem
to coincide with philosophy as a whole, since anything philosophy investigates
is presumably a part of reality, e.g., knowledge, values, and valid reasoning.
But it is useful to reserve the investigation of such more specific topics for
distinct branches of philosophy, e.g., epistemology, ethics, aesthetics, and
logic, since they raise problems peculiar to themselves. Perhaps the most
familiar question in metaphysics is whether there are only material entities –
materialism – or only mental entities, i.e., minds and their states – idealism
– or both – dualism. Here ‘entity’ has its broadest sense: anything real. More
specific questions of metaphysics concern the existence and nature of certain
individuals – also called particulars – (e.g., God), or certain properties
(e.g., are there properties that nothing exemplifies?) or relations (e.g., is
there a relation of causation that is a necessary connection rather than a mere
regular conjunction between events?). The nature of space and time is another
important example of such a more specific topic. Are space and time peculiar
individuals that “contain” ordinary individuals, or are they just systems of
relations between individual things, such as being (spatially) higher or
(temporally) prior. Whatever the answer, space and time are what render a world
out of the totality of entities that are parts of it. Since on any account of
knowledge, our knowledge of the world is extremely limited, concerning both its
spatial and temporal dimensions and its inner constitution, we must allow for
an indefinite number of possible ways the world may be, might have been, or
will be. And this thought gives rise to the idea of an indefinite number of
possible worlds. This idea is useful in making vivid our understanding of the
nature of necessary truth (a necessarily true proposition is one that is true
in all possible worlds) and thus is commonly employed in modal logic. But the
idea can also make possible worlds seem real, a highly controversial doctrine.
The notion of a spatiotemporal world is commonly that employed in discussions
of the socalled issue of realism versus anti-realism, although this issue has
also been raised with respect to universals, values, and numbers, which are not
usually considered spatiotemporal. While there is no clear sense in asserting
that nothing is real, there seems to be a clear sense in asserting that there
is no spatiotemporal world, especially if it is added that there are minds and
their ideas. This was Berkeley’s view. But contemporary philosophers who raise
questions about the reality of the spatiotemporal world are not comfortable
with Berkeleyan minds and ideas and usually just somewhat vaguely speak of
“ourselves” and our “representations.” The latter are themselves often understood
as material (states of our brains), a clearly inconsistent position for anyone
denying the reality of the spatiotemporal world. Usually, the contemporary
anti-realist does not actually deny it but rather adopts a view resembling
Kant’s transcendental idealism. Our only conception of the world, the
anti-realist would argue, rests on our perceptual and conceptual faculties,
including our language. But then what reason do we have to think that this
conception is true, that it corresponds to the world as the world is in itself?
Had our faculties and language been different, surely we would have had very
different conceptions of the world. And very different conceptions of it are
possible even in terms of our present faculties, as seems to be shown by the fact
that very different scientific theories can be supported by exactly the same
data. So far, we do not have anti-realism proper. But it is only a short step
to it: if our conception of an independent spatiotemporal world is necessarily
subjective, then we have no good reason for supposing that there is such a
world, especially since it seems selfcontradictory to speak of a conception
that is independent of our conceptual faculties. It is clear that this
question, like almost all the questions of general metaphysics, is at least in
part epistemological. Metaphysics can also be understood in a more definite
sense, suggested by Aristotle’s notion (in his Metaphysics, the title of which
was given by an early editor of his works, not by Aristotle himself) of “first
philosophy,” namely, the study of being qua being, i.e., of the most general
and necessary characteristics that anything must have in order to count as a
being, an entity (ens). Sometimes ‘ontology’ is used in this sense, but this is
by no means common practice, ‘ontology’ being often used as a synonym of
‘metaphysics’. Examples of criteria (each of which is a major topic in
metaphysics) that anything must meet in order to count as a being, an entity,
are the following. (A) Every entity must be either an individual thing (e.g.,
Socrates and this book), or a property (e.g., Socrates’ color and the shape of
this book), or a relation (e.g., marriage and the distance between two cities),
or an event (e.g., Socrates’ death), or a state of affairs (e.g., Socrates’
having died), or a set (e.g., the set of Greek philosophers). These kinds of
entities are usually called categories, and metaphysics is very much concerned
with the question whether these are the only categories, or whether there are
others, or whether some of them are not ultimate because they are reducible to
others (e.g., events to states of affairs, or individual things to temporal
series of events). (B) The existence, or being, of a thing is what makes it an
entity. (C) Whatever has identity and is distinct from everything else is an
entity. (D) The nature of the “connection” between an entity and its properties
and relations is what makes it an entity. Every entity must have properties and
perhaps must enter into relations with at least some other entities. (E) Every
entity must be logically self-consistent. It is noteworthy that after
announcing his project of first philosophy, Aristotle immediately embarked on a
defense of the law of non-contradiction. Concerning (A) we may ask (i) whether
at least some individual things (particulars) are substances, in the
Aristotelian sense, i.e., enduring through time and changes in their properties
and relations, or whether all individual things are momentary. In that case,
the individuals of common sense (e.g., this book) are really temporal series of
momentary individuals, perhaps events such as the book’s being on a table at a
specific instant. We may also ask (ii) whether any entity has essential
properties, i.e., properties without which it would not exist, or whether all
properties are accidental, in the sense that the entity could exist even if it
lost the property in question. We may ask (iii) whether properties and
relations are particulars or universals, e.g., whether the color of this page
and the color of the next page, which (let us assume) are exactly alike, are
two distinct entities, each with its separate spatial location, or whether they
are identical and thus one entity that is exemplified by, perhaps even located
in, the two pages. Concerning (B), we may ask whether existence is itself a
property. If it is, how is it to be understood, and if it is not, how are we to
understand ‘x exists’ and ‘x does not exist’, which seem crucial to everyday
and scientific discourse, just as the thoughts they express seem crucial to
everyday and scientific thinking? Should we countenance, as Meinong did,
objects having no existence, e.g. golden mountains, even though we can talk and
think about them? We can talk and think about a golden mountain and even claim
that it is true that the mountain is golden, while knowing all along that what
we are thinking and talking about does not exist. If we do not construe
non-existent objects as something, then we are committed to the somewhat
startling view that everything exists. Concerning (C) we may ask how to
construe informative identity statements, such as, to use Frege’s example, ‘The
Evening Star is identical with the Morning Star’. This contrasts with trivial
and perhaps degenerate statements, such as ‘The Evening Star is identical with
the Evening Star’, which are almost never made in ordinary or scientific
discourse. The former are essential to any coherent, systematic cognition (even
to everyday recognition of persons and places). Yet they are puzzling. We
cannot say that they assert of two things that they are one, even though
ordinary language suggests precisely this. Neither can we just say that they
assert that a certain thing is identical with itself, for this view would be
obviously false if the statements are informative. The fact that Frege’s
example includes definite descriptions (‘the Evening Star’, ‘the Morning Star’)
is irrelevant, contrary to Russell’s view. Informative identity statements can
also have as their subject terms proper names and even demonstrative pronouns
(e.g., ‘Hesperus is identical with Phosphorus’ and ‘This [the shape of this
page] is identical with that [the shape of the next page]’), the reference of
which is established not by description but ostensively, perhaps by actual
pointing. Concerning (D) we can ask about the nature of the relationship,
usually called instantiation or exemplification, between an entity and its
properties and relations. Surely, there is such a relationship. But it can
hardly be like an ordinary relation such as marriage that connects things of
the same kind. And we can ask what is the connection between that relation and
the entities it relates, e.g., the individual thing on one hand and its
properties and relations on the other. Raising this question seems to lead to
an infinite regress, as Bradley held; for the supposed connection is yet
another relation to be connected with something else. But how do we avoid the
regress? Surely, an individual thing and its properties and relations are not
unrelated items. They have a certain unity. But what is its character?
Moreover, we can hardly identify the individual thing except by reference to
its properties and relations. Yet if we say, as some have, that it is nothing
but a bundle of its properties and relations, could there not be another bundle
of exactly the same properties and relations, yet distinct from the first one?
(This question concerns the so-called problem of individuation, as well as the
principle of the identity of indiscernibles.) If an individual is something
other than its properties and relations (e.g., what has been called a bare
particular), it would seem to be unobservable and thus perhaps unknowable.
Concerning (E), virtually no philosopher has questioned the law of
non-contradiction. But there are important questions about its status. Is it
merely a linguistic convention? Some have held this, but it seems quite
implausible. Is the law of non-contradiction a deep truth about being qua
being? If it is, (E) connects closely with (B) and (C), for we can think of the
concepts of self-consistency, identity, and existence as the most fundamental
metaphysical concepts. They are also fundamental to logic, but logic, even if
ultimately grounded in metaphysics, has a rich additional subject matter
(sometimes merging with that of mathematics) and therefore is properly regarded
as a separate branch of philosophy. The word ‘metaphysics’ has also been used
in at least two other senses: first, the investigation of entities and states
of affairs “transcending” human experience, in particular, the existence of
God, the immortality of the soul, and the freedom of the will (this was Kant’s
conception of the sort of metaphysics that, according to him, required
“critique”); and second, the investigation of any alleged supernatural or
occult phenomena, such as ghosts and telekinesis. The first sense is properly
philosophical, though seldom occurring today. The second is strictly popular,
since the relevant supernatural phenomena are most questionable on both
philosophical and scientific grounds. They should not be confused with the
subject matter of philosophical theology, which may be thought of as part of
metaphysics in the general philosophical sense, though it was included by
Aristotle in the subject matter of metaphysics in his sense of the study of
being qua being. Refs.: H. P. Grice and P. F. Strawson, “Seminars on
Aristotle’s Categoriae,” Oxford.
metaphysical wisdom: J. London-born philosopher, cited by H. P. Grice in his
third programme lecture on Metaphysics. “Wisdom used to say that metaphysics is
nonsense, but INTERESTING nonsense.” Some more “contemporary” accounts of
“metaphysics” sound, on the face of it at least, very different from either of
these. Consider, for example, from the
OTHER place, John Wisdom's description of a metaphysical, shall we say,
‘statement’ – I prefer ‘utterance’ or pronouncement! Wisdom says that a metaphysical, shall we
say, ‘proposition’ is, characteristically, a sort of illuminating falsehood, a
pointed paradox, which uses what Wisdom calls ‘ordinary language’ in a
disturbing, baffling, and even shocking way, but not otiosely, but in order to
make your tutee aware of a hidden difference or a hidden resemblance between
this thing and that thing – a difference and a resemblance hidden by our
ordinary ways of “talking.” The
metaphysician renders what is clear, obscure.
And the metaphysician MUST retort to some EXTRA-ordinary language, as
Wisdom calls it! Of course, to be fair
to Wisdom and the OTHER place, Wisdom does not claim this to be a complete
characterisation, nor perhaps a literally correct one. Since Wisdom loves a figure of speech and a
figure of thought! Perhaps what Wisdom
claims should *itself* be seen as an illuminating paradox, a meta-meta-physical
one! In any case, its relation to
Aristotle's, or, closer to us, F. H. Bradley's, account of the matter is not
obvious, is it? But perhaps a relation
CAN be established. Certainly not every
metaphysical statement is a paradox serving to call attention to an usually
unnoticed difference or resemblance.
For many a metaphysical statement is so obscure (or unperspicuous, as I
prefer) that it takes long training, usually at Oxford, before the
metaphysician’s meaning can be grasped.
A paradox, such as Socrates’s, must operate with this or that familiar
concept. For the essence of a paradox is
that it administers a shock, and you cannot shock your tutee when he is standing
on such unfamiliar ground that he has no particular expectations. Nevertheless there IS a connection between
“metaphysics” and Wisdom's kind of paradox.
He is not speaking otiosely!
Suppose we consider the paradox:
i. Everyone is really always alone.
Considered by itself, it is no more than an epigram -- rather a flat
one - about the human condition. The implicaturum, via hyperbole, is “I am
being witty.” The pronouncement (i) might be said, at least, to minimise the
difference between “being BY oneself” and “being WITH other people,”
Heidegger’s “Mit-Sein.” But now consider
the pronouncement (i), not simply by itself, but surrounded and supported by a
certain kind of “metaphysical” argument: by a “metaphysical” argument to the
effect that what passes for “knowledge” of the other's mental or psychological
process is, at best, an unverifiable conjecture, since the mind (or soul) and
the body are totally distinct things, and the working of the mind (or soul, as
Aristotle would prefer, ‘psyche’) is always withdrawn behind the screen of its
bodily manifestations, as Witters would have it. (Not in vain Wisdom calls
himself or hisself a disciple of Witters!)
When this solitude-affirming paradox, (i) is seen in the context of a
general theory about the soul and the body and the possibilities and limits of
so-called “knowledge” (as in “Knowledge of other minds,” to use Wisdom’s
fashionable sobriquet), when it is seen as embodying such a “metaphysical”
theory, indeed the paradox BECOMES clearly a “metaphysical” statement. But the fact that the statement or
proposition is most clearly seen as “metaphysical” in such a setting does not
mean that there is no “metaphysics” at all in it when it is deprived of the
setting. (Cf. my “The general theory of context.”). An utterance like (ii) Everyone is alone. invites us to change, for a moment at least
and in one respect, our ordinary way of looking at and talking about things,
and hints (or the metaphysician implicates rather) that the changed view the
tutee gets is the truer, the profounder, view.
Cf. Cook Wilson, “What we know we know,” as delighting this air marshal.
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Metaphysics,” in D. F. Pears, “The nature of metaphysics:
the Third-Programme Lectures for 1953.”
Totum -- Holos – holism -- Methodus -- methodological
holism, also called metaphysical holism, the thesis that with respect to some
system there is explanatory emergence, i.e., the laws of the more complex
situations in the system are not deducible by way of any composition laws or
laws of coexistence from the laws of the simpler or simplest situation(s).
Explanatory emergence may exist in a system for any of the following reasons:
that at some more complex level a variable interacts that does not do so at
simpler levels, that a property of the “whole” interacts with properties of the
“parts,” that the relevant variables interact by different laws at more complex
levels owing to the complexity of the levels, or (the limiting case) that
strict lawfulness breaks down at some more complex level. Thus, explanatory
emergence does not presuppose descriptive emergence, the thesis that there are
properties of “wholes” (or more complex situations) that cannot be defined
through the properties of the “parts” (or simpler situations). The opposite of
methodological holism is methodological individualism, also called explanatory
reductionism, according to which all laws of the “whole” (or more complex
situations) can be deduced from a combination of the laws of the simpler or
simplest situation(s) and either some composition laws or laws of coexistence
(depending on whether or not there is descriptive emergence). Methodological
individualists need not deny that there may be significant lawful connections
among properties of the “whole,” but must insist that all such properties are
either definable through, or connected by laws of coexistence with, properties
of the “parts.”
michelstaedter: essential Italian
philosopher. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice
e Michelstaedter: retorica e persuasione," per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The
Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
migliio: essential
Italian philosopher. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice e Miglio," per il
Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
middle platonism, the period of Platonism
between Antiochus of Ascalon and Plotinus, characterized by a rejection of the
skeptical stance of the New Academy and by a gradual advance, with many
individual variations, toward a comprehensive dogmatic position on metaphysical
principles, while exhibiting a certain latitude, as between Stoicizing and
Peripateticizing positions, in the sphere of ethics. Antiochus himself was much
influenced by Stoic materialism (though disagreeing with the Stoics in ethics),
but in the next generation a neo-Pythagorean influence made itself felt,
generating the mix of doctrines that one may most properly term Middle
Platonic. From Eudorus of Alexandria (fl. c.25 B.C.) on, a transcendental,
two-world metaphysic prevailed, featuring a supreme god, or Monad, a secondary
creator god, and a world soul, with which came a significant change in ethics,
substituting, as an ‘end of goods’ (telos), “likeness to God” (from Plato,
Theaetetus 176b), for the Stoicizing “assimilation to nature” of Antiochus. Our
view of the period is hampered by a lack of surviving texts, but it is plain
that, in the absence of a central validating authority (the Academy as an
institution seems to have perished in the wake of the capture of Athens by
Mithridates in 88 B.C.), a considerable variety of doctrine prevailed among
individual Platonists and schools of Platonists, particularly in relation to a
preference for Aristotelian or Stoic principles of ethics. Most known activity
occurred in the late first and second centuries A.D. Chief figures in this
period are Plutarch of Chaeronea (c.45–125), Calvenus Taurus (fl. c.145), and
Atticus (fl. c.175), whose activity centered on Athens (though Plutarch
remained loyal to Chaeronea in Boeotia); Gaius (fl. c.100) and Albinus (fl.
c.130) – not to be identified with “Alcinous,” author of the Didaskalikos; the
rhetorician Apuleius of Madaura (fl. c.150), who also composed a useful
treatise on the life and doctrines of Plato; and the neo-Pythagoreans Moderatus
of Gades (fl. c.90), Nicomachus of Gerasa (fl. c.140), and Numenius (fl.
c.150), who do not, however, constitute a “school.” Good evidence for an
earlier stage of Middle Platonism is provided by the Jewish philosopher Philo
of Alexandria (c.25 B.C.–A.D. 50). Perhaps the single most important figure for
the later Platonism of Plotinus and his successors is Numenius, of whose works
we have only fragments. His speculations on the nature of the first principle,
however, do seem to have been a stimulus to Plotinus in his postulation of a
supraessential One. Plutarch is important as a literary figure, though most of
his serious philosophical works are lost; and the handbooks of Alcinous and
Apuleius are significant for our understanding of second-century Platonism.Luigi
Speranza, “Middle Griceianism and Middle Platonism, Compared.”
Miletusians, or Ionian Miletusians, or Milesians,
the pre-Socratic philosophers of Miletus, a Grecian city-state on the Ionian
coast of Asia Minor. Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes produced the earliest philosophies,
stressing an “arche” or material source from which the cosmos and all things in
it were generated: water for Thales, and then there’s air, fire, and earth –
the fifth Grice called the ‘quintessentia.’
more
grice to the mill:
Mill: Scots-born philosopher (“One should take grice to one mill but not to the
mill –“ Grice --) and social theorist. He applied the utilitarianism of his
contemporary Bentham to such social matters as systems of education and
government, law and penal systems, and colonial policy. He also advocated the
associationism of Hume. Mill was an influential thinker in early
nineteenth-century London, but his most important role in the history of
philosophy was the influence he had on his son, J. S. Mill. He raised his more
famous son as a living experiment in his associationist theory of education.
His utilitarian views were developed and extended by J. S. Mill, while his
associationism was also adopted by his son and became a precursor of the
latter’s phenomenalism. More grice to the mill -- Mill, Scots
London-born empiricist philosopher and utilitarian social reformer. He was the
son of Mill, a leading defender of Bentham’s utilitarianism, and an advocate of
reforms based on that philosophy. Mill was educated by his father (and thus “at
Oxford we always considered him an outsider!” – Grice) in accordance with the
principles of the associationist psychology adopted by the Benthamites and
deriving from David Hartley, and was raised with the expectation that he would
become a defender of the principles of the Benthamite school. Mill begins the
study of Grecian at three and Roman at eight, and later assisted Mill in
educating his brothers. He went to France to learn the language (“sc. French
--” Grice ), and studied chemistry and mathematics at Montpellier. He wrote
regularly for the Westminster Review, the Benthamite journal. He underwent a
mental crisis that lasted some months. This he later attributed to his rigid
education; in any case he emerged from a period of deep depression still
advocating utilitarianism but in a very much revised version. Mill visits Paris
during the revolution, meeting Lafayette and other popular leaders, and was
introduced to the writings of Saint-Simon and Comte. He also met Harriet Taylor,
to whom he immediately became devoted. They married only in 1851, when Taylor
died. He joined the India House headquarters of the East India Company, serving
as an examiner until the company was dissolved in 1858 in the aftermath of the
Indian Mutiny. Mill sat in Parliament. Harriet dies and is buried at Avignon,
where Mill thereafter regularly resided for half of each year. Mill’s major
works are his “System of Logic, Deductive and Inductive,” “Political Economy,”
“On Liberty,” “Utilitarianism,” in Fraser’s Magazine, “The Subjection of Women”
– Grice: “I wrote a paper for Hardie on this. His only comment was: ‘what do
you mean by ‘of’?” --; “An Examination of Sir William Hamilton’s Philosophy,”
and “Religion.” His writing style is excellent, and his history of his own
mental development, the “Autobiography” is a major Victorian literary text. His
main opponents philosophically are Whewell and Hamilton, and it is safe to say
that after Mill their intuitionism in metaphysics, philosophy of science, and
ethics could no longer be defended. Mill’s own views were later to be eclipsed
by those of such Oxonian lumaries as T. H. Green, F. H. Bradley, and the other
Oxonian Hegelian idealists (Bosanquet, Pater). His views in metaphysics and
philosophy of science have been revived and defended by Russell and the logical
positivists, while his utilitarian ethics has regained its status as one of the
major ethical theories. His social philosophy deeply infuenced the Fabians and
other groups on the English left; its impact continues. Mill was brought up on
the basis of, and to believe in, the strict utilitarianism of his father. His
own development largely consisted in his attempts to broaden it, to include a
larger and more sympathetic view of human nature, and to humanize its program
to fit this broader view of human beings. In his own view, no doubt largely
correct, he did not so much reject his father’s principles as fill in the gaps
and eliminate rigidities and crudities. He continued throughout his life his
father’s concern to propagate principles conceived as essential to promoting
human happiness. These extended from moral principles to principles of
political economy to principles of logic and metaphysics. Mill’s vision of the
human being was rooted in the psychological theories he defended. Arguing
against the intuitionism of Reid and Whewell, he extended the associationism of
his father. On this theory, ideas have their genetic antecedents in sensation,
a complex idea being generated out of a unique set of simple, elementary ideas,
through associations based on regular patterns in the presented sensations.
Psychological analysis reveals the elementary parts of ideas and is thus the
means for investigating the causal origins of our ideas. The elder Mill
followed Locke in conceiving analysis on the model of definition, so that the
psychological elements are present in the idea they compose and the idea is
nothing but its associated elements. Mill emerged from his mental crisis with
the recognition that mental states are often more than the sum of the ideas
that are their genetic antecedents. On the revised model of analysis, the
analytical elements are not actually present in the idea, but are present only
dispositionally, ready to be recovered by association under the analytical set.
Moreover, it is words that are defined, not ideas, though words become general
only by becoming associated with ideas. Analysis thus became an empirical task,
rather than something settled a priori according to one’s metaphysical predispositions,
as it had been for Mill’s predecessors. The revised psychology allowed the
younger Mill to account empirically in a much more subtle way than could the
earlier associationists for the variations in our states of feeling. Thus, for
example, the original motive to action is simple sensations of pleasure, but
through association things originally desired as means become associated with
pleasure and thereby become desirable as ends, as parts of one’s pleasure. But
these acquired motives are not merely the sum of the simple pleasures that make
them up; they are more than the sum of those genetic antecedents. Thus, while
Mill holds with his father that persons seek to maximize their pleasures,
unlike his father he also holds that not all ends are selfish, and that
pleasures are not only quantitatively but also qualitatively distinct. In
ethics, then, Mill can hold with the intuitionists that our moral sentiments
are qualitatively distinct from the lower pleasures, while denying the
intuitionist conclusion that they are innate. Mill urges, with his father and
Bentham, that the basic moral norm is the principle of utility, that an action
is right provided it maximizes human welfare. Persons always act to maximize
their own pleasure, but the general human welfare can be among the pleasures
they seek. Mill’s position thus does not have the problems that the apparently
egoistic psychology of his father created. The only issue is whether a person
ought to maximize human welfare, whether he ought to be the sort of person who
is so motivated. Mill’s own ethics is that this is indeed what one ought to be,
and he tries to bring this state of human being about in others by example, and
by urging them to expand the range of their human sympathy through poetry like
that of Wordsworth, through reading the great moral teachers such as Jesus and
Socrates, and by other means of moral improvement. Mill also offers an argument
in defense of the principle of utility. Against those who, like Whewell, argue
that there is no basic right to pleasure, he argues that as a matter of
psychological fact, people seek only pleasure, and concludes that it is
therefore pointless to suggest that they ought to do anything other than this.
The test of experience thus excludes ends other than pleasure. This is a
plausible argument. Less plausible is his further argument that since each
seeks her own pleasure, the general good is the (ultimate) aim of all. This
latter argument unfortunately presupposes the invalid premise that the law for
a whole follows from laws about the individual parts of the whole. Other moral
rules can be justified by their utility and the test of experience. For
example, such principles of justice as the rules of property and of promise
keeping are justified by their role in serving certain fundamental human needs.
Exceptions to such secondary rules can be justified by appeal to the principle
of utility. But there is also utility in not requiring in every application a
lengthy utilitarian calculation, which provides an objective justification for
overlooking what might be, objectively considered in terms of the principle of
utility, an exception to a secondary rule. Logic and philosophy of science. The
test of experience is also brought to bear on norms other than those of morality,
e.g., those of logic and philosophy of science. Mill argues, against the
rationalists, that science is not demonstrative from intuited premises. Reason
in the sense of deductive logic is not a logic of proof but a logic of
consistency. The basic axioms of any science are derived through generalization
from experience. The axioms are generic and delimit a range of possible
hypotheses about the specific subject matter to which they are applied. It is
then the task of experiment and, more generally, observation to eliminate the
false and determine which hypothesis is true. The axioms, the most generic of
which is the law of the uniformity of nature, are arrived at not by this sort
of process of elimination but by induction by simple enumeration: Mill argues
plausibly that on the basis of experience this method becomes more reliable the
more generic is the hypothesis that it is used to justify. But like Hume, Mill
holds that for any generalization from experience the evidence can never be
sufficient to eliminate all possibility of doubt. Explanation for Mill, as for
the logical positivists, is by subsumption under matter-of-fact
generalizations. Causal generalizations that state sufficient or necessary and
sufficient conditions are more desirable as explanations than mere
regularities. Still more desirable is a law or body of laws that gives
necessary and sufficient conditions for any state of a system, i.e., a body of
laws for which there are no explanatory gaps. As for explanation of laws, this
can proceed either by filling in gaps or by subsuming the law under a generic
theory that unifies the laws of several areas. Mill argues that in the social
sciences the subject matter is too complex to apply the normal methods of
experiment. But he also rejects the purely deductive method of the Benthamite
political economists such as his father and David Ricardo. Rather, one must
deduce the laws for wholes, i.e., the laws of economics and sociology, from the
laws for the parts, i.e., the laws of psychology, and then test these derived
laws against the accumulated data of history. Mill got the idea for this
methodology of the social sciences from Comte, but unfortunately it is vitiated
by the false idea, already noted, that one can deduce without any further
premise the laws for wholes from the laws for the parts. Subsequent
methodologists of the social sciences have come to substitute the more
reasonable methods of statistics for this invalid method Mill proposes. Mill’s
account of scientific method does work well for empirical sciences, such as the
chemistry of his day. He was able to show, too, that it made good sense of a
great deal of physics, though it is arguable that it cannot do justice to
theories that explain the atomic and subatomic structure of matter – something
Mill himself was prepared to acknowledge. He also attempted to apply his views
to geometry, and even more implausibly, to arithmetic. In these areas, he was
certainly bested by Whewell, and the world had to wait for the logical work of
Russell and Whitehead before a reasonable empiricist account of these areas
became available. Metaphysics. The starting point of all inference is the sort
of observation we make through our senses, and since we know by experience that
we have no ideas that do not derive from sense experience, it follows that we
cannot conceive a world beyond what we know by sense. To be sure, we can form
generic concepts, such as that of an event, which enable us to form concepts of
entities that we cannot experience, e.g., the concept of the tiny speck of sand
that stopped my watch or the concept of the event that is the cause of my
present sensation. Mill held that what we know of the laws of sensation is
sufficient to make it reasonable to suppose that the immediate cause of one’s
present sensation is the state of one’s nervous system. Our concept of an
objective physical object is also of this sort; it is the set of events that
jointly constitute a permanent possible cause of sensation. It is our inductive
knowledge of laws that justifies our beliefs that there are entities that fall
under these concepts. The point is that these entities, while unsensed, are (we
reasonably believe) part of the world we know by means of our senses. The
contrast is to such things as the substances and transcendent Ideas of
rationalists, or the God of religious believers, entities that can be known
only by means that go beyond sense and inductive inferences therefrom. Mill
remained essentially pre-Darwinian, and was willing to allow the plausibility
of the hypothesis that there is an intelligent designer for the perceived order
in the universe. But this has the status of a scientific hypothesis rather than
a belief in a substance or a personal God transcending the world of experience
and time. Whewell, at once the defender of rationalist ideas for science and
for ethics and the defender of established religion, is a special object for
Mill’s scorn. Social and political thought. While Mill is respectful of the
teachings of religious leaders such as Jesus, the institutions of religion,
like those of government and of the economy, are all to be subjected to
criticism based on the principle of utility: Do they contribute to human
welfare? Are there any alternatives that could do better? Thus, Mill argues
that a free-market economy has many benefits but that the defects, in terms of
poverty for many, that result from private ownership of the means of production
may imply that we should institute the alternative of socialism or public
ownership of the means of production. He similarly argues for the utility of
liberty as a social institution: under such a social order individuality will
be encouraged, and this individuality in turn tends to produce innovations in
knowledge, technology, and morality that contribute significantly to improving
the general welfare. Conversely, institutions and traditions that stifle
individuality, as religious institutions often do, should gradually be
reformed. Similar considerations argue on the one hand for democratic
representative government and on the other for a legal system of rights that
can defend individuals from the tyranny of public opinion and of the majority.
Status of women. Among the things for which Mill campaigned were women’s
rights, women’s suffrage, and equal access for women to education and to
occupations. He could not escape his age and continued to hold that it was
undesirable for a woman to work to help support her family. While he disagreed
with his father and Bentham that all motives are egoistic and self-interested,
he nonetheless held that in most affairs of economics and government such
motives are dominant. He was therefore led to disagree with his father that
votes for women are unnecessary since the male can speak for the family.
Women’s votes are needed precisely to check the pursuit of male self-interest.
More generally, equality is essential if the interests of the family as such
are to be served, rather than making the family serve male self-interest as had
hitherto been the case. Changing the relation between men and women to one of
equality will force both parties to curb their self-interest and broaden their
social sympathies to include others. Women’s suffrage is an essential step
toward the moral improvement of humankind. Grice: “I am fascinated by how Griceian
Mill can be.” “In treating of the ‘proposition,’ some
considerations of a comparatively elementary nature respecting its form must be
premised,and the ‘import’ which the emisor conveyed by a token of an expression
of a ‘proposition’ – for one cannot communicate but that the cat is on the mat -- . A proposition is a move in the
conversational game in which a feature (P) is predicated of the subject (S) –
The S is P – The subject and the predicate – as in “Strawson’s dog is shaggy”
-- are all that is necessarily required to make up a proposition. But as we can
not conclude from merely seeing two “Strawson’s dog” and “shaggy” put together,
that “Strawson’s dog” is the subject and “shaggy” the predicate, that is, that
the predicate is intended to be ‘predicated’ of the subject, it is necessary
that there should be some mode or form of indicating that such is, in Griceian
parlance, the ‘intention,’ sc. some sign to signal this predication – my father
says that as I was growing up, I would say “dog shaggy” – The explicit
communication of a predication is sometimes done by a slight alteration of the
expression that is the predicate or the expression that is the subject – sc., a
‘casus’ – even if it is ‘rectum’ – or ‘obliquum’ -- inflectum.” Grice: “The example Mill gives is
“Fire burns.”” “The change from ‘burn’ to ‘burns’ shows that the emisor intends
to predicate the predicate “burn” of the subject “fire.” But this function is
more commonly fulfilled by the copula, which serves the purporse of the sign of
predication, “est,” (or by nothing at all as in my beloved Grecian! “Anthropos
logikos,” -- when the predication is, again to use Griceian parlance,
‘intended.’” Grice: “Mill gives the example, ‘The king of France is smooth.”
“It may seem to be implied, or implicated – implicatum, implicaturum -- not
only that the quality ‘smooth’ can be predicated of the king of France, but
moreover that there is a King of France. Grice: “Mill notes: ‘It’s different
with ‘It is not the case that the king of France is smooth’”. “This, however
should not rush us to think that ‘is’ is aequi-vocal, and that it can be
‘copula’ AND ‘praedicatum’, e. g. ‘… is a spatio-temporal continuant.’ Grice:
“Mill then gives my example: ‘Pegasus is [in Grecian mythology – i. e. Pegasus
is *believed* to exist by this or that Grecian mythographer], but does not
exist.’” “A flying horse is a fiction of some Grecian poets.” Grice: “Mill
hastens to add that the annulation of the implicaturum is implicit or
contextual.” “By uttering ‘A flying horse is a Griceian allegory’ the emisor
cannot possibly implicate that a flying horse is a spatio-temporal continuant,
since by uttering the proposition itself the emisor is expressly asserting that
the thing has no real existence.” “Many volumes might be filled” – Grice: “And
will be filled by Strawson!” -- with the frivolous speculations concerning the nature
of being (ƒø D½, øPÃw±, ens, entitas, essentia, and the like), which have
arisen from overlooking the implicaturum of ‘est’; from supposing that when by
uttering “S est P” the emisor communicates that S is a spatio-temporal
continuant. when by uttering it, the emisor communicates that the S is some *specified*
thing, a horse and a flier, to be a phantom, a mythological construct, or the
invention of the journalists (like Marmaduke Bloggs, who climbed Mt. Everest on
hands and knees) even to be a nonentity (as a squared circle) it must still, at
bottom, answer to the same idea; and that a proposition must be found for it
which shall suit all these cases. The fog which rises from this very narrow
spot diffuses itself over the whole surface of ontology. Yet it becomes us not
to triumph over the great intellect of Ariskant because we are now able to
preserve ourselves from many errors into which he, perhaps inevitably, fell.
The fire-teazer of a steam-engine produces by his exertions far greater effects
than Milo of Crotona could, but he is not therefore a stronger man. The
Grecians – like some uneducated Englishman -- seldom knew any language but their
own! This render it far more difficult for *them* than it is for us, to acquire
a readiness in detecting the implicaturum. One of the advantages of having
accurately studied Grecian and Roman at Clifton, especially of those languages
which Ariskant used as the vehicle of his thought, is the practical lesson we
learn respecting the implicaturm, by finding that the same expression in
Grecian, say (e. g. ‘is’) corresponds, on different occasions, to a different
expression in Gricese, say (i. e. ‘hazz’). When not thus exercised, even the
strongest understandings find it difficult to believe that things which fall
under a class, have not in some respect or other a common nature; and often
expend much labour very unprofitably (as is frequently done by Ariskant) in a
vain attempt to discover in what this common nature consists. But, the habit
once formed, intellects much inferior are capable of detecting even an
impicaturum which is common or generalised to Grecian and Griceses: and it is
surprising that this sous-entendu or impicaturum now under consideration,
though it is ordinary at Oxford as well as in the ancient, should have been overlooked
by almost every philosopher until Grice. Grice: “Mill was proud of Mill.” “The
quantity of futilitarian speculation which had been caused by a misapprehension
of the nature of the copula, is hinted at by Hobbes; but my father is the first
who distinctly characterized the implicaturm, and point out to me how many
errors in the received systems of philosophy it has had to answer for. It has,
indeed, misled the moderns scarcely less than the ancients, though their
mistakes, because our understandings are not yet so completely emancipated from
their influence, do not appear equally irrational. Refs.: H. P.
Grice, “Grice to the Mill,” L. G. Wilton, “Mill’s mentalism,” for the Grice
Club. Grice treasured Hardie’s invocation of Mill’s method during a traffic
incident on the HIhg. Mill’s methods, procedures for discovering necessary
conditions, sufficient conditions, and necessary and sufficient conditions,
where these terms are used as follows: if whenever A then B (e.g., whenever
there is a fire then oxygen is present), then B is a necessary (causal)
condition for A; and if whenever C then D (e.g., whenever sugar is in water,
then it dissolves), then C is a sufficient (causal) condition for D. Method of
agreement. Given a pair of hypotheses about necessary conditions, e.g., (1)
whenever A then B1 whenever A then B2, then an observation of an individual
that is A but not B2 will eliminate the second alternative as false, enabling
one to conclude that the uneliminated hypothesis is true. This method for
discovering necessary conditions is called the method of agreement. To
illustrate the method of agreement, suppose several people have all become ill
upon eating potato salad at a restaurant, but have in other respects had quite
different meals, some having meat, some vegetables, some desserts. Being ill
and not eating meat eliminates the latter as the cause; being ill and not
eating dessert eliminates the latter as cause; and so on. It is the condition
in which the individuals who are ill agree that is not eliminated. We therefore
conclude that this is the cause or necessary condition for the illness. Method
of difference. Similarly, with respect to the pair of hypotheses concerning
sufficient conditions, e.g., (2) whenever C1 then D whenever C2 then D, an
individual that is C1 but not D will eliminate the first hypothesis and enable
one to conclude that the second is true. This is the method of difference. A
simple change will often yield an example of an inference to a sufficient
condition by the method of difference. If something changes from C1 to C2, and
also thereupon changes from notD to D, one can conclude that C2, in respect of
which the instances differ, is the cause of D. Thus, Becquerel discovered that
burns can be caused by radium, i.e., proximity to radium is a sufficient but
not necessary condition for being burned, when he inferred that the radium he
carried in a bottle in his pocket was the cause of a burn on his leg by noting
that the presence of the radium was the only relevant causal difference between
the time when the burn was present and the earlier time when it was not.
Clearly, both methods can be generalized to cover any finite number of
hypotheses in the set of alternatives. The two methods can be combined in the
joint method of agreement and difference to yield the discovery of conditions
that are both necessary and sufficient. Sometimes it is possible to eliminate
an alternative, not on the basis of observation, but on the basis of previously
inferred laws. If we know by previous inductions that no C2 is D, then
observation is not needed to eliminate the second hypothesis of (2), and we can
infer that what remains, or the residue, gives us the sufficient condition for
D. Where an alternative is eliminated by previous inductions, we are said to
use the method of residues. The methods may be generalized to cover
quantitative laws. A cause of Q may be taken not to be a necessary and
sufficient condition, but a factor P on whose magnitude the magnitude of Q
functionally depends. If P varies when Q varies, then one can use methods of elimination
to infer that P causes Q. This has been called the method of concomitant
variation. More complicated methods are needed to infer what precisely is the
function that correlates the two magnitudes. Clearly, if we are to conclude
that one of (1) is true on the basis of the given data, we need an additional
premise to the effect that there is at least one necessary condition for B and
it is among the set consisting of A1 and A2. 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM
Page 571 Mimamsa mimesis 572 The existence claim here is known as a principle
of determinism and the delimited range of alternatives is known as a principle
of limited variety. Similar principles are needed for the other methods. Such
principles are clearly empirical, and must be given prior inductive support if
the methods of elimination are to be conclusive. In practice, generic
scientific theories provide these principles to guide the experimenter. Thus,
on the basis of the observations that justified Kepler’s laws, Newton was able
to eliminate all hypotheses concerning the force that moved the planets about
the sun save the inverse square law, provided that he also assumed as applying
to this specific sort of system the generic theoretical framework established
by his three laws of motion, which asserted that there exists a force
accounting for the motion of the planets (determinism) and that this force
satisfies certain conditions, e.g., the action-reaction law (limited variety).
The eliminative methods constitute the basic logic of the experimental method
in science. They were first elaborated by Francis Bacon (see J. Weinberg,
Abstraction, Relation, and Induction, 1965). They were restated by Hume,
elaborated by J. F. W. Herschel, and located centrally in scientific
methodology by J. S. Mill. Their structure was studied from the perspective of
modern developments in logic by Keynes, W. E. Johnson, and especially Broad. Refs.:
H. P. Grice, “Grice to the Mill,” G. L. Brook, “Mill’s Mentalism”, Sutherland,
“Mill in Dodgson’s Semiotics.”
Icon: Iconicity and mimesis. Grice: “If it
hurts, you involuntarily go ‘Ouch.’ ‘Ouch’ can voluntarily become a vehicle for
communication, under voluntary control. But we must allow for any expression to
become a vehicle for communication, even if there is no iconic or mimetic
association -- (from Greek mimesis, ‘imitation’), the modeling of one thing on
another, or the presenting of one thing by another; imitation. The concept
played a central role in the account formulated by Plato and Aristotle of what
we would now call the fine arts. The poet, the dramatist, the painter, the
musician, the sculptor, all compose a mimesis of reality. Though Plato, in his
account of painting, definitely had in mind that the painter imitates physical
reality, the general concept of mimesis used by Plato and Aristotle is usually
better translated by ‘representation’ than by ‘imitation’: it belongs to the
nature of the work of art to represent, to re-present, reality. This
representational or mimetic theory of art remained far and away the dominant
theory in the West until the rise of Romanticism – though by no means everyone
agreed with Plato that it is concrete items of physical reality that the artist
represents. The hold of the mimetic theory was broken by the insistence of the
Romantics that, rather than the work of art being an imitation, it is the
artist who, in his or her creative activity, imitates Nature or God by
composing an autonomous object. Few contemporary theorists of art would say
that the essence of art is to represent; the mimetic theory is all but dead. In
part this is a reflection of the power of the Romantic alternative to the
mimetic theory; in part it is a reflection of the rise to prominence over the
last century of nonobjective, abstract painting and sculpture and of “absolute”
instrumental music. Nonetheless, the phenomenon of representation has not
ceased to draw the attention of theorists. In recent years three quite
different general theories of representation have appeared: Nelson Goodman’s
(The Languages of Art), Nicholas Wolterstorff’s (Works and Worlds of Art), and
Kendall Walton’s (Mimesis as Make-Believe). Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Aristotle’s
mimesis and Paget’s ta-ta theory of communication.”
Ta-ta: Paget: author beloved by Grice,
inventor of what Grice calls the “ta-ta” theory of communication.
Grice’s bellow -- “Ouch” – Grice’s theory
of communication in “Meaning revisited.” Grice’s paradox of the ta-ta. Why
would a simulation of pain be taken as a sign of pain if the sendee recognises
that the emisor is simulating a ‘causally provoked,’ rather than under
voluntary control, expression of pain. Grice’s wording is subtle and good. “Stage
one in the operation involves the supposition that the creature actually
voluntarily produces a certain sort of behaviour which is such that its
nonvoluntary production would be evidence that the creature is, let us say, in
pain.” Cf. Ockham, ‘risus naturaliter significat interiorem laetitiam.’ But the
laughter does NOT resemble the inner joy. There is natural causality, but not
iconicity. So what Grice and Ockham are after is ‘artificial laughter’ which
does imitate (mimic) natural laughter. “Risus significat naturaliter interiorem
laetitiam.” “Risus voluntaries significat NON-naturaliter interiorem
laetitiam.” Ockham wants to say that it is via the iconicity of the artificial
laughter that the communication is effected. So if ontogeny recapitulates
phylogeny, non-natural communication recapitulates natural communication.
“Risus voluntarius non-significat naturaliter (via risus involutarius
significans naturaliter) interiorem laetitiam. “The kinds of cases of this which come most
obviously to mind will be cases of faking or deception.” “A creature normally
voluntarily produces behaviour not only when, but *because*, its nonvoluntary
production would be evidence that the creature is in a certain state, with the
effect that the rest of the world, other creatures around, treat the
production, which is in fact voluntary, as if it were a nonvoluntary
production.” “That is, they come to just the same conclusion about the
creature’s being in the state in question, the signalled state.” Note Grice’s
technical use of Shannon’s ‘signal.’ “The
purpose of the creature’s producing the behaviour voluntarily would be so that
the rest of the world should think that it is in the state which the
nonvoluntary production would signify.” Note
that at this point, while it is behaviour that signifies – the metabolia has to
apply ultimately to the emisor. So that it is the creature who signifies – or
it signifies. The fact that Grice uses ‘it’ for the creature is telling – For,
if Grice claims that only rational Homo sapiens can communicate, Homo sapiens
is an ‘it.’ “In stage two not only does
creature X produce this behaviour voluntarily, instead of nonvoluntarily, as in
the primitive state.” By primitive he means Stage 0. “… but we also assume that
it is *recognised* by another creature Y, involved with X in some transaction, as
being the voluntary production of certain form of behaviour the nonvoluntary
production of which evidences, say, pain.” So again, there is no iconicity. Does
the “Ouch” in Stage 0 ‘imitate’ the pain. How can ‘pain,’ which is a state of
the soul, be ‘imitated’ via a physical, material, medium? There are ways. Pain
may involve some discomfort in the soul. The cry, “Ouch,” involuntary,
‘imitates this disturbance or discomfort. But what about inner joy and the
laughter. Ape studies have demonstrated that the show of teeth is a sign of
agreession. It’s not Mona Lisa’s smile. So Mona Lisa’s inner joy is signified
by her smile. Is this iconic? Is there a resemblance or imitation here? Yes.
Because the inner joy is the opposite of discomfort, and the distended muscles
around the mouth resemble the distended state of the immaterial soul of Mona
Lisa. As a functionalist, Grice was also interested in the input. What makes
Mona Lisa smile? What makes you to utter “Ouch” when you step on a thorn? Is
the disturbance (of pain, since this is the example Grice uses) or the
distension of joy resemble the external stimulus? Yes. Because a thorn on the
ground is NOT to be there – it is a disturbance of the environment. Looking at
Leonardo da Vinci who actually is commanding, “Smile!” is enough of a stimulus
for “The Gioconda” to become what Italians call ‘the gioconda.’ “That is, creature X is now supposed not just
to simulate pain-behaviour, but also to be recognised as simulating
pain-behaviour.” “The import of the recognition by Y that the production is
voluntary UNDERMINES, of course, any tendency on the part of Y to come to the
conclusion that creature X is in pain.” “So, one might ask, what would be
required to restore the situation: what COULD be ADDED which would be an
‘antidote,’ so to speak, to the dissolution on the part of Y of the idea that X
is in pain?” “A first step in this direction would be to go to what we might
think of as stage three.” “Here, we suppose that creature Y not only recognises
that the behaviour is voluntary on the part of X, but also recognises that X
*intends* Y to recognise HIS [no longer its] behaviour as voluntary.” “That is,
we have now undermined the idea that this is a straightforward piece of
deception.” “Deceiving consists in trying to get a creature to accept certain
things AS SIGNS [but cf. Grice on words not being signs in ‘Meaning’] as
something or other without knowing that this is a faked case.” “Here, however, we would have a sort of perverse
faked case, in which something is faked but at the same time a clear indication
is put in that the faking has been done.” Cf. Warhol on Campbell soup and why Aristotle
found ‘mimesis’ so key “Creature Y can be thought of as initially BAFFLED by
this conflicting performance.” “There is this creature, as it were, simulating
pain, but announcing, in a certain sense, that this is what IT [again it, not
he] is doing.” “What on earth can IT be up to?” “It seems to me that if Y does
raise the question of why X should be doing this, it might first come up with
the idea that X is engaging in some form of play or make-believe, a game to
which, since X’s behaviour is seemingly directed TOWARDS Y [alla Kurt Lewin], Y
is EXPECTED OR INTENDED to make some appropriate contribution. “Cases
susceptible of such an interpretation I regard as belonging to stage four.” “But,
we may suppose, there might be cases which could NOT be handled in this way.” “If
Y is to be expected to be a fellow-participant with X in some form of play, it
ought to be possible for Y to recognise what kind of contribution Y [the sendee
– the signalee] is supposed to make; and we can envisage the possibility that Y
has no clue on which to base such recognition, or again that though SOME form
of contribution seems to be SUGGESTED, when Y obliges by coming up with it, X,
instead of producing further pain-behaviour, gets cross and perhaps repeats its
original, and now problematic, performance.” [“Ouch!”]. “We now reach stage five, at which Y supposes
not that X is engaged in play, but that what X is doing is trying to get Y to
believe OR ACCEPT THAT X *is* in pain.” That is, not just faking that he is in
pain, but faking that he is in pain because he IS in pain. Surely the pain
cannot be that GROSS if he has time to consider all this! So “communicating
pain” applies to “MINOR pain,” which the Epicureans called “communicable pains”
(like a tooth-ache – Vitters after reading Diels, came up with the idea that
Marius was wrong and that a tooth-pain is NOT communicable! “: that is, trying to get Y to believe in or
accept the presence of that state in X which the produced behaviour, when
produced NONVOLUNTARILY, in in fact a natural sign of, naturally means.” Here
the under-metabolis is avoidable: “when produced nonvolutarily, in in fact THE
EFFECT OF, or the consequence of.” And if you want to avoid ending a sentence
with a preposition: “that STATE in X of which the produced behaviour is the
CONSEQUENCE or EFFECT. CAUSATUM. The causans-causatum distinction. “More specifically, one might say that at
stage five, creature Y recognises that creature X in the first place INTENDS
that Y recognise the production of the sign of pain (of what is USUALLY the
sign of pain) to be voluntary, and further intends that Y should regard this
first intention I1 as being a sufficient reason for Y to BELIEVE that X is in
pain.” But would that expectation occur in a one-off predicament? “And that X
has these intentions because he has the additional further INTENTION I3 that Y
should not MERELY have sufficient REASON for believing that X is in pain, but
should actually [and AND] believe it.” This substep shows that for Grice it’s
the INFLUENCING and being influenced by others (or the institution of
decision), rather than the exchange of information (giving and receiving
information), which is basic. The protreptic, not the exhibitive. “Whether or
not in these circumstances X will not merely recognise that X intends, in a
certain rather QUEER way, to get Y to believe that X is in pain, whether Y not
only recognises this but actually goes on to believe that X is in pain, would
presumably DEPEND on a FURTHER SET OF CONDITIONS which can be summed up under
the general heading that Y should regard X as TRUSTWORTHY [as a good
meta-faker!] in one or another of perhaps a variety of ways.” This is Grice’s
nod to G. J. Warnock’s complex analysis of the variety of ways in which one can
be said to be ‘trustworthy’ – last chapter of ‘trustworthiness in
conversation,’ in Warnock’s brilliant, “The object of morality.” “For example,
suppose Y thinks that, either in general or at least in THIS type of CASE [this
token, a one-off predicament? Not likely!] X would NOT want Y to believe that X
is in pain UNLESS [to use R. Hall and H. L. A. Hart’s favourite excluder
defeater] X really WERE in pain.” [Cf. Hardie, “Why do you use the
subjunctive?” “Were Hardie to be here, I would respond!” – Grice]. “Suppose
also (this would perhaps not apply to a case of pain but might apply to THE
COMMUNICATION of other states [what is communicated is ONLY a state of the
soul] that Y also believes that X is trustworthy, not just in the sense of not
being malignant [malevolent, ill-willed, maleficent], but also in the sense of
being, as it were, in general [semiotically] responsible, for example, being
the sort of creature, who takes adequate trouble to make sure that what HE [not
it] is trying to get the other creature to believe is in fact the case.” Sill,
“’I have a toothache” never entails that the emisor has a toothache! – a sign
is anything we can lie with!” (Eco). “… and who is not careless, negligent, or
rash.” “Then, given the general fulfilment of the idea that Y regards X either
in general or in this particular case of being trustworthy in this kind of
competent, careful, way, one would regard it as RATIONAL [reasonable] not only
for Y to recognise these intentions on the part of X that Y should have certain
beliefs about X’s being in pain, but also for Y actually to pass to adopting
these beliefs.” Stage six annuls mimesis, or lifts the requirement of mimesis – “we relax this
requirement.” “As Judith Baker suggests, it would be unmanly to utter (or ‘let
out’) a (natural) bellow!” Here Grice speaks of the decibels of the emission of
the bellow – as indicating this or that degree of pain. But what about “It’s
raining.” We have a state of affairs (not necessarily a state in the soul of the
emissor). So by relaxing the requirement, the emissor chooses a behaviour which
is “suggestive, in some recognizable way” with the state of affairs of rain
“without the performance having to be the causal effect of (or ‘response to,’
as Grice also has it) that state of affairs, sc. that it is raining. The connection becomes “non-natural,” or
‘artificial’: any link will do – as long as the correlation is OBVIOUS,
pre-arranged, or foreknown. – ‘one-off predicament’. There are problems with
‘stage zero’ and ‘stage six.’ When it comes to stage zero, Grice is supposing,
obviously that a state of affairs is the CAUSE of some behaviour in a creature
– since there is no interpretant – the phenomenon may very obliquely called
‘semiotic.’ “If a tree falls in the wood and nobody is listening…” – So stage
zero need not involve a mimetic aspect. Since stage one involves ‘pain,’ i.e.
the proposition that ‘X is in pain,’ as Grice has it. Or as we would have it,
‘A is in pain’ or ‘The emisor is in pain.’ Althought he uses the metaphor of
the play where B is expected or intended to make an appropriate contribution or
move in the game, it is one of action, he will have to accept that ‘The emisor
is in pain’ and act appropriately. But Grice is not at all interested in the
cycle of what B might do – as Gardiner is, when he talks of a ‘conversational
dyad.’ Grice explores the conversational ‘dyad’ in his Oxford lectures on the
conversational imlicaturum. A poetic line might not do but: “A: I’m out of
gas.” B: “There’s a garage round the corner.” – is the conversational dyad. In
B’s behaviour, we come to see that he has accepted that A is out of gas. And
his ‘appropriate contribution’ in the game goes beyond that acceptance – he
makes a ‘sentence’ move (“There is a garage round the corner.”). So strictly a
conversational implicaturum is the communicatum by the second item in a
conversational dyad. Now there are connections to be made between stage zero
and stage six. Why? Well, because stage six is intended to broaden the range of
propositions that are communicated to be OTHER than a ‘state’ in the emisor – X
is in pain --. But Grice does not elaborate on the ‘essential psychological
attitude’ requirement. Even if we require this requirement – Grice considers
two requirements. The requirement he is interested in relaxing is that of the
CAUSAL connection – he keeps using ‘natural’ misleadingly --. But can he get
rid of it so easily? Because in stage six, if the emisor wants to communicate
that the cat is on the mat, or that it is raining, it will be via his BELIEF
that the cat is on the mat or that it is raining. The cat being on the mat or
it being raining would CAUSE the emisor to have that belief. Believing is the
CAUSAL consequence. Grice makes a comparison between the mimesis or resemblance
of a bellow produced voluntarily or not – and expands on the decibels. The
‘information’ one may derive at stage 0 of hearing an emisor (who is unaware
that he is being observed) is one that is such and such – and it is decoded by
de-correlating the decibels of the bellow. More decibels, higher pain. There is
a co-relation here. Grice ventures that perhaps that’s too much information (he
is following someone’s else objection). Why would not X just ‘let out a natural
bellow.’ Grice states there are – OBVIOUSLY – varioius reasons why he would not
– the ‘obviously’ implicates the objection is silly (typical tutee behaviour). The first is charming. Grice, seeing the
gender of the tutee, says that it woud be UNMANLY for A to let out a natural
bellow. He realizes that ‘unmanly’ may be considered ‘artless sexism’ (this is
the late mid-70s, and in the provinces!) – So he turns the ‘unmanly’ into the
charmingly Oxonian, “ or otherwise uncreaturely.” – which is a genial piece of
ironic coinage! Surely ‘manly’ and ‘unmanly,’ if it relates to ‘Homo sapiens,’
need not carry a sexist implicaturum. Another answer to the obvious objection
that Grice gives relates to the level of informativeness – the ‘artificial’ (as
he calls it) – His argument is that if one takes Aristotle’s seriously, and the
‘artificial bellow’ is to ‘imitate’ the ‘natural bellow,’ it may not replicate
ALL THE ‘FEATURES’ – which is the expression Grice uses -- he means semiotic distinctive feature --. So
he does not have to calculate the ‘artificial bellow’ to correlate exactly to
the quantity of decibels that the ‘natural bellow’ does. This is important from
a CAUSAL point of view, or in terms of Grice’s causal theory of behaviour. A
specific pain (prooked by Stimulus S1) gives the RESPONSE R2 – with decibels
D1. A different stimulus S2 woud give a different RESPONSE R2, with different
decibels D2. So Grice is exploring the possibility of variance here. In a
causal involuntary scenario, there is nothing the creature can do. The stimulus
Sn will produce the creature Cn to be such that its response is Rn (where Rn is
a response with decibels – this being the semiotic distinctive feature Fn – Dn.
When it comes to the ‘artificial bellow,’ the emisor’s only point is to express
the proposition, ‘I am in pain,’ and not ‘I am in pain such that it causes a
natural bellow of decibels Dn,” which would flout the conversational postulate
of conversational fortitude. The overinformativeness would baffle the sendee,
if not the sender). At this point there is a break in the narrative, and Grice,
in a typical Oxonian way, goes on to say, “But then, we might just as well
relax the requirement that the proposition concerns a state of the sender.” He
gives no specific example, but refers to a ‘state of affairs’ which does NOT
involve a state of the sender – AND ONE TO WHICH, HOWEVER, THE SENDER RESPONDS
with a behaviour. I. e. the state of the affairs, whatever it is, is the
stimulus, and the creature’s behaviour is the response. While ‘The cat is on
the mat’ or ‘It is raining’ does NOT obviously ‘communicate’ that the sender
BELIEVES that to be, the ‘behaviour’ which is the response to the external
state of affairs is mediated by this state – this is pure functionalism. So, in
getting at stage six – due to the objection by his tutee – he must go back to
stage zero. Now, he adds MANY CRUCIAL features with these relaxations of the
requirements. Basically he is getting at GRICESE. And what he says is very
jocular. He knows he is lecturing to ‘service professionals,’ not philosophers,
so he keep adding irritating notes for them (but which we philosophers find
charming), “and we get to something like what people are getting at (correctly,
I would hope) when they speak of a semiotic system!” These characteristics are
elaborated under ‘gricese’ – But in teleological terms they can even be
ordered. What is the order that Grice uses? At this stage, he has already
considered in detail the progression, with his ‘the dog is shaggy,’ so we know
where he is getting at – but he does not want to get philosophically technical
at the lecture. He is aiming then at compositionality. There is utterance-whole
and utterance-part, or as he prefers ‘complete utterance’ and ‘non-complete
utterance’. ‘dog’ and ‘shaggy’ would be non-complete. So the external ‘state of
affairs’ is Grice’s seeing that Strawson’s dog is shaggy and wanting to
communicate this to Pears (Grice co-wrote an essay only with two Englishmen,
these being Strawson and Pears – ‘The three Englishmen’s essay,’ as he called
it’ --. So there is a state of affairs, pretty harmless, Strawson’s dog is
being shaggy – perhaps he needs a haircut, or some brooming. “Shaggy” derives
from ‘shag’ plus –y, as in ‘’twas brillig.’ – so this tells that it is an
adjectival or attribute predication – of the feature of being ‘shaggy’ to
‘dog.’ When the Anglo-Saxons first used ‘dog’ – the Anglo-Saxon ‘Adam,’ he
should have used ‘hound’. Grice is not concerned at the point with ‘dog,’ since
he KNOWS that Strawson’s dog is “Fido” – dogs being characteristically faithful
and the Strawsons not being very original – “I kid” --. In this case, we need a
‘communication function.’ The sender perceives that Fido is shaggy and forms
the proposition ‘Fido is shaggy.’ This is via his belief, caused by his seeing
that Fido is shaggy. He COMPOSES a complete utterance. He could just utter,
elliptically, ‘shaggy’ – but under quieter circumstances, he manages to
PREDICATE ‘shagginess’ to Strawson’s dog – and comes out with “Fido is shaggy.”
That is all the ‘syntactics’ that Gricese needs (Palmer, “Remember when all we
had to care about was nouns and verbs?”) (Strictly, “I miss the good old days
when all we had to care was nouns and verbs”). Well here we have a ‘verb,’
“is,” and a noun – “nomen adjectivum” – or ‘adjective noun’, shaggy. Grice is
suggesting that the lexicon (or corpus) is hardly relevant. What is important
is the syntax. Having had to read Chomsky under Austin’s tutelage (they spent
four Saturday mornings with the Mouton paperback, and Grice would later send a
letter of recommendation on one of his tutees for study with Chomsky overseas).
But Grice has also read Peano. So he needs a set of FINITE set of formation
rules – that will produce an INFINITE SET of ‘sentences’ where Grice highers
the decibels when he says ‘infinite,’ hoping it will upset the rare
Whiteheadian philosopher in the audience! Having come up with “Fido is shaggy,’
the sender sends it to the sendee. “Any link will do” – The link is ‘arranged’
somehow – arranged simpliciter in a one-off predicament, or pre-arranged in
two-off predicament, etc. Stages 2, 3, 4, and 5 – have all to do with
‘trustworthy’ – which would one think otiose seeing that Sir John Lyons has
said that prevarication in the golden plover and the Homo sapiens is an
essential feature of language! (But we are at the Oxford of Warnock!). So, the
sender sends “Fido is shaggy,’ and Pears gets it. He takes Grice to be
expressing his belief that Strawson’s dog is shaggy, and comes not only to
accept that Grice believes this, but to accept that Strawson’s dog is shaggy.
As it happens, Pears recommends a bar of soap to make his hairs at least look
‘cuter.’ Refs.: H. P. Grice, “A teleological model of communication.”
minimal transformationalism. Grice: “I wonder where Chomsky got the idea of a
‘transformation’?” -- Grice was proud that his system PIROTESE ‘allowed for the
most minimal transformations.” transformational
grammar Philosophy of language The most powerful of the three kinds of grammar distinguished
by Chomsky. The other two are finite-state grammar and phrasestructure grammar.
Transformational grammar is a replacement for phrase-structure grammar that (1)
analyzes only the constituents in the structure of a sentence; (2) provides a
set of phrase-structure rules that generate abstract phrase-structure
representations; (and 3) holds that the simplest sentences are produced
according to these rules. Transformational grammar provides a further set of
transformational rules to show that all complex sentences are formed from
simple elements. These rules manipulate elements and otherwise rearrange
structures to give the surface structures of sentences. Whereas
phrase-structure rules only change one symbol to another in a sentence,
transformational rules show that items of a given grammatical form can be
transformed into items of a different grammatical form. For example, they can
show the transformation of negative sentences into positive ones, question
sentences into affirmative ones and passive sentences into active ones.
Transformational grammar is presented as an improvement over other forms of
grammar and provides a model to account for the ability of a speaker to
generate new sentences on the basis of limited data. “The central idea of transformational
grammar is determined by repeated application of certain formal operations
called ‘grammatical transformations’ to objects of a more elementary sort.”
Chomsky, Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Grice: “Some
like Quine, but Chomsky’s MY man,” per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The
Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
miracle, an extraordinary
event brought about by God. In the medieval understanding of nature, objects
have certain natural powers and tendencies to exercise those powers under
certain circumstances. Stones have the power to fall to the ground, and the
tendency to exercise that power when liberated from a height. A miracle is then
an extraordinary event in that it is not brought about by any object exercising
its natural powers – e.g., a liberated stone rising in the air – but brought
about directly by God. In the modern understanding of nature, there are just
events (states of objects) and laws of nature that determine which events
follow which other events. There is a law of nature that heavy bodies when
liberated fall to the ground. A miracle is then a “violation” of a law of
nature by God. We must understand by a law a principle that determines what
happens unless there is intervention from outside the natural order, and by a
“violation” such an intervention. There are then three problems in identifying
a miracle. The first is to determine whether an event of some kind, if it
occurred, would be a violation of a law of nature (beyond the natural power of
objects to bring about). To know this we must know what are the laws of nature.
The second problem is to find out whether such an event did occur on a
particular occasion. Our own memories, the testimony of witnesses, and physical
traces will be the historical evidence of this, but they can mislead. And the
evidence from what happened on other occasions that some law L is a law of
nature is evidence supporting the view that on the occasion in question L was
operative, and so there was no violation. Hume claimed that in practice there
has never been enough historical evidence for a miracle to outweigh the latter
kind of counterevidence. Finally, it must be shown that God was the cause of
the violation. For that we need grounds from natural theology for believing
that there is a God and that this is the sort of occasion on which he is likely
to intervene in nature.
misfire: used by Grice in Meaning Revisited. Cf.
Austin. “When the utterance is a misfire, the procedure which we purport to
invoke is disallowed or is botched: and our act (marrying, etc.) is void or
without effect, etc. We speak of our act as a purported act, or perhaps an
attempt, or we use such an expression as ‘went through a form of marriaage’ by
contrast with ‘married.’ If somebody issues a performative utterance, and the
utterance is classed as a misfire because the procedure invoked is not
accepted , it is presumably persons other than the speaker who do not
accept it (at least if the speaker is speaking seriously ). What would be
an ex- ample ? Consider ‘I divorce you*, said to a wife by her
husband in a Christian country, and both being Chris- tians rather than
Mohammedans. In this case it might be said, ‘nevertheless he has not
(successfully) divorced her: we admit only some other verbal or
non-verbal pro- cedure’; or even possibly ‘we (we) do not admit any
procedure at all for effecting divorce — marriage is indis- soluble’.
This may be carried so far that we reject what may be called a whole code
of procedure, e.g. the code of honour involving duelling: for example, a
challenge may be issued by ‘my seconds will call on you’, which is
equivalent to ‘ I challenge you’, and we merely shrug it off The general
position is exploited in the unhappy story of Don Quixote. Of
course, it will be evident that it is comparatively simple if we never
admit any ‘such’ procedure at all — that is, any procedure at all for
doing that sort of thing, or that procedure anyway for doing that particular
thing. But equally possible are the cases where we do sometimes —
in certain circumstances or at certain hands — accept n
n^A/'Q/1n U UlUVlfU u plUVWUiV/, ULIL UW 111
T\llt 1 n nrttT at* amaiitvwifnnaati at* af ULIL 111
ttllj UL1U/1 L/llCUllli3Lail\/^ KJL CIL other hands. And
here we may often be in doubt (as in 28
Horn to do things with Words the naming example above)
whether an infelicity should be brought into our present class A. i or
rather into A. 2 (or even B. i or B. 2). For example, at a party,
you say, when picking sides, ‘I pick George’: George grunts ‘I’m
not playing.’ Has George been picked? Un- doubtedly, the situation is an
unhappy one. Well, we may say, you have not picked George, whether
because there is no convention that you can pick people who aren’t
playing or because George in the circumstances is an inappropriate object
for the procedure of picking. Or on a desert island you may say to me ‘Go
and pick up wood’; and I may say 4 1 don’t take orders from you’ or
‘you’re not entitled to give me orders’ — I do not take orders from you
when you try to ‘assert your authority’ (which I might fall in with but
may not) on a desert island, as opposed to the case when you are the
captain on a ship and therefore genuinely have authority.
missum: If Grice uses psi-transmission (and
emission, when he speaks of ‘pain,’ and the decibels of the emission of a
bellow) he also uses transmission, and mission, transmissum, and missum. Grice
was out on a mission. Grice uses ‘emissor,’ but then there’s the ‘missor.’ This
is in key with modern communication theory as instituted by Shannon. The
‘missor’ ‘sends’ a ‘message’ to a recipient – or missee. But be careful, he may
miss it. In any case, it shows that e-missor is a compound of ‘ex-‘ plus
‘missor,’ so that makes sense. It transliterates Grice’s ut-terer (which
literally means ‘out-erer’). And then there’s the prolatum, from proferre,
which has the professor, as professing that p, that is. As someone said, if H.
P. Girce were to present a talk to the Oxford Philosophical Society he would
possibly call it “Messaging.” c. 1300,
"a communication transmitted via a messenger, a notice sent through some
agency," from Old French message "message,
news, tidings, embassy" (11c.), from Medieval Latin missaticum, from Latin missus "a sending away,
sending, dispatching; a throwing, hurling," noun use of past participle
of mittere "to
release, let go; send, throw" (see mission). The Latin word is glossed in Old English by ærende. Specific religious sense of
"divinely inspired communication via a prophet" (1540s) led to
transferred sense of "the broad meaning (of something)," which is
attested by 1828. To get the message "understand" is by 1960.
m’naghten: a rule in England’s
law defining legal insanity for purposes of creating a defense to criminal
liability: legal insanity is any defect of reason, due to disease of the mind,
that causes an accused criminal either not to know the nature and quality of
his act, or not to know that his act was morally or legally wrong. Adopted in
the Edward Drummond-M’Naghten case in England in 1843, the rule harks back to
the responsibility test for children, which was whether they were mature enough
to know the difference between right and wrong. The rule is alternatively
viewed today as being either a test of a human being’s general status as a
moral agent or a test of when an admitted moral agent is nonetheless excused
because of either factual or moral/legal mistakes. On the first (or status)
interpretation of the rule, the insane are exempted from criminal liability
because they, like young children, lack the rational agency essential to moral
personhood. On the second (or mistake) interpretation of the rule, the insane
are exempted from criminal liability because they instantiate the accepted
moral excuses of mistake or ignorance. Refs.: H. P. Grice and H. L. A. Hart,
‘Legal rules;’ D. F. Pears, “Motivated irrationality.”
mnemic
causation,
a type of causation in which, in order to explain the proximate cause of an
organism’s behaviour, it is necessary to specify not only the present state of
the organism and the present stimuli operating upon it, but also this or that
past experience of the organism. The term was introduced by Russell in The
Analysis of Mind, and borrowed, but never returned, by Grice for his Lockeian
logical construction of personal identity or “I” in terms of an chain of
mnemonic temporary states. “Unlike Russell, I distinguish between the mnemic
and the mnemonic.”
Modus -- mode of co-relation: a technical jargon, under ‘mode’ – although Grice uses ‘c’
to abbreviate it, and sometimes speaks of ‘way’ of ‘co-relation’ – but ‘mode’
was his favourite. Grice is not sure
whether ‘mode’ ‘of’ and ‘correlation’ are the appropriate terms. Grice speaks
of an associative mode of correlation – vide associatum. He also speaks of a
conventional mode of correlation (or is it mode of conventional correlation) –
vide non-conventional, and he speaks of an iconic mode of correlation, vide
non-iconic. Indeed he speaks once of ‘conventional correlation’ TO THE
ASSOCIATED specific response. So the
mode is rather otiose. In the context when he uses ‘conventional correlation’
TO THE ASSOCIATED specific response, he uses ‘way’ rather than mode – Grice
wants ‘conventional correlation’ TO THE ASSOCIATED specific RESPONSE to be just
one way, or mode. There’s ASSOCIATIVE correlation, and iconic correlation, and
‘etc.’ Strictly, as he puts it, this or that correlation is this or that
provision of a way in which the expressum is correlated to a specific response.
When symbolizing he uses the informal “correlated in way c with response r’ –
having said that ‘c’ stands for ‘mode of correlation.’ But ‘mode sounds too
pretentious, hence his retreat to the more flowing ‘way.’ Modus – modelllo --
model theory:
Grice, “The etymology of ‘model’ is fascinating.” H. P. Grice, “A conversational model.” Grice: “Since the object of the present exercise, is to
provide a bit of theory which will explain, for a certain family of
cases, why is it that a particular implicaturum is present, I
would suggest that the final test of the adequacy and utility of this
model should be: can it be used to construct an explanation of
the presence of such an implicaturum, and is it more comprehensive
and more economical than any rival? is the no
doubt pre-theoretical explanation which one would be prompted to give
of such an implicaturum consistent with, or better still a favourable pointer
towards the requirements involved in the model? cf. Sidonius: Far otherwise:
whoever disputes with you will find those protagonists of heresy, the Stoics,
Cynics, and Peripatetics, shattered with their own arms and their own engines;
for their heathen followers, if they resist the doctrine and spirit of
Christianity, will, under your teaching, be caught in their own familiar
entanglements, and fall headlong into their own toils; the barbed
syllogism of your arguments will hook the glib tongues of the
casuists, and it is you who will tie up their slippery
questions in categorical clews, after the manner of a clever
physician, who, when compelled by reasoned thought, prepares antidotes for
poison even from a serpent.qvin potivs experietvr qvisqve conflixerit stoicos
cynicos peripateticos hæresiarchas propriis armis propriis qvoqve concvti
machinamentis nam sectatores eorum Christiano dogmati ac sensvi si
repvgnaverint mox te magistro ligati vernaculis implicaturis in retia
sua præcipites implagabvntur syllogismis tuæ propositionis vncatis volvbilem
tergiversantvm lingvam inhamantibvs dum spiris categoricis lubricas qvæstiones
tv potivs innodas acrivm more medicorvm qui remedivm contra venena cum ratio
compellit et de serpente conficivnt.” Grice: “Since the object of the present
exercise, is to provide a bit of theory which will explain, for a
certain family of cases, why is it that a particular conversational
implicaturum is present, I would suggest that the final tess of the adequacy and utility of this MODEL
should be various. First: can the model be used to construct an explanation
(argumentum) of the presence of this or that conversational
implicaturum? Second, is the model it more comprehensive than any rival in
providing this explanation? Third, is the model more economical than any rival
in providing this explanation? Fourth, is the no
doubt pre-theoretical (antecedent) explanation which one would be
prompted to give of such a conversational implicaturum consistent with the requirements
involved in the model. Fifth: is the no doubt pre-threoretical (antecedent)
explanation which one would be prompted to give of such a conversational
implciaturum better still, a favourable
POINTER towards the requirements involved in the model? Cf. Sidonius: Far
otherwise: whoever disputes with you will find those protagonists of heresy,
the Stoics, Cynics, and Peripatetics, shattered with their own arms and their
own engines; for their heathen followers, if they resist the doctrine and
spirit of Christianity, will, under your teaching, be caught in their own
familiar entanglements, and fall headlong into their own toils; the barbed
syllogism of your arguments will hook the glib tongues of the
casuists, and it is you who will tie up their slippery questions
in categorical clews, after the manner of a clever physician, who,
when compelled by reasoned thought, prepares antidotes for poison even from a serpent
-- qvin potivs experietvr qvisqve conflixerit stoicos cynicos peripateticos
hæresiarchas propriis armis propriis qvoqve concvti machinamentis nam
sectatores eorum Christiano dogmati ac sensvi si repvgnaverint mox te
magistro ligati vernacvlis implicatvris in retia sva præcipites
implagabvntur syllogismis tuæ propositionis vncatis volvbilem tergiversantvm
lingvam inhamantibvs dum spiris categoricis lvbricas qvæstiones tv potivs
innodas acrivm more medicorvm qui remedivm contra venena cvm ratio compellit et
de serpente conficivnt.
qvin potivs experietvr qvisqve
conflixerit stoicos cynicos peripateticos hæresiarchas propriis armis propriis
qvoqve concvti machinamentis nam sectatores eorum Christiano dogmati ac sensvi
si repvgnaverint mox te magistro ligati vernacvlis IMPILICATVRIS in retia
sva præcipites implagabvntur syllogismis tuæ propositionis vncatis volvbilem
tergiversantvm lingvam inhamantibvs dum spiris categoricis lubricas qvæstiones
tv potivs innodas acrivm more medicorvm qui remedivm contra venena cvm ratio
compellit et de serpente conficivnt. So Grice has the phenomenon: the
conversational implcaturum – the qualifying adjective is crucial, since surely
he is not interested in non-conventional NON-conversational implicatura derived
from moral maxims! --. And then he needs a MODEL – that of the principle or
postulate of conversational benevolence. It fits the various requirements.
First: the model can be used to construct an explanation (argumentum) of the
presence of this or that conversational implicaturum. Second, REQUIREMENT OF
PHILOSOPHICAL GENERALITY -- the model is
more comprehensive than any rival. Third, the OCCAM requirement: the model is
more ECONOMICAL than any rival – in what sense? – “in providing this
explanation” of this or that conversational implicaturum. Fourth, the J. L.
Austin requirement, this or that requirement involved in the model is SURELY
consistent with the no doubt pre-theoretical antecedent explanation
(argumentum) that one would be prompted to give. Fifth, the second J. L. Austin
requirement: towards this or that requirement involved in the model the
no-doubt pre-theoretical (antecedent) explanation (argument) that one would be
prompted to give is, better still, a favourable pointer. Grice’s oversuse of
‘model’ is due to Max Black, who understands model theory as a branch of philosophical
semantics that deals with the connection between a language and its
interpretations or structures. Basic to it is the characterization of the
conditions under which a sentence is true in structure. It is confusing that
the term ‘model’ itself is used slightly differently: a model for a sentence is
a structure for the language of the sentence in which it is true. Model theory
was originally developed for explicitly constructed, formal languages, with the
purpose of studying foundational questions of mathematics, but was later
applied to the semantical analysis of empirical theories, a development
initiated by the Dutch philosopher Evert Beth, and of natural languages, as in
Montague grammar. More recently, in situation theory, we find a theory of
semantics in which not the concept of truth in a structure, but that of
information carried by a statement about a situation, is central. The term
‘model theory’ came into use in the 0s, with the work on first-order model
theory by Tarski, but some of the most central results of the field date from
before that time. The history of the field is complicated by the fact that in
the 0s and 0s, when the first model-theoretic findings were obtained, the
separation between first-order logic and its extensions was not yet completed.
Thus, in 5, there appeared an article by Leopold Löwenheim, containing the
first version of what is now called the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem. Löwenheim
proved that every satisfiable sentence has a countable model, but he did not
yet work in firstorder logic as we now understand it. One of the first who did
so was the Norwegian logician Thoralf Skolem, who showed in 0 that a set of
first-order sentences that has a model, has a countable model, one form of the
LöwenheimSkolem theorem. Skolem argued that logic was first-order logic and
that first-order logic was the proper basis for metamathematical
investigations, fully accepting the relativity of set-theoretic notions in
first-order logic. Within philosophy this thesis is still dominant, but in the
end it has not prevailed in mathematical logic. In 0 Kurt Gödel solved an open
problem of Hilbert-Ackermann and proved a completeness theorem for first-order
logic. This immediately led to another important model-theoretic result, the
compactness theorem: if every finite subset of a set of sentences has a model
then the set has a model. A good source for information about the model theory
of first-order logic, or classical model theory, is still Model Theory by C. C.
Chang and H. J. Keisler 3. When the separation between first-order logic and
stronger logics had been completed and the model theory of first-order logic
had become a mature field, logicians undertook in the late 0s the study of
extended model theory, the model theory of extensions of first-order logic:
first of cardinality quantifiers, later of infinitary languages and of
fragments of second-order logic. With so many examples of logics around where sometimes classical theorems did
generalize, sometimes not Per Lindström
showed in 9 what sets first-order logic apart from its extensions: it is the
strongest logic that is both compact and satisfies the LöwenheimSkolem theorem.
This work has been the beginning of a study of the relations between various
properties logics may possess, the so-called abstract model. Refs.: H. P.
Grice, “The postulate of conversational co-operation,” Oxford.
senofane: “Or as Strawson would
prefer, Xenophanes, but since he emigrated to Italy, we might just as well use
an “S”” – Grice. Grice: “You have to be careful when you research for this in
Italy – they spell it with an ‘s’!” -- Grecian philosopher, a
proponent of an idealized conception of the divine, and the first of the
pre-Socratics to propound epistemological views. Born in Colophon, an Ionian
Grecian city on the coast of Asia Minor, he emigrated as a young man to the
Grecian West Sicily and southern Italy. The formative influence of the
Milesians is evident in his rationalism. He is the first of the pre-Socratics
for whom we have not only ancient reports but also quite a few verbatim
quotations fragments from his “Lampoons” Silloi and from other didactic
poetry. Xenophanes attacks the worldview of Homer, Hesiod, and traditional
Grecian piety: it is an outrage that the poets attribute moral failings to the
gods. Traditional religion reflects regional biases blond gods for the
Northerners; black gods for the Africans. Indeed, anthropomorphic gods reflect
the ultimate bias, that of the human viewpoint “If cattle, or horses, or lions
. . . could draw pictures of the gods . . . ,” frg. 15. There is a single
“greatest” god, who is not at all like a human being, either in body or in
mind; he perceives without the aid of organs, he effects changes without
“moving,” through the sheer power of his thought. The rainbow is no sign from
Zeus; it is simply a special cloud formation. Nor are the sun or the moon gods.
All phenomena in the skies, from the elusive “Twin Sons of Zeus” St. Elmo’s
fire to sun, moon, and stars, are varieties of cloud formation. There are no
mysterious infernal regions; the familiar strata of earth stretch down ad
infinitum. The only cosmic limit is the one visible at our feet: the horizontal
border between earth and air. Remarkably, Xenophanes tempers his theological
and cosmological pronouncements with an epistemological caveat: what he offers
is only a “conjecture.” In later antiquity Xenophanes came to be regarded as
the founder of the Eleatic School, and his teachings were assimilated to those
of Parmenides and Melissus. This appears to be based on nothing more than
Xenophanes’ emphasis on the oneness and utter immobility of God. Refs.: Luigi
Speranza, “Senofane in Italia.”
sensus -- modified Occam’s razor: Grice was obsessed with ‘sense,’ and thought Oxonian
philosohpers were multiplying it otiosely – notably L. J. Cohen (“The diversity
of meaning”). The original razor is what Grice would have as ‘ontological,’ to
which he opposes with in his ‘ontological marxism’. Entities should not be
multiplied beyond the necessity of needing them as honest working entities. He
keeps open house provided they come in help with the work. This restriction
explains what Grice means by ‘necessity’ in the third lecture – a second sense
does not do any work. The implicaturum does. Grice loved a razor, and being into analogy
and focal meaning, if he HAD to have semantic multiplicity, for the case of
‘is,’ (being) or ‘good,’ it had to be a UNIFIED semantic multiplicity, as
displayed by paronymy. The essay had circulated since the Harvard days, and it
was also repr. in Pragmatics, ed. Cole for Academic
Press. Personally, I prefer dialectica. ‒ Grice. This is
the third James lecture at Harvard. It is particularly useful for Grices
introduction of his razor, M. O. R., or Modified Occams Razor, jocularly expressed
by Grice as: Senses are not to be multiplied beyond necessity. An
Englishing of the Ockhams Latinate, Entia non sunt multiplicanda præter
necessitatem. But what do we mean sense. Surely Occam was right with his
Entia non sunt multiplicanda præter necessitatem. We need to translate that
alla linguistic turn. Grice jokes: Senses are not be multiplied beyond
necessity. He also considers irony, stress (supra-segmental fourth-articulatory
phonology), and truth, which the Grice Papers have under a special f. in the s.
V . Three topics where the implicaturum helps. He is a scoundrel may
well be the implicaturum of He is a fine friend. But cf. the pretense
theory of irony. Grice, being a classicist, loved the etymological
connection. With Stress, he was concerned with anti-Gettier uses of emphatic
know: I KNOW. (Implicaturum: I do have conclusive evidence). Truth (or is true) sprang from the attention by Grice
to that infamous Bristol symposium between Austin and Strawson. Cf. Moores
paradox. Grice wants to defend correspondence theory of Austin against the
performative approach of Strawson. If
is true implicates someone previously affirmed this, that does not mean
a ditto implicaturum is part of the entailment of a is true utterance, further notes on logic and
conversation, in Cole, repr. in a revised form, Modified Occams Razor, irony,
stress, truth. The preferred citation should be the Harvard. This is
originally the third James lecture, in a revised form.In that lecture,
Grice introduced the M. O. R., or Modified Occams Razor. Senses are not
be multiplied beyond necessity. The point is that entailment-cum-implicaturum
does the job that multiplied senses should not do! The Grice Papers
contains in a different f. the concluding section for that lecture, on irony,
stress, and truth. Grice went back to the Modified Occams razor, but was
never able to formalise it! It is, as he concedes, almost a vacuous
methodological thingy! It is interesting that the way he defines the alethic
value of true alrady cites satisfactory. I shall use, to Names such a property,
not true but factually satisfactory. Grices sympathies dont lie with
Strawsons Ramsey-based redundance theory of truth, but rather with Tarskis
theory of correspondence. He goes on to claim his trust in the
feasibility of such a theory. It is, indeed, possible to construct a
theory which treats truth as (primarily) a property, not true but factually
satisfactory. One may see that point above as merely verbal and not involving
any serious threat. Lets also assume that it will be a consequence, or
theorem, of such a theory that there will be a class C of utterances
(utterances of affirmative Subjects-predicate sentences [such as snow is white
or the cat is on the mat of the dog is hairy-coated such that each member of C
designates or refers to some item and indicates or predicates some class (these
verbs to be explained within the theory), and is factually satisfactory
if the item belongs to the class. Let us also assume that there can be a
method of introducing a form of expression, it is true that /it is buletic
that and linking it with the notion of
factually or alethic or doxastic satisfactory, a consequence of which will be
that to say it is true that Smith is happy will be equivalent to saying that
any utterance of class C which designates Smith and indicates the class of
happy people is factually satisfactory (that is, any utterance which assigns
Smith to the class of happy people is factually satisfactory. Mutatis mutandis
for Let Smith be happy, and buletic satisfactoriness. The move is Tarskian.
TBy stress, Grice means suprasegmental phonology, but he was too much of a
philosopher to let that jargon affect him! Refs.: The locus classicus, if
that does not sound too pretentious, is Essay 3 in WoW, but there are
references elsewhere, such as in “Meaning Revisited,” and under ‘semantics.’
The only one who took up Grice’s challenge at Oxford was L. J. Cohen, “Grice on
the particles of natural language,” which got a great response by Oxonian R. C.
S. Walker (citing D. Bostock, a tutee of Grice), to which Cohen again responded
“Can the conversationalist hypothesis be defended.” Cohen clearly centres his
criticism on the razor. He had an early essay, citing Grice, on the DIVERSITY
of meaning. Cohen opposes Grice’s conversationalist hypothesis to his own
‘semantic hypothesis’ (“Multiply senses all you want.”). T. D. Bontly
explores the topic of Grice’s MOR. “Ancestors of this essay were presented at
meetings of the Society for Philosophy and Psychology (Edmonton, Alberta), of
the the Pacific Division of the American Philosophical Association (San
Francisco, CA) and at the University of Connecticut. I am indebted to all three
groups and particularly to the commentators D. Sanford (at the Society for
Philosophy and Psychology) and M. Reimer (at the APA). Thanks also to the
following for helpful comments or discussion (inclusive): F. Adams, A. Ariew,
P. Bloom, M. Devitt, B. Enc, C. Gaulker, M. Lynch, R. Millikan, J. Pust, E.
Sober, R. C. Stalnaker, D. W. Stampe, and S. Wheeler.” Bontly
writes, more or less (I have paraphrased him a little, with good intentions,
always!) “Some philosophers have appealed to a principle which H. P. Grice, in
his third William James lecture, dubs Modified Occam’s Razor (henceforth, “M.
O. R.”): “Senses – rather than ‘entities,’ as the inceptor from Ockham more
boringly has it -- are not to be multiplied beyond necessity’.” What
is ‘necessity’? Bontly: “Superficially, Grice’s “M. O. R.”
seems a routine application of Ockham’s principle of parsimony: ‘entities are
not to be multiplied beyond necessity. Now, parsimony arguments, though common
in science, are notoriously problematic, and their use by Grice faces one
objection or two. Grice’s “M. O. R.” makes considerably more sense in light of
certain assumptions about the psychological processes involved in language
development, learning, and acquisition, and it describes recent *empirical*, if
not philosophical or conceptual, of the type Grice seems mainly interested in
-- findings that bear these assumptions out. [My] resulting account solves
several difficulties that otherwise confront Grice’s “M. O. R.”, and it draws
attention to problematic assumptions involved in using parsimony to argue for
pragmatic accounts of the type of phenomena ‘ordinary-language’ philosophers
were interested in. In more general terms, when an expression E has two or more
uses – U1 and U2, say -- enabling its users to express two or more different
meanings – M1 and M2, say -- one is tempted to assume that E is semantically
(i.e. lexically) ambiguous, or polysemous, i.e., that some convention,
constituting the language L, assign E these two meanings M1 and M2
corresponding to its two uses U1 and U2. One hears, for instance, that ‘or’ is
ambiguous (polysemous) between a weak (inclusive) (‘p v q’) and a strong
(exclusive) sense, ‘p w q.’ Grice actually
feels that speaking of the meaning or sense of ‘or’ sounds harsh (“Like if I
were asked what the meaning of ‘to’ is!”). But in one note from a seminar from
Strawson he writes: “Jones is between Smith and Williams.” “I wouldn’t say that
‘between’ is ambiguous, even if we interpret the sentence in a physical sense,
or in an ordering of merit, say.”
Bontly:
“Used exclusively, an utterance of ‘p or q’ (p v q) entails that ‘p’ and ‘q’
are NOT both true. Used inclusively, it does not. Still, ambiguity is not the
only possible explanation.” (This reminds me of Atlas, “Philosophy WITHOUT
ambiguity!” – ambitious title!). The phenomenon can also be approached
pragmatically, from within the framework of a general theory conversation alla
Grice. One could, e. g., first, maintain that ‘p or q’ is unambiguously
monosemous inclusive and, second, apply Grice’s idea of an ‘implicaturum’ to
explain the exclusive.” I actually traced this, and found that O.
P. Wood in an odd review of a logic textbook (by Faris) in “Mind,” in the
1950s, makes the point about the inclusive-exclusive distinction,
pre-Griceianly! Grice seems more interested, as you later consider, the implicaturum:
“Utterer U has non-truth-functional grounds for uttering ‘p or q. Not really
the ‘inclusive-exclusive’ distinction. Jennings deals with this in “The
genealogy of disjunction,” and elsewhere, and indeed notes that ‘or’ may be a
dead metaphor from ‘another.’ Bontly goes on: “On any such account, ‘p
or q’ would have two uses U1 and U2 and two standard interpretations, I1 and
I2, but NEVER two ‘conventional’ meanings,” M1 and M2 Or take ‘and’ (p.q) which
(when used as a sentential connective) ordinarily stands for truth-functional
conjunction (as in 1a, below). Often enough, though, ‘p and q’ seems to imply
temporal priority (1b), while in other cases it suggests causal priority (1c).
(1) a. Bill bought a shirt and Christy [bought] a sweater. b. Adam took off his
shoes and [he] got into bed. c. “Jack fell down and [he] broke his crown, and
Jill came tumbling o:ter.” (to rhyme with ‘water’ in an earlier
line.”Apparently Grice loved this nursery rhyme too, “Jack is an Englishman; he
must, therefore, be brave,” Jill says.” (Grice, “Aspects of reason.”)Bontly:
“Again, one suspects an ambiguity, M1 and M2, but Grice argues that a
‘conversational’ explanation is available and preferable. According to the
‘pragmatist’ or ‘conversationalist’ hypothesis’ (as I shall call it), a
temporal or a causal reading of “and” (p.q) may be part of what the UTTERER
means, but such a reading I2, are not part of what the sentence means, or the
word _and_ means, and thus belong in a general theory of conversation, not the
grammar of a specific language.” Oddly, I once noticed that Chomsky, of all
people, and since you speak of ‘grammar,’ competence, etc. refers to “A.”
Albert? P. Grice in his 1966! Aspects of the theory of syntax. “A. P. Grice
wants to say that the temporal succession is not part of the meaning of ‘and.’”
I suspect one of Grice’s tutees at Oxford was spreading the unauthorized word! Bontly:
“Many an alleged ambiguity seems amenable to Grice’s conversationalist
hypothesis. Besides the sentential connectives or truth-functors, a pragmatic
explanation has been applied fruitfully to quantifiers (Grice lists ‘all’ and
‘some (at least one’), definite descriptions (Grice lists ‘the,’ ‘the
murderer’), the indefinite description (‘a finger’, much discussed by Grice,
“He’s meeting a woman this evening.”), the genitive construction (‘Peter’s bat’),
and the indirect speech act (‘Can you pass the salt?’) — to mention just a few.
The literature on the Griceian treatment of these phenomena is extensive. Some
classic treatments are found in the oeuvre of philosophers like Grice, Bach,
Harnish, and Davis, and linguists like Horn, Gazdar, and Levinson. But the
availability of a pragmatic explanation poses an interesting methodological
problem. Prima facie, the alleged ‘ambiguity’ M1 and M2, can now be explained
either semantically (by positing two or more senses S1 and S2, or M1 and M2, of
expression E) or pragmatically (by positing just one sense (S) plus one
super-imposed implicaturum, I).Sometimes, of course, one approach or the other
is transparently inadequate. When the ‘use’ of E cannot be derived from a
general conversational principle, the pragmatic explanation seems a
non-starter.” Not for a radically radical pragmatist like Atlas! Ambitious!
Similarly, an ambiguity- or polysemy- based explanation seems out of the
question where the interpretation of E at issue is highly context-dependent.”
(My favourite is Grice on “a,” that you analyse in term of ‘developmental’ or
ontogenetical pragmatics – versus Millikan’s phylogenetical! But, in many
cases, a semantic, or polysemy, and a conversational explanations both appear
plausible, and the usual data — Grice’s intuitions about how the expression can
and cannot be used, should or shouldn’t beused — appear to leave the choice of
one of the two hypotheses under-determined.These were the cases that most interest
Grice, the philosopher, since they impinge on various projects in philosophical
analysis. (Cf. Grice, 1989, pp. 3–21 and passim).” Notably
the ‘ordinary-language’ philosophy ‘project,’ I would think. I love the fact
that in the inventory of philosophers who are loose about this (as in the
reference you mention above, pp. 3-21, he includes himself in “Causal theory of
perception”! “To adjudicate these border-line cases, Grice (1978) proposes a
methodological principle which he dubs “Modified Occam’s Razor,” M. O. R.”
‘Senses are not to be multiplied beyond necessity.’ (1978, pp. 118–119) “(I
follow Grice in using the Latinate ‘Occam’ rather than the Anglo-Saxon ‘Ockham’
which is currently preferred). More fully, the idea is that one should not
posit an alleged special, stronger SENSE S2, for an expression E when a general
conversational principle suffices to explain why E, which bears only Sense 1,
S1, receives a certain interpretation or carries implicaturum I. Thus, if the
‘use’ (or an ‘use’) of E can be explained pragmatically, other things being
equal, the use should be explained pragmatically.” Griceians appeal to M. O. R.
quite often,” pragmatically bearded or not! (I love Quine’s idea that Occam’s
razor was created to shave Plato’s beard. Cfr. Schiffer’s anti-shave! It is
affirmed, in spirit if not letter, by philosopher/linguist Atlas and Levinson,
philosopher/linguist Bach, Bach and philosopher Harnish, Horn, Levinson,
Morgan, linguist/philosopher Neale, philosopher Searle, philosopher Stalnaker,
philosopher Walker (of Oxford), and philosopher Ziff” (I LOVE Ziff’s use,
seeing that he could be otherwise so anti-Griceian, vide Martinich, “On Ziff on
Grice on meaning,” and indeed Stampe (that you mention) on Ziff on Grice on
meaning. One particularly forceful statement is found in “of all people”
Kripke, who derides the ambiguity hypothesis as ‘the lazy man’s approach in
philosophy’ and issues a strong warning.”
When I
read that, I was reminded that Stampe, in some unpublished manuscripts, deals
with the loose use of Griceian ideas by Kripke. Stampe discusses at length,
“Let’s get out of here, the cops are coming.” Stampe thinks Kripke is only
superficially a Griceian! Kripke: “‘Do not posit an ambiguity unless
you are really forced to, unless there are really compelling theoretical (or
intuitive) grounds to suppose that an ambiguity really is present’ (1977, p.
20). A similar idea surfaces in Ruhl’s principle of “mono-semic” bias’. One’s
initial effort is directed toward determining a UNITARY meaning S1 for a
lexical item E, trying to attribute apparent variations (S2) in meaning to
other factors. If such an effort fails, one tries to discover a means of
relating the distinct meanings S1 and S2. If this effort fails, there are
several words: E1 and E2 (1989, p. 4).” Grice’s ‘vice’ and Grice’s ‘vyse,’
different words in English, same in Old Roman (“violent.”). Ruhl’s position
differs from Grice’s approach. Whereas Grice takes word-meaning to be its
WEAKEST exhibited meaning, Ruhl argues that word-meaning can be so highly
abstract or schematic as to provide only a CORE of meaning, making EVEN the
weakest familiar reading a pragmatic specialisation.” Loved
that! Ruhl as more Griceian than Grice! Indeed, Grice is freely using the very
abstract notion of a Fregeian ‘sense,’ with the delicacy you would treat a
brick! “The difference between Grice’s and Ruhl’s
positions raises issues beyond the scope of the present essay (though see
Atlas, 1989, for further discussion).” I will! Atlas knows everything you wanted
to know, and more, especially when it comes to linguists! He has a later book
with ‘implicaturum’ in its subtitle.
“Considering
the central role that “M. O. R.” plays in Grice’s programme, one is thus
surprised to find barely any attention paid to whether it is a good principle —
to whether it is true that a pragmatic explanation, when available, is in
general more likely to be true than its ‘ambiguity’ or polysemy, or bi-semy, or
aequi-vocal rival.” Trying to play with this, I see that Grice
loves ‘aequi-vocal.’ He thinks that ‘must’ is ‘aequi-vocal’ between an alethic
and a practical ‘use.’ It took me some time to process that! He means that
since it’s the ‘same,’ ‘aequi’, ‘voice’, vox’. So ‘aequi-vocal’ IS ‘uni-vocal.’
The Aristotelian in Grice, I guess!
“Grice
himself offers vanishingly little argument.” How extended is a Harvard
philosophical audience’s attention-span? “Examining just two (out of the blue,
unphilosophical) cases where we seem happy to attribute a secondary or
derivative sense S2 to one word or expression E, but not another, Grice notes
that, in both cases, the supposition that the expression E has an additional
sense S2 is not superfluous, or unparsimonious, accounting for certain facets
of the use of E that cannot, apparently, be explained pragmatically.” I wonder
if a radically radical pragmatist would agree! I never met a polysemous
expression! Grice concludes that, therefore, ‘there is as yet no reason NOT to
accept M. O. R. ’ (1978, p. 120) — faint praise for a principle so important to
his philosophical programme! Besides this weak argument for “M. O. R.,” Grice
(1978) also mentions a few independent, rather loose, tests for alleged
ambiguity.” (“And how to fail them,” as Zwicky would have it!) But Grice’s
rationale for “M. O. R.,” presumably, is a thought Grice does not bother to
articulate, thinking perhaps that the principle’s name, its kinship with
Occam’s famous razor, ‘Do not multiply entities beyond necessity,’ made its
epistemic credentials sufficiently obvious already.” Plus,
Harvard is very Occamist!“To lay it out, though, the thought is surely that
parsimony -- and other such qualities as simplicity, generality, and
unification -- are always prized in scientific (and philosophical?)
explanation, the more parsimonious (etc.) of two otherwise equally adequate
theories being ipso facto more likely to be true. If, as would seem to be the
case, a pragmatic explanation were more parsimonious than its semantic, or
‘conventionalist,’ or ambiguity, or polysemic, or polysemy or bi-semic rival,
the conversational explanation would be supported by an established, received,
general principle of scientific inference.”
I love
your exploration of Newton on this below! Hypotheses non fingo! “Certainly,
some such argument is on Grice’s mind when he names his principle as he does,
and much the same thought surely lies behind Kripke’s references to ‘general
methodological considerations’ and ‘considerations of economy’ Other ‘Griceian’
appeals to these theoretical virtues are even more transparent. Linguist J. L.
Morgan tells us, for instance, that ‘Occam’s Razor dictates that we take a
Gricean account of an indirect speech act as the correct analysis, lacking
strong evidence to the contrary’ Philosopher Stalnaker argues that a major
advantage accrues to a pragmatic treatment of Strawson’s presupposition in that
‘there will then be no need to complicate the semantics or the lexicon’” or
introduce metaphysically dubious truth-value gaps! Linguist S. C. Levinson
suggests that a major selling point for a conversational theory in general is
that such a theory promises to ‘effect a radical simplification of the
semantics’ and ‘approximately halve the size of the lexicon’.” So we don’t need
to learn two words, ‘vyse’ and ‘vice.’ There can be little doubt, therefore,
that a Griceian takes parsimony to argue for the pragmatic approach.” I
use the rather pedantic and awful spelling “Griceian,” so that I can keep the
pronunciation /grais/ and also because Fodor used it! And non-philosophers,
too! “But a parsimony argument is notoriously
problematic, and the argument for “M. O. R.” is no exception. The preference
for a parsimonious theory is surprisingly difficult to justify, as is the
assumption that a pragmatic explanation IS more parsimonious. This does not
mean Grice’s “M. O. R.” is entirely without merit. On the contrary, Grice is
right to hold that senses should not be multiplied, if a conversational
principle will do.” But the justification for M. O. R. need have nothing to do
with the idea that parsimony is, always and everywhere, a virtue in scientific
theories.” Also because we are dealing with
philosophy, not science, here? What makes Grice’s “M. O. R.” reasonable,
rather, is a set of assumptions about the psychological processes involved in
language learning, development, and acquisition, and I will report some
empirical (rather than conceptual, as Grice does) evidence that these
assumptions are, at least, roughly correct. One disclaimer. While I shall
defend Grice’s “M. O. R.,” and therefore the research programme initiated by
Grice, it is not my goal here to vindicate any specific pragmatic account, nor
to argue that any given linguistic phenomenon requires a pragmatic
explanation.” This reminds me of Kilgariff, a Longman
linguist. He has a lovely piece, “I don’t believe in word SENSE!” I think he
found that Longman had, under ‘horse’: 1. Quadruped animal. 2. Painting of a
horse, notably by Stubbs! He did not like that! Why would ‘sense,’ a Fregeian
notion, have a place in something like ‘lexicography,’ that deals with corpuses
and statistics? “The task is, rather, to understand the
logic of a particular type of inference, a type of Griceian inference that can
be and has been employed by a philosopher such as Grice who disagree on many
other points of theory. Since it would be impossible within the confines of
this essay to discuss these disagreements, or to do justice to the many ways in
which Grice’s paradigm or programme has been revised and extended
(palaeo-Griceians, neo-Griceians, post-Griceians), my discussion is confined to
a few hackneyed examples hackneyed by Grice himself, and to Grice’s orthodox
theory, if a departure therefrom will be noted where relevant. The
conversational explanation of an alleged ambiguity or polysemy or bi-semy aims to
show how an utterer U can take an expression E with one conventional meaning
and use it as if it had other meanings as well. Typically, this requires
showing how the utterer U’s intended message can be ‘inferred,’ with the aid of
a general principle of communicative behaviour, from the conventional meaning
or sense of the word E that U utters. In Grice’s pioneering account, for
instance, the idea is that speech is subject to a Principle of Conversational
Co-Operation (In earlier Oxford seminars, where he introduced ‘implicaturum’ he
speaks of two principles in conflict: the principle of conversational
self-interest, and the principle of conversational benevolence! I much love
THAT than the rather artificial Kant scheme at Harvard). ‘Make your
conversational contribution, or move, such as is required, at the stage at
which it occurs, by the accepted purpose or direction of the conversational
exchange in which you are engaged.’(1975, p. 44). “Sub-ordinate to the
Principle of Conversational Co-Operation are four conversational maxims (he was
jocularly ‘echoing’ Kant!) falling under the four Kantian conversational
categories of Quality, Quantity, Relation, and Modus. Roughly: Make your
contribution true. Kant’s quality has to do with affirmation and negation, rather.
Make your contribution informative. Kant’s quantity has to do with ‘all’ and
‘one,’ rather. Make your contribution relevant. Kant’s relation God knows what
it has to do with. Make your contribution perspicuous [sic]. Kant’s modus has
to do with ‘necessary’ and ‘contingent.’
Grice
actually has ‘sic’ in the original “Logic and Conversation.” It’s like the
self-refuting Kantian. Also in ‘be brief (avoid unnecessary prolixity’”
‘proguard obfuscation,’ sort of thing? “… further specifying what cooperation entails
(pp. 45–46).” It’s sad Grice did not remember about the
principle of conversational benevolence clashing with the principle of
conversational self-interest, or dismissed the idea, when he wrote that
‘retro-spective’ epilogue about the maxims, etc. Bontly: “Unlike the
constitutive (to use Anscombe and Searle, not regulative) principles of a
grammar, the Principle of Conversational Co-Operation and the conversational,
universalisable, maxims are to be thought of not as an arbitrary convention –
vide Lewis -- but rather as a rational STRATEGY or guideline (if ‘strategy’ is
too strong) for achieving one’s communicative ends.” I
DO think ‘strategy’ is too strong. A strategist is a general: it’s a zero-sum
game, war. I think Grice’s idea is that U is a rational agent dealing with his
addressee A, another rational agent. So, it’s not strategic rationality, but
communicative rationality. But then I’m being an etymologist! Surely chess
players speak of ‘strategies,’ but then they also speak of ‘check mate,” kill
the king! Bontly quotes from Grice: “‘[A]nyone who cares about the goals that
are central to conversation,’ says Grice, ought to find the principle of
conversational cooperation eminently reasonable (p. 49).” If
not rational! I love Grice’s /: rational/reasonable. He explores on this later,
“The price of that pair of shoes is not reasonable, but hardly irrational!” Bontly:
“Like a grammar, however, the principle of conversational co-operation is
(supposedly) tacitly known (or assumed) by conversationalists, who can thus
call on it to interpret each other’s conversational moves.” Exactly.
Parents teach their children well, not to lie, etc. “These interpretive
practices being mutual ‘knowledge,’ or common ground, moreover, an utterer U
can plan on his co-conversationalist B using the principle of conversational
cooperation, to interpret his own utterances, enabling him to convey a good
deal of information (and influencing) implicitly by relying on others to infer
his intended meaning.”INFORMING seems to do, because, although Grice makes a
distinction between ‘informing’ and ‘influencing,’ he takes an ‘exhibitive’
approach. So “Close the door!” means “I WANT YOU To believe that I want you to
close the door.” I.e. I’m informing – influencing VIA informing. “Detailed
discussions of Grice’s principle of conversational cooperation are found in
many of the essays collected in Grice (1989), as well as in the work by
linguists like Levinson (1983) and linguist/philosopher Neale (1992).
Extensions and refinements of Grice’s approach are developed by linguist Horn
(1972), linguist/philosopher Bach and philosopher Harnish (1979), linguist
Gazdar (1979), linguist/philosopher Atlas and philosopher Levinson (1981),
anthropologist Sperber and linguist Wilson (1986), linguist/philosopher Bach
(1994), linguisdt Levinson (2000), and linguist Carston (2002).). The Principle
of conversational cooperation and its conversational maxims allow Grice to draw
a distinction between two dimensions of an utterer’s meaning within the total significance.” I
never liked that Grice uses “signification,” here when in “Meaning” he had
said: “Words, for all that Locke said, are NOT signs.” “We apply ‘sign’ to
traffic signals, not to ‘dog’.” Bontly: “That which
is ‘closely related to the conventional meaning of the word’ uttered is what
the utterer has SAID (1975, p. 44),” or the explicatum, or explicitum. That
which must instead be inferred with the aid of the principle of conversational
cooperation is what the utterer U has conversationally implicated, the IMPLICATURUM
(pp. 49–50), or implicitum. This dichotomy is in several ways oversimplified.
First, Grice (1975, 1978) also makes room for ‘conventional’ implicaturums
(“She was poor BUT she was honest”) and non-conversational non-conventional implicaturums
(“Thank you,” abiding with the maxim, ‘be polite’), although these dimensions
are both somewhat controversial (cf. Bach’s attack on conventional implicaturum)
and can be set aside here. Also controversial is the precise delineation of
Grice’s notion of what is said.” He grants he is using ‘say’ ‘artifiicially,’
which means, “natural TO ME!.” Some (anthropologist Sperber and linguist
Wilson, 1986; linguist Carston, 1988, 2002; philosopher Recanati, 1993) hold
that ‘what is said,’ the DICTUM, the explicatum, or explicitum, is
significantly underdetermined by the conventional meaning of the word uttered,
with the result that considerable pragmatic intrusive processing must occur
even to recover what the utterer said.”
And
Grice allows that an implicaturum can occur within the scope of an
operator.“Linguist/philosopher Bach disagrees, though he does add an
‘intermediate’ dimension (that of conversational ‘impliciture’) which is, in
part, pragmatically determined, enriched, or intruded. For my purpose, the
important distinction is between that element of meaning which is conventional
or ‘encoded’ and that element which is ‘inferred,’ ab-duced, or pragmatically
determined, whether or not it is properly considered part of what is said,” in
Grice’s admittedly artificial use of this overused verb! (“A horse says
neigh!”) A conversational implicaturum can itself be either particularized
(henceforth, PCIs) or generalized (GCIs) (56).” Most familiar examples of implicaturum
are particularised, where the inference to the utterer U’s intended meaning
relies on a specific assumption regarding the context of utterance.” Grice’s
first example, possibly, “Jones has beautiful handwriting” (Grice 1961).“Alter
that context much at all and the implicaturum will simply disappear, perhaps to
be replaced by another. With a generalised implicaturum, on the other hand, the
inference or abduction to U’s intended interpretation is relatively
context-independent, going through unless special clues to the contrary are
provided to defeat it.”Love the ‘defeat.’ Levinson cites one of Grice’s
unpublications as “Probability, defeasibility, and mood operators,” where Grice
is actually writing, “desirability.”!
“For
instance, an utterance of the sentence” ‘SOME residents survived the earth-quake,’
would quite generally, absent any special clues to the contrary, seem to
implicate that not all survived. All survived, alas, seems to be, to some, no
news. Cruel world. No special ‘stage-setting’ has to be provided to make the implicaturum
appreciable. No particular context needs to be assumed in order to calculate
the likely intended meaning. All one needs to know is that an utterer U who
thought that everyone, all residents survived the earthquake (or that none
did?) would probably make this stronger assertion (in keeping with Grice’s
first sub-maxim of Quantity: ‘Make your contribution as informative as
required’).” Perhaps it’s best to deal with buildings.
“Some – some 75%, I would say -- of the buildings did not collapse after the
earth-quake on the tiny island, and fortunately, no fatalities need be
reported. It wasn’t such a big earth-quake as pessimist had predicted.” “A
Gricean should maintain that the ‘ambiguity’ of “some” -> “not all”
canvassed at the outset can all be explained in terms of a generalized
conversational implicaturum. For instance, linguist Horn shows, in his PhD on
English, how an exclusive use of ‘or’ can be treated as a consequence of the
maxim of Quantity. Roughly, since ‘p AND q’ is always ‘more informative,’
stronger, than ‘p or q’, an utterer U’s choosing to assert only the disjunction
would ordinarily indicate that he takes one or the other disjunct to be false.
He could assert the conjunction anyway, but then he would be violating Grice’s
first submaxim of Quality: ‘Do not say what you believe to be false’ For
similar reasons, the assertion of a disjunction would ordinarily seem to
implicate that the utterer U does not know which disjunct is true (otherwise he
would assert that disjunct rather than the entire disjunction) and hence, and
this is the way Grice puts it, which is technically, the best way, that the
utterer wants to be ‘interpreted’ as having some ‘non-truth-functional grounds’
for believing the disjunction (philosopher Grice, 1978; linguist Gazdar, 1979).
For recall that this all goes under the
scope of a psychological attitude. In “Method in psychological philosophy: from
the banal to the bizarre,” repr. in “The conception of value,” Grice considers
proper disjunctions: “The eagle is not sure whether to attack the rabbit or the
dove.” I think Loar plays with this too in his book for Cambridge on meaning
and mind and Grice. “Grice (1981) takes a similar line with
regard to asymmetric uses of ‘and’.”
Indeed,
I loved his “Jones got into bed and took off his clothes, but I do not want to
suggest in that order.” “Is that a linguistic offence?” Don’t think so!” “The
fourth submaxim of Manner,” ‘be orderly’ -- I tend to think this is ad-hoc and
that Grice had this maxim JUST to explain away the oddity of “She got a
children and married,” by Strawson in Strawson 1952. “says that utterers should
be ‘orderly,’ and when describing a sequence of events, an orderly presentation
would normally describe the events in the order in which they occurred. So an
utterance of (1b) (‘Jones took off his
trousers – he had taken off his shoes already -- and got into bed.’ “would
ordinarily (unless the utterer U ‘indicates’ otherwise) implicate that Jones
did so in that order, hence the temporal reading of ‘and’.” “(Grice’s (1981) account
of asymmetric ‘and’ seems NOT to account for causal interpretations like
(1c).”Ryle says in “Informal logic,” 1953, in Dilemmas, “She felt ill and took
arsenic,” has the conscript ‘and’ of Whitehead and Russell, not the ‘civil’
‘and’ of the informalist. “Oxonian philosopher R. C. S. Walker – what took him
to respond to Cohen? Walker quotes from Bostock, who was Grice’s tutee at St.
John’s -- (1975, p. 136) suggests that the causal reading can be derived from
the maxim of Relation.”Nowell-Smith had spoken of ‘be relevant’ in Ethics. But
Grice HAD to be a Kantian!“Since conversationalists are expected to make their
utterances relevant, one expects that conjoined sentences will ‘have some
bearing to one another’, often a causal bearing. More nearly adequate accounts
of the temporal and causal uses of ‘and’ (so-called ‘conjunction buttressing’)
are found in linguist/philosopher Atlas and linguist Levinson (1981) and in
linguist Levinson (1983, 2000). Linguist Carston (1988, 2002) develops a rival
pragmatic account within the framework of anthropologist Sperber’s and linguist
Wilson’s Relevance Theory, on which temporal and causal readings are
explicatures rather than implicaturums. For the purposes of this essay, it is
immaterial which of these accounts best accords with the data. In these and
many other cases, it seems that a general principle regarding communicative
RATIONALITY can provide an alternative to positing a semantic
ambiguity.”Williamson is lecturing at Yale that ‘rationality’ has little to do with
it!“But a Gricean goes a step further and claims that the implicaturum account
(when available) is BETTER than an ambiguity or polysemy account. One possible
argument for the stronger thesis is that the various specialised uses of ‘or’
(etc.) bear all the usual hallmarks of a conversational implicaturum. An implicaturum
is: calculable (i.e. derivable from what is said or dictum or explicatum or
explicitum via the Principle of conversational cooperation and the
conversational maxims); cancellable (retractable without contradiction), and;
non-detachable (incapable of being paraphrased away) Grice, 1975, pp. 50 and
57–58). They ought also to be, sort of, universal.” (Cf. Elinor Keenan Ochs,
“The universality of conversational implicaturum.” I hope Williamson considers
this. In Madagascar, they have other ‘norms’ of conversation: since speakers
are guarded, implicatura to the effect, “I don’t know” are never invited!
Unlike the true lexical ambiguity that arises from a language-specific
convention, an implicaturum derives rather from general features of
communicative RATIONALITY and should thus be similar across different languages
(philosopher Kripke, 1977; linguist Levinson, 1983).”I’m not sure. Cfr. Ochs in
Madagascar. But she is a linguist/anthropologist, rather than a philosopher?
From a philosophical point of view, perhaps the best who treated this issues is
English philosopher Martin Hollis in his essays on ‘rationality’ and
‘relativism’ (keywords!)“Since the ‘ambiguity’ in question here has all these features,
at least to some degree, the implicaturum approach may well seem irresistible.
It is well known, however, that none of the features listed on various
occasions by Grice are sufficient (individually or jointly) to establish the
presence of a conversational implicaturum (Grice, 1978; linguist Sadock, 1978).
Take calculability.” Or how to ‘work it out,’ to keep it Anglo-Saxon, as
pretentious Grice would not! The main difficulty is that a conversationalimplicaturum
can become fossilized, or ‘conventionalised’ over time but remain calculable
nonetheless, as happens with some ‘dead’ metaphors — one-time non-literal uses
which congealed into a new conventional meaning.” A linguist at Berkeley worked
on this, Traugott, on items in the history of the English language, or H-E-L,
for short, H.O.T.E.L, history of the English language. I don’t think Grice
considers this. He sticks with old Roman ‘animal’ -> ‘non-human’, strictly,
having a ‘soul,’ or animus, anima. (I think Traugott’s focus was on verb forms,
like “I have eaten,” meaning, literally, “I possess eating,” or something. But
she does quote Grice and speaks of fossilization. “For instance, the
expression.” ‘S went to the bathroom’ (Jones?) could, for obvious reasons, be
used with its original, compositional, meaning to implicate that S ‘relieved
himself’.” “The intended meaning would still be calculable today.”Or “went to
powder her nose?” (Or consider the pre-Griceian (?) child’s overinformative,
standing from table at dinner, “I’m going to the bathroom to do number 2
(unless he is flouting the maxim). “But the use has been absorbed, or encoded
into some people’s grammar, as witnessed by the fact that ‘S went to the bathroom on the living room
carpet.’ is not contradictory (linguist J. L. Morgan, 1978; linguist Sadock,
1978).”I wonder what some contextualists at Yale (De Rose) would say about
that!? Cf. Jason Stanley, enfant terrible. “Grice’s cancellability is similarly
problematic. While one may cancel the exclusive interpretation of ‘p or q’
(e.g. by adding ‘or possibly both’), the added remark could just as well be
disambiguating an ambiguous utterance as canceling the implicaturum
(philosopher Walker, 1975; linguist Sadock, 1978).”Excellent POINT! Walker
would be fascinated to see that Grice once coined ‘disimplicaturum’ for some
loose uses. “Macbeth saw Banquo.” “That tie is yellow under that light, but
orange under this one.” Actually, Grice creates ‘disimplicaturum’ to refute
Davidson on intending: “Jones intends to climb Mt Everest next weekend.” Intending
DOES entail BELIEF, but people abuse ‘intend’ and use it ‘loosely,’ with one
sense dropped. Similarly, Grice says, with “You’re the cream in my coffee,”
where the ‘disimplicaturum’ is TOTAL!“Non-detachability fares no better. When
two sentences are synonymous (if there is, pace Quine, such a thing),
utterances of them ought to generate the same implicaturum. But they will also
have the same semantic implications, so the non-detachability of an alleged implicaturum
shows very little if anything at all (linguist Sadock, 1978).”I never liked
non-detachability, because it ENTAILS that there MUST be a synonym expression:
cfr. God? Divinity? “Universality is perhaps the best test of the four.”I
agree. When linguists like Elinor Keenan disregard this, I tend to think: “the
cunning of conversational reason,” alla Hollis. Grice was a member of Austin’s
playgroup, and the conversational MAXIMS were ‘universalisable’ within THAT
group. That seems okay for both Kant AND Hegel!“Since an implicaturum can
fossilise into a conventional meanings, however, it is always possible for a
cross-linguistic alleged ‘ambiguity’ to be pragmatic in some language though
lexical in another.”Is that ‘f*rnication’? Or is it Grice on ‘pushing up the
daisies’ as an “established idiom” for ‘… is dead’ in WJ5? Austin and Grice
would I think take for granted THREE languages: Greek and Roman, that they
studied at their public schools – and this is important, because Grice says his
method of analysis is somehow grounded on his classical education – and, well,
English. Donald Davidson, in the New World, would object to the
‘substantiation’ that speaking of “Greek” as a language, say, may entail.“So
while Grice’s tests are suggestive, they supply no clear verdict on the
presence of an implicaturum. Besides these inconclusive tests for implicaturum,
Grice could also appeal to various diagnostic tests for alleged ambiguity.”
“And how to fail them,” to echo Zwicky. Grice himself suggests three, although
none of them prove terribly helpful.”Loved your terrible. Cfr. ‘terrific’. And
the king entering St. Paul’s cathedral: “Aweful!” meaning ‘awe-some!’“First,
Grice points out that each alleged sense Sn of an allegedly ambiguous word E
ought to be expressible ‘in a reasonably wide range of linguistic environments’
(1978, p. 117). The fact that the strong implicaturum of ‘or’ is UNavailable
within the scope of a negation, for instance, would seem to count AGAINST
alleged ambiguity or polysemy. On the other hand, the strong implicaturum of
‘or’ IS available within the scope of a propositional-attitude verb. A strong implicaturum
of ‘and’ is arguably available in both environments, within the scope of a
negation, and within the scope of a psychological-attitude verb. So the first
test seems a wash.”Metaphorically, or implicaturally. J“Second, Grice says, if the
expression E is ambiguous with one sense S2 being derived (somehow) from the
initial or original or etymological sense S1, that derivative sense S2 ‘ought
to conform to whatever principle there may be which governs the generation of
derivative senses’ (pp. 117–118).”GRICE AT HIS BEST! I think he is trying to
irritate Quine, who is seating on second row at Harvard! (After all Quine
thought he was a field linguist!)Bontly, charmingly: “Not knowing the content
of thi principle Grice invokes— and Grice gives us no hint as to what it might
be — we cannot bring it, alas, to bear here!”I THINK he was thinking Ullman. At
Oxford, linguists were working on ‘semantics,’ cfr. Gardiner. And he just
thought that it would be Unphilosophical on his part to bore his philosophical
Harvard audience with ‘facts.’ At one point he does mention that the facts of
the history of the English language (how ‘disc’ can be used, etc.) are not part
of the philosopher’s toolkit?“Third and finally, Grice says, we must ‘give due
(but not undue) weight to MY INTUITIONS about the existence (or indeed
non-existence) of a putative sense S2 of a word E.’ (p. 120).”Emphasis on ‘my’
mine! -- As I say, I never had any intuition about an expression having an
extra-putative sense. Not even ‘bank,’ – since in Old Germanic, it’s all
etymologically related!Bontly: “But, even granting the point that ‘or’ is
NON-INTUITIVELY ambiguous in quite the same way that ‘bank’ IS, allegedly,
INTUITIVELY ambiguous, the source of our present difficulty is precisely the
fact that ‘p or q’ often *seems* intuitively to imply that one or the other
disjunct is false.”Grice apparently uses ‘intuition’ and ‘introspection’
interchangeably, if that helps? Continental phenomenological philosophers would
make MUCH of this! For Grice’s intuitions are HIS own. In a lecture at
Wellesley, of all places (in Grice 1989) he writes: “My problems with my use of
E arise from MY intuitions about the use of E. I don’t care how YOU use E.
Philosophy is personal.” Much criticised, but authentic, in a way!“Since he
discounts the latter intuition, Grice cannot place much weight on the
former!”As I say, Grice’s intuitions are hard to fathom! So are his introspections!
Actually, I think that Grice’s sticking with introspections and intuitions save
him, as Suppes shows in PGRICE ed Grandy and Warner, from being a behaviourist.
He is, rather, an intentionalist!“While a complete review of ambiguity tests is
beyond the scope of this essay, we have perhaps seen enough to motivate the
methodological problem with which we began: viz., that an, intuitive, alleged,
ambiguity seems fit to be explained either semantically (ambiguity thesis,
polysemy, bi-semy) or pragmatically/conversationally, with little by way of
direct evidence to tell us which is which!”“If philosophy generated no
problems, it would be dead!” – Grice. J“Linguists
Zwicky and Sadock review several linguistic tests for ambiguity (e.g.
conjunction reduction) and point out that most are ill-suited to detect
ambiguities where the meanings in question are privative opposites,”Oddly,
Grice’s first publication ever was on “Negation and privation,” 1938!Bontly:
“i.e. where one meaning is a specialization or specification of the other (as
for instance with the female and neutral senses of ‘goose’).”Or cf. Urmson,
“There is an animal in the backyard.” “You mean Aunt Matilda?”Bontly: “Since
the putative ambiguities of ‘or’ and the like are all of this sort, it seems inevitable
that these tests will fail us here as well. For further discussion, see
linguist Horn (1989, pp. 317–18 and 365–66) and linguist Carston (2002, pp.
274–77).It is hardly surprising, therefore, to find that a Gricean typically
falls back on a methodological argument like parsimony, as instantiated in “M.
O. R.”Let’s now turn to Parsimony and Its Problems. It may, at first, be less
than obvious why an ambiguity or polysemy or bi-semy account should be deemed
less parsimonious than its Gricean rival.” Where the conventionalist or
ambiguist posits an additional sense S2, Grice adds, to S1, a conversational implicaturum,
I”. Cheap, but no free lunch! (Grice saves)Bontly: “Superficially, little seems
to be gained.” Ah, the surfaces of Oxford superficiality! “Looking closer,
however, the methodological virtues of the Grice’s approach seem fairly
clear.”Good!Bontly: “First, the principles and inference patterns that a
pragmatic or conversational account utilizes are independently motivated. The
principles and inference patterns are needed in any case to account for the
relatively un-controversial class of particularized implicatura, and they
provide an elegant approach to phenomena like figures of rhetoric, or speech --
metaphor, irony, meiosis, litotes, understatement, sarcasm – cfr. Holdcroft --
and tricks like Strawson’s presupposition. So it would seem that Grice can make
do with explanatory material already on hand, whereas the ambiguity or polysemy
theorist must posit a new semantic rule in each and every case. Furthermore,
the explanatory material has an independent grounding in considerations of
rationality.”I love that evening when Grice received a phonecall at Berkeley:
“Professor Grice: You have been appointed the Immanuel Kant Memorial Lecturer
at Stanford.” He gave the lectures on aspects of reason and reasoning!Bontly:
“Since conversation is typically a goal-directed activity, it makes sense for
conversationalists to abide by the Principle of Conversational Cooperation
(something like Kant’s categorical imperative, in conversational format) and
its (universalisable) conversational maxims, and so it makes sense for a
co-conversationalist to interpret the conversationalist accordingly. A
pragmatic explanation is therefore CHEAP – hence Occam on ‘aeconomicus’ -- the
principle it calls on being explainable by — and perhaps even reducible to —
facts about rational behavior in general.”I loved your “REDUCE.” B. F. Loar
indeed thought, and correctly, that the maxims are ‘empirical generalisations
over functional states.’ Genius!Bontly: A pragmatic account is not only more
economic, or cheaper. It also reveals an orderliness or systematicity that
positing a separate lexical ambiguity or polysemy or bisemy in each and every
case would seem to miss (linguist/philosopher Bach). To a Griceian, it is no
accident that a sentential connective or truth-functor (“not,” “and,” “or,” and
“if”), a quantified expression (Grice’s “all” and “some (at least one)”) and a
description (Grice’s “the”) all lend themselves to a weak and a stronger
interpretation”Cf. Holdcroft, “Weak or strong?” in “Words and deeds.”Bontly:
“Note, for instance, that a sentence with the logical form ‘Some Fs are
Gs’, and the pleonethetic, to use
Geach’s and Altham’s coinage, ‘Most Fs are Gs’, and ‘A few Fs are Gs’ are all
allegedly ‘ambiguous’ in the SAME way. Each of those expressions has an obvious
weak reading in addition to a stronger reading: ‘Not all Fs are Gs’.Good
because Grice’s first examination was: “That pillar-box seems red to me.” And
he analyses the oddness in terms of ‘strength.’ (Grice 1961). He tries to
analyse this ‘strength’ in terms of ‘entailment,’ but fails (“Neither ‘The
pillar-box IS red’ NOR ‘The pillar-box SEEMS red’ entail each other.”)Bontly:
For the conventionalist or polysemy theorist, there is no apparent reason why
this should be so. There is no reason, that is, why three etymologically
unrelated words (“some,” “most,” and “few”) should display the SAME pattern of
alleged ambiguity. The Gricean, on the other hand, explains each the SAME way,
by appealing to some rational principle of conversation. The implicatura are
all ‘scalar’ quantity implicatura, attributable to the utterer U’s having
uttered a weaker, less informative, sentence than he might have.” Linguist
Levinson, 1983). Together, these considerations make a persuasive case for the
Grice’s approach. A pragmatic explanation is more economical, and the resulting
view of conversation is more natural and unified. Since economy and unification
are both presumably virtues to be sought in a scientific or philosophical
explanation — virtues which for brevity I lump together under Occamist
‘parsimony’ — it would NOT be unreasonable to conclude that a pragmatic
explanation is (ceteris paribus) a better explanation. So it seems that Grice’s
principle, the “M. O. R.” is correct. Senses ought not to be multiplied when
pragmatics will do. Still, there are several reasons to be suspicious of the
parsimony argument. “I lay out three. It bears emphasis that none of these are
objections to the pragmatic approach per se.” I have no quarrel with the theory
of conversation or particular attempts to apply it to conversational phenomena.
The objections focus rather on the role that parsimony (or simplicity, or
generality, etc.) plays in arguments PRO the implicaturum and CONTRA ambiguity
or polysemy.” Then, there’s Dead Metaphors. First is a worry that parsimony is
too blunt an instrument, generalizing to unwanted conclusions. Versions of this
objection appear in philosopher Walker (1975), linguist Morgan (1978), and
linguist Sadock (1978).” More recently, Reimer (1998) and Devitt (forthcoming)
use it to argue against a Gricean treatment of the referential/attributive
distinction.”But have they read Grice’s VACUOUS NAMES? I know you did! Grice notes:
“My distinction has nothing to do with Donnellan’s!” Grice’s approach is
syntactic: ‘the’ and “THE,” identificatory and non-identificatory uses. R. M.
Sainsbury and D. E. Over have worked on this. Fascinating. Bontly: “For as with
the afore-mentioned so-called ‘dead’ metaphor, it can happen that a word has a
secondary use that is pragmatically predictable, and yet fully conventional. In
many such cases, of course, the original, etymological meaning is long
forgotten: e. g. the contemporary use of ‘fornication’, originally a euphemism
for activities done in fornice (that is, in the vaulted underground dwellings
that once served as brothels in Rome). (I owe this [delightful] example to Sam
Wheeler). Few speakers recall the original meaning, so the metaphor can no
longer be ‘calculated,’ as Grice’s “You’re the cream in my coffee!” (title of
song) can!” The metaphor is both dead _and buried_.”Still un-buriable?“In other
cases, however, speakers do possess the information to construct a Gricean
explanation, and yet the metaphor is dead anyway.”Reimer’s (1998) example of
the verb ‘incense’ is a case in point. One conventional meaning (‘to make or
become angry’) began life as a metaphorical extension of the other (‘to make
fragrant with incense’). The reason for the extension is fairly transparent
(resting on familiar comparisons of burning and emotion), but the use allegedly
represents an additional sense nonetheless.”What dictionaries have as ‘fig.’
But are we sure that when the dictionaries list things like 1., 2., 3., they
are listing SENSES!? Cf. Grice, “I don’t give a hoot what the dictionary says,”
to Austin, “And that’s where you make your big mistake.” Once Grice actually
opened the dictionary (he was studying ‘feeling + adj.’ – he got to
‘byzantine,’ finding that MOST adjectives did, and got bored!Bontly: Such
examples suggest that an implicaturum makes up an important source of
semantic—and, according to linguist Levinson (2000), syntactic—innovation. A
linguistic phenomenon can begin life as a pragmatic specialization or an
extension and subsequently become conventionalized by stages, making it
difficult to determine at what point (and for which ‘utterers’) a use has
become fully conventional. One consequence is that an expression E can have,
allegedly, a second sense S2, even when a pragmatic explanation appears to make
it explanatorily superfluous, and parsimony can therefore mislead.”I’m not sure
dictionary readers read ‘fig.’ as a different ‘sense,’ and lexicographers need
not be Griceian in style!Bontly: “A related point is that an ambiguity account
needn’t be LESS unified than an implicaturum account after all. If pragmatic
considerations can explain the origin and development of new linguistic
conventions, the ambiguity or polysemy theorist can provide a unified
dia-chronic account of how several un-related expressions came to exhibit
similar patterns of alleged ‘ambiguity.’ Quantifiers like ‘some’, ‘most’, and
‘a few’ may be similarly allegedly ambiguous today because they generated
similar implicaturums in the past (cf. Millikan, 2001).”OKAY, so that’s the
right way to go then? Diachrony and evolution, right?Bontly: “Then, there’s
Tradeoffs. A ‘dead’ metaphor suggests that parsimony is too strong for the
pragmatist’s purposes, but as a pragmatic account could have hidden costs to
offset the semantic savings, parsimony may also be too weak! E. g. an implicaturum
account looks, at least superficially, to multiply (to use Occam’s term)
inferential labour, leaving it to the addressee to infer the utterer’s intended
meaning from the words uttered, the context, and the conversational principle.
Thus there are trade-offs involved, and the account which is semantically more
parsimonious may be less parsimonious all things considered.”Grice once invited
the “P. E. R. E.,” principle of economy of rational effort, though. Things
which seem to be psychologically UNREAL are just DEEMED, tacitly, to
occur.Bontly: “To be clear, this is not to suggest that the ambiguity or
polysemy account can dispense with inference entirely. Were the exclusive and
inclusive senses of ‘or’ BOTH lexically encoded (as they were in Old Roman,
‘vel’ and ‘aut,’ hence Whitehead’s choice of ‘v’ for ‘p v q’) still hearers
would need to infer from contextual clues which meaning were intended. The
worry is not, therefore, so much that the implicaturum account increases the
number of inferences which conversants or conversationalists have to perform.
The issue concerns rather the complexity of these inferences. Alleged
dis-ambiguation is a highly constrained process. In principle, one need only
choose the relevant sense Sn, from a finite list represented in the so-called
‘mental lexicon’. Implicaturum calculation, on the other hand, is a matter of
finding the best explanation (abductively, alla Hanson) for an utterer’s
utterance, the utterer’s meaning being introduced as an explanatory hypothesis,
answering to a ‘why’ question. Unlike dis-ambiguation, where the various
possible readings are known in advance, in the conversational explanation, the
only constraints are provided by the addressee’s understanding of the context
and the conversational principle. So it appears that Grice’s approach saves on
the lexical semantics by placing a greater inferential burden on utterer and
addressee.”But Grice played bridge, and loved those burdens. Stampe actually
gives a lovely bridge alleged counter-example to Grice (in Grice 1989).Bontly:
“Now, a Gricean can try to lessen this load in various ways. Grice can argue,
for instance, that the inference used to recover a generalised implicaturum is
less demanding than that for a particularized one, that familiarity with types
of generalised implicate can “stream-line” the inferential process, and so
on.”Love that, P. E. R. E., or principle of economy of rational effort,
above?!Bontly: “We examine these moves. There’s Justification. Another
difficulty with Grice’s appeals to parsimony is the most fundamental. On the
one hand, it can hardly be denied that parsimony plays a role in scientific, if
not philosophical, inference.” Across the sciences, if not in philosophy, it is
standard practice to cite parsimony (simplicity, generality, etc.) as a reason
to choose one hypothesis over another; philosophers often do the same.”Bontly’s
‘often’ implicates, ‘often not’! Grice became an opponent of his own minimalism
at a later stage of his life, vide his “Prejudices and predilections; which
become, the life and opinions of Paul Grice,” by Paul Grice!Bontly: “At the
same time, however, it remains quite mysterious, if that’s the word, why
parsimony (etc.) should be given such weight by Occamists like Grice. If it
were safe to assume that Nature is simple and economical, the preference for
theories with these qualities would make perfect sense. Sir Isaac Newton offers
such an ontological rationale for parsimony in the “Principia.” Sir Isaac
writes (in Roman?) “I am to admit no more cause of a natural thing than such as
are true and sufficient to explain its appearance.” “To this purpose, the
philosopher says that Nature does nothing in vain, and more is in vain when
less serves.” “For Nature is pleased with simplicity, and affects not the pomp
of a superfluous cause.” “While a blanket assertion about the simplicity of
Nature is hardly uncommon in the history of science, today it is viewed with
suspicion.” Bontly: “Newton’s reasons
were presumably theological.” “If I knew that the Creator values simplicity and
economy, I should expect the creatION to display these qualities as well.”
“Lacking much information about the Creator’s tastes, however, the assumption
becomes quite difficult, if not impossible, to support.”Cfr. literature on
‘biological diversity.’Bontly: “(Sober discusses several objections to an
ontological justification for the principle of parsimony. Philosopher of science
Mary Hesse surveys several other attempts to justify the use of parsimony and
simplicity in scientific inference. Philosophers of science today are largely
persuaded that the role of parsimony is ‘purely methodological’
epistemological, pragmatist, rather than ontological — that it is rational to
reject unnecessary posits (or complex, dis-unified theories) no matter what
Nature is like. One might argue, for instance, that the principle of parsimony
is really just a principle of minimum risk. The more existence claims one
accepts, the greater the chance of accepting a falsehood. Better, then, to do
without any existence claim one does not need. Philosopher J. J. C. Smart
attributes this view to John Stuart Mill.”Cf. Grice: “Not to bring more Grice
to the Mill.”Bontly: “Now, risk minimization may be a reasonable methodological
principle, but it does not suffice to explain the role of parsimony in natural
science. When a theoretical posit is deemed explanatorily superfluous, the
accepted practice is not merely to withhold belief in its existence but to
conclude positively that it does not exist. As Sober notes, ‘Occam’s razor
preaches atheism about unnecessary entities, not just a-gnosticism.’”
Similarly, Grice’s razor tells us that we should believe an expression E to be
unambiguous, aequi-vocal, monosemous, unless we have evidence for a second
meaning. The absence of evidence for this alleged additional, ‘multiplied’
‘sense’ is presumed to count as evidence that this alleged second, additional,
multiplied, sense is absent, does not exist. But an absence of evidence is not
the same thing as evidence of an absence.” The difficult question about
scientific methodology is why we should count one as the other. Why, that is,
should a lack of evidence for an existence claim count as evidence for a
non-existence claim? The minimum risk argument leaves this question unanswered.
Indeed, philosophers of science have had so little success in explaining why
parsimony should be a guide to truth that many are tempted to conclude that it
and the other ‘super-empirical virtues’ have no epistemic value whatsoever.
Their role is rather pragmatic, or aesthetic.”This is in part Strawson’s reply
in his “If and the horseshoe” (1968), repr. in PGRICE, in Grandy/Warner. He
says words to the effect: “Grice’s theory may be more BEAUTIFUL than mine, but
that’s that!” (Strawson thinks that ‘if’ acts as ‘so’ or ‘therefore’ but in
UNASSERTED clauses. So it’s a matter of a ‘conventional’ IMPLICATURUM to the
inferrability of “if p, q” or “p; so, q.” I agree with Strawson that Grice’s
account of ‘conventional’ implicaturum is not precisely too beautiful?Bontly:
“Parsimony can make a theory easier to understand or apply, and it pleases
those of us with a taste for desert landscapes, but (according to these
sceptics) they do not make the theory any more likely to be true.”The reference
to the ‘desert landscape’ is genial. Cfr. Strawson’s “A logician’s landscape.”
Later in life, Grice indeed found it unfair that an explanation of cherry trees
blooming in spring should be explained as a ‘desert landscape.’ “That’s
impoverishing it!”Bontly: “van Fraassen, for instance, tells us that a
super-empirical virtue ‘does not concern the relation between the theory and
the world, but rather the use and usefulness of the theory; it provide reasons
to prefer the theory independently of questions of truth.” “If that were
correct, it would be doubtful that parsimony can shoulder the burden Grice
places on it.” “For then the conventionalist may happily grant that a pragmatic
explanation is clever and elegant, and beautiful.” “The conventionalist can agree that an implicaturum
account comprehends a maximum of phenomena with a minimum of theoretical
apparatus.” “But when it comes to truth, or alethic satisfactoriness, as Grice
would prefer, a conventionalist may insist that parsimony is simply
irrelevant.” “One Gricean sympathizer who apparently accepts the ‘aesthetic’
view of parsimony is the philosopher of science R. C. S. Walker (1975), who
claims that the ‘[c]hoice between Grice’s and Cohen’s theories is an aesthetic
matter’ and concludes that ‘we should not regard either the Conversationalist
Hypothesis or its [conventionalist] rivals as definitely right or wrong.’” Cfr.
Strawson in Grandy/Warner, but Strawson is no Griceian sympathiser! “Now asking
Grice to justify the principle of parsimony may seem a bit unfair.” “Grice also
assumes the reality of the external world, the existence of intentional mental
states, and the validity of modus ponens.” “Need Grice justify these
assumptions as well?” “Of course not!” “But even if the epistemic value of
parsimony is taken entirely for granted, it is unclear why it should even count
in semantics.” “All sides agree, after all, that many, perhaps even most,
expressions of natural language are allegedly ‘ambiguous.’” “There are both
poly-semies, where one word has multiple, though related, meanings (‘horn’,
‘trunk’), and homo-nymies, where two distinct words have converged on a single
phonological form (‘bat’, ‘pole’).” “The
distinction between poly-semy and homo-nymy is notoriously difficult to draw
with any precision, chiefly because we lack clear criteria for the identity of
words (Bach).” “If words are individuated phono-logically, there would be no
homo-nyms.” “If words are individuated semantically, there would be no
poly-semies.” “Individuating words historically leads to some odd consequences:
e.g., that ‘bank’ is poly-semous rather than homo-nymous, since the ‘sense’ in
which it means financial institution and the ‘sense’ in which it means edge of
a river are derived from a common source.” “I owe this example to David
Sanford. For further discussion, see Jackendoff.”Soon at Hartford. And Sanford
is right!Bontly: “Given that ambiguity is hardly rare, then, one wonders
whether a semantic theory ought really to minimize it (cf. Stampe, 1974).” “One
might indeed argue that the burden of proof here is on the pragmatist, not the
ambiguity or polysemy theorist.” “Perhaps we ought to assume, ceteris paribus,
that every regular use of an expression represents a SPECIAL sense.” “Such a
methodological policy may be less economical than Grice’s, but it does extend
the same pattern of explanation to all alleged ambiguities, and it might even
accord better with the haphazard ways in which natural languages are prone to
evolve (Millikan, 2001).”Yes, the evolutionary is the way to go!Bontly: “So
Grice owe us some reason to think that parsimony and the like should count in
semantics.” “He needn’t claim, of course, that parsimony is always and everywhere
a reason to believe a hypothesis true.” “He needn’t produce a global
justification for Occam’s Razor, that is—a local justification, one specific to
language, would suffice.” “I propose to set aside the larger issue about
parsimony in general, therefore, and argue that Modified Occam’s Razor can be
justified by considerations peculiar to the study of language.” “Now for A
Developmental Account of Semantic Parsimony.”
“My approach to parsimony in linguistics is inspired by Sober’s work on
parsimony arguments in evolutionary biology.”And Grice was an evolutionary
philosopher of sorts.Bontly: “In Sober’s view, philosophers have misunderstood
the role of parsimony in scientific inference, taking it to function as a
global, domain-general principle of scientific reasoning (akin perhaps to an
axiom of the probability calculus).” “A more realistic analysis, Sober claims,
shows that parsimony arguments function as tacit references to domain-specific
process assumptions — to assumptions (whether clearly articulated or not) about
the process(es) that generate the phenomena under study.” “Where these
processes tend to be frugal, parsimony is a reasonable principle of
theory-choice.” “Where they are apt to be profligate, it is not.” “What makes
parsimony reasonable in one area of inquiry may, on Sober’s view, be quite
unrelated to the reasons it counts in another.” “Parsimony arguments in the
units of selection controversy, for instance, rest on one set of process
assumptions (i.e. assumptions about the conditions necessary for ‘group’
selection to occur).” “The application of parsimony to ‘phylogenetic’ inference
rests on a completely different set of assumptions (about rates of evolutionary
change).” “As Sober notes, in either case the assumptions are empirically
testable, and it could turn out that parsimony is a reliable principle of
inference in one, both, or neither of these areas. Sober’s approach amounts to
a thorough-going local reductionism about parsimony.It counts in theory-choice
if and only if there are domain-specific reasons to think the theory which is
more economical (in some specifiable respect) is more likely to be true. The
‘only if’ claim is the more controversial part of the bi-conditional, and I
need not defend it here. For present purposes I need only the weaker claim that
domain-specific assumptions can be sufficient to justify using parsimony — that
parsimony is a sensible principle of inference if the phenomena in question
result from processes themselves biased, as it were, towards parsimony. Now, in
natural-language semantics, the phenomena in question are ordinarily taken to
be the semantic rules or conventions shared by a community of speakers.”Cf.
Peacocke on Grice as applied to ‘community of utterers,’ in Evans/McDowell,
Truth and meaning, Oxford. Bontly: “The task is to uncover the ‘arbitrary’
mappings between a sound and a meaning (or concepts or referent) of which
utterers have tacit knowledge. This ‘semantic competence’ is shaped by both the
inputs that language learners encounter and the cognitive processes that guide
language acquisition from infancy through adulthood. So the question is whether
that input and these processes are themselves biased toward semantic parsimony
and against the acquisition of multiple meanings for single phonological forms.
As I shall now argue, there are several reasons to suspect that such a bias
should exist. Psychologists often conceptualize learning in general and word
learning in particular as a process of generating and testing hypotheses. A
child (or, in many cases, an adult) encounters an unfamiliar word, forms one or
more hypotheses as to its possible meaning, checks the hypotheses against the
ways in which he hears the word used, and finally adopts one such hypothesis.
This ‘child-as-scientist’ model is plainly short on details, but whatever
mechanism implements the generating and testing, it would seem that the process
cannot be repeated with every subsequent exposure to a word. Once a hypothesis
is accepted — a word learned — the process effectively halts, so that the next
time the child hears that word, he doesn’t have to hypothesize. Instead, the
child can access the known meaning and use it to grasp the intended message.
For that reason, an unfamiliar word ought to be the only one to trigger the
learning process, and that of course makes ambiguity problematic. Take a person
who knows one meaning of an ambiguous word, but not the other. To him, the word
is not unfamiliar, even when used with an unfamiliar meaning. At least, it will
not sound unfamiliar. So, the learning process will not kick in unless some
other source of evidence suggests another, as-yet-unknown meaning. Presumably
the evidence will come from ‘anomalous’ utterances: i.e. uses that are
contextually absurd, given only the familiar meaning. This is not to say, of
course, that hearing one anomalous utterance would be sufficient to re-start
the learning process. Since there are other reasons why an utterance may seem
anomalous (e.g. the utterer simply misspoke), it might take several anomalies
to convince one that the word has another meaning. In the absence of anomalies,
however, it seems highly unlikely that learners would seriously entertain the
possibility of a second sense. A related point is that acquisition involves, or
is at least thought to involve, a variety of ‘boot-strapping’ operations where
the learner uses what he knows of the language in order to learn more.”Oddly
Grice has a bootstrap principle (it relates to having one’s metalanguage as
rich as one’s object-language.Bontly: “It has been argued, for instance, that
children use semantic information to constrain hypotheses about words’
syntactic features (Pinker) and, conversely, syntactic information to constrain
hypotheses about words’ semantic features (Gleitman). Likewise, children must
surely use their knowledge of some words’ meanings to constrain hypotheses as
to the meanings of others, thus inferring the meanings of unfamiliar words from
context. However, that process only works insofar as one can safely assume that
the familiar words in an utterance are typically used with their familiar
meanings. If it were assumed that familiar words are typically used with
unknown meanings, the bootstraps would be too weak. Together, these
considerations point to the hypothesis that language acquisition is
semantically conservative. Children will posit new meanings for familiar words
only when necessary—only when they encounter utterances that make no sense to
them, even though all the words are familiar. Interestingly, experimental work
in language acquisition provides empirical evidence for much the same
conclusion. Psychologists have long observed that children have considerable
difficulties learning and using homo-nyms (Peters and Zaidel), leading many to
suspect that young children operate under the helpful, though mistaken,
assumption that a word can have but one meaning (Slobin). Children have similar
difficulties acquiring synonyms and may likewise assume that a given meaning
can be represented by at most one word. (Markman & Wachtel, see Bloom for a
different explanation). I cannot here survey the many experimental studies
bearing on this hypothesis, but one series of experiments conducted by Michele
Mazzocco is particularly germane. Mazzocco presents children from several age-groups,
as well as adults, with stories designed to mimic one’s first encounter with
the secondary meaning of an ambiguous word. To control the effects of
antecedent familiarity with secondary meanings, the stories used familiar words
(e.g., ‘rope’) as if they had further unknown meanings—as
‘pseudo-homo-nyms’.For comparison, other stories included a non-sense word
(e.g. ‘blus’) used as if it had a conventional meaning — as a ‘pseudo-word’ —
to mimic one’s first encounter with an entirely unfamiliar word.”Cf. Grice’s
seminar at Berkeley: “How pirots karulise elatically: some simpler ways.”“A
pirot can be said to potch or cotch an
obble as fang or feng or fid with another obble.”“A person can be said to
perceive or cognize an object as having the property f or f2 or being in a
relation R with another object.”Bontly: Some stories, finally, used only
genuine words with only their familiar meanings. After hearing a story,
subjects are presented with a series of illustrations and asked to pick out the
item referred to in the story. In a subsequent experiment, subjects had to act
out their interpretations of the stories. In the pseudo-homo-nym condition, one
picture would always illustrate the word’s conventional but contextually
inappropriate meaning, one would depict the unfamiliar but contextually
appropriate meaning, and the rest would be distractors. As one would expect,
adults and older children (10- to 12-year-olds) performed equally well on these
tasks, reliably picking out the intended meanings for familiar words, non-sense
words and pseudo-homonyms alike. Young children (3- to 5-year-olds), on the
other hand, could understand the stories where familiar words were used
conventionally, and they were reasonably good at inferring the intended
meanings of non-sense words from context, but they could not do so for
pseudo-homonyms. Instead, they reliably chose the picture illustrating the
familiar meaning, even though the story made that meaning quite inappropriate.
These results are noteworthy for several reasons. It is significant, first of
all, that spontaneous positing of ambiguities did not occur. As long as the
known meaning of a word comported with its use in a story, subjects show not
the slightest tendency to assign that word a new, secondary meaning—just as one
would expect if the acquisition process were semantically conservative. Second,
note that performance in the non-sense word condition confirms the familiar
finding that young children can acquire the meanings of novel words from
context — just as the bootstrapping procedure suggests. Unlike older children
and adults, however, these young children are unable to determine the meanings
of pseudo-homo-nyms from context, even though they could do so for pseudo-words
— exactly what one would expect if young children assumed that words can have
one meaning only. Why young children would have such a conservative bias
remains controversial. Unfortunately it would take us too far afield to delve
into this debate here. Doherty finds evidence that the understanding of
ambiguity is strongly correlated with a grasp of synonymy, suggesting that
these biases have a common source.” Doherty also finds evidence that the
understanding of ambiguity/synonymy is strongly predicted by the ability to
reason about false beliefs, suggesting the intriguing hypothesis that young
children’s biases are due to their lack of a representational ‘theory of
mind’).” Cf. Grice on transmission of
true beliefs in “Meaning, revisited.” – a transcendental argument.Bontly:
“Nonetheless, Mazzocco’s results provide empirical evidence for our conjecture
that a person will typically posit a second meaning for a known word only when
necessary (and, as with young children, not always then). And that, of course,
is precisely the sort of process assumption that would make Grice’s “M. O. R.”
a reasonable principle for theory choice in semantics. For we have been
operating under the assumption that the principal task of linguistic semantics
is to describe the competent speaker’s tacit linguistic knowledge. If that
knowledge is shaped by a process biased toward semantic parsimony, our semantic
theorizing ought surely to be biased in the same direction. Is Pragmatism
Vindicated?” That said, the question is still open whether Grice’s “M. O. R.,”
understood now developmentally, ontogenetically, and not phylogenetically, as
perhaps Millikan would prefer, has such consequences as Gricea typically
assumes. In particular, it remains for us to consider whether and, if so, when
the above process assumptions favor implicaturum hypotheses over ambiguity
hypotheses, and the answer would seem to hang on two further issues. First,
there is in each case the question whether a child learning the language will
find it necessary to posit a second sense for a given expression. The fact that
linguists, apprised as they are of the principles of conversation, find it
unnecessary to introduce a second sense for (e.g.) ‘or’ does NOT imply that
children would find it unnecessary. For one thing, children might acquire the
various uses of ‘or’ well before they have any pragmatic understanding
themselves.”Cfr. You can eat the cake or the sandwich.”Bontly: Even if they do
not, the order in which the various uses are acquired could make considerable
difference.It may be, for instance, that a child who first learned the
inclusive use of ‘or’ would have no need to posit a second exclusive sense,
whereas a child who originally interpreted ‘or’ exclusively might need
eventually to posit an additional, inclusive sense. So we may well have to determine
what meaning children first attach to an expression in order to determine
whether they would find it necessary to posit a second. The issues raised above
are pretty clearly empirical ones, and significant inter-personal differences
could complicate matters considerably. Just for the sake of argument, however,
let us grant that children do indeed first learn to interpret ‘or’ inclusively,
to interpret ‘and’ as mere conjunction, and so on. Let us assume, that is, that
the meanings which Grice typically takes to be conventional are just that. In
fact, the assumption that weak uses are typically learned first has garnered
some empirical support, as one referee brought to my attention. Paris shows
that children are less likely than adults to interpret ‘or’ exclusively (see
also Sternberg, and Braine and Rumain). More recent experimental work indicates
that children first learn to interpret ‘and’ a-temporally (Noveck and Chevaux)
and ‘some’ weakly (as compatible with ‘all’) (Noveck, 2001). Even so, it remains
an interesting question whether children would posit secondary senses for any
of these expressions, and Grice would be on firm ground in arguing that they
would not. First, the ‘ambiguities’ discussed at the outset all involve
secondary uses which can, with the help of pragmatic principles, be understood
in terms of the presumed primary meaning of the expression. If a child,
encountering this secondary use for the first time, already knows the primary
meaning, and if he has moreover an understanding of the norms of
conversation—if he is a ‘Griceian child’ —, he ought to be able to understand
the secondary use perfectly well. He can recover the implicaturum and infer the
speaker’s meaning from the encoded meaning of the utterance. To the ‘Griceian
child,’ therefore, the utterance would not be anomalous. It would make perfect
sense in context, giving him no reason to posit a secondary meaning. But what
about children who are not yet Griceans — children too young to understand
pragmatic principles or to have the conceptual resources to make inferences
about other people’s likely communicative intentions? While there seems to be
no consensus as to when pragmatic abilities emerge, several considerations
suggest that they develop fairly early. Bloom argues that pragmatic
understanding is part of the best account of how children learn the meanings of
words. Papafragou discusses evidence that children can calculate implicaturums
as early as age three. Such children, knowing only the primary meaning of the
expression, would be unable to recover the conversational implicaturum and thus
unable to grasp the secondary use of the expression via the pragmatic route.
Nonetheless, I argue that they would still (at least in most cases) find it
unnecessary to posit a second meaning for the expression. Consider: the
‘ambiguities’ at issue all involve secondary meanings which are specificatory,
being identical to the primary but for some additional feature making it more
restricted or specific. The primary and second meanings would thus be
privative, as opposed to polar, opposites; Zwicky and Sadock). What a speaker
means when he uses the expression in this secondary way, therefore, would
typically imply the proposition he would mean if he were speaking literally
(i.e. if he were using the primary meaning of the expression). One could thus
say something true using the secondary sense only in contexts where one could
say something true using the primary sense—whenever ‘P exclusive-or Q’ is true,
so is ‘P inclusive-or Q’; whenever ‘P and-then Q’ is true, so is ‘P and Q’; and
so on. Thus even when the intended meaning involves the alleged second sense,
the utterance would still come out true if interpreted with the primary sense
in mind. And this means, crucially, that the utterance would not seem
anomalous, there being no obvious clash between the primary interpretation of
the utterance and the conversational context. The utterance may well be
pragmatically inappropriate when interpreted this way, but our pre-Gricean
child is insensitive to such niceties. Otherwise, he would be already a
‘Gricean’ child. On our account, therefore, the pre-Gricean child still sees no
need to posit a second meaning for the expression, even though he could not
grasp the intended (specificatory) meaning. We may illustrate the above with
the help of an ‘ambiguity’ in the indefinite description (“a dog”) made famous
by Grice. A philosopher would ordinarily take an expressions of the form ‘an F’
to be a straightforward existential quantifier, “(Ex)”, as would seem to be the
case in ‘I am going to a meeting’ On the other hand, an utterance of ‘I broke a
finger’ seems to imply that it is my finger which I broke (unless you are a
nurse – I think Horn’s cancellation goes), whereas ‘I saw a dog in the
backyard’ would seem to carry the opposite sort of implication — i.e. that it
was not my dog which I saw.”Grice finds this delightful ‘reductio’ of the
sense-positer: “a” would have _three_ senses!Bontly: “We have then the
potential for a three-way ambiguity, but our ruminations on word learning argue
against it.”Take a child who has learned (somehow) the weak (existential
quantier) use of ‘an F’ (Ex)Fx, but has for some reason never been exposed to
strong uses: ‘my,’ ‘not mine.’ Now the child hears his mother say ‘Come look!
There is a dog in the backyard!’ Running to the window, the child sees not his
mother’s pet dog Fido, but some strange dog, that is not her mother’s. To an
adult, this would be entirely predictable.” Using the indefinite description ‘a
dog’ (logical form, “(Ex)Dx”) instead of the name for the utterer’s dog would
lead one to expect that Fido (the utterer’s dog) is not the dog in
question.”Actually, like Ryle, Grice has a shaggy-dog story in WJ5, “That dog
is hairy-coated.” “Shaggy, if you must!”. Bontly: “And if the child were of an
age to have a rudimentary understanding of the pragmatic aspects of language
use, he would make the same prediction and thus see no need here to posit a
second ‘sense’ for ‘an F,’ and take ‘not mine’ as an implicaturum.”It’s different
with what Grice would have as an ‘established idiom’ (his example, “He’s
pushing up the daisies,” but not “He is fertilizing the daffodils”) as one
might argue that “I broke a finger” is. Bontly: “The child would not, because
the intended, contextually appropriate interpretation would be clear given the
primary meaning plus pragmatics, or implicaturum. But even if the child fails
to grasp the intended meaning of his mother’s remark, it still seems unlikely
that the child would be compelled to posit an ambiguity. No matter what the
child’s mother means, there is, after all, a dog in the backyard (“Gotcha!
That’s _a_ dog, my Fido is, ain’t it?!”). So the primary interpretation still
yields a true proposition. While the ‘pre-Gricean child’ thus misses (part of)
the intended meaning of the utterance, still he would not experience a clash
between his interpretation and the contextually appropriate interpretation.
Perhaps the pre-Gricean child could be forced to see an anomaly. Consider the
following example. A parent offers her pre-Gricean child dessert, saying,
‘Ice-cream, or cake?’ When the child helps himself to some of each, the mother
removes the cake with a look of annoyance and says:‘I said ice-cream OR
cake’. “While the mother’s behavioural
response makes it abundantly clear that the child’s ‘inclusive’ interpretation
is inappropriate, there are several reasons why he might still refrain from
positing an ambiguity. For one, young children, who are more Griceian (even
pre-Griceian) and logical than a few adults, appear to operate under the
assumption that a word can have one meaning only, and it may be that
pre-Gricean children are simply unable to override this assumption. This would
seem particularly likely if Doherty is right that the ability to understand
ambiguity requires a robust ‘theory of mind’.At any rate, the position taken
here is that recognition of anomaly is necessary for one to posit a second
meaning, not that it is sufficient. Contrast this with a similar case where,
coming to the window, the child sees no dog but does see (e.g.) a motorcycle, a
tree, a bird, and a fence.Then he would have reason to consider an ambiguity,
though other explanations might also fit.” “Perhaps Mom was joking or
hallucinating.” The claim is, then, that language acquisition works in such a
way as to make it unlikely that learners would introduce a second senses for
the ‘ambiguities’ in question. Of course, that claim is contingent on a very
large assumption — viz., that the meaning which Grice take to be lexically
‘encoded’ is indeed the primary meaning of the expression — and that assumption
may be mistaken.” In the continuing debate over Donnellan’s
referential/attributive distinction, for instance, Grice takes it as
uncontroversial that Russell on ‘the’ provides at least one of the conventional
interpretations for sentences of the form ‘The king of France is bald’ (i.e.,
the attributive interpretation).” Grice’s example in “Vacuous names,” that
Bontly quotes, is “Jones’s butler mixed
our coats and hats,” when “Jones’s butler” is actually Jones’s haberdasher
dressed as a butler for the occasion.” So Grice distinguishes between THE
butler (identificatory) and ‘the’ butler (non-identificatory, whoever he might
be). Bontly: From there, they argue that we needn’t posit a secondary
(referential) semantics for descriptions since the referential use can be
captured by Russell’s theory supplemented by Grice’s pragmatics. Grice, 1969
(Vacuous Names); Kripke, 1977; Neale, 1990). From a developmental perspective,
however, the ‘uncontroversial’ assumption that Russell on ‘the’ provides the
primary meaning for description phrases is certainly questionable. It being
likely that the vast majority of descriptions children hear early in life are
used referentially, Grice’s position could conceivably have things exactly
backwards— perhaps the referential is primary with the attributive acquired
later, either as an additional meaning or a pragmatic extension. Still, the
fact, if it is a fact, that a referential use is more common in children’s
early environment does not imply that the referential is acquired first.”
Exclusive uses of ‘or’ are at least as frequent as inclusive uses, and yet
there is a good deal of evidence that the inclusive is developmentally primary.
(Paris, Sternberg, Braine and Rumain). Either way, the point remains that
plausible assumptions about language acquisition do indeed justify a role for
parsimony in semantics. These ‘process’ assumptions may, of course, turn out to
be incorrect.” If the evidence points the other way—if it emerges that the
learning process posits ambiguities quite freely—then Grice’s “M. O. R.” could
conceivably be groundless.”Making it a matter of empirical support or lack
thereof, and that was perhaps why Millikan thought that was the wrong way to
go? But then if she thought the evolutionary was the right way to go, wouldn’t
THAT make Grice’s initially ‘sort of’ analytic pragmatist methodological
philosophical decision a matter of fact or lack thereof? Bontly: “Nonetheless,
we can see now that the debate between Grice and the conventionalists is
ultimately an empirical, rather than, as Grice perhaps thougth, a conceptual
one. Choices between pragmatic and semantic accounts may be under-determined by
Grice’s intuitions about meaning and use, but they need not be under-determined
tout court. Then there’s Tradeoffs, Dead Metaphors, and a Dilemma. The
developmental approach to parsimony provides some purchase on the problems
regarding tradeoffs and dead metaphors as well. The former problem is that
parsimony can be a double-edged sword. While an ambiguity account does multiply
senses, the implicaturum account appears to multiply inferential labour.
Hearers have to ‘work out’ or ‘calculate’ the utterer’s meaning from the
conversational principle, without the benefit of a list of possible meanings as
in disambiguation. Pragmatic inference thus seems complex and time-consuming.
But the fact is that we are rarely conscious of engaging in any reasoning of
the sort Grice requires, pace his Principle of Economy of Rational Effort.
Consequently, the claim that communicators actually work through all these
complicated inferences seems psychologically unrealistic. To combat these
charges, Grice’s response is to claim that implicaturum calculation is largely
unconscious and implicit.”Indeed Grice’s principle of economy of rational
effort. Bontly: “Background assumptions can be taken for granted, steps can be
skipped, and only rarely need the entire process breach the surface of consciousness.
This picture seems particularly plausible with a generalised implicaturum as
opposed to a particularized one.” When a particular use of an expression E,
though unconventional, has become standard or regular (“I broke a finger”?
“He’s pushing up the daisies”), the inferential process can be considerably
stream-lined; it gets ‘short-circuited’ or ‘compressed by precedent’ (Bach and
Harnish). “Bach’s and Harnish’s notion of short-circuited inference is similar
to but not quite the same as J. L. Morgan’s notion of short-circuited implicaturum.
The latter involves conventions of use (as Searle would put it), to which Bach
and Harnish see their account as an alternative. Levinson objects to Bach’s and
Harnish’s characterization of default inferences as those compressed by the
weight of precedent. A generalised implicaturum, Levinson says, ‘is generative,
driven by general heuristics and not dependent on routinization’ But Levinson’s
complaint against Bach and Harnish may seem uncharitable. Even on Bach’s and
Harnish’s view, where a default inference is that ‘compressed by the weight of
precedent’, a generalised implicaturum is still generative: it is still
generated by the maxims of conversation. Only the stream-lined character of the
inference is dependent on precedent, not the implicaturum itself. If the
addressee has calculated the EXCLUSIVE meaning of ‘or’ enough times in the past
(from his mother, we’ll assume) it
becomes the default, allowing one to proceed directly to the exclusive
interpretation (unless something about the context provides a clue that the
standard interpretation would here be inappropriate. Now, the idea that the
generalised implicaturum can be the default interpretation, reached without all
the fancy inference, provides an obvious reply to the worry about tradeoffs.
While it is true that a pragmatic inference, as Grice calls it, in contrast
with the ‘logical inference, -- “Retrospective Epilogue” -- are in principle
abductive, fairly complex and potentially laborious, familiarity can simplify
the process enormously, to the point where it becomes no more difficult than
dis-ambiguation.” But the appeal to a default interpretation raises an
interesting difficulty that (to my knowledge) Grice never adequately addressed.
It is now quite unclear why this default interpretation should be considered an
implicaturum rather than an additional sense of the expression.”Because it’s
cancellable?Bontly: “To say that it is a default interpretation is, after all,
to say that utterers and addressees learn to associate that interpretation with
the type of expression in question. The default meaning is known in advance,
and all one has to do is be on the lookout for information that could rule it
out. “‘Short-circuited’ implicaturum-calculation is thus hard to differentiate
from disambiguation, making Grice’s hypothesis look more like a notional
variant than a real competitor to the ambiguity hypothesis. Insofar as Grice
has considered this problem, his answer appears to be that linguistic meanings,
being conventional, are inherently arbitrary.”cf. Bach and Harnish, 1979, pp.
192–195).”Indeed, in his evolutionary take on language, it all starts with
Green’s self-expression. You get hit, and you express pain unvoluntarily. Then
you proceed to simulate the response in absence of the hit, but the meaning is
“I’m in pain.” Finally, you adopt the conventions, arbitrary, and say, ‘pain,’
which is only arbitrarily connected with, well, the pain. It is the last stage
that Grice stresses as ‘artificial,’ and ‘arbitrary,’ “non-iconic,” as he
retorts to Peirceian terminology he was familiar with since his Oxford days.
Bontly: “The exclusive use of ‘or’, on the other hand, is entirely predictable
from the conversational principle, so there is nothing arbitrary about it. Thus
the exclusive interpretation cannot be part of the encoded meaning, even if it
is the default interpretation. Familiarity with that use, in other words, can
remove the need to go through the canonical inference, but it does not change
the fact that the use has a ‘natural’ (i.e., non-conventional, principled,
indeed rational) explanation. It doesn’t change the fact that it is calculable.
At this point, however, Grice’s defense of default pragmatic interpretations
collides with our remaining issue, the problem of a dead metaphor, such as “He
is pushing up the daisies.”” Or as Grice prefers, an ‘established’ or
‘recognised’ ‘idiom.’Bontly: “A metaphor and other conversational implicatura
can become conventionalized and ‘die’, turning into new senses. In many such
cases the original rationale for the use is long forgotten, but in other cases
the dead metaphor remains calculable. A dead metaphors thus pose a nasty,
macabre?, dilemma for Grice.”Especially if the implicaturum is “He is
dead”!Bontly: “On the one hand, it is tempting to argue that a dead metaphor
involves a new conventional meaning precisely because the interpretation in
question is no longer actually inferred via Gricean inferences (though one
could do so if one had to—if, say, one somehow forgot that the expression had
this secondary meaning). If a conversational implicaturum had to be not just
calculaBLE but actually calculatED, that would suffice to explain why this
one-time, one-off, implicaturum is now semantically significant. But that reply
is apparently closed to pragmatists, for then it will be said that the same is
true of (e.g.) the exclusive use of ‘or.’ The exclusive interpretation is
certainly calculabLE, but since no one actually calculatES it (except in the
most unusual of circumstances, as Grice at Harvard!), the implication should be
considered semantic, not pragmatic. On the other hand, Grice might maintain
that an implicaturum need only be calculabLE and stick by their view that the
exclusive reading of ‘or’ is conversationally implicated. But then we shall
have to face the consequence that many a dead metaphor (“He is pushing up the
daisies”) is likewise calculabLE and thus, according to the present view, ought
not to be considered conventional meanings of the expressions in question,
which in most cases seems quite wrong.”I’m never sure what Grice means by an
‘established idiom.’ Established by whom? Perhaps he SHOULD consult the
dictionary every now and then! Sad the access to OED3 is so expensive!Bontly:
What one needs, evidently, is some reason to treat these two types of cases
differently.To treat the exclusive use of ‘or’ as an implicaturum (even though
it is only rarely calculatED as such) while at the same time to view (e.g.) the
once metaphorical use of ‘incense’ (or ‘… pushing up the daisies”) as
semantically significant (even though it remains calculabLE).” And the
developmental account of parsimony offers just such a reason. On the present
view, the reason that the ambiguity account has the burden of proof has to do
with the nature of the acquisition, learning, ontogenetical process and
specifically with the presumption that language learners will avoid postulating
unnecessary senses. But the implicaturum must be calculable by the learner,
given his prior understanding of the expression E and his level of pragmatic
sophistication.”Grice was a sophisticated. As I think Dora B.-O knows, Moore
has been claiming that Grice’s idea that animals cannot mean, because they are
not ‘sophisticated’ enough, is an empirical claim, even for Grice!Bontly: “t
may be, therefore, that children at the relevant developmental stage have no
difficulty understanding the exclusive use of ‘or’ (etc.) as an implicaturum
and yet lack the understanding necessary to predict that ‘incense’ could be
used to mean to make or become angry, or that to say of someone that he ‘is
pushing up the daisies,’ means that, having died and getting buried, the corpse
is helping the flowers to grow. The child might not realize, for instance, that
‘incense’ also means an aromatic substance that burns with a pleasant odour,
and even those who do probably lack the general background knowledge necessary
to appreciate the metaphorical connections between burning and emotion.”Cf.
Turner and Fauconnier on ‘blends.’Bontly: Either way, the metaphor would be
dead to the child, forcing him to learn that use the same way they learn any
arbitrary convention.”It may do to explore ‘established idioms’ in, say, parts
of England, which are not so ‘established’ in OTHER parts. Nancy Mitford with
his U and non-U distinction may do. “He went to Haddon Hall” invites, for
Mitford, the ‘unintended’ implicaturum that the utterer is NOT upper-class.
“Surely we drop “hall.’ What else can Haddon be?” But the inference may be
lacking for a non-U addressee or utterer. Similarly, in the north of England,
“our Mary,” invites the implicaturum of ‘affection,’ and this may go over the
head of members of the south-of-England community.Bontly: “The way out of the
dilemma, then, is to look to learning.”Alla Kripkenstein?Bontly: To the problem
of tradeoffs, Grice can reply that it is better to multiply (if we must use the
Occamist verb) inferences – logical inference and pragmatic inference -- than
multiply senses because language acquisition is biased in that direction. And
Grice may likewise answer the problem of a dead metaphor, or established idiom
like, “He’s been pushing up the daisies for some time, now. The reason that
Grice’s “M. O. R.” does not mandate an implicaturum account for Grice as well
is that such a dead metaphor or established idiom is not calculable by children
at the time they learn such expressions, even if they are calculable by some
adult speakers.”Is that a fact? I would think that a child is a ‘relentless
literalist,’ as Grice called Austin. “Pushing up the daisies?” “I don’t see any
daisies!”I think Brigitte Nerlich has a similar example re: irony: MOTHER: What
a BEAUTIFUL day! (ironically)CHILD: What do you mean? It’s pouring and nasty. MOTHER:
I was being ironic.I don’t think the child is going to posit a second sense to
‘beautiful’ meaning ‘nasty.’Bontly: “For the deciding question in applying
Grice’s “M. O. R.” is NOT whether the implicaturum account is available to a
philosopher like Grice, but whether it is available to the learner! On this way
of carving things up, by the way, some alleged ambiguities which Grice would
treat as implicatura could turn out to be semantically significant after all.
Likewise, some allegedly dead metaphor may turn out to be very much alive.”
Look! He did kick the bucket!” “But he’s PRETENDING to die, dear! Some uses,
finally, may vary from utterer to utterer, there being no guarantee that every
utterer will have learned the use in the same way. As a conclusion, a better
understanding of developmental processes might therefore enlarge our
appreciation of the ways in which semantics and pragmatics
interact.”Indeed.REFERENCES Atlas, J. D. “Philosophy without Ambiguity.”
Oxford: Clarendon Press. E: Wolfson, Oxford. Philosopher. And S. Levinson,
“It-clefts, informativeness, and logical form: Radical pragmatics (revised
standard version),” in P. Cole (ed.), Radical Pragmatics. New York: Academic
Press.Bach, K. “Thought and Reference,” Oxford.“Conversational impliciture,”
Mind & Language, 9And R. Harnish, “Linguistic Communication and Speech
Acts,” Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bloom, P. “How Children Learn the Meanings of
Words,” Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
“Mind-reading, communication and the learning of names for things,” Mind
& Language, 17Braine, M. and Rumain, B. “Development of comprehension of
‘or’: evidence for a sequence of developmental competencies,” Journal of Experimental
Child Psychology, 31. Davis, S. (ed.) “Pragmatics: A Reader,” Oxford Devitt, M.
“The case for referential descriptions,” in M. Reimer/A. Bezuidenhout,
“Descriptions and Beyond,” Oxford Doherty, M. “Children’s understanding of
homonymy: meta-linguistic awareness and false belief,” Journal of Child
Language, 27 Gazdar, G. “Pragmatics: Implicaturum, Presupposition, and Logical
Form,” New York: Academic Press. Gleitman, L. “The structural sources of verb
meanings,” Language Acquisition, 1Grice, H. P. “Vacuous names,” in D. Davidson
and J. Hintikka, Words and Objections. Dordrecht: Reidel. Repr. in part in
Ostertag, “Definite descriptions,” MIT.Logic and Conversation. In P. Cole and
J. Morgan (eds.), Syntax and Semantics, vol. 3, Speech Acts. New York: Academic
Press, pp. 41–58. Reprinted in Grice, 1989, and Davis, 1991. Grice, P. 1978:
Further notes on logic and conversation. In P. Cole (ed.), Syntax and
Semantics, vol. 9, Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press, pp. 113–128. Reprinted
in Grice, 1989. Presupposition and conversational implicaturum. In P. Cole
(ed.), Radical Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press, 183–198. Reprinted in
Grice, 1989. Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press. Hesse, M. “Simplicity,” in P. Edwards (ed.), The Encyclopedia of
Philosophy. New York: MacMillan.Jackendoff, R. “Foundations of Language: Brain,
Meaning, Grammar, Evolution,” Oxford. Kripke, S. “Speaker’s reference and
semantic reference,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Repr. in Davis, 1991.
Levinson, S. “Pragmatics,” Cambridge.“Presumptive Meanings: The Theory of
Generalized Conversational Implicaturum,” Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Markman,
E./G. Wachtel, “Childrens’ use of mutual exclusivity to constrain the meaning
of words,” Cognitive Psychology, 20Mazzocco, M. “Children’s interpretations of
homonyms: A developmental study,” Journal of Child Language, 24Morgan, J. L.
“Two types of convention in indirect speech acts,” n P. Cole (ed.): Syntax and
Semantics, vol. 9, Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press, reprinted in Davis,
1991. Newton, I. “Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy,” A. Motte
(trans.) and F. Cajori (rev.). Repr. in R. Hutchins (ed.), Great Books of the
Western World, vol. 34. Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc., 1952. Noveck,
I. When children are more logical than adults are: Experimental investigations of
scalar implicaturum, Cognition, 78, 165–188. And F. Chevaux, “The pragmatic
development of and. In A. Ho, S. Fish, and B. Skarabela, Proceedings of the
26th Annual Boston University Conference on Language Development. Somerville,
MA: Cascadilla Press.Papafragou, A. “Mind-reading and verbal communication,”
Mind & Language, 17Paris, S. “Comprehension of language connectives and
propositional logical relationships,” Journal of Experimental Child Psychology,
16.Peters, A./E. Zaidel, “The acquisition of homonymy. Cognition, 8.Pinker, S.
“Language Learnability and Language Development,” Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press. Reimer, M. “Donnellan’s distinction/Kripke’s test.” Analysis,
58.Ruhl, C. “On Monosemy: A Study in Linguistic Semantics,” Albany, NY: SUNY
Press. Sadock, J. “On testing for conversational implicaturum,” in P. Cole
(ed.), Syntax and Semantics, vol. 9, Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press,
Repr. in Davis, 1991. Searle, J. R. “Indirect speech acts,” n P. Cole and J.
Morgan, Syntax and Semantics, vol. 3, Speech Acts. New York: Academic Press,
Repr. in Davis, 1991. Slobin, D. “Crosslinguistic evidence for a
language-making capacity,” n D. Slobin, The Cross-linguistic Study of Language
Acquisition, vol. 2. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Smart, J. “Ockham’s razor,” in J.
Fetzer, “Principles of Philosophical Reasoning,” Totowa, NJ: Rowan and
Allanheld. Sober, E. “The principle of parsimony,” The British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science, 32“Reconstructing the Past,” Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.“Let’s razor Ockham’s razor,” in D. Knowles, Explanation and Its Limits.
Cambridge.Stalnaker, R. C. “Pragmatic presupposition,” in M. Munitz/P. Unger,
“Semantics and Philosophy,” New York: Academic Press, pp. 197–213. Repr. in
Davis, 1991. Stampe, D. W. “Attributives and interrogatives,” in M. Munitz/P.
Unger, Semantics and Philosophy. New York: Academic Press.Sternberg, R.
“Developmental patterns in the encoding and combination of logical
connectives,” Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 28 Van Fraassen, B. “The
Scientific Image,” Oxford.Walker, R. C. S. “Conversational implicaturums: a
reply to Cohen,” in S. W. Blackburn, Meaning, Reference, and Necessity.
Cambridge. Ziff, P. “Semantic Analysis.” Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Zwicky, A./J. Sadock, “Ambiguity tests and how to fail them,” in J. Kimball,
Syntax and Semantics, vol. 4. New York: Academic Press.Refs: The Grice Papers, BANC, Bancroft.
modus: Grice was an expert on mode. There is one mode too many.
If Grice found ‘senses’ obsolete (“Sense are not to be multiplied beyond
necessity”), he was always ready to welcome a new mode – e. g. the quessertive
--. or mode. ἔγκλισις , enclisis, mood of a verb, D.H.Comp.6, D.T.638.7, A.D. Synt.248.14,
etc.Many times, under ‘mode,’ Grice describes what others call ‘aspect.’ Surely
‘tense’ did not affect him much, except when it concerned “=”. But when it came
to modes, he included ‘aspect,’ so there’s the optative, the imperative, the
indicative, the informational, and then the future intentional and the future
indicative, and the subjunctive, and the way they interact with the praesens,
praeteritum and futurum, and wih the axis of what Aristotle called ‘teleios’
and ‘ateleios,’ indefinite and definite, or ‘perfectum, and ‘imperfectum, ‘but
better ‘definitum’ and ‘indefinitum.’ Grice
uses psi-asrisk, to be read asterisk-sub-psi. He is not concerned with
specficics. All the specifics the philosopher can take or rather ‘assume’ as
‘given.’ The category of mode translates ‘tropos,’ modus. Kant wrongly assumed
it was Modalitat, which irritated Grice so much that he echoed Kant as saying
‘manner’! Grice is a modista. He sometimes uses ‘modus,’ after Abbott. The
earliest record is of course “Meaning.” After elucidating what he calls
‘informative cases,’ he moves to ‘imperative’ ones. Grice agreed with Thomas
Urquhart that English needed a few more moods! Grice’s seven
modes.Thirteenthly, In lieu of six moods which other languages have at most,
this one injoyeth seven in its conjugable words. Ayer had said that
non-indicative utterances are hardly significant. Grice had been freely using
the very English not Latinate ‘mood’ until Moravcsik, of all people, corrects
him: What you mean ain’t a mood. I shall call it mode just to please
you, J. M. E. The sergeant is to muster the men at dawn is a perfect
imperative. They shall not pass is a perfect intentional. A version of this
essay was presented in a conference whose proceedings were published, except
for Grices essay, due to technical complications, viz. his idiosyncratic use of
idiosyncratic symbology! By mode Grice means indicative or imperative.
Following Davidson, Grice attaches probability to the indicative, via the
doxastic, and desirability to the indicative, via the
buletic-boulomaic. He also allows for mixed utterances. Probability
is qualified with a suboperator indicating a degree d; ditto for desirability,
degree d. In some of the drafts, Grice kept using mode until Moravsik suggested
to him that mode was a better choice, seeing that Grices modality had little to
do with what other authors were referring to as mood. Probability,
desirability, and modality, modality, desirability, and probability; modality,
probability, desirability. He would use mode operator. Modality is the
more correct term, for things like should, ought, and must, in that order. One
sense. The doxastic modals are correlated to probability. The buletic or
boulomaic modals are correlated to desirability. There is probability to a
degree d. But there is also desirability to a degree d. They
both combine in Grices attempt to show how Kants categorical imperative reduces
to the hypothetical or suppositional. Kant uses modality in a way that Grice
disfavours, preferring modus. Grice is aware of the use by Kant of
modality qua category in the reduction by Kant to four of the original ten
categories in Aristotle). The Jeffrey-style entitled Probability, desirability,
and mode operators finds Grice at his formal-dress best. It predates the Kant
lectures and it got into so much detail that Grice had to leave it at that. So
abstract it hurts. Going further than Davidson, Grice argues that structures
expressing probability and desirability are not merely analogous. They can both
be replaced by more complex structures containing a common element.
Generalising over attitudes using the symbol ψ, which he had used before, repr.
WoW:v, Grice proposes G ψ that p. Further, Grice uses i as a dummy for
sub-divisions of psychological attitudes. Grice uses Op supra i sub α, read:
operation supra i sub alpha, as Grice was fastidious enough to provide reading
versions for these, and where α is a dummy taking the place of either A or B,
i. e. Davidsons prima facie or desirably, and probably. In all this, Grice
keeps using the primitive !, where a more detailed symbolism would have it
correspond exactly to Freges composite turnstile (horizontal stroke of thought
and vertical stroke of assertoric force, Urteilstrich) that Grice of course
also uses, and for which it is proposed, then: !─p. There are generalising
movements here but also merely specificatory ones. α is not generalised.
α is a dummy to serve as a blanket for this or that specifications. On the
other hand, ψ is indeed generalised. As for i, is it generalising or
specificatory? i is a dummy for specifications, so it is not really generalising.
But Grice generalises over specifications. Grice wants to find buletic,
boulomaic or volitive as he prefers when he does not prefer the Greek root for
both his protreptic and exhibitive versions (operator supra exhibitive,
autophoric, and operator supra protreptic, or hetero-phoric). Note that Grice
(WoW:110) uses the asterisk * as a dummy for either assertoric, i.e., Freges
turnstile, and non-assertoric, the !─ the imperative turnstile, if you wish.
The operators A are not mode operators; they are such that they represent some
degree (d) or measure of acceptability or justification. Grice prefers
acceptability because it connects with accepting that which is a psychological,
souly attitude, if a general one. Thus, Grice wants to have It is desirable
that p and It is believable that p as understood, each, by the
concatenation of three elements. The first element is the A-type operator. The
second element is the protreptic-type operator. The third element is the
phrastic, root, content, or proposition itself. It is desirable that p and It
is believable that p share the utterer-oriented-type operator and the
neustic or proposition. They only differ at the protreptic-type operator
(buletic/volitive/boulomaic or judicative/doxastic). Grice uses + for concatenation,
but it is best to use ^, just to echo who knows who. Grice speaks in that mimeo
(which he delivers in Texas, and is known as Grices Performadillo talk ‒
Armadillo + Performative) of various things. Grice speaks, transparently
enough, of acceptance: V-acceptance and J-acceptance. V not for Victory but for
volitional, and J for judicative. The fact that both end with -acceptance would
accept you to believe that both are forms of acceptance. Grice irritatingly
uses 1 to mean the doxastic, and 2 to mean the bulematic. At Princeton in
Method, he defines the doxastic in terms of the buletic and cares to do
otherwise, i. e. define the buletic in terms of the doxastic. So whenever he
wrote buletic read doxastic, and vice versa. One may omits this arithmetic when
reporting on Grices use. Grice uses two further numerals, though: 3 and 4.
These, one may decipher – one finds oneself as an archeologist in Tutankamons
burial ground, as this or that relexive attitude. Thus, 3, i. e. ψ3, where
we need the general operator ψ, not just specificatory dummy, but the idea that
we accept something simpliciter. ψ3 stands for the attitude of buletically
accepting an or utterance: doxastically accepting that p or doxastically
accepting that ~p. Why we should be concerned with ~p is something to
consider. G wants to decide whether to believe p or not. I find that very
Griceian. Suppose I am told that there is a volcano in Iceland. Why would I not
want to believe it? It seems that one may want to decide whether to believe p
or not when p involves a tacit appeal to value. But, as Grice notes, even when
it does not involve value, Grice still needs trust and volition to reign
supreme. On the other hand, theres 4, as attached to an attitude, ψ4. This
stands for an attitude of buletically accepting an or utterance: buletically
accepting that p, or G buletically accepting that ~p, i. e. G wants to decide
whether to will, now that p or not. This indeed is crucial, since, for Grice,
morality, as with Kantotle, does cash in desire, the buletic. Grice smokes. He
wills to smoke. But does he will to will to smoke? Possibly yes. Does he will
to will to will to smoke? Regardless of what Grice wills, one may claim this
holds for a serious imperatives (not Thou shalt not reek, but Thou shalt not
kill, say) or for any p if you must (because if you know that p causes cancer
(p stands for a proposition involving cigarette) you should know you are
killing yourself. But then time also kills, so what gives? So I would submit
that, for Kant, the categoric imperative is one which allows for an indefinite
chain, not of chain-smokers, but of good-willers. If, for some p, we find that
at some stage, the P does not will that he wills that he wills that he wills
that, p can not be universalisable. This is proposed in an essay referred to in
The Philosophers Index but Marlboro Cigarettes took no notice. One may go on to
note Grices obsession on make believe. If I say, I utter expression e because
the utterer wants his addressee to believe that the utterer believes that p,
there is utterer and addresse, i. e. there are two people here ‒ or
any soul-endowed creature ‒ for Grices squarrel means things to Grice. It
even implicates. It miaows to me while I was in bed. He utters miaow. He means
that he is hungry, he means (via implicaturum) that he wants a nut (as provided
by me). On another occasion he miaowes explicating, The door is closed, and
implicating Open it, idiot. On the other hand, an Andy-Capps cartoon read: When
budgies get sarcastic Wild-life programmes are repeating One may note
that one can want some other person to hold an attitude. Grice uses U or
G1 for utterer and A or G2 for addressee. These are merely roles. The important
formalism is indeed G1 and G2. G1 is a Griceish utterer-person; G2 is the other
person, G1s addressee. Grice dislikes a menage a trois, apparently, for he
seldom symbolises a third party, G3. So, G ψ-3-A that p is 1 just in case G
ψ2(G ψ1 that p) or G ψ1 that ~p is 1. And here the utterers addressee, G2
features: G1 ψ³ protreptically that p is 1 just in case G buletically
accepts ψ² (G buletically accepts ψ² (G doxastically accepts ψ1 that p, or G
doxastically accepts ψ1 that ~p))) is 1. Grice seems to be happy with having
reached four sets of operators, corresponding to four sets of propositional
attitudes, and for which Grice provides the paraphrases. The first set is the
doxastic proper. It is what Grice has as doxastic,and which is, strictly,
either indicative, of the utterers doxastic, exhibitive state, as it were, or
properly informative, if addressed to the addressee A, which is different from
U himself, for surely one rarely informs oneself. The second is the buletic
proper. What Grice dubs volitive, but sometimes he prefers the Grecian root.
This is again either self- or utterer-addressed, or utterer-oriented, or
auto-phoric, and it is intentional, or it is other-addressed, or
addressee-addressed, or addressee- oriented, or hetero-phoric, and it is
imperative, for surely one may not always say to oneself, Dont smoke, idiot!.
The third is the doxastic-interrogative, or doxastic-erotetic. One may expand
on ? here is minimal compared to the vagaries of what I called the !─
(non-doxastic or buletic turnstile), and which may be symbolised by ?─p, where
?─ stands for the erotetic turnstile. Geachs and Althams erotetic somehow Grice
ignores, as he more often uses the Latinate interrogative. Lewis and Short have
“interrŏgātĭo,” which they render as “a questioning, inquiry, examination,
interrogation;” “sententia per interrogationem, Quint. 8, 5, 5; instare
interrogation; testium; insidiosa; litteris inclusæ; verbis obligatio fit ex
interrogatione et responsione; as rhet. fig., Quint. 9, 2, 15; 9, 3, 98. B. A
syllogism: recte genus hoc interrogationis ignavum ac iners nominatum est, Cic.
Fat. 13; Sen. Ep. 87 med. Surely more people know what interrogative means
what erotetic means, he would not say ‒ but he would. This attitude comes again
in two varieties: self-addressed or utterer-oriented, reflective (Should I go?)
or again, addresee-addressed, or addressee-oriented, imperative, as in Should
you go?, with a strong hint that the utterer is expecting is addressee to make
up his mind in the proceeding, not just inform the utterer. Last but not least,
there is the fourth kind, the buletic-cum-erotetic. Here again, there is one
varietiy which is reflective, autophoric, as Grice prefers,
utterer-addressed, or utterer-oriented, or inquisitive (for which Ill think of
a Greek pantomime), or addressee-addressed, or addressee-oriented. Grice regrets
that Greek (and Latin, of which he had less ‒ cfr. Shakespeare who had none)
fares better in this respect the Oxonian that would please Austen, if not
Austin, or Maucalay, and certainly not Urquhart -- his language has twelve
parts of speech: each declinable in eleven cases, four numbers, eleven genders
(including god, goddess, man, woman, animal, etc.); and conjugable in eleven
tenses, seven moods, and four voices.These vocal mannerisms will result in the
production of some pretty barbarous English sentences; but we must remember
that what I shall be trying to do, in uttering such sentences, will be to
represent supposedly underlying structure; if that is ones aim, one can hardly
expect that ones speech-forms will be such as to excite the approval of, let us
say, Jane Austen or Lord Macaulay. Cf. the quessertive, or quessertion,
possibly iterable, that Grice cherished. But then you cant have everything.
Where would you put it? Grice: The
modal implicaturum. Grice sees two different, though connected questions
about mode. First, there is the obvious demand for a characterisation, or
partial characterisation, of this or that mode as it emerges in this or that
conversational move, which is plausible to regard as modes primary habitat)
both at the level of the explicatum or the implicaturum, for surely an
indicative conversational move may be the vehicle of an imperatival
implicaturum. A second, question is how, and to what extent, the representation
of mode (Hares neustic) which is suitable for application to this or that
conversational move may be legitimately exported into philosophical psychology,
or rather, may be grounded on questions of philosophical psychology, matters of
this or that psychological state, stance, or attitude (notably desire and
belief, and their species). We need to consider the second question, the
philosophico- psychological question, since, if the general rationality
operator is to read as something like acceptability, as in U accepts, or A
accepts, the appearance of this or that mode within its scope of accepting is
proper only if it may properly occur within the scope of a generic
psychological verb I accept that . Lewis and Short have “accepto,” “v.
freq. a. accipio,” which Short and Lewis render as “to take, receive, accept,”
“argentum,” Plaut. Ps. 2, 2, 32; so Quint. 12, 7, 9; Curt. 4, 6, 5; Dig. 34, 1,
9: “jugum,” to submit to, Sil. Ital. 7, 41. But in Plin. 36, 25, 64, the
correct read. is coeptavere; v. Sillig. a. h. l. The easiest way Grice finds to
expound his ideas on the first question is by reference to a schematic table or
diagram (Some have complained that I seldom use a board, but I will
today. Grice at this point reiterates his temporary contempt for
the use/mention distinction, which which Strawson is obsessed. Perhaps Grices
contempt is due to Strawsons obsession. Grices exposition would make the hair
stand on end in the soul of a person especially sensitive in this area. And Im
talking to you, Sir Peter! (He is on the second row). But Grices
guess is that the only historical philosophical mistake properly attributable
to use/mention confusion is Russells argument against Frege in On denoting, and
that there is virtually always an acceptable way of eliminating disregard of
the use-mention distinction in a particular case, though the substitutes are
usually lengthy, obscure, and tedious. Grice makes three initial
assumptions. He avails himself of two species of acceptance, Namesly,
volitive acceptance and judicative acceptance, which he, on occasion, calls
respectively willing that p and willing that p. These are to be
thought of as technical or semi-technical, theoretical or semi-theoretical,
though each is a state which approximates to what we vulgarly call thinking
that p and wanting that p, especially in the way in which we can speak of a
beast such as a little squarrel as thinking or wanting something ‒ a
nut, poor darling little thing. Grice here treats each will and judge (and
accept) as a primitive. The proper interpretation would be determined by
the role of each in a folk-psychological theory (or sequence of
folk-psychological theories), of the type the Wilde reader in mental philosophy
favours at Oxford, designed to account for the behaviours of members of the
animal kingdom, at different levels of psychological complexity (some classes
of creatures being more complex than others, of course). As Grice suggests in
Us meaning, sentence-meaning, and word-meaning, at least at the point at which
(Schema Of Procedure-Specifiers For Mood-Operators) in ones syntactico-semantical
theory of Pirotese or Griceish, one is introducing this or that mode (and
possibly earlier), the proper form to use is a specifier for this or that
resultant procedure. Such a specifier is of the general form, For the
utterer U to utter x if C, where the blank is replaced by the appropriate
condition. Since in the preceding scheme x represents an utterance or
expression, and not a sentence or open sentence, there is no guarantee that
this or that actual sentence in Pirotese or Griceish contains a perspicuous and
unambiguous modal representation. A sentence may correspond to more than
one modal structure. The sentence is structurally ambiguous
(multiplex in meaning ‒ under the proviso that senses are not to be
multiplied beyond necessity) and will have more than one reading, or parsing,
as every schoolboy at Clifton knows when translating viva voce from Greek or
Latin, as the case might be. The general form of a procedure-specifier for a
modal operator involves a main clause and an antecedent clause, which follows
if. In the schematic representation of the main clause, U represents an
utterer, A his addressee, p the radix or neustic; and Opi represents that
operator whose number is i (1, 2, 3, or 4), e.g g., Op3A represents
Operator 3A, which, since ?⊢ appears in the Operator column for 3A)
would be ?A ⊢ p. This
reminds one of Grandys quessertions, for he did think they were iterable
(possibly)). The antecedent clause consists of a sequence whose elements
are a preamble, as it were, or preface, or prefix, a supplement to a
differential (which is present only in a B-type, or addressee-oriented case), a
differential, and a radix. The preamble, which is always present, is
invariant, and reads: The U U wills (that) A A judges (that) U (For surely meaning is a species of intending
is a species of willing that, alla Prichard, Whites professor,
Corpus). The supplement, if present, is also invariant. And the idea
behind its varying presence or absence is connected, in the first instance,
with the volitive mode. The difference between an ordinary expression of
intention ‒ such as I shall not fail, or They shall not
pass ‒ and an ordinary imperative (Like Be a little kinder to
him) is accommodated by treating each as a sub-mode of the volitive mode,
relates to willing that p) In the intentional case (I shall not fail), the
utterer U is concerned to reveal to his addressee A that he (the utterer U)
wills that p. In the imperative case (They shall not pass), the utterer U is
concerned to reveal to his addressee A that the utterer U wills that the
addresee A will that p. In each case, of course, it is to be
presumed that willing that p will have its standard outcome, viz., the
actualization, or realisation, or direction of fit, of the radix (from expression
to world, downwards). There is a corresponding distinction between two uses of
an indicative. The utterer U may be declaring or affirming that p, in
an exhibitive way, with the primary intention to get his addressee A to judge
that the utterer judges that p. Or the U is telling (in a protreptic way)
ones addressee that p, that is to say, hoping to get his addressee to
judge that p. In the case of an indicative, unlike that of a volitive, there is
no explicit pair of devices which would ordinarily be thought of as sub-mode
marker. The recognition of the sub-mode is implicated, and comes from
context, from the vocative use of the Names of the addressee, from the presence
of a speech-act verb, or from a sentence-adverbial phrase (like for your
information, so that you know, etc.). But Grice has already, in his
initial assumptions, allowed for such a situation. The
exhibitive-protreptic distinction or autophoric-heterophoric distinction, seems
to Grice to be also discernible in the interrogative mode (?). Each differentials
is associated with, and serve to distinguish, each of the two basic modes
(volitive or judicative) and, apart from one detail in the case of the
interrogative mode, is invariant between autophoric-exhibitive) and
heterophoric-protreptic sub-modes of any of the two basic modes. They are
merely unsupplemented or supplemented, the former for an exhibitive sub-mode
and the latter for a protreptic sub-mode. The radix needs (one hopes) no
further explanation, except that it might be useful to bear in mind that Grice
does not stipulated that the radix for an intentional (buletic exhibitive
utterer-based) incorporate a reference to the utterer, or be in the first
person, nor that the radix for an imperative (buletic protreptic
addressee-based) incorporate a reference of the addresee, and be in the second
person. They shall not pass is a legitimate intentional, as is You shall
not get away with it; and The sergeant is to muster the men at dawn, as uttered
said by the captain to the lieutenant) is a perfectly good imperative. Grice
gives in full the two specifiers derived from the schema. U to utter to A
autophoric-exhibitive ⊢ p if U
wills that A judges that U judges p. Again, U to utter to A !
heterophoric-protreptic p if U wills that A A judges that U wills that A wills
that p. Since, of the states denoted by each differential, only willing
that p and judging that p are strictly cases of accepting that p, and Grices
ultimate purpose of his introducing this characterization of mode is to reach a
general account of expressions which are to be conjoined, according to his
proposal, with an acceptability operator, the first two numbered rows of the
figure are (at most) what he has a direct use for. But since it is of some
importance to Grice that his treatment of mode should be (and should be
thought to be) on the right lines, he adds a partial account of the
interrogative mode. There are two varieties of interrogatives, a yes/no
interrogatives (e. g. Is his face clean? Is the king of France bald? Is virtue
a fire-shovel?) and x-interrogatives, on which Grice qua philosopher was
particularly interested, v. his The that and the why. (Who killed Cock
Robin?, Where has my beloved gone?, How did he fix it?). The specifiers
derivable from the schema provide only for yes/no interrogatives, though the
figure could be quite easily amended so as to yield a restricted but very large
class of x-interrogatives. Grice indicates how this could be
done. The distinction between a buletic and a doxastic interrogative
corresponds with the difference between a case in which the utterer U indicates
that he is, in one way or another, concerned to obtain information (Is he at
home?), and a case in which the utterer U indicates that he is concerned to
settle a problem about what he is to do ‒ Am I to leave the door open?, Shall I
go on reading? or, with an heterophoric Subjects, Is the prisoner to be
released? This difference is fairly well represented in grammar, and much
better represented in the grammars of some other languages. The hetero-phoric-cum-protreptic/auto-phoric-cum-
exhibitive difference may not marked at all in this or that grammar, but
it should be marked in Pirotese. This or that sub-mode is, however, often quite
easily detectable. There is usually a recognizable difference between a
case in which the utterer A says, musingly or reflectively, Is he to be
trusted? ‒ a case in which the utterer might say that he is just
wondering ‒ and a case in which he utters a token of the same
sentence as an enquiry. Similarly, one can usually tell whether an utterer A
who utters Shall I accept the invitation? is just trying to make up his
mind, or is trying to get advice or instruction from his addressee. The
employment of the variable α needs to be explained. Grice borrows a little
from an obscure branch of logic, once (but maybe no longer) practised, called,
Grice thinks, proto-thetic ‒ Why? Because it deals with this or that first
principle or axiom, or thesis), the main rite in which is to quantify over, or
through, this or that connective. α is to have as its two substituents
positively and negatively, which may modify either will or judge, negatively
willing or negatively judging that p is judging or willing that ~p. The
quantifier (∃1α) . . . has to
be treated substitutionally. If, for example, I ask someone whether John
killed Cock Robin (protreptic case), I do not want the addressee merely to will
that I have a particular logical quality in mind which I believe to apply. I
want the addressee to have one of the Qualities in mind which he wants me to
believe to apply. To meet this demand, supplementation must drag back the
quantifier. To extend the schema so as to provide specifiers for a single
x-interrogative (i. e., a question like What did the butler see? rather than a
question like Who went where with whom at 4 oclock yesterday afternoon?),
we need just a little extra apparatus. We need to be able to superscribe a
W in each interrogative operator e.g., together with the proviso that a radix
which follows a superscribed operator must be an open radix, which contains one
or more occurrences of just one free variable. And we need a chameleon
variable λ, to occur only in this or that quantifier. (∃λ).Fx is to be regarded as a way of
writing (∃x)Fx. (∃λ)Fy is a way of writing (∃y)Fy. To provide a specifier for a
x-superscribed operator, we simply delete the appearances of α in the specifier
for the corresponding un-superscribed operator, inserting instead the
quantifier (∃1λ) () at the
position previously occupied by (∃1α) (). E.g. the specifiers for Who
killed Cock Robin?, used as an enquiry, would be: U to utter to A killed Cock Robin if U wills A to judge U to
will that (∃1λ) (A should
will that U judges (x killed Cock Robin)); in which (∃1λ) takes on the shape (∃1x) since x is the free variable within
its scope. Grice compares his buletic-doxastic distinction to prohairesis/doxa
distinction by Aristotle in Ethica Nichomachea. Perhaps his simplest
formalisation is via subscripts: I will-b but will-d not. Refs.: The main
references are given above under ‘desirability.’ The most systematic treatment
is the excursus in “Aspects,” Clarendon. BANC. modus. “The
distinction between Judicative and Volitive Interrogatives corresponds with the
difference between cases in which a questioner is indicated as being, in one
way or another, concerned to obtain information ("Is he at home?"),
and cases in which the questioner is indicated as being concerned to settle a
problem about what he is to do ("Am I to leave the door open?",
"Is the prisoner to be released?", "Shall I go on
reading?"). This difference is better represented in Grecian and Roman.”The Greek word was ‘egklisis,’ which Priscian translates as
‘modus’ and defines as ‘inclinatio anima, affectionis demonstrans.’ The Greeks
recognised five: horistike, indicativus, pronuntiativus, finitus, or
definitivus, prostastike, imperativus, euktike, optativus, hypotaktike (subjunctivus,
or conjunnctivus, but also volitivus, hortativus, deliberativus, iussivus,
prohibitivus anticipativus ) and aparemphatos infinitivus or infinitus. Modus -- odus optativus.
optative enclisis (gre:
ευκτική έγκλιση, euktike enclisis, hence it may be seen as a modus optatīvus.
Something that fascinated Grice. The way an ‘action’ is modalised in the way
one describes it. He had learned the basics for Greek and Latin at Oxford, and
he was exhilarated to be able to teach now on the subtleties of the English
system of ‘aspect.’ To ‘opt’ is to choose. So ‘optativus’ is the deliberative
mode. Grice proved the freedom of the will with a “grammatical argument.”
‘Given that the Greeks and the Romans had an optative mode, there is free
will.” Romans, having no special verbal forms recognized as Optative, had no
need of the designation modus
optativus. Yet they sometimes used it, ad imitationem. Modus -- modality: Grice: “Modality is the manner in
which a proposition (or statement) describes or applies to its subject matter.
Derivatively,’ modality’ refers to characteristics of entities or states of
affairs described by this or that modal proposition. Modalities are classified
as follows. An assertoric proposition is the expression of a mere fact. Alethic
modality includes necessity and possibility. The latter two sometimes are referred
to respectively as the apodeictic modality and the problematic modality – vide
Grice’s category of conversational mode – which covers three categories under
what Kant calls the ‘Funktion’ of Mode – the assertoric, the apodeictic and the
problematic). Grice takes ‘must’ as basic and defines ‘may’ in terms of ‘must.’
Causal modality includes causal necessity or empirical necessity and causal
possibility or empirical possibility. The deontic modality includes obligation
and permittedness. Of course this hardly means that ‘must’ is polysemous. It is
‘aequi-vocal’ at most. There is epistemic modality or modalities such as
knowing that and doxastic modality (what Grice calls ‘credibility,’ as opposed
to ‘desirability’) or modalities ones such as believing that. There is
desiderative modality such as ‘willing that’ (what Grice calls ‘desirability’
as prior to ‘credibility.’) Following medieval philosophers, a proposition can
be distinguished on the basis of whether the modality is introduced via
adverbial modification of the “copula” or verb (“sensus divisus”) – as in
Grice’s “Fido is shaggy” versus “Fido may be shaggy” – (in Roman, “Fidus est
fidelis” versus “Fidus sit fidelis” – Grice: “Not to be confused with “Fido,
sit!” ) or via a modal operator that modifies the proposition (“sensus
compositus” – as preferred by Strawson: “It is the case that,” “It is not the
case that,” “It must be the case that” and “It may be the case that”). Grice
actually calls ‘adverbial modifier’ the external version. The internal version
he just calls, as everybody at Clifton does, ‘conjugation’ (“We are not
Tarzan!”). Grice: "In Gricese, in the instance in which the
indicative occurs after "acsian" here is no doubt in the minds of
those who ask the question, the content of the dependent clause being by them
regarded as a fact.
Mk. X. 2. Da genealsehton him pharisei and hine axodon hwseber alyfS senegum men his wif forlsetan. Interrogabant eum: INTERROGABANT EUM: SI LICET Si licet. L. XII. 36. beo gelice pam mannum be hyra hlaforde abidafr hwsenne he sy fram
gyftum gecyrred.
L. XXII. 24. hi flitun betwux him hwylc hyra wsere
yldest. J. XIX. 24.
uton hleotan hwylces ures
heo sy. Mk. XV. 24.
hi hlotu wurpon, hwset
gehwa name.
mittentes sortem
super eis, quis quid tolleret. MITTENTES SORTEM SVPER EIS, QVIS QVID TOLLERET. M. XXVII. 49. Uton geseon hwseber Helias cume and wylle
hyne alysan. Mk. V. 14. hi ut eodon bset hi
gesawon hwset par gedon wsere. L. XIX. 3.he wolde geseon hwylc se hselend
wsere. Mk. IX. 34.hi on wege smeadon hwylc hyra yldost wsere. Mk. IX.
10. L. XI, 38. XXII. 23. L. XIV. 28. Hwylc eower wyle timbrian anne stypel, hu ne sytt he serest and
teleS pa andfengas be him behefe synt, hwseder he hsebbe hine to
full-fremmenne?
L. I. 29. ba wearS heo on his sprsece gedrefed, and pohte
hwset seo greting wsere.
L. Ill, 15. XIV.
31. L. IX. 46.
bset gepanc eode on hig,
hwylc hyra yldest wsere. Mk. XV. 47. Da com Maria Magdalene and Josepes Maria, and beheoldon hwar he
geled wsere. aspiciebant. ubi poneretur ASPICIEBANT. VBI
PONERETVR.
(Looked around, in order
to discover). The notion of purpose is sometimes involved, the indirect
question having something of the force of a final clause: Mk.
XIII. 11. ne foresmeage ge hwset ge specan. L. XXI. 14. *) Direct rather than indirect question. L. XII. 22. ne beo ge ymbehydige eowre
sawle hwset ge etan, ne eowrum lichaman hwset ge scrydun. M. VI, 25. L. XII. 11. ne beo ge embebencynde hu oSSe hwset ge specon
oSSe andswarian. M. X. 19. ne bence ge hu oSSe hwset ge
sprecun. L. XII. 29.
Nelle ge secean hwset ge
eton oSSe drincon.
J. XIX. 12. and sySSan sohte Pilatus hu he hyne forlete. quaerebat Pilatus dimittere eum. QVAEREBAT PILATVS DIMITTERE EVM 2. When the content of the dependent clause is regarded as an actual
fact, which is the case when the leading verb expresses the act of learning,
perceiving, etc., the indicative is used. M. VI. 28. BesceawiaS secyres Man
hu hig weaxaO. M. XXI. 16.gehyrst bu hwset pas cwseoab? M. XXVII. 13. Ne gehyrst Jm hu fela sagena hig ongen be
secgeaS?
L. XVIII. 6. M. IX.
13.leornigeab hwset is, ic wylle mildheortnesse
nses onssegdnesse. M. XXI. 20. loca nu hu hrsedlice bset fic-treow forscranc. Mk. XV. 4. loca hu mycelum hi be wregea§. M. XII. 4.Ne
rsedde ge hwset David dyde hu he ineode on Godes hus, and set ba
offring-hlafas?
L. VI, 4. Mk. XII. 26. Be bam deadum ■ bset hi arison, ne rsedde ge on Moyses bec hu God
to him cwseb?
Mk. I, 26. Mk. V. 16. hi rehton him ba Se hit gesawon hu hit gedon wses. L.
VIII. 36.
Da cyddon him ba Se
gesawon hu he wses hal geworden. L. XXIII. 55.hig gesawon ba
byrgene and hu his lichama aled wses. J. XX. 14.heo geseah hwar se
hselend stod.
Vidit Jesum stantem. *) VIDIT IESVM STANTEM. Not the endeavour to learn, perceive, which
would require the SUBJUNCTIVE. L. XXIV. 6.
gebencao hu he spsec wiS
eow. recordamini.
Mk. VIII. 19.
3.After verbs of knowing both the indicative and subjunctive are used, usually
the indicative. See general statement before § 2. a)
Indicative:*) L. XIII. 27. Ne cann ic hwanon ge
synt. Mk. XIV, 68. M. VI. 8. eower fseder wat hwset eow bearf
ys. M. XX. 22.
Gyt nyton hwset gyt
biddab. L. XIII. 25. nat ic hwanon ge
synt. J. IX. 21. we nyton humete he nu
gesyhb. quomodo autem nunc videat, nescimus. QVOMODO AVTEM NVNC, NESCIMVS. J. IX. 25. gif he synful is, bset ic nat. si peccator est, nescio. SI PECCATOR EST, NESCIO. I know not if he is a sinner. gif he synful is, bset ic nat. "Gif he synful is, ᚦaet ic nat." In Oxonian:
"If he sinful is,
that I know not. M. XXVI. 70. Mk. IX. 6. X, 28. XIII, 33, 35. L. IX,
33. XX, 7. XXII, 60. L. XXIII. 34. J. II. 9. III. 8. V. 13. VII.
27, 27, 28. VIII. 14, 14. J. IX. 29. 30. X. 6. XIII. 18. XIV. 5. XV.
15. b)
Indicative and
subjunctive: L. X. 22. nan man nat hwylc IS se
sunu buton se fseder, ne hwylc SI Se fseder buton se sunu. -- In Latin, both times have subjunctive third person singular,
"sit".)
c)
Subjunctive. a. In the protasis of a conditional sentence: J.
VII. 51.Cwyst bu demS ure se senine man buton hyne man ser gehyre and wite
hwset he do? J. XI. 57. pa pharisei hsefdon beboden gif hwa wiste
hwaer he wsere paet he hyt cydde bset hig mihton hine niman. Translating
the Latin subjunctive in 21 instances, the indic. in 9. As a rule, the mood (or mode, as Grice prefers)
of the Latin (or Roman, as Grice prefers) verb does not determine the O. E. (or
A. S., as Grice prefers) usage. In Anglo-Saxon, Oxonian,
and Gricese, "si" seems to be no more than a literal (mimetic)
rendering of Roman "sit," the correct third person singular
subjunctive.
Ms. A. reads
"ys" with'-sy" above. The Lind. gloss reads
"is". M. XXIV. 43. WitaS bset gyf se hiredes ealdor wiste on hwylcere tide se beof
towerd waere witodlice he wolde wacigean. si sciret paterfamilias qua hora fur
venturus esset vigilaret,
(Cf. J. IV, 10. Gif bu wistest — hwaet se is etc. Si scirest quis est. SI SCIREST QVIS EST. /J. In the apodosis of a conditional sentence: J. VII.
17. gyf hwa wyle his willan don he gecwemo (sic. A.B.C. gecnsewS) be
bsere lare hwseber heo si of Gode hwseber be ic he me sylfum
spece. L. VII. 39. Gyf be man witega wsere
witodlice he wiste hwset and hwylc bis wif wsere be his sethrinb bset heo
synful is.
sciret utique quae et
qualis est mulier. SCIRET VTIQVE QVAE ET QVALIS EST MULIER. y. After a hortatory subjunctive. M. VI.
3. Nyte bin wynstre hwset do bin swybre. 4. After verbs of
saying and declaring. a) Here the indicative is used when the
dependent clause contains a statement rather than a question. L. VIII.
39. cyS hu mycel be God gedon h3efS. L. VIII. 47.Da bset wif
geseah bset hit him nses dyrne heo com forht and astrehte hig to his fotum and
geswutulude beforan eallum folce for hwylcum binge heo hit sethran and hu heo
wearS sona hal. ob quam causam tetigerit eum, indicavit; et quemadmodum
confestim SANATA SIT. Further examples of the indicative are. L. XX.
2.*) Sege us on hwylcum anwalde wyrcst bu Sas
bing oSSe hwset ys se Se be bisne anwald sealde. L. VI. 47. iElc bara be to me cymb and mine sprseca
gehyi*S and pa deb, ic him setywe hwam he gelic is. b) When the subordinate clause refers to the future
both the indicative and subjunctive are used: *) Direct
question, as the order of the words shows. Mk. XIII. 4. Sege us hwsenne bas bing gewurdon (A. geweorSon,
H. gewurSen, R. gewurdon) and hwylc tacen bid
bsenne ealle bas Sing onginnaS beon geendud. (Transition to direct
question.) Dic nobis, quando ista fient? DIC NOBIS, QVANDO ISTA FIENT? et quod signum erit? ET QVOD SIGNVM
ERIT? M. XXIV. 3. Sege us hwsenne bas Sing
gewurbun and hwile tacn si bines to-cymes. J. XVIII. 32. he geswutelode hwylcon deaSe lie swulte. qua
morte ESSET moriturus. c) When the question presents a distinct alternative, so that the
idea of doubt and uncertainty is prominent, the subjunctive in Gricese,
Oxonian, and Anglo-Saxon, qua conjugated version, is used: M. XXVI.
63. Ic halsige be Surh bone lyfiendan God, b*t Su secge us gyf \>u sy
Crist Godes sunu. L. XXII. 67. J. X. 24. d) The following is
hortatory as well as declarative: L. XII. 5. Ic eow setywe
hwsene ge ondredon. Ostendam autem vobis, quem TIMEATIS. 5. In
three indirect questions which in the original are direct, the subjunctive is
used: M. XXIV. 45.Wens (sic. A. H. & R. wenst) \>u
hwa sy getrywe and gleaw BEOW? Quis, putas, EST fidelis
servus? QVIS, PVTAS, EST FIDELIS SERVS. M. XXVI. 25. Cwyst
bu lareow hwseSer ic hyt si? Numquid ego sum? NVMQVID EGO SVM, J. VII. 26. CweSe we hwseber ba ealdras ongyton
^set bis IS Crist?
Numquid vere cognoverunt
principes, quia hie EST Christus? § 11. RELATIVE CLAUSES. Except
in the relations discussed in the following the indicative is used in relative
clauses. Grice:
"The verb 'to be' is actually composed of three different stems -- not
only in Aristotle, but in Gricese." CONIUGATVM, persona, s-stem
(cognate with Roman "sit"), b-stem, w-stem (cognate with Roman,
"ero") MODVS INFINITVUM, the verb "sīn,” the verb
"bion,” the verb "wesan.” MODVS INDICATIVM PRAESENS prima singularis:
"ik" -- Oxonian "I" "em" Oxonian, "am."
Bium wisu secunda singularis: "thū" -- Oxonian: "thou"
"art" Oxonian "art" bis(t) wisis tertia singularis:
"hē" Oxonian, 'he' "ist" (Cognate with Roman
"est") Oxonian 'is' *bid wis(id) prima, secunda, tertia, pluralis "sindun"
*biod wesad MODVS INDCATIVVM PRAETERITVM prima singularis "was"
Oxonian: "was." seconda singularis ""wāri"
Oxonian "were" tertia singularis "was" Oxonian
"was" prima, secunda, tertia, pluralis "wārun" Oxonian
"were" MODVS SVBIVCTIVVM PRAESENS prima, secunda, tertia,
singularis "sīe" (Lost in Oxonian after Occam) "wese"
(cognate with "was", and Roman, "erat") prima, secunda,
tertia, pluralis "sīen" wesen MODVS SVBIVNCTIVVM
PRAETERITUM prima, secunda, tertia, singularis wāri prima, secunda,
tertia, pluralis wārin MODVS IMPERATIVUM singularis "wis,"
"wes" (Cognate with "was" and Roman "erat")
pluralis wesad MODVS PARTICIPIVM PRAESENT wesandi (cognate with Cicero's
"essens" and "essentia" MODVS PARTICIPIVM PRAETERITVM "giwesan"
The present-tense forms of 'be' with the w-stem, "wesan" are
almost never used. Therefore, wesan is used as IMPERATIVE,
in the past tense, and in the participium prasesens versions of "sīn"
-- Grice: "I rue the day when the Bosworth and Toller left Austin!"
-- "Now the OED, is not supposed to include Anglo-Saxon forms!") and
does not have a separate meaning. The b-stem is only met in the present
indicative of wesan, and only for the first and second persons in the singular.
So we see that if Roman had the 'est-sit" distinction, the Oxonians
had "The 'ist'/"sīe"/"wese" tryad).
Grice: "To simplify the Oxonian forms and make them correlative to
Roman, I shall reduce the Oxonian triad, 'ist'/'sīe'/"wese" to
the division actually cognate with Roman: 'ist'/'sīe."
And so, I shall speak of the 'ist'/'sīe" distinction, or the
'est-sit' distinction interchangeably." Today
many deny the distinction or confine attention just to modal operators. Modal
operators in non-assertoric propositions are said to produce referential
opacity or oblique contexts in which truth is not preserved under substitution
of extensionally equivalent expressions. Modal and deontic logics provide
formal analyses of various modalities. Intensional logics investigate the logic
of oblique contexts. Modal logicians have produced possible worlds semantics
interpretations wherein propositions MP with modal operator M are true provided
P is true in all suitable (e.g., logically possible, causally possible, morally
permissible, rationally acceptable) possible worlds. Modal realism grants
ontological status to possible worlds other than the actual world or otherwise
commits to objective modalities in nature or reality. modus: the study of the
logic of the operators ‘it is possible that’ (or, as Grice prefers, “it may be
that”) and ‘it is necessary that’ (or as Grice prefers, “It must be that…”). For
some reason, Grice used ‘mode’ at Oxford – but ‘manner’ in the New World! The
sad thing is that when he came back to the Old World, to the puzzlmenet of
Old-Worlders, he kept using ‘manner.’ So, everytime we see Grice using
‘manner,’ we need to translate to either the traditional Oxonian ‘modus,’ or
the Gricese ‘mode.’ These operators Grice symbolizes by a diamond and a square respectively.
and each can be defined in terms of the other. □p
(necessarily p) is equivalent to ¬◇¬p
("not possible that not-p") ◇p
(possibly p) is equivalent to ¬□¬p ("not necessarily not-p"). To say that Fido
may be shaggy is to say that it is not necessarily false. Thus possP could be
regarded as an abbreviation of -Nec-p Equally, to say that Fido *must* be
shaggy is to deny that its negation is possible. Thus Af could be regarded as
an abbreviation of -B-f. Grice prefers to take ‘poss” as primitive (“for
surely, it may rain before it must pour!”). Grice’s ystem G of modality is
obtained by introducing Poss. and Nec. If system, as Grice’s is, is
classical/intuitionist/minimal, so is the corresponding modal logic. Grice
surely concentrates on the classical case (“Dummett is overconcentraating on
the intuitionist, and nobody at Oxford was, is, or will be minimal!”). As with any kind of logic, there are three
components to a system of modal logic: a syntactics, which determines the system
or calculus + and the notion of well-formed formula (wff). Second, a semantics,
which determines the consequence relation X on +-wffs. Third, a pragmatics or
sub-system of inference, which determines the deductive consequence relation Y
on +-wffs. The syntactis of the modal operators is the same in every system.
Briefly, the modal operator is a one-place or unary ‘connective,’ or operator,
strictly, since it does not connect two atoms into a molecule, like negation.
There are many different systems of modal logic, some of which can be generated
by different ways of setting up the semantics. Each of the familiar ways of
doing this can be associated with a sound and complete system of inference.
Alternatively, a system of inference can be laid down first and we can search
for a semantics for it relative to which it is sound and complete. Grice gives
primacy to the syntactic viewpoint. Semantic consequence is defined in modal
logic in the usual classical way: a set of sentences 9 yields a sentence s, 9 X
s, iff if no “interpretation” (to use Grice’s jargon in “Vacuous Names”) I
makes all members of 9 true and s false. The question is how to extend the
notion of “interpretation” to accommodate for “may be shaggy” – and “must be
shaggy”. In classical sentential logic, an interpretation is an assignment to
each sentence letter of exactly one of the two truth-values = and where n % m !
1. So to determine relative possibility in a model, we identify R with a
collection of pairs of the form where each of u and v is in W. If a pair is in
R, v is possible relative to u, and if is not in R, v is impossible relative to
u. The relative possibility relation then enters into the rules for the
evaluating modal operator. We do not want to say, e. g. that at the actual
world, it is possible for Grice to originate from a different sperm and egg,
since the only worlds where this takes place are impossible relative to the
actual world. So we have the rule that B f is true at a world u if f is true at
some world v such that v is possible relative to u. Similarly, Af is true at a
world u if f is true at every world v which is possible relative to u. R may
have simple first-order properties such as reflexivity, (Ex)Rxx, symmetry,
(Ex)(Ey)(Rxy P Ryx), and transitivity, (Ex)(Ey)(Ez)((Rxy & Ryz) P Rxz), and
different modal systems can be obtained by imposing different combinations of
these on R (other systems can be obtained from higher-order constraints). The
least constrained system is the system Ghp, in which no structural properties
are put on R. In G-hp we have B (B & C) X B B, since if B (B & C) holds
at w* then (B & C) holds at some world w possible relative to w*, and thus
by the truth-function for &, B holds at w as well, so B B holds at w*.
Hence any interpretation that makes B (B & C) true (% true at w*) also
makes B B true. Since there are no restrictions on R in G-hp, we can expect B
(B & C) X B B in every system of modal logic generated by constraining R.
However, for G-hp we also have C Z B C. For suppose C holds at w*. B C holds at
w* only if there is some world possible relative to w* where C holds. But there
need be no such world. In particular, since R need not be reflexive, w* itself
need not be possible relative to w*. Concomitantly, in any system for which we
stipulate a reflexive R, we will have C X B C. The simplest such system is
known as T, which has the same semantics as K except that R is stipulated to be
reflexive in every interpretation. In other systems, further or different
constraints are put on R. For example, in the system B, each interpretation
must have an R that is reflexive and symmetric, and in the system S4, each
interpretation must have an R that is reflexive and transitive. In B we have B
C Z B B C, as can be shown by an interpretation with nontransitive R, while in
S4 we have B AC Z C, as can be shown by an interpretation with non-symmetric R.
Correspondingly, in S4, B C X B B C, and in B, B AC X C. The system in which R
is reflexive, transitive, and symmetric is called S5, and in this system, R can
be omitted. For if R has all three properties, R is an equivalence relation,
i.e., it partitions W into mutually exclusive and jointly exhaustive
equivalence classes. If Cu is the equivalence class to which u belongs, then
the truth-value of a formula at u is independent of the truth-values of
sentence letters at worlds not in Cu, so only the worlds in Cw* are relevant to
the truth-values of sentences in an S5 interpretation. But within Cw* R is
universal: every world is possible relative to every other. Consequently, in an
S5 interpretation, we need not specify a relative possibility relation, and the
evaluation rules for B and A need not mention relative possibility; e.g., we
can say that B f is true at a world u if there is at least one world v at which
f is true. Note that by the characteristics of R, whenever 9 X s in K, T, B, or
S4, then 9 X s in S5: the other systems are contained in S5. K is contained in
all the systems we have mentioned, while T is contained in B and S4, neither of
which is contained in the other. Sentential modal logics give rise to
quantified modal logics, of which quantified S5 is the bestknown. Just as, in
the sentential case, each world in an interpretation is associated with a
valuation of sentence letters as in non-modal sentential logic, so in
quantified modal logic, each world is associated with a valuation of the sort
familiar in non-modal first-order logic. More specifically, in quantified S5,
each world w is assigned a domain Dw – the things that exist at w – such that
at least one Dw is non-empty, and each atomic n-place predicate of the language
is assigned an extension Extw of n-tuples of objects that satisfy the predicate
at w. So even restricting ourselves to just the one first-order extension of a
sentential system, S5, various degrees of freedom are already evident. We
discuss the following: (a) variability of domains, (b) interpretation of
quantifiers, and (c) predication. (a) Should all worlds have the same domain or
may the domains of different worlds be different? The latter appears to be the
more natural choice; e.g., if neither of of Dw* and Du are subsets of the
other, this represents the intuitive idea that some things that exist might not
have, and that there could have been things that do not actually exist (though
formulating this latter claim requires adding an operator for ‘actually’ to the
language). So we should distinguish two versions of S5, one with constant
domains, S5C, and the other with variable domains, S5V. (b) Should the truth of
(Dn)f at a world w require that f is true at w of some object in Dw or merely
of some object in D (D is the domain of all possible objects, 4weWDw)? The
former treatment is called the actualist reading of the quantifiers, the
latter, the possibilist reading. In S5C there is no real choice, since for any
w, D % Dw, but the issue is live in S5V. (c) Should we require that for any
n-place atomic predicate F, an n-tuple of objects satisfies F at w only if
every member of the n-tuple belongs to Dw, i.e., should we require that atomic
predicates be existence-entailing? If we abbreviate (Dy) (y % x) by Ex (for ‘x
exists’), then in S5C, A(Ex)AEx is logically valid on the actualist reading of
E (%-D-) and on the possibilist. On the former, the formula says that at each
world, anything that exists at that world exists at every world, which is true;
while on the latter, using the definition of ‘Ex’, it says that at each world,
anything that exists at some world or other is such that at every world, it
exists at some world or other, which is also true; indeed, the formula stays
valid in S5C with possibilist quantifiers even if we make E a primitive logical
constant, stipulated to be true at every w of exactly the things that exist at
w. But in S5V with actualist quantifiers, A(Ex)AEx is invalid, as is (Ex)AEx –
consider an interpretation where for some u, Du is a proper subset of Dw*.
However, in S5V with possibilist quantifiers, the status of the formula, if
‘Ex’ is defined, depends on whether identity is existence-entailing. If it is
existenceentailing, then A(Ex)AEx is invalid, since an object in D satisfies
(Dy)(y % x) at w only if that object exists at w, while if identity is not
existence-entailing, the formula is valid. The interaction of the various
options is also evident in the evaluation of two well-known schemata: the
Barcan formula, B (Dx)fx P (Dx) B fx; and its converse, (Dx) B fx P B (Dx)fx.
In S5C with ‘Ex’ either defined or primitive, both schemata are valid, but in
S5V with actualist quantifiers, they both fail. For the latter case, if we
substitute -E for f in the converse Barcan formula we get a conditional whose
antecedent holds at w* if there is u with Du a proper subset of Dw*, but whose
consequent is logically false. The Barcan formula fails when there is a world u
with Du not a subset of Dw*, and the condition f is true of some non-actual
object at u and not of any actual object there. For then B (Dx)f holds at w*
while (Dx) B fx fails there. However, if we require atomic predicates to be
existence-entailing, then instances of the converse Barcan formula with f
atomic are valid. In S5V with possibilist quantifiers, all instances of both
schemata are valid, since the prefixes (Dx) B and B (Dx) correspond to (Dx)
(Dw) and (Dw) (Dx), which are equivalent (with actualist quantifiers, the
prefixes correspond to (Dx 1 Dw*), and (Dw) (Dx 1 Dw) which are non-equivalent
if Dw and Dw* need not be the same set). Finally in S5V with actualist
quantifiers, the standard quantifier introduction and elimination rules must be
adjusted. Suppose c is a name for an object that does not actually exist; then
- Ec is true but (Dx) - Ex is false. The quantifier rules must be those of free
logic: we require Ec & fc before we infer (Dv)fv and Ec P fc, as well as
the usual EI restrictions, before we infer (Ev)fv. Refs.: H. P. Grice:
“Modality: Desirability and Credibility;” H. P. Grice, “The may and the may
not;” H. P. Grice, “The Big Philosophical Mistake: ‘What is actual is not also
possible’.” modus: Grice: “In Roman,
‘modus’ may have been rendered as ‘way’, ‘fashion’ – but I will not, and use
‘modus’ as THEY did! ‘Modus’ is used in more than one ‘modus’ in philosophy. In
Ariskantian logic, ‘modus’ refers either to the arrangement of universal,
particular, affirmative, or negative propositions within a syllogism, only
certain of which are valid this is often tr., confusingly, as ‘modus’ in
English – “the valid modes, such as Barbara and Celarent.” But then ‘modus’ may
be used to to the property a proposition has by virtue of which it is necessary
or contingent, possible or impossible, or ‘actual.’ In Oxonian scholastic
metaphysics, ‘modus’ is often used in a not altogether technical way to mean
that which characterizes a thing and distinguishes it from others. Micraelius,
in his best-selling “Lexicon philosophicum,” has it that “a mode does not
compose a thing, but distinguishes it and makes it determinate.” ‘Modus’ is also
used in the context of the modal distinction in the theory of distinctions to
designate the distinction that holds between a substance and its modes or
between two modes of a single substance. ‘Modus’ also appears in the technical
vocabulary of medieval speculative ‘grammar’ or ‘semantics’ (“speculative
semantics” makes more sense) -- in connection with the notions of the “modus
significandi,” “the modus intelligendi” (more or less the same thing), and the
“modus essendi.” The term ‘modus’ becomes especially important when Descartes
(vide Grice, “Descartes on clear and distinct perception”), Spinoza (vide S. N.
Hampshire, “Spinoza”), and Locke each take it up, giving it three somewhat
different special meanings within their respective systems. Descartes (vide
Grice, “Descartes on clear and distinct perception”) makes ‘modus’ a central
notion in his metaphysics in his Principia philosophiae. For Descartes, each
substantia is characterized by a principal attribute, ‘cogitatio’ for ‘anima’
and ‘extensio’ for ‘corpus’. Modes, then, are particular ways of being extended
or thinking, i.e., particular sizes, shapes, etc., or particular thoughts, properties
in the broad sense that individual things substances have. In this way, ‘modus’
occupies the role in Descartes’s philosophy that ‘accident’ does in
Aristotelian philosophy. But for Descartes, each mode must be connected with
the principal attribute of a substance, a way of being extended or a way of
thinking, whereas for the Aristotelian, accidents may or may not be connected
with the essence of the substance in which they inhere. Like Descartes, Spinoza
recognizes three basic metaphysical terms, ‘substania,’ ‘attributum’, and
‘modus’. Recalling Descartes, Spinoza defines ‘modus’ as “the affections of a
substance, or that which is in another, and which is also conceived through
another” Ethics I. But for Spinoza, there is only one substance, which has all
possible attributes. This makes it somewhat difficult to determine exactly what
Spinoza means by ‘modus’, whether they are to be construed as being in some say
a “property” of God, the one infinite substance, or whether they are to be
construed more broadly as simply individual things that depend for their
existence on God, just as Cartesian modes depend on Cartesian substance.
Spinoza also introduces somewhat obscure distinctions between modus infinitus
and modus finitus, and between immediate and mediate infinite modes. Now, much
closer to Grice, Englishman and Oxonian Locke uses ‘mode’ in a way that
evidently derives from Descartes’s usage, but that also differs from it. For
Locke, a ‘modus’ is “such complex idea – as Pegasus the flying horse --, which
however compounded, contain not in them the supposition of subsisting by
themselves, but are considered as Dependences on, or Affections of Substances”
Essay II. A ‘modus,’ for Locke, is thus an idea that represents to us the a ‘complex’
propertiy of a thing, sc. an idea derived from what Locke a ‘simple’ idea that
come to us from experience. Locke distinguishes between a ‘modus simplex,’ like
number, space, and infinity, which are supposed to be constructed by
compounding the SAME simple idea many times, and ‘modus complexum,’ or ‘modus
mixtum,’ a mode like obligation or theft, which is supposed to be compounded of
at least two simple ideas of a different sort.
Refs.: Grice applies Locke’s idea of the modus mixtum in his ‘labour’
against Empiricism, cf. H. P. Grice, “I may care a hoot what the dictionary
says, but it is not the case that I care a hoot what Micraelius’s “Lexicon
philosophicum” says.” Modus – modulus -- Grice
against a pragmatic or rational module: from Latin ‘modulus,’ ‘little mode.’ the commitment to functionally independent and
specialized cognitive system in psychological organizatio, or, more generally,
in the organization of any complex system. A ‘modulus’ entails that behavior is
the product of components with subordinate functions, that these functions are
realized in discrete physical systems, and that the subsystems are minimally
interactive. Organization in terms of a modulus varies from simple
decomposability to what Herbert Simon calls near decomposability. In the
former, component systems are independent, operating according to intrinsically
determined principles; system behavior is an additive or aggregative function
of these independent contributions. In the latter, the short-run behavior of
components is independent of the behavior of other components; the system
behavior is a relatively simple function of component contributions. Gall
defends a modular organization for the mind/brain, holding that the cerebral
hemispheres consist of a variety of organs, or centers, each subserving
specific intellectual and moral functions. This picture of the brain as a
collection of relatively independent organs contrasts sharply with the
traditional view that intellectual activity involves the exercise of a general
unitary ‘faculty’ in a variety of this or that‘domain’, where a ‘domain’ is not
a ‘modulus’ -- a view that was common to Descartes and Hume as well as Gall’s
major opponents such as Flourens. By the middle of the nineteenth century,
Bouillaud and Broca (a French doctor, of Occitan ancestry – brooch, broca –
thorn --) defended the view that language is controlled by localized structures
in the left hemisphere and is relatively independent of other cognitive
activities. It was later discovered by Wernicke that there are at least two
centers for the control of language, one more posterior and one more anterior.
On these views, there are discrete physical structures responsible for communication,
which are largely independent of one another and of structures responsible for
other psychological functions. This is therefore a modular organization. This
view of the neurophysiological organization of communication continues to have
advocates, though the precise characterization of the functions these two
centers serve is controversial. Many more recent views have tended to limit
modularity to more peripheral functions such as vision, hearing, and motor
control and speech, but have excluded “what I am interested in, viz. so-called
higher cognitive processes.” – H. P. Grice, “The power structure of the soul.” Modus -- modus ponendo ponens: 1 the argument
form ‘If A then B; A; therefore, B’, and arguments of this form compare fallacy
of affirming the consequent; 2 the rule of inference that permits one to infer
the consequent of a conditional from that conditional and its antecedent. This
is also known as the rule of /-elimination or rule of /- detachment. modus tollendo tollens: 1 the argument form
‘If A then B; not-B; therefore, not-A’, and arguments of this form compare
fallacy of denying the antecedent; 2 the rule of inference that permits one to
infer the negation of the antecedent of a conditional from that conditional and
the negation of its consequent.
molyneux question: also called Molyneux’s
problem, the question that, in correspondence with Locke, William Molyneux or
Molineux, 1656 98, a Dublin lawyer and member of the Irish Parliament, posed
and Locke inserted in the second edition of his Essay Concerning Human
Understanding 1694; book 2, chap. 9, section 8: Suppose a Man born blind, and
now adult, and taught by his touch to distinguish a Cube, and a Sphere of the
same metal, and nighly of the same bigness, so as to tell, when he felt one and
t’other, which is the Cube, which the Sphere. Suppose then the Cube and Sphere
placed on a Table, and the Blind Man to be made to see. Quære, Whether by his
sight, before he touch’d them, he could now distinguish, and tell, which is the
Globe, which the Cube. Although it is tempting to regard Molyneux’s question as
straightforwardly empirical, attempts to gauge the abilities of newly sighted
adults have yielded disappointing and ambiguous results. More interesting,
perhaps, is the way in which different theories of perception answer the
question. Thus, according to Locke, sensory modalities constitute discrete
perceptual channels, the contents of which perceivers must learn to correlate.
Such a theory answers the question in the negative as did Molyneux himself.
Other theories encourage different responses.
mondolfo: essential Italian philosopher. Like
Grice, Mondolfo believed seriously in the longitudinal unity of philosophy and
made original research on the historiography of philosophy, especially during
the Eleatic, Agrigento, and later Roman periods. Refs.: Luigi Speranza,
"Grice, Mondolfo, e la filosofia greco-romana," per il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
Monte: essential Italian
philosopher. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice e del Monte," per Il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
Montanism, a charismatic, schismatic
movement in early Christianity, originating in Phrygia in the late second
century. It rebuked the mainstream church for laxity and apathy, and taught
moral purity, new, i.e. postbiblical, revelation, and the imminent end of the
world. Traditional accounts, deriving from critics of the movement, contain
exaggerations and probably some fabrications. Montanus himself, abetted by the
prophetesses Maximilla and Prisca, announced in ecstatic speech a new, final
age of prophecy. This fulfilled the biblical promises that in the last days the
Holy Spirit would be poured out universally Joel 2: 28ff.; Acts 2: 16ff. and
would teach “the whole truth” Jon. 14:26; 16:13. It also empowered the
Montanists to enjoin more rigorous discipline than that required by Jesus. The
sect denied that forgiveness through baptism covered serious subsequent sin;
forbade remarriage for widows and widowers; practiced fasting; and condemned
believers who evaded persecution. Some later followers may have identified
Montanus with the Holy Spirit itself, though he claimed only to be the Spirit’s
mouthpiece. The “new prophecy” flourished for a generation, especially in North
Africa, gaining a famous convert in Tertullian. But the church’s bishops
repudiated the movement’s criticisms and innovations, and turned more
resolutely against postapostolic revelation, apocalyptic expectation, and
ascetic extremes.
mooreism: g. e. – and his paradox: cited by H. P. Grice. Irish
London-born philosopher who spearheaded the attack on idealism and was a major
supporter of realism in all its forms: metaphysical, epistemological, and
axiological. He was born in Upper Norwood, a suburb of London; did his
undergraduate work at Cambridge ; spent 84 as a fellow of Trinity ; returned to
Cambridge in 1 as a lecturer; and was granted a professorship there in 5. He
also served as editor of Mind. The bulk of his work falls into four categories:
metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, and philosophical methodology. Metaphysics.
In this area, Moore is mainly known for his attempted refutation of idealism
and his defense thereby of realism. In his “The Refutation of Idealism” 3, he
argued that there is a crucial premise that is essential to all possible
arguments for the idealistic conclusion that “All reality is mental spiritual.”
This premise is: “To be is to be perceived” in the broad sense of ‘perceive’.
Moore argued that, under every possible interpretation of it, that premise is
either a tautology or false; hence no significant conclusion can ever be
inferred from it. His positive defense of realism had several prongs. One was to
show that there are certain claims held by non-realist philosophers, both
idealist ones and skeptical ones. Moore argued, in “A Defense of Common Sense”
5, that these claims are either factually false or self-contradictory, or that
in some cases there is no good reason to believe them. Among the claims that
Moore attacked are these: “Propositions about purported material facts are
false”; “No one has ever known any such propositions to be true”; “Every
purported physical fact is logically dependent on some mental fact”; and “Every
physical fact is causally dependent on some mental fact.” Another major prong
of Moore’s defense of realism was to argue for the existence of an external
world and later to give a “Proof of an External World” 3. Epistemology. Most of
Moore’s work in this area dealt with the various kinds of knowledge we have,
why they must be distinguished, and the problem of perception and our knowledge
of an external world. Because he had already argued for the existence of an
external world in his metaphysics, he here focused on how we know it. In many
papers and chapters e.g., “The Nature and Reality of Objects of Perception,” 6
he examined and at times supported three main positions: naive or direct
realism, representative or indirect realism, and phenomenalism. Although he
seemed to favor direct realism at first, in the majority of his papers he found
representative realism to be the most supportable position despite its
problems. It should also be noted that, in connection with his leanings mood
toward representative realism, Moore maintained the existence of sense-data and
argued at length for an account of just how they are related to physical
objects. That there are sense-data Moore never doubted. The question was, What
is their ontological status? With regard to the various kinds of knowledge or
ways of knowing, Moore made a distinction between dispositional or
non-actualized and actualized knowledge. Within the latter Moore made
distinctions between direct apprehension often known as knowledge by
acquaintance, indirect apprehension, and knowledge proper or propositional
knowledge. He devoted much of his work to finding the conditions for knowledge
proper. Ethics. In his major work in ethics, Principia Ethica 3, Moore
maintained that the central problem of ethics is, What is good? meaning by this, not what things are good,
but how ‘good’ is to be defined. He argued that there can be only one answer,
one that may seem disappointing, namely: good is good, or, alternatively,
‘good’ is indefinable. Thus ‘good’ denotes a “unique, simple object of thought”
that is indefinable and unanalyzable. His first argument on behalf of that
claim consisted in showing that to identify good with some other object i.e.,
to define ‘good’ is to commit the naturalistic fallacy. To commit this fallacy
is to reduce ethical propositions to either psychological propositions or
reportive definitions as to how people use words. In other words, what was
meant to be an ethical proposition, that X is good, becomes a factual proposition
about people’s desires or their usage of words. Moore’s second argument ran
like this: Suppose ‘good’ were definable. Then the result would be even worse
than that of reducing ethical propositions to non-ethical propositions ethical propositions would be tautologies!
For example, suppose you defined ‘good’ as ‘pleasure’. Then suppose you
maintained that pleasure is good. All you would be asserting is that pleasure
is pleasure, a tautology. To avoid this conclusion ‘good’ must mean something other
than ‘pleasure’. Why is this the naturalistic fallacy? Because good is a
non-natural property. But even if it were a natural one, there would still be a
fallacy. Hence some have proposed calling it the definist fallacy the fallacy of attempting to define ‘good’ by
any means. This argument is often known as the open question argument because
whatever purported definition of ‘good’ anyone offers, it would always be an
open question whether whatever satisfies the definition really is good. In the
last part of Principia Ethica Moore turned to a discussion of what sorts of
things are the greatest goods with which we are acquainted. He argued for the
view that they are personal affection and aesthetic enjoyments. Philosophical
methodology. Moore’s methodology in philosophy had many components, but two
stand out: his appeal to and defense of common sense and his utilization of
various methods of philosophical/conceptual analysis. “A Defense of Common
Sense” argued for his claim that the commonsense view of the world is wholly
true, and for the claim that any view which opposed that view is either
factually false or self-contradictory. Throughout his writings Moore
distinguished several kinds of analysis and made use of them extensively in
dealing with philosophical problems. All of these may be found in the works
cited above and other essays gathered into Moore’s Philosophical Studies2 and
Philosophical Papers 9. These have been referred to as refutational analysis,
with two subforms, showing contradictions and “translation into the concrete”;
distinctional analysis; decompositional analysis either definitional or
divisional; and reductional analysis. Moore was greatly revered as a teacher.
Many of his students and colleagues have paid high tribute to him in very warm
and grateful terms. Moore’s paradox, as
first discussed by G. E. Moore, the perplexity involving assertion of what is
expressed by conjunctions such as ‘It’s raining, but I believe it isn’t’ and
‘It’s raining, but I don’t believe it is’. The oddity of such presenttense
first-person uses of ‘to believe’ seems peculiar to those conjunctions just
because it is assumed both that, when asserting
roughly, representing as true a conjunction,
one also asserts its conjuncts, and that, as a rule, the assertor believes the
asserted proposition. Thus, no perplexity arises from assertions of, for
instance, ‘It’s raining today, but I falsely believed it wasn’t until I came
out to the porch’ and ‘If it’s raining but I believe it isn’t, I have been
misled by the weather report’. However, there are reasons to think that, if we
rely only on these assumptions and examples, our characterization of the
problem is unduly narrow. First, assertion seems relevant only because we are
interested in what the assertor believes. Secondly, those conjunctions are
disturbing only insofar as they show that Moore’s paradox Moore’s paradox
583 583 some of the assertor’s
beliefs, though contingent, can only be irrationally held. Thirdly, autobiographical
reports that may justifiably be used to charge the reporter with irrationality
need be neither about his belief system, nor conjunctive, nor true e.g., ‘I
don’t exist’, ‘I have no beliefs’, nor false e.g., ‘It’s raining, but I have no
evidence that it is’. So, Moore’s paradox is best seen as the problem posed by
contingent propositions that cannot be justifiably believed. Arguably, in
forming a belief of those propositions, the believer acquires non-overridable
evidence against believing them. A successful analysis of the problem along these
lines may have important epistemological consequences. Refs.: Grice, “Oxford seminars.” Grice
dedicated a full chapter to the Moore paradox. Mainly, Moore is confused in
lexicological ways. An emisor EXPRESSES the belief that p. What the emisor
communicates is that p, not that he believes that p. He does not convey
explicitly that he believes that p, nor implicitly. Belief and its expression
is linked conceptually with the mode – indicative (‘est’); as is desire and its
expression with the imperative mode (“sit”).
mos,
ethos: ethos:
Grice: “I love Lorenz, and he loved his geese.” -- Grice: “In German, ‘deutsche’ means
‘tribal.’” -- philosophical ethology – phrase used by Grice for his creature
construction routine. ethical constructivism, a form of anti-realism about
ethics which holds that there are moral facts and truths, but insists that
these facts and truths are in some way constituted by or dependent on our moral
beliefs, reactions, or attitudes. For instance, an ideal observer theory that
represents the moral rightness and wrongness of an act in terms of the moral
approval and disapproval that an appraiser would have under suitably idealized
conditions can be understood as a form of ethical constructivism. Another form
of constructivism identifies the truth of a moral belief with its being part of
the appropriate system of beliefs, e.g., of a system of moral and nonmoral
beliefs that is internally coherent. Such a view would maintain a coherence
theory of moral truth. Moral relativism is a constructivist view that allows
for a plurality of moral facts and truths. Thus, if the idealizing conditions
appealed to in an ideal observer theory allow that different appraisers can
have different reactions to the same actions under ideal conditions, then that
ideal observer theory will be a version of moral relativism as well as of
ethical constructivism. Or, if different systems of moral beliefs satisfy the
appropriate epistemic conditions e.g. are equally coherent, then the truth or
falsity of particular moral beliefs will have to be relativized to different
moral systems or codes. -- ethical objectivism, the view that the objects of
the most basic concepts of ethics which may be supposed to be values,
obligations, duties, oughts, rights, or what not exist, or that facts about
them hold, objectively and that similarly worded ethical statements by
different persons make the same factual claims and thus do not concern merely
the speaker’s feelings. To say that a fact is objective, or that something has
objective existence, is usually to say that its holding or existence is not
derivative from its being thought to hold or exist. In the Scholastic
terminology still current in the seventeenth century ‘objective’ had the more
or less contrary meaning of having status only as an object of thought. In
contrast, fact, or a thing’s existence, is subjective if it holds or exists
only in the sense that it is thought to hold or exist, or that it is merely a
convenient human posit for practical purposes. A fact holds, or an object
exists, intersubjectively if somehow its acknowledgment is binding on all
thinking subjects or all subjects in some specified group, although it does not
hold or exist independently of their thinking about it. Some thinkers suppose
that intersubjectivity is all that can ever properly be meant by objectivity.
Objectivism may be naturalist or non-naturalist. The naturalist objectivist
believes that values, duties, or whatever are natural phenomena detectable by
introspection, perception, or scientific inference. Thus values may be
identified with certain empirical qualities of anybody’s experience, or duties
with empirical facts about the effects of action, e.g. as promoting or
hindering social cohesion. The non-naturalist objectivist eschewing what Moore
called the naturalistic fallacy believes that values or obligations or whatever
items he thinks most basic in ethics exist independently of any belief about
them, but that their existence is not a matter of any ordinary fact detectable
in the above ways but can be revealed to ethical intuition as standing in a
necessary but not analytic relation to natural phenomena. ‘Ethical
subjectivism’ usually means the doctrine that ethical statements are simply
reports on the speaker’s feelings though, confusingly enough, such statements
may be objectively true or false. Perhaps it ought to mean the doctrine that
nothing is good or bad but thinking makes it so. Attitude theories of morality,
for which such statements express, rather than report upon, the speaker’s
feelings, are also, despite the objections of their proponents, sometimes
called subjectivist. In a more popular usage an objective matter of fact is one
on which all reasonable persons can be expected to agree, while a matter is
subjective if various alternative opinions can be accepted as reasonable. What
is subjective in this sense may be quite objective in the more philosophical
sense in question above. -- ethics, the
philosophical study of morality. The word is also commonly used interchangeably
with ‘morality’ to mean the subject matter of this study; and sometimes it is
used more narrowly to mean the moral principles of a particular tradition,
group, or individual. Christian ethics and Albert Schweitzer’s ethics are
examples. In this article the word will be used exclusively to mean the
philosophical study. Ethics, along with logic, metaphysics, and epistemology,
is one of the main branches of philosophy. It corresponds, in the traditional
division of the field into formal, natural, and moral philosophy, to the last
of these disciplines. It can in turn be divided into the general study of
goodness, the general study of right action, applied ethics, metaethics, moral
psychology, and the metaphysics of moral responsibility. These divisions are
not sharp, and many important studies in ethics, particularly those that
examine or develop whole systems of ethics, are interdivisional. Nonetheless,
they facilitate the identification of different problems, movements, and
schools within the discipline. The first two, the general study of goodness and
the general study of right action, constitute the main business of ethics.
Correlatively, its principal substantive questions are what ends we ought, as
fully rational human beings, to choose and pursue and what moral principles
should govern our choices and pursuits. How these questions are related is the
discipline’s principal structural question, and structural differences among
systems of ethics reflect different answers to this question. In contemporary
ethics, the study of structure has come increasingly to the fore, especially as
a preliminary to the general study of right action. In the natural order of
exposition, however, the substantive questions come first. Goodness and the
question of ends. Philosophers have typically treated the question of the ends
we ought to pursue in one of two ways: either as a question about the
components of a good life or as a question about what sorts of things are good
in themselves. On the first way of treating the question, it is assumed that we
naturally seek a good life; hence, determining its components amounts to
determining, relative to our desire for such a life, what ends we ought to
pursue. On the second way, no such assumption about human nature is made;
rather it is assumed that whatever is good in itself is worth choosing or
pursuing. The first way of treating the question leads directly to the theory
of human well-being. The second way leads directly to the theory of intrinsic
value. The first theory originated in ancient ethics, and eudaimonia was the
Grecian word for its subject, a word usually tr. ‘happiness,’ but sometimes tr.
‘flourishing’ in order to make the question of human well-being seem more a
matter of how well a person is doing than how good he is feeling. These
alternatives reflect the different conceptions of human well-being that inform
the two major views within the theory: the view that feeling good or pleasure
is the essence of human well-being and the view that doing well or excelling at
things worth doing is its essence. The first view is hedonism in its classical
form. Its most famous exponent among the ancients was Epicurus. The second view
is perfectionism, a view that is common to several schools of ancient ethics.
Its adherents include Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics. Among the moderns, the
best-known defenders of classical hedonism and perfectionism are respectively
J. S. Mill and Nietzsche. Although these two views differ on the question of
what human well-being essentially consists in, neither thereby denies that the
other’s answer has a place in a good human life. Indeed, mature statements of
each typically assign the other’s answer an ancillary place. Thus, hedonism, as
expounded by Epicurus, takes excelling at things worth doing exercising one’s intellectual powers and
moral virtues in exemplary and fruitful ways, e.g. as the tried and true means to experiencing
life’s most satisfying pleasures. And perfectionism, as developed in
Aristotle’s ethics, underscores the importance of pleasure the deep satisfaction that comes from doing
an important job well, e.g. as a natural
concomitant of achieving excellence in things that matter. The two views, as
expressed in these mature statements, differ not so much in the kinds of
activities they take to be central to a good life as in the ways they explain
the goodness of such a life. The chief difference between them, then, is
philosophical rather than prescriptive. The second theory, the theory of
intrinsic value, also has roots in ancient ethics, specifically, Plato’s theory
of Forms. But unlike Plato’s theory, the basic tenets of which include certain
doctrines about the reality and transcendence of value, the theory of intrinsic
value neither contains nor presupposes any metaphysical theses. At issue in the
theory is what things are good in themselves, and one can take a position on
this issue without committing oneself to any thesis about the reality or
unreality of goodness or about its transcendence or immanence. A list of the
different things philosophers have considered good in themselves would include
life, happiness, pleasure, knowledge, virtue, friendship, beauty, and harmony.
The list could easily be extended. An interest in what constitutes the goodness
of the various items on the list has brought philosophers to focus primarily on
the question of whether something unites them. The opposing views on this
question are monism and pluralism. Monists affirm the list’s unity; pluralists
deny it. Plato, for instance, was a monist. He held that the goodness of
everything good in itself consisted in harmony and therefore each such thing
owed its goodness to its being harmonious. Alternatively, some philosophers
have proposed pleasure as the sole constituent of goodness. Indeed, conceiving
of pleasure as a particular kind of experience or state of consciousness, they
have proposed this kind of experience as the only thing good in itself and
characterized all other good things as instrumentally good, as owing their
goodness to their being sources of pleasure. Thus, hedonism too can be a
species of monism. In this case, though, one must distinguish between the view
that it is one’s own experiences of pleasure that are intrinsically good and
the view that anyone’s experiences of pleasure, indeed, any sentient being’s
experiences of pleasure, are intrinsically good. The former is called by
Sidgwick egoistic hedonism, the latter universal hedonism. This distinction can
be made general, as a distinction between egoistic and universal views of what
is good in itself or, as philosophers now commonly say, between agent-relative
and agent-neutral value. As such, it indicates a significant point of
disagreement in the theory of intrinsic value, a disagreement in which the
seeming arbitrariness and blindness of egoism make it harder to defend. In
drawing this conclusion, however, one must be careful not to mistake these
egoistic views for views in the theory of human well-being, for each set of
views represents a set of alternative answers to a different question. One must
be careful, in other words, not to infer from the greater defensibility of
universalism vis-à-vis egoism that universalism is the predominant view in the
general study of goodness. Right action. The general study of right action
concerns the principles of right and wrong that govern our choices and
pursuits. In modern ethics these principles are typically given a jural
conception. Accordingly, they are understood to constitute a moral code that
defines the duties of men and women who live together in fellowship. This
conception of moral principles is chiefly due to the influence of Christianity
in the West, though some of its elements were already present in Stoic ethics.
Its ascendancy in the general study of right action puts the theory of duty at
the center of that study. The theory has two parts: the systematic exposition
of the moral code that defines our duties; and its justification. The first
part, when fully developed, presents complete formulations of the fundamental
principles of right and wrong and shows how they yield all moral duties. The
standard model is an axiomatic system in mathematics, though some philosophers
have proposed a technical system of an applied science, such as medicine or
strategy, as an alternative. The second part, if successful, establishes the
authority of the principles and so validates the code. Various methods and
criteria of justification are commonly used; no single one is canonical.
Success in establishing the principles’ authority depends on the soundness of the
argument that proceeds from whatever method or criterion is used. One
traditional criterion is implicit in the idea of an axiomatic system. On this
criterion, the fundamental principles of right and wrong are authoritative in
virtue of being self-evident truths. That is, they are regarded as comparable
to axioms not only in being the first principles of a deductive system but also
in being principles whose truth can be seen immediately upon reflection. Use of
this criterion to establish the principles’ authority is the hallmark of
intuitionism. Once one of the dominant views in ethics, its position in the
discipline has now been seriously eroded by a strong, twentieth-century tide of
skepticism about all claims of self-evidence. Currently, the most influential
method of justification consistent with using the model of an axiomatic system
to expound the morality of right and wrong draws on the jural conception of its
principles. On this method, the principles are interpreted as expressions of a
legislative will, and accordingly their authority derives from the sovereignty
of the person or collective whose will they are taken to express. The oldest
example of the method’s use is the divine command theory. On this theory, moral
principles are taken to be laws issued by God to humanity, and their authority
thus derives from God’s supremacy. The theory is the original Christian source
of the principles’ jural conception. The rise of secular thought since the
Enlightenment has, however, limited its appeal. Later examples, which continue
to attract broad interest and discussion, are formalism and contractarianism.
Formalism is best exemplified in Kant’s ethics. It takes a moral principle to
be a precept that satisfies the formal criteria of a universal law, and it takes
formal criteria to be the marks of pure reason. Consequently, moral principles
are laws that issue from reason. As Kant puts it, they are laws that we, as
rational beings, give to ourselves and that regulate our conduct insofar as we
engage each other’s rational nature. They are laws for a republic of reason or,
as Kant says, a kingdom of ends whose legislature comprises all rational
beings. Through this ideal, Kant makes intelligible and forceful the otherwise
obscure notion that moral principles derive their authority from the
sovereignty of reason. Contractarianism also draws inspiration from Kant’s
ethics as well as from the social contract theories of Locke and Rousseau. Its
fullest and most influential statement appears in the work of Rawls. On this
view, moral principles represent the ideal terms of social cooperation for
people who live together in fellowship and regard each other as equals.
Specifically, they are taken to be the conditions of an ideal agreement among
such people, an agreement that they would adopt if they met as an assembly of
equals to decide collectively on the social arrangements governing their
relations and reached their decision as a result of open debate and rational
deliberation. The authority of moral principles derives, then, from the
fairness of the procedures by which the terms of social cooperation would be
arrived at in this hypothetical constitutional convention and the assumption
that any rational individual who wanted to live peaceably with others and who
imagined himself a party to this convention would, in view of the fairness of
its procedures, assent to its results. It derives, that is, from the
hypothetical consent of the governed. Philosophers who think of a moral code on
the model of a technical system of an applied science use an entirely different
method of justification. In their view, just as the principles of medicine
represent knowledge about how best to promote health, so the principles of
right and wrong represent knowledge about how best to promote the ends of
morality. These philosophers, then, have a teleological conception of the code.
Our fundamental duty is to promote certain ends, and the principles of right
and wrong organize and direct our efforts in this regard. What justifies the
principles, on this view, is that the ends they serve are the right ones to
promote and the actions they prescribe are the best ways to promote them. The
principles are authoritative, in other words, in virtue of the wisdom of their
prescriptions. Different teleological views in the theory of duty correspond to
different answers to the question of what the right ends to promote are. The
most common answer is happiness; and the main division among the corresponding
views mirrors the distinction in the theory of intrinsic value between egoism
and universalism. Thus, egoism and universalism in the theory of duty hold,
respectively, that the fundamental duty of morality is to promote, as best as
one can, one’s own happiness and that it is to promote, as best as one can, the
happiness of humanity. The former is ethical egoism and is based on the ideal
of rational self-love. The latter is utilitarianism and is based on the ideal
of rational benevolence. Ethical egoism’s most famous exponents in modern
philosophy are Hobbes and Spinoza. It has had few distinguished defenders since
their time. Bentham and J. S. Mill head the list of distinguished defenders of
utilitarianism. The view continues to be enormously influential. On these
teleological views, answers to questions about the ends we ought to pursue
determine the principles of right and wrong. Put differently, the general study
of right action, on these views, is subordinate to the general study of
goodness. This is one of the two leading answers to the structural question about
how the two studies are related. The other is that the general study of right
action is to some extent independent of the general study of goodness. On views
that represent this answer, some principles of right and wrong, notably
principles of justice and honesty, prescribe actions even though more evil than
good would result from doing them. These views are deontological. Fiat justitia
ruat coelum captures their spirit. The opposition between teleology and
deontology in ethics underlies many of the disputes in the general study of
right action. The principal substantive and structural questions of ethics
arise not only with respect to the conduct of human life generally but also
with respect to specific walks of life such as medicine, law, journalism, engineering,
and business. The examination of these questions in relation to the common
practices and traditional codes of such professions and occupations has
resulted in the special studies of applied ethics. In these studies, ideas and
theories from the general studies of goodness and right action are applied to
particular circumstances and problems of some profession or occupation, and
standard philosophical techniques are used to define, clarify, and organize the
ethical issues found in its domain. In medicine, in particular, where rapid
advances in technology create, overnight, novel ethical problems on matters of
life and death, the study of biomedical ethics has generated substantial
interest among practitioners and scholars alike. Metaethics. To a large extent,
the general studies of goodness and right action and the special studies of
applied ethics consist in systematizing, deepening, and revising our beliefs
about how we ought to conduct our lives. At the same time, it is characteristic
of philosophers, when reflecting on such systems of belief, to examine the
nature and grounds of these beliefs. These questions, when asked about ethical
beliefs, define the field of metaethics. The relation of this field to the
other studies is commonly represented by taking the other studies to constitute
the field of ethics proper and then taking metaethics to be the study of the
concepts, methods of justification, and ontological assumptions of the field of
ethics proper. Accordingly, metaethics can proceed from either an interest in
the epistemology of ethics or an interest in its metaphysics. On the first
approach, the study focuses on questions about the character of ethical
knowledge. Typically, it concentrates on the simplest ethical beliefs, such as
‘Stealing is wrong’ and ‘It is better to give than to receive’, and proceeds by
analyzing the concepts in virtue of which these beliefs are ethical and
examining their logical basis. On the second approach, the study focuses on
questions about the existence and character of ethical properties. Typically,
it concentrates on the most general ethical predicates such as goodness and
wrongfulness and considers whether there truly are ethical properties
represented by these predicates and, if so, whether and how they are interwoven
into the natural world. The two approaches are complementary. Neither dominates
the other. The epistemological approach is comparative. It looks to the most
successful branches of knowledge, the natural sciences and pure mathematics,
for paradigms. The former supplies the paradigm of knowledge that is based on
observation of natural phenomena; the latter supplies the paradigm of knowledge
that seemingly results from the sheer exercise of reason. Under the influence
of these paradigms, three distinct views have emerged: naturalism, rationalism,
and noncognitivism. Naturalism takes ethical knowledge to be empirical and
accordingly models it on the paradigm of the natural sciences. Ethical
concepts, on this view, concern natural phenomena. Rationalism takes ethical
knowledge to be a priori and accordingly models it on the paradigm of pure
mathematics. Ethical concepts, on this view, concern morality understood as
something completely distinct from, though applicable to, natural phenomena,
something whose content and structure can be apprehended by reason
independently of sensory inputs. Noncognitivism, in opposition to these other
views, denies that ethics is a genuine branch of knowledge or takes it to be a
branch of knowledge only in a qualified sense. In either case, it denies that
ethics is properly modeled on science or mathematics. On the most extreme form
of noncognitivism, there are no genuine ethical concepts; words like ‘right’,
‘wrong’, ‘good’, and ‘evil’ have no cognitive meaning but rather serve to vent
feelings and emotions, to express decisions and commitments, or to influence
attitudes and dispositions. On less extreme forms, these words are taken to
have some cognitive meaning, but conveying that meaning is held to be decidedly
secondary to the purposes of venting feelings, expressing decisions, or
influencing attitudes. Naturalism is well represented in the work of Mill;
rationalism in the works of Kant and the intuitionists. And noncognitivism,
which did not emerge as a distinctive view until the twentieth century, is most
powerfully expounded in the works of C. L. Stevenson and Hare. Its central
tenets, however, were anticipated by Hume, whose skeptical attacks on
rationalism set the agenda for subsequent work in metaethics. The metaphysical
approach is centered on the question of objectivity, the question of whether
ethical predicates represent real properties of an external world or merely
apparent or invented properties, properties that owe their existence to the
perception, feeling, or thought of those who ascribe them. Two views dominate
this approach. The first, moral realism, affirms the real existence of ethical
properties. It takes them to inhere in the external world and thus to exist
independently of their being perceived. For moral realism, ethics is an
objective discipline, a discipline that promises discovery and confirmation of
objective truths. At the same time, moral realists differ fundamentally on the
question of the character of ethical properties. Some, such as Plato and Moore,
regard them as purely intellective and thus irreducibly distinct from empirical
properties. Others, such as Aristotle and Mill, regard them as empirical and
either reducible to or at least supervenient on other empirical properties. The
second view, moral subjectivism, denies the real existence of ethical
properties. On this view, to predicate, say, goodness of a person is to impose
some feeling, impulse, or other state of mind onto the world, much as one
projects an emotion onto one’s circumstances when one describes them as
delightful or sad. On the assumption of moral subjectivism, ethics is not a
source of objective truth. In ancient philosophy, moral subjectivism was
advanced by some of the Sophists, notably Protagoras. In modern philosophy, Hume
expounded it in the eighteenth century and Sartre in the twentieth century.
Regardless of approach, one and perhaps the central problem of metaethics is
how value is related to fact. On the epistemological approach, this problem is
commonly posed as the question of whether judgments of value are derivable from
statements of fact. Or, to be more exact, can there be a logically valid
argument whose conclusion is a judgment of value and all of whose premises are
statements of fact? On the metaphysical approach, the problem is commonly posed
as the question of whether moral predicates represent properties that are
explicable as complexes of empirical properties. At issue, in either case, is
whether ethics is an autonomous discipline, whether the study of moral values
and principles is to some degree independent of the study of observable
properties and events. A negative answer to these questions affirms the
autonomy of ethics; a positive answer denies ethics’ autonomy and implies that
it is a branch of the natural sciences. Moral psychology. Even those who affirm
the autonomy of ethics recognize that some facts, particularly facts of human
psychology, bear on the general studies of goodness and right action. No one
maintains that these studies float free of all conception of human appetite and
passion or that they presuppose no account of the human capacity for voluntary
action. It is generally recognized that an adequate understanding of desire,
emotion, deliberation, choice, volition, character, and personality is
indispensable to the theoretical treatment of human well-being, intrinsic
value, and duty. Investigations into the nature of these psychological
phenomena are therefore an essential, though auxiliary, part of ethics. They
constitute the adjunct field of moral psychology. One area of particular
interest within this field is the study of those capacities by virtue of which
men and women qualify as moral agents, beings who are responsible for their
actions. This study is especially important to the theory of duty since that
theory, in modern philosophy, characteristically assumes a strong doctrine of
individual responsibility. That is, it assumes principles of culpability for
wrongdoing that require, as conditions of justified blame, that the act of wrongdoing
be one’s own and that it not be done innocently. Only moral agents are capable
of meeting these conditions. And the presumption is that normal, adult human
beings qualify as moral agents whereas small children and nonhuman animals do
not. The study then focuses on those capacities that distinguish the former
from the latter as responsible beings. The main issue is whether the power of
reason alone accounts for these capacities. On one side of the issue are
philosophers like Kant who hold that it does. Reason, in their view, is both
the pilot and the engine of moral agency. It not only guides one toward actions
in conformity with one’s duty, but it also produces the desire to do one’s duty
and can invest that desire with enough strength to overrule conflicting
impulses of appetite and passion. On the other side are philosophers, such as
Hume and Mill, who take reason to be one of several capacities that constitute
moral agency. On their view, reason works strictly in the service of natural
and sublimated desires, fears, and aversions to produce intelligent action, to
guide its possessor toward the objects of those desires and away from the
objects of those fears. It cannot, however, by itself originate any desire or
fear. Thus, the desire to act rightly, the aversion to acting wrongly, which
are constituents of moral agency, are not products of reason but are instead
acquired through some mechanical process of socialization by which their
objects become associated with the objects of natural desires and aversions. On
one view, then, moral agency consists in the power of reason to govern
behavior, and being rational is thus sufficient for being responsible for one’s
actions. On the other view, moral agency consists in several things including
reason, but also including a desire to act rightly and an aversion to acting
wrongly that originate in natural desires and aversions. On this view, to be
responsible for one’s actions, one must not only be rational but also have
certain desires and aversions whose acquisition is not guaranteed by the
maturation of reason. Within moral psychology, one cardinal test of these views
is how well they can accommodate and explain such common experiences of moral
agency as conscience, weakness, and moral dilemma. At some point, however, the
views must be tested by questions about freedom. For one cannot be responsible
for one’s actions if one is incapable of acting freely, which is to say, of
one’s own free will. The capacity for free action is thus essential to moral
agency, and how this capacity is to be explained, whether it fits within a
deterministic universe, and if not, whether the notion of moral responsibility
should be jettisoned, are among the deepest questions that the student of moral
agency must face. What is more, they are not questions to which moral
psychology can furnish answers. At this point, ethics descends into
metaphysics. ethnography, an open-ended
family of techniques through which anthropologists investigate cultures; also,
the organized descriptions of other cultures that result from this method.
Cultural anthropology ethnology is based primarily on fieldwork through which
anthropologists immerse themselves in the life of a local culture village,
neighborhood and attempt to describe and interpret aspects of the culture.
Careful observation is one central tool of investigation. Through it the
anthropologist can observe and record various features of social life, e.g.
trading practices, farming techniques, or marriage arrangements. A second
central tool is the interview, through which the researcher explores the
beliefs and values of members of the local culture. Tools of historical
research, including particularly oral history, are also of use in ethnography,
since the cultural practices of interest often derive from a remote point in
time. ethnology, the comparative and
analytical study of cultures; cultural anthroplogy. Anthropologists aim to
describe and interpret aspects of the culture of various social groups e.g., the hunter-gatherers of the Kalahari,
rice villages of the Chin. Canton Delta, or a community of physicists at
Livermore Laboratory. Topics of particular interest include religious beliefs,
linguistic practices, kinship arrangements, marriage patterns, farming
technology, dietary practices, gender relations, and power relations. Cultural
anthropology is generally conceived as an empirical science, and this raises
several methodological and conceptual difficulties. First is the role of the
observer. The injection of an alien observer into the local culture unavoidably
disturbs that culture. Second, there is the problem of intelligibility across
cultural systems radical translation.
One goal of ethnographic research is to arrive at an interpretation of a set of
beliefs and values that are thought to be radically different from the
researcher’s own beliefs and values; but if this is so, then it is questionable
whether they can be accurately tr. into the researcher’s conceptual scheme.
Third, there is the problem of empirical testing of ethnographic
interpretations. To what extent do empirical procedures constrain the
construction of an interpretation of a given cultural milieu? Finally, there is
the problem of generalizability. To what extent does fieldwork in one location
permit anthropologists to generalize to a larger context other villages, the dispersed ethnic group
represented by this village, or this village at other times? ethnomethodology, a phenomenological approach
to interpreting everyday action and speech in various social contexts. Derived
from phenomenological sociology and introduced by Harold Garfinkel, the method
aims to guide research into meaningful social practices as experienced by
participants. A major objective of the method is to interpret the rules that
underlie everyday activity and thus constitute part of the normative basis of a
given social order. Research from this perspective generally focuses on mundane
social activities e.g., psychiatrists
evaluating patients’ files, jurors deliberating on defendants’ culpability, or
coroners judging causes of death. The investigator then attempts to reconstruct
an underlying set of rules and ad hoc procedures that may be taken to have
guided the observed activity. The approach emphasizes the contextuality of
social practice the richness of unspoken
shared understandings that guide and orient participants’ actions in a given
practice or activity. H. P. Grice, “The Teutons, according to Tacitus.”
dilemma. Grice: “Ryle overuses the word
dilemma in his popularization, “Dilemmas”.” 1 Any problem where morality is
relevant. This broad use includes not only conflicts among moral reasons but
also conflicts between moral reasons and reasons of law, religion, or
self-interest. In this sense, Abraham is in a moral dilemma when God commands
him to sacrifice his son, even if he has no moral reason to obey. Similarly, I
am in a moral dilemma if I cannot help a friend in trouble without forgoing a
lucrative but morally neutral business opportunity. ’Moral dilemma’ also often
refers to 2 any topic area where it is not known what, if anything, is morally
good or right. For example, when one asks whether abortion is immoral in any
way, one could call the topic “the moral dilemma of abortion.” This epistemic
use does not imply that anything really is immoral at all. Recently, moral
philosophers have discussed a much narrower set of situations as “moral
dilemmas.” They usually define ‘moral dilemma’ as 3 a situation where an agent
morally ought to do each of two acts but cannot do both. The bestknown example
is Sartre’s student who morally ought to care for his mother in Paris but at
the same time morally ought to go to England to join the Free and fight the Nazis. However, ‘ought’ covers
ideal actions that are not morally required, such as when someone ought to give
to a certain charity but is not required to do so. Since most common examples
of moral dilemmas include moral obligations or duties, or other requirements,
it is more accurate to define ‘moral dilemma’ more narrowly as 4 a situation
where an agent has a moral requirement to do each of two acts but cannot do
both. Some philosophers also refuse to call a situation a moral dilemma when
one of the conflicting requirements is clearly overridden, such as when I must
break a trivial promise in order to save a life. To exclude such resolvable
conflicts, ‘moral dilemma’ can be defined as 5 a situation where an agent has a
moral requirement to adopt each of two alternatives, and neither requirement is
overridden, but the agent cannot fulfill both. Another common move is to define
‘moral dilemma’ as 6 a situation where every alternative is morally wrong. This
is equivalent to 4 or 5, respectively, if an act is morally wrong whenever it
violates any moral requirement or any non-overridden moral requirement.
However, we usually do not call an act wrong unless it violates an overriding
moral requirement, and then 6 rules out moral dilemmas by definition, since
overriding moral requirements clearly cannot conflict. Although 5 thus seems
preferable, some would object that 5 includes trivial requirements and
conflicts, such as conflicts between trivial promises. To include only tragic
situations, we could define ‘moral dilemma’ as 7 a situation where an agent has
a strong moral obligation or requirement to adopt each of two alternatives, and
neither is overridden, but the agent cannot adopt both alternatives. This
definition is strong enough to raise the important controversies about moral
dilemmas without being so strong as to rule out their possibility by definition.
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Ryle’s dilemmas: are they?”
epistemology, the discipline, at the
intersection of ethics and epistemology, that studies the epistemic status and
relations of moral judgments and principles. It has developed out of an
interest, common to both ethics and epistemology, in questions of justification
and justifiability in epistemology, of
statements or beliefs, and in ethics, of actions as well as judgments of
actions and also general principles of judgment. Its most prominent questions
include the following. Can normative claims be true or false? If so, how can
they be known to be true or false? If not, what status do they have, and are
they capable of justification? If they are capable of justification, how can
they be justified? Does the justification of normative claims differ with
respect to particular claims and with respect to general principles? In
epistemology recent years have seen a tendency to accept as valid an account of
knowledge as entailing justified true belief, a conception that requires an
account not just of truth but also of justification and of justified belief.
Thus, under what conditions is someone justified, epistemically, in believing
something? Justification, of actions, of judgments, and of principles, has long
been a central element in ethics. It is only recently that justification in
ethics came to be thought of as an epistemological problem, hence ‘moral
epistemology’, as an expression, is a fairly recent coinage, although its
problems have a long lineage. One long-standing linkage is provided by the
challenge of skepticism. Skepticism in ethics can be about the existence of any
genuine distinction between right and wrong, or it can focus on the possibility
of attaining any knowledge of right and wrong, good or bad. Is there a right
answer? is a question in the metaphysics of ethics. Can we know what the right
answer is, and if so how? is one of moral epistemology. Problems of perception
and observation and ones about observation statements or sense-data play an
important role in epistemology. There is not any obvious parallel in moral
epistemology, unless it is the role of prereflective moral judgments, or
commonsense moral judgments moral
judgments unguided by any overt moral theory
which can be taken to provide the data of moral theory, and which need
to be explained, systematized, coordinated, or revised to attain an appropriate
relation between theory and data. This would be analogous to taking the data of
epistemology to be provided, not by sense-data or observations but by judgments
of perception or observation statements. Once this step is taken the parallel
is very close. One source of moral skepticism is the apparent lack of any
observational counterpart for moral predicates, which generates the question
how moral judgments can be true if there is nothing for them to correspond to.
Another source of moral skepticism is apparently constant disagreement and
uncertainty, which would appear to be explained by the skeptical hypothesis
denying the reality of moral distinctions. Noncognitivism in ethics maintains
that moral judgments are not objects of knowledge, that they make no statements
capable of truth or falsity, but are or are akin to expressions of attitudes.
Some other major differences among ethical theories are largely epistemological
in character. Intuitionism maintains that basic moral propositions are knowable
by intuition. Empiricism in ethics maintains that moral propositions can be
established by empirical means or are complex forms of empirical statements.
Ethical rationalism maintains that the fundamental principles of morality can
be established a priori as holding of necessity. This is exemplified by Kant’s
moral philosophy, in which the categorical imperative is regarded as synthetic a
priori; more recently by what Alan Gewirth b.2 calls the “principle of generic
consistency,” which he claims it is selfcontradictory to deny. Ethical
empiricism is exemplified by classical utilitarianism, such as that of Bentham,
which aspires to develop ethics as an empirical science. If the consequences of
actions can be scientifically predicted and their utilities calculated, then
ethics can be a science. Situationism is equivalent to concrete case
intuitionism in maintaining that we can know immediately what ought to be done
in specific cases, but most ethical theories maintain that what ought to be
done is, in J. S. Mill’s words, determined by “the application of a law to an
individual case.” Different theories differ on the epistemic status of these laws
and on the process of application. Deductivists, either empiricistic or
rationalistic, hold that the law is essentially unchanged in the application;
non-deductivists hold that the law is modified in the process of application.
This distinction is explained in F. L. Will, “Beyond Deduction.” There is
similar variation about what if anything is selfevident, Sidgwick maintaining
that only certain highly abstract principles are self-evident, Ross that only
general rules are, and Prichard that only concrete judgments are, “by an act of
moral thinking.” Other problems in moral epistemology are provided by the
factvalue distinction and controversies
about whether there is any such distinction
and the isought question, the question how a moral judgment can be derived
from statements of fact alone. Naturalists affirm the possibility,
non-naturalists deny it. Prescriptivists claim that moral judgments are
prescriptions and cannot be deduced from descriptive statements alone. This
question ultimately leads to the question how an ultimate principle can be
justified. If it cannot be deduced from statements of fact, that route is out;
if it must be deduced from some other moral principle, then the principle
deduced cannot be ultimate and in any case this process is either circular or
leads to an infinite regress. If the ultimate principle is self-evident, then
the problem may have an answer. But if it is not it would appear to be
arbitrary. The problem of the justification of an ultimate principle continues
to be a leading one in moral epistemology. Recently there has been much
interest in the status and existence of “moral facts.” Are there any, what are
they, and how are they established as “facts”? This relates to questions about
moral realism. Moral realism maintains that moral predicates are real and can
be known to be so; anti-realists deny this. This denial links with the view
that moral properties supervene on natural ones, and the problem of
supervenience is another recent link between ethics and epistemology. Pragmatism
in ethics maintains that a moral problem is like any problem in that it is the
occasion for inquiry and moral judgments are to be regarded as hypotheses to be
tested by how well they resolve the problem. This amounts to an attempt to
bypass the isought problem and all such “dualisms.” So is constructivism, a
development owing much to the work of Rawls, which contrasts with moral
realism. Constructivism maintains that moral ideas are human constructs and the
task is not epistemological or metaphysical but practical and theoretical that of attaining reflective equilibrium
between considered moral judgments and the principles that coordinate and
explain them. On this view there are no moral facts. Opponents maintain that
this only replaces a foundationalist view of ethics with a coherence
conception. The question whether questions of moral epistemology can in this
way be bypassed can be regarded as itself a question of moral epistemology. And
the question of the foundations of morality, and whether there are foundations,
can still be regarded as a question of moral epistemology, as distinct from a
question of the most convenient and efficient arrangement of our moral ideas.
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Our knowledge of right and wrong: do we have it? Is it intuitive
as Oxonians believe?”
mos: ethos -- meta-ethics:
morality, an informal public system applying to all rational persons, governing
behavior that affects others, having the lessening of evil or harm as its goal,
and including what are commonly known as the moral rules, moral ideals, and
moral virtues. To say that it is a public system means that all those to whom
it applies must understand it and that it must not be irrational for them to
use it in deciding what to do and in judging others to whom the system applies.
Games are the paradigm cases of public systems; all games have a point and the
rules of a game apply to all who play it. All players know the point of the
game and its rules, and it is not irrational for them to be guided by the point
and rules and to judge the behavior of other players by them. To say that
morality is informal means that there is no decision procedure or authority
that can settle all its controversial questions. Morality thus resembles a
backyard game of basketball more than a professional game. Although there is
overwhelming agreement on most moral matters, certain controversial questions
must be settled in an ad hoc fashion or not settled at all. For example, when,
if ever, abortion is acceptable is an unresolvable moral matter, but each
society and religion can adopt its own position. That morality has no one in a
position of authority is one of the most important respects in which it differs
from law and religion. Although morality must include the commonly accepted
moral rules such as those prohibiting killing and deceiving, different
societies can interpret these rules somewhat differently. They can also differ
in their views about the scope of morality, i.e., about whether morality
protects newborns, fetuses, or non-human animals. Thus different societies can
have somewhat different moralities, although this difference has limits. Also
within each society, a person may have his own view about when it is justified
to break one of the rules, e.g., about how much harm would have to be prevented
in order to justify deceiving someone. Thus one person’s morality may differ
somewhat from another’s, but both will agree on the overwhelming number of
non-controversial cases. A moral theory is an attempt to describe, explain, and
if possible justify, morality. Unfortunately, most moral theories attempt to
generate some simplified moral code, rather than to describe the complex moral
system that is already in use. Morality does not resolve all disputes. Morality
does not require one always to act so as to produce the best consequences or to
act only in those ways that one would will everyone to act. Rather morality
includes both moral rules that no one should transgress and moral ideals that
all are encouraged to follow, but much of what one does will not be governed by
morality. H. P. Grice, “Meta-ethics in postwar Oxford philosophy: Hare,
Nowell-Smith, myself, and others!” mos,
ethos – meta-ethical -- meta-ethics:, Grice: “The Romans should have a verb for
‘mos,’ since it’s very nominational!” Surely what we need is something like
Austin’s ‘doing things.’” mos ,
mōris, m. etym. dub.; perh. root ma-, measure; cf.: maturus, matutinus; prop.,
a measuring or guiding rule of life; hence, I.manner, custom, way, usage,
practice, fashion, wont, as determined not by the laws, but by men's will and pleasure,
humor, self-will, caprice (class.; cf.: consuetudo, usus). I. Lit.: “opsequens
oboediensque'st mori atque imperiis patris,” Plaut. Bacch. 3, 3, 54: Grice: “Cicero was
being brilliant when he found that ‘mos’ nicely translates Grecian ‘ethos’ –
cf. Grice’s ethology. Ethologica -- Philosophical
ethology -- 1 the subfield of psychology that traces the development over time
of moral reasoning and opinions in the lives of individuals this subdiscipline
includes work of Jean Piaget, Lawrence Kohlberg, and Carol Gilligan; 2 the part
of philosophy where philosophy of mind and ethics overlap, which concerns all
the psychological issues relevant to morality. There are many different
psychological matters relevant to ethics, and each may be relevant in more than
one way. Different ethical theories imply different sorts of connections. So
moral psychology includes work of many and diverse kinds. But several
traditional clusters of concern are evident. Some elements of moral psychology
consider the psychological matters relevant to metaethical issues, i.e., to
issues about the general nature of moral truth, judgment, and knowledge.
Different metaethical theories invoke mental phenomena in different ways:
noncognitivism maintains that sentences expressing moral judgments do not
function to report truths or falsehoods, but rather, e.g., to express certain
emotions or to prescribe certain actions. So some forms of noncognitivism imply
that an understanding of certain sorts of emotions, or of special activities
like prescribing that may involve particular psychological elements, is crucial
to a full understanding of how ethical sentences are meaningful. Certain forms
of cognitivism, the view that moral declarative sentences do express truths or
falsehoods, imply that moral facts consist of psychological facts, that for
instance moral judgments consist of expressions of positive psychological
attitudes of some particular kind toward the objects of those judgments. And an
understanding of psychological phenomena like sentiment is crucial according to
certain sorts of projectivism, which hold that the supposed moral properties of
things are mere misleading projections of our sentiments onto the objects of
those sentiments. Certain traditional moral sense theories and certain
traditional forms of intuitionism have held that special psychological
faculties are crucial for our epistemic access to moral truth. Particular views
in normative ethics, particular views about the moral status of acts, persons,
and other targets of normative evaluation, also often suggest that an
understanding of certain psychological matters is crucial to ethics. Actions,
intentions, and character are some of the targets of evaluation of normative
ethics, and their proper understanding involves many issues in philosophy of
mind. Also, many normative theorists have maintained that there is a close
connection between pleasure, happiness, or desiresatisfaction and a person’s
good, and these things are also a concern of philosophy of mind. In addition,
the rightness of actions is often held to be closely connected to the motives,
beliefs, and other psychological phenomena that lie behind those actions.
Various other traditional philosophical concerns link ethical and psychological
issues: the nature of the patterns in the long-term development in individuals
of moral opinions and reasoning, the appropriate form for moral education and
punishment, the connections between obligation and motivation, i.e., between
moral reasons and psychological causes, and the notion of free will and its
relation to moral responsibility and autonomy. Some work in philosophy of mind
also suggests that moral phenomena, or at least normative phenomena of some
kind, play a crucial role in illuminating or constituting psychological
phenomena of various kinds, but the traditional concern of moral psychology has
been with the articulation of the sort of philosophy of mind that can be useful
to ethics. Refs.: H. P. Grice,
“Meta-ethics in post-war Oxford philosophy: Hare, Nowell-Smith, myself, and
others!” H. P. Grice, “The morality of morality.” H. P. Grice, “Lorenz and the
‘ethologie der ganse.’”
“practical reason” – Grice: “In ‘practical
reason,’ we have Aristotle at his best: the category is ‘action,’ and the
praedicabile is ‘rational.’ Now ‘action’ is supracategorial: It’s STRAWSON who
acts, not his action!” -- -- “Or ‘to do things,’ as Austin would put it!” -- moral
rationalism, the view that the substance of morality, usually in the form of
general moral principles, can be known a priori. The view is defended by Kant
in Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, but it goes back at least to Plato.
Both Plato and Kant thought that a priori moral knowledge could have an impact
on what we do quite independently of any desire that we happen to have. This
motivational view is also ordinarily associated with moral rationalism. It
comes in two quite different forms. The first is that a priori moral knowledge
consists in a sui generis mental state that is both belief-like and
desire-like. This seems to have been Plato’s view, for he held that the belief that
something is good is itself a disposition to promote that thing. The second is
that a priori moral knowledge consists in a belief that is capable of
rationally producing a distinct desire. Rationalists who make the first claim
have had trouble accommodating the possibility of someone’s believing that
something is good but, through weakness of will, not mustering the desire to do
it. Accordingly, they have been forced to assimilate weakness of will to
ignorance of the good. Rationalists who make the second claim about reason’s
action-producing capacity face no such problem. For this reason, their view is
often preferred. The best-known anti-rationalist about morality is Hume. His
Treatise of Human Nature denies both that morality’s substance can be known by
reason alone and that reason alone is capable of producing action.
Griceian realism: a metaethical view
committed to the objectivity of ethics. It has 1 metaphysical, 2 semantic, and
3 epistemological components. 1 Its metaphysical component is the claim that
there are moral facts and moral properties whose existence and nature are
independent of people’s beliefs and attitudes about what is right or wrong. In
this claim, moral realism contrasts with an error theory and with other forms
of nihilism that deny the existence of moral facts and properties. It contrasts
as well with various versions of moral relativism and other forms of ethical
constructivism that make moral facts consist in facts about people’s moral
beliefs and attitudes. 2 Its semantic component is primarily cognitivist.
Cognitivism holds that moral judgments should be construed as assertions about
the moral properties of actions, persons, policies, and other objects of moral
assessment, that moral predicates purport to refer to properties of such
objects, that moral judgments or the propositions that they express can be true
or false, and that cognizers can have the cognitive attitude of belief toward
the propositions that moral judgments express. These cognitivist claims
contrast with the noncognitive claims of emotivism and prescriptivism,
according to which the primary purpose of moral judgments is to express the
appraiser’s attitudes or commitments, rather than to state facts or ascribe
properties. Moral realism also holds that truth for moral judgments is
non-epistemic; in this way it contrasts with moral relativism and other forms
of ethical constructivism that make the truth of a moral judgment epistemic.
The metaphysical and semantic theses imply that there are some true moral propositions.
An error theory accepts the cognitivist semantic claims but denies the realist
metaphysical thesis. It holds that moral judgments should be construed as
containing referring expressions and having truth-values, but insists that
these referring expressions are empty, because there are no moral facts, and
that no moral claims are true. Also on this theory, commonsense moral thought
presupposes the existence of moral facts and properties, but is systematically
in error. In this way, the error theory stands to moral realism much as atheism
stands to theism in a world of theists. J. L. Mackie introduced and defended
the error theory in his Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, 7. 3 Finally, if
moral realism is to avoid skepticism it must claim that some moral beliefs are
true, that there are methods for justifying moral beliefs, and that moral
knowledge is possible. While making these metaphysical, semantic, and
epistemological claims, moral realism is compatible with a wide variety of
other metaphysical, semantic, and epistemological principles and so can take
many different forms. The moral realists in the early part of the twentieth
century were generally intuitionists. Intuitionism combined a commitment to
moral realism with a foundationalist moral epistemology according to which
moral knowledge must rest on self-evident moral truths and with the
nonnaturalist claim that moral facts and properties are sui generis and not
reducible to any natural facts or properties. Friends of noncognitivism found
the metaphysical and epistemological commitments of intuitionism extravagant
and so rejected moral realism. Later moral realists have generally sought to
defend moral realism without the metaphysical and epistemological trappings of
intuitionism. One such version of moral realism takes a naturalistic form. This
form of ethical naturalism claims that our moral beliefs are justified when
they form part of an explanatorily coherent system of beliefs with one another
and with various non-moral beliefs, and insists that moral properties are just
natural properties of the people, actions, and policies that instantiate them.
Debate between realists and anti-realists and within the realist camp centers
on such issues as the relation between moral judgment and action, the rational
authority of morality, moral epistemology and methodology, the relation between
moral and non-moral natural properties, the place of ethics in a naturalistic
worldview, and the parity of ethics and the sciences.
Quinque sense: visum, olfactum, gustum,
tactum, auditum – quinque organa: oculus, etc. Grice: “I am particularly
irritated by Pitcher, of all people, quoting me to refute my idea that a
‘pain-sense’ is an otiosity! Of course
it is!” – “And I used to like Pitcher when he was at Oxford!” -- Some reamarks
about ‘senusus.’ – Grice’s Modified occam’s razor: “Do not multiply senses
beyond necessity – let there be five: visum, auditum, tactum, gustum, and
olfactum --. “Some remarks about the (five?) senses” – Grice: “Grice: “And then
there’s Shaftesbury who thinks he is being witty when he speaks of a ‘moral’
“sense”!” -- moral sense theory, an ethical theory, developed by some British
philosophers notably Shaftesbury,
Hutcheson, and Hume according to which
the pleasure or pain a person feels upon thinking about or “observing” certain
character traits is indicative of the virtue or vice, respectively, of those
features. It is a theory of “moral perception,” offered in response to moral
rationalism, the view that moral distinctions are derived by reason alone, and
combines Locke’s empiricist doctrine that all ideas begin in experience with
the belief, widely shared at the time, that feelings play a central role in
moral evaluation and motivation. On this theory, our emotional responses to
persons’ characters are often “perceptions” of their morality, just as our
experiences of an apple’s redness and sweetness are perceptions of its color
and taste. These ideas of morality are seen as products of an “internal” sense,
because they are produced in the “observer” only after she forms a concept of
the conduct or trait being observed or contemplated as when a person realizes that she is seeing
someone intentionally harm another and reacts with displeasure at what she
sees. The moral sense is conceived as being analogous to, or possibly an aspect
of, our capacity to recognize varying degrees of beauty in things, which modern
writers call “the sense of beauty.” Rejecting the popular view that morality is
based on the will of God, Shaftesbury maintains rather that morality depends on
human nature, and he introduces the notion of a sense of right and wrong,
possessed uniquely by human beings, who alone are capable of reflection.
Hutcheson argues that to approve of a character is to regard it as virtuous.
For him, reason, which discovers relations of inanimate objects to rational
agents, is unable to arouse our approval in the absence of a moral sense.
Ultimately, we can explain why, for example, we approve of someone’s temperate
character only by appealing to our natural tendency to feel pleasure sometimes
identified with approval at the thought of characters that exhibit benevolence,
the trait to which all other virtues can be traced. This disposition to feel
approval and disapproval is what Hutcheson identifies as the moral sense. Hume
emphasizes that typical human beings make moral distinctions on the basis of
their feelings only when those sentiments are experienced from a disinterested
or “general” point of view. In other words, we turn our initial sentiments into
moral judgments by compensating for the fact that we feel more strongly about
those to whom we are emotionally close than those from whom we are more
distant. On a widely held interpretation of Hume, the moral sense provides not
only judgments, but also motives to act according to those judgments, since its
feelings may be motivating passions or arouse such passions. Roderick Firth’s
787 twentieth-century ideal observer theory, according to which moral good is
designated by the projected reactions of a hypothetically omniscient,
disinterested observer possessing other ideal traits, as well as Brandt’s
contemporary moral spectator theory, are direct descendants of the moral sense
theory. Refs: H. P. Grice:
“Shaftesbury’s moral sense: some remarks about the ‘senses’ of this
‘expression’!” Refs.: H. P. Grice, G. J. Warnock, and J. O. Urmson: “The Roman
names for the five senses.” Luigi Speranza, “The senses in iconography.” The
Anglo-American Club. --.
mos, costume – Grice: “Can a single
individual have an idio-mos, a practice? He certainly can device a set of
pratices that nobody ever puts into use, as in my New Hightway Code, or my
Deutero-Esperanto.” moral scepticism, any metaethical view that raises
fundamental doubts about morality as a whole. Different kinds of doubts lead to
different kinds of moral skepticism. The primary kinds of moral skepticism are
epistemological. Moral justification skepticism is the claim that nobody ever
has any or adequate justification for believing any substantive moral claim.
Moral knowledge skepticism is the claim that nobody ever knows that any
substantive moral claim is true. If knowledge implies justification, as is
often assumed, then moral justification skepticism implies moral knowledge
skepticism. But even if knowledge requires justification, it requires more, so
moral knowledge skepticism does not imply moral justification skepticism.
Another kind of skeptical view in metaethics rests on linguistic analysis. Some
emotivists, expressivists, and prescriptivists argue that moral claims like
“Cheating is morally wrong” resemble expressions of emotion or desire like
“Boo, cheating” or prescriptions for action like “Don’t cheat”, which are
neither true nor false, so moral claims themselves are neither true nor false.
This linguistic moral skepticism, which is sometimes called noncognitivism,
implies moral knowledge skepticism if knowledge implies truth. Even if such
linguistic analyses are rejected, one can still hold that no moral properties
or facts really exist. This ontological moral skepticism can be combined with the
linguistic view that moral claims assert moral properties and facts to yield an
error theory that all positive moral claims are false. A different kind of
doubt about morality is often raised by asking, “Why should I be moral?”
Practical moral skepticism answers that there is not always any reason or any
adequate reason to be moral or to do what is morally required. This view
concerns reasons to act rather than reasons to believe. Moral skepticism of all
these kinds is often seen as immoral, but moral skeptics can act and be
motivated and even hold moral beliefs in much the same way as non-skeptics.
Moral skeptics just deny that their or anyone else’s moral beliefs are
justified or known or true, or that they have adequate reason to be moral. moral
status, the suitability of a being to be viewed as an appropriate object of
direct moral concern; the nature or degree of a being’s ability to count as a
ground of claims against moral agents; the moral standing, rank, or importance
of a kind of being; the condition of being a moral patient; moral
considerability. Ordinary moral reflection involves considering others. But
which others ought to be considered? And how are the various objects of moral
consideration to be weighed against one another? Anything might be the topic of
moral discussion, but not everything is thought to be an appropriate object of
direct moral concern. If there are any ethical constraints on how we may treat
a ceramic plate, these seem to derive from considerations about other beings,
not from the interests or good or nature of the plate. The same applies,
presumably, to a clod of earth. Many philosophers view a living but insentient
being, such as a dandelion, in the same way; others have doubts. According to
some, even sentient animal life is little more deserving of moral consideration
than the clod or the dandelion. This tradition, which restricts significant
moral status to humans, has come under vigorous and varied attack by defenders
of animal liberation. This attack criticizes speciesism, and argues that
“humanism” is analogous to theories that illegitimately base moral status on
race, gender, or social class. Some philosophers have referred to beings that
are appropriate objects of direct moral concern as “moral patients.” Moral agents
are those beings whose actions are subject to moral evaluation; analogously,
moral patients would be those beings whose suffering in the sense of being the
objects of the actions of moral agents permits or demands moral evaluation.
Others apply the label ‘moral patients’ more narrowly, just to those beings
that are appropriate objects of direct moral concern but are not also moral
agents. The issue of moral status concerns not only whether beings count at all
morally, but also to what degree they count. After all, beings who are moral
patients might still have their claims outweighed by the preferred claims of
other beings who possess some special moral status. We might, with Nozick,
propose “utilitarianism for animals, Kantianism for people.” Similarly, the
bodily autonomy argument in defense of abortion, made famous by Thomson, does
not deny that the fetus is a moral patient, but insists that her/his/its claims
are limited by the pregnant woman’s prior claim to control her bodily destiny.
It has often been thought that moral status should be tied to the condition of
“personhood.” The idea has been either that only persons are moral patients, or
that persons possess a special moral status that makes them morally more
important than nonpersons. Personhood, on such theories, is a minimal condition
for moral patiency. Why? Moral patiency is said to be “correlative” with moral
agency: a creature has both or neither. Alternatively, persons have been viewed
not as the only moral patients, but as a specially privileged elite among moral
patients, possessing rights as well as interests.
more grice to
the mill: SOUS-ENTENDU,
-UE, part. passé, adj. et subst. masc. I. − Part. passé de sous-entendre*. A. −
Empl. impers. Il est sous-entendu que + complét. à l'ind. Il est inutile de
préciser que. Synon. il va sans dire que.Elle lui écrivit (...) que (...) elle
aurait enfin, après avoir été si souvent reçue chez eux, le plaisir de les
inviter à son tour. De lui, elle ne disait pas un mot, il était sous-entendu
que leur présence excluait la sienne (Proust,Swann,1913, p. 301). B. − Empl.
ell. à valeur de prop. part. Sous-entendu (inv., le locuteur suppléant ce qui
n'est pas exprimé mais suggéré). Ce qui signifie par là (que). Mon cher Ami,
Encore une! sous-entendu: demande de croix d'honneur (Flaub.,Corresp.,1871, p.
287). II. − Adjectif A. − Synon. implicite, tacite; anton. avoué, explicite,
formulé. 1. Qu'on laisse entendre sans l'exprimer. Le lendemain, à table, mon
mari me dit (je me demandai d'abord s'il n'y avait pas là quelque dessein
sous-entendu): − Sais-tu ce que m'a annoncé Brassy? Gurgine a essayé de se tuer
(Daniel-Rops,Mort,1934, p. 291). 2. Qui reste implicite. Je me rappelle (...)
d'avoir lu dans la déclaration des droits de l'homme cette maxime sous-entendue
dans tous les codes qu'on nous a donnés depuis: « Tout ce qui n'est pas défendu
par la loi ne peut être empêché, et nul ne peut être contraint à faire ce
qu'elle n'ordonne pas » (Bonald,Législ. primit.,t. 1, 1802, p. 152).Toute
mélodie commence par une anacrouse exprimée ou sous-entendue (D'Indy,Compos.
mus.,t. 1, 1897-1900, p. 35). B. − GRAMM. Qui n'est pas exprimé, mais que le
sens ou la syntaxe pourrait suppléer aisément. Observez qu'ainsi est tantôt
adverbe, tantôt conjonction. (...) Il est encore adverbe dans celle-ci [cette
phrase], ainsi que la vertu, le crime a ses degrés; il signifie de la même
manière. C'est que, qui est la conjonction qui lie ensemble la phrase exprimée,
le crime a ses degrés, avec la phrase sous-entendue, la vertu a ses degrés (Destutt
de Tr.,Idéol. 2,1803, p. 140).L'intelligence fait donc naturellement usage des
rapports d'équivalent à équivalent, de contenu à contenant, de cause à effet,
etc., qu'implique toute phrase, où il y a un sujet, un attribut, un verbe,
exprimé ou sous-entendu (Bergson,Évol. créatr.,1907, p. 149). III. − Subst.
masc. A. − Au sing. Comportement de celui qui sous-entend les choses sans les
exprimer explicitement. C'est la plus immense personnalité que je connaisse
[Zola], mais elle est toute dans le sous-entendu: l'homme ne parle pas de lui,
mais toutes les théories, toutes les idées, toutes les logomachies qu'il émet
combattent uniquement, à propos de tout et de n'importe quoi, en faveur de sa
littérature et de son talent (Goncourt, Journal, 1883, p. 251). B. − P. méton.
1. Parfois péj. Ce qui est sous-entendu, insinué dans des propos ou dans un
texte, ou p. ext., par un comportement. Synon. allusion, insinuation.Plus libre
que ses confrères, il ne craignait pas, − bien timidement encore, avec des
clignements d'yeux et des sous-entendus, − de fronder les gens en place
(Rolland,J.-Chr.,Adolesc., 1905, p. 365). − Au sing. à valeur de neutre. Henry
Céard a passé avec moi toute la journée, causant du roman qu'il fait, − et
qu'il veut faire dans le gris, le voilé, le sous-entendu (Goncourt,,
Journal1878, p. 1276). − En partic. Allusion grivoise. Les conversations
fourmillaient d'allusions et de sous-entendus dont la grivoiserie me choquait
(Beauvoir,Mém. j. fille,1958, p. 165). 2. Ce qui n'est pas exprimé explicitement.
Synon. restriction, réticence.Personne ne dit: « Je suis », si ce n'est dans
une certaine attitude très instable et généralement apprise, et on ne le dit
alors qu'avec quantité de sous-entendus: il y faut parfois un long commentaire
(Valéry, Variété IV,1938, p. 228). REM. Sous-entente, subst. fém.,vx. a) Action
de sous-entendre par artifice; p. méton., ce qui est ainsi sous-entendu. Il ne
parle jamais qu'il n'y ait quelque sous-entente à ce qu'il dit. Il y a quelque
sous-entente à cela (Ac. 1798-1878). b) Gramm. Synon. de sous-entendu. (Ds
Bally 1951). Prononc. et Orth.: [suzɑ ̃tɑ ̃dy]. Ac. 1694: sousentendu, -ue,
1718: sousentendu, -üe, dep. 1740: sous-entendu, -ue. Fréq. abs. littér.: 249.
Fréq. rel. littér.: xixes.: a) 189, b) 230; xxes.: a) 480, b) 484. Bbg. Ducrot
(O.). Le Dire et le dit. Paris, 1984, pp. 13-31. − Kerbrat-Orecchioni (C.).
L'Énonciation. De la subjectivité ds le lang. Paris, 1980, 290 p., passim. more grice to the mill: sous-entendu:
used by, of all people, Mill. An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's
Philosophybooks.google.com › books ... and speak with any approach to
precision, and adopting into [the necessary sufficient clauses of a piece of
philosophical conceptual analysis] a mere sous-entendu of common conversation
in its most unprecise form. If I say to any one, Cf. understatement, as opposed
to overstatement. The ‘statement’ thing complicates things,
‘underunderstanding’ seems better, or ‘sub-understanding,’ strictly. Trust
Grice to bring more Grice to the Mill and provide a full essay, indeed theory,
and base his own philosophy, on the sous-tentendu! Cf. Pears, Pears
Cyclopaedia. “The English love meiosis, litotes, and understatement. The French
don’t.” Note all the figures of rhetoric cited by Grice, and why they have philosophical
import. Many entries here: hyperbole, meiosis, litotes, etc. Grice took
‘sous-entendu’ etymologically serious. It is UNDERSTOOD. Nobody taught you, but
it understood. It is understood is like It is known. So “The pillar box seems
red” is understood to mean, “It may not be.” Now a sous-entendu may be
cancellable, in which case it was MIS-understood, or the emissor has changed
his mind. Grice considers the paradoxes the understanding under ‘uptake,’ just
to make fun of Austin’s informalism. The ‘endendu’ is what the French
understand by ‘understand,’ the root being Latin intellectus, or intendo.
more, H: “Not to be confused with the
other More, who was literally beheaded when he refused to swear to the Act of
Supremacy which metaphorically named Henry VIII the head of the C. of E.” -- English
philosopher, theologian, and poet, the most prolific of the Cambridge
Platonists. He entered Christ’s , where he spent the rest of his life after
becoming Fellow . He was primarily an apologist of anti-Calvinist,
latitudinarian stamp whose inalienable philosophico- theological purpose was to
demonstrate the existence and immortality of the soul and to cure “two enormous
distempers of the mind,” atheism and “enthusiasm.” He describes himself as “a
Fisher for Philosophers, desirous to draw them to or retain them in the
Christian Faith.” His eclectic method deployed Neoplatonism notably Plotinus
and Ficino, mystical theologies, cabalistic doctrines as More misconceived
them, empirical findings including reports of witchcraft and ghosts, the new
science, and the new philosophy, notably the philosophy of Descartes. Yet he
rejected Descartes’s beast-machine doctrine, his version of dualism, and the
pretensions of Cartesian mechanical philosophy to explain all physical phenomena.
Animals have souls; the universe is alive with souls. Body and spirit are
spatially extended, the former being essentially impenetrable, inert, and
discerpible divisible into parts, the latter essentially penetrable,
indiscerpible, active, and capable of a spiritual density, which More called
essential spissitude, “the redoubling or contracting of substance into less
space than it does sometimes occupy.” Physical processes are activated and
ordered by the spirit of nature, a hylarchic principle and “the vicarious power
of God upon this great automaton, the world.” More’s writings on natural
philosophy, especially his doctrine of infinite space, are thought to have
influenced Newton. More attacked Hobbes’s materialism and, in the 1660s and
1670s, the impieties of Dutch Cartesianism, including the perceived atheism of
Spinoza and his circle. He regretted the “enthusiasm” for and conversion to
Quakerism of Anne Conway, his “extramural” tutee and assiduous correspondent.
More had a partiality for coinages and linguistic exotica. We owe to him
‘Cartesianism’ coined a few years before the first appearance of the equivalent, and the substantive
‘materialist.’ “But he never coined ‘implicaturum,’” – Grice.
more, Sir Thomas: English humanist,
statesman, martyr, and saint. A lawyer by profession, he entered royal service and
became lord chancellor. After refusing to swear to the Act of Supremacy, which
named (“metaphorically,” – Grice) Henry
VIII the head of the C. of E. h, More was (“ironically, but literally” – Grice)
beheaded as a traitor. Although his writings include biography, poetry,
letters, and anti-heretical tracts, his only philosophical work, Utopia
published in Latin, 1516, is his masterpiece. Covering a wide variety of
subjects including government, education, punishment, religion, family life,
and euthanasia, Utopia contrasts European social institutions with their
counterparts on the imaginary island of Utopia. Inspired in part by Plato’s
Republic, the Utopian communal system is designed to teach virtue and reward it
with happiness. The absence of money, private property, and most social
distinctions allows Utopians the leisure to develop the faculties in which
happiness consists. Because of More’s love of irony, Utopia has been subject to
quite different interpretations. H. P. Grice, “A personal guide to the 39
articles, compleat with their 39 implicatura.”
mosca: Essential Italian
philosopher, who made pioneering contributions to the theory of democratic elitism.
Combining the life of a professor with
that of a politician, he taught such subjects as constitutional law, public
law, political science, and history of political theory; at various times he
was also an editor of the Parliamentary proceedings, an elected member of the
Chamber of Deputies, an under-secretary for colonial affairs, a newspaper
columnist, and a member of the Senate. For Mosca ‘elitism’ refers to the empirical
generalization that a society is ruled by an organised minority. His democratic
commitment is embodied in what he calls juridical defense: the normative
principle that political developments are to be judged by whether and how they
prevent any one person, class, force, or institution from dominating the
others. Mosca’s third main contribution is a framework consisting of two
intersecting distinctions that yield four possible ideal types, defined as
follows: in autocracy, authority flows from the rulers to the ruled. In
liberalism, from the ruled to the rulers. In democracy, the ruling class is
open to renewal by members of other classes; in aristocracy it is not. He was
influenced by, and in turn influenced, positivism, for the elitist thesis
presumably constitutes the fundamental “law” of political “science.” Even
deeper is his connection with the tradition of Machiavelli’s political realism.
There is also no question that he practiced an empirical approach. In the
tradition of elitism, he may be compared and contrasted with Pareto, Michels,
and Schumpeter; and in the tradition of political philosophy, to Croce, Gentile, and
Gramsci. Refs.: H. P. Grice: “Mosca’s liberalism;” Luigi Speranza, "Grice e Mosca," per il Club Anglo-Italiano,
The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
Motus – motivatum – Grice, “Must our motives
be impure?” “Obligation cashes out in motivation.” Motivatum -- motivation, a
property central in motivational explanations of intentional conduct. To assert
that Grice is driving to Lord’s today because she wants to see his cricket team
play and believes that they are playing today at Lord’s is to offer an explanation
of Grice’s action. On a popular interpretation, the assertion mentions a pair
of attitudes: a desire and a belief. Grice’s s desire is a paradigmatic
motivational attitude in that it inclines him to bring about the satisfaction
of that very attitude. The primary function of motivational attitudes is to
bring about their own satisfaction by inducing the agent to undertake a
suitable course of action, and, arguably, any attitude that has that function
is, ipso facto, a motivational one. The related thesis that only attitudes
having this function are motivational
or, more precisely, motivation-constituting is implausible. Grice hopes that the
Oxfordshire Cricket Team won yesterday. Plainly, his hope cannot bring about its
own satisfaction, since Grice has no control over the past. Even so, the hope
seemingly may motivate action e.g., Grice’s searching for sports news on her
car radio, in which case the hope is motivation-constituting. Some philosophers
have claimed that our beliefs that we are morally required to take a particular
course of action are motivation-constituting, and such beliefs obviously do not
have the function of bringing about their own satisfaction i.e., their truth.
However, the claim is controversial, as is the related claim that beliefs of
this kind are “besires” that is, not
merely beliefs but desires as well. Refs.: “Desire, belief, and besire.”
Grice: the explanatory-justificatory
distinction – “To explain” is not to explicate, but to render ‘plain’ – To
justify is hardly to render ‘plain’! Grice is aware of this, because he does
not use the ‘explicatory-justificatory’ distinction. Therefore, the
‘justificatory’ is conceptually prior – a philosopher looks for justification –
hardly to render stuff plain – “Quite the opposite: my claim to fame is to
follow the alleged professional duty of a philosophy professor: to render
obscure what is clear, and vice versa!” -- motivational explanation -- a type
of explanation of goal-directed behavior where the explanans appeals to the
motives of the agent. The explanation usually is in the following form: Smith
swam hard in order to win the race. Here the description of what Smith did
identifies the behavior to be explained, and the phrase that follows ‘in order
to’ identifies the goal or the state of affairs the obtaining of which was the
moving force behind the behavior. The general presumption is that the agent
whose behavior is being explained is capable of deliberating and acting on the
decisions reached as a result of the deliberation. Thus, it is dubious whether
the explanation contained in ‘The plant turned toward the sun in order to
receive more light’ is a motivational explanation. Two problems are thought to
surround motivational explanations. First, since the state of affairs set as
the goal is, at the time of the action, non-existent, it can only act as the
“moving force” by appearing as the intentional object of an inner psychological
state of the agent. Thus, motives are generally desires for specific objects or
states of affairs on which the agent acts. So motivational explanation is
basically the type of explanation provided in folk psychology, and as such it
inherits all the alleged problems of the latter. And second, what counts as a
motive for an action under one description usually fails to be a motive for the
same action under a different description. My motive for saying “hello” may
have been my desire to answer the phone, but my motive for saying “hello”
loudly was to express my irritation at the person calling me so late at
night.
Motus – motivus – “Obligation cashes on
motivation.” Grice, “Must our motives be impure?” -- motivational internalism, the view that moral
motivation is internal to moral duty or the sense of duty. The view represents
the contemporary understanding of Hume’s thesis that morality is essentially
practical. Hume went on to point out the apparent logical gap between
statements of fact, which express theoretical judgments, and statements about
what ought to be done, which express practical judgments. Motivational
internalism offers one explanation for this gap. No motivation is internal to
the recognition of facts. The specific internal relation the view affirms is
that of necessity. Thus, motivational internalists hold that if one sees that
one has a duty to do a certain action or that it would be right to do it, then
necessarily one has a motive to do it. For example, if one sees that it is
one’s duty to donate blood, then necessarily one has a motive to donate blood.
Motivational externalism, the opposing view, denies this relation. Its
adherents hold that it is possible for one to see that one has a duty to do a
certain action or that it would be right to do it yet have no motive to do it.
Motivational externalists typically, though not universally, deny any real gap
between theoretical and practical judgments. Motivational internalism takes
either of two forms, rationalist and anti-rationalist. Rationalists, such as
Plato and Kant, hold that the content or truth of a moral requirement
guarantees in those who understand it a motive of compliance.
Anti-rationalists, such as Hume, hold that moral judgment necessarily has some
affective or volitional component that supplies a motive for the relevant
action but that renders morality less a matter of reason and truth than of
feeling or commitment. It is also possible in the abstract to draw an analogous
distinction between two forms of motivational externalism, cognitivist and noncognitivist,
but because the view springs from an interest in assimilating practical
judgment to theoretical judgment, its only influential form has been
cognitivist.
mystische -- mystical
experience, an experience alleged to reveal some aspect of reality not normally
accessible to sensory experience or cognition. The experience typically characterized by its profound
emotional impact on the one who experiences it, its transcendence of spatial
and temporal distinctions, its transitoriness, and its ineffability is often but not always associated with some
religious tradition. In theistic religions, mystical experiences are claimed to
be brought about by God or by some other superhuman agent. Theistic mystical experiences
evoke feelings of worshipful awe. Their content can vary from something no more
articulate than a feeling of closeness to God to something as specific as an
item of revealed theology, such as, for a Christian mystic, a vision of the
Trinity. Non-theistic mystical experiences are usually claimed to reveal the
metaphysical unity of all things and to provide those who experience them with
a sense of inner peace or bliss. mystische -- ystic -- mysticism, a doctrine or
discipline maintaining that one can gain knowledge of reality that is not
accessible to sense perception or to rational, conceptual thought. Generally
associated with a religious tradition, mysticism can take a theistic form, as
it has in Jewish, Christian, and Islamic traditions, or a non-theistic form, as
it has in Buddhism and some varieties of Hinduism. Mystics claim that the
mystical experience, the vehicle of mystic
knowledge, is usually the result of spiritual training, involving some
combination of prayer, meditation, fasting, bodily discipline, and renunciation
of worldly concerns. Theistic varieties of mysticism describe the mystical
experience as granted by God and thus not subject to the control of the mystic.
Although theists claim to feel closeness to God during the mystical experience,
they regard assertions of identity of the self with God as heretical.
Non-theistic varieties are more apt to describe the experience as one that can
be induced and controlled by the mystic and in which distinctions between the
self and reality, or subject and object, are revealed to be illusory. Mystics
claim that, although veridical, their experiences cannot be adequately
described in language, because ordinary communication is based on sense
experience and conceptual differentiation: mystical writings are thus
characterized by metaphor and simile. It is con 593 troversial whether all mystical
experiences are basically the same, and whether the apparent diversity among
them is the result of interpretations influenced by different cultural traditions.
H. P. Grice, “Vitters and the mystic,” Luigi Speranza, “Vitters und das
mystische,” per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming Pool Library, Villa Grice,
Liguria, Italia.
myth: Grice was aware of Grice, the Welsh philosopher. For Grice
had turned a ‘myth,’ the myth of the compact, into a thing that would justify
moral obligation – When Grice, the Englishman, gives a mythical account of
communication, alla Plato and Paget, he faces the same problem – which he hopes
is “very minor,” compared to others. In this case, it’s not about ‘moral obligation’
but about “something else.” Grice was possibly motivated by Quine’s irreverent,
“The mth of meaning,” a talk at France, “Le mythe de la signification.” It’s
odd that he gives the example of a ‘social contract’, developed by G. R. Grice
as a ‘myth’ as his own on ‘expressing pain.’ “My succession of stages is a
methodological myth designed to exhibit the conceptual link between expression
and communication. Rather than Plato, he appeals to Rawls and the myth of the
social conpact! Grice knows a little about Descartess “Discours de la methode,”
and he is also aware of similar obsession by Collingwood with philosopical
methodology. Grice would joke on midwifery, as the philosopher’s apter method
at Oxford: to strangle error at its birth. Grice typifies a generation at
Oxford. While he did not socialize with the crème de la crème in pre-war
Oxford, he shared some their approach. E.g. a love affair with Russell’s
logical construction. After the war, and in retrospect, Grice liked to
associate himself with Austin. He obviously felt the need to belong to a group,
to make a difference, to make history. Many participants of the play group saw
themselves as doing philosophy, rather than reading about it! It was long after
that Grice started to note the differences in methodology between Austin and
himself. His methodology changed a little. He was enamoured with formalism for
a while, and he grants that this love never ceased. In a still later phase, he
came to realise that his way of doing philosophy was part of literature (essay
writing). And so he started to be slightly more careful about his style – which
some found florid. The stylistic concerns were serious. Oxonian philosophers
like Holloway had been kept away from philosophy because of the stereotype that
the Oxonian philosophers style is pedantic, when it neednt! A philosopher
should be allowed, as Plato was, to use a myth, if he thinks his tutee will
thank him for that! Grice loved to compare his Oxonian dialectic with Platos
Athenian (strictly, Academic) dialectic. Indeed, there is some resemblance of
the use of myth in Plato and Grice for philosophical methodological purposes.
Grice especially enjoys a myth in his programme in philosophical psychology. In
this, he is very much being a philosopher. Non-philosophers usually criticise
this methodological use of a myth, but they would, wouldnt they. Grice suggests
that a myth has diagogic relevance. Creature construction, the philosopher as
demi-god, if mythical, is an easier way for a philosophy don to instil his
ideas on his tutee than, say, privileged access and incorrigibility. myth of Er, a tale
at the end of Plato’s Republic dramatizing the rewards of justice and
philosophy by depicting the process of reincarnation. Complementing the main
argument of the work, that it is intrinsically better to be just than unjust,
this longest of Plato’s myths blends traditional lore with speculative
cosmology to show that justice also pays, usually in life and certainly in the
afterlife. Er, a warrior who revived shortly after death, reports how judges
assign the souls of the just to heaven but others to punishment in the
underworld, and how most return after a thousand years to behold the celestial
order, to choose their next lives, and to be born anew. Refs.:
The main source is Grice’s essay on ‘myth’, in The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC.
N
N: SUBJECT
INDEX: NATURA
N: NAME INDEX: ITALIAN
NEGRI
N: NAME INDEX: ITALIAN
NEGRI
NICOLETTI
NOCE
N:
NAME INDEX: ENGLISHMEN (Oxonian philosophy dons)
NOWELL-SMITH
naso del
camello – thing edge of the wedge -- argumentum ad domino: slippery slope argument, an argument that an action
apparently unobjectionable in itself would set in motion a train of events
leading ultimately to an undesirable outcome. The metaphor portrays one on the
edge of a slippery slope, where taking the first step down will inevitably
cause sliding to the bottom. For example, it is sometimes argued that voluntary
euthanasia should not be legalized because this will lead to killing unwanted
people, e.g. the handicapped or elderly, against their will. In some versions
the argument aims to show that one should intervene to stop an ongoing train of
events; e.g., it has been argued that suppressing a Communist revolution in one
country was necessary to prevent the spread of Communism throughout a whole
region via the so-called domino effect. Slippery slope arguments with dubious
causal assumptions are often classed as fallacies under the general heading of
the fallacy of the false cause. This argument is also sometimes called the wedge
argument. There is some disagreement concerning the breadth of the category of
slippery slope arguments. Some would restrict the term to arguments with
evaluative conclusions, while others construe it more broadly so as to include
other sorites arguments.
natura: Grice -- Grice:
beyond the natural/non-natural distinction
ABSTRACT. When we approach, with Grice, the philosophical question
involved in what we may call the ‘natural’/ ‘non-natural’ distinction, various
conceptual possibilities are open to us. In this contribution, after providing
a a historical survey of the distinction with special focus on its treatment by Grice, I offer a thesis
which, echoing Bennett, I label ‘meaning-naturalism.’ Keywords: H. Paul Grice, meaning,
naturalism, non-natural meaning
Introduction Grice sees his
approach to ‘meaning’ (or “meaning that …”, as he would rather put it) as
‘rhapsody on a theme by Peirce.’ When he
presents his “Meaning” to the Oxford Philosophical Society (only to be
published almost a decade later by The Philosophical Review), Grice endows the
philosophical community with a full-blown ‘natural’/‘non-natural’ distinction,
for which he has naturally become somewhat infamously famous, as when a
philosopher, exploring the different causes of death of this or that other
philosopher cites Grice as having passed of ‘non-natural causes.’ What is Grice’s ‘natural’/‘non-natural’
distinction about? As a member of the so-called
‘Oxford school of “ordinary-language” philosophy’ (he disliked the sobriquet),
Grice seems initially to have been concerned with what at a later stage he
calls a ‘pre-theoretical’ exploration of this or that use of the lexeme ‘mean,’
notably by Peirce. Grice finds Peirce’s
attempt to ‘replace’ the vernacular Anglo-Saxon ‘mean’ with ‘krypto-technical’
jargon as not too sympathetic to these or those Oxonian ears. So, it is this
lexeme, or ‘expression,’ ‘mean,’ to which Grice’s distinction applies. Carefully, as Bennett would point out, using
lower-case ‘x’ and ‘y’ for tokens, Grice attempts to formulate the distinction into two separate
super-expressions, where the sub-expression “means that …” occurs: i. x meansN
that p. ii. x meansNN that q. What is ‘x’? Grice spends some time on this
double-edged elucidation (and indeed, the ‘that’-clause explication is a later
vintage). He grants that his main focus of concern is with (ii). In passing, he
makes some rather intriguing running commentary. It’s clear why Grice feels the need to spend
some time in explicating what he is about to do. Grice’s distinction, as he
formulates it, is supposed to ‘refine’ this or that distinction, made by this
or that philosopher. While ‘ordinary-language’ philosophers are taken as
approaching ‘ordinary-language,’ their underlying motivation is to criticise
this or that philosopher’s mischaracterisation of the linguistic nuance at
hand. Grice’s avowed aim in his talk to
the Oxford Philosophical Society is to shed light on, to use his
characteristically cavalier wording, ‘what people have been thinking,’ which in
that context, means ‘what other philosophers have been thinking’ – including
Ayer -- or even getting at, ‘when they speak of such things as “natural” versus
“conventional” signs.’ Grice thinks that,
by his sticking with ‘meaning that …’ (rather than ‘sign’) and ‘non-natural’
(rather ‘conventional’) he is setting a better scene. Why would this be a
conceptual improvement? Grice gives two reasons. First, and again, Grice presents himself as a
representative of the Oxonian school of ‘ordinary-language’ philosophy, and
exercising what these philosophers referred to this or that adventure in
‘linguistic botany.’ Grice thus sets to explore, introspectively, relying on
his intuitions behind his own usage, philosophical and other: a ‘word,’ for example,
Grice notes, he would not naturally describe as a ‘sign.’ In Grice’s (but
surely not Peirce’s) idio-lect, the expression ‘sign’ is restricted to things
like a traffic signal, say. Second, and
again in this adventure in ‘linguistic-botany,’ x (or strictly ‘a,’ for
‘agent,’ now) that can ‘mean’ that p, in a way that is specifically NON-factive
(as he’ll later put it, echoing the Kiparskys) but which need not be
‘conventional.’ Grice gives the example of ‘a gesture,’ which a few
philosophers would associate with Sraffa’s!
The historical background Grice’s
cavalier reference to ‘what people are getting at’ sounds charmingly Oxonian.
He surely has no intention to underestimate the knowledge of the fellow members
of The Oxford Philosophical Society. He won’t be seen as ‘going to lecture’
them. This is not a seminar, but a public occasion. He is allowed to be a
cavalier. Had this been a seminar, and
being indeed a Lit. Hum. Oxon., Grice knows he can trace the distinction he is
making, as he refines alternative ones, to Plato’s Cratylus, where we have
Socrates and his dialogical companion playing with various adverbial modifiers,
notably, ‘phusei’ and ‘thesei.’ Plato’s
‘phusei,’ surely translates to Grice’s ‘nature’ in ‘natural.’ Plato is
carefully in avoiding the subsantive nominative ‘phusis.’ His ‘phusei’ is meant
to modify the way something may such may be said to ‘mean’ (‘semein’). Possibly
the earliest incarnation of what later will be dubbed as the ‘pooh’ pooh theory
of language. Plato’s ‘thesei’ is
slightly more complicated. It is best to stay lexically conservative here and
understand it to mean, ‘by position,’ i.e. or, in Grice’s freer prose, by
convention. While Plato has to his disposal various other lexemes to do duty
for this, he chooses a rather weak one, and again, not in the nominative
“thesis,” but as applied to something that ‘means’ that p or q. In any case,
Plato’s interest, as indeed Grice’s, is ‘dialectic.’ That x (or a) means that q
thesei, by position, entails (as Plato would say if he could borrow from Moore)
that it is not the case that x (or a) means that q phusei, by nature. The
distinction is supposed to be absolute.
The ‘phusis’/‘thesis’ distinction undergoes a fascinating development in
the philosophical tradition, from Greek (or Grecian) into Latin (Roman), and
eventually makes it to scholastic philosophy: ‘per natura’/ ‘per positionem,’
or ‘ad placitum.’ Closer to Grice,
authors partly philosophising in Grice’s vernacular, such as Hobbes, who is
indeed fighting against Latin for the the use of the vernacular in
philosophical discourse, will speak of what Grice knew would be familiar
terminology to his Oxford audience: ‘natural sign’ versus, rather than Grice’s
intentionally rather ugly-sounding ‘non-natural,’ ‘artificial’ or
‘conventional’ sign. Grice does not use
‘scare quotes,’ but perhaps Umberto Eco would have wished he did! (Indeed, it
is best to see Grice as treating ‘a means that p’ as the only ‘literal’ use of
‘mean,’ with ‘natural’ and ‘expression-relative’ uses as ‘derivative, or
transferred, or figurative. While he does NOT use ‘scare quotes’ for his
examples of ‘meanN,’ as in iii. iii.
Smoke means that there is fire. Grice
cares to quote in the talk from just one rather recent philosopher who was
being discussed at Oxford in connection with A. J. Ayer’s approach to ‘moral’
language as being merely ‘emotive.’
Grice makes an explicit reference to Stevenson. While Grice finds
Stevenson’s account of the ‘non-natural’ use of “mean” ‘circular’ (in that it
relies on conditioning related to ‘communication,’ Stevenson explores various
‘natural’ uses of ‘mean’, and, to emphasise the figurative status, explicitly
employs ‘scare quotes.’ For Stevenson, (iii) becomes (iv). iv. Smoke ‘means’ that there is fire. For surely ‘smoke’ cannot have an
intention – and ‘mean’ is too close to ‘intend’ in the Anglo-Saxon vernacular
to allow smoke to mean that p or q – ‘mean’ at most. This is crucial (and
suggests just one way of the figuration of ‘mean,’ that will go two ways with Grice
when he sees this figuration as applying to ‘expression-relative’ uses of
‘mean,’ as in v. ‘There’s smoke’ ‘means’ that there’s
smoke. (Ubi fumus ibi ignis). By
carefully deploying scare-quotes, Stevenson is fighting against ‘animism.’ The
root of ‘mean’ is cognate with Latin ‘mentare’ and ‘mentire,’ and can notably
be traced back to ‘mens,’ the mind. Surely smoke cannot really (if we must use
one of those adverbs that Austin called ‘trouser words’) that there is fire –
just ‘mean’ it. A careful ‘utterer’ is using the same lexeme in an obviously
‘figurative’ way, and marking this fact explicitly by appealing to an ‘echoic,’
or as Grice may prefer, ‘trans-categorial,’ use. The ‘fun’ side to this (and for Grice, ‘philosophy
need be fun’) is that Grice’s distinction then becomes now the
‘non-natural’/‘natural’ distinction. Scare quotes signal that the realm of
‘mean’ is the realm of the ‘mind,’ and not what Plato might have seen as the
realm of nature simpliciter. But back
to Hobbes. Indeed, Hobbes may be drawing on the earlier explorations on this in
Latin, by, of all people, Ockham, who speaks now of scenarios where
‘significare’ is modified by the adverb ‘naturaliter,’ and scenarios where it
is not. For this or that example of what
Grice has as the ‘natural’ use of ‘mean’, Ockham will stick with ‘significare,’
qualified by ‘naturaliter.’ vi. By
smiling, Smith means that he is happy.
Or as Ockham more generically puts it,
vii. Risus ‘significat’ naturaliter interiorem laetitiam. But Ockham can go pretty Griceian too, as
when he wonders about a ‘circulus’ – of a wine barrel ‘artificially’ (or not
‘naturaliter’) placed, or positioned, outside a building, yielding: viii. Circulus ‘significat’ naturaliter
vinum. The circle, even if artificially
(or at least not naturally) placed, is a ‘sign’ or means that wine which is
being sold inside the building (Ockham is playing with the composite nature of
‘significare,’ literally to ‘make sign’). In the Peirceian theme on which Grice
offers his rhapsody, and which he’ll later adopt in his “Retrospective
epilogue,” there is an iconicity involved in the ‘circulus’ scenario, where
this ‘iconicity’ requires some conceptual elucidation. Ockham’s use of the Latin ‘significare’
poses a further question. Strictly, of course, is to ‘make’ (‘ficare’) a sign.
Therefore, Grice feels its Latinate counterpart, ‘signifies that…’ as too
strong a way to qualify a thing like an expression (or ‘word,’) which for him
may not be a sign at all. Grice’s
cavalier attitude and provocative intent is further evidenced by the fact that,
years later, when delivering the William James lectures at Harvard, and
refining his “Meaning,” he does mention that his programme is concerned with
the elucidation of the ‘total signification’ of a remark as uttered by this or
that utterer, into this or that variety of this or that explicit and implicit
component. When Grice refers to “what
people are thinking,” he is aware that Hobbes more or less maintains the Ockham
(or ‘Occam,’ in Grice’s preferred spelling) paradigm, both in his work written
in his late scholastic Latin (“Computatio, sive logica”) and the vernacular
(“Leviathan”) which almost marks the beginning of so-called, by Sorley,
“English philosophy.” With the coming of
empiricism, with Locke’s Essay (1690), and later Mill’s “System of Logic
(mandatory reading at Oxford for the Lit. Hum. degree – “more Grice to the
Mill,” Grice will put it) it seems obvious that the tradition in which Grice is
immersed is not strange to ‘naturalism.’
“Nature” itself, as Plato already knew, need not be hypostasized. It is
a fascinating fact that, for years, Oxford infamously kept two different chairs
for the philosopher: one of ‘natural’ philosophy, and the Waynflete chair of
‘meta-physical philosophy,’ where ‘metaphysical’ is merely an obscure way of
referring to the ‘trans-natural.’ Or is it the other way around? Few empiricist philosophers need to postulate
the ‘unity’ (less so, the uniformity) of “Nature,” even if this or that
Griceians will later will. Witness Nancy Cartwright in the festschrift for
Grice edited by Grandy and Warner for Clarendon, Philosophical Grounds of
Rationality: Intentions, Categories, Ends (or “G. R. I. C. E.,” for short):
‘how the laws of nature lie.’ In its
simplest formulation, which should do for the purposes of this contribution,
the philosophical thesis of ‘naturalism’ may be understood as positing an
ontological continuum between this or that allegation concerning ‘Nature’ and
what is not nature (‘art,’ as in ‘artifice’).
And then, Grice comes to revisit “Meaning.” In 1976, Grice gets invited to a symposium at
Brighton and resumes his 1948 vintage ‘natural’/‘non-natural’ distinction. He
had more or less kept it all through the William James lectures. At Brighton,
Grice adds some crucial elaborations, in terms of what he now calls
‘philosophical psychology’ (Surely he doesn’t want to be seen as a ‘scientific’
psychologist). The audience is a different one, and not purely philosophical,
so he can be cavalier and provocative in a different way. While in his talk on “Meaning” for the Oxford
Philosophical Society Grice had, rather casually, referred to this or that
application, collocation, or occurrence, of the lexeme ‘mean’ as being this or
that (Fregeian) ‘sense’ of the lexeme ‘mean’ -- and thus yielding ‘mean’ as,
strictly, polysemous -- he now feels it’s time to weaken the claim to this or
that (Ryleian) ‘use,’ not (Fregeian) ‘sense,’ of “mean.” His motivation is obvious, and can be brought
back a point he makes in his third William James lectures, and which in fact
underlies his philosophical methodology regarding other philosophers’ mistakes
when dealing with this or that linguistic nuance. If you are going to be
Occamist, ‘senses,’ as specific entities, are not be multiplied beyond
necessity.’ Grice is playing the etymological game here, concerning ‘mean’
(mens, mind). His example, in “Meaning revisited,” concerns Smith as ‘being
caught in the grip of a vyse/vice.’ The root in both ‘vice’ and ‘vyse’ – Latin
‘vim’ – is cognate with ‘violence’ and gives two lexemes in Grice’s vernacular:
one applies to something like a carpenter’s tool, and the other to the opposite
of a virtue. Grice wants to explore how the ‘natural’/ ‘non-natural’
distinction may compare to the ‘vyse’/‘vice’ distinction. With ‘vice,’ Grice
suggests, we have, in his vernacular, as opposed to Latin, two different
lexemes (even if ultimately from a common Latin root, ‘vim,’ which surely
mitigates the case for polysemy). But with ‘mean,’ that’s surely that’s not the
case. The ultimate root is that of ‘mens,’ mind, and there’s no spelling
difference to deal with. Grice does not
reverse the order of the terms in his ‘natural’/’non-natural’ distinction,
though, as Eco would (“a sign is something you can use to lie”). Rather, he
allows for this or that loose, or figurative, or ‘disimplicatural’ use of
“means ….” His craving for a further philosophical generality justifies his
disimplicature. This generality is of two kinds, one of which he deem thems
‘conceptual,’ or ‘methodological,’ and the other ‘mythic.’ The ‘conceptual’ or methodological manoevure
is ontological in flavour. If there is a common core that both our (i) and (ii)
above share, it should be rephrasable by a neutral form for both the ‘natural’
and the ‘non-natural’ scenario: ix. p is a consequence of x/a ‘Consequentia’ is exactly the term used by
Hobbes (some would prefer post-sequentia) when considering the generic concept
of a ‘sign.’ It is thus very apt of Hacking (in his “Why does language matter to
philosophy?”) to see Hobbes as a pre-Griceian (or is it, Grice as a
post-Hobbesian?) When it comes to
‘naturalism’ proper, we have to be careful in our exegesis of it as label for
this or that philosophical overarching thesis. When reminiscing about his
progress to ‘The City of the Eternal Truth,’ in his parody of Bunyan’s, pilgrim
Grice meets face to face with the monster of “Naturalism.” One may see this as Grice’s warning against
some trends he found in The New World, ‘the devil of scientism,’ as he called
it, towards ‘reductionism’ and ‘eliminationism,’ as flourishing in the idea
that a ‘final cause’ is ‘mechanistically reducible.’ In Grice’s philosophical
psychology, ‘Naturalism’ for Grice, amounts to rejecting this or that
psychological law when this or that physiological law already explains the same
phenomenon. Grice finds that his Occamism for ‘mean’ is not enough here and
fangles an ‘ontological marxism’: this or that entity (an autonomous rational
soul, say) that seems to go against naturalism may be justified, ‘provided they
help with the house-work’ the philosopher is engaged in, in this case, and into
the bargain, saving the philosopher’s existence. The spirit, however, if not the letter, of
‘naturalism’ as a grand philosophical thesis still survives. Grice regards
himself as ultimately a ‘constructivist.’ The realm of his ‘non-natural’ needs
to be rooted in a previous realm of the ‘natural.’ He suggest here a
‘genitorially justified’ ‘myth’ for the ‘natural’/‘non-natural’ distinction: x. a meaninngNN that q derives from
x meaningN that p Grice is exploring
‘emergence’ as a viable concept in philosophical psychology. Philosophical
psychology is thus rooted in philosophical ethology. This or that psychological
(or souly) state, (or attitude, or stance) may be understood as emerging from
(or supervening on) a mere biological and ultimately physical (i. e. natural)
state. (He is clear about that in his “Intention and uncertainty,” when,
adopting the concept of ‘willing that’ from Prichard, he allows it to be
amenable to a ‘physicalist’ treatment).
In his presidential address to the American Philosophical Association,
Grice feels the need to creates a new philosophical sub-discipline, which he,
echoing Carnap, christens ‘pirotology.’
Grice’s ‘pirotology’ concern Carnap’s ‘pirot,’ that ‘karulises
elatically’ in his “Introduction to Semantics.” Grice adds a nod to Locke’s
reflection on Prince Maurice’s ‘parot’ being “very intelligent, and rational.”
The pirotological justification of the ‘natural’/‘non-natural’ distinction
involves three stages. The first stage
in the sequence or series involves the pirot, P1, as a merely physical (or
purely ‘natural’) entity, P1. The second
stage involves our ‘natural’ pirot giving way to the emergence, pretty much
alla Nicolai Hartmann, of a now bio-logical pirot P2 (a ‘human’), endowed with
the goal of survival and adaptation to its natural environment. The third and last stage sees our P2
‘re-constituting’ itself as now a psycho-logical pirot P3, as a ‘person’,
endowed with a higher type of ‘soul.’ (Grice is following Aristotle’s
progression in “De anima.” Grice
carefully avoids the use of ‘mind,’ in what he felt was an over-use by
philosophers in the discipline of ‘mental philosophy,’ as it is referred to at
Oxford in connection with Wilde. As a Kantotelian, Grice sees the biological
pirot P2 as having a ‘soul,’ even if not a rational one. Grice was fascinated
by Aristotle’s insight that, ‘soul,’ like ‘figure’ or ‘number,’ is a concept
that cannot be defined by ‘genus,’ but only within this or that ‘series,’ such
as the three-stage one he provides from the ‘natural’ to the ‘non-natural’
pirot. It is thus no easy exegetic task
to make sense of Grice’s somewhat rhetorical antipathy towards ‘Naturalism,’
but I shall leave that as an open question.
Beyond the distinction? In the
end, for Grice, the key-word is not ‘culture,’ as opposed to ‘nature,’ but
‘rationality,’ as displayed by our ‘non-natural’ pirot P3. Rationality becomes
the philosopher’s main concern, as it is conceptualized to develop from this or
that pre-rational propension, which is biological and ultimately physical, i.e.
natural. Grice’s exploration on the
‘natural’/ ‘non-natural’ distinction thus agrees with a very naturalistic approaches
to things like adaptation and survival in a natural environment, and the
evolution of altruism (a ‘talking pirot’ who transfers his psychological
attitude to another pirot). While his
tone remains distinctively philosophical – and indeed displaying what he
thought as a bit of ‘irreverent, conservative, dissenting rationalism,’ by his
example he has indeed shown that the philosopher’s say has a relevance that no
other discipline can provide. REFERENCES
Grice, H. P. (1948). ‘Meaning,’ repr. in Studies in the Way of
Words. Grice, H. P. (1975). ‘Method in
philosophical psychology: from the banal to the bizarre,’ Proceedings and
Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, repr. in Grice, 1991. Grice, H. P. (1976). ‘Meaning revisited,’
repr. in Studies in the Way of Words.
Grice, H. P. (1986). ‘Reply to Richards,’ in Richard Grandy and Richard
Warner, Philosophical Grounds of Rationality: Intentions, Categories, Ends.
Oxord: The Clarendon Press. Grice, H. P.
(1991). The conception of value. Oxford: The Clarendon Press. Hacking, I. M. (1977). Why does language
matter to philosophy? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hobbes, Thomas. Computatio sive logica. Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. Locke, John. A theory concerning humane [sic]
understanding. Mellor, D. H. (n.d.)
‘Causes of deaths of philosophers’ (accessed February 20th, 2020)
https://www.phil.cam.ac.uk/people/teaching-research-pages/mellor/dhm11/deaths-dg.html Mill, J. S. A system of logic. London:
Macmillan. Ockham, William. Theory of
signs. Pietarinen, Ahti-Veikko and
Francesco Bellucci (2016). ‘H. Paul Grice’s Lecture Notes on Charles S.
Peirce’s Theory of Signs,’ International Review of Pragmatics, 8(1):82-129. Sorley, W. R. (1920). A history of English
philosophy. Cambridge. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Natural and non-natural, and
naturalism.”
NECESSE -- necessitatum:
ananke,
when feeling very Grecian, Grice would use ‘ananke,’ instead of ‘must,’ which
he thought too English! Grecian, necessity. The term was used by early Grecian
philosophers for a constraining or moving natural force. In Parmenides frg. 8,
line 30 ananke encompasses reality in limiting bonds; according to Diogenes
Laertius, Democrianamnesis ananke 27 4065A-
27 tus calls the vortex that generates the cosmos ananke; Plato Timaeus
47e ff. refers to ananke as the irrational element in nature, which reason
orders in creating the physical world. As used by Aristotle Metaphysics V.5,
the basic meaning of ‘necessary’ is ‘that which cannot be otherwise’, a sense
that includes logical necessity. He also distinguishes Physics II.9 between
simple and hypothetical necessity conditions that must hold if something is to
occur.
nicoletti -- paolo di
venezia: philosopher, the son of Andrea Nicola, of Venice – He was born in
Fliuli Venezia Giulia, a hermit of Saint Augustine O.E.S.A., he spent three
years as a student at St. John’s, where the order of St. Augustine had a
‘studium generale,’ at Oxford and taught at Padova, where he became a doctor of
arts. Paolo also held appointments at the universities of Parma, Siena, and
Bologna. Paolo is active in the administration of his order, holding various
high offices. He composed ommentaries on several logical, ethical, and physical
works of Aristotle. His name is connected especially with his best-selling
“Logica parva.” Over 150 manuscripts survive, and more than forty printed
editions of it were made, His huge
sequel, “Logica magna,” was a flop. These Oxford-influenced tracts contributed
to the favorable climate enjoyed by Oxonian semantics in northern Italian
universities. Grice: “My favourite of Paul’s tracts is his “Sophismata aurea” –
how peaceful for a philosopher to die while commentingon Aristotle’s “De
anima.”!” His nom de plum is “Paulus Venetus.”-- Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Paolo
da Harborne, and Paolo da Venezia,”
lecture for the Club Griceiano Anglo-Italiano, Bordighera.
NATURA -- natural intelligence --
artificial (or non-natural) intelligence, also called AI, the scientific effort
to design and build intelligent artifacts. Grice disliked the phrase
“artificial intelligence.” “Strictly, what Minsky means is ‘non-natural’
intelligence.’”Since the effort inevitably presupposes and tests theories about
the nature of intelligence, it has implications for the philosophy of mind perhaps even more than does empirical
psychology. For one thing, actual construction amounts to a direct assault on
the mindbody problem; should it succeed, some form of materialism would seem to
be vindicated. For another, a working model, even a limited one, requires a
more global conception of what intelligence is than do experiments to test specific
hypotheses. In fact, psychology’s own overview of its domain Arouet,
François-Marie artificial intelligence 53
53 has been much influenced by fundamental concepts drawn from AI.
Although the idea of an intelligent artifact is old, serious scientific
research dates only from the 0s, and is associated with the development of
programmable computers. Intelligence is understood as a structural property or
capacity of an active system; i.e., it does not matter what the system is made
of, as long as its parts and their interactions yield intelligent behavior
overall. For instance, if solving logical problems, playing chess, or
conversing in English manifests intelligence, then it is not important whether
the “implementation” is electronic, biological, or mechanical, just as long as
it solves, plays, or talks. Computers are relevant mainly because of their
flexibility and economy: software systems are unmatched in achievable active
complexity per invested effort. Despite the generality of programmable structures
and the variety of historical approaches to the mind, the bulk of AI research
divides into two broad camps which we
can think of as language-oriented and pattern-oriented, respectively.
Conspicuous by their absence are significant influences from the
conditionedresponse paradigm, the psychoanalytic tradition, the mental picture
idea, empiricist atomistic associationism, and so on. Moreover, both AI camps
tend to focus on cognitive issues, sometimes including perception and motor
control. Notably omitted are such psychologically important topics as affect,
personality, aesthetic and moral judgment, conceptual change, mental illness,
etc. Perhaps such matters are beyond the purview of artificial intelligence;
yet it is an unobvious substantive thesis that intellect can be cordoned off
and realized independently of the rest of human life. The two main AI paradigms
emerged together in the 0s along with cybernetic and information-theoretic
approaches, which turned out to be dead ends; and both are vigorous today. But
for most of the sixties and seventies, the language-based orientation dominated
attention and funding, for three signal reasons. First, computer data
structures and processes themselves seemed languagelike: data were
syntactically and semantically articulated, and processing was localized
serial. Second, twentieth-century linguistics and logic made it intelligible
that and how such systems might work: automatic symbol manipulation made clear,
powerful sense. Finally, the sorts of performance most amenable to the
approach explicit reasoning and
“figuring out” strike both popular and
educated opinion as particularly “intellectual”; hence, early successes were
all the more impressive, while “trivial” stumbling blocks were easier to
ignore. The basic idea of the linguistic or symbol manipulation camp is that
thinking is like talking inner
discourse and, hence, that thoughts are
like sentences. The suggestion is venerable; and Hobbes even linked it
explicitly to computation. Yet, it was a major scientific achievement to turn
the general idea into a serious theory. The account does not apply only, or
even especially, to the sort of thinking that is accessible to conscious
reflection. Nor is the “language of thought” supposed to be much like English, predicate
logic, LISP, or any other familiar notation; rather, its detailed character is
an empirical research problem. And, despite fictional stereotypes, the aim is
not to build superlogical or inhumanly rational automata. Our human tendencies
to take things for granted, make intuitive leaps, and resist implausible
conclusions are not weaknesses that AI strives to overcome but abilities
integral to real intelligence that AI aspires to share. In what sense, then, is
thought supposed to be languagelike? Three items are essential. First, thought
tokens have a combinatorial syntactic structure; i.e., they are compounds of
welldefined atomic constituents in well-defined recursively specifiable
arrangements. So the constituents are analogous to words, and the arrangements
are analogous to phrases and sentences; but there is no supposition that they
should resemble any known words or grammar. Second, the contents of thought
tokens, what they “mean,” are a systematic function of their composition: the
constituents and forms of combination have determinate significances that
together determine the content of any wellformed compound. So this is like the
meaning of a sentence being determined by its grammar and the meanings of its
words. Third, the intelligent progress or sequence of thought is specifiable by
rules expressed syntactically they can
be carried out by processes sensitive only to syntactic properties. Here the
analogy is to proof theory: the formal validity of an argument is a matter of
its according with rules expressed formally. But this analogy is particularly
treacherous, because it immediately suggests the rigor of logical inference;
but, if intelligence is specifiable by formal rules, these must be far more
permissive, context-sensitive, and so on, than those of formal logic. Syntax as
such is perfectly neutral as to how the constituents are identified by sound,
by artificial intelligence artificial intelligence 54 54 shape, by magnetic profile and arranged
in time, in space, via address pointers. It is, in effect, a free parameter:
whatever can serve as a bridge between the semantics and the processing. The
account shares with many others the assumptions that thoughts are contentful
meaningful and that the processes in which they occur can somehow be realized
physically. It is distinguished by the two further theses that there must be
some independent way of describing these thoughts that mediates between
simultaneously determines their contents and how they are processed, and that,
so described, they are combinatorially structured. Such a description is
syntactical. We can distinguish two principal phases in language-oriented AI,
each lasting about twenty years. Very roughly, the first phase emphasized
processing search and reasoning, whereas the second has emphasized
representation knowledge. To see how this went, it is important to appreciate
the intellectual breakthrough required to conceive AI at all. A machine, such
as a computer, is a deterministic system, except for random elements. That is
fine for perfectly constrained domains, like numerical calculation, sorting,
and parsing, or for domains that are constrained except for prescribed
randomness, such as statistical modeling. But, in the general case, intelligent
behavior is neither perfectly constrained nor perfectly constrained with a
little random variation thrown in. Rather, it is generally focused and
sensible, yet also fallible and somewhat variable. Consider, e.g., chess
playing an early test bed for AI: listing all the legal moves for any given
position is a perfectly constrained problem, and easy to program; but choosing
the best move is not. Yet an intelligent player does not simply determine which
moves would be legal and then choose one randomly; intelligence in chess play
is to choose, if not always the best, at least usually a good move. This is
something between perfect determinacy and randomness, a “between” that is not
simply a mixture of the two. How is it achievable in a machine? The crucial
innovation that first made AI concretely and realistically conceivable is that
of a heuristic procedure. The term ‘heuristic’ derives from the Grecian word
for discovery, as in Archimedes’ exclamation “Eureka!” The relevant point for
AI is that discovery is a matter neither of following exact directions to a
goal nor of dumb luck, but of looking around sensibly, being guided as much as
possible by what you know in advance and what you find along the way. So a
heuristic procedure is one for sensible discovery, a procedure for sensibly
guided search. In chess, e.g., a player does well to bear in mind a number of
rules of thumb: other things being equal, rooks are more valuable than knights,
it is an asset to control the center of the board, and so on. Such guidelines,
of course, are not valid in every situation; nor will they all be best
satisfied by the same move. But, by following them while searching as far ahead
through various scenarios as possible, a player can make generally sensible
moves much better than random within the constraints of the game. This
picture even accords fairly well with the introspective feel of choosing a
move, particularly for less experienced players. The essential insight for AI
is that such roughand-ready ceteris paribus rules can be deterministically
programmed. It all depends on how you look at it. One and the same bit of
computer program can be, from one point of view, a deterministic, infallible
procedure for computing how a given move would change the relative balance of
pieces, and from another, a generally sensible but fallible procedure for
estimating how “good” that move would be. The substantive thesis about
intelligence human and artificial
alike then is that our powerful but fallible
ability to form “intuitive” hunches, educated guesses, etc., is the result of
largely unconscious search, guided by such heuristic rules. The second phase of
language-inspired AI, dating roughly from the mid-0s, builds on the idea of
heuristic procedure, but dramatically changes the emphasis. The earlier work
was framed by a conception of intelligence as finding solutions to problems
good moves, e.g.. From such a perspective, the specification of the problem the
rules of the game plus the current position and the provision of some heuristic
guides domain-specific rules of thumb are merely a setting of the parameters;
the real work, the real exercise of intelligence, lies in the intensive guided
search undertaken in the specified terms. The later phase, impressed not so
much by our problem-solving prowess as by how well we get along with “simple”
common sense, has shifted the emphasis from search and reasoning to knowledge.
The motivation for this shift can be seen in the following two sentences: We
gave the monkey the banana because it was ripe. We gave the monkey the banana because
it was hungry. artificial intelligence artificial intelligence 55 55 The word ‘it’ is ambiguous, as the
terminal adjectives make clear. Yet listeners effortlessly understand what is
meant, to the point, usually, of not even noticing the ambiguity. The question
is, how? Of course, it is “just common sense” that monkeys don’t get ripe and
bananas don’t get hungry, so . . . But three further observations show that
this is not so much an answer as a restatement of the issue. First, sentences
that rely on common sense to avoid misunderstanding are anything but rare:
conversation is rife with them. Second, just about any odd fact that “everybody
knows” can be the bit of common sense that understanding the next sentence
depends on; and the range of such knowledge is vast. Yet, third, dialogue
proceeds in real time without a hitch, almost always. So the whole range of
commonsense knowledge must be somehow at our mental fingertips all the time.
The underlying difficulty is not with speed or quantity alone, but with
relevance. How does a system, given all that it knows about aardvarks, Alabama,
and ax handles, “home in on” the pertinent fact that bananas don’t get hungry,
in the fraction of a second it can afford to spend on the pronoun ‘it’? The
answer proposed is both simple and powerful: common sense is not just randomly
stored information, but is instead highly organized by topics, with lots of
indexes, cross-references, tables, hierarchies, and so on. The words in the
sentence itself trigger the “articles” on monkeys, bananas, hunger, and so on,
and these quickly reveal that monkeys are mammals, hence animals, that bananas
are fruit, hence from plants, that hunger is what animals feel when they need
to eat and that settles it. The amount
of search and reasoning is minimal; the issue of relevance is solved instead by
the antecedent structure in the stored knowledge itself. While this requires
larger and more elaborate systems, the hope is that it will make them faster
and more flexible. The other main orientation toward artificial intelligence,
the pattern-based approach often called
“connectionism” or “parallel distributed processing” reemerged from the shadow of symbol
processing only in the 0s, and remains in many ways less developed. The basic
inspiration comes not from language or any other psychological phenomenon such
as imagery or affect, but from the microstructure of the brain. The components
of a connectionist system are relatively simple active nodes lots of them
and relatively simple connections between those nodes again, lots of them. One important type and
the easiest to visualize has the nodes divided into layers, such that each node
in layer A is connected to each node in layer B, each node in layer B is
connected to each node in layer C, and so on. Each node has an activation
level, which varies in response to the activations of other, connected nodes;
and each connection has a weight, which determines how strongly and in what
direction the activation of one node affects that of the other. The analogy
with neurons and synapses, though imprecise, is intended. So imagine a layered
network with finely tuned connection weights and random or zero activation
levels. Now suppose the activations of all the nodes in layer A are set in some
particular way some pattern is imposed
on the activation state of this layer. These activations will propagate out
along all the connections from layer A to layer B, and activate some pattern
there. The activation of each node in layer B is a function of the activations
of all the nodes in layer A, and of the weights of all the connections to it
from those nodes. But since each node in layer B has its own connections from
the nodes in layer A, it will respond in its own unique way to this pattern of
activations in layer A. Thus, the pattern that results in layer B is a joint
function of the pattern that was imposed on layer A and of the pattern of
connection weights between the two layers. And a similar story can be told
about layer B’s influence on layer C, and so on, until some final pattern is
induced in the last layer. What are these patterns? They might be any number of
things; but two general possibilities can be distinguished. They might be
tantamount to or substrata beneath representations of some familiar sort, such
as sentencelike structures or images; or they might be a kind or kinds of
representation previously unknown. Now, people certainly do sometimes think in
sentences and probably images; so, to the extent that networks are taken as
complete brain models, the first alternative must be at least partly right.
But, to that extent, the models are also more physiological than psychological:
it is rather the implemented sentences or images that directly model the mind.
Thus, it is the possibility of a new genus of representation sometimes called distributed
representation that is particularly
exciting. On this alternative, the patterns in the mind represent in some way
other than by mimetic imagery or articulate description. How? An important
feature of all network models is that there are two quite different categories
of pattern. On the one hand, there are the relatively ephemeral patterns of
activation in various artificial intelligence artificial intelligence 56 56 groups of nodes; on the other, there are
the relatively stable patterns of connection strength among the nodes. Since
there are in general many more connections than nodes, the latter patterns are
richer; and it is they that determine the capabilities of the network with
regard to the former patterns. Many of the abilities most easily and
“naturally” realized in networks can be subsumed under the heading pattern
completion: the connection weights are adjusted
perhaps via a training regime
such that the network will complete any of the activation patterns from
a predetermined group. So, suppose some fraction say half of the nodes in the
net are clamped to the values they would have for one of those patterns say P
while the remainder are given random or default activations. Then the network,
when run, will reset the latter activations to the values belonging to P thus “completing” it. If the unclamped
activations are regarded as variations or deviations, pattern completion
amounts to normalization, or grouping by similarity. If the initial or input
nodes are always the same as in layered networks, then we have pattern
association or transformation from input to output. If the input pattern is a
memory probe, pattern completion becomes access by content. If the output
pattern is an identifier, then it is pattern recognition. And so on. Note that,
although the operands are activation patterns, the “knowledge” about them, the
ability to complete them, is contained in the connection patterns; hence, that
ability or know-how is what the network represents. There is no obvious upper
bound on the possible refinement or intricacy of these pattern groupings and
associations. If the input patterns are sensory stimuli and the output patterns
are motor control, then we have a potential model of coordinated and even
skillful behavior. In a system also capable of language, a network model or
component might account for verbal recognition and content association, and
even such “nonliteral” effects as trope and tone. Yet at least some sort of
“symbol manipulation” seems essential for language use, regardless of how
networklike the implementation is. One current speculation is that it might
suffice to approximate a battery of symbolic processes as a special subsystem
within a cognitive system that fundamentally works on quite different
principles. The attraction of the pattern-based approach is, at this point, not
so much actual achievement as it is promise
on two grounds. In the first place, the space of possible models, not only
network topologies but also ways of construing the patterns, is vast. Those
built and tested so far have been, for practical reasons, rather small; so it
is possible to hope beyond their present limitations to systems of
significantly greater capability. But second, and perhaps even more attractive,
those directions in which patternbased systems show the most promise skills, recognition, similarity, and the
like are among the areas of greatest
frustration for languagebased AI. Hence it remains possible, for a while at
least, to overlook the fact that, to date, no connectionist network can perform
long division, let alone play chess or solve symbolic logic problems. Refs.: H.
P. Grice, “Intelligence: natural and non-natural.”
Natura – natura-ars distinction -- natural
life -- artificial life, an interdisciplinary science studying the most general
character of the fundamental processes of life. These processes include
self-organization, self-reproduction, learning, adaptation, and evolution.
Artificial life or ALife is to theoretical biology roughly what artificial
intelligence AI is to theoretical psychology
computer simulation is the methodology of choice. In fact, since the
mind exhibits many of life’s fundamental properties, AI could be considered a subfield
of ALife. However, whereas most traditional AI models are serial systems with
complicated, centralized controllers making decisions based on global state
information, most natural systems exhibiting complex autonomous behavior are
parallel, distributed networks of simple entities making decisions based solely
on their local state information, so typical ALife models have a corresponding
distributed architecture. A computer simulation of evolving “bugs” can
illustrate what ALife models are like. Moving around in a two-dimensional world
periodically laden with heaps of “food,” these bugs eat, reproduce, and
sometimes perish from starvation. Each bug’s movement is genetically determined
by the quantities of food in its immediate neighborhood, and random mutations
and crossovers modify these genomes during reproduction. Simulations started
with random genes show spontaneous waves of highly adaptive genetic novelties
continuously sweeping through the population at precisely quantifiable rates.C.
Langston et al., eds., Artificial Life II 1. artificial language artificial
life 57 57 ALife science raises and
promises to inform many philosophical issues, such as: Is functionalism the
right approach toward life? When, if ever, is a simulation of life really alive?
When do systems exhibit the spontaneous emergence of properties? Refs.: Grice: “Life: natural and
non-natural.” naturalism, the twofold view that 1 everything is composed of
natural entities those studied in the
sciences on some versions, the natural sciences
whose properties determine all the properties of things, persons
included abstracta like possibilia and mathematical objects, if they exist,
being constructed of such abstract entities as the sciences allow; and 2
acceptable methods of justification and explanation are continuous, in some
sense, with those in science. Clause 1 is metaphysical or ontological, clause 2
methodological and/or epistemological. Often naturalism is formulated only for
a specific subject matter or domain. Thus ethical naturalism holds that moral
properties are equivalent to or at least determined by certain natural
properties, so that moral judgments either form a subclass of, or are
non-reductively determined by the factual or descriptive judgments, and the
appropriate methods of moral justification and explanation are continuous with
those in science. Aristotle and Spinoza sometimes are counted among the
ancestors of naturalism, as are Democritus, Epicurus, Lucretius, and Hobbes.
But the major impetus to naturalism in the last two centuries comes from advances
in science and the growing explanatory power they signify. By the 1850s, the
synthesis of urea, reflections on the conservation of energy, work on “animal
electricity,” and discoveries in physiology suggested to Feuerbach, L. Buchner,
and others that all aspects of human beings are explainable in purely natural
terms. Darwin’s theory had even greater impact, and by the end of the
nineteenth century naturalist philosophies were making inroads where idealism
once reigned unchallenged. Naturalism’s ranks now included H. Spencer, J.
Tyndall, T. H. Huxley, W. K. Clifford, and E. Haeckel. Early in the twentieth
century, Santayana’s naturalism strongly influenced a number of philosophers, as did Dewey’s. Still other
versions of naturalism flourished in America in the 0s and 0s, including those
of R. W. Sellars and M. Cohen. Today most New-World philosophers of mind are
naturalists of some stripe, largely because of what they see as the lessons of
continuing scientific advances, some of them spectacular, particularly in the
brain sciences. Nonetheless, twentieth-century philosophy has been largely
anti-naturalist. Both phenomenology in the Husserlian tradition and analytic
philosophy in the Fregean tradition, together with their descendants, have been
united in rejecting psychologism, a species of naturalism according to which
empirical discoveries about mental processes are crucial for understanding the
nature of knowledge, language, and logic. In order to defend the autonomy of
philosophy against inroads from descriptive science, many philosophers have
tried to turn the tables by arguing for the priority of philosophy over
science, hence over any of its alleged naturalist implications. Many continue
to do so, often on the ground that philosophy alone can illuminate the
normativity and intentionality involved in knowledge, language, and logic; or
on the ground that philosophy can evaluate the normative and regulative
presuppositions of scientific practice which science itself is either blind to
or unequipped to analyze; or on the ground that phi- losophy understands how
the language of science can no more be used to get outside itself than any
other, hence can no more be known to be in touch with the world and ourselves
than any other; or on the ground that would-be justifications of fundamental
method, naturalist method certainly included, are necessarily circular because
they must employ the very method at issue. Naturalists may reply by arguing
that naturalism’s methodological clause 2 entails the opposite of dogmatism,
requiring as it does an uncompromising fallibilism about philosophical matters
that is continuous with the open, selfcritical spirit of science. If evidence
were to accumulate against naturalism’s metaphysical clause 1, 1 would have to
be revised or rejected, and there is no a priori reason such evidence could in
principle never be found; indeed many naturalists reject the a priori
altogether. Likewise, 2 itself might have to be revised or even rejected in
light of adverse argument, so that in this respect 2 is self-referentially
consistent. Until then, 2’s having survived rigorous criticism to date is
justification enough, as is the case with hypotheses in science, which often
are deployed without circularity in the course of their own evaluation, whether
positive or negative H. I. Brown, “Circular Justifications,” 4. So too can
language be used without circularity in expressing hypotheses about the
relations between language and the prelinguistic world as illustrated by R.
Millikan’s Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories, 4; cf. Post,
“Epistemology,” 6. As for normativity and intentionality, naturalism does not
entail materialism or physicalism, according to which everything is composed of
the entities or processes studied in physics, and the properties of these basic
physical affairs determine all the properties of things as in Quine. Some
naturalists deny this, holding that more things than are dreamt of in physics
are required to account for normativity and intentionality and consciousness. Nor need naturalism be
reductive, in the sense of equating every property with some natural property.
Indeed many physicalists themselves explain how the physical, hence natural,
properties of things might determine other, non-natural properties without
being equivalent to them G. Hellman, T. Horgan, D. Lewis; see J. Post, The
Faces of Existence, 7. Often the determining physical properties are not all
properties of the thing x that has the non-natural properties, but include
properties of items separated from x in space and time or in some cases bearing
no physical relation to x that does any work in determining x’s properties
Post, “ ‘Global’ Supervenient Determination: Too Permissive?” 5. Thus
naturalism allows a high degree of holism and historicity, which opens the way
for a non-reductive naturalist account of intentionality and normativity, such
as Millikan’s, that is immune to the usual objections, which are mostly
objections to reduction. The alternative psychosemantic theories of Dretske and
Fodor, being largely reductive, remain vulnerable to such objections. In these
and other ways non-reductive naturalism attempts to combine a monism of
entities the natural ones of which
everything is composed with a pluralism
of properties, many of them irreducible or emergent. Not everything is nothing
but a natural thing, nor need naturalism accord totalizing primacy to the
natural face of existence. Indeed, some naturalists regard the universe as
having religious and moral dimensions that enjoy a crucial kind of primacy; and
some offer theologies that are more traditionally theist as do H. N. Wieman, C.
Hardwick, J. Post. So far from exhibiting “reptilian indifference” to humans
and their fate, the universe can be an enchanted place of belonging. Refs.: H.
P. Grice: “My labour against Naturalism.” Natura – naturalism -- naturalistic
epistemology, an approach to epistemology that views the human subject as a
natural phenomenon and uses empirical science to study epistemic activity. The
phrase was introduced by Quine “Epistemology Naturalized,” in Ontological
Relativity and Other Essays, 9, who proposed that epistemology should be a
chapter of psychology. Quine construed classical epistemology as Cartesian
epistemology, an attempt to ground all knowledge in a firmly logical way on
immediate experience. In its twentieth-century embodiment, it hoped to give a
translation of all discourse and a deductive validation of all science in terms
of sense experience, logic, and set theory. Repudiating this dream as forlorn,
Quine urged that epistemology be abandoned and replaced by psychology. It would
be a scientific study of how the subject takes sensory stimulations as input
and delivers as output a theory of the three-dimensional world. This
formulation appears to eliminate the normative mission of epistemology. In
later writing, however, Quine has suggested that normative epistemology can be
naturalized as a chapter of engineering: the technology of predicting
experience, or sensory stimulations. Some theories of knowledge are
naturalistic in their depiction of knowers as physical systems in causal
interaction with the environment. One such theory is the causal theory of
knowing, which says that a person knows that p provided his belief that p has a
suitable causal connection with a corresponding state of affairs. Another
example is the information-theoretic approach developed by Dretske Knowledge
and the Flow of Information, 1. This says that a person knows that p only if
some signal “carries” this information that p to him, where information is
construed as an objective commodity that can be processed and transmitted via
instruments, gauges, neurons, and the like. Information is “carried” from one
site to another when events located at those sites are connected by a suitable
lawful dependence. The normative concept of justification has also been the
subject of naturalistic construals. Whereas many theories of justified belief
focus on logical or probabilistic relations between evidence and hypothesis,
naturalistic theories focus on the psychological processes causally responsible
for the belief. The logical status of a belief does not fix its justificational
status. Belief in a tautology, for instance, is not justified if it is formed
by blind trust in an ignorant guru. According to Goldman Epistemology and
Cognition, 6, a belief qualifies as justified only if it is produced by
reliable belief-forming processes, i.e., processes that generally have a high
truth ratio. Goldman’s larger program for naturalistic epistemology is called
“epistemics,” an interdisciplinary enterprise in which cognitive science would
play a major role. Epistemics would seek to identify the subset of cognitive
operations available to the human cognizer that are best from a truth-bearing
standpoint. Relevant truth-linked properties include problem-solving power and
speed, i.e., the abilities to obtain correct answers to questions of interest
and to do so quickly. Close connections between epistemology and artificial
intelligence have been proposed by Clark Glymour, Gilbert Harman, John Pollock,
and Paul Thagard. Harman stresses that principles of good reasoning are not
directly given by rules of logic. Modus ponens, e.g., does not tell you to
infer q if you already believe p and ‘if p then q’. In some cases it is better
to subtract a belief in one of the premises rather than add a belief in q.
Belief revision also requires attention to the storage and computational
limitations of the mind. Limits of memory capacity, e.g., suggest a principle
of clutter avoidance: not filling one’s mind with vast numbers of useless
beliefs Harman, Change in View, 6. Other conceptions of naturalistic
epistemology focus on the history of science. Larry Laudan conceives of
naturalistic epistemology as a scientific inquiry that gathers empirical
evidence concerning the past track records of various scientific methodologies,
with the aim of determining which of these methodologies can best advance the
chosen cognitive ends. Naturalistic epistemology need not confine its attention
to individual epistemic agents; it can also study communities of agents. This
perspective invites contributions from sciences that address the social side of
the knowledge-seeking enterprise. If naturalistic epistemology is a normative
inquiry, however, it must not simply naturalism, biological naturalistic
epistemology 598 598 describe social
practices or social influences; it must analyze the impact of these factors on
the attainment of cognitive ends. Philosophers such as David Hull, Nicholas
Rescher, Philip Kitcher, and Alvin Goldman have sketched models inspired by
population biology and economics to explore the epistemic consequences of
alternative distributions of research activity and different ways that
professional rewards might influence the course of research.
Lockeian ‘sort’ -- natural kind, a
category of entities classically conceived as having modal implications; e.g.,
if Socrates is a member of the natural kind human being, then he is necessarily
a human being. The idea that nature fixes certain sortals, such as ‘water’ and
‘human being’, as correct classifications that appear to designate kinds of
entities has roots going back at least to Plato and Aristotle. Anil Gupta has
argued that sortals are to be distinguished from properties designated by such
predicates as ‘red’ by including criteria for individuating the particulars
bits or amounts for mass nouns that fall under them as well as criteria for
sorting those particulars into the class. Quine is salient among those who find
the modal implications of natural kinds objectionable. He has argued that the
idea of natural kinds is rooted in prescientific intuitive judgments of
comparative similarity, and he has suggested that as these intuitive
classifications are replaced by classifications based on scientific theories
these modal implications drop away. Kripke and Putnam have argued that science
in fact uses natural kind terms having the modal implications Quine finds so
objectionable. They see an important role in scientific methodology for the
capacity to refer demonstratively to such natural kinds by pointing out
particulars that fall under them. Certain inferences within science such as the inference to the charge for
electrons generally from the measurement of the charge on one or a few
electrons seem to be additional aspects
of a role for natural kind terms in scientific practice. Other roles in the
methodology of science for natural kind concepts have been discussed in recent
work by Ian Hacking and Thomas Kuhn. H. P. Grice: “Lockeian sorts: natural and
non-natural.”
Ligatum, lex, -- the natural/non-natural
distinction -- natural law, also called law of nature, in moral and political
philosophy, an objective norm or set of objective norms governing human
behavior, similar to the positive laws of a human ruler, but binding on all
people alike and usually understood as involving a superhuman legislator.
Ancient Grecian and Roman thought, particularly Stoicism, introduced ideas of
eternal laws directing the actions of all rational beings and built into the
very structure of the universe. Roman lawyers developed a doctrine of a law
that all civilized peoples would recognize, and made some effort to explain it
in terms of a natural law common to animals and humans. The most influential
forms of natural law theory, however, arose from later efforts to use Stoic and
legal language to work out a Christian theory of morality and politics. The aim
was to show that the principles of morals could be known by reason alone,
without revelation, so that the whole human race could know how to live
properly. The law of nature applies, on this understanding, only to rational
beings, who can obey or disobey it deliberately and freely. It is thus
different in kind from the laws God laid down for the inanimate and irrational
parts of creation. Natural law theorists often saw continuities and analogies
between natural laws for humans and those for the rest of creation but did not
confuse them. The most enduringly influential natural law writer was Aquinas.
On his view God’s eternal reason ordains laws directing all things to act for
the good of the community of the universe, the declaration of His own glory.
Human reason can participate sufficiently in God’s eternal reason to show us
the good of the human community. The natural law is thus our sharing in the
eternal law in a way appropriate to our human nature. God lays down certain
other laws through revelation; these divine laws point us toward our eternal
goal. The natural law concerns our earthly good, and needs to be supplemented
by human laws. Such laws can vary from community to community, but to be
binding they must always stay within the limits of the law of nature. God
engraved the most basic principles of the natural law in the minds of all
people alike, but their detailed application takes reasoning powers that not
everyone may have. Opponents of Aquinas
called voluntarists argued that
God’s will, not his intellect, is the source of law, and that God could have
laid down different natural laws for us. Hugo Grotius rejected their position,
but unlike Aquinas he conceived of natural law as meant not to direct us to
bring about some definite common good but to set the limits on the ways in
which each of us could properly pursue our own personal aims. This Grotian
outlook was developed by Hobbes, Pufendorf, and Locke along voluntarist lines.
Thomistic views continued to be expounded by Protestant as well as Roman
Catholic writers until the end of the seventeenth century. Thereafter, while
natural law theory remained central to Catholic teaching, it ceased to attract
major new non-Catholic proponents. Natural law doctrine in both Thomistic and
Grotian versions treats morality as basically a matter of compliance with law.
Obligation and duty, obedience and disobedience, merit and guilt, reward and
punishment, are central notions. Virtues are simply habits of following laws.
Though the law is suited to our distinctive human nature and can be discovered
by the proper use of reason, it is not a self-imposed law. In following it we
are obeying God. Since the early eighteenth century, philosophical discussions
of whether or not there is an objective morality have largely ceased to center
on natural law. The idea remains alive, however, in jurisprudence. Natural law
theories are opposed to legal positivism, the view that the only binding laws
are those imposed by human sovereigns, who cannot be subject to higher legal
constraints. Legal theorists arguing that there are rational objective limits
to the legislative power of rulers often think of these limits in terms of
natural law, even when their theories do not invoke or imply any of the
religious aspects of earlier natural law positions. Refs.: N.
Cartwright-Hampshire, “How the laws of phyiscs lie,” in P. G. R. I. C. E.,
without a response by H. P. Grice. (“That will not be feasible.”)
natura – the natural/transnatural
distinction -- natural philosophy – Grice: “It’s funny: there are only three or
four chairs of philosophy at Oxford and one had to be on ‘the trans-natural’
philosophy! Back in the day, I might just as well have to have attended the
‘natural’ philosophy lectures!” -- the
study of nature or of the spatiotemporal world. This was regarded as a task for
philosophy before the emergence of modern science, especially physics and
astronomy, and the term is now only used with reference to premodern times.
Philosophical questions about nature still remain, e.g., whether materialism is
true, but they would usually be placed in metaphysics or in a branch of it that
may be called philosophy of nature. Natural philosophy is not to be confused
with metaphysical naturalism, which is the metaphysical view no part of science
itself that all that there is is the spatiotemporal world and that the only way
to study it is that of the empirical sciences. It is also not to be confused
with natural theology, which also may be considered part of metaphysics. The Sedleian Professor of Natural Philosophy is the name of
a chair at the Mathematical Institute of the University of Oxford. The
Sedleian Chair was founded by Sir William Sedley who, by his will dated 20
October 1618, left the sum of £2,000 to the University of Oxford for purchase
of lands for its endowment. Sedley's bequest took effect in 1621 with the
purchase of an estate at Waddesdon in Buckinghamshire to produce the necessary
income. It is regarded as the oldest of Oxford's scientific chairs.
Holders of the Sedleian Professorship have, since the mid 19th Century, worked
in a range of areas of Applied Mathematics and Mathematical Physics. They are
simultaneously elected to fellowships at Queen's College, Oxford. The
Sedleian Professors in the past century have been Augustus Love (1899-1940),
who was distinguished for his work in the mathematical theory of elasticity,
Sydney Chapman (1946-1953), who is renowned for his contributions to the
kinetic theory of gases and solar-terrestrial physics, George Temple
(1953-1968), who made significant contributions to mathematical physics and the
theory of generalized functions, Brooke Benjamin (1979-1995), who did highly
influential work in the areas of mathematical analysis and fluid mechanics, and
Sir John Ball (1996-2019), who is distinguished for his work in the
mathematical theory of elasticity, materials science, the calculus of
variations, and infinite-dimensional dynamical systems. Refs.: H. P.
Grice: “Oxford and the four Ws: Waynflete, White, Wykeham, and Wilde.”
Natura – nautralism -- natural religion, a
term first occurring in the second half of the seventeenth century, used in
three related senses, the most common being 1 a body of truths about God and
our duty that can be discovered by natural reason. These truths are sufficient
for salvation or according to some orthodox Christians would have been
sufficient if Adam had not sinned. Natural religion in this sense should be
distinguished from natural theology, which does not imply this. A natural
religion may also be 2 one that has a human, as distinct from a divine, origin.
It may also be 3 a religion of human nature as such, as distinguished from
religious beliefs and practices that have been determined by local
circumstances. Natural religion in the third sense is identified with
humanity’s original religion. In all three senses, natural religion includes a
belief in God’s existence, justice, benevolence, and providential government;
in immortality; and in the dictates of common morality. While the concept is
associated with deism, it is also sympathetically treated by Christian writers
like Clarke, who argues that revealed religion simply restores natural religion
to its original purity and adds inducements to compliance. The Faculty of Medicine
appoints an elector for the professorship of Human Anatomy and for the
professorship of Pathology. The Board of Natural Science appoints one elector
for the professorship of Pathology and two for the Lee's Readerships. The Board
of Modern History appoints two electors for the Beit professorship and
lectureship, and three for the Ford lectureship. The Board of Theology appoints
three of the seven electors for the Speaker's lectureship in Biblical Studies.
Three different Boards of Faculty appoint electors for the Wilde lectureship in
Natural Religion. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Natural religion at Oxford
– the Wilde and the Wilde.”
Modus – necessitas -- Necessitarianism:
“An ugly word once used by Strawson in a tutorial!” – Grice. -- the doctrine
that necessity is an objective feature of the world. Natural language permits
speakers to express modalities: a state of affairs can be actual Paris’s being
in France, merely possible chlorophyll’s making things blue, or necessary 2 ! 2
% 4. Anti-necessitarians believe that these distinctions are not grounded in
the nature of the world. Some of them claim that the distinctions are merely
verbal. Others, e.g., Hume, believed that psychological facts, like our
expectations of future events, explain the idea of necessity. Yet others
contend that the modalities reflect epistemic considerations; necessity
reflects the highest level of an inquirer’s commitment. Some necessitarians
believe there are different modes of metaphysical necessity, e.g., causal and
logical necessity. Certain proponents of idealism believe that each fact is
necessarily connected with every other fact so that the ultimate goal of
scientific inquiry is the discovery of a completely rigorous mathematical
system of the world.
modus -- necessitas – necessarium -- necessity,
a modal property attributable to a whole proposition dictum just when it is not
possible that the proposition be false the proposition being de dicto
necessary. Narrowly construed, a proposition P is logically necessary provided P
satisfies certain syntactic conditions, namely, that P’s denial is formally
self-contradictory. More broadly, P is logically necessary just when P
satisfies certain semantic conditions, namely, that P’s denial is false, and P
true, in all possible worlds. These semantic conditions were first suggested by
Leibniz, refined by Vitters and Carnap, and fully developed as the possible
worlds semantics of Kripke, Hintikka, et al., in the 0s. Previously,
philosophers had to rely largely on intuition to determine the acceptability or
otherwise of formulas involving the necessity operator, A, and were at a loss
as to which of various axiomatic systems for modal logic, as developed in the
0s by C. I. Lewis, best captured the notion of logical necessity. There was much
debate, for instance, over the characteristic NN thesis of Lewis’s system S4,
namely, AP / A AP if P is necessary then it is necessarily necessary. But given
a Leibnizian account of the truth conditions for a statement of the form Aa
namely R1 that Aa is true provided a is true in all possible worlds, and R2
that Aa is false provided there is at least one possible world in which a is
false, a proof can be constructed by reductio ad absurdum. For suppose that AP
/ AAP is false in some arbitrarily chosen world W. Then its antecedent will be
true in W, and hence by R1 it follows a that P will be true in all possible
worlds. But equally its consequent will be false in W, and hence by R2 AP will
be false in at least one possible world, from which again by R2 it follows b
that P will be false in at least one possible world, thus contradicting a. A
similar proof can be constructed for the characteristic thesis of S5, namely,
-A-P / A-A-P if P is possibly true then it is necessarily possible. Necessity
is also attributable to a property F of an object O provided it is not possible
that there is no possible world in which O exists and lacks F F being de re necessary, internal or
essential to O. For instance, the non-repeatable haecceitist property of being
identical to O is de re necessary essential to O, and arguably the repeatable
property of being extended is de re necessary to all colored objects. nĕcesse
(arch. nĕcessum , I.v. infra: NECESVS, S. C. de Bacch. l. 4: necessus , Ter.
Heaut. 2, 3, 119 Wagn. ad loc.; id. Eun. 5, 5, 28; Gell. 16, 8, 1; v. Lachm. ad
Lucr. 6, 815), neutr. adj. (gen. necessis, Lucr. 6, 815 ex conj. Lachm.; cf.
Munro ad loc.; elsewhere only nom. and acc. sing., and with esse or habere)
[perh. Sanscr. naç, obtain; Gr. root ἐνεκ-; cf. ἀνάγκη; v. Georg Curtius Gr.
Etym. 424]. I. Form necesse. A. Unavoidable, inevitable, indispensable,
necessary (class.; cf.: opus, usus est) 1. With esse. a. With subject.-clause:
“edocet quanto detrimento...necesse sit constare victoriam,” Caes. B. G. 7, 19:
“necesse est eam, quae ... timere permultos,” Auct. Her. 4, 16, 23: emas, non
quod opus est, sed quod necesse est, Cato ap. Sen. Ep. 94, 28: “nihil fit, quod
necesse non fuerit,” Cic. Fat. 9, 17: “necesse est igitur legem haberi in rebus
optimis,” id. Leg. 2, 5, 12; id. Verr 2, 3, 29, § 70. — b. With dat. (of the
person, emphatic): nihil necesse est mihi de me ipso dicere, Cic. Sen. 9, 30:
“de homine enim dicitur, cui necesse est mori,” id. Fat. 9, 17.— c. With ut and
subj.: “eos necesse est ut petat,” Auct. Her. 4, 16, 23: “sed ita necesse
fuisse, cum Demosthenes dicturus esset, ut concursus ex totā Graeciā fierent,”
Cic. Brut. 84, 289; Sen. Ep. 78, 15: “hoc necesse est, ut, etc.,” Cic. de Or.
2, 29, 129; Sen. Q. N. 2, 14, 2: “neque necesse est, uti vos auferam,” Gell. 2,
29, 9: “necesse est semper, ut id ... per se significet,” Quint. 8, 6, 43.— d.
With subj. alone: “haec autem oratio ... aut nulla sit necesse est, aut omnium
irrisione ludatur,” Cic. de Or. 1, 12, 50: “istum condemnetis necesse est,”
Cic. Verr. 2, 2, 18, § 45: “vel concidat omne caelum necesse est,” id. Tusc. 1,
23, 54: “si necesse est aliquid ex se magni boni pariat,” Lact. 3, 12, 7.— 2.
With habere (class. only with inf.): “non habebimus necesse semper concludere,”
Cic. Part. Or. 13, 47: “eo minus habeo necesse scribere,” id. Att. 10, 1, 4:
“Oppio scripsi ne necesse habueris reddere,” id. ib. 16, 2, 5: “non verbum pro
verbo necesse habui reddere,” id. Opt. Gen. Or. 5, 14: “non necesse habeo omnia
pro meo jure agere,” Ter. Ad. 1, 1, 26; Quint. 11, 1, 74; Vulg. Matt. 14, 16:
necesse habere with abl. (= egere; “late Lat.): non necesse habent sani
medico,” Vulg. Marc. 2, 17.—In agreement with object of habere: “non habet rex
sponsalia necesse,” Vulg. 1 Reg. 18, 25.— B. Needful, requisite, indispensable,
necessary: “id quod tibi necesse minime fuit, facetus esse voluisti,” Cic.
Sull. 7, 22.— II. Form necessum (mostly ante-class.). A. With subject.-clause:
“foras necessum est, quicquid habeo, vendere,” Plaut. Stich. 1, 3, 66: quod sit
necessum scire, Afran. ap. Charis. p. 186 P.: “nec tamen haec retineri hamata
necessumst,” Lucr. 2, 468: “externa corpus de parte necessumst tundier,” id. 4,
933: “necessum est vorsis gladiis depugnarier,” Plaut. Cas. 2, 5, 36: “necessum
est paucis respondere,” Liv. 34, 5: “num omne id aurum in ludos consumi
necessum esset?” id. 39, 5: “tonsorem capiti non est adhibere necessum,” Mart.
6, 57, 3.— B. With dat.: “dicas uxorem tibi necessum esse ducere,” Plaut. Mil.
4, 3, 25.— C. With subj.: “unde anima, atque animi constet natura necessum
est,” Lucr. 4, 120: “quare etiam nativa necessum est confiteare Haec eadem,”
id. 5, 377. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The may and the must,” “Ichthyological
necessity.”
need – H. P. Grice, “Need,” cf. D. Wiggins, “Need.” “What Toby
needs” Grice was also interested in the modal use of ‘need’. “You need to do
it.” “ ‘Need,’ like ‘ought’ takes ‘to.’” “It’s very Anglo-Saxon.” “Or, rather
non-Indo-European substratum!” As it is attested only in Germanic,
Celtic, and Balto-Slavic, it might be non-PIE, from a regional substrate
language.
negri: a crucial Italian
philosopher. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice e Negri," per il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
abdicatum: negation: H. P. Grice,
“Negation.” the logical operation on propositions that is indicated, e.g., by
the prefatory clause ‘It is not the case that . . .’. Negation is standardly
distinguished sharply from the operation on predicates that is called complementation
and that is indicated by the prefix ‘non-’. Because negation can also be
indicated by the adverb ‘not’, a distinction is often drawn between external
negation, which is indicated by attaching the prefatory ‘It is not the case
that . . .’ to an assertion, and internal negation, which is indicated by
inserting the adverb ‘not’ along with, perhaps, nature, right of negation
601 601 grammatically necessary words
like ‘do’ or ‘does’ into the assertion in such a way as to indicate that the
adverb ‘not’ modifies the verb. In a number of cases, the question arises as to
whether external and internal negation yield logically equivalent results. For
example, ‘It is not the case that Santa Claus exists’ would seem obviously to
be true, whereas ‘Santa Claus does not exist’ seems to some philosophers to
presuppose what it denies, on the ground that nothing could be truly asserted
of Santa Claus unless he existed. Refs.:
H. P. Grice, “Negation and privation;” H. P. Grice, “Lectures on negation.”
Nemesius: Grecian philosopher. His
treatise on the soul, On the Nature of Man, tr. from Grecian into Latin by
Alphanus of Salerno and Burgundio of Pisa was attributed to Gregory of Nyssa, and
enjoyed some authority. The treatise rejects Plato for underplaying the unity
of soul and body, and Aristotle for making the soul essentially corporeal. The
soul is self-subsistent, incorporeal, and by nature immortal, but naturally
suited for union with the body. Nemesius draws on Ammonius Saccas and Porphyry to
explain the incorruptible soul’s perfect union with the corruptible body. His
review of the powers of the soul (“what I will call ‘the power structure of the
soul,’” – Grice). draws especially on Galen on the brain. His view that
rational creatures possess free will in virtue of their rationality influenced
Maximus the Confessor and John of Damascus.
Ariskant – Kantianism, palaeo-Kantianism,
neo-Kantianism, Ariskantianism! -- neo-Kantianism – as opposed to
‘palaeo-Kantianism’ -- the diverse Kantian movement that emerged within G.
philosophy in the 1860s, gained a strong academic foothold in the 1870s,
reached its height during the three decades prior to World War I, and
disappeared with the rise of Nazism. The movement was initially focused on
renewed study and elaboration of Kant’s epistemology in response to the growing
epistemic authority of the natural sciences and as an alternative to both
Hegelian and speculative idealism and the emerging materialism of, among
others, Ludwig Büchner 182499. Later neo-Kantianism explored Kant’s whole
philosophy, applied his critical method to disciplines other than the natural
sciences, and developed its own philosophical systems. Some originators and/or
early contributors were Kuno Fischer 18247, Hermann von Helmholtz 182,
Friedrich Albert Lange 182875, Eduard Zeller 18148, and Otto Liebmann 18402,
whose Kant und die Epigonen 1865 repeatedly stated what became a neoKantian
motto, “Back to Kant!” Several forms of neo-Kantianism are to be distinguished.
T. K. Oesterreich 09, in Friedrich Ueberwegs Grundriss der Geschichte der
Philosophie “F.U.’s Compendium of the History of Philosophy,” 3, developed the
standard, somewhat chronological, classification: 1 The physiological
neo-Kantianism of Helmholtz and Lange, who claimed that physiology is
“developed or corrected Kantianism.” 2 The metaphysical neo-Kantianism of the
later Liebmann, who argued for a Kantian “critical metaphysics” beyond
epistemology in the form of “hypotheses” about the essence of things. 3 The
realist neo-Kantianism of Alois Riehl 18444, who emphasized the real existence
of Kant’s thing-in-itself. 4 The logistic-methodological neo-Kantianism of the
Marburg School of Hermann Cohen 18428 and Paul Natorp 18544. 5 The axiological
neo-Kantianism of the Baden or Southwest G. School of Windelband 18485 and
Heinrich Rickert 18636. 6 The relativistic neo-Kantianism of Georg Simmel
18588, who argued for Kantian categories relative to individuals and cultures.
7 The psychological neo-Kantianism of Leonard Nelson 27, originator of the
Göttingen School; also known as the neo-Friesian School, after Jakob Friedrich
Fries 17731843, Nelson’s self-proclaimed precursor. Like Fries, Nelson held
that Kantian a priori principles cannot be transcendentally justified, but can
be discovered only through introspection. Oesterreich’s classification has been
narrowed or modified, partly because of conflicting views on how distinctly
“Kantian” a philosopher must have been to be called “neo-Kantian.” The very
term ‘neo-Kantianism’ has even been called into question, as suggesting real
intellectual commonality where little or none is to be found. There is,
however, growing consensus that Marneo-Euclidean geometry neo-Kantianism
603 603 burg and Baden neo-Kantianism
were the most important and influential. Marburg School. Its founder, Cohen,
developed its characteristic Kantian idealism of the natural sciences by
arguing that physical objects are truly known only through the laws of these
sciences and that these laws presuppose the application of Kantian a priori
principles and concepts. Cohen elaborated this idealism by eliminating Kant’s
dualism of sensibility and understanding, claiming that space and time are
construction methods of “pure thought” rather than a priori forms of perception
and that the notion of any “given” perceptual data prior to the “activity” of
“pure thought” is meaningless. Accordingly, Cohen reformulated Kant’s
thing-in-itself as the regulative idea that the mathematical description of the
world can always be improved. Cohen also emphasized that “pure thought” refers
not to individual consciousess on his
account Kant had not yet sufficiently left behind a “subjectobject”
epistemology but rather to the content
of his own system of a priori principles, which he saw as subject to change
with the progress of science. Just as Cohen held that epistemology must be
based on the “fact of science,” he argued, in a decisive step beyond Kant, that
ethics must transcendentally deduce both the moral law and the ideal moral subject
from a humanistic science more
specifically, from jurisprudence’s notion of the legal person. This analysis
led to the view that the moral law demands that all institutions, including
economic enterprises, become democratic
so that they display unified wills and intentions as transcendental
conditions of the legal person and that
all individuals become colegislators. Thus Cohen arrived at his frequently
cited claim that Kant “is the true and real originator of G. socialism.” Other
important Marburg Kantians were Cohen’s colleague Natorp, best known for his
studies on Plato and philosophy of education, and their students Karl Vorländer
18608, who focused on Kantian socialist ethics as a corrective of orthodox
Marxism, and Ernst Cassirer 18745. Baden School. The basic task of philosophy
and its transcendental method is seen as identifying universal values that make
possible culture in its varied expressions. This focus is evident in
Windelband’s influential insight that the natural sciences seek to formulate
general laws nomothetic knowledge while the historical sciences seek to
describe unique events idiographic
knowledge. This distinction is based on the values interests of mastery of
nature and understanding and reliving the unique past in order to affirm our
individuality. Windelband’s view of the historical sciences as idiographic
raised the problem of selection central to his successor Rickert’s writings:
How can historians objectively determine which individual events are
historically significant? Rickert argued that this selection must be based on
the values that are generally recognized within the cultures under
investigation, not on the values of historians themselves. Rickert also
developed the transcendental argument that the objectivity of the historical
sciences necessitates the assumption that the generally recognized values of
different cultures approximate in various degrees universally valid values.
This argument was rejected by Weber, whose methodological work was greatly
indebted to Rickert. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Kantianism: old and new.”
Platone – Platonism – Walter Pater -- Neo-platonism
– as opposed to ‘palaeo-Platonism’ -- that period of Platonism following on the
new impetus provided by the philosophical speculations of Plotinus A.D. 20469.
It extends, as a minimum, to the closing of the Platonic School in Athens by
Justinian in 529, but maximally through Byzantium, with such figures as Michael
Psellus 101878 and Pletho c.13601452, the Renaissance Ficino, Pico, and the
Florentine Academy, and the early modern period the Cambridge Platonists,
Thomas Taylor, to the advent of the “scientific” study of the works of Plato
with Schleiermacher 17681834 at the beginning of the nineteenth century. The
term was formerly also used to characterize the whole period from the Old
Academy of Plato’s immediate successors, Speusippus and Xenocrates, through
what is now termed Middle Platonism c.80 B.C.A.D. 220, down to Plotinus. This
account confines itself to the “minimum” interpretation. Neoplatonism proper
may be divided into three main periods: that of Plotinus and his immediate
followers third century; the “Syrian” School of Iamblichus and his followers
fourth century; and the “Athenian” School begun by Plutarch of Athens, and
including Syrianus, Proclus, and their successors, down to Damascius fifthsixth
centuries. Plotinus and his school. Plotinus’s innovations in Platonism
developed in his essays, the Enneads, collected and edited by his pupil
Porphyry after his death, are mainly two: a above the traditional supreme
principle of earlier Platonism and Aristotelianism, a self-thinking intellect,
which was also regarded as true being, he postulated a principle superior to
intellect and being, totally unitary and simple “the One”; b he saw reality as
a series of levels One, Intelligence, Soul, each higher one outflowing or
radiating into the next lower, while still remaining unaffected in itself, and
the lower ones fixing themselves in being by somehow “reflecting back” upon
their priors. This eternal process gives the universe its existence and
character. Intelligence operates in a state of non-temporal simultaneity,
holding within itself the “forms” of all things. Soul, in turn, generates time,
and receives the forms into itself as “reason principles” logoi. Our physical
three-dimensional world is the result of the lower aspect of Soul nature
projecting itself upon a kind of negative field of force, which Plotinus calls
“matter.” Matter has no positive existence, but is simply the receptacle for
the unfolding of Soul in its lowest aspect, which projects the forms in
three-dimensional space. Plotinus often speaks of matter as “evil” e.g. Enneads
II.8, and of the Soul as suffering a “fall” e.g. Enneads V.1, 1, but in fact he
sees the whole cosmic process as an inevitable result of the superabundant
productivity of the One, and thus “the best of all possible worlds.” Plotinus
was himself a mystic, but he arrived at his philosophical conclusions by
perfectly logical means, and he had not much use for either traditional
religion or any of the more recent superstitions. His immediate pupils, Amelius
c.22590 and Porphyry 234c.305, while somewhat more hospitable to these,
remained largely true to his philosophy though Amelius had a weakness for
triadic elaborations in metaphysics. Porphyry was to have wide influence, both
in the Latin West through such men as Marius Victorinus, Augustine, and
Boethius, and in the Grecian East and even, through translations, on medieval
Islam, as the founder of the Neoplatonic tradition of commentary on both Plato
and Aristotle, but it is mainly as an expounder of Plotinus’s philosophy that
he is known. He added little that is distinctive, though that little is
currently becoming better appreciated. Iamblichus and the Syrian School.
Iamblichus c.245325, descendant of an old Syrian noble family, was a pupil of
Porphyry’s, but dissented from him on various important issues. He set up his
own school in Apamea in Syria, and attracted many pupils. One chief point of
dissent was the role of theurgy really just magic, with philosophical
underpinnings, but not unlike Christian sacramental theology. Iamblichus
claimed, as against Porphyry, that philosophical reasoning alone could not
attain the highest degree of enlightenment, without the aid of theurgic rites,
and his view on this was followed by all later Platonists. He also produced a
metaphysical scheme far more elaborate than Plotinus’s, by a Scholastic filling
in, normally with systems of triads, of gaps in the “chain of being” left by
Plotinus’s more fluid and dynamic approach to philosophy. For instance, he
postulated two Ones, one completely transcendent, the other the source of all
creation, thus “resolving” a tension in Plotinus’s metaphysics. Iamblichus was
also concerned to fit as many of the traditional gods as possible into his
system, which later attracted the attention of the Emperor Julian, who based
himself on Iamblichus when attempting to set up a Hellenic religion to rival
Christianity, a project which, however, died with him in 363. The Athenian
School. The precise links between the pupils of Iamblichus and Plutarch d.432,
founder of the Athenian School, remain obscure, but the Athenians always
retained a great respect for the Syrian. Plutarch himself is a dim figure, but
Syrianus c.370437, though little of his writings survives, can be seen from
constant references to him by his pupil Proclus 412 85 to be a major figure,
and the source of most of Proclus’s metaphysical elaborations. The Athenians
essentially developed and systematized further the doctrines of Iamblichus,
creating new levels of divinity e.g. intelligibleintellectual gods, and
“henads” in the realm of the One though
they rejected the two Ones, this process reaching its culmination in the
thought of the last head of the Athenian Academy, Damascius c.456540. The drive
to systematize reality and to objectivize concepts, exhibited most dramatically
in Proclus’s Elements of Theology, is a lasting legacy of the later
Neoplatonists, and had a significant influence on the thought, among others, of
Hegel. Grice: “The implicaturum of ‘everything old is new again’ is that
everything new is old again.” “It’s the older generation, knock-knock-knocking
at the door!” -- Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Everything old is new again – and vice
versa.”
Otiumm -- Schole –scholasticism -- neo-scholasticism:
as opposed to palaeo-scholasticism – Grice: “The original name of Oxford was
‘studium generale’! The mascot was the ox!” --. the movement given impetus
Neoplatonism, Islamic neo-Scholasticism 605
605 by Pope Leo XIII’s encyclical Aeterni Patris 1879, which, while
stressing Aquinas, was a general recommendation of the study of medieval
Scholasticism as a source for the solution of vexing modern problems. Leo
assumed that there was a doctrine common to Aquinas, Bonaventure, Albertus
Magnus, and Duns Scotus, and that Aquinas was a preeminent spokesman of the
common view. Maurice De Wulf employed the phrase ‘perennial philosophy’ to
designate this common medieval core as well as what of Scholasticism is
relevant to later times. Historians like Mandonnet, Grabmann, and Gilson soon
contested the idea that there was a single medieval doctrine and drew attention
to the profound differences between the great medieval masters. The discussion
of Christian philosophy precipitated by Brehier in 1 generated a variety of
suggestions as to what medieval thinkers and later Christian philosophers have
in common, but this was quite different from the assumption of Aeterni Patris.
The pedagogical directives of this and later encyclicals brought about a
revival of Thomism rather than of Scholasticism, generally in seminaries,
ecclesiastical s, and Catholic universities. Louvain’s Higher Institute of
Philosophy under the direction of Cardinal Mercier and its Revue de Philosophie
Néoscolastique were among the first fruits of the Thomistic revival. The studia
generalia of the Dominican order continued at a new pace, the Saulchoir
publishing the Revue thomiste. In graduate centers in Milan, Madrid, Latin
America, Paris, and Rome, men were trained for the task of teaching in s and
seminaries, and scholarly research began to flourish as well. The Leonine
edition of the writings of Aquinas was soon joined by new critical editions of
Bonaventure, Duns Scotus, and Ockham, as well as Albertus Magnus. Medieval
studies in the broader sense gained from the quest for manuscripts and the
growth of paleography and codicology. Besides the historians mentioned above,
Jacques Maritain 23, a layman and convert to Catholicism, did much both in his
native France and in the United States to promote the study of Aquinas. The
Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies at Toronto, with Gilson regularly and
Maritain frequently in residence, became a source of and
teachers in Canada and the United States, as Louvain and, in Rome, the
Jesuit Gregorianum and the Dominican Angelicum already were. In the 0s s took
doctorates in theology and philosophy at Laval in Quebec and soon the influence
of Charles De Koninck was felt. Jesuits at St. Louis began to publish The Modern Schoolman,
Dominicans in Washington The Thomist, and the
Catholic Philosophical Association The New Scholasticism. The School of
Philosophy at Catholic , long the primary domestic source of professors and
scholars, was complemented by graduate programs at St. Louis, Georgetown, Notre
Dame, Fordham, and Marquette. In the golden period of the Thomistic revival in
the United States, from the 0s until the end of the Vatican Council II in 5,
there were varieties of Thomism based on the variety of views on the relation
between philosophy and science. By the 0s Thomistic philosophy was a prominent
part of the curriculum of all Catholic s and universities. By 0, it had all but
disappeared under the mistaken notion that this was the intent of Vatican II.
This had the effect of releasing Aquinas into the wider philosophical
world.
Aquino -- Aquinismo – “If followers of
William are called Occamists, followers of a Saint should surely call
themselves “Aquinistae”! -- neo-Thomism – as opposed to palaeo-Thomism --, a
philosophical-theological movement in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries manifesting
a revival of interest in Aquinas. It was stimulated by Pope Leo XIII’s
encyclical Aeterni Patris 1879 calling for a renewed emphasis on the teaching
of Thomistic principles to meet the intellectual and social challenges of
modernity. The movement reached its peak in the 0s, though its influence
continues to be seen in organizations such as the Catholic Philosophical Association. Among its
major figures are Joseph Kleutgen, Désiré Mercier, Joseph Maréchal, Pierre
Rousselot, Réginald Garrigou-LaGrange, Martin Grabmann, M.-D. Chenu, Jacques
Maritain, Étienne Gilson, Yves R. Simon, Josef Pieper, Karl Rahner, Cornelio
Fabro, Emerich Coreth, Bernard Lonergan, and W. Norris Clarke. Few, if any, of
these figures have described themselves as NeoThomists; some explicitly
rejected the designation. Neo-Thomists have little in common except their
commitment to Aquinas and his relevance to the contemporary world. Their
interest produced a more historically accurate understanding of Aquinas and his
contribution to medieval thought Grabmann, Gilson, Chenu, including a
previously ignored use of the Platonic metaphysics of participation Fabro. This
richer understanding of Aquinas, as forging a creative synthesis in the midst
of competing traditions, has made arguing for his relevance easier. Those
Neo-Thomists who were suspicious of modernity produced fresh readings of
Aquinas’s texts applied to contemporary problems Pieper, Gilson. Their
influence can be seen in the revival of virtue theory and the work of Alasdair
MacIntyre. Others sought to develop Aquinas’s thought with the aid of later
Thomists Maritain, Simon and incorporated the interpretations of
Counter-Reformation Thomists, such as Cajetan and Jean Poinsot, to produce more
sophisticated, and controversial, accounts of the intelligence, intentionality,
semiotics, and practical knowledge. Those Neo-Thomists willing to engage modern
thought on its own terms interpreted modern philosophy sympathetically using
the principles of Aquinas Maréchal, Lonergan, Clarke, seeking dialogue rather
than confrontation. However, some readings of Aquinas are so thoroughly
integrated into modern philosophy that they can seem assimilated Rahner,
Coreth; their highly individualized metaphysics inspired as much by other
philosophical influences, especially Heidegger, as Aquinas. Some of the labels
currently used among Neo-Thomists suggest a division in the movement over
critical, postKantian methodology. ‘Existential Thomism’ is used for those who
emphasize both the real distinction between essence and existence and the role
of the sensible in the mind’s first grasp of being. ‘Transcendental Thomism’
applies to figures like Maréchal, Rousselot, Rahner, and Coreth who rely upon
the inherent dynamism of the mind toward the real, rooted in Aquinas’s theory
of the active intellect, from which to deduce their metaphysics of being.
Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Grice e Aquino: grammatici speculative, per il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
Grecian: Grice: “Much as in London The
Royal Opera only staged operas in Italian, and call itself, The Italian Royal
Opera, at Rome, they only philosophised in Grecian! That is the elite’s way to
separate from the riff raff.” – Grice. Grice: “Similarly, at Oxford, I came
with a knowledge of Grecian and Roman far superior than English – and we always
looked down on those who came down to Oxford just to do what we insultingly
called “Eng. Lit.”!” --.
Academia:
academia vecchia/academia nuova -- accademia nuova – v. Grice,
“Carneades at Rome, and the beginning of Western philosophy.” New Academy, the
name given the Academy, the school founded by Plato in the Athenian suburs, during
the time it was controlled by Academic Skeptics. Its principal leaders in this
period were Arcesilaus and Carneades; our most accessible source for the New
Academy is Cicero’s “Academica.” A master of logical techniques such as sorites
which he learned from Diodorus, Arcesilaus attempted to revive the dialectic of
Plato, using it to achieve the suspension of belief he learned to value from
Pyrrho. Later, and especially under the leadership of Carneades, the New
Academy developed a special relationship with Stoicism: as the Stoics found new
ways to defend their doctrine of the criterion, Carneades found new ways to
refute it in the Stoics’ own terms. Carneades’ visit to Rome in 155 B.C. with a
Stoic and a Peripatetic marks the beginning of Rome’s interest, especially with
the elite, just to be different and to speak in a tongue that the vulgus would
not understand, in what the Romans called “philosophia hellenistica” – Cicero,
“Since I cannot think of a vernacular Roman term for ‘philosophia.’” An
Englishman had the same problem with logic, which he rendered as ‘witcraft.’ –
and ‘witlove.’ His anti-Stoic arguments were recorded by his successor
Clitomachus d. c.110 B.C., whose work is known to us through summaries in
Cicero. Clitomachus was succeeded by Philo of Larisa c.16079 B.C., who was the
teacher of Antiochus of Ascalon c.130c.67 B.C.. Philo later attempted to
reconcile the Old and the New Academy by softening the Skepticism of the New
and by fostering a Skeptical reading of Plato. Angered by this, Antiochus broke
away in about 87 B.C. to found what he called the Old Academy, which is now
considered to be the beginning of Middle Platonism. Probably about the same
time, Aenesidemus dates unknown revived the strict Skepticism of Pyrrho and
founded the school that is known to us through the work of Sextus Empiricus.
Academic Skepticism differed from Pyrrhonism in its sharp focus on Stoic
positions, and possibly in allowing for a weak assent as opposed to belief,
which they suspended in what is probable; and Pyrrhonians accused Academic
Skeptics of being dogmatic in their rejection of the possibility of knowledge.
The New Academy had a major influence on the development of modern philosophy,
most conspicuously through Hume, who considered that his brand of mitigated
skepticism belonged to this school. Grice: “Western philosophy begins with
Carneades lecturing the rough Romans some philosophy; because Greece is EAST!”
– Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The longitudinal history of philosophy from Carneades’s
sojourn at Rome to my British Academy lecture at London.”
Newcomb’s paradox: a conflict, which Grice
finds fascinating, between two widely accepted principles of rational decision,
arising in the following decision problem, known as Newcomb’s problem. Two
boxes are before you. The first contains either $1,000,000 or nothing. The
second contains $1,000. You may take the first box alone or both boxes. Someone
with uncanny foresight has predicted your choice and fixed the content of the
first box according to his prediction. If he has predicted that you will take
only the first box, he has put $1,000,000 in that box; and if he has predicted
that you will take both boxes, he has left the first box empty. The expected
utility of an option is commonly obtained by multiplying the utility of its
possible outcomes by their probabilities given the option, and then adding the
products. Because the predictor is reliable, the probability that you receive
$1,000,000 given that you take only the first box is high, whereas the
probability that you receive $1,001,000 given that you take both boxes is low.
Accordingly, the expected utility of taking only the first box is greater than
the expected utility of taking both boxes. Therefore the principle of
maximizing expected utility says to take only the first box. However, the
principle of dominance says that if the states determining the outcomes of
options are causally independent of the options, and there is one option that
is better than the others in each state, then you should adopt it. Since your
choice does not causally influence the contents of the first box, and since choosing
both boxes yields $1,000 in addition to the contents of the first box whatever
they are, the principle says to take both boxes. Newcomb’s paradox is named
after its formulator, William Newcomb. Nozick publicized it in “Newcomb’s
Problem and Two Principles of Choice” 9. Many theorists have responded to the
paradox by changing the definition of the expected utility of an option so that
it is sensitive to the causal influence of the option on the states that
determine its outcome, but is insensitive to the evidential bearing of the
option on those states. Refs: H. P. Grice, “Why I love Newcomb.”
Grice, “Oxford’s kindly light” -- Newman
(“Lead Kindly light”) -- English prelate and philosopher of religion. As fellow
at Oriel , Oxford, he was a prominent member of the Anglican Oxford Movement.
He became a Roman Catholic in 1845, took holy orders in 1847, and was made a
cardinal in 1879. His most important philosophical work is the Grammar of
Assent 1870. Here Newman explored the difference between formal reasoning and
the informal or natural movement of the mind in discerning the truth about the
concrete and historical. Concrete reasoning in the mode of natural inference is
implicit and unreflective; it deals not with general principles as such but
with their employment in particular circumstances. Thus a scientist must judge
whether the phenomenon he confronts is a novel significant datum, a
coincidence, or merely an insignificant variation in the data. The acquired
capacity to make judgments of this sort Newman called the illative sense, an
intellectual skill shaped by experience and personal insight and generally
limited for individuals to particular fields of endeavor. The illative sense
makes possible a judgment of certitude about the matter considered, even though
the formal argument that partially outlines the process possesses only
objective probability for the novice. Hence probability is not necessarily
opposed to certitude. In becoming aware of its tacit dimension, Newman spoke of
recognizing a mode of informal inference. He distinguished such reasoning,
which, by virtue of the illative sense, culminates in a judgment of certitude
about the way things are real assent, from formal reasoning conditioned by the
certainty or probability of the premises, which assents to the conclusion thus
conditioned notional assent. In real assent, the proposition functions to
“image” the reality, to make its reality present. In the Development of
Christian Doctrine 1845, Newman analyzed the ways in which some ideas unfold
themselves only through historical development, within a tradition of inquiry.
He sought to delineate the common pattern of such development in politics,
science, philosophy, and religion. Although his focal interest was in how
religious doctrines develop, he emphasizes the general character of such a
pattern of progressive articulation. H. P. Grice, “Oxford’s kindly light.”
Res – realism – neo-relaism, New Realism –
or neo-realism – as opposed to “palaeo-realism” -- an early twentieth-century
revival in England of various forms of realism in reaction to the dominant
idealisms inherited from the nineteenth century. In America this revival took a
cooperative form when six philosophers Ralph Barton Perry, Edwin Holt, William
Pepperell Montague, Walter Pitkin, Edward Spaulding, and Walter Marvin
published “A Program and First Platform of Six Realists” 0, followed two years
later by the cooperative volume The New Realism, in which each authored an
essay. This volume gave rise to the designation ‘New Realists’ for these six
philosophers. Although they clearly disagreed on many particulars, they
concurred on several matters of philosophical style and epistemological
substance. Procedurally they endorsed a cooperative and piecemeal approach to
philosophical problems, and they were constitutionally inclined to a closeness
of analysis that would prepare the way for later philosophical tendencies.
Substantively they agreed on several epistemological stances central to the
refutation of idealism. Among the doctrines in the New Realist platform were
the rejection of the fundamental character of epistemology; the view that the
entities investigated in logic, mathematics, and science are not “mental” in
any ordinary sense; the view that the things known are not the products of the
knowing relation nor in any fundamental sense conditioned by their being known;
and the view that the objects known are immediately and directly present to
consciousness while being independent of that relation. New Realism was a version
of direct realism, which viewed the notions of mediation and representation in
knowledge as opening gambits on the slippery slope to idealism. Their
refutation of idealism focused on pointing out the fallacy of moving from the
truism that every object of knowledge is known to the claim that its being
consists in its being known. That we are obviously at the center of what we
know entails nothing about the nature of what we know. Perry dubbed this fact
“the egocentric predicament,” and supplemented this observation with arguments
to the effect that the objects of knowledge are in fact independent of the
knowing relation. New Realism as a version of direct realism had as its primary
conceptual obstacle “the facts of relativity,” i.e., error, illusion, perceptual
variation, and valuation. Dealing with these phenomena without invoking “mental
intermediaries” proved to be the stumbling block, and New Realism soon gave way
to a second cooperative venture by another group of philosophers that came to be known as
Critical Realism. The term ‘new realism’ is also occasionally used with regard
to those British philosophers principal among them Moore and Russell similarly
involved in refuting idealism. Although individually more significant than the group, theirs was not a cooperative effort,
so the group term came to have primarily an
referent.
newton, -- “Hypotheses non fingo.” Grice:
“His surname is a toponymic: it literally means ‘new-town,’ but it implicates,
“FROM new-town.” – “We never knew what ‘old’ town Sir Isaac is implicating,
possibly Oldton, in Cumbria.” -- English physicist and mathematician, one of
the greatest scientists of all time. Born in Woolsthorpe, Lincolnshire, he
attended Cambridge , receiving the B.A. in 1665; he became a fellow of Trinity
in New Realism Newton, Sir Isaac 610
610 1667 and Lucasian Professor of Mathematics in 1669. He was elected
fellow of the Royal Society in 1671 and served as its president from 1703 until
his death. In 1696 he was appointed warden of the mint. In his later years he
was involved in political and governmental affairs rather than in active
scientific work. A sensitive, secretive person, he was prone to
irascibility most notably in a dispute
with Leibniz over priority of invention of the calculus. His unparalleled
scientific accomplishments overshadow a deep and sustained interest in ancient
chronology, biblical study, theology, and alchemy. In his early twenties
Newton’s genius asserted itself in an astonishing period of mathematical and
experimental creativity. In the years 1664 67, he discovered the binomial
theorem; the “method of fluxions” calculus; the principle of the composition of
light; and fundamentals of his theory of universal gravitation. Newton’s
masterpiece, Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica “The Mathematical
Principles of Natural Philosophy”, appeared in 1687. This work sets forth the
mathematical laws of physics and “the system of the world.” Its exposition is
modeled on Euclidean geometry: propositions are demonstrated mathematically
from definitions and mathematical axioms. The world system consists of material
bodies masses composed of hard particles at rest or in motion and interacting
according to three axioms or laws of motion: 1 Every body continues in its
state of rest or of uniform motion in a straight line unless it is compelled to
change that state by forces impressed upon it. 2 The change of motion is
proportional to the motive force impressed and is made in the direction of the
straight line in which that force is impressed. [Here, the impressed force
equals mass times the rate of change of velocity, i.e., acceleration. Hence the
familiar formula, F % ma.] 3 To every action there is always opposed an equal
reaction; or, the mutual action of two bodies upon each other is always equal
and directed to contrary parts. Newton’s general law of gravitation in modern
restatement is: Every particle of matter attracts every other particle with a
force varying directly as the product of their masses and inversely as the square
of the distance between them. The statement of the laws of motion is preceded
by an equally famous scholium in which Newton enunciates the ultimate
conditions of his universal system: absolute time, space, place, and motion. He
speaks of these as independently existing “quantities” according to which true
measurements of bodies and motions can be made as distinct from relative
“sensible measures” and apparent observations. Newton seems to have thought
that his system of mathematical principles presupposed and is validated by the
absolute framework. The scholium has been the subject of much critical
discussion. The main problem concerns the justification of the absolute
framework. Newton commends adherence to experimental observation and induction
for advancing scientific knowledge, and he rejects speculative hypotheses. But
absolute time and space are not observable. In the scholium Newton did offer a
renowned experiment using a rotating pail of water as evidence for
distinguishing true and apparent motions and proof of absolute motion. It has
been remarked that conflicting strains of a rationalism anticipating Kant and
empiricism anticipating Hume are present in Newton’s conception of science.
Some of these issues are also evident in Newton’s Optics 1704, especially the
fourth edition, 1730, which includes a series of suggestive “Queries” on the
nature of light, gravity, matter, scientific method, and God. The triumphant
reception given to Newton’s Principia in England and on the Continent led to
idealization of the man and his work. Thus Alexander Pope’s famous epitaph:
Nature and Nature’s laws lay hid in night; God said, “Let Newton be!” and all
was light. The term ‘Newtonian’, then, denoted the view of nature as a
universal system of mathematical reason and order divinely created and
administered. The metaphor of a “universal machine” was frequently applied. The
view is central in the eighteenth-century Enlightenment, inspiring a religion
of reason and the scientific study of society and the human mind. More
narrowly, ‘Newtonian’ suggests a reduction of any subject matter to an ontology
of individual particles and the laws and basic terms of mechanics: mass,
length, and time. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Hypotheses non fingo: Newton e la sua
mela,” Luigi Speranza, per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library,
Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
Autrecourt, philosopher, unimaginatively born
in Autrecourt, he was educated at Paris (“but I kept Autrecourt as my surname,
Paris being so common” – “Letter to Matthew Parris” --) and earned bachelor’s
degrees in theology and law and a master’s degree in arts. After a list of
propositions from his writings was condemned in 1346, he was sentenced to burn
his works publicly and recant, which he did in Paris the following year. He was
appointed dean of Metz cathedral in 1350. Nicholas’s ecclesiastical troubles
arose partly from nine letters two of which survive which reduce to absurdity
the view that appearances provide a sufficient basis for certain and evident
knowledge. On the contrary, except for “certitude of the faith,” we can be
certain only of what is equivalent or reducible to the principle of
noncontradiction. He accepts as a consequence of this that we can never validly
infer the existence of one distinct thing from another, including the existence
of substances from qualities, or causes from effects. Indeed, he finds that “in
the whole of his natural philosophy and metaphysics, Aristotle had such
[evident] certainty of scarcely two conclusions, and perhaps not even of one.”
Nicholas devotes another work, the Exigit ordo executionis also known as The
Universal Treatise, to an extended critique of Aristotelianism. It attacks what
seemed to him the blind adherence given by his contemporaries to Aristotle and
Averroes, showing that the opposite of many conclusions alleged to have been
demonstrated by the Philosopher e.g., on
the divisibility of continua, the reality of motion, and the truth of
appearances are just as evident or
apparent as those conclusions themselves. Because so few of his writings are
extant, however, it is difficult to ascertain just what Nicholas’s own views
were. Likewise, the reasons for his condemnation are not well understood,
although recent studies have suggested that his troubles might have been due to
a reaction to certain ideas that he appropriated from English theologians, such
as Adam de Wodeham. Nicholas’s views elicited comment not only from church
authorities, but also from other philosophers, including Buridan, Marsilius of
Inghen, Albert of Saxony, and Nicholas of Oresme. Despite a few surface
similarities, however, there is no evidence that his teachings on certainty or
causality had any influence on modern philosophers, such as Descartes or
Hume.
Intellectus:
The sensus-intellectus distinction, the: Grice: “Occam’s adage presupposes a
bi-partite philosophical psychology for the credibility realm: the ‘sensus,’ or
perceptual level, and the ‘intellectus,’ or the realm of intellect. nihil est
in intellectu quod non prius fuerit in sensu: a principal tenet of empiricism.
A weak interpretation of the principle maintains that all concepts are acquired
from sensory experience; no concepts are innate or a priori. A stronger
interpretation adds that all propositional knowledge is derived from sense
experience. The weak interpretation was held by Aquinas and Locke, who thought
nevertheless that we can know some propositions to be true in virtue of the
relations between the concepts involved. The stronger interpretation was
endorsed by J. S. Mill, who argued that even the truths of mathematics are inductively
based on experience, as Grice tutored R. Wollheim for his PPE at Oxford: “How
did you find that out?” “Multiplication.” “That proves Mill wrong.”
Activum/passivum distinction: used by Grice,
‘nous poietikos’ ‘nous – intellectus activus, intellectus passivus --. Grice
thought ‘active’ was misused there, “unless there is a hint that Aquinas means
that the self-conscious soul is the site of personal identity, which ‘does’
things.” --.
Nihil ex nihilo fit – Grice: “an intuitive
metaphysical principle first enunciated by Parmenides, often held equivalent to
the proposition that nothing arises without a cause. Creation ex nihilo is
God’s production of the world without any natural or material cause, but
involves a supernatural cause, and so it would not violate the principle.
Noce: essential Italian
philosopher. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice e del Noce," per Il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
Nous – Grice’s favourite formation from
nous is ‘noetic’, noetic – the opposite of the favourite Griceian sub-disipline
in philosophy, aesthetics -- from Grecian noetikos, from noetos, ‘perceiving’,
of or relating to apprehension by the intellect. In a strict sense the term
refers to nonsensuous data given to the cognitive faculty, which discloses
their intelligible meaning as distinguished from their sensible apprehension.
We hear a sentence spoken, but it becomes intelligible for us only when the
sounds function as a foundation for noetic apprehension. For Plato, the objects
of such apprehension noetá are the Forms eide with respect to which the
sensible phenomena are only occasions of manifestation: the Forms in themselves
transcend the sensible and have their being in a realm apart. For empiricist
thinkers, e.g., Locke, there is strictly speaking no distinct noetic aspect,
since “ideas” are only faint sense impressions. In a looser sense, however, one
may speak of ideas as independent of reference to particular sense impressions,
i.e. independent of their origin, and then an idea can be taken to signify a
class of objects. Husserl uses the term to describe the intentionality or
dyadic character of consciousness in general, i.e. including both eidetic or categorial
and perceptual knowing. He speaks of the correlation of noesis or intending and
noema or the intended object of awareness. The categorial or eidetic is the
perceptual object as intellectually cognized; it is not a realm apart, but
rather what is disclosed or made present “constituted” Nihil est in intellectu
quod non prius fuerit in sensu noetic 617
617 when the mode of appearance of the perceptual object is intended by
a categorial noesis.
euclidean/non-euclideeian
distinction, the:
– as applied to geometry. H. P. Grice, “Non-Euclidean implicatura of space” –
“Non-Euclidean geometrical implicatura – None-euclidean geometry refers to any
axiomatized version of geometry in which Euclides’s parallel axiom is rejected,
after so many unsuccessful attempts to prove it. As in so many branches of
mathematics, Gauss had thought out much of the matter first, but he kept most
of his ideas to himself. As a result, credit is given to Bolyai and Lobachevsky.
Instead of assuming that just one line passes through a point in a plane
parallel to a non-coincident co-planar line, Bolyai and Loachevsky offer a
geometry in which a line admits more than one parallel, and the sum of the
“angles” between the “sides” of a “triangle” lies below 180°. Then Riemann
conceived of a geometry in which lines always meet so no parallels, and the sum
of the “angles” exceeds 180°. In this connection Riemann distinguishes between
the unboundedness of space as a property of its extent, and the special case of
the infinite measure over which distance might be taken which is dependent upon
the curvature of that space. Pursuing the published insight of Gauss, that the
curvature of a surface could be defined in terms only of properties dependent
solely on the surface itself and later called “intrinsic”, Riemann also defines
the metric on a surface in a very general and intrinsic way, in terms of the
differential arc length. Thereby he clarified the ideas of “distance” that his
non-Euclidean precursors had introduced drawing on trigonometric and hyperbolic
functions; arc length was now understood geodesically as the shortest
“distance” between two “points” on a surface, and was specified independent of
any assumptions of a geometry within which the surface was embedded. Further properties,
such as that pertaining to the “volume” of a three-“dimensional” solid, were
also studied. The two main types of non-Euclidean geometry, and its Euclidean
parent, may be summarized as follows: Reaction to these geometries was slow to
develop, but their impact gradually emerged. As mathematics, their legitimacy
was doubted; but Beltrami produced a model of a Bolyai-type two-dimensional
space inside a planar circle. The importance of this model was to show that the
consistency of this geometry depended upon that of the Euclidean version,
thereby dispelling the fear that it was an inconsistent flash of the
imagination. During the last thirty years of the nineteenth century a variety
of variant geometries were proposed, and the relationships between them were
studied, together with consequences for projective geometry. On the empirical
side, these geometries, and especially Riemann’s approach, affected the
understanding of the relationship between geometry and space; in particular, it
posed the question whether space is curved or not the later being the Euclidean
answer. The geometries thus played a role in the emergence and articulation of
relativity theory, especially the differential geometry and tensorial calculus
within which its mathematical properties could be expressed. Philosophically
the new geometries stressed the hypothetical nature of axiomatizing, in
contrast to the customary view of mathematical theories as true in some usually
unclear sense. This feature led to the name ‘meta-geometry’ for them. It was
intended as an ironical proposal of opponents to be in line with the
hypothetical character of meta-physics (and meta-ethics) in philosophy. They
also helped to encourage conventionalist philosophy of science with Poincaré,
e.g., and put fresh light on the age-old question of the impossibility of a
priori knowledge.
monotonic/non-monotonice
distinction, the: Grice: “It may be argued that we do not need ‘polytonic,’
just a concept that NEGATES monotone – but since at Clifton I learned about
Grecian polytonicity, I like the idea!” -- “On occasion, the semantics of
implicatura is non-monotonic, i. e. a
logic that fails to be monotonic -- i.e., in proof-theoretic terms, fails to
meet the condition that for all statements u1, . . . un, if f,y, if ‘u1, . . .
un Yf’, for any y, ‘u1 , . . . un, y Y f’. Equivalently, let Γ represent a
collection of statements, u1 . . . un, and say that in a monotonic system, such
as system G (after Grice), if ‘Γ Y f’, for any y, ‘Γ, y Y f’ and similarly in
other cases. A non-monotonic system is any system with the following property:
For some Γ, f, and y, ‘ΓNML f’ but ‘Γ, y K!NML f’. This is what Grice calls a
“weak” non-monotonic system G-w-n-m. In contrast, in a “strong” non-monotonic
system – G-s-n-m, we might have, again for some Γ, f, y, where Γ is consistent
and Γ 8 f is consistent: ‘Γ, y YNML > f’. A primary motivation for Grice for
a non-monotonic system or defeasible reasoning, which is so evident in
conversational reasoning, is to produce a representation for default (ceteris
paribus) reasoning or defeasible reasoning. Grice’s interest in defeasible (or
ceteris paribus) reasoning – for conversational implicatura -- readily spreads
to epistemology, logic, and meta-ethics. The exigencies of this or that
practical affair requires leaping to conclusions, going beyond available
evidence, making assumptions. In doing so, Grice often errs and must leap back
from his conclusion, undo his assumption, revise his belief. In Grice’s
standard example, “Tweety is a bird and all birds fly, except penguins and
ostriches. Does Tweety fly?” If pressed, Grice needs to form a belief about
this matter. Upon discovering that Tweety is a penguin, Grice may have to re-tract
his conclusion. Any representation of defeasible (or ceteris paribus) reasoning
must capture the non-monotonicity of this reasoning. A non-monotonic system
G-s-n-m is an attempt to do this by adding this or that rule of inference that
does not preserve monotonicity. Although a practical affair may require Grice
to reason “defeasibly” – an adverb Grice borrowed from Hart -- the best way to
achieve non-monotonicity may not be to add this or that non-monotonic rule of
inference to System G. What one gives up in such system may well not be worth
the cost: loss of the deduction theorem and of a coherent notion of
consistency. Therefore, Grice’s challenge for a non-monotonic system and for defeasible
reasoning, generally is to develop a rigorous way to re-present the structure
of non-monotonic reasoning without losing or abandoning this or that historically
hard-won propertiy of a monotonic system. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Monotonicity,
and Polytonicity.” G. P. Baker, “Meaning and defeasibility,” in festschrift for
H. L. A. Hart; R. Hall, “Excluders;” H. P. Grice, “Ceteris paribus and
defeasibility.”
nonviolence: H. P. Grice
joined the Royal Navy in 1941 – and served till 1945, earning the degree of captain.
He was involved in the North-Atlantic theatre and later at the Admiralty.
Non-violence is the renunciation of violence in personal, social, or
international affairs. It often includes a commitment called active nonviolence
or nonviolent direct action actively to oppose violence and usually evil or
injustice as well by nonviolent means. Nonviolence may renounce physical
violence alone or both physical and psychological violence. It may represent a
purely personal commitment or be intended to be normative for others as well.
When unconditional absolute 619 norm normative relativism 620
nonviolence it renounces violence in all
actual and hypothetical circumstances. When conditional conditional nonviolence it concedes the justifiability of violence in
hypothetical circumstances but denies it in practice. Held on moral grounds
principled nonviolence, the commitment belongs to an ethics of conduct or an
ethics of virtue. If the former, it will likely be expressed as a moral rule or
principle e.g., One ought always to act nonviolently to guide action. If the
latter, it will urge cultivating the traits and dispositions of a nonviolent
character which presumably then will be expressed in nonviolent action. As a
principle, nonviolence may be considered either basic or derivative. Either
way, its justification will be either utilitarian or deontological. Held on
non-moral grounds pragmatic nonviolence, nonviolence is a means to specific
social, political, economic, or other ends, themselves held on non-moral
grounds. Its justification lies in its effectiveness for these limited purposes
rather than as a way of life or a guide to conduct in general. An alternative
source of power, it may then be used in the service of evil as well as good.
Nonviolent social action, whether of a principled or pragmatic sort, may
include noncooperation, mass demonstrations, marches, strikes, boycotts, and
civil disobedience techniques explored
extensively in the writings of Gene Sharp. Undertaken in defense of an entire
nation or state, nonviolence provides an alternative to war. It seeks to deny
an invading or occupying force the capacity to attain its objectives by
withholding the cooperation of the populace needed for effective rule and by
nonviolent direct action, including civil disobedience. It may also be used
against oppressive domestic rule or on behalf of social justice. Gandhi’s
campaign against British rule in India, Scandinavian resistance to Nazi
occupation during World War II, and Martin Luther King, Jr.’s actions on behalf
of civil rights in the United States are illustrative. Nonviolence has origins
in Far Eastern thought, particularly Taoism and Jainism. It has strands in the
Jewish Talmud, and many find it implied by the New Testament’s Sermon on the
Mount. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “My Royal Navy days: memoirs of a captain.”
normal/non-normal
distinction, the: Grice:
I shall refer to the ‘normal form’ as a formula equivalent to a given formula, but having special properties. The
main varieties follow. A Conjunctive normal form. If D1 . . . Dn are
disjunctions of sentential variables or their negations, such as p 7 -q 7 r, a
formula F is in what I shall call
“conjunctive normal form” provided F % D1 & D2 & . . & Dn. The
following are in conjunctive normal form: -p 7 q; p 7 q 7 r & -p 7 -q 7 -r
& -q 7 r. Every formula of Grice’s predicate calculus – System G, Gricese
-- has an equivalent “conjunctive normal
form.” This fact can be used to prove the completeness of sentential logic.
Disjunctive normal form. If C1 . . . Cn are conjunctions of sentential
variables or their negations, such as p & -q & -r, a formula F is in what I shall call “disjunctive
normal form” provided F % C1 7 C27 . . Cn. The following are thus in
disjunctive normal form: p & -q 7 -p & q; p & q & -r 7 -p &
-q & -r. Every formula of sentential logic has an equivalent disjunctive
normal form. Prenex normal form. A formula of Grice’s predicate calculus –
system G, Gricese -- is in what Grice calls “prenex normal form” if 1 every
quantifier occurs at the beginning of the formula, 2 the scope of the
quantifiers extends to the end of the formula, and 3 what follows the
quantifiers contains at least one occurrence of every variable that appears in
the set of quantifiers. Thus, DxDyFx / Gy and xDyzFxy 7 Gyz / Dxyz are in what
I shall call “prenex normal form.” The formula may contain free variables;
thus, Dxy Fxyz / Gwyx is also in prenex normal form. The following, however,
are not in prenex normal form: xDy Fx / Gx; xy Fxy / Gxy. Every formula of
Grice’s predicate calculus – System G, Gricese -- has an equivalent formula in
prenex normal form. A formula F in predicate logic is in what Grice, as a
tribute to Skolem, calls the “Skolem normal form” provided 1 F is in prenex
normal form, 2 every existential quantifier precedes any universal quantifier,
3 F contains at least one existential quantifier, and 4 F contains no free
variables. Thus, DxDy zFxy / Gyz and DxDyDzwFxy 7 Fyz 7 Fzw are in Skolem
normal form; however, Dx y Fxyz and x y Fxy 7 Gyx are not. Any formula has an equivalent
Skolem normal form. “This has implications for the lack of completeness of my
predicate calculus – but do I worry?”. Refs.: Grice, “Normal and abnormal
forms: a logical introduction.”
notum: Grice was slightly obsessed with “know,” Latin
‘notum – nosco’ -- nosco , nōvi, nōtum, 3 (old form,
GNOSCO, GNOVI, GNOTVM, acc. to Prisc. p. 569 P.; I.inf. pass. GNOSCIER, S. C.
de Bacch.; cf. GNOTV, cognitu, Paul. ex Fest. p. 96 Müll.: GNOT (contr. for gnovit)
οἶδεν, ἐπιγινώσκει; GNOTV, γνῶσιν, διάγνωσιν, Gloss. Labb.—Contr. forms in
class. Lat. are nosti, noram, norim. nosse; nomus for novimus: nomus ambo
Ulixem, Enn. ap. Diom. p. 382 P., or Trag. v. 199 Vahl.), v. a. for gnosco,
from the root gno; Gr. γιγνώσκω, to begin to know, to get a knowledge of,
become acquainted with, come to know a thing (syn.: scio, calleo). I. Lit. 1.
(α). Tempp. praes.: “cum igitur, nosce te, dicit, hoc dicit, nosce animum
tuum,” Cic. Tusc. 1, 22, 52: Me. Sauream non novi. Li. At nosce sane, Plaut.
As. 2, 4, 58; cf.: Ch. Nosce signum. Ni. Novi, id. Bacch. 4, 6, 19; id. Poen.
4, 2, 71: “(Juppiter) nos per gentes alium alia disparat, Hominum qui facta,
mores, pietatem et fidem noscamus,” id. Rud. prol. 12; id. Stich. 1, 1, 4: “id
esse verum, cuivis facile est noscere,” Ter. Ad. 5, 4, 8: “ut noscere possis
quidque,” Lucr. 1, 190; 2, 832; 3, 124; 418; 588; Cic. Rep. 1, 41, 64: deus
ille, quem mente noscimus, id. N. D. 1, 14, 37.—Pass.: “EAM (tabulam) FIGIER
IOVBEATIS, VBEI FACILVMED GNOSCIER POTISIT, S. C. de Bacch.: forma in tenebris
nosci non quita est, Ter Hec. 4, 1, 57 sq.: omnes philosophiae partes tum
facile noscuntur, cum, etc.,” Cic. N. D. 1, 4, 9: philosophiae praecepta
noscenda, id. Fragm. ap. Lact. 3, 14: “nullique videnda, Voce tamen noscar,”
Ov. M. 14, 153: “nec noscitur ulli,” by any one, id. Tr. 1, 5, 29: “noscere
provinciam, nosci exercitui,” by the army, Tac. Agr. 5.— (β). Temppperf., to
have become acquainted with, to have learned, to know: “si me novisti minus,” Plaut.
Aul. 4, 10, 47: “Cylindrus ego sum, non nosti nomen meum?” id. Men. 2, 2, 20:
“novi rem omnem,” Ter. And. 4, 4, 50: “qui non leges, non instituta ... non
jura noritis,” Cic. Pis. 13, 30: “plerique neque in rebus humanis quidquam
bonum norunt, nisi, etc.,” id. Lael. 21, 79: “quam (virtutem) tu ne de facie
quidem nosti,” id. Pis. 32, 81; id. Fin. 2, 22, 71: “si ego hos bene novi,” if
I know them well, id. Rosc. Am. 20 fin.: si Caesarem bene novi, Balb. ap. Cic.
Att. 9, 7, B, 2: “Lepidum pulchre noram,” Cic. Fam. 10, 23, 1: “si tuos digitos
novi,” id. Att. 5, 21, 13: “res gestas de libris novisse,” to have learned from
books, Lact. 5, 19, 15: “nosse Graece, etc. (late Lat. for scire),” Aug. Serm.
45, 5; 167, 40 al.: “ut ibi esses, ubi nec Pelopidarum—nosti cetera,” Cic. Fam.
7, 28, 2; Plin. Ep. 3, 9, 11.— 2. To examine, consider: “ad res suas
noscendas,” Liv. 10, 20: “imaginem,” Plaut. Ps. 4, 2, 29.—So esp., to take
cognizance of as a judge: “quae olim a praetoribus noscebantur,” Tac. A. 12,
60.— II. Transf., in the tempp. praes. A. In gen., to know, recognize (rare;
perh. not in Cic.): hau nosco tuom, I know your (character, etc.), i. e. I know
you no longer, Plaut. Trin. 2, 4, 44: “nosce imaginem,” id. Ps. 4, 2, 29; id.
Bacch. 4, 6, 19: “potesne ex his ut proprium quid noscere?” Hor. S. 2, 7, 89;
Tac. H. 1, 90.— B. In partic., to acknowledge, allow, admit of a reason or an
excuse (in Cic.): “numquam amatoris meretricem oportet causam noscere, Quin,
etc.,” Plaut. Truc. 2, 1, 18: “illam partem excusationis ... nec nosco, nec
probo,” Cic. Fam. 4, 4, 1; cf.: “quod te excusas: ego vero et tuas causas
nosco, et, etc.,” id. Att. 11, 7, 4: “atque vereor, ne istam causam nemo
noscat,” id. Leg. 1, 4, 11.— III. Transf. in tempp. perf. A. To be acquainted
with, i. e. to practise, possess: “alia vitia non nosse,” Sen. Q. N. 4 praef. §
9.— B. In mal. part., to know (in paronomasia), Plaut. Most. 4, 2, 13; id.
Pers. 1, 3, 51.— IV. (Eccl. Lat.) Of religious knowledge: “non noverant
Dominum,” Vulg. Judic. 2, 12; ib. 2 Thess. 1, 8: “Jesum novi, Paulum scio,” I
acknowledge, ib. Act. 19, 15.—Hence, nōtus , a, um, P. a., known. A. Lit.:
“nisi rem tam notam esse omnibus et tam manifestam videres,” Cic. Verr. 2, 3,
58, 134: “ejusmodi res ita notas, ita testatas, ita manifestas proferam,” id.
ib. 2, 2, 34, § “85: fingi haec putatis, quae patent, quae nota sunt omnibus,
quae tenentur?” id. Mil. 28, 76: “noti atque insignes latrones,” id. Phil. 11,
5, 10: “habere omnes philosophiae notos et tractatos locos,” id. Or. 33, 118:
“facere aliquid alicui notum,” id. Fam. 5, 12, 7: “tua nobilitas hominibus
litteratis est notior, populo obscurior,” id. Mur. 7, 16: “nullus fuit civis
Romanus paulo notior, quin, etc.,” Caes. B. C. 2, 19: “vita P. Sullae vobis
populoque Romano notissima,” Cic. Sull. 26, 72: “nulli nota domus sua,” Juv. 1,
7.— (β). With gen. (poet.): “notus in fratres animi paterni,” Hor. C. 2, 2, 6:
noti operum Telchines. Stat. Th. 2, 274: “notusque fugarum, Vertit terga,” Sil.
17, 148.— (γ). With subj.-clause: “notum est, cur, etc.,” Juv. 2, 58.— (δ).
With inf. (poet.): “Delius, Trojanos notus semper minuisse labores,” Sil. 12,
331.— 2. In partic. a. Subst.: nōti , acquaintances, friends: “de dignitate M.
Caelius notis ac majoribus natu ... respondet,” Cic. Cael. 2, 3: “hi suos notos
hospitesque quaerebant,” Caes. B. C. 1, 74, 5; Hor. S. 1, 1, 85; Verg. Cir.
259.— b. In a bad sense, notorious: “notissimi latronum duces,” Cic. Fam. 10,
14, 1: “integrae Temptator Orion Dianae,” Hor. C. 3, 4, 70; Ov. M. 1, 198:
“Clodia, mulier non solum nobilis sed etiam nota,” Cic. Cael. 13, 31; cf. Cic.
Verr. 1, 6, 15: “moechorum notissimus,” Juv. 6, 42.— B. Transf., act., knowing,
that knows: novi, notis praedicas, to those that know, Plaut. Ps. 4, 2, 39.Chisholm:
r. m. influential philosopher whose publications
spanned the field, including ethics and the history of philosophy. He is mainly
known as an epistemologist, metaphysician, and philosopher of mind. In early
opposition to powerful forms of reductionism, such as phenomenalism,
extensionalism, and physicalism, Chisholm developed an original philosophy of
his own. Educated at Brown and Harvard Ph.D., 2, he spent nearly his entire
career at Brown. He is known chiefly for the following contributions. a
Together with his teacher and later his colleague at Brown, C. J. Ducasse, he
developed and long defended an adverbial account of sensory experience, set
against the sense-datum act-object account then dominant. b Based on deeply
probing analysis of the free will problematic, he defended a libertarian position,
again in opposition to the compatibilism long orthodox in analytic circles. His
libertarianism had, moreover, an unusual account of agency, based on
distinguishing transeunt event causation from immanent agent causation. c In
opposition to the celebrated linguistic turn of linguistic philosophy, he
defended the primacy of intentionality, a defense made famous not only through
important papers, but also through his extensive and eventually published
correspondence with Wilfrid Sellars. d Quick to recognize the importance and
distinctiveness of the de se, he welcomed it as a basis for much de re thought.
e His realist ontology is developed through an intentional concept of
“entailment,” used to define key concepts of his system, and to provide criteria
of identity for occupants of fundamental categories. f In epistemology, he
famously defended forms of foundationalism and internalism, and offered a
delicately argued dissolution of the ancient problem of the criterion. The
principles of Chisholm’s epistemology and metaphysics are not laid down
antecedently as hard-and-fast axioms. Lacking any inviolable antecedent
privilege, they must pass muster in the light of their consequences and by
comparison with whatever else we may find plausible. In this regard he sharply
contrasts with such epistemologists as Popper, with the skepticism of
justification attendant on his deductivism, and Quine, whose stranded
naturalism drives so much of his radical epistemology and metaphysics. By
contrast, Chisholm has no antecedently set epistemic or metaphysical
principles. His philosophical views develop rather dialectically, with
sensitivity to whatever considerations, examples, or counterexamples reflection
may reveal as relevant. This makes for a demanding complexity of elaboration,
relieved, however, by a powerful drive for ontological and conceptual
economy. notum per se Latin, ‘known
through itself’, self-evident. This term corresponds roughly to the term
‘analytic’. In Thomistic theology, there are two ways for a thing to be
self-evident, secundum se in itself and quoad nos to us. The proposition that
God exists is self-evident in itself, because God’s existence is identical with
his essence; but it is not self-evident to us humans, because humans are not
directly acquainted with God’s essence.Aquinas’s Summa theologiae I, q.2,a.1,c.
For Grice, by uttering “Smith knows that p,” the emisor explicitly conveys, via
semantic truth-conditional entailment, that (1) p; (2) Smith believes that p;
(3) if (1), (2); and conversationally implicates, in a defeasible pragmatic
way, explainable by his adherence to the principle of conversational
co-operation, that Smith is guaranteeing that p.”Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The
monosemy of ‘know’,” H. P. Grice, “The implicatura of ‘know;’” H. P. Grice, “’I
know’ and ‘I guarantee’;” H. P. Grice, “Austin’s performatory fallacy on ‘know’
and ‘guarantee.’”
conventional/non-conventional distinction, the: “If I were to rename all my taxonomies, I
would say I have always been unconventional, and that it was not convention I’m
interested, but unconventionality --. Grice: “Philosophers and the
unconventional.” “Implicature and the unconventional philosopher.” -- “If I
have to chose, I chose non-conventional, but I don’t have to, so I shall use
‘unconventional.’” -- Unfortunately, Grice never came up with a word or
sobriquet for the non-conventional, and kept using the ‘non-conventional.’
Similarly, he never came up with a positive way to refer to the non-natural,
and non-natural it remained. Luckily, we can take it as a joke. Convention
figures TWICE in Grice’s scheme. For his reductive analysis of communication,
he surely can avoid convention by relying on a self-referring anti-sneaky
clause. But when it comes to the ‘taxonomy’ of the ‘shades’ of implication, he
wants the emissor to implicate that p WITHOUT relying on a convention. If the
emissor RELIES on a convention, there are problems for his analysis. Why? First,
at the explicit level, it can be assumed that conventions will feature (Smith’s
dog is ‘by convention’ called ‘Fido”). At the level of the implied, there are
two ways where convention matters in a wrong way. “My neighbour’s
three-year-old is an adult” FLOUTS a convention – or meaning postulate. And it
corresponds to the entailment. But finally, there is a third realm of the
conventional. For particles like “therefore,” or ‘but.’ “But” Grice does not
care much about, but ‘therefore’ he does. He wants to say that ‘therefore’ is
mainly emphatic.The emissor implies a passage from premise to conclusion. And
that implication relies on a convention YET it is not part of the entailment.
So basically, it is an otiose addition. Why would rational conversationalists
rely on them? The rationale for this is that Grice wants to provide a GENERAL
theory of communication that will defeat Austin’s convention-tied ritualistic
view of language. So Grice needs his crucial philosophical refutations NOT to
rely on convention. What relies on convention cannot be cancellable. What
doesn’t can. I an item relies on convention it has not really redeemed from
that part of the communicative act that can not be explained rationally by
argument. There is no way to calculate a conventional item. It is just a given.
And Grice is interested in providing a rationale. His whole campaign relates to
this idea that Austin has rushed, having detected a nuance in a linguistic
phenomenon, to explain it away, without having explored in detail what kind of
nuance it is. For Grice it is NOT a conventional nuance – it’s a sous-entendu
of conversation (as Mill has it), an unnecessary implication (as Russell has
it). Why did Grice chose ‘convention’? The influence of Lewis seems minor,
because he touches on the topic in “Causal Theory,” before Lewis. The word
‘convention’ does NOT occur in “Causal Theory,” though. But there are phrasings
to that effect. Notably, let us consider his commentary in the reprint, when he
omits the excursus. He says that he presents FOUR cases: a particularized
conversational (‘beautiful handwriting’), a generalised conversational (“in the
kitchen or in the bedroom”), a ‘conventional implicaturum’ (“She was poor but
she was honest”) and a presupposition (“You have not ceased to eat iron”). So
the obvious target for exploration is the third, where Grice has the rubric
‘convention,’ as per ‘conventional.’ So his expansion on the ‘but’ example
(what Frege has as ‘colouring’ of “aber”) is interesting to revise. “plied is that Smith
has been bcating his wifc. (2) " She was poor but she was honcst ",
whele what is implied is (vcry roughly) that there is some contrast between
poverty and honesty, or between her poverty and her honesty. The first cxample
is a stock case of what is sometimes called " prcsupposition " and it
is often held that here 1he truth of what is irnplicd is a necessary condition
of the original statement's beirrg cither true or false. This might be
disputed, but it is at lcast arguable that it is so, and its being arguable
might be enough to distinguish-this type of case from others. I shall however
for convenience assume that the common view mentioned is correct. This
consideration clearly distinguishes (1) from (2); even if the implied
proposition were false, i.e. if there were no reason in the world to contrast
poverty with honesty either in general or in her case, the original statement
could still be false; it would be false if for example she were rich and
dishonest. One might perhaps be less comfortable about assenting to its truth
if the implied contrast did not in fact obtain; but the possibility of falsity
is enough for the immediate purpose. My next experiment on these examples is to
ask what it is in each case which could properly be said to be the vehicle of implication
(to do the implying). There are at least four candidates, not necessarily
mutually exclusive. Supposing someone to have uttered one or other of my sample
sentences, we may ask whether the vehicle of implication would be (a) what the
speaker said (or asserted), or (b) the speaker (" did he imply that . . .
.':) or (c) the words the speaker used, or (d) his saying that (or again his
saying that in that way); or possibly some plurality of these items. As regards
(a) I think (1) and (2) differ; I think it would be correct to say in the case
of (l) that what he speaker said (or asserted) implied that Smith had been
beating this wife, and incorrect to say in the case of (2) that what te said
(or asserted) implied that there was a contrast between e.g., honesty and
poverty. A test on which I would rely is the following : if accepting that the
implication holds involves one in r27 128 H. P. GRICE accepting an
hypothetical' if p then q ' where 'p ' represents the original statement and '
q' represents what is implied, then what the speaker said (or asserted) is a
vehicle of implication, otherwise not. To apply this rule to the given
examples, if I accepted the implication alleged to hold in the case of (1), I
should feel compelled to accept the hypothetical " If Smith has left off
beating his wife, then he has been beating her "; whereas if I accepted
the alleged implication in the case of (2), I should not feel compelled to
accept the hypothetical " If she was poor but honest, then there is some
contrast between poverty and honesty, or between her poverty and her
honesty." The other candidates can be dealt with more cursorily; I should
be inclined to say with regard to both (l) and (2) that the speaker could be
said to have implied whatever it is that is irnplied; that in the case of (2)
it seems fairly clear that the speaker's words could be said to imply a
contrast, whereas it is much less clear whether in the case of (1) the
speaker's words could be said to imply that Smith had been beating his wife;
and that in neither case would it be evidently appropriate to speak of his
saying that, or of his saying that in that way, as implying what is implied.
The third idea with which I wish to assail my two examples is really a twin
idea, that of the detachability or cancellability of the implication. (These
terms will be explained.) Consider example (1): one cannot fi.nd a form of
words which could be used to state or assert just what the sentence "
Smith has left off beating his wife " might be used to assert such that
when it is used the implication that Smith has been beating his wife is just
absent. Any way of asserting what is asserted in (1) involves the irnplication
in question. I shall express this fact by saying that in the case of (l) the
implication is not detqchable from what is asserted (or simpliciter, is not
detachable). Furthermore, one cannot take a form of words for which both what
is asserted and what is implied is the same as for (l), and then add a further
clause withholding commitment from what would otherwise be implied, with the
idea of annulling the implication without annulling the assertion. One cannot
intelligibly say " Smith has left off beating his wife but I do not mean
to imply that he has been beating her." I shall express this fact by saying
that in the case of (1) the implication is not cancellable (without THE CAUSAL
THEORY OF PERCEPTION r29 cancelling the assertion). If we turn to (2) we find,
I think, that there is quite a strong case for saying that here the implication
ls detachable. Thcrc sccms quitc a good case for maintaining that if, instead
of sayirrg " She is poor but shc is honcst " I were to say " She
is poor and slre is honcst", I would assert just what I would havc
asscrtcct ii I had used thc original senterrce; but there would now be no
irnplication of a contrast between e.g', povery and honesty. But the question
whether, in tl-re case of (2), thc inrplication is cancellable, is slightly
more cornplex. Thcrc is a sonse in which we may say that it is non-cancellable;
if sorncone were to say " She is poor but she is honest, though of course
I do not mean to imply that there is any contrast between poverty and honesty
", this would seem a puzzling and eccentric thing to have said; but though
we should wish to quarrel with the speaker, I do not think we should go so far
as to say that his utterance was unintelligible; we should suppose that he had
adopted a most peculiar way of conveying the the news that she was poor and
honesl. The fourth and last test that I wish to impose on my exarnples is to
ask whether we would be inclined to regard the fact that the appropriate
implication is present as being a matter of the meaning of some particular word
or phrase occurring in the sentences in question. I am aware that this may not
be always a very clear or easy question to answer; nevertheless Iwill risk the
assertion that we would be fairly happy to say that, as regards (2), the
factthat the implication obtains is a matter of the meaning of the word ' but
'; whereas so far as (l) is concerned we should have at least some inclination
to say that the presence of the implication was a matter of the meaning of some
of the words in the sentence, but we should be in some difficulty when it came
to specifying precisely which this word, or words are, of which this is true.”
Since the actual wording ‘convention’ does not occur it may do to revise how he
words ‘convention’ in Essay 2 of WoW. So here is the way he words it in Essay
II.“In some cases the CONVENTIONAL meaning of the WORDS used will DETERMINE
what is impliccated, besides helping to determine what is said.” Where
‘determine’ is the key word. It’s not “REASON,” conversational reason that
determines it. “If I say (smugly), ‘He is an Englishman; he is, therefore,
brave,’ I have certainly COMMITTED myself, by virtue of the meaning of my
words, to its being the case that his being brave is a consequence of (follows
from) his being an Englishman. But, while I have said that [or explicitly
conveyed THAT] he is an Englishman, and [I also have] said that [or explicitly
conveyed that] he is brave, I do not want to say [if I may play with what
people conventionally understand by ‘convention’] that I have said [or
explicitly conveyed] (in the favoured sense) that [or explicitly conveyed that]
it follows from his being an Englishman that he is brave, though I have
certainly INDICATED, and so implicated, that this is so.” The rationale as to
why the label is ‘convention’ comes next. “I do not want to say that my
utterance of this sentence would be, strictly speaking, FALSE should the
consequence in question fail to hold. So some implicaturums are conventional,
unlike the one with which I introduce this discussion of implicaturum.”Grice’s
observation or suggestion then or advise then, in terms of nomenclature. His
utterance WOULD be FALSE if the MEANING of ‘therefore’ were carried as an
ENTAILMENT (rather than emphatic truth-value irrelevant rhetorical emphasis).
He expands on this in The John Lecture, where Jill is challenged. “What do you
mean, “Jack is an Englishman; he is, therefore, brave”?” What is being
challenged is the validity of the consequence. ‘Therefore’ is vague enough NOT
to specify what type of consequence is meant. So, should someone challenge the
consequence, Jill would still be regarded by Grice as having uttered a TRUE
utterance. The metabolism here is complex since it involves assignment of
‘meaning’ to this or that expression (in this case ‘therefore’). In Essay VI he
is perhaps more systematic.The wider programme just mentioned arises out of a
distinction which, for purposes which I need not here specify, I wish to make
within the total signification of a remark: a distinction between what the
speaker has said (in a certain favoured, and maybe in some degree artificial,
sense of 'said'), and what he has 'implicated' (e.g. implied, indicated,
suggested, etc.), taking into account the fact that what he has implicated may
be either conventionally implicated (implicated by virtue of the meaning of
some word or phrase which he has used) or non-conventionally implicated (in
which case the specification of the implicaturum falls [TOTALLY] outside [AND
INDEPENDENTLY, i. e. as NOT DETERMINED BY] the specification of the
conventional meaning of the words used [Think ‘beautiful handwriting,’ think
‘In the kitchen or in the bedroom’). He is clearest in Essay 6 – where he adds
‘=p’ in the symbolization.UTTERER'S MEANING, SENTENCE-MEANING, AND WORD-MEANINGMy
present aim is to throw light on the connection between (a) a notion of
‘meaning’ which I want to regard as basic, viz. that notion which is involved
in saying of someone that ‘by’ (when) doing SUCH-AND-SUCH he means THAT
SO-AND-SO (in what I have called a non-natural use of 'means'), and (b) the
notions of meaning involved in saying First, that a given sentence means
'so-and-so' Second, that a given word or phrase means 'so-and-so'. What I have
to say on these topics should be looked upon as an attempt to provide a sketch
of what might, I hope, prove to be a viable theory, rather than as an attempt
to provide any part of a finally acceptable theory. The account which I shall
otTer of the (for me) basic notion of meaning is one which I shall not seek now to defend.I should like its
approximate correctness to be assumed, so that attention may be focused on its
utility, if correct, in the explication of other and (I hope) derivative
notions of meaning. This enterprise forms part of a wider programme which I
shall in a moment delineate, though its later stages lie beyond the limits
which I have set for this paper. The wider programme just mentioned arises out
of a distinction which, for purposes which I need not here specify, I wish to
make within the total signification of a remark: a distinction between what the
speaker has said (in a certain favoured, and maybe in some degree artificial,
sense of 'said'), and what he has 'implicated' (e.g. implied, indicated,
suggested, etc.), taking into account the fact that what he has implicated may
be either conventionally implicated (implicated by virtue of the meaning of
some word or phrase which he has used) or non-conventionally implicated (in
which case the specification of the implicaturum falls [TOTALLY] outside [AND
INDEPENDENTLY, i. e. as NOT DETERMINED BY] the specification of the
conventional meaning of the words used [Think ‘beautiful handwriting,’ think
‘In the kitchen or in the bedroom’). The programme is directed towards an
explication of the favoured SENSE of 'say' and a clarification of its relation
to the notion of conventional meaning. The stages of the programme are as
folIows: First, To distinguish between locutions of the form 'U (utterer) meant
that .. .' (locutions which specify what rnight be called 'occasion-meaning')
and locutions of the From Foundalions oJ Language. 4 (1968), pp. 1-18.
Reprinted by permission of the author and the editor of Foundations oJ
Language. I I hope that material in this paper, revised and re·arranged, will
form part of a book to be published by the Harvard University Press. form 'X (utterance-type) means H ••• "'.
In locutions of the first type, meaning is specified without the use of
quotation-marks, whereas in locutions of the second type the meaning of a sentence,
word or phrase is specified with the aid of quotation marks. This difference is
semantically important. Second, To attempt to provide a definiens for
statements of occasion-meaning; more precisely, to provide a definiens for 'By
(when) uttering x, U meant that *p'. Some explanatory comments are needed here.
First, I use the term 'utter' (together with 'utterance') in an artificially
wide sense, to cover any case of doing x or producing x by the performance of
which U meant that so-and-so. The performance in question need not be a
linguistic or even a conventionalized performance. A specificatory replacement
of the dummy 'x' will in some cases be a characterization of a deed, in others
a characterization of a product (e.g. asound). (b) '*' is a dummy mood-indicator,
distinct from specific mood-indicators like 'I-' (indicative or assertive) or
'!' (imperative). More precisely, one may think of the schema 'Jones meant that
*p' as yielding a full English sentence after two transformation al steps: (i)
replace '*' by a specific mood-indicator and replace 'p' by an indicative
sentence. One might thus get to 'Jones meant that I- Smith will go home' or to
'Jones meant that! Smith will go horne'. (ii) replace the sequence following
the word 'that' by an appropriate clause in indirect speech (in accordance with
rules specified in a linguistic theory). One might thus get to 'Jones meant
that Srnith will go horne' 'Jones meant that Srnith is to go horne'. Third, To
attempt to elucidate the notion of the conventional meaning of an
utterance-type; more precisely, to explicate sentences which make claims of the
form 'X (utterance-type) means "*''', or, in case X is a non-scntcntial
utterancctype, claims of the form 'X means H ••• "', where the location is
completed by a nonsentential expression. Again, some explanatory comments are
required. First, It will be convenient to recognize that what I shall call
statements of timeless meaning (statements of the type 'X means " ...
"', in which the ~pecification of meaning involves quotation-marks) may be
subdivided into (i) statements of timeless 'idiolect-meaning', e.g. 'For U (in
U's idiolect) X means " ... '" and (ü) statements of timeless
'Ianguage meaning', e.g. 'In L (language) X means " ... "'. It will
be convenient to handle these separately, and in the order just given. (b) The
truth of a statement to the effect that X means ' .. .' is of course not
incompatible with the truth of a further statement to the effect that X me ans
'--", when the two lacunae are quite differently completed. An
utterance-type rriay have more than one conventional meaning, and any definiens
which we offer must allow fOT this fact. 'X means " ... '" should be
understood as 'One of the meanings of X is " ... " '. (IV) In view of
the possibility of multiplicity in the timeless meaning of an utterance-type,
we shall need to notice, and to provide an explication of, what I shall call
the applied timeless meaning of an utterance-type. That is to say, we need a
definiens for the schema 'X (utterance-type) meant here " ... "', a
schema the specifications of which announce the correct reading of X for a
given occasion of utterance. Comments. (a) We must be careful to distinguish
the applied timeless meaning of X (type) with respecf to a particular token x (belonging
to X) from the occasionmeaning of U's utterance of x. The following are not
equivalent: (i) 'When U uttered it, the sentence "Palmer gave Nickiaus
quite a beating" meant "Palmer vanquished Nickiaus with some
ease" [rather than, say, "Palmer administered vigorous corporal
punishment to NickIaus."]' (ii) 'When U uttered the sentence "Palmer
gave NickIaus quite a beating" U meant that Palmer vanquished NickIaus
with some ease.' U might have been speaking ironically, in which case he would
very likely have meant that NickIaus vanquished Palmer with some ease. In that
case (ii) would c1early be false; but nevertheless (i) would still have been
true. Second, There is some temptation to take the view that the conjunction of
One, 'By uttering X, U meant that *p' and (Two, 'When uttered by U, X meant
"*p'" provides a definiens for 'In uttering X, U said [OR EXPLICITLY
CONVEYED] that *p'. Indeed, ifwe give consideration only to utterance-types for
which there are available adequate statements of time1ess meaning taking the
exemplary form 'X meant "*p'" (or, in the case of applied time1ess
meaning, the form 'X meant here "*p" '), it may even be possible to
uphold the thesis that such a coincidence of occasion-meaning and applied
time1ess meaning is a necessary and sufficient condition for saying that *p.
But a litde refiection should convince us of the need to recognize the
existence of statements of timeless meaning which instantiate forms other than
the cited exemplary form. There are, I think, at least some sentences whose
‘timeless’ meaning is not adequately specifiable by a statement of the
exemplary form. Consider the sentence 'Bill is a philosopher and he is,
therefore, brave' (S ,). Or Jill: “Jack is an Englishman; he is, therefore,
brave.”It would be appropriate, I think, to make a partial specification of the
timeless meaning of S, by saying 'Part of one meaning of S, is "Bill is
occupationally engaged in philosophical studies" '. One might, indeed,
give a full specifu::ation of timeless meaning for S, by saying 'One meaning of
S, inc1udes "Bill is occupationally engaged in philosophie al
studies" and "Bill is courageous" and "[The fact] That Bill
is courageous follows from his being occupationally engaged in philosophical
studies", and that is all that is included'. We might re-express this as 'One meaning of
S, comprises "Bill is occupationally engaged (etc)", "Bill is
courageous", and "That Bill is
eourageous follows (ete .)".'] It will be preferable to speeify the
timeless meaning of S I in this way than to do so as folIows: 'One meaning of S
I is "Bill is occupationally engaged (etc.) and Bill is courageous and
that Bill is eourageous follows (ete.)" '; for this latter formulation at
least suggests that SI is synonymous with the conjunctive sentence quoted in
the formulation, whieh does not seem to be the case. Since it is true that
another meaning of SI inc1udes 'Bill is addicted to general reftections about
life' (vice 'Bill is occupationally engaged (etc.)'), one could have occasion
to say (truly), with respect to a given utterance by U of SI' 'The meaning of
SI HERE comprised "Bill is oecupationally engaged (ete.)", "Bill
is eourageous", and "That Bill is courageous follows (ete.)"', or
to say 'The meaning of S I HERE included "That Bill is courageous follows
(etc.)" '. It could also be true that when U uttered SI he meant (part of
what he meant was) that that Bill is eourageous follows (ete.). Now I do not
wish to allow that, in my favoured sense of'say', one who utters SI will have
said [OR EXPLICITLY CONVEYED ] that Bill's being courageous follows from his
being a philosopher, though he may weil have said that Bill is a philosopher
and that Bill is courageous. I would wish to maintain that the SEMANTIC
FUNCTION of the 'therefore' is to enable a speaker to indicate, though not to
say [or explicitly convey], that a certain consequenee holds. Mutatis mutandis,
I would adopt the same position with regard to words like 'but' and 'moreover'.
In the case of ‘but’ – contrast.In the case of ‘moreover,’ or ‘furthermore,’
the speaker is not explicitly conveying that he is adding; he is implicitly
conveying that he is adding, and using the emphatic, colloquial, rhetorical,
device. Much favoured by rhetoricians. To start a sentence with “Furthermore”
is very common. To start a sentence, or subsentence with, “I say that in
addition to the previous, the following also holds, viz.”My primary reason for
opting for this partieular sense of'say' is that I expect it to be of greater
theoretical utility than some OTHER sense of'say' [such as one held, say, by L.
J. Cohen at Oxford] would be. So I shall be committed to the view that applied
timeless meaning and occasion=meaning may coincide, that is to say, it may be
true both First, that when U uttered X the meaning of X inc1uded '*p' and Second, that part of what U meant when he uttered X
was that *p, and yet be false that U has said, among other things, that *p. “I
would like to use the expression 'conventionally meant that' in such a way that
the fulfilment of the two conditions just mentioned, while insufficient for the
truth of 'U said that *p' will be suffieient (and neeessary) for the truth of
'U conventionally meant that *p'.”The above is important because Grice is for
the first time allowing the adverb ‘conventionally’ to apply not as he does in
Essay I to ‘implicate’ but to ‘mean’ in general – which would INCLUDE what is
EXPLICITLY CONVEYED. This will not be as central as he thinks he is here,
because his exploration will be on the handwave which surely cannot be
specified in terms of that the emissor CONVENTIONALLY MEANS.(V) This
distinction between what is said [or explicity conveyed] and what is
conventionally meant [or communicated, or conveyed simpliciter] creates the
task of specifying the conditions in which what U conventionally means by an
utterance is also part of what U said [or explicitly conveyed].I have hopes of
being able to discharge this task by proceeding along the following lines.First,
To specify conditions which will be satisfied only by a limited range of
speech-acts, the members of which will thereby be stamped as specially central
or fundamental. “Adding, contrasting, and reasoning” will not. Second, To
stipulate that in uttering X [utterance type], U will have said [or explicitly
conveyed] that *p, if both First, U has 1stFLOOR-ed that *p, where 1stFloor-ing
is a CENTRAL speech-act [not adding, contrasting, or reasoning], and Second, X
[the utterance type] embodies some CONVENTIONAL device [such as the mode of the
copula] the meaning of which is such that its presence in X [the utterance
type] indicates that its utterer is FIRST-FLOOR -ing that *p. Third, To define,
for each member Y of the range of central speech-aets, 'U has Y -ed that *p' in
terms of occasion-meaning (meaning that ... ) or in terms of some important
elements) involved in the already provided definition of occasion-meaning. (VI)
The fulfilment of the task just outlined will need to be supplemented by an
account of this or that ELEMENT in the CONVENTIONAL MEANING of an utterance
(such as one featuring ‘therefore,’ ‘but,’ or ‘moreover’) which is NOT part of
what has been said [or explicitly conveyed].This account, at least for an
important sub-class of such elements, might take the following shape: First,
this or that problematic element is linked with this or that speech-act which
is exhibited as posterior to, and such that their performance is dependent
upon, some member or disjunction of members of the central, first-floor range;
e. g. the meaning of 'moreover' would be linked with the speech-act of adding,
the performance of which would require the performance of one or other of the
central speech-acts. – [and the meaning of ‘but’ with contrasting, and the
meaning of ‘therefore’ with reasoning, or inferring].Second, If
SECOND-FLOOR-ing is such a non-central speech-act [such as inferring/reasoning,
contrasting, or adding], the dependence of SECOND-FLOOR-ing that *p upon the
performance of some central FIRST-FLOOR speech-act [such as stating or
ordering] would have to be shown to be of a nature which justifies a RELUCTANCE
to treat SECOND-FLOOR-ing (e. g. inferring, contrasting, adding) that *p as a
case not merely of saying that *p, but also of saying that = p, or of saying
that = *p (where' = p', or ' = *p', is a representation of one or more
sentential forms specifically associated with SECOND-FLOOR-ing). Z Third, The
notion of SECOND-FLOOR-ing (inferring, contrasting, adding) that *p (where
Z-ing is non-central) would be explicated in terms of the nation of meaning
that (or in terms of some important elements) in the definition of that
notion). When Grice learned that that
brilliant Harvardite, D. K. Lewis, was writing a dissertation under Quine on
‘convention’ he almost fainted! When he noticed that Lewis was relying rightly
on Schelling and mainly restricting the ‘conventionality’ to the
‘arbitrariness,’ which Grice regarded as synonym with ‘freedom’ (Willkuere,
liber arbitrium), he recovered. For Lewis, a two-off predicament occurs when
you REPEAT. Grice is not interested. When you repeat, you may rely on some
‘arbitrariness.’ This is usually the EMISSOR’s auctoritas. As when Humptyy
Dumpty was brought to Davidson’s attention. “Impenetrability!” “I don’t know
what that means.” “Well put, Alice, if that is your name, as you said it was.
What I mean by ‘impenetrability’ is that we rather change the topic, plus it’s
tea time, and I feel like having some eggs.” Grice refers to this as the
‘idion.’ He reminisces when he was in the bath and designed a full new highway
code (“Nobody has yet used it – but the pleasure was in the semiotic design.”).
A second reminiscence pertains to his writing a full grammar of
“Deutero-Esperanto.” “I loved it – because I had all the power a master needs!
I decide what it’s proper!” In the field of the implicatura, Grice uses
‘convention’ casually, mainly to contrast it with HIS field, the
non-conventional. One should not attach importance to this. On occasion Grice
used Frege’s “Farbung,” just to confuse. The sad story is that Strawson was
never convinced by the non-conventional. Being a conventionalist at heart (vide
his “Intention and convention in speech acts,”) and revering Austin, Strawson
opposes Grice’s idea of the ‘non-conventional.’ Note that in Grice’s general
schema for the communicatum, the ‘conventional’ is just ONE MODE OF CORRELATION
between the signum and the signatum, or the communicatum and the intentum. The
‘conventional’ can be explained, unlike Lewis, in mere terms of the validatum.
Strawson and Wiggins “Cogito; ergo, sum”: What is explicitly conveyed is:
“cogito” and “sum”. The conjunction
“cogito” and “sum” is not made an ‘invalidatum’ if the implicated consequence
relation, emotionally expressed by an ‘alas’-like sort of ejaculation, ‘ergo,’
fails to hold. Strawson and Wiggins give other examples. For some reason, Latin
‘ergo’ becomes the more structured, “therefore,” which is a composite of
‘there’ and ‘fore.’ Then there’s the very Hun, “so,” (as in “so so”). Then there’s
the “Sie schoene aber poor,” discussed by Frege --“but,” – and Strawson and
Wiggins add a few more that had Grice elaborating on first-floor versus
second-floor. Descartes is on the first floor. He states “cogito” and he states
“sum.” Then he goes to the second floor, and the screams, “ergo,” or ‘dunc!’”
The examples Strawson and Wiggins give are: “although” (which looks like a
subordinating dyadic connector but not deemed essential by Gazdar’s 16 ones).
Then they give an expression Grice quite explored, “because,” or “for”as Grice
prefers (‘since it improves on Stevenson), the ejaculation “alas,” and in its
‘misusage,’ “hopefully.” This is an adverbial that Grice loved: “Probably, it
will rains,” “Desirably, there is icecream.” There is a confusing side to this
too. “intentions
are to be recognized, in the normal case, by virtue of a knowledge of the
conventional use of the sentence (indeed my account of "non-conventional implicaturum"
depends on this idea).” So here we may disregard the ‘bandaged leg case’ and
the idea that there is implicaturum in art, etc. If we take the sobriquet
‘non-conventional’ seriously, one may be led to suggest that the
‘non-conventional’ DEPENDS on the conventional. One distinctive feature – the
fifth – of the conversational implicaturum is that it is partly generated as
partly depending on the ‘conventional’ “use.” So this is tricky. Grice’s
anti-conventionalism -- conventionalism, the philosophical doctrine that
logical truth and mathematical truth are created by our choices, not dictated
or imposed on us by the world. The doctrine is a more specific version of the
linguistic theory of logical and mathematical truth, according to which the
statements of logic and mathematics are true because of the way people use
language. Of course, any statement owes its truth to some extent to facts about
linguistic usage. For example, ‘Snow is white’ is true in English because of
the facts that 1 ‘snow’ denotes snow, 2 ‘is white’ is true of white things, and
3 snow is white. What the linguistic theory asserts is that statements of logic
and mathematics owe their truth entirely to the way people use language.
Extralinguistic facts such as 3 are not relevant to the truth of such
statements. Which aspects of linguistic usage produce logical truth and
mathematical truth? The conventionalist answer is: certain linguistic
conventions. These conventions are said to include rules of inference, axioms,
and definitions. The idea that geometrical truth is truth we create by adopting
certain conventions received support by the discovery of non-Euclidean
geometries. Prior to this discovery, Euclidean geometry had been seen as a
paradigm of a priori knowledge. The further discovery that these alternative
systems are consistent made Euclidean geometry seem rejectable without
violating rationality. Whether we adopt the Euclidean system or a non-Euclidean
system seems to be a matter of our choice based on such pragmatic
considerations as simplicity and convenience. Moving to number theory,
conventionalism received a prima facie setback by the discovery that arithmetic
is incomplete if consistent. For let S be an undecidable sentence, i.e., a
sentence for which there is neither proof nor disproof. Suppose S is true. In
what conventions does its truth consist? Not axioms, rules of inference, and
definitions. For if its truth consisted in these items it would be provable. Suppose
S is not true. Then its negation must be true. In what conventions does its
truth consist? Again, no answer. It appears that if S is true or its negation
is true and if neither S nor its negation is provable, then not all arithmetic
truth is truth by convention. A response the conventionalist could give is that
neither S nor its negation is true if S is undecidable. That is, the
conventionalist could claim that arithmetic has truth-value gaps. As to logic,
all truths of classical logic are provable and, unlike the case of number
theory and geometry, axioms are dispensable. Rules of inference suffice. As
with geometry, there are alternatives to classical logic. The intuitionist,
e.g., does not accept the rule ‘From not-not-A infer A’. Even detachment ’From A, if A then B, infer B’ is rejected in some multivalued systems of
logic. These facts support the conventionalist doctrine that adopting any set
of rules of inference is a matter of our choice based on pragmatic
considerations. But the anti-conventionalist might respond consider a simple
logical truth such as ‘If Tom is tall, then Tom is tall’. Granted that this is
provable by rules of inference from the empty set of premises, why does it
follow that its truth is not imposed on us by extralinguistic facts about Tom?
If Tom is tall the sentence is true because its consequent is true. If Tom is
not tall the sentence is true because its antecedent is false. In either case
the sentence owes its truth to facts about Tom.
-- convention T, a criterion of material adequacy of proposed truth
definitions discovered, formally articulated, adopted, and so named by Tarski
in connection with his 9 definition of the concept of truth in a formalized
language. Convention T is one of the most important of several independent
proposals Tarski made concerning philosophically sound and logically precise
treatment of the concept of truth. Various of these proposals have been
criticized, but convention T has remained virtually unchallenged and is
regarded almost as an axiom of analytic philosophy. To say that a proposed
definition of an established concept is materially adequate is to say that it
is “neither too broad nor too narrow,” i.e., that the concept it characterizes
is coextensive with the established concept. Since, as Tarski emphasized, for
many formalized languages there are no criteria of truth, it would seem that
there can be no general criterion of material adequacy of truth definitions.
But Tarski brilliantly finessed this obstacle by discovering a specification
that is fulfilled by the established correspondence concept of truth and that
has the further property that any two concepts fulfilling it are necessarily
coextensive. Basically, convention T requires that to be materially adequate a
proposed truth definition must imply all of the infinitely many relevant
Tarskian biconditionals; e.g., the sentence ‘Some perfect number is odd’ is
true if and only if some perfect number is odd. Loosely speaking, a Tarskian
biconditional for English is a sentence obtained from the form ‘The sentence
——— is true if and only if ——’ by filling the right blank with a sentence and
filling the left blank with a name of the sentence. Tarski called these
biconditionals “equivalences of the form T” and referred to the form as a “scheme.”
Later writers also refer to the form as “schema T.”
stuff
and nonsense:
cf. Grice: “P. M. S. Hacker and the nonsense of sense.’ Grice: “One has to be
very careful. For Grice, “You’re the cream in my coffee” involves a category
mistake, it’s nonsense, and neither true nor false. For me, it involves
categorial falsity; therefore, it is analytically false, and therefore,
meaningful, in its poor own ways!” – “”You’re the cream in my coffee” compares
with a not that well known ditty by Freddie Ayer, and the Ambassadors,
“Saturday is in bed – but Garfield isn’t.”” – “ “Saturday is in bed” involves
categorial falsity but surely only Freddie would use it metaphorically – not
all categorial falsities pass the Richards test --. Grice: “ “It is not the
case that you’re the cream in my coffee” is a truism” – But cf. “You haven’t
been cleaning the Aegean stables – because you’ve just said you spent the
summer in Hull, and the stables are in Greece.” Cf. “Grice: “ ‘You’re the cream
in my coffee’ is literally, a piece of nonsense – it involves a categorial
falsity.” “Sentences involving categorial falsity nonsense are the specialty of
Ryle, our current Waynflete!” -- Sense-nonsense -- demarcation, the line
separating empirical science from mathematics and logic, from metaphysics, and
from pseudoscience. Science traditionally was supposed to rely on induction,
the formal disciplines including metaphysics on deduction. In the verifiability
criterion, the logical positivists identified the demarcation of empirical science
from metaphysics with the demarcation of the cognitively meaningful from the
meaningless, classifying metaphysics as gibberish, and logic and mathematics,
more charitably, as without sense. Noting that, because induction is invalid,
the theories of empirical science are unverifiable, Popper proposed
falsifiability as their distinguishing characteristic, and remarked that some
metaphysical doctrines, such as atomism, are obviously meaningful. It is now
recognized that science is suffused with metaphysical ideas, and Popper’s
criterion is therefore perhaps a rather rough criterion of demarcation of the
empirical from the nonempirical rather than of the scientific from the
non-scientific. It repudiates the unnecessary task of demarcating the
cognitively meaningful from the cognitively meaningless. There are cases in which a denial has
to be interpreted as the denial of an implicature. “She is not the cream in my.
Grice: "There
may be an occasion when the denial of
a metaphor -- any absurd utterance when taken literally, e. g., 'You're the
cream in my coffee' -- may be interpreted *not* as, strictly, denying that
you're *literally* the cream in my coffee, but, in a jocular, transferred
-- and strictly illogical -- way, as the denying the implicaturum, or metaphorical
interpretant, viz.'It is not the case that that you're the salt in my
stew,". Grice was interested in how ‘absurdum’ became ‘nonsense’ -- absurdum,
adj. ab, mis-, and Sanscr. svan = “sonare;” cf. susurrus, and σῦριγξ, = a pipe;
cf. also absonus.” Lewis and Short render ‘absurdum’’ as ‘out of tune, hence
giving a disagreeable sound, harsh, rough.’ I. Lit.: “vox absona et absurda,”
Cic. de Or. 3, 11, 41; so of the croaking of frogs: absurdoque sono fontes et
stagna cietis, Poët. ap. Cic. Div. 1, 9, 15.— II. Fig., -- Short and Lewis this
‘absurd’ transferred usage: ‘absurd,’ which is not helpful -- “of persons and
things, irrational, incongruous, absurd, silly, senseless, stupid.” They give a
few quotes: “ratio inepta atque absurda,” – The reason is inept and absurd”
Ter. Ad. 3, 3, 22: “hoc pravum, ineptum, absurdum atque alienum a vitā meā
videtur,” id. ib. 5, 8, 21: “carmen cum ceteris rebus absurdum tum vero in
illo,” Cic. Mur. 26: “illud quam incredibile, quam absurdum!” “How incredible!
How absurd!” -- id. Sull. 20: “absurda res est caveri,” id. Balb. 37: bene
dicere haud absurdum est, is not inglorious, per litotem for, is praiseworthy,
glorious, Sall. C. 3 Kritz.—Homo absurdus, a man who is fit or good for
nothing: “sin plane abhorrebit et erit absurdus,” Cic. de Or. 2, 20, 85:
“absurdus ingenio,” Tac. H. 3, 62; cf.: “sermo comis, nec absurdum ingenium,”
id. A. 13, 45.—Comp., Cic. Phil. 8, 41; id. N. D. 1, 16; id. Fin. 2, 13.—Sup.,
Cic. Att. 7, 13.—Adv.: absurdē . 1. Lit., discordantly: “canere,” Cic. Tusc. 2,
4, 12.— 2. Fig., irrationally, absurdly, Plaut. Ep. 3, 1, 6; Cic. Rep. 2, 15;
id. Div. 2, 58, 219 al.—Comp., Cic. Phil. 8, 1, 4.—Sup., Aug. Trin. 4 fin. Cf.
Tertullian, “Credo quia absurdum est.” – an answer to “Quam incredible, quam
absurdum!” -- Refs.:
H. P. Grice, “Ryle and categorial nonsense;” “The absurdity of ‘You’re the
cream in my coffee.’”
notum – the ‘gnotus’ -- divided line, one
of three analogies with the sun and cave offered in Plato’s Republic VI, 509d
511e as a partial explanation of the Good. Socrates divides a line into two
unequal segments: the longer represents the intelligible world and the shorter
the sensible world. Then each of the segments is divided in the same
proportion. Socrates associates four mental states with the four resulting
segments beginning with the shortest: eikasia, illusion or the apprehension of
images; pistis, belief in ordinary physical objects; dianoia, the sort of
hypothetical reasondispositional belief divided line 239 239 ing engaged in by mathematicians; and
noesis, rational ascent to the first principle of the Good by means of
dialectic. Grice read Austin’s essay on this with interest. Refs.: J. L.
Austin, “Plato’s Cave,” in Philosophical Papers.
noûs: Grice uses ‘nous’
and ‘noetic’ when he is feeling very Grecian. Grecian term for mind or the
faculty of reason. Noûs is the highest type of thinking, the kind a god would
do. Sometimes called the faculty of intellectual intuition, it is at work when
someone understands definitions, concepts, and anything else that is grasped
all at once. Noûs stands in contrast with another intellectual faculty,
dianoia. When we work through the steps of an argument, we exercise dianoia; to
be certain the conclusion is true without argument to just “see” it, as, perhaps, a god
might is to exercise noûs. Just which
objects could be apprehended by noûs was controversial.
No comments:
Post a Comment