cyrenaic
implicaturum
-- Cyrenaics, a classical Grecian philosophical school that began shortly after
Socrates and lasted for several centuries, noted especially for hedonism.
Ancient writers trace the Cyrenaics back to Aristippus of Cyrene fifth-fourth
century B.C., an associate of Socrates. Aristippus came to Athens because of
Socrates’ fame and later greatly enjoyed the luxury of court life in Sicily.
Some people ascribe the founding of the school to his grandchild Aristippus,
because of an ancient report that the elder Aristippus said nothing clear about
the human end. The Cyrenaics include Aristippus’s child Arete, her child
Aristippus taught by Arete, Hegesius, Anniceris, and Theodorus. The school
seems to have been superseded by the Epicureans. No Cyrenaic writings survive,
and the reports we do have are sketchy. The Cyrenaics avoid mathematics and
natural philosophy, preferring ethics because of its utility. According to
them, not only will studying nature not make us virtuous, it also won’t make us
stronger or richer. Some reports claim that they also avoid logic and
epistemology. But this is not true of all the Cyrenaics: according to other
reports, they think logic and epistemology are useful, consider arguments and also
causes as topics to be covered in ethics, and have an epistemology. Their
epistemology is skeptical. We can know only how we are affected; we can know,
e.g., that we are whitening, but not that whatever is causing this sensation is
itself white. This differs from Protagoras’s theory; unlike Protagoras the
Cyrenaics draw no inferences about the things that affect us, claiming only
that external things have a nature that we cannot know. But, like Protagoras,
the Cyrenaics base their theory on the problem of conflicting appearances.
Given their epistemology, if humans ought to aim at something that is not a way
of being affected i.e., something that is immediately perceived according to
them, we can never know anything about it. Unsurprisingly, then, they claim
that the end is a way of being affected; in particular, they are hedonists. The
end of good actions is particular pleasures smooth changes, and the end of bad
actions is particular pains rough changes. There is also an intermediate class,
which aims at neither pleasure nor pain. Mere absence of pain is in this
intermediate class, since the absence of pain may be merely a static state.
Pleasure for Aristippus seems to be the sensation of pleasure, not including
related psychic states. We should aim at pleasure although not everyone does,
as is clear from our naturally seeking it as children, before we consciously
choose to. Happiness, which is the sum of the particular pleasures someone
experiences, is choiceworthy only for the particular pleasures that constitute
it, while particular pleasures are choiceworthy for themselves. Cyrenaics,
then, are not concerned with maximizing total pleasure over a lifetime, but
only with particular pleasures, and so they should not choose to give up
particular pleasures on the chance of increasing the total. Later Cyrenaics
diverge in important respects from the original Cyrenaic hedonism, perhaps in
response to the development of Epicurus’s views. Hegesias claims that happiness
is impossible because of the pains associated with the body, and so thinks of
happiness as total pleasure minus total pain. He emphasizes that wise people
act for themselves, and denies that people actually act for someone else.
Anniceris, on the other hand, claims that wise people are happy even if they
have few pleasures, and so seems to think of happiness as the sum of pleasures,
and not as the excess of pleasures over pains. Anniceris also begins
considering psychic pleasures: he insists that friends should be valued not
only for their utility, but also for our feelings toward them. We should even
accept losing pleasure because of a friend, even though pleasure is the end.
Theodorus goes a step beyond Anniceris. He claims that the end of good actions
is joy and that of bad actions is grief. Surprisingly, he denies that
friendship is reasonable, since fools have friends only for utility and wise
people need no friends. He even regards pleasure as intermediate between
practical wisdom and its opposite. This seems to involve regarding happiness as
the end, not particular pleasures, and may involve losing particular pleasures
for long-term happiness.
D
D:
SUBJECT INDEX: DEMONSTRATUM
D: NAME INDEX – ITALIAN
D: NAME INDEX – ITALIAN
D:
NAME INDEX: ENGLISH: DUMMETT
Experitum
-- Empiricism
– “with a capital E, of course.” – Grice. Czolbe, H., philosopher. He was born
in Danzig and trained in theology and medicine. His main works are Neue
Darstellung des Sensualismus “New Exposition of Sensualism,” 1855, Entstehung
des Selbstbewusstseins “Origin of Self-Consciousness,” 1856, Die Grenzen und
der Ursprung der menschlichen Erkenntnis “The Limits and Origin of Human
Knowledge,” 1865, and a posthumously published study, Grundzüge der
extensionalen Erkenntnistheorie 1875. Czolbe proposed a sensualistic theory of
knowledge: knowledge is a copy of the actual, and spatial extension is ascribed
even to ideas. Space is the support of all attributes. His later work defended
a non-reductive materialism. Czolbe made the rejection of the supersensuous a
central principle and defended a radical “senCzolbe, Heinrich Czolbe, Heinrich
201 201 sationalism.” Despite this, he
did not present a dogmatic materialism, but cast his philosophy in hypothetical
form. In his study of the origin of self-consciousness Czolbe held that
dissatisfaction with the actual world generates supersensuous ideas and branded
this attitude as “immoral.” He excluded supernatural phenomena on the basis not
of physiological or scientific studies but of a “moral feeling of duty towards
the natural world-order and contentment with it.” The same valuation led him to
postulate the eternality of terrestrial life. Nietzsche was familiar with
Czolbe’s works and incorporated some of his themes into his philosophy.
englishry: Grice was first
an Englishman, and then an Oxonian – and then a philosopher – and then a
genius! Englishness – Englishry, -- St. George for England. A critique of
racism, hostility, contempt, condescension, or prejudice, on the basis of
social practices of racial classification, and the wider phenomena of social,
economic, and political mistreatment that often accompany such classification.
The most salient instances of racism include the Nazi ideology of the “Aryan
master race,” chattel slavery, South
African apartheid in the late twentieth century, and the “Jim Crow” laws and
traditions of segregation that subjugated African descendants in the Southern
United States during the century after the
Civil War. Social theorists dispute whether, in its essence, racism is a
belief or an ideology of racial inferiority, a system of social oppression on
the basis of race, a form of discourse, discriminatory conduct, or an attitude
of contempt or heartlessness and its expression in individual or collective
behavior. The case for any of these as the essence of racism has its drawbacks,
and a proponent must show how the others can also come to be racist in virtue
of that essence. Some deny that racism has any nature or essence, insisting it
is nothing more than changing historical realities. However, these thinkers
must explain what makes each reality an instance of racism. Theorists differ
over who and what can be racist and under what circumstances, some restricting
racism to the powerful, others finding it also in some reactions by the
oppressed. Here, the former owe an explanation of why power is necessary for
racism, what sort economic or political? general or contextual?, and in whom or
what racist individuals? their racial groups?. Although virtually everyone
thinks racism objectionable, people disagree over whether its central defect is
cognitive irrationality, prejudice, economic/prudential inefficiency, or moral
unnecessary suffering, unequal treatment. Finally, racism’s connection with the
ambiguous and controversial concept of race itself is complex. Plainly, racism
presupposes the legitimacy of racial classifications, and perhaps the
metaphysical reality of races. Nevertheless, some hold that racism is also
prior to race, with racial classifications invented chiefly to explain and help
justify the oppression of some peoples by others. The term originated to
designate the pseudoscientific theories of racial essence and inferiority that
arose in Europe in the nineteenth century and were endorsed by G.y’s Third
Reich. Since the civil rights movement in the United States after World War II,
the term has come to cover a much broader range of beliefs, attitudes,
institutions, and practices. Today one hears charges of unconscious, covert,
institutional, paternalistic, benign, anti-racist, liberal, and even reverse
racism. Racism is widely regarded as involving ignorance, irrationality,
unreasonableness, injustice, and other intellectual and moral vices, to such an
extent that today virtually no one is willing to accept the classification of
oneself, one’s beliefs, and so on, as racist, except in contexts of
self-reproach. As a result, classifying anything as racist, beyond the most
egregious cases, is a serious charge and is often hotly disputed.
rational
Griceian deconstruction of communication -- a demonstration of the incompleteness
or incoherence of a philosophical position using concepts and principles of
argument whose meaning and use is legitimated only by that philosophical
position. A deconstruction is thus a kind of internal conceptual critique in
which the critic implicitly and provisionally adheres to the position
criticized. The early work of Derrida is the source of the term and provides
paradigm cases of its referent. That deconstruction remains within the position
being discussed follows from a fundamental deconstructive argument about the
nature of language and thought. Derrida’s earliest deconstructions argue
against the possibility of an interior “language” of thought and intention such
that the senses and referents of terms are determined by their very nature.
Such terms are “meanings” or logoi. Derrida calls accounts that presuppose such
magical thought-terms “logocentric.” He claims, following Heidegger, that the
conception of such logoi is basic to the concepts of Western metaphysics, and
that Western metaphysics is fundamental to our cultural practices and
languages. Thus there is no “ordinary language” uncontaminated by philosophy.
Logoi ground all our accounts of intention, meaning, truth, and logical
connection. Versions of logoi in the history of philosophy range from Plato’s
Forms through the self-interpreting ideas of the empiricists to Husserl’s
intentional entities. Thus Derrida’s fullest deconstructions are of texts that
give explicit accounts of logoi, especially his discussion of Husserl in Speech
and Phenomena. There, Derrida argues that meanings that are fully present to
consciousness are in decision tree deconstruction 209 209 principle impossible. The idea of a
meaning is the idea of a repeatable ideality. But “repeatability” is not a
feature that can be present. So meanings, as such, cannot be fully before the
mind. Selfinterpreting logoi are an incoherent supposition. Without logoi,
thought and intention are merely wordlike and have no intrinsic connection to a
sense or a referent. Thus “meaning” rests on connections of all kinds among
pieces of language and among our linguistic interactions with the world.
Without logoi, no special class of connections is specifically “logical.”
Roughly speaking, Derrida agrees with Quine both on the nature of meaning and
on the related view that “our theory” cannot be abandoned all at once. Thus a
philosopher must by and large think about a logocentric philosophical theory
that has shaped our language in the very logocentric terms that that theory has
shaped. Thus deconstruction is not an excision of criticized doctrines, but a
much more complicated, self-referential relationship. Deconstructive arguments
work out the consequences of there being nothing helpfully better than words,
i.e., of thoroughgoing nominalism. According to Derrida, without logoi
fundamental philosophical contrasts lose their principled foundations, since
such contrasts implicitly posit one term as a logos relative to which the other
side is defective. Without logos, many contrasts cannot be made to function as
principles of the sort of theory philosophy has sought. Thus the contrasts
between metaphorical and literal, rhetoric and logic, and other central notions
of philosophy are shown not to have the foundation that their use presupposes.
deductum – also
demonstratum, argumentum -- deduction, a finite sequence of sentences whose
last sentence is a conclusion of the sequence the one said to be deduced and
which is such that each sentence in the sequence is an axiom or a premise or
follows from preceding sentences in the sequence by a rule of inference. A
synonym is ‘derivation’. Deduction is a system-relative concept. It makes sense
to say something is a deduction only relative to a particular system of axioms
and rules of inference. The very same sequence of sentences might be a
deduction relative to one such system but not relative to another. The concept
of deduction is a generalization of the concept of proof. A proof is a finite
sequence of sentences each of which is an axiom or follows from preceding
sentences in the sequence by a rule of inference. The last sentence in the
sequence is a theorem. Given that the system of axioms and rules of inference
are effectively specifiable, there is an effective procedure for determining,
whenever a finite sequence of sentences is given, whether it is a proof
relative to that system. The notion of theorem is not in general effective
decidable. For there may be no method by which we can always find a proof of a
given sentence or determine that none exists. The concepts of deduction and
consequence are distinct. The first is a syntactical; the second is semantical.
It was a discovery that, relative to the axioms and rules of inference of
classical logic, a sentence S is deducible from a set of sentences K provided
that S is a consequence of K. Compactness is an important consequence of this
discovery. It is trivial that sentence S is deducible from K just in case S is
deducible from Dedekind cut deductíon 211
211 some finite subset of K. It is not trivial that S is a consequence
of K just in case S is a consequence of some finite subset of K. This
compactness property had to be shown. A system of natural deduction is
axiomless. Proofs of theorems within a system are generally easier with natural
deduction. Proofs of theorems about a system, such as the results mentioned in
the previous paragraph, are generally easier if the system has axioms. In a
secondary sense, ‘deduction’ refers to an inference in which a speaker claims
the conclusion follows necessarily from the premises. -- deduction theorem, a
result about certain systems of formal logic relating derivability and the
conditional. It states that if a formula B is derivable from A and possibly
other assumptions, then the formula APB is derivable without the assumption of
A: in symbols, if G 4 {A} Y B then GYAPB. The thought is that, for example, if
Socrates is mortal is derivable from the assumptions All men are mortal and
Socrates is a man, then If Socrates is a man he is mortal is derivable from All
men are mortal. Likewise, If all men are mortal then Socrates is mortal is
derivable from Socrates is a man. In general, the deduction theorem is a
significant result only for axiomatic or Hilbert-style formulations of logic.
In most natural deduction formulations a rule of conditional proof explicitly
licenses derivations of APB from G4{A}, and so there is nothing to prove.
Dis-factum – dis-faccere -- defeasibility. Strawson Wiggins ‘somehwere in the kitchen,’ ‘in one of
the dining-room cupboards’ unless some feature of the context defeats the
implication, there is an implicaturum to the effect that the emissor cannot
make a ‘stronger’ move by Grice’s principle of conversational fortitude (“Be ‘a
fortiori’”). Cf. G. P. Baker on H. L. A.
Hart. All very Oxonian. Cf. R. Hall, Oxonian, on ‘Excluders.’ For Strawson and
Wiggins that a principle holds ‘generally, ceteris paribus, is a condition for
the existence of conversation, or of a good conversation. Defeasibility is a
sign of the freedom of the will. The communicators can always opt out. Not a
salivating dog. Note that defeasibility does not apply just to the implicaturum.
Since probabilistic demonstrate are uncertain, there is an element of
defeasibility in the EXplicatum of a probabilistic utterance. Levinson’s quote,
“Probability, Defeasibility, and Mode Operators.” Defeasibility
-- Grice: “So far as generalizations of these kinds are concerned, it seems to
me that one needs to be able to mark five features: (1) conditionality; (2)
generality; (3) type of generality (absolute, ceteris paribus, etc., thereby,
ipso facto, discriminating with respect to defeasibility or indefeasibility).” -- Baker, “Meaning
and defeasibility” – defeater – in Aspects of reason -- defeasibility, a
property that rules, principles, arguments, or bits of reasoning have when they
might be defeated by some competitor. For example, the epistemic principle
‘Objects normally have the properties they appear to have’ or the normative
principle ‘One should not lie’ are defeated, respectively, when perception
occurs under unusual circumstances e.g., under colored lights or when there is
some overriding moral consideration e.g., to prevent murder. Apparently
declarative sentences such as ‘Birds typically fly’ can be taken in part as
expressing defeasible rules: take something’s being a bird as evidence that it
flies. Defeasible arguments and reasoning inherit their defeasibility from the
use of defeasible rules or principles. Recent analyses of defeasibility include
circumscription and default logic, which belong to the broader category of
non-monotonic logic. The rules in several of these formal systems contain
special antecedent conditions and are not truly defeasible since they apply
whenever their conditions are satisfied. Rules and arguments in other
non-monotonic systems justify their conclusions only when they are not defeated
by some other fact, rule, or argument. John Pollock distinguishes between
rebutting and undercutting defeaters. ‘Snow is not normally red’ rebuts in
appropriate circumstances the principle ‘Things that look red normally are
red’, while ‘If the available light is red, do not use the principle that
things that look red normally are red’ only undercuts the embedded rule.
Pollock has influenced most other work on formal systems for defeasible
reasoning.
defensible – H. P. Grice, “Conceptual analysis and the defensible
province of philosophy.” Grice uses the ‘territorial’ province, and the further
implicaturum is that conceptual analysis as the province of philosophy is a
defensible one. Grice thinks it is.
definitum: Grice: There is the definitum and what Kant called the
infinitum --. Grice lists ‘the’ in his list of communicative devices. He was
interested in the iota operator. After Sluga, he knew there were problems here.
He proposed a quantificational approach alla Whitehead and Russell, indeed a
Whitehead and Russellian expansion in three clauses, with identity, involved.
Why wasn’t Russell not involved with the ‘indefinite’. One would think because
that’s rendered already by (Ex), ‘some (at least one)’. Russell’s interest in definitum is not
philosophical. His background was mathematics, rather --. Grice was obsessed
with ‘aspects’ in verbs. There’s the ‘imperfect’ and the ‘perfect.’ These
translate Aristotle’s ‘teleos’ and ‘ateleos.’ But why the change from “factum”
to “fectum”? So it’s better to turn to ‘definitum,’ and ‘indefinitum, as better
paraphrases of Aristotle’s jargon – keeping in mind we are talking of his
‘teleos’ and ‘ateleos. Aristotle
and telos. In the Met. Y.1048b1835, Aristotle discusses the definition of an
action πϱᾶξις. He distinguishes two kinds of activities: kinêseis ϰινήσεις and
energeiai ἐνέϱγειαι: Only that movement in which the end is present is an
action. E.g., at the same time we are v.ing and have v.n ὁϱᾷ ἅμα, are
understanding and have understood φϱονεῖ, are thinking and have thought noei
kai nenoêken νοεῖ ϰαὶ νενόηϰεν when it is not true that at the same time we are
learning and have learnt ou manthanei kai memathêken οὐ μανθάνει ϰαὶ μεμάθηϰεν,
or are being cured and have been cured oud’ hugiazetai kai hugiastai οὐδ᾿ ὑγιάζεται
ϰαὶ ὑγίασται. At the same time we are living well and have lived well εὖ ζῇ ϰαὶ
εὖ ἔζηϰεν ἅμα, and are happy and have been happy εὐδαιμονεῖ ϰαὶ εὐδαιμόνηϰεν.
Of these processes, then, we must call the one set movements ϰινήσεις, and the
other actualities energeiai ἐνέϱγειαι. We v. that the distinctive properties of
these two categories of verbs are provided by relations of inference and
semantic compatibility between the form of the present and the form of the perfect.
In the case of energeiai, there is a relation of inference between the present
and the perfect, in the sense that when someone says I v. we can infer I have
v.n. There is also a relation of semantic compatibility since one can very well
say I have v.n and continue to v.. Thus the two forms—the present and the
perfect— are verifiable at the same time ἅμα, simultaneously. On the other
hand, in the case of kinêseis, the present and the perfect are not verifiable
at the same time. In fact, when someone says I am building a house, we cannot
infer I have built a house, at least in the sense in which the house is
finished. In addition, once the house is finished, one is no longer
constructing it, which means that there is a semantic incompatibility between the
present and the perfect. τέλος, which means both complete action, that is, end,
and limit in competition with πέϱας, plays a crucial role in this opposition.
In the category of energeiai, we have actions proper, that is, activities that
are complete τέλεια because they have an immanent finality ἐνυπάϱχει τὸ τέλος.
In the category of kinêseis, we have imperfect activities ἀτελείς that do not
carry their own end within themselves but are transitive and aim at realizing
something. Thus activities having an external goal that is at the same time a
limit peras do not carry their own goal telos within themselves; they are
directed toward a goal but this goal is not attained during the activity, but
is realized at the end of the activity.
And history repeated itself, in the same terms, regarding Slavic
languages, with on the one hand the words perfective and imperfective, modeled
on the Roman opposition and imported to describe an opposition in which lexicon
and grammar are truly interwoven since it is a question of categories of verbs,
which determine the whole organization of conjugation, and on the other hand
the Russian words that are used to characterize the same categories of verbs,
and that signify the accomplished and the unaccomplished. In the terminological
imbroglio, we can once again v. the effects of a confusion connected with the
inability to acknowledge the autonomy of lexical aspect, or, in the particular
case of Slavic languages, the difficulty of isoRomang the aspectual dimension
in the general system of the language. Nevertheless, the same questions, that
of the telos and that of accomplishment, are at the foundation of the two
aspectual dimensions. They are even so prominent that, alongside the
heterogeneous inventory from which we began, we also find, and almost
simultaneously in the aspectual tradition, a leveling of all differences in
favor of two categories that are supposed to be the categories par excellence
of grammatical aspect: the perfective on the one hand, and the imperfective on
the other. However, there is also the continuing competition of the perfect,
another tr. of the same word, perfectum, designating a category that is not
exactly the same as that of the perfective, and which is, for its part, always
a grammatical category, never a lexical category: one speaks of perfect to
designate compound tenses in G. ic languages, e. g. , of the type I have
received as opposed to I received, which
corresponds to the idea that the telos is not only achieved, but transcended in
the constitution of a fixed state, given as the result of the completion of the
process. Two, or three, grammatical categories that are the same and not the
same as the two, three, or four lexical categories. It is in the name of these
categories, and literally behind their name, that the aspectual descriptions
succeeded in being applicable to all languages, confRomang all the imperfects
of all languages and also the Eng. progressive and the Russian imperfective,
all the aorists in all languages, and aligning perfects, perfectives, the Eng.
perfect, the G. Perfekt, the Roman
perfectum and the Grecian perfect. The facts are different, but the words, and
the recurrence of a problematics that v.ms invariable, are too strong. Although
it is a matter of conjugations, the lexicon and the relation to ontological
questions are too influential. The word imperfectum
was invented, we v. a hesitation that is precisely the one that causes a
problem here, between imperfectum and infectum a nonachieved finality, an
absence of finality. The important point is that the whole history of aspectual
terminology is constituted by such exchanges. The invention of the words
perfectum and imperfectum itself proceeds from an enterprise of tr., in which
it is a question of taking as a model, or rephrasing, the Grecian grammarians’
opposition between suntelikos συντελιϰός and non-suntelikos. However, the
difference between the two terminologies is noticeable. A supine past
participle, -fectum, has replaced telikos, and hence telos, thereby reintroducing,
if not tense was tense really involved in that past participle?, at least the
achievement of an act, and consequently merges with the question of the
accomplished. In this operation, the Stoics’ opposition between suntelikos
which would thus designate the choice of perfects or imperfects and παϱατατιϰός
the extensive, in which the question of the telos is not involved was made
symmetrical, introducing into aspectual terminology a binariness from which we
have never recovered. And this symmetricalization, which sought to describe the
organization of a conjugation, was then modeled on the distinction introduced
by Aristotle between tτέλειος and aἀτελής, which was not grammatical but
lexical. This resulted in a new confusion that is not without foundation because
it was already implicit in the montage constructed by the Grecian philosophers,
with on the one hand the telos used by Aristotle to differentiate types of
process, and on the other the same telos used by the Stoics to structure
conjugation. exist in G. , is said to be primarily a matter of discursive
construction with the imparfait forming the background of a narration, and the
past tenses forming the foreground of what develops and occurs. More recently,
this area has been dominated by theories that situate aspect in a theory of
discursive representations cf. Kamp’s discourse representation theory, and try
to reduce it to a matter of discursive organization: thus the models currently
most discussed make the imparfait an anaphoric mark that repeats an element of
the context instead of constructing an independent referent. Once again the
relations are inextricably confused: the types of discourse clearly have
particular aspectual properties we have already v.n this in connection with
aoristic utterances that structure both aspect and tense differently, and yet
all or almost all aspectual forms can appear anywhere, in all or almost all
types of discursive contexts. Thus we have foregrounded imparfaits, which have
been recorded and are sometimes called narrative imparfaits— e. g. , in an
utterance like Trois jours après, il mourait Three days later, he was dying,
where it is a question of narrating a prominent event, and where the
distinction between imparfait and passé simple becomes more difficult to evaluate.
We also find passé composés in narratives, where they compete with the passé
simple: that is why many analysts of the language consider the passé simple an
archaic form that is being abandoned in favor of the passé composé. The
difficulty is clear: it is hard to attach a given formal procedure to a given
enunciative structuration, not only because enunciative structures are supposed
to be compatible with several aspectual values, but first of all because the
formal procedures themselves are all, more or less broadly, polysemous, their
value depending precisely on the context and thus on the enunciative structure
in which they are situated. Here again, this is commonplace: polysemy is
everywhere in languages. But in this case it affects aspect: it consists
precisely in running through aspectual oppositions, the very ones that are also
supposed to be associated with some aspectual marker. The case of narrative
uses of the imparfait v.ms to indicate that the imparfait can have different
aspectual values, of which some are more or less apparently perfective. The
narrative passé composés for instance, Il s’est levé et il est sorti He got up
and went out describe the process in its advent and thus do not have the same
aspectual properties as those that appear in utterances describing the state
resulting from the process e.g., Désolé, en ce moment il est sorti Sorry, he
left just now. Not to mention the presents, which are highly polysemous in many
languages and which, depending on the language, therefore occupy a more or less
extensive aspectual terrain. We are obliged to note that aspect is at least
partially independent of formal procedures, that it also plays a role
elsewhere, in particular, in the enunciative configuration. teleology: the objectivum. Grice speaks of the objective as
a maxim. This is very Latinate. So if the maxim is an objective, the goal is
the objective, or objectivum. Meaning "goal, aim" (1881)
is from military term objective point (1852), reflecting a sense evolution
in French. This is an expansion on the
desideratum. Cf. ‘desirable,’ and ‘desirability,’ and ‘end.’ Grice feels like
introducing goal-oriented conceptual machinery. In a later stage of his career
he ensured that this machinery be seen as NOT mechanistically derivable. Which is
odd seeing that in the ‘progression’ of the ‘soul,’ he allows for talk of
adaptiveness and survival which suggest a mechanist explanation. If an agent
has a desideratum that means that, to echo Bennett, A displays a goal-oriented
behaviour, where the goal is the ‘telos.’ Smoke cannot ‘mean’ fire, because
smoke doesn’t really behave in a goal-oriented matter. Grice does play with the
idea of finality in nature, because that would allow him to justify the
objectivity of his system. how does soul originate from matter? Does the
vegetal soul have a telos. Purposive-behaviour is obvious in plants
(phototropism). If it is present in the vegetal soul, it is present in the
animal soul. If it is present in the animal soul, it is present in the rational
soul. With each stage, alla Hartmann, there are distinctions in the
specification of the telos. Grice could be more continental than Scheler!
Grices métier. Unity of science was a very New-World expression that Grice did
not quite buy. Grice was brought up in a world, the Old World, indeed, as he
calls it in his Proem to the Locke lectures, of Snows two cultures. At the time
of Grices philosophising, philosophers such as Winch (who indeed quotes fro
Grice) were contesting the idea that science is unitary, when it comes to the
explanation of rational behaviour. Since a philosophical approach to the
explanation of rational behaviour, including conversational behaviour (to
account for the conversational implicatura) is his priority, Grice needs to
distinguish himself from those who propose a unified science, which Grice
regards as eliminationist and reductionist. Grice is ambivalent about science
and also playful (philosophia regina scientiarum). Grice seems to presuppose,
or implicate, that, since there is the devil of scientism, science cannot get
at teleology. The devil is in the physiological details, which are irrelevant.
The language Grice uses to describe his Ps as goal-oriented, aimed at survival
and reproduction, seems teleological and somewhat scientific, though. But he
means that ironically! As the scholastics use it, teleology is a science, the
science of telos, or finality (cf. Aristotle on telos aitia, causa finalis. The
unity of science is threatened by teleology, and vice versa. Unified science
seeks for a mechanistically derivable teleology. But Grices sympathies lie for
detached finality. Grice is obsessed with the Greek idea of a telos, as
slightly overused by Aristotle. Grice thinks that some actions are for their
own sake. What is the telos of Oscar Wilde? Can we speak of Oscar Wilde’s
métier? If a tiger is to tigerise, a human is to humanise, and a person is to
personise. Grice thought that teleology is a key philosophical way to contest
mechanism, so popular in The New World. Strictly, and Grice knew this,
teleology is constituted as a discipline. One term that Cicero was unable to
translate! For the philosopher, teleology is that part of philosophy that
studies the realm of the telos. Informally, teleological is opposed to
mechanistic. Grice is interested in the mechanism/teleology debate, indeed
jumps into it, with a goal in mind! Grice finds some New-World philosophers too
mechanistic-oriented, in contrast with the more two-culture atmosphere he was
familiar with at Oxford! Code is the Aristotelian, and he and Grice are
especially concerned in the idea of causa finalis. For Grice only detached
finality poses a threat to Mechanism, as it should! Axiological objectivity is
possible only given finality or purpose in Nature, the admissibility of a final
cause. Grice’s
“Definition” of Meaning – and Communicatum – Oddly, in “Utterer’s meaning and
intentions,” Grice keeps calling his analyses ‘definition,’ and
‘re-definition.’ He is well aware of the trick introduced by Robinson on this.
definiendum plural: definienda, the expression that is defined in a definition.
The expression that gives the definition is the definiens plural: definientia.
In the definition father, male parent, ‘father’ is the definiendum and ‘male
parent’ is the definiens. In the definition ‘A human being is a rational
animal’, ‘human being’ is the definiendum and ‘rational animal’ is the
definiens. Similar terms are used in the case of conceptual analyses, whether
they are meant to provide synonyms or not; ‘definiendum’ for ‘analysandum’ and
‘definiens’ for ‘analysans’. In ‘x knows that p if and only if it is true that
p, x believes that p, and x’s belief that p is properly justified’, ‘x knows
that p’ is the analysandum and ‘it is true that p, x believes that p, and x’s
belief that p is properly justified’ is the analysans. definist, someone who holds that moral terms,
such as ‘right’, and evaluative terms, such as ‘good’ in short, normative terms are definable in non-moral, non-evaluative
i.e., non-normative terms. William Frankena offers a broader account of a
definist as one who holds that ethical terms are definable in non-ethical
terms. This would allow that they are definable in nonethical but evaluative
terms say, ‘right’ in terms of what is
non-morally intrinsically good. Definists who are also naturalists hold that
moral terms can be defined by terms that denote natural properties, i.e.,
properties whose presence or absence can be determined by observational means.
They might define ‘good’ as ‘what conduces to pleasure’. Definists who are not
naturalists will hold that the terms that do the defining do not denote natural
properties, e.g., that ‘right’ means ‘what is commanded by God’. definition, specification of the meaning or,
alternatively, conceptual content, of an expression. For example, ‘period of
fourteen days’ is a definition of ‘fortnight’. Definitions have traditionally
been judged by rules like the following: 1 A definition should not be too
narrow. ‘Unmarried adult male psychiatrist’ is too narrow a definition for
‘bachelor’, for some bachelors are not psychiatrists. ‘Having vertebrae and a
liver’ is too narrow for ‘vertebrate’, for, even though all actual vertebrate
things have vertebrae and a liver, it is possible for a vertebrate thing to
lack a liver. 2 A definition should not be too broad. ‘Unmarried adult’ is too
broad a definition for ‘bachelor’, for not all unmarried adults are bachelors.
‘Featherless biped’ is too broad for ‘human being’, for even though all actual
featherless bipeds are human beings, it is possible for a featherless biped to
be non-human. 3 The defining expression in a definition should ideally exactly
match the degree of vagueness of the expression being defined except in a
precising definition. ‘Adult female’ for ‘woman’ does not violate this rule,
but ‘female at least eighteen years old’ for ‘woman’ does. 4 A definition
should not be circular. If ‘desirable’ defines ‘good’ and ‘good’ defines
‘desirable’, these definitions are circular. Definitions fall into at least the
following kinds: analytical definition: definition whose corresponding
biconditional is analytic or gives an analysis of the definiendum: e.g.,
‘female fox’ for ‘vixen’, where the corresponding biconditional ‘For any x, x
is a vixen if and only if x is a female fox’ is analytic; ‘true in all possible
worlds’ for ‘necessarily true’, where the corresponding biconditional ‘For any
P, P is necessarily true if and only if P is true in all possible worlds’ gives
an analysis of the definiendum. contextual definition: definition of an expression
as it occurs in a larger expression: e.g., ‘If it is not the case that Q, then
P’ contextually defines ‘unless’ as it occurs in ‘P unless Q’; ‘There is at
least one entity that is F and is identical with any entity that is F’
contextually defines ‘exactly one’ as it occurs in ‘There is exactly one F’.
Recursive definitions see below are an important variety of contextual
definition. Another important application of contextual definition is Russell’s
theory of descriptions, which defines ‘the’ as it occurs in contexts of the
form ‘The so-and-so is such-and-such’. coordinative definition: definition of a
theoretical term by non-theoretical terms: e.g., ‘the forty-millionth part of
the circumference of the earth’ for ‘meter’. definition by genus and species:
When an expression is said to be applicable to some but not all entities of a
certain type and inapplicable to all entities not of that type, the type in
question is the genus, and the subtype of all and only those entities to which
the expression is applicable is the species: e.g., in the definition ‘rational
animal’ for ‘human’, the type animal is the genus and the subtype human is the
species. Each species is distinguished from any other of the same genus by a
property called the differentia. definition in use: specification of how an
expression is used or what it is used to express: e.g., ‘uttered to express
astonishment’ for ‘my goodness’. Vitters emphasized the importance of
definition in use in his use theory of meaning. definition per genus et differentiam:
definition by genus and difference; same as definition by genus and species.
explicit definition: definition that makes it clear that it is a definition and
identifies the expression being defined as such: e.g., ‘Father’ means ‘male
parent’; ‘For any x, x is a father by definition if and only if x is a male
parent’. implicit definition: definition that is not an explicit definition.
lexical definition: definition of the kind commonly thought appropriate for
dictionary definitions of natural language terms, namely, a specification of
their conventional meaning. nominal definition: definition of a noun usually a
common noun, giving its linguistic meaning. Typically it is in terms of
macrosensible characteristics: e.g., ‘yellow malleable metal’ for ‘gold’. Locke
spoke of nominal essence and contrasted it with real essence. ostensive
definition: definition by an example in which the referent is specified by
pointing or showing in some way: e.g., “ ‘Red’ is that color,” where the word
‘that’ is accompanied with a gesture pointing to a patch of colored cloth; “
‘Pain’ means this,” where ‘this’ is accompanied with an insertion of a pin
through the hearer’s skin; “ ‘Kangaroo’ applies to all and only animals like
that,” where ‘that’ is accompanied by pointing to a particular kangaroo.
persuasive definition: definition designed to affect or appeal to the
psychological states of the party to whom the definition is given, so that a
claim will appear more plausible to the party than it is: e.g., ‘self-serving manipulator’
for ‘politician’, where the claim in question is that all politicians are
immoral. precising definition: definition of a vague expression intended to
reduce its vagueness: e.g., ‘snake longer than half a meter and shorter than
two meters’ for ‘snake of average length’; ‘having assets ten thousand times
the median figure’ for ‘wealthy’. prescriptive definition: stipulative
definition that, in a recommendatory way, gives a new meaning to an expression
with a previously established meaning: e.g., ‘male whose primary sexual
preference is for other males’ for ‘gay’. real definition: specification of the
metaphysically necessary and sufficient condition for being the kind of thing a
noun usually a common noun designates: e.g., ‘element with atomic number 79’
for ‘gold’. Locke spoke of real essence and contrasted it with nominal essence.
recursive definition also called inductive definition and definition by
recursion: definition in three clauses in which 1 the expression defined is
applied to certain particular items the base clause; 2 a rule is given for
reaching further items to which the expression applies the recursive, or
inductive, clause; and 3 it is stated that the expression applies to nothing
else the closure clause. E.g., ‘John’s parents are John’s ancestors; any parent
of John’s ancestor is John’s ancestor; nothing else is John’s ancestor’. By the
base clause, John’s mother and father are John’s ancestors. Then by the
recursive clause, John’s mother’s parents and John’s father’s parents are John’s
ancestors; so are their parents, and so on. Finally, by the last closure
clause, these people exhaust John’s ancestors. The following defines
multiplication in terms of definition definition 214 214 addition: ‘0 $ n % 0. m ! 1 $ n % m $ n
! n. Nothing else is the result of multiplying integers’. The base clause tells
us, e.g., that 0 $ 4 % 0. The recursive clause tells us, e.g., that 0 ! 1 $ 4 %
0 $ 4 ! 4. We then know that 1 $ 4 % 0 ! 4 % 4. Likewise, e.g., 2 $ 4 % 1 ! 1 $
4 % 1 $ 4 ! 4 % 4 ! 4 % 8. stipulative definition: definition regardless of the
ordinary or usual conceptual content of the expression defined. It postulates a
content, rather than aiming to capture the content already associated with the
expression. Any explicit definition that introduces a new expression into the
language is a stipulative definition: e.g., “For the purpose of our discussion
‘existent’ means ‘perceivable’ “; “By ‘zoobeedoobah’ we shall mean ‘vain
millionaire who is addicted to alcohol’.” synonymous definition: definition of
a word or other linguistic expression by another word synonymous with it: e.g.,
‘buy’ for ‘purchase’; ‘madness’ for ‘insanity’.
Refs.: There are specific essays on
‘teleology,’ ‘final cause,’ and ‘finality,’ the The Grice Papers. Some of the
material published in “Reply to Richards” (repr. in “Conception”) and “Actions
and events,” The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC.
datum: in epistemology,
the “brute fact” element to be found or postulated as a component of perceptual
experience. Some theorists who endorse the existence of a given element in
experience think that we can find this element by careful introspection of what
we experience Moore, H. H. Price. Such theorists generally distinguish between
those components of ordinary perceptual awareness that constitute what we
believe or know about the objects we perceive and those components that we
strictly perceive. For example, if we analyze introspectively what we are aware
of when we see an apple we find that what we believe of the apple is that it is
a three-dimensional object with a soft, white interior; what we see of it,
strictly speaking, is just a red-shaped expanse of one of its facing sides.
This latter is what is “given” in the intended sense. Other theorists treat the
given as postulated rather than introspectively found. For example, some
theorists treat cognition as an activity imposing form on some material given in
conscious experience. On this view, often attributed to Kant, the given and the
conceptual are interdefined and logically inseparable. Sometimes this
interdependence is seen as rendering a description of the given as impossible;
in this case the given is said to be ineffable C. I. Lewis, Mind and the World
Order. On some theories of knowledge foundationalism the first variant of the
given that which is “found” rather than
“postulated” provides the empirical
foundations of what we might know or justifiably believe. Thus, if I believe on
good evidence that there is a red apple in front of me, the evidence is the
non-cognitive part of my perceptual awareness of the red appleshaped expanse.
Epistemologies postulating the first kind of givenness thus require a single
entity-type to explain the sensorial nature of perception and to provide
immediate epistemic foundations for empirical knowledge. This requirement is
now widely regarded as impossible to satisfy; hence Wilfred Sellars describes
the discredited view as the myth of the given.
Degradatum
-- degree:
Grice on the flat/variable distinction – Grice considers that ‘ought’ is weaker
than ‘must’ – ‘ought’ displays ‘degree-acceptability.’ Grice loved a degree –
he uses “d” in aspects of reason -- degree, also called arity, adicity, in
formal languages, a property of predicate and function expressions that
determines the number of terms with which the expression is correctly combined
to yield a well-formed expression. If an expression combines with a single term
to form a wellformed expression, it is of degree one monadic, singulary.
Expressions that combine with two terms are of degree two dyadic, binary, and
so on. Expressions of degree greater than or equal to two are polyadic. The
formation rules of a formalized language must effectively specify the degrees
of its primitive expressions as part of the effective determination of the
class of wellformed formulas. Degree is commonly indicated by an attached
superscript consisting of an Arabic numeral. Formalized languages have been
studied that contain expressions having variable degree or variable adicity and
that can thus combine with any finite number of terms. An abstract relation
that would be appropriate as extension of a predicate expression is subject to
the same terminology, and likewise for function expressions and their
associated functions. -- degree of
unsolvability, a maximal set of equally complex sets of natural numbers, with
comparative complexity of sets of natural numbers construed as
recursion-theoretic reducibility ordering. Recursion theorists investigate
various notions of reducibility between sets of natural numbers, i.e., various
ways of filling in the following schematic definition. For sets A and B of
natural numbers: A is reducible to B iff if and only if there is an algorithm
whereby each membership question about A e.g., ‘17 1 A?’ could be answered
allowing consultation of an definition, contextual degree of unsolvability
215 215 “oracle” that would correctly
answer each membership question about B. This does not presuppose that there is
a “real” oracle for B; the motivating idea is counterfactual: A is reducible to
B iff: if membership questions about B were decidable then membership questions
about A would also be decidable. On the other hand, the mathematical
definitions of notions of reducibility involve no subjunctive conditionals or
other intensional constructions. The notion of reducibility is determined by
constraints on how the algorithm could use the oracle. Imposing no constraints
yields T-reducibility ‘T’ for Turing, the most important and most studied
notion of reducibility. Fixing a notion r of reducibility: A is r-equivalent to
B iff A is r-reducible to B and B is rreducible to A. If r-reducibility is
transitive, r-equivalence is an equivalence relation on the class of sets of
natural numbers, one reflecting a notion of equal complexity for sets of
natural numbers. A degree of unsolvability relative to r an r-degree is an
equivalence class under that equivalence relation, i.e., a maximal class of
sets of natural numbers any two members of which are r-equivalent, i.e., a
maximal class of equally complex in the sense of r-reducibility sets of natural
numbers. The r-reducibility-ordering of sets of natural numbers transfers to
the rdegrees: for d and dH r-degrees, let d m, dH iff for some A 1 d and B 1 dH
A is r-reducible to B. The study of r-degrees is the study of them under this
ordering. The degrees generated by T-reducibility are the Turing degrees.
Without qualification, ‘degree of unsolvability’ means ‘Turing degree’. The
least Tdegree is the set of all recursive i.e., using Church’s thesis, solvable
sets of natural numbers. So the phrase ‘degree of unsolvability’ is slightly
misleading: the least such degree is “solvability.” By effectively coding
functions from natural numbers to natural numbers as sets of natural numbers,
we may think of such a function as belonging to a degree: that of its coding
set. Recursion theorists have extended the notions of reducibility and degree
of unsolvability to other domains, e.g. transfinite ordinals and higher types
taken over the natural numbers.
demonstratum: Cf. illatum – In act of communication, Grice’s focus is on
the reasoning on the emissor’s part. This is end-means. The conversational
moves is the most effectively designed move. The potential uptake by the
emissee is also taken into the consideration by the emissor. And actual uptake
is not of philosophical importance. hen Grice tried to conceptualise what
‘communicating’ and ‘smoke means fire’ have in common he came with the idea of
‘consequentia,’ as a dyadic relation that, eventually, will become triadic,
with the missor and the missee brought into the bargain. “Look that smoke,
there must be fire somewhere’ – “By that handwave, he meant that he was about
to leave me.” In any case, Grice’s arriving at ‘consequentia’ is exactly
Hobbes’s idea in “Computatio.’ And ‘con-sequentia’ involves a bit of
‘demonstratio.’ One thing follows the other. One thing YIELDS the other. The
link may be causal (smoke means fire) or ‘communicative’). ‘Rationality’ is one
of those words Austin forbids to use. Grice would venture with ‘reason,’ and
better, ‘reasons’ to make it countable, and good for botanising. Only in the
New World, and when he started to get input from non-philosophers, did Grice
explore ‘rationality’ itself. Oxonians philosophers take it for granted, and do
not have to philosophise about it. Especially those who belong to Grice’s play
group of ‘ordinary-language’ philosophers! Oxonian philosophers will quote from
the Locke version! Obviously, while each of the four lectures credits their own
entry below, it may do to reflect on Grices overall aim. Grice structures the
lectures in the form of a philosophical dialogue with his audience. The
first lecture is intended to provide a bit of linguistic botanising for
reasonable, and rational. In later lectures, Grice tackles reason qua
noun. The remaining lectures are meant to explore what he calls the
Aequi-vocality thesis: must has only one Fregeian that crosses what he calls
the buletic-doxastic divide. He is especially concerned ‒ this being
the Kant lectures ‒ with Kants attempt to reduce the
categorical imperative to a counsel of prudence (Ratschlag der Klugheit), where
Kants prudence is Klugheit, versus skill, as in rule of skill, and even if Kant
defines Klugheit as a skill to attain what is good for oneself ‒
itself divided into privatKlugheit and Weltklugheit. Kant re-introduces the
Aristotelian idea of eudaimonia. While a further lecture on happiness as
the pursuit of a system of ends is NOT strictly part of the either the
Kant or the Locke lectures, it relates, since eudaemonia may be
regarded as the goal involved in the relevant
imperative. “Aspects”, Clarendon, Stanford, The Kant memorial
Lectures, “Aspects,” Clarendon, Some aspects of reason, Stanford; reason,
reasoning, reasons. The lectures were also delivered as the Locke
lectures. Grice is concerned with the reduction of the categorical
imperative to the hypothetical or suppositional imperative. His main
thesis he calls the æqui-vocality thesis: must has one unique or singular
sense, that crosses the buletic-boulomaic/doxastic divide. “Aspects,”
Clarendon, Grice, “Aspects, Clarendon, Locke lecture notes: reason. On
“Aspects”. Including extensive language botany on rational, reasonable, and
indeed reason (justificatory, explanatory, and mixed). At this point,
Grice notes that linguistic botany is indispensable towards the construction of
a more systematic explanatory theory. It is an exploration of a range of
uses of reason that leads him to his Aequi-vocality thesis that must has only
one sense; also ‘Aspects of reason and reasoning,’ in Grice, “Aspects,”
Clarendon, the Locke lectures, the Kant lectures, Stanford, reason,
happiness. While Locke hardly mentions reason, his friend Burthogge does,
and profusely! It was slightly ironic that Grice had delivered these
lectures as the Rationalist Kant lectures at Stanford. He was honoured to
be invited to Oxford. Officially, to be a Locke lecture you have to be
*visiting* Oxford. While Grice was a fellow of St. Johns, he was still
most welcome to give his set of lectures on reasoning at the Sub-Faculty of
Philosophy. He quotes very many authors, including Locke! In his proemium,
Grice notes that while he was rejected the Locke scholarship back in the day,
he was extremely happy to be under Lockes ægis now! When preparing for his
second lecture, he had occasion to revise some earlier drafts dated pretty
early, on reasons, Grice, “Aspects,” Clarendon, reason,
reasons. Linguistic analysis on justificatory, explanatory and mixed uses
of reason. While Grice knows that the basic use of reason is qua verb
(reasoner reasons from premise p to conclusion c), he spends some time in
exploring reason as noun. Grice found it a bit of a roundabout way to
approach rationality. However, his distinction between justificatory and
explanatory reason is built upon his linguistic botany on the use of reason qua
noun. Explanatory reason seems more basic for Grice than justificatory
reason. Explanatory reason explains the behaviour of a rational
agent. Grice is aware of Freud and his rationalizations. An agent may
invoke some reason for his acting which is not legitimate. An agent may
convince himself that he wants to move to Bournemouth because of the weather;
when in fact, his reason to move to Bournemouth is to be closer to Cowes and
join the yacht club there. Grice loved an enthymeme. Grices enthymeme. Grice,
the implicit reasoner! As the title of the lecture implies, Grice takes the
verb, to reason, as conceptually prior. A reasoner reasons, briefly, from a
premise to a conclusion. There are types of reason: flat reason and gradual
reason. He famously reports Shropshire, another tutee with Hardie, and his
proof on the immortality of the human soul. Grice makes some remarks on akrasia
as key, too. The first lecture is then dedicated to an elucidation, and indeed
attempt at a conceptual analysis in terms of intentions and doxastic conditions
reasoner R intends that premise P yields conclusion C and believes his
intention will cause his entertaining of the conclusion from his entertaining
the premise. One example of particular interest for a study of the use of
conversational reason in Grice is that of the connection between implicaturum
and reasoning. Grice entitles the sub-section of the lecture as Too good to be
reasoning, which is of course a joke. Cf. too much love will kill you, and
Theres no such thing as too much of a good thing (Shakespeare, As you like it).
Grice notes: I have so far been considering difficulties which may arise from
the attempt to find, for all cases of actual reasoning, reconstructions of
sequences of utterances or explicit thoughts which the reasoner might plausibly
be supposed to think of as conforming to some set of canonical patterns of
inference. Grice then turns to a different class of examples, with regard to
which the problem is not that it is difficult to know how to connect them with
canonical patterns, but rather that it is only too easy (or shall I say
trivial) to make the connection. Like some children (not many), some cases of
reasoning are too well behaved for their own good. Suppose someone says to
Grice, and It is very interesting that Grice gives conversational examples.
Jack has arrived, Grice replies, I conclude from that that Jack has arrived. Or
he says Jack has arrived AND Jill has *also* arrived, And Grice replies, I
conclude that Jill has arrived.(via Gentzens conjunction-elimination). Or he
says, My wife is at home. And Grice replies, I reason from that that someone
(viz. your wife) is at home. Is there not something very strange about the
presence in my three replies of the verb conclude (in example I and II) and the
verb reason (in the third example)? misleading, but doxastically fine,
professor! It is true, of course, that if instead of my first reply I had said
(vii) vii. So Jack has arrived, has he? the strangeness would have been
removed. But here so serves not to indicate that an inference is being made,
but rather as part of a not that otiose way of expressing surprise. One might
just as well have said (viii). viii. Well, fancy that! Now, having spent a
sizeable part of his life exploiting it, Grice is not unaware of the truly fine
distinction between a statements being false (or axiologically satisfactory),
and its being true (or axiologically satisfactory) but otherwise
conversationally or pragmatically misleading or inappropriate or pointless,
and, on that account and by such a fine distinction, a statement, or an
utterance, or conversational move which it would be improper (in terms of the
reasonable/rational principle of conversational helfpulness) in one way or
another, to make. It is worth considering Grices reaction to his own
distinction. Entailment is in sight! But Grice does not find himself lured by
the idea of using that distinction here! Because Moores entailment, rather than
Grices implicaturum is entailed. Or because explicatu, rather than implicaturum
is involved. Suppose, again, that I were to break off the chapter at this
point, and switch suddenly to this argument. ix. I have two hands (here is one
hand and here is another). If had three more hands, I would have five. If I
were to have double that number I would have ten, and if four of them were
removed six would remain. So I would have four more hands than I have now. Is
one happy to describe this performance as reasoning? Depends whos one and whats
happy!? There is, however, little doubt that I have produced a canonically
acceptable chain of statements. So surely that is reasoning, if only
conversationally misleadingly called so. Or suppose that, instead of writing in
my customary free and easy style, I had framed my remarks (or at least the
argumentative portions of my remarks) as a verbal realization, so to speak, of
sequences of steps in strict conformity with the rules of a natural-deduction
system of first-order predicate logic. I give, that is to say, an updated
analogue of a medieval disputation. Implicaturum. Gentzen is Ockham. Would
those brave souls who continued to read be likely to think of my performance as
the production of reasoning, or would they rather think of it as a crazy
formalisation of reasoning conducted at some previous time? Depends on crazy or
formalisation. One is reminded of Grice telling Strawson, If you cannot
formalise, dont say it; Strawson: Oh, no! If I can formalise it, I shant say
it! The points suggested by this stream of rhetorical questions may be
summarized as follows. Whether the samples presented FAIL to achieve the title
of reasoning, and thus be deemed reasoning, or whether the samples achieve the
title, as we may figuratively put it, by the skin of their teeth, perhaps does
not very greatly matter. For whichever way it is, the samples seem to offend
against something (different things in different cases, Im sure) very central
to our conception of reasoning. So central that Moore would call it entailment!
A mechanical application of a ground rule of inference, or a concatenation
thereof, is reluctantly (if at all) called reasoning. Such a mechanical
application may perhaps legitimately enter into (i.e. form individual steps in)
authentic reasonings, but they are not themselves reasonings, nor is a string
of them. There is a demand that a reasoner should be, to a greater or lesser
degree, the author of his reasonings. Parroted sequences are not reasonings
when parroted, though the very same sequences might be reasoning if not
parroted. Ped sequences are another matter. Some of the examples Grice gives
are deficient because they are aimless or pointless. Reasoning is
characteristically addressed to this or that problem: a small problem, a large
problem, a problem within a problem, a clear problem, a hazy problem, a
practical problem, an intellectual problem; but a problem! A mere flow of ideas
minimally qualifies (or can be deemed) as reasoning, even if it happens to be
logically respectable. But if it is directed, or even monitored (with
intervention should it go astray, not only into fallacy or mistake, but also
into such things as conversational irrelevance or otiosity!), that is another
matter! Finicky over-elaboration of intervening steps is frowned upon, and in
extreme cases runs the risk of forfeiting the title of reasoning. In
conversation, such over-elaboration will offend against this or that
conversational maxim, against (presumably) some suitably formulated maxim
conjoining informativeness. As Grice noted with regard to ‘That pillar box
seems red to me.’ That would be baffling if the addressee fails to detect the
communication-point. An utterance is supposed to inform, and what is the above
meant to inform its addressee? In thought, it will be branded as pedantry or
neurotic caution. If a distinction between brooding and conversing is to be
made! At first sight, perhaps, one would have been inclined to say that greater
rather than lesser explicitnessness is a merit. Not that inexplicitness, or implicaturum-status,
as it were ‒ is bad, but that, other things being equal, the more explicitness
the better. But now it looks as if proper explicitness (or explicatum-status)
is an Aristotelian mean, or mesotes, and it would be good some time to enquire what
determines where that mean lies. The burden of the foregoing observations seems
to me to be that the provisional account of reasoning, which has been before
us, leaves out something which is crucially important. What it leaves out is
the conception of reasoning, as I like to see conversation, as a purposive
activity, as something with goals and purposes. The account or picture leaves
out, in short, the connection of reasoning with the will! Moreover, once we
avail ourselves of the great family of additional ideas which the importation
of this conception would give us, we shall be able to deal with the quandary
which I laid before you a few minutes ago. For we could say e.g. that R reasons
(informally) from p to c just in case R thinks that p and intends that, in
thinking c, he should be thinking something which would be the conclusion of a
formally valid argument the premisses of which are a supplementation of p. This
will differ from merely thinking that there exists some formally valid
supplementation of a transition from p to c, which I felt inclined NOT to count
as (or deem) reasoning. I have some hopes that this appeal to the purposiveness
or goal-oriented character of authentic reasoning or good reasoning might be
sufficient to dispose of the quandary on which I have directed it. But I am by
no means entirely confident that this is the case, and so I offer a second
possible method of handling the quandary, one to which I shall return later
when I shall attempt to place it in a larger context. We have available to us
(let us suppose) what I might call a hard way of making inferential moves. We
in fact employ this laborious, step-by-step procedure at least when we are in
difficulties, when the course is not clear, when we have an awkward (or
philosophical) audience, and so forth. An inferential judgement, however, is a
normally desirable undertaking for us only because of its actual or hoped for
destinations, and is therefore not desirable for its own sake (a respect in
which, possibly, it may differ from an inferential capacity). Following the
hard way consumes time and energy. These are in limited supply and it would,
therefore, be desirable if occasions for employing the hard way were minimized.
A substitute for the hard way, the quick way, which is made possible by
habituation and intention, is available to us, and the capacity for it (which
is sometimes called intelligence, and is known to be variable in degree) is a
desirable quality. The possibility of making a good inferential step (there
being one to be made), together with such items as a particular inferers
reputation for inferential ability, may determine whether on a particular
occasion we suppose a particular transition to be inferential (and so to be a
case of reasoning) or not. On this account, it is not essential that there
should be a single supplementation of an informal reasoning which is supposed
to be what is overtly in the inferers mind, though quite often there may be
special reasons for supposing this to be the case. So Botvinnik is properly
credited with a case of reasoning, while Shropshire is not. Drawing from his
recollections of an earlier linguistic botany on reason. Grice distinguishes
between justificatory reason and explanatory reason. There is a special case of
mixed reason, explanatory-cum-justificatory. The lecture can be seen as the way
an exercise that Austin took as taxonomic can lead to explanatory adequacy,
too! Bennett is an excellent correspondent. He holds a very interesting
philosophical correspondence with Hare. This is just one f. with Grices
correspondence with Bennett. Oxford don, Christchurh, NZ-born Bennett, of
Magdalen, B. Phil. Oxon. Bennett has an essay on the interpretation of a formal
system under Austin. It is interesting that Bennett was led to consider the
interpretation of a formal system under Austins Play Group. Bennett attends
Grices seminars. He is my favourite philosopher. Bennett quotes Grice in his
Linguistic behaviour. In return, Grice quotes Bennett in the Preface
toWOW. Bennett has an earlier essay on rationality, which evidences that
the topic is key at Grices Oxford. Bennett has studied better than anyone the
way Locke is Griceian. A word or expression does not just stand for idea, but
for the intention of the utterer to stand for it! Grice also enjoyed construal
by Bennett of Grice as a nominalist. Bennett makes a narrow use of the epithet.
Since Grice does distinguish between an utterance-token (x) and an
utterance-type, and considers that the attribution of meaning from token to
type is metabolic, this makes Grice a nominalist. Bennett is one of the few to
follow Kantotle and make him popular on the pages of the Times Literary
Supplement, of all places. Refs.: The locus classicus is “Aspects,” Clarendon.
But there are allusions on ‘reason’ and ‘rationality, in The H. P. Grice
Papers, BANC.
denotatum -- denotation, the
thing or things that an expression applies to; extension. The term is used in
contrast with ‘meaning’ and ‘connotation’. A pair of expressions may apply to
the same things, i.e., have the same denotation, yet differ in meaning:
‘triangle’, ‘trilateral’; ‘creature with a heart’, ‘creature with a kidney’;
‘bird’, ‘feathered earthling’; ‘present capital of France’, ‘City of Light’. If
a term does not apply to anything, some will call it denotationless, while
others would say that it denotes the empty set. Such terms may differ in
meaning: ‘unicorn’, ‘centaur’, ‘square root of pi’. Expressions may apply to
the same things, yet bring to mind different associations, i.e., have different
connotations: ‘persistent’, ‘stubborn’, ‘pigheaded’; ‘white-collar employee’,
‘office worker’, ‘professional paper-pusher’; ‘Lewis Carroll’, ‘Reverend
Dodgson’. There can be confusion about the denotation-connotation terminology,
because this pair is used to make other contrasts. Sometimes the term
‘connotation’ is used more broadly, so that any difference of either meaning or
association is considered a difference of connotation. Then ‘creature with a
heart’ and ‘creature with a liver’ might be said to denote the same individuals
or sets but to connote different properties. In a second use, denotation is the
semantic value of an expression. Sometimes the denotation of a general term is
said to be a property, rather than the things having the property. This occurs
when the denotation-connotation terminology is used to contrast the property
expressed with the connotation. Thus ‘persistent’ and ‘pig-headed’ might be
said to denote the same property but differ in connotation.
Grice’s
deontic operator
– “The deon is like the Roman ‘necesse,’ Grice was aware of Bentham’s play on
words with deontology -- as a Kantian, Griceian is a deontologist. However, he
refers to the ‘sorry story of deontic logic,’ because of von Wright (from whom
he borrowed but to whom he never returned ‘alethic’) deontic logic, the logic
of obligation and permission. There are three principal types of formal deontic
systems. 1 Standard deontic logic, or SDL, results from adding a pair of
monadic deontic operators O and P, read as “it ought to be that” and “it is
permissible that,” respectively, to the classical propositional calculus. SDL
contains the following axioms: tautologies of propositional logic, OA S - P -
A, OA / - O - A, OA / B / OA / OB, and OT, where T stands for any tautology.
Rules of inference are modus ponens and substitution. See the survey of SDL by
Dagfinn Follesdal and Risto Hilpinin in R. Hilpinin, ed., Deontic Logic, 1. 2
Dyadic deontic logic is obtained by adding a pair of dyadic deontic operators O
/ and P / , to be read as “it ought to
be that . . . , given that . . .” and “it is permissible that . . . , given
that . . . ,” respectively. The SDL monadic operator O is defined as OA S OA/T;
i.e., a statement of absolute obligation OA becomes an obligation conditional
on tautologous conditions. A statement of conditional obligation OA/B is true
provided that some value realized at some B-world where A holds is better than
any value realized at any B-world where A does not hold. This axiological
construal of obligation is typically accompanied by these axioms and rules of
inference: tautologies of propositional logic, modus ponens, and substitution,
PA/C S - O-A/C, OA & B/C S [OA/C & OB/C], OA/C / PA/C, OT/C / OC/C,
OT/C / OT/B 7 C, [OA/B & OA/C] / OA/B 7 C, [PB/B 7 C & OA/B 7 C] /
OA/B, and [P< is the negation of any tautology. See the comparison of
alternative dyadic systems in Lennart Aqvist, Introduction to Deontic Logic and
the Theory of Normative Systems, 7. 3 Two-sorted deontic logic, due to
Castañeda Thinking and Doing, 5, pivotally distinguishes between propositions,
the bearers of truth-values, and practitions, the contents of commands,
imperatives, requests, and such. Deontic operators apply to practitions,
yielding propositions. The deontic operators Oi, Pi, Wi, and li are read as “it
is obligatory i that,” “it is permissible i that,” “it is wrong i that,” and
“it is optional i denotation deontic logic 219
219 that,” respectively, where i stands for any of the various types of
obligation, permission, and so on. Let p stand for indicatives, where these
express propositions; let A and B stand for practitives, understood to express
practitions; and allow p* to stand for both indicatives and practitives. For
deontic definition there are PiA S - Oi - A, WiA S Oi - A, and LiA S - OiA
& - Oi - A. Axioms and rules of inference include p*, if p* has the form of
a truth-table tautology, OiA / - Oi - A, O1A / A, where O1 represents
overriding obligation, modus ponens for both indicatives and practitives, and
the rule that if p & A1 & . . . & An / B is a theorem, so too is p
& OiA1 & . . . & OiAn / OiB.
-- deontic paradoxes, the paradoxes of deontic logic, which typically
arise as follows: a certain set of English sentences about obligation or
permission appears logically consistent, but when these same sentences are
represented in a proposed system of deontic logic the result is a formally
inconsistent set. To illustrate, a formulation is provided below of how two of
these paradoxes beset standard deontic logic. The contrary-to-duty imperative
paradox, made famous by Chisholm Analysis, 3, arises from juxtaposing two
apparent truths: first, some of us sometimes do what we should not do; and
second, when such wrongful doings occur it is obligatory that the best or a
better be made of an unfortunate situation. Consider this scenario. Art and
Bill share an apartment. For no good reason Art develops a strong animosity
toward Bill. One evening Art’s animosity takes over, and he steals Bill’s
valuable lithographs. Art is later found out, apprehended, and brought before
Sue, the duly elected local punishment-and-awards official. An inquiry reveals
that Art is a habitual thief with a history of unremitting parole violation. In
this situation, it seems that 14 are all true and hence mutually consistent: 1
Art steals from Bill. 2 If Art steals from Bill, Sue ought to punish Art for
stealing from Bill. 3 It is obligatory that if Art does not steal from Bill,
Sue does not punish him for stealing from Bill. 4 Art ought not to steal from Bill.
Turning to standard deontic logic, or SDL, let sstand for ‘Art steals from
Bill’ and let p stand for ‘Sue punishes Art for stealing from Bill’. Then 14
are most naturally represented in SDL as follows: 1a s. 2a s / Op. 3a O- s / -
p. 4a O - s. Of these, 1a and 2a entail Op by propositional logic; next, given
the SDL axiom OA / B / OA / OB, 3a implies O - s / O - p; but the latter, taken
in conjunction with 4a, entails O - p by propositional logic. In the
combination of Op, O - p, and the axiom OA / - O - A, of course, we have a
formally inconsistent set. The paradox of the knower, first presented by
Lennart Bqvist Noûs, 7, is generated by these apparent truths: first, some of
us sometimes do what we should not do; and second, there are those who are obligated
to know that such wrongful doings occur. Consider the following scenario. Jones
works as a security guard at a local store. One evening, while Jones is on
duty, Smith, a disgruntled former employee out for revenge, sets the store on
fire just a few yards away from Jones’s work station. Here it seems that 13 are
all true and thus jointly consistent: 1 Smith set the store on fire while Jones
was on duty. 2 If Smith set the store on fire while Jones was on duty, it is
obligatory that Jones knows that Smith set the store on fire. 3 Smith ought not
set the store on fire. Independently, as a consequence of the concept of
knowledge, there is the epistemic theorem that 4 The statement that Jones knows
that Smith set the store on fire entails the statement that Smith set the store
on fire. Next, within SDL 1 and 2 surely appear to imply: 5 It is obligatory
that Jones knows that Smith set the store on fire. But 4 and 5 together yield 6
Smith ought to set the store on fire, given the SDL theorem that if A / B is a
theorem, so is OA / OB. And therein resides the paradox: not only does 6 appear
false, the conjunction of 6 and 3 is formally inconsistent with the SDL axiom
OA / - O - A. The overwhelming verdict among deontic logicians is that SDL
genuinely succumbs to the deontic operator deontic paradoxes 220 220 deontic paradoxes. But it is
controversial what other approach is best followed to resolve these puzzles.
Two of the most attractive proposals are Castañeda’s two-sorted system Thinking
and Doing, 5, and the agent-and-time relativized approach of Fred Feldman
Philosophical Perspectives, 0.
Grice
on types of priority
-- Grice often uses ‘depend’ – but not clearly in what sense – there’s
ontological dependence, the basic one. dependence, in philosophy, a relation of
one of three main types: epistemic dependence, or dependence in the order of
knowing; conceptual dependence, or dependence in the order of understanding;
and ontological dependence, or dependence in the order of being. When a
relation of dependence runs in one direction only, we have a relation of
priority. For example, if wholes are ontologically dependent on their parts,
but the latter in turn are not ontologically dependent on the former, one may
say that parts are ontologically prior to wholes. The phrase ‘logical priority’
usually refers to priority of one of the three varieties to be discussed here.
Epistemic dependence. To say that the facts in some class B are epistemically
dependent on the facts in some other class A is to say this: one cannot know
any fact in B unless one knows some fact in A that serves as one’s evidence for
the fact in B. For example, it might be held that to know any fact about one’s
physical environment e.g., that there is a fire in the stove, one must know as
evidence some facts about the character of one’s own sensory experience e.g.,
that one is feeling warm and seeing flames. This would be to maintain that
facts about the physical world are epistemically dependent on facts about
sensory experience. If one held in addition that the dependence is not
reciprocal that one can know facts about
one’s sensory experience without knowing as evidence any facts about the
physical world one would be maintaining
that the former facts are epistemically prior to the latter facts. Other
plausible though sometimes disputed examples of epistemic priority are the
following: facts about the behavior of others are epistemically prior to facts
about their mental states; facts about observable objects are epistemically
prior to facts about the invisible particles postulated by physics; and
singular facts e.g., this crow is black are epistemically prior to general
facts e.g., all crows are black. Is there a class of facts on which all others
epistemically depend and that depend on no further facts in turn a bottom story in the edifice of knowledge?
Some foundationalists say yes, positing a level of basic or foundational facts
that are epistemically prior to all others. Empiricists are usually foundationalists
who maintain that the basic level consists of facts about immediate sensory
experience. Coherentists deny the need for a privileged stratum of facts to
ground the knowledge of all others; in effect, they deny that any facts are
epistemically prior to any others. Instead, all facts are on a par, and each is
known in virtue of the way in which it fits in with all the rest. Sometimes it
appears that two propositions or classes of them each epistemically depend on
the other in a vicious way to know A,
you must first know B, and to know B, you must first know A. Whenever this is
genuinely the case, we are in a skeptical predicament and cannot know either
proposition. For example, Descartes believed that he could not be assured of
the reliability of his own cognitions until he knew that God exists and is not
a deceiver; yet how could he ever come to know anything about God except by
relying on his own cognitions? This is the famous problem of the Cartesian
circle. Another example is the problem of induction as set forth by Hume: to
know that induction is a legitimate mode of inference, one would first have to
know that the future will resemble the past; but since the latter fact is
establishable only by induction, one could know it only if one already knew
that induction is legitimate. Solutions to these problems must show that
contrary to first appearances, there is a way of knowing one of the problematic
propositions independently of the other. Conceptual dependence. To say that B’s
are conceptually dependent on A’s means that to understand what a B is, you
must understand what an A is, or that the concept of a B can be explained or
understood only through the concept of an A. For example, it could plausibly be
claimed that the concept uncle can be understood only in terms of the concept
male. Empiricists typically maintain that we understand what an external thing
like a tree or a table is only by knowing what experiences it would induce in
us, so that the concepts we apply to physical things depend on the concepts we
apply to our experideontological ethics dependence 221 221 ences. They typically also maintain that
this dependence is not reciprocal, so that experiential concepts are
conceptually prior to physical concepts. Some empiricists argue from the thesis
of conceptual priority just cited to the corresponding thesis of epistemic
priority that facts about experiences
are epistemically prior to facts about external objects. Turning the tables,
some foes of empiricism maintain that the conceptual priority is the other way
about: that we can describe and understand what kind of experience we are
undergoing only by specifying what kind of object typically causes it “it’s a
smell like that of pine mulch”. Sometimes they offer this as a reason for
denying that facts about experiences are epistemically prior to facts about
physical objects. Both sides in this dispute assume that a relation of
conceptual priority in one direction excludes a relation of epistemic priority
in the opposite direction. But why couldn’t it be the case both that facts about
experiences are epistemically prior to facts about physical objects and that
concepts of physical objects are conceptually prior to concepts of experiences?
How the various kinds of priority and dependence are connected e.g., whether
conceptual priority implies epistemic priority is a matter in need of further
study. Ontological dependence. To say that entities of one sort the B’s are
ontologically dependent on entities of another sort the A’s means this: no B
can exist unless some A exists; i.e., it is logically or metaphysically
necessary that if any B exists, some A also exists. Ontological dependence may
be either specific the existence of any B depending on the existence of a
particular A or generic the existence of any B depending merely on the existence
of some A or other. If B’s are ontologically dependent on A’s, but not
conversely, we may say that A’s are ontologically prior to B’s. The traditional
notion of substance is often defined in terms of ontological priority substances can exist without other things, as
Aristotle said, but the others cannot exist without them. Leibniz believed that
composite entities are ontologically dependent on simple i.e., partless
entities that any composite object
exists only because it has certain simple elements that are arranged in a
certain way. Berkeley, J. S. Mill, and other phenomenalists have believed that
physical objects are ontologically dependent on sensory experiences that the existence of a table or a tree consists
in the occurrence of sensory experiences in certain orderly patterns. Spinoza
believed that all finite beings are ontologically dependent on God and that God
is ontologically dependent on nothing further; thus God, being ontologically
prior to everything else, is in Spinoza’s view the only substance. Sometimes
there are disputes about the direction in which a relationship of ontological
priority runs. Some philosophers hold that extensionless points are prior to
extended solids, others that solids are prior to points; some say that things are
prior to events, others that events are prior to things. In the face of such
disagreement, still other philosophers such as Goodman have suggested that
nothing is inherently or absolutely prior to anything else: A’s may be prior to
B’s in one conceptual scheme, B’s to A’s in another, and there may be no saying
which scheme is correct. Whether relationships of priority hold absolutely or
only relative to conceptual schemes is one issue dividing realists and
anti-realists.
de re: as opposed to de dicto, of what is said or of the
proposition, as opposed to de re, of the thing. Many philosophers believe the
following ambiguous, depending on whether they are interpreted de dicto or de
re: 1 It is possible that the number of U.S. states is even. 2 Galileo believes
that the earth moves. Assume for illustrative purposes that there are
propositions and properties. If 1 is interpreted as de dicto, it asserts that
the proposition that the number of U.S. states is even is a possible truth something true, since there are in fact fifty
states. If 1 is interpreted as de re, it asserts that the actual number of
states fifty has the property of being possibly even something essentialism takes to be true.
Similarly for 2; it may mean that Galileo’s belief has a certain content that the earth moves or that Galileo believes, of the earth, that
it moves. More recently, largely due to Castañeda and John Perry, many
philosophers have come to believe in de se “of oneself” ascriptions, distinct
from de dicto and de re. Suppose, while drinking with others, I notice that
someone is spilling beer. Later I come to realize that it is I. I believed at
the outset that someone was spilling beer, but didn’t believe that I was. Once
I did, I straightened my glass. The distinction between de se and de dicto
attributions is supposed to be supported by the fact that while de dicto
propositions must be either true or false, there is no true proposition
embeddable within ‘I believe that . . .’ that correctly ascribes to me the
belief that I myself am spilling beer. The sentence ‘I am spilling beer’ will
not do, because it employs an “essential” indexical, ‘I’. Were I, e.g., to
designate myself other than by using ‘I’ in attributing the relevant belief to
myself, there would be no explanation of my straightening my glass. Even if I
believed de re that LePore is spilling beer, this still does not account for
why I lift my glass. For I might not know I am LePore. On the basis of such
data, some philosophers infer that de se attributions are irreducible to de re
or de dicto attributions. Internal-external
distinction – de re -- externalism, the view that there are objective reasons
for action that are not dependent on the agent’s desires, and in that sense
external to the agent. Internalism about reasons is the view that reasons for
action must be internal in the sense that they are grounded in motivational
facts about the agent, e.g. her desires and goals. Classic internalists such as
Hume deny that there are objective reasons for action. For instance, whether
the fact that an action would promote health is a reason to do it depends on
whether one has a desire to be healthy. It may be a reason for some and not for
others. The doctrine is hence a version of relativism; a fact is a reason only
insofar as it is so connected to an agent’s psychological states that it can
motivate the agent. By contrast, externalists hold that not all reasons depend
on the internal states of particular agents. Thus an externalist could hold
that promoting health is objectively good and that the fact that an action
would promote one’s health is a reason to perform it regardless of whether one
desires health. This dispute is closely tied to the debate over motivational
internalism, which may be conceived as the view that moral beliefs for instance
are, by virtue of entailing motivation, internal reasons for action. Those who
reject motivational internalism must either deny that expressive completeness
externalism 300 300 sound moral beliefs
always provide reasons for action or hold that they provide external reasons.
DE-VOLVTVM
-- In-volutum, ex-volutum – de-volutum -- The involutum/evolutum distinction,
the: evolutum:
evolutionary Grice -- Darwinism, the view that biological species evolve
primarily by means of chance variation and natural selection. Although several
important scientists prior to Charles Darwin 180982 had suggested that species
evolve and had provided mechanisms for that evolution, Darwin was the first to
set out his mechanism in sufficient detail and provide adequate empirical
grounding. Even though Darwin preferred to talk about descent with
modification, the term that rapidly came to characterize his theory was
evolution. According to Darwin, organisms vary with respect to their
characteristics. In a litter of puppies, some will be bigger, some will have
longer hair, some will be more resistant to disease, etc. Darwin termed these
variations chance, not because he thought that they were in any sense
“uncaused,” but to reject any general correlation between the variations that
an organism might need and those it gets, as Lamarck had proposed. Instead,
successive generations of organisms become adapted to their environments in a
more roundabout way. Variations occur in all directions. The organisms that happen
to possess the characteristics necessary to survive and reproduce proliferate.
Those that do not either die or leave fewer offspring. Before Darwin, an
adaptation was any trait that fits an organism to its environment. After
Darwin, the term came to be limited to just those useful traits that arose
through natural selection. For example, the sutures in the skulls of mammals
make parturition easier, but they are not adaptations in an evolutionary sense
because Danto, Arthur Coleman Darwinism 204
204 they arose in ancestors that did not give birth to live young, as is
indicated by these same sutures appearing in the skulls of egg-laying birds.
Because organisms are integrated systems, Darwin thought that adaptations had
to arise through the accumulation of numerous, small variations. As a result,
evolution is gradual. Darwin himself was unsure about how progressive
biological evolution is. Organisms certainly become better adapted to their
environments through successive generations, but as fast as organisms adapt to
their environments, their environments are likely to change. Thus, Darwinian
evolution may be goal-directed, but different species pursue different goals,
and these goals keep changing. Because heredity was so important to his theory
of evolution, Darwin supplemented it with a theory of heredity pangenesis. According to this theory, the
cells throughout the body of an organism produce numerous tiny gemmules that
find their way to the reproductive organs of the organism to be transmitted in
reproduction. An offspring receives variable numbers of gemmules from each of
its parents for each of its characteristics. For instance, the male parent
might contribute 214 gemmules for length of hair to one offspring, 121 to
another, etc., while the female parent might contribute 54 gemmules for length
of hair to the first offspring and 89 to the second. As a result, characters
tend to blend. Darwin even thought that gemmules themselves might merge, but he
did not think that the merging of gemmules was an important factor in the
blending of characters. Numerous objections were raised to Darwin’s theory in
his day, and one of the most telling stemmed from his adopting a blending
theory of inheritance. As fast as natural selection biases evolution in a particular
direction, blending inheritance neutralizes its effects. Darwin’s opponents
argued that each species had its own range of variation. Natural selection
might bias the organisms belonging to a species in a particular direction, but
as a species approached its limits of variation, additional change would become
more difficult. Some special mechanism was needed to leap over the deep, though
possibly narrow, chasms that separate species. Because a belief in biological
evolution became widespread within a decade or so after the publication of
Darwin’s Origin of Species in 1859, the tendency is to think that it was
Darwin’s view of evolution that became popular. Nothing could be further from
the truth. Darwin’s contemporaries found his theory too materialistic and
haphazard because no supernatural or teleological force influenced evolutionary
development. Darwin’s contemporaries were willing to accept evolution, but not
the sort advocated by Darwin. Although Darwin viewed the evolution of species
on the model of individual development, he did not think that it was directed
by some internal force or induced in a Lamarckian fashion by the environment.
Most Darwinians adopted just such a position. They also argued that species
arise in the space of a single generation so that the boundaries between
species remained as discrete as the creationists had maintained. Ideal
morphologists even eliminated any genuine temporal dimension to evolution.
Instead they viewed the evolution of species in the same atemporal way that mathematicians
view the transformation of an ellipse into a circle. The revolution that Darwin
instigated was in most respects non-Darwinian. By the turn of the century,
Darwinism had gone into a decided eclipse. Darwin himself remained fairly open
with respect to the mechanisms of evolution. For example, he was willing to
accept a minor role for Lamarckian forms of inheritance, and he acknowledged
that on occasion a new species might arise quite rapidly on the model of the
Ancon sheep. Several of his followers were less flexible, rejecting all forms
of Lamarckian inheritance and insisting that evolutionary change is always
gradual. Eventually Darwinism became identified with the views of these
neo-Darwinians. Thus, when Mendelian genetics burst on the scene at the turn of
the century, opponents of Darwinism interpreted this new particulate theory of
inheritance as being incompatible with Darwin’s blending theory. The difference
between Darwin’s theory of pangenesis and Mendelian genetics, however, did not concern
the existence of hereditary particles. Gemmules were as particulate as genes.
The difference lay in numbers. According to early Mendelians, each character is
controlled by a single pair of genes. Instead of receiving a variable number of
gemmules from each parent for each character, each offspring gets a single gene
from each parent, and these genes do not in any sense blend with each other.
Blue eyes remain as blue as ever from generation to generation, even when the
gene for blue eyes resides opposite the gene for brown eyes. As the nature of
heredity was gradually worked out, biologists began to realize that a Darwinian
view of evolution could be combined with Mendelian genetics. Initially, the
founders of this later stage in the development of neoDarwinism exhibited
considerable variation in Darwinism Darwinism 205 205 their beliefs about the evolutionary
process, but as they strove to produce a single, synthetic theory, they tended
to become more Darwinian than Darwin had been. Although they acknowledged that
other factors, such as the effects of small numbers, might influence evolution,
they emphasized that natural selection is the sole directive force in
evolution. It alone could explain the complex adaptations exhibited by
organisms. New species might arise through the isolation of a few founder
organisms, but from a populational perspective, evolution was still gradual.
New species do not arise in the space of a single generation by means of
“hopeful monsters” or any other developmental means. Nor was evolution in any
sense directional or progressive. Certain lineages might become more complex
for a while, but at this same time, others would become simpler. Because
biological evolution is so opportunistic, the tree of life is highly irregular.
But the united front presented by the neo-Darwinians was in part an illusion.
Differences of opinion persisted, for instance over how heterogeneous species
should be. No sooner did neo-Darwinism become the dominant view among
evolutionary biologists than voices of dissent were raised. Currently, almost
every aspect of the neo-Darwinian paradigm is being challenged. No one proposes
to reject naturalism, but those who view themselves as opponents of
neo-Darwinism urge more important roles for factors treated as only minor by
the neo-Darwinians. For example, neoDarwinians view selection as being
extremely sharp-sighted. Any inferior organism, no matter how slightly
inferior, is sure to be eliminated. Nearly all variations are deleterious.
Currently evolutionists, even those who consider themselves Darwinians,
acknowledge that a high percentage of changes at the molecular level may be
neutral with respect to survival or reproduction. On current estimates, over 95
percent of an organism’s genes may have no function at all. Disagreement also
exists about the level of organization at which selection can operate. Some
evolutionary biologists insist that selection occurs primarily at the level of
single genes, while others think that it can have effects at higher levels of
organization, certainly at the organismic level, possibly at the level of
entire species. Some biologists emphasize the effects of developmental
constraints on the evolutionary process, while others have discovered
unexpected mechanisms such as molecular drive. How much of this conceptual
variation will become incorporated into Darwinism remains to be seen. Evolutionary griceianism -- evolutionary
epistemology, a theory of knowledge inspired by and derived from the fact and
processes of organic evolution the term was coined by the social psychologist
Donald Campbell. Most evolutionary epistemologists subscribe to the theory of
evolution through natural selection, as presented by Darwin in the Origin of
Species 1859. However, one does find variants, especially one based on some
kind of neoLamarckism, where the inheritance of acquired characters is central
Spencer endorsed this view and another based on some kind of jerky or
“saltationary” evolutionism Thomas Kuhn, at the end of The Structure of
Scientific Revolutions, accepts this idea. There are two approaches to
evolutionary epistemology. First, one can think of the transformation of
organisms and the processes driving such change as an analogy for the growth of
knowledge, particularly scientific knowledge. “Darwin’s bulldog,” T. H. Huxley,
was one of the first to propose this idea. He argued that just as between
organisms we have a struggle for existence, leading to the selection of the
fittest, so between scientific ideas we have a struggle leading to a selection
of the fittest. Notable exponents of this view today include Stephen Toulmin,
who has worked through the analogy in some detail, and David Hull, who brings a
sensitive sociological perspective to bear on the position. Karl Popper
identifies with this form of evolutionary epistemology, arguing that the
selection of ideas is his view of science as bold conjecture and rigorous
attempt at refutation by another name. The problem with this analogical type of
evolutionary epistemology lies in the disanalogy between the raw variants of
biology mutations, which are random, and the raw variants of science new
hypotheses, which are very rarely random. This difference probably accounts for
the fact that whereas Darwinian evolution is not genuinely progressive, science
is or seems to be the paradigm of a progressive enterprise. Because of this
problem, a second set of epistemologists inspired by evolution insist that one
must take the biology literally. This evidence of the senses evolutionary
epistemology 294 294 group, which
includes Darwin, who speculated in this way even in his earliest notebooks,
claims that evolution predisposes us to think in certain fixed adaptive
patterns. The laws of logic, e.g., as well as mathematics and the
methodological dictates of science, have their foundations in the fact that
those of our would-be ancestors who took them seriously survived and
reproduced, and those that did not did not. No one claims that we have innate
knowledge of the kind demolished by Locke. Rather, our thinking is channeled in
certain directions by our biology. In an update of the biogenetic law,
therefore, one might say that whereas a claim like 5 ! 7 % 12 is
phylogenetically a posteriori, it is ontogenetically a priori. A major division
in this school is between the continental evolutionists, most notably the late
Konrad Lorenz, and the Anglo-Saxon supporters, e.g. Michael Ruse. The former
think that their evolutionary epistemology simply updates the critical
philosophy of Kant, and that biology both explains the necessity of the
synthetic a priori and makes reasonable belief in the thing-in-itself. The
latter deny that one can ever get that necessity, certainly not from biology,
or that evolution makes reasonable a belief in an objectively real world, independent
of our knowing. Historically, these epistemologists look to Hume and in some
respects to the pragmatists, especially
William James. Today, they acknowledge a strong family resemblance to such
naturalized epistemologists as Quine, who has endorsed a kind of evolutionary
epistemology. Critics of this position, e.g. Philip Kitcher, usually strike at
what they see as the soft scientific underbelly. They argue that the belief
that the mind is constructed according to various innate adaptive channels is
without warrant. It is but one more manifestation of today’s Darwinians
illicitly seeing adaptation everywhere. It is better and more reasonable to
think knowledge is rooted in culture, if it is person-dependent at all. A mark
of a good philosophy, like a good science, is that it opens up new avenues for
research. Although evolutionary epistemology is not favored by conventional
philosophers, who sneer at the crudities of its frequently nonphilosophically
trained proselytizers, its supporters feel convinced that they are contributing
to a forward-moving philosophical research program. As evolutionists, they are
used to things taking time to succeed. -- evolutionary psychology, the subfield
of psychology that explains human behavior and cultural arrangements by
employing evolutionary biology and cognitive psychology to discover, catalog,
and analyze psychological mechanisms. Human minds allegedly possess many
innate, special-purpose, domain-specific psychological mechanisms modules whose
development requires minimal input and whose operations are context-sensitive,
mostly automatic, and independent of one another and of general intelligence.
Disagreements persist about the functional isolation and innateness of these
modules. Some evolutionary psychologists compare the mind with its specialized modules to a Swiss army knife. Different modules
substantially constrain behavior and cognition associated with language,
sociality, face recognition, and so on. Evolutionary psychologists emphasize
that psychological phenomena reflect the influence of biological evolution.
These modules and associated behavior patterns assumed their forms during the
Pleistocene. An evolutionary perspective identifies adaptive problems and
features of the Pleistocene environment that constrained possible solutions.
Adaptive problems often have cognitive dimensions. For example, an evolutionary
imperative to aid kin presumes the ability to detect kin. Evolutionary
psychologists propose models to meet the requisite cognitive demands. Plausible
models should produce adaptive behaviors and avoid maladaptive ones e.g., generating too many false positives
when identifying kin. Experimental psychological evidence and social scientific
field observations aid assessment of these proposals. These modules have
changed little. Modern humans manage with primitive hunter-gatherers’ cognitive
equipment amid the rapid cultural change that equipment produces. The pace of
that change outstrips the ability of biological evolution to keep up.
Evolutionary psychologists hold, consequently, that: 1 contrary to
sociobiology, which appeals to biological evolution directly, exclusively
evolutionary explanations of human behavior will not suffice; 2 contrary to
theories of cultural evolution, which appeal to biological evolution
analogically, it is at least possible that no cultural arrangement has ever
been adaptive; and 3 contrary to social scientists, who appeal to some general
conception of learning or socialization to explain cultural transmission,
specialized psychological evolutionary ethics evolutionary psychology 295 295 mechanisms contribute substantially to
that process.
descriptum: Grice: “The root
script provides many niceties in Roman: inscriptum, descriptum, prescriptum,
subscriptum, … -- descriptivism, the thesis that the meaning of any evaluative
statement is purely descriptive or factual, i.e., determined, apart from its
syntactical features, entirely by its truth conditions. Nondescriptivism of
which emotivism and prescriptivism are the main varieties is the view that the
meaning of full-blooded evaluative statements is such that they necessarily
express the speaker’s sentiments or commitments. Nonnaturalism, naturalism, and
supernaturalism are descriptivist views about the nature of the properties to
which the meaning rules refer. Descriptivism is related to cognitivism and
moral realism. Discussed at large by
Grice just because his tutee, P. F. Strawson, showed an interst in it. theory
of descriptions, an analysis, initially developed by Peano, and borrowed from
(but never returned to) Peano by Russell, of sentences containing descriptions.
In Peano’s view, it’s about the ‘article,’ definite (‘the’) and ‘indefinite’
(‘some (at least one).’ Descriptions include indefinite descriptions such as
‘an elephant’ and definite descriptions such as ‘the positive square root of
four’. On Russell’s analysis, descriptions are “incomplete symbols” that are
meaningful only in the context of other symbols, i.e., only in the context of
the sentences containing them. Although the words ‘the first president of the
United States’ appear to constitute a singular term that picks out a particular
individual, much as the name ‘George Washington’ does, Russell held that
descriptions are not referring expressions, and that they are “analyzed out” in
a proper specification of the logical form of the sentences in which they
occur. The grammatical form of ‘The first president of the United States is
tall’ is simply misleading as to its logical form. According to Russell’s
analysis of indefinite descriptions, the sentence ‘I saw a man’ asserts that
there is at least one thing that is a man, and I saw that thing symbolically, Ex Mx & Sx. The role of the
apparent singular term ‘a man’ is taken over by the existential quantifier ‘Ex’
and the variables it binds, and the apparent singular term disappears on
analysis. A sentence containing a definite description, such as ‘The present
king of France is bald’, is taken to make three claims: that at least one thing
is a present king of France, that at most one thing is a present king of
France, and that that thing is bald
symbolically, Ex {[Fx & y Fy / y % x] & Bx}. Again, the apparent
referring expression ‘the present king of France’ is analyzed away, with its
role carried out by the quantifiers and variables in the symbolic
representation of the logical form of the sentence in which it occurs. No
element in that representation is a singular referring expression. Russell held
that this analysis solves at least three difficult puzzles posed by
descriptions. The first is how it could be true that George IV wished to know
whether Scott was the author of Waverly, but false that George IV wished to
know whether Scott was Scott. Since Scott is the author of Waverly, we should
apparently be able to substitute ‘Scott’ for ‘the author of Waverly’ and infer
the second sentence from the first, but we cannot. On Russell’s analysis,
‘George IV wished to know whether Scott was the author of Waverly’ does not,
when properly understood, contain an expression ‘the author of Waverly’ for
which the name ‘Scott’ can be substituted. The second puzzle concerns the law
of excluded middle, which rules that either ‘The present king of France is
bald’ or ‘The present king of France is not bald’ must be true; the problem is
that neither the list of bald men nor that of non-bald men contains an entry
for the present king of France. Russell’s solution is that ‘The present king of
France is not bald’ is indeed true if it is understood as ‘It is not the case
that there is exactly one thing that is now King of France and is bald’, i.e.,
as -Ex {Fx & y {[Fy / y % x] & Bx}. The final puzzle is how ‘There is
no present king of France’ or ‘The present king of France does not exist’ can
be true if ‘the present king of France’
is a referring expression that picks out something, how can we truly deny that
that thing exists? Since descriptions are not referring expressions on
Russell’s theory, it is easy for him to show that the negation of the claim
that there is at least and at most i.e., exactly one present king of France,
-Ex [Fx & y Fy / y % x], is true. Strawson offered the first real challenge
to Russell’s theory, arguing that ‘The present king of France is bald’ does not
entail but instead presupposes ‘There is a present king of France’, so that the
former is not falsified by the falsity of the latter, but is instead deprived
of a truth-value. Strawson argued for the natural view that definite
descriptions are indeed referring expressions, used to single something out for
predication. More recently, Keith Donnellan argued that both Russell and
Strawson ignored the fact that definite descriptions have two uses. Used
attributively, a definite description is intended to say something about
whatever it is true of, and when a sentence is so used it conforms to Russell’s
analysis. Used referentially, a definite description is intended to single
something out, but may not correctly describe it. For example, seeing an
inebriated man in a policeman’s uniform, one might say, “The cop on the corner
is drunk!” Donnellan would say that even if the person were a drunken actor
dressed as a policeman, the speaker would have referred to him and truly said
of him that he was drunk. If it is for some reason crucial that the description
be correct, as it might be if one said, “The cop on the corner has the
authority to issue speeding tickets,” the use is attributive; and because ‘the
cop on the corner’ does not describe anyone correctly, no one has been said to
have the authority to issue speeding tickets. Donnellan criticized Russell for
overlooking referential uses of theory of descriptions theory of descriptions
914 914 descriptions, and Strawson for
both failing to acknowledge attributive uses and maintaining that with
referential uses one can refer to something with a definite description only if
the description is true of it. Discussion of Strawson’s and Donnellan’s
criticisms is ongoing, and has provoked very useful work in both semantics and
speech act theory, and on the distinctions between semantics and pragmatics and
between semantic reference and speaker’s reference, among others. .
de sensu implicaturum: vide casus obliquus. The casus rectus/casus obliquus
distinction. Peter Abelard, Kneale, Grice, Aristotle. Aquinas. de sensu implicaturum.
Ariskantian quessertions on de sensu implicate. “My sometimes mischievous friend Richard Grandy once said, in
connection with some other occasion on which I was talking, that to represent
my remarks, it would be necessary to introduce a new form of speech act,
or a new operator, which
was to be called the operator of quessertion. It is to be read as “It is
perhaps possible that someone might assert that . . .” and is to be symbolized
“?├”; possibly it might even be iterable […].
Everything I shall suggest here is highly quessertable.” Grice 1989:297. If Grice had one thing, he had linguistic creativity.
Witness his ‘implicaturum,’ and his ‘implicaturum,’ not to mention his
‘pirotologia.’Sometime, somewhere, in the history of philosophy, a need was
felt by some Griceian philosopher, surely, for numbering intentions. The verb,
denoting the activity, out of which this ‘intention’ sprang was Latin
‘intendere,’ and somewhere, sometime, the need was felt to keep the Latinate
/t/ sound, and sometimes to make it sibilate, /s/. The source of it all seems to be Aristotle in
Soph.
Elen., 166a24–166a30, which was rendered twice om Grecian to Latin. In the
second Latinisation, ‘de sensu’ comes into view. Abelard proposes to use ‘de
rebus,’ or ‘de re,’ for what the previous translation had as ‘per divisionem.’
To make the distinction, he also proposes to use ‘de sensu’ for what the
previous translation has as ‘per compositionem,’ and ‘per conjunctionem.’ But
what did either mean? It was a subtle question, indeed. And trust Nicolai
Hartmann, in his mediaevalist revival, to add numbers and a further
distinction, now the ‘recte/’oblique’ distinction, and ‘intentio’ being
‘prima,’ ‘seconda,’ ‘tertia,’ and so on, ad infinitum. The proposal is clear.
We need a way to conceptualise first-order propositions. But we also need to
conceptualise ‘that’-clauses. The ‘that’-clause subordination is indeed
open-ended. ‘mean.’ Grice’s motivation in the presentation at the Oxford
Philosophical Society is to offer, as he calls it, a ‘proposal.’ In his words,
notice the emphasis on the Latinate ‘intend,’ – where it occurs, as applied to
an emissor, and as having as content, following that ‘that’-clause, an
‘intensional’ verb like ‘believe,’ which again, involves an ‘intentio tertia,’
now referring to a state back in the emissor expressed by yet another
intensional verb – all long for, ‘you communicate that p if you want your
addressee to realise that you hold this or that propositional attitude with
content p.’ "A meantNN something by x" is
(roughly) equivalent to "A intended the utterance of x to produce some
effect in an audience by means of the recognition of this intention"; and
we may add that to ask what A meant is to ask for a specification of the
intended effect (though, of course, it may not always be possible to get a
straight answer involving a "that" clause, for example, "a
belief that . . ."). (Grice 1989: 220). Grice’s motivation is to ‘reduce’ “mean”
to what has come to be known in the Griceian [sic] literature as a ‘Griceian’
[sic] ‘reflexive’ intention – he prefers M-intention -- which we will read as
involving an intentio seconda, and indeed intentio tertia, and beyond, which
makes its appearance explicitly in the second clause -- or ‘prong,’ as he’d
prefer -- of his ‘reductive’ analysis. Prong 1 then corresponds to the
intention prima or intention recta: Utterer U intends1 that
Addressee A believes that Utterer U holds psychological state or attitude ψ
with content “p.” Prong 2 corresponds to the intentio seconda or
intentio obliqua: Utterer
U intends2 that Addressee A believes (i) on the ‘rational,’ and not
just ‘causal,’ basis of (ii), i.e. of the addressee A’s recognition of the
utterer U’s intentio seconda or intentio obliqua i2, that Addressee
A comes to believe that Utterer U holds psychological state or attitude ψ with
content “p.” In Grice’s wording, “i2” acts as a ‘reason,’ and not
merely a ‘cause’ for Addressee A’s coming to believe that U holds psychological
state or attitude ψ with content “p”. Kemmerling has used “↝” to represent this
‘reason’ (i1 ↝ i2,
Kemmerling in Grandy/Warner, 1986, cf. Petrus in Petrus 2010). Prong 3 is a
closure prong, now involving a self-reflective third-order intention, there is
no ‘covert’ higher-order intention involved in (i)-(iii). Meaning-constitutive
intentions in utterer u’s meaning that p should be out there ‘in the open,’ or
‘above board,’ to count as having been ‘communicated.Grice quotes only one
author in ‘Meaning’: C. L. Stevenson, who started his career with a degree in
English from Yale. Willing to allow a ‘metabolical’ use of ‘mean’ he
recognises, he scare quotes it: “There is a
sense, to be sure, in which a groan “means“ something, just a reduced
temperature may at times ”mean” convalescence.” Stevenson 1944:38). This
remark will have Grice later attempting an ‘evolutionary’ model of how an ‘x’
causing ‘y’ may proceed from ‘natural’ to less natural ones. Consider ‘is in
pain.’ A creature is physically hurt, and the expression of pain comes up
naturally as an effect. But if the creature attains rational control over his
expressive behaviour, and the creature is in pain (or expects his addressee A
to think that he is in pain), U can now imitate or replicate, in a something
like a Peirceian iconic mode, the natural behaviour manifested by a spontaneous
response to a hurtful stimulus. The ‘simulated’ pain will be an ‘icon’ of the
natural pain. Grice is getting Peirceian by the day, and he is not telling us!
There are, Grice says, as if to simplify Peirce the most he can, two modes of
representation. The primary one is now the explicitly Peirceian iconic one. The
‘risus naturaliter significat interiorem laetitiam’ of Occam. And then, there’s
the derivative *non*-iconic representation, in that order. The first is, shall
we say, ‘natural,’ and beyond the utterer U’s voluntary control (cf. Darwin on
the expression of emotions in man and animals); the second is not. Grice is
allowing for smoke representing fire, or if one must, alla Stevenson,
‘representing’ it. In Grice’s motivation to along the right lines, his
psychologist austere views of his 1948 ‘Meaning,’ when he rather artificially
disjoins a ‘natural’ “mean” and an ‘artificial’ “mean,” when merely different
‘uses’ stand for what he then thought were senses, he wants now to re-introduce
into philosophical discourse the iconic natural representation or meaning that
he had left aside.If this is part of what he calls a ‘myth,’ even if an
evolutionary one, to account for the emergence of ‘systems of communication,’
it does starts with an utterer U expressing (very much alla Croce or Marty) a
psychological state or attitude ψ by displaying some behavioural pattern in an
unintentional way. Grice is being Wittgensteinian here, and quotes almost
verbatim from Anscombe’s rendition, “No psychological concept except when
backed in behaviour that manifests it.”
If Ockham notes that “Risus naturaliter significat interiorem
laetitiam,” Grice shows this will allow to avoid, also alla Ockham, a polysemy
to ‘mean.’In Grice’s three clauses in his 1948 conceptual analysis of ‘meaning’
– the first clause of exhibitiveness, the second clause of intentio seconda or
reflexivity, and the third clause of communicative overtness, voluntary control
on the part of the utterer U is already in order. Since the utterer’s addressee
A is intended to recognise this, no longer is it required any prior ‘iconic’
association between a simulated behaviour and the behaviour naturally displayed
as a response to a stimulus. This amounts, for Grice to deeming the system of
expression as having become a full system now of intention-based
‘communication.’‘know’’ Intentio seconda or intentio obliqua comes up nicely
when Grice delivers the third William James Lecture, later reprinted as
“Further notes on logic and conversation.” There, Grice targets one type of
anti-Gettier scenario for the use of a factive psychological state or attitude
expressed by a verb like “know,” again followed by a “that”-clause. Grice is
criticisign Austin’s hasty attempt to analyse ‘know’ in terms of the
‘performatory’ ‘guarantee.’ As Grice puts it in “Prolegomena,” “to say ‘I know’
is to give a guarantee.” (Grice 1989:9) which can be traced back to Austin,
although since, as Grice witnessed it, Austin ‘all too frequently ignored’ the
real of emissor’s communicatum, one is never sure. In any case, Grice wants to overcome this
‘performatory’ fallacy, and he expands on the ‘suspect’ example of the
Prolegomena in the Third lecture. Grice’s troubles with ‘know’ were long-dated.
In Causal Theory he lists as the third philosophical mistake, “What is known by
me to be the case is not also believed by me to be the case.” (1989: 237).
Uncredited, but he may be having in mind Ryle’s odd characterisations with
terms such as ‘occurrence,’ ‘episode,’ and so on. In the section on ‘stress,’ Grice asks us to
assume that Grice knows that p. The question is whether this claim commits the
philosopher to the further clause, ‘Grice knows that Grice knows that p, and so
on, … to use the scholastic term we started this with, ad infinitum. It is not
that Grice is adverse to a regressive analysis per se. This is, in effect, with
what the third clause or prong in his analysis of ‘meaning’ does – ‘let all
meaning-constitutive intentions be overt, including this one. Indeed, when it comes to meaning or knowing,
we are talking optimal, we are talking ‘virtue.’ Both ‘meaning,’
‘communicating, ‘and ‘knowing,’ represent an ‘ideal,’ value-paradeigmatic
concept – where value, a favourite with Hartmann, appears under the guise of a
noumenon in the topos ouranos that only realises imperfectly in the sub-lunary
world. In the third William James lecture Grice cursorily dismisses these
demanding or restrictive anti-Gettier scenarios as too stipulatory for the
colloquial, ordinary, use – and thus ‘sense’ -- of ‘know.’ The approach Gettier
is cricising ends up being too convoluted, seeing that conversationalists tend
to make a rather loose use of the verb. Grice’s example illustrates linguistic
botanising. So we have Grice bringing the examinee who does know that the
battle of Waterloo was fought in 1815, with hardly conclusive evidence, or any
‘de sensu’ knowledge that the evidence (which he does not have) is conclusive.
Grice grants that, in a specially emphatic utterance of ‘know,’ there might be
a cancellable implicaturum to the effect that the knower does have conclusive
evidence for what he alleges to know. Grice’s explicit reference to this
‘regressive nature’ (p. 59) touches on the topic of intention de sensu. Grice
is contesting the strong view, as represented, according to Gettier, by
philosophers ranging from Plato’s Thaetetus to Ayer’s Problem of Empirical
Knowledge (indeed the only two loci Gettier cares to cite in his short essay)
that a claim, “Grice knows that p” entails a claim to the effect that there is
conclusive evidence for p, and which gives Grice a feeling of subjective
certainty, and that Grice knows that there is such conclusive evidence, and so
on, ad infinitum. Grice casts doubts on the intentio de sensu as applied to the
colloquial or ‘ordinary’ uses of ‘know’. If I know that p, must I know that I
know that p? Having just introduced his
“Modified Occam’s Razor” – ‘Senses are not to be multiplied beyond necessity’
--, Grice doesn’t think so. At this point, however, he adds a characteristic
bracket: “(cf. causal theory).” With that bracket, Grice is allowing that the
denotatum of “p,” qua content of U’s psychological state or attitude of
‘knowing,’ the state-of-affairs itself, as we may put it, should play something
like a causal role in U’s knowing that p. Grice is open-minded as to what type
of link or connection that is. It need not be strictly causal. He is merely
suggesting the open-endness of ‘know in terms of these “further conditions” as
to how Grice ‘comes’ to know that p, and refers to the ‘causal theory,’ as
later developed by philosophers like E. F. Dretske and others. As a linguistic
botanist, Grice is well aware that ‘know,’ like ‘see,’ is what the Kiparskys
(whom Grice refers to) call a ‘factive.’An ascription of “Grice knows that p,”
or, indeed, “Grice sees that p,” (unless Grice hallucinates) entails “p.” The
defeating ‘hallucination’ scenario is key. It involves what Grice calls a dis-implicaturum.
The utterer is using ‘know’ or‘see’ in a loose way (and meaning less, rather
than more than he explicitly conveys. Note incidentally, as Grice later noted in
later seminars, how his analysis proves the philosopher’s adage wrong. Surely
what is known by me to be the case is believed by me to be the case. Any
divergence to the contrary is a matter of ‘implicatural’ stress – by which he
means supra-segmentation.‘want’Soon after his delivering the William James
lectures, Grice got involved in a project concerning an evaluation of Quine’s
programme, where again he touches on issues of intentio seconda or intentio
obliqua, and brings us back to Russell and ‘the author of Waverley.’ Grice’s
presentation comes out in Words and Objections, edited by Davidson and
Hintikka, a pun on Quine’s Word and Object. Grice’s contribution, ‘Vacuous
Names,’ (later reprinted in part in Ostertag’s volume on Definite descriptions)
concludes with an exploration of “the” phrases, and further on, with some
intriguing remarks on the subtle issues surrounding the scope of an ascription
of a predicate standing for a psychological state or attitude. Grice’s choice
of an ascription now notably involves an ‘opaque’ (rather than ‘factive,’ like
‘know’) psychological state or attitude: ‘wanting,’ which he symbolizes as “W.”
Grice considers a quartet of utterances: Jack wants someone to marry him; Jack
wants someone or other to marry him; Jack wants a particular person to marry
him, and There is someone whom Jack wants to marry him. Grice notes that “there
are clearly at least *two* possible readings” of an utterance like our (i): a
first reading “in which,” as Grice puts it, (i) might be paraphrased by (ii).”
A second reading is one “in which it might be paraphrased by (iii) or by (iv).”
Grice goes on to symbolize the phenomenon in his own version of a first-order
predicate calculus. ‘Ja wants that p’ becomes ‘Wjap,’ where ‘ja’
stands for the individual constant “Jack” as a super-script attached to the
predicate standing for Jack’s psychological state or attitude. Grice writes:
“Using the apparatus of classical predicate logic, we might hope to represent,”
respectively, the external reading and the internal reading (involving an
intentio secunda or intentio obliqua) as ‘(Ǝx)WjaFxja’
and ‘Wja(Ǝx)Fxja.’ Grice then
goes on to discuss a slightly more complex, or oblique, scenario involving this
second internal reading, which is the one that interests us, as it involves an
‘intentio seconda.’ Grice notes: “But suppose that Jack wants a specific
individual, Jill, to marry him, and this because Jack has been “*deceived* into
thinking that his friend Joe has a highly delectable sister called Jill, though
in fact Joe is an only child.” (The Jill Jack eventually goes up the hill with
is, coincidentally, another Jill, possibly existent). Let us recall that
Grice’s main focus of the whole essay is, as the title goes, ‘emptiness’! In
these circumstances, one is inclined to say that (i) is true only on reading
(vii),” where the existential quantifier occurs within the scope of the
psychological-state or -attitude verb, “but we cannot now represent (ii) or
(iii), with ‘Jill’ being vacuous, by (vi), where the existential quantifier (Ǝx) occurs outside the scope of the
psychological-attitude verb, want, “since [well,] Jill does not really exist,”
except as a figment of Jack’s imagination. In a manoeuver that I interpret as
‘purely intentionalist,’ and thus favouring by far Suppes’s over Chomsky’s
characterisation of Grice as a mere ‘behaviourist,’ Grice hopes that “we should
be provided with distinct representations for two familiar readings” of, now:
Jack wants Jill to marry him; Jack wants ‘Jill’ to marry him. It is at this
point that Grice applies a syntactic scope notation involving sub-scripted
numerals, (ix) and (x), where the numeric values merely indicate the order of
introduction of the symbol to which it is attached in a deductive schema for
the predicate calculus in question. Only the first notation yields the internal
de sensu reading (where ‘ji’ stands for ‘Jill’): ‘W2ja4F1ji3ja4’
and ‘W3ja4F2ji1ja4.’
Note that in the alternative external notation, the individual constant for
“Jill,” ‘ji,’ is introduced prior to ‘want,’ – ‘ji’’s sub-script is 1, while
‘W’’s sub-script is the higher numerical value 3. If Russell could have avowed
of this he would have had that the Prince Regents, by issuing the invitation,
wants to confirm that ‘the author of Waverley’ isN Scott, already having
confirmed that the author of Waverley =M the author of Waverley. Grice warns
Quine. Given that Jill does not exist, only the internal reading “can be true,”
or alethically satisfactory. Similarly, we might imagine an alternative
scenario where the butler informs the Prince: ‘We are sorry to inform Your
Majesty that your invitation was returned: apparently the author of Waverley
does not SEEM to exist.’ Grice sums up his reflections on the representation of
the opaqueness of a verb standing for a psychological state or attitude like
that expressed by ‘wanting’ with one observation that further marks him as an
intentionalist, almost of a Meinongian type. If he justified a loose use of
‘know,’ he is now is ready to allow for ‘existential’ phrases in cases of
‘vacuous’ designata, which however baffling, should not lead a philosopher to
the wrong characterisation of the linguistic phenomena (as it led Austin with
‘know’). Provided such a descriptors occur within an opaque, intensional, de
sensu, psychological-state or attitude verbs, Grice captures the nuances of
‘ordinary’ discourse, while keeping Quine happy. As Grice puts it, we should
also have available to us also three neutral, yet distinct, (Ǝx)-quantificational forms (together with their
isomorphs),” as a philosopher who thinks that Wittgenstein denies a
distinction, craves for a generality! “Jill” now becomes “x”: ‘W4ja5Ǝx3F1x2ja5,’
‘Ǝx5W2ja5F1x4ja3’,
and ‘Ǝx5W3ja4F1x2ja4
.’ Since in (xii) the individual variable ‘x’ (ranging over ‘Jill’) “does not
dominate the segment following the ‘(Ǝx)’
quantifier, the formulation does not display any ‘existential’ or de re,
‘force,’ and is suitable therefore for representing the internal readings (ii)
or (iii), “if we have to allow, as we do have, if we want to faithfully
represent ‘ordinary’ discourse, for the possibility of expressing the fact that
a particular person, Jill, does not actually exist.” At least Grice does not
write, “really,” for he knew that Austin detested a ‘trouser word.’ Grice
concludes that (xi) and (xiii) are derivable from each of (ix) and (x), while
(xii) will be “derivable only” from (ix).‘intend’By this time, Grice had been
made a Fellow of the British Academy and it was about time for the delivery of
the philosophical lecture that goes with it. It only took him six five years.
Grice choses “Intention and uncertainty” as its topic. He was provoked by two
members of his ‘playgroup’ at Oxford, Hart and Hampshire, who in an essay
published in Mind, what Grice finds, again, as he did with the anti-Gettier
cases of ‘know,’ as rather a too strong analysis of ‘intending.’ In his
British-Academy lecture, Grice plays now with the psychological state or
attitude, realised by the verbal form, ‘intend,’ when specifically followed by
a ‘that’-clause, “intends that…,” as an echo of his dealing with “meaning to”
as merely ‘natural.’ He calls himself a neo-Prichardian, reviving this ‘willing
that’ which Urmson had popularised at Oxford, bringing to publication
Prichard’s exploration of William James and his “I will that the distant chair
slides over the floor towards me. It does not.”Grice’s ‘intending that…’ is
notably a practical, boulemaic, or buletic, or desiderative, rather than
alethic or doxastic, psychological state or attitude. It involves not just an
itentum, but an intentum that involves both a desideratum AND a factum – for
the ‘future indicative’ is conceptually involved. Grice claims that, if the
conceptual analysis of “intending that…” is to represent ‘ordinary’ discourse,
shows that it contains, as one of its prongs, in the final ‘neo-Prichardian’
version that Grice gives, also a ‘doxastic’ (rather than ‘factive’ and
‘epistemic’) psychological state or attitude, notably a belief on the part of
the ‘intender’ that his willing that p has a probability greater than 0.5 to
the effect that p be realised. Contra Hart and Hampshire, Grice acknowledges
the investigations by the playgroup member Pears on this topic. Interestingly,
a polemic arose elsewhere with Davidson, who trying to be more Griceian thatn
Grice, sees this doxastic constraint as a mere cancellable implicaturum. Grice
grants it may be a dis-implicaturum at most, as in loose cases of ‘know,’ or
‘see.’ Grice is adamant in regarding the doxastic component as a conceptual
‘entailment’ in the ‘ordinary’ use of ‘intend,’ unless the verb is used in a
merely ‘disimplicatural,’ loose fashion. Grice’s example, ‘Jill intends to
climb Everest next week,’ when the prohibitive conditions are all to evident to
anyone concerned with such an utterance of (xv), perhaps Jill included, and
‘intends’ has to be read only ‘internally’ and hyperbolically. At this point,
if in “Vacuous Names, he fights with Meinong while enjoying engaging in
emptiness, it should be stressed that Grice gives as an illustration of a ‘disimplicaturum,’
along with a use of ‘see’ in a Shakespeareian context. ‘See,’ like ‘know,’ or ‘mean,’ exhibit what
Grice calls diaphaneity. So it’s only natural Grice turns his attention to
‘see.’ Grice’s examples are ‘Macbeth saw Banquo’ and ‘Hamlet saw his father on
the ramparts of Elsinore,’ and both involve hallucination! It is worth
comparing the fortune of ‘disimplicaturum’ with that of ‘implicaturum.’ Grice
coins ‘to dis-implicate’ as an active verb, for a case where the utterer does
NOT, as in the case of implicaturum, mean MORE than he says, but LESS. Grice’s
point is a subtle one. It involves his concession on something like an
explicatum, but alsoo on something like Moore’s entailment. If the ‘doxastic
condition’ is entailed by “intending that…,’ an utterer U may STILL use, in an
‘ordinary’ fashion, a strong ‘intending that…’ in a scenario where it is common
ground between the utterer U and his addressee A that the probability of ‘p’
being realised is lower than 0.5. The expression of the psychological state or
attitude is loose, since the utterer is, as it were, dropping an ‘entailment’
that applies in a use of ‘intending that’ where that ‘common-ground’ assumption
is absent. One reason may be echoic. Jill may think that she can succeed in
climbing Mt. Everest; she herself has used ‘intend.’ When that information is
transmitted, the strong psychological verb is kept when the doxastic constraint
is no longer shared by the utterer U and his addressee A (Like an implicaturum,
a disimplicaturum has to be recognised as such to count as one. No such thing as an ‘unwanted’ disimplicaturum.‘motivate’Sometimes,
it would seem that, for Grice, the English philosopher of English
‘ordinary-language’ philosophy, English is not enough! Grice would amuse at
Berkeley seminars, with things like, ‘A pirot potches o as fang, or potches o
and o’ as F-id,’ just to attract his addressee’s attention. The full passage,
in what Grice calls, after Carnap, pirotese, reads: “A pirot can be said to
potch of some obble x as fang or feng; also to cotch of x, or some obble o, as
fang or feng; or to cotch of one obble o and another obble o’ as being fid to
one another.” Grice’s deciphering, with ‘pirot,” a tribute to Carnap – and
Locke -- as any agent, and an ‘obble’ as an object. Grice borrows, but does not
return, the ‘pirot’ from Carnap (for whom pirots karulise elatically – Carnap’s
example of a syntactically well-formed formula in Introduction to Semantics).
Grice uses ‘pirotese’ ‘to potch’ as a correlate for ‘perceive,’ such as the
factive ‘see’ and ‘to cotch’ as a correlate for the similarly factive
‘know.’While ‘perceive’ strictly allows for a ‘that’-clause (as in Grice
analysis of “I perceive that the pillar box is red” in “The causal theory of
perception”), for simplificatory purposes, Grice is using ‘to potch’ as
applying directly to an object, which Grice rephrases as an ‘obble.’ Since some
perceptual feature or other is required in a predication of ‘perceiving’ and
‘potching,’ ‘feng’ is introduced as a perceptual predicate. And since pirots
should also be allowed to perceive an ‘obble’ o in some relation with another
‘obble’ o2, Grice introduces the dyadic ‘relational’ feature ‘fid.’ Grice’s exegesis reads: “‘To potch’ is
something like ‘to perceive,’ whereas ‘to cotch’ is something like ‘to think.’
‘Feng’ and ‘fang’ are possible descriptions, much like our adjectives; ‘fid’ is
a possible relation between ‘obbles.’”).
At this point, Grice has been made, trans-territorially, the President
of the American Philosophical Association, and is ready to give his
Presidential Address (now reprinted in his Conception of Value, for Clarendon.
He chooses ‘philosophical psychology’ It’s when Grice goes on to play now with
the neo-Wittgensteinian issues of incorrigibility and privileged access, that
issues of intentio seconda become prominent.
For any psychological attitude ψ1, if U holds it, U holds, as
a matter of what Grice calls ‘genitorial construction,’ a meta-psychological
attitude, ψ2, a seconda intentio if ever there was one, -- Grice
even uses the numeral ‘2’ -- that has, as its content followed the second
‘that’-clause, the very first psychological attitude ψ1. The general
schema being given below, with an instance of specification: ‘ψup ⊃ ψuψup,’
and ‘if U wills that p, U wills that U wills that p.’ The interesting bit, from
the perspective of our exploration of ‘intentio seconda,’ is that, if, alla
Peano, we apply this to itself, as in the anti-Gettier cases Grice discussed
earlier, we end with an ad-infinitum clause. It was Judith Baker, who earned
her doctorate under Grice at Berkeley who sees this clearlier than everyone
(She was a regular contributor to the Kant Society in Germany). Baker’s
publications are, like those of her tutor, scarce. But in a delightful
contribution to the Grice festschrift, “Do one’s motives have to be pure?” (in
Grandy/Warner 1986), Baker explores the crucial importance of that ad-infinitum
chain of intentiones secondæ as it applies to questions of not alethic but
practical value or satisfactoriness. Consider ‘ought’. Grice would say that
‘must’ is aequi-vocal, i.e. it is not that ‘must’ has an alethic ‘sense’ and a
practical ‘sense.’ Only “one” must, if one must! (As Grice jokes, “Who needs
ichthyological necessity?”). Baker notes
that the ad-infinitum chain may explain how ‘duty’ ‘cashes out’ in ‘interest.’
Both Grice and Baker are avowed Kantotelians. By allowing ‘duty’ to cash out in
interest they are merging Aristotle’s utilitarian teleology with Kant’s
deontology, and succeeding! It is possible to symbolize Grice’s and Baker’s
proposal. If there is a “p” SUCH AS, at some point in the iteration of willing
and intentiones secondæ, the agent is not willing to accept it, this blocks the
potential Kantian universalizability of the content of a teleological attitude
“p,” stripping “p” of any absolute value status that it may otherwise attain.In
Grice’s reductive analysis of ‘mean,’ ‘know,’ ‘want,’ ‘intend,’ and ‘motivate,’
we witness the subtlety of his approach that is only made possible from the
recognition of Aristotle’s insight back in “De Sophisticis Elenchis” to Kant’s
explorations on the purity of motives. It should not surprise us. It’s Grice’s
nod, no doubt, to an unjustly neglected philosopher, who should be neglected no
more.ReferencesBlackburn, S. W. 1984. Spreading the words: groundings in the
philosophy of language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Darwin, Charles. 1872.
The expression of emotions in man and animals. London: Murray. Grandy, R. E.
and R. O. Warner 1986. Philosophical grounds of rationality: intentions,
categories, ends. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Grice, H. P. 1948. Meaning, The
Oxford Philosophical Society. Repr. in Grice 1989. Grice, H. P. 1961. The
causal theory of perception, The Aristotelian Society. Repr. in Grice 1989.
Grice, H. P. 1967. Logic and Conversation, The William James lectures. Repr. in
a revised 1987 form in Grice 1989. Grice, H. P. 1969. Vacuous Names, in
Davidson and Hintikka, Words and objections. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. Grice, H.
P. 1971. Intention and uncertainty, The British Academy. Oxford: Oxford
University Press. Grice, H. P. 1975. How pirots karulise elatically: some
simpler ways, The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC MSS 90/135c, The Bancroft Library,
University of California, Berkeley. Grice, H. P. 1982. Meaning Revisited, in N.
V. Smith, Mutual knowledge. London: Croom Helm, repr. in Grice 1989. Grice,
H.P. 1987. Retrospective epilogue, in Studies in the Way of Words. Grice, H. P.
1989. Studies in the way of words. London and Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press. Hart, H. L. A. and S. N. Hampshire 1958. Intention, decision,
and certainty, Mind, 67:1-12.Kemmerling, A. M. 1986. Utterer’s meaning
revisited, in Grandy/Warner 1986. Kneale, W. C. and M. Kneale. 1966. The
development of logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Pecocke, C. A. B. 1989. Transcendental Arguments in the Theory of Content: An Inaugural Lecture Delivered
Before the University of Oxford on 16 May 1989. Oxford University Press.
Prichard, H. A. 1968. Moral Obligation and Duty and Interest. Essays and
Lectures, edited by
W. D. Ross and J. O. Urmson. Oxford: Oxford University. Stevenson,
C. L. 1944. Ethics and language. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press.
Strawson, P. F. 1964 Intention and convention in speech acts, The Philosophical
Review, repr. in Logico-Linguistic Papers, London, Methuen, 1971, pp. 149-169 as Blackburn puts
it in his discussion of Grice in the intention-based chapter of his “Spreading
the word: groundings in the philosophy of language.” Intentio seconda or
obliqua bears heavily on Grice’s presentation for the Oxford Philosophical
Society. The motivation behind Grice’s analysis pertains to philosophical
methodology. Grice is legitimizing an ascription of ‘mean’ to a rational agent,
such as … a philosopher. This very ascription Grice finds to be ‘seemingly
denied by Wittgenstein’ (Grice 1986). As an exponent of what he would later and
in jest dub “The Post-War Oxonian School of ‘Ordinary-Language’ Philosophy,”
Grice engages in a bit of language botany, and dealing with the intricacies of
‘communicative’ uses of “mean.” Interestingly, and publicly – although a
provision is in order here – Grice acknowledges emotivist Stevenson, who
apparently taught Grice about ‘metabolic’ uses of “mean.” Stevenson, who read
English as a minor at Yale, would not venture to apply ‘mean’ to moans!
Realising it as a colloquial extension, he is allowed to use ‘mean,’ but in
scare quotes only! (“Smith’s reduced temperature ‘means’ that he is is
convalescent.” “There is a sense, to be sure, in
which a groan “means“ something, just a reduced temperature may at times ”mean”
convalescence.” Stevenson 1944:38). Close enough but no cigar. Stevenson
has ‘groan,’ which at least rhymes with ‘moan.’ (As for the proviso, Grice
never ‘meant’ to ‘publish’ his talk on ‘Meaning,’ but one of his tutees
submitted for publication, and on acceptance, Grice allowed the publication).
In “Meaning” Grice does not provide a conceptual analysis for, ‘by moaning, U
means [simpliciter] that p.’ He will in his “Meaning Revisited” – the
metabolical scare quotes are justified on two counts: ‘By moaning U means that
p’ is legitimized on the basis of the generic ‘x ‘means’ y iff x is a
consequence of y.’ But it is also justified on the basis that there is a
continuum between U’s involuntarily moaning thereby meaning that he is in pain,
and U’s voluntarily moaning, thereby ‘communicating’ that he is in pain.
However, and more importantly for our exploration of the ‘intentum,’ Grice
hastens to add that he does not agree with Stevenson’s purely ‘causal’ account.
The main reason is not ‘anti-naturalistic.’ It is just that Grice sees
Stevenson’s proposal as as involving a vicious circle. Typically, Grice
extrapolates the relevant quote from Stevenson, slightly out of context. Grice
refers to Stevenson’s appeal to "an elaborate process of conditioning
attending … communication."Grice: “If we have to take seriously the second
part of the qualifying phrase ("attending … communication"),
Stevenson’s account of meaning is obviously circular. We might just as well
say, "U means” if “U communicates,” which, though true, is not helpful. It
MIGHT be helpful for Cicero translating from Grecian to Roman: ‘com-municatio’
indeed translates a Grecian turn of phrase involving ‘what is common.’ f.
“con-” and root “mu-,” to bind; cf.: immunis, munus, moenia.’And the suggestion
would be helpful if we say that to ‘communicate,’ or ‘mean,’ is just to bring
some intentum to be allotted ‘common ground,’ because of the psi-transmission
it is shared between the emissor and his intended addressee. This one hopes is
both true AND ‘helpful.’ In any case, Grice’s tutee Strawson later
found Grice’s elucidation of utterer’s meaning to be ‘objection-proof’
(Starwson and Wiggins, 2001) in terms of a set of necessary and sufficient
conditions, of an utterer or emissor E meaning that p, by uttering ‘x,’ and appealing
to primary and secondary intentionality. But is Grice’s intentionalism a sort
of behaviourism? Grice denies that in “Method” calling ‘behaviourism’ ‘silly.
Grice further explores intentio obliqua as it pertains to his remarks towards a
general theory of “re-presentation.” The place where this excursus takes place
is crucial. It is his Valediction to his compilation of essays, Studies in the
Way of Words, posthumously published. At this stage, he must have felt that,
what he once regarded krypto-technic in Peirce, is no more! Grice has already
identified in that ‘Valediction’ many strands of his philosophical thought, and
concludes his re-assessment of his ‘philosophy of language’ and semiotics with
an attempt to provide some general remarks about ‘to represent’ in general,
perhaps to counter the allegations of vicious circularity which his approach
had received, seeing that “p” features, as a ‘gap-sign,’ as the content of both
an ‘expression’ and a ‘psychological’ attitude. In trying to reconcile his austere
views on “Meaning,” back in that evening at the Oxford Philosophical Society,
where he distinguished two senses of ‘mean’ (“Smoke ‘means’ fire,” and ““Smoke”
means ‘smoke’”). By focusing on the most general of verbs for a psychological
state or attitude, ‘to represent,’ that even allows for a non-psychological
reading, Grice wants to be seen as answering the challenge of an alleged
vicious circle with which his intention-based approach is usually associated.
The secondary-intentional non-iconic mode of representation rests on a prior
iconic mode and can be understood as ‘pre-conventional,’ without any explicit
recourse to the features we associate with a developed system of communication.
Grice needs no ‘language of thought’ or sermo mentalis alla Ockham there. Grice
allows that one can communicate fully without the need to use what more
conventional philosophers call ‘a language.’ Artists do it all the time! The passage from intentio prima to full
intentio seconda is, for Grice, gradual and complex. Grice means to adhere with
‘ordinary’ discourse, in its implicatura and dis-implicaata. The passage also
adhering to a functionalist approach qua ‘method in philosophical psychology,’
as he’d prefer, that needs not to postulate a full-blown ‘linguistic entity’ as
the object of intentional thought. In this respect, it is worth mentioning the
work of C. A. B. Peacocke, who knew Grice from his Oxford days and later joined
his seminars at Berkeley, and who has developed this line of thought in a
better fashion than less careful philosophers. Grice’s programme has
occasionally, and justly, been compared with phenomenological approaches to
expression and communication, such as Marty’s. It is hoped that the previous
notes have shed some light on those aspects where this interface can further be
elaborated. Even as we leave an intentio seconda to resume the discussion for a
longer day. In his explorations on the embedding of intensional concepts, Grice
should be inspirational to philosophers in more than one way, but especially in
the one that he favoured most: the problematicity of it all. As he put it in
another context, when defending absolute value. “Such
a defence of absolute value is of course, bristling with unsolved or
incompletely solved problems. I do not find this thought daunting. If
philosophy generated no new problems it would be dead, because it would be
finished; and if it recurrently regenerated the same old problems it would not
be alive because it could never begin. So those who still look to philosophy
for their bread-and-butter should pray that the supply of new problems never
dries up.” (Grice 1991). In the Graeco-Roman tradition, philosophers started to
use ‘intentio prima,’ ‘intentio secunda,’ ‘intentio tertia,’ and “… ad
infinitum,” as they would put it. In post-war Oxford, English philosopher H. P.
Grice felt the need. The formalist he was, he found subscribing numbers to
embedded intentions has a strong appeal for him. Grice’s main motivation is in
the philosophy of language, but as ancillary towards solving this or that
problem concerning the ‘linguistic’ methodology of his day. To appreciate
Grice’s contribution one need to abstract a little from his own historical
circumstances, or rather, place them in the proper context, and connect it with
the general history of philosophy. As a matter of history, ‘intentio prima,’
or ‘recta,’ as opposed to ‘obliqua,’ is part of Nicolai Hartmann’s ‘mediaeval
revival,’ as a reaction to mediaevalism having made scorn by the likes of
Rabelais that amused D. P. Henry. For the mediaeval philosopher, to use Grice’s
symbolism, was concerned with whether a chimaera could eat ‘I2,’ a
second intention. The mediaeval philosopher’s implicaturum seems to be that a
chimaera can easily eat ‘I1.’ Such a ‘quaestio subtilissima,’
Rabelais jokes. If ‘I1,’ or, better, for simplificatory purposes, ‘IR’
is a specific state, stance, or attitude of the ‘soul,’ ‘ψ1’ or ‘ψR’
directed towards its ‘de re’ ‘intentum,’ or ‘prae-sentatum,’ of the noumenon,
‘IO,’ ‘intentio obliqua,’ is a state, stance, or attitude of the
‘soul,’ of the same genus, ‘ψ2,’ or ‘ψS’ directed towards
‘ψR,’ its ‘de sensu’ ‘intentum’ now ‘re-prae-sentatum’ of the
phainomenon or ob-jectum (Abelard translates Aristotle’s ‘per divisionem’ as
‘de re’ and ‘per compositionem’ and ‘per conjunctionem’ by ‘de sensu,’ and ‘per
Soph. Elen., Kneale and Kneale, 1966). Grice’s intentionalism has been widely
discussed, but the defense he himself makes of intensionalism (versus
extensionalism) has proved inspiring, as when he assumes as an attending
commentary to his reductive analysis of the state of affairs by which the emissor
communicates that p, that he is putting forward “the legitimacy of [the]
application of [existential generalization] to a statement the expression of
which contains such [an] "intensional" verb[…] as "intend"
(Grice 1989: 116 ). The expression ‘de sensu’ is due to Abelard, but Russell
likes it. While serving as Prince Regent of England in 1815, George IV casually
remarks his wish to meet ‘the author of Waverley’ in the flesh. The Prince was
being funny, you see. The prince would not know this, but when his press
becomes embroiled in pecuniary difficulties, Scotts set out to write a
cash-cow. The result is Waverley, a novel which did not name its author. It is
a tale of the last Jacobite rebellion in England, the “Forty-Five.” The novel
meets with considerable success. The next year, Scott. There follows a sequel,
the same general vein. Mindful of his
reputation, Scotts maintains the anonymous habit he displays with Waverley, and
publishes the sequel under “the Author of Waverley.” The identity “Author of
Waverley” = “Scott” is widely rumoured, and Scott is given the honour of dining with George,
Prince Regent, who had wished to meet “Author of Waverley” in the flesh for a
‘snug little dinner’ at Carleton, on hearing ‘the author of Waverley’ was in
town. The use of a descriptor may lead to the implicaturum that His Majesty is
p’rhaps not sure that ‘the author of Waverley’ has a name, and isR
Scott. Lack of certainty is one thing, yet, to quote from Russell, “an interest
in the law of identity can hardly be attributed to the first gentleman of
Europe.” Grice admired Russell profusely and one of his essays is wittily
entitled, “Definite descriptions in Russell and in the Vernacular,” so his
explorations of ‘intentio’ ‘de sensu’ have an intrinsic interest. Keywords: H. Paul Grice, intentio seconda, implicaturum,
intentionalism, intentum, intentum de sensu,
‘that’-clause, the recte-oblique distinction. Grice explored issues of intentum
de sensu in various areas. First, ‘meaning.’ Second, ‘knowing.’ Third, ‘wanting.’
Fourth, ‘intending,’ Fifth, pirots, with incorrigibility and privileged access.
Sixth, morality and the regressus. Seventh, the continuum and the unity. With Grice, it all
starts, roughly, when Grice comes up with a topic for a talk at The Oxford Philosophical
Society.The Society is holding one of those meetings, and Grice thinks of
presenting a few conclusions he had reached at his seminars on C. S.
Peirce.What’s the good of an Oxford don of keeping tidy lecture notes if you
will not be able to lecture to a philosophical addressee? Peirce is the
philosopher on whom Grice choses to lecture. In part, for “not being
particularly popular on these shores,” and in part because Grice noted the
‘heretic’ in Peirce with which he could identify.Granted, at this stage, Grice
disliked the un-Englishness of some of Peirce’s over-Latinate jargon, what
Grice finds the ‘krypto-technic.’ ‘Sign,’ ‘symbol,’ ‘icon,’ and the rest of
them!Instead, Grice thinks, initially for the sake of his tutees and students –
he was university lecturer -- sticking with the simpler, ‘ordinary’, short
English lexeme ‘mean.’A. M. Kemmerling, of all people, who wrote the obituary
for Grice for Synthese, has precisely cast doubts on the ‘universal’ validity
of Grice’s proposed conceptual reductive analysis, notably in his Ph.D
dissertation on ‘Meinen.’ Note the irony
in Kemmerling’s title: Was Grice mit "Meinen" meint - Eine
Rekonstruktion der Griceschen Analyse rationaler
Kommunikation.” Nothing jocular in the subtitle, for this indeed is a
reconstruction of ‘rational’ communication. The funny bit is in “Was mit
“Meinen” Grice meint”! In that very phrase, which is rhetorical, and allows for
an answer, because ‘meinen’ is both mentioned and used, Kemmerling allows that
he is ‘buying’ Grice’s idea that his reductive analysis of ‘mean’ applies to
German ‘meinen.’ Kemmerling is also pointing to the ‘primacy’ (to use Suppes’s
phrase) of ‘utterer’s’ or ‘emissor’s “communicatum” or ‘Meinung.” Kemmerling
advertises his interest in exploring on what _Grice_ means – by uttering
‘meinen,’ almost! As Kemmerling notes, German ‘meinen,’ cognate via
common Germanic with English ‘mean,’ (cf. Frisian ‘mein,’ – and Hazzlitt,
“Bread, butter, and green cheese, very good English, very good cheese”) is none
other than ‘mean’ that Grice means. And ‘Grice means’ is the only literal, i.
e. non-metabolic use of the verb Grice allows – as applied to a rational agent,
which features in the subtitle to Kemmerling’s dissertation. Thus one reads in
Kluge, “Etymologische Wörterbuch der deutschen Sprache, 1881, of “meinen,” rendered by J. F. Davis as ‘to think, opine, mean,’
from a MHG used to indicate, in
Davis’s rendition, ‘to direct one's thoughts to, have in view, aim at,
be affected towards a person, love,’ OHG meinen, meinan,
‘to mean, think, say, declare.’ = OS mênian, Du. meenen,
OE mœ̂nan, E mean (to this Anglo-Saxon mœ̂nan, cf. prob. moan – I know your meaning from your moaning),
all from WGmc. meinen, mainjan, ‘mênjan,’ and cognate with ‘man,’ ‘to think’ (cf. ‘mahnen,’ ‘Mann,’ and ‘Minne’). Kemmerling
is very apropos, because Grice engaged in philosophical discussion with him, as
testified by his perceptive contribution to P. G. R. I. C. E. (Kemmerling,
1986). On top, in his presentation for the Oxford Philosophical Society, Grice
wants to restrict the philosophical interest to ‘de sensu,’ the ‘that’-clause
(cf. the recte-oblique distinction), viz. not just ‘what Grice means,’ if this
is going to be expaned as ‘something wonderful.’ Not enough for Grice. It has
to be expanded, for the thing to have philosophical interest into a
‘propositional clause,’, an ‘intensional’ context, i. e., ‘Grice means that…’
Grice cavalierly dismisses other use of ‘mean,’ – notably the ubiquitous, ‘mean
to…’ – He will later explain his reason for this. It was after William James
provoked Prichard. For William James uttered: “I will that the distant table
slides on the floor toward me. It doesn’t’. Prichard turns this into the
conceptual priority of ‘will that…’ for which Grice gives him the credit he
deserved at a later lecture now on his being appointed a Fellow of The British
Academy (Grice, 1971). Strictly, what
Grice does in the Oxford Philosophical Socieety presentation is to distinguish
between various ‘mean’ and end up focusing on ‘mean’ as followed by a
‘that’-clause. In the typical Oxonian fashion, that Grice borrows (but never
returns) from J. C. Wilson, Grice has the IO as ‘meaning that
so-and-so’ (Grice, 1989: 217). Grice explicitly displays the primacy of a
reductive analysis of the conceptual circumstances involving an emissor
(Anglo-Saxon ‘utterer’) who ‘means’ that p. It will be a longer ‘shaggy-dog’
story Grice tells when he crosses the divide from ‘propositional’ (p) to
‘predicative’ ascriptions (“By uttering ‘Fido is shaggy,’ Grice means that the
dog is hairy-coated (Grice 1989). Grice notes that ‘metabolically,’ “mean,” at
least in English, can be applied to various other things, sometimes even
involving a ‘that’-clause. “By delivering his budget, the major means that we
will have a hard year.’ Grice finds that ‘but we won’t’ turns him into a
self-contradicter. In Grice’s usage, ‘x ‘means’ y’ iff ‘y is a consequence
[consequentia] of x’ --. Quite a departure from Old Frisian. If Hume’s
objection to the use of the verb ‘cause,’ is that it covers animistic beliefs
(“Charles I’s decapitation willed his death”), English allows for disimplicated
or loose ‘metabolic’ uses of ‘will’ (“It ‘will’ rain”) and ‘mean’ (Grice’s
moaning means that he is in pain).
desideratum: Qua volition,
a mental event involved with the initiation of action. ‘To will’ is sometimes
taken to be the corresponding verb form of ‘volition’. The concept of volition
is rooted in modern philosophy; contemporary philosophers have transformed it
by identifying volitions with ordinary mental events, such as intentions, or
beliefs plus desires. Volitions, especially in contemporary guises, are often
taken to be complex mental events consisting of cognitive, affective, and
conative elements. The conative element is the impetus – the underlying
motivation – for the action. A velleity is a conative element insufficient by
itself to initiate action. The will is a faculty, or set of abilities, that
yields the mental events involved in initiating action. There are three primary
theories about the role of volitions in action. The first is a reductive
account in which action is identified with the entire causal sequence of the
mental event (the volition) causing the bodily behavior. J. S. Mill, for
example, says: “Now what is action? Not one thing, but a series of two things:
the state of mind called a volition, followed by an effect. . . . [T]he two
together constitute the action” (Logic). Mary’s raising her arm is Mary’s
mental state causing her arm to rise. Neither Mary’s volitional state nor her
arm’s rising are themselves actions; rather, the entire causal sequence (the
“causing”) is the action. The primary difficulty for this account is
maintaining its reductive status. There is no way to delineate volition and the
resultant bodily behavior without referring to action. There are two
non-reductive accounts, one that identifies the action with the initiating
volition and another that identifies the action with the effect of the
volition. In the former, a volition is the action, and bodily movements are
mere causal consequences. Berkeley advocates this view: “The Mind . . . is to
be accounted active in . . . so far forth as volition is included. . . . In
plucking this flower I am active, because I do it by the motion of my hand,
which was consequent upon my volition” (Three Dialogues). In this century,
Prichard is associated with this theory: “to act is really to will something”
(Moral Obligation, 1949), where willing is sui generis (though at other places
Prichard equates willing with the action of mentally setting oneself to do
something). In this sense, a volition is an act of will. This account has come
under attack by Ryle (Concept of Mind, 1949). Ryle argues that it leads to a
vicious regress, in that to will to do something, one must will to will to do
it, and so on. It has been countered that the regress collapses; there is
nothing beyond willing that one must do in order to will. Another criticism of
Ryle’s, which is more telling, is that ‘volition’ is an obscurantic term of
art; “[volition] is an artificial concept. We have to study certain specialist
theories in order to find out how it is to be manipulated. . . . [It is like]
‘phlogiston’ and ‘animal spirits’ . . . [which] have now no utility” (Concept
of Mind). Another approach, the causal theory of action, identifies an action
with the causal consequences of volition. Locke, e.g., says: “Volition or
willing is an act of the mind directing its thought to the production of any
action, and thereby exerting its power to produce it. . . . [V]olition is
nothing but that particular determination of the mind, whereby . . . the mind
endeavors to give rise, continuation, or stop, to any action which it takes to
be in its power” (Essay concerning Human Understanding). This is a functional
account, since an event is an action in virtue of its causal role. Mary’s arm
rising is Mary’s action of raising her arm in virtue of being caused by her
willing to raise it. If her arm’s rising had been caused by a nervous twitch,
it would not be action, even if the bodily movements were photographically the
same. In response to Ryle’s charge of obscurantism, contemporary causal
theorists tend to identify volitions with ordinary mental events. For example,
Davidson takes the cause of actions to be beliefs plus desires and Wilfrid
Sellars takes volitions to be intentions to do something here and now. Despite
its plausibility, however, the causal theory faces two difficult problems: the
first is purported counterexamples based on wayward causal chains connecting
the antecedent mental event and the bodily movements; the second is provision
of an enlightening account of these mental events, e.g. intending, that does
justice to the conative element. See also ACTION THEORY, FREE WILL PROBLEM, PRACTICAL
REASONING, WAYWARD CAUSAL CHAIN. M.B. volition volition. Grice makes a double use of this. It should be thus two
entries. There’s the conversational desideratum, where a desideratum is like a
maxim or an imperative – and then there are two specific desiderata: the
desideratum of conversational clarity, and the desideratum of conversational
candour. Grice was never sure what adjective to use for the ‘desiderative.’ He
liked buletic. He liked desideratum because it has the co-relate
‘consideratum,’ for belief. He uses
‘deriderative’ and a few more! Of course what he means is a sub-psychological
modality, or rather a ‘soul.’ So he would apply it ‘primarily’ to the soul, as
Plato and Aristotle does. The ‘psyche’, or ‘anima’ is what is ‘desiderativa.’
The Grecians are pretty confused about this (but ‘boulemaic’ and ‘buletic’ are
used), and the Romans didn’t help. Grice is concerned with a
rational-desiderative, that takes a “that”-clause (or oratio obliqua), and qua
constructivist, he is also concerned with a pre-rational desiderative (he has
an essay on “Needs and Wants,” and his detailed example in “Method” is a
squarrel (sic) who needs a nut. On top, while Grice suggest s that it goes both
ways: the doxastic can be given a reductive analaysis in terms of the buletic,
and the buletic in terms of the doxastic, he only cares to provide the former.
Basically, an agent judges that p, if his willing that p correlates to a state
of affairs that satisfies his desires. Since he does not provide a reductive
analysis for Prichard’s willing-that, one is left wondering. Grice’s position
is that ‘willing that…’ attains its ‘sense’ via the specification, as a
theoretical concept, in some law in the folk-science that agents use to explain
their behaviour. Grice gets subtler when he deals with mode-markers for the
desiderative: for these are either utterer-oriented, or addressee-oriented, and
they may involve a buletic attitude itself, or a doxastic attitude. When
utterer-addressed, utterer wills that utterer wills that p. There is no closure
here, and indeed, a regressus ad infinitum is what Grice wants, since this
regressus allows him to get univeersabilisability, in terms of conceptual,
formal, and applicational kinds of generality. In this he is being Kantian, and
Hareian. While Grice praises Kantotle, Aristotle here would stay unashamedly
‘teleological,’ and giving priority to a will that may not be universalisable,
since it’s the communitarian ‘good’ that matters. what does Grice have to say
about our conversational practice? L and S have “πρᾶξις,” from “πράσσω,” and
which they render as ‘moral action,’ oποίησις, τέχνη;” “oποιότης,” “ἤθη καὶ
πάθη καὶ π.,” “oοἱ πολιτικοὶ λόγοι;” “ἔργῳ καὶ πράξεσιν, οὐχὶ λόγοις” Id.6.3;
ἐν ταῖς πράξεσι ὄντα τε καὶ πραττόμενα, “exhibited in actual life,” action in
drama, “oλόγος; “μία π. ὅλη καὶ τελεία.” With practical Grice means buletic.
Praxis involves acting, and surely Grice presupposes acting. By uttering, i. e.
by the act of uttering, expression x, U m-intends that p. Grice occasionally
refers to action and behaviour as the thing which an ascription of a
psychological state explains. Grice prefers the idiom of soul. Theres the
ratiocinative soul. Within the ratiocinative, theres the executive soul and the
merely administrative soul. Cicero had to translate Aristotle into prudentia,
every time Aristotle talked of phronesis. Grice was aware that the
terminology by Kant can be confusing. Kant used ‘pure’ reason for reason in the
doxastic realm. The critique by Kant of practical reason is hardly
symmetrical to his critique of doxastic reason. Grice, with his
æqui-vocality thesis of must (must crosses the buletic-boulomaic/doxastic
divide), Grice is being more of a symmetricalist. The buletic, boulomaic, or
volitive, is a part of the soul, as is the doxatic or judicative. And
judicative is a trick because there is such a thing as a value judgement, or an
evaluative judgement, which is hardly doxastic. Grice plays with two
co-relative operators: desirability versus probability. Grice invokes the exhibitive/protreptic
distinction he had introduced in the fifth James lecture, now applied to
psychological attitudes themselves. This Grice’s attempt is to tackle the
Kantian problem in the Grundlegung: how to derive the categorical imperative
from a counsel of prudence. Under the assumption that the protasis is Let the
agent be happy, Grice does not find it obtuse at all to construct a
universalisable imperative out of a mere motive-based counsel of prudence.
Grice has an earlier paper on pleasure which relates. The derivation involves
seven steps. Grice proposes seven steps in the derivation. 1. It is a
fundamental law of psychology that, ceteris paribus, for any creature R, for
any P and Q, if R wills P Λ judges if P, P as a result of Q, R wills
Q. 2. Place this law within the scope of a "willing" operator: R
wills for any P Λ Q, if R wills P Λ judges that if P, P as
a result of Q, R wills Q. 3. wills turns to should. If rational, R will have to
block unsatisfactory (literally) attitudes. R should (qua rational) judge for
any P Λ Q, if it is satisfactory to will that P Λ it is
satisfactory to judge that if P, P as a result of Q, it is sastisfactory to
will that Q. 4. Marking the mode: R should (qua rational) judge for any
P Λ Q, if it is satisfactory that !P Λ that if it .P, .P
only as a result of Q, it is satisfactory that !Q. 5. via (p & q
-> r) -> (p -> (q -> r)): R should (qua rational)
judge for any P Λ Q, if it is satisfactory that if .P, .P only
because Q, i is satisfactory that, if let it be that P, let it be that Q. 6. R
should (qua rational) judge for any P Λ Q, if P, P only because p
yields if let it be that P, let it be that Q. 7. For any P Λ Q if P,
P only because Q yields if let it be that P, let it be that Q. Grice was
well aware that a philosopher, at Oxford, needs to be a philosophical
psychologist. So, wanting and needing have to be related to willing. A plant
needs water. A floor needs sweeping. So need is too broad. So is want, a
non-Anglo-Saxon root for God knows what. With willing things get closer to the
rational soul. There is willing in the animal soul. But when it comes to
rational willing, there must be, to echo Pritchard, a conjecture, some doxastic
element. You cannot will to fly, or will that the distant chair slides over the
floor toward you. So not all wants and needs are rational willings, but then
nobody said they would. Grice is interested in emotion in his power structure
of the soul. A need and a want may count as an emotion. Grice was never too
interested in needing and wanting because they do not take a that-clause. He
congratulates Urmson for having introduced him to the brilliant willing that …
by Prichard. Why is it, Grice wonders, that many ascriptions of buletic states
take to-clause, rather than a that-clause? Even mean, as ‘intend.’ In this
Grice is quite different from Austin, who avoids the that-clause. The
explanation by Austin is very obscure, like those of all grammars on the
that’-clause, the ‘that’ of ‘oratio obliqua’ is not in every way similar to the
‘that’-clause in an explicit performative formula. Here the utterer is not
reporting his own ‘oratio’ in the first person singular present indicative
active. Incidentally, of course, it is not in the least necessary that an
explicit performative verb should be followed by a ‘that’-clause. In important
classes of cases it is followed by ‘to . . .,’ or by or nothing, e. g. ‘I
apologize for…,’ ‘I salute you.’ Now many of these verbs appear to be quite
satisfactory pure performatives. Irritating though it is to have them as such,
linked with clauses that look like statements, true or false, e. g., when I say
‘I prophesy that …,’ ‘I concede that …’,
‘I postulate that …,’ the clause following normally looks just like a
statement, but the verb itself seems to be pure performatives. One
may distinguish the performative opening part, ‘I state that …,’ which makes
clear how the utterance is to be taken, that it is a statement, as distinct
from a prediction, etc.), from the bit in the that-clause which is required to
be true or false. However, there are many cases which, as language stands at
present, we are not able to split into two parts in this way, even though the
utterance seems to have a sort of explicit performative in it. Thus, ‘I liken x
to y,’ or ‘I analyse x as y.’ Here we both do the likening and assert that
there is a likeness by means of one compendious phrase of at least a
quasi-performative character. Just to spur us on our way, we may also mention
‘I know that …’, ‘I believe that …’, etc. How complicated are these examples?
We cannot assume that they are purely descriptive, which has Grice talking of
the pseudo-descriptive. Want etymologically means absence; need should be
preferred. The squarrel (squirrel) Toby needs intake of nuts, and youll soon
see gobbling them! There is not much philosophical bibliography on these two
psychological states Grice is analysing. Their logic is interesting. Smith
wants to play cricket. Smith needs to play cricket. Grice is
concerned with the propositional content attached to the want and need
predicate. Wants that sounds harsh; so does need that. Still, there
are propositional attached to the pair above. Smith plays cricket. Grice
took a very cavalier attitude to what linguists spend their lives
analysing. He thought it was surely not the job of the philosopher,
especially from a prestigious university such as Oxford, to deal with the
arbitrariness of grammatical knots attached to this or that English verb. He
rarely used English, but stuck with ordinary language. Surely, he saw
himself in the tradition of Kantotle, and so, aiming at grand philosophical
truths: not conventions of usage, even his own! 1. Squarrel Toby has a
nut, N, in front of him. 2. Toby is short on squarrel food (observed or assumed),
so, 3. Toby wills squarrel food (by postulate of Folk Pyschological
Theory θ connecting willing with intake of N). 4. Toby prehends a nut
as in front (from (1) by Postulate of Folk Psychological Theory θ, if it
is assumed that nut and in front are familiar to Toby). 5. Toby joins squarrel
food with gobbling, nut, and in front (i.e. Toby judges gobbling, on nut in
front, for squarrel food (by Postulate of Folk Psychological
Theory θ with the aid of prior observation. So, from 3, 4 and 5, 6.
Tobby gobbles; and since a nut is in front of him, gobbles the nut in front of
him. The system of values of the society to which the agent belongs forms the
external standard for judging the relative importance of the commitments by the
agent. There are three dimensions of value: universally human, cultural that
vary with societies and times; and personal that vary with individuals. Each
dimension has a standard for judging the adequacy of the relevant values. Human
values are adequate if they satisfy basic needs; cultural values are adequate
if they provide a system of values that sustains the allegiance of the
inhabitants of a society; and personal values are adequate if the conceptions
of well‐being formed out of them enable individuals to live
satisfying lives. These values conflict and our well‐being requires some way of settling their conflicts, but
there is no universal principle for settling the conflicts; it can only be done
by attending to the concrete features of particular conflicts. These features
vary with circumstances and values. Grice reads Porter.The idea of the value
chain is based on the process view of organizations, the idea of seeing a
manufacturing (or service) organization as a system, made up of subsystems each
with inputs, transformation processes and outputs. Inputs, transformation
processes, and outputs involve the acquisition and consumption of resources –
money, labour, materials, equipment, buildings, land, administration and
management. How value chain activities are carried out determines costs and affects
profits.In his choice of value system and value sub-system, Grice is defending
objectivity, since it is usually the axiological relativist who uses such a
pretentious phrasing! More than a value may co-ordinate in a system. One such
is eudæmonia (cf. system of ends). The problem for Kant is the reduction of the
categorical imperative to the hypothetical or
suppositional imperative. For Kant, a value tends towards the
Subjectsive. Grice, rather, wants to offer a metaphysical defence of objective
value. Grice called the manual of conversational maxims the Conversational
Immanuel. The keyword to search the H. P. Grice is ‘will,’ and ‘volitional,’
even ‘ill-will,’ (“Metaphysics and ill-will,” s. V, c. 7-f. 28) and
‘benevolence’ (vide below under ‘conversational benevolence”). Also
‘desirability’: “Modality, desirability, and probability,” s. V, c. 8-ff.
14-15, and the conference lecture in a different series, “Probability,
desirability, and mood operators,” s. II, c. 2-f.11). Grice makes systematic use of ‘practical’ to
contrast with the ‘alethic,’ too (“Practical reason,” s. V, c. 9-f.1), The H.
P. Grice Papers, BANC.
desideratum of conversational
candour: The key for philosophical
attention here is ‘candour’ but the collocation is delightfully Griceian, “the
desideratum of conversational candour”
where only ‘candour,’ and just about, should be taken seriously. The term
‘desideratum’ has to be taken seriously. It involves freedom. This includes the
maximin. It should be noted that candour is DESIRABLE. There is a desirability
for candour. Candour is not a given. Ditto for clarity. See conversational
desideratum, simpliciter. A rational desideratum is a desideratum by a rational
agent and which he expects from another rational agent. One should make the
strongest move, and on the other hand try not to mislead.Grice's Oxford
"Conversation" Lectures, 1966Grice: Between Self-Love and Benevolence
As I was saying (somewhere), Grice uses "self-love", charmingly
qualified with capitals, as
"Conversational Self-Love", and, less charmingly, "Conversational Benevolence", in
lectures advertised at Oxford, as "Logic and Conversation" that he gave at Oxford in
1964 as "University Lecturer in
Philosophy". He also gave seminars on "Conversational
helpfulness." A number of the lectures by Grice include discussion of
thetypes of behaviour people in general exhibit, and thereforethe types of
expectations[cfr. owings]they might bring to a venture such as a
conversation.Grice suggests that people in general both exhibitand EXPECT a
certain degree of helpfulness [-- alla Rosenschein, epistemic/boulemaic:If A
cognizes that B wills p, then A wills p.]
"from OTHERS" [-- reciprocal vs. reflexive, etc.] usually on
the understanding that such helpfulness does NOT get in the way of particular
goals and does not involve undue effort cf. least effort? - cfr. Hobbes on self-love.
It two people, even complete strangers,are going through a gate, the
expectation isthat the FIRST ONE through will hold thegate open, or at least
leave it open, for thesecond. The expectation is such that todo OTHERWISE
without particular reasonwould be interpreted as RUDE. The type of helpfulness
exhibited andexpected in conversation is more specificbecause of a particular,
although not a unique feature of conversation.It is a COLLABORATIVE venture
betweenthe participants.There is a SHARED aimGrice wonders. His words, Does "helpfulness in something WE ARE
DOING TOGETHER” equate to 'cooperation'?He seems to have decided that it
does. By the later lectures in the series, 'the principle of conversational
helpfulness'has been rebranded the expectation of 'cooperation.' During the
Oxford lectures, Grice develops his account of the precise nature of this
cooperation. It can be seen as governed by certain regularities, or principles,
detailing expected behaviour. The expression'maxim' to describe these
regularities appears relatively late in the lectures.Grice's INITIAL choices of
terms are 'objectives' and 'desiderata'.He was particularly fond of the latter.
He was interested in detailing the desirable forms of behaviour for the purpose
of achieving a joint goal of the conversation. Initially, Grice posits TWO such
desiderata. Those relating to candour on the one hand and clarity on the other.
The desideratum of candour contains his general PRINCIPLE of making the
strongest (MAX) possible statement and, as a LIMITING (MAX) factor on this, the
suggestion that speakers should try not to mislead. (Do not mislead). cfr.
our"We are brothers"-- but not mutual."We are married to each
other". "You _are_ a boor".----The desideratum of conversational
clarity concerns the manner of expression. [His later reference to Modus or Mode
as used by Kant as one of the four
categories] for any conversational contribution. It includes the IMPORTANT
expectations of relevance to understanding and also insists that the main
import of an utterance be clear and explicit. (“Explicate!”) These two factors
are constantly to be WEIGHED against two
FUNDAMENTAL and SOMETIMES COMPETING DEMANDS. Contributions to a conversation
are aimed towards the agreed current purposes by the PRINCIPLE of Conversational
Benevolence. The principle of CONVERSATIONAL SELF-LOVE ensures the assumption
on the part of both participants that neither will go to unnecessary trouble
[LEAST EFFORT] in framing their contribution. This has been a topic of interest
to Noh end. In "Conversational Immanuel" Grice tries different ways
of making sense -- it is very easy to do so -- of Grice's distinctions that go
over the head of some linguists I know! Reasonable versus rational for example.
A Rawlsian distinction of sorts. Rational is too weak. We need 'reasonable'.
So, what sort of reasonableness is that which results from this harmonious, we
hope, clash of self-love and benevolence? Grice tried, wittily, to extend the
purposes of conversation to involve MUTUALLY INFLUENCING EACH OTHER -- a
reciprocal. (WoW, ii). And there's a mythical reconstruction of this in his
"Meaning Revisited" which he contributed to this symposium organised
by N. Smith on Mutua knowledge. But issues remains, we hope. The concept of
‘candour’is especially basic for Grice since it is constitutive of what it
means to identify the ‘significatum.’ As he notes, ‘false’ information is no
information. This is serious, because it has to do with the acceptum. A
contribution which is not trustworthy is not deemed a contribution. It is
conceptually impossible to intend to PROVIDE information if you are aware that
you are not being trustworthy and not conveying it. As for the degree of
explicitness, as Grice puts it. Since in communication in a certain fashion all
must be public, if an idea or thesis is heavily obscured, it can no longer be
regarded as having been propounded. This gives acceptum justification to the
correlative desideratum of conversational clarity. On top, if there is a level
of obscurity, the thing is not deemed to have been a communicatum or
significatum. It is all about confidence, you know. U expects A will find him
confident. Thus we find in Short and Lewis, “confīdo,” wich they render as
“to trust confidently in something,” and also, “confide in, rely firmly upon,
to believe, be assured of,” as an enhancing of “sperare,” in Cicero’s Att. 6,
9, 1. Trust and rationality are pre-requisites of conversation. Urmson develops
this. They phrase in Urmson is "implied claim." Whenever U makes a
conversational contribution in a standard context, there is an implied claim to
U being trustworthy and reasonable. What do Grice and Urmson mean by an
"implied claim"? It is obvious enough, but they both love to expand.
Whenever U utters an expression which can be used to convey truth or falsehood
there is an implied claim to trustworthiness by U, unless the situation shows
that this is not so. U may be acting or reciting or incredulously echoing the
remark of another, or flouting the expectation. This, Grice and Urmson think,
may need an explanation. Suppose that U utters, in an ordinary
circumstance, ‘It will rain tomorrow,’ or ‘It rained yesterday,’ or ‘It is
raining.’ This act carries with it the claim that U should be trusted and
licenses A to believe that it will rain tomorrow. By this is meant that
just as it is understood that no U will give an order unless he is entitled to
give orders, so it is understood that no U will utter a sentence of a kind
which can be used to make a statement unless U is willing to claim that that
statement is true, and hence one would be acting in a misleading manner if one
uttered the sentence if he was not willing to make that claim. Here, the
predicate “implies that …,” Grice, Grant, Moore, Nowell-Smith, and Urmson
hasten to add, is being used in such a way that, if there is a an expectation
that a thing is done in Circumstance C, U implies that C holds if he does the
thing. The point is often made if not always in the terms Grice uses, and it
is, Urmson and Grice believe, in substance uncontroversial. Grice and Urmson
wish to make the point that, when an utterer U deploys a hedge with an
indicative sentence, there is not merely an implied claim that the whole
statement is true but also that is true. The implied or expressed claim by
the utterer to trustworthiness need not be very strong. The whole point of
a hedge is to modify or weaken (if not, as Grice would have it, flout) the
claim by U to full trustworthiness which would be implied by the unhedged
assertion. But even if U utters “He is, I suppose, at home;” or “I
guess that the penny will come down heads," U expresses, or for
Urmson plainly implies, with however little reason, that this is what U accepts
as worth the trust by A. Now Grice and Urmson meet an objection which is made
by some philosophers to this comparison. Grice and Urmson intend to meet the
objection by a fairly detailed examination of the example which they themselves
would most likely choose. In doing this Grice and Urmson further explain
the use of a parenthetical verb. The adverb is "probably" and
the verb is “I believe.” To say, that something is probable, the imaginary
objector will say, is to imply that it is reasonable to believe, that the
evidence justifies a guarded claim for the trust or trustworthiness of U and
the truth of the statement. But to say that someone else, a third person,
believes something does not imply that it is reasonable for U or A to believe
it, nor that the evidence justifies the guarded or implied claim to factivity
or truth which U makes. Therefore, the objector continues, the difference
between the use of “I believe” and “probably” is not, as Grice and Urmson
suggest, merely one of nuance and degree of impersonality. In one case,
“probably,” reasonableness is implied; in the other, “believe,” it is not. This
objection is met by Grice and Urmson. They do so by making a general
point. To use the rational-reasonable distinction in “Conversational implicaturum”
and “Aspects,” there is an implied claim by U to reasonableness. Further
to an implied claim to trust whenever a sentence is uttered in a standard
context, now Grice and Urmson add, to meet the sceptical objection about the
contrast between “probably” and “I believe” that, whenever U makes a statement
in a standard context there is an implied claim to reasonableness. This
contention must be explained alla Kant. Cf. Strawson on the presumption of
conversational relevance, and Austin, Moore, Nowell-Smith, Grant, and
Warnock. To use Hart’s defeasibility, and Hall’s excluder, unless U is
acting or story-telling, or preface his remarks with some such phrase
as “I know Im being silly, but …” or, “I admit it is
unreasonable, but …” it is, Grice and Urmson think, a presupposition or
expectation of communication or conversation that a communicator will not make
a statement, thereby implying this trust, unless he has some ground,
however tenuous, for the statement. To utter “The King is visiting Oxford
tomorrow,” or “The President of the BA has a corkscrew in his pocket,” and
then, when asked why the utterer is uttering that, to answer “Oh, for
no reason at all,” would be to sin, theologically, against the basic
conventions governing the use of discourse. Grice goes on to provide a Kantian
justification for that, hence his amusing talk of maxims and stuff.
Therefore, Urmson and Grice think there is an implied or expressed claim
to reasonableness which goes with all our statements, i.e. there is
a mutual expectation that a communicator will not make a statement unless he is
prepared to claim and defend its reasonablenesss. Cf. Grice’s desideratum of
conversational candour, subsumed under the over-arching principle of
conversational helpfulness (formerly conversational
benevolence-cum-self-love). Grice thinks that the principle of
conversational benevolence has to be weighed against the principle of
conversational self-love. The result is the overarching principle of
conversational helpfulness. Clarity gets in the picture. The desideratum of
conversational clarity is a reasonable requirement for conversants to abide
by. Grice follows some observations by Warnock. The logical grammar
of “trust,” “candour,” “charity,” “sincerity,” “decency,” “honesty,” is subtle,
especially when we are considering the two sub-goals of conversation: giving
and receiving information/influencing and being influenced by others. In both
sub-goals, trust is paramount. The explorations of trust has become an Oxonian
hobby, with authors not such like Warnock, but Williams, and
others. Grice’s essay is entitled, “Trust, metaphysics, value.” Trust as a
corollary of the principle of conversational helpfulness. In a given
conversational setting, assuming the principle of conversational helpfulness is
operating, U is assumed by A to be trustworthy and candid. There are two
modes of trust, which relate to the buletic sub-goal and the doxastic sub-goal
which Grice assumes the principle of conversational helpfulness captures:
giving and receiving information, and influencing and being influenced by
others. In both sub-goals, trust is key. In the doxastic realm, trust
has to do, not so much or only, with truth (with which the expression is
cognate), or satisfactoriness-value, but evidence and probability. In the
buletic realm, there are the dimensions of satisfactoriness-value (‘good’
versus ‘true’), and ‘ground’ versus evidence, which becomes less crucial. But
note that one is trustworthy regarding BOTH the buletic attitude and the
doxastic attitude. Grice mentions this or that buletic attitudes which is not
usually judged in terms of evidential support (“I vow to thee my country.”)
However, in the buletic realm, U is be assumed as trustworthy if U has the
buletic attitude he is expressing. The cheater, the insincere, the dishonest,
the untrustworthy, for Grice is not irrational, just repugnant. How immoral is
the idea that honesty is the best policy? Is Kant right in thinking there is no
right to refrain from trust? Surely it is indecent. For Kant, there is no
motivation or ‘motive,’ pure or impure, behind telling the truth – it’s just a
right, and an obligation – an imperative. Being trustworthy for Kant is
associated with a pure motive. Grice agrees. Decency comes into the picture. An
indecent agent may still be rational, but in such a case, conversation may
still be seen as rational (if not reasonable) and surely not be seen as
rational helpfulness or co-operation, but rational adversarial competition,
rather, a zero-sum game. Grice found the etymology of ‘decent’ too obscure.
Short and Lewis have “dĕcet,” which they deem cognate with Sanscrit “dacas,”
‘fame,’ and Grecian “δοκέω,‘to seem,’ ‘to think,’ and with Latin ‘decus,’
‘dingus.’ As an impersonal verb, Short and Lewis render it as ‘it is seemly,
comely, becoming,; it beseems, behooves, is fitting, suitable, proper (for syn.
v. debeo init.): decere quasi aptum esse consentaneumque tempori et personae,
Cic. Or. 22, 74; cf. also nunc quid aptum sit, hoc est, quid maxime deceat in
oratione videamus, id. de Or. 3, 55, 210 (very freq. and class.; not in
Caesar). Grice’s idea of decency is connected to his explorations on rational
and reasonable. To cheat may be neither unreasonable nor rational. It is
just repulsive. Indecent, in other words. In all this, Grice is concerned
with ordinary language, and treasures Austin questioning Warnock, when Warnock
was pursuing a fellowship at Magdalen. “What would you say the difference is
between ‘Smith plays cricket rather properly’ and ‘Smith plays cricket rather
incorrectly’?” They spent the whole dinner over the subtlety. By desserts,
Warnock was in love with Austin. Cf. Grice on his prim and proper Aunt
Matilda. The exploration by Grice on trust is Warnockian in character, or vice
versa. In “Object of morality,” Warnock has trust as key, as indeed, the very
object of morality. Grice starts to focus on trust in an Oxford seminars on the
implicaturum. If there is a desideratum of conversational candour, and the goal
of the principle of conversational helpfulness is that of giving and receiving
information, and influencing and being influenced by others, ‘false’
‘information’ is just no information – Since exhibiteness trumps protrepsis,
this applies to the buletic, too. Grice loved that Latin dictum, “tuus candor.”
He makes an early defence of this in his fatal objection to Malcolm. A
philosopher cannot intentionally instill a falsehood in his tutee, such as
“Decapitation willed the death of Charles I” (the alleged paraphrase of the
paradoxical philosopher saying that ‘causing’ is ‘willing’ and rephrasing
“Decapitation was the cause of the death of Charles I.” There is, for both
Grice and Apel, a transcendental (if weak) justification, not just utilitarian
(honesty as the best policy), as Stalnaker notes in his contribution to the
Grice symposium for APA. Unlike Apel, the transcendental argument is a weak one
in that Grice aims to show that conversation that did not abide by trust would
be unreasonable, but surely still ‘possible.’ It is not a transcendental
justification for the ‘existence’ of conversation simpliciter, but for the
existence of ‘reasonable,’ decent conversation. If we approach charity in the
first person, we trust ourselves that some of our beliefs have to be true, and
that some of our desires have to be satisfactory valid, and we are equally
trusted by our conversational partners. This is Grice’s conversational golden
rule. What would otherwise be the point of holding that conversation is
rational co-operation? What would be the point of conversation simpliciter?
Urmson follows Austin, so Austin’s considerations on this, notably in “Other
minds,” deserve careful examination. Urmson was of course a member of Grice’s
play group, and these are the philosophers that we consider top priority.
Another one was P. H. Nowell-Smith. At least two of his three rules deserve
careful examination. Nowell-Smith notes that this or that ‘rule’ of contextual
implication is not meant to be taken as a ‘rigid rule’. Unlike this or that
rule of entailment, a conversational rule can be broken without the utterer
being involved in self-contradiction or absurdity. When U uses an expression to
make a statement, it is contextually implied that he believes it to be true.
Similarly, when he uses it to perform any of the other jobs for which sentences
are used, it is contextually implied that he is using it for one of the jobs
that it normally does. This rule is often in fact broken. Anti-Kantian lying,
Bernhard-type play-acting, Andersen-type story-telling, and Wildeian irony is
each a case in which U breaks the rule, or flouts the expectation, either
overtly or covertly. But each of these four cases is a secondary use, i.e. a
use to which an expression cannot logically or conceptually be put unless, as
Hart would have it, it has a primary use. There is no limit to the possible
uses to which an expression may be put. In many cases a man makes his point by
deliberately using an expression in a queer way or even using it in the ‘sense’
opposite to its unique normal one, as in irony (“He is a fine friend,” implying
that he is a scoundrel). The distinction between a primary and a secondary use
is important because many an argument used by a philosopher consists in
pointing out some typical example of the way in which some expression E is
used. Such an argument is always illegitimate if the example employed is an
example of a secondary use, however common such a use may be. U contextually
implies that he has what he himself believes to be good reasons for his
statement. Once again, we often break this rule and we have special devices for
indicating when we are breaking it. Phrases such as ‘speaking offhand …,’ 'I do
not really know but …,’ and ‘I should be inclined to say that …,’ are used by
scrupulous persons to warn his addressee that U has not got what seem to him
good reasons for his statement. But unless one of these guarding phrases is
used we are entitled to believe that U believes himself to have good reasons
for his statement and we soon learn to *mistrust* people who habitually
infringe this rule. It is, of course, a mistake to infer from what someone says
categorically that he has in fact good reasons for what he says. If I tell you,
or ‘inform’ to you, that the duck-billed platypus is a bird (because I '
remember ' reading this in a book) I am unreliable; but I am not using language
improperly. But if I tell you this without using one of the guarding phrases
and without having what I think good reasons, I am. What U says may be assumed
to be relevant to the interests of his addressee. This is the most important of
the three rules; unfortunately it is also the most frequently broken. Bores are
more common than liars or careless talkers. This rule is particularly obvious
in the case of answers to questions, since it is assumed that the answer is an
answer. Not all statements are answers to questions; information may be
volunteered. Nevertheless the publication of a text-book on trigonometry
implies that the author believes that there are people who want to learn about
trigonometry, and to give advice implies a belief that the advice is relevant
to one’s addressee's problem. This rule is of the greatest importance for
ethics. For the major problem of ethics is that of bridging the gap between a
decisions, an ought-sentence, an injunction, and a sentence used to give advice
on the one hand and the statements of *fact*, sometime regarding the U’s soul,
that constitute the reasons for these on the other. It is in order to bridge
these gaps that insight into necessary synthetic connexions is invoked. This
rule of contextual implication may help us to show that there is no gap to be
bridged because the reason-giving sentence must turn out to be also *practical*
from the start and not a statement of *fact*, even concerning the state of the
U’s soul, from which a practical sentence can somehow be deduced. This rule is,
therefore, more than a rule of good manners; or rather it shows how, in matters
of ordinary language, rules of good manners shade into logical rules. Unless we
assume that it is being observed we cannot understand the connexions between
decisions, advice, and appraisals and the reasons given in support of them. Refs.: The main reference is in the first set of ‘Logic and
conversation.’ Many keywords are useful, not just ‘candour,’ but notably ‘trust.’
(“Rationality and trust,” c. 9-f. 5, “Trust, metaphysics, and value,” c. 9-f.
20, and “Aristotle and friendship, rationality, trust, and decency,” c. 6-f.
18), BANC.
desideratum of conversational
clarity. There is some overlap here with
Grice’s category of conversational manner – of Grice’s maxim of conversational
perspicuity [sic] – and at least one of the maxims proper, ‘obscuirty
avoidance,’ or maxim of conversational obscurity avoidance. But at Oxford he
defined the philosopher as the one whose profession it is to makes clear things
obscure. The word desideratum has to be taken seriously. It involves freedom.
In what way is “The pillar box seems red to me” less perspicuous than “The
pillar box is red”? In all! If mutual expectation not to mislead and produce
the stronger contribution are characteristics of candour, expectation of mutual
relevance to interests, and being explicit and clear in your point are two
characteristics of this desideratum. “Candour” and “clarity’ are somewhat
co-relative for Grice. He is interested in identifying this or that
desideratum. By having two of them, he can play. So, how UNCLEAR can a
conversationalist be provided he WANTS to be candid? Candour trumps clarity.
But too much ‘unperspicuity’ may lead to something not being deemed an ‘implicaturum’
at all. Grice is especially concerned with philosopher’s paradoxes. Why would
Strawson say that the usage of ‘not,’ ‘and,’ ‘or,’ ‘if,’ ‘if and only if,’
‘all,’ ‘some (at least one), ‘the,’ do not correspond to the logician’s use?
Questions of candour and clarity interact. Grice’s first application, which he
grants is not original, relates to “The pillar box seems red” versus “The
pillar box is red.” “I would not like to give the false impression that the
pillar box is not red” seems less clear than “The pillar box is red” – Yet the
unperspicuous contributin is still ‘candid,’ in the sense that it expresses a
truth. So one has to be careful. On top, philosophers like Lewis were using
‘clarity is not enough’ as a battle cry! Grice’s favourite formulations of the
imperatives here are ‘self-contradictory,’ and for which he uses ‘[sic]’,
notably: “Be perspicuous [sic]’ and “Be brief. Avoid unnecessary prolixity
[sic].’ Desirabile, neuter, out of ‘desideratum’ – so by using ‘desirability,’
Grice is getting into the modals -- desirability: Correlative: credibility.
For Grice, credibility reduces to desirability (He suggests that the reverse
may also be possible but does not give a proposal). This Grice calls the
Jeffrey operator. If Urmson likes ‘probably,’ Grice likes ‘desirably.’ This theorem
is a corollary of the desirability axiom by Jeffrey, which is: "If prob XY
= 0, for a prima facie PF(A V B) A (x E
w)] = PFA A (x E w)] + PfB A (x El+ w)]. This is the account by Grice of the adaptability
of a pirot to its changeable environs. Grice borrows the notion of
probability (henceforth, “pr”) from Davidson, whose early claim to fame was to
provide the logic of the notion. Grice abbreviates probability by Pr. and
compares it to a buletic operator ‘pf,’ ‘for prima facie,’ attached to ‘De’
for desirability. A rational agent must calculate both the probability and the
desirability of his action. For both probability and desirability, the
degree is crucial. Grice symbolises this by d: probability in degree d;
probability in degree d. The topic of life Grice relates to that of
adaptation and surival, and connects with his genitorial programme of creature
construction (Pology.): life as continued operancy. Grice was fascinated with
life (Aristotle, bios) because bios is what provides for Aristotle the definition
(not by genus) of psyche. The steps are as follows. Pf(p ⊃!q)/Pr(p ⊃ q); pf((p1 ^ p2) ⊃!q)/pr(p1
^ p2 ⊃q);
pf((p1 ^ p2 ^ p3) ⊃!q)/pr(p1 ^ p2 ^ p3 ^ p4 ⊃q);
pf (all things before me ⊃!q)/pr (all things before me ⊃
q); pf (all things considered ⊃ !q)/pr(all things considered ⊃ q); !q/|- q; G wills !q/G judges q. Strictly, Grice avoids
using the noun probability (other than for the title of this or that lecture).
One has to use the sentence-modifier ‘probably,’ and ‘desirably.’ So the
specific correlative to the buletic prima facie ‘desirably’ is the doxastic ‘probably.’
Grice liked the Roman sound to ‘prima facie,’ ‘at first sight’: “exceptio, quae prima facie justa videatur.” Refs.:
The two main sources are “Probability, desirability, and mood operators,” c.
2-f. 11, and “Modality, desirability and probability,” c. 8-ff. 14-15. But most
of the material is collected in “Aspects,” especially in the third and fourth
lectures. The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC.
Non-detachability. A rather abstract notion. One thinks of ‘detach’ in
physical terms (‘semi-detached house’). Grice means it in an abstract way. To
detach – what is it that we detach? We detach an implicaturum. Grice is not so
much concerned with how to DETACH an implicaturum, but how sometimes you
cannot. It’s NON-detachability that is the criterion. And this should be a
matter of a prioricity. However, since style gets in the picture, he has to
allow for exceptions to this criterion. A conversational, even philosophically
interesting one, generated by the conversational category of modus (as the
maxim of orderliness: “he went to bed and took off his boots”) is detachable. How
to interpret this in an one-off predicament. Cf. non-detachability. And the
other features or tests or catalysts that Grice uses. In Causal Theory of
Perception, the ideas are FOUR, which he nicely summarises in WoW on the
occasion of eliminating the excursus. And then he expands on Essay II, as an
update. His tutees at Oxford are aware of the changes. Few care, though. Even
his colleagues don’t, they are into their own things. So let’s compare the two
versions of the catalysts in Causal and Essay II. Version of the four catalysts
up to the first two examples in “Causal”: The first cxample is a stock case of what
is sometimes called " prcsupposition " and it is often held that here
1he truth of what is irnplicd is a necessary condition of the original
statement's beirrg cither true or false. This might be disputed, but it is at
lcast arguable that it is so, and its being arguable might be enough to
distinguish-this type of case from others. I shall however for convenience
assume that the common view mentioned is correct. This consideration clearly
distinguishes (1) from (2); even if the implied proposition were false, i.e. if
there were no reason in the world to contrast poverty with honesty either in
general or in her case, the original statement could still be false; it would
be false if for example she were rich and dishonest. One might perhaps be less
comfortable about assenting to its truth if the implied contrast did not in
fact obtain; but the possibility of falsity is enough for the immediate
purpose. My next experiment on these examples is to ask what it is in each case
which could properly be said to be the vehicle of implication (to do the
implying). There are at least four candidates, not necessarily mutually
exclusive. Supposing someone to have uttered one or other of my sample
sentences, we may ask whether the vehicle of implication would be (a) what the
speaker said (or asserted), or (b) the speaker (" did he imply that . . .
.':) or (c) the words the speaker used, or (d) his saying that (or again his
saying that in that way); or possibly some plurality of these items. As regards
(a) I think (1) and (2) differ; I think it would be correct to say in the case
of (l) that what he speaker said (or asserted) implied that Smith had been
beating this wife, and incorrect to say in the case of (2) that what te said
(or asserted) implied that there was a contrast between e.g., honesty and
poverty. A test on which I would rely is the following : if accepting that the
implication holds involves one in r27 128 H. P. GRICE accepting an
hypothetical' if p then q ' where 'p ' represents the original statement and '
q' represents what is implied, then what the speaker said (or asserted) is a
vehicle of implication, otherwise not. To apply this rule to the given
examples, if I accepted the implication alleged to hold in the case of (1), I
should feel compelled to accept the hypothetical " If Smith has left off
beating his wife, then he has been beating her "; whereas if I accepted
the alleged implication in the case of (2), I should not feel compelled to
accept the hypothetical " If she was poor but honest, then there is some
contrast between poverty and honesty, or between her poverty and her
honesty." The other candidates can be dealt with more cursorily; I should
be inclined to say with regard to both (l) and (2) that the speaker could be
said to have implied whatever it is that is irnplied; that in the case of (2)
it seems fairly clear that the speaker's words could be said to imply a
contrast, whereas it is much less clear whether in the case of (1) the
speaker's words could be said to imply that Smith had been beating his wife;
and that in neither case would it be evidently appropriate to speak of his
saying that, or of his saying that in that way, as implying what is implied.
The third idea with which I wish to assail my two examples is really a twin
idea, that of the detachability or cancellability of the implication. (These
terms will be explained.) Consider example (1): one cannot fi.nd a form of
words which could be used to state or assert just what the sentence "
Smith has left off beating his wife " might be used to assert such that
when it is used the implication that Smith has been beating his wife is just
absent. Any way of asserting what is asserted in (1) involves the irnplication
in question. I shall express this fact by saying that in the case of (l) the
implication is not detqchable from what is asserted (or simpliciter, is not
detachable). Furthermore, one cannot take a form of words for which both what
is asserted and what is implied is the same as for (l), and then add a further
clause withholding commitment from what would otherwise be implied, with the
idea of annulling the implication without annulling the assertion. One cannot
intelligibly say " Smith has left off beating his wife but I do not mean
to imply that he has been beating her." I shall express this fact by
saying that in the case of (1) the implication is not cancellable (without THE
CAUSAL THEORY OF PERCEPTION r29 cancelling the assertion). If we turn to (2) we
find, I think, that there is quite a strong case for saying that here the
implication ls detachable. Thcrc sccms quitc a good case for maintaining that
if, instead of sayirrg " She is poor but shc is honcst " I were to
say " She is poor and slre is honcst", I would assert just what I
would havc asscrtcct ii I had used thc original senterrce; but there would now
be no irnplication of a contrast between e.g', povery and honesty. But the
question whether, in tl-re case of (2), thc inrplication is cancellable, is
slightly more cornplex. Thcrc is a sonse in which we may say that it is
non-cancellable; if sorncone were to say " She is poor but she is honest,
though of course I do not mean to imply that there is any contrast between
poverty and honesty ", this would seem a puzzling and eccentric thing to
have said; but though we should wish to quarrel with the speaker, I do not
think we should go so far as to say that his utterance was unintelligible; we
should suppose that he had adopted a most peculiar way of conveying the the
news that she was poor and honesl. The fourth and last test that I wish to
impose on my exarnples is to ask whether we would be inclined to regard the
fact that the appropriate implication is present as being a matter of the
meaning of some particular word or phrase occurring in the sentences in
question. I am aware that this may not be always a very clear or easy question
to answer; nevertheless Iwill risk the assertion that we would be fairly happy
to say that, as regards (2), the factthat the implication obtains is a matter
of the meaning of the word ' but '; whereas so far as (l) is concerned we
should have at least some inclination to say that the presence of the
implication was a matter of the meaning of some of the words in the sentence,
but we should be in some difficulty when it came to specifying precisely which
this word, or words are, of which this is true. After third example
introduced:It is plain that there is no case at all for regarding the truth of
what is implied here as a pre-condition of the truth or falsity cf 130 H. P.
GRICB what I have asserted; a denial of the truth of what is implied would have
no bearing at all on whether what I have asserted is true or false. So (3) is
much closer to (2) than (1) in this respect. Next, I (the speaker) could
certainly be said to have implied that Jones is hopeless (provided that this is
what I intended to get across) and my saying that (at any rate my saying /s/
that and no more) is also certainly a vehicle of implication. On the other hand
my words and what I say (assert) are, I think, not here vehicles of
implication. (3) thus differs from both (1) and (2). The implication is
cancellable but not detachable; if I add o'I do not of course mean to imply
that he is no good at philosophy " my whole utterance is intelligible and
linguistically impeccable, even though it may be extraordinary tutorial
behaviour; and I can no longer be said to have implied that he was no good,
even though perhaps that is what my colleagues might conclude to be the case if
I had nothing else to say. The implication is not however, detachable; any
other way of making, in the same context of utterance, just the assertion I
have made would involve the same implication. Finally, the fact that the
implication holds is not a matter of any particular word or phrase within the
sentence which I have uttered; so in this respect (3) is certainly different
from (2) and, possibly different from (1). One obvious fact should be mentioned
before I pass to the last example. This case of implication is unlike the
others in that the utterance of the sentence " Jones has beautiful
handwriting etc." does not standardly involve the implication here
attributed to it; it requires a special context (that it should be uttered at
Collections) to attach the implication to its uttgrance. After fourth and last
example is introduced: in the case of (a) I can produce a strong argument in
favour of holding that the fulfllment of the THE CAUSAL THEORY OF PERCEPTION
implication of the speaker's ignorance is not a precaution of the truth or
falsity of the disjunctive statement. Suppose (c) that the speaker knows that
his wife is in the kitchen, (b) that the house has only two rooms (and no
passages etc.) Even though (a) is the casc, thc spcaker can certainly say truly
" My wife is in the housc "; he is merely not being as informative as
he could bc if nccd arose. But the true proposition that his wife is in thc
housc together with the true proposition that the house consists entirely of a
kitchen and a bedroom, entail the proposition that his wife is either in the
kitchen or in the bedroom. But il to cxpress the proposition p in certain
circumstances would bc to spcak truly, and p, togelher with another true
proposition, crrtails q, then surely to express 4 in the same circvmstances
must be to speak truly. So I shall take it that the disjunctive statement in
(4) does not fail to be true or false if the implied ignorance is in fact not
realized. Secondly, I think it is fairly clear that in this case, as in the
case of (3), we could say that the speaker had irnplied that he did not know,
and also that his saying that (or his saying that rather than something else,
v2., in which room she was) implied that he did not know. Thirdly, the
irnplication is in a sense non-detachable, in that if in a given context the
utterance of the disjunctive sentence would involve the implication that the
speaker did not know in which room his his wife was, this implication would
also be involved in the utterance of any other form of words which would make
the same assertion(e.g., "The alternatives are (1) .(2) " or "
One of the following things is the case: (a) (r) "). ln another possible
sense, however, the implication could perhaps bc said to be detachable: for
there will be some contexls of ruttcrance in Which the normal implication will
not hold; e.g., thc spokesman who announces, " The next conference will be
cither in Geneva or in New York " perhaps does not imply that lrc does not
know which; for he may well be just not saying which. This points to the fact
that the implication is cancellablg; :r nrarl could say, " My wife is
either in the kitchen or in the bctlroorn " in circumstances in which the
implication would rrornrally be present, and then go on, " Mind you, I'm
not saying tlrrrt I don't know which"; this might be unfriendly (and
grcr'lrrps ungrammatical) but would be perfectly intelligible, I2 131 132 H. P.
GRICB Finally, the fact that the utterance of the disjunctive sentence normally
involves the implication of the speaker's ignorance of the truth-values of the
disjuncts is, I should like to say, to be explained by reference to a general
principle governing the use of language. Exactly what this principle is I am
uncertain, but L first sftol would be the following: "One should not make
a weaker statement rather than a stronger one unless there is a good reason for
so doing." This is certainly not an adequate formulation but will perhaps
be good enough for my present purpose. On the assumption that such a principle
as this is of general application, one can draw the conclusion that the
utterance of a disjunctive sentence would imply the speaker's ignorance of the
truth-values of the disjuncts, given that (a) the obvious reason for not making
a statemcnt which there is some call on one to make is that one is not in a
position to make it, and given (6) the logical fact that each disjunct entails
the disjunctive, but not vice versa; which being so, the disjuncts are stronger
than the disjunctive. lf the outline just given js on the right lines, then I
would wish to say, we have a reason for refusing in the case of (4) to regard
the implication of the speaker's ignorance as being part of the meaning of the
word'or'; someone who knows about the logical relation between a disjunction
and its disjuncts, and who also knew about the alleged general principle
governing discourse, could work out for hirnself that disjunctive utterances
would involve the implication which they do in fact involve. I must insist,
however, that my aim in discussing this last point has been merelyto indicate
the position I would wish to take up, and not to argue scriously in favour of
it. My main purpose in this sub-section has been to introduce four ideas of
which l intend to make some use; and to provide some conception of tlre ways in
which they apply or fail to apply to various types of implication. By the
numbering of it, it seems he has added an extra. It’s FIVE catalysts now. He’ll
go back to them in Essay IV, and in Presupposition and Conversational
Impicature. He needs those catalysts. Why? It seems like he is always thinking
that someone will challenge him! This is Grice: “We can now show that, it
having been stipulated as being what it is, a conversational implicaturum must
possess certain features. Or rather here are some catalyst ideas which will
help us to determine or individuate. Four tests for implicaturum as it were. First,
CANCELLABILITY – as noted in “Causal Theory” – for two of the examples
(‘beautiful handwriting’ and ‘kitchen or bedroom’ and NEGATIVE version of “You
don’t cease to eat iron”) and the one of the pillar box -- Since, to assume the
presence of a conversational implicum, we have to assume that the principle of
conversational co-operation is being observed, and since it is possible to opt
out of the observation of this principle, it follows that an implicaturum can
be canceled in a particular case. It may be explicitly canceled, if need there
be, by the addition of a clause by which the utterer states or implies that
he has opted out (e. g. “The pillar box
seems red but it is.”). Then again it may be contextually (or implicitly)
canceled (e. g. to a very honest person, who knows I disbelieve the examiner
exists, “The loyalty examiner won’t be summoning you at any rate”). The
utterance that usually would carry an implicaturum is used on an occasion that
makes it clear or obvious that the utterer IS opting out without having to bore
his addressee by making this obviousness explicit. There is a second litmus
test or catalyst idea. nsofar as the calculation that a implicaturum is present
requires, besides contextual and background information only a knowledge or
understanding or processing of what has been said or explicitly conveyed (‘are
you playing squash? B shows bandaged leg) (or the ‘conventional’ ‘commitment’ of
the utterance), and insofar as the manner or style, of FORM, rather than
MATTER, of expression plays no role in the calculation, it will NOT be possible
to find another way of explicitly conveying or putting forward the same thing, the
same so-and-so (say that q follows from p) which simply ‘lacks’ the unnecessary
implicaturum in question -- except [will his excluders never end?] where some
special feature of the substituted version [this other way which he says is not
conceivable] is itself relevant to the determination of the implicaturum (in
virtue of this or that conversational maxims pertaining to the category of
conversational mode. If we call this feature, as Grice does in “Causal Theory,”
‘non-detachability’ – in that the implicaturum cannot be detached from any
alternative expression that makes the same point -- one may expect the implicaturum
carried by this or that locution to have a high degree of non-detachability. ALTERNATIVES
FOR “NOT” Not, it is not the case, it is false that. There’s nothing unique about
‘not’.ALTERNATIVES FOR “AND” and, nothing, furthermore, but. There isnothing
unique about ‘and’ALTERNATIVES FOR “OR”: One of the following is true. There is
nothing unique about ‘or’ALTERNATIVES FOR “IF” Provided. ‘There is nothing
unique about ‘if’ALTERNATIVES FOR “THE” – There is at least one and at most
one. And it exists. (existence and uniqueness). There is nothing unique about
‘the’.THIS COVERS STRAWSON’S first problem.What about the other English
philosophers?AUSTIN – on ‘voluntarily’ ALTERNATIVES to ‘voluntarily,’ with the
will, willingly, intentionally. Nothing unique about ‘voluntarily.’STRAWSON on
‘true’ – it is the case, redundance theory, nothing. Nothing unique about
‘true’HART ON good. To say that ‘x is commendable’ is to recommend x. Nothing
unique about ‘good.’HART on ‘carefully.’ Da Vinci painted Mona Lisa carefully,
with caution, with precaution. Nothing unique about ‘carefully.’THIRD LITMUS
TEST or idea. To speak approximately, since the calculation of the presence of
an implicaturum presupposes an initial knowledge, or grasping, or
understanding, or taking into account of the ‘conventional’ force (not in
Austin’s sense, but translating Latin ‘vis’) of the expression the utterance of
which carries the implicaturum, a conversational implicaturum will be a
condition that is NOT, be definition, on risk of circularity of otiosity,
included in the original specification of the expression's conventional force.
If I’m saying that ‘seems’ INVOLVES, as per conventional force, ‘doubt or
denial,’what’s my point? If Strawson is right that ‘if’ has the conventional
force of conventionally committing the utterer with the belief that q follows
from p, why bother? And if that were so, how come the implicaturum is still
cancellable?Though it may not be impossible for what starts life, so to speak,
as a conversational implicaturum to become conventionalized, to suppose that
this is so in a given case would require special justification. (Asking Lewis).
So, initially at least, a conversational implicaturum is, by definition and
stipulation, not part of the sense, truth-condition, conventional force, or
part of what is explicitly conveyed or put forward, or ‘meaning’ of the
expression to the employment of which the impicatum attaches. FOURTH LITMUS
TEST or catalyst idea.Mentioned in “Causal theory” The alethic value –
conjoined with the test about the VEHICLE --. He has these as two different
tests in “Causal”. Since the truth of a conversational implicaturum is not
required by (is not a condition for) the truth of what is said or explicitly
conveyed (what is said or explicated – the explicatum or explcitum, or what is
explicitly conveyed or communicated) may be true -- what is implicated may be
false – that he has beautiful handwriting, that q follows from p, that the
utterer is ENDORSING what someone else said, that the utterer is recommending
x, that the person who is said to act carefully has taken precaution), the implicaturum
is NOT carried by what is said or the EXPLICATUM or EXPLICITUM, or is explicitly
conveyed, but only by the ‘saying’ or EXPLICATING or EXPLICITING of what is
said or of the explicatum or explicitum, or by 'putting it that way.’.The fifth
and last litmus test or catalyst idea. Since, to calculate a conversational implicaturum
is to calculate what has to be supposed in order to preserve the supposition
that the utterer is a rational, benevolent, altruist agent, and that the principle
of conversational cooperation is being observed, and since there may be various
possible specific explanations or alternatives that fill the gap here – as to
what is the content of the psychological attitude to be ascribed to the utterer,
a list of which may be open, or open-ended, the conversational implicaturum in
such cases will technically be an open-ended disjunction of all such specific
explanations, which may well be infinitely non-numerable. Since the list of
these IS open, the implicaturum will have just the kind of INDETERMINACY or
lack of determinacy that an implicaturum appears in most cases to possess.
determinatum: determinable, a
general characteristic or property analogous to a genus except that while a
property independent of a genus differentiates a species that falls under the
genus, no such independent property differentiates a determinate that falls
under the determinable. The color blue, e.g., is a determinate with respect of
the determinable color: there is no property F independent of color such that a
color is blue if and only if it is F. In contrast, there is a property, having
equal sides, such that a rectangle is a square if and only if it has this
property. Square is a properly differentiated species of the genus rectangle.
W. E. Johnson introduces the terms ‘determinate’ and ‘determinable’ in his
Logic, Part I, Chapter 11. His account of this distinction does not closely
resemble the current understanding sketched above. Johnson wants to explain the
differences between the superficially similar ‘Red is a color’ and ‘Plato is a
man’. He concludes that the latter really predicates something, humanity, of Plato;
while the former does not really predicate anything of red. Color is not really
a property or adjective, as Johnson puts it. The determinates red, blue, and
yellow are grouped together not because of a property they have in common but
because of the ways they differ from each other. Determinates under the same
determinable are related to each other and are thus comparable in ways in which
they are not related to determinates under other determinables. Determinates
belonging to different determinables, such as color and shape, are
incomparable. ’More determinate’ is often used interchangeably with ‘more
specific’. Many philosophers, including Johnson, hold that the characters of
things are absolutely determinate or specific. Spelling out what this claim means
leads to another problem in analyzing the relation between determinate and
determinable. By what principle can we exclude red and round as a determinate
of red and red as a determinate of red or round? determinism, the view that every event or
state of affairs is brought about by antecedent events or states of affairs in
accordance with universal causal laws that govern the world. Thus, the state of
the world at any instant determines a unique future, and that knowledge of all
the positions of things and the prevailing natural forces would permit an
intelligence to predict the future state of the world with absolute precision.
This view was advanced by Laplace in the early nineteenth century; he was
inspired by Newton’s success at integrating our physical knowledge of the
world. Contemporary determinists do not believe that Newtonian physics is the
supreme theory. Some do not even believe that all theories will someday be
integrated into a unified theory. They do believe that, for each event, no matter
how precisely described, there is some theory or system of laws such that the
occurrence of that event under that description is derivable from those laws
together with information about the prior state of the system. Some
determinists formulate the doctrine somewhat differently: a every event has a
sufficient cause; b at any given time, given the past, only one future is
possible; c given knowledge of all antecedent conditions and all laws of
nature, an agent could predict at any given time the precise subsequent history
of the universe. Thus, determinists deny the existence of chance, although they
concede that our ignorance of the laws or all relevant antecedent conditions
makes certain events unexpected and, therefore, apparently happen “by chance.”
The term ‘determinism’ is also used in a more general way as the name for any
metaphysical doctrine implying that there is only one possible history of the
world. The doctrine described above is really scientific or causal determinism,
for it grounds this implication on a general fact about the natural order,
namely, its governance by universal causal law. But there is also theological
determinism, which holds that God determines everything that happens or that,
since God has perfect knowledge about the universe, only the course of events
that he knows will happen can happen. And there is logical determinism, which
grounds the necessity of the historical order on the logical truth that all
propositions, including ones about the future, are either true or false.
Fatalism, the view that there are forces e.g., the stars or the fates that
determine all outcomes independently of human efforts or wishes, is claimed by
some to be a version of determinism. But others deny this on the ground that
determinists do not reject the efficacy of human effort or desire; they simply
believe that efforts and desires, which are sometimes effective, are themselves
determined by antecedent factors as in a causal chain of events. Since
determinism is a universal doctrine, it embraces human actions and choices. But
if actions and choices are determined, then some conclude that free will is an
illusion. For the action or choice is an inevitable product of antecedent
factors that rendered alternatives impossible, even if the agent had deliberated
about options. An omniscient agent could have predicted the action or choice
beforehand. This conflict generates the problem of free will and
determinism.
deutero-esperanto: Also Gricese – Pirotese. “Gricese” is best. Arbitrariness
need not be a two-party thing. E communicates to himself that there is danger
by drawing a skull. Grice genially opposed to the idea of a convention. He
hated a convention. A language is not conventional. Meaning is not
conventional. Communication is not conventional. He was even unhappy with the account
of convention by Lewis in terms of an arbitrary co-ordination. While the
co-ordination bit passes rational muster, the arbitrary element is deemed a
necessary condition, and Grice hated that. For Grice there is natural, and
iconic. When a representation ceases to be iconic and becomes, for lack of a
better expression, non-iconic, things get, we may assume conventional. One form
of correlation in his last definition of meaing allows for a conventional
correlation. “Pain!,” the P cries. There is nothing in /pein/ that minimally
resembles the pain the P is suffering. So from his involuntary “Ouch” to his
simulated “Ouch,” he thinks he can say “Pain.” Bennett explored the stages after
that. The dog is shaggy is Grices example. All sorts of resultant procedures
are needed for reference and predication, which may be deemed conventional. One
may refer nonconventionally, by ostension. It seems more difficult to predicate
non-conventionally. But there may be iconic predication. Urquhart promises
twelve parts of speech: each declinable in eleven cases, four numbers, eleven
genders (including god, goddess, man, woman, animal, etc.); and conjugable in
eleven tenses, seven moods, and four voices. The language will translate any
idiom in any other language, without any alteration of the literal sense, but
fully representing the intention. Later, one day, while lying in his bath,
Grice designed deutero-esperanto. The obble is fang may be current only
for Griceian members of the class of utterers. It is only this or that
philosophers practice to utter The obble is fang in such-and-such
circumstances. In this case, the utterer U does have a readiness to utter The
obble is feng in such-and-such circumstances. There is also the scenario in
which The obble is fang is may be conceived by the philosopher not to be deemed
current at all, but the utterance of The obble is feng in such-and-such
circumstances is part of some system of communication which the utterer U
(Lockwith,, Urquart, Wilkins, Edmonds, Grice) has devised but which has never
been put into operation, like the highway code which Grice invent another day
again while lying in his bath. In that case, U does this or that basic or
resultant procedure for the obble is feng in an attenuated but philosophically
legitimate fashion. U has envisaged a possible system of practices which
involve a readiness to utter Example by Grice that does NOT involve a
convention in this usage. Surely Grice can as he indeed did, invent a language, call
it Deutero-Esperanto, Griceish, or Pirotese, which nobody at Oxford ever uses
to communicat. That makes Grice the authority - cf. arkhe, authority,
government (in plural), "authorities" - and Grice can lay down, while
lying in the tub, no doubt - what is proper. A P can be said to potch of
some obble o as fang or as feng. Also to cotch of some obble o, as fang or
feng; or to cotch of one obble o and another obble o as being fid to one
another.” In symbols: (Ex)(Ey).Px ^ Oy ^ potch(x, y, fang) (Ex)(Ey).Px ^ Oy ^
potch(x, y, feng) (Ex)(Ey).Px ^ Oy ^ cotch(x, y, fang) (Ex)(Ey).Px ^ Ox ^ cotch(x,
y, feng) (Ex)(Ey).Px ^ Oz ^ Oy ^ cotch(x, fid(y,z)). Let’s say that Ps (as
Russell and Carnap conceived them) inhabit a world of obbles, material
objects, or things. To potch is something like to perceive; to cotch something
like to think. Feng and fang are possible descriptions, much like our
adjectives. Fid is a possible relation between obbles. Grice provides a
symbolisation for content internalisation. The perceiver or cognitive
Subjects perceives or cognises two objects, x, y, as holding a relation of some
type. There is a higher level that Ps can reach when the object of their
potchings and cotchings is not so much objects but states of affairs. Its
then that the truth-functional operators will be brought to existence “^”:
cotch(p ^ q) “V”: cotch(p v q) “)”: )-cotch(p ) q) A P will be able
to reject a content, refuse-thinking: ~. Cotch(~p). When P1 perceives P2, the
reciprocals get more complicated. P2 cotches that P1!-judges that
p. Grice uses ψ1 for potching and ψ2
for cotching. If P2 is co-operative, and abides by "The Ps Immanuel,"
P2 will honour, in a Kantian benevolent way, his partners goal by adopting
temporarily his partners goal potch(x (portch(y, !p)) ⊃ potch(x, !p). But by then, its hardly simpler
ways. Especially when the Ps outdo their progenitor Carnap as metaphysicians.
The details are under “eschatology,” but the expressions are here “α izzes α.” This
would be the principle of non-contradiction or identity. P1 applies it war, and
utters War is war which yields a most peculiar implicaturum. “if α izzes
β ∧ β izzes γ, α izz γ.” This is transitivity, which is
crucial for Ps to overcome Berkeley’s counterexample to Locke, and define their
identity over time. “if α hazzes β, α izzes β.” Or, what is accidental is not
essential. A P may allow that what is essential is accidental while misleading,
is boringly true. “α hazzes β iff α hazzes x ∧ x izzes β.” “If β is a katholou or universalium, β is
an eidos or forma.” For surely Ps need not be stupid to fail to see
squarrelhood. “if α hazzes β ∧ α
izzes a particular, γ≠α ∧ α izz β.” “α izzes predicable
of β iff ((β izzes α) ∨ (∃x)(β hazzes x ∧ x
izzes α). “α izzes essentially predicable of β ⊃⊂ β izzes α α
izzes non-essentially/accidentally predicable of β ⊃⊂ (∃x)(β hazzes x ∧ x
izzes α). α = β iff α izzes β ∧ β
izzes α. “α izzes an atomon, or individuum ⊃⊂ □(∀β)(β izzes α ⊃ α
izzes β). “α izzes a particular ⊃⊂ □(∀β)(α izzes predicable of β ⊃ (α izzes β ∧ β
izzes α)). α izzes a universalium ⊃⊂ ◊(∃β)(α izzes predicable of α ∧ ~(α izzes β ∧ β
izzes α). α izzes some-thing ⊃ α
izzes an individuum. α izzes an eidos or forma ⊃ (α izzes some-thing ∧ α izzes a universalium); α izzes predicable of β ⊃⊂ (β izzes α) ∨ (∃x)(β hazzes x ∧ x
izzes α). “ α izzes essentially predicable of α α izzes accidentally
predicable of β ⊃ α ≠ β. ~(α izzes accidentally predicable of
β) ⊃ α ≠ β. α izzes an kathekaston or particular ⊃ α izzes an individuum; α izz a particular ⊃ ~(∃x)(x ≠ α ∧ x izz α). ~(∃x).(x
izzes a particular ∧ x izzes a forma) ⊢ α
izzes a forma ⊃ ~(∃x)(x ≠ α ∧ x izzes α). x izzes a particular ⊃ ~(∃β)(α izzes β); α izzes a forma ⊃ ((α izzes predicable of β ∧ α ≠ β) ⊃ β
hazzes α); α izzes a forma ∧ β
izzes a particular ⊃ (α izzes predicable of β ⊃⊂ β hazzes A); (α izzes a particular ∧ β izzes a universalium ∧ β izzes predicable of α) ⊃ (∃γ)(α ≠ γ ∧ γ
izzes essentially predicable of α). (∃x)
(∃y)(x izzes a particular ∧ y
izzes a universalium ∧ y izzes predicable of x ⊃ ~(∀x)(x izzes a universalium ∧ x izzes some-thing). (∀β)(β izzes a universalium ⊃ β izzes some-thing). α izzes a particular) ⊃ ~∃β.(α ≠ β ∧ β
izzes essentially predicable of α). (α izzes predicable of β ∧ α ≠ β) ⊃ α
izzes non-essentially or accidentally predicable of β. Grice
is following a Leibnizian tradition. A philosophical language is any
constructed language that is constructed from first principles or certain
ideologies. It is considered a type of engineered language. Philosophical
languages were popular in Early Modern times, partly motivated by the goal of
recovering the lost Adamic or Divine language. The term “ideal language”
is sometimes used near-synonymously, though more modern philosophical languages
such as “Toki Pona” are less likely to involve such an exalted claim of
perfection. It may be known as a language of pure ideology. The
axioms and grammars of the languages together differ from commonly spoken
languages today. In most older philosophical languages, and some newer
ones, words are constructed from a limited set of morphemes that are treated as
"elemental" or fundamental. "Philosophical language" is
sometimes used synonymously with "taxonomic language", though more
recently there have been several conlangs constructed on philosophical
principles which are not taxonomic. Vocabularies of oligo-synthetic
communication-systems are made of compound expressions, which are coined from a
small (theoretically minimal) set of morphemes; oligo-isolating communication-systems,
such as Toki Pona, similarly use a limited set of root words but produce
phrases which remain s. of distinct words. Toki Pona is based on
minimalistic simplicity, incorporating elements of Taoism. Láadan is designed
to lexicalize and grammaticalise the concepts and distinctions important to
women, based on muted group theory. A priori languages are constructed
languages where the vocabulary is invented directly, rather than being derived
from other existing languages (as with Esperanto, or Grices Deutero-Esperanto,
or Pirotese or Ido). It all starts when Carnap claims to know that pritos
karulise elatically. Grice as engineer. Pirotese is the philosophers
engaging in Pology. Actually, Pirotese is the lingo the Ps parrot. Ps karulise
elatically. But not all of them. Grice finds that the Pological talk
allows to start from zero. He is constructing a language, (basic) Pirotese,
and the philosophical psychology and world that that language is supposed to
represent or denote. An obble is a Ps object. Grice introduces
potching and cotching. To potch, in Pirotese, is what a P does with an obble:
he perceives it. To cotch is Pirotese for what a P can further do with an
obble: know or cognise it. Cotching, unlike potching, is factive. Pirotese
would not be the first language invented by a philosopher. Deutero-Esperanto
-- Couturat, L., philosopher and logician who wrote on the history of
philosophy, logic, philosophy of mathematics, and the possibility of a
universal language. Couturat refuted Renouvier’s finitism and advocated an
actual infinite in The Mathematical Infinite 6. He argued that the assumption
of infinite numbers was indispensable to maintain the continuity of magnitudes.
He saw a precursor of modern logistic in Leibniz, basing his interpretation of
Leibniz on the Discourse on Metaphysics and Leibniz’s correspondence with
Arnauld. His epoch-making Leibniz’s Logic 1 describes Leibniz’s metaphysics as
panlogism. Couturat published a study on Kant’s mathematical philosophy Revue
de Métaphysique, 4, and defended Peano’s logic, Whitehead’s algebra, and
Russell’s logistic in The Algebra of Logic 5. He also contributed to André
Lalande’s Vocabulaire technique et critique de la philosophie 6. Refs.: While the reference to “Deutero-Esperanto’ comes from
“Meaning revisited,” other keywords are useful, notably “Pirotese” and
“Symbolo.” Also keywords like “obble,” and “pirot.” The H. P. Grice Papers,
BANC.
diagoge: Grice makes a triad here: apagoge, diagoge, and epagoge. Cf.
Grice’s emphasis on the ‘argument’ involved in the conversational implciatum,
though. To work out an impilcatum is to reach it ‘by argument.’ No argument, no
conversational implicaturum. But cf. argument in Emissor draws skull and
communicates that there is danger. ARGUMENT involved in that Emissor intends
his addressee WILL REASON. Can the lady communicate to the pigeons that she is
selling ‘twopence a bag’ for their pleasure? Grice contrasted epagoge with
diagoge. Cooperation with competition. Cooperative game with competitive game. But
epagoge is induction, so here we’ll consider his views on probability and how
it contrastds with diagoge. The diagoge is easy to identity: Grice is a social
animal, with the BA, Philosophy, conferences, discussion, The American
Philosophical Association, transcripts by Randall Parker, from the audio-tapes
contained in c. 10 within the same s. IV miscellaneous, Beanfest, transcripts
and audio-cassettes, s. IV, c. 6-f. 8, and f. 10, and s. V, c. 8-f. 4-8 Unfortunately, Parker typed carulise
for karulise, or not. Re: probability, Grice loves to reminisce an anecdote
concerning his tutor Hardie at Corpus when Hardie invoked Mills principles
to prove that Hardie was not responsible for a traffic jam. In drafts on word
play, Grice would speak of not bringing more Grice to your Mill. Mills
System of Logic was part of the reading material for his degree in Lit.
Hum.at Oxford, so he was very familiar with it. Mill represents the best
of the English empiricist tradition. Grice kept an interest on inductive
methodology. In his Life and opinions he mentions some obscure essays by
Kneale and Keynes on the topic. Grice was interested in Kneales secondary
induction, since Grice saw this as an application of a construction routine.
He was also interested in Keyness notion of a generator property, which he
found metaphysically intriguing. Induction. Induction ‒ Mill’s
Induction, induction, deduction, abduction, Mill. More Grice to the Mill.
Grice loved Hardies playing with Mill’s method of difference with an Oxford
copper. He also quotes Kneale and Keynes on induction. Note that his seven-step
derivation of akrasia relies on an inductive step! Grice was fortunate to
associate with Davidson, whose initial work is on porbability. Grice borrows
from Davidson the idea that inductive probability, or probable, attaches to the
doxastic, while prima facie attaches to desirably, or
desirability. Jeffreys notion of desirability is partition-invariant
in that if a proposition, A, can be expressed as the disjoint disjunction of
both {B1, B2, B3} and {C1, C2, C3}, ∑ Bi ∈ AProb
(Bi ∣∣ A). Des (Bi) = ∑Ci ∈ A
Prob (Ci ∣∣ A). Des (Ci). It follows that applying the rule
of desirability maximization will always lead to the same recommendation,
irrespective of how the decision problem is framed, while an alternative theory
may recommend different courses of action, depending on how the decision
problem is formulated. Here, then, is the analogue of Jeffreys
desirability axiom (D), applied to sentences rather than propositions: (D)
(prob(s and t) = 0 and prob(s or t) "# 0, ⊃ d ( ) prob(s)des(s)+ prob(t)des(t) es s or t
=-"---- prob( s) + prob(t ) (Grice writes prob(s) for the Subjectsive
probability of sand des(s) for the desirability or utility of s.) B. Jeffrey admits
that "desirability" (his terms for evidential value) does not
directly correspond to any single pre-theoretical notion of desire. Instead, it
provides the best systematic explication of the decision theoretic idea, which
is itself our best effort to make precise the intuitive idea of weighing
options. As Jeffrey remarks, it is entirely possibly to desire someone’s love
when you already have it. Therefore, as Grice would follow, Jeffrey has the
desirability operator fall under the scope of the probability operator. The
agents desire that p provided he judges that p does not obtain.
Diagoge/epagoge, Grices audio-files, the audio-files, audio-files of various
lectures and conferences, some seminars with Warner and J. Baker, audio files
of various lectures and conferences. Subjects: epagoge, diagoge. A
previous folder in the collection contains the transcripts. These are the
audio-tapes themselves, obviously not in folder. The kind of metaphysical
argument which I have in mind might be said, perhaps, to exemplify a dia-gogic
or trans-ductive as opposed to epa-gogic or in-ductive approach to
philosophical argumentation. Hence Short and Lewis have, for ‘diagoge,’ the
cognates of ‘trādūco,’ f. transduco. Now, the more emphasis is placed on
justification by elimination of the rival, the greater is the impetus given to
refutation, whether of theses or of people. And perhaps a greater emphasis on a
diagogic procedure, if it could be shown to be justifiable, would have an
eirenic effect. Cf. Aristotle on diagoge, schole, otium. Liddell and Scott
have “διαγωγή,” which they render as “literally carrying across,” -- “τριήρων”
Polyaen.5.2.6, also as “carrying through,” and “hence fig.” “ἡ διὰ πάντων αὐτῶν
δ., “taking a person through a subject by instruction, Pl. Ep.343; so, course
of instruction, lectures, ἐν τῇ ἐνεστώσῃ δ. prob. in Phld. Piet.25; also
passing of life, way or course of life, “δ. βίου” Pl. R.344e: abs., Id.
Tht.177a, etc., way of passing time, amusement, “δ. μετὰ παιδιᾶς” Arist. EN
1127b34, cf. 1177a27; “δ. ἐλευθέριος” Id. Pol.1339b5; διαγωγαὶ τοῦ συζῆν public
pastimes, ib.1280b37, cf. Plu.126b (pl.). also delay, D.C. 57.3. management,
τῶν πραγμάτων δ. dispatch of business, Id.48.5. IV. station for ships, f. l. in
Hdn.4.2.8. And there are other entries to consider: διαγωγάν: διαίρεσιν,
διανομήν, διέλευσιν. Grice knew what he was talking about! Refs.: The main
sources listed under ‘desirability,’ above. There is a specific essay on
‘probability and life.’ Good keywords, too, are epagoge and induction The H. P.
Grice Papers, BANC.
dialogos
– the ‘dia’ means ‘trans-‘, not ‘two.’ Deuterologos δευτερο-λόγος , ὁ, A.second
speaker (though, not really conversationalist – cf. conversari) Teles p.5 H. --
is the exact opposite of monologos, cf. Aeschylus when he called on an Athenian
to play the second ‘fighter’ “deuteron-agonistes.” -- dialogical implicaturum – Grice seldom
uses ‘dialogue.’ It’s always conversational with him. He must have thought that
‘dialogue’ was too Buberian. In Roman, ‘she had a conversation with him’ means
‘she had sex with him.’ “She had a dialogue with him” does not. Classicists are
obsessed with the beginning of Greek theatre: it all started with ‘dialogue.’
It wasn’t like Aeschylus needed a partner. He wrote the parts for BOTH. Was he
reconstructing naturally-occurring Athenian dialogue? Who knows! The *two*-actor rule, which was indeed
preceded by a convention in which only a single actor would appear on stage,
along with the chorus. It was in 471 B. C. that Aeschylus introduces a second
actor, called Cleander. You see, Aeschylus
always cast himself as protagonist in his own plays. For the season of 471 B.
C., the Athenians were surprised when Aeschylus introduced Cleander as his
deuteragonist. “I can now conversationally implicate!” he said to a cheering
crowd! Dialogism -- Bakhtin: m. m., philosopher of dialogism -- and
cultural theorist whose influence is pervasive in a wide range of academic
disciplines from literary hermeneutics
to the epistemology of the human sciences, and cultural theory. He may
legitimately be called a philosophical anthropologist in the venerable
Continental tradition. Because of his seminal work on Rabelais and Dostoevsky’s
poetics, Baden School Bakhtin, Mikhail Mikhailovich 70 70 his influence has been greatest in
literary hermeneutics. Without question dialogism, or the construal of
dialogue, is the hallmark of Bakhtin’s thought. Dialogue marks the existential
condition of humanity in which the self and the other are asymmetrical but
double-binding. In his words, to exist means to communicate dialogically, and
when the dialogue ends, everything else ends. Unlike Hegelian and Marxian
dialectics but like the Chin. correlative logic of yin and yang, Bakhtin’s
dialogism is infinitely polyphonic, open-ended, and indeterminate, i.e.,
“unfinalizable” to use his term.
Dialogue means that there are neither first nor last words. The past and the
future are interlocked and revolve around the axis of the present. Bakhtin’s
dialogism is paradigmatic in a threefold sense. First, dialogue is never
abstract but embodied. The lived body is the material condition of social existence
as ongoing dialogue. Not only does the word become enfleshed, but dialogue is
also the incorporation of the self and the other. Appropriately, therefore,
Bakhtin’s body politics may be called a Slavic version of Tantrism. Second, the
Rabelaisian carnivalesque that Bakhtin’s dialogism incorporates points to the
“jesterly” politics of resistance and protest against the “priestly”
establishment of officialdom. Third, the most distinguishing characteristic of
Bakhtin’s dialogism is the primacy of the other over the self, with a twofold
consequence: one concerns ethics and the other epistemology. In modern
philosophy, the discovery of “Thou” or the primacy of the other over the self
in asymmetrical reciprocity is credited to Feuerbach. It is hailed as the “Copernican
revolution” of mind, ethics, and social thought. Ethically, Bakhtin’s
dialogism, based on heteronomy, signals the birth of a new philosophy of
responsibility that challenges and transgresses the Anglo- tradition of “rights
talk.” Epistemologically, it lends our welcoming ears to the credence that the
other may be right the attitude that
Gadamer calls the soul of dialogical hermeneutics.
diaphaneity: Grice unique in his
subtlety. Strawson and Wiggins. 'the quality of being freely pervious to light;
transparency', OED. This is a
crucial concept for Grice. He applies it ‘see,’ which which, after joint
endeavours with G. J. Warnock, he was obsessed! Grice considers the ascription,
“Warnock sees that it is raining.” And then he adds, “And it is true, I see
that it is raining, too.” What’s the diference. Then comes Strawson. “Strawson,
you see that it is raining, right?” So we have an ascription in the first,
second, and third persons. When it comes to the identification of a sense (like
vision) via experience or qualia, we are at a problem, because ‘see,’ allowing
for what Ryle calls a ‘conversational avowal,’ that nobody has an authority to
distrust, is what Grice calls a ‘diaphanous’ predicate. More formally. That
means that “Grice sees that it is raining,” in terms of experience, cannot
really be expanded except by expanding into WHAT IS that Grice sees, viz. that
it is raining. The same with “communicating that p,” and “meaning that p.”
dictum: Grice was fascinated with these multiple vowel roots:
dictum, deictis. Cf. dictor, and dictivenss. Not necessarily involved with
‘say,’ but with ‘deixis,’ So a dictum is involved in Emissor E drawing a skull,
communicating that there is danger. It is Hare who introduced ‘dictum’ in the
Oxonian philosophical literature in his T. H. Green Essay. Hare distinguishes
between the ‘dictum,’ that the cat is on the mat, from the ‘dictor,’ ‘I state
that the cat is on the mat, yes.’ ‘Cat, on the mat, please.’ Grice often refers
to Hare’s play with words, which he obviously enjoys. In “Epilogue,” Grice
elaborates on the ‘dictum,’ and turns it into ‘dictivitas.’ How does he coin
that word? He starts with Cicero, who has ‘dictivm,’ and creates an abstract
noun to match. Grice needs a concept of a ‘dictum’ ambiguous as it is. Grice
distinguishes between what an Utterer explicitly conveys, e. g. that Strawson
took off his boots and went to bed. Then there’s what Grice implicitly conveys,
to wit: that Strawson took off his boots and went to bed – in that order. Surely
Grice has STATED that Strawson took off his boots and went to bed. Grice has
ASSERTED that Strawson took off his boots and went to bed. But if Grice were to
order Strawson: “Put on your parachute and jump!” the implicatura may differ.
By uttering that utterance, Grice has not asserted or stated anything. So Grice
needs a dummy that will do for indicatives and imperatives. ‘Convey’ usually
does – especially in the modality ‘explicitly’ convey. Because by uttering that
utterance Grice has explicitly conveyed that Strawson is to put on his
parachute and jump. Grice has implicitly conveyd that Strawson is to put on his
parachute and THEN jump, surely.
Griceian
dignitas:
a moral worth or status usually attributed to human persons. Persons are said
to have dignity as well as to express it. Persons are typically thought to have
1 “human dignity” an dichotomy paradox dignity 234 234 intrinsic moral worth, a basic moral
status, or both, which is had equally by all persons; and 2 a “sense of
dignity” an awareness of one’s dignity inclining toward the expression of one’s
dignity and the avoidance of humiliation. Persons can lack a sense of dignity
without consequent loss of their human dignity. In Kant’s influential account
of the equal dignity of all persons, human dignity is grounded in the capacity
for practical rationality, especially the capacity for autonomous
self-legislation under the categorical imperative. Kant holds that dignity
contrasts with price and that there is nothing
not pleasure nor communal welfare nor other good consequences for which it is morally acceptable to
sacrifice human dignity. Kant’s categorical rejection of the use of persons as
mere means suggests a now-common link between the possession of human dignity
and human rights see, e.g., the United Nations’ Universal Declaration of Human
Rights. One now widespread discussion of dignity concerns “dying with dignity”
and the right to conditions conducive thereto.
Griceian
dilemma,
a trilemma, tetralemma, monolemma, lemma
– Grice thought that Ryle’s dilemmas
were overrated. Strictly, a ‘dilemma’ is a piece of reasoning or argument or
argument form in which one of the premises is a disjunction, featuring “or.” Constructive
dilemmas take the form ‘If A and B, if C, D, A or C; therefore, B or D’ and are
instances of modus ponendo ponens in the special case where A is C and B is D; A
so-called ‘destructive’ dilemma is of the form ‘If A, B, if C, D, not-B or
not-D; therefore, not-A or not-C’ and it is likewise an instance of modus tollendo tollens
in that special case. A dilemma in which the disjunctive premise is false is
commonly known as a “false” dilemma, which is one of Ryle’s dilemmas: “a
category mistake!”
diminutive: diminished capacity:
explored by Grice in his analysis of legal versus moral right -- a legal
defense to criminal liability that exists in two distinct forms: 1 the mens rea
variant, in which a defendant uses evidence of mental abnormality to cast doubt
on the prosecution’s assertion that, at the time of the crime, the defendant
possessed the mental state criteria, the mens rea, required by the legal
definition of the offense charged; and 2 the partial responsibility variant, in
which a defendant uses evidence of mental abnormality to support a claim that,
even if the defendant’s mental state satisfied the mens rea criteria for the
offense, the defendant’s responsibility for the crime is diminished and thus
the defendant should be convicted of a lesser crime and/or a lesser sentence
should be imposed. The mental abnormality may be produced by mental disorder,
intoxication, trauma, or other causes. The mens rea variant is not a distinct
excuse: a defendant is simply arguing that the prosecution cannot prove the
definitional, mental state criteria for the crime. Partial responsibility is an
excuse, but unlike the similar, complete excuse of legal insanity, partial
responsibility does not produce total acquittal; rather, a defendant’s claim is
for reduced punishment. A defendant may raise either or both variants of
diminished capacity and the insanity defense in the same case. For example, a
common definition of firstdegree murder requires the prosecution to prove that
a defendant intended to kill and did so after premeditation. A defendant
charged with this crime might raise both variants as follows. To deny the
allegation of premeditation, a defendant might claim that the killing occurred
instantaneously in response to a “command hallucination.” If believed, a
defendant cannot be convicted of premeditated homicide, but can be convicted of
the lesser crime of second-degree murder, which typically requires only intent.
And even a defendant who killed intentionally and premeditatedly might claim
partial responsibility because the psychotic mental state rendered the agent’s
reasons for action nonculpably irrational. In this case, either the degree of
crime might be reduced by operation of the partial excuse, rather than by
negation of definitional mens rea, or a defendant might be convicted of
first-degree murder but given a lesser penalty. In the United States the mens
rea variant exists in about half the jurisdictions, although its scope is
usually limited in various ways, primarily to avoid a defendant’s being
acquitted and freed if mental abnormality negated all the definitional mental
state criteria of the crime charged. In English law, the mens rea variant
exists but is limited by the type of evidence usable to support it. No jurisdiction has adopted a distinct,
straightforward partial responsibility variant, but various analogous doctrines
and procedures are widely accepted. For example, partial responsibility grounds
both the doctrine that intentional killing should be reduced from murder to
voluntary manslaughter if a defendant acted “in the heat of passion” upon
legally adequate provocation, and the sentencing judge’s discretion to award a
decreased sentence based on a defendant’s mental abnormality. In addition to
such partial responsibility analogues, England, Wales, and Scotland have
directly adopted the partial responsibility variant, termed “diminished
responsibility,” but it applies only to prosecutions for murder. “Diminished
responsibility” reduces a conviction to a lesser crime, such as manslaughter or
culpable homicide, for behavior that would otherwise constitute murder.
direction
of fit
– referred to by Grice in “Intention and uncertainty,” and symbolized by an
upward arrow and a downward arrow – there are only TWO directions (or senses)
of fit: expressum to ‘re’ and ‘re’ to expressum. The first is indicativus
modus; the second is imperativus modus -- according to his thesis of
aequivocality – the direction of fit is overrated -- a metaphor that derives
from a story in Anscombe’s Intention 7 about a detective who follows a shopper
around town making a list of the things that the shopper buys. As Anscombe
notes, whereas the detective’s list has to match the way the world is each of
the things the shopper buys must be on the detective’s list, the shopper’s list
is such that the world has to fit with it each of the things on the list are
things that he must buy. The metaphor is now standardly used to describe the
difference between kinds of speech act assertions versus commands and mental
states beliefs versus desires. For example, beliefs are said to have the
world-to-mind direction of fit because it is in the nature of beliefs that
their contents are supposed to match the world: false beliefs are to be
abandoned. Desires are said to have the opposite mind-to-world direction of fit
because it is in the nature of desires that the world is supposed to match
their contents. This is so at least to the extent that the role of an
unsatisfied desire that the world be a certain way is to prompt behavior aimed
at making the world that way.
disgrice: In PGRICE,
Kemmerling speaks of disgricing as the opposite of gricing. The first way to
disgrice Kemmerling calls ‘strawsonising.’For Strawson, even the resemblance
(for Grice, equivalence in terms of 'iff' -- cf. his account of what an
syntactically structured non-complete expression) between (G) There
is not a single volume in my uncle’s library which is not by an English
author,’and the negatively existential form (LFG) ~ (Ex)(Ax . ~ Bx)’
is deceptive, ‘It is not the case that there exists an x such that x is a book in Grice’s uncle’s
library and x is written by an
Englishman. FIRST, 'There is not a
single volume in uncle’s library which is not by an English author' -- as normally used, carries the
presupposition -- or entails, for Grice --
(G2) Some (at least one) book is in Grice’s uncle’s library. SECOND, 'There
is not a single volume in Grice’s uncle’s library which is not by an English
author,’ is far from being 'entailed' by (G3e) It is not the case that
there is some (at least one) book in my room. If we give ‘There not a single book in my room which is not by an English
author’ the modernist logical form ‘~
(Ex)(Ax .~ Bx),’ we see that this is ENTAILED
by the briefer, and indeed logicall stronger (in terms of entailments) ~ (Ex)Ax. So when Grice, with a solemn face, utters, ‘There
is not a single foreign volume in my uncle’s library, to reveal later that the library is empty, Grice should expect
his addressee to get some odd feeling. Surely not the feeling of having been
lied to -- or been confronted with an initial false utterance --, because we
have not. Strawson gets the feeling of having been made "the victim of a sort
of communicative outrage." "What you say is outrageous!" This
sounds stronger than it is. An outrage is believed to be an evil deed, offense,
crime; affront, indignity, act not within established or reasonable
limits," of food, drink, dress, speech, etc., from Old French outrage "harm, damage;
insult; criminal behavior; presumption, insolence, overweening" (12c.),
earlier oltrage (11c.),
From Vulgar Latin ‘ultraticum,’
excess," from Latin ultra,
beyond" (from suffixed form of PIE root *al- "beyond"). Etymologically, "the passing beyond
reasonable bounds" in any sense. The meaning narrowed in English toward
violent excesses because of folk etymology from out + rage. Of
injuries to feelings, principles, etc., from outrage, v. outragen, "to go to excess, act
immoderately," from outrage (n.)
or from Old French oultrager.
From 1580s with meaning "do violence to, attack, maltreat."
Related: Outraged; outraging. But Strawson gets the
feeling of having been made "the victim of a sort of communicative
outrage.” When Grice was only trying to tutor him in The Organon. Of
course it is not the case that Grice is explicitly conveying or expressing that
there there is some (at least one) book in his uncle's room. Grice has not said
anything false. Or rather, it is not the case that Grice utters an
utterance which is not alethically or doxastically satisfactory. Yet what Grice
gives Strawson the defeasible, cancellable, license to to assume that
Grice thinks there is at least one book. Unless he goes on to cancel the implicaturum,
Grice may be deemed to be misleading Strawson. What Grice explicitly conveys to
be true (or false) it is necessary (though not sufficient) that there should at
least one volume in his uncle’s library -- It is not the case that my uncle has
a library and in that library all the books are autochthonous to England, i.e.
it is not the case that Grice’s uncle has a library; for starters, it is not
the case that Grice has a literate uncle. Of this SUBTLE, nuantic, or cloudy or
foggy, "slight or delicate degree of difference in expression, feeling,
opinion, etc.," from Fr. nuance "slight difference, shade of colour,” from nuer "to
shade," from nue "cloud," from Gallo-Roman nuba, from
Latin nubes "a
cloud, mist, vapour," sneudh- "fog," source also of
Avestan snaoda "clouds,"
Latin obnubere "to
veil," Welsh nudd "fog," Greek nython, in
Hesychius "dark, dusky") According to Klein, the French usage is a
reference to "the different colours of the clouds,” in reference to color
or tone, "a slight variation in shade; of music, as a French term in
English -- 'sort' is the relation between ‘There is not a volume in my
uncle's library which is not by an English author,’ and ‘My uncle's
library is not empty. RE-ENTER GRICE. Grice suggested that Strawson see such a
fine point such as that, which Grice had the kindness to call an 'implicaturum',
the result of an act of an ‘implicatura’ (they were both attending Kneale’s
seminar on the growth and ungrowth of logic) is irrelevant to the issue of
‘entailment’. It is a 'merely pragmatic’ implicaturum, Grice would say,
bringing forward a couple of distinctions: logical/pragmatic point;
logical/pragmatic inference; entailment/implicaturum; conveying
explicitly/conveying implicitly; stating/implicating; asserting/implying; what
an utterer means/what the expression 'means' -- but cf. Nowell-Smith, who left
Oxford after being overwhelmed by Grice, "this is how the rules of
etiquette inform the rules of logic -- on the 'rule' of relevance in
"Ethics," 1955. If to call such a point, as Grice does, as "irrelevant
to logic" is vacuous in that it may be interpreted as saying that that
such a fine foggy point is not considered in a modernist formal system of
first-order predicate calculus with identity, this Strawson wishes not to
dispute, but to emphasise. Call it his battle cry! But to 'logic' as concerned
with this or that relation between this or that general class of statement
occurring in ordinary use, and the attending general condition under which this
or that statement is correctly called 'true' or 'false,' this fine foggy nice
point would hardly be irrelevant. GRICE'S FORMALIST (MODERNIST)
INTERPRETATION. Some 'pragmatic' consideration, or assumption, or expectation,
a desideratum of conversational conduct obviously underlies and in fact
'explains' the implicaturum, without having to change the ‘sense’ of
Aristotle’s syllogistics in terms of the logical forms of A, E, I, and O. If we
abide by an imperative of conversational helpfulness, enjoining the maximally
giving and receiving of information and the influencing and being influenced by
others in the institution of a decisions, the sub-imperative follows to the
effect, ‘Thou shalt NOT make a weak move compared to the stronger one that thou
canst truthfully make, and with equal or greater economy of means.’ Assume the
form ‘There is not a single … which is not . . .,’ or ‘It is not the case
that ... there is some (at least one) x that ... is not ... is introduced
in ‘ordinary’ language with the same SENSE as the expression in the
‘ideal’ language, ~(Ex)(Ax and ~Bx). Then prohibition inhibits the utterance of
the form where the utterer can truly and truthfully simply convey
explicitly ‘There is not a single ..., i. e. ~(Ex)(Fx). It is
defeasible prohibition which tends to confer on the overprolixic form ('it is
not the case that ... there is some (at least one) x that is not ...') just
that kind of an implicaturum which Strawson identifies. But having
detected a nuance in a conversational phenomenon is not the same thing as
rushing ahead to try to explain it BEFORE exploring in some detail what kind of
a nuance it is. The mistake is often commited by Austin, too (in "Other Minds,"
and "A Plea for Excuses"), and by Hart (on 'carefully'), and by Hare
(on "good"), and by Strawson on 'true,' (Analysis), ‘the,’ and 'if --
just to restrict to the play group. Grice tries to respond to anti-sense-datum
in "That pillar box seems red to me,” but Strawson was not listening. The overprolixic form in the ‘ordinary’
language, ‘It is not the case that there is some (at least one x) such that ...
x is not ...’ would tend, if it does not remain otiose, to develop or generate
just that baffling effect in one's addressee ('outrage!') that Strawson identifies,
as opposed to the formal-device in the ‘ideal’ language with which the the
‘ordinary’ language counterpart is co-related. What weakens our resistance
to the negatively existential analysis in this case more than in the case of
the corresponding "All '-sentence is the powerful attraction of the
negative opening phrase There is not …'. To avoid misunderstanding
one may add a point about the neo-traditionalist interpretation of the forms of
the traditional Aristotelian system. Strawson is not claiming that it
faithfully represents this or that intention of the principal exponent of the
Square of Opposition. Appuleius, who knows, was perhaps, more interested in
formulating this or that theorem governing this or that logical relation of
this or that more imposing general statement than this or that everyday general
statement that Strawson considers. Appuleius, who knows, might have
been interested, e. g., in the logical powers of this or that
generalisation, or this or that sentence which approximates more closely to the
desired conditions that if its utterance by anyone, at any time, at any place,
results in a true statement, so does its utterance by anyone else, at any other
time, at any other place. How far the account by the neo-traditionalist
of this or that general sentence of 'ordinary' langauge is adequate for every
generalization may well be under debate. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “In defence of
Appuleius,” BANC.
The explicaturum/implicaturum/disimplicaturum triad: Grice: “Strictly, it’s a dyad, since disimplicatum
is a derivative of one member of the dyad, the implicatum – so that the
opposition is binary (ex/in) with ‘dis-‘ as applied to the im-, cf.
disexplicaturum – (the annulation of an explicaturum). “We should not conclude
from this that an implication of the existence of thing said to be seen is NOT
part of the conventional meaning of ‘see’ nor even (as some philosophers have
done) that there is one sense of ‘see’ which lacks this implication!” (WoW:44).
If Oxonians are obsessed with ‘implication,’ do they NEED ‘disimplicaturum’?
Grice doesn’t think so! But sometimes you have to use it to correct a mistake.
Grice does not give names, but he says he has heard a philosopher claim that
there are two SENSES of ‘see,’ one which what one sees exists, and one in which
it doesn’t! It would be good to trace that! It relates, in any case to
‘remembers,’but not quite, and to ‘know.’ But not quite. The issue of ‘see’ is
not that central, since Grice realizes that it is just a modality of
perception, even if crucial. He coined ‘visum’ with Warnock to play with the
idea of ‘what is seen’ NOT being existent.
On another occasion, when he cannot name a ridiculous philosopher, he
invents him: “A philosopher will not be given much credit if he comes with an
account of the indefinite ‘one’ as having three senses: one proximate to the
emissor (“I broke a finger”), one distant (“He’s meeting a woman”) and one
where the link is not specified (“A flower”). he target is of course Davidson
having the cheek to quote Grice’s Henriette Herz Trust lecture for the BA!
Lewis and Short have ‘intendere’ under ‘in-tendo,’ which they render as ‘to
stretch out or forth, extend, also to turn ones attention to, exert one’s self
for, to purpose, endeavour,” and finaly as “intend”! “pergin, sceleste,
intendere hanc arguere?” Plaut. Mil. 2, 4, 27 Grices tends towards
claiming that you cannot extend what you dont intend. In the James lectures,
Grice mentions the use of is to mean seem (The tie is red in this light), and
see to mean hallucinate. Denying Existence: The Logic, Epistemology and Pragmatics of
...books.google.com › books ... then it seems unidiomatic if not ungrammatical
to speak of hallucinations as ... that fighting people and 156 APPEARING
UNREALS 4 Two Senses of "See"? A. Chakrabarti - 1997 - Language Arts
& Disciplines The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism,
Morality, and ...books.google.com › books sight, say sense-data; others will
then say that there are two senses of 'see'. ... wrong because I am dreaming or
hallucinating them, which of course could ... Stanley Cavell - 1999 -
Philosophy Wittgenstein and Perception - Page 37 - Google Books
Resultbooks.google.com › books For example, Gilbert Harman characterises the
two senses of see as follows: see† = 'the ... which is common to genuine cases
of seeing and to hallucinations. Michael Campbell, Michael O'Sullivan - 2015 -
Philosophy The Alleged Ambiguity of'See'www.jstor.org › stable
including dreams, hallucinations and the perception of physical objects. ...
existence of at least two senses of ' see' were his adherence to the doctrine
that 'see' ... by AR White - 1963 - Cited by 3 - Related articles
Seeing and Naming - jstorwww.jstor.org › stable there are or aren't two
senses of 'see'. If there are, I'm speaking of ... The third kind of case is
illustrated by Macbeth's dagger hallucination, at least if we assume ... by RJ
Hall - 1977 - Cited by 3 - Related articles Philosophy at
LaGuardia Community Collegewww.laguardia.edu › Philosophy › GADFLY-2011 PDF
Lastly, I will critically discuss Ayer's two senses of 'see', ... (e.g.,
hallucinations); it thus seems correct to say that ... Hallucinations are
hallucinations. There are. Talking about seeing: An examination of
some aspects of the ...etd.ohiolink.edu › ... I propose a distinction between
delusions and hallucinations,'and argue ... say that there are two senses of
.'see* in ordinary language or not, he does, as I will ... by KA Emmett - 1974
- Related articles Wittgenstein and
Perceptionciteseerx.ist.psu.edu › viewdoc › download PDF 2 Two senses of 'see'.
33 ... may see things that are not there, for example in hallucinations. ...
And so, hallucinations are not genuine perceptual experiences. by Y Arahata -
Related articles Allen Blur - University of
Yorkwww-users.york.ac.uk › Publications_files PDF of subjectively
indistinguishable hallucination (e.g. Crane 2006). ... and material objects of
sight, and correlatively for a distinction between two senses of 'see',. by K
Allen - Related articles Austin and sense-data - UBC Library Open
Collectionsopen.library.ubc.ca › ... › UBC Theses and Dissertations Sep 15,
2011 - (5) Illusions and Hallucinations It is not enough to reject Austin's way
of ... I will not deal with Austin and Ayer on "two senses of 'see'"
because I ... by DD Todd - 1967 - Cited by 1 - Related articles. Godfrey
Vesey (1965, p. 73) deposes, "if a person sees something at all it must
look like something to him, even if it only looks like 'somebody doing
something.' With Davidson, Grice was more cavalier, because he could
blame it on a different ‘New-World’ dialect or idiolect, about ‘intend.’ When
Grice uses ‘disimplicaturum’ to apply to ‘cream in coffee’ that is a bit
tangential – and refers more generally to his theory of communication. What
would the rationale of disimplicaturum be? In this case, if the emissee
realizes the obvious category mistake (“She’s not the cream in your coffee”)
there may be a need to disimplicate explicitly. To consider. There is an
example that he gives that compares with ‘see’ and it is even more
philosophical but he doesn’t give examples: to use ‘is’ when one means ‘seem’
(the tie example). The reductive
analyses of being and seeing hold. We have here two cases of loose use (or disimplicaturum).
Same now with his example in “Intention and Uncertainty” (henceforth,
“Uncertainty”): Smith intends to climb Mt. Everest + [common-ground status:
this is difficult]. Grices response to Davidsons pretty unfair use of Grices
notion of conversational implicaturum in Davidsons analysis of intention caught
a lot of interest. Pears loved Grices reply. Implicaturum here is out of the
question ‒ disimplicaturum may not. Grice just saw that his theory of
conversation is too social to be true when applied to intending. The doxastic
condition is one of the entailments in an ascription of an intending. It cannot
be cancelled as an implicaturum can. If it can be cancelled, it is best seen as
a disimplicaturum, or a loose use by an utterer meaning less than what he says
or explicitly conveys to more careful conversants. Grice and Davidson were
members of The Grice and Davidson Mutual Admiration Society. Davidson, not
being Oxonian, was perhaps not acquainted with Grices polemics at Oxford with
Hart and Hampshire (where Grice sided with Pears, rather). Grice and Pears
hold a minimalist approach to intending. On the other hand, Davidson makes
what Grice sees as the same mistake again of building certainty into the
concept. Grice finds that to apply the idea of a conversational implicaturum
at this point is too social to be true. Rather, Grice prefers to coin the
conversational disimplicaturum: Marmaduke Bloggs intends to climb Mt
Everest on hands and knees. The utterance above, if merely reporting what
Bloggs thinks, may involve a loose use of intends. The certainty on the
agents part on the success of his enterprise is thus cast with
doubt. Davidson was claiming that the agents belief in the probability of
the object of the agents intention was a mere conversational implicaturum on
the utterers part. Grice responds that the ascription of such a belief is
an entailment of a strict use of intend, even if, in cases where the utterer
aims at a conversational disimplicaturum, it can be dropped. The
addressee will still regard the utterer as abiding by the principle of
conversational helpfulness. Pears was especially interested in the
Davidson-Grice polemic on intending, disimplicaturum, disimplicaturum. Strictly,
a section of his reply to Davidson. If Grices claim to fame is implicaturum, he
finds disimplicaturum an intriguing notion to capture those occasions when an
utterer means LESS than he says. His examples include: a loose use of intending
(without the entailment of the doxastic condition), the uses of see in
Shakespeareian contexts (Macbeth saw Banquo, Hamlet saw his father on the
ramparts of Elsinore) and the use of is to mean seems (That tie is blue under
this light, but green otherwise, when both conversants know that a change of
colour is out of the question. He plays with Youre the cream in my coffee being
an utterance where the disimplicaturum (i.e. entailment dropping) is total. Disimplicaturum
does not appeal to a new principle of conversational rationality. It is
perfectly accountable by the principle of conversational helpfulness, in
particular, the desideratum of conversational candour. In everyday explanation we exploit, as Grice notes,
an immense richness in the family of expressions that might be thought of as
the wanting family. This wanting family includes expressions like want, desire,
would like to, is eager to, is anxious to, would mind not…, the idea of appeals to me, is thinking of, etc. As Grice
remarks, The likeness and differences within this wanting family demand careful
attention. In commenting on Davidsons treatment of wanting in
Intending, Grice notes: It seems to Grice that the picture of the soul
suggested by Davidsons treatment of wanting is remarkably tranquil and, one
might almost say, computerized. It is the picture of an ideally decorous board
meeting, at which the various heads of sections advance, from the standpoint of
their particular provinces, the case for or against some proposed course of
action. In the end the chairman passes judgement, effective for action;
normally judiciously, though sometimes he is for one reason or another
over-impressed with the presentation made by some particular member. Grices
soul doesnt seem to him, a lot of the time, to be like that at all. It is more
like a particularly unpleasant department meeting, in which some members shout,
wont listen, and suborn other members to lie on their behalf; while the
chairman, who is often himself under suspicion of cheating, endeavours to
impose some kind of order; frequently to no effect, since sometimes the meeting
breaks up in disorder, sometimes, though it appears to end comfortably, in
reality all sorts of enduring lesions are set up, and sometimes, whatever the
outcome of the meeting, individual members go off and do things unilaterally.
Could it be that Davidson, of the New World, and Grice, of the Old World, have
different idiolects regarding intend? Could well be! It is said that the New
World is prone to hyperbole, so perhaps in Grices more cautious use, intend is
restricted to the conditions HE wants it to restrict it too! Odd that for all
the generosity he displays in Post-war Oxford philosophy (Surely I can help you
analyse you concept of this or that, even if my use of the corresponding
expression does not agree with yours), he goes to attack Davidson, and just for
trying to be nice and apply the conversational implicaturum to intend! Genial
Grice! It is natural Davidson, with his naturalistic tendencies, would like to
see intending as merely invoking in a weak fashion the idea of a strong
psychological state as belief. And its natural that Grice hated that! Refs.:
The source is Grice’s comment on Davidson on intending. The H. P. Grice Papers,
BANC.
disjunctum: Strangely enough
Ariskant thought disjunctum, but not conjunctum a categorial related to the
category of ‘community’!Aulus Gellius (The Attic Nights, XVI, 8) tells us about
this disjunction: “There also is ■ another type of a^twpa which the Greeks call
and we call disjunctum, disjunctive sentence. Gellius notes that ‘or’ is by
default ‘inclusive’: where one or several propositions may be simultaneously
true, without ex- cluding one another, although they may also all be false.
Gellius expands on the non-default reading of exclusive disjunction: pleasure
is either good or bad or it is neither good nor bad (“Aut malum est voluplas,
aut bonum, aul neque bonum, neque malum est”). All the elements of the
exclusive disjunctive exclude one another, and their contradictory elements,
Gr. avTtxs'-p.sva, are incompatible with one another”. “Ex omnibus quae
disjunguntiir, unum esse verum debet, falsa cetera.”Grice lists ‘or’ as the
second binary functor in his response to Strawson. But both Grice and Strawson
agreed that the Oxonian expert on ‘or’ is Wood. Mitchell is good, too, though. The
relations between “v” and “or” (or “either ... or …”) are, on the whole, less
intimate than those between “.” and “and,” but less distant than those between
“D” and “if.” Let us speak of a statement made by coupling two clauses by “or” as
an alternative statement ; and let us speak of the first and second alternatesof
such a statement, on analogy with our talk of the antecedent and consequent of
a hypothetical statement. At a bus-stop, someone might say: “Either we catch
this bus or we shall have to walk all the way home.” He might equally well have
said “If we don't catch this bus, we shall have to walk all the way home.” It
will be seen that the antecedent of the hypothetical statement he might have
made is the negation of the first alternate of the alternative statement he did
make. Obviously, we should not regard our catching the bus as a sufficient
condition of the 'truth' of either statement; if it turns out that the bus we
caught was not the last one, we should say that the man who had made the
statement had been wrong. The truth of one of the alternates is no more a
sufficient condition of the truth of the alternative statement than the falsity
of the antecedent is a sufficient condition of the truth of the hypothetical
statement. And since 'p"Dpyq' (and, equally, * q"3p v q ') is a law
of the truth-functional system, this fact sufficiently shows a difference
between at least one standard use of “or” and the meaning given to “v.” Now in
all, or almost all, the cases where we are prepared to say something of the
form “p or q,” we are also prepared to say something of the form 4 if not-p,
then q \ And this fact may us to exaggerate the difference between “v” and “or”
to think that, since in some cases, the fulfilment of one alternate is not a
sufficient condition of the truth of the alternative statement of which It is
an alternate, the fulfilment of one alternate is a sufficient condition of the
truth of an alternative statement. And this is certainly an exaggeration. If
someone says ; “Either it was John or it was Robert but I couldn't tell which,”
we are satisfied of the truth of the alternative statement if either of the
alternates turns out to be true; and we say that the speaker was wrong only if
neither turns out to be true. Here we seem to have a puzzle ; for we seem to be
saying that * Either it was John or it was Robert ' entails 4 If it wasn't
John, it was Robert * and, at the same time, that ‘It was John’ entails the
former, but not the latter. What we are suffering from here is perhaps a
crudity in our notion of entailraent, a difficulty In applying this too
undifferentiated concept to the facts of speech ; or, if we prefer it, an
ambiguity in the notion of a sufficient condition. The statement that it was John
entails the statement that it was either John or Robert in the sense thai it
confirms it; when It turns out to have been John, the man who said that either
It was John or it was Robert is shown to have been right. But the first
statement does not entail the second in the sense that the step ‘It was John,
so it was either John or Robert’ is a logically proper step, unless the person saying
this means by it simply that the alternative statement made previously was
correct, i.e., 'it was one of the two '. For the alternative statement carries
the implication of the speaker's uncertainty as to which of the two it was, and
this implication is inconsistent with the assertion that it was John. So in
this sense of * sufficient condition ', the statement that it was John is no
more a sufficient condition of (no more entails) the statement that it was
either John or Robert than it is a sufficient condition of (entails) the
statement that if it wasn't John, it was Robert. The further resemblance, which
we have already noticed, between the alternative statement and the hypothetical
statement, is that whatever knowledge or experience renders it reasonable to
assert the alternative statement, also renders it reasonable to make the
statement that (under the condition that it wasn't John) it was Robert. But we
are less happy about saying that the hypothetical statement is confirmed by the
discovery that it was John, than we are about saying that the alternative
statement is confirmed by this discovery. For we are inclined to say that the
question of confirmation of the hypothetical statement (as opposed to the
question of its reasonableness or acceptability) arises only if the condition
(that it wasn't John) turns out to be fulfilled. This shows an asymmetry, as
regards confirmation, though not as regards acceptability, between 4 if not p,
then q ' and * if not qy then p ' which is not mirrored in the forms ‘either p
or q’ and ‘either q or p.’ This asymmetry is ignored in the rule that * if not
p, then q ' and ‘if not q, then p’ are logically equivalent, for this rule
regards acceptability rather than confirmation. And rightly. For we may often
discuss the l truth ' of a subjunctive conditional, where the possibility of
confirmation is suggested by the form of words employed to be not envisaged. It
is a not unrelated difference between * if ' sentences and ‘or’ sentences that
whereas, whenever we use one of the latter, we should also be prepared to use
one of the former, the converse does not hold. The cases in which it does not
generally hold are those of subjunctive conditionals. There is no ‘or’ sentence
which would serve as a paraphrase of ‘If the Germans had invaded England in
1940, they would have won the war’ as this sentence would most commonly be
used. And this is connected with the fact that c either . . . or . . .' is
associated with situations involving choice or decision. 4 Either of these
roads leads to Oxford ' does not mean the same as ' Either this road leads to
Oxford or that road does’ ; but both confront us with the necessity of making a
choice. This brings us to a feature of * or ' which, unlike those so far
discussed, is commonly mentioned in discussion of its relation to * v ' ; the
fact, namely, that in certain verbal contexts, ‘either … or …’ plainly carries
the implication ‘and not both . . . and . . .', whereas in other contexts, it
does not. These are sometimes spoken of as, respectively, the exclusive and
inclusive senses of ‘or;’ and, plainly, if we are to identify 4 v’ with either,
it must be the latter. The reason why, unlike others, this feature of the
ordinary use of “or” is commonly mentioned, is that the difference can readily
be accommodated (1 Cf. footnote to p. 86.In the symbolism of the
truth-functional system: It is the difference between “(p y q) .~ (p . q)”
(exclusive sense) and “p v q” (inclusive sense). “Or,” like “and,” is commonly
used to join words and phrases as well as clauses. The 4 mutuality difficulties
attending the general expansion of 4 x and y are/ 5 into * x is /and y is/' do
not attend the expansion of 4 x or y isf into c r Is/or y is/ ? (This is not to
say that the expansion can always correctly be made. We may call “v” the
disjunctive sign and, being warned against taking the reading too seriously,
may read it as ‘or.' While he never approached the topic separately, it’s easy
to find remarks about disjunction in his oeuvre. A veritable genealogy of
disjunction can be traced along Griceian lines. DISJUNCTUM -- disjunction
elimination. 1 The argument form ‘A or B, if A then C, if B then C; therefore,
C’ and arguments of this form. 2 The rule of inference that permits one to
infer C from a disjunction together with derivations of C from each of the
disjuncts separately. This is also known as the rule of disjunctive elimination
or V-elimination. disjunction
introduction. 1 The argument form ‘A or B; therefore, A or B’ and arguments of
this form. 2 The rule of inference that permits one to infer a disjunction from
either of its disjuncts. This is also known as the rule of addition or
Vintroduction. . disjunctive
proposition, a proposition whose main propositional operator main connective is
the disjunction operator, i.e., the logical operator that represents ‘and/or’.
Thus, ‘P-and/orQ-and-R’ is not a disjunctive proposition because its main
connective is the conjunction operation, but ‘P-and/or-Q-and-R’ is disjunctive.
Refs.: Grice uses an illustration involving ‘or’ in the ‘implication’ excursus
in “Causal Theory.” But the systematic account comes from WoW, especially essay
4.
dispositum. Grice: “The
–positum is a very formative Roman expression: there’s the suppositum, the
praepositum, and the dispositum. All very apposite!” -- H. P. Grice,
“Disposition and intention” – Grice inspired D. F. Pears on this, as they tried
to refute Austin’s rather dogmatic views in ‘ifs’ and ‘cans’ – where the ‘can’
relates to the disposition, and the ‘if’ to the conditional analysis for it.
Grice’s phrase is “if I can”. “I intend to climb Mt Everest on hands and
knees,” Marmaduke Bloggs says, “if a can.” A disposition, more generally is,
any tendency of an object or system to act or react in characteristic ways in
certain situations. Fragility, solubility, and radioactivity, and
intentionality, are typical dispositions. And so are generosity and
irritability. For Ryle’s brand of analytic behaviorism, functionalism, and some
forms of materialism, an event of the soul, such as the occurrence of an idea,
and states such as a belief, a will, or an intention, is also a disposition. A hypothetical or
conditional statement is alleged to be ‘implicated’ by dispositional claims.
What’s worse, this conditional is alleged to capture the basic meaning of the
ascription of a state of the soul. The glass would shatter if suitably struck.
Left undisturbed, a radium atom will probably decay in a certain time. An
ascription of a disposition is taken as subjunctive rather than material
conditionals to avoid problems like having to count as soluble anything not
immersed in water. The characteristic mode of action or reaction shattering, decaying, etc. is termed the disposition’s manifestation or
display. But it need not be observable. Fragility is a regular or universal
disposition. A suitably struck glass invariably shatters. Radio-activity on the
other hand is alleged to be a variable or probabilistic disposition. Radium may
(but then again may not) decay in a certain situation. A dispositions may be
what Grice calls “multi-track,” i. e. multiply
manifested, rather than “single-track,” or singly manifested. Hardness or
elasticity may have different manifestations in different situations. In his
very controversial (and only famous essay), “The Concept of Mind,” Ryle, who
held, no less, the chair of metaphysical philosophy at Oxford, argues – just to
provoke -- that there is nothing more to a dispositional claim than its
associated conditional. A dispositional property is not an occurrent property.
To possess a dispositional property is not to undergo any episode or
occurrence, or to be in a particular state. Grice surely refuted this when he
claims that the soul is in this or that a state. Consider reasoning. The soul
is in state premise; then the soul is in state conclusion. The episode or
occurrence is an event, when the state of the premise causes the state of the
conclusion. Coupled with a ‘positivist’ (or ultra-physicalist,
ultra-empiricist, and ultra-naturalist) rejection of any unobservable, and a
conception of an alleged episode or state of the soul as a dispositios, this
supports the view of behaviorism that such alleged episode or state is nothing
but a disposition TO observable behaviour – if Grice intends to climb Mt.
Everest on hands and knees if he can, there is no ascription without the
behaviour that manifests it – the ascription is meant to EXPLAIN (or explicate,
or provide the cause) for the behaviour. Grice reached this ‘functionalist’
approach later in his career, and presented it with full fanfare in “Method in
philosophoical psychology: from the banal to the bizarre.” By contrast, realism
holds that dispositional talk is also about an actual or occurrent property or a
state, possibly unknown or unobservable – the ‘black box’ of the functionalist,
a function from sensory input to behavioural output. In particular, it is about
the bases of dispositions in intrinsic properties or states. Thus, fragility is
based in molecular structure, radioactivity in nuclear structure. A
disposition’s basis is viewed as at least partly the cause of its manifestation
in behaviour. Some philosophers, for fear of an infinite regress, hold that the
basis is categorical, not dispositional D. M. Armstrong, A Materialist Theory
of Mind, 8. Others, notably Popper, Madden, and Harre (Causal powers) hold that
every property is dispositional. Grice’s essay has now historical interest –
but showed the relevance of these topics among two tightly closed groups in
post-war Oxford: the dispositionalists led by Ryle, and the
anti-dispositionalists, a one-member group led by Grice. Refs.: Grice,
“Intention and dispositions.”
distributum: distributio -- undistributed middle: a logical
fallacy in traditional syllogistic logic, resulting from the violation of the
rule that the middle term (the term that appears twice in premises) must be
distributed at least once in the premises. Any syllogism that commits this
error is invalid. Consider “All philosophers are persons,” and “Some persons
are bad.” No conclusion follows from these two premises because “persons” in
the first premise is the predicate of an affirmative proposition, and in the
second is the subject of a particular proposition. Neither of them is
distributed. “If in a syllogism the middle term is distributed in neither
premise, we are said to have a fallacy of undistributed middle.” Keynes, Formal
Logic. DISTRIBUTUM -- distribution, the property of standing for every
individual designated by a term. The Latin term distributio originated in the
twelfth century; it was applied to terms as part of a theory of reference, and
it may have simply indicated the property of a term prefixed by a universal
quantifier. The term ‘dog’ in ‘Every dog has his day’ is distributed, because
it supposedly refers to every dog. In contrast, the same term in ‘A dog bit the
mailman’ is not distributed because it refers to only one dog. In time, the idea
of distribution came to be used only as a heuristic device for determining the
validity of categorical syllogisms: 1 every term that is distributed in a
premise must be distributed in the conclusion; 2 the middle term must be
distributed at least once. Most explanations of distribution in logic textbooks
are perfunctory; and it is stipulated that the subject terms of universal
propositions and the predicate terms of negative propositions are distributed.
This is intuitive for A-propositions, e.g., ‘All humans are mortal’; the
property of being mortal is distributed over each human. The idea of
distribution is not intuitive for, say, the predicate term of O-propositions.
According to the doctrine, the sentence ‘Some humans are not selfish’ says in
effect that if all the selfish things are compared with some select human one
that is not selfish, the relation of identity does not hold between that human
and any of the selfish things. Notice that the idea of distribution is not
mentioned in this explanation. The idea of distribution is currently
disreputable, mostly because of the criticisms of Geach in Reference and
Generality 8 and its irrelevance to standard semantic theories. The related
term ‘distributively’ means ‘in a manner designating every item in a group
individually’, and is used in contrast with ‘collectively’. The sentence ‘The
rocks weighed 100 pounds’ is ambiguous. If ‘rocks’ is taken distributively,
then the sentence means that each rock weighed 100 pounds. If ‘rocks’ is taken
collectively, then the sentence means that the total weight of the rocks was
100 pounds. distributive laws, the
logical principles A 8 B 7 C S A 8 B 7 A 7 C and A 7 B 8 C S A 7 B 8 A 7 C.
Conjunction is thus said to distribute over disjunction and disjunction over
conjunction.
ditto: Or Strawson’s big mistake. Strawson quite didn’t
understand what “Analysis” was for, and submits this essay on the
perlocutionary effects of ‘true.’ Grice comes to the resuce of veritable
analysis. cf. verum. Grice disliked Strawson’s ditto theory in Analysis of
‘true’ as admittive performatory. 1620s, "in the month of the same
name," Tuscan dialectal ditto "(in) the said (month or year),"
literary Italian detto, past participle of dire "to say," from Latin
dicere "speak, tell, say" (from PIE root *deik- "to show,"
also "pronounce solemnly"). Italian used the word to avoid
repetition of month names in a series of dates, and in this sense it was picked
up in English. Its generalized meaning of "the aforesaid, the same thing,
same as above" is attested in English by 1670s. In early 19c. a suit of
men's clothes of the same color and material through was ditto or dittoes
(1755). Dittohead, self-description of followers of U.S. radio personality Rush
Limbaugh, attested by 1995. dittoship is from 1869.
dodgson: c. l. – Grice quotes Carroll often. Cabbages and
kings – Achilles and the Tortoise – Humpty Dumpty and his Deutero-Esperanto -- Carroll,
Lewis, pen name of Charles Lutwidge Dodgson 183298, English writer and
mathematician. The eldest son of a large clerical family, he was educated at
Rugby and Christ Church, Oxford, where he remained for the rest of his
uneventful life, as mathematical lecturer until 1 and curator of the senior
commonroom. His mathematical writings under his own name are more numerous than
important. He was, however, the only Oxonian of his day to contribute to
symbolic logic, and is remembered for his syllogistic diagrams, for his methods
for constructing and solving elaborate sorites problems, for his early interest
in logical paradoxes, and for the many amusing examples that continue to
reappear in modern textbooks. Fame descended upon him almost by accident, as the
author of Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland 1865, Through the Looking Glass
1872, The Hunting of the Snark 1876, and Sylvie and Bruno 9 93; saving the
last, the only children’s books to bring no blush of embarrassment to an adult
reader’s cheek. Dodgson took deacon’s orders in 1861, and though pastorally
inactive, was in many ways an archetype of the prim Victorian clergyman. His
religious opinions were carefully thought out, but not of great philosophic
interest. The Oxford movement passed him by; he worried about sin though
rejecting the doctrine of eternal punishment, abhorred profanity, and fussed
over Sunday observance, but was oddly tolerant of theatergoing, a lifelong
habit of his own. Apart from the sentimental messages later inserted in them,
the Alice books and Snark are blessedly devoid of religious or moral concern.
Full of rudeness, aggression, and quarrelsome, if fallacious, argument, they
have, on the other hand, a natural attraction for philosophers, who pillage
Carneades Carroll, Lewis 119 119 them
freely for illustrations. Humpty-Dumpty, the various Kings and Queens, the Mad
Hatter, the Caterpillar, the White Rabbit, the Cheshire Cat, the Unicorn, the
Tweedle brothers, the Bellman, the Baker, and the Snark make fleeting
appearances in the s of Russell, Moore, Broad, Quine, Nagel, Austin, Ayer,
Ryle, Blanshard, and even Vitters an unlikely admirer of the Mock Turtle. The
first such allusion to the March Hare is in Venn’s Symbolic Logic 1. The usual
reasons for quotation are to make some point about meaning, stipulative
definition, the logic of negation, time reversal, dream consciousness, the
reification of fictions and nonentities, or the absurdities that arise from
taking “ordinary language” too literally. For exponents of word processing, the
effect of running Jabberwocky through a spell-checker is to extinguish all hope
for the future of Artificial Intelligence. Though himself no philosopher,
Carroll’s unique sense of philosophic humor keeps him and his illustrator, Sir
John Tenniel effortlessly alive in the modern age. Alice has been tr. into
seventy-five languages; new editions and critical studies appear every year;
imitations, parodies, cartoons, quotations, and ephemera proliferate beyond
number; and Carroll societies flourish in several countries, notably Britain
and the United States. Refs.: Sutherland, “Grice, Dodgson, and Carroll. The
Carrolian, the journal of the Lewis Carroll Society – Jabberwocky: the
newsletter of the Lewis Carroll Society. A. M. Ghersi, “Turtles and mock-turtles,”
from “Correspondence with Derek Foster.” Alice’s adventures in Griceland.
dominium -- domain – used by Grice in his treatment of
Extensionalism -- of a science, the class of individuals that constitute its
subject matter. Zoology, number theory, and plane geometry have as their
respective domains the class of animals, the class of natural numbers, and the
class of plane figures. In Posterior Analytics 76b10, Aristotle observes that
each science presupposes its domain, its basic concepts, and its basic
principles. In modern formalizations of a science using a standard firstorder
formal language, the domain of the science is often, but not always, taken as
the universe of the intended interpretation or intended model, i.e. as the
range of values of the individual variables.
donkey – quantification – considered by Grice -- sentences,
sentences exemplified by ‘Every man who owns a donkey beats it’, ‘If a man owns
a donkey, he beats it’, and similar forms (“Every nice girl loves a sailor”),
which have posed logical puzzles since medieval times but were noted more
recently by Geach. At issue is the logical form of such sentences specifically, the correct construal of the
pronoun ‘it’ and the indefinite noun phrase ‘a donkey’. Translations into
predicate logic by the usual strategy of rendering the indefinite as
existential quantification and the pronoun as a bound variable cf. ‘John owns a
donkey and beats it’ P Dx x is a donkey & John owns x & John beats x
are either ill-formed or have the wrong truth conditions. With a universal
quantifier, the logical form carries the controversial implication that every
donkey-owning man beats every donkey he owns. Efforts to resolve these issues
have spawned much significant research in logic and linguistic semantics.
dossier: Grice is not clear about the status of this – but
some philosophers have been too mentalistic. How would a genitorial programme
proceed. Is there a dossier in a handwave by which the emissor communicates
that he knows the route or that he is about to leave his emissee. It does not
seem so, because the handwave is unstructured. Unlike “Fido is shaggy.” In the
case of “Fido is shaggy,” there must be some OVERLAP between the emissor’s soul
and the emissee’s soul – in terms of dossier. So perhaps there is overlap in
the handwave. There must be an overlap as to WHICH route he means. By making
the handwave the emissor communicates that HE, the emissor, subject IS (copula)
followed by predicate “knower of the route.” So here we have a definite ‘the
route.’ Which route? To heaven, to hell. Cf. The scots ‘high road,’ ‘low road.’
To Loch Lomond. If there is not this minimal common ground nothing can be
communicated. In the alternative meaning, “I (subject) am (copula) about to
leave you – where again there must be an overlap in the identification of the
denotata of the pronouns. In the case of Blackburn’s skull or the arrow at the
fork of a road, the common ground is instituted in situu in the one-off
predicament, and there still must be some overlap of dossier. In its most
technical usage, Grice wants to demystify Donnellan’s identificatory versus
non-identificatory uses of ‘the,’ as unnecessary implications to Russell’s
otherwise neat account. The topic interested Strawson (“Principle of assumption
of ignorance, knowledge and relevance”) and Urmson’s principle of aptitude. Grice’s
favourite vacuous name is ‘Bellerophon.’ ‘Vacuous names’ is an essay
commissioned by Davison and Hintikka for Words and objections: essays on the
work of W. V. Quine (henceforth, W and O) for Reidel, Dordrecht. “W and O” had
appeared (without Grices contribution) as a special issue of Synthese. Grices
contribution, along with Quines Reply to Grice, appeared only in the reprint of
that special issue for Reidel in Dordrecht. Grice cites from various
philosophers (and logicians ‒ this was the time when logic was starting to
be taught outside philosophy departments, or sub-faculties), such as Mitchell,
Myro, Mates, Donnellan, Strawson, Grice was particularly
proud to be able to quote Mates by mouth or book. Grice takes the
opportunity, in his tribute to Quine, to introduce one of two of his
syntactical devices to allow for conversational implicatura to be given maximal
scope. The device in Vacuous Namess is a subscription device to indicate
the ordering of introduction of this or that operation. Grice wants to
give room for utterances of a special existential kind be deemed
rational/reasonable, provided the principle of conversational helfpulness is
thought of by the addressee to be followed by the utterer. Someone isnt
attending the party organised by the Merseyside Geographical Society. That
is Marmaduke Bloggs, who climbed Mt. Everest on hands and knees. But who,
as it happened, turned out to be an invention of the journalists at the
Merseyside Newsletter, “W and O,” vacuous name, identificatory use,
non-identificatory use, subscript device. Davidson and Hintikka were well aware
of the New-World impact of the Old-World ideas displayed by Grice and
Strawson in their attack to Quine. Quine had indeed addressed Grices and
Strawsons sophisticated version of the paradigm-case argument in Word and
Object. Davidson and Hintikka arranged to publish a special issue for a
periodical publication, to which Strawson had already contributed. It was only
natural, when Davidson and Hintikka were informed by Reidel of their interest
in turning the special issue into a separate volume, that they would approach
the other infamous member of the dynamic duo! Commissioned by Davidson and
Hintikka for “W and O.” Grice introduces a subscript device to account for implicatura
of utterances like Marmaduke Bloggs won’t be attending the party; he was
invented by the journalists. In the later section, he explores
identificatory and non identificatory uses of the without involving himself in
the problems Donnellan did! Some philosophers, notably Ostertag, have
found the latter section the most intriguing bit, and thus Ostertag cared to
reprint the section on Descriptions for his edited MIT volume on the topic. The
essay is structured very systematically with an initial section on a calculus
alla Gentzen, followed by implicatura of vacuous Namess such as Marmaduke
Bloggs, to end with definite descriptions, repr. in Ostertag, and psychological
predicates. It is best to focus on a few things here. First his imaginary
dialogues on Marmaduke Bloggs, brilliant! Second, this as a preamble to his
Presupposition and conversational implicaturum. There is a quantifier phrase,
the, and two uses of it: one is an identificatory use (the haberdasher is
clumsy, or THE haberdasher is clumsy, as Grice prefers) and then theres a
derived, non-identificatory use: the haberdasher (whoever she was! to use
Grices and Mitchells addendum) shows her clumsiness. The use of the numeric
subscripts were complicated enough to delay the publication of this. The whole
thing was a special issue of a journal. Grices contribution came when Reidel
turned that into a volume. Grice later replaced his numeric subscript device by
square brackets. Perhaps the square brackets are not subtle enough,
though. Grices contribution, Vacuous Namess, later repr. in part “Definite
descriptions,” ed. Ostertag, concludes with an exploration of the phrases, and
further on, with some intriguing remarks on the subtle issues surrounding the
scope of an ascription of a predicate standing for a psychological state or
attitude. Grices choice of an ascription now notably involves an
opaque (rather than factive, like know) psychological state or attitude:
wanting, which he symbolizes as W. At least Grice does not write,
really, for he knew that Austin detested a trouser word! Grice concludes that
(xi) and (xiii) will be derivable from each of (ix) and (x), while (xii) will
be derivable only from (ix).Grice had been Strawsons logic tutor at St. Johns
(Mabbott was teaching the grand stuff!) and it shows! One topic that especially
concerned Grice relates to the introduction and elimination rules, as he later
searches for generic satisfactoriness. Grice
wonders [W]hat should be said of Takeutis conjecture (roughly)
that the nature of the introduction rule determines the character of
the elimination rule? There seems to be
no particular problem about allowing an introduction rule which tells
us that, if it is established in Xs personalized system that φ, then it is
necessary with respect to X that φ is true (establishable). The accompanying
elimination rule is, however, slightly less promising. If we suppose such a
rule to tell us that, if one is committed to the idea that it is necessary with
respect to X that φ, then one is also committed to whatever is expressed by φ,
we shall be in trouble; for such a rule is not acceptable; φ will be a volitive
expression such as let it be that X eats his hat; and my commitment to the idea
that Xs system requires him to eat his hat does not ipso facto involve me in
accepting (buletically) let X eat his hat. But if we take the elimination rule
rather as telling us that, if it is necessary with respect to X that let X eat
his hat, then let X eat his hat possesses satisfactoriness-with-respect-to-X,
the situation is easier; for this version of the rule seems inoffensive, even
for Takeuti, we hope. A very interesting concept Grice introduces in the
definite-descriptor section of Vacuous Namess is that of a conversational
dossier, for which he uses δ for a definite descriptor. The key concept is that
of conversational dossier overlap, common ground, or conversational pool. Let
us say that an utterer U has a dossier for a definite description δ if there is
a set of definite descriptions which include δ, all the members of which the
utterer supposes to be satisfied by one and the same item and the utterer U
intends his addressee A to think (via the recognition that A is so intended)
that the utterer U has a dossier for the definite description δ which the
utterer uses, and that the utterer U has specifically selected (or chosen, or
picked) this specific δ from this dossier at least partly in the hope that his
addressee A has his own dossier for δ which overlaps the utterers dossier for δ,
viz. shares a substantial, or in some way specially favoured, su-bset with the
utterers dossier. Its unfortunate that the idea of a dossier is not better
known amog Oxonian philosophers. Unlike approaches to the phenomenon by other
Oxonian philosophers like Grices tutee Strawson and his three principles
(conversational relevance, presumption of conversational knowledge, and
presumption of conversational ignorance) or Urmson and his, apter than
Strawsons, principle of conversational appositeness (Mrs.Smiths husband just
delivered a letter, You mean the postman!?), only Grice took to task the idea
of formalising this in terms of set-theory and philosophical
psychology ‒ note his charming reference to the utterers hope (never
mind intention) that his choice of d from his dossier will overlap with some d
in the dossier of his his addressee. The point of adding whoever he may be for
the non-identificatory is made by Mitchell, of Worcester, in his Griceian
textbook for Hutchinson. Refs.: The main reference is Grice’s “Vacuous names,”
in “W and O” and its attending notes, BANC.
doxastic – discussed by J. L. Austin in the myth of the cave.
Plato is doing some form of linguistic botany when he distinguishes between the
doxa and the episteme – Stich made it worse with his ‘sub-doxastic’! from
Grecian doxa, ‘belief’, of or pertaining to belief. A doxastic mental state,
for instance, is or incorporates a belief. Doxastic states of mind are to be
distinguished, on the one hand, from such non-doxastic states as desires,
sensations, and emotions, and, on the other hand, from subdoxastic states. By
extension, a doxastic principle is a principle governing belief. A doxastic
principle might set out conditions under which an agent’s forming or abandoning
a belief is justified epistemically or otherwise.
doxographia
griceiana -- Griceian doxographers. A
Griceian doxographer is a a compiler of andcommentators on the opinions of
Grice. “I am my first doxographer,” Grice said. Grice enjoyed the term coined
by H. Diels for the title of his work “Doxographi Graeci,” which Grice typed
“Doxographi Gricei”. In his “Doxographi,” Diels assembles a series of Grecian
texts in which the views of Grecian philosophers from the archaic to the
Hellenistic era are set out in a relatively schematic way. In the introduction,
Diels reconstructs the history of the writing of these opinions, viz. the
doxography strictly – the ‘writing’ (graphein) of the ‘opinion’ (“doxa”) – cfr.
the unwritten opinions; Diels’s ‘Doxographi’ is now a standard part of the
historiography of philosophy. Doxography is important both as a source of
information about a philosopher, and also because a later philosopher (later
than Grice, that is), ancient, medieval, and modern, should rely on it besides
what Diels calls the ‘primary’ material – “what Grice actually philosophised
on.” The crucial text for Diels’s reconstruction is the book Physical Opinions
of the Philosophers Placita Philosophorum, traditionally ascribed to Plutarch
but no longer thought to be by him. “Placita philosophorum” lists the views of
various philosophers and schools under subject headings such as “What Is
Nature?” and “On the Rainbow.” Out of this oeuvre and others Diels reconstructs
a Collection of Opinions that he ascribes to Aetius, a philosopher mentioned by
Theodoret as its author. Diels takes Aetius’s ultimate source to be
Theophrastus, who wrote a more discursive Physical Opinions. Because Aetius
mentions the views of Hellenistic philosophers writing after Theophrastus,
Diels postulates an intermediate source, which he calls the “Vetusta Placita.” The
most accessible doxographical material for Grice is in “The Life of Opinions of
the Eminent Philosopher H. P. Grice,” “Vita et sententiae H. P. Griceiani quo
in philosophia probatus fuit.” by H. P. Grice, après “Vitae et sententiae eorum qui in
philosophia probati fuerunt,”
by Diogenes Laertius, who is, however, mainly interested in gossip.
Laertius arranges philosophers by schools and treats each school
chronologically.
dummett – Dummett on ‘implicaturum’ in “Truth and other
enigmas” – Note the animosity by Dummett against
Grice’s playgroup for Grice never inviting him to a Saturday morning! “I will say this: conversational implicaturum, or as he
fastidiously would prefer, the ‘implicaturum,’ was, yes, ‘invented,’ by H. P.
Grice, of St. John’s, but University Lecturer, to boot, to replace an abstract
semantic concept such as Frege’s ‘Sinn,’ expelled in Grice’s original
Playgroup’s determination to pay attention, in the typical Oxonian manner, to
nothing but what an *emisor* (never mind his emission!) ‘communicates’ in a
‘particularised’ context — so that was a good thing -- for Grice!” “Truth and other enigmas.” Cited by Grice in Way of
Words -- dummett, m. a. e. – cited by H. P. Grice. philosopher of language,
logic, and mathematics, noted for his sympathy for metaphysical antirealism and
for his exposition of the philosophy of Frege. Dummett regards allegiance to
the principle of bivalence as the hallmark of a realist attitude toward any
field of discourse. This is the principle that any meaningful assertoric
sentence must be determinately either true or else false, independently of
anyone’s ability to ascertain its truth-value by recourse to appropriate
empirical evidence or methods of proof. According to Dummett, the sentences of
any learnable language cannot have verification-transcendent truth conditions
and consequently we should query the intelligibility of certain statements that
realists regard as meaningful. On these grounds, he calls into question realism
about the past and realism in the philosophy of mathematics in several of the
papers in two collections of his essays, Truth and Other Enigmas 8 and The Seas
of Language 3. In The Logical Basis of Metaphysics 1, Dummett makes clear his
view that the fundamental questions of metaphysics have to be approached
through the philosophy of language, and more specifically through the theory of
meaning. Here his philosophical debts to Frege and Vitters are manifest.
Dummett has been the world’s foremost expositor and champion of Frege’s
philosophy, above all in two highly influential books, Frege: Philosophy of
Language 3 and Frege: Philosophy of Mathematics 1. This is despite the fact
that Frege himself advocated a form of Platonism in semantics and the
philosophy of mathematics that is quite at odds with Dummett’s own anti-realist
inclinations. It would appear, however, from what Dummett says in Origins of
Analytical Philosophy 3, that he regards Frege’s great achievement as that of
having presaged the “linguistic turn” in philosophy that was to see its most
valuable fruit in the later work of Vitters. Vitters’s principle that grasp of
the meaning of a linguistic expression must be exhaustively manifested by the
use of that expression is one that underlies Dummett’s own approach to meaning
and his anti-realist leanings. In logic and the philosophy of mathematics this
is shown in Dummett’s sympathy for the intuitionistic approach of Brouwer and
Heyting, which involves a repudiation of the law of excluded middle, as set
forth in Dummett’s own book on the subject, Elements of Intuitionism 7.
dyad -- co-agency: social action: Grice: “My principle of
co-operation you can call the ‘conversational contract.’ In this respect, I
agree with Grice: Grice: “When I speak of conversation, I mean of a social
action – where one agent’s expectations influence his co-agent’s” -- a subclass
of human action involving the interaction among agents and their mutual
orientation, or the action of groups. While all intelligible actions are in
some sense social, social actions must be directed to others. Talcott Parsons
279 captured what is distinctive about social action in his concept of “double
contingency,” and similar concepts have been developed by other philosophers
and sociologists, including Weber, Mead, and Vitters. Whereas in monological
action the agents’ fulfilling their purposes depends only on contingent facts
about the world, the success of social action is also contingent on how other
agents react to what the agent does and how that agent reacts to other agents,
and so on. An agent successfully communicates, e.g., not merely by finding some
appropriate expression in an existing symbol system, but also by understanding
how other agents will understand him. Game theory describes and explains
another type of double contingency in its analysis of the interdependency of
choices and strategies among rational agents. Games are also significant in two
other respects. First, they exemplify the cognitive requirements for social
interaction, as in Mead’s analysis of agents’ perspective taking: as a subject
“I”, I am an object for others “me”, and can take a third-person perspective
along with others on the interaction itself “the generalized other”. Second,
games are regulated by shared rules and mediated through symbolic meanings;
Vitters’s private language argument establishes that rules cannot be followed
“privately.” Some philosophers, such as Peter Winch, conclude from this
argument that rule-following is a basic feature of distinctively social action.
Some actions are social in the sense that they can only be done in groups.
Individualists such as Weber, Jon Elster, and Raimo Tuomela believe that these
can be analyzed as the sum of the actions of each individual. But holists such
as Marx, Durkheim, and Margaret Gilbert reject this reduction and argue that in
social actions agents must see themselves as members of a collective agent.
Holism has stronger or weaker versions: strong holists, such as Durkheim and
Hegel, see the collective subject as singular, the collective consciousness of
a society. Weak holists, such as Gilbert and Habermas, believe that social
actions have plural, rather than singular, collective subjects. Holists
generally establish the plausibility of their view by referring to larger
contexts and sequences of action, such as shared symbol systems or social
institutions. Explanations of social actions thus refer not only to the mutual
expectations of agents, but also to these larger causal contexts, shared
meanings, and mechanisms of coordination. Theories of social action must then
explain the emergence of social order, and proposals range from Hobbes’s
coercive authority to Talcott Parsons’s value consensus about shared goals
among the members of groups. -- social
biology, the understanding of social behavior, especially human social
behavior, from a biological perspective; often connected with the political
philosophy of social Darwinism. Charles Darwin’s Origin of Species highlighted
the significance of social behavior in organic evolution, and in the Descent of
Man, he showed how significant such behavior is for humans. He argued that it
is a product of natural selection; but it was not until 4 that the English
biologist William Hamilton showed precisely how such behavior could evolve,
namely through “kin selection” as an aid to the biological wellbeing of close
relatives. Since then, other models of explanation have been proposed,
extending the theory to non-relatives. Best known is the self-describing
“reciprocal altruism.” Social biology became notorious in 5 when Edward O.
Wilson published a major treatise on the subject: Sociobiology: The New
Synthesis. Accusations of sexism and racism were leveled because Wilson
suggested that Western social systems are biologically innate, and that in some
respects males are stronger, more aggressive, more naturally promiscuous than
females. Critics argued that all social biology is in fact a manifestation of
social Darwinism, a nineteenthcentury philosophy owing more to Herbert Spencer
than to Charles Darwin, supposedly legitimating extreme laissez-faire economics
and an unbridled societal struggle for existence. Such a charge is extremely
serious, for as Moore pointed out in his Principia Ethica 3, Spencer surely
commits the naturalistic fallacy, inasmuch as he is attempting to derive the
way that the world ought to be from the way that it is. Naturally enough,
defenders of social biology, or “sociobiology” as it is now better known,
denied vehemently that their science is mere right-wing ideology by another
name. They pointed to many who have drawn very different social conclusions on
the basis of biology. Best known is the Russian anarchist Kropotkin, who argued
that societies are properly based on a biological propensity to mutual aid. With
respect to contemporary debate, it is perhaps fairest to say that sociobiology,
particularly that pertaining to humans, did not always show sufficient
sensitivity toward all societal groups
although certainly there was never the crude racism of the fascist
regimes of the 0s. However, recent work is far more careful in these respects.
Now, indeed, the study of social behavior from a biological perspective is one
of the most exciting and forward-moving branches of the life sciences. -- social choice theory, the theory of the
rational action of a group of agents. Important social choices are typically
made over alternative means of collectively providing goods. These might be
goods for individual members of the group, or more characteristically, public
goods, goods such that no one can be excluded from enjoying their benefits once
they are available. Perhaps the most central aspect of social choice theory
concerns rational individual choice in a social context. Since what is rational
for one agent to do will often depend on what is rational for another to do and
vice versa, these choices take on a strategic dimension. The prisoner’s dilemma
illustrates how it can be very difficult to reconcile individual and
collectively rational decisions, especially in non-dynamic contexts. There are
many situations, particularly in the provision of public goods, however, where
simple prisoner’s dilemmas can be avoided and more manageable coordination
problems remain. In these cases, individuals may find it rational to contractually
or conventionally bind themselves to courses of action that lead to the greater
good of all even though they are not straightforwardly utility-maximizing for
particular individuals. Establishing the rationality of these contracts or
conventions is one of the leading problems of social choice theory, because
coordination can collapse if a rational agent first agrees to cooperate and
then reneges and becomes a free rider on the collective efforts of others.
Other forms of uncooperative behaviors such as violating rules established by
society or being deceptive about one’s preferences pose similar difficulties.
Hobbes attempted to solve these problems by proposing that people would agree
to submit to the authority of a sovereign whose punitive powers would make
uncooperative behavior an unattractive option. It has also been argued that
cooperation is rational if the concept of rationality is extended beyond
utility-maximizing in the right way. Other arguments stress benefits beyond
selfinterest that accrue to cooperators. Another major aspect of social choice
theory concerns the rational action of a powerful central authority, or social
planner, whose mission is to optimize the social good. Although the central
planner may be instituted by rational individual choice, this part of the
theory simply assumes the institution. The planner’s task of making a onetime
allocation of resources to the production of various commodities is tractable
if social good or social utility is known as a function of various commodities.
When the planner must take into account dynamical considerations, the technical
problems are more difficult. This economic growth theory raises important
ethical questions about intergenerational conflict. The assumption of a social
analogue of the individual utility functions is particularly worrisome. It can
be shown formally that taking the results of majority votes can lead to
intransitive social orderings of possible choices and it is, therefore, a
generally unsuitable procedure for the planner to follow. Moreover, under very
general conditions there is no way of aggregating individual preferences into a
consistent social choice function of the kind needed by the planner. -- social constructivism, also called social
constructionism, any of a variety of views which claim that knowledge in some
area is the product of our social practices and institutions, or of the
interactions and negotiations between relevant social groups. Mild versions
hold that social factors shape interpretations of the world. Stronger versions
maintain that the world, or some significant portion of it, is somehow
constituted by theories, practices, and institutions. Defenders often move from
mild to stronger versions by insisting that the world is accessible to us only
through our interpretations, and that the idea of an independent reality is at
best an irrelevant abstraction and at worst incoherent. This philosophical
position is distinct from, though distantly related to, a view of the same name
in social and developmental psychology, associated with such figures as Piaget
and Lev Vygotsky, which sees learning as a process in which subjects actively
construct knowledge. Social constructivism has roots in Kant’s idealism, which
claims that we cannot know things in themselves and that knowledge of the world
is possible only by imposing pre-given categories of thought on otherwise
inchoate experience. But where Kant believed that the categories with which we
interpret and thus construct the world are given a priori, contemporary
constructivists believe that the relevant concepts and associated practices
vary from one group or historical period to another. Since there are no
independent standards for evaluating conceptual schemes, social constructivism
leads naturally to relativism. These views are generally thought to be present
in Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, which argues that
observation and methods in science are deeply theory-dependent and that
scientists with fundamentally different assumptions or paradigms effectively
live in different worlds. Kuhn thus offers a view of science in opposition to
both scientific realism which holds that theory-dependent methods can give us
knowledge of a theory-independent world and empiricism which draws a sharp line
between theory and observation. Kuhn was reluctant to accept the apparently
radical consequences of his views, but his work has influenced recent social
studies of science, whose proponents frequently embrace both relativism and
strong constructivism. Another influence is the principle of symmetry advocated
by David Bloor and Barry Barnes, which holds that sociologists should explain
the acceptance of scientific views in the same way whether they believe those
views to be true or to be false. This approach is elaborated in the work of
Harry Collins, Steve Woolgar, and others. Constructivist themes are also
prominent in the work of feminist critics of science such as Sandra Harding and
Donna Haraway, and in the complex views of Bruno Latour. Critics, such as Richard
Boyd and Philip Kitcher, while applauding the detailed case studies produced by
constructivists, claim that the positive arguments for constructivism are
fallacious, that it fails to account satisfactorily for actual scientific
practice, and that like other versions of idealism and relativism it is only
dubiously coherent. Then there’s the
idea of a ‘contract,’ or social contract, an agreement either between the
people and their ruler, or among the people in a community. The idea of a
social contract has been used in arguments that differ in what they aim to
justify or explain e.g., the state, conceptions of justice, morality, what they
take the problem of justification to be, and whether or not they presuppose a
moral theory or purport to be a moral theory. Traditionally the term has been
used in arguments that attempt to explain the nature of political obligation
and/or the kind of responsibility that rulers have to their subjects.
Philosophers such as Plato, Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, and Kant argue that human
beings would find life in a prepolitical “state of nature” a state that some
argue is also presocietal so difficult that they would agree either with one another or with a prospective
ruler to the creation of political
institutions that each believes would improve his or her lot. Note that because
the argument explains political or social cohesion as the product of an
agreement among individuals, it makes these individuals conceptually prior to
political or social units. Marx and other socialist and communitarian thinkers
have argued against conceptualizing an individual’s relationship to her
political and social community in this way. Have social contracts in political
societies actually taken place? Hume ridicules the idea that they are real, and
questions what value makebelieve agreements can have as explanations of actual
political obligations. Although many social contract theorists admit that there
is almost never an explicit act of agreement in a community, nonetheless they
maintain that such an agreement is implicitly made when members of the society
engage in certain acts through which they give their tacit consent to the
ruling regime. It is controversial what actions constitute giving tacit
consent: Plato and Locke maintain that the acceptance of benefits is sufficient
to give such consent, but some have argued that it is wrong to feel obliged to
those who foist upon us benefits for which we have not asked. It is also
unclear how much of an obligation a person can be under if he gives only tacit
consent to a regime. How are we to understand the terms of a social contract
establishing a state? When the people agree to obey the ruler, do they
surrender their own power to him, as Hobbes tried to argue? Or do they merely
lend him that power, reserving the right to take it from him if and when they
see fit, as Locke maintained? If power is merely on loan to the ruler,
rebellion against him could be condoned if he violates the conditions of that
loan. But if the people’s grant of power is a surrender, there are no such
conditions, and the people could never be justified in taking back that power
via revolution. Despite controversies surrounding their interpretation, social
contract arguments have been important to the development of modern democratic
states: the idea of the government as the creation of the people, which they
can and should judge and which they have the right to overthrow if they find it
wanting, contributed to the development of democratic forms of polity in the
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.
and revolutionaries explicitly
acknowledged their debts to social contract theorists such as Locke and
Rousseau. In the twentieth century, the social contract idea has been used as a
device for defining various moral conceptions e.g. theories of justice by those
who find its focus on individuals useful in the development of theories that
argue against views e.g. utilitarianism that allow individuals to be sacrificed
for the benefit of the group -- social epistemology, the study of the social
dimensions or determinants of knowledge, or the ways in which social factors
promote or perturb the quest for knowledge. Some writers use the term
‘knowledge’ loosely, as designating mere belief. On their view social
epistemology should simply describe how social factors influence beliefs,
without concern for the rationality or truth of these beliefs. Many historians
and sociologists of science, e.g., study scientific practices in the same
spirit that anthropologists study native cultures, remaining neutral about the
referential status of scientists’ constructs or the truth-values of their
beliefs. Others try to show that social factors like political or professional
interests are causally operative, and take such findings to debunk any
objectivist pretensions of science. Still other writers retain a normative,
critical dimension in social epistemology, but do not presume that social
practices necessarily undermine objectivity. Even if knowledge is construed as
true or rational belief, social practices might enhance knowledge acquisition.
One social practice is trusting the opinions of authorities, a practice that
can produce truth if the trusted authorities are genuinely authoritative. Such
trust may also be perfectly rational in a complex world, where division of
epistemic labor is required. Even a scientist’s pursuit of extra-epistemic
interests such as professional rewards may not be antithetical to truth in
favorable circumstances. Institutional provisions, e.g., judicial rules of
evidence, provide another example of social factors. Exclusionary rules might
actually serve the cause of truth or accuracy in judgment if the excluded
evidence would tend to mislead or prejudice jurors. -- social philosophy, broadly the philosophy
of socisocial Darwinism social philosophy 856
856 ety, including the philosophy of social science and many of its
components, e.g., economics and history, political philosophy, most of what we
now think of as ethics, and philosophy of law. But we may distinguish two
narrower senses. In one, it is the conceptual theory of society, including the
theory of the study of society the
common part of all the philosophical studies mentioned. In the other, it is a
normative study, the part of moral philosophy that concerns social action and individual
involvement with society in general. The central job of social philosophy in
the first of these narrower senses is to articulate the correct notion or
concept of society. This would include formulating a suitable definition of
‘society’; the question is then which concepts are better for which purposes,
and how they are related. Thus we may distinguish “thin” and “thick”
conceptions of society. The former would identify the least that can be said
before we cease talking about society at all
say, a number of people who interact, whose actions affect the behavior
of their fellows. Thicker conceptions would then add such things as community
rules, goals, customs, and ideals. An important empirical question is whether
any interacting groups ever do lack such things and what if anything is common
to the rules, etc., that actual societies have. Descriptive social philosophy
will obviously border on, if not merge into, social science itself, e.g. into
sociology, social psychology, or economics. And some outlooks in social
philosophy will tend to ally with one social science as more distinctively
typical than others e.g., the
individualist view looks to economics, the holist to sociology. A major
methodological controversy concerns holism versus individualism. Holism
maintains that at least some social groups must be studied as units,
irreducible to their members: we cannot understand a society merely by
understanding the actions and motivations of its members. Individualism denies
that societies are “organisms,” and holds that we can understand society only
in that way. Classic G. sociologists e.g., Weber distinguished between
Gesellschaft, whose paradigm is the voluntary association, such as a chess
club, whose activities are the coordinated actions of a number of people who
intentionally join that group in order to pursue the purposes that identify it;
and Gemeinschaft, whose members find their identities in that group. Thus,
the are not a group whose members teamed
up with like-minded people to form society.
They were before they had separate
individual purposes. The holist views society as essentially a Gemeinschaft.
Individualists agree that there are such groupings but deny that they require a
separate kind of irreducibly collective explanation: to understand the we must understand how typical individuals behave compared, say, with the G.s, and so on. The
methods of Western economics typify the analytical tendencies of methodological
individualism, showing how we can understand large-scale economic phenomena in
terms of the rational actions of particular economic agents. Cf. Adam Smith’s
invisible hand thesis: each economic agent seeks only his own good, yet the
result is the macrophenomenal good of the whole. Another pervasive issue
concerns the role of intentional characterizations and explanations in these
fields. Ordinary people explain behavior by reference to its purposes, and they
formulate these in terms that rely on public rules of language and doubtless
many other rules. To understand society, we must hook onto the
selfunderstanding of the people in that society this view is termed Verstehen.
Recent work in philosophy of science raises the question whether intentional
concepts can really be fundamental in explaining anything, and whether we must
ultimately conceive people as in some sense material systems, e.g. as
computer-like. Major questions for the program of replicating human
intelligence in data-processing terms cf. artificial intelligence are raised by
the symbolic aspects of interaction. Additionally, we should note the emergence
of sociobiology as a potent source of explanations of social phenomena.
Normative social philosophy, in turn, tends inevitably to merge into either
politics or ethics, especially the part of ethics dealing with how people ought
to treat others, especially in large groups, in relation to social institutions
or social structures. This contrasts with ethics in the sense concerned with
how individual people may attain the good life for themselves. All such theories
allot major importance to social relations; but if one’s theory leaves the
individual wide freedom of choice, then a theory of individually chosen goods
will still have a distinctive subject matter. The normative involvements of
social philosophy have paralleled the foregoing in important ways.
Individualists have held that the good of a society must be analyzed in terms
of the goods of its individual members. Of special importance has been the view
that society must respect indisocial philosophy social philosophy 857 857 vidual rights, blocking certain actions
alleged to promote social good as a whole. Organicist philosophers such as
Hegel hold that it is the other way around: the state or nation is higher than
the individual, who is rightly subordinated to it, and individuals have
fundamental duties toward the groups of which they are members. Outrightly
fascist versions of such views are unpopular today, but more benign versions
continue in modified form, notably by communitarians. Socialism and especially
communism, though focused originally on economic aspects of society, have
characteristically been identified with the organicist outlook. Their extreme
opposite is to be found in the libertarians, who hold that the right to
individual liberty is fundamental in society, and that no institutions may
override that right. Libertarians hold that society ought to be treated
strictly as an association, a Gesellschaft, even though they might not deny
that it is ontogenetically Gemeinschaft. They might agree that religious
groups, e.g., cannot be wholly understood as separate individuals.
Nevertheless, the libertarian holds that religious and cultural practices may
not be interfered with or even supported by society. Libertarians are strong
supporters of free-market economic methods, and opponents of any sort of state
intervention into the affairs of individuals. Social Darwinism, advocating the
“survival of the socially fittest,” has sometimes been associated with the
libertarian view. Insofar as there is any kind of standard view on these
matters, it combines elements of both individualism and holism. Typical social
philosophers today accept that society has duties, not voluntary for individual
members, to support education, health, and some degree of welfare for all. But
they also agree that individual rights are to be respected, especially civil
rights, such as freedom of speech and religion. How to combine these two
apparently disparate sets of ideas into a coherent whole is the problem. John
Rawls’s celebrated Theory of Justice, 1, is a contemporary classic that
attempts to do just that. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Grice and Grice on the
conversational contract.”
E
E: SUBJECT
INDEX: EXPLICATVM
E: NAME
INDEX: ITALIAN:
ECO
ENESIDEMO
EMPEDOCLE
EPITTETO
EVOLA
E: NAME
INDEX: ENGLISH.
e: the
‘universalis abdicative.’ Cf. Grice on the Square of Opposition, or figura
quadrata -- Grice, “Circling the square of Opposition.” Grice: “There is an
asymmetry here. It’s supposed to be from Affirmo/Nego, but Affirmo has THREE
vowels, and Nego, two; therefore, the o in affirmo is otiose.”
Ǝ: Ǝx. From
EX-SISTENS -- Grice: “The inverted E is supposed to stand for ‘exist,’ which is
a Ciceronianism – I mean, The Romans thought that you could sist, insist, or
exist!” -- The existential quantifier. When Gentzen used /\ and \/ for ‘all’
and ‘some’ he is being logical, since ‘all’ and ‘some’ behave like ‘and’ and
‘or.’ This is not transparently shown at all by the use of the inverted A and
the inverted E. This Grice called Grice’s Proportion: “and:or::every:some”. Grice: “Surely there is a relation of
‘every’ to ‘and’ and ‘some’ to ‘or.’” “Given a
finite domain of discourse D = {a1, ... an} “every” is equivalent to an “and”
propositions “Pai /\, … Pan.””“Analogously, “some (at least one”) is equivalent
to an “or” proposition having the same structure as before:“Pai V, … Pan.”“For
an infinite domain of discourse the equivalences are pretty similar, and I
shouldn’t bother you with it for two long. But consider the statement, “1 + 1,
and 2 + 2, 3 + 3, ..., and 100 + 100, and ..., etc.” This is an infinite “and”
proposition. From the point of view of a system like System G, this may seem
a problem. Syntax
rules are expected to generate finite formulae. But my example above is fortunate
in that there is a procedure to generate every conjunct. Now, as Austin once
suggested to me, having translated Frege, an assertion were to be made about
every *irrational* number, it would seem that is no (Fregeian) way to enumerate
every conjunct, since irrational numbers cannot be enumerated. However, a
succinct equivalent formulation which avoids this problem with the ‘irrational’
number uses “every” quantification. For each
natural number n, n · 2 = n + n. An analogous analysis applies to the “or”
proposition: “1 is equal to 5 + 5,
2\/ is equal to 5 + 5, \/ 3 is
equal to 5 + 5, ... , \/ 100 is equal to 5 + 5, or ..., etc.” This is easily
rephrasable using “some (at least one)” quantification: “For SOME natural
number n, n is equal to 5+5. Aristotelian predicate calculus rescued from undue existential import
As ... universal quantifier
and conjunction and,
on the other, between the existential
quantifier and disjunction. This analogy has not passed unnoticed in logical circles. ... existential quantifiers correspond
to the conjunction and disjunction operators, ...analogous analysis applies
to propositional logic.
... symbol 'V'
for the existential quantifier in
the 'Californian' notation’
(so-called by H. P. Grice when briefly visiting Berkeley) which was ... In Grice’s system G, the quantifiers are symbolized with
larger versions of the symbols used for conjunction and disjunction. Although
quantified expressions cannot be translated into expressions without
quantifiers, there is a conceptual connection between the universal quantifier
and conjunction and between the existential quantifier and disjunction.
Consider the sentence ∃xPxxPx, for example. It means
that either the first member of the UD is a PP, or the second one is, or the
third one is, . . . . Such a system uses the symbol ‘⋁’ instead of ‘∃.’ Grice’s manoeuver to think of the quantifier versions of De
Morgan's laws is an interesting one. The statement ∀xP(x)∀xP(x) is very much like a
big conjunction. If the universe of discourse is the positive integers, for
example, then it is equivalent to the statement that “P(1)∧P(2)∧P(3)∧⋯P(1)∧P(2)∧P(3)∧⋯” or, more concisely, we might write “⋀x∈UP(x),⋀x∈UP(x),” using
notation similar to "sigma notation'' for sums. Of course, this is not
really a "statement'' in our official mathematical logic, because we don't
allow infinitely long formulas. In the same way, ∃xP(x)∃xP(x) can be thought of as “⋁x∈UP(x).⋁x∈UP(x). Now the first quantifier law can be
written “¬⋀x∈UP(x)⇔⋁x∈U(¬P(x)),¬⋀x∈UP(x)⇔⋁x∈U(¬P(x)),” which looks
very much like the law “¬(P∧Q)⇔(¬P∨¬Q),¬(P∧Q)⇔(¬P∨¬Q),” but with
an infinite conjunction and disjunction. Note that we can also rewrite De
Morgan's laws for ∧∧ and ∨∨ as “¬⋀i=12(Pi(x))¬⋁i=12(Pi(x))⇔⋁i=12(¬Pi(x))⇔⋀i=12(¬Pi(x)).¬⋀i=12(Pi(x))⇔⋁i=12(¬Pi(x))¬⋁i=12(Pi(x))⇔⋀i=12(¬Pi(x)).” As Grice says, “this may look initially cumbersome, but it reflects the close
relationship with the quantifier forms of De Morgan's laws.” Cited by Grice as translatable by “some (at least
one)”. Noting the divergence that Strawson identified but fails to identify as
a conversational implicaturum. It relates in the case of the square of
opposition to the ‘particularis’ but taking into account or NOT taking into
account the ‘unnecessary implication,’ as Russell calls it. “Take ‘every man is
mortal.’ Surely we don’t need the unnecessary implication that there is a man!”
eco: Eco philosophised at the oldest varsity, Bologna –
Grice: “Of course, ‘varsity’ is over-rated, as I’m sure Cicero would agree!” --
Grice: “I would not call Eco a philosopher, since his dissertation is on
aesthetics in Aquinas! Plus, he wrote a novel!” -- scuola bolognese-- possibly,
after Speranza, one of the most Griceian of Italian philosophers (Only Speranza
calls himself an Oxonian, rather! – “Surely alma mater trumps all!”). Umberto Eco (Alessandria, 5 gennaio 1932 – Milano, 19
febbraio 2016[1][2]) è stato un semiologo, filosofo, scrittore, traduttore,
accademico, bibliofilo e medievista italiano. Autografo di Eco
apposto all'edizione tedesca di Arte e bellezza nell'estetica medievale.
Saggista e intellettuale di fama mondiale, ha scritto numerosi saggi di
semiotica, estetica medievale, linguistica e filosofia, oltre a romanzi di
successo. Nel 1971 è stato tra gli ispiratori del primo corso del DAMS
all'Università di Bologna[3][4]. Sempre nello stesso ateneo, negli anni Ottanta
ha promosso l'attivazione del corso di laurea in Scienze della
comunicazione[5], già attivo in altre sedi. Nel 1988 ha fondato il Dipartimento
della Comunicazione dell'Università di San Marino. Dal 2008 era professore
emerito e presidente della Scuola Superiore di Studi Umanistici dell'Università
di Bologna.[6] Dal 12 novembre 2010 Umberto Eco era socio dell'Accademia dei
Lincei, per la classe di Scienze Morali, Storiche e Filosofiche.[7] Tra i suoi
romanzi più famosi figura Il nome della rosa, tradotto in più di 40 lingue, che
è divenuto un bestseller internazionale avendo venduto oltre 50 milioni di
copie in tutto il mondo; da quest'opera sono stati tratti un film ed una serie
televisiva.[8] Figlio di Rita Bisio e di Giulio Eco, un impiegato nelle
Ferrovie, conseguì la maturità al liceo classico Giovanni Plana di
Alessandria,[9] sua città natale. Tra i suoi compagni di classe, vi era il
fisarmonicista Gianni Coscia, con il quale scrisse spettacoli di rivista.[10]
In gioventù fu impegnato nella GIAC (l'allora ramo giovanile dell'Azione
Cattolica) e nei primi anni cinquanta fu chiamato tra i responsabili nazionali
del movimento studentesco dell'AC (progenitore dell'attuale MSAC). Nel 1954
abbandonò l'incarico (così come avevano fatto Carlo Carretto e Mario Rossi) in
polemica con Luigi Gedda. Durante i suoi studi universitari su Tommaso
d'Aquino, smise di credere in Dio e lasciò definitivamente la Chiesa
cattolica;[11] in una nota ironica, in seguito commentò: «si può dire che lui
Tommaso d'Aquino mi abbia miracolosamente curato dalla fede».[12][13] Laureatosi
in filosofia nel 1954 all'Università di Torino (agli esami riportò sempre
30/30, anche con lode, tranne quattro casi: filosofia teoretica e letteratura
latina, in cui ottenne 29/30, e storia della letteratura italiana e pedagogia,
entrambi superati con 27/30) [14] con relatore Luigi Pareyson e tesi
sull'estetica di San Tommaso d'Aquino (controrelatore Augusto Guzzo), cominciò
a interessarsi di filosofia e cultura medievale, campo d'indagine mai più
abbandonato (vedi il volume Dall'albero al labirinto), anche se successivamente
si dedicò allo studio semiotico della cultura popolare contemporanea e
all'indagine critica sullo sperimentalismo letterario e artistico. Nel
1956 pubblicò il suo primo libro, un'estensione della sua tesi di laurea dal
titolo Il problema estetico in San Tommaso. Nel 1954 partecipò e vinse un
concorso della Rai per l'assunzione di telecronisti e nuovi funzionari; con Eco
vi entrarono anche Furio Colombo e Gianni Vattimo. Tutti e tre abbandonarono
l'ente televisivo entro la fine degli anni cinquanta. Nel concorso successivo
entrarono Emmanuele Milano, Fabiano Fabiani, Angelo Guglielmi, e molti altri. I
vincitori dei primi concorsi furono in seguito etichettati come i
"corsari" perché seguirono un corso di formazione diretto da Pier
Emilio Gennarini e avrebbero dovuto, secondo le intenzioni del dirigente
Filiberto Guala, "svecchiare" i programmi. Con altri ingressi
successivi, come quelli di Gianni Serra, Emilio Garroni e Luigi Silori, questi
giovani intellettuali innovarono davvero l'ambiente culturale della
televisione, ancora molto legato a personalità provenienti dall'EIAR, venendo
in seguito considerati come i veri promotori della centralità della RAI nel
sistema culturale italiano.[15] Dall'esperienza lavorativa in RAI,
incluse amicizie con membri del Gruppo 63, Eco trasse spunto per molti scritti,
tra cui il celebre articolo del 1961 Fenomenologia di Mike Bongiorno. Dal
1959 al 1975 fu codirettore editoriale della casa editrice Bompiani. Nel 1962
pubblicò il saggio Opera aperta che, con sorpresa dello stesso autore, ebbe
notevole risonanza a livello internazionale e diede le basi teoriche al Gruppo
63, movimento d'avanguardia letterario e artistico italiano che suscitò
interesse negli ambienti critico-letterari anche per le polemiche che destò
criticando fortemente autori all'epoca già "consacrati" dalla fama
come Carlo Cassola, Giorgio Bassani e Vasco Pratolini, ironicamente definiti
"Liale", con riferimento a Liala, autrice di romanzi rosa.[16] Nel
1961 ebbe inizio anche la sua carriera universitaria che lo portò a tenere
corsi, in qualità di professore incaricato, in diverse università italiane:
Torino, Milano, Firenze e, infine, Bologna dove ha ottenuto la cattedra di
Semiotica nel 1975, diventando professore ordinario.[16] All'Università di
Bologna è stato fra i fondatori del primo corso di laurea in DAMS (era il
1971), poi è stato direttore dell'Istituto di Comunicazione e spettacolo del
DAMS, e in seguito ha dato inizio al corso di laurea in Scienze della
comunicazione. Infine è divenuto Presidente della Scuola Superiore di Studi
Umanistici, fondata nel 2000, che coordina l'attività dei dottorati bolognesi
del settore umanistico, e dove nel 2001 ha ideato il Master in Editoria
Cartacea e Digitale.[17] Nel corso degli anni ha insegnato come
professore invitato alla New York University, Northwestern University, Columbia
University, Yale University, Harvard University, University of California-San
Diego, Cambridge University, Oxford University, Università di São Paulo e Rio
de Janeiro, La Plata e Buenos Aires, Collège de France, École normale
supérieure (Parigi). Nell'ottobre 2007 si è ritirato dall'insegnamento per
limiti di età. Dalla fine degli anni cinquanta, Eco cominciò a
interessarsi all'influenza dei mass media nella cultura di massa, su cui
pubblicò articoli in diversi giornali e riviste, poi in gran parte confluiti in
Diario minimo (1963) e Apocalittici e integrati (1964).[18] Apocalittici e
integrati (che ebbe una nuova edizione nel 1977) analizzò con taglio
sociologico le comunicazioni di massa. Il tema era già stato affrontato in
Diario minimo, che includeva tra gli altri il breve articolo del 1961
Fenomenologia di Mike Bongiorno. Sullo stesso tema, nel 1967 svolse a New
York il seminario Per una guerriglia semiologica, in seguito pubblicato ne Il
costume di casa (1973) e frequentemente citato nelle discussioni sulla
controcultura e la resistenza al potere dei mass media[19]. Significativa
fu anche la sua attenzione per le correlazioni tra dittatura e cultura di massa
ne Il fascismo eterno, capitolo del saggio Cinque scritti morali,[20] dove
individuava le caratteristiche, ricorrenti nel tempo, del cosiddetto
"fascismo eterno", o "Ur-fascismo": il culto della
tradizione, il rifiuto del modernismo, il culto dell'azione per l'azione, il
disaccordo come tradimento, la paura delle differenze, l'appello alle classi
medie frustrate, l'ossessione del complotto, il machismo, il "populismo
qualitativo Tv e Internet" e altre ancora; da esse e dalle loro combinazioni,
secondo Eco, è possibile anche "smascherare" le forme di fascismo che
si riproducono da sempre "in ogni parte del mondo". In
un'intervista del 24 aprile 2010 mise in evidenza la sua visione rispetto a
Wikipedia, della quale Eco si definiva un "utente compulsivo", e al
mondo dell'open source.[21] Nel 1968 pubblicò il suo primo libro di teoria
semiotica, La struttura assente,[19] cui seguirono il fondamentale Trattato di
semiotica generale (1975) e gli articoli per l'Enciclopedia Einaudi poi riuniti
in Semiotica e filosofia del linguaggio (1984). Nel 1971 fondò Versus -
Quaderni di studi semiotici, una delle maggiori riviste internazionali di
semiotica, rimanendone direttore responsabile e membro del comitato scientifico
fino alla morte. È anche stato segretario, vicepresidente e dal 1994 presidente
onorario della IASS/AIS ("International Association for Semiotic
Studies"). È stato invitato a tenere le prestigiose conferenze Tanner
(Università di Cambridge, 1990), Norton (Università di Harvard, 1993), Goggio
(Università di Toronto, 1998), Weidenfeld (Università di Oxford, 2002) e
Richard Ellmann (Università Emory, 2008). Collaborò sin dalla sua
fondazione, nel 1955, al settimanale L'Espresso, sul quale dal 1985 al 2016
tenne in ultima pagina la rubrica La bustina di minerva (nella quale, tra
l'altro, dichiarò di aver contribuito personalmente alla propria voce su
Wikipedia[22]), ai giornali Il Giorno, La Stampa, Corriere della Sera, la
Repubblica, il manifesto[23] e a innumerevoli riviste internazionali
specializzate, tra cui Semiotica (fondata nel 1969 da Thomas Albert Sebeok),
Poetics Today, Degrès, Structuralist Review, Text, Communications (rivista
parigina del EHESS), Problemi dell'informazione, Word & Images, o riviste
letterarie e di dibattito culturale quali Quindici, Il Verri (fondata da
Luciano Anceschi), Alfabeta, Il cavallo di Troia, ecc. Collaborò alla
collana "Fare l'Europa" diretta da Jacques Le Goff con lo studio La
ricerca della lingua perfetta nella cultura europea (1993), in cui si espresse
a favore dell'utilizzo dell'esperanto. Tradusse gli Esercizi di stile di
Raymond Queneau (nel 1983) e Sylvie di Gérard de Nerval (nel 1999 entrambi
presso Einaudi) e introdusse opere di numerosi scrittori e di artisti. Ha anche
collaborato con i musicisti Luciano Berio e Sylvano Bussotti. I suoi
dibattiti, spesso dal tono divertito, con Luciano Nanni, Omar Calabrese, Paolo
Fabbri, Ugo Volli, Francesco Leonetti, Nanni Balestrini, Guido Almansi, Achille
Bonito Oliva o Maria Corti, tanto per nominarne alcuni, hanno aggiunto
contributi non scritti alla storia degli intellettuali italiani, soprattutto
quando sfioravano argomenti non consueti (o almeno non ritenuti tali prima
dell'intervento di Eco), come la figura di James Bond, l'enigmistica, la
fisiognomica, la serialità televisiva, il romanzo d'appendice, il fumetto, il
labirinto, la menzogna, le società segrete o più seriamente gli annosi concetti
di abduzione, di canone e di classico.[senza fonte] Grande appassionato
del fumetto Dylan Dog,[24] a Eco è stato fatto tributo sul numero 136
attraverso il personaggio Humbert Coe, che ha affiancato l'indagatore
dell'incubo in un'indagine sull'origine delle lingue del mondo. È stato inoltre
amico del pittore e autore di fumetti Andrea Pazienza[25] che fu suo allievo al
DAMS di Bologna, e ha scritto la prefazione a libri di Hugo Pratt, Charles
Monroe Schulz, Jules Feiffer e Raymond Peynet. Scrisse la presentazione di
"Cuore" a fumetti, di F. Bonzi e Alain Denis, pubblicata su
"Linus" nel 1975. Nel 1980 Eco esordì nella narrativa. Il suo
primo romanzo, Il nome della rosa, riscontrò un grande successo sia presso la
critica sia presso il pubblico, tanto da divenire un best seller internazionale
tradotto in 47 lingue e venduto in trenta milioni di copie. Il nome della rosa
è stato anche tra i finalisti del prestigioso Edgar Award nel 1984 e ha vinto
il Premio Strega.[26] Dal lavoro fu tratto anche un celebre film con Sean
Connery. Nel 1988 pubblicò il suo secondo romanzo, Il pendolo di
Foucault, satira dell'interpretazione paranoica dei fatti veri o leggendari
della storia e delle sindromi del complotto. Questa critica
dell'interpretazione incontrollata viene ripresa in opere teoriche sulla
ricezione (cfr. I limiti dell'interpretazione). Romanzi successivi sono L'isola
del giorno prima (1994), Baudolino (2000), La misteriosa fiamma della regina
Loana (2004), Il cimitero di Praga (2010) e Numero zero (2015), tutti editi in
italiano da Bompiani. Nel 2012 è stata pubblicata una versione
"riveduta e corretta" del suo primo romanzo Il nome della rosa, con
una nota finale dello stesso Eco che, mantenendo stile e struttura narrativa, è
intervenuto a eliminare ripetizioni ed errori, a modificare l'impianto delle
citazioni latine e la descrizione della faccia del bibliotecario per togliere
un riferimento neogotico. Molte opere furono dedicate alle teorie della
narrazione e della letteratura: Il superuomo di massa (1976), Lector in fabula
(1979), Sei passeggiate nei boschi narrativi (1994), Sulla letteratura (2002),
Dire quasi la stessa cosa (2003, sulla traduzione). È stato inoltre precursore
e divulgatore dell'applicazione della tecnologia alla scrittura. In
contemporanea alla nomina di "guest curator" (curatore ospite) del
Louvre, dove nel mese di novembre 2009 organizzò una serie di eventi e
manifestazioni culturali[27], uscì per Bompiani Vertigine della lista,
pubblicato in quattordici paesi del mondo. Nel 2011 Bompiani pubblicò una
raccolta dal titolo Costruire il nemico e altri scritti occasionali, che
raccoglie saggi occasionali che spaziano nei vari interessi dell'autore, come
quello per la narratologia e il feuilleton ottocentesco. Il primo saggio
riprende temi già presenti ne Il cimitero di Praga. Muore nella sua casa
di Milano il 19 febbraio 2016 alle ore 22:30,[1][2] a causa di un tumore del
pancreas che lo aveva colpito due anni prima.[28] I funerali laici si sono
svolti il 23 febbraio 2016 nel Castello Sforzesco di Milano, dove migliaia di
persone si sono recate per l'ultimo saluto.[29] Sono state eseguite due composizioni
alla viola da gamba e al clavicembalo: Couplets de folies (Les folies
d'Espagne) dalla Suite n. 1 in re maggiore dai Pièces de viole, Livre II (1701)
di Marin Marais e La Folia dalla Sonata per violino e basso continuo in re
minore, op. 5 n. 12 (1700) di Arcangelo Corelli.[30] Nel proprio
testamento Eco ha chiesto ai suoi familiari di non autorizzare né promuovere,
per i dieci anni successivi alla sua morte (quindi sino al 2026), alcun
seminario o conferenza su di lui.[31] Il corpo di Eco è stato infine
cremato. La moglie, Renate Eco-Ramge, rifiutando la proposta di tumularne le
ceneri nel Civico Mausoleo Garbin, ex edicola privata del Cimitero Monumentale
di Milano ora provvista di piccole cellette destinate a ceneri o resti ossei di
personalità artistiche illustri, ne ha preferito la conservazione privata, con
il progetto di costruire un'edicola di famiglia nel medesimo
cimitero.[32] Nei suoi romanzi, Eco racconta storie realmente accadute o
leggende che hanno come protagonisti personaggi storici o inventati. Inserisce
nelle sue opere accesi dibattiti filosofici sull'esistenza del vuoto, di Dio o
sulla natura dell'universo. Attratto da temi piuttosto misteriosi e
oscuri (i cavalieri Templari, il sacro Graal, la sacra Sindone ecc.), nei suoi romanzi
gli scienziati e gli uomini che hanno fatto la storia sono spesso trattati con
indifferenza dai contemporanei. L'umorismo è l'arma letteraria preferita
dallo scrittore di Alessandria, che inserisce innumerevoli citazioni e
collegamenti a opere di vario genere, conosciute quasi esclusivamente da
filologi e bibliofili. Ciò rende romanzi come Il nome della rosa o L'isola del
giorno prima un turbinio variopinto di nozioni di carattere storico,
filosofico, artistico e matematico. Centrale ne Il nome della rosa è la
questione del riso, post-modernisticamente declinata. Ne Il pendolo di
Foucault Eco affronta temi come la ricerca del sacro Graal e la storia dei
cavalieri Templari, facendo numerosi cenni ai misteri dell'età antica e
moderna, rivisitati in chiave parodistica. Ne L'isola del giorno prima
l'umanità intera è simboleggiata dal naufrago Roberto de la Grive, che cerca
un'isola al di fuori del tempo e dello spazio. In Baudolino dà vita ad un
picaresco personaggio medioevale tutto dedito alla ricerca di un paradiso
terrestre (il regno leggendario di Prete Giovanni). Ne La misteriosa
fiamma della regina Loana riflette sulla forza e sull'essenza stessa del
ricordo, rivolto, in questo caso, ad episodi del XX secolo. Il cimitero
di Praga è incentrato sulla natura del complotto e, in particolar modo, sulla
storia 'europea' del popolo ebraico. Il suo ultimo romanzo, Numero zero,
riprendendo temi da sempre cari all'autore (il falso, la costruzione del
complotto e delle notizie) si sofferma sulla storia italiana recente, narrando
fatti realmente accaduti, ma riletti attraverso una chiave
complottistica. Nel 1971 fu tra i 757 firmatari della lettera aperta a
L'Espresso sul caso Pinelli e successivamente della autodenuncia di solidarietà
a Lotta Continua, in cui una cinquantina di firmatari esprimevano solidarietà
verso alcuni militanti e direttori responsabili del giornale, inquisiti per
istigazione a delinquere.[33] I firmatari si autodenunciavano alla
magistratura dicendo di condividere il contenuto dell'articolo. Peraltro le
severe critiche di Eco al terrorismo e ai vari progetti di lotta armata[34]
sono contenute in una serie di articoli scritti sul settimanale L'Espresso e su
Repubblica, specie ai tempi del caso Moro (articoli poi ripubblicati nel volume
Sette anni di desiderio). In effetti l'arma che ha caratterizzato l'impegno
politico di Eco è diventata l'analisi critica dei discorsi politici e delle
comunicazioni di massa. Questo impegno è sintetizzato nella metafora
della guerriglia semiologica dove si sostiene che non è tanto importante
cambiare il contenuto dei messaggi alla fonte ma cercare di animare la loro
analisi là dove essi arrivano (la formula era: non serve occupare la
televisione, bisogna occupare una sedia davanti a ogni televisore). In questo
senso la guerriglia semiologica è una forma di critica sociale attraverso
l'educazione alla ricezione.[35] Dal 2002 partecipa alle attività
dell'associazione Libertà e Giustizia, di cui è uno dei fondatori e garanti più
noti, partecipando attivamente tramite le sue iniziative al dibattito
politico-culturale italiano. Il suo libro A passo di gambero (2006)
contiene le critiche a quello che lui definisce populismo berlusconiano, alla
politica di Bush, al cosiddetto scontro tra etnie e religioni. Nel 2011, nelle
settimane delle rivolte arabe, durante una conferenza stampa registrata alla
Fiera del libro di Gerusalemme, scatena una polemica politica la sua risposta a
un giornalista italiano che gli domanda se condivida il paragone fra Berlusconi
e Mubarak, avanzato da alcuni: "Il paragone potrebbe essere fatto con
Hitler: anche lui giunse al potere con libere elezioni";[36] lo stesso
Eco, dalle colonne de l'Espresso, smentirà tale dichiarazione chiarendo le
circostanze della sua risposta.[37] Eco faceva parte dell'associazione
Aspen Institute Italia.[38] Onorificenze italiane Cavaliere di gran croce
dell'Ordine al merito della Repubblica italiana - nastrino per uniforme
ordinariaCavaliere di gran croce dell'Ordine al merito della Repubblica
italiana — Roma, 9 gennaio 1996[39] Medaglia d'oro ai benemeriti della cultura
e dell'arte - nastrino per uniforme ordinariaMedaglia d'oro ai benemeriti della
cultura e dell'arte — Roma, 13 gennaio 1997[40] Onorificenze straniere
Commendatore dell'Ordine delle Arti e delle Lettere (Francia) - nastrino per
uniforme ordinariaCommendatore dell'Ordine delle Arti e delle Lettere (Francia)
— 1985 Cavaliere dell'Ordine pour le Mérite für Wissenschaften und Künste
(Repubblica Federale di Germania) - nastrino per uniforme ordinariaCavaliere
dell'Ordine pour le Mérite für Wissenschaften und Künste (Repubblica Federale
di Germania) — 1998 Premio Principe delle Asturie per la comunicazione e
l'umanistica (Spagna) - nastrino per uniforme ordinariaPremio Principe delle
Asturie per la comunicazione e l'umanistica (Spagna) — 2000 Ufficiale
dell'Ordine della Legion d'Onore (Francia) - nastrino per uniforme ordinariaUfficiale
dell'Ordine della Legion d'Onore (Francia) — 2003 Gran croce al merito con
placca dell'Ordine al merito della Repubblica Federale di Germania - nastrino
per uniforme ordinariaGran croce al merito con placca dell'Ordine al merito
della Repubblica Federale di Germania — 2009 Commendatore dell'Ordine della
Legion d'Onore (Francia) - nastrino per uniforme ordinariaCommendatore dell'Ordine
della Legion d'Onore (Francia) — Parigi, 13 gennaio 2012[41] Cittadinanze
onorarie Monte Cerignone, 1981. Nizza Monferrato, 6 novembre 2010. San Leo, 11
giugno 2011. Torre Pellice, 2013. Lauree Eco ha ricevuto 40 lauree honoris
causa da prestigiose università europee e americane,[42] come quella del 2014,
che gli è stata conferita dall'Università federale del Rio Grande do Sul, di
Porto Alegre, in Brasile.[43] Nel giugno 2015 in occasione della laurea in
comunicazione conferita dall'Università di Torino, Umberto Eco ha rilasciato
severi giudizi sui social del Web che, a suo dire, possono essere utilizzati da
«legioni di imbecilli» per porsi sullo stesso piano di un vincitore di un
Premio Nobel.[44] Le affermazioni di Eco hanno suscitato approvazioni ma anche
vivaci discussioni.[45][46] Affiliazioni e sodalizi accademici Umberto
Eco è stato membro onorario (Honorary Trustee) della James Joyce Association,
dell'Accademia delle Scienze di Bologna, dell'Academia Europea de Yuste,
dell'American Academy of Arts and Letters, dell'Académie royale des sciences,
des lettres et des beaux-arts de Belgique, della Polska Akademia Umiejętności
("Accademia polacca della Arti"), "Fellow" del St Anne's
College di Oxford e socio dell'Accademia Nazionale dei Lincei.[47] Eco è stato
inoltre membro onorario del CICAP. Altro Gli è stato dedicato l'asteroide
13069 Umbertoeco, scoperto nel 1991 dall'astronomo belga Eric Walter
Elst. Il 12 aprile 2008 è stato nominato Duca dell'Isola del Giorno Prima
del regno di Redonda dal re Xavier. Nel 2016 il comune di Milano ha
deciso che il suo nome venga iscritto nel Pantheon di Milano, all'interno del
cimitero monumentale.[48] Saggistica Eco ha anche scritto numerosi saggi di
filosofia, semiotica, linguistica, estetica: Il problema estetico in San
Tommaso, Torino, Edizioni di Filosofia, 1956; poi Il problema estetico in
Tommaso d'Aquino, 2ª ed., Milano, Bompiani, 1970. Filosofi in libertà, come
Dedalus, Torino, Taylor, 1958, poi in Il secondo diario minimo. Sviluppo
dell'estetica medievale, in Momenti e problemi di storia dell'estetica, I,
Dall'antichità classica al Barocco, Milano, Marzorati, 1959. Arte e bellezza
nell'estetica medievale, Milano, Bompiani, 1987. Storia figurata delle
invenzioni. Dalla selce scheggiata al volo spaziale, a cura di e con G. B.
Zorzoli, Milano, Bompiani, 1961. Opera aperta. Forma e indeterminazione nelle
poetiche contemporanee, Milano, Bompiani, 1962; 1967 sulla base dell'ed.
francese 1965; 1971; 1976. Diario minimo, Milano, A. Mondadori, 1963; 1975. (include
i saggi Fenomenologia di Mike Bongiorno e Elogio di Franti) Apocalittici e
integrati, Milano, Bompiani, 1964; 1977. Il caso Bond. [Le origini, la natura,
gli effetti del fenomeno 007], a cura di e con Oreste del Buono, Milano,
Bompiani, 1965. Le poetiche di Joyce. Dalla "Summa" al
"Finnegans Wake", Milano, Bompiani, 1966. (ed. modificata sulla base
della seconda parte di Opera aperta, 1962) Appunti per una semiologia delle
comunicazioni visive, Milano, Bompiani, 1967. (poi in La struttura assente) L'Italie
par elle-meme. A portrait of Italy. Autoritratto dell'Italia, a cura di e con
Giulio Carlo Argan, Guido Piovene, Luigi Chiarini, Vittorio Gregotti e altri,
Milano, Bompiani, 1967. La struttura assente, Milano, Bompiani, 1968; 1980. La
definizione dell'arte, Milano, Mursia, 1968. L'arte come mestiere, a cura di,
Milano, Bompiani, 1969. I sistemi di segni e lo strutturalismo sovietico, a
cura di e con Remo Faccani, Milano, Bompiani, 1969. L'industria della cultura,
a cura di, Milano, Bompiani, 1969. Le forme del contenuto, Milano, Bompiani,
1971. I fumetti di Mao, a cura di e con Jean Chesneaux e Gino Nebiolo, Bari,
Laterza, 1971. Cent'anni dopo. Il ritorno dell'intreccio, a cura di e con
Cesare Sughi, Milano, Bompiani, 1971. Documenti su il nuovo Medioevo, con
Francesco Alberoni, Furio Colombo e Giuseppe Sacco, Milano, Bompiani, 1972.
Estetica e teoria dell'informazione, a cura di, Milano, Bompiani, 1972. I
pampini bugiardi. Indagine sui libri al di sopra di ogni sospetto: i testi
delle scuole elementari, a cura di e con Marisa Bonazzi, Rimini, Guaraldi,
1972. Il segno, Milano, Isedi, 1973; Milano, A. Mondadori, 1980. Il costume di
casa. Evidenze e misteri dell'ideologia italiana, Milano, Bompiani, 1973. Beato
di Liébana. Miniature del Beato de Fernando I y Sancha. Codice B.N. Madrid Vit.
14-2, testo e commenti alle tavole di, Milano, Franco Maria Ricci, 1973.
Eugenio Carmi. Una pittura di paesaggio?, Milano, Prearo, 1973. Trattato di
semiotica generale, Milano, Bompiani, 1975. (EN) A Theory of Semiotics,
Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 1976. (e London, Macmillan, 1977)
[versione inglese originale del Trattato di semiotica generale] Il superuomo di
massa. Studi sul romanzo popolare, Roma, Cooperativa Scrittori, 1976; Milano,
Bompiani, 1978. Stelle & stellette. La via lattea mormorò, illustrazioni di
Philippe Druillet, Conegliano Treviso, Quadragono Libri, 1976. Storia di una
rivoluzione mai esistita. L'esperimento Vaduz. Appunti del Servizio opinioni,
n.292, settembre 1976, Roma, Rai, Servizio Opinioni, 1976. Dalla periferia
dell'impero, Milano, Bompiani, 1977. Come si fa una tesi di laurea, Milano,
Bompiani, 1977. Carolina Invernizio, Matilde Serao, Liala, con altri, Firenze,
La nuova Italia, 1979. (EN) The Role of the Reader, Bloomington, Indiana University
Press, 1979. (contiene saggi tratti da Opera aperta, Apocalittici e integrati,
Forme del contenuto, Lector in Fabula e Il superuomo di massa) (EN, FR) A
semiotic Landscape. Panorama sémiotique. Proceedings of the Ist Congress of the
International Association for Semiotic Studies, Den Haag, Paris, New York,
Mouton (Approaches to Semiotics, 29) (a cura di, con Seymour Chatman e
Jean-Marie Klinkenberg). Lector in fabula, Milano, Bompiani, 1979. (EN)
Function and sign, the semiotics of architecture; A componential analysis of
the architectural sign /column/, in Geoffrey Broadbent, Richard Bunt, Charles
Jencks (a cura di), Signs, symbols and architecture, Chichester-New York,
Wiley, 1980. (EL) E semeiologia sten kathemerine zoe, Thessaloniki, Malliares,
1980. (antologia di saggi). De bibliotheca, Milano, Comune di Milano, 1981.
Postille al nome della rosa, Milano, Bompiani, 1983. The Sign of Three. Peirce,
Holmes, Dupin (a cura di, con Thomas A. Sebeok), Bloomington, Indiana
University Press, 1983 (trad. Il segno dei tre, Milano, Bompiani) Sette anni di
desiderio. [Cronache, 1977-1983], Milano, Bompiani, 1983. Semiotica e filosofia
del linguaggio, Torino, Einaudi, 1984, ISBN 88-06-05690-5. (PT) Conceito de
texto, São Paulo, Queiroz, 1984. Sugli specchi e altri saggi, Milano, Bompiani,
1985. (DE) Streit der Interpretationen, Konstanz, Universitätverlag Konstanz
GMBH, 1987. (FR) Notes sur la sémiotique de la réception, in "Actes
sémiotiques. Documents", IX, 81, 1987. (ZH) Jie gou zhu yi he fu hao xue.
Dian ying wen ji, San lien shu dian chu ban fa xing, Np, 1987. (edizione cinese
di articoli vari originariamente pubblicati in inglese e francese) (EN) Meaning
and mental representations (a cura di, con M. Santambrogio e Patrizia Violi),
Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 1988. (DE) Im Labyrinth der Vernunft.
Texte über Kunst und Zeichen, Leipzig, Reclam, 1989. (antologia di saggi) Lo
strano caso della Hanau 1609, Milano, Bompiani, 1989. Saggio in Leggere i
Promessi sposi. Analisi semiotiche, a cura di Giovanni Manetti, Milano, Gruppo
editoriale Fabbri-Bompiani-Sonzogno-ETAS, 1989, ISBN 88-452-1466-4. (DE) Auf
dem Wege zu einem Neuen Mittelalter, München, DTV Grossdruck, 1990. (antologia
di saggi). I limiti dell'interpretazione, Milano, Bompiani, 1990, ISBN 88-452-1657-8.
Vocali, con Soluzioni felici di Paolo Domenico Malvinni, Napoli, Collana
"Clessidra" di Alfredo Guida Ed., 1991, ISBN 88-7188-024-2. Il
secondo diario minimo, Milano, Bompiani, 1992, ISBN 88-452-1833-3. (EN)
Interpretation and Overinterpretation, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
1992. La memoria vegetale, Milano, Rovello, 1992. La ricerca della lingua
perfetta nella cultura europea, Roma-Bari, Laterza, 1993, ISBN 88-420-4287-0.
(EL) Ton augousto den Uparchoun eideseis, Thessaloniki, Parateretés, 1993.
(antologia di saggi). (EN) Apocalypse Postponed, Bloomington, Indiana U.P,
1994. (saggi tratti da Apocalittici e integrati scelti e curati da Robert
Lumley) (EN) Six Walks in the Fictional Woods, Cambridge, Harvard U.P., 1994.
(tradotto come Sei passeggiate nei boschi narrativi, Milano, Bompiani) Povero
Pinocchio. Giochi linguistici di studenti del Corso di Comunicazione, a cura
di, Modena, Comix, 1995, ISBN 88-7686-601-9. In cosa crede chi non crede?, con
Carlo Maria Martini, Roma, Liberal, 1996, ISBN 88-86838-03-4. (DE) Neue
Streichholzbriefe, München, DTV, 1997. Kant e l'ornitorinco, Milano, Bompiani,
1997, ISBN 88-452-2868-1. Cinque scritti morali, Milano, Bompiani, 1997, ISBN
88-452-3124-0. (EN) Talking of Joyce, con Liberato Santoro-Brienza, Dublin,
University College Dublin Press, 1998. (DE) Gesammelte Streichholzbriefe,
München, Hanser, 1998. (EN) Serendipities. Language and Lunacy, New York,
Columbia University Press, 1998. Tra menzogna e ironia, Milano, Bompiani, 1998,
ISBN 88-452-3829-6. La bustina di minerva, Milano, Bompiani, 1999, ISBN
88-452-4383-4. (NO) Den nye Middelalderen og andre essays, Oslo, Tiden Norske,
2000. (antologia di saggi) (DE) Mein verrücktes Italien, Berlin, Wagenbach,
2000. (antologia di saggi) (CS) Mysl a smysl, Praha, Moravia press, 2000.
(antologia di saggi) (EN) Experiences in translation, Toronto, Toronto U.P.,
2000. Riflessioni sulla bibliofilia, Milano, Rovello, 2001. (DE) Sämtliche
Glossen und Parodien, München, Hanser, 2001. (raccolta completa da Diario minimo,
Secondo diario minimo, Bustina di minerva e altre parodie da raccolte in
tedesco) Sulla letteratura, Milano, Bompiani, 2002, ISBN 88-452-5069-5. Guerre
sante, passione e ragione. Pensieri sparsi sulla superiorità culturale; Scenari
di una guerra globale, in Islam e Occidente. Riflessioni per la convivenza,
Roma-Bari, Laterza, 2002, ISBN 88-420-6784-9. Bellezza. Storia di un'idea
dell'Occidente, CD-ROM a cura di, Milano, Motta On Line, 2002. Dire quasi la
stessa cosa. Esperienze di traduzione, Milano, Bompiani, 2003, ISBN
88-452-5397-X. (EN) Mouse or Rat?, Translation as Negociation, London,
Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 2003. (Experiences in translation e saggi
selezionati da Dire quasi la stessa cosa) Storia della bellezza, a cura di,
testi di Umberto Eco e Girolamo de Michele, Milano, Bompiani, 2004, ISBN
88-452-3249-2. Il linguaggio della Terra Australe, Milano, Bompiani, 2004. (non
in commercio) Il codice Temesvar, Milano, Rovello, 2005. Nel segno della
parola, con Daniele Del Giudice e Gianfranco Ravasi, a cura e con un saggio di
Ivano Dionigi, Milano, BUR, 2005, ISBN 88-17-00632-7. A passo di gambero.
Guerre calde e populismo mediatico, Collana Overlook, Milano, Bompiani, 2006,
ISBN 88-452-5620-0. La memoria vegetale e altri scritti di bibliofilia, Milano,
Rovello, 2006, ISBN 88-452-5785-1. Sator Arepo eccetera, Roma, Nottetempo,
2006, ISBN 88-7452-085-9. Storia della bruttezza, a cura di, Milano, Bompiani,
2007, ISBN 978-88-452-5965-4. 11/9 La cospirazione impossibile, con Piergiorgio
Odifreddi, Michael Shermer, James Randi, Paolo Attivissimo, Lorenzo Montali,
Francesco Grassi, Andrea Ferrero e Stefano Bagnasco, a cura di Massimo
Polidoro, Casale Monferrato, Piemme, 2007, ISBN 978-88-384-6847-6. Dall'albero
al labirinto. Studi storici sul segno e l'interpretazione, Milano, Bompiani,
2007, ISBN 978-88-452-5902-9. Historia. La grande storia della civiltà europea,
a cura di e con altri, 9 voll., Milano, Motta, 2007. Storia della civiltà
europea, a cura di e con altri, 18 voll., Milano, Corriere della Sera, 2007-2008.
Nebbia, a cura di e con Remo Ceserani, con la collaborazione di Francesco
Ghelli e un saggio di Antonio Costa, Torino, Einaudi, 2009. ISBN
978-88-06-18724-8. (antologia letteraria di racconti a tema) Non sperate di
liberarvi dei libri, con Jean-Claude Carrière, Milano, Bompiani, 2009. ISBN
978-88-452-6215-9. Vertigine della lista, Milano, Bompiani, 2009. ISBN
978-88-452-6345-3. Il Medioevo, a cura di, 4 voll., Milano, Encyclomedia,
2010-2011. ISBN 978-88-905082-0-2, ISBN 978-88-905082-1-9, ISBN 978-88-905082-5-7,
ISBN 978-88-905082-9-5. La grande Storia, a cura di, 28 voll., Milano, Corriere
della Sera, 2011. Costruire il nemico e altri scritti occasionali, Milano,
Bompiani, 2011. ISBN 978-88-452-6585-3. Scritti sul pensiero medievale, Collana
Il pensiero occidentale, Milano, Bompiani, 2012, ISBN 978-88-452-7156-4. L'età
moderna e contemporanea, a cura di, 22 voll., Roma, Gruppo editoriale
L'Espresso, 2012-2013. Storia delle terre e dei luoghi leggendari, Milano,
Bompiani, 2013. ISBN 978-88-452-7392-6. Da dove si comincia?, con Stefano
Bartezzaghi, Roma, La Repubblica, 2013. Riflessioni sul dolore, Bologna,
ASMEPA, 2014. ISBN 978-88-97620-73-0. La filosofia e le sue storie, a cura di e
con Riccardo Fedriga, 3 voll., Roma-Bari, Laterza, 2014-2015. ISBN
978-88-581-1406-3, ISBN 978-88-581-1742-2, ISBN 978-88-581-1741-5. Pape Satàn
Aleppe. Cronache di una società liquida, Milano, La nave di Teseo, 2016, ISBN
978-88-9344-021-9. Come viaggiare con un salmone, Milano, La nave di Teseo,
2016, ISBN 978-88-9344-023-3. Sulle spalle dei giganti, Collana I fari, Milano,
La nave di Teseo, 2017, ISBN 978-88-934-4271-8. Il fascismo eterno, Collana Le
onde, Milano, La nave di Teseo, 2018, ISBN 978-88-934-4241-1. [già pubblicato
in Cinque scritti morali, Bompiani, 1997] Sulla televisione. Scritti 1956-2015,
A cura di Gianfranco Marrone, Collana I fari, Milano, La Nave di Teseo, 2018,
ISBN 978-88-934-4456-9. Narrativa Il nome della rosa, Milano, Bompiani,
1980. Il pendolo di Foucault, Milano, Bompiani, 1988, ISBN 88-452-0408-1
L'isola del giorno prima, Milano, Bompiani, 1994, ISBN 88-452-2318-3 Baudolino,
Milano, Bompiani, 2000, ISBN 88-452-4736-8 La misteriosa fiamma della regina
Loana. Romanzo illustrato, Milano, Bompiani, 2004, ISBN 88-452-1425-7 Il
cimitero di Praga, Milano, Bompiani, 2010, ISBN 978-88-452-6622-5 Numero zero,
Milano, Bompiani, 2015, ISBN 978-88-452-7851-8 Narrativa per l'infanzia La
bomba e il generale, illustrazioni di Eugenio Carmi, Milano, Bompiani, 1966. I
tre cosmonauti, illustrazioni di Eugenio Carmi, Milano, Bompiani, 1966. Ammazza
l'uccellino, come Dedalus, illustrazioni di Monica Sangberg, Milano, Bompiani,
1973. Gli gnomi di Gnu, illustrazioni di Eugenio Carmi, Milano, Bompiani, 1992,
ISBN 88-452-1885-6. Tre racconti, Milano, Fabbri, 2004, ISBN 88-451-0300-5.
(raccolta dei tre precedenti) La storia de "I promessi sposi",
raccontata da, Torino-Roma, Scuola Holden-La biblioteca di
Repubblica-L'Espresso, 2010, ISBN 978-88-8371-311-8. Traduzioni Raymond
Queneau, Esercizi di stile, Torino, Einaudi, 1983. Note Claudio
Gerino, Morto lo scrittore Umberto Eco. Ci mancherà il suo sguardo nel mondo,
in la Repubblica, 20 febbraio 2016. URL consultato il 22 febbraio 2016.
Massimo Delfino e Emma Camagna, Alessandria piange Umberto Eco, in La Stampa,
20 febbraio 2016. URL consultato il 22 febbraio 2016. ^ [1] ^ Cosimo Di Bari,
"A passo di critica: il modello di media education nell'opera di Umberto
Eco", Firenze University Press 2009 ^ [2] ^ Èco, Umberto, in Treccani.it –
Enciclopedie on line, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. ^ LINCEI, ENRICO
MENESTO' E UMBERTO ECO NUOVI SOCI DELL'ACCADEMIA, su tuttoggi.info. URL
consultato il 30 ottobre 2017. ^ 'Il nome della rosa' debutta su Rai1 e
conquista gli ascolti della prima serata, su la Repubblica, 5 marzo 2019. URL
consultato il 30 gennaio 2020. ^ quotidiano la Stampa del 22/11/2000, p. 25. ^
Gianni Coscia: «quando suono col mio amico Umberto Eco», su
genova.mentelocale.it. URL consultato il 20 febbraio 2016 (archiviato dall'url
originale il 12 ottobre 2014). ^ «È il lato dolente e angoscioso di un uomo che
è cresciuto nell'Azione Cattolica, che l'ha lasciata in polemica con il grande
Gedda; un uomo, Eco, che ha studiato – dicono - Tommaso d'Aquino, e che un
giorno se n'è uscito dalla Chiesa proclamandosi orgogliosamente ateo, o se si
preferisce, agnostico.» (In Rassegna stampa cattolica: Mario Palmaro, Eco è
solo un refuso, 21 settembre 2011 ^ (EN) «His new book touches on politics, but
also on faith. Raised Catholic, Eco has long since left the church. "Even
though I'm still in love with that world, I stopped believing in God in my 20s
after my doctoral studies on St. Thomas Aquinas. You could say he miraculously
cured me of my faith..."» (IT) «Il suo nuovo libro tratta di
politica, ma anche di fede. Cresciuto nel cattolicesimo, Eco ha lasciato da
tempo la Chiesa. "Anche se io sono ancora innamorato di quel mondo, ho
smesso di credere in Dio durante i miei anni 20, dopo i miei studi universitari
su Tommaso d'Aquino. Potete dire che egli mi ha miracolosamente curato dalla
mia fede..."» (Articolo in Time, 13 giugno 2005) ^ Liukkonen, Petri
(2003) Umberto Eco (1932–) – Pseudonym: Dedalus Archiviato il 4 agosto 2006 in
Internet Archive. ^ Eco, quando l'Università di Torino gli consegnò il libretto
con 27 in letteratura italiana, su la Repubblica, 20 febbraio 2016. URL
consultato il 17 febbraio 2020. ^ Antonio Galdo, Saranno potenti? Storia,
declino e nuovi protagonisti della classe dirigente italiana, Sperling &
Kupfer, Milano Giuseppe Antonio Camerino, ECO, Umberto, in Enciclopedia
Italiana, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. ^ "Riparte il Master in
Editoria, ideato da Umberto Eco" ^ Capozzi (2008) Bondanella (2005)
pp.53 ^ Umberto Eco, Cinque scritti morali, Bompiani 1997, pp. 25-48 ^
Intervista a Umberto Eco - Wikinotizie, su it.wikinews.org. ^ Umberto Eco, Ho
sposato Wikipedia?, «l'Espresso», 4 settembre 2009. ^ Con lo pseudonimo di
Dedalus: Dedalus e il manifesto, su ilmanifesto.it, 20 Febbraio 2016. URL
consultato il 13 febbraio 2019 (archiviato il 13 febbraio 2019). ^ Ostini
(1998) ^ Sclavi (1998) p. 94, citazione: "Sto leggendo un libro [In cosa
crede chi non crede, N.d.R.] di Umberto Eco che mi è arrivato dall'Italia.
Curioso no? Ha il mio stesso nome e il cognome è l'anagramma del mio..." ^
1981, Umberto Eco, su premiostrega.it. URL consultato il 16 aprile 2019. ^
Italian Writer Umberto Eco is the Louvre's New Guest Curator ^ Emma Camagna, La
morte di Eco, il ricordo di Gianni Coscia, in La Stampa, 20 febbraio 2016. URL
consultato il 22 febbraio 2016. ^ L'ultimo saluto a Umberto Eco: "Grazie
maestro", in La Stampa, 23 febbraio 2016. URL consultato il 23 febbraio
2016. ^ Marco Del Corona, «Follie di Spagna»: ecco che cos'è la musica suonata
per Umberto Eco, su Corriere della Sera. URL consultato il 23 febbraio 2016. ^
Umberto Eco, la richiesta nel testamento: "Non autorizzate convegni su di
me per i prossimi 10 anni", su Il Fatto Quotidiano. URL consultato il 23
marzo 2016. ^ La lettera della vedova Eco al Comune, in Corriere della Sera.
URL consultato il 30 marzo 2017. ^ Pinelli, Calabresi e l'eskimo in redazione
Archiviato il 19 gennaio 2012 in Internet Archive., opinione.it, 30 gennaio
1997 ^ Bruno Pischedda, Come leggere Il nome della rosa di Umberto Eco, Mursia,
1994 p.99 ^ La struttura assente, 1968, pp. 413-18. ^ "Eco a Gerusalemme
attacca il Cavaliere. È polemica", di Francesco Battistini (dal Corriere
della Sera, 24 febbraio 2011) Corriere della Sera ^ Berlusconi, Hitler e io, su
l'Espresso. URL consultato il 20 febbraio 2016. ^ Comitato Esecutivo | Aspen Institute
Italia, su www.aspeninstitute.it. URL consultato il 20 febbraio 2016. ^ Sito
web del Quirinale: dettaglio decorato. ^ Sito web del Quirinale: dettaglio
decorato. ^ Umberto Eco all'Eliseo onorato da Sarkozy con Legion D'Honneur, su
liberoquotidiano.it. URL consultato il 14 gennaio 2012 (archiviato dall'url
originale il 29 ottobre 2013). ^ Curriculum Vitae, su umbertoeco.it. URL
consultato il 20 febbraio 2016. ^ Unibo e Brasile: Laurea ad honorem a Umberto
Eco, su magazine.unibo.it. URL consultato il 20 febbraio 2016. ^ Umberto Eco
contro i social: "Hanno dato diritto di parola a legioni di
imbecilli", su Il Fatto Quotidiano. URL consultato il 20 febbraio 2016. ^
Il problema di Umberto Eco con internet, su Il Post. URL consultato il 20 febbraio
2016. ^ Imbecilli e non, tutto il mondo è social, su LaStampa.it. URL
consultato il 20 febbraio 2016. ^ Serena Vitale e Umberto Eco entrano
nell'Accademia dei Lincei, 12 novembre 2010, Il Giornale. ^ Decise
all'unanimità le 15 personalità illustri da iscrivere nel Pantheon di Milano,
su comune.milano.it, 20 settembre 2016. URL consultato il 28 settembre
2017. Riferimenti Opere: Bondanella, Peter (2005) Umberto Eco and
the Open Text: Semiotics, Fiction, Popular Culture Capozzi, Rocco (2008) Eco's
Prophetic Vision of Mass Culture in McLuhan Studies: Premier Issue, Antonio
Galdo (2003) Saranno potenti? Storia, declino e nuovi protagonisti della classe
dirigente italiana, Sperling & Kupfer, Milano ISBN 88-200-3501-4 Alberto
Ostini (a cura di), Umberto Eco e Tiziano Sclavi. Un dialogo, in Dylan Dog,
indocili sentimenti, arcane paure, Milano, Euresis, 1998. Tiziano Sclavi, Bruno
Brindisi, Lassù qualcuno ci chiama, Dylan Dog n. 136, Milano, Sergio Bonelli
Editore, gennaio 1998, p. 94. Film Walt Disney e l'Italia - Una storia
d'amore (2014): viene mostrata un'intervista durante lo "speciale Walt
Disney" (1965) con Ettore Della Giovanna e Gianni Rodari Bibliografia
Luigi Bauco, Francesco Millocca, Dizionario del «Pendolo di Foucault», Milano,
Corbo, 1989. Manlio Talamo, I segreti del Pendolo, Napoli, Simone, 1989.
Francesco Pansa, Anna Vinci, Effetto Eco, Roma, Nuova Edizione del Gallo, 1990.
Marco Testi, "Il romanzo al passato": medioevo e invenzione in tre
autori contemporanei in Analisi letteraria, 27, Roma, Bulzoni, 1992. Walter
Pedullà, «L'utilitaria di Eco» in Le caramelle di Musil, Milano, Rizzoli, 1992,
pp. 236-243. Salman Rushdie, «Umberto Eco» in Imaginary Homelands: Essays and
Criticism 1981-1991, Londra, Penguin, 1992. Bruno Pischedda, Come leggere «Il
nome della rosa» di Umberto Eco, Milano, Mursia, 1994. Jean Petitot, Paolo
Fabbri (a cura di), Nel nome del senso. Intorno all'opera di Umberto Eco,
Milano, Sansoni, 2001. Antonio Sorella (a cura di), Umberto Eco. Sponde remote
e nuovi orizzonti, Pescara, Tracce, 2002. Roberto Rampi, L'ornitorinco. Umberto
Eco, Peirce e la conoscenza congetturale, M & B Publishing, Milano 2005,
ISBN 88-7451-065-9 Marco Sonzogni, Echi di Eco, Balerna, Edizione Ulivo, 2007.
Cinzia Bianchi, Clare Vassallo, “Umberto Eco's interpretative semiotics:
Interpretation, encyclopedia, translation”, in Semiotica. Journal of the
International Association for Semiotic Studies (Berlin/New York: Mouton de
Gruyter), 2015, vol. 206, issue 1/4, pp. 1-218. Peter Bondanella, Umberto Eco
and the open text. Semiotics, fiction, popular culture, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 1997. Peter Bondanella (a cura di), New Essays on Umberto
Eco, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2009. Jean-Jacques Brochier (a cura
di), Umberto Eco. Du semiologue au romancier, in Le Nouveau Magazine Littéraire
[inserto speciale], n. 262, febbraio 1989. Michael Caesar, Umberto Eco.
Philosophy, Semiotics and the Work of Fiction, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1999.
Rocco Capozzi (a cura di), Reading Eco. An Anthology, Bloomington, Indiana
University Press, 1997. Michele Castelnovi, La mappa della biblioteca:
geografia reale ed immaginaria secondo Umberto Eco, in Miscellanea di Storia
delle esplorazioni n. LX, Genova, 2015, pp. 195-253. Remo Ceserani, Eco e il
postmoderno consapevole in Raccontare il postmoderno, Torino, Bollati
Boringhieri, pp. 180-200. Michele Cogo, Fenomenologia di Umberto Eco. Indagine
sulle origini di un mito intellettuale contemporaneo. Introduzione di Paolo
Fabbri. Bologna, Baskerville, 2010, ISBN 978-88-8000-310-6 Furio Colombo,
«L'isola del giorno prima», in La rivista dei libri, IV, n. 10, ottobre 1994,
pp. 4-8. Roberto Cotroneo, La diffidenza come sistema. Saggio sulla narrativa
di Umberto Eco, Milano, Anabasi, 1995. Roberto Cotroneo, Eco: due o tre cose che
so di lui, Milano, Bompiani, 2001. Teresa de Lauretis, Umberto Eco, Firenze, La
Nuova Italia, 1981. Nunzio Dell'Erba, Alla ricerca delle fonti del romanzo
"Il Cimitero di Praga" , in Id., L'eco della storia. Saggi di critica
storica: massoneria, anarchia, fascismo e comunismo, Universitas Studiorum,
Mantova 2013, ISBN 978-88-97683-30-8 Cosimo Di Bari, A passo di critica. Il
modello di Media Education nell'opera di Umberto Eco, Firenze, Firenze
University Press, 2009, ISBN 978-88-8453-928-1. Richard Ellmann, Murder in the
Monastery?, in The New York Review of Books, n. 12, luglio 1983. Lorenzo
Flabbi, La disposizione del sapere di Umberto Eco, in Atlante dei movimenti
culturali. 1968-2007, a cura di C. Cretella e P. Pieri, Clueb, Bologna 2007,
ISBN 978-8849128994. Cristina Farronato, Eco's Chaosmos, Toronto, University of
Toronto Press, 2003. Franco Forchetti, Il segno e la rosa. I segreti della
narrativa di Umberto Eco, Roma, Castelvecchi, 2005. Grit Fröhlich, Umberto Eco.
Philosophie – Ästhetik – Semiotik, Paderborn, Wilhelm Fink Verlag, 2009, ISBN
978-3-7705-4880-4. Margherita Ganeri, Il «caso» Eco, Palermo, Palumbo, 1991.
Alfredo Giuliani, «Scherzare col fuoco» in Autunno del novecento, Milano,
Feltrinelli, 1984. Renato Giovannoli (a cura di), Saggi su «Il Nome della
Rosa», Milano, Bompiani, 1985. Fabio Izzo, Eco a perdere, Associazione
Culturale Il Foglio, 2005. Paolo Jachia, Umberto Eco. Arte semiotica
letteratura, San Cesario, Manni, 2006. Anna Maria Lorusso, Umberto Eco. Temi,
problemi e percorsi semiotici, Roma, Carocci, 2008. Patrizia Magli et. al. (a
cura di), Semiotica: Storia Teoria Interpretazione. Saggi intorno a Umberto
Eco, Milano, Bompiani, 1992, ISBN 978-88-452-1835-4. Sandro Montalto (a cura
di), Umberto Eco: l'uomo che sapeva troppo, Pisa, ETS, 2007. Franco Musarra et
al., Eco in fabula. Umberto Eco in the Humanities. Umberto Eco dans les
sciences humaines. Umberto Eco nelle scienze umane, Proceedings of the
International Conference, Leuven, 24-27 febbraio 1999, Leuven, Leuven U.P. e
Firenze, Franco Cesati Editore, 2002. Claudio Paolucci, Umberto Eco. Tra ordine
e avventura, Milano, Feltrinelli, 2017. Voci correlate Semiotica Monte
Cerignone, luogo di residenza Struttura (semiotica) Altri progetti Collabora a
Wikisource Wikisource contiene una pagina dedicata a Umberto Eco Collabora a
Wikiquote Wikiquote contiene citazioni di o su Umberto Eco Collabora a
Wikimedia Commons Wikimedia Commons contiene immagini o altri file su Umberto
Eco Collegamenti esterni Sito ufficiale, su umbertoeco.it. Modifica su Wikidata
Umberto Eco, su Treccani.it – Enciclopedie on line, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia
Italiana. Modifica su Wikidata Umberto Eco, in Enciclopedia Italiana, Istituto
dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Modifica su Wikidata (EN) Umberto Eco, su
Enciclopedia Britannica, Encyclopædia Britannica, Inc. Modifica su Wikidata
(EN) Umberto Eco, su The Encyclopedia of Science Fiction. Modifica su Wikidata
Umberto Eco, su BeWeb, Conferenza Episcopale Italiana. Modifica su Wikidata
Opere di Umberto Eco, su Liber Liber. Modifica su Wikidata Opere di Umberto
Eco, su openMLOL, Horizons Unlimited srl. Modifica su Wikidata (EN) Opere di
Umberto Eco, su Open Library, Internet Archive. Modifica su Wikidata (FR)
Pubblicazioni di Umberto Eco, su Persée, Ministère de l'Enseignement supérieur,
de la Recherche et de l'Innovation. Modifica su Wikidata (EN) Bibliografia di
Umberto Eco, su Internet Speculative Fiction Database, Al von Ruff. Modifica su
Wikidata (EN) Umberto Eco (autore), su Goodreads. Modifica su Wikidata (EN)
Umberto Eco (personaggio), su Goodreads. Modifica su Wikidata Bibliografia
italiana di Umberto Eco, su Catalogo Vegetti della letteratura fantastica,
Fantascienza.com. Modifica su Wikidata Registrazioni di Umberto Eco, su
RadioRadicale.it, Radio Radicale. Modifica su Wikidata (EN) Umberto Eco, su
Internet Movie Database, IMDb.com. Modifica su Wikidata (EN) Umberto Eco, su
AllMovie, All Media Network. Modifica su Wikidata (DE, EN) Umberto Eco, su
filmportal.de. Modifica su Wikidata Eco, Umberto, in Lessico del XXI secolo,
Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana, 2012-2013. "La bustina di
minerva": la rubrica periodica di Eco su L'Espresso, L'Espresso. URL
consultato il 10 gennaio 2012. www.signosemio.com - Signo - Biografia di
Umberto Eco e la presentazione della sua teoria semiotica, su signosemio.com.
URL consultato il 19 giugno 2009 (archiviato dall'url originale il 4 giugno
2009). Approfondimento, su italialibri.net. Curiosità (anche la
"cacopedia" - in PDF) (PDF), su bibliotecheoggi.it. Opere in
TecaLibri/1, su tecalibri.info. Opere in TecaLibri/2, su tecalibri.info.
Considerazioni su: "Non sperate di liberarvi dei libri", su
antonietta.philo.unibo.it (archiviato dall'url originale il 18 gennaio 2012).
Golem L'indispensabile (il sito della rivista) - rivista online diretta da
Umberto Eco, Renato Mannheimer, Carlo Bertelli, Danco Singer Un articolo di Eco
su Wikipedia, su espresso.repubblica.it. www.encyclomedia.it, su
encyclomedia.it. Il «questionario Proust» a Umberto Eco, su elapsus.it. URL
consultato il 22 maggio 2016. (DE) Umberto Eco, in Perlentaucher, Perlentaucher
Medien GmbH. Opere di Umberto Eco V · D · M Vincitori del Premio Strega V · D ·
M Vincitori internazionali del Prix Médicis V · D · M Vincitori del Premio
Bancarella V · D · M Vincitori del Premio Cesare Pavese V · D · M Vincitori del
Premio di Stato austriaco per la letteratura europea V · D · M Vincitori del
Premio Mediterraneo per stranieri Controllo di autoritàVIAF (EN) 108299403 ·
ISNI (EN) 0000 0001 2283 9390 · SBN IT\ICCU\CFIV\006213 · Europeana agent/base/145365
· LCCN (EN) n79021285 · GND (DE) 11852884X · BNF (FR) cb11901536g (data) · BNE
(ES) XX1044144 (data) · ULAN (EN) 500075019 · NLA (EN) 35607219 · BAV (EN)
495/158121 · NDL (EN, JA) 00438594 · WorldCat Identities (EN) lccn-n79021285
Biografie Portale Biografie Filosofia Portale Filosofia Giallo Portale Giallo
Letteratura Portale Letteratura Categorie: Semiologi italianiFilosofi italiani
del XX secoloFilosofi italiani del XXI secoloScrittori italiani del XX
secoloScrittori italiani del XXI secoloNati nel 1932Morti nel 2016Nati il 5
gennaioMorti il 19 febbraioNati ad AlessandriaMorti a MilanoUmberto
EcoScrittori per ragazziFondatori di riviste italianeVincitori del Premio
BancarellaVincitori del Premio StregaCavalieri di gran croce OMRIBenemeriti
della cultura e dell'arteDecorati con la Legion d'onoreAutori del Gruppo
63Accademici dei LinceiPersone legate all'Università di HarvardProfessori
dell'Università di BolognaProfessori della Columbia
UniversityPatafisicaTraduttori italianiAccademici italiani del XX
secoloAccademici italiani del XXI secoloSaggisti italiani del XX secoloSaggisti
italiani del XXI secoloUomini universaliStudenti dell'Università degli Studi di
TorinoTraduttori dal franceseTraduttori all'italianoMedievisti
italianiBibliofiliDirettori di periodici italianiCritici e teorici dei nuovi
media[altre]. Econ provides a bridge between Graeco-Roman philosophy and
Grice! Eco is one of the few philosophers who considers the very origins of
philosophy in Bologna – and straight from Rome – On top, Eco is one of the
first to generalise most of Grice’s topics under ‘communication,’ rather than
using the Anglo-Saxon ‘mean’ that does not really belong in the Graeco-Roman
tradition. Eco cites H. P. Grice in “Cognitive constraints of communication.” Umberto
b.2, philosopher, intellectual
historian, and novelist. A leading figure in the field of semiotics, the
general theory of signs. Eco has devoted most of his vast production to the
notion of interpretation and its role in communication. In the 0s, building on
the idea that an active process of interpretation is required to take any sign
as a sign, he pioneered reader-oriented criticism The Open Work, 2, 6; The Role
of the Reader, 9 and championed a holistic view of meaning, holding that all of
the interpreter’s beliefs, i.e., his encyclopedia, are potentially relevant to
word meaning. In the 0s, equally influenced by Peirce and the structuralists, he offered a unified theory
of signs A Theory of Semiotics, 6, aiming at grounding the study of communication
in general. He opposed the idea of communication as a natural process, steering
a middle way between realism and idealism, particularly of the Sapir-Whorf
variety. The issue of realism looms large also in his recent work. In The
Limits of Interpretation 0 and Interpretation and Overinterpretation 2, he
attacks deconstructionism. Kant and the Platypus 7 defends a “contractarian”
form of realism, holding that the reader’s interpretation, driven by the
Peircean regulative idea of objectivity and collaborating with the speaker’s
underdetermined intentions, is needed to fix reference. In his historical
essays, ranging from medieval aesthetics The Aesthetics of Thomas Aquinas, 6 to
the attempts at constructing artificial and “perfect” languages The Search for
the Perfect Language, 3 to medieval semiotics, he traces the origins of some
central notions in contemporary philosophy of language e.g., meaning, symbol,
denotation and such recent concerns as the language of mind and translation, to
larger issues in the history of philosophy. All his novels are pervaded by
philosophical queries, such as Is the world an ordered whole? The Name of the
Rose, 0, and How much interpretation can one tolerate without falling prey to
some conspiracy syndrome? Foucault’s Pendulum, 8. Everywhere, he engages the
reader in the game of controlled interpretations. “Il nome della rosa” is about
the dark ages in Northern Italy, where the monks were the only to find a slight
interest in philosophy, unlike the barbaric Lombards!” -- Refs.: Umberto Econ on H. P. Grice in
“Cognitive constraints on communication,” Luigi
Speranza, "Grice ed Eco: semantica filosofica," per Il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
eddington: “Some like Einstein, but Eddington’s MY man.” – H. P.
Grice. Einstein – discussed by Grice in “Eddington’s Two Tables” -- Albert
18795, G.-born physicist, founder of the
special and general theories of relativity and a fundamental contributor to
several branches of physics and to the philosophical analysis and critique of
modern physics, notably of relativity and the quantum theory. Einstein was
awarded the Nobel Prize for physics in 2, “especially for his discovery of the
law of the photoelectric effect.” Born in Ulm in the G. state of Württemberg,
Einstein studied physics at the Polytechnic in Zürich, Switzerland. He was
called to Berlin as director of the Kaiser Wilhelm Institute for Physics 4 at
the peak of the G. ultranationalism that surrounded World War I. His reaction
was to circulate an internationalist “Manifesto to Europeans” and to pursue
Zionist and pacifist programs. Following the dramatic confirmation of the
general theory of relativity 9 Einstein became an international celebrity. This
fame also made him the frequent target of G. anti-Semites, who, during one
notable episode, described the theory of relativity as “a Jewish fraud.” In 3
Einstein left G.y for the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton. Although
his life was always centered on science, he was also engaged in the politics
and culture of his times. He carried on an extensive correspondence whose
publication will run to over forty volumes with both famous and ordinary
people, including significant philosophical correspondence with Cassirer,
Reichenbach, Moritz Schlick, and others. Despite reservations over logical
positivism, he was something of a patron of the movement, helping to secure
academic positions for several of its leading figures. In 9 Einstein signed a
letter drafted by the nuclear physicist Leo Szilard informing President
Roosevelt about the prospects for harnessing atomic energy and warning of the
G. efforts to make a bomb. Einstein did not further participate in the
development of atomic weapons, and later was influential in the movement
against them. In 2 he was offered, and declined, the presidency of Israel. He
died still working on a unified field theory, and just as the founders of the
Pugwash movement for nuclear disarmament adopted a manifesto he had cosigned
with Russell. Einstein’s philosophical thinking was influenced by early
exposure to Kant and later study of Hume and Mach, whose impact shows in the
operationalism used to treat time in his famous 5 paper on special relativity.
That work also displays a passion for unity in science characteristic of nearly
all his physical thinking, and that may relate to the monism of Spinoza, a
philosopher whom he read and reread. Einstein’s own understanding of relativity
stressed the invariance of the space-time interval and promoted realism with
regard to the structure of spacetime. Realism also shows up in Einstein’s work
on Brownian motion 5, which was explicitly motivated by his long-standing
interest in demonstrating the reality of molecules and atoms, and in the realist
treatment of light quanta in his analysis 5 of the photoelectric effect. While
he pioneered the development of statistical physics, especially in his seminal
investigations of quantum phenomena 525, he never broke with his belief in
determinism as the only truly fundamental approach to physical processes. Here
again one sees an affinity with Spinoza. Realism and determinism brought
Einstein into conflict with the new quantum theory 526, whose observer
dependence and “flight into statistics” convinced him that it could not
constitute genuinely fundamental physics. Although influential in its
development, he became the theory’s foremost critic, never contributing to its
refinement but turning instead to the program of unifying the electromagnetic
and gravitational fields into one grand, deterministic synthesis that would
somehow make room for quantum effects as limiting or singular cases. It is
generally agreed that his unified field program was not successful, although
his vision continues to inspire other unification programs, and his critical
assessments of quantum mechanics still challenge the instrumentalism associated
with the theory. Einstein’s philosophical reflections constitute an important
chapter in twentieth-century thought. He understood realism as less a
metaphysical doctrine than a motivational program, and he argued that
determinism was a feature of theories rather than an aspect of the world
Einstein, Albert Einstein, Albert 256
256 directly. Along with the unity of science, other central themes in
his thinking include his rejection of inductivism and his espousal of holism
and constructivism or conventionalism, emphasizing that meanings, concepts, and
theories are free creations, not logically derivable from experience but
subject rather to overall criteria of comprehensibility, empirical adequacy,
and logical simplicity. Holism is also apparent in his acute analysis of the
testability of geometry and his rejection of Poincaré’s geometric
conventionalism.
einheit – Grice: “I will use the Germanism for two reasons:
it’s pompous, and no Englishman would use ‘unity’ (literally ‘onehood’) like
that!” -- H. P. Grice, “Unity of science
and teleology.” unity of science, a situation in which all branches of
empirical science form a coherent system called unified science. Unified
science is sometimes extended to include formal sciences e.g., branches of
logic and mathematics. ‘Unity of science’ is also used to refer to a research
program aimed at unified science. Interest in the unity of science has a long
history with many roots, including ancient atomism and the work of the Encyclopedists. In the twentieth century this
interest was prominent in logical empiricism see Otto Neurath et al.,
International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, vol. I, 8. Logical empiricists
originally conceived of unified science in terms of a unified language of
science, in particular, a universal observation language. All laws and
theoretical statements in any branch of science were to be translatable into
such an observation language, or else be appropriately related to sentences of
this language. In unified science unity of science 939 939 addition to encountering technical
difficulties with the observationaltheoretical distinction, this conception of
unified science also leaves open the possibility that phenomena of one branch
may require special concepts and hypotheses that are explanatorily independent
of other branches. Another concept of unity of science requires that all
branches of science be combined by the intertheoretic reduction of the theories
of all non-basic branches to one basic theory usually assumed to be some future
physics. These reductions may proceed stepwise; an oversimplified example would
be reduction of psychology to biology, together with reductions of biology to
chemistry and chemistry to physics. The conditions for reducing theory T2 to
theory T1 are complex, but include identification of the ontology of T2 with
that of T1, along with explanation of the laws of T2 by laws of T1 together with
appropriate connecting sentences. These conditions for reduction can be
supplemented with conditions for the unity of the basic theory, to produce a
general research program for the unification of science see Robert L. Causey,
Unity of Science, 7. Adopting this research program does not commit one to the
proposition that complete unification will ever be achieved; the latter is
primarily an empirical proposition. This program has been criticized, and some
have argued that reductions are impossible for particular pairs of theories, or
that some branches of science are autonomous. For example, some writers have
defended a view of autonomous biology, according to which biological science is
not reducible to the physical sciences. Vitalism postulated non-physical
attributes or vital forces that were supposed to be present in living
organisms. More recent neovitalistic positions avoid these postulates, but
attempt to give empirical reasons against the feasibility of reducing biology.
Other, sometimes a priori, arguments have been given against the reducibility
of psychology to physiology and of the social sciences to psychology. These
disputes indicate the continuing intellectual significance of the idea of unity
of science and the broad range of issues it encompasses. Einheitswissenschaft: Used by
Grice ironically. While he was totally ANTI-Einheitwisseschaft, he was ALL for
einheitsphilosophie! The phrase is used by
Grice in a more causal way. He uses the expression ‘unity of science’ vis-à-vis
the topic of teleology. Note that ‘einheitswissenschaft,’ literally translates
as unity-science – there is nothing about ‘making’ if one, which is what –fied
implies. The reason why ‘einheitswissenschaft’ was transliterated as ‘unified
science’ was that Neurath thought that ‘unity-science’ would be a yes-yes in
New England, most New Englanders being Unitarians, but they would like to
include Theology there, ‘into the bargain.’ “Die
Einheit von Wissenschaft.” Die Einheit der Wissenschaft und die neopositivistische Theorie
der „Einheitswissenschaft”.
O. Neurath, „Einheit der
Wissenschaft als Aufgabe“,Einheitswissenschaft oder Einheit der Wissenschaft? | Frank
F Vierter Internationaler Kongress für Einheit der Wissenschaft, Cambridge 1938 ... Einheitswissenschaft als Basis
der Wissenschaftsgeschichte (pp. positivists held that no essential differences in
aim and method exist between the various branches of science. The scientists of
all disciplines should collaborate closely with each other and should unify the
vocabulary of sciences by logical analysis. According to this view, there is no
sharp demarcation between natural
sciences and social sciences. In particular, to establish universal laws in the
social sciences may be difficult in practice, but it is not impossible in
principle. Through Otto Neurath, this ideal of scientific unity became a
program for logical positivists, who published a series of books in Vienna
under the heading Unified Science. After the dissolution of the Vienna Circle,
Neurath renamed the official journal Erkenntnis as The Journal of Unified
Science, and planned to continue publication of a series of works in the United
States under the general title The International Encyclopedia of Unified
Science. He thought that the work would be similar in historical importance to
the eighteenth-century French Encyclopédie under the direction of Diderot.
Unfortunately, this work was never completed, although Carnap and Morris
published some volumes originally prepared for it under the title Foundations
of the Unity of Science. “We have repeatedly pointed out that the formation of
the constructional system as a whole is the task of unified science.” Carnap,
The Logical Structure of the World.
empedocle:
one
of the most important Italian philosophers.
Grecian preSocratic philosopher who created a physical theory in response
to Parmenides while incorporating Pythagorean ideas of the soul into his
philosophy. Following Parmenides in his rejection of coming-to-be and
perishing, he accounted for phenomenal change by positing four elements his
“roots,” rizomata, earth, water, air, and fire. When they mix together in set
proportions they create compound substances such as blood and bone. Two forces
act on the elements, Love and Strife, the former joining the different
elements, the latter separating them. In his cyclical cosmogony the four
elements combine to form the Sphere, a completely homogeneous spherical body
permeated by Love, which, shattered by Strife, grows into a cosmos with the
elements forming distinct cosmic masses of earth, water the seas, air, and
fire. There is controversy over whether Empedocles posits one or two periods
when living things exist in the cycle. On one view there are two periods,
between which intervenes a stage of complete separation of the elements.
Empedocles accepts the Pythagorean view of reincarnation of souls, seeing life
as punishment for an original sin and requiring the expiation of a pious and
philosophical life. Thus the exile and return of the individual soul reflects in
the microcosm the cosmic movement from harmony to division to harmony.
Empedocles’ four elements became standard in natural philosophy down to the
early modern era, and Aristotle recognized his Love and Strife as an early
expression of the efficient cause. Vide
“Italic Griceians” – While in the New World, ‘Grecian philosophy’ is believed
to have happened ‘in Greece,’ Grice was amused that ‘most happened in Italy!’
Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice ed
Empedocle," per Il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa
Grice, Liguria, Italia.
enantiamorphs: “When Moore said
that he knew he had two hands, he implicated, ‘I have two enantiamorphic
hands,’ before they were able to cancel his talk and his implicaturum.” from
Grecian enantios, ‘opposite’, and morphe, ‘form’, objects whose shapes differ
as do those of a right and left hand. One of a pair of enantiamorphs can be
made to look identical in shape to the other by viewing it in a mirror but not
merely by changing its spatial orientation. Enantiamorphs figure prominently in
the work of Kant, who argued that the existence of enantiamorphic pairs
entailed that Leibnizian relational theories of space were to be rejected in
favor of Newtonian absolutist theories, that some facts about space could be
apprehended empiricism, constructive enantiamorphs 263 263 only by “pure intuition,” and that space
was mind-dependent.
ENCYCLOPÆDIA
GRICEIANA:
he way Grice is known in Italy, due to the efforts of Luigi Speranza, of the
Grice Club. Speranza saw that Grice connected, somehow, with philosophy in
general, and tried to pursue a way to make him accessible to anti-Oxonians. The
encyclopædia Griceiana. Grice went to Paris and became enamoured with
encyclopedia, or “encyclopédie,” “or a Descriptive Dictionary of the Sciences,
Arts and Trades,” launched by the Parisian publisher Le Breton, who had secured
d’Alembert’s and Diderot’s editorship, the Encyclopedia was gradually released despite
a temporary revocation of its royal privilege. Comprising seventeen folio
volumes of 17,818 articles and eleven folio volumes of 2,885 plates, the
ENCYCLOPAEDIA GRICEIANA required a staff of 272 Griceian engravers. “But the
good thing,” Grice says, “is that it incorporates the accumulated knowledge and
rationalist, secularist views of the
Enlightenment and prescribed economic, social, and political reforms.”
Strawson adds: “Enormously successful at Oxford, ENCYCLOPÆDIA GRICEIANA was
reprinted with revisions five times before Grice died.” “Contributions were
made by anyone we could bribe!” – As in the old encycloopaedia, the philosophes
Voltaire, Rousseau, Montesquieu, d’Holbach, Naigeon, and Saint-Lambert; the
writers Duclos and Marmontel; the theologians Morellet and Malet; enlightened
clerics, e.g. Raynal; explorers, e.g. La Condamine; natural scientists, e.g.
Daubenton; physicians, e.g. Bouillet; the economists Turgot and Quesnay;
engineers, e.g. Perronet; horologists, e.g. Berthoud; and scores of other
experts. “The purpose of the ENCYCLOPÆDIA GRICEIANA,” writes Grice in the
“Foreword”, “is to collect this or that bit of Griceian knowledge dispersed on
the surface of the earth, and to unfold its general system.” “The Encyclopedia,”
Strawson adds, “offers the educated Oxonian a comprehensive, systematic, and
descriptive repository of contemporary liberal and mechanical arts, with an
appendix on implicaturum by Grice hisself.” D’Alembert and Diderot developed a
sensationalist epistemology, “but I don’t.” “Preliminary Discourse” under the
influence of Locke and Condillac. Grice and Strawson (with the occasional help
from Austin, Warnock, Pears and Thomson) compiled and rationally classified
existing knowledge according to the noetic process memory, imagination, and
reason. Based on the assumption of the unity of theory and praxis, the approach
of the ENCYCLOOPÆDIA GRICEIANA is positivistic and ‘futilitarian.’ The
ENCYCLOPÆDIA GRICEIANA vindicates experimental reason and the rule of nature,
fostered the practice of criticism, and stimulated the development of both old
and new sciences. In religious matters, the ENCYCLOPAEDIA GRICEIANA cultivates
ambiguity and implicaturum to escape censorship by Queen Elizabeth II, an avid
reader of the supplements. Whereas most contributors held either conciliatory
or orthodox positions, J. F. Thomson barely concealed his naturalistic and
atheistic opinions. Thomson’s radicalism was pervasive. Supernaturalism, obscurantism,
and fanaticism, and Heideggerianism are among the Encyclopedists’ favorite
targets. The Griceian Encyclopaedists identify Roman Catholicism (of the type
Dummett practiced) with superstition and theology with occult magic; assert the
superiority of natural morality over theological ethics; demand religious
toleration; and champion human rights and conventional implicaturum alike. They
innovatively retrace the historical conditions of the development of Oxford
(“and a little Cambridge”) philosophy. They furthermore pioneer ideas on trade
and industry and anticipate the relevance of historiography, sociology,
economics, and ‘conversational pragmatics.’ As the most ambitious and expansive
reference work Oxford ever saw, the ENCYCLOPÆDIA GRICEIANA crystallizes the
confidence of England’s midlands bourgeoisie in the capacity of reason to
dispel the shadows of ignorance and improve society – “at least Oxonian
society, if I can.”
enesidemo: or ‘aenesidemus,’ as Strawson would prefer.
Although Grecian, he is listed in the name glossay to the essay on “Roman
philosophers,” and that is because he influenced some Roman-born philosophers
and nnobles. “Nothing beats a
Grecian don,” as Cicero remarked. Academic philosopher, founder of a Pyrrhonist
revival in Rome. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Scetticismo romano.”
English
futilitarians, The: Bergmann’s pun on
H. P. Grice and J. L. Austin. from futile. Cf. conversational futilitarianism.
Can there be a futilitarian theory of communication? Grice’s! The issue is a
complex one. Some may interpret Grice’s theory as resting “on Kantian grounds.”
Not everybody was present at Grice’s seminars at Oxford on helpfulness, where
he discusses the kind of reasoning that a participant to a conversation will
display in assuming that his co-conversationalist is being conversationally
helpful, conversationally benevolent, conversationally ‘altruist,’ almost, and
conversationally, well, co-operative. So, as to the basis for this. We can
simplify the scenario by using the plural. A conversationalist assumes that his
co-conversationalist is being co-operative on Kantian grounds. What are the
alternatives, if any? One can re-describe “Kantian grounds” as “moral grounds.”
Conversationalists abide with the principle of conversational helpfulness on
Kantian, moral grounds. Kant wrote the “Critique of practical reason,” so Kant
would allow for a rephrase of this as follows. Conversationalists abide with
the principle of conversational helpfulness on practical, indeed moral, grounds
– which is the topic of Grice’s last Kant lecture at Stanford. How to turn a
‘counsel of prudence,’ which is ‘practical’ into something that covers Kant’s
“Kategorische Imperativ.” And then there’s the utilitarian. Utilitarianism IS a
moral theory, or a meta-ethical theory. So one would have to allow for the
possibility that conversationalists abide by the principle of conversational
helpfulness on “utilitarian grounds,” which would be “practical grounds,” AND
“moral grounds,” if not Kantian grounds. In any case, the topic WAS raised, and
indeed, for someone like Grice who wrote on ‘pleasure,’ and ‘happiness,’ it
does not seem futilitarian to see him as a futilitarian. Unfortunately, you
need a serious philosophical background to appreciate all this, since it
touches on the very serious, or ‘deep,’ as Grice would say, “and fascinating,”
suburbia or practicality. But surely the keyword ‘utilitarian’ as per
“conversationalists abide by the principle of conversational helpfulness on
utilitarian grounds” is a possibility. Cf. Grice’s reference to the ‘least
effort,’ and in the Oxford lectures on helpfulness to a conversationalist not
getting involved in “undue effort,” or getting into “unnecessary trouble.”
“Undue effort” is ‘forbidden’ by the desideratum of conversational candour; the
‘unnecessary trouble’ is balanced by the ‘principle of conversational
self-love.’ And I don’t think Kant would ever considered loving himself! Grice
being keen on neuter adjectives, he saw the ‘utile’ at the root of utilitarianism.
There is much ‘of value’ in the old Roman concept of ‘utile.’ Lewis and Short
have it as Neutr. absol.: ūtĭle , is, n., what is useful, the useful: omne
tulit punctum, qui miscuit utile dulci, Hor. A. P. 343: “bonus atque fidus
Judex honestum praetulit utili,” id. C. 4, 9, 41: “utilium tardus provisor,”
id. A. P. 164: “sententiae de utilibus honestisque,” Quint. 3, 8, 13; cf. id.
1, 2, 29. —Ultimately, Grice’s meta-ethics, like Hare’s, Nowell-Smith’s,
Austin’s, Hampshire’s, and Warnock’s derives into a qualified utilitarianism,
with notions of agreeableness and eudaemonia being crucial. Grice well knows
that for Aristotle pleasure is just one out of the three sources for phulia;
the others being profit, and virtue. As an English utilitarian, or English
futilitarian, Grice plays with Griceian pleasures. Democritus, as Grice
remarks, seems to be the earliest philosopher to have categorically embraced a
hedonistic philosophy. Democritus claims that the supreme goal of life is
contentment or cheerfulness, stating that joy and sorrow are the distinguishing
mark of things beneficial and harmful. The Cyrenaics are an ultra-hedonist
Grecoam school of philosophy founded by Aristippus. Many of the principles of
the school were set by his grandson, Aristippus the Younger, and Theodorus. The
Cyrenaic school is one of the earliest Socratic schools. The Cyrenaics teach
that the only intrinsic ‘agathon’ is pleasure ‘hedone,’ which means not just
the absence of pain, but a positively enjoyable momentary sensation. A physical
pleasure is stronger than a pleasure of anticipation or memory. The Cyrenaics
do, however, recognize the value of social obligation, and that pleasure may be
gained from altruism. The Cyrenaic school dies out within a century, and is
replaced by Epicureanism. The Cyrenaics are known for their sceptical
epistemology. The Cyrenaics reduce logic to a basic doctrine concerning the
criterion of truth. The Cyrenaics think that one can only know with certainty
his immediate sense-experience, e. g., that he is having a sweet sensation. But
one can know nothing about the nature of the object that causes this sensation,
e.g., that honey is sweet. The Cyrenaics also deny that we can have knowledge
of what the experience of others are like. All knowledge is immediate
sensation. Sensation is a motion which is purely subjective, and is painful,
indifferent or pleasant, according as it is violent, tranquil or gentle.
Further, sensation is entirely individual and can in no way be described as
constituting absolute objective knowledge. Feeling, therefore, is the only
possible criterion of knowledge and of conduct. The way of being affected is
alone knowable. Thus the sole aim for everyone should be
pleasure. Cyrenaicism deduces a single, universal aim for all which is
pleasure. Furthermore, feeling is momentary and homogeneous. It follows that
past and future pleasure have no real existence for us, and that in present
pleasure there is no distinction of kind. Socrates speaks of the higher
pleasure of the intellect. The Cyrenaics denies the validity of this
distinction and say that bodily pleasure (hedone somatike), being more simple
and more intense, is preferable. Momentary pleasure, preferably of a physical
kind, is the only good for a human. However, an action which gives immediate
pleasure can create more than their equivalent of pain. The wise person should
be in control (egcrateia) of pleasure rather than be enslaved to it, otherwise
pain results, and this requires judgement to evaluate this or that pleasure of
life. Regard should be paid to law and custom, because even though neither law
nor custom have an intrinsic value on its own, violating law or custom leads to
an unpleasant penalty being imposed by others. Likewise, friendship and justice
are useful because of the pleasure they provide. Thus the Cyrenaics believe in
the hedonistic value of social obligation and altruistic behaviour.
Epicureanism is a system of philosophy based upon the teachings of Epicurus, an
atomic materialist, following in the steps of Democritus and Leucippus.
Epicurus’s materialism leads him to a general stance against superstition or
the idea of divine intervention. Following Aristippus, Epicurus believes that
the greatest good is to seek modest, sustainable pleasure in the form of a state
of tranquility and freedom from fear (ataraxia) and absence of bodily pain
(aponia) through knowledge of the workings of the world and the limits of
desire. The combination of these two states, ataraxia and aponia, is supposed
to constitute happiness in its highest form. Although Epicureanism is a form of
hedonism, insofar as it declares pleasure as the sole intrinsic good, its
conception of absence of pain as the greatest pleasure and its advocacy of a
simple life make it different from hedonism as it is commonly understood. In
the Epicurean view, the highest pleasure (tranquility and freedom from fear) is
obtained by knowledge, friendship and living a virtuous and temperate life.
Epicurus lauds the enjoyment of a simple pleasure, by which he means abstaining
from the bodily desire, such as sex and the appetite, verging on asceticism.
Epicurus argues that when eating, one should not eat too richly, for it could
lead to dissatisfaction later, such as the grim realization that one could not
afford such delicacies in the future. Likewise, sex could lead to increased
lust and dissatisfaction with the sexual partner. Epicurus does not articulate
a broad system of social ethics that has survived but had a unique version of
the golden rule. It is impossible to live a pleasant life without living
wisely and well and justly, agreeing neither to harm nor be harmed, and it is
impossible to live wisely and well and justly without living a pleasant life.
Epicureanism is originally a challenge to Platonism, though later it became the
main opponent of Stoicism. Epicurus and his followers shun politics. After the
death of Epicurus, his school is headed by Hermarchus. Later many Epicurean
societies flourish in the Late Hellenistic era and during the Roman era, such
as those in Antiochia, Alexandria, Rhodes and Ercolano. The poet Lucretius is
its most known Roman proponent. By the end of the Roman Empire, having
undergone attack and repression, Epicureanism has all but died out, and would
be resurrected in the seventeenth century by the atomist Pierre Gassendi. Some
writings by Epicurus have survived. Some scholars consider the epic poem “De
natura rerum” by Lucretius to present in one unified work the core arguments
and theories of Epicureanism. Many of the papyrus scrolls unearthed at the
Villa of the Papyri at Herculaneum are Epicurean texts. At least some are
thought to have belonged to the Epicurean Philodemus. Cf. Barnes on
epicures and connoiseurs. Many a controversy arising out of this or that value
judgement is settled by saying, ‘I like it and you don’t, and that s the end of
the matter.’ I am content to adopt this solution of the difficulty on matters
such as food and drink. Even here, though, we admit the existence of epicures
and connoisseurs.Why are we not content to accept the same solution on every
matter where value is concerned? The reason I am not so content lies in the
fact that the action of one man dictated by his approval of something is
frequently incompatible with the action of another man dictated by his approval
of something. This is obviously philosophical, especially for the Grecian
hedonistic Epicureians made popular by Marius and Walter Pater at Oxford. L and
S have "ἡδονή,” also “ἁδονά,” or in a chorus in tragedy, “ἡδονά,”
ultimately from "ἥδομαι,” which they render it as “enjoyment, pleasure,”
“prop. of sensual pleasure.” αἱ τοῦ σώματος or περὶ τὸ σῶμα ἡ.; αἱ κατὰ τὸ σῶμα
ἡ. Plato, Republic, 328d; σωματικαὶ ἡ. Arist. Eth. Nich. 1151a13; αἱ περὶ
πότους καὶ περὶ ἐδωδὰς ἡ. Plato, Republic, 389e; but also ἀκοῆς ἡ; ἡ ἀπὸ τοῦ
εἰδέναι ἡ. Pl. R. 582b; of malicious pleasure, ἡ ἐπὶ τοῖς τῶν φίλων κακοῖς, ἐπὶ
ταῖς λοιδορίαις ἡ.; ἡδονῇ ἡσσᾶσθαι, ἡδοναῖς χαρίζεσθαι, to give way to
pleasure; Pl. Lg. 727c; κότερα ἀληθείη χρήσομαι ἢ ἡδονῆ; shall I speak truly or
so as to humour you? εἰ ὑμῖν ἡδονὴ τοῦ ἡγεμονεύειν; ἡ. εἰσέρχεταί τιϝι εἰ, “one
feels pleasure at the thought that …” ; ἡδονὴν ἔχειν τινός to be satisfied
with; ἡδονὴν ἔχει, φέρει; ἡδονὴ ἰδέσθαι (θαῦμα ἰδέσθαι), of a temple; δαίμοσιν
πρὸς ἡδονήν; ὃ μέν ἐστι πρὸς ἡ.; πρὸς ἡ.
Λέγειν, “to speak so as to please another”; δημηγορεῖν; οὐ πρὸς ἡ. οἱ ἦν τὰ
ἀγγελλόμενα; πάντα πρὸς ἡ. ἀκούοντας; later πρὸς ἡδονῆς εἶναί τινι; καθ᾽ ἡδονὴν
κλύειν; καθ᾽ ἡδονήν ἐστί μοι; καθ᾽ ἡ. τι δρᾶν, ποιεῖν; καθ᾽ ἡδονὰς τῷ δήμῳ τὰ πράγματα
ἐνδιδόναι; ἐν ἡδονῇ ἐστί τινι, it is a pleasure or delight to another; ἐν ἡδονῇ
ἔχειν τινάς, to take pleasure in them; ἐν ἡδονῇ ἄρχοντες, oοἱ λυπηροί; μεθ᾽
ἡδονῆς; ὑφ᾽ ἡδονῆς; ὑπὸ τῆς ἡ; ἡδονᾷ with pleasure; a pleasure; ἡδοναὶ
τραγημάτων sweetmeats; plural., desires after pleasure, pleasant lusts. In
Ionic philosophers, taste, flavour, usually joined with χροιή. Note that
Aristotle uses somatike hedone. As a Lit. Hum. Oxon., and especially as a
tutee of Hardie at Corpus, Grice is almost too well aware of the centrality of
hedone in Aristotles system. Pleasure is sometimes rendered “placitum,” as in
“ad placitum,” in scholastic philosophy, but that is because scholastic
philosophy is not as Hellenic as it should be. Actually, Grice prefers
“agreeable.” One of Grices requisites for an ascription of eudaemonia (to have
a fairy godmother) precisely has the system of ends an agent chooses to realise
to be an agreeable one. One form or mode of agreeableness, Grice notes, is,
unless counteracted, automatically attached to the attainment of an object of
desire, such attainment being routinely a source of satisfaction. The
generation of such a satisfaction thus provides an independent ground for
preferring one system of ends to another. However, some other mode of
agreeableness, such as e. g. being a source of delight, which is not routinely
associated with the fulfilment of this or that desire, could discriminate,
independently of other features relevant to such a preference, between one
system of ends and another. Further, a system of ends the operation of which is
especially agreeable is stable not only vis-à-vis a rival system, but also
against the somewhat weakening effect of ‘egcrateia,’ incontinence, or akrasia,
if you mustn’t. A disturbing influence, as Aristotle knows from experience, is
more surely met by a principle in consort with a supporting attraction than by
the principle alone. Grices favourite hedonistic implicaturum was “please,” as
in “please, please me,” by The Beatles. While
Grice claims to love Kantotle, he cannot hide his greater reverence for
Aristotle, instilled early on at Corpus. An Oxonian need not recite Kant in
what during the Second World War was referred to as the Hun, and while
Aristotle was a no-no at Clifton (koine!), Hardie makes Grice love him. With
eudaemonia, Grice finds a perfect synthetic futilitarian concept to balance his
innate analytic tendencies. There is Grecian eudaemonism and there is Griceian
eudaemonism. L and S are not too helpful. They have “εὐδαιμονία” (Ion. –ιη),
which they render not as happiness, but as “prosperity, good fortune,
opulence;” “χρημάτων προσόδῳ καὶ τῇ ἄλλῃ εὐ.;” of countries; “μοῖρ᾽
εὐδαιμονίας.” In a second use, the expression is indeed rendered as “true,
full happiness;” “εὐ. οὐκ ἐν βοσκήμασιν οἰκεῖ οὐδ᾽ ἐν χρυσῷ; εὐ. ψυχῆς,
oκακοδαιμονίη, cf. Pl. Def. 412d, Arist. EN 1095a18, sometimes personified as a
divinity. There is eudaemonia and there is kakodaemonia. Of course, Grice’s
locus classicus is EN 1095a18, which is Grice’s fairy godmother, almost. Cf.
Austin on agathon and eudaimonia in Aristotle’s ethics, unearthed by Urmson and
Warnock, a response to an essay by Prichard in “Philosophy” on the meaning of
agathon in Aristotle’s ethics. Pritchard argues that Aristotle regards
“agathon” to mean conducive to “eudaemonia,” and, consequently, that Aristotle
maintains that every deliberate action stems, ultimately, from the desire for
eudaemonia. Austin finds fault with this. First, agathon in Aristotle does not
have a single usage, and a fortiori not the one Pritchard suggests. Second, if
one has to summarise the usage of “agathon” in one phrase, “being desired”
cannot fulfil this function, for there are other objects of desire besides “τό
άγαθόν,” even if Davidson would disagree. Prichard endeavours to specify what
Aristotle means by αγαθον. In some contexts, “agathon” seems to mean simply
that being desired or an ultimate or non‐ultimate
end or aim of a person. In other contexts, “αγαθον” takes on a normative
quality. For his statements to have content, argues Prichard, Aristotle must
hold that when we pursue something of a certain kind, such as an honour, we
pursue it as “a good.” Prichard argues that by "αγαθον" Aristotle
actually means, except in the Nicomachean Ethics, conducive to eudaemonia, and
holds that when a man acts deliberately, he does it from a desire to attain
eudaemonia. Prichard attributes this position to Plato as well, despite the
fact that both thinkers make statements inconsistent with this view of man’s
ultimate aim. Grice takes life seriously: philosophical biology. He even writes
an essay entitled “Philosophy of life,” listed is in PGRICE. Grice bases his
thought on his tutee Ackrill’s Dawes Hicks essay for the BA, who quotes
extensively from Hardie. Grice also reviews that “serious student of Greek
philosophy,” Austin, in his response to Prichard, Grice’s fairy godmother. Much
the most plausible conjecture regarding what Grecian eudaimonia means is that
eudaemonia is to be understood as the name for that state or condition which
one’s good dæmon would, if he could, ensure for one. One’s good dæmon is a
being motivated, with respect to one, solely by concern for one’s eudaemonia,
well-being or happiness. To change the idiom, eudæmonia is the general
characterisation of what a full-time and unhampered fairy godmother would
secure for one. Grice is concerned with the specific system of ends that
eudaemonia consists for Ariskant. Grice borrows, but never returns, some
reflections by his fomer tuttee at St. Johns, Ackrill. Ackrills point is about
the etymological basis for eudaemonia, from eudaemon, the good dæmon, as Grice
prefers. Grice thinks the metaphor should be disimplicated, and taken
literally. Grice concludes with a set of ends that justify our ascription of
eudaemonia to the agent. For Grice, as for Kantotle, telos and eudaemonia are
related in subtle ways. For eudaemonia we cannot deal with just one end, but a
system of ends, although such a system may be a singleton. Grice specifies a
subtle way of characterising end so that a particular ascription of an end may
entail an ascription of eudaemonia. Grice follows the textual criticism of his
tutee Ackrill, in connection with the Socratic point that eudaemonia is
literally related to the eudaemon. In PGRICE Warner explores Grice’s concept of
eudaemonia. Warner is especially helpful with the third difficult Carus lecture
by Grice, a metaphysical defence of absolute value. Warner connects with Grice
in such topics as the philosophy of perception seen in an evolutionary light
and the Kantotelian idea of eudaemonia. In response to Warner’s overview of the
oeuvre of Grice for the festschrift that Warner co-edited with Grandy, Grice
refers to the editors collectively as Richards. While he feels he has to use
“happiness,” Grice is always having Aristotle’s eudaemonia in mind. The implicaturum
of Smith is ‘happy’ is more complex than Kantotle thinks. Austen knew. For
Emma, you decide if youre happy. Ultimately, for Grice, the rational life is
the happy life. Grice took life seriously: philosophical biology! Grice is
clear when reprinting the Descartes essay in WOW, where he does quote from
Descartes sources quite a bit, even if he implicates he is no Cartesian scholar
– what Oxonian would? It concerns certainty. And certainty is originally
Cantabrigian (Moore), but also Oxonian, in parts. Ayer says that to know is to
assure that one is certain or sure. So he could connect. Grice will at various
stages of his development play and explore this authoritative voice of
introspection: incorrigibility and privileged access. He surely wants to say
that a declaration of an intention is authoritative. And Grice plays with
meaning, too when provoking Malcolm in a don recollection: Grice: I want you to
bring me a paper tomorrow. Strawson: You mean a newspaper? Grice: No, a
philosophical essay. Strawson: How do you know? Are you certain you mean that?
Grice finds not being certain about what one means Strawsonian and otiose.
Tutees. Grice loved to place himself in the role of the philosophical hack,
dealing with his tutees inabilities, a whole week long – until he could find
refreshment in para-philosophy on the Saturday morning. Now, the logical form
of certain is a trick. Grice would symbolize it as numbering of operators. If
G ψs p, G ψs ψs p, and G ψs ψs ψs p, and so ad infinitum. This is a
bit like certainty. But not quite! When he explores trust, Grice considers
something like a backing for it. But does conclusive evidence yield certainty?
He doesnt think so. Certainty, for Grice should apply to any psychological
attitude, state or stance. And it is just clever of him that when he had to
deliver his BA lecture he chooses ‘intention and uncertainty’ as its topic,
just to provoke. Not surprisingly, the “Uncertainty” piece opens with the
sceptics challenge. And he will not conclude that the intender is certain. Only
that theres some good chance (p ˃0.5) that what he intends will get through!
When there is a will, there is a way, when there is a neo-Prichardian will-ing,
there is a palæo-Griceian way-ing! Perhaps by know Moore means certain. Grice
was amused by the fact that Moore thought that he knew that behind the curtains
at the lecture hall at the University of Wisconsin at Madison, there was a
window, when there wasnt. He uses Moores misuse of know – according to Malcolm
– both in Causal theory and Prolegomena. And of course this relates to the
topic of the sceptics implicaturum, above, with the two essays Scepticism and
Common sense and Moore and Philosophers Paradoxes repr. partially in WOW. With
regard to certainty, it is interesting to compare it, as Grice does, not so
much with privileged access, but with incorrigibility. Do we not
have privileged access to our own beliefs and desires? And, worse still,
may it not be true that at least some of our avowals of our beliefs and
desires are incorrigible? One of Grices problems is, as he puts it,
how to accommodate privileged access and,
maybe, incorrigibility. This or that a second-order state may be, in
some fashion, incorrigible. On the contrary, for Grice, this or that
lower-order, first-order judging is only a matter for privileged
access. Note that while he is happy to allow privileged access to
lower-order souly states, only those who are replicated at a higher-order or
second-order may, in some fashion, be said to count as an incorrigible avowal.
It rains. P judges it rains (privileged access). P judges that P judges that it
rains (incorrigible). The justification is conversational. It rains says the P,
or expresses the P. Grice wants to be able to say that if a P expresses that p,
the P judges2 that p. If the P expresses that it rains, the P
judges that he judges that it rains. In this fashion, his second-order,
higher-order judging is incorrigible, only. Although Grice may allow for it to
be corrected by a third-order judging. It is not required that we should stick
with judging here. Let Smith return the money that he owes to Jones. If P
expresses !p, P ψ-s2 that !p. His second-order, higher-order
buletic state is incorrigible (if ceteris paribus is not corrected by a
third-order buletic or doxastic state). His first-order buletic state is a
matter only of privileged access. For a study of conversation as rational
co-operation this utilitarian revival modifies the standard exegesis of Grice
as purely Kantian, and has him more in agreement with the general Oxonian
meta-ethical scene. Refs.: Under ‘futilitarianism,’ we cover Grice’s views on
‘pleasure’ (he has an essay on “Pleasure,”) and “eudaemonia” (He has an essay
on ‘happiness’); other leads are given under ‘grecianism,’ since this is the
Grecian side to Grice’s Ariskant; for specific essays on ‘pleasure,’ and
‘eudaimonia,’ the keywords ‘pleasure’ and ‘happiness’ are useful. A good source
is the essay on happiness in “Aspects,” which combines ‘eudaemonia’ and
‘agreebleness,’ his futilitarianism turned Kantotelian. BANC. English
futilitarians: utilitarianism, the
moral theory that an action is morally right if and only if it produces at
least as much good utility for all people affected by the action as any
alternative action the person could do instead. Its best-known proponent is J.
S. Mill, who formulated the greatest happiness principle also called the
principle of utility: always act so as to produce the greatest happiness. Two
kinds of issues have been central in debates about whether utilitarianism is an
adequate or true moral theory: first, whether and how utilitarianism can be
clearly and precisely formulated and applied; second, whether the moral
implications of utilitarianism in particular cases are acceptable, or instead
constitute objections to it. Issues of formulation. A central issue of
formulation is how utility is to be defined and whether it can be measured in
the way utilitarianism requires. Early utilitarians often held some form of
hedonism, according to which only pleasure and the absence of pain have utility
or intrinsic value. For something to have intrinsic value is for it to be
valuable for its own sake and apart from its consequences or its relations to
other things. Something has instrumental value, on the other hand, provided it brings
about what has intrinsic value. Most utilitarians have held that hedonism is
too narrow an account of utility because there are many things that people
value intrinsically besides pleasure. Some nonhedonists define utility as
happiness, and among them there is considerable debate about the proper account
of happiness. Happiness has also been criticized as too narrow to exhaust
utility or intrinsic value; e.g., many people value accomplishments, not just
the happiness that may accompany them. Sometimes utilitarianism is understood
as the view that either pleasure or happiness has utility, while
consequentialism is understood as the broader view that morally right action is
action that maximizes the good, however the good is understood. Here, we take
utilitarianism in this broader interpretation that some philosophers reserve
for consequentialism. Most utilitarians who believe hedonism gives too narrow
an account of utility have held that utility is the satisfaction of people’s
informed preferences or desires. This view is neutral about what people desire,
and so can account for the full variety of things and experiences that
different people in fact desire or value. Finally, ideal utilitarians have held
that some things or experiences, e.g. knowledge or being autonomous, are
intrinsically valuable or good whether or not people value or prefer them or
are happier with them. Whatever account of utility a utilitarian adopts, it
must be possible to quantify or measure the good effects or consequences of
actions in order to apply the utilitarian standard of moral rightness.
Happiness utilitarianism, e.g., must calculate whether a particular action, or
instead some possible alternative, would produce more happiness for a given
person; this is called the intrapersonal utility comparison. The method of
measurement may allow cardinal utility measurements, in which numerical units
of happiness may be assigned to different actions e.g., 30 units for Jones
expected from action a, 25 units for Jones from alternative action b, or only
ordinal utility measurements may be possible, in which actions are ranked only
as producing more or less happiness than alternative actions. Since nearly all
interesting and difficult moral problems involve the happiness of more than one
person, utilitarianism requires calculating which among alternative actions
produces the greatest happiness for all people affected; this is called the
interpersonal utility comparison. Many ordinary judgments about personal action
or public policy implicitly rely on interpersonal utility comparisons; e.g.,
would a family whose members disagree be happiest overall taking its vacation
at the seashore or in the mountains? Some critics of utilitarianism doubt that
it is possible to make interpersonal utility comparisons. Another issue of
formulation is whether the utilitarian principle should be applied to
individual actions or to some form of moral rule. According to act
utilitarianism, each action’s rightness or wrongness depends on the utility it
produces in comparison with possible alternatives. Even act utilitarians agree,
however, that rules of thumb like ‘keep your promises’ can be used for the most
part in practice because following them tends to maximize utility. According to
rule utilitarianism, on the other hand, individual actions are evaluated, in
theory not just in practice, by whether they conform to a justified moral rule,
and the utilitarian standard is applied only to general rules. Some rule
utilitarians hold that actions are right provided they are permitted by rules
the general acceptance of which would maximize utility in the agent’s society,
and wrong only if they would be prohibited by such rules. There are a number of
forms of rule utilitarianism, and utilitarians disagree about whether act or rule
utilitarianism is correct. Moral implications. Most debate about utilitarianism
has focused on its moral implications. Critics have argued that its
implications sharply conflict with most people’s considered moral judgments,
and that this is a strong reason to reject utilitarianism. Proponents have
argued both that many of these conflicts disappear on a proper understanding of
utilitarianism and that the remaining conflicts should throw the particular
judgments, not utilitarianism, into doubt. One important controversy concerns
utilitarianism’s implications for distributive justice. Utilitarianism
requires, in individual actions and in public policy, maximizing utility
without regard to its distribution between different persons. Thus, it seems to
ignore individual rights, whether specific individuals morally deserve
particular benefits or burdens, and potentially to endorse great inequalities
between persons; e.g., some critics have charged that according to
utilitarianism slavery would be morally justified if its benefits to the
slaveowners sufficiently outweighed the burdens to the slaves and if it
produced more overall utility than alternative practices possible in that
society. Defenders of utilitarianism typically argue that in the real world
there is virtually always a better alternative than the action or practice that
the critic charges utilitarianism wrongly supports; e.g., no system of slavery
that has ever existed is plausibly thought to have maximized utility for the
society in question. Defenders of utilitarianism also typically try to show
that it does take account of the moral consideration the critic claims it
wrongly ignores; for instance, utilitarians commonly appeal to the declining
marginal utility of money equal marginal
increments of money tend to produce less utility e.g. happiness for persons,
the more money they already utilitarianism utilitarianism have as giving some support to equality in income
distribution. Another source of controversy concerns whether moral principles
should be agent-neutral or, in at least some cases, agent-relative.
Utilitarianism is agent-neutral in that it gives all people the same moral
aim act so as to maximize utility for
everyone whereas agent-relative
principles give different moral aims to different individuals. Defenders of
agent-relative principles note that a commonly accepted moral rule like the
prohibition of killing the innocent is understood as telling each agent that he
or she must not kill, even if doing so is the only way to prevent a still
greater number of killings by others. In this way, a non-utilitarian,
agent-relative prohibition reflects the common moral view that each person
bears special moral responsibility for what he or she does, which is greater
than his or her responsibility to prevent similar wrong actions by others.
Common moral beliefs also permit people to give special weight to their own
projects and commitments and, e.g., to favor to some extent their own children
at the expense of other children in greater need; agent-relative
responsibilities to one’s own family reflect these moral views in a way that
agent-neutral utilitarian responsibilities apparently do not. The debate over
neutrality and relativity is related to a final area of controversy about
utilitarianism. Critics charge that utilitarianism makes morality far too
demanding by requiring that one always act to maximize utility. If, e.g., one
reads a book or goes to a movie, one could nearly always be using one’s time
and resources to do more good by aiding famine relief. The critics believe that
this wrongly makes morally required what should be only supererogatory action that is good, but goes beyond “the
call of duty” and is not morally required. Here, utilitarians have often argued
that ordinary moral views are seriously mistaken and that morality can demand
greater sacrifices of one’s own interests for the benefit of others than is
commonly believed. There is little doubt that here, and in many other cases,
utilitarianism’s moral implications significantly conflict with commonsense
moral beliefs the dispute is whether
this should count against commonsense moral beliefs or against utilitarianism.
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Bergmann on Stephen
and the English utilitarians.”
entelecheia -- used by Grice in his philosophical psychology
-- from Grecian entelecheia, energeia, actuality. Aristotle, who coins both
terms, entelecheia and energeia, treats entelecheia as a near synonym of
Energeia (“which makes me often wonder why he felt the need to coin TWICE” – H.
P. Grice.). Entelecheia figures in Aristotle’s definition of the soul (psyche) as
the first actuality of the natural body (De Anima, II.1). This is explained by
analogy with knowledge: first actuality is to knowledge as second actuality is
to the active use of knowledge. ’Entelechia’ is also a technical term, but in
German, in Leibniz for the primitive active force in every monad, which is
combined with primary matter, and from which the active force, vis viva, is
somehow derived (“But I rather use ‘entelecheia’ in the original Grecian.” –
Grice). “The vitalist philosopher Hans Driesch used the Aristotelian term in
his account of biology, and I feel vitalistic on occasion.” “Life, Driesch
holds, is not a bowl of cherries, but an entelechy; and an entelechy is a
substantial entity, rather like a mind, that controls organic processes.” “To
me, life is rather a bowl of cherries, don’t make it serious! It’s just
mysterious!”
enthymeme: an incompletely
stated syllogism, with one premise, or even the conclusion, omitted. The term
sometimes designates incompletely stated arguments of other kinds. We are
expected to supply the missing premise or draw the conclusion if it is not
stated. The result is supposed to be a syllogistic inference. For example: ‘He
will eventually get caught, for he is a thief’; or ‘He will eventually be
caught, for all habitual thieves get caught’. This notion of enthymeme as an
incompletely stated syllogism has a long tradition and does not seem
inconsistent with Aristotle’s own characterization of it. Thus, Peter of Spain
openly declares that an enthymeme is an argument with a single premise that
needs to be reduced to syllogism. But Peter also points out that Aristotle
spoke of enthymeme as “being of ycos and signum,” and he explains that ycos
here means ‘probable proposition’ while signum expresses the necessity of
inference. ‘P, therefore Q’ is an ycos in the sense of a proposition that appears
to be true to all or to many; but insofar as P has virtually a double power,
that of itself and of the proposition understood along with it, it is both
probable and demonstrative, albeit from a different point of view.
EPI-STEMIC
– Grice:
“Philosophers hardly realise how artificial the idea of a Grecian epi-steme is!
from epi "over, near" (see epi-) +
histasthai "to stand," from PIE root *sta- "to stand, make or be
firm." epistemic
deontologism, a duty-based view of the nature of epistemic justification. A
central concern of epistemology is to account for the distinction between
justified and unjustified beliefs. According to epistemic deontologism, the
concept of justification may be analyzed by using, in a specific sense relevant
to the pursuit of knowledge, terms such as ‘ought’, ‘obligatory’,
‘permissible’, and ‘forbidden’. A subject S is justified in believing that p
provided S does not violate any epistemic obligations those that arise from the goal of believing
what is true and not believing what is false. Equivalently, S is justified in
believing that p provided believing p is
from the point of view taken in the pursuit of truth permissible for S. Among contemporary
epistemologists, this view is held by Chisholm, Laurence BonJour, and Carl
Ginet. Its significance is twofold. If justification is a function of meeting
obligations, then it is, contrary to some versions of naturalistic
epistemology, normative. Second, if the normativity of justification is
deontological, the factors that determine whether a belief is justified must be
internal to the subject’s mind. Critics of epistemic deontologism, most
conspicuously Alston, contend that belief is involuntary and thus cannot be a
proper object of obligations. If, e.g., one is looking out the window and
notices that it is raining, one is psychologically forced to believe that it is
raining. Deontologists can reply to this objection by rejecting its underlying
premise: epistemic obligations require that belief be voluntary. Alternatively,
they may insist that belief is voluntary after all, and thus subject to
epistemic obligations, for there is a means by which one can avoid believing
what one ought not to believe: weighing the evidence, or deliberation. -- epistemic logic, the logical investigation
of epistemic concepts and statements. Epistemic concepts include the concepts
of knowledge, reasonable belief, justification, evidence, certainty, and
related notions. Epistemic logic is usually taken to include the logic of
belief or doxastic logic. Much of the recent work on epistemic logic is based
on the view that it is a branch of modal logic. In the early 0s von Wright
observed that the epistemic notions verified known to be true, undecided, and
falsified are related to each other in the same way as the alethic modalities
necessary, contingent, and impossible, and behave logically in analogous ways.
This analogy is not surprising in view of the fact that the meaning of modal
concepts is often explained epistemically. For example, in the 0s Peirce
defined informational possibility as that “which in a given state of
information is not perfectly known not to be true,” and called informationally
necessary “that which is perfectly known to be true.” The modal logic of
epistemic and doxastic concepts was studied systematically by Hintikka in his
pioneering Knowledge and Belief2, which applied to the concepts of knowledge
and belief the semantical method the method of modal sets that he had used
earlier for the investigation of modal logic. In this approach, the truth of
the proposition that a knows that p briefly Kap in a possible world or
situation u is taken to mean that p holds in all epistemic alternatives of u;
these are understood as worlds compatible with what a knows at u. If the relation
of epistemic alternativeness is reflexive, the principle ‘KapPp’ only what is
the case can be known is valid, and the assumption that the alternativeness
relation is transitive validates the so-called KK-thesis, ‘Kap P Ka Ka p’ if a
knows that p, a knows that a knows that p; these two assumptions together make
the logic of knowledge similar to an S4-type modal logic. If the knowledge
operator Ka and the corresponding epistemic possibility operator Pa are added
to quantification theory with identity, it becomes possible to study the
interplay between quantifiers and epistemic operators and the behavior of
individual terms in epistemic contexts, and analyze such locutions as ‘a knows
who what b some F is’. The problems of epistemic logic in this area are part of
the general problem of giving a coherent semantical account of propositional
attitudes. If a proposition p is true in all epistemic alternatives of a given
world, so are all logical consequences of p; thus the possible-worlds semantics
of epistemic concepts outlined above leads to the result that a person knows
all logical consequences of what he knows. This is a paradoxical conclusion; it
is called the problem of logical omniscience. The solution of this problem
requires a distinction between different levels of knowledge for example, between tacit and explicit
knowledge. A more realistic model of knowledge can be obtained by supplementing
the basic possible-worlds account by an analysis of the processes by which the
implicit knowledge can be activated and made explicit. Modal epistemic logics
have found fruitful applications in the recent work on knowledge representation
and in the logic and semantics of questions and answers in which questions are
interpreted as requests for knowledge or “epistemic imperatives.” -- epistemic principle, a principle of
rationality applicable to such concepts as knowledge, justification, and
reasonable belief. Epistemic principles include the principles of epistemic
logic and principles that relate different epistemic concepts to one another,
or epistemic concepts to nonepistemic ones e.g., semantic concepts. Epistemic
concepts include the concepts of knowledge, reasonable belief, justification,
epistemic probability, and other concepts that are used for the purpose of
assessing the reasonableness of beliefs and knowledge claims. Epistemic
principles can be formulated as principles concerning belief systems or
information systems, i.e., systems that characterize a person’s possible
doxastic state at a given time; a belief system may be construed as a set of
accepted propositions or as a system of degrees of belief. It is possible to
distinguish two kinds of epistemic principles: a principles concerning the
rationality of a single belief system, and b principles concerning the rational
changes of belief. The former include the requirements of coherence and
consistency for beliefs and for probabilities; such principles may be said to
concern the statics of belief systems. The latter principles include various
principles of belief revision and adjustment, i.e., principles concerning the
dynamics of belief systems. -- epistemic
privacy, the relation a person has to a proposition when only that person can
have direct or non-inferential knowledge of the proposition. It is widely
thought that people have epistemic privacy with respect to propositions about
certain of their own mental states. According to this view, a person can know
directly that he has certain thoughts or feelings or sensory experiences.
Perhaps others can also know that the person has these thoughts, feelings, or
experiences, but if they can it is only as a result of inference from
propositions about the person’s behavior or physical condition. -- epistemic regress argument, an argument,
originating in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics, aiming to show that knowledge
and epistemic justification have a two-tier structure as described by epistemic
foundationalism. It lends itself to the following outline regarding
justification. If you have any justified belief, this belief occurs in an
evidential chain including at least two links: the supporting link i.e., the
evidence and the supported link i.e., the justified belief. This does not mean,
however, that all evidence consists of beliefs. Evidential chains might come in
any of four kinds: circular chains, endless chains, chains ending in
unjustified beliefs, and chains anchored in foundational beliefs that do not
derive their justification from other beliefs. Only the fourth, foundationalist
kind is defensible as grounding knowledge and epistemic justification. Could
all justification be inferential? A belief, B1, is inferentially justified when
it owes its justification, at least in part, to some other belief, B2. Whence
the justification for B2? If B2 owes its justification to B1, we have a
troublesome circle. How can B2 yield justification or evidence for B1, if B2
owes its evidential status to B1? On the other hand, if B2 owes its
justification to another belief, B3, and B3 owes its justification to yet
another belief, B4, and so on ad infinitum, we have a troublesome endless
regress of justification. Such a regress seems to deliver not actual
justification, but at best merely potential justification, for the belief at
its head. Actual finite humans, furthermore, seem not to be able to comprehend,
or to possess, all the steps of an infinite regress of justification. Finally,
if B2 is itself unjustified, it evidently will be unable to provide
justification for B1. It seems, then, that the structure of inferential justification
does not consist of either circular justification, endless regresses of
justification, or unjustified starter-beliefs. We have foundationalism, then,
as the most viable account of evidential chains, so long as we understand it as
the structural view that some beliefs are justified non-inferentially i.e.,
without deriving justification from other beliefs, but can nonetheless provide
justification for other beliefs. More precisely, if we have any justified
beliefs, we have some foundational, non-inferentially justified beliefs. This
regress argument needs some refinement before its full force can be
appreciated. With suitable refinement, however, it can seriously challenge such
alternatives to foundationalism as coherentism and contextualism. The regress
argument has been a key motivation for foundationalism in the history of
epistemology. -- epistemology from
Grecian episteme, ‘knowledge’, and logos, ‘explanation’, the study of the
nature of knowledge and justification; specifically, the study of a the
defining features, b the substantive conditions or sources, and c the limits of
knowledge and justification. The latter three categories are represented by
traditional philosophical controversy over the analysis of knowledge and
justification, the sources of knowledge and justification e.g., rationalism
versus empiricism, and the viability of skepticism about knowledge and
justification. Kinds of knowledge. Knowledge can be either explicit or tacit.
Explicit knowledge is self-conscious in that the knower is aware of the
relevant state of knowledge, whereas tacit knowledge is implicit, hidden from
self-consciousness. Much of our knowledge is tacit: it is genuine but we are
unaware of the relevant states of knowledge, even if we can achieve awareness
upon suitable reflection. In this regard, knowledge resembles many of our
psychological states. The existence of a psychological state in a person does
not require the person’s awareness of that state, although it may require the
person’s awareness of an object of that state such as what is sensed or
perceived. Philosophers have identified various species of knowledge: for
example, propositional knowledge that something is so, non-propositional
knowledge of something e.g., knowledge by acquaintance, or by direct awareness,
empirical a posteriori propositional knowledge, nonempirical a priori
propositional knowledge, and knowledge of how to do something. Philosophical
controversy has arisen over distinctions between such species, for example,
over i the relations between some of these species e.g., does knowing-how
reduce to knowledge-that?, and ii the viability of some of these species e.g.,
is there really such a thing as, or even a coherent notion of, a priori
knowledge?. A primary concern of classical modern philosophy, in the
seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, was the extent of our a priori knowledge
relative to the extent of our a posteriori knowledge. Such rationalists as
Descartes, Leibniz, and Spinoza contended that all genuine knowledge of the
real world is a priori, whereas such empiricists as Locke, Berkeley, and Hume
argued that all such knowledge is a posteriori. In his Critique of Pure Reason
1781, Kant sought a grand reconciliation, aiming to preserve the key lessons of
both rationalism and empiricism. Since the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries, a posteriori knowledge has been widely regarded as knowledge that
depends for its supporting ground on some specific sensory or perceptual
experience; and a priori knowledge has been widely regarded as knowledge that
does not depend for its supporting ground on such experience. Kant and others
have held that the supporting ground for a priori knowledge comes solely from
purely intellectual processes called “pure reason” or “pure understanding.”
Knowledge of logical and mathematical truths typically serves as a standard
case of a priori knowledge, whereas knowledge of the existence or presence of
physical objects typically serves as a standard case of a posteriori knowledge.
A major task for an account of a priori knowledge is the explanation of what
the relevant purely intellectual processes are, and of how they contribute to
non-empirical knowledge. An analogous task for an account of a posteriori
knowledge is the explanation of what sensory or perceptual experience is and
how it contributes to empirical knowledge. More fundamentally, epistemologists
have sought an account of propositional knowledge in general, i.e., an account
of what is common to a priori and a posteriori knowledge. Ever since Plato’s
Meno and Theaetetus c.400 B.C., epistemologists have tried to identify the
essential, defining components of knowledge. Identifying these components will
yield an analysis of knowledge. A prominent traditional view, suggested by
Plato and Kant among others, is that propositional knowledge that something is
so has three individually necessary and jointly sufficient components:
justification, truth, and belief. On this view, propositional knowledge is, by
definition, justified true belief. This is the tripartite definition that has
come to be called the standard analysis. We can clarify it by attending briefly
to each of its three conditions. The belief condition. This requires that
anyone who knows that p where ‘p’ stands for any proposition or statement must
believe that p. If, therefore, you do not believe that minds are brains say,
because you have not considered the matter at all, then you do not know that
minds are brains. A knower must be psychologically related somehow to a
proposition that is an object of knowledge for that knower. Proponents of the
standard analysis hold that only belief can provide the needed psychological
relation. Philosophers do not share a uniform account of belief, but some
considerations supply common ground. Beliefs are not actions of assenting to a
proposition; they rather are dispositional psychological states that can exist
even when unmanifested. You do not cease believing that 2 ! 2 % 4, for example,
whenever your attention leaves arithmetic. Our believing that p seems to require
that we have a tendency to assent to p in certain situations, but it seems also
to be more than just such a tendency. What else believing requires remains
highly controversial among philosophers. Some philosophers have opposed the
belief condition of the standard analysis on the ground that we can accept, or
assent to, a known proposition without actually believing it. They contend that
we can accept a proposition even if we fail to acquire a tendency, required by
believing, to accept that proposition in certain situations. On this view,
acceptance is a psychological act that does not entail any dispositional
psychological state, and such acceptance is sufficient to relate a knower
psychologically to a known proposition. However this view fares, one underlying
assumption of the standard analysis seems correct: our concept of knowledge
requires that a knower be psychologically related somehow to a known
proposition. Barring that requirement, we shall be hard put to explain how
knowers psychologically possess their knowledge of known propositions. Even if
knowledge requires belief, belief that p does not require knowledge that p,
since belief can typically be false. This observation, familiar from Plato’s
Theaetetus, assumes that knowledge has a truth condition. On the standard
analysis, if you know that p, then it is true that p. If, therefore, it is
false that minds are brains, then you do not know that minds are brains. It is
thus misleading to say, e.g., that astronomers before Copernicus knew that the
earth is flat; at best, they justifiably believed that they knew this. The
truth condition. This condition of the standard analysis has not attracted any
serious challenge. Controversy over it has focused instead on Pilate’s vexing
question: What is truth? This question concerns what truth consists in, not our
ways of finding out what is true. Influential answers come from at least three
approaches: truth as correspondence i.e., agreement, of some specified sort,
between a proposition and an actual situation; truth as coherence i.e.,
interconnectedness of a proposition with a specified system of propositions;
and truth as pragmatic cognitive value i.e., usefulness of a proposition in
achieving certain intellectual goals. Without assessing these prominent approaches,
we should recognize, in accord with the standard analysis, that our concept of
knowledge seems to have a factual requirement: we epistemology epistemology
274 274 genuinely know that p only if
it is the case that p. The pertinent notion of “its being the case” seems
equivalent to the notion of “how reality is” or “how things really are.” The
latter notion seems essential to our notion of knowledge, but is open to
controversy over its explication. The justification condition. Knowledge is not
simply true belief. Some true beliefs are supported only by lucky guesswork and
hence do not qualify as knowledge. Knowledge requires that the satisfaction of
its belief condition be “appropriately related” to the satisfaction of its
truth condition. This is one broad way of understanding the justification
condition of the standard analysis. More specifically, we might say that a
knower must have adequate indication that a known proposition is true. If we
understand such adequate indication as a sort of evidence indicating that a
proposition is true, we have reached the traditional general view of the
justification condition: justification as evidence. Questions about
justification attract the lion’s share of attention in contemporary
epistemology. Controversy focuses on the meaning of ‘justification’ as well as
on the substantive conditions for a belief’s being justified in a way
appropriate to knowledge. Current debates about the meaning of ‘justification’
revolve around the question whether, and if so how, the concept of epistemic
knowledge-relevant justification is normative. Since the 0s Chisholm has
defended the following deontological obligation-oriented notion of
justification: the claim that a proposition, p, is epistemically justified for
you means that it is false that you ought to refrain from accepting p. In other
terms, to say that p is epistemically justified is to say that accepting p is
epistemically permissible at least in
the sense that accepting p is consistent with a certain set of epistemic rules.
This deontological construal enjoys wide representation in contemporary
epistemology. A normative construal of justification need not be deontological;
it need not use the notions of obligation and permission. Alston, for instance,
has introduced a non-deontological normative concept of justification that
relies mainly on the notion of what is epistemically good from the viewpoint of
maximizing truth and minimizing falsity. Alston links epistemic goodness to a
belief’s being based on adequate grounds in the absence of overriding reasons
to the contrary. Some epistemologists shun normative construals of
justification as superfluous. One noteworthy view is that ‘epistemic
justification’ means simply ‘evidential support’ of a certain sort. To say that
p is epistemically justifiable to some extent for you is, on this view, just to
say that p is supportable to some extent by your overall evidential reasons.
This construal will be non-normative so long as the notions of supportability
and an evidential reason are nonnormative. Some philosophers have tried to
explicate the latter notions without relying on talk of epistemic
permissibility or epistemic goodness. We can understand the relevant notion of
“support” in terms of non-normative notions of entailment and explanation or,
answering why-questions. We can understand the notion of an “evidential reason”
via the notion of a psychological state that can stand in a certain
truth-indicating support relation to propositions. For instance, we might
regard nondoxastic states of “seeming to perceive” something e.g., seeming to
see a dictionary here as foundational truth indicators for certain
physical-object propositions e.g., the proposition that there is a dictionary
here, in virtue of those states being best explained by those propositions. If
anything resembling this approach succeeds, we can get by without the
aforementioned normative notions of epistemic justification. Foundationalism
versus coherentism. Talk of foundational truth indicators brings us to a key
controversy over justification: Does epistemic justification, and thus
knowledge, have foundations, and if so, in what sense? This question can be
clarified as the issue whether some beliefs can not only a have their epistemic
justification non-inferentially i.e., apart from evidential support from any
other beliefs, but also b provide epistemic justification for all justified
beliefs that lack such non-inferential justification. Foundationalism gives an
affirmative answer to this issue, and is represented in varying ways by, e.g.,
Aristotle, Descartes, Russell, C. I. Lewis, and Chisholm. Foundationalists do
not share a uniform account of non-inferential justification. Some construe
non-inferential justification as self-justification. Others reject literal
self-justification for beliefs, and argue that foundational beliefs have their
non-inferential justification in virtue of evidential support from the
deliverances of non-belief psychological states, e.g., perception
“seem-ing-to-perceive” states, sensation “seeming-to-sense” states, or memory
“seeming-toremember” states. Still others understand noninferential
justification in terms of a belief’s being “reliably produced,” i.e., caused
and sustained by some non-belief belief-producing process or source e.g., perception,
memory, introspection that tends to produce true rather than false beliefs.
This last view takes the causal source of a belief to be crucial to its
justification. Unlike Descartes, contemporary foundationalists clearly separate
claims to non-inferential, foundational justification from claims to certainty.
They typically settle for a modest foundationalism implying that foundational
beliefs need not be indubitable or infallible. This contrasts with the radical
foundationalism of Descartes. The traditional competitor to foundationalism is
the coherence theory of justification, i.e., epistemic coherentism. This is not
the coherence definition of truth; it rather is the view that the justification
of any belief depends on that belief’s having evidential support from some
other belief via coherence relations such as entailment or explanatory
relations. Notable proponents include Hegel, Bosanquet, and Sellars. A
prominent contemporary version of epistemic coherentism states that evidential
coherence relations among beliefs are typically explanatory relations. The
rough idea is that a belief is justified for you so long as it either best
explains, or is best explained by, some member of the system of beliefs that
has maximal explanatory power for you. Contemporary coherentism is uniformly
systemic or holistic; it finds the ultimate source of justification in a system
of interconnected beliefs or potential beliefs. One problem has troubled all
versions of coherentism that aim to explain empirical justification: the
isolation argument. According to this argument, coherentism entails that you
can be epistemically justified in accepting an empirical proposition that is
incompatible with, or at least improbable given, your total empirical evidence.
The key assumption of this argument is that your total empirical evidence
includes non-belief sensory and perceptual awareness-states, such as your
feeling pain or your seeming to see something. These are not belief-states.
Epistemic coherentism, by definition, makes justification a function solely of
coherence relations between propositions, such as propositions one believes or
accepts. Thus, such coherentism seems to isolate justification from the
evidential import of non-belief awareness-states. Coherentists have tried to handle
this problem, but no resolution enjoys wide acceptance. Causal and
contextualist theories. Some contemporary epistemologists endorse contextualism
regarding epistemic justification, a view suggested by Dewey, Vitters, and
Kuhn, among others. On this view, all justified beliefs depend for their
evidential support on some unjustified beliefs that need no justification. In
any context of inquiry, people simply assume the acceptability of some
propositions as starting points for inquiry, and these “contextually basic”
propositions, though lacking evidential support, can serve as evidential
support for other propositions. Contextualists stress that contextually basic
propositions can vary from context to context e.g., from theological inquiry to
biological inquiry and from social group to social group. The main problem for
contextualists comes from their view that unjustified assumptions can provide
epistemic justification for other propositions. We need a precise explanation
of how an unjustified assumption can yield evidential support, how a
non-probable belief can make another belief probable. Contextualists have not
given a uniform explanation here. Recently some epistemologists have
recommended that we give up the traditional evidence condition for knowledge.
They recommend that we construe the justification condition as a causal
condition. Roughly, the idea is that you know that p if and only if a you
believe that p, b p is true, and c your believing that p is causally produced
and sustained by the fact that makes p true. This is the basis of the causal
theory of knowing, which comes with varying details. Any such causal theory
faces serious problems from our knowledge of universal propositions. Evidently,
we know, for instance, that all dictionaries are produced by people, but our
believing that this is so seems not to be causally supported by the fact that
all dictionaries are humanly produced. It is not clear that the latter fact
causally produces any beliefs. Another problem is that causal theories typically
neglect what seems to be crucial to any account of the justification condition:
the requirement that justificational support for a belief be accessible, in
some sense, to the believer. The rough idea is that one must be able to access,
or bring to awareness, the justification underlying one’s beliefs. The causal
origins of a belief are, of course, often very complex and inaccessible to a
believer. Causal theories thus face problems from an accessibility requirement
on justification. Internalism regarding justification preserves an
accessibility requirement on what confers justification, whereas epistemic
externalism rejects this requirement. Debates over internalism and externalism
abound in current epistemology, but internalists do not yet share a uniform
detailed account of accessibility. The Gettier problem. The standard analysis
of knowledge, however elaborated, faces a devastating challenge that initially
gave rise to causal theories of knowledge: the Gettier problem. In 3 Edmund
Gettier published a highly influential challenge to the view that if you have a
justified true belief that p, then you know that p. Here is one of Gettier’s
counterexamples to this view: Smith is justified in believing the false
proposition that i Jones owns a Ford. On the basis of i, Smith infers, and thus
is justified in believing, that ii either Jones owns a Ford or Brown is in
Barcelona. As it happens, Brown is in Barcelona, and so ii is true. So,
although Smith is justified in believing the true proposition ii, Smith does
not know ii. Gettier-style counterexamples are cases where a person has
justified true belief that p but lacks knowledge that p. The Gettier problem is
the problem of finding a modification of, or an alternative to, the standard
analysis that avoids difficulties from Gettier-style counterexamples. The
controversy over the Gettier problem is highly complex and still unsettled.
Many epistemologists take the lesson of Gettier-style counterexamples to be
that propositional knowledge requires a fourth condition, beyond the
justification, truth, and belief conditions. No specific fourth condition has
received overwhelming acceptance, but some proposals have become prominent. The
so-called defeasibility condition, e.g., requires that the justification appropriate
to knowledge be “undefeated” in the general sense that some appropriate
subjunctive conditional concerning defeaters of justification be true of that
justification. For instance, one simple defeasibility fourth condition requires
of Smith’s knowing that p that there be no true proposition, q, such that if q
became justified for Smith, p would no longer be justified for Smith. So if
Smith knows, on the basis of his visual perception, that Mary removed books
from the library, then Smith’s coming to believe the true proposition that
Mary’s identical twin removed books from the library would not undermine the
justification for Smith’s belief concerning Mary herself. A different approach
shuns subjunctive conditionals of that sort, and contends that propositional
knowledge requires justified true belief that is sustained by the collective
totality of actual truths. This approach requires a detailed account of when
justification is undermined and restored. The Gettier problem is
epistemologically important. One branch of epistemology seeks a precise
understanding of the nature e.g., the essential components of propositional
knowledge. Our having a precise understanding of propositional knowledge
requires our having a Gettier-proof analysis of such knowledge. Epistemologists
thus need a defensible solution to the Gettier problem, however complex that
solution is. Skepticism. Epistemologists debate the limits, or scope, of
knowledge. The more restricted we take the limits of knowledge to be, the more
skeptical we are. Two influential types of skepticism are knowledge skepticism
and justification skepticism. Unrestricted knowledge skepticism implies that no
one knows anything, whereas unrestricted justification skepticism implies the
more extreme view that no one is even justified in believing anything. Some
forms of skepticism are stronger than others. Knowledge skepticism in its
strongest form implies that it is impossible for anyone to know anything. A
weaker form would deny the actuality of our having knowledge, but leave open
its possibility. Many skeptics have restricted their skepticism to a particular
domain of supposed knowledge: e.g., knowledge of the external world, knowledge
of other minds, knowledge of the past or the future, or knowledge of
unperceived items. Such limited skepticism is more common than unrestricted
skepticism in the history of epistemology. Arguments supporting skepticism come
in many forms. One of the most difficult is the problem of the criterion, a
version of which has been stated by the sixteenth-century skeptic Montaigne:
“To adjudicate [between the true and the false] among the appearances of
things, we need to have a distinguishing method; to validate this method, we
need to have a justifying argument; but to validate this justifying argument,
we need the very method at issue. And there we are, going round on the wheel.”
This line of skeptical argument originated in ancient Greece, with epistemology
itself. It forces us to face this question: How can we specify what we know
without having specified how we know, and how can we specify how we know
without having specified what we know? Is there any reasonable way out of this
threatening circle? This is one of the most difficult epistemological problems,
and a cogent epistemology must offer a defensible solution to epistemology
epistemology 277 277 it. Contemporary
epistemology still lacks a widely accepted reply to this urgent problem
erfahrung: Grice used the
German, ‘since I find it difficult to translate.” G. term tr. into English,
especially since Kant, as ‘experience’. Kant does not use it as a technical
term; rather, it indicates that which requires explanation through more
precisely drawn technical distinctions such as those among ‘sensibility’,
‘understanding’, and ‘reason’. In the early twentieth century, Husserl
sometimes distinguishes between Erfahrung and Erlebnis, the former indicating
experience as capable of being thematized and methodically described or
analyzed, the latter experience as “lived through” and never fully available to
analysis. Such a distinction occasionally reappears in later texts of
phenomenology and existentialism.
eristic, the art of controversy, often
involving fallacious but persuasive reasoning. The ancient Sophists brought
this art to a high level to achieve their personal goal. They may have found
their material in the “encounters” in the law courts as well as in daily life.
To enhance persuasion they endorsed the use of unsound principles such as hasty
generalizations, faulty analogies, illegitimate appeal to authority, the post
hoc ergo propter hoc i.e., “after this, therefore because of this” and other
presumed principles. Aristotle exposed eristic argumentation in his Sophistical
Refutations, which itself draws examples from Plato’s Euthydemus. From this
latter work comes the famous example: ‘That dog is a father and that dog is
his, therefore that dog is his father’. What is perhaps worse than its obvious
invalidity is that the argument is superficially similar to a sound argument
such as ‘This is a table and this is brown, therefore this is a brown table’.
In the Sophistical Refutations Aristotle undertakes to find procedures for
detection of bad arguments and to propose rules for constructing sound
arguments.
erlebnis: G. Grice used the
German term, “since I find it difficult to translate it” -- term for experience
used in late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century G. philosophy. Erlebnis
denotes experience in all its direct immediacy and lived fullness. It contrasts
with the more typical G. word Erfahrung, denoting ordinary experience as
mediated through intellectual and constructive elements. As immediate, Erlebnis
eludes conceptualization, in both the lived present and the interiority of
experience. As direct, Erlebnis is also disclosive and extraordinary: it
reveals something real that otherwise escapes thinking. Typical examples
include art, religion, and love, all of which also show the anti-rationalist
and polemical uses of the concept. It is especially popular among the Romantic
mystics like Novalis and the anti-rationalists Nietzsche and Bergson, as well
as in phenomenology, Lebensphilosophie, and existentialism. As used in
post-Hegelian G. philosophy, the term describes two aspects of subjectivity.
The first concerns the epistemology of the human sciences and of phenomenology.
Against naturalism and objectivism, philosophers appeal to the ineliminable,
subjective qualities of experience to argue that interpreters must understand
“what it is like to be” some experiencing subject, from the inside. The second
use of the term is to denote extraordinary and interior experiences like art,
religion, freedom, and vital energy. In both cases, it is unclear how such
experience could be identified or known in its immediacy, and much recent G.
thought, such as Heidegger and hermeneutics, rejects the concept.
erotetic: in the strict
sense, pertaining to questions. Erotetic logic is the logic of questions.
Different conceptions of questions yield different kinds of erotetic logic. A
Platonistic approach holds that questions exist independently of
interrogatives. For P. Tichý, a question is a function on possible worlds, the
right answer being the value of the function at the actual world. Erotetic
logic is the logic of such functions. In the epistemic-imperative approach of
L. Bqvist, Hintikka, et al., one begins with a system for epistemic sentences
and embeds this in a system for imperative sentences, thus obtaining sentences
of the form ‘make it the case that I know . . .’ and complex compounds of such
sentences. Certain ones of these are defined to be interrogatives. Then
erotetic logic is the logic of epistemic imperatives and the conditions for
satisfaction of these imperatives. In the abstract interrogative approach of N.
Belnap, T. Kubigski, and many others, one chooses certain types of expression
to serve as interrogatives, and, for each type, specifies what expressions
count as answers of various kinds direct, partial, . . .. On this approach we
may say that interrogatives express questions, or we may identify questions
with interrogatives, in which case the only meaning that an interrogative has
is that it has the answers that it does. Either way, the emphasis is on
interrogatives, and erotetic logic is the logic of systems that provide
interrogatives and specify answers to them. In the broad sense, ‘erotetic’ designates
what pertains to utterance-and-response. In this sense erotetic logic is the
logic of the relations between 1 sentences of many kinds and 2 the expressions
that count as appropriate replies to them. This includes not only the relations
between question and answer but also, e.g., between assertion and agreement or
denial, command and report of compliance or refusal, and for many types of
sentence S between S and various corrective replies to S e.g., denial of the
presupposition of S. Erotetic logics may differ in the class of sentences
treated, the types of response counted as appropriate, the assignment of other
content presupposition, projection, etc., and other details.
eschatologicum: Possibly related to Latin ‘summum, ‘as in ‘summum genus,’
and ‘summun bonum. From Greek, 5. in the Logic of Arist., τὰ ἔ. are the last or
lowest species, Metaph.1059b26, or individuals, ib.998b16, cf. AP0.96b12, al.;
“τὸ ἔ. ἄτομον” Metaph.1058b10. b. ὁ ἔ. ὅρος the minor term of a syllogism,
EN1147b14. c. last step in geom. analysis or ultimate condition of action, “τὸ
ἔ. ἀρχὴ τῆς πράξεως” de An.433a16. II. Adv. -τως to the uttermost, exceedingly,
“πῦρ ἐ. καίει” Hp.de Arte8; “ἐ. διαμάχεσθαι” Arist.HA613a11 ; “ἐ. φιλοπόλεμος”
X.An.2.6.1 ; “φοβοῦμαί σ᾽ ἐ.” Men.912, cf. Epicur.Ep. 1p.31U. b. -τως
διακεῖσθαι to be at the last extremity, Plb.1.24.2, D.S.18.48 ; “ἔχειν”
Ev.Marc.5.23 ; “ἀπορεῖν” Phld.Oec.p.72J. 2. so ἐς τὸ ἔ.,=ἐσχάτως, Hdt.7.229;
“εἰς τὰ ἔ.” X.HG5.4.33 ; “εἰς τὰ ἔ. μάλα” Id.Lac.1.2 ; “τὸ ἔ.” finally, in the end,
Pl.Grg.473c ; but, τὸ ἔ. what is worst of all, ib.508d. Why ontology is not
enough. The philosopher needs to PLAY with cross-categorial barriers. He is an
eschatologist. Socrates was. being and good, for Aristotle and Grice cover all.
Good was a favourite of Moore and Hare, as Barnes was well aware! Like Barnes,
Grice dislikes Prichards analysis of good. He leans towards the emotion-based
approach by Ogden. If Grice, like Humpty Dumpty, opposes the Establishment with
his meaning liberalism (what a word means is what I mean by uttering it), he
certainly should be concerned with category shifts. Plus, Grice was a closet
Platonist. As Plato once remarked, having the ability to see horses but not
horsehood (ἱππότης) is a mark of stupidity – rendered by Liddell and Scott as
“horse-nature, the concept of horse” (Antisth. et Pl. ap. Simp.in
Cat.208.30,32, Sch.AristId.p.167F). Grice would endure the flinty experience of
giving joint seminars at Oxford with Austin on the first two books of
Aristotles Organon, Categoriae, and De Int. Grice finds the use of a
category, κατηγορία, by Aristotle a bit of a geniality. Aristotle is using
legalese, from kata, against, on, and agoreuô [ἀγορεύω], speak in public),
and uses it to designate both the prosecution in a trial and the
attribution in a logical proposition, i. e., the questions that must be asked
with regard to a Subjects, and the answers that can be given. As a
representative of the linguistic turn in philosophy, Grice is attracted to the
idea that a category can thus be understood variously, as applying to the realm
of reality (ontology), but also to the philosophy of language (category of
expression) and to philosophical psychology (category of
representation). Grice kept his explorations on categories under two very
separate, shall we say, categories: his explorations with Austin (very
serious), and those with Strawson (more congenial). Where is Smiths altruism?
Nowhere to be seen. Should we say it is idle (otiose) to speak of altruism? No,
it is just an attribute, which, via category shift, can be made the Subjects of
your sentence, Strawson. It is not spatio-temporal, though, right. Not
really. ‒ I do not particularly like your trouser words. The essay
is easy to date since Grice notes that Strawson reproduced some of the details in
his Individuals, which we can very well date. Grice thought Aristotle was the
best! Or at any rate almost as good as Kantotle! Aristotle saw Categoriæ, along
with De Int. as part of his Organon. However, philosophers of language
tend to explore these topics without a consideration of the later parts of the
Organon dealing with the syllogism, the tropes, and the topics ‒ the boring
bits! The reason Grice is attracted to the Aristotelian category (as Austin and
Strawson equally were) is that category allows for a linguistic-turn reading.
Plus, its a nice, pretentious (in the Oxonian way) piece of philosophical
jargon! Aristotle couldnt find category in the koine, so he had to coin it.
While meant by Aristotle in a primarily ontological way, Oxonian philosophers
hasten to add that a category of expression, as Grice puts it, is just as valid
a topic for philosophical exploration. His tutee Strawson will actually publish
a book on Subjects and predicate in grammar! (Trivial, Strawson!). Grice will
later add an intermediary category, which is the Subjects of his philosophical
psychology. As such, a category can be construed ontologically, or
representationally: the latter involving philosophical psychological concepts,
and expressions themselves. For Aristotle, as Grice and Austin, and Grice and
Strawson, were well aware as they educated some of the poor at Oxford (Only the
poor learn at Oxford ‒ Arnold), there are (at least ‒ at most?) ten
categories. Grice doesnt (really) care about the number. But the first are
important. Actually the very first: theres substantia prima, such as Grice. And
then theres substantia secunda, such as Grices rationality. The essentia. Then
there are various types of attributes. But, as Grice sharply notes, even substantia
secunda may be regarded as an attribute. Grices favourite game with Strawson
was indeed Category Shift, or Subjects-ification, as Strawson preferred.
Essence may be introduced as a sub-type of an attribute. We would have
substantia prima AND attribute, which in turn gets divided into essential, the
izzing, and non-essential, the hazzing. While Austin is not so fun to play
with, Strawson is. Smith is a very altruist person. Where is his altruism?
Nowhere to be seen, really. Yet we may sensically speak of Smiths altruism. It
is just a matter of a category shift. Grice scores. Grice is slightly
disappointed, but he perfectly understands, that Strawson, who footnotes Grice
as the tutor from whom I never ceased to learn about logic in Introduction to
logical lheory, fails to acknowledge that most of the research in Strawsons
Individuals: an essay in descriptive (not revisionary) metaphysics derives from
the conclusions reached at his joint philosophical investigations at joint
seminars with Grice. Grice later elaborates on this with Code, who is keen on
Grices other game, the hazz and the hazz not, the izz. But then tutor from whom
I never ceased to learn about metaphysics sounds slightlier clumsier, as far as
the implicaturum goes. Categories, the Grice-Myro theory of identity, Relative
identity, Grice on =, identity, notes, with Myro, metaphysics, philosophy, with
Code, Grice izz Grice – or izz he? The idea that = is unqualified requires
qualification. Whitehead and Russell ignored this. Grice and Myro didnt. Grice
wants to allow for It is the case that a = b /t1 and it is not the case that a
= b /t2. The idea is intuitive, but philosophers of a Leibnizian bent are too
accustomed to deal with = as an absolute. Grice applies this to human vs.
person. A human may be identical to a person, but cease to be so. Indeed,
Grices earlier attempt to produce a reductive analsysis of I may be seen as
remedying a circularity he detected in Locke about same. Cf. Wiggins, Sameness
and substance. Grice makes Peano feel deeply Griceian, as Grice lists his =
postulates, here for consideration. And if you wondered why Grice prefers
Latinate individuum to the Grecian. The Grecian is “ἄτομον,” in logic, rendered
by L and S as ‘individual, of terms,’ Pl. Sph. 229d; of the εἶδος or forma,
Arist. Metaph.1034a8, de An. 414b27.2. individual, Id. APo. 96b11, al.: as a
subst., τό ἄτομον, Id. Cat. 1b6, 3a38, Metaph.1058a18 (pl.), Plot. 6.2.2,
al. subst.; latinised from Grecian. Lewis and Short have “indīvĭdŭum,” an atom,
indivisible particle: ex illis individuis, unde omnia Democritus gigni
affirmat, Cic. Ac. 2, 17 fin.: ne individuum quidem, nec quod dirimi distrahive
non possit, id. N. D. 3, 12, 29. Note the use of individuum in alethic
modalities for necessity and possibility, starting with (11). ⊢ (α izzes α). This would be the principle of
non-contradiction or identity. Grice applies it to war: War is war, as yielding
a most peculiar implicaturum. (α izzes β ∧ β izzes γ) ⊃ α
izzes γ. This above is transitivity, which is crucial for Grices tackling of
Reids counterexample to Locke (and which according to Flew in Locke on personal
identity was predated by Berkeley. α hazzes β ⊃ ~(α izzes β). Or, what is accidental is not essential.
Grice allows that what is essential is accidental is, while misleading,
true. ⊢ α hazzes β ⊃⊂ (∃x)(α hazzes x ∧ x
izzes β) ⊢ (∀β)(β izzes a universalium ⊃ β izzes a forma). This above defines a universalium as
a forma, or eidos. (α hazzes β ∧ α
izzes a particular) ⊃ (∃γ).(γ≠α ∧ α izzes β) ⊢ α izzes predicable of β ⊃⊂ ((β izzes α) ∨ (∃x)(β hazzes x ∧ x
izzes α) ⊢ α izzes essentially predicable of β ⊃⊂ β izzes α ⊢ α
izzes non-essentially/accidentally predicable of β ⊃⊂ (∃x)(β hazzes x ∧ x
izzes α) α = β ⊃⊂ α izzes β ∧ β
izzes α ⊢ α izzes an individuum ⊃⊂ □(∀β)(β izzes α ⊃ α izzes β) ⊢ α
izzes a particular ⊃⊂ □(∀β)(α izzes predicable of β ⊃ (α izzes β ∧ β
izzes α)); α izzes a universalium ⊃⊂ ◊(∃β)(α izzes predicable of α ∧ ~(α izzes β ∧ β
izzes α) ⊢ α izzes some-thing ⊃ α
izzes an individuum. ⊢ α izzes a forma ⊃ (α izzes some-thing ∧ α izzes a universalium) 16. ⊢ α izzes predicable of β ⊃⊂ (β izzes α) ∨ (∃x)(β hazzes x ∧ x
izzes α) ⊢ α izzes essentially predicable of α ⊢ α izzes accidentally predicable of β ⊃ α ≠ β; ~(α izzes accidentally predicable of β) ⊃ α ≠ β 20. α izzes a particular ⊃ α izzes an individuum. ⊢ α izzes a particular ⊃ ~(∃x)(x ≠ α ∧ x izzes α) 22. ⊢~
(∃x).(x izzes a particular ∧ x
izzes a forma) α izzes a forma ⊃ ~(∃x)(x ≠ α ∧ x
izzes α) x izzes a particular ⊃ ~(∃β)(α izz β) ⊢ α izzes a forma ⊃ ((α
izzes predicable of β ∧ α ≠ β) ⊃ β hazz α); α izzes a forma ∧ β izzes a particular ⊃ (α izzes predicable of β ⊃⊂ β hazz A) ⊢ (α
izzes a particular ∧ β izzes a universalium ∧ β izzes predicable of α) ⊃ (∃γ)(α ≠ γ ∧ γ
izzes essentially predicable of α) ⊢ (∃x) (∃y)(x izzes a particular ∧ y
izzes a universalium ∧ y izzes predicable of x ⊃ ~(∀x)(x izzes a universalium ∧ x izzes some-thing); (∀β)(β
izzes a universalium ⊃ β izzes some-thing) ⊢ α
izzes a particular) ⊃ ~∃β.(α ≠ β ∧ β
izzes essentially predicable of α); (α izzes predicable of β ∧ α ≠ β)⊃ α izzes non-essentially or
accidentally predicable of β. The use of this or that doxastic modality,
necessity and possibility, starting above, make this a good place to consider
one philosophical mistake Grice mentions in “Causal theory.” What is actual is
not also possible. Cf. What is essential is also accidental. He is criticising
a contemporary, if possible considered dated in the New World, form of
ordinary-language philosophy, where the philosopher detects a nuance, and
embarks risking colliding with the facts, rushing ahead to exploit it before he
can clarify it! Grice liked to see his explorations on = as belonging to
metaphysics, as the s. on his Doctrines
at the Grice Collection testifies. While Grice presupposes the use of = in his
treatment of the king of France, he also explores a relativisation of =. His
motivation was an essay by Wiggins, almost Aristotelian in spirit, against
Strawsons criterion of space-time continuancy for the identification of the
substantia prima. Grice wants to apply = to cases were the time continuancy is
made explicit. This yields that a=b in scenario S, but that it may not be the
case that a = b in a second scenario S. Myro had an occasion to expand on
Grices views in his contribution on the topic for PGRICE. Myro mentions his
System Ghp, a highly powerful/hopefully plausible version of Grices System Q,
in gratitude to to Grice. Grice explored also the logic of izzing and hazzing
with Code. Grice and Myro developed a Geach-type of qualified identity. The
formal aspects were developed by Myro, and also by Code. Grice discussed
Wigginss Sameness and substance, rather than Geach. Cf. Wiggins and Strawson on
Grice for the BA. At Oxford, Grice was more or less given free rein to teach
what he wanted. He found the New World slightly disconcerting at first. At
Oxford, he expected his tutees to be willing to read the classics in the
vernacular Greek. His approach to teaching was diagogic, as Socratess! Even in
his details of izzing and hazzing. Greek enough to me!, as a student recalled! correspondence
with Code, Grice sees in Code an excellent Aristotelian. They collaborated on
an exploration of Aristotles underlying logic of essential and non-essential
predication, for which they would freely use such verbal forms as izzing and
hazing, izzing and hazzing, Code on the significance of the middle book in
Aristotles Met. , Aristotle, metaphysics, the middle book. Very middle.
Grice never knew what was middle for Aristotle, but admired Code too much to
air this! The organisation of Aristotle’s metaphysics was a topic of much
concern for Grice. With Code, Grice coined izzing and hazzing to refer to
essential and non-essential attribution. Izzing and hazzing, “Aristotle on the
multiplicity of being” (henceforth, “Aristotle”) PPQ, Aristotle on
multiplicity, “The Pacific Philosophical Quarterly” (henceforth,
“PPQ,” posthumously ed. by Loar, Aristotle, multiplicity, izzing, hazzing,
being, good, Code. Grice offers a thorough discussion of Owens treatment of
Aristotle as leading us to the snares of ontology. Grice distinguishes between
izzing and hazzing, which he thinks help in clarifying, more axiomatico, what
Aristotle is getting at with his remarks on essential versus non-essential
predication. Surely, for Grice, being, nor indeed good, should not
be multiplied beyond necessity, but izzing and hazzing are already
multiplied. The Grice Papers contains drafts of the essay eventually
submitted for publication by Loar in memoriam Grice. Note that the Grice Papers
contains a typically Griceian un-publication, entitled Aristotle and
multiplicity simpliciter. Rather than Aristotle on, as the title for the
PPQ piece goes. Note also that, since its multiplicity simpliciter, it
refers to Aristotle on two key ideas: being and the good. As Code notes in
his contribution to PGRICE, Grice first presents his thoughts on izzing and hazzing
publicly at Vancouver. Jones has developed the axiomatic treatment favoured by
Grice. For Grice there is multiplicity in both being and good (ton
agathon), both accountable in terms of conversational implicatura, of course.
If in Prolegomena, Grice was interested in criticising himself, in essays of
historical nature like these, Grice is seeing Aristotles Athenian dialectic as
a foreshadow of the Oxonian dialectic, and treating him as an equal. Grice is
yielding his razor: senses are not to be multiplied beyond necessity.
But then Aristotle is talking about the multiplicity of is and is
good. Surely, there are ways to turn Aristotle into the monoguist
he has to be! There is a further item in the Grice collection that
combines Aristotle on being with Aristotle on good, which is relevant in
connection with this. Aristotle on being and good
(ἀγαθόν). Aristotle, being, good (agathon), ἀγαθός. As from this f.,
the essays are ordered alphabetically, starting with Aristotle, Grice will
explore Aristotle on being or is and good (ἀγαθός) in explorations with Code.
Grice comes up with izzing and hazzing as the two counterparts to Aristotles
views on, respectively, essential and non-essential predication. Grices views
on Aristotle on the good (strictly, there is no need to restrict Arisstotles
use to the neuter form, since he employs ἀγαθός) connect with Grices
Aristotelian idea of eudaemonia, that he explores elsewhere. Strictly:
Aristotle on being and the good. If that had been Grices case, he would have
used the definite article. Otherwise, good may well translate as masculine,
ἀγαθός ‒the agathetic implicaturum. He plays with Dodgson, cabbages and
kings. For what is a good cabbage as opposed to a cabbage? It does not
require very sharp eyes, but only our willingness to use the eyes one has, to
see that speech is permeated with the notion of purpose. To say what a
certain kind of thing is is only too frequently partly to say that it is
for. This feature applies to talk of, e. g., ships, shoes, sailing wax,
and kings; and, possibly and perhaps most excitingly, it extends even to
cabbages! Although Grice suspects Urmson might disagree. v. Grice on
Urmsons apples. Grice at his jocular best. If he is going to be a Kantian,
he will. He uses Kantian jargon to present his theory of conversation. This he
does only at Harvard. The implicaturum being that talking of vaguer assumptions
of helpfulness would not sound too convincing. So he has the maxim, the
super-maxim, and the sub-maxim. A principle and a maxim is Kantian enough. But
when he actually echoes Kant, is when he introduces what he later calls the
conversational categories – the keyword here is conversational category, as
categoria is used by Aristotle and Kant ‒ or Kantotle. Grice surely
knew that, say, his Category of Conversational Modality had nothing to do with
the Kantian Category of Modality. Still, he stuck with the idea of four categories
(versus Aristotles ten, eight or seven, as the text you consult may tell you):
category of conversational quantity (which at Oxford he had formulated in much
vaguer terms like strength and informativeness and entailment), the category of
conversational quality (keyword: principle of conversational trust), and the
category of conversational relation, where again Kants relation has nothing to
do with the maxim Grice associates with this category. In any case, his Kantian
joke may be helpful when considering the centrality of the concept category
simpliciter that Grice had to fight with with his pupils at Oxford – he was
lucky to have Austin and Strawson as co-lecturers! Grice was irritated by L and
S defining kategoria as category. I guess I knew that. He agreed with their
second shot, predicable. Ultimately, Grices concern with category is his
concern with person, or prote ousia, as used by Aristotle, and as giving a
rationale to Grices agency-based approach to the philosophical
enterprise. Aristotle used kategorein in the sense of to predicate,
assert something of something, and kategoria. The prote ousia is
exemplified by o tis anthropos. It is obvious that Grice wants to approach
Aristotles semantics and Aristotles metaphysics at one fell swoop. Grice reads
Aristotles Met. , and finds it understandable. Consider the adjective French
(which Aristotle does NOT consider) ‒ as it occurs in phrases such as Michel
Foucault is a French citizen. Grice is not a French citizen. Michel
Foucault once wrote a nice French poem. Urmson once wrote a nice French
essay on pragmatics. Michel Foucault was a French professor. Michel
Foucault is a French professor. Michel Foucault is a French professor of
philosophy. The following features are perhaps significant. The appearance
of the adjective French, or Byzantine, as the case might be ‒ cf. I’m
feeling French tonight. In these phrases is what Grice has as adjunctive rather
than conjunctive, or attributive. A French poem is not necessarily something
which combines the separate features of being a poem and being French, as a
tall philosopher would simply combine the features of being tall and of being a
philosopher. French in French poem, occurs adverbially. French
citizen standardly means citizen of France. French poem standardly means poem
in French. But it is a mistake to suppose that this fact implies that there is
this or that meaning, or, worse, this or that Fregeian sense, of the expression
French. In any case, only metaphorically or metabolically can we say that
French means this or that or has sense. An utterer means. An utterer makes
sense. Cf. R. Pauls doubts about capitalizing major. French means, and
figuratively at that, only one thing, viz. of or pertaining to France. And
English only means of or pertaining to England. French may be what
Grice (unfollowing his remarks on The general theory of context) call
context-sensitive. One might indeed say, if you like, that while French
means ‒ or means only this or that, or that its only sense is this or that,
French still means, again figuratively, a variety of things. French
means-in-context of or pertaining to France. Symbolise that
as expression E means-in-context that p. Expression E means-in-context C2 that
p2. Relative to Context C1 French means of France;
as in the phrase French citizen. Relative to context C2, French
means in the French language, as in the
phrase, French poem ‒ whereas history does not behave, like this. Whether
the focal item is a universal or a particular is, contra Aristotle, quite
irrelevant to the question of what this or that related adjective means, or
what its sense is. The medical art is no more what an utterer means when he
utters the adjective medical, as is France what an utterer means by the
adjective French. While the attachment of this or that context may suggest an
interpretation in context of this or that expression as uttered by the utterer
U, it need not be the case that such a suggestion is indefeasible. It
might be e.g. that French poem would have to mean, poem composed in French,
unless there were counter indications, that brings the utterer and the
addressee to a different context C3. In which case, perhaps
what the utterer means by French poem is poem composed by a French competitor
in this or that competition. For French professor there would be two
obvious things an utterer might mean. Disambiguation will depend on the
wider expression-context or in the situational context attaching to
the this or that circumstance of utterance. Eschatology. Some like Hegel, but
Collingwoods *my* man! ‒ Grice. Grice participated in two
consecutive evenings of the s. of programmes on metaphysics organised by Pears.
Actually, charming Pears felt pretentious enough to label the meetings to be
about the nature of metaphysics! Grice ends up discussing, as he should,
Collingwood on presupposition. Met.
remained a favourite topic for Grices philosophical explorations, as it
is evident from his essay on Met. , Philosophical Eschatology, and Platos Republic,
repr. in his WOW . Possibly Hardie is to blame, since he hardly tutored Grice
on metaphysics! Grices two BBC lectures are typically dated in tone. It was the
(good ole) days when philosophers thought they could educate the non-elite by
dropping Namess like Collingwood and stuff! The Third Programme was extremely
popular, especially among the uneducated ones at London, as Pears almost put
it, as it was a way for Londoners to get to know what is going on down at
Oxford, the only place an uneducated (or educated, for that matter) Londoner at
the time was interested in displaying some interest about! I mean, Johnson is
right: if a man is tired of the nature of metaphysics, he is tired of life!
Since the authorship is Grice, Strawson, and Pears, Met. , in Pears, The Nature
of Met., The BBC Third Programme, it is somewhat difficult to identify what
paragraphs were actually read by Grice (and which ones by Pears and which ones
by Strawson). But trust the sharp Griceian to detect the correct implicaturum!
There are many (too many) other items covered by these two lectures: Kant,
Aristotle, in no particular order. And in The Grice Collection, for that
matter, that cover the field of metaphysics. In the New World, as a sort of
tutor in the graduate programme, Grice was expected to cover the discipline at
various seminars. Only I dislike discipline! Perhaps his clearest exposition is
in the opening section of his Met. , philosophical eschatology, and Platos
Republic, repr. in his WOW , where he states, bluntly that all you need is metaphysics! metaphysics, Miscellaneous,
metaphysics notes, Grice would possible see metaphysics as a class – category
figuring large. He was concerned with the methodological aspects of the
metaphysical enterprise, since he was enough of a relativist to allow for one
metaphysical scheme to apply to one area of discourse (one of Eddingtons
tables) and another metaphysical scheme to apply to another (Eddingtons other
table). In the third programme for the BBC Grice especially enjoyed criticising
John Wisdoms innovative look at metaphysics as a bunch of self-evident
falsehoods (Were all alone). Grice focuses on Wisdom on the knowledge of other
minds. He also discusses Collingwoods presuppositions, and Bradley on the
reality-appearance distinction. Grices reference to Wisdom was due to Ewings
treatment of Wisdom on metaphysics. Grices main motivation here is defending
metaphysics against Ayer. Ayer thought to win more Oxonian philosophers than he
did at Oxford, but he was soon back in London. Post-war Oxford had become
conservative and would not stand to the nonsense of Ayers claiming that
metaphysics is nonsense, especially, as Ayers implicaturum also was, that
philosophy is nonsense! Perhaps the best summary of Griceian metaphysics is his
From Genesis to Revelations: a new discourse on metaphysics. It’s an
ontological answer that one must give to Grices metabolic operation from
utterers meaning to expression meaning, Grice had been interested in the
methodology of metaphysics since his Oxford days. He counts as one
memorable experience in the area his participation in two episodes for the BBC
Third Programme on The nature of metaphysics with the organiser, Pears, and his
former tutee, Strawson on the panel. Grice was particularly keen on
Collingwoods views on metaphysical presuppositions, both absolute and
relative! Grice also considers John Wisdoms view of the metaphysical
proposition as a blatant falsehood. Grice considers Bradleys Hegelian
metaphysics of the absolute, in Appearance and reality. Refs.: While Grice’s
choice was ‘eschatology,’ as per WoW, Essay, other keywords are useful, notably
“metaphysics,” “ontology,” “theorizing,” and “theory-theory,” in The H. P.
Grice Papers, BANC.
ESSE: Grice: “Surely the most important verb,
philosophically speaking. It was good of Boezio to turn Aristotle’s troublesome
‘belonging’ into a simple ‘est’.” ens a se: Grice defines an ‘ens a se’ as a being that is completely independent
and self-sufficient. Since every creature depends at least upon God for its
existence, only God could be ens a se. In fact, only God is, and he must be.
For if God depended on any other being, he would be dependent and hence not
self-sufficient. To the extent that the ontological argument is plausible, it
depends on conceiving of God as ens a se. In other words, God as ens a se is
the greatest conceivable being. The idea of ens a se is very important in the
Monologion and Proslogion of Anselm, in various works of Duns Scotus, and later
Scholastic thought. Ens a se should be distinguished from ens ex se, according
to Anselm in Monologion. Ens a se is from itself and not “out of itself.” In
other words, ens a se does not depend upon itself for its own existence,
because it is supposed to be dependent on absolutely nothing. Further, if ens a
se depended upon itself, it would cause itself to exist, and that is
impossible, according to medieval and Scholastic philosophers, who took
causality to be irreflexive. It is also transitive and asymmetric. Hence, the
medieval idea of ens a se should not be confused with Spinoza’s idea of causa
sui. Later Scholastics often coined abstract terms to designate the property or
entity that makes something to be what it is, in analogy with forming, say,
‘rigidity’ from ‘rigid’. The Latin term ‘aseitas’ is formed from the
prepositional phrase in ‘ens a se’ in this way; ‘aseitas’ is tr. into English
as ‘aseity’. A better-known example of forming an abstract noun from a concrete
word is ‘haecceitas’ thisness from ‘haec’ this.
-- ens rationis Latin, ‘a being of reason’, a thing dependent for its
existence upon reason or thought; sometimes known as an intentional being. Ens
rationis is the contrasting term for a real being res or ens in re extra
animam, such as an individual animal. Real beings exist independently of
thought and are the foundation for truth. A being of reason depends upon
thought or reason for its existence and is an invention of Enlightenment ens
rationis 266 266 the mind, even if it
has a foundation in some real being. This conception requires the idea that
there are degrees of being. Two kinds of entia rationis are distinguished:
those with a foundation in reality and those without one. The objects of logic,
which include genera and species, e.g., animal and human, respectively, are
entia rationis that have a foundation in reality, but are abstracted from it.
In contrast, mythic and fictional objects, such as a chimera or Pegasus, have
no foundation in reality. Blindness and deafness are also sometimes called
entia rationis. -- ens realissimum: used
by Grice. Latin, ‘most real being’, an informal term for God that occurs rarely
in Scholastic philosophers. Within Kant’s philosophy, it has a technical sense.
It is an extension of Baumgarten’s idea of ens perfectissimum most perfect
being, a being that has the greatest number of possible perfections to the
greatest degree. Since ens perfectissimum refers to God as the sum of all
possibilities and since actuality is greater than possibility, according to
Kant, the idea of God as the sum of all actualities, that is, ens realissimum,
is a preferable term for God. Kant thinks that human knowledge is “constrained”
to posit the idea of a necessary being. The necessary being that has the best
claim to necessity is one that is completely unconditioned, that is, dependent
on nothing; this is ens realissimum. He sometimes explicates it in three ways:
as the substratum of all realities, as the ground of all realities, and as the
sum of all realities. Ens realissimum is nonetheless empirically invalid, since
it cannot be experienced by humans. It is something ideal for reason, not real
in experience. According to Kant, the ontological argument begins with the
concept of ens realissimum and concludes that an existing object falls under
that concept Critique of Pure Reason, Book II, chapter 3. esse, essentia:
Grice: “Perhaps the most important verb, philosophical speaking.” Grice: “It
was Boezio who had the witty occurrence of translating the Aristotelian ‘belong’
by the much simpler ‘est’ – “S est P.”
-- Explored byy Grice in “Aristotle on the multiplicity of being”. To avoid
equivocation, Grice distinguishes between the ‘izz’ of essentia, and the ‘hazz’
of accidentia. ssentialism, a metaphysical theory that objects have essences
and that there is a distinction between essential and non-essential or
accidental predications. Different issues have, however, been central in
debates about essences and essential predication in different periods in the
history of philosophy. In our own day, it is commitment to the notion of de re
modality that is generally taken to render a theory essentialist; but in the
essentialist tradition stemming from Aristotle, discussions of essence and
essential predication focus on the distinction between what an object is and
how it is. According to Aristotle, the universals that an ordinary object
instantiates include some that mark it out as what it is and others that
characterize it in some way but do not figure in an account of what it is. In
the Categories, he tells us that while the former are said of the object, the
latter are merely present in it; and in other writings, he distinguishes
between what he calls kath hauto or per se predications where these include the
predication of what-universals and kata sumbebekos or per accidens predications
where these include the predication of how-universals. He concedes that
universals predicated of an object kath hauto are necessary to that object; but
he construes the necessity here as derivative. It is because a universal marks
out an entity, x, as what x is and hence underlies its being the thing that it
is that the universal is necessarily predicated of x. The concept of definition
is critically involved in Aristotle’s essentialism. First, it is the kind infima species under which an object falls or one of the
items genus or differentia included in the definition of that kind that is
predicated of the object kath hauto. But, second, Aristotle’s notion of an
essence just is the notion of the ontological correlate of a definition. The
term in his writings we translate as ‘essence’ is the expression to ti ein
einai the what it is to be. Typically, the expression is followed by a
substantival expression in the dative case, so that the expressions denoting
essences are phrases like ‘the what it is to be for a horse’ and ‘the what it
is to be for an oak tree’; and Aristotle tells us that, for any kind, K, the
what it is to be for a K just is that which we identify when we provide a
complete and accurate definition of K. Now, Aristotle holds that there is
definition only of universals; and this commits him to the view that there are
no individual essences. Although he concedes that we can provide definitions of
universals from any of his list of ten categories, he gives pride of place to
the essences of universals from the category of substance. Substance-universals
can be identified without reference to essences from other categories, but the
essences of qualities, quantities, and other non-substances can be defined only
by reference to the essences of substances. In his early writings, Aristotle
took the familiar particulars of common sense things like the individual man
and horse of Categories V to be the primary substances; and in these writings
it is the essences we isolate by defining the kinds or species under which
familiar particulars fall that are construed as the basic or paradigmatic
essences. However, in later writings, where ordinary particulars are taken to
be complexes of matter and form, it is the substantial forms of familiar
particulars that are the primary substances, so their essences are the primary
or basic essences; and a central theme in Aristotle’s most mature writings is
the idea that the primary substances and their essences are necessarily one and
the same in number. error theory essentialism 281 281 The conception of essence as the
ontological correlate of a definition
often called quiddity persists
throughout the medieval tradition; and in early modern philosophy, the idea
that the identity of an object is constituted by what it is plays an important
role in Continental rationalist thinkers. Indeed, in the writings of Leibniz,
we find the most extreme version of traditional essentialism. Whereas Aristotle
had held that essences are invariably general, Leibniz insisted that each
individual has an essence peculiar to it. He called the essence associated with
an entity its complete individual concept; and he maintained that the
individual concept somehow entails all the properties exemplified by the
relevant individual. Accordingly, Leibniz believed that an omniscient being
could, for each possible world and each possible individual, infer from the
individual concept of that individual the whole range of properties exemplified
by that individual in that possible world. But, then, from the perspective of
an omniscient being, all of the propositions identifying the properties the
individual actually exhibits would express what Aristotle called kath hauto
predications. Leibniz, of course, denied that our perspective is that of an
omniscient being; we fail to grasp individual essences in their fullness, so
from our perspective, the distinction between essential and accidental
predications holds. While classical rationalists espoused a thoroughgoing
essentialism, the Aristotlelian conceptions of essence and definition were the
repeated targets of attacks by classical British empiricists. Hobbes, e.g.,
found the notion of essence philosophically useless and insisted that definition
merely displays the meanings conventionally associated with linguistic
expressions. Locke, on the other hand, continued to speak of essences; but he
distinguished between real and nominal essences. As he saw it, the familiar
objects of common sense are collections of copresent sensible ideas to which we
attach a single name like ‘man’ or ‘horse’. Identifying the ideas constitutive
of the relevant collection gives us the nominal essence of a man or a horse.
Locke did not deny that real essences might underlie such collections, but he
insisted that it is nominal rather than real essences to which we have
epistemic access. Hume, in turn, endorsed the idea that familiar objects are
collections of sensible ideas, but rejected the idea of some underlying real essence
to which we have no access; and he implicitly reinforced the Hobbesian critique
of Aristotelian essences with his attack on the idea of de re necessities. So
definition merely expresses the meanings we conventionally associate with
words, and the only necessity associated with definition is linguistic or
verbal necessity. From its origins, the twentieth-century analytic tradition
endorsed the classical empiricist critique of essences and the Humean view that
necessity is merely linguistic. Indeed, even the Humean concession that there
is a special class of statements true in virtue of their meanings came into
question in the forties and fifties, when philosophers like Quine argued that
it is impossible to provide a noncircular criterion for distinguishing analytic
and synthetic statements. So by the late 0s, it had become the conventional
wisdom of philosophers in the Anglo- tradition that both the notion of a real
essence and the derivative idea that some among the properties true of an
object are essential to that object are philosophical dead ends. But over the
past three decades, developments in the semantics of modal logic have called
into question traditional empiricist skepticism about essence and modality and
have given rise to a rebirth of essentialism. In the late fifties and early
sixties, logicians like Kripke, Hintikka, and Richard Montague showed how
formal techniques that have as their intuitive core the Leibnizian idea that
necessity is truth in all possible worlds enable us to provide completeness
proofs for a whole range of nonequivalent modal logics. Metaphysicians seized
on the intuitions underlying these formal methods. They proposed that we take
the picture of alternative possible worlds seriously and claimed that
attributions of de dicto modality necessity and possibility as they apply to
propositions can be understood to involve quantification over possible worlds.
Thus, to say that a proposition, p, is necessary is to say that for every
possible world, W, p is true in W; and to say that p is possible is to say that
there is at least one possible world, W, such that p is true in W. These
metaphysicians went on to claim that the framework of possible worlds enables
us to make sense of de re modality. Whereas de dicto modality attaches to
propositions taken as a whole, an ascription of de re modality identifies the
modal status of an object’s exemplification of an attribute. Thus, we speak of
Socrates as being necessarily or essentially rational, but only contingently
snub-nosed. Intuitively, the essential properties of an object are those it
could not have lacked; whereas its contingent properties are properties it
exemplifies but could have failed to exemplify. The “friends of possible
worlds” insisted that we can make perfectly good sense of this intuitive
distinction if we say that an object, x, exhibits a property, P, essentially
just in case x exhibits P in the actual world and in every possible world in
which x exists and that x exhibits P merely contingently just in case x exhibits
P in the actual world, but there is at least one possible world, W, such that x
exists in W and fails to exhibit P in W. Not only have these neo-essentialists
invoked the Leibnizian conception of alternative possible worlds in
characterizing the de re modalities, many have endorsed Leibniz’s idea that
each object has an individual essence or what is sometimes called a haecceity.
As we have seen, the intuitive idea of an individual essence is the idea of a
property an object exhibits essentially and that no other object could possibly
exhibit; and contemporary essentialists have fleshed out this intuitive notion
by saying that a property, P, is the haecceity or individual essence of an
object, x, just in case 1 x exhibits P in the actual world and in all worlds in
which x exists and 2 there is no possible world where an object distinct from x
exhibits P. And some defenders of individual essences like Plantinga have
followed Leibniz in holding that the haecceity of an object provides a complete
concept of that object, a property such that it entails, for every possible
world, W, and every property, P, either the proposition that the object in
question has P in W or the proposition that it fails to have P in W.
Accordingly, they agree that an omniscient being could infer from the
individual essence of an object a complete account of the history of that
object in each possible world in which it exists.
eudaemonia: from Grecian
eudaimonia, and then there’s eudaemonism --‘happiness’, ‘flourishing’, the
ethical doctrine that happiness is the ultimate justification for morality. The
ancient Grecian philosophers typically begin their ethical treatises with an
account of happiness, and then argue that the best way to achieve a happy life
is through the cultivation and exercise of virtue. Most of them make virtue or
virtuous activity a constituent of the happy life; the Epicureans, however,
construe happiness in terms of pleasure, and treat virtue as a means to the end
of pleasant living. Ethical eudaimonism is sometimes combined with
psychological eudaimonism i.e., the view
that all free, intentional action is aimed ultimately at the agent’s happiness.
A common feature of ancient discussions of ethics, and one distinguishing them from
most modern discussions, is the view that an agent would not be rationally
justified in a course of action that promised less happiness than some
alternative open to him. Hence it seems that most of the ancient theories are
forms of egosim. But the ancient theories differ from modern versions of egoism
since, according to the ancients, at least some of the virtues are dispositions
to act from primarily other-regarding motives: although the agent’s happiness
is the ultimate justification of virtuous action, it is not necessarily what
motivates such action. Since happiness is regarded by most of the ancients as
the ultimate end that justifies our actions, their ethical theories seem
teleological; i.e., right or virtuous action is construed as action that
contributes to or maximizes the good. But appearances are again misleading, for
the ancients typically regard virtuous action as also valuable for its own sake
and hence constitutive of the agent’s happiness.
event: used by Grice in
“Actions and Events,” -- anything that happens; an occurrence. Two fundamental
questions about events, which philosophers have usually treated together, are:
1 Are there events?, and 2 If so, what is their nature? Some philosophers
simply assume that there are events. Others argue for that, typically through
finding semantic theories for ordinary claims that apparently concern the fact
that some agent has done something or that some thing has changed. Most
philosophers presume that the events whose existence is proved by such
arguments are abstract particulars, “particulars” in the sense that they are
non-repeatable and spatially locatable, “abstract” in the sense that more than
one event can occur simultaneously in the same place. The theories of events
espoused by Davidson in his causal view, Kim though his view may be unstable in
this respect, Jonathan Bennett, and Lawrence Lombard take them to be abstract
particulars. However, Chisholm takes Euler diagram event 292 292 events to be abstract universals; and
Quine and Davidson in his later view take them to be concrete particulars. Some
philosophers who think of events as abstract particulars tend to associate the
concept of an event with the concept of change; an event is a change in some
object or other though some philosophers have doubts about this and others have
denied it outright. The time at which an event, construed as a particular,
occurs can be associated with the shortest time at which the object, which is
the subject of that event, changes from the having of one property to the
having of another, contrary property. Events inherit whatever spatial locations
they have from the spatial locations, if any, of the things that those events
are changes in. Thus, an event that is a change in an object, x, from being F
to being G, is located wherever x is at the time it changes from being F to
being G. Some events are those of which another event is composed e.g., the
sinking of a ship seems composed of the sinkings of its parts. However, it also
seems clear that not every group of events comprises another; there just is no
event composed of a certain explosion on Venus and my birth. Any adequate
theory about the nature of events must address the question of what properties,
if any, such things have essentially. One issue is whether the causes or
effects of events are essential to those events. A second is whether it is
essential to each event that it be a change in the entity it is in fact a
change in. A third is whether it is essential to each event that it occur at
the time at which it in fact occurs. A chief component of a theory of events is
a criterion of identity, a principle giving conditions necessary and sufficient
for an event e and an event eH to be one and the same event. Quine holds that
events may be identified with the temporal parts of physical objects, and that
events and physical objects would thus share the same condition of identity:
sameness of spatiotemporal location. Davidson once proposed that events are
identical provided they have the same causes and effects. More recently,
Davidson abandoned this position in favor of Quine’s. Kim takes an event to be
the exemplification of a property or relation by an object or objects at a
time. This idea has led to his view that an event e is the same as an event eH
if and only if e and eH are the exemplifications of the same property by the
same objects at the same time. Lombard’s view is a variation on this account,
and is derived from the idea of events as the changes that physical objects
undergo when they alter.
No comments:
Post a Comment