The Grice Club

Welcome

The Grice Club

The club for all those whose members have no (other) club.

Is Grice the greatest philosopher that ever lived?

Search This Blog

Thursday, July 30, 2020

IMPLICATVRA, in 18 volumes -- vol. 15



Q


Q: SUBJECT INDEX: QUIDDITAS
Q: NAME INDEX: ITALIAN
Q: NAME INDEX: ENGLISH: QUINTON (Grice’s collaborator)


quale: a property of a mental state or event, in particular of a sensation and a perceptual state, which determine “what it is like” to have them. Sometimes ‘phenomenal properties’ and ‘qualitative features’ are used with the same meaning. The felt difference between pains and itches is said to reside in differences in their “qualitative character,” i.e., their qualia. For those who accept an “actobject” conception of perceptual experience, qualia may include such properties as “phenomenal redness” and “phenomenal roundness,” thought of as properties of sense-data, “phenomenal objects,” or portions of the visual field. But those who reject this conception do not thereby reject qualia; a proponent of the adverbial analysis of perceptual experience can hold that an experience of “sensing redly” is so in virtue of, in part, what qualia it has, while denying that there is any sense in which the experience itself is red. Qualia are thought of as non-intentional, i.e., non-representational, features of the states that have them. So in a case of “spectrum inversion,” where one person’s experiences of green are “qualitatively” just like another person’s experiences of red, and vice versa, the visual experiences the two have when viewing a ripe tomato would be alike in their intentional features both would be of a red, round, bulgy surface, but would have different qualia. Critics of physicalist and functionalist accounts of mind have argued from the possibility of spectrum inversion and other kinds of “qualia inversion,” and from such facts as that no physical or functional description will tell one “what it is like” to smell coffee, that such accounts cannot accommodate qualia. Defenders of such accounts are divided between those who claim that their accounts can accommodate qualia and those who claim that qualia are a philosophical myth and thus that there are none to accommodate.  qualitative predicate, a kind of predicate postulated in some attempts to solve the grue paradox. 1 On the syntactic view, a qualitative predicate is a syntactically more or less simple predicate. Such simplicity, however, is relative to the choice of primitives in a language. In English, ‘green’ and ‘blue’ are primitive, while ‘grue’ and ‘bleen’ must be introduced by definitions ‘green and first examined before T, or blue otherwise’, ‘blue and first examined before T, or green otherwise’, respectively. In other languages, ‘grue’ and ‘bleen’ may be primitive and hence “simple,” while ‘green’ and ‘blue’ must be introduced by definitions ‘grue and first examined before T, or bleen otherwise’, ‘bleen and first examined before T, or grue otherwise’, respectively. 2 On the semantic view, a qualitative predicate is a predicate to which there corresponds a property that is “natural” to us or of easy semantic access. The quality of greenness is easy and natural; the quality of grueness is strained. 3 On the ontological view, a qualitative predicate is a predicate to which there corresponds a property that is woven into the causal or modal structure of reality in a way that gruesome properties are not.  qualities, properties or characteristics. There are three specific philosophical senses. 1 Qualities are physical properties, logical constructions of physical properties, or dispositions. Physical properties, such as mass, shape, and electrical charge, are properties in virtue of which objects can enter into causal relations. Logical constructions of physical properties include conjunctions and disjunctions of them; being 10 # .02 cm long is a disjunctive property. A disposition of an object is a potential for the object to enter into a causal interaction of some specific kind under some specific condition; e.g., an object is soluble in water if and only if it would dissolve were it in enough pure water. Locke held a very complex theory of powers. On Locke’s theory, the dispositions of objects are a kind of power and the human will is a kind of power. However, the human will is not part of the modern notion of disposition. So, predicating a disposition of an object implies a subjunctive conditional of the form: if such-and-such were to happen to the object, then so-and-so would happen to it; that my vase is fragile implies that if my vase were to be hit sufficiently hard then it would break. Whether physical properties are distinct from dispositions is disputed. Three sorts of qualities are often distinguished. Primary qualities are physical properties or logical constructions from physical properties. Secondary qualities are dispositions to produce sensory experiences of certain phenomenal sorts under appropriate conditions. The predication of a secondary quality, Q, to an object implies that if the object were to be perceived under normal conditions then the object would appear to be Q to the perceivers: if redness is a secondary quality, then that your coat is red implies that if your coat were to be seen under normal conditions, it would look red. Locke held that the following are secondary qualities: colors, tastes, smells, sounds, and warmth or cold. Tertiary qualities are dispositions that are not secondary qualities, e.g. fragility. Contrary to Locke, the color realist holds that colors are either primary or tertiary qualities; so that x is yellow is logically independent of the fact that x looks yellow under normal conditions. Since different spectral reflectances appear to be the same shade of yellow, some color realists hold that any shade of yellow is a disjunctive property whose components are spectral reflectances. 2 Assuming a representative theory of perception, as Locke did, qualities have two characteristics: qualities are powers or dispositions of objects to produce sensory experiences sensedata on some theories in humans; and, in sensory experience, qualities are represented as intrinsic properties of objects. Instrinsic properties of objects are properties that objects have independently of their environment. Hence an exact duplicate of an object has all the intrinsic properties of the original, and an intrinsic property of x never has the form, x-stands-in-suchand-such-a-relation-to-y. Locke held that the primary qualities are extension size, figure shape, motion or rest, solidity impenetrability, and number; the primary qualities are correctly represented in perception as intrinsic features of objects, and the secondary qualities listed in 1 are incorrectly represented in perception as intrinsic features of objects. Locke seems to have been mistaken in holding that number is a quality of objects. Positional qualities are qualities defined in terms of the relative positions of points in objects and their surrounding: shape, size, and motion and rest. Since most of Locke’s primary qualities are positional, some non-positional quality is needed to occupy positions. On Locke’s account, solidity fulfills this role, although some have argued Hume that solidity is not a primary quality. 3 Primary qualities are properties common to and inseparable from all matter; secondary qualities are not really qualities in objects, but only powers of objects to produce sensory effects in us by means of their primary qualities. This is another use of ‘quality’ by Locke, where ‘primary’ functions much like ‘real’ and real properties are given by the metaphysical assumptions of the science of Locke’s time. Qualities are distinct from representations of them in predications. Sometimes the same quality is represented in different ways by different predications: ‘That is water’ and ‘That is H2O’. The distinction between qualities and the way they are represented in predications opens up the Lockean possibility that some qualities are incorrectly represented in some predications. Features of predications are sometimes used to define a quality; dispositions are sometimes defined in terms of subjunctive conditionals see definition of ‘secondary qualities’ in 1, and disjunctive properties are defined in terms of disjunctive predications. Features of predications are also used in the following definition of ‘independent qualities’: two qualities, P and Q, are independent if and only if, for any object x, the predication of P and of Q to x are logically independent i.e., that x is P and that x is Q are logically independent; circularity and redness are independent, circularity and triangularity are dependent. If two determinate qualities, e.g., circularity and triangularity, belong to the same determinable, say shape, then they are dependent, but if two determinate qualities, e.g., squareness and redness, belong to different determinables, say shape and color, they are independent.

quantum:  Quantification: H. P. Grice, “Every nice girl loves a sailor.” -- the application of one or more quantifiers e.g., ‘for all x’, ‘for some y’ to an open formula. A quantification or quantified sentence results from first forming an open formula from a sentence by replacing expressions belonging to a certain class of expressions in the sentences by variables whose substituends are the expressions of that class and then prefixing the formula with quantifiers using those variables. For example, from ‘Bill hates Mary’ we form ‘x hates y’, to which we prefix the quantifiers ‘for all x’ and ‘for some y’, getting the quantification sentence ‘for all x, for some y, x hates y’ ‘Everyone hates someone’. In referential quantification only terms of reference may be replaced by variables. The replaceable terms of reference are the substituends of the variables. The values of the variables are all those objects to which reference could be made by a term of reference of the type that the variables may replace. Thus the previous example ‘for all x, for some y, x hates y’ is a referential quantification. Terms standing for people ‘Bill’, ‘Mary’, e.g. are the substituends of the variables ‘x’ and ‘y’. And people are the values of the variables. In substitutional quantification any type of term may be replaced by variables. A variable replacing a term has as its substituends all terms of the type of the replaced term. For example, from ‘Bill married Mary’ we may form ‘Bill R Mary’, to which we prefix the quantifier ‘for some R’, getting the substitutional quantification ‘for some R, Bill R Mary’. This is not a referential quantification, since the substituends of ‘R’ are binary predicates such as ‘marries’, which are not terms of reference. Referential quantification is a species of objectual quantification. The truth conditions of quantification sentences objectually construed are understood in terms of the values of the variable bound by the quantifier. Thus, ‘for all v, fv’ is true provided ‘fv’ is true for all values of the variable ‘v’; ‘for some v, fv’ is true provided ‘fv’ is true for some value of the variable ‘v’. The truth or falsity of a substitutional quantification turns instead on the truth or falsity of the sentences that result from the quantified formula by replacing variables by their substituends. For example, ‘for some R, Bill R Mary’ is true provided some sentence of the form ‘Bill R Mary’ is true. In classical logic the universal quantifier ‘for all’ is definable in terms of negation and the existential quantifier ‘for some’: ‘for all x’ is short for ‘not for some x not’. The existential quantifier is similarly definable in terms of negation and the universal quantifier. In intuitionistic logic, this does not hold. Both quantifiers are regarded as primitive. Then there’s quantifying in, use of a quantifier outside of an opaque construction to attempt to bind a variable within it, a procedure whose legitimacy was first questioned by Quine. An opaque construction is one that resists substitutivity of identity. Among others, the constructions of quotation, the verbs of propositional attitude, and the logical modalities can give rise to opacity. For example, the position of ‘six’ in: 1 ‘six’ contains exactly three letters is opaque, since the substitution for ‘six’ by its codesignate ‘immediate successor of five’ renders a truth into a falsehood: 1H ‘the immediate successor of five’ contains exactly three letters. Similarly, the position of ‘the earth’ in: 2 Tom believes that the earth is habitable is opaque, if the substitution of ‘the earth’ by its codesignate ‘the third planet from the sun’ renders a sentence that Tom would affirm into one that he would deny: 2H Tom believes that the third planet from the sun is habitable. Finally, the position of ‘9’ and of ‘7’ in: 3 Necessarily 9  7 is opaque, since the substitution of ‘the number of major planets’ for its codesignate ‘9’ renders a truth into a falsehood: 3H Necessarily the number of major planets  7. Quine argues that since the positions within opaque constructions resist substitutivity of identity, they cannot meaningfully be quantified. Accordingly, the following three quantified sentences are meaningless: 1I Ex ‘x’  7, 2I Ex Tom believes that x is habitable, 3I Ex necessarily x  7. 1I, 2I, and 3I are meaningless, since the second occurrence of ‘x’ in each of them does not function as a variable in the ordinary nonessentialist quantificational way. The second occurrence of ‘x’ in 1I functions as a name that names the twenty-fourth letter of the alphabet. The second occurrences of ‘x’ in 2I and in 3I do not function as variables, since they do not allow all codesignative terms as substituends without change of truth-value. Thus, they may take objects as values but only objects designated in certain ways, e.g., in terms of their intensional or essential properties. So, short of acquiescing in an intensionalist or essentialist metaphysics, Quine argues, we cannot in general quantify into opaque contexts.  Quantum: one of Aristotle’s categories. Cicero’s translation of Aristotle -- quantum logic, the logic of which the models are certain non-Boolean algebras derived from the mathematical representation of quantum mechanical systems. The models of classical logic are, formally, Boolean algebras. This is the central notion of quantum logic in the literature, although the term covers a variety of modal logics, dialogics, and operational logics proposed to elucidate the structure of quantum mechanics and its relation to classical mechanics. The dynamical quantities of a classical mechanical system position, momentum, energy, etc. form a commutative algebra, and the dynamical properties of the system e.g., the property that the position lies in a specified range, or the property that the momentum is greater than zero, etc. form a Boolean algebra. The transition from classical to quantum mechanics involves the transition from a commutative algebra of dynamical quantities to a noncommutative algebra of so-called observables. One way of understanding the conceptual revolution from classical to quantum mechanics is in terms of a shift from the class of Boolean algebras to a class of non-Boolean algebras as the appropriate relational structures for the dynamical properties of mechanical systems, hence from a Boolean classical logic to a non-Boolean quantum logic as the logic applicable to the fundamental physical processes of our universe. This conception of quantum logic was developed formally in a classic 6 paper by G. Birkhoff and J. von Neumann although von Neumann first proposed the idea in 7. The features that distinguish quantum logic from classical logic vary with the formulation. In the Birkhoffvon Neumann logic, the distributive law of classical logic fails, but this is by no means a feature of all versions of quantum logic. It follows from Gleason’s theorem 7 that the non-Boolean models do not admit two-valued homomorphisms in the general case, i.e., there is no partition of the dynamical properties of a quantum mechanical system into those possessed by the system and those not possessed by the system that preserves algebraic structure, and equivalently no assignment of values to the observables of the system that preserves algebraic structure. This result was proved independently for finite sets of observables by S. Kochen and E. P. Specker 7. It follows that the probabilities specified by the Born interpretation of the state function of a quantum mechanical system for the results of measurements of observables cannot be derived from a probability distribution over the different possible sets of dynamical properties of the system, or the different possible sets of values assignable to the observables of which one set is presumed to be actual, determined by hidden variables in addition to the state function, if these sets of properties or values are required to preserve algebraic structure. While Bell’s theorem 4 excludes hidden variables satisfying a certain locality condition, the Kochen-Specker theorem relates the non-Booleanity of quantum logic to the impossibility of hidden variable extensions of quantum mechanics, in which value assignments to the observables satisfy constraints imposed by the algebraic structure of the observables. Then there’s quantum mechanics, also called quantum theory, the science governing objects of atomic and subatomic dimensions. Developed independently by Werner Heisenberg as matrix mechanics, 5 and Erwin Schrödinger as wave mechanics, 6, quantum mechanics breaks with classical treatments of the motions and interactions of bodies by introducing probability and acts of measurement in seemingly irreducible ways. In the widely used Schrödinger version, quantum mechanics associates with each physical system a time-dependent function, called the state function alternatively, the state vector or Y function. The evolution of the system is represented by the temporal transformation of the state function in accord with a master equation, known as the Schrödinger equation. Also associated with a system are “observables”: in principle measurable quantities, such as position, momentum, and energy, including some with no good classical analogue, such as spin. According to the Born interpretation 6, the state function is understood instrumentally: it enables one to calculate, for any possible value of an observable, the probability that a measurement of that observable would find that particular value. The formal properties of observables and state functions imply that certain pairs of observables such as linear momentum in a given direction, and position in the same direction are incompatible in the sense that no state function assigns probability 1 to the simultaneous determination of exact values for both observables. This is a qualitative statement of the Heisenberg uncertainty principle alternatively, the indeterminacy principle, or just the uncertainty principle. Quantitatively, that principle places a precise limit on the accuracy with which one may simultaneously measure a pair of incompatible observables. There is no corresponding limit, however, on the accuracy with which a single observable say, position alone, or momentum alone may be measured. The uncertainty principle is sometimes understood in terms of complementarity, a general perspective proposed by Niels Bohr according to which the connection between quantum phenomena and observation forces our classical concepts to split into mutually exclusive packages, both of which are required for a complete understanding but only one of which is applicable under any particular experimental conditions. Some take this to imply an ontology in which quantum objects do not actually possess simultaneous values for incompatible observables; e.g., do not have simultaneous position and momentum. Others would hold, e.g., that measuring the position of an object causes an uncontrollable change in its momentum, in accord with the limits on simultaneous accuracy built into the uncertainty principle. These ways of treating the principle are not uncontroversial. Philosophical interest arises in part from where the quantum theory breaks with classical physics: namely, from the apparent breakdown of determinism or causality that seems to result from the irreducibly statistical nature of the theory, and from the apparent breakdown of observer-independence or realism that seems to result from the fundamental role of measurement in the theory. Both features relate to the interpretation of the state function as providing only a summary of the probabilities for various measurement outcomes. Einstein, in particular, criticized the theory on these grounds, and in 5 suggested a striking thought experiment to show that, assuming no action-at-a-distance, one would have to consider the state function as an incomplete description of the real physical state for an individual system, and therefore quantum mechanics as merely a provisional theory. Einstein’s example involved a pair of systems that interact briefly and then separate, but in such a way that the outcomes of various measurements performed on each system, separately, show an uncanny correlation. In 1 the physicist David Bohm simplified Einstein’s example, and later 7 indicated that it may be realizable experimentally. The physicist John S. Bell then formulated a locality assumption 4, similar to Einstein’s, that constrains factors which might be used in describing the state of an individual system, so-called hidden variables. Locality requires that in the EinsteinBohm experiment hidden variables not allow the measurement performed on one system in a correlated pair immediately to influence the outcome obtained in measuring the other, spatially separated system. Bell demonstrated that locality in conjunction with other assumptions about hidden variables restricts the probabilities for measurement outcomes according to a system of inequalities known as the Bell inequalities, and that the probabilities of certain quantum systems violate these inequalities. This is Bell’s theorem. Subsequently several experiments of the Einstein-Bohm type have been performed to test the Bell inequalities. Although the results have not been univocal, the consensus is that the experimental data support the quantum theory and violate the inequalities. Current research is trying to evaluate the implications of these results, including the extent to which they rule out local hidden variables. See J. Cushing and E. McMullin, eds., Philosophical Consequences of Quantum Theory, 9. The descriptive incompleteness with which Einstein charged the theory suggests other problems. A particularly dramatic one arose in correspondence between Schrödinger and Einstein; namely, the “gruesome” Schrödinger cat paradox. Here a cat is confined in a closed chamber containing a radioactive atom with a fifty-fifty chance of decaying in the next hour. If the atom decays it triggers a relay that causes a hammer to fall and smash a glass vial holding a quantity of    766 prussic acid sufficient to kill the cat. According to the Schrödinger equation, after an hour the state function for the entire atom ! relay ! hammer ! glass vial ! cat system is such that if we observe the cat the probability for finding it alive dead is 50 percent. However, this evolved state function is one for which there is no definite result; according to it, the cat is neither alive nor dead. How then does any definite fact of the matter arise, and when? Is the act of observation itself instrumental in bringing about the observed result, does that result come about by virtue of some special random process, or is there some other account compatible with definite results of measurements? This is the so-called quantum measurement problem and it too is an active area of research. 

quasi-demonstratum: The use of ‘quasi-‘ is implicatural. Grice is implicating this is NOT a demonstratum. By a demonstratum he is having in mind a Kaplanian ‘dthis’ or ‘dthat.’ Grice was obsessed with this or that. An abstractum (such as “philosopher”) needs to be attached in a communicatum by what Grice calls a ‘quasi-demonstrative,’ and for which he uses “φ.” Consider, Grice says, an utterance, out of the blue, such as ‘The philosopher in the garden seems bored,’ involving two iota-operators. As there may be more that a philosopher in a garden in the great big world, the utterer intends his addressee to treat the utterance as expandable into ‘The A which is φ is B,’ where “φ” is a quasi-demonstrative epithet to be identified in a particular context of utterance. The utterer intends that, to identify  the denotatum of “φ” for a particular utterance of ‘The philosopher in the garden seems bored,’ the addressee wil proceed via the identification of a particular philosopher, say Grice, as being a good candidate for being the philosopher meant. The addressee is also intended to identify the candidate for a denotatum of φ by finding in the candidate a feature, e. g., that of being the garden at St. John’s, which is intended to be used to yield a composite epithet (‘philosopher in St. John’s garden’), which in turn fills the bill of being the epithet which the utterer believes is being uniquely satisfied by the philosopher selected as the candidate. Determining the denotatum of “φ” standardly involve determining what feature the utterer believes is uniquely instantiated by the predicate “philosopher.” This in turn involves satisfying oneself that some particular feature is in fact uniquely satisfied by a particular actual item, viz. a particular philosopher such as Grice seeming bored in the garden of St. John’s.

Quinton -- A.M. Quinton’s Gedanke Experiment: from “Spaces and Times,” Philosophy.“hardly Thought Out” – Is this apriori or a posteriori? H. P. Grice. Space is ordinarily seen to be a unique individual. All real things are contained in one and the same space, and all spaces are part of the one space. In principle, every place can be reached from every other place by traveling through intermediate places. The spatial relation is symmetrical. Grice’s friend, A. M. Quinton devised a thought experiment to challenge this picture. Suppose that we have richly coherent and connected experience in our dreams just as we have in waking life, so that it becomes arbitrary to claim that our dream experience is not of an objectively existing world like the world of our waking experience. If the space of my waking world and my dream world are not mutually accessible, it is unlikely that we are justified in claiming to be living in a single spatially isolated world. Hence, space is not essentially singular. In assessing this account, we might distinguish between systematic and public physical space and fragmentary and private experiential space. The two-space myth raises questions about how we can justify moving from experiential space to objective space in the world as it is. “We can at least conceive circumstances in which we should have good reason to say that we know of real things located in two distinct spaces.” Quinton, “Spaces and Times,” Philosophy 37.

quod: quid – quiddity. A term used by Grice when talking to his wife. “What quiddity did you buy?”

qv-quæstio -- x-question: Grice borrowed the erotetic from Cook Wilson, who in fact was influenced by Stout and will also influence Collingwood. While Grice starts by considering the pseudo-distinction between x-questions and yes/no questions, he soon finds out that they all reduce to the x-question, since a yes/no question obviously asks for a variable (the truth value of the whole proposition) to be filled. Grice sometimes follows Ryle who had quoted Carnap on the ‘w  frage.’ Grice is aware of the ‘wh’ rune in Anglo-Saxon, but was confused by ‘how.’ “For fun, I will spell ‘how,’ ‘whow.’” Although a Midlander Grice preferred the northern English pronunciation of aspirating the ‘wh-‘ and was irritated that only ‘who’ and ‘whose’ keep the aspiration. Note that “Where is your wife?” is a qu-quaestio, but “(a) in the kitchen, (b) in the bedroom” provides a ‘p v q’ as an answer – “Disjunctive answers to intrusive questions.” Cf. “Iffy answers to intrusive questions.” “The lady doth protest too much: ampliative conjunctive answers to intrusive questions.”

R


R: SUBJECT INDEX: ratio
R: NAME INDEX ITALIAN: RIMINI – ROSMINI – ROSSELLI – ROTA -- ROVERE
R: NAME INDEX: ENGLISH: RYLE

Radix -- Radix -- Grice often talked about logical atomism and molecular propositions – and radix – which is an atomic metaphor -- Democritus, Grecian preSocratic philosopher. He was born at Abdera, in Thrace. Building on Leucippus and his atomism, he developed the atomic theory in The Little World-system and numerous other writings. In response to the Eleatics’ argument that the impossibility of not-being entailed that there is no change, the atomists posited the existence of a plurality of tiny indivisible beings  the atoms  and not-being  the void, or empty space. Atoms do not come into being or perish, but they do move in the void, making possible the existence of a world, and indeed of many worlds. For the void is infinite in extent, and filled with an infinite number of atoms that move and collide with one another. Under the right conditions a concentration of atoms can begin a vortex motion that draws in other atoms and forms a spherical heaven enclosing a world. In our world there is a flat earth surrounded by heavenly bodies carried by a vortex motion. Other worlds like ours are born, flourish, and die, but their astronomical configurations may be different from ours and they need not have living creatures in them. The atoms are solid bodies with countless shapes and sizes, apparently having weight or mass, and capable of motion. All other properties are in some way derivative of these basic properties. The cosmic vortex motion causes a sifting that tends to separate similar atoms as the sea arranges pebbles on the shore. For instance heavier atoms sink to the center of the vortex, and lighter atoms such as those of fire rise upward. Compound bodies can grow by the aggregations of atoms that become entangled with one another. Living things, including humans, originally emerged out of slime. Life is caused by fine, spherical soul atoms, and living things die when these atoms are lost. Human culture gradually evolved through chance discoveries and imitations of nature. Because the atoms are invisible and the only real properties are properties of atoms, we cannot have direct knowledge of anything. Tastes, temperatures, and colors we know only “by convention.” In general the senses cannot give us anything but “bastard” knowledge; but there is a “legitimate” knowledge based on reason, which takes over where the senses leave off  presumably demonstrating that there are atoms that the senses cannot testify of. Democritus offers a causal theory of perception  sometimes called the theory of effluxes  accounting for tastes in terms of certain shapes of atoms and for sight in terms of “effluences” or moving films of atoms that impinge on the eye. Drawing on both atomic theory and conventional wisdom, Democritus develops an ethics of moderation. The aim of life is equanimity euthumiê, a state of balance achieved by moderation and proportionate pleasures. Envy and ambition are incompatible with the good life. Although Democritus was one of the most prolific writers of antiquity, his works were all lost. Yet we can still identify his atomic theory as the most fully worked out of pre-Socratic philosophies. His theory of matter influenced Plato’s Timaeus, and his naturalist anthropology became the prototype for liberal social theories. Democritus had no immediate successors, but a century later Epicurus transformed his ethics into a philosophy of consolation founded on atomism. Epicureanism thus became the vehicle through which atomic theory was transmitted to the early modern period. 

ramseyified description. Grice enjoyed Ramsey’s Engish humour: if you can say it, you can’t whistle it either. Applied by Grice in “Method.”Agent A is in a D state just in case there is a predicate “D”  introduced via implicit definition by nomological generalisation L within theory θ, such L obtains, A instantiates D. Grice distinguishes the ‘descriptor’ from a more primitive ‘name.’ The reference is to Ramsey. The issue is technical and relates to the introduction of a predicate constant – something he would never have dared to at Oxford with Gilbert Ryle and D. F. Pears next to him! But in the New World, they loved a formalism! And of course Ramsey would not have anything to do with it! Ramsey: p. r. – cited by Grice, “The Ramseyfied description. Frank Plumpton 330, influential 769 R    769 British philosopher of logic and mathematics. His primary interests were in logic and philosophy, but decades after his untimely death two of his publications sparked new branches of economics, and in pure mathematics his combinatorial theorems gave rise to “Ramsey theory” Economic Journal 7, 8; Proc. London Math. Soc., 8. During his lifetime Ramsey’s philosophical reputation outside Cambridge was based largely on his architectural reparation of Whitehead and Russell’s Principia Mathematica, strengthening its claim to reduce mathematics to the new logic formulated in Volume 1  a reduction rounded out by Vitters’s assessment of logical truths as tautologous. Ramsey clarified this logicist picture of mathematics by radically simplifying Russell’s ramified theory of types, eliminating the need for the unarguable axiom of reducibility Proc. London Math. Soc., 5. His philosophical work was published mostly after his death. The canon, established by Richard Braithwaite The Foundations of Mathematics . . . , 1, remains generally intact in D. H. Mellor’s edition Philosophical Papers, 0. Further writings of varying importance appear in his Notes on Philosophy, Probability and Mathematics M. C. Galavotti, ed., 1 and On Truth Nicholas Rescher and Ulrich Majer, eds., 1. As an undergraduate Ramsey observed that the redundancy account of truth “enables us to rule out at once some theories of truth such as that ‘to be true’ means ‘to work’ or ‘to cohere’ since clearly ‘p works’ and ‘p coheres’ are not equivalent to ‘p’.” Later, in the canonical “Truth and Probability” 6, he readdressed to knowledge and belief the main questions ordinarily associated with truth, analyzing probability as a mode of judgment in the framework of a theory of choice under uncertainty. Reinvented and acknowledged by L. J. Savage Foundations of Statistics, 4, this forms the theoretical basis of the currently dominant “Bayesian” view of rational decision making. Ramsey cut his philosophical teeth on Vitters’s Tractatus LogicoPhilosophicus. His translation appeared in 2; a long critical notice of the work 3 was his first substantial philosophical publication. His later role in Vitters’s rejection of the Tractatus is acknowledged in the foreword to Philosophical Investigations 3. The posthumous canon has been a gold mine. An example: “Propositions” 9, reading the theoretical terms T, U, etc. of an axiomatized scientific theory as variables, sees the theory’s content as conveyed by a “Ramsey sentence” saying that for some T, U, etc., the theory’s axioms are true, a sentence in which all extralogical terms are observational. Another example: “General Propositions and Causality” 9, offering in a footnote the “Ramsey test” for acceptability of conditionals, i.e., add the if-clause to your ambient beliefs minimally modified to make the enlarged set self-consistent, and accept the conditional if the then-clause follows.  Refs: “Philosophical psychology,” in BANC. ‘

Ramée, philosopher who questioned the authority of Aristotle and influenced the methods of f semantics. He published his “Dialecticae institutiones libri XV,” reworked  as “Dialectique,”  the first philosophical work in what Grice (‘Gris’) calls ‘the vernacular.’ “Not much different, I should say – cf. Redecraft translating Logic!”  Ramée is appointed by François I as the first Regius Professor in Paris, where he teaches until he is  killed in the St. Bartholomew’s Day Massacre. Ramée doubted that we can apodictically intuit the major premises required for Aristotle’s rational syllogism. Turning instead to Plato, Ramée proposed that a “Socratizing” of logic would produce a more workable and fruitful result. As had Agricola and Sturm, Ramée reworks the rhetorical and liberal arts traditions’ concepts of “invention, judgment, and practice,” placing “method” in the center of judgment. Proceeding in these stages, we can “read” nature’s “arguments,” because they are modeled on natural reasoning, which in turn can emulate the reasoning by which God creates. Often Ramée’s results are depicted graphically in tables as in chapter IX of Hobbes’s Leviathan. When carefully done they would show both what is known and where gaps require further investigation; the process from invention to judgment is continuous.  Ramée’s works saw some 750 editions in one century, fostering the “Ramist” movement in emerging Protestant universities and the colonies. He influenced Bacon, Hobbes, Milton, Methodism, Cambridge Platonism, and Alsted. Inconsistencies make him less than a major figure in the history of logic, but his many works and their rapid popularity led to philosophical and educational efforts to bring the world of learning to the “plain man” by using the vernacular, and by more closely correlating the rigor of philosophy with the memorable and persuasive powers of rhetoric; he saw this goal as Socratic.

Rashdall: English historian, theologian, and personal idealist. While acknowledging that Berkeley needed to be corrected by Kant, Rashdall defended Berkeley’s thesis that objects only exist for minds. From this he concluded that there is a divine mind that guarantees the existence of nature and the objectivity of morality. In his most important philosophical work, The Theory of Good and Evil 7, Rashdall argued that actions are right or wrong according to whether they produce well-being, in which pleasure as well as a virtuous disposition are constituents. Rashdall coined the name ‘ideal utilitarianism’ for this view.

Illatum: rational choice: as oppose to irrational choice. V. choose. Grice, “Impicatures of ‘choosing’” “Hobson’s choice, or Hobson’s ‘choice’?” Pears on conversational implicaturum and choosing. That includes choosing in its meaning, and then it is easy to ac- cept the suggestion that choosing might be an S-factor, and that the hypothetical might be a Willkür: one of Grice’s favourite words from Kant – “It’s so Kantish!” I told Pears about this, and having found it’s cognate with English ‘choose,’ he immediately set to write an essay on the topic!” f., ‘option, discretion, caprice,’ from MidHG. willekür, f., ‘free choice, free will’; gee kiesen and Kur-.kiesen, verb, ‘to select,’ from Middle High German kiesen, Old High German chiosan, ‘to test, try, taste for the purpose of testing, test by tasting, select after strict examination.’ Gothic kiusan, Anglo-Saxon ceósan, English to choose. Teutonic root kus (with the change of s into rkur in the participle erkoren, see also Kur, ‘choice’), from pre-Teutonic gus, in Latin gus-tusgus-tare, Greek γεύω for γεύσω, Indian root juš, ‘to select, be fond of.’ Teutonic kausjun passed as kusiti into Slavonic. Insofar as a philosopher explains and predicts the actum as consequences of a choice, which are themselves explained in terms of alleged reasons, it must depict agents as to some extent rational. Rationality, like reasons, involves evaluation, and just as one can assess the rationality of individual choices, so one can assess the rationality of social choices and examine how they are and ought to be related to the preferences and judgments of the actor. In addition, there are intricate questions concerning rationality in ‘strategic’ situations in which outcomes depend on the choices of multiple individuals. Since rationality is a central concept in branches of philosophy such as Grice’s pragmatics, action theory, epistemology, ethics, and philosophy of mind, studies of rationality frequently cross the boundaries various branches of philosophy. The barebones theory of rationality  takes an agent’s preferences, i. e. his rankings of states of affairs, to be rational if they are complete and transitive, and it takes the agent’s choice to be rational if the agent does not prefer any feasible alternative to the one he chooses. Such a theory of rationality is clearly too weak. It says nothing about belief or what rationality implies when the agent does not know (with certainty) everything relevant to his choice. It may also be too strong, since there is nothing irrational about having incomplete preferences in situations involving uncertainty. Sometimes it is rational to suspend judgment and to refuse to rank alternatives that are not well understood. On the other hand, transitivity is a plausible condition, and the so-called “money pump” argument demonstrates that if one’s preferences are intransitive and one is willing to make exchanges, then one can be exploited. Suppose an agent A prefers X to YY to Z and Z to X, and that A will pay some small amount of money $P to exchange Y for XZ for Y, and X for Z. That means that, starting with ZA will pay $P for Y, then $P again for X, then $P again for Z and so on. An agent need not be this stupid. He will instead refuse to trade or adjust his preferences to eliminate the intransitivity. On the other hand, there is evidence that an agent’s preferences are not in fact transitive. Such evidence does not establish that transitivity is not a requirement of rationality. It may show instead that an agent may sometimes not be rational. In, e. g. the case of preference reversals,” it seems plausible that the agent in fact makes the ‘irrational choice.’ Evidence of persistent violations of transitivity is disquieting, since standards of rationality should not be impossibly high. A further difficulty with the barebones theory of rationality concerns the individuation of the objects of preference or choice. Consider e. g. data from a multi-stage ultimatum game. Suppose A can propose any division of $10 between A and BB can accept or reject A’s proposal. If B rejects the proposal, the amount of money drops to $5, and B gets to offer a division of the $5 which A can accept or reject. If A rejects B’s offer, both players get nothing. Suppose that A proposes to divide the money with $7 for A and $3 for BB declines and offers to split the $5 evenly, with $2.50 for each. Behaviour such as this is, in fact, common. Assuming that B prefers more money to less, these choices appear to be a violation of transitivity. B prefers $3 to $2.50, yet declines $3 for certain for $2.50 (with some slight chance of A declining and B getting nothing). But the objects of choice are not just quantities of money. B is turning down $3 as part of “a raw deal” in favour of $2.50 as part of a fair arrangement. If the objects of choice are defined in this way, there is no failure of transitivity. This plausible observation gives rise to a serious conceptual problem that Grice thinks he can solve. Unless there are constraints on how the objects of choice are individuated, conditions of rationality such as transitivity are empty. A’s choice of X over YY over Z and Z over X does not violate transitivity if “X when the alternative is Y” is not the same object of choice as “X when the alternative is Z”. A further substantive principle of rationality isrequired to limit how alternatives are individuated or to require that agents be indifferent between alternatives such as “X when the alternative is Y” and “X when the alternative is Z.” To extend the theory of rationality to circumstances involving risk (where the objects of choice are lotteries with known probabilities) and uncertainty (where agents do not know the probabilities or even all the possible outcomes of their choices) requires a further principle of rationality, as well as a controversial technical simplification. Subjective Bayesians suppose that the agent in circumstances of uncertainty has well-defined subjective probabilities (degrees of belief) over all the payoffs and thus that the objects of choice can be modeled as lotteries, just as in circumstances involving risk, though with subjective probabilities in place of objective probabilities. The most important of the axioms needed for the theory of rational choice under conditions of risk and uncertainty is the independence condition. The preferences of a rational agent between two lotteries that differ in only one outcome should match his preferences between the differing outcomes. A considerable part of Grice’s rational choice theory is concerned with formalizations of conditions of rationality and investigation of their implications. When they are complete and transitive and satisfy a further continuity condition, the agent’s preferences can be represented by an ordinal utility function, i. e. it is then possible to define a function that represents an agent’s preferences so that U(X) > U(Y) iff if the agent prefers X to Y, and U(X) = U(Y) iff if the agent is indifferent between X and Y. This function represents the preference ranking, and contains no information beyond the ranking. When in addition they satisfy the independence condition, the agent’s preferences can be represented by an expected utility function (Ramsey 1926). Such a function has two important properties. First, the expected utility of a lottery is equal to the sum of the expected utilities of its prizes weighted by their probabilities. Second, expected utility functions are unique up to a positive affine transformation. If U and V are both expected utility functions representing the preferences of an agent, for all objects of preference, XV(X) must be equal to aU(X) + b, where a and b are real numbers and a is positive. The axioms of rationality imply that the agent’s degrees of belief will satisfy the axioms of the probability calculus. A great deal of controversy surrounds Grice’s theory of rationality, and there have been many formal investigations into amendeding it. Although a conversational pair is very different from this agent and this other agent, the pair has a mechanism to evaluate alternatives and make a choice. The evaluation and the choice may be rational or irrational. Pace Grice’s fruitful seminars on rational helpfulness in cooperation, t is not, however, obvious, what principles of rationality should govern the choices and evaluations of the conversational dyad. Transitivity is one plausible condition. It seems that a conversational dyad that chooses X when faced with the alternatives X or YY when faced with the alternatives Y or Z and Z when faced with the alternatives X or Z, the conversational dyad has had “a change of hearts” or is choosing ‘irrationally.’ Yet, purported irrationalities such as these can easily arise from a standard mechanism that aims to link a ‘conversational choice’ and individual preferences. Suppose there are two conversationalists in the dyad. Individual One ranks the alternatives XYZ. Individual Two ranks them YZX. (An Individual Three if he comes by, may ranks them ZXY). If decisions are made by pairwise majority voting, X will be chosen from the pair (XY), Y will be chosen from (YZ), and Z will be chosen from (XZ). Clearly this is unsettling. But is a possible cycle in a ‘conversational choice’ “irrational”? Similar problems affect what one might call the logical coherence of a conversational judgment Suppose the dyad consists of two individuals who make the following judgments concerning the truth or falsity of the propositions P and Q and that “conversational” judgment follows the majority. P if P, Q Q Conversationalist A true true true Conversationalist B false true false (Conversationalist C, if he passes by) true false false “Conversation” as an Institution: true true false. The judgment of each conversationalist is consistent with the principles of logic, while the “conversational co-operative” judgment violates the principles of logic. The “cooperative conversational,” “altruistic,” “joint judgment” need not be consistent with the principles of egoist logic. Although conversational choice theory bears on questions of conversational rationality, most work in conversational choice theory explores the consequences of principles of rationality coupled with this or that explicitly practical, or meta-ethical constraint. Grice does not use ‘moral,’ since he distinguishes what he calls a ‘conversational maxim’ from a ‘moral maxim’ of the type Kant universalizes. Arrow’s impossibility theorem assumes that an individual preference and a concerted, joint preference are complete and transitive and that the method of forming a conversational, concerted, joint preference (or making a conversational, concerted, choice) issues in some joint preference ranking or joint choice for any possible profile (or dossier, as Grice prefers) of each individual preference. Arrow’s impossibility theorem imposes a weak UNANIMITY (one-soul) condition. If A and B prefers X to Y, Y must not jointly preferred. Arrow’s impossibility theorem requires that there be no boss (call him Immanuel, the Genitor) whose preference determines a joint preference or choice irrespective of the preferences of anybody else. Arrow’s impossibility theorem imposes the condition that the joint concerted conversational preference between X and Y should depend on how A and B rank X and Y and on nothing else. Arrow’s impossibility theorem proves that no method of co-relating or linking conversational and a monogogic preference can satisfy all these conditions. If an monopreference and a mono-evaluations both satisfy the axioms of expected utility theory (with shared or objective probabilities) and that a duo-preference conform to the unanimous mono-preference, a duo- evaluation is determined by a weighted sum of individual utilities. A form of weighted futilitarianism, which prioritizes the interests of the recipient, rather than the emissor, uniquely satisfies a longer list of rational and practical constraints. When there are instead disagreements in probability assignments, there is an impossibility result. The unanimity (‘one-soul’) condition implies that for some profiles of individual preferences, a joint or duo-evaluation will not satisfy the axioms of expected utility theory. When outcomes depend on what at least two autonomous free agents do, one agent’s best choice may depend on what the other agent chooses. Although the principles of rationality governing mono-choice still apply, there is a further principle of conversational rationality governing the ‘expectation’ (to use Grice’s favourite term) of the action (or conversational move) of one’s co-conversationalist (and obviously, via the mutuality requirement of applicational universalizability) of the co-conversationalist’s ‘expectation’ concerning the conversationalist’s action and expectation, and so forth. Grice’s Conversational Game Theory plays a protagonist role within philosophy, and it is relevant to inquiries concerning conversational rationality and inquiries concerning conversational ethics. Rational choice -- Probability -- Dutch book, a bet or combination of bets whereby the bettor is bound to suffer a net loss regardless of the outcome. A simple example would be a bet on a proposition p at odds of 3 : 2 combined with a bet on not-p at the same odds, the total amount of money at stake in each bet being five dollars. Under this arrangement, if p turned out to be true one would win two dollars by the first bet but lose three dollars by the second, and if p turned out to be false one would win two dollars by the second bet but lose three dollars by the first. Hence, whatever happened, one would lose a dollar.  Dutch book argument, the argument that a rational person’s degrees of belief must conform to the axioms of the probability calculus, since otherwise, by the Dutch book theorem, he would be vulnerable to a Dutch book. R.Ke. Dutch book theorem, the proposition that anyone who a counts a bet on a proposition p as fair if the odds correspond to his degree of belief that p is true and who b is willing to make any combination of bets he would regard individually as fair will be vulnerable to a Dutch book provided his degrees of belief do not conform to the axioms of the probability calculus. Thus, anyone of whom a and b are true and whose degree of belief in a disjunction of two incompatible propositions is not equal to the sum of his degrees of belief in the two propositions taken individually would be vulnerable to a Dutch book. Illatum: rational decision theory -- decidability, as a property of sets, the existence of an effective procedure a “decision procedure” which, when applied to any object, determines whether or not the object belongs to the set. A theory or logic is decidable if and only if the set of its theorems is. Decidability is proved by describing a decision procedure and showing that it works. The truth table method, for example, establishes that classical propositional logic is decidable. To prove that something is not decidable requires a more precise characterization of the notion of effective procedure. Using one such characterization for which there is ample evidence, Church proved that classical predicate logic is not decidable. decision theory, the theory of rational decision, often called “rational choice theory” in political science and other social sciences. The basic idea probably Pascal’s was published at the end of Arnaud’s Port-Royal Logic 1662: “To judge what one must do to obtain a good or avoid an evil one must consider not only the good and the evil in itself but also the probability of its happening or not happening, and view geometrically the proportion that all these things have together.” Where goods and evils are monetary, Daniel Bernoulli 1738 spelled the idea out in terms of expected utilities as figures of merit for actions, holding that “in the absence of the unusual, the utility resulting from a fixed small increase in wealth will be inversely proportional to the quantity of goods previously possessed.” This was meant to solve the St. Petersburg paradox: Peter tosses a coin . . . until it should land “heads” [on toss n]. . . . He agrees to give Paul one ducat if he gets “heads” on the very first throw [and] with each additional throw the number of ducats he must pay is doubled. . . . Although the standard calculation shows that the value of Paul’s expectation [of gain] is infinitely great [i.e., the sum of all possible gains $ probabilities, 2n/2 $ ½n], it has . . . to be admitted that any fairly reasonable man would sell his chance, with great pleasure, for twenty ducats. In this case Paul’s expectation of utility is indeed finite on Bernoulli’s assumption of inverse proportionality; but as Karl Menger observed 4, Bernoulli’s solution fails if payoffs are so large that utilities are inversely proportional to probabilities; then only boundedness of utility scales resolves the paradox. Bernoulli’s idea of diminishing marginal utility of wealth survived in the neoclassical texts of W. S. Jevons 1871, Alfred Marshall 0, and A. C. Pigou 0, where personal utility judgment was understood to cause preference. But in the 0s, operationalistic arguments of John Hicks and R. G. D. Allen persuaded economists that on the contrary, 1 utility is no cause but a description, in which 2 the numbers indicate preference order but not intensity. In their Theory of Games and Economic Behavior 6, John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern undid 2 by pushing 1 further: ordinal preferences among risky prospects were now seen to be describable on “interval” scales of subjective utility like the Fahrenheit and Celsius scales for temperature, so that once utilities, e.g., 0 and 1, are assigned to any prospect and any preferred one, utilities of all prospects are determined by overall preferences among gambles, i.e., probability distributions over prospects. Thus, the utility midpoint between two prospects is marked by the distribution assigning probability ½ to each. In fact, Ramsey had done that and more in a little-noticed essay “Truth and Probability,” 1 teasing subjective probabilities as well as utilities out of ordinal preferences among gambles. In a form independently invented by L. J. Savage Foundations of Statistics, 4, this approach is now widely accepted as a basis for rational decision analysis. The 8 book of that title by Howard Raiffa became a theoretical centerpiece of M.B.A. curricula, whose graduates diffused it through industry, government, and the military in a simplified format for defensible decision making, namely, “costbenefit analyses,” substituting expected numbers of dollars, deaths, etc., for preference-based expected utilities. Social choice and group decision form the native ground of interpersonal comparison of personal utilities. Thus, John C. Harsanyi 5 proved that if 1 individual and social preferences all satisfy the von Neumann-Morgenstern axioms, and 2 society is indifferent between two prospects whenever all individuals are, and 3 society prefers one prospect to another whenever someone does and nobody has the opposite preference, then social utilities are expressible as sums of individual utilities on interval scales obtained by stretching or compressing the individual scales by amounts determined by the social preferences. Arguably, the theorem shows how to derive interpersonal comparisons of individual preference intensities from social preference orderings that are thought to treat individual preferences on a par. Somewhat earlier, Kenneth Arrow had written that “interpersonal comparison of utilities has no meaning and, in fact, there is no meaning relevant to welfare economics in the measurability of individual utility” Social Choice and Individual Values, 1  a position later abandoned P. Laslett and W. G. Runciman, eds., Philosophy, Politics and Society, 7. Arrow’s “impossibility theorem” is illustrated by cyclic preferences observed by Condorcet in 1785 among candidates A, B, C of voters 1, 2, 3, who rank them ABC, BCA, CAB, respectively, in decreasing order of preference, so that majority rule yields intransitive preferences for the group of three, of whom two 1, 3 prefer A to B and two 1, 2 prefer B to C but two 2, 3 prefer C to A. In general, the theorem denies existence of technically democratic schemes for forming social preferences from citizens’ preferences. A clause tendentiously called “independence of irrelevant alternatives” in the definition of ‘democratic’ rules out appeal to preferences among non-candidates as a way to form social preferences among candidates, thus ruling out the preferences among gambles used in Harsanyi’s theorem. See John Broome, Weighing Goods, 1, for further information and references. Savage derived the agent’s probabilities for states as well as utilities for consequences from preferences among abstract acts, represented by deterministic assignments of consequences to states. An act’s place in the preference ordering is then reflected by its expected utility, a probability-weighted average of the utilities of its consequences in the various states. Savage’s states and consequences formed distinct sets, with every assignment of consequences to states constituting an act. While Ramsey had also taken acts to be functions from states to consequences, he took consequences to be propositions sets of states, and assigned utilities to states, not consequences. A further step in that direction represents acts, too, by propositions see Ethan Bolker, Functions Resembling Quotients of Measures,  Microfilms, 5; and Richard Jeffrey, The Logic of Decision, 5, 0. Bolker’s representation theorem states conditions under which preferences between truth of propositions determine probabilities and utilities nearly enough to make the position of a proposition in one’s preference ranking reflect its “desirability,” i.e., one’s expectation of utility conditionally on it. decision theory decision theory 208   208 Alongside such basic properties as transitivity and connexity, a workhorse among Savage’s assumptions was the “sure-thing principle”: Preferences among acts having the same consequences in certain states are unaffected by arbitrary changes in those consequences. This implies that agents see states as probabilistically independent of acts, and therefore implies that an act cannot be preferred to one that dominates it in the sense that the dominant act’s consequences in each state have utilities at least as great as the other’s. Unlike the sure thing principle, the principle ‘Choose so as to maximize CEU conditional expectation of utility’ rationalizes action aiming to enhance probabilities of preferred states of nature, as in quitting cigarettes to increase life expectancy. But as Nozick pointed out in 9, there are problems in which choiceworthiness goes by dominance rather than CEU, as when the smoker like R. A. Fisher in 9 believes that the statistical association between smoking and lung cancer is due to a genetic allele, possessors of which are more likely than others to smoke and to contract lung cancer, although among them smokers are not especially likely to contract lung cancer. In such “Newcomb” problems choices are ineffectual signs of conditions that agents would promote or prevent if they could. Causal decision theories modify the CEU formula to obtain figures of merit distinguishing causal efficacy from evidentiary significance  e.g., replacing conditional probabilities by probabilities of counterfactual conditionals; or forming a weighted average of CEU’s under all hypotheses about causes, with agents’ unconditional probabilities of hypotheses as weights; etc. Mathematical statisticians leery of subjective probability have cultivated Abraham Wald’s Theory of Statistical Decision Functions 0, treating statistical estimation, experimental design, and hypothesis testing as zero-sum “games against nature.” For an account of the opposite assimilation, of game theory to probabilistic decision theory, see Skyrms, Dynamics of Rational Deliberation 0. The “preference logics” of Sören Halldén, The Logic of ‘Better’ 7, and G. H. von Wright, The Logic of Preference 3, sidestep probability. Thus, Halldén holds that when truth of p is preferred to truth of q, falsity of q must be preferred to falsity of p, and von Wright with Aristotle holds that “this is more choiceworthy than that if this is choiceworthy without that, but that is not choiceworthy without this” Topics III, 118a. Both principles fail in the absence of special probabilistic assumptions, e.g., equiprobability of p with q. Received wisdom counts decision theory clearly false as a description of human behavior, seeing its proper status as normative. But some, notably Davidson, see the theory as constitutive of the very concept of preference, so that, e.g., preferences can no more be intransitive than propositions can be at once true and false.  Rational decision: envelope paradox, an apparent paradox in decision theory that runs as follows. You are shown two envelopes, M and N, and are reliably informed that each contains some finite positive amount of money, that the amount in one unspecified envelope is twice the amount in the unspecified other, and that you may choose only one. Call the amount in M ‘m’ and that in N ‘n’. It might seem that: there is a half chance that m % 2n and a half chance that m = n/2, so that the “expected value” of m is ½2n ! ½n/2 % 1.25n, so that you should prefer envelope M. But by similar reasoning it might seem that the expected value of n is 1.25m, so that you should prefer envelope N.  illatum. rationality – while Grice never used to employ ‘rationality’ he learned to! In “Retrospective epilogue” in fact he refers to the principle of conversational helpfulness as ‘promoting conversational rationality.’ Rationality as a faculty psychology, the view that the mind is a collection of departments responsible for distinct psychological functions. Related to faculty psychology is the doctrine of localization of function, wherein each faculty has a specific brain location. Faculty psychologies oppose theories of mind as a unity with one function e.g., those of Descartes and associationism or as a unity with various capabilities e.g., that of Ockham, and oppose the related holistic distributionist or mass-action theory of the brain. Faculty psychology began with Aristotle, who divided the human soul into five special senses, three inner senses common sense, imagination, memory and active and passive mind. In the Middle Ages e.g., Aquinas Aristotle’s three inner senses were subdivied, creating more elaborate lists of five to seven inward wits. Islamic physicianphilosophers such as Avicenna integrated Aristotelian faculty psychology with Galenic medicine by proposing brain locations for the faculties. Two important developments in faculty psychology occurred during the eighteenth century. First, Scottish philosophers led by Reid developed a version of faculty psychology opposed to the empiricist and associationist psychologies of Locke and Hume. The Scots proposed that humans were endowed by God with a set of faculties permitting knowledge of the world and morality. The Scottish system exerted considerable influence in the United States, where it was widely taught as a moral, character-building discipline, and in the nineteenth century this “Old Psychology” opposed the experimental “New Psychology.” Second, despite then being called a charlatan, Franz Joseph Gall 17581828 laid the foundation for modern neuropsychology in his work on localization of function. Gall rejected existing faculty psychologies as philosophical, unbiological, and incapable of accounting for everyday behavior. Gall proposed an innovative behavioral and biological list of faculties and brain localizations based on comparative anatomy, behavior study, and measurements of the human skull. Today, faculty psychology survives in trait and instinct theories of personality, Fodor’s theory that mental functions are implemented by neurologically “encapsulated” organs, and localizationist theories of the brain. rationalism, the position that reason has precedence over other ways of acquiring knowledge, or, more strongly, that it is the unique path to knowledge. It is most often encountered as a view in epistemology, where it is traditionally contrasted with empiricism, the view that the senses are primary with respect to knowledge. It is important here to distinguish empiricism with respect to knowledge from empiricism with respect to ideas or concepts; whereas the former is opposed to rationalism, the latter is opposed to the doctrine of innate ideas. The term is also encountered in the philosophy of religion, where it may designate those who oppose the view that revelation is central to religious knowledge; and in ethics, where it may designate those who oppose the view that ethical principles are grounded in or derive from emotion, empathy, or some other non-rational foundation. The term ‘rationalism’ does not generally designate a single precise philosophical position; there are several ways in which reason can have precedence, and several accounts of knowledge to which it may be opposed. Furthermore, the very term ‘reason’ is not altogether clear. Often it designates a faculty of the soul, distinct from sensation, imagination, and memory, which is the ground of a priori knowledge. But there are other conceptions of reason, such as the narrower conception in which Pascal opposes reason to “knowledge of the heart” Pensées, section 110, or the computational conception of reason Hobbes advances in Leviathan I.5. The term might thus be applied to a number of philosophical positions from the ancients down to the present. Among the ancients, ‘rationalism’ and ‘empiricism’ especially denote two schools of medicine, the former relying primarily on a theoretical knowledge of the hidden workings of the human body, the latter relying on direct clinical experience. The term might also be used to characterize the views of Plato and later Neoplatonists, who argued that we have pure intellectual access to the Forms and general principles that govern reality, and rejected sensory knowledge of the imperfect realization of those Forms in the material world. In recent philosophical writing, the term ‘rationalism’ is most closely associated with the positions of a group of seventeenth-century philosophers, Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, and sometimes Malebranche. These thinkers are often referred to collectively as the Continental rationalists, and are generally opposed to the socalled British empiricists, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume. All of the former share the view that we have a non-empirical and rational access to the truth about the way the world is, and all privilege reason over knowledge derived from the senses. These philosophers are also attracted to mathematics as a model for knowledge in general. But these common views are developed in quite different ways. Descartes claims to take his inspiration from mathematics  not mathematics as commonly understood, but the analysis of the ancients. According to Descartes, we start from first principles known directly by reason the cogito ergo sum of the Meditations, what he calls intuition in his Rules for the Direction of the Mind; all other knowledge is deduced from there. A central aim of his Meditations is to show that this faculty of reason is trustworthy. The senses, on the other hand, are generally deceptive, leading us to mistake sensory qualities for real qualities of extended bodies, and leading us to the false philosophy of Aristotle and to Scholasticism. Descartes does not reject the senses altogether; in Meditation VI he argues that the senses are most often correct in circumstances concerning the preservation of life. Perhaps paradoxically, experiment is important to Descartes’s scientific work. However, his primary interest is in the theoretical account of the phenomena experiment reveals, and while his position is unclear, he may have considered experiment as an auxiliary to intuition and deduction, or as a second-best method that can be used with problems too complex for pure reason. Malebranche, following Descartes, takes similar views in his Search after Truth, though unlike Descartes, he emphasizes original sin as the cause of our tendency to trust the senses. Spinoza’s model for knowledge is Euclidean geometry, as realized in the geometrical form of the Ethics. Spinoza explicitly argues that we cannot have adequate ideas of the world through sensation Ethics II, propositions 1631. In the Ethics he does see a role for the senses in what he calls knowledge of the first and knowledge of the second kinds, and in the earlier Emendation of the Intellect, he suggests that the senses may be auxiliary aids to genuine knowledge. But the senses are imperfect and far less valuable, according to Spinoza, than intuition, i.e., knowledge of the third kind, from which sensory experience is excluded. Spinoza’s rationalism is implicit in a central proposition of the Ethics, in accordance with which “the order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things” Ethics II, proposition 7, allowing one to infer causal connections between bodies and states of the material world directly from the logical connections between ideas. Leibniz, too, emphasizes reason over the senses in a number of ways. In his youth he believed that it would be possible to calculate the truth-value of every sentence by constructing a logical language whose structure mirrors the structure of relations between concepts in the world. This view is reflected in his mature thought in the doctrine that in every truth, the concept of the predicate is contained in the concept of the subject, so that if one could take the God’s-eye view which, he concedes, we cannot, one could determine the truth or falsity of any proposition without appeal to experience Discourse on Metaphysics, section 8. Leibniz also argues that all truths are based on two basic principles, the law of non-contradiction for necessary truths, and the principle of sufficient reason for contingent truths Monadology, section 31, both of which can be known a priori. And so, at least in principle, the truth-values of all propositions can be determined a priori. This reflects his practice in physics, where he derives a number of laws of motion from the principle of the equality of cause and effect, which can be known a priori on the basis of the principle of sufficient reason. But, at the same time, referring to the empirical school of ancient medicine, Leibniz concedes that “we are all mere Empirics in three fourths of our actions” Monadology, section 28. Each of the so-called Continental rationalists does, in his own way, privilege reason over the senses. But the common designation ‘Continental rationalism’ arose only much later, probably in the nineteenth century. For their contemporaries, more impressed with their differences than their common doctrines, the Continental rationalists did not form a single homogeneous school of thought. Illatum: rationality. In its primary sense, rationality is a normative concept that philosophers have generally tried to characterize in such a way that, for any action, belief, or desire, if it is rational we ought to choose it. No such positive characterization has achieved anything close to universal assent because, often, several competing actions, beliefs, or desires count as rational. Equating what is rational with what is rationally required eliminates the category of what is rationally allowed. Irrationality seems to be the more fundamental normative category; for although there are conflicting substantive accounts of irrationality, all agree that to say of an action, belief, or desire that it is irrational is to claim that it should always be avoided. Rationality is also a descriptive concept that refers to those intellectual capacities, usually involving the ability to use language, that distinguish persons from plants and most other animals. There is some dispute about whether some non-human animals, e.g., dolphins and chimpanzees, are rational in this sense. Theoretical rationality applies to beliefs. An irrational belief is one that obviously conflicts with what one should know. This characterization of an irrational belief is identical with the psychiatric characterization of a delusion. It is a personrelative concept, because what obviously conflicts with what should be known by one person need not obviously conflict with what should be known by another. On this account, any belief that is not irrational counts as rational. Many positive characterizations of rational beliefs have been proposed, e.g., 1 beliefs that are either self-evident or derived from self-evident beliefs by a reliable procedure and 2 beliefs that are consistent with the overwhelming majority of one’s beliefs; but all of these positive characterizations have encountered serious objections. Practical rationality applies to actions. For some philosophers it is identical to instrumental rationality. On this view, commonly called instrumentalism, acting rationally simply means acting in a way that is maximally efficient in achieving one’s goals. However, most philosophers realize that achieving one goal may conflict with achieving another, and therefore require that a rational action be one that best achieves one’s goals only when these goals are considered as forming a system. Others have added that all of these goals must be ones that would be chosen given complete knowledge and understanding of what it would be like to achieve these goals. On the latter account of rational action, the system of goals is chosen by all persons for themselves, and apart from consistency there is no external standpoint from which to evaluate rationally any such system. Thus, for a person with a certain system of goals it will be irrational to act morally. Another account of rational action is not at all person-relative. On this account, to act rationally is to act on universalizable principles, so that what is a reason for one person must be a reason for everyone. One point of such an account is to make it rationally required to act morally, thus making all immoral action irrational. However, if to call an action irrational is to claim that everyone would hold that it is always to be avoided, then it is neither irrational to act immorally in order to benefit oneself or one’s friends, nor irrational to act morally even when that goes against one’s system of goals. Only a negative characterization of what is rational as what is not irrational, which makes it rationally permissible to act either morally or in accordance with one’s own system of goals, as long as these goals meet some minimal objective standard, seems likely to be adequate.   Illatum: rationalization, 1 an apparent explanation of a person’s action or attitude by appeal to reasons that would justify or exculpate the person for it  if, contrary to fact, those reasons were to explain it; 2 an explanation or interpretation made from a rational perspective. In sense 1, rationalizations are pseudo-explanations, often motivated by a desire to exhibit an item in a favorable light. Such rationalizations sometimes involve self-deception. Depending on one’s view of justification, a rationalization might justify an action  by adducing excellent reasons for its performance  even if the agent, not having acted for those reasons, deserves no credit for so acting. In sense 2 a sense popularized in philosophy by Donald Davidson, rationalizations of intentional actions are genuine explanations in terms of agents’ reasons. In this sense, we provide a rationalization for  or “rationalize”  Robert’s shopping at Zed’s by identifying the reasons for which he does so: e.g., he wants to buy an excellent kitchen knife and believes that Zed’s sells the best cutlery in town. Also, the reasons for which an agent acts may themselves be said to rationalize the action. Beliefs, desires, and intentions may be similarly rationalized. In each case, a rationalization exhibits the rationalized item as, to some degree, rational from the standpoint of the person to whom it is attributed. rational psychology, the a priori study of the mind. This was a large component of eighteenthand nineteenth-century psychology, and was contrasted by its exponents with empirical psychology, which is rooted in contingent experience. The term ‘rational psychology’ may also designate a mind, or form of mind, having the property of rationality. Current philosophy of mind includes much discussion of rational psychologies, but the notion is apparently ambiguous. On one hand, there is rationality as intelligibility. This is a minimal coherence, say of desires or inferences, that a mind must possess to be a mind. For instance, Donald Davidson, many functionalists, and some decision theorists believe there are principles of rationality of this sort that constrain the appropriate attribution of beliefs and desires to a person, so that a mind must meet such constraints if it is to have beliefs and desires. On another pole, there is rationality as justification. For someone’s psychology to have this property is for that psychology to be as reason requires it to be, say for that person’s inferences and desires to be supported by proper reasons given their proper weight, and hence to be justified. Rationality as justification is a normative property, which it would seem some minds lack. But despite the apparent differences between these two sorts of rationality, some important work in philosophy of mind implies either that these two senses in fact collapse, or at least that there are intervening and significant senses, so that things at least a lot like normative principles constrain what our psychologies are.  rational reconstruction, also called logical reconstruction, translation of a discourse of a certain conceptual type into a discourse of another conceptual type with the aim of making it possible to say everything or everything important that is expressible in the former more clearly or perspicuously in the latter. The best-known example is one in Carnap’s Der Logische Aufbau der Welt. Carnap attempted to translate discourse concerning physical objects e.g., ‘There is a round brown table’ into discourse concerning immediate objects of sense experience ‘Color patches of such-and-such chromatic characteristics and shape appear in such-and-such a way’. He was motivated by the empiricist doctrine that immediate sense experience is conceptually prior to everything else, including our notion of a physical object. In addition to talk of immediate sense experience, Carnap relied on logic and set theory. Since their use is difficult to reconcile with strict empiricism, his translation would not have fully vindicated empiricism even if it had succeeded.  Illatum: rationality -- reasons for action, considerations that call for or justify action. They may be subjective or objective. A subjective reason is a consideration an agent understands to support a course of action, whether or not it actually does. An objective reason is one that does support a course of action, regardless of whether the agent realizes it. What are cited as reasons may be matters either of fact or of value, but when facts are cited values are also relevant. Thus the fact that cigarette smoke contains nicotine is a reason for not smoking only because nicotine has undesirable effects. The most important evaluative reasons are normative reasons  i.e., considerations having e.g. ethical force. Facts become obligating reasons when, in conjunction with normative considerations, they give rise to an obligation. Thus in view of the obligation to help the needy, the fact that others are hungry is an obligating reason to see they are fed. Reasons for action enter practical thinking as the contents of beliefs, desires, and other mental states. But not all the reasons one has need motivate the corresponding behavior. Thus I may recognize an obligation to pay taxes, yet do so only for fear of punishment. If so, then only my fear is an explaining reason for my action. An overriding reason is one that takes precedence over all others. It is often claimed that moral reasons override all others objectively, and should do so subjectively as well. Finally, one may speak of an all-things-considered reason  one that after due consideration is taken as finally determinative of what shall be done.    reasons for belief, roughly, bases of belief. The word ‘belief’ is commonly used to designate both a particular sort of psychological state, a state of believing, and a particular intentional content or proposition believed. Reasons for belief exhibit an analogous duality. A proposition, p, might be said to provide a normative reason to believe a proposition, q, for instance, when p bears some appropriate warranting relation to q. And p might afford a perfectly good reason to believe q, even though no one, as a matter of fact, believes either p or q. In contrast, p is a reason that I have for believing q, if I believe p and p counts as a reason in the sense above to believe q. Undoubtedly, I have reason to believe countless propositions that I shall never, as it happens, come to believe. Suppose, however, that p is a reason for which I believe q. In that case, I must believe both p and q, and p must be a reason to believe q  or, at any rate, I must regard it as such. It may be that I must, in addition, believe q at least in part because I believe p. Reasons in these senses are inevitably epistemic; they turn on considerations of evidence, truth-conduciveness, and the like. But not all reasons for belief are of this sort. An explanatory reason, a reason why I believe p, may simply be an explanation for my having or coming to have this belief. Perhaps I believe p because I was brainwashed, or struck on the head, or because I have strong non-epistemic motives for this belief. I might, of course, hold the belief on the basis of unexceptionable epistemic grounds. When this is so, my believing p may both warrant and explain my believing q. Reflections of this sort can lead to questions concerning the overall or “all-things-considered” reasonableness of a given belief. Some philosophers e.g., Clifford argue that a belief’s reasonableness depends exclusively on its epistemic standing: my believing p is reasonable for me provided it is epistemically reasonable for me; where belief is concerned, epistemic reasons are overriding. Others, siding with James, have focused on the role of belief in our psychological economy, arguing that the reasonableness of my holding a given belief can be affected by a variety of non-epistemic considerations. Suppose I have some evidence that p is false, but that I stand to benefit in a significant way from coming to believe p. If that is so, and if the practical advantages of my holding p considerably outweigh the practical disadvantages, it might seem obvious that my holding p is reasonable for me in some all-embracing sense. 

Ray, J. English naturalist whose work on the structure and habits of plants and animals led to important conclusions on the methodology of classification and gave a strong impetus to the design argument in natural theology. In an early paper he argued that the determining characteristics of a species are those transmitted by seed, since color, scent, size, etc., vary with climate and nutriment. Parallels from the animal kingdom suggested the correct basis for classification would be structural. But we have no knowledge of real essences. Our experience of nature is of a continuum, and for practical purposes kinships are best identified by a plurality of criteria. His mature theory is set out in Dissertatio Brevis 1696 and Methodus Emendata 1703. The Wisdom of God Manifested in the Works of the Creation 1691 and three revisions was a best-selling compendium of Ray’s own scientific learning and was imitated and quarried by many later exponents of the design argument. Philosophically, he relied on others, from Cicero to Cudworth, and was superseded by Paley.

Res: “Possibly the most important word in philosophy.” Grice -- Realism – causal realism -- direct realism, the theory that perceiving is epistemically direct, unmediated by conscious or unconscious inference. Direct realism is distinguished, on the one hand, from indirect, or representative, realism, the view that perceptual awareness of material objects is mediated by an awareness of sensory representations, and, on the other hand, from forms of phenomenalism that identify material objects with states of mind. It might be thought that direct realism is incompatible with causal theories of perception. Such theories invoke causal chains leading from objects perceived causes to perceptual states of perceivers effects. Since effects must be distinct from causes, the relation between an instance of perceiving and an object perceived, it would seem, cannot be direct. This, however, confuses epistemic directness with causal directness. A direct realist need only be committed to the former. In perceiving a tomato to be red, the content of my perceptual awareness is the tomato’s being red. I enter this state as a result of a complex causal process, perhaps. But my perception may be direct in the sense that it is unmediated by an awareness of a representational sensory state from which I am led to an awareness of the tomato. Perceptual error, and more particularly, hallucinations and illusions, are usually thought to pose special difficulties for direct realists. My hallucinating a red tomato, for instance, is not my being directly aware of a red tomato, since I may hallucinate the tomato even when none is present. Perhaps, then, my hallucinating a red tomato is partly a matter of my being directly aware of a round, red sensory representation. And if my awareness in this case is indistinguishable from my perception of an actual red tomato, why not suppose that I am aware of a sensory representation in the veridical case as well? A direct realist may respond by denying that hallucinations are in fact indistinguishable from veridical perceivings or by calling into question the claim that, if sensory representations are required to explain hallucinations, they need be postulated in the veridical case.  reality, in standard philosophical usage, how things actually are, in contrast with their mere appearance. Appearance has to do with how things seem to a particular perceiver or group of perceivers. Reality is sometimes said to be twoway-independent of appearance. This means that appearance does not determine reality. First, no matter how much agreement there is, based on appearance, about the nature of reality, it is always conceivable that reality differs from appearance. Secondly, appearances are in no way required for reality: reality can outstrip the range of all investigations that we are in a position to make. It may be that reality always brings with it the possibility of appearances, in the counterfactual sense that if there were observers suitably situated, then if conditions were not conducive to error, they would have experiences of such-and-such a kind. But the truth of such a counterfactual seems to be grounded in the facts of reality. Phenomenalism holds, to the contrary, that the facts of reality can be explained by such counterfactuals, but phenomenalists have failed to produce adequate non-circular analyses. The concept of reality on which it is two-wayindependent of experience is sometimes called objective reality. However, Descartes used this phrase differently, to effect a contrast with formal or actual reality. He held that there must be at least as much reality in the efficient and total cause of an effect as in the effect itself, and applied this principle as follows: “There must be at least as much actual or formal reality in the efficient and total cause of an idea as objective reality in the idea itself.” The objective reality of an idea seems to have to do with its having representational content, while actual or formal reality has to do with existence independent of the mind. Thus the quoted principle relates features of the cause of an idea to the representational content of the idea. Descartes’s main intended applications were to God and material objects. 

recursum: Grice, ‘anti-sneak.” The third clause (III) in Grice’s final analysis of utterer’s meaning is self-referential and recursive, in a good way, in that (III) itself counts as one of the ‘inference elements’ (that Grice symbolises as “E”) that (III) specifies. Grice loved the heraldy metaphor of the escrutcheon – and the Droste effect. Cf. ‘speculative,’ --.  Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Grice’s mise-en-abyme,” per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia. Then there is the recursive function theory, an area of formal semantics that takes as its point of departure the study of an extremely limited class of functions, the recursive functions. Recursive function theory is a branch of higher arithmetic number theory, or the theory of natural numbers whose universe of discourse is restricted to the non-negative integers: 0, 1, 2, etc. However, the techniques and results of recursive function theory do not resemble those traditionally associated with number theory. The class of recursive functions is defined in a way that makes evident that every recursive function can be computed or calculated. The hypothesis that every calculable function is recursive, which is known as Church’s thesis, is often taken as a kind of axiom in recursive function theory. This theory has played an important role in philosophy of mathematics, especially when epistemological issues are studied, since as Grice knows, super-knowing may be hard, but not impossible!

Redintegratum: a psychological process, similar to or involving classical conditioning, in which one feature of a situation causes a person to recall, visualize, or recompose an entire original situation. On opening a pack of cigarettes, a person may visualize the entire process, including striking the match, lighting the cigarette, and puffing. Redintegration is used as a technique in behavior therapy, e.g. when someone trying to refrain from smoking is exposed to unpleasant odors and vivid pictures of lungs caked with cancer, and then permitted to smoke. If the unpleasantness of the odors and visualization outweighs the reinforcement of smoking, the person may resist smoking. Philosophically, for Grice, so-called barbarically “redintegratum” is of interest for two reasons. First, the process may be critical in prudence. By bringing long-range consequences of behavior into focus in present deliberation, redintegration may help to protect long-range interests. Second, redintegration offers a role for visual images in producing behavior. Images figure in paradigmatic cases of redintegration. In recollecting pictures of cancerous lungs, the person may refrain from smoking. Pears: “Oddly, it didn’t work with Grice who remained a  bit of a chain-smoker – but of Navy’s Cut only, except for the very last. He never smelt the odour in a bad way.”

reduction, the replacement of one expression by a second expression that differs from the first in prima facie reference. So-called reductions have been meant in the sense of uniformly applicable explicit definitions, contextual definitions, or replacements suitable only in a limited range of contexts. Thus, authors have spoken of reductive conceptual analyses, especially in the early days of analytic philosophy. In particular, in the sensedatum theory talk of physical objects was supposed to be reduced to talk of sense-data by explicit definitions or other forms of conceptual analysis. Logical positivists talked of the reduction of theoretical vocabulary to an observational vocabulary, first by explicit definitions, and later by other devices, such as Carnap’s reduction sentences. These appealed to a test condition predicate, T e.g., ‘is placed in water’, and a display predicate, D e.g., ‘dissolves’, to introduce a dispositional or other “non-observational” term, S e.g., ‘is water-soluble’: Ex [Tx / Dx / Sx], with ‘/’ representing the material conditional. Negative reduction sentences for non-occurrence of S took the form Ex [NTx / NDx / - Sx]. For coinciding predicate pairs T and TD and -D and ND Carnap referred to bilateral reduction sentences: Ex [Tx / Dx S Sx]. Like so many other attempted reductions, reduction sentences did not achieve replacement of the “reduced” term, S, since they do not fix application of S when the test condition, T, fails to apply. In the philosophy of mathematics, logicism claimed that all of mathematics could be reduced to logic, i.e., all mathematical terms could be defined with the vocabulary of logic and all theorems of mathematics could be derived from the laws of logic supplemented by these definitions. Russell’s Principia Mathematica carried out much of such a program with a reductive base of something much more like what we now call set theory rather than logic, strictly conceived. Many now accept the reducibility of mathematics to set theory, but only in a sense in which reductions are not unique. For example, the natural numbers can equally well be modeled as classes of equinumerous sets or as von Neumann ordinals. This non-uniqueness creates serious difficulties, with suggestions that set-theoretic reductions can throw light on what numbers and other mathematical objects “really are.” In contrast, we take scientific theories to tell us, unequivocally, that water is H20 and that temperature is mean translational kinetic energy. Accounts of theory reduction in science attempt to analyze the circumstance in which a “reducing theory” appears to tell us the composition of objects or properties described by a “reduced theory.” The simplest accounts follow the general pattern of reduction: one provides “identity statements” or “bridge laws,” with at least the form of explicit definitions, for all terms in the reduced theory not already appearing in the reducing theory; and then one argues that the reduced theory can be deduced from the reducing theory augmented by the definitions. For example, the laws of thermodynamics are said to be deducible from those of statistical mechanics, together with statements such as ‘temperature is mean translational kinetic energy’ and ‘pressure is mean momentum transfer’. How should the identity statements or bridge laws be understood? It takes empirical investigation to confirm statements such as that temperature is mean translational kinetic energy. Consequently, some have argued, such statements at best constitute contingent correlations rather than strict identities. On the other hand, if the relevant terms and their extensions are not mediated by analytic definitions, the identity statements may be analogized to identities involving two names, such as ‘Cicero is Tully’, where it takes empirical investigation to establish that the two names happen to have the same referent. One can generalize the idea of theory reduction in a variety of ways. One may require the bridge laws to suffice for the deduction of the reduced from the reducing theory without requiring that the bridge laws take the form of explicit identity statements or biconditional correlations. Some authors have also focused on the fact that in practice a reducing theory T2 corrects or refines the reduced theory T1, so that it is really only a correction or refinement, T1*, that is deducible from T2 and the bridge laws. Some have consequently applied the term ‘reduction’ to any pair of theories where the second corrects and extends the first in ways that explain both why the first theory was as accurate as it was and why it made the errors that it did. In this extended sense, relativity is said to reduce Newtonian mechanics. Do the social sciences, especially psychology, in principle reduce to physics? This prospect would support the so-called identity theory of mind and body, in particular resolving important problems in the philosophy of mind, such as the mindbody problem and the problem of other minds. Many though by no means all are now skeptical about the prospects for identifying mental properties, and the properties of other special sciences, with complex physical properties. To illustrate with an example from economics adapted from Fodor, in the right circumstances just about any physical object could count as a piece of money. Thus prospects seem dim for finding a closed and finite statement of the form ‘being a piece of money is . . .’, with only predicates from physics appearing on the right though some would want to admit infinite definitions in providing reductions. Similarly, one suspects that attributes, such as pain, are at best functional properties with indefinitely many possible physical realizations. Believing that reductions by finitely stable definitions are thus out of reach, many authors have tried to express the view that mental properties are still somehow physical by saying that they nonetheless supervene on the physical properties of the organisms that have them. In fact, these same difficulties that affect mental properties affect the paradigm case of temperature, and probably all putative examples of theoretical reduction. Temperature is mean translational temperature only in gases, and only idealized ones at that. In other substances, quite different physical mechanisms realize temperature. Temperature is more accurately described as a functional property, having to do with the mechanism of heat transfer between bodies, where, in principle, the required mechanism could be physically realized in indefinitely many ways. In most and quite possibly all cases of putative theory reduction by strict identities, we have instead a relation of physical realization, constitution, or instantiation, nicely illustrated by the property of being a calculator example taken from Cummins. The property of being a calculator can be physically realized by an abacus, by devices with gears and levers, by ones with vacuum tubes or silicon chips, and, in the right circumstances, by indefinitely many other physical arrangements. Perhaps many who have used ‘reduction’, particularly in the sciences, have intended the term in this sense of physical realization rather than one of strict identity. Let us restrict attention to properties that reduce in the sense of having a physical realization, as in the cases of being a calculator, having a certain temperature, and being a piece of money. Whether or not an object counts as having properties such as these will depend, not only on the physical properties of that object, but on various circumstances of the context. Intensions of relevant language users constitute a plausible candidate for relevant circumstances. In at least many cases, dependence on context arises because the property constitutes a functional property, where the relevant functional system calculational practices, heat transfer, monetary systems are much larger than the propertybearing object in question. These examples raise the question of whether many and perhaps all mental properties depend ineliminably on relations to things outside the organisms that have the mental properties.  Then there is the reduction sentence, for a given predicate Q3 of space-time points in a first-order language, any universal sentence S1 of the form: x [Q1x / Q2x / Q3 x], provided that the predicates Q1 and Q2 are consistently applicable to the same space-time points. If S1 has the form given above and S2 is of the form x [Q4x / Q5 / - Q6] and either S1 is a reduction sentence for Q3 or S2 is a reduction sentence for -Q3, the pair {S1, S2} is a reduction pair for Q3. If Q1 % Q4 and Q2 % - Q5, the conjunction of S1 and S2 is equivalent to a bilateral reduction sentence for Q3 of the form x [Q1 / Q3 S Q2]. These concepts were introduced by Carnap in “Testability and Meaning,” Philosophy of Science 637, to modify the verifiability criterion of meaning to a confirmability condition where terms can be introduced into meaningful scientific discourse by chains of reduction pairs rather than by definitions. The incentive for this modification seems to have been to accommodate the use of disposition predicates in scientific discourse. Carnap proposed explicating a disposition predicate Q3 by bilateral reduction sentences for Q3. An important but controversial feature of Carnap’s approach is that it avoids appeal to nonextensional conditionals in explicating disposition predicates.  Then there is the reductio ad absurdum, “Tertullian’s favourite proof,” – Grice. 1 The principles A / - A / -A and -A / A / A. 2 The argument forms ‘If A then B and not-B; therefore, not-A’ and ‘If not-A then B and not-B; therefore, A’ and arguments of these forms. Reasoning via such arguments is known as the method of indirect proof. 3 The rules of inference that permit i inferring not-A having derived a contradiction from A and ii inferring A having derived a contradiction from not-A. Both rules hold in classical logic and come to the same thing in any logic with the law of double negation. In intuitionist logic, however, i holds but ii does not. reductionism: The issue of reductionism is very much twentieth-century. There was Wisdom’s boring contribtions to Mind on ‘logical construction,’ Grice read the summary from Broad. One of the twelve –isms that Grice finds on his ascent to the City of Eternal Truth. He makes the reductive-reductionist distinction. Against J. M. Rountree. So, for Grice, the bad heathen vicious Reductionism can be defeated by the good Christian virtuous. Reductivism. A reductivist tries to define, say, what an emissor communicates (that p) in terms of the content of that proposition that he intends to transmit to his recipient. Following Aristotle, Grice reduces the effect to a ‘pathemata psucheos,’ i. e. a passio of the anima, as Boethius translates. This can be desiderative (“Thou shalt not kill”) or creditativa (“The grass is green.”)


mise-en-abyme-- reflection principles, two varieties of internal statements related to correctness in formal axiomatic systems. 1 Proof-theoretic reflection principles are formulated for effectively presented systems S that contain a modicum of elementary number theory sufficient to arithmetize their own syntactic notions, as done by Kurt Gödel in his 1 work on incompleteness. Let ProvS x express that x is the Gödel number of a statement provable in S, and let nA be the number of A, for any statement A of S. The weakest reflection principle considered for S is the collection RfnS of all statements of the form ProvS nA P A, which express that if A is provable from S then A is true. The proposition ConS expressing the consistency of S is a consequence of RfnS obtained by taking A to be a disprovable statement. Thus, by Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem, RfnS is stronger than S if S is consistent. Reflection principles are used in the construction of ordinal logics as a systematic means of overcoming incompleteness. 2 Set-theoretic reflection principles are formulated for systems S of axiomatic set theory, such as ZF Zermelo-Fraenkel. In the simplest form they express that any property A in the language of S that holds of the universe of “all” sets, already holds of a portion of that universe coextensive with some set x. This takes the form A P DxAx where in Ax all quantifiers of A are relativized to x. In contrast to proof-theoretic reflection principles, these may be established as theorems of ZF. 

Reflectum -- reflective equilibrium, as usually conceived, a coherence method for justifying evaluative principles and theories. The method was first described by Goodman, who proposed it be used to justify deductive and inductive principles. According to Goodman Fact, Fiction and Forecast, 5, a particular deductive inference is justified by its conforming with deductive principles, but these principles are justified in their turn by conforming with accepted deductive practice. The idea, then, is that justified inferences and principles are those that emerge from a process of mutual adjustment, with principles being revised when they sanction inferences we cannot bring ourselves to accept, and particular inferences being rejected when they conflict with rules we are unwilling to revise. Thus, neither principles nor particular inferences are epistemically privileged. At least in principle, everything is liable to revision. Rawls further articulated the method of reflective equilibrium and applied it in ethics. According to Rawls A Theory of Justice, 1, inquiry begins with considered moral judgments, i.e., judgments about which we are confident and which are free from common sources of error, e.g., ignorance of facts, insufficient reflection, or emotional agitation. According to narrow reflective equilibrium, ethical principles are justified by bringing them into coherence with our considered moral judgments through a process of mutual adjustment. Rawls, however, pursues a wide reflective equilibrium. Wide equilibrium is attained by proceeding to consider alternatives to the moral conception accepted in narrow equilibrium, along with philosophical arguments that might decide among these conceptions. The principles and considered judgments accepted in narrow equilibrium are then adjusted as seems appropriate. One way to conceive of wide reflective equilibrium is as an effort to construct a coherent system of belief by a process of mutual adjustment to considered moral judgments and moral principles as in narrow equilibrium along with the background philosophical, social scientific, and any other relevant beliefs that might figure in the arguments for and against alternative moral conceptions, e.g., metaphysical views regarding the nature of persons. As in Goodman’s original proposal, none of the judgments, principles, or theories involved is privileged: all are open to revision. 

regressus vitiosum -- viscious regress – Grice preferred ‘vicious circle’ versus ‘virtuous circle’ – “Whether virtuous regress sounds oxymoronic” -- regress that is in some way unacceptable, where a regress is an infinite series of items each of which is in some sense dependent on a prior item of a similar sort, e.g. an infinite series of events each of which is caused by the next prior event in the series. Reasons for holding a regress to be vicious might be that it is either impossible or that its existence is inconsistent with things known to be true. The claim that something would lead to a vicious regress is often made as part of a reductio ad absurdum argument strategy. An example of this can be found in Aquinas’s argument for the existence of an uncaused cause on the ground that an infinite regress of causes is vicious. Those responding to the argument have sometimes contended that this regress is not in fact vicious and hence that the argument fails. A more convincing example of a regress is generated by the principle that one’s coming to know the meaning of a word must always be based on a prior understanding of other words. If this principle is correct, then one can know the meaning of a word w1 only on the basis of previously understanding the meanings of other words w2 and w3. But a further application of the principle yields the result that one can understand these words w2 and w3 only on the basis of understanding still other words. This leads to an infinite regress. Since no one understands any words at birth, the regress implies that no one ever comes to understand any words. But this is clearly false. Since the existence of this regress is inconsistent with an obvious truth, we may conclude that the regress is vicious and consequently that the principle that generates it is false. 

Griceian renaissance – (“rinascimento”) after J. L. Austin’s death -- Erasmus, D., philosopher who played an important role in Renaissance humanism. Like his  forerunners Petrarch, Coluccio Salutati, Lorenzo Valla, Leonardo Bruni, and others, Erasmus stressed within philosophy and theology the function of philological precision, grammatical correctness, and rhetorical elegance. But for Erasmus the virtues of bonae literarae which are cultivated by the study of authors of Latin and Grecian antiquity must be decisively linked with Christian spirituality. Erasmus has been called by Huizinga the first modern intellectual because he tried to influence and reform the mentality of society by working within the shadow of ecclesiastical and political leaders. He epistemology, evolutionary Erasmus, Desiderius 278   278 became one of the first humanists to make efficient use of the then new medium of printing. His writings embrace various forms, including diatribe, oration, locution, comment, dialogue, and letter. After studying in Christian schools and living for a time in the monastery of Steyn near Gouda in the Netherlands, Erasmus worked for different patrons. He gained a post as secretary to the bishop of Kamerijk, during which time he wrote his first published book, the Adagia first edition 1500, a collection of annotated Latin adages. Erasmus was an adviser to the Emperor Charles V, to whom he dedicated his Institutio principii christiani 1516. After studies at the  of Paris, where he attended lectures by the humanist Faber Stapulensis, Erasmus was put in touch by his patron Lord Mountjoy with the British humanists John Colet and Thomas More. Erasmus led a restless life, residing in several European cities including London, Louvain, Basel, Freiburg, Bologna, Turin where he was awarded a doctorate of theology in 1506, and Rome. By using the means of modern philology, which led to the ideal of the bonae literarae, Erasmus tried to reform the Christian-influenced mentality of his times. Inspired by Valla’s Annotationes to the New Testament, he completed a new Latin translation of the New Testament, edited the writings of the early church fathers, especially St. Hieronymus, and wrote several commentaries on psalms. He tried to regenerate the spirit of early Christianity by laying bare its original sense against the background of scholastic interpretation. In his view, the rituals of the existing church blocked the development of an authentic Christian spirituality. Though Erasmus shared with Luther a critical approach toward the existing church, he did not side with the Reformation. His Diatribe de libero arbitrio 1524, in which he pleaded for the free will of man, was answered by Luther’s De servo arbitrio. The historically most influential books of Erasmus were Enchirion militis christiani 1503, in which he attacked hirelings and soldiers; the Encomium moriae id est Laus stultitiae 1511, a satire on modern life and the ecclesiastical pillars of society; and the sketches of human life, the Colloquia first published in 1518, often enlarged until 1553. In the small book Querela pacis 1517, he rejected the ideology of justified wars propounded by Augustine and Aquinas. Against the madness of war Erasmus appealed to the virtues of tolerance, friendliness, and gentleness. All these virtues were for him the essence of Christianity. 

Regressus: regression analysis, a part of statistical theory concerned with the analysis of data with the aim of inferring a linear functional relationship between assumed independent “regressor” variables and a dependent “response” variable. A typical example involves the dependence of crop yield on the application of fertilizer. For the most part, higher amounts of fertilizer are associated with higher yields. But typically, if crop yield is plotted vertically on a graph with the horizontal axis representing amount of fertilizer applied, the resulting points will not fall in a straight line. This can be due either to random “stochastic” fluctuations involving measurement errors, irreproducible conditions, or physical indeterminism or to failure to take into account other relevant independent variables such as amount of rainfall. In any case, from any resulting “scatter diagram,” it is possible mathematically to infer a “best-fitting” line. One method is, roughly, to find the line that minimizes the average absolute distance between a line and the data points collected. More commonly, the average of the squares of these distances is minimized this is the “least squares” method. If more than one independent variable is suspected, the theory of multiple regression, which takes into account multiple regressors, can be applied: this can help to minimize an “error term” involved in regression. Computers must be used for the complex computations typically encountered. Care must be taken in connection with the possibility that a lawlike, causal dependence is not really linear even approximately over all ranges of the regressor variables e.g., in certain ranges of amounts of application, more fertilizer is good for a plant, but too much is bad. 

reichenbach, “’philosopher,’ as we might say,” -- Grice of science and a major leader of the movement known as logical empiricism. Born in Hamburg, Reichenbach studies engineering (“if that’s something you study than learn” – Grice) for a brief time, then turned to mathematics, philosophy, and physics, which he pursued at Berlin, Munich, and Göttingen (“He kept moving in the area.”) He takes his doctorate in philosophy at Erlangen with a dissertation on conceptual aspects of probability, and a degree in mathematics and physics by state examination at Göttingen – “just in case,” he said. With Hitler’s rise to power, Reichenbach flees to Istanbul, then to “Los Angeles,” a town on the western coast of America -- where he remained until his death, “if not after” (Grice). Prior to his departure from G.y he is  professor of philosophy of science at the  of Berlin, leader of the Berlin Group of logical empiricists, and a close associate of Einstein. With Carnap Reichenbach founds “Erkenntnis,” the major journal of scientific philosophy before World War II. After a short period early in his career as a follower of Kant, Reichenbach rejects, “slightly out of the blue” (Grice),  the synthetic a priori, chiefly because of considerations arising out of Einstein’s general theory of relativity. Reichenbach remains  thereafter champion of empiricism, adhering to a probabilistic version of the verifiability theory of cognitive (“if not emotive”) meaning. Never, however, did he embrace the logical positivism of what he pompously called the “Wiener Kraus.” Ideed, he explicitly described his principal epistemological work, Experience and Prediction 8, as his refutation of logical positivism. In particular, his logical empiricism consisted in rejecting phenomenalism in favor of physicalism; he rejected phenomenalism both in embracing scientific realism and in insisting on a thoroughgoing probabilistic analysis of scientific meaning and scientific knowledge. His main works span a wide range. In Probability and Induction he advocated the frequency interpretation of probability and offered a pragmatic justification of induction. In his philosophy of space and time he defended conventionality of geometry and of simultaneity. In foundations of quantum mechanics he adopted a three-valued logic to deal with causal anomalies. He wrote major works on epistemology, logic, laws of nature, counterfactuals, and modalities. At the time of his death he had almost completed The Direction of Time, which was published posthumously. Grice cites him profusely in “Actions and events.” Refs.: Section on Reichenbach in Grice, “Actions and events.”

Roman Roamn – “Hellenism is what happened to the Grecians after they became a Roman province.” -- hellenistic philosophy: “Once the Romans defeated Greece, at Oxford we stop talking of ‘Greek’ philosophy, but ‘Hellenistic’ philosophy instead – since most Greeks were brought to Rome as slaves to teach philosophy to their children” – Grice. Vide “Roman philosophy” – “Not everybody knows all these Roman philosophers, so that’s a good thing.” – H. P. Grice. Hellenistic philosophy is the philosophical systems of the Hellenistic age 32330 B.C., although 31187 B.C. better defines it as a philosophical era, notably Epicureanism, Stoicism, and Skepticism. These all emerged in the generation after Aristotle’s death 322 B.C., and dominated philosophical debate until the first century B.C., during which there were revivals of traditional Platonism and of Aristotelianism. The age was one in which much of the eastern Mediterranean world absorbed Grecian culture was “Hellenized,” hence “Hellenistic”, and recruits to philosophy flocked from this region to Athens, which remained the center of philosophical activity until 87 B.C. Then the Roman sack of Athens drove many philosophers into exile, and neither the schools nor the styles of philosophy that had grown up there ever fully recovered. Very few philosophical writings survive intact from the period. Our knowledge of Hellenistic philosophers depends mainly on later doxography, on the Roman writers Lucretius and Cicero both mid-first century B.C., and on what we learn from the schools’ critics in later centuries, e.g. Sextus Empiricus and Plutarch. ’Skeptic’, a term not actually current before the very end of the Hellenistic age, serves as a convenient label to characterize two philosophical movements. The first is the New Academy: the school founded by Plato, the Academy, became in this period a largely dialectical one, conducting searching critiques of other schools’ doctrines without declaring any of its own, beyond perhaps the assertion however guarded that nothing could be known and the accompanying recommendation of “suspension of judgment” epoche. The nature and vivacity of Stoicism owed much to its prolonged debates with the New Academy. The founder of this Academic phase was Arcesilaus school head c.268 c.241; its most revered and influential protagonist was Carneades school head in the mid-second century; and its most prestigious voice was that of Cicero 10643 B.C., whose highly influential philosophical works were written mainly from a New Academic stance. But by the early first century B.C. the Academy was drifting back to a more doctrinal stance, and in the later part of the century it was largely eclipsed by a second “skeptic” movement, Pyrrhonism. This was founded by Aenesidemus, a pioneering skeptic despite his claim to be merely reviving the philosophy of Pyrrho, a philosophical guru of the early Hellenistic period. His neo-Pyrrhonism survives today mainly through the writings of Sextus Empiricus second century A.D., an adherent of the school who, strictly speaking, represents its post-Hellenistic phase. The Peripatos, Aristotle’s school, officially survived throughout the era, but it is not regarded as a distinctively “Hellenistic” movement. Despite the eminence of Aristotle’s first successor, Theophrastus school head 322287, it thereafter fell from prominence, its fortunes only reviving around the mid-first century B.C. It is disputed how far the other Hellenistic philosophers were even aware of Aristotle’s treatises, which should not in any case be regarded as a primary influence on them. Each school had a location in Athens to which it could draw pupils. The Epicurean school was a relatively private institution, its “Garden” outside the city walls housing a close-knit philosophical community. The Stoics took their name from the Stoa Poikile, the “Painted Colonnade” in central Athens where they gathered. The Academics were based in the Academy, a public grove just outside the city. Philosophers were public figures, a familiar sight around town. Each school’s philosophical identity was further clarified by its absolute loyalty to the name of its founder  respectively Epicurus, Zeno of Citium, and Plato  and by the polarities that developed in interschool debates. Epicureanism is diametrically opposed on most issues to Stoicism. Academic Skepticism provides another antithesis to Stoicism, not through any positions of its own it had none, but through its unflagging critical campaign against every Stoic thesis. It is often said that in this age the old Grecian political institution of the city-state had broken down, and that the Hellenistic philosophies were an answer to the resulting crisis of values. Whether or not there is any truth in this, it remains clear that moral concerns were now much less confined to the individual city-state than previously, and that at an extreme the boundaries had been pushed back to include all mankind within the scope of an individual’s moral obligations. Our “affinity” oikeiosis to all mankind is an originally Stoic doctrine that acquired increasing currency with other schools. This attitude partly reflects the weakening of national and cultural boundaries in the Hellenistic period, as also in the Roman imperial period that followed it. The three recognized divisions of philosophy were ethics, logic, and physics. In ethics, the central objective was to state and defend an account of the “end” telos, the moral goal to which all activity was subordinated: the Epicureans named pleasure, the Stoics conformity with nature. Much debate centered on the semimythical figure of the wise man, whose conduct in every conceivable circumstance was debated by all schools. Logic in its modern sense was primarily a Stoic concern, rejected as irrelevant by the Epicureans. But Hellenistic logic included epistemology, where the primary focus of interest was the “criterion of truth,” the ultimate yardstick against which all judgments could be reliably tested. Empiricism was a surprisingly uncontroversial feature of Hellenistic theories: there was little interest in the Platonic-Aristotelian idea that knowledge in the strict sense is non-sensory, and the debate between dogmatists and Skeptics was more concerned with the question whether any proposed sensory criterion was adequate. Both Stoics and Epicureans attached especial importance to prolepsis, the generic notion of a thing, held to be either innate or naturally acquired in a way that gave it a guaranteed veridical status. Physics saw an opposition between Epicurean atomism, with its denial of divine providence, and the Stoic world-continuum, imbued with divine rationality. The issue of determinism was also placed on the philosophical map: Epicurean morality depends on the denial of both physical and logical determinism, whereas Stoic morality is compatible with, indeed actually requires, the deterministic causal nexus through which providence operates. 

reid: Scots philosopher, beloved by Woozley, Grice’s friend at Oxford in the late 1930s. Adefender of common sense and critic of the theory of impressions and ideas articulated by Hume. Reid was born exactly one year before Hume, in Strachan, Scotland. A bright lad, he went to Marischal  in Aberdeen at the age of twelve, studying there with Thomas Blackwell and George Turnbull. The latter apparently had great influence on Reid. Turnbull contended that knowledge of the facts of sense and introspection may not be overturned by reasoning and that volition is the only active power known from experience. Turnbull defended common sense under the cloak of Berkeley. Reid threw off that cloak with considerable panache, but he took over the defense of common sense from Turnbull. Reid moved to a position of regent and lecturer at King’s  in Aberdeen in 1751. There he formed, with John Gregory, the Aberdeen Philosophical Society, which met fortnightly, often to discuss Hume. Reid published his Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense in 1764, and, in the same year, succeeded Adam Smith in the chair of moral philosophy at Old  in Glasgow. After 1780 he no longer lectured but devoted himself to his later works, Essays on the Intellectual Powers 1785 and Essays on the Active Powers 1788. He was highly influential in Scotland and on the Continent in the eighteenth century and, from time to time, in England and the United States thereafter. Reid thought that one of his major contributions was the refutation of Hume’s theory of impressions and ideas. Reid probably was convinced in his teens of the truth of Berkeley’s doctrine that what the mind is immediately aware of is always some idea, but his later study of Hume’s Treatise convinced him that, contrary to Berkeley, it was impossible to reconcile this doctrine, the theory of ideas, with common sense. Hume had rigorously developed the theory, Reid said, and drew forth the conclusions. These, Reid averred, were absurd. They included the denial of our knowledge of body and mind, and, even more strikingly, of our conceptions of these things. The reason Reid thought that Hume’s theory of ideas led to these conclusions was that for Hume, ideas were faded impressions of sense, hence, sensations. No sensation is like a quality of a material thing, let alone like the object that has the quality. Consider movement. Movement is a quality of an object wherein the object changes from one place to another, but the visual sensation that arises in us is not the change of place of an object, it is an activity of mind. No two things could, in fact, be more unalike. If what is before the mind is always some sensation, whether vivacious or faded, we should never obtain the conception of something other than a sensation. Hence, we could never even conceive of material objects and their qualities. Even worse, we could not conceive of our own minds, for they are not sensations either, and only sensations are immediately before the mind, according to the theory of ideas. Finally, and even more absurdly, we could not conceive of past sensations or anything that does not now exist. For all that is immediately before the mind is sensations that exist presently. Thus, we could not even conceive of qualities, bodies, minds, and things that do not now exist. But this is absurd, since it is obvious that we do think of all these things and even of things that have never existed. The solution, Reid suggested, is to abandon the theory of ideas and seek a better one. Many have thought Reid was unfair to Hume and misinterpreted him. Reid’s Inquiry was presented to Hume by Dr. Blair in manuscript form, however, and in reply Hume does not at all suggest that he has been misinterpreted or handled unfairly. Whatever the merits of Reid’s criticism of Hume, it was the study of the consequences of Hume’s philosophy that accounts for Reid’s central doctrine of the human faculties and their first principles. Faculties are innate powers, among them the powers of conception and conviction. Reid’s strategy in reply to Hume is to build a nativist theory of conception on the failure of Hume’s theory of ideas. Where the theory of ideas, the doctrine of impressions and ideas, fails to account for our conception of something, of qualities, bodies, minds, past things, nonexistent things, Reid hypothesizes that our conceptions originate from a faculty of the mind, i.e., from an innate power of conception. This line of argument reflects Reid’s respect for Hume, whom he calls the greatest metaphysician of the age, because Hume drew forth the consequences of a theory of conception, which we might call associationism, according to which all our conceptions result from associating sensations. Where the associationism of Hume failed, Reid hypothesized that conceptions arise from innate powers of conception that manifest themselves in accordance with original first principles of the mind. The resulting hypotheses were not treated as a priori necessities but as empirical hypotheses. Reid notes, therefore, that there are marks by which we can discern the operation of an innate first principle, which include the early appearance of the operation, its universality in mankind, and its irresistibility. The operations of the mind that yield our conceptions of qualities, bodies, and minds all bear these marks, Reid contends, and that warrants the conclusion that they manifest first principles. It should be noted that Reid conjectured that nature would be frugal in the implantation of innate powers, supplying us with no more than necessary to produce the conceptions we manifest. Reid is, consequently, a parsimonious empiricist in the development of his nativist psychology. Reid developed his theory of perception in great detail and his development led, surprisingly, to his articulation of non-Euclidean geometry. Indeed, while Kant was erroneously postulating the a priori necessity of Euclidean space, Reid was developing non-Euclidean geometry to account for the empirical features of visual space. Reid’s theory of perception is an example of his empiricism. In the Inquiry, he says that sensations, which are operations of the mind, and impressions on the organs of sense, which are material, produce our conceptions of primary and secondary qualities. Sensations produce our original conceptions of secondary qualities as the causes of those sensations. They are signs that suggest the existence of the qualities. A sensation of smell suggests the existence of a quality in the object that causes the sensation, though the character of the cause is otherwise unknown. Thus, our original conception of secondary qualities is a relative conception of some unknown cause of a sensation. Our conception of primary qualities differs not, as Locke suggested, because of some resemblance between the sensation and the quality for, as Berkeley noted, there is no resemblance between a sensation and quality, but because our original conceptions of primary qualities are clear and distinct. The sensation is a sign that suggests a definite conception of the primary quality, e.g. a definite conception of the movement of the object, rather than a mere conception of something, we know not what, that gives rise to the sensation. These conceptions of qualities signified by sensations result from the operations of principles of our natural constitution. These signs, which suggest the conception of qualities, also suggest a conception of some object that has them. This conception of the object is also relative, in that it is simply a conception of a subject of the qualities. In the case of physical qualities, the conception of the object is a conception of a material object. Though sensations, which are activities of the mind, suggest the existence of qualities, they are not the only signs of sense perception. Some impressions on the organs of sense, the latter being material, also give rise to conceptions of qualities, especially to our conception of visual figure, the seen shape of the object. But Reid can discern no sensation of shape. There are, of course, sensations of color, but he is convinced from the experience of those who have cataracts and see color but not shape that the sensations of color are insufficient to suggest our conceptions of visual figure. His detailed account of vision and especially of the seeing of visual figure leads him to one of his most brilliant moments. He asks what sort of data do we receive upon the eye and answers that the data must be received at the round surface of the eyeball and processed within. Thus, visual space is a projection in three dimensions of the information received on the round surface of the eye, and the geometry of this space is a non-Euclidean geometry of curved space. Reid goes on to derive the properties of the space quite correctly, e.g., in concluding that the angles of a triangle will sum to a figure greater than 180 degrees and thereby violate the parallels postulate. Thus Reid discovered that a non-Euclidean geometry was satisfiable and, indeed, insisted that it accurately described the space of vision not, however, the space of touch, which he thought was Euclidean. From the standpoint of his theory of perceptual signs, the example of visual figure helps to clarify his doctrine of the signs of perception. We do not perceive signs and infer what they signify. This inference, Reid was convinced by Hume, would lack the support of reasoning, and Reid concluded that reasoning was, in this case, superfluous. The information received on the surface of the eye produces our conceptions of visual figure immediately. Indeed, these signs pass unnoticed as they give rise to the conception of visual figure in the mind. The relation of sensory signs to the external things they signify originally is effected by a first principle of the mind without the use of reason. The first principles that yield our conceptions of qualities and objects yield convictions of the existence of these things at the same time. A question naturally arises as to the evidence of these convictions. First principles yield the convictions along with the conceptions, but do we have evidence of the existence of the qualities and objects we are convinced exist? We have the evidence of our senses, of our natural faculties, and that is all the evidence possible here. Reid’s point is that the convictions in questions resulting from the original principles of our faculties are immediately justified. Our faculties are, however, all fallible, so the justification that our original convictions possess may be refuted. We can now better understand Reid’s reply to Hume. To account for our convictions of the existence of body, we must abandon Hume’s theory of ideas, which cannot supply even the conception of body. We must discover both the original first principles that yield the conception and conviction of objects and their qualities, and first principles to account for our convictions of the past, of other thinking beings, and of morals. Just as there are first principles of perception that yield convictions of the existence of presently existing objects, so there are first principles of memory that yield the convictions of the existence of past things, principles of testimony that yield the convictions of the thoughts of others, and principles of morals that yield convictions of our obligations. Reid’s defense of a moral faculty alongside the faculties of perception and memory is striking. The moral faculty yields conceptions of the justice and injustice of an action in response to our conception of that action. Reid shrewdly notes that different people may conceive of the same action in different ways. I may conceive of giving some money as an action of gratitude, while you may consider it squandering money. How we conceive of an action depends on our moral education, but the response of our moral faculty to an action conceived in a specific way is original and the same in all who have the faculty. Hence differences in moral judgment are due, not to principles of the moral faculty, but to differences in how we conceive of our actions. This doctrine of a moral faculty again provides a counterpoint to the moral philosophy of Hume, for, according Reid, Thomas Reid, Thomas 785    785 to Reid, judgments of justice and injustice pertaining to all matters, including promises, contracts, and property, arise from our natural faculties and do not depend on anything artificial. Reid’s strategy for defending common sense is clear enough. He thinks that Hume showed that we cannot arrive at our convictions of external objects, of past events, of the thoughts of others, of morals, or, for that matter, of our own minds, from reasoning about impressions and ideas. Since those convictions are a fact, philosophy must account for them in the only way that remains, by the hypothesis of innate faculties that yield them. But do we have any evidence for these convictions? Evidence, Reid says, is the ground of belief, and our evidence is that of our faculties. Might our faculties deceive us? Reid answers that it is a first principle of our faculties that they are not fallacious. Why should we assume that our faculties are not fallacious? First, the belief is irresistible. However we wage war with first principles, the principles of common sense, they prevail in daily life. There we trust our faculties whether we choose to or not. Second, all philosophy depends on the assumption that our faculties are not fallacious. Here Reid employs an ad hominem argument against Hume, but one with philosophical force. Reid says that, in response to a total skeptic who decides to trust none of his faculties, he puts his hand over his mouth in silence. But Hume trusted reason and consciousness, and therefore is guilty of pragmatic inconsistency in calling the other faculties into doubt. They come from the same shop, Reid says, and he who calls one into doubt has no right to trust the others. All our faculties are fallible, and, therefore, we must, to avoid arbitrary favoritism, trust them all at the outset or trust none. The first principles of our faculties are trustworthy. They not only account for our convictions, but are the ground and evidence of those convictions. This nativism is the original engine of justification. Reid’s theory of original perceptions is supplemented by a theory of acquired perceptions, those which incorporate the effects of habit and association, such as the perception of a passing coach. He distinguishes acquired perceptions from effects of reasoning. The most important way our original perceptions must be supplemented is by general conceptions. These result from a process whereby our attention is directed to some individual quality, e.g., the whiteness of a piece of paper, which he calls abstraction, and a further process of generalizing from the individual quality to the general conception of the universal whiteness shared by many individuals. Reid is a sophisticated nominalist; he says that the only things that exist are individual, but he includes individual qualities as well as individual objects. The reason is that individual qualities obviously exist and are needed as the basis of generalization. To generalize from an individual we must have some conception of what it is like, and this conception cannot be general, on pain of circularity or regress, but must be a conception of an individual quality, e.g., the whiteness of this paper, which it uniquely possesses. Universals, though predicated of objects to articulate our knowledge, do not exist. We can think of universals, just as we can think of centaurs, but though they are the objects of thought and predicated of individuals that exist, they do not themselves exist. Generalization is not driven by ontology but by utility. It is we and not nature that sort things into kinds in ways that are useful to us. This leads to a division-of-labor theory of meaning because general conceptions are the meanings of general words. Thus, in those domains in which there are experts, in science or the law, we defer to the experts concerning the general conceptions that are the most useful in the area in question. Reid’s theory of the intellectual powers, summarized briefly above, is supplemented by his theory of our active powers, those that lead to actions. His theory of the active powers includes a theory of the principles of actions. These include animal principles that operate without understanding, but the most salient and philosophically important part of Reid’s theory of the active powers is his theory of the rational principles of action, which involve understanding and the will. These rational principles are those in which we have a conception of the action to be performed and will its performance. Action thus involves an act of will or volition, but volitions as Reid conceived of them are not the esoteric inventions of philosophy but, instead, the commonplace activities of deciding and resolving to act. Reid is a libertarian and maintains that our liberty or freedom refutes the principle of necessity or determinism. Freedom requires the power to will the action and also the power not to will it. The principle of necessity tells us that our action was necessitated and, therefore, that it was not in our power not to have willed as we did. It is not sufficient for freedom, as Hume suggested, that we act as we will. We must also have the Reid, Thomas Reid, Thomas 786    786 power to determine what we will. The reason is that willing is the means to the end of action, and he who lacks power over the means lacks power over the end. This doctrine of the active power over the determinations of our will is founded on the central principle of Reid’s theory of the active powers, the principle of agent causation. The doctrine of acts of the will or volitions does not lead to a regress, as critics allege, because my act of will is an exercise of the most basic kind of causality, the efficient causality of an agent. I am the efficient cause of my acts of will. My act of will need not be caused by an antecedent act of will because my act of will is the result of my exercise of my causal power. This fact also refutes an objection to the doctrine of liberty  that if my action is not necessitated, then it is fortuitous. My free actions are caused, not fortuitous, though they are not necessitated, because they are caused by me. How, one might inquire, do we know that we are free? The doubt that we are free is like other skeptical doubts, and receives a similar reply, namely, that the conviction of our freedom is a natural and original conviction arising from our faculties. It occurs prior to instruction and it is irresistible in practical life. Any person with two identical coins usable to pay for some item must be convinced that she can pay with the one or the other; and, unlike the ass of Buridan, she readily exercises her power to will the one or the other. The conviction of freedom is an original one, not the invention of philosophy, and it arises from the first principles of our natural faculties, which are trustworthy and not fallacious. The first principles of our faculties hang together like links in a chain, and one must either raise up the whole or the links prove useless. Together, they are the foundation of true philosophy, science, and practical life, and without them we shall lead ourselves into the coalpit of skepticism and despair. 

reimarus: G. philosopher, born in Hamburg and educated in philosophy at Jena. For most of his life he taught foreignl languages at a high school in Hamburg (“anything but Deutsche!”). The most important writings he published were a treatise on natural religion, Abhandlungen von den vornehmsten Wahrheiten der natürlichen Religion,  a textbook on semantics, which he pretentiously called “Vernunftlehre,”  and an interesting work on instincts in animals, “Allgemeine Betrachtungen über die Triebe der Tiere,” “which Strawson thought was about deer!” – Grice.  However, Reimarus is  best known for his Apologie oder Schutzschrift für die vernünftigen Verehrer Gottes.” In it, Reimarus reverses his stance on natural theology and openly advocates a deism in the British tradition. The controversy created by its publication had a profound impact on the further development of G. theology. Though Reimarus always remained basically a follower of Wolff, he is often quite critical of Wolffian rationalism in his discussion of semantics and philosophical psychology. 

Reinhold, Karl Leonhard 17431819, Austrian philosopher who was both a popularizer and a critic of Kant. He was the first occupant of the chair of critical philosophy established at the  of Jena in 1787. His Briefe über die Kantische Philosophie 1786/87 helped to popularize Kantianism. Reinhold also proclaimed the need for a more “scientific” presentation of the critical philosophy, in the form of a rigorously deductive system in which everything is derivable from a single first principle “the principle of consciousness”. He tried to satisfy this need with Elementarphilosophie “Elementary Philosophy” or “Philosophy of the Elements”, expounded in his Versuch einer neuen Theorie des menschlichen Vorstellungsvermögens “Attempt at a New Theory of the Human Faculty of Representation,” 1789, Beyträge zur Berichtigung bisheriger Missverständnisse der Philosophen I “Contributions to the Correction of the Prevailing Misunderstandings of Philosophers,” 1790, and Ueber das Fundament des philosophischen Wissens “On the Foundation of Philosophical Knowledge,” 1791. His criticism of the duality of Kant’s starting point and of the ad hoc character of his deductions contributed to the demand for a more coherent exposition of transcendental idealism, while his strategy for accomplishing this task stimulated others above all,
Fichte to seek an even more “fundamental” first principle for philosophy. Reinhold later became an enthusiastic adherent, first of Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre and then of Bardili’s “rational realism,” before finally adopting a novel “linguistic” approach to philosophical problems. 

res: “No doubt the most important expression in the philosophical vocabulary – nobody knows what it means!” – Grice. reism, also called concretism, the theory that the basic entities are concrete objects. Reism differs from nominalism in that the problem of universals is not its only motivation and often not the principal motivation for the theory. Three types of reism can be distinguished. 1 Brentano held that every object is a concrete or individual thing. He said that substances, aggregates of substances, parts of substances, and individual properties of substances are the only things that exist. There is no such thing as the existence or being of an object; and there are no non-existent objects. One consequence of this doctrine is that the object of thought what the thought is about is always an individual object and not a proposition. For example, the thought that this paper is white is about this paper and not about the proposition that this paper is white. Meinong attacked Brentano’s concretism and argued that thoughts are about “objectives,” not objects. 2 Kotarbigski, who coined the term ‘reism’, holds as a basic principle that only concrete objects exist. Although things may be hard or soft, red or blue, there is no such thing as hardness, softness, redness, or blueness. Sentences that contain abstract words are either strictly meaningless or can be paraphrased into sentences that do not contain any abstract words. Kotarbinski is both a nominalist and a materialist. Brentano was a nominalist and a dualist. 3 Thomas Garrigue Masaryk’s concretism is quite different from the first two. For him, concretism is the theory that all of a person’s cognitive faculties participate in every instance of knowing: reason, senses, emotion, and will. 

relatum – Grice: “One should carefully distinguish between the prior ‘relatum’ and its formative, ‘relatIVUM.’” -- RELATUM -- referentially transparent. An occurrence of a singular term t in a sentence ‘. . . t . . .’ is referentially transparent or purely referential if and only if the truth-value of ‘. . . t . . .’ depends on whether the referent of t satisfies the open sentence ‘. . . x . . .’; the satisfaction of ‘. . . x . . .’ by the referent of t would guarantee the truth of ‘. . . t . . .’, and failure of this individual to satisfy ‘. . . x . . .’ would guarantee that ‘. . . t . . .’ was not true. ‘Boston is a city’ is true if and only if the referent of ‘Boston’ satisfies the open sentence ‘x is a city’, so the occurrence of ‘Boston’ is referentially transparent. But in ‘The expression “Boston” has six letters’, the length of the word within the quotes, not the features of the city Boston, determines the truth-value of the sentence, so the occurrence is not referentially transparent. According to a Fregean theory of meaning, the reference of any complex expression that is a meaningful unit is a function of the referents of its parts. Within this context, an occurrence of a referential term t in a meaningful expression ‘. . . t . . .’ is referentially transparent or purely referential if and only if t contributes its referent to the reference of ‘. . . t . . .’. The expression ‘the area around Boston’ refers to the particular area it does because of the referent of ‘Boston’ and the reference or extension of the function expressed by ‘the area around x’. An occurrence of a referential term t in a meaningful expression ‘. . . t . . .’ is referentially opaque if and only if it is not referentially transparent. Thus, if t has a referentially opaque occurrence in a sentence ‘. . . t . . .’, then the truth-value of ‘. . . t . . .’ depends on something reduction, phenomenological referentially transparent 780    780 other than whether the referent of t satisfies ‘. . . x . . .’. Although these definitions apply to occurrences of referential terms, the terms ‘referentially opaque’ and ‘referentially transparent’ are used primarily to classify linguistic contexts for terms as referentially opaque contexts. If t occurs purely referentially in S but not in CS, then C   is a referentially opaque context. But we must qualify this: C  is a referentially opaque context for that occurrence of t in S. It would not follow without further argument that C  is a referentially opaque context for other occurrences of terms in sentences that could be placed into C . Contexts of quotation, propositional attitude, and modality have been widely noted for their potential to produce referential opacity. Consider: 1 John believes that the number of planets is less than eight. 2 John believes that nine is less than eight. If 1 is true but 2 is not, then either ‘the number of planets’ or ‘nine’ has an occurrence that is not purely referential, because the sentences would differ in truth-value even though the expressions are co-referential. But within the sentences: 3 The number of planets is less than eight. 4 Nine is less than eight. the expressions appear to have purely referential occurrence. In 3 and 4, the truth-value of the sentence as a whole depends on whether the referent of ‘The number of planets’ and ‘Nine’ satisfies ‘x is less than eight’. Because the occurrences in 3 and 4 are purely referential but those in 1 and 2 are not, the context ‘John believes that  ’ is a referentially opaque context for the relevant occurrence of at least one of the two singular terms. Some argue that the occurrence of ‘nine’ in 2 is purely referential because the truth-value of the sentence as a whole depends on whether the referent, nine, satisfies the open sentence ‘John believes that x is less than eight’. Saying so requires that we make sense of the concept of satisfaction for such sentences belief sentences and others and that we show that the concept of satisfaction applies in this way in the case at hand sentence 2. There is controversy about whether these things can be done. In 1, on the other hand, the truth-value is not determined by whether nine the referent of ‘the number of planets’ satisfies the open sentence, so that occurrence is not purely referential. Modal contexts raise similar questions. 5 Necessarily, nine is odd. 6 Necessarily, the number of planets is odd. If 5 is true but 6 is not, then at least one of the expressions does not have a purely referential occurrence, even though both appear to be purely referential in the non-modal sentence that appears in the context ‘Necessarily, ———’. Thus the context is referentially opaque for the occurrence of at least one of these terms. On an alternative approach, genuinely singular terms always occur referentially, and ‘the number of planets’ is not a genuinely singular term. Russell’s theory of definite descriptions, e.g., provides an alternative semantic analysis for sentences involving definite descriptions. This would enable us to say that even simple sentences like 3 and 4 differ considerably in syntactic and semantic structure, so that the similarity that suggests the problem, the seemingly similar occurrences of co-referential terms, is merely apparent. “A formation out of referro,” -- a two-or-more-place property e.g., loves or between, or the extension of such a property. In set theory, a relation is any set of ordered pairs or triplets, etc., but these are reducible to pairs. For simplicity, the formal exposition here uses the language of set theory, although an intensional property-theoretic view is later assumed. The terms of a relation R are the members of the pairs constituting R, the items that R relates. The collection D of all first terms of pairs in R is the domain of R; any collection with D as a subcollection may also be so called. Similarly, the second terms of these pairs make up or are a subcollection of the range counterdomain or converse domain of R. One usually works within a set U such that R is a subset of the Cartesian product U$U the set of all ordered pairs on U. Relations can be: 1 reflexive or exhibit reflexivity: for all a, aRa. That is, a reflexive relation is one that, like identity, each thing bears to itself. Examples: a weighs as much as b; or the universal relation, i.e., the relation R such that for all a and b, aRb. 2 symmetrical or exhibit symmetry: for all a and b, aRb P bRa. In a symmetrical relation, the order of the terms is reversible. Examples: a is a sibling of b; a and b have a common divisor. Also symmetrical is the null relation, under which no object is related to anything. 3 transitive or exhibit transitivity: for all a, b, and c, aRb & bRc P aRc. Transitive relations carry across a middle term. Examples: a is less than b; a is an ancestor of b. Thus, if a is less than b and b is less than c, a is less than c: less than has carried across the middle term, b. 4 antisymmetrical: for all a and b, aRb & bRa P a % b. 5 trichotomous, connected, or total trichotomy: for all a and b, aRb 7 bRa 7 a % b. 6 asymmetrical: aRb & bRa holds for no a and b. 7 functional: for all a, b, and c, aRb & aRc P b % c. In a functional relation which may also be called a function, each first term uniquely determines a second term. R is non-reflexive if it is not reflexive, i.e., if the condition 1 fails for at least one object a. R is non-symmetric if 2 fails for at least one pair of objects a, b. Analogously for non-transitive. R is irreflexive aliorelative if 1 holds for no object a and intransitive if 3 holds for no objects a, b, and c. Thus understands is non-reflexive since some things do not understand themselves, but not irreflexive, since some things do; loves is nonsymmetric but not asymmetrical; and being a cousin of is non-transitive but not intransitive, as being mother of is. 13 define an equivalence relation e.g., the identity relation among numbers or the relation of being the same age as among people. A class of objects bearing an equivalence relation R to each other is an equivalence class under R. 1, 3, and 4 define a partial order; 3, 5, and 6 a linear order. Similar properties define other important classifications, such as lattice and Boolean algebra. The converse of a relation R is the set of all pairs b, a such that aRb; the comreism relation 788    788 plement of R is the set of all pairs a, b such that aRb i.e. aRb does not hold. A more complex example will show the power of a relational vocabulary. The ancestral of R is the set of all a, b such that either aRb or there are finitely many cI , c2, c3, . . . , cn such that aRcI and c1Rc2 and c2Rc3 and . . . and cnRb. Frege introduced the ancestral in his theory of number: the natural numbers are exactly those objects bearing the ancestral of the successor-of relation to zero. Equivalently, they are the intersection of all sets that contain zero and are closed under the successor relation. This is formalizable in second-order logic. Frege’s idea has many applications. E.g., assume a set U, relation R on U, and property F. An element a of U is hereditarily F with respect to R if a is F and any object b which bears the ancestral of R to a is also F. Hence F is here said to be a hereditary property, and the set a is hereditarily finite with respect to the membership relation if a is finite, its members are, as are the members of its members, etc. The hereditarily finite sets or the sets hereditarily of cardinality ‹ k for any inaccessible k are an important subuniverse of the universe of sets. Philosophical discussions of relations typically involve relations as special cases of properties or sets. Thus nominalists and Platonists disagree over the reality of relations, since they disagree about properties in general. Similarly, one important connection is to formal semantics, where relations are customarily taken as the denotations of relational predicates. Disputes about the notion of essence are also pertinent. One says that a bears an internal relation, R, to b provided a’s standing in R to b is an essential property of a; otherwise a bears an external relation to b. If the essentialaccidental distinction is accepted, then a thing’s essential properties will seem to include certain of its relations to other things, so that we must admit internal relations. Consider a point in space, which has no identity apart from its place in a certain system. Similarly for a number. Or consider my hand, which would perhaps not be the same object if it had not developed as part of my body. If it is true that I could not have had other parents  that possible persons similar to me but with distinct parents would not really be me  then I, too, am internally related to other things, namely my parents. Similar arguments would generate numerous internal relations for organisms, artifacts, and natural objects in general. Internal relations will also seem to exist among properties and relations themselves. Roundness is essentially a kind of shape, and the relation larger than is essentially the converse of the relation smaller than. In like usage, a relation between a and b is intrinsic if it depends just on how a and b are; extrinsic if they have it in virtue of their relation to other things. Thus, higher-than intrinsically relates the Alps to the Appalachians. That I prefer viewing the former to the latter establishes an extrinsic relation between the mountain ranges. Note that this distinction is obscure as is internal-external. One could argue that the Alps are higher than the Appalachians only in virtue of the relation of each to something further, such as space, light rays, or measuring rods. Another issue specific to the theory of relations is whether relations are real, given that properties do exist. That is, someone might reject nominalism only to the extent of admitting one-place properties. Although such doctrines have some historical importance in, e.g., Plato and Bradley, they have disappeared. Since relations are indispensable to modern logic and semantics, their inferiority to one-place properties can no longer be seriously entertained. Hence relations now have little independent significance in philosophy. 

Analysandum/analysans, definiens/definiendum, implicans/implicaturum

relational logic, the formal study of the properties of and operations on binary relations that was initiated by Peirce between 1870 and 2. Thus, in relational logic, one might examine the formal properties of special kinds of relations, such as transitive relations, or asymmetrical ones, or orderings of certain types. Or the focus might be on various operations, such as that of forming the converse or relative product. Formal deductive systems used in such studies are generally known as calculi of relations. 

relativum-absolutum distinction, the: “No, we don’t mean Whorft, less so Sapir!” – Grice. relativism, the denial that there are certain kinds of universal truths. There are two main types, cognitive and ethical. Cognitive relativism holds that there are no universal truths about the world: the world has no intrinsic characteristics, there are just different ways of interpreting it. The Grecian Sophist Protagoras, the first person on record to hold such a view, said, “Man is the measure of all things; of things that are that they are, and of things that are not that they are not.” Goodman, Putnam, and Rorty are contemporary philosophers who have held versions of relativism. Rorty says, e.g., that “ ‘objective truth’ is no more and no less than the best idea we currently have about how to explain what is going on.” Critics of cognitive relativism contend that it is self-referentially incoherent, since it presents its statements as universally true, rather than simply relatively so. Ethical relativism is the theory that there are no universally valid moral principles: all moral principles are valid relative to culture or individual choice. There are two subtypes: conventionalism, which holds that moral principles are valid relative to the conventions of a given culture or society; and subjectivism, which maintains that individual choices are what determine the validity of a moral principle. Its motto is, Morality lies in the eyes of the beholder. As Ernest Hemingway wrote, “So far, about morals, I know only that what is moral is what you feel good after and what is immoral is what you feel bad after.” Conventionalist ethical relativism consists of two theses: a diversity thesis, which specifies that what is considered morally right and wrong varies from society to society, so that there are no moral principles accepted by all societies; and a dependency thesis, which specifies that all moral principles derive their validity from cultural acceptance. From these two ideas relativists conclude that there are no universally valid moral principles applying everywhere and at all times. The first thesis, the diversity thesis, or what may simply be called cultural relativism, is anthropological; it registers the fact that moral rules differ from society to society. Although both ethical relativists and non-relativists typically accept cultural relativism, it is often confused with the normative thesis of ethical relativism. The opposite of ethical relativism is ethical objectivism, which asserts that although cultures may differ in their moral principles, some moral principles have universal validity. Even if, e.g., a culture does not recognize a duty to refrain from gratuitous harm, that principle is valid and the culture should adhere to it. There are two types of ethical objectivism, strong and weak. Strong objectivism, sometimes called absolutism, holds that there is one true moral system with specific moral rules. The ethics of ancient Israel in the Old Testament with its hundreds of laws exemplifies absolutism. Weak objectivism holds that there is a core morality, a determinate set of principles that are universally valid usually including prohibitions against killing the innocent, stealing, breaking of promises, and lying. But weak objectivism accepts an indeterminate area where relativism is legitimate, e.g., rules regarding sexual mores and regulations of property. Both types of objectivism recognize what might be called application relativism, the endeavor to apply moral rules where there is a conflict between rules or where rules can be applied in different ways. For example, the ancient Callactians ate their deceased parents but eschewed the impersonal practice of burying them as disrespectful, whereas contemporary society has the opposite attitudes about the care of dead relatives; but both practices exemplify the same principle of the respect for the dead. According to objectivism, cultures or forms of life can fail to exemplify an adequate moral community in at least three ways: 1 the people are insufficiently intelligent to put constitutive principles in order; 2 they are under considerable stress so that it becomes too burdensome to live by moral principles; and 3 a combination of 1 and 2. Ethical relativism is sometimes confused with ethical skepticism, the view that we cannot know whether there are any valid moral principles. Ethical nihilism holds that there are no valid moral principles. J. L. Mackie’s error theory is a version of this view. Mackie held that while we all believe some moral principles to be true, there are compelling arguments to the contrary. Ethical objectivism must be distinguished from moral realism, the view that valid moral principles are true, independently of human choice. Objectivism may be a form of ethical constructivism, typified by Rawls, whereby objective principles are simply those that impartial human beings would choose behind the veil of ignorance. That is, the principles are not truly independent of hypothetical human choices, but are constructs from those choices.   relativum-absolutum distinction, the: relativity, a term applied to Einstein’s theories of electrodynamics special relativity, 5 and gravitation general relativity, 6 because both hold that certain physical quantities, formerly considered objective, are actually “relative to” the state of motion of the observer. They are called “special” and “general” because, in special relativity, electrodynamical laws determine a restricted class of kinematical reference frames, the “inertial frames”; in general relativity, the very distinction between inertial frames and others becomes a relative distinction. Special relativity. Classical mechanics makes no distinction between uniform motion and rest: not velocity, but acceleration is physically detectable, and so different states of uniform motion are physically equivalent. But classical electrodynamics describes light as wave motion with a constant velocity through a medium, the “ether.” It follows that the measured velocity of light should depend on the motion of the observer relative to the medium. When interferometer experiments suggested that the velocity of light is independent of the motion of the source, H. A. Lorentz proposed that objects in motion contract in the direction of motion through the ether while their local time “dilates”, and that this effect masks the difference in the velocity of light. Einstein, however, associated the interferometry results with many other indications that the theoretical distinction between uniform motion and rest in the ether lacks empirical content. He therefore postulated that, in electrodynamics as in mechanics, all states of uniform motion are equivalent. To explain the apparent paradox that observers with different velocities can agree on the velocity of light, he criticized the idea of an “absolute” or frame-independent measure of simultaneity: simultaneity of distant events can only be established by some kind of signaling, but experiment suggested that light is the only signal with an invariant velocity, and observers in relative motion who determine simultaneity with light signals obtain different results. Furthermore, since objective measurement of time and length presupposes absolute simultaneity, observers in relative motion will also disagree on time and length. So Lorentz’s contraction and dilatation are not physical effects, but consequences of the relativity of simultaneity, length, and time, to the motion of the observer. But this relativity follows from the invariance of the laws of electrodynamics, and the invariant content of the theory is expressed geometrically in Minkowski spacetime. Logical empiricists took the theory as an illustration of how epistemological analysis of a concept time could eliminate empirically superfluous notions absolute simultaneity. General relativity. Special relativity made the velocity of light a limit for all causal processes and required revision of Newton’s theory of gravity as an instantaneous action at a distance. General relativity incorporates gravity into the geometry of space-time: instead of acting directly on one another, masses induce curvature in space-time. Thus the paths of falling bodies represent not forced deviations from the straight paths of a flat space-time, but “straightest” paths in a curved space-time. While space-time is “locally” Minkowskian, its global structure depends on mass-energy distribution. The insight behind this theory is the equivalence of gravitational and inertial mass: since a given gravitational field affects all bodies equally, weight is indistinguishable from the inertial force of acceleration; freefall motion is indistinguishable from inertial motion. This suggests that the Newtonian decomposition of free fall into inertial and accelerated components is arbitrary, and that the freefall path itself is the invariant basis for the structure of space-time. A philosophical motive for the general theory was to extend the relativity of motion. Einstein saw special relativity’s restricted class of equivalent reference frames as an “epistemological defect,” and he sought laws that would apply to any frame. His inspiration was Mach’s criticism of the Newtonian distinction between “absolute” rotation and rotation relative to observable bodies like the “fixed stars.” Einstein formulated Mach’s criticism as a fundamental principle: since only relative motions are observable, local inertial effects should be explained by the cosmic distribution of masses and by motion relative to them. Thus not only velocity and rest, but motion in general would be relative. Einstein hoped to effect this generalization by eliminating the distinction between inertial frames and freely falling frames. Because free fall remains a privileged state of motion, however, non-gravitational acceleration remains detectable, and absolute rotation remains distinct from relative rotation. Einstein also thought that relativity of motion would result from the general covariance coordinate-independence of his theory  i.e., that general equivalence of coordinate systems meant general equivalence of states of motion. It is now clear, however, that general covariance is a mathematical property of physical theories without direct implications about motion. So general relativity does not “generalize” the relativity of motion as Einstein intended. Its great accomplishments are the unification of gravity and geometry and the generalization of special relativity to space-times of arbitrary curvature, which has made possible the modern investigation of cosmological structure. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “G. R. Grice, M. Hollis, and Norfolkian relativism.”

relevans: “Hardly in the vocabulary of Cartesio!” – Grice. relevance logic, any of a range of logics and philosophies of logic united by their insistence that the premises of a valid inference must be relevant to the conclusion. Standard, or classical, logic contains inferences that break this requirement, e.g., the spread law, that from a contradiction any proposition whatsoever follows. Relevance logic had its genesis in a system of strenge Implikation published by Wilhelm Ackermann in 6. Ackermann’s idea for rejecting irrelevance was taken up and developed by Alan Anderson and Nuel Belnap in a series of papers between 9 and Anderson’s death in 4. The first main summaries of these researches appeared under their names, and those of many collaborators, in Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity vol. 1, 5; vol. 2, 2. By the time of Anderson’s death, a substantial research effort into relevance logic was under way, and it has continued. Besides the rather vague unity of the idea of relevance between premises and conclusion, there is a technical criterion often used to mark out relevance logic, introduced by Belnap in 0, and applicable really only to propositional logics the main focus of concern to date: a necessary condition of relevance is that premises and conclusion should share a propositional variable. Early attention was focused on systems E of entailment and T of ticket entailment. Both are subsystems of C. I. Lewis’s system S4 of strict implication and of classical truth-functional logic i.e., consequences in E and T in ‘P’ are consequences in S4 in ‘ ’ and in classical logic in ‘/’. Besides rejection of the spread law, probably the most notorious inference that is rejected is disjunctive syllogism DS for extensional disjunction which is equivalent to detachment for material implication: A 7 B,ÝA , B. The reason is immediate, given acceptance of Simplification and Addition: Simplification takes us from A & ÝA to each conjunct, and Addition turns the first conjunct into A 7 B. Unless DS were rejected, the spread law would follow. Since the late 0s, attention has shifted to the system R of relevant implication, which adds permutation to E, to mingle systems which extend E and R by the mingle law A P A P A, and to contraction-free logics, which additionally reject contraction, in one form reading A P A P B P A P B. R minus contraction RW differs from linear logic, much studied recently in computer science, only by accepting the distribution of ‘&’ over ‘7’, which the latter rejects. Like linear logic, relevance logic contains both truth-functional and non-truth-functional connectives. Unlike linear logic, however, R, E, and T are undecidable unusual among propositional logics. This result was obtained only in 4. In the early 0s, relevance logics were given possible-worlds semantics by several authors working independently. They also have axiomatic, natural deduction, and sequent or consecution formulations. One technical result that has attracted attention has been the demonstration that, although relevance logics reject DS, they all accept Ackermann’s rule Gamma: that if A 7 B and ÝA are theses, so is B. A recent result occasioning much surprise was that relevant arithmetic consisting of Peano’s postulates on the base of quantified R does not admit Gamma. Refs.: “’Be relevant’—as a conversational maxim under the category of relation.” Grice, “Strawson’s Principle of Relevance – where did he take it from?”, H. P. Grice, “Nowell-Smith on conversational relevance, and why he left Oxford.” Luigi Rossi, PhD dissertataion on P. H. Nowell-Smith’s conversational relevance. P. H. Nowell-Smith, “Grice et moi.” --. H. P. Grice, “Strawson’s relevance, Urmson’s appositeness, and my helpfulness! Post-war Oxford pragmatics!”

reliabile, the, n. neuter. -- reliabilism, a type of theory in epistemology that holds that what qualifies a belief as knowledge or as epistemically justified is its *reliable* linkage to the truth. Philosophers usually motivate reliabilism with an analogy between a thermometer that reliably indicates the temperature and a belief that reliably indicates the truth. A belief qualifies as knowledge,  if there is a lawlike connection in nature that guarantees that the belief is true. A cousin of the nomic sufficiency account is the counterfactual approach, proposed by Dretske, Goldman, and Nozick. A typical formulation of this approach says that a belief qualifies relativity, general reliabilism 792    792 as knowledge if the belief is true and the cognizer has reasons for believing it that would not obtain unless it were true. For example, someone knows that the telephone is ringing if he believes this, it is true, and he has a specific auditory experience that would not occur unless the telephone were ringing. In a slightly different formulation, someone knows a proposition if he believes it, it is true, and if it were not true he would not believe it. In the example, if the telephone were not ringing, he would not believe that it is, because he would not have the same auditory experience. These accounts are guided by the idea that to know a proposition it is not sufficient that the belief be “accidentally” true. Rather, the belief, or its mode of acquisition, must “track,” “hook up with,” or “indicate” the truth. Unlike knowledge, justified belief need not guarantee or be “hooked up” with the truth, for a justified belief need not itself be true. Nonetheless, reliabilists insist that the concept of justified belief also has a connection with truth acquisition. According to the reliable process account, a belief’s justificational status depends on the psychological processes that produce or sustain it. Justified beliefs are produced by appropriate psychological processes, unjustified beliefs by inappropriate processes. For example, beliefs produced or preserved by perception, memory, introspection, and “good” reasoning are justified, whereas beliefs produced by hunch, wishful thinking, or “bad” reasoning are unjustified. Why are the first group of processes appropriate and the second inappropriate? The difference appears to lie in their reliability. Among the beliefs produced by perception, introspection, or “good” reasoning, a high proportion are true; but only a low proportion of beliefs produced by hunch, wishful thinking, or “bad” reasoning are true. Thus, what qualifies a belief as justified is its being the outcome of a sequence of reliable belief-forming processes. Reliabilism is a species of epistemological externalism, because it makes knowledge or justification depend on factors such as truth connections or truth ratios that are outside the cognizer’s mind and not necessarily accessible to him. Yet reliabilism typically emphasizes internal factors as well, e.g., the cognitive processes responsible for a belief. Process reliabilism is a form of naturalistic epistemology because it centers on cognitive operations and thereby paves the way for cognitive psychology to play a role in epistemology. Grice: “I expect that my co-conversationalist shall be realiable, as I assume he expects I will, too – or is it I assume he expects I *shall*?” Grice: “Covnersational reliability.”

renouvier: philosopher influenced by Kant and Comte, the latter natural, Comte being one of his teachers – “and brainwashing so endemic in academia it hurts! I’m lucky Hardie wasn’t worth my mimesis!” – Grice.  Renouvier rejected many of the views of both these philosophers, however, charting his own course. He emphasized the irreducible plurality and individuality of all things against the contemporary tendencies toward absolute idealism. Human individuality he associated with indeterminism and freedom. To the extent that agents are undetermined by other things and self-determining, they are unique individuals. Indeterminism also extends to the physical world and to knowledge. He rejected absolute certitude, but defended the universality of the laws of logic and mathematics. In politics and religion, he emphasized individual freedom and freedom of conscience. His emphasis on plurality, indeterminism, freedom, novelty, and process influenced James and, through James,  pragmatism. 

re-praesentatum: Grice plays with this as a philosophical semanticist, rather than a philosophical psychologist. But the re-praesentatum depends on the ‘praesentatum,’ which corresponds to Grice’s sub-perceptum (not the ‘conceptus’). cf. Grice on Peirce’s representamen (“You don’t want to go there,” – Grice to his tutees). It seems that in the one-off predicament, iconicy plays a role: the drawing of a skull to indicate danger, the drawing of an arrow at the fork of a road to indicate which way the emissor’s flowers, who were left behind, are supposed to take (Carruthers). Suppose Grice joins the Oxfordshire cricket club. He will represent Oxfordshire. He will do for Oxfordshire what Oxfordshire cannot do for herself. Similarly, by uttering “Smoke!,” the utterer means that there is fire somewhere. “Smoke!” is a communication-device if it does for smoke what smoke cannot do for itself, influence thoughts and behaviour. Or does it?! It MWheIGHT. But suppose that the fire is some distant from the addresse. And the utterer HAS LEARNED That there is fire in the distance. So he utters ‘Smoke!’ Where? Oh, you won’t see it. But I was told there is smoke on the outskirts. Thanks for warning me! rĕ-praesento , āvi, ātum, 1, v. a.  I. To bring before one, to bring back; to show, exhibit, display, manifest, represent (class.): “per quas (visiones) imagines rerum absentium ita repraesentantur animo, ut eas cernere oculis ac praesentes habere videamur,” Quint. 6, 2, 29: “memoriae vis repraesentat aliquid,” id. 11, 2, 1; cf. Plin. Ep. 9, 28, 3: “quod templum repraesentabat memoriam consulatūs mei,” Cic. Sest. 11, 26: si quis vultu torvo ferus simulet Catonem, Virtutemne repraesentet moresque Catonis? * Hor. Ep. 1, 19, 14: “imbecillitatem ingenii mei,” Val. Max. 2, 7, 6: “movendi ratio aut in repraesentandis est aut imitandis adfectibus,” Quint. 11, 3, 156: “urbis species repraesentabatur animis,” Curt. 3, 10, 7; cf.: “affectum patris amissi,” Plin. Ep. 4, 19, 1: “nam et vera esse et apte ad repraesentandam iram deūm ficta possunt,” Liv. 8, 6, 3 Weissenb. ad loc.: “volumina,” to recite, repeat, Plin. 7, 24, 24, § 89: “viridem saporem olivarum etiam post annum,” Col. 12, 47, 8: “faciem veri maris,” id. 8, 17, 6: “colorem constantius,” to show, exhibit, Plin. 37, 8, 33, § 112: “vicem olei,” i. e. to supply the place of, id. 28, 10, 45, § 160; cf. id. 18, 14, 36, § 134.— B. Of painters, sculptors, etc., to represent, portray, etc. (post-Aug. for adumbro): “Niceratus repraesentavit Alcibiadem,” Plin. 34, 8, 19, § 88.—With se, to present one's self, be present, Col. 1, 8, 11; 11, 1, 26; Dig. 48, 5, 15, § 3.— II. In partic., mercant. t. t., to pay immediately or on the spot; to pay in ready money: reliquae pecuniae vel usuram Silio pendemus, dum a Faberio vel ab aliquo qui Faberio debet, repraesentabimus, shall be enabled to pay immediately, Cic. Att. 12, 25, 1; 12, 29, 2: “summam,” Suet. Aug. 101: “legata,” id. Calig. 16: “mercedem,” id. Claud. 18; id. Oth. 5; Front. Strat. 1, 11, 2 Oud. N. cr.: “dies promissorum adest: quem etiam repraesentabo, si adveneris,” shall even anticipate, Cic. Fam. 16, 14, 2; cf. fideicommissum, to discharge immediately or in advance, Dig. 35, 1, 36.— B. Transf., in gen., to do, perform, or execute any act immediately, without delay, forthwith; hence, not to defer or put off; to hasten (good prose): se, quod in longiorem diem collaturus esset, repraesentaturum et proximā nocte castra moturum, * Caes. B. G. 1, 40: “festinasse se repraesentare consilium,” Curt. 6, 11, 33: “petis a me, ut id quod in diem suum dixeram debere differri, repraesentem,” Sen. Ep. 95, 1; and Front. Aquaed. 119 fin.: “neque exspectare temporis medicinam, quam repraesentare ratione possimus,” to apply it immediately, Cic. Fam. 5, 16, 6; so, “improbitatem suam,” to hurry on, id. Att. 16, 2, 3: “spectaculum,” Suet. Calig. 58: “tormenta poenasque,” id. Claud. 34: “poenam,” Phaedr. 3, 10, 32; Val. Max. 6, 5, ext. 4: “verbera et plagas,” Suet. Vit. 10: “vocem,” to sing immediately, id. Ner. 21 et saep.: “si repraesentari morte meā libertas civitatis potest,” can be immediately recovered, Cic. Phil. 2, 46, 118: “minas irasque caelestes,” to fulfil immediately, Liv. 2, 36, 6 Weissenb. ad loc.; cf. Suet. Claud. 38: “judicia repraesentata,” held on the spot, without preparation, Quint. 10, 7, 2.— C. To represent, stand in the place of (late Lat.): nostra per eum repraesentetur auctoritas, Greg. M. Ep. 1, 1.

res publica --: republicanism: cf. Cato -- Grice was a British subject and found classical republicanism false -- also known as civic humanism, a political outlook developed by Machiavelli in Renaissance Italy and by James Harrington in England, modified by eighteenth-century British and Continental writers and important for the thought of the  founding fathers. Drawing on Roman historians, Machiavelli argued that a state could hope for security from the blows of fortune only if its male citizens were devoted to its well-being. They should take turns ruling and being ruled, be always prepared to fight for the republic, and limit their private possessions. Such men would possess a wholly secular virtù appropriate to political beings. Corruption, in the form of excessive attachment to private interest, would then be the most serious threat to the republic. Harrington’s utopian Oceana 1656 portrayed England governed under such a system. Opposing the authoritarian views of Hobbes, it described a system in which the well-to-do male citizens would elect some of their number to govern for limited terms. Those governing would propose state policies; the others would vote on the acceptability of the proposals. Agriculture was the basis of economics, civil rights classical republicanism 145   145 but the size of estates was to be strictly controlled. Harringtonianism helped form the views of the political party opposing the dominance of the king and court. Montesquieu in France drew on classical sources in discussing the importance of civic virtue and devotion to the republic. All these views were well known to Jefferson, Adams, and other  colonial and revolutionary thinkers; and some contemporary communitarian critics of  culture return to classical republican ideas. 

stimulus/response distinction, the: Grice’s motto: “No stimulus, no response.” “The black box is meant to EXPLAIN (make plain) the link between the stimulus and the response – and no item in the black box should be postulated that it lacks this explanatory adequacy. “As Witters says, “No mental concept without the behaviour the mental concept is brought to explain.” Chomsky hated it. Grice changed it to ‘effect.’ Or not. “Stimulus and response,” Skinner's behavioral theory was largely set forth in his first book, Behavior of Organisms (1938).[9] Here, he gives a systematic description of the manner in which environmental variables control behavior. He distinguished two sorts of behavior which are controlled in different ways:  Respondent behaviors are elicited by stimuli, and may be modified through respondent conditioning, often called classical (or pavlovian) conditioning, in which a neutral stimulus is paired with an eliciting stimulus. Such behaviors may be measured by their latency or strength. Operant behaviors are 'emitted,' meaning that initially they are not induced by any particular stimulus. They are strengthened through operant conditioning (aka instrumental conditioning), in which the occurrence of a response yields a reinforcer. Such behaviors may be measured by their rate. Both of these sorts of behavior had already been studied experimentally, most notably: respondents, by Ivan Pavlov;[25] and operants, by Edward Thorndike.[26] Skinner's account differed in some ways from earlier ones,[27] and was one of the first accounts to bring them under one roof.

rerum natura: Latin, ‘the nature of things’, or ‘reality,’ to use the root of ‘res,’ cognate with ‘ratio,’ – (as ‘ding’ is connected with ‘denken,’ and ‘logos’ with ‘legein’ -- metaphysics. The phrase can also be used more narrowly to mean the nature of physical reality, and often it presupposes a naturalistic view of all reality. Lucretius’s epic poem “De rerum natura,” is an Epicurean physics, designed to underpin the Epicurean morality. Seneca told Lucrezio, “You could have looked for a catchier title if you want it a best-seller.”

responsabile, the responsabile: responsibility – cited by H. P. Grice in “The causal theory of perception” -- a condition that relates an agent to actions of, and consequences connected to, that agent, and is always necessary and sometimes sufficient for the appropriateness of certain kinds of appraisals of that agent. Responsibility has no single definition, but is several closely connected specific concepts. Role responsibility. Agents are identified by social roles that they occupy, say parent or professor. Typically duties are associated with such roles  to care for the needs of their children, to attend classes and publish research papers. A person in a social role is “responsible for” the execution of those duties. One who carries out such duties is “a responsible person” or “is behaving responsibly.” Causal responsibility. Events, including but not limited to human actions, cause other events. The cause is “responsible” for the effect. Causal responsibility does not imply consciousness; objects and natural phenomena may have causal responsibility. Liability responsibility. Practices of praise and blame include constraints on the mental stance that an agent must have toward an action or a consequence of action, in order for praise or blame to be appropriate. To meet such constraints is to meet a fundamental necessary condition for liability for praise or blame  hence the expression ‘liability responsibility’. These constraints include such factors as intention, knowledge, recklessness toward consequences, absence of mistake, accident, inevitability of choice. An agent with the capability for liability responsibility may lack it on some occasion  when mistaken, for example. Capacity responsibility. Practices of praise and blame assume a level of intellectual and emotional capability. The severely mentally disadvantaged or the very young, for example, do not have the capacity to meet the conditions for liability responsibility. They are not “responsible” in that they lack capacity responsibility. Both morality and law embody and respect these distinctions, though law institutionalizes and formalizes them. Final or “bottom-line” assignment of responsibility equivalent to indeed deserving praise or blame standardly requires each of the latter three specific kinds of responsibility. The first kind supplies some normative standards for praise or blame. 

resultus: or resultance, a relation according to which one property the resultant property, sometimes called the consequential property is possessed by some object or event in virtue of and hence as a result of that object or event possessing some other property or set of properties. The idea is that properties of things can be ordered into connected levels, some being more basic than and giving rise to others, the latter resulting from the former. For instance, a figure possesses the property of being a triangle in virtue of its possessing a collection of properties, including being a plane figure, having three sides, and so on; the former resulting from the latter. An object is brittle has the property of being brittle in virtue of having a certain molecular structure. It is often claimed that moral properties like rightness and goodness are resultant properties: an action is right in virtue of its possessing other properties. These examples make it clear that the nature of the necessary connection holding between a resultant property and those base properties that ground it may differ from case to case. In the geometrical example, the very concept of being a triangle grounds the resultance relation in question, and while brittleness is nomologically related to the base properties from which it results, in the moral case, the resultance relation is arguably neither conceptual nor causal. 

cornwall – “He hardly spoke English – and Grosseteste hardly spoke Cornish – yet they became best friends at Oxford – Fishacre helped. “But they communicated mainly in the lingua franca, that is Roman!” -- Rrichard Rufus, also called Richard of Cornwall English philosopher who wrote some of the earliest commentaries on Aristotle in the Latin West. Cornwall’s commentaries are not cursory summaries; they include sustained philosophical discussions. “Cornwall,” as he was called (cf. Grice’s “Shropshire,” – all I remember about him is that his name was that of a shire”) was a master of arts at Paris, where he studied with Hales. And they would joke, “I was called after a shire, but you after a town, ain’t that unfair?” – Cornwall is also deeply influenced by Grosseteste – “he of the great head” – or “balls” (testis, testiculus). Cornwall leaves Paris and joins the Franciscan order. He was ordained in England. In 1256, he became regent master of the Franciscan studium at Oxford (“of course,” Grice); according to Bacon, Cornwall is the most influential philosopher  at Oxford In addition to his Aristotle commentaries, Cornwall writes two commentaries on Peter Lombard’s Sentences. In the first of these he borrows  freely from Grosseteste, Hales, and Fishacre (“if you’ve heard of him” – Grice). The second commentary is a critical condensation of the lectures of Fidanza, presented in Paris. Cornwall is a  proponent of the theory of impetus. His views on projectile motion are cited by  Meyronnes. Cornwall also advocates other arguments first presented by Philoponus. Against the eternity of the world, he argued that past time is necessarily finite, since it has been traversed, and, on top, the world is hardly eternal, since “if the world has no beginning, no more time transpires before tomorrow than it transpires before today – but it does so transpire.” Cornwall also argues that if the world had not been created ex nihilo, the first cause would be mutable. Grosseteste cited one of Cornwalls arguments against the eternity of the world in his notes on Aristotle’s Physics. Cornwall denies the validity of Anselm’s ontological argument, but, anticipating Duns Scotus, Cornwall argues that the existence of an independent being could be inferred from its possibility. Like Duns Scotus, Cornwall employs the formal distinction as an explanatory tool; in presenting his own views, Duns Scotus cites Cornwall’s’s definition of the “formal distinction” versus the “material distinction.” Richard states his philosophical views briefly, even cryptically; his Latin prose style is sometimes eccentric (even Griceian), characterized by rather abrupt extemporaneous interjections in which he apparently means to addresses this or that question to God, to himself, or to his intended recipient. Cornwall is hesitant about the value of systematic theology for the theologian, deferring to biblical exposition as the primary forum for theological discussion. In systematic theology, he emphasized Aristotelian semanticsc. He was a well-known semanticist. Some scholars (Kneale, Grice, and Speranza included) believe Cornwall is the famous logician known as the “Magister Abstractionum.” Though Cornwall borrowed freely from his contemporaries, he was a profoundly original philosopher. 

ricoeur: hermeneuticist and phenomenologist who has been a professor at several  universities as well as the  of Naples, Yale , and the  of Chicago. He has received major prizes from France, G.y, and Italy. He is the author of twenty-some volumes tr. in a variety of languages. Among his best-known books are Freedom and Nature: The Voluntary and the Involuntary; Freud and Philosophy: An Essay of Interpretation; The Conflict of Interpretations: Essay in Hermeneutics; The Role of the Metaphor: Multi-Disciplinary Studies of the Creation of Meaning in Language, Time and Narrative; and Oneself as Another. His early studies with the  existentialist Marcel resulted in a book-length study of Marcel’s work and later a series of published dialogues with him. Ricoeur’s philosophical enterprise is colored by a continuing tension between faith and reason. His long-standing commitments to both the significance of the individual and the Christian faith are reflected in his hermeneutical voyage, his commitment to the Esprit movement, and his interest in the writings of Emmanuel Mounier. This latter point is also seen in his claim of the inseparability of action and discourse in our quest for meaning. In our comprehension of both history and fiction one must turn to the text to understand its plot as guideline if we are to comprehend experience of any reflective sort. In the end there are no metaphysical or epistemological grounds by which meaning can be verified, and yet our nature is such that possibility must be present before us. Ricoeur attempts his explanation through a hermeneutic phenomenology. The very hermeneutics of existence that follows is itself limited by reason’s questioning of experience and its attempts to transcend the limit through the language of symbols and metaphors. Freedom and meaning come to be realized in the actualization of an ethics that arises out of the very act of existing and thus transcends the mere natural voluntary distinction of a formal ethic. It is clear from his later work that he rejects any form of foundationalism including phenomenology as well as nihilism and easy skepticism. Through a sort of interdependent dialectic that goes beyond the more mechanical models of Hegelianism or Marxism, the self understands itself and is understood by the other in terms of its suffering and its moral actions.  Refs.: J. O. Urmson, “La pragmatique,” H. P. Grice, “The conflict of interpretations between me and Ricoeur, and vice versa.”

directus -- right: an advantageous position conferred on some possessor by law, morals, rule, or other norm. There is no agreement on the way in which a ‘right’ is an advantage. Will theories hold that rights favor the will of the possessor over the conflicting will of some other party; interest theories maintain that rights serve to protect or promote the interests of the right-holder. Hohfeld identified four legal advantages: liberties, claims, powers, and immunitiesThe concept of a right arose in Roman jurisprudence and was extended to ethics via natural law theory. Just as positive law, the law posited by human lawmakers, confers legal rights, so the natural law confers natural rights. Rights are classified by their specific sources in different sorts of rules. Legal rights are advantageous positions under the law of a society. Other species of institutional rights are conferred by the rules of private organizations, of the moral code of a society, or even of some game. Those who identify natural law with the moral law often identify natural rights with moral rights, but some limit natural rights to our most fundamental rights and contrast them with ordinary moral rights. Others deny that moral rights are natural because they believe that they are conferred by the mores or positive morality of one’s society. One always possesses any specific right by virtue of possessing some status. Thus, rights are also classified by status. Civil rights are those one possesses as a citizen; human rights are possessed by virtue of being human. Presumably women’s rights, children’s rights, patients’ rights, and the rights of blacks as such are analogous. Human rights play very much the same role in ethics once played by natural rights. This is partly because ontological doubts about the existence of God undermine the acceptance of any natural law taken to consist in divine commands, and epistemological doubts about self-evident moral truths lead many to reject any natural law conceived of as the dictates of reason. Although the Thomistic view that natural rights are grounded on the nature of man is often advocated, most moral philosophers reject its teleological conception of human nature defined by essential human purposes. It seems simpler to appeal instead to fundamental rights that must be universal among human beings because they are possessed merely by virtue of one’s status as a human being. Human rights are still thought of as natural in the very broad sense of existing independently of any human action or institution. This explains how they can be used as an independent standard in terms of which to criticize the laws and policies of governments and other organizations. Since human rights are classified by status rather than source, there is another species of human rights that are institutional rather than natural. These are the human rights that have been incorporated into legal systems by international agreements such as the European Convention on Human Rights. It is sometimes said that while natural rights were conceived as purely negative rights, such as the right not to be arbitrarily imprisoned, human rights are conceived more broadly to include positive social and economic rights, such as the right to social security or to an adequate standard of living. But this is surely not true by definition. Traditional natural law theorists such as Grotius and Locke spoke of natural rights as powers and associated them with liberties, rather than with claims against interference. And while modern declarations of human rights typically include social and economic rights, they assume that these are rights in the same sense that traditional political rights are. Rights are often classified by their formal properties. For example, the right not to be battered is a negative right because it imposes a negative duty not to batter, while the creditor’s right to be repaid is a positive right because it imposes a positive duty to repay. The right to be repaid is also a passive right because its content is properly formulated in the passive voice, while the right to defend oneself is an active right because its content is best stated in the active voice. Again, a right in rem is a right that holds against all second parties; a right in personam is a right that holds against one or a few others. This is not quite Hart’s distinction between general and special rights, rights of everyone against everyone, such as the right to free speech, and rights arising from special relations, such as that between creditor and debtor or husband and wife. Rights are conceptually contrasted with duties because rights are advantages while duties are disadvantages. Still, many jurists and philosophers have held that rights and duties are logical correlatives. This does seem to be true of claim rights; thus, the creditor’s right to be repaid implies the debtor’s duty to repay and vice versa. But the logical correlative of a liberty right, such as one’s right to park in front of one’s house, is the absence of any duty for one not to do so. This contrast is indicated by D. D. Raphael’s distinction between rights of recipience and rights of action. Sometimes to say that one has a right to do something is to say merely that it is not wrong for one to act in this way. This has been called the weak sense of ‘a right’. More often to assert that one has a right to do something does not imply that exercising this right is right. Thus, I might have a right to refuse to do a favor for a friend even though it would be wrong for me to do so. Finally, many philosophers distinguish between absolute and prima facie rights. An absolute right always holds, i.e., disadvantages some second party, within its scope; a prima facie right is one that holds unless the ground of the right is outweighed by some stronger contrary reason. Refs. H. P. Grice, “On the conceptual priority of the moral right over the legal right, and vice versa.”

rigorism, the view that morality consists in that single set of simple or unqualified moral rules, discoverable by reason, which applies to all human beings at all times. It is often said that Kant’s doctrine of the categorical imperative is rigoristic. Two main objections to rigorism are 1 some moral rules do not apply universally  e.g., ‘Promises should be kept’ applies only where there is an institution of promising; and 2 some rules that could be universally kept are absurd  e.g., that everyone should stand on one leg while the sun rises. Recent interpreters of Kant defend him against these objections by arguing, e.g., that the “rules” he had in mind are general guidelines for living well, which are in fact universal and practically relevant, or that he was not a rigorist at all, seeing moral worth as issuing primarily from the agent’s character rather than adherence to rules.

rimini: gregorio di, philosopher, he studied in Italy, England, and France, and taught at the universities of Bologna, Padua, Perugia, and Paris before becoming prior general of the Hermits of St. Augustine in his native city of Rimini, about eighteen months before he died. Gregory earned the honorific title “the Authentic Doctor” because he was considered by many of his contemporaries to be a faithful interpreter of Augustine, and thus a defender of tradition, in the midst of the scepticism of Occam and his disciples regarding what could be known in natural philosophy and theology. Thus, in his commentary on Books I and II of Peter Lombard’s Sentences, Gregory rejected the view that because of God’s omnipotence he can do anything and is therefore unknowable in his nature and his ways. Gregory also maintained that after Adam’s fall from righteousness, men need, in conjunction with their free will, God’s help grace to perform morally good actions. In non-religious matters Gregory is usually associated with the theory of the complexe significabile, according to which the object of knowledge acquired by scientific proof is neither an object existing outside the mind, nor a word simplex or a proposition complexum, but rather the complexe significabile, that which is totally and adequately signified by the proposition expressed in the conclusion of the proof in question.


ring of Gyges, a ring that gives its wearer invisibility, discussed in Plato’s Republic II, 359b 360d. Glaucon tells the story of a man who discovered the ring and used it to usurp the throne to defend the claim that those who behave justly do so only because they lack the power to act unjustly. If they could avoid paying the penalty of injustice, Glaucon argues, everyone would be unjust.

romagnosi: important Italian philosopher. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice e Romagnosi," per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.

filosofia romana: Grice: “There is a continuity between the philosophy wrote in Ancient Rome and that done in Italy – as every British soldier who fought in the second world war should know!” -- Grice loved it. Enesidemo, academic philosopher, founder of a Pyrrhonist revival in Rome. Vide “Enesidemo. Anassagora, pre-Socratic enquirer into the origin of the  cosmos – andronico, peripatetic; editor of Aristotle’s  works.antioco, cademic who reverted to Plato’s  dogmatism – Antipater, Stoic, tutor to Cato  Uticensis.apollonide, toic, adviser to Cato  Uticensis – apollonio, eo-pythagorean.apuleio, Platonic, author of the “Isagoge” adored by Boezio, and the "Metamorphoses". – arcelisao, academic sceptic, head of the New Academy --- aristippo, member of Socrates’s circle – aristone, peripatetic and head of the Lyceum – aristotele founder  of the Peripatetic school – aristo, head of the  Academy and teacher of Brutus – ario, adviser to Augustus – artemidoro, stoic, friend of Pliny the Younger and son-in-law of Musonius – atenodoro, Stoic and adviser  to Cato Uticensis, in whose house he lived –atenodoro, Stoic and friend of Cicero – attalo, toic,  teacher of Seneca –augustino, neo-platonist – bione, ynic, popular teacher – boezio, philosopher with Stoic and Neoplatonist views, author of "The Consolation of  Philosophy" – carneade, head of the New Academy, Sceptic  and star of the Athenian embassy to Rome in 155 – cheremone, toic, tutor to Nero – crisippo,  head of the  Stoic school from 232 – cicerone, leading transmitter of  Hellenistic philosophy to Rome and Renaissance Europe, follower of the New  Academy and pupil of Philo of Larissa – cleante, Zeno’s  successor as head of the Stoic school from 262 – clitomaco, ceptic and pupil of Carneades, head of  the New Academy from 127 – cornuto, toic, teacher and  friend of Persius and Lucan – crantore, Academic, the first  commentator on Plato – crate, ynic, follower of Diogenes  of Sinope and teacher of Zeno of Citium – cratippo, eripatetic, friend of Cicero and Nigidius and teacher of Cicero’s son.critolao, head of the Peripatetic school and member  of the Athenian embassy to Rome in 155 – Demetrio, friend of Seneca – Demetrio, adviser of Cato  Uticensis – democrito, pre-Socratic, founder  of atomism – dicherco, Peripatetic, pupil of  Aristotle – diodoto, toic, teacher and friend of  Cicero, in whose house he lived – diogene laerzio, author of "The Lives of the Philosophers" – diogene d’apollonia 2nd half of 5th. cent., pre-Socratic philosopher and enquirer  into the natural world; a source for Seneca’s "Naturates Quaestiones" – diogene da babilonia, head of the Stoic school and member of the  Athenian embassy to Rome in 155, tutor to Panaetius – diogene d’enoanda, Epicurean and part-author of the inscription on the  stoa which he caused to be set up in Oenoanda --  diogene da sinope.  mid-4th.cent., founder of Cynicism --  epitteto, Stoic,  pupil of Musonius – epicuro -- principal source for Lucretius’s  poem – eufrate, Stoic, student of Musonius and  friend of Pliny the Younger – favorino, philosopher of  the Second Sophistic, friend of Plutarch and teacher of Fronto – galeno, physician to Marcus Aurelius, Platonist – ecato, early 1st. cent., Stoic, pupil of Panaetius and member of circle of  Posidonius – ermarco,  pupil of Epicurus  and his successor as head of the Epicurean school from 271, with Epicurus,  Metrodorus and Polyaenus, one of “The Four Men”, founders of the Epicurean  school – ierocle, Stoic --  lelio, consul in 140, friend of Scipio Aemilianus and Panaetius and called by  Cicero "the first Roman philosopher."leucippo, co-founder with Democritus of atomism – lucrezio, Epicurean, author of "De Rerum Natura" – manilio -- Stoic author of "Astronomica" – marc’aurelio, emperor, and Stoic, author of "To Himself",  a private diary – menippo, first half of 3rd. cent., Cynic and  satirical author in prose and verse on philosophical subjects – metrodoro, friend of Epicurus and one “The Four Men”, founders of  Epicureanism – moderato, neo-pythagorean – musonio, Roman of  Etruscan descent, Stoic, teacher of Epictetus – nigidio, eo-pythagorean – panezio, Stoic, head of the Stoic  school from 129, influential at Rome, friend of Scipio Aemilianus and major  source for Cicero’s "De Officiis" – parmenide, pre-Socratic, pioneer enquirer  into the nature of “what is” – patrone,  friend of Cicero and successor of Phaedrus as head of the Epicurean  school – fedro, Epicurean, admired by Cicero. head of the Epicurean school in the last years of his life – filone d’alessandria, philosopher, sympathetic to Stoic ethics and  influential in the later development of Neo-platonism – filone da larissa, head of the New Academy, 110–88, the most influential of Cicero’s  tutors – filodemo, Epicurean philosopher, protegé of Piso Caesoninus and an influence on Virgil and Horace, many of his fragmentary  writings are preserved in the Herculaneum papyri – platone -- founder of the Academy and disciple and interpreter of Socrates – plotino -- eo-platonist, resident in Rome and Campania – Plutarco,  Platonist – polemo,  Platonist and head of the Academy  -- poliaeno, friend of Epicurus and one of “The Four Men,” founders of Epicureanism – posidonio, Stoic, student of Panaetius and head of his own school  in Rhodes, where Cicero heard him. The dominant figure in middle Stoicism, whose  works encompassed the whole range of intellectual enquiry.pirrone, the founder of Scepticism, whose doctrines were revived in Rome by  Enesidemo. – pitagora di samo -- head of a community at  Croton in S. Italy, emphasized the importance of number and proportion, his  doctrines included vegetarianism and the transmigration of souls, influenced  Plato, his philosophy was revived at Rome by Nigidius and the Sextii. –rustico: consul, Stoic, friend and teacher of marc’aurelio. – Seneca, stoic, tutor, adviser and victim of  Nero, author of philosophical treatises, including "Dialogi" and "Epistulae  Morales" – severo: consul, Stoic friend and teacher of marc’aurelio, whose son married his daughter.sestio --  Neo-pythagorean, founder of the only genuinely Roman school of philosophy;  admired by Seneca for his disciplined Roman ethos – sesto empirico --sceptic, author of philosophical works and  critic of Stoicism, principal source for Pyrrhonism – siro, 1st. cent.,  Epicurean, teacher in Campania of Virgil – socrate -- iconic  Athenian philosopher and one of the most influential figures in Graeco-roman philosophy; he wrote nothing but is the central figure in Plato’s dialogues,  admired by non-Academics, including the Stoic Marc’ Aureliio nearly six hundred  years after his death – sotione: Neopythagorean, teacher  of Seneca – speusippo, , Plato’s successor as head of the  Academy – tele, cynic, author of diatribes on ethical subjects – teofrasto, peripatetic, successor to Aristotle as head of the Lyceum– Varrone – – Senocrate,. head of the Academy. Senone da Citio -- founder of Stoicism, originally a  follower of the Cynic Crates, taught at Athens in the Stoa Poikile, which gave  its name to his school. Senone da Sidone, head of the Epicurean school (or Garden) at Athens, where he taught Philodemus and was heard by Cicero. Refs.: Marc’aurelio on Platone.

roscelin de Compiègne: He made fun of Abelard having been ‘castrated’ for his philosophical dogmas on the universals. -- philosopher and logician who became embroiled in theological controversy when he applied his logical teachings to the doctrine of the Trinity. Since almost nothing survives of his written work, we must rely on hostile accounts of his views by Anselm of Canterbury and Peter Abelard, both of whom openly opposed his positions. Perhaps the most notorious view Roscelin is said to have held is that universals are merely the puffs of air produced when a word is pronounced. On this point he opposed views current among many theologians that a universal has an existence independent of language, and somehow is what many different particulars are. Roscelin’s aversion to any proposal that different things can be some one thing is probably what led him in his thinking about the three persons of God to a position that sounded suspiciously like the heresy of tritheism. Roscelin also evidently held that the qualities of things are not entities distinct from the subjects that possess them. This indicates that Roscelin probably denied that terms in the Aristotelian categories other than substance signified anything distinct from substances. Abelard, the foremost logician of the twelfth century, studied under Roscelin around 1095 and was undoubtedly influenced by him on the question of universals. Roscelin’s view that universals are linguistic entities remained an important option in medieval thought. Otherwise his positions do not appear to have had much currency in the ensuing decades. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The universal – and what to do with it.”

rosmini: important Italian philosopher, Catholic priest, counselor to Pope Pius IX, and supporter of the supremacy of the church over civil government Neo-Guelphism. Rosmini had two major concerns: the objectivity of human knowledge and the synthesis of philosophical thought within the tradition of Catholic thought. In his Nuovo saggio sull’origine delle idee “New Essay on the Origin of Ideas,” 1830, he identifies the universal a priori intuitive component of all human knowledge with the idea of being that gives us the notion of a possible or ideal being. Everything in the world is known by intellectual perception, which is the synthesis of sensation and the idea of being. Except for the idea of being, which is directly given by God, all ideas derive from abstraction. The objectivity of human knowledge rests on its universal origin in the idea of being. The harmony between philosophy and religion comes from the fact that all human knowledge is the result of divine revelation. Rosmini’s thought was influenced by Augustine and Aquinas, and stimulated by the attempt to find a solution to the contrasting needs of rationalism and empiricism. Antonio Rosmini Da Wikipedia, l'enciclopedia libera. Jump to navigationJump to search Nota disambigua.svg Disambiguazione – Se stai cercando l'omonimo criminale appartenente alla 'ndrangheta, vedi Antonio Rosmini (criminale). Nota disambigua.svg Disambiguazione – "Rosmini" rimanda qui. Se stai cercando la 'ndrina, vedi Rosmini ('ndrina). Beato Antonio Rosmini Francesco Hayez (1791-1882) Ritratto di Antonio Rosmini (1853-1856) Galleria d'Arte Moderna di Milano.jpg Antonio Rosmini ritratto da Francesco Hayez, 1853-1856   Nascita 24 marzo 1797 Morte 1º luglio 1855 Venerato da Chiesa cattolica Beatificazione 18 novembre 2007 Ricorrenza 1º luglio Manuale Antonio Francesco Davide Ambrogio Rosmini Serbati (Rovereto, 24 marzo 1797 – Stresa, 1º luglio 1855) è stato un filosofo, teologo e presbitero italiano. La chiesa cattolica lo venera come beato dal 18 novembre 2007.   Indice 1 Biografia 2 Pensiero 2.1 Filosofia 2.2 Politica 3 Da Pio VIII a Benedetto XVI: il giudizio dei papi su Rosmini 3.1 La condanna del Sant'Uffizio 3.2 La riabilitazione a seguito del Concilio Vaticano II 4 La beatificazione 4.1 Cronologia della causa di beatificazione 4.2 La cerimonia di beatificazione 5 Opere 5.1 Massime di perfezione cristiana 6 Rosmini e il Concilio Ecumenico Vaticano II 6.1 Tematiche affrontate nell'opera Delle Cinque Piaghe della Santa Chiesa 7 Scuole 8 Note 9 Bibliografia 10 Voci correlate 11 Altri progetti 12 Collegamenti esterni Biografia  Casa natale di Antonio Rosmini, in corso Rosmini, a Rovereto Fu secondogenito di Pier Modesto e di Giovanna dei Conti Formenti di Biacesa in Valle di Ledro, nipote di Ambrogio Rosmini Serbati, e al momento della sua nascita avvenuta il 24 marzo 1797, Rovereto faceva parte del dominio delle forze napoleoniche, che l'avevano strappato all'Impero asburgico. In quegli anni il Trentino fu terra di confine ora Tirolese (Tirolo italiano) ora appartenente al regno d'Italia, con capitale Milano.[1]  Della sua nascita, Rosmini renderà sempre grazie a Dio poiché «Egli la fece coincidere con la vigilia della Beata Maria Vergine Annunziata». Viveva con sua sorella maggiore Margherita, entrata nelle Suore di Canossa, e con suo fratello più piccolo, Giuseppe. Rosmini, terminato l'Imperial Regio Ginnasio di Rovereto, al tempo città della Contea del Tirolo, compì gli studi giuridici e teologici presso l'Università di Padova e manifestò il desiderio di diventare sacerdote. A questo proposito i famigliari raccontavano come, fin dalla più tenera età, Rosmini leggesse alla luce della sua aureola.[2]  Fu nel giugno 1820, in occasione della venuta a Rovereto del Vescovo di Chioggia Giuseppe Manfrin Provedi per consacrare le chiese di Santa Maria del Carmine e di Santa Croce, appartenente all'omonimo Monastero, che Antonio Rosmini, prendendo parte alla cerimonia, ottenne da Monsignor Manfrin il diaconato ed in seguito, a Chioggia, il 21 aprile 1821 ricevette l'ordinazione sacerdotale.[3] Intanto iniziò a mostrare una profonda inclinazione per gli studi filosofici, incoraggiato in tal senso da papa Pio VII.  Dal 1826 si trasferì a Milano dove strinse un profondo rapporto d'amicizia con Alessandro Manzoni che di lui ebbe a dire: «è una delle sei o sette intelligenze che più onorano l'umanità». Manzoni assistette Rosmini sul letto di morte, da cui trasse il testamento spirituale "Adorare, Tacere, Gioire". Gli scritti di Antonio Rosmini destarono l'ammirazione, tra gli altri, anche di Giovanni Stefani, Niccolò Tommaseo e Vincenzo Gioberti dei quali pure divenne amico.  Nel 1828, dopo aver dovuto lasciare il Trentino, per motivi di forte ostilità per le sue posizioni incontrati da parte del vescovo di Trento, il beato Giovanni Nepomuceno de Tschiderer, fondò al Sacro Monte Calvario di Domodossola la congregazione religiosa dell'Istituto della Carità, detta dei "Rosminiani". Le Costituzioni della nuova famiglia religiosa, contenute in un libro che curò per tutta la vita, furono approvate da papa Gregorio XVI nel 1839.  A Borgomanero svolge la sua attività di insegnamento e di guida spirituale in un collegio rosminiano, il "Collegio Rosmini", regolato dalla Congregazione delle Suore della Provvidenza Rosminiane.  Nel 1848 svolse una missione diplomatica per conto del Re di Sardegna Carlo Alberto presso la Santa Sede.  Il filosofo fu presidente dell'Accademia Roveretana degli Agiati ed il suo posto, anni dopo la sua morte, dal 1872 al 1888, fu assunto da don Francesco Paoli, suo segretario ed esecutore delle volontà, già direttore di Casa Rosmini.[4] Tra le volontà del filosofo vi fu anche quella di donare alla città di Rovereto un terreno nell'attuale zona di Santa Maria per costruirvi l'ospedale cittadino, e don Paoli onorò tale decisione.  Rosmini è sepolto all'interno del Santuario del SS. Crocifisso di Stresa. Nella stessa chiesa si trovano le spoglie di Clemente Rebora.  Pensiero Filosofia Rosmini portò avanti tesi filosofiche tese a contrastare sia l'illuminismo che il sensismo. Sottolineando l'inalienabilità dei diritti naturali della persona, fra i quali quello della proprietà privata, entrò in polemica con il socialismo e il comunismo[5], postulando uno Stato il cui intervento fosse ridotto ai minimi termini. Nelle sue teorie il filosofo seguì le concezioni di Sant'Agostino e di San Tommaso, rifacendosi anche a Platone.  Gli esordi filosofici di Antonio Rosmini si ricollegano a Pasquale Galluppi, sia pure polemicamente, in quanto Rosmini avverte con ogni chiarezza come risulti insostenibile una posizione di integrale sensismo gnoseologico.  La necessità di concepire una funzione ordinatrice dell'esperienza, e a questa precedente, porta Rosmini a guardare con interesse la filosofia di Kant. Tuttavia non è soddisfatto di ciò che lui chiama l'innatismo kantiano, legato ad una pluralità imbarazzante e precaria di categorie. Le quali, d'altra parte, gli sembrano fallire lo scopo di far conoscere il reale quale esso è, per la necessaria introduzione di modifiche soggettive nell'atto stesso del conoscere.   Contrada della Terra, a Rovereto. Memoria storica della presenza di Antonio Rosmini. Il problema filosofico di Rosmini si configurava perciò come quello di garantire oggettività alla conoscenza. La soluzione non potrà essere trovata, stante il rifiuto della trascendentalità kantiana e dei connessi sviluppi, se non in una ricerca ontologica, in un principio oggettivo di verità, che riesca ad illuminare l'intelligenza in quanto le si proponga con immediata evidenza, universalità e immutabilità.  Questo principio è per Rosmini l'idea dell'essere possibile, che da indeterminato contenuto dell'intelligenza, quale originariamente è, si fa determinato allorché viene applicato ai dati forniti dal senso. Essa precede e informa di sé tutti i giudizi con cui affermiamo che qualche cosa particolare esiste. L'idea dell'essere, dunque, costituisce l'unico contenuto della mente che non abbia origine dai sensi, ed è perciò innata (Nuovo saggio sull'origine delle idee, del 1830).[6]  Ma qui i problemi del kantismo, che sembrano superati o almeno messi da parte, si riaffacciano con urgenza: di fronte al mero ricevere dati, di cui parlava il sensismo, Rosmini ha chiarito che la mente umana nel suo uso conoscitivo formula giudizi, in cui l'idea dell'essere ha funzione di predicato, cioè di categoria, e la sensazione è il soggetto, di cui si predica qualche cosa. Nel giudizio, inoltre, il predicato si determina e la sensazione si certifica: se questa è la funzione propria del giudicare, ogni concetto non può sussistere che come predicato di un giudizio; né a questa necessità sembra potersi sottrarre il concetto di essere, che è dato solo nell'attività giudicante, come forma del giudizio.  Tuttavia Rosmini non accetta tale riduzione, ed esclude proprio il predicato di esistenza della funzione del giudizio, continuando ad attribuirgli una natura oggettiva e trascendente. È l'essere trascendente che si rivela all'uomo, lo illumina e gli permette di pensare. Chi lo nega come il nichilismo cade in una vuota posizione nullista.  Accanto a questa ontologia l'etica di Rosmini si sviluppa come etica caritativa (Principio della scienza morale, 1831).   Monumento sepolcrale di Antonio Rosmini, Vincenzo Vela, Stresa Politica Rosmini dedicò alla politica una breve ma intensa fase della sua vita. Seguì papa Pio IX riparato a Gaeta dopo la proclamazione della Repubblica Romana, ma la sua formazione attestatasi su ferme posizioni di cattolicesimo liberale era tale per cui fu costretto a ritirarsi sul Lago Maggiore, a Stresa. Tuttavia, quando Pio IX volle istituire dopo il 1849 una commissione incaricata della preparazione del testo per la definizione del dogma dell'Immacolata Concezione, nonostante ben due sue opere (Le cinque piaghe della Chiesa e La costituzione secondo la giustizia sociale) fossero all'Indice, Rosmini fu chiamato a prendere parte a tale commissione.  In generale, Rosmini era favorevole allo Stato liberale (vagheggiando la monarchia costituzionale), al costituzionalismo e anche alla separazione tra Stato e Chiesa (sebbene non "assoluta": Rosmini criticherà lo Statuto Albertino proprio per il suo porre ancora il cattolicesimo come religione di Stato, elogiandone comunque il tentativo distensivo nei confronti della Santa Sede, ma criticherà le leggi laiciste ed anticlericali emanate successivamente). In gioventù ammiratore di François-René de Chateaubriand e di Joseph de Maistre (per cui avrà comunque parole di elogio ancora nel 1839), si convincerà in seguito della sostanziale bontà della maggior parte delle conquiste dell'età moderna, criticandone solo le modalità: in tale ottica, Rosmini criticava sia la rivoluzione francese che l'Ancient Regime, riconoscendo invece la sostanziale bontà dei princìpi sanciti nel 1789 (distinguendoli dalle successive degenerazioni rivoluzionarie), in polemica con chi, da una parte e dall'altra, sosteneva una società da lui definita "perfettista".  Continuò a vivere a Stresa, fecondo nel perseguire il perfezionamento del suo sistema di pensiero con opere come Logica (1853) e Psicologia (1855), sino alla morte, avvenuta a 58 anni il 1º luglio 1855. Il suo corpo è oggi inumato in un sarcofago presso il Santuario SS. Sacramento a Stresa. Da Pio VIII a Benedetto XVI: il giudizio dei papi su Rosmini Ratzinger su Rosmini Il cardinale Joseph Ratzinger, il 18 maggio 1985 (quando la questione rosminiana era ancora ben accesa), nell'ambito di una serata organizzata dal Centro Culturale di Lugano, disse:  Nel confronto con le parole classiche della fede che sembrano così lontane da noi, anche il presente diventa più ricco di quanto sarebbe se rimanesse chiuso solo in se stesso. Vi sono naturalmente anche tra i teologi ortodossi molti spiriti poco illuminati e molti ripetitori di ciò che è già stato detto. Ma ciò succede ovunque; del resto la letteratura dozzinale è cresciuta in modo particolarmente rapido proprio là dove si è inneggiato più forte alla cosiddetta creatività. Io stesso per lungo tempo avevo l'impressione che i cosiddetti eretici fossero per una lettura più interessante dei teologi della chiesa, almeno nell'epoca moderna.  Ma se io ora guardo i grandi e fedeli maestri, da Mohler a Newman a Scheeben, da Rosmini a Guardini, o nel nostro tempo de Lubac, Congar, Balthasar - quanto più attuale è la loro parola rispetto a quella di coloro in cui è scomparso il soggetto comunitario della Chiesa.  In loro diventa chiaro anche qualcos'altro: il pluralismo non nasce dal fatto che uno lo cerca, ma proprio dal fatto che uno, con le sue forze e nel suo tempo, non vuole nient'altro che la verità. Per volerla davvero, si esige tuttavia anche che uno non faccia di se stesso il criterio, ma accetti il giudizio più grande, che è dato nella fede della Chiesa, come voce e via della verità.  Del resto io penso che vale la stessa regola anche per le nuove grandi correnti della teologia, che oggi sono ricercate: teologa africana, latinoamericana, asiatica, ecc. La grande teologia francese non è nata per il fatto che si voleva fare qualcosa di francese, ma perché non si presumeva di cercare nient'altro che la verità e di esprimerla più adeguatamente possibile.  E così questa teologia è diventata anche tanto francese quanto universale. La stessa cosa vale per la grande teologia italiana, tedesca, spagnola. Ciò vale sempre. Solo l'assenza di questa intenzione esplicita è fruttuosa. E di fatto non abbiamo davvero raggiunto la cosa più importante se noi ci siamo convalidati da soli, ci siamo accreditati da soli e ci siamo costruiti un monumento per noi stessi.  Abbiamo veramente raggiunto la meta più importante se siamo giunti più vicino alla verità. Essa non è mai noiosa, mai uniforme, perché il nostro spirito non la contempla che in rifrazioni parziali; tuttavia essa è nello stesso tempo la forza che ci unisce. E solo il pluralismo, che è rivolto all'unità, è veramente grande.»   Monumento ad Antonio Rosmini, in Corso Rosmini, a Rovereto Papa Pio VIII disse a Rosmini, in udienza il 15 maggio 1829:  «È volontà di Dio che voi vi occupiate nello scrivere libri: tale è la vostra vocazione. Ella maneggia assai bene la logica, e la Chiesa al presente ha gran bisogno di scrittori: dico, di scrittori solidi, di cui abbiamo somma scarsezza. Per influire utilmente sugli uomini, non rimane oggidì altro mezzo che quello di prenderli colla ragione, e per mezzo di questa condurli alla religione. Tenetevi certo, che voi potrete recare un vantaggio assai maggiore al prossimo occupandovi nello scrivere, che non esercitando qualunque altra opera del Sacro Ministero.»  Gregorio XVI, successore di Pio VIII, in risposta alla lettera che Antonio Rosmini gli aveva indirizzato il 10 gennaio 1832, il 27 marzo dello stesso anno gli scrisse:  «Diletto Figlio, a te il nostro saluto e la nostra Apostolica Benedizione. Abbiamo volentieri e con animo lieto ricevuto la tua lettera con i sensi della tua devota sommissione a Noi e alla Sede Apostolica che ci hai mandato il 10 gennaio, in cui ci parli della pia Società, chiamata Istituto della Carità e che con le tue fatiche è stata fondata nel territorio della diocesi di Novara con l'approvazione del Vescovo. E soprattutto ci hai anche informato che il medesimo Istituto è stato da poco chiamato anche dal Vescovo di Trento nella sua diocesi e che qui molti ecclesiastici, di provate virtù, vi hanno aderito. Per questi fatti davvero rendiamo il nostro umile grazie a Dio autore di ogni bene. E quantunque questo Istituto non sia stato ancora confermato dall'autorità di questa Santa Sede, tuttavia speriamo in bene di esso e ci allietiamo che lo stesso si dilati con il consenso dei nostri Venerabili Fratelli nell'Episcopato. Quindi, per quanto riguarda le Sante Indulgenze connesse a questo istituto, che domandi siano concesse, ricevi diletto figlio il nostro Rescritto unito a questa lettera, da cui sicuramente comprenderai che rispondiamo positivamente alla tua richiesta. Ti assicuriamo anche che ci è pervenuto il libro sopra i Principi della Dottrina Morale da te edito e mandatoci in omaggio e ti dichiariamo il grazie del nostro animo per il dono. Tuttavia per la tensione nelle gravissime fatiche del Governo Apostolico non abbiamo ancora letto lo stesso libro, ma siamo certamente persuasi che esso sia in tutto conforme alla più sana dottrina e utilissimo alla sua difesa. Continua dunque, diletto figlio, lo studio e prosegui a spendere le tue fatiche ad onore di Dio per l'utilità della Chiesa; in Cielo sarà copiosa la ricompensa per la tua opera. Frattanto la paterna carità con cui ti abbracciamo nell'umanità di Cristo sia pegno dell'apostolica benedizione, che sgorgante dall'intimo del cuore ti impartiamo.»  (Da Breve pontificio di Gregorio P.P.XVI, del 27 marzo 1832) Pio IX rivolgendosi al Vescovo di Cremona, nel 1854 dopo il decreto Dimittantur opera omnia parlando di Rosmini disse[7]:  «Non solo è un buon cattolico, ma santo: Iddio si serve dei santi per far trionfare la verità»  Il papa Leone XIII, al tempo delle aspre e dolorose lotte che si svolgevano intorno al pensiero rosminiano sul finire del diciannovesimo secolo, in una lettera indirizzata agli arcivescovi di Milano, Torino e Vercelli, del 25 gennaio 1882, fra l'altro scrisse:  «Ma non vogliamo che con questo abbia a patir detrimento il religioso Sodalizio della Carità; il quale come per lo innanzi spese utilmente le sue fatiche a beneficio del prossimo, secondo lo spirito dell'Istituto, così è desiderabile che fiorisca in avvenire e prosegua a rendere ognora più abbondanti frutti»  Rosmini Rovereto 02.jpg La condanna del Sant'Uffizio Col decreto del Sant'Uffizio "Post Obitum" del 1887, firmato da Leone XIII, vennero condannate, in quanto "non conformi alla verità cattolica", 40 proposizioni contenute nelle opere del Rosmini, le quali la Sacra Congregazione romana "giudicò doversi riprovare, condannare e proscrivere, nel proprio senso dell’autore", chiarendo inoltre che non era lecito "a chicchessia di inferire, che le altre dottrine del medesimo Autore, che non vengono condannate per questo decreto, siano per veruna guisa approvate"[8].  La riabilitazione a seguito del Concilio Vaticano II Giovanni XXIII, negli ultimi anni della sua vita, meditò in ritiro spirituale le rosminiane "Massime di Perfezione Cristiana", assumendole come propria regola di condotta. Anche Paolo VI prestò interesse nel Rosmini: in occasione del 150º anniversario di fondazione dell'Istituto della Carità inviò un messaggio all'allora padre generale, in cui elogiava l'intuizione del Rosmini nel dare un grande peso alla missione caritativa già nel nome del nativo istituto religioso, appunto l'Istituto della Carità. Pubblicamente Paolo VI citò Rosmini durante il discorso tenuto alla Federazione Universitaria Cattolica Italiana del 2 settembre 1963 riguardante la cultura cattolica e l'Europa. Inoltre sotto il suo pontificato venne tolto il divieto di pubblicazione dell'opera Dalle Cinque Piaghe della Santa Chiesa.  Alla morte di Paolo VI venne eletto papa Giovanni Paolo I, che si era laureato in sacra teologia alla Pontificia Università Gregoriana di Roma con una tesi su L'origine dell'anima umana secondo Antonio Rosmini. È bene precisare che Luciani era fortemente critico nei riguardi del pensiero rosminiano, solo successivamente cambiò opinione, rivolgendo nei riguardi di Rosmini parole di ammirazione e stima.  Tuttavia fu con il pontificato di Giovanni Paolo II che il pensiero rosminiano ha potuto liberarsi delle aspre critiche e delle condanne che accompagnavano l'Istituto della Carità fin dai tempi della sua fondazione. Nella Lettera Enciclica Fides et ratio, Giovanni Paolo II ha annoverato Rosmini «tra i pensatori più recenti nei quali si realizza un fecondo incontro tra sapere filosofico e Parola di Dio». Ne ha inoltre concesso l'introduzione della causa di beatificazione, conclusasi nella sua fase diocesana novarese il 21 marzo 1998.  Nel 2001, Joseph Ratzinger da prefetto della Congregazione per la Dottrina della Fede emanò nel 2001 il famoso documento Nota ai Decreti dottrinali sul Rev.do sac. Antonio Rosmini Serbati. La nota si concludeva confermando la validità del decreto Post obitum sulle quaranta proposizioni, e allo stesso tempo con la riabilitazione di Rosmini:  «Il Decreto dottrinale Post obitum non si riferisce al giudizio sulla negazione formale di verità di fede da parte dell'Autore, ma piuttosto al fatto che il sistema filosofico-teologico del Rosmini era ritenuto insufficiente e inadeguato a custodire ed esporre alcune verità della dottrina cattolica, pur riconosciute e confessate dall'Autore stesso.[...] Si possono attualmente considerare ormai superati i motivi di preoccupazione e di difficoltà dottrinali e prudenziali, che hanno determinato la promulgazione del Decreto Post obitum di condanna delle "Quaranta Proposizioni" tratte dalle opere di Antonio Rosmini. E ciò a motivo del fatto che il senso delle proposizioni, così inteso e condannato dal medesimo Decreto, non appartiene in realtà all'autentica posizione di Rosmini, ma a possibili conclusioni della lettura delle sue opere. Resta tuttavia affidata al dibattito teoretico la questione della plausibilità o meno del sistema rosminiano stesso, della sua consistenza speculativa e delle teorie o ipotesi filosofiche e teologiche in esso espresse. Nello stesso tempo rimane la validità oggettiva del Decreto Post obitum in rapporto al dettato delle proposizioni condannate, per chi le legge, al di fuori del contesto di pensiero rosminiano, in un'ottica idealista, ontologista e con un significato contrario alla fede e alla dottrina cattolica.»  (Nota ai Decreti dottrinali sul Rev.do sac. Antonio Rosmini Serbati[9]) Il documento ribadisce la diversità di linguaggio e apparato concettuale del sistema rosminiano rispetto al tomismo, l'assenza di apparato critico nelle opere postume e la permanente "difficoltà oggettiva di interpretarne le categorie, soprattutto se lette nella prospettiva neotomista".  Il 1º giugno 2007, papa Benedetto XVI ha autorizzato la Congregazione delle Cause dei Santi a promulgare il Decreto sul miracolo della guarigione di Suor Ludovica Noè, attribuito all'intercessione di Antonio Rosmini. Tra quelli portati dalla postulazione dei padri rosminiani, si è scelto di dare maggiore impulso a quello della guarigione della suora sopracitata, poiché il medico che la curò si convertì in seguito all'accaduto.  Il cardinale Angelo Bagnasco, presidente della CEI, a margine del Convegno sulla sfida educativa tenuto a Milano il 18 marzo 2010, ha tenuto un intervento intitolato "Istanze educative e questione antropologica" in cui ha riconosciuto le istanze pedagogiche del Beato Antonio Rosmini. Il 1º luglio 2010, il card. Angelo Bagnasco ha presieduto a Stresa la celebrazione eucaristica per il Dies Natalis di Antonio Rosmini.  Nel corso dell'Angelus domenicale fu ricordato per la sola "carità intellettuale" e perché "testimoniò la virtù della carità in tutte le sue dimensioni e ad alto livello"[10]. Avversario del sensismo e dell'illuminismo settecenteschi, fu mentore e maestro intellettuale di quattro Pontefici eletti consecutivamente: Giovanni XXIII, Paolo VI, Giovanni Paolo I e II[11]. La beatificazione Cronologia della causa di beatificazione 19 febbraio 1994. Nulla osta della Congregazione per la Dottrina della Fede che consente l'inizio della causa di beatificazione. 1º luglio 1997. Apertura del processo informativo diocesano dopo la nomina dei Censori teologi e delle commissioni storiche in Novara. 15 agosto 1997. Don Claudio Massimiliano Papa, I.C., diventa postulatore della Causa succedendo a padre Remo Bessero Belti, storico dell'Istituto e già Direttore del Centro Internazionale di Studi Rosminiani di Stresa. 21 marzo 1998. Chiusura del Processo informativo Diocesano. 26 marzo 1998. Consegna del Trasunto alla Congregazione per le cause dei Santi. 6 giugno 1998. Apertura del Trasunto. 15 gennaio 1999. Decreto di Validità del processo diocesano. 3 marzo 1999. Schema per la stesura della Positio. 2 dicembre 1999. Consegna del lavoro sul Post obitum curato dal Postulatore. 16 dicembre 1999. Il Relatore generale approva il lavoro sul Post obitum e il lumen oculorum tuorum 20 dicembre 1999. Consegna del lavoro sul Post obitum alla Congregazione per la Dottrina della Fede. 1º luglio 2001. Il giorno dell'anniversario della morte di Rosmini viene pubblicata sull'Osservatore Romano la Nota della Congregazione per la dottrina della fede sul valore dei decreti dottrinali concernenti il pensiero e le opere del Rev.do sacerdote Antonio Rosmini Serbati, a firma del cardinal Joseph Ratzinger e di mons. Tarcisio Bertone. 3 luglio 2001. Rilascio del Nihil obstare per la Causa di Beatificazione. 1º luglio 2002. Il Relatore approva e firma la Positio. 23 gennaio 2003. Conclusione della stampa e consegna alla Congregazione per le cause dei santi della Positio (4.693 pagine). 26 maggio 2004. Consegna del Trasunto super miro alla Congregazione per le cause dei santi. 29 maggio 2004. Validità dell'inquisizione diocesana sul processo super miro. 28 giugno 2004. Presentazione fattispecie super miro. 12 ottobre 2004. Revisa della fattispecie con firma del sotto-segretario. 28 ottobre 2004. Relatio et vota del Congresso Storico (con esito positivo). 3 febbraio 2005. Relatio et vota del Congresso teologico super virtutibus (con esito positivo). 6 giugno 2006. Ordinaria della Congregazione per le cause dei santi: esito affermativo. Ponente della Causa Mons. Rino Fisichella. 26 giugno 2006. Papa Benedetto XVI autorizza la Congregazione per le Cause dei Santi a promulgare il decreto di esercizio eroico delle virtù. 12 ottobre 2006. La Consulta medica della Congregazione per le Cause dai Santi, si esprime con esito affermativo (all'unanimità 5 su 5) circa l'inspiegabilità scientifica dell'evento di guarigione avvenuto a Sr. Ludovica Noè. Il presunto evento miracoloso è avvenuto il 6 gennaio 1927. 19 dicembre 2006. Al termine del dibattito, i Consultori si sono unanimemente espressi con voto affermativo (7 su 7), ravvisando nella guarigione in esame un miracolo operato da Dio per intercessione del Ven. Antonio Rosmini. 1º giugno 2007. Papa Benedetto XVI autorizza la pubblicazione da parte della Congregazione per le Cause dei Santi del riconoscimento delle virtù eroiche di Rosmini. 18 novembre 2007. Nella diocesi di Novara si celebra la cerimonia di Beatificazione dando lettura del decreto di Benedetto XVI che iscrive Rosmini tra i Beati. La cerimonia di beatificazione La cerimonia di beatificazione è avvenuta il 18 novembre 2007 nella città di Novara: appositamente è stato fatto allestire il Palasport della città, unico luogo capace di raccogliere un numero di fedeli così significativo.  Con il pontificato di Benedetto XVI le beatificazioni vengono preferibilmente celebrate dai cardinali, per rendere ancora più piena la comunione tra loro e il successore di Pietro, e viene privilegiato il luogo in cui il candidato agli onori degli altari ha vissuto. Così, in qualità di delegato pontificio, la celebrazione è stata officiata dal cardinale José Saraiva Martins, allora prefetto della congregazione per le Cause dei Santi. A fianco dell'altare erano disposti gli spalti da cui hanno concelebrato circa 400 sacerdoti, non soltanto rosminiani.  A prendere parte alla processione e celebrare sull'altare, insieme al preposito generale James Flynn c'era il segretario generale dell'Istituto p. Domenico Mariani con gli allora componenti della Curia Generalizia dell'Istituto della Carità, il Vicario per la Carità Spirituale p. Crish Fuse, il Vicario per la Carità Intellettuale p. Giancarlo Taverna Patron, il Vicario per la Carità Temporale p. David Tobin, l'allora preposito della Provincia Italiana don Umberto Muratore (profondo conoscitore del pensiero di Rosmini) e il padre postulatore della Causa di Beatificazione, don Claudio Massimiliano Papa.  Hanno partecipato alla celebrazione anche il cardinale ex prefetto della Sacra Congregazione per i vescovi Giovanni Battista Re, il cardinale arcivescovo di Torino Severino Poletto, il vescovo di Novara, mons. Renato Corti, l'arcivescovo di Trento, mons. Luigi Bressan, il vescovo rosminiano mons. Antonio Riboldi e fra gli altri anche mons. Germano Zaccheo (che sarebbe improvvisamente scomparso due giorni dopo), vescovo della Diocesi di Casale Monferrato, mons. Luigi Bettazzi, vescovo emerito di Ivrea (che durante la III sessione del Concilio Ecumenico Vaticano II fece per primo il nome di Rosmini), l'allora segretario generale della Conferenza Episcopale Italiana Giuseppe Betori, mons. Giovanni Lajolo, presidente del Governatorato della Città del Vaticano, l'allora rettore della Pontificia Università Lateranense, mons. Rino Fisichella, il Vicario Episcopale per la Vita Consacrata dell'arcidiocesi di Milano monsignor Ambrogio Piantanida e il preposito generale dei barnabiti, padre Giovanni Maria Villa.  Tra i numerosissimi fedeli (più di diecimila) accorsi da diverse parti del mondo per presenziare alla celebrazione, hanno preso parte anche personalità politiche.  Tra queste il senatore a vita Oscar Luigi Scalfaro, l'allora presidente del Senato, Franco Marini, e Arturo Parisi, al tempo Ministro della Difesa. Rosmini è il primo beato della Provincia del Verbano Cusio Ossola.  In occasione della beatificazione sono stati moltissimi i quotidiani e periodici italiani e esteri che hanno dedicato articoli, pagine e interi numeri alla figura di Rosmini.  Opere  Frontespizio dell'opera Delle cinque piaghe della santa chiesa edizione di Bruxelles (1848)  Monumento a Rosmini a Milano (1896) Sono numerosissimi gli scritti del Beato Antonio Rosmini, certamente il più importante a livello ascetico e spirituale sono le Massime di Perfezione Cristiana, su cui anche papa Giovanni XXIII fece delle riflessioni prima di morire. Gli costarono la messa all'Indice dei libri proibiti le opere "Delle Cinque Piaghe della Santa Chiesa" e "Dalla Costituzione secondo la giustizia sociale". In ambito filosofico meritano di essere ricordati:  Nuovo saggio sull'origine delle idee, 1830 Principii della scienza morale, 1831 Filosofia della morale, 1837 Antropologia in servigio della scienza morale, 1838 Filosofia della politica, 1839 Trattato della coscienza morale, 1839 Filosofia del diritto, 1841-1845 Teodicea, 1845 Sull'unità d'Italia, 1848 Il comunismo e il socialismo, 1849 Massime di perfezione cristiana Le Massime di perfezione cristiana furono scritte da Rosmini per definire il fondamento spirituale sul quale tutti i cristiani potessero avere un cammino nella perfezione.  Nel Vangelo stesso è scritto: "Siate perfetti come è perfetto il vostro Padre celeste" (Mt 5,48)  1ª Massima: Desiderare unicamente ed infinitamente di piacere a Dio, cioè di essere giusto.  2ª Massima: Orientare tutti i propri pensieri e le azioni all'incremento e alla gloria della Chiesa di Cristo.  3ª Massima: Rimanere in perfetta tranquillità circa tutto ciò che avviene per disposizione di Dio riguardo alla Chiesa di Cristo, lavorando per essa secondo la chiamata di Dio.  4ª Massima: Abbandonare se stesso nella Provvidenza di Dio.  5ª Massima: Riconoscere intimamente il proprio nulla.  6ª Massima: Disporre tutte le occupazioni della propria vita con uno spirito di intelligenza Rosmini e il Concilio Ecumenico Vaticano II Di particolare interesse fu la sua opera "Le cinque piaghe della santa Chiesa", scritta nel 1832 e pubblicata nel 1848. L'autore mostrò di discostarsi dall'ortodossia dell'epoca. Per tale ragione l'opera fu messa all'Indice sin dal 1849 e ne scaturì una polemica nota col nome di "questione rosminiana". L'opera fu riscoperta al Concilio Vaticano II. Il primo a parlare al Concilio di Rosmini fu il vescovo mons. Luigi Bettazzi, presente durante alcune sessioni in rappresentanza del cardinal Giacomo Lercaro di cui era Vicario generale.  Di Rosmini, Bettazzi disse, il 4 ottobre 1965 durante la Congregazione 141/1 periodo IV:  «...Mi sia consentito ricordare ancora in quest'aula l'esempio di Rosmini, molto legato a Tommaso, ma anche studioso e amante del suo tempo, e che certamente guadagnò a Cristo non pochi uomini contemporanei e posteriori. Tutto questo mi sembra si accordi con le cose che sono state già dette da non pochi Padri su questo schema in generale, che cioè gli uomini non si aspettano dalla Chiesa soluzioni particolari, ma piuttosto la presentazione di valori che li aiutino a trascorrere questa vita umana più nobilmente e con maggiore sicurezza. Parlando della libertà abbiamo dovuto esaltare i valori dell'umiltà; parlando del matrimonio, il ruolo della fortezza; parlando dei problemi economici e di molti altri problemi, l'efficacia di un certo disprezzo delle cose: occorre dunque mettere in luce la necessità dell'ubbidienza, della castità, della povertà, non solo nella vita e nell'esempio (e nella Bozza di Documento!) dei religiosi, aiuto agli uomini di questo tempo, perché possano vivere la loro vita umana nel modo migliore e più efficace; il primo e principale compito dunque per i cristiani che coltivano la sapienza dev'essere, alla luce del Magistero, l'amore delle Scritture e l'amore di questo mondo in un colloquio franco e aperto...»  Papa Paolo VI, in un'udienza concessa alle suore rosminiane disse a proposito di Rosmini:  «...i suoi libri sono pieni di pensiero, un pensiero profondo, originale che spazia in tutti i campi: quello filosofico, morale, politico, sociale, soprannaturale, religioso, ascetico; libri degni di essere conosciuti e divulgati... È stato anche un profeta: Le Cinque piaghe della Chiesa (una volta la chiesa non aveva piacere che si mettessero in luce le sue mancanze, le sue debolezze). Lui, per esempio, previde la partecipazione liturgica del popolo...Tutti i suoi pensieri indicano uno spirito degno di essere conosciuto, imitato e forse invocato anche come protettore dal Cielo. Ve lo auguriamo di cuore...»  Tematiche affrontate nell'opera Delle Cinque Piaghe della Santa Chiesa L'opera è suddivisa in cinque capitoli (corrispondenti ciascuna ad una piaga, paragonata alle piaghe di Cristo). In ogni capitolo la struttura è la medesima:  un quadro ottimistico della Chiesa antica segue un fatto nuovo che cambia la situazione generale (invasioni barbariche, nascita di una società cristiana, ingresso dei vescovi nella politica) la piaga i rimedi. Prima piaga. È la divisione del popolo dal clero nel culto pubblico. Nell'antichità il culto era un mezzo di catechesi e formazione e il popolo partecipava al culto. Poi, le invasioni barbariche, la scomparsa del latino, la scarsa istruzione del popolo, la tendenza del clero a formare una casta hanno eretto un muro di divisione tra il popolo e i ministri di Dio. Rimedi proposti: insegnamento del latino, spiegazione delle cerimonie liturgiche, uso di messalini in lingua volgare.  Seconda piaga. Insufficiente educazione del clero. Se un tempo i preti erano educati dai vescovi, ora ci sono i seminari con "piccoli libri" e "piccoli maestri": dura critica alla scolastica, ma soprattutto ai catechismi. Rimedio: necessità di unire scienza e pietà.  Terza piaga. Disunione tra i vescovi. Critica serrata ai vescovi dell'ancien régime: occupazioni politiche estranee al ministero sacerdotale, ambizione, servilismo verso il governo, preoccupazione di difendere ad ogni costo i beni ecclesiastici, "schiavi di uomini mollemente vestiti anziché apostoli liberi di un Cristo ignudo". Rimedi: riserve sulla difesa del patrimonio ecclesiastico, accenni espliciti di consenso alle tesi dell'Avenir sulla rinunzia alle ricchezze e allo stipendio statale per riavere la libertà.  Quarta piaga. La nomina dei vescovi lasciata al potere temporale. Rosmini compie un'approfondita analisi storica sull'evoluzione del problema e critica i concordati moderni con cui la S. Sede ha ceduto la nomina al potere statale (e, accenna prudentemente, per avere compensi economici). Rimedi: propone un ritorno all'elezione dei vescovi da parte dei fedeli.  Quinta piaga. La servitù dei beni ecclesiastici. Rosmini sostiene la necessità di offerte libere, non imposte d'autorità con l'appoggio dello Stato, rileva i danni del sistema beneficiale, propone la rinuncia ai privilegi e la pubblicazione dei bilanci.  Scuole A lui sono intolati vari istituti scolasti in città italiane.  Rovereto, sua città natale, gli ha dedicato il liceo Antonio Rosmini che frequentò quando ancora si chiamava Imperiale e Regio Ginnasio. Borgomanero ospita l'Istituto Antonio Rosmini dal 1857.[12] Domodossola ospita il liceo delle Scienze Umane "Antonio Rosmini (istituto parificato).[13] Roma ospita la sede dell'Istituto Comprensivo Antonio Rosmini.[14] Torino ospita la biblioteca Antonio Rosmini del polo biomedico universitario che in passato fu un istituto scolastico attivo fino alla fine del XX secolo.[15] Trento, dove si trova il liceo "A. Rosmini".[16] Note ^ M. Farina, pp. 15-47. ^ I. Prosser, p. 154. ^ I. Prosser, p. 129. ^ Marcello Bonazza, L'Accademia Roveretana degli Agiati (PDF), su agiati.it, Accademia Roveretana degli Agiati, 1998. URL consultato il 6 aprile 2018 (archiviato dall'url originale il 7 aprile 2018).  «Don Francesco Paoli (1808-1891)... artefice della rinascita dell'Accademia nel 1872 e suo presidente fino al 1888». ^ Antonio Rosmini, Ragionamento sul comunismo e socialismo, Giovanni Grondona, Genova 1849 ^ Questa tesi fu messa in discussione da Giacomo Andrea Abbà a cui Rosmini controbatté nel Diario filosofico di Adolfo, VII, G.A.A.(pubblicato in Riv. rosminiana, III [1908], pp. 1-8). ^ PAGANI-ROSSI, Vita di Antonio Rosmini, Vol.II, p.680 ^ http://www.rosmini.it/Resource/Causa/05%20Decreto%20Post%20Obitum%201887.pdf ^ Nota sul valore dei Decreti dottrinali concernenti il pensiero e le opere del Rev.do Sac. Antonio Rosmini Serbati, su vatican.va, 1º luglio 2001 (archiviato il 7 agosto 2001). ^ Angelus: Rosmini, esempio per la Chiesa, su agensir.it, 18 novembre 2007. ^ Biografia di Antonio Rosmini, su vatican.va. ^ Istituto Antonio Rosmini, su rosmini-borgomanero.it. URL consultato il 9 maggio 2020. ^ Liceo delle Scienze Umane "Antonio Rosmini", su cercalatuascuola.istruzione.it. URL consultato il 9 maggio 2020. ^ Istituto Comprensivo Antonio Rosmini, su ic-rosmini.edu.it. URL consultato il 9 maggio 2020. ^ Biblioteca Rosmini, su biomedico.campusnet.unito.it. URL consultato il 9 maggio 2020. ^ LICEO "A. Rosmini" - TRENTO, su vivoscuola.it. URL consultato il 9 maggio 2020. Bibliografia Fonti Marcello Farina, Antonio Rosmini e l'Accademia degli Agiati, Brescia, Morcelliana Edizioni, 2000, ISBN 88-372-1805-2. Italo Prosser, El pra' de le Móneghe: cronistoria del monastero di Santa Croce nell'antico comune di Lizzana, Rovereto (Trento), Stella, 2003, SBN IT\ICCU\TO0\1613699. Approfondimenti Michele Federico Sciacca, La filosofia morale di Antonio Rosmini, Torino, Fratelli Bocca, 1955. Giovanni Pusineri, Rosmini (Edizione riveduta e aggiornata da Remo Bessero Belti), Stresa (VB), Edizioni Rosminiane Sodalitas, 1989. Michele Dossi, Profilo filosofico di Antonio Rosmini, Brescia, Morcelliana, 1998, ISBN 88-372-1687-4. Alfeo Valle, Antonio Rosmini. Il carisma del fondatore, Rovereto (TN), Longo Editore, 1991. Paolo Marangon, Il Risorgimento della Chiesa. Genesi e ricezione delle "Cinque piaghe" di A. Rosmini, collana Italia Sacra, Roma, Casa Editrice Herder, 2000. Antonio Rosmini, Frammenti di una storia della empietà, a c. di Alfredo Cattabiani con una nota filologica di M. Albertazzi, Trento, La Finestra, 2003. Fulvio De Giorgi, Rosmini e il suo tempo. L'educazione dell'uomo moderno tra riforma della filosofia e rinnovamento della Chiesa (1797-1833), Brescia, Morcelliana, 2003. Michele Dossi, Il Santo Probito, La vita e il pensiero di Antonio Rosmini, Trento, Il Margine, 2007, ISBN 978-88-6089-021-4. Paolo Gomarasca, Rosmini e la forma morale dell'essere. La "poiesi" del bene come destino della metafisica, Milano, FrancoAngeli, 1998. Francesco Paoli, Antonio Rosmini, Virtù quotidiane, Verona, Edizioni Fede & Cultura, 2007. ISBN 978-88-89913-27-7 Maurizio De Paoli, Antonio Rosmini. Maestro e profeta, Milano, Edizioni San Paolo, 2007. Piero Sapienza, Eclissi Dell'educazione? La sfida educativa nel pensiero di Rosmini, Roma, Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 2008. Giuseppe Goisis, Il pensiero politico di Antonio Rosmini e altri saggi fra critica ed Evangelo, S. Pietro in Cariano (VR), Gabrielli Editori, 2009. Comunità di San Leolino (a cura di), Una profezia per la Chiesa. Antonio Rosmini verso il Vaticano II, Panzano in Chianti (FI), Edizioni Feeria-Comunità di San Leolino, 2009. Umberto Muratore, Rosmini per il Risorgimento. Tra unità e federalismo, Stresa (VB), Edizioni Rosmininane Sodalitas, 2010. Cirillo Bergamaschi, Antonio Rosmini. La perfezione della vita cristiana, Stresa (VB), Edizioni Rosminiane Sodalitas, 2010. Luciano Malusa, Antonio Rosmini per l'unità d'Italia. Tra aspirazione nazionale e fede cristiana, Milano, FrancoAngeli, 2011. Domenico Fisichella, Il caso Rosmini. Cattolicesimo, nazione, federalismo, Roma, Carocci editore, 2011. Umberto Muratore, Apologia della fedeltà. In difesa dei valori etici e spirituali, Stresa (VB), Edizioni Rosminiane Sodalitas, 2011. Luciano Malusa, Stefania Zanardi, Le lettere di Antonio Rosmini-Serbati, un "cantiere" per lo studioso. Introduzione all'epistolario rosminiano, Venezia, Marsilio Editore, 2013. Stefania Zanardi, La filosofia di Antonio Rosmini di fronte alla Congregazione dell'Indice (1850-1854), con Prefazione di Fulvio De Giorgi, Milano, FrancoAngeli, 2018.  Voci correlate Restaurazione Antonio Fogazzaro Altri progetti Collabora a Wikisource Wikisource contiene una pagina dedicata a Antonio Rosmini Collabora a Wikiquote Wikiquote contiene citazioni di o su Antonio Rosmini Collabora a Wikimedia Commons Wikimedia Commons contiene immagini o altri file su Antonio Rosmini Collegamenti esterni Sito ufficiale, su rosmini.it. Modifica su Wikidata Antonio Rosmini, su Treccani.it – Enciclopedie on line, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Modifica su Wikidata Antonio Rosmini, in Enciclopedia Italiana, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Modifica su Wikidata Antonio Rosmini, in Dizionario di storia, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana, 2010. Modifica su Wikidata (EN) Antonio Rosmini, su Enciclopedia Britannica, Encyclopædia Britannica, Inc. Modifica su Wikidata Antonio Rosmini, in Dizionario biografico degli italiani, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Modifica su Wikidata Antonio Rosmini, su accademicidellacrusca.org, Accademia della Crusca. Modifica su Wikidata Antonio Rosmini, su BeWeb, Conferenza Episcopale Italiana. Modifica su Wikidata (DE) Antonio Rosmini (XML), in Dizionario biografico austriaco 1815-1950. Modifica su Wikidata (EN) Antonio Rosmini, su Find a Grave. Modifica su Wikidata Opere di Antonio Rosmini, su Liber Liber. Modifica su Wikidata Opere di Antonio Rosmini, su openMLOL, Horizons Unlimited srl. Modifica su Wikidata (EN) Opere di Antonio Rosmini / Antonio Rosmini (altra versione), su Open Library, Internet Archive. Modifica su Wikidata (EN) Antonio Rosmini, in Catholic Encyclopedia, Robert Appleton Company. Modifica su Wikidata Antonio Rosmini, su Santi, beati e testimoni, santiebeati.it. Modifica su Wikidata Sito ufficiale degli scritti di Antonio Rosmini, su rosminionline.it. Un esteso saggio inedito su Antonio Rosmini si puà trovare sul Blog di Carlo Ellena (EN) Edward N. Zalta (a cura di), Antonio Rosmini, in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Center for the Study of Language and Information (CSLI), Università di Stanford. Controllo di autorità                          VIAF (EN) 49636 · ISNI (EN) 0000 0001 2117 2715 · SBN IT\ICCU\CFIV\005649 · LCCN (EN) n79065278 · GND (DE) 118602888 · BNF (FR) cb121577279 (data) · BNE (ES) XX1164389 (data) · NLA (EN) 36549484 · BAV (EN) 495/21332 · CERL cnp00905104 · WorldCat Identities (EN) lccn-n79065278 Biografie Portale Biografie Cattolicesimo Portale Cattolicesimo Filosofia Portale Filosofia Categorie: Filosofi italiani del XIX secoloTeologi italianiPresbiteri italianiNati nel 1797Morti nel 1855Nati il 24 marzoMorti il 1º luglioNati a RoveretoMorti a StresaBeati italiani del XIX secoloBeati proclamati da Benedetto XVIFondatori di società e istituti cattoliciPersonalità del cattolicesimoMembri dell'Accademia delle Scienze di TorinoFederalistiUomini universaliPersone legate all'Accademia Roveretana degli AgiatiFilosofi cattoliciRosminiani[altre]. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Rosmini e Grice,” per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.

rosselli: important Italian philosopher – There is a Rosselli Circle in Rome – Carlo Rosselli Da Wikipedia, l'enciclopedia libera. Jump to navigationJump to search  Carlo Rosselli Carlo Alberto[1] Rosselli (Roma, 16 novembre 1899 – Bagnoles-de-l'Orne, 9 giugno 1937) è stato un attivista, giornalista, filosofo, storico ed antifascista italiano.  Fu il teorico del "socialismo liberale", un socialismo riformista non marxista direttamente ispirato dal laburismo britannico e dalla tradizione storico-politica, italiana e non, del radicalismo liberale e libertario. Nel 1925 fondò a Firenze il foglio clandestino Non Mollare e nel 1926, insieme al socialista Pietro Nenni, la rivista milanese Il Quarto Stato. Fondò nel 1929 a Parigi il movimento antifascista Giustizia e Libertà, che nel 1936 combatté per la Repubblica nella Guerra civile spagnola, all'interno della Colonna Italiana Rosselli, costituita assieme agli anarchici. Nel 1937 fu ucciso in Francia insieme con il fratello Nello da assassini legati al regime fascista.  Magnifying glass icon mgx2.svgLo stesso argomento in dettaglio: Fratelli Rosselli.  Nello Rosselli  Indice 1Biografia 1.1La nascita, la guerra e gli studi 1.2                                     L'avvento del fascismo e l'inizio della lotta 1.3Il confino e la fuga da Lipari 1.4L'esilio a Parigi. La nascita di "Giustizia e Libertà" 1.5L'impegno nella guerra civile spagnola 1.6L'assassinio 2Il pensiero 3Note 4Bibliografia 4.1Opere di Carlo Rosselli 4.2Opere su Carlo Rosselli 5Altri progetti 6Collegamenti esterni Biografia La nascita, la guerra e gli studi  Amelia Pincherle, madre di Carlo. Rosselli nacque a Roma  il 16 novembre del 1899 da un'agiata famiglia ebraica, secondogenito dei tre figli del livornese Giuseppe Emanuele "Joe" Rosselli (10 agosto 1867 - Firenze, 9 settembre 1911) e della veneziana Amelia Pincherle (16 gennaio 1870 - Firenze, 26 dicembre 1954), sorella di Carlo Pincherle, architetto e pittore, oltreché padre dello scrittore Alberto Moravia. Sia la famiglia paterna che quella materna, fermamente legate agli ideali repubblicani e mazziniani, erano state politicamente attive, avendo partecipato alle vicende del Risorgimento italiano: Pellegrino Rosselli, tra l'altro zio della futura moglie di Ernesto Nathan (Sindaco di Roma dal novembre del 1907 al dicembre del 1913), fu un seguace e stretto collaboratore di Giuseppe Mazzini nei suoi ultimi anni di vita (morì difatti in clandestinità nella sua casa pisana) ed un Pincherle fu nominato ministro durante la breve esperienza della Repubblica di San Marco, instauratasi nel Triveneto a seguito d'una massiccia insurrezione anti-asburgica guidata da Daniele Manin e Niccolò Tommaseo.  I Rosselli avevano abitato per un considerevole periodo a Vienna, dove Giuseppe Emanuele aveva studiato composizione musicale e dove, nel 1895, era nato il primogenito Aldo Sabatino. In seguito, si trasferirono a Roma, dove il padre, rinunciando alle sue aspirazioni artistiche, si dedicò alla vita mondana, mentre la madre ottenne dei discreti successi come autrice di drammi teatrali. Qui, dopo la propria nascita, venne alla luce, l'anno seguente, il terzogenito Sabatino Enrico "Nello".  Nel 1903, i due coniugi si separarono: le condizioni economiche della famiglia avevano subito un grave tracollo a causa della leggerezza del padre. Amelia si trasferì con i suoi tre figli a Firenze, dove frequentarono le scuole: Carlo mostrò in quel periodo poco interesse per gli studi e la madre lo ritirò dal ginnasio, facendogli frequentare le scuole tecniche. Nel 1911 morì il padre.  L'entrata in guerra dell'Italia, nel 1915, fu accolta con entusiasmo dalla famiglia Rosselli, decisamente interventista. Il fratello Aldo fu arruolato come ufficiale di fanteria e morì in combattimento nel 1916, ricevendo una medaglia d'argento alla memoria. Carlo, ancora studente, collaborava dal 1917 al foglio di propaganda «Noi giovani», fondato dal fratello Nello, anche se l'editoriale Il nostro programma, che aprì in gennaio il primo numero del giornale, fu redatto con buone probabilità assieme a Carlo.  Il manifesto, che l'ingenuità di due ragazzi indirizzava verso una fiduciosa speranza in un mondo migliore, proponeva sin da allora alcuni tratti fondamentali della personalità di Carlo, ossia un amore incondizionato per l'umanità e la spinta all'azione nel solco dello spirito mazziniano, che lo inserisce nel filone dell'interventismo democratico. Per «Noi giovani», licenziò i primi articoli, uno in aprile sulla rivoluzione russa di febbraio, il secondo nel mese successivo vertente sull'entrata in guerra degli Stati Uniti.  Il primo testo, Libera Russia, esalta il risveglio del paese di Gorkij, Tolstoj e Dostoevskij, supremi interpreti di un rinnovamento in atto già dal secolo precedente, per cui la rivoluzione di febbraio non era che il punto culminante di una lunga preparazione all'avvento di una società più giusta. Vi «era tutta una massa che saliva lentamente, inesorabilmente. La marcia si poteva ritardare ma non impedire». Dei recentissimi eventi, inoltre, viene esaltata la componente "pacifica", la loro attuazione relativamente non violenta.  L'articolo Wilson mostra tutta la fiducia nutrita per l'uomo che definì il conflitto come «a war to end wars» (una guerra per porre fine alle guerre), uno slogan che rappresentava bene le speranze di Carlo e di tutta la famiglia Rosselli.[2]  In giugno fu chiamato alle armi: frequentò a Caserta il corso allievi ufficiali e venne assegnato nell'aprile del 1918 a un battaglione di alpini in Valtellina. La guerra finì senza che egli avesse dovuto sottomettersi al battesimo del fuoco e venne congedato col grado di tenente nel febbraio 1920.  Il contatto con i giovani militari appartenenti ai ceti più popolari fu molto importante per Rosselli e per altri studenti come lui: «apprezzarono la massa [...] furon posti in grado di comprendere tante cose che sarebbero loro certamente sfuggite nel loro isolamento di classe o di professione».   Gaetano Salvemini Diplomatosi all'Istituto tecnico, si iscrisse a Firenze al corso di Scienze sociali, laureandosi a pieni voti il 4 luglio 1921 con una tesi sul sindacalismo e si preparò a sostenere anche gli esami di maturità classica per ottenere il diritto di frequentare altri corsi universitari. Tramite il fratello Nello aveva conosciuto Gaetano Salvemini, professore dell'Università fiorentina, che sarà da allora un costante punto di riferimento per entrambi i fratelli. Gli fece rivedere la sua tesi, che Salvemini giudicò «non un'opera critica, equilibrata, sostanziosa», ma in essa «era incapsulata un'idea fondamentale: la ricerca di un socialismo che facesse sua la dottrina liberale e non la ripudiasse».  In questo periodo si avvicinò al Partito Socialista Italiano, simpatizzando, in contrapposizione all'allora maggioritaria corrente massimalista di Giacinto Menotti Serrati, per quella riformista di Filippo Turati, che egli ebbe poi modo di conoscere personalmente a Livorno nel 1921, durante lo svolgimento del Congresso nazionale del Partito, che sancì la definitiva scissione dell'ala di sinistra interna filo-bolscevica del Partito, che prenderà il nome di Partito Comunista d'Italia, e scrisse svariati articoli per la sua rivista Critica Sociale.  L'avvento del fascismo e l'inizio della lotta Nell'ottobre del 1922 Mussolini salì al potere; i riformisti di Turati vennero espulsi dal PSI.  In dicembre Carlo Rosselli si trasferì a Torino, dove frequentò il gruppo della rivista gobettiana «La Rivoluzione liberale», in quel momento fortemente impegnata in senso antifascista, e con la quale, dall'aprile 1923, incominciò a collaborare. Conobbe Giacomo Matteotti, segretario dell'appena fondato Partito Socialista Unitario, nel quale erano confluiti Piero Gobetti e la componente riformista espulsa dal PSI.   Ernesto Rossi Nel febbraio del 1923, a Firenze, il gruppo dei socialisti liberali che si raccoglieva intorno alla figura carismatica di Salvemini inaugurò il «Circolo di Cultura». Oltre ai Rosselli vi erano: Piero Calamandrei, Enrico Finzi, Gino Frontali, Piero Jahier, Ludovico Limentani, Alfredo Niccoli ed Ernesto Rossi. Gli ex-combattenti del circolo, nel 1923, aderirono all'associazione antifascista Italia libera.  Qualche mese dopo, il 9 luglio, Carlo si laureò in giurisprudenza all'università di Siena, con la tesi Prime linee di una teoria economica dei sindacati operai e partì per Londra, stimolato dal desiderio di conoscere la capitale del laburismo, di seguire i seminari della Fabian Society e di assistere, a Plymouth, al congresso delle Trade Unions. A Londra vi era anche Salvemini, che teneva un corso sulla storia della politica estera italiana al King's College.  Tornato in Italia in ottobre, grazie anche ai buoni uffici di Salvemini, si impiegò come assistente volontario nella Facoltà di economia dell'Università Bocconi a Milano, dove trasferì il suo domicilio. Proseguì la sua collaborazione alla «Critica Sociale» di Turati: in novembre vi pubblicò un articolo, invitando il Partito socialista a rompere con il marxismo, che egli giudicava espressione di «cieco e tortuoso dogmatismo», per mettersi piuttosto sulla linea di un «sano empirismo all'inglese».  Nel febbraio del 1924, inaugurò la sua collaborazione con la rivista della Federazione giovanile del PSU, «Libertà», scrivendo proprio un articolo sul movimento laburista inglese. Pochi mesi dopo il delitto Matteotti s'iscrisse al P.S.U..  Rosselli sperava invano che in Italia si costituisse una seria opposizione antifascista moderata in grado di offrire un'alternativa politica alla borghesia che guarda con simpatia al fascismo: una di queste avrebbe potuto essere l'Unione democratica nazionale di Giovanni Amendola, alla quale aderì il fratello Nello. In settembre Carlo era in Inghilterra, da dove inviava al giornale del PSU, la «Giustizia», le corrispondenze sull'evolversi della situazione politica inglese, successiva alla vittoria elettorale dei conservatori e alla rottura dell'alleanza tra laburisti e liberali.   Piero Calamandrei Era pessimista sulle condizioni politiche dell'Italia: la secessione aventiniana non produceva effetti, con i suoi sterili tentativi di accordo con il re, con i generali e i fascisti dissidenti. Del resto i fascisti stavano reagendo e lo dimostrarono anche devastando, il 31 dicembre 1924, il «Circolo di Cultura» di Salvemini che, come non bastasse, venne chiuso dal prefetto con una singolare motivazione: «la sua attività provoca il giusto risentimento del partito dominante»[3].  Lasciato l'incarico alla Bocconi, Rosselli passò a insegnare Istituzioni di economia politica a Genova. Scrisse a Salvemini: «forse non avrà apparentemente alcuna positiva efficacia, ma io sento che abbiamo da assolvere una grande funzione, dando esempi di carattere e di forza morale alla generazione che viene dopo di noi». Appare così, nel gennaio 1925, con la collaborazione di Ernesto Rossi, Gaetano Salvemini, Piero Calamandrei, Nello Traquandi, Dino Vannucci e di Nello Rosselli, che ne ha proposto il nome, il foglio clandestino Non Mollare.   Alcuni redattori della rivista Non Mollare nel 1925: Nello Traquandi, Tommaso Ramorino, Carlo Rosselli, Ernesto Rossi, Luigi Emery, Nello Rosselli. In maggio  la denuncia di un tipografo provocò la repressione e la dispersione di alcuni tra i redattori del foglio: Ernesto Rossi riuscì a fuggire a Parigi, il Vannucci in Brasile, Salvemini fu arrestato l'8 giugno a Roma e denunciato per «vilipendio del governo». In attesa del processo, messo in libertà provvisoria, a causa delle minacce dei fascisti, a luglio passò la notte a Firenze, in casa dei Rosselli, che non erano ancora fra i sospettati: gli squadristi però, venuti a conoscenza del fatto, devastarono l'abitazione il giorno dopo. Scrisse Rosselli a Giovanni Ansaldo: «Io sono di ottimo umore e l'altra sera ho financo bevuto alla distruzione compiuta! Se i signori fascisti non hanno altri moccoli, possono andare a dormire: aspetteranno a lungo la mia rinuncia alla lotta».  Ormai preso di mira dai fascisti, Rosselli fu aggredito a Genova mentre si recava all'Università e poi disturbato durante la sua lezione, con la richiesta del suo allontanamento. Nel luglio del 1926 si attivò infine lo stesso Ministro dell'economia, Giuseppe Belluzzo, che chiese il suo licenziamento. A questo punto, preferì dimettersi.  Pochi giorni dopo, il 25 aprile, a Firenze, sposò con rito civile Marion Catherine Cave, una giovane laburista inglese che era venuta nel 1919 a Firenze a insegnare lingua inglese nel British Institute, conosciuta da Rosselli nel 1923 al Circolo della Cultura salveminiano.   Milano - Lapide commemorativa: «In via Ancona 2 visse nel 1926 il martire antifascista Carlo Rosselli e qui ebbe sede la redazione del Quarto Stato rivista socialista a difesa della libertà e della democrazia». I due sposi vissero a Milano, dove Carlo aveva fondato insieme con Pietro Nenni la rivista «Il Quarto Stato», il cui primo numero uscì il 27 marzo 1926. La rivista avrà vita breve, venendo chiusa a novembre con l'entrata in vigore della legge sui «provvedimenti per la difesa dello Stato».  Scopo della pubblicazione era il tentativo di rappresentare un punto d'incontro di tutte le forze socialiste e di sviluppare temi di politica culturale al cui centro fosse «il perfezionamento della personalità umana» e l'elevamento della «vita spirituale e materiale» dei cittadini.  Il 26 novembre 1925 Rosselli, con Claudio Treves e Giuseppe Saragat costituì un triumvirato che, il 29 novembre successivo, costituì clandestinamente il Partito Socialista dei Lavoratori Italiani (PSLI), che prese il posto del P.S.U., sciolto d'imperio dal regime fascista, il 14 novembre, a causa del fallito attentato a Mussolini da parte del suo iscritto Tito Zaniboni, avvenuto il 4 novembre precedente.  Il confino e la fuga da Lipari  12 dicembre 1926 - Lorenzo De Bova, Filippo Turati, Carlo Rosselli, Sandro Pertini e Ferruccio Parri a Calvi in Corsica dopo la fuga in motoscafo da Savona.  Filippo Turati Alla fine del 1926 organizzò con Italo Oxilia[4], Sandro Pertini e Ferruccio Parri l'espatrio di Filippo Turati a Calvi in Corsica, con un motoscafo partito da Savona. Mentre Turati, Pertini e Oxilia proseguirono per Nizza, Parri e Rosselli, ritornati con il motoscafo a Marina di Carrara, furono arrestati, nonostante tentassero di sostenere di essere reduci da una gita di piacere.  Rosselli fu accusato anche di aver favorito la fuga in Svizzera di Giovanni Ansaldo, di Claudio Silvestri, di Claudio Treves e di Giuseppe Saragat.  Venne detenuto nelle carceri di Como fino al maggio del 1927 e poi inviato al confino[5] di Lipari in attesa del processo.  L'8 giugno nacque suo figlio Giovanni Andrea "John". Quando Carlo fu ricondotto da Lipari a Savona per essere processato, nell'isola siciliana giungeva il fratello Nello, condannato a 5 anni di confino.[6]  Al processo, che si aprì il 9 settembre, Rosselli si difese attaccando il regime: «il responsabile primo e unico, che la coscienza degli uomini liberi incrimina è il fascismo [...] che con la legge del bastone, strumento della sua potenza e della sua Nemesi, ha inchiodato in servitù milioni di cittadini, gettandoli nella tragica alternativa della supina acquiescenza o della fame o dell'esilio».  La sentenza, rispetto alle previsioni, fu mite: dieci mesi di reclusione e, avendone già scontati otto, Rosselli avrebbe potuto essere presto libero, ma le nuove leggi speciali permisero alla polizia di infliggergli altri 3 anni di confino da scontare a Lipari.   Emilio Lussu Lì venne raggiunto dalla moglie e dal figlio: la vita al confino trascorreva con le letture di Croce, di Mondolfo, dell'epistolario di Marx ed Engels e di Kant.  Intanto, si preparava la fuga, che venne organizzata da Parigi dall'amico di Salvemini Alberto Tarchiani.  Il 27 luglio 1929 Rosselli evase dall'isola, insieme con Francesco Fausto Nitti ed Emilio Lussu, con un motoscafo guidato dall'amico Italo Oxilia diretto in Tunisia, da cui poi i fuggiaschi raggiunsero la Francia.[7]   Francesco Fausto Nitti Nitti narrerà l'avventurosa evasione nel libro Le nostre prigioni e la nostra evasione, pubblicato quello stesso anno in inglese col titolo di Escape e in edizione italiana nel 1946, mentre Rosselli racconterà le vicende del confino e dell'evasione in Fuga in quattro tempi.  La moglie Marion, che aspettava la seconda figlia, Amelia "Melina", nata il successivo 28 marzo, venne in un primo tempo arrestata per complicità, ma presto fu rilasciata.  L'esilio a Parigi. La nascita di "Giustizia e Libertà"  Carlo Rosselli (in piedi) con Claudio Treves e Filippo Turati in esilio a Parigi nel 1932. Nel 1929 a Parigi, con Lussu, Nitti, e un gruppo di fuoriusciti organizzati da Salvemini, fu fra i fondatori del movimento antifascista "Giustizia e Libertà". GL pubblicò diversi numeri della rivista e dei quaderni omonimi (con cadenza settimanale e mensile) e fu attiva nell'organizzazione di diverse azioni dimostrative, tra cui il volo sopra Milano di Bassanesi nel 1930.  Nello stesso anno pubblicò, in francese, Socialisme liberal. Il libro è una critica appassionata del marxismo ortodosso, colonna portante della stragrande maggioranza dei vari schieramenti politici socialisti dell'epoca. Il "socialismo liberale" propugnato da Rosselli si caratterizza quale una creativa sintesi della tradizione del marxismo revisionista, democratico e riformista (quello, tra gli altri, di Eduard Bernstein, Werner Sombart, Turati e Treves), ed il socialismo non marxista, libertario e decentralista (come quello di Francesco Merlino, Salvemini, G. D. H. Cole, R. H. Tawney e Oszkár Jászi); il testo, però, contiene anche un attacco dirompente contro lo stalinismo della Terza Internazionale che, con la formula del "socialfascismo", accomunava socialdemocrazia, liberalismo "borghese" e fascismo.  Non stupisce perciò che uno fra i più importanti stalinisti, Palmiro Togliatti, abbia definito "Socialismo liberale" un "magro libello antisocialista" e Rosselli "un ideologo reazionario che nessuna cosa lega alla classe operaia".   Il logo di Giustizia e Libertà Nell'ottobre del 1931 Giustizia e Libertà aderì alla Concentrazione Antifascista, unione di tutte le forze antifasciste non comuniste (repubblicani, socialisti, CGL) che intendeva promuovere e coordinare dall'estero ogni possibile azione di lotta al fascismo in Italia; si iniziarono a pubblicare i "Quaderni di Giustizia e Libertà".  Dopo l'avvento del nazismo in Germania nel 1933, GL sostenne la necessità di una rivoluzione preventiva per rovesciare i regimi fascista e nazista prima che questi portassero a una nuova tragica guerra, che a GL sembrava l'inevitabile destino dei due regimi.  L'impegno nella guerra civile spagnola  Bandiera della Colonna Italiana, nota anche come Centuria Giustizia e Libertà, che sostenne i repubblicani nella guerra civile spagnola. Nel 1936 scoppiò in Spagna la guerra civile tra i rivoltosi dell'esercito filo-monarchico, che effettuarono un colpo di Stato, e il legittimo governo repubblicano del Fronte Popolare di ispirazione marxista. Rosselli fu subito attivo nel sostegno alle forze repubblicane, criticando l'immobilismo di Francia e Inghilterra, mentre fascisti e nazisti aiutavano Francisco Franco con uomini e armi agli insorti.  Nell'agosto combatté la sua prima battaglia in Spagna, nei dintorni di Huesca sul fronte di Aragona; cercò poi di costituire un vero e proprio battaglione (intitolato a Giacomo Matteotti).  La prima formazione italiana, che prenderà poi, dopo l'uccisione dei due fratelli, il nome di Colonna Italiana Rosselli, annoverava tra i 50 e i 150 uomini, reclutati fra gli esuli italiani in Francia dal movimento Giustizia e Libertà e dal Comitato Anarchico Italiano Pro Spagna; tra questi c'erano anche gli anarchici Umberto Marzocchi e Camillo Berneri. Umberto Marzocchi scrisse un libro sulla comune esperienza antifascista di anarchici e di militanti di Giustizia e Libertà, "Carlo Rosselli e gli anarchici".  In un discorso a Radio Barcellona il 13 novembre 1936[8], Rosselli pronuncia la frase che poi diverrà il motto degli antifascisti italiani: "Oggi qui, domani in Italia":  «È con questa speranza segreta che siamo accorsi in Ispagna. Oggi qui, domani in Italia. Fratelli, compagni italiani, ascoltate. È un volontario italiano che vi parla dalla Radio di Barcellona. Non prestate fede alle notizie bugiarde della stampa fascista, che dipinge i rivoluzionari spagnuoli come orde di pazzi sanguinari alla vigilia della sconfitta.»  Nel dicembre 1936 in seguito a contrasti con gli anarchici si dimette da comandante della Colonna e nel gennaio 1937 fonda il battaglione Matteotti.  L'assassinio Nel giugno 1937 soggiornò a Bagnoles-de-l'Orne per delle cure termali, località dove fu raggiunto dal fratello Nello.  Il 9 giugno i due furono uccisi da una squadra di "cagoulards", miliziani della "Cagoule", formazione eversiva di destra francese, su mandato, forse, dei servizi segreti fascisti e di Galeazzo Ciano; con un pretesto vennero fatti scendere dall'automobile, poi colpiti da raffiche di pistola: Carlo morì sul colpo, Nello (colpito per primo) venne finito con un'arma da taglio.[9][10]. I corpi vennero trovati due giorni dopo; i colpevoli, dopo numerosi processi, riusciranno quasi tutti a essere prosciolti.  I fratelli Rosselli furono sepolti nel cimitero monumentale parigino del Père Lachaise, ma nel 1951 i familiari ne traslarono le salme in Italia, nel Cimitero Monumentale di Trespiano, nel piccolo borgo omonimo, comune di Firenze, sulla via Bolognese.  L'anziano Salvemini tenne il discorso commemorativo funebre, alla presenza del presidente della Repubblica Luigi Einaudi. La tomba dei due eroi dell'antifascismo si trova nel riquadro subito a destra dell'ingresso.  Nello stesso cimitero sono sepolti anche Gaetano Salvemini, Ernesto Rossi, Piero Calamandrei e Spartaco Lavagnini.  La tomba riporta il simbolo della "spada di fiamma", emblema di GL, e l'epitaffio scritto da Calamandrei:  «GIUSTIZIA E LIBERTA' PER QUESTO MORIRONO PER QUESTO VIVONO»  Il pensiero  Giuseppe Mazzini L'unico suo libro pubblicato mentre era in vita è "Socialismo liberale", scritto durante il confino a Lipari, in una situazione di semi-prigionia. Questa opera si pone in una posizione eretica rispetto ai partiti della sinistra italiana del suo tempo (per i quali Il Capitale di Marx, variamente interpretato, era ancora considerato come la Bibbia).  Indubbiamente è presente l'influsso del laburismo inglese, da lui ben conosciuto. In seguito ai successi elettorali del partito laburista, Rosselli era infatti convinto che l'insieme delle regole della democrazia liberale fossero essenziali non solo per raggiungere il socialismo, ma anche per la sua concreta realizzazione (mentre nella tattica leninista queste regole, una volta preso il potere, debbono essere accantonate): pertanto, la sintesi del pensiero rosselliano è: "il liberalismo come metodo, il socialismo come fine".   Carlo Pisacane L'idea di rivoluzione propria della dottrina marxista era fondata sulla concezione della dittatura del proletariato (che, in realtà, già ai tempi di Rosselli si sta traducendo, in Unione Sovietica, nella dittatura del vertice di un solo partito). Essa viene respinta da Rosselli, a favore di una rivoluzione che, come si nota nel programma di GL, è un sistema coerente di riforme strutturali mirate alla costruzione di un sistema socialista che non rinnega, ma anzi esalta, la libertà individuale e associativa. Nella riflessione degli ultimi anni, Rosselli, alla luce dell'esperienza spagnola (difesa dell'organizzazione sociale di Barcellona compiuta dagli anarchici durante la guerra civile) e dell'avanzata del nazismo, radicalizza le sue posizioni libertarie.  Rosselli, influenzato dalle idee di Mazzini e di Carlo Pisacane, propugna il socialismo liberale: il fine è il socialismo, il metodo il liberalismo, un metodo che garantisce la democrazia e l'autogoverno dei cittadini. Il liberalismo deve svolgere una funzione democratica, il "metodo liberale" è il complesso di regole del gioco che tutte le parti in lotta si impegnano a rispettare, regole dirette ad assicurare la pacifica convivenza dei cittadini, delle classi, degli Stati, a contenere le lotte (peraltro desiderabili se limitate). La violenza è giustificabile come risposta ad altra violenza (per questo era giusta la lotta contro il franchismo e sarebbe stata auspicabile in Italia una rivoluzione violenta in risposta al fascismo); il socialismo è una logica conclusione del liberalismo: socialismo significa libertà per tutti. Rosselli ha fiducia che la classe del futuro sarà la classe proletaria, la borghesia deve fare da guida al proletariato: il fine è la libertà per tutte le classi.  Note ^ Archivio Rosselli - Bio, su archiviorosselli.it. URL consultato il 4 luglio 2019 (archiviato dall'url originale il 27 maggio 2016). ^ N. Tranfaglia, Carlo Rosselli dall'interventismo a Giustizia e Libertà, Bari, Laterza, 1968, pp. 18-20 ^ Il Circolo di Cultura fu rifondato nel settembre 1944, a liberazione di Firenze appena avvenuta, per iniziativa del Partito d'Azione e dei soci superstiti e intitolato ai Fratelli Rosselli. Assunse così il nome di Circolo di Cultura Politica Fratelli Rosselli. La sua prima manifestazione fu presieduta da Piero Calamandrei. Con questo nome è tuttora operante a Firenze. Nel 1990 con decreto del Presidente della Repubblica è stata costituita ed eretta in Ente Morale la Fondazione Circolo Rosselli per sostenerne l'attività. ^ Antonio Martino: Fuorusciti e confinati dopo l'espatrio clandestino di Filippo Turati nelle carte della R. Questura di Savona in Atti e Memorie della Società Savonese di Storia Patria, n.s., vol. XLIII, Savona 2007, pp. 453-516. e Pertini e altri socialisti savonesi nelle carte della R.Questura, Gruppo editoriale L'espresso, Roma, 2009. ^ Cfr. Commissione di Milano, ordinanza del 15.12.1926 contro Carlo Rosselli (“Intensa attività antifascista; tra gli ideatori del giornale clandestino Non Mollare uscito a Firenze nel 1925; favoreggiamento nell'espatrio di Turati e Pertini”). In: Adriano Dal Pont, Simonetta Carolini, L'Italia al confino 1926-1943. Le ordinanze di assegnazione al confino emesse dalle Commissioni provinciali dal novembre 1926 al luglio 1943, Milano 1983 (ANPPIA/La Pietra), vol. III, p. 238 ^ Cfr. Commissione di Firenze, ordinanza del 3.6.1927 contro Nello Rosselli (“Attività antifascista”). In: Adriano Dal Pont, Simonetta Carolini, L'Italia al confino 1926-1943. Le ordinanze di assegnazione al confino emesse dalle Commissioni provinciali dal novembre 1926 al luglio 1943, Milano 1983 (ANPPIA/La Pietra), vol. III, p. 1051 ^ Cfr. La storia sotto inchiesta: Fuga da Lipari, un esilio per la liberta trasmesso da Rai Storia il 3 gennaio 2012. ^ Il discorso di Rosselli su Romacivica.net Archiviato il 29 settembre 2007 in Internet Archive. ^ Giuseppe Fiori, Casa Rosselli, Einaudi, 1999, pp. 202 e segg. ^ Mimmo Franzinelli, Il delitto Rosselli. 9 giugno 1937. Anatomia di un omicidio politico, Mondadori, Milano 2007. Bibliografia Opere di Carlo Rosselli Oggi in Spagna, domani in Italia, prefazione di Gaetano Salvemini, Edizioni di «Giustizia e libertà», Parigi, 1938; seconda edizione, introduzione di Aldo Garosci, Einaudi, Torino, 1967. Scritti politici e autobiografici, prefazione di Gaetano Salvemini, Polis editrice, Napoli, 1944; seconda edizione a cura di Zeffiro Ciuffoletti e Vincenzo Caciulli, Lacaita, Manduria 1992. Lettere di Carlo e Nello Rosselli a Gaetano Salvemini (1925), a cura di Nicola Tranfaglia, «Annali della Fondazione Luigi Einaudi», I (1967), Torino. Carlo Rosselli, Socialismo liberale, Einaudi, 1973. «Il Quarto Stato» di Pietro Nenni e Rosselli, a cura di Domenico Zucàro, SugarCo, Milano, 1977. Epistolario familiare.(1914-1937), introduzione di Leo Valiani, prefazione di Zeffiro Ciuffoletti, SugarCo, Milano, 1979. Socialismo liberale, a cura di John Rosselli, introduzione di Norberto Bobbio, Einaudi, Torino, 1979. Socialismo liberale, a cura di John Rosselli, introduzione e commento di Norberto Bobbio, «Attualità del socialismo liberale» e «Tradizione ed eredità del liberalsocialismo», seconda edizione Einaudi Tascabili. Saggi, 1997, pp. 164. Scritti dell'esilio. I. «Giustizia e libertà» e la concentrazione antifascista (1929-1934), a cura di Costanzo Casucci, Collana Opere scelte di Carlo Rosselli, Einaudi, Torino, 1988 (contiene una cronologia della vita e la bibliografia di C. Rosselli dal 1929 al 1934). Scritti politici, a cura di Zeffiro Ciuffoletti e Paolo Bagnoli, Guida, Napoli, 1988,[1] una grossa anteprima del libri consultabile in rete. Scritti dell'esilio II. Dallo scioglimento della concentrazione antifascista alla guerra di Spagna (1934-1937), a cura di Costanzo Casucci, Einaudi, Torino, 1992, (è riportata la cronologia della vita e una bibliografia di Carlo Rosselli dal 1934 al 1937). Liberalismo socialista e socialismo liberale, a cura di Nicola Terraciano, Galzerano Editore, Casalvelino Scalo (Salerno), 1992. Carlo e Nello Rosselli, Giustizia e libertà, a cura di Giuliana Limiti e Mario di Napoli, prefazione di Pietro Larizza, Roma, 1993, con la tesi di laurea di Carlo Rosselli sul «sindacalismo» (Firenze, 1921). Liberalsocialism, edited by Nadia Urbinati, translated by Williams McCuaig, Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1994, introduzione di Nadia Urbinati. Scritti scelti, a cura di Gian Biagio Furiozzi, “Quaderni del Circolo Rosselli”, n. 4/2000, Alinea Editrice, Firenze. Opere su Carlo Rosselli Gaetano Salvemini, "Carlo e Nello Rosselli", Edizioni di «Giustizia e libertà», Parigi, 1938; ora in "Scritti Vari", a cura di Giorgio Agosti e Alessandro Galante Garrone, Feltrinelli, Milano, 1978 («Opere scelte di Gaetano Salvemini», volume VIII, pp. 673–718). Cultura e società nella formazione di Gaetano Salvemini, buona anteprima del pensiero di Salvemini con i rapporti con Carlo Rosselli e la grangia politica correlata Roberto Gremmo "Rosselli alla Cagoule" Silenzi e segreti d'un oscuro delitto politico. Edizioni Storia Ribelle, Biella 2018. Aldo Garosci, "Vita di Carlo Rosselli", Edizioni U, Roma-Firenze-Milano s.d., 1945, 2 voll., pp. 274 e 298 («Collezione Giustizia e Libertà»); nuova edizione Vallecchi, Firenze, 1973. Alessandro Levi, "Ricordi dei fratelli Rosselli", La Nuova Italia, Firenze, 1947 («Quaderni del Ponte», 2). Stefano Merli, "Il dibattito socialista sotto il fascismo. Lettere di Rodolfo Morandi e Carlo Rosselli (1928-1931)", «Rivista storica del socialismo», a. VI, n. 19. Maggio-Agosto 1963. Parzialmente ricompreso in Id., "Fronte antifascista e politica di classe. Socialisti e comunisti in Italia 1923-1929", De Donato, Bari, 1975 («Movimento operaio», 28). Nicola Tranfaglia, "Carlo Rosselli dall'interventismo all'antifascismo", «Dialoghi del XX», a. I, n. 2, giugno 1967. Cfr. il n. 8. informazioni su volume "Rosselli e l'Aventino: l'eredità di Giacomo Matteotti", «Il movimento di liberazione in Italia», a. XX, n. 92, luglio-Settembre 1968, pp. 3–34. Cfr. il n.8. stralcio di "Carlo Rosselli e l'Aventino"[collegamento interrotto] «L'opposizione diventava per la prima volta opposizione, minoranza; come minoranza, avrebbe potuto darsi una psicologia virile, d'attacco. Ma aveva troppi ex nelle sue file, era troppo appesantita da uomini che avevano gustato le gioie del potere e della popolarità.»  «Fu questo il miracolismo dell'Aventino. Credere di poter vincere con le armi legali l'avversario che ha già vinto sul terreno della forza. Pregustare le gioie del trionfo mentre si riceve la botta più dura. Evitare tutti i problemi (Piero Gobetti diceva: "l'Aventino ha un mito, il mito della cautela"), sperando che la borghesia dimentichi il '19.»  «Quanto alle masse popolari, che si mostravano nei primi giorni in stato di effervescenza, guai a chi avesse tentato metterle in movimento! Solo i comunisti e le minoranze giovani chiesero lo sciopero generale. Ma le opposizioni non vollero, per non spaventare la borghesia e il sovrano.»   "Carlo Rosselli dall'interventismo a «Giustizia e Libertà»", Laterza, Bari, 1968, («Biblioteca di cultura moderna»); in appendice: scritti di Carlo Rosselli (1919-1926) e Lettera di Carlo Rosselli a Pietro Nenni. Cfr. i nn. 6 e 7. "Carlo Rosselli dal processo di Savona alla fondazione di GL (1927-1929). Le fonti di «Socialismo liberale»", «Il movimento di liberazione in Italia», a. XXIV, n. 106, gennaio-Marzo 1972. Mirella Larizza Lolli, "Alcuni appunti per una lettura del «Socialismo liberale» di Rosselli", «Il pensiero politico», a. VII, n. 2, 1974, pp. 283–92. Santi Fedele, "Lo «Schema di programma» di «Giustizia e Libertà», del 1932", «Belfagor», a. XXIX, n. 4, 31 luglio 1974, pp. 437–54 Paolo Bagnoli, "L'esperienza liberale di Carlo Rosselli (1919-1924)", «Italia Contemporanea», * XXVIII, n. 125, ottobre-Dicembre 1976, pp. 29–42. Poi compreso in n. 36, pp. 37–61. "L'antifascismo rivoluzionario dei «Quaderni di Giustizia e Libertà»", «Ricerche Storiche», a. VI, n. 1 (Nuova serie), gennaio-Giugno 1976, pp. 167–89. Poi compreso in n. 36, pp. 143–69. Santi Fedele, "Storia della concentrazione antifascista 1927/1934", prefazione di Nicola Tranfaglia, Feltrinelli, Milano, 1976. Maria Garbari, "I «vinti» della Resistenza. Nel quarantesimo del sacrificio di Carlo e Nello Rosselli", «Studi Trentini di Scienze Storiche», a. LVI, n. 3, 1977, pp. 281–94. "«Quarto Stato» di Pietro Nenni e Rosselli", Tavola rotonda fra Riccardo Bauer, Ugoberto Alfassio Grimaldi, Giovanni Spadolini, Domenico Zucàro, «Critica Sociale», a. LXIX, n. 8, 22 luglio 1977, pp. 44–48. Leo Valiani, "Il pensiero e l'azione di Carlo e Nello Rosselli", «Nuova Antologia», anno 112°, Vol. 530°, Fasc. 2118-2120, giugno-Luglio-Agosto 1977, pp. 24–40. Poi compreso in n. 22, pp. 3–22. Nicola Tranfaglia, "Carlo Rosselli e l'antifascismo", «Mondo Operaio», a. XXX, nn. 7-8, luglio/Agosto 1977, pp. 71–81. Poi compreso in n. 22, pp. 181–204 e in n. 34, pag. 186-211. Roberto Vivarelli, "Carlo Rosselli e Gaetano Salvemini", «Il pensiero politico», a. X, n. 2, 1977, pp. 225–52. Poi compreso in n. 22, pp. 69–97. Giovanni Spadolini, "Carlo Rosselli nella lotta per la libertà", con lettere tra Egidio Reale e Carlo Rosselli, «Nuova Antologia», anno 112°, Vol. 532°, Fasc. 2121-2124, settembre-Ottobre-Novembre-Dicembre 1977, pp. 3–16. Arturo Colombo, "Carlo Rosselli e il «Quarto Stato»", «Nord e Sud», a. XXIV, Terza serie, nn. 34-35, novembre-Dicembre 1977, pp. 108–120. Cfr. n. 29, pp. 55–66. "Giustizia e Libertà nella lotta antifascista e nella storia d'Italia", Atti del convegno internazionale organizzato a Firenze il 10-12 giugno 1977 dall'Istituto storico della Resistenza in Toscana, dalla Giunta regionale toscana, dal Comune di Firenze, dalla Provincia di Firenze, La Nuova Italia, Firenze, 1978. Riccardo Bauer, "Carlo Rosselli e la nascita di GL in Italia". Jan Petersen, "Giustizia e Libertà in Germania". Pierre Guillen, "La risonanza in Francia dell'azione di GL e dell'assassinio dei fratelli Rosselli". Frank Rosengarten, "Carlo Rosselli e Silvio Trentin, teorici della rivoluzione italiana". Max Salvadori, "Giellisti e loro amici degli Stati Uniti durante la seconda guerra mondiale". Santi Fedele, "Giellisti e socialisti dalla fondazione di GL (1929) alla politica dei fronti popolari". Pier Giorgio Zunino, "Giustizia e Libertà e i cattolici". Aldo Garosci, "Le diverse fasi dell'intervento di Giustizia e Libertà nella guerra civile di Spagna. Parte III- Oggi in Spagna, domani in Italia". Umberto Marzocchi, "Carlo Rosselli e gli anarchici"; citazione sottostante da un articolo di Ugo Finetti «Infatti Rosselli considerava una barbarie le stragi di anarchici in Catalogna, tra cui l'uccisione di Camillo Berneri, l'anarchico che lo affiancava nella guida della Prima colonna italiana formata da tremila antifascisti, i primi accorsi in Spagna.»  e si ricorda, nel prosieguo, anche la ferma presa di posizione delle Brigate partigiane di Giustizia e Libertà quando Emilio Canzi fu rimosso da comandante unico della XIII zona operante nel piacentino e grazie a questa presa di posizione fu reintegrato dopo un breve arresto. Le Brigate partigiane di Giustizia e Libertà erano in gran parte influenzate dal pensiero di Rosselli.  Umberto Tommasini, "Testimonianza su Carlo Rosselli; Parte IV- L'eredità di Giustizia e Libertà". Mario Delle Piane, "Rapporti tra socialismo liberale e liberalsocialismo". Tristano Codignola, "GL e Partito d'azione". Nicola Tranfaglia, "Carlo Rosselli", in "Il movimento operaio italiano. Dizionario biografico - IV", a cura di Franco Andreucci e Tommaso Detti, Editori Riuniti, Roma, 1978, pp. 392–99. Arturo Colombo, "Carlo Rosselli e il socialismo liberale", «Il Politico», a. XLIII, n. 4, dicembre 1978, pp. 628–48. Poi compreso in n. 37, pp. 249–73. Paolo Bagnoli, "Di un dissidio in «Giustizia e Libertà». Lettere inedite di Mario Levi, Renzo Giua, Nicola Chiaromonte, Carlo Rosselli, Aldo Garosci (1934-1935)", «Mezzosecolo», n. 3, Centro studi Piero Gobetti, Istituto Storico della Resistenza in Piemonte, Archivio Nazionale Cinematografico della Resistenza, Annali 1978-1979, Torino, 1982, pp. 5–54. Luigi Cirillo, "Il socialismo di Carlo Rosselli", Fasano, Cosenza, 1979. Emilio Lussu, "Lettere a Carlo Rosselli e altri scritti di «Giustizia e Libertà»", a cura di Manlio Brigaglia, Editrice Libreria Dessì, Sassari 1979, pp. 301.informazioni su Storia della Sardegna di Manlio Brigaglia, son presenti correlazioni fra i succitati personaggi. "Le componenti mazziniana e cattaneanea in Salvemini e nei Rosselli. La figura e l'opera di Giulio Andrea Belloni", Atti del Convegno di studi nel venticinquesimo anniversario della fondazione della Domus Mazziniana tenutosi a Pisa il 4-6 novembre 1977, Arti Grafiche Pacini & Mariotti, Pisa, 1979, pp. 257. Comprende: Arturo Colombo, "Carlo Rosselli e il «Quarto Stato»", pp. 55–66 (cfr. il n. 21). Angelo Varni, "Derivazioni mazziniane nella concezione sindacalista di Carlo Rosselli", pp. 67–78. Lucio Ceva, "Aspetti politici dell'azione di Carlo Rosselli in Spagna", pp. 109–26. Giuseppe Tramarollo, "Rosselli e la gioventù del regime", pp. 127–130. Paolo Bagnoli, "Il revisionismo rosselliano", in "Guida alla storia del PSI. La ripresa del pensiero socialista tra eresia e tradizione", a cura di Francesca Taddei e Marco Talluri, «Quaderni del Circolo Rosselli», a. I, n. 3, luglio-Settembre 1981, pp. 95–108. Giuseppe Galasso, "La democrazia da Cattaneo a Rosselli", Le Monnier, Firenze, 1982, pp. 331, («Quaderni di storia», LVII). Aldo Rosselli, "La famiglia Rosselli. Una tragedia italiana", presentazione di Sandro Pertini, prefazione di Alberto Moravia, Bompiani, Milano, 1983, pp. 184. Francesco Kostner, "Carlo Rosselli e il suo socialismo liberale", Lalli, Poggibonsi, 1984, pp. 91 («Linee politiche»). Paolo Bagnoli, "Carlo Rosselli tra pensiero politico e azione", prefazione di Giovanni Spadolini, con uno scritto di Alessandro Galante Garrone, Passigli, Firenze, 1985, pp. 190. Arturo Colombo, "Carlo Rosselli e il socialismo liberale", in "Padri della patria. Protagonisti e testimoni di un'altra Italia", FrancoAngeli, Milano, 1985, pp. 249–73 («Ricerche storiche», 64). Franco Invernici, "L'alternativa di «Giustizia e Libertà». Economia e politica nei progetti del gruppo di Carlo Rosselli", presentazione di Arturo Colombo, FrancoAngeli, Milano, 1987, pp. 196 («Studi e ricerche storiche», 96). Leo Valiani, "Carlo e Nello Rosselli da Mazzini alla lotta di liberazione", «Nuova Antologia», anno 122°, Vol. 558°, Fasc. 2163, luglio-Settembre 1987, pp. 45–59. Diego Scacchi, Arturo Colombo, "Per Carlo e Nello Rosselli", presentazione di Giovanni Spadolini, Casagrande, Lugano, 1988, pp. 71 («Quaderni europei», I). Roberto Vivarelli, "Le ragioni di un comune impegno. Ricordando Gaetano Salvemini, Carlo e Nello Rosselli, Ernesto Rossi", «Rivista Storica Italiana», a. c, Fasc. III, dicembre 1988, pp. 669–78. Giovanni Spadolini, "Carlo e Nello Rosselli. Le radici mazziniane del loro pensiero", Passigli, Firenze, 1990, pp. 61 («Letture Rosselli», 2). Corrado Malandrino, "Socialismo e libertà. Autonomie, federalismo, Europa da Rosselli a Silone", FrancoAngeli, Milano, 1990, pp. 247 (Collana «Gioele Solari». Dipartimento di Studi politici dell'Università di Torino, 6). Franco Bandini, "Il cono d'ombra. Chi armò la mano degli assassini dei fratelli Rosselli", SugarCo, Milano, 1990, pp. 527. Arturo Colombo, "I Rosselli, due guardiani per l'albero della libertà", in Id., "Voci e volti della democrazia. Cultura e impegno civile da Gobetti a Bauer", Le Monnier, Firenze, 1990, pp. 115–145 («Quaderni di storia»). AA. VV., "Nel nome dei Rosselli. 1920-1990", «Quaderni del Circolo Rosselli», a. XI, n. 1, 1991, FrancoAngeli, Milano, pp. 177. Con una bibliografia sui fratelli Rosselli di Giuseppe Muzzi. "A più voci su Carlo Rosselli. Gaetano Arfé, Costanzo Casucci, Aldo Garosci, Francesco Malgeri, Leonardo Rapone, Scritti dell'esilio", «Il Ponte», a. XLVII, n. 6, giugno 1991, pp. 120–150. "Il carteggio di Carlo e Nello Rosselli con Carlo Silvestri (1928-1934)", a cura di Gloria Gabrielli, «Storia Contemporanea», a. XXII, n. 5, ottobre 1991, pp. 875–916. Santi Fedele, "E verrà un'altra Italia. Politica e cultura nei «Quaderni di Giustizia e Libertà»", FrancoAngeli, Milano, 1992, pp. 212 Collana di Fondazione di studi storici Filippo Turati», n °7. Zeffiro Ciuffoletti, "Carlo Rosselli, il mito della rivoluzione russa e il comunismo", in "Socialismo e Comunismo 1892-1992". Vol. I, «Il Ponte», a. XLVIII, n. 5, maggio 1992, pp. 186–202. Paolo Bagnoli, "La lezione rosselliana, La nuova storia. Politica e cultura alla ricerca del socialismo liberale", prefazione di Renato Treves, Festina Lente, Firenze, 1992, pp. 107–34. Nicola Tranfaglia, "Sul socialismo liberale di Carlo Rosselli", in I volume "Dilemmi del liberalsocialismo", a cura di Michelangelo Bovero, Virgilio Mura, Franco Sbarberi, La Nuova Italia Scientifica, Roma, 1994, pp. 88–104 («Studi Superiori NIS/201. Scienze Sociali»). Atti del convegno "Liberalsocialismo: ossimoro o sintesi?", organizzato ad Alghero il 25-27 aprile 1991, Dipartimento di Economia istituzioni e società dell'Università Sassari. Il 1º gennaio del 1924 fu pubblicato il primo numero di “Libertà”, periodico legato all'ala socialista del movimento antifascista, il sottotitolo fu la frase di Carlo Marx ed Federico Engels: Alla società borghese, con le sue classi e con i suoi antagonismi di classe, subentrerà un'associazione nella quale il libero sviluppo di ciascuno sarà la condizione del libero sviluppo di tutti e, su invito Claudio Treves, Rodolfo Mondolfo e Alessandro Levi, Rosselli scrisse un articolo Il partito del lavoro in Inghilterra che fu pubblicato sul numero tre del 1º febbraio 1924, in cui Rosselli riaffermò una parte del suo pensiero del periodo: «Il Labour Party, in base agli elementi che lo compongono può definirsi come una federazione di gruppi economici e di gruppi politici. In realtà è l'organizzazione politica federativa ed associativa del movimento operaio più vecchio e potente del mondo.»  Silvio Suppa, "Note su Carlo Rosselli: temi per due tradizioni", in I volume "dilemmi del liberalsocialismo "cit., pp. 189-208. Del Puppo D., "«Il Quarto Stato»", «Science and Society», a. 58, 1994, n. 2, pp. 136–162. "L'attualità di Carlo Rosselli e del socialismo liberale. Dialoghi tra: Giancarlo Bosetti, Vittorio Foa, Sebastiano Maffettone, Enzo Marzo, Nicola Tranfaglia, Nadia Urbinati", Supplemento al n. I/1995 di «Croce Via», Edizioni Scientifiche Italiane, Napoli, 1995. Atti del dibattito svoltosi a Napoli il 13 gennaio 1995 in occasione della presentazione italiana del volume "Liberal socialism", lavoro di Nadia Urbinati, tradotto da William McCuaig, Princeton University Press, Princenton 1994, pp. 138. Nadia Urbinati, "Carlo Rosselli: la democrazia come fede comune", «il Vieusseux», a. VII, n. 21, settembre-Dicembre 1994, pp. 25–42. Paolo Bagnoli, Rosselli, "Piero Gobetti e la rivoluzione democratica. Uomini e idee tra liberalismo e socialismo", La Nuova Italia, Firenze, 1996, pp. 258 («Biblioteca di Storia», 55). Costanzo Casucci, "La caratteristica di Carlo Rosselli", con un vademecum, «Belfagor», a. LI, n. 2, 31 marzo 1996, pp. 243–248. Simone Visciola, Giuseppe Limone (a cura di), "I Rosselli. Eresia creativa, eredità originale", Napoli, Guida, 2005 Piero Graglia, "Unità europea e federalismo. Da «Giustizia e Libertà» ad Altiero Spinelli", il Mulino, Bologna, 1996, pp. 296 («il Mulino-Ricerca»). "Il dibattito europeista e federalista in «Giustizia e Libertà»", «Storia Contemporanea», a. XXVII, n. 2, aprile 1996, pp. 327–56. Lisetto D., "Carlo Rosselli e le élites. Una teoria tra l'elitismo democratico e la democrazia partecipativa", «Scienza & Politica», 16, 1997, pp. 69–86. Carlo Rosselli, "Pagine scelte di economia", a cura di Simone Visciola e Antonio De Ruggiero, Firenze, Le Monnier, 2010 Salvo Mastellone, "Il partito politico nel socialismo liberale di Carlo Rosselli", «Il pensiero politico», a. XXXI, n. 1, 1998, pag. 111-118. Gianbiagio Furlozzi, "Carlo Rosselli e Georges Sorel", «Il pensiero politico», a. XXXII, n. 2, 1999, pag. 262-270. Giovanna Angeli, "L'eredità democratica da Bignami a Rosselli", Angeli, Milano, 1999. Salvo Mastellone, "Carlo Rosselli e «La rivoluzione liberale del socialismo»". Con scritti e documenti inediti. Olschki, 1999, pp. 266. Son riportati testi pubblicati da Carlo Rosselli non inseriti nel Vol. I delle «Opere scelte». "Rosselli. Dizionario delle idee", a cura di Sergio Bucchi, Editori Riuniti, gennaio 2000, pp. 169. Antonio Martino, Pertini e altri socialisti savonesi nelle carte della R. Questura, Roma, Gruppo editoriale L'espresso, 2009. Mimmo Franzinelli, "Il delitto Rosselli. 9 giugno 1937. Anatomia di un omicidio politico", Mondadori, Milano 2007. Diego Dilettoso, "La Parigi e La Francia di Carlo Rosselli. Sulle orme di un umanista in esilio", Biblion, Milano 2013 .Paolo Bagnoli. Carlo Rosselli: Il socialismo delle libertà. Polistampa, Milano, 2012 Paolo Bagnoli. Carlo Rosselli. Socialismo, giustizia e libertà. Biblion, Milano, 2015 Altri progetti Collabora a Wikisource Wikisource contiene una pagina dedicata a Carlo Rosselli Collabora a Wikiquote Wikiquote contiene citazioni di o su Carlo Rosselli Collabora a Wikimedia Commons Wikimedia Commons contiene immagini o altri file su Carlo Rosselli Collegamenti esterni Carlo Rosselli, su Treccani.it – Enciclopedie on line, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Modifica su Wikidata Carlo Rosselli, in Enciclopedia Italiana, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Modifica su Wikidata Carlo Rosselli, in Dizionario di storia, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana, 2010. Modifica su Wikidata (IT, DE, FR) Carlo Rosselli, su hls-dhs-dss.ch, Dizionario storico della Svizzera. Modifica su Wikidata Carlo Rosselli, in Dizionario biografico degli italiani, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Modifica su Wikidata Carlo Rosselli, su siusa.archivi.beniculturali.it, Sistema Informativo Unificato per le Soprintendenze Archivistiche. Modifica su Wikidata Opere di Carlo Rosselli, su Liber Liber. Modifica su Wikidata Opere di Carlo Rosselli, su openMLOL, Horizons Unlimited srl. Modifica su Wikidata (EN) Opere di Carlo Rosselli, su Open Library, Internet Archive. Modifica su Wikidata Biografia di Rosselli, su romacivica.net. URL consultato il 30 agosto 2006 (archiviato dall'url originale il 30 agosto 2006). Carlo Rosselli e l'Aventino (DOC) [collegamento interrotto], su geocities.com. Giancarlo Iacchini,*Rosselli: socialismo liberale ma... vero!, dal sito del Movimento Radical Socialista 55esima brigata Garibaldi Carlo Rosselli, su 55rosselli.it. Archivio della famiglia Rosselli [collegamento interrotto], su archiviorosselli.it. I fratelli Rosselli, genesi di un delitto impunito, su rifondazionepescara.org (archiviato dall'url originale l'8 aprile 2008). Camillo Berneri e Carlo Rosselli - Vite parallele di Massimo Ortalli (da "Umanità Nova" n.08 del 4 marzo 2001) Fondazione Rosselli, Centro di ricerca, su fondazionerosselli.it. URL consultato il 17 gennaio 2013 (archiviato dall'url originale il 1º settembre 2005). Fondazione Circolo Rosselli - Firenze, su rosselli.org. "Gaetano Pecora" Carlo Rosselli, socialista e liberale.Bilancio critico di un grande italiano, su politicamagazine.it. Valdo Spini, "Perché i Rosselli parlano ancora a questa Italia", sul sito repubblica.it del 7 giugno 2020. V · D · M Antifascismo (1919-1943) Controllo di autorità                                               VIAF (EN) 14809419 · ISNI (EN) 0000 0001 1598 3394 · SBN IT\ICCU\CFIV\090406 · Europeana agent/base/89804 · LCCN (EN) n79042225 · GND (DE) 119181347 · BNF (FR) cb12159402m (data) · WorldCat Identities (EN) lccn-n79042225 Biografie Portale Biografie Filosofia Portale Filosofia Politica Portale Politica Socialismo Portale Socialismo Categorie: Attivisti italianiGiornalisti italiani del XX secoloFilosofi italiani del XX secoloNati nel 1899Morti nel 1937Nati il 16 novembreMorti il 9 giugnoNati a RomaAntifascisti italianiFondatori di riviste italianeDirettori di periodici italianiGiornalisti assassinatiPersone legate agli alpiniEbrei italianiBrigate Giustizia e LibertàSocialistiMazzinianiPolitici assassinatiVittime di dittature nazifascisteSchedati al Casellario Politico CentraleConfinati politiciPolitici del Partito Socialista Unitario[altre]. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Rosselli e Grice,” per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.

rota: Italian philosopher – Gian-Carlo Rota From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Jump to navigationJump to search Not to be confused with Carlo Rota. Gian-Carlo Rota Gian-Carlo Rota blackboard Nizza 1970.jpg Rota in 1970. Born     April 27, 1932 Vigevano, Italy Died April 18, 1999 (aged 66) Cambridge, Massachusetts, U.S. Alma mater Princeton University (A.B.) Yale University (Ph.D.) AwardsLeroy P. Steele Prize (1988) Scientific career Fields Mathematics, philosophy Institutions Massachusetts Institute of Technology Los Alamos National Laboratory The Rockefeller University Doctoral advisor Jacob T. Schwartz Notable students  Thomas H. Brylawski William Y.C. Chen Daniel I. A. Cohen Henry Crapo Peter Duren Richard Ehrenborg Mark Haiman Patrick O'Neil Richard P. Stanley Walter Whiteley Catherine Yan Gian-Carlo Rota (April 27, 1932 – April 18, 1999) was an Italian-American mathematician and philosopher.   Contents 1 Early life and education 2 Career 3 Death 4 See also 5 Notes 6 External links Early life and education Rota was born in Vigevano, Italy. His father, Giovanni, a prominent antifascist, was the brother of the mathematician Rosetta, who was the wife of the writer Ennio Flaiano.[1][2] Gian-Carlo's family left Italy when he was 13 years old, initially going to Switzerland.  Rota attended the Colegio Americano de Quito in Ecuador, and graduated with an A.B. in mathematics from Princeton University in 1953 after completing a senior thesis, titled "On the solubility of linear equations in topological vector spaces", under the supervision of William Feller. He then pursued graduate studies at Yale University, where he received a Ph.D. in mathematics in 1956 after completing a doctoral dissertation, titled "Extension Theory Of Ordinary Linear Differential Operators", under the supervision of Jacob T. Schwartz.[3][4]  Career Much of Rota's career was spent as a professor at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology (MIT), where he was and remains the only person ever to be appointed Professor of Applied Mathematics and Philosophy. Rota was also the Norbert Wiener Professor of Applied Mathematics.  In addition to his professorships at MIT, Rota held four honorary degrees, from the University of Strasbourg, France (1984); the University of L'Aquila, Italy (1990); the University of Bologna, Italy (1996); and Brooklyn Polytechnic University (1997). Beginning in 1966 he was a consultant at Los Alamos National Laboratory, frequently visiting to lecture, discuss, and collaborate, notably with his friend Stanisław Ulam. He was also a consultant for the Rand Corporation (1966–71) and for the Brookhaven National Laboratory (1969–1973). Rota was elected to the National Academy of Sciences in 1982, was vice president of the American Mathematical Society (AMS) from 1995–97, and was a member of numerous other mathematical and philosophical organizations.[5]  He taught a difficult but very popular course in probability. He also taught Applications of Calculus, differential equations, and Combinatorial Theory. His philosophy course in phenomenology was offered on Friday nights to keep the enrollment manageable. Among his many eccentricities, he would not teach without a can of Coca-Cola, and handed out prizes ranging from Hershey bars to pocket knives to students who asked questions in class or did well on tests.[6][7]  Rota began his career as a functional analyst, but switched to become a distinguished combinatorialist. His series of ten papers on the "Foundations of Combinatorics" in the 1960s is credited with making it a respectable branch of modern mathematics.[dubious – discuss] He said that the one combinatorial idea he would like to be remembered for is the correspondence between combinatorial problems and problems of the location of the zeroes of polynomials.[8] He worked on the theory of incidence algebras (which generalize the 19th-century theory of Möbius inversion) and popularized their study among combinatorialists, set the umbral calculus on a rigorous foundation, unified the theory of Sheffer sequences and polynomial sequences of binomial type, and worked on fundamental problems in probability theory. His philosophical work was largely in the phenomenology of Edmund Husserl.  Death Rota died of atherosclerotic cardiac disease on April 18, 1999, apparently in his sleep at his home in Cambridge, Massachusetts.  See also Kallman–Rota inequality Rota's conjecture Rota's basis conjecture Rota–Baxter algebra Joint spectral radius, introduced by Rota in the early 1960s Cyclotomic identity Necklace ring Twelvefold way List of American philosophers Notes  O'Connor, John J.; Robertson, Edmund F., "Gian-Carlo Rota", MacTutor History of Mathematics archive, University of St Andrews.  Palombi, Fabrizio (2011). The Star and the Whole: Gian-Carlo Rota on Mathematics and Phenomenology. CRC Press. pp. 6–7. His aunt, Rosetta Rota (1911–2003), was a mathematician associated with the renowned Rome university Institute of Physics in Via Panispenra…  "American Mathematical Society | Gian-Carlo Rota (1932–1999)" (PDF).  Rota, Gian Carlo (1956). Extension Theory Of Ordinary Linear Differential Operators (Thesis). New Haven, Connecticut: Yale University.  "MIT professor Gian-Carlo Rota, mathematician and philosopher, is dead at 66". April 22, 1999.  Wesley T. Chan (December 5, 1997). "To Teach or Not To Teach: Professors Might Try a New Approach to Classes – Caring about Teaching". The Tech. 117 (63). Retrieved 2008-02-10.  "Gian-Carlo Rota". The Tech. 119 (21). April 23, 1999. Retrieved 2008-02-10.  "Mathematics, Philosophy, and Artificial Intelligence: a dialogue with Gian-Carlo Rota and David Sharp". Archived from the original on August 11, 2007. Retrieved 2007-08-11. External links Gian-Carlo Rota at the Mathematics Genealogy Project O'Connor, John J.; Robertson, Edmund F., "Gian-Carlo Rota", MacTutor History of Mathematics archive, University of St Andrews. Kung, Joseph; Rota, Gian-Carlo; Yan, Catherine (2009). Combinatorics: The Rota Way. Cambridge Mathematical Library. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-73794-4. Archived from the original on 2016-03-03. Retrieved 2010-03-19. The Forbidden City of Gian-Carlo Rota (a memorial site) at the Wayback Machine (archived June 30, 2007) This page at www.rota.org was not originally intended to be a memorial web site, but was created by Rota himself with the assistance of his friend Bill Chen in January 1999 while Rota was visiting Los Alamos National Laboratory. Mathematics, Philosophy, and Artificial Intelligence: a dialogue with Gian-Carlo Rota and David Sharp at the Wayback Machine (archived August 11, 2007) "Fine Hall in its golden age: Remembrances of Princeton in the early fifties" by Gian-Carlo Rota. Tribute page by Prof. Catherine Yan (Texas A&M University), a former student of Rota Scanned copy of Gian-Carlo Rota's and Kenneth Baclawski's Introduction to Probability and Random Processes manuscript in its 1979 version. Gian-Carlo Rota (1996). Indiscrete Thoughts. Birkhäuser Boston. ISBN 0-8176-3866-0., ISBN 0-8176-3866-0; review at MAA.org The Digital Footprint of Gian-Carlo Rota: International Conference in memory of Gian-Carlo Rota, organized by Ottavio D'Antona, Vincenzo Marra and Ernesto Damiani at the University of Milan (Italy) Gian-Carlo Rota on Analysis and Probability, ISBN 978-0-8176-4275-4. Biographical Memoir of Gian-Carlo Rota, National Academy of Science Authority control Edit this at Wikidata IBNF: cb12279061m (data)GND: 119286416ISNI: 0000 0001 0928 3340LCCN: n79018095MGP: 7721NKC: skuk0004876NLI: 000224293NTA: 068390920ICCU: IT\ICCU\CFIV\054252SELIBR: 396279SNAC: w6gc4r4cSUDOC: 031608558VIAF: 98388126WorldCat Identities: lccn-n79018095 Categories: 1932 births1999 deathsPeople from Vigevano20th-century Italian mathematiciansItalian mathematicians20th-century Italian philosophers20th-century American mathematiciansAmerican philosophersCombinatorialistsAmerican people of Italian descentPrinceton University alumniYale University alumniMassachusetts Institute of Technology facultyPhenomenologists. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice e Rota," per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.

rousseau: philosopher, best known for his theories on social freedom and societal rights, education, and religion. Born in Geneva, he was largely self-educated and moved to France as a teenager. Throughout much of his life he moved between Paris and the provinces with several trips abroad including a Scottish stay with Hume and a return visit to Geneva, where he reconverted to Protestantism from his earlier conversion to Catholicism. For a time he was a friend of Diderot and other philosophes and was asked to contribute articles on music for the Encyclopedia. Rousseau’s work can be seen from at least three perspectives. As social contract theorist, he attempts to construct a hypothetical state of nature to explain the current human situation. This evolves a form of philosophical anthropology that gives us both a theory of human nature and a series of pragmatic claims concerning social organization. As a social commentator, he speaks of both practical and ideal forms of education and social organization. As a moralist, he continually attempts to unite the individual and the citizen through some form of universal political action or consent. In Discourse on the Origin and Foundation of Inequality Among Mankind 1755, Rousseau presents us with an almost idyllic view of humanity. In nature humans are first seen as little more than animals except for their special species sympathy. Later, through an explanation of the development of reason and language, he is able to suggest how humans, while retaining this sympathy, can, by distancing themselves from nature, understand their individual selves. This leads to natural community and the closest thing to what Rousseau considers humanity’s perfect moment. Private property quickly follows on the division of labor, and humans find themselves alienated from each other by the class divisions engendered by private property. Thus man, who was born in freedom, now finds himself in chains. The Social Contract or Principles of Political Right 1762 has a more ambitious goal. With an account of the practical role of the legislator and the introduction of the concept of the general will, Rousseau attempts to give us a foundation for good government by presenting a solution to the conflicts between the particular and the universal, the individual and the citizen, and the actual and the moral. Individuals, freely agreeing to a social pact and giving up their rights to the community, are assured of the liberties and equality of political citizenship found in the contract. It is only through being a citizen that the individual can fully realize his freedom and exercise his moral rights and duties. While the individual is naturally good, he must always guard against being dominated or dominating. Rousseau finds a solution to the problems of individual freedoms and interests in a superior form of moral/political action that he calls the general will. The individual as citizen substitutes “I must” for “I will,” which is also an “I shall” when it expresses assent to the general will. The general will is a universal force or statement and thus is more noble than any particular will. In willing his own interest, the citizen is at the same time willing what is communally good. The particular and the universal are united. The individual human participant realizes himself in realizing the good of all. As a practical political commentator Rousseau knew that the universal and the particular do not always coincide. For this he introduced the idea of the legislator, which allows the individual citizen to realize his fulfillment as social being and to exercise his individual rights through universal consent. In moments of difference between the majority will and the general will the legislator will instill the correct moral/political understanding. This will be represented in the laws. While sovereignty rests with the citizens, Rousseau does not require that political action be direct. Although all government should be democratic, various forms of government from representative democracy preferable in small societies to strong monarchies preferable in large nation-states may be acceptable. To shore up the unity and stability of individual societies, Rousseau suggests a sort of civic religion to which all citizens subscribe and in which all members participate. His earlier writings on education and his later practical treatises on the governments of Poland and Corsica reflect related concerns with natural and moral development and with historical and geographical considerations. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Rousseau and Grice and Grice on the explanatory myth of the contract,” per Il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.

rovere: essential Italian philosopher – His family originates in Albalonga, Savona, Liguria. Terenzio Mamiani Da Wikiquote, aforismi e citazioni in libertà. Jump to navigationJump to search  Terenzio Mamiani Terenzio Mamiani della Rovere (1799 – 1885), filosofo, politico e scrittore italiano.   Indice 1 Citazioni di Terenzio Mamiani 2 Antonio Oroboni alla sua fidanzata 2.1 Incipit 2.2 Citazioni 3 D'un nuovo diritto europeo 3.1 Incipit 3.2 Citazioni 4 Dell'ottima congregazione umana 4.1 Incipit 4.2 Citazioni 5 Mario Pagano, ovvero, della immortalità 5.1 Incipit 5.2 Citazioni 6 Prose letterarie 6.1 Avvertenza 6.2 Prefazione alla scelta dei poeti italiani dell'età media 7 Citazioni su Terenzio Mamiani 7.1 Candido Mamini 8 Bibliografia 9 Altri progetti Citazioni di Terenzio Mamiani [...] Testimonio essendo il Pontefice [della insurrezione dell'Italia contro l'Austria] e d'altra parte abborrendo egli, pel suo ministero santissimo, dalle guerre e dal sangue ha pensato... d'interporsi fra i combattenti, e di fare intendere ai nemici della nostra comune patria, quanto crudele ed inutile impresa riesca ormai quella di contendere agli italiani le naturali frontiere... (9 giugno 1848; citato in Giuseppe Fumagalli, Chi l'ha detto?, Hoepli, 1921, p. 631) Antonio Oroboni alla sua fidanzata Incipit Dallo Spielberg, ai 5 d'Aprile. Del soave amor tuo, nobile spirto | Ed infelice, io vissi altera e santa: | Di quel vivrò, giuro all'eterno Iddio, | Si che il dolor nol chiuda entro al sepolcro. | Tai celesti parole in picciol foglio | Vergate, o cara, ebb'io da te quel giorno | Che tramutai le dolci aure lombarde | Con queste ignote al Sol tombe di vivi.  Citazioni Io muojo, ed al suo fine affretta | questa lunga agonia che chiaman vita | qui per istrazio. Quando suonarne il certo annunzio udrai, | non pianger tu, non piangere, o diletto | spirto d'amor, ché del mio ben migliore | Lacrimar ti disdice. [...] Il misero | che gemea quivi giù, poiché il dolore | soverchiò troppo, disperatamente | diè del capo nel sasso e del diffuso | Cerebro il tinse. [...] d'ogni affetto umano affinatrice | fiamma è il dolore, e di virtù maestra | la morte. D'un nuovo diritto europeo Incipit Il giure civile di ciascun popolo ha nel testo delle leggi positive e speciali autorità sufficiente da soddisfare la giustizia ordinaria e da risolvere i dubii e acquetare le controversie intorno agli interessi e agli ufficii d'ogni privato cittadino. Di quindi nasce che possono alcuni curiali riuscire segnalati e famosi al mondo con la sola abilità del pronto ricordare, dell' acuto distinguere e dell'interpretare acconcio e discreto. Al giure delle genti occorre, invece, assai di frequente la discussione delle verità astratte. Perocché esso è indipendente e superiore all'autorità delle sopra citate leggi; si connette immediatamente al giure naturale che è al tutto razionale e speculativo; spesso gli è forza di riandar col pensiero sulle fondamenta medesime dell'ordine sociale umano, e spesso altresì non rinviene modo migliore per risolvere i dubii e acquetare le discrepanze tra popolo e popolo fuor che indagare i grandi pronunziati della ragione perpetua del diritto, chiariti, dedotti e applicati mercé della scienza. Citazioni Poco importa se i metafisici e i letterati si bisticciano; ma non va senza danno del genere umano il discordare e il traviare de' pubblicisti. E già si disse che il fine criterio degli uomini illuminati coglie il certo e il sodo della scienza, ma non la crea e non l'ordina. (p. 5) La demenza degli uonini fa talvolta scandalosa la verità; laonde ella ebbe a pronunziare di se medesima: non venni a recare la pace in mezzo di voi, sibbene la spada. (p. 11) Lo Stato essere certa congregazione di famiglie la qual provvede con leggi e con tribunali al bene proprio e alla propria tutela; tanto che sieno competentemente adempiuti i fini generali della socialità e i particolari di essa congregazione. (p. 13) Lo Stato non esiste per la contiguità sola delle terre e delle abitazioni, ma per certo congiungimento e unità delle menti e degli animi. (p. 15) La libera città di Amburgo è così autonoma come l'impero di Moscovia. Il che riconosciuto e fermato, se ne ritrae ciò che pel diritto internazionale è primo principio ed assioma, non potersi da niuno e sotto niuna ragione arrogare la facoltà di offendere e menomare l'autonomia interna ed esterna di qualchesia Stato insino a tanto che questo non provoca gli altri ad assalirlo con giusta guerra; ed eziandio in tal caso è lecito di occupare temporalmente il suo territorio e dominare il suo popolo nei limiti della difesa e dell'equo rifacimento dei danni. (p. 20-21) Le varie provincie spagnuole o francesi e i tre regni britanni congiunti ed unificati per la conquista o l'eredità palesarono in lungo volgere d'anni la volontà loro ferma ed unanime di perseverare in quella identità e unità di vita sociale e politica. Per lo contrario, l'incorporamento delle provincie basche nell'unità politica degli Spagnuoli fu con violenza adempiuta e poi mantenuta. Voleva ragione e giustizia che per l'azione lenta del tempo e della civiltà riconoscessero quei popoli da se medesimi la utilità di vivere al tutto vita comune coi popoli iberici. Similmente, era iniqua la condizione degl'Irlandesi quando l'irosa Inghilterra per la diversità del culto li segregava dal godimento dei diritti politici. (p. 22) L'uomo individuo può nel servaggio e nelle catene serbare con isforzo la libertà dello spirito e compiere in altro modo e sotto altre condizioni certa eroica purgazione e certo mirabile perfezionamento della sua parte interiore e immortale. Ma ciò è impossibile ad un popolo intero, il quale nel servaggio di necessità si corrompe ed abbietta, e quindi Gian Vincenzo Gravina chiamò assai giustamente la libertà delle nazioni sacrosanta cosa e di giure divino. (p. 25) L'anima non è vendibile e non è nostra, dicevano i teologanti per dimostrare da più parti la iniquità del contratto. E neppure la libertà è vendibile; e se l'usarla e abusarla è nostro, non è tale la facoltà e il principio infuso da Dio con l'alito suo divino e che al dire di Omero vale una mezza anima. (p. 30) Lo Stato possiede onninamente se stesso; niuno fuori di lui può attribuirsene la padronanza. Quindi i popoli o vivono in se od in altri; cioè a dire, o provedono ai propri fini con leggi e ordini propri e componendo un individuo vero e perfetto della universa famiglia umana; ovvero entrano a parte d'altra maggior comunanza con ugualità di diritto e d'ufficio, come quelle riviere che ne' più larghi e reali fiumi confondono le acque e perdono il nome. Questa è la generale e astratta dottrina che danno la ragione e la scienza. (p. 32) Patria, impertanto, significa quella determinata contrada e quella peculiare congregazione di uomini a cui ciascuno degli abitanti e ciascuno dei congregati sentesi legato per tutti i doveri, gl'istinti, i diritti, le speranze e gli affetti del vivere comune. (p.) La patria considerata nella sua morale e profonda significazione è il compiuto sodamento di ciascuno verso di tutti e di tutti verso ciascuno. (p. 36-37) Se la patria non ha debito né possibilità di nudrire del suo ogni giorno tutti i suoi indigenti, spietata cosa sarebbe inibire a questi di procacciarsi altrove la sussistenza. (p. 39) Prediletta opera delle mani di Dio sono le nazioni. (p. 41) Qual nazione è pura, domandano essi, e tutta omogenea, e quale Stato in Europa non è straniero a qualche porzione de' sudditi proprii? L'Inghilterra pesa sul popolo Jonio, la Francia sull' Algerino, la Spagna sul Basco. Non nacquero forse Italiani i Corsi e Tedeschi i popoli dell'Alsazia? I Polacchi di Posen son forse Prussiani; e non è mezzo slava la Silesia? Chiameremo Russi i Lituani o i Finlandesi o gli abitanti di Riga e della Curlandia? E se tinti vediamo della medesima pece tutti i governi, se niuno, a rispetto del puro principio di nazionalità, è incolpevole, qual profitto si può dedurre d'una teorica non mai applicabile; ed anzi, come può essere teorica e vera, se i fatti in ogni luogo e tempo la contradicono? (p. 45) Lo Stato dipendente come si sia da un altro non è, a propriamente parlare, autonomo; e perciò, a rigore di definizione, neppure la denominazione di Stato gli si compete. (p. 61) I prìncipi non sono, del certo, scelti da Dio immediatamente, ma sono da Dio immediatamente investiti di loro sovranità. Il popolo indica l'uomo a cui vuole obbedire e in quell'uomo è subito la pienezza della sovranità che da Dio gli proviene. Perocché come da Dio è istituito il fine della socievole comunanza, così è istituito il mezzo nella autorità del comando. (p. 71) È sicuro che nella lunghezza dei secoli le volontà e i giudizi umani si accostano all'assoluto del bene sociale, quanto che la via che viene trascorsa non procede diritta e spedita ma declina e torce continuo fra molti errori e molte misere concussioni. (p. 75) La libertà, essendo naturale ed essenziale agli uomini e necessaria concomitanza d'ogni bontà, è doveroso per tutti il serbarla integra nella sostanza; e perciò, né il privato individuo si può vendere ad altro privato, né tutto il corpo de' cittadini assoggettarsi pienamente e perpetuamente al dominio d'alcuno, sia forestiere o nativo. (p. 80) Poco o nessun valore ha il dissentimento dei piccioli e deboli, quando anche piglino ardire di esprimerlo; e chi investiga la Storia, ritrova che delle proteste loro giacciono grandi fasci dimenticati negli archivi delle Cancellerie. (p. 98) Dacché siete i più forti, correte poco rischio di vivere ex lege alla maniera dei Ciclopi. Ma confessare il diritto e contro il diritto procedere, non è conceduto a nessuno; e parlavano meglio quegli Ateniesi che alle querele dei Milesi rispondevano senza sturbarsi : il diritto è cosa pei deboli e non già pei forti e pei valorosi. (p. 113) Ogni popolo è autonomo; o con altri vocaboli, ogni Stato vero è libero ed inviolabile inverso tutti i popoli e tutti gli Stati. (p. 121) E patria nel significato morale e politico è sinonimo di Stato, in quanto questo compone uno stretto e nativo consorzio in cui ciascun cittadino ha debito e desiderio insieme di effettuare il grado massimo di unimento sociale e civile. (p. 122) S'incominci dall'avvisare chi sono costoro che si querelano dell'abusata libertà degli Stati e ne temono danni così spaventevoli. Costoro sono i medesimi da cui si alzano lagni e rimproveri cotidiani per qualunque libertà, eccetto la propria loro. Vogliono limitare la stampa, limitare la libera concorrenza, limitare i Parlamenti e in fine ogni cosa col pretesto volgare ed ovvio che i parlamenti, il commercio, la stampa abusano di loro facoltà e trasvanno più d'una volta e in più cose. (p. 207) La volontà umana, dite, è corrotta e inchinevole al male. Può darsi; ma privata di libertà so che depravasi molto di più e i padroni non meno che i servi. (p. 208) Non è lecito agli uomini di esercitare nessun diritto qualora difettino pienamente delle facoltà e dei mezzi correlativi. Perciò il fanciullo, il mentecatto, l'idiota cade naturalmente sotto l'altrui tutela, e per ciò medesimo la parte meno educata del volgo ed offesa di troppa ignoranza, o posta in condizione troppo servile, non ha nel generale facoltà e mezzi proporzionati ad esercitare diritti politici. (p. 219) Dell'ottima congregazione umana Incipit Esaminato il fine del viver comune, fatta rassegna d'alcuni principii direttivi, più bisognevoli al nostro intento e poco o nulla noti agli antichi, segue senza più che noi trapassiamo a contemplare l'ottimo ordinamento civile. Della qual materia stragrande fermammo in principio del libro che sarebbero da noi segnate alquante linee soltanto, scegliendo quelle che più hanno riferimento con l'indole speciale de' tempi nostri. E pur questi pochi lineamenti noi cercheremo di descriverli, come suoi fare l'artista, secondo il concetto d'una bellezza ideale ricavata e desunta con fedeltà squisita dall'essere delle cose e figurandola in mente come e quale uscirebbe dalle mani della natura, quando non la perturbassero gli scorretti accidenti. Cosi noi delineeremo qnalche fattezza dell'incivilimento umano, contemplandolo nella natura primitiva ed universale dei popoli, ed avvisandoci di non iscambiare l'alterato e il mutabile col permanente ed inalterato; e per converso, di non dar nome d'errore emendabile e di accidente transitorio a ciò che appartiene alle condizioni salde e durevoli della comunanza civile. Chè nel primo difetto cadono i troppo retrivi ed i pusillanimi; nel secondo, i novatori audaci e leggeri. Citazioni Aristotile con molto senno incomincia dall'insegnar quello che spetta al buono stato della famiglia, perché della comunanza umana l'individuo compiuto non è lo scapolo, ma l'ammogliato con prole o vogliam dire la famiglia, rimossa la quale, come fu scritto nell'aforismo XIV, non rimane intermezzo alcuno che tempri l'amor proprio e la fiera e violenta natura nostra. (p. 400, I) L'organizzazione tanto è più eccellente quanto meno cede alle esterne azioni ed impressioni ed anzi modifica con maggior efficacia ed appropria a sé quelle azioni. (p. 401, I) È da confessare che un gran trovato fece lo spirito umano e giovevole soprammodo alla prosperità del viver sociale, quando mise in atto quello che fu domandato governo rappresentativo o parlamentare. (p. 404, I) Se dirai: carattere di nazione è la continuità e circoscrizione del suolo, i Tedeschi di qua del Reno sarebber Francesi, e non è Grecia l'Asia minore, e gli Ebrei non compongono nazione, e malamente la compongono le genti slave. Se dirai la lingua; i Baschi non sono spagnuoli, né francesi i Bretoni e quei dell' Alsazia, e non ha niente di nazione la Svizzera né l'Ungheria dove più lingue sono parlate. Se la religione; troppe smentite ci danno Germania, Inghilterra e gli Stati Uniti americani; d'altra parte, sotto il rispetto dell'unità religiosa, farebber nazione insieme Siciliani e Messicani, Irlandesi e Abissini. Se il governo; i Lombardi sono austriaci, sono turchi i Greci, francesi gli Arabi e via discorrendo. Se la letteratura e le arti ; non fanno nazione quei popoli a cui mancano lettere e arti proprie e le accattano dai forestieri, come usavano poco fa i Russi, i Boemi, gli Ungaresi ed altri, e tuttora non cessano. Se le origini e la schiatta; le colonie sono tal membro e così vivace del corpo della patria onde uscirono, da non potersene mai dispiccare, e la guerra americana fu dalla banda dei sollevati iniqua e parricida. Gran questione poi insorge sulle genti di confine, le quali compongonsi il più delle volte di schiatte anfibie, a cosi chiamarle. Quindi noi vogliamo, per via d'esempio, i Nizzardi essere italiani e i Francesi li fanno dei loro. Né minor controversia nasce circa cento popolazioni per la terra disseminate, che è impossibile di ben definire a qual generazione appartengano, né per sé bastano a far nazione, come Bosniaci, Bulgari, Albanesi, Illirii, Maltesi e innumerevoli altri. (p. 429, V) La compagnia civile comincia là solamente dove gli animi si accostano, e sorge desiderio di regolato e comune operare. (p. 2, VI) La Giustizia, secondo Omero, apre e chiude i congressi degli Dei, non quelli degli uomini. (p. 2, VI) La voce nazione nel suo peculiare e pieno significato vuol dire unimento e società d'uomini che la natura stessa con le sue mani à fatta e costituita mediante la mescolanza del sangue e la singolarità delle condizioni interiori ed estrinseche; per talché quella società distinguesi da tutte le altre per tutti gli essenziali caratteri che possono diversificare le genti in fra loro, come la schiatta, la lingua, la religione, l'indole, il territorio, le tradizioni, le arti, i costumi. (p. 2, VI) Nazione vuol significare certo novero di genti per comunanza di sangue, conformità di genio, medesimezza di linguaggio atte e preordinate alla massima unione sociale. (p. 2, VI) Gli Svizzeri varii di lingua, di schiatta, di religione e d'usanza sonosi costituiti artificialmente e politicamente in nazione, mediante una grande e maravigliosa unità morale che turbata e rotta alcune volte di dentro è sempre riuscita gagliarda di fuori a fronte degli stranieri. (p. 5, VI) I Greci ed i Musulmani dell'Asia Minore o d'altra contrada, i quali tuttoché nati e cresciuti nel suolo stesso, pur non si chiamano concittadini, e vivono e sempre vivranno stranieri l'uno accanto dell'altro. (p. 8, VII) Lo stipite umano è ordinato esso pure a spandere discosto da sé le propagini e i semi; e ogni germe nuovo dee nudrirsi del terreno ove cade, non del tronco da cui si origina. (p. 11, VII) Sieno rese grazie publicamente da tutta l'Italia a voi, o Valdesi, che l'antica madre mai non avete voluto e potuto odiare e sconoscere insino al giorno glorioso che fu da Dio coronata la vostra costanza, e un patto comune di libertà vi riconciliava con gli emendati persecutori. (p. 13, VII) S'io credessi quelle armi che assiepano il Foro, dicea Cicerone, starsene qui a minacciare e non a proteggere, cederei al tempo e mi terrei silenzioso. Ma il fatto fu che quelle armi nel Foro inducevano per se sole una fiera minaccia, tanto ch'egli parlò poco e male, e la paura ammazzò l'eloquenza. (p. 18, VIII) Dal riscontro, per tanto, di tutte le storie, senza timore mai d'eccezione, e più ancora dalla ripugnanza intima di certi termini, quali sono felicità a servitù, spontaneità e costrizione, ricavasi questa assoluta sentenza che tra le nazioni civili il governo straniero non può vantarsi mai né della legittimità che abbiamo chiamata interiore, né della esteriore che emana dall'assentimento espresso o tacito delle popolazioni. (p. 20-21, IX) Non può aver luogo prescrizione, dove i diritti innati o fondamentali dell'uomo ricevono sostanziale ingiuria ed offesa; e di si fatti è per appunto la indipendenza o dimezzata o distrutta. (p. 21, IX) Ogni cosa nell'uomo è principiata dalla natura e poi dalla ragione e dall'arte è compiuta. (p. 30, XI) Mario Pagano, ovvero, della immortalità Incipit Francesco Pignatelli — Giuseppe Poerio Pignatelli: Voi stesso l'avete udito? Poerio: E come nò, se rinchiuso era con lui in una prigione medesima? Pignatelli: E fu la vigilia della sua morte? Poerio: Appunto fu la vigilia. Sapete che valica la mezzanotte, una voce improvvisa e sepolcrale veramente rompevane il sonno chiamando forte per nome alcuno di noi; e quella chiamata voleva dire: vieni, ti aspetta il carnefice. La notte pertanto che seguitò quel mirabil discorso di Mario Pagano gli sgherri gridarono il nome suo, e fu menato al patibolo. Pignatelli: Stava per mezzo a voi quell'omerica figura del conte di Ruvo? Poerio: Nò, ma in Castello dell'Uovo insieme con altri uffiziali e con l'intrepido Mantonè. Nel Castel Nuovo e in quella carcere proprio dove era Francesco Mario Pagano, stava il fratel vostro maggiore, principe di Strangoli, stava io, il Conforti, Cirillo, Granali, Eusebio Palmieri, Vincenzo Russo e due giovinetti amorevoli e cari, cioè l'ultimo figliuolo dello Spanò ed un marchese di Genzano, bello come l'Appollino e di cui sentiva il Pagano particolare compassione.  Citazioni Poerio: V'à una cagione suprema di tutte le cose, cagione assoluta e però insofferente di limiti e incapace d'aumento e di defficienza. Ma se niun difetto può stare in lei, ella è il bene infinito e comprende infinitamente ogni specie di bene. Ciò posto, la cagione suprema è altresì infinita bontà che raggia il bene fuor di sé stessa e ne riempie la creazione ed ogni ente se ne satura, a dir così, per quanto fu fatto capace. Tale contenenza di bene è poi sempre difettiva perché sempre è finita. Di quindi si origina il male. Non si chieda dunque perché Dio è permettitore del male, ma chiedasi in quella vece perché piacque a Dio, oltre all'infinito, che sussistesse pure il finito. (p. 16) Poerio: Se il vivere nostro presente fosse condito di molto diletto e noi incapaci di conoscere e desiderare con ismania istintiva l'eternità, forse potrebbesi giudicare senza paradosso aver noi sortito quella porzioncella sola e frammento di beatitudine, brevissima ma sincera e inconsapevole della propria caducità. (p. 17) Poerio: Col presupposto della immortalità, bene avvertiva il Bruno, alcun desiderio naturale non è indarno e alcuna lacrima non cade senza conforto. Con la immortalità non è affetto generoso perduto, non ferita dell'animo a cui non si apparecchi altrove copioso balsamo. Per entro il corso interminato e magnifico de'nostri destini, ogni male vien riparato, ogni speranza risorge, ogni bellezza rifiorisce, ogni felicità si rinnova e giganteggia ne'secoli. (p. 18) Poerio: Quando fosse possibile strappare dal cuor dell'uomo il concetto e la speranza della immortalità, il consorzio civile medesimo pericolerebbe di sciogliersi e i piaceri e le utilità stesse della vita presente verrebbero gran parte impedite o affatto levate di mezzo. (p. 18) Prose letterarie Avvertenza I dotti e i legisti barbareggiavano sempre peggio, e pareva in loro una sorta di necessità tramutata in diritto, e niun discepolo mai se ne querelava; e le lettere cadevano in tale grettezza, che nelle prose del Giordani si appuntavano parecchie mende di stile, ma nessuno accusava la tenuità dei concetti e la critica angusta e slombata. Il Colletta era stimato dai più uno storico sovrano e poco meno che un Tacito redivivo, ed altri istituivano paragone tra il Guicciardini e il Botta, tra il Goldoni ed Alberto Nota. Tale il gusto e il criterio comune. Pochi grandi intelletti non mancavano neppure a quei giorni. Basti ricordare Bartolini nella scultura; Leopardi e Niccolini nella poetica; Rossini, Bellini, Donizetti nella musica. In Italia scemando il sapere e la potenza meditativa, crebbe l'amore spasimato ed irragionevole della bellezza dell'abito esterno, lasciando a digiuno la mente e poco nudriti e mal governati gli affetti. Letteratura vasta, soda e ben definita, e parimente larghe scuole e ben tratteggiate e scolpite mancano alla patria nostra da quasi tre secoli e piuttosto ne abbiamo avuto cenni e frammenti, e ogni cosa a pezzi, a sbalzi e a modo d'assaggio. Miei degni signori, il cibo che v'apparecchio è scarso, scondito e di povera mensa, ma è letteratura e non metafisica. Non appena l'esilio mi astrinse a lasciare l'Italia e fui spettatore d'altro ordine di civiltà e uditore d'altri maestri, subito mi si aprì dentro l'animo l'occhio doloroso della coscienza, ed ebbi della mia ignoranza una paura ed una vergogna da non credere. Per giudicare alla prima prima che tutto è vecchio e trito in un libro convien sapere dell'autore se nel generale à l'abito di pensar di suo capo. IX. — Ed egli evoca nuovi spiriti di più sublime natura, i quali entrano a uno a uno dentro la torre. Spirito del mare. Che vuoi ? Barone. Sapere l'essenza del bene e la fonte della felicità. Spirito del mare. Perché lo chiedi al mare ? Barone. Perché tu sai o puoi sapere ogni cosa; tu nei silenzj della notte tieni misteriosi colloquj con la luna e con le stelle che in te si riflettono ; e tu pur ricevi nell ' ampio tuo seno i fiumi tutti del mondo, i quali ti raccontano le geste antiche dei popoli e le più antiche vicende dei continenti per mezzo a cui essi fluiscono senza posa. Spirito del mare. lo non so nulla (sparisce). Barone. Che tu venga malmenato in eterno dallo spirito delle procelle, e che i tuoi membri immortali sieno rotti e squarciati mai sempre dalle taglienti creste degli ardui scogli.  La coda del cavallo bianco dell' Apocalisse. Che vuoi ? Barone. Sapere in che consiste il bene, e dove è la fonte della felicità. La coda. Perché lo chiedi a me ? Barone. Tu sai la fine ultima delle cose, e tu comparirai poco innanzi della consumazione del secolo. La coda. Quando io comparirò, io ondeggerò nelle sfere, simile alla caduta del Niagara e più tremenda della coda delle comete. Ogni mio crine rinserra un destino ; e ogni mio moto è un cenno di oracolo ; ò trascorsi tutti i cieli di Tolomeo e i cieli di Galileo e i cieli di Herschel; ò lambita con la mia criniera la faccia delle stelle, e l'ò distesa sulle penne de' turbini; molte cose ò conosciute, ma non quel che tu cerchi: io non so nulla (sparisce). Prefazione alla scelta dei poeti italiani dell'età media Dagli Arabi si travasò il mal gusto ne' Catalani e ne' Provenzali, e una vena non troppo scarsa ne fu derivata ne' primi nostri verseggiatori. Dante egli pure non se ne astenne affatto; e noi peniamo a credere che a quel genio sovrano venisse scritta la canzone lambiccatissima della Pietra. (II) Sa ognuno che nel seicento, con lo scadere dell' arte, ricomparvero quelle freddure e mattie, e ogni cosa fu piena di acrostici, d'anagrammi, d'allitterazioni e altrettali sciempiezze. Ma per buona ventura cotesta sorta vanissima di pedanteria non sembra ai moderni pericolosa; e dico ai moderni italiani, perché appresso gli stranieri non ne mancano esempj ; e molti anno letto in un vivente poeta francese di gran nomea certi capricci di metri e di rime i quali dimostrano come in lui siensi venuti rinnovando tutti gli umori e le vertigini dei seicentisti. E nemmanco ci pare immune dalle stranezze di cui parliamo quel concepimento del Goethe di ordire la tragedia del Fausto con questa singolar legge che ogni scena fosse dettata in metro diverso ed una altresì in nuda prosa, onde potesse affermarsi che niuna maniera del verseggiare ed anzi dello scrivere umano (per quanto ne è capace il tedesco idioma) mancasse a quel dramma ; nuova maniera e poco assai naturale e graziosa di porgere idea e figura del panteismo. (II) Non può né deve il poeta scompagnarsi mai troppo dalle opinioni e dai sentimenti comuni dell'età sua; chè da questi principalmente è suscitato l'estro di lui, con questi accende e innamora le moltitudini. D'ogni altro pensiero ed affetto, ove li possieda e li senta egli solo, avrà pochi intenditori, pochissimi lodatori ; e la favella delle Muse langue e muor sulle labbra se non suona ad orecchie benevole e a cuori profondamente commossi. (VI) In Inghilterra il Milton fierissimo repubblicano e segretario eloquente del gran Cromvello, à quasi sempre poetato di cose mistiche e teologiche e nulla v'à di politico, nulla d'inglese e di patrio, né nel Paradiso perduto, né in altri suoi canti. (VI) Riuscirà sempre a gloria grande e invidiata d'Italia che la Gerusalemme del Tasso compaja tanto più bella e mirabile quanto più in lei si contempla e considera intentivamente la perfezione del tutto. (VII) Certo, il Valvasone è meno forbito ed armonioso del Tansillo, meno fluido del Tasso seniore, meno corretto, proprio e limato de' più corretti e limati rimatori toscani; ma non per ciò si capisce come questa minor perfezione di forma, abbia potuto oscurare nel giudicio de' raccoglitori e de' critici il gran merito dell'invenzione. Che il Milton siasi giovato dell' Angeleide non so, quantunque fra i due poemi si vengan trovando molti e singolari riscontri che non è facile a credere casuali; ma questo io so bene che a rispetto della guerra degli angeli episodicamente introdotta nel Paradiso perduto, il Valvasone non perde nulla ad esser letto dopo l'Inglese e con quello essere paragonato; il che non avviene del sicuro né per l' Adamo dell'Andreini né per la Strage degl'Innocenti del cavaliere Marino, due componimenti che dicesi aver suggerito a Milton parecchi pensieri e l'ideal grandezza del suo Lucifero. (VIII) L'ingegno poetico, in versificare ciascuno di quei subbietti, tende a spiegare una novità, un' altezza e una leggiadria suprema di concetto, di sentimento, di fantasia e di stile. Dove mancasse l'una di tali eccellenze, l'arte sarebbe difettosa e quindi increscevole. (IX) Ci venne osservato (cosa che per addietro non ben sapevamo) la critica letteraria incominciata in Italia con Dante essere morta col Tasso e gli amici suoi; e come cadde con quel mirabile intelletto la nostra primazia nel ministero delle Muse, così venne meno la filosofia estetica; e il nuovo dell' arte non fu capito, l'antico fu dalla pedanteria svisato e agghiadato. L'arte critica antica ebbe ultimi promulgatori due grandi ingegni, il Muratori e il Gravina. Della critica nata dipoi con le nuove speculazioni e con le nuove forme di poesia, non conosciamo in Italia alcun degno scrittore e rappresentatore. (X) Dopo Omero nessun poeta, per mio giudicio, può alzarsi a competere con l'Alighieri, salvo Guglielmo Shakspeare, gloria massima dell'Inghilterra. E per fermo, ne' drammi di lui l'animo e la vita umana vengon ritratti così al vero e scandagliati e disaminati così nel profondo, che mai nol saranno di più. Ma le condizioni peculiari della drammatica e l'indole propria degl' ingegni settentrionali impedirono a Shakspeare di raggiungere quella perfetta unione sì delle diverse materie poetiche e sì di tutte l'eccellenze e prerogative onde facciamo discorso. E veramente nelle composizioni sue la religione si mostra sol di lontano e molto di rado; e tra le specie differenti e delicatissime d'amore ivi entro significate, manca quella eccelsa e spiritualissima di cui si scaldò l'amante di Beatrice. (XI) Il poeta è dall'ispirazione allacciato e padroneggiato sì forte, da non saper bene sottomettersi all'arte ed alla meditazione. (XII) Il troppo incivilirsi dei popoli aumentando di soverchio l'osservazione e la critica e affinandovisi l'arte ogni giorno di più per effetto medesimo dell' esercizio e dell' esperienza e per desiderio di novità, mena il poeta a scordar forse troppo l'aurea semplicità degli antichi, il sincero aspetto della natura e i veri e spontanei moti dell'animo. (XII) Il compiuto e l'ottimo della poesia consiste in racchiudere dentro ai poemi con vaga e proporzionata unità di composizione tutto quanto il visibile ed il pensabile umano per ciò che in ambedue è più bello e più commovente. Consiste inoltre nel figurare e ritrarre cotesto subbietto amplissimo e universale con la maggior novità e la maggiore sublimità e leggiadria di concepimento, di fantasia, d'affetto e d'elocuzione che sia fattibile di conseguire. Laonde poi il concepimento, così nel complesso come nelle sentenze particolari, dee riuscir succoso, vario ed inaspettato e pieno di recondita dottrina e saggezza; l'affetto dee correre, quanto è possibile, per tutti i gradi e le differenze, e toccare il sommo della tenerezza e commiserazione e il sommo della terribilità. (XIII) Il Tasso, anima pia e generosa, ma in cui (non so dir come) nulla v'era di popolare. Quindi egli s'infervorò della maestà teocratica dei pontefici e aderì alla nuova cavalleria cortigiana e feudale; quindi pure accettò con zelo e con osservanza scrupolosa l' ortodossia cattolica, e nella vita intellettuale quanto nella civile, fu dall' autorità dei metodi e degli esempj signoreggiato. Da ciò prese nudrimento e moto il divino estro suo e uscirono le maraviglie della Gerusalemme (XIX) Nel Tasso poi sono tutti i pregi e tutta quanta la luce e magnificenza della poesia classica, e spiccano altresì in lui alcuni attributi speciali del genio italiano in ordine al bello. In perpetuo si ammirerà nella Liberata ciò che l'arte, i precetti, l'erudizione e la scienza possono fare, ajutati e avvivati da una stupenda natura poetica. (XX) L'Ariosto significò la commedia umana quale la veggiamo rappresentarsi nel mondo, laddove Dante fece primo subbietto suo il soprammondano, e in esso figurò e simboleggiò le cose terrene. E come il gran Fiorentino nelle fogge variatissime de' tormenti e delle espiazioni dipinse i variatissimi aspetti delle indoli e delle passioni, il simile adempiva l'Ariosto sotto il velo dei portenti magici e delle strane avventure. Ma certo qual narrazione di fatti umani riuscirà più vasta, più immaginosa e più moltiforme di quella dell' Orlando furioso? Quivi sono guerre tra più nazioni, nascimenti e ruine di molti regni, conflitto sanguinoso di religione e di culto, infinita diversità e singolarità di costumi, e tutto il Ponente e il Levante offrono larga scena e strepitoso teatro a cotali imprese e catastrofi. Quivi sono dipinte la vita privata e la pubblica, le corti e le capanne, i castelli ed i romitaggi; quivi s'intrecciano gradevolmente la cronica, la novella e la storia, e ciò che il dramma à di patetico, l'epopeia di maestoso, il romanzo di fantastico. (XXI) Non credo che in veruna straniera letteratura possa come nella nostra volgare annoverarsi una sequela così sterminata di poemi eroici e di romanzeschi, parecchj de' quali brillerebbero di gran luce, ove fossero soli e non li soverchiasse la troppa chiarezza di Dante, dell'Ariosto e del Tasso. Né reputo presontuoso il dire che, per esempio, la Croce racquistata del Bracciolini o il Conquisto di Granata di Girolamo Graziane sostengono bene assai il paragone o con l'Araucana dell' Ercilla o coi medesimi Lusiadi [di Luís Vaz de Camões] ai quali ànno accresciuta non poca fama le sventure e le virtù del poeta ; e per simile, io giudico che l' Amadigi del Tasso il vecchio o l'Orlando innamorato del Berni, non temono di gareggiare con la Regina Fata di Spenser e con quanto di meglio in tal genere ànno prodotto l'altre nazioni. Ma non è da tacere che in quasi tutti questi nostri poemi riconoscesi agevolmente l'uno o l'altro dei tipi che nel Furioso e nella Gerusalemme ricevettero perfezione, ed a cui poca giunta di novità e poche profonde mutazioni si fecero dagl'ingegni posteriori; e ne' poemi eroici singolarmente a niuno è riuscito di ben cantare i difetti del Tasso, molti in quel cambio li esagerarono. (XXII) Scusabile mi si fa il Marino e scusabili gl'Italiani, quand'io considero lo stato di lor nazione sotto il crudele dominio degli Spagnuoli, e fieramente mi sdegno con questi medesimi che nella patria loro ancor sì potente e sì fortunata, plaudivano a que' delirj e incensavano il Gongora, meno ingegnoso assai del Marino e di lui più strano e affettato. In fine, gioverà il ricordare che all'Italia serva, scaduta e dilapidata, rimaneva pur tanto ancora di prevalenza intellettuale appresso l'altre nazioni che de' trionfi più insigni e delle lodi più sperticate del cavalier Marino furono autori i Francesi ; e per lungo tempo assai nessuno de' lor poeti seppe al tutto purgarsi della letteraria corruzione venuta d'oltre Alpe ; testimonio lo stesso Cornelio, alto e robustissimo ingegno, ma nel cui stile nondimeno avria dovuto il Boileau ritrovare assai spesso di quel medesimo talco del quale parevangli luccicare i versi del Tasso. (XXIII) Dal Marino incominciò a propagarsi nel mondo una poesia fantastica e meramente coloritrice, la quale cerca l'arte solo per l'arte, fassi specchio indifferente al falso ed al vero, alle cose buone ed alle malvage, alle vane e giocose come alle grandi e instruttive; sente tutti gli affetti e nessuno con profondità, e nell'essere suo naturale od abituale, canta di Adone, come di Erode e così delle favole greche come delle bibliche narrazioni. (XXIV) [Dal cinquecento al secolo XVII] [...] Fiorirono in tale intervallo tre ingegni eminenti che forse mantennero alla lirica nostra una spiccata maggioranza su quella d'altre nazioni. Ognuno, io penso, à nominato ad una con me il Chiabrera, il Filicaja ed il Guidi. (XXV) Dal solo Chiabrera fu l'Italia regalata di tre nuove corone poetiche ; mercechè veramente nelle sue mani nacque e grandeggiò prima la canzone pindarica, poi la canzone anacreontica e infine il sermone oraziano ; né mal s' apporrebbe colui che attribuisse al Chiabrera eziandio la rinnovazione del Ditirambo. (XXV) Il Filicaja venne a tempi ancora più disavventurati, e quando più non era possibile discoprire ne' suoi Fiorentini un segno e un vestigio pure dell'antica fierezza repubblicana. Ma il senso del bene morale e la pietà religiosa fervevano così profondi nell'animo suo che bastarono a farlo poeta. (XXVI) Mai né in questa nostra patria, né fuori sonosi udite canzoni così ben temperate di splendore pindarico e di maestà scritturale come quelle del Filicaja. (XXVI) Nel Guidi allato a concetti ed a sentimenti spesso comuni e rettorici, splende una forma non superabile di novità, di bellezza e magnificenza. (XXVI) Certo, se ad Alessandro Guidi fosse toccato di vivere in seno di una nazione forte e gloriosa, non ostante la poca fecondità e vastità di pensieri, io non so bene a qual grado di eccellenza non sarebbe salita la lirica sua; perché costui propriamente sortì da natura Yos magna sonaturum, e ce ne porge sicura caparra la sua canzone alla Fortuna. (XXVI) A me sonerà sempre caro ed insigne il nome di Alfonso Varano, perché da lui segnatamente, a quello che io giudico, s'iniziò il corso della poesia moderna italiana ; e forse la patria non gli si mostra ricordevole e grata quanto dovrebbe. (XXVIII) Chi trovasse non poca similitudine tra la mente del Varano e quella del Young, credo che male non si apporrebbe. Anime pie e stoiche ambidue, e dischiuse non pertanto agli affetti gentili, diffondono ne' lor versi un religioso terrore e un' ascetica melanconia che nell'Inglese riescono cupi, inconsolati e monotoni, e nell'Italiano s'allegrano spesso alla vista del nostro bel sole, e dai pensieri del sepolcro volano con gran fede alla pace e serenità della gloria immortale. (XXVIII) Varano poi insieme col Gozzi restituì alla Divina Commedia il debito culto; il Gozzi con li scritti polemici, egli con la virtù dell' esempio; ed ebbe arbitrio di dire a Dante ciò che questi a Virgilio : Tu séi lo mio maestro e il mio autore. Se non che il cantore delle Visioni chiuse e conchiuse l'intero universo nel sentimento della pietà e nei misteri del dogma, e non ben seppe imitare del suo modello la nervosa brevità e parsimonia, la varietà inesauribile e la peregrina eleganza. (XXVIII)  Citazioni su Terenzio Mamiani Se taluno dei suoi piuttosto scarsi scolari volle talora celebrare nel conte Terenzio Mamiani della Rovere (1799-1885) l'ultimo anello della catena che dal Galluppi si continuò in Rosmini e Gioberti, unanime fu il consenso dei suoi maggiori contemporanei e dei posteri nell'affermare il valore pressoché nullo della sua vasta produzione filosofica. (Eugenio Garin) Candido Mamini La teoria del Rosmini fu più scolastica, quella del Mamiani più civile; quella quasi sterile in politica, questa molto feconda, risolvendo i problemi più ardui e interessanti della vita sociale. Quella fu timida, questa coraggiosa; quella arrivò a rifiutare sul terreno pratico le-conseguenze de' suoi principii per un pregiudizioso rispetto di casta non evitando il disonore di una ritirata e la deformità del sofisma; questa per lo contrario tutta intrepida si sostenne colla gloria di una vittoria, colla dignità di una rigorosa coerenza, e colla bellezza di una vera argomentazione. Rosmini in un bel momento di sua ragione scrive stupende pagine sulla riforma del clero; poi ha la debolezza di ritirarle, impaurito dalle minaccia dell'Indice; Mamiani è oggi quel che era ne' primi giorni della sua vita pubblica, e non sa temere altro autorevole indice che quello del buon senso. Nel suo ultimo libro, intitolalo Di un nuovo diritto europeo, si ammira il coraggio della coscienza di un filosofo, e la prudenza d'un uomo di Stato. Riguardo poi ai pregi della forma, Rosmini fu semplicemente filosofo, Mamiani un filosofo-oratore; nel primo spicca la pura meditazione, nel secondo si unisce il genio che feconda il deserto delle speculazioni metafisiche, delle avanzate astrazioni. Nel primo vi ha una ricchezza povera, cioè una stiracchiatura di poche idee in molte parole, quasi diffidi della memoria, e dell'abilità del lettore; nel secondo vi ha una povertà ricca, cioè molte idee in poche parole; il che appaga l'amor proprio del lettore, e ne fa liete tutte le potenze della ritentiva e della ragione. Bibliografia Terenzio Mamiani, Antonio Oroboni alla sua fidanzata, da un libro anonimo del 1929. Terenzio Mamiani, D'un nuovo diritto europeo, Tipografia Scolastica, Torino, 1861. Terenzio Mamiani, Dell'ottima congregazione umana e del principio di nazionalità, Rivista contemporanea, vol. 2-3, Pelazza Tipografia Subalpina, Torino, 1855. Terenzio Mamiani, Mario Pagano, ovvero, della immortalità, Dai Torchi della Signora De Lacombe, Parigi, 1845. Terenzio Mamiani, Prose letterarie, G. Barbera Editore, Firenze, 1867. Altri progetti Collabora a Wikipedia Wikipedia contiene una voce riguardante Terenzio Mamiani Collabora a Wikisource Wikisource contiene una pagina dedicata a Terenzio Mamiani Collabora a Commons Commons contiene immagini o altri file su Terenzio Mamiani Categorie: Filosofi italianiPatrioti italianiPoeti italianiPolitici italianiScrittori italiani. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice e della Rovere," per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.

rule of law, the largely formal or procedural properties of a well-ordered legal system. Commonly, these properties are thought to include: a prohibition of arbitrary power the lawgiver is also subject to the laws; laws that are general, prospective, clear, and consistent capable of guiding conduct; and tribunals courts that are reasonably accessible and fairly structured to hear and determine legal claims. Contemporary discussions of the rule of law focus on two major questions: 1 to what extent is conformity to the rule of law essential to the very idea of a legal system; and 2 what is the connection between the rule of law and the substantive moral value of a legal system? 

Russell: “not really a philosopher,” as Grice puts it, by either education or practice, he was born of Celtic Highland stock into an aristocratic family in Wales (then part of England), Russell always divided his interests between politics, philosophy, and the ladies (he married six times). Orphaned at four, he was brought up by his grandmother, who educated him at home with the help of “rather dull” tutors. He studied mathematics at Cambridge and then, as his grandmother says, ‘out of the blue,’ he turned to philosophy. At home he had absorbed J. S. Mill’s liberalism, but not his empiricism. At Cambridge he came under the influence of neo-Hegelianism, especially the idealism of McTaggart, Ward his tutor, and Bradley. His earliest logical views were influenced most by Bradley, especially Bradley’s rejection of psychologism. But, like Ward and McTaggart, he rejected Bradley’s metaphysical monism in favor of pluralism or monadism. Even as an idealist, he held that scientific knowledge was the best available and that philosophy should be built around it. Through many subsequent changes, this belief about science, his pluralism, and his anti-psychologism remained constant. In 5, he conceived the idea of an idealist encyclopedia of the sciences to be developed by the use of transcendental arguments to establish the conditions under which the special sciences are possible. Russell’s first philosophical book, An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry 7, was part of this project, as were other mostly unfinished and unpublished pieces on physics and arithmetic written at this time see his Collected Papers, vols. 12. Russell claimed, in contrast to Kant, to use transcendental arguments in a purely logical way compatible with his anti-psychologism. In this case, however, it should be both possible and preferable to replace them by purely deductive arguments. Another problem arose in connection with asymmetrical relations, which led to contradictions if treated as internal relations, but which were essential for any treatment of mathematics. Russell resolved both problems in 8 by abandoning idealism including internal relations and his Kantian methodology. He called this the one real revolution in his philosophy. With his Cambridge contemporary Moore, he adopted an extreme Platonic realism, fully stated in The Principles of Mathematics 3 though anticipated in A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz 0. Russell’s work on the sciences was by then concentrated on pure mathematics, but the new philosophy yielded little progress until, in 0, he discovered Peano’s symbolic logic, which offered hope that pure mathematics could be treated without Kantian intuitions or transcendental arguments. On this basis Russell propounded logicism, the claim that the whole of pure mathematics could be derived deductively from logical principles, a position he came to independently of Frege, who held a similar but more restricted view but whose work Russell discovered only later. Logicism was announced in The Principles of Mathematics; its development occupied Russell, in collaboration with Whitehead, for the next ten years. Their results were published in Principia Mathematica 013, 3 vols., in which detailed derivations were given for Cantor’s set theory, finite and transfinite arithmetic, and elementary parts of measure theory. As a demonstration of Russell’s logicism, Principia depends upon much prior arithmetization of mathematics, e.g. of analysis, which is not explicitly treated. Even with these allowances much is still left out: e.g., abstract algebra and statistics. Russell’s unpublished papers Papers, vols. 45, however, contain logical innovations not included in Principia, e.g., anticipations of Church’s lambda-calculus. On Russell’s extreme realism, everything that can be referred to is a term that has being though not necessarily existence. The combination of terms by means of a relation results in a complex term, which is a proposition. Terms are neither linguistic nor psychological. The first task of philosophy is the theoretical analysis of propositions into their constituents. The propositions of logic are unique in that they remain true when any of their terms apart from logical constants are replaced by any other terms. In 1 Russell discovered that this position fell prey to self-referential paradoxes. For example, if the combination of any number of terms is a new term, the combination of all terms is a term distinct from any term. The most famous such paradox is called Russell’s paradox. Russell’s solution was the theory of types, which banned self-reference by stratifying terms and expressions into complex hierarchies of disjoint subclasses. The expression ‘all terms’, e.g., is then meaningless unless restricted to terms of specified types, and the combination of terms of a given type is a term of different type. A simple version of the theory appeared in Principles of Mathematics appendix A, but did not eliminate all the paradoxes. Russell developed a more elaborate version that did, in “Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of Types” 8 and in Principia. From 3 to 8 Russell sought to preserve his earlier account of logic by finding other ways to avoid the paradoxes  including a well-developed substitutional theory of classes and relations posthumously published in Essays in Analysis, 4, and Papers, vol. 5. Other costs of type theory for Russell’s logicism included the vastly increased complexity of the resulting sysRussell, Bertrand Arthur William Russell, Bertrand Arthur William 802    802 tem and the admission of the problematic axiom of reducibility. Two other difficulties with Russell’s extreme realism had important consequences: 1 ‘I met Quine’ and ‘I met a man’ are different propositions, even when Quine is the man I met. In the Principles, the first proposition contains a man, while the second contains a denoting concept that denotes the man. Denoting concepts are like Fregean senses; they are meanings and have denotations. When one occurs in a proposition the proposition is not about the concept but its denotation. This theory requires that there be some way in which a denoting concept, rather than its denotation, can be denoted. After much effort, Russell concluded in “On Denoting” 5 that this was impossible and eliminated denoting concepts as intermediaries between denoting phrases and their denotations by means of his theory of descriptions. Using firstorder predicate logic, Russell showed in a broad, though not comprehensive range of cases how denoting phrases could be eliminated in favor of predicates and quantified variables, for which logically proper names could be substituted. These were names of objects of acquaintance  represented in ordinary language by ‘this’ and ‘that’. Most names, he thought, were disguised definite descriptions. Similar techniques were applied elsewhere to other kinds of expression e.g. class names resulting in the more general theory of incomplete symbols. One important consequence of this was that the ontological commitments of a theory could be reduced by reformulating the theory to remove expressions that apparently denoted problematic entities. 2 The theory of incomplete symbols also helped solve extreme realism’s epistemic problems, namely how to account for knowledge of terms that do not exist, and for the distinction between true and false propositions. First, the theory explained how knowledge of a wide range of items could be achieved by knowledge by acquaintance of a much narrower range. Second, propositional expressions were treated as incomplete symbols and eliminated in favor of their constituents and a propositional attitude by Russell’s multiple relation theory of judgment. These innovations marked the end of Russell’s extreme realism, though he remained a Platonist in that he included universals among the objects of acquaintance. Russell referred to all his philosophy after 8 as logical atomism, indicating thereby that certain categories of items were taken as basic and items in other categories were constructed from them by rigorous logical means. It depends therefore upon reduction, which became a key concept in early analytic philosophy. Logical atomism changed as Russell’s logic developed and as more philosophical consequences were drawn from its application, but the label is now most often applied to the modified realism Russell held from 5 to 9. Logic was central to Russell’s philosophy from 0 onward, and much of his fertility and importance as a philosopher came from his application of the new logic to old problems. In 0 Russell became a lecturer at Cambridge. There his interests turned to epistemology. In writing a popular book, Problems of Philosophy 2, he first came to appreciate the work of the British empiricists, especially Hume and Berkeley. He held that empirical knowledge is based on direct acquaintance with sense-data, and that matter itself, of which we have only knowledge by description, is postulated as the best explanation of sense-data. He soon became dissatisfied with this idea and proposed instead that matter be logically constructed out of sensedata and unsensed sensibilia, thereby obviating dubious inferences to material objects as the causes of sensations. This proposal was inspired by the successful constructions of mathematical concepts in Principia. He planned a large work, “Theory of Knowledge,” which was to use the multiple relation theory to extend his account from acquaintance to belief and inference Papers, vol. 7. However, the project was abandoned as incomplete in the face of Vitters’s attacks on the multiple relation theory, and Russell published only those portions dealing with acquaintance. The construction of matter, however, went ahead, at least in outline, in Our Knowledge of the External World 4, though the only detailed constructions were undertaken later by Carnap. On Russell’s account, material objects are those series of sensibilia that obey the laws of physics. Sensibilia of which a mind is aware sense-data provide the experiential basis for that mind’s knowledge of the physical world. This theory is similar, though not identical, to phenomenalism. Russell saw the theory as an application of Ockham’s razor, by which postulated entities were replaced by logical constructions. He devoted much time to understanding modern physics, including relativity and quantum theory, and in The Analysis of Matter 7 he incorporated the fundamental ideas of those theories into his construction of the physical world. In this book he abandoned sensibilia as fundamental constituents of the world in favor Russell, Bertrand Arthur William Russell, Bertrand Arthur William 803    803 of events, which were “neutral” because intrinsically neither physical nor mental. In 6 Russell was dismissed from Cambridge on political grounds and from that time on had to earn his living by writing and public lecturing. His popular lectures, “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism” 8, were a result of this. These lectures form an interim work, looking back on the logical achievements of 510 and emphasizing their importance for philosophy, while taking stock of the problems raised by Vitters’s criticisms of the multiple relation theory. In 9 Russell’s philosophy of mind underwent substantial changes, partly in response to those criticisms. The changes appeared in “On Propositions: What They Are and How They Mean” 9 and The Analysis of Mind 1, where the influence of contemporary trends in psychology, especially behaviorism, is evident. Russell gave up the view that minds are among the fundamental constituents of the world, and adopted neutral monism, already advocated by Mach, James, and the  New Realists. On Russell’s neutral monism, a mind is constituted by a set of events related by subjective temporal relations simultaneity, successiveness and by certain special “mnemic” causal laws. In this way he was able to explain the apparent fact that “Hume’s inability to perceive himself was not peculiar.” In place of the multiple relation theory Russell identified the contents of beliefs with images “imagepropositions” and words “word-propositions”, understood as certain sorts of events, and analyzed truth qua correspondence in terms of resemblance and causal relations. From 8 to 4 Russell lived in the United States, where he wrote An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth 0 and his popular A History of Western Philosophy 5. His philosophical attention turned from metaphysics to epistemology and he continued to work in this field after he returned in 4 to Cambridge, where he completed his last major philosophical work, Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits 8. The framework of Russell’s early epistemology consisted of an analysis of knowledge in terms of justified true belief though it has been suggested that he unintentionally anticipated Edmund Gettier’s objection to this analysis, and an analysis of epistemic justification that combined fallibilism with a weak empiricism and with a foundationalism that made room for coherence. This framework was retained in An Inquiry and Human Knowledge, but there were two sorts of changes that attenuated the foundationalist and empiricist elements and accentuated the fallibilist element. First, the scope of human knowledge was reduced. Russell had already replaced his earlier Moorean consequentialism about values with subjectivism. Contrast “The Elements of Ethics,” 0, with, e.g., Religion and Science, 5, or Human Society in Ethics and Politics, 4. Consequently, what had been construed as self-evident judgments of intrinsic value came to be regarded as non-cognitive expressions of desire. In addition, Russell now reversed his earlier belief that deductive inference can yield new knowledge. Second, the degree of justification attainable in human knowledge was reduced at all levels. Regarding the foundation of perceptual beliefs, Russell came to admit that the object-knowledge “acquaintance with a sensedatum” was replaced by “noticing a perceptive occurrence” in An Inquiry that provides the non-inferential justification for a perceptual belief is buried under layers of “interpretation” and unconscious inference in even the earliest stages of perceptual processes. Regarding the superstructure of inferentially justified beliefs, Russell concluded in Human Knowledge that unrestricted induction is not generally truthpreserving anticipating Goodman’s “new riddle of induction”. Consideration of the work of Reichenbach and Keynes on probability led him to the conclusion that certain “postulates” are needed “to provide the antecedent probabilities required to justify inductions,” and that the only possible justification for believing these postulates lies, not in their self-evidence, but in the resultant increase in the overall coherence of one’s total belief system. In the end, Russell’s desire for certainty went unsatisfied, as he felt himself forced to the conclusion that “all human knowledge is uncertain, inexact, and partial. To this doctrine we have not found any limitation whatever.” Russell’s strictly philosophical writings of 9 and later have generally been less influential than his earlier writings. His influence was eclipsed by that of logical positivism and ordinary language philosophy. He approved of the logical positivists’ respect for logic and science, though he disagreed with their metaphysical agnosticism. But his dislike of ordinary language philosophy was visceral. In My Philosophical Development 9, he accused its practitioners of abandoning the attempt to understand the world, “that grave and important task which philosophy throughout the ages has hitherto pursued.” 

RECTVM -- DE-RECTUM -- directum. “Searle thought he was being witty when adapting my implicaturum to what he called an Indirect Austinian thing. Holdcroft was less obvious!” – Grice. – indirectum -- indirect discourse, also called oratio obliqua, the use of words to report what others say, but without direct quotation. When one says “John said, ‘Not every doctor is honest,’ “ one uses the words in one’s quotation directly – one uses direct discourseto make an assertion about what John said. Accurate direct discourse must get the exact words. But in indirect discourse one can use other words than John does to report what he said, e.g., “John said that some physicians are not honest.” The words quoted here capture the sense of John’s assertion (the proposition he asserted). By extension, ‘indirect discourse’ designates the use of words in reporting beliefs. One uses words to characterize the proposition believed rather than to make a direct assertion. When Alice says, “John believes that some doctors are not honest,” she uses the words ‘some doctors are not honest’ to present the proposition that John believes. She does not assert the proposition. By contrast, direct discourse, also called oratio recta, is the ordinary use of words to make assertions. Grice struggled for years as to what the ‘fundamentum distinctionis’ is between the central and the peripheric communicatum. He played with first-ground versus second-ground. He played with two different crtieria: formal/material, and dictive-non-dictive. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Holdcroft on direct and indirect communication.”


ryle: the waynflete professor of metaphysical philosophy, known especially for his contributions to the philosophy of mind and his attacks on Cartesianism. His best-known work is the masterpiece The Concept of Mind 9, an attack on what he calls “Cartesian dualism” and a defense of a type of logical behaviorism. This dualism he dubs “the dogma of the Ghost in the Machine,” the Machine being the body, which is physical and publicly observable, and the Ghost being the mind conceived as a private or secret arena in which episodes of sense perception, consciousness, and inner perception take place. A person, then, is a combination of such a mind and a body, with the mind operating the body through exercises of will called “volitions.” Ryle’s attack on this doctrine is both sharply focused and multifarious. He finds that it rests on a category mistake, namely, assimilating statements about mental processes to the same category as statements about physical processes. This is a mistake in the logic of mental statements and mental concepts and leads to the mistaken metaphysical theory that a person is composed of two separate and distinct though somehow related entities, a mind and a body. It is true that statements about the physical are statements about things and their changes. But statements about the mental are not, and in particular are not about a thing called “the mind.” These two types of statements do not belong to the same category. To show this, Ryle deploys a variety of arguments, including arguments alleging the impossibility of causal relations between mind and body and arguments alleging vicious infinite regresses. To develop his positive view on the nature of mind, Ryle studies the uses and hence the logic of mental terms and finds that mental statements tell us that the person performs observable actions in certain ways and has a disposition to perform other observable actions in specifiable circumstances. For example, to do something intelligently is to do something physical in a certain way and to adjust one’s behavior to the circumstances, not, as the dogma of the Ghost in the Machine would have it, to perform two actions, one of which is a mental action of thinking that eventually causes a separate physical action. Ryle buttresses this position with many acute and subtle analyses of the uses of mental terms. Much of Ryle’s other work concerns philosophical methodology, sustaining the thesis which is the backbone of The Concept of Mind that philosophical problems and doctrines often arise from conceptual confusion, i.e., from mistakes about the logic of language. Important writings in this vein include the influential article “Systematically Misleading Expressions” and the book Dilemmas. Ryle was also interested in Grecian philosophy throughout his life, and his last major work, Plato’s Progress, puts forward novel hypotheses about changes in Plato’s views, the role of the Academy, the purposes and uses of Plato’s dialogues, and Plato’s relations with the rulers of Syracuse. Refs: H. P. Grice, “What neither Ryle nor Austin ever taught me!” --. “What I mislearned from ‘The Concept of Mind.’”

No comments:

Post a Comment