All fallacies – argumentum ad:
ship of
Theseus: the ship of the Grecian hero
Theseus, which, according to Plutarch “Life of Theseus,” 23, the Athenians
preserved by gradually replacing its timbers. A classic debate ensued
concerning identity over time. Suppose a ship’s timbers are replaced one by one
over a period of time; at what point, if any, does it cease to be the same
ship? What if the ship’s timbers, on removal, are used to build a new ship,
identical in structure with the first: which ship has the best claim to be the
original ship?
shpet: phenomenologist and highly regarded friend of
Husserl. Shpet plays a major role in the development of phenomenology. Graduating
from Kiev in 6, Shpet accompanied his mentor
Chelpanov to Moscow, ommencing graduate studies at Moscow M.A., 0; Ph.D., 6. He attends Husserl’s
seminars at Göttingen during 213, out of which developed a continuing
friendship between the two, recorded in correspondence extending through 8. In
4 Shpet published a meditation, “Iavlenie i smysl,” nspired by Husserl’s
Logical Investigations and, especially, Ideas I, which had appeared in 3.
Between 4 and 7 he published six additional books on such disparate topics as
the concept of history, Herzen, philosophy, aesthetics, ethnic psychology, and
language. He founds and edited the philosophical yearbook Mysl’ i slovo Thought
and Word between 8 and 1, publishing an important article on skepticism in it.
He was arrested and sentenced to internal exile. Under these conditions he made
a running commentary of Hegel’s Phenomenology. He was executed.
sidgwick: English
philosopher. Best known for “The Methods of Ethics,” he also wrote “Outlines of
the History of Ethics.” In the “Methods,” Sidgwick tries to assess the
rationality of the main ways in which ordinary people go about making this or
that moral decision. Sidgwick thinks that our common “methods of ethics” fall
into three main patterns. The first pattern is articulated by the philosophical
theory known as intuitionism. This is the view that we can just see straight
off either what particular act is right or what binding rule or general principle
we ought to follow. A second pattern is spelled out by what self-love or egoism,
the view that we ought in each act to get as much good as we can for ourselves.
– vide: H. P. Grice, “The principle of conversational self-love and the
principle of conversational benevolence,” H. P.
Grice, “Conversational benevolence, not conversational self-love.” The
third widely used method is represented by utilitarianism, the view that we
ought in each case to bring about as much good as possible for everyone
affected. Can any or all of the methods prescribed by these views be rationally
defended? And how are they related to one another? By framing his philosophical
questions in these terms, Sidgwick makes it centrally important to examine the
chief philosophical theories of morality in the light of the common-sense
morals of his time. Sidgwick thinks that no theory wildly at odds with common-sense
morality would be acceptable. Intuitionism, a theory originating with Butler
(of ‘self-love and benevolence’ fame), transmitted by Reid, and most
systematically expounded during the Victorian era by Whewell, is widely held to
be the best available defense of Christian morals. Egoism (Self-love) was
thought by many to be the clearest pattern of practical (or means-end)
rationality and is frequently said to be compatible with Christianity. And J.
S. Mill had argues that utilitarianism is both rational and in accord with
common sense. But whatever their relation to ordinary morality, the three
methods or patterns seem to be seriously at odds with one another. Examining
all the chief commonsense precepts and rules of morality, such as that promises
ought to be kept, Sidgwick argues that none is truly self-evident or intuitively
certain. Each fails to guide us at certain points where we expect it to answer
our practical questions. Utilitarianism, he found, could provide a complicated
method for filling these gaps. But what ultimately justifies utilitarianism is
certain very general axioms seen intuitively to be true. Among them are the
principles that what is right in one case must be right in any similar case,
and that we ought to aim at good generally, not just at some particular part of
it. Thus intuitionism and utilitarianism can be reconciled. When taken together
they yield a complete and justifiable method of ethics that is in accord with
common sense. What then of egoism and self-love? Self love and egoirm can
provide as complete a method as utilitarianism, and it also involves a
self-evident axiom. But the results of
egoism and self-love often contradict those of utilitarianism. Hence there is a
serious problem. The method that instructs us to act always for the good
generally and the method that tells one to act solely for one’s own good are
equally rational. Since the two methods give contradictory directions, while
each method rests on self-evident axioms, it seems that practical reason is
fundamentally incoherent. Sidgwick could see no way to solve the problem. Sidgwick’s
bleak conclusion is not generally accepted (especially at Oxford), but his
Methods is widely viewed as one of the best works of moral philosophy ever
written in what Grice calls ‘insular’ philosophy (as opposed to mainland
philosophy). Sidgwick’s account of
classical utilitarianism is unsurpassed. Sidwick’s discussions of the general
status of morality and of particular moral concepts are enduring models of
clarity and acumen. His insights about the relations between egoism (self-love)
and utilitarianism have stimulated much valuable research. And his way of
framing moral problems, by asking about the relations between commonsense
beliefs and the best available theories, has set much of the agenda for ethics.
sì/no -- “sic” et “ne” – modus interrogativus. Grice: “Oddly that the Italians call
themselves as speaking the ‘lingua del si,’ contra the Gallics, who speak the
‘lingua del’oc,” or worse, the ‘lingua d’oil”!! -- Grice: Or yes/no question. “Cicero
has this as ‘sic’ and ‘non.’ For Grice, tertium non datur. Grice’s example is
“Have you stopped beating your wife,
Smith?” “Smith is tricked into having to say ‘yes,’ which makes him a criminal,
or “no,” which doesn’t but *implicates* him in a crime.” “The explicit cancellation
would be, “No, because I never started it.” – “But usually Smith is never so
intelligently Griceian like *that*! Vide: modus interrogatives. Grice finds the formalisation of a yes-no
question more complicated than that of an x-question. Like Carnap, he concludes
that the distinction is otiose, because a yes/no question also is after a
variable to be filled by a definite value, regarding the truth-value of the
proposition as a whole rather than a part thereof. Grice: “While I’ll casually
use ‘yes,’ I’m well aware that the ‘s,’ as every German schoolboy knows, is
otiose – it’s ‘yeah’ which is the correct form!” -- Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Cicero
on ‘sic’ and ‘ne’.” BANC, Speranza, “First time in Corpus?”
signatum: Cf. “to sign” as a verb – from French. Grice uses
designatum, too – but more specifically within the ‘propositio’ as a compound
of a subjectum and a predicatum. The subject-item indicates a thing; and the
predicate-item designates a property. As Grice notes, there is a distinction
between Aristotle’s use, in De Int., of ‘sumbolon,’ for which Aristotle
sometimes means ‘semeion,’ and their Roman counterparts, ‘signum’ sounds otiose
enough. But ‘significo’ does not. There is this –fico thing that sounds
obtrusive. The Romans, however, were able to distinguish between ‘make a sign,’
and just ‘signal.’ The point is important when Grice tries to apply the
Graeco-Roman philosophical terminology to a lexeme which does not belong in
there: “mean.” His example is someone in pain, uttering “Oh.” If he later gains
voluntary control, by uttering “Oh” he means that he is in pain, and even at a
later stage, provided he learns ‘lupe,’ he may utter the expression which is
somewhat correlated in a non-iconic fashion with something which iconically is
a vehicle for U to mean that he is in pain. In this way, in a
communication-system, a communication-device, such as “Oh” does for the state
of affairs something that the state of affairs cannot do for itself, govern the
addresee’s thoughts and behaviour (very much as the Oxfordshire cricket team
does for Oxfordshire what Oxfordshire cannot do for herself, viz. to engage in
a game of cricket. There’s rae-presentatum, for you! Short and Lewis have
‘signare,’ from ‘signum,’ and which they render as ‘to set a mark upon, to mark,
mark out, designate (syn.: noto, designo),’ Lit. A. In gen. (mostly poet. and
in post-Aug. prose): discrimen non facit neque signat linea alba, Lucil. ap.
Non. 405, 17: “signata sanguine pluma est,” Ov. M. 6, 670: “ne signare quidem
aut partiri limite campum Fas erat,” Verg. G. 1, 126: “humum limite mensor,”
Ov. M. 1, 136; id. Am. 3, 8, 42: “moenia aratro,” id. F. 4, 819: “pede certo
humum,” to print, press, Hor. A. P. 159; cf.: “vestigia summo pulvere,” to
mark, imprint, Verg. G. 3, 171: auratā cyclade humum, Prop. 4 (5), 7, 40. “haec
nostro signabitur area curru,” Ov. A. A. 1, 39: “locum, ubi ea (cistella)
excidit,” Plaut. Cist. 4, 2, 28: “caeli regionem in cortice signant,” mark,
cut, Verg. G. 2, 269: “nomina saxo,” Ov. M. 8, 539: “rem stilo,” Vell. 1, 16,
1: “rem carmine,” Verg. A. 3, 287; “for which: carmine saxum,” Ov. M. 2, 326:
“cubitum longis litteris,” Plaut. Rud. 5, 2, 7: “ceram figuris,” to imprint,
Ov. M. 15, 169: “cruor signaverat herbam,” had stained, id. ib. 10, 210; cf.
id. ib. 12, 125: “signatum sanguine pectus,” id. A. A. 2, 384: “dubiā lanugine
malas,” id. M. 13, 754: “signata in stirpe cicatrix,” Verg. G. 2, 379: “manibus
Procne pectus signata cruentis,” id. ib. 4, 15: “vocis infinitios sonos paucis
notis,” Cic. Rep. 3, 2, 3: “visum objectum imprimet et quasi signabit in animo
suam speciem,” id. Fat. 19, 43.— B. In partic. 1. To mark with a seal; to seal,
seal up, affix a seal to a thing (usually obsignare): “accepi a te signatum
libellum,” Cic. Att. 11, 1, 1: “volumina,” Hor. Ep. 1, 13, 2: locellum tibi
signatum remisi, Caes. ap. Charis. p. 60 P.: “epistula,” Nep. Pel. 3, 2:
“arcanas tabellas,” Ov. Am. 2, 15, 15: “signatis quicquam mandare tabellis,”
Tib. 4, 7, 7: “lagenam (anulus),” Mart. 9, 88, 7: “testamentum,” Plin. Ep. 2,
20, 8 sq.; cf. Mart. 5, 39, 2: “nec nisi signata venumdabatur (terra),” Plin.
35, 4, 14, § 33.—Absol., Mart. 10, 70, 7; Quint. 5, 7, 32; Suet. Ner. 17.— 2.
To mark with a stamp; hence, a. Of money, to stamp, to coin: “aes argentum
aurumve publice signanto,” Cic. Leg. 3, 3, 6; cf.: “qui primus ex auro denarium
signavit ... Servius rex primus signavit aes ... Signatum est nota pecudum,
unde et pecunia appellata ... Argentum signatum est anno, etc.,” Plin. 33, 3,
13, § 44: “argentum signatum,” Cic. Verr. 2, 5, 25, § 63; Quint. 5, 10, 62; 5,
14, 26: “pecunia signata Illyriorum signo,” Liv. 44, 27, 9: “denarius signatus
Victoriā,” Plin. 33, 3, 13, § 46: “sed cur navalis in aere Altera signata est,”
Ov. F. 1, 230: “milia talentūm argenti non signati formā, sed rudi pondere,”
Curt. 5, 2, 11.— Hence, b. Poet.: “signatum memori pectore nomen habe,”
imprinted, impressed, Ov. H. 13, 66: “(filia) quae patriā signatur imagine
vultus,” i. e. closely resembles her father, Mart. 6, 27, 3.— c. To stamp, i.
e. to license, invest with official authority (late Lat.): “quidam per ampla
spatia urbis ... equos velut publicos signatis, quod dicitur, calceis agitant,”
Amm. 14, 6, 16.— 3. Pregn., to distinguish, adorn, decorate (poet.): “pater
ipse suo superūm jam signat honore,” Verg. A. 6, 781 Heyne: caelum corona,
Claud. Nupt. Hon. et Mar. 273. to point out, signify, indicate, designate,
express (rare; more usually significo, designo; in Cic. only Or. 19, 64, where
dignata is given by Non. 281, 10; “v. Meyer ad loc.): translatio plerumque signandis
rebus ac sub oculos subiciendis reperta est,” Quint. 8, 6, 19: “quotiens suis
verbis signare nostra voluerunt (Graeci),” id. 2, 14, 1; cf.: “appellatione
signare,” id. 4, 1, 2: “utrius differentiam,” id. 6, 2, 20; cf. id. 9, 1, 4;
12, 10, 16: “nomen (Caieta) ossa signat,” Verg. A. 7, 4: “fama signata loco
est,” Ov. M. 14, 433: “miratrixque sui signavit nomine terras,” designated,
Luc. 4, 655; cf.: “(Earinus) Nomine qui signat tempora verna suo,” Mart. 9, 17,
4: “Turnus ut videt ... So signari oculis,” singled out, looked to, Verg. A.
12, 3: signare responsum, to give a definite or distinct answer, Sen. Ben. 7,
16, 1.—With rel.-clause: “memoria signat in quā regione quali adjutore
legatoque fratre meo usus sit,” Vell. 2, 115.— B. To distinguish, recognize:
“primi clipeos mentitaque tela Adgnoscunt, atque ora sono discordia signant,”
Verg. A. 2, 423; cf.: “sonis homines dignoscere,” Quint. 11, 3, 31: “animo
signa quodcumque in corpore mendum est,” Ov. R. Am. 417.— C. To seal, settle,
establish, confirm, prescribe (mostly poet.): “signanda sunt jura,” Prop. 3
(4), 20, 15. “signata jura,” Luc. 3, 302: jura Suevis, Claud. ap. Eutr. 1, 380;
cf.: “precati deos ut velint ea (vota) semper solvi semperque signari,” Plin.
Ep. 10, 35 (44). To close, end: “qui prima novo signat quinquennia lustro,”
Mart. 4, 45, 3.—Hence, A. signan-ter , adv. (acc. to II. A.), expressly,
clearly, distinctly (late Lat. for the class. significanter): “signanter et
breviter omnia indicare,” Aus. Grat. Act. 4: “signanter et proprie dixerat,” Hier.
adv. Jovin. 1, 13 fin. signātus, a, um, P. a. 1. (Acc. to I. B. 1. sealed;
hence) Shut up, guarded, preserved (mostly ante- and post-class.): signata
sacra, Varr. ap. Non. 397, 32: limina. Prop. 4 (5), 1, 145. Chrysidem negat
signatam reddere, i. e. unharmed, intact, pure, Lucil. ap. Non. 171, 6; cf.:
“assume de viduis fide pulchram, aetate signatam,” Tert. Exhort. 12.— 2. (Acc.
to II. A.) Plain, clear, manifest (post-class. for “significans” – a back
formation!): “quid expressius atque signatius in hanc causam?” Tert. Res. Carn.Adv.:
signātē , clearly, distinctly (post-class.): “qui (veteres) proprie atque
signate locuti sunt,” Gell. 2, 6, 6; Macr. S. 6, 7 Comp.: “signatius explicare
aliquid,” Amm. 23, 6, 1. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Sign and sign-making – the Roman
signi-ficare, and beyond.”
significatum: or better ‘signatum.’ Grice knew that in old Roman,
signatum was intransitive, as originally ‘significatum’ was – “He is
signifying,” i. e. making signs. In the Middle Ages it was applied to ‘utens’
of this or that expression, as was an actum, ‘agitur,’ Thus an expression was
not said to ‘signify’ in the same way. Grice plays with the
expression-communication distinction. When dealing with a lexeme that does NOT
belong in the Graeco-Roman tradition, that of “mean,” he is never sure. His
doubts were hightlighted in essays on “Grice without an audience.” While Grice
explicitly says that a ‘word’ is not a sign, he would use ‘signify’ at a later
stage, including the implicaturum as part of the significatum. There is indeed
an entry for signĭfĭcātĭo, f. significare. L and S render it, unhelpfully,
as “a pointing out, indicating, denoting, signifying; an
expression, indication, mark, sign, token, = indicium,
signum, ἐπισημασία, etc., freq. and class. As with Stevenson’s ‘communico,’
Grice goes sraight to ‘signĭfĭco,’ also dep. “signĭfĭcor,” f.
‘significare,’ from signum-facere, to make sign, signum-facio, I make sign,
which L and S render as to signify, which is perhaps not too helpful. Grice, if
not the Grecians, knew that. Strictly, L and S render significare as to show by
signs; to show, point out, express, publish, make known, indicate; to intimate,
notify, signify, etc. Note that the cognate signify almost comes last, but not
least, if not first. Enough to want to coin a word to do duty for them all.
Which is what Grice (and the Grecians) can, but the old Romans cannot, with
mean. If that above were not enough, L and S go on, also, to betoken,
prognosticate, foreshow, portend, mean (syn. praedico), as in to betoken a
change of weather (post-Aug.): “ventus Africus tempestatem significat,
etc.,”cf. Grice on those dark clouds mean a storm is coming. Short
and Lewis go on, to say that significare may be rendered as to call, name; to
mean, import, signify. Hence, ‘signĭfĭcans,’ in rhet. lang., of speech, full
of meaning, expressive, significant; graphic, distinct, clear: adv.:
signĭfĭcanter, clearly, distinctly, expressly, significantly, graphically:
“breviter ac significanter ordinem rei protulisse;” “rem indicare (with
proprie),” “dicere (with ornate),” “apertius, significantius dignitatem alicujus
defendere,” “narrare,”“disponere,” “appellare aliquid (with consignatius);”
“dicere (with probabilius).” -- signifier, a vocal sound or a written symbol.
The concept owes its modern formulation to the Swiss linguist Saussure. Rather
than using the older conception of sign and referent, he divided the sign
itself into two interrelated parts, a signifier and a signified. The signified
is the concept and the signifier is either a vocal sound or writing. The
relation between the two, according to Saussure, is entirely arbitrary, in that
signifiers tend to vary with different languages. We can utter or write
‘vache’, ‘cow’, or ‘vaca’, depending on our native language, and still come up
with the same signified i.e., concept. H. P. Grice, “Significatum and English
‘meaning.’”
signum – Grice: “I prefer token, so Anglo-Saxon! Plus I’m a
‘teacher’ – “to teach philosophy” --” whose explorations on the Nicomachean
Ethics, in one of their earlier incarnations, as a set of lecture notes, sees
me through terms of teaching Aristotle's moral theory.” “My own philosophical
life in this period involves two especially important aspects.” ROBBING PETER
TO PAY PAUL.. “The first is my prolonged collaboration with my tutee at St.
John’s, P. F. Strawson.”“Strawson’s and my efforts are partly directed towards
the giving of joint seminars.”“Strawson and I stage a number of joint seminars
on topics related to the notions of meaning, categories, and logical form.”
“But my association with P. F. Strawson is much more than an alliance for the
purpose of teaching.” -- theory of signs, the philosophical and scientific
theory of information-carrying entities, communication, and information
transmission. The term ‘semiotic’ was introduced by Locke for the science of
signs and signification. The term became more widely used as a result of the
influential work of Peirce and Charles Morris. With regard to linguistic signs,
three areas of semiotic were distinguished: pragmatics the study of the way people, animals, or
machines such as computers use signs; semantics
the study of the relations between signs and their meanings, abstracting
from their use; and syntax the study of
the relations among signs themselves, abstracting both from use and from
meaning. In Europe, the near-equivalent term ‘semiology’ was introduced by
Ferdinand de Saussure, the Swiss linguist. Broadly, a sign is any
information-carrying entity, including linguistic and animal signaling tokens,
maps, road signs, diagrams, pictures, models, etc. Examples include smoke as a
sign of fire, and a red light at a highway intersection as a sign to stop.
Linguistically, vocal aspects of speech such as prosodic features intonation,
stress and paralinguistic features loudness and tone, gestures, facial expressions,
etc., as well as words and sentences, are signs in the most general sense.
Peirce defined a sign as “something that stands for something in some respect
or capacity.” Among signs, he distinguished symbols, icons, and indices. A
symbol, or conventional sign, is a sign, typical of natural language forms,
that lacks any significant relevant physical correspondence with or resemblance
to the entities to which the form refers manifested by the fact that quite
different forms may refer to the same class of objects, and for which there is
no correlation between the occurrence of the sign and its referent. An index,
or natural sign, is a sign whose occurrence is causally or statistically
correlated with occurrences of its referent, and whose production is not
intentional. Thus, yawning is a natural sign of sleepiness; a bird call may be
a natural sign of alarm. Linguistically, loudness with a rising pitch is a sign
of anger. An icon is a sign whose form corresponds to or resembles its referent
or a characteristic of its referent. For instance, a tailor’s swatch is an icon
by being a sign that resembles a fabric in color, pattern, and texture. A
linguistic example is onomatopoeia as
with ‘buzz’. In general, there are conventional and cultural aspects to a sign
being an icon.
simmel: Grice, “As Simmel would say, information is like
money – the giver hardly knows to what use the recipient is going to to put
it.” philosopher and one of the founders of sociology as a distinct discipline.
Born and educated in Berlin, he was a popular lecturer at its university. But
the unorthodoxy of his interests and unprofessional writing style probably kept
him from being offered a regular professorship until late in his career, and then
only at ‘provincial’ Strasbourg. He died four years later.Simmel’s writings range from conventional
philosophical topics with essays on
ethics, philosophy of history, education, religion, and the philosophers Kant,
Schopenhauer, and Nietzsche to essays on
Rembrandt, Goethe, and the philosophy of money. He wrote numerous essays on
various artists and poets, on different cities, and on such themes as love,
adventure, shame, and on being a stranger, as well as on many specifically
sociological topics. Simmel is regarded as a Kulturphilosoph who meditates on
his themes in an insightful and digressive rather than scholarly and systematic
style. Though late in life he sketches a unifying Lebensphilosophie that
considers all works and structures of culture as products of different forms of
human experience, Simmel has remained of interest primarily for a multiplicity
of insights into specific topics. Anyone who uses a
sentence of the form X is meeting a woman this evening would normally implicate
that the person to be met was someone other than X' s wife, mother, sister, or
perhaps even close platonic friend. Similarly, if I were to say X went into a
house yesterday and found a tortoise inside the front door, my hearer would
normally be surprised if some time later I revealed that the house was X's own.
I could produce similar linguistic phenomena involving the expressions a
garden, a car, a college, and so on. Sometimes, however, there would normally
be no such implicature ('I have been sitting in a car all morning'), and
sometimes a reverse implicature ('I broke a finger yesterday'). I am inclined
to think that one would not lend a sympathetic ear to a philosopher who
suggested that there are three senses of the form of expression an X: one in
which it means roughly 'something that satisfies the conditions defining the
word X,' another in which it means approximately 'an X (in the first sense)
that is only remotely related in a certain way to some person indicated by the
context,' and yet another in which it means 'an X (in the first sense) that is closely
related in a certain way to some person indicated by the context.' Would we not
much prefer an account on the following lines (which, of course, may be
incorrect in detail): I I ; .. ' Logic and Conversation 57 When someone, by
using the form of expression an X, implicates that the X does not belong to or
is not otherwise closely connected with some identifiable person, the
implicature is present l >ecause the speaker has failed to be specific in a
way in which he might have been expected to be specific, with the consequence
that it is likely to be assumed that he is not in a position to be specific.
This is a familiar implicature situation and is classifiable as a failure, for
one reason or another, to fulfill the first maxim of Quantity. The only difficult
question is why it should, in certain cases, be presumed, independently of
information about particular contexts of utterance, that specification of the
closeness or remoteness of the connection between a particular person or object
and a further person who is mentioned or indicated by the utterance should be
likely to be of interest. The answer must lie in the following region:
Transactions between a person and other persons or things closely connected
witl1 him are liable to be very different as regards their concomitants and
results from the same sort of transactions involving only remotely connected
persons or things; the concomitants and results, for instance, of my finding a
hole in MY roof are likely to be very different from the concomitants and
results of my finding a hole in someone else's roof. Information, like money,
is often given without the giver's knowing to just what use the recipient will
want to put it. If someone to whom a transaction is mentioned gives it further
consideration, he is likely to find himself wanting the answers to further
questions that the speaker may not be able to identify in advance; if the
appropriate specification will be likely to enable the hearer to answer a
considerable variety of such questions for himself, then there is a presumption
that the speaker should include it in his remark; if not, then there is no such
presumption.
simplicius: Grecian Neoplatonist philosopher. His surviving works
are extensive commentaries on Aristotle’s On the Heavens, Physics, and
Categories, and on the Encheiridion of Epictetus. The authenticity of the commentary
on Aristotle’s “De anima” attributed to
Simplicius has been disputed. He studied with Ammonius in Alexandria, and with
Damascius, the last known head of the Platonist school in Athens. Justinian
closed the school in 529. Two or three years later a group of philosophers,
including Damascius and Simplicius, visited the court of the Sassanian king
Khosrow I Chosroes but soon returned to the Byzantine Empire under a guarantee
of their right to maintain their own beliefs. It is generally agreed that most,
if not all, of Simplicius’s extant works date from the period after his stay
with Khosrow. But there is no consensus about where Simplicius spent his last
years both Athens and Harran have been proposed recently, or whether he resumed
teaching philosophy; his commentaries, unlike most of the others that survive
from that period, are scholarly treatises rather than classroom expositions.
Simplicius’s Aristotle commentaries are the most valuable extant works in the
genre. He is our source for many of the fragments of the preSocratic
philosophers, and he frequently invokes material from now-lost commentaries and
philosophical works. He is a deeply committed Neoplatonist, convinced that
there is no serious conflict between the philosophies of Plato and Aristotle.
The view of earlier scholars that his Encheiridion commentary embodies a more
moderate Platonism associated with Alexandria is now generally rejected.
Simplicius’s virulent defense of the eternity of the world in response to the
attack of the Christian John Philoponus illustrates the intellectual vitality
of paganism at a time when the Mediterranean world had been officially
Christian for about three centuries. H.
P. Grice, “Why we should study Simplicius;” Luigi Speranza, “The history of
philosophical psychology, from the Grecians to the Griceians,” J. O. Urmson,
“Grice and Simplicius on the soul,” for The Grice Club.
simulatum: Grice: “If x simulates y, x is not y – or is this an
implicature – if x is x, is x LIKE x?” -- simulation theory: Grice: “How does
one simulate an implicature? I challenge AI, so-called, to do it!” -- the view that one represents the mental
activities and processes of others by mentally simulating them, i.e.,
generating similar activities and processes in oneself. By simulating them, one
can anticipate their product or outcome; or, where this is already known, test
hypotheses about their starting point. For example, one anticipates the product
of another’s theoretical or practical inferences from given premises by making
inferences from the same premises oneself; or, knowing what the product is, one
retroduces the premises. In the case of practical reasoning, to reason from the
same premises would typically require indexical adjustments, such as shifts in
spatial, temporal, and personal “point of view,” to place oneself in the
other’s physical and epistemic situation insofar as it differs from one’s own.
One may also compensate for the other’s reasoning capacity and level of
expertise, if possible, or modify one’s character and outlook as an actor
might, to fit the other’s background. Such adjustments, even when insufficient
for making decisions in the role of the other, allow one to discriminate
between action options likely to be attractive or unattractive to the agent.
One would be prepared for the former actions and surprised by the latter. The
simulation theory is usually considered an alternative to an assumption
sometimes called the “theory theory” that underlies much recent philosophy of
mind: that our commonsense understanding of people rests on a speculative
theory, a “folk psychology” that posits mental states, events, and processes as
unobservables that explain behavior. Some hold that the simulation theory
undercuts the debate between philosophers who consider folk psychology a
respectable theory and those the eliminative materialists who reject it. Unlike
earlier writing on empathic understanding and historical reenactment, discussions
of the simulation theory often appeal to empirical findings, particularly
experimental results in developmental psychology. They also theorize about the
mechanism that would accomplish simulation: presumably one that calls up
computational resources ordinarily used for engagement with the world, but runs
them off-line, so that their output is not “endorsed” or acted upon and their
inputs are not limited to those that would regulate one’s own behavior.
Although simulation theorists agree that the ascription of mental states to
others relies chiefly on simulation, they differ on the nature of
selfascription. Some especially Robert Gordon and simple supposition simulation
theory 845 845 Jane Heal, who
independently proposed the theory give a non-introspectionist account, while
others especially Goldman lean toward a more traditional introspectionist
account. The simulation theory has affected developmental psychology as well as
branches of philosophy outside the philosophy of mind, especially aesthetics
and philosophy of the social sciences. Some philosophers believe it sheds light
on traditional topics such as the problem of other minds, referential opacity,
broad and narrow content, and the peculiarities of self-knowledge.
singulare: Grice: “I use ‘singular’ in triadic opposition to
plural and singular, and reject Urquart’s bi-dual -- singular term -- singŭlāris , e, adj. singuli. I. Lit. A. In gen., one by
one, one at a time, alone, single, solitary; alone of its kind, singular
(class.; “syn.: unus, unicus): non singulare nec solivagum genus (sc.
homines),” i. e. solitary, Cic. Rep. 1, 25, 39: “hostes ubi ex litore aliquos
singulares ex navi egredientes conspexerant,” Caes. B. G. 4, 26: “homo,” id.
ib. 7, 8, 3; so, “homo (with privatus, and opp. isti conquisiti coloni),” Cic.
Agr. 2, 35, 97: “singularis mundus atque unigena,” id. Univ. 4 med.:
“praeconium Dei singularis facere,” Lact. 4, 4, 8; cf. Cic. Ac. 1, 7, 26:
“natus,” Plin. 28, 10, 42, § 153: “herba (opp. fruticosa),” id. 27, 9, 55, §
78: singularis ferus, a wild boar (hence, Fr. sanglier), Vulg. Psa. 79, 14:
“hominem dominandi cupidum aut imperii singularis,” sole command, exclusive
dominion, Cic. Rep. 1, 33, 50; so, “singulare imperium et potestas regia,” id.
ib. 2, 9, 15: “sunt quaedam in te singularia ... quaedam tibi cum multis
communia,” Cic. Verr. 2, 3, 88, § 206: “singulare beneficium (opp. commune
officium civium),” id. Fam. 1, 9, 4: “odium (opp. communis invidia),” id. Sull.
1, 1: “quam invisa sit singularis potentia et miseranda vita,” Nep. Dion, 9, 5:
“pugna,” Macr. S. 5, 2: “si quando quid secreto agere proposuisset, erat illi
locus in edito singularis,” particular, separate, Suet. Aug. 72.— B. In partic.
1. In gram., of or belonging to unity, singular: “singularis casus,” Varr. L. L.
7, § 33 Müll.; “10, § 54 ib.: numerus,” Quint. 1, 5, 42; 1, 6, 25; 8, 3, 20;
Gell. 19, 8, 13: “nominativus,” Quint. 1, 6, 14: “genitivus,” id. 1, 6, 26 et
saep. —Also absol., the singular number: “alii dicunt in singulari hac ovi et
avi, alii hac ove et ave,” Varr. L. L. 8, § 66 Müll.; Quint. 8, 6, 28; 4, 5, 25
al.— 2. In milit lang., subst.: singŭlāris , is, m. a. In gen., an orderly man
(ordonance), assigned to officers of all kinds and ranks for executing their
orders (called apparitor, Lampr. Alex. Sev. 52): “SINGVLARIS COS (consulis),”
Inscr. Orell. 2003; cf. ib. 3529 sq.; 3591; 6771 al.— b. Esp., under the
emperors, equites singulares Augusti, or only equites singulares, a select
horse body-guard (selected from barbarous nations, as Bessi, Thraces, Bæti,
etc.), Tac. H. 4, 70; Hyg. m. c. §§ 23 and 30; Inscr. Grut. 1041, 12 al.; cf.
on the Singulares, Henzen, Sugli Equiti Singolari, Roma, 1850; Becker, Antiq.
tom. 3, pass. 2, p. 387 sq.— 3. In the time of the later emperors, singulares,
a kind of imperial clerks, sent into the provinces, Cod. Just. 1, 27, 1, § 8;
cf. Lyd. Meg. 3, 7.— II. Trop., singular, unique, matchless, unparalleled,
extraordinary, remarkable (syn.: unicus, eximius, praestans; “very freq. both
in a good and in a bad sense): Aristoteles meo judicio in philosophiā prope
singularis,” Cic. Ac. 2, 43, 132: “Cato, summus et singularis vir,” id. Brut.
85, 293: “vir ingenii naturā praestans, singularis perfectusque undique,”
Quint. 12, 1, 25; so, “homines ingenio atque animo,” Cic. Div. 2, 47, 97:
“adulescens,” Plin. Ep. 7, 24, 2.—Of things: “Antonii incredibilis quaedam et
prope singularis et divina vis ingenii videtur,” Cic. de Or. 1, 38, 172:
“singularis eximiaque virtus,” id. Imp. Pomp. 1, 3; so, “singularis et
incredibilis virtus,” id. Att. 14, 15, 3; cf. id. Fam. 1, 9, 4: “integritas
atque innocentia singularis,” id. Div. in Caecil. 9, 27: “Treviri, quorum inter
Gallos virtutis opinio est singularis,” Caes. B. G. 2, 24: “Pompeius gratias
tibi agit singulares,” Cic. Fam. 13, 41, 1; cf.: “mihi gratias egistis
singularibus verbis,” id. Cat. 4, 3: “fides,” Nep. Att. 4: “singulare omnium
saeculorum exemplum,” Just. 2, 4, 6.—In a bad sense: “nequitia ac turpitudo
singularis,” Cic. Verr. 2, 3, 44, § 106; so, “nequitia,” id. ib. 2, 2, 54, §
134; id. Fin. 5, 20, 56: “impudentia,” Cic. Verr. 2, 2, 7, § 18: audacia (with
scelus incredibile), id. Fragm. ap. Quint. 4, 2, 105: “singularis et nefaria
crudelitas,” Caes. B. G. 7, 77.— Hence, adv.: singŭlārĭter (singlā-rĭter ,
Lucr. 6, 1067). 1. One by one, singly, separately. a. In gen. (ante- and
post-class.): “quae memorare queam inter se singlariter apta, Lucr. l. l. Munro
(Lachm. singillariter): a juventā singulariter sedens,” apart, separately,
Paul. Nol. Carm. 21, 727.— b. In partic. (acc. to I. B. 1.), in the singular
number: “quod pluralia singulariter et singularia pluraliter efferuntur,”
Quint. 1, 5, 16; 1, 7, 18; 9, 3, 20: “dici,” Gell. 19, 8, 12; Dig. 27, 6, 1
al.— 2. (Acc. to II.) Particularly, exceedingly: “aliquem diligere,” Cic. Verr.
2, 2, 47, § 117: “et miror et diligo,” Plin. Ep. 1, 22, 1: “amo,” id. ib. 4,
15, 1. Grice: “I would define a ‘singular implicaturum’ as any vehicle
of communicatum such as an expression, like ‘Zeus’, ‘Pegasus,’ ‘the President’,
‘Strawson’s dog,’ ‘Fido,’ or ‘my favorite chair’, that can be the grammatical
subject of what is semantically a subject-predicate sentence.” Grice: “By
contrast, what one might call a ‘general,’ or ‘non-singular term, such as ‘horse,’
‘dog,’‘table’ or ‘swam’ is one that can serve in predicative position.” It is
also often said that a singular term (‘nomen singularis,’ ‘expressio
singularis’) is a word or phrase that could refer or ostensibly refer, on a
given occasion of use, only to a single (or ‘singular’) object – unless you
show me a ‘general’ object --, whereas a general term is predicable of *more
than one* singular object, if not a ‘general’ object, which does not exist. A
singular term is thus the expression that replace, or are replaced by, an individual
variable (x, y, z, …) in applications of such quantifier rules as universal
instantiation and existential generalization or flank ‘%’ in identity
statements.” H. P. Grice, “System G: the rudiments.”
situation
ethics: what Grice calls the
‘particularised’ – prior obviously to the ‘generalised.’ -- a kind of anti-theoretical, case-by-case
applied ethics in vogue largely in some European and religious circles for twenty years or so
following World War II. It is characterized by the insistence that each moral
choice must be determined by one’s particular context or situation i.e., by a consideration of the outcomes that
various possible courses of action might have, given one’s situation. To that
degree, situation ethics has affinities to both act utilitarianism and
traditional casuistry. But in contrast to utilitarianism, situation ethics
rejects the idea that there are universal or even fixed moral principles beyond
various indeterminate commitments or ideals e.g., to Christian love or
humanism. In contrast to traditional casuistry, it rejects the effort to
construct general guidelines from a case or to classify the salient features of
a case so that it can be used as a precedent. The anti-theoretical stance of
situation ethics is so thoroughgoing that writers identified with the position
have not carefully described its connections to consequentialism,
existentialism, intuitionism, personalism, pragmatism, relativism, or any other
developed philosophical view to which it appears to have some affinity.
st. john’s: st. john’s keeps a record of all of H. P. Grice’s
tutees. It is fascinating that Strawson’s closest collaboration, as Plato with
Socrates, and Aristotle with Plato, was with his tutee Strawson – whom Grice calls
a ‘pupil,’ finding ‘tutee’ too French to his taste. G. J. Warnock recalls that,
of all the venues that the play group held, their favourite one was the room
overlooking the garden at st. john’s. “It’s one of the best gardens in England,
you know. Very peripathetic.” In alphabetical order, some of his English
‘gentlemanly’ tutees include: London-born J. L. Ackrill, London-born David
Bostock, London-born A. G. N. Flew, Leeds-born T. C. Potts, London-born P. F.
Strawson. They were happy to have Grice as a tutorial fellow, since he, unlike
Mabbot, was English, and did not instill on the tutees a vernacular furrin to
the area.
skolem: semanticist, he made fundamental contributions to
recursion theory (Grice: “which I need for my account of communication”), set
theory in particular, the proposal and formulation of the axiom of replacement,
and model theory. The first work devoted exclusively
to recursive definability was Skolem’s (1923) paper The foundations of
elementary arithmetic established by the recursive mode of thought, without the
use of apparent variables ranging over infinite domains. This work is
significant with respect to the subsequent development of computability theory
for at least three reasons. First, it contains a informal description of what
we now call the primitive recursive functions. Second, it can be regarded as
the first place where recursive definability is linked to effective
computability (see also Skolem 1946). And third, it demonstrates that a wide
range of functions and relations are primitive recursive in a manner which
anticipates Gödel’s (1931) use of primitive recursion for the arithmetization
of syntax. One of Skolem’s stated goals was to present a logical
foundation for number theory which avoids the use of unrestricted quantifiers.
He was inspired in this regard by the observation that it is possible to
develop much of elementary arithmetic without the use of the expressions
“always” (i.e. for all) and “sometimes” (i.e. there exists) which figure in the
formalization of number theory given by Russell and Whitehead in Principia
Mathematica (1910–1913). This was to be accomplished by formulating
arithmetical theorems as what he referred to as functional assertions. These
took the form of identities between terms defined by primitive recursive
operations which Skolem referred to as descriptive functions. For instance, the
commutativity of addition is expressed in this form by an equation with free
variables x+y=y+x In cases where such statements are provable in
the system Skolem describes, the intended interpretation is that the claim
holds universally for all natural numbers—e.g., ∀x∀y(x+y=y+x).
But in Skolem’s system there is no means of negating such a statement to express
a bare existential assertion without producing a witness. Statements like
(5) would later be referred to by Hilbert & Bernays (1934) (who provided
the first textbook treatment of recursion) as verifiable in the sense that
their individual instances can be verified computationally by replacing
variables with concrete numerals. This is accomplished by what Skolem referred
to as the “recursive mode of thought”. The sense of this phrase is clarified by
the following properties of the system he describes: the natural numbers
are taken as basic objects together with the successor function x+1; it is
assumed that descriptive functions proven to be equal may be substituted for
one another in other expressions; all definitions of functions and relations on
natural numbers are given by recursion; functional assertions such as (5) must
be proven by induction. Taking these principles as a foundation, Skolem showed
how to obtain recursive definitions of the predecessor and subtraction
functions, the less than, divisibility, and primality relations, greatest
common divisors, least common multiples, and bounded sums and products which
are similar to those given in Section 2.1.2 below. Overall Skolem
considered instances of what we would now refer to as primitive recursion,
course of values recursion, double recursion, and recursion on functions of
type N→N. He did not, however, introduce general schemas so as to
systematically distinguish these modes of definition. Nonetheless, properties
i–iv of Skolem’s treatment provide a means of assimilating calculations like
(2) to derivations in quantifier-free first-order logic. It is thus not
difficult to discern in (Skolem 1923) the kernel of the system we now know as
Primitive Recursive Arithmetic (as later formally introduced by Hilbert &
Bernays 1934, ch. 7). Skolem’s most important
results for philosophical semantics are the Downward Löwenheim-Skolem theorem, whose
first proof involved putting formulas into Skolem normal form; and a
demonstration of the existence of models of first-order arithmetic not
isomorphic to the standard model. Both results exhibit the extreme
non-categoricity that can occur with formulations of mathematical theories in
first-order logic, and causes Skolem to be sceptical about the use of a formal
systems such as System G (after Grice), particularly for set theory, as a
foundation for semantics. The existence of non-standard models is actually a
consequence of the completeness and first incompleteness theorems by Gödel, for
these together show that there must be sentences of arithmetic if consistent that
are true in the standard model, but false in some other, nonisomorphic model.
However, Skolem’s result describes a general technique for constructing such
models. Skolem’s theorem is now more easily proved using the compactness
theorem, an easy consequence of the completeness theorem. The Löwenheim-Skolem
theorem produces a similar problem of characterization, Skolem’s paradox.
Roughly, Skolem’s paradox says that if first-order set theory has a model, it
must also have a countable model whose continuum is a countable set, and thus
apparently non-standard. This does not contradict Cantor’s theorem, which
merely demands that the countable model contain as an element no function that
maps its natural numbers one-toone onto its continuum, although there must be
such a function outside the model. Although usually seen as limiting
first-order logic, this result is extremely fruitful technically, providing one
basis of the proof of the independence of the continuum hypothesis from the
usual axioms of set theory given by Gödel and Cohen. This connection between
independence results and the existence of countable models was partially
foreseen by Skolem. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Skolem’s recursive implicatura.” Skolem, Thoralf, 1923, “Begründung Der Elementaren
Arithmetik Durch Die Rekurrierende Denkweise Ohne Anwendung Scheinbarer
Veranderlichen Mit Unendlichem Ausdehnungsbereich”, Videnskapsselskapets
Skrifter, I. Matematisk-Naturvidenskabelig Klasse, 6: 1–38. –––, 1946, “The
development of recursive arithmetic” In Dixíeme Congrés des Mathimaticiens
Scandinaves, Copenhagen, 1–16. Reprinted in Skolem 1970, pp. 499–415. –––,
1970, Selected Works in Logic Olso: Universitetsforlaget. Edited by J.E.
Fenstad.
Grice, “philosophical semanticist.”
smart and
place: Cambridge-born Australian philosopher
whose name is associated with three very non-Oxonian doctrines in particular:
the mind-body identity theory, scientific realism, and utilitarianism. A
student of Ryle’s at Oxford, from the other place, he rejected logical
behaviorism in favor of what came to be known as Australian or ‘colonial’ or
“Dominion” materialism. This is the view that mental processes and, as, -- “the other colonial,” – Grice -- Armstrong
brought Smart to see, mental states
cannot be explained simply in terms of behavioristic dispositions. In
order to make good sense of how the ordinary person talks of them we have to
see them as brain processes and
states under other names. Smart
developed this identity theory of mind and brain, under the stimulus of his
colleague, Yorkshire-born, Rugby and Corpus-Christi (via Open Scholarship),
tutee of Ryle, U. T. Place, in “Sensations and Brain Processes” Philosophical
Review. It became a mainstay of twentieth-century philosophy. Smart endorsed
the materialist analysis of mind on the grounds that it gave a simple picture
that was consistent with the findings of science. He took a realist view of the
claims of science, rejecting phenomenalism, instrumentalism, and the like, and
he argued that commonsense beliefs should be maintained only so far as they are
plausible in the light of total science. Philosophy and Scientific Realism 3
gave forceful expression to this physicalist picture of the world, as did some
later works. He attracted attention in particular for his argument that if we
take science seriously then we have to endorse the four-dimensional picture of
the universe and recognize as an illusion the experience of the passing of
time. He published a number of defenses of utilitarianism, the best known being
his contribution to J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism, For
and Against 3. He gave new life to act utilitarianism at a time when
utilitarians were few and most were attached to rule utilitarianism or other
restricted forms of the doctrine. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Ryle and the devil of
scientism,” H. P. Grice, “What Smart learned from Ryle.”
smith: Scots philosopher, a founder of modern political
economy and a major contributor to ethics and the psychology of morals. His
first published work is “The Theory of Moral Sentiments.” This book immediately
made him famous, and earned the praise of thinkers of the stature of Hume,
Burke, and Kant. It sought to answer two questions: Wherein does virtue
consist, and by means of what psychological principles do we determine this or
that to be virtuous or the contrary? His answer to the first combined ancient
Stoic and Aristotelian views of virtue with modern views derived from Hutcheson
and others. His answer to the second built on Hume’s theory of sympathy our ability to put ourselves imaginatively in
the situation of another as well as on
the notion of the “impartial spectator.” Smith throughout is skeptical about
metaphysical and theological views of virtue and of the psychology of morals.
The self-understanding of reasonable moral actors ought to serve as the moral
philosopher’s guide. Smith’s discussion ranges from the motivation of wealth to
the psychological causes of religious and political fanaticism. Smith’s second
published work, the immensely influential An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes
of the Wealth of Nations 1776, attempts to explain why free economic,
political, and religious markets are not only more efficient, when properly
regulated, but also more in keeping with nature, more likely to win the
approval of an impartial spectator, than monopolistic alternatives. Taken
together, Smith’s two books attempt to show how virtue and liberty can
complement each other. He shows full awareness of the potentially dehumanizing
force of what was later called “capitalism,” and sought remedies in schemes for
liberal education and properly organized religion. Smith did not live to
complete his system, which was to include an analysis of “natural
jurisprudence.” We possess student notes of his lectures on jurisprudence and
on rhetoric, as well as several impressive essays on the evolution of the
history of science and on the fine arts.
saggio: philosophical essay: ‘saggio filosofico.’ – a
subgenre of the prose genre of ‘essay.’ Grice seems to prefer ‘study’ (“Studies
in the way of words”) but surely each piece is an essay. Austin preferred
“papers” (vide his “Philosophical Papers.”). “The implicature,” Grice says,
“seems to be that an essay is too sketchy!” --. “Storia del saggio filosofico
in Italia” --. Grice: “It is strictly not true that a philosopher needs to
engage in the subgenre of the ‘philosophical essay;’ after all, at Oxford, we
always thought Jowett’s dialogues were the epitome of philosophy – and they
are!”
società italiana per lo studio del pensiero medievale: Grice:
“It always amazed me that the mediaevals at Bologna and Oxford ‘knew’ that they
were in the middle of it!” -- the title of this Society is telling. For the
Italians, they do not want to distinguish Politics, Economics, Theology, and
Philosophy – It is all covered under ‘thought,’ ‘pensiero.’ This is in
accordance with de Sanctis’s view of philosophy as one of the belles lettres
(“if perhaps less ‘belle’ than the rest). The subgenre of the essay –
‘philosophical essay.’ Grice: “While it is easy to take ‘mediaeval’ in a boring
chronological fashion, the mediaevals themselves saw themselves to be in the
‘middle’ of it, of the ‘aevus,’ that is.”
sozzini: -- Socinianism, NELLA PRIMA METÀ DEL SEDICESIMO SECOLO NACQUERO IN QUESTA CASA LELIO E
FAUSTO SOZZINI LETTERATI INSIGNI FILOSOFI SOMMI DELLA LIBERTÀ DI PENSIERO
STRENUI PROPUGNATORI ______ CONTRO IL SOPRANNATURALE VINDICI DELLA UMANA
RAGIONE FONDARONO LA CELEBRE SCUOLA SOCINIANA PRECORRENDO DI TRE SECOLI LE
DOTTRINE DEL MODERNO RAZIONALISMO ______
I LIBERALI SENESI AMMIRATORI REVERENTI QUESTA MEMORIA POSERO 1879
a movement originating in the sixteenth century from the work of reformer Laelius Socinus “Sozzini” and his
nephew Faustus Socinus. Born in Siena of
a patrician family, Sozzini is widely read. Influenced by the evangelical
movement, Sozzini makes contact with noted Protestant reformers, including
Calvin and Melanchthon, some of whom questioned his orthodoxy. In response,
Sozzini writes a confession of faith, one of a small number of his writings to
have survived. After his death, Sozzini’s oeuvre was carried on by his nephew,
Faustus, whose writings including “On the Authority of Scripture,” “On the
Savior Jesus Christ,” and “On
Predestination,” expressed heterodox views. Sozzini believed that Christ’s
nature is entirely human, that the souls does not possess immortality by nature
though there is selective resurrection for believers, that invocation of Christ
in prayer is permissible but not required, and he argues, like Grice, Pears,
and Thomson, against predestination. After publication of his writings, Sozzini is invited to Transylvania
and Poland to engage in a dispute within the Reformed churches there. He
decides to make his permanent residence in Poland, which, through his tireless
efforts, became the center of the Socinian movement. The most important
document of this movement was the Racovian Catechism, published shortly after
Faustus’s death. The Minor church of Poland, centered at Racov, became the focal
point of the movement. Its academy attracted hundreds of students and its
publishing house produced books in many languages defending Socinian ideas.
Socinianism, as represented by the Racovian Catechism and other writings
collected by Faustus’s disciples, involves the views of Laelius and especially
Faustus Socinus, aligned with the anti-Trinitarian views of the Polish Minor
church.. It accepts Christ’s message as the definitive revelation of God, but
regards Christ as human, not divine; rejects the natural immortality of the
soul, but argues for the selective resurrection of the faithful; rejects the
doctrine of the Trinity; emphasizes human free will against predestinationism;
defends pacifism and the separation of church and state; and argues that reason not creeds, dogmatic tradition, or church
authority must be the final interpreter
of Scripture. Its view of God is temporalistic: God’s eternity is existence at
all times, not timelessness, and God knows future free actions only when they
occur. In these respects, the Socinian view of God anticipates aspects of
modern process theology. Socinianism was suppressed in Poland in 1658, but it
had already spread to other European countries, including Holland where it
appealed to followers of Arminius and England, where it influenced the
Cambridge Platonists, Locke, and other philosophers, as well as scientists like
Newton. In England, it also influenced and was closely associated with the
development of Unitarianism. H. P.
Grice, “Sozzini, rationalism, and moi.”
solus ipse, solipsism: Grice: “If my theory of conversation has
any value, is the refutation of solipsism!” -- the doctrine that there exists a
firstperson perspective possessing privileged and irreducible characteristics,
in virtue of which we stand in various kinds of isolation from any other
persons or external things that may exist. This doctrine is associated with but
distinct from egocentricism. On one variant of solipsism Thomas Nagel’s we are
isolated from other sentient beings because we can never adequately understand
their experience empathic solipsism. Another variant depends on the thesis that
the meanings or referents of all words are mental entities uniquely accessible
only to the language user semantic solipsism. A restricted variant, due to
Vitters, asserts that first-person ascriptions of psychological states have a
meaning fundamentally different from that of second- or thirdperson ascriptions
psychological solipsism. In extreme forms semantic solipsism can lead to the
view that the only things that can be meaningfully said to exist are ourselves
or our mental states ontological solipsism. Skepticism about the existence of
the world external to our minds is sometimes considered a form of
epistemological solipsism, since it asserts that we stand in epistemological
isolation from that world, partly as a result of the epistemic priority
possessed by firstperson access to mental states. In addition to these
substantive versions of solipsism, several variants go under the rubric methodological
solipsism. The idea is that when we seek to explain why sentient beings behave
in certain ways by looking to what they believe, desire, hope, and fear, we
should identify these psychological states only with events that occur inside
the mind or brain, not with external events, since the former alone are the
proximate and sufficient causal explanations of bodily behavior.
solovyov: philosopher, author of major treatises and dialogues
in speculative philosophy, The mystical
image of the “Divine Sophia,” which Solovyov articulated in theoretical
concepts as well as poetic symbols, powerfully influenced the Russian symbolist
poets of the early twentieth century. His stress on the human role in the
“divine-human process” that creates both cosmic and historical being led to
charges of heresy from Russian Orthodox traditionalists. Solovyov’s
rationalistic “justification of the good” in history, society, and individual
life was inspired by Plato, Spinoza, and especially Hegel. However, at the end
of his life Solovyov offered in Three Conversations on War, Progress, and the
End of History, 0 a contrasting apocalyptic vision of historical and cosmic
disaster, including the appearance, in the twenty-first century, of the Antichrist.
In ethics, social philosophy, philosophy of history, and theory of culture,
Solovyov was both a vigorous ecumenist and a “good European” who affirmed the
intrinsic value of both the “individual human person” Russian lichnost’ and the
“individual nation or people” narodnost’, but he decisively repudiated the
perversions of these values in egoism and nationalism, respectively. He
contrasted the fruits of English narodnost’
the works of Shakespeare and Byron, Berkeley and Newton with the fruits of English nationalism the repressive and destructive expansion of
the British Empire. In opposing ethnic, national, and religious exclusiveness
and self-centeredness, Solovyov also, and quite consistently, opposed the
growing xenophobia and antiSemitism of his own time. Since 8 long-suppressed
works by and about Solovyov have been widely republished in Russia, and fresh
interpretations of his philosophy and theology have begun to appear.
sophisma: Grice’s favourite for a time was “Have you stopped
beating your wife.” In “Presupposition and conversational implicature,” he does
admit that he has grown tired of it, what he calls his having had his eyes
glued to “the inquiry whether you have left off beating your wife” --. an
utterance illustrating a semantic or logical issue associated with the analysis
of a syncategorematic term, or a term lacking independent signification.
Typically a sophisma was used from the thirteenth century into the sixteenth
century to analyze relations holding between logic or semantics and broader
philosophical issues. For example, the syncategorematic term ‘besides’ praeter
in ‘Socrates twice sees every man besides Plato’ is ambiguous, because it could
mean ‘On two occasions Socrates sees every-man-but-Plato’ and also ‘Except for overlooking
Plato once, on two occasions Socrates sees every man’. Roger Bacon used this
sophisma to discuss the ambiguity of distribution, in this case, of the scope
of the reference of ‘twice’ and ‘besides’. Sherwood used the sophisma to
illustrate the applicability of his rule of the distribution of ambiguous
syncategoremata, while Pseudo-Peter of Spain uses it to establish the truth of
the rule, ‘If a proposition is in part false, it can be made true by means of
an exception, but not if it is completely false’. In each case, the philosopher
uses the ambiguous signification of the syncategorematic term to analyze
broader logical problems. The sophisma ‘Every man is of necessity an animal’
has ambiguity through the syncategorematic ‘every’ that leads to broader
philosophical problems. In the 1270s, Boethius of Dacia analyzed this sophisma
in terms of its applicability when no man exists. Is the knowledge derived from
understanding the proposition destroyed when the object known is destroyed?
Does ‘man’ signify anything when there are no men? If we can correctly
predicate a genus of a species, is the nature of the genus in that species
something other than, or distinct from, what finally differentiates the
species? In this case, the sophisma proves a useful approach to addressing
metaphysical and epistemological problems central to Scholastic discourse. sophisma: Grice: “Literally, a
wisecrack.” “’Sophisma’ is a very Griceian and Grecian pun on ‘sophos,’ the
wise men of Gotham -- any of a number of ancient Grecians, roughly
contemporaneous with Socrates, who professed to teach, for a fee, rhetoric,
philosophy, and how to succeed in life. They typically were itinerants,
visiting much of the Grecian world, and gave public exhibitions at Olympia and
Delphi. They were part of the general expansion of Grecian learning and of the
changing culture in which the previous informal educational methods were
inadequate. For example, the growing litigiousness of Athenian society demanded
Solovyov, Vladimir Sophists 862 862 instruction
in the art of speaking well, which the Sophists helped fulfill. The Sophists
have been portrayed as intellectual charlatans hence the pejorative use of
‘sophism’, teaching their sophistical reasoning for money, and at the other
extreme as Victorian moralists and educators. The truth is more complex. They
were not a school, and shared no body of opinions. They were typically
concerned with ethics unlike many earlier philosophers, who emphasized physical
inquiries and about the relationship between laws and customs nomos and nature
phusis. Protagoras of Abdera c.490c.420 B.C. was the most famous and perhaps
the first Sophist. He visited Athens frequently, and became a friend of its
leader, Pericles; he therefore was invited to draw up a legal code for the
colony of Thurii 444. According to some late reports, he died in a shipwreck as
he was leaving Athens, having been tried for and found guilty of impiety. He
claimed that he knew nothing about the gods, because of human limitations and
the difficulty of the question. We have only a few short quotations from his
works. His “Truth” also known as the “Throws,” i.e., how to overthrow an
opponent’s arguments begins with his most famous claim: “Humans are the measure
of all things of things that are, that
they are, of things that are not, that they are not.” That is, there is no
objective truth; the world is for each person as it appears to that person. Of
what use, then, are skills? Skilled people can change others’ perceptions in
useful ways. For example, a doctor can change a sick person’s perceptions so
that she is healthy. Protagoras taught his students to “make the weaker
argument the stronger,” i.e., to alter people’s perceptions about the value of
arguments. Aristophanes satirizes Protagoras as one who would make unjust
arguments defeat just arguments. This is true for ethical judgments, too: laws
and customs are simply products of human agreement. But because laws and
customs result from experiences of what is most useful, they should be followed
rather than nature. No perception or judgment is more true than another, but
some are more useful, and those that are more useful should be followed.
Gorgias c.483376 was a student of Empedocles. His town, Leontini in Sicily,
sent him as an ambassador to Athens in 427; his visit was a great success, and
the Athenians were amazed at his rhetorical ability. Like other Sophists, he
charged for instruction and gave speeches at religious festivals. Gorgias
denied that he taught virtue; instead, he produced clever speakers. He insisted
that different people have different virtues: for example, women’s virtue
differs from men’s. Since there is no truth and if there were we couldn’t know
it, we must rely on opinion, and so speakers who can change people’s opinions have
great power greater than the power
produced by any other skill. In his “Encomium on Helen” he argues that if she
left Menelaus and went with Paris because she was convinced by speech, she
wasn’t responsible for her actions. Two paraphrases of Gorgias’s “About What
Doesn’t Exist” survive; in this he argues that nothing exists, that even if
something did, we couldn’t know it, and that even if we could know anything we
couldn’t explain it to anyone. We can’t know anything, because some things we
think of do not exist, and so we have no way of judging whether the things we
think of exist. And we can’t express any knowledge we may have, because no two
people can think of the same thing, since the same thing can’t be in two
places, and because we use words in speech, not colors or shapes or objects.
This may be merely a parody of Parmenides’ argument that only one thing exists.
Antiphon the Sophist fifth century is probably although not certainly to be
distinguished from Antiphon the orator d. 411, some of whose speeches we
possess. We know nothing about his life if he is distinct from the orator. In
addition to brief quotations in later authors, we have two papyrus fragments of
his “On Truth.” In these he argues that we should follow laws and customs only
if there are witnesses and so our action will affect our reputation; otherwise,
we should follow nature, which is often inconsistent with following custom.
Custom is established by human agreement, and so disobeying it is detrimental
only if others know it is disobeyed, whereas nature’s demands unlike those of
custom can’t be ignored with impunity. Antiphon assumes that rational actions
are selfinterested, and that justice demands actions contrary to
self-interest a position Plato attacks
in the Republic. Antiphon was also a materialist: the nature of a bed is wood,
since if a buried bed could grow it would grow wood, not a bed. His view is one
of Aristotle’s main concerns in the Physics, since Aristotle admits in the
Categories that persistence through change is the best test for substance, but
won’t admit that matter is substance. Hippias fifth century was from Elis, in
the Peloponnesus, which used him as an ambasSophists Sophists 863 863 sador. He competed at the festival of
Olympus with both prepared and extemporaneous speeches. He had a phenomenal
memory. Since Plato repeatedly makes fun of him in the two dialogues that bear
his name, he probably was selfimportant and serious. He was a polymath who
claimed he could do anything, including making speeches and clothes; he wrote a
work collecting what he regarded as the best things said by others. According
to one report, he made a mathematical discovery the quadratrix, the first curve
other than the circle known to the Grecians. In the Protagoras, Plato has Hippias
contrast nature and custom, which often does violence to nature. Prodicus fifth
century was from Ceos, in the Cyclades, which frequently employed him on
diplomatic missions. He apparently demanded high fees, but had two versions of
his lecture one cost fifty drachmas, the
other one drachma. Socrates jokes that if he could have afforded the
fifty-drachma lecture, he would have learned the truth about the correctness of
words, and Aristotle says that when Prodicus added something exciting to keep
his audience’s attention he called it “slipping in the fifty-drachma lecture
for them.” We have at least the content of one lecture of his, the “Choice of
Heracles,” which consists of banal moralizing. Prodicus was praised by Socrates
for his emphasis on the right use of words and on distinguishing between
synonyms. He also had a naturalistic view of the origin of theology: useful
things were regarded as gods.
sorel: sphilosopher best known for his “Reflections on
Violence,” which develops the notion of revolutionary syndicalism as seen
through proletarian violence and the interpretation of myth. An early proponent
of the quasiMarxist position of gradual democratic reformism, Sorel eventually
developed a highly subjective interpretation of historical materialism that,
while retaining a conception of proletarian revolution, now understood it
through myth rather than reason. He was in large part reacting to the
empiricism of the Enlightenment and the
statistical structuring of sociological studies. In contrast to Marx and
Engels, who held that revolution would occur when the proletariat attained its
own class consciousness through an understanding of its true relationship to
the means of production in capitalist society, Sorel introduced myth rather
than reason as the correct way to interpret social totality. Myth allows for
the necessary reaction to bourgeois rationalism and permits the social theorist
to negate the status quo through the authenticity of revolutionary violence. By
acknowledging the irrationality of the status quo, myth permits the possibility
of social understanding and its necessary reaction, human emancipation through
proletarian revolution. Marxism is myth because it juxtaposes the
irreducibility of capitalist organization to its negation violent proletarian revolution. The
intermediary stage in this development is radical syndicalism, which organizes
workers into groups opposed to bourgeois authority, instills the myth of
proletarian revolution in the workers, and allows them in postrevolutionary
times to work toward a social arrangement of worker and peasant governance and
collaboration. The vehicle through which all this is accomplished is the
general strike, whose aim, through the justified violence of its ends, is to
facilitate the downfall and ultimate elimination of the bourgeoisie. In doing
so the proletariat will lead society to a classless and harmonious stage in
history. By stressing the notion of spontaneity Sorel thought he had solved the
vexing problems of party and future bureaucracy found in much of the
revolutionary literature of his day. In his later years he was interested in
the writings of both Lenin and Mussolini.
sort: Grice, “One of the few technicisms introduced by an
English philosopher, in this case Locke.” – a sortal predicate, roughly, a
predicate whose application to an object says what kind of object it is and
implies conditions for objects of that kind to be identical. Person, green
apple, regular hexagon, and pile of coal would generally be regarded as sortal
predicates, whereas tall, green thing, and coal would generally be regarded as
non-sortal predicates. An explicit and precise definition of the distinction is
hard to come by. Sortal predicates are sometimes said to be distinguished by
the fact that they provide a criterion of counting or that they do not apply to
the parts of the objects to which they apply, but there are difficulties with
each of these characterizations. The notion figures in recent philosophical
discussions on various topics. Robert Ackermann and others have suggested that
any scientific law confirmable by observation might require the use of sortal
predicates. Thus ‘all non-black things are non-ravens’, while logically
equivalent to the putative scientific law ‘all ravens are black’, is not itself
confirmable by observation because ‘non-black’ is not a sortal predicate. David
Wiggins and others have discussed the sortal sortal predicate 865 865 idea that all identity claims are
sortal-relative in the sense that an appropriate response to the claim a % b is
always “the same what as b?” John Wallace has argued that there would be
advantages in relativizing the quantifiers of predicate logic to sortals. ‘All
humans are mortal’ would be rendered Ex[m]Dx, rather than ExMxPDx. Crispin
Wright has suggested that the view that natural number is a sortal concept is
central to Frege’s or any other number-theoretic platonism. The word ‘sortal’
as a technical term in philosophy apparently first occurs in Locke’s Essay
Concerning Human Understanding. Locke argues that the so-called essence of a
genus or sort unlike the real essence of a thing is merely the abstract idea
that the general or sortal name stands for. But ‘sortal’ has only one
occurrence in Locke’s Essay. Its currency in contemporary philosophical idiom
probably should be credited to P. F. Strawson’s Individuals. The general idea
may be traced at least to the notion of second substance in Aristotle’s
Categories.
Sotione, teacher of Seneca. In glossary to Roman
philosophers, in “Roman philosophers.”
soul: -- cf. Grice on “soul-to-soul transfer” -- also
called spirit, an entity supposed to be present only in living things,
corresponding to the Grecian psyche and Latin anima. Since there seems to be no
material difference between an organism in the last moments of its life and the
organism’s newly dead body, many philosophers since the time of Plato have
claimed that the soul is an immaterial component of an organism. Because only
material things are observed to be subject to dissolution, Plato took the
soul’s immateriality as grounds for its immortality. Neither Plato nor
Aristotle thought that only persons had souls: Aristotle ascribed souls to
animals and plants since they all exhibited some living functions. Unlike
Plato, Aristotle denied the transmigration of souls from one species to another
or from one body to another after death; he was also more skeptical about the
soul’s capacity for disembodiment
roughly, survival and functioning without a body. Descartes argued that
only persons had souls and that the soul’s immaterial nature made freedom possible
even if the human body is subject to deterministic physical laws. As the
subject of thought, memory, emotion, desire, and action, the soul has been
supposed to be an entity that makes self-consciousness possible, that
differentiates simultaneous experiences into experiences either of the same
person or of different persons, and that accounts for personal identity or a
person’s continued identity through time. Dualists argue that soul and body
must be distinct in order to explain consciousness and the possibility of
immortality. Materialists argue that consciousness is entirely the result of
complex physical processes.
soundness: Grice: “The etymology if fascinating.” The English
Grice. "Most of the terms I use are
Latinate." "I implicate: a few are not." "I say that System
G should be sound." "free from special defect or injury," c.
1200, from Old English gesund "sound, safe, having the organs and
faculties complete and in perfect action," from Proto-Germanic *sunda-,
from Germanic root *swen-to- "healthy, strong" (source also of Old
Saxon gisund, Old Frisian sund, Dutch gezond, Old High German gisunt, German
gesund "healthy," as in the post-sneezing interjection gesundheit;
also Old English swið "strong," Gothic swinþs "strong,"
German geschwind "fast, quick"), with connections in Indo-Iranian and
Balto-Slavic. Meaning "right, correct, free from error" is from
mid-15c. Meaning "financially solid or safe" is attested from c.
1600; of sleep, "undisturbed," from 1540s. Sense of "holding
accepted opinions" is from 1520s Grice: “’sound’ is not polysemous,
but it has different usages: of an argument the property of being valid and
having all true premises; of a system, like Sytem G, the property of being not too strong in a
certain respect. A System G has weak
soundness provided every theorem of G is
valid. And G has strong soundness if for every set S of sentences, every
sentence deducible from S using system G is a logical consequence of S.
spatium: space, an extended manifold of several dimensions, where
the number of dimensions corresponds to the number of variable magnitudes Soto,
Domingo de space 866 866 needed to
specify a location in the manifold; in particular, the three-dimensional
manifold in which physical objects are situated and with respect to which their
mutual positions and distances are defined. Ancient Grecian atomism defined
space as the infinite void in which atoms move; but whether space is finite or
infinite, and whether void spaces exist, have remained in question. Aristotle
described the universe as a finite plenum and reduced space to the aggregate of
all places of physical things. His view was preeminent until Renaissance
Neoplatonism, the Copernican revolution, and the revival of atomism
reintroduced infinite, homogeneous space as a fundamental cosmological
assumption. Further controversy concerned whether the space assumed by early
modern astronomy should be thought of as an independently existing thing or as
an abstraction from the spatial relations of physical bodies. Interest in the
relativity of motion encouraged the latter view, but Newton pointed out that
mechanics presupposes absolute distinctions among motions, and he concluded
that absolute space must be postulated along with the basic laws of motion
Principia, 1687. Leibniz argued for the relational view from the identity of
indiscernibles: the parts of space are indistinguishable from one another and
therefore cannot be independently existing things. Relativistic physics has
defused the original controversy by revealing both space and spatial relations
as merely observer-dependent manifestations of the structure of spacetime.
Meanwhile, Kant shifted the metaphysical controversy to epistemological grounds
by claiming that space, with its Euclidean structure, is neither a
“thing-in-itself” nor a relation of thingsin-themselves, but the a priori form
of outer intuition. His view was challenged by the elaboration of non-Euclidean
geometries in the nineteenth century, by Helmholtz’s arguments that both
intuitive and physical space are known through empirical investigation, and
finally by the use of non-Euclidean geometry in the theory of relativity.
Precisely what geometrical presuppositions are inherent in human spatial
perception, and what must be learned from experience, remain subjects of
psychological investigation.
space-time: a four-dimensional continuum combining the three
dimensions of space with time in order to represent motion geometrically. Each
point is the location of an event, all of which together represent “the world”
through time; paths in the continuum worldlines represent the dynamical
histories of moving particles, so that straight worldlines correspond to
uniform motions; three-dimensional sections of constant time value “spacelike
hypersurfaces” or “simultaneity slices” represent all of space at a given time.
The idea was foreshadowed when Kant represented “the phenomenal world” as a
plane defined by space and time as perpendicular axes Inaugural Dissertation,
1770, and when Joseph Louis Lagrange 17361814 referred to mechanics as “the
analytic geometry of four dimensions.” But classical mechanics assumes a
universal standard of simultaneity, and so it can treat space and time
separately. The concept of space-time was explicitly developed only when Einstein
criticized absolute simultaneity and made the velocity of light a universal
constant. The mathematician Hermann Minkowski showed in 8 that the
observer-independent structure of special relativity could be represented by a
metric space of four dimensions: observers in relative motion would disagree on
intervals of length and time, but agree on a fourdimensional interval combining
spatial and temporal measurements. Minkowski’s model then made possible the
general theory of relativity, which describes gravity as a curvature of
spacetime in the presence of mass and the paths of falling bodies as the
straightest worldlines in curved space-time.
spatio-temporal
continuancy: or continunity, a
property of the careers, or space-time paths, of well-behaved objects. Let a
space-time path be a series of possible spatiotemporal positions, each
represented in a selected coordinate system by an ordered pair consisting of a
time its temporal component and a volume of space its spatial component. Such a
path will be spatiotemporally continuous provided it is such that, relative to
any inertial frame selected as coordinate system, space, absolute
spatiotemporal continuity 867 867 1 for
every segment of the series, the temporal components of the members of that
segment form a continuous temporal interval; and 2 for any two members ‹ti, Vi
and ‹tj, Vj of the series that differ in their temporal components ti and tj,
if Vi and Vj the spatial components differ in either shape, size, or location,
then between these members of the series there will be a member whose spatial
component is more similar to Vi and Vj in these respects than these are to each
other. This notion is of philosophical interest partly because of its
connections with the notions of identity over time and causality. Putting aside
such qualifications as quantum considerations may require, material objects at
least macroscopic objects of familiar kinds apparently cannot undergo
discontinuous change of place, and cannot have temporal gaps in their
histories, and therefore the path through space-time traced by such an object
must apparently be spatiotemporally continuous. More controversial is the claim
that spatiotemporal continuity, together with some continuity with respect to
other properties, is sufficient as well as necessary for the identity of such
objects e.g., that if a spatiotemporally
continuous path is such that the spatial component of each member of the series
is occupied by a table of a certain description at the time that is the
temporal component of that member, then there is a single table of that
description that traces that path. Those who deny this claim sometimes maintain
that it is further required for the identity of material objects that there be
causal and counterfactual dependence of later states on earlier ones ceteris
paribus, if the table had been different yesterday, it would be correspondingly
different now. Since it appears that chains of causality must trace spatiotemporally
continuous paths, it may be that insofar as spatiotemporal continuity is
required for transtemporal identity, this is because it is required for
transtemporal causality. Refs.: H. P. Grice and P. F. Strawson, “Categories,”
in The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC MSS 90/135c, The Bancroft Library, The
University of California, Berkeley.
specious
present: the supposed time between
past and future. The phrase was first offered by Clay in “The Alternative: A Study in
Psychology,” and is cited by James in his
Principles of Psychology Clay challenges
the assumption that the “present” as a “datum” is given as “present” to us in
our experience. “The present to which the datum refers is really a part of the *past*,
a recent past delusively given as benign
time that intervenes between the past and the future. Let it be named ‘the
specious present,’ and let the past that is given as being the past be known as
‘the obvious past.’” For James, this position is supportive of his contention
that consciousness (conscientia) is a stream and can be divided into parts only
by conceptual addition, i.e., only by our ascribing past, present, and future
to what is, in our actual experience, a seamless flow. James holds that the
“practically cognized present is no knife-edge but a saddleback,” a sort of
“ducatum” which we experience as a whole, and only upon reflective attention do
we “distinguish its beginning from its end.” Whereas Clay refers to the datum
of the present as “delusive,” one might rather say that it is perpetually *elusive*,
for as we have our experience, now, it is always bathed retrospectively and
prospectively. Contrary to common wisdom, no single experience ever is had by
our consciousness utterly alone, single and without relations, fore and aft.
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The logical-construction theory of personal identity.”
speculatum: Grice: “Philosophy may broadly be divided into
‘philosophia speculativa” and “philosophia practica.”” -- speculative
philosophy, a form of theorizing that goes beyond verifiable observation;
specifically, a philosophical approach informed by the impulse to construct a
grand narrative of a worldview that encompasses the whole of reality.
Speculative philosophy purports to bind together reflections on the existence
and nature of the cosmos, the psyche, and God. It sets for its goal a unifying
matrix and an overarching system whereswith to comprehend the considered
judgments of cosmology, psychology, and theology. Hegel’s absolute idealism,
particularly as developed in his later thought, paradigmatically illustrates
the requirements for speculative philosophizing. His system of idealism offered
a vision of the unity of the categories of human thought as they come to
realization in and through their opposition to each other. Speculative thought
tends to place a premium on universality, totality, and unity; and it tends to
marginalize the concrete particularities of the natural and social world. In
its aggressive use of the systematic principle, geared to a unification of
human experience, speculative philosophy aspires to a comprehensive
understanding and explanation of the structural interrelations of the culture
spheres of science, morality, art, and religion. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Practical
and doxastic attitudes: why I need exhibitive clauses.”
spencer: English philosopher, social reformer, and editor of
The Economist. In epistemology, Spencer adopted the ninespeculative reason
Spencer, Herbert 869 869 teenth-century
trend toward positivism: the only reliable knowledge of the universe is to be
found in the sciences. His ethics were utilitarian, following Bentham and J. S.
Mill: pleasure and pain are the criteria of value as signs of happiness or
unhappiness in the individual. His Synthetic Philosophy, expounded in books
written over many years, assumed both in biology and psychology the existence
of Lamarckian evolution: given a characteristic environment, every animal
possesses a disposition to make itself into what it will, failing maladaptive
interventions, eventually become. The dispositions gain expression as inherited
acquired habits. Spencer could not accept that species originate by chance
variations and natural selection alone: direct adaptation to environmental
constraints is mainly responsible for biological changes. Evolution also
includes the progression of societies in the direction of a dynamical
equilibrium of individuals: the human condition is perfectible because human
faculties are completely adapted to life in society, implying that evil and
immorality will eventually disappear. His ideas on evolution predated
publication of the major works of Darwin; A. R. Wallace was influenced by his
writings. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Evolutionary pirotology,” in “Method in
philosophical psychology: from the banal to the bizarre.”
speranza: luigi della --. Italian philosopher, attracted, for
some reason, to H. P. Grice. Speranza knows St. John’s very well. He is the
author of “Dorothea Oxoniensis.” He is a member of a number of cultivated Anglo-Italian
societies, like H. P. Grice’s Playgroup. He is the custodian of Villa Grice,
not far from Villa Speranza. He works at the Swimming-Pool Library. Cuisine is
one of his hobbies – grisottoa alla ligure, his specialty. He can be reached
via H. P. Grice. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Vita ed opinion di Luigi Speranza,”
par Luigi Speranza. The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC MSS 90/135c, The Bancroft
Library, The University of California, Berkeley.
Speranza, villa – The Swimming-Pool Library – H. P.
Grice’s Play Group, Liguria, Italia.
spinoza: Jewish metaphysician, born in the Netherlanads -- epistemologist,
psychologist, moral philosopher, political theorist, and philosopher of
religion, generally regarded as one of the most important figures of
seventeenth-century rationalism. Life and works. Born and educated in the
Jewish ‘community’ of Amsterdam, he forsook his given name ‘Baruch’ in favor of
the Latin ‘Benedict’ at the age of twenty-two. Between 1652 and 1656 he studied
the philosophy of Descartes in the school of Francis van den Enden. Having
developed unorthodox views of the divine nature and having ceased to be fully
observant of Jewish practice, he was excommunicated by the Jewish community in
1656. He spent his entire life in Holland; after leaving Amsterdam in 1660, he
resided successively in Rijnsburg, Voorburg, and the Hague. He supported
himself at least partly through grinding lenses, and his knowledge of optics
involved him in an area of inquiry of great importance to seventeenth-century
science. Acquainted with such leading intellectual figures as Leibniz, Huygens,
and Henry Oldenberg, he declined a professorship at the of Heidelberg partly on the grounds that it
might interfere with his intellectual freedom. His premature death at the age
of fortyfour was due to consumption. The only work published under Spinoza’s
name during his lifetime was his Principles of Descartes’s Philosophy Renati
Des Cartes Principiorum Philosophiae, Pars I et II, 1663, an attempt to recast
and present Parts I and II of Descartes’s Principles of Philosophy in the
manner that Spinoza called geometrical order or geometrical method. Modeled on
the Elements of Euclid and on what Descartes called the method of synthesis,
Spinoza’s “geometrical order” involves an initial set of definitions and
axioms, from which various propositions are demonstrated, with notes or scholia
attached where necessary. This work, which established his credentials as an
expositor of Cartesian philosophy, had its origins in his endeavor to teach
Descartes’s Principles of Philosophy to a private student. Spinoza’s
TheologicalPolitical Treatise Tractatus Theologico-Politicus was published
anonymously in 1670. After his death, his close circle of friends published his
Posthumous Works Opera Postuma, 1677, which included his masterpieces, Ethic,
Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Ethica, Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata. The
Posthumous Works also included his early unfinished Treatise on the Emendation
of the Intellect Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione, his later unfinished
Political Treatise Tractatus Politicus, a Hebrew Grammar, and Correspondence.
An unpublished early work entitled Short Treatise on God, Man, and His
Well-Being Korte Vorhandelung van God, de Mensch en deszelvs Welstand, in many
ways a forerunner of the Ethics, was rediscovered in copied manuscript and
published in the nineteenth century. Spinoza’s authorship of two brief
scientific treatises, On the Rainbow and On the Calculation of Chances, is
still disputed. Metaphysics. Spinoza often uses the term ‘God, or Nature’ “Deus,
sive Natura“, and this identification of God with Nature is at the heart of his
metaphysics. Because of this identification, his philosophy is often regarded
as a version of pantheism and/or naturalism. But although philosophy begins
with metaphysics for Spinoza, his metaphysics is ultimately in the service of
his ethics. Because his naturalized God has no desires or purposes, human
ethics cannot properly be derived from divine command. Rather, Spinozistic
ethics seeks to demonstrate, from an adequate understanding of the divine
nature and its expression in human nature, the way in which human beings can
maximize their advantage. Central to the successful pursuit of this advantage
is adequate knowledge, which leads to increasing control of the passions and to
cooperative action. Spinoza’s ontology, like that of Descartes, consists of
substances, their attributes which Descartes called principal attributes, and
their modes. In the Ethics, Spinoza defines ‘substance’ as what is “in itself,
and is conceived through itself”; ‘attribute’ as that which “the intellect
perceives of a substance as constituting its essence”; and ‘mode’ as “the
affections of a substance, or that which is in another through which also it is
conceived.” While Descartes had recognized a strict sense in which only God is
a substance, he also recognized a second sense in which there are two kinds of
created substances, each with its own principal attribute: extended substances,
whose only principal attribute is extension; and minds, whose only principal
attribute is thought. Spinoza, in contrast, consistently maintains that there
is only one substance. His metaphysics is thus a form of substantial monism.
This one substance is God, which Spinoza defines as “a being absolutely
infinite, i.e., a substance consisting of an infinity of attributes, of which
each expresses an eternal and infinite essence.” Thus, whereas Descartes
limited each created substance to one principal attribute, Spinoza claims that
the one substance has infinite attributes, each expressing the divine nature
without limitation in its own way. Of these infinite attributes, however,
humans can comprehend only two: extension and thought. Within each attribute,
the modes of God are of two kinds: infinite modes, which are pervasive features
of each attribute, such as the laws of nature; and finite modes, which are
local and limited modifications of substance. There is an infinite sequence of
finite modes. Descartes regarded a human being as a substantial union of two
different substances, the thinking soul and the extended body, in causal
interaction with each other. Spinoza, in contrast, regards a human being as a
finite mode of God, existing simultaneously in God as a mode of thought and as
a mode of extension. He holds that every mode of extension is literally
identical with the mode of thought that is the “idea of” that mode of
extension. Since the human mind is the idea of the human body, it follows that
the human mind and the human body are literally the same thing, conceived under
two different attributes. Because they are actually identical, there is no
causal interaction between the mind and the body; but there is a complete
parallelism between what occurs in the mind and what occurs in the body. Since
every mode of extension has a corresponding and identical mode of thought
however rudimentary that might be, Spinoza allows that every mode of extension
is “animated to some degree”; his view is thus a form of panpsychism. Another
central feature of Spinoza’s metaphysics is his necessitarianism, expressed in
his claim that “things could have been produced . . . in no other way, and in
no other order” than that in which they have been produced. He derives this
necessitarianism from his doctrine that God exists necessarily for which he
offers several arguments, including a version of the ontological argument and
his doctrine that everything that can follow from the divine nature must
necessarily do so. Thus, although he does not use the term, he accepts a very
strong version of the principle of sufficient reason. At the outset of the
Ethics, he defines a thing as free when its actions are determined by its own
nature alone. Only God whose actions are
determined entirely by the necessity of his own nature, and for whom nothing is
external is completely free in this
sense. Nevertheless, human beings can achieve a relative freedom to the extent
that they live the kind of life described in the later parts of the Ethics.
Hence, Spinoza is a compatibilist concerning the relation between freedom and
determinism. “Freedom of the will” in any sense that implies a lack of causal
determination, however, is simply an illusion based on ignorance of the true
causes of a being’s actions. The recognition that all occurrences are causally
determined, Spinoza holds, has a positive consolatory power that aids one in
controlling the passions. Epistemology and psychology. Like other rationalists,
Spinoza distinguishes two representational faculties: the imagination and the
intellect. The imagination is a faculty of forming imagistic representations of
things, derived ultimately from the mechanisms of the senses; the intellect is
a faculty of forming adequate, nonimagistic conceptions of things. He also
distinguishes three “kinds of knowledge.” The first or lowest kind he calls
opinion or imagination opinio, imaginatio. It includes “random or indeterminate
experience” experientia vaga and also “hearsay, or knowledge from mere signs”;
it thus depends on the confused and mutilated deliverances of the senses, and
is inadequate. The second kind of knowledge he calls reason ratio; it depends
on common notions i.e., features of things that are “common to all, and equally
in the part and in the whole” or on adequate knowledge of the properties as
opposed to the essences of things. The third kind of knowledge he calls
intuitive knowledge scientia intuitiva; it proceeds from adequate knowledge of
the essence or attributes of God to knowledge of the essence of things, and
hence proceeds in the proper order, from causes to effects. Both the second and
third kinds of knowledge are adequate. The third kind is preferable, however,
as involving not only certain knowledge that something is so, but also
knowledge of how and why it is so. Because there is only one substance God
the individual things of the world are not distinguished from one
another by any difference of substance. Rather, among the internal qualitative
modifications and differentiations of each divine attribute, there are patterns
that have a tendency to endure; these constitute individual things. As they
occur within the attribute of extension, Spinoza calls these patterns fixed
proportions of motion and rest. Although these individual things are thus modes
of the one substance, rather than substances in their own right, each has a
nature or essence describable in terms of the thing’s particular pattern and
its mechanisms for the preservation of its own being. This tendency toward
self-preservation Spinoza calls conatus sometimes tr. as ‘endeavor’. Every individual
thing has some conatus. An individual thing acts, or is active, to the extent
that what occurs can be explained or understood through its own nature i.e.,
its selfpreservatory mechanism alone; it is passive to the extent that what
happens must be explained through the nature of other forces impinging on it.
Thus, every thing, to whatever extent it can, actively strives to persevere in
its existence; and whatever aids this self-preservation constitutes that
individual’s advantage. Spinoza’s specifically human psychology is an
application of this more general doctrine of conatus. That application is made
through appeal to several specific characteristics of human beings: they form
imagistic representations of other individuals by means of their senses; they
are sufficiently complex to undergo increases and decreases in their capacity
for action; and they are capable of engaging in reason. The fundamental
concepts of his psychology are desire, which is conatus itself, especially as
one is conscious of it as directed toward attaining a particular object;
pleasure, which is an increase in capacity for action; and pain, which is a
decrease in capacity for action. He defines other emotions in terms of these
basic emotions, as they occur in particular combinations, in particular kinds
of circumstances, with particular kinds of causes, and/or with particular kinds
of objects. When a person is the adequate cause of his or her own emotions,
these emotions are active emotions; otherwise, they are passions. Desire and pleasure
can be either active emotions or passions, depending on the circumstances;
pain, however, can only be a passion. Spinoza does not deny the phenomenon of
altruism: one’s self-preservatory mechanism, and hence one’s desire, can become
focused on a wide variety of objects, including the well-being of a loved
person or object even to one’s own
detriment. However, because he reduces all human motivation, including
altruistic motivation, to permutations of the endeavor to seek one’s own
advantage, his theory is arguably a form of psychological egoism. Ethics.
Spinoza’s ethical theory does not take the form of a set of moral commands.
Rather, he seeks to demonstrate, by considering human actions and appetites
objectively “just as if it were a
Question of lines, planes, and bodies”
wherein a person’s true advantage lies. Readers who genuinely grasp the
demonstrated truths will, he holds, ipso facto be motivated, to at least some
extent, to live their lives accordingly. Thus, Spinozistic ethics seeks to show
how a person acts when “guided by reason“; to act in this way is at the same
time to act with virtue, or power. All actions that result from
understanding i.e., all virtuous actions may be attributed to strength of character
fortitudo. Such virtuous actions may be further divided into two classes: those
due to tenacity animositas, or “the Desire by which each one strives, solely
from the dictate of reason, to preserve his being”; and those due to nobility
generositas, or “the Desire by which each one strives, solely from the dictate
of reason, to aid other men and join them to him in friendship.” Thus, the
virtuous person does not merely pursue private advantage, but seeks to
cooperate with others; returns love for hatred; always acts honestly, not deceptively;
and seeks to join himself with others in a political state. Nevertheless, the
ultimate reason for aiding others and joining them to oneself in friendship is
that “nothing is more useful to man than man”
i.e., because doing so is conducive to one’s own advantage, and
particularly to one’s pursuit of knowledge, which is a good that can be shared
without loss. Although Spinoza holds that we generally use the terms ‘good’ and
‘evil’ simply to report subjective appearances
so that we call “good” whatever we desire, and “evil” whatever we seek
to avoid he proposes that we define
‘good’ philosophically as ‘what we certainly know to be useful to us’, and
‘evil’ as ‘what we certainly know prevents us from being masters of some good’.
Since God is perfect and has no needs, it follows that nothing is either good
or evil for God. Spinoza’s ultimate appeal to the agent’s advantage arguably
renders his ethical theory a form of ethical egoism, even though he emphasizes
the existence of common shareable goods and the instrumental ethical importance
of cooperation with others. However, it is not a form of hedonism; for despite
the prominence he gives to pleasure, the ultimate aim of human action is a
higher state of perfection or capacity for action, of whose increasing
attainment pleasure is only an indicator. A human being whose self-preservatory
mechanism is driven or distorted by external forces is said to be in bondage to
the passions; in contrast, one who successfully pursues only what is truly
advantageous, in consequence of genuine understanding of where that advantage
properly lies, is free. Accordingly, Spinoza also expresses his conception of a
virtuous life guided by reason in terms of an ideal “free man.” Above all, the
free man seeks understanding of himself and of Nature. Adequate knowledge, and
particularly knowledge of the third kind, leads to blessedness, to peace of
mind, and to the intellectual love of God. Blessedness is not a reward for
virtue, however, but rather an integral aspect of the virtuous life. The human
mind is itself a part of the infinite intellect of God, and adequate knowledge
is an eternal aspect of that infinite intellect. Hence, as one gains knowledge,
a greater part of one’s own mind comes to be identified with something that is
eternal, and one becomes less dependent on
and less disturbed by the local
forces of one’s immediate environment. Accordingly, the free man “thinks of
nothing less than of death, and his wisdom is a meditation on life, not on
death.” Moreover, just as one’s adequate knowledge is literally an eternal part
of the infinite intellect of God, the resulting blessedness, peace of mind, and
intellectual love are literally aspects of what might be considered God’s own
eternal “emotional” life. Although this endows the free man with a kind of
blessed immortality, it is not a personal immortality, since the sensation and
memory that are essential to personal individuality are not eternal. Rather,
the free man achieves during his lifetime an increasing participation in a body
of adequate knowledge that has itself always been eternal, so that, at death, a
large part of the free man’s mind has become identified with the eternal. It is
thus a kind of “immortality” in which one can participate while one lives, not
merely when one dies. Politics and philosophical theology. Spinoza’s political
theory, like that of Hobbes, treats rights and power as equivalent. Citizens
give up rights to the state for the sake of the protection that the state can
provide. Hobbes, however, regards this social contract as nearly absolute, one
in which citizens give up all of their rights except the right to resist death.
Spinoza, in contrast, emphasizes that citizens cannot give up the right to
pursue their own advantage as they see it, in its full generality; and hence
that the power, and right, of any actual state is always limited by the state’s
practical ability to enforce its dictates so as to alter the citizens’
continuing perception of their own advantage. Furthermore, he has a more extensive
conception of the nature of an individual’s own advantage than Hobbes, since
for him one’s own true advantage lies not merely in fending off death and
pursuing pleasure, but in achieving the adequate knowledge that brings
blessedness and allows one to participate in that which is eternal. In
consequence, Spinoza, unlike Hobbes, recommends a limited, constitutional state
that encourages freedom of expression and religious toleration. Such a
state itself a kind of individual best preserves its own being, and provides
both the most stable and the most beneficial form of government for its
citizens. In his Theological-Political Treatise, Spinoza also takes up popular
religion, the interpretation of Scripture, and their bearing on the well-being
of the state. He characterizes the Old Testament prophets as individuals whose
vivid imaginations produced messages of political value for the ancient Hebrew
state. Using a naturalistic outlook and historical hermeneutic methods that
anticipate the later “higher criticism” of the Bible, he seeks to show that
Scriptural writers themselves consistently treat only justice and charity as
essential to salvation, and hence that dogmatic doxastic requirements are not
justified by Scripture. Popular religion should thus propound only these two
requirements, which it may imaginatively represent, to the minds of the many,
as the requirements for rewards granted by a divine Lawgiver. The few, who are
more philosophical, and who thus rely on intellect, will recognize that the natural
laws of human psychology require charity and justice as conditions of
happiness, and that what the vulgar construe as rewards granted by personal
divine intervention are in fact the natural consequences of a virtuous life.
Because of his identificaton of God with Nature and his treatment of popular
religion, Spinoza’s contemporaries often regarded his philosophy as a thinly
disguised atheism. Paradoxically, however, nineteenth-century Romanticism
embraced him for his pantheism; Novalis, e.g., famously characterized him as
“the God-intoxicated man.” In fact, Spinoza ascribes to Nature most of the
characteristics that Western theologians have ascribed to God: Spinozistic
Nature is infinite, eternal, necessarily existing, the object of an ontological
argument, the first cause of all things, all-knowing, and the being whose
contemplation produces blessedness, intellectual love, and participation in a
kind of immortality or eternal life. Spinoza’s claim to affirm the existence of
God is therefore no mere evasion. However, he emphatically denies that God is a
person or acts for purposes; that anything is good or evil from the divine
perspective; or that there is a personal immortality involving memory. In
addition to his influence on the history of biblical criticism and on
literature including not only Novalis but such writers as Wordsworth,
Coleridge, Heine, Shelley, George Eliot, George Sand, Somerset Maugham, Jorge
Luis Borges, and Bernard Malamud, Spinoza has affected the philosophical
outlooks of such diverse twentieth-century thinkers as Freud and Einstein.
Contemporary physicists have seen in his monistic metaphysics an anticipation
of twentieth-century field metaphysics. More generally, he is a leading
intellectual forebear of twentieth-century determinism and naturalism, and of
the mindbody identity theory. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Hampshire’s Spinoza.”
spir: philosopher. He served in the Crimean War as a
Russian officer. His major works are “Forschung nach der Gewissheit in der
Erkenntnis der Wirklichkeit,” and “Denken und Wirklichkeit: Versuch einer
Erneuerung der kritischen Philosophie..” The latter essay presents a
metaphysics based on the radical separation of the apparent world and an
absolute reality. All we can know about the “unconditioned” is that it must
conform with the principle of identity. While retaining the unknowable thing-in-itself
of Kant, Spir argues for the empirical reality of time, which is given to us in
immediate experience and depends on our experience of a succession of
differential states (cf. Grice, “Personal identity”). The aim of philosophy is
to reach fundamental and immediate certainties. Of the works included in his “Gesammelte
Schriften,” the essay “Right and Wrong,” was tr.There are a number of
references to Spir in the writings of Nietzsche, which indicate that some of
Nietzsche’s central notions were influenced, both positively and negatively, by
Spir’s analyses of becoming and temporality, as well as by his concept of the
separation of the world of appearance and the “true world.” Refs.: H. P. Grice,
“Bradley’s absolute: a relative account.”
split-brain
effect: one of a wide array of
behavioral effects consequent upon the severing of the cerebral commisures, and
generally interpreted as indicating asymmetry in cerebral functions. The human
brain has considerable leftright functional differentiation, or asymmetry, that
affects behavior. The most obvious example is handedness. By the 1860s
Bouillaud, Dax, and Broca had observed that the effects of unilateral damage
indicated that the left hemisphere was preferentially involved in language.
Since the 0s, this commitment to functional asymmetry has been reinforced by
studies of patients in whom communication between the hemispheres has been
surgically disrupted. Split brain effects depend on severing the cerebral
commisures, and especially the corpus callosum, which are neural structures
mediating communication between the cerebral hemispheres. Commisurotomies have
been performed since the 0s to control severe epilepsy. This is intended to
leave both hemispheres intact and functioning independently. Beginning in the
0s, J. E. Bogen, M. S. Gazzaniga, and R. W. Sperry conducted an array of
psychological tests to evaluate the distinctive abilities of the different
hemispheres. Ascertaining the degree of cerebral asymmetry depends on a
carefully controlled experimental design in which access of the disassociated
hemispheres to peripheral cues is limited. The result has been a wide array of
striking results. For example, patients are unable to match an object such as a
key felt in one hand with a similar object felt in the other; patients are
unable to name an object Spir, Afrikan split brain effects 874 874 held in the left hand, though they can
name an object held in the right. Researchers have concluded that these results
confirm a clear lateralization of speech, writing, and calculation in the left
hemisphere for righthanded patients, leaving the right hemisphere largely
unable to respond in speech or writing, and typically unable to perform even
simple calculations. It is often concluded that the left hemisphere is
specialized for verbal and analytic modes of thinking, while the right
hemisphere is specialized for more spatial and synthetic modes of thinking. The
precise character and extent of these differences in normal subjects are less
clear.
sraffa: an Italian noble -- vitters, and Grice -- L. – cited by H. P. Grice, “Some like
Vitters, but Moore’s MY man.” Vienna-born philosopher trained as an enginner at
Manchester. Typically referred to Wittgenstein in the style of English
schoolboy slang of the time as, “Witters,” pronounced “Vitters.”“I heard Austin
said once: ‘Some like Witters, but Moore’s MY man.’ Austin would open the
“Philosophical Investigations,” and say, “Let’s see what Witters has to say
about this.” Everybody ended up loving Witters at the playgroup.” Witters’s
oeuvre was translated first into English by C. K. Ogden. There are interesting
twists. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Vitters.” Grice was sadly discomforted when one of
his best friends at Oxford, D. F. Pears, dedicated so much effort to the
unveiling of the mysteries of ‘Vitters.’ ‘Vitters’ was all in the air in
Grice’s inner circle. Strawson had written a review of Philosophical
Investigations. Austin was always mocking ‘Vitters,’ and there are other
connections. For Grice, the most important is that remark in “Philosohpical Investigations,”
which he never cared to check ‘in the Hun,’ about a horse not being seen ‘as a
horse.’ But in “Prolegomena” he mentions Vitters in other contexts, too, and in
“Causal Theory,” almost anonymously – but usually with regard to the ‘seeing as’
puzzle. Grice would also rely on Witters’s now knowing how to use ‘know’ or
vice versa. In “Method” Grice quotes verbatim: ‘No psyche without the
manifestation the ascription of psyche is meant to explain,” and also to the
effect that most ‘-etic’ talk of behaviour is already ‘-emic,’ via internal
perspective, or just pervaded with intentionalism. One of the most original and
challenging philosophical writers of the twentieth century. Born in Vienna into
an assimilated family of Jewish extraction, he went to England as a student and
eventually became a protégé of Russell’s at Cambridge. He returned to Austria
at the beginning of The Great War I, but went back to Cambridge in 8 and taught
there as a fellow and professor. Despite spending much of his professional life
in England, Vitters never lost contact with his Austrian background, and his
writings combine in a unique way ideas derived from both the insular and the
continental European tradition. His thought is strongly marked by a deep
skepticism about philosophy, but he retained the conviction that there was
something important to be rescued from the traditional enterprise. In his Blue
Book 8 he referred to his own work as “one of the heirs of the subject that
used to be called philosophy.” What strikes readers first when they look at
Vitters’s writings is the peculiar form of their composition. They are
generally made up of short individual notes that are most often numbered in
sequence and, in the more finished writings, evidently selected and arranged with
the greatest care. Those notes range from fairly technical discussions on
matters of logic, the mind, meaning, understanding, acting, seeing,
mathematics, and knowledge, to aphoristic observations about ethics, culture,
art, and the meaning of life. Because of their wide-ranging character, their
unusual perspective on things, and their often intriguing style, Vitters’s
writings have proved to appeal to both professional philosophers and those
interested in philosophy in a more general way. The writings as well as his
unusual life and personality have already produced a large body of interpretive
literature. But given his uncompromising stand, it is questionable whether his
thought will ever be fully integrated into academic philosophy. It is more
likely that, like Pascal and Nietzsche, he will remain an uneasy presence in
philosophy. From an early date onward Vitters was greatly influenced by the
idea that philosophical problems can be resolved by paying attention to the
working of language a thought he may
have gained from Fritz Mauthner’s Beiträge zu einer Kritik der Sprache 102.
Vitters’s affinity to Mauthner is, indeed, evident in all phases of his
philosophical development, though it is particularly noticeable in his later
thinking.Until recently it has been common to divide Vitters’s work into two
sharply distinct phases, separated by a prolonged period of dormancy. According
to this schema the early “Tractarian” period is that of the Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus 1, which Vitters wrote in the trenches of World War I, and
the later period that of the Philosophical Investigations 3, which he composed
between 6 and 8. But the division of his work into these two periods has proved
misleading. First, in spite of obvious changes in his thinking, Vitters remained
throughout skeptical toward traditional philosophy and persisted in channeling
philosophical questioning in a new direction. Second, the common view fails to
account for the fact that even between 0 and 8, when Vitters abstained from
actual work in philosophy, he read widely in philosophical and
semiphilosophical authors, and between 8 and 6 he renewed his interest in
philosophical work and wrote copiously on philosophical matters. The posthumous
publication of texts such as The Blue and Brown Books, Philosophical Grammar,
Philosophical Remarks, and Conversations with the Vienna Circle has led to
acknowledgment of a middle period in Vitters’s development, in which he
explored a large number of philosophical issues and viewpoints a period that served as a transition between
the early and the late work. Early period. As the son of a greatly successful
industrialist and engineer, Vitters first studied engineering in Berlin and
Manchester, and traces of that early training are evident throughout his writing.
But his interest shifted soon to pure mathematics and the foundations of
mathematics, and in pursuing questions about them he became acquainted with
Russell and Frege and their work. The two men had a profound and lasting effect
on Vitters even when he later came to criticize and reject their ideas. That
influence is particularly noticeable in the Tractatus, which can be read as an
attempt to reconcile Russell’s atomism with Frege’s apriorism. But the book is
at the same time moved by quite different and non-technical concerns. For even
before turning to systematic philosophy Vitters had been profoundly moved by
Schopenhauer’s thought as it is spelled out in The World as Will and
Representation, and while he was serving as a soldier in World War I, he renewed
his interest in Schopenhauer’s metaphysical, ethical, aesthetic, and mystical
outlook. The resulting confluence of ideas is evident in the Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus and gives the book its peculiar character. Composed in a
dauntingly severe and compressed style, the book attempts to show that
traditional philosophy rests entirely on a misunderstanding of “the logic of
our language.” Following in Frege’s and Russell’s footsteps, Vitters argued
that every meaningful sentence must have a precise logical structure. That
structure may, however, be hidden beneath the clothing of the grammatical
appearance of the sentence and may therefore require the most detailed analysis
in order to be made evident. Such analysis, Vitters was convinced, would
establish that every meaningful sentence is either a truth-functional composite
of another simpler sentence or an atomic sentence consisting of a concatenation
of simple names. He argued further that every atomic sentence is a logical
picture of a possible state of affairs, which must, as a result, have exactly
the same formal structure as the atomic sentence that depicts it. He employed
this “picture theory of meaning” as it
is usually called to derive conclusions
about the nature of the world from his observations about the structure of the
atomic sentences. He postulated, in particular, that the world must itself have
a precise logical structure, even though we may not be able to determine it
completely. He also held that the world consists primarily of facts, corresponding
to the true atomic sentences, rather than of things, and that those facts, in
turn, are concatenations of simple objects, corresponding to the simple names
of which the atomic sentences are composed. Because he derived these
metaphysical conclusions from his view of the nature of language, Vitters did
not consider it essential to describe what those simple objects, their
concatenations, and the facts consisting of them are actually like. As a
result, there has been a great deal of uncertainty and disagreement among
interpreters about their character. The propositions of the Tractatus are for
the most part concerned with spelling out Vitters’s account of the logical
structure of language and the world and these parts of the book have understandably
been of most interest to philosophers who are primarily concerned with
questions of symbolic logic and its applications. But for Vitters himself the
most important part of the book consisted of the negative conclusions about
philosophy that he reaches at the end of his text: in particular, that all
sentences that are not atomic pictures of concatenations of objects or
truth-functional composites of such are strictly speaking meaningless. Among
these he included all the propositions of ethics and aesthetics, all
propositions dealing with the meaning of life, all propositions of logic,
indeed all philosophical propositions, and finally all the propositions of the
Tractatus itself. These are all strictly meaningless; they aim at saying
something important, but what they try to express in words can only show
itself. As a result Vitters concluded that anyone who understood what the
Tractatus was saying would finally discard its propositions as senseless, that
she would throw away the ladder after climbing up on it. Someone who reached
such a state would have no more temptation to pronounce philosophical
propositions. She would see the world rightly and would then also recognize
that the only strictly meaningful propositions are those of natural science;
but those could never touch what was really important in human life, the
mystical. That would have to be contemplated in silence. For “whereof one
cannot speak, thereof one must be silent,” as the last proposition of the
Tractatus declared. Middle period. It was only natural that Vitters should not
embark on an academic career after he had completed that work. Instead he
trained to be a school teacher and taught primary school for a number of years
in the mountains of lower Austria. In the mid-0s he also built a house for his
sister; this can be seen as an attempt to give visual expression to the
logical, aesthetic, and ethical ideas of the Tractatus. In those years he
developed a number of interests seminal for his later development. His school
experience drew his attention to the way in which children learn language and
to the whole process of enculturation. He also developed an interest in
psychology and read Freud and others. Though he remained hostile to Freud’s
theoretical explanations of his psychoanalytic work, he was fascinated with the
analytic practice itself and later came to speak of his own work as therapeutic
in character. In this period of dormancy Vitters also became acquainted with
the members of the Vienna Circle, who had adopted his Tractatus as one of their
key texts. For a while he even accepted the positivist principle of meaning
advocated by the members of that Circle, according to which the meaning of a
sentence is the method of its verification. This he would later modify into the
more generous claim that the meaning of a sentence is its use. Vitters’s most
decisive step in his middle period was to abandon the belief of the Tractatus
that meaningful sentences must have a precise hidden logical structure and the
accompanying belief that this structure corresponds to the logical structure of
the facts depicted by those sentences. The Tractatus had, indeed, proceeded on
the assumption that all the different symbolic devices that can describe the
world must be constructed according to the same underlying logic. In a sense,
there was then only one meaningful language in the Tractatus, and from it one
was supposed to be able to read off the logical structure of the world. In the
middle period Vitters concluded that this doctrine constituted a piece of unwarranted
metaphysics and that the Tractatus was itself flawed by what it had tried to
combat, i.e., the misunderstanding of the logic of language. Where he had
previously held it possible to ground metaphysics on logic, he now argued that
metaphysics leads the philosopher into complete darkness. Turning his attention
back to language he concluded that almost everything he had said about it in
the Tractatus had been in error. There were, in fact, many different languages
with many different structures that could meet quite different specific needs.
Language was not strictly held together by logical structure, but consisted, in
fact, of a multiplicity of simpler substructures or language games. Sentences
could not be taken to be logical pictures of facts and the simple components of
sentences did not all function as names of simple objects. These new
reflections on language served Vitters, in the first place, as an aid to
thinking about the nature of the human mind, and specifically about the
relation between private experience and the physical world. Against the
existence of a Cartesian mental substance, he argued that the word ‘I’ did not
serve as a name of anything, but occurred in expressions meant to draw
attention to a particular body. For a while, at least, he also thought he could
explain the difference between private experience and the physical world in
terms of the existence of two languages, a primary language of experience and a
secondary language of physics. This duallanguage view, which is evident in both
the Philosophical Remarks and The Blue Book, Vitters was to give up later in
favor of the assumption that our grasp of inner phenomena is dependent on the
existence of outer criteria. From the mid-0s onward he also renewed his
interest in the philosophy of mathematics. In contrast to Frege and Russell, he
argued strenuously that no part of mathematics is reducible purely to logic.
Instead he set out to describe mathematics as part of our natural history and
as consisting of a number of diverse language games. He also insisted that the
meaning of those games depended on the uses to which the mathematical formulas
were put. Applying the principle of verification to mathematics, he held that
the meaning of a mathematical formula lies in its proof. These remarks on the
philosophy of mathematics have remained among Vitters’s most controversial and
least explored writings. Later period. Vitters’s middle period was
characterized by intensive philosophical work on a broad but quickly changing
front. By 6, however, his thinking was finally ready to settle down once again
into a steadier pattern, and he now began to elaborate the views for which he
became most famous. Where he had constructed his earlier work around the logic
devised by Frege and Russell, he now concerned himself mainly with the actual
working of ordinary language. This brought him close to the tradition of
British common sense philosophy that Moore had revived and made him one of the
godfathers of the ordinary language philosophy that was to flourish in Oxford
in the 0s. In the Philosophical Investigations Vitters emphasized that there
are countless different uses of what we call “symbols,” “words,” and
“sentences.” The task of philosophy is to gain a perspicuous view of those
multiple uses and thereby to dissolve philosophical and metaphysical puzzles.
These puzzles were the result of insufficient attention to the working of
language and could be resolved only by carefully retracing the linguistic steps
by which they had been reached. Vitters thus came to think of philosophy as a
descriptive, analytic, and ultimately therapeutic practice. In the
Investigations he set out to show how common philosophical views about meaning
including the logical atomism of the Tractatus, about the nature of concepts,
about logical necessity, about rule-following, and about the mindbody problem
were all the product of an insufficient grasp of how language works. In one of
the most influential passages of the book he argued that concept words do not
denote sharply circumscribed concepts, but are meant to mark family
resemblances between the things labeled with the concept. He also held that
logical necessity results from linguistic convention and that rules cannot
determine their own applications, that rule-following presupposes the existence
of regular practices. Furthermore, the words of our language have meaning only
insofar as there exist public criteria for their correct application. As a
consequence, he argued, there cannot be a completely private language, i.e., a
language that in principle can be used only to speak about one’s own inner
experience. This private language argument has caused much discussion.
Interpreters have disagreed not only over the structure of the argument and
where it occurs in Vitters’s text, but also over the question whether he meant
to say that language is necessarily social. Because he said that to speak of
inner experiences there must be external and publicly available criteria, he
has often been taken to be advocating a logical behaviorism, but nowhere does
he, in fact, deny the existence of inner states. What he says is merely that
our understanding of someone’s pain is connected to the existence of natural
and linguistic expressions of pain. In the Philosophical Investigations Vitters
repeatedly draws attention to the fact that language must be learned. This
learning, he says, is fundamentally a process of inculcation and drill. In
learning a language the child is initiated in a form of life. In Vitters’s
later work the notion of form of life serves to identify the whole complex of
natural and cultural circumstances presupposed by our language and by a
particular understanding of the world. He elaborated those ideas in notes on
which he worked between 8 and his death in 1 and which are now published under
the title On Certainty. He insisted in them that every belief is always part of
a system of beliefs that together constitute a worldview. All confirmation and
disconfirmation of a belief presuppose such a system and are internal to the
system. For all this he was not advocating a relativism, but a naturalism that
assumes that the world ultimately determines which language games can be
played. Vitters’s final notes vividly illustrate the continuity of his basic
concerns throughout all the changes his thinking went through. For they reveal
once more how he remained skeptical about all philosophical theories and how he
understood his own undertaking as the attempt to undermine the need for any
such theorizing. The considerations of On Certainty are evidently directed
against both philosophical skeptics and those philosophers who want to refute
skepticism. Against the philosophical skeptics Vitters insisted that there is
real knowledge, but this knowledge is always dispersed and not necessarily
reliable; it consists of things we have heard and read, of what has been
drilled into us, and of our modifications of this inheritance. We have no
general reason to doubt this inherited body of knowledge, we do not generally
doubt it, and we are, in fact, not in a position to do so. But On Certainty
also argues that it is impossible to refute skepticism by pointing to
propositions that are absolutely certain, as Descartes did when he declared ‘I
think, therefore I am’ indubitable, or as Moore did when he said, “I know for
certain that this is a hand here.” The fact that such propositions are
considered certain, Vitters argued, indicates only that they play an
indispensable, normative role in our language game; they are the riverbed
through which the thought of our language game flows. Such propositions cannot
be taken to express metaphysical truths. Here, too, the conclusion is that all
philosophical argumentation must come to an end, but that the end of such
argumentation is not an absolute, self-evident truth, but a certain kind of
natural human practice. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Il gesto della mano di Sraffa.”
Speranza, “Sraffa’s handwave, and his impicaturum.” Refs.: Luigi Speranza,
“L’implicatura di Sraffa,” per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library,
Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
standard: Grice:
“People, philosophers included, misuse ‘standard’ – in Italian, it just means
‘flag’!” -- model, a term that, like ‘non-standard model’, is used with regard
to theories that systematize part of our knowledge of some mathematical
structure, for instance the structure of natural numbers with addition,
multiplication, and the successor function, or the structure of real numbers
with ordering, addition, and multiplication. Models isomorphic to this intended
mathematical structure are the “standard models” of the theory, while any
other, non-isomorphic, model of the theory is a ‘non-standard’ model. Since
Peano arithmetic is incomplete, it has consistent extensions that have no
standard model. But there are also non-standard, countable models of complete
number theory, the set of all true first-order sentences about natural numbers,
as was first shown by Skolem in 4. Categorical theories do not have a
non-standard model. It is less clear whether there is a standard model of set
theory, although a countable model would certainly count as non-standard. The
Skolem paradox is that any first-order formulation of set theory, like ZF, due
to Zermelo and Fraenkel, has a countable model, while it seems to assert the
existence of non-countable sets. Many other important mathematical structures
cannot be characterized by a categorical set of first-order axioms, and thus
allow non-standard models. The
philosopher Putnam has argued that this fact has important implications
for the debate about realism in the philosophy of language. If axioms cannot
capture the spontaneity, liberty of standard model 875 875 “intuitive” notion of a set, what could?
Some of his detractors have pointed out that within second-order logic categorical
characterizations are often possible. But Putnam has objected that the intended
interpretation of second-order logic itself is not fixed by the use of the
formalism of second-order logic, where “use” is determined by the rules of
inference for second-order logic we know about. Moreover, categorical theories
are sometimes uninformative.
state, Grice: “I will use the phrase ‘state of the soul’ –
This may sound pedantic, and it is!” – “I will use ‘psychological state,’ where
the more correct phrase would be ‘state’ of the ‘soul,’ since theory – as in
‘-logical,’ has nothing to do with it. Now you’ll wonder if the soul has
states. A state of the soul – or a ‘frame of mind,’ as Strawson wrongly puts it
– is a physical state on which a ‘state’ of the soul supervenes, alla
Funcionalism” – “Note that a ’state’ of the soul may be quite specific and
involving other states, like the belief that Strawson’s dog is shaggy.” – “A
state is anything that follows a ‘that’-clause; the way an object or system
basically is; the fundamental, intrinsic properties of an object or system, and
the basis of its other properties. An instantaneous state is a state at a given
time. State variables are constituents of a state whose values may vary with
time. In classical or Newtonian mechanics the instantaneous state of an
n-particle system consists of the positions and momenta masses multiplied by
velocities of the n particles at a given time. Other mechanical properties are
functions of those in states. Fundamental and derived properties are often,
though possibly misleadingly, called observables. The set of a system’s
possible states can be represented as an abstract phase space or state space,
with dimensions or coordinates for the components of each state variable. In
quantum theory, states do not fix the particular values of observables, only
the probabilities of observables assuming particular values in particular
measurement situations. For positivism or instrumentalism, specifying a quantum
state does nothing more than provide a means for calculating such
probabilities. For realism, it does more
e.g., it refers to the basis of a quantum system’s probabilistic
dispositions or propensities. Vectors in Hilbert spaces represent possible
states, and Hermitian operators on vectors represent observables.
state of
affairs: Grice: “My poor friend D. F.
Pears got himself into a lot of trouble by offering to correct C. K. Ogden’s
passe translation of Vitters’s Tractatus!” a possibility, actuality, or
impossibility of the kind expressed by a nominalization of a declarative
sentence. The declarative sentence ‘This die comes up six’ can be nominalized
either through the construction ‘that this die comes up six’ or through the
likes of ‘this die’s coming up six’. The resulting nominalizations might be
interpreted as naming corresponding propositions or states of affairs. States
of affairs come in several varieties. Some are possible states of affairs, or
possibilities. Consider the possibility of a certain die coming up six when
rolled next. This possibility is a state of affairs, as is its
“complement” the die’s not coming up six
when rolled next. There is in addition the state of affairs which conjoins that
die’s coming up six with its not coming up six. And this contradictory state of
affairs is of course not a possibility, not a possible state of affairs.
Moreover, for every actual state of affairs there is a non-actual one, its
complement. For every proposition there is hence a state of affairs: possible
or impossible, actual or not. Indeed some consider propositions to be states of
affairs. Some take facts to be actual states of affairs, while others prefer to
define them as true propositions. If propositions are states of affairs, then
facts are of course both actual states of affairs and true propositions. In a
very broad sense, events are just possible states of affairs; in a narrower
sense they are contingent states of affairs; and in a still narrower sense they
are contingent and particular states of affairs, involving just the exemplification
of an nadic property by a sequence of individuals of length n. In a yet
narrower sense events are only those particular and contingent states of
affairs that entail change. A baseball’s remaining round throughout a certain
period does not count as an event in this narrower sense but only as a state of
that baseball, unlike the event of its being hit by a certain bat.
statistics: Grice: “I shall use the singular, ‘statistic’” -- statistical explanation. Grice: “Jill
says, “Jack is an Englishman; he is, therefore, brave.” Is the validty of her
reasoning based on statistics?” -- an explanation expressed in an explanatory
argument containing premises and conclusions making claims about statistical
probabilities. These arguments include deductions of less general from more
general laws and differ from other such explanations only insofar as the
contents of the laws imply claims about statistical probability. Most
philosophical discussion in the latter half of the twentieth century has
focused on statistical explanation of events rather than laws. This type of
argument was discussed by Ernest Nagel The Structure of Science, 1 under the
rubric “probabilistic explanation,” and by Hempel Aspects of Scientific Explanation,
5 as “inductive statistical” explanation. The explanans contains a statement
asserting that a given system responds in one of several ways specified by a
sample space of possible outcomes on a trial or experiment of some type, and
that the statistical probability of an event represented by a set of points in
the sample space on the given kind of trial is also given for each such event.
Thus, the statement might assert that the statistical probability is near 1 of
the relative frequency r/n of heads in n tosses being close to the statistical
probability p of heads on a single toss, where the sample space consists of the
2n possible sequences of heads and tails in n tosses. Nagel and Hempel
understood such statistical probability statements to be covering laws, so that
inductive-statistical explanation and deductivenomological explanation of
events are two species of covering law explanation. The explanans also contains
a claim that an experiment of the kind mentioned in the statistical assumption has
taken place e.g., the coin has been tossed n times. The explanandum asserts
that an event of some kind has occurred e.g., the coin has landed heads
approximately r times in the n tosses. In many cases, the kind of experiment
can be described equivalently as an n-fold repetition of some other kind of
experiment as a thousandfold repetition of the tossing of a given coin or as
the implementation of the kind of trial thousand-fold tossing of the coin one
time. Hence, statistical explanation of events can always be construed as
deriving conclusions about “single cases” from assumptions about statistical
probabilities even when the concern is to explain mass phenomena. Yet, many
authors controversially contrast statistical explanation in quantum mechanics, which
is alleged to require a singlecase propensity interpretation of statistical
probability, with statistical explanation in statistical mechanics, genetics,
and the social sciences, which allegedly calls for a frequency interpretation.
The structure of the explanatory argument of such statistical explanation has
the form of a direct inference from assumptions about statistical probabilities
and the kind of experiment trial which has taken place to the outcome. One
controversial aspect of direct inference is the problem of the reference class.
Since the early nineteenth century, statistical probability has been understood
to be relative to the way the experiment or trial is described. Authors like J.
Venn, Peirce, R. A. Fisher, and Reichenbach, among many others, have been
concerned with how to decide on which kind of trial to base a direct inference
when the trial under investigation is correctly describable in several ways and
the statistical probabilities of possible outcomes may differ relative to the different
sorts of descriptions. The most comprehensive discussion of this problem of the
reference class is found in the work of H. E. Kyburg e.g., Probability and the
Logic of Rational Belief, 1. Hempel acknowledged its importance as an
“epistemic ambiguity” in inductive statistical explanation. Controversy also
arises concerning inductive acceptance. May the conclusion of an explanatory
direct inference be a judgment as to the subjective probability that the
outcome event occurred? May a judgment that the outcome event occurred is
inductively “accepted” be made? Is some other mode of assessing the claim about
the outcome appropriate? Hempel’s discussion of the “nonconjunctiveness of
inductivestatistical” explanation derives from Kyburg’s earlier account of direct
inference where high probability is assumed to be sufficient for acceptance.
Non-conjunctiveness has been avoided by abandoning the sufficiency of high
probability I. Levi, Gambling with Truth, 7 or by denying that direct inference
in inductive-statistical explanation involves inductive acceptance at all R. C.
Jeffrey, “Statistical Explanation vs. Statistical Inference,” in Essays in
Honor of C. G. Hempel. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Jack and Jill.”
steiner: Austrian spiritualist and founder of anthroposophy.
Trained as a scientist, he edited Goethe’s scientific writings and prepared the
standard edition of his complete works from 9 to 6. Steiner’s major work, Die
Philosophie der Freiheit, was published in 4. His Friedrich Nietzsche: Ein
Kämpfer gegen seine Zeit 5 was tr. in 0 by Margaret deRis as Friedrich
Nietzsche: Fighter for Freedom. Steiner taught at a workingmen’s and edited a literary journal, Magazin für
Literatur, in Berlin. In 1 he embraced a spiritualism which emphasized a form
of knowledge that transcended sensory experience and was attained by the
“higher self.” He held that man had previously been attuned to spiritual
processes by virtue of a dreamlike state of consciousness, but was diverted
from this consciousness by preoccupation with material entities. Through
training, individuals could retrieve their innate capacity to perceive a
spiritual realm. Steiner’s writings on this theme are The Philosophy of
Spiritual Activity 4, Occult Science: An Outline 3, On the Riddle of Man 6, and
On the Riddles of the Soul 7. His last work was his autobiography 4. To advance
his teachings, he founded the Anthroposophical Society 2 and a school of
“spiritual science” called the Goetheanum near Basel, Switzerland. His work
inspired the Waldorf School movement, which comprises some eighty schools for
children. The anthroposophy movement he established remains active in Europe
and the United States. G.J.S. Stephen, Sir Leslie 18324, English literary
critic, editor, intellectual historian, and philosopher. He was the first chief
editor of the great Dictionary of National Biography, writing hundreds of the
entries himself. Brought up in an intensely religious household, he lost his
faith and spent much of his time trying to construct a moral and intellectual
outlook to replace it. His main works in intellectual history, the two-volume
History of English Thought in the Eighteenth Century 1876 and the three-volume
English Utilitarians 0, were undertaken as part of this project. So was his one
purely philosophical work, the Science of Ethics 2, in which he tried to
develop an evolutionary theory of morality. Stephen was impatient of
philosophical technicalities. Hence his treatise on ethics does very little to
resolve the problems some of them
pointed out to him by his friend Henry Sidgwick
with evolutionary ethics, and does not get beyond the several other
works on the subject published during this period. His histories of thought are
sometimes superficial, and their focus of interest is not ours; but they are
still useful because of their scope and the massive scholarship they put to
use. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Steiner and
moi.”
stillingfleet: English divine and controversialist who first made
his name with “Irenicum,” using natural-law doctrines to oppose religious
sectarianism. His “Origines Sacrae” ostensibly on the superiority of the
Scriptural record over other forms of ancient history, was for its day a
learned study in the moral certainty of historical evidence, the authority of
testimony, and the credibility of miracles. In drawing eclectically on
philosophy from antiquity to the Cambridge Platonists, he was much influenced
by the Cartesian theory of ideas, but later repudiated Cartesianism for its
mechanist tendency. For three decades he pamphleteered on behalf of the moral
certainty of orthodox Protestant belief against what he considered the beliefs
“contrary to reason” of Roman Catholicism. This led to controversy with
Unitarian and deist writers who argued that mysteries like the Trinity were
equally contrary to “clear and distinct” ideas. He was alarmed at the use made
of Locke’s “new,” i.e. nonCartesian, way of ideas by John Toland in Christianity
not Mysterious, and devoted his last years to challenging Locke to prove his
orthodoxy. The debate was largely over the concepts of substance, essence, and
person, and of faith and certainty. Locke gave no quarter in the public
controversy, but in the fourth edition of his Essay he silently amended some
passages that had provoked Stillingfleet.
schmidt: stirner, Max, pseudonym of Kasper Schmidt, philosopher
who proposed a theory of radical individualism. Born in Bayreuth, he taught in
Gymnasiums and later at a Berlin academy for women. He tr. what became a
standard G. version of Smith’s Wealth of Nations and contributed articles to
the Rhenische Zeitung. His most important work was statistical probability, “Der
Einzige und sein Eigenthum,” tr. by Steven T. Byington as The Ego and His Own,
and Grice as “The idiot and his idiocy.” -- His second book was “Die Geschichte
der Reaktion.” Schmidt is in reaction to Hegel and was for a time associated
with the left Hegelians. He stressed the priority of will and instinct over
reason and proposed a radical anarchic individualism. Each individual is
unique, and the independent ego is the fundamental value and reality. Stirner
attacks the state, religious ideas, and abstractions such as “humanity” as
“spectres” that are deceptive illusions, remnants of erroneous
hypostatizations. His defense of egoism is such that the individual is
considered to have no obligations or duties, and especially not to the state.
Encouraging an individual “rebellion” against state domination and control,
Stirner attracted a following among nineteenthand twentieth-century anarchists.
The sole goal of life is the cultivation of “uniqueness” or “ownness.” Engels
and Marx attack his ideas at length under the rubric “Saint Marx” in The G.
Ideology. Insofar as his theory of radical individualism offers no clearly
stated ethical requirements, it has been characterized as a form of nihilistic
egoism. Refs.: H. P. Grice: “Schmidt, or the idiot and his idiocy.”
sttochasis: stochastic process –“"pertaining
to conjecture," from Greek stokhastikos "able to guess,
conjecturing," from stokhazesthai "to guess, aim at,
conjecture," from stokhos "a guess, aim, fixed target, erected pillar
for archers to shoot at," perhaps from PIE *stogh-, variant of root
*stegh- "to stick, prick, sting." The sense of "randomly
determined" is from 1934, from German stochastik (1917). a process
that evolves, as time goes by, according to a probabilistic principle rather
than a deterministic principle. Such processes are also called random
processes, but ‘stochastic’ does not imply complete disorderliness. The
principle of evolution governing a stochastic or random process is precise,
though probabilistic, in form. For example, suppose some process unfolds in
discrete successive stages. And suppose that given any initial sequence of
stages, S1, S2, . . . , Sn, there is a precise probability that the next stage
Sn+1 will be state S, a precise probability that it will be SH, and so on for
all possible continuations of the sequence of states. These probabilities are
called transition probabilities. An evolving sequence of this kind is called a
discrete-time stochastic process, or discrete-time random process. A theoretically
important special case occurs when transition probabilities depend only on the
latest stage in the sequence of stages. When an evolving process has this
property it is called a discrete-time Markov process. A simple example of a
discrete-time Markov process is the behavior of a person who keeps taking
either a step forward or a step back according to whether a coin falls heads or
tails; the probabilistic principle of movement is always applied to the
person’s most recent position. The successive stages of a stochastic process
need not be discrete. If they are continuous, they constitute a
“continuous-time” stochastic or random process. The mathematical theory of
stochastic processes has many applications in science and technology. The
evolution of epidemics, the process of soil erosion, and the spread of cracks
in metals have all been given plausible models as stochastic processes, to
mention just a few areas of research. H.
P. Grice, “Stochastic implicatum.”
stoa – stoa --
Stoicus: stoicism -- Neo-stoicism -- du Vair, Guillaume, philosopher, bishop,
and political figure. Du Vair and Justus Lipsius were the two most influential
propagators of neo-Stoicism in early modern Europe. Du Vair’s Sainte
Philosophie “Holy Philosophy,” 1584 and his shorter Philosophie morale des
Stoïques “Moral Philosophy of the Stoics,” 1585, were tr. and frequently
reprinted. The latter presents Epictetus in a form usable by ordinary people in
troubled times. We are to follow nature and live according to reason; we are
not to be upset by what we cannot control; virtue is the good. Du Vair inserts,
moreover, a distinctly religious note. We must be pious, accept our lot as
God’s will, and consider morality obedience to his command. Du Vair thus
Christianized Stoicism, making it widely acceptable. By teaching that reason
alone enables us to know how we ought to live, he became a founder of modern
rationalism in ethics. Stōĭcus , a, um, adj., =
Στωϊκός, I.of or belonging to the Stoic philosophy or to the Stoics, Stoic:
“schola,” Cic. Fam. 9, 22 fin.: “secta,” Sen. Ep. 123, 14: “sententia,” id. ib.
22, 7: “libelli,” Hor. Epod. 8, 15: “turba,” Mart. 7, 69, 4: “dogmata,” Juv.
13, 121: “disciplina,” Gell. 19, 1, 1: “Stoicum est,” it is a saying of the
Stoics, Cic. Ac. 2, 26, 85: “non loquor tecum Stoicā linguā, sed hac
submissiore,” Sen. Ep. 13, 4: “est aliquid in illo Stoici dei: nec cor nec
caput habet,” Sen. Apoc. 8.— Subst.: Stōĭcus , i, m., a Stoic philosopher, a
Stoic, Cic. Par. praef. § 2; Hor. S. 2, 3, 160; 2, 3, 300; plur., Cic. Mur. 29,
61; and in philosophical writings saepissime.— 2. Stōĭca , ōrum, n. plur., the
Stoic philosophy, Cic. N. D. 1, 6, 15.—Adv.: Stōĭcē , like a Stoic, Stoically:
“agere austere et Stoice,” Cic. Mur. 35, 74: dicere, id. Par. praef. § 3.H.
P. Grice, “The Stoa: from Athenian to Oxonian dialectic,” H. P. Grice, “The
Stoa and Athenian dialectic.” H. P.
Grice: “The Stoa and Athenian dialectic.” -- stoicism, one of the three leading
movements constituting Hellenistic philosophy. Its founder was Zeno of Citium,
who was succeeded as school head by Cleanthes. But the third head, Chrysippus,
was its greatest exponent and most voluminous writer. These three are the
leading representatives of Early Stoicism. No work by any early Stoic survives
intact, except Cleanthes’ short “Hymn to Zeus.” Otherwise we are dependent on
doxography, on isolated quotations, and on secondary sources, most of them
hostile. Nevertheless, a remarkably coherent account of the system can be
assembled. The Stoic world is an ideally good organism, all of whose parts
interact for the benefit of the whole. It is imbued with divine reason logos,
its entire development providentially ordained by fate and repeated identically
from one world phase to the next in a never-ending cycle, each phase ending
with a conflagration ekpyrosis. Only bodies strictly “exist” and can interact.
Body is infinitely divisible, and contains no void. At the lowest level, the
world is analyzed into an active principle, god, and a passive principle,
matter, both probably corporeal. Out of these are generated, at a higher level,
the four elements air, fire, earth, and water, whose own interaction is
analogous to that of god and matter: air and fire, severally or conjointly, are
an active rational force called breath Grecian pneuma, Latin spiritus, while
earth and water constitute the passive substrate on which these act, totally
interpenetrating each other thanks to the non-particulate structure of body and
its capacity to be mixed “through and through.” Most physical analysis is
conducted at this higher level, and pneuma becomes a key concept in physics and
biology. A thing’s qualities are constituted by its pneuma, which has the
additional role of giving it cohestochastic process Stoicism 879 879 sion and thus an essential identity. In
inanimate objects this unifying pneuma is called a hexis state; in plants it is
called physis nature; and in animals “soul.” Even qualities of soul, e.g.
justice, are portions of pneuma, and they too are therefore bodies: only thus
could they have their evident causal efficacy. Four incorporeals are admitted:
place, void which surrounds the world, time, and lekta see below; these do not
strictly “exist” they lack the corporeal
power of interaction but as items with
some objective standing in the world they are, at least, “somethings.”
Universals, identified with Plato’s Forms, are treated as concepts ennoemata,
convenient fictions that do not even earn the status of “somethings.” Stoic
ethics is founded on the principle that only virtue is good, only vice bad.
Other things conventionally assigned a value are “indifferent” adiaphora,
although some, e.g., health, wealth, and honor, are naturally “preferred”
proegmena, while their opposites are “dispreferred” apoproegmena. Even though
their possession is irrelevant to happiness, from birth these indifferents
serve as the appropriate subject matter of our choices, each correct choice
being a “proper function” kathekon not
yet a morally good act, but a step toward our eventual end telos of “living in
accordance with nature.” As we develop our rationality, the appropriate choices
become more complex, less intuitive. For example, it may sometimes be more in
accordance with nature’s plan to sacrifice your wealth or health, in which case
it becomes your “proper function” to do so. You have a specific role to play in
the world plan, and moral progress prokope consists in learning it. This
progress involves widening your natural “affinity” oikeiosis: an initial
concern for yourself and your parts is later extended to those close to you,
and eventually to all mankind. That is the Stoic route toward justice. However,
justice and the other virtues are actually found only in the sage, an idealized
perfectly rational person totally in tune with the divine cosmic plan. The
Stoics doubted whether any sages existed, although there was a tendency to
treat at least Socrates as having been one. The sage is totally good, everyone
else totally bad, on the paradoxical Stoic principle that all sins are equal.
The sage’s actions, however similar externally to mere “proper functions,” have
an entirely distinct character: they are renamed ‘right actions’ katorthomata.
Acting purely from “right reason,” he is distinguished by his “freedom from
passion” apatheia: morally wrong impulses, or passions, are at root
intellectual errors of mistaking what is indifferent for good or bad, whereas
the sage’s evaluations are always correct. The sage alone is happy and truly
free, living in perfect harmony with the divine plan. All human lives are
predetermined by the providentially designed, all-embracing causal nexus of
fate; yet being the principal causes of their actions, the good and the bad
alike are responsible for them: determinism and morality are fully compatible.
Stoic epistemology defends the existence of cognitive certainty against the
attacks of the New Academy. Belief is described as assent synkatathesis to an
impression phantasia, i.e. taking as true the propositional content of some
perceptual or reflective impression. Certainty comes through the “cognitive
impression” phantasia kataleptike, a self-certifying perceptual representation
of external fact, claimed to be commonplace. Out of sets of such impressions we
acquire generic conceptions prolepseis and become rational. The highest
intellectual state, knowledge episteme, in which all cognitions become mutually
supporting and hence “unshakable by reason,” is the prerogative of the wise.
Everyone else is in a state of mere opinion doxa or of ignorance. Nevertheless,
the cognitive impression serves as a “criterion of truth” for all. A further
important criterion is prolepseis, also called common conceptions and common
notions koinai ennoiai, often appealed to in philosophical argument. Although
officially dependent on experience, they often sound more like innate
intuitions, purportedly indubitable. Stoic logic is propositional, by contrast
with Aristotle’s logic of terms. The basic unit is the simple proposition
axioma, the primary bearer of truth and falsehood. Syllogistic also employs
complex propositions conditional,
conjunctive, and disjunctive and rests
on five “indemonstrable” inference schemata to which others can be reduced with
the aid of four rules called themata. All these items belong to the class of
lekta “sayables” or “expressibles.”
Words are bodies vibrating portions of air, as are external objects, but
predicates like that expressed by ‘ . . . walks’, and the meanings of whole
sentences, e.g., ‘Socrates walks’, are incorporeal lekta. The structure and
content of both thoughts and sentences are analyzed by mapping them onto lekta,
but the lekta are themselves causally inert. Conventionally, a second phase of
the school is distinguished as Middle Stoicism. It developed largely at Rhodes
under Panaetius and Posidonius, both of whom influenced the presentation of
Stoicism in Cicero’s influential philosophical treatises mid-first century
B.C.. Panaetius Stoicism Stoicism 880
880 c.185c.110 softened some classical Stoic positions, his ethics being
more pragmatic and less concerned with the idealized sage. Posidonius c.135c.50
made Stoicism more open to Platonic and Aristotelian ideas, reviving Plato’s
inclusion of irrational components in the soul. A third phase, Roman Stoicism,
is the only Stoic era whose writings have survived in quantity. It is
represented especially by the younger Seneca A.D. c.165, Epictetus A.D.
c.55c.135, and Marcus Aurelius A.D. 12180. It continued the trend set by
Panaetius, with a strong primary focus on practical and personal ethics. Many prominent
Roman political figures were Stoics. After the second century A.D. Stoicism as
a system fell from prominence, but its terminology and concepts had by then
become an ineradicable part of ancient thought. Through the writings of Cicero
and Seneca, its impact on the moral and political thought of the Renaissance
was immense.
stoutianism: philosophical psychologist, astudent of Ward, he was
influenced by Herbart and especially Brentano. He influenced Grice to the point
that Grice called himself “a true Stoutian.” He was editor of Mind 20. He followed Ward in
rejecting associationism and sensationism, and proposing analysis of mind as
activity rather than passivity, consisting of acts of cognition, feeling, and
conation. Stout stressed attention as the essential function of mind, and
argued for the goal-directedness of all mental activity and behavior, greatly
influencing McDougall’s hormic psychology. He reinterpreted traditional associationist
ideas to emphasize primacy of mental activity; e.g., association by
contiguity a passive mechanical process
imposed on mind became association by
continuity of attentional interest. With Brentano, he argued that mental
representation involves “thought reference” to a real object known through the
representation that is itself the object of thought, like Locke’s “idea.” In
philosophy he was influenced by Moore and Russell. His major works are Analytic
Psychology 6 and Manual of Psychology 9.
strato: Grecian philosopher and polymath nicknamed “the
Physicist” for his innovative ideas in natural science. He succeeded
Theophrastus as head of the Lyceum. Earlier he served as royal tutor in
Alexandria, where his students included Aristarchus, who devised the first
heliocentric model. Of Strato’s many writings only fragments and summaries
survive. These show him criticizing the abstract conceptual analysis of earlier
theorists and paying closer attention to empirical evidence. Among his targets
were atomist arguments that motion is impossible unless there is void, and also
Aristotle’s thesis that matter is fully continuous. Strato argued that no large
void occurs in nature, but that matter is naturally porous, laced with tiny
pockets of void. His investigations of compression and suction were influential
in ancient physiology. In dynamics, he proposed that bodies have no property of
lightness but only more or less weight.
strawson: Grice’s tutee. b.9, London-born, Oxford-educated philosopher
who has made major contributions to logic, metaphysics, and the study of Kant.
His career has been mainly at Oxford (he spent a term in Wales and visited the
New World a lot), where he was the leading philosopher of his generation, due
to that famous tutor he had for his ‘logic paper’: H. P. Grice, at St. John’s. His
first important work, “On Referring” argues that Baron Russell’s theory of
descriptions fails to deal properly with the role of descriptions as “referring
expressions” because Russell assumed the “bogus trichotomy” that sentences are
true, false, or meaningless: for Strawson, sentences with empty descriptions
are meaningful but “neither true nor false” because the general presuppositions
governing the use of referring expressions are not fulfilled. One aspect of
this argument was Russell’s alleged insensitivity to the ordinary use of
definite descriptions. The contrast between the abstract schemata of formal
logic and the manifold richness of the inferences inherent in ordinary language
is the central theme of Strawson’s “ Introduction to Logical Theory,” where he
credits H. P. Grice for making him aware of ‘pragmatic rules’ of conversation –
Grice was amused that Baron Russell cared to respond to Strawson in “Mind” –
where Russell’s original “On denoting” had been published. Together, after a
joint seminar with Quine, Strawson submitted “In defense of a dogma,”
co-written with Grice – A year later Strawson submitted on Grice’s behalf
“Meaning” to the same journal – They participated with Pears in a Third programme
lecture, published by Pears in “The nature of metaphysics” (London,
Macmillan”). In Individuals, provocatively entitled “an essay in DESCRIPTIVE
(never revisionary) metaphysics,” Strawson, drawing “without crediting” on
joint seminars with Grice on Categories and De Interpretatione, Strawson reintroduced metaphysics as a respectable
philosophical discipline after decades of positivist rhetoric. But his project
is only “descriptive” metaphysics
elucidation of the basic features of our own conceptual scheme and his arguments are based on the philosophy
of language: “basic” particulars are those like “Grice” or his “cricket bat”,
which are basic objects of reference, and it is the spatiotemporal and sortal
conditions for their identification and reidentification by speakers that
constitute the basic categories. Three arguments are especially famous. First, even
in a purely auditory world objective reference on the basis of experience
requires at least an analogue of space. Second, because self-reference
presupposes reference to others, persons, conceived as bearers of both physical
and psychological properties, are a type of basic particular – cfr. Grice on
“Personal identity.” Third, “feature-placing” discourse, such as ‘it is snowing
here now’, is “the ultimate propositional level” through which reference to
particulars enters discourse. Strawson’s next book, The Bounds of Sense 6,
provides a critical reading of Kant’s theoretical philosophy. His aim is to
extricate what he sees as the profound truths concerning the presuppositions of
objective experience and judgment that Kant’s transcendental arguments
establish from the mysterious metaphysics of Kant’s transcendental idealism.
Strawson’s critics have argued, however, that the resulting position is unstable:
transcendental arguments can tell us only what we must suppose to be the case.
So if Kant’s idealism, which restricts such suppositions to things as they
appear to us, is abandoned, we can draw conclusions concerning the way the
world itself must be only if we add the verificationist thesis that ability to
make sense of such suppositions requires ability to verify them. In his next
book, Skepticism and Naturalism: Some Varieties 5, Strawson conceded this:
transcendental arguments belong within descriptive metaphysics and should not
be regarded as attempts to provide an external justification of our conceptual
scheme. In truth no such external justification is either possible or needed:
instead and here Strawson invokes Hume
rather than Kant our reasonings come to
an end in natural propensities for belief that are beyond question because they
alone make it possible to raise questions. In a famous earlier paper Strawson
had urged much the same point concerning the free will debate: defenders of our
ordinary attitudes of reproach and gratitude should not seek to ground them in
the “panicky metaphysics” of a supra-causal free will; instead they can and
need do no more than point to our unshakable commitment to these “reactive”
attitudes through which we manifest our attachment to that fundamental category
of our conceptual scheme persons.
strawsonise: verb invented by A. M. Kemmerling. To adopt
Strawson’s manoever in the analysis of ‘meaning.’ “A form of ‘disgricing,’” –
Kemmerling adds.
strawsonism – Grice’s favourite Strawsonisms were too
many to count. His first was Strawson on ‘true’ for ‘Analysis.’ Grice was
amazed by the rate of publishing in Strawson’s case. Strawson kept publishing
and Grice kept criticizing. In “Analysis,’ Strawson gives Grice his first
‘strawsonism’ “To say ‘true’ is ditto.’ The second strawsonism is that there is
such a thing as ‘ordinary language’ which is not Russellian. As Grice shows,
ordinary language IS Russellian. Strawson said that composing “In defence of a
dogma” was torture and that it is up to Strawson to finish the thing off. So there are a few strawonisms there, too.
Strawson had the courtesy never to reprint ‘In defence’ in any of his
compilations, and of course to have Grice as fist author. There are ‘strawsonisms’
in Grice’s second collaboration with Strawson – that Grice intentionally
ignores in “Life and opinions.” This is a transcript of the talk of the dynamic
trio: Grice, Pears, and Strawson, published three years later by Pears in “The
nature of metaphysics.” Strawson collaborated with “If and the horseshoe” to
PGRICE, but did not really write it for the occasion. It was an essay he had
drafted ages ago, and now saw fit to publish. He expands on this in his note on
Grice for the British Academy, and in his review of Grice’s compilation. Grice
makes an explicit mention of Strawson in a footnote in “Presupposition and
conversational implicaturum,” the euphemism he uses is ‘tribute’: the
refutation of Strawson’s truth-value gap as a metaphysical excrescence and
unnecessary is called a ‘tribute,’ coming from the tutor – “in this and other
fields,” implicating, “there may be mistakes all over the place.” Kemmerling
somewhat ignores Urmson when he says, “Don’t disgrice if you can grice.” To
strawsonise, for Kemmerling is to avoid Grice’s direct approach and ask for a
higher-level intention. To strawsonise is the first level of disgrice. But
Grice first quotes Urmson and refers to Stampe’s briddge example before he does
to Strawson’s rat-infested house example.
strawson’s
rat-infested house. Few in Grice’s
playgroup had Grice’s analytic skills. Only a few cared to join him in his
analysis of ‘mean.’ The first was Urmson with the ‘bribe.’ The second was
Strawson, with his rat-infested house. Grice re-writes Strawson’s alleged
counterexample. To deal with his own rat-infested house example, Strawson
proposes that the analysans of "U means that p" might be restricted
by the addition of a further condition, namely that the utterer U should utter
x not only, as already provided, with the intention that his addressee should
think that U intends to obtain a certain response from his addressee, but also
with the intention that his addressee should think (recognize) that U has the
intention just mentioned. In Strawson's example, in The Philosohical
Review (that Grice cites on WOW:x) repr. in his "Logico-Linguistic
Papers," the potential home buyer is intended to think that the realtor
wants him to think that the house is rat-infested. However, the potential house-buyer
is not intended by the realtor to think that he is intended to think that the
realtor wants him to think that the house is rat infested. The addressee is
intended to think that it is only as a result of being too clever for the
realtor that he has learned that the potential home buyer wants him
to think that the house is rat-infested; the potential home-buyer is to
think that he is supposed to take the artificially displayed dead
rat as a evidence that the house is rat infested. U wants to get A
to believe that the house A is thinking of buying is rat-infested. S decides
to· bring about this belief in A by taking into the house and letting loose a
big fat sewer rat. For S has the following scheme. He knows that A is
watching him and knows that A believes that S is unaware that he, A, is
watching him. It isS's intention that A should (wrongly) infer from the
fact that S let the rat loose that S did so with the intention that A should
arrive at the house, see the rat, and, taking the rat as "natural evidence",
infer therefrom that the house is rat-infested. S further intends A to realize
that given the nature of the rat's arrival, the existence of the rat cannot be
taken as genuine or natural evidence that the house is rat-infested; but S
kilows that A will believe that S would not so contrive to get A to believe the
house is rat-infested unless Shad very good reasons for thinking that it was,
and so S expects and intends A to infer that the house is rat-infested from the
fact that Sis letting the rat loose with the intention of getting A to believe
that the house is rat-infested. Thus S satisfies the conditions purported to be
necessary and sufficient for his meaning something by letting the rat loose: S
lets the rat loose intending (4) A to think that the house is rat-infested,
intending (1)-(3) A to infer from the fact that S let the rat loose that S did
so intending A to think that the house is rat-infested, and intending (5) A's
recognition of S's . intention (4) to function as his reason for thinking that
the house is rat-infested. But even though S's action meets these
conditions, Strawson feels that his scenario fits Grice's conditions in
Grice's reductive analysis and not yet Strawson's intuition about his own use
of 'communicate.' To minimise Strawson's discomfort, Grice brings an
anti-sneaky clause. ("Although I never shared Strawson's intuition about
his use of 'communicate;' in fact, I very rarely use 'communicate that...' To
exterminate the rats in Strawson's rat-infested house, Grice uses, as he should,
a general "anti-deception" clause. It may be that the use
of this exterminating procedure is possible. It may be that any
'backward-looking' clauses can be exterminated, and replaced by a general
prohibitive, or closure clause, forbidding an intention by the utterer to be
sneaky. It is a conceptual point that if you intend your addressee NOT TO
REALISE that p, you are not COMMUNICATING that p. (3A) (if) (3r)
(ic): (a) U utters x intending (I) A to think x possesses
f (2) A to thinkf correlated in way c with the type to which r
belongs (3) A to think, on the basis of the fulfillment of (I) and (3)
that U intends A to produce r (4) A, on the basis of the fulfillment of (3) to
produce r, and (b) There is no inference-element E such that U
intends both (I') A in his determination of r to rely on E (2') A to think Uto
intend (I') to be false. In the final version Grice reaches after considering
alleged counterexamples to the NECESSITY of some of the conditions in the
analysans, Grice reformulates. It is not the case that, for some inference
element E, U intends x to be such that anyone who
has φ both rely on E in coming to ψ, or think that U ψ-s, that p and think that (Ǝφ) U intends x to be
such that anyone who has φ come to ψ (or think that U ψ-s) that
p without relying on E. Embedded in the general definition. By uttering x,
U means that-ψb-dp ≡ (Ǝφ)(Ǝf)(Ǝc) U
utters x intending x to be such that anyone who
has φ think that x has f, f is correlated in way c
with ψ-ing that p, and (Ǝφ') U intends x to be such
that anyone who has φ' think, via thinking that x has
f and that f is correlated in way c with ψ-ing that p, that U ψ-s that
p, and in view of (Ǝφ') U intending x to be such
that anyone who has φ' think, via thinking that x has
f, and f is correlated in way c with ψ-ing that p, that U ψ-s that
p, U ψ-s that p, and, for some
substituends of ψb-d, U utters x
intending that, should there actually be anyone who
has φ, he will, via thinking in view of (Ǝφ') U
intending x to be such that anyone who has φ' think, via thinking
that x has f, and f is correlated in way c with ψ-ing that p, that U ψ-s that p, U ψ-s that
p himself ψ that p, and it is not
the case that, for some inference element E, U intends x to be such
that anyone who has φ both rely on E in coming to ψ, or think that U ψ-s, that p and think that (Ǝφ) U intends x to be
such that anyone who has φ come to ψ (or think that U ψ-s) that
p without relying on E,
strozzi: Important Italian
philosopher, especially influential at what Grice called Italy’s Oxford, i. e.
Firenze – “Palla Strozzi was more a mentor than a philosopher, but I would
consider him both a Grecian and Griceian in spirit.” -- Luigi
Speranza, "Grice e Strozzi -- Grecian, Griceian," per il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
structuratum: mid-15c.,
"action or process of building or construction;" 1610s, "that
which is constructed, a building or edifice;" from Latin structura "a
fitting together, adjustment; a building, mode of building;" figuratively,
"arrangement, order," from structus, past participle of struere
"to pile, place together, heap up; build, assemble, arrange, make by
joining together," related to strues "heap," from PIE *streu-,
extended form of root *stere- "to spread.” structuralism, a
distinctive yet extremely wide range of productive research conducted in the
social and human sciences from the 0s through the 0s, principally in France. It
is difficult to describe structuralism as a movement, because of the
methodological constraints exercised by the various disciplines that came to be
influenced by structuralism e.g.,
anthropology, philosophy, literary theory, psychoanalysis, political theory,
even mathematics. Nonetheless, structuralism is generally held to derive its
organizing principles from the early twentieth-century work of Saussure, the
founder of structural linguistics. Arguing against the prevailing historicist
and philological approaches to linguistics, he proposed a “scientific” model of
language, one understood as a closed system of elements and rules that account
for the production and the social communication of meaning. Inspired by
Durkheim’s notion of a “social fact”
that domain of objectivity wherein the psychological and the social
orders converge Saussure viewed language
as the repository of discursive signs shared by a given linguistic community.
The particular sign is composed of two elements, a phonemic signifier, or
distinctive sound element, and a corresponding meaning, or signified element.
The defining relation between the sign’s sound and meaning components is held
to be arbitrary, i.e., based on conventional association, and not due to any
function of the speaking subject’s personal inclination, or to any external
consideration of reference. What lends specificity or identity to each
particular signifier is its differential relation to the other signifiers in
the greater set; hence, each basic unit of language is itself the product of
differences between other elements within the system. This principle of
differential and structural relation was extended by Troubetzkoy to the
order of phonemes, whereby a defining set of vocalic differences underlies the
constitution of all linguistic phonemes. Finally, for Saussure, the closed set
of signs is governed by a system of grammatical, phonemic, and syntactic rules.
Language thus derives its significance from its own autonomous organization,
and this serves to guarantee its communicative function. Since language is the
foremost instance of social sign systems in general, the structural account
might serve as an exemplary model for understanding the very intelligibility of
social systems as such hence, its
obvious relevance to the broader concerns of the social and human sciences.
This implication was raised by Saussure himself, in his Course on General Linguistics6,
but it was advanced dramatically by the
anthropologist Claude Lévi-Strauss
who is generally acknowledged to be the founder of modern structuralism in his extensive analyses in the area of
social anthropology, beginning with his Elementary Structures of Kinship 9.
Lévi-Strauss argued that society is itself organized according to one form or
another of significant communication and exchange whether this be of information, knowledge, or
myths, or even of its members themselves. The organization of social phenomena
could thus be clarified through a detailed elaboration of their subtending
structures, which, collectively, testify to a deeper and all-inclusive, social
rationality. As with the analysis of language, these social structures would be
disclosed, not by direct observation, but by inference and deduction from the
observed empirical data. Furthermore, since these structures are models of
specific relations, which in turn express the differential properties of the
component elements under investigation, the structural analysis is both readily
formalizable and susceptible to a broad variety of applications. In Britain,
e.g., Edmund Leach pursued these analyses in the domain of social anthropology;
in the United States, Chomsky applied insights of structuralism to linguistic
theory and philosophy of mind; in Italy, Eco conducted extensive structuralist
analyses in the fields of social and literary semiotics. With its
acknowledgment that language is a rule-governed social system of signs, and that
effective communication depends on the resources available to the speaker from
within the codes of language itself, the structuralist approach tends to be
less preoccupied with the more traditional considerations of “subjectivity” and
“history” in its treatment of meaningful discourse. In the post-structuralism
that grew out of this approach, the
philosopher Foucault, e.g., focused on the generation of the “subject”
by the various epistemic discourses of imitation and representation, as well as
on the institutional roles of knowledge and power in producing and conserving
particular “disciplines” in the natural and social sciences. These disciplines,
Foucault suggested, in turn govern our theoretical and practical notions of
madness, criminality, punishment, sexuality, etc., notions that collectively
serve to “normalize” the individual subject to their determinations. Likewise,
in the domain of psychoanalysis, Lacan drew on the work of Saussure and
Lévi-Strauss to emphasize Freud’s concern with language and to argue that, as a
set of determining codes, language serves to structure the subject’s very
unconscious. Problematically, however, it is the very dynamism of language,
including metaphor, metonymy, condensation, displacement, etc., that introduces
the social symbolic into the constitution of the subject. Althusser applied the
principles of structuralist methodology to his analysis of Marxism, especially
the role played by contradiction in understanding infrastructural and
superstructural formation, i.e., for the constitution of the historical
dialectic. His account followed Marx’s rejection of Feuerbach, at once denying
the role of traditional subjectivity and humanism, and presenting a
“scientific” analysis of “historical materialism,” one that would be anti-historicist
in principle but attentive to the actual political state of affairs. For
Althusser, such a philosophical analysis helped provide an “objective”
discernment to the historical transformation of social reality. The restraint
the structuralists extended toward the traditional views of subjectivity and
history dramatically colored their treatment both of the individuals who are
agents of meaningful discourse and of the linguistically articulable object
field in general. This redirection of research interests particularly in
France, due to the influential work of Barthes and Michel Serres in the fields
of poetics, cultural semiotics, and communication theory has resulted in a
series of original analyses and also provoked lively debates between the adherents
of structuralist methodology and the more conventionally oriented schools of
thought e.g., phenomenology, existentialism, Marxism, and empiricist and
positivist philosophies of science. These debates served as an agency to open
up subsequent discussions on deconstruction and postmodernist theory for the
philosophical generation of the 0s and later. These post-structuralist thinkers
were perhaps less concerned with the organization of social phenomena than with
their initial constitution and subsequent dynamics. Hence, the problematics of
the subject and history or, in broader
terms, temporality itself were again
engaged. The new discussions were abetted by a more critical appraisal of
language and tended to be antiHegelian in their rejection of the totalizing
tendency of systematic metaphysics. Heidegger’s critique of traditional
metaphysics was one of the major influences in the discussions following
structuralism, as was the reexamination of Nietzsche’s earlier accounts of
“genealogy,” his antiessentialism, and his teaching of a dynamic “will to
power.” Additionally, many poststructuralist philosophers stressed the Freudian
notions of the libido and the unconscious as determining factors in
understanding not only the subject, but the deep rhetorical and affective
components of language use. An astonishing variety of philosophers and critics
engaged in the debates initially framed by the structuralist thinkers of the
period, and their extended responses and critical reappraisals formed the
vibrant, poststructuralist period of
intellectual life. Such figures as Ricoeur, Emmanuel Levinas, Kristeva,
Maurice Blanchot, Derrida, Gilles Deleuze, Félix Guattari, Lyotard, Jean
Baudrillard, Philippe LacoueLabarthe, Jean-Luc Nancy, and Irigaray inaugurated
a series of contemporary reflections that have become international in scope. Refs.:
H. P. Grice, “The structure of structure.” .
sub-perceptual -- subdoxastic, pertaining to states of
mind postulated to account for the production and character of certain
apparently non-inferential beliefs. These were first discussed by Stephen P.
Stich in “Beliefs and Subdoxastic States” 8. I may form the belief that you are
depressed, e.g., on the basis of subtle cues that I am unable to articulate.
The psychological mechanism responsible for this belief might be thought to
harbor information concerning these cues subdoxastically. Although subdoxastic
states resemble beliefs in certain respects
they incorporate intentional content, they guide behavior, they can
bestow justification on beliefs they
differ from fullyfledged doxastic states or beliefs in at least two respects.
First, as noted above, subdoxastic states may be largely inaccessible to
introspection; I may be unable to describe, even on reflection, the basis of my
belief that you are depressed. Second, subdoxastic states seem cut off
inferentially from an agent’s corpus of beliefs; my subdoxastic appreciation
that your forehead is creased may contribute to my believing that you are
depressed, but, unlike the belief that your forehead is creased, it need not,
in the presence of other beliefs, lead to further beliefs about your visage.
subiectum: sub-iectum – sub-iectificatio -- subjectification: Grice
is right in distinguishing this from nominalization, because not all
nominalization takes the subject position. Grice plays with this. It is a
derivation of the ‘subjectum,’ which Grice knows it is Aristotelian. Liddell
and Scott have the verb first, and the neuter singular later. “τὸ ὑποκείμενον,”
Liddell and Scott note “has three main applications.” The first is “to the
matter (hyle) which underlies the form (eidos), as opp. To both “εἶδος” and
“ἐντελέχεια” Met. 983a30; second, to the substantia (hyle + morphe) which
underlies the accidents, and as opposed to “πάθη,” and “συμβεβηκότα,” as in
Cat. 1a20,27 and Met.1037b16, 983b16; third, and this is the use that
‘linguistic’ turn Grice and Strawson are interested in, “to the logical subject
to which attributes are ascribed,” and here opp. “τὸ κατηγορούμενον,” (which would
be the ‘praedicatum’), as per Cat.1b10,21, Ph.189a31. If Grice uses Kiparsky’s
factive, he is also using ‘nominalisation’ as grammarians use it. Refs.: Grice,
“Reply to Richards,” in PGRICE, also BANC. subjectivism: When Grice speaks of
the subjective condition on intention, he is using ‘subject,’ in a way a
philosophical psychologist would. He does not mean Kant’s transcendental
subject or ego. Grice means the simpler empiricist subject, personal identity,
or self. The choice is unfelicitious in that ‘subject’ contrasts with ‘object.’
So when he speaks of a ‘subjective’ person he means an ‘ego-centric’ condition,
or a self-oriented condition, or an agent-oriented condition, or an
‘utterer-oriented’ or ‘utterer-relative’ condition. But this is tricky. His
example: “Nixon should get that chair of theology.” The utterer may have to put
into Nixon’s shoes. He has to perceive Nixon as a PERSON, a rational agent,
with views of his own. So, the philosophical psychologist that Grice is has to
think of a conception of the self by the self, and the conception of the other
by the self. Wisdom used to talk of ‘other minds;’ Grice might speak of other
souls. Grice was concerned with intending folloed by a that-clause. Jeffrey
defines desirability as doxastically modified. It is entirely possible for
someone to desire the love that he already has. It is what he thinks that
matters. Cf. his dispositional account to intending. A Subjectsive
condition takes into account the intenders, rather than the ascribers, point of
view: Marmaduke Bloggs intends to climb Mt. Everest on hands and knees.
Bloggs might reason: Given my present state, I should do what is
fun. Given my present state, the best thing for me to do would be to do
what is fun. For me in my present state it would make for my well-being,
to have fun. Having fun is good, or, a good. Climbing a mountain would be
fun. Climbing the Everest would be/make for climbing fun. So, I shall
climb the Everest. Even if a critic insisted that a practical syllogism is
the way to represent Bloggs finding something to be appealing, and that it
should be regarded as a respectable evaluation, the assembled propositions dont
do the work of a standard argument. The premises do not support or yield the
conclusion as in a standard argument. The premises may be said to yield the
conclusion, or directive, for the particular agent whose reasoning process it
is, only on the basis of a Subjectsive condition: that the agent is in a
certain Subjectsive state, e.g. feels like going out for dinner-fun. Rational
beings (the agent at some other time, or other individuals) who do not have
that feeling, will not accept the conclusion. They may well accept as true. It
is fun to climb Everest, but will not accept it as a directive unless they feel
like it now. Someone wondering what to do for the summer might think that if he
were to climb Everest he would find it fun or pleasant, but right now she does
not feel like it. That is in general the end of the matter. The alleged
argument lacks normativity. It is not authoritative or directive unless there
is a supportive argument that he needs/ought to do something diverting/pleasant
in the summer. A practical argument is different. Even if an agent did not feel
like going to the doctor, an agent would think I ought to have a medical check
up yearly, now is the time, so I should see my doctor to be a directive with
some force. It articulates a practical argument. Perhaps the strongest
attempt to reconstruct an (acceptable or rational) thought
transition as a standard arguments is to treat the Subjectsive
condition, I feel like having climbing fun in the summer, as a premise, for
then the premises would support the conclusion. But the individual, whose
thought transition we are examining, does not regard a description of his
psychological state as a consideration that supports the conclusion. It
will be useful to look more closely at a variant of the example to note when it
is appropriate to reconstruct thinking in the form of argument. Bloggs,
now hiking with a friend in the Everest, comes to a difficult spot and
says: I dont like the look of that, I am frightened. I am going back. That
is usually enough for Bloggs to return, and for the friend to turn back with
him. Bloggss action of turning back, admittedly motivated by fear, is, while
not acting on reasons, nonetheless rational unless we judge his fear to be
irrational. Bloggss Subjectsive condition can serve as a
premise, but only in a very different situation. Bloggs resorts to reasons.
Suppose that, while his friend does not think Bloggss fear irrational, the
friend still attempts to dissuade Bloggs from going back. After listening and
reflecting, Bloggs may say I am so frightened it is not worth it. I am not
enjoying this climbing anymore. Or I am too frightened to be able to safely go
on. Or I often climb the Everest and dont usually get frightened. The fact that
I am now is a good indication that this is a dangerous trail and I should turn
back. These are reasons, considerations implicitly backed by principles, and
they could be the initial motivations of someone. But in Bloggss case they
emerged when he was challenged by his friend. They do not express his initial
practical reasoning. Bloggs was frightened by the trail ahead, wanted to go
back, and didnt have any reason not to. Note that there is no general
rational requirement to always act on reasons, and no general truth that a
rational individual would be better off the more often he acted on
reasons. Faced with his friends objections, however, Bloggs needed
justification for acting on his fear. He reflected and found reason(s) to act on
his fear. Grice plays with Subjectsivity already in Prolegomena. Consider the
use of carefully. Surely we must include the agents own idea of this. Or
consider the use of phi and phi – surely we dont want the addressee to regard
himself under the same guise with which the utterer regards him. Or consider “Aspects”:
Nixon must be appointed professor of theology at Oxford. Does he feel the need?
Grice raises the topic of Subjectsivity again in the Kant lectures just after
his discussion of mode, in a sub-section entitled, Modalities: relative and
absolute. He finds the topic central for his æqui-vocality thesis: Subjectsive
conditions seem necessary to both practical and alethic considerations. Refs.:
The source is his essay on intentions and the subjective condition, The H. P. Grice
Papers, BANC. The subject: hypokeimenon -- When Frege turned from ‘term logic’
to ‘predicate logic’ “he didn’t know what he was doing.” Cf. Oxonian
nominalization. Grice plays a lot on that. His presentation at the Oxford
Philosophical Society he entitled, in a very English way, as “Meaning” (echoing
Ogden and Richards). With his “Meaning, Revisited,” it seems more clearly that
he is nominalizing. Unless he means, “The essay “Meaning,” revisited,” – alla
Putnam making a bad joke on Ogden: “The meaning of ‘meaning’” – “ ‘Meaning,’
revisited” -- Grice is very familiar
with this since it’s the literal transliteration of Aristotle’s hypokeimenon,
opp. in a specific context, to the ‘prae-dicatum,’ or categoroumenon. And with
the same sort of ‘ambiguity,’ qua opposite a category of expression, thought,
or reality. In philosophical circles, one has to be especially aware of the
subject-object distinction (which belong in philosophical psychology) and the
thing which belongs in ontology. Of course there’s the substance (hypousia,
substantia), the essence, and the sumbebekon, accidens. So one has to be
careful. Grice expands on Strawson’s explorations here. Philosophy, to
underlie, as the foundation in which something else inheres, to be implied or
presupposed by something else, “ἑκάστῳ τῶν ὀνομάτων . . ὑ. τις ἴδιος οὐσία”
Pl.Prt.349b, cf. Cra.422d, R.581c, Ti.Locr.97e: τὸ ὑποκείμενον has three main
applications: (1) to the matter which underlies the form, opp. εἶδος,
ἐντελέχεια, Arist.Metaph.983a30; (2) to the substance (matter + form) which
underlies the accidents, opp. πάθη, συμβεβηκότα, Id.Cat.1a20,27,
Metaph.1037b16, 983b16; (3) to the logical subject to which attributes are
ascribed, opp. τὸ κατηγορούμενον, Id.Cat.1b10,21, Ph.189a31: applications (1)
and (2) are distinguished in Id.Metaph.1038b5, 1029a1-5, 1042a26-31: τὸ ὑ. is
occasionally used of what underlies or is presupposed in some other way, e. g.
of the positive termini presupposed by change, Id.Ph.225a3-7. b. exist, τὸ
ἐκτὸς ὑποκείμενον the external reality, Stoic.2.48, cf. Epicur.Ep.1pp.12,24 U.;
“φῶς εἶναι τὸ χρῶμα τοῖς ὑ. ἐπιπῖπτον” Aristarch. Sam. ap. Placit.1.15.5; “τὸ
κρῖνον τί τε φαίνεται μόνον καὶ τί σὺν τῷ φαίνεσθαι ἔτι καὶ κατ᾽ ἀλήθειαν
ὑπόκειται” S.E.M.7.143, cf. 83,90,91, 10.240; = ὑπάρχω, τὰ ὑποκείμενα πράγματα
the existing state of affairs, Plb.11.28.2, cf. 11.29.1, 15.8.11,13, 3.31.6,
Eun.VSp.474 B.; “Τίτος ἐξ ὑποκειμένων ἐνίκα, χρώμενος ὁπλις μοῖς καὶ τάξεσιν
αἷς παρέλαβε” Plu.Comp.Phil.Flam.2; “τῆς αὐτῆς δυνάμεως ὑποκειμένης” Id.2.336b;
“ἐχομένου τοῦ προσιόντος λόγου ὡς πρὸς τὸν ὑποκείμενον” A.D.Synt.122.17. c. ὁ
ὑ. ἐνιαυτός the year in question, D.S.11.75; οἱ ὑ. καιροί the time in question,
Id.16.40, Plb.2.63.6, cf. Plu.Comp.Sol.Publ.4; τοῦ ὑ. μηνός the current month,
PTeb.14.14 (ii B. C.), al.; ἐκ τοῦ ὑ. φόρου in return for a reduction from the
said rent, PCair.Zen.649.18 (iii B. C.); πρὸς τὸ ὑ. νόει according to the
context, Gp.6.11.7. Note that both Grice and Strawson oppose Quine’s Humeian
dogma that, since the subjectum is beyond comprehension, we can do with a
‘predicate’ calculus, only. Vide Strawson, “Subject and predicate in logic and
grammar.” Refs: H. P. Grice, Work on the categories with P. F. Strawson, The H.
P. Grice Papers, BANC MSS 90/135c.
sub-ordination. Grice must be the only Oxonian
philosopher in postwar Oxford that realised the relevance of subordination.
Following J. C. Wilson, Grice notes that ‘if’ is a subordinating connective,
and the only one of the connectives which is not commutative. This gives Grice
the idea to consult Cook Wilson and develop his view of ‘interrogative
subordination.’ Who killed Cock Robin. If it was not the Hawk, it was the
Sparrow. It was not the Hawk. It was the Sparrow. What Grecian idiom is
Romanesque sub-ordinatio translating. The opposite is co-ordination. “And” and
“or” are coordinative particles. Interrogative coordination is provided by
‘or,’ but it relates to yes/no questions. Interrogative subordination involves
x-question. WHO killed Cock Robin. The Grecians were syntactic and hypotactic.
Varro uses jungendi. is the same and wherefrom it is different, in relation to
what &c." It may well be doubted whether he has thus improved upon his
predecessors. Surely the discernment of sameness and difference is a function
necessarily belonging to soul and necessarily included in the catalogue of her
functions : yet Stallbaum's rendering excludes it from that catalogue. The fact
that we have ory hv $, not orcp ecri, does not really favour his view—"
with whatsoever a thing may be the same, she declares it the same.' I coincide
then with the other interpreters in regarding the whole sentence from orw t' hv
as indirect INTERROGATION SUBORDINATE interrogation subordinateto \iyeiThis
mistake in logic carries with it serious mistakes in trans lation. The clause
otw t av ti tovtov rj kcu otov hv erepov is made an indirect INTERROGATIVE
COORDINATE with itpbs o tC re pu£Aio-ra xai ottt? [ 39 ] k.t.\., which is
impossible. Stallbaum rightly makes the clause a substantive clause and subject
of elvai or £vp.f}aivei elvai. (3) eKao-ra is of course predicate with elvai to
this sthe question, ‘How many sugars would Tom like in his tea?’ is not
‘satisfied’ by the answer ‘Tom loves sugar’. It may well be true that Tom loves
sugar, but the question is not satisfied by that form of answer. Conversely the
answer ‘one spoonful’ satisfies the question, even though it might be the wrong
answer and leave the tea insufficiently sugary for the satisfaction of Tom’s
sweet tooth.
sub-perceptum: This relates to Stich and his sub-doxastic. For
Aristotle, “De An.,” the anima leads to the desideratum. Unlike in ‘phuta,’ or
vegetables, which are still ‘alive,’ (‘zoa’ – he had a problem with ‘sponges’
which were IN-animate, to him, most likely) In WoW:139, Grice refers to “the
pillar box seems red” as “SUB-PERCEPTUAL,” the first of a trio. The second is
the perceptual, “A perceives that the pillar box is red,” and the third, “The
pillar box is red.” He wishes to explore the truth-conditons of the
subperceptum, and although first in the list, is last in the analsysis. Grice
proposes: ‘The pillar box seems red” iff (1) the pillar box is red; (2) A
perceives that the pillar box is red; and (3) (1) causes (2). In this there is
a parallelism with his quasi-causal account of ‘know’ (and his caveat that
‘literally,’ we may just know that 2 + 2 = 4 (and such) (“Meaning Revisited). In
what he calls ‘accented sub-perceptum,’ the idea is that the U is choosing the
superceptum (“seems”) as opposed to his other obvious choices (“The pillar box
IS red,”) and the passive-voice version of the ‘perceptum’: “The pillar box IS
PERCEIVED red.” The ‘accent’ generates the D-or-D implicaturum: By uttering
“The pillar box seems red,” U IMPLICATES that it is denied that or doubted that
the pillar box is perceived red by U or that the pillar box is red. In this,
the accented version contrasts with the unaccented version where the implicaturum
is NOT generated, and the U remains uncommitted re: this doubt or denial implicaturum.
It is this uncommitment that will allow to disimplicate or cancel the implicaturum
should occasion arise. The reference Grice makes between the sub-perceptum and
the perceptum is grammatical, not psychological. Or else he may be meaning that
in uttering, “I perceive that the pillar box is red,” one needs to appeal to
Kant’s apperception of the ego. Refs.: Pecocke, Sense and content, Grice, BANC.
subscriptum: Quine thought that Grice’s subscript device was
otiose, and that he would rather use brackets, or nothing, any day. Grice plays with various roots of ‘scriptum.’
He was bound to. Moore had showed that ‘good’ was not ‘descriptive.’ Grice
thinks it’s pseudo-descriptive. So here we have the first, ‘descriptum,’ where
what is meant is Griceian: By uttering the “The cat is on the mat” U means, by
his act of describing, that the cat is on the mat. Then there’s the
‘prae-scriptum.’ Oddly, Grice, when criticizing the ‘descriptive’ fallacy,
seldom mentions the co-relative ‘prescriptum.’ “Good” would be understood in
terms of a ‘prae-scriptum’ that appeals to his utterer’s intentions. Then
there’s the subscriptum. This may have various use, both in Grice. “I
subscribe,” and in the case of “Pegasus flies.” Where the utterer subscribes to
his ontological commitment. subscript device. Why does Grice think we NEED a
subscript device? Obviously, his wife would not use it. I mean, you cannot
pronounce a subscript device or a square-bracket device. So his point is
ironic. “Ordinary” language does not need it. But if Strawson and Quine are
going to be picky about stuff – ontological commitment, ‘existential
presupposition,’ let’s subscribe and bracket! Note that Quine’s response to
Grice is perfunctory: “Brackets would have done!” Grice considers a quartet of
utterances: Jack wants someone to marry him; Jack wants someone or
other to marry him; Jack wants a particular person to marry him,
and There is someone whom Jack wants to marry him.Grice notes that
there are clearly at least two possible readings of an utterance
like our (i): a first reading in which, as Grice puts it, (i) might be
paraphrased by (ii). A second reading is one in which it might be
paraphrased by (iii) or by (iv). Grice goes on to symbolize the
phenomenon in his own version of a first-order predicate calculus. Ja wants
that p becomes Wjap where ja stands for the individual constant Jack
as a super-script attached to the predicate standing for Jacks psychological
state or attitude. Grice writes: Using the apparatus of classical predicate
logic, we might hope to represent, respectively, the external reading and the
internal reading (involving an intentio secunda or intentio
obliqua) as (Ǝx)WjaFxja and Wja(Ǝx)Fxja. Grice then
goes on to discuss a slightly more complex, or oblique, scenario involving this
second internal reading, which is the one that interests us, as it involves an
intentio seconda.Grice notes: But suppose that Jack wants a specific
individual, Jill, to marry him, and this because Jack has been deceived
into thinking that his friend Joe has a highly delectable sister called Jill,
though in fact Joe is an only child. The Jill Jack eventually goes up the hill
with is, coincidentally, another Jill, possibly existent. Let us
recall that Grices main focus of the whole essay is, as the title goes,
emptiness! In these circumstances, one is inclined to say that (i) is true only on
reading (vii), where the existential quantifier occurs within the
scope of the psychological-state or -attitude verb, but we cannot now
represent (ii) or (iii), with Jill being vacuous, by (vi), where the
existential quantifier (Ǝx) occurs outside the scope of the
psychological-attitude verb, want, since [well,] Jill does not really
exist, except as a figment of Jacks imagination. In a manoeuver that I
interpret as purely intentionalist, and thus favouring by far Suppess over
Chomskys characterisation of Grice as a mere behaviourist, Grice hopes that
we should be provided with distinct representations
for two familiar readings of, now: Jack wants Jill to marry him and
Jack wants Jill to marry him. It is at this point that Grice applies a
syntactic scope notation involving sub-scripted numerals, (ix) and (x),
where the numeric values merely indicate the order of introduction of the
symbol to which it is attached in a deductive schema for the predicate calculus
in question. Only the first formulation represents the internal reading (where
ji stands for Jill): W2ja4F1ji3ja4 and
W3ja4F2ji1ja4. Note
that in the second formulation, the individual constant for Jill, ji, is
introduced prior to want, – jis sub-script is 1, while Ws sub-script is the
higher numerical value 3. Grice notes: Given that Jill does not exist, only the
internal reading can be true, or alethically satisfactory. Grice sums up
his reflections on the representation of the opaqueness of a verb standing for
a psychological state or attitude like that expressed by wanting with one
observation that further marks him as an intentionalist, almost of a Meinongian
type. He is willing to allow for existential phrases in cases of vacuous
designata, provided they occur within opaque psychological-state or attitude
verbs, and he thinks that by doing this, he is being faithful to the richness and
exuberance of ordinary discourse, while keeping Quine happy. As Grice puts
it, we should also have available to us also three neutral, yet distinct,
(Ǝx)-quantificational forms (together with their isomorphs), as a philosopher
who thinks that Wittgenstein denies a distinction, craves for a generality!
Jill now becomes x. W4ja5Ǝx3F1x2ja5, Ǝx5W2ja5F1x4ja3, Ǝx5W3ja4F1x2ja4. As Grice
notes, since in (xii) the individual variable x (ranging over Jill) does not
dominate the segment following the (Ǝx) quantifier, the formulation does not
display any existential or de re, force, and is suitable therefore for
representing the internal readings (ii) or (iii), if we have to allow, as we do
have, if we want to faithfully represent ordinary discourse, for the possibility
of expressing the fact that a particular person, Jill, does not actually exist.
stupid. Grice loved Plato. They are considering
‘horseness.’ “I cannot see horeseness; I can see horses.” “You are the epitome
of stupidity.” “I cannot see stupidity. I see stupid.”
sub-gestum -- suggestio falsi – suggest. To suggest is
like to ‘insinuate,’ only different. The root involves a favourite with Grice,
‘a gesture.’ That gesture is very suggesture. Grice explores hint versus
suggest in Retrospective epilogue. Also cited by Strawson and Wiggins. The
emissor’s implication is exactly this suggestio, for which suggestum. To suggest, advise, prompt, offer, bring to mind: “quoties aequitas restitutionem suggerit,” Dig. 4,
6, 26 fin.; cf.: “quae (res) suggerit, ut Italicarum rerum esse credantur eae res,” reminds, admonishes, ib. 28, 5, 35 fin.: “quaedam de republicā,” Aur. Vict. Vir. Ill. 66, 2. — Absol.: “suggerente conjuge,” at the instigation of, Aur. Vict. Epit. 41, 11; cf.: “suggerente irā,” id. ib. 12, 10 suggestio falsi. Pl. suggestiones
falsi. [mod.L., = suggestion of what is false.] A misrepresentation
of the truth whereby something incorrect is implied to be true; an indirect
lie. Often in contexts with suppressio veri. QUOTES: 1815 H.
Maddock Princ. & Pract. Chancery I. 208 Whenever Suppressio veri or
Suggestio falsi occur..they afford a sufficient ground for setting aside any
Release or Conveyance. 1855 Newspaper & Gen. Reader's Pocket
Compan. i.4 He was bound to say that the suppressio veri on that occasion
approached very nearly to a positive suggestio falsi. 1898 Kipling
Stalky & Co. (1899) 36 It seems..that they had held back material
facts; that they were guilty both of suppressio veri and suggestio falsi.
1907 W. de Morgan Alice-for-Short xxxvi. 389 That's suppressio veri
and suggestio falsi! Besides, it's fibs! 1962 J. Wilson Public
Schools & Private Practice i. 19 It is rare to find a positively
verifiable untruth in a school brochure: but it is equally rare not to find a
great many suggestiones falsi, particularly as regards the material comfort and
facilities available. 1980 D. Newsome On Edge of Paradise 7 There
are undoubted cases of suppressio veri; on the other hand, he appears to eschew
suggestio falsi. --- Fibs indeed. Suppress, suggest. Write:
"Griceland, Inc." "Yes, I agree to become a Doctor
in Gricean Studies" EXAM QUESTION: 1. Discuss suggestio
falsi in terms of detachability. 2. Compare suppresio veri and suggestion
falsi in connection with "The king of France is bald" uttered during
Napoleon's time. 3. Invent things for 'suppressio falsi' and 'suggestio
veri'. 4. No. You cannot go to the bathroom.
sub-gestum --
suggestum: not necesarilyy ‘falsi.’
The verb is ‘to suggest that…’ which is diaphanous. Note that the ‘su-‘ stands
for ‘sub-‘ which conveys the implicitness or covertness of the impicatum.
Indirectness. It’s ‘under,’ not ‘above’ board.’ To suggest, advise, prompt,
offer, bring to mind: “quoties aequitas restitutionem suggerit,” Dig. 4, 6, 26
fin.; cf.: “quae (res) suggerit, ut Italicarum rerum esse credantur eae res,”
reminds, admonishes, ib. 28, 5, 35 fin.: “quaedam de republicā,” Aur. Vict.
Vir. Ill. 66, 2. — Absol.: “suggerente conjuge,” at the instigation of, Aur.
Vict. Epit. 41, 11; cf.: “suggerente irā,” id. ib. 12, 10.— The implicaturum is
a suggestum – ALWAYS cancellable. Or not? Sometimes not, if ‘reasonable,’ but
not ‘rational.’ Jill suggests that Jack is brave when she says, “He is an
Englishman, he is; therefore, brave.” The tommy suggests that her povery
contrasts with her honesty (“’Tis the same the whole world over.”) So the
‘suggestum’ is like the implicaturum. A particular suggesta are ‘conversational
suggestum.’ For Grice this is philosophically important, because many
philosophical adages cover ‘suggesta’ which are not part of the philosopher’s
import! Vide Holdcroft, “Some forms of indirect communication.”
sub-pressum
-- suppresum veri: This is a bit like
an act of omission – about which Urmson once asked, “Is that ‘to do,’ Grice?” –
Strictly, it is implicatural. “Smith has a beautiful handwriting.” Grice’s
abductum: “He must be suppressing some ‘veri,’ but surely the ‘suggestio falsi’
is cancellable. On the other hand, my abent-minded uncle, who ‘suppresses,’ is
not ‘implicating.’ The ‘suppressio’ has to be ‘intentional,’ as an ‘omission’
is. Since for the Romans, the ‘verum’ applied to a unity (alethic/practical)
this was good. No multiplication, but unity – cf. untranslatable (think) –
modality ‘the ‘must’, neutral – desideratum-doxa – think – Yes, when
Untranslatable discuss ‘vero’ they do say it applies to ‘factual’ and
sincerity, I think. At Collections, the expectation is that Grice gives a
report on the philosopher’s ability – not on
his handwriting. It is different when Grice applied to St. John’s. “He
doesn’t return library books.” G. Richardson. Why did he use this on two
occasions? In “Prolegomena,” he uses it for his desideratum of conversational
fortitude (“make a strong conversational move”). To suppress. suggestio falsi. Pl.
suggestiones falsi. [mod.L., = suggestion of what is false.] A
misrepresentation of the truth whereby something incorrect is implied to be
true; an indirect lie. Often in contexts with suppressio veri.
QUOTES: 1815 H. Maddock Princ. & Pract. Chancery I. 208
Whenever Suppressio veri or Suggestio falsi occur..they afford a sufficient
ground for setting aside any Release or Conveyance. 1855 Newspaper
& Gen. Reader's Pocket Compan. i.4 He was bound to say that the
suppressio veri on that occasion approached very nearly to a positive suggestio
falsi. 1898 Kipling Stalky & Co. (1899) 36 It seems..that
they had held back material facts; that they were guilty both of suppressio
veri and suggestio falsi. 1907 W. de Morgan Alice-for-Short xxxvi.
389 That's suppressio veri and suggestio falsi! Besides, it's
fibs! 1962 J. Wilson Public Schools & Private Practice i.
19 It is rare to find a positively verifiable untruth in a school
brochure: but it is equally rare not to find a great many suggestiones falsi,
particularly as regards the material comfort and facilities available.
1980 D. Newsome On Edge of Paradise 7 There are undoubted cases of
suppressio veri; on the other hand, he appears to eschew suggestio falsi.
--- Fibs indeed. Suppress, suggest. Write: "Griceland,
Inc." "Yes, I agree to become a Doctor in Gricean
Studies" EXAM QUESTION: 1. Discuss suggestio falsi in
terms of detachability. 2. Compare suppresio veri and suggestion falsi in
connection with "The king of France is bald" uttered during
Napoleon's time. 3. Invent things for 'suppressio falsi' and 'suggestio
veri'. 4. No. You cannot go to the bathroom.
super-knowing. In WoW. A notion Grice detested. Grice,
“I detest superknowing.” “For that reason, I propose a closure clause – for a
communicatum to count as one, there should not be any sneaky intention.” The
use of ‘super’ is Plotinian. If God is super-good, he is not good. If someobody
superknows, he doesn’t know. This is an implicaturum. Surely it is cancellable:
“God is supergood; therefore, He is good.” “Smith superknows that p; therefore,
Smith, as per a semantic entailment, knows that p.” Grice: “The implicature arise
out of the postulate of conversational fortitude: why stop at knowing if you
can claim that Smith superknows? Why say that God is love, when He is
super-love?”
subjectum – Grecian hypokeimenon – Grice’s ‘implying,’
qua nominalization, is a category shift, a subjectification, or
objectificiation. – We have ‘employ,’ ‘imply,’ and then ‘implication,’
‘implicature, and ‘implying’ Using the participles, we have the active voice
present implicans, the active voice future, implicaturum, and the passive perfect
‘impicatum.’ subjectivism, any philosophical view that attempts to understand
in a subjective manner what at first glance would seem to be a class of
judgments that are objectively either true or false i.e., true or false independently of what we
believe, want, or hope. There are two ways of being a subjectivist. In the
first way, one can say that the judgments in question, despite first
appearances, are really judgments about our own attitudes, beliefs, emotions,
etc. In the second way, one can deny that the judgments are true or false at
all, arguing instead that they are disguised commands or expressions of
attitudes. In ethics, for example, a subjective view of the second sort is that
moral judgments are simply expressions of our positive and negative attitudes.
This is emotivism. Prescriptivism is also a subjective view of the second sort;
it is the view that moral judgments are really commands to say “X is good” is to say, details aside,
“Do X.” Views that make morality ultimately a matter of conventions or what we
or most people agree to can also be construed as subjective theories, albeit of
the first type. Subjectivism is not limited to ethics, however. According to a
subjective view of epistemic rationality, the standards of rational belief are the
standards that the individual or perhaps most members in the individual’s
community would approve of insofar as they are interested in believing those
propositions that are true and not believing those propositions that are false.
Similarly, phenomenalists can be regarded as proposing a subjective account of
material object statements, since according to them, such statements are best
understood as complex statements about the course of our experiences.
subiectum-obiectum-abiectumm-exiectum
quartet, the: Grice: subject-object
dichotomy, the distinction between thinkers and what they think about. The
distinction is not exclusive, since subjects can also be objects, as in
reflexive self-conscious thought, which takes the subject as its intended
object. The dichotomy also need not be an exhaustive distinction in the strong
sense that everything is either a subject or an object, since in a logically
possible world in which there are no thinkers, there may yet be
mind-independent things that are neither subjects nor objects. Whether there
are non-thinking things that are not objects of thought in the actual world
depends on whether or not it is sufficient in logic to intend every individual
thing by such thoughts and expressions as ‘We can think of everything that
exists’. The dichotomy is an interimplicative distinction between thinkers and
what they think about, in which each presupposes the other. If there are no
subjects, then neither are there objects in the true sense, and conversely. A
subjectobject dichotomy is acknowledged in most Western philosophical
traditions, but emphasized especially in Continental philosophy, beginning with
Kant, and carrying through idealist thought in Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, and
Schopenhauer. It is also prominent in intentionalist philosophy, in the
empirical psychology of Brentano, the object theory of Meinong, Ernst Mally, and
Twardowski, and the transcendental phenomenology of Husserl. Subjectobject
dichotomy is denied by certain mysticisms, renounced as the philosophical
fiction of duality, of which Cartesian mindbody dualism is a particular
instance, and criticized by mystics as a confusion that prevents mind from
recognizing its essential oneness with the world, thereby contributing to
unnecessary intellectual and moral dilemmas.
sublime: sub-lime, neuter. sublīmie (collat.
form sublīmus , a, um: ex sublimo vertice, Cic. poët. Tusc. 2, 7, 19; Enn. ap.
Non. 169; Att. and Sall. ib. 489, 8 sq.; Lucr. 1, 340), adj. etym. dub.; perh.
sub-limen, up to the lintel; cf. sublimen (sublimem est in altitudinem elatum,
Fest. p. 306 Müll.), I.uplifted, high, lofty, exalted, elevated (mostly poet.
and in postAug. prose; not in Cic. or Cæs.; syn.: editus, arduus, celsus,
altus). I. Lit. A. In gen., high, lofty: “hic vertex nobis semper sublimis,”
Verg. G. 1, 242; cf. Hor. C. 1, 1, 36: “montis cacumen,” Ov. M. 1, 666:
“tectum,” id. ib. 14, 752: “columna,” id. ib. 2, 1: “atrium,” Hor. C. 3, 1, 46:
“arcus (Iridis),” Plin. 2, 59, 60, § 151: “portae,” Verg. A. 12, 133: “nemus,”
Luc. 3, 86 et saep.: os, directed upwards (opp. to pronus), Ov. M. 1, 85; cf.
id. ib. 15, 673; Hor. A. P. 457: “flagellum,” uplifted, id. C. 3, 26, 11:
“armenta,” Col. 3, 8: “currus,” Liv. 28, 9.—Comp.: “quanto sublimior Atlas
Omnibus in Libyā sit montibus,” Juv. 11, 24.—Sup.: “triumphans in illo
sublimissimo curru,” Tert. Apol. 33.— B. Esp., borne aloft, uplifted, elevated,
raised: “rapite sublimem foras,” Plaut. Mil. 5, 1: “sublimem aliquem rapere
(arripere, auferre, ferre),” id. As. 5, 2, 18; id. Men. 5, 7, 3; 5, 7, 6; 5, 7,
13; 5, 8, 3; Ter. And. 5, 2, 20; id. Ad. 3, 2, 18; Verg. A. 5, 255; 11, 722 (in
all these passages others read sublimen, q. v.); Ov. M 4, 363 al.: “campi armis
sublimibus ardent,” borne aloft, lofty, Verg. A. 11, 602: sublimes in equis
redeunt, id. ib. 7, 285: “apparet liquido sublimis in aëre Nisus,” id. G. 1,
404; cf.: “ipsa (Venus) Paphum sublimis abit,” on high through the air, id. A.
1, 415: “sublimis abit,” Liv. 1, 16; 1, 34: “vehitur,” Ov. M. 5, 648 al.— C. On
high, lofty, in a high position: “tenuem texens sublimis aranea telum,” Cat.
68, 49: “juvenem sublimem stramine ponunt,” Verg. A. 11, 67: “sedens solio
sublimis avito,” Ov. M. 6, 650: “Tyrio jaceat sublimis in ostro,” id. H. 12,
179.— D. Subst.: sublīme , is, n., height; sometimes to be rendered the air:
“piro per lusum in sublime jactato,” Suet. Claud. 27; so, in sublime, Auct. B.
Afr. 84, 1; Plin. 10, 38, 54, § 112; 31, 6, 31, § 57: “per sublime volantes
grues,” id. 18, 35, 87, § 362: “in sublimi posita facies Dianae,” id. 36, 5, 4,
§ 13: “ex sublimi devoluti,” id. 27, 12, 105, § 129.—Plur.: “antiquique memor
metuit sublimia casus,” Ov. M. 8, 259: “per maria ac terras sublimaque caeli,”
Lucr. 1, 340.— II. Trop., lofty, exalted, eminent, distinguished. A. In gen.:
“antiqui reges ac sublimes viri,” Varr. R. R. 2, 4, 9; cf. Luc. 10, 378:
“mens,” Ov. P. 3, 3, 103: “pectora,” id. F. 1, 301: “nomen,” id. Tr. 4, 10,
121: “sublimis, cupidusque et amata relinquere pernix,” aspiring, Hor. A. P.
165; cf.: “nil parvum sapias et adhuc sublimia cures,” id. Ep. 1, 12,
15.—Comp.: “quā claritate nihil in rebus humanis sublimius duco,” Plin. 22, 5,
5, § 10; Juv. 8, 232.—Sup.: “sancimus supponi duos sublimissimos judices,” Cod.
Just. 7, 62, 39.— B. In partic., of language, lofty, elevated, sublime (freq. in
Quint.): “sublimia carmina,” Juv. 7, 28: “verbum,” Quint. 8, 3, 18: “clara et
sublimia verba,” id. ib.: “oratio,” id. 8, 3, 74: “genus dicendi,” id. 11, 1,
3: “actio (opp. causae summissae),” id. 11, 3, 153: “si quis sublimia humilibus
misceat,” id. 8, 3, 60 et saep.—Transf., of orators, poets, etc.: “natura
sublimis et acer,” Hor. Ep. 2, 1, 165: “sublimis et gravis et grandiloquus
(Aeschylus),” Quint. 10, 1, 66: “Trachalus plerumque sublimis,” id. 10, 1,
119.—Comp.: “sublimior gravitas Sophoclis,” Quint. 10, 1, 68: “sublimius
aliquid,” id. 8, 3, 14: “jam sublimius illud pro Archiā, Saxa atque solitudines
voci respondent,” id. 8, 3, 75.—Hence, advv. 1. Lit., aloft, loftily, on high.
(α). Form sub-līmĭter (rare ): “stare,” upright, Cato, R. R. 70, 2; so id. ib.
71: “volitare,” Col. 8, 11, 1: “munitur locus,” id. 8, 15, 1.— (β). Form
sub-līme (class. ): “Theodori nihil interest, humine an sublime putescat,” Cic.
Tusc. 1, 43, 102; cf.: “scuta, quae fuerant sublime fixa, sunt humi inventa,”
id. Div. 2, 31, 67: “volare,” Lucr. 2, 206; 6, 97: “ferri,” Cic. Tusc. 1, 17,
40; id. N. D. 2, 39, 101; 2, 56, 141 Orell. N. cr.: “elati,” Liv. 21, 30:
“expulsa,” Verg. G. 1, 320 et saep.— b. Comp.: “sublimius altum Attollit
caput,” Ov. Hal. 69.— 2. Trop., of speech, in a lofty manner, loftily (very
rare): “alia sublimius, alia gravius esse dicenda,” Quint. 9, 4, 130. Grice’s
favoured translation of Grecian ‘hypsos’ -- a feeling brought about by objects
that are infinitely large or vast such as the heavens or the ocean or
overwhelmingly powerful such as a raging torrent, huge mountains, or
precipices. The former in Kant’s terminology is the mathematically sublime and
the latter the dynamically sublime. Though the experience of the sublime is to
an important extent unpleasant, it is also accompanied by a certain pleasure:
we enjoy the feeling of being overwhelmed. On Kant’s view, this pleasure
results from an awareness that we have powers of reason that are not dependent
on sensation, but that legislate over sense. The sublime thus displays both the
limitations of sense experience and hence our feeling of displeasure and the
power of our own mind and hence the feeling of pleasure. The sublime was an
especially important concept in the aesthetic theory of the eighteenth and
nineteenth centuries. Reflection on it was stimulated by the appearance of a
translation of Longinus’s Peri hypsous On the Sublime in 1674. The “postmodern
sublime” has in addition emerged in late twentieth century thought as a basis
for raising questions about art. Whereas beauty is associated with that whose
form can be apprehended, the sublime is associated with the formless, that
which is “unpresentable” in sensation. Thus, it is connected with critiques of
“the aesthetic” understood as that which
is sensuously present as a way of
understanding what is important about art. It has also been given a political
reading, where the sublime connects with resistance to rule, and beauty
connects with conservative acceptance of existing forms or structures of
society.
subsidiarium: sub-sidiarium -- subsidiarity, a basic principle of
social order and the common good governing the relations between the higher and
lower associations in a political community. Positively, the principle of
subsidiarity holds that the common good, i.e., the ensemble of social resources
and institutions that facilitate human self-realization, depends on fostering
the free, creative initiatives of individuals and of their voluntary
associations; thus, the state, in addition to its direct role in maintaining
public good which comprises justice, public peace, and public morality also has
an indirect role in promoting other aspects of the common good by rendering
assistance subsidium to those individuals and associations whose activities
facilitate cooperative human self-realization in work, play, the arts,
sciences, and religion. Negatively, the principle of subsidiarity holds that
higher-level i.e., more comprehensive associations while they must monitor, regulate, and
coordinate ought not to absorb, replace,
or undermine the free initiatives and activities of lower-level associations
and individuals insofar as these are not contrary to the common good. This
presumption favoring free individual and social initiative has been defended on
various grounds, such as the inefficiency of burdening the state with myriad
local concerns, as well as the corresponding efficiency of unleashing the free,
creative potential of subordinate groups and individuals who build up the
shared economic, scientific, and artistic resources of society. But the deeper
ground for this presumption is the view subjunctive conditional subsidiarity
886 886 that human flourishing depends
crucially on freedom for individual self-direction and for the self-government
of voluntary associations and that human beings flourish best through their own
personal and cooperative initiatives rather than as the passive consumers or beneficiaries
of the initiatives of others.
subsistum: sub-sistum -- subsistence translation of G. Bestand,
in current philosophy, especially Meinong’s system, the kind of being that
belongs to “ideal” objects such as mathematical objects, states of affairs, and
abstractions like similarity and difference. By contrast, the kind of being
that belongs to “real” wirklich objects, things of the sorts investigated by
the sciences other than psychology and pure mathematics, is called existence
Existenz. Existence and subsistence together exhaust the realm of being Sein.
So, e.g., the subsistent ideal figures whose properties are investigated by
geometers do not exist they are nowhere
to be found in the real world but it is
no less true of them that they have being than it is of an existent physical
object: there are such figures. Being does not, however, exhaust the realm of
objects or things. The psychological phenomenon of intentionality shows that
there are in some sense of ‘there are’ objects that neither exist nor subsist.
Every intentional state is directed toward an object. Although one may covet
the Hope Diamond or desire the unification of Europe, one may also covet a
non-existent material object or desire a non-subsistent state of affairs. If
one covets a non-existent diamond, there is in some sense of ‘there is’
something that one covets one’s state of
mind has an object and it has certain
properties: it is, e.g., a diamond. It may therefore be said to inhabit the
realm of Sosein ‘being thus’ or ‘predication’ or ‘having properties’, which is
the category comprising the totality of objects. Objects that do not have any
sort of being, either existence or subsistence, belong to non-being Nichtsein.
In general, the properties of an object do not determine whether it has being
or non-being. But there are special cases: the round square, by its very
nature, cannot subsist. Meinong thus maintains that objecthood is ausserseiend,
i.e., independent of both existence and subsistence.
substratum: sub-statum: hypoeinai, hypostasis, hypokemeinon -- substantia
– Grice: “The Romans never felt the need for the word ‘substantia’ but trust
Cicero to force them to use it!” -- Grice lectured on this with J. L. Austin
and P. F. Strawson. hypousia -- as defined by Aristotle in the Categories, that
which is neither predicable “sayable” of anything nor present in anything as an
aspect or property of it. The examples he gives are an individual man and an
individual horse. We can predicate being a horse of something but not a horse;
nor is a horse in something else. He also held that only substances can remain
self-identical through change. All other things are accidents of substances and
exist only as aspects, properties, or relations of substances, or kinds of
substances, which Aristotle called secondary substances. An example of an
accident would be the color of an individual man, and an example of a secondary
substance would be his being a man. For Locke, a substance is that part of an
individual thing in which its properties inhere. Since we can observe, indeed
know, only a thing’s properties, its substance is unknowable. Locke’s sense is
obviously rooted in Aristotle’s but the latter carries no skeptical
implications. In fact, Locke’s sense is closer in meaning to what Aristotle
calls matter, and would be better regarded as a synonym of ‘substratum’, as
indeed it is by Locke. Substance may also be conceived as that which is capable
of existing independently of anything else. This sense is also rooted in
Aristotle’s, but, understood quite strictly, leads to Spinoza’s view that there
can be only one substance, namely, the totality of reality or God. A fourth
sense of ‘substance’ is the common, ordinary sense, ‘what a thing is made of’.
This sense is related to Locke’s, but lacks the latter’s skeptical
implications. It also corresponds to what Aristotle meant by matter, at least
proximate matter, e.g., the bronze of a bronze statue Aristotle analyzes
individual things as composites of matter and form. This notion of matter, or
stuff, has great philosophical importance, because it expresses an idea crucial
to both our ordinary and our scientific understandings of the world.
Philosophers such as Hume who deny the existence of substances hold that
individual things are mere bundles of properties, namely, the properties
ordinarily attributed to them, and usually hold that they are incapable of
change; they are series of momentary events, rather than things enduring
through time.
substantialism, the view that the primary, most
fundamental entities are substances, everything else being dependent for its
existence on them, either as a property of them or a relation between them.
Different versions of the view would correspond to the different senses of the
word ‘substance’.
salva-veritate/salva-congruitate distinction, the The phrase occurs in two fragments from Gottfried Leibniz's
General Science. Characteristics: In Chapter 19, Definition 1, Leibniz
writes: "Two terms are the same (eadem) if one can be substituted for the
other without altering the truth of any statement (salva veritate)." In
Chapter 20, Definition 1, Leibniz writes: "Terms which can be substituted
for one another wherever we please without altering the truth of any statement
(salva veritate), are the same (eadem) or coincident (coincidentia). For
example, 'triangle' and 'trilateral', for in every proposition demonstrated by
Euclid concerning 'triangle', 'trilateral' can be substituted without loss of
truth (salva veritate)." ubstitutivity salva veritate: Grice: “The
phrase ‘salva veritate’ has been used at Oxford for years, Kneale tells me!” --
a condition met by two expressions when one is substitutable for the other at a
certain occurrence in a sentence and the truth-value truth or falsity of the
sentence is necessarily unchanged when the substitution is made. In such a case
the two expressions are said to exhibit substitutivity or substitutability
salva veritate literally, ‘with truth saved’ with respect to one another in that
context. The expressions are also said to be interchangeable or
intersubstitutable salva veritate in that context. Where it is obvious from a
given discussion that it is the truth-value that is to be preserved, it may be
said that the one expression is substitutable for the other or exhibits
substitutability with respect to the other at that place. Leibniz proposed to
use the universal interchangeability salva veritate of two terms in every
“proposition” in which they occur as a necessary and sufficient condition for
identity presumably for the identity of
the things denoted by the terms. There are apparent exceptions to this
criterion, as Leibniz himself noted. If a sentence occurs in a context governed
by a psychological verb such as ‘believe’ or ‘desire’, by an expression
conveying modality e.g., ‘necessarily’, ‘possibly’, or by certain temporal
expressions such as ‘it will soon be the case that’, then two terms may denote
the same thing but not be interchangeable within such a sentence. Occurrences of
expressions within quotation marks or where the expressions are both mentioned
and used cf. Quine’s example, “Giorgione was so-called because of his size”
also exhibit failure of substitutivity. Frege urged that such failures are to
be explained by the fact that within such contexts an expression does not have
its ordinary denotation but denotes instead either its usual sense or the
expression itself. Salva congruitate From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Jump
to navigationJump to search Salva congruitate[1] is a Latin scholastic term in
logic, which means "without becoming ill-formed",[2] salva meaning
rescue, salvation, welfare and congruitate meaning combine, coincide, agree.
Salva Congruitate is used in logic to mean that two terms may be substituted for
each other while preserving grammaticality in all contexts.[3][4] Contents 1 Remarks on salva congruitate 1.1
Timothy C. Potts 1.2 Bob Hale 2See also 3References Remarks on salva
congruitate Timothy C. Potts Timothy C. Potts describes salva congruitate as a
form of replacement in the context of meaning. It is a replacement which
preserves semantic coherence and should be distinguished from a replacement
which preserves syntactic coherence but may yield an expression to which no
meaning has been given. This means that supposing an original expression is
meaningful, the new expression obtained by the replacement will also be
meaningful, though it will not necessarily have the same meaning as the
original one, nor, if the expression in question happens to be a proposition,
will the replacement necessarily preserve the truth value of the
original.[5] Bob Hale Bob Hale explains
salva congruitate, as applied to singular terms, as substantival expressions in
natural language, which are able to replace singular terms without destructive
effect on the grammar of a sentence.[6] Thus the singular term 'Bob' may be
replaced by the definite description 'the first man to swim the English
Channel' salva congruitate. Such replacement may shift both meaning and reference,
and so, if made in the context of a sentence, may cause a change in
truth-value. Thus terms which may be interchanged salva congruitate may not be
interchangeable salva veritate (preserving truth). More generally, expressions
of any type are interchangeable salva congruitate if and only if they can
replace one another preserving grammaticality or well-formedness. See also Salva veritate Reference principle
Referential opacity Crispin Wright Peter Geach References W.V.O. Quine, Philosophy of logic Dr. Benjamin Schnieder, Canonical Property
Designators, P9 W.V.O. Quine,
Quiddities, P204 W.V.O. Quine,
Philosophy of Logic, P18 Timothy C. Potts,
Structures and categories for the representation of meaning, p57 Bob Hale, Singular Terms, P34 Categories: Concepts
in logicPhilosophical logicPhilosophy of languageLatin logical phrases. Refs.:
H. P. Grice, “Implicaturum salva veritate,” H. P. Grice, “What I learned from
T. C. Potts.” – T. C. Potts, “My tutorials with Grice at St. John’s.”
summum bonum: Grice: “that in relation to which all other things
have at most instrumental value value only insofar as they are productive of
what is the highest good. Philosophical conceptions of the summum bonum have
for the most part been teleological in character. That is, they have identified
the highest good in terms of some goal or goals that human beings, it is
supposed, pursue by their very nature. These natural goals or ends have
differed considerably. For the theist, this end is God; for the rationalist, it
is the rational comprehension of what is real; for hedonism, it is pleasure;
etc. The highest good, however, need not be teleologically construed. It may
simply be posited, or supposed, that it is known, through some intuitive
process, that a certain type of thing is “intrinsically good.” On such a view,
the relevant contrast is not so much between what is good as an end and what is
good as a means to this end, as between what is good purely in itself and what
is good only in combination with certain other elements the “extrinsically
good”. Perhaps the best example of such a view of the highest good would be the
position of Moore. Must the summum bonum be just one thing, or one kind of
thing? Yes, to this extent: although one could certainly combine pluralism the
view that there are many, irreducibly different goods with an assertion that
the summum bonum is “complex,” the notion of the highest good has typically
been the province of monists believers in a single good, not pluralists.
summum genus. What adjective is the ‘sumum’ translating, Grice
wondered. And he soon found out. We know that the Romans were unoriginally
enough with their ‘genus’ (cf. ‘gens’) translating Grecian ‘genos.’ The highest
category in the ‘arbor griceiana’ -- The categories. There is infimum genus, or
sub-summum. Talk of categories becomes informal in Grice when he ‘echoes’ Kant
in the mention of four ‘functions’ that generate for Kant twelve categories.
Grice however uses the functions themselves, echoing Ariskant, rather, as
‘caegory’. We have then a category of conversational quantity (involved in a
principle of maximization of conversational informativeness). We have a
category of conversational quality (or a desideratum of conversational
candour). We have a category of conversational relation (cf. Strawson’s
principle of relevance along with Strawson’s principles of the presumption of
knowledge and the presumption of ignorance). Lastly, we have a category of
conversational mode. For some reason, Grice uses ‘manner’ sometimes in lieu of
Meiklejohn’s apt translation of Kant’s modality into the shorter ‘mode.’ The
four have Aristotelian pedigree, indeed Grecian and Graeco-Roman: The quantity
is Kant’s quantitat which is Aristotle’s posotes (sic abstract) rendered in
Roman as ‘quantitas.’ Of course, Aristotle derives ‘posotes,’ from ‘poson,’ the
quantum. No quantity without quantum. The quality is Kant’s qualitat, which
again has Grecian and Graeco-Roman pediegree. It is Aristotel’s poiotes (sic in
abstract), rendered in Roman as qualitas. Again, derived from the more basic
‘poion,’ or ‘quale.’ Aristotle was unable to find a ‘-tes’ ending form for what
Kant has as ‘relation.’ ‘pros it’ is used, and first translated into Roman as
‘relatio.’ We see here that we are talking of a ‘summum genus.’ For who other
but a philosopher is going to lecture on the ‘pros it’? What Aristotle means is
that Socrates is to the right of Plato. Finally, for Grice’s mode, there is
Kant’s wrong ‘modalitat,’ since this refers to Aristotle ‘te’ and translated in
Roman as ‘modus,’ which Meiklejohn, being a better classicist than Kant,
renders as ‘mode,’ and not the pretentious sounding ‘modality.’ Now for Kant,
12 categories are involved here. Why? Because he subdivides each summum genus
into three sub-summum or ‘inferiore’ genus. This is complex. Kant would
DISAGREE with Grice’s idea that a subject can JUDGE in generic terms, say,
about the quantum. The subject has THREE scenarios. It’s best to reverse the
order, for surely unity comes before totality. One scenario, he utters a
SINGULAR or individual utterance (Grice on ‘the’). The CATEGORY is the first
category, THE UNUM or UNITAS. The one. The unity. Second scenario, he utters a
PARTICULAR utterance (Grice’s “some (at least one). Here we encounter the
SECOND category, that of PLURALITAS, the plurum, plurality. It’s a good thing
Kant forgot that the Greeks had a dual number, and that Urquhart has fourth
number, a re-dual. A third scenario: the nirvana. He utters a UNIVERSAL (totum)
utterance (Grice on “all”). The category is that of TOTUM, TOTALITAS, totality.
Kant does not deign to specify if he means substitutional or
non-substitutional. For the quale, there are again three scenarios for Kant,
and he would deny that the subject is confronted with the FUNCTION quale and be
able to formulate a judgement. The first scenario involves the subject uttering
a PROPOSITIO DEDICATIVA (Grice elaborates on this before introducing ‘not’ in
“Indicative conditionals” – “Let’s start with some unstructured amorophous
proposition.” Here the category is NOT AFFIRMATION, but the nirvana “REALITAS,”
Reality, reale.Second scenario, subject utters a PROPOSITIO ABDICATIVA (Grice
on ‘not’). While Kant does not consider affirmatio a category (why should he?),
he does consider NEGATIO a category. Negation. See abdicatum. Third scenario,
subject utters an PROPOSITIO INFINITA. Here the category is that of LIMITATION,
which is quite like NEGATIO (cf. privatio, stelesis, versus habitus or hexis),
but not quite. Possibly LIMITATUM. Regarding the ‘pros ti.’ The first scenario
involves a categorema, PROPOSITIO CATEGORICA. Here Kant seems to think that
there is ONE category called “INHERENCE AND SUBSTISTENCE or substance and
accident. There seem rather two. He will go to this ‘pair’ formulation in one
more case in the relation, and for the three under modus. If we count the
‘categorical pairs’ as being two categories. The total would not be 12
categories but 17, which is a rather ugly number for a list of categories,
unles it is not. Kant is being VERY serious here, because if he has
SUBSTISTENCE or SUBSTANCE as a category, this is SECUNDA SUBSTANTIA or
‘deutero-ousia.’ It is a no-no to count the prote ousia or PRIMA SUBSTANTIA as
a category. It is defined as THE THING which cannot be predicated of anything!
“SUMBEBEKOS” is a trick of Kant, for surely EVERYTHING BUT THE SUBSTANCE can be
seen as an ‘accidens’ (In fact, those who deny categories, reduce them to
‘attribute’, or ‘property.’ The second scenario involves an ‘if’ Grice on ‘if’
– PROPOSITIO CONDITIONALIS – hypothetike protasis -- this involves for the
first time a MOLECULAR proposition. As in the previous case, we have a
‘category pair’, which is formulated either as CAUSALITY (CAUSALITAS) and
DEPENDENCE (Dependentia), or “cause’ (CAUSA) and ‘effect’ (Effectum). Kant is
having in mind Strawson’s account of ‘if’ (The influence of P. F. Strawson on
Kant). For since this is the hypothetical, Kant is suggeseting that in ‘if p,
q’ q depends on p, or q is an effect of its cause, p. As in “If it rains, the
boots are in the closet.” (J). The third scenario also involves a molectural proposition, A
DISJUNCTUM. PROPOSITIO DISJUNCTIVA. Note that in Kant, ‘if’ before ‘or’! His
implicaturum: subordination before coordination, which makes sense. Grice on
‘or.’ FOR SOME REASON, the category here for Kant is that of COMMUNITAS
(community) or RECIPROCITAS, reciprocity. He seems to be suggesting that if you
turn to the right or to the left, you are reciprocally forbidden to keep on
going straight. For the modus, similar. Here Kant is into modality. Again, it
is best to re-order the scenarios in terms of priority. Here it’s the middle
which is basic. The first scenario, subject utters an ASSERTORIC. The category
is a pair: EXISTENCE (how is this different from REALITY) and NON-EXISTENCE
(how is this different from negation?). He has in mind: ‘the cat is in the
room,’ ‘the room is empty.’ Second scenario, the subject doubts. subject utters
a problematical. (“The pillar box may be red”). Here we have a category pair:
POSSIBILITIAS (possibility) and, yes, IMPOSSIBILITAS – IMPOSSIBILITY. This is
odd, because ‘impossibility’ goes rather with the negation of necessity. The
third and last scenario, subject utters an APODEICTIC. Here again there is a
category pair – yielding 17 as the final number --: NECESSITAS, necessity, and
guess what, CONTINGENTIA, or contingency. Surely, possibilitas and contingentia
are almost the same thing. It may be what Grice has in mind when he blames a
philosopher to state that ‘what is actual is not also possible.’ Or not. Refs.:
H. P. Grice, “Gilbert Ryle’s criticism of Ariskant’s categories,” Ryle,
“Categories.” “The nisnamed categories.” Ryle notes that when it comes to
‘relatio,’ Kant just murders Aristotle’s idea of a ‘relation’ as in higher
than, or smaller than. – “His idea of the molecular propositions has nothing to
do with Aristotle’s ‘relation’ or ‘pros ti.’”
sub-positum, suppositum – (literally, ‘sub-positum,’) -- cf.
presuppositum -- in the Middle Ages, reference. The theory of supposition, the
central notion in the theory of proprietates terminorum, was developed in the
twelfth century, and was refined and discussed into early modern times. It has
two parts their names are a modern convenience. 1 The theory of supposition
proper. This typically divided suppositio into “personal” reference to
individuals not necessarily to persons, despite the name, “simple” reference to
species or genera, and “material” reference to spoken or written expressions.
Thus ‘man’ in ‘Every man is an animal’ has personal supposition, in ‘Man is a
species’ simple supposition, and in ‘Man is a monosyllable’ material
supposition. The theory also included an account of how the range of a term’s
reference is affected by tense and by modal factors. 2 The theory of “modes” of
personal supposition. This part of supposition theory divided personal
supposition typically into “discrete” ‘Socrates’ in ‘Socrates is a man’,
“determinate” ‘man’ in ‘Some man is a Grecian’, “confused and distributive”
‘man’ in ‘Every man is an animal’, and “merely confused” ‘animal’ in ‘Every man
is an animal’. The purpose of this second part of the theory is a matter of
some dispute. By the late fourteenth century, it had in some authors become a
theory of quantification. The term ‘suppositio’ was also used in the Middle
Ages in the ordinary sense, to mean ‘assumption’, ‘hypothesis’. H. P. Grice,
“Implicaturum, implicatum, positum, subpositum;” H. P. Grice: “A communicational
analogy: explicatum/expositum:implicatum/impositum,” H. P. Grice, “The positum:
between the sub-positum and the supra-positum,” H. P. Grice, “The implicaturum,
the sous-entendu, and the sub-positum.”
survival: discussed by Grice in what he calls the ‘genoritorial
programme, where the philosopher posits himself as a creature-constructor. It’s
an expository device that allows to ask questions in the third person, “seeing
that we can thus avoid the so-called ‘first-person bias’” -- continued
existence after one’s biological death. So understood, survival can pertain
only to beings that are organisms at some time or other, not to beings that are
disembodied at all times as angels are said to be or to beings that are
embodied but never as organisms as might be said of computers. Theories that
maintain that one’s individual consciousness is absorbed into a universal
consciousness after death or that one continues to exist only through one’s
descendants, insofar as they deny one’s own continued existence as an individual,
are not theories of survival. Although survival does not entail immortality or
anything about reward or punishment in an afterlife, many theories of survival
incorporate these features. Theories about survival have expressed differing
attitudes about the importance of the body. supervenient behaviorism survival
892 892 Some philosophers have
maintained that persons cannot survive without their own bodies, typically
espousing a doctrine of resurrection; such a view was held by Aquinas. Others,
including the Pythagoreans, have believed that one can survive in other bodies,
allowing for reincarnation into a body of the same species or even for
transmigration into a body of another species. Some, including Plato and
perhaps the Pythagoreans, have claimed that no body is necessary, and that
survival is fully achieved by one’s escaping embodiment. There is a similar
spectrum of opinion about the importance of one’s mental life. Some, such as
Locke, have supposed that survival of the same person would require memory of
one’s having experienced specific past events. Plato’s doctrine of
recollection, in contrast, supposes that one can survive without any
experiential memory; all that one typically is capable of recollecting are
impersonal necessary truths. Philosophers have tested the relative importance
of bodily versus mental factors by means of various thought experiments, of
which the following is typical. Suppose that a person’s whole mental life memories, skills, and character traits were somehow duplicated into a data bank and
erased from the person, leaving a living radical amnesiac. Suppose further that
the person’s mental life were transcribed into another radically amnesiac body.
Has the person survived, and if so, as whom?
swedenborgianism: the theosophy professed by a worldwide movement
established as the New Jerusalem Church in London by the followers of the
philosopher Emanuel Swedenborg. Swedenborg fuses the rationalist Cartesian and
empiricist Lockean legacies into a natural philosophy “Principia Rerum
Naturalium,” that propounds the harmony of the mechanistic universe with
biblical revelation. Inspired by Liebniz, Malebranche, Platonism, and
Neoplatonism, Swedenborg unfolds a doctrine of correspondence, “A Hieroglyphic
Key,” to account for the relation between body and soul and between the natural
and spiritual worlds, and applied it to biblical exegesis. What attracts the
wide following of the “Spirit-Seer” are his speculations in the line of Boehme
and the mystical, prophetic tradition in which he excelled, as in Heavenly
Arcana. Grice’s great uncle was a Swedenborgian.
swinburne: Grice: “Those Savoyards among us should never confuse
Swinburne, parodied in “Patience,” and the Oxonian theologian – hardly an
aesthete!” -- English philosopher of religion and of science. In philosophy of
science, he has contributed to confirmation theory and to the philosophy of
space and time. His work in philosophy of religion is the most ambitious
project in philosophical theology undertaken by a British philosopher in the
twentieth century. Its first part is a trilogy on the coherence and
justification of theistic belief and the rationality of living by that belief:
TheCoherence of Theism 7, The Existence of God 9, and Faith and Reason 1. Since
5, when Swinburne became Nolloth Professor of the Philosophy of the Christian
Religion at the of Oxford, he has
written a tetralogy about some of the most central of the distinctively
Christian religious doctrines: Responsibility and Atonement 9, Revelation 2,
The Christian God 4, and Providence and the Problem of Evil 8. The most
interesting feature of the trilogy is its contribution to natural theology.
Using Bayesian reasoning, Swinburne builds a cumulative case for theism by
arguing that its probability is raised sustaining cause Swinburne, Richard
893 893 by such things as the existence
of the universe, its order, the existence of consciousness, human opportunities
to do good, the pattern of history, evidence of miracles, and religious
experience. The existence of evil does not count against the existence of God.
On our total evidence theism is more probable than not. In the tetralogy he
explicates and defends such Christian doctrines as original sin, the Atonement,
Heaven, Hell, the Trinity, the Incarnation, and Providence. He also analyzes
the grounds for supposing that some Christian doctrines are revealed truths,
and argues for a Christian theodicy in response to the problem of evil. Refs.:
H. P. Grice, “Swinburne et moi.”
synæsthesia: cum-perceptum: co-sensibile – cum-sensibile –
co-sensatio, co-sensation -- a conscious experience in which qualities normally
associated with one sensory modality are or seem to be sensed in another.
Examples include auditory and tactile visions such as “loud sunlight” and “soft
moonlight” as well as visual bodily sensations such as “dark thoughts” and
“bright smiles.” Two features of synaesthesia are of philosophic interest.
First, the experience may be used to judge the appropriateness of sensory
metaphors and similes, such as Baudelaire’s “sweet as oboes.” The metaphor is
appropriate just when oboes sound sweet. Second, synaesthesia challenges the
manner in which common sense distinguishes among the external senses. It is
commonly acknowledged that taste, e.g., is not only unlike hearing, smell, or
any other sense, but differs from them because taste involves gustatory rather
than auditory experiences. In synaesthesia, however, one might taste sounds
sweet-sounding oboes. G.A.G. syncategoremata, 1 in grammar, words that cannot
serve by themselves as subjects or predicates of categorical propositions. The
opposite is categoremata, words that can do this. For example, ‘and’, ‘if’,
‘every’, ‘because’, ‘insofar’, and ‘under’ are syncategorematic terms, whereas
‘dog’, ‘smooth’, and ‘sings’ are categorematic ones. This usage comes from the
fifth-century Latin grammarian Priscian. It seems to have been the original way
of drawing the distinction, and to have persisted through later periods along
syllogism, demonstrative syncategoremata 896
896 with other usages described below. 2 In medieval logic from the
twelfth century on, the distinction was drawn semantically. Categoremata are
words that have a definite independent signification. Syncategoremata do not
have any independent signification or, according to some authors, not a
definite one anyway, but acquire a signification only when used in a
proposition together with categoremata. The examples used above work here as
well. 3 Medieval logic distinguished not only categorematic and
syncategorematic words, but also categorematic and syncategorematic uses of a
single word. The most important is the word ‘is’, which can be used both
categorematically to make an existence claim ‘Socrates is’ in the sense
‘Socrates exists’ or syncategorematically as a copula ‘Socrates is a
philosopher’. But other words were treated this way too. Thus ‘whole’ was said
to be used syncategorematically as a kind of quantifier in ‘The whole surface
is white’ from which it follows that each part of the surface is white, but
categorematically in ‘The whole surface is two square feet in area’ from which
it does not follow that each part of the surface is two square feet in area. 4
In medieval logic, again, syncategoremata were sometimes taken to include words
that can serve by themselves as subjects or predicates of categorical
propositions, but may interfere with standard logical inference patterns when
they do. The most notorious example is the word ‘nothing’. If nothing is better
than eternal bliss and tepid tea is better than nothing, still it does not
follow by the transitivity of ‘better than’ that tepid tea is better than
eternal bliss. Again, consider the verb ‘begins’. Everything red is colored,
but not everything that begins to be red begins to be colored it might have
been some other color earlier. Such words were classified as syncategorematic
because an analysis called an expositio of propositions containing them reveals
implicit syncategoremata in sense 1 or perhaps 2. Thus an analysis of ‘The apple
begins to be red’ would include the claim that it was not red earlier, and
‘not’ is syncategorematic in both senses 1 and 2. 5 In modern logic, sense 2 is
extended to apply to all logical symbols, not just to words in natural
languages. In this usage, categoremata are also called “proper symbols” or
“complete symbols,” while syncategoremata are called “improper symbols” or
“incomplete symbols.” In the terminology of modern formal semantics, the
meaning of categoremata is fixed by the models for the language, whereas the
meaning of syncategoremata is fixed by specifying truth conditions for the
various formulas of the language in terms of the models. H. P. Grice,
“Implicatures of synaesthesia,” “Some remarks about the senses.”
syneidesis,
conscientia -- synderesis: Grice
disliked the word as a ‘barbarism.’ Grice: “synderesis was by most of us at the Playgroup
reckoned to be a corruption of the Greician
“συνείδησις” shared knowledge, literally
‘co-ideatio,’ formed from ‘syn’ and ‘eidesis,’ ‘co-vision,’ or conscience,
the corruption appearing in the medieval manuscripts of what Austin called
‘that ignorant saint,’ Jerome in his Commentary.” Douglas Kries in Traditio vol.
57: Origen, Plato, and Conscience (Synderesis) in Jerome's Ezekiel
Commentary, p. 67. συνείδησις , εως, ἡ, A.
Liddell and Scott render as “knowledge shared with another,” -- τῶν ἀλγημάτων
(in a midwife) Sor.1.4. 2. communication, information, εὑρήσεις ς. PPar. p.422
(ii A.D.); “ς. εἰσήνεγκαν τοῖς κολλήγαις αὐτῶν” POxy. 123.13 (iii/iv A.D.). 3.
knowledge, λῦε ταῦτα πάντα μὴ διαλείψας ἀγαθῇ ς. (v.l. ἀγαθῇ τύχῃ) Hp.Ep.1. 4.
consciousness, awareness, [τῆς αὑτοῦ συστάσεως] Chrysipp.Stoic.3.43, cf.
Phld.Rh.2.140 S., 2 Ep.Cor.4.2, 5.11, 1 Ep.Pet.2.19; “τῆς κακοπραγμοσύνης”
Democr.297, cf. D.S.4.65, Ep.Hebr.10.2; “κατὰ συνείδησιν ἀτάραχοι διαμενοῦσι”
Hero Bel.73; inner consciousness, “ἐν ς. σου βασιλέα μὴ καταράσῃ” LXX Ec.
10.20; in 1 Ep.Cor.8.7 συνειδήσει is f.l. for συνηθείᾳ. 5. consciousness of
right or wrong doing, conscience, Periander and Bias ap. Stob.3.24.11,12,
Luc.Am.49; ἐὰν ἐγκλήματός τινος ἔχῃ ς. Anon. Oxy.218 (a) ii 19; “βροτοῖς ἅπασιν ἡ ς. θεός” Men.Mon.654, cf. LXX
Wi.17.11, D.H.Th.8 (but perh. interpol.); “ς. ἀγαθή” Act.Ap.23.1; ἀπρόσκοπος
πρὸς τὸν θεόν ib.24.16; “καθαρά” 1 Ep.Ti.3.9, POsl.17.10 (ii A.D.);
“κολαζομένους κατὰ συνείδησιν” Vett.Val.210.1; “θλειβομένη τῇ ς. περὶ ὧν
ἐνοσφίσατο” PRyl.116.9 (ii A.D.); τὸν . . θεὸν κεχολωμένον ἔχοιτο καὶ τὴν ἰδίαν
ς. Ath.Mitt.24.237 (Thyatira); conscientiousness, Arch.Pap.3.418.13 (vi
A.D.).--Senses 4 and 5 sts. run one into the other, v. 1 Ep.Cor.8.7, 10.27 sq.
6. complicity, guilt, crime, “περὶ τοῦ πεφημίσθαι αὐτὴν ἐν ς. τοιαύτῃ”
Supp.Epigr.4.648.13 (Lydia, ii A.D.). Grice: “The rough Romans could not do
with the ‘cum-‘ of the ‘syn-‘ but few of us at Oxford think of Laurel and Hardy
or Grice and Strawson when they say ‘conscientia’!” con-scĭo , īre, v. a. * I.
To be conscious of wrong: nil sibi, * Hor. Ep. 1, 1, 61.— II. To know well
(late Lat.): “consciens Christus, quid esset,” Tert. Carn. Chr. 3. moral theology, conscience. Jerome used ‘synderesis.’
‘Synderesis’ becomes a fixture because of Peter Lombard’s inclusion of it in
his Sentences. Despite this origin, Grecian ‘synderesis’ is distinguished from Roman
‘conscience’ (from cum-scire) -- by
Aquinas. For Aquinas, Grecian ‘synderesis’ is the quasi-habitual grasp of the
most common principles of the moral order i.e., natural law, whereas ‘conscienntia’
is the *application* of such knowledge to fleeting and unrepeatable
circumstances. ’Conscientia,’ Aquinas misleadingly claims, is allegedly ambiguous
in the way in which ‘knowledge’ is. Knowledge (Scientia) can be the mental
state of the knower or what the knower knows (scitum, cognitum) – Grice: “In
fact, Roman has four participles, active present, sciens, passive perfect,
sctium, future active, sciendus, future passive, sciturus -- But ‘conscientia’ like ‘synderesis’, is typically used for the
state of the soul. Sometimes, however, conscientia is taken to include general
moral knowledge as well as its application here and now; but the content of
synderesis is the most general precepts, whereas the content of conscience, if
general knowledge, will be less general precepts. Since conscience can be
erroneous, the question arises as to whether synderesis and its object, natural
law precepts, can be obscured and forgotten because of bad behavior or
upbringing. Aquinas holds that while great attrition can take place, such
common moral knowledge cannot be wholly expunged from the soul. This is a
version of the Aristotelian doctrine that there are starting points of
knowledge so easily grasped that the grasping of them is a defining mark of the
human being. However perversely the human agent behaves there will remain not
only the comprehensive realization that good (bonum) is to be done and evil (malum)
avoided, but also the recognition of some substantive human goods. Refs.: Luigi
Speranza, “Grice ad Aquino,” Villa Grice --. H. P. Grice, “Kenny on Aquinas,”
“Kenny uses barbaric Griceian and Grecian.”
synergism: in soteriology, the cooperation within human
consciousness of free will and divine grace in the processes of conversion and
regeneration. Synergism became an issue in sixteenth-century Lutheranism during
a controversy prompted by Philip Melanchthon 1497 syncategorematic synergism
897 897 1569. Under the influence of
Erasmus, Melanchthon mentioned, in the 1533 edition of his Common Places, three
causes of good actions: “the Word, the Holy Spirit, and the will.” Advocated by
Pfeffinger, a Philipist, synergism was attacked by the orthodox,
predestinarian, and monergist party, Amsdorf and Flacius, who retorted with
Gnesio-Lutheranism. The ensuing Formula of Concord 1577 officialized monergism.
Synergism occupies a middle position between uncritical trust in human noetic
and salvific capacity Pelagianism and deism and exclusive trust in divine
agency Calvinist and Lutheran fideism. Catholicism, Arminianism, Anglicanism,
Methodism, and nineteenth- and twentieth-century liberal Protestantism have
professed versions of synergism.
systems
theory: the transdisciplinary study of
the abstract organization of phenomena, independent of their substance, type,
or spatial or temporal scale of existence. It investigates both the principles
common to all complex entities and the usually mathematical models that can be
used to describe them. Systems theory was proposed in the 0s by the biologist
Ludwig von Bertalanffy and furthered by Ross Ashby Introduction to Cybernetics,
6. Von Bertalanffy was both reacting against reductionism and attempting to
revive the unity of science. He emphasized that real systems are open to, and
interact with, their environments, and that they can acquire qualitatively new
properties through emergence, resulting in continual evolution. Rather than
reduce an entity e.g. the human body to the properties of its parts or elements
e.g. organs or cells, systems theory focuses on the arrangement of and
relations among the parts that connect them into a whole cf. holism. This
particular organization determines a system, which is independent of the
concrete substance of the elements e.g. particles, cells, transistors, people.
Thus, the same concepts and principles of organization underlie the different
disciplines physics, biology, technology, sociology, etc., providing a basis
for their unification. Systems concepts include: system environment boundary,
input, output, process, state, hierarchy, goal-directedness, and information.
The developments of systems theory are diverse Klir, Facets of Systems Science,
1, including conceptual foundations and philosophy e.g. the philosophies of
Bunge, Bahm, and Laszlo; mathematical modeling and information theory e.g. the
work of Mesarovic and Klir; and practical applications. Mathematical systems
theory arose from the development of isomorphies between the models of
electrical circuits and other systems. Applications include engineering,
computing, ecology, management, and family psychotherapy. Systems analysis,
developed independently of systems theory, applies systems principles to aid a
decision maker with problems of identifying, reconstructing, optimizing, and
controlling a system usually a socio-technical organization, while taking into
account multiple objectives, constraints, and resources. It aims to specify
possible courses of action, together with their risks, costs, and benefits.
Systems theory is closely connected to cybernetics, and also to system
dynamics, which models changes in a network of synergy systems theory 898 898 coupled variables e.g. the “world
dynamics” models of Jay Forrester and the Club of Rome. Related ideas are used
in the emerging “sciences of complexity,” studying self-organization and
heterogeneous networks of interacting actors, and associated domains such as
far-from-equilibrium thermodynamics, chaotic dynamics, artificial life,
artificial intelligence, neural networks, and computer modeling and simulation.
T
tarski: a., cited by Grice. Grice liked Tarski because unlike
Strawson, he was an Aristotelian correspondenntist at heart, philosopher of
logic famous for his investigations of the concepts of truth and consequence
conducted in the 0s. His analysis of the concept of truth in syntactically
precise, fully interpreted languages resulted in a definition of truth and an
articulate defense of the correspondence theory of truth. Sentences of the
following kind are now known as Tarskian biconditionals: ‘The sentence “Every
perfect number is even” is true if and only if every perfect number is even.’
One of Tarski’s major philosophical insights is that each Tarskian
biconditional is, in his words, a partial definition of truth and,
consequently, all Tarskian biconditionals whose right-hand sides exhaust the
sentences of a given formal language together constitute an implicit definition
of ‘true’ as applicable to sentences of that given formal language. This
insight, because of its penetrating depth and disarming simplicity, has become
a staple of modern analytic philosophy. Moreover, it in effect reduced the
philosophical problem of defining truth to the logical problem of constructing
a single sentence having the form of a definition and having as consequences
each of the Tarskian biconditionals. Tarski’s solution to this problem is the
famous Tarski truth definition, versions of which appear in virtually every
mathematical logic text. Tarski’s second most widely recognized philosophical
achievement was his analysis and explication of the concept of consequence.
Consequence is interdefinable with validity as applied to arguments: a given
conclusion is a consequence of a given premise-set if and only if the argument
composed of the given conclusion and the given premise-set is valid;
conversely, a given argument is valid if and only if its conclusion is a
consequence of its premise-set. Shortly after discovering the truth definition,
Tarski presented his “no-countermodels” definition of consequence: a given
sentence is a consequence of a given set of sentences if and only if every
model of the set is a model of the sentence in other words, if and only if
there is no way to reinterpret the non-logical terms in such a way as to render
the sentence false while rendering all sentences in the set true. As Quine has
emphasized, this definition reduces the modal notion of logical necessity to a
combination of syntactic and semantic concepts, thus avoiding reference to
modalities and/or to “possible worlds.” After Tarski’s definitive work on truth
and on consequence he devoted his energies largely to more purely mathematical
work. For example, in answer to Gödel’s proof that arithmetic is incomplete and
undecidable, Tarski showed that algebra and geometry are both complete and
decidable. Tarski’s truth definition and his consequence definition are found
in his 6 collection Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics 2d ed., 3: article VIII,
pp. 152278, contains the truth definition; article XVI, pp. 40920, contains the
consequence definition. His published articles, nearly 3,000 s in all, have
been available together since 6 in the four-volume Alfred Tarski, Collected
Papers, edited by S. Givant and R. McKenzie.
tautologicum: Grice gives two examples: War is war, and Women are
women – “Note that “Men are men” sounds contingent.” tautology, a proposition
whose negation is inconsistent, or self- contradictory, e.g. ‘Socrates is
Socrates’, ‘Every human is either male or nonmale’, ‘No human is both male and
non-male’, ‘Every human is identical to itself’, ‘If Socrates is human then
Socrates is human’. A proposition that is or is logically equivalent to the
negation of a tautology is called a self-contradiction. According to classical
logic, the property of being Tao Te Ching tautology 902 902 implied by its own negation is a
necessary and sufficient condition for being a tautology and the property of
implying its own negation is a necessary and sufficient condition for being a
contradiction. Tautologies are logically necessary and contradictions are
logically impossible. Epistemically, every proposition that can be known to be
true by purely logical reasoning is a tautology and every proposition that can
be known to be false by purely logical reasoning is a contradiction. The
converses of these two statements are both controversial among classical
logicians. Every proposition in the same logical form as a tautology is a
tautology and every proposition in the same logical form as a contradiction is
a contradiction. For this reason sometimes a tautology is said to be true in
virtue of form and a contradiction is said to be false in virtue of form; being
a tautology and being a contradiction tautologousness and contradictoriness are
formal properties. Since the logical form of a proposition is determined by its
logical terms ‘every’, ‘some’, ‘is’, etc., a tautology is sometimes said to be
true in virtue of its logical terms and likewise mutatis mutandis for a
contradiction. Since tautologies do not exclude any logical possibilities they
are sometimes said to be “empty” or “uninformative”; and there is a tendency
even to deny that they are genuine propositions and that knowledge of them is
genuine knowledge. Since each contradiction “includes” implies all logical
possibilities which of course are jointly inconsistent, contradictions are
sometimes said to be “overinformative.” Tautologies and contradictions are
sometimes said to be “useless,” but for opposite reasons. More precisely,
according to classical logic, being implied by each and every proposition is
necessary and sufficient for being a tautology and, coordinately, implying each
and every proposition is necessary and sufficient for being a contradiction.
Certain developments in mathematical logic, especially model theory and modal
logic, seem to support use of Leibniz’s expression ‘true in all possible
worlds’ in connection with tautologies. There is a special subclass of
tautologies called truth-functional tautologies that are true in virtue of a
special subclass of logical terms called truthfunctional connectives ‘and’,
‘or’, ‘not’, ‘if’, etc.. Some logical writings use ‘tautology’ exclusively for
truth-functional tautologies and thus replace “tautology” in its broad sense by
another expression, e.g. ‘logical truth’. Tarski, Gödel, Russell, and many
other logicians have used the word in its broad sense, but use of it in its narrow
sense is widespread and entirely acceptable. Propositions known to be
tautologies are often given as examples of a priori knowledge. In philosophy of
mathematics, the logistic hypothesis of logicism is the proposition that every
true proposition of pure mathematics is a tautology. Some writers make a sharp
distinction between the formal property of being a tautology and the non-formal
metalogical property of being a law of logic. For example, ‘One is one’ is not
metalogical but it is a tautology, whereas ‘No tautology is a contradiction’ is
metalogical but is not a tautology.
tautologum: The difference between a truth and a tautological
truth is part of the dogma Grice defends. “A three-year old cannot understand
Russell’s theory of types” is possibly true. “It is not the case that a
three-year old is an adult” is TAUTOLOGICALLY true. As Strawson and Wiggins
note, by coining implicaturum Grice is mainly interested in having the MAN
implying this or that, as opposed to what the man implies implying this or
that. So, in Strawson and Wiggins’s rephrasing, the implicaturum is to be
distinguished with the logical and necessary implication, i. e., the
‘tautological’ implication. Grice uses ‘tautological’ variously. It is
tautological that we smell smells, for example. This is an extension of
‘paradigm-case,’ re: analyticity. Without ‘analytic’ there is no
‘tautologicum.’ tautŏlŏgĭa , ae, f., = ταυτολογία,I.a repetition of the same
meaning in different words, tautology, Mart. Cap. 5, § 535; Charis,
p. 242 P. ταὐτολογ-έω ,A.repeat what has been said, “περί τινος” Plb.1.1.3; “ὑπέρ τινος” Id.1.79.7; “τ. τὸν λόγον” Str.12.3.27:—abs., Plb.36.12.2, Phld. Po.Herc.994.30, Hermog.Inv.3.15.
Oddly why Witters restricts tautology to truth-table propositional logic,
Grice’s two examples are predicate calculus: Women are women and war is war.
4.46 GER [→OGD | →P/M] Unter den möglichen Gruppen von Wahrheitsbedingungen
gibt es zwei extreme Fälle. In dem einen Fall ist der Satz für sämtliche
Wahrheitsmöglichkeiten der Elementarsätze wahr. Wir sagen, die
Wahrheitsbedingungen sind t a u t o l o g i s c h. Im zweiten Fall ist der Satz
für sämtliche Wahrheitsmöglichkeiten falsch: Die Wahrheitsbedingungen sind k o
n t r a d i k t o r i s c h. Im ersten Fall nennen wir den Satz eine
Tautologie, im zweiten Fall eine Kontradiktion. 4.461 GER [→OGD | →P/M] Der
Satz zeigt was er sagt, die Tautologie und die Kontradiktion, dass sie nichts
sagen. Die Tautologie hat keine Wahrheitsbedingungen, denn sie ist
bedingungslos wahr; und die Kontradiktion ist unter keiner Bedingung wahr.
Tautologie und Kontradiktion sind sinnlos. (Wie der Punkt, von dem zwei Pfeile
in entgegengesetzter Richtung auseinandergehen.) (Ich weiß z. B. nichts über
das Wetter, wenn ich weiß, dass es regnet oder nicht regnet.) 4.4611 GER [→OGD
| →P/M] Tautologie und Kontradiktion sind aber nicht unsinnig; sie gehören zum
Symbolismus, und zwar ähnlich wie die „0“ zum Symbolismus der Arithmetik. 4.462
GER [→OGD | →P/M] Tautologie und Kontradiktion sind nicht Bilder der
Wirklichkeit. Sie stellen keine mögliche Sachlage dar. Denn jene lässt j e d e
mögliche Sachlage zu, diese k e i n e. In der Tautologie heben die Bedingungen
der Übereinstimmung mit der Welt—die darstellenden Beziehungen—einander auf, so
dass sie in keiner darstellenden Beziehung zur Wirklichkeit steht. 4.463 GER
[→OGD | →P/M] Die Wahrheitsbedingungen bestimmen den Spielraum, der den
Tatsachen durch den Satz gelassen wird. (Der Satz, das Bild, das Modell, sind
im negativen Sinne wie ein fester Körper, der die Bewegungsfreiheit der anderen
beschränkt; im positiven Sinne, wie der von fester Substanz begrenzte Raum,
worin ein Körper Platz hat.) Die Tautologie lässt der Wirklichkeit den
ganzen—unendlichen—logischen Raum; die Kontradiktion erfüllt den ganzen
logischen Raum und lässt der Wirklichkeit keinen Punkt. Keine von beiden kann
daher die Wirklichkeit irgendwie bestimmen. 4.464 GER [→OGD | →P/M] Die Wahrheit
der Tautologie ist gewiss, des Satzes möglich, der Kontradiktion unmöglich.
(Gewiss, möglich, unmöglich: Hier haben wir das Anzeichen jener Gradation, die
wir in der Wahrscheinlichkeitslehre brauchen.) 4.465 GER [→OGD | →P/M] Das
logische Produkt einer Tautologie und eines Satzes sagt dasselbe, wie der Satz.
Also ist jenes Produkt identisch mit dem Satz. Denn man kann das Wesentliche
des Symbols nicht ändern, ohne seinen Sinn zu ändern. 4.466 GER [→OGD | →P/M]
Einer bestimmten logischen Verbindung von Zeichen entspricht eine bestimmte
logische Verbindung ihrer Bedeutungen; j e d e b e l i e - b i g e Verbindung
entspricht nur den unverbundenen Zeichen. Das heißt, Sätze, die für jede
Sachlage wahr sind, können überhaupt keine Zeichenverbindungen sein, denn sonst
könnten ihnen nur bestimmte Verbindungen von Gegenständen entsprechen. (Und
keiner logischen Verbindung entspricht k e i n e Verbindung der Gegenstände.)
Tautologie und Kontradiktion sind die Grenzfälle der Zeichenverbindung, nämlich
ihre Auflösung. 4.4661 GER [→OGD | →P/M] Freilich sind auch in der Tautologie
und Kontradiktion die Zeichen noch mit einander verbunden, d. h. sie stehen in
Beziehungen zu einander, aber diese Beziehungen sind bedeu- tungslos, dem S y m
b o l unwesentlich. 4.46 OGD [→GER | →P/M] Among the possible groups of
truthconditions there are two extreme cases. In the one case the proposition is
true for all the truth-possibilities of the elementary propositions. We say
that the truth-conditions are tautological. In the second case the proposition
is false for all the truth-possibilities. The truth-conditions are
self-contradictory. In the first case we call the proposition a tautology, in
the second case a contradiction. 4.461 OGD [→GER | →P/M] The proposition shows
what it says, the tautology and the contradiction that they say nothing. The
tautology has no truth-conditions, for it is unconditionally true; and the
contradiction is on no condition true. Tautology and contradiction are without
sense. (Like the point from which two arrows go out in opposite directions.) (I
know, e.g. nothing about the weather, when I know that it rains or does not
rain.) 4.4611 OGD [→GER | →P/M] Tautology and contradiction are, however, not
nonsensical; they are part of the symbol- ism, in the same way that “0” is part
of the symbolism of Arithmetic. 4.462 OGD [→GER | →P/M] Tautology and
contradiction are not pictures of the reality. They present no possible state
of affairs. For the one allows every possible state of affairs, the other none.
In the tautology the conditions of agreement with the world—the presenting
relations— cancel one another, so that it stands in no presenting relation to
reality. 4.463 OGD [→GER | →P/M] The truth-conditions determine the range,
which is left to the facts by the proposition. (The proposition, the picture,
the model, are in a negative sense like a solid body, which restricts the free
movement of another: in a positive sense, like the space limited by solid
substance, in which a body may be placed.) Tautology leaves to reality the
whole infinite logical space; contradiction fills the whole logi- cal space and
leaves no point to reality. Neither of them, therefore, can in any way
determine reality. 4.464 OGD [→GER | →P/M] The truth of tautology is certain,
of propositions possible, of contradiction impossible. (Certain, possible,
impossible: here we have an indication of that gradation which we need in the
theory of probability.) 4.465 OGD [→GER | →P/M] The logical product of a
tautology and a proposition says the same as the proposition. Therefore that
product is identical with the proposition. For the essence of the symbol cannot
be altered without altering its sense. 4.466 OGD [→GER | →P/M] To a definite
logical combination of signs corresponds a definite logical combination of
their meanings; every arbitrary combination only corresponds to the unconnected
signs. That is, propositions which are true for ev- ery state of affairs cannot
be combinations of signs at all, for otherwise there could only correspond to
them definite combinations of objects. (And to no logical combination
corresponds no combination of the objects.) Tautology and contradiction are the
limiting cases of the combination of symbols, namely their dissolution. 4.4661
OGD [→GER | →P/M] Of course the signs are also combined with one another in the
tautology and contradiction, i.e. they stand in relations to one another, but
these relations are meaningless, unessential to the symbol. 4.46 P/M [→GER |
→OGD] Among the possible groups of truthconditions there are two extreme cases.
In one of these cases the proposition is true for all the truth-possibilities
of the elementary propositions. We say that the truth-conditions are
tautological. In the second case the proposition is false for all the
truth-possibilities: the truth-conditions are contradictory. In the first case
we call the proposition a tautology; in the second, a contradiction. 4.461 P/M
[→GER | →OGD] Propositions show what they say: tautolo- gies and contradictions
show that they say nothing. A tautology has no truth-conditions, since it is
unconditionally true: and a contradiction is true on no condition. Tautologies
and contradictions lack sense. (Like a point from which two arrows go out in
opposite directions to one another.) (For example, I know nothing about the
weather when I know that it is either raining or not raining.) 4.4611 P/M [→GER
| →OGD] Tautologies and contradictions are not, however, nonsensical. They are
part of the symbolism, much as ‘0’ is part of the symbolism of arithmetic. 4.462
P/M [→GER | →OGD] Tautologies and contradictions are not pictures of reality.
They do not represent any possible situations. For the former admit all
possible situations, and latter none. In a tautology the conditions of
agreement with the world—the representational relations—cancel one another, so
that it does not stand in any representational relation to reality. 4.463 P/M
[→GER | →OGD] The truth-conditions of a proposition determine the range that it
leaves open to the facts. (A proposition, a picture, or a model is, in the
negative sense, like a solid body that restricts the freedom of movement of
others, and, in the positive sense, like a space bounded by solid substance in
which there is room for a body.) A tautology leaves open to reality the whole—the
infinite whole—of logical space: a contradiction fills the whole of logical
space leaving no point of it for reality. Thus neither of them can determine
reality in any way. 4.464 P/M [→GER | →OGD] A tautology’s truth is certain, a
proposition’s possible, a contradiction’s impossible. (Certain, possible,
impossible: here we have the first indication of the scale that we need in the
theory of probability.) 4.465 P/M [→GER | →OGD] The logical product of a
tautology and a proposition says the same thing as the proposition. This
product, therefore, is identical with the proposition. For it is impossible to
alter what is essential to a symbol without altering its sense. 4.466 P/M [→GER
| →OGD] What corresponds to a determinate logical combination of signs is a determinate
logical combination of their meanings. It is only to the uncombined signs that
absolutely any combination corresponds. In other words, propositions that are
true for every situation cannot be combinations of signs at all, since, if they
were, only determinate combinations of objects could correspond to them. (And
what is not a logical combination has no combination of objects corresponding
to it.) Tautology and contradiction are the limiting cases—indeed the
disintegration—of the combination of signs. 4.4661 P/M [→GER | →OGD] Admittedly
the signs are still combined with one another even in tautologies and
contradictions—i.e. they stand in certain relations to one another: but these
relations have no meaning, they are not essential to the symbol. Grice would
often use ‘tautological,’ and ‘self-contradiction’ presupposes ‘analyticity,’
or rather the analytic-synthetic distinction. Is it contradictory, or a
self-contradiction, to say that one’s neighbour’s three-year-old child is an
adult? Is there an implicaturum for ‘War is not war’? Grice refers to Bayes in
WOW re Grices paradox, and to crazy Bayesy, as Peter Achinstein does (Newton
was crazy, but not Bayesy). We can now, in principle, characterize
the desirability of the action a 1 , relative to each end (E1 and E2), and to
each combination of ends (here just E1 and E2), as a function of the
desirability of the end and the probability that the action a 1 will realize
that end, or combination of ends. If we envisage a range of possible actions,
which includes a 1 together with other actions, we can imagine that each such
action has a certain degree of desirability relative to each end (E1 and (or)
E2) and to their combination. If we suppose that, for each possible action,
these desirabilities can be compounded (perhaps added), then we can suppose
that one particular possible action scored higher (in actiondesirability
relative to these ends) than any alternative possible action; and that this is
the action which wins out; that is, is the action which is, or at least should,
end p.105 be performed. (The computation would in fact be more complex than I
have described, once account is taken of the fact that the ends involved are
often not definite (determinate) states of affairs (like becoming President),
but are variable in respect of the degree to which they might be realized (if
ones end is to make a profit from a deal, that profit might be of a varying
magnitude); so one would have to consider not merely the likelihood of a
particular actions realizing the end of making a profit, but also the
likelihood of its realizing that end to this or that degree; and this would
considerably complicate the computational problem.) No doubt most readers are
far too sensible ever to have entertained any picture even remotely resembling
the "Crazy-Bayesy" one I have just described. Grice was
fascinated by the fact that paradox translates the Grecian neuter paradoxon.
Some of the paradoxes of entailment, entailment and paradoxes. This is not the
first time Grice uses paradox. As a classicist, he was aware of the nuances
between paradox (or paradoxon, as he preferred, via Latin paradoxum, and
aporia, for example. He was interested in Strawsons treatment of this or that
paradox of entailment. He even called his own paradox involving if and
probablility Grices paradox.
teichmüller: philosopher who contributes to the history of
philosophy and develops a theory of knowledge and a metaphysical conception
based on these historical studies. Born in Braunschweig, Teichmüller teaches at
Göttingen and Basel and is influenced by Lotze and Leibniz. Teichmüller’s major
works are “Aristotelische Forschungen” and “Die wirkliche und scheinbar Welt.” His
other works are “Ueber die Unsterblichkeit der Seele,” vide H. P. Grice, “The immortality of
Shropshire’s soul” Old English steorfan "to
die" (past tense stearf, past participle storfen), literally "become
stiff," from Proto-Germanic *sterbanan "be stiff, starve"
(source also of Old Frisian sterva, Old Saxon sterban, Dutch sterven, Old High
German sterban "to die," Old Norse stjarfi "tetanus"), from
extended form of PIE root *ster- (1) "stiff." The conjugation
became weak in English by 16c. The sense narrowed to "die of cold"
(14c.); transitive meaning "to kill with hunger" is first recorded
1520s (earlier to starve of hunger, early 12c.). Intransitive sense of "to
die of hunger" dates from 1570s. German cognate sterben retains the
original sense of the word, but the English has come so far from its origins
that starve to death (1910) is now common. “Studien zur Geschichte der
Begriffe,” “Darwinismus und Philosophie,” “Ueber das Wesen der Liebe,” “
Religionsphilosophie,” and “Neue Grundlegung der Psychologie und Logik.”
Teichmüller maintains that the self of immediate experience, the “I,” is the
most fundamental reality and that the conceptual world is a projection of its
constituting activity. On the basis of his studies in the history of
metaphysics and his sympathies with Leibniz’s monadology, he held that each
metaphysical system contained partial truths and construed each metaphysical
standpoint as a perspective on a complex reality. Thinking of both metaphysical
interpretations of reality and the subjectivity of individual immediate
experience, Teichmüller christened his own philosophical position
“perspectivism.” His work influenced later thought through its impact on the
philosophical reflections of Nietzsche, who was probably influenced by him in
the development of his perspectival theory of knowledge.
teilhard: philosopher whose oeuvre is vigorously discussed
throughout his career. Teilhard de Chardin’s philosophy generates considerable
controversy within the church, since one of his principal concerns is to bring
about a forceful yet generous reconciliation between the traditional Christian
dogma and the dramatic advances yielded by modern science. His philosophy
consisted of systematic reflections on cosmology, biology, physics,
anthropology, social theory, and theology
reflections guided, he maintains, by his fascination with the nature of
life, energy, and matter, and by his profound respect for human spirituality.
Teilhard is educated in philosophy at Mongré. He entered the Jesuit order at
the age of eighteen and was ordained a priest.He went on to study at
Aix-en-Provence, Laval, and Caen, as well as on the Isle of Jersey and at
Hastings, England. Returning to Paris after the war, he studies biology,
geology, and paleontology at the Museum of Natural History and at the Institut
Catholique, receiving a doctoral degree in geology. Shortly after appointment
to the faculty of geology at the Institut Catholique, he takes leave to pursue
field research. His research resulted in the discovery of “Sinanthropus
pekinensis,” which he saw as “perhaps the next to the last step traceable between
the anthropoids and man.” It was during this period that Teilhard begins to
compose one of his major theoretical works, “Le phenomene de l’homme,” in which
he stressed the deep continuity of evolutionary development and the emergence
of humanity from the animal realm. He argues that received evolutionary theory
is fully compatible with Christian doctrine. Indeed, it is the synthesis of
evolutionary theory with his own Christian theology that perhaps best
characterizes the broad tenor of his thought. Starting with the very inception
of the evolutionary trajectory, i.e., with what he termed the “alpha point” of
creation, Teilhard’s general theory resists any absolute disjunction between
the inorganic and organic. Indeed, matter and spirit are two “stages” or
“aspects” of the same cosmic stuff. These transitions from one state to another
may be said to correspond to those between the somatic and psychic, the
exterior and interior, according to the state of relative development,
organization, and complexity. Hence, for Teilhard, much as for Bergson whose
work greatly influenced him, evolutionary development is characterized by a
progression from the simplest components of matter and energy what he termed
the lithosphere, through the organization of flora and fauna the biosphere, to
the complex formations of sentient and cognitive human life the noosphere. In
this sense, evolution is a “progressive spiritualization of matter.” He held
this to be an orthogenetic process, one of “directed evolution” or “Genesis,”
by which matter would irreversibly metamorphose itself, in a process of
involution and complexification, toward the psychic. Specifically, Teilhard’s
account sought to overcome what he saw as a prescientific worldview, one based
on a largely antiquated and indefensible metaphysical dualism. By accomplishing
this, he hoped to realize a productive convergence of science and religion. The
end of evolution, what he termed “the Omega point,” would be the full presence
of Christ, embodied in a universal human society. Many have tended to see a
Christian pantheism expressed in such views. Teilhard himself stressed a
profoundly personalist, spiritual perspective, drawn not only from the
theological tradition of Thomism, but from that of Pauline Neoplatonism and Christian
mysticism as well especially that
tradition extending from Meister Eckhart through Cardinal Bérulle and
Malebranche. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Teilhard et moi,” – “Method in philosophical
psychology: from the banal to the bizarre.”
telementationalism: see psi-transmission. The coinage is interesting.
Since Grice has an essay on ‘modest mentalism,’ and would often use ‘mental’
for ‘psychological,’ it does make sense. ‘Ideationalism’ is analogous. this is
a special note, or rather, a very moving proem, on Grices occasion of
delivering his lectures on ‘Aspects of reason and reasoning’ at Oxford as the
Locke Lectures at Merton. Particularly apt in mentioning, with humility, his
having failed, *thrice* [sic] to obtain the Locke lectureship, Strawson did, at
once, but feeling safe under the ægis of that great English philosopher (viz.
Locke! always implicated, never explicited) now. Grice starts the proem in a
very moving, shall we say, emotional, way: I find it difficult to convey to you
just how happy I am, and how honoured I feel, in being invited to give these
lectures. Difficult, but not impossible. I think of this university and this
city, it has a cathedral, which were my home for thirty-six years, as my
spiritual and intellectual parents. The almost majestic plural is Grices
implicaturum to the town and gown! Whatever I am was originally fashioned here;
I never left Oxford, Oxford made me, and I find it a moving experience to be,
within these splendid and none too ancient walls, once more engaged in my old
occupation of rendering what is clear obscure, by flouting the desideratum of
conversational clarity and the conversational maxim, avoid obscurity of
expression, under be perspicuous [sic]!. Grices implicaturum on none too
ancient seems to be addressed to the truly ancient walls that saw Athenian
dialectic! On the other hand, Grices funny variant on the obscurum per
obscurius ‒ what Baker found as Grices skill in rendering an orthodoxy into a
heterodoxy! Almost! By clear Grice implicates Lewis and his clarity is not
enough! I am, at the same time, proud of my mid-Atlantic [two-world] status,
and am, therefore, delighted that the Old World should have called me in, or
rather recalled me, to redress, for once, the balance of my having left her for
the New. His implicaturum seems to be: Strictly, I never left? Grice concludes
his proem: I am, finally, greatly heartened by my consciousness of the fact
that that great English philosopher, under whose ægis I am now speaking, has in
the late afternoon of my days extended to me his Lectureship as a gracious
consolation for a record threefold denied to me, in my early morning, of his
Prize. I pray that my present offerings may find greater favour in his sight
than did those of long ago. They did! Even if Locke surely might have found
favour to Grices former offerings, too, Im sure. Refs.: The allusions to Locke
are in “Aspects.” Good references under ‘ideationalism,’ above, especially in
connection with Myro’s ‘modest mentalism,’ The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC.
telesio: philosopher whose empiricism influences Francis Bacon
and Galileo. Telesio studies in Padova, where he completed his doctorate, and practiced philosophy in Naples and Cosenza
without holding any academic position. His major oeuvre, “De rerum natura iuxta
propria principia,” contains an attempt to interpret nature on the basis of its
own principles, which Telesio identifies with the two incorporeal active forces
of heat and cold, and the corporeal and passive physical substratum. As the two
active forces permeate all of nature and are endowed with sensation, Telesio
argues that all of nature possesses some degree of sensation. Human beings
share with animals a material substance produced by heat and coming into
existence with the body, called spirit. They are also given a mind by God.
Telesio knew various interpretations of Aristotle. However, Telesio broke with foreign exegeses, criticizing
Aristotle’s Physics and claiming that nature is investigated better by the
senses than by the intellect. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Telesio e Grice,” per il
Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
tempus: cited by Grice and Myro in the Grice-Myro theory of
identity. tense logic, an extension of classical logic introduced by Arthur
Prior Past, Present, and Future, 7, involving operators P and F for the past
and future tenses, or ‘it was the case that . . .’ and ‘it will be the case
that . . .’. Classical or mathematical logic was developed as a logic of
unchanging mathematical truth, and can be applied to tensed discourse only by
artificial regimentation inspired by mathematical physics, introducing
quantification over “times” or “instants.” Thus ‘It will have been the case
that p,’ which Prior represents simply as FPp, classical logic represents as
‘There [exists] an instant t and there [exists] an instant tH such that t [is]
later than the present and tH [is] earlier than t, and at tH it [is] the case
that pH, or DtDtH t o‹t8tH ‹t8ptH, where the brackets indicate that the verbs are
to be understood as tenseless. Prior’s motives were in part linguistic to
produce a formalization less removed from natural language than the classical
and in part metaphysical to avoid ontological commitment to such entities as
instants. Much effort was devoted to finding tense-logical principles
equivalent to various classical assertions about the structure of the
earlierlater order among instants; e.g., ‘Between any two instants there is
another instant’ corresponds to the validity of the axioms Pp P PPp and Fp P
FFp. Less is expressible using P and F than is expressible with explicit
quantification over instants, and further operators for ‘since’ and ‘until’ or
‘now’ and ‘then’ have been introduced by Hans Kamp and others. These are
especially important in combination with quantification, as in ‘When he was in
power, all who now condemn him then praised him.’ As tense is closely related
to mood, so tense logic is closely related to modal logic. As Kripke models for
modal logic consist each of a set X of “worlds” and a relation R of ‘x is an
alternative to y’, so for tense logic they consist each of a set X of
“instants” and a relation R of ‘x is earlier than y’: Thus instants, banished
from the syntax or proof theory, reappear in the semantics or model theory.
Modality and tense are both involved in the issue of future contingents, and
one of Prior’s motives was a desire to produce a formalism in which the views
on this topic of ancient, medieval, and early modern logicians from Aristotle
with his “sea fight tomorrow” and Diodorus Cronos with his “Master Argument”
through Ockham to Peirce could be represented. The most important precursor to
Prior’s work on tense logic was that on many-valued logics by Lukasiewicz,
which was motivated largely by the problem of future contingents. Also related
to tense and mood is aspect, and modifications to represent this grammatical
category evaluating formulas at periods rather than instants of time have also
been introduced. Like modal logic, tense logic has been the object of intensive
study in theoretical computer science, especially in connection with attempts
to develop languages in which properties of programs can be expressed and
proved; variants of tense logic under such labels as “dynamic logic” or
“process logic” have thus been extensively developed for technological rather
than philosophical motives. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “D. H. Mellor on real and
irreal time.” applied by H. P. Grice and G. Myro in the so-called “Grice-Myro
theory of identity,” a time-relative identity, drawing from A. N. Prior, of
Oxford, D. Wiggins, Wykeham professor of logic at Oxford, and Geach (married to
an Oxonian donna), time, “a moving image
of eternity” Plato; “the number of movements in respect of the before and
after” Aristotle; “the Life of the Soul in movement as it passes from one stage
of act or experience to another” Plotinus; “a present of things past, memory, a
present of things present, sight, and a present of things future, expectation”
Augustine. These definitions, like all attempts to encapsulate the essence of
time in some neat formula, are unhelpfully circular because they employ
temporal notions. Although time might be too basic to admit of definition,
there still are many questions about time that philosophers have made some
progress in answering by analysis both of how we ordinarily experience and talk
about time, and of the deliverances of science, thereby clarifying and
deepening our understanding of what time is. What follows gives a sample of
some of the more important of these issues. Temporal becoming and the A- and
B-theories of time. According to the B-theory, time consists in nothing but a
fixed “B-series” of events running from earlier to later. The A-theory requires
that these events also form an “A-series” going from the future through the
present into the past and, moreover, shift in respect to these determinations.
The latter sort of change, commonly referred to as “temporal becoming,” gives
rise to well-known perplexities concerning both what does the shifting and the
sort of shift involved. Often it is said that it is the present or now that
shifts to ever-later times. This quickly leads to absurdity. ‘The present’ and
‘now’, like ‘this time’, are used to refer to a moment of time. Thus, to say
that the present shifts to later times entails that this very moment of
time the present will become some other moment of time and
thus cease to be identical with itself! Sometimes the entity that shifts is the
property of nowness or presentness. The problem is that every event has this
property at some time, namely when it occurs. Thus, what must qualify some
event as being now simpliciter is its having the property of nowness now; and
this is the start of an infinite regress that is vicious because at each stage
we are left with an unexpurgated use of ‘now’, the very term that was supposed
to be analyzed in terms of the property of nowness. If events are to change
from being future to present and from present to past, as is required by
temporal becoming, they must do so in relation to some mysterious transcendent
entity, since temporal relations between events and/or times cannot change. The
nature of the shift is equally perplexing, for it must occur at a particular
rate; but a rate of change involves a comparison between one kind of change and
a change of time. Herein, it is change of time that is compared to change of
time, resulting in the seeming tautology that time passes or shifts at the rate
of one second per second, surely an absurdity since this is not a rate of
change at all. Broad attempted to skirt these perplexities by saying that
becoming is sui generis and thereby defies analysis, which puts him on the side
of the mystically inclined Bergson who thought that it could be known only
through an act of ineffable intuition. To escape the clutches of both
perplexity and mysticism, as well as to satisfy the demand of science to view
the world non-perspectivally, the B-theory attempted to reduce the A-series to
the B-series via a linguistic reduction in which a temporal indexical
proposition reporting an event as past, present, or future is shown to be
identical with a non-indexical proposition reporting a relation of precedence
or simultaneity between it and another event or time. It is generally conceded
that such a reduction fails, since, in general, no indexical proposition is
identical with any non-indexical one, this being due to the fact that one can
have a propositional attitude toward one of them that is not had to the other;
e.g., I can believe that it is now raining without believing that it rains
tenselessly at t 7. The friends of becoming have drawn the wrong moral from
this failure that there is a mysterious
Mr. X out there doing “The Shift.” They have overlooked the fact that two
sentences can express different propositions and yet report one and the same
event or state of affairs; e.g., ‘This is water’ and ‘this is a collection of
H2O molecules’, though differing in sense, report the same state of
affairs this being water is nothing but
this being a collection of H2O molecules. It could be claimed that the same
holds for the appropriate use of indexical and non-indexical sentences; the
tokening at t 7 of ‘Georgie flies at this time at present’ is coreporting with
the non-synonymous ‘Georgie flies tenselessly at t 7’, since Georgie’s flying
at this time is the same event as Georgie’s flying at t 7, given that this time
is t 7. This effects the same ontological reduction of the becoming of events
to their bearing temporal relations to each other as does the linguistic
reduction. The “coreporting reduction” also shows the absurdity of the
“psychological reduction” according to which an event’s being present, etc.,
requires a relation to a perceiver, whereas an event’s having a temporal
relation to another event or time does not require a relation to a perceiver.
Given that Georgie’s flying at this time is identical with Georgie’s flying at
t 7, it follows that one and the same event both does and does not have the
property of requiring relation to a perceiver, thereby violating Leibniz’s law
that identicals are indiscernible. Continuous versus discrete time. Assume that
the instants of time are linearly ordered by the relation R of ‘earlier than’.
To say that this order is continuous is, first, to imply the property of
density or infinite divisibility: for any instants i 1 and i 2 such that Ri1i
2, there is a third instant i 3, such that Ri1i 3 and Ri3i 2. But continuity
implies something more since density allows for “gaps” between the instants, as
with the rational numbers. Think of R as the ‘less than’ relation and the i n
as rationals. To rule out gaps and thereby assure genuine continuity it is
necessary to require in addition to density that every convergent sequence of
instants has a limit. To make this precise one needs a distance measure d
, on pairs of instants, where di m, i n
is interpreted as the lapse of time between i m and i n. The requirement of
continuity proper is then that for any sequence i l , i 2, i 3, . . . , of
instants, if di m i n P 0 as m, n P C, there is a limit instant i ø such that
di n, iø P 0 as n P C. The analogous
property obviously fails for the rationals. But taking the completion of the
rationals by adding in the limit points of convergent sequences yields the real
number line, a genuine continuum. Numerous objections have been raised to the
idea of time as a continuum and to the very notion of the continuum itself.
Thus, it was objected that time cannot be composed of durationless instants
since a stack of such instants cannot produce a non-zero duration. Modern
measure theory resolves this objection. Leibniz held that a continuum cannot be
composed of points since the points in any finite closed interval can be put in
one-to-one correspondence with a smaller subinterval, contradicting the axiom
that the whole is greater than any proper part. What Leibniz took to be a
contradictory feature is now taken to be a defining feature of infinite
collections or totalities. Modern-day Zenoians, while granting the viability of
the mathematical doctrine of the continuum and even the usefulness of its
employment in physical theory, will deny the possibility of its applying to
real-life changes. Whitehead gave an analogue of Zeno’s paradox of the
dichotomy to show that a thing cannot endure in a continuous manner. For if i
1, i 2 is the interval over which the thing is supposed to endure, then the
thing would first have to endure until the instant i 3, halfway between i 1 and
i 2; but before it can endure until i 3, it must first endure until the instant
i 4 halfway between i 1 and i 3, etc. The seductiveness of this paradox rests
upon an implicit anthropomorphic demand that the operations of nature must be
understood in terms of concepts of human agency. Herein it is the demand that
the physicist’s description of a continuous change, such as a runner traversing
a unit spatial distance by performing an infinity of runs of ever-decreasing
distance, could be used as an action-guiding recipe for performing this feat,
which, of course, is impossible since it does not specify any initial or final
doing, as recipes that guide human actions must. But to make this
anthropomorphic demand explicit renders this deployment of the dichotomy, as
well as the arguments against the possibility of performing a “supertask,”
dubious. Anti-realists might deny that we are committed to real-life change
being continuous by our acceptance of a physical theory that employs principles
of mathematical continuity, but this is quite different from the Zenoian claim
that it is impossible for such change to be continuous. To maintain that time
is discrete would require not only abandoning the continuum but also the
density property as well. Giving up either conflicts with the intuition that
time is one-dimensional. For an explanation of how the topological analysis of
dimensionality entails that the dimension of a discrete space is 0, see W.
Hurewicz, Dimension Theory, 1. The philosophical and physics literatures
contain speculations about a discrete time built of “chronons” or temporal
atoms, but thus far such hypothetical entities have not been incorporated into
a satisfactory theory. Absolute versus relative and relational time. In a
scholium to the Principia, Newton declared that “Absolute, true and
mathematical time, of itself and from its own nature, flows equably without
relation to anything external.” There are at least five interrelated senses in
which time was absolute for Newton. First, he thought that there was a
frame-independent relation of simultaneity for events. Second, he thought that
there was a frame-independent measure of duration for non-simultaneous events.
He used ‘flows equably’ not to refer to the above sort of mysterious “temporal
becoming,” but instead to connote the second sense of absoluteness and partly
to indicate two further kinds of absoluteness. To appreciate the latter, note
that ‘flows equably’ is modified by ‘without relation to anything external’.
Here Newton was asserting third sense of ‘absolute’ that the lapse of time
between two events would be what it is even if the distribution and motions of
material bodies were different. He was also presupposing a related form of
absoluteness fourth sense according to which the metric of time is intrinsic to
the temporal interval. Leibniz’s philosophy of time placed him in agreement
with Newton as regards the first two senses of ‘absolute’, which assert the
non-relative or frame-independent nature of time. However, Leibniz was very
much opposed to Newton on the fourth sense of ‘absolute’. According to Leibniz’s
relational conception of time, any talk about the length of a temporal interval
must be unpacked in terms of talk about the relation of the interval to an
extrinsic metric standard. Furthermore, Leibniz used his principles of
sufficient reason and identity of indiscernibles to argue against a fifth sense
of ‘absolute’, implicit in Newton’s philosophy of time, according to which time
is a substratum in which physical events are situated. On the contrary, the
relational view holds that time is nothing over and above the structure of
relations of events. Einstein’s special and general theories of relativity have
direct bearing on parts of these controversies. The special theory necessitates
the abandonment of frame-independent notions of simultaneity and duration. For
any pair of spacelike related events in Minkowski space-time there is an
inertial frame in which the events are simultaneous, another frame in which the
first event is temporally prior, and still a third in which the second event is
temporally prior. And the temporal interval between two timelike related events
depends on the worldline connecting them. In fact, for any e 0, no matter how small, there is a worldline
connecting the events whose proper length is less than e. This is the essence
of the so-called twin paradox. The general theory of relativity abandons the
third sense of absoluteness since it entails that the metrical structure of
space-time covaries with the distribution of mass-energy in a manner specified
by Einstein’s field equations. But the heart of the absoluterelational
controversy as focused by the fourth and
fifth senses of ‘absolute’ is not
settled by relativistic considerations. Indeed, opponents from both sides of
the debate claim to find support for their positions in the special and general
theories. H. P. Grice, “D. H. Mellor on real and irreal time.” Tempus is ne of
Arsitotle’s categories, along with space – cfr. Kant – and Grice on Strawson’s
“Individuals” -- time slice: used by Grice in two different contexts: personal
identity, and identity in general. In identity in general, Grice draws from
Geach and Wiggins, and with the formal aid of Myro, construct a system of a
first-order predicate calculus with time-relative identity -- a temporal part
or stage of any concrete particular that exists for some interval of time; a
three-dimensional cross section of a fourdimensional object. To think of an
object as consisting of time slices or temporal stages is to think of it as
related to time in much the way that it is related to space: as extending
through time as well as space, rather than as enduring through it. Just as an
object made up of spatial parts is thought of as a whole made up of parts that
exist at different locations, so an object made up of time slices is thought of
as a whole made up of parts or stages that exist at successive times; hence,
just as a spatial whole is only partly present in any space that does not
include all its spatial parts, so a whole made up of time slices is only partly
present in any stretch of time that does not include all its temporal parts. A
continuant, by contrast, is most commonly understood to be a particular that
endures through time, i.e., that is wholly present at each moment at which it
exists. To conceive of an object as a continuant is to conceive of it as
related to time in a very different way from that in which it is related to
space. A continuant does not extend through time as well as space; it does not
exist at different times by virtue of the existence of successive parts of it
at those times; it is the continuant itself that is wholly present at each such
time. To conceive an object as a continuant, therefore, is to conceive it as
not made up of temporal stages, or time slices, at all. There is another, less
common, use of ‘continuant’ in which a continuant is understood to be any
particular that exists for some stretch of time, regardless of whether it is
the whole of the particular or only some part of it that is present at each
moment of the particular’s existence. According to this usage, an entity that
is made up of time slices would be a kind of continuant rather than some other
kind of particular. Philosophers have disputed whether ordinary objects such as
cabbages and kings endure through time are continuants or only extend through
time are sequences of time slices. Some argue that to understand the
possibility of change one must think of such objects as sequences of time
slices; others argue that for the same reason one must think of such objects as
continuants. If an object changes, it comes to be different from itself. Some
argue that this would be possible only if an object consisted of distinct,
successive stages; so that change would simply consist in the differences among
the successive temporal parts of an object. Others argue that this view would
make change impossible; that differences among the successive temporal parts of
a thing would no more imply the thing had changed than differences among its spatial
parts would. H. P. Grice, “D. H. Mellor
on real and irreal time.”
terminus – horos – Cicero’s transliteration of the Greianism
--. terminist logic, a school of semantics until its demise in the humanistic
reforms. The chief goal of ‘terminisim’ – or terministic semantics -- is the
elucidation (or conceptual analysis) of the
form, the “exposition,” of a proposition advanced in the context of
Scholastic disputation. The cntral theory of terminisitc semantics concerns
this or that property of this or that term, especially the suppositum.
Terminisic semantics does the work of modern quantification theory. Important
semanticists in the school include Peter of Spain, Sherwood, Burleigh
(Burlaeus), Heytesbury, and Paolo Veneto.
terminus a
quo-terminus a quem distinction, the: used
by Grice for the starting point of some process, as opposed to the terminus ad
quem, the ending point. E. g., change is a process that begins from some state,
the terminus a quo, and proceeds to some state at which it ends, the terminus
ad quem. In particular, in the ripening of an apple, the green apple is the
terminus a quo and the red apple is the terminus ad quem.
tertulliano: Roman – Grice says that ‘you’re the cream in my
coffee’ is absurd – “Can you believe it?” -- Adored by Grice because he
believed what he thought was absurd.
theologian, an early father of the Christian church. A layman from
Carthage, he laid the conceptual and linguistic basis for the doctrine of the
Trinity. Though appearing hostile to philosophy “What has Athens to do with
Jerusalem?” and to rationality “It is certain because it is impossible”,
Tertullian was steeped in Stoicism. He denounced all eclecticism not governed
by the normative tradition of Christian doctrine, yet commonly used philosophical
argument and Stoic concepts e.g., the corporeality of God and the soul. Despite
insisting on the sole authority of the New Testament apostles, he joined with
Montanism, which taught that the Holy Spirit was still inspiring prophecy
concerning moral discipline. Reflecting this interest in the Spirit, Tertullian
pondered the distinctions to which he gave the neologism trinitas within God.
God is one “substance” but three “persons”: a plurality without division. The
Father, Son, and Spirit are distinct, but share equally in the one Godhead.
This threeness is manifest only in the “economy” of God’s temporal action
toward the world; later orthodoxy e.g. Athanasius, Basil the Great, Augustine,
would postulate a Triunity that is eternal and “immanent,” i.e., internal to
God’s being.
testing: Grice: “A token proving testability.” Grice: “We need
a meta-test: a test for a test for implicatura.” late
14c., "small vessel used in assaying precious metals," from Old
French test, from Latin testum "earthen pot," related to testa
"piece of burned clay, earthen pot, shell" (see tete). Sense of
"trial or examination to determine the correctness of something" is
recorded from 1590s. The connecting notion is "ascertaining the quality of
a metal by melting it in a pot." Test Act was the name given to various
laws in English history meant to exclude Catholics and Nonconformists from
office, especially that of 1673, repealed 1828. Test drive (v.) is first
recorded 1954. In the sciences, capacity of a theory to undergo experimental
testing. Theories in the natural sciences are regularly subjected to
experimental tests involving detailed and rigorous control of variable factors.
Not naive observation of the workings of nature, but disciplined, designed
intervention in such workings, is the hallmark of testability. Logically
regarded, testing takes the form of seeking confirmation of theories by
obtaining positive test results. We can represent a theory as a conjunction of
a hypothesis and a statement of initial conditions, H • A. This conjunction
deductively entails testable or observational consequences O. Hence, H • A P O.
If O obtains, H • A is said to be confirmed, or rendered probable. But such
confirmation is not decisive; O may be entailed by, and hence explained by,
many other theories. For this reason, Popper insisted that the testability of
theories should seek disconfirmations or falsifications. The logical schema H •
A P O not-O not-H • A is deductively valid, hence apparently decisive. On this
view, science progresses, not by finding the truth, but by discarding the
false. Testability becomes falsifiability. This deductive schema modus tollens
is also employed in the analysis of crucial tests. Consider two hypotheses H1
and H2, both introduced to explain some phenomenon. H1 predicts that for some
test condition C, we have the test result ‘if C then e1’, and H2, the result
‘if C then e2’, where e1 and e2 are logically incompatible. If experiment
falsifies ‘if C then e1’ e1 does not actually occur as a test result, the hypothesis
H1 is false, which implies that H2 is true. It was originally supposed that the
experiments of J. B. L. Foucault constituted a decisive falsifcation of the
corpuscular theory of the nature of light, and thus provided a decisive
establishment of the truth of its rival, the wave theory of light. This account
of crucial experiments neglects certain points in logic and also the role of
auxiliary hypotheses in science. As Duhem pointed term, minor testability
908 908 out, rarely, if ever, does a
hypothesis face the facts in isolation from other supporting assumptions.
Furthermore, it is a fact of logic that the falsification of a conjunction of a
hypothesis and its auxiliary assumptions and initial conditions not-H • A is
logically equivalent to not-H or not-A, and the test result itself provides no
warrant for choosing which alternative to reject. Duhem further suggested that
rejection of any component part of a complex theory is based on
extra-evidential considerations factors like simplicity and fruitfulness and
cannot be forced by negative test results. Acceptance of Duhem’s view led Quine
to suggest that a theory must face the tribunal of experience en bloc; no
single hypothesis can be tested in isolation. Original conceptions of
testability and falsifiability construed scientific method as
hypothetico-deductive. Difficulties with these reconstructions of the logic of
experiment have led philosophers of science to favor an explication of
empirical support based on the logic of probability. Grice: “Linguists never
take ‘testability’ too conceptually, as one can witness in Saddock’s hasty
proofs!” – Refs: H. P. Grice, “On testing for testing for conversational
implicatura.”
testis:
n., pl. testes; Latin
testis "testicle," usually regarded as a special application of
testis "witness" (see testament), presumably because it "bears
witness to male virility" [Barnhart]. Stories that trace the use of the
Latin word to some supposed swearing-in ceremony are modern and
groundless. Compare Greek parastatai "testicles," from
parastates "one that stands by;" and French slang témoins, literally
"witnesses." But Buck thinks Greek parastatai "testicles"
has been wrongly associated with the legal sense of parastates "supporter,
defender" and suggests instead parastatai in the sense of twin
"supporting pillars, props of a mast," etc. Or it might be a
euphemistic use of the word in the sense "comrades." OED, meanwhile,
points to Walde's suggestion of a connection between testis and testa
"pot, shell, etc." (see tete). testis "witness," from PIE *tri-st-i- "third
person standing by," from root *tris- "three" (see three) on the
notion of "third person, disinterested witness." -- as Grice
notes, “it is etymologically -- or
etymythologically -- related to ‘testicles,’” -- Grice proposes an analysis of ‘testify’ in
terms of necessary and sufficient conditions, “t is a testimony iff t is an act
of telling, including any assertion apparently intended to impart information,
regardless of social setting.” In an extended use, personal letters and
messages, books, and other published material purporting to contain factual
information also constitute testimony. As Grice notes, “testimony may be
sincere or insincere” -- and may express knowledge or baseless prejudice. When
it expresses knowledge, and it is rightly believed, this knowledge is
disseminated to its recipient, near or remote. Second-hand knowledge can be
passed on further, producing long chains of testimony; but these chains always
begin with the report of an eye-witness or expert. In any social group with a
common language there is potential for the sharing, through testimony, of the
fruits of individuals’ idiosyncratic acquisition of knowledge through
perception and inference. In advanced societies specialization in the gathering
and production of knowledge and its wider dissemination through spoken and
written testimony is a fundamental socio-epistemic fact, and a very large part
of each person’s body of knowledge and belief stems from testimony. Thus, the
question when a person may properly believe what another tells her, and what
grounds her epistemic entitlement to do so, is a crucial one in epistemology.
Reductionists about testimony insist that this entitlement must derive from our
entitlement to believe what we perceive to be so, and to draw inferences from
this according to familiar general principles. See e.g., Hume’s classic
discussion, in his “Enquiry into Human Understanding,” section X. On this view,
I can perceive that someone has told me that p, but can thereby come to know
that p only by means of an inference one
that goes via additional, empirically grounded knowledge of the trustworthiness
of that person. Anti-reductionists insist, by contrast, that there is a general
entitlement to believe what one is told just as such defeated by knowledge of
one’s informant’s lack of trustworthiness her mendacity or incompetence, but
not needing to be bolstered positively by empirically based knowledge of her
trustworthiness. Anti-reductionists thus see testimony as an autonomous source
of knowledge on a par with perception, inference, and memory. One argument
adduced for anti-reductionism is transcendental: We have many beliefs acquired
from testimony, and these beliefs are knowledge; their status as knowledge
cannot be accounted for in the way required by the reductionist, i. e., the
reliability of testimony cannot be independently confirmed; therefore, the
reductionist’s insistence on this is mistaken. However, while it is perhaps
true that the reliability of all the beliefs one has that depend on past
testimony cannot be simultaneously confirmed, one can certainly sometimes
ascertain, without circularity, that a specific assertion by a particular
person is likely to be correct if, e.g.,one’s
own experience has established that that person has a good track record of
reliability about that kind of thing. Grice: “Sometimes I use testimonium.”
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Trust and rationality.”
tetens: philosopher, referred to by Grice as “Dutch Locke.”
After his studies in Rostock and Copenhagen, Tetens teaches at Bützow and Kiel.
He had a second successful career as a public servant in Denmark that did not leave him time for philosophical
explorations. Tetens is one of the most important mainland philosophers between
Wolff and Kant. Like Kant, whom he significantly influenced, Tetens attempts to
find a middle way between Descartes’s rationalism and Locke’s empiricism.
Tetens’s most important work, the “Philosophische Versuche über die menschliche
Natur und ihre Entwicklung,” is indicative of the state of philosophical
discussion before Kant’s Critique of
Pure Reason. Tetens, who follows the “psychological method” of Locke, tends
toward a naturalism. Tetens makes a more radical distinction between sensation
and reason than Hume allows and attempts to show how this or that basic
rational principle – a prequel to Grice’s principle of conversational
cooperation -- guarantee the objectivity of human knowledge.
thales: Grice: “We call him Greek, but he certainly weren’t
[sic] born in Greece!” -- called by Grice the first Grecian philosopher
(“Oddly, we call him a Ionian, but the Ionian is quite a way from where he was
born!”) – who poisted a ‘philosophical’ why-explanation. Grecian philosopher who was regarded as one
of the Seven Sages of Greece. He was also considered the first philosopher,
founder of the Milesians. Thales is also reputed to have been an engineer,
astronomer, mathematician, and statesman. His doctrines even early Grecian
sources know only by hearsay: he said that water is the arche, and that the
earth floats on water like a raft. The magnet has a soul, and all things are
full of the gods. Thales’ attempt to explain natural phenomena in natural
rather than exclusively supernatural terms bore fruit in his follower
Anaximander.
‘that’: a demonstrative. Since Grice would make so many
references to the ‘that’-clause, he is aware that ‘that’ is etymologically a
demonstrative, that has lost its efficacy there. But the important etymological
lesson is that what follows a ‘that’-clause (cf. the classical languages Grice
learned at Clifton, Greek and Latin) is a ‘propositio’ just because the ‘that’
POINTS at the proposition. Sometimes he refers to ‘obliquus casus,’ and ‘oratio
obliqua,’ but he is more at home with things like ‘verba percipienda,’ verba
volendi, etc. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Bradley on this and that and thisnesss and
thatness.’
‘that’-clause: Grice’s priority for the ‘that’-clause is multiple.
He dislikes what he calls an ‘amorphous’ propositional complex. His idea is to
have at least ‘The S is P,’ one act involving a subjectum or denotatum, and one
involving the praedicatum. There is also what he calls sub-perceptual
utterances. They do look like structured (“That red pillar seems red”) but they
are not perceptual reports like “I perceive that the pillar box is red.” At
points he wanst to restrict utterer’s communucatum to a ‘that’-clause; but
ignoring Austin’s remark that to wonder about what a ‘word’ ‘means’ is
senseless, Grice sometimes allows for things like ‘The cat sat on the mat’ to
‘mean’ that the cat sat on the mat. Grice thinks that his account of ‘the
red-seeming pillar box’ succeeded, and that it was this success that prompted
him to apply the thing to other areas, notably Strawson, but one hopes, all the
theses he presents in “Causal” and “Prolegomena.” But he does not go back to
the is/seems example, other than perhaps the tie is/seems blue. The reason is
that the sense-datum theory is very complex. Note “seems.” “It seems to me
that…” but the ‘that’-clause not as a content of a state of the agent. If the
pillar box seems red to Grice because it is red, what ‘that’-clause are we
talking about to involve in the implicaturum? And what generates the
implicaturum. “By uttering “The pillar box seems red,” U conversationally
implicates that there is a denial or doubt, somewhere as to whether the pillar
box IS red.” Grice thought of Staal as particularly good at this type of
formalistic philosophy, which was still adequate to reflect the subtleties of
ordinary language. How do we define a Griceian action? How do we
define a Griceian event? This is Grices examination and criticism of Davidson,
as a scientific realist, followed by a Kantian approach to freedom and
causation. Grice is especially interested in the logical form, or explicitum,
so that he can play with the implicaturum. One of his favourite examples: He
fell on his sword, having tripped as he crossed the Galliæ. Grice manages to
quote from many and varied authors (some of which you would not expect him to
quote) such as Reichenbach, but also Robinson, of Oriel, of You Names it fame
(for any x, if you can Names it, x exists). Robinson has a brilliant essay on
parts of Cook Wilsons Statement and inference, so he certainly knows what he is
talking about. Grice also quotes from von Wright and Eddington. Grice offers a
linguistic botanic survey of autonomy and free (sugar-free, free fall,
implicaturum-free) which some have found inspirational. His favourite is
Finnegans alcohol-free. Finnegans obvious implicaturum is that everything is
alcohol-laden. Grice kept a copy of Davidsons The logical form of action
sentences, since surely Davidson, Grice thought, is making a primary
philosophical point. Horses run fast; therefore, horses run. A Davidsonian
problem, and there are more to come! Smith went fishing. Grices category shift
allows us to take Smiths fishing as the grammatical Subjects of an action
sentence. Cf. indeed the way to cope with entailment in The horse runs fast;
therefore, the horse runs. Grices Actions and events is Davidsonian in
motivation, but Kantian in method, one of those actions by Grice to promote a
Griceian event! Davidson had published, Grice thought, some pretty influential
(and provocative, anti-Quineian) stuff on actions and events, or events and actions,
actually, and, worse, he was being discussed at Oxford, too, over which Grice
always keeps an eye! Davidsons point, tersely put, is that while p.q (e.g. It
is raining, and it is pouring) denotes a concatenation of events. Smith is
fishing denotes an action, which is a kind of event, if you are following him
(Davidson, not Smith). However, Davidson is fighting against the intuition, if
you are a follower of Whitehead and Russell, to symbolise the Smith is fishing
as Fs, where s stands for Smith and F for fishing. The logical form of a report
of an event or an action seems to be slightly more complicated. Davidsons point
specifically involves adverbs, or adverbial modifiers, and how to play with
them in terms of entailment. The horse runs fast; therefore, the horse runs.
Symbolise that! as Davidson told Benson Mates! But Mates had gone to the
restroom. Grice explores all these and other topics and submits the thing for
publication. Grice quotes, as isnt his wont, from many and various
philosophers, not just Davidson, whom he saw every Wednesday, but others he
didnt, like Reichenbach, Robinson, Kant, and, again even a physicist like
Eddington. Grice remarks that Davidson is into hypothesis, suppositio, while he
is, as he should, into hypostasis, substantia. Grice then expands on the
apparent otiosity of uttering, It is a fact that grass is green. Grice goes on
to summarise what he ironically dubs an ingenious argument. Let
σ abbreviate the operator consists
in the fact that , which, when prefixed to a sentence, produces a
predicate or epithet. Let S abbreviate Snow is white, and
let G abbreviate Grass is green. In that case, xσS is 1 just in
case xσ(y(y=y and S) = y(y=y) is 1, since the first part of the
sub-sentence which follows σ in the main sentence is logically equivalent
logically equivalent to the second part. And xσ(y(y=y and S) =
y(y=y) is 1 just in case xσ(y(if y=y, G) = y(y=y) is 1,
since y(if y=y, S) and y(if y=y, G) are each a singular term, which, if
S and G are both true, each refers to y(y=y), and are therefore
co-referential and inter-substitutable. And xσ(y(if y=y, G) =
y(y=y) is true just in case xσG is 1, since G is logically equivalent
to the sub-sentence which follows σ. So, this fallacy goes, provided that
S and G are both 1, regardless of what an utterer explicitly conveys by
uttering a token of it, any event which consists of the otiose fact that S also
consists of the otiose fact that G, and vice versa, i. e. this randomly
chosen event is identical to any other randomly chosen event. Grice hastens to
criticise this slingshot fallacy licensing the inter-substitution of this or
that co-referential singular term and this or that logically equivalent
sub-sentence as officially demanded because it is needed to license a
patently valid, if baffling, inference. But, if in addition to providing
this benefit, the fallacy saddles the philosopher with a commitment to a
hideous consequence, the rational course is to endeavour to find a way of
retaining the benefit while eliminating the disastrous accompaniment, much
as in set theory it seems rational to seek as generous a comprehension
axiom as the need to escape this or that paradox permits. Grice proposes
to retain the principle of co-reference, but prohibit is
use after the principle of logical equivalence has been
used. Grice finds such a measure to have some intuitive appeal. In
the fallacy, the initial deployment of the principle of logical
equivalence seems tailored to the production of a sentence
which provides opportunity for trouble-raising application of
the principle of co-referentiality. And if that is what the game is,
why not stop it? On the assumption that this or that problem which
originally prompts this or that analysis is at least on their way towards
independent solution, Grice turns his attention to the possibility of
providing a constructivist treatment of things which might perhaps have
more intuitive appeal than a naïve realist approach. Grice begins with a
class of happenstance attributions, which is divided into this or that
basic happenstance attribution, i.e. ascriptions to a Subjects-item of an
attribute which is metabolically expressible, and this or that non-basic
resultant happenstance attribution, in which the attribute ascribed,
though not itself metabolically expressible, is such that its possession
by a Subjects item is suitably related to the possession by that or by some
other Subjects item, of this or that attribute which is metabolically
expressible. Any member of the class of happenstance attributions may be
used to say what happens, or happens to be the case, without talking about
any special entity belonging to a class of a happening or a happenstance. A
next stage involves the introduction of the operator consists of the fact that This
operator, when prefixed to a sentence S that makes a happen-stance
attribution to a Subjects-item, yields a predicate which is satisfied by an
entity which is a happenstance, provided that sentence S is doxastically
satisfactory, i. e., 1, and that some further metaphysical condition obtains,
which ensures the metaphysical necessity of the introduction into reality of
the category of a happenstance, thereby ensuring that this new category is
not just a class of this or that fiction. As far as the slingshot fallacy,
and the hideous consequence that all facts become identical to one Great Big
Fact, in the light of a defence of Reichenbach against the realist attack,
Grice is reasonably confident that a metaphysical extension of reality will not
saddle him with an intolerable paradox, pace the caveat that, to some, the
slingshot is not contradictory in the way a paradox is, but merely an
unexpected consequence ‒ not seriously hideous, at that. What this
metaphysical condition would be which would justify the metaphysical extension
remains, alas, to be determined. It is tempting to think that the
metaphysical condition is connected with a theoretical need to have this or
that happenstance as this or that item in, say, a causal relation. Grice goes
on to provide a progression of linguistic botanising
including free. Grice distinguishes four elements or stages in the
step-by-step development of freedom. A first stage is the transeunt
causation one finds in inanimate objects, as when we experience a stone in free
fall. This is Hume’s realm, the atomistss realm. This is external or transeunt
casuation, when an object is affected by processes in other objects. A second
stage is internal or immanent causation, where a process in an object is the
outcome of previous stages in that process, as in a freely moving body. A third
stage is the internal causation of a living being, in which changes are
generated in a creature by internal features of the creature which are not
earlier stages of the same change, but independent items, the function or finality
of which is to provide for the good of the creature in question. A fourth stage
is a culminating stage at which the conception of a certain mode by a human of
something as being for that creatures good is sufficient to initiate the doing
of that thing. Grice expands on this interesting last stage. At this stage, it
is the case that the creature is liberated from every factive cause. There is
also a discussion of von Wrights table of adverbial modifiers, or Grices
pentagram. Also an exploration of specificity: Jack buttering a parsnip in the
bathroom in the presence of Jill. Grice revisits some of his earlier concerns,
and these are discussed in the appropriate places, such as his exploration on
the Grecian etymology of aition. “That”-clause should be preferred to ‘oratio
obliqua,’ since the latter is a misnomer when you ascribe a psychological state
rather than an utterance. Refs.: The main sources are given under ‘oratio
obliqua’ above, The BANC.
theism: as an
Aristotelian scholar, H. P. Grice is aware of the centrality of God, nous
nouseos, in Aristotle’s philosophy -- atheism from Grecian a-, ‘not’, and
theos, ‘god’, the view that there are no gods. A widely used sense denotes
merely not believing in God and is consistent with agnosticism. A stricter
sense denotes a belief that there is no God; this use has become the standard
one. In the Apology Socrates is accused of atheism for not believing in the
official Athenian gods. Some distinguish between theoretical atheism and
practical atheism. A theoretical atheist is one who self-consciously denies the
existence of a supreme being, whereas a practical atheist may believe that a
supreme being exists but lives as though there were no god.
theology -- Grice’s philosophical theology -- concursus
dei, God’s concurrence. The notion derives from a theory from medieval
philosophical theology, according to which any case of causation involving
created substances requires both the exercise of genuine causal powers inherent
in creatures and the exercise of God’s causal activity. In particular, a
person’s actions are the result of the person’s causal powers, often including
the powers of deliberation and choice, and God’s causal endorsement. Divine
concurrence maintains that the nature of God’s activity is more determinate
than simply conserving the created world in existence. Although divine
concurrence agrees with occasionalism in holding God’s power to be necessary
for any event to occur, it diverges from occasionalism insofar as it regards
creatures as causally active.
theosophia: any philosophical mysticism, especially
those that purport to be mathematically or scientifically based, such as
Pythagoreanism, Neoplatonism, or gnosticism. Vedic Hinduism, and certain
aspects of Buddhism, Taoism, and Islamic Sufism, can also be considered
theosophical. In narrower senses, ‘theosophy’ may refer to the philosophy of
Swedenborg, Steiner, or Madame Helena Petrovna Blavatsky 183. Swedenborg’s
theosophy originally consisted of a rationalistic cosmology, inspired by certain
elements of Cartesian and Leibnizian philosophy, and a Christian mysticism.
Swedenborg labored to explain the interconnections between soul and body.
Steiner’s theosophy is a reaction to standard scientific theory. It purports to
be as rigorous as ordinary science, but superior to it by incorporating
spiritual truths about reality. According to his theosophy, reality is organic
and evolving by its own resource. Genuine knowledge is intuitive, not
discursive. Madame Blavatsky founded the Theosophical Society in 1875. Her
views were eclectic, but were strongly influenced by mystical elements of philosophy.
thema: a term Grice borrows from Stoic logic, after
attending a seminar on the topic by Benson Mates – a ‘thema’ is a ground rule
used to reduce argument forms to basic forms. The Stoics analyzed arguments by
their form schema, or tropos. They represented forms using numbers to represent
claims; for example, ‘if the first, the second; but the first; therefore the
second’. Grice uses “so-and-so” for ‘the first’ and ‘such and such’ for the
‘second’. “If so and so, such and such, but so and so; therefore, such and
such.” Some forms were undemonstrable; others were reduced to the
undemonstrable argument forms by ground rules themata; e.g., if R follows from
P & Q, -Q follows from P & -R. The five undemonstrable arguments are: 1
modus ponendo ponens; 2 modus tollendo tollens; 3 not both P and Q, P, so
not-Q; 4 P or Q but not both, P, so not-Q; and 5 disjunctive syllogism. The
evidence about the four ground rules is incomplete, but a sound and consistent
system for propositional logic can be developed that is consistent with the
evidence we have. See Diogenes Laertius, Lives of the Philosophers, for an
introduction to the Stoic theory of arguments; other evidence is more
scattered.
theseus’s
ship. Grice sails on Theseus’s ship. Theseus’ ship: Example used by Grice to relativise
‘identity.’ After the hero Theseus accomplished his mission to sail to Crete to
kill the Minotaur, his ship (Ship 1) was put on display in Athens. As the time
went by, its original planks and other parts were replaced one by one with new
materials until one day all of its parts were new, with none of its original
parts remaining. Do we want to say that the completely rebuilt ship (Ship 2) is
the same as the original or that it is
a different ship? The case is further complicated. If all the original
materials were kept and eventually used to construct a ship (Ship 3), would
this ship be the same as the original? This example has inspired much
discussion concerning the problems of identity and individuation. “To be
something later is to be its closest continuer. Let us apply this view to one
traditional puzzle about identity over time: the puzzle of the ship of
Theseus.” Nozick, Philosophical Explanation. Grice basically formalized this
with G. Myro. Refs.: Collingwood, translation of Benedetto Croce, “Il paradosso
della nave di Teseo,” H. P. Grice, “Relative identity,” The Grice Papers, BANC.
θ: or theta -- Grice’s symbol for a theory. Grice uses
small-case theta for a token of a theory, and capital theta for a type of
theory.– Grice couldn’t quite stand some type of attitude he found in people
like J. M. Rountree – Rountree was claiming that one needs a ‘theory’ of
meaning. Grice responded: “ Rountree is wrong: if meaning is a matter of
theory, it cannot be a matter of intuition; and I’m sure it should be a matter
of intuition for Rountree!” theoretical term – Grice was once attracted to
Ramsey’s essay on “Theories,” but later came to see it as ‘pretentious’.
“Surely the way *I* use ‘theory’ is not Ramsey’s!” – If something is an object
of an intuition by Grice, it cannot be a theoretical term – theory and
intuition don’t go together. They repel each other! a term occurring in a
scientific theory that purports to make reference to an unobservable entity
e.g., ‘electron’, property e.g., ‘the monatomicity of a molecule’, or relation
‘greater electrical resistance’. The qualification ‘purports to’ is required because
instrumentalists deny that any such unobservables exist; nevertheless, they
acknowledge that a scientific theory, such as the atomic theory of matter, may
be a useful tool for organizing our knowledge of observables and predicting
future experiences. Scientific realists, in contrast, maintain that at least
some of the theoretical terms e.g., ‘quark’ or ‘neutrino’ actually denote
entities that are not directly observable
they hold, i.e., that such things exist. For either group, theoretical
terms are contrasted with such observational terms as ‘rope’, ‘smooth’, and
‘louder than’, which refer to observable entities, properties, or relations.
Much philosophical controversy has centered on how to draw the distinction
between the observable and the unobservable. Did Galileo observe the moons of
Jupiter with his telescope? Do we observe bacteria under a microscope? Do
physicists observe electrons in bubble chambers? Do astronomers observe the
supernova explosions with neutrino counters? Do we observe ordinary material
objects, or are sense-data the only observables? Are there any observational
terms at all, or are all terms theory-laden? Another important meaning of
‘theoretical term’ occurs if one regards a scientific theory as a semiformal
axiomatic system. It is then natural to think of its vocabulary as divided into
three parts, i terms of logic and mathematics, ii terms drawn from ordinary
language or from other theories, and iii theoretical terms that constitute the
special vocabulary of that particular theory. Thermodynamics, e.g., employs i
terms for numbers and mathematical operations, ii such terms as ‘pressure’ and
‘volume’ that are common to many branches of physics, and iii such special
thermodynamical terms as ‘temperature’, ‘heat’, and ‘entropy’. In this second
sense, a theoretical term need not even purport to refer to unobservables. For
example, although special equipment is necessary for its precise
quantitatheoretical entity theoretical term 912 912 tive measurement, temperature is an
observable property. Even if theories are not regarded as axiomatic systems,
their technical terms can be considered theoretical. Such terms need not
purport to refer to unobservables, nor be the exclusive property of one
particular theory. In some cases, e.g., ‘work’ in physics, an ordinary word is
used in the theory with a meaning that departs significantly from its ordinary
use. Serious questions have been raised about the meaning of theoretical terms.
Some philosophers have insisted that, to be meaningful, they must be given
operational definitions. Others have appealed to coordinative definitions to
secure at least partial interpretation of axiomatic theories. The verifiability
criterion has been invoked to secure the meaningfulness of scientific theories
containing such terms. A theoretical concept or construct is a concept
expressed by a theoretical term in any of the foregoing senses. The term
‘theoretical entity’ has often been used to refer to unobservables, but this
usage is confusing, in part because, without introducing any special
vocabulary, we can talk about objects too small to be perceived directly e.g., spheres of gamboge a yellow resin less
than 106 meters in diameter, which figured in a historically important
experiment by Jean Perrin. Grice uses
Ramsey’s concept of ‘theory’ – “granting that Ramsey overrated theory, as all
Cambridge men do!” -- theory-laden, dependent on theory; specifically,
involving a theoretical interpretation of what is perceived or recorded. In the
heyday of logical empiricism it was thought, by Carnap and others, that a rigid
distinction could be drawn between observational and theoretical terms. Later,
N. R. Hanson, Paul Feyerabend, and others questioned this distinction, arguing
that perhaps all observations are theory-laden either because our perception of
the world is colored by perceptual, linguistic, and cultural differences or
because no attempt to distinguish sharply between observation and theory has
been successful. This shift brings a host of philosophical problems. If we
accept the idea of radical theoryladenness, relativism of theory choice becomes
possible, for, given rival theories each of which conditions its own
observational evidence, the choice between them would seem to have to be made
on extra-evidential grounds, since no theory-neutral observations are
available. In its most perplexing form, relativism holds that, theory-ladenness
being granted, one theory is as good as any other, so far as the relationship
of theory to evidence is concerned. Relativists couple the thesis of
theory-ladenness with the alleged fact of the underdetermination of a theory by
its observational evidence, which yields the idea that any number of
alternative theories can be supported by the same evidence. The question
becomes one of what it is that constrains choices between theories. If
theory-laden observations cannot constrain such choices, the individual
subjective preferences of scientists, or rules of fraternal behavior agreed
upon by groups of scientists, become the operative constraints. The logic of
confirmation seems to be intrinsically contaminated by both idiosyncratic and
social factors, posing a threat to the very idea of scientific
rationality.
thomson: Grice did not collaborate with that many friends. He
did with his tutee Strawson. He later did it with G. J. Warnock only on the
theory of perception (notably the ‘visum’). He collaborated with two more
Oxonian philosophers, and with both on the philosophy of action: D. F. Pears
and J. F. Thomson. J. F. Scots
London-born philosopher who would often give seminars with H. P. Grice. They
also explored ‘philosophy of action.’ Thomson presented his views on public
occasons on the topic, usually under the guidance of D. F. Pears – on topics
such as ‘freedom of the will.’ Thomson has assocations with University, and is
a Fellow of Corpus, Grice’s alma.
thomsonianism: Grice explored philosophy of action with J. F.
Thomson. Thomson would socialize mainly with Grice and D. F. Pears. Oddly,
Thomson was also interested in ‘if’ and reached more or less the same Philonian
consequences that Grice does.
thoreau: h. d. born in Concord, Massachusetts, New
England, he attended Harvard, and, rather than the usual Rhodes scholarship to
Oxford, he returns to Concord to study nature and write, making a frugal living
as a schoolteacher, land surveyor, and pencil maker. Commentators have
emphasized three aspects of his life: his love and penetrating study of the
flora and fauna of the Concord area, recorded with philosophical reflections in
Walden 1854; his continuous pursuit of simplicity in the externals of life,
thus avoiding a life of “quiet desperation”; and his acts of civil
disobedience. The last item has been somewhat overemphasized; not paying a poll
tax by way of protest was not original with Thoreau. However, his essay
“Resistance to Civil Government” immortalized his protest and influenced people
like Gandhi and Martin Luther King, Jr., in later years. Thoreau eventually
helped runaway slaves at considerable risk; still, he considered himself a
student of nature and not a reformer. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “What Thoreau missed
at Oxford.”
three-year-old’s
guide to Russell’s theory of types, the
– by H. P. Grice, with an appendix by P. F. Strawson, “Advice to parents,” v.
Grice’s three-year-old’s guide.
tillich:
philosopher, b. in Starzeddel, eastern Germany, he was educated in
philosophy and theology and ordained in the Prussian Evangelical Church in 2.
He served as an army chaplain during World War I and later taught at Berlin,
Marburg, Dresden, Leipzig, and Frankfurt. In November 3, following suspension
from his teaching post by the Nazis, he emigrated to the United States, where
he taught at Columbia and Union Theological Seminary until 5, and then at
Harvard and Chicago until his death. A popular preacher and speaker, he
developed a wide audience in the United States through such writings as The
Protestant Era 8, Systematic Theology three volumes: 1, 7, 3, The Courage to Be
2, and Dynamics of Faith 7. His sometimes unconventional lifestyle, as well as
his syncretic yet original thought, moved “on the boundary” between theology
and other elements of culture especially
art, literature, political thought, and depth psychology in the belief that religion should relate to
the whole extent, and the very depths, of human existence. Tillich’s thought,
despite its distinctive “ontological” vocabulary, was greatly influenced by the
voluntaristic tradition from Augustine through Schelling, Schopenhauer, Marx,
Nietzsche, and Freud. It was a systematic theology that sought to state fresh
Christian answers to deep existential questions raised by individuals and
cultures his method of correlation.
Every age has its distinctive kairos, “crisis” or “fullness of time,” the right
time for creative thought and action. In Weimar G.y, Tillich found the times
ripe for religious socialism. In postWorld War II America, he focused more on
psychological themes: in the midst of anxiety over death, meaninglessness, and
guilt, everyone seeks the courage to be, which comes only by avoiding the abyss
of non-being welling up in the demonic and by placing one’s unconditional
faith ultit’ien Tillich, Paul 919 919 mate concern not in any particular being e.g. God but in
Being-Itself “the God above God,” the ground of being. This is essentially the
Protestant principle, which prohibits lodging ultimate concern in any finite
and limited reality including state, race, and religious institutions and symbols.
Tillich was especially influential after World War II. He represented for many
a welcome critical openness to the spiritual depths of modern culture, opposing
both demonic idolatry of this world as in National Socialism and sectarian
denial of cultural resources for faith as in Barthian neo-orthodoxy.
tonk: a sentential connective whose meaning and logic
are completely characterized by the two rules or axioms 1 [P P P tonk Q] and 2
[P tonk Q P Q]. If 1 and 2 are added to any normal system, then every Q can be
derived from any P. A. N. Prior invented ‘tonk’ to show that deductive validity
must not be conceived as depending solely on arbitrary syntactically defined
rules or axioms. We may prohibit ‘tonk’ on the ground that it is not a natural,
independently meaningful notion, but we may also prohibit it on purely
syntactical grounds. E.g., we may require that, for every connective C, the
C-introduction rule [xxx P . . . C . . .] and the C-elimination rule [ - - - C
- - - P yyy] be such that the yyy is part of xxx or is related to xxx in some
other syntactical way.
token-reflexive, an expression that refers to itself in
an act of speech or writing, such as ‘this token’. The term was coined by
Reichenbach, who conjectured that all indexicals, all expressions whose
semantic value depends partly on features of the context of utterance, are
tokenreflexive and definable in terms of the phrase ‘this token’. He suggested
that ‘I’ means the same as ‘the person who utters this token’, ‘now’ means the
same as ‘the time at which this token is uttered’, ‘this table’ means the same
as ‘the table pointed to by a gesture accompanying this token’, and so forth.
Russell made a somewhat similar suggestion in his discussion of egocentric
particulars. Reichenbach’s conjecture is widely regarded as false; although ‘I’
does pick out the person using it, it is not synonymous with ‘the person who
utters this token’. If it were, as David Kaplan observes, ‘If no one were to
utter this token, I would not exist’ would be true.
token-type
distinction – Grice: “Strictly, they
are not antonyms – and token is too English!” Grice: “Token is cognate with
‘teach,’ a Graeco-Roman thing, cfr. insignum – insignare – to teach is to show,
almost, with an m-intention behind.” -- first the token, then the type – if
necessary; “After all a type is a set of tokens” -- used by Grice: there’s a
type of an utterer, but there’s the individual utterer: In symbols, “u” is an
individual utterer, say, Grice. “U” is a type of utterer, say Oxonian philosophy
dons. Aas drawn by Peirce, the contrast between a category and a member of that
category. An individual or token is said to exemplify a type; it possesses the
property that characterizes that type. In philosophy this distinction is often
applied to linguistic expressions and to mental states, but it can be applied
also to objects, events, properties, and states of affairs. Related to it are
the distinctions between type and token individuation and between qualitative
and numerical identity. Distinct tokens of the same type, such as two ants, may
be qualitatively identical but cannot be numerically identical. Irrespective of
the controversial metaphysical view that every individual has an essence, a
type to which it belongs essentially, every individual belongs to many types,
although for a certain theoretical or practical purpose it may belong to one
particularly salient type e.g., the entomologist’s Formicidae or the
picnicker’s buttinsky. The typetoken distinction as applied in the philosophy
of language marks the difference between linguistic expressions, such as words
and sentences, which are the subject of linguistics, and the products of acts
of writing or speaking the subject of speech act theory. Confusing the two can
lead to conflating matters of speaker meaning withmatters of word or sentence
meaning as noted by Grice. An expression is a linguistic type and can be used
over and over, whereas a token of a type can be produced only once, though of
course it may be reproduced copied. A writer composes an essay a type and
produces a manuscript a token, of which there might be many copies more tokens.
A token of a type is not the same as an occurrence of a type. In the previous
sentence there are two occurrences of the word ‘type’; in each inscription of
that sentence, there are two tokens of that word. In philosophy of mind the
typetoken distinction underlies the contrast between two forms of physicalism,
the typetype identity theory or type physicalism and the tokentoken identity
theory or token physicalism.
topic-neutral, noncommittal between two or more
ontological interpretations of a term. J. J. C. Smart suggested that
introspective reports can be taken as topic-neutral: composed of terms neutral
between “dualistic metaphysics” and “materialistic metaphysics.” When one
asserts, e.g., that one has a yellowish-orange afterimage, this is tantamount
to saying ‘There is something going on that is like what is going on when I
have my eyes open, am awake, and there is an orange illuminated in good light in
front of me, i.e., when I really see an orange’. The italicized phrase is, in
Smart’s terms, topic-neutral; it refers to an event, while remaining
noncommittal about whether it is material or immaterial. The term has not
always been restricted to neutrality regarding dualism and materialism. Smart
suggests that topic-neutral descriptions are composed of “quasi-logical” words,
and hence would be suitable for any occasion where a relatively noncommittal
expression of a view is required.
topos – Grice: “I will use the Latinate ‘commonplace’”
– ‘locus communis’-- topic, the analysis of common strategies of argumentation,
later a genre of literature analyzing syllogistic reasoning. Aristotle
considered the analysis of types of argument, or “topics,” the best means of
describing the art of dialectical reasoning; he also used the term to refer to
the principle underlying the strategy’s production of an argument. Later
classical commentators on Aristotle, particularly Latin rhetoricians like Cicero,
developed Aristotle’s discussions of the theory of dialectical reasoning into a
philosophical form. Boethius’s work on topics exemplifies the later classical
expansion of the scope of topics literature. For him, a topic is either a
self-evidently true universal generalization, also called a “maximal
proposition,” or a differentia, a member of the set of a maximal proposition’s
characteristics that determine its genus and species. Man is a rational animal
is a maximal proposition, and like from genus, the differentia that
characterizes the maximal proposition as concerning genera, it is a topic.
Because he believed dialectical reasoning leads to categorical, not
conditional, conclusions, Boethius felt that the discovery of an argument
entailed discovering a middle term uniting the two, previously unjoined terms
of the conclusion. Differentiae are the genera of these middle terms, and one
constructs arguments by choosing differentiae, thereby determining the middle
term leading to the conclusion. In the eleventh century, Boethius’s logical
structure of maximal propositions and differentiae was used to study
hypothetical syllogisms, while twelfth-century theorists like Abelard extended
the applicability of topics structure to the categorical syllogism. By the
thirteenth century, Peter of Spain, Robert Kilwardby, and Boethius of Dacia
applied topics structure exclusively to the categorical syllogism, principally
those with non-necessary, probable premises. Within a century, discussion of
topics structure to evaluate syllogistic reasoning was subsumed by consequences
literature, which described implication, entailment, and inference relations
between propositions. While the theory of consequences as an approach to
understanding relations between propositions is grounded in Boethian, and
perhaps Stoic, logic, it became prominent only in the later thirteenth century
with Burley’s recognition of the logical significance of propositional
logic.
toxin puzzle, a puzzle about intention and practical
rationality: trustworthy billionaire, call him Paul, offers you, Peter, a
million pounds for intending tonight to drink a certain toxin tomorrow. Peter
is convinced that Paul can tell what Peter intends independently of what Peter
does. The toxin would make Peter painfully ill for a day. But Peter needs to
drink it to get the money. Constraints on the formation of a prize-winning
intention include prohibitions against “gimmicks,” “external incentives,” and
forgetting relevant details; e. g. Peter will not receive the money if Peter
has a hypnotist “implant the intention” or hire a hit man to kill Peter should
Peter not drink the toxin. If, by midnight tonight, without violating any
rules, Peter forms an intention to drink the toxin tomorrow, Peter will find a
million pounds in his bank account when he awakes tomorrow morning. Peter
probably would drink the toxin for a million dollars. But can you, without
violating the rules, intend tonight to drink it tomorrow? Apparently, you have
no reason to drink it and an excellent reason not to drink it. Seemingly, you
will infer from this that you will eschew drinking the toxin, and believing
that you will top-down eschew drinking it seems inconsistent with intending to
drink it. Even so, there are several reports in the philosophical literature of
possible people who struck it rich when offered the toxin deal! Refs: H. P.
Grice, “Grice’s book of paradoxes, with puzzling illustrations to match!”
transcendens -- transcendental argument: Transcendental
argument -- Davidson, D.: H. P. Grice, “Reply to Davidson,” philosopher of mind
and language. His views on the relationship between our conceptions of
ourselves as persons and as complex physical objects have had an enormous
impact on contemporary philosophy. Davidson regards the mindbody problem as the
problem of the relation between mental and physical events; his discussions of
explanation assume that the entities explained are events; causation is a
relation between events; and action is a species of events, so that events are
the very subject matter of action theory. His central claim concerning events
is that they are concrete particulars
unrepeatable entities located in space and time. He does not take for
granted that events exist, but argues for their existence and for specific claims
as to their nature. In “The Individuation of Events” in Essays on Actions and
Events, 0, Davidson argues that a satisfactory theory of action must recognize
that we talk of the same action under different descriptions. We must therefore
assume the existence of actions. His strongest argument for the existence of
events derives from his most original contribution to metaphysics, the semantic
method of truth Essays on Actions and Events, pp. 10580; Essays on Truth and
Interpretation, 4, pp. 214. The argument is based on a distinctive trait of the
English language one not obviously shared by signal systems in lower animals,
namely, its productivity of combinations. We learn modes of composition as well
as words and are thus prepared to produce and respond to complex expressions
never before encountered. Davidson argues, from such considerations, that our
very understanding of English requires assuming the existence of events. To
understand Davidson’s rather complicated views about the relationships between
mind and body, consider the following claims: 1 The mental and the physical are
distinct. 2 The mental and the physical causally interact. 3 The physical is
causally closed. Darwinism, social Davidson, Donald 206 206 1 says that no mental event is a physical
event; 2, that some mental events cause physical events and vice versa; and 3,
that all the causes of physical events are physical events. If mental events
are distinct from physical events and sometimes cause them, then the physical
is not causally closed. The dilemma posed by the plausibility of each of these
claims and by their apparent incompatibility just is the traditional mind body
problem. Davidson’s resolution consists of three theses: 4 There are no strict
psychological or psychophysical laws; in fact, all strict laws are expressible
in purely physical vocabulary. 5 Mental events causally interact with physical
events. 6 Event c causes event e only if some strict causal law subsumes c and
e. It is commonly held that a property expressed by M is reducible to a
property expressed by P where M and P are not logically connected only if some
exceptionless law links them. So, given 4, mental and physical properties are
distinct. 6 says that c causes e only if there are singular descriptions, D of
c and DH of e, and a “strict” causal law, L, such that L and ‘D occurred’
entail ‘D caused D'’. 6 and the second part of 4 entail that physical events
have only physical causes and that all event causation is physically grounded.
Given the parallel between 13 and 4 6, it may seem that the latter, too, are
incompatible. But Davidson shows that they all can be true if and only if
mental events are identical to physical events. Let us say that an event e is a
physical event if and only if e satisfies a basic physical predicate that is, a
physical predicate appearing in a “strict” law. Since only physical predicates
or predicates expressing properties reducible to basic physical properties
appear in “strict” laws, every event that enters into causal relations satisfies
a basic physical predicate. So, those mental events which enter into causal
relations are also physical events. Still, the anomalous monist is committed
only to a partial endorsement of 1. The mental and physical are distinct
insofar as they are not linked by strict law
but they are not distinct insofar as mental events are in fact physical
events.
transcendental
club. “A club I created to discuss
what I call a ‘metaphysical argument,’ but Kant calls ‘transcendental.’
Strawson objected to my calling it “The Metaphysical Club.” transcendentalism: Also called “New England
transcendentalism,” an early nineteenth-century spiritual and philosophical
movement in the United States, represented by Ralph Waldo Emerson and Henry
David Thoreau. It was centered in the so-called The Transcendental Club in
Boston, and published a quarterly journal The Dial. Influenced by German
idealism and Romanticism, it claimed that there is a spirit of the whole, the
over-soul, which is beyond the space and time of the everyday world but at the
same time immanent in it, and which forms a higher spiritual reality. It
advocated an ascetic lifestyle, emphasized selfreliance and communal living,
and rejected contemporary civilization. The eventual goal of life is to achieve
a mystical unity with this spiritual reality, that is, with nature.
Transcendentalism is viewed as a mixture of speculative philosophy and
semi-religious faith. This philosophical movement had a deep influence upon
existentialism, James’s pragmatism, and contemporary environmental philosophy.
In a broad sense, transcendentalism is any doctrine that emphasizes the
transcendental, and is taken as a synonym of transcendental philosophy. In this
sense, all types of absolute philosophy, especially those idealist systems that
emphasize the transcendence of the Absolute over the finite world, are
considered examples of transcendentalism. Thus, transcendentalists had aims
differing from those of Kant’s transcendental philosophy, which criticized
those who wished to extend knowledge beyond experience and instead sought to
use a transcendental argument to establish the conditions for the possibility
of experience. “The transcendentalists believed in man’s ability to apprehend
absolute Truth, absolute Justice, absolute Rectitude, absolute goodness. They
spoke of the Right, the True, the Beautiful as eternal realities which man can
discover in the world and which he can incorporate into his life. And they were
convinced of the unlimited perfectibility of man.” Werkmeister, A History of
Philosophical Ideas in America.
transcendental argument: Grice: “I prefer metaphysical
argument.’ -- an argument that elucidates the conditions for the possibility of
some fundamental phenomenon whose existence is unchallenged or uncontroversial
in the philosophical context in which the argument is propounded. Such an
argument proceeds deductively, from a premise asserting the existence of some
basic phenomenon such as meaningful discourse, conceptualization of objective
states of affairs, or the practice of making promises, to a conclusion
asserting the existence of some interesting, substantive enabling conditions
for that phenomenon. The term derives from Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason,
which gives several such arguments. The paradigmatic Kantian transcendental
argument is the “Transcendental Deduction of the Pure Concepts of
Understanding.” Kant argued there that the objective validity of certain pure,
or a priori, concepts the “categories” is a condition for the possibility of
experience. Among the concepts allegedly required for having experience are
those of substance and cause. Their apriority consists in the fact that
instances of these concepts are not directly given in sense experience in the
manner of instances of empirical concepts such as red. This fact gave rise to
the skepticism of Hume concerning the very coherence of such alleged a priori
concepts. Now if these concepts do have objective validity, as Kant endeavored
to prove in opposition to Hume, then the world contains genuine instances of
the concepts. In a transcendental argument concerning the conditions for the
possibility of experience, it is crucial that some feature entailed by the
having of experience is identified. Then it is argued that experience could not
have this feature without satisfying some substantive conditions. In the
Transcendental Deduction, the feature of experience on which Kant concentrates
is the ability of a subject of experience to be aware of several distinct inner
states as all belonging to a single consciousness. There is no general
agreement on how Kant’s argument actually unfolded, though it seems clear to
most that he focused on the role of the categories in the synthesis or
combination of one’s inner states in judgments, where such synthesis is said to
be required for one’s awareness of the states as being all equally one’s own
states. Another famous Kantian transcendental argument the “Refutation of Idealism” in the
CriToynbee, Arnold transcendental argument 925
925 tique of Pure Reason shares a
noteworthy trait with the Transcendental Deduction. The Refutation proceeds
from the premise that one is conscious of one’s own existence as determined in
time, i.e., knows the temporal order of some of one’s inner states. According
to the Refutation, a condition for the possibility of such knowledge is one’s
consciousness of the existence of objects located outside oneself in space. If
one is indeed so conscious, that would refute the skeptical view, formulated by
Descartes, that one lacks knowledge of the existence of a spatial world
distinct from one’s mind and its inner states. Both of the Kantian
transcendental arguments we have considered, then, conclude that the falsity of
some skeptical view is a condition for the possibility of some phenomenon whose
existence is acknowledged even by the skeptic the having of experience;
knowledge of temporal facts about one’s own inner states. Thus, we can isolate
an interesting subclass of transcendental arguments: those which are
anti-skeptical in nature. Barry Stroud has raised the question whether such
arguments depend on some sort of suppressed verificationism according to which
the existence of language or conceptualization requires the availability of the
knowledge that the skeptic questions since verificationism has it that
meaningful sentences expressing coherent concepts, e.g., ‘There are tables’,
must be verifiable by what is given in sense experience. Dependence on a highly
controversial premise is undesirable in itself. Further, Stroud argued, such a
dependence would render superfluous whatever other content the anti-skeptical
transcendental argument might embody since the suppressed premise alone would
refute the skeptic. There is no general agreement on whether Stroud’s doubts
about anti-skeptical transcendental arguments are well founded. It is not
obvious whether the doubts apply to arguments that do not proceed from a
premise asserting the existence of language or conceptualization, but instead
conform more closely to the Kantian model. Even so, no anti-skeptical
transcendental argument has been widely accepted. This is evidently due to the
difficulty of uncovering substantive enabling conditions for phenomena that
even a skeptic will countenance.
transcendentale: Grice: “Trust Cicero to look for the abstract!” --
transcendentia, broadly, the property of rising out of or above other things
virtually always understood figuratively; in philosophy, the property of being,
in some way, of a higher order. A being, such as God, may be said to be transcendent
in the sense of being not merely superior, but incomparably superior, to other
things, in any sort of perfection. God’s transcendence, or being outside or
beyond the world, is also contrasted, and by some thinkers combined, with God’s
immanence, or existence within the world. In medieval philosophy of logic,
terms such as ‘being’ and ‘one’, which did not belong uniquely to any one of
the Aristotelian categories or types of predication such as substance, quality,
and relation, but could be predicated of things belonging to any or to none of
them, were called transcendental. In Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, principles
that profess wrongly to take us beyond the limits of any possible experience
are called transcendent; whereas anything belonging to non-empirical thought
that establishes, and draws consequences from, the possibility and limits of
experience may be called transcendental. Thus a transcendental argument in a
sense still current is one that proceeds from premises about the way in which
experience is possible to conclusions about what must be true of any
experienced world. Transcendentalism was a philosophical or religious movement
in mid-nineteenth-century New England, characterized, in the thought of its
leading representative, Ralph Waldo Emerson, by belief in a transcendent
spiritual and divine principle in human nature. Grice: “The formation of this
Ciceronian expression is fascinating. There’s the descent of the lark, and the
transcend of the lark!” -- transcendentals, also called transcendentalia, terms
or concepts that apply to all things regardless of the things’ ontological kind
or category. transcendental deduction transcendentals 926 926 Terms or concepts of this sort are
transcendental in the sense that they transcend or are superordinate to all
classificatory categories. The classical doctrine of the transcendentals,
developed in detail in the later Middle Ages, presupposes an Aristotelian
ontology according to which all beings are substances or accidents classifiable
within one of the ten highest genera, the ten Aristotelian categories. In this
scheme being Grecian on, Latin ens is not itself one of the categories since
all categories mark out kinds of being. But neither is it a category above the
ten categories of substance and accidents, an ultimate genus of which the ten
categories are species. This is because being is homonymous or equivocal, i.e.,
there is no single generic property or nature shared by members of each
category in virtue of which they are beings. The ten categories identify ten
irreducible, most basic ways of being. Being, then, transcends the categorial
structure of the world: anything at all that is ontologically classifiable is a
being, and to say of anything that it is a being is not to identify it as a
member of some kind distinct from other kinds of things. According to this
classical doctrine, being is the primary transcendental, but there are other
terms or concepts that transcend the categories in a similar way. The most
commonly recognized transcendentals other than being are one unum, true verum,
and good bonum, though some medieval philosophers also recognized thing res,
something aliquid, and beautiful pulchrum. These other terms or concepts are
transcendental because the ontological ground of their application to a given
thing is precisely the same as the ontological ground in virtue of which that
thing can be called a being. For example, for a thing with a certain nature to
be good is for it to perform well the activity that specifies it as a thing of
that nature, and to perform this activity well is to have actualized that
nature to a certain extent. But for a thing to have actualized its nature to
some extent is just what it is for the thing to have being. So the actualities
or properties in virtue of which a thing is good are precisely those in virtue
of which it has being. Given this account, medieval philosophers held that
transcendental terms are convertible convertuntur or extensionally equivalent
idem secundum supposita. They are not synonymous, however, since they are
intensionally distinct differunt secundum rationem. These secondary
transcendentals are sometimes characterized as attributes passiones of being
that are necessarily concomitant with it. In the modern period, the notion of
the transcendental is associated primarily with Kant, who made ‘transcendental’
a central technical term in his philosophy. For Kant the term no longer
signifies that which transcends categorial classification but that which
transcends our experience in the sense of providing its ground or structure.
Kant allows, e.g., that the pure forms of intuition space and time and the pure
concepts of understanding categories such as substance and cause are
transcendental in this sense. Forms and concepts of this sort constitute the
conditions of the possibility of experience.
transcendentalism, a religious-philosophical viewpoint
held by a group of New England intellectuals, of whom Emerson, Thoreau, and
Theodore Parker were the most important. A distinction taken over from Samuel
Taylor Coleridge was the only bond that universally united the members of the
Transcendental Club, founded in 1836: the distinction between the understanding
and reason, the former providing uncertain knowledge of appearances, the latter
a priori knowledge of necessary truths gained through intuition. The
transcendentalists insisted that philosophical truth could be reached only by
reason, a capacity common to all people unless destroyed by living a life of
externals and accepting as true only secondhand traditional beliefs. On almost
every other point there were disagreements. Emerson was an idealist, while
Parker was a natural realist they simply
had conflicting a priori intuitions. Emerson, Thoreau, and Parker rejected the
supernatural aspects of Christianity, pointing out its unmistakable parochial
nature and sociological development; while James Marsh, Frederick Henry Hedge,
and Caleb Henry remained in the Christian fold. The influences on the
transcendentalists differed widely and explain the diversity of opinion. For
example, Emerson was influenced by the Platonic tradition, G. Romanticism,
Eastern religions, and nature poets, while Parker was influenced by modern
science, the Scottish realism of Reid and Cousin which also emphasized a priori
intuitions, and the G. Higher Critics. Emerson, Thoreau, and Parker were also
bonded by negative beliefs. They not only rejected Calvinism but Unitarianism
as well; they rejected the ordinary concept of material success and put in its
place an Aristotelian type of selfrealization that emphasized the rational and
moral self as the essence of humanity and decried idiosyncratic
self-realization that admires what is unique in people as constituting their
real value.
trans-finitum: definitum, infinitum: Trans-finite number, in set
theory, an infinite cardinal or ordinal number.
transformation – Grice: “My system G makes minimal use
of transformations” -- minimal transformation rule: an axiom-schema or rule of
inference. Grice: “Strictly, an Ovidian metamorphose!” -- A transformation rule
is thus a rule for transforming a possibly empty set of wellformed formulas
into a formula, where that rule operates only upon syntactic information. It
was this conception of an axiom-schema and rule of inference that was one of
the keys to creating a genuinely rigorous science of deductive reasoning. In
the 0s, the idea was imported into linguistics, giving rise to the notion of a
transformational rule. Such a rule transforms tree structures into tree
structures, taking one from the deep structure of a sentence, which determines
its semantic interpretation, to the surface structure of that sentence, which
determines its phonetic interpretation. Grice: “Chomsky misuses
‘transformation.’”
triangulus -- Grice’s triangle. He uses the word in “Meaning
Revisited,” (WoW: 286). It’s the semiotic triange between what he calls the
‘communication device,’ the denotatum, and the soul. While
often referred to as H. P. Grice’s triangle, or H. P. Grice’s semiotic
triangle, or "Ogden/Richards triangle" the idea is also expressed in
1810, by Bernard Bolzano, in his rather obscure, Grice grants, “Beiträge zu
einer begründeteren Darstellung der Mathematik.” However, the triangle can be
traced back to the 4th century BC, in Aristotle's Peri Hermeneias (often
referred to in its Latin translation De Interpretatione, second book of his
Organon, on which Grice gave seminars as University Lecturer at Oxford with J.
L. Austin). H. P. Grice’s semiotic Triangle relates to the problem of
universals, a philosophical debate which split ancient and medieval
philosophers (mainly realists and nominalists). The triangle describes a
simplified form of relationship between the emissor as subject, a concept as
object or referent or denotatum, and its designation (sign, signans, or as
Grice prefers ‘communication device’). For more elaborated research see
Semiotics. Ogden semiotic triangle.png Contents 1Interlocutory
applications 1.1Other triangles 1.2The communicative stand 1.3Direction of fit
2See also 3References 4External links Interlocutory applications Other
triangles The relations between the triangular corners may be phrased more
precisely in causal terms as follows[citation needed][original research?]. The
matter evokes the emissor's soul. The emissor refers the matter to the symbol.
The symbol evokes the emissee’s soul. The emissee refers the symbol back to the
matter. The communicative stand Such a triangle represents ONE agent, the
emissor, whereas communication takes place between TWO (objects, not
necessarily agents). So imagine another triangle and consider that for the two
to understand each other, the content that the "triangles" represent
must fit or be aligned. Clearly, this calls for synchronisation and an interface
as well as scale among other things. Notice also, that we perceive the world
mostly through our eyes and in alternative phases of seeing and not seeing with
change in the environment as the most important information to look for. Our
eyes are lenses and we see a surface (2D) in ONE direction (focusing) if we are
stationary and the object is not moving either. This is why you may position
yourself in one corner of the triangle and by replicating (mirroring) it, you
will be able to see the whole picture, your cognitive epistemological and the
ontological existential or physical model of life, the universe, existence,
etc. combined.[citation needed][original research?] Direction of fit Main
article: Direction of fit This section has multiple issues. Please help improve
it or discuss these issues on the talk page. (Learn how and when to remove
these template messages) This section does not cite any sources. (December
2012) This section is written like a personal reflection, personal essay, or
argumentative essay that states a Wikipedia editor's personal feelings or
presents an original argument about a topic. (December 2012) Grice uses the
notion of "direction of fit" (in “Intention and Uncertainty”) to
create a taxonomy of acts. [3] [4] This table possibly contains
original research. Please improve it by verifying the claims made and adding
inline citations. Statements consisting only of original research should be
removed. (December 2012) (Learn how and when to remove this template message)
World or Referentintended →Writer's Thought decoded ↑ ↓
encoded Thought Emissee's← extendedSymbol or Word Emissor's
THOUGHT retrieves SYMBOL suited to REFERENT, Word suited to World.
Reader's THOUGHT retrieves REFERENT suited to SYMBOL, World suited to
Word. Actually the arrows indicate that there is something exchanged between
the two parties and it is a feedback cycle. Especially, if you imagine that the
world is represented in the soul of both the emissor and the emissee and used
for reality check. If you look at the triangle above again, remember that
reality check is not what is indicated there between the sign and the referent
and marked as "true', because a term or a sign is allocated
"arbitrarily'. What you check for is the observance of the law of identity
which requires you and your partner to sort out that you are on the same page,
that the emissor is communicating and the emissee is understanding about the
same thing. So the chunk of reality and the term are
replaceable/interchangeable within limits and your concepts in the soul as
presented in some appropriate way are all related and mean the same thing.
Usually the check does not stop there, your ideas must also be tested for
feasibility and doability to make sure that they are "real" and not
"phantasy". Reality check comes from consolidating your experience
with other people's experience to avoid solipsism and/or by putting your ideas
(projection) in practice (production) and see the reaction. Notice, however how
vague the verbs used and how the concept of a fit itself is left unexplained in
details.[editorializing] See also The Delta Factor De dicto De se De re
References Colin Cherry (1957) On Human Communication C. K. Ogden
and I. A. Richards (1923) The Meaning of Meaning John Searle (1975)
"A Taxonomy of Illocutionary Acts", in: Gunderson, K. (ed.),
Language, Mind, and Knowledge (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press) pp.
344-369. John Searle (1976) "A Classification of Illocutionary
Acts", Language in Society, Vol.5, pp. 1-24. External links Jessica
Erickstad (1998) Richards' Meaning of Meaning Theory. University of Colorado at
Boulder. Allie Cahill (1998) "Proper Meaning Superstition" (I. A.
Richards). University of Colorado at Boulder. Categories:
SemioticsSemanticsPragmaticsPhilosophy of languagePhilosophy of mind.
Semiotisches Dreieck Zur Navigation springen. Zur Suche springen. Das
semiotische Dreieck stellt die Relation zwischen dem Symbol, dem dadurch
hervorgerufenen Begriff und dem damit gemeinten realen Ding dar. Das
semiotische Dreieck ist ein in der Sprachwissenschaft und Semiotik verwendetes
Modell. Es soll veranschaulichen, dass ein Zeichenträger (Graphem, Syntagma,
Symbol) sich nicht direkt und unmittelbar auf einen außersprachlichen
Gegenstand bezieht, sondern dieser Bezug nur mittelbar durch eine
Vorstellung/einen Begriff erfolgt. Das semiotische Dreieck publizierten
erstmals Charles Kay Ogden und Ivor Armstrong Richards in dem Werk The Meaning
of Meaning. Das semiotische Dreieck in vereinfachter Beschreibung. Die Welt
besteht aus Gegenständen, Sachverhalten, Ereignissen und Ähnlichem. Diese sind
wirklich und bestimmen alles, was geschieht. Das Symbol für ein Einzelnes davon
steht in den folgenden Dreiecken rechts und bedeutet vereinfacht: Ding oder
„was Sache ist“. Wenn der Mensch ein Ding bemerkt oder sich vorstellt, macht er
sich ein gedachtes Bild davon. Das Symbol dafür steht in den folgenden
Dreiecken oben und bedeutet: Begriff oder „was man meint“. Wenn Menschen mit
diesen Begriffen von Dingen reden, so verwenden sie Zeichen (meist hörbar,
gelegentlich auch sichtbar oder anders wahrnehmbar). Das sind Wörter (auch
Bezeichnungen, Benennungen, Symbole oder Ähnliches). Das Symbol dafür steht in
den folgenden DREIECKEN links und bedeutet: Wort oder „was man dazu sagt“.
Ding, Begriff und Wort sollen eindeutig zusammengehören. Das gelingt nicht
immer, vielmehr muss man immerzu aufpassen, ob der eben verwendete Begriff das
betrachtete Ding richtig erfasst, ob das eben verwendete Wort den gemeinten
Begriff trifft, und sogar ob das eben betrachtete Ding überhaupt eins ist und
nicht etwa einige oder gar keins. Passen die drei Ecken nicht zueinander, „So
entstehen leicht die fundamentalsten Verwechslungen (deren die ganze
Philosophie voll ist).“ Vitters: Tractatus 3.324. Das semiotische Dreieck
als bildliche Darstellung der Mehrdimensionalität der Zeichen
Begriff /\ / \
/ \ / \
/ \ Zeichen ...... Gegenstand (Wort) (Ding). Das
semiotische Dreieck ist zunächst nur ein bildliches Hilfsmittel, um sich
Beziehungen „im“ bzw. „des“ Zeichens zu veranschaulichen. Seine Interpretation
und nähere Ausgestaltung hängt daher von der zugrunde gelegten
Erkenntnistheorie ab. In entscheidender Weise wird durch das semiotische
Dreieck veranschaulicht, dass zwischen dem Wort (der Zeichenform, d. h. dem
Schriftbild oder dem Lautbild) und dem Bezeichneten (Ding, Gegenstand) keine
direkte Beziehung, sondern nur durch (mindestens) eine hier so genannte
Vermittlungsinstanz vermittelte Beziehung besteht. Graphisch wird dies durch
eine unterschiedliche Linie dargestellt. Gebräuchlich ist ein Dreieck.
Entscheidend ist die nicht-direkte Beziehung zwischen Zeichen (Wort) und
Gegenstand (Ding). Je nach Anzahl der zu veranschaulichenden (nicht
auszublendenden) Bezugspunkte und Vermittlungsinstanzen und der Art der
betonten Beziehungen kann man auch ein Quadrat, ein sonstiges Vieleck bzw.
einen mehrdimensionalen Körper benutzen. Darauf hinzuweisen ist, dass die
Vermittlungsinstanz – hier mit dem mehrdeutigen Ausdruck „Begriff“ bezeichnet –
sehr unterschiedlich gesehen wird, was aus dem Terminologiebefund unten
deutlich wird. Das semiotische Dreieck ist Veranschaulichung eines
Zeichenverständnisses, das dem Zeichenbegriff von Ferdinand de Saussure, wonach
ein Zeichen eine „psychische Einheit“ zwischen einem „akustischen Bild“
(Signifikanten) und einem „Begriff“ (Signifikat) (bei ihm im Sinne einer
psychischen Vorstellung)[2] sein soll, widersprechen dürfte:[3] statt der
„Papierblattmetapher“ für das Verhältnis von Signifikant/Signifikat (von de
Saussure) wird im semiotischen Dreieck eine optische Trennung und Distanzierung
von Zeichenkörper und Begriff (Sinn) vorgenommen. Das semiotische Dreieck
blendet auch pragmatische Bedingungen und Bezüge aus bzw. reduziert sie auf die
semantische Dimension und wird daher von pragmatischen Bedeutungstheorien
kritisiert (vgl. Semiotik). Das Fehlen einer unmittelbaren Beziehung
zwischen Zeichen und Gegenstand wird zugleich als Ausdruck der (von de Saussure
betonten) Arbitrarität und Konventionalität von Zeichen interpretiert.
Geschichte Man muss unterscheiden zwischen dem semiotischen Dreieck als Bild
und einem dreiseitigen (triadischen) Zeichenbegriff, dessen Veranschaulichung
es dient. Verbreitet wird die sprachwissenschaftliche Entwicklung so
dargestellt, als gäbe es ein semiotisches Dreieck erst seit Ogden/Richards, die
damit einen nur zweigliedrigen Zeichenbegriff von de Saussure
modifiziert/überwunden hätten.[4] Es heißt, bis ins 19. Jahrhundert sei der
Zeichenbegriff im Wesentlichen hinsichtlich seines Sachbezugs als „zweistellige
Relation“ diskutiert worden.[5] Andere betonen den zugrunde liegenden
dreiseitigen („triadischen“) Zeichenbegriff, der meist bei Aristoteles,
mitunter auch schon bei Platon angesetzt wird. Schon bei Platon findet
sich ein gedankliches Wort-Gegenstand-Modell zwischen Namen (Zeichen) – Idee
(Begriff) und Ding. Bei Aristoteles ist ein Zeichen (semeion, damit meint er
ein Wort) ein Symptom für eine Seelenregung, d. h. für etwas, das der Sprecher
sich vorstellt. Diese Vorstellung des Sprechers ist dann ein Ikon für ein Ding.
Dies sind für ihn die primären Zeichenrelationen (rot in der untenstehenden
Figur). Davon abgeleitet ist die sekundäre Zeichenrelation (schwarz in der
Figur). Das Semiotische Dreieck bei Aristoteles Seit Aristoteles
wird vertreten, dass Zeichen Dinge der Welt nicht unvermittelt, sondern
vermittelt über einen „Begriff“, „Vorstellung“ etc. bezeichnen. Dies bedeutet
eine Differenzierung gegenüber der einfachen aliquid-stat-pro-aliquo-Konzeption
und ist „für die ganze Geschichte der Semiotik entscheidend“. Bei Aristoteles
stehen „Zeichen […] für Sachen, welche von den Bewußtseinsinhalten abgebildet
worden sind“. „Die Sachen werden von den Zeichen nicht präsentiert, sondern
repräsentiert.“. Die Interpretation von De interpretatione ist dabei seit
Jahrtausenden kontrovers. Die oben wiedergegebene Interpretation entspricht
einer psychologischen Deutung, die einen Psychologismus nahelegt. Dies
erscheint fraglich, da Aristoteles eher einen erkenntnistheoretischen Realismus
vertreten haben dürfte. Scholastik In der Sprachphilosophie der
Scholastik finden sich Überlegungen zum Dreierschema res (Sache, Ding),
intellectus (Verstand, Gedanken, Begriff), vox (Wortzeichen). Logik von
Port-Royal. In der Grammatik von Port-Royal (Mitte des 17. Jh.) soll das
semiotische Dreieck eingeführt worden sein.[10] In der Logik von Port-Royal
sind die Gegenstände und die Sprachzeichen nicht unmittelbar, sondern über
Universalien miteinander verknüpft. Nach KANT ist das zwischen Begrifflichkeit
und Sinnlichkeit bzw. Gegenstand vermittelnde Element das Schema als ein
bildhaftes und anschauliches Zeichen. Das Verfahren des Verstandes, mit Hilfe
der ‚Einbildungskraft‘ die reinen Verstandesbegriffe zu versinnlichen, heißt
Schematismus. Auch Arthur Schopenhauer, ein deutscher Philosoph des 19.
Jahrhunderts, unterscheidet in seinem Hauptwerk Die Welt als Wille und
Vorstellung strikt zwischen Wort, Begriff und Anschauung. Ausblendung des
Referenzbezugs im Zeichenmodell von de Saussure Nach verbreiteter Auffassung
haben die moderne Sprachwissenschaft und der moderne Zeichenbegriff erst mit de
Saussure eingesetzt. Nach de Saussure ist ein Zeichen die Verbindung eines
Ausdrucks (signifiant) mit einem Inhalt (signifié), wobei das Zeichen als
„psychische Einheit mit zwei Seiten“[14] aufgefasst wurde. In diesem
zweigliedrigen (dyadischen) Zeichenmodell „hat die reale Welt keine
Bedeutung“:[15] „Hier Bezeichnetes als geistige Vorstellung, dort Bezeichnendes
als dessen Materialisation in der Sprache, aber kein Platz für das Objekt
selbst“. Triadisches Zeichenmodells bei Peirce. Charles S. Peirce entwickelte
eine pragmatische Semiotik[16] und die Pragmatik soll auf dem triadischen
Zeichenmodell von Peirce beruhen.[17] Statt eines dyadischen entwickelte Peirce
ein kommunikativ-pragmatisches, triadisches Zeichenmodell: das Zeichen ist eine
„triadische Relation (semiotisches Dreieck)“. Dies, indem er zu Zeichenmittel
und Objekt den „Interpretanten“ ergänzte, d. h. die Bedeutung, die durch
Interpretation der Zeichenbenutzer (Sprecher bzw. Hörer) in einem
Handlungszusammenhang zustande kommt. „Das, was als Bewusstseinsinhalt
erscheint, der Interpretant, ist der individuell erkannte Sinn, der seinerseits
kulturell vor- oder mitgeprägt sein kann. Daher wird in diesem Konzept die Zeichenbedeutung
(…) auch als „kulturelle Einheit“ (Eco, 1972) postuliert.“Peirce-Interpreten
wie Floyd Merrell oder Gerhard Schönrich wenden sich gegen die
Dreiecksdarstellung peircescher Zeichentriaden, da sie suggerieren könnte, dass
sich die irreduzible triadische Relation zerlegen lasse in einzelne
zweistellige Relationen. Stattdessen schlagen sie eine Y-förmige Darstellung
vor, bei der die drei Relate jeweils durch eine Linie mit dem Mittelpunkt
verbunden sind, aber entlang der Seiten des „Dreiecks“ keine Linien
verlaufen. Charles Kay Ogden / Ivor Armstrong Richards Als „die“
Vertreter eines dreiseitigen Zeichenmodells bzw. eines semiotischen Dreiecks
(unter Ausblendung ihrer Vorläufer) werden verbreitet Charles Kay Ogden und
Ivor Armstrong Richards angeführt. Diese erkannten eine Welt außerhalb des
menschlichen Bewusstseins ausdrücklich an und wandten sich gegen „idealistische
Konzepte“. Nach Charles Kay Ogden und Ivor Armstrong Richards symbolisiert das
Zeichen (symbol) etwas und ruft einen entsprechenden Bewusstseinsinhalt
(reference) hervor, der sich auf das Objekt (referent) bezieht.[6] Das
semiotische Dreieck wird wie folgt erklärt: „Umweltsachverhalte werden im
Gedächtnis begrifflich bzw. konzeptuell repräsentiert und mit Sprachzeichen
assoziiert. So ist z. B. das Wort „Baum“ ein Sprachzeichen, das mit dem Begriff
bzw. Konzept von „BAUM“ assoziiert ist und über diesen auf reale Bäume (Buchen,
Birken, Eichen usw.) verweisen kann.“. Siehe auch Organon-Modell (von Karl
Bühler) Literatur Metamorphosen des semiotischen Dreieck. In: Zeitschrift für
Semiotik. Band 10, (darin 8 einzelne Artikel). Umberto Eco: Semiotik – Entwurf
einer Theorie der Zeichen. 2. Auflage. Wilhelm Fink Verlag, München 1991, ISBN
3-7705-2323-7. Umberto Eco: Einführung in die Semiotik. Wilhelm Fink Verlag,
München 1994, ISBN 3-7705-0633-2. Einzelnachweise C. K. Ogden, I. A.
Richards: The Meaning of Meaning. 1923 Kassai: Sinn. In: Martinet
(Hrsg.): Linguistik. Ohne Problematisierung trotz der Nähe zu Saussure hingegen
bei Kassai: Sinn. In: Martinet (Hrsg.): Linguistik. 1973, S. 251 (S. 254 f.)
referiert So wohl Fischer Kolleg Abiturwissen, Deutsch (2002), S.
27 So z. B. Schülerduden, Philosophie (2002), Semiotik Triadische
Zeichenrelation. In: Homberger: Sachwörterbuch zur Sprachwissenschaft.
2000 Trabant: Semiotik. Trabant: Semiotik. So auch Triadische
Zeichenrelation. In: Homberger: Sachwörterbuch zur Sprachwissenschaft. 2000,
wonach Aristoteles das Platonische Modell „psychologisiert“ haben soll So
Schülerduden, Philosophie (2002), Sprachphilosophie Schülerduden,
Philosophie (2002), Sprachphilosophie Baumgartner: Kants „Kritik der
reinen Vernunft“, Anleitung zur Lektüre. [1988], neu ersch. 5. Auflage. ALBER,
Freiburg Hierzu vor allem das Kapitel: „Zur Lehre von der abstrakten, oder
Vernunft-Erkenntnis“ (Zweiter Band) Fischer Kolleg Abiturwissen, Deutsch
(2002), S. 26 Ernst: Pragmalinguistik. 2002, S. 66 Schülerduden,
Philosophie (2002), Peirce So Pelz: Linguistik. 1996, S. 242
Zeichenprozess. In: Homberger: Sachwörterbuch zur Sprachwissenschaft.
2000 Bedeutung. In: Homberger: Sachwörterbuch zur Sprachwissenschaft.
2000 Kategorien: SemiotikSemantik. For Grice, the triangle represents the three
correspondences. First, psychophysical, second psychosemiotic, and third semio-physical.
trinitarianism, -- “Raining, raining, raining.” -- the
theological doctrine that God consists of three persons, “in Strawson’s usage
of the expression” – Vide Grice, “Personal identity,” -- The persons who
constitute the Holy Trinity are the Father; the Son, who is Jesus Christ; and
the Holy Spirit or Holy Ghost. The doctrine states that each of these three
persons is God and yet they are not three Gods but one God. According to a
traditional formulation, the three persons are but one substance. In the
opinion of Aquinas, the existence of God can be proved by human reason, but the
existence of the three persons cannot be proved and is known only by
revelation. According to Christian tradition, revelation contains information
about the relations among the three persons, and these relations ground proper
attributes of each that distinguish them from one another. Thus, since the
Father begets the Son, a proper attribute of the Father is paternity and a
proper attribute of the Son is filiation. Procession transparent Trinitarianism
928 928 or spiration is a proper
attribute of the Holy Spirit. A disagreement about procession has contributed
to dividing Eastern and Western Christianity. The Eastern Orthodox church teaches
that the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Father through the Son. A theory of
double procession according to which the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Father
and the Son has been widely accepted in the West. This disagreement is known as
the filioque ‘and the Son’ controversy because it arose from the fact that
adding this Latin phrase to the Nicene Creed became acceptable in the West but
not in the East. Unitarianism denies that God consists of three persons and so
is committed to denying the divinity of Jesus. The monotheistic faiths of Judaism
and Islam are unitarian, but there are unitarians who consider themselves
Christians. H. P. Grice, “Raining, raining, raining – my mother and the
Trinitarians.”
troeltsch: philosopher whose primary aim was to provide a
scientific foundation for theology. Educated at Erlangen, Göttingen under
Ritschl and Lagarde, and Berlin, he initially taught theology at Heidelberg and
later philosophy in Berlin. He launched the school of history of religion with
his epoch-making “On Historical and Dogmatical Method in Theology” 6. His
contributions to theology The Religious Apriori, 4, philosophy, sociology, and
history Historicism and Its Problems, 2 were vastly influential. Troeltsch
claimed that only a philosophy of religion drawn from the history and
development of religious consciousness could strengthen the standing of the
science of religion among the sciences and advance the Christian strategy
against materialism, naturalism, skepticism, aestheticism, and pantheism. His
historical masterpiece, Protestantism and Progress 6, argues that early
Protestantism was a modified medieval Catholicism that delayed the development
of modern culture. As a sociologist, he addressed, in The Social Teachings of
the Christian Churches 2, the twofold issue of whether religious beliefs and
movements are conditioned by external factors and whether, in turn, they affect
society and culture. From Christian social history he inferred three types of
“sociological self-formation of the Christian idea”: the church, the sect, and
the mystic
transversum -- Transversality – a term Grice borrowed from
Heidegger – ‘the greatest philosopher that ever lived.” -- transcendence of the sovereignty of identity
or self-sameness by recognizing the alterity of the Other as Unterschied to use Heidegger’s term which signifies the sense of relatedness by
way of difference. An innovative idea employed and appropriated by such diverse
philosophers as Merleau-Ponty, Sartre, Gilles Deleuze, and Félix Guattari,
transversality is meant to replace the Eurocentric formulation of truth as
universal in an age when the world is said to be rushing toward the global
village. Universality has been a Eurocentric idea because what is particular in
the West is universalized, whereas what is particular elsewhere remains particularized.
Since its center is everywhere and its circumference nowhere, truth is
polycentric and correlative. Particularly noteworthy is the phenomenologist Calvin O. Schrag’s attempt to
appropriate transversality by splitting the difference between the two extremes
of absolutism and relativism on the one hand and modernity’s totalizing
practices and postmodernity’s fragmentary tendencies on the other.
tropic: Grice: “Cf. Cicero, ‘Tropicus, and
sub-tropicus’ –“ used by R. M. Hare and H. P. Grice – Hare introduced the
‘tropic’ to contrast with the ‘phrastic,’ the ‘neustic,’ and the ‘clistic’ – “I
often wondered if Hare was not distinguishing too narrowly” – H. P. Grice
--trope, in recent philosophical usage, an “abstract particular”; an instance
of a property occurring at a particular place and time, such as the color of
the cover of this book or this . The whiteness of this and the whiteness of the previous are two distinct tropes, identical neither
with the universal whiteness that is instantiated in both s, nor with the itself; although the whiteness of this cannot exist independently of this ,
this could be dyed some other color. A
number of writers, perhaps beginning with D. C. Williams, have argued that
tropes must be included in our ontology if we are to achieve an adequate
metaphysics. More generally, a trope is a figure of speech, or the use of an
expression in a figurative or nonliteral sense. Metaphor and irony, e.g., fall
under the category of tropes. If you are helping someone move a glass table but
drop your end, and your companion says, “Well, you’ve certainly been a big
help,” her utterance is probably ironical, with the intended meaning that you
have been no help. One important question is whether, in order to account for
the ironical use of this sentence, we must suppose that it has an ironical
meaning in addition to its literal meaning. Quite generally, does a sentence
usable to express two different metaphors have, in addition to its literal
meaning, two metaphorical meanings and another
if it can be hyperbolic, and so forth? Many philosophers and other theorists
from Aristotle on have answered yes, and postulated such figurative meanings in
addition to literal sentence meaning. Recently, philosophers loath to multiply
sentence meanings have denied that sentences have any non-literal
meanings.Their burden is to explain how, e.g., a sentence can be used
ironically if it does not have an ironical sense or meaning. Such philosophers
disagree on whether tropes are to be explained semantically or pragmatically. A
semantic account might hypothesize that tropes are generated by violations of
semantical rules. An important pragmatic approach is Grice’s suggestion that
tropes can be subsumed under the more general phenomenon of conversational implicaturum.
tukey’s bit: from binary digit, a unit or measure of information.
Suggested by John W. Tukey, a bit is both an amount of information a reduction
of eight equally likely possibilities to one generates three bits [% log2 8] of
information and a system of representing that quantity. The binary system uses
1’s and 0’s.
Turing: Grice: “While not a philosopher, Turing’s thought
experiment is about the ‘conceptual analysis’ of ‘thought’” --similar to a
Griceian machine -- a machine, an
abstract automaton or imagined computer consisting of a finite automaton
operating an indefinitely long storage tape. The finite automaton provides the
computing power of the machine. The tape is used for input, output, and
calculation workspace; in the case of the universal Turing machine, it also
specifies another Turing machine. Initially, only a finite number of squares of
the tape are marked with symbols, while the rest are blank. The finite
automaton part of the machine has a finite number of internal states and
operates discretely, at times t % 0, 1, 2, . . . . At each time-step the
automaton examines the tape square under its tape head, possibly changes what
is there, moves the tape left or right, and then changes its internal state.
The law governing this sequence of actions is deterministic and is defined in a
state table. For each internal state and each tape symbol or blank under the
tape head, the state table describes the tape action performed by the machine
and gives the next internal state of the machine. Since a machine has only a
finite number of internal states and of tape symbols, the state table of a
machine is finite in length and can be stored on a tape. There is a universal
Turing machine Mu that can simulate every Turing machine including itself: when
the state table of any machine M is written on the tape of Mu, the universal
machine Mu will perform the same input-output computation that M performs. Mu
does this by using the state table of M to calculate M’s complete history for
any given input. Turing machines may be thought of as conceptual devices for
enumerating the elements of an infinite set e.g., the theorems of a formal
language, or as decision machines e.g., deciding of any truth-functional
formula whether it is a tautology. A. M. Turing showed that there are welldefined
logical tasks that cannot be carried out by any machine; in particular, no
machine can solve the halting problem. Turing’s definition of a machine was
theoretical; it was not a practical specification for a machine. After the
modern electronic computer was invented, he proposed a test for judging whether
there is a computer that is behaviorally equivalent to a human in reasoning and
intellectual creative power. The Turing test is a “black box” type of
experiment that Turing proposed as a way of deciding whether a computer can
think. Two rooms are fitted with the same input-output equipment going to an
outside experimenter. A person is placed in one room and a programmed
electronic computer in the other, each in communication with the experimenter. By
issuing instructions and asking questions, the experimenter tries to decide
which room has the computer and which the human. If the experimenter cannot
tell, that outcome is strong evidence that the computer can think as well as
the person. More directly, it shows that the computer and the human are
equivalent for all the behaviors tested. Since the computer is a finite
automaton, perhaps the most significant test task is that of doing creative
mathematics about the non-enumerable infinite.
Turnbull: philosopher, was briefly a philosophy regent at
Aberdeen and a teacher of Reid. His Principles of Moral and Christian
Philosophy 1740 and Discourse upon the Nature and Origin of Moral and Civil
Laws 1741 show him as the most systematic of those who aimed to recast moral
philosophy on a Newtonian model, deriving moral laws “experimentally” from
human psychology. In A Treatise on Ancient Painting 1740, Observations Upon
Liberal Education 1742, and some smaller works, he extolled history and the
arts as propaedeutic to the teaching of virtue and natural religion. Grice
calls him a “moral-sense philosopher”
tychism: from Grecian tyche, ‘chance’, Peirce’s doctrine that
there is absolute chance in the universe and its fundamental laws are
probabilistic and inexact. Peirce’s tychism is part of his evolutionary
cosmology, according to which all regularities of nature are products of growth
and development, i.e., results of evolution. The laws of nature develop over
time and become increasingly rigid and exact; the apparently deterministic laws
of physics are limiting cases of the basic, probabilistic laws. Underlying all
other laws is “the tendency of all things to take habits”; Peirce calls this
the Law of Habit. In his cosmology his tychism is associated with synechism,
the doctrine of the continuity of nature. His synechism involves the doctrine
of the continuity of mind and matter; Peirce sometimes expressed this view by
saying that “matter is effete mind.”
type: v.
Grice’s three-year-old’s guide to Russell’s theory of type
U
ubaldi: Italian philosopher. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Ubalid e
Grice,” per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice,
Liguria, Italia.
uncertainty: one of those negativisims by Grice – cfr.
‘non-certainty’ -- v. certum. It may be held that ‘uncertain’ is wrong. Grice
is certain that p. It is not the case that Grice is certain that p.
unexpected
examination paradox, a paradox about
belief and prediction. One version is as follows: It seems that a teacher could
both make, and act on, the following announcement to his class: “Sometime
during the next week I will set you an examination, but at breakfast time on
the day it will occur, you will have no good reason to expect that it will
occur on that day.” If he announces this on Friday, could he not do what he
said he would by, say, setting the examination on the following Wednesday? The
paradox is that there is an argument purporting to show that there could not be
an unexpected examination of this kind. For let us suppose that the teacher
will carry out his threat, in both its parts; i.e., he will set an examination,
and it will be unexpected. Then he cannot set the examination on Friday
assuming this to be the last possible day of the week. For, by the time Friday
breakfast arrives, and we know that all the previous days have been
examination-free, we would have every reason to expect the examination to occur
on Friday. So leaving the examination until Friday is inconsistent with setting
an unexpected examination. For similar reasons, the examination cannot be held
on Thursday. Given our previous conclusion that it cannot be delayed until
Friday, we would know, when Thursday morning came, and the previous days had
been examination-free, that it would have to be held on Thursday. So if it were
held on Thursday it would not be unexpected. So it cannot be held on Thursday.
Similar reasoning sup938 U 938 posedly
shows that there is no day of the week on which it can be held, and so
supposedly shows that the supposition that the teacher can carry out his threat
must be rejected. This is paradoxical, for it seems plain that the teacher can
carry out his threat. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Grice’s book of paradoxes, with
pictures and illustrations to confuse you.”
uniformity of
nature – Grice: “’uniformity’ has
nothing to do with ‘form’ here!” – Grice: “I once used the phrase in a tutorial
with Hardie: “What do you mean by ‘of’?’ he asked” -- a state of affairs thought to be required if
induction is to be justified. For example, inductively strong arguments, such
as ‘The sun has risen every day in the past; therefore, the sun will rise
tomorrow’, are thought to presuppose that nature is uniform in the sense that
the future will resemble the past, in this case with respect to the diurnal
cycle. The Scottish empiricist Hume was the first to make explicit that the
uniformity of nature is a substantial assumption in inductive reasoning. Hume
argued that, because the belief that the future will resemble the past cannot
be grounded in experience for the future
is as yet unobserved induction cannot be
rationally justified; appeal to it in defense of induction is either
question-begging or illicitly metaphysical. Francis Bacon’s “induction by
enumeration” and J. S. Mill’s “five methods of experimental inquiry” presuppose
that nature is uniform. Whewell appealed to the uniformity of nature in order
to account for the “consilience of inductions,” the tendency of a hypothesis to
explain data different from those it was originally introduced to explain. For
reasons similar to Hume’s, Popper holds that our belief in the uniformity of
nature is a matter of faith. Reichenbach held that although this belief cannot
be justified in advance of any instance of inductive reasoning, its
presupposition is vindicated by successful inductions. It has proved difficult
to formulate a philosophical statement of the uniformity of nature that is both
coherent and informative. It appears contradictory to say that nature is
uniform in all respects, because inductive inferences always mark differences
of some sort e.g., from present to future, from observed to unobserved, etc.,
and it seems trivial to say that nature is uniform in some respects, because
any two states of nature, no matter how different, will be similar in some
respect. Not all observed regularities in the world or in data are taken to
support successful inductive reasoning; not all uniformities are, to use Goodman’s
term, “projectible.” Philosophers of science have therefore proposed various
rules of projectibility, involving such notions as simplicity and explanatory
power, in an attempt to distinguish those observed patterns that support
successful inductions and thus are taken to represent genuine causal relations
from those that are accidental or spurious.
unity in
diversity, in aesthetics, the
principle that the parts of the aesthetic object must cohere or hang together
while at the same time being different enough to allow for the object to be
complex. This principle defines an important formal requirement used in judging
aesthetic objects. If an object has insufficient unity e.g., a collection of
color patches with no recognizable patterns of any sort, it is chaotic or lacks
harmony; it is more a collection than one object. But if it has insufficient
diversity e.g., a canvas consisting entirely of one color with no internal
differentiations, it is monotonous. Thus, the formal pattern desired in an
aesthetic object is that of complex parts that differ significantly from each
other but fit together to form one interdependent whole such that the character
or meaning of the whole would be changed by the change of any part.
universal
instantiation: Grice: “Slightly
confusing in that the universe is not a pluri-verse.” -- discussed by Grice in
his System G -- also called universal quantifier elimination. 1 The argument
form ‘Everything is f; therefore a is f’, and arguments of this form. 2 The
rule of inference that permits one to infer that any given thing is f from the
premise that everything is f. In classical logic, where all terms are taken to
denote things in the domain of discourse, the rule says simply that from vA[v]
one may infer A[t], the result of replacing all free occurrences of v in A[v]
by the term t. If non-denoting terms are allowed, however, as in free logic,
then the rule would require an auxiliary premise of the form Duu % t to ensure
that t denotes something in the range of the variable v. Likewise in modal
logic, which is sometimes held to contain terms that do not denote “genuine
individuals” the things over which variables range, an auxiliary premise may be
required. 3 In higher-order logic, the rule of inference that says that from
XA[X] one may infer A[F], where F is any expression of the grammatical category
e.g., n-ary predicate appropriate to that of X e.g., n-ary predicate variable.
universale: Grice: “Very Ciceronian – not found in Aristotle.” --
Like ‘qualia,’ which is the plural for ‘quale,’ ‘universalia’ is the plural for
‘universale.’ The totum for Grice on “all” -- This is a Gricism. It all started
with arbor porphyriana. It is supposed to translate Aristotle’s “to kath’olou”
(which happens to be one of the categories in Kant, “alleheit,” and which
Aristotle contrasts with “to kath’ekastou,” (which Kant has as a category,
SINGULARITAS. For a nominalist, any predicate is a ‘name,’ hence ‘nominalism.’
Opposite ‘realism.’ “Nominalism” is actually a misnomer. The opposite of
realism is anti-realism. We need something like ‘universalism,’ (he who
believes in the existence, not necessary ‘reality’ of a universal) and a
‘particularist,’ or ‘singularist,’ who does not. Note that the opposite of
‘particularism,’ is ‘totalism.’ (Totum et pars). Grice holds a set-theoretical
approach to the universalium. Grice is willing to provide always a
set-theoretical extensionalist (in terms of predicate) and an intensionalist
variant in terms of property and category. Grice explicitly uses ‘X’ for utterance-type
(WOW:118), implying a distinction with the utterance-token. Grice gets engaged
in a metabolical debate concerning the reductive analysis of what an
utterance-type means in terms of a claim to the effect that, by uttering
x, an utterance-token of utterance-type X, the utterer means that p. The
implicaturum is x (utterance-token). Grice is not enamoured with the type/token
or token/type distinction. His thoughts on logical form are provocative. f
you cannot put it in logical form, it is not worth saying. Strawson
infamously reacted with a smile. Oh, no: if you CAN put it in logical form, it
is not worth saying. Grice refers to the type-token distinction when he uses x
for token and X for type. Since Bennett cares to call Grice a meaning-nominalist
we should not care about the type X anyway. He expands on this in Retrospective
Epilogue. Grice should have payed more attention to the distinction seeing that
it was Ogdenian. A common mode of estimating the amount of matter in a
printed book is to count the number of words. There will ordinarily be about
twenty thes on a page, and, of course, they count as twenty words. In another
use of the word word, however, there is but one word the in the English
language; and it is impossible that this word should lie visibly on a page, or
be heard in any voice. Such a Form, Peirce, as cited by Ogden and Richards,
proposes to term a type. A single object such as this or that word on a single
line of a single page of a single copy of a book, Peirce ventures to call a token.
In order that a type may be used, it has to be embodied in a token which shall
be a sign of the type, and thereby of the object the type signifies, and Grice
followed suit. Refs.: Some of the sources are given under ‘abstractum.’ Also
under ‘grecianism,’ since Grice was keen on exploring what Aristotle has to say
about this in Categoriae, due to his joint research with Austin, Code,
Friedman, and Strawson. Grice also has a specific Peirceian essay on the
type-token distinction. BANC. Grice – “A Ciceronian technicism, not found in
Aristotle. -- (‘the altogether nice girl’) dictum de omni et nullo, also dici
de omni et nullo Latin, ‘said of all and none’, two principles that were
supposed by medieval logicians to underlie all valid syllogisms. Dictum de omni
applies most naturally to universal affirmative propositions, maintaining that
in such a proposition, whatever falls under the subject term also falls under
the predicate term. Thus, in ‘Every whale is a mammal’, whatever is included
under ‘whale’ is included under ‘mammal’. Dictum de nullo applies to universal
negative propositions, such as ‘No whale is a lizard’, maintaining that
whatever falls under the subject term does not fall under the predicate
term. SYLLOGISM. W.E.M. Diderot, Denis
171384, philosopher, Encyclopedist,
dramatist, novelist, and art critic, a champion of Enlightenment values. He is
known primarily as general editor of the Encyclopedia 174773, an analytical and
interpretive compendium of eighteenth-century science and technology. A friend
of Rousseau and Condillac, Diderot tr. Shaftesbury’s Inquiry Concerning Virtue
1745 into . Revealing Lucretian affinities Philosophical Thoughts, 1746, he
assailed Christianity in The Skeptics’ Walk 1747 and argued for a materialistic
and evolutionary universe Letter on the Blind, 1749; this led to a short
imprisonment. Diderot wrote mediocre bourgeois comedies; some bleak fiction The
Nun, 1760; and two satirical dialogues, Rameau’s Nephew 1767 and Jacques the
Fatalist 176584, his masterpieces. He innovatively theorized on drama Discourse
on Dramatic Poetry, 1758 and elevated art criticism to a literary genre Salons
in Grimm’s Literary Correspondence. At Catherine II’s invitation, Diderot
visited Saint Petersburg in 1773 and planned the creation of a Russian .
Promoting science, especially biology and chemistry, Diderot unfolded a
philosophy of nature inclined toward monism. His works include physiological
investigations, Letter on the Deaf and Dumb 1751 and Elements of Physiology
177480; a sensationalistic epistemology, On the Interpretation of Nature 1745;
an aesthetic, Essays on Painting 1765; a materialistic philosophy of science,
D’Alembert’s Dream 1769; an anthropology, Supplement to the Voyage of
Bougainville 1772; and an anti-behavioristic Refutation of Helvétius’ Work “On
Man” 177380.
universalisability: -- Grice: ‘Slightly confusing, in that the universe
is not a pluri-verse” -- discussed along three dimension by Grice:
applicational conceptual, and formal. -- 1 Since the 0s, the moral criterion
implicit in Kant’s first formulation of the categorical imperative: “Act only
on that maxim that you can at the same time will to be a universal law,” often
called the principle of universality. A maxim or principle of action that
satisfies this test is said to be universalizable, hence morally acceptable;
one that does not is said to be not universalizable, hence contrary to duty. 2
A second sense developed in connection with the work of Hare in the 0s. For
Hare, universalizability is “common to all judgments which carry descriptive
meaning”; so not only normative claims moral and evaluative judgments but also
empirical statements are universalizable. Although Hare describes how such
universalizuniversal universalizability 940
940 ability can figure in moral argument, for Hare “offenses against . .
. universalizability are logical, not moral.” Consequently, whereas for Kant
not all maxims are universalizable, on Hare’s view they all are, since they all
have descriptive meaning. 3 In a third sense, one that also appears in Hare,
‘universalizability’ refers to the principle of universalizability: “What is
right or wrong for one person is right or wrong for any similar person in
similar circumstances.” This principle is identical with what Sidgwick The Methods
of Ethics called the Principle of Justice. In Generalization in Ethics 1 by M.
G. Singer b.6, it is called the Generalization Principle and is said to be the
formal principle presupposed in all moral reasoning and consequently the
explanation for the feature alleged to hold of all moral judgments, that of
being generalizable. A particular judgment of the form ‘A is right in doing x’
is said to imply that anyone relevantly similar to A would be right in doing
any act of the kind x in relevantly similar circumstances. The characteristic
of generalizability, of presupposing a general rule, was said to be true of
normative claims, but not of all empirical or descriptive statements. The
Generalization Principle GP was said to be involved in the Generalization
Argument GA: “If the consequences of everyone’s doing x would be undesirable,
while the consequences of no one’s doing x would not be, then no one ought to
do x without a justifying reason,” a form of moral reasoning resembling, though
not identical with, the categorical imperative CI. One alleged resemblance is
that if the GP is involved in the GP, then it is involved in the CI, and this
would help explain the moral relevance of Kant’s universalizability test. 4 A
further extension of the term ‘universalizability’ appears in Alan Gewirth’s
Reason and Morality 8. Gewirth formulates “the logical principle of
universalizability”: “if some predicate P belongs to some subject S because S
has the property Q . . . then P must also belong to all other subjects S1, S2,
. . . , Sn that have Q.” The principle of universalizability “in its moral
application” is then deduced from the logical principle of universalizability,
and is presupposed in Gewirth’s Principle of Generic Consistency, “Act in
accord with the generic rights of your recipients as well as yourself,” which
is taken to provide an a priori determinate way of determining relevant
similarities and differences, hence of applying the principle of
universalizability. The principle of universalizability is a formal principle;
universalizability in sense 1, however, is intended to be a substantive
principle of morality.
universalisierung: Grice: “Ironically, the Dutch so careful with
their lingo, this is vague, in that the universe is not a pluriverse.” -- While
Grice uses ‘universal,’ he means like Russell, the unnecessary implication of
‘every.’ Oddly, Kant does not relate this –ung with the first of his three
categories under ‘quantitas,’ the universal. But surely they are related.
Problem is that Kant wasn’t aware because he kept moving from the Graeco-Roman
classical vocabulary to the Hun. Thus, Kant has “Allheit,” which he renders in Latinate
as “Universitas,” and “Totalität,” gehört in der Kategorienlehre des
Philosophen Immanuel Kant zu den reinen Verstandesbegriffen, d. h. zu den
Elementen des Verstandes, welche dem Menschen bereits a priori, also unabhängig
von der sinnlichen Erfahrung gegeben sind. “Allheit” wird wie Einheit und
Vielheit den Kategorien der “Quantität” zugeordnet und entspricht den Einzelnen
Urteilen (Urteil hier im Sinn von 'Aussage über die Wirklichkeit') in der Form
„Ein S ist P“, also z. B. „Immanuel Kant ist ein Philosoph“. Sie wird von Kant
definiert als „die Vielheit als Einheit betrachtet“ (KrV, B 497 f.)[3]. Siehe
auch Transzendentale Analytik Weblinks. Allheit – Bedeutungserklärungen,
Wortherkunft, Synonyme, Übersetzungen Einzelnachweise Immanuel Kant: Kritik der reinen Vernunft.
Reclam, Stuttgart 1966, ISBN 3-15-006461-9.
Peter Kunzmann, Franz-Peter Burkard, Franz Wiedmann: dtv-Atlas zur
Philosophie. dtv, München 1991, ISBN 3-423-03229-4, S. 136 ff. Zitiert nach Arnim Regenbogen, Uwe Meyer
(Hrsg.): Wörterbuch der Philosophischen Begriffe. Meiner, Hamburg 2005, ISBN
3-7873-1738-4: Allheit Kategorie: Ontologie. Referred to by Grice in his
“Method,” – “A requisite for a maxim to enter my manual, which I call the
Immanuel, is that it should be universalizable. Die Untersuchung zur
»Universalisierung in der Ethik« greift eine Problematik auf, die für eine
Reihe der prominentesten Ethikentwürfe der Gegenwart sowohl des
deutschsprachigen wie des angelsächsischen Raumes zentral ist, nämlich ob der
normative Rationalitätsanspruch, den ethische Argumentationen erheben, auf eine
dem wissenschaftlichen Anspruch der deskriptiven Gesetzeswissenschaften
vergleichbare Weise eingelöst werden kann, nämlich durch Verallgemeinerungs-
oder Universalisierungsprinzipien. universalizability
Ethics The idea that moral judgments should be universalizable can be traced to
the Golden Rule and Kant’s ethics. In the twentieth century it was elaborated
by Hare and became a major thesis of his prescriptivism. The principle states
that all moral judgments are universalizable in the sense that if it is right
for a particular person A to do an action X, then it must likewise be right to
do X for any person exactly like A, or like A in the relevant respects.
Furthermore, if A is right in doing X in this situation, then it must be right
for A to do X in other relevantly similar situations. Hare takes this feature
to be an essential feature of moral judgments. An ethical statement is the
issuance of a universal prescription. Universalizability is not the same as
generality, for a moral judgment can be highly specific and detailed and need
not be general or simple. The universalizability principle enables Hare to
avoid the charge of irrationality that is usually lodged against
non-cognitivism, to which his prescriptivism belongs, and his theory is thus a
great improvement on emotivism. “I have been maintaining that the meaning of
the word ‘ought’ and other moral words is such that a person who uses them
commits himself thereby to a universal rule. This is the thesis of
universalizability.” Hare, Freedom and Reason.
universe of
discourse: Grice: “The phrase is
confusing, seeing the uni-verse, is not a pluri-verse.” Tthe usually limited
class of individuals under discussion, whose existence is presupposed by the
discussants, and which in some sense constitutes the ultimate subject matter of
the discussion. Once the universe of a discourse has been established,
expressions such as ‘every object’ and ‘some object’ refer respectively to
every object or to some object in the universe of discourse. The concept of
universe of discourse is due to De Morgan in 1846, but the expression was
coined by Boole eight years later. When a discussion is formalized in an
interpreted standard first-order language, the universe of discourse is taken
as the “universe” of the interpretation, i.e., as the range of values of the
variables. Quine and others have emphasized that the universe of discourse
represents an ontological commitment of the discussants. In a discussion in a
particular science, the universe of discourse is often wider than the domain of
the science, although economies of expression can be achieved by limiting the
universe of discourse to the domain.
unstructured:
Typically, Grice is more interested in the negatives: the unstructured is prior
to the structured, surely. Grice: “Paget was able to structure compositionality
with his hands!” -- one of those negativisms of Grice (cfr. ‘non-structured’).
Surely Grice cared a hoot for French anthropological structuralism! So he has
the ‘unstructured’ followed by the structured. A handwave is unstructured,
meaning syntactically unstructured, and in it you have all the enigma of reason
resolved. By waving his hand, U means that SUBJECT: the emissor, copula IS,
predicate: A KNOWER OF THE ROUTE, or ABOUT TO LEAVE the emissor.There is a lot
of structure in the soul of the emissor. So apply this to what Grice calls a
‘soul-to-soul transfer’ to which he rightly reduces communication. Even if it
is n unstructured communication device, and maybe a ‘one-off’ one, to use
Blackburn’s vulgarism, we would have the three types of correspondence of
Grice’s Semantic Triangle obtaining. First, the psychophysical. The emissor
knows the route, and he shows it. And he wants the emissee to ‘catch’ or get
the emissor’s drift. It is THAT route which he knows. So the TWO psychophysical
correspondences obtain. Then there are the two psychosemiotic correspondences.
The emissor intends that the emissor will recognise the handwave as a signal
that he, the emissor, knows the route. As for the emissee’s psychosemiotic
correspondence: he better realise it is THAT route – to Banbury, surely, with
bells in his shoes, as Grice’s mother would sing to him. And then we have the
two semio-physical correspondences. If the emissor DOES know the route (and he
is not lying, or rather, he is not mistaken about it), then that’s okay. Many
people say or signal that they know because they feel ashamed to admit their
ignorance. So it is very expectable, outside Oxford, to have someone waving
meaning that he knows the route, when he doesn’t. This is surely non-natural,
because it’s Kiparsky-non-factive. Waving the hand thereby communicating that
he knows the route does not entail that he knows the route (as ‘spots’ do entail
measles). From the emissee’s point of view, provided the emissor knows the
route and shows it, the emissee will understand, hopefully, and feel assured
that the emissor will hopefully reach the destination, Banbury, surely, safely
enough.
uptake: used
by Grice slightly different from Austin. Austin: “The performance of an
illocutionary act involves the securing of uptake.” “I distinguish some senses
of consequences and effects, especially three senses in which effects can come
in even with illocutionary acts, viz. securing uptake, taking effect, and
inviting a response.” “Comparing
stating to what we have said about the illocu- tionary act, it is an act
to which, just as much as to other illocutionary acts, it is essential to
‘secure uptake’ : the doubt about whether I stated something if it was
not heard or understood is just the same as the doubt about whether
I warned sotto voce or protested if someone did not take it as a protest,
&c. And statements do ‘take effect’ just as much as ‘namings’, say:
if I have stated something, then that commits me to other
statements: other statements made by me will be in order or out of
order.” Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Verstehen and uptake.”
urmsonianism.
Urmson is possibly more English than Grice, in that ‘gris’ is Nordic – but
Urmson, with such a suffix, -son, HAS to be English English! Plus, he is a
charmer! Who other than Urmson would come up with a counter-example to the
sufficiency of Grice’s analysis of an act of communication. In a case of
bribery, the response or effect in the emittee is NOT meant to be recognised.
So we need a further restriction unless we want to say that the briber means
that his emittee recognise the ‘gift’ as a meta-bribe. Refs.: Urmson,
“Introduction” to Austin’s Philosophical Papers, cited by Grice. Urmson,
Introduction to Austin’s How to do things with words, cited by Grice. Urmson on
Grice, “The Independent.” Urmson on pragmatics.
urmson’s
bribe: Urmson’s use of the bribe is
‘accidental.’ What Urmson is getting at is that if the briber intends the bribe
acts as a cause to effect a response, even a cognitive one, in the bribe, the
propositional complexum, “This is a bribe,” should not necessarily be
communicated. It is amazing how Grice changed the example into one about physical
action. They seem different. On the other hand, Grice would not have cared to
credit Urmson had it not believed it worth knowing that the criticism arose
within the Play Group (Grice admired Urmson). In his earlier “Meaning,” Grice
presents his own self-criticisms to arrive at a more refined analysis. But in
“Utterer’s meaning and intention,” when it comes to the SUFFICIENCY, it’s all
about other people: notably Urmson and Strawson. Grice cites Stampe before
Strawson, but many ignore Stampe on the basis that Strawson does not credit
him, and there is no reason why he should have been aware of it. But Stampe was
at Oxford at the time so this is worth noting. It has to be emphasised that the
author list is under ‘sufficiency.’ Under necessity, Grice does not credit the
source of the objections, so we can assume it is Grice himself, as he had
presented criticisms to his own view within the same ‘Meaning.’ It is curious
that Grice loved Stampe. Grice CHANGED Urmon’s example, and was unable to
provide a specific scenario to Strawson’s alleged counterexample, because
Strawson is vague himself. But Stampe’s, Grice left unchanged. It seems few
Oxonian philosohpers of Grice’s playgroup had his analytic acumen. Consider his
sophisticated account of ‘meaning.’ It’s different if you are a graduate
student from the New World, and you have to prove yourself intelligent. But for
Grice’s playgroup companion, only three or four joined in the analysis. The
first is Urmson. The second is Strawson. The case by Urmson involved a tutee
offering to buy Gardiner an expensive dinner, hoping that Gardiner will give
him permission for an over-night visit to London. Gardiner knows that
his tutee wants his permission. The appropriate analysans for "By offering
to buy Gardiner an expensive dinner, the tuttee means that Gardiner should give
him permission for an overnight stay in London" are fulfilled: (1) The
tutee offers to buy Gardiner an expensive dinner with the intention of
producing a certain response on the part of Gardiner (2) The tutee intends that
Gardiner should recognize (know, think) that the tutee is offering to buy him
an expensive dinner with the intention of producing this response; (3) The
tutee intends that Gardiners recognition (thought) that the tutee has the
intention mentioned in (2) should be at least part of Gardiners reason for
producing the response mentioned. If in general to specify in (i) the nature of
an intended response is to specify what was meant, it should be correct not
only to say that by offering to buy Gardiner an expensive dinner, the tutee
means that Gardiner is to give him permission for an overnight stay in London,
but also to say that he meas that Gardiner should (is to) give him permission
for an over-night visit to London. But in fact one would not wish to say either
of these things; only that the tutee meant Gardiner to give him permission. A
restriction seems to be required, and one which might serve to eliminate this
range of counterexamples can be identified from a comparison of two scenarios.
Grice goes into a tobacconists shop, ask for a packet of my favorite
cigarettes, and when the unusually suspicious tobacconist shows that he wants
to see the color of my money before he hands over the goods, I put down the
price of the cigarettes on the counter. Here nothing has been meant.
Alternatively, Grice goes to his regular tobacconist (from whom I also purchase
other goods) for a packet of my regular brand of Players Navy Cuts, the price
of which is distinctive, say 43p. Grice says nothing, but puts down 43p. The
tobacconist recognizes my need, and hands over the packet. Here, I think, by
putting down 43p I meant something-Namesly, that I wanted a packet of Players
Navy Cuts. I have at the same time provided an inducement. The distinguishing
feature of the second example seems to be that here the tobacconist recognized,
and was intended to recognize, what he was intended to do from my
"utterance" (my putting down the money), whereas in the first example
this was not the case. Nor is it the case with respect to Urmson’s case of the
tutees attempt to bribe Gardiner. So one might propose that the analysis of
meaning be amended accordingly. U means something by uttering x is true if: (i)
U intends, by uttering x, to induce a certain response in A (2) U intends A to
recognize, at least in part from the utterance of x, that U intends to produce
that response (3) U intends the fulfillment of the intention mentioned in (2)
to be at least in part As reason for fulfilling the intention mentioned in (i).
This copes with Urmsons counterexample to Grices proposal in the Oxford
Philosophical Society talk involving the tutee attempting to bribe Gardiner.
Urmson’s super-erogation: ‘super-erogatum --. 1520s, "performance of more than duty requires,"
in Catholic theology, from Late Latin supererogationem (nominative
supererogatio) "a payment in addition," noun of action from past
participle stem of supererogare "pay or do additionally," from Latin
super "above, over" (see super-) + erogare "pay out," from
ex "out" (see ex-) + rogare "ask, request," apparently a
figurative use of a PIE verb meaning literally "to stretch out (the
hand)," from root *reg- "move in a straight line." Grice
got interested in this thanks to J. O. Urmson who discussed his ‘saints and
heroes’ with the Saturday morning kindergarten held by Austin -- the property
of going beyond the call of duty. Supererogatory actions are sometimes equated
with actions that are morally good in the sense that they are encouraged by
morality but not required by it. Sometimes they are equated with morally
commendable actions, i.e., actions that indicate a superior moral character. It
is quite common for morally good actions to be morally commendable and vice
versa, so that it is not surprising that these two kinds of supererogatory
actions are not clearly distinguished even though they are quite distinct.
Certain kinds of actions are not normally considered to be morally required,
e.g., giving to charity, though morality certainly encourages doing them.
However, if one is wealthy and gives only a small amount to charity, then,
although one’s act is supererogatory in the sense of being morally good, it is
not supererogatory in the sense of being morally commendable, for it does not
indicate a superior moral character. Certain kinds of actions are normally
morally required, e.g., keeping one’s promises. However, when the harm or risk
of harm of keeping one’s promise is sufficiently great compared to the harm
caused by breaking the promise to excuse breaking the promise, then keeping
one’s promise counts as a supererogatory act in the sense of being morally
commendable. Some versions of consequentialism claim that everyone is always morally
required to act so as to bring about the best consequences. On such a theory
there are no actions that are morally encouraged but not required; thus, for
those holding such theories, if there are supererogatory acts, they must be
morally commendable. Many versions of non-consequentialism also fail to provide
for acts that are morally encouraged but not morally required; thus, if they
allow for supererogatory acts, they must regard them as morally required acts
done at such significant personal cost that one might be excused for not doing
them. The view that all actions are either morally required, morally
prohibited, or morally indifferent makes it impossible to secure a place for
supererogatory acts in the sense of morally good acts. This view that there are
no acts that are morally encouraged but not morally required may be the result
of misleading terminology. Both Kant and Mill distinguish between duties of
perfect obligation and duties of imperfect obligation, acknowledging that a
duty of imperfect obligation does not specify any particular act that one is
morally required to do. However, since they use the term ‘duty’ it is very easy
to view all acts falling under these “duties” as being morally required. One
way of avoiding the view that all morally encouraged acts are morally required
is to avoid the common philosophical misuse of the term ‘duty’. One can replace
‘duties of perfect obligation’ with ‘actions required by moral rules’ and
‘duties of imperfect obligation’ with ‘actions encouraged by moral ideals’.
However, a theory that includes the kinds of acts that are supererogatory in
the sense of being morally good has to distinguish between that sense of
‘supererogatory’ and the sense meaning ‘morally commendable’, i.e., indicating
a superior moral character in the agent. For as pointed out above, not all
morally good acts are morally commendable, nor are all morally commendable acts
morally good, even though a particular act may be supererogatory in both
senses. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Urmson’s supererogation,” H. P. Grice, “Urmson no
saint, hero perhaps –.” H. P. Grice, “Urmson, my hero.”
use-mention
distinction: Grice: “I once used
Jevons’s coinage in a tutorial with Hardie; he said, ‘What do you mean by
‘of’?’” -- Grice: “Strictly, if you mention, you are using!” -- discussed by
Grice in “Retrospective epilogue” – the only use of a vehicle of communication
is to communicate. two ways in which terms enter into discourse used when they refer to or assert something,
mentioned when they are exhibited for consideration of their properties as
terms. If I say, “Mary is sad,” I use the name ‘Mary’ to refer to Mary so that
I can predicate of her the property of being sad. But if I say, “ ‘Mary’
contains four letters,” I am mentioning Mary’s name, exhibiting it in writing
or speech to predicate of that term the property of being spelled with four
letters. In the first case, the sentence occurs in what Carnap refers to as the
material mode; in the second, it occurs in the formal mode, and hence in a
metalanguage a language used to talk about another language. Single quotation
marks or similar orthographic devices are conventionally used to disambiguate
mentioned from used terms. The distinction is important because there are fallacies
of reasoning based on usemention confusions in the failure to observe the use
mention distinction, especially when the referents of terms are themselves
linguistic entities. Consider the inference: 1 Some sentences are written in
English. 2 Some sentences are written in English. Here it looks as though the
argument offers a counterexample to the claim that all arguments of the form
‘P, therefore P’ are circular. But either 1 asserts that some sentences are
written in English, or it provides evidence in support of the conclusion in 2
by exhibiting a sentence written in English. In the first case, the sentence is
used to assert the same truth in the premise as expressed in the conclusion, so
that the argument remains circular. In the second case, the sentence is
mentioned, and although the argument so interpreted is not circular, it is no
longer strictly of the form ‘P, therefore P’, but has the significantly
different form, ‘ “P” is a sentence written in English, therefore P’.
usus: ad usum
griceianum -- use: Grice: “I would rephrase Vitter’s adage, ‘Don’t ask for the
expression meaning, as for the UTTERER’s meaning, if you have to axe at all!”
-- while Grice uses ‘use,’ as Ryle once told him, ‘you should use ‘usage, too.’
Parkinson was nearby. When Warnock commissioned Parkinson to compile a couple
of Oxonian essays on meaning and communication, Parkinson unearthed the old
symposium by Ryle and Findlay on the matter. Typically, when Ryle reprinted it,
he left Findlay out!
V
vagum: oddly,
A. C. Ewing has a very early thing on ‘vagueness.’ Grice liked Ewing. There is
an essay on “Clarity” which relates. Cf. Price, “Clarity is not enough” Which
implicates it IS a necessity, though. Cf. “Clarity – who cares?” Some days,
Grice did not feel ‘Grecian,’ and would use very vernacular expressions. He
thought that what Cicero calls ‘vagum’ is best rendered in Oxfordshire dialect
as ‘fuzzy.’ It is not clear which of Grice’s maxim controls this. The opposite
of ‘vague’ is ‘specific.’ Grice was more concerned about this in the earlier
lectures where he has under the desideratum of conversational candour and the
principle of conversational benevolence, and the desideratum of conversational
clarity that one should be explicit, and make one’s point explicit. But under
the submaxims of the conversational category of modus (‘be perspicuous [sic]),
none seem to prohibit ‘vagueness’ as such: Avoid
obscurity of expression.Avoid ambiguity.Be brief (avoid unnecessary prolixity).Be orderly The one he later calls a ‘tailoring
principle’ ‘frame your contribution in way that facilitates a reply’, the
‘vagueness’ avoidance seems implicit. Cf. fuzzy. The
indeterminacy of the field of application of an expression, in contrast to
precision. For instance, the expression “young man” is vague since the point at
which its appropriate application to a person begins and ends cannot be
precisely defined. Vagueness should be distinguished from ambiguity, by which
a term has more than one meaning. The
vagueness of an expression is due to a semantic feature of the term itself,
rather than to the subjective condition of its user. Vagueness gives rise to
borderline cases, and propositions with vague terms lack a definite truth-value.
For this reason, Frege rejected the possibility of vague concepts, although
they are tolerated in recent work in vague or fuzzy logic. Various paradoxes
arise due to the vagueness of words, including the ancient sorites paradox. It
is because of its intrinsic vagueness that some philosophers seek to replace
ordinary language with an ideal language. But ordinary language philosophers
hold that this proposal creates a false promise of eliminating vagueness.
Wittgenstein’s notion of family resemblance in part is a model of meaning that
tolerates vagueness. As a property of expressions, vagueness extends to all
sorts of cognitive representations. Some philosophers hold that there can be
vagueness in things as well as in the representation of things. “A
representation is vague when the relation of the representing system to the
represented system is not one–one, but one–many.” Russell, Collected Papers of
Bertrand Russell, vol. IX. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Fuzzy impicatures, and
how to unfuzz them;” H. P. Grice, “The conversational maxim of vagueness
avoidance.” Oddly, Grice does not have a conversational, ‘be precise,’; but he
did. In his earlier desideratum of conversational clarity, the point was to
make your point precise – rather than fuzzy -- vagueness, a property of an
expression in virtue of which it can give rise to a “borderline case.” A
borderline case is a situation in which the application of a particular
expression to a name of a particular object does not generate an expression
with a definite truth-value; i.e., the piece of language in question neither
unequivocally applies to the object nor fails to apply. Although such a
formulation leaves it open what the pieces of language might be whole
sentences, individual words, names or singular terms, predicates or general
terms, most discussions have focused on vague general terms and have considered
other types of terms to be nonvague. Exceptions to this have called attention
to the possibility of vague objects, thereby rendering vague the designation
relation for singular terms. The formulation also leaves open the possible
causes for the expression’s lacking a definite truth-value. If this
indeterminacy is due to there being insufficient information available to
determine applicability or non-applicability of the term i.e., we are convinced
the term either does or does not apply, but we just do not have enough
information to determine which, then this is sometimes called epistemic
vagueness. It is somewhat misleading to call this vagueness, for unlike true
vagueness, this epistemic vagueness disappears if more information is brought
into the situation. ‘There are between 1.89 $ 106 and 1.9 $ 106 stars in the
sky’ is epistemically vague but is not vague in the generally accepted sense of
the term. ’Vagueness’ may also be used to characterize non-linguistic items
such as concepts, memories, and objects, as well as such semilinguistic items
as statements and propositions. Many of the issues involved in discussing the
topic of vagueness impinge upon other philosophical topics, such as the
existence of truth-value gaps
declarative sentences that are neither true nor false and the plausibility of many-valued logic.
There are other related issues such as the nature of propositions and whether
they must be either true or false. We focus here on linguistic vagueness, as it
manifests itself with general terms; for it is this sort of indeterminacy that
defines what most researchers call vagueness, and which has led the push in
some schools of thought to “eliminate vagueness” or to construct languages that
do not manifest vagueness. Linguistic vagueness is sometimes confused with
other linguistic phenomena: generality, ambiguity, and open texture. Statements
can be general ‘Some wheelbarrows are red’, ‘All insects have antennae’ and if
there is no other vagueness infecting them, they are true or false and not borderline or vague. Terms can be
general ‘person’, ‘dog’ without being vague. Those general terms apply to many
different objects but are not therefore vague; and furthermore, the fact that
they apply to different kinds of objects ‘person’ applies to both men and women
also does not show them to be vague or ambiguous. A vague term admits of
borderline cases a completely determinate
situation in which there just is no correct answer as to whether the term
applies to a certain object or not and
this is not the case with generality. Ambiguous linguistic items, including
structurally ambiguous sentences, also do not have this feature unless they
also contain vague terms. Rather, an ambiguous sentence allows there to be a
completely determinate situation in which one can simultaneously correctly
affirm the sentence and also deny the sentence, depending on which of the
claims allowed by the ambiguities is being affirmed or denied. Terms are
considered open-textured if they are precise along some dimensions of their
meaning but where other possible dimensions simply have not been considered. It
would therefore not be clear what the applicability of the term would be were
objects to vary along these other dimensions. Although related to vagueness,
open texture is a different notion. Friedrich Waismann, who coined the term,
put it this way: “Open texture . . . is something like the possibility of
vagueness.” Vagueness has long been an irritant to philosophers of logic and
language. Among the oldest of the puzzles associated with vagueness is the
sorites ‘heap’ paradox reported by Cicero Academica 93: One grain of sand does
not make a heap, and adding a grain of sand to something that is not a heap
will not create a heap; there945 V 945
fore there are no heaps. This type of paradox is traditionally attributed to
Zeno of Elea, who said that a single millet seed makes no sound when it falls,
so a basket of millet seeds cannot make a sound when it is dumped. The term
‘sorites’ is also applied to the entire series of paradoxes that have this
form, such as the falakros ‘bald man’, Diogenes Laertius, Grammatica II, 1, 45:
A man with no hairs is bald, and adding one hair to a bald man results in a
bald man; therefore all men are bald. The original version of these sorites
paradoxes is attributed to Eubulides Diogenes Laertius II, 108: “Isn’t it true
that two are few? and also three, and also four, and so on until ten? But since
two are few, ten are also few.” The linchpin in all these paradoxes is the
analysis of vagueness in terms of some underlying continuum along which an
imperceptible or unimportant change occurs. Almost all modern accounts of the
logic of vagueness have assumed this to be the correct analysis of vagueness,
and have geared their logics to deal with such vagueness. But we will see below
that there are other kinds of vagueness too. The search for a solution to the
sorites-type paradoxes has been the stimulus for much research into alternative
semantics. Some philosophers, e.g. Frege, view vagueness as a pervasive defect
of natural language and urge the adoption of an artificial language in which
each predicate is completely precise, without borderline cases. Russell too
thought vagueness thoroughly infected natural language, but thought it
unavoidable and indeed beneficial for ordinary usage and discourse. Despite the
occasional argument that vagueness is pragmatic rather than a semantic
phenomenon, the attitude that vagueness is inextricably bound to natural
language together with the philosophical logician’s self-ascribed task of
formalizing natural language semantics has led modern writers to the
exploration of alternative logics that might adequately characterize
vagueness i.e., that would account for
our pretheoretic beliefs concerning truth, falsity, necessary truth, validity,
etc., of sentences containing vague predicates. Some recent writers have also
argued that vague language undermines realism, and that it shows our concepts
to be “incoherent.” Long ago it was seen that the attempt to introduce a third
truth-value, indeterminate, solved nothing
replacing, as it were, the sharp cutoff between a predicate’s applying and
not applying with two sharp cutoffs. Similar remarks could be made against the
adoption of any finitely manyvalued logic as a characterization of vagueness.
In the late 0s and early 0s, fuzzy logic was introduced into the philosophic
world. Actually a restatement of the Tarski-Lukasiewicz infinitevalued logics
of the 0s, one of the side benefits of fuzzy logics was claimed to be an
adequate logic for vagueness. In contrast to classical logic, in which there
are two truth-values true and false, in fuzzy logic a sentence is allowed to
take any real number between 0 and 1 as a truthvalue. Intuitively, the closer
to 1 the value is, the “more true” the sentence is. The value of a negated
sentence is 1 minus the value of the unnegated sentence; conjuction is viewed
as a minimum function and disjunction as a maximum function. Thus, a
conjunction takes the value of the “least true” conjunct, while a disjunction
takes the value of the “most true” disjunct. Since vague sentences are
maximally neither true nor false, they will be valued at approximately 0.5. It
follows that if F is maximally vague, so is the negation -F; and so are the
conjunction F & -F and the disjunction ~F 7 -F. Some theorists object to
these results, but defenders of fuzzy logic have argued in favor of them. Other
theorists have attempted to capture the elusive logic of vagueness by employing
modal logic, having the operators AF meaning ‘F is definite’ and B F meaning ‘F
is vague’. The logic generated in this way is peculiar in that A F & YPAF
& AY is not a theorem. E.g., p & -p is definitely false, hence
definite; hence A p & -p. Yet neither p nor -p need be definite.
Technically, it is a non-Kripke-normal modal logic. Some other peculiarities
are that AF Q A -F is a theorem, and that AFPBF is not. There are also puzzles
about whether B FP ABF should be a theorem, and about iterated modalities in
general. Modal logic treatments of vagueness have not attracted many advocates,
except as a portion of a general epistemic logic i.e., modal logics might be
seen as an account of so-called epistemic vagueness. A third direction that has
been advocated as a logical account of vagueness has been the method of
supervaluations sometimes called “supertruth”. The underlying idea here is to
allow the vague predicate in a sentence to be “precisified” in an arbitrary
manner. Thus, for the sentence ‘Friar Tuck is bald’, we arbitrarily choose a
precise number of hairs on the head that will demarcate the bald/not-bald
border. In this valuation Friar Tuck is either definitely bald or definitely
not bald, and the sentence either is true or is false. Next, we alter the
valuation so that there is some other bald/not-bald bordervagueness vagueness
946 946 line, etc. A sentence true in
all such valuations is deemed “really true” or “supertrue”; one false in all
such valuations is “really false” or “superfalse.” All others are vague. Note
that, in this conception of vagueness, if F is vague, so is -F. However, unlike
fuzzy logic ‘F & -F’ is not evaluated as vague it is false in every valuation and hence is
superfalse. And ‘F 7 -F’ is supertrue. These are seen by some as positive
features of the method of supervaluations, and as an argument against the whole
fuzzy logic enterprise. In fact there seem to be at least two distinct types of
linguistic vagueness, and it is not at all clear that any of the previously
mentioned logic approaches can deal with both. Without going into the details,
we can just point out that the “sorites vagueness” discussed above presumes an
ordering on a continuous underlying scale; and it is the indistinguishability
of adjacent points on this scale that gives rise to borderline cases. But there
are examples of vague terms for which there is no such scale. A classic example
is ‘religion’: there are a number of factors relevant to determining whether a
social practice is a religion. Having none of these properties guarantees
failing to be a religion, and having all of them guarantees being one. However,
there is no continuum of the sorites variety here; for example, it is easy to
distinguish possessing four from possessing five of the properties, unlike the
sorites case where such a change is imperceptible. In the present type of
vagueness, although we can tell these different cases apart, we just do not know
whether to call the practice a religion or not. Furthermore, some of the
properties or combinations of properties are more important or salient in
determining whether the practice is a religion than are other properties or
combinations. We might call this family resemblance vagueness: there are a
number of clearly distinguishable conditions of varying degrees of importance,
and family resemblance vagueness is attributed to there being no definite
answer to the question, How many of which conditions are necessary for the term
to apply? Other examples of family resemblance vagueness are ‘schizophrenia
sufferer’, ‘sexual perversion’, and the venerable ‘game’. A special subclass of
family resemblance vagueness occurs when there are pairs of underlying properties
that normally co-occur, but occasionally apply to different objects. Consider,
e.g., ‘tributary’. When two rivers meet, one is usually considered a tributary
of the other. Among the properties relevant to being a tributary rather than
the main river are: relative volume of water and relative length. Normally, the
shorter of the two rivers has a lesser volume, and in that case it is the
tributary of the other. But occasionally the two properties do not co-occur and
then there is a conflict, giving rise to a kind of vagueness we might call
conflict vagueness. The term ‘tributary’ is vague because its background
conditions admit of such conflicts: there are borderline cases when these two
properties apply to different objects. To conclude: the fundamental philosophical
problems involving vagueness are 1 to give an adequate characterization of what
the phenomenon is, and 2 to characterize our ability to reason with these
terms. These were the problems for the ancient philosophers, and they remain
the problems for modern philosophers. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The conversational
maxim for vagueness avoidance.”
vaihinger: Grice once gave a seminar on Vaihinger – “but
thinking it would not attract that many, I titled it ‘As if.’” – H. P. Grice. philosopher
best known for Die Philosophie des Als Ob; tr. by C. K. Ogden as The Philosophy
of “As If” in 4. A neo-Kantian, he was also influenced by Schopenhauer and
Nietzsche. His commentary on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason 2 vols., 1 is still
a standard work. Vaihinger was a cofounder of both the Kant Society and
Kant-Studien. The “philosophy of the as if” involves the claim that values and
ideals amount only to “fictions” that serve “life” even if they are irrational.
We must act “as if” they were true because they have biological utility.
valentinianism: Grice: “I will only explore the actdivities of the
so-called “Valentinians” in Rome.” -- a form of Christian gnosticism of
Alexandrian origin, founded by Valentinus in the second century and propagated
by Theodotus in Eastern, and Heracleon in Western, Christianity. To every
gnostic, pagan or Christian, knowledge leads to salvation from the perishable,
material world. Valentinianism therefore prompted famous refutations by
Tertullian Adversus Valentinianos and Irenaeus Adversus haereses. The latter
accused the Valentinians of maintaining “creatio ex nihilo.” Valentinus is
believed to have authored the Peri trion phuseon, the Evangelium veritatis, and
the Treatise on the Resurrection. Since only a few fragments of these remain,
his Neoplatonic cosmogony is accessible mainly through his opponents and
critics Hippolytus, Clement of Alexandria and in the Nag Hammadi codices. To
explain the origins of creation and of evil, Valentinus separated God primal
Father from the Creator Demiurge and attributed the cruVaihinger, Hans
Valentinianism 947 947 cial role in the
processes of emanation and redemption to Sophia.
valentino: -- or as Strawson would have it, ‘valentinus,’ gnostic
teacher, b. in Alexandria, where he teaches until he moved to Rome. A dualist,
he constructed an elaborate cosmology in which God the Father Bythos, or Deep
Unknown unites the the feminine Silence Sige and in the overflow of love
produces thirty successive divine emanations or aeons constituting the Pleroma
fullness of the Godhead. Each emanation is arranged hierarchically with a
graded existence, becoming progressively further removed from the Father and
hence less divine. The lowest emanation, Sophia wisdom, yields to passion and
seeks to reach, beyond her ability, to the Father, which causes her fall. In
the process, she causes the creation of the material universe wherein resides
evil and the loss of divine sparks from the Pleroma. The divine elements are
embodied in those humans who are the elect. Jesus Christ is an aeon close to
the Father and is sent to retrieve the souls into the heavenly Pleroma.
Valentinus wrote a gospel. The sect of Valentino stood out in the early church
for ordaining women priests and prophetesses. Grice: “Since he lived in Rome,
he was almost a Roman.” – Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Valentinus e Grice,” Villa
Grice.
vailati: n important figure in the history
of formal semantics, influenced by Peano, who in turn influenced Whitehead and
Russell, and thus Grice. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice e Vailati: la
semantica filosofica," The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria,
Italia.
valla: Rome-born philosopher, teaches rhetoric in Pav a and
is later secretary of Alfonso I di Naoli, and apostolic secretary in Rome under
papa Nichola V. In his dialogue On Pleasure or On the True Good, Stoic and
Epicurean interlocutors present their ethical views, which Valla proceeds to
criticize. This dialogue is often regarded as a defense of Epicurean hedonism,
because Valla equates the good with pleasure; but he claims that Italians can find
pleasure only in heaven. Valla’s description of pleasure reflects the
contemporary Renaissance attitude toward the joys of life and might have
contributed to Valla’s reputation for hedonism. In another work, On Free Will
between, Valla discusses the conflict between divine foreknowledge and human
freedom and rejects Boezio’’s then predominantly accepted solution. Valla
distinguishes between God’s knowledge and God’s will – as in Grice’s phrase,
“God willing,” “Deo volente,” -- but denies that there is a rational solution
of the apparent conflict between God’s will and human freedom. As a historian,
he is famous for The Donation of Constantine 1440, which denounces as spurious
the famous document on which medieval jurists and theologians based the papal
rights to secular power. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Valla e Grice,”per la
Fondazione Lorenzo Valla, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria,
Italia.
valitum: Oddly Vitters has a couple of lectures on ‘value,’
that Grice ‘ignored.’ Valitum should be contrasted from‘validum.’ ‘Valid,’
which is cognate with ‘value,’ a noun Grice loved, is used by logicians. In
Grice’s generalised alethic-cum-deontic logic, ‘valid’ applies, too. ‘Valid’ is
contrasted to the ‘satisfactoriness’ value that attaches directly to the
utterance. ‘Valid’ applies to the reasoning, i.e. the sequence of psychological
states from the premise to the conclusion. How common and insidious was the
talk of a realm of ‘values’ at Oxford in the early 1930s to have Barnes attack
it, and Grice defend it? ‘The realm of values’ sounds like an ordinary man’s
expression, and surely Oxford never had a Wilson Chair of Metaphysical
Axiology. validum is the correct form
out of Roman ‘valeor.’ Grice finds the need for the English equivalent, and
plays with constructing the ‘concept’ “to be of value”! There’s also the
axiologicum. The root for ‘value’ as ‘axis’ is found in Grice’s favourite book
of the Republic, the First! Grice sometimes enjoys sounding pretentious and
uses the definite article ‘the’ indiscriminately, just to tease Flew, his
tutee, who said that talking of ‘the self’ is just ‘rubbish’. It is different
with Grice’s ‘the good’ (to agathon), ‘the rational,’ (to logikon), ‘the
valuable’ (valitum), and ‘the axiological’. Of course, whilesticking with
‘value,’ Grice plays with Grecian “τιμή.” Lewis and
Short have ‘vălor,’ f. ‘valeo,’ which
they render as ‘value,’ adding that it is supposed to translate in Gloss. Lab,
Grecian ‘τιμή.’
‘valor, τιμή, Gloss. Lab.’ ‘Valere,’ which of course algo gives English
‘valid,’ that Grice overuses, is said by Lewis and Short to be cognate with
“vis,” “robur,” “fortissimus,” cf. debilis” and they render as “to be strong.”
So one has to be careful here. “Axiology” is a German thing, and not used at
Clifton or Oxford, where they stick with ‘virtus’ or ‘arete.’ This or that
Graeco-Roman philosopher may have explored a generic approach to ‘value.’ Grice
somewhat dismisses Hare who in Language of Morals very clearly distinguishes
between deontic ‘ought’ and teleological, value-judgemental ‘good.’ For ‘good’
may have an aesthetic use: ‘that painting is good,’ the food is good). The
sexist ‘virtus’ of the Romans perhaps did a disservice to Grecian ‘arete,’ but
Grice hardly uses ‘arete,’ himself. It is etymologically unrelated to
‘agathon,’ yet rumour has it that ‘arete,’ qua ‘excellence,’ is ‘aristos,’ the
superlative of ‘agathon.’ Since Aristotle is into the ‘mesotes,’ Grice worries
not. Liddell and Scott have “ἀρετή” and render it simpliciter as “goodness,
excellence, of any kind,” adding that “in Hom. esp. of manly qualities”: “ποδῶν
ἀρετὴν ἀναφαίνων;” “ἀμείνων παντοίας ἀρετὰς ἠμὲν πόδας ἠδὲ μάχεσθαι καὶ νόον;”
so of the gods, “τῶν περ καὶ μείζων ἀ. τιμή τε βίη τε;” also of women, “ἀ.
εἵνεκα for valour,” “ἀ. ἀπεδείκνυντο,” “displayed brave deeds.” But when Liddell and Scott give the
philosophical references (Plathegel and Ariskant), they do render “ἀρετή,” as
‘value,’ generally, excellence, “ἡ ἀ.
τελείωσίς τις” Arist. Met. 1021b20, cf. EN1106a15, etc.; of persons, “ἄνδρα πὺξ
ἀρετὰν εὑρόντα,” “τὸ φρονεῖν ἀ. μεγίστη,” “forms of excellence, “μυρίαι ἀνδρῶν
ἀ.;” “δικαστοῦ αὕτη ἀ.;” esp. moral virtue, opp. “κακία,” good nature,
kindness, etc. We should not be so concerned about this, were not for the fact
that Grice explored Foot, not just on meta-ethics as a ‘suppositional’
imperratives, but on ‘virtue’ and
‘vice,’ by Foot, who had edited a reader in meta-ethics for the series of
Grice’s friend, Warnock. Grice knows that when he hears the phrases value
system, or belief system, he is conversing with a relativist. So he plays
jocular here. If a value is not a concept, a value system at least is not what
Davidson calls a conceptual scheme. However, in “The conception of value” (henceforth,
“Conception”) Grice does argue that value IS a concept, and thus part of the
conceptual scheme by Quine. Hilary Putnam congratulates Grice on this in “Fact
and value,” crediting Baker – i. e. Judy – into the bargain. While
utilitarianism, as exemplified by Bentham, denies that a moral intuition need
be taken literally, Bentham assumes the axiological conceptual scheme of
hedonistic eudaemonism, with eudaemonia as the maximal value (summum bonum)
understood as hedone. The idea
of a system of values (cf. system of ends) is meant to unify the goals of the
agent in terms of the pursuit of eudæmonia. Grice wants to disgress from
naturalism, and the distinction between a
description and anything else. Consider the use of ‘rational’ as applied to
‘value.’ A naturalist holds that ‘rational’ can be legitimately
apply to the ‘doxastic’ realm, not to the ‘buletic’ realm. A desire (or a
‘value’) a naturalist would say is not something of which ‘rational’ is
predicable. Suppose, Grice says, I meet a philosopher who is in the habit of
pushing pins into other philosophers. Grice asks the philosopher why he does
this. The philosopher says that it gives him pleasure. Grice asks him whether
it is the fact that he causes pain that gives him pleasure. The philosopher replies
that he does not mind whether he causes pain. What gives him pleasure is the
physical sensation of driving a pin into a philosopher’s body. Grice asks him
whether he is aware that his actions cause pain. The philosopher says that he
is. Grice asks him whether he would not feel pain if others did this to him.
The philosopher agrees that he would. I ask him whether he would allow this to
happen. He says that he guesses he would seek to prevent it. Grice asks him
whether he does not think that others must feel pain when he drives pins into
them, and whether he should not do to others what he would try to prevent them
from doing to him. The philosopher says that pins driven into him cause him
pain and he wishes to prevent this. Pins driven by him into others do not cause
him pain, but pleasure, and he therefore wishes to do it. Grice asks him
whether the fact that he causes pain to other philosophers does not seem to him
to be relevant to the issue of whether it is rationally undesirable to drive
pins into people. He says that he does not see what possible difference can
pain caused to others, or the absence of it, make to the desirability of
deriving pleasure in the way that he does. Grice asks him what it is that
gives him pleasure in this particular activity. The philosopher replies that he
likes driving pins into a philosopher’s resilient body. Grice asks whether he
would derive equal pleasure from driving pins into a tennis ball. The
philosopher says that he would derive equal pleasure, that into what he drives
his pins, a philosopher or a tennis ball, makes no difference to him – the
pleasure is similar, and he is quite prepared to have a tennis ball
substituted, but what possible difference can it make whether his pins
perforate living men or tennis balls? At this point, Grice begins to suspect
that the philosopher is evil. Grice does not feel like agreeing with a
naturalist, who reasons that the pin-pushing philosopher is a philosopher with
a very different scale of moral values from Grice, that a value not being
susceptible to argument, Grice may disagree but not reason with the pin-pushing
philosopher. Grice rather sees the pin-pushing philosopher beyond the reach of
communication from the world occupied by him. Communication is as unattainable
as it is with a philosopher who that he is a doorknob, as in the story by
Hoffman. A value enters into the essence of what constitutes a person. The
pursuit of a rational end is part of the essence of a person. Grice does not
claim any originality for his position (which much to Ariskant), only validity.
The implicaturum by Grice is that rationalism and axiology are incompatible,
and he wants to cancel that. So the keyword here is rationalistic axiology, in
the neo-Kantian continental vein, with a vengeance. Grice arrives at value
(validitum, optimum, deeming) via Peirce on meaning. And then there is the
truth “value,” a German loan-translation (as value judgment, Werturteil). The
sorry story of deontic logic, Grice says, faces Jørgensens
dilemma. The dilemma by Jørgensens is best seen as a trilemma, Grice says;
viz. Reasoning requires that premise and conclusion have what Boole, Peirce,
and Frege call a “truth” value. An imperative dos not have a “truth” value.
There may be a reasoning with an imperative as premise or conclusion. A
philosopher can reject the first horn and provide an inference mechanism on
elements – the input of the premise and the output of the conclusion -- which
are not presupposed to have a “truth” value. A philosopher can reject the
second horn and restrict ‘satisfactory’ value to a doxastic embedding a buletic
(“He judges he wills…”). A philosopher can reject the third horn, and refuse to
explore the desideratum. Grice generalizes over value as the mode-neutral
‘satisfactory.’ Both ‘p’ and “!p” may be satisfactory. ‘.p’ has doxastic value
(0/1); ‘!p’ has buletic value (0/1). The
mode marker of the utterance guides the addresse you as to how to read
‘satisfactory.’ Grice’s ‘satisfactory’ is a variation on a theme by
Hofstadter and McKinsey, who elaborate a syntax for the imperative mode, using
satisfaction. They refer to what they call the ‘satisfaction-function’ of a
fiat. A fiat is ‘satisfied’ (as The door is closed may also be said to be
satisfied iff the door is closed) iff what is commanded is the case. The fiat
‘Let the door be closed’ is satisfied if the door is closed. An unary or dyadic
operator becomes a satisfaction-functor. As
Grice puts it, an inferential rule, which flat rationality is the
capacity to apply, is not arbitrary. The inferential rule picks out a
transition of acceptance in which transmission of ‘satisfactory’ is
guaranteed or expected. As Grice notes, since mode marker indicate the species
‘satisfactory’ does. He imports into the object-language ‘It is
satisfactory-d/p that’ just in case psi-d/b-p is satisfactory. Alla
Tarski, Grice introduces ‘It is acceptable that’: It is acceptable that
psi-d/b-p is satisfactory-b/d just in case ‘psi-d/b-p is satisfactory-d/b’ is
satisfactory-b/d. Grice goes on to provide a generic value-assignment
for satisfactoriness-functors. For coordinators: “φ Λ ψ” is
1-b/d just in case φ is 1-b/d and ψ is 1-b/d. “φ ν ψ” is 1-b/d just in case one of the pair, φ and
ψ, is 1-b/d. For subordinator: “φ⊃ψ” is 1-b/d just in case either
φ is 0-b/d or ψ is 0-b/d. There are, however, a number of points to
be made. It is not fully clear to Grice just how strong the motivation is for
assigning a value to a mode-neutral, generic functor. Also he is assuming
symmetry, leaving room for a functor is introduced if a restriction is imposed.
Consider a bi-modal utterance. “The beast is filthy and do not touch it” and
“The beast is filthy and I shall not touch it” seem all right. The commutated
“Do not touch the beast and it is filthy” is dubious. “Touch the beast and it
will bite you,” while idiomatic is hardly an imperative, since ‘and’ is hardly
a conjunction. “Smith is taking a bath or leave the bath-room door open” is
intelligible. The commutated “Leave the bath-room door open or Smith is taking
a bath” is less so. In a bi-modal utterance, Grice makes a case for the buletic
to be dominant over the doxastic. The crunch comes, however, with one of the
four possible unary satisfactoriness-functors, especially with regard to the
equivalence of “~psi-b/d-p” and “psi-b/d-~p).
Consider “Let it be that I now put my hand on my head” or “Let it be that my bicycle faces north” in
which neither seems to be either satisfactory or unsatisfactory. And it is a
trick to assign a satisfactory value to “~psi-b/d-p” and “~psi-b/d~p.” Do we
proscribe this or that form altogether, for every cases? But that would seem to
be a pity, since ~!~p seems to be quite promising as a representation for you
may (permissive) do alpha that satisfies p; i.e., the utterer explicitly
conveys his refusal to prohibit his addressee A doing alpha. Do we disallow
embedding of (or iterating) this or that form? But that (again if we use ~!p
and ~!~p to represent may) seems too restrictive. Again, if !p is neither
buletically satisfactory nor buletically unsatisfactory (U could care less) do
we assign a value other than 1 or 0 to !p (desideratively neuter, 0.5). Or do
we say, echoing Quine, that we have a buletically satisfactoriness value gap?
These and other such problems would require careful consideration. Yet Grice
cannot see that those problems would prove insoluble, any more than this or
that analogous problem connected with Strawsons presupposition (Dont arrest the
intruder!) are insoluble. In Strawsons case, the difficulty is not so much to
find a solution as to select the best solution from those which present
themselves. Grice takes up the topic of a calculus in connection with the
introduction rule and the elimination rule of a modal such as must. We
might hope to find, for each member of a certain family of modalities, an
introduction rule and an elimination rule which would be analogous to the rules
available for classical logical constants. Suggestions are not hard to come by.
Let us suppose that we are seeking to provide such a pair of rules for the
particular modality of necessity □. For
(□,+) Grice considers the following (Grice
thinks equivalent) forms: if φ is demonstrable, □φ
is demonstrable. Provided φ is dependent on no assumptions, derive φ from □φ. For (□,-), Grice considers From □φ derive φ. It is to be understood, of course, that the
values of the syntactical variable φ would contain either a buletic or a
doxastic mode markers. Both !p and .p would be proper substitutes for φ but p
would not. Grice wonders: [W]hat should be said of Takeuti’s conjecture
(roughly) that the nature of the introduction rule determines the character of
the elimination rule? There seems to be no particular problem about
allowing an introduction rule which tells us that, if it is established in P’s
personalised system that φ, it is necessary, with respect to P, that φ is
doxastically satisfactory/establishable. The accompanying elimination rule is,
however, slightly less promising. If we suppose such a rule to tell us that, if
one is committed to the idea that it is necessary, with respect to P, that φ,
one is also committed to whatever is expressed by φ, we shall be in trouble.
For such a rule is not acceptable. φ will be a buletic expression such as Let
it be that Smith eats his hat. And my commitment to the idea that Smiths system
requires him to eat his hat does not ipso facto involve me in accepting
volitively Let Smith eat his hat. But if we take the elimination rule rather as
telling us that, if it is necessary, with respect to X, that let X eat his hat,
then let X eat his hat possesses satisfactoriness-with-respect-to-X, the
situation is easier. For this person-relativised version of the rule seems
inoffensive, even for Takeuti, we hope. Grice, following Mackie, uses
absolutism, as opposed to
relativism, which denies the rational basis to attitude ascriptions (but cf.
Hare on Subjectsivism). Grice is concerned with the absence of a thorough
discussion of value by English philosophers, other than Hare (and he is only
responding to Mackie!). Continental philosophers, by comparison, have a special
discipline, axiology, for it! Similarly, a continental-oriented tradition
Grice finds in The New World in philosophers of a pragmatist bent, such as
Carus. Grice wants to say that rationality is a value, because it is a
faculty that a creature (human) displays to adapt and survive to his changing
environments. The implicaturum of the title is that values have been considered
in the English philosophical tradition, almost alla Nietzsche, to belong to the
realm irrational. Grice grants that axiological implicaturum rests on a
PRE-rational propension. While Grice could
play with “the good” in the New World, as a Lit. Hum. he knew he had to be
slightly more serious. The good is one of the values, but what is valuing?
Would the New Worlders understand valuing unattached to the pragmatism that
defines them? Grice starts by invoking Hume on his bright side: the concept of
value, versus the conception of value. Or rather, how the concept of value
derives from the conception of value. A distinction that would even please
Aquinas (conceptum/conceptio), and the Humeian routine. Some background for his
third Carus lecture. He tries to find out what Mackie means when he says that a
value is ultimately Subjectsive. What about inter-Subjectsive, and
constructively objective? Grice constructs absolute value out of relative
value. But once a rational pirot P (henceforth, P – Grice liked how it sounded
like Locke’s parrot) constructs value, the P assigns absolute status to
rationality qua value. The P cannot then choose not to be rational at the risk
of ceasing to exist (qua person, or essentially rationally human agent). A
human, as opposed to a person, assigns relative value to his rationality. A
human is accidentally rational. A person is necessarily so. A distinction
seldom made by Aristotle and some of his dumbest followers obsessed with the
modal-free adage, Homo rationale animal. Short and Lewis have “hūmānus”
(old form: hemona humana et hemonem hominem dicebant, Paul. ex Fest. p. 100 Müll.;
cf. homo I.init.), adj., f. “homo,” and which they render as “of or belonging
to man, human.” Grice also considers the etymology of ‘person.’ Lewis and Short
have ‘persōna,’ according to Gabius
Bassus ap. Gell. 5, 7, 1 sq., f. ‘persŏno,’ “to sound through, with the second
syllable lengthened.’ Falsa est (finitio), si dicas, Equus est animal
rationale: nam est equus animal, sed irrationale, Quint.7,3,24:homo est animal
rationale; “nec si mutis finis voluptas, rationalibus quoque: quin immo ex
contrario, quia mutis, ideo non rationalibus;” “a rationali ad rationale;” “τὸ
λογικόν ζῷον,” ChrysiStoic.3.95; ἀρεταὶ λ., = διανοητικαί, oἠθικαί, Arist.
EN1108b9; “λογικός, ή, όν, (λόγος), ζῶον λόγον ἔχον NE, 1098a3-5. λόγον δὲ
μόνον ἄνθρωπος ἔχει τῶν ζῴων, man alone of all animals possesses speech, from
the Politics. Grice takes the stratification of values by Hartmann much more
seriously than Barnes. Grice plays with rational motivation. He means it
seriously. The motivation is the psychological bite, but since it is qualified
by rational, it corresponds to the higher more powerful bit of the soul, the
rational soul. There are, for Grice, the Grecians, Kantotle and Plathegel,
three souls: the vegetal, the animal, and the rational. As a matter of history,
Grice reaches value (in its guises of optimum and deeming) via his analysis of
meaning by Peirce. Many notions are value-paradeigmatic. The most
important of all philosophical notions that of rationality, presupposes
objective value as one of its motivations. For Grice, ratio can be
understood cognoscendi but also essendi, indeed volendi and fiendi, too.
Rational motivation involves a ratio cognoscendi and a ratio volendi;
objective, “objectum,” and “objectus,” ūs, m. f. “obicio,” rendered as “a
casting before, a putting against, in the way, or opposite, an opposing; or,
neutr., a lying before or opposite (mostly poet. and in postAug. prose): dare
objectum parmaï, the opposing of the shield” “vestis;” “insula portum efficit
objectu laterum,” “by the opposition,” “cum terga flumine, latera objectu
paludis tegerentur;” “molis;” “regiones, quæ Tauri montis objectu separantur;”
“solem interventu lunæ occultari, lunamque terræ objectu, the interposition,”
“eademque terra objectu suo umbram noctemque efficiat;” “al. objecta soli: hi
molium objectus (i. e. moles objectas) scandere, the projection,” transf., that
which presents itself to the sight, an object, appearance, sight, spectacle;”
al. objecto; and if not categoric. This
is analogous to the overuse by Grice of psychoLOGICAL when he just means
souly. It is perhaps his use of psychological for souly that leads to take
any souly concept as a theoretical concept within a folksy psychoLOGICAL
theory. Grice considered the stratification of values, alla Hartmann, unlike
Barnes, who dismissed him in five minutes. “Some like Philippa Foot, but Hare
is MY man,” Grice would say. “Virtue” ethics was becoming all the fashion,
especially around Somerville. Hare was getting irritated by the worse offender,
his Anglo-Welsh tutee, originally with a degree from the other place, Williams.
Enough for Grice to want to lecture on value, and using Carus as an excuse!
Mackie was what Oxonians called a colonial, and a clever one! In fact, Grice
quotes from Hares contribution to a volume on Mackie. Hares and Mackies
backgrounds could not be more different. Like Grice, Hare was a Lit. Hum., and
like Grice, Hare loves the Grundlegung. But unlike Grice and Barnes, Hare would
have nothing to say about Stevenson. Philosophers in the play group of Grice
never took the critique by Ayer of emotivism seriously. Stevenson is the thing.
V. Urmson on the emotive theory of ethics, tracing it to English philosphers
like Ogden, Barnes, and Duncan-Jones. Barnes was opposing both Prichard (who
was the Whites professor of moral philosophy – and more of an interest than
Moore is, seeing that Prichard is Barness tutor at Corpus) and Hartmann. Ryle
would have nothing to do with Hartmann, but these were the days before Ryle
took over Oxford, and forbade any reference to a continental philosopher, even
worse if a “Hun.” Grice reaches the notion of value through that of meaning. If
Peirce is simplistic, Grice is not. But his ultra-sophisticated analysis ends
up being deemed to hold in this or that utterer. And deeming is valuing, as is
optimum. While Grice rarely used axiology, he should! A set of three
lectures, which are individually identified below. I love Carus! Grice was
undecided as to what his Carus lectures were be on. Grice explores meaning
under its value optimality guise in Meaning revisited. Grice thinks that a
value-paradeigmatic notion allows him to respond in a more apt way to what some
critics were raising as a possible vicious circle in his approach to semantic
and psychological notions. The Carus lectures are then dedicated to the
construction, alla Hume, of a value-paradeigmatic notion in general, and value
itself. Grice starts by quoting Austin, Hare, and Mackie, of
Oxford. The lectures are intended to a general audience, provided it is a
philosophical general audience. Most of the second lecture is a subtle
exploration by Grice of the categorical imperative of Kant, with which he had
struggled in the last Locke lecture in “Aspects,” notably the reduction of the
categorical imperative to this or that counsel of prudence with an implicated
protasis to the effect that the agent is aiming at eudæmonia. The Carus
Lectures are three: on objectivity and value, on relative and absolute value,
and on metaphysics and value. The first lecture, on objectivity and value,
is a review Inventing right and wrong by Mackie, quoting Hare’s
antipathy for a value being ‘objective’. The second lecture, on relative and
absolute value, is an exploration on the categorical imperative, and its
connection with a prior hypothetical or suppositional imperative. The
third lecture, on metaphycis and value, is an eschatological defence of
absolute value. The collective citation should be identified by each lecture
separately. This is a metaphysical defence by Grice of absolute value. The topic
fascinates Grice, and he invents a few routines to cope with it. Humeian
projection rationally reconstructs the intuitive concept being of
value. Category shift allows to put a value such as the disinterestedness
by Smith in grammatical subject position, thus avoiding to answer that the
disinterestedness of Smith is in the next room, since it is not the
spatio-temporal continuan prote ousia that Smith is. But the
most important routine is that of trans-substantatio, or metousiosis. A
human reconstructs as a rational personal being, and alla Kantotle,
whatever he judges is therefore of absolute value. The issue involves for
Grice the introduction of a telos qua aition, causa finalis (final cause),
role, or métier. The final cause of a tiger is to tigerise, the
final cause of a reasoner is to reason, the final cause of a person is to
personise. And this entails absolute value, now metaphysically defended. The
justification involves the ideas of end-setting, unweighed rationality,
autonomy, and freedom. In something like a shopping list that Grice
provides for issues on free. Attention to freedom calls for formidably
difficult undertakings including the search for a justification for the
adoption or abandonment of an ultimate end. The point is to secure that freedom
does not dissolve into compulsion or chance. Grice proposes four items for this
shopping list. A first point is that full action calls for strong freedom. Here
one has to be careful that since Grice abides by what he calls the Modified
Occams Razor in the third James lecture on Some remarks about logic and
conversation, he would not like to think of this two (strong freedom and weak
freedom) as being different senses of free. Again, his calls for is best
understood as presupposes. It may connect with, say, Kanes full-blown examples
of decisions in practical settings that call for or presuppose
libertarianism. A second point is that the buletic-doxastic justification
of action has to accomodate for the fact that we need freedom which is strong.
Strong or serious autonomy or freedom ensures that this or that action is
represented as directed to this or that end E which are is not merely the
agents, but which is also freely or autonomously adopted or pursued by the
agent. Grice discusses the case of the gym instructor commanding, Raise your
left arm! The serious point then involves this free adoption or free pursuit.
Note Grices use of this or that personal-identity pronoun: not merely mine,
i.e. not merely the agents, but in privileged-access position. This connects
with what Aristotle says of action as being up to me, and Kant’s idea of the
transcendental ego. An end is the agents in that the agent adopts it with
liberum arbitrium. This or that ground-level desire may be circumstantial. A
weak autonomy or freedom satisfactorily accounts for this or that action as
directed to an end which is mine. However, a strong autonomy or freedom, and a
strong autonomy or freedom only, accounts for this or that action as directed
to an end which is mine, but, unlike, say, some ground-level circumstantial
desire which may have sprung out of some circumstantial adaptability to a given
scenario, is, first, autonomously or freely adopted by the agent, and, second,
autonomously or freely pursued by the agent. The use of the disjunctive
particle or in the above is of some interest. An agent may autonomously or
freely adopt an end, yet not care to pursue it autonomously or freely, even in
this strong connotation that autonomous or free sometimes has. A further point
relates to causal indeterminacy. Any attempt to remedy this situation by
resorting to causal indeterminacy or chance will only infuriate the scientist
without aiding the philosopher. This remark by Grice has to be understood
casually. For, as it can be shown, this or that scientist may well have
resorted to precisely that introduction and in any case have not
self-infuriated. The professional tag that is connoted by philosopher should
also be seen as best implicated than entailed. A scientist who does resort to
the introduction of causal indeterminacy may be eo ipso be putting forward a
serious consideration regarding ethics or meta-ethics. In other words, a
cursory examination of the views of a scientist like Eddington, beloved by
Grice, or this or that moral philosopher like Kane should be born in mind when
considering this third point by Grice. The reference by Grice to chance,
random, and causal indeterminacy, should best be understood vis-à-vis
Aristotles emphasis on tykhe, fatum, to the effect that this or that event may
just happen just by accident, which may well open a can of worms for the naive
Griceian, but surely not the sophisticated one (cf. his remarks on
accidentally, in Prolegomena). A further item in Grices shopping list involves
the idea of autonomous or free as a value, or optimum. The specific character
of what Grice has as strong autonomy or freedom may well turn out to
consist, Grice hopes, in the idea of this or that action as the outcome of a
certain kind of strong valuation ‒ where this would include the
rational selection, as per e.g. rational-decision theory, of this or that
ultimate end. What Grice elsewhere calls out-weighed or extrinsically weighed
rationality, where rational includes the buletic, of the end and not the means
to it. This or that full human action calls for the presence of this or that
reason, which require that this or that full human action for which this or
that reason accounts should be the outcome of a strong rational valuation. Like
a more constructivist approach, this line suggests that this or that action may
require, besides strong autonomy or freedom, now also strong valuation. Grice
sets to consider how to adapt the buletic-doxastic soul progression to reach
these goals. In the case of this or that ultimate end E, justification should
be thought of as lying, directly, at least, in this or that outcome, not on the
actual phenomenal fulfilment of this or that end, but rather of the, perhaps
noumenal, presence qua end. Grice relates to Kants views on the benevolentia or
goodwill and malevolentia, or evil will, or illwill. Considers Smiths action of
giving Jones a job. Smith may be deemed to have given Jones a job, whether or
not Jones actually gets the job. It is Smiths benevolentia, or goodwill, not
his beneficentia, that matters. Hence in Short and Lewis, we have
“bĕnĕfĭcentĭa,” f. “beneficus,” like “magnificentia” f. magnificus, and
“munificentia” f. munificus; Cicero, Off. 1, 7, 20, and which they thus render
as “the quality of beneficus, kindness, beneficence, an honorable and kind
treatment of others” (omaleficentia, Lact. Ira Dei, 1, 1; several times in the
philos. writings of Cicero. Elsewhere rare: quid praestantius bonitate et
beneficentiā?” “beneficentia, quam eandem vel benignitatem vel liberalitatem
appellari licet,” “comitas ac beneficentia,” “uti beneficentiā adversus
supplices,”“beneficentia augebat ornabatque subjectsos.” In a more general
fashion then, it is the mere presence of an end qua end of a given action that
provides the justification of the end, and not its phenomenal satisfaction or
fulfilment. Furthermore, the agents having such and such an end, E1, or
such and such a combination of ends, E1 and E2, would be justified by showing
that the agents having this end exhibits some desirable feature, such as this
or that combo being harmonious. For how can one combine ones desire to smoke
with ones desire to lead a healthy life? Harmony is one of the six requirements
by Grice for an application of happy to the life of Smith. The buletic-doxastic
souly ascription is back in business at a higher level. The suggestion would
involve an appeal, in the justification of this or that end, to this or that
higher-order end which would be realised by having this or that lower, or
first-order end of a certain sort. Such valuation of this or that lower-order
end lies within reach of a buletic-doxastic souly ascription. Grice has an
important caveat at this point. This or that higher-order end involved in the
defense would itself stand in need of justification, and the regress might well
turn out to be vicious. One is reminded of Watson’s requirement for a thing
like freedom or personal identity to overcome this or that alleged
counterexample to freewill provided by H. Frankfurt. It is after the
laying of a shopping list, as it were, and considerations such as those above
that Grice concludes his reflection with a defense of a noumenon, complete with
the inner conflict that it brings. Attention to the idea of autonomous and free
leads the philosopher to the need to resolve if not dissolve the most important
unsolved problem of philosophy, viz. how an agent can be, at the same time, a
member of both the phenomenal world and the noumenal world, or, to settle the
internal conflict between one part of our rational nature, the doxastic, even
scientific, part which seems to call for the universal reign of a deterministic
law and the other buletic part which insists that not merely moral
responsibility but every variety of rational belief demands exemption from just
such a reign. In this lecture, Grice explores freedom and value from a
privileged-access incorrigible perspective rather than the creature
construction genitorial justification. Axiology – v. axiological. Valitum
-- Fact-value distinction, the apparently fundamental difference between how
things are and how they should be. That people obey the law or act honestly or
desire money is one thing; that they should is quite another. The first is a
matter of fact, the second a matter of value. Hume is usually credited with drawing
the distinction when he noticed that one cannot uncontroversially infer an
‘ought’ from an ‘is’ the isought gap. From the fact, say, that an action would
maximize overall happiness, we cannot legitimately infer that it ought to be
done without the introduction of some so
far suppressed evaluative premise. We could secure the inference by assuming
that one ought always to do what maximizes overall happiness. But that
assumption is evidently evaluative. And any other premise that might link the
non-evaluative premises to an evaluative conclusion would look equally
evaluative. No matter how detailed and extensive the non-evaluative premises,
it seems no evaluative conclusion follows directly and as a matter of logic.
Some have replied that at least a few non-evaluative claims do entail
evaluative ones. To take one popular example, from the fact that some promise
was made, we might it appears legitimately infer that it ought to be kept,
other things equal and this without the
introduction of an evaluative premise. Yet many argue that the inference fails,
or that the premise is actually evaluative, or that the conclusion is not. Hume
himself was both bold and brief about the gap’s significance, claiming simply
that paying attention to it “wou’d subvert all the vulgar systems of morality,
and let us see, that the distinction of vice and virtue is not founded merely
on the relations of objects, nor is perceiv’d by reason” Treatise of Human
Nature. Others have been more expansive. Moore, for instance, in effect relied
upon the gap to establish via the open question argument that any attempt to
define evaluative terms using non-evaluative ones would commit the naturalistic
fallacy. Moore’s main target was the suggestion that ‘good’ means “pleasant”
and the fallacy, in this context, is supposed to be misidentifying an
evaluative property, being good, with a natural property, being pleasant.
Assuming that evaluative terms have meaning, Moore held that some could be
defined using others he thought, e.g., that ‘right’ could be defined as
“productive of the greatest possible good” and that the rest, though
meaningful, must be indefinable terms denoting simple, non-natural, properties.
Accepting Moore’s use of the open question argument but rejecting both his
non-naturalism and his assumption that evaluative terms must have descriptive
meaning, emotivists and prescriptivists e.g. Ayer, C. L. Stevenson, and Hare
argued that evaluative terms have a role in language other than to denote
properties. According to them, the primary role of evaluative language is not
to describe, but to prescribe. The logical gap between ‘is’ and ‘ought’, they
argue, establishes both the difference between fact and value and the
difference between describing how things are and recommending how they might
be. Some naturalists, though, acknowledge the gap and yet maintain that the
evaluative claims nonetheless do refer to natural properties. In the process
they deny the ontological force of the open question argument and 302 F 302 treat evaluative claims as describing a
special class of facts. Refs.: The main
source is The construction of value, the Carus lectures, Clarendon. But there
are scattered essays on value and valuing in the Grice Papers. H. P. Grice,
“Objectivity and value,” s. V, c. 8-f. 18, “The rational motivation for
objective value,” s. V, c. 8-f. 19, “Value,” s. V, c. 9-f. 20; “Value,
metaphysics, and teleology,” s. V, c. 9-f. 23, “Values, morals, absolutes, and
the metaphysical,” s. V., c. 9-f. 24;
“Value sub-systems and the Kantian problem,” s. V. c. 9-ff. 25-27; “Values and
rationalism,” s. V, c. 9-f. 28; while the Carus are in the second series, in
five folders, s. II, c-2, ff. 12-16, the H. P. Grice Papers, BANC. value, the
worth of something. Philosophers have discerned these main forms: intrinsic,
instrumental, inherent, and relational value. Intrinsic value may be taken as
basic and many of the others defined in terms of it. Among the many attempts to
explicate the concept of intrinsic value, some deal primarily with the source
of value, while others employ the concept of the “fittingness” or
“appropriateness” to it of certain kinds of emotions and desires. The first is
favored by Moore and the second by Brentano. Proponents of the first view hold
that the intrinsic value of X is the value that X has solely in virtue of its
intrinsic nature. Thus, the state of affairs, Smith’s experiencing pleasure,
has intrinsic value provided it has value solely in virtue of its intrinsic
nature. Followers of the second approach explicate intrinsic value in terms of
the sorts of emotions and desires appropriate to a thing “in and for itself” or
“for its own sake”. Thus, one might say X has intrinsic value or is
intrinsically good if and only if X is worthy of desire in and for itself, or,
alternatively, it is fitting or appropriate for anyone to favor X in and for
itself. Thus, the state of affairs of Smith’s experiencing pleasure is
intrinsically valuable provided that state of affairs is worthy of desire for
its own sake, or it is fitting for anyone to favor that state of affairs in and
for itself. Concerning the other forms of value, we may say that X has
instrumental value if and only if it is a means to, or causally contributes to,
something that is intrinsically valuable. If Smith’s experiencing pleasure is
intrinsically valuable and his taking a warm bath is a means to, or Valentinus
value 948 948 causally contributes to,
his being pleased, then his taking a warm bath is instrumentally valuable or “valuable
as a means.” Similarly, if health is intrinsically valuable and exercise is a
means to health, then exercise is instrumentally valuable. X has inherent value
if and only if the experience, awareness, or contemplation of X is
intrinsically valuable. If the experience of a beautiful sunset is
intrinsically valuable, then the beautiful sunset has inherent value. X has
contributory value if and only if X contributes to the value of some whole, W,
of which it is a part. If W is a whole that consists of the facts that Smith is
pleased and Brown is pleased, then the fact that Smith is pleased contributes
to the value of W, and Smith’s being pleased has contributory value. Our
example illustrates that something can have contributory value without having
instrumental value, for the fact that Smith is pleased is not a means to W and,
strictly speaking, it does not bring about or causally contribute to W. Given
the distinction between instrumental and contributory value, we may say that
certain sorts of experiences and activities can have contributory value if they
are part of an intrinsically valuable life and contribute to its value, even
though they are not means to it. Finally, we may say that X has relational
value if and only if X has value in virtue of bearing some relation to
something else. Instrumental, inherent, and contributory value may be construed
as forms of relational value. But there are other forms of relational value one
might accept, e.g. one might hold that X is valuable for S in virtue of being
desired by S or being such that S would desire X were S “fully informed” and
“rational.” Some philosophers defend the organicity of intrinsic value. Moore,
for example, held that the intrinsic value of a whole is not necessarily equal
to the sum of the intrinsic values of its parts. According to this view, the
presence of an intrinsically good part might lower the intrinsic value of a
whole of which it is a part and the presence of an intrinsically bad part might
raise the intrinsic value of a whole to which it belongs. Defenders of organicity
sometimes point to examples of Mitfreude taking joy or pleasure in another’s
joy and Schadenfreude taking joy or pleasure in another’s suffering to
illustrate their view. Suppose Jones believes incorrectly that Smith is happy
and Brown believes incorrectly that Gray is suffering, but Jones is pleased
that Smith is happy and Brown is pleased that Gray is suffering. The former
instance of Mitfreude seems intrinsically better than the latter instance of
Schadenfreude even though they are both instances of pleasure and neither whole
has an intrinsically bad part. The value of each whole is not a “mere sum” of
the values of its parts. Valitum --
axiology: value theory, also called axiology, the branch of philosophy
concerned with the nature of value and with what kinds of things have value.
Construed very broadly, value theory is concerned with all forms of value, such
as the aesthetic values of beauty and ugliness, the ethical values of right,
wrong, obligation, virtue, and vice, and the epistemic values of justification
and lack of justification. Understood more narrowly, value theory is concerned
with what is intrinsically valuable or ultimately worthwhile and desirable for
its own sake and with the related concepts of instrumental, inherent, and
contributive value. When construed very broadly, the study of ethics may be
taken as a branch of value theory, but understood more narrowly value theory
may be taken as a branch of ethics. In its more narrow form, one of the chief
questions of the theory of value is, What is desirable for its own sake? One
traditional sort of answer is hedonism. Hedonism is roughly the view that i the
only intrinsically good experiences or states of affairs are those containing
pleasure, and the only instrinsically bad experiences or states of affairs are
those containing pain; ii all experiences or states of affairs that contain
more pleasure than pain are intrinsically good and all experiences or states of
affairs that contain more pain than pleasure are intrinsically bad; and iii any
experience or state of affairs that is intrinsically good is so in virtue of
being pleasant or containing pleasure and any experience or state of affairs
that is intrinsically bad is so in virtue of being painful or involving pain.
Hedonism has been defended by philosophers such as Epicurus, Bentham, Sidgwick,
and, with significant qualifications, J. S. Mill. Other philosophers, such as
C. I. Lewis, and, perhaps, Brand Blanshard, have held that what is
intrinsically or ultimately desirable are experiences that exhibit
“satisfactoriness,” where being pleasant is but one form of being satisfying.
Other philosophers have recognized a plurality of things other than pleasure or
satisfaction as having intrinsic value. Among the value pluralists are Moore,
Rashdall, Ross, Brentano, Hartmann, and Scheler. In addition to certain kinds
of pleasures, these thinkers count some or all of the following as
intrinsically good: consciousness and the flourishing of life, knowledge and
insight, moral virtue and virtuous actions, friendship and mutual affection,
beauty and aesthetic experience, a just distribution of goods, and
self-expression. Many, if not all, of the philosophers mentioned above
distinguish between what has value or is desirable for its own sake and what is
instrumentally valuable. Furthermore, they hold that what is desirable for its
own sake or intrinsically good has a value not dependent on anyone’s having an
interest in it. Both of these claims have been challenged by other value
theorists. Dewey, for example, criticizes any sharp distinction between what is
intrinsically good or good as an end and what is good as a means on the ground
that we adopt and abandon ends to the extent that they serve as means to the
resolution of conflicting impulses and desires. Perry denies that anything can
have value without being an object of interest. Indeed, Perry claims that ‘X is
valuable’ means ‘Interest is taken in X’ and that it is a subject’s interest in
a thing that confers value on it. Insofar as he holds that the value of a thing
is dependent upon a subject’s interest in that thing, Perry’s value theory is a
subjective theory and contrasts sharply with objective theories holding that
some things have value not dependent on a subject’s interests or attitudes.
Some philosophers, dissatisfied with the view that value depends on a subject’s
actual interests and theories, have proposed various alternatives, including
theories holding that the value of a thing depends on what a subject would
desire or have an interest in if he were fully rational or if desires were
based on full information. Such theories may be called “counterfactual” desire
theories since they take value to be dependent, not upon a subject’s actual
interests, but upon what a subject would desire if certain conditions, which do
not obtain, were to obtain. Value theory is also concerned with the nature of
value. Some philosophers have denied that sentences of the forms ‘X is good’ or
‘X is intrinsically good’ are, strictly speaking, either true or false. As with
other forms of ethical discourse, they claim that anyone who utters these
sentences is either expressing his emotional attitudes or else prescribing or
commending something. Other philosophers hold that such sentences can express
what is true or false, but disagree about the nature of value and the meaning
of value terms like ‘good’, ‘bad’, and ‘better’. Some philosophers, such as
Moore, hold that in a truth of the form ‘X is intrinsically good’, ‘good’
refers to a simple, unanalyzable, non-natural property, a property not
identical with or analyzable by any “natural” property such as being pleasant
or being desired. Moore’s view is one form of non-naturalism. Other
philosophers, such as Brentano, hold that ‘good’ is a syncategorematic
expression; as such it does not refer to a property or relation at all, though
it contributes to the meaning of the sentence. Still other philosophers have
held that ‘X is good’ and ‘X is intrinsically good’ can be analyzed in natural
or non-ethical terms. This sort of naturalism about value is illustrated by
Perry, who holds that ‘X is valuable’ means ‘X is an object of interest’. The
history of value theory is full of other attempted naturalistic analyses, some
of which identify or analyze ‘good’ in terms of pleasure or being the object of
rational desire. Many philosophers argue that naturalism is preferable on
epistemic grounds. If, e.g., ‘X is valuable’ just means ‘X is an object of
interest’, then in order to know whether something is valuable, one need only
know whether it is the object of someone’s interest. Our knowledge of value is
fundamentally no different in kind from our knowledge of any other empirical
fact. This argument, however, is not decisive against non-naturalism, since it
is not obvious that there is no synthetic a priori knowledge of the sort Moore
takes as the fundamental value cognition. Furthermore, it is not clear that one
cannot combine non-naturalism about value with a broadly empirical
epistemology, one that takes certain kinds of experience as epistemic grounds
for beliefs about value. Valitum --
valid, having the property that a well-formed formula, argument, argument form,
or rule of inference has when it is logically correct in a certain respect. A
well-formed formula is valid if it is true under every admissible
reinterpretation of its non-logical symbols. If truth-value gaps or multiple
truth-values are allowed, ‘true’ here might be replaced by ‘non-false’ or takes
a “designated” truth-value. An argument is valid if it is impossible for the
premises all to be true and, at the same time, the conclusion false. An
argument form schema is valid if every argument of that form is valid. A rule
of inference is valid if it cannot lead from all true premises to a false
conclusion. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The conception of value,” The Paul Carus
Lectures for the American Philosophical Association, published by Oxford, at
the Clarendon Press.
vanini: philosopher, a Renaissance Aristotelian who studied
law and theology. He became a monk and traveled all over Europe. After
abjuring, he taught and practiced medicine. He was burned at the stake by the
Inquisition. His major work is four volumes of dialogues, De admirandis naturae
reginae deaeque mortalium arcanis “On the Secrets of Nature, Queen and Goddess
of Mortal Beings,” 1616. He was influenced by Averroes and Pietro Pomponazzi,
whom he regarded as his teacher. Vanini rejects revealed religion and claims
that God is immanent in nature. The world is ruled by a necessary natural order
and is eternal. Like Averroes, he denies the immortality and the immateriality
of the human soul. Like Pomponazzi, he denies the existence of miracles and
claims that all apparently extraordinary phenomena can be shown to have natural
causes and to be predetermined. Despite the absence of any original
contribution, from the second half of the seventeenth century Vanini was
popular as a symbol of free and atheist thought. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Vanini
e Grice,” Villa Grice, Luigi Speranza, “La statua all’aperto di Vanini,” Luigi
Speranza, “Il medaglione di Vanini a Roma.”
variable: in semantics, a symbol interpreted so as to be
associated with a range of values, a set of entities any one of which may be
temporarily assigned as a value of the variable. Grice uses more specifically
for a variable for a ‘grice,’ a type of extinct pig that existed (‘in the
past’) in Northern England – “There is a variable number of grices in the backyard,
Paul.” An occurrence of a variable in a mathematical or logical expression is a
free occurrence if assigning a value is necessary in order for the containing
expression to acquire a semantic value a
denotation, truth-value, or other meaning. Suppose a semantic value is assigned
to a variable and the same value is attached to a constant as meaning of the
same kind; if an expression contains free occurrences of just that variable,
the value of the expression for that assignment of value to the variable is
standardly taken to be the same as the value of the expression obtained by
substituting the constant for all the free occurrences of the variable. A bound
occurrence of a variable is one that is not free. Grice: “Strictly, a variable
is the opposite of a constant, but a constant varies – ain’t that paradoxical?”
-- H. P. Grice, “The variable and the constant;” H. P. Grice, “Variable and
meta-variable,” “Order and variable.”
varrone: Grice: “I know his Loeb edition by
heart!” -- Academic, Roman polymath,
author of works on language, agriculture, history and philosophy, as well as satires, and principal
speaker in the later version of Cicero’s
"Academica"
varzi: essential Italian
philosopher. Refs.: Luigi Speranza,
"Grice e Varzi: semantica filosofia," per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The
Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia
vasto: essential Italian
philosopher – Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice e del Vasto," per Il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
vattimo: Italian philosopher – not one that
provinicial Beaney would include in his handbooks and dictionaries – Vattimo’s
philosophy shares quite a bit with Grice’s programme, as anyone familiar with
both Vattimo and Grice may testify. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice e
Vattimo," The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
vauvenargues: luc de Clapiers
de, army officer and secular moralist. Discovering Plutarch at an early age, he
critically adopted Stoic idealism. Poverty-stricken, obscure, and solitary, he
was ambitious for glory. Though eventful, his military career brought little reward.
In poor health, he resigned in 1744 to write. In 1747, he published
Introduction to the Knowledge of the Human Mind, followed by Reflections and
Maxims. Voltaire and Mirabeau praised his vigorous and eclectic thought, which
aimed at teaching people how to live. Vauvenargues was a deist and an optimist
who equally rejected Bossuet’s Christian pessimism and La Rochefoucauld’s
secular pessimism. He asserted human freedom and natural goodness, but denied
social and political equality. A lover of martial virtues and noble passions,
Vauvenargues crafted memorable maxims and excelled in character depiction. His
complete works were published in 1862.
velia -- Velia -- Grice as Eleatic -- School, strictly, two
fifth-century B.C. Grecian philosophers, Parmenides and Zeno of Elea. The
Ionian Grecian colony of Elea or Hyele in southern Italy became Velia in Roman
times and retains that name today. A playful remark by Plato in Sophist 242d
gave rise to the notion that Xenophanes of Colophon, who was active in southern
Italy and Sicily, was Parmenides’ teacher, had anticipated Parmenides’ views,
and founded the Eleatic School. Moreover, Melissus of Samos and according to
some ancient sources even the atomist philosopher Leucippus of Abdera came to
be regarded as “Eleatics,” in the sense of sharing fundamental views with
Parmenides and Zeno. In the broad and traditional use of the term, the Eleatic
School characteristically holds that “all is one” and that change and plurality
are unreal. So stated, the School’s position is represented best by Melissus.
Grice: “Crotone and Velia are the origins of western philosophy, since Greece
is eastern!” – Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Grice a Velia,” Villa Grice.
venn diagram, a logic diagram invented by the English philosopher
J. Venn in which standard form statements the four kinds listed below are
represented by two appropriately marked overlapping circles, as follows:
Syllogisms are represented by three overlapping circles, as in the examples
below. If a few simple rules are followed, e.g. “diagram universal premises
first,” then in a valid syllogism diagramming the premises automatically gives
a diagram in which the conclusion is represented. In an invalid syllogism
diagramming the premises does not automatically give a diagram in which the
conclusion is represented, as below. Venn diagrams are less perspicuous for the
beginner than Euler diagrams. Grice: “I tried to teach Strawson some Euler
first; but English as he is, he said, ‘Stick with Venn.’” – Refs.: H. P. Grice,
“From Euler to Strawson via Venn: diagramme and impicaturum.”
verificatum:
Grice: “Strictly, what is ‘verified’ is therefore ‘made true,’ analytically.”
-- see ayerism. Grice would possibly NOT be interested in verificationism had
not been for Ayer ‘breaking tradition’ “and other things” with it --. Oppoiste
Christian virtuous –ism: falsificationism. Verificationism is one of the twelve
temptations Grice finds on his way to the City of Eternal Truth. (Each one has
its own entry). Oddly, Boethius was the first verificationist. He use
‘verifico’ performatively. “When I say, ‘verifico’, I verify that what I say is
true.” He didn’t mean it as a sophisma (or Griceisma, but it was
(mis-)understood as such! “When I was listing the temptations, I thought of
calling this ‘Ayerism,’ but then I changed my mind. verification theory of
meaning The theory of meaning advocated by the logical positivists and
associated with the criterion of verifiability. The latter provides a criterion
of meaningfulness for sentences, while the verification theory of meaning
specifies the nature of meaning. According to the criterion, a sentence is
cognitively meaningful if and only if it is logically possible for it to be
verified. The meaning of a sentence is its method of verification, that is, the
way in which it can be verified or falsified, particularly by experience. The
theory has been challenged because the best formulations still exclude
meaningful sentences and allow meaningless sentences. Critics also claim that
the theory is a test for meaningfulness rather than a theory of meaning proper.
Further, they claim that it fails to recognize that the interconnectedness of
language might allow a sentence that cannot itself be verified to be
meaningful. “The verification theory of meaning, which dominated the Vienna
Circle, was concerned with the meaning and meaningfulness of sentences rather
than words.” Quine, Theories and Things verificationism Philosophical method,
philosophy of science, philosophy of language A position fundamental to logical
positivism, claiming that the meaning of a statement is its method of
verification. Accordingly, apparent statements lacking a method of
verification, such as those of religion and metaphysics, are meaningless.
Theoretical expressions can be defined in terms of the experiences by means of
which assertions employing them can be verified. In the philosophy of mind,
behaviorism, which tries to reduce unobserved inner states to patterns of
behavior, turns out to be a version of verificationism. Some philosophers
require conclusive verification for a statement to be meaningful, while others
allow any positive evidence to confer meaning. There are disputes whether every
statement must be verified separately or theories can be verified as a whole
even if some of their statements cannot be individually verified. Attempts to
offer a rigorous account of verification have run into difficulties because
statements that should be excluded as meaningless nevertheless pass the test of verification and
statements that should be allowed as meaningful are excluded. “For over a
hundred years, one of the dominant tendencies in the philosophy of science has
been verificationism, that is, the doctrine that to know the meaning of a
scientific proposition . . . is to know what would be evidence for that
proposition.” Putnam, Mind, Language and Reality verisimilitude Philosophy of
science [from Latin verisimilar, like the truth] The degree of approximation or
closeness to truth of a statement or a theory. Popper defined it in terms of
the difference resulting from truth-content minus falsity-content. The
truthcontent of a statement is all of its true consequences, while the
falsity-content of a statement is all of its false consequences. The aim of
science is to find better verisimilitude. One theory has a better
verisimilitude than competing theories if it can explain the success of
competing theories and can also explain cases where the other theories fail.
Popper emphasized that verisimilitude is different from probability.
Probability is the degree of logical certainty abstracted from content, while
verisimilitude is degree of likeness to truth and combines truth and content.
“This suggests that we combine here the ideas of truth and content into one –
the idea of a degree of better (or worse) correspondence to truth or of greater
(or less) likeness or similarity to truth; or to use a term already mentioned
above (in contradistinction to probability) the idea of (degrees of )
verisimilitude.” Popper, Conjectures and Refutations.
verisimile -- verisimilitude -- truthlikeness, a term
introduced by Karl Popper to explicate the idea that one theory may have a
better correspondence with reality, or be closer to the truth, or have more
verisimilitude, than another theory. Truthlikeness, which combines truth with
information content, has to be distinguished from probability, which increases
with lack of content. Let T and F be the classes of all true and false
sentences, respectively, and A and B deductively closed sets of sentences.
According to Popper’s qualitative definition, A is more truthlike than B if and
only if B 3 T 0 A 3 T and A 3 F 0 B 3 F, where one of these setinclusions is
strict. In particular, when A and B are non-equivalent and both true, A is more
truthlike than B if and only if A logically entails B. David Miller and Pavel
Tichý proved in 4 that Popper’s definition is not applicable to the comparison
of false theories: if A is more truthlike than B, then A must be true. Since
the mid-0s, a new approach to truthlikeness has been based upon the concept of
similarity: the degree of truthlikeness of a statement A depends on the
distances from the states of affairs allowed by A to the true state. In Graham
Oddie’s Likeness to Truth 6, this dependence is expressed by the average
function; in Ilkka Niiniluoto’s Truthlikeness 7, by the weighted average of the
minimum distance and the sum of all distances. The concept of verisimilitude is
also used in the epistemic sense to express a rational evaluation of how close
to the truth a theory appears to be on available evidence.
verri: essential Italian philosopher.
Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice e Verri," per il Club Anglo-Italiano,
The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
verum – verum – Grice: “Cognate with German ‘wahr’” -- there’s
the ‘truth table’ and the ‘truth’ -- truth table, a tabular display of one or
more truth-functions, truth-functional operators, or representatives of
truth-functions or truth-functional operators such as well-formed formulas of
propositional logic. In the tabular display, each row displays a possible assignment
of truthvalues to the arguments of the truth-functions or truth-functional
operators. Thus, the collection of all rows in the table displays all possible
assignments of truth-values to these arguments. The following simple truth
table represents the truth-functional operators negation and conjunction:
truth, coherence theory of truth table 931
931 Because a truth table displays all possible assignments of
truth-values to the arguments of a truth-function, truth tables are useful
devices for quickly ascertaining logical properties of propositions. If, e.g.,
all entries in the column of a truth table representing a proposition are T,
then the proposition is true for all possible assignments of truth-values to
its ultimate constituent propositions; in this sort of case, the proposition is
said to be logically or tautologically true: a tautology. If all entries in the
column of a truth table representing a proposition are F, then the proposition
is false for all possible assignments of truth-values to its ultimate
constituent propositions, and the proposition is said to be logically or
tautologically false: a contradiction. If a proposition is neither a tautology
nor a contradiction, then it is said to be a contingency. The truth table above
shows that both Not-P and Pand-Q are contingencies. For the same reason that
truth tables are useful devices for ascertaining the logical qualities of
single propositions, truth tables are also useful for ascertaining whether
arguments are valid or invalid. A valid argument is one such that there is no
possibility no row in the relevant truth table in which all its premises are
true and its conclusion false. Thus the above truth table shows that the
argument ‘P-and-Q; therefore, P’ is valid.
Verum -- truth-value, most narrowly, one of the values T for ‘true’ or F
for ‘false’ that a proposition may be considered to have or take on when it is
regarded as true or false, respectively. More broadly, a truth-value is any one
of a range of values that a proposition may be considered to have when taken to
have one of a range of different cognitive or epistemic statuses. For example,
some philosophers speak of the truth-value I for ‘indeterminate’ and regard a
proposition as having the value I when it is indeterminate whether the proposition
is true or false. Logical systems employing a specific number n of truthvalues
are said to be n-valued logical systems; the simplest sort of useful logical
system has two truth-values, T and F, and accordingly is said to be two-valued.
Truth-functions are functions that take truth-values as arguments and that
yield truth-values as resultant values. The truthtable method in propositional
logic exploits the idea of truth-functions by using tabular displays. Verum --
truth-value semantics, interpretations of formal systems in which the
truth-value of a formula rests ultimately only on truth-values that are
assigned to its atomic subformulas where ‘subformula’ is suitably defined. The
label is due to Hugues Leblanc. On a truth-value interpretation for first-order
predicate logic, for example, the formula atomic ExFx is true in a model if and
only if all its instances Fm, Fn, . . . are true, where the truth-value of
these formulas is simply assigned by the model. On the standard Tarskian or
objectual interpretation, by contrast, ExFx is true in a model if and only if
every object in the domain of the model is an element of the set that
interprets F in the model. Thus a truth-value semantics for predicate logic
comprises a substitutional interpretation of the quantifiers and a
“non-denotational” interpretation of terms and predicates. If t 1, t 2, . . .
are all the terms of some first-order language, then there are objectual models
that satisfy the set {Dx-Fx, Ft1, Ft2 . . . .}, but no truth-value interpretations
that do. One can ensure that truth-value semantics delivers the standard logic,
however, by suitable modifications in the definitions of consistency and
consequence. A set G of formulas of language L is said to be consistent, for
example, if there is some G' obtained from G by relettering terms such that G'
is satisfied by some truth-value assignment, or, alternatively, if there is
some language L+ obtained by adding terms to L such that G is satisfied by some
truth-value assignment to the atoms of L+. Truth-value semantics is of both
technical and philosophical interest. Technically, it allows the completeness
of first-order predicate logic and a variety of other formal systems to be
obtained in a natural way from that of propositional logic. Philosophically, it
dramatizes the fact that the formulas in one’s theories about the world do not,
in themselves, determine one’s ontological commitments. It is at least possible
to interpret first-order formulas without reference to special truth-table
method truth-value semantics 932 932
domains of objects, and higher-order formulas without reference to special
domains of relations and properties. The idea of truth-value semantics dates at
least to the writings of E. W. Beth on first-order predicate logic in 9 and of
K. Schütte on simple type theory in 0. In more recent years similar semantics
have been suggested for secondorder logics, modal and tense logics,
intuitionistic logic, and set theory. Truth, the quality of those propositions
that accord with reality, specifying what is in fact the case. Whereas the aim
of a science is to discover which of the propositions in its domain are true
i.e., which propositions possess the property of Trinity truth 929 929 truth
the central philosophical concern with truth is to discover the nature
of that property. Thus the philosophical question is not What is true? but
rather, What is truth? What is one
saying about a proposition in saying that it is true? The importance of this
question stems from the variety and depth of the principles in which the
concept of truth is deployed. We are tempted to think, e.g., that truth is the
proper aim and natural result of scientific inquiry, that true beliefs are
useful, that the meaning of a sentence is given by the conditions that would
render it true, and that valid reasoning preserves truth. Therefore insofar as
we wish to understand, assess, and refine these epistemological, ethical,
semantic, and logical views, some account of the nature of truth would seem to
be required. Such a thing, however, has been notoriously elusive. The belief
that snow is white owes its truth to a certain feature of the external world:
the fact that snow is white. Similarly, the belief that dogs bark is true
because of the fact that dogs bark. Such trivial observations lead to what is
perhaps the most natural and widely held account of truth, the correspondence
theory, according to which a belief statement, sentence, proposition, etc. is
true provided there exists a fact corresponding to it. This Aristotelian thesis
is unexceptionable in itself. However, if it is to provide a complete theory of
truth and if it is to be more than
merely a picturesque way of asserting all instances of ‘the belief that p is
true if and only if p’ then it must be
supplemented with accounts of what facts are, and what it is for a belief to
correspond to a fact; and these are the problems on which the correspondence
theory of truth has foundered. A popular alternative to the correspondence
theory has been to identify truth with verifiability. This idea can take on
various forms. One version involves the further assumption that verification is
holistic i.e., that a belief is verified
when it is part of an entire system of beliefs that is consistent and
“harmonious.” This is known as the coherence theory of truth and was developed
by Bradley and Brand Blanchard. Another version, due to Dummett and Putnam,
involves the assumption that there is, for each proposition, some specific
procedure for finding out whether one should believe it or not. On this
account, to say that a proposition is true is to say that it would be verified
by the appropriate procedure. In mathematics this amounts to the identification
of truth with provability and is sometimes referred to as intuitionistic truth.
Such theories aim to avoid obscure metaphysical notions and explain the close
relation between knowability and truth. They appear, however, to overstate the
intimacy of that link: for we can easily imagine a statement that, though true,
is beyond our power to establish as true. A third major account of truth is
James’s pragmatic theory. As we have just seen, the verificationist selects a
prominent property of truth and considers it to be the essence of truth.
Similarly the pragmatist focuses on another important characteristic namely, that true beliefs are a good basis
for action and takes this to be the very
nature of truth. True assumptions are said to be, by definition, those that
provoke actions with desirable results. Again we have an account with a single
attractive explanatory feature. But again the central objection is that the
relationship it postulates between truth and its alleged analysans in this case, utility is implausibly close. Granted, true beliefs
tend to foster success. But often actions based on true beliefs lead to
disaster, while false assumptions, by pure chance, produce wonderful results.
One of the few fairly uncontroversial facts about truth is that the proposition
that snow is white is true if and only if snow is white, the proposition that
lying is wrong is true if and only if lying is wrong, and so on. Traditional
theories of truth acknowledge this fact but regard it as insufficient and, as
we have seen, inflate it with some further principle of the form ‘X is true if
and only if X has property P’ such as corresponding to reality, verifiability,
or being suitable as a basis for action, which is supposed to specify what
truth is. A collection of radical alternatives to the traditional theories
results from denying the need for any such further specification. For example,
one might suppose with Ramsey, Ayer, and Strawson that the basic theory of
truth contains nothing more than equivalences of the form, ‘The proposition
that p is true if and only if p’ excluding instantiation by sentences such as
‘This proposition is not true’ that generate contradiction. This so-called
deflationary theory is best presented following Quine in conjunction with an
account of the raison d’être of our notion of truth: namely, that its function
is not to describe propositions, as one might naively infer from its syntactic
form, but rather to enable us to construct a certain type of generalization.
For example, ‘What Einstein said is true’ is intuitively equivalent to the
infinite conjunction ‘If Einstein said that nothing goes faster than light,
then nothing goes faster than light; and if Einstein said truth truth 930 930 that nuclear weapons should never be
built, then nuclear weapons should never be built; . . . and so on.’ But
without a truth predicate we could not capture this statement. The deflationist
argues, moreover, that all legitimate uses of the truth predicate including those in science, logic, semantics,
and metaphysics are simply displays of
this generalizing function, and that the equivalence schema is just what is
needed to explain that function. Within the deflationary camp there are various
competing proposals. According to Frege’s socalled redundancy theory,
corresponding instances of ‘It is true that p’ and ‘p’ have exactly the same
meaning, whereas the minimalist theory assumes merely that such propositions
are necessarily equivalent. Other deflationists are skeptical about the
existence of propositions and therefore take sentences to be the basic vehicles
of truth. Thus the disquotation theory supposes that truth is captured by the
disquotation principle, ‘p’ is true if and only if p’. More ambitiously, Tarski
does not regard the disquotation principle, also known as Tarski’s T schema, as
an adequate theory in itself, but as a specification of what any adequate
definition must imply. His own account shows how to give an explicit definition
of truth for all the sentences of certain formal languages in terms of the
referents of their primitive names and predicates. This is known as the
semantic theory of truth. Grice: “From ‘verum’ we have to ‘make’ true, as the
Romans put it, ‘verificare’ -- verificatum -- verificationism, a metaphysical
theory about what determines meaning: the meaning of a statement consists in
its methods of verification. Verificationism thus differs radically from the
account that identifies meaning with truth conditions, as is implicit in
Frege’s work and explicit in Vitters’s Tractatus and throughout the writings of
Davidson. On Davidson’s theory, e.g., the crucial notions for a theory of
meaning are truth and falsity. Contemporary verificationists, under the
influence of the Oxford philosopher Michael Dummett, propose what they see as a
constraint on the concept of truth rather than a criterion of meaningfulness.
No foundational place is generally assigned in modern verificationist semantics
to corroboration by observation statements; and modern verificationism is not
reductionist. Thus, many philosophers read Quine’s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”
as rejecting verificationism. This is because they fail to notice an important
distinction. What Quine rejects is not verificationism but “reductionism,”
namely, the theory that there is, for each statement, a corresponding range of
verifying conditions determinable a priori. Reductionism is inherently localist
with regard to verification; whereas verificationism, as such, is neutral on
whether verification is holistic. And, lastly, modern verificationism is, veil
of ignorance verificationism 953 953
whereas traditional verificationism never was, connected with revisionism in
the philosophy of logic and mathematics e.g., rejecting the principle of
bivalence. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The taming of the true.” Porphyry called the
verum one of the four transcendental, along with unum, pulchrum and bonum –
Grice agreed. Grice’s concern with the ‘verum’ is serious. If Quine is right,
and logical truth should go, so truth should go. Grice needs ‘true’ to correct
a few philosophical mistakes. It is true that Grice sees a horse as a horse,
for example. The nuances of the implicaturum are of a lesser concern for Grice
than the taming of the true. The root of
Latin ‘vero’ is cognate with an idea Grice loved: that of ‘sincerity.’ The
point is more obviously realised lexically in the negative: the fallax versus
the mendax. But ‘verum’ had to do with candidum – and thus very much cognate
with the English that Grice avoided, ‘truth,’ cognate with ‘trust.’ quod non
possit ab honestate sejungi The true and simple Good which cannot be separated
from honesty, Cicero, Academica, I, 2, but also for the ontological which one
can find in Cicero’s tr. Topica, 35 of etumologia ἐτυμολογία by veriloquium.
Most contemporary hypotheses propose that verus —and the words signifying true,
vrai, vérité, G. wahr, G. Wahrheit — derive from an Indo-European root, *wer,
which would retain meanings of to please, pleasing, manifesting benevolence,
gifts, services rendered, fidelity, pact. Chantraine Dictionnaire étymologique
de la langue grecque links it to the Homeric expression êra pherein ἦϱα φέϱειν,
to please, as well as to ἐπίηϱα, ἐπίηϱος, and ἐπιήϱανος, agreeable Odyssey, 19,
343, just like the Roman verus cf. se-vere, without benevolence, the G. war, and the Russian vera, faith, or verit’
верить, to believe. Pokorny adds to this same theme the Grecian ἑοϱτή,
religious feast, cult. And from the same basis have come terms signifying
guarantee, protect: Fr. garir and later
garant, G. Gewähren, Eng. warrant, to
grant. According to Chantraine, this root *wer should be distinguished from
another root ver-, whence eirô εἴϱω in Grecian , verbum in Roman word in
English, etc., and words from the family of vereor, revereor, to fear, to
respect, verecundia respectful fear. According to Chantraine, this root *wer
should be distinguished from another root ver-, whence eirô εἴϱω in Grecian ,
verbum in Roman word in English, etc., and words from the family of vereor,
revereor, to fear, to respect, verecundia respectful fear. Alfred Ernout does
not support this separation. We should recall that plays on the words verum and
verbum were common, as Augustine mentions verbum = verum boare, proclaiming the
truth, Dialectics 1. P. Florensky, following G. Curtius, “Grundzüge der
griechischen Etymologie,” also claims a single root for the ensemble of these
derivations, including the Sanskrit vratum, sacred act, vow, promise, the
Grecian bretas βϱέτας, cult object, wooden idol Aeschylus, Eumenides, v. 258,
and the Roman “ver-bum.” The signification of verus must be considered as belonging
first to the field of religious ritual and subsequently of juridical formulas:
strictly speaking, verus means protected or grounded in the sense of that which
is the object of a taboo or consecration Pillar and Ground. Then there’s from
the juridical to the philosophical. “Verum” implies a rectification of an
adversarial allegation considered to be fraudulent, as is indicated by the
original opposition verax/fallax-mendax. It thus signifies the properly founded
in fact or in the rules of law: crimen verissimum a well-founded accusation
Cicero, In Verrem, 5, 15. In texts of grammar and rhetoric, but also in
juridical texts as well, verus and veritas signify the veracity of the rule,
inasmuch as it can be distinguished from usage. “Quid verum sit intellego; sed
alias ita loquor ut concessum est I know what is correct, but sometimes I avail
myself of the variation in usage, Cicero, De oratore, Loeb Classical Library;
Consule veritatem: reprehendet; refer ad auris: probabunt If you consult the
strict rule of analogy, it will say this practice is wrong, but if you consult
the ear, it will approve 1586. The juridical connotation of the word verus and
thus of veritas is retained and subsequently reinforced. In the glosses of the
Middle Ages, verus signifies legitimate and the Roman sense of the word, legal
and authentic or conforming to existing law. One normally finds “verum est” in
legal texts to certify that a new rule conforms to preexisting ones Digest, 8,
4, 1. It is this juridical dimension that produces the meaning of verus as
authenticated, authentic in contrast to false, imitative, deceiving and thus
real as in real cream or a genuine Rolex watch.
The juridical here provides a foundation not only for the moral Verum et
simplex bonum. The paradigm of “verum” is not easy to separate from any
epistemological dimensions, as is evident in the varied fates of the
Indo-European root *wer, from which derives, in addition to vera in Russian,
belief, the old Fr. garir, in the sense
of certifying as true, designating as true, whence the participle garant. The
evolution of these derived words inscribes G. “wahr,” and “Wahrheit” in a
semantic network from which emerge two directions, belief and salvation.
Belief. “Wahr” is often linked back, in composite words, to the idea of belief,
in the sense of true belief, to take as true. “Wahrsagen,” to predict, “wahr
haben,” to admit, agree upon, “für wahr halten,” to hold as true, to believe.
This is the term that Kant employs in the Critique of Pure Reason,
Transcendental theory of method, ch.2, 3 On Opinion, Science, and Belief: “das
Fürwahrhalten” is a belief, as a modality of subjectivity, that can be divided
into conviction Überzeugung or persuasion Überredung and that is capable of
three degrees: opinion Meinung, belief Glaube, and science Wissenschaft.
Safeguarding, conservation. Similarly “wahren,” “bewahren” in the sense of to
guard, to conserve is linked to “Wahrung” in the sense of defending one’s
interests or safeguarding. One might refer to Heidegger’s use of this etymological
and semantic relation in reference to Nietzsche. It remains to be said that
many common or colloquial expressions, in Fr.
as well as in English, play on the semantic slippages of vrai and real,
between the ontological sense and linguistic meanings. Thus in Fr. , c’est pas
vrai! does not mean it is false, but rather that it is not reality. In English,
the opposite is the case: get real! means come back down to earth, accept the
truth. Grice’s main manoeuvre may be seen as intended to crack the crib of
reality. For he wants to say some philosophers engaged in conceptual analysis
are misled if they think an inappropriate usage reveals a truth-condition. By
coining ‘implicaturum,’ his point is to give room for “Emissor E communicates
that p,” as opposed to ‘emissum x ‘means’ ‘p.’ Therefore, Grice can claim that
an utterance may very well totally baffling and misleading YET TRUE (or
otherwise ‘good’), and that in no way that reveals anything about the emissum
itself. This is due to the fact that ‘Emissor E communicates that p’ is
diaphanous. And one can conjoin what the emissor E communicates to what he
explicitly conveys and NOT HAVE the emissor contradicting himself or uttering a
falsehood. And that is what in philosophy should count. H. P. Grice was always
happy with a ‘correspondence’ theory of truth. It was what Aristotle thought.
So why change? The fact that Austin agreed helped. The fact that Strawson
applied Austin’s shining new tool of the performatory had him fashion a new
shining skid, and that helped, because, once Grice has identified a
philosophical mistake, that justifies his role as methodologist in trying to
‘correct’ the mistake. The Old Romans did not have an article. For them it is
the unum, the verum, the bonum, and the pulchrum. They were trying to translate
the very articled Grecian ‘to alethes,’ ‘to agathon,’ and ‘to kallon.’ Grecian
Grice is able to restore the articles. He would use ‘the alethic’ for the
‘verum,’ after von Wright. But occasionally uses the ‘verum’ root. E. g. when
his account of ‘personal identity’ was seen to fail to distinguish between a
‘veridical’ memory and a non-veridical one. If it had not been for Strawson’s
‘ditto’ theory to the ‘verum,’ Grice would not have minded much. Like Austin,
his inclination was for a ‘correspondence’ theory of truth alla Aristotle and
Tarski, applied to the utterance, or ‘expressum.’ So, while we cannot say that
an utterer is TRUE, we can say that he is TRUTHFUL, and trustworthy
(Anglo-Saxon ‘trust,’ being cognate with ‘true,’ and covering both the
credibility and desirability realms. Grice approaches the ‘verum’ in terms of
predicate calculus. So we need at least an utterance of the form, ‘the dog is
shaggy.’ An utterance of ‘The dog is shaggy’ is true iff the denotatum of ‘the
dog’ is a member of the class ‘shaggy.’ So, when it comes to ‘verum,’ Grice
feels like ‘solving’ a problem rather than looking for new ones. He thought
that Strawson’s controversial ‘ditto’ was enough of a problem ‘to get rid of.’
VERUM. Along with verum, comes the falsum. fallibilism, the doctrine, relative
to some significant class of beliefs or propositions, that they are inherently
uncertain and possibly mistaken. The most extreme form of the doctrine
attributes uncertainty to every belief; more restricted forms attribute it to
all empirical beliefs or to beliefs concerning the past, the future, other
minds, or the external world. Most contemporary philosophers reject the
doctrine in its extreme form, holding that beliefs about such things as
elementary logical principles and the character of one’s current feelings
cannot possibly be mistaken. Philosophers who reject fallibilism in some form
generally insist that certain beliefs are analytically true, self-evident, or
intuitively obvious. These means of supporting the infallibility of faculty
psychology fallibilism 303 303 some
beliefs are now generally discredited. W. V. Quine has cast serious doubt on
the very notion of analytic truth, and the appeal to self-evidence or intuitive
obviousness is open to the charge that those who officially accept it do not
always agree on what is thus evident or obvious there is no objective way of
identifying it, and that beliefs said to be self-evident have sometimes been
proved false, the causal principle and the axiom of abstraction in set theory
being striking examples. In addition to emphasizing the evolution of logical
and mathematical principles, fallibilists have supported their position mainly
by arguing that the existence and nature of mind-independent objects can
legitimately be ascertained only be experimental methods and that such methods
can yield conclusions that are, at best, probable rather than certain. false
consciousness, 1 lack of clear awareness of the source and significance of
one’s beliefs and attitudes concerning society, religion, or values; 2
objectionable forms of ignorance and false belief; 3 dishonest forms of
self-deception. Marxists if not Marx use the expression to explain and condemn
illusions generated by unfair economic relationships. Thus, workers who are
unaware of their alienation, and “happy homemakers” who only dimly sense their
dependency and quiet desperation, are molded in their attitudes by economic
power relationships that make the status quo seem natural, thereby eclipsing their
long-term best interests. Again, religion is construed as an economically
driven ideology that functions as an “opiate” blocking clear awareness of human
needs. Collingwood interprets false consciousness as self-corrupting
untruthfulness in disowning one’s emotions and ideas The Principles of Art,
8. . false pleasure, pleasure taken in
something false. If it is false that Jones is honest, but Smith believes Jones
is honest and is pleased that Jones is honest, then Smith’s pleasure is false.
If pleasure is construed as an intentional attitude, then the truth or falsity
of a pleasure is a function of whether its intentional object obtains. On this
view, S’s being pleased that p is a true pleasure if an only if S is pleased
that p and p is true. S’s being pleased that p is a false pleasure if and only
if S is pleased that p and p is false. Alternatively, Plato uses the expression
‘false pleasure’ to refer to things such as the cessation of pain or neutral
states that are neither pleasant nor painful that a subject confuses with
genuine or true pleasures. Thus, being released from tight shackles might
mistakenly be thought pleasant when it is merely the cessation of a pain. Refs:
Grice, “Rationality and Trust,” Grice, “The alethic.” “P. F. Strawson and the
performatory account of ‘true’”, The Grice Papers.
verstehen G., ‘understanding’ (literally, for-standing), ‘interpretation’,
a method in the human sciences that aims at reconstructing meanings from the
“agent’s point of view.” Such a method makes primary how agents understand
themselves, as, e.g., when cultural anthropologists try to understand symbols
and practices from the “native’s point of view.” Understanding in this sense is
often contrasted with explanation, or Erklärung. Whereas explanations discover
causes in light of general laws and take an external perspective, understanding
aims at explicating the meaning that, from an internal perspective, an action
or expression has for the actor. This distinction often is the basis for a
further methodological and ontological distinction between the natural and the
human sciences, the Natur- and the Geisteswissenschaften. Whereas the data of
the natural sciences may be theory-dependent and in that sense interpretive,
the human sciences are “doubly” interpretive; they try to interpret the
interpretations that human subjects give to their actions and practices. The
human sciences do not aim at explaining events but at understanding meanings,
texts, and text analogues. Actions, artifacts, and social relations are all
like texts in that they have a significance for and by human subjects. The
method of Verstehen thus denies the “unity of science” thesis typical of
accounts of explanation given by empiricists and positivists. However, other
philosophers such as Weber argue against such a dichotomy and assert that the
social sciences in particular must incorporate features of both explanation and
understanding, and psychoanalysis and theories of ideology unify both
approaches. Even among proponents of this method, the precise nature of
interpretation remains controversial. While Dilthey and other neo-Kantians
proposed that Verstehen is the imaginative reexperiencing of the subjective
point of view of the actor, Vitters and his following propose a sharp
distinction between reasons and causes and understand reasons in terms of
relating an action to the relevant rules or norms that it follows. In both
cases, the aim of the human sciences is to understand what the text or text
analogue really means for the agent. Following Heidegger, recent G.
hermeneutics argues that Verstehen does not refer to special disciplinary
techniques nor to merely cognitive and theoretical achievements, but to the
practical mode of all human existence, its situatedness in a world that
projects various possibilities. All understanding then becomes interpretation,
itself a universal feature of all human activity, including the natural
sciences. The criteria of success in Verstehen also remain disputed,
particularly since many philosophers deny that it constitutes a method. If all
understanding is interpretation, then there are no presuppositionless, neutral
data that can put them to an empirical test. Verstehen is therefore not a
method but an event, in which there is a “fusion of horizons” between text and
interpreter. Whether criteria such as coherence, the capacity to engage in a
tradition, or increasing dialogue apply depends on the type, purpose, and
context of various interpretations. Grice: “If Austin coined a witticism,
that’s ‘uptake,’ so much better than the verbose ‘understanding,’ which in
Cockney means a leg!” --.
vico: He is
so beloved by the Italians “that they made a stamp of him.” – Grice. cited by
H. P. Grice, “Vico and the origin of language.” Philosopher who founded modern
philosophy of history, philosophy of culture, and philosophy of mythology. He
was born and lived all his life in or near Naples, where he taught eloquence.
The Inquisition was a force in Naples throughout Vico’s lifetime. A turning
point in his career was his loss of the concourse for a chair of civil law
1723. Although a disappointment and an injustice, it enabled him to produce his
major philosophical work. He was appointed royal historiographer by Charles of
Bourbon. Vico’s major work is “La scienza nuova” completely revised in a second, definitive
version in 1730. In the 1720s, he published three connected works in Latin on
jurisprudence, under the title Universal Law; one contains a sketch of his
conception of a “new science” of the historical life of nations. Vico’s
principal works preceding this are On the Study Methods of Our Time 1709,
comparing the ancients with the moderns regarding human education, and On the
Most Ancient Wisdom of the s 1710, attacking the Cartesian conception of
metaphysics. His Autobiography inaugurates the conception of modern
intellectual autobiography. Basic to Vico’s philosophy is his principle that
“the true is the made” “verum ipsum factum”, that what is true is convertible
with what is made. This principle is central in his conception of “science”
scientia, scienza. A science is possible only for those subjects in which such
a conversion is possible. There can be a science of mathematics, since
mathematical truths are such because we make them. Analogously, there can be a
science of the civil world of the historical life of nations. Since we make the
things of the civil world, it is possible for us to have a science of them. As
the makers of our own world, like God as the maker who makes by knowing and
knows by making, we can have knowledge per caussas through causes, from within.
In the natural sciences we can have only conscientia a kind of “consciousness”,
not scientia, because things in nature are not made by the knower. Vico’s “new
science” is a science of the principles whereby “men make history”; it is also
a demonstration of “what providence has wrought in history.” All nations rise
and fall in cycles within history corsi e ricorsi in a pattern governed by
providence. The world of nations or, in the Augustinian phrase Vico uses, “the
great city of the human race,” exhibits a pattern of three ages of “ideal
eternal history” storia ideale eterna. Every nation passes through an age of
gods when people think in terms of gods, an age of heroes when all virtues and
institutions are formed through the personalities of heroes, and an age of
humans when all sense of the divine is lost, life becomes luxurious and false,
and thought becomes abstract and ineffective; then the cycle must begin again.
In the first two ages all life and thought are governed by the primordial power
of “imagination” fantasia and the world is ordered through the power of humans
to form experience in terms of “imaginative universals” universali fantastici.
These two ages are governed by “poetic wisdom” sapienza poetica. At the basis
of Vico’s conception of history, society, and knowledge is a conception of
mythical thought as the origin of the human world. Fantasia is the original
power of the human mind through which the true and the made are converted to
create the myths and gods that are at the basis of any cycle of history.
Michelet was the primary supporter of Vico’s ideas in the nineteenth century;
he made them the basis of his own philosophy of history. Coleridge is the
principal disseminator of Vico’s views in England. James Joyce used the New
Science as a substructure for Finnegans Wake, making plays on Vico’s name,
beginning with one in Latin in the first sentence: “by a commodius vicus of
recirculation.” Croce revives Vico’s philosophical thought, wishing to conceive
Vico as the Hegel. Vico’s ideas have
been the subject of analysis by such prominent philosophical thinkers as
Horkheimer and Berlin, by anthropologists such as Edmund Leach, and by literary
critics such as René Wellek and Herbert Read. Refs.: S. N. Hampshire, “Vico,”
in The New Yorker. Luigi Speranza, “Vico alla Villa Grice.” H. P. Grice, “Vico
and language.” vico -- Danesi,
Marcel. Vico, Metaphor, and the
Origin of Language. Bloomington: Indiana. Serious scholars of Vico as well as glottogeneticists
will find much of value in this excellent monograph. Vico Studies. A
provocative, well-researched argument which might find reapplication in
philosophy." —Theological Book Review.
Danesi returns to Vico to create a
persuasive, original account of the evolution and development of language, one
of the deep mysteries of human existence. The Vico’s reconstruction of the
origin of language is described at length, then evaluated in light of Grice’s
philosophical conversational pragmatics. Glottogenesis Vico’s Reconstruction.
The New Science Basic Notions. Language and the Imagination: Vito’s
Glottogenetic Scenario Vico’s Approach Reconstructing the Primal Scene After
the Primal Scence. The Dawn of Communication: Iconicity and Mimesis Hypotheses
The Nature of Iconicity. Imagery, Iconicity, and Gesture. Iconic
Representation. Osmosis Hypothesis Ontogenesis From Percepts to Concepts The
Metaphoricity Metaphor Metaphor and Concept-Formation Mentation, Narrativity,
and Myth The Sociobiological-Computationist
Viewpoint:A Vichian Critique The Vichian Scenario Revisited Revisting the
Genetic Perspective computationism.
Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Vico e Grice,” Villa Grice.
vio: essential Italian philosopher. Grice was irritated that
when ‘vio’ became a saint, the Italians list them under ‘c’. He wrote
extensively on freewill, and had a colourful dispute with, of all people,
Calvin – well represented in a painting Grice adored. Refs.: Luigi Speranza,
“Grice e de Vio.” The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
violence: Grice: “I would define ‘violence’ as the use of force
to cause physical harm, death, or destruction physical violence; the causing of severe mental or emotional
harm, as through humiliation, deprivation, or brainwashing, whether using force
or not psychological violence; more broadly, profaning, desecrating, defiling,
or showing disrespect for i.e., “doing violence” to something valued, sacred,
or cherished; extreme physical force in the natural world, as in tornados,
hurricanes, and earthquakes. Physical violence may be directed against persons,
animals, or property.” Grice goes on: “In the first two cases, harm, pain, suffering,
and death figure prominently; in the third, illegality or illegitimacy the
forceful destruction of property is typically considered violence when it lacks
authorization. Psychological violence applies principally to persons. It may be
understood as the violation of beings worthy of respect. But it can apply to
higher animals as well as in the damaging mental effects of some
experimentation, e.g., involving isolation and deprivation. Environmentalists
sometimes speak of violence against the environment, implying both destruction
and disrespect for the natural world. Sometimes the concept of violence is used
to characterize acts or practices of which one morally disapproves. To this
extent it has a normative force. But this prejudges whether violence is wrong.
One may, on the other hand, regard inflicting harm or death as only prima facie
wrong i.e., wrong all other things being equal. This gives violence a normative
character, establishing its prima facie wrongness. But it leaves open the
ultimate moral justifiability of its use. Established practices of physical or
psychological violence e.g., war,
capital punishment constitute
institutionalized violence. So do illegal or extralegal practices like
vigilantism, torture, and state terrorism e.g., death squads. Anarchists
sometimes regard the courts, prisons, and police essential to maintaining the
state as violence. Racism and sexism may be considered institutional violence
owing to their associated psychological as well as physical violence. Refs.: H.
P. Grice, “Causes and reasons.”
virtuosum – Grice: “The etymology of ‘virtue’ is fantastic: it
is strictly a bit like ‘manliness,’ only the Romans were never sure who was
‘vir’ and who wasn’t!” -- “virtue is entire” – “Do not multiply virtues beyond
necessity” -- virtue ethics, also called virtue-based ethics and agent-based
ethics, conceptions or theories of morality in which virtues play a central or
independent role. Thus, it is more than simply the account of the virtues
offered by a given theory. Some take the principal claim of virtue ethics to be
about the moral subject that, in living
her life, she should focus her attention on the cultivation of her or others’
virtues. Others take the principal claim to be about the moral theorist that, in mapping the structure of our moral
thought, she should concentrate on the virtues. This latter view can be
construed weakly as holding that the moral virtues are no less basic than other
moral concepts. In this type of virtue ethics, virtues are independent of other
moral concepts in that claims about morally virtuous character or action are,
in the main, neither reducible to nor justified on the basis of underlying
claims about moral duty or rights, or about what is impersonally valuable. It
can also be construed strongly as holding that the moral virtues are more basic
than other moral concepts. In such a virtue ethics, virtues are fundamental,
i.e., claims about other moral concepts are either reducible to underlying
claims about moral virtues or justified on their basis. Forms of virtue ethics
predominated in Western philosophy before the Renaissance, most notably in
Aristotle, but also in Plato and Aquinas. Several ancient and medieval
philosophers endorsed strong versions of virtue ethics. These views focused on
character rather than on discrete behavior, identifying illicit behavior with
vicious behavior, i.e., conduct that would be seriously out of character for a
virtuous person. A virtuous person, in turn, was defined as one with
dispositions relevantly linked to human flourishing. On these views, while a
person of good character, or someone who carefully observes her, may be able to
articulate certain principles or rules by which she guides her conduct or to
which, at least, it outwardly conforms, the principles are not an ultimate
source of moral justification. On the contrary, they are justified only insofar
as the conduct they endorse would be in character for a virtuous person. For
Aristotle, the connection between flourishing and virtue seems conceptual. He
conceived moral virtues as dispositions to choose under the proper guidance of
reason, and defined a flourishing life as one lived in accordance with these
virtues. While most accounts of the virtues link them to the flourishing of the
virtuous person, there are other possibilities. In principle, the flourishing
to which virtue is tied whether causally or conceptually may be either that of
the virtuous subject herself, or that of some patient who is a recipient of her
virtuous behavior, or that of some larger affected group the agent’s community, perhaps, or all
humanity, or even sentient life in general. For the philosophers of ancient
Greece, it was human nature, usually conceived teleologically, that fixed the
content of this flourishing. Medieval Christian writers reinterpreted this,
stipulating both that the flourishing life to which the virtues lead extends
past death, and that human flourishing is not merely the fulfillment of
capacities and tendencies inherent in human nature, but is the realization of a
divine plan. In late twentieth-century versions of virtue ethics, some
theorists have suggested that it is neither to a teleology inherent in human
nature nor to the divine will that we should look in determining the content of
that flourishing to which the virtues lead. They understand flourishing more as
a matter of a person’s living a life that meets the standards of her cultural,
historical tradition. In his most general characterization, Aristotle called a
thing’s virtues those features of it that made it and its operation good. The
moral virtues were what made people live well. This use of ‘making’ is
ambiguous. Where he and other premodern thinkers thought the connection between
virtues and living well to be conceptual, moral theorists of the modernist era
have usually virtue ethics virtue ethics understood it causally. They commonly
maintain that a virtue is a character trait that disposes a person to do what
can be independently identified as morally required or to effect what is best best
for herself, according to some theories; best for others, according to
different ones. Benjamin Franklin, e.g., deemed it virtuous for a person to be
frugal, because he thought frugality was likely to result in her having a less
troubled life. On views of this sort, a lively concern for the welfare of
others has moral importance only inasmuch as it tends to motivate people
actually to perform helpful actions. In short, benevolence is a virtue because
it conduces to beneficent conduct; veracity, because it conduces to truth
telling; fidelity, because it conduces to promise keeping; and so on. Reacting
to this aspect of modernist philosophy, recent proponents of virtue ethics deny
that moral virtues derive from prior determinations of what actions are right
or of what states of affairs are best. Some, especially certain theorists of
liberalism, assign virtues to what they see as one compartment of moral thought
and duties to a separate, and only loosely connected compartment. For them, the
life and theory of virtue is autonomous. They hold that virtues and duties have
independent sources of justification, with virtues chiefly concerned with the
individual’s personal “ideals,” self-image, or conception of her life goals,
while duties and rights are thought to derive from social rules regulating
interpersonal dealings. Proponents of virtue ethics maintain that it has
certain advantages over more modern alternatives. They argue that virtue ethics
is properly concrete, because it grounds morality in facts about human nature
or about the concrete development of particular cultural traditions, in
contrast with modernist attempts to ground morality in subjective preference or
in abstract principles of reason. They also claim that virtue ethics is truer
to human psychology in concentrating on the less conscious aspects of
motivation on relatively stable
dispositions, habits, and long-term goals, for example where modern ethics focuses on decision
making directed by principles and rules. Virtue ethics, some say, offers a more
unified and comprehensive conception of moral life, one that extends beyond
actions to comprise wants, goals, likes and dislikes, and, in general, what
sort of person one is and aims to be. Proponents of virtue ethics also contend
that, without the sensitivity and appreciation of their situation and its
opportunities that only virtues consistently make available, agents cannot
properly apply the rules that modernist ethical theories offer to guide their
actions. Nor, in their view, will the agent follow those rules unless her
virtues offer her sufficient clarity of purpose and perseverance against
temptation. Several objections have been raised against virtue ethics in its
most recent forms. Critics contend that it is antiquarian, because it relies on
conceptions of human nature whose teleology renders them obsolete; circular,
because it allegedly defines right action in terms of virtues while defining
virtues in terms of right action; arbitrary and irrelevant to modern society,
since there is today no accepted standard either of what constitutes human
flourishing or of which dispositions lead to it; of no practical use, because
it offers no guidance when virtues seem to conflict; egoistic, in that it
ultimately directs the subject’s moral attention to herself rather than to
others; and fatalistic, in allowing the morality of one’s behavior to hinge
finally on luck in one’s constitution, upbringing, and opportunities. There may
be versions of virtue ethics that escape the force of all or most of the objections,
but not every form of virtue ethics can claim for itself all the advantages
mentioned above. virtue epistemology,
the subfield of epistemology that takes epistemic virtue to be central to
understanding justification or knowledge or both. An epistemic virtue is a
personal quality conducive to the discovery of truth, the avoidance of error,
or some other intellectually valuable goal. Following Aristotle, we should
distinguish these virtues from such qualities as wisdom or good judgment, which
are the intellectual basis of practical
but not necessarily intellectual
success. The importance, and to an extent, the very definition, of this
notion depends, however, on larger issues of epistemology. For those who favor
a naturalist conception of knowledge say, as belief formed in a “reliable” way,
there is reason to call any truth-conducive quality or properly working
cognitive mechanism an epistemic virtue. There is no particular reason to limit
the epistemic virtues to recognizable personal qualities: a high mathematical
aptitude may count as an epistemic virtue. For those who favor a more
“normative” conception of knowledge, the corresponding notion of an epistemic
virtue or vice will be narrower: it will be tied to personal qualities like
impartiality or carelessness whose exercise one would associate with an ethics
of belief. H. P. Grice, “Philosophy, like virtue, is entire;” H. P. Grice,
“Virtutes non sunt multiplicanda praeter necessitatem,” H. P. Grice,
“Aristotle’s mesotes – where virtue lies.”
vis: When in a Latinate mood, Grice would refer to a ‘vis’
of an expression. Apparently, ‘vis’ is cognate with ‘validum,’ transf., of abstr. things, force, notion, meaning, sense, import, nature, essence (cf. significatio): “id, in quo est omnis vis amicitiae,” Cic. Lael. 4, 15: “eloquentiae vis et natura,” id. Or. 31, 112: “vis honesti (with natura),” id. Off. 1, 6, 18; cf. id. Fin. 1, 16, 50: “virtutis,” id. Fam. 9, 16, 5: “quae est alia vis legis?” id. Dom. 20, 53: “vis, natura, genera verborum et simplicium et copulatorum,” i.e. the sense, signification, id. Or. 32, 115: “vis verbi,” id. Inv. 1, 13, 17; id. Balb. 8, 21: “quae vis insit in his paucis verbis, si attendes, si attendes, intelleges,” id. Fam. 6, 2, 3: “quae vis subjecta sit vocibus,” id. Fin. 2, 2, 6: “nominis,” id. Top. 8, 35: μετωνυμία, cujus vis est, pro eo, quod dicitur, causam, propter
quam dicitur, ponere, Quint. 8, 6, 23.
vital lie: Grice: “I would define a vital life as an instance of
self-deception or lying to oneself when it fosters hope, confidence,
self-esteem, mental health, or creativity; or any false belief or unjustified
attitude that helps people cope with difficulties; or a lie to other people designed to promote
their wellbeing; e.. g.: self-deceiving optimism about one’s prospects for
success in work or personal relationships may generate hope, mobilize energy,
enrich life’s meaning, and increase chances for success. Grice considers the
optimism law as basic in folk-psychology. Ibsen dramatises “life-lies” as
essential for happiness The Wild Duck, and O’Neill portrays “pipe dreams” as
necessary crutches The Iceman Cometh. Nietzsche endorsed “pious illusions” or
“holy fictions” about the past that liberate individuals and societies from
shame and guilt On the Advantage and Disadvantage of History for Life. In
Problems of belief, Schiller praised normal degrees of vanity and self-conceit
because they support selfesteem. Refs.: H. P. Grice: “Optimism,” in “Method in
philosophical psychology: from the banal to the bizarre.”
vitoria: dominican jurist, political philosopher, and
theologian who is regarded as the founder of modern international law. Born in
Vitoria or Burgos, he studied and taught at the
of SaintJacques in Paris, where he met Erasmus and Vives. He also taught
at the of San Gregorio in Valladolid and
at Salamanca. His most famous works are the notes relectiones for twelve public
addresses he delivered at Salamanca, published posthumously in 1557. Two
relectiones stand out: De Indis and De jure belli. They were responses to the
legal and political issues raised by the discovery and colonization of America.
In contrast with Mariana’s contract Arianism, Vitoria held that political
society is our natural state. The aim of the state is to promote the common
good and preserve the rights of citizens. Citizenship is the result of
birthplace jus solis rather than blood jus sanguini. The authority of the state
resides in the body politic but is transferred to rulers for its proper
exercise. The best form of government is monarchy because it preserves the
unity necessary for social action while safeguarding individual freedoms. Apart
from the societies of individual states, humans belong to an international
society. This society has its own authority and laws that establish the rights
and duties of the states. These laws constitute the law of nations jus gentium.
vives: attended the
of Paris and lived most of his life in Flanders. With his friend Erasmus
he prepared a widely used commentary of Augustine’s De civitate Dei. From 1523
to 1528 Vives visited England, taught at Oxford, befriended More, and became
Catherine of Aragon’s confidant. While in Paris, Vives repudiated medieval
logic as useless Adversus pseudodialecticos, 1520 and proposed instead a
dialectic emphasizing resourceful reasoning and clear and persuasive exposition
De tradendis disciplinis. His method was
partially inspired by Rudolph Agricola and probably influential upon Peter
Ramus. Less interested in theology than Erasmus or More, he surpassed both in
philosophical depth. As one of the great pedagogues of his age, Vives proposed
a plan of education that substituted the Aristotelian ideal of speculative
certainty for a pragmatic probability capable of guiding action. Vives enlarged
the scope of women’s education De institutione feminae Christianae, 1524 and
contributed to the teaching of classical Latin Exercitatio linguae latinae,
1538. A champion of EuroVisistadvaita Vedanta Vives, Juan Luis 962 962 pean unity against the Turks, he
professed the belief that international order De concordia, 1526 depended upon
the control of passion De anima et vita, 1538. As a social reformer, Vives
pioneered the secularization of welfare De subventione pauperum, 1526 and
opposed the abuse of legal jargon Aedes legum, 1520. Although his Jewish
parents were victimized by the Inquisition, Vives remained a Catholic and
managed to write an apology of Christianity without taking sides in
controversial theological matters De veritate fidei.
volition: cf. desideratum. a mental event involved with the
initiation of action. ‘To will’ is sometimes taken to be the corresponding verb
form of ‘volition’. The concept of volition is rooted in modern philosophy;
contemporary philosophers have transformed it by identifying volitions with
ordinary mental events, such as intentions, or beliefs plus desires. Volitions,
especially in contemporary guises, are often taken to be complex mental events
consisting of cognitive, affective, and conative elements. The conative element
is the impetus the underlying
motivation for the action. A velleity is
a conative element insufficient by itself to initiate action. The will is a
faculty, or set of abilities, that yields the mental events involved in
initiating action. There are three primary theories about the role of volitions
in action. The first is a reductive account in which action is identified with
the entire causal sequence of the mental event the volition causing the bodily
behavior. J. S. Mill, for example, says: “Now what is action? Not one thing,
but a series of two things: the state of mind called a volition, followed by an
effect. . . . [T]he two together constitute the action” Logic. Mary’s raising
her arm is Mary’s mental state causing her arm to rise. Neither Mary’s
volitional state nor her arm’s rising are themselves actions; rather, the
entire causal sequence the “causing” is the action. The primary difficulty for
this account is maintaining its reductive status. There is no way to delineate
volition and the resultant bodily behavior without referring to action. There
are two non-reductive accounts, one that identifies the action with the
initiating volition and another that identifies the action with the effect of
the volition. In the former, a volition is the action, and bodily movements are
mere causal consequences. Berkeley advocates this view: “The Mind . . . is to
be accounted active in . . . so far forth as volition is included. . . . In
plucking this flower I am active, because I do it by the motion of my hand,
which was consequent upon my volition” Three Dialogues. In this century,
Prichard is associated with this theory: “to act is really to will something”
Moral Obligation, 9, where willing is sui generis though at other places
Prichard equates willing with the action of mentally setting oneself to do
something. In this sense, a volition is an act of will. This account has come
under attack by Ryle Concept of Mind. Ryle argues that it leads to a vicious
regress, in that to will to do something, one must will to will to do it, and
so on. It has been countered that the regress collapses; there is nothing
beyond willing that one must do in order to will. Another criticism of Ryle’s,
which is more telling, is that ‘volition’ is an obscurantic term of art;
“[volition] is an artificial concept. We have to study certain specialist
theories in order to find out how it is to be manipulated. . . . [It is like]
‘phlogiston’ and ‘animal spirits’ . . . [which] have now no utility” Concept of
Mind. Another approach, the causal theory of action, identifies an action with
the causal consequences of volition. Locke, e.g., says: “Volition or willing is
an act of the mind directing its thought to the production of any action, and
thereby exerting its power to produce it. . . . [V]olition is nothing but that
particular determination of the mind, whereby . . . the mind endeavors to give
rise, continuation, or stop, to any action which it takes to be in its power”
Essay concerning Human Understanding. This is a functional account, since an
event is an action in virtue of its causal role. Mary’s arm rising is Mary’s
action of raising her arm in virtue of being caused by her willing to raise it.
If her arm’s rising had been caused by a nervous twitch, it would not be
action, even if the bodily movements were photographically the same. In
response to Ryle’s charge of obscurantism, contemporary causal theorists tend
to identify volitions with ordinary mental events. For example, Davidson takes
the cause of actions to be beliefs plus desires and Wilfrid Sellars takes
volitions to be intentions to do something here and now. Despite its
plausibility, however, the causal theory faces two difficult problems: the
first is purported counterexamples based on wayward causal chains connecting
the antecedent mental event and the bodily movements; the second is provision
of an enlightening account of these mental events, e.g. intending, that does
justice to the conative element. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “A. J. P. Kenny on
voliting.”
voluntarism: -- W. James: “I will that the chair slides over the
floor toward me. It doesn’t.” cf. Grice on the volitive – desiderative -- any
philosophical view that makes our ability to control the phenomena in question
an essential part of the correct understanding of those phenomena. Thus,
ethical voluntarism is the doctrine that the standards that define right and
wrong conduct are in some sense chosen by us. Doxastic voluntarism is the
doctrine that we have extensive control over what we believe; we choose what to
believe. A special case of doxastic voluntarism is theological voluntarism,
which implies that religious belief requires a substantial element of choice;
the evidence alone cannot decide the issue. This is a view that is closely
associated with Pascal, Kierkegaard, and James. Historical voluntarism is the
doctrine that the human will is a major factor in history. Such views contrast
with Marxist views of history. Metaphysical voluntarism is the doctrine, linked
with Schopenhauer, that the fundamental organizing principle of the world is
not the incarnation of a rational or a moral order but rather the will, which
for Schopenhauer is an ultimately meaningless striving for survival, to be
found in all of nature. Refs.: H. P.
Grice, “The will”
voting
paradox: the possibility that if there
are three candidates, A, B, and C, for democratic choice, with at least three
choosers, and the choosers are asked to make sequential choices among pairs of
candidates, A could defeat B by a majority vote, B could defeat C, and C could
defeat A. This would be the outcome if the choosers’ preferences were ABC, BCA,
and CAB. Hence, although each individual voter may have a clear preference
ordering over the candidates, the collective may have cyclic preferences, so
that individual and majoritarian collective preference orderings are not
analogous. While this fact is not a logical paradox, it is perplexing to many
analysts of social choice. It may also be morally perplexing in that it
suggests majority rule can be quite capricious. For example, suppose we vote
sequentially over various pairs of candidates, with the winner at each step
facing a new candidate. If the candidates are favored by cyclic majorities, the
last candidate to enter the fray will win the final vote. Hence, control over
the sequence of votes may determine the outcome. It is easy to find cyclic
preferences over such candidates as movies and other matters of taste. Hence,
the problem of the voting paradox is clearly real and not merely a logical
contrivance. But is it important? Institutions may block the generation of
evidence for cyclic majorities by making choices pairwise and sequentially, as
above. And some issues over which we vote provoke preference patterns that
cannot produce cycles. For example, if our issue is one of unidimensional
liberalism versus conservatism on some major political issue such as welfare
programs, there may be no one who would prefer to spend both more and less
money than what is spent in the status quo. Hence, everyone may display
single-peaked preferences with preferences falling as we move in either
direction toward more money or toward less from the peak. If all important issues
and combinations of issues had this preference structure, the voting paradox
would be unimportant. It is widely supposed by many public choice scholars that
collective preferences are not single-peaked for many issues or, therefore, for
combinations of issues. Hence, collective choices may be quite chaotic. What
order they display may result from institutional manipulation. If this is
correct, we may wonder whether democracy in the sense of the sovereignty of the
electorate is a coherent notion. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Grice’s Book of Paradoxes
– with pictures and illustrations.”
vyse: an unfortunate example by Grice. He wants to give an
ambiguous sentence, “Strawson is caught in the grip of a vice.” Oddly, in The
New World, Webster noticed this, and favoured the spelling ‘vyse.’ “But what
Webster fails,” Grice adds, “to note, is that ‘vice’ and ‘vyse’ ARE cognate,
hence no need for double talk!” “They both can be traced to ‘violence.’” Sir
Cecil Vyse happens to be a character in Forster’s “A room with a view,” which gives
a triple ambiguity, to “Strawson was caught in the grip of a Vyse.” Vyse was
wonderfully played by Daniel Day Lewis in the film. “What is your profession,
Mister Vyse?” Vyse: “Must one have a profeesion?” – Vyse’s favourite motto
applies to Grice, “Ingelese italianato, diavolo incarnate.” – Grice: “Stupidly,
when this is reversed the implicature is lost.
W
ward: j. English philosopher and psychologist. Influenced
by Lotze, Herbart, and Brentano, Ward sharply criticized Bain’s associationism
and its allied nineteenth-century reductive naturalism. His psychology rejected
the associationists’ sensationism, which regarded mind as passive, capable only
of sensory receptivity and composed solely of cognitive presentations. Ward
emphasized the mind’s inherent activity, asserting, like Kant, the prior
existence of an inferred but necessarily existing ego or subject capable of
feeling and, most importantly, of conation, shaping both experience and
behavior by the willful exercise of attention. Ward’s psychology stresses
attention and will. In his metaphysics, Ward resisted the naturalists’
mechanistic materialism, proposing instead a teleological spiritualistic
monism. While his criticisms of associationism and naturalism were telling,
Ward was a transitional figure whose positive influence is limited, if we
except H. P. Grice who follows him to a T. Although sympathetic to scientific
psychology – he founded scientific psychology in Britain by establishing a
psychology laboratory – he, with his
student Stout, represented the beginning of armchair psychology at Oxford,
which Grice adored. Through Stout he influenced the hormic psychology of
McDougall, and Grice who calls himself a Stoutian (“until Prichard converted
me”). Ward’s major work is “Psychology” (Encyclopedia Britannica, 9th ed.,
1886), reworked as Psychological Principles (1918). “one of the most
philosophical psychologists England (if not Oxford) ever produced!” – H. P.
Grice -- cited by H. P. Grice. -- English philosopher. Influenced by Lotze,
Herbart, and Brentano, Ward sharply criticized Bain’s associationism and its
allied nineteenth-century reductive naturalism. His psychology rejected the
associationists’ sensationism, which regarded mind as passive, capable only of
sensory receptivity and composed solely of cognitive presentations. Ward
emphasized the mind’s inherent activity, asserting, like Kant, the prior
existence of an inferred but necessarily existing ego or subject capable of
feeling and, most importantly, of conation, shaping both experience and
behavior by the willful exercise of attention. Ward’s psychology stresses
attention and will. In his metaphysics, Ward resisted the naturalists’
mechanistic materialism, proposing instead a teleological spiritualistic
monism. While his criticisms of associationism and naturalism were telling,
Ward was a transitional figure whose positive influence is limited, if we
except H. P. Grice who follows him to a T. Although sympathetic to scientific
psychology he founded scientific
psychology in Britain by establishing a psychology laboratory he, with his student Stout, represented the
beginning of armchair psychology at Oxford, which Grice adored. Through Stout
he influenced the hormic psychology of McDougall, and Grice who calls himself a
Stoutian “until Prichard converted me”. Ward’s major work is “Psychology”
Encyclopedia Britannica, 9th ed., 6, reworked as Psychological Principles
8.
warnock: Irish
philosopher, born in the north of England (“He was so Irish, I could sing
‘Danny Boy’ to him all day long – Dame Mary Warnock). “One of my most
intelligent collaborators.” Unlike any other of the collaborators, Warnock had
what Grice calls “the gift for botanising.” They would spend hours on the
philosophy of perception. His other English collaborators were, in alphabetic
order: Pears, Strawson, and Thomson. And you can see the difference. Thomson
was pretty obscure. Pears was a closet Vittersian. And Strawson was ‘to the
point.’ With Warnock, Grice could ramble at ease. Warnock became the custodian
of Austin’s heritage which somehow annoyed Grice. But the Warnock that Grice
enjoyed most was the Warnock-while-the-SchoolMaster-Austin-was-around. Because
they could play. And NOT in the play group, which was “anything but.” But Grice
would philosophise on ‘perception,’ and especially ‘see’ – with Warnock. Their
idiolects differed. Warnock, being Irish, was more creative, and less
conservative. So it was good for Warnock to have Grice to harness him! Through
Warnock, Grice got to discuss a few things with Urmson, the co-custodian of Austin’s
legacy. But again, most of the discussions with Urmson were before Austin’s
demise. Urmson and Warnock are the co-editors of Austin’s “Philosophical
Papers.” Would Austin have accepted? Who knows. The essays were more or less
easily available. Still.
warnockianism: Grice: “I told Warnock, ‘How clever language is!” “He
agreed, for we realised that language makes all the distinctions you need, and
when you feel there is one missing, language allows you to introduce it!” --.
Refs.: H. P. Grice and G. J. Warnock, The philosophy of perception – Folder –
BANC MSS 90/135c, The Bancroft Library, The University of California, Berkeley.
weapon: Grice’s shining new tool. The funny thing is that his
tutee Strawson didn’t allow him to play with it ONCE! Or weapon. Grice refers
to the implicaturum as a philosopher’s tool, and that the fun comes in the
application. Strawson and Wiggins p. 522, reminds us of Austin. Austin used to
say that when a philosopher “forges a new weapon, he is also fshioning new
skids to put under his feet.” It is perhaps inappropriate that a memorial
should mention this, but here they were, the memorialists. They were suggesting
that Grice forged a shining new tool, the implicaturum, or implicaturum –
rather, he proposed a rational explanation for the distinction between what an
emissor means (e. g., that p) and what anything else may be said,
‘metabolically,’ to “mean.” Suggesting an analogy with J. L. Austin and his
infelicitious notion of infelicity, which found him fashioning a shining new
skid, the memorialists suggest the same for Grice – but of course the analogy
does not apply.
weber: philosopher, b. Berlin. Grice liked him “because he
invented, or thought he invented, more or less, ‘zweckrationalitaet’ – which he
refused to translate!” – H. P. Grice.-- born in a liberal and intellectual
household, he taught economics in Heidelberg, where his circle included leading
sociologists and philosophers such as Simmel and Lukacs. Although Weber gave up
his professorship after a nervous breakdown in 9, he remained important in
public life, an adviser to the commissions that drafted the peace treaty at
Versailles and the Weimar constitution. Weber’s social theory was influenced
philosophically by both neo-Kantianism and Nietzsche, creating tensions in a theorist
who focused much of his attention on Occidental rationalism and yet was a
noncognitivist in ethics. He wrote many comparative studies on topics such as
law and urbanization and a celebrated study of the cultural factors responsible
for the rise of capitalism, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism
4. But his major, synthetic work in social theory is Economy and Society 4; it
includes a methodological introduction to the basic concepts of sociology that
has been treated by many philosophers of social science. One of the main
theoretical goals of Weber’s work is to understand how social processes become
“rationalized,” taking up certain themes want-belief model Weber, Max 968 of the G. philosophy of history since
Hegel as part of social theory. Culture, e.g., became rationalized in the
process of the “disenchantment of worldviews” in the West, a process that Weber
thought had “universal significance.” But because of his goal-oriented theory
of action and his noncognitivism in ethics, Weber saw rationalization
exclusively in terms of the spread of purposive, or meansends rationality
Zweckrationalität. Rational action means choosing the most effective means of
achieving one’s goals and implies judging the consequences of one’s actions and
choices. In contrast, value rationality Wertrationalität consists of actions
oriented to ultimate ends, where considerations of consequences are irrelevant.
Although such action is rational insofar as it directs and organizes human
conduct, the choice of such ends or values themselves cannot be a matter for
rational or scientific judgment. Indeed, for Weber this meant that politics was
the sphere for the struggle between irreducibly competing ultimate ends, where
“gods and demons fight it out” and charismatic leaders invent new gods and
values. Professional politicians, however, should act according to an “ethics
of responsibility” Verantwortungsethik aimed at consequences, and not an
“ethics of conviction” Gesinnungsethik aimed at abstract principles or ultimate
ends. Weber also believed that rationalization brought the separation of “value
spheres” that can never again be unified by reason: art, science, and morality
have their own “logics.” Weber’s influential methodological writings reject
positivist philosophy of science, yet call for “value neutrality.” He accepts
the neo-Kantian distinction, common in his day under the influence of Rickert,
between the natural and the human sciences, between the Natur- and the
Geisteswissenschaften. Because human social action is purposive and meaningful,
the explanations of social sciences must be related to the values Wertbezogen
and ideals of the actors it studies. Against positivism, Weber saw an
ineliminable element of Verstehen, or understanding of meanings, in the methodology
of the human sciences. For example, he criticized the legal positivist notion
of behavioral conformity for failing to refer to actors’ beliefs in legitimacy.
But for Weber Verstehen is not intuition or empathy and does not exclude causal
analysis; reasons can be causes. Thus, explanations in social science must have
both causal and subjective adequacy. Weber also thought that adequate
explanations of large-scale, macrosocial phenomena require the construction of
ideal types, which abstract and summarize the common features of complex,
empirical phenomena such as “sects,” “authority,” or even “the Protestant
ethic.” Weberian ideal types are neither merely descriptive nor simply
heuristic, but come at the end of inquiry through the successful theoretical analysis
of diverse phenomena in various historical and cultural contexts. Weber’s
analysis of rationality as the disenchantment of the world and the spread of
purposive reason led him to argue that reason and progress could turn into
their opposites, a notion that enormously influenced critical theory. Weber had
a critical “diagnosis of the times” and a pessimistic philosophy of history. At
the end of The Protestant Ethic Weber warns that rationalism is desiccating
sources of value and constructing an “iron cage” of increasing
bureaucratization, resulting in a loss of meaning and freedom in social life.
According to Weber, these basic tensions of modern rationality cannot be
resolved.
well-formed
formula (Villa Grice: formula). For Grice, an otiosity – surely an ill-formed
formula is an oxymoron -- a grammatically wellformed sentence or structured
predicate of an artificial language of the sort studied by logicians. A
well-formed formula is sometimes known as a wff pronounced ‘woof’ or simply a
formula. Delineating the formulas of a language involves providing it with a
syntax or grammar, composed of both a vocabulary a specification of the symbols
from which the language is to be built, sorted into grammatical categories and
formation rules a purely formal or syntactical specification of which strings
of symbols are grammatically well-formed and which are not. Formulas are
classified as either open or closed, depending on whether or not they contain
free variables variables not bound by quantifiers. Closed formulas, such as x
Fx / Gx, are sentences, the potential bearers of truth-values. Open formulas,
such as Fx / Gx, are handled in any of three ways. On some accounts, these
formulas are on a par with closed ones, the free variables being treated as names.
On others, open formulas are structured predicates, the free variables being
treated as place holders for terms. And on still other accounts, the free
variables are regarded as implicitly bound by universal quantifiers, again
making open formulas sentences.
westermarck: “philosopher who spent his life studying all the
mores and morals of cultures – except his own – because he claimed he didn’t
have one!” – H. P. Grice. His main works, The Origin and Development of Moral
Ideas and Ethical Relativity, attack the idea that moral principles express
objective value. In defending ethical relativism, he argued that moral
judgments are based not on intellectual but on emotional grounds. He admitted
that cultural variability in itself does not prove ethical relativism, but
contended that the fundamental differences are so comprehensive and deep as to
constitute a strong presumption in favor of relativism.
what the eye
no longer sees the heart no longer grieves for. Grice. Vide sytactics. Grice played with ‘elimination
rules’ for his scope device. Once applied, Grice said: “What the eye no longer
sees the heart no longer grieves for.” “As they say,” he added.
whewell: English philosopher of science. He was a master of Trinity
, Cambridge. Francis Bacon’s early work on induction was furthered by Whewell,
J. F. W. Herschel, and J. S. Mill, who attempted to create a logic of welfare
economics Whewell, William 970 970
induction, a methodology that can both discover generalizations about
experience and prove them to be necessary. Whewell’s theory of scientific
method is based on his reading of the history of the inductive sciences. He
thought that induction began with a non-inferential act, the superimposition of
an idea on data, a “colligation,” a way of seeing facts in a “new light.”
Colligations generalize over data, and must satisfy three “tests of truth.”
First, colligations must be empirically adequate; they must account for the
given data. Any number of ideas may be adequate to explain given data, so a
more severe test is required. Second, because colligations introduce
generalizations, they must apply to events or properties of objects not yet
given: they must provide successful predictions, thereby enlarging the evidence
in favor of the colligation. Third, the best inductions are those where
evidence for various hypotheses originally thought to cover unrelated kinds of
data “jumps together,” providing a consilience of inductions. Consilience
characterizes those theories achieving large measures of simplicity,
generality, unification, and deductive strength. Furthermore, consilience is a
test of the necessary truth of theories, which implies that what many regard as
merely pragmatic virtues of theories like simplicity and unifying force have an
epistemic status. Whewell thus provides a strong argument for scientific
realism. Whewell’s examples of consilient theories are Newton’s theory of
universal gravitation, which covers phenomena as seemingly diverse as the
motions of the heavenly bodies and the motions of the tides, and the undulatory
theory of light, which explains both the polarization of light by crystals and
the colors of fringes. There is evidence that Whewell’s methodology was
employed by Maxwell, who designed the influential Cavendish Laboratories at
Cambridge. Peirce and Mach favored Whewell’s account of method over Mill’s
empiricist theory of induction. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “From induction to
deduction, via abduction.”
what the eye
no longer sees the heart no longer grieves for. Grice. Vide sytactics. Grice played with ‘elimination
rules’ for his scope device. Once applied, Grice said: “What the eye no longer
sees the heart no longer grieves for.” “As they say,” he added.
whistle. If you can’t say it you can’t whistle it either – But
you can implicate it. “To say” takes a ‘that’-clause. “To implicate” takes a
‘that’-clause. Grice: “ ‘To whisle’ takes a ‘that’-clause, “By whistling, E
communicates that he intends his emissee to be there.” “Whistle and I’ll be
there” – Houseman to a Shropshire farmer.
whitehead: cited by H. P. Grice, a. n., philosopher of science,
educated first at the Sherborne School in Dorsetshire and then at Trinity ,
Cambridge, Whitehead emerged as a first-class mathematician with a rich general
background. In 5 he became a fellow of Trinity
and remained there in a teaching role until 0. In the early 0s Bertrand
Russell entered Trinity as a student in
mathematics; by the beginning of the new century Russell had become not only a
student and friend but a colleague of Whitehead’s at Trinity . Each had written
a first book on algebra Whitehead’s A Treatise on Universal Algebra won him
election to the Royal Society in 3. When they discovered that their projected
second books largely overlapped, they undertook a collaboration on a volume
that they estimated would take about a year to write; in fact, it was a decade
later that the three volumes of their ground-breaking Principia Mathematica
appeared, launching symbolic logic in its modern form. In the second decade of
this century Whitehead and Russell drifted apart; their responses to World War
I differed radically, and their intellectual interests and orientations
diverged. Whitehead’s London period 024 is often viewed as the second phase of
a three-phase career. His association with the
of London involved him in practical issues affecting the character of
working-class education. For a decade Whitehead held a professorship at the
Imperial of Science and Technology and
also served as dean of the Faculty of Science in the , chair of the Academic Council
which managed educational affairs in London, and chair of the council that
managed Goldsmith’s . His book The Aims of Education 8 is a collection of
essays largely growing out of reflections on the experiences of these years.
Intellectually, Whitehead’s interests were moving toward issues in the
philosophy of science. In the years 922 he published An Enquiry Concerning the
Principles of Natural Knowledge, The Concept of Nature, and The Principle of
Relativity the third led to his later 1
election as a fellow of the British Academy. In 4, at the age of sixty-three,
Whitehead made a dramatic move, both geographically and intellectually, to
launch phase three of his career: never having formally studied philosophy in
his life, he agreed to become professor of philosophy at Harvard , a position
he held until retirement in 7. The accompanying intellectual shift was a move
from philosophy of science to metaphysics. The earlier investigations had
assumed the self-containedness of nature: “nature is closed to mind.” The
philosophy of nature examined nature at the level of abstraction entailed by
this assumption. Whitehead had come to regard philosophy as “the critic of
abstractions,” a notion introduced in Science and the Modern World 5. This book
traced the intertwined emergence of Newtonian science and its philosophical
presuppositions. It noted that with the development of the theory of relativity
in the twentieth century, scientific understanding had left behind the
Newtonian conceptuality that had generated the still-dominant philosophical
assumptions, and that those philosophical assumptions considered in themselves
had become inadequate to explicate our full concrete experience. Philosophy as
the critic of abstractions must recognize the limitations of a stance that
assumes that nature is closed to mind, and must push deeper, beyond such an
abstraction, to create a scheme of ideas more in harmony with scientific
developments and able to do justice to human beings as part of nature. Science
and the Modern World merely outlines what such a philosophy might be; in 9
Whitehead published his magnum opus, titled Process and Reality. In this
volume, subtitled “An Essay in Cosmology,” his metaphysical understanding is
given its final form. It is customary to regard this book as the central
document of what has become known as process philosophy, though Whitehead
himself frequently spoke of his system of ideas as the philosophy of organism.
Process and Reality begins with a sentence that sheds a great deal of light upon
Whitehead’s metaphysical orientation: “These lectures are based upon a
recurrence to that phase of philosophic thought which began with Descartes and
ended with Hume.” Descartes, adapting the classical notion of substance to his
own purposes, begins a “phase of philosophic thought” by assuming there are two
distinct, utterly different kinds of substance, mind and matter, each requiring
nothing but itself in order to exist. This assumption launches the reign of
epistemology within philosophy: if knowing begins with the experiencing of a
mental substance capable of existing by itself and cut off from everything
external to it, then the philosophical challenge is to try to justify the claim
to establish contact with a reality external to it. The phrase “and ended with
Hume” expresses Whitehead’s conviction that Hume and more elegantly, he notes,
Santayana showed that if one begins with Descartes’s metaphysical assumptions,
skepticism is inevitable. Contemporary philosophers have talked about the end
of philosophy. From Whitehead’s perspective such talk presupposes a far too
narrow view of the nature of philosophy. It is true that a phase of philosophy
has ended, a phase dominated by epistemology. Whitehead’s response is to offer
the dictum that all epistemological difficulties are at bottom only camouflaged
metaphysical difficulties. One must return to that moment of Cartesian
beginning and replace the substance metaphysics with an orientation that avoids
the epistemological trap, meshes harmoniously with the scientific
understandings that have displaced the much simpler physics of Descartes’s day,
and is consonant with the facts of evolution. These are the considerations that
generate Whitehead’s fundamental metaphysical category, the category of an
actual occasion. An actual occasion is not an enduring, substantial entity.
Rather, it is a process of becoming, a process of weaving together the
“prehensions” a primitive form of ‘apprehension’ meant to indicate a “taking
account of,” or “feeling,” devoid of conscious awareness of the actual
occasions that are in the immediate past. Whitehead calls this process of
weaving together the inheritances of the past “concrescence.” An actual entity
is its process of concrescence, its process of growing together into a unified
perspective on its immediate past. The seeds of Whitehead’s epistemological
realism are planted in these fundamental first moves: “The philosophy of
organism is the inversion of Kant’s philosophy. . . . For Kant, the world
emerges from the subject; for the philosophy of organism, the subject emerges
from the world.” It is customary to compare an actual occasion with a
Leibnizian monad, with the caveat that whereas a monad is windowless, an actual
occasion is “all window.” It is as though one were to take Aristotle’s system
of categories and ask what would result if the category of substance were
displaced from its position of preeminence by the category of relation the result would, mutatis mutandis, be an
understanding of being somewhat on the model of a Whiteheadian actual occasion.
In moving from Descartes’s dualism of mental substance and material substance
to his own notion of an actual entity, Whitehead has been doing philosophy
conceived of as the critique of abstractions. He holds that both mind and
matter are abstractions from the concretely real. They are important
abstractions, necessary for everyday thought and, of supreme importance,
absolutely essential in enabling the seventeenth through nineteenth centuries
to accomplish their magnificent advances in scientific thinking. Indeed,
Whitehead, in his philosophy of science phase, by proceeding as though “nature
is closed to mind,” was operating with those selfsame abstractions. He came to
see that while these abstractions were indispensable for certain kinds of
investigations, they were, at the philosophical level, as Hume had
demonstrated, a disaster. In considering mind and matter to be ontological
ultimates, Descartes had committed what Whitehead termed the fallacy of
misplaced concreteness. The category of an actual occasion designates the fully
real, the fully concrete. The challenge for such an orientation, the challenge
that Process and Reality is designed to meet, is so to describe actual
occasions that it is intelligible how collections of actual occasions, termed
“nexus” or societies, emerge, exhibiting the characteristics we find associated
with “minds” and “material structures.” Perhaps most significantly, if this
challenge is met successfully, biology will be placed, in the eyes of philosophy,
on an even footing with physics; metaphysics will do justice both to human
beings and to human beings as a part of nature; and such vexing contemporary
problem areas as animal rights and environmental ethics will appear in a new
light. Whitehead’s last two books, Adventures of Ideas 3 and Modes of Thought
8, are less technical and more lyrical than is Process and Reality. Adventures
of Ideas is clearly the more significant of these two. It presents a
philosophical study of the notion of civilization. It holds that the social
changes in a civilization are driven by two sorts of forces: brute, senseless
agencies of compulsion on the one hand, and formulated aspirations and
articulated beliefs on the other. These two sorts of forces are epitomized by
barbarians and Christianity in the ancient Roman world and by steam and
democracy in the world of the industrial revolution. Whitehead’s focal point in
Adventures of Ideas is aspirations, beliefs, and ideals as instruments of
change. In particular, he is concerned to articulate the ideals and aspirations
appropriate to our own era. The character of such ideals and aspirations at any
moment is limited by the philosophical understandings available at that moment,
because in their struggle for release and efficacy such ideals and aspirations
can appear only in the forms permitted by the available philosophical
discourse. In the final section of Adventures of Ideas Whitehead presents a
statement of ideals and aspirations fit for our era as his own philosophy of
organism allows them to take shape and be articulated. The notions of beauty,
truth, adventure, zest, Eros, and peace are given a content drawn from the
technical understandings elaborated in Process and Reality. But in Adventures
of Ideas a less technical language is used, a language reminiscent of the
poetic imagery found in the style of Plato’s Republic, a language making the
ideas accessible to readers who have not mastered Process and Reality, but at
the same time far richer and more meaningful to those who have. Whitehead notes
in Adventures of Ideas that Plato’s later thought “circles round the
interweaving of seven main notions, namely, The Ideas, The Physical Elements,
The Psyche, The Eros, The Harmony, The Mathematical Relations, The Receptacle.
These notions are as important for us now, as they were then at the dawn of the
modern world, when civilizations of the old type were dying.” Whitehead uses
these notions in quite novel and modern ways; one who is unfamiliar with his
metaphysics can get something of what he means as he speaks of the Eros of the
Universe, but if one is familiar from Process and Reality with the notions of
the Primordial Nature of God and the Consequent Nature of God then one sees
much deeper into the meanings present in Adventures of Ideas. Whitehead was not
religious in any narrow, doctrinal, sectarian sense. He explicitly likened his
stance to that of Aristotle, dispassionately considering the requirements of
his metaphysical system as they refer to the question of the existence and
nature of God. Whitehead’s thoughts on these matters are most fully developed
in Chapter 11 of Science and the Modern World, in the final chapter of Process
and Reality, and in Religion in the Making 6. These thoughts are expressed at a
high level of generality. Perhaps because of this, a large part of the interest
generated by Whitehead’s thought has been within the community of theologians.
His ideas fairly beg for elaboration and development in the context of
particular modes of religious understanding. It is as though many modern
theologians, recalling the relation between the theology of Aquinas and the
metaphysics of Aristotle, cannot resist the temptation to play Aquinas to
Whitehead’s Aristotle. Process theology, or Neo-Classical Theology as it is
referred to by Hartshorne, one of its leading practitioners, has been the arena
within which a great deal of clarification and development of Whitehead’s ideas
has occurred. Whitehead was a gentle man, soft-spoken, never overbearing or
threatening. He constantly encouraged students to step out on their own, to
develop their creative capacities. His concern not to inhibit students made him
a notoriously easy grader; it was said that an A-minus in one of his courses
was equivalent to failure. Lucien Price’s Dialogues of Alfred North Whitehead
chronicles many evenings of discussion in the Whitehead household. He there
described Whitehead as follows: his face, serene, luminous, often smiling, the
complexion pink and white, the eyes brilliant blue, clear and candid as a
child’s yet with the depth of the sage, often laughing or twinkling with
humour. And there was his figure, slender, frail, and bent with its lifetime of
a scholar’s toil. Always benign, there was not a grain of ill will anywhere in
him; for all his formidable armament, never a wounding word. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Definite descriptions in
Whitehead and Russell and in the vernacular,” “Definite descriptions in
Whitethead’s and Russell’s formalese and in Strawson’s vernacular” -- BANC.
weiner kraus -- Vienna Circle
vide ayerism -- a group of philosophers and scientists who met
periodically for discussions in Vienna from 2 to 8 and who proposed a
self-consciously revolutionary conception of scientific knowledge. The Circle
was initiated by the mathematician Hans Hahn to continue a prewar forum with
the physicist Philip Frank and the social scientist Otto Neurath after the
arrival in Vienna of Moritz Schlick, a philosopher who had studied with Max
Planck. Carnap joined in 6 from 1 in Prague; other members included Herbert
Feigl from 0 in Iowa, Friedrich Waismann, Bergmann, Viktor Kraft, and Bela von
Juhos. Viennese associates of the Circle included Kurt Gödel, Karl Menger,
Felix Kaufmann, and Edgar Zilsel. Popper was not a member or associate. During
its formative period the Circle’s activities were confined to discussion
meetings many on Vitters’s Tractatus. In 9 the Circle entered its public period
with the formation of the Verein Ernst Mach, the publication of its manifesto
Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung: Der Wiener Kreis by Carnap, Hahn, and Neurath
tr. in Neurath, Empiricism and Sociology, 3, and the first of a series of
philosophical monographs edited by Frank and Schlick. It also began
collaboration with the independent but broadly like-minded Berlin “Society of
Empirical Philosophy,” including Reichenbach, Kurt Grelling, Kurt Lewin,
Friedrich Kraus, Walter Dubislav, Hempel, and Richard von Mises: the groups
together organized their first public conferences in Prague and Königsberg,
acquired editorship of a philosophical journal renamed Erkenntnis, and later
organized the international Unity of Science congresses. The death and
dispersion of key members from 4 onward Hahn died in 4, Neurath left for
Holland in 4, Carnap left for the United States in 5, Schlick died in 6 did not
mean the extinction of Vienna Circle philosophy. Through the subsequent work of
earlier visitors Ayer, Ernest Nagel, Quine and members and collaborators who
emigrated to the United States Carnap, Feigl, Frank, Hempel, and Reichenbach,
the logical positivism of the Circle Reichenbach and Neurath independently
preferred “logical empiricism” strongly influenced the development of analytic
philosophy. The Circle’s discussions concerned the philosophy of formal and
physical science, and even though their individual publications ranged much
wider, it is the attitude toward science that defines the Circle within the
philosophical movements of central Europe at the time. The Circle rejected the
need for a specifically philosophical epistemology that bestowed justification
on knowledge claims from beyond science itself. In this, the Circle may also
have drawn on a distinct Austrian tradition a thesis of its historian Neurath:
in most of G.y, science and philosophy had parted ways during the nineteenth
century. Starting with Helmholtz, of course, there also arose a movement that
sought to distinguish the scientific respectability of the Kantian tradition
from the speculations of G. idealism, yet after 0 neo-Kantians insisted on the
autonomy of epistemology, disparaging earlier fellow travelers as “positivist.”
Yet the program of reducing the knowledge claim of science and providing
legitimations to what’s left found wide favor with the more empirical-minded
like Mach. Comprehensive description, not explanation, of natural phenomena
became the task for theorists who no longer looked to philosophy for
foundations, but found them in the utility of their preferred empirical
procedures. Along with the positivists, the Vienna Circle thought uneconomical
the Kantian answer to the question of the possibility of objectivity, the
synthetic a priori. Moreover, the Vienna Circle and its conventionalist
precursors Poincaré and Duhem saw them contradicted by the results of formal
science. Riemann’s geometries showed that questions about the geometry of
physical space were open to more than one answer: Was physical space Euclidean
or non-Euclidean? It fell to Einstein and the pre-Circle Schlick Space and Time
in Contemporary Physics, 7 to argue that relativity theory showed the
untenability of Kant’s conception of space and time as forever fixed synthetic
a priori forms of intuition. Yet Frege’s anti-psychologistic critique had also
shown empiricism unable to account for knowledge of arithmetic and the conventionalists
had ended the positivist dream of a theory of experiential elements that
bridged the gap between descriptions of fact and general principles of science.
How, then, could the Vienna Circle defend the claim under attack as just one worldview among
others that science provides knowledge?
The Circle confronted the problem of constitutive conventions. As befitted
their self-image beyond Kant and Mach, they found their paradigmatic answer in
the theory of relativity: they thought that irreducible conventions of
measurement with wide-ranging implications were sharply separable from pure
facts like point coincidences. Empirical theories were viewed as logical
structures of statements freely created, yet accountable to experiential input
via their predictive consequences identifiable by observation. The Vienna
Circle defended empiricism by the reconceptualization of the relation between a
priori and a posteriori inquiries. First, in a manner sympathetic to Frege’s
and Russell’s doctrine of logicism and guided by Vitters’s notion of tautology,
arithmetic was considered a part of logic and treated as entirely analytical,
without any empirical content; its truth was held to be exhausted by what is
provable from the premises and rules of a formal symbolic system. Carnap’s
Logical Syntax of Language, 4, assimilated Gödel’s incompleteness result by
claiming that not every such proof could be demonstrated in those systems
themselves which are powerful enough to represent classical arithmetic. The
synthetic a priori was not needed for formal science because all of its results
were non-synthetic. Second, the Circle adopted verificationism: supposedly
empirical concepts whose applicability was indiscernible were excluded from
science. The terms for unobservables were to be reconstructed by logical
operations from the observational terms. Only if such reconstructions were
provided did the more theoretical parts of science retain their empirical
character. Just what kind of reduction was aimed for was not always clear and
earlier radical positions were gradually weakened; Reichenbach instead
considered the relation between observational and theoretical statements to be
probabilistic. Empirical science needed no synthetic a priori either; all of
its statements were a posteriori. Combined with the view that the analysis of
the logical form of expressions allowed for the exact determination of their
combinatorial value, verificationism was to exhibit the knowledge claims of
science and eliminate metaphysics. Whatever meaning did not survive
identification with the scientific was deemed irrelevant to knowledge claims
Reichenbach did not share this view either. Since the Circle also observed the
then long-discussed ban on issuing unconditional value statements in science, its
metaethical positions may be broadly characterized as endorsing noncognitivism.
Its members were not simply emotivists, however, holding that value judgments
were mere expressions of feeling, but sought to distinguish the factual and
evaluative contents of value judgments. Those who, like Schlick Questions of
Ethics, 0, engaged in metaethics, distinguished the expressive component x
desires y of value judgments from their implied descriptive component doing
zfurthers aim y and held that the demand inherent in moral principles possessed
validity if the implied description was true and the expressed desire was
endorsed. This analysis of normative concepts did not render them meaningless
but allowed for psychological and sociological studies of ethical systems;
Menger’s formal variant Morality, Decision and Social Organization, 4 proved
influential for decision theory. The semiotic view that knowledge required
structured representations was developed in close contact with foundational
research in mathematics and depended on the “new” logic of Frege, Russell, and
Vitters, out of which quantification theory was emerging. Major new results
were quickly integrated albeit controversially and Carnap’s works reflect the
development of the conception of logic itself. In his Logical Syntax he adopted
the “Principle of Tolerance” vis-à-vis the question of the foundation of the
formal sciences: the choice of logics and languages was conventional and
constrained, apart from the demand for consistency, only by pragmatic considerations.
The proposed language form and its difference from alternatives simply had to
be stated as exactly as possible: whether a logico-linguistic framework as a
whole correctly represented reality was a cognitively meaningless question. Yet
what was the status of the verifiability principle? Carnap’s suggestion that it
represents not a discovery but a proposal for future scientific language use
deserves to be taken seriously, for it not only characterizes his own
conventionalism, but also amplifies the Circle’s linguistic turn, according to
which all philosophy concerned ways of representing, rather than the nature of
the represented. What the Vienna Circle “discovered” was how much of science
was conventional: its verificationism was a proposal for accommodating the
creativity of scientific theorizing without accommodating idealism. Whether an
empirical claim in order to be meaningful needed to be actually verified or
only potentially verifiable, or fallible or only potentially testable, and
whether so by current or only by future means, became matters of discussion
during the 0s. Equally important for the question whether the Circle’s
conventionalism avoided idealism and metaphysics were the issues of the status
of theoretical discourse about unobservables and the nature of science’s
empirical foundation. The view suggested in Schlick’s early General Theory of
Knowledge 8, 2d. ed. 5 and Frank’s The Causal Law and its Limitations 2 and
elaborated in Carnap’s “Logical Foundations of the Unity of Science” in
Foundations of the Unity of Science I.1, 8 characterized the theoretical
language as an uninterpreted calculus that is related to the fully interpreted
observational language only by partial definitions. Did such an instrumentalism
require for its empirical anchor the sharp separation of observational from
theoretical terms? Could such a separation even be maintained? Consider the
unity of science thesis. According to the methodological version, endorsed by
all members, all of science abides by the same criteria: no basic
methodological differences separate the natural from the social or cultural
sciences Geisteswissenschaften as claimed by those who distinguish between
‘explanation’ and ‘understanding’. According to the metalinguistic version, all
objects of scientific knowledge could in principle be comprehended by the same
“universal” language. Physicalism asserts that this is the language that speaks
of physical objects. While everybody in the Circle endorsed physicalism in this
sense, the understanding of its importance varied, as became clear in the
socalled protocol sentence debate. The nomological version of the unity thesis
was only later clearly distinguished: whether all scientific laws could be
reduced to those of physics was another matter on which Neurath came to differ.
Ostensively, this debate concerned the question of the form, content, and
epistemological status of scientific evidence statements. Schlick’s unrevisable
“affirmations” talked about phenomenal states in statements not themselves part
of the language of science “The Foundation of Knowledge,” 4, tr. in Ayer, ed.,
Logical Positivism. Carnap’s preference changed from unrevisable statements in
a primitive methodologically solipsistic protocol language that were fallibly
translatable into the physicalistic system language 1; see Unity of Science, 4,
via arbitrary revisable statements of that system language that are taken as
temporary resting points in testing 2, to revisable statements in the
scientific observation language 5; see “Testability and Meaning,” Philosophy of
Science, 637. These changes were partly prompted by Neurath, whose own
revisable “protocol statements” spoke, amongst other matters, of the relation
between observers and the observed in a “universal slang” that mixed
expressions of the physicalistically cleansed colloquial and the high
scientific languages “Protocol Statements,”
tr. in Ayer, ed., Logical Positivism. Ultimately, these proposals
answered to different projects. Since all agreed that all statements of science
were hypothetical, the questions of their “foundation” concerned rather the
very nature of Vienna Circle philosophy. For Schlick philosophy became the
activity of meaning determination inspired by Vitters; Carnap pursued it as the
rational reconstruction of knowledge claims concerned only with what
Reichenbach called the “context of justification” its logical aspects, not the
“context of discovery”; and Neurath replaced philosophy altogether with a
naturalistic, interdisciplinary, empirical inquiry into science as a
distinctive discursive practice, precluding the orthodox conception of the
unity of science. The Vienna Circle was neither a monolithic nor a necessarily
reductionist philosophical movement, and quick assimilation to the tradition of
British empiricism mistakes its struggles with the formcontent dichotomy for
foundationalism, when instead sophisticated responses to the question of the
presuppositions of their own theories of knowledge were being developed. In its
time and place, the Circle was a minority voice; the sociopolitical dimension
of its theories stressed more by some
Neurath than others Schlick as a renewal
of Enlightenment thought, ultimately against the rising tide of Blutund-Boden
metaphysics, is gaining recognition. After the celebrated “death” of
reductionist logical positivism in the 0s the historical Vienna Circle is
reemerging as a multifaceted object of the history of analytical philosophy
itself, revealing in nuce different strands of reasoning still significant for
postpositivist theory of science. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “What Freddie brought us
from Vienna.”
williams: “There are many Williams in Oxford, but only one “B.
A. O., “ as he pretentiously went by!” – H. P. Grice. B. A. O. London-born
Welsh philosopher who has made major contributions to many fields but is
primarily known as a moral philosopher. His approach to ethics, set out in
Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy 5, is characterized by a wide-ranging
skepticism, directed mainly at the capacity of academic moral philosophy to
further the aim of reflectively living an ethical life. One line of skeptical
argument attacks the very idea of practical reason. Attributions of practical
reasons to a particular agent must, in Williams’s view, be attributions of
states that can potentially explain the agent’s action. Therefore such reasons
must be either within the agent’s existing set of motivations or within the
revised set of motivations that the agent would acquire upon sound reasoning.
Williams argues from these minimal assumptions that this view of reasons as
internal reasons undermines the idea of reason itself being a source of
authority over practice. Williams’s connected skepticism about the claims of
moral realism is based both on his general stance toward realism and on his
view of the nature of modern societies. In opposition to internal realism,
Williams has consistently argued that reflection on our conception of the world
allows one to develop a conception of the world maximally independent of our
peculiar ways of conceptualizing reality
an absolute conception of the world. Such absoluteness is, he argues, an
inappropriate aspiration for ethical thought. Our ethical thinking is better
viewed as one way of structuring a form of ethical life than as the ethical
truth about how life is best lived. The pervasive reflectiveness and radical
pluralism of modern societies makes them inhospitable contexts for viewing
ethical concepts as making knowledge available to groups of concept users.
Modernity has produced at the level of theory a distortion of our ethical
practice, namely a conception of the morality system. This view is
reductionist, is focused centrally on obligations, and rests on various
fictions about responsibility and blame that Williams challenges in such works
as Shame and Necessity 3. Much academic moral philosophy, in his view, is
shaped by the covert influence of the morality system, and such distinctively
modern outlooks as Kantianism and utilitarianism monopolize the terms of
contemporary debate with insufficient attention to their origin in a distorted
view of the ethical. Williams’s views are not skeptical through and through; he
retains a commitment to the values of truth, truthfulness in a life, and
individualism. His most recent work, which thematizes the long-implicit
influence of Nietzsche on his ethical philosophy, explicitly offers a
vindicatory “genealogical” narrative for these ideals.
willkür, v.
Hobson’s choice. Grice: “‘will-kuer’ is a fascinating German expression,
literally will-care’.”
wilson – this
is the way to quote J. C. Wilson. Grice loved him, and thanked Farquarhson for
editing his papers.
wilson’s
ultimate counterexample to Grice --
Grice’s counterexample – “the ultimate counter-example” -- counterinstance,
also called counterexample. 1 A particular instance of an argument form that
has all true premises but a false conclusion, thereby showing that the form is
not universally valid. The argument form ‘p 7 q, - p / , ~q’, for example, is
shown to be invalid by the counterinstance ‘Grass is either red or green; Grass
is not red; Therefore, grass is not green’. 2 A particular false instance of a
statement form, which demonstrates that the form is not a logical truth. A
counterinstance to the form ‘p 7 q / p’, for example, would be the statement
‘If grass is either red or green, then grass is red’. 3 A particular example
that demonstrates that a universal generalization is false. The universal
statement ‘All large cities in the United States are east of the Mississippi’
is shown to be false by the counterinstance of San Francisco, which is a large
city in the United States that is not east of the Mississippi. V.K. counterpart
theory, a theory that analyzes statements about what is possible and impossible
for individuals statements of de re modality in terms of what holds of
counterparts of those individuals in other possible worlds, a thing’s
counterparts being individuals that resemble it without being identical with
it. The name ‘counterpart theory’ was coined by David Lewis, the theory’s
principal exponent. Whereas some theories analyze ‘Mrs. Simpson might have been
queen of England’ as ‘In some possible world, Mrs. Simpson is queen of England’,
counterpart theory analyzes it as ‘In some possible world, a counterpart of
Mrs. Simpson is queen of a counterpart of England’. The chief motivation for
counterpart theory is a combination of two views: a de re modality should be
given a possible worlds analysis, and b each actual individual exists only in
the actual world, and hence cannot exist with different properties in other
possible worlds. Counterpart theory provides an analysis that allows ‘Mrs.
Simpson might have been queen’ to be true compatibly with a and b. For Mrs.
Simpson’s counterparts in other possible worlds, in those worlds where she
herself does not exist, may have regal properties that the actual Mrs. Simpson
lacks. Counterpart theory is perhaps prefigured in Leibniz’s theory of
possibility.
wilson: not to be confused with wilson, author of “Grice: The
ultimate counterexample” -- Oxonian philosopher, like Grice. Cook Wilson
studied with T. H. Green before becoming Wykeham Professor of Logic at Oxford
and leading the Oxford reaction against the then entrenched absolute idealism.
More influential as a tutor than as a writer, his major oeuvre, Statement and
Inference, was posthumously reconstructed from drafts of papers, philosophical
correspondence, and an extensive set of often inconsistent lectures for his
logic courses. A staunch critic of Whitehead’s mathematical logic, Wilson
conceived of logic as the study of thinking, an activity unified by the fact
that thinking either is knowledge or depends on knowledge “What we know we
kow”. Wilson claims that knowledge involves apprehending an object that in most
cases is independent of the act of apprehension and that knowledge is
indefinable without circularity, views he defended by appealing to common
usage. Many of Wilson’s ideas are disseminated by H. W. B. Joseph, especially
in his “Logic.” Rejecting “symbolic logic,” Joseph attempts to reinvigorate
traditional logic conceived along Wilsonian lines. To do so Joseph combined a
careful exposition of Aristotle with insights drawn from idealistic logicians.
Besides Joseph, Wilson decisively influenced a generation of Oxford
philosophers including Prichard and Ross, and Grice who explores the
‘interrogative subordination’ in the account of ‘if.’ “Who killed Cock Robin”.
winchism: After P. Winch, P. London-born philosopher. He
quotes Grice in a Royal Philosophy talk:
“Grice’s point is that we should distinguish the truth of one’s remark form the
point of one’s remarks – Grice’s example is: “Surely I have neither any doubt
nor any desire to deny that the pillar box in front of me is red, and yet I
won’t hesitate to say that it seems red to me” – Surely pointless, but an
incredible truth meant to refute G. A. Paul!” Winch translated Vitters’s
“little essay on value” which Grice “did not use for [his] essay on the
conception of value.” (“Kultur und Wert.”). Grice: “Not contented with natural
science, Winch wants a social one!”
windelband: philosopher and originator of Baden neoKantianism. He
studied under Kuno Fischer 18247 and Lotze, and was professor at Zürich,
Freiburg, Strasbourg, and Heidelberg. Windelband gave Baden neo-Kantianism its
distinctive mark of Kantian axiology as the core of critical philosophy. He is
widely recognized for innovative work in the history of philosophy, in which
problems rather than individual philosophers are the focus and organizing
principle of exposition. He is also known for his distinction, first drawn in
“Geschichte und Naturwissenschaft” “History and Natural Science,” 4, between
the nomothetic knowledge that most natural sciences seek the discovery of
general laws in order to master nature and the idiographic knowledge that the
historical sciences pursue description of individual and unique aspects of
reality with the aim of self-affirmation. His most important student, and
successor at Heidelberg, was Heinrich Rickert 1863 6, who made lasting
contributions to the methodology of the historical sciences.
wodeham: “If Adam of Wodeham was called Wodeham, I should, by
the same token, be called “Harborne”” – H. P. Grice. Oxonian philosopher, like
Grice. Adam de English Franciscan philosopher-theologian who lectured on Peter
Lombard’s Sentences at London, Norwich, and Oxford. His published works include
the Tractatus de indivisibilibus; his Lectura secunda Norwich lectures; and an
abbreviation of his Oxford lectures by Henry Totting of Oyta, published by John
Major in 1512. Wodeham’s main work, the Oxford lectures, themselves remain
unpublished. A brilliant interpreter of Duns Scotus, whose original manuscripts
he consulted, Wodeham deemed Duns Scotus the greatest Franciscan doctor.
William Ockham, Wodeham’s teacher, was the other great influence on Wodeham’s
philosophical theology. Wodeham defended Ockham’s views against attacks mounted
by Walter Chatton; he also wrote the prologue to Ockham’s Summa logicae.
Wodeham’s own influence rivaled that of Ockham. Among the authors he strongly
influenced are Gregory of Rimini, John of Mirecourt, Nicholas of Autrecourt,
Pierre d’Ailly, Peter Ceffons, Alfonso Vargas, Peter of Candia Alexander V,
Henry Totting of Oyta, and John Major. Wodeham’s theological works were written
for an audience with a very sophisticated understanding of current issues in
semantics, logic, and medieval mathematical physics. Contrary to Duns Scotus
and Ockham, Wodeham argued that the sensitive and intellective souls were not
distinct. He further develops the theory of intuitive cognition, distinguishing
intellectual intuition of our own acts of intellect, will, and memory from
sensory intuition of external objects. Scientific knowledge based on experience
can be based on intuition, according to Wodeham. He distinguishes different
grades of evidence, and allows that sensory perceptions may be mistaken.
Nonetheless, they can form the basis for scientific knowledge, since they are
reliable; mistakes can be corrected by reason and experience. In semantic
theory, Wodeham defends the view that the immediate object of scientific
knowledge is the complexe significabile, that which the conclusion is designed
to signify. Oxonian philosopher, like Grice. Adam de (c. 1295–1358), English
Franciscan philosopher- who lectured on Peter Lombard’s Sentences at Oxford.
His oeuvre includes a “Tractatus de indivisibilibus, divisum in cinque
partibus”; his “Lectura secunda” and
“Lecturae Oxonienses” as transcribed by Henry Totting of Oyta, and published by
John Major. Wodeham’s main work, like Grice’s, the Oxford lectures, themselves
remain only partially published. A brilliant interpreter of Duns Scotus, whose
original manuscripts he consulted in his main unpublication, Wodeham deems Duns
Scotus the greatest Franciscan doctor. Occam, Wodeham’s teacher, is the other
great influence on Wodeham (“I treasure the razor he gave me for my birthday.”)
Wodeham defends his tutor Ockham’s views against attacks mounted by Walter
Chatton. Grice was familiar with Wodeham (“from Wodeham, as it happens”)
because he wrote the prologue to Ockham’s Summa logicae. Wodeham’s own
influence rivals that of Ockham. Among the authors he strongly influenced are
Gregory of Rimini, John of Mirecourt, Nicholas of Autrecourt, Pierre d’Ailly,
Peter Ceffons, Alfonso Vargas, Peter of Candia (Alexander V), Henry Totting of
Oyta, John Major, and lastly, but certainly not leastly, H. P. Grice. Wodeham’s
lectures were composed for tutees with a very sophisticated understanding of
current issues in semantics, logic, and mathematical physics. Contrary to Duns
Scotus and Occam, Wodeham argues – and this is borrowed by Grice -- that the
sensitive and intellective souls are not distinct (vide Grice, “The power
structure of the soul”). Wodeham further develops the theory of intuitive
cognition, distinguishing intellectual intuition of our own acts of intellect,
will, and memory from sensory intuition of external objects. This is developed
by Grice in his contrast of “I am not hearing a noise,” and “That is not blue.”
Thus, knowledge based on experience can be based on intuition, according to
Wodeham. Wodeham goes on to distinguishs different grades (or degrees, as Grice
prefers, which Grice symbolises as ‘d’) of evidence (for credibility and
desirability) and allows that this or that sensory perception may be mistaken
(“but if all were, we are in trouble’). Nonetheless, they can form the basis
for knowledge, since they are, caeteris paribus, reliable. “A mistake can
always be corrected by reason and experience. In semantic and pragmatic
theories, Wodeham defends the view that the immediate object of knowledge is
what he calls the “complexum significabile,” that which the conclusion is
designed to signify.
wolff: cited by H. P. Grice, c. philosopher and the most
powerful advocate for secular rationalism in early eighteenth-century G.y.
Although he was a Lutheran, his early education in Catholic Breslau made him
familiar with both the Scholasticism of Aquinas and Suárez and more modern
sources. His later studies at Leipzig were completed with a dissertation on the
application of mathematical methods to ethics 1703, which brought him to the
attention of Leibniz. He remained in correspondence with Leibniz until the
latter’s death 1716, and became known as the popularizer of Leibniz’s
philosophy, although his views did not derive from that source alone. Appointed
to teach mathematics in Halle in 1706 he published mathematical textbooks and
compendia that dominated G. universities for decades, Wolff began lecturing on
philosophy as well by 1709. His rectoral address On the Practical Philosophy of
the Chin. argued that revelation and even belief in God were unnecessary for
arriving at sound principles of moral and political reasoning; this brought his
uneasy relations with the Halle Pietists to a head, and in 1723 they secured
his dismissal and indeed banishment. Wolff was immediately welcomed in Marburg,
where he became a hero for freedom of thought, and did not return to Prussia
until the ascension of Frederick the Great in 1740, when he resumed his post at
Halle. Wolff published an immense series of texts on logic, metaphysics,
ethics, politics, natural theology, and teleology, in which he created the
philosophical terminology of modern G.; he then published an even more
extensive series of works in Latin for the rest of his life, expanding and
modifying his G. works but also adding works on natural and positive law and
economics. He accepted the traditional division of logic into the doctrines of
concepts, judgment, and inference, which influenced the organization of Kant’s
Critique of Pure Reason and even Hegel’s Science of Logic1816. In metaphysics,
he included general ontology and then the special disciplines of rational
cosmology, rational psychology, and rational theology Kant replaced Wolff’s
general ontology with his transcendental aesthetic and analytic, and then
demolished Wolff’s special metaphysics in his transcendental dialectic. Wolff’s
metaphysics drew heavily on Leibniz, but also on Descartes and even empiricists
like Locke. Methodologically, he attempted to derive the principle of
sufficient reason from the logical law of identity like the unpublished Leibniz
of the 1680s rather than the published Leibniz of the 1700s; substantively, he
began his G. metaphysics with a reconstruction of Descartes’s cogito argument,
then argued for a simple, immaterial soul, all of its faculties reducible to
forms of representation and related to body by preestablished harmony. Although
rejected by Crusius and then Kant, Wolff’s attempt to found philosophy on a
single principle continued to influence G. idealism as late as Reinhold,
Fichte, and Hegel, and his example of beginning metaphysics from the unique
representative power of the soul continued to influence not only later writers
such as Reinhold and Fichte but also Kant’s own conception of the
transcendental unity of apperception. In spite of the academic influence of his
metaphysics, Wolff’s importance for G. culture lay in his rationalist rather
than theological ethics. He argued that moral worth lies in the perfection of
the objective essence of mankind; as the essence of a human is to be an
intellect and a will with the latter dependent on the former, which are
physically embodied and dependent for their well-being on the well-being of
their physical body, morality requires perfection of the intellect and will,
physical body, and external conditions for the well-being of that combination.
Each person is obliged to perfect all instantiations of this essence, but in
practice does so most effectively in his own case; duties to oneself therefore
precede duties to others and to God. Because pleasure is the sensible sign of
perfection, Wolff’s perfectionism resembles contemporary utilitarianism. Since
he held that human perfection can be understood by human reason independently
of any revelation, Wolff joined contemporary British enlighteners such as
Shaftesbury and Hutcheson in arguing that morality does not depend on divine
commands, indeed the recognition of divine commands depends on an antecedent
comprehension of morality although morality does require respect for God, and
thus the atheistic morality of the Chin., even though sound as far as it went,
was not complete. This was the doctrine that put Wolff’s life in danger, but it
had tremendous repercussions for the remainder of his century, and certainly in
Kant. H. P. Grice, “Psychologia ratioalis.”“Who’s afraid of the rationalist wolff,”
Grice would chant. Grice borrowed (“but I was never able to return”) from Wolff
the idea of ‘psychologia rationalis,’ that Grice uses profusely. philosopher
and the most powerful advocate for secular rationalism in early
eighteenth-century Germany. Although he was a Lutheran, his early education in
Catholic Breslau made him familiar with both the Scholasticism of Aquinas and
Suárez and more modern sources. His later studies at Leipzig were completed
with a dissertation on the application of mathematical methods to ethics
(1703), which brought him to the attention of Leibniz. He remained in
correspondence with Leibniz until the latter’s death (1716), and became known
as the popularizer of Leibniz’s philosophy, although his views did not derive
from that source alone. Appointed to teach mathematics in Halle in 1706 (he
published mathematical textbooks and compendia that dominated German
universities for decades), Wolff began lecturing on philosophy as well by 1709.
His rectoral address On the Practical Philosophy of the Chinese (1721) argued
that revelation and even belief in God were unnecessary for arriving at sound
principles of moral and political reasoning; this brought his uneasy relations
with the Halle Pietists to a head, and in 1723 they secured his dismissal and
indeed banishment. Wolff was immediately welcomed in Marburg, where he became a
hero for freedom of thought, and did not return to Prussia until the ascension
of Frederick the Great in 1740, when he resumed his post at Halle. Wolff published
an immense series of texts on logic, metaphysics, ethics, politics, natural
theology, and teleology (1713–24), in which he created the philosophical
terminology of modern German; he then published an even more extensive series
of works in Latin for the rest of his life, expanding and modifying his German
works but also adding works on natural and positive law and economics
(1723–55). He accepted the traWodeham, Adam de Wolff, Christian 980 980 ditional division of logic into the
doctrines of concepts, judgment, and inference, which influenced the
organization of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason (1781–87) and even Hegel’s
Science of Logic(1816). In metaphysics, he included general ontology and then
the special disciplines of rational cosmology, rational psychology, and
rational theology (Kant replaced Wolff’s general ontology with his
transcendental aesthetic and analytic, and then demolished Wolff’s special
metaphysics in his transcendental dialectic). Wolff’s metaphysics drew heavily
on Leibniz, but also on Descartes and even empiricists like Locke.
Methodologically, he attempted to derive the principle of sufficient reason
from the logical law of identity (like the unpublished Leibniz of the 1680s
rather than the published Leibniz of the 1700s); substantively, he began his
German metaphysics with a reconstruction of Descartes’s cogito argument, then
argued for a simple, immaterial soul, all of its faculties reducible to forms
of representation and related to body by preestablished harmony. Although rejected
by Crusius and then Kant, Wolff’s attempt to found philosophy on a single
principle continued to influence German idealism as late as Reinhold, Fichte,
and Hegel, and his example of beginning metaphysics from the unique
representative power of the soul continued to influence not only later writers
such as Reinhold and Fichte but also Kant’s own conception of the
transcendental unity of apperception. In spite of the academic influence of his
metaphysics, Wolff’s importance for German culture lay in his rationalist
rather than theological ethics. He argued that moral worth lies in the
perfection of the objective essence of mankind; as the essence of a human is to
be an intellect and a will (with the latter dependent on the former), which are
physically embodied and dependent for their well-being on the well-being of
their physical body, morality requires perfection of the intellect and will,
physical body, and external conditions for the well-being of that combination.
Each person is obliged to perfect all instantiations of this essence, but in
practice does so most effectively in his own case; duties to oneself therefore
precede duties to others and to God. Because pleasure is the sensible sign of
perfection, Wolff’s perfectionism resembles contemporary utilitarianism. Since
he held that human perfection can be understood by human reason independently
of any revelation, Wolff joined contemporary British enlighteners such as
Shaftesbury and Hutcheson in arguing that morality does not depend on divine
commands, indeed the recognition of divine commands depends on an antecedent
comprehension of morality (although morality does require respect for God, and
thus the atheistic morality of the Chinese, even though sound as far as it
went, was not complete). This was the doctrine that put Wolff’s life in danger,
but it had tremendous repercussions for the remainder of his century, and
certainly in Kant.
wollaston: when Grice is in a humorous mood, or mode, as he
prefers, he cites Wollaston at large! Wollaston is notorious for arguing that
the immorality of this or that action lies in an utterer who describes it
implicating a false proposition. Wollaston maintains that there is harmony
between reason (or truth) and happiness. Therefore, any ction that contradict truth
through misrepresentation thereby frustrates human happiness and is thus “plain
evil.” Wollaston gives the example of Willard [Quine] who, to pay Paul [Grice],
robs Peter [Strawspm] stealing his watch.
Grice comments: “In falsely epresenting Strawson’s watch as his own,
Willard makes the act wrong, even if he did it to pay me what he owed me.”
Wollaston’s views, particularly his taking morality to consist in universal and
necessary truths, were influenced by the rationalists Ralph Cudworth and Clarke.
Among his many critics the most famous is, as Grice would expect, Hume, who
contends that Wollaston’s theory implies an absurdity (“unless you disimplicate
it in the bud.”). For Hume, any action concealed from public view (e.g.,
adultery) conveys (or ‘explicates’) no false proposition and therefore is not
immoral, since one can annul it, to use Grice’s jargon. Refs.: H. P. Grice,
“Wollaston and the longitudinal unity of philosophy.” cited by H. P. Grice.
English moralist notorious for arguing that the immorality of actions lies in
their implying false propositions. An assistant headmaster who later took
priestly orders, Wollaston maintains in his one published work, The Religion of
Nature Delineated 1722, that the foundations of religion and morality are mutually
dependent. God has preestablished a harmony between reason or truth and
happiness, so that actions that contradict truth through misrepresentation
thereby frustrate human happiness and are thus evil. For instance, if a person
steals another’s watch, her falsely representing the watch as her own makes the
act wrong. Wollaston’s views, particularly his taking morality to consist in
universal and necessary truths, were influenced by the rationalists Ralph
Cudworth and Clarke. Among his many critics the most famous was Hume, who
contends that Wollaston’s theory implies an absurdity: any action concealed
from public view e.g., adultery conveys no false proposition and therefore is
not immoral. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Why bother with Wollaston?” BANC.
wollheim: R. A. London-born philosopher of Eastern-European
ancestry, BPhil Oxon, Balliol (under D. Marcus) and All Souls. Examined by H. P. Grice. “What’s two times
two?” Wollheim treasured that examination. It was in the context of a
discussion of J. S. Mill and I. Kant, for whom addition and multiplication are
‘synthetic’ – a priori for Kant, a posteriori for Mill. Grice was trying to
provide a counterexample to Mill’s thesis that all comes via deduction or
induction. Refs.: I. C. Dengler and Luigi Speranza, “Wollheilm and Grice,” for
the Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
woodianism: Roy Hudd: “Not to be confused with the woodianisms of
Victoria Wood.” -- Grice loved O. P. Wood, as anyone at Oxford did – even those
who disliked Ryle! Refs.: H. P. Grice, “O. P. Wood and some remarks about the
senses,” -- O. P. Wood, “Implicatura in
Hereford,” for The Swimming-Pool Library, custodian: Luigi Speranza – Villa
Grice, Liguria, Italia.
woozleyianism: R. M. Harnish discussed H. P. Grice’s implicaturum
with A. D. Woozley. Woozley would know because he had been in contact with
Grice since for ever. Woozley had a closer contact with Austin, since, unlike
Grice, ‘being from the right side of the tracks,’ he socialized with Austin in
what Berlin pretentiously calls the ‘early beginnings of Oxford philosophy,’ as
if the Middle Ages never happened. Woozley edited Reid, that Grice read, or
reed. Since the first way to approach Grice’s philosophy is with his colleagues
at his Play Group, Woozley plays a crucial role. Grice: “While Woozley would
attend Austin’s Sat. morns., he wouldn’t say much – in fact, he seldom said
much.” Refs.: R. M. Harnish and A. D. Woozley, “Implicatura,” for The
Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
wright: philosopher. His philosophical discussions are
stimulating and attracted many, including Peirce, James, and Oliver Wendell
Holmes, Jr., who thinks of him as their “intellectual boxing master.” Wright
eventually accepted empiricism, especially that of J. S. Mill, though under
Darwinian influence he modified Mill’s view considerably by rejecting the
empiricist claim that general propositions merely summarize particulars. Wright
claims instead that scientific theories are hypotheses to be further developed,
and insisted that a moral rule is irreducible and needs no utilitarian “proof.”
Though he denied the “summary” view of universals, he is not strictly a
pragmatist, since for him a low-level empirical proposition like Peirce’s ‘this
diamond is hard’ is not a hypothesis but a self-contained irreducible
statement. Then there is the furrin wright, pronounced /rixt/.
wright: pronounced /rixt/. Finnish philosopher, one of the
most influential analytic philosophers of the twentieth century. His early
work, influenced by logical empiricism, is on logic, probability, and
induction, including contributions in modal and deontic logic, the logic of
norms and action, preference logic, tense logic, causality, and determinism. In
the 0s his ideas about the explanation of action helped to link the analytic
tradition to Continental hermeneutics. His most important contribution is A
Treatise on Induction and Probability 1, which develops a system of eliminative
induction using the concepts of necessary and sufficient condition. In 9 von
Wright went to Cambridge to meet Broad, and he attended Vitters’s lectures.
Regular discussions with Moore also had an impact on him. In 8 von Wright
succeeded Vitters as professor at Cambridge . After Vitters’s death in 1, von
Wright returned to Helsinki. Together with Anscombe and Rush Rhees, he became
executor and editor of Vitters’s Nachlass. The study, organization,
systematization, and publication of this exceptionally rich work became a
lifelong task for him. In his Cambridge years von Wright became interested in
the logical properties of various modalities: alethic, deontic, epistemic. An
Essay in Modal Logic 1 studies, syntactically, various deductive systems of
modal logic. That year he published his famous article “Deontic Logic” in Mind.
It made him the founder of modern deontic logic. These logical works profoundly
influenced analytic philosophy, especially action theory. Von Wright
distinguishes technical oughts means-ends relationships from norms issued by a
norm-authority. His Norm and Action 3 discusses philosophical problems
concerning the existence of norms and the truth of normative statements. His
main work on metaethics is The Varieties of Goodness 3. In Explanation and
Understanding 1 he turned to philosophical problems concerning the human
sciences. He defends a manipulation view of causality, where the concept of
action is basic for that of cause: human action cannot be explained causally by
laws, but must be understood intentionally. The basic model of intentionality
is the practical syllogism, which explains action by a logical connection with
wants and beliefs. This work, sometimes characterized as anti-positivist
analytical hermeneutics, bridges analytic and Continental philosophy. His
studies in truth, knowledge, modality, lawlikeness, causality, determinism,
norms, and practical inference were published in 384 in his Philosophical
Papers. von Neumann, John von Wright, G. H. 965 965 In 1 von Wright became a member of the
Academy of Finland, the highest honor Finland gives to its scientists. Over
many years he has written, in Swedish and Finnish, eloquent essays in the
history of ideas and the philosophy of culture. He has become increasingly
critical of the modern scientific-technological civilization, its narrowly
instrumental concept of rationality, and its myth of progress. His public pleas
for peace, human rights, and a more harmonious coexistence of human beings and
nature have made him the most esteemed intellectual in the Scandinavian
countries. Refs.: H. P. Grice’s “von Wright’s ‘alethic’ and why I need it;” H.
P. Grice, “von Wright on the eight state-of-affair connectors;” H. P. Grice,
“von Wright and the sorry story of deontic logic.”
wundt: proto-Griceian philosophical psychologist. philosopher
that Grice, who calls himself a ‘philosophical psychologist,’ often quotes. “As
the founder of scientific psychology, Wundt was influential in my embracing
‘philosophical psychology,’ as a revenge.” Although trained as a physician
(“like Vitters”), Wundt turns to philosophy and in Leipzig’s downtown
established the first recognized psychology laboratory. For Wundt, psychology
deals with conscious experience, a definition soon overtaken by Ryle’s
behaviourism. Wundt’s psychology has two departments: the so-called physiological
psychology (Grundzuge der physiologischen Psychologie, Grice preferred
‘philosophical physiology’), primarily the experimental study of immediate
experience broadly modeled on Fechner’s psycho-physics; and the
Volkerpsychologie (Volkerpsychologie, -- or ‘folkpsychology,’ as Grice prefers
– ‘philosohical psychology is a folk-science’ -- which circulated at Oxford as
“The Language of Gestures,” the non-experimental study of the higher mental
processes via their products, conversation, language, myth, and custom.
Although Wundt is a prodigious investigator and author, and was revered as
psychology’s founder, his theories, unlike his methods, exerted little
influence, except on Grice and a few intelligent Griceians. A typical scholar
of his time, Wundt, like Grice, also explored across the whole of philosophy,
including logic and ethics. W. M. philosopher and psychologist, a founder of
scientific psychology. Although trained as a physician, he turned to philosophy
and in 1879, at the of Leipzig,
established the first recognized psychology laboratory. For Wundt, psychology
was the science of conscious experience, a definition soon overtaken by
behaviorism. Wundt’s psychology had two departments: the so-called
physiological psychology Grundzuge der physiologischen Psychologie, 3 vols.,
1873 74; only vol. 1 of the fifth edition, 0, was tr. into English, primarily
the experimental study of immediate experience broadly modeled on Fechner’s
psychophysics; and the Volkerpsychologie Volkerpsychologie, 10 vols., 020; fragment
tr. as The Language of Gestures, 3, the non-experimental study of the higher
mental processes via their products, language, myth, and custom. Although Wundt
was a prodigious investigator and author, and was revered as psychology’s
founder, his theories, unlike his methods, exerted little influence. A typical
G. scholar of his time, he also wrote across the whole of philosophy, including
logic and ethics. .
wyclif: “It never ceased to amaze me how Wyclif was able to
find Anglo-Saxon terms for all the “Biblia Vulgata”!” – H. P. Grice. English
Griceian philosophical theologian and religious reformer. He worked for most of
his life in Oxford as a secular clerk, teaching philosophy and later theology
and writing extensively in both fields. The mode of thought expressed in his
surviving works is one of extreme realism, and in this his thought fostered the
split of Bohemian, later Hussite, philosophy from that of the G. masters
teaching in Prague. His worldline Wyclif, John 982 982 philosophical summa was most influential
for his teaching on universals, but also dealt extensively with the question of
determinism; these issues underlay his later handling of the questions of the
Eucharist and of the identity of the church respectively. His influence on
English philosophy was severely curtailed by the growing hostility of the
church to his ideas, the condemnation of many of his tenets, the persecution of
his followers, and the destruction of his writings.
X
xenophanes:
Grice: “You have to be careful when you research for this in Italy – they spell
it with an ‘s’!” -- Grecian philosopher, a proponent of an idealized
conception of the divine, and the first of the pre-Socratics to propound
epistemological views. Born in Colophon, an Ionian Grecian city on the coast of
Asia Minor, he emigrated as a young man to the Grecian West Sicily and southern
Italy. The formative influence of the Milesians is evident in his rationalism.
He is the first of the pre-Socratics for whom we have not only ancient reports
but also quite a few verbatim quotations fragments from his “Lampoons”
Silloi and from other didactic poetry. Xenophanes attacks the worldview of
Homer, Hesiod, and traditional Grecian piety: it is an outrage that the poets
attribute moral failings to the gods. Traditional religion reflects regional
biases blond gods for the Northerners; black gods for the Africans. Indeed,
anthropomorphic gods reflect the ultimate bias, that of the human viewpoint “If
cattle, or horses, or lions . . . could draw pictures of the gods . . . ,” frg.
15. There is a single “greatest” god, who is not at all like a human being,
either in body or in mind; he perceives without the aid of organs, he effects
changes without “moving,” through the sheer power of his thought. The rainbow
is no sign from Zeus; it is simply a special cloud formation. Nor are the sun
or the moon gods. All phenomena in the skies, from the elusive “Twin Sons of
Zeus” St. Elmo’s fire to sun, moon, and stars, are varieties of cloud
formation. There are no mysterious infernal regions; the familiar strata of
earth stretch down ad infinitum. The only cosmic limit is the one visible at
our feet: the horizontal border between earth and air. Remarkably, Xenophanes
tempers his theological and cosmological pronouncements with an epistemological
caveat: what he offers is only a “conjecture.” In later antiquity Xenophanes
came to be regarded as the founder of the Eleatic School, and his teachings
were assimilated to those of Parmenides and Melissus. This appears to be based
on nothing more than Xenophanes’ emphasis on the oneness and utter immobility
of God.
xenophon: Grice: “You have to be carefully
when researching for this philosopher in Italy – They spell it ‘Senofonte’ Grecian
soldier and historian, author of several Socratic dialogues, along with
important works on history, education, political theory, and other topics. He
was interested in philosophy, and he was a penetrating and intelligent “social
thinker” whose views on morality and society have been influential over many
centuries. His perspective on Socrates’ character and moral significance
provides a valuable supplement and corrective to the better-known views of
Plato. Xenophon’s Socratic dialogues, the only ones besides Plato’s to survive
intact, help us obtain a broader picture of the Socratic dialogue as a literary
genre. They also provide precious evidence concerning the thoughts and
personalities of other followers of Socrates, such as Antisthenes and Alcibiades.
Xenophon’s longest and richest Socratic work is the Memorabilia, or “Memoirs of
Socrates,” which stresses Socrates’ self-sufficiency and his beneficial effect
on his companions. Xenophon’s Apology of Socrates and his Symposium were
probably intended as responses to Plato’s Apology and Symposium. Xenophon’s
Socratic dialogue on estate management, the Oeconomicus, is valuable for its
underlying social theory and its evidence concerning the role and status of
women in classical Athens. Refs.: Speranza, “All you need is Loeb,” Villa
Grice.
Y
yog and zog: “My inspiration was Carroll’s “What the tortoise said to
Achilles.” Trust me to go to the defense of the underdog, or undertortoise!”
“Achilles had enough praise by the Romans!” -- “If” (Cicero’s ‘si’) is a
problem for Grice. “Especially in it being the only subordinate particle I have
seriously explored.” According to Strawson and Wiggins, this was Grice having
forged his shining new tool – the distinction between ‘By emitting x, An
emissor coomunicates that p” and “The emissum x ‘means’ ‘p.’ Apply that to
‘if.’ In Strawson and Wiggins’s precis, for Grice, ‘p yields q’ is part of the
conversational implicaturum – for Strawson and Wiggins it is part of the
conventional implicaturum. They agree on ‘p
horseshoe q’ being the explicit emissum or explicatum in “Emissor
explicitly conveys and communicates that p horseshoe q.” For Grice, the implicaturum,
which, being conversational is cancellable, is calculated on the assumption
that the addressee can work out that the emissor has non-truth-functional
grounds for the making of any stronger claim. For Strawson, that
non-truth-functional reason is precisely ‘p yields q,’ which leads Strawson to
think that the thing is not cancellable and conventionally implicated. If
Strawson were right that this is Grice forging a new shining tool to crack the
crib of reality and fashioning thereby a new shining skid under his
metaphysical feet, it would be almost the second use of the tool! This is an expansion by Grice on the implicaturum
of a ‘propositio conditionalis.’ Grice, feeling paradoxical, invites us
to suppose a scenario involving ‘if.’ He takes it as a proof that his
account of the conversational implicaturum of ‘if’ is, as Strawson did not
agree, correct, and that what an utterer explicitly conveys by ‘if p, q’ is ‘p
> q.’ that two chess players, Yog and
Zog, play 100 games under the following conditions. Yog is white nine of ten
times. There are no draws. And the results are: Yog, when white,
won 80 of 90 games. Yog, when black, won zero of ten games. This implies
that: 8/9 times, if Yog was white, Yog won. 1/2 of the time, if Yog lost,
Yog was black. 9/10 that either Yog
wasnt white or he won. From these statements, it might appear one could
make these deductions by contraposition and conditional disjunction: If
Yog was white, then 1/2 of the time Yog won. 9/10 times, if Yog was white, then
he won. But both propositions are untrue. They contradict the assumption.
In fact, they do not provide enough information to use Bayesian reasoning to
reach those conclusions. That might be clearer if the propositions had instead
been stated differently. When Yog was white, Yog won 8/9 times. No information
is given about when Yog was black. When Yog lost, Yog was black 1/2 the time.
No information is given about when Yog won. (9/10 times, either Yog was black
and won, Yog was black and lost, or Yog was white and won. No information is
provided on how the 9/10 is divided among those three situations. The paradox by
Grice shows that the exact meaning of statements involving conditionals and
probabilities is more complicated than may be obvious on casual examination. Refs.:
Grice’s interest with ‘if’ surely started after he carefully read the section
on ‘if’ and the horseshoe in Strawson’s Introduction to Logical Theory. He was
later to review his attack on Strawson in view of Strawson’s defense in ‘If and
the horseshoe.’ The polemic was pretty much solved as a matter of different
intuitions: what Grice sees as a conversational implicaturum, Strawson does see
as an ‘implicaturum,’ but a non-defeasible one – what Grice would qualify as
‘conventional.’ Grice leaves room for an implicaturum to be nonconversational
and yet nonconventional, but it is not worth trying to fit Strawson’s
suggestion in this slot, since Strawson, unlike Grice, has nothing against a
convention. Grice was motivated to formulate his ‘paradox,’ seeing that
Strawson was saying that the so-called ‘paradoxes’ of ‘entailment’ and
‘implication’ are a misnomer. “They are not paradoxical; they are false!” Grice
has specific essays on both the paradoxes of entailment and the paradoxes of
implication-. The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC MSS 90/135c, The University of
California, Berkeley.
Z
zabarella: Grice: “Zabarella
is what I would call a proto-Griceain.” In fact, at Villa Grice, Grice was
often called the English Zabarella, after philosopher Jacopo Zabarella, of
Padova. Zabarella produces extensive commentaries on Grice’s favourite tract by
Aristotle, “De Anima,” and Physica and also discussed some Aristotelian
interpreters. However, Zabarella’s most original contribution is his work in
semantics, “Opera logica.” Zabarella regards semantics as a preliminary study
that provides the tools necessary for philosophical analysis. Two such tools
are what Zabarella calls “order” (cf. Grice, ‘be orderly’). Another tool is
what Zabarella calls “ method.” Order teaches us how to organize the content of
a discipline to apprehend it more easily. Method teaches us how to draw a
syllogistic inference. Zabarella reduces the varieties of orders and methods
classified by other interpreters to compositive order, and resolutive order,
and composite method and and resolutive method. The compositive order from a
principle to this or that corollary applies to this or that speculative,
alethic or theoretical discipline. The ‘resolutive’ order, from a desired end
to the means appropriate to its achievement applies to this or that practical
discipline, such as ‘pragmatics’ understood as a manual of rules of etiquette.
This much is already in Aristotle. However, Zabarella offers an original
analysis of ‘method.’ The compositive method infers a particular consequence or
corollary from a ‘generic’ principle. The ‘resolutive’ method INFERS an
originating gneric principle from this or that particular consequence,
corollary, or instantiantion, as in inductive reasoning or in reasoning from
effect to cause. Zabarella’s terminology influenced Galileo’s mechanics, and
has been applied to Grice’s inference of the principle of conversational
co-operation out from the only evidence which Grice has, which is this or that
‘dyadic’ exchange, as he calls it. In Grice’s case, his corpus is intentionally
limited to conversations between two philosophers: A: What’s that? B: A pillar
box? A: What colour is it? B: Seems red to me. From such an exchange, Grice
infers the principle of conversational co-operation. It clashes when a
cancellation (or as Grice prefers, an annulation) is on sight: “I surely don’t
mean to imply that it MIGHT actually be red.” “Then why be so guarded? I
thought you were cooperating.”H. P. Grice. “We can regard Jacopo as an Aristotelian
philosopher who taught at the of Padua.
He wrote extensive commentaries on Aristotle’s Physics and On the Soul and also
discussed other interpreters such as Averroes. However, his most original
contribution was his work in logic, Opera logica 1578. Zabarella regards logic
as a preliminary study that provides the tools necessary for philosophical
analysis. Two such tools are order and method: order teaches us how to organize
the content of a discipline to apprehend it more easily; method teaches us how
to draw syllogistic inferences. Zabarella reduces the varieties of orders and
methods classified by other interpreters to compositive and resolutive orders
and methods. The compositive order from first principles to their consequences
applies to theoretical disciplines. The resolutive order from a desired end to
means appropriate to its achievement applies to practical disciplines. This
much was already in Aristotle. Zabarella offers an original analysis of method.
The compositive method infers particular consequences from general principles.
The resolutive method infers originating principles from particular
consequences, as in inductive reasoning or in reasoning from effect to cause.
It has been suggested that Zabarella’s terminology might have influenced
Galileo’s mechanics. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Zabarella,” Speranza, “Grice and
Zabarella,” Villa Grice.
zeigarnik
effect:
‘Conversation as a compete task and the Zeigmaik effect’ -- H. P. Grice. the
selective recall of uncompleted tasks in comparison to completed tasks. The effect
was named for Bluma Zeigarnik, a student of K. Lewin, who discovered it and
described it in a paper published in the Psychologische Forschung in 7.
Subjects received an array of short tasks, such as counting backward and
stringing beads, for rapid completion. Performance on half of these was
interrupted. Subsequent recall for the tasks favored the interrupted tasks.
Zeigarnik concluded that recall is influenced by motivation and not merely
associational strength. The effect was thought relevant to Freud’s claim that
unfulfilled wishes are persistent. Lewin attempted to derive the effect from
field theory, suggesting that an attempt to reach a goal creates a tension
released only when that goal is reached; interruption of the attempt produces a
tension favoring recall. Conditions affecting the Zeigarnik effect are
incompletely understood, as is its significance. Refs.: H. P. Grice,
“Conversation as a complete task and the Zeigmarnik effect.” BANC
zettel: Grice entitled his further notes on logic and conversation,
“zettel” – “What’s good enough for Vitters is good enough for me.” Refs.: H. P.
Grice, “Conversation: Zettel,” BANC.
zoroastro:
the
founder of so-called ‘zoroastrianism.’ H. P. Grice wrote, “Thus Implicated
Zarahustra,” the national religion of ancient Iran. Zoroastrianism suffered a
steep decline after the seventh century A.D. because of conversion to Islam. Of
a remnant of roughly 100,000 adherents today, three-fourths are Parsis
“Persians” in or from western India; the others are Iranian Zoroastrians. The
tradition is identified with its prophet; his name in Persian, Zarathushtra, is
preserved in G. and Griceian, but the ancient Grecian rendering of that name,
Zoroaster, is the form used in most other modern European languages.
Zoroaster’s hymns to Ahura Mazda “the Wise Lord”, called the Gathas, are
interspersed among ritual hymns to other divine powers in the collection known
as the Avesta. In them, Zoroaster seeks reassurance that good will ultimately
triumph over evil and that Ahura Mazda will be a protector to him in his
prophetic mission. The Gathas expect that humans, by aligning themselves with
the force of righteousness and against evil, will receive bliss and benefit in
the next existence. The dating of the texts and of the prophet himself is an
elusive matter for scholars, but it is clear that Zoroaster lived somewhere in
Iran sometime prior to the emergence of the Achaemenid empire in the sixth
century B.C. His own faith in Ahura Mazda, reflected in the Gathas, came to be
integrated with other strains of old Indo-Iranian religion. We see these in the
Avesta’s hymns and the religion’s ritual practices. They venerate an array of
Iranian divine powers that resemble in function the deities found in the Vedas
of India. A common Indo-Iranian heritage is indicated conclusively by
similarities of language and of content between the Avesta and the Vedas.
Classical Zoroastrian orthodoxy does not replace the Indo-Iranian divinities
with Ahura Mazda, but instead incorporates them into its thinking more or less
as Ahura Mazda’s agents. The Achaemenid kings from the sixth through the fourth
centuries B.C. mention Ahura Mazda in their inscriptions, but not Zoroaster.
The Parthians, from the third century B.C. to the third century A.D.,
highlighted Mithra among the Indo-Iranian pantheon. But it was under the
Sasanians, who ruled Iran from the third to the seventh centuries, that
Zoroastrianism became the established religion. A salient doctrine is the
teaching concerning the struggle between good and evil. The time frame from the
world’s creation to the final resolution or judgment finds the Wise Lord, Ahura
Mazda or Ohrmazd, in the Pahlavi language of Sasanian times, locked in a
struggle with the evil spirit, Angra Mainyu in Pahlavi, Ahriman. The teaching
expands on an implication in the text of the Gathas, particularly Yasna 30,
that the good and evil spirits, coming together in the beginning and
establishing the living and inanimate realms, determined that at the end
benefit would accrue to the righteous but not the wicked. In Sasanian times,
there was speculative concern to assert Ahura Mazda’s infinity, omnipotence,
and omniscience, qualities that may indicate an impact of Mediterranean
philosophy. For example, the Bundahishn, a Pahlavi cosmological and
eschatological narrative, portrays Ahura Mazda as infinite in all four compass
directions but the evil spirit as limited in one and therefore doomed to
ultimate defeat. Such doctrine has been termed by some dualistic, in that it
has at least in Sasanian times seen the power of God rivaled by that of an evil
spirit. Zoroastrians today assert that they are monotheists, and do not worship
the evil spirit. But to the extent that the characterization may hold
historically, Zoroastrianism has manifested an “ethical” dualism, of good and
evil forces. Although capable of ritual pollution through waste products and
decay, the physical world, God’s creation, remains potentially morally good.
Contrast “ontological” dualism, as in gnostic and Manichaean teaching, where
the physical world itself is the result of the fall or entrapment of spirit in
matter. In the nineteenth century, Zoroastrian texts newly accessible to Europe
produced an awareness of the prophet’s concern for ethical matters. Nietzsche’s
values in his work Thus Spake Zarathustra, however, are his own, not those of
the ancient prophet. The title is arresting, but the connection of Nietzsche
with historical Zoroastrianism is a connection in theme only, in that the work
advances ideas about good and evil in an oracular style. Refs.: H. P. Grice,
“Nietzsche’s implicatura,” BANC.
zweckrationalität: “I chose this to
be one of the last entries in my dictionary!” -- Grice: “What I like about
Weber’s ‘zweckrationalitaet’ is that it’s one of the latter items in my
dictionary!” -- Grice: “I’m slightly confused by Weber, who was hardly a
philosopher, and his use of ‘zweck,’ – which Kant would have disliked. H. P.
Grice used the vernacular here, since he found it tricky to look for the
Oxonian for ‘Zweck.’ As he was reading Weber, Grice realises that one
of the main theoretical goals of Weber’s work is to understand how a social
process (such as a conversation, seen as a two-player game) become
“rationalized,” taking up certain themes of philosophy of history since Hegel
as part of social theory. Conversation, as part of culture, e.g., becomes
‘rationalised’ in the process of the “disenchantment of a world views” in the
West, a process that Weber thinks has “universal significance.” But because of
his goal-oriented theory of action and his non-cognitivism in ethics, Weber
sees rationalization, like Grice, and unlike, say, Habermas, exclusively in
terms of the spread of purposive, or MEANS–ends rationality (“Zweckrationalität”).
Rational action means choosing the most effective MEANS of achieving one’s
goals and implies judging the consequences of one’s actions and choices. In
contrast, value rationality (“Wertrationalität,” that Grice translates as
‘worth-rationality’) consists of any action oriented to this or that ultimate
END, where considerations of consequences are irrelevant. Although such action
is rational insofar as it directs and organises human conduct, the choice of
this or that end, or this or that value itself cannot be, for Weber, unlike
Grice, a matter for rational or scientific judgment. Indeed, for Weber this
means that politics is the sphere for the struggle between at least two of this
or that irreducibly competing ultimate end, where “gods and demons fight it
out” and charismatic leaders invent new gods and values. Grice tries to look for a way to give a criterion of
rationality other than the ‘common-or-garden’ means-end variety. When it comes
to conversation, see, Speranza, “The feast of [conversational] reason – Grice’s
Conversational immanuel – three steps towards a critique of conversational
reason.” Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Conversational rationality,” in The H. P. Grice
Papers, BANC MSS 90/135c, The Bancroft Library, The University of California,
Berkeley.
References
Following
the tradition of H. P. Grice’s Playgroup, only Oxonian English-born male
philosophers of Grice’s generation listed)
Austin,
J. L. Philosophical papers, edited by J. O. Urmson and G. J. Warnock. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Austin,
J. L. Sense and sensibilia, reconstructed from manuscript notes by G. J.
Warnock. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Austin,
J. L. How to do things with words, ed. by J. O. Urmson. Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Blackburn,
S. W. Spreading the word. Oxford.
Bostock,
D. Logic.
Flew,
A. G. N. Logic and language. Oxford: Blackwell.
Grice,
H. P. Studies in the Way of Words
Grice,
H. P. Negation and privation
Grice,
H. P. The conception of value. Oxford, at the Clarendon Press.
Grice,
H. P. Aspects of reason, Oxford, at the Clarendon Press.
Grice,
H. P., D. F. Pears, and P. F. Strawson, ‘Metaphysics,’ in D. F. Pears, The
nature of metaphysics. London: Macmillan.
Hampshire,
S. N. Thought and action. London: Chatto and Windus.
Hampshire,
S. N. and H. L. A. Hart, Intention, decision, and certainty. Mind.
Hare,
R. M. The language of morals. Oxford, at the Clarendon Press.
Hart,
H. L. A. Review of Holloway, The Philosophical Quarterly
Nowell-Smith,
P. H. Ethics. Middlesex: Penguin
Pears,
D. F. Philosophical psychology. London: Duckworth.
Pears,
D. F. Motivated irrationality.
Pears,
D. F. and H. P. Grice, The philosophy of action.
Speranza,
Minutes of H. P. Grice’s Play-Group – The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice,
Liguria, Italia.
Strawson,
P. F. Introduction to Logical Theory.
Strawson,
P. F. Logico-Linguistic Papers.
Strawson,
P. F. and H. P. Grice, In defense of a dogma.
Strawson,
P. F. and H. P. Grice, Categories
Strawson,
P. F. and H. P. Grice, Meaning.
Thomson,
J. F. and H. P. Grice, The philosophy of action.
Urmson,
J. O. Philosophical Analysis: its development between the two wars.
Warnock,
G. J. The object of morality
Warnock,
G. J. Language and Morals
Woozley,
A. D. On H. P. Grice. – A. M. G. is Anna Maria Ghersi – Ghersi instilled and
keeps instilling – never ceases to instill -- in Luigi Speranza a love for
philosophy.
No comments:
Post a Comment