Guicciardini. Grice:
“Guicciardini is what I call an Italian classic; some like Machiavelli, as
Austin used to say, “but Guicciardini is MY Renaissance man!” – Grice: “There
are various topics of interest: the italian of Machiavelli and Guicciardini in
the development of a philosophical political lexicon; there’s the trope of the
centaur –‘all’ombra del centauro.’ – Pure political philosophy of the type
enjoyed by members of the Debating Union at Oxford!” Ritratto di francesco guicciardini.. Ambasciatore
della Repubblica di Firenze in Spagna Durata mandato 17 ottobre 1511ottobre 1513 Capo di StatoPier
Soderini (Repubblica) Cardinale Giovanni de' Medici (Signoria) Membro del
consiglio degli Otto di Guardia e Balia Durata mandato14 agosto 1514ottobre
1515 MonarcaGiuliano di Lorenzo de' Medici Lorenzo di Piero de' Medici
Membro della Signoria di Firenze Durata mandatosettembre 1515ottobre 1515
MonarcaGiuliano di Lorenzo de' Medici Commissario pontificio di Modena Durata
mandato5 aprile 15164 maggio 1519 MonarcaLorenzo di Piero de' Medici
Commissario generale dell'esercito dello Stato Pontificio Durata mandato12
luglio 152125 dicembre 1523 MonarcaLeone X Adriano VI Presidente della Romagna
Pontificia Durata mandato19 marzo 15231526 MonarcaAdriano VI Clemente VII
Dati generali Titolo di studioLaurea in diritto civile UniversitàPisa
ProfessioneAvvocato Statua di Francesco Guicciardini, Galleria degli
Uffizi, Firenze. Francesco Guicciardini (Firenze), filosofo. Dettaglio della
statua del Guicciardini. Francesco Guicciardini nacque a Firenze il 6 marzo
1483, terzogenito dei Guicciardini, famiglia tra le più fedeli al governo
mediceo. Dopo una prima formazione umanistica in ambito familiare dedicata alla
lettura dei grandi storici dell'antichità (Senofonte, Tucidide, Livio, Tacito),
studiò a Firenze giurisprudenza, seguendo le lezioni del celebre Francesco
Pepi. Dal 1500 soggiornò a Ferrara per circa due anni, per poi trasferirsi a
Padova per seguire le lezioni di docenti di maggior importanza. Rientrato a
Firenze nel 1505, vi esercitò, sebbene non fosse ancora laureato, l'incarico di
istituzioni di diritto civile; nel novembre dello stesso anno ottenne il
dottorato in ius civile ed iniziò la sua carriera forense. Nel 1506 si
concluse la sua attività accademica; nel frattempo, contrasse matrimonio,
contro il volere paterno, con Maria Salviati, figlia di Alamanno Salviati e
appartenente ad una famiglia politicamente esposta ed apertamente contraria a
Pier Soderini, all'epoca gonfaloniere a vita di Firenze. Guicciardini si curò
poco di queste rivalità, in quanto il suo interesse principale era avere un
futuro ruolo politico, alla luce soprattutto del prestigio di cui godeva la
famiglia della moglie, che avrebbe potuto avere per lui un effetto
positivo. Questo matrimonio infatti funse per lui da trampolino di
lancio, garantendogli una brillante e rapida ascesa politica: con l'aiuto del
suocero fu nominato tra i capitani dello Spedale del Ceppo, una carica non molto
significativa di per sé, ma prestigiosa in quanto a membri insigniti
dell'onorificenza. Nel 1508 curò l'istruttoria contro il podestà Piero Ludovico
da Fano, iniziando la stesura delle Storie fiorentine e dei Ricordi.
Esattamente dieci anni prima, ossia con l'anno 1498, si chiudono quelle
Cronache forlivesi di Leone Cobelli che espongono le premesse degli avvenimenti
riguardanti Caterina Sforza e Cesare Borgia di cui Guicciardini si occupa,
nelle sue Storie, per i notevoli riflessi che hanno sulla politica fiorentina.
Nel 1509, in occasione della guerra contro Pisa, venne chiamato a pratica dalla
signoria, ottenendo, grazie all'aiuto del Salviati, l'avvocatura del capitolo
di Santa Liberata. Questi progressi portarono il Guicciardini anche ad una
rapida ascesa nella politica internazionale, ricevendo dalla Repubblica
Fiorentina l'incarico di ambasciatore in Spagna presso Ferdinando il Cattolico
nel 1512. Da questa sua esperienza nell'attività diplomatica nacque la
Relazione di Spagna, una lucida analisi delle condizioni socio-politiche della
Penisola Iberica e anche il "Discorso di Logrogno", un'opera di
teoria politica in cui Guicciardini sostiene una riforma in senso aristocratico
della Repubblica fiorentina. Nel 1513 fece ritorno a Firenze, dove da
circa un anno era stata restaurata la Signoria Medicea con l'appoggio
dell'esercito ispano-pontificio. Dal 1514 fece parte degli Otto di Guardia e
Balia e nel 1515 entrò a far parte della signoria, divenendo, grazie ai suoi
servigi resi ai Medici, avvocato concistoriale e governatore di Modena nel
1516, con la salita al soglio pontificio di Giovanni de' Medici, col nome di
Leone X. Il suo ruolo di primo piano nella politica emiliano-romagnola si
rinforzò notevolmente nel 1517, con la nomina a governatore di Reggio Emilia e
di Parma, proprio nel periodo del delicato conflitto franco-imperiale. Fu
nominato nel 1521 commissario generale dell'esercito pontificio, alleato
di Carlo V contro i francesi; in questo periodo maturò quell'esperienza che
sarebbe stata cruciale nella redazione dei suoi Ricordi e della Storia
d'Italia. Alla morte di Leone X, avvenuta nel 1521, Guicciardini si trovò
a contrastare l'assedio di Parma, argomento trattato nella Relazione della
difesa di Parma. Dopo l'assunzione al papato di Giulio de' Medici, col nome di
Clemente VII, venne inviato a governare la Romagna, una terra agitata dalle
lotte tra le famiglie più potenti; qui Guicciardini diede ampio sfoggio delle
sue notevoli abilità diplomatiche. Per contrastare lo strapotere di Carlo
V, propagandò un'alleanza fra gli stati regionali allora presenti in Italia e
la Francia, in modo da salvaguardare in un certo qual modo l'indipendenza della
penisola. L'accordo fu sottoscritto a Cognac nel 1526, ma si rivelò ben presto
fallimentare; di questo periodo è il Dialogo del reggimento di Firenze, in due
libri, scritti fra il 1521 e il 1526, in cui si ripropone il modello della
repubblica aristocratica; nel 1527 la Lega subì una cocente disfatta e Roma fu
messa al sacco dai Lanzichenecchi, mentre a Firenze veniva instaurata (per la
terza ed ultima volta) la repubblica. Coinvolto in queste vicissitudini, e
visto con diffidenza dai repubblicani per i suoi trascorsi medicei, si ritirò
in un volontario esilio nella sua villa di Finocchieto, nei pressi di Firenze.
Qui compose due orazioni, l'Oratio accusatoria e la defensoria, ed una Lettera
Consolatoria, che segue il modello dell'oratio ficta, nella quale espose le
accuse imputabili alla sua condotta con le adeguate confutazioni, e finse di
ricevere consolazioni da un amico. Nel 1529 scrisse le Considerazioni intorno
ai "Discorsi" del Machiavelli "sopra la prima deca di Tito
Livio", in cui accese una polemica nei confronti della mentalità
pessimistica dell'illustre concittadino. In questi mesi completa anche la redazione
definitiva dei Ricordi. Dopo la confisca dei beni, nel 1529 lasciò
Firenze e ritornò a Roma, per rimettersi di nuovo al servizio di Clemente VII,
che gli offrì l'incarico di diplomatico a Bologna. Dopo il rientro dei Medici a
Firenze (1531), fu accolto alla corte medicea come consigliere del duca
Alessandro e scrisse i Discorsi del modo di riformare lo stato dopo la caduta
della Repubblica e di assicurarlo al duca Alessandro; non fu tenuto tuttavia in
altrettanta considerazione dal successore di Alessandro, Cosimo I, che lo
lasciò in disparte. Guicciardini allora si ritirò nella sua villa di Santa
Margherita in Montici ad Arcetri, dove trascorse i suoi ultimi anni dedicandosi
alla letteratura: riordinò i Ricordi politici e civili, raccolse i suoi Discorsi
politici e soprattutto scrisse la Storia d'Italia. Morì ad Arcetri nel 1540,
quando da circa due anni si era ormai ritirato a vita privata. Il
pensiero politico Questa voce non è neutrale! La neutralità di questa voce o
sezione sugli argomenti storia e politica è stata messa in dubbio. Motivo:
Fatta eccezione per il primo paragrafo, il testo esprime opinioni di parte e
non supportate da fonti Per contribuire, correggi i toni enfatici o di parte e
partecipa alla discussione. Non rimuovere questo avviso finché la disputa non è
risolta. Segui i suggerimenti dei progetti di riferimento 1, 2. Guicciardini è
noto soprattutto per la Storia d'Italia, vasto e dettagliato affresco delle
vicende italiane tra il 1494 (anno della discesa in italia del Re francese
Carlo VIII) e il 1534 (anno della morte di Papa Clemente VII) e capolavoro
della storiografia della prima epoca moderna e della storiografia scientifica
in generale. Come tale, è un monumento al ceto intellettuale italiano del XVI
secolo, e più specificamente alla scuola fiorentina di storici filosofici (o
politici) di cui fecero parte anche Niccolò Machiavelli, Bernardo Segni, Pitti,
Jacopo Nardi, Benedetto Varchi, Francesco Vettori e Donato Giannotti.
L'opera districa la rete attorcigliata della politica degli stati italiani del
Rinascimento con pazienza ed intuito. L'autore volutamente si pone come
spettatore imparziale, come critico freddo e curioso, raggiungendo risultati
eccellenti come analista e pensatore (anche se più debole è la comprensione delle
forze in gioco nel più vasto quadro europeo). Guicciardini è l'uomo dei
programmi che mutano "per la varietà delle circunstanze" per cui al
saggio è richiesta la discrezione (Ricordi, 6), ovvero la capacità di percepire
"con buono e perspicace occhio" tutti gli elementi da cui si
determina la varietà delle circostanze. La realtà non è quindi costituita da
leggi universali immutabili come per Machiavelli. Altro concetto saliente del
pensiero guicciardiniano è il particulare (Ricordi, 28) a cui si deve attenere
il saggio, cioè il proprio interesse inteso nel suo significato più nobile come
realizzazione piena della propria intelligenza e della propria capacità di
agire a favore di se stesso e dello stato. In altre parole il particulare non
va inteso egoisticamente, come un invito a prendere in considerazione solamente
l'interesse personale, ma come un invito a considerare pragmaticamente quanto
ognuno può effettivamente realizzare nella specifica situazione in cui si trova
(pensiero che collima con quello di Machiavelli). In netta polemica con
Francesco Guicciardini, per alcuni passi della Storia d'Italia, Jacopo Pitti
scrisse l'opuscolo Apologia dei Cappucci (1570-1575), a difesa della fazione
dei democratici, soprannominati i Cappucci. Fortuna Guicciardini è
considerato il progenitore della storiografia moderna, per il suo pionieristico
impiego di documenti ufficiali a fini di verifica della sua Storia
d'Italia. Fino al 1857 la reputazione di Guicciardini poggiava sulla
Storia d'Italia e su alcuni estratti dai suoi aforismi. Nel 1857 i suoi
discendenti, i conti Piero e Luigi Guicciardini, aprirono gli archivi di
famiglia e diedero incarico a Giuseppe Canestrini di pubblicare, in 10 volumi,
le sue memorie. Negli anni dal 1938 al 1972 furono pubblicati i suoi
Carteggi, che contribuirono in modo determinante ad un'accurata conoscenza
della sua personalità. La critica secentesca Antoon van Dyck,
Ritratto equestre di Anton Giulio Brignole Sale, 1627 «L’angolo di prospettiva
dal quale si prese a considerare, nella prima metà del secolo XVII,
l’opera guicciardiniana, la posizione di questa nel giudizio dei lettori
secenteschi, sono bene indicati da uno spirito acuto dell’epoca, A. G. Brignole
Sale (1636): «quindi non per altro, a mio giudizio, porta pregio il Guicciardini
sopra il Giovio, sol che questi, qual pittor gentile, de’ soggetti ch’egli ha
per le mani colorisce agli occhi altrui con vivacissimi ritratti, senza
inviscerarsi, la superficie, quegli per contrario, qual esperto notomista,
trascurando anzi dilacerando la vaghezza della pelle, vien con l’acutezza della
sua sagacità fino a mostrarci il cuore e il cervello de’ famosi personaggi ben
penetrato». All’affiatamento con lo spirito dell’opera guicciardiniana si
accompagnò, sul piano letterario, una migliore intelligenza del suo stile, di
cui si cominciò ad ammirare, superando le pedanti riserve linguistiche, la
scorrevolezza, l’intima misura e precisione pur nel tono sostenuto. Tuttavia,
proprio dal più accreditato esponente letterario del tacitismo, T. Boccalini
(1612), fu formulato un giudizio tra i meno benevoli alla Storia.» Il
giudizio di Francesco De Sanctis Copertina di un'antica edizione della
Storia d'Italia Francesco De Sanctis non ebbe simpatia per Guicciardini ed
infatti non nascose di apprezzare maggiormente il Machiavelli. Nella sua Storia
della letteratura italiana il critico irpino mise in evidenza come Guicciardini
fosse, sì, in linea con le aspirazioni di Machiavelli, ma se il secondo agì in
linea con i suoi ideali, il primo invece "non metterebbe un dito a
realizzarli". Sempre nella sua Storia della letteratura italiana De
Sanctis affermò: “Il dio del Guicciardini è il suo particolare. Ed è un dio non
meno assorbente che il Dio degli ascetici, o lo stato del Machiavelli. Tutti
gli ideali scompaiono. Ogni vincolo religioso, morale, politico, che tiene
insieme un popolo, è spezzato. Non rimane sulla scena del mondo che
l'individuo. Ciascuno per sé, verso e contro tutti. Questo non è più
corruzione, contro la quale si gridi: è saviezza, è dottrina predicata e
inculcata, è l'arte della vita”. E poco più in basso aggiunse:
"Questa base intellettuale è quella medesima del Machiavelli, l'esperienza
e l'osservazione, il fatto e lo «speculare» o l'osservare. Né altro è il
sistema. Il Guicciardini nega tutto quello che il Machiavelli nega, e in forma
anche più recisa, e ammette quello che è più logico e più conseguente. Poiché
la base è il mondo com'è, crede un'illusione a volerlo riformare, e volergli
dare le gambe di cavallo, quando esso le ha di asino, e lo piglia com'è e vi si
acconcia, e ne fa la sua regola e il suo istrumento". Nel
Romanticismo, la mancanza di evidenti passioni per l'oggetto dell'opera era
infatti vista come un grave difetto, nei confronti sia del lettore che dell'arte
letteraria. A ciò si aggiunga che il Guicciardini vale più come analista e
pensatore che come scrittore. Lo stile è infatti prolisso, preciso a prezzo di
circonlocuzioni e di perdita del senso generale della narrazione.
"Qualsiasi oggetto egli tocchi, giace già cadavere sul tavolo delle
autopsie". Le opere Scritti autobiografici e rari, Laterza,
1936 Storie fiorentine (dal 1508 al 1509), rimasta inedita fino al 1859
Discorso di Logrogno (1512) Considerazioni sui Discorsi del Machiavelli,
(15271529) Ricordi politici e civili Dialogo del Reggimento di Firenze (dal
1521 al 1526) Storia d'Italia (dal 1537 al 1540) Scritti inediti sopra la
politica di Clemente VII dopo la battaglia di PaviaGuicciardini , Firenze,
Olschki, 1940. Le cose fiorentine, R. Ridolfi , Firenze, Olschki, 1945.
Carteggi, 17 voll., 1938-72 (voll. 1-2 presso Zanichelli, Bologna; 3 presso Istituto per gli studi di politica
internazionale, Firenze; 4 presso
Istituto storico italiano per l'età moderna e contemporanea, Roma; voll. 5-17
presso P. G. Ricci, Roma) Note
"Donna di grandissimo animo e molto virile", secondo il
Guicciardini (Storie fiorentine, cap. XIX).
Natalino Sapegno, Compendio di storia della letteratura italiana, La
Nuova Italia, Firenze, 1963, 94-97. A. G. BRIGNOLE-SALE, Tacito abburatato,
Genova, 1643, Disc. IV133. «Or chi non
vedescriveva il Tassoniche questo è uno stil maestoso e nobile, quale appunto
conviensi alla grandezza delle cose proposte e alla prudenza politica
dell’Istorico che le tratta? e che non ostante i periodi sien tutti numerosi e
sostenuti, per esser ben collocate le parole fra loro, e però l’ordine, e ’l
senso facile e piano in maniera che ’l lettore non trova scabrosità né intoppi,
come nello stil del Villani, che va saltellando e intoppando a ogni passo etc...
». A. TASSONI, Pensieri diversi, Venezia, 1665, libro IX324. Il legame del
pensiero politico tassoniano con quello del Guicciardini (incluso, a differenza
del Machiavelli, tra gli storici della «prima schiera» con Comines e Giovio,
ossia considerato pari agli antichi; v. cap. XIII del libro X dei Pensieri) e
del Machiavelli è noto: i due fiorentini, come dice il Fassò, furono «i due
poli» a cui si volse la sua riflessione politica. (Introduz. a TASSONI, Opere,
Milano-Roma, 194249). T. BOCCALINI,
Ragguagli di Parnaso e Pietra del paragone politico, I, Bari, 1910, Cent. I,
ragg. VI. Walter Binni, I classici
italiani nella storia della critica: Da Dante al Marino, Nuova Italia,
1970, 493. Testi Francesco Guicciardini, Dialogo e
discorsi del reggimento di Firenze, Bari, Gius. Laterza & Figli, 1932.
Francesco Guicciardini, Historia di Italia,
1, Pisa, presso Niccolò Capurro, 1819. Francesco Guicciardini, Historia
di Italia, 2, Pisa, presso Niccolò
Capurro, 1819. Francesco Guicciardini, Historia di Italia, 3, Pisa, presso Niccolò Capurro, 1819.
Francesco Guicciardini, Historia di Italia,
4, Pisa, presso Niccolò Capurro, 1819. Francesco Guicciardini, Historia
di Italia, 5, Pisa, presso Niccolò
Capurro, 1819. Francesco Guicciardini, Historia di Italia, 6, Pisa, presso Niccolò Capurro, 1819.
Francesco Guicciardini, Historia di Italia,
7, Pisa, presso Niccolò Capurro, 1819. Francesco Guicciardini, Historia
di Italia, 8, Pisa, presso Niccolò
Capurro, 1820. Francesco Guicciardini, Historia di Italia, 9, Pisa, presso Niccolò Capurro, 1820.
Francesco Guicciardini, Historia di Italia,
10, Pisa, presso Niccolò Capurro, 1820. Francesco Guicciardini, Historia
di Italia. Libri 1.-16., In Venetia, appresso Giorgio Angelieri, 1574.
Francesco Guicciardini, Scritti autobiografici e rari, Bari, G. Laterza e
Figli, 1936. Francesco Guicciardini, Scritti politici, Bari, G. Laterza, 1933.
Francesco Guicciardini, Storia d'Italia,
1, Bari, G. Laterza, 1929. Francesco Guicciardini, Storia d'Italia, 2, Bari, G. Laterza, 1929. Francesco
Guicciardini, Storia d'Italia, 3, Bari,
G. Laterza, 1929. Francesco Guicciardini, Storia d'Italia, 4, Bari, G. Laterza, 1929. Francesco
Guicciardini, Storia d'Italia, 5, Bari,
G. Laterza, 1929. Francesco Guicciardini, Storie fiorentine dal 1378 al 1509,
Bari, G. Laterza, 1931. Studi R. Ridolfi, 'Vita di Francesco Guicciardini',
Milano 1982, Rusconi P. Treves, Il realismo politico di Francesco Guicciardini,
Firenze, 1931 R. Ramat, Il Guicciardini e la tragedia d'Italia, Firenze 1953 V.
De Caprariis, Francesco Guicciardini. Dalla politica alla storia, Napoli 1950
(ristampa Bologna 1993) G. Sasso, Per Francesco Guicciardini. Quattro studi,
Roma 1985 E. Cutinelli-Rèndina, Guicciardini, Roma 2009 Famiglia Guicciardini Altri progetti
Collabora a Wikisource Wikisource contiene una pagina dedicata a Francesco
Guicciardini Collabora a Wikiquote Citazionio su Francesco Guicciardini
Collabora a Wikimedia Commons Wikimedia Commons contiene immagini o altri file
su Francesco Guicciardini Francesco
Guicciardini, su Treccani.itEnciclopedie on line, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia
Italiana. Francesco Guicciardini, in
Enciclopedia Italiana, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Francesco Guicciardini, in Dizionario di
storia, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana, . (IT, DE, FR) Francesco Guicciardini, su
hls-dhs-dss.ch, Dizionario storico della Svizzera. Francesco Guicciardini, su
Enciclopedia Britannica, Encyclopædia Britannica, Inc. Francesco Guicciardini, in Dizionario
biografico degli italiani, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Francesco Guicciardini, su BeWeb, Conferenza
Episcopale Italiana. Opere di Francesco
Guicciardini, su Liber Liber. Opere di
Francesco Guicciardini, su openMLOL, Horizons Unlimited srl. Opere di Francesco
Guicciardini / Francesco Guicciardini (altra versione), . Edmund Garratt
Gardner, Francesco Guicciardini, in Catholic Encyclopedia, Robert Appleton
Company. Propositioni, overo
Considerationi in materia di cose di Stato, sotto titolo di Avvertimenti,
Avvedimenti Civili, & Concetti Politici di Guicciardinii, Lottini,
Sansovini, Venezia, Presso Altobello Salicato, 1583. Opere inedite di Francesco
Guicciardini illustrate da Giuseppe Canestrini e pubblicate per cura dei conti
Piero e Luigi Guicciardini, 10 voll., Firenze, Barbera, Bianchi e Comp.,
1857-67: 1, 2,
3, 4, 5,
6, 7, 8,
9, 10. Opere, 9 voll., Bari,
Gius. Laterza & figli, 1929-36:
1, 2, 3,
4,//bibliotecaitaliana.it/indice/visualizza_scheda/si150 5],
6, 7, 8, 9.
PredecessoreGovernatore di ModenaSuccessore Giuliano de' Medici15161522PredecessoreGovernatore
di Reggio EmiliaSuccessore 1517 PredecessoreGovernatore di
ParmaSuccessore.
Guzzi: Grice: “Myy favourite
is his dictionary of the unheard tongue – with a foreword like sounds like
Blair on newspeak!” -- Marco Guzzi (Roma), filosofo. Ha trascorso l'adolescenza
partecipando alla lotta politica studentesca, da allievo del Liceo classico
statale Giulio Cesare, uno degli istituti scolastici superiori che più furono
coinvolti nella contestazione giovanile dei primi anni settanta. Dopo aver
conseguito la maturità classica nel 1973, si è laureato in giurisprudenza e
successivamente anche in filosofia. Ha
coltivato in particolare l'interesse per la poesia e la filosofia tedesca, perfezionandosi
presso le Friburgo in Brisgovia e Bonn. Le sue attività principali, nel campo
culturale, hanno spaziato dalla partecipazione a trasmissioni radiofoniche
culturali giovanili alla pubblicazione di numerose raccolte di poesia, alla
redazione di numerosi saggi filosofici, in cui la filosofia contemporanea, in
particolare heideggeriana, si coniuga a una profonda rimeditazione dei temi
della teologia cattolica. A questa attività culturale, sviluppata anche in
numerosi seminari tenuti, dal 1985 al 2002, come direttore dei seminari del Centro
studi Eugenio Montale, si è affiancata la conduzione di trasmissioni
radiofoniche per Radio RAI, fra le quali Dentro la sera, 3131, Lo specchio del
cielo e Sognando il giorno. Dal 1999 ha
fondato e avviato l'esperienza dei Gruppi Darsi-pace, una ricerca sperimentale
di liberazione interiore nell'orizzonte di una riconiugazione tra fede
cristiana e modernità. Dal 2004 dirige la collana "Crocevia" presso
le Edizioni Paoline. Dal 2005 tiene
corsi presso il "Claretianum", Istituto di Teologia della Vita Consacrata
dell'Università Lateranense. Dal 2008 è professore invitato nella Facoltà di
Scienze dell'Educazione dell'Università Pontificia Salesiana. Nel 2009 Benedetto XVI lo ha nominato membro
della Pontificia Accademia di Belle Arti e Lettere dei Virtuosi al
Pantheon. Dal scrive sul blog collettivo Vinonuovo. Guzzi è sposato e ha tre figli. La poesia La poetica di Guzzi, fin
dall'inizio, si è concepita come un'esperienza spirituale, una ricerca di stati
più dilatati della coscienza, sulla scia della linea che da Hölderlin, e
attraverso Rimbaud, arriva fino al nostro migliore ermetismo. Di raccolta in
raccolta, la scrittura è diventata sempre più limpida fino ad approdare a una
concezione profetica e meditativa della scrittura in versi. La parola, da strumento
di autoanalisi, diventa così veicolo dell'annuncio di una rivoluzione
teo-cosmologica, oltre che di una svolta interiore: Il mio confine è Dio. È spalancato. Non c'è
cancello o argine, un respiro lega i miei colori ai suoi comandamenti. Il mio confine è il mio promesso sposo. Un bambinetto batte le manine, lancia
coriandoli sul capo del risorto. Il
pensiero Sulla scia di questa evoluzione della sua poetica, la ricerca teoretica
di Guzzi ha affrontato, in particolare nel saggio filosofico La svolta,
significativamente sottotitolato "La fine della storia e la via del
ritorno", il tema del cambiamento epocale che a suo avviso l'uomo è
chiamato a conoscere e riconoscere, dentro e fuori di sé. Questo cambiamento
comporta, secondo Guzzi, l'abbandono di tutte quelle resistenze che impediscono
all'uomo di aprirsi all'ascolto del messaggio cristiano: solo un ascolto
autenticamente rigenerante della parola di Dio, intesa come appello alla
rinascita innanzitutto personale, potrà consentire, secondo Guzzi, il
superamento della crisi individuale e storica in cui versa l'uomo
contemporaneo. La proposta teorica di Guzzi si concretizza, quindi,
specialmente a partire dal volume Darsi paceUn manuale di liberazione
interiore, in un vero e proprio cammino di autotrasformazione, a partire dalle
proprie difficoltà personali; un lavoro interiore di formazione e di
riflessione, che passa anche attraverso il linguaggio profetico e meditativo
dei maggiori poeti e dei testi religiosi, per raggiungere, attraverso un
percorso di rivelazione, la liberazione nel segno della pace. La teorizzazione
si pone perciò a servizio dei processi concreti di trasformazione interiore
proposti nei Gruppi Darsi-pace. Opere
Raccolte di poesia Anima in vetrina, 1977 Il Giorno, Scheiwiller, 1988 Teatro
Cattolico, Jaca Book, 1991 Figure dell'ira e dell'indulgenza, Jaca Book, 1997
Preparativi alla vita terrena, Passigli,2002 Nella mia storia Dio, Passigli,
2005 Parole per nascere, Edizioni Paoline,
Saggi di filosofia e di religione La Svolta, Jaca Book 1987
Rivolgimenti, Marietti 1990 L'Uomo Nascente, Red, 1997 Passaggi di millennio,
Edizioni Paoline, 1998 L'Ordine del Giorno, Edizioni Paoline, 1999 Cristo e la
nuova era, Edizioni Paoline, 2000 La profezia dei poeti, Moretti e Vitali, 2002
Darsi pace, Edizioni Paoline, 2004 La nuova umanità, Edizioni Paoline, 2005 Per
donarsi, Edizioni Paoline, 2007 Yoga e preghiera cristiana, Edizioni Paoline,
2009 Dalla fine all'inizio, Edizioni Paoline,
Dodici parole per ricominciare, Ancora
Il cuore a nudo, Edizioni Paoline,
Buone Notizie, Ed. Messaggero
Imparare ad amare, Edizioni Paoline
L'Insurrezione dell'umanità nascente, Edizioni Paoline, Fede e Rivoluzione, Edizioni Paoline FacebookIl profilo dell'Uomo di Dio, Edizioni
Paoline Alla ricerca del continente
della gioia, Edizioni Paoline Dizionario
della lingua inauditaLingua e Rivoluzione, Edizioni Paoline Altri progetti Collabora a Wikimedia Commons
Wikimedia Commons contiene immagini o altri file su Marco Guzzi Il sito ufficiale di Marco Guzzi, su marcoguzzi.it.
Il sito ufficiale dei Gruppi Darsi pace, su darsipace.it. Blog, su
vinonuovo.it.
Guzzo: Grice: “I admire Guzzo;
he founded ‘Filosofia,’ a philosophy magazine and led a school at Torino, but
he selected ‘pagine di filosofi per i giovani italiani.’ He wrote interesting
essays on “Gli hegeliani d’Italia” and Croce versus Gentile – a very systematic
philosopher. The logo of his revista shows Oedipus and thes sphynx – that says
it all!” -- Augusto
Guzzo (Napoli), filosofo. Si laureò
all'Napoli nel 1915, dove fu allievo del neohegeliano Sebastiano Maturi. Dal
1924 al 1932 insegnò filosofia e storia della filosofia alla facoltà di
magistero dell'Torino, fondando la rivista "Erma", e dal 1932 al 1934
filosofia morale presso l'Pisa, dove fu anche direttore del seminario di
filosofia della Scuola normale superiore. Nel 1934 tornò a Torino, dove insegnò
prima filosofia morale (succedendo a Erminio Juvalta) e poi, dal 1939 al 1964,
filosofia teoretica (succedendo ad Annibale Pastore). Fondò, insieme con Nicola
Abbagnano, la sezione piemontese dell'Istituto Italiano per gli Studi
filosofici. Ebbe fra i suoi allievi
Luigi Pareyson, Francesco Barone e Valerio Verra. Fu presidente dell'Accademia delle Scienze di
Torino dal 17 giugno 1970 al 25 giugno 1973, anno in cui gli subentrò Francesco
Giacomo Tricomi. Nel 1955 l'Accademia
dei Lincei gli conferì il Premio Feltrinelli per la Filosofia. Morì a Torino il 23 agosto 1986. È sepolto
nel Cimitero monumentale di Torino.
Pensiero Esponente dell'idealismo italiano, si avvicinò all'attualismo
di Giovanni Gentile, interpretato però in chiave di conciliazione con il
pensiero cattolico. È considerato quindi uno dei più grandi esponenti dello
spiritualismo italiano. Opere principali
Il pensiero di Spinoza, 1924 Kant precritico, 1924 Verità e realtà. Apologia
dell'idealismo, 1925 Idealisti ed empiristi, 1935 Agostino e Tommaso, 1958
Giordano Bruno, 1960 Vita di Cordelia Guzzo, 1974 Storia della filosofia e
della civiltà per saggi, 1975 L'uomo, Brescia, Morcelliana; poi Torino,
Edizioni di filosofia, 1947-1964. Comprende: 1. L'io e la ragione, 1947 2. La
moralità, 1950 3. La scienza, 1955 4. L'arte, 1962 5. La religione, 1964 6. La
filosofia, 1964 Con la collaborazione di sua moglie Cordelia Capone, anche lei
filosofa, tradusse in italiano The Idea of Christ in the Gospels or God in Man
di George Santayana, opera di cui pubblicò una recensione nel Giornale di
metafisica, IV, 4 (15 luglio 1949). Pubblicò nel 1963 anche un Alcifrone di
George Berkeley a cura sua e della moglie Cordelia. Pubblicò a partire dal 1950
la rivista "Filosofia", alla quale aggiunse nel 1959 un fascicolo
internazionale, che nel 1969 divenne "Studi internazionali di
filosofia". Nella stessa rivista, in un fascicolo speciale del 1974,
pubblicò una "Vita di Cordelia Guzzo", biografia della moglie, ricca
di aneddoti sulla vita privata e l'attività scientifica dell'autore. Note
Presidenti Archiviato il 22 aprile 2009 in . dell'Accademia delle
Scienze di Torino. Premi Feltrinelli
1950-, su lincei.it. 17 novembre .
Pietro Fernando Quarta, Augusto Guzzo e la sua scuola, Urbino, Argalìa,
1976. Google Libri Piergiorgio Donatelli, «GUZZO, Augusto» in Dizionario
Biografico degli Italiani, Volume 61, Roma, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia
Italiana, 2004. Giletta Giovanni, Filosofia hegeliana e religione. Osservazioni
su Sebastiano Maturi, Ed.Natan, Benevento, . Altri progetti Collabora a
Wikisource Wikisource contiene una pagina dedicata a Augusto Guzzo Augusto Guzzo, su Treccani.itEnciclopedie on
line, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana.
Augusto Guzzo / Augusto Guzzo (altra versione), in Enciclopedia
Italiana, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana.
Augusto Guzzo, in Dizionario biografico degli italiani, Istituto
dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Augusto
Guzzo, su BeWeb, Conferenza Episcopale Italiana. Opere di Augusto Guzzo, su openMLOL, Horizons
Unlimited srl. Opere di Augusto Guzzo, .
Filosofia, Rivista annuale fondata nel 1950 da Augusto Guzzo. 14
febbraio.
habitus:
hexis
Grecian, from hexo, ‘to have’, ‘to be disposed’, a good or bad condition,
disposition, or state. The traditional rendering, ‘habit’ Latin habitus, is
misleading, for it tends to suggest the idea of an involuntary and merely
repetitious pattern of behavior. A hexis is rather a state of character or of
mind that disposes us to deliberately choose to act or to think in a certain
way. The term acquired a quasi-technical status after Aristotle advanced the
view that hexis is the genus of virtue, both moral and intellectual. In the
Nicomachean Ethics he distinguishes hexeis from passions pathe and faculties
dunamis of the soul. If a man fighting in the front ranks feels afraid when he
sees the enemy approaching, he is undergoing an involuntary passion. His
capacity to be affected by fear on this or other occasions is part of his
makeup, one of his faculties. If he chooses to stay where his commanders placed
him, this is due to the hexis or state of character we call courage. Likewise,
one who is consistently good at identifying what is best for oneself can be
said to possess a hexis called prudence. Not all states and dispositions are
commendable. Cowardice and stupidity are also hexeis. Both in the sense of
‘state’ and of ‘possession’ hexis plays a role in Aristotle’s Categories.
Halesianism: from Alexander
of Halesowen, Salop (on the border with Worcs.).. Grice called William of Occam
“Occam,” William of Sherwood, “Shyrewood,” and Alexander of Hales “Hales,”why,
I wish people would call me “Harborne,” and not Grice!”Grice. English
Franciscan theologian, known as the Doctor Irrefragabilis. The first to teach
theology by lecturing on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, Alexander’s emphasis
on speculative theology initiated the golden age of Scholasticism. Alexander
wrote commentaries on the Psalms and the Gospels; his chief works include his
Glossa in quattuor libros sententiarum, Quaestiones disputatatae antequam esset
frater, and Quaestiones quodlibetales. Alexander did not complete the Summa
fratris Alexandri; Pope Alexander IV ordered the Franciscans to complete the
Summa Halesiana in 1255. Master of theology in 1222, Alexander played an
important role in the history of Paris, writing parts of Gregory IX’s Parens
scientiarum 1231. He also helped negotiate the peace between England and
France. He gave up his position as canon of Lichfield and archdeacon of
Coventry to become a Franciscan, the first Franciscan master of theology; his
was the original Franciscan chair of theology at Paris. Among the Franciscans,
his most prominent disciples include St. Bonaventure, Richard Rufus of
Cornwall, and John of La Rochelle, to whom he resigned his chair in theology
near the end of his life. Hales wrote commentaries on Aristotle’s metaphysics,
on the multiplicity of being, that Grice found fascinating. Vide “Summa halensis.”
hampshireism: His second wife was from the New World. His first wife
wasn’t. He married Renée Orde-Lees, the daughter of the very English Thomas
Orde-Lees, in 1961, and had two children, a son, Julian, and a daughter. To add
to the philosophers’ mistakes. There’s Austin (in “Plea for Excuses” and “Other
Minds”), Strawson (in “Truth” and “Introduction to Logical Theory,” and “On
referring”), Hart (in conversation, on ‘carefully,”), Hare (“To say ‘x is good’
is to recommend x”) and Hampshire (“Intention and certainty”). For Grice, the
certainty is merely implicated and on occasion, only. Cited by Grice as a member of the play group.
Hampshire would dine once a week with Grice. He would discuss and find very
amusing to discuss with Grice on post-war Oxford philosophy. Unlike Grice,
Hampshire attended Austin’s Thursday evening meetings at All Souls. Grice wrote
“Intention and uncertainty” in part as a response to Hampshire and Hart,
Intention and certainty. But Grice brought the issue back to an earlier
generation, to a polemic between Stout (who held a certainty-based view) and
Prichard.
hareism r. m. cited by H.
P. Grice, “Hare’s neustrics”. b.9, English philosopher who is one of the most
influential moral philosophers of the twentieth century and the developer of
prescriptivism in metaethics. Hare was educated at Rugby and Oxford, then
served in the British army during World War II and spent years as a prisoner of
war in Burma. In 7 he took a position at Balliol and was appointed White’s Professor of Moral
Philosophy at the of Oxford in 6. On
retirement from Oxford, he became Graduate Research Professor at the of Florida 393. His major books are Language
of Morals 3, Freedom and Reason 3, Moral Thinking 1, and Sorting Out Ethics 7.
Many collections of his essays have also appeared, and a collection of other
leading philosophers’ articles on his work was published in 8 Hare and Critics,
eds. Seanor and Fotion. According to Hare, a careful exploration of the nature
of our moral concepts reveals that nonironic judgments about what one morally
ought to do are expressions of the will, or commitments to act, that are
subject to certain logical constraints. Because moral judgments are
prescriptive, we cannot sincerely subscribe to them while refusing to comply
with them in the relevant circumstances. Because moral judgments are universal
prescriptions, we cannot sincerely subscribe to them unless we are willing for
them to be followed were we in other people’s positions with their preferences.
Hare later contended that vividly to imagine ourselves completely in other
people’s positions involves our acquiring preferences about what should happen
to us in those positions that mirror exactly what those people now want for
themselves. So, ideally, we decide on a universal prescription on the basis of
not only our existing preferences about the actual situation but also the new
preferences we would have if we were wholly in other people’s positions. What
we can prescribe universally is what maximizes net satisfaction of this
amalgamated set of preferences. Hence, Hare concluded that his theory of moral
judgment leads to preference-satisfaction act utilitarianism. However, like
most other utilitarians, he argued that the best way to maximize utility is to
have, and generally to act on, certain not directly utilitarian
dispositions such as dispositions not to
hurt others or steal, to keep promises and tell the truth, to take special
responsibility for one’s own family, and so on. Then there’s Hare’s
phrastic: It is convenient to take Grice mocking Hare in Prolegomena. “To say
‘x is good’ is to recommend x.’ An implicaturum: annullable: “x is good but I don’t recommend it.” Hare
was well aware of the implicaturum. Loving Grice’s account of ‘or,’ Hare gives
the example: “Post the letter: therefore; post the letter or burn it.” Grice
mainly quotes Hare’s duet, the phrastic and the neustic, and spends some time
exploring what the phrastic actually is. He seems to prefer ‘radix.’ But then
Hare also has then the ‘neustic,’ that Grice is not so concerned with since he
has his own terminology for it. And for Urmson’s festschrift, Hare comes up
with the tropic and the clistic. So each has a Griceian correlate. Then there’s Hareian supervenience: a dependence
relation between properties or facts of one type, and properties or facts of
another type. In the other place, G. E. Moore, for instance, holds that the
property intrinsic value is dependent in the relevant way on certain non-moral
properties. Moore did not employ the expression ‘supervenience’. As Moore puts
it, “if a given thing possesses any kind of intrinsic value in a certain
degree, not only must that same thing
possess it, under all circumstances, in the same degree, but also anything exactly
like it, must, under all circumstances, possess it in exactly the same degree”
(Philosophical Studies, 2). The concept of supervenience, as a relation between
properties, is essentially this: A poperties of type A is supervenient (or
better, as Grice prefesrs, supervenes) on a property of type B if and only if
two objects cannot differ with respect to their A-properties without also
differing with respect to their B-properties. Properties that allegedly are
supervenient on others are often called consequential properties, especially in
ethics; the idea is that if something instantiates a moral property, then it
does so in virtue of, i.e., as a non-causal consequence of, instantiating some
lower-level property on which the moral property supervenes. In another,
related sense, supervenience is a feature of discourse of one type, vis-à-vis
discourse of another type. ‘Supervenience’ is so used by Hare. “First, let us
take that characteristic of “good” which has been called its ‘supervenience.’”
Grice: “Hare has a good ear for the neologism: he loved my ‘implicature,’ and
used in an essay he submitted to “Mind,” way before I ventured to publish the
thing!”“Suppose that we say, “St. Francis is a good man.” It is logically
impossible to say this and to maintain at the same time that there might have
been another man placed exactly in the same circumstances as St. Francis, and
who behaved in exactly the same way, but who differed from St. Francis in this
respect only, that it is NOT the case that this man is a good man.” (“The
Language of Morals”). Here the idea is that it would be a misuse of moral
language, a violation of the “logic of moral discourse,” to apply ‘good’ to one
thing but not to something else exactly similar in all pertinent non-moral
respects. Hare is a meta-ethical irrealist. He denies that there are moral
properties or facts. So for him, supervenience is a ‘category of expression,’ a
feature of discourse and judgment, not a relation between properties or facts
of two types. The notion of supervenience has come to be used quite widely in
metaphysics and philosophical philosophy, usually in the way explained above.
This use is heralded by Davidson in articulating a position about the relation
between a physical property and a property of the ‘soul,’ or statet-ypes, that
eschews the reducibility of mental properties to physical ones. “Although the
position I describe denies there are psycho-physical laws, it is consistent
with the view that mental characteristics are in some sense dependent, or supervenient,
or plainly supervene on physical characteristics. Such supervenience might be
taken to mean that there cannot be two events alike in all physical respects
but differing in some mental respects, or that an object cannot alter in some
mental respects without altering in some physical respects. Dependence or
supervenience of this kind does not entail reducibility through law or
definition. “Mental Events.” A variety of supervenience theses have been
propounded in metaphysics and philosophical psychology, usually although not
always in conjunction with attempts to formulate metaphysical positions that
are naturalistic, in some way, without being strongly reductionistic, if
reductive. E. g. it is often asserted that mental properties and facts are
supervenient on neurobiological properties, and/or on physicochemical
properties and facts. And it is often claimed, more generally, that all
properties and facts are supervenient on the properties and facts of the kind
described by physics. Much attention has been directed at how to formulate the
desired supervenience theses, and thus how to characterize supervenience
itself. A distinction has been drawn between weak supervenience, asserting that
in any single possible world w, any two individuals in w that differ in their
A-properties also differ in their B-properties; and strong supervenience,
asserting that for any two individuals i and j, either within a single possible
world or in two distinct ones, if i and j differ in A-properties then they also
differ in Bproperties. It is sometimes alleged that traditional formulations of
supervenience, like Moore’s or Hare’s, articulate only weak supervenience,
whereas strong supervenience is needed to express the relevant kind of
determination or dependence. It is sometimes replied, however, that the
traditional natural-language formulations do in fact express strong
supervenience and that formalizations
expressing mere weak supervenience are mistranslations. Questions about how best
to formulate supervenience theses also arise in connection with intrinsic and
non-intrinsic properties. For instance, the property being a bank, instantiated
by the brick building on Main Street, is not supervenient on intrinsic physical
properties of the building itself; rather, the building’s having this
social-institutional property depends on a considerably broader range of facts
and features, some of which are involved in subserving the social practice of
banking. The term ‘supervenience base’ is frequently used to denote the range
of entities and happenings whose lowerlevel properties and relations jointly
underlie the instantiation of some higher-level property like being a bank by
some individual like the brick building on Main Street. Supervenience theses
are sometimes formulated so as to smoothly accommodate properties and facts
with broad supervenience bases. For instance, the idea that the physical facts
determine all the facts is sometimes expressed as global supervenience, which
asserts that any two physically possible worlds differing in some respect also
differ in some physical respect. Or, sometimes this idea is expressed as the
stronger thesis of regional supervenience, which asserts that for any two
spatiotemporal regions r and s, either within a single physically possible world
or in two distinct ones, if r and s differ in some intrinsic respect then they
also differ in some intrinsic physical respect. H. P. Grice, “Hare on
supervenience.” H. P. Grice, “Supervenience in my method in philosophical
psychology: from the banal to the bizarre.” H. P. Grice, “Supervenience and the
devil of scientism.”
Harrisianism: philosopher of languageclassical. Grice adored him,
and he was quite happy that few knew about Harris! Cf. Tooke. Cf. Priestley and
Hartleyall pre-Griceian philosohers of language that are somehow outside the
canon, when they shouldn’t. They are very Old World, and it’s the influence of
the New World that has made them sort of disappear! That’s what Grice said!
Hartianism: h. l.
a.cited by Grice, “Hare on ‘carefully.’ Philosopher of European ancestry born
in Yorkshire, principally responsible for the revival of legal and political
philosophy after World War II. After wartime work with military intelligence,
Hart gave up a flourishing law practice to join the Oxford faculty, where he
was a brilliant lecturer, a sympathetic and insightful critic, and a generous
mentor to many scholars. Like the earlier “legal positivists” Bentham and John
Austin, Hart accepted the “separation of law and morals”: moral standards can
deliberately be incorporated in law, but there is no automatic or necessary
connection between law and sound moral principles. In The Concept of Law 1 he
critiqued the Bentham-Austin notion that laws are orders backed by threats from
a political community’s “sovereign” some
person or persons who enjoy habitual obedience and are habitually obedient to
no other human and developed the more
complex idea that law is a “union of primary and secondary rules.” Hart agreed
that a legal system must contain some “obligation-imposing” “primary” rules,
restricting freedom. But he showed that law also includes independent
“power-conferring” rules that facilitate choice, and he demonstrated that a
legal system requires “secondary” rules that create public offices and
authorize official action, such as legislation and adjudication, as well as
“rules of recognition” that determine which other rules are valid in the
system. Hart held that rules of law are “open-textured,” with a core of
determinate meaning and a fringe of indeterminate meaning, and thus capable of
answering some but not all legal questions that can arise. He doubted courts’
claims to discover law’s meaning when reasonable competing interpretations are
available, and held that courts decide such “hard cases” by first performing
the important “legislative” function of filling gaps in the law. Hart’s first
book was an influential study with A. M. Honoré of Causation in the Law 9. His
inaugural lecture as Professor of Jurisprudence, “Definition and Theory in
Jurisprudence” 3, initiated a career-long study of rights, reflected also in
Essays on Bentham: Studies in Jurisprudence and Political Theory 2 and in
Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy 3. He defended liberal public policies.
In Law, Liberty and Morality 3 he refuted Lord Devlin’s contention that a
society justifiably enforces the code of its moral majority, whatever it might
be. In The Morality of the Criminal Law 5 and in Punishment and Responsibility
8, Hart contributed substantially to both analytic and normative theories of
crime and punishment.
Hartleyianism: British philosopher.
Although the notion of association of ideas is ancient, he is generally
regarded as the founder of associationism as a self-sufficient psychology.
Despite similarities between his association psychology and Hume’s, Hartley
developed his system independently, acknowledging only the writings of
clergyman John Gay 1699 1745. Hartley was one of many Enlightenment thinkers
aspiring to be “Newtons of the mind,” in Peter Gay’s phrase. In Hartley, this
took the form of uniting association philosophy with physiology, a project
later brought to fruition by Bain. His major work, Observations on Man 1749,
pictured mental events and neural events as operating on parallel tracks in
which neural events cause mental events. On the mental side, Hartley
distinguished like Hume between sensation and idea. On the physiological side,
Hartley adopted Newton’s conception of nervous transmission by vibrations of a
fine granular substance within nerve-tubes. Vibrations within sensory nerves
peripheral to the brain corresponded to the sensations they caused, while small
vibrations in the brain, vibratiuncles, corresponded to ideas. Hartley proposed
a single law of association, contiguity modified by frequency, which took two
forms, one for the mental side and one for the neural: ideas, or vibratiuncles,
occurring together regularly become associated. Hartley distinguished between
simultaneous association, the link between ideas that occur at the same
harmony, preestablished Hartley, David 362
AM 362 moment, and successive
association, between ideas that closely succeed one another. Successive
associations occur only in a forward direction; there are no backward
associations, a thesis generating much controversy in the later experimental
study of memory. Hartleyianism: Josephphilosopher. Hartmann: philosopher who
sought to synthesize the thought of Schelling, Hegel, and Schopenhauer. The
most important of his essays is “Philosophie des Unbewussten.” For Hartmann both
will and idea are interrelated and are expressions of an absolute
“thing-in-itself,” the unconscious. The unconscious is the active essence in
natural and psychic processes and is the teleological dynamic in organic life.
Paradoxically, he claimed that the teleology immanent in the world order and
the life process leads to insight into the irrationality of the “will-to-live.”
The maturation of rational consciousness would, he held, lead to the negation
of the total volitional process and the entire world process would cease. Ideas
indicate the “what” of existence and constitute, along with will and the
unconscious, the three modes of being. Despite its pessimism, this work enjoyed
considerable popularity. Hartmann was an unusual combination of speculative
idealist and philosopher of science defending vitalism and attacking
mechanistic materialism; his pessimistic ethics was part of a cosmic drama of
redemption. Some of his later works dealt with a critical form of Darwinism
that led him to adopt a positive evolutionary stance that undermined his
earlier pessimism. His general philosophical position was selfdescribed as
“transcendental realism.” His Philosophy of the Unconscious was tr. into
English by W. C. Coupland in three volumes in 4. There is little doubt that his
metaphysics of the unconscious prepared the way for Freud’s later theory of the
unconscious mind.
hazzing: under conjunctum, we see that the terminology is varied.
There is the copulatum. But Grice prefers to restrict to use of the copulatum
to izzing and hazzing. Oddly Grice sees hazzing as a predicate which he
formalizes as Hxy. To be read x hazzes y, although sometimes he uses ‘x hazz
y.’ Vide ‘accidentia.’ For Grice the role of métier is basic since it shows
finality in nature. Homo sapiens, qua pirot, is to be rational.
Heno-theism, allegiance to one supreme
deity while conceding existence to others; also described as monolatry,
incipient monotheism, or practical monotheism. It occupies a middle ground
between polytheism and radical monotheism, which denies reality to all gods
save one. It has been claimed that early Judaism passed through a henotheistic
phase, acknowledging other Middle Eastern deities albeit condemning their
worship, en route to exclusive recognition of Yahweh. But the concept of
progress from polytheism through henotheism to monotheism is a rationalizing
construct, and cannot be supposed to capture the complex development of any
historical religion, including that of ancient Israel.
hermetism, also hermeticism, a philosophical
theology whose basic impulse was the gnostic conviction that human salvation
depends on revealed knowledge gnosis of God and of the human and natural
creations. Texts ascribed to Hermes Trismegistus, a Greco-Egyptian version of
the Egyptian god Thoth, may have appeared as early as the fourth century B.C.,
but the surviving Corpus Hermeticum in Grecian and Latin is a product of the
second and third centuries A.D. Fragments of the same literature exist in
Grecian, Armenian, and Coptic as well; the Coptic versions are part of a
discovery made at Nag Hammadi after World War II. All these Hermetica record
hermetism as just described. Other Hermetica traceable to the same period but
surviving in later Arabic or Latin versions deal with astrology, alchemy,
magic, and other kinds of occultism. Lactantius, Augustine, and other early
Christians cited Hermes but disagreed on his value; before Iamblichus, pagan
philosophers showed little interest. Muslims connected Hermes with a Koranic
figure, Idris, and thereby enlarged the medieval hermetic tradition, which had
its first large effects in the Latin West among the twelfth-century Platonists
of Chartres. The only ancient hermetic text then available in the West was the
Latin Asclepius, but in 1463 Ficino interrupted his epochal translation of
Plato to Latinize fourteen of the seventeen Grecian discourses in the main body
of the Corpus Hermeticum as distinct from the many Grecian fragments preserved
by Stobaeus but unknown to Ficino. Ficino was willing to move so quickly to
Hermes because he believed that this Egyptian deity stood at the head of the
“ancient theology” prisca theologia, a tradition of pagan revelation that ran
parallel to Christian scripture, culminated with Plato, and continued through
Plotinus and the later Neoplatonists. Ficino’s Hermes translation, which he
called the Pimander, shows no interest in the magic and astrology about which
he theorized later in his career. Trinitarian theology was his original
motivation. The Pimander was enormously influential in the later Renaissance,
when Giovanni Pico della Mirandola, Lodovico Lazzarelli, Jacques Lefèvre
d’Etaples, Symphorien Champier, Francesco Giorgi, Agostino Steuco, Francesco
Patrizi, and others enriched Western appreciation of Hermes. The first printed
Grecian Hermetica was the 1554 edition of Adrien Turnebus. The last before the
nineteenth century appeared in 1630, a textual hiatus that reflected a decline
in the reputation of Hermes after Isaac Casaubon proved philologically in 1614
that the Grecian Hermetica had to be post-Christian, not the remains of
primeval Egyptian wisdom. After Casaubon, hermetic ideas fell out of fashion
with most Western philosophers of the current canon, but the historiography of
the ancient theology remained influential for Newton and for lesser figures
even later. The content of the Hermetica was out of tune with the new science,
so Casaubon’s redating left Hermes to the theosophical heirs of Robert Fludd,
whose opponents Kepler, Mersenne, Gassendi turned away from the Hermetica and
similar fascinations of Renaissance humanist culture. By the nineteenth
century, only theosophists took Hermes seriously as a prophet of pagan wisdom,
but he was then rediscovered by G. students of Christianity and Hellenistic
religions, especially Richard Reitzenstein, who published his Poimandres in 4.
The ancient Hermetica are now read in the 654 edition of A. D. Nock and A. J.
Festugière.
heuristics, a rule or
solution adopted to reduce the complexity of computational tasks, thereby
reducing demands on resources such as time, memory, and attention. If an
algorithm is a procedure yielding a correct solution to a problem, then a
heuristic procedure may not reach a solution even if there is one, or may
provide an incorrect answer. The reliability of heuristics varies between
domains; the resulting biases are predictable, and provide information about
system design. Chess, for example, is a finite game with a finite number of
possible positions, but there is no known algorithm for finding the optimal
move. Computers and humans both employ heuristics in evaluating intermediate
moves, relying on a few significant cues to game quality, such as safety of the
king, material balance, and center control. The use of these criteria
simplifies the problem, making it computationally tractable. They are heuristic
guides, reliable but limited in success. There is no guarantee that the result
will be the best move or even good. They are nonetheless satisfactory for
competent chess. Work on human judgment indicates a similar moral. Examples of
judgmental infelicities support the view that human reasoning systematically
violates standards for statistical reasoning, ignoring base rates, sample size,
and correlations. Experimental results suggest that humans utilize judgmental
heuristics in gauging probabilities, such as representativeness, or the degree
to which an individual or event resembles a prototypical member of a category.
Such heuristics produce reasonable judgments in many cases, but are of limited
validity when measured by a Bayesian standard. Judgmental heuristics are biased
and subject to systemic errors. Experimental support for the importance of
these heuristics depends on cases in which subjects deviate from the normative
standard.
hierarchy, a division of mathematical
objects into subclasses in accordance with an ordering that reflects their
complexity. Around the turn of the century, analysts interested in the
“descriptive set theory” of the real numbers defined and studied two systems of
classification for sets of reals, the Borel (due to Emil Borel) and the G
hierarchies. In the 1940s, logicians interested in recursion and definability
(most importantly, Stephen Kleene) introduced and studied other hierarchies
(the arithmetic, the hyperarithmetic, and the analytical hierarchies) of reals
(identified with sets of natural numbers) and of sets of reals; the relations
between this work and the earlier work were made explicit in the 1950s by J.
Addison. Other sorts of hierarchies have been introduced in other corners of
logic. All these so-called hierarchies have at least this in common: they
divide a class of mathematical objects into subclasses subject to a natural
well-founded ordering (e.g., by subsethood) that reflects the complexity (in a
sense specific to the hierarchy under consideration) of the objects they
contain. What follows describes several hierarchies from the study of
definability. (For more historical and mathematical information see Descriptive
Set Theory by Y. Moschovakis, North-Holland Publishing Co., 1980.) (1)
Hierarchies of formulas. Consider a formal language L with quantifiers ‘E’ and
‘D’. Given a set B of formulas in L, we inductively define a hierarchy that
treats the members of B as “basic.” Set P0 % S0 % B. Suppose sets Pn and Sn of
formulas have been defined. Let Pn!1 % the set of all formulas of the form Q1u1
. . . Qmumw when u1, . . . , um are distinct variables, Q1, . . . , Qm are all
‘E’, m M 1, and w 1 Sn. Let Sn+1 % the set of all formulas of that form for Q1,
. . . , Qm all ‘D’, and w 1 Pn. Here are two such hierarchies for languages of
arithmetic. Take the logical constants to be truthfunctions, ‘E’ and ‘D’. (i)
Let L0 % the first-order language of arithmetic, based on ‘%’, a two-place
predicate-constant ‘‹’, an individual-constant for 0, functionconstants for
successor, addition, and multiplication; ‘first-order’ means that bound
variables are all first-order (ranging over individuals); we’ll allow free
second-order variables (ranging over properties or sets of individuals). Let B
% the set of bounded formulas, i.e. those formed from atomic formulas using
connectives and bounded quantification: if w is bounded so are Eu(u ‹ t / w)
and Du(u ‹ t & w). (ii) Let L1 % the second-order language of arithmetic (formed
from L0 by allowing bound second-order variables); let B % the set of formulas
in which no second-order variable is bound, and take all u1, . . . , um as
above to be second-order variables. (2) Hierarchies of definable sets. (i) The
Arithmetic Hierarchy. For a set of natural numbers (call such a thing ‘a real’)
A : A 1 P0 n [ or S0 n ] if and only if A is defined over the standard model of
arithmetic (i.e., with the constant for 0 assigned to 0, etc., and with the
first-order variables ranging over the natural numbers) by a formula of L0 in
Pn [respectively Sn] as described in (1.i). Set D0 n % P0 n Thus: In fact, all
these inclusions are proper. This hierarchy classifies the reals simple enough
to be defined by arithmetic formulas. Example: ‘Dy x % y ! y’ defines the set
even of even natural numbers; the formula 1 S1, so even 1 S0 1; even is also
defined by a formula in P1; so even 1 P0 1, giving even 1 D0 1. In fact, S0 1 %
the class of recursively enumerable reals, and D0 1 % the class of recursive
reals. The classification of reals under the arithmetic hierarchy reflects
complexity of defining formulas; it differs from classification in terms of a
notion of degree of unsolvability, that reflecting a notion of comparative
computational complexity; but there are connections between these
classifications. The Arithmetic Hierarchy extends to sets of reals (using a
free second-order variable in defining sentences). Example: ‘Dx (Xx & Dy y
% x ! x)’ 1 S1 and defines the set of those reals with an even number; so that
set 1 S0 1.The Analytical Hierarchy. Given a real A : A 1 P1 n [S1 1] if and
only if A is defined (over the standard model of arithmetic with second-order
variables ranging over all sets of natural numbers) by a formula of L1 in Pn
(respectively Sn) as described in (1.ii); D1 n % P1 n 3 S1 n. Similarly for a
set of reals. The inclusions pictured above carry over, replacing superscripted
0’s by 1’s. This classifies all reals and sets of reals simple enough to have
analytical (i.e., second-order arithmetic) definitions.The subscripted ‘n’ in
‘P0 n’, etc., ranged over natural numbers. But the Arithmetic Hierarchy is
extended “upward” into the transfinite by the ramified-analytical hierarchy.
Let R0 % the class of all arithmetical reals. For an ordinal a let Ra!1 % the
class of all sets of reals definable by formulas of L1 in which second-order
variables range only over reals in Rathis constraint imposes ramification. For
a limit-ordinal l, let Rl % UaThe above hierarchies arise in arithmetic.
Similar hierarchies arise in pure set theory; e.g. by transferring the
“process” that produced the ramified analytical hierarchy to pure set theory we
obtain the constructible hierarchy, defined by Gödel in his 1939 monograph on
the continuum hypothesis.
Historia -- historicism, the doctrine that
knowledge of human affairs has an irreducibly historical character and that
there can be no ahistorical perspective for an understanding of human nature
and society. What is needed instead is a philosophical explication of historical
knowledge that will yield the rationale for all sound knowledge of human
activities. So construed, historicism is a philosophical doctrine originating
in the methodological and epistemological presuppositions of critical
historiography. In the mid-nineteenth century certain German thinkers (Dilthey
most centrally), reacting against positivist ideals of science and knowledge,
rejected scientistic models of knowledge, replacing them with historical ones.
They applied this not only to the discipline of history but to economics, law,
political theory, and large areas of philosophy. Initially concerned with
methodological issues in particular disciplines, historicism, as it developed,
sought to work out a common philosophical doctrine that would inform all these
disciplines. What is essential to achieve knowledge in the human sciences is to
employ the ways of understanding used in historical studies. There should in
the human sciences be no search for natural laws; knowledge there will be
interpretive and rooted in concrete historical occurrences. As such it will be
inescapably perspectival and contextual (contextualism). This raises the issue
of whether historicism is a form of historical relativism. Historicism appears
to be committed to the thesis that what for a given people is warrantedly
assertible is determined by the distinctive historical perspective in which
they view life and society. The stress on uniqueness and concrete specificity
and the rejection of any appeal to universal laws of human development
reinforce that. But the emphasis on cumulative development into larger contexts
of our historical knowledge puts in doubt an identification of historicism and
historical relativism. The above account of historicism is that of its main
proponents: Meinecke, Croce, Collingwood, Ortega y Gasset, and Mannheim. But in
the twentieth century, with Popper and Hayek, a very different conception of
historicism gained some currency. For them, to be a historicist is to believe
that there are “historical laws,” indeed even a “law of historical
development,” such that history has a pattern and even an end, that it is the
central task of social science to discover it, and that these laws should
determine the direction of political action and social policy. They attributed
(incorrectly) this doctrine to Marx but rightly denounced it as pseudo-science.
However, some later Marxists (Lukács, Korsch, and Gramsci) were historicists in
the original nonPopperian sense as was the critical theorist Adorno and hermeneuticists
such as Gadamer.
Homeo-logical, hetero-logical: Grice and Thomson go heterological. Grice was
fascinated by Baron Russell’s remarks on heterological and its implicate. Grice
is particularly interested in Russell’s philosophy because of the usual Oxonian
antipathy towards his type of philosophising. Being an irreverent
conservative rationalist, Grice found in Russell a good point for
dissent! If paradoxes were always sets of propositions or arguments or
conclusions, they would always be meaningful. But some paradoxes are
semantically flawed and some have answers that are backed by a pseudo-argument
employing a defective lemma that lacks a truth-value. Grellings paradox,
for instance, opens with a distinction between autological and heterological
words. An autological word describes itself, e.g., polysyllabic is
polysllabic, English is English, noun is a noun, etc. A heterological word
does not describe itself, e.g., monosyllabic is not monosyllabic, Chinese is
not Chinese, verb is not a verb, etc. Now for the riddle: Is
heterological heterological or autological? If heterological is
heterological, since it describes itself, it is autological. But if
heterological is autological, since it is a word that does not describe itself,
it is heterological. The common solution to this puzzle is that
heterological, as defined by Grelling, is not what Grice a genuine
predicate ‒ Gricing is!In other words, Is heterological
heterological? is without meaning. That does not mean that an utterer, such as
Baron Russell, may implicate that he is being very witty by uttering the
Grelling paradox! There can be no predicate that applies to all and only those
predicates it does not apply to for the same reason that there can be no barber
who shaves all and only those people who do not shave themselves. Grice
seems to be relying on his friend at Christ Church, Thomson in On Some
Paradoxes, in the same volume where Grice published his Remarks about the
senses, Analytical Philosophy, Butler (ed.), Blackwell, Oxford, 104–119. Grice
thought that Thomson was a genius, if ever there is one! Plus, Grice thought
that, after St. Johns, Christ Church was the second most beautiful venue in the
city of dreaming spires. On top, it is what makes Oxford a city, and not, as
villagers call it, a town. Refs.: the main source is Grice’s essay on
‘heterologicality,’ but the keyword ‘paradox’ is useful, too, especially as
applied to Grice’s own paradox and to what, after Moore, Grice refers to as the
philosopher’s paradoxes. The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC.
hobbesian
implicatura -- hobbes:
“Hobbes is a Griceian”Grice. Grice was a member of the Hobbes Society -- Thomas.
English philosopher whose writings, especially the English version of Leviathan
(1651), strongly influenced all of subsequent English moral and political
philosophy. He also wrote a trilogy comprising De Cive (1642; English version,
Philosophical Rudiments Concerning Government and Society, 1651), De Corpore
(On the Body, 1655), and De Homine (On Man, 1658). Together with Leviathan (the
revised Latin version of which was published in 1668), these are his major
philosophical works. However, an early draft of his thoughts, The Elements of
Law, Natural and Political(also known as Human Nature and De Corpore Politico),
was published without permission in 1650. Many of the misinterpretations of
Hobbes’s views on human nature come from mistaking this early work as
representing his mature views. Hobbes was influential not only in England, but
also on the Continent. He is the author of the third set of objections to
Descartes’s Meditations. Spinoza’s Tractatus Theologico-politicus was deeply
influenced by Hobbes, not only in its political views but also in the way it
dealt with Scripture. Hobbes was not merely a philosopher; he was mathematical
tutor to Charles II and also a classical scholar. His first published work was
a translation of Thucydides (1628), and among his latest, about a half-century
later, were translations of Homer’s Iliad and Odyssey. Hobbes’s philosophical
views have a remarkably contemporary sound. In metaphysics, he holds a strong
materialist view, sometimes viewing mental phenomena as epiphenomenal, but
later moving toward a reductive or eliminative view. In epistemology he held a
sophisticated empiricism, which emphasized the importance of language for
knowledge. If not the originator of the contemporary compatibilist view of the
relationship between free will and determinism (see The Questions Concerning
Liberty, Necessity and Chance, 1656), he was one of the primary influences. He
also was one of the most important philosophers of language, explicitly noting
that language is used not only to describe the world but to express attitudes
and, performatively, to make promises and contracts. One of Hobbes’s
outstanding characteristics is his intellectual honesty. Though he may have
been timid (he himself claims that he was, explaining that his mother gave
birth to him because of fright over the coming of the Spanish Armada), his
writing shows no trace of it. During more than half his long lifetime he
engaged in many philosophical controversies, which required considerably more
courage in Hobbes’s day than at present. Both the Roman Catholic church and
Oxford University banned the reading of his books and there was talk not only
of burning his books but of burning Hobbes himself. An adequate interpretation
of Hobbes requires careful attention to his accounts of human nature, reason,
morality, and law. Although he was not completely consistent, his moral and
political philosophy is remarkably coherent. His political theory is often
thought to require an egoistic psychology, whereas it actually requires only
that most persons be concerned with their own self-interest, especially their
own preservation. It does not require that most not be concerned with other
persons as well. All that Hobbes denies is an undifferentiated natural
benevolence: “For if by nature one man should love another (that is) as man,
there could no reason be returned why every man should not equally love every
man, as being equally man.” His argument is that limited benevolence is not an
adequate foundation upon which to build a state. Hobbes’s political theory does
not require the denial of limited benevolence, he indeed includes benevolence
in his list of the passions in Leviathan: “Desire of good to another,
BENEVOLENCE, GOOD WILL, CHARITY. If to man generally, GOOD NATURE.” Psychological
egoism not only denies benevolent action, it also denies action done from a
moral sense, i.e., action done because one believes it is the morally right
thing to do. But Hobbes denies neither kind of action. But when the words
[’just’ and ‘unjust’] are applied to persons, to be just signifies as much as
to be delighted in just dealing, to study how to do righteousness, or to
endeavor in all things to do that which is just; and to be unjust is to neglect
righteous dealing, or to think it is to be measured not according to my
contract, but some present benefit. Hobbes’s pessimism about the number of just
people is primarily due to his awareness of the strength of the passions and
his conviction that most people have not been properly educated and disciplined.
Hobbes is one of the few philosophers to realize that to talk of that part of
human nature which involves the passions is to talk about human populations. He
says, “though the wicked were fewer than the righteous, yet because we cannot
distinguish them, there is a necessity of suspecting, heeding, anticipating,
subjugating, self-defending, ever incident to the most honest and fairest
conditioned.” Though we may be aware of small communities in which mutual trust
and respect make law enforcement unnecessary, this is never the case when we
are dealing with a large group of people. Hobbes’s point is that if a large
group of people are to live together, there must be a common power set up to
enforce the rules of the society. That there is not now, nor has there ever
been, any large group of people living together without such a common power is
sufficient to establish his point. Often overlooked is Hobbes’s distinction
between people considered as if they were simply animals, not modified in any
way by education or discipline, and civilized people. Though obviously an
abstraction, people as animals are fairly well exemplified by children. “Unless
you give children all they ask for, they are peevish, and cry, aye and strike
their parents sometimes; and all this they have from nature.” In the state of
nature, people have no education or training, so there is “continual fear, and
danger of violent death, and the life of man, [is] solitary, poor, nasty,
brutish, and short.” But real people have been brought up in families; they
are, at least to some degree, civilized persons, and how they will behave
depends on how they are brought up. Hobbes does not say that society is a
collection of misfits and that this is why we have all the trouble that we doa
position congenial to the psychological egoist. But he does acknowledge that
“many also (perhaps most men) either through defect of mind, or want of
education, remain unfit during the whole course of their lives; yet have they,
infants as well as those of riper years, a human nature; wherefore man is made
fit for society not by nature, but by education.” Education and training may
change people so that they act out of genuine moral motives. That is why it is
one of the most important functions of the sovereign to provide for the proper
training and education of the citizens. In the current debate between nature
and nurture, on the question of behavior Hobbes would come down strongly on the
side of nurture. Hobbes’s concept of reason has more in common with the classical
philosophical tradition stemming from Plato and Aristotle, where reason sets
the ends of behavior, than with the modern tradition stemming from Hume where
the only function of reason is to discover the best means to ends set by the
passions. For Hobbes, reason is very complex; it has a goal, lasting
selfpreservation, and it seeks the way to this goal. It also discovers the
means to ends set by the passions, but it governs the passions, or tries to, so
that its own goal is not threatened. Since its goal is the same in all people,
it is the source of rules applying to all people. All of this is surprisingly
close to the generally accepted account of rationality. We generally agree that
those who follow their passions when they threaten their life are acting
irrationally. We also believe that everyone always ought to act rationally,
though we know that few always do so. Perhaps it was just the closeness of
Hobbes’s account of reason to the ordinary view of the matter that has led to
its being so completely overlooked. The failure to recognize that the avoidance
of violent death is the primary goal of reason has distorted almost all
accounts of Hobbes’s moral and political philosophy, yet it is a point on which
Hobbes is completely clear and consistent. He explicitly says that reason
“teaches every man to fly a contra-natural dissolution [mortem violentam] as
the greatest mischief that can arrive to nature.” He continually points out
that it is a dictate of right reason to seek peace when possible because people
cannot “expect any lasting preservation continuing thus in the state of nature,
that is, of war.” And he calls temperance and fortitude precepts of reason
because they tend to one’s preservation. It has not generally been recognized
that Hobbes regarded it as an end of reason to avoid violent death because he
often talks of the avoidance of death in a way that makes it seem merely an
object of a passion. But it is reason that dictates that one take all those
measures necessary for one’s preservation; peace if possible, if not, defense.
Reason’s dictates are categorical; it would be a travesty of Hobbes’s view to
regard the dictates of reason as hypothetical judgments addressed to those
whose desire for their own preservation happens to be greater than any conflicting
desire. He explicitly deplores the power of the irrational appetites and
expressly declares that it is a dictate of reason that one not scorn others
because “most men would rather lose their lives (that I say not, their peace)
than suffer slander.” He does not say if you would rather die than suffer
slander, it is rational to do so. Hobbes, following Aristotle, regards morality
as concerned with character traits or habits. Since morality is objective, it
is only those habits that are called good by reason that are moral virtues.
“Reason declaring peace to be good, it follows by the same reason, that all the
necessary means to peace be good also; and therefore that modesty, equity,
trust, humanity, mercy (which we have demonstrated to be necessary to peace),
are good manners or habits, that is, virtues.” Moral virtues are those habits
of acting that the reason of all people must praise. It is interesting to note
that it is only in De Homine that Hobbes explicitly acknowledges that on this
account, prudence, temperance, and courage are not moral virtues. In De Cive he
distinguishes temperance and fortitude from the other virtues and does not call
them moral, but he does not explicitly deny that they are moral virtues. But in
De Homine, he explicitly points out that one should not “demand that the
courage and prudence of the private man, if useful only to himself, be praised
or held as a virtue by states or by any other men whatsoever to whom these same
are not useful.” That morality is determined by reason and that reason has as
its goal self-preservation seems to lead to the conclusion that morality also
has as its goal self-preservation. But it is not the selfpreservation of an
individual person that is the goal of morality, but of people as citizens of a
state. That is, moral virtues are those habits of persons that make it rational
for all other people to praise them. These habits are not those that merely
lead to an individual’s own preservation, but to the preservation of all; i.e.,
to peace and a stable society. Thus, “Good dispositions are those that are
suitable for entering into civil society; and good manners (that is, moral
virtues) are those whereby what was entered upon can be best preserved.” And in
De Cive, when talking of morality, he says, “The goodness of actions consist[s]
in this, that it [is] in order to peace, and the evil in this, that it [is]
related to discord.” The nature of morality is a complex and vexing question.
If, like Hobbes, we regard morality as applying primarily to those manners or
habits that lead to peace, then his view seems satisfactory. It yields, as he
notes, all of the moral virtues that are ordinarily considered such, and
further, it allows one to distinguish courage, prudence, and temperance from
the moral virtues. Perhaps most important, it provides, in almost self-evident
fashion, the justification of morality. For what is it to justify morality but
to show that reason favors it? Reason, seeking self-preservation, must favor
morality, which seeks peace and a stable society. For reason knows that peace
and a stable society are essential for lasting preservation. This simple and
elegant justification of morality does not reduce morality to prudence; rather
it is an attempt, in a great philosophical tradition stemming from Plato, to
reconcile reason or rational self-interest and morality. In the state of nature
every person is and ought to be governed only by their own reason. Reason
dictates that they seek peace, which yields the laws of nature, but it also allows
them to use any means they believe will best preserve themselves, which is what
Hobbes calls The Right of Nature. Hobbes’s insight is to see that, except when
one is in clear and present danger, in which case one has an inalienable right
to defend oneself, the best way to guarantee one’s longterm preservation is to
give up one’s right to act on one’s own decisions about what is the best way to
guarantee one’s long-term preservation and agree to act on the decisions of
that single person or group who is the sovereign. If all individuals and groups
are allowed to act on the decisions they regard as best, not accepting the
commands of the sovereign, i.e., the laws, as the overriding guide for their
actions, the result is anarchy and civil war. Except in rare and unusual cases,
uniformity of action following the decision of the sovereign is more likely to
lead to long-term preservation than diverse actions following diverse
decisions. And this is true even if each one of the diverse decisions, if
accepted by the sovereign as its decision, would have been more likely to lead
to long-term preservation than the actual decision that the sovereign made.
This argument explains why Hobbes holds that sovereigns cannot commit
injustice. Only injustice can properly be punished. Hobbes does not deny that
sovereigns can be immoral, but he does deny that the immorality of sovereigns
can properly be punished. This is important, for otherwise any immoral act by
the sovereign would serve as a pretext for punishing the sovereign, i.e., for
civil war. What is just and unjust is determined by the laws of the state, what
is moral and immoral is not. Morality is a wider concept than that of justice
and is determined by what leads to peace and stability. However, to let justice
be determined by what the reason of the people takes to lead to peace and
stability, rather than by what the reason of the sovereign decides, would be to
invite discord and civil war, which is contrary to the goal of morality: a
stable society and peace. One can create an air of paradox by saying that for
Hobbes it is immoral to attempt to punish some immoral acts, namely, those of
the sovereign. Hobbes is willing to accept this seeming paradox for he never
loses sight of the goal of morality, which is peace. To summarize Hobbes’s
system: people, insofar as they are rational, want to live out their natural
lives in peace and security. To do this, they must come together into cities or
states of sufficient size to deter attack by any group. But when people come together
in such a large group there will always be some that cannot be trusted, and
thus it is necessary to set up a government with the power to make and enforce
laws. This government, which gets both its right to govern and its power to do
so from the consent of the governed, has as its primary duty the people’s
safety. As long as the government provides this safety the citizens are obliged
to obey the laws of the state in all things. Thus, the rationality of seeking
lasting preservation requires seeking peace; this in turn requires setting up a
state with sufficient power to keep the peace. Anything that threatens the
stability of the state is to be avoided. As a practical matter, Hobbes took God
and religion very seriously, for he thought they provided some of the strongest
motives for action. Half of Leviathan is devoted to trying to show that his
moral and political views are supported by Scripture, and to discredit those
religious views that may lead to civil strife. But accepting the sincerity of
Hobbes’s religious views does not require holding that Hobbes regarded God as
the foundation of morality. He explicitly denies that atheists and deists are
subject to the commands of God, but he never denies that they are subject to
the laws of nature or of the civil state. Once one recognizes that, for Hobbes,
reason itself provides a guide to conduct to be followed by all people, there
is absolutely no need to bring in God. For in his moral and political theory
there is nothing that God can do that is not already done by reason. Grice read
most of Hobbes, both in Latin (for his Lit. Hum.) and in English. When in
“Meaning,” Grice says “this is what people are getting at with their natural
versus artificial signs”he means Hobbes.
Hobson’s choice: willkürHobson’s
choice. One of Grice’s favourite words from Kant“It’s so Kantish!” I told Pears
about this, and having found it’s cognate with English ‘choose,’ he immediately
set to write an essay on the topic!” f., ‘option, discretion, caprice,’ from
MidHG. willekür, f., ‘free
choice, free will’; gee kiesen and Kur-kiesen, verb, ‘to select,’ from Middle
High German kiesen, Old
High German chiosan, ‘to
test, try, taste for the purpose of testing, test by tasting, select after
strict examination.’ Gothic kiusan,
Anglo-Saxon ceósan,
English to choose.
Teutonic root kus (with
the change of s into r, kur in the participle erkoren, see also Kur,
‘choice’), from pre-Teutonic gus,
in Latin gus-tus, gus-tare, Greek γεύω for γεύσω, Indian root juš, ‘to select, be fond of.’
Teutonic kausjun passed
as kusiti into
Slavonic. There is an oil portrait of Thomas Hobson, in the National Portrait
Gallery, London. He looks straight to the artist and is dressed in typical
Tudor dress, with a heavy coat, a ruff, and tie tails Thomas Hobson, a portrait
in the National Portrait Gallery, London. A Hobson's choice is a free choice in
which only one thing is offered. Because a person may refuse to accept what is
offered, the two options are taking it or taking nothing. In other words, one
may "take it or leave it". The
phrase is said to have originated with Thomas Hobson (1544–1631), a livery
stable owner in Cambridge, England, who offered customers the choice of either
taking the horse in his stall nearest to the door or taking none at all.
According to a plaque underneath a painting of Hobson donated to Cambridge
Guildhall, Hobson had an extensive stable of some 40 horses. This gave the
appearance to his customers that, upon entry, they would have their choice of
mounts, when in fact there was only one: Hobson required his customers to
choose the horse in the stall closest to the door. This was to prevent the best
horses from always being chosen, which would have caused those horses to become
overused. Hobson's stable was located on land that is now owned by St
Catharine's College, Cambridge. Early
appearances in writing According to the Oxford English Dictionary, the first
known written usage of this phrase is in The rustick's alarm to the Rabbies,
written by Samuel Fisher in 1660: If in
this Case there be no other (as the Proverb is) then Hobson's choice...which
is, chuse whether you will have this or none.
It also appears in Joseph Addison's paper The Spectator (No. 509 of 14
October 1712); and in Thomas Ward's 1688 poem "England's
Reformation", not published until after Ward's death. Ward wrote: Where to elect there is but one, 'Tis
Hobson's choice—take that, or none. The term "Hobson's choice" is
often used to mean an illusion of choice, but it is not a choice between two
equivalent options, which is a Morton's fork, nor is it a choice between two
undesirable options, which is a dilemma. Hobson's choice is one between something
or nothing. John Stuart Mill, in his
book Considerations on Representative Government, refers to Hobson's
choice: When the individuals composing
the majority would no longer be reduced to Hobson's choice, of either voting
for the person brought forward by their local leaders, or not voting at all. In
another of his books, The Subjection of Women, Mill discusses marriage: Those who attempt to force women into
marriage by closing all other doors against them, lay themselves open to a
similar retort. If they mean what they say, their opinion must evidently be,
that men do not render the married condition so desirable to women, as to
induce them to accept it for its own recommendations. It is not a sign of one's
thinking the boon one offers very attractive, when one allows only Hobson's
choice, 'that or none'.... And if men are determined that the law of marriage
shall be a law of despotism, they are quite right in point of mere policy, in
leaving to women only Hobson's choice. But, in that case, all that has been
done in the modern world to relax the chain on the minds of women, has been a
mistake. They should have never been allowed to receive a literary
education. A Hobson's choice is
different from: Dilemma: a choice
between two or more options, none of which is attractive. False dilemma: only
certain choices are considered, when in fact there are others. Catch-22: a
logical paradox arising from a situation in which an individual needs something
that can only be acquired by not being in that very situation. Morton's fork,
and a double bind: choices yield equivalent, and often undesirable, results.
Blackmail and extortion: the choice between paying money (or some non-monetary
good or deed) or risk suffering an unpleasant action. A common error is to use
the phrase "Hobbesian choice" instead of "Hobson's choice",
confusing the philosopher Thomas Hobbes with the relatively obscure Thomas
Hobson (It's possible they may be
confusing "Hobson's choice" with "Hobbesian trap", which
refers to the trap into which a state falls when it attacks another out of
fear). Notwithstanding that confused usage, the phrase "Hobbesian
choice" is historically incorrect. Common law In Immigration and
Naturalization Service v. Chadha (1983), Justice Byron White dissented and
classified the majority's decision to strike down the "one-house
veto" as unconstitutional as leaving Congress with a Hobson's choice. Congress
may choose between "refrain[ing] from delegating the necessary authority,
leaving itself with a hopeless task of writing laws with the requisite
specificity to cover endless special circumstances across the entire policy
landscape, or in the alternative, to abdicate its lawmaking function to the
executive branch and independent agency".
In Philadelphia v. New Jersey, 437 U.S. 617 (1978), the majority opinion
ruled that a New Jersey law which prohibited the importation of solid or liquid
waste from other states into New Jersey was unconstitutional based on the
Commerce Clause. The majority reasoned that New Jersey cannot discriminate
between the intrastate waste and the interstate waste with out due
justification. In dissent, Justice Rehnquist stated: [According to the Court,] New Jersey must
either prohibit all landfill operations, leaving itself to cast about for a
presently nonexistent solution to the serious problem of disposing of the waste
generated within its own borders, or it must accept waste from every portion of
the United States, thereby multiplying the health and safety problems which
would result if it dealt only with such wastes generated within the State.
Because past precedents establish that the Commerce Clause does not present
appellees with such a Hobson's choice, I dissent. In Monell v. Department of Social Services of
the City of New York, 436 U.S. 658 (1978) the judgement of the court was
that [T]here was ample support for
Blair's view that the Sherman Amendment, by putting municipalities to the
Hobson's choice of keeping the peace or paying civil damages, attempted to
impose obligations to municipalities by indirection that could not be imposed
directly, thereby threatening to "destroy the government of the
states". In the South African
Constitutional Case MEC for Education, Kwa-Zulu Natal and Others v Pillay, 2008
(1) SA 474 (CC) Chief Justice Langa for the majority of the Court (in Paragraph
62 of the judgement) writes that: The
traditional basis for invalidating laws that prohibit the exercise of an
obligatory religious practice is that it confronts the adherents with a
Hobson's choice between observance of their faith and adherence to the law.
There is however more to the protection of religious and cultural practices
than saving believers from hard choices. As stated above, religious and
cultural practices are protected because they are central to human identity and
hence to human dignity which is in turn central to equality. Are voluntary
practices any less a part of a person's identity or do they affect human
dignity any less seriously because they are not mandatory? In Epic Systems Corp. v. Lewis (), Justice
Ruth Bader Ginsburg dissented and added in one of the footnotes that the
petitioners "faced a Hobson’s choice: accept arbitration on their
employer’s terms or give up their jobs".
In Trump et al v. Mazars USA, LLP, US Court of Appeals for the District
of Columbia No. 19-5142, 49 (D.C. Cir. 11 October ) ("[w]orse still, the
dissent’s novel approach would now impose upon the courts the job of ordering
the cessation of the legislative function and putting Congress to the Hobson’s
Choice of impeachment or nothing.").
Popular culture Hobson's Choice is a full-length stage comedy written by
Harold Brighouse in 1915. At the end of the play, the central character, Henry
Horatio Hobson, formerly a wealthy, self-made businessman but now a sick and
broken man, faces the unpalatable prospect of being looked after by his
daughter Maggie and her husband Will Mossop, who used to be one of Hobson's
underlings. His other daughters have refused to take him in, so he has no
choice but to accept Maggie's offer which comes with the condition that he must
surrender control of his entire business to her and her husband, Will. The play was adapted for film several times,
including versions from 1920 by Percy Nash, 1931 by Thomas Bentley, 1954 by
David Lean and a 1983 TV movie. Alfred
Bester's 1952 short story Hobson's Choice describes a world in which time travel
is possible, and the option is to travel or to stay in one's native time. In the 1951 Robert Heinlein book Between
Planets, the main character Don Harvey incorrectly mentions he has a Hobson's
choice. While on a space station orbiting Earth, Don needs to get to Mars,
where his parents are. The only rockets available are back to Earth (where he
is not welcome) or on to Venus. In The
Grim Grotto by Lemony Snicket, the Baudelaire orphans and Fiona are said to be
faced with a Hobson's Choice when they are trapped by the Medusoid Mycelium
Mushrooms in the Gorgonian Grotto: "We can wait until the mushrooms
disappear, or we can find ourselves poisoned".In Bram Stoker's short story
"The Burial of Rats", the narrator advises he has a case of Hobson's
Choice while being chased by villains. The story was written around 1874. The Terminal Experiment, a 1995 science
fiction novel by Robert J. Sawyer, was originally serialised under the title
Hobson's Choice. Half-Life, a video game
created in 1998 by Valve includes a Hobson's Choice in the final chapter. A
human-like entity, known only as the 'G-Man', offers the protagonist Gordon
Freeman a job, working under his control. If Gordon were to refuse this offer,
he would be killed in an unwinnable battle, thus creating the 'illusion of free
choice'. In Early Edition, the lead
character Gary Hobson is named after the choices he regularly makes during his
adventures. In an episode of Inspector
George Gently, a character claims her resignation was a Hobson's choice, prompting
a debate among other police officers as to who Hobson is. In "Cape May" (The Blacklist season
3, episode 19), Raymond Reddington describes having faced a Hobson's choice in
the previous episode where he was faced with the choice of saving Elizabeth
Keen's baby and losing Elizabeth Keen or losing them both. In his 1984 novel Job: A Comedy of Justice,
Robert A. Heinlein's protagonist is said to have Hobson's Choice when he has
the options of boarding the wrong cruise ship or staying on the island. Remarking about the 1909 Ford Model T, US industrialist
Henry Ford is credited as saying “Any customer can have a car painted any color
that he wants so long as it is black” In
'The Jolly Boys' Outing', a 1989 Christmas Special episode of Only Fools and
Horses, Alan states they are left with Hobson's Choice after their coach has
blown up (due to a dodgy radio, supplied by Del). There's a rail strike, the
last bus has gone, and their coach is out of action. They can't hitch-hike as
there's 27 of them, and the replacement coach doesn't come till the next
morning, thus their only choice is to stay in Margate for the night. See also Buckley's Chance Buridan's ass
Boulwarism Death and Taxes Locus of control Morton's fork No-win situation
Standard form contract Sophie's Choice Zugzwang References Barrett, Grant. "Hobson's Choice",
A Way with Words "Thomas Hobson:
Hobson's Choice and Hobson's Conduit". Historyworks. See Samuel Fisher. "Rusticus ad academicos
in exercitationibus expostulatoriis, apologeticis quatuor the rustick's alarm
to the rabbies or The country correcting the university and clergy, and ...
contesting for the truth ... : in four apologeticall and expostulatory
exercitations : wherein is contained, as well a general account to all
enquirers, as a general answer to all opposers of the most truly catholike and
most truly Christ-like Chistians called Quakers, and of the true divinity of
their doctrine : by way of entire entercourse held in special with four of the
clergies chieftanes, viz, John Owen ... Tho. Danson ... John Tombes ... Rich.
Baxter ." Europeana. Retrieved 8 August .
See The Spectator with Notes and General Index, the Twelve Volumes
Comprised in Two. Philadelphia: J.J. Woodward. 1832. p. 272. Retrieved 4 August
. via Google Books Ward, Thomas (1853).
English Reformation, A Poem. New York: D.& J. Sadlier & Co. p. 373.
Retrieved 8 August . via See Mill, John
Stuart (1861). Considerations on Representative Government (1 ed.). London:
Parker, Son, & Bourn. p. 145. Retrieved 23 June . via Google Books Mill, John Stuart (1869). The Subjection of
Women (1869 first ed.). London: Longmans, Green, Reader & Dyer. 51–2. Retrieved 28 July . Hobbes, Thomas (1982) [1651]. Leviathan, or
the Matter, Form, and Power of a Commonwealth, Ecclesiastical and Civil. New
York: Viking Press. Martinich, A. P.
(1999). Hobbes: A Biography. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University
Press. 978-0-521-49583-7. Martin, Gary. "Hobson's Choice".
The Phrase Finder. Archived from the original on 6 March 2009. Retrieved 7
August . "The Hobbesian Trap"
. 21 September . Retrieved 8 April .
"Sunday Lexico-Neuroticism". boaltalk.blogspot.com. 27 July
2008. Retrieved 7 August . Levy, Jacob
(10 June 2003). "The Volokh Conspiracy". volokh.com. Retrieved 7
August . Oxford English Dictionary,
Editor: "Amazingly, some writers have confused the obscure Thomas Hobson
with his famous contemporary, the philosopher Thomas Hobbes. The resulting
malapropism is beautifully grotesque". Garner, Bryan (1995). A Dictionary
of Modern Legal Usage (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press. 404–405.
supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/437/617/ "Monell v. Department of Soc. Svcs.436
U.S. 658 (1978)". justicia.com. US Supreme Court. 6 June 1978. 436 U.S.
658. Retrieved 19 February . "MEC
for Education: Kwazulu-Natal and Others v Pillay (CCT 51/06) [2007] ZACC 21;
2008 (1) SA 474 (CC); 2008 (2) BCLR 99 (CC) (5 October 2007)".
saflii.org. Snicket, Lemony (2004) The
Grim Grotto, New York: HarperCollins Publishers p.145147 Henry Ford in collaboration with Samuel
Crowther in My Life and Work. 1922. Page 72 External links Chisholm, Hugh, ed.
(1911). "Hobson's Choice" . Encyclopædia Britannica. 13 (11th ed.).
Cambridge University Press. p. 553. Categories: English-language idiomsFree
willMetaphors referring to peopleDilemmas. Refs.: H. P. Grice and D. F. Pears,
The philosophy of action, Pears, Choosing and deciding. The H. P. Grice Papers,
BANC.
hoc
-- hic, the hæc, and the hoc, theGrice: “The proper way to enter this in a
philosophical lexicon is via that favourite gender of philosophers: the epicene
or neuter!” -- “Scotus was being clever. Since he wanted an abstract noun, and
abstract nouns are feminine in both Greek and Latin (‘ippotes, eqquitas’), he
chose the feminine ‘haec,’ to turn into a ‘thess.’ But we should expand his
rather sexist view to apply to ‘hic’ and ‘hoc,’ too. In Anglo-Saxon, there is
only ‘this,’ with ‘thess’ first used by Pope George. The OED first registers
‘thess’ in 1643.”cf. OED: "It
is at its such-&-suchness, at its character -- in other words, at the _universal_ in it -- that we have to look. the first cite in the OED for 'thess' also features 'thatness':
"thess,” from "this" + "-ness": rendering
‘haecceitas,’ the quality of being 'this' (as distinct from anything else): =
haecceity. First cite: "It is evident that [...] THess, and THATness
belong[...] not to matter by itself, but onely as [matter] is distinguished
& individuated by the form." The two further quotes for 'thess' being:
1837 Whewell Hist Induct Sc 1857 I 244: "Which his school called
‘HAECcceity’from the feminine form of the demonstrative masculine ‘hic,’ in
Roman, neutre ‘hoc’ (Scotus uses the femine because ‘-ity- is a feminine
ending) -- or ‘thess.’", and 1895 Rashdall Universities II 532: "An
individuating form called by the later Scotists its ‘haecceitas’ or its
`thess'"). "The investing of the content,
which is in Bradleian language a `what',
with self-existent reality or
‘that-ness'." Athenaeum 24 Dec. 1904
868/2. -- OED, 'thatness'. Trudgill writes in _The Dialects of England_
(Oxford: Blackwell), that Grice would often consult (he was from Harborne and
had a special interest in this“I seem to have lost my dialect when I moved to
Corpus.” The 'this'-'that' demonstrative system is a two-way system which
distinguishes between things which are distant and things which are near.
Interestingly, however, a number of traditional dialects in England (if not
Oxford) differ from this system in having what Grice called a Griceian
_three_-way distinction. The Yorkshire dialect, for example, has ‘this’ (sing.,
near), ‘thir’ (pl. near), ‘that’ (sing. Medial) ‘tho’ (plural, medial), thon
(sing. distal) and ‘thon’ (pl., distal). The Mercian Anglian dialect has
‘these’ (sing. near), ‘theys’ (plural, near), ‘that’ (sing. medial), ‘they’
(pl., medial), ‘thik’ (sing./pl., distal). “The northern dialect is better in
that it distinguishes between the singular and the plural form for the distal,
unlike the southern dialect which has ‘thik’ for either.” Grice. Still, Grice
likes the sound of ‘thik’ and quotes from his friend M. Wakelin, _The Southwest
of England_. "When I awoke one May day morn/I found an urge within me
born/To see the beauteous countryside/That's all round wher'I do bide./So I set
out wi' dog & stick,/ My head were just a trifle thick./But good ole' fresh
air had his say/& blowed thik trouble clean away." -- B. Green, in
_The Dorset Year Book_. Dorset: Society of Dorset Men. “Some like Russell, but
Bradley’s MY man.”H. P. Grice: Grice:
"Russell is pretentious; Bradley, an English angel, is not!" "Bradley can use 'thatness' freely; Russell uses it after
Bradley and artificially."
all the rest of the
watery bulk : but return back those few drops from whence they were
taken, and the glass-full that even now had an individuation by itself,
loseth that, and groweth one and the same with the other main stock : yet
if you fill your glass again, wheresoever you take it up, so it be
of the same uniform bulk of water you had before, it is the same glassfuU
of water that you had. But as I said before, this example fitteth
entirely no more than the other did. In such abstracted speculations,
where we must consider matter without form, (which hath no actual being,)
we must not expect adequated examples in nature. But enough is said to
make a speculative man see, that if God should join the soul of a
lately dead man, (even whilst his dead corpse should lie en- tire in his
windingsheet here,) unto a body made of earth, taken from some mountain
in America; it were most true and certain, that the body he should then
live by, were the same identical body he lived with before his death, and
late resurrection. It is evident, that sameness, thess, and that-
ness, belongeth not to matter by itself, (for a general indiffer- ence
runneth through it all,) but only as it is distinguished and individuated
by the form. Which in our case, whensoever the same soul doth, it must be
understood always to be the same matter and body.” (Browne, 1643). Grice. Corbin says
that English is such a plastic language, “unlike Roman,” but then there’s haec,
and hæcceitas -- Duns Scotus, J., Scottish Franciscan metaphysician and
philosophical theologian. He lectured at Oxford, Paris, and Cologne, where he
died and his remains are still venerated. Modifying Avicenna’s conception of
metaphysics as the science of being qua being, but univocally conceived, Duns
Scotus showed its goal was to demonstrate God as the Infinite Being revealed to
Moses as the “I am who am”, whose creative will is the source of the world’s
contingency. Out of love God fashioned each creature with a unique “haecceity”
or particularity formally distinct from its individualized nature.
Descriptively identical with others of its kind, this nature, conceived in
abstraction from haecceity, is both objectively real and potentially universal,
and provides the basis for scientific knowledge that Peirce calls “Scotistic
realism.” Duns Scotus brought many of Augustine’s insights, treasured by his
Franciscan predecessors, into the mainstream of the Aristotelianism of his day.
Their notion of the will’s “supersufficient potentiality” for
self-determination he showed can be reconciled with Aristotle’s notion of an
“active potency,” if one rejects the controDuhem thesis Duns Scotus, John
247 247 versial principle that
“whatever is moved is moved by another.” Paradoxically, Aristotle’s criteria
for rational and non-rational potencies prove the rationality of the will, not
the intellect, for he claimed that only rational faculties are able to act in
opposite ways and are thus the source of creativity in the arts. If so, then
intellect, with but one mode of acting determined by objective evidence, is
non-rational, and so is classed with active potencies called collectively “nature.”
Only the will, acting “with reason,” is free to will or nill this or that. Thus
“nature” and “will” represent Duns Scotus’s primary division of active
potencies, corresponding roughly to Aristotle’s dichotomy of non-rational and
rational. Original too is his development of Anselm’s distinction of the will’s
twofold inclination or “affection”: one for the advantageous, the other for
justice. The first endows the will with an “intellectual appetite” for
happiness and actualization of self or species; the second supplies the will’s
specific difference from other natural appetites, giving it an innate desire to
love goods objectively according to their intrinsic worth. Guided by right
reason, this “affection for justice” inclines the will to act ethically, giving
it a congenital freedom from the need always to seek the advantageous. Both
natural affections can be supernaturalized, the “affection for justice” by
charity, inclining us to love God above all and for his own sake; the affection
for the advantageous by the virtue of hope, inclining us to love God as our
ultimate good and future source of beatitude. Another influential psychological
theory is that of intuitive intellectual cognition, or the simple,
non-judgmental awareness of a hereand-now existential situation. First
developed as a necessary theological condition for the face-toface vision of
God in the next life, intellectual intuition is needed to explain our certainty
of primary contingent truths, such as “I think,” “I choose,” etc., and our awareness
of existence. Unlike Ockham, Duns Scotus never made intellectual intuition the
basis for his epistemology, nor believed it puts one in direct contact with any
extramental substance material or spiritual, for in this life, at least, our
intellect works through the sensory imagination. Intellectual intuition seems
to be that indistinct peripheral aura associated with each direct
sensory-intellectual cognition. We know of it explicitly only in retrospect
when we consider the necessary conditions for intellectual memory. It continued
to be a topic of discussion and dispute down to the time of Calvin, who,
influenced by the Scotist John Major, used an auditory rather than a visual
sense model of intellectual intuition to explain our “experience of God.” haecceity from Latin haec, ‘this’, 1 loosely,
thess; more specifically, an irreducible category of being, the fundamental
actuality of an existent entity; or 2 an individual essence, a property an
object has necessarily, without which it would not be or would cease to exist
as the individual it is, and which, necessarily, no other object has. There are
in the history of philosophy two distinct concepts of haecceity. The idea
originated with the work of the thirteenthcentury philosopher Duns Scotus, and was
discussed in the same period by Aquinas, as a positive perfection that serves
as a primitive existence and individuation principle for concrete existents. In
the seventeenth century Leibniz transformed the concept of haecceity, which
Duns Scotus had explicitly denied to be a form or universal, into the notion of
an individual essence, a distinctive nature or set of necessary characteristics
uniquely identifying it under the principle of the identity of indiscernibles.
Duns Scotus’s haecceitas applies only to the being of contingently existent
entities in the actual world, but Leibniz extends the principle to individuate
particular things not only through the changes they may undergo in the actual
world, but in any alternative logically possible world. Leibniz admitted as a
consequence the controversial thesis that every object by virtue of its
haecceity has each of its properties essentially or necessarily, so that only
the counterparts of individuals can inhabit distinct logically possible worlds.
A further corollary since the possession
of particular parts in a particular arrangement is also a property and hence
involved in the individual essence of any complex object is the doctrine of mereological essentialism:
every composite is necessarily constituted by a particular configuration of
particular proper parts, and loses its self-identity if any parts are removed
or replaced. Grice was more familiar with the thatness than the thess (“Having
had to read Bradley for my metaphysics paper!”).
holo-gram: the image of an
object in three dimensions created and reproduced by the use of lasers.
Holography is a method for recording and reproducing such images. Holograms are
remarkable in that, unlike normal photographs, every part of them contains the
complete image but in reduced detail. Thus a small square cut from a hologram
can still be laser-illuminated to reveal the whole scene originally
holographed, albeit with loss of resolution. This feature made the hologram
attractive to proponents of the thesis of distribution of function in the
brain, who argued that memories are like holograms, not being located in a
single precise engramas claimed by advocates of localization of functionbut
distributed across perhaps all of the cortex. Although intriguing, the holographic
model of memory storage failed to gain acceptance. Current views favor D. O.
Hebb’s “cell assembly” concept, in which memories are stored in the connections
between a group of neurons.
Hoesle: Grice: “I like Hösle – for one, he helped me understand Vico when stating
that what Vico is after is a ‘science of the inter-subjective world;’ since I’m
also into that I suppose I am Vico!” -- Vittorio Hösle (Milano), filosofo. Nato
da padre Tedesco Johannes Hösle, docente di filologia romanzae da madre italiana
Carla Gronda –, Vittorio Hösle trascorse la sua prima infanzia a Milano, dove
il padre era direttore del Goethe Institut, e compì poi gli studi in Germania,
dove la famiglia si era trasferita. Vero «enfant prodige» della filosofia,
precoce e profondo conoscitore delle lingue antiche (greco, latino, sanscrito,
ma anche pali e avestico) e di numerose lingue occidentali (ne parla sette ed è
in grado di leggerne dodici), a ventidue anni si laureò con una tesi sulla
filosofia antica (v. infra), a ventisei anni fu chiamato come professore
associato alla New School for Social Research di New York e a trentadue anni
divenne Professore all'Essen. Attualmente insegna alla Notre Dame University
(Indiana) negli Stati Uniti. Il 6 agosto
è stato nominato Accademico ordinario della Pontificia Accademia delle
Scienze Sociali da Papa Francesco. Gli studi sul pensiero antico Alla
«scoperta» di Hösle contribuì in modo determinante l'Istituto Italiano per gli
Studi Filosofici, che lo chiamò a Napoli come borsista (venticinquenne)
dell'Istituto negli anni 1985-1986. Nell'anno precedente l'Istituto aveva
accolto nel suo programma editoriale la tesi di laurea di Hösle, un poderoso
lavoro sulla filosofia antica di quasi 800 pagine intitolato Wahrheit und
Geschichte. Studien zur Struktur der Philosophiegeschichte unter
paradigmatischer Analyse der Entwicklung von Parmenides bis Platon (Verità e
storia. Studi sulla struttura della storia della filosofia sulla base di
un'analisi paradigmatica dell'evoluzione da Parmenide a Platone), promuovendone
la pubblicazione per la casa editrice Frommann-Holzboog e successivamente una
traduzione italiana per i tipi della Guerini e Associati. In quest'opera
l'allora giovanissimo filosofo imposta in maniera originale il problema dei
rapporti tra dimensione sistematica e dimensione storica della filosofia,
analizzando lo sviluppo del pensiero greco da Parmenide a Platone. Nel
lavoro successivo, Die Vollendung der Tragödie im Spätwerk des Sophokles.
Ästhetisch-historische Bemerkungen zur Struktur der attischen Tragödie (Il
compimento della tragedia nell'opera tarda di Sofocle. Osservazioni
storico-estetiche sulla struttura della tragedia attica)pubblicato nel 1984
dalla Fromann-Holzboog e in traduzione italiana nel 1986 da Bibliopolis –,
Hösle, combinando l'approccio estetico con l'approccio filosofico, cerca di
individuare una logica di sviluppo nella storia della tragedia greca e, in
contrasto con l'approccio consueto, considera Sofocle come il compimento
sintetico di questa storia: "il pensiero fondamentale espresso nell'opera
tarda di Sofocle è sintesi dei principi che sono alla base dell'arte di Eschilo
e di Euripide, principi che vengono fatti valere insieme da Sofocle e così
portati alla loro verità". Negli anni Ottanta Hösle, che a Regensburg
era stato allievo del matematico e filosofo Imre Toth, si occupò anche del
problema della matematica in Platone, scrivendo nel 1982 e nel 1984 alcuni
saggi, che, per interessamento di Giovanni Reale, vengono tradotti in italiano
e riuniti in un volume pubblicato nel 1994 dalla casa editrice "Vita e
Pensiero" con il titolo I fondamenti dell'aritmetica e della geometria in
Platone. In anni recenti Hösle è tornato ad occuparsi della filosofia e
della letteratura antiche. In un lavoro del 2004, Platoninterpretieren
(Interpretare Platone), di cui è uscita nel 2007 anche la traduzione italiana,
discute il problema delle interpretazioni di Platone enel volume del 2006, Der
philosophische Dialog. Poetik eines Genres (Il dialogo filosofico. Poetica di
un genere), analizza ilgenere del dialogo mettendo in connessione il punto di
vista filosofico con il punto di vista letterario. Al problema della tragedia è
poi dedicato il lavoro del 2009 Die Rangordnung der drei griechischen Tragiker
(La gerarchia dei tre tragici greci). Gli studi sull'idealismo tedesco e
il problema della fondazione ultima riflessiva Nei suoi anni italiani a Napoli
Hösle tenne una serie di seminari e di conferenze sull'idealismo tedesco, in
particolare sul sistema di Hegel, e presentò diverse relazioni in convegni
internazionali. Va ricordato il convegno sulla filosofia hegeliana del diritto
(Napoli, 1984), i cui atti, pubblicati nel 1987 Christoph Jermann, amico e
collaboratore del filosofo, col titolo Anspruch und Leistung von Hegels
Rechtphilosophie, contengono, ben tre ampi saggi di Hösle, oltre a contributi
dello stesso Jermann, di Kurt Seelmann e di Matthias Hartwig. Di uno di essi,
Lo Stato in Hegel, esiste una traduzione italiana pubblicata nel 2008 per i
tipi de "La città del Sole". La riflessione hösliana
sull'idealimo oggettivo di Hegel si sviluppa in stretta connessione col
problema della "fondazione ultima riflessiva" (reflexive
Letztbegründung) e con la soluzione fornita a tale problema dalla pragmatica
trascendentale di Karl-Otto Apel. L'unica alternativa consistente al
relativismo scettico, dominante nel panorama della filosofia contemporanea ed
assurto oggi ad una sorta di principio dell'opinione pubblica, consiste,
secondo Hösle, nell'impostazione riflessiva presente negli idealisti
postkantiani e soprattutto in Hegel, impostazione che è necessario sviluppare
con gli strumenti elaborati dalla filosofia contemporanea e in stretta
connessione con i più recenti risultati delle scienze. Alla pragmatica
trascendentale di Apel va riconosciuto il merito di aver riproposto in maniera
originale la nozione di "fondazione ultima riflessiva", ma tale
nozione va ripensata nella sua portata ontologica, superando il formalismo
apeliano nella direzione di una formulazione profondamente rielaborata dell'idealismo
oggettivo di matrice hegeliana. In questa direzione, che culminerà nel
poderoso lavoro del 1987 sul sistema di Hegel (v. infra), vanno le lezioni
hegeliane tenute a Napoli da Hösle nel 1986 e parzialmente pubblicate in volume
nel 1991 con il titolo Hegel e la fondazione dell'idealismo oggettivo, in cui è
compresa anche la traduzione dell'importante saggio Begründungsfragen des
objektiven Idealismus (Questioni di fondazione dell'idealismo oggettivo)
scritto proprio nel 1987. Della pragmatica trascendentale, soprattutto in
relazione al problema decisivo della fondazione ultima riflessiva, Hösle tornò
ad occuparsi alla fine degli anni Ottanta in una vasta monografia, Die Krise
der Gegenwart und die Verantwortung der Philosophie (La crisi della contemporaneità
e la responsabilità della filosofia), pubblicata nel 1990 (e tradotta in
francese nel 2004): la filosofia di Apel viene analizzata all'interno delle più
importanti tendenze della filosofia contemporanea, viene esposta in modo
dettagliato la "prova" della fondazione ultima riflessiva (la
cosiddetta "prova apagogica") e vengono discussi questioni relative
al linguaggio privato, alla controversia “spiegare-comprendere
(Erklären-Verstehen)” e alla fondazione dell'etica. Gli studi su Vico e
la traduzione in tedesco della Scienza Nuova Sempre in questo periodo Hösle
intraprese la traduzione integrale in tedesco (la prima traduzione integrale in
questa lingua) della Scienza nuova di Giambattista Vico nella terza edizione
del 1744, compito affidatogli dall'Istituto Italiano per gli Studi Filosofici e
che egli, insieme a Christoph Jermann, portò a termine in tempi
straordinariamente brevi. Il capolavoro vichiano uscì nel 1990 per i tipi della
casa editrice Felix Meiner in due volumi; la traduzione è preceduta da una
introduzione filologica e teoretica di quasi 300 pagine, in cui Hösle illustra
il significato ancora attuale della concezione vichiana per una teoria delle
scienze della cultura filosoficamente fondata. Questa introduzione è stata
tradotta in italiano e pubblicata in volume nel 1997 con il titolo Introduzione
a Vico. La scienza del mondo intersoggettivo per i tipi della Guerini e
Associati. Critica e riformulazione dell'idealismo oggettivo: Il sistema
di Hegel La rilessione teoretica di Hösle culmina, come si è detto, nella
riformulazione critica dell'idealismo oggettivo elaborata in un lavoro di vaste
proporzioni, nato come scritto di abilitazione all'insegnamento universitario e
pubblicato dalla casa editrice Felix Meiner nel 1987 in due volumi col titolo
Hegels System. Der Idealismus der Subjektivität und das Problem der
Intersubjektivität (Il sistema di Hegel. L'idealismo della soggettività e il
problema dell'intersoggettività). Sulla base di un'approfondita e articolata
analisi, in primo luogo teoretica, del sistema hegeliano, la cui articolazione
viene criticamente ripercorsa in modo dettagliato, Hösle vi sostiene la tesi
seguente: l'aporia principale della filosofia di Hegel consiste nell'aver
trascurato il problema dell'intersoggettività nella scienza della logica ossia
nella parte fondativa del sistema; questa lacuna comporta un grave squilibrio
nella struttura complessiva del sistema, in particolare, nella filosofia dello
spirito oggettivo e dello spirito assoluto, che restano "scoperte"
sul piano logico, ossia senza un corrispettivo categoriale in grado di fondare
le strutture intersoggettive di cui trattano. Questa aporia fondamentale è alla
radice delle altre aporie presenti nel sistema hegeliano, come, ad esempio,
l'appiattimento del dover-essere sull'essere con la conseguente visione
passatista e la questione della conclusione del sistema. Nel contempo Hösle
cerca di mostrare come l'idea fondamentale dell'idealismo oggettivo sia
teoreticamente ancora attuale e indispensabile sia per fondare in modo rigoroso
la specificità del discorso filosofico sia per superare la scissione tra
scienze della natura e scienze dello spirito che caratterizza in modo aporetico
il pensiero moderno e contemporaneo. Quest'opera ha avuto una vasta risonanza
internazionale ed è stata tradotta in portoghese e parzialmente in coreano. Nel
, promossa dall'Istituto Italiano per gli Studi Filosofici e per i tipi della
casa editrice "La scuola di Pitagora", è uscita la traduzione
integrale italiana (comprendente anche la Postfazione scritta dall'Autore per
la seconda edizione del 1998) col titolo Il sistema di Hegel. L'idealismo della
soggettività e il problema dell'intersoggettività. La riflessione sulla
filosofia pratica A partire dagli anni Novanta del secolo trascorso Hösle
spostò la sua riflessione dalla "filosofia prima" alla
"filosofia seconda", occupandosi di problemi morali e politici, tra
cui ha un posto di rilievo la questione dell'ecologia. Notevole eco hanno
suscitato la sua Philosophie der ökologischen Krise (Filosofia della crisi
ecologica) del 1991, che è stata tradotta in italiano, in francese, in russo,
in croato, in coreano e parzialmente in olandese. I suoi studi delle
moderne scienze sociali, politologia ed economia soprattutto, sono poi confluiti
in un poderoso lavoro di filosofia pratica elaborata sul fondamento
dell'idealismo oggettivo: Moral und Politik. Grundlagen einer Politischen Ethik
für das 21. Jahrhundert (Morale e politica. Fondamenti di un'etica politica per
il XXI secolo), pubblicato nel 1997 da Beck e tradotto in inglese nel 2004, che
costituisce senz'altro la sua opera più impegnativa dopo Il sistema di
Hegel. Vanno menzionche i saggi, scritti in tempi diversi e poi raccolti
nel volume Praktische Philosophie in der modernen Welt del 1992, in cui vengono
discussi problemi come quello della tecnica, della valutazione etica del
capitalismo, del terzo mondo, della dialettica illuminismo/controilluminismo
ecc. Altri studi e ricerche Dei numerosissimi scritti di Hösle, che riflettono
la vastità dei suoi interessi e dei suoi ambiti di ricerca, è impossibile dar
conto in modo easustivo. Ne segnaliamo alcuni soltanto, avendo riguardo in
particolare alle traduzioni italiane disponibili. Vanno ricordati, innanzi
tutto, i lavori sul significato filosofico della teoria dell'evoluzione di
Charles Darwin, tra cui il saggio del 1988 Tragweite und Grenzen der
evolutionären Erkenntnistheorie, tradotto in italiano col titolo Portata e
limiti della teoria evoluzionistica della conoscenza (Napoli 1996, La Città del
Sole), e i lavori scritti in collaborazione col biologo Christian Illies, in
particolare la monografia Darwin del 1999. Un affascinante esempio di
Kinderphilosophie o Philosophy for children è il best seller scritto da Hösle
insieme all'adolescente Nora K.: Das Café der toten Philosophen. Ein
philosophischer Briefwechsel für Kinder und Erwachsene uscito per le edizioni
Beck nel 1996 e più volte ristampato. Il libro è stato tradotto in italiano nel
1999 col titolo Aristotele e il dinosauro. La filosofia spiegata a una
ragazzina, nonché in inglese, olandese, spagnolo, portoghese,
portoghese/brasiliano, catalano, persiano, coreano, giapponese, turco,
taiwanese, cinese e indonesiano. Va ricordato infine il saggio su Woody
Allen, Woody Allen. Versuch über das Komische (Woody Allen. Sulla comicità),
uscito nel 2001 da Beck, e di cui esiste anche la versione inglese (2007), a
riprova del costante interesse nutrito da Hösle per le forme d'arte, come il
teatro e il cinema, in cui l'intersoggettivitàla categoria centrale della sua
riflessione filosoficagioca un ruolo determinante. Note Il compimento della tragedia nell'opera tarda
di Sofocle. Osservazioni storico-estetiche sulla struttura della tragedia attica,
Napoli 1986, Bibliopolis17 Nel 2006 sono
state pubblicate anche le lezioni sulla filosofia hegeliana della religione,
tenute da Hösle a Napoli nel 1985, col titolo Il concetto di filosofia della
religione in Hegel per l'editrice "La Scuola di Pitagora". Die Krise der Gegenwart und die Verantwortung
der Philosophie'. Transzendentalpragmatik, Letztbegründung und Ethik, München
1990, Beck.' Prinzipien einer neuen
Wissenschaft über die gemeinsame Natur der Völker, Tl.1-2, Hamburg 1990, Felix
Meiner. Opere principali di Hösle
Platons Grundlegung der Euklidizität der Geometrie, in: "Philologus",
126 (1982); Zu Platons Philosophie der Zahlen und deren mathematischer und
philosophischer Bedeutung, in: "Theologie und Philosophie", 59 (1984
[I fondamenti dell'aritmetica e della geometria in Platone (tr. di E. Cattanei,
Introduzione di G.Reale), Milano 1994, Vita e pensiero]. Wahrheit und
Geschichte. Studien zur Struktur der Philosophiegeschichte unter
paradigmatischer Analyse der Entwicklung von Parmenides bis Platon,
Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt 1984, Frommann-Holzboog [Verità e storia. Studi sulla
struttura della storia della filosofia sulla base di un'analisi paradigmatica
dell'evoluzione da Parmenide a Platone (A. Tassi; senza la III parte per
volontà dell'Autore), Milano 1998, Guerini e Associati (Istituto Italiano per
gli Studi FilosoficiHegeliana 24)]. Die Vollendung der Tragödie im Spätwerk des
Sophokles. Ästhetisch-historische Bemerkungen zur Struktur der attischen
Tragödie, Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt 1984, Frommann-Holzboog [Il compimento della
tragedia nell'opera tarda di Sofocle. Osservazioni storico-estetiche sulla
struttura della tragedia attica (A. Gargano), Napoli 1986, Bibliopolis (Memorie
dell'Istituto Italiano per gli Studi Filosofici 16)]. Il concetto di filosofia
della religione in Hegel (trascrizione delle lezioni napoletane del 1985 M.
Cuccurullo e F. Iannello), Napoli 2006, La Scuola di Pitagora.
Begründungsfragen des objektiven Idealismus, in: Philosophie und Begründung
(hg. vom Forum für Philosophie Bad Homburg), Frankfurt 1987 [tr. it. in Hegel e
la fondazione dell'idealismo oggettivo (G. Stelli; insieme alle lezioni
napoletane su Hegel del 1986), Milano 1991, Guerini e Associati (Istituto
Italiano per gli Studi FilosoficiHegeliana 1)]. Carl Schmitts Kritik an der
Selbstaufhebung einer wertneutralen Verfassung in "Legalität und
Legitimität", in: "Deutsche Vierteljahrsschrift", 61 (1987);
Morality and Politics: Reflections on Machiavelli's Prince, in:
"International Journal of Politics, Culture and Society", 3/1 (1989)
[La legittimità del politico (tr. di S. Calabrò, I. Santa Maria, M. Ivaldo),
Milano 1990, Guerini e Associati (Istituto Italiano per gli Studi Filosofici.
Saggi 7)]. Hegels System. Der Idealismus der Subjektivität und das Problem der
Intersubjektivität, 2 Bde., Hamburg 1987, Studienausgabe 1988, Felix Meiner
Verlag [Il sistema di Hegel. L'idealismo della soggettività e il problema
dell'intersoggettività (G. Stelli), Napoli , La Scuola di Pitagora]. Tragweite
und Grenzen der evolutionären Erkenntnistheorie, in: "Zeitschrift für allgemeine
Wissenschaftstheorie", 19 (1988) [Portata e limiti della teoria
evoluzionistica della conoscenza (tr. di C. Sessa e G. Stelli), Napoli 1996, La
Città del Sole]. Die Krise der Gegenwart und die Verantwortung der Philosophie.
Transzendentalpragmatik, Letztbegründung, Ethik, München 1990, C.H.Beck. Vico
und die Idee der Kulturwissenschaft, Einleitung zu Giambattista Vico,
Prinzipien einer neuen Wissenschaft über die gemeinsame Natur der Völker, übs.
von V. Hösle und Ch.Jermann, Hamburg 1990, Felix Meiner [Introduzione a Vico.
La scienza del mondo intersoggettivo (tr. di C. e G. Stelli), Milano 1997,
Guerini e Associati(Istituto Italiano per gli Studi Filosofici. Saggi 28)].
Philosophie der ökologischen Krise. Moskauer Vorträge, München 1991 sgg., C.H.Beck
[Filosofia della crisi ecologica (tr. di P. Scibelli), Torino 1992, Einaudi].
Praktische Philosophie in der modernen Welt, München 1992 sgg., C.H.Beck.
Philosophiegeschichte und objektiver Idealismus, München 1996 sgg., C.H.Beck.
(con Nora K.), Das Café der toten Philosophen. Ein philosophischer Briefwechsel
für Kinder und Erwachsene, München 1996 sgg., C.H.Beck [Aristotele e il
dinosauro. La filosofia spiegata a una ragazzina (tr. di S. Bortoli), Torino
1999, Einaudi]. Die Philosophie und die Wissenschaften, München 1999 sgg.,
C.H.Beck. (con Christian Illies), Darwin, Freiburg etc. 1999, Herder. Woody
Allen. Versuch über das Komische, München 2001, C.H.Beck. Platon
interpretieren, Paderborn etc. 2004, Ferdinand Schöningh [Interpretare Platone
(tr. di B. Marte e F. Perelda), Milano 2007, Guerini e Associati (=Istituto
Italiano per gli Studi Filosofici. Saggi 43)]. Wie sollte eine synthetische
Platondarstellung aussehen? Einige Ueberlegungen angesichts von Kutscheras
neuer Platonmonographie, in: "Logical Analsis and History of
Philosophy", Paderborn 2006, Mentis Verlag, 175-211 [Per una lettura non riduttiva di
Platone (G. Longo), Napoli , La scuola di Pitagora] Die Rangordnung der drei
griechischen Tragiker, Basel 2009, Schwabe.
Giambattista Vico Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel Altri progetti Collabora
a Wikiquote Citazionio su Vittorio Hösle Collabora a Wikimedia Commons
Wikimedia Commons contiene immagini o altri file su Vittorio Hösle Opere di
Vittorio Hösle, . Vittorio Hösle, su Goodreads.
Vittorio Hösle sul RAI Filosofia,
su filosofia.rai.it. Vittorio Hösle sul sito della Pontificia Accademia delle
Scienze Sociali, su pass.va. F
HOMOE-CLITIC
-- The homoclitical/heteroclitical distinction, the: heteroclitical
implicaturum:--
Greek κλιτικός (klitikós, “inflexional”, but
transliterated as ‘heterocliticum’) -- signifying a stem which alternates
between more than one form when declined for grammatical case. Examples of
heteroclitic noun stems in Proto-Indo-European include *wod-r/n-
"water" (nominoaccusative *wódr; genitive *udnés; locative *udén) and
*yékw-r/n- "liver" (nominoaccusative *yékwr, genitive *ikwnés). In
Proto-Indo-European, heteroclitic stems tend to be noun stems with
grammatically inanimate gender. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The heteroclitical implicaturum:
implicaturum, implicitum, explicatum, explicitum: what I learned at Clifton,
and why.” homœmerum: an adjective Grice
adored, from Grecian homoiomeres, ‘of like parts’). Aristotle: “A lump of bronze differs from a statue in
being homoeo-merous. The lump of bronze is divisible into at least
two partial lumps of bronze, whereas the statue is not divisible into statues.”
Having parts, no matter how small, that share the constitutive properties of
the whole. The derivative abstract noun is ‘homœomeria’. The Grecian forms of
the adjective and of its corresponding privative ‘anhomoeomerous’ are used by
Aristotle to distinguish between (a) non-uniform parts of living things, e.g.,
limbs and organs, and (b) biological stuffs, e.g., blood, bone, sap. In spite
of being composed of the four elements, each biological stuff, when taken
individually and without admixtures, is through-and-through F, where F
represents the cluster of the constitutive properties of that stuff. Thus, if a
certain physical volume qualifies as blood, all its mathematically possible sub-volumes,
regardless of size, also qualify as blood. Blood is thus homoeomerous. By
contrast, a face or a stomach or a leaf are an-homoeomerous: the parts of a
face are not a face, etc. In Aristotle’s system, the homœomeria of the
biological stuff is tied to his doctrine of the infinite divisibility of
matter. The homœomerum-heterormerum distinction is prefigured in Plato
(Protagoras 329d). ‘Homœomerous’ is narrow in its application than ‘homogeneous’
and ‘uniform’. We speak of a homogeneous entity even if the properties at issue
are identically present only in samples that fall above a certain size. The
colour of the sea can be homogeneously or uniformly blue; but it is heteromerously
blue. “homoiomeres” and “homoiomereia” also occur –in the ancient sources for a
pre-Aristotelian philosopher, Anaxagoras of Clazomenae, with reference to the
constituent things (“chremata”) involved in his scheme of universal mixture.
Moreover, homœeomeria plays a significant role outside ancient Grecian (or
Griceian) philosophy, notably in twentieth-century accounts of the contrast
between mass terms and count terms or sortals, and the discussion was
introduced by Grice. ANAXAGORAS' THEORY OF
MATTER-I. 17 homoeomerous in Anaxagoras' system falls into one of
these three class. (I. 834), for example, says: 'When he ... by FM Cornford1930. Refs. Grice, “Cornford on Anaxagoras.” homomorphism: cf. isomorphism
-- in Grice’s model theory of conversation, a structure-preserving mapping from
one structure to another: thus the demonstratum is isomorph with the implicaturum,
since every conversational implicaturum can be arrived via an argumentum. A
structure consists of a domain of objects together with a function specifying
interpretations, with respect to that domain, of the relation symbols, function
symbols, and individual symbols of a given calculus. Relations, functions, and
individuals in different structures for a system like System GHP correspond to
one another if they are interpretations of the same symbol of GHP. To call a
mapping “structure-preserving” is to say, first, that if objects in the first
structure bear a certain relation to one another, then their images in the
second structure (under the mapping) bear the corresponding relation to one
another; second, that the value of a function for a given object (or ntuple of
objects) in the first structure has as its image under the mapping the value of
the corresponding function for the image of the object (or n-tuple of images)
in the second structure; and third, that the image in the second structure of
an object in the first is the corresponding object. An isomorphism is a
homomorphism that is oneto-one and whose inverse is also a homomorphism.
homuncularism
-- Grice on the ‘fallacia homunculi’ Grice borrows ‘homunculus’ from St.
Augustine, for a miniature ‘homo’ held to inhabit the brain (or some other
organ) who perceives all the inputs to the sense organs and initiates all the
commands to the muscles. Any theory that posits such an internal agent risks an
infinite regress (what Grice, after Augustine, calls the ‘fallacia homunculi’) since
we can ask whether there is a little man in the little man’s head, responsible
for his perception and action, and so on. Many familiar views of the mind and
its activities seem to require a homunculus. E. g. models of visual perception
that posit an inner picture as its product apparently require a homunculus to
look at the picture, and models of action that treat intentions as commands to
the muscles apparently require a homunculus to issue the commands. It is never
an easy matter to determine whether a theory is committed to the existence of a
homunculus that vitiates the theory, and in some circumstances, a homunculus
can be legitimately posited at intermediate levels of theory. As Grice says, a
homunculus is, shall we say, a bogey-man (to use a New-World expression) only if
he duplicates entire the talents he is rung in to explain. If one can get a
relatively ignorant, narrow-minded, blind homunculus to produce the intelligent
behaviour of the whole, this is progress. Grice calls a theory (in philosophoical
psychology) that posit such a homunculus “homuncular functionalism.” Paracelsus is credited with the first mention of the
homunculus in De homunculis (c. 1529–1532),
and De natura rerum (1537).
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Paracelsus.” HUMAN: Grice uses ‘human,’ technically, as
opposed to ‘person.’ A human is a bio-psycho-social thing, a person is
schatological. Oddly, Varro spent some time trying to explore the root of human
from humus, soil.
Iacono: Grice:
“I love Iacono; for one, he has taken Marx’s chapter on cooperation in Das
Kapital seriously; but as he notes, Marx subverts the order, the symbolic
interaction becomes a super-structure! Iacono recognises the perplexities of
shared intentionality, and finds ways to deal with them conceptually --.” Alfonso
Maurizio Iacono (Agrigento), filosofo. Ordinario di Storia della Filosofia
all'Pisa, nell'anno accademico è stato Visiting Professor all'Université de
Paris 1 (Sorbonne-Panthéon). Fino al ha ricoperto
la carica di Preside della Facoltà di Lettere e Filosofia dell'Pisa. Dal al è
stato Presidente del Sistema Museale di Ateneo (SMA) dell'Pisa. Iacono è
stato fra gli studiosi italiani che negli anni settanta e ottanta si sono
interessati ai rapporti storici e teorici tra filosofia, antropologia e
politica. Fin dai primi anni ottanta, si è inoltre occupato di epistemologia
della complessità, collaborando con Gianluca Bocchi, Mauro Ceruti, e Francisco
Varela, contribuendo all'introduzione dei temi dell'epistemologia della
complessità nel dibattito filosofico italiano. In continuità con quell'impegno
di ricerca, che trovò prima espressione nella pubblicazione de L'evento e
l'osservatore (1987), nel 2005 ha fondato il Laboratorio filosofico sulla complessità
Ichnos. La sua ricerca si è concentrata sui rapporti tra filosofia,
politica e antropologia nel pensiero moderno e contemporaneo, in un costante
confronto con il pensiero antico: al riguardo, ha dedicato numerosi studi
all'analisi storiografica di nozioni quali feticismo, paura e meraviglia, e
all'indagine epistemologica sul tema dell'osservatore. Tali ricerche gravitano
attorno ad una riflessione sul tema dell'altro nelle relazioni storico-sociali
e politiche: da qui i saggi sulle triadi concettuali autonomia, potere,
minorità e storia, verità, finzione. Ne Il borghese e il selvaggio (1982)
Iacono ha analizzato l'influenza della figura di Robinson Crusoe nei paradigmi
filosofico-economici di Turgot e Adam Smith rilevando gli elementi di antropologia
occidentalista là dove la rappresentazione teorica della società e della storia
si mostrava nei suoi aspetti apparentemente semplici, ovvi e trasparenti tali
da nascondere con l'evidenza i presupposti del punto di vista coloniale.
In Teorie del feticismo (1985), la genealogia del concetto di feticismo dalla
sua origine nell'illuminista Charles de Brosses fino a Marx, a Freud e al
pensiero contemporaneo, ha contribuito, sul piano metodologico, all'idea di una
storia della filosofia interpretata attraverso concetti e, sul piano
interpretativo, alla messa in evidenza dei mutamenti semantici del “feticismo”,
un concetto di origine coloniale che si è trasformato con Marx e con Freud in
due modi di operare, rispettivamente sul mondo storico-sociale e sul mondo
della psiche, basati sulla pratica teorica di un'antropologia dall'interno. Le
fétichisme. Histoire d'un concept del 1992 è ancora oggi uno dei testi più
citati sull'argomento. Nel 1998, in Paura e meraviglia, i temi storiografici
dell'illuminismo e del feticismo vengono ripresi e ridiscussi alla luce del
pensiero contemporaneo. Il problema filosofico e politico
dell'antropologia dall'interno è stato sviluppato attraverso la questione
epistemologica dell'osservatore a cui Iacono ha dedicato alcuni scritti teorici
tra i quali L'evento e l'osservatore (1987). Influenzato da Marx, ma anche da
Foucault e da Bateson, Iacono ha analizzato le teorie della storia di Bossuet,
Vico e Droysen attraverso il tema del ruolo dell'osservatore che interpreta gli
eventi sociali e naturali nella loro storicità. Interessato alle teorie
contemporanee dell'autorganizzazione biologica (Atlan, Maturana, Varela),
Iacono ha cercato di reinterpretare il senso epistemologico della storia, la
parzialità dei punti di vista impliciti dell'osservatore e delle sue visioni
del mondo, la questione dell'altro, il rapporto tra scienze storico-sociali e
scienze naturali, alla luce del concetto di complessità. In questa chiave, in
Tra individui e cose del 1995, Iacono raccoglieva i risultati di ricerche che,
all'interno dei rapporti fra filosofia, antropologia e politica, si interrogava
attraverso Gregory Bateson sull'idea del ‘pensare per storie' come momento
metodologico e critico di un'antropologia dall'interno in una società come
quella occidentale moderna dove le cose si sostituiscono feticisticamente agli
uomini e il conformismo si mostra incessantemente e paradossalmente come
l'irrompere del nuovo. Il problema della critica sociale e dell'autonomia
individuale come decisivo in una società occidentale che domina il mondo
dichiarandosi libera e democratica è al centro del libro Autonomia, potere,
minorità (2000, Premio Speciale Pozzale Luigi Russo 2001). Partendo dallo
scritto di Kant Risposta alla domanda: che cos'è l'Illuminismo?, Iacono si
chiede perché in una società istituzionalmente ‘libera' e ‘democratica',
all'indomani della fine dei regimi socialisti, il desiderio di uscire dallo
stato di minorità non riesce a vincere il contrastante desiderio di rimanere
nello stato di minorità, perché in sostanza è così forte la paura di essere
autonomi. La questione dell'autonomia ha portato Iacono a interessarsi ai
temi della verità, dell'illusione e dell'inganno. Per un'antropologia
dall'interno occorre vedere con altri occhi e per vedere con altri occhi è
necessario acquisire uno sguardo d'altrove. I temi dell'universalismo e della
questione dell'altro sono discussi in quest'ottica in Storia, verità, finzione
del 2006. La meraviglia che connota il tono emotivo della conoscenza
filosofica deve passare attraverso lo straniamento: essere straniero a te
stesso affinché l'altro non sia straniero a te. L'autonomia può realizzarsi
soltanto nella relazione con l'altro e non, come se l'è immaginato il pensiero
moderno, recidendo ogni legame per poi andarlo a costituire da padroni. Ma
un'antropologia dall'interno è continuamente in tensione con un senso comune
che, conservando le verità condivise ovvero i pregiudizi, tende a mostrarle
come ovvie, naturali, eterne, uniche, a renderle dunque salde e indiscutibili.
Ci si dimentica allora che viviamo in molti mondi, in mondi intermedi (Mondi
intermedi e complessità, 2005), e che siamo capaci, con la coda dell'occhio, di
percepire sempre un mondo altro da quello in cui siamo immersi. Perdendo questa
percezione perdiamo la nostra capacità di uscire da noi stessi e dunque la
facoltà di essere autonomi. L'illusione, attraverso cui ci si approssima alla
verità, che è consapevolezza critica di un'illusione stessa (Nietzsche,
Pirandello), si trasforma in inganno e in autoinganno, sulle cui basi si
produce il rischio della costituzione delle regole del consenso, in una società
libera ma senza autonomia. Nel ha
pubblicato L'illusione e il sostituto. Riprodurre, imitare, rappresentare.
Un'altra direzione di studi riguarda le genealogie dell'immagine
della finestra e del concetto di illusione nella storia del pensiero
occidentale. In quest'ambito di riflessione Iacono ha realizzato con il regista
Renzo Boldrini e l'artista Andrea Bastogi (produzione Giallo Mare Minimal Teatro)
una conferenza multimediale sullo spettatore e i suoi paradossi, dal titolo Con
altri occhi. Iacono dirige il bimestrale di politica e cultura Il
Grandevetro. Ha collaborato per anni al quotidiano il manifesto. Fa parte del
Comitato scientifico della Scuola di formazione e ricerca sui conflitti
Polemos. Fa parte del comitato scientifico della Fondazione Collegio San Carlo
di Modena. Ha laureato molti studenti al polo universitario universitario
penitenziario della casa circondariale Don Bosco di Pisa e tuttora collabora a
progetti e iniziative per un'effettiva opera di recupero del detenuto che
sconta la pena. Opere (selezione) Saggi Il borghese e il selvaggio, Pisa
2003 (2nd. ed.) Teorie del feticismo, Milano 1985 L'evento e l'osservatore, Bergamo
1987; trad. fr., L'evenement et l'observateur Paris 1998 Le fétichisme.
Histoire d'un concept, Paris 1992 Fetischismus, in H.J. Sandkühler (Hg.),
Europäische Enzyklopädie zu Philosophie und Wissenschaften, Bd. 2, Felix, Meiner
Verlag, Hamburg The American Indians and the Ancients of Europe, in The Classical Tradition and the
Americans, I, Berlin-New York 1994 Tra
individui e cose, Roma 1995 Paura e meraviglia. Storie filosofiche del XVIII
secolo, Catanzaro 1998 Autonomia, potere, minorità, Milano 2000 (Premio
Speciale Pozzale Luigi Russo 2001) Caminhos de saida do estado de menoridate,
Rio de Janeiro, 2001 (con A. G. Gargani), Mondi intermedi e complessità, Pisa
2005 Storia, verità e finzione, Roma 2006 L'illusione e il sostituto.
Riprodurre, imitare, rappresentare, Bruno Mondadori, Milano The History and Theory of Fetishism (trad. di
Teorie del feticismo), Palgrave Macmillan US, New York Il sogno di una copia. Del doppio, del dubbio,
della malinconia, Guerini Scientifica, Milano
Storie di mondi intermedi, Edizioni ETS, Pisa , Studi su Karl Marx. La
cooperazione, l'individuo sociale, le merci, Edizioni ETS, Pisa , Filosofia alle elementari (con S. Viti), Le
domande sono ciliegie, Manifestolibri, Roma 2000 (con S. Viti), Per mari
aperti. Viaggi tra filosofia e poesia nelle scuole elementari, Roma 2003
Filosofia alle scuole superiori La giustizia è l'utile del più forte? Incontro
con gli studenti del Liceo classico «Empedocle» di Agrigento, Pisa 2000 Ra
Racconti L'accelerato, in Favolare Antonia Casini e Giovanni Vannozzi, MdS
editore, Pisa, La scelta, in Gabbie,
Michele Bulzomì, Antonia Casini, Giovanni Vannozzi, MdS editore, Pisa Note
il sito è momentaneamente disattivato
PSYCHOMEDIAJOURNAL OF EUROPEAN PSYCHOANALYSISAlfonso M. IaconoFrancisco
Varela and the Concept of Autonomy
Alfonso Maurizio Iacono, su siusa.archivi.beniculturali.it, Sistema
Informativo Unificato per le Soprintendenze Archivistiche.
Illuminati – Grice: “I like Illuminati, especially his essay on
Rousseay, between solipsism and conversation!” -- Augusto Illuminati, aforismi
e citazioni in libertà. Jump to navigationJump to search Augusto Illuminati, filosofo
italiano. La città e il desiderio Le trascrizioni sono da controllare e va
specificata in l'edizione di riferimento
Le trascrizioni sono da controllare e va specificata in l'edizione di riferimento Viene meno un modo di fare in cui la
soggettività potente si appropria il mondo subordinando le altre potenze
soggettive e realizza la sua essenza destinale mediante adeguati meccanismi di
rappresentazione e manipolazione tecnica. ( 108-109) Come utilizzare regole
pubblicamente valide senza colpevolizzare e controllare dall'altro le forme di
vita degli uomini è precisamente l'antinomia della cittadinanza. (p. 109) La
politicizzazione di sfere inabituali va insieme alla diserzione di istituzioni
sclerotiche. Una ricaduta pratica ne è l'integrazione delle strutture
rappresentative con nuove lobbies o la richiesta di quote per minoranze (p.
115) Nel lasciar-essere che si contrappone alla tracotanza istituzionale
convivono cosi l'ancora-non-rappresentato che cerca lobbisticamente
rappresentazione, e rifiuto radicare di rappresentazione. (p. 115) Altri
progetti Categoria: Filosofi italiani|
Incardona, Grice: “I like Incardona; for one, he gave seminars on ‘la
costanza dell’io,’ as I did! Second, he used Greek freely, as I do! Third, he
is slightly incomprehensible, as I am SAID to be!” -- Nunzio Incardona, filosofo. Professore di filosofia a 'Palermo.
Ha studiato nel Liceo classico Ruggero Settimo. È stato direttore, dal 1982,
del Giornale di Metafisica, fondato da Michele Federico Sciacca. Tra gli altri
ha collaborato con Giuseppe Masi. La tematica fondamentale della filosofia di
Nunzio Incardona è la "filosofia del principio", un percorso nella
storia della filosofia occidentale e nel pensiero suoi protagonisti volto
all'interrogazione riguardo al fondamento e all'archè. Le due categorie
concettuali attraverso cui Incardona legge la storia della filosofia sono
l'arcaicità, identificata con Aristotele, e l'arcaismo, identificato con Hegel.
Aristotele ed Hegel sono infatti nella filosofia del principio incardoniana le
due porte, l'inizio e la fine, l'elemento e il compimento della filosofia. Il
percorso del pensiero è per Incardona un percorso aporetico, in cui la
dialettica assume l'aspetto di un dialogo senza soluzione fra tensione naturale
alla conoscenza e fallimento destinale dell'impresa conoscitiva. A Nunzio
Incardona è succeduto, nella direzione del Giornale di Metafisica, Giuseppe
Nicolaci. Incardona è un'importante figura della filosofia italiana dell'ultimo
novecento anche per l'influenza che ha esercitato nel campo dell'ermeneutica e
della filosofia continentale. Il suo magistero ha portato alla creazione della
scuola di Palermo. Il pensiero: breve
sinossi Il contributo determinante di Nunzio Incardona è stata la sua
riflessione non scettica ma aporetica sull'archè. La questione aristotelica dei
principi (ontologici ed epistemologici) e del principio (inteso in senso
conoscitivo come principio di non contraddizione e in senso teologico come Dio)
viene colta da Incardona ed elevata da questione logica a questione
esistenziale. Compagni di strada naturali, sebbene fortemente criticati dal
filosofo palermitano, sono, in questa sorta di teologia negativa, Jacques
Derrida e Martin Heidegger. In essi è infatti rintracciabile la tematica
privativa e mistico-antirazionale del rapporto con l'assoluto. L'unica cosa che
si può dire dell'assoluto è che esso non è alla nostra portata, esso nasconde
al filosofo il volto come all'esule è nascosta la patria. Sebbene Incardona
veda nella filosofia post-hegeliana una sorta di "pleonasmo" che non
ha più alcuna utilità nella società contemporanea (antifilosofia), sembra che
le sue intuizioni più originali e più feconde nascano proprio da una
rielaborazione personale delle tematiche ermeneutiche del secondo
Heidegger. Opere principali Idealismo
della filosofia ed esperienza storica, L'Epos, Palermo, 1995. Idealismo tedesco
e neo-idealismo italiano, L'Epos, Palermo, 1995. Gli inferi del principio.
Interrogazione e invocazione, L'Epos, Palermo, 1994. Karpòs, L'Epos, Palermo,
1991. Meditatio in curriculo mortis, L'Epos, Palermo, 1990. Kéntron, L'Epos,
Palermo, 1988. Rosaria Caldarone,
"L'inclusione dell’altro. Profilo di Giuseppe Nicolaci", Epekeina.
International Journal of Ontology, History and Critics.
Infantino: Grice:
“I like Infantino: for one, he prefaced an essay on ‘the perils of solidarity,’
which is all my conversational pragmatics is about!” -- Lorenzo Infantino
(Gioia Tauro), filosofo. Pprofessore a Roma. Ha studiato economia, sociologia,
politica e teoria della conoscenza. Ha svolto la parte prevalente della sua
ricerca presso l’Oxford (Linacre College). Sul “Times Literary Supplement”,
Kenneth Minogue lo ha definito uno “studioso di orientamento anglo-austriaco”.
La sua attività intellettuale si svolge infatti nel solco tracciato da
Friedrich A. von Hayek che, com’è noto, ha coniugato le acquisizioni di
Mandeville e dei moralisti scozzesi con quelle della Scuola Austriaca di
Economia. Infantino si è intensamente dedicato alla divulgazione di
classiche opere della Scuola Austriaca, curando l’edizione italiana di numerosi
testi di Menger, Boehm-Bawerk, Mises e Hayek, apparsi tutti presso la casa
editrice Rubbettino, nella collana editoriale “Biblioteca Austriaca”. Ha
inoltre pubblicato importanti risultati della sua ricerca, in quattro
principali volumi. 1) L’ordine senza piano, apparso originariamente in italiano
nel 1995, che ha avuto poi varie riedizioni. Il testo è stato pubblicato in
inglese dalla Routledge di Londra nel 1998 e ha ricevuto favorevoli recensioni
da parte di Kenneth Minogue e Andrew Cohen; il libro è stato tradotto anche in
spagnolo dalla Union Editorial di Madrid. 2) Ignoranza e libertà è apparso nel
1999 ed è stato pubblicato in inglese dalla Routledge (2003) e in spagnolo
dalla Union Editorial (2004). 3) Individualismo, mercato e storia delle idee
(2008), apparso anche in spagnolo, presso la Union Editorial (). 4) Potere. La
dimensione politica dell’azione umana (), la cui versione inglese è stata
pubblicata dalla Palgrave Macmillan (). Lorenzo Infantino vede nelle
conseguenze inintenzionali delle azioni umane intenzionali l’oggetto delle
scienze sociali, che vengono in tal modo affrancate da qualsiasi psicologismo.
È il tema sollevato da Mandeville e dai moralisti scozzesi, ripreso poi con
forza da Carl Menger e da Friedrich A. von Hayek. Non sono le intenzioni dei
singoli (o quelli che sono stati infelicemente chiamati “spiriti animali”) a
spiegare i fenomeni sociali. Occorre piuttosto individuare le condizioni che
rendono possibile o impossibile un dato evento. Tale tradizione di ricerca ha
come suo presupposto il riconoscimento dell’ignoranza e della fallibilità
umane. Da cui discende l’abbattimento del mito del “Grande Legislatore”, il cui
posto viene occupato dal processo sociale, cioè dalla cooperazione volontaria.
Questa costituisce un procedimento di esplorazione dell’ignoto e di correzione
degli errori. Ed è su tale teoria della società che Infantino si muove per
spiegare il fenomeno del potere, da lui studiato come potere infrasociale,
derivante cioè dall’interazione fra gli uomini, e il potere pubblico, ossia il
potere d’intervento dello Stato nella vita sociale. La competizione minimizza
il potere infrasociale, perché non c’è un’unica persona che offre o un’unica
persona che richiede. Il potere pubblico si minimizza o si limita, attribuendo
allo Stato un’esclusiva funzione di servizio nei confronti della cooperazione
sociale volontaria. Lorenzo Infantino ha pubblicato di recente una
raccolta di saggi, Cercatori di Libertà (Rubbettino, ), in cui è ospitato un
suo scritto che ha fatto da introduzione alla traduzione italiana del volume (A
proposito di Rousseau), dedicato da David Hume alla rottura dei suoi rapporti
con Jean-Jacques Rousseau; gli altri saggi della raccolta si occupano di
Benjamin Constant, Ludwig von Mises, Friedrich A. von Hayek, Bruno Leoni,
Robert Nozick, José Ortega y Gasset, Luigi Einaudi. Sempre nel , Raimondo
Cubeddu e Pietro Reichlin hanno curato un volume (Rubbettino Editore) di
scritti in onore di Lorenzo Infantino, a cui hanno contribuito numerosi
studiosi di ispirazione liberale. Nel 2008, Infantino ha partecipato
all’Austrian Colloquium della New York University, e ha tenuto la Hayek
Memorial Lecture presso il Ludwig von Mises Institute di Auburn (Alabama). È
stato per due volte presidente dell’Italian Linacre Society; è presidente della
Fondazione HayekItalia. Pubblicazioni Lorenzo Infantino , Sociologia dell'imperialismo:
interpretazioni liberali, Milano, FrancoAngeli, 1980, 88-204-1796-0. Dall'utopia al totalitarismo:
Marx, Dio e l'impossibile, Roma, Borla, 1985,
88-263-0647-8. Ortega y Gasset: una introduzione, Roma, Armando,
1990, 88-7144-193-1. Ludwig von Mises e
la societa aperta, Roma, Quaderni del Centro di metodologia delle scienze
socialiLUISS Guido Carli, 1992, .
L'ordine senza piano: le ragioni dell'individualismo metodologico, Roma, NIS, L'ordine senza piano: le ragioni dell'individualismo
metodologico, 2ª ed., Roma, Armando, 1998,
88-7144-863-4. L'ordine senza piano: le ragioni dell'individualismo
metodologico, 3ª ed., Roma, Armando, 2Individualism in Modern Thought: From
Adam Smith to Hayek, Londra-New York, Routledge, 1998, 0-415-18524-6.El orden sin plan: las razones
del individualismo metodológico, Madrid, Union Editorial, 2Metodo e mercato,
Soveria Mannelli, Rubbettino, 1998,
88-7284-699-4. Ignoranza e libertà, Soveria Mannelli, Rubbettino,
1999, 88-7284-841-5.Ignorance and
Liberty, Londra-New York, Routledge, .Ignorancia y Libertad, Madrid, Union
Editorial, 2004, 978-84-7209-405-5.
Dario Antiseri e Lorenzo Infantino , Destra e sinistra due parole ormai
inutili, Soveria Mannelli, Rubbettino,
Dario Antiseri e Lorenzo Infantino
Scuola austriaca di economia: album di famiglia , Soveria Mannelli,
Rubbettino, 1999, 88-7284-822-9.Ensayos
de Teorìa Econòmica, Madrid, Union Editorial, Dario Antiseri e Lorenzo
Infantino , Le ragioni degli sconfitti: nella lotta per la scuola libera, Roma,
Armando, Lorenzo Infantino e Nicola Iannello
, Ludwig von Mises: le scienze sociali nella grande Vienna, Soveria
Mannelli, Rubbettino, 2004,
88-7284-841-5. Individualismo, mercato e storia delle idee, Soveria
Mannelli, Rubbettino, .Individualismo, mercado y historia de las ideas, Madrid,
Union Editorial, Potere. La dimensione
politica dell'azione umana, Soveria Mannelli, Rubbettino, , 978-88-498-3732-2. Nicola Iannello e Lorenzo
Infantino , Idee di libertà. Economia, diritto, società, Soveria Mannelli, Rubbettino,
Cercatori di libertà, Soveria Mannelli, Rubbettino, . Raimondo Cubeddu e Pietro
Reichlin , Individuo, libertà e potere. Studi in onore di Lorenzo Infantino,
Soveria Mannelli, Rubbettino, . Infrasocial Power. Political Dimensions of
Human Action, Palgrave MacMillan, New York, . trad, inglese di Potere: la
dimensione politica dell'azione umana, Rubbettino, Soveria Mannelli, .
Note Opere di Lorenzo Infantino. Registrazioni di Lorenzo Infantino, su
RadioRadicale.it, Radio Radicale.
iorio: Grice: “The line and
the circle is what Chomsky would call a NP, but there’s two books on it by
Italian philosophers! Oddly, I visited Sorrento on my way to Greece!” -- Paolo
D'Iorio (Seravezza), filosofo. Si è laureato in filosofia all'Pisa con Giuliano
Campioni perfezionandosi poi alla Scuola Normale Superiore. È stato borsista
della Stiftung Weimarer Klassik di Weimar, dell'Pisa (formazione
post-dottorale) e della Technische Universität di Berlino. Nel 1998 è stato
assunto al Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique di Parigi. Nel 2001 ha ricevuto il premio Sofja
Kovalevskaja della Fondazione von Humboldt e del Ministero della ricerca
tedesco e ha diretto per alcuni anni un'équipe di ricerca all'Monaco di iera.
Dal 2007 al ha effettuato un soggiorno
di ricerca a Oxford come visiting fellow dell'Oxford Internet Institute e
membro della Maison Française d'Oxford e dell'Oxford e-Research Centre. Attualmente insegna all'École Normale
Supérieure di Parigi e dirige l'Institut des Textes et Manuscrits Modernes
(ITEM). Specialista di Nietzsche, si è
occupato del rapporto del filosofo con i suoi contemporanei e con la Grecia
antica. Si interessa inoltre dell'uso di Internet per l'edizione critica di
testi filosofici. È direttore editoriale di Nietzsche Source, un sito web
dedicato alla pubblicazione di edizioni e altri contributi riguardanti la vita
e l'opera di Friedrich Nietzsche. I contenuti del sito possono essere
liberamente utilizzati per la ricerca e l'insegnamento. Principali pubblicazioni La linea e il
circolo. Cosmologia e filosofia dell'eterno ritorno in Nietzsche. Genova,
Pantograf, 1995 Le voyage de Nietzsche à Sorrente. Genèse de la philosophie de
l'esprit libre, Paris, CNRS Éditions, Juin ,
246; trad. port. Nietzsche na Itália A viagem que mudou os rumos da
filosofia, Zahar, Rio de Janeiro, ; traduzione turca Nietzsche’nin Sorrento
Yolculuğu, Isbank Culture Publishing, Istanbul, ; traduzione spagnola El viaje
de Nietzsche a Sorrento. Una travesía crucial hacia el espíritu libre, Gedisa,
Barcelona, ; traduzione americana Nietzsche’s Journey to Sorrento. Genesis of
the Philosoophy of the Free Spirit, University of Chicago Press, . 'Friedrich
Nietzsche, Les philosophes préplatoniciens. Combas, l'éclat 1994 (prima edizione
in traduzione francese del manoscritto delle lezioni di Nietzsche sui filosofi
preplatonici, introdotta e commentata assieme a Francesco Fronterotta)
Friedrich Nietzsche, "Écrits de jeunesse" P. D'Iorio et F.
Fronterotta, in Friedrich Nietzsche, Oeuvres,
I, Bibliothèque de la Pléiade, Paris, Gallimard, Giuliano Campioni,
Paolo D'Iorio, Maria Cristina Fornari, Francesco Fronterotta, Andrea Orsucci,
unter Mitwirkung von Renate Müller-Buck, "Nietzsches persönliche
Bibliothek", De Gruyter, Berlin-New York, 2003, 736 p. Mazzino Montinari,
'La volonté de puissance' n'existe pas, a cura e con una postfazione di P.
D'Iorio, Paris, Éditions de l'éclat, 1996. Genesi, critica, edizioneD'Iorio e
N. Ferrand, Pisa, Scuola Normale Superiore, 1999. "Bibliothèques d'écrivains",
sous la direction de Paolo D'Iorio et Daniel Ferrer, Paris, éditions du CNRS,
2001, 214 p. HyperNietzsche. Modèle d'un hypertexte savant sur Internet pour la
recherche en sciences humaines. Questions philosophiques, problèmes juridiques,
outils informatiques", Paolo D'Iorio. Paris, Presses Universitaires de
France, Paolo D'Iorio, Michele Barbera, «Scholarsource: A Digital
Infrastructure for the Humanities», in Th. Bartscherer and R. Coover (éds.)
"Switching Codes. Thinking through New Technology in the Humanities and
the Arts", Chicago, University of Chicago Press, , 61–87. Note
Pagina di Paolo D'Iorio sul sito dell'ITEM/ENS Nietzsche Source Friedrich Nietzsche/
IN-LATUM: illatum, f. illātĭo (inl- ), ōnis, f. in-fero,
a logical inference, conclusion: “vel illativum rogamentum. quod ex acceptionibus colligitur et infertur,” A Dogm. Plat. 3, 34, 15.infero: to conclude, infer, draw an inference, Cic. Inv. 1, 47, 87; Quint. 5, 11, 27. ILLATUM -- inference, the
process of drawing a conclusion from premises or assumptions, or, loosely, the
conclusion so drawn. An argument can be merely a number of statements of which
one is designated the conclusion and the rest are designated premises. Whether
the premises imply the conclusion is thus independent of anyone’s actual
beliefs in either of them. Belief, however, is essential to inference.
Inference occurs only if someone, owing to believing the premises, begins to
believe the conclusion or continues to believe the conclusion with greater
confidence than before. Because inference requires a subject who has beliefs,
some requirements of (an ideally) acceptable inference do not apply to abstract
arguments: one must believe the premises; one must believe that the premises
support the conclusion; neither of these beliefs induction, eliminative
inference 426 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 426 may be based on one’s
prior belief in the conclusion. W. E. Johnson called these the epistemic conditions
of inference. In a reductio ad absurdum argument that deduces a
self-contradiction from certain premises, not all steps of the argument will
correspond to steps of inference. No one deliberately infers a contradiction.
What one infers, in such an argument, is that certain premises are
inconsistent. Acceptable inferences can fall short of being ideally acceptable
according to the above requirements. Relevant beliefs are sometimes indefinite.
Infants and children infer despite having no grasp of the sophisticated notion
of support. One function of idealization is to set standards for that which
falls short. It is possible to judge how nearly inexplicit, automatic,
unreflective, lessthan-ideal inferences meet ideal requirements. In ordinary
speech, ‘infer’ often functions as a synonym of ‘imply’, as in ‘The new tax law
infers that we have to calculate the value of our shrubbery’. Careful
philosophical writing avoids this usage. Implication is, and inference is not,
a relation between statements. Valid deductive inference corresponds to a valid
deductive argument: it is logically impossible for all the premises to be true
when the conclusion is false. That is, the conjunction of all the premises and
the negation of the conclusion is inconsistent. Whenever a conjunction is
inconsistent, there is a valid argument for the negation of any conjunct from
the other conjuncts. (Relevance logic imposes restrictions on validity to avoid
this.) Whenever one argument is deductively valid, so is another argument that
goes in a different direction. (1) ‘Stacy left her slippers in the kitchen’
implies (2) ‘Stacy had some slippers’. Should one acquainted with Stacy and the
kitchen infer (2) from (1), or infer not-(1) from not-(2), or make neither
inference? Formal logic tells us about implication and deductive validity, but
it cannot tell us when or what to infer. Reasonable inference depends on
comparative degrees of reasonable belief. An inference in which every premise
and every step is beyond question is a demonstrative inference. (Similarly,
reasoning for which this condition holds is demonstrative reasoning.) Just as
what is beyond question can vary from one situation to another, so can what
counts as demonstrative. The term presumably derives from Aristotle’s Posterior
Analytics. Understanding Aristotle’s views on demonstration requires
understanding his general scheme for classifying inferences. Not all inferences
are deductive. In an inductive inference, one infers from an observed
combination of characteristics to some similar unobserved combination.
‘Reasoning’ like ‘painting’, and ‘frosting’, and many other words, has a
process–product ambiguity. Reasoning can be a process that occurs in time or it
can be a result or product. A letter to the editor can both contain reasoning
and be the result of reasoning. It is often unclear whether a word such as
‘statistical’ that modifies the words ‘inference’ or ‘reasoning’ applies
primarily to stages in the process or to the content of the product. One view,
attractive for its simplicity, is that the stages of the process of reasoning
correspond closely to the parts of the product. Examples that confirm this view
are scarce. Testing alternatives, discarding and reviving, revising and
transposing, and so on, are as common to the process of reasoning as to other
creative activities. A product seldom reflects the exact history of its
production. In An Examination of Sir William Hamilton’s Philosophy, J. S. Mill
says that reasoning is a source from which we derive new truths (Chapter 14).
This is a useful saying so long as we remember that not all reasoning is
inference. -- inference to the best explanation, an inference by which one
concludes that something is the case on the grounds that this best explains
something else one believes to be the case. Paradigm examples of this kind of
inference are found in the natural sciences, where a hypothesis is accepted on
the grounds that it best explains relevant observations. For example, the
hypothesis that material substances have atomic structures best explains a
range of observations concerning how such substances interact. Inferences to
the best explanation occur in everyday life as well. Upon walking into your
house you observe that a lamp is lying broken on the floor, and on the basis of
this you infer that the cat has knocked it over. This is plausibly analyzed as
an inference to the best explanation; you believe that the cat has knocked over
the lamp because this is the best explanation for the lamp’s lying broken on
the floor. The nature of inference to the best explanation and the extent of
its use are both controversial. Positions that have been taken include: (a)
that it is a distinctive kind of inductive reasoning; (b) inference rule
inference to the best explanation 427 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 427
that all good inductive inferences involve inference to the best explanation;
and (c) that it is not a distinctive kind of inference at all, but is rather a
special case of enumerative induction. Another controversy concerns the criteria
for what makes an explanation best. Simplicity, cognitive fit, and explanatory
power have all been suggested as relevant merits, but none of these notions is
well understood. Finally, a skeptical problem arises: inference to the best
explanation is plausibly involved in both scientific and commonsense knowledge,
but it is not clear why the best explanation that occurs to a person is likely
to be true. -- inferential knowledge, a kind of “indirect” knowledge, namely,
knowledge based on or resulting from inference. Assuming that knowledge is at
least true, justified belief, inferential knowledge is constituted by a belief
that is justified because it is inferred from certain other beliefs. The
knowledge that 7 equals 7 seems non-inferential. We do not infer from anything
that 7 equals 7it is obvious and self-evident. The knowledge that 7 is the cube
root of 343, in contrast, seems inferential. We cannot know this without
inferring it from something else, such as the result obtained when multiplying
7 times 7 times 7. Two sorts of inferential relations may be distinguished. ‘I
inferred that someone died because the flag is at half-mast’ may be true
because yesterday I acquired the belief about the flag, which caused me to
acquire the further belief that someone died. ‘I inferentially believe that
someone died because the flag is at halfmast’ may be true now because I retain
the belief that someone died and it remains based on my belief about the flag.
My belief that someone died is thus either episodically or structurally
inferential. The episodic process is an occurrent, causal relation among belief
acquisitions. The structural basing relation may involve the retention of
beliefs, and need not be occurrent. (Some reserve ‘inference’ for the episodic
relation.) An inferential belief acquired on one basis may later be held on a
different basis, as when I forget I saw a flag at half-mast but continue to
believe someone died because of news reports. That “How do you know?” and
“Prove it!” always seem pertinent suggests that all knowledge is inferential, a
version of the coherence theory. The well-known regress argument seems to show,
however, that not all knowledge can be inferential, which is a version of
foundationalism. For if S knows something inferentially, S must infer it
correctly from premises S knows to be true. The question whether those premises
are also known inferentially begins either an infinite regress of inferences
(which is humanly impossible) or a circle of justification (which could not
constitute good reasoning). Which sources of knowledge are non-inferential
remains an issue even assuming foundationalism. When we see that an apple is
red, e.g., our knowledge is based in some manner on the way the apple looks.
“How do you know it is red?” can be answered: “By the way it looks.” This
answer seems correct, moreover, only if an inference from the way the apple
looks to its being red would be warranted. Nevertheless, perceptual beliefs are
formed so automatically that talk of inference seems inappropriate. In
addition, inference as a process whereby beliefs are acquired as a result of
holding other beliefs may be distinguished from inference as a state in which
one belief is sustained on the basis of others. Knowledge that is inferential
in one way need not be inferential in the other. When it came to
rationalityGrice was especially irritated by the adjective ‘theoretical’ as
applied to ‘reason’. “Kant was cleverer when he used the metaphorical ‘pure’!”
-- theoretical reasonGrice preferred ‘conversational reason.’ “There’s no need
to divide reason into pure and impure!’ -- in its traditional sense, a faculty
or capacity whose province is theoretical knowledge or inquiry; more broadly,
the faculty concerned with ascertaining truth of any kind also sometimes called
speculative reason. In Book 6 of his Metaphysics, Aristotle identifies
mathematics, physics, and theology as the subject matter of theoretical reason.
Theoretical reason is traditionally distinguished from practical reason, a
faculty exercised in determining guides to good conduct and in deliberating
about proper courses of action. Aristotle contrasts it, as well, with
productive reason, which is concerned with “making”: shipbuilding, sculpting,
healing, and the like. Kant distinguishes theoretical reason not only from
practical reason but also sometimes from the faculty of understanding, in which
the categories originate. Theoretical reason, possessed of its own a priori
concepts “ideas of reason”, regulates the activities of the understanding. It
presupposes a systematic unity in nature, sets the goal for scientific inquiry,
and determines the “criterion of empirical truth” Critique of Pure Reason.
Theoretical reason, on Kant’s conception, seeks an explanatory “completeness”
and an “unconditionedness” of being that transcend what is possible in
experience. Reason, as a faculty or capacity, may be regarded as a hybrid
composed of theoretical and practical reason broadly construed or as a unity
having both theoretical and practical functions. Some commentators take
Aristotle to embrace the former conception and Kant the latter. Reason is
contrasted sometimes with experience, sometimes with emotion and desire,
sometimes with faith. Its presence in human beings has often been regarded as
constituting the primary difference between human and non-human animals; and
reason is sometimes represented as a divine element in human nature. Socrates,
in Plato’s Philebus, portrays reason as “the king of heaven and earth.” Hobbes,
in his Leviathan, paints a more sobering picture, contending that reason, “when
we reckon it among the faculties of the mind, . . . is nothing but
reckoning that is, adding and
subtracting of the consequences of
general names agreed upon for the marking and signifying of our thoughts.”
IN-LUMINATUM:
illuminism:
d’Alembert, Jean Le Rond, philosopher, and Encyclopedist. According to Grimm,
d’Alembert was the prime luminary of the philosophic party. Cf. the French
ideologues that influenced Humboldt. An abandoned, illegitimate child, he nonetheless
received an outstanding education at the Jansenist Collège des Quatre-Nations
in Paris. He read law for a while, tried medicine, and settled on mathematics.
In 1743, he published an acclaimed Treatise of Dynamics. Subsequently, he
joined the Paris Academy of Sciences and contributed decisive works on
mathematics and physics. In 1754, he was elected to the Academy, of which he later became permanent
secretary. In association with Diderot, he launched the Encyclopedia, for which
he wrote the epoch-making Discours préliminaire 1751 and numerous entries on
science. Unwilling to compromise with the censorship, he resigned as coeditor
in 1758. In the Discours préliminaire, d’Alembert specified the divisions of
the philosophical discourse on man: pneumatology, logic, and ethics. Contrary
to Christian philosophies, he limited pneumatology to the investigation of the
human soul. Prefiguring positivism, his Essay on the Elements of Philosophy
1759 defines philosophy as a comparative examination of physical phenomena.
Influenced by Bacon, Locke, and Newton, d’Alembert’s epistemology associates
Cartesian psychology with the sensory origin of ideas. Though assuming the
universe to be rationally ordered, he discarded metaphysical questions as
inconclusive. The substance, or the essence, of soul and matter, is unknowable.
Agnosticism ineluctably arises from his empirically based naturalism.
D’Alembert is prominently featured in D’Alembert’s Dream 1769, Diderot’s
dialogical apology for materialism. Grice’s
illuminism“reason enlightens us” Enlightenment, a late eighteenth-century
international movement in thought, with important social and political
ramifications. The Enlightenment is at once a style, an attitude, a temper critical, secular, skeptical, empirical, and
practical. It is also characterized by core beliefs in human rationality, in
what it took to be “nature,” and in the “natural feelings” of mankind. Four of
its most prominent exemplars are Hume, Thomas Jefferson, Kant, and Voltaire.
The Enlightenment belief in human rationality had several aspects. 1 Human
beings are free to the extent that their actions are carried out for a reason.
Actions prompted by traditional authority, whether religious or political, are
therefore not free; liberation requires weakening if not also overthrow of this
authority. 2 Human rationality is universal, requiring only education for its
development. In virtue of their common rationality, all human beings have
certain rights, among them the right to choose and shape their individual
destinies. 3 A final aspect of the belief in human rationality was that the
true forms of all things could be discovered, whether of the universe Newton’s
laws, of the mind associationist psychology, of good government the U.S.
Constitution, of a happy life which, like good government, was “balanced”, or
of beautiful architecture Palladio’s principles. The Enlightenment was
preeminently a “formalist” age, and prose, not poetry, was its primary means of
expression. The Enlightenment thought of itself as a return to the classical
ideas of the Grecians and more especially the Romans. But in fact it provided
one source of the revolutions that shook Europe and America at the end of the
eighteenth century, and it laid the intellectual foundations for both the
generally scientific worldview and the liberal democratic society, which,
despite the many attacks made on them, continue to function as cultural ideals.
IN-LUSUM: in-nludo -- illusion: Grice: “The etymology of illusion is fascinatinglusion is
of course from ludo, game, so ‘inludo’ is the verb we must be look forif you
have an illusion, you are ‘playing with yourself’ -- cf. veridical memories,
who needs them? hallucination is Grice’s topic.Malcolm argues in Dreaming and
Skepticism and in his Dreaming that the notion of a dream qua conscious
experience that occurs at a definite time and has definite duration during
sleep, is unintelligible. This contradicts the views of philosophers like
Descartes (and indeed Moore!), who, Malcolm holds, assume that a human being
may have a conscious thought and a conscious experience during sleep. Descartes
claims that he had been deceived during sleep. Malcolms point is that ordinary
language contrasts consciousness and sleep. The claim that one is conscious
while one is sleep-walking is stretching the use of the term. Malcolm rejects
the alleged counter-examples based on sleepwalking or sleep-talking, e.g.
dreaming that one is climbing stairs while one is actually doing so is not a
counter-example because, in such a case, the individual is not sound asleep
after all. If a person is in any state of consciousness, it logically follows
that he is not sound asleep. The concept of dreaming is based on our descriptions
of dreams after we have awakened in telling a dream. Thus, to have dreamt that
one has a thought during sleep is not to have a thought any more than to have
dreamt that one has climbed Everest is to have climbed Everest. Since one
cannot have an experience during sleep, one cannot have a mistaken experience
during sleep, thereby undermining the sort of scepticism based on the idea that
our experience might be wrong because we might be dreaming. Malcolm further
argues that a report of a conscious state during sleep is unverifiable. If
Grice claims that he and Strawson saw a big-foot in charge of the reserve desk
at the Bodleian library, one can verify that this took place by talking to
Strawson and gathering forensic evidence from the library. However, there is no
way to verify Grices claim that he dreamed that he and Strawson saw a big-foot
working at the Bodleian. Grices only basis for his claim that he dreamt this is
that Grice says so after he wakes up. How does one distinguish the case where Grice
dreamed that he saw a big-foot working at The Bodleian and the case in which he
dreamed that he saw a person in a big-foot suit working at the library but,
after awakening, mis-remembered that person in a big-foot suit as a big-foot
proper? If Grice should admit that he had earlier mis-reported his dream and
that he had actually dreamed he saw a person in a big-foot suit at The
Bodleian, there is no more independent verification for this new claim than
there was for the original one. Thus, there is, for Malcolm, no sense to the
idea of mis-remembering ones dreams. Malcolm here applies one of Witters ideas
from his private language argument. One would like to say: whatever is going to
seem right to me is right. And that only means that here we cannot talk about
right. For a similar reason, Malcolm challenges the idea that one can assign a
definite duration or time of occurrence to a dream. If Grice claims that he ran
the mile in 3.4 minutes, one could verify this in the usual ways. If, however,
Grice says he dreamt that he ran the mile in 3.4 minutes, how is one to measure
the duration of his dreamt run? If Grice says he was wearing a stopwatch in the
dream and clocked his run at 3.4 minutes, how can one know that the dreamt
stopwatch is not running at half speed (so that he really dreamt that he ran
the mile in 6.8 minutes)? Grice might argue that a dream report does not carry
such a conversational implicatura. But Malcolm would say that just admits the
point. The ordinary criteria one uses for determining temporal duration do not
apply to dreamt events. The problem in both these cases (Grice dreaming one saw
a bigfoot working at The Bodleian and dreaming that he ran the mile in 3.4
minutes) is that there is no way to verify the truth of these dreamt events —
no direct way to access that dreamt inner experience, that mysterious glow of
consciousness inside the mind of Grice lying comatose on the couch, in order to
determine the facts of the matter. This is because, for Malcolm, there are no
facts of the matter apart from the report by the dreamer of the dream upon
awakening. Malcolm claims that the empirical evidence does not enable one to
decide between the view that a dream experience occurs during sleep and the
view that they are generated upon the moment of waking up. Dennett agrees with
Malcolm that nothing supports the received view that a dream involves a
conscious experience while one is asleep but holds that such issues might be
settled empirically. Malcolm also argues against the attempt to provide a
physiological mark of the duration of a dream, for example, the view that the
dream lasted as long as the rapid eye movements. Malcolm replies that there can
only be as much precision in that common concept of dreaming as is provided by
the common criterion of dreaming. These scientific researchers are misled by
the assumption that the provision for the duration of a dream is already there,
only somewhat obscured and in need of being made more precise. However, Malcolm
claims, it is not already there (in the ordinary concept of dreaming). These
scientific views are making radical conceptual changes in the concept of
dreaming, not further explaining our ordinary concept of dreaming. Malcolm
admits, however, that it might be natural to adopt such scientific views about
REM sleep as a convention. Malcolm points out, however, that if REM sleep is
adopted as a criterion for the occurrence of a dream, people would have to
be informed upon waking up that they had dreamed or not. As Pears observes,
Malcolm does not mean to deny that people have dreams in favour of the view
that they only have waking dream-behaviour. Of course it is no misuse of
language to speak of remembering a dream. His point is that since the concept
of dreaming is so closely tied to our concept of waking report of a dreams, one
cannot form a coherent concept of this alleged inner (private) something that
occurs with a definite duration during sleep. Malcolm rejects a certain
philosophical conception of dreaming, not the ordinary concept of dreaming,
which, he holds, is neither a hidden private something nor mere outward
behaviour.The account of dreaming by Malcolm has come in for considerable
criticism. Some argue that Malcolms claim that occurrences in dreams cannot be
verified by others does not require the strict criteria that Malcolm proposes
but can be justified by appeal to the simplicity, plausibility, and predictive
adequacy of an explanatory system as a whole. Some argue that Malcolms account
of the sentence I am awake is inconsistent. A comprehensive programme in
considerable detail has been offered for an empirical scientific investigation
of dreaming of the sort that Malcolm rejects. Others have proposed various
counterexamples and counter arguments against dreaming by Malcolm. Grices
emphasis is in Malcolms easy way out with statements to the effect that implicatura
do or do not operate in dream reports. They do in mine! Grice considers, I may
be dreaming in the two essays opening the Part II: Explorations on semantics
and metaphysics in WOW. Cf. Urmson on ‘delusion’ in ‘Parentheticals’ as
‘conceptually impossible.’ Refs.: The main reference is Grice’s essay on
‘Dreaming,’ but there are scattered references in his treatment of Descartes,
and “The causal theory of perception” (henceforth, “Causal theory”), The H. P.
Grice Papers, BANC.
IMITATVM
-- Imago -- imaginatumimagofrom
“imago”imago) "copy, imitation, likeness;
statue, picture," also "phantom, ghost, apparition,"
figuratively "idea, appearance," from stem of imitari "to copy, imitate"
(from PIE root *aim- "to copy"). The root of ‘imago’ is cognate with that of ‘emulate,’
aemulatumand the verb is under imitor --
Discussed by Grice in “Vacuous Names.” A population may imagine that a
certain expeditioner, Marmaduke Bloggs, climbed Mt. Everest on hands and knees.
He is the imaginatum. imagination:
referred to by Grice in “Prolegomena”the rabbit that looks like a duck -- the
mental faculty sometimes thought to encompass all acts of thinking about
something novel, contrary to fact, or not currently perceived; thus: “Imagine
that Lincoln had not been assassinated,” or “Use your imagination to create a
new design for roller skates.” ‘Imagination’ also denotes an important
perception-like aspect of some such thoughts, so that to imagine something is
to bring to mind what it would be like to perceive it. Philosophical theories
of imagination must explain its apparent intentionality: when we imagine, we
always imagine something. Imagination is always directed toward an object, even
though the object may not exist. Moreover, imagination, like perception, is
often seen as involving qualia, or special subjective properties that are
sometimes thought to discredit materialist, especially functionalist, theories
of mind. The intentionality of imagination and its perceptual character lead
some theories to equate imagination with “imaging”: being conscious of or
perceiving a mental image. However, because the ontological status of such
images and the nature of their properties are obscure, many philosophers have
rejected mental images in favor of an adverbial theory on which to imagine
something red is best analyzed as imagining “redly.” Such theories avoid the
difficulties associated with mental images, but must offer some other way to
account for the apparent intentionality of imagination as well as its perceptual
character. Imagination, in the hands of Husserl and Sartre, becomes a
particularly apt subject for phenomenology. It is also cited as a faculty that
idols of the cave imagination 417 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 417
separates human thought from any form of artificial intelligence. Finally,
imagination often figures prominently in debates about possibility, in that
what is imaginable is often taken to be coextensive with what is possible.
IN-MANENS
-- anens,
a term most often used in contrast to ‘transcendence’ to express the way in
which God is thought to be present in the world. The most extreme form of
immanence is expressed in pantheism, which identifies God’s substance either
partly or wholly with the world. In contrast to pantheism, Judaism and
Christianity hold God to be a totally separate substance from the world. In
Christianity, the separateness of God’s substance from that of the world is
guaranteed by the doctrine of creation ex nihilo. Aquinas held that God is in
the world as an efficient cause is present to that on which it acts. Thus, God
is present in the world by continuously acting on it to preserve it in
existence. Perhaps the weakest notion of immanence is expressed in eighteenth-
and nineteenthcentury deism, in which God initially creates the world and
institutes its universal laws, but is basically an absentee landlord,
exercising no providential activity over its continuing history.
INTER-PRETATVM
-- interpretatum: h
“While ‘heremneia’ sounds poetic and sweet, ‘interpretatio’ sounds thomistic
and rough!”H. P. Grice. “Plus ‘hermeneia is metaphorical.’ hermeneia:
hermeneutics, the art or theory of interpretation, as well as a type of
philosophy that starts with questions of interpretation. Originally concerned
more narrowly with interpreting sacred texts, the term acquired a much broader
significance in its historical development and finally became a philosophical
position in twentieth-century G. philosophy. There are two competing positions
in hermeneutics: whereas the first follows Dilthey and sees interpretation or
Verstehen as a method for the historical and human sciences, the second follows
Heidegger and sees it as an “ontological event,” an interaction between
interpreter and text that is part of the history of what is understood.
Providing rules or criteria for understanding what an author or native “really”
meant is a typical problem for the first approach. The interpretation of the
law provides an example for the second view, since the process of applying the
law inevitably transforms it. In general, hermeneutics is the analysis of this
process and its conditions of possibility. It has typically focused on the
interpretation of ancient texts and distant peoples, cases where the
unproblematic everyday understanding and communication cannot be assumed.
Schleiermacher’s analysis of understanding and expression related to texts and
speech marks the beginning of hermeneutics in the modern sense of a scientific
methodology. This emphasis on methodology continues in nineteenth-century
historicism and culminates in Dilthey’s attempt to ground the human sciences in
a theory of interpretation, understood as the imaginative but publicly
verifiable reenactment of the subjective experiences of others. Such a method
of interpretation reveals the possibility of an objective knowledge of human
beings not accessible to empiricist inquiry and thus of a distinct methodology
for the human sciences. One result of the analysis of interpretation in the
nineteenth century was the recognition of “the hermeneutic circle,” first
developed by Schleiermacher. The circularity of interpretation concerns the
relation of parts to the whole: the interpretation of each part is dependent on
the interpretation of the whole. But interpretation is circular in a stronger
sense: if every interpretation is itself based on interpretation, then the
circle of interpretation, even if it is not vicious, cannot be escaped.
Twentieth-century hermeneutics advanced by Heidegger and Gadamer radicalize
this notion of the hermeneutic circle, seeing it as a feature of all knowledge
and activity. Hermeneutics is then no longer the method of the human sciences
but “universal,” and interpretation is part of the finite and situated
character of all human knowing. “Philosophical hermeneutics” therefore
criticizes Cartesian foundationalism in epistemology and Enlightenment
universalism in ethics, seeing science as a cultural practice and prejudices or
prejudgments as ineliminable in all judgments. Positively, it emphasizes
understanding as continuing a historical tradition, as well as dialogical
openness, in which prejudices are challenged and horizons broadened.
IN-PERATVM -- imperatumWhile of course there is a verb in the infinitive for this,
Grice prefers the past participle“It’s so diaphanous!” -- This starts with the
Greeks, who had the klesis porstktike, modus imperativus. But then, under the
modus subjunctives, the Romans added the modus prohibitivus. So this is
interesting, because it seems that most of Grice’s maxims are ‘prohibitions’:
“Do not say what you believe to be false.” “Do not that for which you lack
adequate evidence.” And some while formally in the ‘affirmative,’ look
prohibitive with ‘negative-loaded’ verbs like ‘avoid ambiguity,’ etc. hile an
imperatus, m. is a command, ‘imperatum’ refers, diaphanously, to what is
commanded. “Impero” is actually a derivation from the intensive “in-“ and the
“paro,” as in “prepare,” “Paratum” would thus reflect the ssame cognateness
with ‘imperatum.” Modus imperativus -- imperative
mode: At one point, Grice loved the “psi,” Actions are alright, but we need to
stop at the psi level. The emissor communicates that the addressee thinks that
the emissor has propositional attitude psi. No need to get into the logical
form of action. One can just do with the logical form of a ‘that’-clause in the
ascription of a state of the soul. This should usually INVOLVE an action, as in
Hare, “The door is shut, please.” like Hare, Grice loves an imperative. In this
essay, Grice attempts an exploration of the logical form of Kant’s concoction.
Grice is especially irritated by the ‘the.’ ‘They speak of Kant’s categorical
imperative, when he cared to formulate a few versions of it!” Grice lists them
all in Abbott’s version. There are nine of them! Grice is interested in the conceptual
connection of the categorical imperative with the hypothetical or suppositional
imperative, in terms of the type of connection between the protasis and the
apodosis. Grice spends the full second Carus lecture on the conception of
value on this. Grice is aware that the topic is central to Oxonian
philosophers such as Hare, a member of Austin’s Play Group, too, who regard the
universability of an imperative as a mark of its categoricity, and indeed,
moral status. Grice chose some of the Kantian terminology on purpose.Grice
would refer to this or that ‘conversational maxim.’A ‘conversational maxim’
contributes to what Grice jocularly refers to as the ‘conversational
immanuel.’But there is an admission test.The ‘conversational maxim’ has to be
shown that, qua items under an overarching principle of conversational
helpfulness, the maxim displays a quality associated with conceptual, formal,
and applicational generality. Grice never understood what Kant meant by the
categoric imperative. But for Grice, from the acceptability of the the immanuel
you can deduce the acceptability of this or that maxim, and from the
acceptability of the conversational immanuel, be conversationally helpful, you
can deduce the acceptability of this or that convesational maxim. Grice hardly
considered Kants approach to the categoric imperative other than via the
universability of this or that maxim. This or that conversational maxim,
provided by Grice, may be said to be universalisable if and only if it displays
what Grice sees as these three types of generality: conceptual, formal, and
applicational. He does the same for general maxims of conduct. The results are
compiled in a manual of universalisable maxims, the conversational immanuel, an
appendix to the general immanuel. The other justification by Kant of the
categoric imperative involve an approach other than the genitorial
justification, and an invocation of autonomy and freedom. It is the use by
Plato of imperative as per categoric imperative that has Grice expanding on modes
other than the doxastic, to bring in the buletic, where the categoric
imperative resides. Note that in the end Kant DOES formulate the categoric
imperative, as Grice notes, as a real imperative, rather than a command, etc.
Grice loved Kant, but he loved Kantotle best. In the last Kant lecture, he
proposes to define the categorical imperative as a counsel of prudence, with a
protasis Let Grice be happy. The derivation involves eight stages! Grice found
out that out of his play-group activities with this or that linguistic nuance
he had arrived at the principle, or imperative of conversational helpfulness,
indeed formulated as an imperative: Make your contribution such as is required,
at the stage at which it occurs, by the accepted purpose of the conversation in
which you are engaged. He notes that the rationality behind the idea of
conversation as rational co-operation does not preclude seeing rationality in
conversation as other than cooperation. The fact that he chooses maxim, and
explicitly echoes Kant, indicates where Grice is leading! An exploration on
Paton on the categorical imperative. Grice had previously explored the
logical form of hypothetical or suppositional imperatives in the Kant
(and later Locke) lectures, notably in Lecture IV, Further remarks on
practical and alethic reasons. Here he considers topics related to Hares
tropic-clistic neustic-phrastic quartet. What does it mean to say that
a command is conditional? The two successors of Grices post as
Tutorial Fellow at St. Johns, Baker Hacker, will tackle the same issue with
humour, in Sense and nonsense, published by Blackwell (too irreverent to be
published by the Clarendon). Is the logical form of a maxim, .p⊃!q, or !(.p ⊃.q),
etc. Kant thought that there is a special
sub-class of hypothetical or suppositional imperative (which he
called a counsels of prudence) which is like his class of technical imperative,
except in that the end specified in a full specfication of the imperative is
the special end of eudæmonia (the agents eudæmonia). For
Grice, understanding Kant’s first version of the categorical imperative
involves understanding what a maxim is supposed to be. Grice
explores at some length four alternative interpretations of an
iffy buletic (as opposed to a non-iffy buletic): three formal, one material.
The first interpretation is the horseshoe interpretation. A blind logical
nose might lead us or be led to the assumption of a link between a
buletically iffy utterance and a doxastically iffy utterance. Such a link
no doubt exists, but the most obvious version of it is plainly
inadequate. At least one other philosopher besides Grice has noticed that If he
torments the cat, have him arrested! is unlikely to express an
buletically iffy utterance, and that even if one restricts oneself to
this or that case in which the protasis specifies a will, we find pairs of
examples like If you will to go to Oxford, travel by AA via Richmond! or
If you will to go to Cambridge, see a psychiatrist! where it is plain that one
is, and the other is not, the expression of a buletically iffy utterance. For
fun, Grice does not tell which! A less easily eliminable suggestion, yet one
which would still interprets the notion of a buletically iffy utterance in
terms of that particular logical form to which if, hypothetical or
suppositional and conditional attach,
would be the following. Let us assume that it is established, or conceded, as
legitimate to formulate an if utterance in which not only the apodosis is
couched in some mode other than the doxastic, as in this or that conditional
command. If you see the whites of their eyes, shoot fire! but also the protasis
or some part (clause) of them. In which case all of the following might be
admissible conditionals. Thus, we might have a doxastic protasis (If the cat is
sick, take it to the vet), or a mixed (buletic-cum-doxastic protasis (If you
are to take the cat to the vet and theres no cage available, put it on Marthas
lap!), and buletic protasis (If you are to take the cat to the vet, put it in a
cage!). If this suggestion seems rebarbative, think of this or that quaint if
utterance (when it is quaint) as conditionalised versions of this or that
therefore-sequence, such as: buletic-cum-doxastic premises (Take the cat
to the vet! There t a cage. Therefore; Put the cat on Marthas lap!), buletic
premise (Take the cat to the vet! Put it in a cage!). And then, maybe, the
discomfort is reduced. Grice next considers a second formal interpretation or
approach to the buletically iffy/non-iffy utterance. Among if utterances with a
buletic apodosis some will have, then, a mixed doxastic-cum buletic protasis
(partly doxastic, partly buletic), and some will have a purely doxastic
protasis (If the cat is sick, take him to the vet!). Grice proposes a
definition of the iffy/non-iffy distinction. A buletically iffy utterance is an
iffy utterance the apodosis of which is buletic and the protasis of which is
buletic or mixed (buletic-cum-dxastic) or it is an elliptical version of such
an iffy utterance. A buletically non-iffy utterance is a buletic utterance
which is not iffy or else, if it is iffy, has a purely doxastic protasis. Grice
makes three quick comments on this second interpretation. First, re: a real
imperative. The structures which are being offered as a way of interpreting an
iffy and a non-iffy imperative do not, as they stand, offer any room for
the appearance this or that buletic modality like ought and should which are so
prominently visible in the standard examples of those kinds of imperatives. The
imperatives suggested by Grice are explicit imperatives. An explicit buletic
utterance is Do such-and-such! and not You ought to do such and such or, worse,
One ought to do such and such. Grice thinks, however, that one can modify this
suggestion to meet the demand for the appearance or occurrence of ought (etc)
if such occurrence is needed. Second, it would remain to be decided how close
the preferred reading of Grices deviant conditional imperatives would be to the
accepted interpretation of standard hypothetical or suppositional imperatives.
But even if there were some divergence that might be acceptable if the new
interpretation turns out to embody a more precise notion than the standard
conception. Then theres the neustical versus tropical protases. There are, Grice
thinks, serious doubts of the admissibility of conditionals with a NON-doxastic
protasis, which are for Grice connected with the very difficult question
whether the doxastic and the buletic modes are co-ordinate or whether the
doxastic mode is in some crucial fashion (but not in other) prior (to use
Suppess qualification) to the buletic. Grice confesses he does not know the
answer to that question. A third formal interpretation links the
iffy/non-iffy distinction to the absolute-relative value distinction. An iffy
imperatives would be end-relative and might be analogous
to an evidence-relative probability. A non-iffy imperatives would not
be end-relative. Finally, a fourth Interpretation is not formal, but
material. This is close to part of what Kant says on the topic. It is a
distinction between an imperative being escapable (iffy), through the
absence of a particular will and its not being escapable (non-iffy). If
we understand the idea of escabability sufficiently widely, the following imperatives
are all escapable, even though their logical form is not in every case the
same: Give up popcorn!, To get slim, give up popcorn!, If you will to get slim,
give up popcorn! Suppose Grice has no will to get slim. One might say that
the first imperative (Give up popcorn!) is escaped, provided giving up
popcorn has nothing else to recommend it, by falsifying You should give up
popcorn. The second and the third imperatives (To get slim, give up
pocorn! and If you will to get slim, give up popcorn!) would not, perhaps,
involve falsification but they would, in the circumstances, be
inapplicable to Griceand inapplicability, too, counts, as escape. A
non-iffy imperative however, is in no way escapable. Re: the Dynamics of
Imperatives in Discourse, Grice then gives three examples which he had
discussed in “Aspects,” which concern arguments (or therefore-chains). This we
may see as an elucidation to grasp the logical form of buletically iffy
utterance (elided by the therefore, which is an if in the metalanguage)
in its dynamics in argumentation. We should, Grice suggests,
consider not merely imperatives of each sort, together with the range
of possible characterisations, but also the possible forms of argument into
which_particular_ hypothetical or suppositional imperatives might enter.
Consider: Defend the Philosophy Department! If you are to defend the
philosophy department, learn to use bows and arrows! Therefore, learn to
use bows and arrows! Grice says he is using the dichotomy of original-derived
value. In this example, in the first premise, it is not specified whether the
will is original or derived, the second premise specifies conducive to (means),
and the conclusion would involve a derived will, provided the second premise is
doxastically satisfactory. Another example would be: Fight for your country! If
you are to fight for your country, join up one of the services! Therefore, join
up! Here, the first premise and the conclusion do not specify the protasis. If
the conclusion did, it would repeat the second premise. Then theres Increase
your holdings in oil shares! If you visit your father, hell give you some oil
shares. Therefore, visit your father! This argument (purportedly) transmits
value. Let us explore these characterisations by Grice with the aid of
Hares distinctions. For Hare in a hypothetical or suppositional imperative, the
protasis contains a neustic-cum-tropic. A distinction may be made between this
or that hypothetical or suppositional imperative and a term used by Grice
in his first interpretation of the hypothetical or suppositional
imperative, that of conditional command (If you see the whites of their
eyes, shoot fire!). A hypothetical or suppositional imperative can
be distinguished from a conditional imperative (If you want to make bread,
use yeast! If you see anything suspicious, telephone the police!) by the
fact that modus ponens is not valid for it. One may use hypothetical,
suppositional or conditional imperative for a buletic utterance which features
if, and reserve conditional command for a command which is expressed by an
imperative, and which is conditional on the satisfaction of the protasis.
Thus, on this view, treating the major premise of an argument as a
hypothetical or suppositional imperative turns the therefore-chain invalid.
Consider the sequence with the major premise as a hypothetical or suppositional
imperative. If you will to make someone mad, give him drug D! You
will to make Peter mad; therefore, give Peter drug D! By uttering this
hypothetical or suppositional imperative, the utterer tells his addressee A
only what means to adopt to achieve a given end in a way which
does not necessarily endorse the adoption of that end, and hence of
the means to it. Someone might similarly say, if you will to make
someone mad, give him drug D! But, of course, even if you will to do
that, you must not try to do so. On the other hand, the
following is arguably valid because the major premise is a
conditional imperative and not a mere hypothetical or suppositional
one. We have a case of major premise as a conditional imperative: You will to
make someone mad, give him drug D! Make Peter mad! Therefore, give
Peter drug D!. We can explain this in terms of the presence of the neustic
in the antecedent of the imperative working as the major premise.
The supposition that the protasis of a hypothetical or suppositional
imperative contains a clause in the buletic mode neatly explains why the
argument with the major premise as a hypothetical or suppositional
imperative is not valid. But the argument with the major premise as a
conditional imperative is, as well as helping to differentiate a
suppositional or hypothetical or suppositional iffy imperative from a
conditional iffy imperative. For, if the protasis of the major premise in the
hypothetical or suppositional imperative is volitival, the mere fact that
you will to make Peter mad does not license the inference of the
imperative to give him the drug; but this _can_ be inferred from the
major premise of the hypothetical or suppositional imperative
together with an imperative, the minor premise in the conditional
imperative, to make Peter mad. Whether the subordinate
clause contains a neustic thus does have have a consequence as
to the validity of inferences into which the complex sentence
enters. Then theres an alleged principle of mode constancy in buletic and
and doxastic inference. One may tries to elucidate Grices ideas on the
logical form of the hypothetical or suppositional imperative proper.
His suggestion is, admittedly, rather tentative. But it might be
argued, in the spirit of it, that an iffy imperative is of the
form ((!p⊃!q) Λ .p)) ∴ !q
But this violates a principle of mode constancy. A phrastic must
remain in the same mode (within the scope of the same tropic) throughout
an argument. A conditional imperative does not violate the principle of
Modal Constancy, since it is of the form ((p⊃!q) Λ
!p)) ∴ !q The question of the logical form of
the hypothetical or suppositional imperative is
too obscure to base much on arguments concerning it. There is an
alternative to Grices account of the validity of an argument featuring a
conditional imperative. This is to treat the major premise of a
conditional imperative, as some have urged it should be as a doxastic utterance
tantamount to In order to make someone mad, you have to give him drug D.
Then an utterer who explicitly conveys or asserts the major premise of a
conditional imperative and commands the second premise is in
consistency committed to commanding the conclusion. If does not
always connect phrastic with phrastic but sometimes
connects two expressions consisting of a phrastic and a
tropic. Consider: If you walk past the post office, post the
letter! The antecedent of this imperative states, it seems, the
condition under which the imperative expressed becomes operative,
and so can not be construed buletically, since by uttering a buletic
utterance, an utterer cannot explicitly convey or assert that a condition
obtains. Hence, the protasis ought not be within the scope of the
buletic !, and whatever we take to represent the form of the
utterance above we must not take !(if p, q) to do so. One way out. On
certain interpretation of the isomorphism or æqui-vocality Thesis between
Indicative and Imperative Inference the utterance has to be construed
as an imperative (in the generic reading) to make the doxasatic
conditional If you will walk past the post office, you will post
the letter satisfactory. Leaving aside issues of the implicaturum of if,
that the utterance can not be so construed seems to be shown by
the fact that the imperative to make the associated doxastically iffy
utterance satisfactory is conformed with by one who does not walk past the
post office. But it seems strange at best to say that the utterance
is conformed with in the same circumstances. This strangeness or
bafflingliness, as Grice prefers, is aptly explained away in terms of the implicaturum.
At Oxford, Dummett is endorsing this idea that a
conditional imperative be construed as an imperative to make an
indicative if utterance true. Dummett urges to divide conditional
imperatives into those whose antecedent is within the power of
the addressee, like the utterance in question, and those in which it
is not. Consider: If you go out, wear your coat! One may be not so much
concerned with how to escape this, as Grice is, but how to conform it. A child
may choose not to go out in order to comply with the imperative. For an imperative
whose protasis is_not_ within the power of the addressee (If anyone tries to
escape, shoot him!) it is indifferent whether we treat it as a
conditional imperative or not, so why bother. A small
caveat here. If no one tries to escape, the imperative is *not violated*.
One might ask, might there not be an important practical difference
bewteen saying that an imperative has not been violated and that
it has been complied with? Dummett ignores this distinction. One may
feel think there is much of a practical difference there. Is Grice
an intuitionist? Suppose that you are a frontier guard and
the antecedent has remained unfulfilled. Then, whether we say that you
complied with it, or simply did not *violate* it will make a great
deal of difference if you appear before a war crimes tribunal.
For Dummett, the fact that in the case of an imperative expressed by a
conditional imperative in which the antecedent is not within the agents power,
we should *not* say that the agent had obeyed just on the ground that the
protassi is false, is no ground for construing an imperative as expressing a
conditional command: for there is no question of fixing what shall
constitute obedience independently of the determination of what shall
constitute disobedience. This complicates the issues. One may with Grice (and
Hare, and Edgley) defend imperative inference against other Oxonian
philosophers, such as Kenny or Williams. What is questioned by the sceptics
about imperative inference is whether if each one of a set of imperatives
is used with the force of a command, one can infer a _further_ imperative
with that force from them. Cf. Wiggins on Aristotle on the practical
syllogism. One may be more conservative than Hare, if not Grice. Consider If
you stand by Jane, dont look at her! You stand by Jane; therefore, dont look at
her! This is valid. However, the following, obtained by anti-logism, is not: If
you stand by Jane, dont look at her! Look at her! Therefore, you dont stand by
Jane. It may seem more reasonable to some to deny Kants thesis, and maintain
that anti-logism is valid in imperative inference than it is to hold onto Kants
thesis and deny that antilogism is valid in the case in question. Then theres
the question of the implicatura involved in the ordering of modes. Consider:
Varnish every piece of furniture you make! You are going to make a table;
therefore, varnish it! This is prima facie valid. The following, however,
switching the order of the modes in the premises is not. You are going to
varnish every piece of furniture that you make. Make a table! Therefore;
varnish it! The connection between the if and the therefore is metalinguistic,
obviouslythe validity of the therefore chain is proved by the associated if
that takes the premise as, literally, the protasis and the consequence as the
apodosis. Conversational Implicaturum at the Rescue. Problems with
or: Consider Rosss infamous example: Post the letter! Therefore, post the
letter or burn it! as invalid, Rossand endorsed at Oxford by Williams. To
permit to do p or q is to permit to do p and to permit to do q. Similarly,
to give permission to do something is to lift a prohibition against doing
it. Admittedly, Williams does not need this so we are stating his
claim more strongly than he does. One may review Grices way out (defense
of the validity of the utterance above in terms of the implicaturum. Grice
claims that in Rosss infamous example (valid, for Grice), whilst (to state it
roughly) the premises permissive presupposition (to use the rather clumsy
term introduced by Williams) is entailed by it, the conclusions
is only conversationally implicated. Typically for an isomorphist, Grice
says this is something shared by indicative inferences. If, being
absent-minded, Grice asks his wife, What have I done with the letter? And she
replies, You have posted it or burnt it, she conversationally implicates that
she is not in a position to say which Grice has done. She also conversationally
implicates that Grice may not have post it, so long as he has burnt it.
Similarly, the future tense indicative, You are going to post the letter has
the conversational implicaturum You may be not going to post the letter so long
as you are going to burn it. But this surely does not validate the
introduction rule for OR, to wit: p; therefore, p or q. One can
similarly, say: Eclipse will win. He may not, of course, if it rains. And I
*know* it will *not* rain. Problems with and. Consider: Put on your parachute
AND jump out! Therefore, jump out! Someone who _only_ jumps out of an
æroplane does not fulfil Put on your parachute and jump out! He has
done only what is necessary, but not sufficient to fulfil it. Imperatives
do not differ from indicatives in this respect, except that fulfilment takes
the place of belief or doxa, which is the form of acceptance apprpriate to a
doxasatic utterance, as the Names implies. Someone who is told Smith put
on his parachute AND jumped out is entitled to believe that Smith jumped
out. But if he believes that this is _all_ Smith did he is in error (Cf. Edgley).
One may discuss Grices test of cancellability in the case of the transport
officer who says: Go via Coldstream or Berwick! It seems the transport officers
way of expressing himself is extremely eccentric, or conversationally
baffling, as Grice prefersyet validly. If the transport officer is not
sure if a storm may block one of the routes, what he should say is
_Prepare_ to go via Coldstream or Berwick! As for the application of Grices
test of explicit cancellation here, it yield, in the circumstances, the
transport officer uttering Go either via Coldstream or Berwick! But
you may not go via Coldstream if you do not go via Berwick, and you may not go
via Berwick if you do not go via Coldstream. Such qualifications ‒
what Grice calls explicit cancellation of the implicaturum ‒ seem to
the addressee to empty the buletic mode of utterance of all content and is thus
reminiscent of Henry Fords utterance to the effect that people can choose what
colour car they like provided it is black. But then Grice doesnt think Ford is
being illogical, only Griceian and implicatural! Grice was fascinated by “if”
clauses in mode other than the indicative: “if the cat is on the mat, she is
purring.” “If the cat had been, make her purr!” etc. He spent years at Clifton
mastering thisonly to have Ayer telling him at Oxford he didn’t need it! “I
won’t take that!” -- Refs.: There is at least one essay just about the
categorical imperative, but there are scattered references wherever Grice
considers the mood markers, The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC.
IN-PLICATVM. Grice: “It is obvious that
the Romans used this creatively, ‘plico in,’ ‘in-plico.’ The assimilation of
the ‘n’ into ‘m’ before ‘p’ is only vugar!” -- IN-PLICATVRVM -- implicaturum: Grice, “Fortunately, philosophy’s
main verb, “to imply,” ‘implicare,’ is like amare, perfectly regular.. So we
have implicans, who is the utterer or his utterance, the implicaturum, which is
the utterance that implies in the future, and the impilicatumBy way of
nominalization, or what I call subjectification or category shift we do have
‘impliatura,’ qua nounBut surely ‘implicatura’ qua feminine noun should be
distinguished from the non-categorially shifted ‘implicatura’ as plural of
‘implicaturum.’ There is no category shift in thinking of an expression as a
vehicle of an ‘implicatum’. This vehicle is the implicaturum when seen as the
expression itself. The utterer is the implicans. And then there’s the
‘implicandtum.’ Similarly, in definition, we speak of definiens and
definiendumdefiniturumThe definies is what defines. This applies strictly to
the ‘definer’the human being. The definiturum if in plural applies to the
expression that defines, -- when in masculine, definiturus, it applies to the
definer. Similarly we may say that he who is implies is an IMPLIER, or an
IMPLICATURUS. We do speak of a professor as being ‘a great explicator.’ So we
shoud speak of myself as a great implicator. in his Oxford seminars. Grice: “I
distinguish between the ‘implicaturum’ and the ‘implicaturum.’” “The ‘implicaturum’
corresponds to Moore’s entailment.” “For the ‘pragmatic-type’ of thing, one
should use ‘implicaturum.’” “The –aturum’ form is what at Clifton I learned as
the future, and a ‘future’ twist it has, since it refers to the future.” “
‘Implicaturum esse’ is, strictly, the infinitivum futurum, made out of the
‘esse’ plus the ‘indicaturum.’ We loved these things at Clifton!” a pragmatic relation different from, but
easily confused with, the semantic relation of entailment. This concept was
first identified, explained, and used by H. P. Grice (Studies in the Way of
Words, 1989). Grice identified two main types of implicaturum, conventional and
non-conventional (including conversational). An emisor is said to
conversationally implicate that p in uttering x, provided that, although p is
NOT logically implied by what the emisor explicitly communicates, the
assumption that the emisor is attempting cooperative communication warrants
inferring that the emisor is communicating that p. If Grice utters “There is a
garage around the corner” in response to Strawson’s saying, “I am out of gas,”
Grice conversationally implicates that the garage is open and has gas to sell.
Grice identifies several conversational maxims to which cooperative
conversationalists may be expected to conform, and which justify inferences
about what the emisor implicates. In the above example, the implicaturums are
due to the maxim of conversational relevance. Another important maxim is the
maxim of conversational fortitude (“Make
your contribution as informatively strong as is required”). Among implicatura
due to the Maxim of conversational fortitude is the scalar implicaturum,
wherein the utterance contains an element that is part of a quantitative scale.
Utterance of such a sentence conversationally implicates that the emisor does
not believe related propositions higher on the scale of conversational
fortitude or informativeness. E. g. an emisor who says, “Some of the zoo
animals escaped,” implies that he does not believe that that most of the zoo
animals escaped, or that every animal of the zoo animals escaped. Unlike a
conversational implicaturum, a conventional implicaturum is due solely to the
semantics of the expression. An emisor is said by Grice to conventionally imply
that p, if the semantics of the expression commits the emisor to p, even though
what the emisor explicitly communicates does not entail that p. Thus, uttering,
as the Tommies did during the Great War, “She was poor but she was honest” a
Tommy implicates, but does not explicitly convey, that there is a contrast
between her poverty and her honesty. Grice
fought with this. It’s a term of art, and he mainly wants to avoid,
fastidiously, equivocation. “I say fastidiously because at Oxford, fewHare is
one of themfollowed suit --. Most stuck with ‘implicatio.’ “So, if we stick with Roman, we have
‘implicatio.’ This gives English ‘implication,’ because the Anglo-Norman
nominative proceeded via the Roman accusative, i. e. ‘implicationem.’ The use
of –ure is also Anglo-Norman, for Roman ‘-ura.’ So we have ‘implicatura,’ and
in Anglo-Norman, ‘implicature.’ ‘Implicatio’ is a feminine noun, and so is
‘implicatura.’ ‘Implicatio’ is a ‘active voice’ noun; so is ‘implicatura.’ The
Roman allows for a correlative neuter to the past participle, ‘implicatum,’ or
‘implicitum’ (there are vowel alternation here). So, the two neuter correlative
active forms for the two neuter passive perfect forms, ‘implicatum’ and
‘implicitum’ are ‘implicaturum’ and ‘impliciturum.’ Kneale has expanded on the
use of ‘implicans.’ If ‘implicans’ is the active PRESENT participle for
‘implicare,’ ‘implicaturum’ is the active FUTURE participle. There is no need
to specify the vehicle, as per Kneale, ‘propositio implicans,’ ‘propositio
implicata’Since ‘implicatura’ is definitely constructed out of the active-voice
future participle, we should have in fact a trio, where the two second items
get two variants, each: the implicans, the implicaturum/impliciturum, and the
implicatum/implicitum. Note that in the present participle, the vowel
alternation does not apply: there’s ‘implicans’ (masculine, feminine, and
neuter) only, which then yields, in the neuter forms, the future,
‘implicaturum’/’impliciturum,’ and the perfect, ‘implicatum’/’implicitum.’ The
same for ‘explicare’: explicatio, explicatura, -- explicans, yielding
explicaturum/expliciturm, explicatum/explciitum. Note that when I speak of what
is seen, ‘see’ being diaphanous, I refer to ‘visum,’ what is seen.There is no
need, and in fact it is best not to, spceficy the vehicle. The Romans used the
neuter, singular, for each case --.” “If
I were serious about ‘implicature’ being feminine, I would speak of the
‘implicata’ as a singular form, but I do not. I use ‘implicatum,’ what is impliedand
use ‘implicata’ as plural neuter. Since an implicatum is usually indeterminate,
it’s best to refer to the plural, ‘implicata’Ditto for the ‘implicaturum,’
which becomes, in the plural, ‘implicatura.’the vehicles are various in that
stress, emphasis, context, all change the vehicle, somehow --. Implicatio then
is like ‘conceptio,’ it is an abstract form (strictly feminine) that has a
process-producti ambiguity that the neuter family: implicans,
implicaturum/impliciturm, implicatum/implicitum avoids. Note that while –ure
form in Anglo-Norman does not derive from the accusative, as ‘implication,’
does hence no accusative nasal ‘n’ (of ‘implicatioN,’ but not ‘implicatio’) in
‘implicature.’ The fact that the Anglo-Normans confused it all by turning this
into ‘employ,’ and ‘imply’ should not deter the Oxonian for his delightful
coinages!” Active Nominal Forms Infinitive:
implicā́re Present participle: implicāns; implicántis Future participle:
implicītúrus; implicātúrus Gerund: implicándum Gerundive: implicándus
Passive Nominal Forms Infinitive: implicā́re Perfect participle: implicī́tum;
implicā́tum. implicitura (Latin Dictionary)
lemma part voice mood tense gender number case implicare verb active
participle future feminine singularnominative ablative vocative lemma part
voice mood tense gender number case implicare verb active participle future
neuter plural nominative accusative vocative INFLECTION Temporal inflection
presentmasculine implicans futuremasculine impliciturus / implicaturus
presentfeminine implicans futurefeminine implicitura / implicatura
presentneuter implicans futureneuter impliciturum / implicaturum. De camptgii ,
vel eampacis dicemus inlra in vita Galheni apud TtebeUtum Pollionem, ratdeiorum
cajcci ISc imperatotum ita vocabantur , non "gamba," vel
"campa," qua pro crure pofteriores wfuipatunt, quod crure tenus
calcea xeniui: id k corrigiarum flexuris, & implicaturis , quibus
circumligabantur. lologiae et Mercurii di Marziano Capella
(I 68), e avanza una nuova ipotesi di ... naculis implicaturis in retia sua
praecipites implagabuntur, syllogismis tuae pro- ... miliae suae longo ordine
ac multis stemmatum inligata flexuris in
parte prima. It may be argued that when Grice compares ‘impicature’ to “the
‘implying,’ that’s a feminine form, cognate with German/Dutch, -ung. Cf. Grice,
“The conception of value”The conceiving of value,” the concept of value, the
conceptus of value, the conceptum of value. Active
Nominal Forms Present participle: cōncipiēns; cōncipiéntis Future participle:
cōnceptúrus Passive Nominal Forms Perfect participle: cōnceptum. Since Grice
plays with this in “Conception of value,” let’s compare. “Grice: “It is worth
comparing ‘to conceive’ with ‘to employ’.” Active present participle:
implicansconcipiens, concipientis --. Active future participle: implicaturum/impliciturm,
concepturus --. Passive perfect participle: implicatum/implicitumconceptum.
Hardie would ask, “what do you mean ‘of’?”The implication of implication. The
conception of value. In an objective (passive) interpretation: it’s the
conceptum of ‘value’. In a subjective (active) interpretion, it’s the
‘conceiving’ of ‘value.’ Cfr. “the love of god,” “the fear of the enemy.” “The
implication of implication.” For Grice, it’s the SENDER who implicates, a
rational agentalthough he may allow for an expression to ‘imply’via connotation
--, and provided the sender does, or would occasionally do. In terms of the
subjective/active, and objective/passive distinction, we would have,
‘implication,’ as in Strawson’s implication, meaning Strawson’s ‘implying’ (originally
a feminine noun), i. e. Strawson’s ‘implicatio’ and Strawson’s ‘implicatura’,
and Strawson’s ‘implicature,’ and Strawson’s ‘implicaturum’/’impliciturm.’ In
terms of the passive/objective realm, what is implied by Strawsonthe
implicatum, and the implicitum. There passive interpretation allows for only
one form (with two vowel alternates): implicatum and implicitum. The active
forms can be present: ‘implicans’ and ‘implicaturum’. If it’s Strawson the
‘implier’implicans is ‘masculine.’ If it’s Strawson the one about to imply,
it’s “Strawson implicaturus” --. By use of the genitive“Ciceronis” we would
have, “implicatura Ciceronis”Cicero’s implicature --, Cicero the implier,
Cicero implicans --. Surely Cicero did something to imply. This ‘something’ is
best conceived in the neuter, ‘implicans,’ as applied, say, to sententia, or
propositio‘propositio implicans‘sententia implicans’‘implicatura’ would refer
to the act of implyingas the conceiving of value --. Since ‘implicatura’ is
formed out of the future participle, its corresponding form in the neuter would
be ‘implicaturum.’ By his handwave (implicaturum/implicitumqua vehicle of
Cicero’s implicatureor implicaturahis act of implying), Cicero (implicans)
implies (implicat) this or that ‘implicatum’ or ‘implicitum.’ Or, Grice’s
implication. Grice makes an important distinction which he thinks Austin
doesn’t make because what a philosopher EXPLICITLY conveys and what he
IMPLICITLY conveys. It was only a few years Grice was interacting
philosophically with Austin and was reading some material by Witters, when
Grice comes with this criticism and complaint. Austin ignores “all too
frequently” a distinction that Witters apparently dnies. This is a distinction
between what an emissor communicates (e. g. that p), which can be either
explicitly (that p1) or implicitly (that p2) and what, metabolically, and
derivatively, the emissum ‘communictates’ (explicitly or implicitly). At the
Oxford Philosophical Society, he is considering Moore’s ‘entailment.’ This is
not a vernacular expression, but a borrowing from a Romance language. But
basically, Moore’s idea is that ‘p’ may be said to ‘entail’ q iff at least two
conditions follow. Surely ‘entail’ has only one sense. In this metabolically
usage where it is a ‘p’ that ‘entails’ the conditions are that there is a
property and that there is a limitation. Now suppose Grice is discussing with
Austin or reading Witters. Grice wants to distinguish various things: what the
emissor communicates (explicitly or implicitly) and the attending diaphanous
but metabolical, what WHAT THE EMSSOR COMMUNICATES (explicitly or implicitly)
ENTAILS, AND the purely metabolical what the emissum ‘entails’ (explicitly or
implicitly). This is Grice’s wording:“If we can elucidate the meaning of
"A meantNN by x that p (on a particular occasion)," this might
reasonably be expected to help us with the explication of "entails.”The
second important occasion is in the interlude or excursus of his Aristotelian
Society talk. How does he introduce the topic of ‘implication’? At that time
there was a lot being written about ‘contextual’ or ‘pragmatic’ implicationeven
within Grice’s circleas in D. K. Grant’s essay on pragmatic implication for
Philosophy, and even earlier Nowell-Smith’s on ‘contextual implication’ in “Ethics,”
and even earlier, and this is perhaps Grice’s main triggerF. Strawson’s
criticism of Whitehead and Russell, with Strawson having that, by uttering ‘The
king of France is not bald,’ the emissor IMPLIES that there is a king of France
(Strawson later changes the idiom from ‘imply,’ and the attending ‘implication,
to ‘presuppose,’ but he keeps ‘imply’ in all the reprints of his earlier
essays). In “Causal Theory,” Grice
surely cannot just ‘break’ the narrative and start with ‘implication’ in an
excursus. So the first stage is to explore the use of ‘implication’ or related
concepts in the first part of “Causal Theory” LEADING to the excursus for which
need he felt. The first use appears in section 2. The use is the noun, ‘implication.’ And Grice
is reporting the view of an objector, so does not care to be to careful
himself.“the OBJECTION MIGHT run as follows.” “… When someone makes a remark
such as “The pillar box seems red” A CERTAIN IMPLICATION IS CARRIED.” He goes
on “This implication is “DISJUNCTIVE IN FORM,” which should not concerns us
here. Since we are considering the status of the implication, as seen by the
objector as reported by Grice. He does not give a source, so we may assume G.
A. Paul reading Witters, and trying to indoctrinate a few Oxonians into
Wittgensteinianism (Grice notes that besides the playgroup there was Ryle’s
group at Oxford and a THIRD, “perhaps more disciplined” group, that tended
towards Witters.Grice goes on:“It IS implied that…” p. Again, he expands it,
and obviously shows that he doesn’t care to be careful. And he is being ironic,
because the implication is pretty lengthy! Yet he says, typically:“This may not
be an absolutely EXACT or complete characterisation of the implication, but it
is, perhaps, good ENOUGH to be going with!” Grice goes on to have his objector
a Strawsonian, i. e. as REFUSING TO ASSIGN A TRUTH-VALUE to the utterance,
while Grice would have that it is ‘uninterestingly true. In view of this it may
to explore the affirmative and negative versions. Because the truth-values may
change:In Grice’s view: “The pillar box seems red to me” IS “UNINTERESTINGLY
TRUE,” in spite of the implication.As for “It is not the case that the pillar
box seems red,” this is more of a trick. In “Negation,” Grice has a similar
example. “That pillar box is red; therefore, it is not blue.”He is concerned
with “The pillar box is not blue,” or “It is not the case that the pillar box
is blue.”What about the truth-value now of the utterance in connection with the
implication attached to it?Surely, Grice would like, unless accepting
‘illogical’ conversationalists (who want to make that something is UNASSERTIBLE
or MISLEADING by adding ‘not’), the utterance ‘It is not the case that the pillar
box seems red to me’ is FALSE in the scenario where the emissor would be
truthful in uttering ‘The pillar box seems red to me.” Since Grice allows that
the affirmative is ‘uninterestingly true,’ he is committed to having ‘It is not
the case that the pillar box seems red’ as FALSE.For the Strawsonian
Wittgensteinian, or truth-value gap theorist, the situation is easier to
characterise. Both ‘The pillar box seems red to me” and its negation, “The
pillar box does not seem red to me” lack a truth value, or in Grice’s word, as
applied to the affirmative, “far from being uninterestingly true, is neither
true nor false,” i. e. ‘neuter.’ It wold not be true but it would not be false
eitherbreakdown of bivalence. Grice’s case is a complicated one because he distinguishes
between the sub-perceptual “The pillar box seems red” from the perceptual
‘vision’ statement, “Grice sees that the pillar box is red.” So the truth of
“The pillar box seems red” is a necessary condition for the statement about
‘seeing.’ This is itself controversial. Some philosophers have claimed that
“Grice knows that p” does NOT entail “Grice believes that p,” for example. But
for the causal theory Grice is thinking of an analysis of “Grice sees that the
pillar box is red” in terms of three conditions: First, the pillar box seems
red to Grice. Second, the pillar box is red. And third, it is the pillar box
being red that causes it seeming red to Grice. Grice goes to reformulate the
idea that “The pillar box seems red” being true. But now not “uninterestingly
true,” but “true (under certain conditions),” or as he puts it “(subject to
certain qualifications) true.” He may be having in mind a clown in a circus
confronted with the blue pillar box and making a joke about it. Those ‘certain
qualifications’ would not apply to the circus case. Grice goes on to change the
adverb, it’s ‘boringly true,’ or ‘highly boringly true.’ He adds ‘suggestio
falsi,’ which seems alright but which would not please the Wittgensteinian who
would also reject the ‘false.’ We need a ‘suggestio neutri.’ In this second
section, he gives the theoretical explanation. The “implication” arises “in
virtue of a GENERAL FEATURE OR PRINCIPLE” of conversation, or pertaining to a
system put in ‘communication,’ or a general feature or principle governing an
emissor communicating that p. Note that ‘feature’ and ‘principle’ are
appropriately ‘vague.’ “Feature” can be descriptive. “Principle” is
Aristotelian. Boethius’s translation for Aristotle’s ‘arche.’ It can be
descriptive. The first use of ‘principle’ in a ‘moral’ or ‘practical’ context
seems to post-date its use in, say, geometryEuclid’s axioms as ‘principia
mathematica,’ or Newton’s “Principia.” Grice may be having in mind Moore’s
‘paradox’ (true, surely) when Grice adds ‘it is raining.’Grice’s careful
wording is worth exploring. “The mistake [incorrectness, falsehood] of
supposing the implication to constitute a "part of the meaning [sense]” of
"The Alpha seems Beta" is somewhat similar to, though MORE INSIDUOUS …”[moral
implication here: 1540s, from Middle
French insidieux "insidious"
(15c.) or directly from Latin insidiosus "deceitful, cunning, artful, treacherous,"
from insidiae (plural)
"plot, snare, ambush," from insidere "sit on,
occupy," from in- "in" (from PIE root *en "in")
+ sedere "to
sit," from PIE root *sed- (1) "to
sit." Figurative, usually with a suggestion of lying in wait and the
intent to entrap. Related: Insidiously; insidiousness]“than,
the mistake which one IF one supposes that the SO-CALLED [‘pragmatic’ or
‘contextualimplicaturum, “as I would not,” and indeed he does nothe prefers
“expresses” here, not the weak ‘imply’] “implication” that one believes it to
be raining is "a part of the meaning [or sense]" of the expression
[or emissum] "It is raining.”Grice allows that no philosopher may have
made this mistake. He will later reject the view that one conversationally
implicates that one believes that it is raining by uttering ‘It is raining.’
But again he does not give sources. In these case, while without the
paraphernalia about the ‘a part of the ‘sense’” bit, can be ascribed at Oxford
to Nowell-Smith and Grant (but not, we hope to Strawson). Nowell-Smith is clear
that it is a contextual implication, but one would not think he would make the
mistake of bringing in ‘sense’ into the bargain. Grice goes on:“The short and
literally inaccurate reply to such a supposition [mistake] might be that the so-called
“implication” attaches because the expression (or emissum) is a PROPOSITIONAL
one [expressable by a ‘that so-and-so’ clause] not because it is the particular
propositional expression which it happens to be.”By ‘long,’ Grice implicates: “And
it is part of the function of the informative mode that you utter an utterance
in the informative mode if you express your belief in the content of the
propositonal expression.”Grice goes on to analyse ‘implication’ in terms of
‘petitio principii.’ This is very interesting and requires exploration. Grice
claims that his success the implicaturum in the field of the philosophy of
perception led his efforts against Strawson on the syncategoremata.But here we
see Grice dealing what will be his success.One might, for example, suggest that
it is open to the champion of sense_data to lay down that the sense-datum
sentence " I have a pink sense-datum " should express truth if and
only if the facts are as they would have to be for it to be true, if it were in
order, to say .. Something looks pink to me ", even though it may not
actually be in ordei to say this (because the D-or-D condition is unfulfilled).
But this attempt to by-pass the objector's position would be met by the reply
that it begs the question; for it assumes that there is some way of specifying
the facts in isolation from the implication standardly carried by such a
specification; and this is precisely what the objector is denying.Rephrasing
that:“One might, for example, suggest that it is open to the champion of
sense_data to lay down that the sense-datum sentence "The pillar box seems
red” is TRUE if and only if the facts are as the facts WOULD HAVE to be for
“The pillar box seems red” to be true, IF (or provided that) it were IN ORDER
[i. e. conversationally appropriate], to utter or ‘state’ or explicitly convey
that the pillar box seems red, even though it may NOT actually be in order
[conversationally appropriate] to explicitly convey that the pillar box seems
red (because the condition specified in the implication is unfulfilled).”“But
this attempt to by-pass the objector's position would be met by a charge of
‘petitio principia,’ i. e. the reply that it begs the question.”“Such a manoeuvre is invalid in that it assumes that
there IS some way of providing a SPECIFICATION of the facts of the matter in
isolation from, or without recourse to, the implication that is standardly
carried by such a specification.”“This is precisely what the objector is
denying, i. e. the objector believes it is NOT the case that there is a way of
giving a specification of the scenario without bringing in the implication.”Grice
refers to the above as one of the “frustrations,” implicating that the above,
the ‘petitio principia,’ is just one of the trials Grice underwent before
coming with the explanation in terms of the general feature of communication,
or as he will late express, in terms of ‘what the hell’ the
‘communication-function’ of “The pillar seems red to me” might be when the implicaturum
is not meantand you have to go on and cancel it (“That pillar box seems red;
mind, I’m not suggesting that it’s notI’m practicing my sub-perceptual
proficiency.”).Grice goes on to note the generality he saw in the idea of the
‘implication.’ Even if “The pillar box seems red” was his FIRST attack, the
reason he was willing to do the attacking was that the neo-Wittgensteinian was
saying things that went against THE TENOR OF THE THINGS GRICE would say with
regard to other ‘linguistic philosophical’ cases OTHER than in the philosophy
of perception, notably his explorations were against Malcolm reading of Moore,
about Moore ‘misusing’ “know.”Grice:“I was inclined to rule against my
objector, partly because his opponent's position was more in line with the kind
of thing I was inclined to say about other linguistic phenomena which are in
some degree comparable.”Rephrase:“My natural inclination was to oppose the
objector.”“And that was because his opponent's position is more “in line” with
the kind of thing Grice is inclined to sayor thesis he is willing to put
forward-- about OTHER phenomena involving this or that ‘communication-function’
of this or that philosophical adage, which are in some degree comparable to “The
pillar box seems red.””So just before the ‘excursus,’ or ‘discursus,’ as he has
itwhich is then not numberedbut subtitlted (‘Implication’), he embark on a
discursus about “certain ASPECTS of the concept OR CONCEPTS of implication.”He
interestingly adds: “using some more or less well-worn examples.” This is not
just a reference to Strawson, Grant, Moore, Hungerland and Nowell-Smith, but to
the scholastics and the idea of the ‘suppositio’ as an ‘implicatio,’: “Tu non
cessas edere ferrum.” Grice says he will consider only four aspects or FOUR
IDEAS (used each as a ‘catalyst’) in particular illustrations.“Smith has not
ceased beating his wife.”“Smith’s girlfriend is poor, but honest.”“Smith’s
handwriting is beautiful”“Smith’s wife is in the kitchen or in the bathroom.”Each
is a case, as Grice puts it, “in which in ordinary parlance, or at least in
Oxonian philosophical parlance, something might be said to be ‘implied’
(hopefully by the emissor) -- as distinct from being ‘stated,’ or ‘explicitly
put.’One first illustrationEXPLICITLY CONVEYED: “Smith has not ceased beating
his wife.” IMPLICITLY CONVEYED, but cancellable: “Smith has been beating his
wife.”CANCELLATION: “Smith has not ceased beating his wife; he never started.”APPLY
THREE OTHER IDEAS.A second illustrationEXPLICITLY CONVEYED:“Smith’s girlfriend
is poor, but honest.”IMPLICITLY CONVEYED: “There is some contrast between
Smith’s girlfriend’s honesty and her poverty; and possibly between Smith and
the utterer.”CANCELLATION: “I’m sorry, I cannot cancel that.”TRY OTHER THREE
IDEAS.A third illustrationEXPLICITLY CONVEYED “Smith’s handwriting is
beautiful”“Or “If only his outbursts were more angelic.”IMPLICITLY CONVEYED:
“He possibly cannot read Hegel in German.”CANCELLATION: “Smith’s handwriting is
beautiful; on top, he reads Hegel in German.”TRY THREEOTHER IDEASA fourth
illustration:EXPLICITLY CONVEYED: “Smith’s wife is in the kitchen or in the
bathroom.”IMPLICITLY CONVEYED: “It is not the case that I have truth-functional
grounds to express disjunct D1, and it is not the case that I have
truth-functional grounds to express disjunct D2; therefore, I am introducting
the disjunction EITHER than by the way favoured by Gentzen.” (Grice actually
focuses on the specific ‘doxastic’ condition: emissor believes …CANCELLATION:
“I know perfectly well where she is, but I want you to find out for
yourself.”TRY THREE OTHER IDEAS.Within the discursus he gives SIX (a sextet)
other examples, of the philosophical type, because he is implicating the above
are NOT of the really of philosophical type, hence his reference to ‘ordinary
parlance.’ He points out that he has no doubt there are other candidates
besides his sextet.FIRST IN THE SEXTETEXPLICITLY CONVEYED: “You cannot see a
knife as a knife, though you may see what is not a knife as a knife.”IMPLICITLY
CONVEYED: “”AS” REQUIRES A GESTALT.”CANCELLATION: “I see the horse as a horse,
because my gestalt is mine.”TRY THREE OTHER IDEASSECOND IN THE SEXTET:EXPLICITLY
CONVEYED:“When Moore said he knew that the objects before him were human hands,
he was guilty of misusing the word "know".”IMPLICITLY CONVEYED: “You
can only use ‘know’ for ‘difficult cases.’CANCELLATION: “If I know that p iff I
believe that p, p, and p causes my belief in p, I know that the objects before
me are human hands.”TRY THREE OTHER IDEAS.THIRD IN THE SEXTETEXPLICITLY
CONVEYED: “For an occurrence to be properly said to have a ‘cause,’ the
occurrence must be something abnormal or unusual.”IMPLICILTY CONVEYED: “Refrain
from using ‘cause’ when the thing is normal and usual.”CANCELLATION: “If I see
that the pillar box is red iff the pillar box seems red, the pillar box is red,
and the pillar box being red causes the pillar box seeming red, the cause of
the pillar box seeming red is that the pillar box is red.”TRY OTHER THREE
IDEAS.FOURTH IN THE SEXTET: EXPLICITLY
CONVEYED: “For an action to be properly described as one for which the agent is
responsible, it must be the sort of action for which people are condemned.”IMPLICITLY
CONVEYED: “Refrain ascribing ‘responsibility’ to Timmy having cleaned up his
bedroom.”CANCELLATION: “Timmy is very responsible. He engages in an action for
which people are not condemned.”TRY THREE OTHER IDEAS.FIFTH IN THE SEXTET:EXPLICITLY
CONVEYED: “What is actual is not also possible.”IMPLICITLY CONVEYED: “There is
a realm of possibilities which does not overlap with the realm of
actualities.”CANCELLATION: “If p is actual iff p obtains in world w1, and p is
possible iff p obtains in any world wn which includes w1, p is possible.”TRY
THREE OTHER IDEAS.SIXTH IN THE SEXTETEXPLICITLY CONVEYED: “What is known by me
to be the case is not also believed by me to be the case.”IMPLICITLY CONVEYED:
“To know is magical!”CANCELLATION: “If I know that p iff I believe that p, p,
and p causes my believing that p, then what is known by me to be the case is
also believed by me to be the case.”TRY THREE OTHER IDEAS.CASE IN QUESTION:EXPLICITLY
CONVEYED: “The pillar box seems red.”IMPLICITLY CONVEYED: “One will doubt it
is.”CANCELLATION: “The pillar box seems red and I hope no one doubt it is.”TRY
THREE OTHER IDEAS. THAT LISTING became commonplace for Grice. In
ProlegomenaGROUP A: EXAMPLE I: RYLE on ‘voluntarily’ and “involuntarily” in
“The Concept of Mind.” RYLE WAS LISTENING! BUT GRICE WAS without reach! Grice
would nothavecriticised Ryle at a shorter distance.EXAMPLE II: MALCOLM IN
“Defending common sense” in the Philosophical Review, on Moore’s misuse of
‘know’also in Causal, above, as second in the sextet.EXPLICITLY CONVEYED:“When
Moore said he knew that the objects before him were human hands, he was guilty
of misusing the word "know".REPHRASE IN “PROLEGOMENA.”IMPLICITLY
CONVEYED: “You can only use ‘know’ for ‘difficult cases.’CANCELLATION: “If I
know that p iff I believe that p, p, and p causes my belief in p, I know that
the objects before me are human hands.”EXAMPLE III: BENJAMIN ON BROAD ON THE
“SENSE” OF “REMEMBERING”EXPLICITLY CONVEYED;IMPLICITLY CONVEYEDCANCELLATIONEXAMPLES,
GROUP A, CLASS IV: philosophy of perception FIRST EXAMPLE: Witters on ‘seeing
as’ in Philosophical InvestigationsEXPLICITLY CONVEYEDIMPLICITLY
CONVEYEDCANCELLATION.Previously used in Causal as first in the sextet: FIRST IN
THE SEXTETEXPLICITLY CONVEYED: “You cannot see a knife as a knife, though you
may see what is not a knife as a knife.”Rephrased in Prolegomena. IMPLICITLY
CONVEYED: “”AS” REQUIRES A GESTALT.”CANCELLATION: “I see the horse as a horse,
because my gestalt is mine.”GROUP ACLASS IVPHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTIONEXAMPLE II“The
pillar box seems red to me.”Used in“Causal”EXPLICITLY CONVEYED: “The pillar box
seems red.”IMPLICITLY CONVEYED: “One will doubt it is.”CANCELLATION: “The
pillar box seems red and I hope no one doubt it is.”GROUP ACLASS VPHILOSOPHY OF
ACTIONHere unlike Class IV, he uses (a), etc.EXAMPLE A: WITTERS AND OTHERS on
‘trying’ EXPLICITLY CONVEYEDIMPLICITLY CONVEYED:CANCELLATIONGROUP ACLASS
V“ACTION,” not ‘philosophy of action’cf. ‘ordinary parlance.’EXAMPLE B: Hart on
‘carefully.’EXPLICITLY CONVEYEDIMPLICITLY CONVEYEDCANCELLATION GROUP ACLASS VACTIONEXAMPLE
C: Austin in “A plea for excuses” on ‘voluntarily’ and ‘involuntarily’a
refinement on Ryle aboveusing variable “Mly”Grice would not have criticised
Austin in the play group. He rather took it against his tutee, Strawson.EXPLICITLY
CONVEYED IMPLICITLY CONVEYEDCANCELLATIONGROUP B: syncategoremanot lettered butFIRST
EXAMPLE: “AND” (not ‘not’)SECOND EXAMPLE: “OR”THIRD EXAMPLE: “IF”particularly
relevant under ‘implication.’ STRAWSON, Introduction to logical theory.GRICE’S
PHRASING: “if p, q” ENTAILS ‘p horseshoe q.’ The reverse does not hold: it is
not the case that ‘p horseshoe q’ ENTAILS ‘if p, q’. Odd way of putting it, but
it was all from Strawson. It may be argued that ‘entail’ belongs in a system,
and ‘p horseshoe q’ and ‘if p, q’ are DISPARATE. Grice quotes verbatim from
Strawson:a ‘primary or standard’ use of “if … then …,” or “if,” of which the
main characteristics were: that for each hypothetical statement made by this
use of “if,” there could be made just one statement which would be the
antecedent of the hypothetical and just onestatement which would be its
consequent; that the hypothetical statement is acceptable (true, reasonable) if
the antecedent statement, if made or accepted, would, in the circumstances, be
a good ground or reason for accepting the consequent statement; and that the
making of the hypothetical statement carries the implicationeither of
uncertainty about, or of disbelief in, the fulfilment of both antecedent and
consequent.Grice rephrases that by stating that for Grice “a primary or
standard use of ‘if, then’” is characterised as follows:“for each hypothetical
statement made by this use of “if,” there could be made just one statement
which would be the antecedent of the hypothetical and just one statement which
would be its consequent; that the hypothetical statement is acceptable (true,
reasonable) if the antecedent statement, if made or accepted, would, in the
circumstances, be a good ground or reason for accepting the consequent
statement; and that the making of the hypothetical statement carries the implication
either of uncertainty about, or of disbelief in, the fulfilment of both
antecedent and consequent.”Grice rephrases the characterisation as from “each”
and eliding a middle part, but Grice does not care to add the fastidious “[…],”
or quote, unquote.“each hypothetical ‘statement’ made by this use of “if” is
acceptable (TRUE, reasonable) if the antecedent ‘statement,’ IF made or
accepted, would, in the circumstances, be a good ground or reason for accepting
the consequent ‘statement;’ and that the making of thehypothetical statement
carries the implication either of uncertainty about, or of disbelief in, the
fulfilment of both antecedent and consequent.
“A hypothetical, or conditional ‘statement’ or composite proposition such
as “If it is day, I talk”is acceptable (or TRUE, or ‘reasonable’) if (but not
only if), first, the antecedent ‘statement,’ ‘It is day,’ IF made on its own, or
accepted on its own, i. e. simpliciter, would, in the circumstances, be a good
ground or ‘reason’ for accepting the consequent ‘statement,’ to wit: “I talk;”
and, second, that the making of the conditional proposition or hypothetical ‘statement’
carries the implication, or rather the emissor of the emissum IMPLIES, either it
is not the case that the emissor is CERTAIN about or that it is day and CERTAIN
about or that he talks, or BELIEVES that it is day and BELIEVES that he
talks.”More or less Grice’s denial or doubt. Or rather ‘doubt’ (Strawson’s
‘uncertainty about’) or denial (‘disbelief in’). But it will do at this point
to explore the argument by Strawson to which Grice is responding. First two
comments. Strawson has occasion to respond to Grice’s response in more than one
opportunity. But Grice never took up the issue again in a detailed fashionafter
dedicating a full lecture to it. One occasion was Strawson’s review of the
reprint of Grice in 1989. Another is in the BA memorial. The crucial one is
repr. by Strawson (in a rather otiose way) in his compilation, straight from
PGRICE. This is an essay which Strawson composed soon after the delivery by
Grice of the lecture without consulting. Once Stawson is aware of Grice’s
terminology, he is ready to frame his view in Grice’s terms: for Strawson,
there IS an implicaturum, but it is a conventional one. His analogy is with the
‘asserted’ “therefore” or “so.” Since this for Grice was at least the second
exemplar of his manoeuvre, it will do to revise the argument from which Grice
extracts the passage in “Prolegomena.” In the body of the full lecture IV,
Grice does not care to mention Strawson at all; in fact, he makes rather hasty
commentaries generalising on both parties of the debate: the formalists, who
are now ‘blue-collared practitioners of the sciences,” i. e. not philosophers
like Grice and Strawson; and the informalists or ‘traditionalists’ like Strawson
who feel offended by the interlopers to the tranquil Elysium of philosophy.
Grice confesses a sympathy for the latter, of course. So here is straight from
the tranquil Elysium of philosophy. For Strawson, the relations between “if”
and “⊃” have already, but only in part, been
discussed (Ch. 2, S. 7).” So one may need to review those passages. But now he
has a special section that finishes up the discussion which has been so far
only partial. So Strawson resumes the points of the previous partial discussion
and comes up with the ‘traditionalist’ tenet. The sign “⊃” is called the
material implication sign. Only by Whitehead and Russell, that is,
‘blue-collared practitioners of the sciences,’ in Grice’s wording. Whitehead
and Russell think that ‘material’ is a nice opposite to ‘formal,’ and ‘formal
implication’ is something pretty complex that only they know to which it
refers! Strawson goes on to explain, and this is a reminder of his
“Introduction” to his “Philosophical Logic” where he reprints Grice’s Meaning
(for some reason). There Strawson has a footnote quoting from Quine’s “Methods
of Logic,” where the phrasing is indeed about the rough phrase, ‘the meaning of
‘if’’cf. Grice’s laughter at philosophers talking of ‘the sense of ‘or’’“Why,
one must should as well talk of the ‘sense’ of ‘to,’ or ‘of’!’Grice’s implicaturum
is to O. P. Wood, whose claim to fame is for having turned Oxford into the
place where ‘the sense of ‘or’’ was the key issue with which philosophers were
engaged. Strawson goes on to say that
its meaning is given by the ‘rule’ that any statement of the form ‘p⊃q’
is FALSE in the case in which the first of its constituent statements is true
and the second false, and is true in every other case considered in the system;
i. e., the falsity of the first constituent statement or the truth of the
second are, equally, sufficient conditions of the truth of a statement of
material implication. The combination of truth in the first with falsity in the
second is the single, NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT, condition of its falsity. The
standard or primary -- the importance of this qualifying phrase, ‘primary,’ can
scarcely be overemphasizedGrice omits this bracket when he expolates the quote.
The bracket continues. The place where Strawson opens the bracket is a curious
one: it is obvious he is talking about the primary use of ‘if’. So here he
continues the bracket with the observation that there are uses of “if” which do not answer to the description given
here, or to any other descriptions given in this [essay] -- use of “if”
sentence, on the other hand [these are Strawson’s two hands], are seen to be in
circumstances where, not knowing whether some statement which could be made by
the use of a sentence corresponding in a certain way to the sub-ordinated clause
of the utterance is true or not, or believing it to be false, the emissor
nevertheless considers that a step in reasoning from THAT statement to a
statement related in a similar way to the main clause would be a sound or
reasonable step [a reasonable reasoning, that is]; this statement related to
the main clause also being one of whose truth the emissor is in doubt, or which
the emissor believes to be false. Even in such circumstances as these a
philosopher may sometimes hesitate to apply ‘true’ to a conditional or
hypothetical statement, i.e., a statement which could be made by the use of “if
”(Philo’s ‘ei,’ Cicero’s ‘si’) in its
standard significance, preferring to call a conditional statement reasonable or
well-founded. But if the philosopher does apply ‘true’ to an ‘if’ utterance at
all, it will be in such circumstances as these. Now one of the sufficient
conditions of the truth of a ‘statement’ or formula of material implication may
very well be fulfilled without the conditions for the truth, or reasonableness,
of the corresponding hypothetical or conditional statement being fulfilled. A
statement of the form ‘p ⊃ q’ (where the horseshoe is meant to
represent an inverted ‘c’ for ‘contentum’ or ‘consequutum’ -- does not entail
the corresponding statement of the ‘form’ “if p, q.” But if the emissor is
prepared to accept the hypothetical statement, he must in consistency be
prepared to deny the conjunction of the statement corresponding to the
sub-ordinated clause of the sentence used to make the hypothetical statement
with the negation of the statement corresponding to its main or super-ordinated
clause. A statement of the ‘form’ “if p, q” does entail the corresponding
statement of the form ‘p ⊃ q.’ The force of “corresponding” may need
some elucidation. Consider the following very ‘ordinary’ or ‘natural’ specimens
of a hypothetical sentence. Strawson starts with a totally unordinary
subjective counterfactual ‘if,’ an abyss with Philo, “If it’s day, I talk.”
Strawson surely involves The Hun. ‘If the Germans had invaded England in 1940,
they, viz. the Germans, would have won the war.’ Because for the Germans,
invading England MEANT winning the war. They never cared much for Wales or
Scotland, never mind Northern Ireland. Possibly ‘invaded London’ would suffice.
Strawson’s second instantiation again is the odd subjective counter-factual
‘if,’ an abyss or chasm from Philo, ‘If it’s day, I talk.’ “If Smith were in
charge, half the staff would have been dismissed.’ Strawson is thinking Noel
Coward, who used to make fun of the music-hall artist Wade. “If you WERE the
only girl in the world, and I WAS the only boy…’. The use of ‘were’ is Oxonian.
A Cockney is forbidden to use it, using ‘was’ instead. The rationale is
Philonian. ‘was’ is indicative. “If
Smith were in charge, half the staff would have been dismissed.’ Strawson’s
third instantiation is, at last, more or less Philonian, a plain indicative
‘weather’ protasis, etc. “If it rains, the match will be cancelled.” The only
reservation Philo would have is ‘will’. Matches do not have ‘will,’ and the sea
battle may never take placethe world may be destroyed by then. “If it rains,
the match will be cancelled.” Or “If it rains, the match is cancelledbut there
is a ‘rain date.’” The sentence which could be used to make a statement corresponding
in the required ‘sense’ to the sub-ordinate clause can be ascertained by
considering what it is that the emissor of each hypothetical sentence must (in
general) be assumed either to be in doubt about or to believe to be not the
case. Thus, the corresponding sentences. ‘The Germans invaded England in 1940.’
Or ‘The Germans invade England’historical present -- ‘The Germans won the war.’
Or ‘The Germans win the war’historical present. ‘Smith is in charge.’ ‘Half the
staff has been dismissed.’ Or ‘Half the staff is dismissed.’ ‘It will rain.’ Or
‘It rains.’‘The match will be cancelled.’ Or ‘The match is cancelled.’ A
sentence could be used to make a statement of material implication corresponding
to the hypothetical statement made by the
sentence is framed, in each case, from these pairs of sentences as
follows. ‘The Germans invaded England in 1940 ⊃ they won the war.’
Or in the historical present,’The Germans invade London ⊃
The Germans win the war. ‘ ‘Smith is in charge ⊃ half the staff has
been, dismissed.’ Or in the present tense, ‘Smith is in charge ⊃
half the staff is dismissed.’ ‘ It will rain ⊃ the match will be
cancelled.’ Or in the present ‘It rains ⊃ the match is
cancelled.’ The very fact that a few
verbal modifications are necessary to please the Oxonian ear, in order to
obtain from the clauses of the hypothetical sentence the clauses of the
corresponding material implication sentence is itself a symptom of the radical
difference between a hypothetical statement and a truth-functional statement.
Some detailed differences are also evident from these instantiations. The
falsity of a statement made by the use of ‘The Germans invade London in 1940’
or ‘Smith is in charge’ is a sufficient condition of the truth of the
corresponding statements made by the use of the ⊃-utterances. But
not, of course, of the corresponding statement made by the use of the ‘if’
utterance. Otherwise, there would normally be no point in using an ‘if’ sentence
at all.An ‘if’ sentence would normally carrybut not necessarily: one may use
the pluperfect or the imperfect subjunctive when one is simply working out the
consequences of an hypothesis which one may be prepared eventually to accept --
in the tense or mode of the verb, an implication (or implicaturum) of the
emissor’s belief in the FALSITY of the statements corresponding to the clauses
of the hypothetical.That it is not the case that it rains is sufficient to
verify (or truth-functionally confirm) a statement made by the use of “⊃,”
but not a statement made by the use of ‘if.’ That it is not the case that it
rains is also sufficient to verify (or truth-functionally confirm) a statement
made by the use of ‘It will rain ⊃ the match will not
be cancelled.’ Or ‘It rains ⊃ the match is
cancelled.’ The formulae ‘p ⊃ q’ and ‘p ⊃
~ q' are consistent with one another.The joint assertion of corresponding
statements of these forms is equivalent to the assertion of the corresponding
statement of the form ‘~ p.’ But, and here is one of Philo’s ‘paradoxes’: “If
it rains, the match will be cancelled” (or ‘If it rains, the match is
cancelled’) seems (or sounds) inconsistent with “If it rains, the match will
not be cancelled,’ or ‘If it rains, it is not the case that the match is cancelled.’But
here we add ‘not,’ so Philo explains the paradox away by noting that his
account is meant for ‘pure’ uses of “ei,” or “si.”Their joint assertion in the
same context sounds self-contradictory. But cf. Philo, who wisely said of ‘If it is day, it is night’ “is true only at night.”
(Diog. Laert. Repr. in Long, The Hellenistic Philosophers). Suppose we
call the statement corresponding to the sub-ordinated clause of a sentence used
to make a hypothetical statement the antecedent of the hypothetical statement;
and the statement corresponding to the super-ordinated clause, its consequent. It
is sometimes fancied that, whereas the futility of identifying a conditional
‘if’ statement with material implication is obvious in those cases where the
implication of the falsity of the antecedent is normally carried by the mode or
tense of the verbas in “If the Germans invade London in 1940, they, viz. the
Germans, win the war’ and ‘If Smith is in charge, half the staff is dismissed’
-- there is something to be said for at least a PARTIAL identification in cases
where no such implication is involved, i.e., where the possibility of the truth
of both antecedent and consequent is left openas in ‘If it rains, the match is
cancelled.’ In cases of the first kind (an ‘unfulfilled,’ counterfactual, or
‘subjunctive’ conditional) the intended addressee’s attention is directed, as
Grice taught J. L. Mackie, in terms of the principle of conversational
helpfulness, ONLY TO THE LAST TWO ROWS of the truth-tables for ‘ p ⊃
q,’ where the antecedent has the truth-value, falsity. Th suggestion that ‘~p’ ‘entails’
‘if p, q’ is felt or to be or ‘sounds’if not to Philo’s or Grice’s ears -- obviously
wrong. But in cases of the second kind
one inspects also the first two ROWS. The possibility of the antecedent's being
fulfilled is left open. It is claimed that it is NOT the case that the
suggestion that ‘p ⊃ q’ ‘entails’ ‘if p, q’ is felt to be or
sound obviously wrong, to ANYBODY, not just the bodies of Grice and Philo. This
Strawson calls, to infuriate Grice, ‘an illusion,’ ‘engendered by a reality.’The
fulfilment of both antecedent and consequent of a hypothetical statement does
not show that the man who made the hypothetical statement is right. It is not
the case that the man would be right, Strawson claims, if the consequent is
made true as a result of this or that factor unconnected with, or in spite of,
rather than ‘because’ of, the fulfilment of the antecedent. E. g. if Grice’s unmissable match is missed
because the Germans invadeand not because of the ‘weather.’but cf. “The weather
in the streets.” Strawson is prepared to say that the man (e. g., Grice, or
Philo) who makes the hypothetical statement is right only if Strawson is also
prepared to say that the antecedent being true is, at least in part, the ‘explanation’
of the consequent being true. The reality behind the illusion Strawson
naturally finds ‘complex,’ for surely there ain’t one! Strawson thinks that
this is due to two phenomena. First, Strawson claims, in many cases, the
fulfilment of both antecedent and consequent provides confirmation for the view
that the existence of states of affairs like those described by the antecedent
IS a good ‘reason’ for expecting (alla Hume, assuming the uniformity of nature,
etc.) a states of affair like that described by the consequent. Second,
Starwson claims, a man (e. g. Philo, or Grice) who (with a straight Grecian or
Griceian face) says, e. g. ‘If it rains, the match is cancelled’ makes a bit of
a prediction, assuming the ‘consequent’ to be referring to t2>t1but cf. if
he is reporting an event taking place at THE OTHER PLACE. The prediction
Strawson takes it to be ‘The match is cancelled.’And the man is making the
prediction ONLY under what Strawson aptly calls a “proviso,” or “caveat,”first
used by Boethius to translate Aristotle -- “It rains.” Boethius’s terminology
later taken up by the lawyers in Genoa. mid-15c.,
from Medieval Latin proviso (quod) "provided (that)," phrase
at the beginning of clauses in legal documents (mid-14c.), from Latin proviso "it
being provided," ablative neuter of provisus, past participle
of providere (see provide).
Related: Provisory.
And that the cancellation of the match because of the rain therefore leads us
to say, not only that the reasonableness of the prediction was confirmed, but
also that the prediction itself was confirmed. Because it is not the case that a statement of
the form ‘ p ⊃ q’ entails the corresponding statement of
the form ' if p, q ' (in its standard employment), Strawson thinks he can find
a divergence between this or that ‘rule’ for '⊃' and this or that
‘rule’ for '’if ,’ in its standard employment. Because ‘if p, q’ does entail ‘p
⊃ q,’ we shall also expect to find some
degree of parallelism between the rules. For whatever is entailed by ‘p ⊃
q’ is entailed by ‘if p, q,’ though not everything which entails ‘p ⊃
q’ does Strawson claims, entail ‘if p, q.’ Indeed, we find further parallels than those
which follow simply from the facts that ‘if p, q’ entails ‘p ⊃
q’ and that entailment is transitive. To
some laws for ‘⊃,’ Strawson finds no parallels for ‘if.’ Strawson
notes that for at least four laws for ‘⊃,’ we find that parallel
laws ‘hold’ good for ‘if. The first law is mentioned by Grice, modus ponendo
ponens, as elimination of ‘⊃.’ Strawson does
not consider the introduction of the horseshoe, where p
an q forms a collection of all active assumptions previously introduced which
could have been used in the deduction of ‘if p, q.’ When
inferring ‘if p, q’ one is allowed to discharge assumptions of the
form p. The fact that after deduction of ‘if p, q’ this
assumption is discharged (not active is pointed out by using [ ] in vertical
notation, and by deletion from the set of assumptions in horizontal notation.
The latter notation shows better the character of the rule; one deduction is
transformed into the other. It shows also that the rule for the introduction
of ‘if’ corresponds to an important metatheorem, the Deduction Theorem,
which has to be proved in axiomatic formalizations of logic. But back to
the elimination of ‘if’. Modus ponendo ponens. ‘‘((p ⊃
q).p) ⊃ q.’ For some reason, Strawson here mixes
horseshoes and ifs as if Boethius is alive! Grice calls these “half-natural,
half-artificial.’ Chomsky prefers ‘semi-native.’ ‘(If p, q, and p) ⊃q.’
Surely what Strawson wants is a purely ‘if’ one, such as ‘If, if p, q, and p,
q.’ Some conversational implicaturum! As
Grice notes: “Strawson thinks that one can converse using his converses, but we
hardly.’ The second law. Modus tollendo tollens. ‘((p⊃q).
~ q)) ⊃ (~ p).’ Again, Strawson uses a ‘mixed’
formula: (if p, q, and it is not the case that q) ⊃
it is not the case that p. Purely unartificial: If, if p, q, and it is not the
case that q, it is not the case that p. The third law, which Strawson finds
problematic, and involves an operator that Grice does not even consider. ‘(p ⊃
q) ≡ (~ q
⊃ ~ p). Mixed version, Strawson simplifies
‘iff’ to ‘if’ (in any case, as Pears notes, ‘if’ IMPLICATES ‘iff.’). (If p, q) ⊃
if it is not the case that q, it is not the case that p. Unartificial: If, if
p, q, it is not the case that if q, it is not the case that p. The fourth law. ((p
⊃ q).(q ⊃ r)) ⊃
(p ⊃ r). Mixed: (if p, q, and if q, r) ⊃
(if p, r). Unartificial: ‘If, if p, q, and if q, r, if p, r.’ Try to say that
to Mrs. Grice! (Grice: “It’s VERY SURPRISING that Strawson think we can
converse in his lingo!”). Now Strawson displays this or that ‘reservation.’
Mainly it is an appeal to J. Austen and J. Austin. Strawson’s implicaturum is
that Philo, in Megara, has hardly a right to unquiet the tranquil Elysium. This
or that ‘reservation’ by Strawson takes TWO pages of his essay. Strawson claims
that the reservations are important. It is, e. g., often impossible to apply
entailment-rule (iii) directly without obtaining incorrect or absurd results. Some
modification of the structure of the clauses of the hypothetical is commonly
necessary. Alas, Whitehead and Russell give us little guide as to which
modifications are required. If we apply
rule (iii) to our specimen hypothetical sentences, without modifying at all the
tenses or moods of the individual clauses, we obtain expressions which Austin
would not call ‘ordinary language,’ or Austen, for that matter, if not
Macaulay. If we preserve as nearly as
possible the tense-mode structure, in the simplest way consistent with
grammatical requirements, we obtain this or that sentence. TOLLENDO TOLLENS. ‘If
it is not the case that the Germans win the war, it is not the case that they,
viz. the Germans, invade England in 1940.’ ‘If it is not the case that half the
staff is dismissed, it is not the case that Smith is in charge.’ ‘If it is not
the case that the match is cancelled, it is not the case that it rains.’ But,
Strawson claims, these sentences, so far from SOUNDING or seeming logically
equivalent to the originals, have in each case a quite different ‘sense.’ It is
possible, at least in some cases, to frame, via tollendo tollens a target
setence of more or less the appropriate pattern for which one can imagine a use
and which DOES stand in the required relationship to the source sentence. ‘If it
is not the case that the Germans win the war, (trust) it is not the case that
they, viz. the Germans, invade England in 1940,’ with the attending imlicatum:
“only because they did not invade England in 1940.’ or even, should historical
evidence be scanty). ‘If it is not the case that the Germans win the war, it
SURELY is not the case that they, viz. the Germans, invade London in 1940.’ ‘If
it is not the case that half the staff is dismissed, it surely is not the case
that Smith is in charge.’ These changes reflect differences in the
circumstances in which one might use these, as opposed to the original,
sentences. The sentence beginning ‘If
Smith is in charge …’ is normally, though not necessarily, used by a man who
antecedently knows that it is not the case that Smith is in charge. The
sentence beginning ‘If it is not the case that half the staff is dismissed …’ is normally, though not necessarily, used by
by a man who is, as Cook Wilson would put it, ‘working’ towards the ‘consequent’
conclusion that Smith is not in charge. To
say that the sentences are nevertheless truth-functionally equivalent seems to
point to the fact that, given the introduction rule for ‘if,’ the grounds for
accepting the original ‘if’-utterance AND the ‘tollendo tollens’ correlatum, would,
in two different scenarios, have been grounds for accepting the soundness or
validity of the passage or move from a premise ‘Smith is in charge’ to its
‘consequentia’ ‘consequutum,’ or ‘conclusion,’ ‘Half the staff is dismissed.’ One
must remember that calling each formula (i)-(iv) a LAW or a THEOREM is the same
as saying that, e.g., in the case of (iii), ‘If p, q’ ‘ENTAILS’ ‘If it is not
the case that q, it is not the case that p.’ Similarly, Strawson thinks, for
some steps which would be invalid for ‘if,’ there are corresponding steps that
would be invalid for ‘⊃.’ He gives two example using a symbol
Grice does not consider, for ‘therefore,’ or ‘ergo,’ and lists a fallacy. First
example. ‘(p ⊃ q).q ∴ p.’
Second example of a fallacy:‘(p ⊃ q). ~p ∴ ~q.’ These are
invalid inference-patterns, and so are the correlative patterns with ‘if’: ‘If
p, q; and q ∴ p’ ‘If p, q; and it
is not the case that p ∴
it is not the case that q.
The formal analogy here may be described by saying that neither ‘p ⊃ q’ nor ‘if p, q’ is a simply convertible (“nor
hardly conversable”Grice) formula. Strawson thinks, and we are getting closer
to Philo’s paradoxes, revisied, that there may be this or that laws which holds
for ‘p ⊃ q’ and not for ‘If p, q.’ As an example of a law which holds for ‘if’
but not for ‘⊃,’ one may give an analytic formula. ~[(if
p, q) . (if p, it is not the case that q)]’. The corresponding formula with the
horseshoe is not analytic. ‘~[(p ⊃ q) . (p ⊃
~q)]’ is not analytic, and is equivalent to the contingent formula ‘~ ~p.’ The
rules to the effect that this or that formula is analytic is referred to by
Johnson, in the other place, as the ‘paradox of implication.’ This Strawson
finds a Cantabrigian momer. If Whitehead’s and Russell’s ‘⊃’
is taken as identical either with Moore’s ‘entails’ or, more widely, with Aelfric’s‘if’as in his “Poem to the If,” MSS
Northumberland“If” meant trouble in Anglo-Saxon -- in its standard use, the
rules that yield this or that so-called ‘paradox’ -- are not, for Strawson, “just
paradoxical.” With an attitude, he adds. “They are simply incorrect.”This is
slightly illogical.“That’s not paradoxical; that’s incorrect.”Cf. Grice, “What
is paradoxical is not also incorrect.” And cf. Grice: “Philo defines a
‘paradox’ as something that surprises _his father_.’ He is ‘using’ “father,”
metaphorically, to refer to his tutor. His father was unknown (to him). On the
other hand (vide Strawson’s Two Hands), with signs you can introduce alla
Peirce and Johnson by way of ostensive definition any way you wish! If ‘⊃’
is given the meaning it is given by what Grice calls the ‘truth-table
definition,’ or ‘stipulation’ in the system of truth functions, the rules and
the statements they represent, may be informally dubbed ‘paradoxical,’ in that
they don’t agree with the ‘man in the street,’ or ‘the man on High.’ The
so-called ‘paradox’ would be a simple and platitudinous consequence of the
meaning given to the symbol. Strawson had expanded on the paradoxes in an essay
he compiled while away from Oxford. On his return to Oxford, he submitted it to
“Mind,” under the editorship by G. Ryle, where it was published. The essay
concerns the ‘paradoxes’ of ‘entailment’ in detail, and mentions Moore and C.
I. Lewis. He makes use of modal operators, nec. and poss. to render the
‘necessity’ behind ‘entail.’ He thinks the paradoxes of ‘entailment’ arise from
inattention to this modality. At the time, Grice and Strawson were pretty sure
that nobody then accepted, if indeed anyone ever did and did make, the identification
of the relation symbolised by the horseshoe, ⊃, with the relation
which Moore calls ‘entailment,’ p⊃q, i. e. The mere
truth-functional ‘if,’ as in ‘p ⊃ q,’ ‘~(pΛ~q)’ is
rejected as an analysis of the meta-linguistic ‘p entails q.’ Strawson thinks
that the identification is rejected because ‘p ⊃ q’ involves this
or that allegedly paradoxical implicaturum.Starwson explicitly mentions ‘ex
falso quodlibeet.’ Any FALSE proposition entails any proposition, true or
false. And any TRUE proposition is entailed by any proposition, true or falso
(consequentia mirabilis). It is a commonplace
that Lewis, whom Grice calls a
‘blue-collared practioner of the sciences,’ Strawson thinks, hardly solved the
thing. The amendment by Lewis, for Strawson, has consequences scarcely less
paradoxical in terms of the implicatura. For if p is impossible, i.e.
self-contradictory, it is impossible that p and ~q. And if q is necessary,
~q is impossible and it is impossible that p and ~q; i. e., if p entails q
means it is impossible that p and ~q any necessary proposition is entailed by
any proposition and any self-contradictory proposition entails any proposition.
On the other hand, the definition by Lewis of ‘strict’ implication or
entailment (i.e. of the relation which holds from p to q whenever q is
deducible from p), Strawson thinks, obviously commends itself in some respects.
Now, it is clear that the emphasis laid on the expression-mentioning character
of the intensional contingent statement by writing ‘ ‘pΛ~q’ is impossible
instead’ of ‘It is impossible that p and ~q’ does not avoid the alleged
paradoxes of entailment. But, Starwson optimistically thinks, it is equally
clear that the addition of some provision does avoid them. Strawson
proposes that one should use “p entails q” such that no necessary statement and
no negation of a necessary statement can significantly be said to “entail” or
be entailed by any statement; i. e. the function “p entails q” cannot take
necessary or self-contradictory statements as arguments. The expression “p
entails q” is to be used to mean “ ‘p ⊃ q’ is necessary,
and neither ‘p’ nor ‘q’ is either necessary or self-contradictory.” Alternatively,
“p entails q” should be used only to mean “ ‘pΛ~q’ is impossible and neither ‘p’
nor ‘q,’ nor either of their contradictories, is necessary. In this way,
Strawson thinks the paradoxes are avoided. Strawson’s proof. Let us assume that
p1 expresses a contingent, and q1 a necessary, proposition. p1 and ~q1 is now
impossible because ~q1 is impossible. But q1 is necessary. So, by that
provision, p1 does not entail q1. We may avoid the paradoxical assertion “p1
entails q2” as merely falling into the equally paradoxical assertion “ “p1
entails q1” is necessary.” For: If ‘q’ is necessary, ‘q is necessary’ is,
though true, not necessary, but a CONTINGENT INTENSIONAL (Latinate) statement. This becomes part of the
philosophers lexicon: intensĭo, f. intendo, which L and S render as
a stretching out, straining, effort. E. g. oculorum, Scrib. Comp. 255.
Also an intensifying, increase. Calorem suum (sol) intensionibus ac remissionibus
temperando fovet,” Sen. Q. N. 7, 1, 3. The tune: “gravis, media, acuta,”
Censor. 12. Hence: ‘~ (‘q’ is necessary)’ is, though false, possible.
Hence “p1 Λ ~ (q1 is necessary)” is, though false, possible. Hence ‘p1’ does NOT entail ‘q1 is necessary.’ Thus,
by adopting the view that an entailment statement, and other intensional
statements, are contingent, viz. non-necessary, and that no necessary statement
or its contradictory can entail or be entailed by any statement, Strawson
thinks he can avoid the paradox that a necessary proposition is entailed by any
proposition, and indeed all the other associated paradoxes of entailment. Grice objects that the alleged cure by
Strawson is worse than disease of Moore! The denial that a necessary proposition can
entail or be entailed by any proposition, and, therefore, that necessary
propositions can be related to each other by the entailment relation, is too
high a price to pay for the solution of the paradoxes, which are perfectly true
utterances with only this or that attending cancellable implicaturum. Strawson’s
introduction of ‘acc.’ makes sense. Which makes sense in that Philo first
supplied his truth-functional account of ‘if’ to criticise his tutor Diodorus
on modality. Philo reported to Diodorus something he had heard from Neptune. In
dreams, Neptune appeared to Philo and told him: “I saw down deep in the waters
a wooden trunk of a plant that only grows under weatheralgae -- The trunk can
burn!” Neptune said.Awakening, Philo ran to Diodorus: “A wooden trunk deep down
in the ocean can burn.” Throughout this section, Strawson refers to a
‘primary or standard’ use of ‘if,’ of which the main characteristics are
various. First, that for each hypothetical statement made by this use of ‘if,’ there
could be made just one statement which would be the antecedent of the
hypothetical and just one statement which would be its consequent. Second, that
the hypothetical statement is acceptable (true, reasonable) if the antecedent
statement, if made or accepted, would, in the circumstances, be a good ground
or reason for accepting the consequent statement. Third, the making of the
hypothetical statement carries the implication either of uncertainty about, or
of disbelief in, the fulfilment of both antecedent and consequent.’ This above
is the passage extrapolated by Grice. Grice does not care to report the
platitudionous ‘first’ ‘characteristic’ as Strawson rather verbosely puts it.
The way Grice reports it, it is not clear Strawson is listing THREE
characteristics. Notably, from the extrapolated quote, it would seem as if
Grice wishes his addressee to believe that Strawson thinks that characteristic
2 and characteristic 3 mix. On top, Grice omits a caveat immediately after the
passage he extrapolates. Strawso notes: “There is much more than this to be
said about this way of using ‘if;’ in particular, about the meaning of the
question whether the antecedent would be a GOOD ground or reason for accepting
the consequent, and about the exact way in which THIS question is related to
the question of whether the hypothetical is TRUE {acceptable, reasonable) or
not.’ Grice does not care to include a caveat by Strawson: “Not all uses of ‘if
,’ however, exhibit all these three characteristics.” In particular, there is a
use which has an equal claim to rank as standard ‘if’ and which is closely
connected with the use described, but which does not exhibit the first
characteristic and for which the description of the remainder must consequently
be modified. Strawson has in mind what
is sometimes called a ‘formal’ (by Whitehead and Russell) or 'variable' or
'general’ or ‘generic’ hypothetical. Strawson gives three examples. The first
example is ‘lf ice is left in the sun, it melts.’ This is Kantian. Cf. Grice on
indicative conditionals in the last Immanuel Kant Lecture. Grice: "It
should be, given that it is the case that one smears one's skin with peanut
butter before retiring and that it is the case that one has a relatively insensitive
skin, that it is the case that one preserves a youthful complexion." More
generally, there is some plausibility to the idea that an exemplar of the form
'Should (! E, ⊢F;
! G)' is true just in case a corresponding examplar of the form 'Should (⊢ F, ⊢G; ⊢E)' is true. Before
proceeding further, I will attempt to deal briefly with a possible objection
which might be raised at this point. I can end imagine an ardent descriptivist,
who first complains, in the face of someone who wishes to allow a legitimate
autonomous status to practical acceptability generalizations, that
truth-conditions for such generalizations are not available, and perhaps are in
principle not available; so such generalizations are not to be taken seriously.
We then point out to him that, at least for a class of such cases,
truth-conditions are available, and that they are to be found in related
alethic generalizations, a kind of generalization he accepts. He then complains
that, if finding truth-conditions involves representing the practical
acceptability generalizations as being true just in case related alethic
generalizations are true, then practical acceptability generalizations are
simply reducible to alethic generalizations, and so are not to be taken
seriously for another reason, namely, that they are simply transformations of
alethic generalizations, and we could perfectly well get on without them. Maybe
some of you have heard some ardent descriptivists arguing in a style not so
very different from this. Now a deep reply to such an objection would involve
(I think) a display of the need for a system of reasoning in which the value to
be transmitted by acceptable inference is not truth but practical value,
together with a demonstration of the role of practical acceptability generalizations
in such a system. I suspect that such a reply could be constructed, but I do
not have it at my fingertips (or tongue-tip), so I shall not try to produce it.
An interim reply, however, might take the following form: even though it may be
true (which is by no means certain) that certain practical acceptability
generalizations have the same truth-conditions as certain corresponding alethic
generalizations, it is not to be supposed that the former generalizations are
simply reducible to the latter (in some disrespectful sense of 'reducible').
For though both kinds of generalization are
defeasible, they are not defeasible in the same way; more exactly, what is a
defeating condition for a given practical generalization is not a defeating
condition for its alethic counterpart. A generalization of the form 'should (!
E, ⊢F;
! G)' may have, as a defeating condition, 'E*'; that is to say, consistently
with the truth of this generalization, it may be true that 'should (! E & !
E*, ⊢F;
! G*)' where 'G*' is
inconsistent with 'G'. But since, in the
alethic counterpart generalization 'should (⊢ F, ⊢G; ⊢E)', 'E' does not occur
in the antecedent, 'E*' cannot be a defeating end p.92 condition for this
generalization. And, since liability to defeat by a certain range of defeating
conditions is essential to the role which acceptability generalizations play in
reasoning, this difference between a practical generalization and its alethic
counterpart is sufficient to eliminate the reducibility of the former to the
latter. To return to the main theme of this section. If, without further ado,
we were to accept at this point the suggestion that 'should (! E, ⊢F; ! G)' is true just
in case 'should (⊢
F, ⊢G;
⊢E)'
is true, we should be accepting it simply on the basis of intuition (including,
of course, linguistic or logical intuition under the head of 'intuition'). If the
suggestion is correct then we should attain, at the same time, a stronger
assurance that it is correct and a better theoretical understanding of the
alethic and practical acceptability, if we could show why it is correct by
deriving it from some general principle(s). Kant, in fact, for reasons not
unlike these, sought to show the validity of a different but fairly closely
related Technical Imperative by just such a method. The form which he selects
is one which, in my terms, would be represented by "It is fully
acceptable, given let it be that B, that let it be that A" or "It is
necessary, given let it be that B, that let it be that A". Applying this
to the one fully stated technical imperative given in Grundlegung, we get
Kant’s hypothetical which is of the type Strawson calls ‘variable,’ formal,
‘generic,’ or ‘generic.’ Kant: “It is necessary, given let it be that one
bisect a line on an unerring principle, that let it be that I draw from its
extremities two intersecting arcs". Call this statement, (α). Though he
does not express himself very clearly, I am certain that his claim is that this
imperative is validated in virtue of the fact that it is, analytically, a
consequence of an indicative statement which is true and, in the present
context, unproblematic, namely, the statement vouched for by geometry, that if
one bisects a line on an unerring principle, then one does so only as a result
of having drawn from its extremities two intersecting arcs. Call this
statement, (β). His argument seems to be expressible as follows. (1) It is
analytic that he who wills the end (so far as reason decides his conduct),
wills the indispensable means thereto. (2) So it is analytic that (so far as
one is rational) if one wills that A, and judges that if A, then A as a result
of B, then one wills that B. end p.93 (3) So it is analytic that (so far as one
is rational) if one judges that if A, then A as a result of B, then if one
wills that A then one wills that B. (4) So it is analytic that, if it is true
that if A, then A as a result of B, then if let it be that A, then it must be
that let it be that B. From which, by substitution, we derive (5): it is
analytic that if β then α. Now it seems to me to be meritorious, on Kant's
part, first that he saw a need to justify hypothetical imperatives of this
sort, which it is only too easy to take for granted, and second that he invoked
the principle that "he who wills the end, wills the means";
intuitively, this invocation seems right. Unfortunately, however, the step from
(3) to (4) seems open to dispute on two different counts. (1) It looks as if an
unwarranted 'must' has appeared in the consequent of the conditional which is
claimed, in (4), as analytic; the most that, to all appearances, could be
claimed as being true of the antecedent is that 'if let it be that A then let
it be that B'. (2) (Perhaps more serious.) It is by no means clear by what
right the psychological verbs 'judge' and 'will', which appear in (3), are
omitted in (4); how does an (alleged) analytic connection between (i) judging
that if A, A as a result of B and (ii) its being the case that if one wills
that A then one wills that B yield an analytic connection between (i) it's
being the case that if A, A as a result of B and (ii) the 'proposition' that if
let it be that A then let it be that B? Can the presence in (3) of the phrase
"in so far as one is rational" legitimize this step? I do not know
what remedy to propose for the first of these two difficulties; but I will
attempt a reconstruction of Kant's line of argument which might provide relief
from the second. It might, indeed, even be an expansion of Kant's actual
thinking; but whether or not this is so, I am a very long way from being
confident in its adequacy. Back to Strawson. First example: ‘lf ice is left in the sun, it melts.’Or “If
apple goes up, apple goes down.”Newton, “Principia Mathematica.” “If ice is
left in the sun, it, viz. ice, melts.” Strawson’s second example of a formal,
variable, generic, or general ‘if’ ‘If the side of a triangle is produced, the
exterior angle is equal to the sum of the two interior and opposite angles.’
Cf. Kant: “If a line on an unerring principle
is bisected, two intersecting arcs are drawn from its extremities.” Synthetical
propositions must no doubt be employed in defining the means to a proposed end;
but they do not concern the principle, the act of the will, but the object and
its realization. E.g., that in order to bisect a line on an unerring principle
I must draw from its extremities two intersecting arcs; this no doubt is taught
by mathematics only in synthetical propositions; but if I know that it is only
by this process that the intended operation can be performed, then to say that,
if I fully will the operation, I also will the action required for it, is an analytical
proposition; for it is one and the same thing to conceive something as an
effect which I can produce in a certain way, and to conceive myself as acting
in this way. Strawson’s third example: ‘If
a child is very strictly disciplined in the nursery, it, viz. the child, that
should be seen but not heard, will develop aggressive tendencies in adult
life.’ To a statement made by the use of a sentence such as these there
corresponds no single pair of statements which are, respectively, its
antecedent and consequent. On the other hand,
for every such statement there is an indefinite number of NON-general, or not
generic, hypothetical statements which might be called exemplifications,
applications, of the variable hypothetical; e.g., a statement made by the use
of the sentence ‘If THIS piece of ice is left in the sun, it, viz. this piece,
melts.’Strawson, about to finish his section on “ ‘⊃’
and ‘if’,”the expression, ‘’ ⊃’ and ‘if’” only
occurs in the “Table of Contents,” on p. viii, not in the body of the essay, as
found redundantit is also the same title Strawson used for his essay which
circulated (or ‘made the rounds’) soon after Grice delivered his attack on
Strawson, and which Strawson had, first, the cheek to present it to PGRICE, and
then, voiding the idea of a festschrift, reprint it in his own compilation of
essays. -- from which Grice extracted the quote for “Prolegomena,” notes that
there are two ‘relatively uncommon uses of ‘if.’‘If he felt embarrassed, he
showed no signs of it.’It is this example that Grice is having in mind in the
fourth lecture on ‘indicative conditionals.’ “he didn’t show it.”Grice is
giving an instantiation of an IMPLICIT, or as he prefers, ‘contextual,’
cancellation of the implicaturum of ‘if.’
He does this to show that even if the implicaturum of ‘if’ is a
‘generalised,’ not ‘generic,’ or ‘general,’ one, it need not obtain or be
present in every PARTICULAR case. “That is why I use the weakened form
‘generalISED, not general. It’s all ceteris paribus always with me).” The
example Grice gives corresponds to the one Strawson listed as one of the two ‘relatively
uncommon’ uses of ‘if.’ By sticking with the biscuit conditional, Grice is
showing Strawson that this use is ‘relatively uncommon’ because it is
absolutely otiose! “If he was surprised,
he didn’t show it.”Or cf. AustinIf you are hungry, there are. Variants by Grice
on his own example:“If Strawson was surprised, he did not show it.”“If he was
surprised, it is not the case that Strawson showed it, viz. that he was
surprised.”Grice (on the phone with Strawson’s friend) in front of Strawsonpresent
tense version:“If he IS surprised, it is not th case that he, Strawson, is
showing it, viz. the clause that he is surprised. Are you implicating he
SHOULD?”and a second group:‘If Rembrandt passes the exam at the Koninklijke Academie van Beeldende Kunsten, I am
a Dutchman.’‘If the Mad Hatter is not mad, I'll eat my hat.’(as opposed to ‘If
the Mad Hatter IS mad, I’ll eat HIS hat.’)Hats were made at Oxford in a
previous generation, by mad ‘hatters.’ “To eat one’s hat,” at Oxford, became
synonymous with ‘I’ll poison myself and die.’ The reason of the prevalence of
Oxonian ‘lunatic’ hatters is chemical. Strawson is referring to what he calls
an ‘old wives’ tale’As every grandmother at Oxford knows, the chemicals used in
hat-making include mercurious nitrate, which is used in ‘curing’ felt. Now exposure
to the mercury vapours cause mercury poisoning. Or, to use an ‘if’: “If Kant is
exposed to mercury vapour, Kant gets poisoned. A poisoned victim develops a severe and uncontrollable muscular
tremors and twitching limbs, distorted vision and confused speech,
hallucinations and psychosis, if not death. For a time, it was at Oxford
believed that a wearer of a hat could similarly die, especially by eating the
felt containing the mercurial nitrate. The sufficient and necessary condition
of the truth of a statement made by “If he was surprised, it is not the case
that Strawson showed it, viz. that he was surprised” is that it is not the case
that Strawson showed that he was surprised. The antecedent is otiose. Cf. “If
you are hungry, there are biscuits in the cupboard.’ Austin used to expand the
otiose antecedent further, ‘If you are hungryAND EVEN IF YOU ARE NOTthere are
biscuits in the cupboard,” just in case someone was ignorant of Grice’s
principle of conversational helpfulness. Consequently, Strawson claims that such
a statement cannot be treated either as a standard hypothetical or as a
material implication. This is funny because by the time Grice is criticizing
Strawson he does take “If Strawson is surprised, it is not the case that he is
showing it, viz. that he is surprised.” But when it comes to “Touch the beast
and it will bite you” he is ready to say that here we do not have a case of
‘conjunction.’Why? Stanford.Stanford is the answer.Grice had prepared the text
to deliver at Stanford, of all places. Surely, AT STANFORD, you don’t want to
treat your addressee idiotically. What Grice means is:“Now let us consider
‘Touch the beast and it will bite you.’ Symbolise it: !p et !q. Turn it into
the indicative: You tell your love and love bites you (variant on William
Blake).” Grice: “One may object to the
use of ‘p.q’ on Whiteheadian grounds. Blue-collared practitioners of the
sciences will usually proclaim that they do not care about the ‘realisability’
of this or that operator. In fact, the very noun, ‘realisability,’ irritated me
so that I coined non-detachability as a balance. The blue-collared scientist
will say that ‘and’ is really Polish, and should be PRE-FIXED as an “if,” or
condition, or proviso. So that the conjunction becomes “Provided you tell your
love, love bites you.”Strawson gives his reason about the ‘implicaturum’ of
what P. L. Gardiner called the ‘dutchman’ ‘if,’ after G. F. Stout’s “
‘hat-eating’ if.” Examples of the second
kind are sometimes erroneously treated as evidence that Philo was not crazy,
and that ‘if’ does, after all, behave somewhat as ‘⊃’
behaves. Boethius appropriately
comments: “Philo had two drawbacks against his favour. He had no drawing board,
and he couldn’t write. Therefore he never symbolized, other than ‘via
verba,’ his ‘ei’ utterance, “If it is
day, it is night,” which he held to be true “at night only.”” Strawson echoes
Grice. The evidence for this conversational explanation of the oddity of the
‘dutcham’ if, as called by Gardiner, and the ‘hat-eating’ if, as called by Stout,
is, presumably, the facts, first, that the relation between antecedent and
consequent is non-Kantian. Recall that Kant has a ‘Funktion’ which, after
Aristotle’s ‘pros ti,’ and Boethius’s ‘relatio,’ he called ‘Relation’ where he
considers the HYPOTHETICAL. Kant expands in section 8.5. “In the hypothetical,
‘If God exists, I’ll eat my hat,’ existence is no predicate.”Strawson appeals
to a second, “more convincing,” fact, viz. that the consequent is obviously notin
the Dutchman ‘if,’ or not to be, in the ‘hat-eating’ if, fulfilled, or
true.Grice’s passing for a Dutchman and sitting for an exam at the Koninklijke Academie van Beeldende Kunsten, hardly
makes him a Dutchman.Dickens was well aware of the idiocy of people blaming
hatters for the increases of deaths at Oxford. He would often expand the
consequent in a way that turned it “almost a Wittgensteinian ‘contradiction’”
(“The Cricket in the House, vii). “If the Hatter is not mad, I will eat my hat,
with my head in it.”Grice comments: “While it is analytic that you see with
your eyes, it is not analytic that you eat with your mouth. And one can imagine
Dickens’s mouth to be situated in his right hand. Therefore, on realizing that
the mad hatter is not mad, Dickens is allowing for it to be the case that he
shall eat his hat, with his head in it. Since not everybody may be aware of the
position of Dickens’s mouth, I shall not allot this common-ground status.”Strawson
gives a third Griciean fact.“The intention of the emissor, by uttering a
‘consequens falsum’ that renders the ‘conditionalis’ ‘verum’ only if the
‘antecedens’ is ‘falsum, is an emphatic, indeed, rude, gesture, with a
gratuitious nod to Philo, to the conviction that the antecedens is not
fulfilled either. The emissor is further abiding by what Grice calls the
‘principle of truth,’ for the emissor would rather see himself dead than
uttering a falsehood, even if he has to fill the conversational space with
idiocies like ‘dutchman-being’ and ‘hat-eating.’ The fourth Griceian fact is
obviously Modus Tollendo Tollens, viz. that “(p ⊃ q) . ~q” entails
“~p,” or rather, to avoid the metalanguage (Grice’s Bootlace: Don’t use a
metalanguage: you can only implicate that your object-language is not
objectual.”), “[(p ⊃ q) . ~ q] ⊃ ~ p.”At this
point, Strawson reminisces: “I was slightly surprised that on my first tutorial
with Grice, he gave me “What the Tortoise Said To Achilles,” with the hint,
which I later took as a defeasible implicaturum, “See if you can resolve this!”
ACHILLEs had overtaken the Tortoise, and had seated himself comfortably on its
back. "So you've got to the end of our race-course?" said the
Tortoise. "Even though it does consist of an infinite series of distances
? I thought some wiseacre or other had proved that the thing couldnl't be doiie
? " " It can be done," said Achilles. " It has been done!
Solvitur ambulando. You see the distances were constaiitly diminishing; and
so-" "But if they had beenl constantly increasing?" the Tortoise
interrupted. "How then?" "Then I shouldn't be here," Achilles
modestly replied; "and you would have got several times round the world,
by this time! " "You flatter me-flatten, I mean," said the
Tortoise; "for you are a heavy weight, and no mistake! Well now, would you
like to hear of a race-course, that most people fancy they can get to the end
of in two or three steps, while it really consists of an infinite number of
distances, each one longer than the previous one? " "Very much indeed
!" said the Grecian warrior, as he drew from his helmet (few Grecian warriors
possessed pockets in those days) an enormous note-book and a pencil.
"Proceed! And speak slowly, please! Shorthand 't invented yet !"
"That beautiful First Proposition of Euclid! " the Tortoise miurmured
dreamily. "You admire Euclid?" "Passionately! So far, at least,
as one can admire a treatise that wo'n't be published for some centuries to
come ! " "Well, now, let's take a little bit of the argument in that
First Proposition-just two steps, and the conclusion drawn from them. Kindly
enter them in your note-book. And in order to refer to them conveniently, let's
call them A, B, and Z:- (A) Things that are equal to the same are equal to each
other. (B) The two sides of this Triangle are things that are equal to the
same. (Z) The two sides of this Triangle are equal to each other. Readers of
Euclid will grant, I suppose, that Z follows logically from A and B, so that
any one who accepts A and B as true, must accept Z as true?" "
Undoubtedly! The youngest child in a High School-as. soon as High Schools are
invented, which will not be till some two thousand years later-will grant
that." " And if some reader had not yet accepted A and B as true, he
might still accept the sequence as a valid one, I suppose?" NOTES. 279
"No doubt such a reader might exist. He might say 'I accept as true the
Hypothetical Proposition that, if A and B be true, Z must be true; but, I don't
accept A and B as true.' Such a reader would do wisely in abandoning Euclid,
and taking to football." " And might there not also be some reader who
would say ' I accept A anld B as true, but I don't accept the
Hypothetical'?" "Certainly there might. He, also, had better take to
football." "And neither of these readers," the Tortoise
continued, "is as yet under any logical necessity to accept Z as true?"
"Quite so," Achilles assented. "Well, now, I want you to
consider me as a reader of the second kind, and to force me, logically, to
accept Z as true." " A tortoise playing football would be--"
Achilles was beginning " -an anomaly, of course," the Tortoise
hastily interrupted. "Don't wander from the point. Let's have Z first, and
football afterwards !" " I'm to force you to accept Z, am I?"
Achilles said musingly. "And your present position is that you accept A
and B, but you don't accept the Hypothetical-" " Let's call it
C," said the Tortoise. "-but you don't accept (C) If A and B are
true, Z must be true." "That is my present position," said the
Tortoise. "Then I must ask you to accept C.""I'll do so,"
said the Tortoise, "as soon as you've entered it in that note-book of
yours. What else have you got in it?" " Only a few memoranda,"
said Achilles, nervously fluttering the leaves: "a few memoranda of-of the
battles in which I have distinguished myself!" "Plenty of blank
leaves, I see !" the Tortoise cheerily remarked. "We shall need them
all !" (Achilles shuddered.) "Now write as I dictate: (A) Things that
are equal to the same are equal to each other. (B) The two sides of this
Triangle are things that are equal to the same. (C) If A and B are true, Z must
be true. (Z) The two sides of this Triangle are equal to each other."
" You should call it D, not Z," said Achilles. " It comes next
to the other three. If you accept A and B and C, you must accept Z."
"And why must I?" "Because it follows logically from them. If A
and B and C are true, Z must be true. You don't dispute that, I imagine ?"
"If A and B and C are true, Z must be true," the Tortoise
thoughtfully repeated. " That's another Hypothetical, 't it? And, if I
failed to see its truth, I might accept A and B and C, and still not accept Z,
mightn't I?" "You might," the candid hero admitted; "though
such obtuseness would certainly be phenomenal. Still, the event is possible. So
I must ask you to grant one more Hypothetical." " Very good. I'm
quite willing to grant it, as soon as you've written it down. We will call it
(D) If A and B and C are true, Z must be true. Have you entered that in your
note-book ? " " I have! " Achilles joyfully exclaimed, as he ran
the pencil into its sheath. "And at last we've got to the end of this
ideal race-course! Now that you accept A and B and C and D, of course you
accept Z." " Do I ? " said the Tortoise innocently. " Let's
make that quite clear. I accept A and B and C and D. Suppose I still refused to
accept Z? " 280 NOTES. " Then Logic would take you by the throat, and
force you to do it !" Achilles triumphantly replied. "Logic would
tell you 'You ca'n't help yourself. Now that you've accepted A and B and C and
D, you mvust accept Z!' So you've no choice, you see." "Whatever
Logic is good enough to tell me is worth writing down," said the Tortoise.
" So enter it in your book, please. We will call it (E) If A and B and C
and Dare true, Zmust be true. Until I've granted that, of course I needn't
grant Z. So it's quite a necessary step, you see?" "I see," said
Achilles; and there was a touch of sadness in his tone. Here the narrator,
having pressing business at the Bank, was obliged to leave the happy pair, and
did not again pass the spot until some months afterwards. When he did so,
Achilles was still seated on the back of the much-enduring Tortoise, and was
writing in his note-book, which appeared to be nearly full. The Tortoise was
saying " Have you got that last step written down ? Unless I've lost
count, that makes a thousand and one. There are several millions more to come.
And would you mind, as a personal favour, considering what a lot of instruction
this colloquy of ours will provide for the Logicians of the Nineteenth
Century-would you mnind adopting a pun that my cousin the Mock-Turtle will then
make, and allowing yourself to be re-named Taught- Us ?" "As you
please !" replied the weary warrior, in the hollow tones of despair, as he
buried his face in his hands. " Provided that you, for your part, will
adopt a pun the Mock-Turtle never made, and allow yourself to be re-named A
Kill-Ease !"Strawon protests:“But this is a strange piece of logic.”Grice
corrects: “Pieceyou mean ‘piece’ simpliciter.”“But what do you protest that
much!?”“Well, it seems that, on any possible interpretation, “if p, q” has, in
respect of modus tollendo tollens the same powers as ‘p ⊃
q.’“And it is just these powers that
you, and Cook Wilson before you, are jokingly (or fantastically) exploiting!”“Fantastically?”
“You call Cook Wilson ‘fantastical’? You can call me exploitative.’Strawson: “It
is the absence of Kantian ‘Relation,’ Boethius’s ‘relatio,’ Aristotle’s ‘pros
ti,’ referred to in that makes both Stout’s hat-eating if and Gardiner’s
dutchman if quirks (as per Sir Randolph Quirk, another Manx, like Quine), a
verbal or conversational flourish, an otiosity, alla Albritton, an odd, call it
Philonian, use of ‘if.’ If a hypothetical statement IS, as Grice, after Philo,
claims, is what Whitehead and Russell have as a ‘material’ implication, the
statements would be not a quirkish oddity, but a linguistic sobriety and a
simple truth. Or rather they are each, the dutchman if and the hat-eating if, each a ‘quirkish
oddity’ BECAUSE each is a simple, sober, truth. “Recall my adage,” Grice
reminded Strawson, “Obscurely baffling, but Hegelianly true!”Strawson notes, as
a final commentary on the relevant section, that ‘if’ can be employed PERFORMATORILY, which will
have Grice finding his topic for the Kant lectures at Stanford: “must” is
univocal in “Apples must fall,” and “You must not lie.”An ‘if’ is used
‘performatorily’ when it is used not simply in making this or that statement,
but in, e.g., making a provisional announcement of an intention. Strawson’s
example:“If it rains, I shall stay at home.”Grice corrected:“*I* *will* stay at
home. *YOU* *shall.*”“His quadruple implicatura never ceased to amaze me.”Grice
will take this up later in ‘Ifs and cans.’“If I can, I intend to climb Mt
Everest on hands and knees, if I may disimplicate that to Davidson.”This hich,
like an unconditional announcement of intention, Strawson “would rather not”
call ‘truly true’ or ‘falsely false.’ “I would rather describe it in some other
wayGriceian perhaps.” “A quessertion, not to be iterated.”“If the man who utters
the quoted sentence leaves home in spite of the rain, we do not say that what
he said was false, though we might say that he lied (never really intended to
stay in) ; or that he changed his mindwhich, Strawson adds, “is a form of lying
to your former self.” “I agreed with you!” Grice screamed from the other side
of the Quadrangle!Strawson notes: “There are further uses of ‘if’ which I shall
not discuss.”This is a pantomime for Austin (Strawson’s letter to Grice,
“Austin wants me to go through the dictionary with ‘if.’ Can you believe it,
Grice, that the OED has NINE big pages on it?! And the sad thing is that Austin
has already did ‘if’ in “Ifs and cans.” Why is he always telling OTHERS what to
do?”Strawson’s Q. E. D.: “The safest way to read the material implication sign
is, perhaps, ‘not both … and not …,” and avoid the ‘doubt’ altogether. (NB:
“Mr. H. P. Grice, from whom I never ceased to learn about logic since he was my
tutor for my Logic paper in my PPE at St. John’s back in the day, illustrates
me that ‘if’ in Frisian means ‘doubt.’ And he adds, “Bread, butter, green
cheese; very good English, very good Friese!”. GROUP C“Performatory”
theoriesdescriptive, quasi-descriptive, prescriptiveexamples not
lettered.EXAMPLE I: Strawson on ‘true’ in Analysis.EXAMPLE II: Austin on ‘know’
EXAMPLE III: Hare on ‘good.’EXPLICITLY CONVEYED: if p, qIMPLICITLY CONVEYED: p
is the consequensCANCELLATION: “I know perfectly well where your wife is, but
all I’ll say is that if she is not in kitchen she is in the bedroom.”Next would
be to consider uses of ‘implication’ in the essay on the ‘indicative conditional.’
We should remember that the titling came out in 1987. The lecture circulated
without a title for twenty years. And in fact, it is about ‘indicative
conditional’ AND MORE BESIDES, including Cook Wilson, if that’s a plus. Grice
states the indirectness condition in two terms:One in the obviously false terms
“q is INFERRABLE, that’s the word Grice uses, from p”The other one is in terms
of truth-value assignment:The emissor has NON-TRUTH-FUNCTIONAL GROUNDS for the
emissum, ‘if p, q’. In Grice’s parlance: “Grounds for ACCEPTING “p ⊃
q.”This way Grice chooses is controversial in that usually he holds ‘accept’ as
followed by the ‘that’-clause. So ‘accepting ‘p ⊃ q’” is not clear
in that respect. A rephrase would be, accepting that the emissor is in a
position to emit, ‘if p, q’ provided that what he EXPLICITLY CONVEYS by that is
what is explicitly conveyed by the Philonian ‘if,’ in other words, that the
emissor is explicitly conveying that it is the case of p or it is not the case
of q, or that it is not the case that a situation obtains such that it is the
case that p and it is not the case that q.“p ⊃ q” is F only in
the third row. It is no wonder that Grice says that the use-mention was only
used correctly ONCE.For Grice freely uses ‘the proposition that p ⊃
q.’ But this may be licensed because it was meant as for ‘oral delivery.’ THE
FIRST INSTANTIATION GRICE GIVES (WoW:58) is“If Smith is in London, he, viz. Smith,
is attending the meeting.”Grice goes on (WoW:59) to give FIVE alternatives to
the ‘if’ utterance, NOT using ‘if.’ For the first four, he notes that he fells
the ‘implicaturum’ of ‘indirectness’ seems ‘persistent.’On WoW:59, Grice refers
to Strawson as a ‘strong theorist,’ and himself as a ‘weak theorist,’ i. e. an
Occamist. Grice gives a truth-table or the ‘appropriate truth table,’ and its
formulation, and notes that he can still detect the indirectness condition
implication. Grice challenges Strawson. How is one to learn that what one
conveys by the scenario formulated in the truth-table for the pair “Smith is in
London” and “Smith is attending the meeting”without using ‘if’ because this is
Grice’s exercise in detachmentis WEAKER than what one would convey by “If Smith
is in London, he, viz. Smith, is attending the meeting”?This sort of rhetorical
questions“Of course he can’t” are a bit insidious. Grice failed to give
Strawson a copy of the thing. And Strawson is then invited to collaborate with
P. G. R. I. C. E., so he submits a rather vague “If and ⊃,”
getting the rebuke by Grice’s friend Bennett“Strawson could at least say that
Grice’s views were published in three different loci.” BUT: Strawson compiled
that essay in 1968. And Strawson was NOT relying on a specific essay by Grice,
but on his memory of the general manoeuvre. Grice had been lecturing on ‘if’
before at Oxford, in seminars entitled “Logic and Convesation.” But surely at
Oxford you are not supposed to ‘air’ your seminar views. Outside Oxford it might
be different. It shoud not!And surely knowing Grice, why would *GRICE* provide
the input to Strawson. For Grice, philosophy is very personal, and while Grice
might have thought that Sir Peter was slightly interested in what his former
tutor would say about ‘if,’ it would be inappropriate of the tutor to overwhelm
the tutee, or keep informing the tutee how wrong he is. For a tutor, once a
tutee, always a tutee. On WoW:59, Grice provides the FIRST CANCELLATION of an
‘if,’ and changes it slightly from the one on p. 58. The ‘if’ now becomesIf
Smith is in the library, he, viz. Smith, is working.’In Wiltshire:“If Smith is
in the swimming-pool library, he, viz. Smith, is swimming.”THE CANCELLATION
GOES by ‘opting out’:“I know just where Smith is and what he, viz. Smith, is
doing, but all I will tell you is that if he is in the library he is
working.”Grice had to keep adding his ‘vizes’viz. Smithbecause of the insidious
contextualistssome of them philosophical!“What do you mean ‘he,’are you sure
you are keeping the denotatum constant?”Grice is challenging Strawson’s
‘uncertainty and disbelief.’No one would be surprised if Grice’s basis for his
saying “I know just where Smith is and what he, viz. Smith, is doing, but all I
will tell you is that if he is in the library, he is working” is that Grice has
just looked in the library and found Smith working. So, Grice IS uttering “If
Smith is in the library, he is working” WHEN THE INDIRECT (strong) condition
ceteris-paribus carried by what Grice ceteris paribus IMPLIES by uttering “If
Smith is in the library, Smith is working.”The situation is a bit of the blue,
because Grice presents it on purpose as UNVOLUNTEERED. The ‘communication-function’
does the trick. GRICE THEN GIVES (between pages WoW: 59 and 60) TWO IMPLICIT
cancellations of an implicaturum, or, to avoid the alliteration, ‘contextual’
cancellation. Note incidentally that Grice is aware of the explicit/implicit
when he calls the cancellation, first, EXPLICIT, and then contextual. By
‘explicit,’ he means, ‘conveying explicitly’ in a way that commits you. THE THIRD
INSTANTIATION refers to this in what he calls a ‘logical’ puzzle, which may be
a bit question-begging, cf. ‘appropriate truth-table.’ For Strawson would say
that Grice is using ‘if’ as a conscript, when it’s a civil. “If Smith has
black, Mrs. Smith has black.”Grice refers to ‘truth-table definition’ OR
STIPULATION. Note that the horseshoe is an inverted “C” for ‘contentum.’F.
Cajori, “A history of mathematical notations,” SYMBOLS IN MATHEMATICAL LOGIC,
§667-on : [§674] “A theory of the ‘meccanisme du raisonnement’ is offered by J.
D. Gergonne in his “Essai de dialectique rationnelle.”In Gergonne’s “Essai,”
“H” stands for complete logical disjunction, X” for logical product, “I” for
"identity," [cf. Grize on izzing] “C” for "contains," and
"Ɔ (inverted C)" for "is contained in." [§685] Gergonne is using the Latinate,
contineoIn rhet., the neuter substantive “contĭnens” is rendered as “that
on which something rests or depends, the chief point, hinge: “causae,” Cic. Part. Or. 29, 103; id. Top. 25, 95: “intuendum videtur, quid sit quaestio, ratio, judicatio, continens, vel ut alii vocant, firmamentum,” Quint. 3, 11, 1; cf. id. ib. § 18 sqq.—Adv.: contĭnen-ter . So it is a natural evolution in
matters of implication. while Giusberti (“Materiale per studio,” 31) always
reads “pro constanti,” the MSS occasionally has the pretty Griciean
“precontenti,” from “prae” and “contenti.” Cf. Quine, “If my father was a
bachelor, he was male. And I can say that, because ‘male’ is CONTAINED in
‘bachelor.’”E. Schröder, in his “Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik,”
[§690] Leipzig, uses “⊂”
for "untergeordnet”, roughly, “is included in,” and the inverted “⊃”
for the passive voice, "übergeordnet,” or includes. Some additional symbols are introduced by
Peano into Number 2 of Volume II of his influential “Formulaire.” Thus "ɔ"
becomes ⊃. By “p.⊃ x ... z. q” is
expressed “from p one DEDUCES, whatever x ... z may be, and q." In “Il calcolo geometrico,”“according to the
Ausdehnungslehre of H. Grassmann, preceded by the operations of deductive
logic,” Peano stresses the duality of interpretations of “p.⊃
x ... z. q” in terms of classes and propositions. “We shall indicate [the
universal affirmative proposition] by the expression A < B, or B > A, which can be read "every A is a B,"
or "the class B CONTAINS A." [...]
Hence, if a,b,... are CONDITIONAL propositions, we have: a < b, or b > a, ‘says’ that "the
class defined by the condition a is part of that defined by b," or [...]
"b is a CONSEQUENCE of a," "if a is true, b is true." In Peano’s “Arithmetices principia: nova
methodo exposita,” we have: “II.
Propositions.” “The sign “C” means is a consequence of [“est consequentia.” Thus
b C a is read b is a consequence of the proposition a.” “The sign “Ɔ” means one
deduces [DEDUCITUR]; thus “a Ɔ b” ‘means’ the same as b C a. [...] IV. Classes “The sign Ɔ ‘means’ is contained
in. Thus a Ɔ b means class a is contained in class b. a, b ∈ K Ɔ (a Ɔ b) :=: (x)(x
∈ a Ɔ x ∈ b). In his “Formulaire,” Peano writes: “Soient a et b des Cls. a ⊃
b signifie "tout a est b".
Soient p et q des propositions contenant une variable x; p ⊃x
q, signifie "de p on déduit, quel que soit x, la q", c'est-à-dire:
"les x qui satisfont à la condition p satisferont aussi à la q". Russell criticizes Peano’s dualism in “The
Principles of mathematics,” §13. “The subject of Symbolic Logic consists of
three parts, the calculus of propositions, the calculus of classes and the
calculus of relations. Between the first two, there is, within limits, a
certain parallelism, which arises as follows: In any symbolic expression, the
letters may be interpreted as classes or as propositions, and the relation of
inclusion in the one case may be replaced by that of formal implication in the
other. A great deal has been made of
this duality, and in the later editions of his “Formulaire,” Peano appears to
have sacrificed logical precision to its preservation. But, as a matter of
fact, there are many ways in which the calculus of propositions differs from
that of classes.” Whiehead and Russell borrow the basic logical symbolism from
Peano, but they freed it from the "dual" interpretation. Thus, Whitehead and Russell adopt Schröder's ⊂
for class inclusion: a ⊂
b :=: (x)(x ∈ a Ɔ x ∈ b) Df. and restricted the use of the
"horseshoe" ⊃ to the connective "if’: “p⊃q.’
Whitehead’s and Russell’s decision isobvious, if we consider the following
example from Cesare Burali-Forti, “Logica Matematica,” a Ɔ b . b Ɔ c : Ɔ : a Ɔ
c [...] The first, second and fourth
[occurrences] of the sign Ɔ mean is contained, the third one means one deduces.So
the horseshoe is actually an inverted “C” meant to read “contentum” or
“consequens” (“consequutum”). Active Nominal Forms Infinitive: implicā́re
Present participle: implicāns; implicántis Future participle: implicītúrus;
implicātúrus Gerund: implicándum Gerundive: implicándus Passive Nominal Forms Infinitive: implicā́re
Perfect participle: implicī́tum; implicā́tumGRICE’s second implicit or
contextual cancellation does not involve a ‘logical puzzle’ but bridgeand it’s
his fourth instantiation:“If I have a red king, I also have a black king.”to
announce to your competititve opponents upon inquiry a bid of five no trumps. Cf.
Alice, “The red Queen” which is a chess queen, as opposed to the white queen. After
a precis, he gives a FIFTH instantiation to prove that ‘if’ is always EXPLICITLY
cancellable.WoW:60“If you put that bit of sugar in water, it will dissolve,
though so far as I know there can be no way of knowing in advance that this
will happen.”This is complex. The cancellation turns the ‘if p, q’ into a
‘guess,’ in which case it is odd that the emissor would be guessing and yet be
being so fortunate as to make such a good guess. At the end of page 60, Grice
gives THREE FURTHER instantations which are both of philosophical importance
and a pose a problem to such a strong theorist as Strawson.The first of the
trio is:“If the Australians win the first Test, they will win the series, you
mark my words.”The second of the trio is:“Perhaps if he comes, he will be in a
good mood.”The third in the trio is:“See that, if he comes, he gets his money.”Grice’s
point is that in the three, the implicaturum is cancelled. So the strong
theorist has to modify the thesis ‘a sub-primary case of a sub-primary use of
‘if’ is…” which seems like a heavy penalty for the strong theorist. For Grice,
the strong theorist is attaching the implicaturum to the ‘meaning’ of ‘if,’
where, if attached at all, should attach to some mode-marker, such as
‘probably,’ which may be contextual. On p. 61 he is finding play and using
‘logically weaker’ for the first time, i. e. in terms of entailment. If it is
logically weaker, it is less informative. “To deny that p, or to assert that
q.”Grice notes it’s ceteris paribus.“Provided it would be worth contributing
with the ‘more informative’ move (“why deny p? Why assert q?) While the
presumption that one is interested in the truth-values of at least p or q, this
is ceteris paribus. A philosopher may just be interested in “if p, q” for the
sake of exploring the range of the relation between p and q, or the powers of p
and q. On p. 62 he uses the phrase “non-truth functional” as applied not to grounds
but to ‘evidence’: “non-truth-functional evidence.”Grice wants to say that
emissor has implicated, in a cancellable way, that he has non-truth-functional
evidence for “if p, q,” i. e. evidence that proceeds by his inability to utter
“if p, q” on truth-functional grounds. The emissor is signaling that he is
uttering “if p, q” because he cannot deny p, or that he cannot assert q(p ⊃
q) ≡ ((~p) v q)Back to the first
instantiation“If Smith is in London, he, viz. Smith is attending the meeting
there, viz. in London”I IMPLICATE, in a cancellable way, that I have no
evidence for “Smith is not in London”I IMPLICATE, in a cancellable way, that I
have no evidence for “Smith is attending the lecture.On p. 61 he gives an
example of an contextual cancellation to show that even if the implicaturum is
a generalised one, it need not be present in every PARTICULAR case (hence the
weakned form ‘generalISED, not general). “If he was surprised, he didn’t show
it.”Or cf. AustinIf you are hungry, there are biscuits in the cupboard. Traditionalist
Grice on the tranquil Elysium of philosophyĒlysĭum , ii, n., = Ἠλύσιον, the
abode of the blest, I.Elysium, Verg. A. 5, 735 Serv.; 6, 542; 744 al.; cf.
Heyne Verg. A. 6, 675 sq.; and ejusd. libri Exc. VIII. p. 1019 Wagn.—Hence, II.
Ēlysĭus , a, um, adj., Elysian: “campi,” Verg. G. 1, 38; Tib. 1, 3, 58; Ov. Ib.
175; cf. “ager,” Mart. 10, 101: “plagae,” id. 6, 58: “domus,” Ov. M. 14, 111;
cf. “sedes,” Luc. 3, 12: “Chaos,” Stat. Th. 4, 520: “rosae,” Prop. 4 (5), 7,
60. “puella,” i. e. Proserpine, Mart. 10, 24.—On p. 63, Grice uses ‘sense’ for
the first time to apply to a Philonian ‘if p, q.’He is exploring that what
Strawson would have as a ‘natural’ if, not an artificial ‘if’ like Philo’s, may
have a sense that descends from the sense of the Philonian ‘if,’ as in Darwin’s
descent of man. Grice then explores the ‘then’ in some formulations, ‘if p,
then q’, and notes that Philo never used it, “ei” simpliciteror the Romans,
“si.”Grice plays with the otiosity of “if p, in that case q.”And then there’s
one that Grice dismisses as ultra-otiose:“if p, then, in that case, viz. p.,
q.”Grice then explores ‘truth-functional’ now applied not to ‘evidence’ but to
‘confirmation.’“p or q” is said to be truth-functionally confirmable.While “p
horseshoe q’ is of course truth-functionally confirmable.Grice has doubts that
‘if p, q’ may be regarded by Strawson as NOT being ‘truth-functionally
confirmable.’ If would involve what he previously called a ‘metaphysical
excrescence.’Grice then reverts to his bridge example“If I have a red king, I
have a black king.”And provides three scenarios for a post-mortem
truth-functional confirmability.For each of the three rowsNo red, no blackRed,
no blackRed, blackWhich goes ditto for
the ‘logical’ puzzleIf Jones has black, Mrs. Jones has black. The next
crop of instantiations come from PM, and begins on p. 64.He kept revising these
notes. And by the time he was submitting the essay to the publisher, he gives
up and kept the last (but not least, never latter) version. Grice uses the
second-floor ‘disagree,’ and not an explicit ‘not.’ So is partially agreeing a
form of disagreeing? In 1970, Conservative Heath won to Labour Wilson.He uses
‘validate’for ‘confirm’. ‘p v q’ is validated iff proved factually satisfactory.On
p. 66 he expands“if p, q”as a triple disjunction of the three rows when ‘if p,
q’ is true:“(not-p and not-q) or (not-p and q) or (p and q)”The only left out
is “(p and not-q).”Grice gives an instantiation for [p et]q“The innings closed
at 3:15, Smith no batting.”as opposed to“The inning close at 3:15, and Smith
did not bat.”as displayed byp.qAfter using ‘or’ for elections he gives the
first instantation with ‘if’:“If Wilson will not be prime minister, it will be
Heath.”“If Wilson loses, he loses to Heath.”‘if’ is noncommutativethe only
noncommutative of the three dyadic truth-functors he considers (‘and,’ ‘or’ and
‘if’).This means that there is a ‘semantic’ emphasis here.There is a
distinction between ‘p’ and ‘q’. In the case of ‘and’ and ‘or’ there is not, since
‘p and q’ iff ‘q and p’ and ‘p or q’ iff ‘q or p.’The distinction is expressed
in terms of truth-sufficiency and false-sufficiency.The antecedent or protasis,
‘p’ is FALSE-SUFFICIENT for the TRUTH of ‘if p, q.’The apodosis is
TRUE-sufficient for the truth of ‘if p, q.’On p. 67 he raises three questions.FIRST
QUESTIONHe is trying to see ‘if’ as simpler:The three instantiations areIf
Smith rings, the butler will let Smith inIt is not the case that Smith rings,
or the butler will let Smith in.It is not the case both Smith rings and it is
not the the butler will let Smith in. (Grice changes the tense, since the
apodosis sometimes requires the future tense) (“Either Smith WILL RING…”)SECOND
QUESTIONWhy did the Anglo-Saxons feel the need for ‘if’German ‘ob’? After all,
if Whitehead and Russell are right, the Anglo-Saxons could have done with ‘not’
and ‘and,’ or indeed with ‘incompatible.’The reason is that ‘if’ is cognate
with ‘doubt,’ but The Anglo-Saxons left the doubt across the North Sea. it originally from an oblique case of the
substantive which may be rendered as "doubt,” and cognate with archaic
German “iba,”
which may be rendered as “condition, stipulation, doubt," Old Norse if "doubt,
hesitation," modern Swedish jäf "exception,
challenge")It’s all different with ‘ei’ and ‘si.’For sisī (orig. and ante-class. form seī ),I.conj. [from
a pronominal stem = Gr. ἑ; Sanscr. sva-, self; cf. Corss. Ausspr. 1,
778; Georg Curtius
Gr. Etym. 396], a conditional particle, if.As
for “ei”εἰ , Att.-Ion. and Arc. (for εἰκ, v. infr. 11 ad init.), = Dor. and
Aeol. αἰ, αἰκ (q. v.), Cypr.A.“ἤ” Inscr.Cypr.135.10 H., both εἰ and αἰ in Ep.:— Particle used interjectionally
with imper. and to express a wish, but usu. either in conditions, if, or in indirect questions, whether. In the former use its
regular negative is μή; in the latter, οὐ.THIRD QUESTION. Forgetting Grecian neutral
apodosis and protasis, why did the Romans think that while ‘antecedens’ is a
good Humeian rendition of ‘protasis,’ yet instead they chose for the Grecian
Humeian ‘apodosis,’ the not necessarily Humeian ‘con-sequens,’ rather than mere
‘post-sequens’?The Latin terminology is antecedens and consequens, the
ancestors and ... tothem the way the Greek grammatical termsή πρότασιs and
ήαπόδοσιsBRADWARDINE: Note that a consequence is an argumentation made up of an
antecedent and a consequent. He starts with the métiers.For ‘or’ he speaks of
‘semiotic economy’ (p. 69). Grice’s Unitarianismunitary particle.If,
like iff, is subordinating, but only if is non-commutative. Gazdar considers
how many dyadic particles are possible and why such a small bunch is chosen.
Grice did not even care, as Strawson did, to take care of ‘if and only if.’ Grice
tells us the history behind the ‘nursery rhyme’ about Cock Robin. He learned it
from his mother, Mabel Fenton, at Harborne. Clifton almost made it forget it!
But he recovered in the New World, after reading from Colin Sharp that many of
those nursery rhymes travelled “with the Mayflower.” "Who Killed Cock
Robin" is an English nursery rhyme, which has been much used as a murder
archetype[citation needed] in world culture. It has a Roud Folk Song Index number
of 494. Contents 1Lyrics 2Origin and
meaning 3Notes 4 External links Lyrics[edit] The earliest record of the rhyme
is in Tommy Thumb's Pretty Song Book, published c. 1744, which noted only the
first four verses. The extended version given below was not printed until c.
1770. Who killed Cock Robin? I, said the
Sparrow, with my bow and arrow, I killed Cock Robin. Who saw him die? I, said
the Fly, with my little eye, I saw him die. Who caught his blood? I, said the
Fish, with my little dish, I caught his blood. Who'll make the shroud? I, said
the Beetle, with my thread and needle, I'll make the shroud. Who'll dig his
grave? I, said the Owl, with my little trowel, I'll dig his grave. Who'll be
the parson? I, said the Rook, with my little book, I'll be the parson. Who'll
be the clerk? I, said the Lark, if it's not in the dark, I'll be the clerk.
Who'll carry the link? I, said the Linnet, I'll fetch it in a minute, I'll
carry the link. Who'll be chief mourner? I, said the Dove, I mourn for my love,
I'll be chief mourner. Who'll carry the coffin? I, said the Kite, if it's not
through the night, I'll carry the coffin. Who'll bear the pall? We, said the
Wren, both the cock and the hen, We'll bear the pall. Who'll sing a psalm? I,
said the Thrush, as she sat on a bush, I'll sing a psalm. Who'll toll the bell?
I, said the Bull, because I can pull, I'll toll the bell. All the birds of the
air fell a-sighing and a-sobbing, when they heard the bell toll for poor Cock
Robin. The rhyme has often been reprinted with illustrations, as suitable
reading material for small children.[citation needed] The rhyme also has an
alternative ending, in which the sparrow who killed Cock Robin is hanged for
his crime. Several early versions picture a stocky, strong-billed bullfinch
tolling the bell, which may have been the original intention of the rhyme. Origin and meaning[edit] Although the song
was not recorded until the mid-eighteenth century, there is some evidence that
it is much older. The death of a robin by an arrow is depicted in a
15th-century stained glass window at Buckland Rectory, Gloucestershire, and the
rhyme is similar to a story, Phyllyp Sparowe, written by John Skelton about
1508. The use of the rhyme 'owl' with 'shovel', could suggest that it was
originally used in older middle English pronunciation. Versions of the story appear
to exist in other countries, including Germany.
A number of the stories have been advanced to explain the meaning of the
rhyme: The rhyme records a mythological
event, such as the death of the god Balder from Norse mythology, or the ritual
sacrifice of a king figure, as proposed by early folklorists as in the 'Cutty
Wren' theory of a 'pagan survival'. It is a parody of the death of King William
II, who was killed by an arrow while hunting in the New Forest (Hampshire) in
1100, and who was known as William Rufus, meaning "red". The rhyme is
connected with the fall of Robert Walpole's government in 1742, since Robin is
a diminutive form of Robert and the first printing is close to the time of the
events mentioned. All of these theories are based on perceived similarities in
the text to legendary or historical events, or on the similarities of names.
Peter Opie pointed out that an existing rhyme could have been adapted to fit
the circumstances of political events in the eighteenth century. The theme of Cock Robin's death as well as
the poem's distinctive cadence have become archetypes, much used in literary
fiction and other works of art, from poems, to murder mysteries, to
cartoons. Notes[edit] Jump up to:a b c d e f g h I. Opie and P.
Opie, The Oxford Dictionary of Nursery Rhymes (Oxford University Press, 1951,
2nd edn., 1997), 130–3. * Cock Robin at Project Gutenberg M. C. Maloney, ed., English illustrated books
for children: a descriptive companion to a selection from the Osborne
Collection (Bodley Head, 1981)31.
Lockwood, W. B. "The Marriage of the Robin and the Wren."
Folklore 100.2 (1989): 237–239. The
gentry house that became the old rectory at Buckland has an impressive timbered
hall that dates from the fifteenth century with two lights of contemporary
stained glass in the west wall with the rebus of William Grafton and arms of
Gloucester Abbey in one and the rising sun of Edward IV in the other light;
birds in various attitudes hold scrolls "In Nomine Jesu"; none is
reported transfixed by an arrow in Anthony Emery, Greater Medieval Houses of
England and Wales, 1300–1500: Southern England, s.v. "Buckland Old
Rectory, Gloucestershire", (Cambridge University Press, 2006)80. R. J. Stewart, Where is St. George? Pagan
Imagery in English Folksong (1976). B.
Forbes, Make Merry in Step and Song: A Seasonal Treasury of Music, Mummer's
Plays & Celebrations in the English Folk Tradition (Llewellyn Worldwide,
2009)5. J. Harrowven, The origins of
rhymes, songs and sayings (Kaye & Ward, 1977)92. External links[edit] Children's
literature portal Death and Burial of Poor Cock Robin, by H. L. Stephens, from
Project Gutenberg Death and Burial of Poor Cock Robin From the Collections at
the Library of Congress Categories: Robert Walpole1744 songsFictional passerine
birdsEnglish nursery rhymesSongwriter unknownEnglish folk songsEnglish
children's songsTraditional children's songsSongs about birdsSongs about
deathMurder balladsThe train from Oakland to Berkeley.Grice's aunt once visited
him, and he picked her up at the Oakland Railway Station. On p. 74, Grice
in terms of his aunt, mentions for the first time ‘premise’ and ‘conclusion.’On
same p. for the record he uses ‘quality’ for affirmative, negative or infinite.
On p. 74 he uses for the first time, with a point, the expression ‘conditional’
as attached to ‘if.’Oddly on the first line of p. 75, he uses ‘material
conditional,’ which almost nobody doesexcept for a blue-collared practitioner
of the sciences. ‘Material’ was first introduced by blue-collared Whitehead and
Russell, practictioners of the sciences. They used ‘material’ as applied to
‘implication,’ to distinguish it, oddly, and unclassily, from ‘formal’
implication. It is only then he quotes Wilson verbatim in quotes“The question
whether so and so is a case of a question whether such and such” This actually
influenced Collingwood, and Grice is trying to tutor Strawson here once more!For the logic of question and answer has roots in the
very philosophy that it was ... is John Cook Wilson, whose Statement and Inference can
be regarded as the STATEMENT AND ITS RELATION TO THINKING AND APREHENSIOTHE
DISTINCTION OF SUBJECT AND PREDICATE IN LOGIC AND GRAMMAR The influence of
Strawson on Cook Wilson.“The building is the Bodleian.”As answer to“What is
that building?”“Which building is the Bodleian”If the proposition is answer to
first question, ‘that building’ is the subject, if the proposition is answer to
second question, ‘the bodleian’ is the subject. Cf. “The exhibition was not
visited by a bald kingof France, as it doesn’t happen.SUBJECT AS TOPICPREDICATE
AS COMMENT.Cf. Grice, “The dog is a shaggy thig”What is shaggy?What is the
dog?THIS DOGSubjectTopicTHAT SHAGGY THINGSubjectoccasionally, but usually
Predicate, Comment.In fact, Wilson bases on StoutI am hungryWho is hungry?:
subject IIs there anything amiss with you? ‘hungry’ is the subjectAre you
really hungry? ‘am’ is the subject.Grice used to be a neo-Stoutian before he
turned a neo-Prichardian so he knew. But perhaps Grice thought better of Cook
Wilson. More of a philosopher. Stout seemed to have been seen as a
blue-collared practioner of the SCIENCE of psychology, not philosophical
psychology! Cf. Leicester-born B. Mayo, e: Magdalen, Lit. Hum. (Philosophy)
under? on ‘if’ and Cook Wilson in Analysis.Other example by Wilson:“Glass is
elastic.”Grice is motivated to defend Cook Wilson because Chomsky was
criticizing him (via a student who had been at Oxford). [S]uppose
instruction was being given in the properties of glass, and the instructor said
‘glass is elastic’, it would be natural to say that what was being talkedabout
and thought about was ‘glass’, and that what was said of it was that it was
elastic. Thus glass would be the subject and that it is elastic would be the
predicate. (Cook Wilson 1926/1969,
1:117f.) What Cook Wilson discusses here is a categorical sentence. The
next two quotes are concerned with an identificational sentence. [I]n the
statement ‘glass is elastic’, if the matter of inquiry was elasticity and the
question was what substances possessed the property of elasticity, glass, in
accordance with the principle of the definition, would no longer be subject,
and the kind of stress which fell upon ‘elastic’ when glass was the subject,
would now be transferred to ‘glass’. [. . .] Thus the same form of words should
be analyzed differently according as the words are the answer to one question
or another. (Cook Wilson 1926/1969,
1:119f.) When the stress falls upon ‘glass’, in ‘glass is elastic’,
there is no word in the sentence which denotes the actual subject elasticity;
the word ‘elastic’ refers to what is already known of the subject, and glass,
which has the stress, is the only word which refers to the supposed new fact in
the nature of elasticity, that it is found in glass. Thus, according to the
proposed formula, ‘glass’ would have to be the predicate. [. . .] Introduction
and overview But the ordinary analysis would never admit that ‘glass’ was the
predicate in the given sentence and elasticity the subject. (Cook Wilson 1926/1969, 1:121)H. P. Grice knew that P. F. Strawson
knew of J. C. Wilson on “That building
is the Bodleian” via Sellars’s criticism.There is a strong
suggestion in Sellars' paper that I would have done
better if I had stuck to Cook Wilson. This suggestion I want equally strongly
to repudiate. Certainly Cook Wilson draws
attention to an interesting difference in ways in which items
may appear in discourse. It may be roughly expressed as follows.
When we say Glass is elastic we may be talking about glass or we
may be talking about elasticity (and we may, in the relevant sense of
'about' be doing neither). We are talking about glass if we are citing
elasticity as one of the properties of glass, we
are talking about elasticity if we are citing
glass as one of the substances which are elastic. Similarly
when we say Socrates is wise, we may be citing Socrates as an
instance of wisdom or wisdom as one of the proper- ties of
Socrates. And of course we may be doing neither but,
e.g., just imparting miscellaneous information. Now
how, if at all, could this difference help me with my
question? Would it help at all, for example, if it were plausible
(which it is not) to say that we were inevitably more interested in determining
what properties a given particular had,than in determining what
particular had a given property? Wouldn't this at least suggest that
particulars were the natural subjects, in the sense of subjects of
&erest? Let me answer this question by the
reminder that what I have to do is to establish a
connexion between some formal linguistic difference and
a category difference; and a formal
linguistic difference is one which logic can take cognizance of, in
abstraction from pragmatic considerations, like the direction
of interest. Such a formal ditference exists in the
difference between appearing in discourse directly designated and
appearing in discourse under the cloak of
quantification. ““But the difference in the use of
unquantified statements to which Cook Wilson draws attention is not a
formal difference at all.”Both glass and elasticity, Socrates and wisdom
appear named in such statements, whichever, in Cook
Wilson's sense, we are talking about. An appeal
to pragmatic considerations is, certainly, an essential
part of my own account at a certain point:
but this is the point at which such considerations are in- voked to
explain why a certain formal difference should be particularly
closely linked, in common speech, with a certain category difference. The
difference of which Cook Wilson speaks is, then, though
interesting in itself, irrelevant to my question. Cook Wilson is, and I am not,
concerned with what Sellars calls dialectical
distinctions.” On p.76 Grice mentions for the
first time the “ROLE” of if in an indefinite series of ‘interrogative
subordination.”For Cook Wilson,as Price knew (he quotes him in Belief),
the function of ‘if’ is to LINK TWO QUESTIONS. You’re the cream in my coffee as
‘absurd’ if literally (p. 83). STATEMENT In
this entry we will explore how Grice sees the ‘implicaturum’ that he regards as
‘conversational’ as applied to the emissor and in reference to the Graeco-Roman
classical tradition. Wht is implicated may not be the result of any maxim, and
yet not conventionaldepending on a feature of context. But nothing like a
maximStrawson Wiggins p. 523. Only a CONVERSATIONAL IMPLICATURUM is the result
of a CONVERSATIONAL MAXIM and the principle of conversational helpfulness. In a
‘one-off’ predicament, there may be an ‘implicaturum’ that springs from the
interaction itself. If E draws a skull, he communicates that there is danger.
If addressee runs away, this is not part of the implicaturum. This Grice
considers in “Meaning.” “What is meant” should cover the immediate effect, and
not any effect that transpires out of the addressee’s own will. Cf. Patton on
Kripke. One thief to another: “The cops are coming!” The expressiom
“IMPLICATION” is figures, qua entry, in a philosophical dictionary that Grice
consulted at Oxford. In the vernacular, there are two prominent relata:
entailment and implicaturum, the FRENCH have their “implication.” When it comes
to the Germans, it’s more of a trick. There’s the “nachsichziehen,” the
“zurfolgehaben,” the “Folge(-rung),” the “Schluß,” the “Konsequenz,” and of
course the “Implikation” and the “Implikatur,” inter alia. In Grecian, which Grice learned at Clifton, we
have the “sumpeplegmenon,” or “συμπεπλεγμένον,” if you must, i. e. the
“sum-peplegmenon,” but there’s also the “sumperasma,” or “συμπέϱασμα,” if you
must, “sum-perasma;” and then there’s the “sunêmmenon,” or “συνημμένον,” “sun-emmenon,”
not to mention (then why does Grice?) the “akolouthia,” or “ἀϰολουθία,” if you
must, “akolouthia,” and the “antakolouthia,” ἀνταϰολουθία,” “ana-kolouthia.”
Trust clever Cicero to regard anything ‘Grecian’ as not displaying enough
gravitas, and thus rendering everything into Roman. There’s the “illatio,” from
‘in-fero.’ The Romans adopted two different roots for this, and saw them as
having the same ‘sense’cf. referro, relatum, proferro, prolatum; and then
there’s the “inferentia,”– in-fero; and then there’s the “consequentia,” --
con-sequentia. The seq- root is present in ‘sequitur,’ non sequitur. The ‘con-‘
is transliterating Greek ‘syn-’ in the three expressions with ‘syn’:
sympleplegmenon, symperasma, and synemmenon. The Germans, avoiding the
Latinate, have a ‘follow’ root: in “Folge,” “Folgerung,” and the verb
“zur-folge-haben. And perhaps ‘implicatio,’
which is the root Grice is playing with. In Italian and French it
underwent changes, making ‘to imply’ a doublet with Grice’s ‘to implicate’ (the
form already present, “She was implicated in the crime.”). The strict opposite
is ‘ex-plicatio,’ as in ‘explicate.’ ‘implico’ gives both ‘implicaturum’ and
‘implicitum.’ Consequently, ‘explico’ gives both ‘explicatum’ and ‘explicitum.’
In English Grice often uses ‘impicit,’ and ‘explicit,’ as they relate to communication,
as his ‘implicaturum’ does. His ‘implicaturum’ has more to do with the contrast
with what is ‘explicit’ than with ‘what follows’ from a premise. Although in
his formulation, both readings are valid: “by uttering x, implicitly conveying
that q, the emissor CONVERSATIONALY implicates that p’ if he has explicitly
conveyed that p, and ‘q’ is what is required to ‘rationalise’ his
conversational behavioiur. In terms of the emissor, the distinction is between
what the emissor has explicitly conveyed and what he has conversationally
implicated. This in turn contrasts what some philosophers refer metabolically
as an ‘expression,’ the ‘x’ ‘implying’ that pGrice does not bother with this
because, as Strawson and Wiggins point out, while an emissor cannot be true,
it’s only what he has either explicitly or implicitly conveyed that can be
true. As Austin says, it’s always a FIELD where you do the linguistic botany.
So, you’ll have to vide and explore: ANALOGY, PROPOSITION, SENSE, SUPPOSITION,
and TRUTH. Implication denotes a relation between propositions and statements
such that, from the truth-value of the protasis or antecedent (true or false),
one can derive the truth of the apodosis or consequent. More broadly, we can
say that one idea ‘implies’ another if the first idea cannot be thought without
the second one -- RT: Lalande, Vocabulaire technique et critique de la
philosophie. Common usage makes no strict differentiation between “to imply,”
“to infer,” and “to lead to.” Against Dorothy Parker. She noted that those of
her friends who used ‘imply’ for ‘infer’ were not invited at the Algonquin. The
verb “to infer,” (from Latin, ‘infero,’ that gives both ‘inferentia,’
inference, and ‘illatio,’ ‘illatum’) meaning “to draw a consequence, to deduce”
(a use dating to 1372), and the noun “inference,” meaning “consequence” (from
1606), do not on the face of it seem to be manifestly different from “to imply”
and “implication.” But in Oxonian usage, Dodgson avoided a confusion. “There
are two ways of confusing ‘imply’ with ‘infer’: to use ‘imply’ to mean ‘infer,’
and vice versa. Alice usually does the latter; the Dodo the former.” Indeed,
nothing originally distinguishes “implication” as Lalande defines it — “a
relation by which one thing ‘implies’ another”— from “inference” as it is
defined in Diderot and d’Alembert’s Encyclopédie (1765): “An operation by which
one ACCEPTS (to use a Griceism) a proposition because of its connection to
other propositions held to be true.” The same phenomenon can be seen in the
German language, in which the terms corresponding to “implication,” “Nach-sich-ziehen,”
“Zur-folge-haben,” “inference,” “Schluß”-“Folgerung,” “Schluß,” “to infer,”
“schließen,” “consequence,” “Folge” “-rung,” “Schluß,” “Konsequenz,”
“reasoning,” “”Schluß-“ “Folgerung,” and “to reason,” “schließen,” “Schluß-folger-ung-en
ziehen,” intersect or overlap to a large extent. In the French language, the
expression “impliquer” reveals several characteristics that the expression does
not seem to share with “to infer” or “to lead to.” First of all, “impliquer” is
originally (1663) connected to the notion of contradiction, as shown in the use
of impliquer in “impliquer contradiction,” in the sense of “to be
contradictory.” The connection between ‘impliquer’ and ‘contradiction’ does
not, however, explain how “impliquer” has passed into its most commonly
accepted meaning — “implicitly entail” — viz. to lead to a consequence. Indeed,
the two usages (“impliquer” connected with contradiction” and otherwise)
constantly interfere with one another, which certainly poses a number of
difficult problems. An analogous phenomenon can be found in the case of
“import,” commonly given used as “MEAN” or “imply,” but often wavering instead,
in certain cases, between “ENTAIL” and “imply.” In French, the noun “import” itself
is generally left as it I (“import existentiel,” v. SENSE, Box 4, and cf.
that’s unimportant, meaningless). “Importer,”
as used by Rabelais, 1536, “to necessitate, to entail,” forms via It.“importare,” as used by Dante), from the Fr.
“emporter,” “to entail, to have as a consequence,” dropped out of usage, and
was brought back through Engl. “import.” The nature of the connection between
the two primary usages of L. ‘implicare,’ It. ‘implicare,’ and Fr. ‘impliquer,’
“to entail IMPLICITitly” and “to lead to a consequence,” nonetheless remains obscure,
but not to a Griceian, or Grecian. Another difficulty is understanding how the
transition occurs from Fr. “impliquer,” “to lead to a consequence,” to
“implication,” “a logical relation in which one statement necessarily supposes
another one,” and how we can determine what in this precise case distinguishes
“implication” from “PRAE-suppositio.” We therefore need to be attentive to what
is implicit in Fr. “impliquer” and “implication,” to the dimension of Fr.
“pli,” a pleat or fold, of Fr. “re-pli,” folding back, and of the Fr. “pliure,”
folding, in order to separate out “imply,” “infer,” “lead to,” or
“implication,” “inference,” “consequence”—which requires us to go back to
Latin, and especially to medieval Latin. Once we clarify the relationship
between the usage of “implication” and the medieval usage of “implicatio,” we
will be able to examine certain derivations (as in Sidonius’s ‘implicatura,”
and H. P. Grice’s “implicaturum,” after ‘temperature,’ from ‘temperare,’) or
substitutes (“entailment”) of terms related to the generic field (for
linguistic botanising) of “implicatio,” assuming that it is difficulties with
the concept of implication (e. g., the ‘paradoxes,’ true but misleading, of
material versus formal implication‘paradox of implication’ first used by
Johnson 1921) that have given rise to this or that newly coined expression
corresponding to this or that original attempt. This whole set of difficulties
certainly becomes clearer as we leave Roman and go further upstream to Grecian,
using the same vocabulary of implication, through the conflation of several
heterogeneous gestures that come from the systematics in Aristotle and the
Stoics. The Roman Vocabulary of Implication and the Implicatio has the
necessary ‘gravitas,’ but Grice, being a Grecian at heart, found it had ‘too
much gravitas,’ hence his ‘implicaturum,’ “which is like the old Roman
‘implicare,’ but for fun!” A number of different expressions in medieval Latin
can express in a more or less equivalent manner the relationship between
propositions and statements such that, from the truth-value of the antecedent
(true or false), one can derive the truth-value of the consequent. There is
“illatio,” and of course “illatum,” which Varro thought fell under ‘inferre.’
Then there’s the feminine noun, ‘inferentia,’ from the ‘participium praesens’
of ‘inferre,’ cf. ‘inferens’ and ‘ilatum.’ There is also ‘consequentia,’ which
is a complex transliterating the Greek ‘syn-,’ in this case with ‘’sequentia,’
from the deponent verb. “I follow you.” Peter Abelard (Petrus Abelardus, v.
Abelardus) makes no distinction in using the expression “consequentia” for the
‘propositio conditionalis,’ hypothetical. Si est homo, est animal. If Grice is
a man, Grice is an animal (Dialectica, 473Abelardus uses ‘Greek man,’ not
Grice.’ His implicaturum is ‘if a Greek man is a man, he is therefore also some
sort of an animal’). But Abelardus also uses the expression “inferentia” for ‘same
old same old’ (cf. “Implicaturum happens.”). Si non est iustus homo, est non
iustus homo. Grice to Strawson on the examiner having given him a second. “If
it is not the case that your examiner was a fair man, it follows thereby that
your examiner was not a fair man, if that helps.” (Dialectica., 414). For some reason, which Grice found obscure,
‘illatio” appears “almost always” in the context of commenting on Aristotle’s
“Topics,”“why people found the topic commenting escapes me” -- aand denotes
more specifically a reasoning, or “argumentum,” in Boethius, allowing for a “consequentia”
to be drawn from a given place. So Abelardus distinguishes: “illatio a causa.”
But there is also “illatio a simili.” And there is “iillatio a pari.” And there
is “illatio a partibus.” “Con-sequentia” sometimes has a very generic usage,
even if not as generic as ‘sequentia.” “Consequentia est quaedam habitudo inter
antecedens et consequens,” “Logica modernorum,” 2.1:38Cfr. Grice on Whitehead
as a ‘modernist’! Grice draws his ‘habit’ from the scholastic ‘habitudo.’ Noe
that ‘antededens’ and ‘consequens.’ The point is a tautological formula, in
terms of formation. Surely ‘consequentia’ relates to a ‘consequens,’ where the
‘consequens’ is the ‘participium praesens’ of the verb from which
‘consequentia’ derives. It’s like deving ‘love’ by ‘to have a beloved.’ “Consequentia”
is in any case present, in some way, without the intensifier ‘syn,’ which the
Roman gravitas added to transliterate the Greek ‘syn,’ i. e. ‘cum.’ -- in the
expression “sequitur” and in the expression “con-sequitur,” literally, ‘to
follow,’ ‘to ensue,’ ‘to result in’). Keenan told Grice that this irritated
him. “If there is an order between a premise and a conclusion, I will stop
using ‘follow,’ because that reverts the order. I’ll use ‘… yields …’ and write
that ‘p yields q.’” “Inferentia,” which is cognate (in the Roman way of using
this expression broadly) with ‘illatio,’ and ‘illatum,’ -- frequently appears,
by contrast, and “for another Grecian reason,” as Grice would put it -- in the
context of the Aristotle’s “De Interpretatione,” on which Grice lectures only
with J. L. Austin (Grice lectured with Strawson on “Categoriae,” onlybut with
Austin, from whom Grice learnedGrice lectured on both “Categoriae’ AND “De
Interpretatione.” -- whether it is as
part of a commentarium on Apuleius’s Isagoge and the Square of Oppositions
(‘figura quadrata spectare”), in order to explain this or that “law” underlying
any of the four sides of the square. So, between A and E we have ‘propositio
opposita.’ Between A and I, and between E and O, we have propositio
sub-alterna. Between A and O, and between E and I, we have propositio
contradictoria. And between I and O, we have “propositio sub-alterna.” --
Logica modernorum, 2.1:115. This was irritatingly explored by P. F. Strawson
and brought to H. P. Grice’s attention, who refused to accept Strawson’s
changes and restrictions of the ‘classical’ validities (or “laws”) because
Strawson felt that the ‘implication’ violated some ‘pragmatic rule,’ while still
yielding a true statement. Then there’s the odd use of “inferentia” to apply to
the different ‘laws’ of ‘conversio’ -- from ‘convertire,’ converting one
proposition into another (Logica modernorum 131–39). Nevertheless, “inferentia”
is used for the dyadic (or triadic, alla Peirce) relationship of ‘implicatio,’
which for some reason, the grave Romans were using for less entertaining
things, and not this or that expressions from the “implication” family, or
sub-field. Surprisingly, a philosopher
without a classical Graeco-Roman background could well be mislead into thinking
that “implicatio” and “implication” are disparate! A number of treatises,
usually written by monksSt. John’s, were Grice teaches, is a Cicercian monastery
-- explore the “implicits.” Such a “tractatus” is not called
‘logico-philosophicus,’ but a “tractatus implicitarum,” literally a treatise on
this or that ‘semantic’ property of the
proposition said to be an ‘implicaturum’ or an ‘implication,’ or ‘propositio re-lativa.’
This is Grice’s reference to the conversational category of ‘re-lation.’
“Re-latio” and “Il-latio” are surely cognate. The ‘referre’ is a bring back;
while the ‘inferre’ is the bring in. The propositio is not just ‘brought’
(latum, or lata) it is brought back. Proposition Q is brought back (relata) to
Proposition P. P and Q become ‘co-relative.’ This is the terminology behind the
idea of a ‘relative clause,’ or ‘oratio relativa.’ E.g. “Si Plato tutee
Socrates est, Socratos tutor Platonis est,” translated by Grice, “If Strawson was
my tutee, it didn’t show!”. Now, closer to Grice “implicitus,” with an “i”
following the ‘implic-‘ rather than the expected ‘a’ (implica), “implicita,”
and “implicitum,” is an alternative “participium passatum” from “im-plic-are,”
in Roman is used for “to be joined, mixed, enveloped.” implĭco (inpl- ), āvi,
ātum, or (twice in Cic., and freq. since the Aug. per.) ŭi, ĭtum (v. Neue,
Formenl. 2, 550 sq.), 1, v. a. in-plico, to fold into; hence, I.to infold, involve,
entangle, entwine, inwrap, envelop, encircle, embrace, clasp, grasp (freq. and
class.; cf.: irretio, impedio). I. Lit.: “involvulus in pampini folio se,”
Plaut. Cist. 4, 2, 64: “ut tenax hedera huc et illuc Arborem implicat errans,”
Cat. 61, 35; cf. id. ib. 107 sq.: “et nunc huc inde huc incertos implicat
orbes,” Verg. A. 12, 743: “dextrae se parvus Iulus Implicuit,” id. ib. 2, 724;
cf.: “implicuit materno bracchia collo,” Ov. M. 1, 762: “implicuitque suos
circum mea colla lacertos,” id. Am. 2, 18, 9: “implicuitque comam laevā,”
grasped, Verg. A. 2, 552: “sertis comas,” Tib. 3, 6, 64: “crinem auro,” Verg.
A. 4, 148: “frondenti tempora ramo,” id. ib. 7, 136; cf. Ov. F. 5, 220: in
parte inferiore hic implicabatur caput, Afran. ap. Non. 123, 16 (implicare
positum pro ornare, Non.): “aquila implicuit pedes atque unguibus haesit,”
Verg. A. 11, 752: “effusumque equitem super ipse (equus) secutus Implicat,” id.
ib. 10, 894: “congressi in proelia totas Implicuere inter se acies,” id. ib.
11, 632: “implicare ac perturbare aciem,” Sall. J. 59, 3: “(lues) ossibus
implicat ignem,” Verg. A. 7, 355.—In part. perf.: “quini erant ordines
conjuncti inter se atque implicati,” Caes. B. G. 7, 73, 4: “Canidia brevibus implicatura
viperis Crines,” Hor. Epod. 5, 15: “folium implicaturum,” Plin. 21, 17, 65, §
105: “intestinum implicaturum,” id. 11, 4, 3, § 9: “impliciti laqueis,” Ov. A.
A. 2, 580: “Cerberos implicitis angue minante comis,” id. H. 9, 94:
“implicitamque sinu absstulit,” id. A. A. 1, 561: “impliciti Peleus rapit
oscula nati,” held in his arms, Val. Fl. 1, 264. II. Trop. A. In gen., to
entangle, implicate, involve, envelop, engage: “di immortales vim suam ... tum
terrae cavernis includunt, tum hominum naturis implicant,” Cic. Div. 1, 36, 79:
“contrahendis negotiis implicari,” id. Off. 2, 11, 40: “alienis (rebus) nimis
implicari molestum esse,” id. Lael. 13, 45: “implicari aliquo certo genere
cursuque vivendi,” id. Off. 1, 32, 117: “implicari negotio,” id. Leg. 1, 3:
“ipse te impedies, ipse tua defensione implicabere,” Cic. Verr. 2, 2, 18, § 44;
cf.: multis implicari erroribus, id. Tusc. 4, 27, 58: “bello,” Verg. A. 11,
109: “eum primo incertis implicantes responsis,” Liv. 27, 43, 3: “nisi forte
implacabiles irae vestrae implicaverint animos vestros,” perplexed, confounded,
id. 40, 46, 6: “paucitas in partitione servatur, si genera ipsa rerum ponuntur,
neque permixte cum partibus implicantur,” are mingled, mixed up, Cic. Inv. 1,
22, 32: ut omnibus copiis conductis te implicet, ne ad me iter tibi expeditum
sit, Pompei. ap. Cic. Att. 8, 12, D, 1: “tanti errores implicant temporum, ut
nec qui consules nec quid quoque anno actum sit digerere possis,” Liv. 2, 21,
4.—In part. perf.: “dum rei publicae quaedam procuratio multis officiis implicaturum
et constrictum tenebat,” Cic. Ac. 1, 3, 11: “Deus nullis occupationibus est
implicatus,” id. N. D. 1, 19, 51; cf.: “implicatus molestis negotiis et
operosis,” id. ib. 1, 20, 52: “animos dederit suis angoribus et molestiis
implicatos,” id. Tusc. 5, 1, 3: “Agrippina morbo corporis implicatura,” Tac. A.
4, 53: “inconstantia tua cum levitate, tum etiam perjurio implicatura,” Cic.
Vatin. 1, 3; cf. id. Phil. 2, 32, 81: “intervalla, quibus implicatura atque
permixta oratio est,” id. Or. 56, 187: “(voluptas) penitus in omni sensu implicatura
insidet,” id. Leg. 1, 17, 47: “quae quatuor inter se colligata atque implicatura,”
id. Off. 1, 5, 15: “natura non tam propensus ad misericordiam quam implicatus
ad severitatem videbatur,” id. Rosc. Am. 30, 85; “and in the form implicitus,
esp. with morbo (in morbum): quies necessaria morbo implicitum exercitum
tenuit,” Liv. 3, 2, 1; 7, 23, 2; 23, 40, 1: “ubi se quisque videbat Implicitum
morbo,” Lucr. 6, 1232: “graviore morbo implicitus,” Caes. B. C. 3, 18, 1; cf.:
“implicitus in morbum,” Nep. Ages. 8, 6; Liv. 23, 34, 11: “implicitus
suspicionibus,” Plin. Ep. 3, 9, 19; cf.: “implicitus terrore,” Luc. 3, 432:
“litibus implicitus,” Hor. A. P. 424: “implicitam sinu abstulit,” Ov. A. A. 1,
562: “(vinum) jam sanos implicitos facit,” Cael. Aur. Acut. 3, 8, 87.— B. In
partic., to attach closely, connect intimately, to unite, join; in pass., to be
intimately connected, associated, or related: “(homo) profectus a caritate
domesticorum ac suorum serpat longius et se implicet primum civium, deinde
mortalium omnium societate,” Cic. Fin. 2, 14, 45: “omnes qui nostris
familiaritatibus implicantur,” id. Balb. 27, 60: “(L. Gellius) ita diu vixit,
ut multarum aetatum oratoribus implicaretur,” id. Brut. 47, 174: “quibus
applicari expediet, non implicari,” Sen. Ep. 105, 5.— In part. perf.: “aliquos
habere implicatos consuetudine et benevolentia,” Cic. Fam. 6, 12, 2:
“implicatus amicitiis,” id. Att. 1, 19, 8: “familiaritate,” id. Pis. 29, 70:
“implicati ultro et citro vel usu diuturno vel etiam officiis,” id. Lael. 22,
85. —Hence, 1. implĭcātus (inpl- ), a, uma., entangled, perplexed, confused,
intricate: “nec in Torquati sermone quicquam implicaturum aut tortuosum fuit,”
Cic. Fin. 3, 1, 3: “reliquae (partes orationis) sunt magnae, implicaturae,
variae, graves, etc.,” id. de Or. 3, 14, 52: vox rauca et implicatura, Sen.
Apocol. med. — Comp.: “implicatior ad loquendum,” Amm. 26, 6, 18. — Sup.:
“obscurissima et implicatissima quaestio,” Gell. 6, 2, 15: “ista tortuosissima
et implicatissima nodositas,” Aug. Conf. 2, 10 init.— 2. im-plĭcĭtē (inpl- ),
adv., intricately (rare): “non implicite et abscondite, sed patentius et
expeditius,” Cic. Inv. 2, 23, 69. -- “Implicare” adds to these usages the idea
of an unforeseen difficulty, i. e. a hint of “impedire,” and even of deceit, i.
e. a hint of “fallere.” Why imply what you can exply? Cf. subreptitious. subreption (n.)"act
of obtaining a favor by fraudulent suppression of facts," c. 1600, from
Latin subreptionem (nominative subreptio),
noun of action from past-participle stem of subripere, surripere (see surreptitious).
Related: Subreptitious.
surreptitious (adj.)mid-15c., from Latin surrepticius "stolen,
furtive, clandestine," from surreptus, past participle
of surripere "seize
secretly, take away, steal, plagiarize," from assimilated form of sub "from
under" (hence, "secretly;" see sub-)
+ rapere "to
snatch" (see rapid).
Related: Surreptitiously.
The source of the philosophers’s usage of ‘implicare’ is a passage from
Aristotle’s “De Int.” on the contrariety of proposition A and E (14.23b25–27),
in which “implicita” (that sould be ‘com-plicita,’ and ‘the emissor complicates
that p”) renders Gk. “sum-pepleg-menê,” “συμ-πεπλεγμένη,” f. “sum-plek-ein,”
“συμ-πλέϰein,” “to bind together,” as in ‘com-plicatio,’ complication, and
Sidonius’s ‘complicature,’ and Grice’s ‘complicature,’ as in ‘temperature,’
from ‘temperare.’ “One problem with P. F. Strawson’s exegesis of J. L. Austin
is the complicature is brings.” This is from the same family or field as
“sum-plokê,” “συμ-πλοϰή,” which Plato (Pol. 278b; Soph. 262c) uses for the
‘second articulation,’ the “com-bination” of sounds (phone) that make up a word
(logos), and, more philosophically interesting, for ‘praedicatio,’ viz., the
interrelation within a ‘logos’ or ‘oratio’ of a noun, or onoma or nomen, as in
“the dog,” and a verb, or rhema, or verbum, -- as in ‘shaggisising’ -- that
makes up a propositional complex, as “The dog is shaggy,” or “The dog
shaggisises.” (H. P. Grice, “Verbing from adjectiving.”). In De Int. 23b25-27,
referring to the contrariety of A and O, Aristotle, “let’s grant it”as Grice
puts it“is hardly clear.” Aristotle writes: “hê de tou hoti kakon to agathon
SUM-PEPLEG-MENÊ estin.” “Kai gar hoti ouk agathon anagkê isôs hupolambanein ton
auton.”“ἡ δὲ τοῦ ὅτι ϰαϰὸν τὸ ἀγαθὸν συμπεπλεγμένη ἐστίν.”“ϰαὶ γὰϱ ὅτι οὐϰ ἀγαθὸν
ἀνάγϰη ἴσως ὑπολαμϐάνειν τὸν αὐτόν.” Back in Rome, Boethius thought of bring
some gravitas to this. “Illa vero quae est,” Boethius goes,” Quoniam malum est
quod est bonum, IMPLICATURA est. Et enim: “Quoniam non bonum est.” necesse est
idem ipsum opinari (repr. in Aristoteles latinus, 2.1–2.4–6. In a later vulgar
Romance, we have J. Tricot). “Quant au jugement, “Le bon est mal” ce n’est en
réalité qu’une COMBINAISON de jugements, cars sans doute est-il nécessaire de
sous-entendre en même temps “le bon n’est pas le bon.” Cf. Mill on ‘sous-entendu’
of conversation. This was discussed by H. P. Grice in a tutorial with
Reading-born English philosopher J. L. Ackrill at St. John’s. With the help of H. P. Grice, J. L. Ackrill
tries to render Boethius into the vernacular (just to please Austin) as
follows. “Hê de tou hoti kakon to agathon SUM-PEPLEG-MENÊ estin, kai gar hoti
OUK agathon ANAGKê isôs hupo-lambanein ton auton” “Illa vero quae est, ‘Quoniam
malum est quod est bonum,’ IMPLICATURA est, et enim, ‘Quoniam non bonum est,’ necesse
est idem ipsum OPINARI. In the vernacular: “The belief expressed by the
proposition, ‘The good is bad,’ is COM-PLICATED or com-plex, for the same
person MUST, perhaps, suppose also the proposition, ‘The good it is not good.’”
Aristotle goes on, “For what kind of utterance is “The good is not good,” or as
they say in Sparta, “The good is no good”? Surely otiose. “The good” is a
Platonic ideal, a universal, separate from this or that good thing. So surely,
‘the good,’ qua idea ain’t good in the sense that playing cricket is good. But
playing cricket is NOT “THE” good: philosophising is.” H. P. Grice found
Boethius’s commentary “perfectly elucidatory,” but Ackrill was perplexed, and
Grice intended Ackrill’s perplexity to go ‘unnoticed’ (“He is trying to
communicate his perplexity, but I keep ignoring it.” For Ackrill was
surreptitiously trying to ‘correct’ his tutor. Aristotle, Acrkill thought, is
wishing to define the ‘contrariety’ between two statements or opinions, or not
to use a metalanguage second order, that what is expressed by ‘The good is bad’
is a contrarium of what is expressed by ‘The good is no good.’” Aristotle starts,
surely, from a principle. The principle states that a maximally false
proposition, set in opposition to a maximally true proposition (such as “The
good is good”), deserves the name “contraria”and ‘contrarium’ to what is
expressed by it. In a second phase, Aristotle then tries to demonstrate, in a
succession of this or that stage, that ‘The good is good’ understood as a
propositio universalis dedicativafor all x, if x is (the) good, x is good (To
agathon agathon estin,’ “Bonum est bonum”) is a maximally true proposition.” And
the reason for this is that “To agathon agathon estin,” or “Bonum bonum est,”
applies to the essence (essentia) of “good,” and ‘predicates’ “the same of the
same,” tautologically. Now consider Aristotle’s other proposition “The good is
the not-bad,” the correlative E form, For all x, if x is good, x is not bad. This
does not do. This is not a maximally true proposition. Unlike “The good is
good,” The good is not bad” does not apply to the essence of ‘the good,’ and it
does not predicate ‘the same of the same’ tautologically. Rather, ‘The good is
not bad,’ unless you bring one of those ‘meaning postulates’ that Grice rightly
defends against Quine in “In defense of a dogma,”in this case, (x)(Bx iff
~Gx)we stipulate something ‘bad’ if it ain’t good -- is only true notably NOT
by virtue of a necessary logical implication, but, to echo my tutor, by implicaturum,
viz. by accident, and not by essence (or essential) involved in the ‘sense’ of
either ‘good’ or ‘bad,’ or ‘not’ for that matter. Surely Aristotle equivocates slightly
when he convinced Grice that an allegedly maximally false proposition (‘the
good is bad’) entails or yields the negation of the same attribute, viz., ‘The
good is not good,’ or more correctly, ‘It is not the case that the good is
good,’ for this is axiomatically contradictory, or tautologically and
necessarily false without appeal to any meaning postulate. For any predicate,
Fx and ~Fx. The question then is one of knowing whether ‘The good is bad’
deserves to be called the contrary proposition (propositio contraria) of ‘The
good is good.’ Aristotle notes that the proposition, ‘The good is bad,’ “To
agathon kakon estin,” “Bonum malum est,” is NOT the maximally false proposition
opposed to the maximally true, tautological, and empty, proposition, “The good
is good,” ‘To agathon agathon estin,’ “Bonum bonum est.” “Indeed, “the good is
bad” is sumpeplegmenê, or COMPLICATA. What the emissor means is a complicatum,
or as Grice preferred, a ‘complicature. Grice’s complicature (roughly rendered
as ‘complification’) condenses all of the moments of the transition from the
simple idea of a container (cum-tainer) to the “modern” ideas of implication,
Grice’s implicaturum, and prae-suppositio. The ‘propositio complicate,’ is, as
Boethius puts it, duplex, or equivocal. The proposition has a double meaningone explicit, the other
implicit. “A ‘propositio complicata’ contains within itself [“continet in se, intra
se”]: bonum non est.” Boethius then goes rightly to conclude (or infer), or
stipulate, that only a “simplex” proposition, not a propositio complicata,
involving some ‘relative clause,’ can be said to be contrary to another -- Commentarii
in librum Aristotelis Peri hermêneais, 219. Boethius’s exegesis thesis is
faithful to Aristotle. For Aristotle, nothing like “the good is not bad,” but
only the tautologically false “the good is not good,” or it is not the case
that the good is good, (to agathon agathon esti, bonum bonum est), a propositio
simplex, and not a propositio complicate, is the opposite (oppositum, -- as per
the ‘figura quadrata’ of ‘oppoista’ -- of “the good is good,” another
propositio simplex. Boethius’s analysis of “the good is bad,” a proposition
that Boethius calls ‘propositio complicate or ‘propositio implicita’ are
manifestly NOT the same as Aristotle’s. For Aristotle, the “doxa hoti kakon to
agathon [δόξα ὅτι ϰαϰὸν τὸ ἀγαθόν],” the opinion according to which the good is
bad, is only ‘contrary’ to “the good is good” to the extent that it “con-tains”
(in Boethius’s jargon) the tautologically false ‘The good is not good.’ For
Boethius, ‘The good is bad’ is contrary to ‘the good is good’ is to the extent
that ‘the good is bad’ contains, implicitly, the belief which Boethius
expresses as ‘Bonum NON est —“ cf. Grice on ‘love that never told can
be”Featuring “it is not the case that,” the proposition ‘bonum non est’ is a
remarkably complicated expression in Latin, a proposition complicata indeed.
‘Bonum non est’ can mean, in the vernacular, “the good is not.” “Bonum non est”
can only be rendered as “there is nothing good.’ “Bonum non est’ may also be
rendered, when expanded with a repeated property, the tautologically false ‘The
good is not good” (Bonum non bonum est). Strangely, Abelard goes in the same
direction as Aristotle, contra Boethius. “The good is bad” (Bonum malum est) is “implicit” (propositio implicita or
complicate) with respect to the tautologically false ‘Bonum bonum non est’ “the
good is not good.”Abelardus, having read Gricevide Strawson, “The influence of
Grice on Abelardus” -- explains clearly the meaning of “propositio implicita”:
“IMPLYING implicitly ‘bonum non bonum est,’ ‘the good is not good’ within
itself, and in a certain wa containing it [“IM-PLICANS eam in se, et quodammodo
continens.” Glossa super Periermeneias, 99–100. But Abelard expands on
Aristotle. “Whoever thinks ‘bonum malum est,’ ‘the good is bad’ also thinks
‘bonum non bonum est,’ ‘the good is not good,’ whereas the reverse does not
hold true, i. e. it is not the case that whoever thinks the tautologically
false ‘the good is not good’ (“bonum bonum non est”) also think ‘the good is
bad’ (‘bonum malum est’). He may refuse to even ‘pronounce’ ‘malum’ (‘malum
malum est’) -- “sed non convertitur.” Abelard’s explanation is decisive for the
natural history of Grice’s implication. One can certainly express in terms of
“implication” what Abelard expresses when he notes the non-reciprocity or
non-convertibility of the two propositions. ‘The good is bad,’ or ‘Bonum malum
est’ implies or presupposes the tautologically true “the good is not good;’It
is not the case that the tautologically false “the good is not good” (‘Bonum
bonum non est’) implies ridiculous “the good is bad.” Followers of Aristotle
inherit these difficulties. Boethius and
Abelard bequeath to posterity an interpretation of the passage in Aristotle’s
“De Interpretatione” according to which “bonum malum est” “the good is bad” can
only be considered the ‘propositio opposita’ of the tautologically true ‘bonum
bonum est’ (“the good is good”) insofar as, a ‘propositio implicita’ or ‘relativa’
or ‘complicata,’ it contains the ‘propositio contradictoria, viz. ‘the good is
not good,’ the tautologically false ‘Bonum non bonum est,’ of the
tautologically true ‘Bonum bonum est’ “the good is good.” It is this meaning of
“to contain a contradiction” that, in a still rather obscure way, takes up this
analysis by specifying a usage of “impliquer.” The first attested use in French
of the verb “impliquer” is in 1377 in Oresme, in the syntagm “impliquer
contradiction” (RT: DHLF, 1793). These same texts give rise to another
analysis. A propositio implicita or pregnant, or complicate, is a proposition
that “implies,” that is, that in fact contains two propositions, one
principalis, and the other relative, each a ‘propositio explicita,’ and that
are equivalent or equipollent to the ‘propositio complicata’ when paraphrased.
Consider. “Homo qui est albus est animal quod currit,” “A man who is white is
an animal who runs.” This ‘propositio complicate contains the the propositio
implicita, “homo est albus” (“a man is white”) and the propositio implicita,
“animal currit” (“an animal runs.”). Only
by “exposing” or “resolving” (via ex-positio, or via re-solutio) such an ‘propositio
complicata’ can one assign it a truth-value. “Omnis proposition implicita habet
duas propositiones explicitas.” “A proposition implicita “P-im” has (at least)
a proposition implicita P-im-1 and a different proposition implicita P-im-2.”
“Verbi gratia.” “Socrates est id quod est homo.” “Haec propositio IMplicita
aequivalet huic copulativae constanti ex duis propositionis explicitis. Socrates
est aliquid est illud est homo. Haec proposition est vera, quare et propositio
implicita vera. Every “implicit proposition” has two explicit propositions.”
“Socrates is something (aliquid) which is a man.” This implicit proposition,
“Socrates is something shich is a man,” is equivalent or equipoent to the
following conjunctive proposition made up of two now EXplicit propositions, to
wit, “Socrates is something,” and “That something is a man.” This latter
conjunctive proposition of the two explicit propositions is true. Therefore,
the “implicit” proposition is also true” (Tractatus implicitarum, in GiusbertiMateriale
per studum, 43). The two “contained” propositions are usually relative
propositions. Each is called an ‘implicatio.’ ‘Implicatio’ (rather than
‘implicitio’) becomes shorthand for “PROPOSITIO implicita.” An ‘implicatio’
becomes one type of ‘propositio
exponibilis,’ i. e. a proposition that is to be “exposed” or paraphrased for
its form or structure to be understood. In
the treatises of Terminist logic, one chapter is by custom devoted to the
phenomenon of “restrictio,” viz. a restriction in the denotation or the
suppositio of the noun (v. SUPPOSITION). A relative expression (an implication),
along with others, has a restrictive function (viz., “officium implicandi”),
just like a sub-propositional expression like an adjective or a participle.
Consider. “A man, Grice, who argues,
runs to the second base.” “Man,” because
of the relative expression or clause “who runs,” is restricted to denoting the
present time (it is not Grice, who argues NOW but ran YESTERDAY). Moreover there
is an equivalence or equipolence between the relative expression “qui currit”
and the present participle “currens.” Running Grice argues. Grice who runs
argues. Summe metenses, Logica modernorum, 2.1:464. In the case in which a
relative expression is restrictive, its function is to “leave something that is
constant,” “aliquid pro constanti relinquere,” viz., to produce a pre-assertion
that conditions the truth of the main super-ordinate assertion without being
its primary object or topic or signification or intentio. “Implicare est pro
constanti et involute aliquid significare.” “Ut cum dicitur homo qui est albus
currit.” “Pro constanti” dico, quia
praeter hoc quod assertitur ibi cursus de homine, aliquid datur intelligi,
scilicet hominem album; “involute” dico quia praeter hoc quod ibi proprie et
principaliter significatur hominem currere, aliquid intus intelligitur, scilicet
hominem esse album. Per hoc patet quod implicare est intus plicare. Id enim
quod intus “plicamus” sive “ponimus,” pro constanti relinquimus. Unde implicare
nil aliud est quam subiectum sub aliqua dispositione pro constanti relinquere
et de illo sic disposito aliquid affirmare. Ackrill translates to Grice: “To
imply” is to signify something by stating it as constant, and in a pretty
‘hidden’ manner“involute.” When I state that the man <who is white> runs,
I state, stating it as constant, because, beyond (“praeter”) the main
supra-ordinate assertion or proposition that predicates the running of the man,
my addressee is given to understand something else (“aliquid intus
intelligitur”), viz. that the man is white; This is communicated in a hidden
manner (“involute”) because, beyond (“praeter”) what is communicated (“significatur”)
primarily, principally (“principaliter”) properly (“proprie”), literally, and
explicitly, viz. that the man is running, we are given to understand something
else (“aliquid intus intelligutur”) within (“intus”), viz. that the man is white. It follows from this that implicare is
nothing other than what the form of the expression literally conveys, intus
plicare (“folded within”). What we fold
or state within, we leave as a constant.
It follows from this that “to imply” is nothing other than leaving
something as a constant in the subject (‘subjectum’), such that the subject (subjectum,
‘homo qui est albus”) is under a certain disposition, and that it is only under
this disposition that something about the subjectum is affirmed” -- De
implicationibus, Nota, 100) For the record: while Giusberti (“Materiale per
studio,” 31) always reads “pro constanti,” the MSS occasionally has the pretty
Griciean “precontenti.” This is a case of what the “Logique du Port-Royal”
describes as an “in-cidental” assertion. The situation is even more complex,
however, insofar as this operation only relates to one usage of a relative
proposition, viz. when the proposition is restrictive. A restriction can
sometimes be blocked, or cancelled, and the reinscriptions are then different
for a nonrestrictive and a restrictive
relative proposition. One such case of a blockage is that of “false
implication” (Johnson’s ‘paradox of ‘implicatio’) as in “a [or the] man who is
a donkey runs,” (but cf. the centaur, the man who is a horse, runs) where there
is a conflict (“repugnantia”) between what the determinate term itself denotes
(homo, man) and the determination (ansinus, donkey). The truth-values of a
proposition containing a relative clause or propositio thus varies according to
whether it is restrictive, and of composite meaning, as in “homo, qui est albus,
currit” (A man, who is white, runs), or non-restrictive, and of divided
meaning, as in “Homo currit qui est albus” (Rendered in the vernacular in the
same way, the Germanic languages not having the syntactic freedom the classical
languages do: A man, who is white, is running. When the relative is
restrictive, as in “Homo, qui est albus, curris”, the propositio implicits only
produces one single assertion, since the relative corresponds to a pre-assertion.
Thus, it is the equivalent, at the level of the underlying form, to a
proposition conditionalis or hypothetical. Only in the second case can there be
a “resolution” of the proposition implicita into the pair of this and that
‘propositio explicita, to wit, “homo currit,”
“homo est albus.”—and an equipolence between the complex proposition
implicita and the conjunction of the first proposition explicita and the second
proposition explicitta. Homo currit et ille est albus. So it is only in this second
case of proposition irrestrictiva that
one can say that “Homo currit, qui est albus implies “Homo currit,” and “Homo
est albus” and therefore, “Homo qui est albus currit.” The poor grave Romans
are having trouble with Grecisms. The Grecist vocabulary of implication is both
disparate and systematic, in a Griceian oxymoronic way. The grave Latin
“implicare” covers and translates an extremely varied Grecian field of
expressions ready to be botanized, that bears the mark of heterogeneous rather
than systematic operations, whether one is dealing Aristotle or the Stoics. The
passage through grave Roman allows us to understand retrospectively the
connection in Aristotle’s jargon between the “implicatio” of the “propositio
implicita,” sum-pepleg-menê, as an interweaving or interlacing, and conclusive
or con-sequential implicatio, sumperasma, “συμπέϱασμα,” or “sumpeperasmenon,” “συμπεπεϱασμένον,”
“sumpeperasmenê,” “συμπεπεϱασμένη,” f. perainein, “πεϱαίνein, “to limit,” which
is the jargon Aristotle uses in the Organon to denote the conclusion of a
syllogism (Pr. Anal. 1.15.34a21–24). If one designates as A the premise, tas
protaseis, “τὰς πϱοτάσεις,” and as B the con-clusion, “to sumperasma,” συμπέϱασμα.”
Cf. the Germanic puns with ‘closure,’ etc.
When translating Aristotle’s definition of the syllogism at Prior
Analytics 1.1.24b18–21, Tricot chooses to render as the “con-sequence”
Aristotle’s verb “sum-bainei,” “συμ-ϐαίνει,” that which “goes with” the premise
and results from it. A syllogism is a discourse, “logos,” “λόγος,” in which,
certain things being stated, something other than what is stated necessarily
results simply from the fact of what is stated. Simply from the fact of what is
stated, I mean that it is because of this that the consequence is obtained, “legô
de tôi tauta einai to dia tauta sumbainei,” “λέγω δὲ τῷ ταῦτα εἶναι τὸ διὰ ταῦτα
συμϐαίνει.” (Pr. Anal. 1.1, 24b18–21). To make the connection with
“implication,” though, we also have to take into account, as is most often the
case, the Stoics’ own jargon. What the Stoics call “sumpeplegmenon,” “συμπεπλεγμένον,”
is a “conjunctive” proposition; e. g. “It is daytime, and it is light” (it is
true both that A and that B). The conjunctive is a type of molecular
proposition, along with the “conditional” (sunêmmenon [συνημμένον] -- “If it is
daytime, it is light”) and the “subconditional” (para-sunêmmenon [παϱασυνημμένον];
“SINCE it is daytime, it is light”), and the “disjunctive” (diezeugmenon
[διεζευγμένον] -- “It is daytime, or it
is night.” Diog. Laert. 7.71–72; cf. RT: Long and Sedley, A35, 2:209 and
1:208). One can see that there is no ‘implicatio’ in the conjunctive, whereas
there is one in the ‘sunêmmenon’ (“if p, q”), which constitutes the Stoic
expression par excellence, as distinct from the Aristotelian categoric
syllogism.Indeed, it is around the propositio conditionalis that the question
and the vocabulary of ‘implicatio’ re-opens. The Aristotelian sumbainein [συμϐαίνειν],
which denotes the accidental nature of a result, however clearly it has been
demonstrated (and we should not forget that sumbebêkos [συμϐεϐηϰός] denotes
accident; see SUBJECT, I), is replaced by “akolouthein” [ἀϰολουθεῖν] (from the
copulative a- and keleuthos [ϰέλευθος], “path” [RT: Chantraine, Dictionnaire
étymologique de la langue grecque, s.v. ἀϰόλουθος]), which denotes instead
being accompanied by a consequent conformity. This connector, i. e. the “if”
(ei, si) indicates that the second proposition, the con-sequens (“it is light”)
follows (akolouthei [ἀϰολουθεῖ]) from the first (“it is daytime”) (Diog. Laert,
7.71). Attempts, beginning with Philo or Diodorus Cronus up to Grice and
Strawson to determine the criteria of a “valid” conditional (to hugies
sunêmmenon [τὸ ὑγιὲς συνημμένον] offer, among other possibilities, the notion
of emphasis [ἔμφασις], which Long and Sedley translate as “G. E. Moore’s entailment”
and Brunschwig and Pellegrin as “implication” (Sextus Empiricus, The Skeptic
Way, in RT: Long and Sedley, The Hellenistic Philosophers, 35B, 2:211 and
1:209), a term that is normally used to refer to a reflected image and to the
force, including rhetorical force, of an impression. Elsewhere, this “emphasis”
is explained in terms of dunamis [δύναμις], of “virtual” content (“When we have
the premise which results in a certain conclusion, we also have this conclusion
virtually [dunamei (δυνάμει)] in the premise, even if it is not explicitly
indicated [kan kat’ ekphoran mê legetai (ϰἂν ϰατ̕ ἐϰφοϱὰν μὴ λέγεται)], Sextus
Empiricus, Against the Grammarians 8.229ff., D. L. Blank, 49 = RT: Long and
Sedley, G36 (4), 2:219 and 1:209)—where connecting the different usages of
“implication” creates new problems. One has to understand that the type of
implicatio represented by the proposition conditionalis implies, in the double
usage of “contains implicitly” and “has as its consequence,” the entire Stoic
system. It is a matter of to akolouthon en zôêi [τὸ ἀϰόλουθον ἐν ζωῇ],
“consequentiality in life,” or ‘rational life, as Grice prefers, as Long and
Sedley translate it (Stobeus 2.85.13 = RT: Long and Sedley, 59B, 2:356; Cicero
prefers “congruere,” (congruential) De finibus 3.17 = RT: Long and Sedley, 59D,
2:356). It is akolouthia [ἀϰολουθία] that refers to the conduct con-sequent
upon itself that is the conduct of the wise man, the chain of causes defining
will or fate, and finally the relationship that joins the antecedent to the con-sequent
in a true proposition. Goldschmidt, having cited Bréhier (Le système stoïcien),
puts the emphasis on antakolouthia [ἀνταϰολουθία], a Stoic neologism that may
be translated as “reciprocal” implicatio,” and that refers specifically to the
solidarity of virtues (antakolouthia tôn aretôn [ἀνταϰολουθία τῶν ἀϱετῶν],
Diog. Laert. 7.125; Goldschmidt, as a group that would be encompassed by
dialectical virtue, immobilizing akolouthia in the absolute present of the wise
man. “Implicatio” is, in the final analysis, from then on, the most literal
name of the Stoic system. Refs.: Aristotle.
Anal. Pr.. ed. H. Tredennick, in
Organon, Harvard; Goldschmidt, Le système stoïcien et l’idée de temps. Paris:
Vrin, Sextus Empiricus. Against the Grammarians, ed. D. L. Blank. Oxford:
Oxford. END OF INTERLUDE. Now for “Implication”/“Implicaturum.” Implicatura was
used by Sidonius in a letter (that Grice found funny) and used by Grice in
seminars on conversational helpfulness at Oxford. Grice sets out the basis of a
systematic approach to communication, viz, concerning the relation between a
proposition p and a proposition q in a conversational context. The need is felt
by Sidonius and Grice for ‘implicaturum,’ tdistinct from “implication,” insofar
as “implication” is used for a relation between a proposition p and a proposition
q, whereas an “implicaturum” is a relation between this or that statement,
within a given context, that results from an EMISSOR having utterered an
utterance (thereby explicitly conveying that p) and thereby implicitly
conveying and implicating that q. Grice thought the distinction was ‘frequently
ignored by Austin,’ and Grice thought it solved a few problems, initially in G.
A. Paul’s neo-Wttigensteinian objections to Price’s causal theory of perception
(“The pillar box seems red to me; which does not surprise me, seeing that it is
red”). An “implication” is a relation
bearing on the truth or falsity of this or that proposition (e. g. “The pillar
box seems red” and, say, “The pillar box MAY NOT be red”) whereas an “implicaturum”
brings an extra meaning to this or that statement it governs (By uttering “The
pillar box seems red” thereby explicitly conveying that the pillar box seems
red, the emissor implicates in a cancellable way that the pillar box MAY NOT be
red.”). Whenever “implicaturum” is determined according to its context (as at
Collections, “Strawson has beautiful handwriting; a mark of his character. And
he learned quite a bit in spite of the not precisely angelic temperament of his
tutor Mabbott”) it enters the field of pragmatics, and therefore has to be
distinguished from a presupposition. Implicatio simpliciter is a relation
between two propositions, one of which is the consequence of the other (Quine’s
example: “My father is a bachelor; therefore, he is male”). An equivalent of “implication”
is “entailment,” as used by Moore. Now, Moore was being witty. ‘Entail’ is
derived from “tail” (Fr. taille; ME entaill or entailen = en + tail), and prior
to its logical use, the meaning of “entailment” is “restriction,” “tail” having
the sense of “limitation.” As Moore explains in his lecture: “An entailment is
a limitation on the transfer or handing down of a property or an inheritance.
*My* use of ‘entailment’ has two features in common with the Legalese that
Father used to use; to wit: the handing down of a property; and; the limitation
on one of the poles of this transfer. As I stipulate we should use “entailment”
(at Cambridge, but also at Oxford), a PROPERTY is transferred from the
antecedent to the con-sequent. And also, normally in semantics, some LIMITATION
(or restriction, or ‘stricting,’ or ‘relevancing’) on the antecedent is
stressed.” The mutation from the legalese to Moore’s usage explicitly occurs by
analogy on the basis of these two shared common elements. Now, Whitehead had
made a distinction between a material (involving a truth-value) implication and
formal (empty) implication. A material implication (“if,” symbolized by the
horseshoe “⊃,” because “it resembles an arrow,”
Whitehead said“Some arrow!” was Russell’s response) is a Philonian implication
as defined semantically in terms of a truth-table by Philo of Megara. “If p, q”
is false only when the antecedent is true and the con-sequent false. In terms
of a formalization of communication, this has the flaw of bringing with it a
counter-intuitive feeling of ‘baffleness’ (cf. “The pillar box seems red,
because it is”), since a false proposition implies materially any proposition: If
the moon is made of green cheese, 2 + 2 = 4. This “ex falso quodlibet sequitur”
has a pedigreed history. For the Stoics and the Megarian philosophers, “ex
falso quodlibet sequitur” is what distinguishes Philonian implication and
Diodorean implication. It traverses the theory of consequence and is ONE of the
paradoxes of material implication that is perfectly summed up in these two
rules of Buridan: First, if P is false, Q follows from P; Second, if P is true,
P follows from Q (Bochenski, History of Formal Logic). A formal (empty) implication
(see Russell, Principles of Mathematics, 36–41) is a universal conditional
implication: Ɐx (Ax ⊃ Bx), for any x, if Ax, then Bx. Different
means of resolving the paradoxes of implication have been proposed. All failed
except Grice’s. An American, C. I. Lewis’s “strict” implication (Lewis and
Langford, Symbolic Logic) is defined as an implication that is ‘reinforced’
such that it is impossible for the antecedent to be true and the con-sequent
false. Unfortunately, as Grice tells Lewis in a correspondence, “your strict
implication, I regret to prove, has the same alleged flaw as the ‘material’
implication that your strict implication was meant to improve on. (an
impossible—viz., necessarily false—proposition strictly implies any
proposition). The relation of entailment introduced by Moore in 1923 is a
relation that seems to avoid this or that paradox (but cf. Grice, “Paradoxes of
entailment, followed by paradoxes of implicationall conversationally resolved”)
by requiring a derivation of the antecedent from the con-sequent. In this case,
“If 2 + 2 = 5, 2 + 3 = 5” is false, since the con-sequent is stipulated not be
derivable from the antecedent. Occasionally, one has to call upon the pair
“entailment”/“implication” in order to distinguish between an implication in
qua material implication and an implication in Moore’s usage (metalinguisticthe
associated material implication is a theorem), which is also sometimes called
“relevant” if not strictc implication (Anderson and Belnap, Entailment), to
ensure that the entire network of expressions is covered. Along with this first
series of expressions in which “entailment” and “implication” alternate with
one another, there is a second series of expressions that contrasts two kinds
of “implicaturum,” or ‘implicatura.’ “Implicaturum” (Fr. implicaturum, G.
Implikatur) is formed from “implicatio” and the suffix –ture, which expresses,
as Grice knew since his Clifton days, a ‘resultant aspect,’ ‘aspectum
resultativus’ (as in “signature”; cf. L. temperatura, from temperare). “Implicatio” may be thought as derived from
“to imply” (if not ‘employ’) and “implicaturum” may be thought as deriving from
“imply”’s doulet, “to implicate” (from L. “in-“ + “plicare,” from plex; cf. the
IE. plek), which has the same meaning. Some mistakenly see Grice’s “implicaturum”
as an extension and modification of the concept of presupposition, which
differs from ‘material’ implication in that the negation of the antecedent
implies the consequent (the question “Have you stopped beating your wife?”
presupposes the existence of a wife in both cases). An implicaturum escapes the
paradoxes of material implication from the outset. In fact, Grice, the ever
Oxonian, distinguishes “at least” two kinds of implicaturum, conventional and
non-conventional, the latter sub-divided into non-conventional
non-converastional, and non-conventional conversational. A non-conventional
non-conversational implicaturum may occur in a one-off predicament. A Conventional
implicaturum and a conventional implicaturum is practically equivalent,
Strawson wrongly thought, to presupposition prae-suppositum, since it refers to
the presuppositions attached by linguistic convention to a lexical item or
expression. E. g. “Mary EVEN loves
Peter” has a relation of conventional implicaturum to “Mary loves other
entities than Peter.” This is equivalent to: “ ‘Mary EVEN loves Peter’
presupposes ‘Mary loves other entities than Peter.’ With this kind of implicaturum,
we remain within the expression, and thus the semantic, field. A conventional implicaturum,
however, is surely different from a material implicatio. It does not concern
the truth-values. With conversational implicaturum, we are no longer dependent
on this or that emissum, but move into pragmatics (the area that covers the
relation between statements and contexts. Grice gives the following example:
If, in answer to A’s question about how C is getting on in his new job at a
bank, B utters, “Well, he likes his colleagues, and he hasn’t been to in prison
yet,” what B implicates by the proposition that it is not the case that C has
been to prison yet depends on the context. It compatible with two very different
contexts: one in which C, naïve as he is, is expected to be entrapped by
unscrupulous colleagues in some shady deal, or, more likely, C is well-known by
A and B to tend towards dishonesty (hence the initial question). References: Abelard,
Peter. Dialectica. Edited by L. M. De Rijk. Assen, Neth.: Van Gorcum, 1956. 2nd
rev. ed., 1970. Glossae super Periermeneias. Edited by Lorenzo Minio-Paluello.
In TwelfthCentury Logic: Texts and Studies,
2, Abelaerdiana inedita. Rome: Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura, 1958. Anderson,
Allan Ross, and Nuel Belnap. Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and
Necessity. 1. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1975. Aristotle. De interpretatione. English translation by
J. L. Ackrill: Aristotle’s Categories and De interpretatione. Notes by J. L.
Ackrill. Oxford: Clarendon, 1963. French translation by J. Tricot: Organon.
Paris: Vrin, 1966. Auroux, Sylvain, and Irène Rosier. “Les sources historiques
de la conception des deux types de relatives.” Langages 88 (1987): 9–29. Bochenski,
Joseph M. A History of Formal Logic. Translated by Ivo Thomas. New York:
Chelsea, 1961. Boethius. Aristoteles latinus. Edited by Lorenzo Minio-Paluello.
Paris: Descleé de Brouwer, 1965. Translation by Lorenzo Minio-Paluello: The
Latin Aristotle. Toronto: Hakkert, 1972. Commentarii in librum Aristotelis Peri
hermêneias. Edited by K. Meiser. Leipzig: Teubner, 1877. 2nd ed., 1880. De
Rijk, Lambertus Marie. Logica modernorum: A Contribution to the History of
Early Terminist Logic. 2 vols. Assen, Neth.: Van Gorcum, 1962–67. “Some Notes on the Mediaeval Tract De
insolubilibus, with the Edition of a Tract Dating from the End of the
Twelfth-Century.” Vivarium 4 (1966): 100–103. Giusberti, Franco. Materials for
a Study on Twelfth-Century Scholasticism. Naples, It.: Bibliopolis, 1982.
Grice, H. P. “Logic and Conversation.” In Syntax and Semantics 3: Speech Acts,
edited by P. Cole and J. Morgan, 41–58. New York: Academic Press, 1975. (Also
in The Logic of Grammar, edited by D. Davidson and G. Harman, 64–74. Encino,
CA: Dickenson, 1975.) Lewis, Clarence Irving, and Cooper Harold Langford.
Symbolic Logic. New York: New York Century, 1932. Meggle, Georg. Grundbegriffe
der Kommunikation. 2nd ed. Berlin: De Gruyter, 1997. Meggle, Georg, and
Christian Plunze, eds. Saying, Meaning, Implicating. Leipzig: Leipziger
Universitätsverlag, 2003. Moore, G. E.. Philosophical Studies. London: Kegan Paul,
1923. Rosier, I. “Relatifs et relatives dans les traits terministes des XIIe et
XIIIe siècles: (2) Propositions relatives (implicationes), distinction entre
restrictives et non restrictives.” Vivarium 24: 1 (1986): 1–21. Russell,
Bertrand. The Principles of Mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1903. implication, a relation that holds between two statements when the truth
of the first ensures the truth of the second. A number of statements together
imply Q if their joint truth ensures the truth of Q. An argument is deductively
valid exactly when its premises imply its conclusion. Expressions of the
following forms are often interchanged one for the other: ‘P implies Q’, ‘Q
follows from P’, and ‘P entails Q’. (‘Entailment’ also has a more restricted
meaning.) In ordinary discourse, ‘implication’ has wider meanings that are
important for understanding reasoning and communication of all kinds. The
sentence ‘Last Tuesday, the editor remained sober throughout lunch’ does not
imply that the editor is not always sober. But one who asserted the sentence
typically would imply this. The theory of conversational implicaturum explains
how speakers often imply more than their sentences imply. The term
‘implication’ also applies to conditional statements. A material implication of
the form ‘if P, then Q’ (often symbolized ‘P P Q’ or ‘P / Q’) is true so long
as either the if-clause P is false or the main clause Q is true; it is false
only if P is true and Q is false. A strict implication of the form ‘if P, then
Q’ (often symbolized ‘P Q’) is true exactly when the corresponding material
implication is necessarily true; i.e., when it is impossible for P to be true
when Q is false. The following valid forms of argument are called paradoxes of
material implication: Q. Therefore, P / Q. Not-P. Therefore, P / Q. The
appearance of paradox here is due to using ‘implication’ as a name both for a
relation between statements and for statements of conditional form. A
conditional statement can be true even though there is no relation between its
components. Consider the following valid inference: Butter floats in milk.
Therefore, fish sleep at night / butter floats in milk. Since the simple
premise is true, the conditional conclusion is also true despite the fact that
the nocturnal activities of fish and the comparative densities of milk and
butter are completely unreimmediate inference implication 419 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 419 lated. The statement ‘Fish sleep at night’ does not
imply that butter floats in milk. It is better to call a conditional statement
that is true just so long as it does not have a true if-clause and a false main
clause a material conditional rather than a material implication. Strict
conditional is similarly preferable to ‘strict implication’. Respecting this
distinction, however, does not dissolve all the puzzlement of the so-called
paradoxes of strict implication: Necessarily Q. Therefore, P Q. Impossible that
P. Therefore, P Q. Here is an example of the first pattern: Necessarily, all
rectangles are rectangles. Therefore, fish sleep at night all rectangles are
rectangles. ‘All rectangles are rectangles’ is an example of a vacuous truth,
so called because it is devoid of content. ‘All squares are rectangles’ and ‘5
is greater than 3’ are not so obviously vacuous truths, although they are
necessary truths. Vacuity is not a sharply defined notion. Here is an example
of the second pattern: It is impossible that butter always floats in milk yet
sometimes does not float in milk. Therefore, butter always floats in milk yet
sometimes does not float in milk fish sleep at night. Does the if-clause of the
conclusion imply (or entail) the main clause? On one hand, what butter does in
milk is, as before, irrelevant to whether fish sleep at night. On this ground,
relevance logic denies there is a relation of implication or entailment. On the
other hand, it is impossible for the if-clause to be true when the main clause
is false, because it is impossible for the if-clause to be true in any
circumstances whatever. Speranza, Luigi. Join the Grice Club! StrawsonF.. “On
Referring.” Mind 59 (1950): 320–44.
IN-POSITVM
-- Grice:
“Again, the assimilation of the ‘n’ to ‘m’ before ‘p’ is only vulgar!” -- impositum:
“An apt term by Boezio,” Grice. There’s preposition, proposition, supposition,
and imposition! a property of terms resulting from a convention to designate
something. A term is not a mere noise but a significant sound. A term
designating extralinguistic entities, such as ‘tree’, ‘stone’, ‘blue’, and the
like, are classified by the tradition since Boethius as terms of “prima
impositio,” first imposition. A term designating another term or other
communicative items, such as ‘noun’, ‘declension’, and the like, is classified
as terms of ‘secunda imposition.’ The distinction between a terms of ‘prima
impositio’ and ‘secunda impositio’ belongs to the realm of the communicatum, while
the parallel distinction between terms of first and second ‘intentio’ belongs
to the realm of the animatum A ‘prima intentio’ (intentio re re), frst
intention is, broadly, thoughts about trees, stones, colours, etc. A ‘intentio
secunda,’ (intention de sensu), second intention, is a thought about a first
intention. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “De sensu implicaturum.”
IN-DUCTVM
-- inductum:
in the narrow sense, inference to a generalization from its instances; (2) in
the broad sense, any ampliative inferencei.e., any inference where the claim
made by the conclusion goes beyond the claim jointly made by the premises.
Induction in the broad sense includes, as cases of particular interest:
argument by analogy, predictive inference, inference to causes from signs and
symptoms, and confirmation of scientific laws and theories. The narrow sense
covers one extreme case that is not ampliative. That is the case of
mathematical induction, where the premises of the argument necessarily imply
the generalization that is its conclusion. Inductive logic can be conceived
most generally as the theory of the evaluation of ampliative inference. In this
sense, much of probability theory, theoretical statistics, and the theory of
computability are parts of inductive logic. In addition, studies of scientific
method can be seen as addressing in a less formal way the question of the logic
of inductive inference. The name ‘inductive logic’ has also, however, become
associated with a specific approach to these issues deriving from the work of
Bayes, Laplace, De Morgan, and Carnap. On this approach, one’s prior
probabilities in a state of ignorance are determined or constrained by some
principle for the quantification of ignorance and one learns by conditioning on
the evidence. A recurrent difficulty with this line of attack is that the way
in which ignorance is quantified depends on how the problem is described, with
different logically equivalent descriptions leading to different prior
probabilities. Carnap laid down as a postulate for the application of his
inductive logic that one should always condition on one’s total evidence. This
rule of total evidence is usually taken for granted, but what justification is
there for it? Good pointed out that the standard Bayesian analysis of the
expected value of new information provides such a justification. Pure cost-free
information always has non-negative expected value, and if there is positive
probability that it will affect a decision, its expected value is positive.
Ramsey made the same point in an unpublished manuscript. The proof generalizes
to various models of learning uncertain evidence. A deductive account is
sometimes presented indubitability induction 425 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM
Page 425 where induction proceeds by elimination of possibilities that would
make the conclusion false. Thus Mill’s methods of experimental inquiry are
sometimes analyzed as proceeding by elimination of alternative possibilities.
In a more general setting, the hypothetico-deductive account of science holds
that theories are confirmed by their observational consequencesi.e., by
elimination of the possibilities that this experiment or that observation
falsifies the theory. Induction by elimination is sometimes put forth as an
alternative to probabilistic accounts of induction, but at least one version of
it is consistent withand indeed a consequence ofprobabilistic accounts. It is
an elementary fact of probability that if F, the potential falsifier, is
inconsistent with T and both have probability strictly between 0 and 1, then
the probability of T conditional on not-F is higher than the unconditional
probability of T. In a certain sense, inductive support of a universal
generalization by its instances may be a special case of the foregoing, but this
point must be treated with some care. In the first place, the universal
generalization must have positive prior probability. (It is worth noting that
Carnap’s systems of inductive logic do not satisfy this condition, although
systems of Hintikka and Niiniluoto do.) In the second place, the notion of
instance must be construed so the “instances” of a universal generalization are
in fact logical consequences of it. Thus ‘If A is a swan then A is white’ is an
instance of ‘All swans are white’ in the appropriate sense, but ‘A is a white
swan’ is not. The latter statement is logically stronger than ‘If A is a swan
then A is white’ and a complete report on species, weight, color, sex, etc., of
individual A would be stronger still. Such statements are not logical consequences
of the universal generalization, and the theorem does not hold for them. For
example, the report of a man 7 feet 11¾ inches tall might actually reduce the
probability of the generalization that all men are under 8 feet tall. Residual
queasiness about the foregoing may be dispelled by a point made by Carnap
apropos of Hempel’s discussion of paradoxes of confirmation. ‘Confirmation’ is
ambiguous. ‘E confirms H’ may mean that the probability of H conditional on E
is greater than the unconditional probability of H, in which case deductive
consequences of H confirm H under the conditions set forth above. Or ‘E
confirms H’ may mean that the probability of H conditional on E is high (e.g.,
greater than .95), in which case if E confirms H, then E confirms every logical
consequence of H. Conflation of the two senses can lead one to the paradoxical
conclusion that E confirms E & P and thus P for any statement inductum
-- inductivism: “A philosophy of science invented by Popper and P. K.
Feyerabend as a foil for their own views. Why, I must just have well invented
‘sensism’ as a foil for my theory of implicaturum!” -- According to
inductivism, a unique a priori inductive logic enables one to construct an
algorithm that will compute from any input of data the best scientific theory
accounting for that data. inductum: Not deductum, --
nor abductum -- epapoge, Grecian term for ‘induction’. Especially in the logic
of Aristotle, epagoge is opposed to argument by syllogism. Aristotle describes
it as “a move from particulars to the universal.” E.g., premises that the
skilled navigator is the best navigator, the skilled charioteer the best
charioteer, and the skilled philosopher the best philosopher may support the
conclusion by epagoge that those skilled in something are usually the best at
it. Aristotle thought it more persuasive and clearer than the syllogistic
method, since it relies on the senses and is available to all humans. The term
was later applied to dialectical arguments intended to trap opponents. R.C. epicheirema,
a polysyllogism in which each premise represents an enthymematic argument;
e.g., ‘A lie creates disbelief, because it is an assertion that does not
correspond to truth; flattery is a lie, because it is a conscious distortion of
truth; therefore, flattery creates disbelief’. Each premise constitutes an
enthymematic syllogism. Thus, the first premise could be expanded into the
following full-fledged syllogism: ‘Every assertion that does not correspond to
truth creates disbelief; a lie is an assertion that does not correspond to
truth; therefore a lie creates disbelief’. We could likewise expand the second
premise and offer a complete argument for it. Epicheirema can thus be a
powerful tool in oral polemics, especially when one argues regressively, first
stating the conclusion with a sketch of support in terms of enthymemes, and
then if challenged to do so expanding any or all of these enthymemes into
standard categorical syllogisms.
IN-LATUM -- illatum: A form of the conjugation
Grice enjoyed was “inferentia,” cf essentia,
sententia, prudentia, etc..see illatum -- Cf. illatio. Consequentia.
Implicatio. Grice’s implicaturum and what the emissor implicates as a variation
on the logical usage.
infima species (Latin, ‘lowest species’),
a species that is not a genus of any other species. According to the theory of
classification, division, and definition that is part of traditional or
Aristotelian logic, every individual is a specimen of some infima species. An
infima species is a member of a genus that may in turn be a species of a more
inclusive genus, and so on, until one reaches a summum genus, a genus that is
not a species of a more inclusive genus. Socrates and Plato are specimens of
the infima specis human being (mortal rational animal), which is a species of
the genus rational animal, which is a species of the genus animal, and so on,
up to the summum genus substance. Whereas two specimens of animale.g., an
individual human and an individual horsecan differ partly in their essential
characteristics, no two specimens of the infima species human being can differ
in essence.
infinite-off
predicament, or ∞-off predicament.
IN-FINITVM -- infinitum: Cantor, G. Grice
thought that “I know there are infinitely many stars” is a stupid thing to say
-- one of a number of late nineteenthcentury philosophers including Frege,
Dedekind, Peano, Russell, and Hilbert who transformed both mathematics and the
study of its philosophical foundations. The philosophical import of Cantor’s
work is threefold. First, it was primarily Cantor who turned arbitrary
collections into objects of mathematical study, sets. Second, he created a
coherent mathematical theory of the infinite, in particular a theory of
transfinite numbers. Third, linking these, he was the first to indicate that it
might be possible to present mathematics as nothing but the theory of sets,
thus making set theory foundational for mathematics. This contributed to the
Camus, Albert Cantor, Georg 116 116
view that the foundations of mathematics should itself become an object of
mathematical study. Cantor also held to a form of principle of plenitude, the
belief that all the infinities given in his theory of transfinite numbers are
represented not just in mathematical or “immanent” reality, but also in the
“transient” reality of God’s created world. Cantor’s main, direct achievement
is his theory of transfinite numbers and infinity. He characterized as did Frege
sameness of size in terms of one-to-one correspondence, thus accepting the
paradoxical results known to Galileo and others, e.g., that the collection of
all natural numbers has the same cardinality or size as that of all even
numbers. He added to these surprising results by showing 1874 that there is the
same number of algebraic and thus rational numbers as there are natural
numbers, but that there are more points on a continuous line than there are
natural or rational or algebraic numbers, thus revealing that there are at
least two different kinds of infinity present in ordinary mathematics, and
consequently demonstrating the need for a mathematical treatment of these
infinities. This latter result is often expressed by saying that the continuum
is uncountable. Cantor’s theorem of 2 is a generalization of part of this, for
it says that the set of all subsets the power-set of a given set must be
cardinally greater than that set, thus giving rise to the possibility of
indefinitely many different infinities. The collection of all real numbers has
the same size as the power-set of natural numbers. Cantor’s theory of
transfinite numbers 0 97 was his developed mathematical theory of infinity,
with the infinite cardinal numbers the F-, or aleph-, numbers based on the
infinite ordinal numbers that he introduced in 0 and 3. The F-numbers are in
effect the cardinalities of infinite well-ordered sets. The theory thus
generates two famous questions, whether all sets in particular the continuum
can be well ordered, and if so which of the F-numbers represents the
cardinality of the continuum. The former question was answered positively by
Zermelo in 4, though at the expense of postulating one of the most
controversial principles in the history of mathematics, the axiom of choice.
The latter question is the celebrated continuum problem. Cantor’s famous
continuum hypothesis CH is his conjecture that the cardinality of the continuum
is represented by F1, the second aleph. CH was shown to be independent of the
usual assumptions of set theory by Gödel 8 and Cohen 3. Extensions of Cohen’s
methods show that it is consistent to assume that the cardinality of the
continuum is given by almost any of the vast array of F-numbers. The continuum
problem is now widely considered insoluble. Cantor’s conception of set is often
taken to admit the whole universe of sets as a set, thus engendering
contradiction, in particular in the form of Cantor’s paradox. For Cantor’s
theorem would say that the power-set of the universe must be bigger than it, while,
since this powerset is a set of sets, it must be contained in the universal
set, and thus can be no bigger. However, it follows from Cantor’s early 3
considerations of what he called the “absolute infinite” that none of the
collections discovered later to be at the base of the paradoxes can be proper
sets. Moreover, correspondence with Hilbert in 7 and Dedekind in 9 see Cantor,
Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen Inhalts, 2 shows
clearly that Cantor was well aware that contradictions will arise if such
collections are treated as ordinary sets.
“What is not finite.” “I know that there
are infinitely many stars”an example of a stupid thing to say by the man in the
street. apeiron, Grecian term meaning ‘the boundless’ or ‘the unlimited’,
which evolved to signify ‘the infinite’. Anaximander introduced the term to
philosophy by saying that the source of all things was apeiron. There is some
disagreement about whether he meant by this the spatially antinomy apeiron unbounded,
the temporally unbounded, or the qualitatively indeterminate. It seems likely
that he intended the term to convey the first meaning, but the other two senses
also happen to apply to the spatially unbounded. After Anaximander, Anaximenes
declared as his first principle that air is boundless, and Xenophanes made his
flat earth extend downward without bounds, and probably outward horizontally
without limit as well. Rejecting the tradition of boundless principles,
Parmenides argued that “what-is” must be held within determinate boundaries.
But his follower Melissus again argued that what-is must be boundless in both time and space for it can have no beginning or end. Another
follower of Parmenides, Zeno of Elea, argued that if there are many substances,
antinomies arise, including the consequences that substances are both limited
and unlimited apeira in number, and that they are so small as not to have size
and so large as to be unlimited in size. Rejecting monism, Anaxagoras argued
for an indefinite number of elements that are each unlimited in size, and the
Pythagorean Philolaus made limiters perainonta and unlimiteds apeira the
principles from which all things are composed. The atomists Leucippus and
Democritus conceived of a boundless universe, partly full of an infinite number
of atoms and partly void; and in the universe are countless apeiroi worlds.
Finally Aristotle arrived at an abstract understanding of the apeiron as “the
infinite,” claiming to settle paradoxes about the boundless by allowing for
real quantities to be infinitely divisible potentially, but not actually
Physics III.48. The development of the notion of the apeiron shows how Grecian
philosophers evolved ever more abstract philosophical ideas from relatively
concrete conceptions. Infinity -- Grice thougth
that “There are infinitely many stars” was a stupid thing to say -- diagonal
procedure, a method, originated by Cantor, for showing that there are infinite
sets that cannot be put in one-to-one correspondence with the set of natural
numbers i.e., enumerated. For example, the method can be used to show that the
set of real numbers x in the interval 0 ‹ x m 1 is not enumerable. Suppose x0,
x1, x2, . . . were such an enumeration x0 is the real correlated with 0; x1,
the real correlated with 1; and so on. Then consider the list formed by
replacing each real in the enumeration with the unique non-terminating decimal
fraction representing it: The first decimal fraction represents x0; the second,
x1; and so on. By diagonalization we select the decimal fraction shown by the
arrows: and change each digit xnn, taking care to avoid a terminating decimal.
This fraction is not on our list. For it differs from the first in the tenths
place, from the second in the hundredths place, and from the third in the
thousandths place, and so on. Thus the real it represents is not in the
supposed enumeration. This contradicts the original assumption. The idea can be
put more elegantly. Let f be any function such that, for each natural number n,
fn is a set of natural numbers. Then there is a set S of natural numbers such
that n 1 S S n 2 fn. It is obvious that, for each n, fn & S. Infinity -- eternal return, the doctrine that
the same events, occurring in the same sequence and involving the same things,
have occurred infinitely many times in the past and will occur infinitely many
times in the future. Attributed most notably to the Stoics and Nietzsche, the
doctrine is antithetical to philosophical and religious viewpoints that claim
that the world order is unique, contingent in part, and directed toward some
goal. The Stoics interpret eternal return as the consequence of perpetual
divine activity imposing exceptionless causal principles on the world in a
supremely rational, providential way. The world, being the best possible, can
only be repeated endlessly. The Stoics do not explain why the best world cannot
be everlasting, making repetition unnecessary. It is not clear whether
Nietzsche asserted eternal return as a cosmological doctrine or only as a
thought experiment designed to confront one with the authenticity of one’s
life: would one affirm that life even if one were consigned to live it over
again without end? On either interpretation, Nietzsche’s version, like the
Stoic version, stresses the inexorability and necessary interconnectedness of
all things and events, although unlike the Stoic version, it rejects divine
providence. infinitary logic, the logic
of expressions of infinite length. Quine has advanced the claim that firstorder
logic (FOL) is the language of science, a position accepted by many of his
followers. Howinferential justification infinitary logic 428 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 428 ever, many important notions of mathematics and
science are not expressible in FOL. The notion of finiteness, e.g., is central
in mathematics but cannot be expressed within FOL. There is no way to express
such a simple, precise claim as ‘There are only finitely many stars’ in FOL.
This and related expressive limitations in FOL seriously hamper its
applicability to the study of mathematics and have led to the study of stronger
logics. There have been various approaches to getting around the limitations by
the study of so-called strong logics, including second-order logic (where one
quantifies over sets or properties, not just individuals), generalized
quantifiers (where one adds quantifiers in addition to the usual ‘for all’ and
‘there exists’), and branching quantifiers (where notions of independence of
variables is introduced). One of the most fruitful methods has been the
introduction of idealized “infinitely long” statements. For example, the above
statement about the stars would be formalized as an infinite disjunction: there
is at most one star, or there are at most two stars, or there are at most three
stars, etc. Each of these disjuncts is expressible in FOL. The expressive
limitations in FOL are closely linked with Gödel’s famous completeness and
incompleteness theorems. These results show, among other things, that any
attempt to systematize the laws of logic is going to be inadequate, one way or
another. Either it will be confined to a language with expressive limitations,
so that these notions cannot even be expressed, or else, if they can be
expressed, then an attempt at giving an effective listing of axioms and rules
of inference for the language will fall short. In infinitary logic, the rules
of inference can have infinitely many premises, and so are not effectively
presentable. Early work in infinitary logic used cardinality as a guide:
whether or not a disjunction, conjunction, or quantifier string was permitted
had to do only with the cardinality of the set in question. It turned out that
the most fruitful of these logics was the language with countable conjunctions
and finite strings of first-order quantifiers. This language had further
refinements to socalled admissible languages, where more refined set-theoretic
considerations play a role in determining what counts as a formula. Infinitary
languages are also connected with strong axioms of infinity, statements that do
not follow from the usual axioms of set theory but for which one has other
evidence that they might well be true, or at least consistent. In particular,
compact cardinals are infinite cardinal numbers where the analogue of the
compactness theorem of FOL generalizes to the associated infinitary language.
These cardinals have proven to be very important in modern set theory. During
the 1990s, some infinitary logics played a surprising role in computer science.
By allowing arbitrarily long conjunctions and disjunctions, but only finitely
many variables (free or bound) in any formula, languages with attractive
closure properties were found that allowed the kinds of inductive procedures of
computer science, procedures not expressible in FOL. -- infinite regress
argument, a distinctively philosophical kind of argument purporting to show
that a thesis is defective because it generates an infinite series when either
(form A) no such series exists or (form B) were it to exist, the thesis would
lack the role (e.g., of justification) that it is supposed to play. The mere
generation of an infinite series is not objectionable. It is misleading
therefore to use ‘infinite regress’ (or ‘regress’) and ‘infinite series’
equivalently. For instance, both of the following claims generate an infinite
series: (1) every natural number has a successor that itself is a natural
number, and (2) every event has a causal predecessor that itself is an event.
Yet (1) is true (arguably, necessarily true), and (2) may be true for all that
logic can say about the matter. Likewise, there is nothing contrary to logic
about any of the infinite series generated by the suppositions that (3) every
free act is the consequence of a free act of choice; (4) every intelligent
operation is the result of an intelligent mental operation; (5) whenever
individuals x and y share a property F there exists a third individual z which
paradigmatically has F and to which x and y are somehow related (as copies, by
participation, or whatnot); or (6) every generalization from experience is
inductively inferable from experience by appeal to some other generalization
from experience. What Locke (in the Essay concerning Human Understanding)
objects to about the theory of free will embodied in (3) and Ryle (in The Concept
of Mind) objects to about the “intellectualist leginfinite, actual infinite
regress argument 429 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 429 end” embodied in
(4) can therefore be only that it is just plain false as a matter of fact that
we perform an infinite number of acts of choice or operations of the requisite
kinds. In effect their infinite regress arguments are of form A: they argue
that the theories concerned must be rejected because they falsely imply that
such infinite series exist. Arguably the infinite regress arguments employed by
Plato (in the Parmenides) regarding his own theory of Forms and by Popper (in
the Logic of Scientific Discovery) regarding the principle of induction
proposed by Mill, are best construed as having form B, their objections being
less to (5) or (6) than to their epistemic versions: (5*) that we can
understand how x and y can share a property F only if we understand that there
exists a third individual (the “Form” z) which paradigmatically has F and to
which x and y are related; and (6*) that since the principle of induction must
itself be a generalization from experience, we are justified in accepting it
only if it can be inferred from experience by appeal to a higherorder, and
justified, inductive principle. They are arguing that because the series
generated by (5) and (6) are infinite, the epistemic enlightenment promised by
(5*) and (6*) will forever elude us. When successful, infinite regress
arguments can show us that certain sorts of explanation, understanding, or justification
are will-o’-thewisps. As Passmore has observed (in Philosophical Reasoning)
there is an important sense of ‘explain’ in which it is impossible to explain
predication. We cannot explain x’s and y’s possession of the common property F
by saying that they are called by the same name (nominalism) or fall under the
same concept (conceptualism) any more than we can by saying that they are
related to the same form (Platonic realism), since each of these is itself a
property that x and y are supposed to have in common. Likewise, it makes no
sense to try to explain why anything at all exists by invoking the existence of
something else (such as the theist’s God). The general truths that things
exist, and that things may have properties in common, are “brute facts” about
the way the world is. Some infinite regress objections fail because they are
directed at “straw men.” Bradley’s regress argument against the pluralist’s
“arrangement of given facts into relations and qualities,” from which he
concludes that monism is true, is a case in point. He correctly argues that if
one posits the existence of two or more things, then there must be relations of
some sort between them, and then (given his covert assumption that these
relations are things) concludes that there must be further relations between
these relations ad infinitum. Bradley’s regress misfires because a pluralist
would reject his assumption. Again, some regress arguments fail because they
presume that any infinite series is vicious. Aquinas’s regress objection to an
infinite series of movers, from which he concludes that there must be a prime
mover, involves this sort of confusion. -- infinity, in set theory, the
property of a set whereby it has a proper subset whose members can be placed in
one-to-one correspondence with all the members of the set, as the even integers
can be so arranged in respect to the natural numbers by the function f(x) =
x/2, namely: Devised by Richard Dedekind in defiance of the age-old intuition
that no part of a thing can be as large as the thing, this set-theoretical
definition of ‘infinity’, having been much acclaimed by philosophers like
Russell as a model of conceptual analysis that philosophers were urged to
emulate, can elucidate the putative infinity of space, time, and even God, his
power, wisdom, etc. If a set’s being denumerablei.e., capable of having its
members placed in one-to-one correspondence with the natural numberscan well
appear to define much more simply what the infinity of an infinite set is,
Cantor exhibited the real numbers (as expressed by unending decimal expansions)
as a counterexample, showing them to be indenumerable by means of his famous
diagonal argument. Suppose all the real numbers between 0 and 1 are placed in
one-to-one correspondence with the natural numbers, thus: Going down the
principal diagonal, we can construct a new real number, e.g., .954 . . . , not
found in the infinite “square array.” The most important result in set theory,
Cantor’s theorem, is denied its full force by the maverick followers infinity
infinity 430 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 430 of Skolem, who appeal to
the fact that, though the real numbers constructible in any standard axiomatic
system will be indenumerable relative to the resources of the system, they can
be seen to be denumerable when viewed from outside it. Refusing to accept the
absolute indenumerability of any set, the Skolemites, in relativizing the
notion to some system, provide one further instance of the allure of
relativism. More radical still are the nominalists who, rejecting all abstract
entities and sets in particular, might be supposed to have no use for Cantor’s
theorem. Not so. Assume with Democritus that there are infinitely many of his
atoms, made of adamant. Corresponding to each infinite subset of these atoms
will be their mereological sum or “fusion,” namely a certain quantity of
adamant. Concrete entities acceptable to the nominalist, these quantities can
be readily shown to be indenumerable. Whether Cantor’s still higher infinities
beyond F1 admit of any such nominalistic realization remains a largely
unexplored area. Aleph-zero or F0 being taken to be the transfinite number of
the natural numbers, there are then F1 real numbers (assuming the continuum
hypothesis), while the power set of the reals has F2 members, and the power set
of that F3 members, etc. In general, K2 will be said to have a greater number
(finite or transfinite) of members than K1 provided the members of K1 can be
put in one-to-one correspondence with some proper subset of K2 but not vice
versa. Skepticism regarding the higher infinities can trickle down even to F0,
and if both Aristotle and Kant, the former in his critique of Zeno’s paradoxes,
the latter in his treatment of cosmological antinomies, reject any actual, i.e.
completed, infinite, in our time Dummett’s return to verificationism, as
associated with the mathematical intuitionism of Brouwer, poses the keenest
challenge. Recognition-transcendent sentences like ‘The total number of stars
is infinite’ are charged with violating the intersubjective conditions required
for a speaker of a language to manifest a grasp of their meaning. Strawson,
or Grice’s favourite informalist: THE INFORMALISTSA Group under which Grice
situated his post-generational Strawson and his pre-generational Ryle. informal
fallacy, an error of reasoning or tactic of argument that can be used to
persuade someone with whom you are reasoning that your argument is correct when
really it is not. The standard treatment of the informal fallacies in logic textbooks
draws heavily on Aristotle’s list, but there are many variants, and new
fallacies have often been added, some of which have gained strong footholds in
the textbooks. The word ‘informal’ indicates that these fallacies are not
simply localized faults or failures in the given propositions (premises and
conclusion) of an argument to conform to a standard of semantic correctness
(like that of deductive logic), but are misuses of the argument in relation to
a context of reasoning or type of dialogue that an arguer is supposed to be
engaged in. Informal logic is the subfield of logical inquiry that deals with
these fallacies. Typically, informal fallacies have a pragmatic (practical)
aspect relating to how an argument is being used, and also a dialectical
aspect, pertaining to a context of dialoguenormally an exchange between two
participants in a discussion. Both aspects are major concerns of informal
logic. Logic textbooks classify informal fallacies in various ways, but no
clear and widely accepted system of classification has yet become established.
Some textbooks are very inventive and prolific, citing many different
fallacies, including novel and exotic ones. Others are more conservative,
sticking with the twenty or so mainly featured in or derived from Aristotle’s
original treatment, with a few widely accepted additions. The paragraphs below
cover most of these “major” or widely featured fallacies, the ones most likely
to be encountered by name in the language of everyday educated conversation. The
genetic fallacy is the error of drawing an inappropriate conclusion about the
goodness or badness of some property of a thing from the goodness or badness of
some property of the origin of that thing. For example, ‘This medication was
derived from a plant that is poisonous; therefore, even though my physician
advises me to take it, I conclude that it would be very bad for me if I took
it.’ The error is inappropriately arguing from the origin of the medication to
the conclusion that it must be poisonous in any form or situation. The genetic
fallacy is often construed very broadly making it coextensive with the personal
attack type of argument (see the description of argumentum ad hominem below)
that condemns a prior argument by condemning its source or proponent.
Argumentum ad populum (argument to the people) is a kind of argument that uses
appeal to popular sentiments to support a conclusion. Sometimes called “appeal
to the gallery” or “appeal to popular pieties” or even “mob appeal,” this kind
of argument has traditionally been portrayed as fallacious. However, there
infinity, axiom of informal fallacy 431 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 431
need be nothing wrong with appealing to popular sentiments in argument, so long
as their evidential value is not exaggerated. Even so, such a tactic can be
fallacious when the attempt to arouse mass enthusiasms is used as a substitute
to cover for a failure to bring forward the kind of evidence that is properly
required to support one’s conclusion. Argumentum ad misericordiam (argument to
pity) is a kind of argument that uses an appeal to pity, sympathy, or
compassion to support its conclusion. Such arguments can have a legitimate
place in some discussionse.g., in appeals for charitable donations. But they
can also put emotional pressure on a respondent in argument to try to cover up
a weak case. For example, a student who does not have a legitimate reason for a
late assignment might argue that if he doesn’t get a high grade, his
disappointed mother might have a heart attack. The fallacy of composition is
the error of arguing from a property of parts of a whole to a property of the
wholee.g., ‘The important parts of this machine are light; therefore this
machine is light.’ But a property of the parts cannot always be transferred to
the whole. In some cases, examples of the fallacy of composition are arguments
from all the parts to a whole, e.g. ‘Everybody in the country pays her debts.
Therefore the country pays its debts.’ The fallacy of division is the converse
of that of composition: the error of arguing from a property of the whole to a
property of its partse.g., ‘This machine is heavy; therefore all the parts of
this machine are heavy.’ The problem is that the property possessed by the
whole need not transfer to the parts. The fallacy of false cause, sometimes
called post hoc, ergo propter hoc (after this, therefore because of this), is
the error of arguing that because two events are correlated with one another,
especially when they vary together, the one is the cause of the other. For
example, there might be a genuine correlation between the stork population in
certain areas of Europe and the human birth rate. But it would be an error to
conclude, on that basis alone, that the presence of storks causes babies to be
born. In general, however, correlation is good, if sometimes weak, evidence for
causation. The problem comes in when the evidential strength of the correlation
is exaggerated as causal evidence. The apparent connection could just be
coincidence, or due to other factors that have not been taken into account,
e.g., some third factor that causes both the events that are correlated with
each other. The fallacy of secundum quid (neglecting qualifications) occurs
where someone is arguing from a general rule to a particular case, or vice
versa. One version of it is arguing from a general rule while overlooking or
suppressing legitimate exceptions. This kind of error has also often been
called the fallacy of accident. An example would be the argument ‘Everyone has the
right to freedom of speech; therefore it is my right to shout “Fire” in this
crowded theater if I want to.’ The other version of secundum quid, sometimes
also called the fallacy of converse accident, or the fallacy of hasty
generalization, is the error of trying to argue from a particular case to a
general rule that does not properly fit that case. An example would be the
argument ‘Tweetie [an ostrich] is a bird that does not fly; therefore birds do
not fly’. The fault is the failure to recognize or acknowledge that Tweetie is
not a typical bird with respect to flying. Argumentum consensus gentium
(argument from the consensus of the nations) is a kind that appeals to the
common consent of mankind to support a conclusion. Numerous philosophers and
theologians in the past have appealed to this kind of argument to support
conclusions like the existence of God and the binding character of moral
principles. For example, ‘Belief in God is practically universal among human
beings past and present; therefore there is a practical weight of presumption
in favor of the truth of the proposition that God exists’. A version of the
consensus gentium argument represented by this example has sometimes been put
forward in logic textbooks as an instance of the argumentum ad populum
(described above) called the argument from popularity: ‘Everybody believes
(accepts) P as true; therefore P is true’. If interpreted as applicable in all
cases, the argument from popularity is not generally sound, and may be regarded
as a fallacy. However, if regarded as a presumptive inference that only applies
in some cases, and as subject to withdrawal where evidence to the contrary
exists, it can sometimes be regarded as a weak but plausible argument, useful
to serve as a provisional guide to prudent action or reasoned commitment.
Argumentum ad hominem (literally, argument against the man) is a kind of
argument that uses a personal attack against an arguer to refute her argument.
In the abusive or personal variant, the character of the arguer (especially
character for veracity) is attacked; e.g., ‘You can’t believe what Smith sayshe
is a liar’. In evaluating testimony (e.g., in legal cross-examination),
attacking an arguer’s character can be legitimate in some cases. Also in
political debate, character can be a legitimate issue. However, ad hominem
arguinformal fallacy informal fallacy 432 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page
432 ments are commonly used fallaciously in attacking an opponent unfairlye.g.,
where the attack is not merited, or where it is used to distract an audience
from more relevant lines of argument. In the circumstantial variant, an
arguer’s personal circumstances are claimed to be in conflict with his
argument, implying that the arguer is either confused or insincere; e.g., ‘You
don’t practice what you preach’. For example, a politician who has once
advocated not raising taxes may be accused of “flip-flopping” if he himself
subsequently favors legislation to raise taxes. This type of argument is not
inherently fallacious, but it can go badly wrong, or be used in a fallacious
way, for example if circumstances changed, or if the alleged conflict was less
serious than the attacker claimed. Another variant is the “poisoning the well”
type of ad hominem argument, where an arguer is said to have shown no regard
for the truth, the implication being that nothing he says henceforth can ever
be trusted as reliable. Yet another variant of the ad hominem argument often
cited in logic textbooks is the tu quoque (you-too reply), where the arguer attacked
by an ad hominem argument turns around and says, “What about you? Haven’t you
ever lied before? You’re just as bad.” Still another variant is the bias type
of ad hominem argument, where one party in an argument charges the other with
not being honest or impartial or with having hidden motivations or personal
interests at stake. Argumentum ad baculum (argument to the club) is a kind of
argument that appeals to a threat or to fear in order to support a conclusion,
or to intimidate a respondent into accepting it. Ad baculum arguments often
take an indirect form; e.g., ‘If you don’t do this, harmful consequences to you
might follow’. In such cases the utterance can often be taken as a threat. Ad
baculum arguments are not inherently fallacious, because appeals to threatening
or fearsome sanctionse.g., harsh penalties for drunken drivingare not
necessarily failures of critical argumentation. But because ad baculum
arguments are powerful in eliciting emotions, they are often used persuasively
as sophistical tactics in argumentation to avoid fulfilling the proper
requirements of a burden of proof. Argument from authority is a kind of
argument that uses expert opinion (de facto authority) or the pronouncement of
someone invested with an institutional office or title (de jure authority) to
support a conclusion. As a practical but fallible method of steering discussion
toward a presumptive conclusion, the argument from authority can be a
reasonable way of shifting a burden of proof. However, if pressed too hard in a
discussion or portrayed as a better justification for a conclusion than the
evidence warrants, it can become a fallacious argumentum ad verecundiam (see
below). It should be noted, however, that arguments based on expert opinions
are widely accepted both in artificial intelligence and everyday argumentation
as legitimate and sound under the right conditions. Although arguments from
authority have been strongly condemned during some historical periods as
inherently fallacious, the current climate of opinion is to think of them as
acceptable in some cases, even if they are fallible arguments that can easily
go wrong or be misused by sophistical persuaders. Argumentum ad judicium
represents a kind of knowledge-based argumentation that is empirical, as
opposed to being based on an arguer’s personal opinion or viewpoint. In modern
terminology, it apparently refers to an argument based on objective evidence,
as opposed to somebody’s subjective opinion. The term appears to have been
invented by Locke to contrast three commonly used kinds of arguments and a
fourth special type of argument. The first three types of argument are based on
premises that the respondent of the argument is taken to have already accepted.
Thus these can all be called “personal” in nature. The fourth kind of
argumentargumentum ad judiciumdoes not have to be based on what some person
accepts, and so could perhaps be called “impersonal.” Locke writes that the
first three kinds of arguments can dispose a person for the reception of truth,
but cannot help that person to the truth. Only the argumentum ad judicium can
do that. The first three types of arguments come from “my shamefacedness,
ignorance or error,” whereas the argumentum ad judicium “comes from proofs and
arguments and light arising from the nature of things themselves.” The first
three types of arguments have only a preparatory function in finding the truth
of a matter, whereas the argumentum ad judicium is more directly instrumental
in helping us to find the truth. Argumentum ad verecundiam (argument to
reverence or respect) is the fallacious use of expert opinion in argumentation
to try to persuade someone to accept a conclusion. In the Essay concerning
Human Understanding (1690) Locke describes such arguments as tactics of trying
to prevail on the assent of someone by portraying him as irreverent or immodest
if he does not readily yield to the authority of some learned informal opinion
cited. Locke does not claim, however, that all appeals to expert authority in
argument are fallacious. They can be reasonable if used judiciously. Argumentum
ad ignorantiam (argument to ignorance) takes the following form: a proposition
a is not known or proved to be true (false); therefore A is false (true). It is
a negative type of knowledge-based or presumptive reasoning, generally not
conclusive, but it is nevertheless often non-fallacious in
balance-of-consideration cases where the evidence is inconclusive to resolve a
disputed question. In such cases it is a kind of presumption-based
argumentation used to advocate adopting a conclusion provisionally, in the
absence of hard knowledge that would determine whether the conclusion is true
or false. An example would be: Smith has not been heard from for over seven
years, and there is no evidence that he is alive; therefore it may be presumed
(for the purpose of settling Smith’s estate) that he is dead. Arguments from
ignorance ought not to be pressed too hard or used with too strong a degree of
confidence. An example comes from the U.S. Senate hearings in 1950, in which
Senator Joseph McCarthy used case histories to argue that certain persons in
the State Department should be considered Communists. Of one case he said, “I
do not have much information on this except the general statement of the agency
that there is nothing in the files to disprove his Communist connections.” The
strength of any argument from ignorance depends on the thoroughness of the
search made. The argument from ignorance can be used to shift a burden of proof
merely on the basis of rumor, innuendo, or false accusations, instead of real
evidence. Ignoratio elenchi (ignorance of refutation) is the traditional name,
following Aristotle, for the fault of failing to keep to the point in an
argument. The fallacy is also called irrelevant conclusion or missing the
point. Such a failure of relevance is essentially a failure to keep closely
enough to the issue under discussion. Suppose that during a criminal trial, the
prosecutor displays the victim’s bloody shirt and argues at length that murder
is a horrible crime. The digression may be ruled irrelevant to the question at
issue of whether the defendant is guilty of murder. Alleged failures of this
type in argumentation are sometimes quite difficult to judge fairly, and a
ruling should depend on the type of discussion the participants are supposed to
be engaged in. In some cases, conventions or institutional rules of
proceduree.g. in a criminal trialare aids to determining whether a line of
argumentation should be judged relevant or not. Petitio principii (asking to be
granted the “principle” or issue of the discussion to be proved), also called
begging the question, is the fallacy of improperly arguing in a circle.
Circular reasoning should not be presumed to be inherently fallacious, but can
be fallacious where the circular argument has been used to disguise or cover up
a failure to fulfill a burden of proof. The problem arises where the conclusion
that was supposed to be proved is presumed within the premises to be granted by
the respondent of the argument. Suppose I ask you to prove that this bicycle
(the ownership of which is subject to dispute) belongs to Hector, and you
reply, “All the bicycles around here belong to Hector.” The problem is that
without independent evidence that shows otherwise, the premise that all the
bicycles belong to Hector takes for granted that this bicycle belongs to
Hector, instead of proving it by properly fulfilling the burden of proof. The
fallacy of many questions (also called the fallacy of complex question) is the
tactic of packing unwarranted presuppositions into a question so that any
direct answer given by the respondent will trap her into conceding these
presuppositions. The classical case is the question, “Have you stopped beating
your spouse?” No matter how the respondent answers, yes or no, she concedes the
presuppositions that (a) she has a spouse, and (b) she has beaten that spouse
at some time. Where one or both of these presumptions are unwarranted in the
given case, the use of this question is an instance of the fallacy of many
questions. The fallacy of equivocation occurs where an ambiguous word has been
used more than once in an argument in such a way that it is plausible to
interpret it in one way in one instance of its use and in another way in
another instance. Such an argument may seem persuasive if the shift in the
context of use of the word makes these differing interpretations plausible.
Equivocation, however, is generally seriously deceptive only in longer
sequences of argument where the meaning of a word or phrase shifts subtly but
significantly. A simplistic example will illustrate the gist of the fallacy:
‘The news media should present all the facts on anything that is in the public
interest; the public interest in lives of movie stars is intense; therefore the
news media should present all the facts on the private lives of movie stars’.
This argument goes from plausible premises to an implausible conclusion by
trading on the ambiguity of ‘public interest’. In one sense informal fallacy
informal fallacy 434 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 434 it means ‘public
benefit’ while in another sense it refers to something more akin to curiosity.
Amphiboly (double arrangement) is a type of traditional fallacy (derived from
Aristotle’s list of fallacies) that refers to the use of syntactically
ambiguous sentences like ‘Save soap and waste paper’. Although the logic
textbooks often cite examples of such sentences as fallacies, they have never
made clear how they could be used to deceive in a serious discussion. Indeed,
the example cited is not even an argument, but simply an ambiguous sentence. In
cases of some advertisements like ‘Two pizzas for one special price’, however,
one can see how the amphiboly seriously misleads readers into thinking they are
being offered two pizzas for the regular price of one. Accent is the use of
shifting stress or emphasis in speech as a means of deception. For example, if
a speaker puts stress on the word ‘created’ in ‘All men were created equal’ it
suggests (by implicaturum) the opposite proposition to ‘All men are equal’,
namely ‘Not all men are (now) equal’. The oral stress allows the speaker to
covertly suggest an inference the hearer is likely to draw, and to escape
commitment to the conclusion suggested by later denying he said it. The
slippery slope argument, in one form, counsels against some contemplated action
(or inaction) on the ground that, once taken, it will be a first step in a
sequence of events that will be difficult to resist and will (or may or must)
lead to some dangerous (or undesirable or disastrous) outcome in the end. It is
often argued, e.g., that once you allow euthanasia in any form, such as the
withdrawal of heroic treatments of dying patients in hospitals, then (through
erosion of respect for human life), you will eventually wind up with a
totalitarian state where old, feeble, or politically troublesome individuals
are routinely eliminated. Some slippery slope arguments can be reasonable, but
they should not be put forward in an exaggerated way, supported with
insufficient evidence, or used as a scare tactic.
informatum“What has ‘forma’
to do with ‘inform’?”Grice. While etymologically it means ‘to mould,’ Lewis and
Short render ‘informare’ as “to inform, instruct,
educate (syn.: “instruere, instituere): artes quibus aetas puerilis ad
humanitatem informari solet,” Cic. Arch. 3, 4: “animus a natura bene
informatus,” formed, id. Off. 1, 4, 13. I. e. “the soul is well informed by
nature.” Informativusinformational. Grice distinguishes between the
indicative and the informational. “Surely it is stupid to inform myself, but
not Strawson, that it is raining. Grammarians don’t care, but I do!”
information theory, also called communication theory, a primarily mathematical
theory of communication. Prime movers in its development include Claude
Shannon, H. Nyquist, R. V. L. Hartley, Norbert Wiener, Boltzmann, and Szilard.
Original interests in the theory were largely theoretical or applied to
telegraphy and telephony, and early development clustered around engineering
problems in such domains. Philosophers (Bar-Hillel, Dretske, and Sayre, among
others) are mainly interested in information theory as a source for developing
a semantic theory of information and meaning. The mathematical theory has been
less concerned with the details of how a message acquires meaning and more
concerned with what Shannon called the “fundamental problem of
communication”reproducing at one point either exactly or approximately a
message (that already has a meaning) selected at another point. Therefore, the
two interests in informationthe mathematical and the philosophicalhave remained
largely orthogonal. Information is an objective (mind-independent) entity. It
can be generated or carried by messages (words, sentences) or other products of
cognizers (interpreters). Indeed, communication theory focuses primarily on
conditions involved in the generation and transmission of coded (linguistic)
messages. However, almost any event can (and usually does) generate information
capable of being encoded or transmitted. For example, Colleen’s acquiring red
spots can contain information about Colleen’s having the measles and graying
hair can carry information about her grandfather’s aging. This information can
be encoded into messages about measles or aging (respectively) and transmitted,
but the information would exist independently of its encoding or transmission.
That is, this information would be generated (under the right conditions) by
occurrence of the measles-induced spots and the age-induced graying
themselvesregardless of anyone’s actually noticing. This objective feature of
information explains its potential for epistemic and semantic development by
philosophers and cognitive scientists. For example, in its epistemic dimension,
a single (event, message, or Colleen’s spots) that contains informal logic
information theory 435 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 435 (carries) the
information that Colleen has the measles is something from which one (mom,
doctor) can come to know that Colleen has the measles. Generally, an event
(signal) that contains the information that p is something from which one can
come to know that p is the caseprovided that one’s knowledge is indeed based on
the information that p. Since information is objective, it can generate what we
want from knowledgea fix on the way the world objectively is configured. In its
semantic dimension, information can have intentionality or aboutness. What is
happening at one place (thermometer reading rising in Colleen’s mouth) can
carry information about what is happening at another place (Colleen’s body
temperature rising). The fact that messages (or mental states, for that matter)
can contain information about what is happening elsewhere, suggests an exciting
prospect of tracing the meaning of a message (or of a thought) to its
informational origins in the environment. To do this in detail is what a
semantic theory of information is about. The mathematical theory of information
is purely concerned with information in its quantitative dimension. It deals
with how to measure and transmit amounts of information and leaves to others
the work of saying what (how) meaning or content comes to be associated with a
signal or message. In regard to amounts of information, we need a way to
measure how much information is generated by an event (or message) and how to
represent that amount. Information theory provides the answer. Since
information is an objective entity, the amount of information associated with
an event is related to the objective probability (likelihood) of the event.
Events that are less likely to occur generate more information than those more
likely to occur. Thus, to discover that the toss of a fair coin came up heads
contains more information than to discover this about the toss of a coin biased
(.8) toward heads. Or, to discover that a lie was knowingly broadcast by a
censored, state-run radio station, contains less information than that a lie
was knowingly broadcast by a non-censored, free radio station (say, the BBC). A
(perhaps surprising) consequence of associating amounts of information with
objective likelihoods of events is that some events generate no information at
all. That is, that 55 % 3125 or that water freezes at 0oC. (on a specific
occasion) generates no information at allsince these things cannot be otherwise
(their probability of being otherwise is zero). Thus, their occurrence
generates zero information. Shannon was seeking to measure the amount of
information generated by a message and the amount transmitted by its reception
(or about average amounts transmissible over a channel). Since his work, it has
become standard to think of the measure of information in terms of reductions
of uncertainty. Information is identified with the reduction of uncertainty or
elimination of possibilities represented by the occurrence of an event or state
of affairs. The amount of information is identified with how many possibilities
are eliminated. Although other measures are possible, the most convenient and
intuitive way that this quantity is standardly represented is as a logarithm
(to the base 2) and measured in bits (short for how many binary digits) needed
to represent binary decisions involved in the reduction or elimination of
possibilities. If person A chooses a message to send to person B, from among 16
equally likely alternative messages (say, which number came up in a fair
drawing from 16 numbers), the choice of one message would represent 4 bits of
information (16 % 24 or log2 16 % 4). Thus, to calculate the amount of
information generated by a selection from equally likely messages (signals,
events), the amount of information I of the message s is calculated I(s) %
logn. If there is a range of messages (s1 . . . sN) not all of which are
equally likely (letting (p (si) % the probability of any si’s occurrence), the
amount of information generated by the selection of any message si is
calculated I(si) % log 1/p(si) % –log p(si) [log 1/x % –log x] While each of
these formulas says how much information is generated by the selection of a specific
message, communication theory is seldom primarily interested in these measures.
Philosophers are interested, however. For if knowledge that p requires
receiving the information that p occurred, and if p’s occurrence represents 4
bits of information, then S would know that p occurred only if S received
information equal to (at least) 4 bits. This may not be sufficient for S to
know pfor S must receive the right amount of information in a non-deviant
causal way and S must be able to extract the content of the informationbut this
seems clearly necessary. Other measures of information of interest in
communication theory include the average information, or entropy, of a source,
information theory information theory 436 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page
436 I(s) % 9p(si) $ I(si), a measure for noise (the amount of information that
person B receives that was not sent by person A), and for equivocation (the
amount of information A wanted or tried to send to B that B did not receive).
These concepts from information theory and the formulas for measuring these
quantities of information (and others) provide a rich source of tools for
communication applications as well as philosophical applications. informed
consent, voluntary agreement in the light of relevant information, especially
by a patient to a medical procedure. An example would be consent to a specific
medical procedure by a competent adult patient who has an adequate
understanding of all the relevant treatment options and their risks. It is
widely held that both morality and law require that no medical procedures be
performed on competent adults without their informed consent. This doctrine of
informed consent has been featured in case laws since the 1950s, and has been a
focus of much discussion in medical ethics. Underwritten by a concern to
protect patients’ rights to self-determination and also by a concern with
patients’ well-being, the doctrine was introduced in an attempt to delineate
physicians’ duties to inform patients of the risks and benefits of medical
alternatives and to obtain their consent to a particular course of treatment or
diagnosis. Interpretation of the legitimate scope of the doctrine has focused
on a variety of issues concerning what range of patients is competent to give
consent and hence from which ones informed consent must be required; concerning
how much, how detailed, and what sort of information must be given to patients
to yield informed consent; and concerning what sorts of conditions are required
to ensure both that there is proper understanding of the information and that
consent is truly voluntary rather than unduly influenced by the institutional
authority of the physician.
IN-SCRIPTVM -- inscriptum -- inscriptionalism -- nominalism. While Grice pours scorn
on the American School of Latter-Day
Nominalists, nominalism, as used by Grice is possibly a momer. He
doesn’t mean Occam, and Occam did not use ‘nominalismus.’ “Terminimus’ at most.
So one has to be careful. The implicaturum is that the nominalist calls a
‘name’ what others shouldn’t. Mind,
Grice had two nominalist friends: S. N. Hamphsire (Scepticism and meaning”) and
A. M. Quinton, of the play group! In “Properties and classes,” for the Aristotelian
Society. And the best Oxford philosophical stylist, Bradley, is also a
nominalist. There are other, more specific arguments against universals.
One is that postulating such things leads to a vicious infinite regress. For
suppose there are universals, both monadic and relational, and that when an
entity instantiates a universal, or a group of entities instantiate a
relational universal, they are linked by an instantiation relation. Suppose now
that a instantiates
the universal F. Since
there are many things that instantiate many universals, it is plausible to
suppose that instantiation is a relational universal. But if instantiation is a
relational universal, when a instantiates F, a, F and
the instantiation relation are linked by an instantiation relation. Call this
instantiation relation i2 (and suppose it, as is plausible, to be
distinct from the instantiation relation (i1) that links a and F). Then
since i2 is
also a universal, it looks as if a, F, i1 and i2 will have to
be linked by another instantiation relation i3, and so on ad infinitum.
(This argument has its source in Bradley 1893, 27–8.)
IN-SINUATUM -- insinuatum: Cf. ‘indirectum’ Oddly, Ryle found an ‘insinuation’
abusive, which Russell found abusive. When McGuinness listed the abusive terms
by Gellner, ‘insinuation’ was one of them, so perhaps Grice should take note! insinuation
insinuate. The etymology is abscure. Certainly not Ciceronian. A bit of
linguistic botany, “E implicates that p”implicate to do duty for, in alphabetic
order: mean, suggest, hint, insinuate, indicate, implicitly convey, indirectly
convey, imply. Intransitive meaning "hint obliquely" is from
1560s. The problem is that Grice possibly used it transitively, with a
‘that’-clause. “Emissor E communicates that p, via insinuation,” i.e. E
insinuates that p.” In fact, there’s nothing odd with the ‘that’-clause
following ‘insinuate.’ Obviosuly, Grice will be saying that what is a mere
insinuation it is taken by Austin, Strawson, Hart or Hare or Hampshireas he
criticizes him in the “Mind” article on intention and certainty -- (to restrict
to mistakes by the play group) as part of the ‘analysans.’ `Refs. D. Holdcroft,
“Forms of indirect communication,” Journal of Rhetoric, H. P. Grice,
“Communicatum: directum-indirectum.”
Swinehead: “I like
Swineheadit sounds almost like Grice!”Grice. Merton school.
solubile -- insolubile: “As
opposed to the ‘piece-of-cake’ solubilia”Grice. A solubile is a piece of a
cake. An insolubile is a sentences embodying a semantic antinomy such as the
liar paradox. The insolubile is used by philosophers to analyze a self-nullifying
sentences, the possibility that every sentence implies that they are true, and
the relation between a communicatum and an animatum (psi). At first, Grice
focuses on nullification to explicate a sentence like ‘I am lying’ (“Mento.”
“Mendax”) which, when spoken, entails that the utterer “says nothing.” Grice:
“Bradwardine suggests that such a sentence as “Mento” signifies that it is at
once true and false, prompting Burleigh to argue that every sentences implies
that it is true.” “Swineshead uses the insolubile to distinguish between truth and
correspondence to reality.” While ‘This sentence is false’ is itself false, it
corresponds to reality, while its contradiction, ‘This sentence is not false,’
does not, although the latter is also false. “Wyclif uses the insolubile to
describe the senses (or implicatura) in which a sentence can be true, which led
to his belief in the reality of logical beings or entities of reason, a central
tenet of his realism.” “d’Ailly uses the insolubile to explain how the animatum
(or soul) differs from the communicatum, holding that there is no insoluble in
the soul, but that communication lends itself to the phenomenon by admitting a
single sentence corresponding to two distinct states of the soul. Grice: “Of
course that was Swine’s unEnglish overstatement, ‘unsolvable;’ everything is
solvable!” Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Liars at Oxford.”
IN-STITUTUM
-- institutumGrice
speaks of the institution of decision as the goal of conversation --
institution. (1) An organization such as a corporation or college. (2) A social
practice such as marriage or making promises. (3) A system of rules defining a
possible form of social organization, such as capitalist versus Communist
principles of economic exchange. In light of the power of institutions to shape
societies and individual lives, writers in professional ethics have explored
four main issues. First, what political and legal institutions are feasible,
just, and otherwise desirable (Plato, Republic; Rawls, A Theory of Justice)?
Second, how are values embedded in institutions through the constitutive rules
that define them (for example, “To promise is to undertake an obligation”), as
well as through regulatory rules imposed on them from outside, such that to
participate in institutions is a value-laden activity (Searle, Speech Acts,
1969)? Third, do institutions have collective responsibilities or are the only
responsibilities those of individuals, and in general how are the
responsibilities of individuals, institutions, and communities related? Fourth,
at a more practical level, how can we prevent institutions from becoming
corrupted by undue regard for money and power (MacIntyre, After Virtue, 1981)
and by patriarchal prejudices (Susan Moller Okin, Justice, Gender, and the
Family, 1989)? -- institutional theory of art, the view that something becomes
an artwork by virtue of occupying a certain position within the context of a set
of institutions. George Dickie originated this theory of art (Art and the
Aesthetic, 1974), which was derived loosely from Arthur Danto’s “The Artworld”
(Journal of Philosophy, 1964). In its original form it was the view that a work
of art is an artifact that has the status of candidate for appreciation
conferred upon it by some person acting on behalf of the art world. That is,
there are institutionssuch as museums, galleries, and journals and newspapers
that publish reviews and criticismand there are individuals who work within
those institutionscurators, directors, dealers, performers, criticswho decide,
by accepting objects or events for discussion and display, what is art and what
is not. The concept of artifactuality may be extended to include found art,
conceptual art, and other works that do not involve altering some preexisting
material, by holding that a use, or context for display, is sufficient to make
something into an artifact. This definition of art raises certain questions.
What determinesindependently of such notions as a concern with artwhether an
institution is a member of the art world? That is, is the definition ultimately
circular? What is it to accept something as a candidate for appreciation? Might
not this concept also threaten circularity, since there could be not only
artistic but also other kinds of appreciation?
instrumentum:
is
Grice an instrumentalist? According to C. Lord (“Griceian instrumentalism”) he
isbut he is not! Lord takes ‘tool’ literally. In Grice’s analysandum of the act
of the communicatum, Lord takes ‘x’ to be a ‘tool’ or instrument for the
production of a response in the emisor’s sendee. But is this the original Roman
meaning of ‘instrumentum’? Griceian aesthetic instrumetalism according to
Catherine Lord. instrumentalism, in its most common meaning, a kind of
anti-realistic view of scientific theories wherein theories are construed as
calculating devices or instruments for conveniently moving from a given set of
observations to a predicted set of observations. As such the theoretical
statements are not candidates for truth or reference, and the theories have no
ontological import. This view of theories is grounded in a positive distinction
between observation statements and theoretical statements, and the according of
privileged epistemic status to the former. The view was fashionable during the
era of positivism but then faded; it was recently revived, in large measure
owing to the genuinely perplexing character of quantum theories in physics.
’Instrumentalism’ has a different and much more general meaning associated with
the pragmatic epistemology of Dewey. Deweyan instrumentalism is a general
functional account of all concepts (scientific ones included) wherein the
epistemic status of concepts and the rationality status of actions are seen as
a function of their role in integrating, predicting, and controlling our
concrete interactions with our experienced world. There is no positivistic
distinction instantiation instrumentalism 438 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM
Page 438 between observation and theory, and truth and reference give way to
“warranted assertability.”
INTER-LEGO: intellectum: The noun is ‘intellectus.’ But what is understood is ‘the
intellectum’cf. ‘implicatum’ -- hile the ‘dianoia’ is the intellectus, the
‘intellectum’ is the Griceian diaphanous ‘what is understood.’ (dianoia): Grice
was fascinated by Cicero. “The way he managed to translate the Grecian ‘dia’ by
the ‘inter is genial!” As Short and Lewis have it, it’s from
“inter-legere,” to see into, perceive, understand. “intelligere,” originally meaning to comprehend, appeared
frequently in Cicero, then underwent a slippage in its passive form,
“intelligetur,” toward to understand, to communicate, to mean, ‘to give it to
be understood.’ What is understoodINTELLECTUM -- by an expression can be not
only its obvious sense but also something that is connoted, implied,
insinuated, IMPLICATED, as Grice would prefer. Verstand, corresponding to Greek
dianoia and Latin intellectio] Kant distinguished understanding from
sensibility and reason. While sensibility is receptive, understanding is
spontaneous. While understanding is concerned with the range of phenomena and
is empty without intuition, reason, which moves from judgment to judgment
concerning phenomena, is tempted to extend beyond the limits of experience to
generate fallacious inferences. Kant claimed that the main act of understanding
is judgment and called it a faculty of judgment. He claimed that there is an a
priori concept or category corresponding to each kind of judgment as its
logical function and that understanding is constituted by twelve categories.
Hence understanding is also a faculty of concepts. Understanding gives the
synthetic unity of appearance through the categories. It thus brings together
intuitions and concepts and makes experience possible. It is a lawgiver of
nature. Herder criticized Kant for separating sensibility and understanding.
Fichte and Hegel criticized him for separating understanding and reason. Some
neo-Kantians criticized him for deriving the structure of understanding from
the act of judgment. “Now we can reduce all acts of the understanding to
judgements, and the understanding may therefore be represented as a faculty of
judgement.” Kant, Critique of Pure Reason Intellectus -- dianoia, Grecian term for
the faculty of thought, specifically of drawing conclusions from assumptions
and of constructing and following arguments. The term may also designate the
thought that results from using this faculty. We would use dianoia to construct
a mathematical proof; in contrast, a being
if there is such a being it would be a god that could simply intuit the truth of the
theorem would use the faculty of intellectual intuition, noûs. In contrast with
noûs, dianoia is the distinctly human faculty of reason. Plato uses noûs and
dianoia to designate, respectively, the highest and second levels of the
faculties represented on the divided line Republic 511de. PLATO. E.C.H. dialectical argument dianoia
233 233 dichotomy paradox. Refs: Grice,
“The criteria of intelligence.”
IN-TENSVMEX-TENSVM -- intensionalism: Grice finds a way to relieve a predicate that is vacuous
from the embarrassing consequence of denoting or being satisfied by the empty
set. Grice exploits the nonvoidness of a predicate which is part of the
definition of the void predicate. Consider the vacuous predicate:‘... is
married to a daughter of an English queen and a pope.'The class '... is a
daugther of an English queen and a pope.'is co-extensive with the
predicate '... stands in relation to a sequence composed of the
class married to, daughters, English queens, and popes.'We correlate the
void predicate with the sequence composed of relation R, the set ‘married
to,’ the set ‘daughters,’ the set ‘English queens,’ and the set ‘popes.'Grice
uses this sequence, rather than the empty set, to determine the explanatory
potentiality of a void predicate. The admissibility of a nonvoid predicate
in an explanation of a possible phenomenon (why it would happen if it did
happen) may depends on the availability of a generalisation whithin which the
predicate specifies the antecedent condition. A non-trivial
generalisations of this sort is certainly available if derivable from some
further generalisation involving a less specific antecedent condition,
supported by an antecedent condition that is specified by means a nonvoid
predicate. intension,
the meaning or connotation of an expression, as opposed to its extension or
denotation, which consists of those things signified by the expression. The
intension of a declarative sentence is often taken to be a proposition and the
intension of a predicate expression (common noun, adjective) is often taken to
be a concept. For Frege, a predicate expression refers to a concept and the
intension or Sinn (“sense”) of a predicate expression is a mode of presentation
distinct from the concept. Objects like propositions or concepts that can be
the intension of terms are called intensional objects. (Note that ‘intensional’
is not the same word as ‘intentional’, although the two are related.) The
extension of a declarative sentence is often taken to be a state of affairs and
that of a predicate expression to be the set of objects that fall under the
concept which is the intension of the term. Extension is not the same as
reference. For example, the term ‘red’ may be said to refer to the property
redness but to have as its extension the set of all red things. Alternatively
properties and relations are sometimes taken to be intensional objects, but the
property redness is never taken to be part of the extension of the adjective
‘red’. intensionality, failure of extensionality. A linguistic context is
extensional if and only if the extension of the expression obtained by placing
any subexpression in that context is the same as the extension of the
expression obtained by placing in that context any subexpression with the same
extension as the first subexpression. Modal, intentional, and direct
quotational contexts are main instances of intensional contexts. Take, e.g.,
sentential contexts. The extension of a sentence is its truth or falsity
(truth-value). The extension of a definite description is what it is true of:
‘the husband of Xanthippe’ and ‘the teacher of Plato’ have the same extension,
for they are true of the same man, Socrates. Given this, it is easy to see that
‘Necessarily, . . . was married to Xanthippe’ is intensional, for ‘Necessarily,
the husband of Xanthippe was married to Xanthippe’ is true, but ‘Necessarily,
the teacher of Plato was married to Xanthippe’ is not. Other modal terms that
generate intensional contexts include ‘possibly’, ‘impossibly’, ‘essentially’,
‘contingently’, etc. Assume that Smith has heard of Xanthippe but not Plato.
‘Smith believes that . . . was married to Xanthippe’ is intensional, for ‘Smith
believes that the husband of Xanthippe was married to Xanthippe’ is true, but
‘Smith believes that the teacher of Plato was married to Xanthippe’ is not.
Other intentional verbs that generate intensional contexts include ‘know’,
‘doubt’, ‘wonder’, ‘fear’, ‘intend’, ‘state’, and ‘want’. ‘The fourth word in
“. . . “ has nine letters’ is intensional, for ‘The fourth word in “the husband
of Xanthippe” has nine letters’ is true but ‘the fourth word in “the teacher of
Plato” has nine letters’ is not. intensional logic, that part of deductive
logic which treats arguments whose validity or invalidity depends on strict
difference, or identity, of meaning. The denotation of a singular term (i.e., a
proper name or definite description), the class of things of which a predicate
is true, and the truth or falsity (the truth-value) of a sentence may be called
the extensions of these respective linguistic expressions. Their intensions are
their meanings strictly so called: the (individual) concept conveyed by the
singular term, the property expressed by the predicate, and the proposition
asserted by the sentence. The most extensively studied part of formal logic
deals largely with inferences turning only on extensions. One principle of extensional
logic is that if two singular terms have identical denotations, the
truth-values of corresponding sentences containing the terms are identical.
Thus the inference from ‘Bern is the capital of Switzerland’ to ‘You are in
Bern if and only if you are in the capital of Switzerland’ is valid. But this
is invalid: ‘Bern is the capital of Switzerland. Therefore, you believe that
you are in Bern if and only if you believe that you are in the capital of
Switzerland.’ For one may lack the belief instrumental rationality intensional
logic 439 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 439 that Bern is the capital of
Switzerland. It seems that we should distinguish between the intensional
meanings of ‘Bern’ and of ‘the capital of Switzerland’. One supposes that only
a strict identity of intension would license interchange in such a context, in
which they are in the scope of a propositional attitude. It has been questioned
whether the idea of an intension really applies to proper names, but parallel
examples are easily constructed that make similar use of the differences in the
meanings of predicates or of whole sentences. Quite generally, then, the
principle that expressions with the same extension may be interchanged with
preservation of extension of the containing expression, seems to fail for such
“intensional contexts.” The range of expressions producing such sensitive
contexts includes psychological verbs like ‘know’, ‘believe’, ‘suppose’,
‘assert’, ‘desire’, ‘allege’, ‘wonders whether’; expressions conveying modal
ideas such as necessity, possibility, and impossibility; some adverbs, e.g.
‘intentionally’; and a large number of other expressions’prove’, ‘imply’, ‘make
probable’, etc. Although reasoning involving some of these is well understood,
there is not yet general agreement on the best methods for dealing with
arguments involving many of these notions.
IN-TENSVUM -- intentionalism: Grice analyses ‘intend’ in two prongs; the first is a
willing-clause, and the second is a causal clause about the willing causing the
action. It’s a simplified account that he calls Prichardian because he relies
on ‘willin that.’ The intender intends that some action takes place. It does
not have to be an action by the intender. Cf. Suppes’s specific section. when
Anscombe comes out with her “Intention,” Grice’s Play Group does not know what
to do. Hampshire is almost finished with his “Thought and action” that came out
the following year. Grice is lecturing on how a “dispositional” reductive
analysis of ‘intention’ falls short of his favoured instrospectionalism. Had he
not fallen for an intention-based semantics (or strictly, an analysis of
"U means that p" in terms of U intends that p"), Grice
would be obsessed with an analysis of ‘intending that …’ James makes an
observation about the that-clause. I will that the distant table slides over
the floor toward me. It does not. The Anscombe Society. Irish-born Anscombe’s
views are often discussed by Oxonian philosophers. She brings Witters to the
Dreaming Spires, as it were. Grice is especially connected with Anscombes
reflections on intention. While he favoures an approach such as that of
Hampshire in Thought and Action, Grice borrows a few points from Anscombe, notably
that of direction of fit, originally Austin’s. Grice explicitly refers to
Anscombe in “Uncertainty,” and in his reminiscences he hastens to add that
Anscombe would never attend any of the Saturday mornings of the play group, as
neither does Dummett. The view of Ryle is standardly characterised as a
weaker or softer version of behaviourism According to this standard
interpretation, the view by Ryle is that a statements containin this or that
term relating to the ‘soul’ can be translated, without loss of meaning, into an
‘if’ utterance about what an agent does. So Ryle, on this account, is to be
construed as offering a dispositional analysis of a statement about the soul
into a statement about behaviour. It is conceded that Ryle does not confine a
description of what the agent does to purely physical behaviour—in terms, e. g.
of a skeletal or a muscular description. Ryle is happy to speak of a
full-bodied action like scoring a goal or paying a debt. But the soft
behaviourism attributed to Ryle still attempts an analysis or translation of
statement about the soul into this or that dispositional statement which is
itself construed as subjunctive if describing what the agent does. Even this
soft behaviourism fails. A description of the soul is not analysable or
translatable into a statement about behaviour or praxis even if this
is allowed to include a non-physical descriptions of action. The list of
conditions and possible behaviour is infinite since any one proffered
translation may be ‘defeated,’ as Hart and Hall would say, by a slight
alteration of the circumstances. The defeating condition in any particular case
may involve a reference to a fact about the agent’s soul, thereby rendering the
analysis circular. In sum, the standard interpretation of Ryle construes him as
offering a somewhat weakened form of reductive behaviourism whose reductivist
ambition, however weakened, is nonetheless futile. This characterisation
of Ryle’s programme is wrong. Although it is true that he is keen to point out
the disposition behind this or that concept about the soul, it would be wrong
to construe Ryle as offering a programme of analysis of a ‘soul’ predicate in
terms of an ‘if’ utterance. The relationship between a ‘soul’ predicate and the
‘if’ utterance with which he unpack it is other than that required by this kind
of analysis. It is helpful to keep in mind that Ryle’s target is the
official doctrine with its eschatological commitment. Ryle’s argument serves to
remind one that we have in a large number of cases ways of telling or settling
disputes, e. g., about someone’s character or intellect. If A disputes a
characterisation of Smith as willing that p, or judging that p, B may point to
what Smith says and does in defending the attribution, as well as to features
of the circumstances. But the practice of giving a reason of this kind to defend
or to challenge an ascription of a ‘soul’ predicates would be put under
substantial pressure if the official doctrine is correct. For Ryle to
remind us that we do, as a matter of fact, have a way of settling disputes
about whether Smith wills that he eat an apple is much weaker than saying that
the concept of willing is meaningless unless it is observable or verifiable; or
even that the successful application of a soul predicate requires that we have
a way of settling a dispute in every case. Showing that a concept is one for
which, in a large number of cases, we have an agreement-reaching procedure,
even if it do not always guarantee success, captures an important point,
however: it counts against any theory of, e. g., willing that would render it
unknowable in principle or in practice whether or not the concept is
correctly applied in every case. And this is precisely the problem with the
official doctrine (and is still a problem, with some of its progeny. Ryle
points out that there is a form of dilemma that pits the reductionist against
the dualist: those whose battle-cry is ‘nothing but…’ and those who insist
on ‘something else as well.’ Ryle attempts a dissolution of the dilemma by
rejecting the two horns; not by taking sides with either one, though part of
what dissolution requires in this case, as in others, is a description of how
each side is to be commended for seeing what the other side does not, and
criticised for failing to see what the other side does. The attraction of
behaviourism, Ryle reminds us, is simply that it does not insist on an occult
happening as the basis upon which a ‘soul’ term is given meaning, and points to
a perfectly observable criterion that is by and large employed when we are
called upon to defend or correct our employment of a ‘soul’ term. The problem
with behaviourism is that it has a too-narrow view both of what counts as
behaviour and of what counts as observable. Then comes Grice to play with
meaning and intending, and allowing for deeming an avowal of this or that souly
state as, in some fashion, incorrigible. For Grice, while U does have, ceteris
paribus privileged access to each state of his soul, only his or that avowal of
this or that souly state is deemed incorrigible. This concerns communication as
involving intending. Grice goes back to this at Brighton. He plays with G
judges that it is raining, G judges that G judges that it is raining. Again,
Grice uses a subscript: “G judges2 that it is raining.” If now G
expresses that it is raining, G judges2 that it is raining. A
second-order avowal is deemed incorrigible. It is not surprising the the
contemporary progeny of the official doctrine sees a behaviourist in Grice. Yet
a dualist is badly off the mark in his critique of Grice. While Grice does
appeal to a practice and a habif, and even the more technical ‘procedure’ in
the ordinary way as ‘procedure’ is used in ordinary discussion. Grice does not
make a technical concept out of them as one expect of some behavioural
psychologist, which he is not. He is at most a philosophical psychologist, and
a functionalist one, rather than a reductionist one. There is nothing in any
way that is ‘behaviourist’ or reductionist or physicalist about Grice’s talk.
It is just ordinary talk about behaviour. There is nothing exceptional in
talking about a practice, a customs, or a habit regarding communication. Grice
certainly does not intend that this or that notion, as he uses it, gives anything
like a detailed account of the creative open-endedness of a
communication-system. What this or that anti-Griceian has to say IS essentially
a diatribe first against empiricism (alla Quine), secondarily against a
Ryle-type of behaviourism, and in the third place, Grice. In more reasoned and
dispassionate terms, one would hardly think of Grice as a behaviourist (he in
fact rejects such a label in “Method”), but as an intentionalist. When we call
Grice an intentionalist, we are being serious. As a modista, Grice’s keyword is
intentionalism, as per the good old scholastic ‘intentio.’ We hope so. This is
Aunt Matilda’s conversational knack. Grice keeps a useful correspondence with
Suppes which was helpful. Suppes takes Chomsky more seriously than an Oxonian
philosopher would. An Oxonian philosopher never takes Chomsky too seriously. Granted,
Austin loves to quote “Syntactic Structures” sentence by sentence for fun,
knowing that it would never count as tutorial material. Surely “Syntactic
Structures” would not be a pamphlet a member of the play group would use to
educate his tutee. It is amusing that when he gives the Locke lectures, Chomsky
cannot not think of anything better to do but to criticise Grice, and citing him
from just one reprint in the collection edited by, of all people, Searle. Some
gratitude. The references are very specific to Grice. Grice feels he needs to
provide, he thinks, an analysis ‘mean’ as metabolically applied to an expression.
Why? Because of the implicaturum. By uttering x (thereby explicitly conveying
that p), U implicitly conveys that q iff U relies on some procedure in his and
A’s repertoire of procedures of U’s and A’s communication-system. It is this
talk of U’s being ‘ready,’ and ‘having a procedure in his repertoire’ that
sounds to New-World Chomsky too Morrisian, as it does not to an Oxonian.
Suppes, a New-Worlder, puts himself in Old-Worlder Grice’s shoes about this. Chomsky
should never mind. When an Oxonian philosopher, not a psychologist, uses ‘procedure’
and ‘readiness,’ and having a procedure in a repertoire, he is being Oxonian
and not to be taken seriously, appealing to ordinary language, and so on.
Chomsky apparently does get it. Incidentally, Suppess has defended Grice
against two other targets, less influential. One is Hungarian-born J. I. Biro,
who does not distinguish between reductive analysis and reductionist analysis,
as Grice does in his response to Somervillian Rountree-Jack. The other target
is perhaps even less influential: P. Yu in a rather simplistic survey of the
Griceian programme for a journal that Grice finds too specialized to count, “Linguistics
and Philosophy.” Grice is always ashamed and avoided of being described as “our
man in the philosophy of language.” Something that could only have happened in
the Old World in a red-brick university, as Grice calls it. Suppes contributes to PGRICE with an
excellent ‘The primacy of utterers meaning,’ where he addresses what he rightly
sees as an unfair characterisations of Grice as a behaviourist. Suppes’s use of
“primacy” is genial, since its metabole which is all about. Biro actually responds
to Suppes’s commentary on Grice as proposing a reductive but not reductionist
analysis of meaning. Suppes rightly characterises Grice as an Oxonian ‘intentionalist’
(alla Ogden), as one would characterize Hampshire, with philosophical
empiricist, and slightly idealist, or better ideationalist, tendencies, rather.
Suppes rightly observes that Grice’ use of such jargon is meant to impress.
Surely there are more casual ways of referring to this or that utterer having a
basic procedure in his repertoire. It is informal and colloquial, enough,
though, rather than behaviouristically, as Ryle would have it. Grice is very
happy that in the New World Suppes teaches him how to use ‘primacy’ with a
straight face! Intentionalism is also all the vogue in Collingwood reading
Croce, and Gardiner reading Marty via Ogden, and relates to expression. In his
analysis of intending Grice is being very Oxonian, and pre-Austinian: relying,
just to tease leader Austin, on Stout, Wilson, Bosanquet, MacMurray, and
Pritchard. Refs.: There are two sets of essays. An early one on ‘disposition
and intention,’ and the essay for The British Academy (henceforth, BA). Also
his reply to Anscombe and his reply to Davidson. There is an essay on the
subjective condition on intention. Obviously, his account of communication has
been labeled the ‘intention-based semantic’ programme, so references under
‘communication’ above are useful. BANC.Grice's reductIOn, or partial reduction
anyway, of meamng to intention places a heavy load on the theory of intentions.
But in the articles he has written about these matters he has not been very
explicit about the structure of intentIOns. As I understand his position on
these matters, it is his view that the defence of the primacy of utterer's
meaning does not depend on having worked out any detailed theory of intention.
It IS enough to show how the reduction should be thought of in a schematic
fashion in order to make a convincing argument. I do think there is a fairly
straightforward extenSIOn of Grice's ideas that provides the right way of
developing a theory of intentIOns appropnate for Ius theory of utterer's
meaning. Slightly changing around some of the words m Grice we have the
following The Primacy of Utterer's Meaning 125 example. U utters '''Fido is
shaggy", if "U wants A to think that U thinks that Jones's dog is
hairy-coated.'" Put another way, U's intention is to want A to think U
thinks that Jones's dog is hairy-coated. Such intentions clearly have a
generative structure similar but different from the generated syntactic
structure we think of verbal utterances' having. But we can even say that the
deep structures talked about by grammarians of Chomsky's ilk could best be
thought of as intentions. This is not a suggestion I intend to pursue
seriously. The important point is that it is a mistake to think about
classifications of intentions; rather, we should think in terms of mechanisms
for generating intentions. Moreover, it seems to me that such mechanisms in the
case of animals are evident enough as expressed in purposeful pursuit of prey
or other kinds of food, and yet are not expressed in language. In that sense
once again there is an argument in defence of Grice's theory. The primacy of
utterer's meaning has primacy because of the primacy of intention. We can have
intentions without words, but we cannot have words of any interest without intentions.
In this general context, I now turn to Biro's (1979) interesting criticisms of
intentionalism in the theory of meaning. Biro deals from his own standpoint
with some of the issues I have raised already, but his central thesis about
intention I have not previously discussed. It goes to the heart of
controversies about the use of the concept of intention to explain the meaning
of utterances. Biro puts his point in a general way by insisting that utterance
meaning must be separate from and independent of speaker's meaning or, in the
terminology used here, utterer's meaning. The central part of his argument is
his objection to the possibility of explaining meaning in terms of intentions.
Biro's argument goes like this: 1. A central purpose of speech is to enable
others to learn about the speaker's intentions. 2. It will be impossible to
discover or understand the intentions of the speaker unless there are
independent means for understanding what he says, since what he says will be
primary evidence about his intentions. 3. Thus the meaning of an utterance must
be conceptually independent of the intentions of the speaker. This is an
appealing positivistic line. The data relevant to a theory or hypothesis must
be known independently of the hypothesis. Biro is quick to state that he is not
against theoretical entities, but the way in which he separates theoretical
entities and observable facts makes clear the limited role he wants them to
play, in this case the theoretical entities being intentions. The central idea
is to be found in the following passage: The point I am insisting on here is
merely that the ascription of an intention to an agent has the character of an
hypothesis, something invoked to explain phenomena which may be described
independently of that explanation (though not necessarily independently of the
fact that they fall into a class for which the hypothesis in question generally
or normally provides an explanation). ( 250-1.) [The italics are Biro's.]
Biro's aim is clear from this quotation. The central point is that the data
about intentions, namely, the utterance, must be describable independently of
hypotheses about the intentions. He says a little later to reinforce this: 'The
central pointis this: it is the intention-hypothesis that is revisable, not the
act-description' (p. 251). Biro's central mistake, and a large one too, is to
think that data can be described independently of hypotheses and that somehow
there is a clean and simple version of data that makes such description a
natural and inevitable thing to have. It would be easy enough to wander off
into a description of such problems in physics, where experiments provide a
veritable wonderland of seemingly arbitrary choices about what to include and
what to exclude from the experimental experience as 'relevant data', and where
the arbitrariness can only be even partly understood on the basis of
understanding the theories bemg tested. Real data do not come in simple linear
strips like letters on the page. Real experiments are blooming confusions that
never get sorted out completely but only partially and schematically, as
appropriate to the theory or theories being tested, and in accordance with the
traditions and conventions of past similar experiments. makes a point about the
importance of convention that I agree but it is irrelevant to my central of
controversy with What I say about
experiments is even more true of undisciplined and unregulated human
interactiono Experiments, especially in physics, are presumably among the best
examples of disciplined and structured action. Most conversations, in contrast,
are really examples of situations of confusion that are only straightened out
under strong hypotheses of intentions on the of speakers and listeners as well.
There is more than one level at which the takes The Primacy of Utterer's
Meaning 127 place through the beneficent use of hypotheses about intentions. I
shall not try to deal with all of them here but only mention some salient
aspects. At an earlier point, Biro says:The main reason for introducing
intentions into some of these analyses is precisely that the public (broadly
speaking) features of utterances -the sounds made, the circumstances in which
they are made and the syntactic and semantic properties of these noises
considered as linguistic items-are thought to be insufficient for the
specification of that aspect of the utterance which we call its meaning. [po
244.] If we were to take this line of thought seriously and literally, we would
begin with the sound pressure waves that reach our ears and that are given the
subtle and intricate interpretation required to accept them as speech. There is
a great variety of evidence that purely acoustical concepts are inadequate for
the analysis of speech. To determine the speech content of a sound pressure
wave we need extensive hypotheses about the intentions that speakers have in
order to convert the public physical features of utterances into intentional
linguistic items. Biro might object at where I am drawing the line between
public and intentional, namely, at the difference between physical and
linguistic, but it would be part of my thesis that it is just because of
perceived and hypothesized intentions that we are mentally able to convert
sound pressure waves into meaningful speech. In fact, I can envisage a kind of
transcendental argument for the existence of intentions based on the
impossibility from the standpoint of physics alone of interpreting sound
pressure waves as speech. Biro seems to have in mind the nice printed sentences
of science and philosophy that can be found on the printed pages of treatises
around the world. But this is not the right place to begin to think about
meaning, only the end point. Grice, and everybody else who holds an intentional
thesis about meaning, recognizes the requirement to reach an account of such
timeless sentence meaning or linguistic meaning.In fact, Grice is perhaps more
ready than I am to concede that such a theory can be developed in a relatively
straightforward manner. One purpose of my detailed discussion of congruence of
meaning in the previous section is to point out some of the difficulties of
having an adequate detailed theory of these matters, certainly an adequate
detailed theory of the linguistic meaning or the sentence meaning. Even if I were
willing to grant the feasibility of such a theory, I would not grant the use of
it that Biro has made. For the purposes of this discussion printed text may be
accepted as well-defined, theoryindependent data. (There are even issues to be
raised about the printed page, but ones that I will set aside in the present
context. I have in mind the psychological difference between perception of
printed letters, words, phrases, or sentences, and that of related but
different nonlinguistic marks on paper.) But no such data assumptions can be
made about spoken speech. Still another point of attack on Biro's positivistic
line about data concerns the data of stress and prosody and their role in
fixing the meaning of an utterance. Stress and prosody are critical to the
interpretation of the intentions of speakers, but the data on stress and
prosody are fleeting and hard to catch on the fly_ Hypotheses about speakers'
intentions are needed even in the most humdrum interpret atins of what a given
prosodic contour or a given point of stress has contributed to the meaning of
the utterance spoken. The prosodic contour and the points of stress of an
utterance are linguistic data, but they do not have the independent physical
description Biro vainly hopes for. Let me put my point still another way. I do
not deny for a second that conventions and traditions of speech play a role in
fixing the meaning of a particular utterance on a particular occasion. It is
not a matter of interpretmg afresh, as if the universe had just begun, a
particular utterance in terms of particular intentions at that time and place
without dependence upon past prior mtentions and the traditions of spoken
speech that have evolved in the community of which the speaker and listener are
a part. It is rather that hypotheses about intentions are operating continually
and centrally in the interpretation of what is said. Loose, live speech depends
upon such active 'on-line' interpretation of intention to make sense of what
has been said. If there were some absolutely agreed-upon concept of firm and
definite linguistlc meaning that Biro and others could appeal to, then it might
be harder to make the case I am arguing for. But I have already argued in the
discussion of congruence of meaning that this is precisely what is not the
case. The absence of any definite and satisfactory theory of linguistic meaning
argues also for movmg back to the more concrete and psychologically richer
concept of utterer's meaning. This is the place to begin the theory of meaning,
and this Itself rests to a very large extent on the concept of intention --
intention, (1) a characteristic of action, as when one acts intentionally or
with a certain intention; (2) a feature of one’s mind, as when one intends (has
an intention) to act in a certain way now or in the future. Betty, e.g.,
intentionally walks across the room, does so with the intention of getting a
drink, and now intends to leave the party later that night. An important
question is: how are (1) and (2) related? (See Anscombe, Intention, 1963, for a
groundbreaking treatment of these and other basic problems concerning
intention.) Some philosophers see acting with an intention as basic and as
subject to a three-part analysis. For Betty to walk across the room with the
intention of getting a drink is for Betty’s walking across the room to be
explainable (in the appropriate way) by her desire or (as is sometimes said)
pro-attitude in favor of getting a drink and her belief that walking across the
room is a way of getting one. On this desire-belief model (or wantbelief model)
the main elements of acting with an intention are (a) the action, (b)
appropriate desires (pro-attitudes) and beliefs, and (c) an appropriate
explanatory relation between (a) and (b). (See Davidson, “Actions, Reasons, and
Causes” in Essays on Actions and Events, 1980.) In explaining (a) in terms of
(b) we give an explanation of the action in terms of the agent’s purposes or
reasons for so acting. This raises the fundamental question of what kind of
explanation this is, and how it is related to explanation of Betty’s movements
by appeal to their physical causes. What about intentions to act in the future?
Consider Betty’s intention to leave the party later. Though the intended action
is later, this intention may nevertheless help explain some of Betty’s planning
and acting between now and then. Some philosophers try to fit such
futuredirected intentions directly into the desire-belief model. John Austin,
e.g., would identify Betty’s intention with her belief that she will leave
later because of her desire to leave (Lectures on Jurisprudence, I, 1873). Others see futuredirected
intentions as distinctive attitudes, not to be reduced to desires and/or
beliefs. How is belief related to intention? One question here is whether an
intention to A requires a belief that one will A. A second question is whether
a belief that one will A in executing some intention ensures that one intends
to A. Suppose that Betty believes that by walking across the room she will
interrupt Bob’s conversation. Though she has no desire to interrupt, she still
proceeds across the room. Does she intend to interrupt the conversation? Or is
there a coherent distinction between what one intends and what one merely
expects to bring about as a result of doing what one intends? One way of
talking about such cases, due to Bentham (An Introduction to the Principles of
Morals and Legislation, 1789), is to say that Betty’s walking across the room
is “directly intentional,” whereas her interrupting the conversation is only
“obliquely intentional” (or indirectly intentional). -- intentional fallacy,
the (purported) fallacy of holding that the meaning of a work of art is fixed
by the artist’s intentions. (Wimsatt and Beardsintensive magnitude intentional
fallacy 440 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 440 ley, who introduced the
term, also used it to name the [purported] fallacy that the artist’s aims are
relevant to determining the success of a work of art; however, this distinct
usage has not gained general currency.) Wimsatt and Beardsley were formalists;
they held that interpretation should focus purely on the work of art itself and
should exclude appeal to biographical information about the artist, other than
information concerning the private meanings the artist attached to his words.
Whether the intentional fallacy is in fact a fallacy is a much discussed issue
within aesthetics. Intentionalists deny that it is: they hold that the meaning
of a work of art is fixed by some set of the artist’s intentions. For instance,
Richard Wollheim (Painting as an Art) holds that the meaning of a painting is
fixed by the artist’s fulfilled intentions in making it. Other intentionalists
appeal not to the actual artist’s intentions, but to the intentions of the
implied or postulated artist, a construct of criticism, rather than a real
person. See also AESTHETIC FORMALISM, AESTHETICS, INTENTION. B.Ga.
intentionality, aboutness. Things that are about other things exhibit
intentionality. Beliefs and other mental states exhibit intentionality, but so,
in a derived way, do sentences and books, maps and pictures, and other
representations. The adjective ‘intentional’ in this philosophical sense is a
technical term not to be confused with the more familiar sense, characterizing
something done on purpose. Hopes and fears, for instance, are not things we do,
not intentional acts in the latter, familiar sense, but they are intentional
phenomena in the technical sense: hopes and fears are about various things. The
term was coined by the Scholastics in the Middle Ages, and derives from the
Latin verb intendo, ‘to point (at)’ or ‘aim (at)’ or ‘extend (toward)’.
Phenomena with intentionality thus point outside of themselves to something
else: whatever they are of or about. The term was revived by the nineteenth-century
philosopher and psychologist Franz Brentano, who claimed that intentionality
defines the distinction between the mental and the physical; all and only
mental phenomena exhibit intentionality. Since intentionality is an irreducible
feature of mental phenomena, and since no physical phenomena could exhibit it,
mental phenomena could not be a species of physical phenomena. This claim,
often called the Brentano thesis or Brentano’s irreducibility thesis, has often
been cited to support the view that the mind cannot be the brain, but this is
by no means generally accepted today. There was a second revival of the term in
the 1960s and 1970s by analytic philosophers, in particular Chisholm, Sellars,
and Quine. Chisholm attempted to clarify the concept by shifting to a logical
definition of intentional idioms, the terms used to speak of mental states and
events, rather than attempting to define the intentionality of the states and
events themselves. Intentional idioms include the familiar “mentalistic” terms
of folk psychology, but also their technical counterparts in theories and
discussions in cognitive science, ‘X believes that p,’ and ‘X desires that q’
are paradigmatic intentional idioms, but according to Chisholm’s logical
definition, in terms of referential opacity (the failure of substitutivity of
coextensive terms salva veritate), so are such less familiar idioms as ‘X
stores the information that p’ and ‘X gives high priority to achieving the
state of affairs that q’. Although there continue to be deep divisions among
philosophers about the proper definition or treatment of the concept of
intentionality, there is fairly widespread agreement that it marks a
featureaboutness or contentthat is central to mental phenomena, and hence a
central, and difficult, problem that any theory of mind must solve.
INTER-SUB-IAECTVM
-- intersubjectiveGrice:
“Who was the first Grecian philosopher to philosophise on conversational
intersubjectivity? Surely Plato! Socrates is just his alter egoand after
Aeschylus, there is always a ‘deuterogonist’”! conversational
intersubjectivity. Philosophical sociologyWhile Grice saw himself as a
philosophical psychologist, he would rather be seen dead than as a
philosophical sociologist‘intersubjective at most’! -- Comte: A. philosopher
and sociologist, the founder of positivism. He was educated in Paris at l’École
Polytechnique, where he briefly taught mathematics. He suffered from a mental
illness that occasionally interrupted his work. In conformity with empiricism,
Comte held that knowledge of the world arises from observation. He went beyond
many empiricists, however, in denying the possibility of knowledge of
unobservable physical objects. He conceived of positivism as a method of study
based on observation and restricted to the observable. He applied positivism
chiefly to science. He claimed that the goal of science is prediction, to be
accomplished using laws of succession. Explanation insofar as attainable has
the same structure as prediction. It subsumes events under laws of succession;
it is not causal. Influenced by Kant, he held that the causes of phenomena and
the nature of things-in-themselves are not knowable. He criticized metaphysics
for ungrounded speculation about such matters; he accused it of not keeping
imagination subordinate to observation. He advanced positivism for all the
sciences but held that each science has additional special methods, and has
laws not derivable by human intelligence from laws of other sciences. He
corresponded extensively with J. S. Mill, who Comte, Auguste Comte, Auguste
168 168 encouraged his work and
discussed it in Auguste Comte and Positivism 1865. Twentieth-century logical
positivism was inspired by Comte’s ideas. Comte was a founder of sociology,
which he also called social physics. He divided the science into two
branches statics and dynamics dealing
respectively with social organization and social development. He advocated a
historical method of study for both branches. As a law of social development,
he proposed that all societies pass through three intellectual stages, first
interpreting phenomena theologically, then metaphysically, and finally
positivistically. The general idea that societies develop according to laws of
nature was adopted by Marx. Comte’s most important work is his six-volume Cours
de philosophie positive Course in Positive Philosophy, 183042. It is an
encyclopedic treatment of the sciences that expounds positivism and culminates
in the introduction of sociology.
INTER-VENTUM -- intervention -- intervening
variable, in Grice’s philosophical psychology, a state of an organism, person or,
as Grice prefers, a ‘pirot,’ (vide his ‘pirotology’) or ‘creature,’ postulated
to explain the pirot’s behaviour and defined in ‘functioanlist,’ Aristotelian
terms of its cause (perceptual input) and effect (the behavioural output to be
explained by attribution of a state of the ‘soul’) rather than its intrinsic
properties. A food drive or need for nuts, in a squarrel (as Grice calls his
‘Toby’) conceived as an intervening variable, is defined in terms of the number
of hours without food (the cause) and the strength or robustness of efforts to
secure it (effect).. The squarrel’s feeling hungry (‘needing a nut), is no
longer an intrinsic propertythe theoretical term ‘need’ is introduced in a
ramseyified sentence by describingand it need not be co-related to a state in
the brainsince there is room for variable realisability. Grice sees at least
three reasons for postulating an intervening variable (like the hours without
nut-hobbling). First, time lapse between stimulus (perceptual input) and
behavioural output may be large, as when an animaleven a squirrel -- eats food found
hours earlier. Why did not the animal hobble the nut when it first found it?
Perhaps at the time of discovery, the squarrel had already eaten, so food drive
(the squarrel’s need) is reduced. Second, Toby may act differently in the same
sort of situation, as when Toby hobbles a nut at noon one day but delay until
sunset the next. Again, this may be because of variation in food drive or the
squarrel’s need. Third, behaviour may occur in the absence of external
stimulation or perceptual input, as when Toby forages for nut for the winter.
This, too, may be explained by the strength of the food drive or squarrel’s
need. An intervening variables has been viewed, as Grice notes reviewing
Oxonian philosophical psychology from Stout to Ryle via Prichard) depending on
the background theory, as a convenient ‘fiction’ (as Ramsey, qua theoretical
construct) or as a psychologically real state, or as a physically real state
with multiple realisability conditions. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Method in
philosophical psychology: from the banal to the bizarre,” in “The Conception of
value.”
IN-TUITUM -- intuitum: Grice: “At Oxford,
the tutor teaches to trust your ‘intuition’and will point to the cognateness of
‘tutor’ and ‘in-tuition’!”tŭĕor , tuĭtus, 2 (
I.perf. only post-Aug., Quint. 5, 13, 35; Plin. Ep. 6, 29, 10; collat. form
tūtus, in the part., rare, Sall. J. 74, 3; Front. Strat. 2, 12, 13; but
constantly in the P. a.; inf. parag. tuerier, Plaut. Rud. 1, 4, 35; collat.
form acc. to the 3d conj. tŭor , Cat. 20, 5; Stat. Th. 3, 151: “tuĕris,” Plaut.
Trin. 3, 2, 82: “tuimur,” Lucr. 1, 300; 4, 224; 4, 449; “6, 934: tuamur,” id.
4, 361: “tuantur,” id. 4, 1004; imper. tuĕre, id. 5, 318), v. dep. a. [etym.
dub.], orig., to see, to look or gaze upon, to watch, view; hence, pregn., to
see or look to, to defend, protect, etc.: tueri duo significat; unum ab
aspectu, unde est Ennii illud: tueor te senex? pro Juppiter! (Trag. v. 225
Vahl.); “alterum a curando ac tutela, ut cum dicimus bellum tueor et tueri
villam,” Varr. L. L. 7, § 12 Müll. sq.—Accordingly, I. To look at, gaze at,
behold, watch, view, regard, consider, examine, etc. (only poet.; syn.: specto,
adspicio, intueor): quam te post multis tueor tempestatibus, Pac. ap. Non. 407,
32; 414, 3: “e tenebris, quae sunt in luce, tuemur,” Lucr. 4, 312: “ubi nil
aliud nisi aquam caelumque tuentur,” id. 4, 434: “caeli templa,” id. 6, 1228
al.: “tuendo Terribiles oculos, vultum, etc.,” Verg. A. 8, 265; cf. id. ib. 1,
713: “talia dicentem jam dudum aversa tuetur,” id. ib. 4, 362: “transversa
tuentibus hircis,” id. E. 3, 8: “acerba tuens,” looking fiercely, Lucr. 5, 33;
cf. Verg. A. 9, 794: “torva,” id. ib. 6, 467.— (β). With object-clause: “quod
multa in terris fieri caeloque tuentur (homines), etc.,” Lucr. 1, 152; 6, 50;
6, 1163.— II. Pregn., to look to, care for, keep up, uphold, maintain, support,
guard, preserve, defend, protect, etc. (the predom. class. signif. of the word;
cf.: “curo, conservo, tutor, protego, defendo): videte, ne ... vobis
turpissimum sit, id, quod accepistis, tueri et conservare non posse,” Cic. Imp.
Pomp. 5, 12: “ut quisque eis rebus tuendis conservandisque praefuerat,” Cic.
Verr. 2, 4, 63, 140: “omnia,” id. N. D. 2, 23, 60: “mores et instituta vitae
resque domesticas ac familiares,” id. Tusc. 1, 1, 2: “societatem conjunctionis
humanae munifice et aeque,” id. Fin. 5, 23, 65: “concordiam,” id. Att. 1, 17,
10: rem et gratiam et auctoritatem suam, id. Fam. 13, 49, 1: “dignitatem,” id.
Tusc. 2, 21, 48: “L. Paulus personam principis civis facile dicendo tuebatur,”
id. Brut. 20, 80: “personam in re publicā,” id. Phil. 8, 10, 29; cf.: tuum munus,
Planc. ap. Cic. Fam. 10, 11, 1: “tueri et sustinere simulacrum pristinae
dignitatis,” Cic. Rab. Post. 15, 41: “aedem Castoris P. Junius habuit tuendam,”
to keep in good order, Cic. Verr. 2, 1, 50, § 130; cf. Plin. Pan. 51, 1:
“Bassum ut incustoditum nimis et incautum,” id. Ep. 6, 29, 10: “libertatem,”
Tac. A. 3, 27; 14, 60: “se, vitam corpusque tueri,” to keep, preserve, Cic.
Off. 1, 4, 11: “antea majores copias alere poterat, nunc exiguas vix tueri
potest,” id. Deiot. 8, 22: “se ac suos tueri,” Liv. 5, 4, 5: “sex legiones (re
suā),” Cic. Par. 6, 1, 45: “armentum paleis,” Col. 6, 3, 3: “se ceteris armis
prudentiae tueri atque defendere,” to guard, protect, Cic. de Or. 1, 38, 172;
cf.: “tuemini castra et defendite diligenter,” Caes. B. C. 3, 94: “suos fines,”
id. B. G. 4, 8: “portus,” id. ib. 5, 8: “oppidum unius legionis praesidio,” id.
B. C. 2, 23: “oram maritimam,” id. ib. 3, 34: “impedimenta,” to cover, protect,
Hirt. B. G. 8, 2.—With ab and abl.: “fines suos ab excursionibus et
latrociniis,” Cic. Deiot. 8, 22: “domum a furibus,” Phaedr. 3, 7, 10: mare ab
hostibus, Auct. B. Afr. 8, 2.—With contra: “quos non parsimoniā tueri potuit
contra illius audaciam,” Cic. Prov. Cons. 5, 11: “liberūm nostrorum pueritiam
contra inprobitatem magistratuum,” Cic. Verr. 2, 1, 58, § 153; Quint. 5, 13,
35; Plin. 20, 14, 54, § 152; Tac. A. 6, 47 (41).—With adversus: “tueri se
adversus Romanos,” Liv. 25, 11, 7: “nostra adversus vim atque injuriam,” id. 7,
31, 3: “adversus Philippum tueri Athenas,” id. 31, 9, 3; 42, 46, 9; 42, 23, 6:
“arcem adversus tres cohortes tueri,” Tac. H. 3, 78; Just. 17, 3, 22; 43, 3,
4.—In part. perf.: “Verres fortiter et industrie tuitus contra piratas Siciliam
dicitur,” Quint. 5, 13, 35 (al. tutatus): “Numidas in omnibus proeliis magis
pedes quam arma tuta sunt,” Sall. J. 74, 3.!*? 1. Act. form tŭĕo , ēre:
“censores vectigalia tuento,” Cic. Leg. 3, 3, 7: “ROGO PER SVPEROS, QVI ESTIS,
OSSA MEA TVEATIS,” Inscr. Orell. 4788.— 2. tŭĕor , ēri, in pass. signif.:
“majores nostri in pace a rusticis Romanis alebantur et in bello ab his
tuebantur,” Varr. R. R. 3, 1, 4; Lucr. 4, 361: “consilio et operā curatoris
tueri debet non solum patrimonium, sed et corpus et salus furiosi,” Dig. 27,
10, 7: “voluntas testatoris ex bono et aequo tuebitur,” ib. 28, 3, 17.—Hence,
tūtus , a, uma. (prop. well seen to or guarded; hence), safe, secure, out of
danger (cf. securus, free from fear). A. Lit. (α). Absol.: “nullius res tuta,
nullius domus clausa, nullius vita saepta ... contra tuam cupiditatem,” Cic.
Verr. 2, 5, 15, § 39: “cum victis nihil tutum arbitrarentur,” Caes. B. G. 2,
28: “nec se satis tutum fore arbitratur,” Hirt. B. G. 8, 27; cf.: “me biremis
praesidio scaphae Tutum per Aegaeos tumultus Aura feret,” Hor. C. 3, 29, 63;
Ov. M. 8, 368: “tutus bos rura perambulat,” Hor. C. 4, 5, 17: “quis locus tam
firmum habuit praesidium, ut tutus esset?” Cic. Imp. Pomp. 11, 31: “mare tutum
praestare,” id. Fl. 13, 31: “sic existimabat tutissimam fore Galliam,” Hirt. B.
G. 8, 54: “nemus,” Hor. C. 1, 17, 5: “via fugae,” Cic. Caecin. 15, 44; cf.:
“commodior ac tutior receptus,” Caes. B. C. 1, 46: “perfugium,” Cic. Rep. 1, 4,
8: “tutum iter et patens,” Hor. C. 3, 16, 7: “tutissima custodia,” Liv. 31, 23,
9: “praesidio nostro pasci genus esseque tutum,” Lucr. 5, 874: “vitam
consistere tutam,” id. 6, 11: “tutiorem et opulentiorem vitam hominum reddere,”
Cic. Rep. 1, 2, 3: est et fideli tuta silentio Merces, secure, sure (diff. from
certa, definite, certain), Hor. C. 3, 2, 25: “tutior at quanto merx est in
classe secundā!” id. S. 1, 2, 47: “non est tua tuta voluntas,” not without
danger, Ov. M. 2, 53: “in audaces non est audacia tuta,” id. ib. 10, 544:
“externā vi non tutus modo rex, sed invictus,” Curt. 6, 7, 1: “vel tutioris
audentiae est,” Quint. 12, prooem. § 4: “ cogitatio tutior,” id. 10, 7, 19:
“fuit brevitas illa tutissima,” id. 10, 1, 39: “regnum et diadema tutum
Deferens uni,” i. e. that cannot be taken away, Hor. C. 2, 2, 21: male tutae
mentis Orestes, i. e. unsound, = male sanae, id. S. 2, 3, 137: quicquid habes,
age, Depone tutis auribus, qs. carefully guarded, i. e. safe, faithful, id. C.
1, 27, 18 (cf. the o: auris rimosa, id. S. 2, 6, 46).—Poet., with gen.: “(pars
ratium) tuta fugae,” Luc. 9, 346.— (β). With ab and abl.: tutus ab insidiis
inimici, Asin. ap. Cic. Fam. 10, 31, 2: “ab insidiis,” Hor. S. 2, 6, 117: “a
periculo,” Caes. B. G. 7, 14: “ab hoste,” Ov. H. 11, 44: “ab hospite,” id. M.
1, 144: “a conjuge,” id. ib. 8, 316: “a ferro,” id. ib. 13, 498: “a bello, id.
H. (15) 16, 344: ab omni injuriā,” Phaedr. 1, 31, 9.— (γ). With ad and acc.:
“turrim tuendam ad omnis repentinos casus tradidit,” Caes. B. C. 3, 39: “ad id,
quod ne timeatur fortuna facit, minime tuti sunt homines,” Liv. 25, 38, 14:
“testudinem tutam ad omnes ictus video esse,” id. 36, 32, 6.— (δ). With
adversus: “adversus venenorum pericula tutum corpus suum reddere,” Cels. 5, 23,
3: “quo tutiores essent adversus ictus sagittarum,” Curt. 7, 9, 2: “loci
beneficio adversus intemperiem anni tutus est,” Sen. Ira, 2, 12, 1: “per quem
tutior adversus casus steti,” Val. Max. 4, 7, ext. 2: “quorum praesidio tutus
adversus hostes esse debuerat,” Just. 10, 1, 7.—(ε) With abl.: incendio fere tuta est Alexandria, Auct. B. Alex. 1,
3.— b. Tutum est, with a subj. -clause, it is prudent or safe, it is the part
of a prudent man: “si dicere palam parum tutum est,” Quint. 9, 2, 66; 8, 3, 47;
10, 3, 33: “o nullis tutum credere blanditiis,” Prop. 1, 15, 42: “tutius esse
arbitrabantur, obsessis viis, commeatu intercluso sine ullo vulnere victoriā
potiri,” Caes. B. G. 3, 24; Quint. 7, 1, 36; 11, 2, 48: “nobis tutissimum est,
auctores plurimos sequi,” id. 3, 4, 11; 3, 6, 63.— 2. As subst.: tūtum , i, n.,
a place of safety, a shelter, safety, security: Tr. Circumspice dum, numquis
est, Sermonem nostrum qui aucupet. Th. Tutum probe est, Plaut. Most. 2, 2, 42:
“tuta et parvula laudo,” Hor. Ep. 1, 15, 42: “trepidum et tuta petentem Trux
aper insequitur,” Ov. M. 10, 714: “in tuto ut collocetur,” Ter. Heaut. 4, 3,
11: “esse in tuto,” id. ib. 4, 3, 30: “ut sitis in tuto,” Cic. Fam. 12, 2, 3:
“in tutum eduxi manipulares meos,” Plaut. Most. 5, 1, 7: “in tutum receptus
est,” Liv. 2, 19, 6.— B. Transf., watchful, careful, cautious, prudent (rare
and not ante-Aug.; “syn.: cautus, prudens): serpit humi tutus nimium timidusque
procellae,” Hor. A. P. 28: “tutus et intra Spem veniae cautus,” id. ib. 266:
“non nisi vicinas tutus ararit aquas,” Ov. Tr. 3, 12, 36: “id suā sponte,
apparebat, tuta celeribus consiliis praepositurum,” Liv. 22, 38, 13: “celeriora
quam tutiora consilia magis placuere ducibus,” id. 9, 32, 3.—Hence, adv. in two
forms, tūtē and tūtō , safely, securely, in safety, without danger. a. Posit.
(α). Form tute (very rare): “crede huic tute,” Plaut. Trin. 1, 2, 102: “eum
tute vivere, qui honeste vivat,” Auct. Her. 3, 5, 9: “tute cauteque agere,” id.
ib. 3, 7, 13.— (β). Form tuto (class. in prose and poetry): “pervenire,” Plaut.
Mil. 2, 2, 70; Lucr. 1, 179: “dimicare,” Caes. B. G. 3, 24: “tuto et libere
decernere,” id. B. C. 1, 2: “ut tuto sim,” in security, Cic. Fam. 14, 3, 3: “ut
tuto ab repentino hostium incursu etiam singuli commeare possent,” Caes. B. G.
7, 36. — b. Comp.: “ut in vadis consisterent tutius,” Caes. B. G. 3, 13:
“tutius et facilius receptus daretur,” id. B. C. 2, 30: “tutius ac facilius id
tractatur,” Quint. 5, 5, 1: “usitatis tutius utimur,” id. 1, 5, 71: “ut ubivis
tutius quam in meo regno essem,” Sall. J. 14, 11.— c. Sup. (α). Form tutissime:
nam te hic tutissime puto fore, Pomp. ap. Cic. Att. 8, 11, A.— (β). Form
tutissimo: “quaerere, ubi tutissimo essem,” Cic. Att. 8, 1, 2; cf. Charis. p.
173 P.: “tutissimo infunduntur oboli quattuor,” Plin. 20, 3, 8, § 14. Grice was
especially interested in the misuses of intuition. He found that J. L. Austin
(born in Lancaster) had “Northern intuitions.” “I myself have proper
heart-of-England intuitions.” “Strawson has Cockney intuitions.” “I wonder how
we conducted those conversations on Saturday mornings!” “Strictly, an
intuition is a non-inferential knowledge or grasp, as of a proposition,
concept, or entity, that is not based on perception, memory, or introspection;
also, the capacity in virtue of which such cognition is possible. A person
might know that 1 ! 1 % 2 intuitively, i.e., not on the basis of inferring it
from other propositions. And one might know intuitively what yellow is, i.e.,
might understand the concept, even though ‘yellow’ is not definable. Or one
might have intuitive awareness of God or some other entity. Certain mystics
hold that there can be intuitive, or immediate, apprehension of God. Ethical
intuitionists hold both that we can have intuitive knowledge of certain moral
concepts that are indefinable, and that certain propositions, such as that
pleasure is intrinsically good, are knowable through intuition. Self-evident
propositions are those that can be seen (non-inferentially) to be true once one
fully understands them. It is often held that all and only self-evident
propositions are knowable through intuition, which is here identified with a
certain kind of intellectual or rational insight. Intuitive knowledge of moral
or other philosophical propositions or concepts has been compared to the
intuitive knowledge of grammaticality possessed by competent users of a
language. Such language users can know immediately whether certain sentences
are grammatical or not without recourse to any conscious reasoning. Refs.: H.
P. Grice, “My intutions.” BANC.
ionian-sea-coast philosophy: Grice, “Or
mar ionio, as the Italians have it!” -- the characteristically naturalist and
rationalist thought of Grecian philosophers of the sixth and fifth centuries
B.C. who were active in Ionia, the region of ancient Greek colonies on the
coast of Asia Minor and adjacent islands. First of the Ionian philosophers were
the three Milesians. Grice: “It always amused me that they called themselves
Ionians, but then Williams, who founded Providence in the New World, called
himself an Englishman!”. Refs.: H. P. Grice: “The relevance of Ionian
philosophy today.”
iron-age
metaphysics:
Euclidean geometry, the version of geometry that includes among its axioms the
parallel axiom, which asserts that, given a line L in a plane, there exists
just one line in the plane that passes through a point not on L but never meets
L. The phrase ‘Euclidean geometry’ refers both to the doctrine of geometry to
be found in Euclid’s Elements fourth century B.C. and to the mathematical
discipline that was built on this basis afterward. In order to present
properties of rectilinear and curvilinear curves in the plane and solids in
space, Euclid sought definitions, axioms, ethics, divine command Euclidean
geometry 290 290 and postulates to
ground the reasoning. Some of his assumptions belonged more to the underlying
logic than to the geometry itself. Of the specifically geometrical axioms, the
least self-evident stated that only one line passes through a point in a plane
parallel to a non-coincident line within it, and many efforts were made to
prove it from the other axioms. Notable forays were made by G. Saccheri, J.
Playfair, and A. M. Legendre, among others, to put forward results logically
contradictory to the parallel axiom e.g., that the sum of the angles between
the sides of a triangle is greater than 180° and thus standing as candidates
for falsehood; however, none of them led to paradox. Nor did logically
equivalent axioms such as that the angle sum equals 180° seem to be more or
less evident than the axiom itself. The next stages of this line of reasoning
led to non-Euclidean geometry. From the point of view of logic and rigor,
Euclid was thought to be an apotheosis of certainty in human knowledge; indeed,
‘Euclidean’ was also used to suggest certainty, without any particular concern
with geometry. Ironically, investigations undertaken in the late nineteenth
century showed that, quite apart from the question of the parallel axiom,
Euclid’s system actually depended on more axioms than he had realized, and that
filling all the gaps would be a formidable task. Pioneering work done
especially by M. Pasch and G. Peano was brought to a climax in 9 by Hilbert,
who produced what was hoped to be a complete axiom system. Even then the axiom
of continuity had to wait for the second edition! The endeavor had consequences
beyond the Euclidean remit; it was an important example of the growth of
axiomatization in mathematics as a whole, and it led Hilbert himself to see
that questions like the consistency and completeness of a mathematical theory
must be asked at another level, which he called metamathematics. It also gave
his work a formalist character; he said that his axiomatic talk of points,
lines, and planes could be of other objects. Within the Euclidean realm,
attention has fallen in recent decades upon “neo-Euclidean” geometries, in
which the parallel axiom is upheld but a different metric is proposed. For
example, given a planar triangle ABC, the Euclidean distance between A and B is
the hypotenuse AB; but the “rectangular distance” AC ! CB also satisfies the
properties of a metric, and a geometry working with it is very useful in, e.g.,
economic geography, as anyone who drives around a city will readily
understand. Grice:
"Much the most significant opposition to my type of philosophising comes
from those like Baron Russell who feel that ‘ “ordinary-language” philosophy’
is an affront to science and to intellectual progress, and who regard exponents
like me as wantonly dedicating themselves to what the Baron calls 'stone-age
metaphysics', "The Baron claims that 'stone-age metaphysics' is the best
that can be dredged up from a ‘philosophical’ study of an ‘ordinary’ language,
such as Oxonian, as it ain't. "The use made of Russell’s phrase
‘stone-age metaphysics’ has more rhetorical appeal than argumentative
force."“Certainly ‘stone-age’ *physics*, if by that we mean a
'primitive' (as the Baron puts it -- in contrast to 'iron-age physics') set of
hypotheses about how the world goes which might conceivably be embedded somehow
or other in an ‘ordinary’ language such as Oxonian, does not seem to be a
proper object for first-order devotion -- I'll grant the Baron that!"“But
this fact should *not* prevent something derivable or extractable
from ‘stone-age’ (if not 'iron-age') *physics*, perhaps some very
general characterization of the nature of reality, from being a proper target
for serious research.”"I would not be surprised if an extractable
characterization of this may not be the same as that which is extractable from,
or that which underlies, the Baron's favoured iron-age physics!" iron-age physics: Grice on Russellian compresence,
an unanalyzable relation in terms of which Russell, in his later writings
especially in Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits, 8, took concrete
particular objects to be analyzable. Concrete particular objects are analyzable
in terms of complexes of qualities all of whose members are compresent.
Although this relation can be defined only ostensively, Russell states that it
appears in psychology as “simultaneity in one experience” and in physics as
“overlapping in space-time.” Complete complexes of compresence are complexes of
qualities having the following two properties: 1 all members of the complex are
compresent; 2 given anything not a member of the complex, there is at least one
member of the complex with which it is not compresent. He argues that there is
strong empirical evidence that no two complete complexes have all their
qualities in common. Finally, space-time pointinstants are analyzed as complete
complexes of compresence. Concrete particulars, on the other hand, are analyzed
as series of incomplete complexes of compresence related by certain causal
laws.
SEQUITVR/NON-SEQVITVR
-- non sequitur
--: irrationality, unreasonableness. Whatever it entails, irrationality can
characterize belief, desire, intention, and action. intuitions irrationality
443 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 443 Irrationality is often explained in
instrumental, or goal-oriented, terms. You are irrational if you (knowingly)
fail to do your best, or at least to do what you appropriately think adequate,
to achieve your goals. If ultimate goals are rationally assessable, as
Aristotelian and Kantian traditions hold, then rationality and irrationality
are not purely instrumental. The latter traditions regard certain specific
(kinds of) goals, such as human well-being, as essential to rationality. This
substantialist approach lost popularity with the rise of modern decision
theory, which implies that, in satisfying certain consistency and completeness
requirements, one’s preferences toward the possible outcomes of available
actions determine what actions are rational and irrational for one by
determining the personal utility of their outcomes. Various theorists have
faulted modern decision theory on two grounds: human beings typically lack the
consistent preferences and reasoning power required by standard decision theory
but are not thereby irrational, and rationality requires goods exceeding
maximally efficient goal satisfaction. When relevant goals concern the
acquisition of truth and the avoidance of falsehood, epistemic rationality and
irrationality are at issue. Otherwise, some species of non-epistemic
rationality or irrationality is under consideration. Species of non-epistemic
rationality and irrationality correspond to the kind of relevant goal: moral,
prudential, political, economic, aesthetic, or some other. A comprehensive
account of irrationality will elucidate epistemic and non-epistemic
irrationality as well as such sources of irrationality as weakness of will and
ungrounded belief.
esse:“est” (“Homo
animale rationalis est”Aristotle, cited by Grice in “Aristotle on the
multiplicity of being”)“is” is the third person singular form of the verb ‘be’,
with at least three fundamental usages that philosophers distinguish according
to the resources required for a proper semantic representation. First, there is
the ‘is’ of existence, which Grice finds otiose“Marmaduke Bloggs is a journalist
who climbed Mt Everest on hands and kneesa typical invention by journalists”.
(There is a unicorn in the garden: Dx (Ux8Gx)) uses the existential quantifier.
Bellerophon’s dad: “There is a flying horse in the stable.” “That’s mine,
dad.”Then, second, there is the ‘is’ of identity (Hesperus is Phosphorus: j %
k) employs the predicate of identity, or dyadic relation of “=,” as per
Leibniz’s problem“The king of France”Kx = Ky. Then third there is the ‘is’ of
predication, which can be essential (izzing) or accidentail (hazzing). (Samson
is strong: Sj) merely juxtaposes predicate symbol and proper name. Some controversy
attends the first usage. Some (notably that eccentric philosopher that went by
the name of Meinong) maintain that ‘is’ applies more broadly than ‘exists.’
“Is” produces truths when combined with ‘deer’ and ‘unicorn.’ ‘Exists,’ rather
than ‘is’, produces a truth when combined with ‘deer’ -- but not ‘unicorn’.
Aquinas takes “esse” to denote some special activity that every existing thing necessarily
performs, which would seem to imply that with ‘est’ they attribute more to an
object than we do with ‘exists’. Other issues arise in connection with the
second usage. Does, e.g. “Hesperus is Phosphorus,” attribute anything more to
the heavenly body than its identity with itself? Consideration of such a
question leads Frege, wrongly to conclude, in what Ryle calls the “Fido”-Fido
theory of meaning that names (and other meaningful expressions) of ordinary
language have a “sense” or “mode of presenting” the thing to which they refer
that representations within our standard, extensional logical systems fail to
expose. The distinction between the ‘is’ of identity and the ‘is’ of
predication parallels Frege’s distinction between ‘objekt” and concept: words
signifying objects stand to the right of the ‘is’ of identity and those
signifying concepts stand to the right of the ‘is’ of predication. Although it
seems remarkable that so many deep and difficult philosophical concepts should
link to a single short and commonplace word, we should perhaps not read too
much into that observation. Grecian and Roman indeed divide the various roles
played by English’s compact copula among several constructions, but there are
dialects, even within Oxford, that use the expression “is” for other purposes. Refs.:
H. P. Grice, “Aristotle on the multiplicity of being.”
-ism: used by Grice
derogatorily. In his ascent to the City of the Eternal Truth, he meets twelve
–isms, which he orders alphabetically. These are: Empiricism. Extensionalism.
Functionalism. MaterialismMechanism. Naturalism. Nominalism. Phenomenalism.
Positivism. Physicalism. Reductionism. Scepticism. Grice’s implicaturum is that
each is a form of, er, minimalism, as opposed to maximalism. He also seems to
implicate that, while embracing one of those –isms is a reductionist vice,
embracing their opposites is a Christian virtueHe explicitly refers to the name
of Bunyan’s protagonist, “Christian”“in a much more publicized journey, I
grant.” So let’s see how we can correlate each vicious heathen ism with the
Griceian Christian virtuous ism. Empiricism. “Surely not all is experience. My
bones are not.” Opposite: Rationalism. Extensionalism. Surely the empty set
cannot end up being the fullest! Opposite Intensionalism. Functionalism. What
is the function of love? We have to extend functionalism to cover one’s concern
for the otherAnd also there’s otiosity. Opposite: Mentalism. MaterialismMy
bones are ‘hyle,’ but my eternal soul ’t. Opposite Spiritualism. MechanismSurely there is finality in nature,
and God designed it. Opposite Vitalism. NaturalismSurely Aristotle meant
something by ‘ta meta ta physica,’ There is a transnatural realm. Opposite:
Transnaturalism. Nominalism. Occam was
good, except with his ‘sermo mentalis.’ Opposite: Realism. PhenomenalismAustin
and Grice soon realised that Berlin was wrong. Opposite ‘thing’-language-ism.
PositivismAnd then there’s not. Opposite: Negativism. PhysicalismSurely my soul is not a brain
state. Opposite: Transnaturalism, since Physicalismm and Naturalism mean the
same thing, ony in Greek, the other in Latin. ReductionismJulie is wrong when she thinks I’m
a reductionist. Opposite: Reductivism. Scepticism:
Surely there’s common sense. Opposite: Common-Sensism. Refs: H. P. Grice,
“Prejudices and predilections; which become, the life and opinions of H. P. Grice,”
The Grice Papers, BANC.
Istituto italiano
per gli studi filosofici: the title is telling, This is an institute for
philosophical studies, aka ‘research.’ Cf. Witters, “Philosophische
untersuchungen,” translated as ‘investigations.’ Grice prefers ‘studio,’ as in
‘studi’ (Studies in the way of words).
No comments:
Post a Comment