more
grice to the mill:
Mill: Scots-born philosopher (“One should take grice to one mill but not to the
mill –“ Grice --) and social theorist. He applied the utilitarianism of his
contemporary Bentham to such social matters as systems of education and
government, law and penal systems, and colonial policy. He also advocated the
associationism of Hume. Mill was an influential thinker in early
nineteenth-century London, but his most important role in the history of
philosophy was the influence he had on his son, J. S. Mill. He raised his more
famous son as a living experiment in his associationist theory of education.
His utilitarian views were developed and extended by J. S. Mill, while his
associationism was also adopted by his son and became a precursor of the
latter’s phenomenalism. More grice to the mill -- Mill, Scots
London-born empiricist philosopher and utilitarian social reformer. He was the
son of Mill, a leading defender of Bentham’s utilitarianism, and an advocate of
reforms based on that philosophy. Mill was educated by his father (and thus “at
Oxford we always considered him an outsider!”Grice) in accordance with the
principles of the associationist psychology adopted by the Benthamites and
deriving from David Hartley, and was raised with the expectation that he would
become a defender of the principles of the Benthamite school. Mill begins the
study of Grecian at three and Roman at eight, and later assisted Mill in
educating his brothers. He went to France to learn the language (“sc. French
--” Grice ), and studied chemistry and mathematics at Montpellier. He wrote
regularly for the Westminster Review, the Benthamite journal. He underwent a
mental crisis that lasted some months. This he later attributed to his rigid
education; in any case he emerged from a period of deep depression still
advocating utilitarianism but in a very much revised version. Mill visits Paris
during the revolution, meeting Lafayette and other popular leaders, and was
introduced to the writings of Saint-Simon and Comte. He also met Harriet
Taylor, to whom he immediately became devoted. They married only in 1851, when
Taylor died. He joined the India House headquarters of the East India Company,
serving as an examiner until the company was dissolved in 1858 in the aftermath
of the Indian Mutiny. Mill sat in Parliament. Harriet dies and is buried at
Avignon, where Mill thereafter regularly resided for half of each year. Mill’s
major works are his “System of Logic, Deductive and Inductive,” “Political
Economy,” “On Liberty,” “Utilitarianism,” in Fraser’s Magazine, “The Subjection
of Women”Grice: “I wrote a paper for Hardie on this. His only comment was:
‘what do you mean by ‘of’?” --; “An Examination of Sir William Hamilton’s
Philosophy,” and “Religion.” His writing style is excellent, and his history of
his own mental development, the “Autobiography” is a major Victorian literary
text. His main opponents philosophically are Whewell and Hamilton, and it is
safe to say that after Mill their intuitionism in metaphysics, philosophy of
science, and ethics could no longer be defended. Mill’s own views were later to
be eclipsed by those of such Oxonian lumaries as T. H. Green, F. H. Bradley,
and the other Oxonian Hegelian idealists (Bosanquet, Pater). His views in
metaphysics and philosophy of science have been revived and defended by Russell
and the logical positivists, while his utilitarian ethics has regained its
status as one of the major ethical theories. His social philosophy deeply
infuenced the Fabians and other groups on the English left; its impact
continues. Mill was brought up on the basis of, and to believe in, the strict
utilitarianism of his father. His own development largely consisted in his
attempts to broaden it, to include a larger and more sympathetic view of human
nature, and to humanize its program to fit this broader view of human beings.
In his own view, no doubt largely correct, he did not so much reject his
father’s principles as fill in the gaps and eliminate rigidities and crudities.
He continued throughout his life his father’s concern to propagate principles
conceived as essential to promoting human happiness. These extended from moral
principles to principles of political economy to principles of logic and
metaphysics. Mill’s vision of the human being was rooted in the psychological
theories he defended. Arguing against the intuitionism of Reid and Whewell, he
extended the associationism of his father. On this theory, ideas have their
genetic antecedents in sensation, a complex idea being generated out of a
unique set of simple, elementary ideas, through associations based on regular
patterns in the presented sensations. Psychological analysis reveals the
elementary parts of ideas and is thus the means for investigating the causal
origins of our ideas. The elder Mill followed Locke in conceiving analysis on
the model of definition, so that the psychological elements are present in the
idea they compose and the idea is nothing but its associated elements. Mill
emerged from his mental crisis with the recognition that mental states are
often more than the sum of the ideas that are their genetic antecedents. On the
revised model of analysis, the analytical elements are not actually present in
the idea, but are present only dispositionally, ready to be recovered by
association under the analytical set. Moreover, it is words that are defined,
not ideas, though words become general only by becoming associated with ideas.
Analysis thus became an empirical task, rather than something settled a priori
according to one’s metaphysical predispositions, as it had been for Mill’s
predecessors. The revised psychology allowed the younger Mill to account
empirically in a much more subtle way than could the earlier associationists
for the variations in our states of feeling. Thus, for example, the original
motive to action is simple sensations of pleasure, but through association
things originally desired as means become associated with pleasure and thereby
become desirable as ends, as parts of one’s pleasure. But these acquired
motives are not merely the sum of the simple pleasures that make them up; they
are more than the sum of those genetic antecedents. Thus, while Mill holds with
his father that persons seek to maximize their pleasures, unlike his father he
also holds that not all ends are selfish, and that pleasures are not only
quantitatively but also qualitatively distinct. In ethics, then, Mill can hold
with the intuitionists that our moral sentiments are qualitatively distinct
from the lower pleasures, while denying the intuitionist conclusion that they
are innate. Mill urges, with his father and Bentham, that the basic moral norm
is the principle of utility, that an action is right provided it maximizes
human welfare. Persons always act to maximize their own pleasure, but the
general human welfare can be among the pleasures they seek. Mill’s position
thus does not have the problems that the apparently egoistic psychology of his
father created. The only issue is whether a person ought to maximize human
welfare, whether he ought to be the sort of person who is so motivated. Mill’s
own ethics is that this is indeed what one ought to be, and he tries to bring
this state of human being about in others by example, and by urging them to
expand the range of their human sympathy through poetry like that of
Wordsworth, through reading the great moral teachers such as Jesus and
Socrates, and by other means of moral improvement. Mill also offers an argument
in defense of the principle of utility. Against those who, like Whewell, argue
that there is no basic right to pleasure, he argues that as a matter of
psychological fact, people seek only pleasure, and concludes that it is
therefore pointless to suggest that they ought to do anything other than this.
The test of experience thus excludes ends other than pleasure. This is a
plausible argument. Less plausible is his further argument that since each
seeks her own pleasure, the general good is the (ultimate) aim of all. This
latter argument unfortunately presupposes the invalid premise that the law for
a whole follows from laws about the individual parts of the whole. Other moral
rules can be justified by their utility and the test of experience. For
example, such principles of justice as the rules of property and of promise
keeping are justified by their role in serving certain fundamental human needs.
Exceptions to such secondary rules can be justified by appeal to the principle
of utility. But there is also utility in not requiring in every application a
lengthy utilitarian calculation, which provides an objective justification for
overlooking what might be, objectively considered in terms of the principle of
utility, an exception to a secondary rule. Logic and philosophy of science. The
test of experience is also brought to bear on norms other than those of
morality, e.g., those of logic and philosophy of science. Mill argues, against
the rationalists, that science is not demonstrative from intuited premises.
Reason in the sense of deductive logic is not a logic of proof but a logic of
consistency. The basic axioms of any science are derived through generalization
from experience. The axioms are generic and delimit a range of possible
hypotheses about the specific subject matter to which they are applied. It is
then the task of experiment and, more generally, observation to eliminate the
false and determine which hypothesis is true. The axioms, the most generic of
which is the law of the uniformity of nature, are arrived at not by this sort
of process of elimination but by induction by simple enumeration: Mill argues
plausibly that on the basis of experience this method becomes more reliable the
more generic is the hypothesis that it is used to justify. But like Hume, Mill
holds that for any generalization from experience the evidence can never be
sufficient to eliminate all possibility of doubt. Explanation for Mill, as for
the logical positivists, is by subsumption under matter-of-fact
generalizations. Causal generalizations that state sufficient or necessary and
sufficient conditions are more desirable as explanations than mere
regularities. Still more desirable is a law or body of laws that gives
necessary and sufficient conditions for any state of a system, i.e., a body of
laws for which there are no explanatory gaps. As for explanation of laws, this
can proceed either by filling in gaps or by subsuming the law under a generic theory
that unifies the laws of several areas. Mill argues that in the social sciences
the subject matter is too complex to apply the normal methods of experiment.
But he also rejects the purely deductive method of the Benthamite political
economists such as his father and David Ricardo. Rather, one must deduce the
laws for wholes, i.e., the laws of economics and sociology, from the laws for
the parts, i.e., the laws of psychology, and then test these derived laws
against the accumulated data of history. Mill got the idea for this methodology
of the social sciences from Comte, but unfortunately it is vitiated by the
false idea, already noted, that one can deduce without any further premise the
laws for wholes from the laws for the parts. Subsequent methodologists of the
social sciences have come to substitute the more reasonable methods of
statistics for this invalid method Mill proposes. Mill’s account of scientific
method does work well for empirical sciences, such as the chemistry of his day.
He was able to show, too, that it made good sense of a great deal of physics,
though it is arguable that it cannot do justice to theories that explain the
atomic and subatomic structure of mattersomething Mill himself was prepared to
acknowledge. He also attempted to apply his views to geometry, and even more
implausibly, to arithmetic. In these areas, he was certainly bested by Whewell,
and the world had to wait for the logical work of Russell and Whitehead before
a reasonable empiricist account of these areas became available. Metaphysics.
The starting point of all inference is the sort of observation we make through
our senses, and since we know by experience that we have no ideas that do not
derive from sense experience, it follows that we cannot conceive a world beyond
what we know by sense. To be sure, we can form generic concepts, such as that
of an event, which enable us to form concepts of entities that we cannot
experience, e.g., the concept of the tiny speck of sand that stopped my watch
or the concept of the event that is the cause of my present sensation. Mill
held that what we know of the laws of sensation is sufficient to make it
reasonable to suppose that the immediate cause of one’s present sensation is
the state of one’s nervous system. Our concept of an objective physical object
is also of this sort; it is the set of events that jointly constitute a
permanent possible cause of sensation. It is our inductive knowledge of laws
that justifies our beliefs that there are entities that fall under these
concepts. The point is that these entities, while unsensed, are (we reasonably
believe) part of the world we know by means of our senses. The contrast is to
such things as the substances and transcendent Ideas of rationalists, or the
God of religious believers, entities that can be known only by means that go
beyond sense and inductive inferences therefrom. Mill remained essentially
pre-Darwinian, and was willing to allow the plausibility of the hypothesis that
there is an intelligent designer for the perceived order in the universe. But
this has the status of a scientific hypothesis rather than a belief in a
substance or a personal God transcending the world of experience and time.
Whewell, at once the defender of rationalist ideas for science and for ethics
and the defender of established religion, is a special object for Mill’s scorn.
Social and political thought. While Mill is respectful of the teachings of
religious leaders such as Jesus, the institutions of religion, like those of
government and of the economy, are all to be subjected to criticism based on
the principle of utility: Do they contribute to human welfare? Are there any
alternatives that could do better? Thus, Mill argues that a free-market economy
has many benefits but that the defects, in terms of poverty for many, that
result from private ownership of the means of production may imply that we
should institute the alternative of socialism or public ownership of the means
of production. He similarly argues for the utility of liberty as a social institution:
under such a social order individuality will be encouraged, and this
individuality in turn tends to produce innovations in knowledge, technology,
and morality that contribute significantly to improving the general welfare.
Conversely, institutions and traditions that stifle individuality, as religious
institutions often do, should gradually be reformed. Similar considerations
argue on the one hand for democratic representative government and on the other
for a legal system of rights that can defend individuals from the tyranny of
public opinion and of the majority. Status of women. Among the things for which
Mill campaigned were women’s rights, women’s suffrage, and equal access for
women to education and to occupations. He could not escape his age and
continued to hold that it was undesirable for a woman to work to help support
her family. While he disagreed with his father and Bentham that all motives are
egoistic and self-interested, he nonetheless held that in most affairs of
economics and government such motives are dominant. He was therefore led to
disagree with his father that votes for women are unnecessary since the male
can speak for the family. Women’s votes are needed precisely to check the
pursuit of male self-interest. More generally, equality is essential if the
interests of the family as such are to be served, rather than making the family
serve male self-interest as had hitherto been the case. Changing the relation
between men and women to one of equality will force both parties to curb their
self-interest and broaden their social sympathies to include others. Women’s
suffrage is an essential step toward the moral improvement of humankind. Grice:
“I am fascinated by how Griceian Mill can be.” “In
treating of the ‘proposition,’ some considerations of a comparatively
elementary nature respecting its form must be premised,and the ‘import’ which
the emisor conveyed by a token of an expression of a ‘proposition’for one
cannot communicate but that the cat
is on the mat -- . A proposition is a move in the conversational game in which
a feature (P) is predicated of the subject (S)The S is PThe subject and the
predicateas in “Strawson’s dog is shaggy” -- are all that is necessarily
required to make up a proposition. But as we can not conclude from merely
seeing two “Strawson’s dog” and “shaggy” put together, that “Strawson’s dog” is
the subject and “shaggy” the predicate, that is, that the predicate is intended
to be ‘predicated’ of the subject, it is necessary that there should be some
mode or form of indicating that such is, in Griceian parlance, the ‘intention,’
sc. some sign to signal this predicationmy father says that as I was growing
up, I would say “dog shaggy”The explicit communication of a predication is
sometimes done by a slight alteration of the expression that is the predicate
or the expression that is the subjectsc., a ‘casus’even if it is ‘rectum’or
‘obliquum’ -- inflectum.” Grice: “The
example Mill gives is “Fire burns.”” “The change from ‘burn’ to ‘burns’ shows
that the emisor intends to predicate the predicate “burn” of the subject “fire.”
But this function is more commonly fulfilled by the copula, which serves the
purporse of the sign of predication, “est,” (or by nothing at all as in my
beloved Grecian! “Anthropos logikos,” -- when the predication is, again to use
Griceian parlance, ‘intended.’” Grice: “Mill gives the example, ‘The king of
France is smooth.” “It may seem to be implied, or implicatedimplicatum,
implicaturum -- not only that the quality ‘smooth’ can be predicated of the
king of France, but moreover that there is a King of France. Grice: “Mill
notes: ‘It’s different with ‘It is not the case that the king of France is
smooth’”. “This, however should not rush us to think that ‘is’ is aequi-vocal,
and that it can be ‘copula’ AND ‘praedicatum’, e. g. ‘… is a spatio-temporal
continuant.’ Grice: “Mill then gives my example: ‘Pegasus is [in Grecian
mythologyi. e. Pegasus is *believed* to exist by this or that Grecian
mythographer], but does not exist.’” “A flying horse is a fiction of some
Grecian poets.” Grice: “Mill hastens to add that the annulation of the
implicaturum is implicit or contextual.” “By uttering ‘A flying horse is a
Griceian allegory’ the emisor cannot possibly implicate that a flying horse is
a spatio-temporal continuant, since by uttering the proposition itself the
emisor is expressly asserting that the thing has no real existence.” “Many
volumes might be filled”Grice: “And will be filled by Strawson!” -- with the
frivolous speculations concerning the nature of being (ƒø D½, øPÃw±, ens,
entitas, essentia, and the like), which have arisen from overlooking the
implicaturum of ‘est’; from supposing that when by uttering “S est P” the
emisor communicates that S is a spatio-temporal continuant. when by uttering
it, the emisor communicates that the S is some *specified* thing, a horse and a
flier, to be a phantom, a mythological construct, or the invention of the
journalists (like Marmaduke Bloggs, who climbed Mt. Everest on hands and knees)
even to be a nonentity (as a squared circle) it must still, at bottom, answer
to the same idea; and that a proposition must be found for it which shall suit
all these cases. The fog which rises from this very narrow spot diffuses itself
over the whole surface of ontology. Yet it becomes us not to triumph over the
great intellect of Ariskant because we are now able to preserve ourselves from
many errors into which he, perhaps inevitably, fell. The fire-teazer of a steam-engine
produces by his exertions far greater effects than Milo of Crotona could, but
he is not therefore a stronger man. The Grecianslike some uneducated Englishman
-- seldom knew any language but their own! This render it far more difficult
for *them* than it is for us, to acquire a readiness in detecting the
implicaturum. One of the advantages of having accurately studied Grecian and
Roman at Clifton, especially of those languages which Ariskant used as the
vehicle of his thought, is the practical lesson we learn respecting the implicaturm,
by finding that the same expression in Grecian, say (e. g. ‘is’) corresponds,
on different occasions, to a different expression in Gricese, say (i. e.
‘hazz’). When not thus exercised, even the strongest understandings find it
difficult to believe that things which fall under a class, have not in some
respect or other a common nature; and often expend much labour very unprofitably
(as is frequently done by Ariskant) in a vain attempt to discover in what this
common nature consists. But, the habit once formed, intellects much inferior
are capable of detecting even an impicaturum which is common or generalised to
Grecian and Griceses: and it is surprising that this sous-entendu or
impicaturum now under consideration, though it is ordinary at Oxford as well as
in the ancient, should have been overlooked by almost every philosopher until
Grice. Grice: “Mill was proud of Mill.” “The quantity of futilitarian speculation
which had been caused by a misapprehension of the nature of the copula, is hinted
at by Hobbes; but my father is the first who distinctly characterized the implicaturm,
and point out to me how many errors in the received systems of philosophy it
has had to answer for. It has, indeed, misled the moderns scarcely less than
the ancients, though their mistakes, because our understandings are not yet so
completely emancipated from their influence, do not appear equally
irrational. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Grice to the Mill,” L. G. Wilton,
“Mill’s mentalism,” for the Grice Club. Grice treasured Hardie’s invocation of
Mill’s method during a traffic incident on the HIhg. Mill’s methods, procedures
for discovering necessary conditions, sufficient conditions, and necessary and
sufficient conditions, where these terms are used as follows: if whenever A
then B (e.g., whenever there is a fire then oxygen is present), then B is a
necessary (causal) condition for A; and if whenever C then D (e.g., whenever
sugar is in water, then it dissolves), then C is a sufficient (causal)
condition for D. Method of agreement. Given a pair of hypotheses about
necessary conditions, e.g., (1) whenever A then B1 whenever A then B2, then an
observation of an individual that is A but not B2 will eliminate the second
alternative as false, enabling one to conclude that the uneliminated hypothesis
is true. This method for discovering necessary conditions is called the method
of agreement. To illustrate the method of agreement, suppose several people
have all become ill upon eating potato salad at a restaurant, but have in other
respects had quite different meals, some having meat, some vegetables, some desserts.
Being ill and not eating meat eliminates the latter as the cause; being ill and
not eating dessert eliminates the latter as cause; and so on. It is the
condition in which the individuals who are ill agree that is not eliminated. We
therefore conclude that this is the cause or necessary condition for the
illness. Method of difference. Similarly, with respect to the pair of
hypotheses concerning sufficient conditions, e.g., (2) whenever C1 then D
whenever C2 then D, an individual that is C1 but not D will eliminate the first
hypothesis and enable one to conclude that the second is true. This is the
method of difference. A simple change will often yield an example of an
inference to a sufficient condition by the method of difference. If something
changes from C1 to C2, and also thereupon changes from notD to D, one can
conclude that C2, in respect of which the instances differ, is the cause of D.
Thus, Becquerel discovered that burns can be caused by radium, i.e., proximity
to radium is a sufficient but not necessary condition for being burned, when he
inferred that the radium he carried in a bottle in his pocket was the cause of
a burn on his leg by noting that the presence of the radium was the only
relevant causal difference between the time when the burn was present and the
earlier time when it was not. Clearly, both methods can be generalized to cover
any finite number of hypotheses in the set of alternatives. The two methods can
be combined in the joint method of agreement and difference to yield the
discovery of conditions that are both necessary and sufficient. Sometimes it is
possible to eliminate an alternative, not on the basis of observation, but on
the basis of previously inferred laws. If we know by previous inductions that
no C2 is D, then observation is not needed to eliminate the second hypothesis
of (2), and we can infer that what remains, or the residue, gives us the
sufficient condition for D. Where an alternative is eliminated by previous
inductions, we are said to use the method of residues. The methods may be
generalized to cover quantitative laws. A cause of Q may be taken not to be a
necessary and sufficient condition, but a factor P on whose magnitude the
magnitude of Q functionally depends. If P varies when Q varies, then one can use
methods of elimination to infer that P causes Q. This has been called the
method of concomitant variation. More complicated methods are needed to infer
what precisely is the function that correlates the two magnitudes. Clearly, if
we are to conclude that one of (1) is true on the basis of the given data, we
need an additional premise to the effect that there is at least one necessary
condition for B and it is among the set consisting of A1 and A2. 4065m-r.qxd
08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 571 Mimamsa mimesis 572 The existence claim here is
known as a principle of determinism and the delimited range of alternatives is
known as a principle of limited variety. Similar principles are needed for the
other methods. Such principles are clearly empirical, and must be given prior
inductive support if the methods of elimination are to be conclusive. In
practice, generic scientific theories provide these principles to guide the
experimenter. Thus, on the basis of the observations that justified Kepler’s
laws, Newton was able to eliminate all hypotheses concerning the force that
moved the planets about the sun save the inverse square law, provided that he
also assumed as applying to this specific sort of system the generic
theoretical framework established by his three laws of motion, which asserted
that there exists a force accounting for the motion of the planets
(determinism) and that this force satisfies certain conditions, e.g., the
action-reaction law (limited variety). The eliminative methods constitute the
basic logic of the experimental method in science. They were first elaborated
by Francis Bacon (see J. Weinberg, Abstraction, Relation, and Induction, 1965).
They were restated by Hume, elaborated by J. F. W. Herschel, and located
centrally in scientific methodology by J. S. Mill. Their structure was studied
from the perspective of modern developments in logic by Keynes, W. E. Johnson,
and especially Broad. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Grice to the Mill,” G. L. Brook,
“Mill’s Mentalism”, Sutherland, “Mill in Dodgson’s Semiotics.”
Icon: Iconicity and mimesis. Grice: “If it
hurts, you involuntarily go ‘Ouch.’ ‘Ouch’ can voluntarily become a vehicle for
communication, under voluntary control. But we must allow for any expression to
become a vehicle for communication, even if there is no iconic or mimetic
association -- (from Greek mimesis, ‘imitation’), the modeling of one thing on
another, or the presenting of one thing by another; imitation. The concept
played a central role in the account formulated by Plato and Aristotle of what
we would now call the fine arts. The poet, the dramatist, the painter, the
musician, the sculptor, all compose a mimesis of reality. Though Plato, in his
account of painting, definitely had in mind that the painter imitates physical
reality, the general concept of mimesis used by Plato and Aristotle is usually
better translated by ‘representation’ than by ‘imitation’: it belongs to the
nature of the work of art to represent, to re-present, reality. This
representational or mimetic theory of art remained far and away the dominant
theory in the West until the rise of Romanticismthough by no means everyone
agreed with Plato that it is concrete items of physical reality that the artist
represents. The hold of the mimetic theory was broken by the insistence of the
Romantics that, rather than the work of art being an imitation, it is the
artist who, in his or her creative activity, imitates Nature or God by
composing an autonomous object. Few contemporary theorists of art would say
that the essence of art is to represent; the mimetic theory is all but dead. In
part this is a reflection of the power of the Romantic alternative to the
mimetic theory; in part it is a reflection of the rise to prominence over the
last century of nonobjective, abstract painting and sculpture and of “absolute”
instrumental music. Nonetheless, the phenomenon of representation has not
ceased to draw the attention of theorists. In recent years three quite
different general theories of representation have appeared: Nelson Goodman’s
(The Languages of Art), Nicholas Wolterstorff’s (Works and Worlds of Art), and
Kendall Walton’s (Mimesis as Make-Believe). Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Aristotle’s
mimesis and Paget’s ta-ta theory of communication.”
Ta-ta: Paget: author beloved by Grice,
inventor of what Grice calls the “ta-ta” theory of communication.
Grice’s bellow -- “Ouch”Grice’s theory of
communication in “Meaning revisited.” Grice’s paradox of the ta-ta. Why would a
simulation of pain be taken as a sign of pain if the sendee recognises that the
emisor is simulating a ‘causally provoked,’ rather than under voluntary
control, expression of pain. Grice’s wording is subtle and good. “Stage one in
the operation involves the supposition that the creature actually voluntarily
produces a certain sort of behaviour which is such that its nonvoluntary
production would be evidence that the creature is, let us say, in pain.” Cf.
Ockham, ‘risus naturaliter significat interiorem laetitiam.’ But the laughter
does NOT resemble the inner joy. There is natural causality, but not iconicity.
So what Grice and Ockham are after is ‘artificial laughter’ which does imitate
(mimic) natural laughter. “Risus significat naturaliter interiorem laetitiam.”
“Risus voluntaries significat NON-naturaliter interiorem laetitiam.” Ockham
wants to say that it is via the iconicity of the artificial laughter that the
communication is effected. So if ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny, non-natural
communication recapitulates natural communication. “Risus voluntarius
non-significat naturaliter (via risus involutarius significans naturaliter)
interiorem laetitiam. “The kinds of
cases of this which come most obviously to mind will be cases of faking or
deception.” “A creature normally voluntarily produces behaviour not only when,
but *because*, its nonvoluntary production would be evidence that the creature
is in a certain state, with the effect that the rest of the world, other
creatures around, treat the production, which is in fact voluntary, as if it
were a nonvoluntary production.” “That is, they come to just the same
conclusion about the creature’s being in the state in question, the signalled state.”
Note Grice’s technical use of Shannon’s ‘signal.’ “The purpose of the creature’s producing the
behaviour voluntarily would be so that the rest of the world should think that
it is in the state which the nonvoluntary production would signify.” Note that at this point, while it is behaviour
that signifiesthe metabolia has to apply ultimately to the emisor. So that it
is the creature who signifiesor it signifies. The fact that Grice uses ‘it’ for
the creature is tellingFor, if Grice claims that only rational Homo sapiens can
communicate, Homo sapiens is an ‘it.’ “In
stage two not only does creature X produce this behaviour voluntarily, instead
of nonvoluntarily, as in the primitive state.” By primitive he means Stage 0. “…
but we also assume that it is *recognised* by another creature Y, involved with
X in some transaction, as being the voluntary production of certain form of
behaviour the nonvoluntary production of which evidences, say, pain.” So again,
there is no iconicity. Does the “Ouch” in Stage 0 ‘imitate’ the pain. How can
‘pain,’ which is a state of the soul, be ‘imitated’ via a physical, material,
medium? There are ways. Pain may involve some discomfort in the soul. The cry,
“Ouch,” involuntary, ‘imitates this disturbance or discomfort. But what about
inner joy and the laughter. Ape studies have demonstrated that the show of
teeth is a sign of agreession. It’s not Mona Lisa’s smile. So Mona Lisa’s inner
joy is signified by her smile. Is this iconic? Is there a resemblance or
imitation here? Yes. Because the inner joy is the opposite of discomfort, and
the distended muscles around the mouth resemble the distended state of the
immaterial soul of Mona Lisa. As a functionalist, Grice was also interested in
the input. What makes Mona Lisa smile? What makes you to utter “Ouch” when you
step on a thorn? Is the disturbance (of pain, since this is the example Grice
uses) or the distension of joy resemble the external stimulus? Yes. Because a
thorn on the ground is NOT to be thereit is a disturbance of the environment.
Looking at Leonardo da Vinci who actually is commanding, “Smile!” is enough of
a stimulus for “The Gioconda” to become what Italians call ‘the gioconda.’ “That is, creature X is now supposed not just
to simulate pain-behaviour, but also to be recognised as simulating
pain-behaviour.” “The import of the recognition by Y that the production is
voluntary UNDERMINES, of course, any tendency on the part of Y to come to the
conclusion that creature X is in pain.” “So, one might ask, what would be
required to restore the situation: what COULD be ADDED which would be an
‘antidote,’ so to speak, to the dissolution on the part of Y of the idea that X
is in pain?” “A first step in this direction would be to go to what we might
think of as stage three.” “Here, we suppose that creature Y not only recognises
that the behaviour is voluntary on the part of X, but also recognises that X
*intends* Y to recognise HIS [no longer its] behaviour as voluntary.” “That is,
we have now undermined the idea that this is a straightforward piece of
deception.” “Deceiving consists in trying to get a creature to accept certain
things AS SIGNS [but cf. Grice on words not being signs in ‘Meaning’] as
something or other without knowing that this is a faked case.” “Here, however, we would have a sort of perverse
faked case, in which something is faked but at the same time a clear indication
is put in that the faking has been done.” Cf. Warhol on Campbell soup and why Aristotle
found ‘mimesis’ so key “Creature Y can be thought of as initially BAFFLED by
this conflicting performance.” “There is this creature, as it were, simulating
pain, but announcing, in a certain sense, that this is what IT [again it, not
he] is doing.” “What on earth can IT be up to?” “It seems to me that if Y does
raise the question of why X should be doing this, it might first come up with
the idea that X is engaging in some form of play or make-believe, a game to
which, since X’s behaviour is seemingly directed TOWARDS Y [alla Kurt Lewin], Y
is EXPECTED OR INTENDED to make some appropriate contribution. “Cases
susceptible of such an interpretation I regard as belonging to stage four.” “But,
we may suppose, there might be cases which could NOT be handled in this way.” “If
Y is to be expected to be a fellow-participant with X in some form of play, it
ought to be possible for Y to recognise what kind of contribution Y [the
sendeethe signalee] is supposed to make; and we can envisage the possibility that
Y has no clue on which to base such recognition, or again that though SOME form
of contribution seems to be SUGGESTED, when Y obliges by coming up with it, X,
instead of producing further pain-behaviour, gets cross and perhaps repeats its
original, and now problematic, performance.” [“Ouch!”]. “We now reach stage five, at which Y supposes
not that X is engaged in play, but that what X is doing is trying to get Y to
believe OR ACCEPT THAT X *is* in pain.” That is, not just faking that he is in
pain, but faking that he is in pain because he IS in pain. Surely the pain
cannot be that GROSS if he has time to consider all this! So “communicating
pain” applies to “MINOR pain,” which the Epicureans called “communicable pains”
(like a tooth-acheVitters after reading Diels, came up with the idea that
Marius was wrong and that a tooth-pain is NOT communicable! “: that is, trying to get Y to believe in or
accept the presence of that state in X which the produced behaviour, when
produced NONVOLUNTARILY, in in fact a natural sign of, naturally means.” Here
the under-metabolis is avoidable: “when produced nonvolutarily, in in fact THE
EFFECT OF, or the consequence of.” And if you want to avoid ending a sentence
with a preposition: “that STATE in X of which the produced behaviour is the
CONSEQUENCE or EFFECT. CAUSATUM. The causans-causatum distinction. “More specifically, one might say that at
stage five, creature Y recognises that creature X in the first place INTENDS
that Y recognise the production of the sign of pain (of what is USUALLY the
sign of pain) to be voluntary, and further intends that Y should regard this
first intention I1 as being a sufficient reason for Y to BELIEVE that X is in
pain.” But would that expectation occur in a one-off predicament? “And that X
has these intentions because he has the additional further INTENTION I3 that Y
should not MERELY have sufficient REASON for believing that X is in pain, but
should actually [and AND] believe it.” This substep shows that for Grice it’s
the INFLUENCING and being influenced by others (or the institution of
decision), rather than the exchange of information (giving and receiving
information), which is basic. The protreptic, not the exhibitive. “Whether or
not in these circumstances X will not merely recognise that X intends, in a certain
rather QUEER way, to get Y to believe that X is in pain, whether Y not only
recognises this but actually goes on to believe that X is in pain, would
presumably DEPEND on a FURTHER SET OF CONDITIONS which can be summed up under
the general heading that Y should regard X as TRUSTWORTHY [as a good
meta-faker!] in one or another of perhaps a variety of ways.” This is Grice’s
nod to G. J. Warnock’s complex analysis of the variety of ways in which one can
be said to be ‘trustworthy’last chapter of ‘trustworthiness in conversation,’
in Warnock’s brilliant, “The object of morality.” “For example, suppose Y
thinks that, either in general or at least in THIS type of CASE [this token, a
one-off predicament? Not likely!] X would NOT want Y to believe that X is in
pain UNLESS [to use R. Hall and H. L. A. Hart’s favourite excluder defeater] X
really WERE in pain.” [Cf. Hardie, “Why do you use the subjunctive?” “Were
Hardie to be here, I would respond!”Grice]. “Suppose also (this would perhaps
not apply to a case of pain but might apply to THE COMMUNICATION of other
states [what is communicated is ONLY a state of the soul] that Y also believes
that X is trustworthy, not just in the sense of not being malignant
[malevolent, ill-willed, maleficent], but also in the sense of being, as it
were, in general [semiotically] responsible, for example, being the sort of
creature, who takes adequate trouble to make sure that what HE [not it] is
trying to get the other creature to believe is in fact the case.” Sill, “’I
have a toothache” never entails that the emisor has a toothache!a sign is
anything we can lie with!” (Eco). “… and who is not careless, negligent, or
rash.” “Then, given the general fulfilment of the idea that Y regards X either
in general or in this particular case of being trustworthy in this kind of
competent, careful, way, one would regard it as RATIONAL [reasonable] not only
for Y to recognise these intentions on the part of X that Y should have certain
beliefs about X’s being in pain, but also for Y actually to pass to adopting
these beliefs.” Stage six annuls mimesis, or lifts the requirement of mimesis“we relax this
requirement.” “As Judith Baker suggests, it would be unmanly to utter (or ‘let
out’) a (natural) bellow!” Here Grice speaks of the decibels of the emission of
the bellowas indicating this or that degree of pain. But what about “It’s
raining.” We have a state of affairs (not necessarily a state in the soul of the
emissor). So by relaxing the requirement, the emissor chooses a behaviour which
is “suggestive, in some recognizable way” with the state of affairs of rain
“without the performance having to be the causal effect of (or ‘response to,’
as Grice also has it) that state of affairs, sc. that it is raining. The connection becomes “non-natural,” or
‘artificial’: any link will doas long as the correlation is OBVIOUS,
pre-arranged, or foreknown.‘one-off predicament’. There are problems with
‘stage zero’ and ‘stage six.’ When it comes to stage zero, Grice is supposing,
obviously that a state of affairs is the CAUSE of some behaviour in a
creaturesince there is no interpretantthe phenomenon may very obliquely called
‘semiotic.’ “If a tree falls in the wood and nobody is listening…”So stage zero
need not involve a mimetic aspect. Since stage one involves ‘pain,’ i.e. the
proposition that ‘X is in pain,’ as Grice has it. Or as we would have it, ‘A is
in pain’ or ‘The emisor is in pain.’ Althought he uses the metaphor of the play
where B is expected or intended to make an appropriate contribution or move in
the game, it is one of action, he will have to accept that ‘The emisor is in
pain’ and act appropriately. But Grice is not at all interested in the cycle of
what B might doas Gardiner is, when he talks of a ‘conversational dyad.’ Grice
explores the conversational ‘dyad’ in his Oxford lectures on the conversational
imlicaturum. A poetic line might not do but: “A: I’m out of gas.” B: “There’s a
garage round the corner.”is the conversational dyad. In B’s behaviour, we come
to see that he has accepted that A is out of gas. And his ‘appropriate
contribution’ in the game goes beyond that acceptancehe makes a ‘sentence’ move
(“There is a garage round the corner.”). So strictly a conversational
implicaturum is the communicatum by the second item in a conversational dyad. Now
there are connections to be made between stage zero and stage six. Why? Well,
because stage six is intended to broaden the range of propositions that are
communicated to be OTHER than a ‘state’ in the emisorX is in pain --. But Grice
does not elaborate on the ‘essential psychological attitude’ requirement. Even
if we require this requirementGrice considers two requirements. The requirement
he is interested in relaxing is that of the CAUSAL connectionhe keeps using
‘natural’ misleadingly --. But can he get rid of it so easily? Because in stage
six, if the emisor wants to communicate that the cat is on the mat, or that it
is raining, it will be via his BELIEF that the cat is on the mat or that it is
raining. The cat being on the mat or it being raining would CAUSE the emisor to
have that belief. Believing is the CAUSAL consequence. Grice makes a comparison
between the mimesis or resemblance of a bellow produced voluntarily or notand
expands on the decibels. The ‘information’ one may derive at stage 0 of hearing
an emisor (who is unaware that he is being observed) is one that is such and
suchand it is decoded by de-correlating the decibels of the bellow. More
decibels, higher pain. There is a co-relation here. Grice ventures that perhaps
that’s too much information (he is following someone’s else objection). Why
would not X just ‘let out a natural bellow.’ Grice states there
areOBVIOUSLYvarioius reasons why he would notthe ‘obviously’ implicates the
objection is silly (typical tutee behaviour). The first is charming. Grice, seeing the
gender of the tutee, says that it woud be UNMANLY for A to let out a natural
bellow. He realizes that ‘unmanly’ may be considered ‘artless sexism’ (this is
the late mid-70s, and in the provinces!)So he turns the ‘unmanly’ into the
charmingly Oxonian, “ or otherwise uncreaturely.”which is a genial piece of
ironic coinage! Surely ‘manly’ and ‘unmanly,’ if it relates to ‘Homo sapiens,’
need not carry a sexist implicaturum. Another answer to the obvious objection
that Grice gives relates to the level of informativenessthe ‘artificial’ (as he
calls it)His argument is that if one takes Aristotle’s seriously, and the
‘artificial bellow’ is to ‘imitate’ the ‘natural bellow,’ it may not replicate
ALL THE ‘FEATURES’which is the expression Grice uses -- he means semiotic distinctive feature --. So
he does not have to calculate the ‘artificial bellow’ to correlate exactly to
the quantity of decibels that the ‘natural bellow’ does. This is important from
a CAUSAL point of view, or in terms of Grice’s causal theory of behaviour. A
specific pain (prooked by Stimulus S1) gives the RESPONSE R2with decibels D1. A
different stimulus S2 woud give a different RESPONSE R2, with different
decibels D2. So Grice is exploring the possibility of variance here. In a
causal involuntary scenario, there is nothing the creature can do. The stimulus
Sn will produce the creature Cn to be such that its response is Rn (where Rn is
a response with decibelsthis being the semiotic distinctive feature FnDn. When
it comes to the ‘artificial bellow,’ the emisor’s only point is to express the
proposition, ‘I am in pain,’ and not ‘I am in pain such that it causes a
natural bellow of decibels Dn,” which would flout the conversational postulate
of conversational fortitude. The overinformativeness would baffle the sendee,
if not the sender). At this point there is a break in the narrative, and Grice,
in a typical Oxonian way, goes on to say, “But then, we might just as well
relax the requirement that the proposition concerns a state of the sender.” He
gives no specific example, but refers to a ‘state of affairs’ which does NOT
involve a state of the senderAND ONE TO WHICH, HOWEVER, THE SENDER RESPONDS
with a behaviour. I. e. the state of the affairs, whatever it is, is the
stimulus, and the creature’s behaviour is the response. While ‘The cat is on
the mat’ or ‘It is raining’ does NOT obviously ‘communicate’ that the sender
BELIEVES that to be, the ‘behaviour’ which is the response to the external
state of affairs is mediated by this statethis is pure functionalism. So, in
getting at stage sixdue to the objection by his tuteehe must go back to stage
zero. Now, he adds MANY CRUCIAL features with these relaxations of the
requirements. Basically he is getting at GRICESE. And what he says is very
jocular. He knows he is lecturing to ‘service professionals,’ not philosophers,
so he keep adding irritating notes for them (but which we philosophers find
charming), “and we get to something like what people are getting at (correctly,
I would hope) when they speak of a semiotic system!” These characteristics are
elaborated under ‘gricese’But in teleological terms they can even be ordered. What
is the order that Grice uses? At this stage, he has already considered in
detail the progression, with his ‘the dog is shaggy,’ so we know where he is
getting atbut he does not want to get philosophically technical at the lecture.
He is aiming then at compositionality. There is utterance-whole and utterance-part,
or as he prefers ‘complete utterance’ and ‘non-complete utterance’. ‘dog’ and
‘shaggy’ would be non-complete. So the external ‘state of affairs’ is Grice’s
seeing that Strawson’s dog is shaggy and wanting to communicate this to Pears
(Grice co-wrote an essay only with two Englishmen, these being Strawson and
Pears‘The three Englishmen’s essay,’ as he called it’ --. So there is a state
of affairs, pretty harmless, Strawson’s dog is being shaggyperhaps he needs a
haircut, or some brooming. “Shaggy” derives from ‘shag’ plus –y, as in ‘’twas
brillig.’so this tells that it is an adjectival or attribute predicationof the
feature of being ‘shaggy’ to ‘dog.’ When the Anglo-Saxons first used ‘dog’the
Anglo-Saxon ‘Adam,’ he should have used ‘hound’. Grice is not concerned at the
point with ‘dog,’ since he KNOWS that Strawson’s dog is “Fido”dogs being
characteristically faithful and the Strawsons not being very original“I kid”
--. In this case, we need a ‘communication function.’ The sender perceives that
Fido is shaggy and forms the proposition ‘Fido is shaggy.’ This is via his
belief, caused by his seeing that Fido is shaggy. He COMPOSES a complete
utterance. He could just utter, elliptically, ‘shaggy’but under quieter
circumstances, he manages to PREDICATE ‘shagginess’ to Strawson’s dogand comes
out with “Fido is shaggy.” That is all the ‘syntactics’ that Gricese needs
(Palmer, “Remember when all we had to care about was nouns and verbs?”) (Strictly,
“I miss the good old days when all we had to care was nouns and verbs”). Well
here we have a ‘verb,’ “is,” and a noun“nomen adjectivum”or ‘adjective noun’,
shaggy. Grice is suggesting that the lexicon (or corpus) is hardly relevant.
What is important is the syntax. Having had to read Chomsky under Austin’s
tutelage (they spent four Saturday mornings with the Mouton paperback, and
Grice would later send a letter of recommendation on one of his tutees for
study with Chomsky overseas). But Grice has also read Peano. So he needs a set
of FINITE set of formation rulesthat will produce an INFINITE SET of
‘sentences’ where Grice highers the decibels when he says ‘infinite,’ hoping it
will upset the rare Whiteheadian philosopher in the audience! Having come up
with “Fido is shaggy,’ the sender sends it to the sendee. “Any link will do”The
link is ‘arranged’ somehowarranged simpliciter in a one-off predicament, or
pre-arranged in two-off predicament, etc. Stages 2, 3, 4, and 5have all to do
with ‘trustworthy’which would one think otiose seeing that Sir John Lyons has
said that prevarication in the golden plover and the Homo sapiens is an
essential feature of language! (But we are at the Oxford of Warnock!). So, the
sender sends “Fido is shaggy,’ and Pears gets it. He takes Grice to be
expressing his belief that Strawson’s dog is shaggy, and comes not only to
accept that Grice believes this, but to accept that Strawson’s dog is shaggy.
As it happens, Pears recommends a bar of soap to make his hairs at least look
‘cuter.’ Refs.: H. P. Grice, “A teleological model of communication.”
minimal transformationalism. Grice: “I wonder where Chomsky got the idea of a
‘transformation’?” -- Grice was proud that his system PIROTESE ‘allowed for the
most minimal transformations.” transformational
grammar Philosophy of language The most powerful of the three kinds of grammar
distinguished by Chomsky. The other two are finite-state grammar and
phrasestructure grammar. Transformational grammar is a replacement for phrase-structure
grammar that (1) analyzes only the constituents in the structure of a sentence;
(2) provides a set of phrase-structure rules that generate abstract
phrase-structure representations; (and 3) holds that the simplest sentences are
produced according to these rules. Transformational grammar provides a further
set of transformational rules to show that all complex sentences are formed
from simple elements. These rules manipulate elements and otherwise rearrange
structures to give the surface structures of sentences. Whereas
phrase-structure rules only change one symbol to another in a sentence,
transformational rules show that items of a given grammatical form can be
transformed into items of a different grammatical form. For example, they can show
the transformation of negative sentences into positive ones, question sentences
into affirmative ones and passive sentences into active ones. Transformational
grammar is presented as an improvement over other forms of grammar and provides
a model to account for the ability of a speaker to generate new sentences on
the basis of limited data. “The central idea of transformational grammar is
determined by repeated application of certain formal operations called
‘grammatical transformations’ to objects of a more elementary sort.” Chomsky,
Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Grice: “Some like
Quine, but Chomsky’s MY man,” per il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool
Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
Miraculus
– admiraculus -- miracle, an extraordinary event brought about by God. In the
medieval understanding of nature, objects have certain natural powers and
tendencies to exercise those powers under certain circumstances. Stones have
the power to fall to the ground, and the tendency to exercise that power when
liberated from a height. A miracle is then an extraordinary event in that it is
not brought about by any object exercising its natural powerse.g., a liberated
stone rising in the airbut brought about directly by God. In the modern
understanding of nature, there are just events (states of objects) and laws of
nature that determine which events follow which other events. There is a law of
nature that heavy bodies when liberated fall to the ground. A miracle is then a
“violation” of a law of nature by God. We must understand by a law a principle
that determines what happens unless there is intervention from outside the
natural order, and by a “violation” such an intervention. There are then three
problems in identifying a miracle. The first is to determine whether an event
of some kind, if it occurred, would be a violation of a law of nature (beyond
the natural power of objects to bring about). To know this we must know what
are the laws of nature. The second problem is to find out whether such an event
did occur on a particular occasion. Our own memories, the testimony of
witnesses, and physical traces will be the historical evidence of this, but
they can mislead. And the evidence from what happened on other occasions that
some law L is a law of nature is evidence supporting the view that on the
occasion in question L was operative, and so there was no violation. Hume
claimed that in practice there has never been enough historical evidence for a
miracle to outweigh the latter kind of counterevidence. Finally, it must be
shown that God was the cause of the violation. For that we need grounds from
natural theology for believing that there is a God and that this is the sort of
occasion on which he is likely to intervene in nature.
misfire: Grice: “When Austin was invited to
lecture in Italy, he had to translate ‘mis-fire’ into Italian – eventually, he
cancelled the trip!” – Grice: “While every schoolboy knows it’s ‘fare
cilecca’!” -- Uused by Grice in Meaning Revisited. Cf. Austin. “When the
utterance is a misfire, the procedure which we purport to invoke is disallowed
or is botched: and our act (marrying, etc.) is void or without effect, etc. We
speak of our act as a purported act, or perhaps an attempt, or we use such an
expression as ‘went through a form of marriaage’ by contrast with ‘married.’ If
somebody issues a performative utterance, and the utterance is classed as
a misfire because the procedure invoked is not accepted , it is
presumably persons other than the speaker who do not accept it (at least
if the speaker is speaking seriously ). What would be an ex- ample
? Consider ‘I divorce you*, said to a wife by her husband in a Christian
country, and both being Chris- tians rather than Mohammedans. In this
case it might be said, ‘nevertheless he has not (successfully)
divorced her: we admit only some other verbal or non-verbal pro-
cedure’; or even possibly ‘we (we) do not admit any procedure at all for
effecting divorce — marriage is indis- soluble’. This may be carried so
far that we reject what may be called a whole code of procedure, e.g. the
code of honour involving duelling: for example, a challenge may be
issued by ‘my seconds will call on you’, which is equivalent to ‘ I
challenge you’, and we merely shrug it off The general position is
exploited in the unhappy story of Don Quixote. Of course, it
will be evident that it is comparatively simple if we never admit any
‘such’ procedure at all — that is, any procedure at all for doing that
sort of thing, or that procedure anyway for doing that particular
thing. But equally possible are the cases where we do sometimes —
in certain circumstances or at certain hands — accept n
nA/'Q/1n U UlUVlfU u plUVWUiV/, ULIL UW 111
T\llt 1 n nrttT at* amaiitvwifnnaati at* af ULIL 111
ttllj UL1U/1 L/llCUllli3Lail\/ KJL CIL other hands. And here
we may often be in doubt (as in 28 Horn
to do things with Words the naming example above) whether an
infelicity should be brought into our present class A. i or rather
into A. 2 (or even B. i or B. 2). For example, at a party, you say,
when picking sides, ‘I pick George’: George grunts ‘I’m not playing.’ Has
George been picked? Un- doubtedly, the situation is an unhappy one. Well,
we may say, you have not picked George, whether because there is no
convention that you can pick people who aren’t playing or because George
in the circumstances is an inappropriate object for the procedure of
picking. Or on a desert island you may say to me ‘Go and pick up
wood’; and I may say 4 1 don’t take orders from you’ or ‘you’re not
entitled to give me orders’ — I do not take orders from you when you try
to ‘assert your authority’ (which I might fall in with but may not) on a
desert island, as opposed to the case when you are the captain on a
ship and therefore genuinely have authority.
missum: If Grice uses psi-transmission (and
emission, when he speaks of ‘pain,’ and the decibels of the emission of a
bellow) he also uses transmission, and mission, transmissum, and missum. Grice
was out on a mission. Grice uses ‘emissor,’ but then there’s the ‘missor.’ This
is in key with modern communication theory as instituted by Shannon. The
‘missor’ ‘sends’ a ‘message’ to a recipientor missee. But be careful, he may
miss it. In any case, it shows that e-missor is a compound of ‘ex-‘ plus
‘missor,’ so that makes sense. It transliterates Grice’s ut-terer (which
literally means ‘out-erer’). And then there’s the prolatum, from proferre,
which has the professor, as professing that p, that is. As someone said, if H.
P. Girce were to present a talk to the Oxford Philosophical Society he would
possibly call it “Messaging.” c. 1300,
"a communication transmitted via a messenger, a notice sent through some
agency," from Old French message "message,
news, tidings, embassy" (11c.), from Medieval Latin missaticum, from Latin missus "a sending away,
sending, dispatching; a throwing, hurling," noun use of past participle
of mittere "to
release, let go; send, throw" (see mission). The Latin word is glossed in Old English by ærende. Specific religious sense of
"divinely inspired communication via a prophet" (1540s) led to
transferred sense of "the broad meaning (of something)," which is
attested by 1828. To get the message "understand" is by 1960.
memoria
-- mnemic causation,
a type of causation in which, in order to explain the proximate cause of an
organism’s behaviour, it is necessary to specify not only the present state of
the organism and the present stimuli operating upon it, but also this or that
past experience of the organism. The term was introduced by Russell in The
Analysis of Mind, and borrowed, but never returned, by Grice for his Lockeian
logical construction of personal identity or “I” in terms of an chain of
mnemonic temporary states. “Unlike Russell, I distinguish between the mnemic
and the mnemonic.”
senofane: Grice: “It is unusual for an Italian to call Senofane an Italian
philosopher, but he has all the requisites: born in Italy – what else do you
want?” “Or as Strawson would prefer, Xenophanes, but since he emigrated to
Italy, we might just as well use an “S””Grice. Grice: “You have to be careful
when you research for this in Italythey spell it with an ‘s’!”
-- Grecian philosopher, a proponent of an idealized conception of
the divine, and the first of the pre-Socratics to propound epistemological
views. Born in Colophon, an Ionian Grecian city on the coast of Asia Minor, he
emigrated as a young man to the Grecian West Sicily and southern Italy. The
formative influence of the Milesians is evident in his rationalism. He is the
first of the pre-Socratics for whom we have not only ancient reports but also
quite a few verbatim quotations fragments from his “Lampoons” Silloi
and from other didactic poetry. Xenophanes attacks the worldview of Homer,
Hesiod, and traditional Grecian piety: it is an outrage that the poets
attribute moral failings to the gods. Traditional religion reflects regional
biases blond gods for the Northerners; black gods for the Africans. Indeed,
anthropomorphic gods reflect the ultimate bias, that of the human viewpoint “If
cattle, or horses, or lions . . . could draw pictures of the gods . . . ,” frg.
15. There is a single “greatest” god, who is not at all like a human being,
either in body or in mind; he perceives without the aid of organs, he effects
changes without “moving,” through the sheer power of his thought. The rainbow
is no sign from Zeus; it is simply a special cloud formation. Nor are the sun or
the moon gods. All phenomena in the skies, from the elusive “Twin Sons of Zeus”
St. Elmo’s fire to sun, moon, and stars, are varieties of cloud formation.
There are no mysterious infernal regions; the familiar strata of earth stretch
down ad infinitum. The only cosmic limit is the one visible at our feet: the
horizontal border between earth and air. Remarkably, Xenophanes tempers his
theological and cosmological pronouncements with an epistemological caveat:
what he offers is only a “conjecture.” In later antiquity Xenophanes came to be
regarded as the founder of the Eleatic School, and his teachings were
assimilated to those of Parmenides and Melissus. This appears to be based on
nothing more than Xenophanes’ emphasis on the oneness and utter immobility of
God. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Senofane in Italia.”
sensus -- modified Occam’s razor: Grice was obsessed with ‘sense,’ and thought Oxonian
philosohpers were multiplying it otioselynotably L. J. Cohen (“The diversity of
meaning”). The original razor is what Grice would have as ‘ontological,’ to
which he opposes with in his ‘ontological marxism’. Entities should not be
multiplied beyond the necessity of needing them as honest working entities. He
keeps open house provided they come in help with the work. This restriction
explains what Grice means by ‘necessity’ in the third lecturea second sense
does not do any work. The implicaturum does. Grice loved a razor, and being into analogy
and focal meaning, if he HAD to have semantic multiplicity, for the case of
‘is,’ (being) or ‘good,’ it had to be a UNIFIED semantic multiplicity, as
displayed by paronymy. The essay had circulated since the Harvard days, and it
was also repr. in Pragmatics, ed. Cole for Academic
Press. Personally, I prefer dialectica. ‒ Grice. This is
the third James lecture at Harvard. It is particularly useful for Grices
introduction of his razor, M. O. R., or Modified Occams Razor, jocularly
expressed by Grice as: Senses are not to be multiplied beyond necessity.
An Englishing of the Ockhams Latinate, Entia non sunt multiplicanda præter
necessitatem. But what do we mean sense. Surely Occam was right with his
Entia non sunt multiplicanda præter necessitatem. We need to translate that
alla linguistic turn. Grice jokes: Senses are not be multiplied beyond
necessity. He also considers irony, stress (supra-segmental fourth-articulatory
phonology), and truth, which the Grice Papers have under a special f. in the s.
V . Three topics where the implicaturum helps. He is a scoundrel may
well be the implicaturum of He is a fine friend. But cf. the pretense
theory of irony. Grice, being a classicist, loved the etymological
connection. With Stress, he was concerned with anti-Gettier uses of
emphatic know: I KNOW. (Implicaturum: I do have conclusive
evidence). Truth (or is true)
sprang from the attention by Grice to that infamous Bristol symposium between
Austin and Strawson. Cf. Moores paradox. Grice wants to defend correspondence
theory of Austin against the performative approach of Strawson. If is true implicates someone previously
affirmed this, that does not mean a ditto implicaturum is part of the
entailment of a is true utterance, further
notes on logic and conversation, in Cole, repr. in a revised form, Modified
Occams Razor, irony, stress, truth. The preferred citation should be the
Harvard. This is originally the third James lecture, in a revised
form.In that lecture, Grice introduced the M. O. R., or Modified Occams
Razor. Senses are not be multiplied beyond necessity. The point is
that entailment-cum-implicaturum does the job that multiplied
senses should not do! The Grice Papers contains in a different f. the
concluding section for that lecture, on irony, stress, and truth. Grice
went back to the Modified Occams razor, but was never able to formalise it! It
is, as he concedes, almost a vacuous methodological thingy! It is interesting
that the way he defines the alethic value of true alrady cites satisfactory. I
shall use, to Names such a property, not true but factually satisfactory. Grices
sympathies dont lie with Strawsons Ramsey-based redundance theory of truth, but
rather with Tarskis theory of correspondence. He goes on to claim his trust in
the feasibility of such a theory. It is, indeed, possible to construct a
theory which treats truth as (primarily) a property, not true but factually
satisfactory. One may see that point above as merely verbal and not involving
any serious threat. Lets also assume that it will be a consequence, or
theorem, of such a theory that there will be a class C of utterances
(utterances of affirmative Subjects-predicate sentences [such as snow is white
or the cat is on the mat of the dog is hairy-coated such that each member of C
designates or refers to some item and indicates or predicates some class (these
verbs to be explained within the theory), and is factually satisfactory
if the item belongs to the class. Let us also assume that there can be a
method of introducing a form of expression, it is true that /it is buletic
that and linking it with the notion of
factually or alethic or doxastic satisfactory, a consequence of which will be
that to say it is true that Smith is happy will be equivalent to saying that
any utterance of class C which designates Smith and indicates the class of happy
people is factually satisfactory (that is, any utterance which assigns Smith to
the class of happy people is factually satisfactory. Mutatis mutandis for Let
Smith be happy, and buletic satisfactoriness. The move is Tarskian. TBy
stress, Grice means suprasegmental phonology, but he was too much of a
philosopher to let that jargon affect him! Refs.: The locus classicus, if
that does not sound too pretentious, is Essay 3 in WoW, but there are
references elsewhere, such as in “Meaning Revisited,” and under ‘semantics.’
The only one who took up Grice’s challenge at Oxford was L. J. Cohen, “Grice on
the particles of natural language,” which got a great response by Oxonian R. C.
S. Walker (citing D. Bostock, a tutee of Grice), to which Cohen again responded
“Can the conversationalist hypothesis be defended.” Cohen clearly centres his
criticism on the razor. He had an early essay, citing Grice, on the DIVERSITY
of meaning. Cohen opposes Grice’s conversationalist hypothesis to his own
‘semantic hypothesis’ (“Multiply senses all you want.”). T. D. Bontly
explores the topic of Grice’s MOR. “Ancestors of this essay were presented at
meetings of the Society for Philosophy and Psychology (Edmonton, Alberta), of
the the Pacific Division of the American Philosophical Association (San
Francisco, CA) and at the University of Connecticut. I am indebted to all three
groups and particularly to the commentators D. Sanford (at the Society for
Philosophy and Psychology) and M. Reimer (at the APA). Thanks also to the
following for helpful comments or discussion (inclusive): F. Adams, A.
AriewBloom, M. Devitt, B. Enc, C. Gaulker, M. Lynch, R. Millikan, J. Pust, E.
Sober, R. C. Stalnaker, D. W. Stampe, and S. Wheeler.” Bontly
writes, more or less (I have paraphrased him a little, with good intentions,
always!) “Some philosophers have appealed to a principle which H. P. Grice, in
his third William James lecture, dubs Modified Occam’s Razor (henceforth, “M.
O. R.”): “Sensesrather than ‘entities,’ as the inceptor from Ockham more boringly
has it -- are not to be multiplied beyond necessity’.” What
is ‘necessity’? Bontly: “Superficially, Grice’s “M. O. R.”
seems a routine application of Ockham’s principle of parsimony: ‘entities are
not to be multiplied beyond necessity. Now, parsimony arguments, though common
in science, are notoriously problematic, and their use by Grice faces one
objection or two. Grice’s “M. O. R.” makes considerably more sense in light of
certain assumptions about the psychological processes involved in language development,
learning, and acquisition, and it describes recent *empirical*, if not
philosophical or conceptual, of the type Grice seems mainly interested in --
findings that bear these assumptions out. [My] resulting account solves several
difficulties that otherwise confront Grice’s “M. O. R.”, and it draws attention
to problematic assumptions involved in using parsimony to argue for pragmatic
accounts of the type of phenomena ‘ordinary-language’ philosophers were
interested in. In more general terms, when an expression E has two or more
usesU1 and U2, say -- enabling its users to express two or more different
meaningsM1 and M2, say -- one is tempted to assume that E is semantically (i.e.
lexically) ambiguous, or polysemous, i.e., that some convention, constituting
the language L, assign E these two meanings M1 and M2 corresponding to its two
uses U1 and U2. One hears, for instance, that ‘or’ is ambiguous (polysemous)
between a weak (inclusive) (‘p v q’) and a strong (exclusive) sense, ‘p w q.’ Grice
actually feels that speaking of the meaning or sense of ‘or’ sounds harsh
(“Like if I were asked what the meaning of ‘to’ is!”). But in one note from a
seminar from Strawson he writes: “Jones is between Smith and Williams.” “I
wouldn’t say that ‘between’ is ambiguous, even if we interpret the sentence in
a physical sense, or in an ordering of merit, say.” Bontly:
“Used exclusively, an utterance of ‘p or q’ (p v q) entails that ‘p’ and ‘q’
are NOT both true. Used inclusively, it does not. Still, ambiguity is not the only
possible explanation.” (This reminds me of Atlas, “Philosophy WITHOUT
ambiguity!”ambitious title!). The phenomenon can also be approached
pragmatically, from within the framework of a general theory conversation alla
Grice. One could, e. g., first, maintain that ‘p or q’ is unambiguously
monosemous inclusive and, second, apply Grice’s idea of an ‘implicaturum’ to
explain the exclusive.” I actually traced this, and found that O.
P. Wood in an odd review of a logic textbook (by Faris) in “Mind,” in the 1950s,
makes the point about the inclusive-exclusive distinction, pre-Griceianly!
Grice seems more interested, as you later consider, the implicaturum: “Utterer
U has non-truth-functional grounds for uttering ‘p or q. Not really the
‘inclusive-exclusive’ distinction. Jennings deals with this in “The genealogy
of disjunction,” and elsewhere, and indeed notes that ‘or’ may be a dead
metaphor from ‘another.’ Bontly goes on: “On any such account, ‘p
or q’ would have two uses U1 and U2 and two standard interpretations, I1 and
I2, but NEVER two ‘conventional’ meanings,” M1 and M2 Or take ‘and’ (p.q) which
(when used as a sentential connective) ordinarily stands for truth-functional
conjunction (as in 1a, below). Often enough, though, ‘p and q’ seems to imply
temporal priority (1b), while in other cases it suggests causal priority (1c).
(1) a. Bill bought a shirt and Christy [bought] a sweater. b. Adam took off his
shoes and [he] got into bed. c. “Jack fell down and [he] broke his crown, and
Jill came tumbling o:ter.” (to rhyme with ‘water’ in an earlier
line.”Apparently Grice loved this nursery rhyme too, “Jack is an Englishman; he
must, therefore, be brave,” Jill says.” (Grice, “Aspects of reason.”)Bontly:
“Again, one suspects an ambiguity, M1 and M2, but Grice argues that a
‘conversational’ explanation is available and preferable. According to the
‘pragmatist’ or ‘conversationalist’ hypothesis’ (as I shall call it), a
temporal or a causal reading of “and” (p.q) may be part of what the UTTERER
means, but such a reading I2, are not part of what the sentence means, or the
word _and_ means, and thus belong in a general theory of conversation, not the
grammar of a specific language.” Oddly, I once noticed that Chomsky, of all
people, and since you speak of ‘grammar,’ competence, etc. refers to “A.”
Albert? P. Grice in his 1966! Aspects of the theory of syntax. “A. P. Grice
wants to say that the temporal succession is not part of the meaning of ‘and.’”
I suspect one of Grice’s tutees at Oxford was spreading the unauthorized word! Bontly:
“Many an alleged ambiguity seems amenable to Grice’s conversationalist
hypothesis. Besides the sentential connectives or truth-functors, a pragmatic
explanation has been applied fruitfully to quantifiers (Grice lists ‘all’ and
‘some (at least one’), definite descriptions (Grice lists ‘the,’ ‘the
murderer’), the indefinite description (‘a finger’, much discussed by Grice,
“He’s meeting a woman this evening.”), the genitive construction (‘Peter’s
bat’), and the indirect speech act (‘Can you pass the salt?’) — to mention just
a few. The literature on the Griceian treatment of these phenomena is
extensive. Some classic treatments are found in the oeuvre of philosophers like
Grice, Bach, Harnish, and Davis, and linguists like Horn, Gazdar, and Levinson.
But the availability of a pragmatic explanation poses an interesting
methodological problem. Prima facie, the alleged ‘ambiguity’ M1 and M2, can now
be explained either semantically (by positing two or more senses S1 and S2, or
M1 and M2, of expression E) or pragmatically (by positing just one sense (S)
plus one super-imposed implicaturum, I).Sometimes, of course, one approach or
the other is transparently inadequate. When the ‘use’ of E cannot be derived
from a general conversational principle, the pragmatic explanation seems a
non-starter.” Not for a radically radical pragmatist like Atlas! Ambitious!
Similarly, an ambiguity- or polysemy- based explanation seems out of the
question where the interpretation of E at issue is highly context-dependent.”
(My favourite is Grice on “a,” that you analyse in term of ‘developmental’ or
ontogenetical pragmaticsversus Millikan’s phylogenetical! But, in many cases, a
semantic, or polysemy, and a conversational explanations both appear plausible,
and the usual data — Grice’s intuitions about how the expression can and cannot
be used, should or shouldn’t beused — appear to leave the choice of one of the
two hypotheses under-determined.These were the cases that most interest Grice,
the philosopher, since they impinge on various projects in philosophical
analysis. (Cf. Grice, 1989, 3–21 and
passim).” Notably the ‘ordinary-language’ philosophy
‘project,’ I would think. I love the fact that in the inventory of philosophers
who are loose about this (as in the reference you mention above, 3-21, he includes himself in “Causal theory
of perception”! “To adjudicate these border-line cases, Grice (1978) proposes a
methodological principle which he dubs “Modified Occam’s Razor,” M. O. R.”
‘Senses are not to be multiplied beyond necessity.’ (1978, 118–119) “(I follow Grice in using the
Latinate ‘Occam’ rather than the Anglo-Saxon ‘Ockham’ which is currently
preferred). More fully, the idea is that one should not posit an alleged
special, stronger SENSE S2, for an expression E when a general conversational
principle suffices to explain why E, which bears only Sense 1, S1, receives a
certain interpretation or carries implicaturum I. Thus, if the ‘use’ (or an
‘use’) of E can be explained pragmatically, other things being equal, the use
should be explained pragmatically.” Griceians appeal to M. O. R. quite often,”
pragmatically bearded or not! (I love Quine’s idea that Occam’s razor was
created to shave Plato’s beard. Cfr. Schiffer’s anti-shave! It is affirmed, in
spirit if not letter, by philosopher/linguist Atlas and Levinson,
philosopher/linguist Bach, Bach and philosopher Harnish, Horn, Levinson,
Morgan, linguist/philosopher Neale, philosopher Searle, philosopher Stalnaker,
philosopher Walker (of Oxford), and philosopher Ziff” (I LOVE Ziff’s use,
seeing that he could be otherwise so anti-Griceian, vide Martinich, “On Ziff on
Grice on meaning,” and indeed Stampe (that you mention) on Ziff on Grice on
meaning. One particularly forceful statement is found in “of all people”
Kripke, who derides the ambiguity hypothesis as ‘the lazy man’s approach in
philosophy’ and issues a strong warning.”
When I
read that, I was reminded that Stampe, in some unpublished manuscripts, deals
with the loose use of Griceian ideas by Kripke. Stampe discusses at length,
“Let’s get out of here, the cops are coming.” Stampe thinks Kripke is only
superficially a Griceian! Kripke: “‘Do not posit an ambiguity unless
you are really forced to, unless there are really compelling theoretical (or
intuitive) grounds to suppose that an ambiguity really is present’ (197720). A
similar idea surfaces in Ruhl’s principle of “mono-semic” bias’. One’s initial
effort is directed toward determining a UNITARY meaning S1 for a lexical item
E, trying to attribute apparent variations (S2) in meaning to other factors. If
such an effort fails, one tries to discover a means of relating the distinct
meanings S1 and S2. If this effort fails, there are several words: E1 and E2
(19894).” Grice’s ‘vice’ and Grice’s ‘vyse,’ different words in English, same
in Old Roman (“violent.”). Ruhl’s position differs from Grice’s approach.
Whereas Grice takes word-meaning to be its WEAKEST exhibited meaning, Ruhl
argues that word-meaning can be so highly abstract or schematic as to provide
only a CORE of meaning, making EVEN the weakest familiar reading a pragmatic
specialisation.” Loved that! Ruhl as more Griceian than
Grice! Indeed, Grice is freely using the very abstract notion of a Fregeian
‘sense,’ with the delicacy you would treat a brick! “The
difference between Grice’s and Ruhl’s positions raises issues beyond the scope
of the present essay (though see Atlas, 1989, for further discussion).” I will! Atlas knows
everything you wanted to know, and more, especially when it comes to linguists!
He has a later book with ‘implicaturum’ in its subtitle. “Considering
the central role that “M. O. R.” plays in Grice’s programme, one is thus
surprised to find barely any attention paid to whether it is a good principle —
to whether it is true that a pragmatic explanation, when available, is in
general more likely to be true than its ‘ambiguity’ or polysemy, or bi-semy, or
aequi-vocal rival.” Trying to play with this, I see that Grice
loves ‘aequi-vocal.’ He thinks that ‘must’ is ‘aequi-vocal’ between an alethic
and a practical ‘use.’ It took me some time to process that! He means that
since it’s the ‘same,’ ‘aequi’, ‘voice’, vox’. So ‘aequi-vocal’ IS ‘uni-vocal.’
The Aristotelian in Grice, I guess!
“Grice
himself offers vanishingly little argument.” How extended is a Harvard
philosophical audience’s attention-span? “Examining just two (out of the blue,
unphilosophical) cases where we seem happy to attribute a secondary or
derivative sense S2 to one word or expression E, but not another, Grice notes
that, in both cases, the supposition that the expression E has an additional
sense S2 is not superfluous, or unparsimonious, accounting for certain facets
of the use of E that cannot, apparently, be explained pragmatically.” I wonder
if a radically radical pragmatist would agree! I never met a polysemous
expression! Grice concludes that, therefore, ‘there is as yet no reason NOT to
accept M. O. R. ’ (1978120) — faint praise for a principle so important to his
philosophical programme! Besides this weak argument for “M. O. R.,” Grice
(1978) also mentions a few independent, rather loose, tests for alleged
ambiguity.” (“And how to fail them,” as Zwicky would have it!) But Grice’s
rationale for “M. O. R.,” presumably, is a thought Grice does not bother to
articulate, thinking perhaps that the principle’s name, its kinship with
Occam’s famous razor, ‘Do not multiply entities beyond necessity,’ made its
epistemic credentials sufficiently obvious already.” Plus,
Harvard is very Occamist!“To lay it out, though, the thought is surely that
parsimony -- and other such qualities as simplicity, generality, and
unification -- are always prized in scientific (and philosophical?)
explanation, the more parsimonious (etc.) of two otherwise equally adequate
theories being ipso facto more likely to be true. If, as would seem to be the
case, a pragmatic explanation were more parsimonious than its semantic, or
‘conventionalist,’ or ambiguity, or polysemic, or polysemy or bi-semic rival,
the conversational explanation would be supported by an established, received,
general principle of scientific inference.”
I love
your exploration of Newton on this below! Hypotheses non fingo! “Certainly,
some such argument is on Grice’s mind when he names his principle as he does,
and much the same thought surely lies behind Kripke’s references to ‘general
methodological considerations’ and ‘considerations of economy’ Other ‘Griceian’
appeals to these theoretical virtues are even more transparent. Linguist J. L.
Morgan tells us, for instance, that ‘Occam’s Razor dictates that we take a
Gricean account of an indirect speech act as the correct analysis, lacking
strong evidence to the contrary’ Philosopher Stalnaker argues that a major
advantage accrues to a pragmatic treatment of Strawson’s presupposition in that
‘there will then be no need to complicate the semantics or the lexicon’” or
introduce metaphysically dubious truth-value gaps! Linguist S. C. Levinson
suggests that a major selling point for a conversational theory in general is
that such a theory promises to ‘effect a radical simplification of the
semantics’ and ‘approximately halve the size of the lexicon’.” So we don’t need
to learn two words, ‘vyse’ and ‘vice.’ There can be little doubt, therefore,
that a Griceian takes parsimony to argue for the pragmatic approach.” I
use the rather pedantic and awful spelling “Griceian,” so that I can keep the
pronunciation /grais/ and also because Fodor used it! And non-philosophers,
too! “But a parsimony argument is notoriously
problematic, and the argument for “M. O. R.” is no exception. The preference
for a parsimonious theory is surprisingly difficult to justify, as is the
assumption that a pragmatic explanation IS more parsimonious. This does not
mean Grice’s “M. O. R.” is entirely without merit. On the contrary, Grice is
right to hold that senses should not be multiplied, if a conversational
principle will do.” But the justification for M. O. R. need have nothing to do
with the idea that parsimony is, always and everywhere, a virtue in scientific
theories.” Also because we are dealing with
philosophy, not science, here? What makes Grice’s “M. O. R.” reasonable,
rather, is a set of assumptions about the psychological processes involved in
language learning, development, and acquisition, and I will report some
empirical (rather than conceptual, as Grice does) evidence that these
assumptions are, at least, roughly correct. One disclaimer. While I shall
defend Grice’s “M. O. R.,” and therefore the research programme initiated by
Grice, it is not my goal here to vindicate any specific pragmatic account, nor
to argue that any given linguistic phenomenon requires a pragmatic
explanation.” This reminds me of Kilgariff, a Longman
linguist. He has a lovely piece, “I don’t believe in word SENSE!” I think he
found that Longman had, under ‘horse’: 1. Quadruped animal. 2. Painting of a
horse, notably by Stubbs! He did not like that! Why would ‘sense,’ a Fregeian
notion, have a place in something like ‘lexicography,’ that deals with corpuses
and statistics? “The task is, rather, to understand the
logic of a particular type of inference, a type of Griceian inference that can
be and has been employed by a philosopher such as Grice who disagree on many
other points of theory. Since it would be impossible within the confines of
this essay to discuss these disagreements, or to do justice to the many ways in
which Grice’s paradigm or programme has been revised and extended
(palaeo-Griceians, neo-Griceians, post-Griceians), my discussion is confined to
a few hackneyed examples hackneyed by Grice himself, and to Grice’s orthodox
theory, if a departure therefrom will be noted where relevant. The
conversational explanation of an alleged ambiguity or polysemy or bi-semy aims
to show how an utterer U can take an expression E with one conventional meaning
and use it as if it had other meanings as well. Typically, this requires
showing how the utterer U’s intended message can be ‘inferred,’ with the aid of
a general principle of communicative behaviour, from the conventional meaning
or sense of the word E that U utters. In Grice’s pioneering account, for
instance, the idea is that speech is subject to a Principle of Conversational
Co-Operation (In earlier Oxford seminars, where he introduced ‘implicaturum’ he
speaks of two principles in conflict: the principle of conversational
self-interest, and the principle of conversational benevolence! I much love
THAT than the rather artificial Kant scheme at Harvard). ‘Make your
conversational contribution, or move, such as is required, at the stage at
which it occurs, by the accepted purpose or direction of the conversational
exchange in which you are engaged.’(197544). “Sub-ordinate to the Principle of
Conversational Co-Operation are four conversational maxims (he was jocularly
‘echoing’ Kant!) falling under the four Kantian conversational categories of
Quality, Quantity, Relation, and Modus. Roughly: Make your contribution true.
Kant’s quality has to do with affirmation and negation, rather. Make your
contribution informative. Kant’s quantity has to do with ‘all’ and ‘one,’
rather. Make your contribution relevant. Kant’s relation God knows what it has
to do with. Make your contribution perspicuous [sic]. Kant’s modus has to do
with ‘necessary’ and ‘contingent.’
Grice
actually has ‘sic’ in the original “Logic and Conversation.” It’s like the
self-refuting Kantian. Also in ‘be brief (avoid unnecessary prolixity’”
‘proguard obfuscation,’ sort of thing? “… further specifying what cooperation
entails ( 45–46).” It’s sad Grice did not remember about the
principle of conversational benevolence clashing with the principle of
conversational self-interest, or dismissed the idea, when he wrote that
‘retro-spective’ epilogue about the maxims, etc. Bontly: “Unlike the
constitutive (to use Anscombe and Searle, not regulative) principles of a
grammar, the Principle of Conversational Co-Operation and the conversational,
universalisable, maxims are to be thought of not as an arbitrary conventionvide
Lewis -- but rather as a rational STRATEGY or guideline (if ‘strategy’ is too
strong) for achieving one’s communicative ends.”
I DO
think ‘strategy’ is too strong. A strategist is a general: it’s a zero-sum
game, war. I think Grice’s idea is that U is a rational agent dealing with his
addressee A, another rational agent. So, it’s not strategic rationality, but
communicative rationality. But then I’m being an etymologist! Surely chess
players speak of ‘strategies,’ but then they also speak of ‘check mate,” kill
the king! Bontly quotes from Grice: “‘[A]nyone who cares about the goals that
are central to conversation,’ says Grice, ought to find the principle of
conversational cooperation eminently reasonable (p. 49).” If
not rational! I love Grice’s /: rational/reasonable. He explores on this later,
“The price of that pair of shoes is not reasonable, but hardly irrational!” Bontly:
“Like a grammar, however, the principle of conversational co-operation is
(supposedly) tacitly known (or assumed) by conversationalists, who can thus
call on it to interpret each other’s conversational moves.” Exactly.
Parents teach their children well, not to lie, etc. “These interpretive
practices being mutual ‘knowledge,’ or common ground, moreover, an utterer U
can plan on his co-conversationalist B using the principle of conversational
cooperation, to interpret his own utterances, enabling him to convey a good
deal of information (and influencing) implicitly by relying on others to infer
his intended meaning.”INFORMING seems to do, because, although Grice makes a
distinction between ‘informing’ and ‘influencing,’ he takes an ‘exhibitive’
approach. So “Close the door!” means “I WANT YOU To believe that I want you to
close the door.” I.e. I’m informinginfluencing VIA informing. “Detailed
discussions of Grice’s principle of conversational cooperation are found in
many of the essays collected in Grice (1989), as well as in the work by
linguists like Levinson (1983) and linguist/philosopher Neale (1992).
Extensions and refinements of Grice’s approach are developed by linguist Horn
(1972), linguist/philosopher Bach and philosopher Harnish (1979), linguist
Gazdar (1979), linguist/philosopher Atlas and philosopher Levinson (1981),
anthropologist Sperber and linguist Wilson (1986), linguist/philosopher Bach
(1994), linguisdt Levinson (2000), and linguist Carston (2002).). The Principle
of conversational cooperation and its conversational maxims allow Grice to draw
a distinction between two dimensions of an utterer’s meaning within the total
significance.” I never liked that Grice uses
“signification,” here when in “Meaning” he had said: “Words, for all that Locke
said, are NOT signs.” “We apply ‘sign’ to traffic signals, not to ‘dog’.” Bontly:
“That which is ‘closely related to the conventional meaning of the word’
uttered is what the utterer has SAID (197544),” or the explicatum, or
explicitum. That which must instead be inferred with the aid of the principle
of conversational cooperation is what the utterer U has conversationally
implicated, the IMPLICATURUM ( 49–50), or implicitum. This dichotomy is in
several ways oversimplified. First, Grice (1975, 1978) also makes room for
‘conventional’ implicaturums (“She was poor BUT she was honest”) and
non-conversational non-conventional implicaturums (“Thank you,” abiding with
the maxim, ‘be polite’), although these dimensions are both somewhat
controversial (cf. Bach’s attack on conventional implicaturum) and can be set
aside here. Also controversial is the precise delineation of Grice’s notion of
what is said.” He grants he is using ‘say’ ‘artifiicially,’ which means,
“natural TO ME!.” Some (anthropologist Sperber and linguist Wilson, 1986;
linguist Carston, 1988, 2002; philosopher Recanati, 1993) hold that ‘what is
said,’ the DICTUM, the explicatum, or explicitum, is significantly
underdetermined by the conventional meaning of the word uttered, with the
result that considerable pragmatic intrusive processing must occur even to
recover what the utterer said.” And Grice allows
that an implicaturum can occur within the scope of an
operator.“Linguist/philosopher Bach disagrees, though he does add an
‘intermediate’ dimension (that of conversational ‘impliciture’) which is, in
part, pragmatically determined, enriched, or intruded. For my purpose, the
important distinction is between that element of meaning which is conventional
or ‘encoded’ and that element which is ‘inferred,’ ab-duced, or pragmatically
determined, whether or not it is properly considered part of what is said,” in
Grice’s admittedly artificial use of this overused verb! (“A horse says
neigh!”) A conversational implicaturum can itself be either particularized
(henceforth, PCIs) or generalized (GCIs) (56).” Most familiar examples of implicaturum
are particularised, where the inference to the utterer U’s intended meaning
relies on a specific assumption regarding the context of utterance.” Grice’s
first example, possibly, “Jones has beautiful handwriting” (Grice 1961).“Alter
that context much at all and the implicaturum will simply disappear, perhaps to
be replaced by another. With a generalised implicaturum, on the other hand, the
inference or abduction to U’s intended interpretation is relatively
context-independent, going through unless special clues to the contrary are
provided to defeat it.”Love the ‘defeat.’ Levinson cites one of Grice’s
unpublications as “Probability, defeasibility, and mood operators,” where Grice
is actually writing, “desirability.”!
“For
instance, an utterance of the sentence” ‘SOME residents survived the
earth-quake,’ would quite generally, absent any special clues to the contrary,
seem to implicate that not all survived. All survived, alas, seems to be, to
some, no news. Cruel world. No special ‘stage-setting’ has to be provided to
make the implicaturum appreciable. No particular context needs to be assumed in
order to calculate the likely intended meaning. All one needs to know is that
an utterer U who thought that everyone, all residents survived the earthquake
(or that none did?) would probably make this stronger assertion (in keeping
with Grice’s first sub-maxim of Quantity: ‘Make your contribution as informative
as required’).” Perhaps it’s best to deal with buildings.
“Somesome 75%, I would say -- of the buildings did not collapse after the
earth-quake on the tiny island, and fortunately, no fatalities need be
reported. It wasn’t such a big earth-quake as pessimist had predicted.” “A
Gricean should maintain that the ‘ambiguity’ of “some” -> “not all”
canvassed at the outset can all be explained in terms of a generalized
conversational implicaturum. For instance, linguist Horn shows, in his PhD on
English, how an exclusive use of ‘or’ can be treated as a consequence of the
maxim of Quantity. Roughly, since ‘p AND q’ is always ‘more informative,’
stronger, than ‘p or q’, an utterer U’s choosing to assert only the disjunction
would ordinarily indicate that he takes one or the other disjunct to be false.
He could assert the conjunction anyway, but then he would be violating Grice’s
first submaxim of Quality: ‘Do not say what you believe to be false’ For
similar reasons, the assertion of a disjunction would ordinarily seem to
implicate that the utterer U does not know which disjunct is true (otherwise he
would assert that disjunct rather than the entire disjunction) and hence, and
this is the way Grice puts it, which is technically, the best way, that the
utterer wants to be ‘interpreted’ as having some ‘non-truth-functional grounds’
for believing the disjunction (philosopher Grice, 1978; linguist Gazdar, 1979).
For recall that this all goes under the
scope of a psychological attitude. In “Method in psychological philosophy: from
the banal to the bizarre,” repr. in “The conception of value,” Grice considers
proper disjunctions: “The eagle is not sure whether to attack the rabbit or the
dove.” I think Loar plays with this too in his book for Cambridge on meaning and
mind and Grice. “Grice (1981) takes a similar line with
regard to asymmetric uses of ‘and’.”
Indeed,
I loved his “Jones got into bed and took off his clothes, but I do not want to
suggest in that order.” “Is that a linguistic offence?” Don’t think so!” “The
fourth submaxim of Manner,” ‘be orderly’ -- I tend to think this is ad-hoc and
that Grice had this maxim JUST to explain away the oddity of “She got a
children and married,” by Strawson in Strawson 1952. “says that utterers should
be ‘orderly,’ and when describing a sequence of events, an orderly presentation
would normally describe the events in the order in which they occurred. So an
utterance of (1b) (‘Jones took off his
trousershe had taken off his shoes already -- and got into bed.’ “would ordinarily
(unless the utterer U ‘indicates’ otherwise) implicate that Jones did so in
that order, hence the temporal reading of ‘and’.” “(Grice’s (1981) account of
asymmetric ‘and’ seems NOT to account for causal interpretations like
(1c).”Ryle says in “Informal logic,” 1953, in Dilemmas, “She felt ill and took
arsenic,” has the conscript ‘and’ of Whitehead and Russell, not the ‘civil’
‘and’ of the informalist. “Oxonian philosopher R. C. S. Walkerwhat took him to
respond to Cohen? Walker quotes from Bostock, who was Grice’s tutee at St.
John’s -- (1975136) suggests that the causal reading can be derived from the
maxim of Relation.”Nowell-Smith had spoken of ‘be relevant’ in Ethics. But
Grice HAD to be a Kantian!“Since conversationalists are expected to make their
utterances relevant, one expects that conjoined sentences will ‘have some
bearing to one another’, often a causal bearing. More nearly adequate accounts
of the temporal and causal uses of ‘and’ (so-called ‘conjunction buttressing’)
are found in linguist/philosopher Atlas and linguist Levinson (1981) and in
linguist Levinson (1983, 2000). Linguist Carston (1988, 2002) develops a rival
pragmatic account within the framework of anthropologist Sperber’s and linguist
Wilson’s Relevance Theory, on which temporal and causal readings are
explicatures rather than implicaturums. For the purposes of this essay, it is
immaterial which of these accounts best accords with the data. In these and
many other cases, it seems that a general principle regarding communicative RATIONALITY
can provide an alternative to positing a semantic ambiguity.”Williamson is
lecturing at Yale that ‘rationality’ has little to do with it!“But a Gricean
goes a step further and claims that the implicaturum account (when available)
is BETTER than an ambiguity or polysemy account. One possible argument for the
stronger thesis is that the various specialised uses of ‘or’ (etc.) bear all
the usual hallmarks of a conversational implicaturum. An implicaturum is:
calculable (i.e. derivable from what is said or dictum or explicatum or
explicitum via the Principle of conversational cooperation and the
conversational maxims); cancellable (retractable without contradiction), and;
non-detachable (incapable of being paraphrased away) Grice, 1975, 50 and 57–58). They ought also to be, sort
of, universal.” (Cf. Elinor Keenan Ochs, “The universality of conversational implicaturum.”
I hope Williamson considers this. In Madagascar, they have other ‘norms’ of
conversation: since speakers are guarded, implicatura to the effect, “I don’t
know” are never invited! Unlike the true lexical ambiguity that arises from a
language-specific convention, an implicaturum derives rather from general
features of communicative RATIONALITY and should thus be similar across
different languages (philosopher Kripke, 1977; linguist Levinson, 1983).”I’m
not sure. Cfr. Ochs in Madagascar. But she is a linguist/anthropologist, rather
than a philosopher? From a philosophical point of view, perhaps the best who
treated this issues is English philosopher Martin Hollis in his essays on
‘rationality’ and ‘relativism’ (keywords!)“Since the ‘ambiguity’ in question
here has all these features, at least to some degree, the implicaturum approach
may well seem irresistible. It is well known, however, that none of the
features listed on various occasions by Grice are sufficient (individually or
jointly) to establish the presence of a conversational implicaturum (Grice,
1978; linguist Sadock, 1978). Take calculability.” Or how to ‘work it out,’ to
keep it Anglo-Saxon, as pretentious Grice would not! The main difficulty is
that a conversationalimplicaturum can become fossilized, or ‘conventionalised’
over time but remain calculable nonetheless, as happens with some ‘dead’
metaphors — one-time non-literal uses which congealed into a new conventional
meaning.” A linguist at Berkeley worked on this, Traugott, on items in the
history of the English language, or H-E-L, for short, H.O.T.E.L, history of the
English language. I don’t think Grice considers this. He sticks with old Roman
‘animal’ -> ‘non-human’, strictly, having a ‘soul,’ or animus, anima. (I
think Traugott’s focus was on verb forms, like “I have eaten,” meaning,
literally, “I possess eating,” or something. But she does quote Grice and
speaks of fossilization. “For instance, the expression.” ‘S went to the
bathroom’ (Jones?) could, for obvious reasons, be used with its original,
compositional, meaning to implicate that S ‘relieved himself’.” “The intended
meaning would still be calculable today.”Or “went to powder her nose?” (Or
consider the pre-Griceian (?) child’s overinformative, standing from table at
dinner, “I’m going to the bathroom to do number 2 (unless he is flouting the
maxim). “But the use has been absorbed, or encoded into some people’s grammar,
as witnessed by the fact that ‘S went to
the bathroom on the living room carpet.’ is not contradictory (linguist J. L.
Morgan, 1978; linguist Sadock, 1978).”I wonder what some contextualists at Yale
(De Rose) would say about that!? Cf. Jason Stanley, enfant terrible. “Grice’s
cancellability is similarly problematic. While one may cancel the exclusive
interpretation of ‘p or q’ (e.g. by adding ‘or possibly both’), the added
remark could just as well be disambiguating an ambiguous utterance as canceling
the implicaturum (philosopher Walker, 1975; linguist Sadock, 1978).”Excellent
POINT! Walker would be fascinated to see that Grice once coined ‘disimplicaturum’
for some loose uses. “Macbeth saw Banquo.” “That tie is yellow under that
light, but orange under this one.” Actually, Grice creates ‘disimplicaturum’ to
refute Davidson on intending: “Jones intends to climb Mt Everest next weekend.”
Intending DOES entail BELIEF, but people abuse ‘intend’ and use it ‘loosely,’
with one sense dropped. Similarly, Grice says, with “You’re the cream in my
coffee,” where the ‘disimplicaturum’ is TOTAL!“Non-detachability fares no
better. When two sentences are synonymous (if there is, pace Quine, such a
thing), utterances of them ought to generate the same implicaturum. But they
will also have the same semantic implications, so the non-detachability of an
alleged implicaturum shows very little if anything at all (linguist Sadock,
1978).”I never liked non-detachability, because it ENTAILS that there MUST be a
synonym expression: cfr. God? Divinity? “Universality is perhaps the best test
of the four.”I agree. When linguists like Elinor Keenan disregard this, I tend
to think: “the cunning of conversational reason,” alla Hollis. Grice was a
member of Austin’s playgroup, and the conversational MAXIMS were
‘universalisable’ within THAT group. That seems okay for both Kant AND Hegel!“Since
an implicaturum can fossilise into a conventional meanings, however, it is
always possible for a cross-linguistic alleged ‘ambiguity’ to be pragmatic in
some language though lexical in another.”Is that ‘f*rnication’? Or is it Grice
on ‘pushing up the daisies’ as an “established idiom” for ‘… is dead’ in WJ5?
Austin and Grice would I think take for granted THREE languages: Greek and
Roman, that they studied at their public schoolsand this is important, because
Grice says his method of analysis is somehow grounded on his classical
educationand, well, English. Donald Davidson, in the New World, would object to
the ‘substantiation’ that speaking of “Greek” as a language, say, may
entail.“So while Grice’s tests are suggestive, they supply no clear verdict on
the presence of an implicaturum. Besides these inconclusive tests for implicaturum,
Grice could also appeal to various diagnostic tests for alleged ambiguity.”
“And how to fail them,” to echo Zwicky. Grice himself suggests three, although
none of them prove terribly helpful.”Loved your terrible. Cfr. ‘terrific’. And
the king entering St. Paul’s cathedral: “Aweful!” meaning ‘awe-some!’“First,
Grice points out that each alleged sense Sn of an allegedly ambiguous word E
ought to be expressible ‘in a reasonably wide range of linguistic environments’
(1978117). The fact that the strong implicaturum of ‘or’ is UNavailable within
the scope of a negation, for instance, would seem to count AGAINST alleged
ambiguity or polysemy. On the other hand, the strong implicaturum of ‘or’ IS
available within the scope of a propositional-attitude verb. A strong implicaturum
of ‘and’ is arguably available in both environments, within the scope of a
negation, and within the scope of a psychological-attitude verb. So the first
test seems a wash.”Metaphorically, or implicaturally. J“Second, Grice says, if the
expression E is ambiguous with one sense S2 being derived (somehow) from the
initial or original or etymological sense S1, that derivative sense S2 ‘ought
to conform to whatever principle there may be which governs the generation of
derivative senses’ ( 117–118).”GRICE AT HIS BEST! I think he is trying to
irritate Quine, who is seating on second row at Harvard! (After all Quine
thought he was a field linguist!)Bontly, charmingly: “Not knowing the content
of thi principle Grice invokes— and Grice gives us no hint as to what it might
be — we cannot bring it, alas, to bear here!”I THINK he was thinking Ullman. At
Oxford, linguists were working on ‘semantics,’ cfr. Gardiner. And he just
thought that it would be Unphilosophical on his part to bore his philosophical
Harvard audience with ‘facts.’ At one point he does mention that the facts of
the history of the English language (how ‘disc’ can be used, etc.) are not part
of the philosopher’s toolkit?“Third and finally, Grice says, we must ‘give due
(but not undue) weight to MY INTUITIONS about the existence (or indeed
non-existence) of a putative sense S2 of a word E.’ (p. 120).”Emphasis on ‘my’
mine! -- As I say, I never had any intuition about an expression having an
extra-putative sense. Not even ‘bank,’since in Old Germanic, it’s all
etymologically related!Bontly: “But, even granting the point that ‘or’ is
NON-INTUITIVELY ambiguous in quite the same way that ‘bank’ IS, allegedly, INTUITIVELY
ambiguous, the source of our present difficulty is precisely the fact that ‘p
or q’ often *seems* intuitively to imply that one or the other disjunct is
false.”Grice apparently uses ‘intuition’ and ‘introspection’ interchangeably,
if that helps? Continental phenomenological philosophers would make MUCH of
this! For Grice’s intuitions are HIS own. In a lecture at Wellesley, of all
places (in Grice 1989) he writes: “My problems with my use of E arise from MY
intuitions about the use of E. I don’t care how YOU use E. Philosophy is
personal.” Much criticised, but authentic, in a way!“Since he discounts the
latter intuition, Grice cannot place much weight on the former!”As I say,
Grice’s intuitions are hard to fathom! So are his introspections! Actually, I
think that Grice’s sticking with introspections and intuitions save him, as
Suppes shows in PGRICE ed Grandy and Warner, from being a behaviourist. He is,
rather, an intentionalist!“While a complete review of ambiguity tests is beyond
the scope of this essay, we have perhaps seen enough to motivate the
methodological problem with which we began: viz., that an, intuitive, alleged,
ambiguity seems fit to be explained either semantically (ambiguity thesis,
polysemy, bi-semy) or pragmatically/conversationally, with little by way of
direct evidence to tell us which is which!”“If philosophy generated no
problems, it would be dead!”Grice. J“Linguists
Zwicky and Sadock review several linguistic tests for ambiguity (e.g.
conjunction reduction) and point out that most are ill-suited to detect
ambiguities where the meanings in question are privative opposites,”Oddly,
Grice’s first publication ever was on “Negation and privation,” 1938!Bontly:
“i.e. where one meaning is a specialization or specification of the other (as
for instance with the female and neutral senses of ‘goose’).”Or cf. Urmson,
“There is an animal in the backyard.” “You mean Aunt Matilda?”Bontly: “Since
the putative ambiguities of ‘or’ and the like are all of this sort, it seems
inevitable that these tests will fail us here as well. For further discussion,
see linguist Horn (1989, 317–18 and
365–66) and linguist Carston (2002,
274–77).It is hardly surprising, therefore, to find that a Gricean
typically falls back on a methodological argument like parsimony, as
instantiated in “M. O. R.”Let’s now turn to Parsimony and Its Problems. It may,
at first, be less than obvious why an ambiguity or polysemy or bi-semy account
should be deemed less parsimonious than its Gricean rival.” Where the
conventionalist or ambiguist posits an additional sense S2, Grice adds, to S1,
a conversational implicaturum, I”. Cheap, but no free lunch! (Grice
saves)Bontly: “Superficially, little seems to be gained.” Ah, the surfaces of
Oxford superficiality! “Looking closer, however, the methodological virtues of
the Grice’s approach seem fairly clear.”Good!Bontly: “First, the principles and
inference patterns that a pragmatic or conversational account utilizes are
independently motivated. The principles and inference patterns are needed in
any case to account for the relatively un-controversial class of particularized
implicatura, and they provide an elegant approach to phenomena like figures of
rhetoric, or speech -- metaphor, irony, meiosis, litotes, understatement,
sarcasmcfr. Holdcroft -- and tricks like Strawson’s presupposition. So it would
seem that Grice can make do with explanatory material already on hand, whereas
the ambiguity or polysemy theorist must posit a new semantic rule in each and
every case. Furthermore, the explanatory material has an independent grounding
in considerations of rationality.”I love that evening when Grice received a
phonecall at Berkeley: “Professor Grice: You have been appointed the Immanuel
Kant Memorial Lecturer at Stanford.” He gave the lectures on aspects of reason
and reasoning!Bontly: “Since conversation is typically a goal-directed
activity, it makes sense for conversationalists to abide by the Principle of
Conversational Cooperation (something like Kant’s categorical imperative, in
conversational format) and its (universalisable) conversational maxims, and so
it makes sense for a co-conversationalist to interpret the conversationalist
accordingly. A pragmatic explanation is therefore CHEAPhence Occam on
‘aeconomicus’ -- the principle it calls on being explainable by — and perhaps
even reducible to — facts about rational behavior in general.”I loved your
“REDUCE.” B. F. Loar indeed thought, and correctly, that the maxims are
‘empirical generalisations over functional states.’ Genius!Bontly: A pragmatic
account is not only more economic, or cheaper. It also reveals an orderliness
or systematicity that positing a separate lexical ambiguity or polysemy or
bisemy in each and every case would seem to miss (linguist/philosopher Bach).
To a Griceian, it is no accident that a sentential connective or truth-functor
(“not,” “and,” “or,” and “if”), a quantified expression (Grice’s “all” and
“some (at least one)”) and a description (Grice’s “the”) all lend themselves to
a weak and a stronger interpretation”Cf. Holdcroft, “Weak or strong?” in “Words
and deeds.”Bontly: “Note, for instance, that a sentence with the logical form
‘Some Fs are Gs’, and the pleonethetic,
to use Geach’s and Altham’s coinage, ‘Most Fs are Gs’, and ‘A few Fs are Gs’
are all allegedly ‘ambiguous’ in the SAME way. Each of those expressions has an
obvious weak reading in addition to a stronger reading: ‘Not all Fs are
Gs’.Good because Grice’s first examination was: “That pillar-box seems red to
me.” And he analyses the oddness in terms of ‘strength.’ (Grice 1961). He tries
to analyse this ‘strength’ in terms of ‘entailment,’ but fails (“Neither ‘The
pillar-box IS red’ NOR ‘The pillar-box SEEMS red’ entail each other.”)Bontly:
For the conventionalist or polysemy theorist, there is no apparent reason why
this should be so. There is no reason, that is, why three etymologically
unrelated words (“some,” “most,” and “few”) should display the SAME pattern of
alleged ambiguity. The Gricean, on the other hand, explains each the SAME way,
by appealing to some rational principle of conversation. The implicatura are
all ‘scalar’ quantity implicatura, attributable to the utterer U’s having
uttered a weaker, less informative, sentence than he might have.” Linguist
Levinson, 1983). Together, these considerations make a persuasive case for the
Grice’s approach. A pragmatic explanation is more economical, and the resulting
view of conversation is more natural and unified. Since economy and unification
are both presumably virtues to be sought in a scientific or philosophical
explanation — virtues which for brevity I lump together under Occamist
‘parsimony’ — it would NOT be unreasonable to conclude that a pragmatic
explanation is (ceteris paribus) a better explanation. So it seems that Grice’s
principle, the “M. O. R.” is correct. Senses ought not to be multiplied when
pragmatics will do. Still, there are several reasons to be suspicious of the
parsimony argument. “I lay out three. It bears emphasis that none of these are
objections to the pragmatic approach per se.” I have no quarrel with the theory
of conversation or particular attempts to apply it to conversational phenomena.
The objections focus rather on the role that parsimony (or simplicity, or
generality, etc.) plays in arguments PRO the implicaturum and CONTRA ambiguity
or polysemy.” Then, there’s Dead Metaphors. First is a worry that parsimony is
too blunt an instrument, generalizing to unwanted conclusions. Versions of this
objection appear in philosopher Walker (1975), linguist Morgan (1978), and
linguist Sadock (1978).” More recently, Reimer (1998) and Devitt (forthcoming)
use it to argue against a Gricean treatment of the referential/attributive
distinction.”But have they read Grice’s VACUOUS NAMES? I know you did! Grice
notes: “My distinction has nothing to do with Donnellan’s!” Grice’s approach is
syntactic: ‘the’ and “THE,” identificatory and non-identificatory uses. R. M.
Sainsbury and D. E. Over have worked on this. Fascinating. Bontly: “For as with
the afore-mentioned so-called ‘dead’ metaphor, it can happen that a word has a
secondary use that is pragmatically predictable, and yet fully conventional. In
many such cases, of course, the original, etymological meaning is long
forgotten: e. g. the contemporary use of ‘fornication’, originally a euphemism
for activities done in fornice (that is, in the vaulted underground dwellings
that once served as brothels in Rome). (I owe this [delightful] example to Sam
Wheeler). Few speakers recall the original meaning, so the metaphor can no
longer be ‘calculated,’ as Grice’s “You’re the cream in my coffee!” (title of
song) can!” The metaphor is both dead _and buried_.”Still un-buriable?“In other
cases, however, speakers do possess the information to construct a Gricean
explanation, and yet the metaphor is dead anyway.”Reimer’s (1998) example of
the verb ‘incense’ is a case in point. One conventional meaning (‘to make or
become angry’) began life as a metaphorical extension of the other (‘to make
fragrant with incense’). The reason for the extension is fairly transparent
(resting on familiar comparisons of burning and emotion), but the use allegedly
represents an additional sense nonetheless.”What dictionaries have as ‘fig.’
But are we sure that when the dictionaries list things like 1., 2., 3., they
are listing SENSES!? Cf. Grice, “I don’t give a hoot what the dictionary says,”
to Austin, “And that’s where you make your big mistake.” Once Grice actually
opened the dictionary (he was studying ‘feeling + adj.’he got to ‘byzantine,’
finding that MOST adjectives did, and got bored!Bontly: Such examples suggest
that an implicaturum makes up an important source of semantic—and, according to
linguist Levinson (2000), syntactic—innovation. A linguistic phenomenon can
begin life as a pragmatic specialization or an extension and subsequently
become conventionalized by stages, making it difficult to determine at what
point (and for which ‘utterers’) a use has become fully conventional. One
consequence is that an expression E can have, allegedly, a second sense S2,
even when a pragmatic explanation appears to make it explanatorily superfluous,
and parsimony can therefore mislead.”I’m not sure dictionary readers read
‘fig.’ as a different ‘sense,’ and lexicographers need not be Griceian in
style!Bontly: “A related point is that an ambiguity account needn’t be LESS
unified than an implicaturum account after all. If pragmatic considerations can
explain the origin and development of new linguistic conventions, the ambiguity
or polysemy theorist can provide a unified dia-chronic account of how several
un-related expressions came to exhibit similar patterns of alleged ‘ambiguity.’
Quantifiers like ‘some’, ‘most’, and ‘a few’ may be similarly allegedly
ambiguous today because they generated similar implicaturums in the past (cf.
Millikan, 2001).”OKAY, so that’s the right way to go then? Diachrony and
evolution, right?Bontly: “Then, there’s Tradeoffs. A ‘dead’ metaphor suggests
that parsimony is too strong for the pragmatist’s purposes, but as a pragmatic
account could have hidden costs to offset the semantic savings, parsimony may
also be too weak! E. g. an implicaturum account looks, at least superficially,
to multiply (to use Occam’s term) inferential labour, leaving it to the
addressee to infer the utterer’s intended meaning from the words uttered, the
context, and the conversational principle. Thus there are trade-offs involved,
and the account which is semantically more parsimonious may be less
parsimonious all things considered.”Grice once invited the “P. E. R. E.,”
principle of economy of rational effort, though. Things which seem to be
psychologically UNREAL are just DEEMED, tacitly, to occur.Bontly: “To be clear,
this is not to suggest that the ambiguity or polysemy account can dispense with
inference entirely. Were the exclusive and inclusive senses of ‘or’ BOTH
lexically encoded (as they were in Old Roman, ‘vel’ and ‘aut,’ hence
Whitehead’s choice of ‘v’ for ‘p v q’) still hearers would need to infer from
contextual clues which meaning were intended. The worry is not, therefore, so much
that the implicaturum account increases the number of inferences which
conversants or conversationalists have to perform. The issue concerns rather
the complexity of these inferences. Alleged dis-ambiguation is a highly
constrained process. In principle, one need only choose the relevant sense Sn,
from a finite list represented in the so-called ‘mental lexicon’. Implicaturum
calculation, on the other hand, is a matter of finding the best explanation
(abductively, alla Hanson) for an utterer’s utterance, the utterer’s meaning
being introduced as an explanatory hypothesis, answering to a ‘why’ question.
Unlike dis-ambiguation, where the various possible readings are known in
advance, in the conversational explanation, the only constraints are provided
by the addressee’s understanding of the context and the conversational
principle. So it appears that Grice’s approach saves on the lexical semantics
by placing a greater inferential burden on utterer and addressee.”But Grice
played bridge, and loved those burdens. Stampe actually gives a lovely bridge
alleged counter-example to Grice (in Grice 1989).Bontly: “Now, a Gricean can
try to lessen this load in various ways. Grice can argue, for instance, that
the inference used to recover a generalised implicaturum is less demanding than
that for a particularized one, that familiarity with types of generalised
implicate can “stream-line” the inferential process, and so on.”Love thatE. R.
E., or principle of economy of rational effort, above?!Bontly: “We examine
these moves. There’s Justification. Another difficulty with Grice’s appeals to
parsimony is the most fundamental. On the one hand, it can hardly be denied
that parsimony plays a role in scientific, if not philosophical, inference.”
Across the sciences, if not in philosophy, it is standard practice to cite
parsimony (simplicity, generality, etc.) as a reason to choose one hypothesis
over another; philosophers often do the same.”Bontly’s ‘often’ implicates,
‘often not’! Grice became an opponent of his own minimalism at a later stage of
his life, vide his “Prejudices and predilections; which become, the life and
opinions of Paul Grice,” by Paul Grice!Bontly: “At the same time, however, it
remains quite mysterious, if that’s the word, why parsimony (etc.) should be given
such weight by Occamists like Grice. If it were safe to assume that Nature is
simple and economical, the preference for theories with these qualities would
make perfect sense. Sir Isaac Newton offers such an ontological rationale for
parsimony in the “Principia.” Sir Isaac writes (in Roman?) “I am to admit no
more cause of a natural thing than such as are true and sufficient to explain
its appearance.” “To this purpose, the philosopher says that Nature does
nothing in vain, and more is in vain when less serves.” “For Nature is pleased
with simplicity, and affects not the pomp of a superfluous cause.” “While a
blanket assertion about the simplicity of Nature is hardly uncommon in the
history of science, today it is viewed with suspicion.” Bontly: “Newton’s reasons were presumably
theological.” “If I knew that the Creator values simplicity and economy, I
should expect the creatION to display these qualities as well.” “Lacking much
information about the Creator’s tastes, however, the assumption becomes quite
difficult, if not impossible, to support.”Cfr. literature on ‘biological
diversity.’Bontly: “(Sober discusses several objections to an ontological
justification for the principle of parsimony. Philosopher of science Mary Hesse
surveys several other attempts to justify the use of parsimony and simplicity
in scientific inference. Philosophers of science today are largely persuaded
that the role of parsimony is ‘purely methodological’ epistemological,
pragmatist, rather than ontological — that it is rational to reject unnecessary
posits (or complex, dis-unified theories) no matter what Nature is like. One
might argue, for instance, that the principle of parsimony is really just a
principle of minimum risk. The more existence claims one accepts, the greater the
chance of accepting a falsehood. Better, then, to do without any existence
claim one does not need. Philosopher J. J. C. Smart attributes this view to
John Stuart Mill.”Cf. Grice: “Not to bring more Grice to the Mill.”Bontly:
“Now, risk minimization may be a reasonable methodological principle, but it
does not suffice to explain the role of parsimony in natural science. When a
theoretical posit is deemed explanatorily superfluous, the accepted practice is
not merely to withhold belief in its existence but to conclude positively that
it does not exist. As Sober notes, ‘Occam’s razor preaches atheism about
unnecessary entities, not just a-gnosticism.’” Similarly, Grice’s razor tells
us that we should believe an expression E to be unambiguous, aequi-vocal, monosemous,
unless we have evidence for a second meaning. The absence of evidence for this
alleged additional, ‘multiplied’ ‘sense’ is presumed to count as evidence that
this alleged second, additional, multiplied, sense is absent, does not exist.
But an absence of evidence is not the same thing as evidence of an absence.”
The difficult question about scientific methodology is why we should count one
as the other. Why, that is, should a lack of evidence for an existence claim
count as evidence for a non-existence claim? The minimum risk argument leaves
this question unanswered. Indeed, philosophers of science have had so little
success in explaining why parsimony should be a guide to truth that many are
tempted to conclude that it and the other ‘super-empirical virtues’ have no
epistemic value whatsoever. Their role is rather pragmatic, or aesthetic.”This
is in part Strawson’s reply in his “If and the horseshoe” (1968), repr. in
PGRICE, in Grandy/Warner. He says words to the effect: “Grice’s theory may be
more BEAUTIFUL than mine, but that’s that!” (Strawson thinks that ‘if’ acts as
‘so’ or ‘therefore’ but in UNASSERTED clauses. So it’s a matter of a
‘conventional’ IMPLICATURUM to the inferrability of “if p, q” or “p; so, q.” I
agree with Strawson that Grice’s account of ‘conventional’ implicaturum is not
precisely too beautiful?Bontly: “Parsimony can make a theory easier to
understand or apply, and it pleases those of us with a taste for desert
landscapes, but (according to these sceptics) they do not make the theory any
more likely to be true.”The reference to the ‘desert landscape’ is genial. Cfr.
Strawson’s “A logician’s landscape.” Later in life, Grice indeed found it
unfair that an explanation of cherry trees blooming in spring should be
explained as a ‘desert landscape.’ “That’s impoverishing it!”Bontly: “van
Fraassen, for instance, tells us that a super-empirical virtue ‘does not
concern the relation between the theory and the world, but rather the use and
usefulness of the theory; it provide reasons to prefer the theory independently
of questions of truth.” “If that were correct, it would be doubtful that
parsimony can shoulder the burden Grice places on it.” “For then the
conventionalist may happily grant that a pragmatic explanation is clever and
elegant, and beautiful.” “The
conventionalist can agree that an implicaturum account comprehends a maximum of
phenomena with a minimum of theoretical apparatus.” “But when it comes to
truth, or alethic satisfactoriness, as Grice would prefer, a conventionalist
may insist that parsimony is simply irrelevant.” “One Gricean sympathizer who
apparently accepts the ‘aesthetic’ view of parsimony is the philosopher of
science R. C. S. Walker (1975), who claims that the ‘[c]hoice between Grice’s
and Cohen’s theories is an aesthetic matter’ and concludes that ‘we should not
regard either the Conversationalist Hypothesis or its [conventionalist] rivals
as definitely right or wrong.’” Cfr. Strawson in Grandy/Warner, but Strawson is
no Griceian sympathiser! “Now asking Grice to justify the principle of
parsimony may seem a bit unfair.” “Grice also assumes the reality of the
external world, the existence of intentional mental states, and the validity of
modus ponens.” “Need Grice justify these assumptions as well?” “Of course not!”
“But even if the epistemic value of parsimony is taken entirely for granted, it
is unclear why it should even count in semantics.” “All sides agree, after all,
that many, perhaps even most, expressions of natural language are allegedly
‘ambiguous.’” “There are both poly-semies, where one word has multiple, though
related, meanings (‘horn’, ‘trunk’), and homo-nymies, where two distinct words
have converged on a single phonological form (‘bat’, ‘pole’).” “The distinction between poly-semy and
homo-nymy is notoriously difficult to draw with any precision, chiefly because
we lack clear criteria for the identity of words (Bach).” “If words are
individuated phono-logically, there would be no homo-nyms.” “If words are
individuated semantically, there would be no poly-semies.” “Individuating words
historically leads to some odd consequences: e.g., that ‘bank’ is poly-semous
rather than homo-nymous, since the ‘sense’ in which it means financial
institution and the ‘sense’ in which it means edge of a river are derived from
a common source.” “I owe this example to David Sanford. For further discussion,
see Jackendoff.”Soon at Hartford. And Sanford is right!Bontly: “Given that
ambiguity is hardly rare, then, one wonders whether a semantic theory ought
really to minimize it (cf. Stampe, 1974).” “One might indeed argue that the
burden of proof here is on the pragmatist, not the ambiguity or polysemy
theorist.” “Perhaps we ought to assume, ceteris paribus, that every regular use
of an expression represents a SPECIAL sense.” “Such a methodological policy may
be less economical than Grice’s, but it does extend the same pattern of
explanation to all alleged ambiguities, and it might even accord better with
the haphazard ways in which natural languages are prone to evolve (Millikan,
2001).”Yes, the evolutionary is the way to go!Bontly: “So Grice owe us some
reason to think that parsimony and the like should count in semantics.” “He
needn’t claim, of course, that parsimony is always and everywhere a reason to
believe a hypothesis true.” “He needn’t produce a global justification for
Occam’s Razor, that is—a local justification, one specific to language, would
suffice.” “I propose to set aside the larger issue about parsimony in general,
therefore, and argue that Modified Occam’s Razor can be justified by
considerations peculiar to the study of language.” “Now for A Developmental
Account of Semantic Parsimony.” “My
approach to parsimony in linguistics is inspired by Sober’s work on parsimony arguments
in evolutionary biology.”And Grice was an evolutionary philosopher of
sorts.Bontly: “In Sober’s view, philosophers have misunderstood the role of
parsimony in scientific inference, taking it to function as a global,
domain-general principle of scientific reasoning (akin perhaps to an axiom of
the probability calculus).” “A more realistic analysis, Sober claims, shows
that parsimony arguments function as tacit references to domain-specific
process assumptions — to assumptions (whether clearly articulated or not) about
the process(es) that generate the phenomena under study.” “Where these
processes tend to be frugal, parsimony is a reasonable principle of
theory-choice.” “Where they are apt to be profligate, it is not.” “What makes
parsimony reasonable in one area of inquiry may, on Sober’s view, be quite
unrelated to the reasons it counts in another.” “Parsimony arguments in the
units of selection controversy, for instance, rest on one set of process
assumptions (i.e. assumptions about the conditions necessary for ‘group’
selection to occur).” “The application of parsimony to ‘phylogenetic’ inference
rests on a completely different set of assumptions (about rates of evolutionary
change).” “As Sober notes, in either case the assumptions are empirically
testable, and it could turn out that parsimony is a reliable principle of
inference in one, both, or neither of these areas. Sober’s approach amounts to
a thorough-going local reductionism about parsimony.It counts in theory-choice
if and only if there are domain-specific reasons to think the theory which is
more economical (in some specifiable respect) is more likely to be true. The
‘only if’ claim is the more controversial part of the bi-conditional, and I
need not defend it here. For present purposes I need only the weaker claim that
domain-specific assumptions can be sufficient to justify using parsimony — that
parsimony is a sensible principle of inference if the phenomena in question
result from processes themselves biased, as it were, towards parsimony. Now, in
natural-language semantics, the phenomena in question are ordinarily taken to
be the semantic rules or conventions shared by a community of speakers.”Cf.
Peacocke on Grice as applied to ‘community of utterers,’ in Evans/McDowell,
Truth and meaning, Oxford. Bontly: “The task is to uncover the ‘arbitrary’
mappings between a sound and a meaning (or concepts or referent) of which
utterers have tacit knowledge. This ‘semantic competence’ is shaped by both the
inputs that language learners encounter and the cognitive processes that guide language
acquisition from infancy through adulthood. So the question is whether that
input and these processes are themselves biased toward semantic parsimony and
against the acquisition of multiple meanings for single phonological forms. As
I shall now argue, there are several reasons to suspect that such a bias should
exist. Psychologists often conceptualize learning in general and word learning
in particular as a process of generating and testing hypotheses. A child (or,
in many cases, an adult) encounters an unfamiliar word, forms one or more
hypotheses as to its possible meaning, checks the hypotheses against the ways
in which he hears the word used, and finally adopts one such hypothesis. This
‘child-as-scientist’ model is plainly short on details, but whatever mechanism
implements the generating and testing, it would seem that the process cannot be
repeated with every subsequent exposure to a word. Once a hypothesis is
accepted — a word learned — the process effectively halts, so that the next
time the child hears that word, he doesn’t have to hypothesize. Instead, the
child can access the known meaning and use it to grasp the intended message.
For that reason, an unfamiliar word ought to be the only one to trigger the
learning process, and that of course makes ambiguity problematic. Take a person
who knows one meaning of an ambiguous word, but not the other. To him, the word
is not unfamiliar, even when used with an unfamiliar meaning. At least, it will
not sound unfamiliar. So, the learning process will not kick in unless some
other source of evidence suggests another, as-yet-unknown meaning. Presumably
the evidence will come from ‘anomalous’ utterances: i.e. uses that are
contextually absurd, given only the familiar meaning. This is not to say, of
course, that hearing one anomalous utterance would be sufficient to re-start
the learning process. Since there are other reasons why an utterance may seem
anomalous (e.g. the utterer simply misspoke), it might take several anomalies
to convince one that the word has another meaning. In the absence of anomalies,
however, it seems highly unlikely that learners would seriously entertain the
possibility of a second sense. A related point is that acquisition involves, or
is at least thought to involve, a variety of ‘boot-strapping’ operations where
the learner uses what he knows of the language in order to learn more.”Oddly
Grice has a bootstrap principle (it relates to having one’s metalanguage as
rich as one’s object-language.Bontly: “It has been argued, for instance, that
children use semantic information to constrain hypotheses about words’
syntactic features (Pinker) and, conversely, syntactic information to constrain
hypotheses about words’ semantic features (Gleitman). Likewise, children must
surely use their knowledge of some words’ meanings to constrain hypotheses as
to the meanings of others, thus inferring the meanings of unfamiliar words from
context. However, that process only works insofar as one can safely assume that
the familiar words in an utterance are typically used with their familiar
meanings. If it were assumed that familiar words are typically used with
unknown meanings, the bootstraps would be too weak. Together, these
considerations point to the hypothesis that language acquisition is semantically
conservative. Children will posit new meanings for familiar words only when
necessary—only when they encounter utterances that make no sense to them, even
though all the words are familiar. Interestingly, experimental work in language
acquisition provides empirical evidence for much the same conclusion.
Psychologists have long observed that children have considerable difficulties
learning and using homo-nyms (Peters and Zaidel), leading many to suspect that
young children operate under the helpful, though mistaken, assumption that a
word can have but one meaning (Slobin). Children have similar difficulties
acquiring synonyms and may likewise assume that a given meaning can be
represented by at most one word. (Markman & Wachtel, see Bloom for a different
explanation). I cannot here survey the many experimental studies bearing on
this hypothesis, but one series of experiments conducted by Michele Mazzocco is
particularly germane. Mazzocco presents children from several age-groups, as
well as adults, with stories designed to mimic one’s first encounter with the
secondary meaning of an ambiguous word. To control the effects of antecedent
familiarity with secondary meanings, the stories used familiar words (e.g.,
‘rope’) as if they had further unknown meanings—as ‘pseudo-homo-nyms’.For
comparison, other stories included a non-sense word (e.g. ‘blus’) used as if it
had a conventional meaning — as a ‘pseudo-word’ — to mimic one’s first
encounter with an entirely unfamiliar word.”Cf. Grice’s seminar at Berkeley: “How
pirots karulise elatically: some simpler ways.”“A pirot can be said to potch or cotch an obble as
fang or feng or fid with another obble.”“A person can be said to perceive or
cognize an object as having the property f or f2 or being in a relation R with another
object.”Bontly: Some stories, finally, used only genuine words with only their
familiar meanings. After hearing a story, subjects are presented with a series
of illustrations and asked to pick out the item referred to in the story. In a
subsequent experiment, subjects had to act out their interpretations of the
stories. In the pseudo-homo-nym condition, one picture would always illustrate
the word’s conventional but contextually inappropriate meaning, one would
depict the unfamiliar but contextually appropriate meaning, and the rest would
be distractors. As one would expect, adults and older children (10- to
12-year-olds) performed equally well on these tasks, reliably picking out the
intended meanings for familiar words, non-sense words and pseudo-homonyms
alike. Young children (3- to 5-year-olds), on the other hand, could understand
the stories where familiar words were used conventionally, and they were
reasonably good at inferring the intended meanings of non-sense words from
context, but they could not do so for pseudo-homonyms. Instead, they reliably
chose the picture illustrating the familiar meaning, even though the story made
that meaning quite inappropriate. These results are noteworthy for several
reasons. It is significant, first of all, that spontaneous positing of
ambiguities did not occur. As long as the known meaning of a word comported
with its use in a story, subjects show not the slightest tendency to assign
that word a new, secondary meaning—just as one would expect if the acquisition
process were semantically conservative. Second, note that performance in the
non-sense word condition confirms the familiar finding that young children can
acquire the meanings of novel words from context — just as the bootstrapping
procedure suggests. Unlike older children and adults, however, these young
children are unable to determine the meanings of pseudo-homo-nyms from context,
even though they could do so for pseudo-words — exactly what one would expect
if young children assumed that words can have one meaning only. Why young
children would have such a conservative bias remains controversial.
Unfortunately it would take us too far afield to delve into this debate here.
Doherty finds evidence that the understanding of ambiguity is strongly correlated
with a grasp of synonymy, suggesting that these biases have a common source.”
Doherty also finds evidence that the understanding of ambiguity/synonymy is
strongly predicted by the ability to reason about false beliefs, suggesting the
intriguing hypothesis that young children’s biases are due to their lack of a
representational ‘theory of mind’).” Cf.
Grice on transmission of true beliefs in “Meaning, revisited.”a transcendental
argument.Bontly: “Nonetheless, Mazzocco’s results provide empirical evidence for
our conjecture that a person will typically posit a second meaning for a known
word only when necessary (and, as with young children, not always then). And
that, of course, is precisely the sort of process assumption that would make
Grice’s “M. O. R.” a reasonable principle for theory choice in semantics. For
we have been operating under the assumption that the principal task of
linguistic semantics is to describe the competent speaker’s tacit linguistic
knowledge. If that knowledge is shaped by a process biased toward semantic
parsimony, our semantic theorizing ought surely to be biased in the same
direction. Is Pragmatism Vindicated?” That said, the question is still open
whether Grice’s “M. O. R.,” understood now developmentally, ontogenetically, and
not phylogenetically, as perhaps Millikan would prefer, has such consequences
as Gricea typically assumes. In particular, it remains for us to consider
whether and, if so, when the above process assumptions favor implicaturum
hypotheses over ambiguity hypotheses, and the answer would seem to hang on two
further issues. First, there is in each case the question whether a child
learning the language will find it necessary to posit a second sense for a
given expression. The fact that linguists, apprised as they are of the
principles of conversation, find it unnecessary to introduce a second sense for
(e.g.) ‘or’ does NOT imply that children would find it unnecessary. For one
thing, children might acquire the various uses of ‘or’ well before they have
any pragmatic understanding themselves.”Cfr. You can eat the cake or the
sandwich.”Bontly: Even if they do not, the order in which the various uses are
acquired could make considerable difference.It may be, for instance, that a
child who first learned the inclusive use of ‘or’ would have no need to posit a
second exclusive sense, whereas a child who originally interpreted ‘or’
exclusively might need eventually to posit an additional, inclusive sense. So
we may well have to determine what meaning children first attach to an
expression in order to determine whether they would find it necessary to posit
a second. The issues raised above are pretty clearly empirical ones, and
significant inter-personal differences could complicate matters considerably.
Just for the sake of argument, however, let us grant that children do indeed
first learn to interpret ‘or’ inclusively, to interpret ‘and’ as mere
conjunction, and so on. Let us assume, that is, that the meanings which Grice
typically takes to be conventional are just that. In fact, the assumption that
weak uses are typically learned first has garnered some empirical support, as
one referee brought to my attention. Paris shows that children are less likely
than adults to interpret ‘or’ exclusively (see also Sternberg, and Braine and
Rumain). More recent experimental work indicates that children first learn to
interpret ‘and’ a-temporally (Noveck and Chevaux) and ‘some’ weakly (as
compatible with ‘all’) (Noveck, 2001). Even so, it remains an interesting
question whether children would posit secondary senses for any of these
expressions, and Grice would be on firm ground in arguing that they would not.
First, the ‘ambiguities’ discussed at the outset all involve secondary uses
which can, with the help of pragmatic principles, be understood in terms of the
presumed primary meaning of the expression. If a child, encountering this
secondary use for the first time, already knows the primary meaning, and if he
has moreover an understanding of the norms of conversation—if he is a ‘Griceian
child’ —, he ought to be able to understand the secondary use perfectly well.
He can recover the implicaturum and infer the speaker’s meaning from the
encoded meaning of the utterance. To the ‘Griceian child,’ therefore, the
utterance would not be anomalous. It would make perfect sense in context,
giving him no reason to posit a secondary meaning. But what about children who
are not yet Griceans — children too young to understand pragmatic principles or
to have the conceptual resources to make inferences about other people’s likely
communicative intentions? While there seems to be no consensus as to when
pragmatic abilities emerge, several considerations suggest that they develop
fairly early. Bloom argues that pragmatic understanding is part of the best
account of how children learn the meanings of words. Papafragou discusses
evidence that children can calculate implicaturums as early as age three. Such
children, knowing only the primary meaning of the expression, would be unable
to recover the conversational implicaturum and thus unable to grasp the
secondary use of the expression via the pragmatic route. Nonetheless, I argue
that they would still (at least in most cases) find it unnecessary to posit a
second meaning for the expression. Consider: the ‘ambiguities’ at issue all
involve secondary meanings which are specificatory, being identical to the
primary but for some additional feature making it more restricted or specific.
The primary and second meanings would thus be privative, as opposed to polar, opposites;
Zwicky and Sadock). What a speaker means when he uses the expression in this
secondary way, therefore, would typically imply the proposition he would mean
if he were speaking literally (i.e. if he were using the primary meaning of the
expression). One could thus say something true using the secondary sense only
in contexts where one could say something true using the primary sense—whenever
‘P exclusive-or Q’ is true, so is ‘P inclusive-or Q’; whenever ‘P and-then Q’
is true, so is ‘P and Q’; and so on. Thus even when the intended meaning
involves the alleged second sense, the utterance would still come out true if
interpreted with the primary sense in mind. And this means, crucially, that the
utterance would not seem anomalous, there being no obvious clash between the
primary interpretation of the utterance and the conversational context. The
utterance may well be pragmatically inappropriate when interpreted this way,
but our pre-Gricean child is insensitive to such niceties. Otherwise, he would be
already a ‘Gricean’ child. On our account, therefore, the pre-Gricean child
still sees no need to posit a second meaning for the expression, even though he
could not grasp the intended (specificatory) meaning. We may illustrate the
above with the help of an ‘ambiguity’ in the indefinite description (“a dog”)
made famous by Grice. A philosopher would ordinarily take an expressions of the
form ‘an F’ to be a straightforward existential quantifier, “(Ex)”, as would
seem to be the case in ‘I am going to a meeting’ On the other hand, an
utterance of ‘I broke a finger’ seems to imply that it is my finger which I
broke (unless you are a nurseI think Horn’s cancellation goes), whereas ‘I saw
a dog in the backyard’ would seem to carry the opposite sort of implication —
i.e. that it was not my dog which I saw.”Grice finds this delightful ‘reductio’
of the sense-positer: “a” would have _three_ senses!Bontly: “We have then the
potential for a three-way ambiguity, but our ruminations on word learning argue
against it.”Take a child who has learned (somehow) the weak (existential
quantier) use of ‘an F’ (Ex)Fx, but has for some reason never been exposed to
strong uses: ‘my,’ ‘not mine.’ Now the child hears his mother say ‘Come look!
There is a dog in the backyard!’ Running to the window, the child sees not his
mother’s pet dog Fido, but some strange dog, that is not her mother’s. To an
adult, this would be entirely predictable.” Using the indefinite description ‘a
dog’ (logical form, “(Ex)Dx”) instead of the name for the utterer’s dog would
lead one to expect that Fido (the utterer’s dog) is not the dog in
question.”Actually, like Ryle, Grice has a shaggy-dog story in WJ5, “That dog
is hairy-coated.” “Shaggy, if you must!”. Bontly: “And if the child were of an
age to have a rudimentary understanding of the pragmatic aspects of language
use, he would make the same prediction and thus see no need here to posit a
second ‘sense’ for ‘an F,’ and take ‘not mine’ as an implicaturum.”It’s
different with what Grice would have as an ‘established idiom’ (his example,
“He’s pushing up the daisies,” but not “He is fertilizing the daffodils”) as
one might argue that “I broke a finger” is. Bontly: “The child would not,
because the intended, contextually appropriate interpretation would be clear
given the primary meaning plus pragmatics, or implicaturum. But even if the
child fails to grasp the intended meaning of his mother’s remark, it still
seems unlikely that the child would be compelled to posit an ambiguity. No
matter what the child’s mother means, there is, after all, a dog in the
backyard (“Gotcha! That’s _a_ dog, my Fido is, ain’t it?!”). So the primary
interpretation still yields a true proposition. While the ‘pre-Gricean child’
thus misses (part of) the intended meaning of the utterance, still he would not
experience a clash between his interpretation and the contextually appropriate
interpretation. Perhaps the pre-Gricean child could be forced to see an
anomaly. Consider the following example. A parent offers her pre-Gricean child
dessert, saying, ‘Ice-cream, or cake?’ When the child helps himself to some of
each, the mother removes the cake with a look of annoyance and says:‘I said
ice-cream OR cake’. “While the mother’s
behavioural response makes it abundantly clear that the child’s ‘inclusive’
interpretation is inappropriate, there are several reasons why he might still
refrain from positing an ambiguity. For one, young children, who are more
Griceian (even pre-Griceian) and logical than a few adults, appear to operate
under the assumption that a word can have one meaning only, and it may be that
pre-Gricean children are simply unable to override this assumption. This would
seem particularly likely if Doherty is right that the ability to understand
ambiguity requires a robust ‘theory of mind’.At any rate, the position taken
here is that recognition of anomaly is necessary for one to posit a second
meaning, not that it is sufficient. Contrast this with a similar case where,
coming to the window, the child sees no dog but does see (e.g.) a motorcycle, a
tree, a bird, and a fence.Then he would have reason to consider an ambiguity,
though other explanations might also fit.” “Perhaps Mom was joking or
hallucinating.” The claim is, then, that language acquisition works in such a
way as to make it unlikely that learners would introduce a second senses for
the ‘ambiguities’ in question. Of course, that claim is contingent on a very
large assumption — viz., that the meaning which Grice take to be lexically
‘encoded’ is indeed the primary meaning of the expression — and that assumption
may be mistaken.” In the continuing debate over Donnellan’s
referential/attributive distinction, for instance, Grice takes it as
uncontroversial that Russell on ‘the’ provides at least one of the conventional
interpretations for sentences of the form ‘The king of France is bald’ (i.e.,
the attributive interpretation).” Grice’s example in “Vacuous names,” that
Bontly quotes, is “Jones’s butler mixed
our coats and hats,” when “Jones’s butler” is actually Jones’s haberdasher
dressed as a butler for the occasion.” So Grice distinguishes between THE
butler (identificatory) and ‘the’ butler (non-identificatory, whoever he might
be). Bontly: From there, they argue that we needn’t posit a secondary
(referential) semantics for descriptions since the referential use can be
captured by Russell’s theory supplemented by Grice’s pragmatics. Grice, 1969
(Vacuous Names); Kripke, 1977; Neale, 1990). From a developmental perspective,
however, the ‘uncontroversial’ assumption that Russell on ‘the’ provides the
primary meaning for description phrases is certainly questionable. It being
likely that the vast majority of descriptions children hear early in life are
used referentially, Grice’s position could conceivably have things exactly backwards—
perhaps the referential is primary with the attributive acquired later, either
as an additional meaning or a pragmatic extension. Still, the fact, if it is a
fact, that a referential use is more common in children’s early environment
does not imply that the referential is acquired first.” Exclusive uses of ‘or’
are at least as frequent as inclusive uses, and yet there is a good deal of
evidence that the inclusive is developmentally primary. (Paris, Sternberg,
Braine and Rumain). Either way, the point remains that plausible assumptions
about language acquisition do indeed justify a role for parsimony in semantics.
These ‘process’ assumptions may, of course, turn out to be incorrect.” If the
evidence points the other way—if it emerges that the learning process posits
ambiguities quite freely—then Grice’s “M. O. R.” could conceivably be
groundless.”Making it a matter of empirical support or lack thereof, and that
was perhaps why Millikan thought that was the wrong way to go? But then if she
thought the evolutionary was the right way to go, wouldn’t THAT make Grice’s
initially ‘sort of’ analytic pragmatist methodological philosophical decision a
matter of fact or lack thereof? Bontly: “Nonetheless, we can see now that the
debate between Grice and the conventionalists is ultimately an empirical,
rather than, as Grice perhaps thougth, a conceptual one. Choices between
pragmatic and semantic accounts may be under-determined by Grice’s intuitions
about meaning and use, but they need not be under-determined tout court. Then
there’s Tradeoffs, Dead Metaphors, and a Dilemma. The developmental approach to
parsimony provides some purchase on the problems regarding tradeoffs and dead
metaphors as well. The former problem is that parsimony can be a double-edged
sword. While an ambiguity account does multiply senses, the implicaturum
account appears to multiply inferential labour. Hearers have to ‘work out’ or
‘calculate’ the utterer’s meaning from the conversational principle, without
the benefit of a list of possible meanings as in disambiguation. Pragmatic
inference thus seems complex and time-consuming. But the fact is that we are
rarely conscious of engaging in any reasoning of the sort Grice requires, pace
his Principle of Economy of Rational Effort. Consequently, the claim that
communicators actually work through all these complicated inferences seems
psychologically unrealistic. To combat these charges, Grice’s response is to
claim that implicaturum calculation is largely unconscious and implicit.”Indeed
Grice’s principle of economy of rational effort. Bontly: “Background
assumptions can be taken for granted, steps can be skipped, and only rarely
need the entire process breach the surface of consciousness. This picture seems
particularly plausible with a generalised implicaturum as opposed to a
particularized one.” When a particular use of an expression E, though
unconventional, has become standard or regular (“I broke a finger”? “He’s
pushing up the daisies”), the inferential process can be considerably
stream-lined; it gets ‘short-circuited’ or ‘compressed by precedent’ (Bach and
Harnish). “Bach’s and Harnish’s notion of short-circuited inference is similar
to but not quite the same as J. L. Morgan’s notion of short-circuited implicaturum.
The latter involves conventions of use (as Searle would put it), to which Bach
and Harnish see their account as an alternative. Levinson objects to Bach’s and
Harnish’s characterization of default inferences as those compressed by the
weight of precedent. A generalised implicaturum, Levinson says, ‘is generative,
driven by general heuristics and not dependent on routinization’ But Levinson’s
complaint against Bach and Harnish may seem uncharitable. Even on Bach’s and
Harnish’s view, where a default inference is that ‘compressed by the weight of
precedent’, a generalised implicaturum is still generative: it is still
generated by the maxims of conversation. Only the stream-lined character of the
inference is dependent on precedent, not the implicaturum itself. If the
addressee has calculated the EXCLUSIVE meaning of ‘or’ enough times in the past
(from his mother, we’ll assume) it
becomes the default, allowing one to proceed directly to the exclusive
interpretation (unless something about the context provides a clue that the
standard interpretation would here be inappropriate. Now, the idea that the
generalised implicaturum can be the default interpretation, reached without all
the fancy inference, provides an obvious reply to the worry about tradeoffs. While
it is true that a pragmatic inference, as Grice calls it, in contrast with the
‘logical inference, -- “Retrospective Epilogue” -- are in principle abductive,
fairly complex and potentially laborious, familiarity can simplify the process
enormously, to the point where it becomes no more difficult than
dis-ambiguation.” But the appeal to a default interpretation raises an
interesting difficulty that (to my knowledge) Grice never adequately addressed.
It is now quite unclear why this default interpretation should be considered an
implicaturum rather than an additional sense of the expression.”Because it’s
cancellable?Bontly: “To say that it is a default interpretation is, after all,
to say that utterers and addressees learn to associate that interpretation with
the type of expression in question. The default meaning is known in advance,
and all one has to do is be on the lookout for information that could rule it
out. “‘Short-circuited’ implicaturum-calculation is thus hard to differentiate
from disambiguation, making Grice’s hypothesis look more like a notional
variant than a real competitor to the ambiguity hypothesis. Insofar as Grice
has considered this problem, his answer appears to be that linguistic meanings,
being conventional, are inherently arbitrary.”cf. Bach and Harnish, 1979, 192–195).”Indeed, in his evolutionary take on
language, it all starts with Green’s self-expression. You get hit, and you
express pain unvoluntarily. Then you proceed to simulate the response in
absence of the hit, but the meaning is “I’m in pain.” Finally, you adopt the
conventions, arbitrary, and say, ‘pain,’ which is only arbitrarily connected
with, well, the pain. It is the last stage that Grice stresses as ‘artificial,’
and ‘arbitrary,’ “non-iconic,” as he retorts to Peirceian terminology he was
familiar with since his Oxford days. Bontly: “The exclusive use of ‘or’, on the
other hand, is entirely predictable from the conversational principle, so there
is nothing arbitrary about it. Thus the exclusive interpretation cannot be part
of the encoded meaning, even if it is the default interpretation. Familiarity
with that use, in other words, can remove the need to go through the canonical
inference, but it does not change the fact that the use has a ‘natural’ (i.e.,
non-conventional, principled, indeed rational) explanation. It doesn’t change
the fact that it is calculable. At this point, however, Grice’s defense of
default pragmatic interpretations collides with our remaining issue, the
problem of a dead metaphor, such as “He is pushing up the daisies.”” Or as
Grice prefers, an ‘established’ or ‘recognised’ ‘idiom.’Bontly: “A metaphor and
other conversational implicatura can become conventionalized and ‘die’, turning
into new senses. In many such cases the original rationale for the use is long
forgotten, but in other cases the dead metaphor remains calculable. A dead
metaphors thus pose a nasty, macabre?, dilemma for Grice.”Especially if the implicaturum
is “He is dead”!Bontly: “On the one hand, it is tempting to argue that a dead
metaphor involves a new conventional meaning precisely because the
interpretation in question is no longer actually inferred via Gricean
inferences (though one could do so if one had to—if, say, one somehow forgot
that the expression had this secondary meaning). If a conversational implicaturum
had to be not just calculaBLE but actually calculatED, that would suffice to
explain why this one-time, one-off, implicaturum is now semantically
significant. But that reply is apparently closed to pragmatists, for then it
will be said that the same is true of (e.g.) the exclusive use of ‘or.’ The
exclusive interpretation is certainly calculabLE, but since no one actually
calculatES it (except in the most unusual of circumstances, as Grice at
Harvard!), the implication should be considered semantic, not pragmatic. On the
other hand, Grice might maintain that an implicaturum need only be calculabLE
and stick by their view that the exclusive reading of ‘or’ is conversationally
implicated. But then we shall have to face the consequence that many a dead
metaphor (“He is pushing up the daisies”) is likewise calculabLE and thus,
according to the present view, ought not to be considered conventional meanings
of the expressions in question, which in most cases seems quite wrong.”I’m
never sure what Grice means by an ‘established idiom.’ Established by whom?
Perhaps he SHOULD consult the dictionary every now and then! Sad the access to
OED3 is so expensive!Bontly: What one needs, evidently, is some reason to treat
these two types of cases differently.To treat the exclusive use of ‘or’ as an implicaturum
(even though it is only rarely calculatED as such) while at the same time to
view (e.g.) the once metaphorical use of ‘incense’ (or ‘… pushing up the
daisies”) as semantically significant (even though it remains calculabLE).” And
the developmental account of parsimony offers just such a reason. On the
present view, the reason that the ambiguity account has the burden of proof has
to do with the nature of the acquisition, learning, ontogenetical process and
specifically with the presumption that language learners will avoid postulating
unnecessary senses. But the implicaturum must be calculable by the learner,
given his prior understanding of the expression E and his level of pragmatic
sophistication.”Grice was a sophisticated. As I think Dora B.-O knows, Moore
has been claiming that Grice’s idea that animals cannot mean, because they are
not ‘sophisticated’ enough, is an empirical claim, even for Grice!Bontly: “t
may be, therefore, that children at the relevant developmental stage have no
difficulty understanding the exclusive use of ‘or’ (etc.) as an implicaturum
and yet lack the understanding necessary to predict that ‘incense’ could be
used to mean to make or become angry, or that to say of someone that he ‘is
pushing up the daisies,’ means that, having died and getting buried, the corpse
is helping the flowers to grow. The child might not realize, for instance, that
‘incense’ also means an aromatic substance that burns with a pleasant odour,
and even those who do probably lack the general background knowledge necessary
to appreciate the metaphorical connections between burning and emotion.”Cf.
Turner and Fauconnier on ‘blends.’Bontly: Either way, the metaphor would be
dead to the child, forcing him to learn that use the same way they learn any
arbitrary convention.”It may do to explore ‘established idioms’ in, say, parts
of England, which are not so ‘established’ in OTHER parts. Nancy Mitford with
his U and non-U distinction may do. “He went to Haddon Hall” invites, for
Mitford, the ‘unintended’ implicaturum that the utterer is NOT upper-class.
“Surely we drop “hall.’ What else can Haddon be?” But the inference may be
lacking for a non-U addressee or utterer. Similarly, in the north of England,
“our Mary,” invites the implicaturum of ‘affection,’ and this may go over the
head of members of the south-of-England community.Bontly: “The way out of the
dilemma, then, is to look to learning.”Alla Kripkenstein?Bontly: To the problem
of tradeoffs, Grice can reply that it is better to multiply (if we must use the
Occamist verb) inferenceslogical inference and pragmatic inference -- than
multiply senses because language acquisition is biased in that direction. And
Grice may likewise answer the problem of a dead metaphor, or established idiom
like, “He’s been pushing up the daisies for some time, now. The reason that
Grice’s “M. O. R.” does not mandate an implicaturum account for Grice as well
is that such a dead metaphor or established idiom is not calculable by children
at the time they learn such expressions, even if they are calculable by some
adult speakers.”Is that a fact? I would think that a child is a ‘relentless
literalist,’ as Grice called Austin. “Pushing up the daisies?” “I don’t see any
daisies!”I think Brigitte Nerlich has a similar example re: irony: MOTHER: What
a BEAUTIFUL day! (ironically)CHILD: What do you mean? It’s pouring and nasty. MOTHER:
I was being ironic.I don’t think the child is going to posit a second sense to
‘beautiful’ meaning ‘nasty.’Bontly: “For the deciding question in applying
Grice’s “M. O. R.” is NOT whether the implicaturum account is available to a
philosopher like Grice, but whether it is available to the learner! On this way
of carving things up, by the way, some alleged ambiguities which Grice would
treat as implicatura could turn out to be semantically significant after all.
Likewise, some allegedly dead metaphor may turn out to be very much alive.”
Look! He did kick the bucket!” “But he’s PRETENDING to die, dear! Some uses,
finally, may vary from utterer to utterer, there being no guarantee that every
utterer will have learned the use in the same way. As a conclusion, a better
understanding of developmental processes might therefore enlarge our appreciation
of the ways in which semantics and pragmatics interact.”Indeed.REFERENCES Atlas,
J. D. “Philosophy without Ambiguity.” Oxford: Clarendon Press. E: Wolfson,
Oxford. Philosopher. And S. Levinson, “It-clefts, informativeness, and logical
form: Radical pragmatics (revised standard version),” in P. Cole (ed.), Radical
Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press.Bach, K. “Thought and Reference,”
Oxford.“Conversational impliciture,” Mind & Language, 9And R. Harnish,
“Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts,” Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bloom“How
Children Learn the Meanings of Words,” Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. “Mind-reading, communication and the learning
of names for things,” Mind & Language, 17Braine, M. and Rumain, B. “Development
of comprehension of ‘or’: evidence for a sequence of developmental
competencies,” Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 31. Davis, S. (ed.)
“Pragmatics: A Reader,” Oxford Devitt, M. “The case for referential
descriptions,” in M. Reimer/A. Bezuidenhout, “Descriptions and Beyond,” Oxford
Doherty, M. “Children’s understanding of homonymy: meta-linguistic awareness
and false belief,” Journal of Child Language, 27 Gazdar, G. “Pragmatics: Implicaturum,
Presupposition, and Logical Form,” New York: Academic Press. Gleitman, L. “The
structural sources of verb meanings,” Language Acquisition, 1Grice, H. P.
“Vacuous names,” in D. Davidson and J. Hintikka, Words and Objections. Dordrecht:
Reidel. Repr. in part in Ostertag, “Definite descriptions,” MIT.Logic and
Conversation. In P. Cole and J. Morgan (eds.), Syntax and Semantics, 3, Speech Acts. New York: Academic Press, 41–58. Reprinted in Grice, 1989, and Davis,
1991. Grice1978: Further notes on logic and conversation. In P. Cole (ed.),
Syntax and Semantics, 9, Pragmatics. New
York: Academic Press, 113–128. Reprinted
in Grice, 1989. Presupposition and conversational implicaturum. In P. Cole
(ed.), Radical Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press, 183–198. Reprinted in
Grice, 1989. Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press. Hesse, M. “Simplicity,” in P. Edwards (ed.), The Encyclopedia of
Philosophy. New York: MacMillan.Jackendoff, R. “Foundations of Language: Brain,
Meaning, Grammar, Evolution,” Oxford. Kripke, S. “Speaker’s reference and
semantic reference,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Repr. in Davis, 1991.
Levinson, S. “Pragmatics,” Cambridge.“Presumptive Meanings: The Theory of
Generalized Conversational Implicaturum,” Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Markman,
E./G. Wachtel, “Childrens’ use of mutual exclusivity to constrain the meaning
of words,” Cognitive Psychology, 20Mazzocco, M. “Children’s interpretations of
homonyms: A developmental study,” Journal of Child Language, 24Morgan, J. L.
“Two types of convention in indirect speech acts,” n P. Cole (ed.): Syntax and
Semantics, 9, Pragmatics. New York:
Academic Press, reprinted in Davis, 1991. Newton, I. “Mathematical Principles
of Natural Philosophy,” A. Motte (trans.) and F. Cajori (rev.). Repr. in R.
Hutchins (ed.), Great Books of the Western World, 34. Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc.,
1952. Noveck, I. When children are more logical than adults are: Experimental
investigations of scalar implicaturum, Cognition, 78, 165–188. And F. Chevaux,
“The pragmatic development of and. In A. Ho, S. Fish, and B. Skarabela,
Proceedings of the 26th Annual Boston University Conference on Language
Development. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.Papafragou, A. “Mind-reading and
verbal communication,” Mind & Language, 17Paris, S. “Comprehension of
language connectives and propositional logical relationships,” Journal of
Experimental Child Psychology, 16.Peters, A./E. Zaidel, “The acquisition of
homonymy. Cognition, 8.Pinker, S. “Language Learnability and Language
Development,” Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Reimer, M. “Donnellan’s
distinction/Kripke’s test.” Analysis, 58.Ruhl, C. “On Monosemy: A Study in
Linguistic Semantics,” Albany, NY: SUNY Press. Sadock, J. “On testing for
conversational implicaturum,” in P. Cole (ed.), Syntax and Semantics, 9, Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press,
Repr. in Davis, 1991. Searle, J. R. “Indirect speech acts,” n P. Cole and J.
Morgan, Syntax and Semantics, 3, Speech
Acts. New York: Academic Press, Repr. in Davis, 1991. Slobin, D.
“Crosslinguistic evidence for a language-making capacity,” n D. Slobin, The
Cross-linguistic Study of Language Acquisition,
2. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Smart, J. “Ockham’s razor,” in J. Fetzer,
“Principles of Philosophical Reasoning,” Totowa, NJ: Rowan and Allanheld.
Sober, E. “The principle of parsimony,” The British Journal for the Philosophy
of Science, 32“Reconstructing the Past,” Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.“Let’s razor
Ockham’s razor,” in D. Knowles, Explanation and Its Limits.
Cambridge.Stalnaker, R. C. “Pragmatic presupposition,” in M. Munitz/P. Unger,
“Semantics and Philosophy,” New York: Academic Press, 197–213. Repr. in Davis, 1991. Stampe, D. W.
“Attributives and interrogatives,” in M. Munitz/P. Unger, Semantics and
Philosophy. New York: Academic Press.Sternberg, R. “Developmental patterns in
the encoding and combination of logical connectives,” Journal of Experimental
Child Psychology, 28 Van Fraassen, B. “The Scientific Image,” Oxford.Walker, R.
C. S. “Conversational implicaturums: a reply to Cohen,” in S. W. Blackburn,
Meaning, Reference, and Necessity. Cambridge. Ziff“Semantic Analysis.” Ithaca:
Cornell University Press. Zwicky, A./J. Sadock, “Ambiguity tests and how to
fail them,” in J. Kimball, Syntax and Semantics, 4. New York: Academic Press.Refs: The Grice Papers, BANC, Bancroft.
MESURA
-- CUM-MESURATUM -- commensuratum: There’s commensurability and there’s
incommensurability“But Protagoras never explies what makes man
commensurableonly implies it!” In the philosophy of science, the property
exhibited by two scientific theories provided that, even though they may not
logically contradict one another, they have reference to no common body of
data. Positivist and logical empiricist philosophers of science like Carnap had
long sought an adequate account of a theoryneutral language to serve as the
basis for testing competing theories. The predicates of this language were
thought to refer to observables; the observation language described the observable
world or (in the case of theoretical terms) could do so in principle. This view
is alleged to suffer from two major defects. First, observation is infected
with theorywhat else could specify the meanings of observation terms except the
relevant theory? Even to perceive is to interpret, to conceptualize, what is
perceived. And what about observations made by instruments? Are these not
completely constrained by theory? Second, studies by Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend, and
others argued that in periods of revolutionary change in science the adoption
of a new theory includes acceptance of a completely new conceptual scheme that
is incommensurable with the older, now rejected, theory. The two theories are
incommensurable because their constituent terms cannot have reference to a
theory-neutral set of observations; there is no overlap of observational
meaning between the competitor theories; even the data to be explained are
different. Thus, when Galileo overthrew the physics of Aristotle he replaced
his conceptual schemehis “paradigm”with one that is not logically incompatible
with Aristotle’s, but is incommensurable with it because in a sense it is about
a different world (or the world conceived entirely differently). Aristotle’s
account of the motion of bodies relied upon occult qualities like natural
tendencies; Galileo’s relied heavily upon contrived experimental situations in
which variable factors could be mathematically calculated. Feyerabend’s even
more radical view is that unless scientists introduce new theories
incommensurable with older ones, science cannot possibly progress, because
falsehoods will never be uncovered. It is an important implication of these
views about incommensurability that acceptance of theories has to do not only
with observable evidence, but also with subjective factors, social pressures,
and expectations of the scientific community. Such acceptance appears to
threaten the very possibility of developing a coherent methodology for science.
modus -- mode of co-relation: a technical jargon, under ‘mode’although Grice uses ‘c’ to
abbreviate it, and sometimes speaks of ‘way’ of ‘co-relation’but ‘mode’ was his
favourite. Grice is not sure whether
‘mode’ ‘of’ and ‘correlation’ are the appropriate terms. Grice speaks of an
associative mode of correlationvide associatum. He also speaks of a
conventional mode of correlation (or is it mode of conventional
correlation)vide non-conventional, and he speaks of an iconic mode of
correlation, vide non-iconic. Indeed he speaks once of ‘conventional correlation’
TO THE ASSOCIATED specific response. So
the mode is rather otiose. In the context when he uses ‘conventional
correlation’ TO THE ASSOCIATED specific response, he uses ‘way’ rather than
modeGrice wants ‘conventional correlation’ TO THE ASSOCIATED specific RESPONSE
to be just one way, or mode. There’s ASSOCIATIVE correlation, and iconic
correlation, and ‘etc.’ Strictly, as he puts it, this or that correlation is
this or that provision of a way in which the expressum is correlated to a
specific response. When symbolizing he uses the informal “correlated in way c
with response r’having said that ‘c’ stands for ‘mode of correlation.’ But
‘mode sounds too pretentious, hence his retreat to the more flowing ‘way.’ Modusmodelllo --
model theory:
Grice, “The etymology of ‘model’ is fascinating.” H. P. Grice, “A conversational model.” Grice: “Since the object of the present exercise, is to
provide a bit of theory which will explain, for a certain family of
cases, why is it that a particular implicaturum is present, I
would suggest that the final test of the adequacy and utility of this
model should be: can it be used to construct an explanation of
the presence of such an implicaturum, and is it more comprehensive
and more economical than any rival? is the no
doubt pre-theoretical explanation which one would be prompted to give
of such an implicaturum consistent with, or better still a favourable pointer
towards the requirements involved in the model? cf. Sidonius: Far otherwise:
whoever disputes with you will find those protagonists of heresy, the Stoics,
Cynics, and Peripatetics, shattered with their own arms and their
own engines; for their heathen followers, if they resist the doctrine and
spirit of Christianity, will, under your teaching, be caught in their own
familiar entanglements, and fall headlong into their own toils; the barbed
syllogism of your arguments will hook the glib tongues of the
casuists, and it is you who will tie up their slippery
questions in categorical clews, after the manner of a clever
physician, who, when compelled by reasoned thought, prepares antidotes for
poison even from a serpent.qvin potivs experietvr qvisqve conflixerit stoicos
cynicos peripateticos hæresiarchas propriis armis propriis qvoqve concvti
machinamentis nam sectatores eorum Christiano dogmati ac sensvi si
repvgnaverint mox te magistro ligati vernaculis implicaturis in retia
sua præcipites implagabvntur syllogismis tuæ propositionis vncatis volvbilem
tergiversantvm lingvam inhamantibvs dum spiris categoricis lubricas qvæstiones
tv potivs innodas acrivm more medicorvm qui remedivm contra venena cum ratio
compellit et de serpente conficivnt.” Grice: “Since the object of the present
exercise, is to provide a bit of theory which will explain, for a certain
family of cases, why is it that a particular conversational
implicaturum is present, I would suggest that
the final tess of the adequacy
and utility of this MODEL should be various. First: can the model be used to
construct an explanation (argumentum) of the presence of this or that
conversational implicaturum? Second, is the model it more comprehensive than
any rival in providing this explanation? Third, is the model more economical
than any rival in providing this explanation? Fourth, is the no doubt pre-theoretical (antecedent)
explanation which one would be prompted to give of such a conversational
implicaturum consistent with the requirements involved in the model. Fifth: is
the no doubt pre-threoretical (antecedent) explanation which one would be prompted
to give of such a conversational implciaturum
better still, a favourable POINTER towards the requirements involved in
the model? Cf. Sidonius: Far otherwise: whoever disputes with you will find
those protagonists of heresy, the Stoics, Cynics, and Peripatetics, shattered
with their own arms and their own engines; for their heathen followers, if
they resist the doctrine and spirit of Christianity, will, under your teaching,
be caught in their own familiar entanglements, and fall headlong into their
own toils; the barbed syllogism of your arguments will hook the
glib tongues of the casuists, and it is you who will tie
up their slippery questions in categorical clews, after the
manner of a clever physician, who, when compelled by reasoned thought, prepares
antidotes for poison even from a serpent -- qvin potivs experietvr qvisqve
conflixerit stoicos cynicos peripateticos hæresiarchas propriis armis propriis
qvoqve concvti machinamentis nam sectatores eorum Christiano dogmati ac sensvi
si repvgnaverint mox te magistro ligati vernacvlis implicatvris in
retia sva præcipites implagabvntur syllogismis tuæ propositionis vncatis
volvbilem tergiversantvm lingvam inhamantibvs dum spiris categoricis lvbricas
qvæstiones tv potivs innodas acrivm more medicorvm qui remedivm contra venena
cvm ratio compellit et de serpente conficivnt. qvin
potivs experietvr qvisqve conflixerit stoicos cynicos peripateticos
hæresiarchas propriis armis propriis qvoqve concvti machinamentis nam
sectatores eorum Christiano dogmati ac sensvi si repvgnaverint mox te
magistro ligati vernacvlis IMPILICATVRIS in retia sva præcipites
implagabvntur syllogismis tuæ propositionis vncatis volvbilem tergiversantvm
lingvam inhamantibvs dum spiris categoricis lubricas qvæstiones tv potivs
innodas acrivm more medicorvm qui remedivm contra venena cvm ratio compellit et
de serpente conficivnt. So Grice has the phenomenon: the conversational
implcaturumthe qualifying adjective is crucial, since surely he is not
interested in non-conventional NON-conversational implicatura derived from
moral maxims! --. And then he needs a MODELthat of the principle or postulate
of conversational benevolence. It fits the various requirements. First: the
model can be used to construct an explanation (argumentum) of the presence of
this or that conversational implicaturum. Second, REQUIREMENT OF PHILOSOPHICAL
GENERALITY -- the model is more
comprehensive than any rival. Third, the OCCAM requirement: the model is more
ECONOMICAL than any rivalin what sense?“in providing this explanation” of this
or that conversational implicaturum. Fourth, the J. L. Austin requirement, this
or that requirement involved in the model is SURELY consistent with the no
doubt pre-theoretical antecedent explanation (argumentum) that one would be
prompted to give. Fifth, the second J. L. Austin requirement: towards this or
that requirement involved in the model the no-doubt pre-theoretical
(antecedent) explanation (argument) that one would be prompted to give is,
better still, a favourable pointer. Grice’s oversuse of ‘model’ is due to Max
Black, who understands model theory as a branch of philosophical semantics that
deals with the connection between a language and its interpretations or
structures. Basic to it is the characterization of the conditions under which a
sentence is true in structure. It is confusing that the term ‘model’ itself is
used slightly differently: a model for a sentence is a structure for the
language of the sentence in which it is true. Model theory was originally
developed for explicitly constructed, formal languages, with the purpose of
studying foundational questions of mathematics, but was later applied to the
semantical analysis of empirical theories, a development initiated by the Dutch
philosopher Evert Beth, and of natural languages, as in Montague grammar. More
recently, in situation theory, we find a theory of semantics in which not the
concept of truth in a structure, but that of information carried by a statement
about a situation, is central. The term ‘model theory’ came into use in the 0s,
with the work on first-order model theory by Tarski, but some of the most
central results of the field date from before that time. The history of the
field is complicated by the fact that in the 0s and 0s, when the first
model-theoretic findings were obtained, the separation between first-order
logic and its extensions was not yet completed. Thus, in 5, there appeared an
article by Leopold Löwenheim, containing the first version of what is now
called the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem. Löwenheim proved that every satisfiable
sentence has a countable model, but he did not yet work in firstorder logic as
we now understand it. One of the first who did so was the Norwegian logician
Thoralf Skolem, who showed in 0 that a set of first-order sentences that has a
model, has a countable model, one form of the LöwenheimSkolem theorem. Skolem
argued that logic was first-order logic and that first-order logic was the
proper basis for metamathematical investigations, fully accepting the
relativity of set-theoretic notions in first-order logic. Within philosophy
this thesis is still dominant, but in the end it has not prevailed in
mathematical logic. In 0 Kurt Gödel solved an open problem of Hilbert-Ackermann
and proved a completeness theorem for first-order logic. This immediately led
to another important model-theoretic result, the compactness theorem: if every
finite subset of a set of sentences has a model then the set has a model. A
good source for information about the model theory of first-order logic, or
classical model theory, is still Model Theory by C. C. Chang and H. J. Keisler
3. When the separation between first-order logic and stronger logics had been
completed and the model theory of first-order logic had become a mature field,
logicians undertook in the late 0s the study of extended model theory, the
model theory of extensions of first-order logic: first of cardinality
quantifiers, later of infinitary languages and of fragments of second-order
logic. With so many examples of logics around
where sometimes classical theorems did generalize, sometimes not Per Lindström showed in 9 what sets
first-order logic apart from its extensions: it is the strongest logic that is
both compact and satisfies the LöwenheimSkolem theorem. This work has been the
beginning of a study of the relations between various properties logics may
possess, the so-called abstract model. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The postulate of
conversational co-operation,” Oxford. Modus
-- necessitas -- Necessitarianism: “An ugly word once used by Strawson in a
tutorial!”Grice. -- the doctrine that necessity is an objective feature of the
world. Natural language permits speakers to express modalities: a state of
affairs can be actual Paris’s being in France, merely possible chlorophyll’s
making things blue, or necessary 2 ! 2 % 4. Anti-necessitarians believe that
these distinctions are not grounded in the nature of the world. Some of them
claim that the distinctions are merely verbal. Others, e.g., Hume, believed
that psychological facts, like our expectations of future events, explain the
idea of necessity. Yet others contend that the modalities reflect epistemic
considerations; necessity reflects the highest level of an inquirer’s
commitment. Some necessitarians believe there are different modes of metaphysical
necessity, e.g., causal and logical necessity. Certain proponents of idealism
believe that each fact is necessarily connected with every other fact so that
the ultimate goal of scientific inquiry is the discovery of a completely
rigorous mathematical system of the world. -- modus -- necessitasnecessarium --
necessity, a modal property attributable to a whole proposition dictum just
when it is not possible that the proposition be false the proposition being de
dicto necessary. Narrowly construed, a proposition P is logically necessary
provided P satisfies certain syntactic conditions, namely, that P’s denial is
formally self-contradictory. More broadly, P is logically necessary just when P
satisfies certain semantic conditions, namely, that P’s denial is false, and P
true, in all possible worlds. These semantic conditions were first suggested by
Leibniz, refined by Vitters and Carnap, and fully developed as the possible
worlds semantics of Kripke, Hintikka, et al., in the 0s. Previously,
philosophers had to rely largely on intuition to determine the acceptability or
otherwise of formulas involving the necessity operator, A, and were at a loss
as to which of various axiomatic systems for modal logic, as developed in the
0s by C. I. Lewis, best captured the notion of logical necessity. There was
much debate, for instance, over the characteristic NN thesis of Lewis’s system
S4, namely, AP / A AP if P is necessary then it is necessarily necessary. But
given a Leibnizian account of the truth conditions for a statement of the form
Aa namely R1 that Aa is true provided a is true in all possible worlds, and R2
that Aa is false provided there is at least one possible world in which a is
false, a proof can be constructed by reductio ad absurdum. For suppose that AP
/ AAP is false in some arbitrarily chosen world W. Then its antecedent will be
true in W, and hence by R1 it follows a that P will be true in all possible
worlds. But equally its consequent will be false in W, and hence by R2 AP will
be false in at least one possible world, from which again by R2 it follows b
that P will be false in at least one possible world, thus contradicting a. A
similar proof can be constructed for the characteristic thesis of S5, namely,
-A-P / A-A-P if P is possibly true then it is necessarily possible. Necessity
is also attributable to a property F of an object O provided it is not possible
that there is no possible world in which O exists and lacks F F being de re necessary, internal or essential
to O. For instance, the non-repeatable haecceitist property of being identical
to O is de re necessary essential to O, and arguably the repeatable property of
being extended is de re necessary to all colored objects. nĕcesse (arch.
nĕcessum , I.v. infra: NECESVS, S. C. de Bacch. l. 4: necessus , Ter. Heaut. 2,
3, 119 Wagn. ad loc.; id. Eun. 5, 5, 28; Gell. 16, 8, 1; v. Lachm. ad Lucr. 6,
815), neutr. adj. (gen. necessis, Lucr. 6, 815 ex conj. Lachm.; cf. Munro ad
loc.; elsewhere only nom. and acc. sing., and with esse or habere) [perh. Sanscr.
naç, obtain; Gr. root ἐνεκ-; cf. ἀνάγκη; v. Georg Curtius Gr. Etym. 424]. I.
Form necesse. A. Unavoidable, inevitable, indispensable, necessary (class.;
cf.: opus, usus est) 1. With esse. a. With subject.-clause: “edocet quanto
detrimento...necesse sit constare victoriam,” Caes. B. G. 7, 19: “necesse est
eam, quae ... timere permultos,” Auct. Her. 4, 16, 23: emas, non quod opus est,
sed quod necesse est, Cato ap. Sen. Ep. 94, 28: “nihil fit, quod necesse non
fuerit,” Cic. Fat. 9, 17: “necesse est igitur legem haberi in rebus optimis,”
id. Leg. 2, 5, 12; id. Verr 2, 3, 29, § 70. — b. With dat. (of the person,
emphatic): nihil necesse est mihi de me ipso dicere, Cic. Sen. 9, 30: “de
homine enim dicitur, cui necesse est mori,” id. Fat. 9, 17.— c. With ut and
subj.: “eos necesse est ut petat,” Auct. Her. 4, 16, 23: “sed ita necesse
fuisse, cum Demosthenes dicturus esset, ut concursus ex totā Graeciā fierent,”
Cic. Brut. 84, 289; Sen. Ep. 78, 15: “hoc necesse est, ut, etc.,” Cic. de Or.
2, 29, 129; Sen. Q. N. 2, 14, 2: “neque necesse est, uti vos auferam,” Gell. 2,
29, 9: “necesse est semper, ut id ... per se significet,” Quint. 8, 6, 43.— d.
With subj. alone: “haec autem oratio ... aut nulla sit necesse est, aut omnium
irrisione ludatur,” Cic. de Or. 1, 12, 50: “istum condemnetis necesse est,”
Cic. Verr. 2, 2, 18, § 45: “vel concidat omne caelum necesse est,” id. Tusc. 1,
23, 54: “si necesse est aliquid ex se magni boni pariat,” Lact. 3, 12, 7.— 2.
With habere (class. only with inf.): “non habebimus necesse semper concludere,”
Cic. Part. Or. 13, 47: “eo minus habeo necesse scribere,” id. Att. 10, 1, 4:
“Oppio scripsi ne necesse habueris reddere,” id. ib. 16, 2, 5: “non verbum pro
verbo necesse habui reddere,” id. Opt. Gen. Or. 5, 14: “non necesse habeo omnia
pro meo jure agere,” Ter. Ad. 1, 1, 26; Quint. 11, 1, 74; Vulg. Matt. 14, 16:
necesse habere with abl. (= egere; “late Lat.): non necesse habent sani
medico,” Vulg. Marc. 2, 17.—In agreement with object of habere: “non habet rex
sponsalia necesse,” Vulg. 1 Reg. 18, 25.— B. Needful, requisite, indispensable,
necessary: “id quod tibi necesse minime fuit, facetus esse voluisti,” Cic.
Sull. 7, 22.— II. Form necessum (mostly ante-class.). A. With subject.-clause:
“foras necessum est, quicquid habeo, vendere,” Plaut. Stich. 1, 3, 66: quod sit
necessum scire, Afran. ap. Charis. p. 186 P.: “nec tamen haec retineri hamata
necessumst,” Lucr. 2, 468: “externa corpus de parte necessumst tundier,” id. 4,
933: “necessum est vorsis gladiis depugnarier,” Plaut. Cas. 2, 5, 36: “necessum
est paucis respondere,” Liv. 34, 5: “num omne id aurum in ludos consumi
necessum esset?” id. 39, 5: “tonsorem capiti non est adhibere necessum,” Mart.
6, 57, 3.— B. With dat.: “dicas uxorem tibi necessum esse ducere,” Plaut. Mil.
4, 3, 25.— C. With subj.: “unde anima, atque animi constet natura necessum
est,” Lucr. 4, 120: “quare etiam nativa necessum est confiteare Haec eadem,”
id. 5, 377. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The may and the must,” “Ichthyological
necessity.” modus: Grice was
an expert on mode. There is one mode too many. If Grice found ‘senses’ obsolete
(“Sense are not to be multiplied beyond necessity”), he was always ready to
welcome a new modee. g. the quessertive --. or mode. ἔγκλισις , enclisis, mood of a verb, D.H.Comp.6, D.T.638.7, A.D. Synt.248.14,
etc.Many times, under ‘mode,’ Grice describes what others call ‘aspect.’ Surely
‘tense’ did not affect him much, except when it concerned “=”. But when it came
to modes, he included ‘aspect,’ so there’s the optative, the imperative, the
indicative, the informational, and then the future intentional and the future
indicative, and the subjunctive, and the way they interact with the praesens,
praeteritum and futurum, and wih the axis of what Aristotle called ‘teleios’
and ‘ateleios,’ indefinite and definite, or ‘perfectum, and ‘imperfectum, ‘but
better ‘definitum’ and ‘indefinitum.’ Grice
uses psi-asrisk, to be read asterisk-sub-psi. He is not concerned with
specficics. All the specifics the philosopher can take or rather ‘assume’ as
‘given.’ The category of mode translates ‘tropos,’ modus. Kant wrongly assumed
it was Modalitat, which irritated Grice so much that he echoed Kant as saying
‘manner’! Grice is a modista. He sometimes uses ‘modus,’ after Abbott. The
earliest record is of course “Meaning.” After elucidating what he calls
‘informative cases,’ he moves to ‘imperative’ ones. Grice agreed with Thomas
Urquhart that English needed a few more moods! Grice’s seven
modes.Thirteenthly, In lieu of six moods which other languages have at most,
this one injoyeth seven in its conjugable words. Ayer had said that
non-indicative utterances are hardly significant. Grice had been freely using
the very English not Latinate ‘mood’ until Moravcsik, of all people, corrects
him: What you mean ain’t a mood. I shall call it mode just to please
you, J. M. E. The sergeant is to muster the men at dawn is a perfect
imperative. They shall not pass is a perfect intentional. A version of this
essay was presented in a conference whose proceedings were published, except
for Grices essay, due to technical complications, viz. his idiosyncratic use of
idiosyncratic symbology! By mode Grice means indicative or imperative.
Following Davidson, Grice attaches probability to the indicative, via the
doxastic, and desirability to the indicative, via the
buletic-boulomaic. He also allows for mixed utterances. Probability
is qualified with a suboperator indicating a degree d; ditto for desirability,
degree d. In some of the drafts, Grice kept using mode until Moravsik suggested
to him that mode was a better choice, seeing that Grices modality had little to
do with what other authors were referring to as mood. Probability,
desirability, and modality, modality, desirability, and probability; modality,
probability, desirability. He would use mode operator. Modality is the
more correct term, for things like should, ought, and must, in that order. One
sense. The doxastic modals are correlated to probability. The buletic or
boulomaic modals are correlated to desirability. There is probability to a
degree d. But there is also desirability to a degree d. They
both combine in Grices attempt to show how Kants categorical imperative reduces
to the hypothetical or suppositional. Kant uses modality in a way that Grice
disfavours, preferring modus. Grice is aware of the use by Kant of
modality qua category in the reduction by Kant to four of the original ten
categories in Aristotle). The Jeffrey-style entitled Probability, desirability,
and mode operators finds Grice at his formal-dress best. It predates the Kant lectures
and it got into so much detail that Grice had to leave it at that. So abstract
it hurts. Going further than Davidson, Grice argues that structures expressing
probability and desirability are not merely analogous. They can both be
replaced by more complex structures containing a common element. Generalising
over attitudes using the symbol ψ, which he had used before, repr. WoW:v, Grice
proposes G ψ that p. Further, Grice uses i as a dummy for sub-divisions of
psychological attitudes. Grice uses Op supra i sub α, read: operation supra i
sub alpha, as Grice was fastidious enough to provide reading versions for
these, and where α is a dummy taking the place of either A or B, i. e.
Davidsons prima facie or desirably, and probably. In all this, Grice keeps
using the primitive !, where a more detailed symbolism would have it correspond
exactly to Freges composite turnstile (horizontal stroke of thought and
vertical stroke of assertoric force, Urteilstrich) that Grice of course also
uses, and for which it is proposed, then: !─p. There are generalising movements
here but also merely specificatory ones. α is not generalised. α is a
dummy to serve as a blanket for this or that specifications. On the other hand,
ψ is indeed generalised. As for i, is it generalising or specificatory? i is a
dummy for specifications, so it is not really generalising. But Grice
generalises over specifications. Grice wants to find buletic, boulomaic or
volitive as he prefers when he does not prefer the Greek root for both his
protreptic and exhibitive versions (operator supra exhibitive, autophoric, and
operator supra protreptic, or hetero-phoric). Note that Grice (WoW:110) uses
the asterisk * as a dummy for either assertoric, i.e., Freges turnstile, and
non-assertoric, the !─ the imperative turnstile, if you wish. The operators A
are not mode operators; they are such that they represent some degree (d) or
measure of acceptability or justification. Grice prefers acceptability because
it connects with accepting that which is a psychological, souly attitude, if a
general one. Thus, Grice wants to have It is desirable that p and It
is believable that p as understood, each, by the concatenation of three
elements. The first element is the A-type operator. The second element is the protreptic-type
operator. The third element is the phrastic, root, content, or proposition
itself. It is desirable that p and It is believable that p share the
utterer-oriented-type operator and the neustic or proposition. They only differ
at the protreptic-type operator (buletic/volitive/boulomaic or
judicative/doxastic). Grice uses + for concatenation, but it is best to use ,
just to echo who knows who. Grice speaks in that mimeo (which he delivers in
Texas, and is known as Grices Performadillo talk ‒ Armadillo + Performative) of
various things. Grice speaks, transparently enough, of acceptance: V-acceptance
and J-acceptance. V not for Victory but for volitional, and J for judicative.
The fact that both end with -acceptance would accept you to believe that both
are forms of acceptance. Grice irritatingly uses 1 to mean the doxastic, and 2
to mean the bulematic. At Princeton in Method, he defines the doxastic in terms
of the buletic and cares to do otherwise, i. e. define the buletic in terms of
the doxastic. So whenever he wrote buletic read doxastic, and vice versa. One
may omits this arithmetic when reporting on Grices use. Grice uses two further
numerals, though: 3 and 4. These, one may decipherone finds oneself as an
archeologist in Tutankamons burial ground, as this or that relexive attitude.
Thus, 3, i. e. ψ3, where we need the general operator ψ, not just
specificatory dummy, but the idea that we accept something simpliciter. ψ3
stands for the attitude of buletically accepting an or utterance: doxastically accepting
that p or doxastically accepting that ~p. Why we should be concerned with ~p is
something to consider. G wants to decide whether to believe p or not. I
find that very Griceian. Suppose I am told that there is a volcano in Iceland.
Why would I not want to believe it? It seems that one may want to decide
whether to believe p or not when p involves a tacit appeal to value. But, as
Grice notes, even when it does not involve value, Grice still needs trust and
volition to reign supreme. On the other hand, theres 4, as attached to an
attitude, ψ4. This stands for an attitude of buletically accepting an or
utterance: buletically accepting that p, or G buletically accepting that ~p, i.
e. G wants to decide whether to will, now that p or not. This indeed is crucial,
since, for Grice, morality, as with Kantotle, does cash in desire, the buletic.
Grice smokes. He wills to smoke. But does he will to will to smoke? Possibly
yes. Does he will to will to will to smoke? Regardless of what Grice wills, one
may claim this holds for a serious imperatives (not Thou shalt not reek, but
Thou shalt not kill, say) or for any p if you must (because if you know that p
causes cancer (p stands for a proposition involving cigarette) you should know
you are killing yourself. But then time also kills, so what gives? So I would
submit that, for Kant, the categoric imperative is one which allows for an
indefinite chain, not of chain-smokers, but of good-willers. If, for some p, we
find that at some stage, the P does not will that he wills that he wills that
he wills that, p can not be universalisable. This is proposed in an essay
referred to in The Philosophers Index but Marlboro Cigarettes took no notice.
One may go on to note Grices obsession on make believe. If I say, I utter
expression e because the utterer wants his addressee to believe that the
utterer believes that p, there is utterer and addresse, i. e. there are two
people here ‒ or any soul-endowed creature ‒ for Grices
squarrel means things to Grice. It even implicates. It miaows to me while I was
in bed. He utters miaow. He means that he is hungry, he means (via
implicaturum) that he wants a nut (as provided by me). On another occasion he
miaowes explicating, The door is closed, and implicating Open it, idiot. On the
other hand, an Andy-Capps cartoon read: When budgies get sarcastic Wild-life
programmes are repeating One may note that one can want some other person
to hold an attitude. Grice uses U or G1 for utterer and A or G2 for addressee.
These are merely roles. The important formalism is indeed G1 and G2. G1 is a
Griceish utterer-person; G2 is the other person, G1s addressee. Grice dislikes
a menage a trois, apparently, for he seldom symbolises a third party, G3. So, G
ψ-3-A that p is 1 just in case G ψ2(G ψ1 that p) or G ψ1 that ~p is 1. And here
the utterers addressee, G2 features: G1 ψ³ protreptically that p is 1 just
in case G buletically accepts ψ² (G buletically accepts ψ² (G doxastically
accepts ψ1 that p, or G doxastically accepts ψ1 that ~p))) is 1. Grice seems to
be happy with having reached four sets of operators, corresponding to four sets
of propositional attitudes, and for which Grice provides the paraphrases. The
first set is the doxastic proper. It is what Grice has as doxastic,and which
is, strictly, either indicative, of the utterers doxastic, exhibitive state, as
it were, or properly informative, if addressed to the addressee A, which is
different from U himself, for surely one rarely informs oneself. The second is
the buletic proper. What Grice dubs volitive, but sometimes he prefers the
Grecian root. This is again either self- or utterer-addressed, or
utterer-oriented, or auto-phoric, and it is intentional, or it is
other-addressed, or addressee-addressed, or addressee- oriented, or
hetero-phoric, and it is imperative, for surely one may not always say to
oneself, Dont smoke, idiot!. The third is the doxastic-interrogative, or
doxastic-erotetic. One may expand on ? here is minimal compared to the
vagaries of what I called the !─ (non-doxastic or buletic turnstile), and which
may be symbolised by ?─p, where ?─ stands for the erotetic turnstile. Geachs
and Althams erotetic somehow Grice ignores, as he more often uses the Latinate
interrogative. Lewis and Short have “interrŏgātĭo,” which they render as “a
questioning, inquiry, examination, interrogation;” “sententia per
interrogationem, Quint. 8, 5, 5; instare interrogation; testium; insidiosa;
litteris inclusæ; verbis obligatio fit ex interrogatione et responsione; as
rhet. fig., Quint. 9, 2, 15; 9, 3, 98. B. A syllogism: recte genus hoc
interrogationis ignavum ac iners nominatum est, Cic. Fat. 13; Sen. Ep. 87
med. Surely more people know what interrogative means what erotetic means,
he would not say ‒ but he would. This attitude comes again in two varieties:
self-addressed or utterer-oriented, reflective (Should I go?) or again,
addresee-addressed, or addressee-oriented, imperative, as in Should you go?,
with a strong hint that the utterer is expecting is addressee to make up his
mind in the proceeding, not just inform the utterer. Last but not least, there
is the fourth kind, the buletic-cum-erotetic. Here again, there is one varietiy
which is reflective, autophoric, as Grice prefers, utterer-addressed, or
utterer-oriented, or inquisitive (for which Ill think of a Greek pantomime), or
addressee-addressed, or addressee-oriented. Grice regrets that Greek (and
Latin, of which he had less ‒ cfr. Shakespeare who had none) fares better in
this respect the Oxonian that would please Austen, if not Austin, or Maucalay,
and certainly not Urquhart -- his language has twelve parts of speech: each
declinable in eleven cases, four numbers, eleven genders (including god,
goddess, man, woman, animal, etc.); and conjugable in eleven tenses, seven
moods, and four voices.These vocal mannerisms will result in the production of
some pretty barbarous English sentences; but we must remember that what I shall
be trying to do, in uttering such sentences, will be to represent supposedly
underlying structure; if that is ones aim, one can hardly expect that ones
speech-forms will be such as to excite the approval of, let us say, Jane Austen
or Lord Macaulay. Cf. the quessertive, or quessertion, possibly iterable,
that Grice cherished. But then you cant have everything. Where would you put it? Grice: The modal implicaturum. Grice
sees two different, though connected questions about mode. First,
there is the obvious demand for a characterisation, or partial
characterisation, of this or that mode as it emerges in this or that conversational
move, which is plausible to regard as modes primary habitat) both at the level
of the explicatum or the implicaturum, for surely an indicative conversational
move may be the vehicle of an imperatival implicaturum. A second, question is
how, and to what extent, the representation of mode (Hares neustic) which is
suitable for application to this or that conversational move may be
legitimately exported into philosophical psychology, or rather, may be grounded
on questions of philosophical psychology, matters of this or that psychological
state, stance, or attitude (notably desire and belief, and their
species). We need to consider the second question, the philosophico-
psychological question, since, if the general rationality operator is to read
as something like acceptability, as in U accepts, or A accepts, the appearance
of this or that mode within its scope of accepting is proper only if it may
properly occur within the scope of a generic psychological verb I accept that
. Lewis and Short have “accepto,” “v. freq. a. accipio,” which Short and
Lewis render as “to take, receive, accept,” “argentum,” Plaut. Ps. 2, 2, 32; so
Quint. 12, 7, 9; Curt. 4, 6, 5; Dig. 34, 1, 9: “jugum,” to submit to, Sil.
Ital. 7, 41. But in Plin. 36, 25, 64, the correct read. is coeptavere; v. Sillig.
a. h. l. The easiest way Grice finds to expound his ideas on the first question
is by reference to a schematic table or diagram (Some have complained that I
seldom use a board, but I will today. Grice at this point reiterates his
temporary contempt for the use/mention distinction, which which Strawson
is obsessed. Perhaps Grices contempt is due to Strawsons obsession. Grices
exposition would make the hair stand on end in the soul of a person especially
sensitive in this area. And Im talking to you, Sir Peter! (He is on the
second row). But Grices guess is that the only historical philosophical
mistake properly attributable to use/mention confusion is Russells argument
against Frege in On denoting, and that there is virtually always an acceptable
way of eliminating disregard of the use-mention distinction in a particular
case, though the substitutes are usually lengthy, obscure, and
tedious. Grice makes three initial assumptions. He avails himself of
two species of acceptance, Namesly, volitive acceptance and judicative
acceptance, which he, on occasion, calls respectively willing that p and
willing that p. These are to be thought of as technical or
semi-technical, theoretical or semi-theoretical, though each is a state which
approximates to what we vulgarly call thinking that p and wanting that p,
especially in the way in which we can speak of a beast such as a little
squarrel as thinking or wanting something ‒ a nut, poor darling
little thing. Grice here treats each will and judge (and accept) as a primitive.
The proper interpretation would be determined by the role of each in a
folk-psychological theory (or sequence of folk-psychological theories), of the
type the Wilde reader in mental philosophy favours at Oxford, designed to
account for the behaviours of members of the animal kingdom, at different
levels of psychological complexity (some classes of creatures being more
complex than others, of course). As Grice suggests in Us meaning,
sentence-meaning, and word-meaning, at least at the point at which (Schema Of
Procedure-Specifiers For Mood-Operators) in ones syntactico-semantical
theory of Pirotese or Griceish, one is introducing this or that mode (and
possibly earlier), the proper form to use is a specifier for this or that
resultant procedure. Such a specifier is of the general form, For the
utterer U to utter x if C, where the blank is replaced by the appropriate
condition. Since in the preceding scheme x represents an utterance or
expression, and not a sentence or open sentence, there is no guarantee that
this or that actual sentence in Pirotese or Griceish contains a perspicuous and
unambiguous modal representation. A sentence may correspond to more than
one modal structure. The sentence is structurally ambiguous
(multiplex in meaning ‒ under the proviso that senses are not to be
multiplied beyond necessity) and will have more than one reading, or parsing,
as every schoolboy at Clifton knows when translating viva voce from Greek or
Latin, as the case might be. The general form of a procedure-specifier for a
modal operator involves a main clause and an antecedent clause, which follows
if. In the schematic representation of the main clause, U represents an
utterer, A his addressee, p the radix or neustic; and Opi represents that
operator whose number is i (1, 2, 3, or 4), e.g g., Op3A represents
Operator 3A, which, since ?⊢ appears in the Operator column for 3A)
would be ?A ⊢ p. This
reminds one of Grandys quessertions, for he did think they were iterable
(possibly)). The antecedent clause consists of a sequence whose elements
are a preamble, as it were, or preface, or prefix, a supplement to a
differential (which is present only in a B-type, or addressee-oriented case), a
differential, and a radix. The preamble, which is always present, is invariant,
and reads: The U U wills (that) A A judges (that) U (For surely meaning is a species of intending
is a species of willing that, alla Prichard, Whites professor,
Corpus). The supplement, if present, is also invariant. And the idea
behind its varying presence or absence is connected, in the first instance,
with the volitive mode. The difference between an ordinary expression of
intention ‒ such as I shall not fail, or They shall not
pass ‒ and an ordinary imperative (Like Be a little kinder to
him) is accommodated by treating each as a sub-mode of the volitive mode,
relates to willing that p) In the intentional case (I shall not fail), the
utterer U is concerned to reveal to his addressee A that he (the utterer U)
wills that p. In the imperative case (They shall not pass), the utterer U is
concerned to reveal to his addressee A that the utterer U wills that the
addresee A will that p. In each case, of course, it is to be
presumed that willing that p will have its standard outcome, viz., the actualization,
or realisation, or direction of fit, of the radix (from expression to world,
downwards). There is a corresponding distinction between two uses of
an indicative. The utterer U may be declaring or affirming that p, in
an exhibitive way, with the primary intention to get his addressee A to judge
that the utterer judges that p. Or the U is telling (in a protreptic way)
ones addressee that p, that is to say, hoping to get his addressee to
judge that p. In the case of an indicative, unlike that of a volitive, there is
no explicit pair of devices which would ordinarily be thought of as sub-mode
marker. The recognition of the sub-mode is implicated, and comes from
context, from the vocative use of the Names of the addressee, from the presence
of a speech-act verb, or from a sentence-adverbial phrase (like for your
information, so that you know, etc.). But Grice has already, in his
initial assumptions, allowed for such a situation. The
exhibitive-protreptic distinction or autophoric-heterophoric distinction, seems
to Grice to be also discernible in the interrogative mode (?).
Each differentials is associated with, and serve to distinguish, each of
the two basic modes (volitive or judicative) and, apart from one detail in the
case of the interrogative mode, is invariant between autophoric-exhibitive) and
heterophoric-protreptic sub-modes of any of the two basic modes. They are
merely unsupplemented or supplemented, the former for an exhibitive sub-mode
and the latter for a protreptic sub-mode. The radix needs (one hopes) no
further explanation, except that it might be useful to bear in mind that Grice
does not stipulated that the radix for an intentional (buletic exhibitive
utterer-based) incorporate a reference to the utterer, or be in the first
person, nor that the radix for an imperative (buletic protreptic
addressee-based) incorporate a reference of the addresee, and be in the second
person. They shall not pass is a legitimate intentional, as is You shall
not get away with it; and The sergeant is to muster the men at dawn, as uttered
said by the captain to the lieutenant) is a perfectly good
imperative. Grice gives in full the two specifiers derived from the
schema. U to utter to A autophoric-exhibitive ⊢ p if U wills that A judges that U
judges p. Again, U to utter to A ! heterophoric-protreptic p if U wills that A
A judges that U wills that A wills that p. Since, of the states denoted by
each differential, only willing that p and judging that p are strictly cases of
accepting that p, and Grices ultimate purpose of his introducing this
characterization of mode is to reach a general account of expressions which are
to be conjoined, according to his proposal, with an acceptability operator, the
first two numbered rows of the figure are (at most) what he has a direct use for. But
since it is of some importance to Grice that his treatment of mode should
be (and should be thought to be) on the right lines, he adds a partial account
of the interrogative mode. There are two varieties of interrogatives, a
yes/no interrogatives (e. g. Is his face clean? Is the king of France bald? Is
virtue a fire-shovel?) and x-interrogatives, on which Grice qua philosopher was
particularly interested, v. his The that and the why. (Who killed Cock
Robin?, Where has my beloved gone?, How did he fix it?). The specifiers
derivable from the schema provide only for yes/no interrogatives, though the
figure could be quite easily amended so as to yield a restricted but very large
class of x-interrogatives. Grice indicates how this could be done. The
distinction between a buletic and a doxastic interrogative corresponds with the
difference between a case in which the utterer U indicates that he is, in one
way or another, concerned to obtain information (Is he at home?), and a case in
which the utterer U indicates that he is concerned to settle a problem about
what he is to do ‒ Am I to leave the door open?, Shall I go on reading? or,
with an heterophoric Subjects, Is the prisoner to be released? This difference
is fairly well represented in grammar, and much better represented in the
grammars of some other languages. The
hetero-phoric-cum-protreptic/auto-phoric-cum- exhibitive difference may
not marked at all in this or that grammar, but it should be marked in Pirotese.
This or that sub-mode is, however, often quite easily detectable. There is
usually a recognizable difference between a case in which the utterer A says,
musingly or reflectively, Is he to be trusted? ‒ a case in which the
utterer might say that he is just wondering ‒ and a case in which he
utters a token of the same sentence as an enquiry. Similarly, one can usually
tell whether an utterer A who utters Shall I accept the invitation? is
just trying to make up his mind, or is trying to get advice or instruction from
his addressee. The employment of the variable α needs to be
explained. Grice borrows a little from an obscure branch of logic, once
(but maybe no longer) practised, called, Grice thinks, proto-thetic ‒ Why?
Because it deals with this or that first principle or axiom, or thesis), the main
rite in which is to quantify over, or through, this or that connective. α is to
have as its two substituents positively and negatively, which may modify either
will or judge, negatively willing or negatively judging that p is judging or
willing that ~p. The quantifier (∃1α) . . . has to be treated
substitutionally. If, for example, I ask someone whether John killed Cock
Robin (protreptic case), I do not want the addressee merely to will that I have
a particular logical quality in mind which I believe to apply. I want the
addressee to have one of the Qualities in mind which he wants me to believe to
apply. To meet this demand, supplementation must drag back the
quantifier. To extend the schema so as to provide specifiers for a single
x-interrogative (i. e., a question like What did the butler see? rather than a
question like Who went where with whom at 4 oclock yesterday afternoon?),
we need just a little extra apparatus. We need to be able to superscribe a
W in each interrogative operator e.g., together with the proviso that a radix
which follows a superscribed operator must be an open radix, which contains one
or more occurrences of just one free variable. And we need a chameleon
variable λ, to occur only in this or that quantifier. (∃λ).Fx is to be regarded as a way of
writing (∃x)Fx. (∃λ)Fy is a way of writing (∃y)Fy. To provide a specifier for a
x-superscribed operator, we simply delete the appearances of α in the specifier
for the corresponding un-superscribed operator, inserting instead the
quantifier (∃1λ) () at the
position previously occupied by (∃1α) (). E.g. the specifiers for Who
killed Cock Robin?, used as an enquiry, would be: U to utter to A killed Cock Robin if U wills A to judge U to
will that (∃1λ) (A should
will that U judges (x killed Cock Robin)); in which (∃1λ) takes on the shape (∃1x) since x is the free variable within
its scope. Grice compares his buletic-doxastic distinction to prohairesis/doxa
distinction by Aristotle in Ethica Nichomachea. Perhaps his simplest
formalisation is via subscripts: I will-b but will-d not. Refs.: The main
references are given above under ‘desirability.’ The most systematic treatment
is the excursus in “Aspects,” Clarendon. BANC. modus. “The
distinction between Judicative and Volitive Interrogatives corresponds with the
difference between cases in which a questioner is indicated as being, in one
way or another, concerned to obtain information ("Is he at home?"),
and cases in which the questioner is indicated as being concerned to settle a problem
about what he is to do ("Am I to leave the door open?", "Is the
prisoner to be released?", "Shall I go on reading?"). This
difference is better represented in Grecian and Roman.”The Greek word was ‘egklisis,’ which Priscian translates as
‘modus’ and defines as ‘inclinatio anima, affectionis demonstrans.’ The Greeks
recognised five: horistike, indicativus, pronuntiativus, finitus, or
definitivus, prostastike, imperativus, euktike, optativus, hypotaktike
(subjunctivus, or conjunnctivus, but also volitivus, hortativus, deliberativus,
iussivus, prohibitivus anticipativus ) and aparemphatos infinitivus or
infinitus. Modus --
odus optativus. optative enclisis (gre:
ευκτική έγκλιση, euktike enclisis, hence it may be seen as a modus optatīvus.
Something that fascinated Grice. The way an ‘action’ is modalised in the way
one describes it. He had learned the basics for Greek and Latin at Oxford, and
he was exhilarated to be able to teach now on the subtleties of the English
system of ‘aspect.’ To ‘opt’ is to choose. So ‘optativus’ is the deliberative
mode. Grice proved the freedom of the will with a “grammatical argument.”
‘Given that the Greeks and the Romans had an optative mode, there is free
will.” Romans, having no special verbal forms recognized as Optative, had no need
of the designation modus optativus. Yet they sometimes used it, ad
imitationem. Modus -- modality: Grice: “Modality
is the manner in which a proposition (or statement) describes or applies to its
subject matter. Derivatively,’ modality’ refers to characteristics of entities
or states of affairs described by this or that modal proposition. Modalities
are classified as follows. An assertoric proposition is the expression of a
mere fact. Alethic modality includes necessity and possibility. The latter two sometimes
are referred to respectively as the apodeictic modality and the problematic
modalityvide Grice’s category of conversational modewhich covers three
categories under what Kant calls the ‘Funktion’ of Modethe assertoric, the
apodeictic and the problematic). Grice takes ‘must’ as basic and defines ‘may’
in terms of ‘must.’ Causal modality includes causal necessity or empirical
necessity and causal possibility or empirical possibility. The deontic modality
includes obligation and permittedness. Of course this hardly means that ‘must’
is polysemous. It is ‘aequi-vocal’ at most. There is epistemic modality or
modalities such as knowing that and doxastic modality (what Grice calls
‘credibility,’ as opposed to ‘desirability’) or modalities ones such as believing
that. There is desiderative modality such as ‘willing that’ (what Grice calls
‘desirability’ as prior to ‘credibility.’) Following medieval philosophers, a
proposition can be distinguished on the basis of whether the modality is
introduced via adverbial modification of the “copula” or verb (“sensus
divisus”)as in Grice’s “Fido is shaggy” versus “Fido may be shaggy”(in Roman,
“Fidus est fidelis” versus “Fidus sit fidelis”Grice: “Not to be confused with
“Fido, sit!” ) or via a modal operator that modifies the proposition (“sensus
compositus”as preferred by Strawson: “It is the case that,” “It is not the case
that,” “It must be the case that” and “It may be the case that”). Grice
actually calls ‘adverbial modifier’ the external version. The internal version
he just calls, as everybody at Clifton does, ‘conjugation’ (“We are not
Tarzan!”). Grice: "In Gricese, in the instance in which the
indicative occurs after "acsian" here is no doubt in the minds of
those who ask the question, the content of the dependent clause being by them
regarded as a fact.
Mk. X. 2. Da genealsehton him pharisei and hine axodon hwseber alyfS senegum men his wif forlsetan. Interrogabant eum: INTERROGABANT EUM: SI LICET Si licet. L. XII. 36. beo gelice pam mannum be hyra hlaforde abidafr hwsenne he sy fram
gyftum gecyrred.
L. XXII. 24. hi flitun betwux him hwylc hyra wsere
yldest. J. XIX. 24.
uton hleotan hwylces
ures heo sy. Mk. XV. 24. hi hlotu wurpon, hwset
gehwa name.
mittentes sortem
super eis, quis quid tolleret. MITTENTES SORTEM SVPER EIS, QVIS QVID TOLLERET. M. XXVII. 49. Uton geseon hwseber Helias cume and wylle
hyne alysan. Mk. V. 14. hi ut eodon bset hi
gesawon hwset par gedon wsere. L. XIX. 3.he wolde geseon hwylc se hselend
wsere. Mk. IX. 34.hi on wege smeadon hwylc hyra yldost wsere. Mk. IX.
10. L. XI, 38. XXII. 23. L. XIV. 28. Hwylc eower wyle timbrian anne stypel, hu ne sytt he serest and
teleS pa andfengas be him behefe synt, hwseder he hsebbe hine to
full-fremmenne?
L. I. 29. ba wearS heo on his sprsece gedrefed, and pohte
hwset seo greting wsere.
L. Ill, 15. XIV.
31. L. IX. 46.
bset gepanc eode on hig,
hwylc hyra yldest wsere. Mk. XV. 47. Da com Maria Magdalene and Josepes Maria, and beheoldon hwar he
geled wsere. aspiciebant. ubi poneretur ASPICIEBANT. VBI
PONERETVR.
(Looked around, in order
to discover). The notion of purpose is sometimes involved, the indirect
question having something of the force of a final clause: Mk.
XIII. 11. ne foresmeage ge hwset ge specan. L. XXI. 14. *) Direct rather than indirect question. L. XII. 22. ne beo ge ymbehydige eowre
sawle hwset ge etan, ne eowrum lichaman hwset ge scrydun. M. VI, 25. L. XII. 11. ne beo ge embebencynde hu oSSe hwset ge specon
oSSe andswarian. M. X. 19. ne bence ge hu oSSe hwset ge
sprecun. L. XII. 29.
Nelle ge secean hwset ge
eton oSSe drincon.
J. XIX. 12. and sySSan sohte Pilatus hu he hyne forlete. quaerebat Pilatus dimittere eum. QVAEREBAT PILATVS DIMITTERE EVM 2. When the content of the dependent clause is regarded as an actual
fact, which is the case when the leading verb expresses the act of learning,
perceiving, etc., the indicative is used. M. VI. 28. BesceawiaS secyres Man
hu hig weaxaO. M. XXI. 16.gehyrst bu hwset pas cwseoab? M. XXVII. 13. Ne gehyrst Jm hu fela sagena hig ongen be
secgeaS?
L. XVIII. 6. M. IX.
13.leornigeab hwset is, ic wylle mildheortnesse
nses onssegdnesse. M. XXI. 20. loca nu hu hrsedlice bset fic-treow forscranc. Mk. XV. 4. loca hu mycelum hi be wregea§. M. XII. 4.Ne
rsedde ge hwset David dyde hu he ineode on Godes hus, and set ba offring-hlafas? L. VI, 4. Mk. XII. 26.
Be bam deadum ■ bset hi
arison, ne rsedde ge on Moyses bec hu God to him cwseb? Mk. I, 26. Mk. V. 16. hi rehton him ba Se hit
gesawon hu hit gedon wses. L. VIII. 36. Da cyddon him ba Se gesawon hu he wses hal
geworden. L. XXIII. 55.hig gesawon ba byrgene and hu his lichama
aled wses. J. XX. 14.heo geseah hwar se hselend stod. Vidit Jesum stantem. *) VIDIT IESVM STANTEM. Not the endeavour to learn, perceive, which
would require the SUBJUNCTIVE. L. XXIV. 6.
gebencao hu he spsec wiS
eow. recordamini.
Mk. VIII. 19.
3.After verbs of knowing both the indicative and subjunctive are used, usually
the indicative. See general statement before § 2. a)
Indicative:*) L. XIII. 27. Ne cann ic hwanon ge
synt. Mk. XIV, 68. M. VI. 8. eower fseder wat hwset eow bearf
ys. M. XX. 22.
Gyt nyton hwset gyt
biddab. L. XIII. 25. nat ic hwanon ge
synt. J. IX. 21. we nyton humete he nu
gesyhb. quomodo autem nunc videat, nescimus. QVOMODO AVTEM NVNC, NESCIMVS. J. IX. 25. gif he synful is, bset ic nat. si peccator est, nescio. SI PECCATOR EST, NESCIO. I know not if he is a sinner. gif he synful is, bset ic nat. "Gif he synful is, ᚦaet ic nat." In Oxonian:
"If he sinful is,
that I know not. M. XXVI. 70. Mk. IX. 6. X, 28. XIII, 33, 35. L. IX,
33. XX, 7. XXII, 60. L. XXIII. 34. J. II. 9. III. 8. V. 13. VII.
27, 27, 28. VIII. 14, 14. J. IX. 29. 30. X. 6. XIII. 18. XIV. 5. XV.
15. b)
Indicative and
subjunctive: L. X. 22. nan man nat hwylc IS se
sunu buton se fseder, ne hwylc SI Se fseder buton se sunu. -- In Latin, both times have subjunctive third person singular,
"sit".)
c)
Subjunctive. a. In the protasis of a conditional sentence: J.
VII. 51.Cwyst bu demS ure se senine man buton hyne man ser gehyre and wite
hwset he do? J. XI. 57. pa pharisei hsefdon beboden gif hwa wiste
hwaer he wsere paet he hyt cydde bset hig mihton hine niman. Translating
the Latin subjunctive in 21 instances, the indic. in 9. As a rule, the mood (or mode, as Grice prefers)
of the Latin (or Roman, as Grice prefers) verb does not determine the O. E. (or
A. S., as Grice prefers) usage. In Anglo-Saxon, Oxonian,
and Gricese, "si" seems to be no more than a literal (mimetic)
rendering of Roman "sit," the correct third person singular
subjunctive.
Ms. A. reads
"ys" with'-sy" above. The Lind. gloss reads
"is". M. XXIV. 43. WitaS bset gyf se hiredes ealdor wiste on hwylcere tide se beof
towerd waere witodlice he wolde wacigean. si sciret paterfamilias qua hora fur
venturus esset vigilaret,
(Cf. J. IV, 10. Gif bu wistest — hwaet se is etc. Si scirest quis est. SI SCIREST QVIS EST. /J. In the apodosis of a conditional sentence: J. VII.
17. gyf hwa wyle his willan don he gecwemo (sic. A.B.C. gecnsewS) be
bsere lare hwseber heo si of Gode hwseber be ic he me sylfum spece. L.
VII. 39.
Gyf be man witega wsere
witodlice he wiste hwset and hwylc bis wif wsere be his sethrinb bset heo
synful is.
sciret utique quae et
qualis est mulier. SCIRET VTIQVE QVAE ET QVALIS EST MULIER. y. After a hortatory subjunctive. M. VI.
3. Nyte bin wynstre hwset do bin swybre. 4. After verbs of
saying and declaring. a) Here the indicative is used when the
dependent clause contains a statement rather than a question. L. VIII.
39. cyS hu mycel be God gedon h3efS. L. VIII. 47.Da bset wif
geseah bset hit him nses dyrne heo com forht and astrehte hig to his fotum and
geswutulude beforan eallum folce for hwylcum binge heo hit sethran and hu heo
wearS sona hal. ob quam causam tetigerit eum, indicavit; et quemadmodum
confestim SANATA SIT. Further examples of the indicative are. L. XX.
2.*) Sege us on hwylcum anwalde wyrcst bu Sas
bing oSSe hwset ys se Se be be anwald sealde. L. VI. 47. iElc bara be to me cymb and mine sprseca
gehyi*S and pa deb, ic him setywe hwam he gelic is. b) When the subordinate clause refers to the future
both the indicative and subjunctive are used: *) Direct
question, as the order of the words shows. Mk. XIII. 4. Sege us hwsenne bas bing gewurdon (A. geweorSon,
H. gewurSen, R. gewurdon) and hwylc tacen bid
bsenne ealle bas Sing onginnaS beon geendud. (Transition to direct
question.) Dic nobis, quando ista fient? DIC NOBIS, QVANDO ISTA FIENT? et quod signum erit? ET QVOD SIGNVM
ERIT? M. XXIV. 3. Sege us hwsenne bas Sing
gewurbun and hwile tacn si bines to-cymes. J. XVIII. 32. he geswutelode hwylcon deaSe lie swulte. qua
morte ESSET moriturus. c) When the question presents a distinct alternative, so that the
idea of doubt and uncertainty is prominent, the subjunctive in Gricese,
Oxonian, and Anglo-Saxon, qua conjugated version, is used: M. XXVI.
63. Ic halsige be Surh bone lyfiendan God, b*t Su secge us gyf \>u sy
Crist Godes sunu. L. XXII. 67. J. X. 24. d) The following is
hortatory as well as declarative: L. XII. 5. Ic eow setywe
hwsene ge ondredon. Ostendam autem vobis, quem TIMEATIS. 5. In
three indirect questions which in the original are direct, the subjunctive is
used: M. XXIV. 45.Wens (sic. A. H. & R. wenst) \>u
hwa sy getrywe and gleaw BEOW? Quis, putas, EST fidelis
servus? QVIS, PVTAS, EST FIDELIS SERVS. M. XXVI. 25. Cwyst
bu lareow hwseSer ic hyt si? Numquid ego sum? NVMQVID EGO SVM, J. VII. 26. CweSe we hwseber ba ealdras
ongyton set bis IS Crist?
Numquid vere cognoverunt
principes, quia hie EST Christus? § 11. RELATIVE
CLAUSES. Except in the relations discussed in the following the indicative
is used in relative clauses. Grice:
"The verb 'to be' is actually composed of three different stems -- not
only in Aristotle, but in Gricese." CONIUGATVM, persona, s-stem
(cognate with Roman "sit"), b-stem, w-stem (cognate with Roman,
"ero") MODVS INFINITVUM, the verb "sīn,” the verb
"bion,” the verb "wesan.” MODVS INDICATIVM PRAESENS prima singularis:
"ik" -- Oxonian "I" "em" Oxonian, "am."
Bium wisu secunda singularis: "thū" -- Oxonian: "thou"
"art" Oxonian "art" bis(t) wisis tertia singularis:
"hē" Oxonian, 'he' "ist" (Cognate with Roman
"est") Oxonian 'is' *bid wis(id) prima, secunda, tertia, pluralis
"sindun" *biod wesad MODVS INDCATIVVM PRAETERITVM prima singularis
"was" Oxonian: "was." seconda singularis
""wāri" Oxonian "were" tertia singularis
"was" Oxonian "was" prima, secunda, tertia, pluralis
"wārun" Oxonian "were" MODVS SVBIVCTIVVM PRAESENS
prima, secunda, tertia, singularis "sīe" (Lost in Oxonian after
Occam) "wese" (cognate with "was", and Roman,
"erat") prima, secunda, tertia, pluralis "sīen" wesen
MODVS SVBIVNCTIVVM PRAETERITUM prima, secunda, tertia, singularis
wāri prima, secunda, tertia, pluralis wārin MODVS IMPERATIVUM singularis
"wis," "wes" (Cognate with "was" and Roman
"erat") pluralis wesad MODVS PARTICIPIVM PRAESENT wesandi (cognate
with Cicero's "essens" and "essentia" MODVS PARTICIPIVM
PRAETERITVM "giwesan" The present-tense forms of 'be'
with the w-stem, "wesan" are almost never used.
Therefore, wesan is used as IMPERATIVE, in the past tense, and in the
participium prasesens versions of "sīn" -- Grice:
"I rue the day when the Bosworth and Toller left Austin!" --
"Now the OED, is not supposed to include Anglo-Saxon forms!") and
does not have a separate meaning. The b-stem is only met in the present
indicative of wesan, and only for the first and second persons in the
singular. So we see that if Roman had the 'est-sit"
distinction, the Oxonians had "The 'ist'/"sīe"/"wese"
tryad). Grice: "To simplify the Oxonian forms and make
them correlative to Roman, I shall reduce the Oxonian triad,
'ist'/'sīe'/"wese" to the division actually cognate with Roman:
'ist'/'sīe." And so, I shall speak of the
'ist'/'sīe" distinction, or the 'est-sit' distinction
interchangeably." Today many deny the
distinction or confine attention just to modal operators. Modal operators in
non-assertoric propositions are said to produce referential opacity or oblique
contexts in which truth is not preserved under substitution of extensionally
equivalent expressions. Modal and deontic logics provide formal analyses of
various modalities. Intensional logics investigate the logic of oblique
contexts. Modal logicians have produced possible worlds semantics
interpretations wherein propositions MP with modal operator M are true provided
P is true in all suitable (e.g., logically possible, causally possible, morally
permissible, rationally acceptable) possible worlds. Modal realism grants
ontological status to possible worlds other than the actual world or otherwise
commits to objective modalities in nature or reality. modus: the study of the
logic of the operators ‘it is possible that’ (or, as Grice prefers, “it may be
that”) and ‘it is necessary that’ (or as Grice prefers, “It must be that…”).
For some reason, Grice used ‘mode’ at Oxfordbut ‘manner’ in the New World! The
sad thing is that when he came back to the Old World, to the puzzlmenet of
Old-Worlders, he kept using ‘manner.’ So, everytime we see Grice using
‘manner,’ we need to translate to either the traditional Oxonian ‘modus,’ or
the Gricese ‘mode.’ These operators Grice symbolizes by a diamond and a square
respectively. and each can be defined in terms of the other. □p (necessarily p) is equivalent to ¬◇¬p ("not possible that not-p") ◇p (possibly p) is equivalent to ¬□¬p ("not necessarily
not-p").
To say that Fido may be shaggy is to say that it is not necessarily false. Thus
possP could be regarded as an abbreviation of -Nec-p Equally, to say that Fido
*must* be shaggy is to deny that its negation is possible. Thus Af could be
regarded as an abbreviation of -B-f. Grice prefers to take ‘poss” as primitive
(“for surely, it may rain before it must pour!”). Grice’s ystem G of modality
is obtained by introducing Poss. and Nec. If system, as Grice’s is, is
classical/intuitionist/minimal, so is the corresponding modal logic. Grice
surely concentrates on the classical case (“Dummett is overconcentraating on
the intuitionist, and nobody at Oxford was, is, or will be minimal!”). As with any kind of logic, there are three
components to a system of modal logic: a syntactics, which determines the
system or calculus + and the notion of well-formed formula (wff). Second, a
semantics, which determines the consequence relation X on +-wffs. Third, a
pragmatics or sub-system of inference, which determines the deductive
consequence relation Y on +-wffs. The syntactis of the modal operators is the
same in every system. Briefly, the modal operator is a one-place or unary
‘connective,’ or operator, strictly, since it does not connect two atoms into a
molecule, like negation. There are many different systems of modal logic, some
of which can be generated by different ways of setting up the semantics. Each
of the familiar ways of doing this can be associated with a sound and complete
system of inference. Alternatively, a system of inference can be laid down
first and we can search for a semantics for it relative to which it is sound
and complete. Grice gives primacy to the syntactic viewpoint. Semantic
consequence is defined in modal logic in the usual classical way: a set of
sentences 9 yields a sentence s, 9 X s, iff if no “interpretation” (to use
Grice’s jargon in “Vacuous Names”) I makes all members of 9 true and s false.
The question is how to extend the notion of “interpretation” to accommodate for
“may be shaggy”and “must be shaggy”. In classical sentential logic, an
interpretation is an assignment to each sentence letter of exactly one of the
two truth-values = and where n % m ! 1. So to determine relative possibility in
a model, we identify R with a collection of pairs of the form where each of u
and v is in W. If a pair is in R, v is possible relative to u, and if is not in
R, v is impossible relative to u. The relative possibility relation then enters
into the rules for the evaluating modal operator. We do not want to say, e. g.
that at the actual world, it is possible for Grice to originate from a
different sperm and egg, since the only worlds where this takes place are
impossible relative to the actual world. So we have the rule that B f is true
at a world u if f is true at some world v such that v is possible relative to
u. Similarly, Af is true at a world u if f is true at every world v which is
possible relative to u. R may have simple first-order properties such as reflexivity,
(Ex)Rxx, symmetry, (Ex)(Ey)(Rxy P Ryx), and transitivity, (Ex)(Ey)(Ez)((Rxy
& Ryz) P Rxz), and different modal systems can be obtained by imposing
different combinations of these on R (other systems can be obtained from
higher-order constraints). The least constrained system is the system Ghp, in
which no structural properties are put on R. In G-hp we have B (B & C) X B
B, since if B (B & C) holds at w* then (B & C) holds at some world w
possible relative to w*, and thus by the truth-function for &, B holds at w
as well, so B B holds at w*. Hence any interpretation that makes B (B & C)
true (% true at w*) also makes B B true. Since there are no restrictions on R
in G-hp, we can expect B (B & C) X B B in every system of modal logic generated
by constraining R. However, for G-hp we also have C Z B C. For suppose C holds
at w*. B C holds at w* only if there is some world possible relative to w*
where C holds. But there need be no such world. In particular, since R need not
be reflexive, w* itself need not be possible relative to w*. Concomitantly, in
any system for which we stipulate a reflexive R, we will have C X B C. The
simplest such system is known as T, which has the same semantics as K except
that R is stipulated to be reflexive in every interpretation. In other systems,
further or different constraints are put on R. For example, in the system B,
each interpretation must have an R that is reflexive and symmetric, and in the
system S4, each interpretation must have an R that is reflexive and transitive.
In B we have B C Z B B C, as can be shown by an interpretation with
nontransitive R, while in S4 we have B AC Z C, as can be shown by an
interpretation with non-symmetric R. Correspondingly, in S4, B C X B B C, and
in B, B AC X C. The system in which R is reflexive, transitive, and symmetric
is called S5, and in this system, R can be omitted. For if R has all three
properties, R is an equivalence relation, i.e., it partitions W into mutually
exclusive and jointly exhaustive equivalence classes. If Cu is the equivalence
class to which u belongs, then the truth-value of a formula at u is independent
of the truth-values of sentence letters at worlds not in Cu, so only the worlds
in Cw* are relevant to the truth-values of sentences in an S5 interpretation.
But within Cw* R is universal: every world is possible relative to every other.
Consequently, in an S5 interpretation, we need not specify a relative
possibility relation, and the evaluation rules for B and A need not mention
relative possibility; e.g., we can say that B f is true at a world u if there
is at least one world v at which f is true. Note that by the characteristics of
R, whenever 9 X s in K, T, B, or S4, then 9 X s in S5: the other systems are
contained in S5. K is contained in all the systems we have mentioned, while T
is contained in B and S4, neither of which is contained in the other.
Sentential modal logics give rise to quantified modal logics, of which
quantified S5 is the bestknown. Just as, in the sentential case, each world in
an interpretation is associated with a valuation of sentence letters as in
non-modal sentential logic, so in quantified modal logic, each world is
associated with a valuation of the sort familiar in non-modal first-order
logic. More specifically, in quantified S5, each world w is assigned a domain
Dwthe things that exist at wsuch that at least one Dw is non-empty, and each
atomic n-place predicate of the language is assigned an extension Extw of
n-tuples of objects that satisfy the predicate at w. So even restricting
ourselves to just the one first-order extension of a sentential system, S5,
various degrees of freedom are already evident. We discuss the following: (a)
variability of domains, (b) interpretation of quantifiers, and (c) predication.
(a) Should all worlds have the same domain or may the domains of different
worlds be different? The latter appears to be the more natural choice; e.g., if
neither of of Dw* and Du are subsets of the other, this represents the
intuitive idea that some things that exist might not have, and that there could
have been things that do not actually exist (though formulating this latter
claim requires adding an operator for ‘actually’ to the language). So we should
distinguish two versions of S5, one with constant domains, S5C, and the other
with variable domains, S5V. (b) Should the truth of (Dn)f at a world w require
that f is true at w of some object in Dw or merely of some object in D (D is
the domain of all possible objects, 4weWDw)? The former treatment is called the
actualist reading of the quantifiers, the latter, the possibilist reading. In
S5C there is no real choice, since for any w, D % Dw, but the issue is live in
S5V. (c) Should we require that for any n-place atomic predicate F, an n-tuple
of objects satisfies F at w only if every member of the n-tuple belongs to Dw,
i.e., should we require that atomic predicates be existence-entailing? If we
abbreviate (Dy) (y % x) by Ex (for ‘x exists’), then in S5C, A(Ex)AEx is
logically valid on the actualist reading of E (%-D-) and on the possibilist. On
the former, the formula says that at each world, anything that exists at that
world exists at every world, which is true; while on the latter, using the
definition of ‘Ex’, it says that at each world, anything that exists at some world
or other is such that at every world, it exists at some world or other, which
is also true; indeed, the formula stays valid in S5C with possibilist
quantifiers even if we make E a primitive logical constant, stipulated to be
true at every w of exactly the things that exist at w. But in S5V with
actualist quantifiers, A(Ex)AEx is invalid, as is (Ex)AExconsider an
interpretation where for some u, Du is a proper subset of Dw*. However, in S5V
with possibilist quantifiers, the status of the formula, if ‘Ex’ is defined,
depends on whether identity is existence-entailing. If it is
existenceentailing, then A(Ex)AEx is invalid, since an object in D satisfies
(Dy)(y % x) at w only if that object exists at w, while if identity is not
existence-entailing, the formula is valid. The interaction of the various
options is also evident in the evaluation of two well-known schemata: the
Barcan formula, B (Dx)fx P (Dx) B fx; and its converse, (Dx) B fx P B (Dx)fx.
In S5C with ‘Ex’ either defined or primitive, both schemata are valid, but in
S5V with actualist quantifiers, they both fail. For the latter case, if we
substitute -E for f in the converse Barcan formula we get a conditional whose
antecedent holds at w* if there is u with Du a proper subset of Dw*, but whose
consequent is logically false. The Barcan formula fails when there is a world u
with Du not a subset of Dw*, and the condition f is true of some non-actual
object at u and not of any actual object there. For then B (Dx)f holds at w*
while (Dx) B fx fails there. However, if we require atomic predicates to be
existence-entailing, then instances of the converse Barcan formula with f
atomic are valid. In S5V with possibilist quantifiers, all instances of both
schemata are valid, since the prefixes (Dx) B and B (Dx) correspond to (Dx)
(Dw) and (Dw) (Dx), which are equivalent (with actualist quantifiers, the
prefixes correspond to (Dx 1 Dw*), and (Dw) (Dx 1 Dw) which are non-equivalent
if Dw and Dw* need not be the same set). Finally in S5V with actualist
quantifiers, the standard quantifier introduction and elimination rules must be
adjusted. Suppose c is a name for an object that does not actually exist;
thenEc is true but (Dx)Ex is false. The quantifier rules must be those of free
logic: we require Ec & fc before we infer (Dv)fv and Ec P fc, as well as
the usual EI restrictions, before we infer (Ev)fv. Refs.: H. P. Grice:
“Modality: Desirability and Credibility;” H. P. Grice, “The may and the may
not;” H. P. Grice, “The Big Philosophical Mistake: ‘What is actual is not also
possible’.” modus: Grice: “In Roman,
‘modus’ may have been rendered as ‘way’, ‘fashion’but I will not, and use
‘modus’ as THEY did! ‘Modus’ is used in more than one ‘modus’ in philosophy. In
Ariskantian logic, ‘modus’ refers either to the arrangement of universal,
particular, affirmative, or negative propositions within a syllogism, only
certain of which are valid this is often tr., confusingly, as ‘modus’ in
English“the valid modes, such as Barbara and Celarent.” But then ‘modus’ may be
used to to the property a proposition has by virtue of which it is necessary or
contingent, possible or impossible, or ‘actual.’ In Oxonian scholastic
metaphysics, ‘modus’ is often used in a not altogether technical way to mean
that which characterizes a thing and distinguishes it from others. Micraelius,
in his best-selling “Lexicon philosophicum,” has it that “a mode does not
compose a thing, but distinguishes it and makes it determinate.” ‘Modus’ is
also used in the context of the modal distinction in the theory of distinctions
to designate the distinction that holds between a substance and its modes or
between two modes of a single substance. ‘Modus’ also appears in the technical
vocabulary of medieval speculative ‘grammar’ or ‘semantics’ (“speculative
semantics” makes more sense) -- in connection with the notions of the “modus
significandi,” “the modus intelligendi” (more or less the same thing), and the
“modus essendi.” The term ‘modus’ becomes especially important when Descartes
(vide Grice, “Descartes on clear and distinct perception”), Spinoza (vide S. N.
Hampshire, “Spinoza”), and Locke each take it up, giving it three somewhat
different special meanings within their respective systems. Descartes (vide
Grice, “Descartes on clear and distinct perception”) makes ‘modus’ a central
notion in his metaphysics in his Principia philosophiae. For Descartes, each
substantia is characterized by a principal attribute, ‘cogitatio’ for ‘anima’
and ‘extensio’ for ‘corpus’. Modes, then, are particular ways of being extended
or thinking, i.e., particular sizes, shapes, etc., or particular thoughts,
properties in the broad sense that individual things substances have. In this
way, ‘modus’ occupies the role in Descartes’s philosophy that ‘accident’ does
in Aristotelian philosophy. But for Descartes, each mode must be connected with
the principal attribute of a substance, a way of being extended or a way of
thinking, whereas for the Aristotelian, accidents may or may not be connected
with the essence of the substance in which they inhere. Like Descartes, Spinoza
recognizes three basic metaphysical terms, ‘substania,’ ‘attributum’, and
‘modus’. Recalling Descartes, Spinoza defines ‘modus’ as “the affections of a
substance, or that which is in another, and which is also conceived through
another” Ethics I. But for Spinoza, there is only one substance, which has all
possible attributes. This makes it somewhat difficult to determine exactly what
Spinoza means by ‘modus’, whether they are to be construed as being in some say
a “property” of God, the one infinite substance, or whether they are to be
construed more broadly as simply individual things that depend for their
existence on God, just as Cartesian modes depend on Cartesian substance.
Spinoza also introduces somewhat obscure distinctions between modus infinitus
and modus finitus, and between immediate and mediate infinite modes. Now, much
closer to Grice, Englishman and Oxonian Locke uses ‘mode’ in a way that
evidently derives from Descartes’s usage, but that also differs from it. For Locke,
a ‘modus’ is “such complex ideaas Pegasus the flying horse --, which however
compounded, contain not in them the supposition of subsisting by themselves,
but are considered as Dependences on, or Affections of Substances” Essay II. A
‘modus,’ for Locke, is thus an idea that represents to us the a ‘complex’
propertiy of a thing, sc. an idea derived from what Locke a ‘simple’ idea that
come to us from experience. Locke distinguishes between a ‘modus simplex,’ like
number, space, and infinity, which are supposed to be constructed by
compounding the SAME simple idea many times, and ‘modus complexum,’ or ‘modus
mixtum,’ a mode like obligation or theft, which is supposed to be compounded of
at least two simple ideas of a different sort.
Refs.: Grice applies Locke’s idea of the modus mixtum in his ‘labour’
against Empiricism, cf. H. P. Grice, “I may care a hoot what the dictionary
says, but it is not the case that I care a hoot what Micraelius’s “Lexicon
philosophicum” says.” Modusmodulus --
Grice against a pragmatic or rational module: from Latin ‘modulus,’ ‘little
mode.’ the commitment to functionally
independent and specialized cognitive system in psychological organizatio, or,
more generally, in the organization of any complex system. A ‘modulus’ entails
that behavior is the product of components with subordinate functions, that
these functions are realized in discrete physical systems, and that the
subsystems are minimally interactive. Organization in terms of a modulus varies
from simple decomposability to what Herbert Simon calls near decomposability.
In the former, component systems are independent, operating according to
intrinsically determined principles; system behavior is an additive or
aggregative function of these independent contributions. In the latter, the
short-run behavior of components is independent of the behavior of other
components; the system behavior is a relatively simple function of component
contributions. Gall defends a modular organization for the mind/brain, holding
that the cerebral hemispheres consist of a variety of organs, or centers, each
subserving specific intellectual and moral functions. This picture of the brain
as a collection of relatively independent organs contrasts sharply with the
traditional view that intellectual activity involves the exercise of a general
unitary ‘faculty’ in a variety of this or that‘domain’, where a ‘domain’ is not
a ‘modulus’ -- a view that was common to Descartes and Hume as well as Gall’s
major opponents such as Flourens. By the middle of the nineteenth century,
Bouillaud and Broca (a French doctor, of Occitan ancestrybrooch, brocathorn --)
defended the view that language is controlled by localized structures in the
left hemisphere and is relatively independent of other cognitive activities. It
was later discovered by Wernicke that there are at least two centers for the
control of language, one more posterior and one more anterior. On these views,
there are discrete physical structures responsible for communication, which are
largely independent of one another and of structures responsible for other
psychological functions. This is therefore a modular organization. This view of
the neurophysiological organization of communication continues to have
advocates, though the precise characterization of the functions these two
centers serve is controversial. Many more recent views have tended to limit
modularity to more peripheral functions such as vision, hearing, and motor
control and speech, but have excluded “what I am interested in, viz. so-called higher
cognitive processes.”H. P. Grice, “The power structure of the soul.” Modus -- modus ponendo ponens: 1 the argument
form ‘If A then B; A; therefore, B’, and arguments of this form compare fallacy
of affirming the consequent; 2 the rule of inference that permits one to infer
the consequent of a conditional from that conditional and its antecedent. This
is also known as the rule of /-elimination or rule of /- detachment. modus tollendo tollens: 1 the argument form
‘If A then B; not-B; therefore, not-A’, and arguments of this form compare
fallacy of denying the antecedent; 2 the rule of inference that permits one to
infer the negation of the antecedent of a conditional from that conditional and
the negation of its consequent.
mondolfo: Grice: “Mondolfo is one of the few
who have focused on ‘gli eleati’ as involving a locus – pretty much as I do
when I talk of Oxonian dialectic.” Grice: “Mondolfo’s study of the politics of
Risorgimento is good; especially since every Englishman seemed to endorse it!”
-- essential Italian philosopher. Like Grice, Mondolfo believed seriously in
the longitudinal unity of philosophy and made original research on the
historiography of philosophy, especially during the Eleatic, Agrigento, and
later Roman periods. Rodolfo Mondolfo Rodolfo Mondolfo. Rodolfo Mondolfo
(Senigallia), filosofo. Nacque in provincia di Ancona, ultimogenito di Vito
Mondolfo e Gismonda Padovani, una famiglia benestante di commercianti di
origine ebraica. Suo fratello maggiore Ugo Guido (18751958) fu uno storico,
membro del Partito Socialista Italiano sin dalla sua fondazione e stretto
collaboratore di Filippo Turati alla rivista "Critica sociale". Anche
Rodolfo aderisce alle idee marxiste e socialiste. Tra il 1895 ed il 1899
compie gli studi universitari a Firenze, dove raggiunge il fratello, anch'egli
studente dell'ateneo fiorentino, e si laurea in Lettere e Filosofia con Felice
Tocco, discutendo una tesi su Condillac dal titolo: "Contributo alla
storia della teoria dell'associazione", un lavoro da cui saranno poi
tratti alcuni dei suoi primi saggi di storia della filosofia. Insieme i
due fratelli frequentavano un gruppo di giovani socialisti, di cui facevano
parte Gaetano Salvemini, Cesare Battisti ed Ernesta Bittanti. Fino al
1904 Mondolfo si dedica all'insegnamento nei licei nelle città di Potenza,
Ferrara e Mantova. Nel 1904 inizia la carriera universitaria con un
incarico all'Padova, in sostituzione di Roberto Ardigò. Nel 1910 si
trasferisce ad insegnare Storia della filosofia all'Torino, dove rimarrà sino
al 1914, anno in cui ottiene la stessa cattedra all'Bologna. Nell'immediato
primo dopoguerra, a Senigallia, viene eletto consigliere comunale nelle file
del Partito Socialista Italiano, al quale anch'egli aveva aderito sin dagli anni
universitari, ma questo sarà l'unico incarico ufficiale ricoperto da Mondolfo
nel partito. Gli anni che vanno dall'inizio del secolo al 1926 sono forse
quelli in cui è più intensa e fervida l'attività letteraria e politica di
Mondolfo: nel 1903 inizia infatti la sua collaborazione con la rivista
"Critica Sociale", protrattasi fino al 1926, anno in cui la rivista
viene soppressa dal regime fascista. In questo stesso periodo pubblica
alcune delle sue opere più importanti come i "Saggi per la storia della
morale utilitaria" di Hobbes (1903) ed Helvetius (1904), "Tra il
diritto di natura e il comunismo", (1909), "Rousseau nella formazione
della coscienza moderna" (1912), "Il materialismo storico in F.
Engels" (1912), "Sulle orme di Marx" (1919). Nel 1925 Mondolfo è
tra i firmatari del Manifesto degli intellettuali antifascisti, redatto da
Benedetto Croce. Dopo il 1926, per la soppressione della rivista a cui
collabora più attivamente, e per l'inasprirsi dei controlli e delle censure
poste dal regime fascista, nell'evidente impossibilità di proseguire i suoi
studi sulla dottrina marxista, si dedica allo studio del pensiero filosofico
greco. Ciò nonostante, pur in questo periodo, grazie alla politica di Giovanni
Gentile che volle coinvolgere studiosi di diverso orientamento nell'impresa,
collabora con l'Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana e scrive la voce Socialismo
pubblicata nella prima edizione dell'Enciclopedia Treccani (Volume XXXI,
1936). Nel maggio 1939, in seguito alle leggi razziali fasciste che
vietavano agli ebrei di ricoprire cariche pubbliche, Mondolfo scrisse il
proprio curriculum di benemerenze e vi inserì lo stesso Gentile come testimone
il quale "nel 1937 ebbe a propormi per il Premio Reale di filosofia presso
la R. Accademia dei Lincei". Gentile autorizzò Mondolfo a citarlo tra i
testimoni e tentò inutilmente di farlo rientrare tra gli esclusi dalle leggi
razziali. Costretto a lasciare l'Italia Gentile scrisse al filosofo Coriolano
Alberini e lo aiutò a trovare lavoro in Argentina dove intendeva trasferirsi
insieme con la moglie e i figli. Qui, nel 1940, dopo un breve periodo di
incertezze, riesce ad ottenere un incarico presso l'Córdoba per un seminario di
filosofia ed una cattedra di greco antico. Mondolfo scrisse in seguito a
Gentile ringraziandolo per l'"amicizia fraterna". Nel 1946 ha
inizio in Argentina il periodo del regime peronista, che si protrarrà sino al
1955, e di lì a poco sarà seguito dalla dittatura militare argentina. Sono anni
questi che fanno rivivere a Mondolfo molte delle spiacevoli esperienze passate
in Italia durante il fascismo. Anche se in Argentina non si dedica attivamente
alla vita politica, è proprio per contrasti di tipo politico con l'ambiente
universitario di Córdoba che nel 1948 preferisce trasferirsi all'Tucumán, in
cui ottiene la cattedra di Storia della filosofia antica che mantiene fino al
1952, anno in cui si trasferisce a Buenos Aires dove muore il 16 luglio del
1976. Il suo archivio personale è depositato in parte a Firenze presso la
Fondazione di Studi Storici Filippo Turati ed in parte presso la Biblioteca di
Filosofia Università degli Studi di Milano. Opere: “Il materialismo
storico in Engels,” Formiggimi, La Nuova Italia, La Nuova Italia, “Sulle orme di Marx,” – Grice: “Whitehead
used to say that metaphysics has been but footnotes to Plato; and Strawson used
to say that to rob peter to pay paul you must show first that pragmatics is but
footnotes to Grice!” -- Grice: “But of
course a footnote is not a footprint – only similar!” – Grice: “While
‘footprint’ involves Roman pressum, ‘orma’ obviates that!” -- Cappelli, “L'infinito nel pensiero dei Greci,
Felice Le Monnier, La Nuova Italia, “Problemi e metodi di ricerca nella storia
della filosofia, Zanichelli, La Nuova Italia, Firenze, Milano, Bompiani, “Gli
albori della filosofia in Grecia,” «La Nuova Italia», Editrice Petite
Plaisance, Pistoia, . La comprensione del soggetto umano nella cultura antica,
La Nuova Italia (Milano, Bompiani ). Alle origini della filosofia della
cultura, Il Mulino, “Il pensiero politico nel Risorgimento italiano,” Nuova
accademia, Cesare Beccaria, Nuova Accademia Editrice,. “Moralisti greci: la
coscienza morale da Omero a Epicuro,” Ricciardi, “Da Ardigò a Gramsci,” Nuova
Accademia, “Il concetto dell'uomo in Marx,” Città di Senigallia, “Momenti del
pensiero greco e cristiano,” Morano, “Umanismo di Marx. Studi filosofici,
Einaudi, “Il contributo di Spinoza alla concezione storicistica, Lacaita, 1970.
Polis, lavoro e tecnica, Feltrinelli, Educazione e socialismo, Lacaita, “Gli
eleati,” Bompiani, . Note Vedi Paolo Favilli, Dizionario Biografico degli
Italiani, riferimenti in . Fu una delle
prime donne italiane a conseguire la laurea (cfr. Le donne nell'Firenze). Il 7
agosto 1899 sposò civilmente a Firenze in Palazzo Vecchio Cesare Battisti. La
sorella di Ernesta, Irene, sposerà Giovanni Battista Trener, per anni
collaboratore di Cesare. Amedeo
Benedetti, L'Enciclopedia Italiana Treccani e la sua biblioteca, "Biblioteche
Oggi", Milano, n. 8, ottobre 200540.
Enciclopedia Treccani, vedi alla voce futuro di Cesare Medail, Corriere
della Sera, 11 ottobre 200035, Archivio storico. Rodolfo Mondolfo, «SOCIALISMO» la voce nella
Enciclopedia Italiana, Volume XXXI, Roma, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana,
1936. Paolo Simoncelli41. Paolo
Simoncelli42. Paolo Simoncelli43.
Vedi Fabio Frosini, Il contributo italiano alla storia del PensieroFilosofia,
riferimenti in . Archivio Rodolfo
Mondolfo. Inventari Stefano Vitali e Piero Giordanetti. Ministero per i beni
culturali e ambientali. Ufficio Centrale per i beni archivistici. Archivio Rodolfo Mondolfo. Inventari, Stefano
Vitali e Piero Giordanetti, Roma, Ministero per i beni culturali e ambientali.
Ufficio Centrale per i beni archivistici, 1997. Paolo Simoncelli "Non credo
neanch'io alla razza" Gentile e i colleghi ebrei, Le Lettere,
Firenze, L. Vernetti, R. Mondolfo e la
filosofia della prassi, Morano, 1966. E. Bassi, Rodolfo Mondolfo nella vita e
nel pensiero socialista, Tamari, 1968. A. Santucci , Pensiero antico e pensiero
moderno in Rodolfo Mondolfo, Cappelli, Bologna 1979. N. Bobbio, Umanesimo di
Rodolfo Mondolfo, in Maestri e compagni, Passigli Editore, Firenze 1984. M.
Pasquini, Del Vecchio, il kantismo giuridico e la sua incidenza
nell'elaborazione di Rodolfo Mondolfo (1906-1909), Alfagrafica, Città di
Castello, 1999. C. Calabrò, Il socialismo mite. Rodolfo Mondolfo tra marxismo e
democrazia, Polistampa, Firenze 2007. E. Amalfitano, Dalla parte dell'essere
umano. Il socialismo di Rodolfo Mondolfo, L'asino d'oro, Roma. Treccani.itEnciclopedie
on line, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Enciclopedia Italiana, Istituto
dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Dizionario biografico degli italiani, Istituto
dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. su siusa.archivi.beniculturali.it, Sistema Informativo
Unificato per le Soprintendenze Archivistiche.
Opere su openMLOL, Horizons Unlimited srl. Opere Fabio Frosini,
MONDOLFO, Rodolfo, in Il contributo italiano alla storia del Pensiero:
Filosofia, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana, . Vita opere e pensiero Diego
Fusaro, sito "filosofico.net". Fondo Rodolfo Mondolfo Università
degli Studi di Milano. Biblioteca di Filosofia. Fondo Rodolfo Mondolfo
Fondazione di Studi Storici Filippo Turati. V D M Vincitori del Premio Marzotto
Filosofia Università Università Filosofo
Professore1877 1976 20 agosto 16 luglio Senigallia Buenos Aires -- Italiani emigrati in Argentina -- Refs.:
Luigi Speranza, "Grice, Mondolfo, e la filosofia greco-romana," per
il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria,
Italia.
Monferrato
-- CASALE-MONFERRATO (under M) Giovanni
da Casale Giovanni da Casale (Casale
Monferrato), filosofo. Autore di opere di teologia e scienza e legato
pontificio. Biografia Nacque a Casale
Monferrato intorno al 1320. Successivamente entrò nell'ordine francescano nella
provincia genovese. Fu docente presso lo studio francescano di Assisi dal 1335
al 1340. Circa nel 1346 scrisse il
trattato Quaestio de velocitate motus alterationis, ispirato alle dottrine di
Richard Swineshead e di Nicola d'Oresme, e successivamente pubblicato a Venezia
nel 1505. In esso presentò un'analisi grafica del movimento dei corpi
uniformemente accelerati. La sua attività di insegnamento in fisica matematica
influenzò gli studiosi che operarono all'Padova e, si crede, possa aver infine
influenzato il pensiero scientifico di Galileo Galilei che ripropose idee
simili più di due secoli dopo. Note ‘Giovanni da Casale’, Enciclopedie on line,
Treccani. Filosofia Filosofo del XIV secoloTeologi italiani Casale
MonferratoStoria della scienza
monte: Grice: “I like to illustrate a
‘scientific revolution’ with Del Monte’s refutation on the equilibrium
controversy, since it involves a lot of analyticity that only a philosopher can
digest!” -- essential Italian philosopher. guidobaldo del Monte o dal monte. Ritratto.
Il marchese Guidobaldo Del Monte o Guidubaldo Bourbon Del Monte (Pesaro),
filosofo. Mecanicorum liber, 1615 Suo padre, Ranieri, originario da un famiglia
benestante di Urbino, discendente dalla schiatta dei Bourbon del Monte Santa
Maria, fu notato per il suo ruolo bellico e fu autore di due libri
sull'architettura militare. Il duca di Urbino, Guidobaldo II della Rovere, gli
attribuì, per meriti, il titolo di Marchese del Monte, dunque la famiglia
divenne nobile solo un generazione prima di Guidobaldo. Alla morte del padre,
ottenne il titolo di Marchese.
Guidobaldo studiò matematica all'Padova, nel 1564. Mentre era lì,
strinse una grande amicizia con il poeta Torquato Tasso (1544-1595). Guidobaldo poi combatté nel conflitto in
Ungheria, tra l'impero degli Asburgo e l'Impero Ottomano. Al termine della
guerra, tornò nella sua tenuta a Mombaroccio, vicino Urbino, dove passava i
giorni studiando matematica, meccanica, astronomia e ottica. Studiò matematica
con l'aiuto di Federico Commandino (1509-1575). Divenne amico di Bernardino
Baldi (1533-1617), che fu anch'esso studente di Commandino. Nel 1588 venne
nominato ispettore delle fortificazioni del Granducato di Toscana, pur
continuando a risiedere nel Ducato di Urbino.
In quegli anni, Del Monte corrispondeva con numerosi matematici inclusi
Giacomo Contarini (1536-1595), Francesco Barozzi (1537-1604) e Galileo Galilei
(1564-1642), e con alcuni di loro si dice abbia avuto anche relazioni più che
professionali. L'invenzione per la costruzione
di poligoni regolari e per dividere in un numero determinato di segmento
qualsiasi linea fu incorporata come caratteristica del compasso geometrico e
militare di Galileo. Proprio Guidobaldo fu fondamentale nell'aiutare Galilei
nella sua carriera universitaria, che a 26 anni era un promessa ma disoccupato.
Del Monte raccomandò il toscano al suo fratello Cardinale, che a sua volta
parlò con il potente Duca di Toscana, Ferdinando I de' Medici. Sotto la sua
protezione, Galileo ebbe una cattedra di matematica all'Pisa, nel 1589.
Guidobaldo divenne un amico fidato di Galileo e lo aiutò nuovamente nel 1592,
quando dovette necessariamente fare domanda per poter insegnare matematica
all'Padova, a causa dell'odio e della macchinazione di Giovanni de' Medici, un
figlio di Cosimo de' Medici, contro Galileo. Nonostante la loro amicizia,
Guidobaldo fu un critico di alcune teorie di Galileo, come quella relativa alla
legge dell'isocronismo delle oscillazioni.
Guidobaldo scrisse un importante libro sulla prospettiva, intitolato
Perspectivae Libri VI, pubblicato a Pesaro nel 1600, che avrà ampia diffusione
nel corso del XVII. Fu sicuramente, anche secondo il parere di Galileo, uno dei
massimi studiosi di meccanica e matematica del Cinquecento. Mechanicorum liber, Pisauri, 1577 Opere:
“Mechanicorum liber,” Pisauri, Girolamo Concordia, “Planisphaeriorum
universalium theorica, Pisauri, Girolamo Concordia, “De ecclesiastici
calendarii restitutione, Pisauri, Girolamo Concordia, “Perspectivae libri sex,”
Pisauri, Girolamo Concordia, “Problematum astronomicorum libri septem,” Venetiis,
Bernardo Giunta, Giovanni Battista & C Ciotti, “De cochlea,” Venetiis,
Evangelista Deuchino, “Mecanicorum liber,” Venetiis, Evangelista Deuchino. Opere
su Del Monte Le mechaniche
dell'illustriss. sig. Guido Vbaldo de' marchesi Del Monte: tradotte in volgare
dal sig. Filippo Pigafetta, Venetia, Le mechaniche dell'illustriss. sig. Guido
Vbaldo de' marchesi Del Monte: tradotte in volgare dal sig. Filippo Pigafetta
nelle quali si contiene la vera dottrina di tutti gli istrumenti principali da
mouer pesi grandissimi con picciola forza, in Venetia, appresso Francesco di
Franceschi senese, Due lettere inedite di Guidobaldo del Monte a Giacomo
Contarini, pubblicate ed illustrate da Antonio Favaronota, Venezia, I sei libri
della prospettiva di Guidobaldo dei marchesi Del Monte dal latino tradotti
interpretati e commentati da Rocco Sinisgalli, presentazione di Gaspare De
Fiore, Roma, La teoria sui planisferi
universali di Guidobaldo Del Monte, Rocco Sinisgalli, Salvatore Vastola,
Firenze, "Solo nel settembre del
1592 Galileo (che nel frattempo era stato molto probabilmente anche suo ospite)
poteva occupare la cattedra di Padova, grazie anche all’intervento del D., che
nell’ambiente veneto poteva contare, oltre che sull’amicizia di un Contarini e
di un Pinelli, sull’autorità e l’influenza di Giambattista Del Monte, generale
delle fanterie della Repubblica":
fondazionecardinalefrancescomariadelmonte.it/guidobaldo-del-monte/. Questo testo proviene in parte dalla relativa
voce del progetto Mille anni di scienza in Italia, opera del Museo Galileo.
Istituto Museo di Storia della Scienza di Firenze (home page), pubblicata sotto
licenza Creative Commons CC-BY-3.0 G.
Galilei, Le opere, t. VI, Società editrice fiorentina, Firenze 1847, su
books.google.it. S. Hildebrandt, The Parsimonious Universe: Shape and Form in
the Natural World, Springer Verlag, 1996.
0387979913 Lives of Eminent Persons, Baldwin and Cradock, London 1833.
A. Giostra, La stella o cometa nelle lettere di Guidobaldo dal Monte a pier Matteo
Giordani, Giornale di Astronomia, 29 n°
3, 2003. A. BecchiD. Bertoloni MeliE. Gamba (eds): Guidobaldo del Monte. Theory
and Practice of the Mathematical Disciplines from Urbino to Europe, Edition
Open Access, Berlin . Galileo Galilei
Guidobaldo II della Rovere Mombaroccio. Guidobaldo Del Monte, in Enciclopedia
Italiana, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana.
Guidobaldo Del Monte, in Dizionario biografico degli italiani, Istituto
dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Guidobaldo Del Monte, su MacTutor, University of St
Andrews, Scotland. Opere di Guidobaldo
Del Monte / Guidobaldo Del Monte (altra versione) / Guidobaldo Del Monte (altra
versione), su openMLOL, Horizons Unlimited srl. Opere di Guidobaldo Del Monte,
. Aterini B. (),‘Guidobaldo del Monte (1545 -1607)’, in Cigola, M. (Ed.),
Distinguished Figures in Descriptive Geometry and Its Applications for
Mechanism Science: From the Middle Ages to the 17th Century , 30 serie 'History of Mechanism and Machine
Science',direction by Ceccarelli M., New York, London: Ed. Springer, 153180.
978-3-319-6-2 (Print). DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-7-9 7.
Online:link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007%2F978-3-319-7-9_7#page-1 Biografia di
Guidobaldo Del Monte sul sito del comune di Mombaroccio, su mombaroccio.eu. The
Galileo Project, su galileo.rice.edu. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, "Grice e del
Monte," per Il Club Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa
Grice, Liguria, Italia.
mooreism: g. e. and his paradox: cited by H. P. Grice.
Irish London-born philosopher who spearheaded the attack on idealism and was a
major supporter of realism in all its forms: metaphysical, epistemological, and
axiological. He was born in Upper Norwood, a suburb of London; did his
undergraduate work at Cambridge ; spent 84 as a fellow of Trinity ; returned to
Cambridge in 1 as a lecturer; and was granted a professorship there in 5. He
also served as editor of Mind. The bulk of his work falls into four categories:
metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, and philosophical methodology. Metaphysics.
In this area, Moore is mainly known for his attempted refutation of idealism
and his defense thereby of realism. In his “The Refutation of Idealism” 3, he
argued that there is a crucial premise that is essential to all possible
arguments for the idealistic conclusion that “All reality is mental spiritual.”
This premise is: “To be is to be perceived” in the broad sense of ‘perceive’.
Moore argued that, under every possible interpretation of it, that premise is
either a tautology or false; hence no significant conclusion can ever be
inferred from it. His positive defense of realism had several prongs. One was
to show that there are certain claims held by non-realist philosophers, both
idealist ones and skeptical ones. Moore argued, in “A Defense of Common Sense”
5, that these claims are either factually false or self-contradictory, or that
in some cases there is no good reason to believe them. Among the claims that
Moore attacked are these: “Propositions about purported material facts are
false”; “No one has ever known any such propositions to be true”; “Every
purported physical fact is logically dependent on some mental fact”; and “Every
physical fact is causally dependent on some mental fact.” Another major prong
of Moore’s defense of realism was to argue for the existence of an external
world and later to give a “Proof of an External World” 3. Epistemology. Most of
Moore’s work in this area dealt with the various kinds of knowledge we have,
why they must be distinguished, and the problem of perception and our knowledge
of an external world. Because he had already argued for the existence of an
external world in his metaphysics, he here focused on how we know it. In many
papers and chapters e.g., “The Nature and Reality of Objects of Perception,” 6
he examined and at times supported three main positions: naive or direct
realism, representative or indirect realism, and phenomenalism. Although he
seemed to favor direct realism at first, in the majority of his papers he found
representative realism to be the most supportable position despite its
problems. It should also be noted that, in connection with his leanings mood
toward representative realism, Moore maintained the existence of sense-data and
argued at length for an account of just how they are related to physical
objects. That there are sense-data Moore never doubted. The question was, What
is their ontological status? With regard to the various kinds of knowledge or
ways of knowing, Moore made a distinction between dispositional or
non-actualized and actualized knowledge. Within the latter Moore made
distinctions between direct apprehension often known as knowledge by
acquaintance, indirect apprehension, and knowledge proper or propositional
knowledge. He devoted much of his work to finding the conditions for knowledge
proper. Ethics. In his major work in ethics, Principia Ethica 3, Moore
maintained that the central problem of ethics is, What is good? meaning by this, not what things are good,
but how ‘good’ is to be defined. He argued that there can be only one answer,
one that may seem disappointing, namely: good is good, or, alternatively,
‘good’ is indefinable. Thus ‘good’ denotes a “unique, simple object of thought”
that is indefinable and unanalyzable. His first argument on behalf of that
claim consisted in showing that to identify good with some other object i.e.,
to define ‘good’ is to commit the naturalistic fallacy. To commit this fallacy
is to reduce ethical propositions to either psychological propositions or
reportive definitions as to how people use words. In other words, what was
meant to be an ethical proposition, that X is good, becomes a factual
proposition about people’s desires or their usage of words. Moore’s second
argument ran like this: Suppose ‘good’ were definable. Then the result would be
even worse than that of reducing ethical propositions to non-ethical
propositions ethical propositions would
be tautologies! For example, suppose you defined ‘good’ as ‘pleasure’. Then
suppose you maintained that pleasure is good. All you would be asserting is
that pleasure is pleasure, a tautology. To avoid this conclusion ‘good’ must
mean something other than ‘pleasure’. Why is this the naturalistic fallacy?
Because good is a non-natural property. But even if it were a natural one,
there would still be a fallacy. Hence some have proposed calling it the
definist fallacy the fallacy of
attempting to define ‘good’ by any means. This argument is often known as the
open question argument because whatever purported definition of ‘good’ anyone
offers, it would always be an open question whether whatever satisfies the
definition really is good. In the last part of Principia Ethica Moore turned to
a discussion of what sorts of things are the greatest goods with which we are
acquainted. He argued for the view that they are personal affection and
aesthetic enjoyments. Philosophical methodology. Moore’s methodology in
philosophy had many components, but two stand out: his appeal to and defense of
common sense and his utilization of various methods of philosophical/conceptual
analysis. “A Defense of Common Sense” argued for his claim that the commonsense
view of the world is wholly true, and for the claim that any view which opposed
that view is either factually false or self-contradictory. Throughout his
writings Moore distinguished several kinds of analysis and made use of them
extensively in dealing with philosophical problems. All of these may be found
in the works cited above and other essays gathered into Moore’s Philosophical
Studies2 and Philosophical Papers 9. These have been referred to as
refutational analysis, with two subforms, showing contradictions and
“translation into the concrete”; distinctional analysis; decompositional
analysis either definitional or divisional; and reductional analysis. Moore was
greatly revered as a teacher. Many of his students and colleagues have paid
high tribute to him in very warm and grateful terms. Moore’s paradox, as first discussed by G. E.
Moore, the perplexity involving assertion of what is expressed by conjunctions
such as ‘It’s raining, but I believe it ’t’ and ‘It’s raining, but I don’t
believe it is’. The oddity of such presenttense first-person uses of ‘to
believe’ seems peculiar to those conjunctions just because it is assumed both
that, when asserting roughly,
representing as true a conjunction, one
also asserts its conjuncts, and that, as a rule, the assertor believes the
asserted proposition. Thus, no perplexity arises from assertions of, for
instance, ‘It’s raining today, but I falsely believed it wasn’t until I came
out to the porch’ and ‘If it’s raining but I believe it ’t, I have been misled
by the weather report’. However, there are reasons to think that, if we rely
only on these assumptions and examples, our characterization of the problem is
unduly narrow. First, assertion seems relevant only because we are interested
in what the assertor believes. Secondly, those conjunctions are disturbing only
insofar as they show that Moore’s paradox Moore’s paradox 583 583 some of the assertor’s beliefs, though
contingent, can only be irrationally held. Thirdly, autobiographical reports
that may justifiably be used to charge the reporter with irrationality need be
neither about his belief system, nor conjunctive, nor true e.g., ‘I don’t
exist’, ‘I have no beliefs’, nor false e.g., ‘It’s raining, but I have no
evidence that it is’. So, Moore’s paradox is best seen as the problem posed by
contingent propositions that cannot be justifiably believed. Arguably, in
forming a belief of those propositions, the believer acquires non-overridable
evidence against believing them. A successful analysis of the problem along
these lines may have important epistemological consequences. Refs.: Grice, “Oxford seminars.” Grice
dedicated a full chapter to the Moore paradox. Mainly, Moore is confused in
lexicological ways. An emisor EXPRESSES the belief that p. What the emisor
communicates is that p, not that he believes that p. He does not convey
explicitly that he believes that p, nor implicitly. Belief and its expression
is linked conceptually with the modeindicative (‘est’); as is desire and its
expression with the imperative mode (“sit”).
Lemma – di-lemma – tri-lemma – tetra-lemma
-- dilemma. Grice: “Ryle overuses the word dilemma in his popularization,
“Dilemmas”.” 1 Any problem where morality is relevant. This broad use includes
not only conflicts among moral reasons but also conflicts between moral reasons
and reasons of law, religion, or self-interest. In this sense, Abraham is in a
moral dilemma when God commands him to sacrifice his son, even if he has no
moral reason to obey. Similarly, I am in a moral dilemma if I cannot help a
friend in trouble without forgoing a lucrative but morally neutral business
opportunity. ’Moral dilemma’ also often refers to 2 any topic area where it is
not known what, if anything, is morally good or right. For example, when one
asks whether abortion is immoral in any way, one could call the topic “the
moral dilemma of abortion.” This epistemic use does not imply that anything
really is immoral at all. Recently, moral philosophers have discussed a much
narrower set of situations as “moral dilemmas.” They usually define ‘moral
dilemma’ as 3 a situation where an agent morally ought to do each of two acts
but cannot do both. The bestknown example is Sartre’s student who morally ought
to care for his mother in Paris but at the same time morally ought to go to
England to join the Free and fight the
Nazis. However, ‘ought’ covers ideal actions that are not morally required,
such as when someone ought to give to a certain charity but is not required to
do so. Since most common examples of moral dilemmas include moral obligations
or duties, or other requirements, it is more accurate to define ‘moral dilemma’
more narrowly as 4 a situation where an agent has a moral requirement to do
each of two acts but cannot do both. Some philosophers also refuse to call a
situation a moral dilemma when one of the conflicting requirements is clearly
overridden, such as when I must break a trivial promise in order to save a
life. To exclude such resolvable conflicts, ‘moral dilemma’ can be defined as 5
a situation where an agent has a moral requirement to adopt each of two
alternatives, and neither requirement is overridden, but the agent cannot
fulfill both. Another common move is to define ‘moral dilemma’ as 6 a situation
where every alternative is morally wrong. This is equivalent to 4 or 5,
respectively, if an act is morally wrong whenever it violates any moral
requirement or any non-overridden moral requirement. However, we usually do not
call an act wrong unless it violates an overriding moral requirement, and then
6 rules out moral dilemmas by definition, since overriding moral requirements
clearly cannot conflict. Although 5 thus seems preferable, some would object
that 5 includes trivial requirements and conflicts, such as conflicts between
trivial promises. To include only tragic situations, we could define ‘moral
dilemma’ as 7 a situation where an agent has a strong moral obligation or
requirement to adopt each of two alternatives, and neither is overridden, but
the agent cannot adopt both alternatives. This definition is strong enough to
raise the important controversies about moral dilemmas without being so strong
as to rule out their possibility by definition. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Ryle’s
dilemmas: are they?”
episteme -- epistemology, the discipline,
at the intersection of ethics and epistemology, that studies the epistemic
status and relations of moral judgments and principles. It has developed out of
an interest, common to both ethics and epistemology, in questions of
justification and justifiability in
epistemology, of statements or beliefs, and in ethics, of actions as well as
judgments of actions and also general principles of judgment. Its most
prominent questions include the following. Can normative claims be true or
false? If so, how can they be known to be true or false? If not, what status do
they have, and are they capable of justification? If they are capable of
justification, how can they be justified? Does the justification of normative
claims differ with respect to particular claims and with respect to general
principles? In epistemology recent years have seen a tendency to accept as
valid an account of knowledge as entailing justified true belief, a conception
that requires an account not just of truth but also of justification and of
justified belief. Thus, under what conditions is someone justified,
epistemically, in believing something? Justification, of actions, of judgments,
and of principles, has long been a central element in ethics. It is only
recently that justification in ethics came to be thought of as an
epistemological problem, hence ‘moral epistemology’, as an expression, is a
fairly recent coinage, although its problems have a long lineage. One
long-standing linkage is provided by the challenge of skepticism. Skepticism in
ethics can be about the existence of any genuine distinction between right and
wrong, or it can focus on the possibility of attaining any knowledge of right
and wrong, good or bad. Is there a right answer? is a question in the
metaphysics of ethics. Can we know what the right answer is, and if so how? is
one of moral epistemology. Problems of perception and observation and ones
about observation statements or sense-data play an important role in
epistemology. There is not any obvious parallel in moral epistemology, unless
it is the role of prereflective moral judgments, or commonsense moral
judgments moral judgments unguided by
any overt moral theory which can be
taken to provide the data of moral theory, and which need to be explained,
systematized, coordinated, or revised to attain an appropriate relation between
theory and data. This would be analogous to taking the data of epistemology to
be provided, not by sense-data or observations but by judgments of perception
or observation statements. Once this step is taken the parallel is very close.
One source of moral skepticism is the apparent lack of any observational
counterpart for moral predicates, which generates the question how moral judgments
can be true if there is nothing for them to correspond to. Another source of
moral skepticism is apparently constant disagreement and uncertainty, which
would appear to be explained by the skeptical hypothesis denying the reality of
moral distinctions. Noncognitivism in ethics maintains that moral judgments are
not objects of knowledge, that they make no statements capable of truth or
falsity, but are or are akin to expressions of attitudes. Some other major
differences among ethical theories are largely epistemological in character.
Intuitionism maintains that basic moral propositions are knowable by intuition.
Empiricism in ethics maintains that moral propositions can be established by
empirical means or are complex forms of empirical statements. Ethical
rationalism maintains that the fundamental principles of morality can be
established a priori as holding of necessity. This is exemplified by Kant’s
moral philosophy, in which the categorical imperative is regarded as synthetic
a priori; more recently by what Alan Gewirth b.2 calls the “principle of
generic consistency,” which he claims it is selfcontradictory to deny. Ethical
empiricism is exemplified by classical utilitarianism, such as that of Bentham,
which aspires to develop ethics as an empirical science. If the consequences of
actions can be scientifically predicted and their utilities calculated, then
ethics can be a science. Situationism is equivalent to concrete case
intuitionism in maintaining that we can know immediately what ought to be done
in specific cases, but most ethical theories maintain that what ought to be
done is, in J. S. Mill’s words, determined by “the application of a law to an
individual case.” Different theories differ on the epistemic status of these
laws and on the process of application. Deductivists, either empiricistic or
rationalistic, hold that the law is essentially unchanged in the application;
non-deductivists hold that the law is modified in the process of application.
This distinction is explained in F. L. Will, “Beyond Deduction.” There is
similar variation about what if anything is selfevident, Sidgwick maintaining
that only certain highly abstract principles are self-evident, Ross that only
general rules are, and Prichard that only concrete judgments are, “by an act of
moral thinking.” Other problems in moral epistemology are provided by the
factvalue distinction and controversies
about whether there is any such distinction
and the isought question, the question how a moral judgment can be
derived from statements of fact alone. Naturalists affirm the possibility,
non-naturalists deny it. Prescriptivists claim that moral judgments are
prescriptions and cannot be deduced from descriptive statements alone. This
question ultimately leads to the question how an ultimate principle can be
justified. If it cannot be deduced from statements of fact, that route is out;
if it must be deduced from some other moral principle, then the principle
deduced cannot be ultimate and in any case this process is either circular or
leads to an infinite regress. If the ultimate principle is self-evident, then
the problem may have an answer. But if it is not it would appear to be
arbitrary. The problem of the justification of an ultimate principle continues
to be a leading one in moral epistemology. Recently there has been much
interest in the status and existence of “moral facts.” Are there any, what are
they, and how are they established as “facts”? This relates to questions about
moral realism. Moral realism maintains that moral predicates are real and can
be known to be so; anti-realists deny this. This denial links with the view
that moral properties supervene on natural ones, and the problem of
supervenience is another recent link between ethics and epistemology.
Pragmatism in ethics maintains that a moral problem is like any problem in that
it is the occasion for inquiry and moral judgments are to be regarded as
hypotheses to be tested by how well they resolve the problem. This amounts to
an attempt to bypass the isought problem and all such “dualisms.” So is
constructivism, a development owing much to the work of Rawls, which contrasts
with moral realism. Constructivism maintains that moral ideas are human
constructs and the task is not epistemological or metaphysical but practical and
theoretical that of attaining reflective
equilibrium between considered moral judgments and the principles that
coordinate and explain them. On this view there are no moral facts. Opponents
maintain that this only replaces a foundationalist view of ethics with a
coherence conception. The question whether questions of moral epistemology can
in this way be bypassed can be regarded as itself a question of moral
epistemology. And the question of the foundations of morality, and whether
there are foundations, can still be regarded as a question of moral
epistemology, as distinct from a question of the most convenient and efficient
arrangement of our moral ideas. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Our knowledge of right and
wrong: do we have it? Is it intuitive as Oxonians believe?”
“practical
reason”Grice: “In ‘practical reason,’ we have Aristotle at his best: the
category is ‘action,’ and the praedicabile is ‘rational.’ Now ‘action’ is
supracategorial: It’s STRAWSON who acts, not his action!” -- -- “Or ‘to do
things,’ as Austin would put it!” -- moral rationalism, the view that the
substance of morality, usually in the form of general moral principles, can be
known a priori. The view is defended by Kant in Groundwork of the Metaphysic of
Morals, but it goes back at least to Plato. Both Plato and Kant thought that a
priori moral knowledge could have an impact on what we do quite independently
of any desire that we happen to have. This motivational view is also ordinarily
associated with moral rationalism. It comes in two quite different forms. The
first is that a priori moral knowledge consists in a sui generis mental state
that is both belief-like and desire-like. This seems to have been Plato’s view,
for he held that the belief that something is good is itself a disposition to
promote that thing. The second is that a priori moral knowledge consists in a
belief that is capable of rationally producing a distinct desire. Rationalists
who make the first claim have had trouble accommodating the possibility of
someone’s believing that something is good but, through weakness of will, not
mustering the desire to do it. Accordingly, they have been forced to assimilate
weakness of will to ignorance of the good. Rationalists who make the second
claim about reason’s action-producing capacity face no such problem. For this
reason, their view is often preferred. The best-known anti-rationalist about
morality is Hume. His Treatise of Human Nature denies both that morality’s
substance can be known by reason alone and that reason alone is capable of
producing action.
Griceian realism: a metaethical view
committed to the objectivity of ethics. It has 1 metaphysical, 2 semantic, and
3 epistemological components. 1 Its metaphysical component is the claim that
there are moral facts and moral properties whose existence and nature are
independent of people’s beliefs and attitudes about what is right or wrong. In
this claim, moral realism contrasts with an error theory and with other forms
of nihilism that deny the existence of moral facts and properties. It contrasts
as well with various versions of moral relativism and other forms of ethical
constructivism that make moral facts consist in facts about people’s moral
beliefs and attitudes. 2 Its semantic component is primarily cognitivist.
Cognitivism holds that moral judgments should be construed as assertions about
the moral properties of actions, persons, policies, and other objects of moral
assessment, that moral predicates purport to refer to properties of such
objects, that moral judgments or the propositions that they express can be true
or false, and that cognizers can have the cognitive attitude of belief toward
the propositions that moral judgments express. These cognitivist claims
contrast with the noncognitive claims of emotivism and prescriptivism,
according to which the primary purpose of moral judgments is to express the
appraiser’s attitudes or commitments, rather than to state facts or ascribe
properties. Moral realism also holds that truth for moral judgments is non-epistemic;
in this way it contrasts with moral relativism and other forms of ethical
constructivism that make the truth of a moral judgment epistemic. The
metaphysical and semantic theses imply that there are some true moral
propositions. An error theory accepts the cognitivist semantic claims but
denies the realist metaphysical thesis. It holds that moral judgments should be
construed as containing referring expressions and having truth-values, but
insists that these referring expressions are empty, because there are no moral
facts, and that no moral claims are true. Also on this theory, commonsense
moral thought presupposes the existence of moral facts and properties, but is
systematically in error. In this way, the error theory stands to moral realism
much as atheism stands to theism in a world of theists. J. L. Mackie introduced
and defended the error theory in his Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, 7. 3
Finally, if moral realism is to avoid skepticism it must claim that some moral
beliefs are true, that there are methods for justifying moral beliefs, and that
moral knowledge is possible. While making these metaphysical, semantic, and
epistemological claims, moral realism is compatible with a wide variety of
other metaphysical, semantic, and epistemological principles and so can take
many different forms. The moral realists in the early part of the twentieth
century were generally intuitionists. Intuitionism combined a commitment to
moral realism with a foundationalist moral epistemology according to which
moral knowledge must rest on self-evident moral truths and with the
nonnaturalist claim that moral facts and properties are sui generis and not
reducible to any natural facts or properties. Friends of noncognitivism found
the metaphysical and epistemological commitments of intuitionism extravagant
and so rejected moral realism. Later moral realists have generally sought to
defend moral realism without the metaphysical and epistemological trappings of
intuitionism. One such version of moral realism takes a naturalistic form. This
form of ethical naturalism claims that our moral beliefs are justified when
they form part of an explanatorily coherent system of beliefs with one another
and with various non-moral beliefs, and insists that moral properties are just
natural properties of the people, actions, and policies that instantiate them.
Debate between realists and anti-realists and within the realist camp centers
on such issues as the relation between moral judgment and action, the rational
authority of morality, moral epistemology and methodology, the relation between
moral and non-moral natural properties, the place of ethics in a naturalistic
worldview, and the parity of ethics and the sciences.
Quinque sensa: Grice: “Grice and Strawson
should not be thy teachers, but thy five senses!” -- visum, olfactum, gustum,
tactum, auditumquinque organa: oculus, etc. Grice: “I am particularly irritated
by Pitcher, of all people, quoting me to refute my idea that a ‘pain-sense’ is
an otiosity! Of course it is!”“And I
used to like Pitcher when he was at Oxford!” -- Some reamarks about ‘senusus.’Grice’s
Modified occam’s razor: “Do not multiply senses beyond necessitylet there be
five: visum, auditum, tactum, gustum, and olfactum --. “Some remarks about the (five?)
senses”Grice: “Grice: “And then there’s Shaftesbury who thinks he is being
witty when he speaks of a ‘moral’ “sense”!” -- moral sense theory, an ethical
theory, developed by some British philosophers
notably Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, and Hume
according to which the pleasure or pain a person feels upon thinking
about or “observing” certain character traits is indicative of the virtue or
vice, respectively, of those features. It is a theory of “moral perception,”
offered in response to moral rationalism, the view that moral distinctions are
derived by reason alone, and combines Locke’s empiricist doctrine that all
ideas begin in experience with the belief, widely shared at the time, that
feelings play a central role in moral evaluation and motivation. On this theory,
our emotional responses to persons’ characters are often “perceptions” of their
morality, just as our experiences of an apple’s redness and sweetness are
perceptions of its color and taste. These ideas of morality are seen as
products of an “internal” sense, because they are produced in the “observer”
only after she forms a concept of the conduct or trait being observed or
contemplated as when a person realizes
that she is seeing someone intentionally harm another and reacts with
displeasure at what she sees. The moral sense is conceived as being analogous
to, or possibly an aspect of, our capacity to recognize varying degrees of
beauty in things, which modern writers call “the sense of beauty.” Rejecting
the popular view that morality is based on the will of God, Shaftesbury
maintains rather that morality depends on human nature, and he introduces the
notion of a sense of right and wrong, possessed uniquely by human beings, who
alone are capable of reflection. Hutcheson argues that to approve of a character
is to regard it as virtuous. For him, reason, which discovers relations of
inanimate objects to rational agents, is unable to arouse our approval in the
absence of a moral sense. Ultimately, we can explain why, for example, we
approve of someone’s temperate character only by appealing to our natural
tendency to feel pleasure sometimes identified with approval at the thought of
characters that exhibit benevolence, the trait to which all other virtues can
be traced. This disposition to feel approval and disapproval is what Hutcheson
identifies as the moral sense. Hume emphasizes that typical human beings make
moral distinctions on the basis of their feelings only when those sentiments
are experienced from a disinterested or “general” point of view. In other
words, we turn our initial sentiments into moral judgments by compensating for
the fact that we feel more strongly about those to whom we are emotionally
close than those from whom we are more distant. On a widely held interpretation
of Hume, the moral sense provides not only judgments, but also motives to act
according to those judgments, since its feelings may be motivating passions or
arouse such passions. Roderick Firth’s 787 twentieth-century ideal observer
theory, according to which moral good is designated by the projected reactions
of a hypothetically omniscient, disinterested observer possessing other ideal
traits, as well as Brandt’s contemporary moral spectator theory, are direct
descendants of the moral sense theory. Refs:
H. P. Grice: “Shaftesbury’s moral sense: some remarks about the ‘senses’ of
this ‘expression’!” Refs.: H. P. Grice, G. J. Warnock, and J. O. Urmson: “The
Roman names for the five senses.” Luigi Speranza, “The senses in iconography.”
The Anglo-American Club. --.
MEDIUS
-- mediautum-inmediatum distinction, the: mediatum: Grice is all
about the mediatum. This he call a ‘soul-to-soul’ transfer. Imagine you pick up
a rose, the thorn hurts you. You are in pain. You say “Ouch.” You transmit this
to the fellow gardener. The mediacy means, “Beware of the thorn. It may hurt
you.” “I am amazed that in The New World, it’s all about immediacy (Chisholm)
when there’s so much which is mediately of immediate philosophical importance!”
immediatum: Grice: “Here the ‘in-’
is negative!”the presence to the mind without intermediaries. The term
‘immediatum’ and its cognates have been used extensively throughout the history
of philosophy, generally without much explanation. Descartes, e.g., explains
his notion of thought thus: “I use this term to include everything that is
within us in a way that we are IMMEDIATELY aware of it” (Second Replies).
Descartes offers no explanation of immediate awareness, but the implicaturum is
“contextually cancellable.” “Only an idiot would not realise that he is opposing
it to mediated experience.”Grice. Grice is well aware of this. “Check with
Lewis and Short.” “mĕdĭo , 1, v. a. medius, I.to
halve, divide in the middle (post-class.), Apic. 3, 9. — B. Neutr., to be in
the middle: “melius Juno mediante,” Pall. Mart. 10, 32.” “So you see, ‘mediare’
can be transitive, but surely Descartes means it in the intransitive
waysomething mediates or something doesn’tClear as water!” However, when
used as a primitive in this way, ‘immediatum’ may simply mean that thoughts are
the immediate objects of perception because thoughts are the only things
perceived in the strict and proper sense that no perception of an intermediary
is required for the person’s awareness of them. Sometimes ‘immediate’ means
‘not mediated’. (1) An inference from a premise to a conclusion can exhibit
logical immediacy because it does not depend on other premises. This is a
technical usage of proof theory to describe the form of a certain class of
inference rules. (2) A concept can exhibit conceptual immediacy because it is
definitionally primitive, as in the Berkeleian doctrine that perception of
qualities is immediate, and perception of objects is defined by the perception
of their qualities, which is directly understood. (3) Our perception of
something can exhibit causal immediacy because it is not caused by intervening
acts of perception or cognition, as with seeing someone immediately in the
flesh rather than through images on a movie screen. (4) A belief-formation
process can possess psychological immediacy because it contains no subprocess
of reasoning and in that sense has no psychological mediator. (5) Our knowledge
of something can exhibit epistemic immediacy because it is justified without
inference from another proposition, as in intuitive knowledge of the existence
of the self, which has no epistemic mediator. A noteworthy special application
of immediacy is to be found in Russell’s notion of knowledge by acquaintance.
This notion is a development of the venerable doctrine originating with Plato, and
also found in Augustine, that understanding the nature of some object requires
that we can gain immediate cognitive access to that object. Thus, for Plato, to
understand the nature of beauty requires acquaintance with beauty itself. This
view contrasts with one in which understanding the nature of beauty requires
linguistic competence in the use of the word ‘beauty’ or, alternatively, with
one that requires having a mental representation of beauty. Russell offers
sense-data and universals as examples of things known by acquaintance. To these
senses of immediacy we may add another category whose members have acquired
special meanings within certain philosophical traditions. For example, in
Hegel’s philosophy if (per impossibile) an object were encountered “as existing
in simple immediacy” it would be encountered as it is in itself, unchanged by
conceptualization. In phenomenology “immediate” experience is, roughly,
bracketed experience.
monti: paolo rossi monti (Urbino), filosofo. Firma in una lettera a Antonio
Banfi. Ha studiato prima ad Ancona e poi a Bologna, dove si è iscritto a filosofia.
Si è laureato na Firenze, con il filosofo dell'umanesimo Garin, con il quale
nel 1947 ha conseguito anche il diploma di perfezionamento. Fra il 1947 e il
1949 ha insegnato storia e filosofia al Liceo Classico "Plinio il
Giovane" di Città di Castello (PG). Dal 1950 al 1959 è stato assistente di
Antonio Banfi all'Università degli Studi di Milano. Fra il 1950 e il 1955 ha
lavorato all'Enciclopedia dei ragazzi presso la casa editrice Mondadori.
Dal 1955 ha insegnato storia della filosofia, prima all'Università degli Studi
di Milano (fino al 1961), poi a Cagliari (1961-1962) e Bologna. Nel 1962
è stato adottato dalla zia materna Elena Monti. Di conseguenza il suo cognome e
quello dei suoi figli è diventato Rossi Monti nei documenti ufficiali.
Tuttavia, poiché all'epoca il filosofo aveva già pubblicato tre libri e diversi
saggi con il cognome Rossi, ha deciso per chiarezza di continuare ad
utilizzare, nell'attività culturale, il solo cognome Rossi. Dal 1966 si è
definitivamente stabilito a Firenze, dove ha tenuto fino al 1999 la cattedra di
storia della filosofia presso la facoltà di lettere dell'Università. Nello
stesso 1999 è stato nominato professore emerito dall'Firenze. Fra i suoi
figli, Mario Rossi Monti (1953), psichiatra, è ordinario di psicologia
all'Urbino. Attività pubblicistica Paolo Rossi si è sempre occupato di
storia della filosofia e della scienza, con particolare riguardo al Cinquecento
e al Seicento, pubblicando centinaia di saggi e articoli su riviste italiane e
straniere. Ha curato edizioni di diversi autori, tra i quali Cattaneo
(Mondadori), Bacone (UTET), Vico (Rizzoli), Diderot (Feltrinelli), Rousseau
(Sansoni), e diretto diverse collane scientifiche e filosofiche per le case
editrici Feltrinelli, Sansoni e La Nuova Italia. Ha diretto la collana
"Storia della scienza" dell'editore Olschki insieme con il filosofo
Walter Bernardi. Ha partecipato alla direzione di varie riviste, tra le quali
la Rivista di filosofia, e ai comitati di consulenza di numerose altre, tra le
quali European Journal of Philosophy, Révue internationale d'histoire et
méthodologie de la psychiatrie, Science in Context, Time and Society. Le
collaborazioni con giornali italiani vanno dalla rubrica "Scienza e
filosofia" sul settimanale Panorama alla rubrica "Storia delle
idee" per il supplemento culturale La Domenica del quotidiano Il Sole 24
ore (dal 1999 alla morte). Nel 1988 è stato eletto presidente del comitato
scientifico del centro di studi filosofici "Antonio Banfi" di Reggio
Emilia. È stato membro dell'Accademia Europea dal 1989 e membro onorario della
Società Italiana di Psicopatologia. Nel 1997 è stato nominato presidente della
«Società italiana per lo studio dei rapporti tra scienza e letteratura».
È stato uno dei promotori del "Festival della Filosofia della Scienza di
Città di Castello", del quale è stato direttore scientifico negli anni
2008, 2009 e . Pensiero Ha dedicato studi particolarmente approfonditi a
Francesco Bacone(che per primo fece conoscere al pubblico italiano), ma il
campo nel quale ha dato il contributo più innovativo è quello della cosiddetta
"rivoluzione scientifica" del Seicento. Rossi sostiene che la
scienza, a cavallo tra XVI e XVII secolo, ha vissuto un vero e proprio
mutamento di paradigma. Il carattere rivoluzionario dei mutamenti nel modo di
fare scienza avvenuti all'epoca di Bacone e Galileo grazie a una serie di
fattori: la nuova visione della natura, non più divisa tra corpi naturali e
"artificiali", la dimensione continentale (e, in prospettiva,
mondiale) della nuova cultura scientifica, l'autonomia dal pensiero religioso,
la pubblicità dei risultati. Un'altra importante novità fu costituita, secondo
Rossi, dal formarsi di un'autonoma comunità scientifica internazionale,
"una sorta di autonoma Repubblica della Scienza [...] dove non esiste
l'ipse dixit". Si è dedicato per oltre trent'anni al tema della
memoria, in chiave filosofica e storica, al quale ha dedicato nel 1991 il saggio
Il passato, la memoria, l'oblio con il quale ha vinto il Premio
Viareggio. Nei suoi ultimi anni ha analizzato e denunciato l'esistenza di
diverse forme di "ostilità alla scienza" (il "primitivismo"
e l'"antiscienza") che, come forma di reazione allo sviluppo tecnologico
e industriale, propugnano come soluzione di tutti i mali il ritorno a un mondo
premoderno idealizzato e il rifiuto della razionalità. Riconoscimenti Nel
1972 è stato eletto membro del "Comitato 08" del Consiglio Nazionale
delle Ricerche (rieletto nel 1977). È stato presidente sia della Società
Filosofica Italiana sia della Società Italiana di Storia della Scienza (dal
1983 al 1990). È stato socio corrispondente dell'Accademia Pontaniana di Napoli
dal 1981, socio corrispondente dell'Accademia Nazionale dei Lincei dal 1988 e
socio nazionale della stessa dal 1992. Nel 1985 ha ricevuto la Medaglia
Sarton per la storia della scienza dalla «American History of Science Society»
(USA) e successivamente la Medaglia Pictet dalla «Société de Physique et d'Histoire
Naturelle de Genève». Gli è stato conferito il Premio Balzan per la storia
delle scienze "per i suoi decisivi contributi allo studio dei fondamenti
intellettuali della scienza dal Rinascimento all'Illuminismo". La Società
Psicoanalitica Italiana lo ha insignito del Premio Musatti. L'archivio e la
biblioteca Paolo Rossi ha lasciato la propria collezione privata di libri e
documenti alla biblioteca del Museo Galileo, che nel giugno ne ha ricevuta una prima tranche. Il
materiale archivistico raccoglie scritti e appunti a tema storico-filosofico e
storico-scientifico, relazioni tenute a convegni e conferenze, minute, bozze di
stampa e materiali preparatori per pubblicazioni, documenti attinenti
all'attività di docenza e divulgazione, nonché un'ampia selezione di ritagli e
articoli di argomento vario tratti dalle maggiori testate italiane e una
raccolta di documenti di Antonio Banfi. Nella biblioteca privata, invece,
ai numerosi testi di storia della filosofia e storia della scienza, si
affiancano volumi di argomento diverso, che rispecchiano i molteplici interessi
di chi li ha raccolti, così come si sono evoluti nel corso di una vita:
politica, sociologia, religione, in una ricca raccolta di monografie, miscellanee
e periodici. Opere: “Giacomo Aconcio,” Milano, F.lli Bocca, “L'interpretazione
baconiana delle favole antiche,” Milano, F.lli Bocca, “Francesco Bacone: dalla
magia alla scienza,” Bari, Laterza, “Clavis Universalis: arti della memoria e
logica combinatoria da Lullo a Leibniz,” Milano, Napoli, R. Ricciardi, “I
filosofi e le machine,” Milano, Feltrinelli, Galilei, Roma-Milano, CEI-Compagnia
Edizioni Internazionali, “Il pensiero di Galilei: una antologia dagli scritti,
Torino, Loescher Editore, “Le sterminate antichità: studi vichiani,” Pisa,
Nistri-Lischi, Storia e filosofia: saggi sulla storiografia filosofica, Torino,
Einaudi, Aspetti della rivoluzione scientifica, Napoli, A. Morano, La
rivoluzione scientifica: da Copernico a Newton, Torino, Loescher, Pisa,
Edizioni ETS, “Immagini della scienza,” Roma,
Editori Riuniti, “I segni del tempo: storia della Terra e storia delle nazioni
da Hooke a Vico,” Milano, Feltrinelli, “I
ragni e le formiche: un'apologia della storia della scienza,” Bologna, Il
Mulino, “Storia della scienza moderna e contemporanea,” Torino, Utet, “La scienza
e la filosofia dei moderni: aspetti della rivoluzione scientifica,” Torino,
Bollati Boringhieri, “Paragone degli ingegni moderni e postmoderni,”Bologna, Il
Mulino, “Il passato, la memoria, l'oblio: sei saggi di storia delle idee,
Bologna, Il Mulino (Premio Viareggio) “La filosofia,” Torino, Utet, “Naufragi
senza spettatore: l'idea di progresso,” Bologna, Il Mulino, “La nascita della
scienza moderna in Europa,” Roma, Laterza, “Le sterminate antichità e nuovi
saggi vichiani,” Scandicci, La Nuova Italia, “Un altro presente: saggi sulla
storia della filosofia,” Bologna, Il Mulino, Bambini, sogni, furori: tre
lezioni di storia delle idee, Milano, Feltrinelli, Il tempo dei maghi:
Rinascimento e modernità, Milano, R. Cortina, Speranze, Bologna, Il Mulino, Mangiare,
Bologna, Il Mulino, Un breve viaggio e
altre storie: le guerre, gli uomini, la memoria, Milano, R. Cortina. Premio
letterario Viareggio-Rèpaci, su premioletterarioviareggiorepaci.it. Vincitori
del Premio Musatti su SpiWebSocietà
Psicoanalitica Italiana. 15 gennaio .
Inventario del Fondo archivistico , su opac.museogalileo.it. Fondo librario: le monografie moderne , su
opac.museogalileo.it. Fondo librario: le
miscellanee , su opac.museogalileo.it.
Fondo librario: i periodici , su opac.museogalileo.it. Storia della filosofia, Storia della scienza:
saggi in onore di Paolo Rossi, Antonello La Vergata e Alessandro Pagnini, Nuova
Italia, Firenze, Segni e percorsi della modernità: saggi in onore di Paolo
Rossi, Ferdinando Abbri e Marco Segala, Dipartimento di Studi Filosofici
dell'Siena, Antonio Rainone, «Rossi Monti, Paolo» in Enciclopedia
ItalianaVI Appendice, Roma, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana, John L.
Heilbron , Advancements of learning: essays in honour of Paolo Rossi, Firenze,
L.S. Olschki, Ferdinando Abbri, Paolo Rossi, in Nuncius, «Rossi (propr. Rossi
Monti), Paolo» in Dizionario di filosofia, Roma, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia
Italiana, Paolo Rossi, un maestro, Pisa, Edizioni della Normale, Pietro Rossi,
Tra Banfi e Garin: la formazione filosofica di Paolo Rossi, in Rivista di filosofia,
Treccani.itEnciclopedie, Istituto
dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Paolo Rossi
Monti, in Enciclopedia Italiana, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Dizionario
biografico degli italiani, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. Paolo Rossi Monti, su
siusa.archivi.beniculturali.it, Sistema Informativo Unificato per le
Soprintendenze Archivistiche. Opere di
Paolo Rossi Monti, su openMLOL, Horizons Unlimited srl. Registrazioni di Paolo Rossi Monti, su
RadioRadicale.it, Radio Radicale. Sito
ufficiale Paolo Rossi, su paolorossimonti.altervista.org. Biografia
dell'enciclopedia multimediale RAI delle scienze filosofiche, su emsf.rai.it. Rassegna
stampa del sito web italiano per la filosofia, su lgxserver.uniba.it. Per una
scienza libera, intervista a Paolo Rossi. Opere di Paolo Rossi su
StoriaModerna.it, su stmoderna.it. intervista, Società Psicoanalitica Italiana,
videointervista, Paolo Rossi: memoria e reminiscenza, sul RAI Filosofia, su filosofia.rai.it. Il Fondo
Rossi nella biblioteca del Museo Galileo, su museogalileo.it.
mos -- meta-ethics. “philosophia moralis” was te traditional labeluntil
Nowell-Smith. Hare is professor of moral philosophy, not meta-ethics. Strictly,
‘philosophia practica’ as opposed to ‘philosophia speculativa’. Philosophia speculativa is distinguished
from philosophia
practica; the former is further differentiated into physica,
mathematica, and theologia; the latter into moralis, oeconomica and politica.
Surely the philosophical mode does not change
when he goes into ethics or other disciplines. Philosophy is ENTIRE. Ethics
relates to metaphysics, but this does not mean that the philosopher is a
moralist. In this respect, unlike, say Philippa Foot, Grice remains a
meta-ethicist. Grice is ‘meta-ethically’ an futilitarian, since he provides a
utilitarian backing of Kantian rationalism, within his empiricist, naturalist,
temperament. For Grice it is complicated, since there is an ethical or
practical side even to an eschatological argument. Grice’s views on ethics are
Oxonian. At Oxford, meta-ethics is a generational thing: there’s Grice, and the
palaeo-Gricieans, and the post-Gricieans. There’s Hampshire, and Hare, and
Nowell-Smith, and Warnock. P. H. Nowell Smith felt overwhelmed by Grice’s
cleverness and they would hardly engage in meta-ethical questions. But Nowell
Smith felt that Grice was ‘too clever.’ Grice objected Hare’s use of
descriptivism and Strawsons use of definite descriptor. Grice preferred to say
“the the.”. “Surely Hare is wrong when sticking with his anti-descriptivist
diatribe. Even his dictum is descriptive!” Grice was amused that it all started
with Abbott BEFORE 1879, since Abbott’s first attempt was entitled, “Kant’s
theory of ethics, or practical philosophy” (1873). ”! Grices explorations on
morals are language based. With a substantial knowledge of the classical
languages (that are so good at verb systems and modes like the optative, that
English lacks), Grice explores modals like should, (Hampshire) ought to
(Hare) and, must (Grice ‒ necessity). Grice is well aware of Hares
reflections on the neustic qualifications on the phrastic. The imperative has
usually been one source for the philosophers concern with the language of
morals. Grice attempts to balance this with a similar exploration on good,
now regarded as the value-paradeigmatic notion par excellence. We cannot
understand, to echo Strawson, the concept of a person unless we understand the
concept of a good person, i.e. the philosopher’s conception of a good
person. Morals is very Oxonian. There were in Grices time only
three chairs of philosophy at Oxford: the three W: the Waynflete chair of
metaphysical philosophy, the Wykeham chair of logic (not philosophy, really),
and the White chair of moral philosophy. Later, the Wilde chair of
philosophical psychology was created. Grice was familiar with Austin’s
cavalier attitude to morals as Whites professor of moral philosophy, succeeding
Kneale. When Hare succeeds Austin, Grice knows that it is time to play
with the neustic implicaturum! Grices approach to morals is very
meta-ethical and starts with a fastidious (to use Blackburns characterisation,
not mine!) exploration of modes related to propositional phrases involving
should, ought to, and must. For Hampshire, should is the moral word par
excellence. For Hare, it is ought. For Grice, it is only must that
preserves that sort of necessity that, as a Kantian rationalist, he is looking
for. However, Grice hastens to add that whatever hell say about the buletic,
practical or boulomaic must must also apply to the doxastic must, as in What
goes up must come down. That he did not hesitate to use necessity operators is
clear from his axiomatic treatment, undertaken with Code, on Aristotelian categories
of izzing and hazzing. To understand Grices view on ethics, we should
return to the idea of creature construction in more detail. Suppose we are
genitors-demigods-designing living creatures, creatures Grice calls Ps. To
design a type of P is to specify a diagram and table for that type plus
evaluative procedures, if any. The design is implemented in animal stuff-flesh
and bones typically. Let us focus on one type of P-a very sophisticated type
that Grice, borrowing from Locke, calls very intelligent rational Ps. Let me be
a little more explicit, and a great deal more speculative, about the possible
relation to ethics of my programme for philosophical psychology. I shall
suppose that the genitorial programme has been realized to the point at which we
have designed a class of Ps which, nearly following Locke, I might call very
intelligent rational Ps. These Ps will be capable of putting themselves in the
genitorial position, of asking how, if they were constructing themselves with a
view to their own survival, they would execute this task; and, if we have done
our work aright, their answer will be the same as ours . We might, indeed,
envisage the contents of a highly general practical manual, which these Ps
would be in a position to compile. The contents of the initial manual would
have various kinds of generality which are connected with familiar discussions
of universalizability. The Ps have, so far, been endowed only with the
characteristics which belong to the genitorial justified psychological theory;
so the manual will have to be formulated in terms of that theory, together with
the concepts involved in the very general description of livingconditions which
have been used to set up that theory; the manual will therefore have conceptual
generality. There will be no way of singling out a special subclass of
addressees, so the injunctions of the manual will have to be addressed,
indifferently, to any very intelligent rational P, and will thus have
generality of form. And since the manual can be thought of as being composed by
each of the so far indistinguishable Ps, no P would include in the manual
injunctions prescribing a certain line of conduct in circumstances to which he
was not likely to be Subjects; nor indeed could he do so even if he would. So the
circumstances for which conduct is prescribed could be presumed to be such as
to be satisfied, from time to time, by any addressee; the manual, then, will
have generality of application. Such a manual might, perhaps, without
ineptitude be called an immanuel; and the very intelligent rational Ps, each of
whom both composes it and from time to time heeds it, might indeed be ourselves
(in our better moments, of course). Refs.: Most of Grice’s theorizing on ethics
counts as ‘meta-ethic,’ especially in connection with R. M. Hare, but also with
less prescriptivist Oxonian philosophers such as Nowell-Smith, with his
bestseller for Penguin, Austin, Warnock, and Hampshire. Keywords then are
‘ethic,’ and ‘moral.’ There are many essays on both Kantotle, i.e. on Aristotle
and Kant. The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC. mos, -- Grice:
“Roman can be tricky, since they like to pluralise this, and in the many
tracts, “De moribus”!” – mos: ethos -- meta-ethics: morality, an
informal public system applying to all rational persons, governing behavior
that affects others, having the lessening of evil or harm as its goal, and
including what are commonly known as the moral rules, moral ideals, and moral
virtues. To say that it is a public system means that all those to whom it
applies must understand it and that it must not be irrational for them to use
it in deciding what to do and in judging others to whom the system applies.
Games are the paradigm cases of public systems; all games have a point and the
rules of a game apply to all who play it. All players know the point of the
game and its rules, and it is not irrational for them to be guided by the point
and rules and to judge the behavior of other players by them. To say that
morality is informal means that there is no decision procedure or authority
that can settle all its controversial questions. Morality thus resembles a
backyard game of basketball more than a professional game. Although there is
overwhelming agreement on most moral matters, certain controversial questions
must be settled in an ad hoc fashion or not settled at all. For example, when,
if ever, abortion is acceptable is an unresolvable moral matter, but each
society and religion can adopt its own position. That morality has no one in a
position of authority is one of the most important respects in which it differs
from law and religion. Although morality must include the commonly accepted
moral rules such as those prohibiting killing and deceiving, different
societies can interpret these rules somewhat differently. They can also differ
in their views about the scope of morality, i.e., about whether morality
protects newborns, fetuses, or non-human animals. Thus different societies can
have somewhat different moralities, although this difference has limits. Also
within each society, a person may have his own view about when it is justified
to break one of the rules, e.g., about how much harm would have to be prevented
in order to justify deceiving someone. Thus one person’s morality may differ
somewhat from another’s, but both will agree on the overwhelming number of
non-controversial cases. A moral theory is an attempt to describe, explain, and
if possible justify, morality. Unfortunately, most moral theories attempt to
generate some simplified moral code, rather than to describe the complex moral
system that is already in use. Morality does not resolve all disputes. Morality
does not require one always to act so as to produce the best consequences or to
act only in those ways that one would will everyone to act. Rather morality
includes both moral rules that no one should transgress and moral ideals that
all are encouraged to follow, but much of what one does will not be governed by
morality. H. P. Grice, “Meta-ethics in postwar Oxford philosophy: Hare,
Nowell-Smith, myself, and others!” mos,
ethosmeta-ethical -- meta-ethics:, Grice: “The Romans should have a verb for
‘mos,’ since it’s very nominational!” Surely what we need is something like
Austin’s ‘doing things.’” mos ,
mōris, m. etym. dub.; perh. root ma-, measure; cf.: maturus, matutinus; prop.,
a measuring or guiding rule of life; hence, I.manner, custom, way, usage,
practice, fashion, wont, as determined not by the laws, but by men's will and
pleasure, humor, self-will, caprice (class.; cf.: consuetudo, usus). I. Lit.:
“opsequens oboediensque'st mori atque imperiis patris,” Plaut. Bacch. 3, 3, 54: Grice: “Cicero was
being brilliant when he found that ‘mos’ nicely translates Grecian ‘ethos’cf.
Grice’s ethology. Ethologica --
Philosophical ethology -- 1 the subfield of psychology that traces the
development over time of moral reasoning and opinions in the lives of
individuals this subdiscipline includes work of Jean Piaget, Lawrence Kohlberg,
and Carol Gilligan; 2 the part of philosophy where philosophy of mind and ethics
overlap, which concerns all the psychological issues relevant to morality.
There are many different psychological matters relevant to ethics, and each may
be relevant in more than one way. Different ethical theories imply different
sorts of connections. So moral psychology includes work of many and diverse
kinds. But several traditional clusters of concern are evident. Some elements
of moral psychology consider the psychological matters relevant to metaethical
issues, i.e., to issues about the general nature of moral truth, judgment, and
knowledge. Different metaethical theories invoke mental phenomena in different
ways: noncognitivism maintains that sentences expressing moral judgments do not
function to report truths or falsehoods, but rather, e.g., to express certain
emotions or to prescribe certain actions. So some forms of noncognitivism imply
that an understanding of certain sorts of emotions, or of special activities
like prescribing that may involve particular psychological elements, is crucial
to a full understanding of how ethical sentences are meaningful. Certain forms
of cognitivism, the view that moral declarative sentences do express truths or
falsehoods, imply that moral facts consist of psychological facts, that for
instance moral judgments consist of expressions of positive psychological
attitudes of some particular kind toward the objects of those judgments. And an
understanding of psychological phenomena like sentiment is crucial according to
certain sorts of projectivism, which hold that the supposed moral properties of
things are mere misleading projections of our sentiments onto the objects of
those sentiments. Certain traditional moral sense theories and certain
traditional forms of intuitionism have held that special psychological faculties
are crucial for our epistemic access to moral truth. Particular views in
normative ethics, particular views about the moral status of acts, persons, and
other targets of normative evaluation, also often suggest that an understanding
of certain psychological matters is crucial to ethics. Actions, intentions, and
character are some of the targets of evaluation of normative ethics, and their
proper understanding involves many issues in philosophy of mind. Also, many
normative theorists have maintained that there is a close connection between
pleasure, happiness, or desiresatisfaction and a person’s good, and these
things are also a concern of philosophy of mind. In addition, the rightness of
actions is often held to be closely connected to the motives, beliefs, and
other psychological phenomena that lie behind those actions. Various other
traditional philosophical concerns link ethical and psychological issues: the
nature of the patterns in the long-term development in individuals of moral
opinions and reasoning, the appropriate form for moral education and
punishment, the connections between obligation and motivation, i.e., between
moral reasons and psychological causes, and the notion of free will and its
relation to moral responsibility and autonomy. Some work in philosophy of mind
also suggests that moral phenomena, or at least normative phenomena of some
kind, play a crucial role in illuminating or constituting psychological
phenomena of various kinds, but the traditional concern of moral psychology has
been with the articulation of the sort of philosophy of mind that can be useful
to ethics. Refs.: H. P. Grice,
“Meta-ethics in post-war Oxford philosophy: Hare, Nowell-Smith, myself, and
others!” H. P. Grice, “The morality of morality.” H. P. Grice, “Lorenz and the
‘ethologie der ganse.’” costumeGrice: “Can a single individual have an
idio-mos, a practice? He certainly can device a set of pratices that nobody
ever puts into use, as in my New Hightway Code, or my Deutero-Esperanto.” moral
scepticism, any metaethical view that raises fundamental doubts about morality
as a whole. Different kinds of doubts lead to different kinds of moral
skepticism. The primary kinds of moral skepticism are epistemological. Moral
justification skepticism is the claim that nobody ever has any or adequate
justification for believing any substantive moral claim. Moral knowledge
skepticism is the claim that nobody ever knows that any substantive moral claim
is true. If knowledge implies justification, as is often assumed, then moral
justification skepticism implies moral knowledge skepticism. But even if
knowledge requires justification, it requires more, so moral knowledge
skepticism does not imply moral justification skepticism. Another kind of
skeptical view in metaethics rests on linguistic analysis. Some emotivists,
expressivists, and prescriptivists argue that moral claims like “Cheating is
morally wrong” resemble expressions of emotion or desire like “Boo, cheating”
or prescriptions for action like “Don’t cheat”, which are neither true nor
false, so moral claims themselves are neither true nor false. This linguistic
moral skepticism, which is sometimes called noncognitivism, implies moral
knowledge skepticism if knowledge implies truth. Even if such linguistic
analyses are rejected, one can still hold that no moral properties or facts
really exist. This ontological moral skepticism can be combined with the
linguistic view that moral claims assert moral properties and facts to yield an
error theory that all positive moral claims are false. A different kind of
doubt about morality is often raised by asking, “Why should I be moral?”
Practical moral skepticism answers that there is not always any reason or any
adequate reason to be moral or to do what is morally required. This view
concerns reasons to act rather than reasons to believe. Moral skepticism of all
these kinds is often seen as immoral, but moral skeptics can act and be
motivated and even hold moral beliefs in much the same way as non-skeptics.
Moral skeptics just deny that their or anyone else’s moral beliefs are
justified or known or true, or that they have adequate reason to be moral. moral
status, the suitability of a being to be viewed as an appropriate object of
direct moral concern; the nature or degree of a being’s ability to count as a
ground of claims against moral agents; the moral standing, rank, or importance
of a kind of being; the condition of being a moral patient; moral
considerability. Ordinary moral reflection involves considering others. But which
others ought to be considered? And how are the various objects of moral
consideration to be weighed against one another? Anything might be the topic of
moral discussion, but not everything is thought to be an appropriate object of
direct moral concern. If there are any ethical constraints on how we may treat
a ceramic plate, these seem to derive from considerations about other beings,
not from the interests or good or nature of the plate. The same applies,
presumably, to a clod of earth. Many philosophers view a living but insentient
being, such as a dandelion, in the same way; others have doubts. According to
some, even sentient animal life is little more deserving of moral consideration
than the clod or the dandelion. This tradition, which restricts significant
moral status to humans, has come under vigorous and varied attack by defenders
of animal liberation. This attack criticizes speciesism, and argues that
“humanism” is analogous to theories that illegitimately base moral status on
race, gender, or social class. Some philosophers have referred to beings that
are appropriate objects of direct moral concern as “moral patients.” Moral
agents are those beings whose actions are subject to moral evaluation;
analogously, moral patients would be those beings whose suffering in the sense
of being the objects of the actions of moral agents permits or demands moral
evaluation. Others apply the label ‘moral patients’ more narrowly, just to
those beings that are appropriate objects of direct moral concern but are not
also moral agents. The issue of moral status concerns not only whether beings
count at all morally, but also to what degree they count. After all, beings who
are moral patients might still have their claims outweighed by the preferred
claims of other beings who possess some special moral status. We might, with
Nozick, propose “utilitarianism for animals, Kantianism for people.” Similarly,
the bodily autonomy argument in defense of abortion, made famous by Thomson,
does not deny that the fetus is a moral patient, but insists that her/his/its
claims are limited by the pregnant woman’s prior claim to control her bodily
destiny. It has often been thought that moral status should be tied to the
condition of “personhood.” The idea has been either that only persons are moral
patients, or that persons possess a special moral status that makes them
morally more important than nonpersons. Personhood, on such theories, is a
minimal condition for moral patiency. Why? Moral patiency is said to be
“correlative” with moral agency: a creature has both or neither. Alternatively,
persons have been viewed not as the only moral patients, but as a specially
privileged elite among moral patients, possessing rights as well as
interests. mos, ethos: ethos: Grice: “I love Lorenz, and he loved his geese.”
-- Grice: “In German, ‘deutsche’ means
‘tribal.’” -- philosophical ethologyphrase used by Grice for his creature
construction routine. ethical constructivism, a form of anti-realism about ethics
which holds that there are moral facts and truths, but insists that these facts
and truths are in some way constituted by or dependent on our moral beliefs,
reactions, or attitudes. For instance, an ideal observer theory that represents
the moral rightness and wrongness of an act in terms of the moral approval and
disapproval that an appraiser would have under suitably idealized conditions
can be understood as a form of ethical constructivism. Another form of
constructivism identifies the truth of a moral belief with its being part of
the appropriate system of beliefs, e.g., of a system of moral and nonmoral
beliefs that is internally coherent. Such a view would maintain a coherence
theory of moral truth. Moral relativism is a constructivist view that allows
for a plurality of moral facts and truths. Thus, if the idealizing conditions
appealed to in an ideal observer theory allow that different appraisers can
have different reactions to the same actions under ideal conditions, then that
ideal observer theory will be a version of moral relativism as well as of
ethical constructivism. Or, if different systems of moral beliefs satisfy the
appropriate epistemic conditions e.g. are equally coherent, then the truth or
falsity of particular moral beliefs will have to be relativized to different
moral systems or codes. -- ethical objectivism, the view that the objects of
the most basic concepts of ethics which may be supposed to be values,
obligations, duties, oughts, rights, or what not exist, or that facts about
them hold, objectively and that similarly worded ethical statements by
different persons make the same factual claims and thus do not concern merely
the speaker’s feelings. To say that a fact is objective, or that something has
objective existence, is usually to say that its holding or existence is not
derivative from its being thought to hold or exist. In the Scholastic
terminology still current in the seventeenth century ‘objective’ had the more
or less contrary meaning of having status only as an object of thought. In
contrast, fact, or a thing’s existence, is subjective if it holds or exists
only in the sense that it is thought to hold or exist, or that it is merely a
convenient human posit for practical purposes. A fact holds, or an object
exists, intersubjectively if somehow its acknowledgment is binding on all
thinking subjects or all subjects in some specified group, although it does not
hold or exist independently of their thinking about it. Some thinkers suppose
that intersubjectivity is all that can ever properly be meant by objectivity. Objectivism
may be naturalist or non-naturalist. The naturalist objectivist believes that
values, duties, or whatever are natural phenomena detectable by introspection,
perception, or scientific inference. Thus values may be identified with certain
empirical qualities of anybody’s experience, or duties with empirical facts
about the effects of action, e.g. as promoting or hindering social cohesion.
The non-naturalist objectivist eschewing what Moore called the naturalistic
fallacy believes that values or obligations or whatever items he thinks most
basic in ethics exist independently of any belief about them, but that their
existence is not a matter of any ordinary fact detectable in the above ways but
can be revealed to ethical intuition as standing in a necessary but not
analytic relation to natural phenomena. ‘Ethical subjectivism’ usually means
the doctrine that ethical statements are simply reports on the speaker’s
feelings though, confusingly enough, such statements may be objectively true or
false. Perhaps it ought to mean the doctrine that nothing is good or bad but
thinking makes it so. Attitude theories of morality, for which such statements
express, rather than report upon, the speaker’s feelings, are also, despite the
objections of their proponents, sometimes called subjectivist. In a more
popular usage an objective matter of fact is one on which all reasonable
persons can be expected to agree, while a matter is subjective if various
alternative opinions can be accepted as reasonable. What is subjective in this
sense may be quite objective in the more philosophical sense in question
above. -- ethics, the philosophical
study of morality. The word is also commonly used interchangeably with
‘morality’ to mean the subject matter of this study; and sometimes it is used
more narrowly to mean the moral principles of a particular tradition, group, or
individual. Christian ethics and Albert Schweitzer’s ethics are examples. In
this article the word will be used exclusively to mean the philosophical study.
Ethics, along with logic, metaphysics, and epistemology, is one of the main
branches of philosophy. It corresponds, in the traditional division of the
field into formal, natural, and moral philosophy, to the last of these
disciplines. It can in turn be divided into the general study of goodness, the
general study of right action, applied ethics, metaethics, moral psychology,
and the metaphysics of moral responsibility. These divisions are not sharp, and
many important studies in ethics, particularly those that examine or develop
whole systems of ethics, are interdivisional. Nonetheless, they facilitate the
identification of different problems, movements, and schools within the
discipline. The first two, the general study of goodness and the general study
of right action, constitute the main business of ethics. Correlatively, its
principal substantive questions are what ends we ought, as fully rational human
beings, to choose and pursue and what moral principles should govern our
choices and pursuits. How these questions are related is the discipline’s
principal structural question, and structural differences among systems of
ethics reflect different answers to this question. In contemporary ethics, the
study of structure has come increasingly to the fore, especially as a
preliminary to the general study of right action. In the natural order of
exposition, however, the substantive questions come first. Goodness and the
question of ends. Philosophers have typically treated the question of the ends
we ought to pursue in one of two ways: either as a question about the
components of a good life or as a question about what sorts of things are good
in themselves. On the first way of treating the question, it is assumed that we
naturally seek a good life; hence, determining its components amounts to
determining, relative to our desire for such a life, what ends we ought to
pursue. On the second way, no such assumption about human nature is made;
rather it is assumed that whatever is good in itself is worth choosing or pursuing.
The first way of treating the question leads directly to the theory of human
well-being. The second way leads directly to the theory of intrinsic value. The
first theory originated in ancient ethics, and eudaimonia was the Grecian word
for its subject, a word usually tr. ‘happiness,’ but sometimes tr.
‘flourishing’ in order to make the question of human well-being seem more a
matter of how well a person is doing than how good he is feeling. These
alternatives reflect the different conceptions of human well-being that inform
the two major views within the theory: the view that feeling good or pleasure
is the essence of human well-being and the view that doing well or excelling at
things worth doing is its essence. The first view is hedonism in its classical
form. Its most famous exponent among the ancients was Epicurus. The second view
is perfectionism, a view that is common to several schools of ancient ethics.
Its adherents include Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics. Among the moderns, the
best-known defenders of classical hedonism and perfectionism are respectively
J. S. Mill and Nietzsche. Although these two views differ on the question of
what human well-being essentially consists in, neither thereby denies that the
other’s answer has a place in a good human life. Indeed, mature statements of
each typically assign the other’s answer an ancillary place. Thus, hedonism, as
expounded by Epicurus, takes excelling at things worth doing exercising one’s intellectual powers and
moral virtues in exemplary and fruitful ways, e.g. as the tried and true means to experiencing
life’s most satisfying pleasures. And perfectionism, as developed in
Aristotle’s ethics, underscores the importance of pleasure the deep satisfaction that comes from doing
an important job well, e.g. as a natural
concomitant of achieving excellence in things that matter. The two views, as
expressed in these mature statements, differ not so much in the kinds of
activities they take to be central to a good life as in the ways they explain
the goodness of such a life. The chief difference between them, then, is
philosophical rather than prescriptive. The second theory, the theory of
intrinsic value, also has roots in ancient ethics, specifically, Plato’s theory
of Forms. But unlike Plato’s theory, the basic tenets of which include certain
doctrines about the reality and transcendence of value, the theory of intrinsic
value neither contains nor presupposes any metaphysical theses. At issue in the
theory is what things are good in themselves, and one can take a position on
this issue without committing oneself to any thesis about the reality or
unreality of goodness or about its transcendence or immanence. A list of the
different things philosophers have considered good in themselves would include life,
happiness, pleasure, knowledge, virtue, friendship, beauty, and harmony. The
list could easily be extended. An interest in what constitutes the goodness of
the various items on the list has brought philosophers to focus primarily on
the question of whether something unites them. The opposing views on this
question are monism and pluralism. Monists affirm the list’s unity; pluralists
deny it. Plato, for instance, was a monist. He held that the goodness of
everything good in itself consisted in harmony and therefore each such thing
owed its goodness to its being harmonious. Alternatively, some philosophers
have proposed pleasure as the sole constituent of goodness. Indeed, conceiving
of pleasure as a particular kind of experience or state of consciousness, they
have proposed this kind of experience as the only thing good in itself and
characterized all other good things as instrumentally good, as owing their
goodness to their being sources of pleasure. Thus, hedonism too can be a
species of monism. In this case, though, one must distinguish between the view
that it is one’s own experiences of pleasure that are intrinsically good and
the view that anyone’s experiences of pleasure, indeed, any sentient being’s
experiences of pleasure, are intrinsically good. The former is called by
Sidgwick egoistic hedonism, the latter universal hedonism. This distinction can
be made general, as a distinction between egoistic and universal views of what
is good in itself or, as philosophers now commonly say, between agent-relative
and agent-neutral value. As such, it indicates a significant point of
disagreement in the theory of intrinsic value, a disagreement in which the
seeming arbitrariness and blindness of egoism make it harder to defend. In
drawing this conclusion, however, one must be careful not to mistake these
egoistic views for views in the theory of human well-being, for each set of
views represents a set of alternative answers to a different question. One must
be careful, in other words, not to infer from the greater defensibility of
universalism vis-à-vis egoism that universalism is the predominant view in the
general study of goodness. Right action. The general study of right action
concerns the principles of right and wrong that govern our choices and
pursuits. In modern ethics these principles are typically given a jural
conception. Accordingly, they are understood to constitute a moral code that
defines the duties of men and women who live together in fellowship. This
conception of moral principles is chiefly due to the influence of Christianity
in the West, though some of its elements were already present in Stoic ethics.
Its ascendancy in the general study of right action puts the theory of duty at
the center of that study. The theory has two parts: the systematic exposition
of the moral code that defines our duties; and its justification. The first
part, when fully developed, presents complete formulations of the fundamental
principles of right and wrong and shows how they yield all moral duties. The
standard model is an axiomatic system in mathematics, though some philosophers
have proposed a technical system of an applied science, such as medicine or
strategy, as an alternative. The second part, if successful, establishes the
authority of the principles and so validates the code. Various methods and
criteria of justification are commonly used; no single one is canonical.
Success in establishing the principles’ authority depends on the soundness of
the argument that proceeds from whatever method or criterion is used. One
traditional criterion is implicit in the idea of an axiomatic system. On this
criterion, the fundamental principles of right and wrong are authoritative in
virtue of being self-evident truths. That is, they are regarded as comparable
to axioms not only in being the first principles of a deductive system but also
in being principles whose truth can be seen immediately upon reflection. Use of
this criterion to establish the principles’ authority is the hallmark of
intuitionism. Once one of the dominant views in ethics, its position in the
discipline has now been seriously eroded by a strong, twentieth-century tide of
skepticism about all claims of self-evidence. Currently, the most influential
method of justification consistent with using the model of an axiomatic system
to expound the morality of right and wrong draws on the jural conception of its
principles. On this method, the principles are interpreted as expressions of a
legislative will, and accordingly their authority derives from the sovereignty
of the person or collective whose will they are taken to express. The oldest
example of the method’s use is the divine command theory. On this theory, moral
principles are taken to be laws issued by God to humanity, and their authority
thus derives from God’s supremacy. The theory is the original Christian source
of the principles’ jural conception. The rise of secular thought since the
Enlightenment has, however, limited its appeal. Later examples, which continue
to attract broad interest and discussion, are formalism and contractarianism.
Formalism is best exemplified in Kant’s ethics. It takes a moral principle to
be a precept that satisfies the formal criteria of a universal law, and it
takes formal criteria to be the marks of pure reason. Consequently, moral
principles are laws that issue from reason. As Kant puts it, they are laws that
we, as rational beings, give to ourselves and that regulate our conduct insofar
as we engage each other’s rational nature. They are laws for a republic of
reason or, as Kant says, a kingdom of ends whose legislature comprises all
rational beings. Through this ideal, Kant makes intelligible and forceful the
otherwise obscure notion that moral principles derive their authority from the
sovereignty of reason. Contractarianism also draws inspiration from Kant’s
ethics as well as from the social contract theories of Locke and Rousseau. Its
fullest and most influential statement appears in the work of Rawls. On this
view, moral principles represent the ideal terms of social cooperation for
people who live together in fellowship and regard each other as equals.
Specifically, they are taken to be the conditions of an ideal agreement among
such people, an agreement that they would adopt if they met as an assembly of
equals to decide collectively on the social arrangements governing their
relations and reached their decision as a result of open debate and rational
deliberation. The authority of moral principles derives, then, from the
fairness of the procedures by which the terms of social cooperation would be
arrived at in this hypothetical constitutional convention and the assumption
that any rational individual who wanted to live peaceably with others and who
imagined himself a party to this convention would, in view of the fairness of
its procedures, assent to its results. It derives, that is, from the
hypothetical consent of the governed. Philosophers who think of a moral code on
the model of a technical system of an applied science use an entirely different
method of justification. In their view, just as the principles of medicine
represent knowledge about how best to promote health, so the principles of
right and wrong represent knowledge about how best to promote the ends of
morality. These philosophers, then, have a teleological conception of the code.
Our fundamental duty is to promote certain ends, and the principles of right
and wrong organize and direct our efforts in this regard. What justifies the
principles, on this view, is that the ends they serve are the right ones to
promote and the actions they prescribe are the best ways to promote them. The
principles are authoritative, in other words, in virtue of the wisdom of their
prescriptions. Different teleological views in the theory of duty correspond to
different answers to the question of what the right ends to promote are. The
most common answer is happiness; and the main division among the corresponding
views mirrors the distinction in the theory of intrinsic value between egoism
and universalism. Thus, egoism and universalism in the theory of duty hold,
respectively, that the fundamental duty of morality is to promote, as best as
one can, one’s own happiness and that it is to promote, as best as one can, the
happiness of humanity. The former is ethical egoism and is based on the ideal
of rational self-love. The latter is utilitarianism and is based on the ideal
of rational benevolence. Ethical egoism’s most famous exponents in modern
philosophy are Hobbes and Spinoza. It has had few distinguished defenders since
their time. Bentham and J. S. Mill head the list of distinguished defenders of
utilitarianism. The view continues to be enormously influential. On these
teleological views, answers to questions about the ends we ought to pursue
determine the principles of right and wrong. Put differently, the general study
of right action, on these views, is subordinate to the general study of
goodness. This is one of the two leading answers to the structural question
about how the two studies are related. The other is that the general study of
right action is to some extent independent of the general study of goodness. On
views that represent this answer, some principles of right and wrong, notably
principles of justice and honesty, prescribe actions even though more evil than
good would result from doing them. These views are deontological. Fiat justitia
ruat coelum captures their spirit. The opposition between teleology and
deontology in ethics underlies many of the disputes in the general study of
right action. The principal substantive and structural questions of ethics
arise not only with respect to the conduct of human life generally but also
with respect to specific walks of life such as medicine, law, journalism,
engineering, and business. The examination of these questions in relation to
the common practices and traditional codes of such professions and occupations
has resulted in the special studies of applied ethics. In these studies, ideas
and theories from the general studies of goodness and right action are applied
to particular circumstances and problems of some profession or occupation, and
standard philosophical techniques are used to define, clarify, and organize the
ethical issues found in its domain. In medicine, in particular, where rapid
advances in technology create, overnight, novel ethical problems on matters of
life and death, the study of biomedical ethics has generated substantial
interest among practitioners and scholars alike. Metaethics. To a large extent,
the general studies of goodness and right action and the special studies of
applied ethics consist in systematizing, deepening, and revising our beliefs
about how we ought to conduct our lives. At the same time, it is characteristic
of philosophers, when reflecting on such systems of belief, to examine the
nature and grounds of these beliefs. These questions, when asked about ethical
beliefs, define the field of metaethics. The relation of this field to the
other studies is commonly represented by taking the other studies to constitute
the field of ethics proper and then taking metaethics to be the study of the
concepts, methods of justification, and ontological assumptions of the field of
ethics proper. Accordingly, metaethics can proceed from either an interest in
the epistemology of ethics or an interest in its metaphysics. On the first
approach, the study focuses on questions about the character of ethical
knowledge. Typically, it concentrates on the simplest ethical beliefs, such as
‘Stealing is wrong’ and ‘It is better to give than to receive’, and proceeds by
analyzing the concepts in virtue of which these beliefs are ethical and
examining their logical basis. On the second approach, the study focuses on
questions about the existence and character of ethical properties. Typically,
it concentrates on the most general ethical predicates such as goodness and
wrongfulness and considers whether there truly are ethical properties
represented by these predicates and, if so, whether and how they are interwoven
into the natural world. The two approaches are complementary. Neither dominates
the other. The epistemological approach is comparative. It looks to the most
successful branches of knowledge, the natural sciences and pure mathematics,
for paradigms. The former supplies the paradigm of knowledge that is based on
observation of natural phenomena; the latter supplies the paradigm of knowledge
that seemingly results from the sheer exercise of reason. Under the influence
of these paradigms, three distinct views have emerged: naturalism, rationalism,
and noncognitivism. Naturalism takes ethical knowledge to be empirical and
accordingly models it on the paradigm of the natural sciences. Ethical
concepts, on this view, concern natural phenomena. Rationalism takes ethical
knowledge to be a priori and accordingly models it on the paradigm of pure
mathematics. Ethical concepts, on this view, concern morality understood as
something completely distinct from, though applicable to, natural phenomena,
something whose content and structure can be apprehended by reason independently
of sensory inputs. Noncognitivism, in opposition to these other views, denies
that ethics is a genuine branch of knowledge or takes it to be a branch of
knowledge only in a qualified sense. In either case, it denies that ethics is
properly modeled on science or mathematics. On the most extreme form of
noncognitivism, there are no genuine ethical concepts; words like ‘right’,
‘wrong’, ‘good’, and ‘evil’ have no cognitive meaning but rather serve to vent
feelings and emotions, to express decisions and commitments, or to influence
attitudes and dispositions. On less extreme forms, these words are taken to
have some cognitive meaning, but conveying that meaning is held to be decidedly
secondary to the purposes of venting feelings, expressing decisions, or
influencing attitudes. Naturalism is well represented in the work of Mill;
rationalism in the works of Kant and the intuitionists. And noncognitivism,
which did not emerge as a distinctive view until the twentieth century, is most
powerfully expounded in the works of C. L. Stevenson and Hare. Its central
tenets, however, were anticipated by Hume, whose skeptical attacks on
rationalism set the agenda for subsequent work in metaethics. The metaphysical
approach is centered on the question of objectivity, the question of whether
ethical predicates represent real properties of an external world or merely
apparent or invented properties, properties that owe their existence to the
perception, feeling, or thought of those who ascribe them. Two views dominate
this approach. The first, moral realism, affirms the real existence of ethical
properties. It takes them to inhere in the external world and thus to exist
independently of their being perceived. For moral realism, ethics is an
objective discipline, a discipline that promises discovery and confirmation of
objective truths. At the same time, moral realists differ fundamentally on the
question of the character of ethical properties. Some, such as Plato and Moore,
regard them as purely intellective and thus irreducibly distinct from empirical
properties. Others, such as Aristotle and Mill, regard them as empirical and
either reducible to or at least supervenient on other empirical properties. The
second view, moral subjectivism, denies the real existence of ethical properties.
On this view, to predicate, say, goodness of a person is to impose some
feeling, impulse, or other state of mind onto the world, much as one projects
an emotion onto one’s circumstances when one describes them as delightful or
sad. On the assumption of moral subjectivism, ethics is not a source of
objective truth. In ancient philosophy, moral subjectivism was advanced by some
of the Sophists, notably Protagoras. In modern philosophy, Hume expounded it in
the eighteenth century and Sartre in the twentieth century. Regardless of
approach, one and perhaps the central problem of metaethics is how value is
related to fact. On the epistemological approach, this problem is commonly
posed as the question of whether judgments of value are derivable from statements
of fact. Or, to be more exact, can there be a logically valid argument whose
conclusion is a judgment of value and all of whose premises are statements of
fact? On the metaphysical approach, the problem is commonly posed as the
question of whether moral predicates represent properties that are explicable
as complexes of empirical properties. At issue, in either case, is whether
ethics is an autonomous discipline, whether the study of moral values and
principles is to some degree independent of the study of observable properties
and events. A negative answer to these questions affirms the autonomy of
ethics; a positive answer denies ethics’ autonomy and implies that it is a
branch of the natural sciences. Moral psychology. Even those who affirm the autonomy
of ethics recognize that some facts, particularly facts of human psychology,
bear on the general studies of goodness and right action. No one maintains that
these studies float free of all conception of human appetite and passion or
that they presuppose no account of the human capacity for voluntary action. It
is generally recognized that an adequate understanding of desire, emotion,
deliberation, choice, volition, character, and personality is indispensable to
the theoretical treatment of human well-being, intrinsic value, and duty.
Investigations into the nature of these psychological phenomena are therefore
an essential, though auxiliary, part of ethics. They constitute the adjunct
field of moral psychology. One area of particular interest within this field is
the study of those capacities by virtue of which men and women qualify as moral
agents, beings who are responsible for their actions. This study is especially
important to the theory of duty since that theory, in modern philosophy,
characteristically assumes a strong doctrine of individual responsibility. That
is, it assumes principles of culpability for wrongdoing that require, as
conditions of justified blame, that the act of wrongdoing be one’s own and that
it not be done innocently. Only moral agents are capable of meeting these
conditions. And the presumption is that normal, adult human beings qualify as
moral agents whereas small children and nonhuman animals do not. The study then
focuses on those capacities that distinguish the former from the latter as
responsible beings. The main issue is whether the power of reason alone
accounts for these capacities. On one side of the issue are philosophers like
Kant who hold that it does. Reason, in their view, is both the pilot and the
engine of moral agency. It not only guides one toward actions in conformity
with one’s duty, but it also produces the desire to do one’s duty and can
invest that desire with enough strength to overrule conflicting impulses of
appetite and passion. On the other side are philosophers, such as Hume and
Mill, who take reason to be one of several capacities that constitute moral
agency. On their view, reason works strictly in the service of natural and
sublimated desires, fears, and aversions to produce intelligent action, to
guide its possessor toward the objects of those desires and away from the
objects of those fears. It cannot, however, by itself originate any desire or
fear. Thus, the desire to act rightly, the aversion to acting wrongly, which
are constituents of moral agency, are not products of reason but are instead
acquired through some mechanical process of socialization by which their
objects become associated with the objects of natural desires and aversions. On
one view, then, moral agency consists in the power of reason to govern
behavior, and being rational is thus sufficient for being responsible for one’s
actions. On the other view, moral agency consists in several things including
reason, but also including a desire to act rightly and an aversion to acting
wrongly that originate in natural desires and aversions. On this view, to be
responsible for one’s actions, one must not only be rational but also have
certain desires and aversions whose acquisition is not guaranteed by the
maturation of reason. Within moral psychology, one cardinal test of these views
is how well they can accommodate and explain such common experiences of moral
agency as conscience, weakness, and moral dilemma. At some point, however, the
views must be tested by questions about freedom. For one cannot be responsible
for one’s actions if one is incapable of acting freely, which is to say, of
one’s own free will. The capacity for free action is thus essential to moral
agency, and how this capacity is to be explained, whether it fits within a
deterministic universe, and if not, whether the notion of moral responsibility
should be jettisoned, are among the deepest questions that the student of moral
agency must face. What is more, they are not questions to which moral
psychology can furnish answers. At this point, ethics descends into
metaphysics. ethnography, an open-ended
family of techniques through which anthropologists investigate cultures; also,
the organized descriptions of other cultures that result from this method.
Cultural anthropology ethnology is based primarily on fieldwork through which
anthropologists immerse themselves in the life of a local culture village,
neighborhood and attempt to describe and interpret aspects of the culture.
Careful observation is one central tool of investigation. Through it the
anthropologist can observe and record various features of social life, e.g.
trading practices, farming techniques, or marriage arrangements. A second
central tool is the interview, through which the researcher explores the beliefs
and values of members of the local culture. Tools of historical research,
including particularly oral history, are also of use in ethnography, since the
cultural practices of interest often derive from a remote point in time. ethnology, the comparative and analytical
study of cultures; cultural anthroplogy. Anthropologists aim to describe and
interpret aspects of the culture of various social groups e.g., the hunter-gatherers of the Kalahari,
rice villages of the Chin. Canton Delta, or a community of physicists at
Livermore Laboratory. Topics of particular interest include religious beliefs,
linguistic practices, kinship arrangements, marriage patterns, farming
technology, dietary practices, gender relations, and power relations. Cultural
anthropology is generally conceived as an empirical science, and this raises
several methodological and conceptual difficulties. First is the role of the
observer. The injection of an alien observer into the local culture unavoidably
disturbs that culture. Second, there is the problem of intelligibility across
cultural systems radical translation.
One goal of ethnographic research is to arrive at an interpretation of a set of
beliefs and values that are thought to be radically different from the
researcher’s own beliefs and values; but if this is so, then it is questionable
whether they can be accurately tr. into the researcher’s conceptual scheme.
Third, there is the problem of empirical testing of ethnographic
interpretations. To what extent do empirical procedures constrain the
construction of an interpretation of a given cultural milieu? Finally, there is
the problem of generalizability. To what extent does fieldwork in one location
permit anthropologists to generalize to a larger context other villages, the dispersed ethnic group
represented by this village, or this village at other times? ethnomethodology, a phenomenological approach
to interpreting everyday action and speech in various social contexts. Derived
from phenomenological sociology and introduced by Harold Garfinkel, the method
aims to guide research into meaningful social practices as experienced by
participants. A major objective of the method is to interpret the rules that
underlie everyday activity and thus constitute part of the normative basis of a
given social order. Research from this perspective generally focuses on mundane
social activities e.g., psychiatrists
evaluating patients’ files, jurors deliberating on defendants’ culpability, or
coroners judging causes of death. The investigator then attempts to reconstruct
an underlying set of rules and ad hoc procedures that may be taken to have
guided the observed activity. The approach emphasizes the contextuality of
social practice the richness of unspoken
shared understandings that guide and orient participants’ actions in a given
practice or activity. H. P. Grice, “The Teutons, according to Tacitus.”
more grice to
the mill: SOUS-ENTENDU,
-UE, part. passé, adj. et subst. masc. I. − Part. passé de sous-entendre*. A. −
Empl. impers. Il est sous-entendu que + complét. à l'ind. Il est inutile de
préciser que. Synon. il va sans dire que.Elle lui écrivit (...) que (...) elle
aurait enfin, après avoir été si souvent reçue chez eux, le plaisir de les
inviter à son tour. De lui, elle ne disait pas un mot, il était sous-entendu
que leur présence excluait la sienne (Proust,Swann,1913301). B. − Empl. ell. à
valeur de prop. part. Sous-entendu (inv., le locuteur suppléant ce qui n'est
pas exprimé mais suggéré). Ce qui signifie par là (que). Mon cher Ami, Encore
une! sous-entendu: demande de croix d'honneur (Flaub.,Corresp.,1871287). II. −
Adjectif A. − Synon. implicite, tacite; anton. avoué, explicite, formulé. 1.
Qu'on laisse entendre sans l'exprimer. Le lendemain, à table, mon mari me dit
(je me demandai d'abord s'il n'y avait pas là quelque dessein sous-entendu): −
Sais-tu ce que m'a annoncé Brassy? Gurgine a essayé de se tuer
(Daniel-Rops,Mort,1934291). 2. Qui reste implicite. Je me rappelle (...)
d'avoir lu dans la déclaration des droits de l'homme cette maxime sous-entendue
dans tous les codes qu'on nous a donnés depuis: « Tout ce qui n'est pas défendu
par la loi ne peut être empêché, et nul ne peut être contraint à faire ce
qu'elle n'ordonne pas » (Bonald,Législ. primit.,t. 1, 1802152).Toute mélodie
commence par une anacrouse exprimée ou sous-entendue (D'Indy,Compos. mus.,t. 1,
1897-190035). B. − GRAMM. Qui n'est pas exprimé, mais que le sens ou la syntaxe
pourrait suppléer aisément. Observez qu'ainsi est tantôt adverbe, tantôt
conjonction. (...) Il est encore adverbe dans celle-ci [cette phrase], ainsi
que la vertu, le crime a ses degrés; il signifie de la même manière. C'est que,
qui est la conjonction qui lie ensemble la phrase exprimée, le crime a ses
degrés, avec la phrase sous-entendue, la vertu a ses degrés (Destutt de
Tr.,Idéol. 2,1803140).L'intelligence fait donc naturellement usage des rapports
d'équivalent à équivalent, de contenu à contenant, de cause à effet, etc.,
qu'implique toute phrase, où il y a un sujet, un attribut, un verbe, exprimé ou
sous-entendu (Bergson,É créatr.,1907149). III. − Subst. masc. A. − Au sing.
Comportement de celui qui sous-entend les choses sans les exprimer
explicitement. C'est la plus immense personnalité que je connaisse [Zola], mais
elle est toute dans le sous-entendu: l'homme ne parle pas de lui, mais toutes
les théories, toutes les idées, toutes les logomachies qu'il émet combattent
uniquement, à propos de tout et de n'importe quoi, en faveur de sa littérature
et de son talent (Goncourt, Journal, 1883251). B. − P. méton. 1. Parfois péj.
Ce qui est sous-entendu, insinué dans des propos ou dans un texte, ou p. ext.,
par un comportement. Synon. allusion, insinuation.Plus libre que ses confrères,
il ne craignait pas, − bien timidement encore, avec des clignements d'yeux et
des sous-entendus, − de fronder les gens en place (Rolland,J.-Chr.,Adolesc.,
1905365). − Au sing. à valeur de neutre. Henry Céard a passé avec moi toute la
journée, causant du roman qu'il fait, − et qu'il veut faire dans le gris, le
voilé, le sous-entendu (Goncourt,, Journal18781276). − En partic. Allusion
grivoise. Les conversations fourmillaient d'allusions et de sous-entendus dont
la grivoiserie me choquait (Beauvoir,Mém. j. fille,1958165). 2. Ce qui n'est
pas exprimé explicitement. Synon. restriction, réticence.Personne ne dit: « Je
suis », si ce n'est dans une certaine attitude très instable et généralement
apprise, et on ne le dit alors qu'avec quantité de sous-entendus: il y faut
parfois un long commentaire (Valéry, Variété IV,1938228). REM. Sous-entente,
subst. fém.,vx. a) Action de sous-entendre par artifice; p. méton., ce qui est
ainsi sous-entendu. Il ne parle jamais qu'il n'y ait quelque sous-entente à ce
qu'il dit. Il y a quelque sous-entente à cela (Ac. 1798-1878). b) Gramm. Synon.
de sous-entendu. (Ds Bally 1951). Prononc. et Orth.: [suzɑ ̃tɑ ̃dy]. Ac. 1694:
sousentendu, -ue, 1718: sousentendu, -üe, dep. 1740: sous-entendu, -ue. Fréq.
abs. littér.: 249. Fréq. rel. littér.: xixes.: a) 189, b) 230; xxes.: a) 480,
b) 484. Bbg. Ducrot (O.). Le Dire et le dit. Paris, 1984, 13-31. − Kerbrat-Orecchioni (C.).
L'Énonciation. De la subjectivité ds le lang. Paris, 1980, 290 p., passim. more grice to the mill: sous-entendu:
used by, of all people, Mill. An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's
Philosophybooks.google.com › books ... and speak with any approach to
precision, and adopting into [the necessary sufficient clauses of a piece of
philosophical conceptual analysis] a mere sous-entendu of common conversation
in its most unprecise form. If I say to any one, Cf. understatement, as opposed
to overstatement. The ‘statement’ thing complicates things,
‘underunderstanding’ seems better, or ‘sub-understanding,’ strictly. Trust
Grice to bring more Grice to the Mill and provide a full essay, indeed theory,
and base his own philosophy, on the sous-tentendu! Cf. Pears, Pears
Cyclopaedia. “The English love meiosis, litotes, and understatement. The French
don’t.” Note all the figures of rhetoric cited by Grice, and why they have
philosophical import. Many entries here: hyperbole, meiosis, litotes, etc.
Grice took ‘sous-entendu’ etymologically serious. It is UNDERSTOOD. Nobody
taught you, but it understood. It is understood is like It is known. So “The
pillar box seems red” is understood to mean, “It may not be.” Now a
sous-entendu may be cancellable, in which case it was MIS-understood, or the
emissor has changed his mind. Grice considers the paradoxes the understanding
under ‘uptake,’ just to make fun of Austin’s informalism. The ‘endendu’ is what
the French understand by ‘understand,’ the root being Latin intellectus, or
intendo.
macaulay: Grice: “Unlike Whitehead, I care
for style; so when it comes to ‘if,’ we
have to please Macaulaythe verbs change, for each modeand sub-mode!” -- Grice: A curious phenomenon comes to light. I began by
assuming (or stipulating) that the verbs 'judge' and 'will' (acceptance-verbs)
are to be 'completed' by radicals (phrastics). Yet when the machinery developed
above has been applied, we find that the verb 'accept' (or 'think') is to be
completed by something of the form 'Op + p', that is, by a sentence. Perhaps we
might tolerate this syntactical ambivalence; but if we cannot, the remedy is
not clear. It would, for example, not be satisfactory to suppose that 'that',
when placed before a sentence, acts as a 'radicalizer' (is a functor expressing
a function which takes that sentence on to its radical); for that way we should
lose the differentiations effected by varying mode-markers, and this would be
fatal to the scheme. This phenomenon certainly suggests that the attempt to
distinguish radicals from sentences may be misguided; that if radicals are to
be admitted at all, they should be identified with indicative sentences. The operator '⊢' would then be a
'semantically vanishing' operator. But this does not wholly satisfy me; for, if
'⊢'
is semantically vacuous, what happens to the subordinate distinction made by
'A' and 'B' markers, which seems genuine enough? We might find these markers
'hanging in the air', like two smiles left behind by the Cheshire Cat. Whatever
the outcome of this debate, however, I feel fairly confident that I could
accommodate the formulation of my discussion to it. Fuller Exposition of the
'Initial Idea' First, some preliminary points. To provide at least a modicum of
intelligibility for my discourse, I shall pronounce the judicative end p.72
operator '⊢'
as 'it is the case that', and the volitive operator '!' as 'let it be that';
and I shall pronounce the sequence 'φ, ψ' as 'given that φ, ψ'. These vocal mannerisms
will result in the production of some pretty barbarous 'English sentences'; but
we must remember that what I shall be trying to do, in uttering such sentences,
will be to represent supposedly underlying structure; if that is one's aim, one
can hardly expect that one's speech-forms will be such as to excite the
approval of, let us say, Jane Austen or Lord Macaulay. In any case, less
horrendous, though (for my purposes) less perspicuous, alternatives will, I
think, be available. Further, I am going to be almost exclusively concerned
with alethic and practical arguments, the proximate conclusions of which will
be, respectively, of the forms 'Acc (⊢ p)' and 'Acc (! p)'; for example, 'acceptable (it is the
case that it snows)' and 'acceptable (let it be that I go home)'. There will be
two possible ways of reading the latter sentence. We might regard 'acceptable'
as a sentential adverb (modifier) like 'demonstrably'; in that case to say or
think 'acceptable (let it be that I go home)' will be to say or think 'let it
be that I go home', together with the qualification that what I say or think is
acceptable; as one might say, 'acceptably, let it be that I go home'. To adopt
this reading would seem to commit us to the impossibility of incontinence; for
since 'accept that let it be that I go home' is to be my rewrite for 'Vaccept
(will) that I go home', anyone x who concluded, by practical argument, that
'acceptable let it be that x go home' would ipso facto will to go home.
Similarly (though less paradoxically) any one who concluded, by alethic
argument, 'acceptable it is the case that it snows', would ipso facto judge
that it snows. So an alternative reading 'it is acceptable that let it be that
I go home', which does not commit the speaker or thinker to 'let it be that I
go home', seems preferable. We can, of course, retain the distinct form
'acceptably, let it be that (it is the case that) p' for renderings of
'desirably' and 'probably'. Let us now tackle the judicative cases. I start
with the assumption that arguments of the form 'A, so probably B' are sometimes
(informally) valid; 'he has an exceptionally red face, so probably he has high
blood pressure' might be informally valid, whereas 'he has an exceptionally red
face, so probably he has musical talent' is unlikely to be allowed informal
validity. end p.73 We might re-express this assumption by saying that it is
sometimes the case that A informally yields-with-probability that B (where
'yields' is the converse of 'is inferable from'). If we wish to construct a
form of argument the acceptability of which does not depend on choice of
substituends for 'A' and 'B', we may, so to speak, allow into the
object-language forms of sentence which correspond to metastatements of the
form: 'A yields-with-probability that B'; we may allow ourselves, for example,
such a sentence as "it is probable, given that he has a very red face,
that he has high blood pressure". This will provide us with the
argument-patterns: “Probable, given A, that B A So, probably, B” or “Probable,
given A, that B A So probably that B” To take
the second pattern, the legitimacy of such an inferential transition will not
depend on the identity of 'A' or of 'B', though it will depend (as was stated
in the previous chapter) on a licence from a suitably formulated 'Principle of
Total Evidence'. The proposal which I am considering (in pursuit of the
'initial idea') would (roughly) involve rewriting the second pattern of
argument so that it reads: It is acceptable, given that it is the case that A,
that it is the case that B. It is the case that A. To apply this schema to a
particular case, we generated the particular argument: It is acceptable, given
that it is the case that Snodgrass has a red face, that it is the case that
Snodgrass has high blood pressure. It is the case that Snodgrass has a red
face. So, it is acceptable that it is the case that Snodgrass has high blood
pressure. end p.74 If we make the further assumption that the singular
'conditional' acceptability statement which is the first premiss of the above
argument may be (and perhaps has to be) reached by an analogue of the rule of
universal instantiation from a general acceptability statement, we make room
for such general acceptability sentences as: It is acceptable, given that it is
the case that x has a red face, that it is the case that x has high blood
pressure. which are of the form "It is acceptable, given that it is the
case that Fx, that it is the case that Gx'; 'x' here is, you will note, an
unbound variable; and the form might also (loosely) be read (pronounced) as:
"It is acceptable, given that it is the case that one (something) is F,
that it is the case that oneis G." All of this is (I think) pretty
platitudinous; which is just as well, since it is to serve as a model for the
treatment of practical argument. To turn from the alethic to the practical
dimension. Here (the proposal goes) we may proceed, in a fashion almost exactly
parallel to that adopted on the alethic side, through the following sequence of
stages: (1) Arguments (in thought or speech) of the form: Let it be that A It
is the case that B so, with some degree of desirability, let it be that C are
sometimes (and sometimes not) informally valid (or acceptable). (2) Arguments
of the form: It is desirable, given that let it be that A and that it is the
case that B, that let it be that C Let it be that A It is the case that B so,
it is desirable that let it be that C should, therefore, be allowed to be
formally acceptable, subject to licence from a Principle of Total Evidence. (3)
In accordance with our proposal such arguments will be rewritten: end p.75 It
is acceptable, given that let it be A and that it is the case that B, that let
it be that C Let it be that A It is the case that B so, it is desirable that
let it be that C (4) The first premisses of such arguments may be (and perhaps
have to be) reached by instantiation from general acceptability statements of
the form: "It is acceptable, given that let one be E and that it is the
case that one is F, that let it be that one is G." We may note that
sentences like "it is snowing" can be trivially recast so as (in
effect) to appear as third premisses in such arguments (with 'open'
counterparts inside the acceptability sentence; they can be rewritten as, for
example, "Snodgrass is such that it is snowing"). We are now in
possession of such exciting general acceptability sentences as: "It is
acceptable, given that let it be that one keeps dry and that it is the case
that one is such that it is raining, that let one take with one one's
umbrella." (5) A special subclass
of general acceptability sentences (and of practical arguments) can be
generated by 'trivializing' the predicate in the judicative premiss (making it
a 'universal predicate'). If, for example, I take 'x is F' to represent 'x is
identical with x' the judicative subclause may be omitted from the general
acceptability sentence, with a corresponding 'reduction' in the shape of the
related practical argument. We have therefore such argument sequences as the
following: (P i ) It is acceptable, given that let it be that one survives,
that let it be that one eats So (by U i ) It is acceptable, given that let it
be that Snodgrass survives, that let it be that Snodgrass eats (P 2 ) Let it be
that Snodgrass survives So (by Det) It is acceptable that let it be that
Snodgrass eats. We should also, at some point, consider further transitions to:
(a) Acceptably, let it be that Snodgrass eats, and to: (b) Let it be that
Snodgrass eats. end p.76 And we may also note that, as a more colloquial
substitute for "Let it be that one (Snodgrass) survives (eats)" the
form "one (Snodgrass) is to survive (eat)" is available; we thus
obtain prettier inhabitants of antecedent clauses, for example, "given
that Snodgrass is to survive". We must now pay some attention to the
varieties of acceptability statement to be found within each of the alethic and
practical dimensions; it will, of course, be essential to the large-scale
success of the proposal which I am exploring that one should be able to show that
for every such variant within one dimension there is a corresponding variant
within the other. Within the area of defeasible generalizations, there is
another variant which, in my view, extends across the board in the way just
indicated, namely, the unweighted acceptability generalization (with associated
singular conditionals), or, as I shall also call it, the ceteris paribus
generalization. Such generalization I take to be of the form "It is
acceptable (ceteris paribus), given that φX, that ψX" and I think we find
both practical and alethic examples of the form; for example, "It is
ceteris paribus acceptable, given that it is the case that one likes a person,
that it is the case that one wants his company", which is not incompatible
with "It is ceteris paribus acceptable, given that it is the case that one
likes a person and that one is feeling ill, that one does not want his
company". We also find "It is ceteris paribus acceptable, given that
let it be that one leaves the country and given that it is the case that one is
an alien, that let it be that one obtains a sailing permit from Internal
Revenue", which is compatible with "It is ceteris paribus acceptable,
given that let it be that one leaves the country and given that it is the case
that one is an alien and that one is a close friend of the President, that let
it be that one does not obtain a sailing permit, and that one arranges to
travel in Air Force I". I discussed this kind of generalization, or 'law',
briefly in "Method in Philosophical Psychology"1 and shall not dilate
on its features here. I will just remark that it can be adapted to handle
'functional laws' (in the way suggested in that address), and that end p.77 it
is different from the closely related use of universal generalizations in 'artificially
closed systems', where some relevant parameter is deliberately ignored, to be
taken care of by an extension to the system; for in that case, when the
extension is made, the original law has to be modified or corrected, whereas my
ceteris paribus generalization can survive in an extended system; and I regard
this as a particular advantage to philosophical psychology. In addition to
these two defeasible types of acceptability generalization (each with alethic
and practical sub-types), we have non-defeasible acceptability generalizations,
with associated singular conditionals, exemplifying what I might call
'unqualified', 'unreserved', or 'full' acceptability claims. To express these I
shall employ the (constructed) modal 'it is fully acceptable that . . .'; and
again there will be occasion for its use in the representation both of alethic
and of practical discourse. We have, in all, then, three varieties of
acceptability statement (each with alethic and practical sub-types), associated
with the modals "It is fully acceptable that . . . "
(non-defeasible), 'it is ceteris paribus acceptable that . . . ', and 'it is to
such-and-such a degree acceptable that . . . ', both of the latter pair being
subject to defeasibility. (I should re-emphasize that, on the practical side, I
am so far concerned to represent only statements which are analogous with
Kant's Technical Imperatives ('Rules of Skill').)
more, H: “Not to be confused with the
other More, who was literally beheaded when he refused to swear to the Act of
Supremacy which metaphorically named Henry VIII the head of the C. of E.” -- English
philosopher, theologian, and poet, the most prolific of the Cambridge
Platonists. He entered Christ’s , where he spent the rest of his life after
becoming Fellow . He was primarily an apologist of anti-Calvinist,
latitudinarian stamp whose inalienable philosophico- theological purpose was to
demonstrate the existence and immortality of the soul and to cure “two enormous
distempers of the mind,” atheism and “enthusiasm.” He describes himself as “a
Fisher for Philosophers, desirous to draw them to or retain them in the
Christian Faith.” His eclectic method deployed Neoplatonism notably Plotinus
and Ficino, mystical theologies, cabalistic doctrines as More misconceived them,
empirical findings including reports of witchcraft and ghosts, the new science,
and the new philosophy, notably the philosophy of Descartes. Yet he rejected
Descartes’s beast-machine doctrine, his version of dualism, and the pretensions
of Cartesian mechanical philosophy to explain all physical phenomena. Animals
have souls; the universe is alive with souls. Body and spirit are spatially
extended, the former being essentially impenetrable, inert, and discerpible
divisible into parts, the latter essentially penetrable, indiscerpible, active,
and capable of a spiritual density, which More called essential spissitude,
“the redoubling or contracting of substance into less space than it does
sometimes occupy.” Physical processes are activated and ordered by the spirit
of nature, a hylarchic principle and “the vicarious power of God upon this
great automaton, the world.” More’s writings on natural philosophy, especially
his doctrine of infinite space, are thought to have influenced Newton. More
attacked Hobbes’s materialism and, in the 1660s and 1670s, the impieties of
Dutch Cartesianism, including the perceived atheism of Spinoza and his circle.
He regretted the “enthusiasm” for and conversion to Quakerism of Anne Conway,
his “extramural” tutee and assiduous correspondent. More had a partiality for
coinages and linguistic exotica. We owe to him ‘Cartesianism’ coined a few
years before the first appearance of the
equivalent, and the substantive ‘materialist.’ “But he never coined
‘implicaturum,’”Grice.
more, Sir Thomas: English humanist,
statesman, martyr, and saint. A lawyer by profession, he entered royal service and
became lord chancellor. After refusing to swear to the Act of Supremacy, which
named (“metaphorically,”Grice) Henry VIII
the head of the C. of E. h, More was (“ironically, but literally”Grice) beheaded
as a traitor. Although his writings include biography, poetry, letters, and
anti-heretical tracts, his only philosophical work, Utopia published in Latin,
1516, is his masterpiece. Covering a wide variety of subjects including
government, education, punishment, religion, family life, and euthanasia,
Utopia contrasts European social institutions with their counterparts on the
imaginary island of Utopia. Inspired in part by Plato’s Republic, the Utopian
communal system is designed to teach virtue and reward it with happiness. The
absence of money, private property, and most social distinctions allows
Utopians the leisure to develop the faculties in which happiness consists.
Because of More’s love of irony, Utopia has been subject to quite different
interpretations. H. P. Grice, “A personal guide to the 39 articles, compleat
with their 39 implicatura.”
morelli: “Grice: ‘I once
told Austin, I don’t give a hoot what the dictionary says;’ ‘And that’s where
you make your big mistake,’ his crass response was!” -- Grice: “I once told
Ackrill, ‘should there be a manual of philosophy, must we follow it?’ He
replied, “One thing is to know the manual, another is to know how to abide by
it!” – raffaele Morelli (Milano), filosofo. Si laurea
a Pavia e l'anno dopo assolve
all'obbligo di leva a Trieste dove presta attenzione alle problematiche
relazionali dei militari nello svolgimento delle proprie mansioni; si è poi
specializzato in Psichiatria presso l'Università degli Studi di Milano nel
1977. Dal 1979 è direttore dell'Istituto Riza, gruppo di ricerca che
pubblica la rivista Riza Psicosomatica ed altre pubblicazioni specializzate,
con lo scopo di "studiare l'uomo come espressione della simultaneità
psicofisica riconducendo a questa concezione l'interpretazione della malattia,
della sua diagnosi e della sua cura". Inoltre è direttore delle riviste
Dimagrire e Salute Naturale. Dall'attività dell'Istituto Riza è sorta
anche la Scuola di Formazione in Psicoterapia ad indirizzo psicosomatico,
riconosciuta ufficialmente dal Ministero dell'università e della ricerca
scientifica e tecnologica nell'ottobre del 1994. Raffaele Morelli è anche
vicepresidente della SIMP (Società Italiana di Medicina Psicosomatica).
Ha partecipato a numerose trasmissioni televisive sia per la RAI sia per
Mediaset (Maurizio Costanzo Show, Tutte le mattine, Matrix, ecc.) e per la
radio. Nelle sue opere ci sono molti riferimenti alle dottrine
orientali.[senza fonte] Opere Verso la concezione di un sé psicosomatico.
Il corpo è come un grande sogno della mente, con Diego Frigoli e Gianlorenzo Masaraki,
Milano, UNICOPLI, Milano, Edizioni Libreria Cortina, La dimensione
respiratoria. Studio psicosomatico del respiro, con Gianlorenzo Masaraki, Milano,
Masson Italia, Dove va la medicina psicosomatica, a cura di, Milano-Roma, Riza
libri, Endas, 1982. Il sacro. Antropoanalisi, psicosomatica, comunicazione, con
Erminio Gius e Carlo Tosetti, Milano, Riza-Endas, 1983. Convegno internazionale
Mente-corpo: il momento unificante. Milano, Atti, e con Piero Parietti, Milano,
UNICOPLI, Riza, I sogni dell'infinito, e con Franco Sabbadini, Milano, Riza, Autostima.
Le regole pratiche, Milano, a cura dell'Istituto Riza di medicina psicosomatica,
Il talento. Come scoprire e realizzare la tua vera natura, Milano, Riza, Ansia,
con testi di Piero Parietti e Vittorio Caprioglio, Milano, Riza, Insonnia, con
testi di Piero Parietti e Vittorio Caprioglio, Milano, Riza, Cefalea, con testi
di Piero Parietti e Vittorio Caprioglio, Milano, Riza, Lo psichiatra e
l'alchimista. Romanzo, Milano, Riza, Le nuove vie dell'autostima. Se piaci a te
stesso ogni miracolo è possibile, Milano, Riza, Conosci davvero tuo figlio?
Sconosciuto in casa. Dal delitto di Novi Ligure al disagio di una generazione,
con Gianna Schelotto, Milano, Riza, Come essere felici, Milano, A. Mondadori, Cosa
dire e non dire nella coppia, Milano, A. Mondadori, Come mantenere il cervello
giovane, Milano, A. Mondadori, Come affrontare lo stress, Milano, A. Mondadori,
Come amare ed essere amati, Milano, A. Mondadori, Come dimagrire senza soffrire,
Milano, A. Mondadori, Come risvegliare l'eros, Milano, A. Mondadori, Come star
bene al lavoro, Milano, A. Mondadori, Come essere single e felici, Milano, A.
Mondadori, Cosa dire o non dire ai
nostri figli, Milano, A. Mondadori, La rinascita interiore, Milano, Riza, Volersi
bene. Tutto ciò che conta è già dentro di noi, Milano, Riza, L'amore giusto.
C'è una persona che aspetta solo te, Milano, Riza, Vincere i disagi. Puoi farcela
da solo perché li hai creati tu, Milano, Riza, 2004. Felici sul lavoro. Come
ritrovare il benessere in ufficio, Milano, Riza, I figli felici. Aiutiamoli a
diventare se stessi, Milano, Riza, La gioia di vivere. Scorre spontaneamente
dentro di noi, Milano, Riza, Essere se stessi. L'unica via per incontrare il
benessere, Milano, Riza, Accendi la passione. È la scintilla che risveglia
l'energia vitale, Milano, Riza, Alle radici della felicità. Editoriali dal 1980
al 1990 pubblicati su Riza psicosomatica, rivista mensile delle Edizioni Riza,
Milano, Riza, Ciascuno è perfetto. L'arte di star bene con se stessi, Milano, Mondadori,
Il segreto di vivere. Aforismi, Milano, Riza, Realizzare se stessi, Milano,
Riza, Vincere la solitudine, Milano, Riza, Dimagrire senza fatica, Milano,
Riza, Amare senza soffrire, Milano, Riza, Guarire con la psiche, Milano, Riza, Superare
il tradimento, Milano, Riza, Dizionario della felicità, 6 voll, Milano, Riza, Non
siamo nati per soffrire, Milano, Mondadori,L'autostima. Le cinque regole.
Vivere la vita. Adesso, Milano, Riza, Conoscersi. L'arte di valorizzare se
stessi. Via le zavorre dalla mente, Milano, Riza, I figli difficili sono i figli migliori,
Milano, Riza, Il matrimonio è in crisi... che fortuna!, Milano, Riza, Autostima,
I consigli di Raffaele Morelli per un anno di felicità, Milano, Riza, 2006. Le
parole che curano, Milano, Riza, Perché le donne non ne possono più... degli
uomini, Milano, Riza, Le piccole cose che cambiano la vita, Milano, Mondadori, Come
trovare l'armonia in se stessi, Milano, Oscar Mondadori, Ama e non pensare, Milano, Mondadori, Curare
il panico. Gli attacchi vengono per farci esprimere le parti migliori di noi
stessi, con Vittorio Caprioglio, Milano, Riza, Non dipende da te. Affidati alla
vita così realizzi i tuoi desideri, Milano, Mondadori, L'alchimia. L'arte di
trasformare se stessi, Milano, Riza, Il sesso è amore. Vivere l'eros senza
sensi di colpa, Milano, Mondadori, Puoi fidarti di te, Milano, Mondadori, La felicità
è dentro di te, Milano, Mondadori,L'unica cosa che conta, Milano, Mondadori, La
felicità è qui. Domande e risposte sulla vita, l'amore, l'eternità, con Luciano
Falsiroli, Milano, Mondadori, Guarire senza medicine. La vera cura è dentro di
te, Milano, Mondadori, Lezioni di autostima. Come imparare a stare beni con se
stessi e con gli altri, Milano, Mondadori, .Il segreto dell'amore felice,
Milano, Mondadori, La saggezza dell'anima. Quello che ci rende unici, Milano, Mondadori,
.Pensa magro. Le 6 mosse psicologiche per dimagrire senza dieta, Milano, Mondadori,
Vincere il panico. [Le parole per capirlo, i consigli per affrontarlo, cosa
fare per guarirlo], con Vittorio Caprioglio, Milano, Mondadori, Nessuna ferita
è per sempre. Come superare i dolori del passato, Milano, Mondadori, Solo la
mente può bruciare i grassi. Come attivare l'energia dimagrante che è dentro di
noi, Milano, Mondadori, .Breve corso di felicità. Le antiregole che ti danno la
gioia di vivere, Milano, Mondadori, La vera cura sei tu, Milano, Mondadori, .
Il meglio deve ancora arrivare. Come attivare l'energia che ringiovanisce,
Milano, Mondadori, Il potere curativo del digiuno. La pratica che rigenera
corpo e mente, con Michael Morelli, Milano, Mondadori, Segui il tuo destino. Come riconoscere se sei
sulla strada giusta, Milano, Mondadori, .Il manuale della felicità. Le dieci
regole pratiche che ti miglioreranno la vita, Milano, Mondadori, .Pronto
soccorso per le emozioni. Le parole da dirsi nei momenti difficili, Milano,
Mondadori, .Sito Mondadori
SIMPDirettivo, simpitalia.com. 4riza.itSito ufficiale dell'istituto Riza,
su riza.it. su Internet Movie Database, IMDb.com. Grice: “Should there be a
‘dizionario della felicita,’ I would perhaps follow Austin’s advice and go
through it!” –.
moretti: Grice: “I like
Moretti – he uses a good metaphor, ‘the wounded poet,’ unless we mean Owen, but
he was more than wounded, even if that implicature is cancellable --.” Grice:
“I like Moretti also because he wrote on ‘ermeneutica sensibile,’ which is
exactly what I do.” Grice: “I like Moretti also because he uses ‘segnatura’
etymologically, when he writes of the ‘la segnatura romantica’ – talk of
tokens!” -- Giampiero Moretti (Roma), filosofo. Nasce a Roma, nel borghese
quartiere Trieste, primo di due fratelli. Ottiene nel 1973 il diploma di
maturità classica presso il Liceo Giulio Cesare. Successivamente, nel 1977,
consegue una prima laurea in Giurisprudenza, con una tesi in filosofia del
diritto, e, nel 1980, una seconda in filosofia, con una tesi in filosofia
morale, entrambe presso l'Roma La Sapienza. È poi borsista presso l'Friburgo in
Brisgovia, dove imposta un progetto di ricerca che, partendo
dall'interpretazione del pensiero di Martin Heidegger, mira ad un'analisi
critica delle categorie filosofico-estetiche del “romantico” in Germania, con
particolare attenzione alle opere di autori del romanticismo di Heidelberg,
quali Friedrich Creuzer, Joseph Görres, i Fratelli Grimm e Johann Jakob
Bachofen, che contribuisce a tradurre e a far conoscere in Italia. Al suo
rientro insegna dapprima materie letterarie nelle scuole medie e, in seguito,
filosofia presso la Scuola germanica di Roma.
La sua ricerca si amplia poi al pensiero estetico di Novalis, di cui
cura la prima edizione completa in lingua italiana della Opera filosofica;
durante questo periodo consegue il dottorato di ricerca in Estetica presso
l'Bologna. Nel 1992 vince la cattedra di professore associato di Estetica
all'Bari; dal 2000 è Professore di Estetica presso l'Napoli L’Orientale. Redattore di Itinerari e Studi Filosofici,
collabora con varie altre riviste filosofiche (Agalma, Rivista di Estetica,
Studi di Estetica, aut aut, Nuovi Argomenti, Filosofia e Società, Filosofia
Oggi, Estetica) e ha spesso partecipato a trasmissioni RAI su temi filosofici e
a numerosi convegni . Opere:”Heidelberg
romantica. Studio sui rapporti poesia-mito-storia e arte-natura nel pre-romanticismo
e in J. Görres, F. Creuzer, J. e W. Grimm, J. J. Bachofen, Itinerari, Lanciano,
“Anima e immagine. Sul «poetico» in L. Klages, Aesthetica pre-print, Palermo, Nichilismo
e romanticismo. Estetica e filosofia della storia fra Ottocento e Novecento,
Cadmo, Roma, Hestia. Interpretazione del romanticismo tedesco, Ianua, Roma, L'estetica
di Novalis. Analogia e principio poetico nella profezia romantica, Rosenberg
& Sellier, Torino, La segnatura romantica. Filosofia e sentimento da
Novalis a Heidegger, Hestia, Cernusco L., Il genio, il Mulino, Bologna, “Il
poeta ferito.” Hölderlin, Heidegger e la storia dell'essere, Editrice La
Mandragora, Imola, “Anima e immagine.” Studi su Ludwig Klages, Mimesis, Milano,
Heidelberg romantica. Romanticismo tedesco e nichilismo europeo, Guida Editori,
Napoli, Introduzione all'estetica del Romanticismo tedesco, Nuova Cultura,
Roma, Il genio, nuova edizione ampliata,
Morcelliana, Brescia. Per immagini. Esercizi di ermeneutica sensibile, Moretti
& Vitali, Bergamo, Heidelberg
romantica. Romanticismo tedesco e nichilismo europeo, Morcelliana, Brescia, Novalis.
Pensiero, poesia, romanzo Morcelliana, Brescia, Opere curate o tradotte Romano
Guardini, Hölderlin, Giampiero Moretti, Morcelliana, Brescia. Novalis, Scritti
filosofici, Fabrizio Desideri e Giampiero Moretti, Morcelliana, Brescia. J. J.
Bachofen, Il matriarcato, scelta antologica con introduzione e note di Moretti,
Christian Marinotti Editore, Milano, Novalis, Opera filosofica, I, Einaudi, Torino, Un video con una
trasmissione RAI del prof. Moretti Un
video con un intervento del prof. Moretti.
mori: Grice: “I like Mori; he wrote a treatise on Stephen, better
known as Virginia Woolf’s father; which reminded me of Bergmann who once called
me an English futilitarian!” -- Maurizio mori (Cremona), filosofo. Professore
di Filosofia morale e bioetica all’Torino e presidente della Consulta di
Bioetica Onlus, un'associazione di volontariato culturale per la promozione
della bioetica laica. L’etica e la bioetica con le varie problematiche connesse
sono le tematiche al centro dei suoi interessi filosofici e teorici. Mori ha studiato all’Università degli Studi
di Milano, dove ha conseguito la laurea (con Andrea Bonomi e Claudio Pizzi) e
il dottorato sotto la guida di Uberto Scarpelli e Mario Jori. Ha studiato due
semestri all’Helsinki con G.H. von Wright, e ha un M.A. in Philosophy dalla
University of Arizona, dove ha studiato con Joel Feinberg, Allen Buchanan e
Jules Coleman. In Italia ha insegnato all’Università del Piemonte Orientale
(Alessandria) e all’Pisa, prima di essere chiamato a Torino. Temi di ricerca Mori ha studiato i temi della
metaetica e della logica dell’etica con le problematiche della teoria etica. Ha
tradotto in italiano i Metodi dell’etica di Henry Sidgwick e Etica di W.K.
Frankena. È stato tra i primi in Italia a occuparsi di bioetica, nella quale ha
dato contributi in tutti i principali settori, con particolare attenzione
all’aborto e alla fecondazione assistita. Sollecitato dai casi Welby e Englaro
ha dato contributi anche sul fine-vita a difesa dell’autonomia individuale. Per
primo ha teorizzato la contrapposizione paradigmatica tra bioetica laica e
bioetica cattolica, derivante dal fatto che quest’ultima propone un’etica della
sacralità della vita caratterizzata da divieti assoluti, mentre l’altra avanza
un’etica della qualità della vita senza assoluti e soli divieti prima facie.
Infine, sin dalla fine degli anni ’70 ha prestato grande attenzione al problema
della liberazione animale. Riviste Nel
1993 Mori ha fondato Bioetica. Rivista interdisciplinare (Ananke Lab, Torino),
e da allora ne è il direttore. È membro di numerosi comitati, tra cui il
comitato scientifico di Notizie di Politeia, di Iride del Journal of Medicine
and Philosophy e altre. Opere: “Manuale di bioetica: verso una civiltà bio-medica
secolarizzata”, Le Lettere, Firenze, . Introduzione alla bioetica. 12 temi per
capire e discutere, Daniela Piazza Editore, Torino, . Il caso Eluana Englaro.
La “Porta Pia” del vitalismo ippocratico ovvero perché è moralmente giusto
sospendere ogni intervento, Pendragon, Bologna, Aborto e morale. Per capire un
nuovo diritto, Einaudi, Torino, La fecondazione artificiale. Una nuova forma di
riproduzione umana, Laterza, Roma-Bari, La fecondazione artificiale: questioni
morali nell'esperienza giuridica, Giuffrè, Milano, Utilitarismo e morale razionale.
Per una teoria etica obiettivista, Giuffrè, Milano, La legge sulla procreazione
medicalmente assistita. Paradigmi a confronto, Net, Milano, Laici e cattolici
in bioetica: storia e teoria di un confronto, Le Lettere, Firenze, .La
fecondazione assistita dopo 10 anni di legge 40. Meglio ricominciare da capo!,
Ananke editore, Torino, Questa è la scienza, bellezze! La fecondazione
assistita come novo modo di costruire le famiglie, Ananke Lab, Torino.
moriggi: Grice: “I like it
when Moriggi does substantial metaphysics; he has edited a collection on ‘why
is there something rather than nothing?” – hardly rhetoric – and the subtitle
is fascinating: the vacuum, the zero, and nothingness! All in Italian, to
offend Heidegger!” -- stefano moriggi (Milano), filosofo. Specializzato in
teoria e modelli della razionalità, fondamenti della probabilità e di
pragmatism. Docente a Brescia, Parma, Milano
e presso la European School of Molecular Medicine (SEMM), è conosciuto al
grande pubblico attraverso la trasmissione TV E se domani di Rai 3 e per alcuni
interventi ad altre trasmissioni (in particolare di Corrado Augias). Pubblicazioni Le tre bocche di Cerbero, con
E. Sindoni (Bompiani. Perché esiste qualcosa anziché nulla? Vuoto, Nulla, Zero,
con P.Giaretta e G.Federspil (Itaca) Perché la tecnologia ci rende umani, con
G. Nicoletti (Sironi) Connessi. Beati quelli che sapranno pensare con le
macchine (San Paolo) School Rocks! La scuola spacca, con A. Incorvaia (San
Paolo, ), con prefazione rap di Frankie Hi-nrg Note
//wired.it/attualita//04/18/connessi-pensare-la-macchina-pensare-con-le-macchine/
//smau.it/speakers/stefano.moriggi/
unimib.academia.edu/StefanoMoriggi
scholar.google.it/scholar?hl=it&q=stefano+moriggi&btnG=&lr= Sito ufficiale, su stefanomoriggi.it. Blog ufficiale, su stefanomoriggi.it. Opere di Stefano Moriggi, su openMLOL,
Horizons Unlimited srl.
mosca: Grice: “When
Austin was defending the ‘man in the street,’ he was thinking Mosca!” -- Grice:
“I like Mosca; he speaks of elites – Gellner speaks of elites, too!” -- Grice:
“Do Italians consider Mosca a philosopher?” – gaetano
mosca (Palermo), filosofo. Opere: Sulla teorica dei governi e sul governo
parlamentare, Appunti sulla libertà di
stampa, Questioni costituzionali, Le Costituzioni modern, Elementi di scienza
politica, Che cosa è la mafia, Appunti di diritto Costituzionale, Italia e
Libia, Stato liberale e stato sindacale, Il problema sindacale, Saggi di storia delle dottrine politiche,
Crisi e rimedi del regime parlamentare, Storia delle dottrine politiche,
Partiti e sindacati nella crisi del regime parlamentare, Ciò che la storia
potrebbe insegnare. Scritti di scienza politica (Milano), Il tramonto dello
Stato liberale (a cura di A. Lombardo, Catania 1971) Scritti sui sindacati (a cura
di F. Perfetti, M. Ortolani, Roma 1974) Discorsi parlamentari (con un saggio di
A. Panebianco, Bologna 2003)Essential Italian philosopher, who made
pioneering contributions to the theory of democratic elitism. Combining the
life of a professor with that of a
politician, he taught such subjects as constitutional law, public law,
political science, and history of political theory; at various times he was
also an editor of the Parliamentary proceedings, an elected member of the
Chamber of Deputies, an under-secretary for colonial affairs, a newspaper
columnist, and a member of the Senate. For Mosca ‘elitism’ refers to the empirical
generalization that a society is ruled by an organised minority. His democratic
commitment is embodied in what he calls juridical defense: the normative
principle that political developments are to be judged by whether and how they
prevent any one person, class, force, or institution from dominating the
others. Mosca’s third main contribution is a framework consisting of two intersecting
distinctions that yield four possible ideal types, defined as follows: in
autocracy, authority flows from the rulers to the ruled. In liberalism, from
the ruled to the rulers. In democracy, the ruling class is open to renewal by
members of other classes; in aristocracy it is not. He was influenced by, and
in turn influenced, positivism, for the elitist thesis presumably constitutes
the fundamental “law” of political “science.” Even deeper is his connection
with the tradition of Machiavelli’s political realism. There is also no
question that he practiced an empirical approach. In the tradition of elitism,
he may be compared and contrasted with Pareto, Michels, and Schumpeter; and in
the tradition of political philosophy, to
Croce, Gentile, and Gramsci. Refs.: H. P. Grice: “Mosca’s liberalism;” Luigi Speranza, "Grice e Mosca," per il Club
Anglo-Italiano, The Swimming-Pool Library, Villa Grice, Liguria, Italia.
motta: Grice: “If Mill’s claim to fame is to some his examination of
Mill, Motta’s claim to fame is his examination of Rosmini!” -- Il conte Emiliano
Avogadro della Motta (Vercelli), filosofo. Nacque dal conte Ignazio della Motta
e da Ifigenia Avogadro di Casanova, entrambi appartenenti a nobili famiglie di
vassalli e visconti, i cui antenati risalgono a poco oltre il mille. Tra gli
Avogadro vi fu anche Amedeo, inventore della legge sui fluidi. Il ramo degli
Avogadro della Motta si estinguerà nel 1944, con la morte di Emiliano II, suo
nipote. Emiliano frequentò con profitto gli studi e si laureò in utroque
iure, ma proseguì lo studio in diverse aree della teologia e della filosofia,
trasformando le dimore familiari in “piccole accademie” dove giuristi, filosofi,
studiosi di diritto canonico e vescovi si riunivano, per discutere vari
argomenti ed approfondire la filosofia moderna e i diversi aspetti del nascente
socialismo. Il 13 agosto 1833 ricevette l'incarico, che già fu del padre
e che manterrà fino al 1847, di riformatore degli studi del Vercellese e in
un'epoca in cui si guardava ancora con diffidenza all'istruzione delle classi
popolari, egli visitava ciclicamente le scuole d'ogni ordine, scegliendone
accuratamente gli insegnanti, convinto che l'istruzione e l'educazione fossero
un diritto di tutti e dovessero procedere simultaneamente. Nel 1837
assunse la carica di Consigliere di Formigliana e continuò a dedicarsi allo
sviluppo culturale della natia Vercelli, ove fondò la Società di Storia Patria,
per incrementare gli studi sul glorioso passato della città. Nel 1843 divenne
membro del Consiglio Generale del Debito Pubblico e più tardi sindaco di
Collobiano e “Consigliere di Sua Maestà per il pubblico insegnamento”.
Nel 1852 la sua notorietà varcò i confini del Piemonte, allorché ricevette
l'eccezionale invito di partecipazione alla fase preparatoria della definizione
del dogma dell'Immacolata e le sue riflessioni ebbero un seguito fra alcuni
importanti gesuiti, come il direttore de La Civiltà Cattolica, che fece dono a
papa Pio IX del Saggio intorno al socialismo. Luigi Taparelli d'Azeglio,
richiamandosi ad Avogadro, espresse la propria preferenza per una condanna
esplicita di tali errori, da includere nella bolla di definizione del dogma, ma
l'autore sollecitò apertamente la distinzione di due argomenti (definizione del
dogma e condanna degli errori) dalla portata tanto diversa e lo stesso Pio IX
incaricò la Commissione, che aveva già lavorato sulla definizione del dogma, di
esaminare gli errori moderni e di preparare il materiale necessario per la
bolla e chiese al cardinale Fornari di invitare formalmente alcuni laici a
collaborare. Avogadro fu l'unico laico italiano ad essere interpellato e inviò
a Roma una risposta singolare e ricca di argomentazioni. Ben presto la
Commissione incaricata abbandonò la trattazione univoca dei due argomenti e la
solenne definizione su Maria sarà fatta da Pio IX l'8 dicembre 1854, mentre
l'esame degli errori si trascinerà per altri dieci anni, mentre prevaleva in
ambito ecclesiastico l'idea di una severa condanna. Attività parlamentare
Dall'8 dicembre 1853 al 1859 diventò membro attivo nella vita politica, quale
deputato eletto nel collegio di Avigliana e operò nelle file dello stesso
schieramento politico della Destra. La proposta avanzata in Parlamento di
ridurre il numero delle feste, indusse Avogadro a scrivere un apposito
opuscolo, per difendere la dignità dell'uomo che, in quanto essere
intelligente e creativo, «senza tempo libero non vive da uomo, e mal lo
conoscono gli economisti che altro non sanno procacciargli se non “lavoro e
pane”». In Parlamento prendeva spesso la parola, come il 17 gennaio 1857,
contro il progetto di legge che prevedeva l'obbligo del servizio militare e
criticò la cessione di Nizza e Savoia alla Francia, smascherando le reali
intenzioni che sull'Italia nutriva l'ambiguo Napoleone III. Nel 1860
ricevette la decorazione della Croce di Ufficiale dei Santi Maurizio e Lazzaro
e continuò a scrivere, oltre a collaborare con l'Armonia, l'Unità cattolica, l'Apologista,
il Conservatore, rivista quest'ultima stampata a Bologna e di cui è ritenuto
uno dei fondatori e collaboratori. Morì "giovedì 9 febbraio 1865 alle 3½
in Torino”, come annotano diversi giornali e riviste, non ultima La Civiltà
Cattolica, che gli dedicò un sentito necrologio. Opere: “Saggio intorno
al Socialismo e alle dottrine e tendenze socialistiche,” Torino, Zecchi e Bona,
“Sul valore scientifico e sulle pratiche conseguenze del sistema filosofico di
Rosmini,” Napoli, Societa Editrice Fr. Giannini, “Teorica dell'istituzione del
matrimonio e della guerra moltiforme cui soggiace per Emiliano Avogadro conte
della Motta già Riformatore delle R. Scuole provinciali degli Stati Sardi, a
spese della Societa Editrice Speirani e Tortone, 1853. Teorica dell'istituzione
del matrimonio Parte II che tratta della guerra moltiforme cui soggiace, per E.
Avogadro conte della Motta già deputato al Parlamento Subalpino, Torino,
Edizione Speirani e Figli, 1862. Teorica dell'istituzione del matrimonio e
della guerra a cui soggiace, Parte III che tratta delle difese e dei rimedi,
con una Appendice intorno alla ricerca del principio teorico morale generatore
degli uffizi e dei doveri coniugali,” Torino, Edizione Speirani e Tortone, per
Emiliano Avogadro conte della Motta deputato al Parlamento Nazionale, Torino,
Tipografia Speirani e Tortone, “Teorica dell'istituzione del matrimonio e della
guerra a cui soggiace, Parte IV Documenti per E. Avogadro conte della Motta già
deputato al parlamento nazionale, Torino, Edizione Speirani e Tortone, “Gesù
Cristo nel secolo XIX, Studi religiosi e sociali, Modena, Tipografia
dell'Immacolata Concezione, “La filosofia di Rosmini esaminata da Emiliano Avogadro-conte
Della Motta, Napoli, Societa Editrice Fr. Giannini, “La festa di S. Michele e
il mese di ottobre agli angeli santi, Torino, Marietti, 1Il mese di novembre
dedicato a suffragio dei morti, Torino, Marietti, Le colonne di S. Chiesa.
Omaggi a S. Giovanni Battista e ai Santi Apostoli nel mese di giugno e novena
per la festa dei Santi Principi Pietro e Paolo, Torino, Marietti, 1863. Il mese
di dicembre in adorazione al Verbo Incarnato Gesu nascente e ad onore di Maria
Madre SS.ma, Torino, Marietti, 1863. Opuscoli di carattere storico-giuridico
Rivista retrospettiva di un fatto seguito in Vercelli con osservazioni al
diritto legale di libera censura, Vercelli, De Gaudenzi, 1848. Delle feste
sacre e loro variazioni nel Regno subalpino, Torino, Marietti, Quistioni di
diritto intorno alle istituzioni religiose e alle loro persone e proprietà, in
occasione della Proposta di Legge fatta al Parlamento torinese per la
soppressione di alcune corporazioni, Torino, Marietti, Cenni sulla Congregazione degli Oblati dei SS.
Eusebio e Carlo eretta nella Basilica di S. Andrea in Vercelli e sulla proposta
sua soppressione. Per un elettore Vercellese, Torino, Marietti (non datato).
Parole di conciliazione sulla questione della circolare di S. E. Arcivescovo di
Torino, 1850. Del diritto di petizione e delle petizioni pel ritorno di S. E.
l'Arcivescovo di Torino, 1850. Lo statuto condanna la Legge Siccardi, Torino,
Fontana, 1850. Erroneità e pericoli di alcune teorie ed ipotesi invocate a
sostegno della proposta di Legge di soppressione di vari stabilimenti
religiosi, Torino, Speirani e Tortone, 1855. Alcuni schiarimenti intorno alla
natura della Proprietà Ecclesiastica allo stato di povertà religiosa, ed alle
quistioni relative ai diritti e ai mezzi temporali di sussistenza della Chiesa.
Con una Appendice intorno alla legalità nell'esecuzione della legge 29 maggio
1855 sulle Corporazioni religiose, Torino, Speirani e Tortone, 1856.
Considerazioni sugli affari dell'Italia e del Papa, Torino, Speirani e Tortone,
1860. Una quistione preliminare al Parlamento Torinese, Torino, Speirani e
Tortone, Il progetto di revisione del Codice Civile Albertino e il matrimonio
civile in Italia, Torino, Speirani e Figli, La Rivoluzione e il Ministero
Torinese in faccia al Papa ed all'Episcopato Italiano. Riflessioni
retrospettive e prospettive, Torino, Speirani, L'Armonia, Civiltà Cattolica, Rivista
retrospettiva sopra la discussione delle leggi Siccardi, Unità Cattolica, Famiglia
Avogadro di Collobiano e della Motta, Angelo Ballestreri, segretario della
Famiglia, presso l'Archivio Storico di Torino. Avogadro della Motta, in
Enciclopedia storico-nobiliare italiana, promossa e diretta dal marchese
Vittorio Spreti, I, Milano, Avogadro di
Vigliano F., Pagine di storia Vercellese e Biellese, in Antologia, M. Cassetti,
Vercelli, Avogadro di Vigliano F., Antiche vicende di alcuni feudi Biellesi
degli Avogadro di San Giorgio Monferrato (e poi Conti di Collobiano e di Motta
Alciata), Estratto dalla Illustrazione biellese, XIX, Biella 1941. Corboli G.,
Per le nozze del Conte Federico Sclopis di Salerano e della Contessa Isabella
Avogadro, Cremona, Feraboli, 1838. De Gregory G., Historia della Vercellese
letteratura ed arti, parte IV, Torino, Di Crollallanza G. B., Dizionario
storico-blasonico delle famiglie nobili e notabili italiane estinte e
fiorenti, I, Sala Bolognese 1986.
Dionisotti C., Notizie biografiche dei vercellesi illustri, Biella, Amos, Manno
A., Il patriziato Subalpino. Notizie di fatto storiche, genealogiche, feudali
ed araldiche desunte da documenti, I,
Firenze, I vescovi di Italia. Il
Piemonte, Savio F., Torino, Bocca, Bonvegna G., Filosofia sociale e critica
dello Stato moderno nel pensiero di un legittimista italiano: Emiliano Avogadro
della Motta in Annali Italiani. Rivista di studi storici, anno I, n. 2,
luglio-dicembre 2002, 177–196. Bonvegna
G., Il rapporto tra fede e ragione in Avogadro della Motta, in Sensus
Communis, Valentino V., E. Avogadro
della Motta, un difensore rigoroso dei diritti della Chiesa e del Papa, in
Divinitas, rivista internazionale di ricerca e di critica teologica, anno XLVI,
n. 2 (2003). Volumi e tesi sull'autore Bonvegna G., Emiliano Avogadro della
Motta. Il pensiero filosofico-politico e la critica al socialismo, Tesi di
laurea in Filosofia. Università Cattolica, Milano 2000. De Gaudenzi L., Ultima
parola su di una pretesa ritrattazione del Conte Emiliano Avogadro della
Motta, Mortara, Cortellezzi, 1889. De Gaudenzi L., Un'asserzione del P.
Fr. Paoli D.I.D.C. riguardante il Conte Emiliano Avogadro-della Motta, tolta ad
esame, Mortara, Cortellezzi, 1889. De Gaudenzi P. G., Istruzione del vescovo di
Vigevano al Ven.do Suo Clero sul Matrimonio, Vigevano, Spargella, Manacorda G.,
Storiografia e socialismo, Padova, Martire G., E. Avogadro in Enciclopedia
Cattolica, II, Roma, Omodeo A., L'opera
politica del conte di Cavour, Firenze 1940. Pirri P. , Carteggi del P. L.
Taparelli d'Azeglio, XIV di Biblioteca
di Storia Italiana Recente (1800-1870), Torino 1932. La scienza e la fede, XXIV, Napoli 1851. Spadolini G., L'opposizione
cattolica da porta Pia al '98, 3ª edizione, Firenze 1955. Storia del Parlamento
Italiano, diretta da N. Rodolico, IV,
Palermo 1966. Traniello F., Cattolicesimo conciliarista. Religione e cultura
nella tradizione Rosminiana Lombardo-Piemontese, Milano, Valentino V., Il
matrimonio e la vita coniugale nel pensiero di Emiliano Avogadro, Tesi di
licenza in teologia presso la Facoltà teologica dell'Italia Centrale, Anno
Accademico 1998-1999. Valentino V., Il conte Emiliano Avogadro 1798-1865.
Un'introduzione alla vita e alle opere, Vercelli, Saviolo, 2001. Valentino V.,
Un laico tra i teologi, Vercelli, Valentino V., E. Avogadro della Motta, Il
pensiero di V. Gioberti, Genova, Verucci G., E. Avogadro in Dizionario
Biografico Italiano, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana, IV, Roma. Guido Verucci, Emiliano Avogadro
della Motta, in Dizionario biografico degli italiani, 4, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana, 1962.
Opere di Emiliano Avogadro della Motta, .
Emiliano Della Motta (Avogadro), su storia.camera.it, Camera dei
deputati.
motterlini: Grice: “I like Motterlini – he has
written, echoing Kant, a critique of economic reason, which Stalnaker should
read before saying I’m Kantian rather than Futilitarian!” -- Matteo Motterlini (Milano),
filosofo. Specializzato in filosofia della scienza, economia comportamentale e
neuroeconomia. È noto per i suoi lavori in ambito psicoeconomico su
processi decisionali, emozioni e razionalità umana; e per le sue ricerche in
ambito epistemologico sulla razionalità della scienza e il metodo scientifico, con
particolare riferimento ai contributi di Imre Lakatos e Paul Feyerabend. Attualmente
è E.ON Professor in Behavior Change. Environment, Heath and Education
all'Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele di Milanodove è Professore di Logica e
Filosofia della Scienza. È stato Consigliere per le Scienze Sociali e
Comportamentali della Presidenza del Consiglio dei Ministri (DPCM 5 maggio )
(dal 5.4. all'1.6.). Laureatosi in filosofia all'Milano, dove ha portato
a termine il proprio dottorato in filosofia della scienza, ha conseguito il
Master of Science in Logic and Scientific Method e ottenuto il Graduate Diploma
in Economics alla London School of Economics and Political Science. È stato
ricercatore di economia politica e professore associato di filosofia della
scienza presso l'Trento; Visiting Associate Professor al Department of Social
and Decision Sciences della Carnegie Mellon University di Pittsburgh, Visiting
Research Scholar al Department of Psychology della UCLA. Dal 2007 è Professore
di filosofia della scienza presso l'Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele.
Tra gli altri incarichi è collaboratore de Il Corriere Economia, Il Corriere
della Sera e Il Sole 24 Ore, per cui ha curato per anni il blog Controvento. È
stato consulente scientifico di MilanLab, A.C. Milan, fondatore e direttore di
Anima FinLab, di Anima Sgr, centro di ricerca di finanza comportamentale e
Scientific advisor di MarketPsychData, Ls Angeles. È direttore del CRESA
(Centro di ricerca in epistemologia sperimentale e applicata), da lui fondato a
Milano nel 2007 presso la facoltà di filosofia dell'Università Vita-Salute San
Raffaele. I progetti di ricerca del centro si concentrano su vari aspetti della
cognizione umana, dal linguaggio al rapporto tra mente e cervello,
dall'economia comportamentale alle neuroscienze cognitive della decisione, con
particolare attenzione all'indagine sperimentale multidisciplinare e alle sue
ricadute pratiche e applicative (per esempio nell'ambito del policy making e
dell'evidence-based policy). A inizio , ha avviato il progetto di finanza
comportamentale per Schroder Italia, dal quale è nato Investimente, un test
psicofinanziario al servizio di risparmiatori, promotori finanziari e private
banker, per raccogliere e quindi analizzare i dati riguardanti le decisioni di investimento
e i bias cognitivi nell'ambito della gestione del risparmio. Attualmente
è direttore dell'E.ON Customer Behavior Lab e Chief Behavior Officer di E.ON
Italia; stesso incarico che ricopre per il Gruppo Ospedaliero San Donato.
Studi e ricerche Pro e contro il metodo I suoi primi lavori analizzano la
proposta falsificazionista di Karl Popper, rivelando le difficoltà in cui si
imbatte il progetto demarcazionista e anti-induttivista. Affrontano quindi il
modo in cui Imre Lakatos ha preteso superare alcune di queste difficoltà, e
insieme raccogliere la ‘sfida di Duhem' circa il carattere olistico del
controllo empirico, tenendo conto delle immagini che scienziati e matematici
hanno avuto della loro stessa pratica e riferendosi a particolari casi storici
come termine di confronto. La sua ricostruzione del progetto filosofico di
Lakatos si avvale di un'originale analisi del materiale dell'Archivio Lakatos.
Una selezione del quale, accompagnata da un importante apparato critico, è
pubblicata in italiano Sull'orlo della scienza e in edizione ampliata per
University of Chicago Press (1999, For and Against Method). Nel suo
Reconstructing Lakatos (Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science) e
nella monografia Imre Lakatos. Scienza, matematica e storia avanza una nuova
interpretazione del progetto razionalista di Lakatos come il prodotto di una
peculiare combinazione delle idee di Popper e di Hegel. Ciò è motivo della
straordinaria fecondità del pensiero lakatosiano, ma anche di una inesauribile
tensione al suo interno. Una tensione che viene illustrata affrontando la
relazione tra filosofia della scienza e storia della scienza in riferimento
alla questione della valutazione di una data metodologia in base alle
'ricostruzioni razionali' a cui essa conduce. Nell'idea che le varie
metodologie vadano confrontate con la storia della scienza è contenuto il germe
di una logica della scoperta in cui i canoni non siano fissati una volta per
sempre, ma mutano nel tempo, anche se con ritmi non necessariamente uguali a quelli
delle teorie scientifiche. Metodo e cognizione in economia In una fase
successiva i suoi studi si sono focalizzati su questioni di metodologia
dell'economia da una prospettiva interdisciplinare che combina riflessione
epistemologica, scienze cognitive, ed economia sperimentale con aspetti più
tecnici di teoria della scelta e della decisione individuale in condizioni
d'incertezza. Le ricerche di questo periodo analizzano criticamente lo status
delle assunzioni della teoria della scelta razionale, valutando l'impatto delle
violazioni comportamentali sistematiche alle restrizioni assiomatiche imposte
dai modelli normativi di razionalità. Avanzano quindi ragioni epistemologiche
per la composizione della frattura economia e psicologia cognitiva in ambito della
teoria della decisione; e suggeriscono di guardare ai recenti risultati
dell'economia cognitiva in prospettiva di una nuova sintesi 'quasi-razionale'
in cui i modelli neoclassici, integrati da teorie psicologiche che tengano
conto dei limiti cognitivi dei soggetti decisionali, rafforzano le previsioni
del comportamento economico degli esseri umani. Neuroeconomia e
evidence-based policy Le sue ricerche indagano le basi neurobiologiche della
razionalità umana attraverso lo studio dei correlati neurali dei processi
decisionali in contesti economico-finanziari, con particolare attenzione al
ruolo svolto dalle emozioni, dal rimpianto, e dall'apprendimento sociale.
Parallelamente progetta ed esperimenta i modi in cui i risultati dell'economia
comportamentale e della neuroeconomia possono informare politiche
pubbliche più efficaci e basate sull'evidenza. Queste ricerche sono
oggetto dei corsi di Filosofia della scienza e di Economia cognitiva e
neuroeconomia che insegna all'università San Raffaele, e hanno altresì trovato
diffusione attraverso numerosi articoli divulgativi e due libri, Economia
emotiva e Trappole mentali. Il suo ultimo libro è Psicoeconomia di Charlie
Brown. Strategia per una società più felice. Opere: “Sull'orlo della scienza,” –
Grice: “Must say that ‘orlo’ is a genial word, wish Popper knew it!” -- Imre Lakatos,
Paul K. Feyerabend: Pro e contro il metodo, Cortina, Milano. Popper, Il Saggiatore-Flammarion, Milano, For
and Against Method. Including Lakatos's Lectures on Method and the
Lakatos-Feyerabend Correspondence', University of Chicago Press, Chicago, Imre
Lakatos. Scienza, matematica e storia, Il Saggiatore, Milano, Decisioni
mediche. Un approccio cognitive, Raffaello Cortina, Milano. Critica della
ragione economica. Tre saggi: Mc Fadden, Kahneman, Smith, Il Saggiatore,
Milano, Economia cognitiva & sperimentale, Università Bocconi Editore, Milano
La dimensione cognitiva dell'errore in medicina, Fondazione Smith Kline, Franco
Angeli, Milano Economia emotiva
(Emotional Economics), Rizzoli, Milano Trappole mentali, Rizzoli, Milano Mente,
Mercati, Decisioni. Introduzione all'economia cognitiva e sperimentale, Egea,
Milano Psicoeconomia di Charlie Brown.
Strategia per una società più felice, Rizzoli, Milano Alcuni articoli
scientifici, Lakatos between the Hegelian devil and the Popperian blue sea. In
Kampis, G., Kvasz, L., Stoeltzner, M. Appraising Lakatos, Mathematics,
Methodology, and the Man. Vienna Circle Institute Library, Dordrecht: Kluwer, Reconstructing
Lakatos. A reassessment of Lakatos' philosophical project in light of the
Lakatos Archive , Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science , Considerazioni
epistemologiche e mitologiche sulla relazione tra psicologia ed economia,
Sistemi intelligenti, Il Mulino, Metodo e standard di valutazione in economia.
Dall'apriorismo a Friedman, Studi Economici, Milano, In search of the
neurobiological basis of decision-making, explanation, reduction and emergence,
in P. Churchand, M. Di Francesco (eds.) Functional Neurology, Understanding
Others' Regret: A fMRI Study, con Nicola Canessa, Cinzia Di Dio, Daniela
Perani, Paola Scifo, Stefano F. Cappa, Giacomo Rizzolatti, PlosONE', Vai in
laboratorio e capirai il mercato (con Francesco Guala) Prefazione a Vernon
Smith, La razionalità in economia. Tra teoria e analisi sperimentale, IBL,
Milano. . Neuroeconomia e Teoria del prospetto, voci Enciclopedia dell'economia
Garzanti, Milano. . Learning from other peoples experience: a neuroimaging
study of decisional interactive-learning, con Nicola Canessa, Federica
Alemanno, Daniela Perani, Stefano Cappa, Neuroimage, The functional and
structural neural basis of individual differences in loss aversion, con Nicola
Canessa, Stefano F.Cappa et. al., The Journal of Neuroscience, Choice
Architecture Matters: The Case of Investor Protection within the Italian
Crowdfunding Market”with Elisa Broli European Company Law, “Testing donation menus: on charitable giving
for cancer researche vidence from a natural field experiment” (con Marianna
Baggio), Behavioural Public Policy, Cambridge University Press A.C. Milan
Investimente. Test dell'investitore consapevole Recensione di Ian Hacking sulla The London
Review of Books IlSole24Ore 22.5.//ilsole24ore.com/art/cultura/-05-18/motterlini-spinta-riforme--shtml?uuid=ADAaR2J
ASito personale, su matteomotterlini.it. Sito CRESA, su cresa.eu.
Motus motivatumGrice, “Must our motives be
impure?” “Obligation cashes out in motivation.” Motivatum -- motivation, a
property central in motivational explanations of intentional conduct. To assert
that Grice is driving to Lord’s today because she wants to see his cricket team
play and believes that they are playing today at Lord’s is to offer an explanation
of Grice’s action. On a popular interpretation, the assertion mentions a pair
of attitudes: a desire and a belief. Grice’s s desire is a paradigmatic
motivational attitude in that it inclines him to bring about the satisfaction
of that very attitude. The primary function of motivational attitudes is to
bring about their own satisfaction by inducing the agent to undertake a
suitable course of action, and, arguably, any attitude that has that function
is, ipso facto, a motivational one. The related thesis that only attitudes
having this function are motivational
or, more precisely, motivation-constituting is implausible. Grice hopes that the
Oxfordshire Cricket Team won yesterday. Plainly, his hope cannot bring about its
own satisfaction, since Grice has no control over the past. Even so, the hope
seemingly may motivate action e.g., Grice’s searching for sports news on her
car radio, in which case the hope is motivation-constituting. Some philosophers
have claimed that our beliefs that we are morally required to take a particular
course of action are motivation-constituting, and such beliefs obviously do not
have the function of bringing about their own satisfaction i.e., their truth.
However, the claim is controversial, as is the related claim that beliefs of
this kind are “besires” that is, not
merely beliefs but desires as well. Refs.: “Desire, belief, and besire.” Motus
-- motivantional explanation -- Grice: the explanatory-justificatory
distinction“To explain” is not to explicate, but to render ‘plain’To justify is
hardly to render ‘plain’! Grice is aware of this, because he does not use the
‘explicatory-justificatory’ distinction. Therefore, the ‘justificatory’ is
conceptually priora philosopher looks for justificationhardly to render stuff
plain“Quite the opposite: my claim to fame is to follow the alleged
professional duty of a philosophy professor: to render obscure what is clear,
and vice versa!” -- motivational explanation -- a type of explanation of
goal-directed behavior where the explanans appeals to the motives of the agent.
The explanation usually is in the following form: Smith swam hard in order to
win the race. Here the description of what Smith did identifies the behavior to
be explained, and the phrase that follows ‘in order to’ identifies the goal or
the state of affairs the obtaining of which was the moving force behind the
behavior. The general presumption is that the agent whose behavior is being
explained is capable of deliberating and acting on the decisions reached as a
result of the deliberation. Thus, it is dubious whether the explanation
contained in ‘The plant turned toward the sun in order to receive more light’
is a motivational explanation. Two problems are thought to surround
motivational explanations. First, since the state of affairs set as the goal
is, at the time of the action, non-existent, it can only act as the “moving
force” by appearing as the intentional object of an inner psychological state
of the agent. Thus, motives are generally desires for specific objects or
states of affairs on which the agent acts. So motivational explanation is
basically the type of explanation provided in folk psychology, and as such it inherits
all the alleged problems of the latter. And second, what counts as a motive for
an action under one description usually fails to be a motive for the same
action under a different description. My motive for saying “hello” may have
been my desire to answer the phone, but my motive for saying “hello” loudly was
to express my irritation at the person calling me so late at night. Motus-motivus
-- “Obligation cashes on motivation.” Grice, “Must our motives be impure?”
-- motivational internalism, the view
that moral motivation is internal to moral duty or the sense of duty. The view
represents the contemporary understanding of Hume’s thesis that morality is
essentially practical. Hume went on to point out the apparent logical gap
between statements of fact, which express theoretical judgments, and statements
about what ought to be done, which express practical judgments. Motivational
internalism offers one explanation for this gap. No motivation is internal to
the recognition of facts. The specific internal relation the view affirms is
that of necessity. Thus, motivational internalists hold that if one sees that
one has a duty to do a certain action or that it would be right to do it, then
necessarily one has a motive to do it. For example, if one sees that it is
one’s duty to donate blood, then necessarily one has a motive to donate blood.
Motivational externalism, the opposing view, denies this relation. Its
adherents hold that it is possible for one to see that one has a duty to do a
certain action or that it would be right to do it yet have no motive to do it.
Motivational externalists typically, though not universally, deny any real gap
between theoretical and practical judgments. Motivational internalism takes
either of two forms, rationalist and anti-rationalist. Rationalists, such as
Plato and Kant, hold that the content or truth of a moral requirement
guarantees in those who understand it a motive of compliance.
Anti-rationalists, such as Hume, hold that moral judgment necessarily has some
affective or volitional component that supplies a motive for the relevant
action but that renders morality less a matter of reason and truth than of
feeling or commitment. It is also possible in the abstract to draw an analogous
distinction between two forms of motivational externalism, cognitivist and
noncognitivist, but because the view springs from an interest in assimilating
practical judgment to theoretical judgment, its only influential form has been
cognitivist.
musatti: Grice: “Musatti reminds me of Malcolm, “Tonight I had a dream,””
– Grice: “Musatti has explored the implicatures of ‘who’s afraid of the big bad
wolf?’, which comes strictly from Grimm – this is a rhetorical question – and
Grimm is implicating that nobody should!” -- Ccesare luigi eugenio musatti
(Dolo), filosofo. Tra i primi che posero le basi della psicoanalisi, in Italia
. Nacque in località Casello 12 a Dolo, sulla riviera del Brenta, nella
casa di campagna del nonno paterno in cui i parenti erano soliti trascorrere la
villeggiatura. Figlio di Elia Musatti, ebreo veneziano e deputato
socialista amico di Giacomo Matteotti, e della napoletana Emma Leanza,
cattolica non praticante, Cesare non fu né circonciso, né battezzato (durante
le persecuzioni razziali si era procurato un falso certificato di battesimo
dalla parrocchia di Santa Maria in Transpontina di Roma) e non professò mai
alcun credo religioso. Frequentò il liceo Foscarini di Venezia, poi si
iscrisse dapprima alla facoltà di Scienze dell'Padova per il corso di Ingegneria,
e immediatamente dopo alla facoltà di Lettere e Filosofia, dove si laureò in
filosofia il 3 novembre 1921 con 110 e lode. Dopo la laurea, nel 1921 si
iscrisse per due anni al corso di Matematica della facoltà di Scienze
matematiche, fisiche e naturali di Padova, ma non sostenne esame alcuno.
Giovinezza A diciannove anni fu chiamato a Roma per il servizio di leva. Dopo
un periodo di addestramento a Torino, nel 1917 fu mandato al fronte come
ufficiale, con impegni marginali. Finita la guerra tornò a Padova per terminare
gli studi. Sulla cattedra di Psicologia Sperimentale c'era Vittorio Benussi,
allora chiamato per chiara fama nel 1919 a insegnare a Padova dall'Graz.
Musatti si laureò in filosofia nel 1921 e l'anno successivo divenne assistente
volontario del Laboratorio di psicologia sperimentale. Nel 1927 Benussi si
uccise con il cianuro a causa di una grave forma di disturbo bipolare,
lasciando tutto nelle mani di Musatti e di Silvia De Marchi, anch'essa
assistente volontaria, che poi divenne sua moglie. Il suicidio di Benussi fu
scoperto da Musatti, il quale però lo nascose per paura di ripercussioni
negative sulla psicologia italiana in una situazione di fragilità e precarietà
accademica, sottoposta a pressioni da parte sia del regime fascista, con le sue
istanze gentiliane, che della Chiesa Cattolica. Negli anni ottanta Musatti
rivelò che Benussi s'era suicidato, non era morto a causa di un malore.
Nel 1928 Musatti divenne direttore del Laboratorio di Psicologia dell'Padova.
Portò in Italia la Psicologia della Forma con importanti lavori di livello
internazionale. Dopo aver diffuso in Italia la psicologia della Gestalt,
divenne il primo studioso italiano di psicoanalisi. Studiando la
psicologia della suggestione e dell'ipnosi, introdotta in Italia da Vittorio
Benussi, approdò alla psicoanalisi, sulla quale tenne il primo corso
universitario italiano. Il corso si tenne presso l'Padova nell'anno accademico
1933-34. Musatti divenne allora uno dei primi e più importanti rappresentanti
italiani della psicoanalisi. Nell'Italia degli anni '30 le teorie di Freud non
erano state accolte bene né dalle Università, né dalla Chiesa cattolica, a
causa dell'ideologia culturale gentiliana assunta dal fascismo. La Società
psicoanalitica italiana, fondata nel 1925, venne limitata anche dalle leggi
razziali fasciste (1938), che colpirono i membri ebrei della Società. Benché
non fosse ebreo (poiché figlio di madre cattolica), Musatti fu allontanato
dall'insegnamento universitario che svolgeva presso l'Università degli Studi di
Urbino e declassato ad insegnante di liceo. Maturità Nel 1940 fu nominato
professore di Filosofia al Liceo Parini di Milano. Nel 1943 Musatti si
ritrovò con Lelio Basso, Ferrazzutto e altri vecchi socialisti con l'intento di
creare un partito erede del Partito Socialista Italiano; ebbe l'incarico di
trovare denaro per una prima organizzazione e di allacciare rapporti col
Partito Comunista clandestino. Musatti lavorò anche durante la guerra. Nel
1944, nel periodo dell'occupazione nazista, fu tratto in salvo dall'avvocato
Paolo Toffanin (1890-1971), fratello di Giuseppe Toffanin, che lo aiutò a
trasferirsi a Ivrea, ospite dell'amico Adriano Olivetti. Con il suo sostegno
fondò un centro di psicologia del lavoro. Ricoprì anche l'incarico di direttore
della Scuola Allievi Meccanici, scuola aperta per formare operai meccanici
specializzati. Successivamente fu richiamato dall'Esercito per andare sul
fronte francese. Nel 1947 ottenne all'Università degli Studi di Milano la
prima cattedra di Psicologia costituita nel dopoguerra in Italia, presso la
Facoltà di Lettere e Filosofia. Vi insegnò per venti anni. A Milano ebbe il
periodo più florido della sua ricerca scientifica: gli studenti affollavano le
sue lezioni. Musatti fu il leader del movimento psicoanalitico italiano nei
primi anni del dopoguerra. A quel periodo risale il suo “Trattato di
Psicoanalisi”, pubblicato da Einaudi nel 1949. Nel 1955 divenne direttore della
“Rivista di psicoanalisi”. Nel 1963 è presidente del Centro Milanese di
Psicoanalisi fondato da Franco Ciprandi, Renato Sigurtà e Pietro Veltri, che
gli verrà intitolato dopo la sua morte. Nel 1976 è diventato curatore della
edizione italiana delle Opere di Sigmund Freud, della Casa Editrice Bollati
Boringhieri di Torino.. Vecchiaia La località a lui dedicata
Musatti scrisse anche libri di letteratura, tra cui Il pronipote di Giulio
Cesare, che nel 1980 gli fece vincere il Premio Viareggio. Fu eletto per due
volte consigliere comunale di Milano nella lista del PSIUP e fu anche
consulente del Tribunale dei Minori del capoluogo lombardo. Sostenne sempre la
pace, il progresso dei lavoratori, l'emancipazione femminile ed i diritti
civili. Cesare Musatti era ateo, come ebbe a dichiarare in più
occasioni, l'ultima delle quali in uno dei "martedì letterari" del
Casinò di Sanremo. Morì nella sua abitazione di via Sabbatini a Milano il 21
marzo 1989; l'indomani dopo una cerimonia laica di commiato celebrata in forma
strettamente privata, la sua salma venne cremata a Lambrate. Le sue ceneri sono
tumulate, secondo le sue ultime volontà, nel cimitero comunale di Brinzio (VA),
località in cui era solito trascorrere i periodi di vacanza. L'archivio
di Cesare Musatti è conservato presso l'AspiArchivio Storico della Psicologia
Italiana dell'Università degli Studi di Milano-Bicocca. Il comune di Dolo
ha ribattezzato la sua località natale Casello 12 località Cesare Musatti e gli
ha intitolato il locale istituto professionale. Musatti e il suicidio di
Benussi Anche dopo la rivelazione che si era trattato di un suicidio, Musatti
non parlò mai volentieri della morte del maestro. Nel generale silenzio dello
studioso di Dolo emerge un'intervista uscita sul quotidiano El País del 21
ottobre 1985. Nell'intervista Musatti confessa di sognare a volte che in una
caserma dei carabinieri in cui viene tradotto, il commissario lo interroga
sulla morte di tre sue mogli (si sposò quattro volte), decedute tragicamente, e
di Vittorio Benussi. A fine colloquio il militare intima a Musatti di
confessare di aver ucciso il maestro per prendere la cattedra di psicologia.
«Io gli rispondoprosegue Musatti, da buon psicoanalistache sicuramente nel mio
subconscio mi sono sentito responsabile per questa e per altre morti. Il
commissario, che non capiva nulla di subconscio, decide: “Mi spiace professore,
ma devo arrestarla”. Io allora gli rispondo: ”Non è possibile commissario,
perché si tratta di delitti commessi più di cinquant'anni fa, e quindi sono
prescritti!”». Note Il nome Cesare
è un riferimento al prozio Cesare Musatti, medico pediatra (uno dei primi in
Italia) che aveva visitato il piccolo, nato settimino; Luigi era il nome del
bonno materno (Luigi Leanza, morto in carcere, partecipò alla rivolta
antiborbonica del 1848); Eugenio era il nome di un altro prozio paterno, lo
storico Eugenio Musatti; cfr. MusattiIX-XIII
"Forse la psicoanalisi in Italia è nata e morta con Cesare
Musatti" (Umberto Galimberti, Idee: il catalogo è questo, Milano,
Feltrinelli) Il nome allude alla fermata
della tranvia Padova-Malcontenta-Fusina che il nonno, presidente della Società
Veneta Lagunare, odierna ACTV, aveva fatto aprire per raggiungere più
agevolmente Venezia.
MusattiIX-XIII. Archivio
dell'Università degli Studi di Padova, Carriere scolastiche della Facoltà di
Lettere e filosofia, reg. 2, pag. 174
Archivio dell'Università degli Studi di Padova, Carriere scolastiche
della Facoltà di scienze matematiche, fisiche e naturali, Opuscolo del Centro
Milanese di Psicoanalisi, a cura del Comitato Direttivo, redatto da L.
AmbrosianoCapazziGammaro Moroni, L.Reatto, L.Schwartz, M.Sforza, M.Stufflesser,
p.4, 1994-1996 Milano Per una storia del
Centro Milanese di PsicoanalisiChiari, Seminario tenuto il 15 gennaio 2009
presso il Centro Milanese di Psicoanalisi Cesare Musatti, 15 gennaio Milano Sigmund Freud, Opere, Cesare Musatti. Torino,
Bollati Boringhieri, pSilvia Giacomoni, Cerimonia privata per Cesare Musatti,
la Repubblica, Musatti è consultabile sul
dell'Aspi, all'indirizzo web AspiArchivio storico della psicologia
italiana, Università degli studi di Milano-Bicocca. 7 settembre (archiviato il 12 luglio ). D. Mont D'Arpizio, Vittorio Benussi, Padre
della psicologia padovana[collegamento interrotto], in La Difesa del popolo 2
marzo 200835 Questo testo proviene in
parte dalla relativa voce del progetto Mille anni di scienza in Italia, opera
del Museo Galileo. Istituto Museo di Storia della Scienza di Firenze (home
page), pubblicata sotto licenza Creative Commons CC-BY-3.0 Cesare Musatti, Mia
sorella gemella la psicoanalisi, 1ª ed., Pordenone, Edizioni Studio Tesi,Luciano
Mecacci, Cesare L. Musatti, voce dell'Enciclopedia italiana di scienze, lettere
ed arti. Il contributo italiano alla storia del pensiero. Ottava appendice,
Roma, Istituto della Enciclopedia Italiana,. Opere: “Analisi del concetto di
realtà empirica,” Il Solco, Città di Castello, “Forma e assimilazione,” in:
Archivio italiano di psicologia, “Elementi di psicologia della testimonianza,
nuova edizione in Biblioteca Universale Rizzoli, Forma e movimento, Officine
grafiche C. Ferrari, Venezia 1937, (Estratto da: Atti del Reale Istituto veneto
di scienze, lettere ed arti 97, 1937-1938, seconda parte) 1938: Gli elementi
della psicologia della forma, Gruppo Universitario Fascista, Padova 1949:
Trattato di psicoanalisi, Paolo Boringhieri, Torino 1961: Super io individuale
e Super io collettivo, Leo S. Olschki Firenze, Condizioni dell'esperienza e fondazione della
psicologia, Editrice Universitaria, Firenze, Riflessioni sul pensiero
psicoanalitico e incursioni nel mondo delle immagini, Paolo Boringhieri, Torino,
Svevo e la psicoanalisi, Leo S. Olschki, Firenze, I rapporti personali
Freud-Jung attraverso il carteggio, Leo S. Olschki, Firenze, Commemorazione
accademica, Leo S. Olschki, Firenze 1978: Nino Valeri, Leo S. Olschki Firenze, Il
pronipote di Giulio Cesare, Mondadori Milano 1981: A ciascuno la sua morte, Leo
S. Olschki, Firenze 1982: Hanno cancellato Livorno, Leo S. Olschki, Firenze, Mia
sorella gemella la psicoanalisi, Editori Riuniti, Roma 1983: Una famiglia
diversa ed un analista di campagna, Leo S. Olschki, Firenze 1983: Questa notte
ho fatto un sogno, Editori Riuniti, Roma 1987: Chi ha paura del lupo cattivo?,
Editori Riuniti, Roma 1988: Psicoanalisti e pazienti a teatro, a teatro,
Mondadori, Milano, Leggere Freud, Bollati Boringhieri, Torino, Curar nevrotici
con la propria autoanalisi, Mondadori, Milano : Geometrie non-euclidee e
problema della conoscenza, Aurelio Molaro, prefazione di Mauro Antonelli,
Mimesis, Milano,Treccani.itEnciclopedie on line, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia
Italiana. Cesare Musatti, in Dizionario
biografico degli italiani, Istituto dell'Enciclopedia Italiana. siusa.archivi.beniculturali.it,
Sistema Informativo Unificato per le Soprintendenze Archivistiche. Opere su openMLOL, Horizons Unlimited srl. italiana di Cesare Musatti, su Catalogo
Vegetti della letteratura fantastica, Fantascienza.com.
mustè: marcello mustè (Roma),
filosofo. Laureato in filosofia con una tesi su Marx, dal 1984 al 1987 è stato
borsista dell'Istituto italiano per gli studi storici di Napoli, dove ha svolto
attività didattica e di ricerca, collaborando con Gennaro Sasso. Dal 1985 al
1987 è stato redattore della “nuova serie” della “Rivista trimestrale”. Nel
1991 ha conseguito il titolo di dottore di ricerca alla Sapienza. Dal 1997 al
2005 ha lavorato alla "Fondazione Giovanni Gentile per gli Studi
Filosofici" dell'Università "La Sapienza" in qualità di
“Segretario e Curatore dell'archivio e della biblioteca di Gentile”. È stato
professore a contratto di Storia della filosofia dal 2001 al 2007. Attualmente
è professore di filosofia teoretica all'Università La Sapienza di Roma. È
membro del Consiglio scientifico della Fondazione Gramsci e della Commissione
scientifica per la Edizione nazionale degli scritti di Antonio Gramsci. Ha
collaborato con l'Enciclopedia Italiana, in particolare ai volumi: Il
contributo italiano alla storia del pensiero. Filosofia (ottava appendice),
Enciclopedia machiavelliana e Croce e Gentile. La cultura italiana e l'Europa.
Ha diretto la rivista "Novecento" dal 1991 al 1999. Fa parte del
Comitato scientifico di alcune riviste, tra cui: "Giornale critico della
filosofia italiana", "Annali della Fondazione Gramsci", “La
Cultura”, “Filosofia italiana”. Scrive su diverse riviste scientifiche, tra le
quali, con maggiore continuità: "Giornale critico della filosofia
italiana", "La Cultura", "Studi storici",
"Filosofia italiana". Nel è
stato nominato dal Ministero dei beni culturali Segretario del "Comitato
nazionale per il bicentenario della nascita di Bertrando Spaventa".
Dal al
ha insegnato Ermeneutica filosofica, in qualità di Visiting Professor,
alla Pontificia Università Antonianum. Ricerche Le sue ricerche si sono
rivolte alla storia della filosofia italiana, con contributi dedicati
all'idealismo e al marxismo. Per quanto riguarda l'idealismo italiano, ha
indagato i momenti e le figure fondamentali (sino al profilo complessivo
pubblicato nel 2008) e le premesse nella filosofia dell'Ottocento, specie in
relazione al pensiero di Vincenzo Gioberti (soprattutto con il libro del 2000
su La scienza ideale). Di particolare interesse gli studi su Bertrando Spaventa
e le monografie su Adolfo Omodeo e Benedetto Croce. Ha dedicato saggi e
ricerche al pensiero di Antonio Gramsci e ad altri momenti del pensiero
marxista italiano: del è la monografia
su Marxismo e filosofia della praxis, che ricostruisce la storia del marxismo
italiano da Labriola a Gramsci. Sono noti i suoi studi sul pensiero politico
nell'Italia contemporanea, con particolare riguardo alle figure di Franco
Rodano, Felice Balbo, Augusto Del Noce. Ha approfondito lo studio
dell'opera di Marx e in generale la storia della filosofia tedesca tra Hegel e
Nietzsche. Particolare attenzione ha poi rivolto (con il libro su La storia e con altri scritti, tra cui
quelli sull'evento e sulla teoria delle fonti) alle questioni specifiche della
teoria della storiografia. Metodi Conduce l’indagine teoretica in stretta
relazione con gli studi di storia della filosofia e di storia della
storiografia, in generale nell’ambito della storia delle idee, adottando un
metodo storico-critico che spesso privilegia l’uso di fonti archivistiche e di
documentazione inedita. Il suo metodo cerca di coniugare l'analisi strutturale
delle opere filosofiche con la ricerca filologica sulle fonti e sulla
tradizione dei testi, con particolare riguardo ai processi di lungo periodo
della filosofia italiana moderna e contemporanea. Opere: Adolfo Omodeo.
Storiografia e pensiero politico, Il Mulino, Bologna, Benedetto Croce, Morano,
Napoli Franco Rodano. Critica delle
ideologie e ricerca della laicità, Il Mulino, Bologna (Curatela) Carteggio Croce-Antoni, Il Mulino,
Bologna Politica e storia in Bloch, Aracne, Roma La scienza ideale. Filosofia e
politica in Gioberti, Rubbettino, Soveria Mannelli, Franco Rodano. Laicità,
democrazia, società del superfluo, Studium, Roma (Curatela) Grice: “’superfluo’ is possibly one of the
most unsuperfluous words in the Italian philosophical dictionary – cf. “I was
in New York, which was black out.” -- Gioberti, Il governo federativo, Gangemi
Editore, Roma (Curatela) Franco Rodano, Cristianesimo e società opulenta,
Edizioni di storia e letteratura, Roma, Il giudizio sul nazismo. Le interpretazioni
-- La storia: teoria e metodi, Carocci, Roma, La filosofia dell'idealismo
italiano, -- Grice: “filosofia” is superfluous here, seeing that idealism
already ENTAILS philosophy!” -- Carocci, Roma, Croce, Carocci, Roma Tra
filosofia e storiografia. Hegel, Croce e altri studi, Aracne, Roma La prassi e il valore. La filosofia
dell'essere di Balbo, Aracne, Roma Marxismo
e filosofia della praxis: da Labriola a Gramsci, Viella, Roma (Con Giuseppe Vacca) In cammino con Gramsci,
Viella, Roma. L'ermeneutica di Gadamer, in «Rivista trimestrale», Il problema
del mondo nel «Tractatus» di Wittgenstein, in «Rivista trimestrale», Le fonti
del giudizio marxiano sulla Rivoluzione francese nei «Kreuznacher Hefte», in
«Annali dell'Istituto Italiano per gli Studi Storici», L' «orizzonte liberale»
di Dahrendorf, in «Critica marxista», Sturzo e il popolarismo nel giudizio di
Gobetti, in Sturzo e la democrazia europea, Laterza, Roma-Bari, Croce e il
problema del diritto, in «Novecento», Metodo storico e senso della libertà. Omodeo
e i problemi della storiografia crociana, in «La Cultura», Omodeo. Il pensiero
politico, in «Annali dell'Istituto Italiano per gli Studi Storici», Libertà e
storicismo assoluto: per un'interpretazione del liberalismo di Croce, in Croce
e Gentile fra tradizione nazionale e filosofia europea, Editori Riuniti, Roma, Arendt
e la società civile democratica, in «Novecento», Sul giudizio politico, in «Novecento», Il
marxismo politico nell'interpretazione di Noce, in «Poietica», Gioberti e
Cartesio, in Bibliopolis, Napoli,Comunismo e democrazia, in La democrazia nel
pensiero politico del Novecento, Aracne, Roma, Guido Calogero, in «Belfagor»,Gioberti
e Leopardi, in «La Cultura», Verità e storia, in «Storiografia», Il significato
della morale nella filosofia di Gioberti, in Rosmini e Gioberti. G. Beschin e
L. Cristellon, Morcelliana, Brescia, Il destino dell'evento nella “nuova
storia” francese, in «La Cultura», Carattere e svolgimento delle prime teorie
estetiche di Croce, «La Cultura», Liberalismo
etico e liberismo economico, in Croce filosofo liberale, -- cf. Grice, “Do not
multiply liberalisms beyond necessity: ‘liberalismo semiotico’” – Grice: “Muste
is very witty in distinguishing between liberalism and liberrism!” -- M. Reale,
LUISS University Press, Roma, La teoria della storia in Croce, in «Giornale
critico della filosofia italiana», L'idea di “Risorgimento” in Gioberti, in
«Quaderni della Fondazione Centro Studi Noce», Il significato delle fonti
storiche, in «La Cultura», La storia:
teoria e metodi, in «History and Theory», Il passaggio all'anti-fascismo di Croce,
in Anni di svolta. Crisi e trasformazione nel pensiero politico della prima età
contemporanea, F.M. Di Sciullo, Rubbettino, Soveria Mannelli, Alterità e
principio del dialogo in Guido Calogero, in L'idea e la differenza. Noi e gli
altri, ipotesi di inclusione nel dibattito contemporaneo, M.P. Paternò, Rubbettino,
Soveria Mannelli Il principio del nous nella filosofia di Calogero, in «La
Cultura», La filosofia come sapere storico, in Il Novecento di Eugenio Garin.
Atti del Convegno di studi, G. Vacca e S. Ricci, Istituto della Enciclopedia
Italiana, Roma, Gioberti, in Il contributo italiano alla storia del pensiero.
Filosofia, M. Ciliberto, Istituto della Enciclopedia Italiana, Roma , Lo
storicismo italiano nel secondo dopoguerra, in Il contributo italiano alla
storia del pensiero. Filosofia, M. Ciliberto, Istituto della Enciclopedia
Italiana, Roma, Il problema della libertà nella filosofia di Scaravelli, in «La
Cultura», La libertà del volere nella filosofia di Croce, in Filosofia e
politica. G. Cesarale, M. Mustè, S. Petrucciani, Mimesis, Milano, Il senso
della dialettica nella filosofia di Spaventa, in "Filosofia
italiana", apr. Storia, metodo,
verità, in «La Cultura», , Gentile e Marx, «Giornale critico della filosofia
italiana», Togliatti e De Luca, «Studi storici», Gentile e Socrate, (Grice: cf.
caricature of Gentile as Aristotele in ‘La scuola d’Atene”) -- in La bandiera
di Socrate. Momenti di storiografia filosofica italiana nel Novecento, E.
Spinelli e F. Trabattoni, Sapienza Università Editrice, Roma, Gentile e
Gioberti, «La Cultura», Gramsci, Croce e il canto decimo dell’Inferno di Dante,
«Giornale critico della filosofia italiana», , fBertrando Spaventa e Gioberti,
«Studi storici», , La presenza di Gramsci nella storiografia filosofica e nella
storia della cultura, «Filosofia italiana», Dialettica e società civile.
Gramsci “interprete” di Hegel, «Pólemos. Materiali di filosofia e critica
sociale», Marx e i marxismi italiani, «Giornale critico della filosofia
italiana», La “via alla storia” di Carlo
Ginzburg, in Streghe, sciamani, visionari. In margine a “Storia notturna” di
Carlo Ginzburg, Cora Presezzi, Viella, Roma , Filosofia e storia della filosofia
nella riflessione di Sasso, «Filosofia italiana», Opere Sapienza Roma.
Dipartimento di studi filosofici ed epistemologici, su lettere.uniroma1.it.
Intervista sulla storia della "Rivista trimestrale" Intervista di
Mustè su Croce del
//diacritica.it/letture-critiche/lo-storicismo-di-croce-e-la-morte-della-metafisica-intervista-a-marcello-muste.html
No comments:
Post a Comment