Agitation. A
Byzantine feeling is a Ryleian agitation. If
Grice were to advance the not wholly plausible thesis that ‘to feel Byzantine’
is just to have a an anti-rylean agitation which is caused by the thought that
Grice is or might *be* Byzantine, it would surely be ridiculous to criticise
Grice on the grounds that Grice saddles himself with an ontological commitment
to feelings, or to modes of feeling. And why? Well, because, alla Parsons, if a
quantifier is covertly involved at all, it will only be a universal quantifier
which in such a case as this is more than adequately handled by a
substitutional account of quantification. Grice’s situation vis-a-vis the
‘proposition’ is in no way different. In the idiolect of
Ryle, “a serious student of Grecian philosophy,” as Grice puts it, ‘emotion’
designates at least three or four different kinds of things, which Ryle calls
an ‘inclination, or ‘motive,’ a ‘mood’, an ‘agitation,’ or a ‘commotion,’ and a
‘feeling.’ An inclination or a mood, including an agitation, is not occurrences
and doest not therefore take place either publicly or privately. It is a
propensity, not an act or state. An inclination is, however, a propensity of
this or that kind, and the kind is important. A feeling, on the other hand, IS
an occurrence, but the place that mention of it should take in a description of
human behaviour is very different from that which the standard theories accord
to it. A susceptibility to a specific agitation is on the same general footing
with an inclination, viz. that each is a general propensity and not an
occurrence. An agitation is not a motive. But an agitation does presuppose a
motive, or rather an agitataion presupposes a behaviour trend of which a motive
is for us the most interesting sort. There
is however a matter of expression which is the source of some confusion, even
among Oxonian Wilde readers, and that did confuse philosophical psychologists
of the ability of G. F. Stout. An expression may signify both an inclination
and an agitation. But an expression may signify anything but an agitations.
Again, some other expression may signify anything but an inclination. An
expression like ‘uneasy’, ‘anxious’, ‘distressed’, ‘excited’, ‘startled’ always
signifies an agitations. An expression like ‘fond of fishing’, ‘keen on
gardening’, ‘bent on becoming a bishop’ never signifies an agitation. But an expression
like ‘love’, ‘want’, ‘desire’, ‘proud’, ‘eager,’ or many others, stands
sometimes for a simple inclination and sometimes for an agitations which is resultant
upon the inclinations and interferences with the exercise of it. Thus ‘hungry’
for ‘having a good appetite’ means roughly ‘is eating or would eat heartily and
without sauces, etc..’ This is different from ‘hungry’ in which a person might
be said to be ‘too hungry to concentrate on his work’. Hunger in this second
expression is a distress, and requires for its existence the conjunction of an
appetite with the inability to eat. Similarly the way in which a boy is proud
of his school is different from the way in which he is speechless with pride on
being unexpectedly given a place in a school team. To remove a possible
misapprehension, it must be pointed out that an agitation may be quite agreeable.
A man may voluntarily subject himself to suspense, fatigue, uncertainty,
perplexity, fear and surprise in such practices as angling, rowing, travelling,
crossword puzzles, rock-climbing and joking. That a thing like a thrill, a rapture,
a surprise, an amusement and an relief is an agitation is shown by the fact
that we can say that someone is too much
thrilled, amused or relieved to act, think or talk coherently. It is helpful to
notice that, anyhow commonly, the expression which completes ‘pang of . . .’ or ‘chill of . . .’ denotes an
agitation. A feeling, such as a man feeling Byzantine, is intrinsically
connected with an agitation. But a feeling, e. g. of a man who is feeling
Byzantine, is not intrinsically connected with an inclination, save in so far
as the inclination is a factor in the agitation. This is no novel psychological
hypothesis; It is part of the logic of our descriptions of a feeling that a
feeling (such as a man feeling Byzantine) is a sign of an agitation and is not
an exercise of an inclination.
A feeling, such as
a man feeling Byzantine, in other words, is not a thing of which it makes sense
to ask from what motive it issues. The same is true, for the same reasons, of
any sign of any agitation.
This point shows
why we were right to suggest above that a feeling (like a man feeling
Byzantine) does not belong directly to a simple inclination. An inclination is
a certain sort of proneness or readiness to do certain sorts of things on
purpose. These things are therefore describable as being done from that motive.
They are the exercises of the disposition that we call ‘a motive’. A feeling
(such as a man feeling Byzantine) is not from a motive and is therefore not
among the possible exercise of such a propensiy. The widespread theory that a
motive such as vanity, or affection, is in the first instance a disposition to
experience certain specific feeling is therefore absurd. There may be, of
course, a tendency to have a feeling, such as feeling Byzantine; being
vertiginous and rheumatic are such tendencies. But we do not try to modify a tendency
of these kinds by a sermon. What a feeling, such as being Byzantine, does causally
belong to is the agitation. A feeling (such as feeling Byzantine) is a sign of an
agitation in the same sort of way as a stomach-ache is a sign of indigestion.
Roughly, we do not, as the prevalent theory holds, act purposively because we
experience a feeling (such as feeling Byzantine); we experience a feeling (such
as feeling Byzantine), as we wince and shudder, because we are inhibited from
acting purposively. A
sentimentalist is a man who indulges in this or that induced feeling (such as
feeling Byzantine) without acknowledging the fictitiousness of his agitation.
It seems to be generally supposed that ‘pleasure’ or ‘desire’ is always used to
signify a feeling. And there certainly are feelings which can be described as a
feeling of pleasure or desire. Some thrills, shocks, glows and ticklings are
feelings of delight, surprise, relief and amusement; and things like a hankering,
an itche, a gnawing and a yearning is a sign that something is both wanted and
missed. But the transports, surprises, reliefs and distresses of which such a feeling
is diagnosed, or mis-diagnosed, as a sign is not itself a feeling. It is an agitation
or a mood, just as are the transports and distresses which a child betrays by
his skips and his whimpers. Nostalgia is an agitation and one which can be
called a ‘desire’; but it is not merely a feeling or series of feelings. There
is the sense of ‘pleasure’ in which it is commonly replaced by such expressions
as ‘delight’, ‘transport’, ‘rapture’, ‘exultation’ and ‘joy’. These are
expressions of this or that mood signifying this or that agitation. There are
two quite different usages of ‘emotion’, in which we explain people’s behaviour
by reference to emotions. In the first usage of ‘emotion,’ we are referring to
the motives or inclinations from which more or less intelligent actions are
done. In a second usage we are referring to a mood, including the agitation or
perturbation of which some aimless movement may be a sign. In neither of these
usages are we asserting or implicating that the overt behaviour is the effect
of a felt turbulence in the agent’s stream of consciousness. In a third usage
of ‘emotion’, pangs and twinges are feelings or emotions, but they are not,
save per accidens, things by reference to which we explain behaviour. They are
things for which diagnoses are required, not things required for the diagnoses
of behaviour. Since a convulsion of merriment is not the state of mind of the
sober experimentalist, the enjoyment of a joke is also not an introspectible
happening. States of mind such as these more or less violent agitations can be
examined only in retrospect. Yet nothing disastrous follows from this
restriction. We are not shorter of information about panic or amusement than
about other states of mind. If retrospection can give us the data we need for
our knowledge of some states of mind, there is no reason why it should not do
so for all. And this is just what seems to be suggested by the popular phrase
‘to catch oneself doing so and so’. We catch, as we pursue and overtake, what
is already running away from us. I catch myself daydreaming about a mountain
walk after, perhaps very shortly after, I have begun the daydream; or I catch
myself humming a particular air only when the first few notes have already been
hummed. Retrospection, prompt or delayed, is a genuine process and one which is
exempt from the troubles ensuing from the assumption of multiply divided
attention; it is also exempt from the troubles ensuing from the assumption that
violent agitations could be the objects of cool, contemporary scrutiny. One may
be aware that he is whistling ‘Tipperary’ and not know that he is whistling it in
order to give the appearance of a sang-froid which he does not feel. Or, again,
he may be aware that he is shamming sang-froid without knowing that the tremors
which he is trying to hide derive from the agitation of a guilty conscience.
No comments:
Post a Comment