theory of descriptions,
an analysis, initially developed by Peano and Russell, of sentences containing
descriptions. Descriptions include indefinite descriptions such as ‘an
elephant’ and definite descriptions such as ‘the positive square root of four’.
On Russell’s analysis, descriptions are “incomplete symbols” that are
meaningful only in the context of other symbols, i.e., only in the context of
the sentences containing them. Although the words ‘the first president of the
United States’ appear to constitute a singular term that picks out a particular
individual, much as the name ‘George Washington’ does, Russell held that
descriptions are not referring expressions, and that they are “analyzed out” in
a proper specification of the logical form of the sentences in which they
occur. The grammatical form of ‘The first president of the United States is
tall’ is simply misleading as to its logical form. According to Russell’s
analysis of indefinite descriptions, the sentence ‘I saw a man’ asserts that
there is at least one thing that is a man, and I saw that thing – symbolically,
(Ex) (Mx & Sx). The role of the apparent singular term ‘a man’ is taken
over by the existential quantifier ‘(Ex)’ and the variables it binds, and the
apparent singular term disappears on analysis. A sentence containing a definite
description, such as ‘The present king of France is bald’, is taken to make
three claims: that at least one thing is a present king of France, that at most
one thing is a present king of France, and that that thing is bald –
symbolically, (Ex) {[Fx & (y) (Fy / y % x)] & Bx}. Again, the apparent
referring expression ‘the present king of France’ is analyzed away, with its
role carried out by the quantifiers and variables in the symbolic
representation of the logical form of the sentence in which it occurs. No
element in that representation is a singular referring expression. Russell held
that this analysis solves at least three difficult puzzles posed by
descriptions. The first is how it could be true that George IV wished to know
whether Scott was the author of Waverly, but false that George IV wished to
know whether Scott was Scott. Since Scott is the author of Waverly, we should
apparently be able to substitute ‘Scott’ for ‘the author of Waverly’ and infer
the second sentence from the first, but we cannot. On Russell’s analysis,
‘George IV wished to know whether Scott was the author of Waverly’ does not,
when properly understood, contain an expression ‘the author of Waverly’ for
which the name ‘Scott’ can be substituted. The second puzzle concerns the law
of excluded middle, which rules that either ‘The present king of France is
bald’ or ‘The present king of France is not bald’ must be true; the problem is
that neither the list of bald men nor that of non-bald men contains an entry
for the present king of France. Russell’s solution is that ‘The present king of
France is not bald’ is indeed true if it is understood as ‘It is not the case
that there is exactly one thing that is now King of France and is bald’, i.e.,
as -(Ex) {Fx & (y) {[Fy / y % x)] & Bx}. The final puzzle is how ‘There
is no present king of France’ or ‘The present king of France does not exist’
can be true – if ‘the present king of France’ is a referring expression that
picks out something, how can we truly deny that that thing exists? Since
descriptions are not referring expressions on Russell’s theory, it is easy for
him to show that the negation of the claim that there is at least and at most
(i.e., exactly) one present king of France, -(Ex) [Fx & (y) (Fy / y % x)],
is true. Strawson offered the first real challenge to Russell’s theory, arguing
that ‘The present king of France is bald’ does not entail but instead
presupposes ‘There is a present king of France’, so that the former is not
falsified by the falsity of the latter, but is instead deprived of a
truth-value. Strawson argued for the natural view that definite descriptions
are indeed referring expressions, used to single something out for predication.
More recently, Keith Donnellan argued that both Russell and Strawson ignored
the fact that definite descriptions have two uses. Used attributively, a
definite description is intended to say something about whatever it is true of,
and when a sentence is so used it conforms to Russell’s analysis. Used
referentially, a definite description is intended to single something out, but
may not correctly describe it. For example, seeing an inebriated man in a
policeman’s uniform, one might say, “The cop on the corner is drunk!” Donnellan
would say that even if the person were a drunken actor dressed as a policeman,
the speaker would have referred to him and truly said of him that he was drunk.
If it is for some reason crucial that the description be correct, as it might
be if one said, “The cop on the corner has the authority to issue speeding
tickets,” the use is attributive; and because ‘the cop on the corner’ does not
describe anyone correctly, no one has been said to have the authority to issue
speeding tickets. Donnellan criticized Russell for overlooking referential uses
of theory of descriptions theory of descriptions 914 914 descriptions, and Strawson for both
failing to acknowledge attributive uses and maintaining that with referential
uses one can refer to something with a definite description only if the
description is true of it. Discussion of Strawson’s and Donnellan’s criticisms
is ongoing, and has provoked very useful work in both semantics and speech act
theory, and on the distinctions between semantics and pragmatics and between
semantic reference and speaker’s reference, among others.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment