Schelling, Friedrich
Wilhelm Joseph 1775 1854, German philosopher whose metamorscalar implicature
Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph 816
816 phoses encompass the entire history of German idealism. A Schwabian,
Schelling first studied at Tübingen, where he befriended Hölderlin and Hegel.
The young Schelling was an enthusiastic exponent of Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre
and devoted several early essays to its exposition. After studying science and
mathematics at Leipzig, he joined Fichte at Jena in 1798. Meanwhile, in such
writings as Philosophische Briefe über Dogmatismus und Kritizismus
“Philosophical Letters on Dogmatism and Criticism,” 1795, Schelling betrayed
growing doubts concerning Fichte’s philosophy above all, its treatment of
nature and a lively interest in Spinoza. He then turned to constructing a
systematic Naturphilosophie philosophy of nature within the context of which
nature would be treated more holistically than by either Newtonian science or
transcendental idealism. Of his many publications on this topic, two of the
more important are Ideen zu einer Philosophie der Natur “Ideas concerning a
Philosophy of Nature,” 1797 and Von der Weltseele “On the World-Soul,” 1798.
Whereas transcendental idealism attempts to derive objective experience from an
initial act of free self-positing, Schelling’s philosophy of nature attempts to
derive consciousness from objects. Beginning with “pure objectivity,” the
Naturphilosophie purports to show how nature undergoes a process of unconscious
self-development, culminating in the conditions for its own self-representation.
The method of Naturphilosophie is fundamentally a priori: it begins with the
concept of the unity of nature and accounts for its diversity by interpreting
nature as a system of opposed forces or “polarities,” which manifest themselves
in ever more complex levels of organization Potenzen. At Jena, Schelling came
into contact with Tieck, Novalis, and the Schlegel brothers and became
interested in art. This new interest is evident in his System des
transzendentalen Idealismus 1800, which describes the path from pure
subjectivity self-consciousness to objectivity the necessary positing of the
Not-I, or of nature. The most innovative and influential portion of this
treatise, which is otherwise closely modeled on Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre, is
its conclusion, which presents art as the concrete accomplishment of the
philosophical task. In aesthetic experience the identity between the subjective
and the objective, the ideal and the real, becomes an object to the
experiencing I itself. For Schelling, transcendental idealism and
Naturphilosophie are two complementary sides or subdivisions of a larger, more
encompassing system, which he dubbed the System of Identity or Absolute
Idealism and expounded in a series of publications, including the Darstellung
meines Systems der Philosophie “Presentation of My System of Philosophy,” 1801,
Bruno 1802, and Vorlesungen über die Methode des akademischen Studiums
“Lectures on the Method of Academic Study,” 1803. The most distinctive feature
of this system is that it begins with a bald assertion of the unity of thought
and being, i.e., with the bare idea of the self-identical “Absolute,” which is
described as the first presupposition of all knowledge. Since the identity with
which this system commences transcends every conceivable difference, it is also
described as the “point of indifference.” From this undifferentiated or
“indifferent” starting point, Schelling proceeds to a description of reality as
a whole, considered as a differentiated system within which unity is maintained
by various synthetic relationships, such as substance and attribute, cause and
effect, attraction and repulsion. Like his philosophy of nature, Schelling’s
System of Identity utilizes the notion of various hierarchically related
Potenzen as its basic organizing principle. The obvious question concerns the
precise relationship between the “indifferent” Absolute and the real system of
differentiated elements, a question that may be said to have set the agenda for
Schelling’s subsequent philosophizing. From 1803 to 1841 Schelling was in
Bavaria, where he continued to expound his System of Identity and to explore
the philosophies of art and nature. The most distinctive feature of his thought
during this period, however, was a new interest in religion and in the theosophical
writings of Boehme, whose influence is prominent in the Philosophische
Untersuchungen über das Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit “Philosophical
Investigations concerning the Nature of Human Freedom,” 1809, a work often
interpreted as anticipating existentialism. He also worked on a speculative
interpretation of human history, Die Weltalter, which remained unpublished, and
lectured regularly on the history of philosophy. In 1841 Schelling moved to
Berlin, where he lectured on his new philosophy of revelation and mythology,
which he now characterized as “positive philosophy,” in contradistinction to
the purely “negative” philosophy of Kant, Fichte, and Hegel. Some scholars have
interpreted these posthumously published lectures as representing the culmination
both of Schelling’s own protracted philosophical development and of German
idealism as a whole.
Schelling, Friedrich
Wilhelm Joseph Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph 817 817 schema.THEMA. schemata.KANT. schematic
form.LOGICAL FORM. scheme, also schema plural: schemata, a metalinguistic frame
or template used to specify an infinite set of sentences, its instances, by
finite means, often taken with a side condition on how its blanks or
placeholders are to be filled. The sentence ‘Either Abe argues or it is not the
case that Abe argues’ is an instance of the excluded middle scheme for English:
‘Either . . . or it is not the case that . . .’, where the two blanks are to be
filled with one and the same well-formed declarative English sentence. Since
first-order number theory cannot be finitely axiomatized, the mathematical
induction scheme is used to effectively specify an infinite set of axioms: ‘If
zero is such that . . . and the successor of every number such that . . . is
also such that . . . , then every number is such that . . .’, where the four
blanks are to be filled with one and the same arithmetic open sentence, such as
‘it precedes its own successor’ or ‘it is finite’. Among the best-known is
Tarski’s scheme T: ‘. . . is a true sentence if and only if . . .’, where the
second blank is filled with a sentence and the first blank by a name of the
sentence.
Schiller, Johann
Christoph Friedrich von 1759 1805, German poet, dramatist, and philosopher.
Along with his colleagues Reinhold and Fichte, he participated in
systematically revising Kant’s transcendental idealism. Though Schiller’s
bestknown theoretical contributions were to aesthetics, his philosophical
ambitions were more general, and he proposed a novel solution to the problem of
the systematic unity, not merely of the critical philosophy, but of human
nature. His most substantial philosophical work, Briefe über die äesthetische
Erziehung des Menschen “Letters on the Aesthetic Education of Man,” 1794/95,
examines the relationship between natural necessity and practical freedom and
addresses two problems raised by Kant: How can a creature governed by natural
necessity and desire ever become aware of its own freedom and thus capable of
autonomous moral action? And how can these two sides of human nature the natural, sensuous side and the rational,
supersensuous one be reconciled? In
contradistinction both to those who subordinate principles to feelings
“savages” and to those who insist that one should strive to subordinate
feelings to principles “barbarians”, Schiller posited an intermediary realm
between the sphere of nature and that of freedom, as well as a third basic
human drive capable of mediating between sensuous and rational impulses. This
third impulse is dubbed the “play impulse,” and the intermediary sphere to
which it pertains is that of art and beauty. By cultivating the play impulse
i.e., via “aesthetic education” one is not only freed from bondage to
sensuality and granted a first glimpse of one’s practical freedom, but one also
becomes capable of reconciling the rational and sensuous sides of one’s own
nature. This idea of a condition in which opposites are simultaneously
cancelled and preserved, as well as the specific project of reconciling freedom
and necessity, profoundly influenced subsequent thinkers such as Schelling and
Hegel and contributed to the development of German idealism.
Schlegel, Friedrich von
17721829, German literary critic and philosopher, one of the principal
representatives of German Romanticism. In On the Study of Grecian Poetry 1795,
Schlegel laid the foundations for the distinction of classical and Romantic
literature and a pronounced consciousness of literary modernity. Together with
his brother August Wilhelm, he edited the Athenaeum 17981800, the main
theoretical organ of German Romanticism, famous for its collection of fragments
as a new means of critical communication. Schlegel is the originator of the
Romantic theory of irony, a non-dialectical form of philosophizing and literary
writing that takes its inspiration from Socratic irony and combines it with
Fichte’s thought process of affirmation and negation, “self-creation” and
“self-annihilation.” Closely connected wih Schlegel’s theory of irony is his
theory of language and understanding hermeneutics. Critical reflection on
language promotes an ironic awareness of the “necessity and impossibility of
complete communication” Critical Fragments, No. 108; critical reflection on
understanding reveals the amount of incomprehensibility, of “positive not-understanding”
involved in every act of understanding On Incomprehensibility, 1800. Schlegel’s
writings were essential for the rise of historical consciousness in German
Romanticism. His On Ancient and Modern Literature 1812 is reputed to represent
the first literary history in a modern and broadly comparative fashion. His
Philosophy of History 1828, together with his Philosophy of Life 1828 schema
Schlegel, Friedrich von 818 818 and
Philosophy of Language 1829, confront Hegel’s philosophy from the point of view
of a Christian and personalistic type of philosophizing. Schlegel converted to
Catholicism in 1808.
Schleiermacher, Friedrich
17681834, German philosopher, a “critical realist” working among post-Kantian
idealists. In philosophy and science he presupposed transcendental features,
noted in his dialectic lectures, and advocated integrative but historically
contingent, empirical functions. Both develop, but, contra Hegel, not
logically. Schleiermacher was a creator of modern general hermeneutics; a father
of modern theological and religious studies; an advocate of women’s rights; the
cofounder, with Humboldt, of the at
Berlin 180810, where he taught until 1834; and the classic translator of Plato
into German. Schleiermacher has had an undeservedly minor place in histories of
philosophy. Appointed chiefly to theology, he published less philosophy, though
he regularly lectured, in tightly argued discourse, in Grecian philosophy,
history of philosophy, dialectic, hermeneutics and criticism, philosophy of
mind “psychology”, ethics, politics, aesthetics, and philosophy of education.
From the 1980s, his collected writings and large correspondence began to appear
in a forty-volume critical edition and in the larger Schleiermacher Studies and
Translations series. Brilliant, newly available pieces from his twenties on
freedom, the highest good, and values, previously known only in fragments but
essential for understanding his views fully, were among the first to appear.
Much of his outlook was formed before he became prominent in the early Romantic
circle 17961806, distinguishable by his markedly religious, consistently
liberal views.
Scholasticism, a set of
scholarly and instructional techniques developed in Western European schools of
the late medieval period, including the use of commentary and disputed
question. ‘Scholasticism’ is derived from Latin scholasticus, which in the
twelfth century meant the master of a school. The Scholastic method is usually
presented as beginning in the law schools
notably at Bologna and as being
then transported into theology and philosophy by a series of masters including
Abelard and Peter Lombard. Within the new universities of the thirteenth
century the standardization of the curriculum and the enormous prestige of
Aristotle’s work despite the suspicion with which it was initially greeted
contributed to the entrenchment of the method and it was not until the
educational reforms of the beginning of the sixteenth century that it ceased to
be dominant. There is, strictly speaking, no such thing as Scholasticism. As
the term was originally used it presupposed that a single philosophy was taught
in the universities of late medieval Europe, but there was no such philosophy.
The philosophical movements working outside the universities in the late
sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries and the “neo-Scholastics” of the late
nineteenth and early twentieth centuries all found such a presupposition
useful, and their influence led scholars to assume it. At first this generated
efforts to find a common core in the philosophies taught in the late medieval
schools. More recently it has led to efforts to find methods characteristic of
their teaching, and to an extension of the term to the schools of late
antiquity and of Byzantium. Both among the opponents of the schools in the
seventeenth century and among the “neoScholastics,” ‘Scholasticism’ was
supposed to designate a doctrine whose core was the doctrine of substance and
accidents. As portrayed by Descartes and Locke, the Scholastics accepted the
view that among the components of a thing were a substantial form and a number
of real accidental forms, many of which corresponded to perceptible properties
of the thing its color, shape,
temperature. They were also supposed to have accepted a sharp distinction
between natural and unnatural motion.
School of Names, also
called, in Chinese, ming chia, a loosely associated group of Chinese
philosophers of the Warring States period 403 221 B.C., also known as pien che
Dialecticians or Sophists. The most famous were Hui Shih and Kung-sun Lung Tzu.
Though interested in the relation between names and reality, the Sophists
addressed such issues as relativity, perspectivism, space, time, causality,
essentialism, universalism, and particularism. Perhaps more important than
their subject matter, however, was their methodology. As their name suggests,
the Sophists Schleiermacher, Friedrich School of Names 819 819 delighted in language games and logical
puzzles. They used logic and rational argument not only as a weapon to defeat
their philosophical opponents but as a tool to sharpen rational argumentation
itself. Paradoxes such as ‘I go to Yüeh today but arrive yesterday’ and ‘A
white horse is not a horse’ continue to stimulate philosophical discussion today.
Yet frustrated Confucian, Taoist, and Legalist contemporaries chided Sophists
for wasting their time on abstractions and puzzles, and for succumbing to
intellectualism for its own sake. As Confucianism emerged to become the state
ideology, the School of Names disappeared sometime in the early Han dynasty 206
B.C.A.D. 220; having been in important measure co-opted by the leading
interpreter of Confucianism of the period, Hsün Tzu.
Schopenhauer, Arthur
17881860, German philosopher. Born in Danzig and schooled in Germany, France,
and England during a welltraveled childhood, he became acquainted through his
novelist mother with Goethe, Schlegel, and the brothers Grimm. He studied
medicine at the of Göttingen and philosophy
at the of Berlin; received the doctorate
from the of Jena in 1813; and lived much
of his adult life in Frankfurt, where he died. Schopenhauer’s dissertation, On
the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason 1813, lays the
groundwork for all of his later philosophical work. The world of representation
equivalent to Kant’s phenomenal world is governed by “the principle of
sufficient reason”: “every possible object . . . stands in a necessary relation
to other objects, on the one hand as determined, on the other as determining” The
World as Will and Representation. Thus, each object of consciousness can be
explained in terms of its relations with other objects. The systematic
statement of Schopenhauer’s philosophy appeared in The World as Will and
Representation 1818. His other works are On Vision and Colors 1815, “On the
Will in Nature” 1836, conjoined with “On the Foundation of Morality” in The Two
Fundamental Problems of Ethics 1841; the second edition of The World as Will
and Representation, which included a second volume of essays 1844; an enlarged
and revised edition of On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient
Reason 1847; and Parerga and Paralipomena, a series of essays 1851. These are
all consistent with the principal statement of his thought in The World as Will
and Representation. The central postulate of Schopenhauer’s system is that the
fundamental reality is will, which he equates with the Kantian thing-in-itself.
Unlike Kant, Schopenhauer contends that one can immediately know the
thing-in-itself through the experience of an inner, volitional reality within
one’s own body. Every phenomenon, according to Schopenhauer, has a comparable
inner reality. Consequently, the term ‘will’ can extend to the inner nature of
all things. Moreover, because number pertains exclusively to the phenomenal
world, the will, as thing-initself, is one. Nevertheless, different types of
things manifest the will to different degrees. Schopenhauer accounts for these
differences by invoking Plato’s Ideas or Forms. The Ideas are the universal
prototypes for the various kinds of objects in the phenomenal world. Taken
collectively, the Ideas constitute a hierarchy. We usually overlook them in
everyday experience, focusing instead on particulars and their practical
relationships to us. However, during aesthetic experience, we recognize the
universal Idea within the particular; simultaneously, as aesthetic beholders,
we become “the universal subject of knowledge.” Aesthetic experience also
quiets the will within us. The complete silencing of the will is, for
Schopenhauer, the ideal for human beings, though it is rarely attained. Because
will is the fundamental metaphysical principle, our lives are dominated by
willing and, consequently, filled with
struggle, conflict, and dissatisfaction. Inspired by Buddhism, Schopenhauer
contends that all of life is suffering, which only an end to desire can
permanently eliminate as opposed to the respite of aesthetic experience. This
is achieved only by the saint, who rejects desire in an inner act termed “denial
of the will to live.” The saint fully grasps that the same will motivates all
phenomena and, recognizing that nothing is gained through struggle and
competition, achieves “resignation.” Such a person achieves the ethical ideal
of all religions compassion toward all
beings, resulting from the insight that all are, fundamentally, one.
Schröder-Bernstein
theorem, the theorem that mutually dominant sets are equinumerous. A set A is
said to be dominated by a set B if and only if each element of A can be mapped
to a unique element of B in such a way that no two elements of A are mapped to
the same element of B posSchopenhauer, Arthur Schröder-Bernstein theorem
820 820 sibly with some elements of B
left over. Intuitively, if A is dominated by B, then B has at least as many
members as A. Given this intuition, one would expect that if A is dominated by
B and B is dominated by A, then A and B are equinumerous i.e., A can be mapped
to B as described above with no elements of B left over. This is the Schröder-Bernstein
theorem. Stated in terms of cardinal numbers, the theorem says that if k m l
and l m k, then k % l. Despite the simplicity of the theorem’s statement, its
proof is non-trivial.
Schrödinger, Erwin
18871961, Austrian physicist best known for five papers published in 1926, in
which he discovered the Schrödinger wave equation and created modern wave
mechanics. For this achievement, he was awarded the Nobel prize in physics
shared with Paul Dirac in 1933. Like Einstein, Schrödinger was a resolute but
ultimately unsuccessful critic of the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum
mechanics. Schrödinger defended the view which he derived from Boltzmann that
theories should give a picture, continuous in space and time, of the real
processes that produce observable phenomena. Schrödinger’s realistic philosophy
of science played an important role in his discovery of wave mechanics.
Although his physical interpretation of the psi function was soon abandoned,
his approach to quantum mechanics survives in the theories of Louis de Broglie
and David Bohm.
.
Schulze, Gottlob Ernst
17611833, German philosopher today known mainly as an acute and influential
early critic of Kant and Reinhold. He taught at Wittenberg, Helmstedt, and
Göttingen; one of his most important students was Schopenhauer, whose view of
Kant was definitely influenced by Schulze’s interpretation. Schulze’s most
important work was his Aenesidemus, or “On the Elementary Philosophy Put
Forward by Mr. Reinhold in Jena. Together with a Defense of Skepticism” 1792.
It fundamentally changed the discussion of Kantian philosophy. Kant’s earliest
critics had accused him of being a skeptic like Hume. Kantians, like Reinhold,
had argued that critical philosophy was not only opposed to skepticism, but
also contained the only possible refutation of skepticism. Schulze tried to
show that Kantianism could not refute skepticism, construed as the doctrine
that doubts the possibility of any knowledge concerning the existence or
non-existence of “things-in-themselves,” and he argued that Kant and his
followers begged the skeptic’s question by presupposing that such things exist
and causally interact with us. Schulze’s Aenesidemus had a great impact on
Fichte and Hegel, and it also influenced neoKantianism.
scientific realism, the
view that the subject matter of scientific research and scientific theories
exists independently of our knowledge of it, and that the goal of science is
the description and explanation of both observable and unobservable aspects of
the world. Scientific realism is contrasted with logical empiricism and social
constructivism. Early arguments for scientific realism simply stated that, in
light of the impressive products and methods of science, realism is the only
philosophy that does not make the success of science a miracle. Formulations of
scientific realism focus on the objects of theoretical knowledge: theories,
laws, and entities. One especially robust argument for scientific realism due
to Putnam and Richard Boyd is that the instrumental reliability of scientific
methodology in the mature sciences such as physics, chemistry, and some areas
of biology can be explained adequately only if we suppose that theories in the
mature sciences are at least approximately true and their central theoretical terms
are at least partially referential Putnam no longer holds this view. More timid
versions of scientific realism do not infer approximate truth of mature
theories. For example, Ian Hacking’s “entity realism” 1983 asserts that the
instrumental manipulation of postulated entities to produce further effects
gives us legitimate grounds for ontological commitment to theoretical entities,
but not to laws or theories. Paul Humphreys’s “austere realism” 1989 states
that only theoretical commitment to unobserved structures or dispositions could
Schrödinger, Erwin scientific realism 821
821 explain the stability of observed outcomes of scientific inquiry.
Distinctive versions of scientific realism can be found in works by Richard
Boyd 1983, Philip Kitcher 1993, Richard Miller 1987, William Newton-Smith 1981,
and J. D. Trout 1998. Despite their differences, all of these versions of
realism are distinguished against
logical empiricism by their commitment
that knowledge of unobservable phenomena is not only possible but actual. As
well, all of the arguments for scientific realism are abductive; they argue
that either the approximate truth of background theories or the existence of
theoretical entities and laws provides the best explanation for some
significant fact about the scientific theory or practice. Scientific realists
address the difference between real entities and merely useful constructs,
arguing that realism offers a better explanation for the success of science. In
addition, scientific realism recruits evidence from the history and practice of
science, and offers explanations for the success of science that are designed
to honor the dynamic and uneven character of that evidence. Most arguments for
scientific realism cohabit with versions of naturalism. Anti-realist opponents
argue that the realist move from instrumental reliability to truth is
question-begging. However, realists reply that such formal criticisms are
irrelevant; the structure of explanationist arguments is inductive and their
principles are a posteriori.
scope, the “part” of the
sentence or proposition to which a given term “applies” under a given
interpretation of the sentence. If the sentence ‘Abe does not believe Ben died’
is interpreted as expressing the proposition that Abe believes that it is not
the case that Ben died, the scope of ‘not’ is ‘Ben died’; interpreted as “It is
not the case that Abe believes that Ben died,” the scope is the rest of the
sentence, i.e., ‘Abe believes Ben died’. In the first case we have narrow
scope, in the second wide scope. If ‘Every number is not even’ is interpreted
with narrow scope, it expresses the false proposition that every number is
non-even, which is logically equivalent to the proposition that no number is
even. Taken with wide scope it expresses the truth that not every number is
even, which is equivalent to the truth that some number is non-even. Under
normal interpretations of the sentences, ‘hardened’ has narrow scope in ‘Carl
is a hardened recidivist’, whereas ‘alleged’ has wide scope in ‘Dan is an
alleged criminal’. Accordingly, ‘Carl is a hardened recidivist’ logically
implies ‘Carl is a recidivist’, whereas ‘Dan is an alleged criminal’, being
equivalent to ‘Allegedly, Dan is a criminal’, does not imply ‘Dan is a
criminal’. Scope considerations are useful in analyzing structural ambiguity
and in understanding the difference between the grammatical form of a sentence
and the logical form of a proposition it expresses. In a logically perfect
language grammatical form mirrors logical form, there is no scope ambiguity,
and the scope of a given term is uniquely determined by its context.
Scottish common sense
philosophy, a comprehensive philosophical position developed by Reid in the
latter part of the eighteenth century. Reid’s views were propagated by a
succession of Scottish popularizers, of whom the most successful was Dugald
Stewart. Through them common sense doctrine became nearly a philosophical
orthodoxy in Great Britain during the first half of the nineteenth century.
Brought to the United States through the s in Princeton and Philadelphia,
common sensism continued to be widely taught until the later nineteenth
century. The early Reidians Beattie and Oswald were, like Reid himself, read in
Germany by Kant and others; and Reid’s views were widely taught in
post-Napoleonic France. The archenemy for the common sense theorists was Hume.
Reid saw in his skepticism the inevitable outcome of Descartes’s thesis,
accepted by Locke, that we do not perceive external objects directly, but that
the immediate object of perception is something in the mind. Against this he
argued that perception involves both sensation and certain intuitively known
general truths or principles that together yield knowledge of external objects.
He also argued that there are many other intuitively known general principles,
including moral principles, available to all normal humans. As a result he
scientific relativism Scottish common sense philosophy 822 822 thought that whenever philosophical
argument results in conclusions that run counter to common sense, the
philosophy must be wrong. Stewart made some changes in Reid’s acute and
original theory, but his main achievement was to propagate it through eloquent
classes and widely used textbooks. Common sensism, defending the considered
views of the ordinary man, was taken by many to provide a defense of the
Christian religious and moral status quo. Reid had argued for free will, and
presented a long list of self-evident moral axioms. If this might be plausibly
presented as part of the common sense of his time, the same could not be said
for some of the religious doctrines that Oswald thought equally self-evident.
Reid had not given any rigorous tests for what might count as selfevident. The
easy intuitionism of later common sensists was a natural target for those who,
like J. S. Mill, thought that any appeal to self-evidence was simply a way of
justifying vested interest. Whewell, in both his philosophy of science and his
ethics, and Sidgwick, in his moral theory, acknowledged debts to Reid and tried
to eliminate the abuses to which his method was open. But in doing so they
transformed common sensism beyond the limits within which Reid and those shaped
by him operated.
Searle, John R. b.1932,
American philosopher of language and mind D. Phil., Oxford influenced by Frege,
Wittgenstein, and J. L. Austin; a founder of speech act theory and an important
contributor to debates on intentionality, consciousness, and institutional
facts. Language. In Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language 1969,
Searle brings together modified versions of Frege’s distinctions between the
force F and content P of a sentence, and between singular reference and
predication, Austin’s analysis of speech acts, and Grice’s analysis of speaker
meaning. Searle explores the hypothesis that the semantics of a natural
language can be regarded as a conventional realization of underlying
constitutive rules and that illocutionary acts are acts performed in accordance
with these rules. Expression and Meaning 1979 extends this analysis to
non-literal and indirect illocutionary acts, and attempts to explain
Donnellan’s referential-attributive distinction in these terms and proposes an
influential taxonomy of five basic types of illocutionary acts based on the illocutionary
point or purpose of the act, and word-to-world versus world-toword direction of
fit. Language and mind. Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind 1983
forms the foundation for the earlier work on speech acts. Now the semantics of
a natural language is seen as the result of the mind intrinsic intentionality
imposing conditions of satisfaction or aboutness on objects expressions in a
language, which have intentionality only derivatively. Perception and action
rather than belief are taken as fundamental. Satisfaction conditions are
essentially Fregean i.e. general versus singular and internal meaning is in the head, relative to a
background of non-intentional states, and relative to a network of other
intentional states. The philosophy of language becomes a branch of the
philosophy of mind. Mind. “Minds, Brains and Programs” 1980 introduced the
famous “Chinese room” argument against strong artificial intelligence the view that appropriately programming a
machine is sufficient for giving it intentional states. Suppose a monolingual
English-speaker is working in a room producing Chinese answers to Chinese
questions well enough to mimic a Chinesespeaker, but by following an algorithm
written in English. Such a person does not understand Chinese nor would a
computer computing the same algorithm. This is true for any such algorithms
because they are syntactically individuated and intentional states are
semantically individuated. The Rediscovery of the Mind 1992 continues the
attack on the thesis that the brain is a digital computer, and develops a
non-reductive “biological naturalism” on which intentionality, like the
liquidity of water, is a high-level feature, which is caused by and realized in
the brain. Society. The Construction of Social Reality 1995 develops his
realistic worldview, starting with an independent world of particles and
forces, up through evolutionary biological systems capable of consciousness and
intentionality, to institutions and social facts, which are created when persons
impose status-features on things, which are collectively recognized and
accepted.
second-order logic, the
logic of languages that contain, in addition to variables ranging over objects,
variables ranging over properties, relations, functions, or classes of those
objects. A model, or interpretation, of a formal language usually contains a
domain of discourse. This domain is what the language is about, in the model in
question. Variables that range over this domain are called first-order
variables. If the language contains only first-order variables, it is called a
first-order language, and it is within the purview of first-order logic. Some
languages also contain variables that range over properties, relations,
functions, or classes of members of the domain of discourse. These are
second-order variables. A language that contains first-order and second-order
variables, and no others, is a secondorder language. The sentence ‘There is a
property shared by all and only prime numbers’ is straightforwardly rendered in
a second-order language, because of the bound variable ranging over properties.
There are also properties of properties, relations of properties, and the like.
Consider, e.g., the property of properties expressed by ‘P has an infinite
extension’ or the relation expressed by ‘P has a smaller extension than Q’. A
language with variables ranging over such items is called thirdorder. This
construction can be continued, producing fourth-order languages, etc. A
language is called higher-order if it is at least second-order. Deductive
systems for second-order languages are obtained from those for first-order
languages by adding straightforward extensions of the axioms and rules
concerning quantifiers that bind first-order variables. There may also be an axiom
scheme of comprehension: DPExPx S Fx, one instance for each formula F that does
not contain P free. The scheme “asserts” that every formula determines the
extension of a property. If the language has variables ranging over functions,
there may also be a version of the axiom of choice: ERExDyRxy P DfExRxfx. In
standard semantics for second-order logic, a model of a given language is the
same as a model for the corresponding first-order language. The relation
variables range over every relation over the domain-of-discourse, the function
variables range over every function from the domain to the domain, etc. In
non-standard, or Henkin semantics, each model consists of a domain-ofdiscourse
and a specified collection of relations, functions, etc., on the domain. The
latter may not include every relation or function. The specified collections
are the range of the second-order variables in the model in question. In
effect, Henkin semantics regards second-order languages as multi-sorted,
first-order languages.
secundum quid, in a
certain respect, or with a qualification. Fallacies can arise from confusing
what is true only secundum quid with what is true simpliciter ‘without
qualification’, ‘absolutely’, ‘on the whole’, or conversely. Thus a strawberry
is red simpliciter on the whole. But it is black, not red, with respect to its
seeds, secundum quid. By ignoring the distinction, one might mistakenly infer
that the strawberry is both red and not red. Again, a certain thief is a good
cook, secundum quid; but it does not follow that he is good simpliciter without
qualification. Aristotle was the first to recognize the fallacy secundum quid
et simpliciter explicitly, in his Sophistical Refutations. On the basis of some
exceptionally enigmatic remarks in the same work, the liar paradox was often
regarded in the Middle Ages as an instance of this fallacy.
self-deception, 1
purposeful action to avoid unpleasant truths and painful topics about oneself
or the world; 2 unintentional processes of denial, avoidance, or biased
perception; 3 mental states resulting from such action or processes, such as
ignorance, false belief, wishful thinking, unjustified opinions, or lack of
clear awareness. Thus, parents tend to exaggerate the virtues of their
children; lovers disregard clear signs of unreciprocated affection; overeaters
rationalize away the need to diet; patients dying of cancer pretend to
themselves that their health is improving. In some contexts ‘self-deception’ is
neutral and implies no criticism. Deceiving oneself can even be desirable,
generating a vital lie that promotes happiness or the ability to cope with
difficulties. In other contexts ‘self-deception’ has negative connotations,
suggesting bad faith, false consciousness, or what Joseph Butler called “inner
hypocrisy” the refusal to acknowledge
our wrongdoing, character flaws, or onerous responsibilities. Existentialist
philosophers, like Kierkegaard, Heidegger, and most notably Sartre Being and
Nothingness, 1943, denounced self-deception as an inauthentic dishonest,
cowardly refusal to confront painful though significant truths, especially
about freedom, responsibility, and death. Herbert Fingarette, however, argued
that self-deception is morally ambiguous
neither clearly blameworthy nor clearly faultless because of how it erodes capacities for
acting rationally Self-Deception, 1969. The idea of intentionally deceiving
oneself seems paradoxical. In deceiving other people I usually know a truth
that guides me as I state the opposite falsehood, intending thereby to mislead
them into believing the falsehood. Five difficulties seem to prevent me from
doing anything like that to myself. 1 With interpersonal deception, one person
knows something that another person does not. Yet self-deceivers know the truth
all along, and so it seems they cannot use it to make themselves ignorant. One
solution is that self-deception occurs over time, with the initial knowledge
becoming gradually eroded. Or perhaps selfdeceivers only suspect rather than
know the truth, and then disregard relevant evidence. 2 If consciousness
implies awareness of one’s own conscious acts, then a conscious intention to
deceive myself would be self-defeating, for I would remain conscious of the
truth I wish to flee. Sartre’s solution was to view self-deception as
spontaneous and not explicitly reflected upon. Freud’s solution was to conceive
of self-deception as unconscious repression. 3 It seems that self-deceivers
believe a truth that they simultaneously get themselves not to believe, but how
is that possible? Perhaps they keep one of two conflicting beliefs unconscious
or not fully conscious. 4 Self-deception suggests willfully creating beliefs,
but that seems impossible since beliefs cannot voluntarily be chosen. Perhaps
beliefs can be indirectly manipulated by selectively ignoring and attending to
evidence. 5 It seems that one part of a person the deceiver manipulates another
part the victim, but such extreme splits suggest multiple personality disorders
rather than self-deception. Perhaps we are composed of “subselves” relatively unified clusters of elements in
the personality. Or perhaps at this point we should jettison interpersonal
deception as a model for understanding self-deception. .
self-determination, the
autonomy possessed by a community when it is politically independent; in a
strict sense, territorial sovereignty. Within international law, the principle
of self-determination appears to grant every people a right to be
self-determining, but there is controversy over its interpretation. Applied to
established states, the principle calls for recognition of state sovereignty
and non-intervention in internal affairs. By providing for the
self-determination of subordinate communities, however, it can generate demands
for secession that conflict with existing claims of sovereignty. Also, what
non-self-governing groups qualify as beneficiaries? The national interpretation
of the principle treats cultural or national units as the proper claimants,
whereas the regional interpretation confers the right of self-determination
upon the populations of well-defined regions regardless of cultural or national
affiliations. This difference reflects the roots of the principle in the
doctrines of nationalism and popular sovereignty, respectively, but comseeing,
non-epistemic self-determination 825
825 plicates its application.
self-evidence, the
property of being self-evident. Only true propositions or truths are
self-evident, though false propositions can appear to be self-evident. It is
widely held that a true proposition is self-evident if and only if one would be
justified in believing it if one adequately understood it. Some would also
require that self-evident propositions are known if believed on the basis of
such an understanding. Some self-evident propositions are obvious, such as the
proposition that all stags are male, but others are not, since it may take
considerable reflection to achieve an adequate understanding of them. That
slavery is wrong and that there is no knowledge of falsehoods are perhaps examples
of the latter. Not all obvious propositions are self-evident, e.g., it is
obvious that a stone will fall if dropped, but adequate understanding of that
claim does not by itself justify one in believing it. An obvious proposition is
one that immediately seems true for anyone who adequately understands it, but
its obviousness may rest on wellknown and commonly accepted empirical facts,
not on understanding. All analytic propositions are self-evident but not all
self-evident propositions are analytic. The propositions that if A is older
than B, then B is younger than A, and that no object can be red and green all
over at the same time and in the same respects, are arguably self-evident but
not analytic. All self-evident propositions are necessary, for one could not be
justified in believing a contingent proposition simply in virtue of
understanding it. However, not all necessary propositions are self-evident,
e.g., that water is H2O and that temperature is the measure of the molecular
activity in substances are necessary but not self-evident. A proposition can
appear to be selfevident even though it is not. For instance, the proposition
that all unmarried adult males are bachelors will appear self-evident to many
until they consider that the pope is such a male. A proposition may appear
self-evident to some but not to others, even though it must either have or lack
the property of being self-evident. Self-evident propositions are knowable
non-empirically, or a priori, but some propositions knowable a priori are not
self-evident, e.g., certain conclusions of long and difficult chains of
mathematical reasoning.
self-presenting, in the
philosophy of Meinong, having the ability
common to all mental states to be
immediately present to our thought. In Meinong’s view, no mental state can be
presented to our thought in any other way
e.g., indirectly, via a Lockean “idea of reflection.” The only way to
apprehend a mental state is to experience or “live through” it. The experience
involved in the apprehension of an external object has thus a double
presentational function: 1 via its “content” it presents the object to our
thought; 2 as its own “quasi-content” it presents itself immediately to our
thought. In the contemporary era, Roderick Chisholm has based his account of
empirical knowledge in part on a related concept of the self-presenting. In
Chisholm’s sense the definition of which
we omit here all self-presenting states
are mental, but not conversely; for instance, being depressed because of the
death of one’s spouse would not be self-presenting. In Chisholm’s epistemology,
self-presenting states are a source of certainty in the following way: if F is
a self-presenting state, then to be certain that one is in state F it is
sufficient that one is, and believes oneself to be in state F.
self-referential
incoherence, an internal defect of an assertion or theory, which it possesses
provided that a it establishes some requirement that must be met by assertions
or theories, b it is itself subject to this requirement, and c it fails to meet
the requirement. The most famous example is logical positivism’s meaning
criterion, which requires that all meaningful assertions be either tautological
or empirically verifiable, yet is itself neither. A possible early example is
found in Hume, whose own writings might have been consigned to the flames had
librarians followed his counsel to do so with volumes that contain neither
“abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number” nor “experimental reasoning
concerning matter of fact and existence.” Bold defiance was shown by
Wittgenstein, who, realizing that the propositions of the Tractatus did not
“picture” the world, advised the reader to “throw away the ladder after he has
climbed up it.” An epistemological example is furnished by any foundationalist
theory that establishes criteria for rational acceptability that the theory
itself cannot meet.
self-reproducing
automaton, a formal model of self-reproduction of a kind introduced by von
Neumann. He worked with an intuitive robot model and then with a well-defined
cellular automaton model. Imagine a class of robotic automata made of robot
parts and operating in an environment of such parts. There are computer parts
switches, memory elements, wires, input-output parts sensing elements, display
elements, action parts grasping and moving elements, joining and cutting
elements, and straight bars to maintain structure and to employ in a storage
tape. There are also energy sources that enable the robots to operate and move
around. These five categories of parts are sufficient for the construction of
robots that can make objects of various kinds, including other robots. These
parts also clearly suffice for making a robot version of any finite automaton.
Sensing and acting parts can then be added to this robot so that it can make an
indefinitely expandable storage tape from straight bars. A “blank tape”
consists of bars joined in sequence, and the robot stores information on this
tape by attaching bars or not at the junctions. If its finite automaton part
can execute programs and is sufficiently powerful, such a robot is a universal
computing robot cf. a universal Turing machine. A universal computing robot can
be augmented to form a universal constructing robot a robot that can construct any robot, given
its description. Let r be any robot with an indefinitely expandable tape, let
Fr be the description of its finite part, and let Tr be the information on its
tape. Now take a universal computing robot and augment it with sensing and
acting devices and with programs so that when Fr followed by Tr is written on
its tape, this augmented universal computer performs as follows. First, it
reads the description Fr, finds the needed parts, and constructs the finite
part of r. Second, it makes a blank tape, attaches it to the finite part of r,
and then copies the information Tr from its own tape onto the new tape. This
augmentation of a universal computing robot is a universal constructor. For
when it starts with the information Fr,Tr written on its tape, it will
construct a copy of r with Tr on its tape. Robot self-reproduction results from
applying the universal constructor to itself. Modify the universal constructor
slightly so that when only a description Fr is written on its tape, it
constructs the finite part of r and then attaches a tape with Fr written on it.
Call this version of the universal constructor Cu. Now place Cu’s description
FCu on its own tape and start it up. Cu first reads this description and
constructs a copy of the finite part of itself in an empty region of the
cellular space. Then it adds a blank tape to the new construction and copies
FCu onto it. Hence Cu with FCu on its tape has produced another copy of Cu with
FCu on its tape. This is automaton self-reproduction. This robot model of
self-reproduction is very general. To develop the logic of self-reproduction
further, von Neumann first extended the concept of a finite automaton to that
of an infinite cellular automaton consisting of an array or “space” of cells,
each cell containing the same finite automaton. He chose an infinite
checkerboard array for modeling self-reproduction, and he specified a
particular twenty-nine-state automaton for each square cell. Each automaton is
connected directly to its four contiguous neighbors, and communication between
neighbors takes one or two time-steps. The twenty-nine states of a cell fall
into three categories. There is a blank state to represent the passivity of an
empty area. There are twelve states for switching, storage, and communication,
from which any finite automaton can be constructed in a sufficiently large
region of cells. And there are sixteen states for simulating the activities of
construction and destruction. Von Neumann chose these twenty-nine states in
such a way that an area of non-blank cells could compute and grow, i.e.,
activate a path of cells out to a blank region and convert the cells of that
region into a cellular automaton. A specific cellular automaton is embedded in
this space by the selection of the initial states of a finite area of cells,
all other cells being left blank. A universal computer consists of a
sufficiently powerful finite automaton with a tape. The tape is an indefinitely
long row of cells in which bits are represented by two different cell states.
The finite automaton accesses these cells by means of a construction arm that
it extends back and forth in rows of cells contiguous to the tape. When
activated, this finite automaton will execute programs stored on its tape.
self-reproducing automaton self-reproducing automaton 827 827 A universal constructor results from
augmenting the universal computer cf. the robot model. Another construction arm
is added, together with a finite automaton controller to operate it. The
controller sends signals into the arm to extend it out to a blank region of the
cellular space, to move around that region, and to change the states of cells
in that region. After the universal constructor has converted the region into a
cellular automaton, it directs the construction arm to activate the new
automaton and then withdraw from it. Cellular automaton selfreproduction
results from applying the universal constructor to itself, as in the robot
model. Cellular automata are now studied extensively by humans working
interactively with computers as abstract models of both physical and organic
systems. See Arthur W. Burks, “Von Neumann’s Self-Reproducing Automata,” in
Papers of John von Neumann on Computers and Computer Theory, edited by William
Aspray and Arthur Burks, 1987. The study of artificial life is an outgrowth of
computer simulations of cellular automata and related automata. Cellular
automata organizations are sometimes used in highly parallel computers.
Sellars, Wilfrid 191289,
American philosopher, son of Roy Wood Sellars, and one of the great systematic
philosophers of the century. His most influential and representative works are
“Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind” 1956 and “Philosophy and the Scientific
Image of Man” 1960. The Sellarsian system may be outlined as follows. The myth
of the given. Thesis 1: Classical empiricism foundationalism maintains that our
belief in the commonsense, objective world of physical objects is ultimately
justified only by the way that world presents itself in sense experience. Thesis
2: It also typically maintains that sense experience a is not part of that
world and b is not a form of conceptual cognition like thinking or believing.
Thesis 3: From 1 and 2a classical empiricism concludes that our knowledge of
the physical world is inferred from sense experience. Thesis 4: Since
inferences derive knowledge from knowledge, sense experience itself must be a
form of knowledge. Theses 14 collectively are the doctrine of the given. Each
thesis taken individually is plausible. However, Sellars argues that 2b and 4
are incompatible if, as he thinks, knowledge is a kind of conceptual cognition.
Concluding that the doctrine of the given is false, he maintains that classical
empiricism is a myth. The positive system. From an analysis of theoretical
explanation in the physical sciences, Sellars concludes that postulating
theoretical entities is justified only if theoretical laws nomological generalizations referring to
theoretical entities are needed to
explain particular observable phenomena for which explanation in terms of
exceptionless observation laws is unavailable. While rejecting any classical
empiricist interpretation of observation, Sellars agrees that some account of
non-inferential knowledge is required to make sense of theoretical explanation
thus conceived. He thinks that utterances made in direct response to sensory
stimuli observational reports count as non-inferential knowledge when a they
possess authority, i.e., occur in conditions ensuring that they reliably
indicate some physical property say, shape in the environment and are accepted
by the linguistic community as possessing this quality; and b the utterer has
justified belief that they possess this authority. Sellars claims that some
perceptual conditions induce ordinary people to make observation reports
inconsistent with established explanatory principles of the commonsense
framework. We thus might tend to report spontaneously that an object is green
seen in daylight and blue seen indoors, and yet think it has not undergone any
process that could change its color. Sellars sees in such conflicting
tendencies vestiges of a primitive conceptual framework whose tensions have
been partially resolved by introducing the concept of sense experiences. These
experiences count as theoretical entities, since they are postulated to account
for observational phenomena for which no exceptionless observation laws exist.
This example may serve as a paradigm for a process of theoretical explanation
occurring in the framework of commonsense beliefs that Sellars calls the
manifest image, a process that itself is a model for his theory of the rational
dynamics of conceptual change in both the manifest image and in science the scientific image. Because the actual
process of conceptual evolution in Homo sapiens may not fit this pattern of
rational dynamics, Sellars treats these dynamics as occurring within certain
hypothetical ideal histories myths of the way in which, from certain
conSellars, Roy Wood Sellars, Wilfrid 828
828 ceptually primitive beginnings, one might have come to postulate the
requisite theoretical explanations. The manifest image, like the proto-theories
from which it arose, is itself subject to various tensions ultimately resolved
in the scientific image. Because this latter image contains a metaphysical
theory of material objects and persons that is inconsistent with that of its
predecessor framework, Sellars regards the manifest image as replaced by its
successor. In terms of the Peircean conception of truth that Sellars endorses,
the scientific image is the only true image. In this sense Sellars is a
scientific realist. There is, however, also an important sense in which Sellars
is not a scientific realist: despite discrediting classical empiricism, he
thinks that the intrinsic nature of sense experience gives to conceptualization
more than simply sensory stimulus yet less than the content of knowledge
claims. Inspired by Kant, Sellars treats the manifest image as a Kantian
phenomenal world, a world that exists as a cognitive construction which, though
lacking ideal factual truth, is guided in part by intrinsic features of sense
experience. This is not analytic phenomenalism, which Sellars rejects.
Moreover, the special methodological role for sense experience has effects even
within the scientific image itself. Theories of mind, perception, and
semantics. Mind: In the manifest image thoughts are private episodes endowed
with intentionality. Called inner speech, they are theoretical entities whose
causal and intentional properties are modeled, respectively, on inferential and
semantic properties of overt speech. They are introduced within a behaviorist
proto-theory, the Rylean framework, to provide a theoretical explanation for
behavior normally accompanied by linguistically overt reasons. Perception: In
the manifest image sense experiences are sense impressions states of persons modeled on two-dimensional,
colored physical replicas and introduced in the theoretical language of the
adverbial theory of perception to explain why it can look as if some
perceptible quality is present when it is not. Semantics: The meaning of a
simple predicate p in a language L is the role played in L by p defined in
terms of three sets of linguistic rules: language entry rules, intralinguistic
rules, and language departure rules. This account also supports a nominalist
treatment of abstract entities. Identification of a role for a token of p in L
can be effected demonstratively in the speaker’s language by saying that p in L
is a member of the class of predicates playing the same role as a demonstrated
predicate. Thus a speaker of English might say that ‘rot’ in German plays the
semantic role ‘red’ has in English. Sellars sees science and metaphysics as
autonomous strands in a single web of philosophical inquiry. Sellarsianism thus
presents an important alternative to the view that what is fundamentally real
is determined by the logical structure of scientific language alone. Sellars
also sees ordinary language as expressing a commonsense framework of beliefs
constituting a kind of proto-theory with its own methods, metaphysics, and
theoretical entities. Thus, he also presents an important alternative to the
view that philosophy concerns not what is ultimately real, but what words like
‘real’ ultimately mean in ordinary language.
semantic holism, a
metaphysical thesis about the nature of representation on which the meaning of
a symbol is relative to the entire system of representations containing it.
Thus, a linguistic expression can have meaning only in the context of a
language; a hypothesis can have significance only in the context of a theory; a
concept can have intentionality only in the context of the belief system.
Holism about content has profoundly influenced virtually every aspect of
contemporary theorizing about language and mind, not only in philosophy, but in
linguistics, literary theory, artificial intelligence, psychology, and
cognitive science. Contemporary semantic holists include Davidson, Quine,
Gilbert Harman, Hartry Field, and Searle. Because semantic holism is a
metaphysical and not a semantic thesis, two theorists might agree about the
semantic facts but disagree about semantic holism. So, e.g., nothing in
Tarski’s writings determines whether the semantic facts expressed by the
theorems of an absolute truth semantic atomism semantic holism 829 829 theory are holistic or not. Yet
Davidson, a semantic holist, argued that the correct form for a semantic theory
for a natural language L is an absolute truth theory for L. Semantic theories,
like other theories, need not wear their metaphysical commitments on their
sleeves. Holism has some startling consequences. Consider this. Franklin D.
Roosevelt who died when the United States still had just forty-eight states did
not believe there were fifty states, but I do; semantic holism says that what
‘state’ means in our mouths depends on the totality of our beliefs about
states, including, therefore, our beliefs about how many states there are. It
seems to follow that he and I must mean different things by ‘state’; hence, if
he says “Alaska is not a state” and I say “Alaska is a state” we are not
disagreeing. This line of argument leads to such surprising declarations as
that natural langauges are not, in general, intertranslatable Quine, Saussure; that
there may be no fact of the matter about the meanings of texts Putnam, Derrida;
and that scientific theories that differ in their basic postulates are
“empirically incommensurable” Paul Feyerabend, Kuhn. For those who find these
consequences of semantic holism unpalatable, there are three mutually exclusive
responses: semantic atomism, semantic molecularism, or semantic nihilism.
Semantic atomists hold that the meaning of any representation linguistic,
mental, or otherwise is not determined by the meaning of any other
representation. Historically, Anglo-American philosophers in the eighteenth and
nineteenth centuries thought that an idea of an X was about X’s in virtue of
this idea’s physically resembling X’s. Resemblance theories are no longer
thought viable, but a number of contemporary semantic atomists still believe
that the basic semantic relation is between a concept and the things to which
it applies, and not one among concepts themselves. These philosophers include
Dretske, Dennis Stampe, Fodor, and Ruth Millikan. Semantic molecularism, like
semantic holism, holds that the meaning of a representation in a language L is
determined by its relationships to the meanings of other expressions in L, but,
unlike holism, not by its relationships to every other expression in L.
Semantic molecularists are committed to the view, contrary to Quine, that for
any expression e in a language L there is an in-principle way of distinguishing
between those representations in L the meanings of which determine the meaning
of e and those representations in L the meanings of which do not determine the
meaning of e. Traditionally, this inprinciple delimitation is supported by an
analytic/synthetic distinction. Those representations in L that are
meaning-constituting of e are analytically connected to e and those that are
not meaning-constituting are synthetically connected to e. Meaning molecularism
seems to be the most common position among those philosophers who reject
holism. Contemporary meaning molecularists include Michael Devitt, Dummett, Ned
Block, and John Perry. Semantic nihilism is perhaps the most radical response
to the consequences of holism. It is the view that, strictly speaking, there
are no semantic properties. Strictly speaking, there are no mental states; words
lack meanings. At least for scientific purposes and perhaps for other purposes
as well we must abandon the notion that people are moral or rational agents and
that they act out of their beliefs and desires. Semantic nihilists include
among their ranks Patricia and Paul Churchland, Stephen Stich, Dennett, and,
sometimes, Quine.
semantic paradoxes, a
collection of paradoxes involving the semantic notions of truth, predication,
and definability. The liar paradox is the oldest and most widely known of these,
having been formulated by Eubulides as an objection to Aristotle’s
correspondence theory of truth. In its simplest form, the liar paradox arises
when we try to assess the truth of a sentence or proposition that asserts its
own falsity, e.g.: A Sentence A is not true. It would seem that sentence A
cannot be true, since it can be true only if what it says is the case, i.e., if
it is not true. Thus sentence A is not true. But then, since this is precisely
what it claims, it would seem to be true. Several alternative forms of the liar
paradox have been given their own names. The postcard paradox, also known as a
liar cycle, envisions a postcard with sentence B on one side and sentence C on
the other: B The sentence on the other side of this card is true. semantic
molecularism semantic paradoxes 830
830 C The sentence on the other side of this card is false. Here, no
consistent assignment of truth-values to the pair of sentences is possible. In
the preface paradox, it is imagined that a book begins with the claim that at
least one sentence in the book is false. This claim is unproblematically true
if some later sentence is false, but if the remainder of the book contains only
truths, the initial sentence appears to be true if and only if false. The
preface paradox is one of many examples of contingent liars, claims that can
either have an unproblematic truth-value or be paradoxical, depending on the
truth-values of various other claims in this case, the remaining sentences in
the book. Related to the preface paradox is Epimenedes’ paradox: Epimenedes,
himself from Crete, is said to have claimed that all Cretans are liars. This
claim is paradoxical if interpreted to mean that Cretans always lie, or if
interpreted to mean they sometimes lie and if no other claim made by Epimenedes
was a lie. On the former interpretation, this is a simple variation of the liar
paradox; on the latter, it is a form of contingent liar. Other semantic
paradoxes include Berry’s paradox, Richard’s paradox, and Grelling’s paradox.
The first two involve the notion of definability of numbers. Berry’s paradox
begins by noting that names or descriptions of integers consist of finite
sequences of syllables. Thus the three-syllable sequence ‘twenty-five’ names
25, and the seven-syllable sequence ‘the sum of three and seven’ names ten. Now
consider the collection of all sequences of English syllables that are less
than nineteen syllables long. Of these, many are nonsensical ‘bababa’ and some
make sense but do not name integers ‘artichoke’, but some do ‘the sum of three
and seven’. Since there are only finitely many English syllables, there are
only finitely many of these sequences, and only finitely many integers named by
them. Berry’s paradox arises when we consider the eighteen-syllable sequence
‘the smallest integer not nameable in less than nineteen syllables’. This
phrase appears to be a perfectly well-defined description of an integer. But if
the phrase names an integer n, then n is nameable in less than nineteen
syllables, and hence is not described by the phrase. Richard’s paradox
constructs a similarly paradoxical description using what is known as a
diagonal construction. Imagine a list of all finite sequences of letters of the
alphabet plus spaces and punctuation, ordered as in a dictionary. Prune this
list so that it contains only English definitions of real numbers between 0 and
1. Then consider the definition: “Let r be the real number between 0 and 1
whose kth decimal place is if the kth
decimal place of the number named by the kth member of this list is 1, and 0
otherwise’. This description seems to define a real number that must be
different from any number defined on the list. For example, r cannot be defined
by the 237th member of the list, because r will differ from that number in at
least its 237th decimal place. But if it indeed defines a real number between 0
and 1, then this description should itself be on the list. Yet clearly, it
cannot define a number different from the number defined by itself. Apparently,
the definition defines a real number between 0 and 1 if and only if it does not
appear on the list of such definitions. Grelling’s paradox, also known as the
paradox of heterologicality, involves two predicates defined as follows. Say
that a predicate is “autological” if it applies to itself. Thus ‘polysyllabic’
and ‘short’ are autological, since ‘polysyllabic’ is polysyllabic, and ‘short’
is short. In contrast, a predicate is “heterological” if and only if it is not
autological. The question is whether the predicate ‘heterological’ is
heterological. If our answer is yes, then ‘heterological’ applies to
itself and so is autological, not
heterological. But if our answer is no, then it does not apply to itself and so is heterological, once again
contradicting our answer. The semantic paradoxes have led to important work in
both logic and the philosophy of language, most notably by Russell and Tarski.
Russell developed the ramified theory of types as a unified treatment of all
the semantic paradoxes. Russell’s theory of types avoids the paradoxes by
introducing complex syntactic conditions on formulas and on the definition of
new predicates. In the resulting language, definitions like those used in
formulating Berry’s and Richard’s paradoxes turn out to be ill-formed, since they
quantify over collections of expressions that include themselves, violating
what Russell called the vicious circle principle. The theory of types also
rules out, on syntactic grounds, predicates that apply to themselves, or to
larger expressions containing those very same predicates. In this way, the liar
paradox and Grelling’s paradox cannot be constructed within a language
conforming to the theory of types. Tarski’s attention to the liar paradox made
two fundamental contributions to logic: his development of semantic techniques
for defining the truth predicate for formalized languages and his semantic
paradoxes semantic paradoxes 831 831
proof of Tarski’s theorem. Tarskian semantics avoids the liar paradox by starting
with a formal language, call it L, in which no semantic notions are
expressible, and hence in which the liar paradox cannot be formulated. Then
using another language, known as the metalanguage, Tarski applies recursive
techniques to define the predicate true-in-L, which applies to exactly the true
sentences of the original language L. The liar paradox does not arise in the
metalanguage, because the sentence D Sentence D is not true-in-L. is, if
expressible in the metalanguage, simply true. It is true because D is not a
sentence of L, and so a fortiori not a true sentence of L. A truth predicate
for the metalanguage can then be defined in yet another language, the
metametalanguage, and so forth, resulting in a sequence of consistent truth
predicates. Tarski’s theorem uses the liar paradox to prove a significant
result in logic. The theorem states that the truth predicate for the
first-order language of arithmetic is not definable in arithmetic. That is, if
we devise a systematic way of representing sentences of arithmetic by numbers,
then it is impossible to define an arithmetical predicate that applies to all
and only those numbers that represent true sentences of arithmetic. The theorem
is proven by showing that if such a predicate were definable, we could
construct a sentence of arithmetic that is true if and only if it is not true:
an arithmetical version of sentence A, the liar paradox. Both Russell’s and
Tarski’s solutions to the semantic paradoxes have left many philosophers
dissatisfied, since the solutions are basically prescriptions for constructing
languages in which the paradoxes do not arise. But the fact that paradoxes can
be avoided in artificially constructed languages does not itself give a
satisfying explanation of what is going wrong when the paradoxes are
encountered in natural language, or in an artificial language in which they can
be formulated. Most recent work on the liar paradox, following Kripke’s
“Outline of a Theory of Truth” 1975, looks at languages in which the paradox
can be formulated, and tries to provide a consistent account of truth that
preserves as much as possible of the intuitive notion.
semiosis from Grecian
semeiosis, ‘observation of signs’, the relation of signification involving the
three relata of sign, object, and mind. Semiotic is the science or study of
semiosis. The semiotic of John of Saint Thomas and of Peirce includes two
distinct components: the relation of signification and the classification of
signs. The relation of signification is genuinely triadic and cannot be reduced
to the sum of its three subordinate dyads: sign-object, sign-mind, object-mind.
A sign represents an object to a mind just as A gives a gift to B. Semiosis is
not, as it is often taken to be, a mere compound of a sign-object dyad and a
sign-mind dyad because these dyads lack the essential intentionality that
unites mind with object; similarly, the gift relation involves not just A
giving and B receiving but, crucially, the intention uniting A and B. semantics
semiosis 832 832 In the Scholastic
logic of John of Saint Thomas, the sign-object dyad is a categorial relation
secundum esse, that is, an essential relation, falling in Aristotle’s category
of relation, while the sign-mind dyad is a transcendental relation secundum
dici, that is, a relation only in an analogical sense, in a manner of speaking;
thus the formal rationale of semiosis is constituted by the sign-object dyad.
By contrast, in Peirce’s logic, the sign-object dyad and the sign-mind dyad are
each only potential semiosis: thus, the hieroglyphs of ancient Egypt were
merely potential signs until the discovery of the Rosetta Stone, just as a
road-marking was a merely potential sign to the driver who overlooked it.
Classifications of signs typically follow from the logic of semiosis. Thus John
of Saint Thomas divides signs according to their relations to their objects
into natural signs smoke as a sign of fire, customary signs napkins on the
table as a sign that dinner is imminent, and stipulated signs as when a
neologism is coined; he also divides signs according to their relations to a
mind. An instrumental sign must first be cognized as an object before it can
signify e.g., a written word or a symptom; a formal sign, by contrast, directs
the mind to its object without having first been cognized e.g., percepts and concepts.
Formal signs are not that which we cognize but that by which we cognize. All
instrumental signs presuppose the action of formal signs in the semiosis of
cognition. Peirce similarly classified signs into three trichotomies according
to their relations with 1 themselves, 2 their objects, and 3 their
interpretants usually minds; and Charles Morris, who followed Peirce closely,
called the relationship of signs to one another the syntactical dimension of
semiosis, the relationship of signs to their objects the semantical dimension
of semiosis, and the relationship of signs to their interpreters the pragmatic
dimension of semiosis.
sensationalism, the
belief that all mental states
particularly cognitive states are
derived, by composition or association, from sensation. It is often joined to
the view that sensations provide the only evidence for our beliefs, or more
rarely to the view that statements about the world can be reduced, without
loss, to statements about sensation. Hobbes was the first important
sensationalist in modern times. “There is no conception in man’s mind,” he
wrote, “which hath not at first, totally, or by parts, been begotten upon the
organs of sense. The rest are derived from that original.” But the belief
gained prominence in the eighteenth century, due largely to the influence of
Locke. Locke himself was not a sensationalist, because he took the mind’s
reflection on its own operations to be an independent source of ideas. But his
distinction between simple and complex ideas was used by eighteenthcentury
sensationalists such as Condillac and Hartley to explain how conceptions that
seem distant from sense might nonetheless be derived from it. And to account
for the particular ways in which simple ideas are in fact combined, Condillac and
Hartley appealed to a second device described by Locke: the association of
ideas. “Elementary” sensations the
building blocks of our mental life were
held by the sensationalists to be non-voluntary, independent of judgment, free
of interpretation, discrete or atomic, and infallibly known. Nineteenth-century
sensationalists tried to account for perception in terms of such building
blocks; they struggled particularly with the perception of space and time. Late
nineteenth-century critics such as Ward and James advanced powerful arguments
against the reduction of perception to sensation. Perception, they claimed,
involves more than the passive reception or recombination and association of
discrete pellets of incorrigible information. They urged a change in perspective to a functionalist viewpoint more closely
allied with prevailing trends in biology
from which sensationalism never fully recovered.
sensibile: Austin, “Sense
and sensibile,” as used by Russell, those entities that no one is at the moment
perceptually aware of, but that are, in every other respect, just like the
objects of perceptual awareness. If one is a direct realist and believes that
the objects one is aware of in sense perception are ordinary physical objects,
then sensibilia are, of course, just physical objects of which no one is at the
moment aware. Assuming with common sense that ordinary objects continue to
exist when no one is aware of them, it follows that sensibilia exist. If,
however, one believes as Russell did that what one is aware of in ordinary
sense perception is some kind of idea in the mind, a so-called sense-datum,
then sensibilia have a problematic status. A sensibile then turns out to be an
unsensed sense-datum. On some the usual conceptions of sense-data, this is like
an unfelt pain, since a sense-datum’s existence not as a sense-datum, but as
anything at all depends on our someone’s perception of it. To exist for such
things is to be perceived see Berkeley’s “esse est percipii“. If, however, one
extends the notion of sense-datum as Moore was inclined to do to whatever it is
of which one is directly aware in sense perception, then sensibilia may or may
not exist. It depends on what physical
objects or ideas in the mind we are
directly aware of in sense perception and, of course, on the empirical facts
about whether objects continue to exist when they are not being perceived. If
direct realists are right, horses and trees, when unobserved, are sensibilia.
So are the front surfaces of horses and trees things Moore once considered to
be sensedata. If the direct realists are wrong, and what we are perceptually
aware of are “ideas in the mind,” then whether or not sensibilia exist depends
on whether or not such ideas can exist apart from any mind.
sensorium, the seat and cause
of sensation in the brain of humans and other animals. The term is not part of
contemporary psychological parlance; it belongs to prebehavioral, prescientific
psychology, especially of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. Only
creatures possessed of a sensorium were thought capable of bodily and
perceptual sensations. Some thinkers believed that the sensorium, when excited,
also produced muscular activity and motion.
sensus communis, a
cognitive faculty to which the five senses report. It was first argued for in
Aristotle’s On the Soul II.12, though the term ‘common sense’ was first
introduced in Scholastic thought. Aristotle refers to properties such as
magnitude that are perceived by more than one sense as common sensibles. To
recognize common sensibles, he claims, we must possess a single cognitive power
to compare such qualities, received from the different senses, to one another.
Augustine says the “inner sense” judges whether the senses are working
properly, and perceives whether the animal perceives De libero arbitrio II.35.
Aquinas In De anima II, 13.370 held that it is also by the common sense that we
perceive we live. He says the common sense uses the external senses to know
sensible forms, preparing the sensible species it receives for the operation of
the cognitive power, which recognizes the real thing causing the sensible
species.
sentential connective,
also called sentential operator, propositional connective, propositional
operator, a word or phrase, such as ‘and’, ‘or’, or ‘if . . . then’, that is
used to construct compound sentences from atomic i.e., non-compound sentences. A sentential connective can be
defined formally as an expression containing blanks, such that when the blanks
are replaced with sentences the result is a compound sentence. Thus, ‘if ———
then ———’ and ‘——— or ———’ are sentential connectives, since we can replace the
blanks with sentences to get the compound sentences ‘If the sky is clear then
we can go swimming’ and ‘We can go swimming or we can stay home’. Classical
logic makes use of truth-functional connectives only, for which the truth-value
of the compound sentence can be determined uniquely by the truth-value of the
sentences that replace the blanks. The standard truth-functional sensibilia
sentential connective 834 834
connectives are ‘and’, ‘or’, ‘not’, ‘if . . . then’, and ‘if and only if’.
There are many non-truth-functional connectives as well, such as ‘it is
possible that ———’ and ‘——— because ———’.
sentimentalism, the
theory, prominent in the eighteenth century, that epistemological or moral
relations are derived from feelings. Although sentimentalism and sensationalism
are both empiricist positions, the latter view has all knowledge built up from
sensations, experiences impinging on the senses. Sentimentalists may allow that
ideas derive from sensations, but hold that some relations between them are
derived internally, that is, from sentiments arising upon reflection. Moral
sentimentalists, such as Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, and Hume, argued that the
virtue or vice of a character trait is established by approving or disapproving
sentiments. Hume, the most thoroughgoing sentimentalist, also argued that all
beliefs about the world depend on sentiments. On his analysis, when we form a
belief, we rely on the mind’s causally connecting two experiences, e.g., fire
and heat. But, he notes, such causal connections depend on the notion of
necessity that the two perceptions will
always be so conjoined and there is
nothing in the perceptions themselves that supplies that notion. The idea of
necessary connection is instead derived from a sentiment: our feeling of
expectation of the one experience upon the other. Likewise, our notions of
substance the unity of experiences in an object and of self the unity of experiences
in a subject are sentimentbased. But whereas moral sentiments do not purport to
represent the external world, these metaphysical notions of necessity,
substance, and self are “fictions,” creations of the imagination purporting to
represent something in the outside world.
set-theoretic paradoxes,
a collection of paradoxes that reveal difficulties in certain central notions
of set theory. The best-known of these are Russell’s paradox, Burali-Forti’s
paradox, and Cantor’s paradox. Russell’s paradox, discovered in 1901 by
Bertrand Russell, is the simplest and so most problematic of the set-theoretic
paradoxes. Using it, we can derive a contradiction directly from Cantor’s
unrestricted comprehension schema. This schema asserts that for any formula Px containing
x as a free variable, there is a set {x _ Px} whose members are exactly those
objects that satisfy Px. To derive the contradiction, take Px to be the formula
x 1 x, and let z be the set {x _ x 2 x} whose existence is guaranteed by the
comprehension schema. Thus z is the set whose members are exactly those objects
that are not members of themselves. We now ask whether z is, itself, a member
of z. If the answer is yes, then we can conclude that z must satisfy the
criterion of membership in z, i.e., z must not be a member of z. But if the
answer is no, then since z is not a member of itself, it satisfies the
criterion for membership in z, and so z is a member of z. All modern
axiomatizations of set theory avoid Russell’s paradox by restricting the principles
that assert the existence of sets. The simplest restriction replaces
unrestricted comprehension with the separation schema. Separation asserts that,
given any set A and formula Px, there is a set {x 1 A _ Px}, whose members are
exactly those members of A that satisfy Px. If we now take Px to be the formula
x 2 x, then separation guarantees the existence of a set zA % {x 1 A _ x 2 x}.
We can then use Russell’s reasoning to prove the result that zA cannot be a
member of the original set A. If it were a member of A, then we could prove
that it is a member of itself if and only if it is not a member of itself.
Hence it is not a member of A. But this result is not problematic, and so the
paradox is avoided. The Burali-Forte paradox and Cantor’s paradox are sometimes
known as paradoxes of size, since they show that some collections are too large
to be considered sets. The Burali-Forte paradox, discovered by Cesare
Burali-Forte, is concerned with the set of all ordinal numbers. In Cantor’s set
theory, an ordinal number can be sentential operator set-theoretic paradoxes
835 835 assigned to any well-ordered
set. A set is wellordered if every subset of the set has a least element. But
Cantor’s set theory also guarantees the existence of the set of all ordinals,
again due to the unrestricted comprehension schema. This set of ordinals is
well-ordered, and so can be associated with an ordinal number. But it can be
shown that the associated ordinal is greater than any ordinal in the set, hence
greater than any ordinal number. Cantor’s paradox involves the cardinality of
the set of all sets. Cardinality is another notion of size used in set theory:
a set A is said to have greater cardinality than a set B if and only if B can
be mapped one-to-one onto a subset of A but A cannot be so mapped onto B or any
of its subsets. One of Cantor’s fundamental results was that the set of all
subsets of a set A known as the power set of A has greater cardinality than the
set A. Applying this result to the set V of all sets, we can conclude that the
power set of V has greater cardinality than V. But every set in the power set
of V is also in V since V contains all sets, and so the power set of V cannot
have greater cardinality than V. We thus have a contradiction. Like Russell’s
paradox, both of these paradoxes result from the unrestricted comprehension
schema, and are avoided by replacing it with weaker set-existence principles.
Various principles stronger than the separation schema are needed to get a
reasonable set theory, and many alternative axiomatizations have been proposed.
But the lesson of these paradoxes is that no setexistence principle can entail
the existence of the Russell set, the set of all ordinals, or the set of all
sets, on pain of contradiction.
set theory, the study of
collections, ranging from familiar examples like a set of encyclopedias or a
deck of cards to mathematical examples like the set of natural numbers or the
set of points on a line or the set of functions from a set A to another set B.
Sets can be specified in two basic ways: by a list e.g., {0, 2, 4, 6, 8} and as
the extension of a property e.g., {x _ x is an even natural number less than
10}, where this is read ‘the set of all x such that x is an even natural number
less than 10’. The most fundamental relation in set theory is membership, as in
‘2 is a member of the set of even natural numbers’ in symbols: 2 1 {x _ x is an
even natural number}. Membership is determinate, i.e., any candidate for
membership in a given set is either in the set or not in the set, with no room
for vagueness or ambiguity. A set’s identity is completely determined by its
members or elements i.e., sets are extensional rather than intensional. Thus {x
_ x is human} is the same set as {x _ x is a featherless biped} because they have
the same members. The smallest set possible is the empty or null set, the set
with no members. There cannot be more than one empty set, by extensionality. It
can be specified, e.g., as {x _ x & x}, but it is most often symbolized as
/ or { }. A set A is called a subset of a set B and B a superset of A if every
member of A is also a member of B; in symbols, A 0 B. So, the set of even
natural numbers is a subset of the set of all natural numbers, and any set is a
superset of the empty set. The union of two sets A and B is the set whose
members are the members of A and the members of B in symbols, A 4 B % {x _ x 1 A or x 1 B} so the union of the set of even natural
numbers and the set of odd natural numbers is the set of all natural numbers.
The intersection of two sets A and B is the set whose members are common to
both A and B in symbols, A 3 B % {x _ x
1 A and x 1 B} so the intersection of
the set of even natural numbers and the set of prime natural numbers is the
singleton set {2}, whose only member is the number 2. Two sets whose
intersection is empty are called disjoint, e.g., the set of even natural
numbers and the set of odd natural numbers. Finally, the difference between a
set A and a set B is the set whose members are members of A but not members of
B in symbols, A B % {x _ x 1 A and x 2 B} so the set of odd numbers between 5 and 20
minus the set of prime natural numbers is {9, 15}. By extensionality, the order
in which the members of a set are listed is unimportant, i.e., {1, 2, 3} % {2,
3, 1}. To introduce the concept of ordering, we need the notion of the ordered
pair of a and b in symbols, a, b or .
All that is essential to ordered pairs is that two of them are equal only when
their first entries are equal and their second entries are equal. Various sets
can be used to simulate this behavior, but the version most commonly used is
the Kuratowski ordered pair: a, b is defined to be {{a}, {a, b}}. On this
definition, it can indeed be proved that a, b % c, d if and only if a % c and b
% d. The Cartesian product of two sets A and B is the set of all ordered pairs
whose first entry is in A and whose second entry is B in symbols, A $ B % {x _ x % a, b for some a
1 A and some b 1 B}. This set-theoretic reflection principles set theory
836 836 same technique can be used to
form ordered triples a, b, c % a, b, c;
ordered fourtuples a, b, c, d % a, b, c,
d; and by extension, ordered n-tuples for all finite n. Using only these simple
building blocks, substitutes for all the objects of classical mathematics can
be constructed inside set theory. For example, a relation is defined as a set
of ordered pairs so the successor
relation among natural numbers becomes {0, 1, 1, 2, 2, 3 . . . } and a function is a relation containing no
distinct ordered pairs of the form a, b and a, c so the successor relation is a function. The
natural numbers themselves can be identified with various sequences of sets,
the most common of which are finite von Neumann ordinal numbers: /, {/}, {/,
{/}, {/}, {/}, {/, {/}}}, . . . . On this definition, 0 % /, 1 % {/}, 2 % {/,
{/}}, etc., each number n has n members, the successor of n is n 4 {n}, and n ‹
m if and only if n 1 m. Addition and multiplication can be defined for these
numbers, and the Peano axioms proved from the axioms of set theory; see below.
Negative, rational, real, and complex numbers, geometric spaces, and more
esoteric mathematical objects can all be identified with sets, and the standard
theorems about them proved. In this sense, set theory provides a foundation for
mathematics. Historically, the theory of sets arose in the late nineteenth
century. In his work on the foundations of arithmetic, Frege identified the
natural numbers with the extensions of certain concepts; e.g., the number two
is the set of all concepts C under which two things fall in symbols, 2 % {x _ x is a concept, and
there are distinct things a and b which fall under x, and anything that falls
under x is either a or b}. Cantor was led to consider complex sets of points in
the pursuit of a question in the theory of trigonometric series. To describe
the properties of these sets, Cantor introduced infinite ordinal numbers after
the finite ordinals described above. The first of these, w, is {0, 1, 2, . .
.}, now understood in von Neumann’s terms as the set of all finite ordinals.
After w, the successor function yields w ! 1 % w 4 {w} % {0, 1, 2, . . . n, n +
1, . . . , w}, then w ! 2 % w ! 1 ! 1 % {0, 1, 2, . . . , w , w ! 1}, w ! 3 % w
! 2 ! 1 % {0, 1, 2, . . . , w, w ! 1, w ! 2}, and so on; after all these comes
w ! w % {0, 1, 2, . . . , w, w ! 1, w ! 2, . . . , w ! n, w ! n ! 1, . . .},
and the process begins again. The ordinal numbers are designed to label the
positions in an ordering. Consider, e.g., a reordering of the natural numbers
in which the odd numbers are placed after the evens: 0, 2, 4, 6, . . . 1, 3, 5,
7, . . . . The number 4 is in the third position of this sequence, and the
number 5 is in the w + 2nd. But finite numbers also perform a cardinal
function; they tell us how many so-andso’s there are. Here the infinite
ordinals are less effective. The natural numbers in their usual order have the
same structure as w, but when they are ordered as above, with the evens before
the odds, they take on the structure of a much larger ordinal, w ! w. But the
answer to the question, How many natural numbers are there? should be the same
no matter how they are arranged. Thus, the transfinite ordinals do not provide
a stable measure of the size of an infinite set. When are two infinite sets of
the same size? On the one hand, the infinite set of even natural numbers seems
clearly smaller than the set of all natural numbers; on the other hand, these
two sets can be brought into one-to-one correspondence via the mapping that
matches 0 to 0, 1 to 2, 2 to 4, 3 to 6, and in general, n to 2n. This puzzle
had troubled mathematicians as far back as Galileo, but Cantor took the
existence of a oneto-one correspondence between two sets A and B as the
definition of ‘A is the same size as B’. This coincides with our usual
understanding for finite sets, and it implies that the set of even natural
numbers and the set of all natural numbers and w ! 1 and w! 2 and w ! w and w !
w and many more all have the same size. Such infinite sets are called
countable, and the number of their elements, the first infinite cardinal
number, is F0. Cantor also showed that the set of all subsets of a set A has a
size larger than A itself, so there are infinite cardinals greater than F0,
namely F1, F2, and so on. Unfortunately, the early set theories were prone to
paradoxes. The most famous of these, Russell’s paradox, arises from
consideration of the set R of all sets that are not members of themselves: is R
1 R? If it is, it isn’t, and if it isn’t, it is. The Burali-Forti paradox involves
the set W of all ordinals: W itself qualifies as an ordinal, so W 1 W, i.e., W
‹ W. Similar difficulties surface with the set of all cardinal numbers and the
set of all sets. At fault in all these cases is a seemingly innocuous principle
of unlimited comprehension: for any property P, there is a set {x _ x has P}.
Just after the turn of the century, Zermelo undertook to systematize set theory
by codifying its practice in a series of axioms from which the known
derivations of the paradoxes could not be carried out. He proposed the axioms
of extensionality two sets with the same members are the same; pairing for any
a and b, there is a set {a, b}; separation for any set A and property P, there
set theory set theory 837 837 is a set
{x _ x 1 A and x has P}; power set for any set A, there is a set {x _ x0 A};
union for any set of sets F, there is a set {x _ x 1 A for some A 1 F} this yields A 4 B, when F % {A, B} and {A, B}
comes from A and B by pairing; infinity w exists; and choice for any set of
non-empty sets, there is a set that contains exactly one member from each. The
axiom of choice has a vast number of equivalents, including the well-ordering
theorem every set can be well-ordered and Zorn’s lemma if every chain in a partially ordered set has
an upper bound, then the set has a maximal element. The axiom of separation
limits that of unlimited comprehension by requiring a previously given set A
from which members are separated by the property P; thus troublesome sets like
Russell’s that attempt to collect absolutely all things with P cannot be
formed. The most controversial of Zermelo’s axioms at the time was that of
choice, because it posits the existence of a choice set a set that “chooses” one from each of
possibly infinitely many non-empty sets
without giving any rule for making the choices. For various
philosophical and practical reasons, it is now accepted without much debate.
Fraenkel and Skolem later formalized the axiom of replacement if A is a set,
and every member a of A is replaced by some b, then there is a set containing
all the b’s, and Skolem made both replacement and separation more precise by
expressing them as schemata of first-order logic. The final axiom of the
contemporary theory is foundation, which guarantees that sets are formed in a
series of stages called the iterative hierarchy begin with some non-sets, then
form all possible sets of these, then form all possible sets of the things
formed so far, then form all possible sets of these, and so on. This iterative
picture of sets built up in stages contrasts with the older notion of the
extension of a concept; these are sometimes called the mathematical and the
logical notions of collection, respectively. The early controversy over the
paradoxes and the axiom of choice can be traced to the lack of a clear
distinction between these at the time. Zermelo’s first five axioms all but
choice plus foundation form a system usually called Z; ZC is Z with choice
added. Z plus replacement is ZF, for Zermelo-Fraenkel, and adding choice makes
ZFC, the theory of sets in most widespread use today. The consistency of ZFC
cannot be proved by standard mathematical means, but decades of experience with
the system and the strong intuitive picture provided by the iterative
conception suggest that it is. Though ZFC is strong enough for all standard
mathematics, it is not enough to answer some natural set-theoretic questions
e.g., the continuum problem. This has led to a search for new axioms, such as
large cardinal assumptions, but no consensus on these additional principles has
yet been reached.
Sextus Empiricus third
century A.D., Grecian Skeptic philosopher whose writings are the chief source
of our knowledge about the extreme Skeptic view, Pyrrhonism. Practically
nothing is known about him as a person. He was apparently a medical doctor and
a teacher in a Skeptical school, probably in Alexandria. What has survived are
his Hypotoposes, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, and a series of Skeptical critiques,
Against the Dogmatists, questioning the premises and conclusions in many
disciplines, such as physics, mathematics, rhetoric, and ethics. In these
works, Sextus summarized and organized the views of Skeptical arguers before
him. The Outlines starts with an attempt to indicate what Skepticism is, to
explain the terminology employed by the Skeptics, how Pyrrhonian Skepticism
differs from other so-called Skeptical views, and how the usual answers to
Skepticism are rebutted. Sextus points out that the main Hellenistic
philosophies, Stoicism, Epicureanism, and Academic Skepticism which is
presented as a negative dogmatism, claimed that they would bring the adherent
peace of mind, ataraxia. Unfortunately the dogmatic adherent would only become
more perturbed by seeing the Skeptical objections that could be brought against
his or her view. Then, by suspending judgment, epoche, one would find the
tranquillity being sought. Pyrrhonian Skepticism is a kind of mental hygiene or
therapy that cures one of dogmatism or rashness. It is like a purge that cleans
out foul matter as well as itself. To bring about this state of affairs there
are sets of Skeptical arguments that should bring one to suspense of judgment.
The first set are the ten tropes of the earlier Skeptic, Anesidemus. The next
are the five tropes about causality. And lastly are the tropes about the
criterion of knowledge. The ten tropes stress the variability of sense
experience among men seven emotions the Sextus Empiricus 838 838 and animals, among men, and within one individual.
The varying and conflicting experiences present conflicts about what the
perceived object is like. Any attempt to judge beyond appearances, to ascertain
that which is non-evident, requires some way of choosing what data to accept.
This requires a criterion. Since there is disagreement about what criterion to
employ, we need a criterion of a criterion, and so on. Either we accept an
arbitrary criterion or we get into an infinite regress. Similarly if we try to
prove anything, we need a criterion of what constitutes a proof. If we offer a
proof of a theory of proof, this will be circular reasoning, or end up in
another infinite regress. Sextus devotes most of his discussion to challenging
Stoic logic, which claimed that evident signs could reveal what is non-evident.
There might be signs that suggested what is temporarily non-evident, such as
smoke indicating that there is a fire, but any supposed linkage between evident
signs and what is non-evident can be challenged and questioned. Sextus then
applies the groups of Skeptical arguments to various specific subjects physics, mathematics, music, grammar,
ethics showing that one should suspend
judgment on any knowledge claims in these areas. Sextus denies that he is
saying any of this dogmatically: he is just stating how he feels at given moments.
He hopes that dogmatists sick with a disease, rashness, will be cured and led
to tranquillity no matter how good or bad the Skeptical arguments might
be.
Shaftesbury, Lord, in
full, Third Earl of Shaftesbury, title of Anthony Ashley Cooper 1671 1713,
English philosopher and politician who originated the moral sense theory. He
was born at Wimborne St. Giles, Dorsetshire. As a Country Whig he served in the
House of Commons for three years and later, as earl, monitored meetings of the
House of Lords. Shaftesbury introduced into British moral philosophy the notion
of a moral sense, a mental faculty unique to human beings, involving reflection
and feeling and constituting their ability to discern right and wrong. He
sometimes represents the moral sense as analogous to a purported aesthetic
sense, a special capacity by which we perceive, through our emotions, the
proportions and harmonies of which, on his Platonic view, beauty is composed.
For Shaftesbury, every creature has a “private good or interest,” an end to
which it is naturally disposed by its constitution. But there are other goods
as well notably, the public good and the
good without qualification of a sentient being. An individual creature’s
goodness is defined by the tendency of its “natural affections” to contribute
to the “universal system” of nature of which it is a part i.e., their tendency to promote the public
good. Because human beings can reflect on actions and affections, including
their own and others’, they experience emotional responses not only to physical
stimuli but to these mental objects as well e.g., to the thought of one’s
compassion or kindness. Thus, they are capable of perceiving and acquiring through their actions a particular species of goodness, namely,
virtue. In the virtuous person, the person of integrity, natural appetites and
affections are in harmony with each other wherein lies her private good and in
harmony with the public interest. Shaftesbury’s attempted reconciliation of
selflove and benevolence is in part a response to the egoism of Hobbes, who
argued that everyone is in fact motivated by self-interest. His defining
morality in terms of psychological and public harmony is also a reaction to the
divine voluntarism of his former tutor, Locke, who held that the laws of nature
and morality issue from the will of God. On Shaftesbury’s view, morality exists
independently of religion, but belief in God serves to produce the highest
degree of virtue by nurturing a love for the universal system. Shaftesbury’s
theory led to a general refinement of eighteenth-century ideas about moral
feelings; a theory of the moral sense emerged, whereby sentiments are under certain conditions perceptions of, or constitutive of, right and
wrong. In addition to several essays collected in three volumes under the title
Characteristics of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times second edition, 1714,
Shaftesbury also wrote stoical moral and religious meditations reminiscent of
Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius. His ideas on moral sentiments exercised considerable
influence on the ethical theories of Hutcheson and Hume, who later worked out
in detail their own accounts of the moral sense. shan, o, Chinese terms for ‘good’ and ‘evil’,
respectively. These are primary concerns for Chinese philosophers: the
Confucianists wanted to do good and get rid of evil, while the Taoists wanted
to go beyond good and evil. In fact the Shaftesbury shan, o 839 839 Taoists presupposed that man has the
ability to reach a higher level of spirituality. Chinese philosophers often
discussed shan and o in relation to human nature. Mencius believed that nature
is good; his opponent Kao Tzu, nature is neither good nor evil; Hsün Tzu,
nature is evil; and Yang Hsiung, nature is both good and evil. Most Chinese
philosophers believed that man is able to do good; they also accepted evil as
something natural that needed no explanation.
shang ti, Chinese term
meaning ‘high ancestor’, ‘God’. Shang ti
synonymous with t’ien, in the sense of a powerful anthropomorphic
entity is responsible for such things as
the political fortunes of the state. Some speculate that shang ti was
originally only a Shang deity, later identified by the Chou conquerors with
their t’ien. The term shang ti is also used as a translation of ‘God’.
Shang Yang, also called
Lord Shang d. 338 B.C., Chinese statesman. A prime minister of Ch’in and
prominent Legalist, he emphasized the importance of fa law, or more broadly,
impartial standards for punishment and reward to the sociopolitical order.
Shang Yang maintained that agriculture and war were the keys to a strong state.
However, humans are self-interested rational actors. Their interest to avoid
hard work and the risk of death in battle is at odds with the ruler’s desire
for a strong state. Accordingly, the ruler must rely on harsh punishments and
positive rewards to ensure the cooperation of the people.
Shankara, also
transliterated Sankara and Samkara A.D. 788820, Indian philosopher who founded
Advaita Vedanta Hinduism. His major works are the Brahma-Sutra-Bhafya a
commentary on Badarayana’s Brahma Sutras and his Gita-Bhayfa a commentary on
the Bhagavad Gita. He provides a vigorous defense of mindbody dualism, of the
existence of a plurality of minds and mind-independent physical objects, and of
monotheism. Then, on the basis of appeal to sruti scripture i.e., the Vedas and Upanishads and an esoteric enlightenment experience
moksha, he relegates dualism, realism, and theism to illusion the level of
appearance in favor of a monism that holds that only nirguna or qualityless
Brahman exists the level of reality. Some interpreters read this distinction
between levels metaphysically rather than epistemologically, but this is
inconsistent with Shankara’s monism.
Shao Yung 101177, Chinese
philosopher, a controversial Neo-Confucian figure. His Huangchi ching-shih
“Ultimate Principles Governing the World” advances a numerological
interpretation of the I-Ching. Shao noticed that the IChing expresses certain
cosmological features in numerical terms. He concluded that the cosmos itself
must be based on numerical relationships and that the I-Ching is its cipher,
which is why the text can be used to predict the future. One of Shao’s charts
of the I-Ching’s hexagrams came to the attention of Leibniz, who noticed that,
so arranged, they can be construed as describing the numbers 063 in binary
expression. Shao probably was not aware of this, and Leibniz interpreted Shao’s
arrangement in reverse order, but they shared the belief that certain numerical
sequences revealed the structure of the cosmos. P.J.I. Sheffer stroke, also
called alternative denial, a binary truth-functor represented by the symbol
‘_’, the logical force of which can be expressed contextually in terms of ‘-’
and ‘&’ by the following definition: p_q % Df -p & q. The importance of
the Sheffer stroke lies in the fact that it by itself can express any
well-formed expression of truth-functional logic. Thus, since {-,7} forms an
expressively complete set, defining -p as p_p and p 7 q as p_p _q_q provides
for the possibility of a further reduction of primitive functors to one. This
system of symbols is commonly called the stroke notation. I.Bo. shen, Chinese
term meaning ‘spirit’, ‘spiritual’, ‘numinous’, ‘demonic’. In early texts, shen
is used to mean various nature spirits, with emphasis on the efficacy of
spirits to both know and accomplish hence one seeks their advice and aid. Shen
came to describe the operations of nature, which accomplishes its ends with
“spiritual” efficacy. In texts like the Chuang Tzu, Hsün Tzu, and I-Ching, shen
no longer refers to an entity but to a state of resonance with the cosmos. In
such a state, the sage can tap into the “spiritual” nature of an event,
situation, person, or text and successfully read, react to, and guide the
course of events. P.J.I. sheng, Chinese term meaning ‘the sage’, ‘sagehood’.
This is the Chinese concept of extraordishang ti sheng 840 840 nary human attainment or perfection.
Philosophical Taoism focuses primarily on sheng as complete attunement or
adaptability to the natural order of events as well as irregular occurrences
and phenomena. Classical Confucianism focuses, on the other hand, on the ideal
unity of Heaven t’ien and human beings as having an ethical significance in
resolving human problems. Neo-Confucianism tends to focus on sheng as a
realizable ideal of the universe as a moral community. In Chang Tsai’s words,
“Heaven is my father and Earth is my mother, and even such a small creature as
I finds an intimate place in their midst. . . . All people are my brothers and
sisters, and all things are my companions.” In Confucianism, sheng the sage is
often viewed as one who possesses comprehensive knowledge and insights into the
ethical significance of things, events, and human affairs. This ideal of sheng
contrasts with chün-tzu, the paradigmatic individual who embodies basic ethical
virtues jen, li, i, and chih, but is always liable to error, especially in
responding to changing circumstances of human life. For Confucius, sheng
sagehood is more like an abstract, supreme ideal of a perfect moral
personality, an imagined vision rather than a possible objective of the moral
life. He once remarked that he could not ever hope to meet a sheng-jen a sage,
but only a chün-tzu. For his eminent followers, on the other hand, e.g.,
Mencius, Hsün Tzu, and the Neo-Confucians, sheng is a humanly attainable
ideal.
Shen Pu-hai d.337 B.C.,
Chinese Legalist philosopher who emphasized shu, pragmatic methods or
techniques of bureaucratic control whereby the ruler checked the power of
officials and ensured their subordination. These techniques included impartial
application of publicly promulgated positive law, appointment based on merit,
mutual surveillance by officials, and most importantly hsing ming the assignment of punishment and reward based
on the correspondence between one’s official title or stipulated duties ming
and one’s performance hsing. Law for Shen Pu-hai was one more pragmatic means
to ensure social and bureaucratic order.
HSING, MING. R.P.P. & R.T.A. Shen Tao, also called Shen Tzu 350?275?
B.C., Chinese philosopher associated with Legalism, Taoism, and the HuangLao
school. Depicted in the Chuang Tzu as a simple-minded naturalist who believed
that one only had to abandon knowledge to follow tao the Way, Shen Tao advocated
rule by law where laws were to be impartial, publicly promulgated, and changed
only if necessary and then in accordance with tao. His main contribution to
Legalist theory is the notion that the ruler must rely on shih political
purchase, or the power held by virtue of his position. Shen’s law is the
pragmatic positive law of the Legalists rather than the natural law of
HuangLao.
Shepherd, Mary d.1847,
Scottish philosopher whose main philosophical works are An Essay on the
Relation of Cause and Effect 1824 and Essays on the Perception of an External
Universe 1827. The first addresses what she takes to be the skeptical
consequences of Hume’s account of causation, but a second target is the use
William Lawrence 17831867 made of Hume’s associative account of causation to
argue that mental functions are reducible to physiological ones. The second
work focuses on Hume’s alleged skepticism with regard to the existence of the
external world, but she is also concerned to distinguish her position from
Berkeley’s. Shepherd was drawn into a public controversy with John Fearn, who
published some remarks she had sent him on a book of his, together with his
extensive reply. Shepherd replied in an article in Fraser’s magazine 1832,
“Lady Mary Shepherd’s Metaphysics,” which deftly refuted Fearn’s rather
condescending attack.
Sherwood, William, also
called William Shyreswood 1200/101266/71, English logician who taught logic at
Oxford and at Paris between 1235 and 1250. He was the earliest of the three
great “summulist” writers, the other two whom he influenced strongly being
Peter of Spain and Lambert of Auxerre fl. 1250. His main works are
Introductiones in Logicam, Syncategoremata, De insolubilibus, and Obligationes
some serious doubts have recently arisen about the authorship of the latter
work. Since M. Grabmann published Sherwood’s Introductiones in 1937, historians
of logic have paid considerable attention to this seminal medieval logician.
While the first four chapters of Introductiones offer the basic ideas of Aristotle’s
Organon, and the last chapter neatly lays out the Sophistical Refutations, the
fifth tract expounds the famous doctrine of the properties of terms:
signification, supposition, conjunction, and appellation hence the label ‘terminist’ for this sort of
logic. These Shen Pu-hai Sherwood, William 841
841 logico-semantic discussions, together with the discussions of
syncategorematic words, constitute the logica moderna, as opposed to the more
strictly Aristotelian contents of the earlier logica vetus and logica nova. The
doctrine of properties of terms and the analysis of syncategorematic terms,
especially those of ‘all’, ‘no’ and ‘nothing’, ‘only’, ‘not’, ‘begins’ and
‘ceases’, ‘necessarily’, ‘if’, ‘and’, and ‘or’, may be said to constitute
Sherwood’s philosophy of logic. He not only distinguishes categorematic
descriptive and syncategorematic logical words but also shows how some terms
are used categorematically in some contexts and syncategorematically in others.
He recognizes the importance of the order of words and of the scope of logical
functors; he also anticipates the variety of composite and divided senses of
propositions. Obligationes, if indeed his, attempts to state conditions under
which a formal disputation may take place. De Insolubilibus deals with
paradoxes of self-reference and with ways of solving them. Understanding
Sherwood’s logic is important for understanding the later medieval developments
of logica moderna down to Ockham. I.Bo. shih1, Chinese term meaning ‘strategic
advantage’. Shih was the key and defining idea in the Militarist philosophers,
later appropriated by some of the other classical schools, including the
Legalists Han Fei Tzu and the Confucians Hsün Tzu. Like ritual practices li and
speaking yen, shih is a level of discourse through which one actively
cultivates the leverage and influence of one’s particular place. In the
Military texts, the most familiar metaphor for shih is the taut trigger on the
drawn crossbow, emphasizing advantageous position, timing, and precision. Shih
like immanental order generally begins from the full consideration of the
concrete detail. The business of war or effective government does not occur as
some independent and isolated event, but unfolds within a broad field of unique
natural, social, and political conditions proceeding according to a general
pattern that can not only be anticipated but manipulated to one’s advantage. It
is the changing configuration of these specific conditions that determines
one’s place and one’s influence at any point in time, and gives one a defining
disposition. Shih includes intangible forces such as morale, opportunity,
timing, psychology, and logistics.
shih2, Chinese term
meaning ‘scholar-knight’ and ‘service’. In the service of the rulers of the
“central states” of preimperial China, shih were a lower echelon of the
official nobility responsible for both warfare and matters at court, including
official documentation, ritual protocol, and law. Most of the early
philosophers, trained in the “six arts” of rites, music, archery,
charioteering, writing, and counting, belonged to this stratum. Without
hereditary position, they lived by their wits and their professional skills,
and were responsible for both the intellectual vigor and the enormous social
mobility of Warring States China 403221 B.C..
ship of Theseus, the ship
of the Grecian hero Theseus, which, according to Plutarch “Life of Theseus,”
23, the Athenians preserved by gradually replacing its timbers. A classic
debate ensued concerning identity over time. Suppose a ship’s timbers are
replaced one by one over a period of time; at what point, if any, does it cease
to be the same ship? What if the ship’s timbers, on removal, are used to build
a new ship, identical in structure with the first: which ship has the best
claim to be the original ship?
Shpet, Gustav Gustavovich
18791937, leading Russian phenomenologist and highly regarded student and
friend of Husserl. He played a major role in the development of phenomenology
in Russia prior to the revolution. Graduating from Kiev in 1906, Shpet accompanied his mentor
Chelpanov to Moscow in 1907, commencing graduate studies at Moscow M.A., 1910; Ph.D., 1916. He attended
Husserl’s seminars at Göttingen during 191213, out of which developed a
continuing friendship between the two, recorded in correspondence extending
through 1918. In 1914 Shpet published a meditation, Iavlenie i smysl Appearance
and Sense, inspired by Husserl’s Logical Investigations and, especially, Ideas
I, which had appeared in 1913. Between 1914 and 1927 he published six
additional books on such disparate topics as the concept of history, Herzen,
Russian philosophy, aesthetics, ethnic psychology, and language. He founded and
edited the philosophical yearbook Mysl’ i slovo Thought and Word between 1918
and 1921, publishing an important article on skepticism in it. He was arrested
in 1935 and sentenced to internal exile. Under these conditions he completed a
fine new translation of Hegel’s Phenomenology into Russian, which was published
in 1959. He was executed in November 1937.
.
shu1, Chinese term for
‘technique of statecraft’. Such techniques were advocated by Shen Pu-hai and
the other Legalist philosophers as instruments of the ruler in power that would
guarantee the stable and efficient operations of government. The best-known shu
include 1 “accountability” hsing-ming: the duties and obligations of office are
clearly articulated, and at intervals a comparison is made between stipulated
responsibilities ming and performance hsing; 2 “doing nothing” wu-wei: the
engine of state is constructed so that the ministers are integral, functioning
components guided by clearly promulgated laws fa, while the ruler stands aloof
as the embodiment of the authority of government, thereby receiving credit for successes
and deflecting blame back to the officials; 3 “showing nothing” wu-hsien: by
secreting the royal person, concealing all likes and dislikes, and proffering
no opinion, the ruler not only shields his limitations from public scrutiny,
but further encourages a personal mystique as an ideal invested with a
superlative degree of all things worthwhile.
Sidgwick, Henry 18381900,
English philosopher, economist, and educator. Best known for The Methods of
Ethics1874, he also wrote the still valuable Outlines of the History of Ethics
1886, as well as studies of economics, politics, literature, and alleged
psychic phenomena. He was deeply involved in the founding of the first for women at Cambridge , where he was a professor.
In the Methods Sidgwick tried to assess the rationality of the main ways in
which ordinary people go about making moral decisions. He thought that our
common “methods of ethics” fall into three main patterns. One is articulated by
the philosophical theory known as intuitionism. This is the view that we can
just see straight off either what particular act is right or what binding rule
or general principle we ought to follow. Another common method is spelled out
by philosophical egoism, the view that we ought in each act to get as much good
as we can for ourselves. The third widely used method is represented by
utilitarianism, the view that we ought in each case to bring about as much good
as possible for everyone affected. Can any or all of the methods prescribed by
these views be rationally defended? And how are they related to one another? By
framing his philosophical questions in these terms, Sidgwick made it centrally
important to examine the chief philosophical theories of morality in the light
of the commonsense morals of his time. He thought that no theory wildly at odds
with commonsense morality would be acceptable. Intuitionism, a theory
originating with Butler, transmitted by Reid, and most systematically expounded
during the Victorian era by Whewell, was widely held to be the best available
defense of Christian morals. Egoism was thought by many to be the clearest
pattern of practical rationality and was frequently said to be compatible with
Christianity. And J. S. Mill had argued that utilitarianism was both rational
and in accord with common sense. But whatever their relation to ordinary
morality, the theories seemed to be seriously at odds with one another.
Examining all the chief commonsense precepts and rules of morality, such as
that promises ought to be kept, Sidgwick argued that none is truly self-evident
or intuitively certain. Each fails to guide us at certain points where we
expect it to answer our practical questions. Utilitarianism, he found, could
provide a complicated method for filling these gaps. But what ultimately justifies
utilitarianism is certain very general axioms seen intuitively to be true.
Among them are the principles that what is right in one case must be right in
any similar case, and that we ought to aim at good generally, not just at some
particular part of it. Thus intuitionism and utilitarianism can be reconciled.
When taken together they yield a complete and justifiable method of ethics that
is in accord with common sense. What then of egoism? It can provide as complete
a method as utilitarianism, and it also involves a self-evident axiom. But its
results often contradict those of utilitarianism. Hence there is a serious
problem. The method that instructs us to act always for the good generally and
the method that tells one to act solely for one’s own good are equally
rational. Since the two methods give contradictory directions, while each
method rests on self-evident axioms, it shriek operator Sidgwick, Henry
843 843 seems that practical reason is
fundamentally incoherent. Sidgwick could see no way to solve the problem.
Sidgwick’s bleak conclusion has not been generally accepted, but his Methods is
widely viewed as one of the best works of moral philosophy ever written. His
account of classical utilitarianism is unsurpassed. His discussions of the general
status of morality and of particular moral concepts are enduring models of
clarity and acumen. His insights about the relations between egoism and
utilitarianism have stimulated much valuable research. And his way of framing
moral problems, by asking about the relations between commonsense beliefs and
the best available theories, has set much of the agenda for twentiethcentury
ethics.
Siger of Brabant
c.124084, French philosopher, an activist in the philosophical and political
struggles both within the arts faculty and between arts and theology at Paris
during the 1260s and 1270s. He is usually regarded as a leader of a “radical
Aristotelianism” that owed much to Liber de causis, to Avicenna, and to
Averroes. He taught that everything originates through a series of emanations
from a first cause. The world and each species including the human species are
eternal. Human beings share a single active intellect. There is no good reason
to think that Siger advanced the view that there was a double truth, one in
theology and another in natural philosophy. It is difficult to distinguish
Siger’s own views from those he attributes to “the Philosophers” and thus to
know the extent to which he held the heterodox views he taught as the best
interpretation of the prescribed texts in the arts curriculum. In any case,
Siger was summoned before the French Inquisition in 1276, but fled Paris. He
was never convicted of heresy, but it seems that the condemnations at Paris in
1277 were partially directed at his teaching. He was stabbed to death by his
clerk in Orvieto then the papal seat in 1284. .
signifier, a vocal sound
or a written symbol. The concept owes its modern formulation to the Swiss
linguist Saussure. Rather than using the older conception of sign and referent,
he divided the sign itself into two interrelated parts, a signifier and a
signified. The signified is the concept and the signifier is either a vocal
sound or writing. The relation between the two, according to Saussure, is
entirely arbitrary, in that signifiers tend to vary with different languages.
We can utter or write ‘vache’, ‘cow’, or ‘vaca’, depending on our native
language, and still come up with the same signified i.e., concept.
Simmel, Georg 18581918,
German philosopher and one of the founders of sociology as a distinct
discipline. Born and educated in Berlin, he was a popular lecturer at its university.
But the unorthodoxy of his interests and unprofessional writing style probably
kept him from being offered a regular professorship until 1914, and then only
at the provincial of Strasbourg. He died
four years later. His writings ranged from conventional philosophical
topics with books on ethics, philosophy
of history, education, religion, and the philosophers Kant, Schopenhauer, and
Nietzsche to books on Rembrandt, Goethe,
and the philosophy of money. He wrote numerous essays on various artists and
poets, on different cities, and on such themes as love, adventure, shame, and
on being a stranger, as well as on many specifically sociological topics.
Simmel was regarded as a Kulturphilosoph who meditated on his themes in an
insightful and digressive rather than scholarly and systematic style. Though
late in life he sketched a unifying Lebensphilosophie philosophy of life that
considers all works and structures of culture as products of different forms of
human experience, Simmel has remained of interest primarily for a multiplicity
of insights into specific topics.
Simplicius sixth century
A.D., Grecian Neoplatonist philosopher born in Cilicia on the southeast coast
of modern Turkey. His surviving works are extensive commentaries on Aristotle’s
On the Heavens, Physics, and Categories, and on the Encheiridion of Epictetus.
The authenticity of the commentary on Aristotle’s On the Soul attributed to Simplicius
has been disputed. He studied with Ammonius in Alexandria, and with Damascius,
the last known head of the Platonist school in Athens. Justinian closed the
school in 529. Two or three years later a group of philosophers, including
Damascius and Simplicius, visited the court of the Sassanian king Khosrow I
Chosroes but soon returned to the Byzantine Empire under a guarantee of their
right to maintain their own beliefs. It is generally agreed that most, if not
all, of Simplicius’s extant works date from the period after his stay with
Khosrow. But there is no consensus about where Simplicius spent his last years
both Athens and Harran have been proposed recently, or whether he resumed
teaching philosophy; his commentaries, unlike most of the others that survive
from that period, are scholarly treatises rather than classroom expositions.
Simplicius’s Aristotle commentaries are the most valuable extant works in the
genre. He is our source for many of the fragments of the preSocratic
philosophers, and he frequently invokes material from now-lost commentaries and
philosophical works. He is a deeply committed Neoplatonist, convinced that
there is no serious conflict between the philosophies of Plato and Aristotle.
The view of earlier scholars that his Encheiridion commentary embodies a more
moderate Platonism associated with Alexandria is now generally rejected.
Simplicius’s virulent defense of the eternity of the world in response to the
attack of the Christian John Philoponus illustrates the intellectual vitality
of paganism at a time when the Mediterranean world had been officially
Christian for about three centuries.
simulation theory, the
view that one represents the mental activities and processes of others by
mentally simulating them, i.e., generating similar activities and processes in
oneself. By simulating them, one can anticipate their product or outcome; or,
where this is already known, test hypotheses about their starting point. For
example, one anticipates the product of another’s theoretical or practical
inferences from given premises by making inferences from the same premises
oneself; or, knowing what the product is, one retroduces the premises. In the
case of practical reasoning, to reason from the same premises would typically
require indexical adjustments, such as shifts in spatial, temporal, and
personal “point of view,” to place oneself in the other’s physical and
epistemic situation insofar as it differs from one’s own. One may also
compensate for the other’s reasoning capacity and level of expertise, if
possible, or modify one’s character and outlook as an actor might, to fit the
other’s background. Such adjustments, even when insufficient for making
decisions in the role of the other, allow one to discriminate between action
options likely to be attractive or unattractive to the agent. One would be
prepared for the former actions and surprised by the latter. The simulation
theory is usually considered an alternative to an assumption sometimes called
the “theory theory” that underlies much recent philosophy of mind: that our
commonsense understanding of people rests on a speculative theory, a “folk
psychology” that posits mental states, events, and processes as unobservables
that explain behavior. Some hold that the simulation theory undercuts the
debate between philosophers who consider folk psychology a respectable theory
and those the eliminative materialists who reject it. Unlike earlier writing on
empathic understanding and historical reenactment, discussions of the
simulation theory often appeal to empirical findings, particularly experimental
results in developmental psychology. They also theorize about the mechanism
that would accomplish simulation: presumably one that calls up computational
resources ordinarily used for engagement with the world, but runs them
off-line, so that their output is not “endorsed” or acted upon and their inputs
are not limited to those that would regulate one’s own behavior. Although
simulation theorists agree that the ascription of mental states to others relies
chiefly on simulation, they differ on the nature of selfascription. Some
especially Robert Gordon and simple supposition simulation theory 845 845 Jane Heal, who independently proposed
the theory give a non-introspectionist account, while others especially Goldman
lean toward a more traditional introspectionist account. The simulation theory
has affected developmental psychology as well as branches of philosophy outside
the philosophy of mind, especially aesthetics and philosophy of the social
sciences. Some philosophers believe it sheds light on traditional topics such
as the problem of other minds, referential opacity, broad and narrow content,
and the peculiarities of self-knowledge.
singular term, an
expression, such as ‘Zeus’, ‘the President’, or ‘my favorite chair’, that can
be the grammatical subject of what is semantically a subject-predicate
sentence. By contrast, a general term, such as ‘table’ or ‘swam’ is one that
can serve in predicative position. It is also often said that a singular term is
a word or phrase that could refer or ostensibly refer, on a given occasion of
use, only to a single object, whereas a general term is predicable of more than
one object. Singular terms are thus the expressions that replace, or are
replaced by, individual variables in applications of such quantifier rules as
universal instantiation and existential generalization or flank ‘%’ in identity
statements.
situation ethics, a kind
of anti-theoretical, caseby-case applied ethics in vogue largely in some
European and American religious circles for twenty years or so following World
War II. It is characterized by the insistence that each moral choice must be
determined by one’s particular context or situation i.e., by a consideration of the outcomes that
various possible courses of action might have, given one’s situation. To that
degree, situation ethics has affinities to both act utilitarianism and
traditional casuistry. But in contrast to utilitarianism, situation ethics
rejects the idea that there are universal or even fixed moral principles beyond
various indeterminate commitments or ideals e.g., to Christian love or
humanism. In contrast to traditional casuistry, it rejects the effort to
construct general guidelines from a case or to classify the salient features of
a case so that it can be used as a precedent. The anti-theoretical stance of
situation ethics is so thoroughgoing that writers identified with the position
have not carefully described its connections to consequentialism,
existentialism, intuitionism, personalism, pragmatism, relativism, or any other
developed philosophical view to which it appears to have some affinity.
Siva, one of the great
gods of Hinduism with Vishnu and Brahman, auspicious controller of karma and
samsara, destroyer but also giver of life. He is worshiped in Saivism with his
consort Sakti. A variety of deities are regarded in Saivism as forms of Siva,
with the consequence that polytheism is moved substantially toward monotheism.
K.E.Y. six emotions the.CH’ING. skepticism, in the most common sense, the
refusal to grant that there is any knowledge or justification. Skepticism can
be either partial or total, either practical or theoretical, and, if
theoretical, either moderate or radical, and either of knowledge or of
justification. Skepticism is partial iff if and only if it is restricted to
particular fields of beliefs or propositions, and total iff not thus
restricted. And if partial, it may be highly restricted, as is the skepticism
for which religion is only opium, or much more general, as when not only is
religion simulator, universal skepticism 846
846 called opium, but also history bunk and metaphysics meaningless.
Skepticism is practical iff it is an attitude of deliberately withholding both
belief and disbelief, accompanied perhaps but not necessarily by commitment to
a recommendation for people generally, that they do likewise. Practical
skepticism can of course be either total or partial, and if partial it can be
more or less general. Skepticism is theoretical iff it is a commitment to the
belief that there is no knowledge justified belief of a certain kind or of
certain kinds. Such theoretical skepticism comes in several varieties. It is
moderate and total iff it holds that there is no certain superknowledge
superjustified belief whatsoever, not even in logic or mathematics, nor through
introspection of one’s present experience. It is radical and total iff it holds
that there isn’t even any ordinary knowledge justified belief at all. It is
moderate and partial, on the other hand, iff it holds that there is no certain
superknowledge superjustified belief of a certain specific kind K or of certain
specific kinds K1, . . . , Kn less than the totality of such kinds. It is
radical and partial, finally, iff it holds that there isn’t even any ordinary
knowledge justified belief at all of that kind K or of those kinds K1, . . . ,
Kn. Grecian skepticism can be traced back to Socrates’ epistemic modesty.
Suppressed by the prolific theoretical virtuosity of Plato and Aristotle, such
modesty reasserted itself in the skepticism of the Academy led by Arcesilaus
and later by Carneades. In this period began a long controversy pitting
Academic Skeptics against the Stoics Zeno and later Chrysippus, and their
followers. Prolonged controversy, sometimes heated, softened the competing
views, but before agreement congealed Anesidemus broke with the Academy and
reclaimed the arguments and tradition of Pyrrho, who wrote nothing, but whose
Skeptic teachings had been preserved by a student, Timon in the third century
B.C.. After enduring more than two centuries, neoPyrrhonism was summarized,
c.200 A.D., by Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism and Adversus
mathematicos. Skepticism thus ended as a school, but as a philosophical
tradition it has been influential long after that, and is so even now. It has
influenced strongly not only Cicero Academica and De natura deorum, St.
Augustine Contra academicos, and Montaigne “Apology for Raimund Sebond”, but
also the great historical philosophers of the Western tradition, from Descartes
through Hegel. Both on the Continent and in the Anglophone sphere a new wave of
skepticism has built for decades, with logical positivism, deconstructionism,
historicism, neopragmatism, and relativism, and the writings of Foucault
knowledge as a mask of power, Derrida deconstruction, Quine indeterminacy and
eliminativism, Kuhn incommensurability, and Rorty solidarity over objectivity,
edification over inquiry. At the same time a rising tide of books and articles
continues other philosophical traditions in metaphysics, epistemology, ethics,
etc. It is interesting to compare the cognitive disengagement recommended by
practical skepticism with the affective disengagement dear to stoicism
especially in light of the epistemological controversies that long divided
Academic Skepticism from the Stoa, giving rise to a rivalry dominant in
Hellenistic philosophy. If believing and favoring are positive, with
disbelieving and disfavoring their respective negative counterparts, then the
magnitude of our happiness positive or unhappiness negative over a given matter
is determined by the product of our belief/disbelief and our
favoring/disfavoring with regard to that same matter. The fear of unhappiness
may lead one stoically to disengage from affective engagement, on either side
of any matter that escapes one’s total control. And this is a kind of practical
affective “skepticism.” Similarly, if believing and truth are positive, with
disbelieving and falsity their respective negative counterparts, then the
magnitude of our correctness positive or error negative over a given matter is
determined by the product of our belief/disbelief and the truth/falsity with
regard to that same matter where the positive or negative magnitude of the
truth or falsity at issue may be determined by some measure of “theoretical
importance,” though alternatively one could just assign all truths a value of
!1 and all falsehoods a value of †1. The fear of error may lead one skeptically
to disengage from cognitive engagement, on either side of any matter that
involves risk of error. And this is “practical cognitive skepticism.” We wish
to attain happiness and avoid unhappiness. This leads to the disengagement of
the stoic. We wish to attain the truth and avoid error. This leads to the
disengagement of the skeptic, the practical skeptic. Each opts for a
conservative policy, but one that is surely optional, given just the reasoning
indicated. For in avoiding unhappiness the stoic also forfeits a corresponding
possibility of happiness. And in avoiding error the skeptic also forfeits a
corresponding possibility to grasp a truth. These twin policies appeal to
conservatism in our nature, and will reasonably preskepticism skepticism
847 847 vail in the lives of those
committed to avoiding risk as a paramount objective. For this very desire must
then be given its due, if we judge it rational. Skepticism is instrumental in
the birth of modern epistemology, and modern philosophy, at the hands of
Descartes, whose skepticism is methodological but sophisticated and well
informed by that of the ancients. Skepticism is also a main force, perhaps the
main force, in the broad sweep of Western philosophy from Descartes through
Hegel. Though preeminent in the history of our subject, skepticism since then
has suffered decades of neglect, and only in recent years has reclaimed much
attention and even applause. Some recent influential discussions go so far as
to grant that we do not know we are not dreaming. But they also insist one can
still know when there is a fire before one. The key is to analyze knowledge as
a kind of appropriate responsiveness to its object truth: what is required is
that the subject “track” through his belief the truth of what he believes. S
tracks the truth of P iff: S would not believe P if P were false. Such an
analysis of tracking, when conjoined with the view of knowledge as tracking,
enables one to explain how one can know about the fire even if for all one
knows it is just a dream. The crucial fact here is that even if P logically
entails Q, one may still be able to track the truth of P though unable to track
the truth of Q. Nozick, Philosophical Explanations, 1981. Many problems arise
in the literature on this approach. One that seems especially troubling is that
though it enables us to understand how contingent knowledge of our surroundings
is possible, the tracking account falls short of enabling an explanation of how
such knowledge on our part is actual. To explain how one knows that there is a
fire before one F, according to the tracking account one presumably would
invoke one’s tracking the truth of F. But this leads deductively almost
immediately to the claim that one is not dreaming: Not D. And this is not
something one can know, according to the tracking account. So how is one to
explain one’s justification for making that claim? Most troubling of all here
is the fact that one is now cornered by the tracking account into making
combinations of claims of the following form: I am quite sure that p, but I
have no knowledge at all as to whether p. And this seems incoherent. A
Cartesian dream argument that has had much play in recent discussions of
skepticism is made explicit by Barry Stroud, The Significance of Philosophical
Scepticism, 1984 as follows. One knows that if one knows F then one is not
dreaming, in which case if one really knows F then one must know one is not
dreaming. However, one does not know one is not dreaming. So one does not know
F. Q.E.D. And why does one fail to know one is not dreaming? Because in order
to know it one would need to know that one has passed some test, some empirical
procedure to determine whether one is dreaming. But any such supposed test say, pinching oneself could just be part of a dream, and dreaming
one passes the test would not suffice to show one was not dreaming. However,
might one not actually be witnessing the fire, and passing the test and be doing this in wakeful life, not in a
dream and would that not be compatible
with one’s knowing of the fire and of one’s wakefulness? Not so, according to
the argument, since in order to know of the fire one needs prior knowledge of
one’s wakefulness. But in order to know of one’s wakefulness one needs prior
knowledge of the results of the test procedure. But this in turn requires prior
knowledge that one is awake and not dreaming. And we have a vicious circle. We
might well hold that it is possible to know one is not dreaming even in the
absence of any positive test result, or at most in conjunction with coordinate
not prior knowledge of such a positive indication. How in that case would one
know of one’s wakefulness? Perhaps one would know it by believing it through
the exercise of a reliable faculty. Perhaps one would know it through its
coherence with the rest of one’s comprehensive and coherent body of beliefs.
Perhaps both. But, it may be urged, if these are the ways one might know of
one’s wakefulness, does not this answer commit us to a theory of the form of A
below? A The proposition that p is something one knows believes justifiably if
and only if one satisfies conditions C with respect to it. And if so, are we
not caught in a vicious circle by the question as to how we know what justifies us in believing A itself? This is far from obvious, since the
requirement that we must submit to some test procedure for wakefulness and know
ourselves to test positively, before we can know ourselves to be awake, is
itself a requirement that seems to lead equally to a principle such as A. At
least it is not evident why the proposal of the externalist or of the
coherentist as to how we know we are awake should be any more closely related
to a general principle like A than is the foundationalist? notion skepticism
skepticism 848 848 that in order to know
we are awake we need epistemically prior knowledge that we test positive in a
way that does not presuppose already acquired knowledge of the external world.
The problem of how to justify the likes of A is a descendant of the infamous
“problem of the criterion,” reclaimed in the sixteenth century and again in
this century by Chisholm, Theory of Knowledge, 1966, 1977, and 1988 but much
used already by the Skeptics of antiquity under the title of the diallelus.
About explanations of our knowledge or justification in general of the form
indicated by A, we are told that they are inadequate in a way revealed by
examples like the following. Suppose we want to know how we know anything at
all about the external world, and part of the answer is that we know the
location of our neighbor by knowing the location of her car in her driveway.
Surely this would be at best the beginning of an answer that might be
satisfactory in the end if recursive, e.g., but as it stands it cannot be
satisfactory without supplementation. The objection here is based on a comparison
between two appeals: the appeal of a theorist of knowledge to a principle like
A in the course of explaining our knowledge or justification in general, on one
side; and the appeal to the car’s location in explaining our knowledge of facts
about the external world, on the other side. This comparison is said to be
fatal to the ambition to explain our knowledge or justification in general. But
are the appeals relevantly analogous? One important difference is this. In the
example of the car, we explain the presence, in some subject S, of a piece of
knowledge of a certain kind of the external world by appeal to the presence in
S of some other piece of knowledge of the very same kind. So there is an
immediate problem if it is our aim to explain how any knowledge of the sort in
question ever comes to be unless the explication is just beginning, and is to
turn recursive in due course. Now of course A is theoretically ambitious, and
in that respect the theorist who gives an answer of the form of A is doing
something similar to what must be done by the protagonist in our car example,
someone who is attempting to provide a general explanation of how any knowledge
of a certain kind comes about. Nevertheless, there is also an important
difference, namely that the theorist whose aim it is to give a general account
of the form of A need not attribute any knowledge whatsoever to a subject S in
explaining how that subject comes to have a piece of knowledge or justified
belief. For there is no need to require that the conditions C appealed to by
principle A must be conditions that include attribution of any knowledge at all
to the subject in question. It is true that in claiming that A itself meets
conditions C, and that it is this which explains how one knows A, we do perhaps
take ourselves to know A or at least to be justified in believing it. But if
so, this is the inevitable lot of anyone who seriously puts forward any
explanation of anything. And it is quite different from a proposal that part of
what explains how something is known or justifiably believed includes a claim
to knowledge or justified belief of the very same sort. In sum, as in the case
of one’s belief that one is awake, the belief in something of the form of A may
be said to be known, and in so saying one does not commit oneself to adducing
an ulterior reason in favor of A, or even to having such a reason in reserve.
One is of course committed to being justified in believing A, perhaps even to
having knowledge that A. But it is not at all clear that the only way to be
justified in believing A is by way of adduced reasons in favor of A, or that
one knows A only if one adduces strong enough reasons in its favor. For we
often know things in the absence of such adduced reasons. Thus consider one’s
knowledge through memory of which door one used to come into a room that has
more than one open door. Returning finally to A, in its case the explanation of
how one knows it may, once again, take the form of an appeal to the justifying
power of intellectual virtues or of coherence
or both. Recent accounts of the nature of thought and representation
undermine a tradition of wholesale doubt about nature, whose momentum is hard
to stop, and threatens to leave the subject alone and restricted to a solipsism
of the present moment. But there may be a way to stop skepticism early by questioning the possibility of its being
sensibly held, given what is required for meaningful language and thought.
Consider our grasp of observable shape and color properties that objects around
us might have. Such grasp seems partly constituted by our discriminatory
abilities. When we discern a shape or a color we do so presumably in terms of a
distinctive impact that such a shape or color has on us. We are put
systematically into a certain distinctive state X when we are appropriately
related, in good light, with our eyes open, etc., to the presence in our
environment of that shape or color. What makes one’s distinctive state one of
thinking of sphericity rather than something else, is said to be that it is a
state tied by systematic causal relations to skepticism skepticism 849 849 the presence of sphericity in one’s
normal environment. A light now flickers at the end of the skeptic’s tunnel. In
doubt now is the coherence of traditional skeptical reflection. Indeed, our
predecessors in earlier centuries may have moved in the wrong direction when
they attempted a reduction of nature to the mind. For there is no way to make
sense of one’s mind without its contents, and there is no way to make sense of
how one’s mind can have such contents except by appeal to how one is causally
related to one’s environment. If the very existence of that environment is put
in doubt, that cuts the ground from under one’s ability reasonably to
characterize one’s own mind, or to feel any confidence about its contents.
Perhaps, then, one could not be a “brain in a vat.” Much contemporary thought
about language and the requirements for meaningful language thus suggests that
a lot of knowledge must already be in place for us to be able to think
meaningfully about a surrounding reality, so as to be able to question its very
existence. If so, then radical skepticism answers itself. For if we can so much
as understand a radical skepticism about the existence of our surrounding reality,
then we must already know a great deal about that reality.
Skeptics, those ancient
thinkers who developed sets of arguments to show either that no knowledge is
possible Academic Skepticism or that there is not sufficient or adequate
evidence to tell if any knowledge is possible. If the latter is the case then
these thinkers advocated suspending judgment on all question concerning
knowledge Pyrrhonian Skepticism. Academic Skepticism gets its name from the
fact that it was formulated in Plato’s Academy in the third century B.C.,
starting from Socrates’ statement, “All I know is that I know nothing.” It was
developed by Arcesilaus c.268241 and Carneades c.213129, into a series of
arguments, directed principally against the Stoics, purporting to show that
nothing can be known. The Academics posed a series of problems to show that
what we think we know by our senses may be unreliable, and that we cannot be
sure about the reliability of our reasoning. We do not possess a guaranteed
standard or criterion for ascertaining which of our judgments is true or false.
Any purported knowledge claim contains some element that goes beyond immediate
experience. If this claim constituted knowledge we would have to know something
that could not possibly be false. The evidence for the claim would have to be
based on our senses and our reason, both of which are to some degree
unreliable. So the knowledge claim may be false or doubtful, and hence cannot
constitute genuine knowledge. So, the Academics said that nothing is certain.
The best we can attain is probable information. Carneades is supposed to have
developed a form of verification theory and a kind of probabilism, similar in
some ways to that of modern pragmatists and positivists. Academic Skepticism
dominated the philosophizing of Plato’s Academy until the first century B.C.
While Cicero was a student there, the Academy turned from Skepticism to a kind
of eclectic philosophy. Its Skeptical arguments have been preserved in Cicero’s
works, Academia and De natura deorum, in Augustine’s refutation in his Contra
academicos, as well as in the summary presented by Diogenes Laertius in his
lives of the Grecian philosophers. Skeptical thinking found another home in the
school of the Pyrrhonian Skeptics, probably connected with the Methodic school
of medicine in Alexandria. The Pyrrhonian movement traces its origins to Pyrrho
of Elis c.360275 B.C. and his student Timon c.315225 B.C.. The stories about
Pyrrho indicate that he was not a theoretician but a practical doubter who would
not make any judgments that went beyond immediate experience. He is supposed to
have refused to judge if what appeared to be chariots might strike him, and he
was often rescued by his students because he would not make any commitments.
His concerns were apparently ethical. He sought to avoid unhappiness that might
result from accepting any value theory. If the theory was at all doubtful,
accepting it might lead to mental anguish. The theoretical formulation of
Pyrrhonian Skepticism is attributed to Aenesidemus c.100 40 B.C.. Pyrrhonists
regarded dogmatic philosophers and Academic Skeptics as asserting too much, the
former saying that something can be known and the latter that nothing can be
known. The Pyrrhonists suspended judgments on all questions on which there was
any conflicting evidence, including whether or not anything could be known. The
Pyrrhonists used some of the same kinds of arguments developed by Arcesilaus
and skepticism, moral Skeptics 850 850
Carneades. Aenesidemus and those who followed after him organized the arguments
into sets of “tropes” or ways of leading to suspense of judgment on various
questions. Sets of ten, eight, five, and two tropes appear in the only
surviving writing of the Pyrrhonists, the works of Sextus Empiricus, a third-century
A.D. teacher of Pyrrhonism. Each set of tropes offers suggestions for
suspending judgment about any knowledge claims that go beyond appearances. The
tropes seek to show that for any claim, evidence for and evidence against it
can be offered. The disagreements among human beings, the variety of human
experiences, the fluctuation of human judgments under differing conditions,
illness, drunkenness, etc., all point to the opposition of evidence for and
against each knowledge claim. Any criterion we employ to sift and weigh the
evidence can also be opposed by countercriterion claims. Given this situation,
the Pyrrhonian Skeptics sought to avoid committing themselves concerning any
kind of question. They would not even commit themselves as to whether the
arguments they put forth were sound or not. For them Skepticism was not a
statable theory, but rather an ability or mental attitude for opposing evidence
for and against any knowledge claim that went beyond what was apparent, that
dealt with the non-evident. This opposing produced an equipollence, a balancing
of the opposing evidences, that would lead to suspending judgment on any
question. Suspending judgment led to a state of mind called “ataraxia,”
quietude, peace of mind, or unperturbedness. In such a state the Skeptic was no
longer concerned or worried or disturbed about matters beyond appearances. The
Pyrrhonians averred that Skepticism was a cure for a disease called “dogmatism”
or rashness. The dogmatists made assertions about the non-evident, and then
became disturbed about whether these assertions were true. The disturbance
became a mental disease or disorder. The Pyrrhonians, who apparently were
medical doctors, offered relief by showing the patient how and why he should
suspend judgment instead of dogmatizing. Then the disease would disappear and
the patient would be in a state of tranquillity, the peace of mind sought by
Hellenistic dogmatic philosophers. The Pyrrhonists, unlike the Academic
Skeptics, were not negative dogmatists. The Pyrrhonists said neither that
knowledge is possible nor that it is impossible. They remained seekers, while
allowing the Skeptical arguments and the equipollence of evidences to act as a
purge of dogmatic assertions. The purge eliminates all dogmas as well as itself.
After this the Pyrrhonist lives undogmatically, following natural inclinations,
immediate experience, and the laws and customs of his society, without ever
judging or committing himself to any view about them. In this state the
Pyrrhonist would have no worries, and yet be able to function naturally and
according to law and custom. The Pyrrhonian movement disappeared during the
third century A.D., possibly because it was not considered an alternative to
the powerful religious movements of the time. Only scant traces of it appear
before the Renaissance, when the texts of Sextus and Cicero were rediscovered
and used to formulate a modern skeptical view by such thinkers as Montaigne and
Charron.
Skolem, Thoralf 18871963,
Norwegian mathematician. A pioneer of mathematical logic, he made fundamental
contributions to recursion theory, set theory in particular, the proposal and
formulation in 1922 of the axiom of replacement, and model theory. His most
important results for the philosophy of mathematics are the Downward
Löwenheim-Skolem theorem 1919, 1922, whose first proof involved putting
formulas into Skolem normal form; and a demonstration 193334 of the existence
of models of first-order arithmetic not isomorphic to the standard model. Both
results exhibit the extreme non-categoricity that can occur with formulations
of mathematical theories in firstorder logic, and caused Skolem to be skeptical
about the use of formal systems, particularly for set theory, as a foundation
for mathematics. The existence of non-standard models is actually a consequence
of the completeness and first incompleteness theorems Gödel, 1930, 1931, for
these together show that there must be sentences of arithmetic if consistent
that are true in the standard model, but false in some other, nonisomorphic
model. However, Skolem’s result describes a general technique for constructing
such models. Skolem’s theorem is now more easily proved using the compactness
theorem, an easy consequence of the completeness theorem. The Löwenheim-Skolem
theorem produces a similar problem of characterization, the Skolem paradox,
pointed out by Skolem in 1922. Roughly, this says that if first-order set
theory has a model, it must also have a countable model whose continuum is a
countable set, and thus apparently non-standard. This does not contraSkolem,
Thoralf Skolem, Thoralf 851 851 dict
Cantor’s theorem, which merely demands that the countable model contain as an
element no function that maps its natural numbers one-toone onto its continuum,
although there must be such a function outside the model. Although usually seen
as limiting first-order logic, this result is extremely fruitful technically,
providing one basis of the proof of the independence of the continuum
hypothesis from the usual axioms of set theory given by Gödel in 1938 and Cohen
in 1963. This connection between independence results and the existence of
countable models was partially foreseen by Skolem in 1922.
slippery slope argument,
an argument that an action apparently unobjectionable in itself would set in
motion a train of events leading ultimately to an undesirable outcome. The
metaphor portrays one on the edge of a slippery slope, where taking the first
step down will inevitably cause sliding to the bottom. For example, it is
sometimes argued that voluntary euthanasia should not be legalized because this
will lead to killing unwanted people, e.g. the handicapped or elderly, against
their will. In some versions the argument aims to show that one should
intervene to stop an ongoing train of events; e.g., it has been argued that
suppressing a Communist revolution in one country was necessary to prevent the
spread of Communism throughout a whole region via the so-called domino effect.
Slippery slope arguments with dubious causal assumptions are often classed as
fallacies under the general heading of the fallacy of the false cause. This
argument is also sometimes called the wedge argument. There is some
disagreement concerning the breadth of the category of slippery slope
arguments. Some would restrict the term to arguments with evaluative
conclusions, while others construe it more broadly so as to include other
sorites arguments.
Smart, John Jamieson
Carswell b.1920, British-born Australian philosopher whose name is associated
with three doctrines in particular: the mindbody identity theory, scientific
realism, and utilitarianism. A student of Ryle’s at Oxford, he rejected logical
behaviorism in favor of what came to be known as Australian materialism. This
is the view that mental processes and,
as Armstrong brought Smart to see, mental states cannot be explained simply in terms of
behavioristic dispositions. In order to make good sense of how the ordinary
person talks of them we have to see them as brain processes and states
under other names. Smart developed this identity theory of mind and
brain, under the stimulus of his colleague, U. T. Place, in “Sensations and
Brain Processes” Philosophical Review, 1959. It became a mainstay of
twentieth-century philosophy. Smart endorsed the materialist analysis of mind
on the grounds that it gave a simple picture that was consistent with the
findings of science. He took a realist view of the claims of science, rejecting
phenomenalism, instrumentalism, and the like, and he argued that commonsense
beliefs should be maintained only so far as they are plausible in the light of
total science. Philosophy and Scientific Realism 1963 gave forceful expression
to this physicalist picture of the world, as did some later works. He attracted
attention in particular for his argument that if we take science seriously then
we have to endorse the four-dimensional picture of the universe and recognize
as an illusion the experience of the passing of time. He published a number of
defenses of utilitarianism, the best known being his contribution to J. J. C.
Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism, For and Against 1973. He gave new
life to act utilitarianism at a time when utilitarians were few and most were
attached to rule utilitarianism or other restricted forms of the doctrine.
Smith, Adam 172390,
Scottish economist and philosopher, a founder of modern political economy and a
major contributor to ethics and the psychology of morals. His first published
work was The Theory of Moral Sentiments 1759. This book immediately made him
famous, and earned the praise of thinkers of the stature of Hume, Burke, and
Kant. It sought to answer two questions: Wherein does virtue consist, and by
means of what psychological principles do we deterSkolem-Löwenheim theorem
Smith, Adam 852 852 mine this or that
to be virtuous or the contrary? His answer to the first combined ancient Stoic
and Aristotelian views of virtue with modern views derived from Hutcheson and
others. His answer to the second built on Hume’s theory of sympathy our ability to put ourselves imaginatively in
the situation of another as well as on
the notion of the “impartial spectator.” Smith throughout is skeptical about
metaphysical and theological views of virtue and of the psychology of morals.
The self-understanding of reasonable moral actors ought to serve as the moral
philosopher’s guide. Smith’s discussion ranges from the motivation of wealth to
the psychological causes of religious and political fanaticism. Smith’s second
published work, the immensely influential An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes
of the Wealth of Nations 1776, attempts to explain why free economic,
political, and religious markets are not only more efficient, when properly
regulated, but also more in keeping with nature, more likely to win the
approval of an impartial spectator, than monopolistic alternatives. Taken
together, Smith’s two books attempt to show how virtue and liberty can
complement each other. He shows full awareness of the potentially dehumanizing
force of what was later called “capitalism,” and sought remedies in schemes for
liberal education and properly organized religion. Smith did not live to
complete his system, which was to include an analysis of “natural
jurisprudence.” We possess student notes of his lectures on jurisprudence and
on rhetoric, as well as several impressive essays on the evolution of the
history of science and on the fine arts.
social action, a subclass
of human action involving the interaction among agents and their mutual
orientation, or the action of groups. While all intelligible actions are in
some sense social, social actions must be directed to others. Talcott Parsons
190279 captured what is distinctive about social action in his concept of
“double contingency,” and similar concepts have been developed by other
philosophers and sociologists, including Weber, Mead, and Wittgenstein. Whereas
in monological action the agents’ fulfilling their purposes depends only on
contingent facts about the world, the success of social action is also
contingent on how other agents react to what the agent does and how that agent
reacts to other agents, and so on. An agent successfully communicates, e.g.,
not merely by finding some appropriate expression in an existing symbol system,
but also by understanding how other agents will understand him. Game theory
describes and explains another type of double contingency in its analysis of
the interdependency of choices and strategies among rational agents. Games are
also significant in two other respects. First, they exemplify the cognitive
requirements for social interaction, as in Mead’s analysis of agents’
perspective taking: as a subject “I”, I am an object for others “me”, and can
take a third-person perspective along with others on the interaction itself
“the generalized other”. Second, games are regulated by shared rules and
mediated through symbolic meanings; Wittgenstein’s private language argument
establishes that rules cannot be followed “privately.” Some philosophers, such
as Peter Winch, conclude from this argument that rule-following is a basic
feature of distinctively social action. Some actions are social in the sense
that they can only be done in groups. Individualists such as Weber, Jon Elster,
and Raimo Tuomela believe that these can be analyzed as the sum of the actions
of each individual. But holists such as Marx, Durkheim, and Margaret Gilbert
reject this reduction and argue that in social actions agents must see
themselves as members of a collective agent. Holism has stronger or weaker
versions: strong holists, such as Durkheim and Hegel, see the collective
subject as singular, the collective consciousness of a society. Weak holists,
such as Gilbert and Habermas, believe that social actions have plural, rather
than singular, collective subjects. Holists generally establish the
plausibility of their view by referring to larger contexts and sequences of
action, such as shared symbol systems or social institutions. Explanations of
social actions thus refer not only to the mutual expectations of agents, but also
to these larger causal contexts, shared meanings, and mechanisms of
coordination. Theories of social action must then explain the emergence of
social order, and proposals range from Hobbes’s coercive authority to Talcott
Parsons’s value consensus about shared goals among the members of groups.
social biology, the
understanding of social behavior, especially human social behavior, from a
biological perspective; often connected with the political philosophy of social
Darwinism. social action social biology 853
853 Charles Darwin’s Origin of Species highlighted the significance of
social behavior in organic evolution, and in the Descent of Man, he showed how
significant such behavior is for humans. He argued that it is a product of
natural selection; but it was not until 1964 that the English biologist William
Hamilton showed precisely how such behavior could evolve, namely through “kin
selection” as an aid to the biological wellbeing of close relatives. Since
then, other models of explanation have been proposed, extending the theory to
non-relatives. Best known is the self-describing “reciprocal altruism.” Social
biology became notorious in 1975 when Edward O. Wilson published a major
treatise on the subject: Sociobiology: The New Synthesis. Accusations of sexism
and racism were leveled because Wilson suggested that Western social systems
are biologically innate, and that in some respects males are stronger, more
aggressive, more naturally promiscuous than females. Critics argued that all
social biology is in fact a manifestation of social Darwinism, a
nineteenthcentury philosophy owing more to Herbert Spencer than to Charles
Darwin, supposedly legitimating extreme laissez-faire economics and an
unbridled societal struggle for existence. Such a charge is extremely serious,
for as Moore pointed out in his Principia Ethica 1903, Spencer surely commits
the naturalistic fallacy, inasmuch as he is attempting to derive the way that
the world ought to be from the way that it is. Naturally enough, defenders of
social biology, or “sociobiology” as it is now better known, denied vehemently
that their science is mere right-wing ideology by another name. They pointed to
many who have drawn very different social conclusions on the basis of biology.
Best known is the Russian anarchist Kropotkin, who argued that societies are
properly based on a biological propensity to mutual aid. With respect to
contemporary debate, it is perhaps fairest to say that sociobiology,
particularly that pertaining to humans, did not always show sufficient
sensitivity toward all societal groups
although certainly there was never the crude racism of the fascist
regimes of the 1930s. However, recent work is far more careful in these
respects. Now, indeed, the study of social behavior from a biological
perspective is one of the most exciting and forward-moving branches of the life
sciences. .
social choice theory, the
theory of the rational action of a group of agents. Important social choices
are typically made over alternative means of collectively providing goods.
These might be goods for individual members of the group, or more
characteristically, public goods, goods such that no one can be excluded from
enjoying their benefits once they are available. Perhaps the most central
aspect of social choice theory concerns rational individual choice in a social
context. Since what is rational for one agent to do will often depend on what
is rational for another to do and vice versa, these choices take on a strategic
dimension. The prisoner’s dilemma illustrates how it can be very difficult to
reconcile individual and collectively rational decisions, especially in
non-dynamic contexts. There are many situations, particularly in the provision
of public goods, however, where simple prisoner’s dilemmas can be avoided and
more manageable coordination problems remain. In these cases, individuals may
find it rational to contractually or conventionally bind themselves to courses
of action that lead to the greater good of all even though they are not
straightforwardly utility-maximizing for particular individuals. Establishing
the rationality of these contracts or conventions is one of the leading
problems of social choice theory, because coordination can collapse if a
rational agent first agrees to cooperate and then reneges and becomes a free
rider on the collective efforts of others. Other forms of uncooperative
behaviors such as violating rules established by society or being deceptive
about one’s preferences pose similar difficulties. Hobbes attempted to solve these
problems by proposing that people would agree to submit to the authority of a
sovereign whose punitive powers would make uncooperative behavior an
unattractive option. It has also been argued that cooperation is rational if
the concept of rationality is extended beyond utility-maximizing in the right
way. Other arguments stress benefits beyond selfinterest that accrue to
cooperators. Another major aspect of social choice theory concerns the rational
action of a powerful central authority, or social planner, whose mission is to
optimize the social good. Although the central planner may be instituted by
rational individual choice, this part of the theory simply assumes the
institution. The planner’s task of making a onetime allocation of resources to
the production of various commodities is tractable if social good or social
utility is known as a function of various commodities. When the planner must
take into account dynamical considerations, the technical social choice theory
social choice theory 854 854 problems
are more difficult. This economic growth theory raises important ethical
questions about intergenerational conflict. The assumption of a social analogue
of the individual utility functions is particularly worrisome. It can be shown
formally that taking the results of majority votes can lead to intransitive
social orderings of possible choices and it is, therefore, a generally
unsuitable procedure for the planner to follow. Moreover, under very general
conditions there is no way of aggregating individual preferences into a
consistent social choice function of the kind needed by the planner.
social constructivism,
also called social constructionism, any of a variety of views which claim that
knowledge in some area is the product of our social practices and institutions,
or of the interactions and negotiations between relevant social groups. Mild
versions hold that social factors shape interpretations of the world. Stronger
versions maintain that the world, or some significant portion of it, is somehow
constituted by theories, practices, and institutions. Defenders often move from
mild to stronger versions by insisting that the world is accessible to us only
through our interpretations, and that the idea of an independent reality is at
best an irrelevant abstraction and at worst incoherent. This philosophical
position is distinct from, though distantly related to, a view of the same name
in social and developmental psychology, associated with such figures as Piaget
and Lev Vygotsky, which sees learning as a process in which subjects actively
construct knowledge. Social constructivism has roots in Kant’s idealism, which
claims that we cannot know things in themselves and that knowledge of the world
is possible only by imposing pre-given categories of thought on otherwise
inchoate experience. But where Kant believed that the categories with which we
interpret and thus construct the world are given a priori, contemporary
constructivists believe that the relevant concepts and associated practices
vary from one group or historical period to another. Since there are no
independent standards for evaluating conceptual schemes, social constructivism
leads naturally to relativism. These views are generally thought to be present
in Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, which argues that
observation and methods in science are deeply theory-dependent and that
scientists with fundamentally different assumptions or paradigms effectively
live in different worlds. Kuhn thus offers a view of science in opposition to
both scientific realism which holds that theory-dependent methods can give us
knowledge of a theory-independent world and empiricism which draws a sharp line
between theory and observation. Kuhn was reluctant to accept the apparently
radical consequences of his views, but his work has influenced recent social
studies of science, whose proponents frequently embrace both relativism and
strong constructivism. Another influence is the principle of symmetry advocated
by David Bloor and Barry Barnes, which holds that sociologists should explain
the acceptance of scientific views in the same way whether they believe those
views to be true or to be false. This approach is elaborated in the work of
Harry Collins, Steve Woolgar, and others. Constructivist themes are also
prominent in the work of feminist critics of science such as Sandra Harding and
Donna Haraway, and in the complex views of Bruno Latour. Critics, such as
Richard Boyd and Philip Kitcher, while applauding the detailed case studies
produced by constructivists, claim that the positive arguments for
constructivism are fallacious, that it fails to account satisfactorily for
actual scientific practice, and that like other versions of idealism and
relativism it is only dubiously coherent.
social contract, an
agreement either between the people and their ruler, or among the people in a
community. The idea of a social contract has been used in arguments that differ
in what they aim to justify or explain e.g., the state, conceptions of justice,
morality, what they take the problem of justification to be, and whether or not
they presuppose a moral theory or purport to be a moral theory. Traditionally
the term has been used in arguments that attempt to explain the nature of
political obligation and/or the kind of responsibility that rulers have to
their subjects. Philosophers such as Plato, Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, and Kant
argue that human beings would find life in a prepolitical “state of nature” a
state that some argue is also presocietal so difficult that they would
agree either with one another or with a
social constructivism social contract 855
855 prospective ruler to the
creation of political institutions that each believes would improve his or her
lot. Note that because the argument explains political or social cohesion as
the product of an agreement among individuals, it makes these individuals
conceptually prior to political or social units. Marx and other socialist and
communitarian thinkers have argued against conceptualizing an individual’s relationship
to her political and social community in this way. Have social contracts in
political societies actually taken place? Hume ridicules the idea that they are
real, and questions what value makebelieve agreements can have as explanations
of actual political obligations. Although many social contract theorists admit
that there is almost never an explicit act of agreement in a community,
nonetheless they maintain that such an agreement is implicitly made when
members of the society engage in certain acts through which they give their
tacit consent to the ruling regime. It is controversial what actions constitute
giving tacit consent: Plato and Locke maintain that the acceptance of benefits
is sufficient to give such consent, but some have argued that it is wrong to
feel obliged to those who foist upon us benefits for which we have not asked.
It is also unclear how much of an obligation a person can be under if he gives
only tacit consent to a regime. How are we to understand the terms of a social
contract establishing a state? When the people agree to obey the ruler, do they
surrender their own power to him, as Hobbes tried to argue? Or do they merely
lend him that power, reserving the right to take it from him if and when they
see fit, as Locke maintained? If power is merely on loan to the ruler,
rebellion against him could be condoned if he violates the conditions of that
loan. But if the people’s grant of power is a surrender, there are no such
conditions, and the people could never be justified in taking back that power
via revolution. Despite controversies surrounding their interpretation, social
contract arguments have been important to the development of modern democratic
states: the idea of the government as the creation of the people, which they can
and should judge and which they have the right to overthrow if they find it
wanting, contributed to the development of democratic forms of polity in the
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. American and French revolutionaries
explicitly acknowledged their debts to social contract theorists such as Locke
and Rousseau. In the twentieth century, the social contract idea has been used
as a device for defining various moral conceptions e.g. theories of justice by
those who find its focus on individuals useful in the development of theories
that argue against views e.g. utilitarianism that allow individuals to be
sacrificed for the benefit of the group.
social epistemology, the
study of the social dimensions or determinants of knowledge, or the ways in
which social factors promote or perturb the quest for knowledge. Some writers
use the term ‘knowledge’ loosely, as designating mere belief. On their view
social epistemology should simply describe how social factors influence
beliefs, without concern for the rationality or truth of these beliefs. Many
historians and sociologists of science, e.g., study scientific practices in the
same spirit that anthropologists study native cultures, remaining neutral about
the referential status of scientists’ constructs or the truth-values of their
beliefs. Others try to show that social factors like political or professional
interests are causally operative, and take such findings to debunk any
objectivist pretensions of science. Still other writers retain a normative,
critical dimension in social epistemology, but do not presume that social
practices necessarily undermine objectivity. Even if knowledge is construed as
true or rational belief, social practices might enhance knowledge acquisition.
One social practice is trusting the opinions of authorities, a practice that
can produce truth if the trusted authorities are genuinely authoritative. Such
trust may also be perfectly rational in a complex world, where division of
epistemic labor is required. Even a scientist’s pursuit of extra-epistemic
interests such as professional rewards may not be antithetical to truth in
favorable circumstances. Institutional provisions, e.g., judicial rules of
evidence, provide another example of social factors. Exclusionary rules might
actually serve the cause of truth or accuracy in judgment if the excluded
evidence would tend to mislead or prejudice jurors.
social philosophy,
broadly the philosophy of socisocial Darwinism social philosophy 856 856 ety, including the philosophy of social
science and many of its components, e.g., economics and history, political
philosophy, most of what we now think of as ethics, and philosophy of law. But
we may distinguish two narrower senses. In one, it is the conceptual theory of
society, including the theory of the study of society the common part of all the philosophical
studies mentioned. In the other, it is a normative study, the part of moral
philosophy that concerns social action and individual involvement with society
in general. The central job of social philosophy in the first of these narrower
senses is to articulate the correct notion or concept of society. This would
include formulating a suitable definition of ‘society’; the question is then
which concepts are better for which purposes, and how they are related. Thus we
may distinguish “thin” and “thick” conceptions of society. The former would
identify the least that can be said before we cease talking about society at
all say, a number of people who interact,
whose actions affect the behavior of their fellows. Thicker conceptions would
then add such things as community rules, goals, customs, and ideals. An
important empirical question is whether any interacting groups ever do lack
such things and what if anything is common to the rules, etc., that actual
societies have. Descriptive social philosophy will obviously border on, if not
merge into, social science itself, e.g. into sociology, social psychology, or
economics. And some outlooks in social philosophy will tend to ally with one
social science as more distinctively typical than others e.g., the individualist view looks to
economics, the holist to sociology. A major methodological controversy concerns
holism versus individualism. Holism maintains that at least some social groups
must be studied as units, irreducible to their members: we cannot understand a
society merely by understanding the actions and motivations of its members.
Individualism denies that societies are “organisms,” and holds that we can
understand society only in that way. Classic German sociologists e.g., Weber
distinguished between Gesellschaft, whose paradigm is the voluntary
association, such as a chess club, whose activities are the coordinated actions
of a number of people who intentionally join that group in order to pursue the
purposes that identify it; and Gemeinschaft, whose members find their
identities in that group. Thus, the French are not a group whose members teamed
up with like-minded people to form French society. They were French before they
had separate individual purposes. The holist views society as essentially a
Gemeinschaft. Individualists agree that there are such groupings but deny that
they require a separate kind of irreducibly collective explanation: to
understand the French we must understand how typical French individuals
behave compared, say, with the Germans,
and so on. The methods of Western economics typify the analytical tendencies of
methodological individualism, showing how we can understand large-scale
economic phenomena in terms of the rational actions of particular economic
agents. Cf. Adam Smith’s invisible hand thesis: each economic agent seeks only
his own good, yet the result is the macrophenomenal good of the whole. Another
pervasive issue concerns the role of intentional characterizations and
explanations in these fields. Ordinary people explain behavior by reference to
its purposes, and they formulate these in terms that rely on public rules of
language and doubtless many other rules. To understand society, we must hook
onto the selfunderstanding of the people in that society this view is termed
Verstehen. Recent work in philosophy of science raises the question whether
intentional concepts can really be fundamental in explaining anything, and
whether we must ultimately conceive people as in some sense material systems,
e.g. as computer-like. Major questions for the program of replicating human
intelligence in data-processing terms cf. artificial intelligence are raised by
the symbolic aspects of interaction. Additionally, we should note the emergence
of sociobiology as a potent source of explanations of social phenomena.
Normative social philosophy, in turn, tends inevitably to merge into either
politics or ethics, especially the part of ethics dealing with how people ought
to treat others, especially in large groups, in relation to social institutions
or social structures. This contrasts with ethics in the sense concerned with
how individual people may attain the good life for themselves. All such
theories allot major importance to social relations; but if one’s theory leaves
the individual wide freedom of choice, then a theory of individually chosen
goods will still have a distinctive subject matter. The normative involvements
of social philosophy have paralleled the foregoing in important ways.
Individualists have held that the good of a society must be analyzed in terms
of the goods of its individual members. Of special importance has been the view
that society must respect indisocial philosophy social philosophy 857 857 vidual rights, blocking certain actions
alleged to promote social good as a whole. Organicist philosophers such as
Hegel hold that it is the other way around: the state or nation is higher than
the individual, who is rightly subordinated to it, and individuals have fundamental
duties toward the groups of which they are members. Outrightly fascist versions
of such views are unpopular today, but more benign versions continue in
modified form, notably by communitarians. Socialism and especially communism,
though focused originally on economic aspects of society, have
characteristically been identified with the organicist outlook. Their extreme
opposite is to be found in the libertarians, who hold that the right to
individual liberty is fundamental in society, and that no institutions may
override that right. Libertarians hold that society ought to be treated
strictly as an association, a Gesellschaft, even though they might not deny
that it is ontogenetically Gemeinschaft. They might agree that religious
groups, e.g., cannot be wholly understood as separate individuals.
Nevertheless, the libertarian holds that religious and cultural practices may
not be interfered with or even supported by society. Libertarians are strong
supporters of free-market economic methods, and opponents of any sort of state
intervention into the affairs of individuals. Social Darwinism, advocating the
“survival of the socially fittest,” has sometimes been associated with the
libertarian view. Insofar as there is any kind of standard view on these matters,
it combines elements of both individualism and holism. Typical social
philosophers today accept that society has duties, not voluntary for individual
members, to support education, health, and some degree of welfare for all. But
they also agree that individual rights are to be respected, especially civil
rights, such as freedom of speech and religion. How to combine these two
apparently disparate sets of ideas into a coherent whole is the problem. John
Rawls’s celebrated Theory of Justice, 1971, is a contemporary classic that
attempts to do just that.
Socinianism, an
unorthodox Christian religious movement originating in the sixteenth century
from the work of Italian reformer Laelius Socinus “Sozzini” in Italian; 152562
and his nephew Faustus Socinus 15391603. Born in Siena of a patrician family,
Laelius was widely read in theology. Influenced by the evangelical movement in
Italy, he made contact with noted Protestant reformers, including Calvin and
Melanchthon, some of whom questioned his orthodoxy. In response, he wrote a
confession of faith one of a small number of his writings to have survived.
After Laelius’s death, his work was carried on by his nephew, Faustus, whose
writings including On the Authority of Scripture, 1570; On the Savior Jesus Christ,
1578; and On Predestination, 1578 expressed heterodox views. Faustus believed
that Christ’s nature was entirely human, that souls did not possess immortality
by nature though there would be selective resurrection for believers, that
invocation of Christ in prayer was permissible but not required, and he argued
against predestination. After publication of his 1578 writings, Faustus was
invited to Transylvania and Poland to engage in a dispute within the Reformed
churches there. He decided to make his permanent residence in Poland, which,
through his tireless efforts, became the center of the Socinian movement. The
most important document of this movement was the Racovian Catechism, published
in 1605 shortly after Faustus’s death. The Minor church of Poland, centered at
Racov, became the focal point of the movement. Its academy attracted hundreds
of students and its publishing house produced books in many languages defending
Socinian ideas. Socinianism, as represented by the Racovian Catechism and other
writings collected by Faustus’s Polish disciples, involves the views of Laelius
and especially Faustus Socinus, aligned with the anti-Trinitarian views of the
Polish Minor church founded in 1556. It accepts Christ’s message as the
definitive revelation of God, but regards Christ as human, not divine; rejects
the natural immortality of the soul, but argues for the selective resurrection
of the faithful; rejects the doctrine of the Trinity; emphasizes human free
will against predestinationism; defends pacifism and the separation of church
and state; and argues that reason not
creeds, dogmatic tradition, or church authority
must be the final interpreter of Scripture. Its view of God is
temporalistic: God’s eternity is existence at all times, not timelessness, and
God knows future free actions only when they occur. In these respects, the
Socinian view of God anticipates aspects of modern process theology.
Socinianism was suppressed in Poland in 1658, but it had already spread to
other European social sciences, philosophy of the Socinianism 858 858 countries, including Holland where it
appealed to followers of Arminius and England, where it influenced the
Cambridge Platonists, Locke, and other philosophers, as well as scientists like
Newton. In England, it also influenced and was closely associated with the
development of Unitarianism.
Socrates 469399 B.C., Grecian
philosopher, the exemplar of the examined life, best known for his dictum that
only such a life is worth living. Although he wrote nothing, his thoughts and
way of life had a profound impact on many of his contemporaries, and, through
Plato’s portrayal of him in his early writings, he became a major source of
inspiration and ideas for later generations of philosophers. His daily
occupation was adversarial public conversation with anyone willing to argue
with him. A man of great intellectual brilliance, moral integrity, personal
magnetism, and physical self-command, he challenged the moral complacency of
his fellow citizens, and embarrassed them with their inability to answer such
questions as What is virtue? questions
that he thought we must answer, if we are to know how best to live our lives.
His ideas and personality won him a devoted following among the young, but he
was far from universally admired. Formal charges were made against him for
refusing to recognize the gods of the city, introducing other new divinities,
and corrupting the youth. Tried on a single day before a large jury 500 was a
typical size, he was found guilty by a small margin: had thirty jurors voted
differently, he would have been acquitted. The punishment selected by the jury
was death and was administered by means of poison, probably hemlock. Why was he
brought to trial and convicted? Part of the answer lies in Plato’s Apology, which
purports to be the defense Socrates gave at his trial. Here he says that he has
for many years been falsely portrayed as someone whose scientific theories
dethrone the traditional gods and put natural forces in their place, and as
someone who charges a fee for offering private instruction on how to make a
weak argument seem strong in the courtroom. This is the picture of Socrates
drawn in a play of Aristophanes, the Clouds, first presented in 423. It is
unlikely that Aristophanes intended his play as an accurate depiction of
Socrates, and the unscrupulous buffoon found in the Clouds would never have won
the devotion of so serious a moralist as Plato. Aristophanes drew together the
assorted characteristics of various fifth-century thinkers and named this
amalgam “Socrates” because the real Socrates was one of several controversial
intellectuals of the period. Nonetheless, it is unlikely that the charges
against Socrates or Aristophanes’ caricature were entirely without foundation.
Both Xenophon’s Memorabilia and Plato’s Euthyphro say that Socrates aroused
suspicion because he thought a certain divine sign or voice appeared to him and
gave him useful instruction about how to act. By claiming a unique and private
source of divine inspiration, Socrates may have been thought to challenge the
city’s exclusive control over religious matters. His willingness to disobey the
city is admitted in Plato’s Apology, where he says that he would have to
disobey a hypothetical order to stop asking his philosophical questions, since
he regards them as serving a religious purpose. In the Euthyphro he seeks a
rational basis for making sacrifices and performing other services to the gods;
but he finds none, and implies that no one else has one. Such a challenge to
traditional religious practice could easily have aroused a suspicion of atheism
and lent credibility to the formal charges against him. Furthermore, Socrates
makes statements in Plato’s early dialogues and in Xenophon’s Memorabilia that
could easily have offended the political sensibilities of his contemporaries.
He holds that only those who have given special study to political matters
should make decisions. For politics is a kind of craft, and in all other crafts
only those who have shown their mastery are entrusted with public
responsibilities. Athens was a democracy in which each citizen had an equal
legal right to shape policy, and Socrates’ analogy between the role of an
expert in politics and in other crafts may have been seen as a threat to this
egalitarianism. Doubts about his political allegiance, though not mentioned in
the formal charges against him, could easily have swayed some jurors to vote
against him. Socrates is the subject not only of Plato’s early dialogues but
also of Xenophon’s Memorabilia, Socinus, Faustus Socrates 859 859 and in many respects their portraits are
consistent with each other. But there are also some important differences. In
the Memorabilia, Socrates teaches whatever a gentleman needs to know for civic
purposes. He is filled with platitudinous advice, and is never perplexed by the
questions he raises; e.g., he knows what the virtues are, equating them with
obedience to the law. His views are not threatening or controversial, and
always receive the assent of his interlocutors. By contrast, Plato’s Socrates
presents himself as a perplexed inquirer who knows only that he knows nothing
about moral matters. His interlocutors are sometimes annoyed by his questions
and threatened by their inability to answer them. And he is sometimes led by force
of argument to controversial conclusions. Such a Socrates could easily have
made enemies, whereas Xenophon’s Socrates is sometimes too “good” to be true.
But it is important to bear in mind that it is only the early works of Plato
that should be read as an accurate depiction of the historical Socrates.
Plato’s own theories, as presented in his middle and late dialogues, enter into
philosophical terrain that had not been explored by the historical
Socrates even though in the middle and
some of the late dialogues a figure called Socrates remains the principal
speaker. We are told by Aristotle that Socrates confined himself to ethical
questions, and that he did not postulate a separate realm of imperceptible and
eternal abstract objects called “Forms” or “Ideas.” Although the figure called
Socrates affirms the existence of these objects in such Platonic dialogues as
the Phaedo and the Republic, Aristotle takes this interlocutor to be a vehicle
for Platonic philosophy, and attributes to Socrates only those positions that
we find in Plato’s earlier writing, e.g. in the Apology, Charmides, Crito,
Euthyphro, Hippias Minor, Hippias Major, Ion, Laches, Lysis, and Protagoras.
Socrates focused on moral philosophy almost exclusively; Plato’s attention was
also devoted to the study of metaphysics, epistemology, physical theory,
mathematics, language, and political philosophy. When we distinguish the
philosophies of Socrates and Plato in this way, we find continuities in their
thought for instance, the questions
posed in the early dialogues receive answers in the Republic but there are important differences. For
Socrates, being virtuous is a purely intellectual matter: it simply involves
knowing what is good for human beings; once we master this subject, we will act
as we should. Because he equates virtue with knowledge, Socrates frequently
draws analogies between being virtuous and having mastered any ordinary
subject cooking, building, or geometry,
e.g. For mastery of these subjects does not involve a training of the emotions.
By contrast, Plato affirms the existence of powerful emotional drives that can
deflect us from our own good, if they are not disciplined by reason. He denies
Socrates’ assumption that the emotions will not resist reason, once one comes
to understand where one’s own good lies. Socrates says in Plato’s Apology that
the only knowledge he has is that he knows nothing, but it would be a mistake
to infer that he has no convictions about moral matters convictions arrived at through a difficult
process of reasoning. He holds that the unexamined life is not worth living,
that it is better to be treated unjustly than to do injustice, that
understanding of moral matters is the only unconditional good, that the virtues
are all forms of knowledge and cannot be separated from each other, that death
is not an evil, that a good person cannot be harmed, that the gods possess the
wisdom human beings lack and never act immorally, and so on. He does not accept
these propositions as articles of faith, but is prepared to defend any of them;
for he can show his interlocutors that their beliefs ought to lead them to
accept these conclusions, paradoxical though they may be. Since Socrates can
defend his beliefs and has subjected them to intellectual scrutiny, why does he
present himself as someone who has no knowledge
excepting the knowledge of his own ignorance? The answer lies in his
assumption that it is only a fully accomplished expert in any field who can
claim knowledge or wisdom of that field; someone has knowledge of navigational
matters, e.g., only if he has mastered the art of sailing, can answer all
inquiries about this subject, and can train others to do the same. Judged by
this high epistemic standard, Socrates can hardly claim to be a moral expert,
for he lacks answers to the questions he raises, and cannot teach others to be
virtuous. Though he has examined his moral beliefs and can offer reasons for
them an accomplishment that gives him an
overbearing sense of superiority to his contemporaries he takes himself to be quite distant from the
ideal of moral perfection, which would involve a thorough understanding of all
moral matters. This keen sense of the moral and intellectual deficiency of all
human beings accounts for a great deal of Socrates’ appeal, just as his
arrogant disdain for his fellow citizens no doubt contributed to his demise.
Socrates Socrates 860 860
Socratic intellectualism,
the claim that moral goodness or virtue consists exclusively in a kind of
knowledge, with the implication that if one knows what is good and evil, one
cannot fail to be a good person and to act in a morally upright way. The claim
and the term derive from Socrates; a corollary is another claim of Socrates:
there is no moral weakness or akrasia
all wrong action is due to the agent’s ignorance. Socrates defends this
view in Plato’s dialogue Protagoras. There are two ways to understand Socrates’
view that knowledge of the good is sufficient for right action. 1 All desires
are rational, being focused on what is believed to be good; thus, an agent who
knows what is good will have no desire to act contrary to that knowledge. 2
There are non-rational desires, but knowledge of the good has sufficient
motivational power to overcome them. Socratic intellectualism was abandoned by Plato
and Aristotle, both of whom held that emotional makeup is an essential part of
moral character. However, they retained the Socratic idea that there is a kind
of knowledge or wisdom that ensures right action but this knowledge presupposes antecedent training
and molding of the passions. Socratic intellectualism was later revived and
enjoyed a long life as a key doctrine of the Stoics.
Socratic irony, a form of
indirect communication frequently employed by Socrates in Plato’s early
dialogues, chiefly to praise insincerely the abilities of his interlocutors
while revealing their ignorance; or, to disparage his own abilities, e.g. by
denying that he has knowledge. Interpreters disagree whether Socrates’
self-disparagement is insincere.
Socratic paradoxes, a
collection of theses associated with Socrates that contradict opinions about
moral or practical matters shared by most people. Although there is no
consensus on the precise number of Socratic paradoxes, each of the following
theses has been identified as one. 1 Because no one desires evil things, anyone
who pursues evil things does so involuntarily. 2 Because virtue is knowledge,
anyone who does something morally wrong does so involuntarily. 3 It is better
to be unjustly treated than to do what is unjust. The first two theses are
associated with weakness of will or akrasia. It is sometimes claimed that the
topic of the first thesis is prudential weakness, whereas that of the second is
moral weakness; the reference to “evil things” in 1 is not limited to things
that are morally evil. Naturally, various competing interpretations of these
theses have been offered.
solipsism, the doctrine
that there exists a firstperson perspective possessing privileged and
irreducible characteristics, in virtue of which we stand in various kinds of
isolation from any other persons or external things that may exist. This
doctrine is associated with but distinct from egocentricism. On one variant of
solipsism Thomas Nagel’s we are isolated from other sentient beings because we
can never adequately understand their experience empathic solipsism. Another
variant depends on the thesis that the meanings or referents of all words are
mental entities uniquely accessible only to the language user semantic
solipsism. A restricted variant, due to Wittgenstein, asserts that first-person
ascriptions of psychological states have a meaning fundamentally different from
that of second- or thirdperson ascriptions psychological solipsism. In extreme
forms semantic solipsism can lead to the view that the only things that can be
meaningfully said to exist are ourselves or our mental states ontological
solipsism. Skepticism about the existence of the world external to our minds is
sometimes considered a form of epistemological solipsism, since it asserts that
we stand in epistemological isolation from that world, partly as a result of
the epistemic priority possessed by firstperson access to mental states. In
addition to these substantive versions of solipsism, several variants go under
the rubric methodological solipsism. The idea is that when we seek to explain
why sentient beings behave in certain ways by looking to what they believe,
desire, hope, and fear, we should identify these psychological states only with
events that occur inside the mind or brain, not with external events, since the
former alone are the proximate and sufficient causal explanations of bodily
behavior. Socratic intellectualism solipsism 861 861
Solovyov, Vladimir
18531900, Russian philosopher, theologian, essayist, and poet. In addition to
major treatises and dialogues in speculative philosophy, Solovyov wrote
sensitive literary criticism and influential essays on current social,
political, and ecclesiastical questions. His serious verse is subtle and
delicate; his light verse is rich in comic invention. The mystical image of the
“Divine Sophia,” which Solovyov articulated in theoretical concepts as well as
poetic symbols, powerfully influenced the Russian symbolist poets of the early
twentieth century. His stress on the human role in the “divine-human process”
that creates both cosmic and historical being led to charges of heresy from
Russian Orthodox traditionalists. Solovyov’s rationalistic “justification of
the good” in history, society, and individual life was inspired by Plato,
Spinoza, and especially Hegel. However, at the end of his life Solovyov offered
in Three Conversations on War, Progress, and the End of History, 1900 a
contrasting apocalyptic vision of historical and cosmic disaster, including the
appearance, in the twenty-first century, of the Antichrist. In ethics, social
philosophy, philosophy of history, and theory of culture, Solovyov was both a
vigorous ecumenist and a “good European” who affirmed the intrinsic value of
both the “individual human person” Russian lichnost’ and the “individual nation
or people” narodnost’, but he decisively repudiated the perversions of these
values in egoism and nationalism, respectively. He contrasted the fruits of
English narodnost’ the works of
Shakespeare and Byron, Berkeley and Newton
with the fruits of English nationalism
the repressive and destructive expansion of the British Empire. In
opposing ethnic, national, and religious exclusiveness and self-centeredness,
Solovyov also, and quite consistently, opposed the growing xenophobia and
antiSemitism of his own time. Since 1988 long-suppressed works by and about
Solovyov have been widely republished in Russia, and fresh interpretations of
his philosophy and theology have begun to appear.
sophisma, a sentenca
illustrating a semantic or logical issue associated with the analysis of a
syncategorematic term, or a term lacking independent signification. Typically a
sophisma was used from the thirteenth century into the sixteenth century to
analyze relations holding between logic or semantics and broader philosophical
issues. For example, the syncategorematic term ‘besides’ praeter in ‘Socrates
twice sees every man besides Plato’ is ambiguous, because it could mean ‘On two
occasions Socrates sees every-man-but-Plato’ and also ‘Except for overlooking
Plato once, on two occasions Socrates sees every man’. Roger Bacon used this
sophisma to discuss the ambiguity of distribution, in this case, of the scope
of the reference of ‘twice’ and ‘besides’. Sherwood used the sophisma to
illustrate the applicability of his rule of the distribution of ambiguous
syncategoremata, while Pseudo-Peter of Spain uses it to establish the truth of
the rule, ‘If a proposition is in part false, it can be made true by means of
an exception, but not if it is completely false’. In each case, the philosopher
uses the ambiguous signification of the syncategorematic term to analyze
broader logical problems. The sophisma ‘Every man is of necessity an animal’
has ambiguity through the syncategorematic ‘every’ that leads to broader
philosophical problems. In the 1270s, Boethius of Dacia analyzed this sophisma
in terms of its applicability when no man exists. Is the knowledge derived from
understanding the proposition destroyed when the object known is destroyed?
Does ‘man’ signify anything when there are no men? If we can correctly
predicate a genus of a species, is the nature of the genus in that species
something other than, or distinct from, what finally differentiates the
species? In this case, the sophisma proves a useful approach to addressing
metaphysical and epistemological problems central to Scholastic discourse.
Sophists, any of a number
of ancient Grecians, roughly contemporaneous with Socrates, who professed to
teach, for a fee, rhetoric, philosophy, and how to succeed in life. They
typically were itinerants, visiting much of the Grecian world, and gave public
exhibitions at Olympia and Delphi. They were part of the general expansion of Grecian
learning and of the changing culture in which the previous informal educational
methods were inadequate. For example, the growing litigiousness of Athenian
society demanded Solovyov, Vladimir Sophists 862 862 instruction in the art of speaking well,
which the Sophists helped fulfill. The Sophists have been portrayed as
intellectual charlatans hence the pejorative use of ‘sophism’, teaching their
sophistical reasoning for money, and at the other extreme as Victorian
moralists and educators. The truth is more complex. They were not a school, and
shared no body of opinions. They were typically concerned with ethics unlike
many earlier philosophers, who emphasized physical inquiries and about the
relationship between laws and customs nomos and nature phusis. Protagoras of
Abdera c.490c.420 B.C. was the most famous and perhaps the first Sophist. He
visited Athens frequently, and became a friend of its leader, Pericles; he
therefore was invited to draw up a legal code for the colony of Thurii 444.
According to some late reports, he died in a shipwreck as he was leaving
Athens, having been tried for and found guilty of impiety. He claimed that he
knew nothing about the gods, because of human limitations and the difficulty of
the question. We have only a few short quotations from his works. His “Truth”
also known as the “Throws,” i.e., how to overthrow an opponent’s arguments
begins with his most famous claim: “Humans are the measure of all things of things that are, that they are, of things
that are not, that they are not.” That is, there is no objective truth; the world
is for each person as it appears to that person. Of what use, then, are skills?
Skilled people can change others’ perceptions in useful ways. For example, a
doctor can change a sick person’s perceptions so that she is healthy.
Protagoras taught his students to “make the weaker argument the stronger,”
i.e., to alter people’s perceptions about the value of arguments. Aristophanes
satirizes Protagoras as one who would make unjust arguments defeat just
arguments. This is true for ethical judgments, too: laws and customs are simply
products of human agreement. But because laws and customs result from
experiences of what is most useful, they should be followed rather than nature.
No perception or judgment is more true than another, but some are more useful,
and those that are more useful should be followed. Gorgias c.483376 was a
student of Empedocles. His town, Leontini in Sicily, sent him as an ambassador
to Athens in 427; his visit was a great success, and the Athenians were amazed
at his rhetorical ability. Like other Sophists, he charged for instruction and
gave speeches at religious festivals. Gorgias denied that he taught virtue;
instead, he produced clever speakers. He insisted that different people have
different virtues: for example, women’s virtue differs from men’s. Since there
is no truth and if there were we couldn’t know it, we must rely on opinion, and
so speakers who can change people’s opinions have great power greater than the power produced by any other skill.
In his “Encomium on Helen” he argues that if she left Menelaus and went with
Paris because she was convinced by speech, she wasn’t responsible for her
actions. Two paraphrases of Gorgias’s “About What Doesn’t Exist” survive; in
this he argues that nothing exists, that even if something did, we couldn’t
know it, and that even if we could know anything we couldn’t explain it to
anyone. We can’t know anything, because some things we think of do not exist,
and so we have no way of judging whether the things we think of exist. And we
can’t express any knowledge we may have, because no two people can think of the
same thing, since the same thing can’t be in two places, and because we use
words in speech, not colors or shapes or objects. This may be merely a parody
of Parmenides’ argument that only one thing exists. Antiphon the Sophist fifth
century is probably although not certainly to be distinguished from Antiphon
the orator d. 411, some of whose speeches we possess. We know nothing about his
life if he is distinct from the orator. In addition to brief quotations in
later authors, we have two papyrus fragments of his “On Truth.” In these he
argues that we should follow laws and customs only if there are witnesses and
so our action will affect our reputation; otherwise, we should follow nature, which
is often inconsistent with following custom. Custom is established by human
agreement, and so disobeying it is detrimental only if others know it is
disobeyed, whereas nature’s demands unlike those of custom can’t be ignored
with impunity. Antiphon assumes that rational actions are selfinterested, and
that justice demands actions contrary to self-interest a position Plato attacks in the Republic.
Antiphon was also a materialist: the nature of a bed is wood, since if a buried
bed could grow it would grow wood, not a bed. His view is one of Aristotle’s
main concerns in the Physics, since Aristotle admits in the Categories that
persistence through change is the best test for substance, but won’t admit that
matter is substance. Hippias fifth century was from Elis, in the Peloponnesus,
which used him as an ambasSophists Sophists 863 863 sador. He competed at the festival of
Olympus with both prepared and extemporaneous speeches. He had a phenomenal
memory. Since Plato repeatedly makes fun of him in the two dialogues that bear
his name, he probably was selfimportant and serious. He was a polymath who
claimed he could do anything, including making speeches and clothes; he wrote a
work collecting what he regarded as the best things said by others. According to
one report, he made a mathematical discovery the quadratrix, the first curve
other than the circle known to the Grecians. In the Protagoras, Plato has
Hippias contrast nature and custom, which often does violence to nature.
Prodicus fifth century was from Ceos, in the Cyclades, which frequently
employed him on diplomatic missions. He apparently demanded high fees, but had
two versions of his lecture one cost
fifty drachmas, the other one drachma. Socrates jokes that if he could have
afforded the fifty-drachma lecture, he would have learned the truth about the
correctness of words, and Aristotle says that when Prodicus added something
exciting to keep his audience’s attention he called it “slipping in the
fifty-drachma lecture for them.” We have at least the content of one lecture of
his, the “Choice of Heracles,” which consists of banal moralizing. Prodicus was
praised by Socrates for his emphasis on the right use of words and on
distinguishing between synonyms. He also had a naturalistic view of the origin
of theology: useful things were regarded as gods.
Sorel, Georges 18471922,
French socialist activist and philosopher best known for his Reflections on
Violence 1906, which develops the notion of revolutionary syndicalism as seen
through proletarian violence and the interpretation of myth. An early proponent
of the quasiMarxist position of gradual democratic reformism, Sorel eventually
developed a highly subjective interpretation of historical materialism that,
while retaining a conception of proletarian revolution, now understood it
through myth rather than reason. He was in large part reacting to the
empiricism of the French Enlightenment and the statistical structuring of
sociological studies. In contrast to Marx and Engels, who held that revolution
would occur when the proletariat attained its own class consciousness through
an understanding of its true relationship to the means of production in
capitalist society, Sorel introduced myth rather than reason as the correct way
to interpret social totality. Myth allows for the necessary reaction to
bourgeois rationalism and permits the social theorist to negate the status quo
through the authenticity of revolutionary violence. By acknowledging the
irrationality of the status quo, myth permits the possibility of social
understanding and its necessary reaction, human emancipation through
proletarian revolution. Marxism is myth because it juxtaposes the
irreducibility of capitalist organization to its negation violent proletarian revolution. The
intermediary stage in this development is radical syndicalism, which organizes
workers into groups opposed to bourgeois authority, instills the myth of
proletarian revolution in the workers, and allows them in postrevolutionary
times to work toward a social arrangement of worker and peasant governance and
collaboration. The vehicle through which all this is accomplished is the
general strike, whose aim, through the justified violence of its ends, is to
facilitate the downfall and ultimate elimination of the bourgeoisie. In doing
so the proletariat will lead society to a classless and harmonious stage in
history. By stressing the notion of spontaneity Sorel thought he had solved the
vexing problems of party and future bureaucracy found in much of the
revolutionary literature of his day. In his later years he was interested in
the writings of both Lenin and Mussolini.
sorites, an argument
consisting of categorical propositions that can be represented as or decomposed
into a sequence of categorical syllogisms such that the conclusion of each
syllogism except the last one in the sequence is a premise of the next
syllogism in the sequence. An example is ‘All cats are felines; all felines are
mammals; all mammals are warm-blooded animals; therefore, all cats are
warm-blooded animals’. This sorites may be viewed as composed of the two
syllogisms ‘All cats are felines; all felines are mammals; therefore, all cats
are mammals’ and ‘All cats are mammals; all mammals are warm-blooded animals;
therefore, all cats are warm-blooded animals’. A sorites is valid if and only
if each categorical syllogism into which it decomposes is valid. In the
example, the sorites decomposes into two syllogisms in the mood Barbara; since
any syllogism in Barbara is valid, the sorites is valid.
sorites paradox from Grecian
soros, ‘heap’, any of a number of paradoxes about heaps and their Sorel,
Georges sorites paradox 864 864
elements, and more broadly about gradations. A single grain of sand cannot be
arranged so as to form a heap. Moreover, it seems that given a number of grains
insufficient to form a heap, adding just one more grain still does not make a
heap. If a heap cannot be formed with one grain, it cannot be formed with two;
if a heap cannot be formed with two, it cannot be formed with three; and so on.
But this seems to lead to the absurdity that however large the number of
grains, it is not large enough to form a heap. A similar paradox can be
developed in the opposite direction. A million grains of sand can certainly be
arranged so as to form a heap, and it is always possible to remove a grain from
a heap in such a way that what is left is also a heap. This seems to lead to
the absurdity that a heap can be formed even from just a single grain. These
paradoxes about heaps were known in antiquity they are associated with
Eubulides of Miletus, fourth century B.C., and have since given their name to a
number of similar paradoxes. The loss of a single hair does not make a man
bald, and a man with a million hairs is certainly not bald. This seems to lead
to the absurd conclusion that even a man with no hairs at all is not bald. Or
consider a long painted wall hundreds of yards or hundreds of miles long. The
left-hand region is clearly painted red, but there is a subtle gradation of
shades and the right-hand region is clearly yellow. A small double window
exposes a small section of the wall at any one time. It is moved progressively
rightward, in such a way that at each move after the initial position the
left-hand segment of the window exposes just the area that was in the previous
position exposed by the right-hand segment. The window is so small relative to
the wall that in no position can you tell any difference in color between the
exposed areas. When the window is at the extreme left, both exposed areas are
certainly red. But as the window moves to the right, the area in the right
segment looks just the same color as the area in the left, which you have
already pronounced to be red. So it seems that one must call it red too. But
then one is led to the absurdity of calling a clearly yellow area red. As some
of these cases suggest, there is a connection with dynamic processes. A tadpole
turns gradually into a frog. Yet if you analyze a motion picture of the
process, it seems that there are no two adjacent frames of which you can say
the earlier shows a tadpole, the later a frog. So it seems that you could
argue: if something is a tadpole at a given moment, it must also be a tadpole
and not a frog a millionth of a second later, and this seems to lead to the
absurd conclusion that a tadpole can never turn into a frog. Most responses to
this paradox attempt to deny the “major premise,” the one corresponding to the
claim that if you cannot make a heap with n grains of sand then you cannot make
a heap with n ! 1. The difficulty is that the negation of this premise is
equivalent, in classical logic, to the proposition that there is a sharp
cutoff: that, e.g., there is some number n of grains that are not enough to
make a heap, where n ! 1 are enough to make a heap. The claim of a sharp cutoff
may not be so very implausible for heaps perhaps for things like grains of
sand, four is the smallest number which can be formed into a heap but is very
implausible for colors and tadpoles. There are two main kinds of response to
sorites paradoxes. One is to accept that there is in every such case a sharp
cutoff, though typically we do not, and perhaps cannot, know where it is.
Another kind of response is to evolve a non-classical logic within which one
can refuse to accept the major premise without being committed to a sharp
cutoff. At present, no such non-classical logic is entirely free of
difficulties. So sorites paradoxes are still taken very seriously by
contemporary philosophers.
sortal predicate,
roughly, a predicate whose application to an object says what kind of object it
is and implies conditions for objects of that kind to be identical. Person,
green apple, regular hexagon, and pile of coal would generally be regarded as
sortal predicates, whereas tall, green thing, and coal would generally be
regarded as non-sortal predicates. An explicit and precise definition of the
distinction is hard to come by. Sortal predicates are sometimes said to be
distinguished by the fact that they provide a criterion of counting or that
they do not apply to the parts of the objects to which they apply, but there
are difficulties with each of these characterizations. The notion figures in
recent philosophical discussions on various topics. Robert Ackermann and others
have suggested that any scientific law confirmable by observation might require
the use of sortal predicates. Thus ‘all non-black things are non-ravens’, while
logically equivalent to the putative scientific law ‘all ravens are black’, is
not itself confirmable by observation because ‘non-black’ is not a sortal
predicate. David Wiggins and others have discussed the sortal sortal predicate
865 865 idea that all identity claims
are sortal-relative in the sense that an appropriate response to the claim a %
b is always “the same what as b?” John Wallace has argued that there would be
advantages in relativizing the quantifiers of predicate logic to sortals. ‘All
humans are mortal’ would be rendered Ex[m]Dx, rather than ExMxPDx. Crispin
Wright has suggested that the view that natural number is a sortal concept is
central to Frege’s or any other number-theoretic platonism. The word ‘sortal’
as a technical term in philosophy apparently first occurs in Locke’s Essay
Concerning Human Understanding. Locke argues that the so-called essence of a
genus or sort unlike the real essence of a thing is merely the abstract idea
that the general or sortal name stands for. But ‘sortal’ has only one
occurrence in Locke’s Essay. Its currency in contemporary philosophical idiom
probably should be credited to P. F. Strawson’s Individuals. The general idea
may be traced at least to the notion of second substance in Aristotle’s
Categories.
Soto, Domingo de
14941560, Spanish Dominican theologian and philosopher. Born in Segovia, he
studied in Alcalá de Henares and Paris, taught at Segovia and Salamanca, and
was named official representative of the Holy Roman Empire at the Council of
Trent by Charles V. Among Soto’s many works, his commentaries on Aristotle’s
Physics and On the Soul stand out. He also wrote a book on the nature of grace
and an important treatise on law. Soto was one of the early members of the
school of Spanish Thomism, but he did not always follow Aquinas. He rejected
the doctrine of the real distinction between essence and existence and adopted
Duns Scotus’s position that the primary object of human understanding is
indeterminate being in general. Apart from metaphysics and theology, Soto’s
philosophy of law and political theory are historically important. He
maintained, contrary to his teacher Vitoria, that law originates in the
understanding rather than in the will of the legislator. He also distinguished
natural from positive law: the latter arises from the decision of legislators,
whereas the former is based on nature. Soto was a founder of the general theory
of international law.
soul, also called spirit,
an entity supposed to be present only in living things, corresponding to the Grecian
psyche and Latin anima. Since there seems to be no material difference between
an organism in the last moments of its life and the organism’s newly dead body,
many philosophers since the time of Plato have claimed that the soul is an
immaterial component of an organism. Because only material things are observed
to be subject to dissolution, Plato took the soul’s immateriality as grounds
for its immortality. Neither Plato nor Aristotle thought that only persons had
souls: Aristotle ascribed souls to animals and plants since they all exhibited
some living functions. Unlike Plato, Aristotle denied the transmigration of
souls from one species to another or from one body to another after death; he
was also more skeptical about the soul’s capacity for disembodiment roughly, survival and functioning without a
body. Descartes argued that only persons had souls and that the soul’s
immaterial nature made freedom possible even if the human body is subject to
deterministic physical laws. As the subject of thought, memory, emotion,
desire, and action, the soul has been supposed to be an entity that makes
self-consciousness possible, that differentiates simultaneous experiences into
experiences either of the same person or of different persons, and that
accounts for personal identity or a person’s continued identity through time.
Dualists argue that soul and body must be distinct in order to explain
consciousness and the possibility of immortality. Materialists argue that
consciousness is entirely the result of complex physical processes.
soundness, 1 of an
argument the property of being valid and having all true premises; 2 of a logic
the property of being not too strong in a certain respect. A logic L has weak
soundness provided every theorem of L is valid. And L has strong soundness if
for every set G of sentences, every sentence deducible from G using L is a logical
consequence of G.
space, an extended
manifold of several dimensions, where the number of dimensions corresponds to
the number of variable magnitudes Soto, Domingo de space 866 866 needed to specify a location in the
manifold; in particular, the three-dimensional manifold in which physical
objects are situated and with respect to which their mutual positions and
distances are defined. Ancient Grecian atomism defined space as the infinite
void in which atoms move; but whether space is finite or infinite, and whether
void spaces exist, have remained in question. Aristotle described the universe
as a finite plenum and reduced space to the aggregate of all places of physical
things. His view was preeminent until Renaissance Neoplatonism, the Copernican
revolution, and the revival of atomism reintroduced infinite, homogeneous space
as a fundamental cosmological assumption. Further controversy concerned whether
the space assumed by early modern astronomy should be thought of as an
independently existing thing or as an abstraction from the spatial relations of
physical bodies. Interest in the relativity of motion encouraged the latter
view, but Newton pointed out that mechanics presupposes absolute distinctions
among motions, and he concluded that absolute space must be postulated along
with the basic laws of motion Principia, 1687. Leibniz argued for the
relational view from the identity of indiscernibles: the parts of space are
indistinguishable from one another and therefore cannot be independently
existing things. Relativistic physics has defused the original controversy by
revealing both space and spatial relations as merely observer-dependent
manifestations of the structure of spacetime. Meanwhile, Kant shifted the
metaphysical controversy to epistemological grounds by claiming that space,
with its Euclidean structure, is neither a “thing-in-itself” nor a relation of
thingsin-themselves, but the a priori form of outer intuition. His view was
challenged by the elaboration of non-Euclidean geometries in the nineteenth
century, by Helmholtz’s arguments that both intuitive and physical space are
known through empirical investigation, and finally by the use of non-Euclidean
geometry in the theory of relativity. Precisely what geometrical
presuppositions are inherent in human spatial perception, and what must be
learned from experience, remain subjects of psychological investigation.
space-time, a
four-dimensional continuum combining the three dimensions of space with time in
order to represent motion geometrically. Each point is the location of an
event, all of which together represent “the world” through time; paths in the
continuum worldlines represent the dynamical histories of moving particles, so
that straight worldlines correspond to uniform motions; three-dimensional
sections of constant time value “spacelike hypersurfaces” or “simultaneity
slices” represent all of space at a given time. The idea was foreshadowed when
Kant represented “the phenomenal world” as a plane defined by space and time as
perpendicular axes Inaugural Dissertation, 1770, and when Joseph Louis Lagrange
17361814 referred to mechanics as “the analytic geometry of four dimensions.”
But classical mechanics assumes a universal standard of simultaneity, and so it
can treat space and time separately. The concept of space-time was explicitly
developed only when Einstein criticized absolute simultaneity and made the
velocity of light a universal constant. The mathematician Hermann Minkowski
showed in 1908 that the observer-independent structure of special relativity
could be represented by a metric space of four dimensions: observers in
relative motion would disagree on intervals of length and time, but agree on a
fourdimensional interval combining spatial and temporal measurements.
Minkowski’s model then made possible the general theory of relativity, which
describes gravity as a curvature of spacetime in the presence of mass and the
paths of falling bodies as the straightest worldlines in curved
space-time.
spatiotemporal
continuity, a property of the careers, or space-time paths, of well-behaved
objects. Let a space-time path be a series of possible spatiotemporal
positions, each represented in a selected coordinate system by an ordered pair
consisting of a time its temporal component and a volume of space its spatial
component. Such a path will be spatiotemporally continuous provided it is such
that, relative to any inertial frame selected as coordinate system, space,
absolute spatiotemporal continuity 867
867 1 for every segment of the series, the temporal components of the members
of that segment form a continuous temporal interval; and 2 for any two members
‹ti, Vi and ‹tj, Vj of the series that differ in their temporal components ti
and tj, if Vi and Vj the spatial components differ in either shape, size, or
location, then between these members of the series there will be a member whose
spatial component is more similar to Vi and Vj in these respects than these are
to each other. This notion is of philosophical interest partly because of its
connections with the notions of identity over time and causality. Putting aside
such qualifications as quantum considerations may require, material objects at
least macroscopic objects of familiar kinds apparently cannot undergo
discontinuous change of place, and cannot have temporal gaps in their
histories, and therefore the path through space-time traced by such an object
must apparently be spatiotemporally continuous. More controversial is the claim
that spatiotemporal continuity, together with some continuity with respect to
other properties, is sufficient as well as necessary for the identity of such
objects e.g., that if a spatiotemporally
continuous path is such that the spatial component of each member of the series
is occupied by a table of a certain description at the time that is the
temporal component of that member, then there is a single table of that
description that traces that path. Those who deny this claim sometimes maintain
that it is further required for the identity of material objects that there be
causal and counterfactual dependence of later states on earlier ones ceteris
paribus, if the table had been different yesterday, it would be correspondingly
different now. Since it appears that chains of causality must trace
spatiotemporally continuous paths, it may be that insofar as spatiotemporal
continuity is required for transtemporal identity, this is because it is
required for transtemporal causality.
specious present, the
supposed time between past and future. The term was first offered by E. R. Clay
in The Alternative: A Study in Psychology 1882, and was cited by James in
Chapter XV of his Principles of Psychology 1890. Clay challenges the assumption
that the “present” as a “datum” is given as “present” to us in our experience.
“The present to which the datum refers is really a part of the past a recent past
delusively given as benign time that intervenes between the past and the
future. Let it be named the specious present, and let the past that is given as
being the past be known as the obvious past.” For James, this position is
supportive of his contention that consciousness is a stream and can be divided
into parts only by conceptual addition, i.e., only by our ascribing past,
present, and future to what is, in our actual experience, a seamless flow.
James holds that the “practically cognized present is no knife-edge but a
saddleback,” a sort of “ducatum” which we experience as a whole, and only upon
reflective attention do we “distinguish its beginning from its end.” Whereas
Clay refers to the datum of the present as “delusive,” one might rather say
that it is perpetually elusive, for as we have our experience, now, it is
always bathed retrospectively and prospectively. Contrary to common wisdom, no
single experience ever is had by our consciousness utterly alone, single and
without relations, fore and aft.
speculative philosophy, a
form of theorizing that goes beyond verifiable observation; specifically, a
philosophical approach informed by the impulse to construct a grand narrative
of a worldview that encompasses the whole of reality. Speculative philosophy
purports to bind together reflections on the existence and nature of the
cosmos, the psyche, and God. It sets for its goal a unifying matrix and an
overarching system wherespeaker’s meaning speculative philosophy 868 868 with to comprehend the considered
judgments of cosmology, psychology, and theology. Hegel’s absolute idealism,
particularly as developed in his later thought, paradigmatically illustrates
the requirements for speculative philosophizing. His system of idealism offered
a vision of the unity of the categories of human thought as they come to
realization in and through their opposition to each other. Speculative thought
tends to place a premium on universality, totality, and unity; and it tends to
marginalize the concrete particularities of the natural and social world. In
its aggressive use of the systematic principle, geared to a unification of
human experience, speculative philosophy aspires to a comprehensive
understanding and explanation of the structural interrelations of the culture
spheres of science, morality, art, and religion.
speech act theory, the
theory of language use, sometimes called pragmatics, as opposed to the theory
of meaning, or semantics. Based on the meaninguse distinction, it categorizes
systematically the sorts of things that can be done with words and explicates
the ways these are determined, underdetermined, or undetermined by the meanings
of the words used. Relying further on the distinction between speaker meaning
and linguistic meaning, it aims to characterize the nature of communicative
intentions and how they are expressed and recognized. Speech acts are a species
of intentional action. In general, one and the same utterance may comprise a
number of distinct though related acts, each corresponding to a different
intention on the part of the speaker. Beyond intending to produce a certain
sequence of sounds forming a sentence in English, a person who utters the
sentence ‘The door is open’, e.g., is likely to be intending to perform, in the
terminology of J. L. Austin How to Do Things with Words, 1962, 1 the locutionary
act of saying expressing the proposition that a certain door is open, 2 the
illocutionary act of making the statement expressing the belief that it is
open, and 3 the perlocutionary act of getting his listener to believe that it
is open. In so doing, he may be performing the indirect speech act of
requesting illocutionary the listener to close the door and of getting
perlocutionary the hearer to close the door. The primary focus of speech act
theory is on illocutionary acts, which may be classified in a variety of ways.
Statements, predictions, and answers exemplify constatives; requests, commands
and permissions are directives; promises, offers, and bets are commissives;
greetings, apologies, and congratulations are acknowledgments. These are all
communicative illocutionary acts, each distinguished by the type of
psychological state expressed by the speaker. Successful communication consists
in the audience’s recognition of the speaker’s intention to be expressing a
certain psychological state with a certain content. Conventional illocutionary
acts, on the other hand, effect or officially affect institutional states of
affairs. Examples of the former are appointing, resigning, sentencing, and
adjourning; examples of the latter are assessing, acquitting, certifying, and
grading. See Kent Bach and Robert M. Harnish, Linguistic Communication and
Speech Acts, 1979. The type of act an utterance exemplifies determines its
illocutionary force. In the example ‘The door is open’, the utterance has the
force of both a statement and a request. The illocutionary force potential of a
sentence is the force or forces with which it can be used literally, e.g., in
the case of the sentence ‘The door is open’, as a statement but not as a
request. The felicity conditions on an illocutionary act pertain not only to
its communicative or institutional success but also to its sincerity,
appropriateness, and effectiveness. An explicit performative utterance is an
illocutionary act performed by uttering an indicative sentence in the simple
present tense with a verb naming the type of act being performed, e.g., ‘I
apologize for everything I did’ and ‘You are requested not to smoke’. The
adverb ‘hereby’ may be used before the performative verb ‘apologize’ and
‘request’ in these examples to indicate that the very utterance being made is
the vehicle of the performance of the illocutionary act in question. A good
test for distinguishing illocutionary from perlocutionary acts is to determine
whether a verb naming the act can be used performatively. Austin exploited the
phenomenon of performative utterances to expose the common philosophical error
of assuming that the primary use of language is to make statements.
Spencer, Herbert
18201903, English philosopher, social reformer, and editor of The Economist. In
epistemology, Spencer adopted the ninespeculative reason Spencer, Herbert
869 869 teenth-century trend toward
positivism: the only reliable knowledge of the universe is to be found in the
sciences. His ethics were utilitarian, following Bentham and J. S. Mill:
pleasure and pain are the criteria of value as signs of happiness or
unhappiness in the individual. His Synthetic Philosophy, expounded in books
written over many years, assumed both in biology and psychology the existence
of Lamarckian evolution: given a characteristic environment, every animal
possesses a disposition to make itself into what it will, failing maladaptive
interventions, eventually become. The dispositions gain expression as inherited
acquired habits. Spencer could not accept that species originate by chance
variations and natural selection alone: direct adaptation to environmental
constraints is mainly responsible for biological changes. Evolution also
includes the progression of societies in the direction of a dynamical
equilibrium of individuals: the human condition is perfectible because human
faculties are completely adapted to life in society, implying that evil and
immorality will eventually disappear. His ideas on evolution predated
publication of the major works of Darwin; A. R. Wallace was influenced by his
writings.
Spinoza, Baruch 163277,
Dutch metaphysician, epistemologist, psychologist, moral philosopher, political
theorist, and philosopher of religion, generally regarded as one of the most
important figures of seventeenth-century rationalism. Life and works. Born and
educated in the Jewish community of Amsterdam, he forsook his given name
‘Baruch’ in favor of the Latin ‘Benedict’ at the age of twenty-two. Between
1652 and 1656 he studied the philosophy of Descartes in the school of Francis
van den Enden. Having developed unorthodox views of the divine nature and
having ceased to be fully observant of Jewish practice, he was excommunicated
by the Jewish community in 1656. He spent his entire life in Holland; after
leaving Amsterdam in 1660, he resided successively in Rijnsburg, Voorburg, and
the Hague. He supported himself at least partly through grinding lenses, and
his knowledge of optics involved him in an area of inquiry of great importance
to seventeenth-century science. Acquainted with such leading intellectual
figures as Leibniz, Huygens, and Henry Oldenberg, he declined a professorship
at the of Heidelberg partly on the
grounds that it might interfere with his intellectual freedom. His premature
death at the age of fortyfour was due to consumption. The only work published
under Spinoza’s name during his lifetime was his Principles of Descartes’s
Philosophy Renati Des Cartes Principiorum Philosophiae, Pars I et II, 1663, an
attempt to recast and present Parts I and II of Descartes’s Principles of
Philosophy in the manner that Spinoza called geometrical order or geometrical
method. Modeled on the Elements of Euclid and on what Descartes called the
method of synthesis, Spinoza’s “geometrical order” involves an initial set of
definitions and axioms, from which various propositions are demonstrated, with
notes or scholia attached where necessary. This work, which established his
credentials as an expositor of Cartesian philosophy, had its origins in his
endeavor to teach Descartes’s Principles of Philosophy to a private student.
Spinoza’s TheologicalPolitical Treatise Tractatus Theologico-Politicus was
published anonymously in 1670. After his death, his close circle of friends
published his Posthumous Works Opera Postuma, 1677, which included his
masterpieces, Ethic, Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Ethica, Ordine
Geometrico Demonstrata. The Posthumous Works also included his early unfinished
Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect Tractatus de Intellectus
Emendatione, his later unfinished Political Treatise Tractatus Politicus, a
Hebrew Grammar, and Correspondence. An unpublished early work entitled Short
Treatise on God, Man, and His Well-Being Korte Vorhandelung van God, de Mensch
en deszelvs Welstand, in many ways a forerunner of the Ethics, was rediscovered
in copied manuscript and published in the nineteenth century. Spinoza’s
authorship of two brief scientific treatises, On the Rainbow and On the
Calculation of Chances, is still disputed. Metaphysics. Spinoza often uses the
term ‘God, or Nature’ “Deus, sive Natura“, and this identification of God with
Nature is at the heart of his metaphysics. Because of this identification, his philosophy
is often regarded as a version of pantheism and/or naturalism. But although
philosophy begins with metaphysics for Spinoza, his metaphysics is ultimately
in the service of his ethics. Because his naturalized God has no desires or
purposes, human ethics cannot properly be derived from divine command. Rather,
Spinozistic ethics seeks to demonstrate, from an adequate understanding of the
divine nature and its expression in human nature, the way in which human beings
can maximize their advantage. Central to the successful pursuit of this
Speusippus Spinoza, Baruch 870 870
advantage is adequate knowledge, which leads to increasing control of the
passions and to cooperative action. Spinoza’s ontology, like that of Descartes,
consists of substances, their attributes which Descartes called principal
attributes, and their modes. In the Ethics, Spinoza defines ‘substance’ as what
is “in itself, and is conceived through itself”; ‘attribute’ as that which “the
intellect perceives of a substance as constituting its essence”; and ‘mode’ as
“the affections of a substance, or that which is in another through which also
it is conceived.” While Descartes had recognized a strict sense in which only
God is a substance, he also recognized a second sense in which there are two
kinds of created substances, each with its own principal attribute: extended
substances, whose only principal attribute is extension; and minds, whose only
principal attribute is thought. Spinoza, in contrast, consistently maintains
that there is only one substance. His metaphysics is thus a form of substantial
monism. This one substance is God, which Spinoza defines as “a being absolutely
infinite, i.e., a substance consisting of an infinity of attributes, of which
each expresses an eternal and infinite essence.” Thus, whereas Descartes
limited each created substance to one principal attribute, Spinoza claims that
the one substance has infinite attributes, each expressing the divine nature
without limitation in its own way. Of these infinite attributes, however,
humans can comprehend only two: extension and thought. Within each attribute,
the modes of God are of two kinds: infinite modes, which are pervasive features
of each attribute, such as the laws of nature; and finite modes, which are
local and limited modifications of substance. There is an infinite sequence of
finite modes. Descartes regarded a human being as a substantial union of two
different substances, the thinking soul and the extended body, in causal
interaction with each other. Spinoza, in contrast, regards a human being as a
finite mode of God, existing simultaneously in God as a mode of thought and as
a mode of extension. He holds that every mode of extension is literally
identical with the mode of thought that is the “idea of” that mode of
extension. Since the human mind is the idea of the human body, it follows that
the human mind and the human body are literally the same thing, conceived under
two different attributes. Because they are actually identical, there is no
causal interaction between the mind and the body; but there is a complete
parallelism between what occurs in the mind and what occurs in the body. Since
every mode of extension has a corresponding and identical mode of thought
however rudimentary that might be, Spinoza allows that every mode of extension
is “animated to some degree”; his view is thus a form of panpsychism. Another
central feature of Spinoza’s metaphysics is his necessitarianism, expressed in
his claim that “things could have been produced . . . in no other way, and in
no other order” than that in which they have been produced. He derives this
necessitarianism from his doctrine that God exists necessarily for which he
offers several arguments, including a version of the ontological argument and
his doctrine that everything that can follow from the divine nature must
necessarily do so. Thus, although he does not use the term, he accepts a very
strong version of the principle of sufficient reason. At the outset of the
Ethics, he defines a thing as free when its actions are determined by its own
nature alone. Only God whose actions are
determined entirely by the necessity of his own nature, and for whom nothing is
external is completely free in this
sense. Nevertheless, human beings can achieve a relative freedom to the extent
that they live the kind of life described in the later parts of the Ethics.
Hence, Spinoza is a compatibilist concerning the relation between freedom and
determinism. “Freedom of the will” in any sense that implies a lack of causal
determination, however, is simply an illusion based on ignorance of the true
causes of a being’s actions. The recognition that all occurrences are causally
determined, Spinoza holds, has a positive consolatory power that aids one in
controlling the passions. Epistemology and psychology. Like other rationalists,
Spinoza distinguishes two representational faculties: the imagination and the
intellect. The imagination is a faculty of forming imagistic representations of
things, derived ultimately from the mechanisms of the senses; the intellect is
a faculty of forming adequate, nonimagistic conceptions of things. He also
distinguishes three “kinds of knowledge.” The first or lowest kind he calls
opinion or imagination opinio, imaginatio. It includes “random or indeterminate
experience” experientia vaga and also “hearsay, or knowledge from mere signs”;
it thus depends on the confused and mutilated deliverances of the senses, and
is inadequate. The second kind of knowledge he calls reason ratio; it depends
on common notions i.e., features of things that are “common to all, and equally
in the part and in the whole” or on adequate knowledge of the properties as
opposed to the Spinoza, Baruch Spinoza, Baruch 871 871 essences of things. The third kind of
knowledge he calls intuitive knowledge scientia intuitiva; it proceeds from
adequate knowledge of the essence or attributes of God to knowledge of the
essence of things, and hence proceeds in the proper order, from causes to
effects. Both the second and third kinds of knowledge are adequate. The third
kind is preferable, however, as involving not only certain knowledge that
something is so, but also knowledge of how and why it is so. Because there is
only one substance God the individual things of the world are not
distinguished from one another by any difference of substance. Rather, among
the internal qualitative modifications and differentiations of each divine
attribute, there are patterns that have a tendency to endure; these constitute
individual things. As they occur within the attribute of extension, Spinoza
calls these patterns fixed proportions of motion and rest. Although these
individual things are thus modes of the one substance, rather than substances
in their own right, each has a nature or essence describable in terms of the
thing’s particular pattern and its mechanisms for the preservation of its own
being. This tendency toward self-preservation Spinoza calls conatus sometimes
translated as ‘endeavor’. Every individual thing has some conatus. An
individual thing acts, or is active, to the extent that what occurs can be
explained or understood through its own nature i.e., its selfpreservatory
mechanism alone; it is passive to the extent that what happens must be
explained through the nature of other forces impinging on it. Thus, every
thing, to whatever extent it can, actively strives to persevere in its
existence; and whatever aids this self-preservation constitutes that
individual’s advantage. Spinoza’s specifically human psychology is an
application of this more general doctrine of conatus. That application is made
through appeal to several specific characteristics of human beings: they form
imagistic representations of other individuals by means of their senses; they
are sufficiently complex to undergo increases and decreases in their capacity
for action; and they are capable of engaging in reason. The fundamental
concepts of his psychology are desire, which is conatus itself, especially as
one is conscious of it as directed toward attaining a particular object;
pleasure, which is an increase in capacity for action; and pain, which is a
decrease in capacity for action. He defines other emotions in terms of these
basic emotions, as they occur in particular combinations, in particular kinds
of circumstances, with particular kinds of causes, and/or with particular kinds
of objects. When a person is the adequate cause of his or her own emotions,
these emotions are active emotions; otherwise, they are passions. Desire and
pleasure can be either active emotions or passions, depending on the
circumstances; pain, however, can only be a passion. Spinoza does not deny the
phenomenon of altruism: one’s self-preservatory mechanism, and hence one’s
desire, can become focused on a wide variety of objects, including the well-being
of a loved person or object even to
one’s own detriment. However, because he reduces all human motivation,
including altruistic motivation, to permutations of the endeavor to seek one’s
own advantage, his theory is arguably a form of psychological egoism. Ethics.
Spinoza’s ethical theory does not take the form of a set of moral commands.
Rather, he seeks to demonstrate, by considering human actions and appetites
objectively “just as if it were a
Question of lines, planes, and bodies”
wherein a person’s true advantage lies. Readers who genuinely grasp the
demonstrated truths will, he holds, ipso facto be motivated, to at least some
extent, to live their lives accordingly. Thus, Spinozistic ethics seeks to show
how a person acts when “guided by reason“; to act in this way is at the same
time to act with virtue, or power. All actions that result from
understanding i.e., all virtuous
actions may be attributed to strength of
character fortitudo. Such virtuous actions may be further divided into two
classes: those due to tenacity animositas, or “the Desire by which each one
strives, solely from the dictate of reason, to preserve his being”; and those
due to nobility generositas, or “the Desire by which each one strives, solely
from the dictate of reason, to aid other men and join them to him in
friendship.” Thus, the virtuous person does not merely pursue private
advantage, but seeks to cooperate with others; returns love for hatred; always
acts honestly, not deceptively; and seeks to join himself with others in a
political state. Nevertheless, the ultimate reason for aiding others and
joining them to oneself in friendship is that “nothing is more useful to man
than man” i.e., because doing so is
conducive to one’s own advantage, and particularly to one’s pursuit of
knowledge, which is a good that can be shared without loss. Although Spinoza
holds that we generally use the terms ‘good’ and ‘evil’ simply to report
subjective appearances so that we call
“good” whatever we desire, and “evil” whatever we seek to avoid he proposes that we Spinoza, Baruch Spinoza,
Baruch 872 872 define ‘good’
philosophically as ‘what we certainly know to be useful to us’, and ‘evil’ as
‘what we certainly know prevents us from being masters of some good’. Since God
is perfect and has no needs, it follows that nothing is either good or evil for
God. Spinoza’s ultimate appeal to the agent’s advantage arguably renders his
ethical theory a form of ethical egoism, even though he emphasizes the
existence of common shareable goods and the instrumental ethical importance of
cooperation with others. However, it is not a form of hedonism; for despite the
prominence he gives to pleasure, the ultimate aim of human action is a higher
state of perfection or capacity for action, of whose increasing attainment
pleasure is only an indicator. A human being whose self-preservatory mechanism
is driven or distorted by external forces is said to be in bondage to the
passions; in contrast, one who successfully pursues only what is truly
advantageous, in consequence of genuine understanding of where that advantage
properly lies, is free. Accordingly, Spinoza also expresses his conception of a
virtuous life guided by reason in terms of an ideal “free man.” Above all, the
free man seeks understanding of himself and of Nature. Adequate knowledge, and
particularly knowledge of the third kind, leads to blessedness, to peace of
mind, and to the intellectual love of God. Blessedness is not a reward for
virtue, however, but rather an integral aspect of the virtuous life. The human
mind is itself a part of the infinite intellect of God, and adequate knowledge
is an eternal aspect of that infinite intellect. Hence, as one gains knowledge,
a greater part of one’s own mind comes to be identified with something that is
eternal, and one becomes less dependent on
and less disturbed by the local
forces of one’s immediate environment. Accordingly, the free man “thinks of
nothing less than of death, and his wisdom is a meditation on life, not on
death.” Moreover, just as one’s adequate knowledge is literally an eternal part
of the infinite intellect of God, the resulting blessedness, peace of mind, and
intellectual love are literally aspects of what might be considered God’s own
eternal “emotional” life. Although this endows the free man with a kind of
blessed immortality, it is not a personal immortality, since the sensation and
memory that are essential to personal individuality are not eternal. Rather,
the free man achieves during his lifetime an increasing participation in a body
of adequate knowledge that has itself always been eternal, so that, at death, a
large part of the free man’s mind has become identified with the eternal. It is
thus a kind of “immortality” in which one can participate while one lives, not
merely when one dies. Politics and philosophical theology. Spinoza’s political
theory, like that of Hobbes, treats rights and power as equivalent. Citizens
give up rights to the state for the sake of the protection that the state can
provide. Hobbes, however, regards this social contract as nearly absolute, one
in which citizens give up all of their rights except the right to resist death.
Spinoza, in contrast, emphasizes that citizens cannot give up the right to
pursue their own advantage as they see it, in its full generality; and hence
that the power, and right, of any actual state is always limited by the state’s
practical ability to enforce its dictates so as to alter the citizens’
continuing perception of their own advantage. Furthermore, he has a more
extensive conception of the nature of an individual’s own advantage than
Hobbes, since for him one’s own true advantage lies not merely in fending off
death and pursuing pleasure, but in achieving the adequate knowledge that
brings blessedness and allows one to participate in that which is eternal. In
consequence, Spinoza, unlike Hobbes, recommends a limited, constitutional state
that encourages freedom of expression and religious toleration. Such a
state itself a kind of individual best preserves its own being, and provides
both the most stable and the most beneficial form of government for its
citizens. In his Theological-Political Treatise, Spinoza also takes up popular
religion, the interpretation of Scripture, and their bearing on the well-being
of the state. He characterizes the Old Testament prophets as individuals whose
vivid imaginations produced messages of political value for the ancient Hebrew
state. Using a naturalistic outlook and historical hermeneutic methods that
anticipate the later “higher criticism” of the Bible, he seeks to show that
Scriptural writers themselves consistently treat only justice and charity as
essential to salvation, and hence that dogmatic doxastic requirements are not
justified by Scripture. Popular religion should thus propound only these two
requirements, which it may imaginatively represent, to the minds of the many,
as the requirements for rewards granted by a divine Lawgiver. The few, who are
more philosophical, and who thus rely on intellect, will recognize that the
natural laws of human psychology require charity and justice as conditions of
happiness, and that what the vulgar construe as rewards granted by personal
divine intervention are in fact the natural consequences of a virtuous life.
Spinoza, Baruch Spinoza, Baruch 873 873
Because of his identificaton of God with Nature and his treatment of popular
religion, Spinoza’s contemporaries often regarded his philosophy as a thinly
disguised atheism. Paradoxically, however, nineteenth-century Romanticism
embraced him for his pantheism; Novalis, e.g., famously characterized him as
“the God-intoxicated man.” In fact, Spinoza ascribes to Nature most of the
characteristics that Western theologians have ascribed to God: Spinozistic
Nature is infinite, eternal, necessarily existing, the object of an ontological
argument, the first cause of all things, all-knowing, and the being whose
contemplation produces blessedness, intellectual love, and participation in a
kind of immortality or eternal life. Spinoza’s claim to affirm the existence of
God is therefore no mere evasion. However, he emphatically denies that God is a
person or acts for purposes; that anything is good or evil from the divine
perspective; or that there is a personal immortality involving memory. In
addition to his influence on the history of biblical criticism and on
literature including not only Novalis but such writers as Wordsworth,
Coleridge, Heine, Shelley, George Eliot, George Sand, Somerset Maugham, Jorge
Luis Borges, and Bernard Malamud, Spinoza has affected the philosophical
outlooks of such diverse twentieth-century thinkers as Freud and Einstein.
Contemporary physicists have seen in his monistic metaphysics an anticipation
of twentieth-century field metaphysics. More generally, he is a leading
intellectual forebear of twentieth-century determinism and naturalism, and of
the mindbody identity theory.
Spir, Afrikan 183790,
German philosopher. He served in the Crimean War as a Russian officer. A
non-academic, he published books in German and French. His major works are
Forschung nach der Gewissheit in der Erkenntnis der Wirklichkeit Inquiry
concerning Certainty in the Knowledge of Actuality, 1869 and the two-volume
Denken und Wirklichkeit: Versuch einer Erneuerung der kritischen Philosophie
Thought and Actuality: Attempt at a Revival of Critical Philosophy, 1873.
Thought and Actuality presents a metaphysics based on the radical separation of
the apparent world and an absolute reality. All we can know about the
“unconditioned” is that it must conform with the principle of identity. While
retaining the unknowable thing-in-itself of Kant, Spir argued for the empirical
reality of time, which is given to us in immediate experience and depends on
our experience of a succession of differential states. The aim of philosophy is
to reach fundamental and immediate certainties. Of the works included in his
Gesammelte Schriften 1883 84, only a relatively minor study, Right and Wrong,
was translated into English in 1954. There are a number of references to Spir
in the writings of Nietzsche, which indicate that some of Nietzsche’s central
notions were influenced, both positively and negatively, by Spir’s analyses of
becoming and temporality, as well as by his concept of the separation of the world
of appearance and the “true world.” G.J.S. spirit.SOUL. spirit, Absolute.
split brain effects, a
wide array of behavioral effects consequent upon the severing of the cerebral
commisures, and generally interpreted as indicating asymmetry in cerebral functions.
The human brain has considerable leftright functional differentiation, or
asymmetry, that affects behavior. The most obvious example is handedness. By
the 1860s Bouillaud, Dax, and Broca had observed that the effects of unilateral
damage indicated that the left hemisphere was preferentially involved in
language. Since the 1960s, this commitment to functional asymmetry has been
reinforced by studies of patients in whom communication between the hemispheres
has been surgically disrupted. Split brain effects depend on severing the
cerebral commisures, and especially the corpus callosum, which are neural
structures mediating communication between the cerebral hemispheres.
Commisurotomies have been performed since the 1940s to control severe epilepsy.
This is intended to leave both hemispheres intact and functioning
independently. Beginning in the 1960s, J. E. Bogen, M. S. Gazzaniga, and R. W.
Sperry conducted an array of psychological tests to evaluate the distinctive
abilities of the different hemispheres. Ascertaining the degree of cerebral
asymmetry depends on a carefully controlled experimental design in which access
of the disassociated hemispheres to peripheral cues is limited. The result has
been a wide array of striking results. For example, patients are unable to
match an object such as a key felt in one hand with a similar object felt in
the other; patients are unable to name an object Spir, Afrikan split brain
effects 874 874 held in the left hand,
though they can name an object held in the right. Researchers have concluded
that these results confirm a clear lateralization of speech, writing, and
calculation in the left hemisphere for righthanded patients, leaving the right
hemisphere largely unable to respond in speech or writing, and typically unable
to perform even simple calculations. It is often concluded that the left
hemisphere is specialized for verbal and analytic modes of thinking, while the
right hemisphere is specialized for more spatial and synthetic modes of
thinking. The precise character and extent of these differences in normal
subjects are less clear. R.C.R. spontaneity, liberty of.FREE WILL PROBLEM,
HUME. spread law.
square of opposition, a
graphic representation of various logical relations among categorical
propositions. Relations among modal and even among hypothetical propositions
have also been represented on the square. Two propositions are said to be each
other’s 1 contradictories if exactly one of them must be true and exactly one
false; 2 contraries if they could not both be true although they could both be
false; and 3 subcontraries if at least one of them must be true although both
of them may be true. There is a relation of 4 subalternation of one
proposition, called subaltern, to another called superaltern, if the truth of
the latter implies the truth of the former, but not conversely. Applying these
definitions to the four types of categorical propositions, we find that SaP and
SoP are contradictories, and so are SeP and SiP. SaP and SeP are contraries.
SiP and SoP are subcontraries. SiP is subaltern to SaP, and SoP is subaltern to
SeP. These relations can be represented graphically in a square of opposition:
The four relations on the traditional square are expressed in the following
theses: Contradictories: SaP S -SoP, SeP S -SiP Contraries: -SaP & SeP or
SaP P -SeP Subcontraries: SiP 7 SoP Subalterns: SaP P SiP, SeP P SoP For these
relations to hold, an underlying existential assumption must be satisfied: the
terms serving as subjects of propositions must be satisfied, not empty e.g.,
‘man’ is satisfied and ‘elf’ empty. Only the contradictory opposition remains
without that assumption. Modern interpretations of categorical propositions
exclude the existential assumption; thus, only the contradictory opposition
remains in the square.
standard model, a term
that, like ‘non-standard model’, is used with regard to theories that
systematize part of our knowledge of some mathematical structure, for instance
the structure of natural numbers with addition, multiplication, and the
successor function, or the structure of real numbers with ordering, addition,
and multiplication. Models isomorphic to this intended mathematical structure
are the “standard models” of the theory, while any other, non-isomorphic, model
of the theory is a ‘non-standard’ model. Since Peano arithmetic is incomplete,
it has consistent extensions that have no standard model. But there are also
non-standard, countable models of complete number theory, the set of all true
first-order sentences about natural numbers, as was first shown by Skolem in
1934. Categorical theories do not have a non-standard model. It is less clear
whether there is a standard model of set theory, although a countable model
would certainly count as non-standard. The Skolem paradox is that any
first-order formulation of set theory, like ZF, due to Zermelo and Fraenkel,
has a countable model, while it seems to assert the existence of non-countable
sets. Many other important mathematical structures cannot be characterized by a
categorical set of first-order axioms, and thus allow non-standard models. The
American philosopher Putnam has argued that this fact has important
implications for the debate about realism in the philosophy of language. If
axioms cannot capture the spontaneity, liberty of standard model 875 875 “intuitive” notion of a set, what could?
Some of his detractors have pointed out that within second-order logic
categorical characterizations are often possible. But Putnam has objected that
the intended interpretation of second-order logic itself is not fixed by the
use of the formalism of second-order logic, where “use” is determined by the
rules of inference for second-order logic we know about. Moreover, categorical
theories are sometimes uninformative.
state, the way an object
or system basically is; the fundamental, intrinsic properties of an object or
system, and the basis of its other properties. An instantaneous state is a
state at a given time. State variables are constituents of a state whose values
may vary with time. In classical or Newtonian mechanics the instantaneous state
of an n-particle system consists of the positions and momenta masses multiplied
by velocities of the n particles at a given time. Other mechanical properties
are functions of those in states. Fundamental and derived properties are often,
though possibly misleadingly, called observables. The set of a system’s
possible states can be represented as an abstract phase space or state space,
with dimensions or coordinates for the components of each state variable. In
quantum theory, states do not fix the particular values of observables, only
the probabilities of observables assuming particular values in particular
measurement situations. For positivism or instrumentalism, specifying a quantum
state does nothing more than provide a means for calculating such
probabilities. For realism, it does more
e.g., it refers to the basis of a quantum system’s probabilistic
dispositions or propensities. Vectors in Hilbert spaces represent possible
states, and Hermitian operators on vectors represent observables.
state of affairs, a
possibility, actuality, or impossibility of the kind expressed by a
nominalization of a declarative sentence. The declarative sentence ‘This die
comes up six’ can be nominalized either through the construction ‘that this die
comes up six’ or through the likes of ‘this die’s coming up six’. The resulting
nominalizations might be interpreted as naming corresponding propositions or
states of affairs. States of affairs come in several varieties. Some are
possible states of affairs, or possibilities. Consider the possibility of a
certain die coming up six when rolled next. This possibility is a state of
affairs, as is its “complement” the
die’s not coming up six when rolled next. There is in addition the state of
affairs which conjoins that die’s coming up six with its not coming up six. And
this contradictory state of affairs is of course not a possibility, not a
possible state of affairs. Moreover, for every actual state of affairs there is
a non-actual one, its complement. For every proposition there is hence a state
of affairs: possible or impossible, actual or not. Indeed some consider
propositions to be states of affairs. Some take facts to be actual states of
affairs, while others prefer to define them as true propositions. If
propositions are states of affairs, then facts are of course both actual states
of affairs and true propositions. In a very broad sense, events are just
possible states of affairs; in a narrower sense they are contingent states of
affairs; and in a still narrower sense they are contingent and particular
states of affairs, involving just the exemplification of an nadic property by a
sequence of individuals of length n. In a yet narrower sense events are only
those particular and contingent states of affairs that entail change. A
baseball’s remaining round throughout a certain period does not count as an
event in this narrower sense but only as a state of that baseball, unlike the
event of its being hit by a certain bat.
statistical explanation,
an explanation expressed in an explanatory argument containing premises and
conclusions making claims about statistical probabilities. These arguments
include deductions of less general from more general laws and differ from other
such explanations only insofar as the contents of the laws imply claims about
statistical probability. Most philosophical discussion in the latter half of
the twentieth century has focused on statistical explanation of events rather
than laws. This type of argument was discussed by Ernest Nagel The Structure of
Science, 1961 under the rubric “probabilistic explanation,” and by Hempel
Aspects of Scientific Explanation, 1965 as “inductive statistical” explanation.
The explanans contains a statement asserting that a given system responds in
one of several ways specified by a sample space of possible outcomes on a trial
or experiment of some type, and that the statistical probability of an event
represented by a set of points in the sample space on the given kind of trial
is also given for each such event. Thus, the statement might assert that the
statistical probability is near 1 of the relative frequency r/n of heads in n
tosses being close to the statistical probability p of heads on a single toss,
where the sample space consists of the 2n possible sequences of heads and tails
in n tosses. Nagel and Hempel understood such statistical probability
statements to be covering laws, so that inductive-statistical explanation and
deductivenomological explanation of events are two species of covering law
explanation. The explanans also contains a claim that an experiment of the kind
mentioned in the statistical assumption has taken place e.g., the coin has been
tossed n times. The explanandum asserts that an event of some kind has occurred
e.g., the coin has landed heads approximately r times in the n tosses. In many
cases, the kind of experiment can be described equivalently as an n-fold
repetition of some other kind of experiment as a thousandfold repetition of the
tossing of a given coin or as the implementation of the kind of trial
thousand-fold tossing of the coin one time. Hence, statistical explanation of
events can always be construed as deriving conclusions about “single cases”
from assumptions about statistical probabilities even when the concern is to
explain mass phenomena. Yet, many authors controversially contrast statistical
explanation in quantum mechanics, which is alleged to require a singlecase
propensity interpretation of statistical probability, with statistical
explanation in statistical mechanics, genetics, and the social sciences, which
allegedly calls for a frequency interpretation. The structure of the
explanatory argument of such statistical explanation has the form of a direct
inference from assumptions about statistical probabilities and the kind of experiment
trial which has taken place to the outcome. One controversial aspect of direct
inference is the problem of the reference class. Since the early nineteenth
century, statistical probability has been understood to be relative to the way
the experiment or trial is described. Authors like J. Venn, Peirce, R. A.
Fisher, and Reichenbach, among many others, have been concerned with how to
decide on which kind of trial to base a direct inference when the trial under
investigation is correctly describable in several ways and the statistical
probabilities of possible outcomes may differ relative to the different sorts
of descriptions. The most comprehensive discussion of this problem of the
reference class is found in the work of H. E. Kyburg e.g., Probability and the
Logic of Rational Belief, 1961. Hempel acknowledged its importance as an
“epistemic ambiguity” in inductive statistical explanation. Controversy also
arises concerning inductive acceptance. May the conclusion of an explanatory
direct inference be a judgment as to the subjective probability that the
outcome event occurred? May a judgment that the outcome event occurred is
inductively “accepted” be made? Is some other mode of assessing the claim about
the outcome appropriate? Hempel’s discussion of the “nonconjunctiveness of
inductivestatistical” explanation derives from Kyburg’s earlier account of
direct inference where high probability is assumed to be sufficient for
acceptance. Non-conjunctiveness has been avoided by abandoning the sufficiency of
high probability I. Levi, Gambling with Truth, 1967 or by denying that direct
inference in inductive-statistical explanation involves inductive acceptance at
all R. C. Jeffrey, “Statistical Explanation vs. Statistical Inference,” in
Essays in Honor of C. G. Hempel, 1969.
Steiner, Rudolf 18611925,
Austrian spiritualist and founder of anthroposophy. Trained as a scientist, he
edited Goethe’s scientific writings and prepared the standard edition of his
complete works from 1889 to 1896. Steiner’s major work, Die Philosophie der
Freiheit, was published in 1894. His Friedrich Nietzsche: Ein Kämpfer gegen
seine Zeit 1895 was translated in 1960 by Margaret deRis as Friedrich
Nietzsche: Fighter for Freedom. Steiner taught at a workingmen’s and edited a literary journal, Magazin für
Literatur, in Berlin. In 1901 he embraced a spiritualism which emphasized a
form of knowledge that transcended sensory experience and was attained by the
“higher self.” He held that man had previously been attuned to spiritual
processes by virtue of a dreamlike state of consciousness, but was diverted
from this consciousness by preoccupation with material entities. Through
training, individuals could retrieve their innate capacity to perceive a
spiritual realm. Steiner’s writings on this theme are The Philosophy of
Spiritual Activity 1894, Occult Science: An Outline 1913, On the Riddle of Man
1916, and On the Riddles of the Soul 1917. His last work was his autobiography
1924. To advance his teachings, he founded the Anthroposophical Society 1912
and a school of “spiritual science” called the Goetheanum near Basel, Switzerland.
His work inspired the Waldorf School movement, which comprises some eighty
schools for children. The anthroposophy movement he established remains active
in Europe and the United States. G.J.S. Stephen, Sir Leslie 18321904, English
literary critic, editor, intellectual historian, and philosopher. He was the
first chief editor of the great Dictionary of National Biography, writing
hundreds of the entries himself. Brought up in an intensely religious
household, he lost his faith and spent much of his time trying to construct a
moral and intellectual outlook to replace it. His main works in intellectual
history, the two-volume History of English Thought in the Eighteenth Century
1876 and the three-volume English Utilitarians 1900, were undertaken as part of
this project. So was his one purely philosophical work, the Science of Ethics
1882, in which he tried to develop an evolutionary theory of morality. Stephen
was impatient of philosophical technicalities. Hence his treatise on ethics
does very little to resolve the problems
some of them pointed out to him by his friend Henry Sidgwick with evolutionary ethics, and does not get
beyond the several other works on the subject published during this period. His
histories of thought are sometimes superficial, and their focus of interest is
not ours; but they are still useful because of their scope and the massive
scholarship they put to use.
Stillingfleet, Edward
163599, English divine and controversialist who first made his name with
Irenicum 1659, using natural-law doctrines to oppose religious sectarianism.
His Origines Sacrae 1662, ostensibly on the superiority of the Scriptural
record over other forms of ancient history, was for its day a learned study in
the moral certainty of historical evidence, the authority of testimony, and the
credibility of miracles. In drawing eclectically on philosophy from antiquity
to the Cambridge Platonists, he was much influenced by the Cartesian theory of
ideas, but later repudiated Cartesianism for its mechanist tendency. For three
decades he pamphleteered on behalf of the moral certainty of orthodox
Protestant belief against what he considered the beliefs “contrary to reason”
of Roman Catholicism. This led to controversy with Unitarian and deist writers
who argued that mysteries like the Trinity were equally contrary to “clear and
distinct” ideas. He was alarmed at the use made of Locke’s “new,” i.e.
nonCartesian, way of ideas by John Toland in Christianity not Mysterious 1696,
and devoted his last years to challenging Locke to prove his orthodoxy. The
debate was largely over the concepts of substance, essence, and person, and of
faith and certainty. Locke gave no quarter in the public controversy, but in
the fourth edition of his Essay 1700 he silently amended some passages that had
provoked Stillingfleet.
Stirner, Max, pseudonym
of Kasper Schmidt 180556, German philosopher who proposed a theory of radical
individualism. Born in Bayreuth, he taught in Gymnasiums and later at a Berlin
academy for women. He translated what became a standard German version of
Smith’s Wealth of Nations and contributed articles to the Rhenische Zeitung.
His most important work was statistical probability Stirner, Max 878 878 Der Einzige und sein Eigenthum 1845,
translated by Steven T. Byington as The Ego and His Own 1907. His second book
was Die Geschichte der Reaktion 1852. Stirner was in reaction to Hegel and was
for a time associated with the left Hegelians. He stressed the priority of will
and instinct over reason and proposed a radical anarchic individualism. Each
individual is unique, and the independent ego is the fundamental value and
reality. Stirner attacked the state, religious ideas, and abstractions such as
“humanity” as “spectres” that are deceptive illusions, remnants of erroneous
hypostatizations. His defense of egoism is such that the individual is
considered to have no obligations or duties, and especially not to the state.
Encouraging an individual “rebellion” against state domination and control,
Stirner attracted a following among nineteenthand twentieth-century anarchists.
The sole goal of life is the cultivation of “uniqueness” or “ownness.” Engels
and Marx attacked his ideas at length under the rubric “Saint Marx” in The
German Ideology. Insofar as his theory of radical individualism offers no
clearly stated ethical requirements, it has been characterized as a form of
nihilistic egoism.
stochastic process, a
process that evolves, as time goes by, according to a probabilistic principle
rather than a deterministic principle. Such processes are also called random
processes, but ‘stochastic’ does not imply complete disorderliness. The
principle of evolution governing a stochastic or random process is precise,
though probabilistic, in form. For example, suppose some process unfolds in
discrete successive stages. And suppose that given any initial sequence of
stages, S1, S2, . . . , Sn, there is a precise probability that the next stage
Sn+1 will be state S, a precise probability that it will be SH, and so on for all
possible continuations of the sequence of states. These probabilities are
called transition probabilities. An evolving sequence of this kind is called a
discrete-time stochastic process, or discrete-time random process. A
theoretically important special case occurs when transition probabilities
depend only on the latest stage in the sequence of stages. When an evolving
process has this property it is called a discrete-time Markov process. A simple
example of a discrete-time Markov process is the behavior of a person who keeps
taking either a step forward or a step back according to whether a coin falls
heads or tails; the probabilistic principle of movement is always applied to
the person’s most recent position. The successive stages of a stochastic process
need not be discrete. If they are continuous, they constitute a
“continuous-time” stochastic or random process. The mathematical theory of
stochastic processes has many applications in science and technology. The
evolution of epidemics, the process of soil erosion, and the spread of cracks
in metals have all been given plausible models as stochastic processes, to
mention just a few areas of research.
Stoicism, one of the
three leading movements constituting Hellenistic philosophy. Its founder was
Zeno of Citium 334262 B.C., who was succeeded as school head by Cleanthes 331
232. But the third head, Chrysippus c.280 c.206, was its greatest exponent and
most voluminous writer. These three are the leading representatives of Early
Stoicism. No work by any early Stoic survives intact, except Cleanthes’ short
“Hymn to Zeus.” Otherwise we are dependent on doxography, on isolated
quotations, and on secondary sources, most of them hostile. Nevertheless, a
remarkably coherent account of the system can be assembled. The Stoic world is
an ideally good organism, all of whose parts interact for the benefit of the
whole. It is imbued with divine reason logos, its entire development
providentially ordained by fate and repeated identically from one world phase
to the next in a never-ending cycle, each phase ending with a conflagration
ekpyrosis. Only bodies strictly “exist” and can interact. Body is infinitely
divisible, and contains no void. At the lowest level, the world is analyzed
into an active principle, god, and a passive principle, matter, both probably
corporeal. Out of these are generated, at a higher level, the four elements
air, fire, earth, and water, whose own interaction is analogous to that of god
and matter: air and fire, severally or conjointly, are an active rational force
called breath Grecian pneuma, Latin spiritus, while earth and water constitute
the passive substrate on which these act, totally interpenetrating each other
thanks to the non-particulate structure of body and its capacity to be mixed
“through and through.” Most physical analysis is conducted at this higher
level, and pneuma becomes a key concept in physics and biology. A thing’s
qualities are constituted by its pneuma, which has the additional role of
giving it cohestochastic process Stoicism 879
879 sion and thus an essential identity. In inanimate objects this
unifying pneuma is called a hexis state; in plants it is called physis nature;
and in animals “soul.” Even qualities of soul, e.g. justice, are portions of
pneuma, and they too are therefore bodies: only thus could they have their
evident causal efficacy. Four incorporeals are admitted: place, void which
surrounds the world, time, and lekta see below; these do not strictly
“exist” they lack the corporeal power of
interaction but as items with some
objective standing in the world they are, at least, “somethings.” Universals,
identified with Plato’s Forms, are treated as concepts ennoemata, convenient
fictions that do not even earn the status of “somethings.” Stoic ethics is
founded on the principle that only virtue is good, only vice bad. Other things
conventionally assigned a value are “indifferent” adiaphora, although some,
e.g., health, wealth, and honor, are naturally “preferred” proegmena, while
their opposites are “dispreferred” apoproegmena. Even though their possession
is irrelevant to happiness, from birth these indifferents serve as the
appropriate subject matter of our choices, each correct choice being a “proper
function” kathekon not yet a morally
good act, but a step toward our eventual end telos of “living in accordance
with nature.” As we develop our rationality, the appropriate choices become
more complex, less intuitive. For example, it may sometimes be more in
accordance with nature’s plan to sacrifice your wealth or health, in which case
it becomes your “proper function” to do so. You have a specific role to play in
the world plan, and moral progress prokope consists in learning it. This
progress involves widening your natural “affinity” oikeiosis: an initial concern
for yourself and your parts is later extended to those close to you, and
eventually to all mankind. That is the Stoic route toward justice. However,
justice and the other virtues are actually found only in the sage, an idealized
perfectly rational person totally in tune with the divine cosmic plan. The
Stoics doubted whether any sages existed, although there was a tendency to
treat at least Socrates as having been one. The sage is totally good, everyone
else totally bad, on the paradoxical Stoic principle that all sins are equal.
The sage’s actions, however similar externally to mere “proper functions,” have
an entirely distinct character: they are renamed ‘right actions’ katorthomata.
Acting purely from “right reason,” he is distinguished by his “freedom from
passion” apatheia: morally wrong impulses, or passions, are at root
intellectual errors of mistaking what is indifferent for good or bad, whereas
the sage’s evaluations are always correct. The sage alone is happy and truly
free, living in perfect harmony with the divine plan. All human lives are
predetermined by the providentially designed, all-embracing causal nexus of
fate; yet being the principal causes of their actions, the good and the bad
alike are responsible for them: determinism and morality are fully compatible.
Stoic epistemology defends the existence of cognitive certainty against the
attacks of the New Academy. Belief is described as assent synkatathesis to an
impression phantasia, i.e. taking as true the propositional content of some
perceptual or reflective impression. Certainty comes through the “cognitive
impression” phantasia kataleptike, a self-certifying perceptual representation
of external fact, claimed to be commonplace. Out of sets of such impressions we
acquire generic conceptions prolepseis and become rational. The highest
intellectual state, knowledge episteme, in which all cognitions become mutually
supporting and hence “unshakable by reason,” is the prerogative of the wise.
Everyone else is in a state of mere opinion doxa or of ignorance. Nevertheless,
the cognitive impression serves as a “criterion of truth” for all. A further
important criterion is prolepseis, also called common conceptions and common
notions koinai ennoiai, often appealed to in philosophical argument. Although
officially dependent on experience, they often sound more like innate
intuitions, purportedly indubitable. Stoic logic is propositional, by contrast
with Aristotle’s logic of terms. The basic unit is the simple proposition
axioma, the primary bearer of truth and falsehood. Syllogistic also employs
complex propositions conditional,
conjunctive, and disjunctive and rests
on five “indemonstrable” inference schemata to which others can be reduced with
the aid of four rules called themata. All these items belong to the class of
lekta “sayables” or “expressibles.”
Words are bodies vibrating portions of air, as are external objects, but
predicates like that expressed by ‘ . . . walks’, and the meanings of whole
sentences, e.g., ‘Socrates walks’, are incorporeal lekta. The structure and
content of both thoughts and sentences are analyzed by mapping them onto lekta,
but the lekta are themselves causally inert. Conventionally, a second phase of
the school is distinguished as Middle Stoicism. It developed largely at Rhodes
under Panaetius and Posidonius, both of whom influenced the presentation of
Stoicism in Cicero’s influential philosophical treatises mid-first century
B.C.. Panaetius Stoicism Stoicism 880
880 c.185c.110 softened some classical Stoic positions, his ethics being
more pragmatic and less concerned with the idealized sage. Posidonius c.135c.50
made Stoicism more open to Platonic and Aristotelian ideas, reviving Plato’s
inclusion of irrational components in the soul. A third phase, Roman Stoicism,
is the only Stoic era whose writings have survived in quantity. It is
represented especially by the younger Seneca A.D. c.165, Epictetus A.D.
c.55c.135, and Marcus Aurelius A.D. 12180. It continued the trend set by
Panaetius, with a strong primary focus on practical and personal ethics. Many
prominent Roman political figures were Stoics. After the second century A.D.
Stoicism as a system fell from prominence, but its terminology and concepts had
by then become an ineradicable part of ancient thought. Through the writings of
Cicero and Seneca, its impact on the moral and political thought of the
Renaissance was immense.
Stout, George Frederick
18601944, British psychologist and philosopher. A student of Ward, he was
influenced by Herbart and especially Brentano. He was editor of Mind 18921920.
He followed Ward in rejecting associationism and sensationism, and proposing
analysis of mind as activity rather than passivity, consisting of acts of
cognition, feeling, and conation. Stout stressed attention as the essential
function of mind, and argued for the goal-directedness of all mental activity
and behavior, greatly influencing McDougall’s hormic psychology. He
reinterpreted traditional associationist ideas to emphasize primacy of mental
activity; e.g., association by contiguity
a passive mechanical process imposed on mind became association by continuity of
attentional interest. With Brentano, he argued that mental representation involves
“thought reference” to a real object known through the representation that is
itself the object of thought, like Locke’s “idea.” In philosophy he was
influenced by Moore and Russell. His major works are Analytic Psychology 1896
and Manual of Psychology 1899.
Strato of Lampsacus
c.335c.267 B.C., Grecian philosopher and polymath nicknamed “the Physicist” for
his innovative ideas in natural science. He succeeded Theophrastus as head of
the Lyceum. Earlier he served as royal tutor in Alexandria, where his students
included Aristarchus, who devised the first heliocentric model. Of Strato’s
many writings only fragments and summaries survive. These show him criticizing
the abstract conceptual analysis of earlier theorists and paying closer
attention to empirical evidence. Among his targets were atomist arguments that
motion is impossible unless there is void, and also Aristotle’s thesis that
matter is fully continuous. Strato argued that no large void occurs in nature,
but that matter is naturally porous, laced with tiny pockets of void. His
investigations of compression and suction were influential in ancient
physiology. In dynamics, he proposed that bodies have no property of lightness
but only more or less weight.
Strawson: p. f. – Grice’s
tutee. b.1919, British philosopher who has made major contributions to logic,
metaphysics, and the study of Kant. His career has been at Oxford, where he was
the leading philosopher of his generation. His first important work, “On
Referring” 1950, argues that Russell’s theory of descriptions fails to deal
properly with the role of descriptions as “referring expressions” because
Russell assumed the “bogus trichotomy” that sentences are true, false, or
meaningless: for Strawson, sentences with empty descriptions are meaningful but
“neither true nor false” because the general presuppositions governing the use
of referring expressions are not fulfilled. One aspect of this argument was
Russell’s alleged insensitivity to the ordinary use of definite descriptions.
The contrast between the abstract schemata of formal logic and the manifold
richness of the inferences inherent in ordinary language is the central theme
of Strawson’s first book, Introduction to Logical Theory 1952. In Individuals
1959 Strawson reintroduced metaphysics as a respectable philosophical
discipline after decades of positivist rhetoric. But his project is only
“descriptive” metaphysics elucidation of
the basic features of our own conceptual scheme
and his arguments are based on the philosophy of language: “basic”
particulars Stoicism, Middle Strawson, Sir Peter 881 881 are those which are basic objects of
reference, and it is the spatiotemporal and sortal conditions for their
identification and reidentification by speakers that constitute the basic
categories. Three arguments are especially famous: 1 even in a purely auditory
world objective reference on the basis of experience requires at least an
analogue of space; 2 because self-reference presupposes reference to others,
persons, conceived as bearers of both physical and psychological properties,
are a type of basic particular; and 3 “feature-placing” discourse, such as ‘it
is snowing here now’, is “the ultimate propositional level” through which
reference to particulars enters discourse. Strawson’s next book, The Bounds of
Sense 1966, provides a critical reading of Kant’s theoretical philosophy. His
aim is to extricate what he sees as the profound truths concerning the
presuppositions of objective experience and judgment that Kant’s transcendental
arguments establish from the mysterious metaphysics of Kant’s transcendental
idealism. Strawson’s critics have argued, however, that the resulting position
is unstable: transcendental arguments can tell us only what we must suppose to
be the case. So if Kant’s idealism, which restricts such suppositions to things
as they appear to us, is abandoned, we can draw conclusions concerning the way
the world itself must be only if we add the verificationist thesis that ability
to make sense of such suppositions requires ability to verify them. In his next
book, Skepticism and Naturalism: Some Varieties 1985, Strawson conceded this:
transcendental arguments belong within descriptive metaphysics and should not
be regarded as attempts to provide an external justification of our conceptual
scheme. In truth no such external justification is either possible or needed:
instead and here Strawson invokes Hume
rather than Kant our reasonings come to
an end in natural propensities for belief that are beyond question because they
alone make it possible to raise questions. In a famous earlier paper Strawson
had urged much the same point concerning the free will debate: defenders of our
ordinary attitudes of reproach and gratitude should not seek to ground them in
the “panicky metaphysics” of a supra-causal free will; instead they can and need
do no more than point to our unshakable commitment to these “reactive”
attitudes through which we manifest our attachment to that fundamental category
of our conceptual scheme persons.
structuralism, a
distinctive yet extremely wide range of productive research conducted in the
social and human sciences from the 1950s through the 1970s, principally in
France. It is difficult to describe structuralism as a movement, because of the
methodological constraints exercised by the various disciplines that came to be
influenced by structuralism e.g.,
anthropology, philosophy, literary theory, psychoanalysis, political theory,
even mathematics. Nonetheless, structuralism is generally held to derive its
organizing principles from the early twentieth-century work of Saussure, the
founder of structural linguistics. Arguing against the prevailing historicist
and philological approaches to linguistics, he proposed a “scientific” model of
language, one understood as a closed system of elements and rules that account
for the production and the social communication of meaning. Inspired by
Durkheim’s notion of a “social fact”
that domain of objectivity wherein the psychological and the social
orders converge Saussure viewed language
as the repository of discursive signs shared by a given linguistic community.
The particular sign is composed of two elements, a phonemic signifier, or
distinctive sound element, and a corresponding meaning, or signified element.
The defining relation between the sign’s sound and meaning components is held
to be arbitrary, i.e., based on conventional association, and not due to any
function of the speaking substrict conditional structuralism 882 882 ject’s personal inclination, or to any
external consideration of reference. What lends specificity or identity to each
particular signifier is its differential relation to the other signifiers in
the greater set; hence, each basic unit of language is itself the product of
differences between other elements within the system. This principle of
differential and structural relation was extended by Troubetzkoy to the
order of phonemes, whereby a defining set of vocalic differences underlies the
constitution of all linguistic phonemes. Finally, for Saussure, the closed set
of signs is governed by a system of grammatical, phonemic, and syntactic rules.
Language thus derives its significance from its own autonomous organization,
and this serves to guarantee its communicative function. Since language is the
foremost instance of social sign systems in general, the structural account
might serve as an exemplary model for understanding the very intelligibility of
social systems as such hence, its
obvious relevance to the broader concerns of the social and human sciences.
This implication was raised by Saussure himself, in his Course on General
Linguistics1916, but it was advanced dramatically by the French anthropologist
Claude Lévi-Strauss who is generally
acknowledged to be the founder of modern structuralism in his extensive analyses in the area of
social anthropology, beginning with his Elementary Structures of Kinship 1949.
Lévi-Strauss argued that society is itself organized according to one form or
another of significant communication and exchange whether this be of information, knowledge, or
myths, or even of its members themselves. The organization of social phenomena
could thus be clarified through a detailed elaboration of their subtending
structures, which, collectively, testify to a deeper and all-inclusive, social
rationality. As with the analysis of language, these social structures would be
disclosed, not by direct observation, but by inference and deduction from the
observed empirical data. Furthermore, since these structures are models of
specific relations, which in turn express the differential properties of the
component elements under investigation, the structural analysis is both readily
formalizable and susceptible to a broad variety of applications. In Britain,
e.g., Edmund Leach pursued these analyses in the domain of social anthropology;
in the United States, Chomsky applied insights of structuralism to linguistic
theory and philosophy of mind; in Italy, Eco conducted extensive structuralist
analyses in the fields of social and literary semiotics. With its
acknowledgment that language is a rule-governed social system of signs, and
that effective communication depends on the resources available to the speaker
from within the codes of language itself, the structuralist approach tends to
be less preoccupied with the more traditional considerations of “subjectivity”
and “history” in its treatment of meaningful discourse. In the
post-structuralism that grew out of this approach, the French philosopher
Foucault, e.g., focused on the generation of the “subject” by the various
epistemic discourses of imitation and representation, as well as on the
institutional roles of knowledge and power in producing and conserving
particular “disciplines” in the natural and social sciences. These disciplines,
Foucault suggested, in turn govern our theoretical and practical notions of
madness, criminality, punishment, sexuality, etc., notions that collectively
serve to “normalize” the individual subject to their determinations. Likewise,
in the domain of psychoanalysis, Lacan drew on the work of Saussure and
Lévi-Strauss to emphasize Freud’s concern with language and to argue that, as a
set of determining codes, language serves to structure the subject’s very
unconscious. Problematically, however, it is the very dynamism of language,
including metaphor, metonymy, condensation, displacement, etc., that introduces
the social symbolic into the constitution of the subject. Althusser applied the
principles of structuralist methodology to his analysis of Marxism, especially
the role played by contradiction in understanding infrastructural and
superstructural formation, i.e., for the constitution of the historical
dialectic. His account followed Marx’s rejection of Feuerbach, at once denying
the role of traditional subjectivity and humanism, and presenting a
“scientific” analysis of “historical materialism,” one that would be
anti-historicist in principle but attentive to the actual political state of
affairs. For Althusser, such a philosophical analysis helped provide an
“objective” discernment to the historical transformation of social reality. The
restraint the structuralists extended toward the traditional views of
subjectivity and history dramatically colored their treatment both of the
individuals who are agents of meaningful discourse and of the linguistically
articulable object field in general. This redirection of research interests
particularly in France, due to the influential work of Barthes and Michel
Serres in the fields of poetics, cultural semiotics, and communication theory
has resulted in a series of original analyses and also provoked lively debates
between the adherents of structuralist structuralism structuralism 883 883 methodology and the more conventionally
oriented schools of thought e.g., phenomenology, existentialism, Marxism, and
empiricist and positivist philosophies of science. These debates served as an
agency to open up subsequent discussions on deconstruction and postmodernist
theory for the philosophical generation of the 1980s and later. These
post-structuralist thinkers were perhaps less concerned with the organization
of social phenomena than with their initial constitution and subsequent
dynamics. Hence, the problematics of the subject and history or, in broader terms, temporality itself were again engaged. The new discussions were
abetted by a more critical appraisal of language and tended to be antiHegelian
in their rejection of the totalizing tendency of systematic metaphysics.
Heidegger’s critique of traditional metaphysics was one of the major influences
in the discussions following structuralism, as was the reexamination of
Nietzsche’s earlier accounts of “genealogy,” his antiessentialism, and his
teaching of a dynamic “will to power.” Additionally, many poststructuralist philosophers
stressed the Freudian notions of the libido and the unconscious as determining
factors in understanding not only the subject, but the deep rhetorical and
affective components of language use. An astonishing variety of philosophers
and critics engaged in the debates initially framed by the structuralist
thinkers of the period, and their extended responses and critical reappraisals
formed the vibrant, poststructuralist period of French intellectual life. Such
figures as Ricoeur, Emmanuel Levinas, Kristeva, Maurice Blanchot, Derrida,
Gilles Deleuze, Félix Guattari, Lyotard, Jean Baudrillard, Philippe
LacoueLabarthe, Jean-Luc Nancy, and Irigaray inaugurated a series of
contemporary reflections that have become international in scope.
Suárez, Francisco, also
known as Doctor Eximius 15481617, Spanish Jesuit philosopher and theologian.
Born in Granada, he studied at Salamanca and taught there and at Rome, Coimbra,
and other leading universities. Suárez’s most important works are De legibus
“On Law,” 1612, De Deo uno et trino “On the Trinity,” 1606, De anima “On the
Soul,” 1621, and the monumental Disputationes metaphysicae “Metaphysical
Disputations,” 1597. The Disputationes has a unique place in philosophy, being
the first systematic and comprehensive work of metaphysics written in the West
that is not a commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Divided into fifty-four
disputations, it discusses every metaphysical issue known at the time. Its
influence was immediate and lasting and can be seen in the work of Scholastics
in both Europe and Latin America, and of modern philosophers such as Descartes,
Leibniz, Wolff, and Schopenhauer. Suárez’s main contributions to philosophy
occurred in metaphysics, epistemology, and the philosophy of law. In all three
areas he was influenced by Aristotle and Aquinas, although he also drew inspiration
from Ockham, Duns Scotus, and others. In metaphysics, Suárez is known for his
views on the nature of metaphysics, being, and individuation. Metaphysics is
the science of “being insofar as it is real being” ens in quantum ens reale,
and its proper object of study is the object concept of being. This
understanding of the object of metaphysics is often seen as paving the way for
early modern metaphysical theory, in which the object of metaphysics is mental.
For Suárez the concept of being is derived by analogy from the similarity
existing among things. Existing reality for Suárez is composed of individuals:
everything that exists is individual, including substances and their
properties, accidents, principles, and components. He understands individuality
as incommunicability, namely, the inability of individuals to be divided into
entities of the same specific kind as themselves. The principle of
individuation is “entity,” which he identifies with “essence as it exists.”
This principle applies both to substances and their properties, accidents,
principles, and components. In epistemology, two of Suárez’s views stand out:
that the intellect knows the individual through a proper and separate concept
without structuralism, mathematical Suárez, Francisco 884 884 having to turn to reflection, a position
that supports an empiricist epistemology in which, contrary to Thomism,
knowledge of the individual is not mediated through universals; and 2 his view
of middle knowledge scientia media, the knowledge God has of what every free
creature would freely do in every possible situation. This notion was used by
Suárez and Molina to explain how God can control human actions without
violating free will. In philosophy of law, Suárez was an innovative thinker
whose ideas influenced Grotius. For him law is fundamentally an act of the will
rather than a result of an ordinance of reason, as Aquinas held. Law is divided
into eternal, divine, natural, and human. Human law is based on natural or
divine law and is not the result of human creation.
subdoxastic, pertaining
to states of mind postulated to account for the production and character of
certain apparently non-inferential beliefs. These were first discussed by
Stephen P. Stich in “Beliefs and Subdoxastic States” 1978. I may form the
belief that you are depressed, e.g., on the basis of subtle cues that I am
unable to articulate. The psychological mechanism responsible for this belief
might be thought to harbor information concerning these cues subdoxastically.
Although subdoxastic states resemble beliefs in certain respects they incorporate intentional content, they
guide behavior, they can bestow justification on beliefs they differ from fullyfledged doxastic states
or beliefs in at least two respects. First, as noted above, subdoxastic states
may be largely inaccessible to introspection; I may be unable to describe, even
on reflection, the basis of my belief that you are depressed. Second,
subdoxastic states seem cut off inferentially from an agent’s corpus of
beliefs; my subdoxastic appreciation that your forehead is creased may
contribute to my believing that you are depressed, but, unlike the belief that
your forehead is creased, it need not, in the presence of other beliefs, lead
to further beliefs about your visage.
subjectivism, any
philosophical view that attempts to understand in a subjective manner what at
first glance would seem to be a class of judgments that are objectively either
true or false i.e., true or false independently
of what we believe, want, or hope. There are two ways of being a subjectivist.
In the first way, one can say that the judgments in question, despite first
appearances, are really judgments about our own attitudes, beliefs, emotions,
etc. In the second way, one can deny that the judgments are true or false at
all, arguing instead that they are disguised commands or expressions of
attitudes. In ethics, for example, a subjective view of the second sort is that
moral judgments are simply expressions of our positive and negative attitudes.
This is emotivism. Prescriptivism is also a subjective view of the second sort;
it is the view that moral judgments are really commands to say “X is good” is to say, details aside,
“Do X.” Views that make morality ultimately a matter of conventions or what we
or most people agree to can also be construed as subjective theories, albeit of
the first type. Subjectivism is not limited to ethics, however. According to a
subjective view of epistemic rationality, the standards of rational belief are
the standards that the individual or perhaps most members in the individual’s
community would approve of insofar as they are interested in believing those
propositions that are true and not believing those propositions that are false.
Similarly, phenomenalists can be regarded as proposing a subjective account of
material object statements, since according to them, such statements are best
understood as complex statements about the course of our experiences.
subject-object dichotomy,
the distinction between thinkers and what they think about. The distinction is
not exclusive, since subjects can also be objects, as in reflexive
self-conscious thought, which takes the subject as its intended object. The
dichotomy also need not be an exhaustive distinction in the strong sense that
everything is either a subject or an object, since in a logically possible
world in which there are no thinkers, there may yet be mind-independent
subaltern subjectobject dichotomy 885
885 things that are neither subjects nor objects. Whether there are
non-thinking things that are not objects of thought in the actual world depends
on whether or not it is sufficient in logic to intend every individual thing by
such thoughts and expressions as ‘We can think of everything that exists’. The
dichotomy is an interimplicative distinction between thinkers and what they
think about, in which each presupposes the other. If there are no subjects,
then neither are there objects in the true sense, and conversely. A
subjectobject dichotomy is acknowledged in most Western philosophical
traditions, but emphasized especially in Continental philosophy, beginning with
Kant, and carrying through idealist thought in Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, and
Schopenhauer. It is also prominent in intentionalist philosophy, in the
empirical psychology of Brentano, the object theory of Meinong, Ernst Mally
18791944, and Twardowski, and the transcendental phenomenology of Husserl. Subjectobject
dichotomy is denied by certain mysticisms, renounced as the philosophical
fiction of duality, of which Cartesian mindbody dualism is a particular
instance, and criticized by mystics as a confusion that prevents mind from
recognizing its essential oneness with the world, thereby contributing to
unnecessary intellectual and moral dilemmas.
sublime, a feeling brought
about by objects that are infinitely large or vast such as the heavens or the
ocean or overwhelmingly powerful such as a raging torrent, huge mountains, or
precipices. The former in Kant’s terminology is the mathematically sublime and
the latter the dynamically sublime. Though the experience of the sublime is to
an important extent unpleasant, it is also accompanied by a certain pleasure:
we enjoy the feeling of being overwhelmed. On Kant’s view, this pleasure
results from an awareness that we have powers of reason that are not dependent
on sensation, but that legislate over sense. The sublime thus displays both the
limitations of sense experience and hence our feeling of displeasure and the
power of our own mind and hence the feeling of pleasure. The sublime was an
especially important concept in the aesthetic theory of the eighteenth and
nineteenth centuries. Reflection on it was stimulated by the appearance of a
translation of Longinus’s Peri hypsous On the Sublime in 1674. The “postmodern
sublime” has in addition emerged in late twentieth century thought as a basis
for raising questions about art. Whereas beauty is associated with that whose
form can be apprehended, the sublime is associated with the formless, that
which is “unpresentable” in sensation. Thus, it is connected with critiques of
“the aesthetic” understood as that which
is sensuously present as a way of
understanding what is important about art. It has also been given a political
reading, where the sublime connects with resistance to rule, and beauty
connects with conservative acceptance of existing forms or structures of
society.
subsidiarity, a basic
principle of social order and the common good governing the relations between
the higher and lower associations in a political community. Positively, the
principle of subsidiarity holds that the common good, i.e., the ensemble of
social resources and institutions that facilitate human self-realization,
depends on fostering the free, creative initiatives of individuals and of their
voluntary associations; thus, the state, in addition to its direct role in
maintaining public good which comprises justice, public peace, and public
morality also has an indirect role in promoting other aspects of the common
good by rendering assistance subsidium to those individuals and associations
whose activities facilitate cooperative human self-realization in work, play,
the arts, sciences, and religion. Negatively, the principle of subsidiarity holds
that higher-level i.e., more comprehensive associations while they must monitor, regulate, and
coordinate ought not to absorb, replace,
or undermine the free initiatives and activities of lower-level associations
and individuals insofar as these are not contrary to the common good. This
presumption favoring free individual and social initiative has been defended on
various grounds, such as the inefficiency of burdening the state with myriad
local concerns, as well as the corresponding efficiency of unleashing the free,
creative potential of subordinate groups and individuals who build up the
shared economic, scientific, and artistic resources of society. But the deeper
ground for this presumption is the view subjunctive conditional subsidiarity
886 886 that human flourishing depends
crucially on freedom for individual self-direction and for the self-government
of voluntary associations and that human beings flourish best through their own
personal and cooperative initiatives rather than as the passive consumers or
beneficiaries of the initiatives of others.
subsistence translation
of German Bestand, in current philosophy, especially Meinong’s system, the kind
of being that belongs to “ideal” objects such as mathematical objects, states
of affairs, and abstractions like similarity and difference. By contrast, the
kind of being that belongs to “real” wirklich objects, things of the sorts
investigated by the sciences other than psychology and pure mathematics, is
called existence Existenz. Existence and subsistence together exhaust the realm
of being Sein. So, e.g., the subsistent ideal figures whose properties are
investigated by geometers do not exist
they are nowhere to be found in the real world but it is no less true of them that they have
being than it is of an existent physical object: there are such figures. Being
does not, however, exhaust the realm of objects or things. The psychological
phenomenon of intentionality shows that there are in some sense of ‘there are’
objects that neither exist nor subsist. Every intentional state is directed
toward an object. Although one may covet the Hope Diamond or desire the
unification of Europe, one may also covet a non-existent material object or
desire a non-subsistent state of affairs. If one covets a non-existent diamond,
there is in some sense of ‘there is’ something that one covets one’s state of mind has an object and it has certain properties: it is, e.g., a
diamond. It may therefore be said to inhabit the realm of Sosein ‘being thus’
or ‘predication’ or ‘having properties’, which is the category comprising the
totality of objects. Objects that do not have any sort of being, either
existence or subsistence, belong to non-being Nichtsein. In general, the
properties of an object do not determine whether it has being or non-being. But
there are special cases: the round square, by its very nature, cannot subsist.
Meinong thus maintains that objecthood is ausserseiend, i.e., independent of both
existence and subsistence.
substance, as defined by
Aristotle in the Categories, that which is neither predicable “sayable” of
anything nor present in anything as an aspect or property of it. The examples
he gives are an individual man and an individual horse. We can predicate being
a horse of something but not a horse; nor is a horse in something else. He also
held that only substances can remain self-identical through change. All other
things are accidents of substances and exist only as aspects, properties, or
relations of substances, or kinds of substances, which Aristotle called
secondary substances. An example of an accident would be the color of an
individual man, and an example of a secondary substance would be his being a
man. For Locke, a substance is that part of an individual thing in which its
properties inhere. Since we can observe, indeed know, only a thing’s
properties, its substance is unknowable. Locke’s sense is obviously rooted in
Aristotle’s but the latter carries no skeptical implications. In fact, Locke’s
sense is closer in meaning to what Aristotle calls matter, and would be better
regarded as a synonym of ‘substratum’, as indeed it is by Locke. Substance may
also be conceived as that which is capable of existing independently of
anything else. This sense is also rooted in Aristotle’s, but, understood quite
strictly, leads to Spinoza’s view that there can be only one substance, namely,
the totality of reality or God. A fourth sense of ‘substance’ is the common,
ordinary sense, ‘what a thing is made of’. This sense is related to Locke’s,
but lacks the latter’s skeptical implications. It also corresponds to what
Aristotle meant by matter, at least proximate matter, e.g., the bronze of a
bronze statue Aristotle analyzes individual things as composites of matter and
form. This notion of matter, or stuff, has great philosophical importance,
because it expresses an idea crucial to both our ordinary and our scientific
understandings of the world. Philosophers such as Hume who deny the existence
of substances hold that individual things are mere bundles of properties,
namely, the properties ordinarily attributed to them, and usually hold that
they are incapable of change; they are series of momentary events, rather than
things enduring through time.
substantialism, the view
that the primary, most fundamental entities are substances, everything else
being dependent for its existence on them, either as a property of them or a
relation between them. Different versions of the view would correspond to the
different senses of the word ‘substance’.
substitutivity salva
veritate, a condition met by two expressions when one is substitutable for the
other at a certain occurrence in a sentence and the truth-value truth or
falsity of the sentence is necessarily unchanged when the substitution is made.
In such a case the two expressions are said to exhibit substitutivity or
substitutability salva veritate literally, ‘with truth saved’ with respect to
one another in that context. The expressions are also said to be
interchangeable or intersubstitutable salva veritate in that context. Where it
is obvious from a given discussion that it is the truth-value that is to be
preserved, it may be said that the one expression is substitutable for the
other or exhibits substitutability with respect to the other at that place.
Leibniz proposed to use the universal interchangeability salva veritate of two
terms in every “proposition” in which they occur as a necessary and sufficient condition
for identity presumably for the identity
of the things denoted by the terms. There are apparent exceptions to this
criterion, as Leibniz himself noted. If a sentence occurs in a context governed
by a psychological verb such as ‘believe’ or ‘desire’, by an expression
conveying modality e.g., ‘necessarily’, ‘possibly’, or by certain temporal
expressions such as ‘it will soon be the case that’, then two terms may denote
the same thing but not be interchangeable within such a sentence. Occurrences
of expressions within quotation marks or where the expressions are both
mentioned and used cf. Quine’s example, “Giorgione was so-called because of his
size” also exhibit failure of substitutivity. Frege urged that such failures
are to be explained by the fact that within such contexts an expression does
not have its ordinary denotation but denotes instead either its usual sense or
the expression itself.
Sufism from Arabic fufi,
‘mystic’, Islamic mysticism. The Arabic word is tafawwuf. The philosophically
significant aspects of Sufism are its psychology in its early phase and its
epistemology and ontology in its later phase. The early practices of
asceticism, introspection, and meditation on God and the hereafter as depicted
in the Koran eventually developed in classical Sufism eightheleventh centuries
into the spiritual journey of the mystic, the successive stages of which were
described with a sophisticated psychological terminology. Sufis differentiated
two levels of spiritual attainment: the first was that of “stations” maqamat
that were reached through individual effort, abnegation, and spiritual
exercises e.g., tawakkul, ‘selfless trust in God’, fabr, ‘patience’, etc.. The
characteristic they all shared was that the Sufi, through an act of the will
and deliberate deeds, suppressed his individual ego and its concomitant
attachment to worldly things and emotions in order to become receptive to the
following level of “states” ahwal, which were vouchsafed to him through God’s
grace. These culminated in the goal of the mystical quest, the final states of
bliss, which were variously identified by Sufis, according to their
proclivities, as love mahabba, later ‘ishq, mystical knowledge ma‘rifa, and the
total loss of ego consciousness and the concomitant absorption and subsistence
in and through God fana’ and baqa’. The language describing these stages and
states was allusive and symbolical rather than descriptive. Sufism, which was
viewed initially with suspicion by the authorities and the orthodox, was
substance-function Sufism 888 888
integrated into mainstream belief in the eleventh century, primarily through
the work of al-Ghazali d.1111. After al-Ghazali, the theoretical and practical
aspects of Sufism, which had previously gone hand in hand, developed in different
ways. At the popular level, Sufi practices and instruction were
institutionalized in fraternities and orders that, ever since, have played a
vital role in all Islamic societies, especially among the disenfranchised. Life
in the orders revolved around the regimented initiation of the novices to the
Sufi path by the master. Although theoretical instruction was also given, the
goal of the mystic was primarily achieved by spiritual practices, chiefly the
repetition of religious formulas dhikr. Among the intellectuals, Sufism
acquired a philosophical gloss and terminology. All the currents of earlier
Sufism, as well as elements of Neoplatonic emanationism drawn from Arabic
philosophy, were integrated into a complex and multifaceted system of
“theosophy” in the monumental work of Ibn ‘Arabid.1240. This system rests on
the pivotal concept of “unity of being” wahdat al-wujud, according to which God
is the only being and the only reality, while the entire creation constitutes a
series of his dynamic and continuous self-manifestations. The individual who
combines in himself the totality of these manifestations to become the
prototype of creation, as well as the medium through which God can be known, is
the Perfect Man, identified with the Prophet Muhammad. The mystic’s quest
consists of an experiential epistemological retracing of the levels of
manifestations back to their origin and culminates in the closest possible
approximation to the level of the Perfect Man. Ibn ‘Arabi’s mystical thought,
which completely dominated Sufism, found expression in later times primarily in
the poetry of the various Islamic languages, while certain aspects of it were
reintroduced into Arabic philosophy in Safavid times.
summum bonum Latin,
‘highest good’, that in relation to which all other things have at most
instrumental value value only insofar as they are productive of what is the
highest good. Philosophical conceptions of the summum bonum have for the most
part been teleological in character. That is, they have identified the highest
good in terms of some goal or goals that human beings, it is supposed, pursue
by their very nature. These natural goals or ends have differed considerably.
For the theist, this end is God; for the rationalist, it is the rational
comprehension of what is real; for hedonism, it is pleasure; etc. The highest
good, however, need not be teleologically construed. It may simply be posited,
or supposed, that it is known, through some intuitive process, that a certain
type of thing is “intrinsically good.” On such a view, the relevant contrast is
not so much between what is good as an end and what is good as a means to this
end, as between what is good purely in itself and what is good only in
combination with certain other elements the “extrinsically good”. Perhaps the
best example of such a view of the highest good would be the position of Moore.
Must the summum bonum be just one thing, or one kind of thing? Yes, to this
extent: although one could certainly combine pluralism the view that there are
many, irreducibly different goods with an assertion that the summum bonum is
“complex,” the notion of the highest good has typically been the province of
monists believers in a single good, not pluralists. J.A.M. summum genus.
Sung Hsing, also called
Sung Tzu c.360290 B.C., Chinese philosopher associated with Mohism and the
HuangLao school. He was a member of the Chi-hsia Academy of Ch’i, a late
Warring States center that attracted intellectuals of every persuasion. His
Mohist ideas include an emphasis on utility, thrift, meritocracy, and a
reluctance to wage war. He is praised by the Taoist Chuang Tzu for his beliefs
that one’s essential desires and needs are few and that one should heed
internal cultivation rather than social judgments. The combination of internal tranquillity
and political activism is characteristic of HuangLao thought.
sunyata Sanskrit,
‘emptiness’, a property said by some Indian Buddhist philosophers to be
possessed necessarily by everything that exists. If something is empty it
possesses no essential or inherent nature svabhava, which is to say that both
its existence and its nature are dependent on things or events other than
itself. The thesis ‘everything is empty’ is therefore approximately equivalent
to ‘everything is causally dependent’; the contradictories of these theses were
typically argued by defenders of emptiness to be incoherent and thus not worthy
of assent. To deny emptiness was also taken to require the affirmasuicide,
assisted sunyata 889 889 tion of permanence
and non-contingency: if something is non-empty in any respect, it is in just
that respect permanent and non-contingent.
Sun Yat-sen 18661925,
Chinese statesman, founder of the Republic of China in 1911. Educated as a
medical doctor in England, he became a revolutionary to end the reign of the
last dynasty in China. He founded the Nationalist Party and developed the
so-called Three People’s Principles: the nationalist, democratic, and socialist
principles. He claimed to be transmitting the Confucian Way. Sun adopted a
policy of cooperation with the Communists, but his successor Chiang Kai-shek
18871975 broke with them. He is now also honored on the mainland as a bourgeois
social democrat paving the way for the Communist Revolution.
supererogation, the
property of going beyond the call of duty. Supererogatory actions are sometimes
equated with actions that are morally good in the sense that they are
encouraged by morality but not required by it. Sometimes they are equated with
morally commendable actions, i.e., actions that indicate a superior moral
character. It is quite common for morally good actions to be morally
commendable and vice versa, so that it is not surprising that these two kinds
of supererogatory actions are not clearly distinguished even though they are
quite distinct. Certain kinds of actions are not normally considered to be
morally required, e.g., giving to charity, though morality certainly encourages
doing them. However, if one is wealthy and gives only a small amount to
charity, then, although one’s act is supererogatory in the sense of being
morally good, it is not supererogatory in the sense of being morally
commendable, for it does not indicate a superior moral character. Certain kinds
of actions are normally morally required, e.g., keeping one’s promises.
However, when the harm or risk of harm of keeping one’s promise is sufficiently
great compared to the harm caused by breaking the promise to excuse breaking
the promise, then keeping one’s promise counts as a supererogatory act in the
sense of being morally commendable. Some versions of consequentialism claim
that everyone is always morally required to act so as to bring about the best
consequences. On such a theory there are no actions that are morally encouraged
but not required; thus, for those holding such theories, if there are
supererogatory acts, they must be morally commendable. Many versions of
non-consequentialism also fail to provide for acts that are morally encouraged
but not morally required; thus, if they allow for supererogatory acts, they
must regard them as morally required acts done at such significant personal
cost that one might be excused for not doing them. The view that all actions
are either morally required, morally prohibited, or morally indifferent makes
it impossible to secure a place for supererogatory acts in the sense of morally
good acts. This view that there are no acts that are morally encouraged but not
morally required may be the result of misleading terminology. Both Kant and
Mill distinguish between duties of perfect obligation and duties of imperfect
obligation, acknowledging that a duty of imperfect obligation does not specify
any particular act that one is morally required to do. However, since they use
the term ‘duty’ it is very easy to view all acts falling under these “duties”
as being morally required. One way of avoiding the view that all morally
encouraged acts are morally required is to avoid the common philosophical
misuse of the term ‘duty’. One can replace ‘duties of perfect obligation’ with
‘actions required by moral rules’ and ‘duties of imperfect obligation’ with
‘actions encouraged by moral ideals’. However, a theory that includes the kinds
of acts that are supererogatory in the sense of being morally good has to
distinguish between that sense of ‘supererogatory’ and the sense meaning
‘morally commendable’, i.e., indicating a superior moral character in the
agent. For as pointed out above, not all morally good acts are morally
commendable, nor are all morally commendable acts morally good, even though a
particular act may be supererogatory in both senses.
supervenience, a
dependence relation between properties or facts of one type, and properties or
facts of another type. Moore, for instance, held that the property intrinsic
value is dependent in the relevant way on certain non-moral properties although
he did not employ the word ‘supervenience’. As he put it, “if a given thing
possesses any kind of intrinsic value in a certain degree, then not only must
that same thing possess it, under all circumstances, in the same degree, but
also anything exactly like it, must, under all circumstances, possess it in
exactly the same degree” Philosophical Studies, 1922. The concept of
supervenience, as a relation between properties, is essentially this:
Properties of type A are supervenient on properties of type B if and only if
two objects cannot differ with respect to their A-properties without also
differing with respect to their B-properties. Properties that allegedly are
supervenient on others are often called consequential properties, especially in
ethics; the idea is that if something instantiates a moral property, then it
does so in virtue of, i.e., as a non-causal consequence of, instantiating some
lower-level property on which the moral property supervenes. In another,
related sense, supervenience is a feature of discourse of one type, vis-à-vis
discourse of another type. The term was so used, again in connection with
morals, by Hare, who wrote: First, let us take that characteristic of “good”
which has been called its supervenience. Suppose that we say, “St. Francis was
a good man.” It is logically impossible to say this and to maintain at the same
time that there might have been another man placed exactly in the same
circumstances as St. Francis, and who behaved in exactly the same way, but who
differed from St. Francis in this respect only, that he was not a good man. The
Language of Morals, 1952 Here the idea is that it would be a misuse of moral
language, a violation of the “logic of moral discourse,” to apply ‘good’ to one
thing but not to something else exactly similar in all pertinent non-moral
respects. Hare is a metaethical irrealist: he denies that there are moral
properties or facts. So for him, moral supervenience is a feature of moral
discourse and judgment, not a relation between properties or facts of two
types. The notion of supervenience has come to be used quite widely in
metaphysics and philosophy of mind, usually in the first sense explained above.
This use was heralded by Davidson in articulating a position about the relation
between physical and mental properties, or statetypes, that eschews the
reducibility of mental properties to physical ones. He wrote: Although the
position I describe denies there are psychophysical laws, it is consistent with
the view that mental characteristics are in some sense dependent, or
supervenient, on physical characteristics. Such supervenience might be taken to
mean that there cannot be two events alike in all physical respects but differing
in some mental respects, or that an object cannot alter in some mental respects
without altering in some physical respects. Dependence or supervenience of this
kind does not entail reducibility through law or definition. “Mental Events,”
1970 A variety of supervenience theses have been propounded in metaphysics and
philosophy of mind, usually although not always in conjunction with attempts to
formulate metaphysical positions that are naturalistic, in some sense, without
being strongly reductionistic. For instance, it is often asserted that mental
properties and facts are supervenient on neurobiological properties, and/or on
physicochemical properties and facts. And it is often claimed, more generally,
that all properties and facts are supervenient on the properties and facts of
the kind described by physics. Much attention has been directed at how to
formulate the desired supervenience theses, and thus how to characterize
supervenience itself. A distinction has been drawn between weak supervenience,
asserting that in any single possible world w, any two individuals in w that
differ in their A-properties also differ in their B-properties; and strong
supervenience, asserting that for any two individuals i and j, either within a
single possible world or in two distinct ones, if i and j differ in
A-properties then they also differ in Bproperties. It is sometimes alleged that
traditional formulations of supervenience, like Moore’s or Hare’s, articulate
only weak supervenience, whereas strong supervenience is needed to express the
relevant kind of determination or dependence. It is sometimes replied, however,
superset supervenience 891 891 that the
traditional natural-language formulations do in fact express strong supervenience and that formalizations expressing mere weak
supervenience are mistranslations. Questions about how best to formulate
supervenience theses also arise in connection with intrinsic and non-intrinsic
properties. For instance, the property being a bank, instantiated by the brick
building on Main Street, is not supervenient on intrinsic physical properties
of the building itself; rather, the building’s having this social-institutional
property depends on a considerably broader range of facts and features, some of
which are involved in subserving the social practice of banking. The term
‘supervenience base’ is frequently used to denote the range of entities and
happenings whose lowerlevel properties and relations jointly underlie the
instantiation of some higher-level property like being a bank by some
individual like the brick building on Main Street. Supervenience theses are
sometimes formulated so as to smoothly accommodate properties and facts with
broad supervenience bases. For instance, the idea that the physical facts
determine all the facts is sometimes expressed as global supervenience, which
asserts that any two physically possible worlds differing in some respect also
differ in some physical respect. Or, sometimes this idea is expressed as the
stronger thesis of regional supervenience, which asserts that for any two
spatiotemporal regions r and s, either within a single physically possible
world or in two distinct ones, if r and s differ in some intrinsic respect then
they also differ in some intrinsic physical respect.
suppositio Latin,
‘supposition’, in the Middle Ages, reference. The theory of supposition, the
central notion in the theory of proprietates terminorum, was developed in the
twelfth century, and was refined and discussed into early modern times. It has
two parts their names are a modern convenience. 1 The theory of supposition
proper. This typically divided suppositio into “personal” reference to
individuals not necessarily to persons, despite the name, “simple” reference to
species or genera, and “material” reference to spoken or written expressions.
Thus ‘man’ in ‘Every man is an animal’ has personal supposition, in ‘Man is a
species’ simple supposition, and in ‘Man is a monosyllable’ material
supposition. The theory also included an account of how the range of a term’s reference
is affected by tense and by modal factors. 2 The theory of “modes” of personal
supposition. This part of supposition theory divided personal supposition
typically into “discrete” ‘Socrates’ in ‘Socrates is a man’, “determinate”
‘man’ in ‘Some man is a Grecian’, “confused and distributive” ‘man’ in ‘Every
man is an animal’, and “merely confused” ‘animal’ in ‘Every man is an animal’.
The purpose of this second part of the theory is a matter of some dispute. By
the late fourteenth century, it had in some authors become a theory of
quantification. The term ‘suppositio’ was also used in the Middle Ages in the
ordinary sense, to mean ‘assumption’, ‘hypothesis’.
survival, continued
existence after one’s biological death. So understood, survival can pertain
only to beings that are organisms at some time or other, not to beings that are
disembodied at all times as angels are said to be or to beings that are
embodied but never as organisms as might be said of computers. Theories that
maintain that one’s individual consciousness is absorbed into a universal
consciousness after death or that one continues to exist only through one’s
descendants, insofar as they deny one’s own continued existence as an
individual, are not theories of survival. Although survival does not entail
immortality or anything about reward or punishment in an afterlife, many
theories of survival incorporate these features. Theories about survival have
expressed differing attitudes about the importance of the body. supervenient
behaviorism survival 892 892 Some
philosophers have maintained that persons cannot survive without their own
bodies, typically espousing a doctrine of resurrection; such a view was held by
Aquinas. Others, including the Pythagoreans, have believed that one can survive
in other bodies, allowing for reincarnation into a body of the same species or
even for transmigration into a body of another species. Some, including Plato
and perhaps the Pythagoreans, have claimed that no body is necessary, and that
survival is fully achieved by one’s escaping embodiment. There is a similar
spectrum of opinion about the importance of one’s mental life. Some, such as
Locke, have supposed that survival of the same person would require memory of
one’s having experienced specific past events. Plato’s doctrine of
recollection, in contrast, supposes that one can survive without any
experiential memory; all that one typically is capable of recollecting are
impersonal necessary truths. Philosophers have tested the relative importance
of bodily versus mental factors by means of various thought experiments, of
which the following is typical. Suppose that a person’s whole mental life memories, skills, and character traits were somehow duplicated into a data bank and
erased from the person, leaving a living radical amnesiac. Suppose further that
the person’s mental life were transcribed into another radically amnesiac body.
Has the person survived, and if so, as whom?
sutra from Sanskrit
sutra, ‘thread’, ‘precept’, a single verse or aphorism of Hindu or Buddhist
teaching, or a collection of them. Written to be memorized, they provide a
means of encoding and transmitting laws and rules of grammar, ritual, poetic
meter, and philosophical disputation. Typically using technical terms and
written so as to be mnemonic, they serve well for passing on information in an
oral tradition. What makes them serviceable for this purpose also makes them
largely unintelligible without commentary. The sutra style is typical in
philosophical traditions. The Brahma-Sutras of Badharana are an example of a
set of sutras regarded as authoritative by Vedanta but interpreted in vastly
different ways by Shankara, Ramanuja, and Madhva. The sutras associated with
Buddhism typically are more expansive than those associated with Hinduism, and
thus more intelligible on their own. The Tripitaka “Basket of the Teachings” is
a collection of sutras that Buddhist tradition ascribes to Ananda, who is said
to have recited them from memory at the first Buddhist council; each sutra is introduced
by the words ‘Thus have I heard’. Sutras are associated with Theravada as well
as Mahayana Buddhism and deal with both religious and philosophical topics.
K.E.Y. Swedenborgianism, the theosophy professed by a worldwide movement
established as the New Jerusalem Church in London in 1788 by the followers of
Emanuel Swedenborg 16881772, a Swedish natural philosopher, visionary, and
biblical exegete. Author of geological and cosmological works, he fused the
rationalist Cartesian and empiricist Lockean legacies into a natural philosophy
Principia Rerum Naturalium, 1734 that propounded the harmony of the mechanistic
universe with biblical revelation. Inspired by Liebniz, Malebranche, Platonism,
and Neoplatonism, he unfolded a doctrine of correspondence A Hieroglyphic Key,
1741 to account for the relation between body and soul and between the natural
and spiritual worlds, and applied it to biblical exegesis. What attracted the
wide following of the “Spirit-Seer” were his theosophic speculations in the
line of Boehme and the mystical, prophetic tradition in which he excelled
Heavenly Arcana, 174956. J.-L.S. Swinburne, Richard b.1934, British philosopher
of religion and of science. In philosophy of science, he has contributed to
confirmation theory and to the philosophy of space and time. His work in
philosophy of religion is the most ambitious project in philosophical theology
undertaken by a British philosopher in the twentieth century. Its first part is
a trilogy on the coherence and justification of theistic belief and the
rationality of living by that belief: The Coherence of Theism 1977, The
Existence of God 1979, and Faith and Reason 1981. Since 1985, when Swinburne
became Nolloth Professor of the Philosophy of the Christian Religion at the of Oxford, he has written a tetralogy about
some of the most central of the distinctively Christian religious doctrines:
Responsibility and Atonement 1989, Revelation 1992, The Christian God 1994, and
Providence and the Problem of Evil 1998. The most interesting feature of the
trilogy is its contribution to natural theology. Using Bayesian reasoning,
Swinburne builds a cumulative case for theism by arguing that its probability
is raised sustaining cause Swinburne, Richard 893 893 by such things as the existence of the universe,
its order, the existence of consciousness, human opportunities to do good, the
pattern of history, evidence of miracles, and religious experience. The
existence of evil does not count against the existence of God. On our total
evidence theism is more probable than not. In the tetralogy he explicates and
defends such Christian doctrines as original sin, the Atonement, Heaven, Hell,
the Trinity, the Incarnation, and Providence. He also analyzes the grounds for
supposing that some Christian doctrines are revealed truths, and argues for a
Christian theodicy in response to the problem of evil.
.
syllogism, in Aristotle’s
words, “a discourse in which, a certain thing being stated, something other
than what is stated follows of necessity from being so” Prior Analytics, 24b
18. Three types of syllogism were usually distinguished: categorical,
hypothetical, and disjunctive. Each will be treated in that order. The
categorical syllogism. This is an argument consisting of three categorical
propositions, two serving as premises and one serving as conclusion. E.g.,
‘Some students are happy; all students are high school graduates;
therefore, some high school graduates are happy’. If a syllogism is valid, the
premises must be so related to the conclusion that it is impossible for both
premises to be true and the conclusion false. There are four types of
categorical propositions: universal affirmative or A-propositions ‘All S are P’, or ‘SaP’; universal negative
or E-propositions ‘No S are P’, or
‘SeP’; particular affirmative or I-propositions
‘Some S are P’, or ‘SiP’; and particular negative or O-propositions:
‘Some S are not P’, or ‘SoP’. The mediate basic components of categorical
syllogism are terms serving as subjects or predicates in the premises and the
conclusion. There must be three and only three terms in any categorical
syllogism, the major term, the minor term, and the middle term. Violation of
this basic rule of structure is called the fallacy of four terms quaternio
terminorum; e.g., ‘Whatever is right is useful; only one of my hands is right;
therefore only one of my hands is useful’. Here ‘right’ does not have the same
meaning in its two occurrences; we therefore have more than three terms and
hence no genuine categorical syllogism. The syllogistic terms are identifiable
and definable with reference to the position they have in a given syllogism.
The predicate of the conclusion is the major term; the subject of the
conclusion is the minor term; the term that appears once in each premise but
not in the conclusion is the middle term. As it is used in various types of
categorical propositions, a term is either distributed stands for each and
every member of its extension or undistributed. There is a simple rule
regarding the distribution: universal propositions SaP and SeP distribute their
subject terms; negative propositions SeP and SoP distribute their predicate
terms. No terms are distributed in an I-proposition. Various sets of rules governing
validity of categorical syllogisms have been offered. The following is a
“traditional” set from the popular Port-Royal Logic 1662. R1: The middle term
must be distributed at least once. Violation: ‘All cats are animals; some
animals do not eat liver; therefore some cats do not eat liver’. The middle
term ‘animals’ is not distributed either in the first or minor premise, being
the predicate of an affirmative proposition, nor in the second or major
premise, being the subject of a particular proposition; hence, the fallacy of
undistributed middle. R2: A term cannot be distributed in the conclusion if it
is undistributed in the premises. Violation: ‘All dogs are carnivorous; no
flowers are dogs; therefore, no flowers are carnivorous’. Here the major, ‘carnivorous’,
is distributed in the conclusion, being the predicate of a negative
proposition, but not in the premise, serving there as predicate of an
affirmative proposition; hence, the fallacy of illicit major term. Another
violation of R2: ‘All students are happy individuals; no criminals are
students; therefore, no happy individuals are criminals’. Here the minor,
‘happy individuals’, is distributed in the conclusion, but not distributed in
the minor premise; hence the fallacy of illicit minor term. R3: No conclusion
may be drawn from two negative premises. Violation: ‘No dogs are cats; some
dogs do not like liver; therefore, some cats do not like liver’. Here R1 is
satisfied, since the middle term ‘dogs’ is distributed in the minor premise; R2
is satisfied, since both the minor term ‘cats’ as well as the major term
‘things that like liver’ are distributed in the premises and thus no violation
of distribution of terms occurs. It is only by virtue of R3 that we can
proclaim this syllogism to be invalid. R4: A negative conclusion cannot be
drawn where both premises are affirmative. Violation: ‘All educated people take
good care of their children; all syllogism syllogism 894 894 who take good care of their children are
poor; therefore, some poor people are not educated’. Here, it is only by virtue
of the rule of quality, R4, that we can proclaim this syllogism invalid. R5:
The conclusion must follow the weaker premise; i.e., if one of the premises is
negative, the conclusion must be negative, and if one of them is particular,
the conclusion must be particular. R6: From two particular premises nothing
follows. Let us offer an indirect proof for this rule. If both particular
premises are affirmative, no term is distributed and therefore the fallacy of
undistributed middle is inevitable. To avoid it, we have to make one of the
premises negative, which will result in a distributed predicate as middle term.
But by R5, the conclusion must then be negative; thus, the major term will be
distributed in the conclusion. To avoid violating R2, we must distribute that
term in the major premise. It could not be in the position of subject term,
since only universal propositions distribute their subject term and, by
hypothesis, both premises are particular. But we could not use the same
negative premise used to distribute the middle term; we must make the other
particular premise negative. But then we violate R3. Thus, any attempt to make
a syllogism with two particular premises valid will violate one or more basic
rules of syllogism. This set of rules assumes that A- and Epropositions have
existential import and hence that an I- or an O-proposition may legitimately be
drawn from a set of exclusively universal premises. Categorical syllogisms are
classified according to figure and mood. The figure of a categorical syllogism
refers to the schema determined by the possible position of the middle term in
relation to the major and minor terms. In “modern logic,” four syllogistic
figures are recognized. Using ‘M’ for middle term, ‘P’ for major term, and ‘S’
for minor term, they can be depicted as follows: Aristotle recognized only
three syllogistic figures. He seems to have taken into account just the two
premises and the extension of the three terms occurring in them, and then asked
what conclusion, if any, can be derived from those premises. It turns out,
then, that his procedure leaves room for three figures only: one in which the M
term is the subject of one and predicate of the other premise; another in which
the M term is predicated in both premises; and a third one in which the M term
is the subject in both premises. Medievals followed him, although all
considered the so-called inverted first i.e., moods of the first figure with
their conclusion converted either simply or per accidens to be legitimate also.
Some medievals e.g., Albalag and most moderns since Leibniz recognize a fourth
figure as a distinct figure, considering syllogistic terms on the basis not of
their extension but of their position in the conclusion, the S term of the
conclusion being defined as the minor term and the P term being defined as the
major term. The mood of a categorical syllogism refers to the configuration of
types of categorical propositions determined on the basis of the quality and
quantity of the propositions serving as premises and conclusion of any given
syllogism; e.g., ‘No animals are plants; all cats are animals; therefore no
cats are plants’, ‘MeP, SaM /, SeP’, is a syllogism in the mood EAE in the
first figure. ‘All metals conduct electricity; no stones conduct electricity;
therefore no stones are metals’, ‘PaM, SeM /, SeP’, is the mood AEE in the
second figure. In the four syllogistic figures there are 256 possible moods,
but only 24 are valid only 19 in modern logic, on the ground of a non-existential
treatment of A- and E-propositions. As a mnemonic device and to facilitate
reference, names have been assigned to the valid moods, with each vowel
representing the type of categorical proposition. William Sherwood and Peter of
Spain offered the famous list designed to help students to remember which moods
in any given figure are valid and how the “inevident” moods in the second and
third figures are provable by reduction to those in the first figure: barbara,
celarent, darii, ferio direct Fig. 1; baralipton, celantes, dabitis, fapesmo,
frisesomorum indirect Fig. 1; cesare, camestres, festino, baroco Fig. 2;
darapti, felapton, disamis, datisi, bocardo, ferison Fig. 3. The hypothetical
syllogism. The pure hypothetical syllogism is an argument in which both the
premises and the conclusion are hypothetical, i.e. conditional, propositions;
e.g., ‘If the sun is shining, it is warm; if it is warm, the plants will grow;
therefore if the sun is shining, the plants will grow’. Symbolically, this
argument form can be represented by ‘A P B, B P C /, A P C’. It was not
recognized as such by Aristotle, but Aristotle’s pupil Theophrastus
foreshadowed it, even syllogism syllogism 895
895 though it is not clear from his example of it ‘If man is, animal is; if animal is, then
substance is; if therefore man is, substance is’ whether this was seen to be a principle of
term logic or a principle of propositional logic. It was the MegaricStoic
philosophers and Boethius who fully recognized hypothetical propositions and
syllogisms as principles of the most general theory of deduction. Mixed
hypothetical syllogisms are arguments consisting of a hypothetical premise and
a categorical premise, and inferring a categorical proposition; e.g., ‘If the
sun is shining, the plants will grow; the sun is shining; therefore the plants
will grow’. Symbolically, this is represented by ‘P P Q, P /, Q’. This argument
form was explicitly formulated in ancient times by the Stoics as one of the
“indemonstrables” and is now known as modus ponens. Another equally basic form
of mixed hypothetical syllogism is ‘P P Q, -Q /, ~P’, known as modus tollens.
The disjunctive syllogism. This is an argument in which the leading premise is
a disjunction, the other premise being a denial of one of the alternatives,
concluding to the remaining alternative; e.g., ‘It is raining or I will go for
a walk; but it is not raining; therefore I will go for a walk’. It is not
always clear whether the ‘or’ of the disjunctive premise is inclusive or
exclusive. Symbolic logic removes the ambiguity by using two different symbols
and thus clearly distinguishes between inclusive or weak disjunction, ‘P 7 Q’,
which is true provided not both alternatives are false, and exclusive or strong
disjunction, ‘P W Q’, which is true provided exactly one alternative is true
and exactly one false. The definition of ‘disjunctive syllogism’ presupposes
that the lead premise is an inclusive or weak disjunction, on the basis of
which two forms are valid: ‘P 7 Q, -P /, Q’ and ‘P 7 Q, -Q /, P’. If the
disjunctive premise is exclusive, we have four valid argument forms, and we
should speak here of an exclusive disjunctive syllogism. This is defined as an
argument in which either from an exclusive disjunction and the denial of one of
its disjuncts we infer the remaining disjunct
’P W Q, -P /,Q’, and ‘P W Q, -Q /, P’ modus tollendo ponens; or else,
from an exclusive disjunction and one of its disjuncts we infer the denial of
the remaining disjunct ’P W Q, P /, -Q’,
and ‘P W Q, Q /,-P’ modus ponendo tollens.
synaesthesia, a conscious
experience in which qualities normally associated with one sensory modality are
or seem to be sensed in another. Examples include auditory and tactile visions
such as “loud sunlight” and “soft moonlight” as well as visual bodily
sensations such as “dark thoughts” and “bright smiles.” Two features of
synaesthesia are of philosophic interest. First, the experience may be used to
judge the appropriateness of sensory metaphors and similes, such as
Baudelaire’s “sweet as oboes.” The metaphor is appropriate just when oboes
sound sweet. Second, synaesthesia challenges the manner in which common sense
distinguishes among the external senses. It is commonly acknowledged that
taste, e.g., is not only unlike hearing, smell, or any other sense, but differs
from them because taste involves gustatory rather than auditory experiences. In
synaesthesia, however, one might taste sounds sweet-sounding oboes. G.A.G.
syncategoremata, 1 in grammar, words that cannot serve by themselves as subjects
or predicates of categorical propositions. The opposite is categoremata, words
that can do this. For example, ‘and’, ‘if’, ‘every’, ‘because’, ‘insofar’, and
‘under’ are syncategorematic terms, whereas ‘dog’, ‘smooth’, and ‘sings’ are
categorematic ones. This usage comes from the fifth-century Latin grammarian
Priscian. It seems to have been the original way of drawing the distinction,
and to have persisted through later periods along syllogism, demonstrative
syncategoremata 896 896 with other
usages described below. 2 In medieval logic from the twelfth century on, the
distinction was drawn semantically. Categoremata are words that have a definite
independent signification. Syncategoremata do not have any independent
signification or, according to some authors, not a definite one anyway, but
acquire a signification only when used in a proposition together with
categoremata. The examples used above work here as well. 3 Medieval logic
distinguished not only categorematic and syncategorematic words, but also
categorematic and syncategorematic uses of a single word. The most important is
the word ‘is’, which can be used both categorematically to make an existence
claim ‘Socrates is’ in the sense ‘Socrates exists’ or syncategorematically as a
copula ‘Socrates is a philosopher’. But other words were treated this way too.
Thus ‘whole’ was said to be used syncategorematically as a kind of quantifier
in ‘The whole surface is white’ from which it follows that each part of the
surface is white, but categorematically in ‘The whole surface is two square
feet in area’ from which it does not follow that each part of the surface is
two square feet in area. 4 In medieval logic, again, syncategoremata were
sometimes taken to include words that can serve by themselves as subjects or
predicates of categorical propositions, but may interfere with standard logical
inference patterns when they do. The most notorious example is the word
‘nothing’. If nothing is better than eternal bliss and tepid tea is better than
nothing, still it does not follow by the transitivity of ‘better than’ that
tepid tea is better than eternal bliss. Again, consider the verb ‘begins’.
Everything red is colored, but not everything that begins to be red begins to
be colored it might have been some other color earlier. Such words were
classified as syncategorematic because an analysis called an expositio of
propositions containing them reveals implicit syncategoremata in sense 1 or
perhaps 2. Thus an analysis of ‘The apple begins to be red’ would include the
claim that it was not red earlier, and ‘not’ is syncategorematic in both senses
1 and 2. 5 In modern logic, sense 2 is extended to apply to all logical
symbols, not just to words in natural languages. In this usage, categoremata
are also called “proper symbols” or “complete symbols,” while syncategoremata
are called “improper symbols” or “incomplete symbols.” In the terminology of
modern formal semantics, the meaning of categoremata is fixed by the models for
the language, whereas the meaning of syncategoremata is fixed by specifying
truth conditions for the various formulas of the language in terms of the
models.
synderesis, in medieval
moral theology, conscience. St. Jerome used the term, and it became a fixture
because of Peter Lombard’s inclusion of it in his Sentences. Despite this
origin, ‘synderesis’ is distinguished from ‘conscience’ by Aquinas, for whom
synderesis is the quasi-habitual grasp of the most common principles of the
moral order i.e., natural law, whereas conscience is the application of such
knowledge to fleeting and unrepeatable circumstances. ’Conscience’ is ambiguous
in the way in which ‘knowledge’ is: knowledge can be the mental state of the
knower or what the knower knows. But ‘conscience’, like ‘synderesis’, is
typically used for the mental state. Sometimes, however, conscience is taken to
include general moral knowledge as well as its application here and now; but
the content of synderesis is the most general precepts, whereas the content of
conscience, if general knowledge, will be less general precepts. Since
conscience can be erroneous, the question arises as to whether synderesis and
its object, natural law precepts, can be obscured and forgotten because of bad
behavior or upbringing. Aquinas held that while great attrition can take place,
such common moral knowledge cannot be wholly expunged from the human mind. This
is a version of the Aristotelian doctrine that there are starting points of
knowledge so easily grasped that the grasping of them is a defining mark of the
human being. However perversely the human agent behaves there will remain not
only the comprehensive realization that good is to be done and evil avoided,
but also the recognition of some substantive human goods.
synergism, in Christian
soteriology, the cooperation within human consciousness of free will and divine
grace in the processes of conversion and regeneration. Synergism became an
issue in sixteenth-century Lutheranism during a controversy prompted by Philip
Melanchthon 1497 syncategorematic synergism 897 897 1569. Under the influence of Erasmus,
Melanchthon mentioned, in the 1533 edition of his Common Places, three causes
of good actions: “the Word, the Holy Spirit, and the will.” Advocated by
Pfeffinger, a Philipist, synergism was attacked by the orthodox,
predestinarian, and monergist party, Amsdorf and Flacius, who retorted with
Gnesio-Lutheranism. The ensuing Formula of Concord 1577 officialized monergism.
Synergism occupies a middle position between uncritical trust in human noetic
and salvific capacity Pelagianism and deism and exclusive trust in divine
agency Calvinist and Lutheran fideism. Catholicism, Arminianism, Anglicanism,
Methodism, and nineteenth- and twentieth-century liberal Protestantism have
professed versions of synergism.
systems theory, the transdisciplinary
study of the abstract organization of phenomena, independent of their
substance, type, or spatial or temporal scale of existence. It investigates
both the principles common to all complex entities and the usually mathematical
models that can be used to describe them. Systems theory was proposed in the
1940s by the biologist Ludwig von Bertalanffy and furthered by Ross Ashby
Introduction to Cybernetics, 1956. Von Bertalanffy was both reacting against
reductionism and attempting to revive the unity of science. He emphasized that
real systems are open to, and interact with, their environments, and that they
can acquire qualitatively new properties through emergence, resulting in
continual evolution. Rather than reduce an entity e.g. the human body to the
properties of its parts or elements e.g. organs or cells, systems theory
focuses on the arrangement of and relations among the parts that connect them
into a whole cf. holism. This particular organization determines a system,
which is independent of the concrete substance of the elements e.g. particles,
cells, transistors, people. Thus, the same concepts and principles of
organization underlie the different disciplines physics, biology, technology,
sociology, etc., providing a basis for their unification. Systems concepts
include: system environment boundary, input, output, process, state, hierarchy,
goal-directedness, and information. The developments of systems theory are
diverse Klir, Facets of Systems Science, 1991, including conceptual foundations
and philosophy e.g. the philosophies of Bunge, Bahm, and Laszlo; mathematical
modeling and information theory e.g. the work of Mesarovic and Klir; and
practical applications. Mathematical systems theory arose from the development
of isomorphies between the models of electrical circuits and other systems.
Applications include engineering, computing, ecology, management, and family
psychotherapy. Systems analysis, developed independently of systems theory,
applies systems principles to aid a decision maker with problems of
identifying, reconstructing, optimizing, and controlling a system usually a
socio-technical organization, while taking into account multiple objectives,
constraints, and resources. It aims to specify possible courses of action, together
with their risks, costs, and benefits. Systems theory is closely connected to
cybernetics, and also to system dynamics, which models changes in a network of
synergy systems theory 898 898 coupled
variables e.g. the “world dynamics” models of Jay Forrester and the Club of
Rome. Related ideas are used in the emerging “sciences of complexity,” studying
self-organization and heterogeneous networks of interacting actors, and
associated domains such as far-from-equilibrium thermodynamics, chaotic
dynamics, artificial life, artificial intelligence, neural networks, and
computer modeling and simulation.
Ta-hsüeh, a part of the
Chinese Confucian classic Book of Rites whose title is standardly translated as
Great Learning. Chu Hsi significantly amended the text composed in the third or
second century B.C. and elevated it to the status of an independent classic as
one of the Four Books. He regarded it as a quotation from Confucius and a
commentary by Confucius’s disciple Tseng-tzu, but neither his emendations nor
his interpretation of the text is beyond dispute. The Ta-hsüeh instructs a
ruler in how to bring order to his state by self-cultivation. Much discussion
of the text revolves around the phrase ko wu, which describes the first step in
self-cultivation but is left undefined. The Ta-hsüeh claims that one’s
virtuousness or viciousness is necessarily evident to others, and that virtue
manifests itself first in one’s familial relationships, which then serve as an
exemplar of order in both families and the state.
Tai Chen 172477, Chinese
philologist, philosopher, mathematician, and astronomer. A prominent member of
the K’ao-cheng evidential research School, Tai attacked the Neo-Confucian
dualism of li pattern and ch’i ether, insisting that li is simply the orderly
structure of ch’i. In terms of ethics, li consists of “feelings that do not
err.” In his Meng-tzu tzu-yi shu-cheng “Meanings of Terms in the Mencius
Explained and Attested”, Tai argues for the need to move from mere yi-chien
opinions to pu-te chih-yi undeviating standards by applying the Confucian
golden rule not as a formal principle
determining right action but as a winnowing procedure that culls out improper
desires and allows only proper ones to inform one’s actions. Beginning with tzu
jan natural desires, one tests their universalizability with the golden rule,
thereby identifying those that accord with what is pi-jan necessary. One
spontaneously k’o approves of the “necessary,” and Tai claims this is what
Mencius describes as the “joy” of moral action.
MENCIUS. P.J.I. t’ai-chi, Chinese term meaning ‘Great Ultimate’, an idea
first developed in the “Appended Remarks” of the I-Ching, where it is said that
in the system of Change there is the Great Ultimate. It generates the Two Modes
yin and yang; the Two Modes generate the Four Forms major and minor yin and
yang; and the Four Forms generate the Eight Trigrams. In his “Explanation of
the Diagram of the Great Ultimate,” Chou Tunyi 101773 spoke of “Non-ultimate
wu-chi and also the Great Ultimate!” He generated controversies. Chu Hsi
11301200 approved Chou’s formulation and interpreted t’ai-chi as li principle,
which is formless on the one hand and has principle on the other hand.
T’ang Chün-i 190978,
Chinese philosopher, a leading contemporary New Confucian and cofounder, with
Ch’ien Mu, of New Asia in Hong Kong in
1949. He acknowledged that it was through the influence of Hsiung Shih-li that
he could see the true insights in Chinese philosophy. He drafted a manifesto
published in 1958 and signed by Carsun Chang 18871969, Hsü Fu-kuan, and Mou
Tsung-san. They criticized current sinological studies as superficial and
inadequate, and maintained that China must learn science and democracy from the
West, but the West must also learn human-heartedness and love of harmony and
peace from Chinese culture.
T’an Ssu-t’ung 186498,
Chinese philosopher of the late Ching dynasty, a close associate of K’ang
Yu-wei and Liang Ch’i-ch’ao. He was a syncretist who lumped together
Confucianism, Mohism, Taoism, Buddhism, Christianity, and Western science. His
book on Jen-hsüeh philosophy of humanity identified humanity with ether, a
cosmic force, and gave a new interpreta900 T
900 tion to the unity between nature and humanity. Jen for him is the
source of all existence and creatures; it is none other than reality itself. He
participated in the Hundred Days Reform in 1898 and died a martyr. His personal
example inspired many revolutionaries afterward.
tao, Chinese term meaning
‘path’, ‘way’, ‘account’. From the sense of a literal path, road, or way, the
term comes to mean a way of doing something e.g., living one’s life or
organizing society, especially the way advocated by a particular individual or
school of thought “the way of the Master,” “the way of the Mohists,” etc..
Frequently, it refers to the way of doing something, the right way e.g., “The
Way has not been put into practice for a long time”. Tao also came to refer to
the linguistic account that embodies or describes a way. Finally, in some texts
the tao is a metaphysical entity. For example, in Neo-Confucianism, tao is
identified with li principle. In some contexts it is difficult to tell what
sense is intended.
tao-hsin, jen-hsin,
Chinese terms used by NeoConfucian philosophers to contrast the mind according
to the Way tao-hsin and the mind according to man’s artificial, selfish desires
jenhsin. When one responds spontaneously without making discrimination, one is
acting according to the Way. One is naturally happy, sad, angry, and joyful as
circumstances require. But when one’s self is alienated from the Way, one works
only for self-interest, and the emotions and desires are excessive and deviate
from the Mean. In the Confucian tradition sages and worthies take Heaven as
their model, while common people are urged to take chün-tzu the superior men as
their model. .
Taoism, a Chinese
philosophy identified with the Tao-chia School of the Way, represented by
Chuang Tzu and Lao Tzu. The term may also refer to the HuangLao School;
Neo-Taoists, such as Wang Pi and Kuo Hsiang; and Tao-chiao, a diverse religious
movement. Only the Tao-chia is discussed here. The school derives its name from
the word tao Way, a term used by Chinese thinkers of almost every persuasion.
Taoists were the first to use the term to describe the comprehensive structure
and dynamic of the cosmos. Taoists believe that 1 there is a way the world
should be, a way that, in some deep sense, it is; 2 human beings can understand
this and need to have and follow such knowledge if they and the world are to
exist in harmony; and 3 the world was once in such a state. Most early Chinese
thinkers shared similar beliefs, but Taoists are distinct in claiming that the
Way is not codifiable, indeed is ineffable. Taoists thus are metaphysical and
ethical realists, but epistemological skeptics of an unusual sort, being
language skeptics. Taoists further deny that one can strive successfully to
attain the Way; Taoist self-cultivation is a process not of accumulation but of
paring away. One must unweave the social fabric, forsake one’s cultural
conditioning, and abandon rational thought, to be led instead by one’s tzu jan
spontaneous inclinations. With a hsü tenuous mind, one then will perceive the
li pattern of the cosmos and live by wu wei non-action. Though sharing a strong
family resemblance, the Taoisms of Lao Tzu and Chuang Tzu are distinct. Lao Tzu
advocates a primitive utopianism in which people enjoy the simple life of small
agrarian communities, indifferent to what is happening in the neighboring
village. Having abandoned cultural achievements such as writing, they keep
accounts by knotting cords. Lao Tzu blames human “cleverness,” which imposes
the “human” on the “Heavenly,” for most of what is bad in the world. For him, a
notion like beauty gives rise to its opposite and only serves to increase
anxiety and dissatisfaction; extolling a virtue, such as benevolence, only
encourages people to affect it hypocritically. Lao Tzu advocates “turning back”
to the time when intellect was young and still obedient to intuition and
instinct. To accomplish this, the Taoist sage must rule and enforce this view
upon the clever, if they should “dare to act.” Chuang Tzu emphasizes changing oneself
more than changing society. He too is a kind of anti-rationalist and sees
wisdom as a “knowing how” rather than a “knowing that.” He invokes a repertoire
of skillful individuals as exemplars of the Way. Such individuals engage the
world through a knack that eludes definitive description and display all the
Taoist virtues. Their minds are hsü empty of preconceptions, and so they
perceive the li pattern in each situation. They respond spontaneously and so
are tzu jan; they don’t force things and so practice wu wei. In accord with the
tao, they lead a frictionless existence; they “walk without touching the
ground.”
tao-t’ung, Chinese term meaning ‘the orthodox
line of transmission of the Way’. According to Chu Hsi 11301200, the first to
use this term, the line of transmission can be traced back to ancient
sage-emperors, Confucius and Mencius. The line was broken since Mencius and was
only revived by the Ch’eng brothers in the Sung dynasty. The interesting
feature is that the line has excluded important Confucian scholars such as Hsün
Tzu fl. 298238 B.C. and Tung Chungshu c.179c.104 B.C.. The idea of tao-t’ung
can be traced back to Han Yü 768824 and Mencius.
Tarski, Alfred 190183,
Polish-born American mathematician, logician, and philosopher of logic famous
for his investigations of the concepts of truth and consequence conducted in
the 1930s. His analysis of the concept of truth in syntactically precise, fully
interpreted languages resulted in a definition of truth and an articulate
defense of the correspondence theory of truth. Sentences of the following kind
are now known as Tarskian biconditionals: ‘The sentence “Every perfect number
is even” is true if and only if every perfect number is even.’ One of Tarski’s
major philosophical insights is that each Tarskian biconditional is, in his
words, a partial definition of truth and, consequently, all Tarskian
biconditionals whose right-hand sides exhaust the sentences of a given formal
language together constitute an implicit definition of ‘true’ as applicable to
sentences of that given formal language. This insight, because of its
penetrating depth and disarming simplicity, has become a staple of modern
analytic philosophy. Moreover, it in effect reduced the philosophical problem
of defining truth to the logical problem of constructing a single sentence
having the form of a definition and having as consequences each of the Tarskian
biconditionals. Tarski’s solution to this problem is the famous Tarski truth
definition, versions of which appear in virtually every mathematical logic
text. Tarski’s second most widely recognized philosophical achievement was his
analysis and explication of the concept of consequence. Consequence is
interdefinable with validity as applied to arguments: a given conclusion is a
consequence of a given premise-set if and only if the argument composed of the
given conclusion and the given premise-set is valid; conversely, a given
argument is valid if and only if its conclusion is a consequence of its
premise-set. Shortly after discovering the truth definition, Tarski presented
his “no-countermodels” definition of consequence: a given sentence is a
consequence of a given set of sentences if and only if every model of the set
is a model of the sentence in other words, if and only if there is no way to
reinterpret the non-logical terms in such a way as to render the sentence false
while rendering all sentences in the set true. As Quine has emphasized, this
definition reduces the modal notion of logical necessity to a combination of
syntactic and semantic concepts, thus avoiding reference to modalities and/or
to “possible worlds.” After Tarski’s definitive work on truth and on
consequence he devoted his energies largely to more purely mathematical work.
For example, in answer to Gödel’s proof that arithmetic is incomplete and
undecidable, Tarski showed that algebra and geometry are both complete and
decidable. Tarski’s truth definition and his consequence definition are found
in his 1956 collection Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics 2d ed., 1983: article
VIII, pp. 152278, contains the truth definition; article XVI, pp. 40920, contains
the consequence definition. His published articles, nearly 3,000 s in all, have
been available together since 1986 in the four-volume Alfred Tarski, Collected
Papers, edited by S. Givant and R. McKenzie.
tautology, a proposition
whose negation is inconsistent, or self- contradictory, e.g. ‘Socrates is
Socrates’, ‘Every human is either male or nonmale’, ‘No human is both male and
non-male’, ‘Every human is identical to itself’, ‘If Socrates is human then
Socrates is human’. A proposition that is or is logically equivalent to the
negation of a tautology is called a self-contradiction. According to classical
logic, the property of being Tao Te Ching tautology 902 902 implied by its own negation is a
necessary and sufficient condition for being a tautology and the property of
implying its own negation is a necessary and sufficient condition for being a
contradiction. Tautologies are logically necessary and contradictions are
logically impossible. Epistemically, every proposition that can be known to be
true by purely logical reasoning is a tautology and every proposition that can
be known to be false by purely logical reasoning is a contradiction. The
converses of these two statements are both controversial among classical
logicians. Every proposition in the same logical form as a tautology is a
tautology and every proposition in the same logical form as a contradiction is
a contradiction. For this reason sometimes a tautology is said to be true in
virtue of form and a contradiction is said to be false in virtue of form; being
a tautology and being a contradiction tautologousness and contradictoriness are
formal properties. Since the logical form of a proposition is determined by its
logical terms ‘every’, ‘some’, ‘is’, etc., a tautology is sometimes said to be
true in virtue of its logical terms and likewise mutatis mutandis for a
contradiction. Since tautologies do not exclude any logical possibilities they
are sometimes said to be “empty” or “uninformative”; and there is a tendency
even to deny that they are genuine propositions and that knowledge of them is
genuine knowledge. Since each contradiction “includes” implies all logical
possibilities which of course are jointly inconsistent, contradictions are
sometimes said to be “overinformative.” Tautologies and contradictions are
sometimes said to be “useless,” but for opposite reasons. More precisely,
according to classical logic, being implied by each and every proposition is
necessary and sufficient for being a tautology and, coordinately, implying each
and every proposition is necessary and sufficient for being a contradiction.
Certain developments in mathematical logic, especially model theory and modal
logic, seem to support use of Leibniz’s expression ‘true in all possible
worlds’ in connection with tautologies. There is a special subclass of
tautologies called truth-functional tautologies that are true in virtue of a
special subclass of logical terms called truthfunctional connectives ‘and’,
‘or’, ‘not’, ‘if’, etc.. Some logical writings use ‘tautology’ exclusively for
truth-functional tautologies and thus replace “tautology” in its broad sense by
another expression, e.g. ‘logical truth’. Tarski, Gödel, Russell, and many
other logicians have used the word in its broad sense, but use of it in its
narrow sense is widespread and entirely acceptable. Propositions known to be
tautologies are often given as examples of a priori knowledge. In philosophy of
mathematics, the logistic hypothesis of logicism is the proposition that every
true proposition of pure mathematics is a tautology. Some writers make a sharp
distinction between the formal property of being a tautology and the non-formal
metalogical property of being a law of logic. For example, ‘One is one’ is not
metalogical but it is a tautology, whereas ‘No tautology is a contradiction’ is
metalogical but is not a tautology.
Taylor, Charles b.1931,
Canadian philosopher and historian of modernity. Taylor was educated at McGill
and Oxford and has taught primarily at these universities. His work has a
broadly analytic character, although he has consistently opposed the
naturalistic and reductionist tendencies that were associated with the
positivist domination of analytic philosophy during the 1950s and 1960s. He
was, for example, a strong opponent of behaviorism and defended the essentially
interpretive nature of the social sciences against efforts to reduce their
methodology to that of the natural sciences. Taylor has also done important
work on the histiory of philosophy, particularly on Hegel, and has connected
his work with that of Continental philosophers such as Heidegger and
Merleau-Ponty. He has contributed to political theory and written on
contemporary political issues such as multiculturalism in, e.g., The Ethics of
Authenticity, 1991, often with specific reference to Canadian politics. He has
also taken an active political role in Quebec. Taylor’s most important work,
Sources of the Self 1989, is a historical and critical study of the emergence
of the modern concept of the self. Like many other critics of modernity, Taylor
rejects modern tendencies to construe personal identity in entirely scientific
or naturalistic terms, arguing that these construals lead to a view of the self
that can make no sense of our undeniable experience of ourselves as moral
agents. He develops this critique in a historical mode through discussion of
the radical Enlightenment’s e.g., Locke’s reduction of the self to an atomic
individual, essentially disengaged from everything except its own ideas and
desires. But unlike many critics, Taylor also finds in modernity other, richer
sources for a conception of the self. These include the idea of the self’s
inwardness, traceable as far back as Augustine Taylor, Charles Taylor, Charles
903 903 but developed in a
distinctively modern way by Montaigne and Descartes; the affirmation of
ordinary life and of ourselves as participants in it, particularly associated
with the Reformation; and the expressivism of, e.g., the Romantics for which
the self fulfills itself by embracing and articulating the voice of nature
present in its depths. Taylor thinks that these sources constitute a modern
self that, unlike the “punctual self” of the radical Enlightenment, is a
meaningful ethical agent. He suggests, nonetheless, that an adequate conception
of the modern self will further require a relation of human inwardness to God.
This suggestion so far remains undeveloped.
Taylor, Harriet 180758,
English feminist and writer. She was the wife of J. S. Mill, who called her the
“most admirable person” he had ever met; but according to her critics, Taylor
was “a stupid woman” with “a knack for repeating prettily what J.S.M. said.”
Although Mill may have exaggerated her moral and intellectual virtues, her
writings on marriage, the enfranchisement of women, and toleration did
influence his Subjection of Women and On Liberty. In The Enfranchisement of
Women, Taylor rejected the reigning “angel in the house” ideal of woman. She
argued that confining women to the house impeded both sexes’ development.
Taylor was a feminist philosopher in her own right, who argued even more
strongly than Mill that women are entitled to the same educational, legal, and
economic opportunities that men enjoy. R.T. te, Chinese term meaning ‘moral
charisma’ or ‘virtue’. In its earliest use, te is the quality bestowed on a
ruler by Heaven t’ien which makes his subjects willingly follow him. Rule by te
is traditionally thought to be not just ethically preferable to rule by force
but also more effective instrumentally. It is a necessary condition for having
te that one be ethically exemplary, but traditional thinkers differ over
whether being virtuous is also sufficient for the bestowal of te, and whether
the bestowal of te makes one even more virtuous. Te soon came also to refer to
virtue, in the sense of either a disposition that contributes to human
flourishing benevolence, courage, etc. or the specific excellence of any kind
of thing. B.W.V.N. techne Grecian, ‘art’, ‘craft’, a human skill based on
general principles and capable of being taught. In this sense, a manual craft
such as carpentry is a techne, but so are sciences such as medicine and
arithmetic. According to Plato Gorgias 501a, a genuine techne understands its
subject matter and can give a rational account of its activity. Aristotle
Metaphysics I.1 distinguishes technefrom experience on the grounds that techne
involves knowledge of universals and causes, and can be taught. Sometimes
‘techne’ is restricted to the productive as opposed to theoretical and
practical arts, as at Nicomachean Ethics VI.4. Techne and its products are
often contrasted with physis, nature Physics II.1.
Teichmüller, Gustav
183288, German philosopher who contributed to the history of philosophy and
developed a theory of knowledge and a metaphysical conception based on these
historical studies. Born in Braunschweig, he taught at Göttingen and Basel and
was influenced by Lotze and Leibniz. His major works are Aristotelische
Forschungen Aristotelian Investigations, 186773 and Die wirkliche und scheinbar
Welt The Actual and the Apparent World, 1882. His other works are Ueber die
Unsterblichkeit der Seele 1874, Studien zur Geschichte der Begriffe 1874,
Darwinismus und Philosophie 1877, Ueber das Wesen der Liebe 1879,
Religionsphilosophie 1886, and the posthumously published Neue Grundlegung der
Psychologie und Logik 1889. Teichmüller maintained that the self of immediate
experience, the “I,” is the most fundamental reality and that the conceptual
world is a projection of its constituting activity. On the basis of his studies
in the history of metaphysics and his sympathies with Leibniz’s monadology, he
held that each metaphysical system contained partial truths and construed each
metaphysical standpoint as a perspective on a complex reality. Thinking of both
metaphysical interpretations of reality and the subjectivity of individual
immediate experience, Teichmüller christened his own philosophical position
“perspectivism.” His work influenced later European thought through its impact
on the philosophical reflections of Nietzsche, who was probably influenced by
him in the development of his perspectival theory of knowledge.
Teilhard de Chardin,
Pierre 18811955, French paleontologist, Jesuit priest, and philosopher. His
Taylor, Harriet Teilhard de Chardin, Pierre 904 904 philosophical work, while published only
posthumously, was vigorously discussed throughout his career. His writings
generated considerable controversy within the church, since one of his
principal concerns was to bring about a forceful yet generous reconciliation
between the traditional Christian dogma and the dramatic advances yielded by
modern science. His philosophy consisted of systematic reflections on
cosmology, biology, physics, anthropology, social theory, and theology reflections guided, he maintained, by his
fascination with the nature of life, energy, and matter, and by his profound
respect for human spirituality. Teilhard was educated in philosophy and
mathematics at the Jesuit of Mongré,
near Lyons. He entered the Jesuit order at the age of eighteen and was ordained
a priest in 1911. He went on to study at Aix-en-Provence, Laval, and Caen, as
well as on the Isle of Jersey and at Hastings, England. Returning to Paris
after the war, he studied biology, geology, and paleontology at the Museum of
Natural History and at the Institut Catholique, receiving a doctoral degree in
geology in 1922. In 1923, shortly after appointment to the faculty of geology
at the Institut Catholique, he took leave to pursue field research in China.
His research resulted in the discovery, in 1929, of Peking man Sinanthropus
pekinensis which he saw as “perhaps the
next to the last step traceable between the anthropoids and man.” It was during
this period that Teilhard began to compose one of his major theoretical works,
The Phenomenon of Man 1955, in which he stressed the deep continuity of
evolutionary development and the emergence of humanity from the animal realm.
He argued that received evolutionary theory was fully compatible with Christian
doctrine. Indeed, it is the synthesis of evolutionary theory with his own
Christian theology that perhaps best characterizes the broad tenor of his
thought. Starting with the very inception of the evolutionary trajectory, i.e.,
with what he termed the “Alpha point” of creation, Teilhard’s general theory
resists any absolute disjunction between the inorganic and organic. Indeed,
matter and spirit are two “stages” or “aspects” of the same cosmic stuff. These
transitions from one state to another may be said to correspond to those
between the somatic and psychic, the exterior and interior, according to the
state of relative development, organization, and complexity. Hence, for
Teilhard, much as for Bergson whose work greatly influenced him, evolutionary
development is characterized by a progression from the simplest components of
matter and energy what he termed the lithosphere, through the organization of
flora and fauna the biosphere, to the complex formations of sentient and
cognitive human life the noosphere. In this sense, evolution is a “progressive
spiritualization of matter.” He held this to be an orthogenetic process, one of
“directed evolution” or “Genesis,” by which matter would irreversibly
metamorphose itself, in a process of involution and complexification, toward
the psychic. Specifically, Teilhard’s account sought to overcome what he saw as
a prescientific worldview, one based on a largely antiquated and indefensible
metaphysical dualism. By accomplishing this, he hoped to realize a productive
convergence of science and religion. The end of evolution, what he termed “the
Omega point,” would be the full presence of Christ, embodied in a universal
human society. Many have tended to see a Christian pantheism expressed in such
views. Teilhard himself stressed a profoundly personalist, spiritual
perspective, drawn not only from the theological tradition of Thomism, but from
that of Pauline Neoplatonism and Christian mysticism as well especially that tradition extending from
Meister Eckhart through Cardinal Bérulle and Malebranche.
teleology, the
philosophical doctrine that all of nature, or at least intentional agents, are
goaldirected or functionally organized. Plato first suggested that the
organization of the natural world can be understood by comparing it to the
behavior of an intentional agent
external teleology. For example, human beings can anticipate the future
and behave in ways calculated to realize their telekinesis teleology 905 905 intentions. Aristotle invested nature
itself with goals internal teleology.
Each kind has its own final cause, and entities are so constructed that they
tend to realize this goal. Heavenly bodies travel as nearly as they are able in
perfect circles because that is their nature, while horses give rise to other
horses because that is their nature. Natural theologians combined these two
teleological perspectives to explain all phenomena by reference to the
intentions of a beneficent, omniscient, all-powerful God. God so constructed
the world that each entity is invested with the tendency to fulfill its own
God-given nature. Darwin explained the teleological character of the living
world non-teleologically. The evolutionary process is not itself teleological,
but it gives rise to functionally organized systems and intentional agents.
Present-day philosophers acknowledge intentional behavior and functional
organization but attempt to explain both without reference to a supernatural
agent or internal natures of the more metaphysical sort. Instead, they define
‘function’ cybernetically, in terms of persistence toward a goal state under
varying conditions, or etiologically, in terms of the contribution that a
structure or action makes to the realization of a goal state. These definitions
confront a battery of counterexamples designed to show that the condition
mentioned is either not necessary, not sufficient, or both; e.g., missing goal
objects, too many goals, or functional equivalents. The trend has been to
decrease the scope of teleological explanations from all of nature, to the
organization of those entities that arise through natural selection, to their
final refuge in the behavior of human beings. Behaviorists have attempted to
eliminate this last vestige of teleology. Just as natural selection makes the
attribution of goals for biological species redundant, the selection of
behavior in terms of its consequences is designed to make any reference to
intentions on the part of human beings unnecessary.
Telesio, Bernardino
150988, Italian philosopher whose early scientific empiricism influenced
Francis Bacon and Galileo. He studied in Padua, where he completed his
doctorate in 1535, and practiced philosophy in Naples and Cosenza without
holding any academic position. His major work, the nine volumes of De rerum
natura iuxta propria principia “On the Nature of Things According to Their
Principles,” 1586, contains an attempt to interpret nature on the basis of its
own principles, which Telesio identifies with the two incorporeal active forces
of heat and cold, and the corporeal and passive physical substratum. As the two
active forces permeate all of nature and are endowed with sensation, Telesio argues
that all of nature possesses some degree of sensation. Human beings share with
animals a material substance produced by heat and coming into existence with
the body, called spirit. They are also given a mind by God. Telesio knew both
the Averroistic and the Alexandrist interpretations of Aristotle. However, he
broke with both, criticizing Aristotle’s Physics and claiming that nature is
investigated better by the senses than by the intellect. P.Gar. telishment,
punishment of one suspected of wrongdoing, but whom the authorities know to be
innocent, imposed as a deterrent to future wrongdoers. Telishment is thus not
punishment insofar as punishment requires that the recipient’s harsh treatment
be deserved. Telishment is classically given as one of the thought experiments
challenging utilitarianism and more broadly, consequentialism as a theory of
ethics, for such a theory seems to justify telishment on some occasions.
telos, ancient Grecian
term meaning ‘end’ or ‘purpose’. Telos is a key concept not only in Grecian
ethics but also in Grecian science. The purpose of a human being is a good
life, and human activities are evaluated according to whether they lead to or
manifest this telos. Plants, animals, and even inanimate objects were also
thought to have a telos through which their activities and relations could be
understood and evaluated. Though a telos could be something that transcends
human activities and sensible things, as Plato thought, it need not be anything
apart from nature. Aristotle, e.g., identified the telos of a sensible thing
with its immanent form. It follows that the purpose of the thing is simply to
be what it is and that, in general, a thing pursues its purpose when it
endeavors to preserve itself. Aristotle’s view shows that ‘purpose in nature’
need not mean a higher purpose beyond nature. Yet, his immanent purpose does
not exclude “higher” purposes, and Aristotelian teleology was pressed into
service by medieval thinkers as a framework for understanding God’s agency
through nature. Thinkers in the modern period argued against the prominent role
accorded to telos by ancient telepathy telos 906 906 and medieval thinkers, and they replaced
it with analyses in terms of mechanism and law.
tense logic, an extension
of classical logic introduced by Arthur Prior Past, Present, and Future, 1967,
involving operators P and F for the past and future tenses, or ‘it was the case
that . . .’ and ‘it will be the case that . . .’. Classical or mathematical
logic was developed as a logic of unchanging mathematical truth, and can be
applied to tensed discourse only by artificial regimentation inspired by
mathematical physics, introducing quantification over “times” or “instants.”
Thus ‘It will have been the case that p,’ which Prior represents simply as FPp,
classical logic represents as ‘There [exists] an instant t and there [exists]
an instant tH such that t [is] later than the present and tH [is] earlier than
t, and at tH it [is] the case that pH, or DtDtH t o‹t8tH ‹t8ptH, where the brackets
indicate that the verbs are to be understood as tenseless. Prior’s motives were
in part linguistic to produce a formalization less removed from natural
language than the classical and in part metaphysical to avoid ontological
commitment to such entities as instants. Much effort was devoted to finding
tense-logical principles equivalent to various classical assertions about the
structure of the earlierlater order among instants; e.g., ‘Between any two
instants there is another instant’ corresponds to the validity of the axioms Pp
P PPp and Fp P FFp. Less is expressible using P and F than is expressible with
explicit quantification over instants, and further operators for ‘since’ and
‘until’ or ‘now’ and ‘then’ have been introduced by Hans Kamp and others. These
are especially important in combination with quantification, as in ‘When he was
in power, all who now condemn him then praised him.’ As tense is closely
related to mood, so tense logic is closely related to modal logic. As Kripke
models for modal logic consist each of a set X of “worlds” and a relation R of
‘x is an alternative to y’, so for tense logic they consist each of a set X of
“instants” and a relation R of ‘x is earlier than y’: Thus instants, banished
from the syntax or proof theory, reappear in the semantics or model theory.
Modality and tense are both involved in the issue of future contingents, and
one of Prior’s motives was a desire to produce a formalism in which the views
on this topic of ancient, medieval, and early modern logicians from Aristotle
with his “sea fight tomorrow” and Diodorus Cronos with his “Master Argument”
through Ockham to Peirce could be represented. The most important precursor to
Prior’s work on tense logic was that on many-valued logics by Lukasiewicz, which
was motivated largely by the problem of future contingents. Also related to
tense and mood is aspect, and modifications to represent this grammatical
category evaluating formulas at periods rather than instants of time have also
been introduced. Like modal logic, tense logic has been the object of intensive
study in theoretical computer science, especially in connection with attempts
to develop languages in which properties of programs can be expressed and
proved; variants of tense logic under such labels as “dynamic logic” or
“process logic” have thus been extensively developed for technological rather
than philosophical motives.
of Ávila, Saint 151582,
Spanish religious, mystic, and author of spiritual treatises. Having entered
the Carmelite order at Ávila at twenty-two, Teresa spent the next twenty-five
years seeking guidance in the practice of prayer. Despite variously inept
spiritual advisers, she seems to have undergone a number of mystical experiences
and to have made increasingly important discoveries about interior life. After
1560 Teresa took on a public role by attaching herself to the reforming party
within the Spanish Carmelites. Her remaining years were occupied with the
reform, in which she was associated most famously with John of the Cross. She
also composed several works, including a spiritual autobiography the Vida and
two masterpieces of spirituality, the Way of Perfection and the Interior
Castle. The latter two, but especially the Castle, offer philosophical
suggestions about the soul’s passions, activities, faculties, and ground. Their
principal motive is to teach the reader how to progress, by successive
surrender, toward the divine Trinity dwelling at the soul’s center.
terminist logic, a school
of logic originating in twelfth-century Europe and dominant in the universities
until its demise in the humanistic reforms. Its chief goal was the elucidation
of the logical form the “exposition” of propositions advanced in the context of
Scholastic disputation. Its central theory concerned the properties of terms,
especially supposition, and did the work of modern quantification theory.
Important logicians in the school include Peter of Spain, William Sherwood,
Walter Burley, William Heytesbury, and Paul of Venice.
terminus a quo Latin,
‘term from which’, the starting point of some process. The terminus ad quem is
the ending point. For example, change is a process that begins from some state
the terminus a quo and proceeds to some state at which it ends the terminus ad
quem. In particular, in the ripening of an apple, the green apple is the
terminus a quo and the red apple is the terminus ad quem.
Tertullian A.D.
c.155c.240, Latin theologian, an early father of the Christian church. A layman
from Carthage, he laid the conceptual and linguistic basis for the doctrine of
the Trinity. Though appearing hostile to philosophy “What has Athens to do with
Jerusalem?” and to rationality “It is certain because it is impossible”,
Tertullian was steeped in Stoicism. He denounced all eclecticism not governed
by the normative tradition of Christian doctrine, yet commonly used
philosophical argument and Stoic concepts e.g., the corporeality of God and the
soul. Despite insisting on the sole authority of the New Testament apostles, he
joined with Montanism, which taught that the Holy Spirit was still inspiring
prophecy concerning moral discipline. Reflecting this interest in the Spirit,
Tertullian pondered the distinctions to which he gave the neologism trinitas
within God. God is one “substance” but three “persons”: a plurality without
division. The Father, Son, and Spirit are distinct, but share equally in the
one Godhead. This threeness is manifest only in the “economy” of God’s temporal
action toward the world; later orthodoxy e.g. Athanasius, Basil the Great,
Augustine, would postulate a Triunity that is eternal and “immanent,” i.e.,
internal to God’s being.
testability, in the
sciences, capacity of a theory to undergo experimental testing. Theories in the
natural sciences are regularly subjected to experimental tests involving
detailed and rigorous control of variable factors. Not naive observation of the
workings of nature, but disciplined, designed intervention in such workings, is
the hallmark of testability. Logically regarded, testing takes the form of
seeking confirmation of theories by obtaining positive test results. We can
represent a theory as a conjunction of a hypothesis and a statement of initial
conditions, H • A. This conjunction deductively entails testable or observational
consequences O. Hence, H • A P O. If O obtains, H • A is said to be confirmed,
or rendered probable. But such confirmation is not decisive; O may be entailed
by, and hence explained by, many other theories. For this reason, Popper
insisted that the testability of theories should seek disconfirmations or
falsifications. The logical schema H • A P O not-O not-H • A is deductively
valid, hence apparently decisive. On this view, science progresses, not by
finding the truth, but by discarding the false. Testability becomes
falsifiability. This deductive schema modus tollens is also employed in the
analysis of crucial tests. Consider two hypotheses H1 and H2, both introduced
to explain some phenomenon. H1 predicts that for some test condition C, we have
the test result ‘if C then e1’, and H2, the result ‘if C then e2’, where e1 and
e2 are logically incompatible. If experiment falsifies ‘if C then e1’ e1 does
not actually occur as a test result, the hypothesis H1 is false, which implies
that H2 is true. It was originally supposed that the experiments of J. B. L.
Foucault constituted a decisive falsify
cation of the corpuscular
theory of the nature of light, and thus provided a decisive establishment of
the truth of its rival, the wave theory of light. This account of crucial
experiments neglects certain points in logic and also the role of auxiliary
hypotheses in science. As Duhem pointed term, minor testability 908 908 out, rarely, if ever, does a hypothesis
face the facts in isolation from other supporting assumptions. Furthermore, it
is a fact of logic that the falsification of a conjunction of a hypothesis and
its auxiliary assumptions and initial conditions not-H • A is logically
equivalent to not-H or not-A, and the test result itself provides no warrant
for choosing which alternative to reject. Duhem further suggested that
rejection of any component part of a complex theory is based on
extra-evidential considerations factors like simplicity and fruitfulness and
cannot be forced by negative test results. Acceptance of Duhem’s view led Quine
to suggest that a theory must face the tribunal of experience en bloc; no
single hypothesis can be tested in isolation. Original conceptions of
testability and falsifiability construed scientific method as hypothetico-deductive.
Difficulties with these reconstructions of the logic of experiment have led
philosophers of science to favor an explication of empirical support based on
the logic of probability.
testimony, an act of
telling, including all assertions apparently intended to impart information,
regardless of social setting. In an extended sense personal letters and
messages, books, and other published material purporting to contain factual
information also constitute testimony. Testimony may be sincere or insincere,
and may express knowledge or baseless prejudice. When it expresses knowledge,
and it is rightly believed, this knowledge is disseminated to its recipients,
near or remote. Secondhand knowledge can be passed on further, producing long
chains of testimony; but these chains always begin with the report of an
eyewitness or expert. In any social group with a common language there is
potential for the sharing, through testimony, of the fruits of individuals’
idiosyncratic acquisition of knowledge through perception and inference. In
advanced societies specialization in the gathering and production of knowledge
and its wider dissemination through spoken and written testimony is a fundamental
socioepistemic fact, and a very large part of each person’s body of knowledge
and belief stems from testimony. Thus the question when a person may properly
believe what another tells her, and what grounds her epistemic entitlement to
do so, is a crucial one in epistemology. Reductionists about testimony insist
that this entitlement must derive from our entitlement to believe what we
perceive to be so, and to draw inferences from this according to familiar
general principles. See e.g., Hume’s classic discussion, in his Enquiry into
Human Understanding, section X. On this view, I can perceive that someone has
told me that p, but can thereby come to know that p only by means of an
inference one that goes via additional,
empirically grounded knowledge of the trustworthiness of that person.
Anti-reductionists insist, by contrast, that there is a general entitlement to
believe what one is told just as such
defeated by knowledge of one’s informant’s lack of trustworthiness her
mendacity or incompetence, but not needing to be bolstered positively by
empirically based knowledge of her trustworthiness. Anti-reductionists thus see
testimony as an autonomous source of knowledge on a par with perception,
inference, and memory. One argument adduced for anti-reductionism is
transcendental: We have many beliefs acquired from testimony, and these beliefs
are knowledge; their status as knowledge cannot be accounted for in the way
required by the reductionist that is,
the reliability of testimony cannot be independently confirmed; therefore the
reductionist’s insistence on this is mistaken. However, while it is perhaps
true that the reliability of all the beliefs one has that depend on past
testimony cannot be simultaneously confirmed, one can certainly sometimes ascertain,
without circularity, that a specific assertion by a particular person is likely
to be correct if, e.g.,one’s own
experience has established that that person has a good track record of
reliability about that kind of thing.
Tetens, Johann Nicolas
17361807, German philosopher and psychologist, sometimes called the German
Locke. After his studies in Rostock and Copenhagen, he taught at Bützow and
Kiel until 1789. He had a second successful career as a public servant in
Denmark 17901807 that did not leave him time for philosophical work. Tetens was
one of the most important German philosophers between Wolff and Kant. Like
Kant, whom he significantly influenced, Tetens attempted to find a middle way
between empiricism and rationalism. His most important work, the Philosophische
Versuche über die menschliche Natur und ihre Entwicklung “Philosophical Essays
on Human Nature and its Development,” 1777, is indicative of the state of
philosophical discustestimony Tetens, Johann Nicolas 909 909 sion in Germany before Kant’s Critique
of Pure Reason. Tetens, who followed the “psychological method” of Locke,
tended toward a naturalism, like that of Hume. However, Tetens made a more
radical distinction between reason and sensation than Hume allowed and
attempted to show how basic rational principles guarantee the objectivity of
human knowledge. M.K. Tetractys.
Thales of Miletus fl.
c.585 B.C., Grecian philosopher who was regarded as one of the Seven Sages of
Greece. He was also considered the first philosopher, founder of the Milesians.
Thales is also reputed to have been an engineer, astronomer, mathematician, and
statesman. His doctrines even early Grecian sources know only by hearsay: he
said that water is the arche, and that the earth floats on water like a raft.
The magnet has a soul, and all things are full of the gods. Thales’ attempt to
explain natural phenomena in natural rather than exclusively supernatural terms
bore fruit in his follower Anaximander.
Thema: in Stoic logic, a
ground rule used to reduce argument forms to basic forms. The Stoics analyzed
arguments by their form schema, or tropos. They represented forms using numbers
to represent claims; for example, ‘if the first, the second; but the first;
therefore the second’. Some forms were undemonstrable; others were reduced to
the undemonstrable argument forms by ground rules themata; e.g., if R follows
from P & Q, -Q follows from P & -R. The five undemonstrable arguments
are: 1 modus ponens; 2 modus tollens; 3 not both P and Q, P, so not-Q; 4 P or Q
but not both, P, so not-Q; and 5 disjunctive syllogism. The evidence about the
four ground rules is incomplete, but a sound and consistent system for
propositional logic can be developed that is consistent with the evidence we
have. See Diogenes Laertius, Lives of the Philosophers, 77681, for an
introduction to the Stoic theory of arguments; other evidence is more
scattered.
theodicy from Grecian
theos, ‘God’, and dike, ‘justice’, a defense of the justice or goodness of God
in the face of doubts or objections arising from the phenomena of evil in the
world ‘evil’ refers here to bad states of affairs of any sort. Many types of
theodicy have been proposed and vigorously debated; only a few can be sketched
here. 1 It has been argued that evils are logically necessary for greater goods
e.g., hardships for the full exemplification of certain virtues, so that even
an omnipotent being roughly, one whose power has no logically contingent limits
would have a morally sufficient reason to cause or permit the evils in order to
obtain the goods. Leibniz, in his Theodicy 1710, proposed a particularly
comprehensive theodicy of this type. On his view, God had adequate reason to
bring into existence the actual world, despite all its evils, because it is the
best of all possible worlds, and all actual evils are essential ingredients in
it, so that omitting any of them would spoil the design of the whole. Aside
from issues about whether actual evils are in fact necessary for greater goods,
this approach faces the question whether it assumes wrongly that the end
justifies the means. 2 An important type of theodicy traces some or all evils
to sinful free actions of humans or other beings such as angels created by God.
Proponents of this approach assume that free action in creatures is of great
value and is logically incompatible with divine causal control of the
creatures’ actions. It follows that God’s not intervening to prevent sins is
necessary, though the sins themselves are not, to the good of created freedom.
This is proposed as a morally sufficient reason for God’s not preventing them.
It is a major task for this type of theodicy to explain why God would permit
those evils that are not themselves free choices of creatures but are at most
consequences of such choices. 3 Another type of theodicy, both ancient and
currently influential among theologians, though less congenial to orthodox
traditions in the major theistic religions, proposes to defend God’s goodness
by abandoning the doctrine that God is omnipotent. On this view, God is
causally, rather than logically, unable to prevent many evils while pursuing
sufficiently great goods. A principal sponsor of this approach at present is
the movement known as process theology, inspired by Whitehead; it depends on a
complex metaphysical theory about the nature of causal relationships. 4 Other
theodicies focus more on outcomes than on origins. Some religious beliefs
suggest that God will turn out to have been very good to created persons by
virtue of gifts especially religious gifts, such as communion with God as
supreme Good that may be bestowed in a life Tetractys theodicy 910 910 after death or in religious experience
in the present life. This approach may be combined with one of the other types
of theodicy, or adopted by people who think that God’s reasons for permitting
evils are beyond our finding out.
theologia naturalis
Latin, ‘natural theology’, theology that uses the methods of investigation and
standards of rationality of any other area of philosophy. Traditionally, the
central problems of natural theology are proofs for the existence of God and
the problem of evil. In contrast with natural theology, supernatural theology
uses methods that are supposedly revealed by God and accepts as fact beliefs
that are similarly outside the realm of rational acceptability. Relying on a
prophet or a pope to settle factual questions would be acceptable to
supernatural, but not to natural, theology. Nothing prevents a natural
theologian from analyzing concepts that can be used sanguinely by supernatural
theologians, e.g., revelation, miracles, infallibility, and the doctrine of the
Trinity. Theologians often work in both areas, as did, e.g., Anselm and
Aquinas. For his brilliant critiques of traditional theology, Hume deserves the
title of “natural anti-theologian.”
theological naturalism,
the attempt to develop a naturalistic conception of God. As a philosophical
position, naturalism holds 1 that the only reliable methods of knowing what
there is are methods continuous with those of the developed sciences, and 2
that the application of those methods supports the view that the constituents
of reality are either physical or are causally dependent on physical things and
their modifications. Since supernaturalism affirms that God is purely spiritual
and causally independent of physical things, naturalists hold that either
belief in God must be abandoned as rationally unsupported or the concept of God
must be reconstituted consistently with naturalism. Earlier attempts to do the
latter include the work of Feuerbach and Comte. In twentieth-century American
naturalism the most significant attempts to develop a naturalistic conception
of God are due to Dewey and Henry Nelson Wieman 18841975. In A Common Faith
Dewey proposed a view of God as the unity of ideal ends resulting from human
imagination, ends arousing us to desire and action. Supernaturalism, he argued,
was the product of a primitive need to convert the objects of desire, the
greatest ideals, into an already existing reality. In contrast to Dewey, Wieman
insisted on viewing God as a process in the natural world that leads to the
best that humans can achieve if they but submit to its working in their lives.
In his earlier work he viewed God as a cosmic process that not only works for human
good but is what actually produced human life. Later he identified God with
creative interchange, a process that occurs only within already existing human
communities. While Wieman’s God is not a human creation, as are Dewey’s ideal
ends, it is difficult to see how love and devotion are appropriate to a natural
process that works as it does without thought or purpose. Thus, while Dewey’s
God ideal ends lacks creative power but may well qualify as an object of love
and devotion, Wieman’s God a process in nature is capable of creative power
but, while worthy of our care and attention, does not seem to qualify as an
object of love and devotion. Neither view, then, satisfies the two fundamental
features associated with the traditional idea of God: possessing creative power
and being an appropriate object of supreme love and devotion.
theoretical reason, in
its traditional sense, a faculty or capacity whose province is theoretical
knowledge or inquiry; more broadly, the faculty concerned with ascertaining
truth of any kind also sometimes called speculative reason. In Book 6 of his
Metaphysics, Aristotle identifies mathematics, physics, and theology as the
subject matter of theoretical reason. Theoretical reason is traditionally
distinguished from practical reason, a faculty exercised in determining guides
to good conduct and in deliberating about proper courses of action. Aristotle
contrasts it, as well, with productive reason, which is concerned with
“making”: shipbuilding, sculpting, healing, and the like. Kant distinguishes
theoretical reason not only from practical reason but also sometimes from the
faculty of understanding, in which the categories originate. Theoretical
reason, possessed of its own a priori concepts “ideas of reason”, regulates the
activities of the understanding. It presupposes a systematic unity in nature,
sets the goal for scientific inquiry, and determines the “criterion of
empirical truth” Critique of Pure Reason. Theoretical reason, on Kant’s
conception, seeks an explanatory “completeness” and an “unconditionedness” of
being that transcend what is possible in experience. Reason, as a faculty or
capacity, may be regarded as a hybrid composed of theoretical and practical
reason broadly construed or as a unity having both theoretical and practical
functions. Some commentators take Aristotle to embrace the former conception
and Kant the latter. Reason is contrasted sometimes with experience, sometimes
with emotion and desire, sometimes with faith. Its presence in human beings has
often been regarded as constituting the primary difference between human and
non-human animals; and reason is sometimes represented as a divine element in
human nature. Socrates, in Plato’s Philebus, portrays reason as “the king of
heaven and earth.” Hobbes, in his Leviathan, paints a more sobering picture,
contending that reason, “when we reckon it among the faculties of the mind, . .
. is nothing but reckoning that is,
adding and subtracting of the
consequences of general names agreed upon for the marking and signifying of our
thoughts.”
theoretical term, a term
occurring in a scientific theory that purports to make reference to an
unobservable entity e.g., ‘electron’, property e.g., ‘the monatomicity of a
molecule’, or relation ‘greater electrical resistance’. The qualification
‘purports to’ is required because instrumentalists deny that any such
unobservables exist; nevertheless, they acknowledge that a scientific theory,
such as the atomic theory of matter, may be a useful tool for organizing our
knowledge of observables and predicting future experiences. Scientific
realists, in contrast, maintain that at least some of the theoretical terms
e.g., ‘quark’ or ‘neutrino’ actually denote entities that are not directly
observable they hold, i.e., that such
things exist. For either group, theoretical terms are contrasted with such observational
terms as ‘rope’, ‘smooth’, and ‘louder than’, which refer to observable
entities, properties, or relations. Much philosophical controversy has centered
on how to draw the distinction between the observable and the unobservable. Did
Galileo observe the moons of Jupiter with his telescope? Do we observe bacteria
under a microscope? Do physicists observe electrons in bubble chambers? Do
astronomers observe the supernova explosions with neutrino counters? Do we
observe ordinary material objects, or are sense-data the only observables? Are there
any observational terms at all, or are all terms theory-laden? Another
important meaning of ‘theoretical term’ occurs if one regards a scientific
theory as a semiformal axiomatic system. It is then natural to think of its
vocabulary as divided into three parts, i terms of logic and mathematics, ii
terms drawn from ordinary language or from other theories, and iii theoretical
terms that constitute the special vocabulary of that particular theory.
Thermodynamics, e.g., employs i terms for numbers and mathematical operations,
ii such terms as ‘pressure’ and ‘volume’ that are common to many branches of
physics, and iii such special thermodynamical terms as ‘temperature’, ‘heat’,
and ‘entropy’. In this second sense, a theoretical term need not even purport to
refer to unobservables. For example, although special equipment is necessary
for its precise quantitatheoretical entity theoretical term 912 912 tive measurement, temperature is an
observable property. Even if theories are not regarded as axiomatic systems,
their technical terms can be considered theoretical. Such terms need not
purport to refer to unobservables, nor be the exclusive property of one
particular theory. In some cases, e.g., ‘work’ in physics, an ordinary word is
used in the theory with a meaning that departs significantly from its ordinary
use. Serious questions have been raised about the meaning of theoretical terms.
Some philosophers have insisted that, to be meaningful, they must be given
operational definitions. Others have appealed to coordinative definitions to
secure at least partial interpretation of axiomatic theories. The verifiability
criterion has been invoked to secure the meaningfulness of scientific theories
containing such terms. A theoretical concept or construct is a concept
expressed by a theoretical term in any of the foregoing senses. The term
‘theoretical entity’ has often been used to refer to unobservables, but this
usage is confusing, in part because, without introducing any special
vocabulary, we can talk about objects too small to be perceived directly e.g., spheres of gamboge a yellow resin less
than 106 meters in diameter, which figured in a historically important
experiment by Jean Perrin.
theory-laden, dependent
on theory; specifically, involving a theoretical interpretation of what is
perceived or recorded. In the heyday of logical empiricism it was thought, by
Carnap and others, that a rigid distinction could be drawn between
observational and theoretical terms. Later, N. R. Hanson, Paul Feyerabend, and
others questioned this distinction, arguing that perhaps all observations are
theory-laden either because our perception of the world is colored by
perceptual, linguistic, and cultural differences or because no attempt to
distinguish sharply between observation and theory has been successful. This
shift brings a host of philosophical problems. If we accept the idea of radical
theoryladenness, relativism of theory choice becomes possible, for, given rival
theories each of which conditions its own observational evidence, the choice
between them would seem to have to be made on extra-evidential grounds, since
no theory-neutral observations are available. In its most perplexing form,
relativism holds that, theory-ladenness being granted, one theory is as good as
any other, so far as the relationship of theory to evidence is concerned.
Relativists couple the thesis of theory-ladenness with the alleged fact of the
underdetermination of a theory by its observational evidence, which yields the
idea that any number of alternative theories can be supported by the same
evidence. The question becomes one of what it is that constrains choices
between theories. If theory-laden observations cannot constrain such choices,
the individual subjective preferences of scientists, or rules of fraternal
behavior agreed upon by groups of scientists, become the operative constraints.
The logic of confirmation seems to be intrinsically contaminated by both
idiosyncratic and social factors, posing a threat to the very idea of
scientific rationality.
theory of appearing, the
theory that to perceive an object is simply for that object to appear present
itself to one as being a certain way, e.g., looking round or like a rock,
smelling vinegary, sounding raucous, or tasting bitter. Nearly everyone would
accept this formulation on some interpretation. But the theory takes this to be
a rock-bottom characterization of perception, and not further analyzable. It
takes “appearing to subject S as so-and-so” as a basic, irreducible relation, one
readily identifiable in experience but not subject to definition in other
terms. The theory preserves the idea that in normal perception we are directly
aware of objects in the physical environment, not aware of them through
non-physical sense-data, sensory impressions, or other intermediaries. When a
tree looks to me a certain way, it is the tree and nothing else of which I am
directly aware. That involves “having” a sensory experience, but that
experience just consists of the tree’s looking a certain way to me. After
enjoying a certain currency early in this century the theory was largely
abandoned under the impact of criticisms by Price, Broad, and Chisholm. The
most widely advertised difficulty theoretical underdetermination theory of
appearing 913 913 is this. What is it
that appears to the subject in completely hallucinatory experience? Perhaps the
greatest strength of the theory is its fidelity to what perceptual experience
seems to be.
theory of descriptions,
an analysis, initially developed by Russell, of sentences containing
descriptions. Descriptions include indefinite descriptions such as ‘an
elephant’ and definite descriptions such as ‘the positive square root of four’.
On Russell’s analysis, descriptions are “incomplete symbols” that are meaningful
only in the context of other symbols, i.e., only in the context of the
sentences containing them. Although the words ‘the first president of the
United States’ appear to constitute a singular term that picks out a particular
individual, much as the name ‘George Washington’ does, Russell held that
descriptions are not referring expressions, and that they are “analyzed out” in
a proper specification of the logical form of the sentences in which they
occur. The grammatical form of ‘The first president of the United States is
tall’ is simply misleading as to its logical form. According to Russell’s
analysis of indefinite descriptions, the sentence ‘I saw a man’ asserts that
there is at least one thing that is a man, and I saw that thing symbolically, Ex Mx & Sx. The role of the
apparent singular term ‘a man’ is taken over by the existential quantifier ‘Ex’
and the variables it binds, and the apparent singular term disappears on
analysis. A sentence containing a definite description, such as ‘The present
king of France is bald’, is taken to make three claims: that at least one thing
is a present king of France, that at most one thing is a present king of
France, and that that thing is bald
symbolically, Ex {[Fx & y Fy / y % x] & Bx}. Again, the apparent
referring expression ‘the present king of France’ is analyzed away, with its
role carried out by the quantifiers and variables in the symbolic
representation of the logical form of the sentence in which it occurs. No
element in that representation is a singular referring expression. Russell held
that this analysis solves at least three difficult puzzles posed by
descriptions. The first is how it could be true that George IV wished to know
whether Scott was the author of Waverly, but false that George IV wished to
know whether Scott was Scott. Since Scott is the author of Waverly, we should
apparently be able to substitute ‘Scott’ for ‘the author of Waverly’ and infer
the second sentence from the first, but we cannot. On Russell’s analysis,
‘George IV wished to know whether Scott was the author of Waverly’ does not,
when properly understood, contain an expression ‘the author of Waverly’ for
which the name ‘Scott’ can be substituted. The second puzzle concerns the law
of excluded middle, which rules that either ‘The present king of France is
bald’ or ‘The present king of France is not bald’ must be true; the problem is
that neither the list of bald men nor that of non-bald men contains an entry
for the present king of France. Russell’s solution is that ‘The present king of
France is not bald’ is indeed true if it is understood as ‘It is not the case
that there is exactly one thing that is now King of France and is bald’, i.e.,
as -Ex {Fx & y {[Fy / y % x] & Bx}. The final puzzle is how ‘There is
no present king of France’ or ‘The present king of France does not exist’ can
be true if ‘the present king of France’
is a referring expression that picks out something, how can we truly deny that
that thing exists? Since descriptions are not referring expressions on Russell’s
theory, it is easy for him to show that the negation of the claim that there is
at least and at most i.e., exactly one present king of France, -Ex [Fx & y
Fy / y % x], is true. Strawson offered the first real challenge to Russell’s
theory, arguing that ‘The present king of France is bald’ does not entail but
instead presupposes ‘There is a present king of France’, so that the former is
not falsified by the falsity of the latter, but is instead deprived of a
truth-value. Strawson argued for the natural view that definite descriptions
are indeed referring expressions, used to single something out for predication.
More recently, Keith Donnellan argued that both Russell and Strawson ignored
the fact that definite descriptions have two uses. Used attributively, a
definite description is intended to say something about whatever it is true of,
and when a sentence is so used it conforms to Russell’s analysis. Used
referentially, a definite description is intended to single something out, but
may not correctly describe it. For example, seeing an inebriated man in a
policeman’s uniform, one might say, “The cop on the corner is drunk!” Donnellan
would say that even if the person were a drunken actor dressed as a policeman,
the speaker would have referred to him and truly said of him that he was drunk.
If it is for some reason crucial that the description be correct, as it might
be if one said, “The cop on the corner has the authority to issue speeding
tickets,” the use is attributive; and because ‘the cop on the corner’ does not
describe anyone correctly, no one has been said to have the authority to issue
speeding tickets. Donnellan criticized Russell for overlooking referential uses
of theory of descriptions theory of descriptions 914 914 descriptions, and Strawson for both
failing to acknowledge attributive uses and maintaining that with referential
uses one can refer to something with a definite description only if the
description is true of it. Discussion of Strawson’s and Donnellan’s criticisms
is ongoing, and has provoked very useful work in both semantics and speech act
theory, and on the distinctions between semantics and pragmatics and between
semantic reference and speaker’s reference, among others. .
theory of signs, the
philosophical and scientific theory of information-carrying entities,
communication, and information transmission. The term ‘semiotic’ was introduced
by Locke for the science of signs and signification. The term became more
widely used as a result of the influential work of Peirce and Charles Morris.
With regard to linguistic signs, three areas of semiotic were distinguished:
pragmatics the study of the way people,
animals, or machines such as computers use signs; semantics the study of the relations between signs and
their meanings, abstracting from their use; and syntax the study of the relations among signs
themselves, abstracting both from use and from meaning. In Europe, the
near-equivalent term ‘semiology’ was introduced by Ferdinand de Saussure, the
Swiss linguist. Broadly, a sign is any information-carrying entity, including
linguistic and animal signaling tokens, maps, road signs, diagrams, pictures,
models, etc. Examples include smoke as a sign of fire, and a red light at a
highway intersection as a sign to stop. Linguistically, vocal aspects of speech
such as prosodic features intonation, stress and paralinguistic features
loudness and tone, gestures, facial expressions, etc., as well as words and
sentences, are signs in the most general sense. Peirce defined a sign as “something
that stands for something in some respect or capacity.” Among signs, he
distinguished symbols, icons, and indices. A symbol, or conventional sign, is a
sign, typical of natural language forms, that lacks any significant relevant
physical correspondence with or resemblance to the entities to which the form
refers manifested by the fact that quite different forms may refer to the same
class of objects, and for which there is no correlation between the occurrence
of the sign and its referent. An index, or natural sign, is a sign whose
occurrence is causally or statistically correlated with occurrences of its
referent, and whose production is not intentional. Thus, yawning is a natural
sign of sleepiness; a bird call may be a natural sign of alarm. Linguistically,
loudness with a rising pitch is a sign of anger. An icon is a sign whose form
corresponds to or resembles its referent or a characteristic of its referent.
For instance, a tailor’s swatch is an icon by being a sign that resembles a
fabric in color, pattern, and texture. A linguistic example is
onomatopoeia as with ‘buzz’. In general,
there are conventional and cultural aspects to a sign being an icon.
Theosophy, any
philosophical mysticism, especially those that purport to be mathematically or
scientifically based, such as Pythagoreanism, Neoplatonism, or gnosticism.
Vedic Hinduism, and certain aspects of Buddhism, Taoism, and Islamic Sufism,
can also be considered theosophical. In narrower senses, ‘theosophy’ may refer
to the philosophy of Swedenborg, Steiner, or Madame Helena Petrovna Blavatsky
183191. Swedenborg’s theosophy originally consisted of a rationalistic
cosmology, inspired by certain elements of Cartesian and Leibnizian philosophy,
and a Christian mysticism. Swedenborg labored to explain the interconnections
between soul and body. Steiner’s theosophy is a reaction to standard scientific
theory. It purports to be as rigorous as ordinary science, but superior to it
by incorporating spiritual truths about reality. According to his theosophy,
reality is organic and evolving by its own resource. Genuine knowledge is
intuitive, not discursive. Madame Blavatsky founded the Theosophical Society in
1875. Her views were eclectic, but were strongly influenced by mystical
elements of Indian philosophy.
Thomism, the theology and
philosophy of Thomas Aquinas. The term is applied broadly to various thinkers
from different periods who were heavily influenced by Aquinas’s thought in
their own philosophizing and theologizing. Here three different eras and three
different groups of thinkers will be distinguished: those who supported
Aquinas’s thought in the fifty years or so following his death in 1274; certain
highly skilled interpreters and commentators who flourished during the period
of “Second Thomism” sixteenthseventeenth centuries; and various late
nineteenth- and twentieth-century thinkers who have been deeply influenced in
their own work by Aquinas. Thirteenth- and fourteenth-century Thomism. Although
Aquinas’s genius was recognized by many during his own lifetime, a number of
his views were immediately contested by other Scholastic thinkers.
Controversies ranged, e.g., over his defense of only one substantial form in
human beings; his claim that prime matter is purely potential and cannot,
therefore, be kept in existence without some substantial form, even by divine
power; his emphasis on the role of the human intellect in the act of choice;
his espousal of a real distinction betweeen the soul and its powers; and his
defense of some kind of objective or “real” rather than a merely mind-dependent
composition of essence and act of existing esse in creatures. Some of Aquinas’s
positions were included directly or indirectly in the 219 propositions
condemned by Bishop Stephen Tempier of Paris in 1277, and his defense of one
single substantial form in man was condemned by Archbishop Robert Kilwardby at
Oxford in 1277, with renewed prohibitions by his successor as archbishop of
Canterbury, John Peckham, in 1284 and 1286. Only after Aquinas’s canonization
in 1323 were the Paris prohibitions revoked insofar as they touched on his
teaching in 1325. Even within his own Dominican order, disagreement about some
of his views developed within the first decades after his death,
notwithstanding the order’s highly sympathetic espousal of his cause. Early
English Dominican defenders of his general views included William Hothum
d.1298, Richard Knapwell d.c.1288, Robert Orford b. after 1250, fl.129095,
Thomas Sutton d. c.1315?, and William Macclesfield d.1303. French Dominican
Thomists included Bernard of Trilia d.1292, Giles of Lessines in present-day
Belgium d.c.1304?, John Quidort of Paris d. 1306, Bernard of Auvergne d. after
1307, Hervé Nédélec d.1323, Armand of Bellevue fl. 131634, and William Peter
Godin d.1336. The secular master at Paris, Peter of Auvergne d. 1304, while
remaining very independent in his own views, knew Aquinas’s thought well and
completed some of his commentaries on Aristotle. Sixteenth- and
seventeenth-century Thomism. Sometimes known as the period of Second Thomism,
this revival gained impetus from the early fifteenth-century writer John
Capreolus 13801444 in his Defenses of Thomas’s Theology Defensiones theologiae
Divi Thomae, a commentary on the Sentences. A number of fifteenth-century
Dominican and secular teachers in German universities also contributed: Kaspar
Grunwald Freiburg; Cornelius Sneek and John Stoppe in Rostock; Leonard of
Brixental Vienna; Gerard of Heerenberg, Lambert of Heerenberg, and John Versor
all at Cologne; Gerhard of Elten; and in Belgium Denis the Carthusian.
Outstanding among various sixteenth-century commentators on Thomas were Tommaso
de Vio Cardinal Cajetan, Francis Sylvester of Ferrara, Francisco de Vitoria
Salamanca, and Francisco’s disciples Domingo de Soto and Melchior Cano. Most
important among early seventeenth-century Thomists was John of St. Thomas, who
lectured at Piacenza, Madrid, and Alcalá, and is best known for his Cursus
philosophicus and his Cursus theologicus. Theravada Buddhism Thomism 916 916 The nineteenth- and twentieth-century
revival. By the early to mid-nineteenth century the study of Aquinas had been
largely abandoned outside Dominican circles, and in most Roman Catholic s and
seminaries a kind of Cartesian and Suarezian Scholasticism was taught. Long
before he became Pope Leo XIII, Joachim Pecci and his brother Joseph had taken
steps to introduce the teaching of Thomistic philosophy at the diocesan
seminary at Perugia in 1846. Earlier efforts in this direction had been made by
Vincenzo Buzzetti 17781824, by Buzzetti’s students Serafino and Domenico Sordi,
and by Taparelli d’Aglezio, who became director of the Collegio Romano
Gregorian in 1824. Leo’s encyclical
Aeterni Patris1879 marked an official effort on the part of the Roman Catholic
church to foster the study of the philosophy and theology of Thomas Aquinas. The
intent was to draw upon Aquinas’s original writings in order to prepare
students of philosophy and theology to deal with problems raised by
contemporary thought. The Leonine Commission was established to publish a
critical edition of all of Aquinas’s writings; this effort continues today.
Important centers of Thomistic studies developed, such as the Higher Institute
of Philosophy at Louvain founded by Cardinal Mercier, the Dominican School of
Saulchoir in France, and the Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies in
Toronto. Different groups of Roman, Belgian, and French Jesuits acknowledged a
deep indebtedness to Aquinas for their personal philosophical reflections.
There was also a concentration of effort in the United States at universities
such as The Catholic of America, St.
Louis , Notre Dame, Fordham, Marquette, and Boston , to mention but a few, and
by the Dominicans at River Forest. A great weakness of many of the
nineteenthand twentieth-century Latin manuals produced during this effort was a
lack of historical sensitivity and expertise, which resulted in an unreal and
highly abstract presentation of an “Aristotelian-Thomistic” philosophy. This
weakness was largely offset by the development of solid historical research
both in the thought of Aquinas and in medieval philosophy and theology in
general, championed by scholars such as H. Denifle, M. De Wulf, M. Grabmann, P.
Mandonnet, F. Van Steenberghen, E. Gilson and many of his students at Toronto,
and by a host of more recent and contemporary scholars. Much of this historical
work continues today both within and without Catholic scholarly circles. At the
same time, remarkable diversity in interpreting Aquinas’s thought has emerged
on the part of many twentieth-century scholars. Witness, e.g., the heavy
influence of Cajetan and John of St. Thomas on the Thomism of Maritain; the
much more historically grounded approaches developed in quite different ways by
Gilson and F. Van Steenberghen; the emphasis on the metaphysics of
participation in Aquinas in the very different presentations by L. Geiger and
C. Fabro; the emphasis on existence esse promoted by Gilson and many others but
resisted by still other interpreters; the movement known as Transcendental
Thomism, originally inspired by P. Rousselot and by J. Marechal in dialogue
with Kant; and the long controversy about the appropriateness of describing
Thomas’s philosophy and that of other medievals as a Christian philosophy. An
increasing number of non-Catholic thinkers are currently directing considerable
attention to Aquinas, and the varying backgrounds they bring to his texts will
undoubtedly result in still other interesting interpretations and applications
of his thought to contemporary concerns.
Jarvis, j. b.1929, American analytic philosopher best
known for her contribution to moral philosophy and for her paper “A Defense of
Abortion” 1971. Thomson has taught at M.I.T. since 1964. Her work is centrally
concerned with issues in moral philosophy, most notably questions regarding
rights, and with issues in metaphysics such as the identity across time of
people and the ontology of events. Her Acts and Other Events 1977 is a study of
human action and provides an analysis of the part whole relation among events.
“A Defense of Abortion” has not only influenced much later work on this topic
but is one of the most widely discussed papers in contemporary philosophy. By
appeal to imaginative scenarios analogous to pregnancy, Thomson argues that
even if the fetus is assumed to be a person, its rights are in many
circumstances outweighed by the rights of the pregnant woman. Thus the paper
advances an argument for a right to abortion that does not turn upon the
question of whether the fetus is a person. Several of Thomson’s essays,
including “Preferential Hiring” 1973, “The Right to Privacy” 1975, and
“Killing, Letting Die, and the Trolley Problem” 1976, address the questions of
what constitutes Thomson, Judith Jarvis Thomson, Judith Jarvis 917 917 an infringement of rights and when it is
morally permissible to infringe a right. These are collected in Rights,
Restitution, and Risk: Essays in Moral Theory 1986. Thomson’s The Realm of
Rights 1990 offers a systematic account of human rights, addressing first what
it is to have a right and second which rights we have. Thomson’s work is
distinguished by its exceptionally lucid style and its reliance on highly
inventive examples. The centrality of examples to her work reflects a
methodological conviction that our views about actual and imagined cases
provide the data for moral theorizing.
Thoreau, Henry David
181762, American naturalist and writer. Born in Concord, Massachusetts, he
attended Harvard 183337 and then returned to Concord to study nature and write,
making a frugal living as a schoolteacher, land surveyor, and pencil maker.
Commentators have emphasized three aspects of his life: his love and
penetrating study of the flora and fauna of the Concord area, recorded with
philosophical reflections in Walden 1854; his continuous pursuit of simplicity
in the externals of life, thus avoiding a life of “quiet desperation”; and his
acts of civil disobedience. The last item has been somewhat overemphasized; not
paying a poll tax by way of protest was not original with Thoreau. However, his
essay “Resistance to Civil Government” immortalized his protest and influenced
people like Gandhi and Martin Luther King, Jr., in later years. Thoreau
eventually helped runaway slaves at considerable risk; still, he considered
himself a student of nature and not a reformer.
thought experiment, a
technique for testing a hypothesis by imagining a situation and what would be
said about it or more rarely, happen in it. This technique is often used by
philosophers to argue for or against a hypothesis about the meaning or
applicability of a concept. For example, Locke imagined a switch of minds
between a prince and a cobbler as a way to argue that personal identity is
based on continuity of memory, not continuity of the body. To argue for the
relativity of simultaneity, Einstein imagined two observers one on a train, the other beside it who observed lightning bolts. And according
to some scholars, Galileo only imagined the experiment of tying two five-pound
weights together with a fine string in order to argue that heavier bodies do
not fall faster. Thought experiments of this last type are rare because they
can be used only when one is thoroughly familiar with the outcome of the
imagined situation. J.A.K. Thrasymachus fl. 427 B.C., Grecian Sophist from
Bithynia who is known mainly as a character in Book I of Plato’s Republic. He
traveled and taught extensively throughout the Grecian world, and was well
known in Athens as a teacher and as the author of treatises on rhetoric.
Innovative in his style, he was credited with inventing the “middle style” of
rhetoric. The only surviving fragment of a speech by Thrasymachus was written
for delivery by an Athenian citizen in the assembly, at a time when Athens was
not faring well in the Peloponnesian War; it shows him concerned with the
efficiency of government, pleading with the Athenians to recognize their common
interests and give up their factionalism. Our only other source for his views
on political matters is Plato’s Republic, which most scholars accept as
presenting at least a half-truth about Thrasymachus. There, Thrasymachus is
represented as a foil to Socrates, claiming that justice is only what benefits
the stronger, i.e., the rulers. From the point of view of those who are ruled,
then, justice always serves the interest of someone else, and rulers who seek
their own advantage are unjust.
t’i, yung, Chinese terms
often rendered into English as ‘substance’ and ‘function’, respectively. Ch’eng
Yi 10331107, in the preface to his Commentary to the Book of Changes, says:
“Substance t’i and function yung come from the same source, and there is no gap
between the manifest and the hidden.” Such thought is characteristic of the
Chinese way of thinking. Chu Hsi 11301200 applied the pair of concepts to his theory
of human nature; he maintained that jen humanity is nature, substance, while
love is Thoreau, Henry David t’i, yung 918
918 feeling, function. In the late Ch’ing dynasty 16441912 Chang
Chih-tung 18371909 advocated Chinese learning for t’i and Western learning for
yung.
t’ien, Chinese term
meaning ‘heaven’, ‘sky’. T’ien has a range of uses running from the most to the
least anthropomorphic. At one extreme, t’ien is identified with shang ti. T’ien
can be spoken of as having desires and engaging in purposive actions, such as
bestowing the Mandate of Heaven t’ien ming. T’ien ming has a political and an
ethical use. It can be the mandate to rule given to a virtuous individual. It
can also be the moral requirements that apply to each individual, especially as
these are embodied in one’s nature. At the other extreme, thinkers such as
Hsün-Tzu identify t’ien with the natural order. Even in texts where t’ien is
sometimes used anthropomorphically, it can also be used as synonymous with ming
in the sense of fate, or simply refer to the sky. After the introduction of
Buddhism into China, the phrase ‘Hall of Heaven’ t’ien t’ang is used to refer
to the paradise awaiting some souls after death.
t’ien-jen ho-i, Chinese
term for the relationship between t’ien Heaven and human beings. Most ancient
Chinese philosophers agreed on the ideal t’ien-jen ho-i: the unity and harmony
of Heaven or the natural order of events and human affairs. They differed on
the means of achieving this ideal vision. The Taoists, Lao Tzu and Chuang Tzu,
focused on adaptability to all natural occurrences without human intervention.
The Confucians stressed the cultivation of virtues such as jen benevolence, i
rightness, and li propriety, both in the rulers and the people. Some later
Confucians, along with Mo Tzu, emphasized the mutual influence and response or
interaction of Heaven and humans. Perhaps the most distinctive Confucian
conception is Hsün Tzu’s thesis that Heaven provides resources for completion
by human efforts. A.S.C. t’ien li, jen-yü, Chinese terms literally meaning
‘heavenly principles’ and ‘human desires’, respectively. SungMing Neo-Confucian
philosophers believed that Heaven enables us to understand principles and to
act according to them. Therefore we must try our best to preserve heavenly
principles and eliminate human desires. When hungry, one must eat; this is
acting according to t’ien li. But when one craves gourmet food, the only thing
one cares about is gratification of desire; this is jen-yü. Neo-Confucian
philosophers were not teaching asceticism; they only urged us not to be slaves
of our excessive, unnatural, artificial, “human” desires.
Tillich, Paul 18861965,
German-born American philosopher and theologian. Born in Starzeddel, eastern
Germany, he was educated in philosophy and theology and ordained in the
Prussian Evangelical Church in 1912. He served as an army chaplain during World
War I and later taught at Berlin, Marburg, Dresden, Leipzig, and Frankfurt. In
November 1933, following suspension from his teaching post by the Nazis, he
emigrated to the United States, where he taught at Columbia and Union Theological
Seminary until 1955, and then at Harvard and Chicago until his death. A popular
preacher and speaker, he developed a wide audience in the United States through
such writings as The Protestant Era 1948, Systematic Theology three volumes:
1951, 1957, 1963, The Courage to Be 1952, and Dynamics of Faith 1957. His
sometimes unconventional lifestyle, as well as his syncretic yet original
thought, moved “on the boundary” between theology and other elements of
culture especially art, literature,
political thought, and depth psychology
in the belief that religion should relate to the whole extent, and the
very depths, of human existence. Tillich’s thought, despite its distinctive
“ontological” vocabulary, was greatly influenced by the voluntaristic tradition
from Augustine through Schelling, Schopenhauer, Marx, Nietzsche, and Freud. It
was a systematic theology that sought to state fresh Christian answers to deep
existential questions raised by individuals and cultures his method of correlation. Every age has its
distinctive kairos, “crisis” or “fullness of time,” the right time for creative
thought and action. In Weimar Germany, Tillich found the times ripe for
religious socialism. In postWorld War II America, he focused more on
psychological themes: in the midst of anxiety over death, meaninglessness, and
guilt, everyone seeks the courage to be, which comes only by avoiding the abyss
of non-being welling up in the demonic and by placing one’s unconditional
faith ultit’ien Tillich, Paul 919 919 mate concern not in any particular being e.g. God but in
Being-Itself “the God above God,” the ground of being. This is essentially the
Protestant principle, which prohibits lodging ultimate concern in any finite
and limited reality including state, race, and religious institutions and
symbols. Tillich was especially influential after World War II. He represented
for many a welcome critical openness to the spiritual depths of modern culture,
opposing both demonic idolatry of this world as in National Socialism and sectarian
denial of cultural resources for faith as in Barthian neo-orthodoxy.
time, “a moving image of
eternity” Plato; “the number of movements in respect of the before and after”
Aristotle; “the Life of the Soul in movement as it passes from one stage of act
or experience to another” Plotinus; “a present of things past, memory, a
present of things present, sight, and a present of things future, expectation”
Augustine. These definitions, like all attempts to encapsulate the essence of
time in some neat formula, are unhelpfully circular because they employ
temporal notions. Although time might be too basic to admit of definition,
there still are many questions about time that philosophers have made some
progress in answering by analysis both of how we ordinarily experience and talk
about time, and of the deliverances of science, thereby clarifying and
deepening our understanding of what time is. What follows gives a sample of
some of the more important of these issues. Temporal becoming and the A- and
B-theories of time. According to the B-theory, time consists in nothing but a
fixed “B-series” of events running from earlier to later. The A-theory requires
that these events also form an “A-series” going from the future through the
present into the past and, moreover, shift in respect to these determinations.
The latter sort of change, commonly referred to as “temporal becoming,” gives
rise to well-known perplexities concerning both what does the shifting and the
sort of shift involved. Often it is said that it is the present or now that
shifts to ever-later times. This quickly leads to absurdity. ‘The present’ and
‘now’, like ‘this time’, are used to refer to a moment of time. Thus, to say
that the present shifts to later times entails that this very moment of time the present
will become some other moment of time and thus cease to be identical
with itself! Sometimes the entity that shifts is the property of nowness or
presentness. The problem is that every event has this property at some time,
namely when it occurs. Thus, what must qualify some event as being now
simpliciter is its having the property of nowness now; and this is the start of
an infinite regress that is vicious because at each stage we are left with an
unexpurgated use of ‘now’, the very term that was supposed to be analyzed in
terms of the property of nowness. If events are to change from being future to
present and from present to past, as is required by temporal becoming, they
must do so in relation to some mysterious transcendent entity, since temporal
relations between events and/or times cannot change. The nature of the shift is
equally perplexing, for it must occur at a particular rate; but a rate of
change involves a comparison between one kind of change and a change of time.
Herein, it is change of time that is compared to change of time, resulting in
the seeming tautology that time passes or shifts at the rate of one second per
second, surely an absurdity since this is not a rate of change at all. Broad
attempted to skirt these perplexities by saying that becoming is sui generis
and thereby defies analysis, which puts him on the side of the mystically
inclined Bergson who thought that it could be known only through an act of
ineffable intuition. To escape the clutches of both perplexity and mysticism,
as well as to satisfy the demand of science to view the world
non-perspectivally, the B-theory attempted to reduce the A-series to the
B-series via a linguistic reduction in which a temporal indexical proposition
reporting an event as past, present, or future is shown to be identical with a
non-indexical proposition reporting a relation of precedence or simultaneity
between it and another event or time. It is generally conceded that such a
reduction fails, since, in general, no indexical proposition is identical with
any non-indexical one, this being due to the fact that one can have a
propositional attitude toward one of them that is not had to the other; e.g., I
can believe that it is now raining without believing that it rains tenselessly at
t 7. The friends of becoming have drawn the wrong moral from this failure that there is a mysterious Mr. X out there
doing “The Shift.” They have overlooked the fact that two sentences can express
different propositions and yet report one and the same event or state of
affairs; e.g., ‘This time time 920 920
is water’ and ‘this is a collection of H2O molecules’, though differing in
sense, report the same state of affairs
this being water is nothing but this being a collection of H2O
molecules. It could be claimed that the same holds for the appropriate use of
indexical and non-indexical sentences; the tokening at t 7 of ‘Georgie flies at
this time at present’ is coreporting with the non-synonymous ‘Georgie flies
tenselessly at t 7’, since Georgie’s flying at this time is the same event as
Georgie’s flying at t 7, given that this time is t 7. This effects the same
ontological reduction of the becoming of events to their bearing temporal
relations to each other as does the linguistic reduction. The “coreporting
reduction” also shows the absurdity of the “psychological reduction” according
to which an event’s being present, etc., requires a relation to a perceiver,
whereas an event’s having a temporal relation to another event or time does not
require a relation to a perceiver. Given that Georgie’s flying at this time is
identical with Georgie’s flying at t 7, it follows that one and the same event
both does and does not have the property of requiring relation to a perceiver,
thereby violating Leibniz’s law that identicals are indiscernible. Continuous
versus discrete time. Assume that the instants of time are linearly ordered by
the relation R of ‘earlier than’. To say that this order is continuous is,
first, to imply the property of density or infinite divisibility: for any
instants i 1 and i 2 such that Ri1i 2, there is a third instant i 3, such that
Ri1i 3 and Ri3i 2. But continuity implies something more since density allows
for “gaps” between the instants, as with the rational numbers. Think of R as
the ‘less than’ relation and the i n as rationals. To rule out gaps and thereby
assure genuine continuity it is necessary to require in addition to density
that every convergent sequence of instants has a limit. To make this precise
one needs a distance measure d , on
pairs of instants, where di m, i n is interpreted as the lapse of time between
i m and i n. The requirement of continuity proper is then that for any sequence
i l , i 2, i 3, . . . , of instants, if di m i n P 0 as m, n P C, there is a
limit instant i ø such that di n, iø P 0
as n P C. The analogous property obviously fails for the rationals. But taking
the completion of the rationals by adding in the limit points of convergent
sequences yields the real number line, a genuine continuum. Numerous objections
have been raised to the idea of time as a continuum and to the very notion of
the continuum itself. Thus, it was objected that time cannot be composed of
durationless instants since a stack of such instants cannot produce a non-zero
duration. Modern measure theory resolves this objection. Leibniz held that a
continuum cannot be composed of points since the points in any finite closed
interval can be put in one-to-one correspondence with a smaller subinterval,
contradicting the axiom that the whole is greater than any proper part. What
Leibniz took to be a contradictory feature is now taken to be a defining
feature of infinite collections or totalities. Modern-day Zenoians, while
granting the viability of the mathematical doctrine of the continuum and even
the usefulness of its employment in physical theory, will deny the possibility
of its applying to real-life changes. Whitehead gave an analogue of Zeno’s
paradox of the dichotomy to show that a thing cannot endure in a continuous
manner. For if i 1, i 2 is the interval over which the thing is supposed to
endure, then the thing would first have to endure until the instant i 3,
halfway between i 1 and i 2; but before it can endure until i 3, it must first
endure until the instant i 4 halfway between i 1 and i 3, etc. The
seductiveness of this paradox rests upon an implicit anthropomorphic demand
that the operations of nature must be understood in terms of concepts of human
agency. Herein it is the demand that the physicist’s description of a continuous
change, such as a runner traversing a unit spatial distance by performing an
infinity of runs of ever-decreasing distance, could be used as an
action-guiding recipe for performing this feat, which, of course, is impossible
since it does not specify any initial or final doing, as recipes that guide
human actions must. But to make this anthropomorphic demand explicit renders
this deployment of the dichotomy, as well as the arguments against the
possibility of performing a “supertask,” dubious. Anti-realists might deny that
we are committed to real-life change being continuous by our acceptance of a
physical theory that employs principles of mathematical continuity, but this is
quite different from the Zenoian claim that it is impossible for such change to
be continuous. To maintain that time is discrete would require not only
abandoning the continuum but also the density property as well. Giving up
either conflicts with the intuition that time is one-dimensional. For an
explanation of how the topological analysis of dimensionality entails that the
dimension of a discrete space is 0, see W. Hurewicz, Dimension Theory, 1941.
The philotime time 921 921 sophical and
physics literatures contain speculations about a discrete time built of
“chronons” or temporal atoms, but thus far such hypothetical entities have not
been incorporated into a satisfactory theory. Absolute versus relative and
relational time. In a scholium to the Principia, Newton declared that
“Absolute, true and mathematical time, of itself and from its own nature, flows
equably without relation to anything external.” There are at least five
interrelated senses in which time was absolute for Newton. First, he thought
that there was a frame-independent relation of simultaneity for events. Second,
he thought that there was a frame-independent measure of duration for
non-simultaneous events. He used ‘flows equably’ not to refer to the above sort
of mysterious “temporal becoming,” but instead to connote the second sense of
absoluteness and partly to indicate two further kinds of absoluteness. To
appreciate the latter, note that ‘flows equably’ is modified by ‘without
relation to anything external’. Here Newton was asserting third sense of
‘absolute’ that the lapse of time between two events would be what it is even
if the distribution and motions of material bodies were different. He was also
presupposing a related form of absoluteness fourth sense according to which the
metric of time is intrinsic to the temporal interval. Leibniz’s philosophy of
time placed him in agreement with Newton as regards the first two senses of
‘absolute’, which assert the non-relative or frame-independent nature of time.
However, Leibniz was very much opposed to Newton on the fourth sense of
‘absolute’. According to Leibniz’s relational conception of time, any talk
about the length of a temporal interval must be unpacked in terms of talk about
the relation of the interval to an extrinsic metric standard. Furthermore,
Leibniz used his principles of sufficient reason and identity of indiscernibles
to argue against a fifth sense of ‘absolute’, implicit in Newton’s philosophy
of time, according to which time is a substratum in which physical events are
situated. On the contrary, the relational view holds that time is nothing over
and above the structure of relations of events. Einstein’s special and general
theories of relativity have direct bearing on parts of these controversies. The
special theory necessitates the abandonment of frame-independent notions of
simultaneity and duration. For any pair of spacelike related events in
Minkowski space-time there is an inertial frame in which the events are
simultaneous, another frame in which the first event is temporally prior, and
still a third in which the second event is temporally prior. And the temporal
interval between two timelike related events depends on the worldline
connecting them. In fact, for any e 0,
no matter how small, there is a worldline connecting the events whose proper
length is less than e. This is the essence of the so-called twin paradox. The
general theory of relativity abandons the third sense of absoluteness since it
entails that the metrical structure of space-time covaries with the
distribution of mass-energy in a manner specified by Einstein’s field
equations. But the heart of the absoluterelational controversy as focused by the fourth and fifth senses of
‘absolute’ is not settled by
relativistic considerations. Indeed, opponents from both sides of the debate
claim to find support for their positions in the special and general
theories.
time slice, a temporal
part or stage of any concrete particular that exists for some interval of time;
a three-dimensional cross section of a fourdimensional object. To think of an
object as consisting of time slices or temporal stages is to think of it as
related to time in much the way that it is related to space: as extending
through time as well as space, rather than as enduring through it. Just as an
object made up of spatial parts is thought of as a whole made up of parts that
exist at different locations, so an object made up of time slices is thought of
as a whole made up of parts or stages that exist at successive times; hence,
just as a spatial whole is only partly present in any space that does not
include all its spatial parts, so a whole made up of time slices is only partly
present in any stretch of time that does not include all its temporal parts. A
continuant, by contrast, is most commonly understood to be a particular that
endures through time, i.e., that is wholly present at each moment at which it
exists. To conceive of an object as a continuant is to conceive of it as
related to time in a very different way from that in which it is related to
space. A continuant does not extend through time as well as space; it does not
exist at different times by virtue of the existence of successive parts of it
at those times; it is the continuant itself that is wholly present at each such
time. To conceive an object as a continuant, therefore, is to conceive it as
not made time lag argument time slice 922
922 up of temporal stages, or time slices, at all. There is another,
less common, use of ‘continuant’ in which a continuant is understood to be any
particular that exists for some stretch of time, regardless of whether it is the
whole of the particular or only some part of it that is present at each moment
of the particular’s existence. According to this usage, an entity that is made
up of time slices would be a kind of continuant rather than some other kind of
particular. Philosophers have disputed whether ordinary objects such as
cabbages and kings endure through time are continuants or only extend through
time are sequences of time slices. Some argue that to understand the
possibility of change one must think of such objects as sequences of time
slices; others argue that for the same reason one must think of such objects as
continuants. If an object changes, it comes to be different from itself. Some
argue that this would be possible only if an object consisted of distinct, successive
stages; so that change would simply consist in the differences among the
successive temporal parts of an object. Others argue that this view would make
change impossible; that differences among the successive temporal parts of a
thing would no more imply the thing had changed than differences among its
spatial parts would.
token-reflexive, an
expression that refers to itself in an act of speech or writing, such as ‘this
token’. The term was coined by Reichenbach, who conjectured that all
indexicals, all expressions whose semantic value depends partly on features of
the context of utterance, are tokenreflexive and definable in terms of the
phrase ‘this token’. He suggested that ‘I’ means the same as ‘the person who
utters this token’, ‘now’ means the same as ‘the time at which this token is
uttered’, ‘this table’ means the same as ‘the table pointed to by a gesture
accompanying this token’, and so forth. Russell made a somewhat similar
suggestion in his discussion of egocentric particulars. Reichenbach’s
conjecture is widely regarded as false; although ‘I’ does pick out the person
using it, it is not synonymous with ‘the person who utters this token’. If it
were, as David Kaplan observes, ‘If no one were to utter this token, I would
not exist’ would be true.
Toletus, Francisco
153296, Spanish Jesuit theologian and philosopher. Born in Córdoba, he studied
at Valencia, Salamanca, and Rome, and became the first Jesuit cardinal in 1594.
He composed commentaries on several of Aristotle’s works and a commentary on
Aquinas’s Summa theologiae. Toletus followed a Thomistic line, but departed
from Thomism in some details. He held that individuals are directly apprehended
by the intellect and that the agent intellect is the same power as the possible
intellect. He rejected the Thomistic doctrines of the real distinction between
essence and existence and of individuation by designated matter; for Toletus
individuation results from form.
AQUINAS. J.J.E.G. tonk, a sentential connective whose meaning and logic
are completely characterized by the two rules or axioms 1 [P P P tonk Q] and 2
[P tonk Q P Q]. If 1 and 2 are added to any normal system, then every Q can be
derived from any P. Arthur Prior invented ‘tonk’ to show that deductive
validity must not be conceived as depending solely on arbitrary syntactically
defined rules or axioms. We may prohibit ‘tonk’ on the ground that it is not a
natural, independently meaningful notion, but we may also prohibit it on purely
syntactical grounds. E.g., we may require that, for every connective C, the
C-introduction rule [xxx P . . . C . . .] and the C-elimination rule [ - - - C
- - - P yyy] be such that the yyy is part of xxx or is related to xxx in some
other syntactical way.
topic-neutral,
noncommittal between two or more ontological interpretations of a term. J. J.
C. Smart in 1959 suggested that introspective reports can be taken as topic-neutral:
composed of terms neutral between “dualistic metaphysics” and “materialistic
metaphysics.” When one asserts, e.g., that one has a yellowish-orange
afterimage, this is tantamount to saying ‘There is something going on that is
like what is going on when I have my eyes open, am awake, and there is an
orange illuminated in good light in front of me, i.e., when I really see an
orange’. The italicized phrase is, in Smart’s terms, topic-neutral; it refers
to an event, while remaining noncommittal about whether it is material or
immaterial. The term has not always been restricted to neutrality regarding
dualism and materialism. Smart suggests that topic-neutral descriptions are
composed of “quasi-logical” words, and hence would be suitable for any occasion
where a relatively noncommittal expression of a view is required.
topics, the analysis of
common strategies of argumentation, later a genre of literature analyzing
syllogistic reasoning. Aristotle considered the analysis of types of argument,
or “topics,” the best means of describing the art of dialectical reasoning; he
also used the term to refer to the principle underlying the strategy’s
production of an argument. Later classical commentators on Aristotle,
particularly Latin rhetoricians like Cicero, developed Aristotle’s discussions
of the theory of dialectical reasoning into a philosophical form. Boethius’s
work on topics exemplifies the later classical expansion of the scope of topics
literature. For him, a topic is either a self-evidently true universal
generalization, also called a “maximal proposition,” or a differentia, a member
of the set of a maximal proposition’s characteristics that determine its genus
and species. Man is a rational animal is a maximal proposition, and like from
genus, the differentia that characterizes the maximal proposition as concerning
genera, it is a topic. Because he believed dialectical reasoning leads to
categorical, not conditional, conclusions, Boethius felt that the discovery of
an argument entailed discovering a middle term uniting the two, previously
unjoined terms of the conclusion. Differentiae are the genera of these middle
terms, and one constructs arguments by choosing differentiae, thereby
determining the middle term leading to the conclusion. In the eleventh century,
Boethius’s logical structure of maximal propositions and differentiae was used
to study hypothetical syllogisms, while twelfth-century theorists like Abelard
extended the applicability of topics structure to the categorical syllogism. By
the thirteenth century, Peter of Spain, Robert Kilwardby, and Boethius of Dacia
applied topics structure exclusively to the categorical syllogism, principally
those with non-necessary, probable premises. Within a century, discussion of
topics structure to evaluate syllogistic reasoning was subsumed by consequences
literature, which described implication, entailment, and inference relations
between propositions. While the theory of consequences as an approach to
understanding relations between propositions is grounded in Boethian, and
perhaps Stoic, logic, it became prominent only in the later thirteenth century
with Burley’s recognition of the logical significance of propositional
logic.
toxin puzzle, a puzzle
about intention and practical rationality posed by Gregory Kavka. A trustworthy
billionaire offers you a million dollars for intending tonight to drink a
certain toxin tomorrow. You are convinced that he can tell what you intend
independently of what you do. The toxin would make you painfully ill for a day,
but you need to drink it to get the money. Constraints on the formation of a
prize-winning intention include prohibitions against “gimmicks,” “external
incentives,” and forgetting relevant details. For example, you will not receive
the money if you have a hypnotist “implant the intention” or hire a hit man to
kill you should you not drink the toxin. If, by midnight tonight, without
violating any rules, you form an intention to drink the toxin tomorrow, you
will find a million dollars in your bank account when you awake tomorrow
morning. You probably would drink the toxin for a million dollars. But can you,
without violating the rules, intend tonight to drink it tomorrow? Apparently,
you have no reason to drink it and an excellent reason not to drink it.
Seemingly, you will infer from this that you will eschew drinking the toxin,
and believing that you will top-down toxin puzzle 924 924 eschew drinking it seems inconsistent
with intending to drink it. Even so, there are several reports in the
philosophical literature of possible people who struck it rich when offered the
toxin deal!
transcendence, broadly,
the property of rising out of or above other things virtually always understood
figuratively; in philosophy, the property of being, in some way, of a higher
order. A being, such as God, may be said to be transcendent in the sense of
being not merely superior, but incomparably superior, to other things, in any
sort of perfection. God’s transcendence, or being outside or beyond the world,
is also contrasted, and by some thinkers combined, with God’s immanence, or
existence within the world. In medieval philosophy of logic, terms such as
‘being’ and ‘one’, which did not belong uniquely to any one of the Aristotelian
categories or types of predication such as substance, quality, and relation,
but could be predicated of things belonging to any or to none of them, were
called transcendental. In Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, principles that
profess wrongly to take us beyond the limits of any possible experience are
called transcendent; whereas anything belonging to non-empirical thought that
establishes, and draws consequences from, the possibility and limits of
experience may be called transcendental. Thus a transcendental argument in a
sense still current is one that proceeds from premises about the way in which
experience is possible to conclusions about what must be true of any
experienced world. Transcendentalism was a philosophical or religious movement
in mid-nineteenth-century New England, characterized, in the thought of its
leading representative, Ralph Waldo Emerson, by belief in a transcendent
spiritual and divine principle in human nature.
transcendental argument,
an argument that elucidates the conditions for the possibility of some
fundamental phenomenon whose existence is unchallenged or uncontroversial in
the philosophical context in which the argument is propounded. Such an argument
proceeds deductively, from a premise asserting the existence of some basic
phenomenon such as meaningful discourse, conceptualization of objective states
of affairs, or the practice of making promises, to a conclusion asserting the
existence of some interesting, substantive enabling conditions for that
phenomenon. The term derives from Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, which gives
several such arguments. The paradigmatic Kantian transcendental argument is the
“Transcendental Deduction of the Pure Concepts of Understanding.” Kant argued
there that the objective validity of certain pure, or a priori, concepts the
“categories” is a condition for the possibility of experience. Among the
concepts allegedly required for having experience are those of substance and
cause. Their apriority consists in the fact that instances of these concepts
are not directly given in sense experience in the manner of instances of
empirical concepts such as red. This fact gave rise to the skepticism of Hume
concerning the very coherence of such alleged a priori concepts. Now if these
concepts do have objective validity, as Kant endeavored to prove in opposition
to Hume, then the world contains genuine instances of the concepts. In a
transcendental argument concerning the conditions for the possibility of
experience, it is crucial that some feature entailed by the having of
experience is identified. Then it is argued that experience could not have this
feature without satisfying some substantive conditions. In the Transcendental
Deduction, the feature of experience on which Kant concentrates is the ability
of a subject of experience to be aware of several distinct inner states as all
belonging to a single consciousness. There is no general agreement on how
Kant’s argument actually unfolded, though it seems clear to most that he
focused on the role of the categories in the synthesis or combination of one’s
inner states in judgments, where such synthesis is said to be required for
one’s awareness of the states as being all equally one’s own states. Another
famous Kantian transcendental argument
the “Refutation of Idealism” in the CriToynbee, Arnold transcendental
argument 925 925 tique of Pure
Reason shares a noteworthy trait with
the Transcendental Deduction. The Refutation proceeds from the premise that one
is conscious of one’s own existence as determined in time, i.e., knows the
temporal order of some of one’s inner states. According to the Refutation, a
condition for the possibility of such knowledge is one’s consciousness of the
existence of objects located outside oneself in space. If one is indeed so
conscious, that would refute the skeptical view, formulated by Descartes, that
one lacks knowledge of the existence of a spatial world distinct from one’s
mind and its inner states. Both of the Kantian transcendental arguments we have
considered, then, conclude that the falsity of some skeptical view is a
condition for the possibility of some phenomenon whose existence is
acknowledged even by the skeptic the having of experience; knowledge of
temporal facts about one’s own inner states. Thus, we can isolate an
interesting subclass of transcendental arguments: those which are
anti-skeptical in nature. Barry Stroud has raised the question whether such
arguments depend on some sort of suppressed verificationism according to which
the existence of language or conceptualization requires the availability of the
knowledge that the skeptic questions since verificationism has it that
meaningful sentences expressing coherent concepts, e.g., ‘There are tables’,
must be verifiable by what is given in sense experience. Dependence on a highly
controversial premise is undesirable in itself. Further, Stroud argued, such a
dependence would render superfluous whatever other content the anti-skeptical
transcendental argument might embody since the suppressed premise alone would
refute the skeptic. There is no general agreement on whether Stroud’s doubts
about anti-skeptical transcendental arguments are well founded. It is not
obvious whether the doubts apply to arguments that do not proceed from a
premise asserting the existence of language or conceptualization, but instead
conform more closely to the Kantian model. Even so, no anti-skeptical
transcendental argument has been widely accepted. This is evidently due to the
difficulty of uncovering substantive enabling conditions for phenomena that even
a skeptic will countenance.
transcendentalism, a
religious-philosophical viewpoint held by a group of New England intellectuals,
of whom Emerson, Thoreau, and Theodore Parker were the most important. A
distinction taken over from Samuel Taylor Coleridge was the only bond that
universally united the members of the Transcendental Club, founded in 1836: the
distinction between the understanding and reason, the former providing
uncertain knowledge of appearances, the latter a priori knowledge of necessary
truths gained through intuition. The transcendentalists insisted that philosophical
truth could be reached only by reason, a capacity common to all people unless
destroyed by living a life of externals and accepting as true only secondhand
traditional beliefs. On almost every other point there were disagreements.
Emerson was an idealist, while Parker was a natural realist they simply had conflicting a priori
intuitions. Emerson, Thoreau, and Parker rejected the supernatural aspects of
Christianity, pointing out its unmistakable parochial nature and sociological
development; while James Marsh, Frederick Henry Hedge, and Caleb Henry remained
in the Christian fold. The influences on the transcendentalists differed widely
and explain the diversity of opinion. For example, Emerson was influenced by
the Platonic tradition, German Romanticism, Eastern religions, and nature
poets, while Parker was influenced by modern science, the Scottish realism of
Reid and Cousin which also emphasized a priori intuitions, and the German
Higher Critics. Emerson, Thoreau, and Parker were also bonded by negative
beliefs. They not only rejected Calvinism but Unitarianism as well; they
rejected the ordinary concept of material success and put in its place an
Aristotelian type of selfrealization that emphasized the rational and moral
self as the essence of humanity and decried idiosyncratic self-realization that
admires what is unique in people as constituting their real value.
transcendentals, also
called transcendentalia, terms or concepts that apply to all things regardless
of the things’ ontological kind or category. transcendental deduction
transcendentals 926 926 Terms or
concepts of this sort are transcendental in the sense that they transcend or
are superordinate to all classificatory categories. The classical doctrine of
the transcendentals, developed in detail in the later Middle Ages, presupposes
an Aristotelian ontology according to which all beings are substances or
accidents classifiable within one of the ten highest genera, the ten
Aristotelian categories. In this scheme being Grecian on, Latin ens is not
itself one of the categories since all categories mark out kinds of being. But
neither is it a category above the ten categories of substance and accidents,
an ultimate genus of which the ten categories are species. This is because
being is homonymous or equivocal, i.e., there is no single generic property or
nature shared by members of each category in virtue of which they are beings.
The ten categories identify ten irreducible, most basic ways of being. Being,
then, transcends the categorial structure of the world: anything at all that is
ontologically classifiable is a being, and to say of anything that it is a
being is not to identify it as a member of some kind distinct from other kinds
of things. According to this classical doctrine, being is the primary
transcendental, but there are other terms or concepts that transcend the
categories in a similar way. The most commonly recognized transcendentals other
than being are one unum, true verum, and good bonum, though some medieval
philosophers also recognized thing res, something aliquid, and beautiful
pulchrum. These other terms or concepts are transcendental because the
ontological ground of their application to a given thing is precisely the same
as the ontological ground in virtue of which that thing can be called a being.
For example, for a thing with a certain nature to be good is for it to perform
well the activity that specifies it as a thing of that nature, and to perform
this activity well is to have actualized that nature to a certain extent. But
for a thing to have actualized its nature to some extent is just what it is for
the thing to have being. So the actualities or properties in virtue of which a
thing is good are precisely those in virtue of which it has being. Given this
account, medieval philosophers held that transcendental terms are convertible
convertuntur or extensionally equivalent idem secundum supposita. They are not
synonymous, however, since they are intensionally distinct differunt secundum
rationem. These secondary transcendentals are sometimes characterized as
attributes passiones of being that are necessarily concomitant with it. In the
modern period, the notion of the transcendental is associated primarily with
Kant, who made ‘transcendental’ a central technical term in his philosophy. For
Kant the term no longer signifies that which transcends categorial
classification but that which transcends our experience in the sense of
providing its ground or structure. Kant allows, e.g., that the pure forms of
intuition space and time and the pure concepts of understanding categories such
as substance and cause are transcendental in this sense. Forms and concepts of
this sort constitute the conditions of the possibility of experience.
transfinite number, in
set theory, an infinite cardinal or ordinal number.
transformation rule, an
axiom-schema or rule of inference. A transformation rule is thus a rule for
transforming a possibly empty set of wellformed formulas into a formula, where
that rule operates only upon syntactic information. It was this conception of
an axiom-schema and rule of inference that was one of the keys to creating a
genuinely rigorous science of deductive reasoning. In the 1950s, the idea was
imported into linguistics, giving rise to the notion of a transformational
rule. Such a rule transforms tree structures into tree structures, taking one
from the deep structure of a sentence, which determines its semantic
interpretation, to the surface structure of that sentence, which determines its
phonetic interpretation.
transubstantiation,
change of one substance into another. Aristotelian metaphysics distinguishes
between substances and the accidents that inhere in them; thus, Socrates is a
substance and being snub-nosed is one of his accidents. The Roman Catholic and
Eastern Orthodox churches appeal to transubstantiation to explain how Jesus
Christ becomes really present in the Eucharist when the consecration takes
place: the whole substances of the bread and wine are transformed into the body
and blood of Christ, but the accidents of the bread and wine such as their
shape, color, and taste persist after the transformation. This seems to commit
its adherents to holding that these persisting accidents subsequently either
inhere in Christ or do not inhere in any substance. Luther proposed an
alternative explanation in terms of consubstantiation that avoids this hard
choice: the substances of the bread and wine coexist in the Eucharist with the
body and blood of Christ after the consecration; they are united but each
remains unchanged. P.L.Q. transvaluation of values.
transversality,
transcendence of the sovereignty of identity or self-sameness by recognizing
the alterity of the Other as Unterschied
to use Heidegger’s term which
signifies the sense of relatedness by way of difference. An innovative idea
employed and appropriated by such diverse philosophers as Merleau-Ponty,
Sartre, Gilles Deleuze, and Félix Guattari, transversality is meant to replace
the Eurocentric formulation of truth as universal in an age when the world is
said to be rushing toward the global village. Universality has been a
Eurocentric idea because what is particular in the West is universalized,
whereas what is particular elsewhere remains particularized. Since its center
is everywhere and its circumference nowhere, truth is polycentric and
correlative. Particularly noteworthy is the American phenomenologist Calvin O.
Schrag’s attempt to appropriate transversality by splitting the difference
between the two extremes of absolutism and relativism on the one hand and
modernity’s totalizing practices and postmodernity’s fragmentary tendencies on
the other.
Arbor porphyriana: a structure generated from the logical and
metaphysical apparatus of Aristotle’s Categories, as systematized by Porphyry
and later writers. A tree in the category of substance begins with substance as
its highest genus and divides that genus into mutually exclusive and
collectively exhaustive subordinate genera by means of a pair of opposites,
called differentiae, yielding, e.g., corporeal substance and incorporeal
substance. The process of division by differentiae continues until a lowest
species is reached, a species that cannot be divided further. The species
“human being” is said to be a lowest species whose derivation can be recaptured
from the formula “mortal, rational, sensitive, animate, corporeal
substance.”
Trinitarianism, the
theological doctrine that God consists of three persons. The persons who
constitute the Holy Trinity are the Father; the Son, who is Jesus Christ; and
the Holy Spirit or Holy Ghost. The doctrine states that each of these three
persons is God and yet they are not three Gods but one God. According to a
traditional formulation, the three persons are but one substance. In the
opinion of Aquinas, the existence of God can be proved by human reason, but the
existence of the three persons cannot be proved and is known only by
revelation. According to Christian tradition, revelation contains information
about the relations among the three persons, and these relations ground proper
attributes of each that distinguish them from one another. Thus, since the
Father begets the Son, a proper attribute of the Father is paternity and a
proper attribute of the Son is filiation. Procession transparent Trinitarianism
928 928 or spiration is a proper
attribute of the Holy Spirit. A disagreement about procession has contributed
to dividing Eastern and Western Christianity. The Eastern Orthodox church
teaches that the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Father through the Son. A theory
of double procession according to which the Holy Spirit proceeds from the
Father and the Son has been widely accepted in the West. This disagreement is
known as the filioque ‘and the Son’ controversy because it arose from the fact
that adding this Latin phrase to the Nicene Creed became acceptable in the West
but not in the East. Unitarianism denies that God consists of three persons and
so is committed to denying the divinity of Jesus. The monotheistic faiths of
Judaism and Islam are unitarian, but there are unitarians who consider
themselves Christians.
Troeltsch, Ernst
18651923, German philosopher and historian whose primary aim was to provide a
scientific foundation for theology. Educated at Erlangen, Göttingen under
Ritschl and Lagarde, and Berlin, he initially taught theology at Heidelberg and
later philosophy in Berlin. He launched the school of history of religion with
his epoch-making “On Historical and Dogmatical Method in Theology” 1896. His
contributions to theology The Religious Apriori, 1904, philosophy, sociology,
and history Historicism and Its Problems, 1922 were vastly influential.
Troeltsch claimed that only a philosophy of religion drawn from the history and
development of religious consciousness could strengthen the standing of the
science of religion among the sciences and advance the Christian strategy
against materialism, naturalism, skepticism, aestheticism, and pantheism. His
historical masterpiece, Protestantism and Progress 1906, argues that early
Protestantism was a modified medieval Catholicism that delayed the development
of modern culture. As a sociologist, he addressed, in The Social Teachings of
the Christian Churches 1912, the twofold issue of whether religious beliefs and
movements are conditioned by external factors and whether, in turn, they affect
society and culture. From Christian social history he inferred three types of
“sociological self-formation of the Christian idea”: the church, the sect, and
the mystic
trope, in recent
philosophical usage, an “abstract particular”; an instance of a property
occurring at a particular place and time, such as the color of the cover of
this book or this . The whiteness of this
and the whiteness of the previous
are two distinct tropes, identical neither with the universal whiteness
that is instantiated in both s, nor with the
itself; although the whiteness of this
cannot exist independently of this , this could be dyed some other color. A number of
writers, perhaps beginning with D. C. Williams, have argued that tropes must be
included in our ontology if we are to achieve an adequate metaphysics. More
generally, a trope is a figure of speech, or the use of an expression in a
figurative or nonliteral sense. Metaphor and irony, e.g., fall under the
category of tropes. If you are helping someone move a glass table but drop your
end, and your companion says, “Well, you’ve certainly been a big help,” her
utterance is probably ironical, with the intended meaning that you have been no
help. One important question is whether, in order to account for the ironical
use of this sentence, we must suppose that it has an ironical meaning in addition
to its literal meaning. Quite generally, does a sentence usable to express two
different metaphors have, in addition to its literal meaning, two metaphorical
meanings and another if it can be
hyperbolic, and so forth? Many philosophers and other theorists from Aristotle
on have answered yes, and postulated such figurative meanings in addition to
literal sentence meaning. Recently, philosophers loath to multiply sentence
meanings have denied that sentences have any non-literal meanings.Their burden
is to explain how, e.g., a sentence can be used ironically if it does not have
an ironical sense or meaning. Such philosophers disagree on whether tropes are
to be explained semantically or pragmatically. A semantic account might
hypothesize that tropes are generated by violations of semantical rules. An
important pragmatic approach is Grice’s suggestion that tropes can be subsumed
under the more general phenomenon of conversational implicature.
truth, the quality of
those propositions that accord with reality, specifying what is in fact the
case. Whereas the aim of a science is to discover which of the propositions in
its domain are true i.e., which propositions possess the property of Trinity
truth 929 929 truth the central philosophical concern with truth
is to discover the nature of that property. Thus the philosophical question is
not What is true? but rather, What is truth?
What is one saying about a proposition in saying that it is true? The
importance of this question stems from the variety and depth of the principles
in which the concept of truth is deployed. We are tempted to think, e.g., that
truth is the proper aim and natural result of scientific inquiry, that true
beliefs are useful, that the meaning of a sentence is given by the conditions
that would render it true, and that valid reasoning preserves truth. Therefore
insofar as we wish to understand, assess, and refine these epistemological,
ethical, semantic, and logical views, some account of the nature of truth would
seem to be required. Such a thing, however, has been notoriously elusive. The
belief that snow is white owes its truth to a certain feature of the external
world: the fact that snow is white. Similarly, the belief that dogs bark is
true because of the fact that dogs bark. Such trivial observations lead to what
is perhaps the most natural and widely held account of truth, the
correspondence theory, according to which a belief statement, sentence,
proposition, etc. is true provided there exists a fact corresponding to it.
This Aristotelian thesis is unexceptionable in itself. However, if it is to
provide a complete theory of truth and
if it is to be more than merely a picturesque way of asserting all instances of
‘the belief that p is true if and only if p’
then it must be supplemented with accounts of what facts are, and what
it is for a belief to correspond to a fact; and these are the problems on which
the correspondence theory of truth has foundered. A popular alternative to the
correspondence theory has been to identify truth with verifiability. This idea
can take on various forms. One version involves the further assumption that
verification is holistic i.e., that a
belief is verified when it is part of an entire system of beliefs that is consistent
and “harmonious.” This is known as the coherence theory of truth and was
developed by Bradley and Brand Blanchard. Another version, due to Dummett and
Putnam, involves the assumption that there is, for each proposition, some
specific procedure for finding out whether one should believe it or not. On
this account, to say that a proposition is true is to say that it would be
verified by the appropriate procedure. In mathematics this amounts to the
identification of truth with provability and is sometimes referred to as
intuitionistic truth. Such theories aim to avoid obscure metaphysical notions
and explain the close relation between knowability and truth. They appear,
however, to overstate the intimacy of that link: for we can easily imagine a
statement that, though true, is beyond our power to establish as true. A third
major account of truth is James’s pragmatic theory. As we have just seen, the
verificationist selects a prominent property of truth and considers it to be
the essence of truth. Similarly the pragmatist focuses on another important
characteristic namely, that true beliefs
are a good basis for action and takes
this to be the very nature of truth. True assumptions are said to be, by
definition, those that provoke actions with desirable results. Again we have an
account with a single attractive explanatory feature. But again the central
objection is that the relationship it postulates between truth and its alleged
analysans in this case, utility is implausibly close. Granted, true beliefs
tend to foster success. But often actions based on true beliefs lead to
disaster, while false assumptions, by pure chance, produce wonderful results.
One of the few fairly uncontroversial facts about truth is that the proposition
that snow is white is true if and only if snow is white, the proposition that
lying is wrong is true if and only if lying is wrong, and so on. Traditional
theories of truth acknowledge this fact but regard it as insufficient and, as
we have seen, inflate it with some further principle of the form ‘X is true if
and only if X has property P’ such as corresponding to reality, verifiability,
or being suitable as a basis for action, which is supposed to specify what
truth is. A collection of radical alternatives to the traditional theories
results from denying the need for any such further specification. For example,
one might suppose with Ramsey, Ayer, and Strawson that the basic theory of
truth contains nothing more than equivalences of the form, ‘The proposition
that p is true if and only if p’ excluding instantiation by sentences such as
‘This proposition is not true’ that generate contradiction. This so-called
deflationary theory is best presented following Quine in conjunction with an
account of the raison d’être of our notion of truth: namely, that its function
is not to describe propositions, as one might naively infer from its syntactic
form, but rather to enable us to construct a certain type of generalization.
For example, ‘What Einstein said is true’ is intuitively equivalent to the
infinite conjunction ‘If Einstein said that nothing goes faster than light,
then nothing goes faster than light; and if Einstein said truth truth 930 930 that nuclear weapons should never be
built, then nuclear weapons should never be built; . . . and so on.’ But
without a truth predicate we could not capture this statement. The deflationist
argues, moreover, that all legitimate uses of the truth predicate including those in science, logic, semantics,
and metaphysics are simply displays of
this generalizing function, and that the equivalence schema is just what is
needed to explain that function. Within the deflationary camp there are various
competing proposals. According to Frege’s socalled redundancy theory,
corresponding instances of ‘It is true that p’ and ‘p’ have exactly the same
meaning, whereas the minimalist theory assumes merely that such propositions
are necessarily equivalent. Other deflationists are skeptical about the
existence of propositions and therefore take sentences to be the basic vehicles
of truth. Thus the disquotation theory supposes that truth is captured by the
disquotation principle, ‘p’ is true if and only if p’. More ambitiously, Tarski
does not regard the disquotation principle, also known as Tarski’s T schema, as
an adequate theory in itself, but as a specification of what any adequate
definition must imply. His own account shows how to give an explicit definition
of truth for all the sentences of certain formal languages in terms of the
referents of their primitive names and predicates. This is known as the
semantic theory of truth. .
truthlikeness, a term
introduced by Karl Popper in 1960 to explicate the idea that one theory may
have a better correspondence with reality, or be closer to the truth, or have
more verisimilitude, than another theory. Truthlikeness, which combines truth
with information content, has to be distinguished from probability, which
increases with lack of content. Let T and F be the classes of all true and
false sentences, respectively, and A and B deductively closed sets of sentences.
According to Popper’s qualitative definition, A is more truthlike than B if and
only if B 3 T 0 A 3 T and A 3 F 0 B 3 F, where one of these setinclusions is
strict. In particular, when A and B are non-equivalent and both true, A is more
truthlike than B if and only if A logically entails B. David Miller and Pavel
Tichý proved in 1974 that Popper’s definition is not applicable to the
comparison of false theories: if A is more truthlike than B, then A must be
true. Since the mid-1970s, a new approach to truthlikeness has been based upon
the concept of similarity: the degree of truthlikeness of a statement A depends
on the distances from the states of affairs allowed by A to the true state. In
Graham Oddie’s Likeness to Truth 1986, this dependence is expressed by the
average function; in Ilkka Niiniluoto’s Truthlikeness 1987, by the weighted
average of the minimum distance and the sum of all distances. The concept of
verisimilitude is also used in the epistemic sense to express a rational
evaluation of how close to the truth a theory appears to be on available
evidence.
truth table, a tabular
display of one or more truth-functions, truth-functional operators, or
representatives of truth-functions or truth-functional operators such as
well-formed formulas of propositional logic. In the tabular display, each row
displays a possible assignment of truthvalues to the arguments of the
truth-functions or truth-functional operators. Thus, the collection of all rows
in the table displays all possible assignments of truth-values to these
arguments. The following simple truth table represents the truth-functional
operators negation and conjunction: truth, coherence theory of truth table
931 931 Because a truth table displays
all possible assignments of truth-values to the arguments of a truth-function,
truth tables are useful devices for quickly ascertaining logical properties of
propositions. If, e.g., all entries in the column of a truth table representing
a proposition are T, then the proposition is true for all possible assignments
of truth-values to its ultimate constituent propositions; in this sort of case,
the proposition is said to be logically or tautologically true: a tautology. If
all entries in the column of a truth table representing a proposition are F,
then the proposition is false for all possible assignments of truth-values to
its ultimate constituent propositions, and the proposition is said to be
logically or tautologically false: a contradiction. If a proposition is neither
a tautology nor a contradiction, then it is said to be a contingency. The truth
table above shows that both Not-P and Pand-Q are contingencies. For the same
reason that truth tables are useful devices for ascertaining the logical
qualities of single propositions, truth tables are also useful for ascertaining
whether arguments are valid or invalid. A valid argument is one such that there
is no possibility no row in the relevant truth table in which all its premises
are true and its conclusion false. Thus the above truth table shows that the
argument ‘P-and-Q; therefore, P’ is valid.
truth-value, most
narrowly, one of the values T for ‘true’ or F for ‘false’ that a proposition
may be considered to have or take on when it is regarded as true or false,
respectively. More broadly, a truth-value is any one of a range of values that
a proposition may be considered to have when taken to have one of a range of
different cognitive or epistemic statuses. For example, some philosophers speak
of the truth-value I for ‘indeterminate’ and regard a proposition as having the
value I when it is indeterminate whether the proposition is true or false.
Logical systems employing a specific number n of truthvalues are said to be
n-valued logical systems; the simplest sort of useful logical system has two
truth-values, T and F, and accordingly is said to be two-valued.
Truth-functions are functions that take truth-values as arguments and that
yield truth-values as resultant values. The truthtable method in propositional
logic exploits the idea of truth-functions by using tabular displays.
truth-value semantics,
interpretations of formal systems in which the truth-value of a formula rests
ultimately only on truth-values that are assigned to its atomic subformulas
where ‘subformula’ is suitably defined. The label is due to Hugues Leblanc. On
a truth-value interpretation for first-order predicate logic, for example, the
formula atomic ExFx is true in a model if and only if all its instances Fm, Fn,
. . . are true, where the truth-value of these formulas is simply assigned by
the model. On the standard Tarskian or objectual interpretation, by contrast,
ExFx is true in a model if and only if every object in the domain of the model
is an element of the set that interprets F in the model. Thus a truth-value
semantics for predicate logic comprises a substitutional interpretation of the
quantifiers and a “non-denotational” interpretation of terms and predicates. If
t 1, t 2, . . . are all the terms of some first-order language, then there are
objectual models that satisfy the set {Dx-Fx, Ft1, Ft2 . . . .}, but no
truth-value interpretations that do. One can ensure that truth-value semantics
delivers the standard logic, however, by suitable modifications in the
definitions of consistency and consequence. A set G of formulas of language L
is said to be consistent, for example, if there is some G' obtained from G by
relettering terms such that G' is satisfied by some truth-value assignment, or,
alternatively, if there is some language L+ obtained by adding terms to L such
that G is satisfied by some truth-value assignment to the atoms of L+.
Truth-value semantics is of both technical and philosophical interest.
Technically, it allows the completeness of first-order predicate logic and a
variety of other formal systems to be obtained in a natural way from that of
propositional logic. Philosophically, it dramatizes the fact that the formulas
in one’s theories about the world do not, in themselves, determine one’s
ontological commitments. It is at least possible to interpret first-order
formulas without reference to special truth-table method truth-value semantics
932 932 domains of objects, and
higher-order formulas without reference to special domains of relations and
properties. The idea of truth-value semantics dates at least to the writings of
E. W. Beth on first-order predicate logic in 1959 and of K. Schütte on simple
type theory in 1960. In more recent years similar semantics have been suggested
for secondorder logics, modal and tense logics, intuitionistic logic, and set
theory.
Tsou Yen 350?270? B.C.,
Chinese cosmologist, a member of the Chi-hsia Academy and influential political
figure who applied yinyang fivephases thinking to dynastic cycles. Tsou Yen
believed that the natural order, the human order, and the relation between the
two were all governed and made intelligible by the dynamic interplay among
yinyang and the five phases wu-hsing: earth, wood, metal, fire, and water. He
gained political fame for his idea that the rise and fall of dynasties are
correlated with the five phases and accord with the same cyclical pattern:
earth, wood, metal, fire, and water. Thus, the reign of the Yellow Emperor,
correlated with the earth phase, was followed by the Hsia wood, the Shang
metal, and the Chou fire dynasties. Tsou Yen predicted that the ascendancy of
the water phase would signal the end of the Chou and the beginning of a new
dynasty.
Tung Chung-shu c.179c.104
B.C., Chinese philosopher, a Han scholar famous for his answers to questions by
Emperor Wu, which were instrumental in making Confucianism the state doctrine
in 136 B.C. He wrote Ch’un-ch’iu fan-lu “Luxuriant Gems of the Spring and
Autumn Annals”, in which he read moral messages from historical events recorded
in the classic in such a way that they could be applied to future history.
Tung’s teachings were actually quite different from those of Confucius and
Mencius. He believed that Heaven and the Way do not change, and he taught the
so-called Three Bonds, according to which the ruler, the father, and the
husband are to be the standards of the ruled, the son, and the wife. These
added a conservative ring to Confucianism, so that the rulers were happy to use
it in combination with Legalist practice to create a state Confucianism. He
also incorporated many ideas from the yinyang school in his philosophy. He
believed that history goes in cycles, the five powers wood, fire, earth, metal,
water succeed each other, and there is a strict correlation between natural
affairs and human affairs. He saw natural disasters as warning signs for the rulers
to cultivate virtues and not to abuse their powers.
Turing machine, an
abstract automaton or imagined computer consisting of a finite automaton
operating an indefinitely long storage tape. The finite automaton provides the
computing power of the machine. The tape is used for input, output, and
calculation workspace; in the case of the universal Turing machine, it also
specifies another Turing machine. Initially, only a finite number of squares of
the tape are marked with symbols, while the rest are blank. The finite
automaton part of the machine has a finite number of internal states and
operates discretely, at times t % 0, 1, 2, . . . . At each time-step the
automaton examines the tape square under its tape head, possibly changes what
is there, moves the tape left or right, and then changes its internal state.
The law governing this sequence of actions is deterministic and is defined in a
state table. For each internal state and each tape symbol or blank under the
tape head, the state table describes the tape action performed by the machine
and gives the next internal state of the machine. Since a machine has only a
finite number of internal states and of tape symbols, the state table of a
machine is finite in length and can be stored on a tape. There is a universal
Turing machine Mu that can simulate every Turing machine including itself: when
the state table of any machine M is written on the tape of Mu, the universal
machine Mu will perform the same input-output computation that M performs. Mu
does this by using the state table of M to calculate M’s complete history for
any given input. Turing machines may be thought of as conceptual devices for
enumerating the elements of an infinite set e.g., the theorems of a formal
language, or as decision machines e.g., deciding of any truth-functional
formula whether it is a tautology. A. M. Turing showed that there are
welldefined logical tasks that cannot be carried out by any machine; in
particular, no machine can solve the halting problem. Tsou Yen Turing machine
933 933 Turing’s definition of a
machine was theoretical; it was not a practical specification for a machine.
After the modern electronic computer was invented, he proposed a test for
judging whether there is a computer that is behaviorally equivalent to a human
in reasoning and intellectual creative power. The Turing test is a “black box”
type of experiment that Turing proposed as a way of deciding whether a computer
can think. Two rooms are fitted with the same input-output equipment going to
an outside experimenter. A person is placed in one room and a programmed
electronic computer in the other, each in communication with the experimenter.
By issuing instructions and asking questions, the experimenter tries to decide
which room has the computer and which the human. If the experimenter cannot
tell, that outcome is strong evidence that the computer can think as well as
the person. More directly, it shows that the computer and the human are
equivalent for all the behaviors tested. Since the computer is a finite
automaton, perhaps the most significant test task is that of doing creative
mathematics about the non-enumerable infinite.
Turnbull, George
16981748, Scottish moral sense philosopher and educational theorist. He was
briefly a philosophy regent at Aberdeen 172127 and a teacher of Reid. His
Principles of Moral and Christian Philosophy 1740 and Discourse upon the Nature
and Origin of Moral and Civil Laws 1741 show him as the most systematic of
those who aimed to recast moral philosophy on a Newtonian model, deriving moral
laws “experimentally” from human psychology. In A Treatise on Ancient Painting
1740, Observations Upon Liberal Education 1742, and some smaller works, he
extolled history and the arts as propaedeutic to the teaching of virtue and natural
religion.
Twin-Earth, a fictitious
planet first visited by Hilary Putnam in a thought experiment designed to show,
among other things, that “ ‘meanings’ just ain’t in the head” “The Meaning of
‘Meaning’,” 1975. Twin-Earth is exactly like Earth with one notable exception:
ponds, rivers, and ice trays on Twin-Earth contain, not H2O, but XYZ, a liquid
superficially indistinguishable from water but with a different chemical
constitution. According to Putnam, although some inhabitants of Twin-Earth closely
resemble inhabitants of Earth, ‘water’, when uttered by a Twin-Earthling, does
not mean water. Water is H2O, and, on Twin-Earth, the word ‘water’ designates a
different substance, XYZ, Twin-water. The moral drawn by Putnam is that the
meanings of at least some of our words, and the significance of some of our
thoughts, depend, in part, on how things stand outside our heads. Two
“molecular duplicates,” two agents with qualitatively similar mental lives,
might mean very different things by their utterances and think very different
thoughts. Although Twin-Earth has become a popular stopping-off place for
philosophers en route to theories of meaning and mental content, others regard
Twin-Earth as hopelessly remote, doubting that useful conclusions can be drawn
about our Earthly circumstances from research conducted there.
tychism from Grecian
tyche, ‘chance’, Peirce’s doctrine that there is absolute chance in the
universe and its fundamental laws are probabilistic and inexact. Peirce’s
tychism is part of his evolutionary cosmology, according to which all
regularities of nature are products of growth and development, i.e., results of
evolution. The laws of nature develop over time and become increasingly rigid
and exact; the apparently deterministic laws of physics are limiting cases of
the basic, probabilistic laws. Underlying all other laws is “the tendency of
all things to take habits”; Peirce calls this the Law of Habit. In his
cosmology his tychism is associated with synechism, the doctrine of the continuity
of nature. His synechism involves the doctrine of the continuity of mind and
matter; Peirce sometimes expressed this view by saying that “matter is effete
mind.”
type theory, broadly, any
theory according to which the things that exist fall into natural, perhaps
mutually exclusive, categories or types. In most modern discussions, ‘type
theory’ refers to the theory of logical types first sketched by Russell in The
Principles of Mathematics 1903. It is a theory of logical types insofar as it
purports only to classify things into the most general categories that must be
presupposed by an adequate logical theory. Russell proposed his theory in
response to his discovery of the now-famous paradox that bears his name. The
paradox is this. Common sense suggests that some classes are members of
themselves e.g., the class of all classes, while others are not e.g., the class
of philosophers. Let R be the class whose membership consists of exactly those
classes of the latter sort, i.e., those that are not members of themselves. Is
R a member of itself? If so, then it is a member of the class of all classes
that are not members of themselves, and hence is not a member of itself. If, on
the other hand, it is not a member of itself, then it satisfies its own
membership conditions, and hence is a member of itself after all. Either way
there is a contradiction. The source of the paradox, Russell suggested, is the
assumption that classes and their members form a single, homogeneous logical
type. To the contrary, he proposed that the logical universe is stratified into
a regimented hierarchy of types. Individuals constitute the lowest type in the
hierarchy, type 0. For purposes of exposition, individuals can be taken to be
ordinary objects like chairs and persons. Type 1 consists of classes of
individuals, type 2 of classes of classes of individuals, type 3 classes of
classes of classes of individuals, and so on. Unlike the homogeneous universe,
then, in the type hierarchy the members of a given class must all be drawn from
a single logical type n, and the class itself must reside in the next higher
type n ! 1. Russell’s sketch in the Principles differs from this account in
certain details. Russell’s paradox cannot arise in this conception of the
universe of classes. Because the members of a class must all be of the same
logical type, there is no such class as R, whose definition cuts across all
types. Rather, there is only, for each type n, the class Rn of all
non-self-membered classes of that type. Since Rn itself is of type n ! 1, the
paradox breaks down: from the assumption that Rn is not a member of itself as
in fact it is not in the type hierarchy, it no longer follows that it satisfies
its own membership conditions, since those conditions apply only to objects of
type n. Most formal type theories, including Russell’s own, enforce the class
membership restrictions of simple type theory syntactically such that a can be
asserted to be a member of b only if b is of the next higher type than a. In
such theories, the definition of R, hence the paradox itself, cannot even be
expressed. Numerous paradoxes remain unscathed by the simple type hierarchy. Of
these, the most prominent are the semantic paradoxes, so called because they
explicitly involve semantic notions like truth, as in the following version of
the liar paradox. Suppose Epimenides asserts that all the propositions he
asserts today are false; suppose also that that is the only proposition he
asserts today. It follows immediately that, under those conditions, the proposition
he asserts is true if and only if it is false. To address such paradoxes,
Russell was led to the more refined and substantially more complicated system
known as ramified type theory, developed in detail in his 1908 paper
“Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of Types.” In the ramified theory,
propositions and properties or propositional functions, in Russell’s jargon
come to play the central roles in the type-theoretic universe. Propositions are
best construed as the metaphysical and semantical counterparts of
sentences what sentences express and properties as the counterparts of “open
sentences” like ‘x is a philosopher’ that contain a variable ‘x’ in place of a
noun phrase. To distinguish linguistic expressions from their semantic
counterparts, the property expressed by, say, ‘x is a philosopher’, will be
denoted by ‘x ^ is a philosopher’, and the proposition expressed by ‘Aristotle
is a philosopher’ will be denoted by ‘Aristotle is a philosopher’. A property .
. .x ^ . . . is said to be true of an individual a if . . . a . . . is a true
proposition, and false of a if . . . a . . . is a false proposition where ‘. .
. a . . .’ is the result of replacing ‘x ^ ’ with ‘a’ in ‘. . . x ^ . . .’. So,
e.g., x ^ is a philosopher is true of Aristotle. The range of significance of a
property P is the collection of objects of which P is true or false. a is a
possible argument for P if it is in P’s range of significance. In the ramified
theory, the hierarchy of classes is supplanted by a hierarchy of properties:
first, properties of individuals i.e., properties whose range of significance
is restricted to individuals, then properties of properties of individuals, and
so on. Parallel to the simple theory, then, the type of a property must exceed
the type of its possible arguments by one. Thus, Russell’s paradox with R now
in the guise of the property x ^ is a property that is not true of itself is avoided along analogous lines. Following
the French mathematician Henri Poincaré, Russell traced the type theory type theory
935 935 source of the semantic
paradoxes to a kind of illicit self-reference. So, for example, in the liar
paradox, Epimenides ostensibly asserts a proposition p about all propositions,
p itself among them, namely that they are false if asserted by him today. p
thus refers to itself in the sense that it
or more exactly, the sentence that expresses it quantifies over i.e., refers generally to all
or some of the elements of a collection of entities among which p itself is
included. The source of semantic paradox thus isolated, Russell formulated the
vicious circle principle VCP, which proscribes all such self-reference in
properties and propositions generally. The liar proposition p and its ilk were
thus effectively banished from the realm of legitimate propositions and so the
semantic paradoxes could not arise. Wedded to the restrictions of simple type
theory, the VCP generates a ramified hierarchy based on a more complicated form
of typing. The key notion is that of an object’s order. The order of an
individual, like its type, is 0. However, the order of a property must exceed
the order not only of its possible arguments, as in simple type theory, but
also the orders of the things it quantifies over. Thus, type 1 properties like
x ^ is a philosopher and x ^ is as wise as all other philosophers are
first-order properties, since they are true of and, in the second instance,
quantify over, individuals only. Properties like these whose order exceeds the
order of their possible arguments by one are called predicative, and are of the
lowest possible order relative to their range of significance. Consider, by
contrast, the property call it Q x ^ has all the first-order properties of a
great philosopher. Like those above, Q also is a property of individuals. However,
since Q quantifies over first-order properties, by the VDP, it cannot be
counted among them. Accordingly, in the ramified hierarchy, Q is a second-order
property of individuals, and hence non-predicative or impredicative. Like Q,
the property x ^ is a first-order property of all great philosophers is also
second-order, since its range of significance consists of objects of order 1
and it quantifies only over objects of order 0; but since it is a property of
first-order properties, it is predicative. In like manner it is possible to
define third-order properties of individuals, third-order properties of
first-order properties, third-order properties of second-order properties of
individuals, third-order properties of secondorder properties of first-order
properties, and then, in the same fashion, fourth-order properties, fifth-order
properties, and so on ad infinitum. A serious shortcoming of ramified type
theory, from Russell’s perspective, is that it is an inadequate foundation for
classical mathematics. The most prominent difficulty is that many classical
theorems appeal to definitions that, though consistent, violate the VCP. For
instance, a wellknown theorem of real analysis asserts that every bounded set
of real numbers has a least upper bound. In the ramified theory, real numbers
are identified with certain predicative properties of rationals. Under such an
identification, the usual procedure is to define the least upper bound of a
bounded set S of reals to be the property call it b some real number in S is
true of x ^ , and then prove that this property is itself a real number with
the requisite characteristics. However, b quantifies over the real numbers.
Hence, by the VCP, b cannot itself be taken to be a real number: although of
the same type as the reals, and although true of the right things, b must be
assigned a higher order than the reals. So, contrary to the classical theorem,
S fails to have a least upper bound. Russell introduced a special axiom to
obviate this difficulty: the axiom of reducibility. Reducibility says, in
effect, that for any property P, there is a predicative property Q that is true
of exactly the same things as P. Reducibility thus assures that there is a
predicative property bH true of the same rational numbers as b. Since the reals
are predicative, hence of the same order as bH, it turns out that bH is a real
number, and hence that S has a least upper bound after all, as required by the
classical theorem. The general role of reducibility is thus to undo the
draconian mathematical effects of ramification without undermining its capacity
to fend off the semantic paradoxes.
typetoken distinction, as
drawn by Peirce, the contrast between a category and a member of that category.
An individual or token is said to exemplify a type; it possesses the property
that characterizes that type. In philosophy this distinction is often applied
to linguistic expressions and to mental states, but it can be applied also to
objects, events, properties, and states of affairs. Related to it are the
distinctions between type and token individuation and between qualitative and
numerical identity. Distinct tokens of the same type, such as two ants, may be
qualitatively identical but cannot be numerically identical. Irrespective of
the controversial metaphysical view that every individual has an essence, a
type type theory, ramified typetoken distinction 936 936 to which it belongs essentially, every
individual belongs to many types, although for a certain theoretical or
practical purpose it may belong to one particularly salient type e.g., the
entomologist’s Formicidae or the picnicker’s buttinsky. The typetoken
distinction as applied in the philosophy of language marks the difference
between linguistic expressions, such as words and sentences, which are the
subject of linguistics, and the products of acts of writing or speaking the
subject of speech act theory. Confusing the two can lead to conflating matters
of speaker meaning withmatters of word or sentence meaning as noted by Grice.
An expression is a linguistic type and can be used over and over, whereas a
token of a type can be produced only once, though of course it may be
reproduced copied. A writer composes an essay a type and produces a manuscript
a token, of which there might be many copies more tokens. A token of a type is
not the same as an occurrence of a type. In the previous sentence there are two
occurrences of the word ‘type’; in each inscription of that sentence, there are
two tokens of that word. In philosophy of mind the typetoken distinction
underlies the contrast between two forms of physicalism, the typetype identity
theory or type physicalism and the tokentoken identity theory or token
physicalism.
tzu jan, Chinese term
meaning ‘naturally’, ‘spontaneity’, or ‘so-of-itself’. It is a Taoist term of
art describing the ideal state of agents and quality of actions. A coordinate
concept is wu wei nonaction, particularly in the Tao Te Ching. Taoists seek to
eliminate the rational “human” perspective and return to spontaneous “Heavenly”
inclinations. Actions then will be unself-conscious, and we and what we do will
be tzu jan spontaneous. Wang Ch’ung presents an early critique of this Taoist
notion in chapter 54 of his Lun Heng. Later thinkers appropriate the term to
support their own positions. For example, Neo-Confucians regard particular
familial and social obligations as tzu jan, as are certain virtuous
inclinations.
Unamuno, Miguel de
18641936, Spanish philosopher, scholar, and writer. Born in Bilbao, he studied
in Bilbao and Madrid and taught Grecian and philosophy in Salamanca. His open
criticism of the Spanish government led to dismissal from the and exile 192430 and, again, to dismissal
from the rectorship in 1936. Unamuno is an important figure in Spanish letters.
Like Ortega y Gasset, his aim was to capture life in its complex emotional and
intellectual dimensions rather than to describe the world scientifically. Thus,
he favored fiction as a medium for his ideas and may be considered a precursor
of existentialism. He wrote several philosophically significant novels, a
commentary on Don Quijote 1905, and some poetry and drama; his philosophical
ideas are most explicitly stated in Del sentimiento trágico de la vida “The
Tragic Sense of Life,” 1913. Unamuno perceived a tragic sense permeating human
life, a sense arising from our desire for immortality and from the certainty of
death. In this predicament man must abandon all pretense
of rationalism and embrace faith. Faith
characterizes the authentic life, while reason leads to despair, but faith can
never completely displace reason. Torn between the two, we can find hope only
in faith; for reason deals only with abstractions, while we are “flesh and
bones” and can find fulfillment only through commitment to an ideal.
unexpected examination
paradox, a paradox about belief and prediction. One version is as follows: It
seems that a teacher could both make, and act on, the following announcement to
his class: “Sometime during the next week I will set you an examination, but at
breakfast time on the day it will occur, you will have no good reason to expect
that it will occur on that day.” If he announces this on Friday, could he not
do what he said he would by, say, setting the examination on the following
Wednesday? The paradox is that there is an argument purporting to show that
there could not be an unexpected examination of this kind. For let us suppose
that the teacher will carry out his threat, in both its parts; i.e., he will
set an examination, and it will be unexpected. Then he cannot set the
examination on Friday assuming this to be the last possible day of the week.
For, by the time Friday breakfast arrives, and we know that all the previous
days have been examination-free, we would have every reason to expect the
examination to occur on Friday. So leaving the examination until Friday is
inconsistent with setting an unexpected examination. For similar reasons, the
examination cannot be held on Thursday. Given our previous conclusion that it
cannot be delayed until Friday, we would know, when Thursday morning came, and
the previous days had been examination-free, that it would have to be held on
Thursday. So if it were held on Thursday it would not be unexpected. So it
cannot be held on Thursday. Similar reasoning sup938 U 938 posedly shows that there is no day of
the week on which it can be held, and so supposedly shows that the supposition
that the teacher can carry out his threat must be rejected. This is
paradoxical, for it seems plain that the teacher can carry out his threat.
uniformity of nature, a
state of affairs thought to be required if induction is to be justified. For
example, inductively strong arguments, such as ‘The sun has risen every day in
the past; therefore, the sun will rise tomorrow’, are thought to presuppose
that nature is uniform in the sense that the future will resemble the past, in
this case with respect to the diurnal cycle. The Scottish empiricist Hume was
the first to make explicit that the uniformity of nature is a substantial
assumption in inductive reasoning. Hume argued that, because the belief that
the future will resemble the past cannot be grounded in experience for the future is as yet unobserved induction cannot be rationally justified;
appeal to it in defense of induction is either question-begging or illicitly
metaphysical. Francis Bacon’s “induction by enumeration” and J. S. Mill’s “five
methods of experimental inquiry” presuppose that nature is uniform. Whewell
appealed to the uniformity of nature in order to account for the “consilience
of inductions,” the tendency of a hypothesis to explain data different from
those it was originally introduced to explain. For reasons similar to Hume’s,
Popper holds that our belief in the uniformity of nature is a matter of faith.
Reichenbach held that although this belief cannot be justified in advance of
any instance of inductive reasoning, its presupposition is vindicated by
successful inductions. It has proved difficult to formulate a philosophical
statement of the uniformity of nature that is both coherent and informative. It
appears contradictory to say that nature is uniform in all respects, because
inductive inferences always mark differences of some sort e.g., from present to
future, from observed to unobserved, etc., and it seems trivial to say that
nature is uniform in some respects, because any two states of nature, no matter
how different, will be similar in some respect. Not all observed regularities
in the world or in data are taken to support successful inductive reasoning;
not all uniformities are, to use Goodman’s term, “projectible.” Philosophers of
science have therefore proposed various rules of projectibility, involving such
notions as simplicity and explanatory power, in an attempt to distinguish those
observed patterns that support successful inductions and thus are taken to
represent genuine causal relations from those that are accidental or
spurious.
unity in diversity, in
aesthetics, the principle that the parts of the aesthetic object must cohere or
hang together while at the same time being different enough to allow for the
object to be complex. This principle defines an important formal requirement
used in judging aesthetic objects. If an object has insufficient unity e.g., a
collection of color patches with no recognizable patterns of any sort, it is
chaotic or lacks harmony; it is more a collection than one object. But if it
has insufficient diversity e.g., a canvas consisting entirely of one color with
no internal differentiations, it is monotonous. Thus, the formal pattern
desired in an aesthetic object is that of complex parts that differ
significantly from each other but fit together to form one interdependent whole
such that the character or meaning of the whole would be changed by the change
of any part.
unity of science, a
situation in which all branches of empirical science form a coherent system
called unified science. Unified science is sometimes extended to include formal
sciences e.g., branches of logic and mathematics. ‘Unity of science’ is also
used to refer to a research program aimed at unified science. Interest in the
unity of science has a long history with many roots, including ancient atomism
and the work of the French Encyclopedists. In the twentieth century this
interest was prominent in logical empiricism see Otto Neurath et al., International
Encyclopedia of Unified Science, vol. I, 1938. Logical empiricists originally
conceived of unified science in terms of a unified language of science, in
particular, a universal observation language. All laws and theoretical
statements in any branch of science were to be translatable into such an
observation language, or else be appropriately related to sentences of this
language. In unified science unity of science 939 939 addition to encountering technical difficulties
with the observationaltheoretical distinction, this conception of unified
science also leaves open the possibility that phenomena of one branch may
require special concepts and hypotheses that are explanatorily independent of
other branches. Another concept of unity of science requires that all branches
of science be combined by the intertheoretic reduction of the theories of all
non-basic branches to one basic theory usually assumed to be some future
physics. These reductions may proceed stepwise; an oversimplified example would
be reduction of psychology to biology, together with reductions of biology to
chemistry and chemistry to physics. The conditions for reducing theory T2 to
theory T1 are complex, but include identification of the ontology of T2 with
that of T1, along with explanation of the laws of T2 by laws of T1 together
with appropriate connecting sentences. These conditions for reduction can be
supplemented with conditions for the unity of the basic theory, to produce a
general research program for the unification of science see Robert L. Causey,
Unity of Science, 1977. Adopting this research program does not commit one to
the proposition that complete unification will ever be achieved; the latter is
primarily an empirical proposition. This program has been criticized, and some
have argued that reductions are impossible for particular pairs of theories, or
that some branches of science are autonomous. For example, some writers have
defended a view of autonomous biology, according to which biological science is
not reducible to the physical sciences. Vitalism postulated non-physical
attributes or vital forces that were supposed to be present in living
organisms. More recent neovitalistic positions avoid these postulates, but
attempt to give empirical reasons against the feasibility of reducing biology.
Other, sometimes a priori, arguments have been given against the reducibility
of psychology to physiology and of the social sciences to psychology. These
disputes indicate the continuing intellectual significance of the idea of unity
of science and the broad range of issues it encompasses.
universal instantiation,
also called universal quantifier elimination. 1 The argument form ‘Everything
is f; therefore a is f’, and arguments of this form. 2 The rule of inference
that permits one to infer that any given thing is f from the premise that
everything is f. In classical logic, where all terms are taken to denote things
in the domain of discourse, the rule says simply that from vA[v] one may infer
A[t], the result of replacing all free occurrences of v in A[v] by the term t.
If non-denoting terms are allowed, however, as in free logic, then the rule
would require an auxiliary premise of the form Duu % t to ensure that t denotes
something in the range of the variable v. Likewise in modal logic, which is
sometimes held to contain terms that do not denote “genuine individuals” the
things over which variables range, an auxiliary premise may be required. 3 In
higher-order logic, the rule of inference that says that from XA[X] one may infer
A[F], where F is any expression of the grammatical category e.g., n-ary
predicate appropriate to that of X e.g., n-ary predicate variable. G.F.S.
universalizability. 1
Since the 1920s, the moral criterion implicit in Kant’s first formulation of
the categorical imperative: “Act only on that maxim that you can at the same
time will to be a universal law,” often called the principle of universality. A
maxim or principle of action that satisfies this test is said to be
universalizable, hence morally acceptable; one that does not is said to be not
universalizable, hence contrary to duty. 2 A second sense developed in
connection with the work of Hare in the 1950s. For Hare, universalizability is
“common to all judgments which carry descriptive meaning”; so not only
normative claims moral and evaluative judgments but also empirical statements
are universalizable. Although Hare describes how such universalizuniversal
universalizability 940 940 ability can
figure in moral argument, for Hare “offenses against . . . universalizability
are logical, not moral.” Consequently, whereas for Kant not all maxims are
universalizable, on Hare’s view they all are, since they all have descriptive
meaning. 3 In a third sense, one that also appears in Hare,
‘universalizability’ refers to the principle of universalizability: “What is
right or wrong for one person is right or wrong for any similar person in
similar circumstances.” This principle is identical with what Sidgwick The
Methods of Ethics called the Principle of Justice. In Generalization in Ethics
1961 by M. G. Singer b.1926, it is called the Generalization Principle and is
said to be the formal principle presupposed in all moral reasoning and
consequently the explanation for the feature alleged to hold of all moral
judgments, that of being generalizable. A particular judgment of the form ‘A is
right in doing x’ is said to imply that anyone relevantly similar to A would be
right in doing any act of the kind x in relevantly similar circumstances. The
characteristic of generalizability, of presupposing a general rule, was said to
be true of normative claims, but not of all empirical or descriptive
statements. The Generalization Principle GP was said to be involved in the
Generalization Argument GA: “If the consequences of everyone’s doing x would be
undesirable, while the consequences of no one’s doing x would not be, then no
one ought to do x without a justifying reason,” a form of moral reasoning
resembling, though not identical with, the categorical imperative CI. One
alleged resemblance is that if the GP is involved in the GP, then it is
involved in the CI, and this would help explain the moral relevance of Kant’s
universalizability test. 4 A further extension of the term ‘universalizability’
appears in Alan Gewirth’s Reason and Morality 1978. Gewirth formulates “the
logical principle of universalizability”: “if some predicate P belongs to some
subject S because S has the property Q . . . then P must also belong to all
other subjects S1, S2, . . . , Sn that have Q.” The principle of
universalizability “in its moral application” is then deduced from the logical
principle of universalizability, and is presupposed in Gewirth’s Principle of
Generic Consistency, “Act in accord with the generic rights of your recipients
as well as yourself,” which is taken to provide an a priori determinate way of
determining relevant similarities and differences, hence of applying the
principle of universalizability. The principle of universalizability is a
formal principle; universalizability in sense 1, however, is intended to be a
substantive principle of morality.
universe of discourse,
the usually limited class of individuals under discussion, whose existence is
presupposed by the discussants, and which in some sense constitutes the
ultimate subject matter of the discussion. Once the universe of a discourse has
been established, expressions such as ‘every object’ and ‘some object’ refer
respectively to every object or to some object in the universe of discourse.
The concept of universe of discourse is due to De Morgan in 1846, but the
expression was coined by Boole eight years later. When a discussion is
formalized in an interpreted standard first-order language, the universe of
discourse is taken as the “universe” of the interpretation, i.e., as the range
of values of the variables. Quine and others have emphasized that the universe
of discourse represents an ontological commitment of the discussants. In a
discussion in a particular science, the universe of discourse is often wider
than the domain of the science, although economies of expression can be
achieved by limiting the universe of discourse to the domain.
Upanishads, a group of
ancient Hindu philosophical texts, or the esoteric sacred doctrines contained
in them. ‘Upanishad’ includes the notion of the student “sitting near” the
guru. In the eighth century A.D., Shankara identified certain Upanishads as the
official source of Vedanta teachings: Aitreya, Brhadaranyaka, Chandogya, Isa,
Katha, Kaufitaki, Kena, Maitri, Mupdaka, Prasna, Svetasvatara, and Taittiriya.
These are the classic universalizability, principle of Upanishads 941 941 Upanishads; together with the Vedanta
Sutras, they constitute the doctrinally authoritative sources for Vedanta. The
Vedanta Sutras are a series of aphorisms, composed somewhere between 200 B.C.
and A.D. 200, attributed to Badarayana. Practically unintelligible without
commentary, these sutras are interpreted in one way by Shankara, in another by
Ramanuja, and in a third way by Madhva though Madhva’s reading is closer to
Ramanuja’s than to Shankara’s. For Vedanta, the Upanishads are “the end of the
Vedas,” both in the sense of completing the transcript of the immutable source
of truth and articulating the foundational wisdom that the Vedas presuppose.
While the Upanishads agree on the importance of religious knowledge, on the
priority of religious over other sorts of wellbeing, and on the necessity of
religious discipline, they contain radically disparate cosmologies that differ
regarding agent, modality, and product of the creative process and offer
various notions of Brahman and Atman.
usemention distinction,
two ways in which terms enter into discourse
used when they refer to or assert something, mentioned when they are
exhibited for consideration of their properties as terms. If I say, “Mary is
sad,” I use the name ‘Mary’ to refer to Mary so that I can predicate of her the
property of being sad. But if I say, “ ‘Mary’ contains four letters,” I am
mentioning Mary’s name, exhibiting it in writing or speech to predicate of that
term the property of being spelled with four letters. In the first case, the
sentence occurs in what Carnap refers to as the material mode; in the second,
it occurs in the formal mode, and hence in a metalanguage a language used to
talk about another language. Single quotation marks or similar orthographic
devices are conventionally used to disambiguate mentioned from used terms. The
distinction is important because there are fallacies of reasoning based on
usemention confusions in the failure to observe the use mention distinction,
especially when the referents of terms are themselves linguistic entities.
Consider the inference: 1 Some sentences are written in English. 2 Some
sentences are written in English. Here it looks as though the argument offers a
counterexample to the claim that all arguments of the form ‘P, therefore P’ are
circular. But either 1 asserts that some sentences are written in English, or
it provides evidence in support of the conclusion in 2 by exhibiting a sentence
written in English. In the first case, the sentence is used to assert the same
truth in the premise as expressed in the conclusion, so that the argument
remains circular. In the second case, the sentence is mentioned, and although
the argument so interpreted is not circular, it is no longer strictly of the
form ‘P, therefore P’, but has the significantly different form, ‘ “P” is a
sentence written in English, therefore P’.
utilitarianism, the moral
theory that an action is morally right if and only if it produces at least as
much good utility for all people affected by the action as any alternative
action the person could do instead. Its best-known proponent is J. S. Mill, who
formulated the greatest happiness principle also called the principle of
utility: always act so as to produce the greatest happiness. Two kinds of
issues have been central in debates about whether utilitarianism is an adequate
or true moral theory: first, whether and how utilitarianism can be clearly and
precisely formulated and applied; second, whether the moral implications of
utilitarianism in particular cases are acceptable, or instead constitute
objections to it. Issues of formulation. A central issue of formulation is how
utility is to be defined and whether it can be measured in the way
utilitarianism requires. Early utilitarians often held some form of hedonism,
according to which only pleasure and the absence of pain have utility or
intrinsic value. For something to have intrinsic value is for it to be valuable
for its own sake and apart from its consequences or its relations to other
things. Something has instrumental value, on the other hand, provided it brings
about what has intrinsic value. Most utilitarians have held that hedonism is
too narrow an account of utility because there are many things that people
value intrinsically besides pleasure. Some nonhedonists define utility as
happiness, and among them there is considerable debate about the proper account
of happiness. Happiness has also been criticized as too narrow to exhaust
utility or intrinsic value; e.g., many people value accomplishments, not just
the happiness that may usemention distinction utilitarianism 942 942 accompany them. Sometimes utilitarianism
is understood as the view that either pleasure or happiness has utility, while
consequentialism is understood as the broader view that morally right action is
action that maximizes the good, however the good is understood. Here, we take
utilitarianism in this broader interpretation that some philosophers reserve for
consequentialism. Most utilitarians who believe hedonism gives too narrow an
account of utility have held that utility is the satisfaction of people’s
informed preferences or desires. This view is neutral about what people desire,
and so can account for the full variety of things and experiences that
different people in fact desire or value. Finally, ideal utilitarians have held
that some things or experiences, e.g. knowledge or being autonomous, are
intrinsically valuable or good whether or not people value or prefer them or
are happier with them. Whatever account of utility a utilitarian adopts, it
must be possible to quantify or measure the good effects or consequences of
actions in order to apply the utilitarian standard of moral rightness.
Happiness utilitarianism, e.g., must calculate whether a particular action, or
instead some possible alternative, would produce more happiness for a given
person; this is called the intrapersonal utility comparison. The method of
measurement may allow cardinal utility measurements, in which numerical units
of happiness may be assigned to different actions e.g., 30 units for Jones
expected from action a, 25 units for Jones from alternative action b, or only
ordinal utility measurements may be possible, in which actions are ranked only
as producing more or less happiness than alternative actions. Since nearly all
interesting and difficult moral problems involve the happiness of more than one
person, utilitarianism requires calculating which among alternative actions produces
the greatest happiness for all people affected; this is called the
interpersonal utility comparison. Many ordinary judgments about personal action
or public policy implicitly rely on interpersonal utility comparisons; e.g.,
would a family whose members disagree be happiest overall taking its vacation
at the seashore or in the mountains? Some critics of utilitarianism doubt that
it is possible to make interpersonal utility comparisons. Another issue of
formulation is whether the utilitarian principle should be applied to
individual actions or to some form of moral rule. According to act
utilitarianism, each action’s rightness or wrongness depends on the utility it
produces in comparison with possible alternatives. Even act utilitarians agree,
however, that rules of thumb like ‘keep your promises’ can be used for the most
part in practice because following them tends to maximize utility. According to
rule utilitarianism, on the other hand, individual actions are evaluated, in
theory not just in practice, by whether they conform to a justified moral rule,
and the utilitarian standard is applied only to general rules. Some rule
utilitarians hold that actions are right provided they are permitted by rules
the general acceptance of which would maximize utility in the agent’s society,
and wrong only if they would be prohibited by such rules. There are a number of
forms of rule utilitarianism, and utilitarians disagree about whether act or
rule utilitarianism is correct. Moral implications. Most debate about utilitarianism
has focused on its moral implications. Critics have argued that its
implications sharply conflict with most people’s considered moral judgments,
and that this is a strong reason to reject utilitarianism. Proponents have
argued both that many of these conflicts disappear on a proper understanding of
utilitarianism and that the remaining conflicts should throw the particular
judgments, not utilitarianism, into doubt. One important controversy concerns
utilitarianism’s implications for distributive justice. Utilitarianism
requires, in individual actions and in public policy, maximizing utility
without regard to its distribution between different persons. Thus, it seems to
ignore individual rights, whether specific individuals morally deserve particular
benefits or burdens, and potentially to endorse great inequalities between
persons; e.g., some critics have charged that according to utilitarianism
slavery would be morally justified if its benefits to the slaveowners
sufficiently outweighed the burdens to the slaves and if it produced more
overall utility than alternative practices possible in that society. Defenders
of utilitarianism typically argue that in the real world there is virtually
always a better alternative than the action or practice that the critic charges
utilitarianism wrongly supports; e.g., no system of slavery that has ever
existed is plausibly thought to have maximized utility for the society in
question. Defenders of utilitarianism also typically try to show that it does
take account of the moral consideration the critic claims it wrongly ignores;
for instance, utilitarians commonly appeal to the declining marginal utility of
money equal marginal increments of money
tend to produce less utility e.g. happiness for persons, the more money they
already utilitarianism utilitarianism have
as giving some support to equality in income distribution. Another
source of controversy concerns whether moral principles should be agent-neutral
or, in at least some cases, agent-relative. Utilitarianism is agent-neutral in
that it gives all people the same moral aim
act so as to maximize utility for everyone whereas agent-relative principles give
different moral aims to different individuals. Defenders of agent-relative
principles note that a commonly accepted moral rule like the prohibition of
killing the innocent is understood as telling each agent that he or she must
not kill, even if doing so is the only way to prevent a still greater number of
killings by others. In this way, a non-utilitarian, agent-relative prohibition
reflects the common moral view that each person bears special moral
responsibility for what he or she does, which is greater than his or her
responsibility to prevent similar wrong actions by others. Common moral beliefs
also permit people to give special weight to their own projects and commitments
and, e.g., to favor to some extent their own children at the expense of other
children in greater need; agent-relative responsibilities to one’s own family
reflect these moral views in a way that agent-neutral utilitarian
responsibilities apparently do not. The debate over neutrality and relativity
is related to a final area of controversy about utilitarianism. Critics charge
that utilitarianism makes morality far too demanding by requiring that one
always act to maximize utility. If, e.g., one reads a book or goes to a movie,
one could nearly always be using one’s time and resources to do more good by
aiding famine relief. The critics believe that this wrongly makes morally
required what should be only supererogatory
action that is good, but goes beyond “the call of duty” and is not
morally required. Here, utilitarians have often argued that ordinary moral
views are seriously mistaken and that morality can demand greater sacrifices of
one’s own interests for the benefit of others than is commonly believed. There
is little doubt that here, and in many other cases, utilitarianism’s moral
implications significantly conflict with commonsense moral beliefs the dispute is whether this should count
against commonsense moral beliefs or against utilitarianism.
vagueness, a property of
an expression in virtue of which it can give rise to a “borderline case.” A
borderline case is a situation in which the application of a particular
expression to a name of a particular object does not generate an expression
with a definite truth-value; i.e., the piece of language in question neither
unequivocally applies to the object nor fails to apply. Although such a
formulation leaves it open what the pieces of language might be whole
sentences, individual words, names or singular terms, predicates or general
terms, most discussions have focused on vague general terms and have considered
other types of terms to be nonvague. Exceptions to this have called attention
to the possibility of vague objects, thereby rendering vague the designation
relation for singular terms. The formulation also leaves open the possible
causes for the expression’s lacking a definite truth-value. If this
indeterminacy is due to there being insufficient information available to
determine applicability or non-applicability of the term i.e., we are convinced
the term either does or does not apply, but we just do not have enough
information to determine which, then this is sometimes called epistemic
vagueness. It is somewhat misleading to call this vagueness, for unlike true
vagueness, this epistemic vagueness disappears if more information is brought
into the situation. ‘There are between 1.89 $ 106 and 1.9 $ 106 stars in the
sky’ is epistemically vague but is not vague in the generally accepted sense of
the term. ’Vagueness’ may also be used to characterize non-linguistic items
such as concepts, memories, and objects, as well as such semilinguistic items
as statements and propositions. Many of the issues involved in discussing the
topic of vagueness impinge upon other philosophical topics, such as the
existence of truth-value gaps
declarative sentences that are neither true nor false and the plausibility of many-valued logic.
There are other related issues such as the nature of propositions and whether
they must be either true or false. We focus here on linguistic vagueness, as it
manifests itself with general terms; for it is this sort of indeterminacy that
defines what most researchers call vagueness, and which has led the push in
some schools of thought to “eliminate vagueness” or to construct languages that
do not manifest vagueness. Linguistic vagueness is sometimes confused with
other linguistic phenomena: generality, ambiguity, and open texture. Statements
can be general ‘Some wheelbarrows are red’, ‘All insects have antennae’ and if
there is no other vagueness infecting them, they are true or false and not borderline or vague. Terms can be
general ‘person’, ‘dog’ without being vague. Those general terms apply to many
different objects but are not therefore vague; and furthermore, the fact that
they apply to different kinds of objects ‘person’ applies to both men and women
also does not show them to be vague or ambiguous. A vague term admits of
borderline cases a completely
determinate situation in which there just is no correct answer as to whether
the term applies to a certain object or not
and this is not the case with generality. Ambiguous linguistic items,
including structurally ambiguous sentences, also do not have this feature
unless they also contain vague terms. Rather, an ambiguous sentence allows
there to be a completely determinate situation in which one can simultaneously
correctly affirm the sentence and also deny the sentence, depending on which of
the claims allowed by the ambiguities is being affirmed or denied. Terms are
considered open-textured if they are precise along some dimensions of their
meaning but where other possible dimensions simply have not been considered. It
would therefore not be clear what the applicability of the term would be were
objects to vary along these other dimensions. Although related to vagueness,
open texture is a different notion. Friedrich Waismann, who coined the term,
put it this way: “Open texture . . . is something like the possibility of
vagueness.” Vagueness has long been an irritant to philosophers of logic and
language. Among the oldest of the puzzles associated with vagueness is the
sorites ‘heap’ paradox reported by Cicero Academica 93: One grain of sand does
not make a heap, and adding a grain of sand to something that is not a heap
will not create a heap; there945 V 945
fore there are no heaps. This type of paradox is traditionally attributed to
Zeno of Elea, who said that a single millet seed makes no sound when it falls,
so a basket of millet seeds cannot make a sound when it is dumped. The term
‘sorites’ is also applied to the entire series of paradoxes that have this
form, such as the falakros ‘bald man’, Diogenes Laertius, Grammatica II, 1, 45:
A man with no hairs is bald, and adding one hair to a bald man results in a
bald man; therefore all men are bald. The original version of these sorites
paradoxes is attributed to Eubulides Diogenes Laertius II, 108: “Isn’t it true
that two are few? and also three, and also four, and so on until ten? But since
two are few, ten are also few.” The linchpin in all these paradoxes is the
analysis of vagueness in terms of some underlying continuum along which an
imperceptible or unimportant change occurs. Almost all modern accounts of the
logic of vagueness have assumed this to be the correct analysis of vagueness,
and have geared their logics to deal with such vagueness. But we will see below
that there are other kinds of vagueness too. The search for a solution to the
sorites-type paradoxes has been the stimulus for much research into alternative
semantics. Some philosophers, e.g. Frege, view vagueness as a pervasive defect
of natural language and urge the adoption of an artificial language in which
each predicate is completely precise, without borderline cases. Russell too
thought vagueness thoroughly infected natural language, but thought it
unavoidable and indeed beneficial for ordinary usage and discourse. Despite the
occasional argument that vagueness is pragmatic rather than a semantic
phenomenon, the attitude that vagueness is inextricably bound to natural
language together with the philosophical logician’s self-ascribed task of
formalizing natural language semantics has led modern writers to the
exploration of alternative logics that might adequately characterize
vagueness i.e., that would account for
our pretheoretic beliefs concerning truth, falsity, necessary truth, validity,
etc., of sentences containing vague predicates. Some recent writers have also
argued that vague language undermines realism, and that it shows our concepts
to be “incoherent.” Long ago it was seen that the attempt to introduce a third
truth-value, indeterminate, solved nothing
replacing, as it were, the sharp cutoff between a predicate’s applying
and not applying with two sharp cutoffs. Similar remarks could be made against
the adoption of any finitely manyvalued logic as a characterization of
vagueness. In the late 1960s and early 1970s, fuzzy logic was introduced into
the philosophic world. Actually a restatement of the Tarski-Lukasiewicz
infinitevalued logics of the 1930s, one of the side benefits of fuzzy logics
was claimed to be an adequate logic for vagueness. In contrast to classical
logic, in which there are two truth-values true and false, in fuzzy logic a
sentence is allowed to take any real number between 0 and 1 as a truthvalue.
Intuitively, the closer to 1 the value is, the “more true” the sentence is. The
value of a negated sentence is 1 minus the value of the unnegated sentence;
conjuction is viewed as a minimum function and disjunction as a maximum
function. Thus, a conjunction takes the value of the “least true” conjunct,
while a disjunction takes the value of the “most true” disjunct. Since vague sentences
are maximally neither true nor false, they will be valued at approximately 0.5.
It follows that if F is maximally vague, so is the negation -F; and so are the
conjunction F & -F and the disjunction ~F 7 -F. Some theorists object to
these results, but defenders of fuzzy logic have argued in favor of them. Other
theorists have attempted to capture the elusive logic of vagueness by employing
modal logic, having the operators AF meaning ‘F is definite’ and B F meaning ‘F
is vague’. The logic generated in this way is peculiar in that A F & YPAF
& AY is not a theorem. E.g., p & -p is definitely false, hence
definite; hence A p & -p. Yet neither p nor -p need be definite.
Technically, it is a non-Kripke-normal modal logic. Some other peculiarities
are that AF Q A -F is a theorem, and that AFPBF is not. There are also puzzles
about whether B FP ABF should be a theorem, and about iterated modalities in
general. Modal logic treatments of vagueness have not attracted many advocates,
except as a portion of a general epistemic logic i.e., modal logics might be
seen as an account of so-called epistemic vagueness. A third direction that has
been advocated as a logical account of vagueness has been the method of
supervaluations sometimes called “supertruth”. The underlying idea here is to
allow the vague predicate in a sentence to be “precisified” in an arbitrary
manner. Thus, for the sentence ‘Friar Tuck is bald’, we arbitrarily choose a
precise number of hairs on the head that will demarcate the bald/not-bald border.
In this valuation Friar Tuck is either definitely bald or definitely not bald,
and the sentence either is true or is false. Next, we alter the valuation so
that there is some other bald/not-bald bordervagueness vagueness 946 946 line, etc. A sentence true in all such
valuations is deemed “really true” or “supertrue”; one false in all such
valuations is “really false” or “superfalse.” All others are vague. Note that,
in this conception of vagueness, if F is vague, so is -F. However, unlike fuzzy
logic ‘F & -F’ is not evaluated as vague
it is false in every valuation and hence is superfalse. And ‘F 7 -F’ is
supertrue. These are seen by some as positive features of the method of
supervaluations, and as an argument against the whole fuzzy logic enterprise. In
fact there seem to be at least two distinct types of linguistic vagueness, and
it is not at all clear that any of the previously mentioned logic approaches
can deal with both. Without going into the details, we can just point out that
the “sorites vagueness” discussed above presumes an ordering on a continuous
underlying scale; and it is the indistinguishability of adjacent points on this
scale that gives rise to borderline cases. But there are examples of vague
terms for which there is no such scale. A classic example is ‘religion’: there
are a number of factors relevant to determining whether a social practice is a
religion. Having none of these properties guarantees failing to be a religion,
and having all of them guarantees being one. However, there is no continuum of
the sorites variety here; for example, it is easy to distinguish possessing
four from possessing five of the properties, unlike the sorites case where such
a change is imperceptible. In the present type of vagueness, although we can
tell these different cases apart, we just do not know whether to call the
practice a religion or not. Furthermore, some of the properties or combinations
of properties are more important or salient in determining whether the practice
is a religion than are other properties or combinations. We might call this
family resemblance vagueness: there are a number of clearly distinguishable
conditions of varying degrees of importance, and family resemblance vagueness
is attributed to there being no definite answer to the question, How many of
which conditions are necessary for the term to apply? Other examples of family
resemblance vagueness are ‘schizophrenia sufferer’, ‘sexual perversion’, and
the venerable ‘game’. A special subclass of family resemblance vagueness occurs
when there are pairs of underlying properties that normally co-occur, but
occasionally apply to different objects. Consider, e.g., ‘tributary’. When two
rivers meet, one is usually considered a tributary of the other. Among the
properties relevant to being a tributary rather than the main river are:
relative volume of water and relative length. Normally, the shorter of the two
rivers has a lesser volume, and in that case it is the tributary of the other.
But occasionally the two properties do not co-occur and then there is a
conflict, giving rise to a kind of vagueness we might call conflict vagueness.
The term ‘tributary’ is vague because its background conditions admit of such
conflicts: there are borderline cases when these two properties apply to different
objects. To conclude: the fundamental philosophical problems involving
vagueness are 1 to give an adequate characterization of what the phenomenon is,
and 2 to characterize our ability to reason with these terms. These were the
problems for the ancient philosophers, and they remain the problems for modern
philosophers.
Vaihinger, philosopher
best known for Die Philosophie des Als Ob 1911; translated by C. K. Ogden as
The Philosophy of “As If” in 1924. A neo-Kantian, he was also influenced by
Schopenhauer and Nietzsche. His commentary on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason 2
vols., 1881 is still a standard work. Vaihinger was a cofounder of both the
Kant Society and Kant-Studien. The “philosophy of the as if” involves the claim
that values and ideals amount only to “fictions” that serve “life” even if they
are irrational. We must act “as if” they were true because they have biological
utility.
Valentinianism, a form of
Christian gnosticism of Alexandrian origin, founded by Valentinus in the second
century and propagated by Theodotus in Eastern, and Heracleon in Western,
Christianity. To every gnostic, pagan or Christian, knowledge leads to
salvation from the perishable, material world. Valentinianism therefore
prompted famous refutations by Tertullian Adversus Valentinianos and Irenaeus
Adversus haereses. The latter accused the Valentinians of maintaining “creatio
ex nihilo.” Valentinus is believed to have authored the Peri trion phuseon, the
Evangelium veritatis, and the Treatise on the Resurrection. Since only a few
fragments of these remain, his Neoplatonic cosmogony is accessible mainly
through his opponents and critics Hippolytus, Clement of Alexandria and in the
Nag Hammadi codices. To explain the origins of creation and of evil, Valentinus
separated God primal Father from the Creator Demiurge and attributed the
cruVaihinger, Hans Valentinianism 947
947 cial role in the processes of emanation and redemption to
Sophia.
Valentinus A.D. 10065,
Christian gnostic teacher. He was born in Alexandria, where he taught until he
moved to Rome in 135. A dualist, he constructed an elaborate cosmology in which
God the Father Bythos, or Deep Unknown unites the the feminine Silence Sige and
in the overflow of love produces thirty successive divine emanations or aeons
constituting the Pleroma fullness of the Godhead. Each emanation is arranged
hierarchically with a graded existence, becoming progressively further removed
from the Father and hence less divine. The lowest emanation, Sophia wisdom,
yields to passion and seeks to reach, beyond her ability, to the Father, which
causes her fall. In the process, she causes the creation of the material
universe wherein resides evil and the loss of divine sparks from the Pleroma.
The divine elements are embodied in those humans who are the elect. Jesus
Christ is an aeon close to the Father and is sent to retrieve the souls into
the heavenly Pleroma. Valentinus wrote a gospel. His sect stood out in the
early church for ordaining women priests and prophetesses.
valid, having the
property that a well-formed formula, argument, argument form, or rule of
inference has when it is logically correct in a certain respect. A well-formed
formula is valid if it is true under every admissible reinterpretation of its
non-logical symbols. If truth-value gaps or multiple truth-values are allowed,
‘true’ here might be replaced by ‘non-false’ or takes a “designated”
truth-value. An argument is valid if it is impossible for the premises all to
be true and, at the same time, the conclusion false. An argument form schema is
valid if every argument of that form is valid. A rule of inference is valid if
it cannot lead from all true premises to a false conclusion.
Valla, Lorenzo c.140757,
Italian humanist and historian who taught rhetoric in Pavia and was later
secretary of King Alfonso I of Aragona in Naples, and apostolic secretary in
Rome under Pope Nicholas V. In his dialogue On Pleasure or On the True Good
143134, Stoic and Epicurean interlocutors present their ethical views, which
Valla proceeds to criticize from a Christian point of view. This work is often
regarded as a defense of Epicurean hedonism, because Valla equates the good
with pleasure; but he claims that Christians can find pleasure only in heaven.
His description of the Christian pleasures reflects the contemporary
Renaissance attitude toward the joys of life and might have contributed to
Valla’s reputation for hedonism. In the later work, On Free Will between 1435
and 1448, Valla discusses the conflict between divine foreknowledge and human
freedom and rejects Boethius’s then predominantly accepted solution. Valla
distinguishes between God’s knowledge and God’s will, but denies that there is
a rational solution of the apparent conflict between God’s will and human
freedom. As a historian, he is famous for The Donation of Constantine 1440,
which denounces as spurious the famous document on which medieval jurists and
theologians based the papal rights to secular power.
value, the worth of
something. Philosophers have discerned these main forms: intrinsic,
instrumental, inherent, and relational value. Intrinsic value may be taken as
basic and many of the others defined in terms of it. Among the many attempts to
explicate the concept of intrinsic value, some deal primarily with the source of
value, while others employ the concept of the “fittingness” or
“appropriateness” to it of certain kinds of emotions and desires. The first is
favored by Moore and the second by Brentano. Proponents of the first view hold
that the intrinsic value of X is the value that X has solely in virtue of its
intrinsic nature. Thus, the state of affairs, Smith’s experiencing pleasure,
has intrinsic value provided it has value solely in virtue of its intrinsic
nature. Followers of the second approach explicate intrinsic value in terms of
the sorts of emotions and desires appropriate to a thing “in and for itself” or
“for its own sake”. Thus, one might say X has intrinsic value or is
intrinsically good if and only if X is worthy of desire in and for itself, or,
alternatively, it is fitting or appropriate for anyone to favor X in and for
itself. Thus, the state of affairs of Smith’s experiencing pleasure is
intrinsically valuable provided that state of affairs is worthy of desire for
its own sake, or it is fitting for anyone to favor that state of affairs in and
for itself. Concerning the other forms of value, we may say that X has
instrumental value if and only if it is a means to, or causally contributes to,
something that is intrinsically valuable. If Smith’s experiencing pleasure is
intrinsically valuable and his taking a warm bath is a means to, or Valentinus
value 948 948 causally contributes to,
his being pleased, then his taking a warm bath is instrumentally valuable or
“valuable as a means.” Similarly, if health is intrinsically valuable and
exercise is a means to health, then exercise is instrumentally valuable. X has
inherent value if and only if the experience, awareness, or contemplation of X
is intrinsically valuable. If the experience of a beautiful sunset is
intrinsically valuable, then the beautiful sunset has inherent value. X has
contributory value if and only if X contributes to the value of some whole, W,
of which it is a part. If W is a whole that consists of the facts that Smith is
pleased and Brown is pleased, then the fact that Smith is pleased contributes
to the value of W, and Smith’s being pleased has contributory value. Our
example illustrates that something can have contributory value without having
instrumental value, for the fact that Smith is pleased is not a means to W and,
strictly speaking, it does not bring about or causally contribute to W. Given
the distinction between instrumental and contributory value, we may say that
certain sorts of experiences and activities can have contributory value if they
are part of an intrinsically valuable life and contribute to its value, even
though they are not means to it. Finally, we may say that X has relational
value if and only if X has value in virtue of bearing some relation to
something else. Instrumental, inherent, and contributory value may be construed
as forms of relational value. But there are other forms of relational value one
might accept, e.g. one might hold that X is valuable for S in virtue of being
desired by S or being such that S would desire X were S “fully informed” and
“rational.” Some philosophers defend the organicity of intrinsic value. Moore,
for example, held that the intrinsic value of a whole is not necessarily equal
to the sum of the intrinsic values of its parts. According to this view, the
presence of an intrinsically good part might lower the intrinsic value of a
whole of which it is a part and the presence of an intrinsically bad part might
raise the intrinsic value of a whole to which it belongs. Defenders of
organicity sometimes point to examples of Mitfreude taking joy or pleasure in
another’s joy and Schadenfreude taking joy or pleasure in another’s suffering
to illustrate their view. Suppose Jones believes incorrectly that Smith is
happy and Brown believes incorrectly that Gray is suffering, but Jones is
pleased that Smith is happy and Brown is pleased that Gray is suffering. The
former instance of Mitfreude seems intrinsically better than the latter
instance of Schadenfreude even though they are both instances of pleasure and
neither whole has an intrinsically bad part. The value of each whole is not a
“mere sum” of the values of its parts.
value theory, also called
axiology, the branch of philosophy concerned with the nature of value and with
what kinds of things have value. Construed very broadly, value theory is
concerned with all forms of value, such as the aesthetic values of beauty and
ugliness, the ethical values of right, wrong, obligation, virtue, and vice, and
the epistemic values of justification and lack of justification. Understood
more narrowly, value theory is concerned with what is intrinsically valuable or
ultimately worthwhile and desirable for its own sake and with the related
concepts of instrumental, inherent, and contributive value. When construed very
broadly, the study of ethics may be taken as a branch of value theory, but
understood more narrowly value theory may be taken as a branch of ethics. In
its more narrow form, one of the chief questions of the theory of value is,
What is desirable for its own sake? One traditional sort of answer is hedonism.
Hedonism is roughly the view that i the only intrinsically good experiences or
states of affairs are those containing pleasure, and the only instrinsically
bad experiences or states of affairs are those containing pain; ii all
experiences or states of affairs that contain more pleasure than pain are
intrinsically good and all experiences or states of affairs that contain more
pain than pleasure are intrinsically bad; and iii any experience or state of
affairs that is intrinsically good is so in virtue of being pleasant or
containing pleasure and any experience or state of affairs that is
intrinsically bad is so in virtue of being painful or involving pain. Hedonism
has value, cognitive value theory 949
949 been defended by philosophers such as Epicurus, Bentham, Sidgwick,
and, with significant qualifications, J. S. Mill. Other philosophers, such as
C. I. Lewis, and, perhaps, Brand Blanshard, have held that what is
intrinsically or ultimately desirable are experiences that exhibit
“satisfactoriness,” where being pleasant is but one form of being satisfying.
Other philosophers have recognized a plurality of things other than pleasure or
satisfaction as having intrinsic value. Among the value pluralists are Moore,
Rashdall, Ross, Brentano, Hartmann, and Scheler. In addition to certain kinds
of pleasures, these thinkers count some or all of the following as
intrinsically good: consciousness and the flourishing of life, knowledge and
insight, moral virtue and virtuous actions, friendship and mutual affection,
beauty and aesthetic experience, a just distribution of goods, and
self-expression. Many, if not all, of the philosophers mentioned above
distinguish between what has value or is desirable for its own sake and what is
instrumentally valuable. Furthermore, they hold that what is desirable for its
own sake or intrinsically good has a value not dependent on anyone’s having an
interest in it. Both of these claims have been challenged by other value
theorists. Dewey, for example, criticizes any sharp distinction between what is
intrinsically good or good as an end and what is good as a means on the ground
that we adopt and abandon ends to the extent that they serve as means to the
resolution of conflicting impulses and desires. Perry denies that anything can
have value without being an object of interest. Indeed, Perry claims that ‘X is
valuable’ means ‘Interest is taken in X’ and that it is a subject’s interest in
a thing that confers value on it. Insofar as he holds that the value of a thing
is dependent upon a subject’s interest in that thing, Perry’s value theory is a
subjective theory and contrasts sharply with objective theories holding that
some things have value not dependent on a subject’s interests or attitudes.
Some philosophers, dissatisfied with the view that value depends on a subject’s
actual interests and theories, have proposed various alternatives, including
theories holding that the value of a thing depends on what a subject would
desire or have an interest in if he were fully rational or if desires were
based on full information. Such theories may be called “counterfactual” desire
theories since they take value to be dependent, not upon a subject’s actual
interests, but upon what a subject would desire if certain conditions, which do
not obtain, were to obtain. Value theory is also concerned with the nature of
value. Some philosophers have denied that sentences of the forms ‘X is good’ or
‘X is intrinsically good’ are, strictly speaking, either true or false. As with
other forms of ethical discourse, they claim that anyone who utters these
sentences is either expressing his emotional attitudes or else prescribing or
commending something. Other philosophers hold that such sentences can express
what is true or false, but disagree about the nature of value and the meaning
of value terms like ‘good’, ‘bad’, and ‘better’. Some philosophers, such as
Moore, hold that in a truth of the form ‘X is intrinsically good’, ‘good’
refers to a simple, unanalyzable, non-natural property, a property not
identical with or analyzable by any “natural” property such as being pleasant
or being desired. Moore’s view is one form of non-naturalism. Other
philosophers, such as Brentano, hold that ‘good’ is a syncategorematic expression;
as such it does not refer to a property or relation at all, though it
contributes to the meaning of the sentence. Still other philosophers have held
that ‘X is good’ and ‘X is intrinsically good’ can be analyzed in natural or
non-ethical terms. This sort of naturalism about value is illustrated by Perry,
who holds that ‘X is valuable’ means ‘X is an object of interest’. The history
of value theory is full of other attempted naturalistic analyses, some of which
identify or analyze ‘good’ in terms of pleasure or being the object of rational
desire. Many philosophers argue that naturalism is preferable on epistemic
grounds. If, e.g., ‘X is valuable’ just means ‘X is an object of interest’,
then in order to know whether something is valuable, one need only know whether
it is the object of someone’s interest. Our knowledge of value is fundamentally
no different in kind from our knowledge of any other empirical fact. This
argument, however, is not decisive against non-naturalism, since it is not
obvious that there is no synthetic a priori knowledge of the sort Moore takes
as the fundamental value cognition. Furthermore, it is not clear that one
cannot combine non-naturalism about value with a broadly empirical
epistemology, one that takes certain kinds of experience as epistemic grounds for
beliefs about value.
Vanini, philosopher, a
Renaissance Aristotelian who studied law and theology. He became a monk and
traveled all over Europe. After abjuring, he taught and practiced medicine. He
was burned at the stake by the Inquisition. His major work is four volumes of
dialogues, De admirandis naturae reginae deaeque mortalium arcanis “On the
Secrets of Nature, Queen and Goddess of Mortal Beings,” 1616. He was influenced
by Averroes and Pietro Pomponazzi, whom he regarded as his teacher. Vanini
rejects revealed religion and claims that God is immanent in nature. The world
is ruled by a necessary natural order and is eternal. Like Averroes, he denies
the immortality and the immateriality of the human soul. Like Pomponazzi, he
denies the existence of miracles and claims that all apparently extraordinary
phenomena can be shown to have natural causes and to be predetermined. Despite
the absence of any original contribution, from the second half of the
seventeenth century Vanini was popular as a symbol of free and atheist thought.
variable, in logic and
mathematics, a symbol interpreted so as to be associated with a range of
values, a set of entities any one of which may be temporarily assigned as a
value of the variable. An occurrence of a variable in a mathematical or logical
expression is a free occurrence if assigning a value is necessary in order for
the containing expression to acquire a semantic value a denotation, truth-value, or other meaning.
Suppose a semantic value is assigned to a variable and the same value is
attached to a constant as meaning of the same kind; if an expression contains
free occurrences of just that variable, the value of the expression for that
assignment of value to the variable is standardly taken to be the same as the
value of the expression obtained by substituting the constant for all the free
occurrences of the variable. A bound occurrence of a variable is one that is
not free.
vasana, Buddhist
philosophical term meaning ‘tendency’. It is an explanatory category, designed
to show how it is possible to talk of tendencies or capacities in persons on
the basis of a metaphysic that denies that there are any enduring existents in
the continua of events conventionally called “persons.” According to this
metaphysic, when we speak of the tendency of persons understood in this way to do
this or that to be jealous, lustful,
angry we are speaking of the presence of
karmic seeds in continua of events, seeds that may mature at different times
and so produce tendencies to engage in this or that action.
Vasubandhu fourthfifth
century A.D., Indian philosopher, a Mahayana Buddhist of the Yogacara or
Sarvastivada school. He wrote the Abhidharmakosá “Treasure Chamber of the
Abhidharma,” the Abhidharma being a compilation of Buddhist philosophy and
psychology and the Vimcatika “Proof in Twenty Verses That Everything Is Only
Conception”. He held that the mind is only a stream of ideas and that there is
nothing non-mental. In contrast to Buddhist direct and representational
realists, he argued that dream experience seems to be of objects located in
space and existing independent of the dreamer without their actually doing
so.
Vauvenargues, Luc de
Clapiers de 171547, French army officer and secular moralist. Discovering
Plutarch at an early age, he critically adopted Stoic idealism.
Poverty-stricken, obscure, and solitary, he was ambitious for glory. Though
eventful, his military career brought little reward. In poor health, he
resigned in 1744 to write. In 1747, he published Introduction to the Knowledge
of the Human Mind, followed by Reflections and Maxims. Voltaire and Mirabeau
praised his vigorous and eclectic thought, which aimed at teaching people how
to live. Vauvenargues was a deist and an optimist who equally rejected
Bossuet’s Christian pessimism and La Rochefoucauld’s secular pessimism. He
asserted human freedom and natural goodness, but denied social and political
equality. A lover of martial virtues and noble passions, Vauvenargues crafted
memVardhamana Jnatrputra Vauvenargues, Luc de Clapiers de 951 951 orable maxims and excelled in character
depiction. His complete works were published in 1862.
Vázquez, Gabriel
15491604, Spanish Jesuit theologian and philosopher. Born in Villaescusa de
Haro, he studied at Alcalá de Henares and taught at Ocaña, Madrid, Alcalá, and
Rome. He was a prolific writer; his philosophically most important work is a
commentary on Aquinas’s Summa theologiae. Vázquez was strongly influenced by
Aquinas, but he differed from him in important ways and showed marked leanings
toward Augustine. He rejected the Thomistic doctrine of the real distinction
between essence and existence and the position that matter designated by
quantity materia signata quantitate is the principle of individuation. Instead
of Aquinas’s five ways for proving the existence of God, he favored a version
of the moral argument similar to the one later used by Kant and also favored
the teleological argument. Following Augustine, he described the union of body
and soul as a union of two parts. Finally, Vázquez modified the doctrine of
formal and objective concepts present in Toletus and Suárez in a way that
facilitated the development of idealism in early modern philosophy. He
accomplished this by identifying the actual being esse of the thing that is
known conceptus objectivus with the act conceptus formalis whereby it is
known.
Vedanta, also called
Uttara Mimamsa ‘the end of the Vedas’, the most influential of the six orthodox
schools of Hinduism. Much of the philosophical content of other schools has
been taken up into it. It claims to present the correct interpretation of the
Vedas and Upanishads, along with the Bhagavad Gita, sacred texts within Indian
culture. Much of the dispute over these texts is religious as well as
philosophical in nature; it concerns whether or not they are best read
theistically or monistically. To read these texts theistically is to see them
as teaching the existence of an omnipotent and omniscient personal Brahman, who
in sport not out of need, but not without moral seriousness everlastingly
sustains the material world and conscious selves in existence; the ultimate
good of the conscious selves then consists in being rightly related to Brahman.
To read these texts monistically is to see them as teaching the existence of a
qualityless ineffable Brahman who appears to the unenlightened to be manifested
in a multiplicity of bodies and minds and in a personal deity; critics
naturally ask to whom such an appearance appears. Two great thinkers in the
theistic Vedantic tradition are Ramanuja traditional dates: 1017 1137 and
Madhva b.1238. Shankara 788 820? represents Advaita Vedanta ‘Advaita’ meaning
‘non-dual’ and defends the view that the sacred texts ought to be read
monistically; his view is often compared to the absolute idealism embraced by
Bradley; for Shankara what appears as a pluralistic world is really a seamless
unity. Madhva is a leading proponent of Dvaita Vedanta, an uncompromisingly
theistic reading of the same texts; for him, what appears as a pluralistic
world is a pluralistic world that exists distinct from, though dependent on,
Brahman. Ramanuja is a leading exponent of Visistadvaita Vedanta, often called
“qualified non-dualism” because Ramanuja, in contrast to Madhva, views the
pluralistic world that appears as the body of Brahman but, in contrast to
Shankara, views that body as real and distinct from Brahman conceived as an
omnicompetent person.
Vedas, the earliest Hindu
sacred texts. ‘Veda’ literally means a text that contains knowledge, in
particular sacred knowledge concerning the nature of ultimate reality and the
proper human ways of relating thereto. Passed down orally and then composed
over a millennium beginning around 1400 B.C., there are four collections of
Vedas: the Rg Veda 1,028 sacred songs of praise with some cosmological
speculations, the Sama Veda chants to accompany sacrifices, Yajur Veda
sacrificial formulas and mantras, and Atharva Veda magical formulas, myths, and
legends. The term ‘Veda’ also applies to the Brahmanas ritual and theological
commentaries on the prior Vedas; the Aranyakasmainly composed by men who have
passed through their householder stage of life and retired to the forest to
meditate, and the Upanishads, which more fully reflect the idea of theoretical
sacred knowledge, while the early Vedas are more practice-oriented, concerned
with ritual and sacrifice. All these texts are regarded as scripture sruti,
“heard” in an oral tradition believed to be handed down by sages by whom their
content was “seen.” The content is held to express a timeless and uncreated
wisdom produced by neither God nor human. It contains material ranging from
instructions concerning the proper sacrifices to make and how to make them
properly, through hymns and mantras, to accounts of the nature of Brahman,
humankind, and the cosmos. Sruti contrasts with smrti tradition, which is
humanly produced commentary on scripture. The Bhagavad Gita, perhaps strictly
smrti, typically has the de facto status of sruti.
Venn diagram, a logic
diagram invented by the logician John Venn in which standard form statements
the four kinds listed below are represented by two appropriately marked
overlapping circles, as follows: Syllogisms are represented by three
overlapping circles, as in the examples below. If a few simple rules are
followed, e.g. “diagram universal premises first,” then in a valid syllogism
diagramming the premises automatically gives a diagram in which the conclusion
is represented. In an invalid syllogism diagramming the premises does not
automatically give a diagram in which the conclusion is represented, as below.
Venn diagrams are less perspicuous for the beginner than Euler diagrams.
verificationism, a
metaphysical theory about what determines meaning: the meaning of a statement
consists in its methods of verification. Verificationism thus differs radically
from the account that identifies meaning with truth conditions, as is implicit
in Frege’s work and explicit in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus and throughout the
writings of Davidson. On Davidson’s theory, e.g., the crucial notions for a
theory of meaning are truth and falsity. Contemporary verificationists, under
the influence of the Oxford philosopher Michael Dummett, propose what they see
as a constraint on the concept of truth rather than a criterion of
meaningfulness. No foundational place is generally assigned in modern
verificationist semantics to corroboration by observation statements; and
modern verificationism is not reductionist. Thus, many philosophers read
Quine’s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” as rejecting verificationism. This is
because they fail to notice an important distinction. What Quine rejects is not
verificationism but “reductionism,” namely, the theory that there is, for each
statement, a corresponding range of verifying conditions determinable a priori.
Reductionism is inherently localist with regard to verification; whereas
verificationism, as such, is neutral on whether verification is holistic. And,
lastly, modern verificationism is, veil of ignorance verificationism 953 953 whereas traditional verificationism
never was, connected with revisionism in the philosophy of logic and
mathematics e.g., rejecting the principle of bivalence.
Verstehen German,
‘understanding’, ‘interpretation’, a method in the human sciences that aims at
reconstructing meanings from the “agent’s point of view.” Such a method makes
primary how agents understand themselves, as, e.g., when cultural
anthropologists try to understand symbols and practices from the “native’s
point of view.” Understanding in this sense is often contrasted with
explanation, or Erklärung. Whereas explanations discover causes in light of
general laws and take an external perspective, understanding aims at
explicating the meaning that, from an internal perspective, an action or
expression has for the actor. This distinction often is the basis for a further
methodological and ontological distinction between the natural and the human
sciences, the Natur- and the Geisteswissenschaften. Whereas the data of the
natural sciences may be theory-dependent and in that sense interpretive, the
human sciences are “doubly” interpretive; they try to interpret the
interpretations that human subjects give to their actions and practices. The
human sciences do not aim at explaining events but at understanding meanings,
texts, and text analogues. Actions, artifacts, and social relations are all
like texts in that they have a significance for and by human subjects. The
method of Verstehen thus denies the “unity of science” thesis typical of
accounts of explanation given by empiricists and positivists. However, other
philosophers such as Weber argue against such a dichotomy and assert that the
social sciences in particular must incorporate features of both explanation and
understanding, and psychoanalysis and theories of ideology unify both
approaches. Even among proponents of this method, the precise nature of
interpretation remains controversial. While Dilthey and other neo-Kantians
proposed that Verstehen is the imaginative reexperiencing of the subjective
point of view of the actor, Wittgenstein and his following propose a sharp
distinction between reasons and causes and understand reasons in terms of
relating an action to the relevant rules or norms that it follows. In both
cases, the aim of the human sciences is to understand what the text or text
analogue really means for the agent. Following Heidegger, recent German
hermeneutics argues that Verstehen does not refer to special disciplinary techniques
nor to merely cognitive and theoretical achievements, but to the practical mode
of all human existence, its situatedness in a world that projects various
possibilities. All understanding then becomes interpretation, itself a
universal feature of all human activity, including the natural sciences. The
criteria of success in Verstehen also remain disputed, particularly since many
philosophers deny that it constitutes a method. If all understanding is
interpretation, then there are no presuppositionless, neutral data that can put
them to an empirical test. Verstehen is therefore not a method but an event, in
which there is a “fusion of horizons” between text and interpreter. Whether
criteria such as coherence, the capacity to engage in a tradition, or increasing
dialogue apply depends on the type, purpose, and context of various interpretations.
vicious regress, regress
that is in some way unacceptable, where a regress is an infinite series of
items each of which is in some sense dependent on a prior item of a similar
sort, e.g. an infinite series of events each of which is caused by the next
prior event in the series. Reasons for holding a regress to be vicious might be
that it is either impossible or that its existence is inconsistent with things known
to be true. The claim that something would lead to a vicious regress is often
made as part of a reductio ad absurdum argument strategy. An example of this
can be found in Aquinas’s argument for the existence of an uncaused cause on
the ground that an infinite regress of causes is vicious. Those responding to
the argument have sometimes contended that this regress is not in fact vicious
and hence that the argument fails. A more convincing example of a regress is
generated by the principle that one’s coming to know the meaning of a word must
always be based on a prior understanding of other words. If this principle is
correct, then one can know the meaning of a word w1 only on the basis of
previously understanding the meanings of other words w2 and w3. But a further
application of the principle yields the result that one can understand these
words w2 and w3 only on the basis of understanding still other words. This
leads to an infinite regress. Since no one understands any words at birth, the
regress implies that no one ever comes to understand any words. But this is
clearly false. Since the existence of this regress is inconsistent with an
obvious truth, we may conclude that the regress is vicious and consequently
that the principle that generates it is false.
Vico, Philosopher who
founded modern philosophy of history, philosophy of culture, and philosophy of
mythology. He was born and lived all his life in or near Naples, where he
taught eloquence. The Inquisition was a force in Naples throughout Vico’s lifetime.
A turning point in his career was his loss of the concourse for a chair of
civil law 1723. Although a disappointment and an injustice, it enabled him to
produce his major philosophical work. He was appointed royal historiographer by
Charles of Bourbon. Vico’s major work is “La scienza nuova” completely revised in a second, definitive
version in 1730. In the 1720s, he published three connected works in Latin on
jurisprudence, under the title Universal Law; one contains a sketch of his
conception of a “new science” of the historical life of nations. Vico’s
principal works preceding this are On the Study Methods of Our Time 1709,
comparing the ancients with the moderns regarding human education, and On the
Most Ancient Wisdom of the Italians 1710, attacking the Cartesian conception of
metaphysics. His Autobiography inaugurates the conception of modern
intellectual autobiography. Basic to Vico’s philosophy is his principle that
“the true is the made” “verum ipsum factum”, that what is true is convertible
with what is made. This principle is central in his conception of “science”
scientia, scienza. A science is possible only for those subjects in which such
a conversion is possible. There can be a science of mathematics, since
mathematical truths are such because we make them. Analogously, there can be a
science of the civil world of the historical life of nations. Since we make the
things of the civil world, it is possible for us to have a science of them. As
the makers of our own world, like God as the maker who makes by knowing and
knows by making, we can have knowledge per caussas through causes, from within.
In the natural sciences we can have only conscientia a kind of “consciousness”,
not scientia, because things in nature are not made by the knower. Vico’s “new
science” is a science of the principles whereby “men make history”; it is also
a demonstration of “what providence has wrought in history.” All nations rise
and fall in cycles within history corsi e ricorsi in a pattern governed by
providence. The world of nations or, in the Augustinian phrase Vico uses, “the
great city of the human race,” exhibits a pattern of three ages of “ideal
eternal history” storia ideale eterna. Every nation passes through an age of
gods when people think in terms of gods, an age of heroes when all virtues and
institutions are formed through the personalities of heroes, and an age of
humans when all sense of the divine is lost, life becomes luxurious and false,
and thought becomes abstract and ineffective; then the cycle must begin again.
In the first two ages all life and thought are governed by the primordial power
of “imagination” fantasia and the world is ordered through the power of humans
to form experience in terms of “imaginative universals” universali fantastici.
These two ages are governed by “poetic wisdom” sapienza poetica. At the basis
of Vico’s conception of history, society, and knowledge is a conception of
mythical thought as the origin of the human world. Fantasia is the original
power of the human mind through which the true and the made are converted to
create the myths and gods that are at the basis of any cycle of history.
Michelet was the primary supporter of Vico’s ideas in the nineteenth century;
he made them the basis of his own philosophy of history. Coleridge is the principal
disseminator of Vico’s views in England. James Joyce used the New Science as a
substructure for Finnegans Wake, making plays on Vico’s name, beginning with
one in Latin in the first sentence: “by a commodius vicus of recirculation.”
Croce revives Vico’s philosophical thought, wishing to conceive Vico as the
Italian Hegel. Vico’s ideas have been the subject of analysis by such prominent
philosophical thinkers as Horkheimer and Berlin, by anthropologists such as
Edmund Leach, and by literary critics such as René Wellek and Herbert
Read.
Vienna Circle vide ayerism -- a group of philosophers and
scientists who met periodically for discussions in Vienna from 1922 to 1938 and
who proposed a self-consciously revolutionary conception of scientific
knowledge. The Circle was initiated by the mathematician Hans Hahn to continue
a prewar forum with the physicist Philip Frank and the social scientist Otto
Neurath after the arrival in Vienna of Moritz Schlick, a philosopher who had
studied with Max Planck. Carnap joined in 1926 from 1931 in Prague; other
members included Herbert Feigl from 1930 in Iowa, Friedrich Waismann, Bergmann,
Viktor Kraft, and Bela von Juhos. Viennese associates of the Circle included
Kurt Gödel, Karl Menger, Felix Kaufmann, and Edgar Zilsel. Popper was not a
member or associate. During its formative period the Circle’s activities were
confined to discussion meetings many on Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. In 1929 the
Circle entered its public period with the formation of the Verein Ernst Mach,
the publication of its manifesto Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung: Der Wiener
Kreis by Carnap, Hahn, and Neurath translated in Neurath, Empiricism and
Sociology, 1973, and the first of a series of philosophical monographs edited
by Frank and Schlick. It also began collaboration with the independent but
broadly like-minded Berlin “Society of Empirical Philosophy,” including
Reichenbach, Kurt Grelling, Kurt Lewin, Friedrich Kraus, Walter Dubislav,
Hempel, and Richard von Mises: the groups together organized their first public
conferences in Prague and Königsberg, acquired editorship of a philosophical
journal renamed Erkenntnis, and later organized the international Unity of
Science congresses. The death and dispersion of key members from 1934 onward
Hahn died in 1934, Neurath left for Holland in 1934, Carnap left for the United
States in 1935, Schlick died in 1936 did not mean the extinction of Vienna
Circle philosophy. Through the subsequent work of earlier visitors Ayer, Ernest
Nagel, Quine and members and collaborators who emigrated to the United States
Carnap, Feigl, Frank, Hempel, and Reichenbach, the logical positivism of the
Circle Reichenbach and Neurath independently preferred “logical empiricism”
strongly influenced the development of analytic philosophy. The Circle’s
discussions concerned the philosophy of formal and physical science, and even
though their individual publications ranged much wider, it is the attitude
toward science that defines the Circle within the philosophical movements of
central Europe at the time. The Circle rejected the need for a specifically
philosophical epistemology that bestowed justification on knowledge claims from
beyond science itself. In this, the Circle may also have drawn on a distinct
Austrian tradition a thesis of its historian Neurath: in most of Germany,
science and philosophy had parted ways during the nineteenth century. Starting
with Helmholtz, of course, there also arose a movement that sought to
distinguish the scientific respectability of the Kantian tradition from the
speculations of German idealism, yet after 1880 neo-Kantians insisted on the
autonomy of epistemology, disparaging earlier fellow travelers as “positivist.”
Yet the program of reducing the knowledge claim of science and providing
legitimations to what’s left found wide favor with the more empirical-minded
like Mach. Comprehensive description, not explanation, of natural phenomena
became the task for theorists who no longer looked to philosophy for
foundations, but found them in the utility of their preferred empirical
procedures. Along with the positivists, the Vienna Circle thought uneconomical
the Kantian answer to the question of the possibility of objectivity, the
synthetic a priori. Moreover, the Vienna Circle and its conventionalist
precursors Poincaré and Duhem saw them contradicted by the results of formal
science. Riemann’s geometries showed that questions about the geometry of
physical space were open to more than one answer: Was physical space Euclidean
or non-Euclidean? It fell to Einstein and the pre-Circle Schlick Space and Time
in Contemporary Physics, 1917 to argue that relativity theory showed the
untenability of Kant’s conception of space and time as forever fixed synthetic
a priori forms of intuition. Yet Frege’s anti-psychologistic critique had also
shown empiricism unable to account for knowledge of arithmetic and the
conventionalists had ended the positivist dream of a theory of experiential
elements that bridged the gap between descriptions of fact and general
principles of science. How, then, could the Vienna Circle defend the claim under attack as just one worldview among
others that science provides knowledge?
The Circle confronted the problem of constitutive conventions. As befitted
their self-image beyond Kant and Mach, they found their paraVienna Circle
Vienna Circle 956 956 digmatic answer
in the theory of relativity: they thought that irreducible conventions of
measurement with wide-ranging implications were sharply separable from pure
facts like point coincidences. Empirical theories were viewed as logical
structures of statements freely created, yet accountable to experiential input
via their predictive consequences identifiable by observation. The Vienna
Circle defended empiricism by the reconceptualization of the relation between a
priori and a posteriori inquiries. First, in a manner sympathetic to Frege’s
and Russell’s doctrine of logicism and guided by Wittgenstein’s notion of
tautology, arithmetic was considered a part of logic and treated as entirely
analytical, without any empirical content; its truth was held to be exhausted
by what is provable from the premises and rules of a formal symbolic system.
Carnap’s Logical Syntax of Language, 1934, assimilated Gödel’s incompleteness
result by claiming that not every such proof could be demonstrated in those
systems themselves which are powerful enough to represent classical arithmetic.
The synthetic a priori was not needed for formal science because all of its
results were non-synthetic. Second, the Circle adopted verificationism:
supposedly empirical concepts whose applicability was indiscernible were
excluded from science. The terms for unobservables were to be reconstructed by
logical operations from the observational terms. Only if such reconstructions
were provided did the more theoretical parts of science retain their empirical
character. Just what kind of reduction was aimed for was not always clear and
earlier radical positions were gradually weakened; Reichenbach instead
considered the relation between observational and theoretical statements to be
probabilistic. Empirical science needed no synthetic a priori either; all of
its statements were a posteriori. Combined with the view that the analysis of
the logical form of expressions allowed for the exact determination of their
combinatorial value, verificationism was to exhibit the knowledge claims of
science and eliminate metaphysics. Whatever meaning did not survive
identification with the scientific was deemed irrelevant to knowledge claims
Reichenbach did not share this view either. Since the Circle also observed the
then long-discussed ban on issuing unconditional value statements in science,
its metaethical positions may be broadly characterized as endorsing
noncognitivism. Its members were not simply emotivists, however, holding that
value judgments were mere expressions of feeling, but sought to distinguish the
factual and evaluative contents of value judgments. Those who, like Schlick
Questions of Ethics, 1930, engaged in metaethics, distinguished the expressive
component x desires y of value judgments from their implied descriptive
component doing zfurthers aim y and held that the demand inherent in moral
principles possessed validity if the implied description was true and the expressed
desire was endorsed. This analysis of normative concepts did not render them
meaningless but allowed for psychological and sociological studies of ethical
systems; Menger’s formal variant Morality, Decision and Social Organization,
1934 proved influential for decision theory. The semiotic view that knowledge
required structured representations was developed in close contact with
foundational research in mathematics and depended on the “new” logic of Frege,
Russell, and Wittgenstein, out of which quantification theory was emerging.
Major new results were quickly integrated albeit controversially and Carnap’s
works reflect the development of the conception of logic itself. In his Logical
Syntax he adopted the “Principle of Tolerance” vis-à-vis the question of the
foundation of the formal sciences: the choice of logics and languages was
conventional and constrained, apart from the demand for consistency, only by
pragmatic considerations. The proposed language form and its difference from
alternatives simply had to be stated as exactly as possible: whether a
logico-linguistic framework as a whole correctly represented reality was a
cognitively meaningless question. Yet what was the status of the verifiability
principle? Carnap’s suggestion that it represents not a discovery but a
proposal for future scientific language use deserves to be taken seriously, for
it not only characterizes his own conventionalism, but also amplifies the
Circle’s linguistic turn, according to which all philosophy concerned ways of representing,
rather than the nature of the represented. What the Vienna Circle “discovered”
was how much of science was conventional: its verificationism was a proposal
for accommodating the creativity of scientific theorizing without accommodating
idealism. Whether an empirical claim in order to be meaningful needed to be
actually verified or only potentially verifiable, or fallible or only
potentially testable, and whether so by current or only by future means, became
matters of discussion during the 1930s. Equally important for the question
whether the Circle’s conventionalism avoided idealism and metaphysics were the
issues of the status of theoretical discourse about unobservables and the
nature of science’s empirical foundation. The view suggested in Schlick’s early
General Theory of Knowledge 1918, 2d. ed. 1925 and Frank’s The Causal Law and
its Limitations 1932 and elaborated in Carnap’s “Logical Foundations of the
Unity of Science” in Foundations of the Unity of Science I.1, 1938
characterized the theoretical language as an uninterpreted calculus that is
related to the fully interpreted observational language only by partial
definitions. Did such an instrumentalism require for its empirical anchor the
sharp separation of observational from theoretical terms? Could such a
separation even be maintained? Consider the unity of science thesis. According
to the methodological version, endorsed by all members, all of science abides
by the same criteria: no basic methodological differences separate the natural
from the social or cultural sciences Geisteswissenschaften as claimed by those
who distinguish between ‘explanation’ and ‘understanding’. According to the
metalinguistic version, all objects of scientific knowledge could in principle
be comprehended by the same “universal” language. Physicalism asserts that this
is the language that speaks of physical objects. While everybody in the Circle
endorsed physicalism in this sense, the understanding of its importance varied,
as became clear in the socalled protocol sentence debate. The nomological
version of the unity thesis was only later clearly distinguished: whether all
scientific laws could be reduced to those of physics was another matter on
which Neurath came to differ. Ostensively, this debate concerned the question
of the form, content, and epistemological status of scientific evidence
statements. Schlick’s unrevisable “affirmations” talked about phenomenal states
in statements not themselves part of the language of science “The Foundation of
Knowledge,” 1934, translated in Ayer, ed., Logical Positivism. Carnap’s
preference changed from unrevisable statements in a primitive methodologically
solipsistic protocol language that were fallibly translatable into the
physicalistic system language 1931; see Unity of Science, 1934, via arbitrary
revisable statements of that system language that are taken as temporary
resting points in testing 1932, to revisable statements in the scientific
observation language 1935; see “Testability and Meaning,” Philosophy of Science,
193637. These changes were partly prompted by Neurath, whose own revisable
“protocol statements” spoke, amongst other matters, of the relation between
observers and the observed in a “universal slang” that mixed expressions of the
physicalistically cleansed colloquial and the high scientific languages
“Protocol Statements,” 1932, translated in Ayer, ed., Logical Positivism.
Ultimately, these proposals answered to different projects. Since all agreed
that all statements of science were hypothetical, the questions of their
“foundation” concerned rather the very nature of Vienna Circle philosophy. For
Schlick philosophy became the activity of meaning determination inspired by
Wittgenstein; Carnap pursued it as the rational reconstruction of knowledge
claims concerned only with what Reichenbach called the “context of
justification” its logical aspects, not the “context of discovery”; and Neurath
replaced philosophy altogether with a naturalistic, interdisciplinary,
empirical inquiry into science as a distinctive discursive practice, precluding
the orthodox conception of the unity of science. The Vienna Circle was neither
a monolithic nor a necessarily reductionist philosophical movement, and quick
assimilation to the tradition of British empiricism mistakes its struggles with
the formcontent dichotomy for foundationalism, when instead sophisticated
responses to the question of the presuppositions of their own theories of
knowledge were being developed. In its time and place, the Circle was a
minority voice; the sociopolitical dimension of its theories stressed more by some Neurath than others
Schlick as a renewal of Enlightenment
thought, ultimately against the rising tide of Blutund-Boden metaphysics, is
gaining recognition. After the celebrated “death” of reductionist logical
positivism in the 1960s the historical Vienna Circle is reemerging as a
multifaceted object of the history of analytical philosophy itself, revealing
in nuce different strands of reasoning still significant for postpositivist
theory of science. .
Vijñanavada, an idealist
school of Buddhist thought in India in the fourth century A.D. It engaged in
lively debates on important epistemological and metaphysical issues with the
Buddhist Madhyamika school known for its relativistic and nihilistic views,
with Buddhist realist schools, and with various Hindu philosophical systems of
its time. Madhyamika philosophy used effective dialectic to show the
contradictions in our everyday philosophical notions such as cause, substance,
self, etc., but the Vijñanavada school, while agreeing with the Madhyamikas on
this point, went further and Vijñanavada Vijñanavada 958 958 gave innovative explanations regarding
the origin and the status of our mental constructions and of the mind itself.
Unlike the Madhyamikas, who held that reality is “emptiness” sunyata, the
Vijñanavadins held that the reality is consciousness or the mind vijñana. The
Vijñanavada school is also known as Yogacara. Its idealism is remarkably
similar to the subjective idealism of Berkeley. Consistent with the process
ontology of all the Buddhist schools in India, Vijñanavadins held that
consciousness or the mind is not a substance but an ever-changing stream of
ideas or impressions.
vijñapti, Indian Buddhist
term meaning ‘representation’, used by some philosophers as a label for a
mental event that appears, phenomenally, to have an intentional object and to
represent or communicate to its possessor some information about extramental
reality. The term was used mostly by Buddhists with idealist tendencies who
claimed that there is nothing but representation, nothing but communicative
mental events, and that a complete account of human experience can be given
without postulating the existence of anything extramental. This view was not
uncontroversial, and in defending it Indian Buddhists developed arguments that
are in important ways analogous to those constructed by Western idealists.
violence, 1 the use of
force to cause physical harm, death, or destruction physical violence; 2 the
causing of severe mental or emotional harm, as through humiliation,
deprivation, or brainwashing, whether using force or not psychological
violence; 3 more broadly, profaning, desecrating, defiling, or showing
disrespect for i.e., “doing violence” to something valued, sacred, or
cherished; 4 extreme physical force in the natural world, as in tornados,
hurricanes, and earthquakes. Physical violence may be directed against persons,
animals, or property. In the first two cases, harm, pain, suffering, and death
figure prominently; in the third, illegality or illegitimacy the forceful
destruction of property is typically considered violence when it lacks
authorization. Psychological violence applies principally to persons. It may be
understood as the violation of beings worthy of respect. But it can apply to
higher animals as well as in the damaging mental effects of some
experimentation, e.g., involving isolation and deprivation. Environmentalists
sometimes speak of violence against the environment, implying both destruction
and disrespect for the natural world. Sometimes the concept of violence is used
to characterize acts or practices of which one morally disapproves. To this
extent it has a normative force. But this prejudges whether violence is wrong.
One may, on the other hand, regard inflicting harm or death as only prima facie
wrong i.e., wrong all other things being equal. This gives violence a normative
character, establishing its prima facie wrongness. But it leaves open the
ultimate moral justifiability of its use. Established practices of physical or
psychological violence e.g., war,
capital punishment constitute
institutionalized violence. So do illegal or extralegal practices like
vigilantism, torture, and state terrorism e.g., death squads. Anarchists
sometimes regard the courts, prisons, and police essential to maintaining the
state as violence. Racism and sexism may be considered institutional violence
owing to their associated psychological as well as physical violence.
vipassana Pali, ‘insight’,
‘discernment’, Indian Buddhist term used to describe both a particular kind of
meditational practice and the states of consciousness produced by it. The
meditational practice is aimed at getting the practitioner to perceive and
cognize in accord with the major categories of Buddhist metaphysics. Since that
metaphysics is constitutively deconstructive, being concerned with parts rather
than wholes, the method too is analytic and deconstructive. The practitioner is
encouraged to analyze the perceived solidities and continuities of her everyday
experience into transitory events, and so to cultivate the perception of such
events until she experiences the world no longer in terms of medium-sized
physical objects that endure through time, but solely in terms of transitory
events. Arriving at such a condition is called the attainment of vipassana.
virtue epistemology, the
subfield of epistemology that takes epistemic virtue to be central to
understanding justification or knowledge or both. An epistemic virtue is a
personal quality conducive to the discovery of truth, the avoidance of error,
or some other intellectually valuable goal. Following Aristotle, we should
distinguish these virtues from such qualities as wisdom or good judgment, which
are the intellectual basis of practical
but not necessarily intellectual
success. The importance, and to an extent, the very definition, of this
notion depends, however, on larger issues of epistemology. For those who favor
a naturalist conception of knowledge say, as belief formed in a “reliable” way,
there is reason to call any truth-conducive quality or properly working
cognitive mechanism an epistemic virtue. There is no particular reason to limit
the epistemic virtues to recognizable personal qualities: a high mathematical
aptitude may count as an epistemic virtue. For those who favor a more
“normative” conception of knowledge, the corresponding notion of an epistemic
virtue or vice will be narrower: it will be tied to personal qualities like
impartiality or carelessness whose exercise one would associate with an ethics
of belief.
virtue ethics, also
called virtue-based ethics and agent-based ethics, conceptions or theories of
morality in which virtues play a central or independent role. Thus, it is more
than simply the account of the virtues offered by a given theory. Some take the
principal claim of virtue ethics to be about the moral subject that, in living her life, she should focus
her attention on the cultivation of her or others’ virtues. Others take the principal
claim to be about the moral theorist
that, in mapping the structure of our moral thought, she should
concentrate on the virtues. This latter view can be construed weakly as holding
that the moral virtues are no less basic than other moral concepts. In this
type of virtue ethics, virtues are independent of other moral concepts in that
claims about morally virtuous character or action are, in the main, neither
reducible to nor justified on the basis of underlying claims about moral duty
or rights, or about what is impersonally valuable. It can also be construed
strongly as holding that the moral virtues are more basic than other moral
concepts. In such a virtue ethics, virtues are fundamental, i.e., claims about
other moral concepts are either reducible to underlying claims about moral
virtues or justified on their basis. Forms of virtue ethics predominated in
Western philosophy before the Renaissance, most notably in Aristotle, but also
in Plato and Aquinas. Several ancient and medieval philosophers endorsed strong
versions of virtue ethics. These views focused on character rather than on
discrete behavior, identifying illicit behavior with vicious behavior, i.e.,
conduct that would be seriously out of character for a virtuous person. A
virtuous person, in turn, was defined as one with dispositions relevantly
linked to human flourishing. On these views, while a person of good character,
or someone who carefully observes her, may be able to articulate certain
principles or rules by which she guides her conduct or to which, at least, it
outwardly conforms, the principles are not an ultimate source of moral
justification. On the contrary, they are justified only insofar as the conduct
they endorse would be in character for a virtuous person. For Aristotle, the
connection between flourishing and virtue seems conceptual. He conceived moral
virtues as dispositions to choose under the proper guidance of reason, and
defined a flourishing life as one lived in accordance with these virtues. While
most accounts of the virtues link them to the flourishing of the virtuous
person, there are other possibilities. In principle, the flourishing to which
virtue is tied whether causally or conceptually may be either that of the
virtuous subject herself, or that of some patient who is a recipient of her
virtuous behavior, or that of some larger affected group the agent’s community, perhaps, or all
humanity, or even sentient life in general. For the philosophers of ancient
Greece, it was human nature, usually conceived teleologically, that fixed the
content of this flourishing. Medieval Christian writers reinterpreted this,
stipulating both that the flourishing life to which the virtues lead extends
past death, and that human flourishing is not merely the fulfillment of capacities
and tendencies inherent in human nature, but is the realization of a divine
plan. In late twentieth-century versions of virtue ethics, some theorists have
suggested that it is neither to a teleology inherent in human nature nor to the
divine will that we should look in determining the content of that flourishing
to which the virtues lead. They understand flourishing more as a matter of a
person’s living a life that meets the standards of her cultural, historical
tradition. In his most general characterization, Aristotle called a thing’s
virtues those features of it that made it and its operation good. The moral
virtues were what made people live well. This use of ‘making’ is ambiguous.
Where he and other premodern thinkers thought the connection between virtues
and living well to be conceptual, moral theorists of the modernist era have
usually virtue ethics virtue ethics understood it causally. They commonly
maintain that a virtue is a character trait that disposes a person to do what
can be independently identified as morally required or to effect what is best
best for herself, according to some theories; best for others, according to
different ones. Benjamin Franklin, e.g., deemed it virtuous for a person to be
frugal, because he thought frugality was likely to result in her having a less
troubled life. On views of this sort, a lively concern for the welfare of
others has moral importance only inasmuch as it tends to motivate people
actually to perform helpful actions. In short, benevolence is a virtue because
it conduces to beneficent conduct; veracity, because it conduces to truth
telling; fidelity, because it conduces to promise keeping; and so on. Reacting
to this aspect of modernist philosophy, recent proponents of virtue ethics deny
that moral virtues derive from prior determinations of what actions are right
or of what states of affairs are best. Some, especially certain theorists of
liberalism, assign virtues to what they see as one compartment of moral thought
and duties to a separate, and only loosely connected compartment. For them, the
life and theory of virtue is autonomous. They hold that virtues and duties have
independent sources of justification, with virtues chiefly concerned with the
individual’s personal “ideals,” self-image, or conception of her life goals,
while duties and rights are thought to derive from social rules regulating
interpersonal dealings. Proponents of virtue ethics maintain that it has
certain advantages over more modern alternatives. They argue that virtue ethics
is properly concrete, because it grounds morality in facts about human nature
or about the concrete development of particular cultural traditions, in
contrast with modernist attempts to ground morality in subjective preference or
in abstract principles of reason. They also claim that virtue ethics is truer
to human psychology in concentrating on the less conscious aspects of
motivation on relatively stable
dispositions, habits, and long-term goals, for example where modern ethics focuses on decision
making directed by principles and rules. Virtue ethics, some say, offers a more
unified and comprehensive conception of moral life, one that extends beyond
actions to comprise wants, goals, likes and dislikes, and, in general, what
sort of person one is and aims to be. Proponents of virtue ethics also contend
that, without the sensitivity and appreciation of their situation and its
opportunities that only virtues consistently make available, agents cannot
properly apply the rules that modernist ethical theories offer to guide their
actions. Nor, in their view, will the agent follow those rules unless her
virtues offer her sufficient clarity of purpose and perseverance against
temptation. Several objections have been raised against virtue ethics in its
most recent forms. Critics contend that it is antiquarian, because it relies on
conceptions of human nature whose teleology renders them obsolete; circular,
because it allegedly defines right action in terms of virtues while defining
virtues in terms of right action; arbitrary and irrelevant to modern society,
since there is today no accepted standard either of what constitutes human
flourishing or of which dispositions lead to it; of no practical use, because
it offers no guidance when virtues seem to conflict; egoistic, in that it
ultimately directs the subject’s moral attention to herself rather than to
others; and fatalistic, in allowing the morality of one’s behavior to hinge
finally on luck in one’s constitution, upbringing, and opportunities. There may
be versions of virtue ethics that escape the force of all or most of the
objections, but not every form of virtue ethics can claim for itself all the advantages
mentioned above.
Vishnu from Sanskrit
Vifpu, major Hindu god and Supreme Lord for his devotees, the Vaishpavites.
Vaishpavite philosophers regard Vishnu as the referent of the term ‘Brahman’ in
the Vedic texts. Later texts attempt a synthesis of Vishnu with two other
deities into a trimurti ‘three forms’ of the Absolute, with Brahma as Creator,
Vishnu as Preserver, and Siva as Destroyer. This relatively unpopular idea is
used by modern thinkers to speak of these gods as three forms of the formless
Absolute. Madhva and Ramanuja regard Vishnu as the Highest Lord, possessed of
infinite good qualities and superior to the qualityless Absolute of the
nondualist thinkers. Vaishpavite thinkers identify Vishnu with the Purusa, the
primeval, cosmic person, and Prajapati, Creator god, of the Vedas, and give him
epithets that identify Vishnu with other representatives of a Supreme Being. He
is Creator, Preserver, and Destroyer of the Universe. Vishnu is best known for
the doctrine of avatar, his “descents” into the world in various virtues,
cardinal forms to promote righteousness. Through this and the concept of
vyuhas, aspects or fragments, Vaishpavites incorporated other deities, hero
cults, and savior myths into their fold. He was a minor deity in the early
Vedic literature, known for his “three strides” across the universe, which
indicate that he pervades all. During the epic period 400 B.C.A.D. 400, Vishnu
became one of the most popular gods in India, represented iconographically as
dark-complexioned and holding a conch and discus. His consort is usually Laksmi
and his vehicle the bird Garuda.
Visistadvaita Vedanta, a
form of Hinduism for which Brahman is an independently existing, omnipotent,
omniscient personal deity. In creative, morally serious sport, Brahman
everlastingly sustains in existence a world of both minds and physical things,
these together being the body of Brahman in the sense that Brahman can act on
any part of the world without first acting on some other part and that the
world manifests though in some ways it also hides Brahman’s nature. In response
to repentance and trust, Brahman will forgive one’s sins and bring one into a
gracious relationship that ends the cycle of rebirths.
vital lie, 1 an instance
of self-deception or lying to oneself when it fosters hope, confidence,
self-esteem, mental health, or creativity; 2 any false belief or unjustified
attitude that helps people cope with difficulties; 3 a lie to other people
designed to promote their wellbeing. For example, self-deceiving optimism about
one’s prospects for success in work or personal relationships may generate
hope, mobilize energy, enrich life’s meaning, and increase chances for success.
Henrik Ibsen dramatized “life-lies” as essential for happiness The Wild Duck,
1884, and Eugene O’Neill portrayed “pipe dreams” as necessary crutches The
Iceman Cometh, 1939. Nietzsche endorsed “pious illusions” or “holy fictions”
about the past that liberate individuals and societies from shame and guilt On
the Advantage and Disadvantage of History for Life, 1874. Schiller praised
normal degrees of vanity and self-conceit because they support selfesteem Problems
of Belief, 1924.
Vitoria, Dominican
jurist, political philosopher, and theologian who is regarded as the founder of
modern international law. Born in Vitoria or Burgos, he studied and taught at
the of SaintJacques in Paris, where he
met Erasmus and Vives. He also taught at the
of San Gregorio in Valladolid and at Salamanca. His most famous works
are the notes relectiones for twelve public addresses he delivered at
Salamanca, published posthumously in 1557. Two relectiones stand out: De Indis
and De jure belli. They were responses to the legal and political issues raised
by the discovery and colonization of America. In contrast with Mariana’s
contract Arianism, Vitoria held that political society is our natural state. The
aim of the state is to promote the common good and preserve the rights of
citizens. Citizenship is the result of birthplace jus solis rather than blood
jus sanguini. The authority of the state resides in the body politic but is
transferred to rulers for its proper exercise. The best form of government is
monarchy because it preserves the unity necessary for social action while
safeguarding individual freedoms. Apart from the societies of individual
states, humans belong to an international society. This society has its own
authority and laws that establish the rights and duties of the states. These
laws constitute the law of nations jus gentium.
Vives, Juan Luis
1492?1540, Spanish humanist and teacher. Born in Valencia, he attended the of Paris 150914 and lived most of his life in
Flanders. With his friend Erasmus he prepared a widely used commentary 1522 of
Augustine’s De civitate Dei. From 1523 to 1528 Vives visited England, taught at
Oxford, befriended More, and became Catherine of Aragon’s confidant. While in
Paris, Vives repudiated medieval logic as useless Adversus pseudodialecticos,
1520 and proposed instead a dialectic emphasizing resourceful reasoning and
clear and persuasive exposition De tradendis disciplinis, 1532. His method was
partially inspired by Rudolph Agricola and probably influential upon Peter
Ramus. Less interested in theology than Erasmus or More, he surpassed both in
philosophical depth. As one of the great pedagogues of his age, Vives proposed
a plan of education that substituted the Aristotelian ideal of speculative
certainty for a pragmatic probability capable of guiding action. Vives enlarged
the scope of women’s education De institutione feminae Christianae, 1524 and
contributed to the teaching of classical Latin Exercitatio linguae latinae,
1538. A champion of EuroVisistadvaita Vedanta Vives, Juan Luis 962 962 pean unity against the Turks, he
professed the belief that international order De concordia, 1526 depended upon
the control of passion De anima et vita, 1538. As a social reformer, Vives
pioneered the secularization of welfare De subventione pauperum, 1526 and
opposed the abuse of legal jargon Aedes legum, 1520. Although his Jewish
parents were victimized by the Inquisition, Vives remained a Catholic and managed
to write an apology of Christianity without taking sides in controversial
theological matters De veritate fidei, 1543. C.G.Nore.
volition, cf.
desideratum. a mental event involved with the initiation of action. ‘To will’
is sometimes taken to be the corresponding verb form of ‘volition’. The concept
of volition is rooted in modern philosophy; contemporary philosophers have
transformed it by identifying volitions with ordinary mental events, such as
intentions, or beliefs plus desires. Volitions, especially in contemporary
guises, are often taken to be complex mental events consisting of cognitive,
affective, and conative elements. The conative element is the impetus the underlying motivation for the action. A velleity is a conative
element insufficient by itself to initiate action. The will is a faculty, or
set of abilities, that yields the mental events involved in initiating action.
There are three primary theories about the role of volitions in action. The
first is a reductive account in which action is identified with the entire
causal sequence of the mental event the volition causing the bodily behavior.
J. S. Mill, for example, says: “Now what is action? Not one thing, but a series
of two things: the state of mind called a volition, followed by an effect. . .
. [T]he two together constitute the action” Logic. Mary’s raising her arm is
Mary’s mental state causing her arm to rise. Neither Mary’s volitional state
nor her arm’s rising are themselves actions; rather, the entire causal sequence
the “causing” is the action. The primary difficulty for this account is
maintaining its reductive status. There is no way to delineate volition and the
resultant bodily behavior without referring to action. There are two
non-reductive accounts, one that identifies the action with the initiating
volition and another that identifies the action with the effect of the
volition. In the former, a volition is the action, and bodily movements are
mere causal consequences. Berkeley advocates this view: “The Mind . . . is to be
accounted active in . . . so far forth as volition is included. . . . In
plucking this flower I am active, because I do it by the motion of my hand,
which was consequent upon my volition” Three Dialogues. In this century,
Prichard is associated with this theory: “to act is really to will something”
Moral Obligation, 1949, where willing is sui generis though at other places
Prichard equates willing with the action of mentally setting oneself to do
something. In this sense, a volition is an act of will. This account has come
under attack by Ryle Concept of Mind, 1949. Ryle argues that it leads to a
vicious regress, in that to will to do something, one must will to will to do
it, and so on. It has been countered that the regress collapses; there is
nothing beyond willing that one must do in order to will. Another criticism of
Ryle’s, which is more telling, is that ‘volition’ is an obscurantic term of
art; “[volition] is an artificial concept. We have to study certain specialist
theories in order to find out how it is to be manipulated. . . . [It is like]
‘phlogiston’ and ‘animal spirits’ . . . [which] have now no utility” Concept of
Mind. Another approach, the causal theory of action, identifies an action with
the causal consequences of volition. Locke, e.g., says: “Volition or willing is
an act of the mind directing its thought to the production of any action, and
thereby exerting its power to produce it. . . . [V]olition is nothing but that
particular determination of the mind, whereby . . . the mind endeavors to give
rise, continuation, or stop, to any action which it takes to be in its power”
Essay concerning Human Understanding. This is a functional account, since an
event is an action in virtue of its causal role. Mary’s arm rising is Mary’s
action of raising her arm in virtue of being caused by her willing to raise it.
If her arm’s rising had been caused by a nervous twitch, it would not be
action, even if the bodily movements were photographically the same. In
response to Ryle’s charge of obscurantism, contemporary causal theorists tend
to identify volitions with ordinary mental events. For example, Davidson takes
the cause of actions to be beliefs plus desires and Wilfrid Sellars takes
volitions to be intentions to do something here and now. Despite its plausibility,
however, the causal theory faces two difficult problems: the first is purported
counterexamples based on wayward causal chains connecting the antecedent mental
event and the bodily movements; the second is provision of an enlightening
account of these mental events, e.g. intending, that does justice to the conative
element.
Voltaire, pen name of
François-Marie Arouet 16941778, French philosopher and writer who won early
fame as a playwright and poet and later was an influential popularizer of Newtonian
natural philosophy. His enduring reputation rests on his acerbically witty
essays on religious and moral topics especially the Philosophical Letters,
1734, and the Philosophical Dictionary, 1764, his brilliant stories, and his
passionate polemics against the injustices of the ancien régime. In Whitehead’s
phrase, he was more “a philosophe than a philosopher” in the current
specialized disciplinary sense. He borrowed most of his views on metaphysics
and epistemology from Locke, whose work, along with Newton’s, he came to know
and extravagantly admire during his stay 172628 in England. His is best placed
in the line of great French literary moralists that includes Montaigne, Pascal,
Diderot, and Camus. Voltaire’s position is skeptical, empirical, and humanistic.
His skepticism is not of the radical sort that concerned Descartes. But he
denies that we can find adequate support for the grand metaphysical claims of
systematic philosophers, such as Leibniz, or for the dogmatic theology of
institutional religions. Voltaire’s empiricism urges us to be content with the
limited and fallible knowledge of our everyday experience and its development
through the methods of empirical science. His humanism makes a plea, based on
his empiricist skepticism, for religious and social tolerance: none of us can
know enough to be justified in persecuting those who disagree with us on
fundamental philosophical and theological matters. Voltaire’s positive view is
that our human condition, for all its flaws and perils, is meaningful and
livable strictly in its own terms, quite apart from any connection to the
threats and promises of dubious transcendental realms. Voltaire’s position is
well illustrated by his views on religion. Although complex doctrines about the
Trinity or the Incarnation strike him as gratuitous nonsense, he nonetheless is
firmly convinced of the reality of a good God who enjoins us through our moral
sense to love one another as brothers and sisters. Indeed, it is precisely this
moral sense that he finds outraged by the intolerance of institutional
Christianity. His deepest religious thinking concerns the problem of evil,
which he treated in his “Poem of the Lisbon Earthquake” and the classic tales
Zadig 1747 and Candide 1759. He rejects the Panglossian view held by Candide’s
Dr. Pangloss, a caricature of Leibniz that we can see the hand of providence in
our daily life but is prepared to acknowledge that an all-good God does not as
an extreme deism would hold let his universe just blindly run. Whatever
metaphysical truth there may be in the thought that “all is for the best in the
best of all possible worlds,” Voltaire insists that this idea is ludicrous as a
practical response to evil and recommends instead concrete action to solve
specific local problems: “We must cultivate our garden.” Voltaire was and
remains an immensely controversial figure. Will Durant regarded him as “the
greatest man who ever lived,” while Joseph de Maistre maintained that
“admiration for Voltaire is an infallible sign of a corrupt soul.” Perhaps it
is enough to say that he wrote with unequaled charm and wit and stood for
values that are essential to, if perhaps not the very core of, our humanity.
voluntarism, any
philosophical view that makes our ability to control the phenomena in question
an essential part of the correct understanding of those phenomena. Thus,
ethical voluntarism is the doctrine that the standards that define right and
wrong conduct are in some sense chosen by us. Doxastic voluntarism is the
doctrine that we have extensive control over what we believe; we choose what to
believe. A special case of doxastic voluntarism is theological voluntarism,
which implies that religious belief requires a substantial element of choice;
the evidence alone cannot decide the issue. This is a view that is closely
associated with Pascal, Kierkegaard, and James. Historical voluntarism is the
doctrine that the human will is a major factor in history. Such views contrast
with Marxist views of history. Metaphysical voluntarism is the doctrine, linked
with Schopenhauer, that the fundamental organizing principle of the world is
not the incarnation of a rational or a moral order but rather the will, which
for Schopenhauer is an ultimately meaningless striving for survival, to be
found in all of nature.
von Neumann, John 190357,
Hungarian-born American mathematician, physicist, logician, economist,
engineer, and computer scientist. Born in Budapest and trained in Hungary,
Switzerland, and Germany, he visited Princeton
in 1930 and became a professor at the Institute for Advanced Study at
Princeton in 1933. His most outstanding work in pure mathematics was on rings
of operators in Hilbert spaces. In quantum mechanics he showed the equivalence
of matrix mechanics to wave mechanics, and argued that quantum mechanics could
not be embedded in an underlying deterministic system. He established important
results in set theory and mathematical logic, and worked on Hilbert’s Program
to prove the consistency of mathematics within mathematics until he was shocked
by Gödel’s incompleteness theorems. He established the mathematical theory of
games and later showed its application to economics. In these many different
areas, von Neumann demonstrated a remarkable ability to analyze a subject
matter and develop a mathematical formalism that answered basic questions about
that subject matter; formalization in logic is the special case of this process
where the subject matter is language and reasoning. With the advent of World
War II von Neumann turned his great analytical ability to more applied areas of
hydrodynamics, ballistics, and nuclear explosives. In 1945 he began to work on
the design, use, and theory of electronic computers. He later became a leading
scientist in government. Von Neumann contributed to the hardware architecture
of the modern electronic computer, and he invented the first modern program
language. A program in this language could change the addresses of its own
instructions, so that it became possible to use the same subroutine on
different data structures and to write programs to process programs. Von
Neumann proposed to use a computer as a research tool for exploring very
complex phenomena, such as the discontinuous nature of shock waves. He began
the development of a theory of automata that would cover computing,
communication, and control systems, as well as natural organisms, biological
evolution, and societies. To this end, he initiated the study of probabilistic
automata and of selfreproducing and cellular automata.
von Wright, G. H., Finnish
philosopher, one of the most influential analytic philosophers of the twentieth
century. His early work, influenced by logical empiricism, is on logic,
probability, and induction, including contributions in modal and deontic logic,
the logic of norms and action, preference logic, tense logic, causality, and
determinism. In the 1970s his ideas about the explanation of action helped to
link the analytic tradition to Continental hermeneutics. His most important
contribution is A Treatise on Induction and Probability 1951, which develops a
system of eliminative induction using the concepts of necessary and sufficient
condition. In 1939 von Wright went to Cambridge to meet Broad, and he attended
Wittgenstein’s lectures. Regular discussions with Moore also had an impact on
him. In 1948 von Wright succeeded Wittgenstein as professor at Cambridge .
After Wittgenstein’s death in 1951, von Wright returned to Helsinki. Together
with Anscombe and Rush Rhees, he became executor and editor of Wittgenstein’s
Nachlass. The study, organization, systematization, and publication of this
exceptionally rich work became a lifelong task for him. In his Cambridge years
von Wright became interested in the logical properties of various modalities:
alethic, deontic, epistemic. An Essay in Modal Logic 1951 studies,
syntactically, various deductive systems of modal logic. That year he published
his famous article “Deontic Logic” in Mind. It made him the founder of modern
deontic logic. These logical works profoundly influenced analytic philosophy,
especially action theory. Von Wright distinguishes technical oughts means-ends
relationships from norms issued by a norm-authority. His Norm and Action 1963
discusses philosophical problems concerning the existence of norms and the
truth of normative statements. His main work on metaethics is The Varieties of
Goodness 1963. In Explanation and Understanding 1971 he turned to philosophical
problems concerning the human sciences. He defends a manipulation view of
causality, where the concept of action is basic for that of cause: human action
cannot be explained causally by laws, but must be understood intentionally. The
basic model of intentionality is the practical syllogism, which explains action
by a logical connection with wants and beliefs. This work, sometimes
characterized as anti-positivist analytical hermeneutics, bridges analytic and
Continental philosophy. His studies in truth, knowledge, modality, lawlikeness,
causality, determinism, norms, and practical inference were published in 198384
in his Philosophical Papers. von Neumann, John von Wright, G. H. 965 965 In 1961 von Wright became a member of
the Academy of Finland, the highest honor Finland gives to its scientists. Over
many years he has written, in Swedish and Finnish, eloquent essays in the
history of ideas and the philosophy of culture. He has become increasingly
critical of the modern scientific-technological civilization, its narrowly
instrumental concept of rationality, and its myth of progress. His public pleas
for peace, human rights, and a more harmonious coexistence of human beings and
nature have made him the most esteemed intellectual in the Scandinavian
countries.
voting paradox, the
possibility that if there are three candidates, A, B, and C, for democratic
choice, with at least three choosers, and the choosers are asked to make
sequential choices among pairs of candidates, A could defeat B by a majority
vote, B could defeat C, and C could defeat A. This would be the outcome if the
choosers’ preferences were ABC, BCA, and CAB. Hence, although each individual
voter may have a clear preference ordering over the candidates, the collective
may have cyclic preferences, so that individual and majoritarian collective
preference orderings are not analogous. While this fact is not a logical
paradox, it is perplexing to many analysts of social choice. It may also be
morally perplexing in that it suggests majority rule can be quite capricious.
For example, suppose we vote sequentially over various pairs of candidates,
with the winner at each step facing a new candidate. If the candidates are
favored by cyclic majorities, the last candidate to enter the fray will win the
final vote. Hence, control over the sequence of votes may determine the
outcome. It is easy to find cyclic preferences over such candidates as movies
and other matters of taste. Hence, the problem of the voting paradox is clearly
real and not merely a logical contrivance. But is it important? Institutions
may block the generation of evidence for cyclic majorities by making choices
pairwise and sequentially, as above. And some issues over which we vote provoke
preference patterns that cannot produce cycles. For example, if our issue is
one of unidimensional liberalism versus conservatism on some major political
issue such as welfare programs, there may be no one who would prefer to spend
both more and less money than what is spent in the status quo. Hence, everyone
may display single-peaked preferences with preferences falling as we move in
either direction toward more money or toward less from the peak. If all
important issues and combinations of issues had this preference structure, the
voting paradox would be unimportant. It is widely supposed by many public
choice scholars that collective preferences are not single-peaked for many
issues or, therefore, for combinations of issues. Hence, collective choices may
be quite chaotic. What order they display may result from institutional
manipulation. If this is correct, we may wonder whether democracy in the sense
of the sovereignty of the electorate is a coherent notion.
Vorstellung voting
paradox 966 966 wang, pa, Chinese
political titles meaning ‘king’ and ‘hegemon’, respectively. A true wang has
the Mandate of Heaven and rules by te rather than by force. The institution of
the pa developed during a period in which the kings of China lacked any real
power. In order to bring an end to political chaos, the most powerful of the
nobles was appointed pa, and effectively ruled while the wang reigned. During
the Warring States period in China 403221 B.C., rulers began to assume the
title of wang regardless of whether they had either the power of a pa or the
right to rule of a wang. After this period, the title of Emperor ti or huang-ti
replaced wang.
Wang Ch’ung A.D. 27100?,
Chinese philosopher, commonly regarded as the most independent-minded thinker
in the Later Han period 25220. He wrote the Lun-heng “Balanced Inquiries”.
Since Tung Chung-shu, Confucian doctrine of the unity of man and nature had
degenerated into one of mutual influence, with talk of strange phenomena and
calamities abounding. Wang Ch’ung cast serious doubts on such superstitions. He
even dared to challenge the authority of Confucius and Mencius. His outlook was
naturalistic. According to him, things in the world are produced by the
interaction of material forces ch’i. He rejected the teleological point of view
and was fatalistic.
Wang Fu-chih 161992,
Chinese philosopher and innovative Confucian thinker. Wang attacked the
Neo-Confucian dualism of li pattern and ch’i ether, arguing that li is the
orderly structure of individual ch’i implements/things and events, which are
composed of ch’i ether. Wang rejected all transcendental ontology and believed
society evolves and improves over time. He is touted as a “materialist” by
Marxist thinkers in contemporary China, though the term is hardly applicable,
as is clear from his criticisms of Shao Yung. Wang attacked Shao’s overly
“objective” account of the world, arguing that all such formal descriptions
fail because they disregard intuition, our only access to the lively, shen
spiritual nature of the universe.
Wang Pi A.D. 22649,
Chinese philosopher of the Hsüan hsüeh Mysterious Learning School. He is
described, along with thinkers like Kuo Hsiang, as a Neo-Taoist. Unlike Kuo,
who believed the world to be self-generated, Wang claimed it arose from a
mysterious unified state called wu non-being. But like Kuo, Wang regarded
Confucius as the one true sage, arguing that Lao Tzu and Chuang Tzu only
“talked about” non-being, whereas Confucius embodied it. Wang is important for
his development of the notion li pattern and his pioneering use of the paired
concepts t’i substance and yung function. His commentary on the Tao Te Ching,
the oldest known, has had a profound and persistent influence on later Chinese
thought.
Wang Yang-ming 14721529,
Chinese philosopher known for his doctrines of the unity of knowledge and
action chih-hsing ho-i and liangchih innate knowledge of the good. Wang was
also known as a sort of metaphysical idealist, anticipated by Lu Hsiang-shan,
for his insistence on the quasi-identity of mind and li principle, reason. The
basic concern of Wang’s philosophy is the question, How can one become a
Confucian sage sheng? This is a question intelligible only in the light of
understanding and commitment to the Confucian vision of jen or ideal of the
universe as a moral community. Wang reminded his students that the concrete
significance of such a vision in human life cannot be exhausted with any claim
to finality. He stressed that one must get rid of any selfish desires in the
pursuit of jen. Unlike Chu Hsi, Wang showed little interest in empirical
inquiry concerning the rationales of existing things. For him, “things” are the
objectives of moral will. To investigate things is to rectify one’s mind, to
get rid of evil thoughts and to do good. Rectification of the mind involves, in
particular, an acknowledgment of the unity of moral knowledge and action
chihhsing ho-i, an enlargement of the scope of moral concern in the light of
the vision of jen, rather than extensive acquisition of factual knowledge.
Ward, James 18431925,
English philosopher and psychologist. Influenced by Lotze, Herbart, and
Brentano, Ward sharply criticized Bain’s associationism and its allied nineteenth-century
reductive naturalism. His psychology rejected the associationists’
sensationism, which regarded mind as passive, capable only of sensory
receptivity and composed solely of cognitive presentations. Ward emphasized the
mind’s inherent activity, asserting, like Kant, the prior existence of an
inferred but necessarily existing ego or subject capable of feeling and, most
importantly, of conation, shaping both experience and behavior by the willful
exercise of attention. Ward’s psychology stresses attention and will. In his
metaphysics, Ward resisted the naturalists’ mechanistic materialism, proposing
instead a teleological spiritualistic monism. While his criticisms of
associationism and naturalism were telling, Ward was a transitional figure
whose positive influence is limited, if we except H. P. Grice who follows him
to a T. Although sympathetic to scientific psychology he founded scientific psychology in Britain
by establishing a psychology laboratory he, with his student Stout, represented the beginning
of armchair psychology at Oxford, which Grice adored. Through Stout he
influenced the hormic psychology of McDougall, and Grice who calls himself a
Stoutian “until Prichard converted me”. Ward’s major work is “Psychology”
Encyclopedia Britannica, 9th ed., 1886, reworked as Psychological Principles
1918.
wayward causal chain, a
causal chain, referred to in a proposed causal analysis of a key concept, that
goes awry. Causal analyses have been proposed for key concepts e.g., reference, action, explanation,
knowledge, artwork. There are two main cases of wayward or deviant causal
chains that defeat a causal analysis: 1 those in which the prescribed causal
route is followed, but the expected event does not occur; and 2 those in which
the expected event occurs, but the prescribed causal route is not followed.
Consider action. One proposed analysis is that a person’s doing something is an
action if and only if what he does is caused by his beliefs and desires. The
possibility of wayward causal chains defeats this analysis. For case 1,
suppose, while climbing, John finds he is supporting another man on a rope.
John wants to rid himself of this danger, and he believes that he can do so by
loosening his grip. His belief and desire unnerve him, causing him to loosen
his hold. The prescribed causal route was followed, but the ensuing event, his
grip loosening, is not an action. For case 2, suppose Harry wants to kill his
rich uncle, and he believes that he can find him at home. His beliefs and
desires so agitate him that he drives recklessly. He hits and kills a
pedestrian, who, by chance, is his uncle. The killing occurs, but without
following the prescribed causal route; the killing was an accidental
consequence of what Harry did.
Weber, Max 18641920, German
social theorist and sociologist. Born in Berlin in a liberal and intellectual
household, he taught economics in Heidelberg, where his circle included leading
sociologists and philosophers such as Simmel and Lukacs. Although Weber gave up
his professorship after a nervous breakdown in 1889, he remained important in
public life, an adviser to the commissions that drafted the peace treaty at
Versailles and the Weimar constitution. Weber’s social theory was influenced
philosophically by both neo-Kantianism and Nietzsche, creating tensions in a
theorist who focused much of his attention on Occidental rationalism and yet
was a noncognitivist in ethics. He wrote many comparative studies on topics
such as law and urbanization and a celebrated study of the cultural factors
responsible for the rise of capitalism, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of
Capitalism 1904. But his major, synthetic work in social theory is Economy and
Society 1914; it includes a methodological introduction to the basic concepts
of sociology that has been treated by many philosophers of social science. One
of the main theoretical goals of Weber’s work is to understand how social
processes become “rationalized,” taking up certain themes want-belief model
Weber, Max 968 of the German philosophy
of history since Hegel as part of social theory. Culture, e.g., became
rationalized in the process of the “disenchantment of worldviews” in the West,
a process that Weber thought had “universal significance.” But because of his
goal-oriented theory of action and his noncognitivism in ethics, Weber saw
rationalization exclusively in terms of the spread of purposive, or meansends
rationality Zweckrationalität. Rational action means choosing the most
effective means of achieving one’s goals and implies judging the consequences
of one’s actions and choices. In contrast, value rationality Wertrationalität
consists of actions oriented to ultimate ends, where considerations of
consequences are irrelevant. Although such action is rational insofar as it
directs and organizes human conduct, the choice of such ends or values
themselves cannot be a matter for rational or scientific judgment. Indeed, for
Weber this meant that politics was the sphere for the struggle between
irreducibly competing ultimate ends, where “gods and demons fight it out” and
charismatic leaders invent new gods and values. Professional politicians,
however, should act according to an “ethics of responsibility”
Verantwortungsethik aimed at consequences, and not an “ethics of conviction”
Gesinnungsethik aimed at abstract principles or ultimate ends. Weber also
believed that rationalization brought the separation of “value spheres” that
can never again be unified by reason: art, science, and morality have their own
“logics.” Weber’s influential methodological writings reject positivist
philosophy of science, yet call for “value neutrality.” He accepts the
neo-Kantian distinction, common in his day under the influence of Rickert,
between the natural and the human sciences, between the Natur- and the Geisteswissenschaften.
Because human social action is purposive and meaningful, the explanations of
social sciences must be related to the values Wertbezogen and ideals of the
actors it studies. Against positivism, Weber saw an ineliminable element of Verstehen,
or understanding of meanings, in the methodology of the human sciences. For
example, he criticized the legal positivist notion of behavioral conformity for
failing to refer to actors’ beliefs in legitimacy. But for Weber Verstehen is
not intuition or empathy and does not exclude causal analysis; reasons can be
causes. Thus, explanations in social science must have both causal and
subjective adequacy. Weber also thought that adequate explanations of
large-scale, macrosocial phenomena require the construction of ideal types,
which abstract and summarize the common features of complex, empirical
phenomena such as “sects,” “authority,” or even “the Protestant ethic.”
Weberian ideal types are neither merely descriptive nor simply heuristic, but
come at the end of inquiry through the successful theoretical analysis of
diverse phenomena in various historical and cultural contexts. Weber’s analysis
of rationality as the disenchantment of the world and the spread of purposive
reason led him to argue that reason and progress could turn into their
opposites, a notion that enormously influenced critical theory. Weber had a
critical “diagnosis of the times” and a pessimistic philosophy of history. At
the end of The Protestant Ethic Weber warns that rationalism is desiccating
sources of value and constructing an “iron cage” of increasing
bureaucratization, resulting in a loss of meaning and freedom in social life.
According to Weber, these basic tensions of modern rationality cannot be
resolved.
Weil, Simone 190943,
French religious philosopher and writer. Born in Paris, Weil was one of the
first women to graduate from the École Normale Supérieure, having earlier
studied under the philosopher Alain. While teaching in various French lycées
Weil became involved in radical leftist politics, and her early works concern
social problems and labor. They also show an attempt to work out a theory of
action as fundamental to human knowing. This is seen first in her diploma
essay, “Science and Perception in Descartes,” and later in her critique of
Marx, capitalism, and technocracy in “Reflections concerning the Causes of
Social Oppression and Liberty.” Believing that humans cannot escape certain
basic harsh necessities of embodied life, Weil sought to find a way by which
freedom and dignity could be achieved by organizing labor in such a way that
the mind could understand that necessity and thereby come to consent to it.
After a year of testing her theories by working in three factories in 193435,
Weil’s early optimism was shattered by the discovery of what she called
“affliction” malheur, a destruction of the human person to which one cannot
consent. Three important religious experiences, however, caused her to attempt
to put the problem into a Weber’s law Weil, Simone 969 969 larger context. By arguing that
necessity obeys a transcendent goodness and then by using a kenotic model of
Christ’s incarnation and crucifixion, she tried to show that affliction can
have a purpose and be morally enlightening. The key is the renunciation of any
ultimate possession of power as well as the social personality constituted by
that power. This is a process of “attention” and “decreation” by which one
sheds the veil that otherwise separates one from appreciating goodness in
anything but oneself, but most especially from God. She understands God as a
goodness that is revealed in self-emptying and in incarnation, and creation as
an act of renunciation and not power. During her last months, while working for
the Free French in London, Weil’s social and religious interests came together,
especially in The Need for Roots. Beginning with a critique of social rights
and replacing it with obligations, Weil sought to show, on the one hand, how
modern societies had illegitimately become the focus of value, and on the other
hand, how cultures could be reconstructed so that they would root humans in
something more ultimate than themselves. Returning to her earlier themes, Weil
argued that in order for this rootedness to occur, physical labor must become
the spiritual core of culture. Weil died of tuberculosis while this book was in
progress. Often regarded as mystical and syncretistic, Weil’s philosophy owes
much to an original reading of Plato e.g., in Intimations of Christianity Among
the Ancient Grecians as well as to Marx, Alain, and Christianity. Recent
studies, however, have also seen her as significantly contributing to social,
moral, and religious philosophy. Her concern with problems of action and
persons is not dissimilar to Wittgenstein’s.
well-formed formula, a
grammatically wellformed sentence or structured predicate of an artificial
language of the sort studied by logicians. A well-formed formula is sometimes
known as a wff pronounced ‘woof’ or simply a formula. Delineating the formulas
of a language involves providing it with a syntax or grammar, composed of both
a vocabulary a specification of the symbols from which the language is to be
built, sorted into grammatical categories and formation rules a purely formal
or syntactical specification of which strings of symbols are grammatically
well-formed and which are not. Formulas are classified as either open or
closed, depending on whether or not they contain free variables variables not
bound by quantifiers. Closed formulas, such as x Fx / Gx, are sentences, the
potential bearers of truth-values. Open formulas, such as Fx / Gx, are handled
in any of three ways. On some accounts, these formulas are on a par with closed
ones, the free variables being treated as names. On others, open formulas are
structured predicates, the free variables being treated as place holders for
terms. And on still other accounts, the free variables are regarded as
implicitly bound by universal quantifiers, again making open formulas
sentences.
Westermarck: philosopher
who spent his life studying the mores and morals of cultures. His main works,
The Origin and Development of Moral Ideas and Ethical Relativity, attack the
idea that moral principles express objective value. In defending ethical
relativism, he argued that moral judgments are based not on intellectual but on
emotional grounds. He admitted that cultural variability in itself does not
prove ethical relativism, but contended that the fundamental differences are so
comprehensive and deep as to constitute a strong presumption in favor of relativism.
Whewell, William
17941866, English historian, astronomer, and philosopher of science. He was a
master of Trinity , Cambridge 184166. Francis Bacon’s early work on induction
was furthered by Whewell, J. F. W. Herschel, and J. S. Mill, who attempted to
create a logic of welfare economics Whewell, William 970 970 induction, a methodology that can both
discover generalizations about experience and prove them to be necessary.
Whewell’s theory of scientific method is based on his reading of the history of
the inductive sciences. He thought that induction began with a non-inferential
act, the superimposition of an idea on data, a “colligation,” a way of seeing
facts in a “new light.” Colligations generalize over data, and must satisfy
three “tests of truth.” First, colligations must be empirically adequate; they
must account for the given data. Any number of ideas may be adequate to explain
given data, so a more severe test is required. Second, because colligations
introduce generalizations, they must apply to events or properties of objects
not yet given: they must provide successful predictions, thereby enlarging the
evidence in favor of the colligation. Third, the best inductions are those
where evidence for various hypotheses originally thought to cover unrelated
kinds of data “jumps together,” providing a consilience of inductions.
Consilience characterizes those theories achieving large measures of
simplicity, generality, unification, and deductive strength. Furthermore, consilience
is a test of the necessary truth of theories, which implies that what many
regard as merely pragmatic virtues of theories like simplicity and unifying
force have an epistemic status. Whewell thus provides a strong argument for
scientific realism. Whewell’s examples of consilient theories are Newton’s
theory of universal gravitation, which covers phenomena as seemingly diverse as
the motions of the heavenly bodies and the motions of the tides, and the
undulatory theory of light, which explains both the polarization of light by
crystals and the colors of fringes. There is evidence that Whewell’s
methodology was employed by Maxwell, who designed the influential Cavendish
Laboratories at Cambridge. Peirce and Mach favored Whewell’s account of method
over Mill’s empiricist theory of induction.
Whitehead, A. N.
18611947, English mathematician, logician, philosopher of science, and
metaphysician. Educated first at the Sherborne School in Dorsetshire and then
at Trinity , Cambridge, Whitehead emerged as a first-class mathematician with a
rich general background. In 1885 he became a fellow of Trinity and remained there in a teaching role until
1910. In the early 1890s Bertrand Russell entered Trinity as a student in mathematics; by the beginning
of the new century Russell had become not only a student and friend but a
colleague of Whitehead’s at Trinity . Each had written a first book on algebra
Whitehead’s A Treatise on Universal Algebra won him election to the Royal
Society in 1903. When they discovered that their projected second books largely
overlapped, they undertook a collaboration on a volume that they estimated
would take about a year to write; in fact, it was a decade later that the three
volumes of their ground-breaking Principia Mathematica appeared, launching
symbolic logic in its modern form. In the second decade of this century
Whitehead and Russell drifted apart; their responses to World War I differed
radically, and their intellectual interests and orientations diverged.
Whitehead’s London period 191024 is often viewed as the second phase of a
three-phase career. His association with the
of London involved him in practical issues affecting the character of
working-class education. For a decade 191424 Whitehead held a professorship at
the Imperial of Science and Technology
and also served as dean of the Faculty of Science in the , chair of the
Academic Council which managed educational affairs in London, and chair of the
council that managed Goldsmith’s . His book The Aims of Education 1928 is a
collection of essays largely growing out of reflections on the experiences of
these years. Intellectually, Whitehead’s interests were moving toward issues in
the philosophy of science. In the years 191922 he published An Enquiry
Concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge, The Concept of Nature, and The
Principle of Relativity the third led to
his later 1931 election as a fellow of the British Academy. In 1924, at the age
of sixty-three, Whitehead made a dramatic move, both geographically and
intellectually, to launch phase three of his career: never having formally
studied philosophy in his life, he agreed to become professor of philosophy at
Harvard , a position he held until retirement in 1937. The accompanying
intellectual shift was a move from philosophy of science to metaphysics. The
earlier investigations had assumed the self-containedness of nature: “nature is
closed to mind.” The philosophy of nature examined nature at the level of
abstraction entailed by this assumption. Whitehead had come to regard
philosophy as “the critic of abstractions,” a notion introduced in Science and
the Modern World 1925. This book traced the intertwined emergence of Newtonian
science and its philosophical presuppositions. It noted that with the
development of the theory of relativity in the twentieth century, scientific
understanding had left behind the Newtonian conceptuality that had generated
the still-dominant philosophical assumptions, and that those philosophical
assumptions considered in themselves had become inadequate to explicate our
full concrete experience. Philosophy as the critic of abstractions must
recognize the limitations of a stance that assumes that nature is closed to
mind, and must push deeper, beyond such an abstraction, to create a scheme of ideas
more in harmony with scientific developments and able to do justice to human
beings as part of nature. Science and the Modern World merely outlines what
such a philosophy might be; in 1929 Whitehead published his magnum opus, titled
Process and Reality. In this volume, subtitled “An Essay in Cosmology,” his
metaphysical understanding is given its final form. It is customary to regard
this book as the central document of what has become known as process
philosophy, though Whitehead himself frequently spoke of his system of ideas as
the philosophy of organism. Process and Reality begins with a sentence that
sheds a great deal of light upon Whitehead’s metaphysical orientation: “These
lectures are based upon a recurrence to that phase of philosophic thought which
began with Descartes and ended with Hume.” Descartes, adapting the classical
notion of substance to his own purposes, begins a “phase of philosophic
thought” by assuming there are two distinct, utterly different kinds of
substance, mind and matter, each requiring nothing but itself in order to
exist. This assumption launches the reign of epistemology within philosophy: if
knowing begins with the experiencing of a mental substance capable of existing
by itself and cut off from everything external to it, then the philosophical
challenge is to try to justify the claim to establish contact with a reality
external to it. The phrase “and ended with Hume” expresses Whitehead’s
conviction that Hume and more elegantly, he notes, Santayana showed that if one
begins with Descartes’s metaphysical assumptions, skepticism is inevitable.
Contemporary philosophers have talked about the end of philosophy. From
Whitehead’s perspective such talk presupposes a far too narrow view of the
nature of philosophy. It is true that a phase of philosophy has ended, a phase
dominated by epistemology. Whitehead’s response is to offer the dictum that all
epistemological difficulties are at bottom only camouflaged metaphysical
difficulties. One must return to that moment of Cartesian beginning and replace
the substance metaphysics with an orientation that avoids the epistemological
trap, meshes harmoniously with the scientific understandings that have
displaced the much simpler physics of Descartes’s day, and is consonant with
the facts of evolution. These are the considerations that generate Whitehead’s
fundamental metaphysical category, the category of an actual occasion. An
actual occasion is not an enduring, substantial entity. Rather, it is a process
of becoming, a process of weaving together the “prehensions” a primitive form
of ‘apprehension’ meant to indicate a “taking account of,” or “feeling,” devoid
of conscious awareness of the actual occasions that are in the immediate past.
Whitehead calls this process of weaving together the inheritances of the past
“concrescence.” An actual entity is its process of concrescence, its process of
growing together into a unified perspective on its immediate past. The seeds of
Whitehead’s epistemological realism are planted in these fundamental first
moves: “The philosophy of organism is the inversion of Kant’s philosophy. . . .
For Kant, the world emerges from the subject; for the philosophy of organism,
the subject emerges from the world.” It is customary to compare an actual
occasion with a Leibnizian monad, with the caveat that whereas a monad is
windowless, an actual occasion is “all window.” It is as though one were to
take Aristotle’s system of categories and ask what would result if the category
of substance were displaced from its position of preeminence by the category of
relation the result would, mutatis
mutandis, be an understanding of being somewhat on the model of a Whiteheadian
actual occasion. In moving from Descartes’s dualism of mental substance and
material substance to his own notion of an actual entity, Whitehead has been
doing philosophy conceived of as the critique of abstractions. He holds that
both mind and matter are abstractions from the concretely real. They are
important abstractions, necessary for everyday thought and, of supreme
importance, absolutely essential in enabling the seventeenth through nineteenth
centuries to accomplish their magnificent advances in scientific thinking.
Indeed, Whitehead, in his philosophy of science phase, by proceeding as though
“nature is closed to mind,” was operating with those selfsame abstractions. He
came to see that while these abstractions were indispensable for certain kinds
of investigations, they were, at the philosophical level, as Hume had
demonstrated, a disaster. In considering mind and matter to be ontological
ultimates, Descartes had committed what Whitehead termed the fallacy of
misplaced concreteness. The category of an actual occasion designates the fully
real, the fully concrete. The challenge for such an orientation, the challenge
that Process and Reality is designed to meet, is so to describe actual
occasions that it is intelligible how collections of actual occasions, termed
“nexus” or societies, emerge, exhibiting the characteristics we find associated
with “minds” and “material structures.” Perhaps most significantly, if this
challenge is met successfully, biology will be placed, in the eyes of
philosophy, on an even footing with physics; metaphysics will do justice both
to human beings and to human beings as a part of nature; and such vexing
contemporary problem areas as animal rights and environmental ethics will
appear in a new light. Whitehead’s last two books, Adventures of Ideas 1933 and
Modes of Thought 1938, are less technical and more lyrical than is Process and
Reality. Adventures of Ideas is clearly the more significant of these two. It
presents a philosophical study of the notion of civilization. It holds that the
social changes in a civilization are driven by two sorts of forces: brute,
senseless agencies of compulsion on the one hand, and formulated aspirations
and articulated beliefs on the other. These two sorts of forces are epitomized
by barbarians and Christianity in the ancient Roman world and by steam and
democracy in the world of the industrial revolution. Whitehead’s focal point in
Adventures of Ideas is aspirations, beliefs, and ideals as instruments of
change. In particular, he is concerned to articulate the ideals and aspirations
appropriate to our own era. The character of such ideals and aspirations at any
moment is limited by the philosophical understandings available at that moment,
because in their struggle for release and efficacy such ideals and aspirations
can appear only in the forms permitted by the available philosophical
discourse. In the final section of Adventures of Ideas Whitehead presents a
statement of ideals and aspirations fit for our era as his own philosophy of
organism allows them to take shape and be articulated. The notions of beauty,
truth, adventure, zest, Eros, and peace are given a content drawn from the
technical understandings elaborated in Process and Reality. But in Adventures
of Ideas a less technical language is used, a language reminiscent of the
poetic imagery found in the style of Plato’s Republic, a language making the
ideas accessible to readers who have not mastered Process and Reality, but at
the same time far richer and more meaningful to those who have. Whitehead notes
in Adventures of Ideas that Plato’s later thought “circles round the
interweaving of seven main notions, namely, The Ideas, The Physical Elements,
The Psyche, The Eros, The Harmony, The Mathematical Relations, The Receptacle.
These notions are as important for us now, as they were then at the dawn of the
modern world, when civilizations of the old type were dying.” Whitehead uses
these notions in quite novel and modern ways; one who is unfamiliar with his
metaphysics can get something of what he means as he speaks of the Eros of the
Universe, but if one is familiar from Process and Reality with the notions of
the Primordial Nature of God and the Consequent Nature of God then one sees
much deeper into the meanings present in Adventures of Ideas. Whitehead was not
religious in any narrow, doctrinal, sectarian sense. He explicitly likened his
stance to that of Aristotle, dispassionately considering the requirements of
his metaphysical system as they refer to the question of the existence and
nature of God. Whitehead’s thoughts on these matters are most fully developed
in Chapter 11 of Science and the Modern World, in the final chapter of Process
and Reality, and in Religion in the Making 1926. These thoughts are expressed
at a high level of generality. Perhaps because of this, a large part of the
interest generated by Whitehead’s thought has been within the community of
theologians. His ideas fairly beg for elaboration and development in the
context of particular modes of religious understanding. It is as though many
modern theologians, recalling the relation between the theology of Aquinas and
the metaphysics of Aristotle, cannot resist the temptation to play Aquinas to
Whitehead’s Aristotle. Process theology, or Neo-Classical Theology as it is
referred to by Hartshorne, one of its leading practitioners, has been the arena
within which a great deal of clarification and development of Whitehead’s ideas
has occurred. Whitehead was a gentle man, soft-spoken, never overbearing or
threatening. He constantly encouraged students to step out on their own, to
develop their creative capacities. His concern not to inhibit students made him
a notoriously easy grader; it was said that an A-minus in one of his courses
was equivalent to failure. Lucien Price’s Dialogues of Alfred North Whitehead
chronicles many evenings of discussion in the Whitehead household. He there
described Whitehead as follows: Whitehead, Alfred North Whitehead, Alfred North
973 973 his face, serene, luminous,
often smiling, the complexion pink and white, the eyes brilliant blue, clear
and candid as a child’s yet with the depth of the sage, often laughing or
twinkling with humour. And there was his figure, slender, frail, and bent with
its lifetime of a scholar’s toil. Always benign, there was not a grain of ill
will anywhere in him; for all his formidable armament, never a wounding
word.
Alnwick -- d. 1333,
English Franciscan theologian. William studied under Duns Scotus at Paris, and
wrote the Reportatio Parisiensia, a central source for Duns Scotus’s teaching.
In his own works, William opposed Scotus on the univocity of being and
haecceitas. Some of his views were attacked by Ockham.
William of Auvergne
c.11901249, French philosopher who was born in Aurillac, taught at Paris, and
became bishop of Paris in 1228. Critical of the new Aristotelianism of his
time, he insisted that the soul is an individual, immortal form of intellectual
activity alone, so that a second form was needed for the body and sensation.
Though he rejected the notion of an agent intellect, he described the soul as a
mirror that reflects both exemplary ideas in God’s mind and sensible singulars.
He conceived being as something common to everything that is, after the manner
of Duns Scotus, but rejected the Avicennan doctrine that God necessarily
produces the universe, arguing that His creative activity is free of all determination.
He is the first example of the complex of ideas we call Augustinianism, which
would pass on through Alexander of Hales to Bonaventure and other Franciscans,
forming a point of departure for the philosophy of Duns Scotus.
William of Auxerre c.11401231,
French theologian and renowned teacher of grammar, arts, and theology at
the of Paris. In 1231 he was appointed
by Pope Gregory IX to a commission charged with editing Aristotle’s writings
for doctrinal purity. The commission never submitted a report, perhaps partly
due to William’s death later that same year. William’s major work, the Summa
aurea 121520, represents one of the earliest systematic attempts to reconcile
the Augustinian and Aristotelian traditions in medieval philosophy. William tempers,
e.g., the Aristotelian concession that human cognition begins with the
reception in the material intellect of a species or sensible representation
from a corporeal thing, with the Augustinian idea that it is not possible to
understand the principles of any discipline without an interior, supernatural
illumination. He also originated the theological distinction between perfect
happiness, which is uncreated and proper to God, and imperfect happiness, which
pertains to human beings. William was also one of the first to express what
became, in later centuries, the important distinction between God’s absolute
and ordained powers, taking, with Gilbert of Poitiers, the view that God could,
absolutely speaking, change the past. The Summa aurea helped shape the thought
of several important philosophers and theologians who were active later in the
century, including Albertus Magnus, Bonaventure, and Aquinas. William remained
an authority in theological discussions throughout the fourteenth and fifteenth
centuries.
William of Moerbeke
c.12151286, French scholar who was the most important thirteenth century
translator from Grecian into Latin of works in philosophy and natural science.
Having joined the Dominicans and spent some time in Grecian-speaking
territories, William served at the papal court and then as Catholic archbishop
of Corinth 1278c.1286. But he worked from the 1260s on as a careful and
literal-minded translator. William was the first to render into Latin white
horse paradox William of Moerbeke 974 974
some of the most important works by Aristotle, including the Politics, Poetics,
and History of Animals. He retranslated or revised earlier translations of
several other Aristotelian works. William also provided the first Latin
versions of commentaries on Aristotle by Alexander of Aphrodisias, Themistius,
Ammonius, John Philoponus, and Simplicius, not to mention his efforts on behalf
of Grecian optics, mathematics, and medicine. When William provided the first
Latin translation of Proclus’s Elements of Theology, Western readers could at
last recognize the Liber de causis as an Arabic compilation from Proclus rather
than as a work by Aristotle.
Williams: B. A. O.
London-born Welsh philosopher who has made major contributions to many fields
but is primarily known as a moral philosopher. His approach to ethics, set out
in Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy 1985, is characterized by a wide-ranging
skepticism, directed mainly at the capacity of academic moral philosophy to
further the aim of reflectively living an ethical life. One line of skeptical
argument attacks the very idea of practical reason. Attributions of practical
reasons to a particular agent must, in Williams’s view, be attributions of
states that can potentially explain the agent’s action. Therefore such reasons
must be either within the agent’s existing set of motivations or within the
revised set of motivations that the agent would acquire upon sound reasoning.
Williams argues from these minimal assumptions that this view of reasons as
internal reasons undermines the idea of reason itself being a source of
authority over practice. Williams’s connected skepticism about the claims of
moral realism is based both on his general stance toward realism and on his
view of the nature of modern societies. In opposition to internal realism,
Williams has consistently argued that reflection on our conception of the world
allows one to develop a conception of the world maximally independent of our
peculiar ways of conceptualizing reality
an absolute conception of the world. Such absoluteness is, he argues, an
inappropriate aspiration for ethical thought. Our ethical thinking is better
viewed as one way of structuring a form of ethical life than as the ethical
truth about how life is best lived. The pervasive reflectiveness and radical
pluralism of modern societies makes them inhospitable contexts for viewing
ethical concepts as making knowledge available to groups of concept users.
Modernity has produced at the level of theory a distortion of our ethical practice,
namely a conception of the morality system. This view is reductionist, is
focused centrally on obligations, and rests on various fictions about
responsibility and blame that Williams challenges in such works as Shame and
Necessity 1993. Much academic moral philosophy, in his view, is shaped by the
covert influence of the morality system, and such distinctively modern outlooks
as Kantianism and utilitarianism monopolize the terms of contemporary debate
with insufficient attention to their origin in a distorted view of the ethical.
Williams’s views are not skeptical through and through; he retains a commitment
to the values of truth, truthfulness in a life, and individualism. His most
recent work, which thematizes the long-implicit influence of Nietzsche on his
ethical philosophy, explicitly offers a vindicatory “genealogical” narrative
for these ideals.
Wilson, J. C. Oxonian
philosopher, like Grice. Cook Wilson studied with T. H. Green before becoming
Wykeham Professor of Logic at Oxford and leading the Oxford reaction against
the then entrenched absolute idealism. More influential as a tutor than as a
writer, his major oeuvre, Statement and Inference, was posthumously
reconstructed from drafts of papers, philosophical correspondence, and an
extensive set of often inconsistent lectures for his logic courses. A staunch
critic of Whitehead’s mathematical logic, Wilson conceived of logic as the
study of thinking, an activity unified by the fact that thinking either is
knowledge or depends on knowledge “What we know we kow”. Wilson claims that
knowledge involves apprehending an object that in most cases is independent of
the act of apprehension and that knowledge is indefinable without circularity,
views he defended by appealing to common usage. Many of Wilson’s ideas are
disseminated by H. W. B. Joseph, especially in his “Logic.” Rejecting “symbolic
logic,” Joseph attempts to reinvigorate traditional logic conceived along
Wilsonian lines. To do so Joseph combined a careful exposition of Aristotle
with insights drawn from idealistic logicians. Besides Joseph, Wilson
decisively influenced a generation of Oxford philosophers including Prichard
and Ross, and Grice who explores the ‘interrogative subordination’ in the
account of ‘if.’ “Who killed Cock Robin”.
Windelband, Wilhelm
18481915, German philosopher and originator of Baden neoKantianism. He studied
under Kuno Fischer 18241907 and Lotze, and was professor at Zürich, Freiburg,
Strasbourg, and Heidelberg. Windelband gave Baden neo-Kantianism its
distinctive mark of Kantian axiology as the core of critical philosophy. He is
widely recognized for innovative work in the history of philosophy, in which
problems rather than individual philosophers are the focus and organizing
principle of exposition. He is also known for his distinction, first drawn in
“Geschichte und Naturwissenschaft” “History and Natural Science,” 1894, between
the nomothetic knowledge that most natural sciences seek the discovery of
general laws in order to master nature and the idiographic knowledge that the
historical sciences pursue description of individual and unique aspects of
reality with the aim of self-affirmation. His most important student, and
successor at Heidelberg, was Heinrich Rickert 1863 1936, who made lasting
contributions to the methodology of the historical sciences. NEO-KANTIANISM. H.v.d.L. wisdom, an
understanding of the highest principles of things that functions as a guide for
living a truly exemplary human life. From the preSocratics through Plato this
was a unified notion. But Aristotle introduced a distinction between
theoretical wisdom sophia and practical wisdom phronesis, the former being the
intellectual virtue that disposed one to grasp the nature of reality in terms
of its ultimate causes metaphysics, the latter being the ultimate practical
virtue that disposed one to make sound judgments bearing on the conduct of
life. The former invoked a contrast between deep understanding versus wide
information, whereas the latter invoked a contrast between sound judgment and mere
technical facility. This distinction between theoretical and practical wisdom
persisted through the Middle Ages and continues to our own day, as is evident
in our use of the term ‘wisdom’ to designate both knowledge of the highest kind
and the capacity for sound judgment in matters of conduct.
Vitters, Ludwig 18891951,
Vienna-born philosopher trained as an enginner at Manchester, one of the most
original and challenging philosophical writers of the twentieth century. Born
in Vienna into an assimilated family of Jewish extraction, he went to England
as a student and eventually became a protégé of Russell’s at Cambridge. He
returned to Austria at the beginning of The Great War I, but went back to
Cambridge in 1928 and taught there as a fellow and professor. Despite spending
much of his professional life in England, Wittgenstein never lost contact with
his Austrian background, and his writings combine in a unique way ideas derived
from both the insular and the continental European tradition. His thought is strongly
marked by a deep skepticism about philosophy, but he retained the conviction
that there was something important to be rescued from the traditional
enterprise. In his Blue Book 1958 he referred to his own work as “one of the
heirs of the subject that used to be called philosophy.” What strikes readers
first when they look at Wittgenstein’s writings is the peculiar form of their
composition. They are generally made up of short individual notes that are most
often numbered in sequence and, in the more finished writings, evidently
selected and arranged with the greatest care. Those notes range from fairly
technical discussions on matters of logic, the mind, meaning, understanding,
acting, seeing, mathematics, and knowledge, to aphoristic observations about
ethics, culture, art, and the meaning of life. Because of their wide-ranging
character, their unusual perspective on things, and their often intriguing
style, Wittgenstein’s writings have proved to appeal to both professional
philosophers and those interested in philosophy in a more general way. The
writings as well as his unusual life and personality have already produced a
large body of interpretive literature. But given his uncompromising stand, it
is questionable whether his thought will ever be fully integrated into academic
philosophy. It is more likely that, like Pascal and Nietzsche, he will remain
an uneasy presence in philosophy. From an early date onward Wittgenstein was
greatly influenced by the idea that philosophical problems can be resolved by
paying attention to the working of language
a thought he may have gained from Fritz Mauthner’s Beiträge zu einer
Kritik der Sprache 190102. Wittgenstein’s affinity to Mauthner is, indeed,
evident in all phases of his philosophical development, though it is
particularly noticeable in his later thinking.Until recently it has been common
to divide Wittgenstein’s work into two sharply distinct phases, separated by a
prolonged period of dormancy. According to this schema the early “Tractarian”
period is that of the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus 1921, which Wittgenstein
wrote in the trenches of World War I, and the later period that of the
Philosophical Investigations 1953, which he composed between 1936 and 1948. But
the division of his work into these two periods has proved misleading. First,
in spite of obvious changes in his thinking, Wittgenstein remained throughout
skeptical toward traditional philosophy and persisted in channeling
philosophical questioning in a new direction. Second, the common view fails to
account for the fact that even between 1920 and 1928, when Wittgenstein
abstained from actual work in philosophy, he read widely in philosophical and
semiphilosophical authors, and between 1928 and 1936 he renewed his interest in
philosophical work and wrote copiously on philosophical matters. The posthumous
publication of texts such as The Blue and Brown Books, Philosophical Grammar,
Philosophical Remarks, and Conversations with the Vienna Circle has led to
acknowledgment of a middle period in Wittgenstein’s development, in which he
explored a large number of philosophical issues and viewpoints a period that served as a transition between
the early and the late work. Early period. As the son of a greatly successful
industrialist and engineer, Wittgenstein first studied engineering in Berlin
and Manchester, and traces of that early training are evident throughout his
writing. But his interest shifted soon to pure mathematics and the foundations
of mathematics, and in pursuing questions about them he became acquainted with
Russell and Frege and their work. The two men had a profound and lasting effect
on Wittgenstein even when he later came to criticize and reject their ideas.
That influence is particularly noticeable in the Tractatus, which can be read
as an attempt to reconcile Russell’s atomism with Frege’s apriorism. But the
book is at the same time moved by quite different and non-technical concerns.
For even before turning to systematic philosophy Wittgenstein had been
profoundly moved by Schopenhauer’s thought as it is spelled out in The World as
Will and Representation, and while he was serving as a soldier in World War I,
he renewed his interest in Schopenhauer’s metaphysical, ethical, aesthetic, and
mystical outlook. The resulting confluence of ideas is evident in the Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus and gives the book its peculiar character. Composed in a
dauntingly severe and compressed style, the book attempts to show that
traditional philosophy rests entirely on a misunderstanding of “the logic of
our language.” Following in Frege’s and Russell’s footsteps, Wittgenstein
argued that every meaningful sentence must have a precise logical structure.
That structure may, however, be hidden beneath the clothing of the grammatical
appearance of the sentence and may therefore require the most detailed analysis
in order to be made evident. Such analysis, Wittgenstein was convinced, would
establish that every meaningful sentence is either a truth-functional composite
of another simpler sentence or an atomic sentence consisting of a concatenation
of simple names. He argued further that every atomic sentence is a logical
picture of a possible state of affairs, which must, as a result, have exactly
the same formal structure as the atomic sentence that depicts it. He employed
this “picture theory of meaning” as it
is usually called to derive conclusions
about the nature of the world from his observations about the structure of the
atomic sentences. He postulated, in particular, that the world must itself have
a precise logical structure, even though we may not be able to determine it
completely. He also held that the world consists primarily of facts,
corresponding to the true atomic sentences, rather than of things, and that
those facts, in turn, are concatenations of simple objects, corresponding to
the simple names of which the atomic sentences are composed. Because he derived
these metaphysical conclusions from his view of the nature of language,
Wittgenstein did not consider it essential to describe what those simple
objects, their concatenations, and the facts consisting of them are actually
like. As a result, there has been a great deal of uncertainty and disagreement
among interpreters about their character. The propositions of the Tractatus are
for the most part concerned with spelling out Wittgenstein’s account of the
logical structure of language and the world and these parts of the book have
understandably been of most interest to philosophers who are primarily
concerned with questions of symbolic logic and its applications. But for
Wittgenstein himself the most important part of the book consisted of the
negative conclusions about philosophy that he reaches at the end of his text:
in particular, that all sentences that are not atomic pictures of concatenations
of objects or truth-functional composites of such are strictly speaking
meaningless. Among these he included all the propositions of ethics and
aesthetics, all propositions dealing with the meaning of life, all propositions
of logic, indeed all philosophical propositions, and finally all the
propositions of the Tractatus itself. These are all strictly meaningless; they
aim at saying something important, but what they try to express in words can
only show itself. As a result Wittgenstein concluded that anyone who understood
what the Tractatus was saying would finally discard its propositions as
senseless, that she would throw away the ladder after climbing up on it.
Someone who reached such a state would have no more temptation to pronounce
philosophical propositions. She would see the world rightly and would then also
recognize that the only strictly meaningful propositions are those of natural
science; but those could never touch what was really important in human life,
the mystical. That would have to be contemplated in silence. For “whereof one
cannot speak, thereof one must be silent,” as the last proposition of the
Tractatus declared. Middle period. It was only natural that Wittgenstein should
not embark on an academic career after he had completed that work. Instead he
trained to be a school teacher and taught primary school for a number of years
in the mountains of lower Austria. In the mid-1920s he also built a house for
his sister; this can be seen as an attempt to give visual expression to the
logical, aesthetic, and ethical ideas of the Tractatus. In those years he
developed a number of interests seminal for his later development. His school
experience drew his attention to the way in which children learn language and
to the whole process of enculturation. He also developed an interest in
psychology and read Freud and others. Though he remained hostile to Freud’s
theoretical explanations of his psychoanalytic work, he was fascinated with the
analytic practice itself and later came to speak of his own work as therapeutic
in character. In this period of dormancy Wittgenstein also became acquainted
with the members of the Vienna Circle, who had adopted his Tractatus as one of
their key texts. For a while he even accepted the positivist principle of
meaning advocated by the members of that Circle, according to which the meaning
of a sentence is the method of its verification. This he would later modify
into the more generous claim that the meaning of a sentence is its use.
Wittgenstein’s most decisive step in his middle period was to abandon the
belief of the Tractatus that meaningful sentences must have a precise hidden
logical structure and the accompanying belief that this structure corresponds
to the logical structure of the facts depicted by those sentences. The
Tractatus had, indeed, proceeded on the assumption that all the different
symbolic devices that can describe the world must be constructed according to
the same underlying logic. In a sense, there was then only one meaningful
language in the Tractatus, and from it one was supposed to be able to read off
the logical structure of the world. In the middle period Wittgenstein concluded
that this doctrine constituted a piece of unwarranted metaphysics and that the
Tractatus was itself flawed by what it had tried to combat, i.e., the
misunderstanding of the logic of language. Where he had previously held it
possible to ground metaphysics on logic, he now argued that metaphysics leads
the philosopher into complete darkness. Turning his attention back to language
he concluded that almost everything he had said about it in the Tractatus had
been in error. There were, in fact, many different languages with many
different structures that could meet quite different specific needs. Language
was not strictly held together by logical structure, but consisted, in fact, of
a multiplicity of simpler substructures or language games. Sentences could not
be taken to be logical pictures of facts and the simple components of sentences
did not all function as names of simple objects. These new reflections on
language served Wittgenstein, in the first place, as an aid to thinking about
the nature of the human mind, and specifically about the relation between
private experience and the physical world. Against the existence of a Cartesian
mental substance, he argued that the word ‘I’ did not serve as a name of
anything, but occurred in expressions meant to draw attention to a particular
body. For a while, at least, he also thought he could explain the difference
between private experience and the physical world in terms of the existence of
two languages, a primary language of experience and a secondary language of
physics. This duallanguage view, which is evident in both the Philosophical
Remarks and The Blue Book, Wittgenstein was to give up later in favor of the
assumption that our grasp of inner phenomena is dependent on the existence of
outer criteria. From the mid-1930s onward he also renewed his interest in the
philosophy of mathematics. In contrast to Frege and Russell, he argued
strenuously that no part of mathematics is reducible purely to logic. Instead
he set out to describe mathematics as part of our natural history and as
consisting of a number of diverse language games. He also insisted that the
meaning of those games depended on the uses to which the mathematical formulas
were put. Applying the principle of verification to mathematics, he held that
the meaning of a mathematical formula lies in its proof. These remarks on the
philosophy of mathematics have remained among Wittgenstein’s most controversial
and least explored writings. Later period. Wittgenstein’s middle period was
characterized by intensive philosophical work on a broad but quickly changing
front. By 1936, however, his thinking was finally ready to settle down once
again into a steadier pattern, and he now began to elaborate the views for
which he became most famous. Where he had constructed his earlier work around
the logic devised by Frege and Russell, he now concerned himself mainly with
the actual working of ordinary language. This brought him close to the
tradition of British common sense philosophy that Moore had revived and made
him one of the godfathers of the ordinary language philosophy that was to
flourish in Oxford in the 1950s. In the Philosophical Investigations
Wittgenstein emphasized that there are countless different uses of what we call
“symbols,” “words,” and “sentences.” The task of philosophy is to gain a
perspicuous view of those multiple uses and thereby to dissolve philosophical
and metaphysical puzzles. These puzzles were the result of insufficient
attention to the working of language and could be resolved only by carefully
retracing the linguistic steps by which they had been reached. Wittgenstein
thus came to think of philosophy as a descriptive, analytic, and ultimately
therapeutic practice. In the Investigations he set out to show how common
philosophical views about meaning including the logical atomism of the
Tractatus, about the nature of concepts, about logical necessity, about
rule-following, and about the mindbody problem were all the product of an
insufficient grasp of how language works. In one of the most influential
passages of the book he argued that concept words do not denote sharply
circumscribed concepts, but are meant to mark family resemblances between the
things labeled with the concept. He also held that logical necessity results
from linguistic convention and that rules cannot determine their own
applications, that rule-following presupposes the existence of regular
practices. Furthermore, the words of our language have meaning only insofar as
there exist public criteria for their correct application. As a consequence, he
argued, there cannot be a completely private language, i.e., a language that in
principle can be used only to speak about one’s own inner experience. This
private language argument has caused much discussion. Interpreters have
disagreed not only over the structure of the argument and where it occurs in
Wittgenstein’s text, but also over the question whether he meant to say that
language is necessarily social. Because he said that to speak of inner
experiences there must be external and publicly available criteria, he has
often been taken to be advocating a logical behaviorism, but nowhere does he,
in fact, deny the existence of inner states. What he says is merely that our
understanding of someone’s pain is connected to the existence of natural and
linguistic expressions of pain. In the Philosophical Investigations
Wittgenstein repeatedly draws attention to the fact that language must be
learned. This learning, he says, is fundamentally a process of inculcation and
drill. In learning a language the child is initiated in a form of life. In
Wittgenstein’s later work the notion of form of life serves to identify the
whole complex of natural and cultural circumstances presupposed by our language
and by a particular understanding of the world. He elaborated those ideas in
notes on which he worked between 1948 and his death in 1951 and which are now published
under the title On Certainty. He insisted in them that every belief is always
part of a system of beliefs that together constitute a worldview. All
confirmation and disconfirmation of a belief presuppose such a system and are
internal to the system. For all this he was not advocating a relativism, but a
naturalism that assumes that the world ultimately determines which language
games can be played. Wittgenstein’s final notes vividly illustrate the
continuity of his basic concerns throughout all the changes his thinking went
through. For they reveal once more how he remained skeptical about all
philosophical theories and how he understood his own undertaking as the attempt
to undermine the need for any such theorizing. The considerations of On Certainty
are evidently directed against both philosophical skeptics and those
philosophers who want to refute skepticism. Against the philosophical skeptics
Wittgenstein insisted that there is real knowledge, but this knowledge is
always dispersed and not necessarily reliable; it consists of things we have
heard and read, of what has been drilled into us, and of our modifications of
this inheritance. We have no general reason to doubt this inherited
Wittgenstein, Ludwig Wittgenstein, Ludwig 979
979 body of knowledge, we do not generally doubt it, and we are, in
fact, not in a position to do so. But On Certainty also argues that it is
impossible to refute skepticism by pointing to propositions that are absolutely
certain, as Descartes did when he declared ‘I think, therefore I am’
indubitable, or as Moore did when he said, “I know for certain that this is a
hand here.” The fact that such propositions are considered certain,
Wittgenstein argued, indicates only that they play an indispensable, normative
role in our language game; they are the riverbed through which the thought of
our language game flows. Such propositions cannot be taken to express
metaphysical truths. Here, too, the conclusion is that all philosophical
argumentation must come to an end, but that the end of such argumentation is
not an absolute, self-evident truth, but a certain kind of natural human
practice.
wodeham: Oxonian
philosopher, like Grice. Adam de c. 12951358, English Franciscan
philosopher-theologian who lectured on Peter Lombard’s Sentences at London,
Norwich, and Oxford. His published works include the Tractatus de
indivisibilibus; his Lectura secunda Norwich lectures; and an abbreviation of
his Oxford lectures by Henry Totting of Oyta, published by John Major in 1512.
Wodeham’s main work, the Oxford lectures, themselves remain unpublished. A
brilliant interpreter of Duns Scotus, whose original manuscripts he consulted,
Wodeham deemed Duns Scotus the greatest Franciscan doctor. William Ockham,
Wodeham’s teacher, was the other great influence on Wodeham’s philosophical
theology. Wodeham defended Ockham’s views against attacks mounted by Walter
Chatton; he also wrote the prologue to Ockham’s Summa logicae. Wodeham’s own
influence rivaled that of Ockham. Among the authors he strongly influenced are
Gregory of Rimini, John of Mirecourt, Nicholas of Autrecourt, Pierre d’Ailly,
Peter Ceffons, Alfonso Vargas, Peter of Candia Alexander V, Henry Totting of
Oyta, and John Major. Wodeham’s theological works were written for an audience
with a very sophisticated understanding of current issues in semantics, logic,
and medieval mathematical physics. Contrary to Duns Scotus and Ockham, Wodeham
argued that the sensitive and intellective souls were not distinct. He further
develops the theory of intuitive cognition, distinguishing intellectual
intuition of our own acts of intellect, will, and memory from sensory intuition
of external objects. Scientific knowledge based on experience can be based on
intuition, according to Wodeham. He distinguishes different grades of evidence,
and allows that sensory perceptions may be mistaken. Nonetheless, they can form
the basis for scientific knowledge, since they are reliable; mistakes can be
corrected by reason and experience. In semantic theory, Wodeham defends the view
that the immediate object of scientific knowledge is the complexe
significabile, that which the conclusion is designed to signify.
wolff, Christian
16791754, German philosopher and the most powerful advocate for secular
rationalism in early eighteenth-century Germany. Although he was a Lutheran,
his early education in Catholic Breslau made him familiar with both the
Scholasticism of Aquinas and Suárez and more modern sources. His later studies
at Leipzig were completed with a dissertation on the application of
mathematical methods to ethics 1703, which brought him to the attention of
Leibniz. He remained in correspondence with Leibniz until the latter’s death
1716, and became known as the popularizer of Leibniz’s philosophy, although his
views did not derive from that source alone. Appointed to teach mathematics in
Halle in 1706 he published mathematical textbooks and compendia that dominated
German universities for decades, Wolff began lecturing on philosophy as well by
1709. His rectoral address On the Practical Philosophy of the Chinese 1721
argued that revelation and even belief in God were unnecessary for arriving at
sound principles of moral and political reasoning; this brought his uneasy
relations with the Halle Pietists to a head, and in 1723 they secured his
dismissal and indeed banishment. Wolff was immediately welcomed in Marburg,
where he became a hero for freedom of thought, and did not return to Prussia
until the ascension of Frederick the Great in 1740, when he resumed his post at
Halle. Wolff published an immense series of texts on logic, metaphysics,
ethics, politics, natural theology, and teleology 171324, in which he created
the philosophical terminology of modern German; he then published an even more
extensive series of works in Latin for the rest of his life, expanding and
modifying his German works but also adding works on natural and positive law
and economics 172355. He accepted the traWodeham, Adam de Wolff, Christian
980 980 ditional division of logic into
the doctrines of concepts, judgment, and inference, which influenced the
organization of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason 178187 and even Hegel’s Science
of Logic1816. In metaphysics, he included general ontology and then the special
disciplines of rational cosmology, rational psychology, and rational theology
Kant replaced Wolff’s general ontology with his transcendental aesthetic and
analytic, and then demolished Wolff’s special metaphysics in his transcendental
dialectic. Wolff’s metaphysics drew heavily on Leibniz, but also on Descartes
and even empiricists like Locke. Methodologically, he attempted to derive the
principle of sufficient reason from the logical law of identity like the
unpublished Leibniz of the 1680s rather than the published Leibniz of the
1700s; substantively, he began his German metaphysics with a reconstruction of
Descartes’s cogito argument, then argued for a simple, immaterial soul, all of
its faculties reducible to forms of representation and related to body by
preestablished harmony. Although rejected by Crusius and then Kant, Wolff’s
attempt to found philosophy on a single principle continued to influence German
idealism as late as Reinhold, Fichte, and Hegel, and his example of beginning
metaphysics from the unique representative power of the soul continued to
influence not only later writers such as Reinhold and Fichte but also Kant’s
own conception of the transcendental unity of apperception. In spite of the
academic influence of his metaphysics, Wolff’s importance for German culture
lay in his rationalist rather than theological ethics. He argued that moral
worth lies in the perfection of the objective essence of mankind; as the
essence of a human is to be an intellect and a will with the latter dependent
on the former, which are physically embodied and dependent for their well-being
on the well-being of their physical body, morality requires perfection of the
intellect and will, physical body, and external conditions for the well-being
of that combination. Each person is obliged to perfect all instantiations of
this essence, but in practice does so most effectively in his own case; duties
to oneself therefore precede duties to others and to God. Because pleasure is
the sensible sign of perfection, Wolff’s perfectionism resembles contemporary
utilitarianism. Since he held that human perfection can be understood by human
reason independently of any revelation, Wolff joined contemporary British
enlighteners such as Shaftesbury and Hutcheson in arguing that morality does
not depend on divine commands, indeed the recognition of divine commands
depends on an antecedent comprehension of morality although morality does
require respect for God, and thus the atheistic morality of the Chinese, even
though sound as far as it went, was not complete. This was the doctrine that
put Wolff’s life in danger, but it had tremendous repercussions for the
remainder of his century, and certainly in Kant.
wollaston, William
16591724, English moralist notorious for arguing that the immorality of actions
lies in their implying false propositions. An assistant headmaster who later
took priestly orders, Wollaston maintains in his one published work, The
Religion of Nature Delineated 1722, that the foundations of religion and
morality are mutually dependent. God has preestablished a harmony between
reason or truth and happiness, so that actions that contradict truth through
misrepresentation thereby frustrate human happiness and are thus evil. For
instance, if a person steals another’s watch, her falsely representing the
watch as her own makes the act wrong. Wollaston’s views, particularly his
taking morality to consist in universal and necessary truths, were influenced
by the rationalists Ralph Cudworth and Clarke. Among his many critics the most
famous was Hume, who contends that Wollaston’s theory implies an absurdity: any
action concealed from public view e.g., adultery conveys no false proposition
and therefore is not immoral.
Wollstonecraft, Mary
175997, English author and feminist whose A Vindication of the Rights of Women
1792 is a central text of feminist philosophy. Her chief target is Rousseau:
her goal is to argue against the separate and different education Rousseau
provided for girls and to extend his recommendations to girls as well as boys.
Wollstonecraft saw such an improved education for women as necessary to their
asserting their right as “human creatures” to develop their faculties in a way
conducive to human virtue. She also wrote A Vindication of the Rights of Men
1790, an attack on Edmund Burke’s pamphlet on the French Revolution, as well as
novels, essays, an account of her travels, and books for children.
wright, C: philosopher. His
philosophical discussions are stimulating and attracted many, including Peirce,
James, and Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., who thinks of him as their “intellectual
boxing master.” Wright eventually accepted empiricism, especially that of J. S.
Mill, though under Darwinian influence he modified Mill’s view considerably by
rejecting the empiricist claim that general propositions merely summarize
particulars. Wright claims instead that scientific theories are hypotheses to
be further developed, and insisted that a moral rule is irreducible and needs
no utilitarian “proof.” Though he denied the “summary” view of universals, he
is not strictly a pragmatist, since for him a low-level empirical proposition
like Peirce’s ‘this diamond is hard’ is not a hypothesis but a self-contained
irreducible statement.
wu.YU, WU. wu-hsing,
Chinese term meaning ‘five phases, processes, or elements’. The five
phases earth, wood, metal, fire, and
water along with yin and yang, were the
basis of Chinese correlative cosmologies developed in the Warring States period
403221 B.C. and early Han dynasty 206 B.C. A.D. 220. These cosmologies posited
a relation between the human world and the natural order. Thus the five phases
were correlated to patterns in human history such as the cyclical rise and fall
of dynasties, to sociopolitical order and the monthly rituals of rulers, to
musical notes and tastes, even to organs of the body. Whereas the goal of early
cosmologists such as Tsou Yen was to bring the human order into harmony with
the natural order via the five phases, Han dynasty cosmologists and immortality
seekers sought to control nature and prolong life by manipulating the five
phases, particularly within the body.
Wundt: Wilhelm Maximilien
18321920, German philosopher and psychologist, a founder of scientific
psychology. Although trained as a physician, he turned to philosophy and in
1879, at the of Leipzig, established the
first recognized psychology laboratory. For Wundt, psychology was the science
of conscious experience, a definition soon overtaken by behaviorism. Wundt’s
psychology had two departments: the so-called physiological psychology
Grundzuge der physiologischen Psychologie, 3 vols., 1873 74; only vol. 1 of the
fifth edition, 1910, was translated into English, primarily the experimental
study of immediate experience broadly modeled on Fechner’s psychophysics; and
the Volkerpsychologie Volkerpsychologie, 10 vols., 190020; fragment translated
as The Language of Gestures, 1973, the non-experimental study of the higher
mental processes via their products, language, myth, and custom. Although Wundt
was a prodigious investigator and author, and was revered as psychology’s
founder, his theories, unlike his methods, exerted little influence. A typical
German scholar of his time, he also wrote across the whole of philosophy, including
logic and ethics. .
wu wei, Chinese
philosophical term often translated as ‘non-action’ and associated with Taoism.
It is actually used in both Taoist and non-Taoist texts to describe an ideal
state of existence or ideal form of government, interpreted differently in
different texts. In the Chuang Tzu, it describes a state of existence in which
one is not guided by preconceived goals or projects, including moral ideals; in
the Lao Tzu, it refers to the absence of striving toward worldly goals, and
also describes the ideal form of government, which does not teach or impose on
the people standards of behavior, including those of conventional morality. In
other texts, it is sometimes used to describe the effortlessness of moral
action, and sometimes used to refer to the absence of any need for active
participation in government by the ruler, resulting either from the appointment
of worthy and able officials inspired by the moral example of the ruler, or
from the establishment of an effective machinery of government presided over by
a ruler with prestige.
Wyclif, John c.133084,
English theologian and religious reformer. He worked for most of his life in
Oxford as a secular clerk, teaching philosophy and later theology and writing
extensively in both fields. The mode of thought expressed in his surviving
works is one of extreme realism, and in this his thought fostered the split of
Bohemian, later Hussite, philosophy from that of the German masters teaching in
Prague. His worldline Wyclif, John 982
982 philosophical summa was most influential for his teaching on universals,
but also dealt extensively with the question of determinism; these issues
underlay his later handling of the questions of the Eucharist and of the
identity of the church respectively. His influence on English philosophy was
severely curtailed by the growing hostility of the church to his ideas, the
condemnation of many of his tenets, the persecution of his followers, and the
destruction of his writings.
Xenophanes c.570c.475
B.C., Grecian philosopher, a proponent of an idealized conception of the
divine, and the first of the pre-Socratics to propound epistemological views.
Born in Colophon, an Ionian Grecian city on the coast of Asia Minor, he
emigrated as a young man to the Grecian West Sicily and southern Italy. The
formative influence of the Milesians is evident in his rationalism. He is the
first of the pre-Socratics for whom we have not only ancient reports but also
quite a few verbatim quotations fragments
from his “Lampoons” Silloi and from other didactic poetry. Xenophanes attacks
the worldview of Homer, Hesiod, and traditional Grecian piety: it is an outrage
that the poets attribute moral failings to the gods. Traditional religion
reflects regional biases blond gods for the Northerners; black gods for the
Africans. Indeed, anthropomorphic gods reflect the ultimate bias, that of the
human viewpoint “If cattle, or horses, or lions . . . could draw pictures of
the gods . . . ,” frg. 15. There is a single “greatest” god, who is not at all
like a human being, either in body or in mind; he perceives without the aid of
organs, he effects changes without “moving,” through the sheer power of his
thought. The rainbow is no sign from Zeus; it is simply a special cloud
formation. Nor are the sun or the moon gods. All phenomena in the skies, from
the elusive “Twin Sons of Zeus” St. Elmo’s fire to sun, moon, and stars, are
varieties of cloud formation. There are no mysterious infernal regions; the
familiar strata of earth stretch down ad infinitum. The only cosmic limit is
the one visible at our feet: the horizontal border between earth and air.
Remarkably, Xenophanes tempers his theological and cosmological pronouncements
with an epistemological caveat: what he offers is only a “conjecture.” In later
antiquity Xenophanes came to be regarded as the founder of the Eleatic School,
and his teachings were assimilated to those of Parmenides and Melissus. This
appears to be based on nothing more than Xenophanes’ emphasis on the oneness
and utter immobility of God.
Xenophon c.430c.350 B.C.,
Grecian soldier and historian, author of several Socratic dialogues, along with
important works on history, education, political theory, and other topics. He
was interested in philosophy, and he was a penetrating and intelligent “social
thinker” whose views on morality and society have been influential over many
centuries. His perspective on Socrates’ character and moral significance
provides a valuable supplement and corrective to the better-known views of
Plato. Xenophon’s Socratic dialogues, the only ones besides Plato’s to survive
intact, help us obtain a broader picture of the Socratic dialogue as a literary
genre. They also provide precious evidence concerning the thoughts and
personalities of other followers of Socrates, such as Antisthenes and
Alcibiades. Xenophon’s longest and richest Socratic work is the Memorabilia, or
“Memoirs of Socrates,” which stresses Socrates’ self-sufficiency and his
beneficial effect on his companions. Xenophon’s Apology of Socrates and his
Symposium were probably intended as responses to Plato’s Apology and Symposium.
Xenophon’s Socratic dialogue on estate management, the Oeconomicus, is valuable
for its underlying social theory and its evidence concerning the role and
status of women in classical Athens.
Yang Chu, also called
Yang Tzu c.370319 B.C., Chinese philosopher most famous for the assertion,
attributed to him by Mencius, that one ought not sacrifice even a single hair
to save the whole world. Widely criticized as a selfish egotist and hedonist,
Yang Chu was a private person who valued bodily integrity, health, and
longevity over fame, fortune, and power. He believed that because one’s body
and lifespan were bestowed by Heaven t’ien, one has a duty and natural
inclination to maintain bodily health and live out one’s years. Far from
sanctioning hedonistic indulgence, this Heavenimposed duty requires discipline.
Yang Hsiung 53 B.C.A.D.
18, Chinese philosopher who wrote two books: Tai-hsüan ching “Classic of the
Supremely Profound Principle”, an imitation of the I-Ching, and Fa-yen “Model
Sayings”, an imitation of the Analects. The former was ignored by his
contemporaries, but the latter was quite popular in his time. His thoughts were
eclectic. He was the first in the history of Chinese thought to advance the
doctrine of human nature as a mixture of good and evil in order to avoid the
extremes of Mencius and Hsün Tzu.
Yen Yuan 16351704,
Chinese traditionalist and social critic. Like Wang Fu-chih, he attacked
Neo-Confucian metaphysical dualism, regarding the Neo-Confucians’ views as wild
speculations obscuring the true nature of Confucianism. Chu Hsi interpreted ko
wu investigating things as discovering some transcendent “thing” called li
pattern, and Wang Yang-ming understood ko wu as rectifying one’s thoughts, but
Yen argued it meant a kind of knowledge by acquaintance: the “hands-on”
practice of traditional rituals and disciplines. As “proof” that SungMing
Confucians were wrong, Yen pointed to their social and political failures. Like
many, he believed Confucianism was not only true but efficacious as well;
failure to reform the world could be understood only as a personal failure to grasp
and implement the Way. .
yi, Chinese term probably
with an earlier meaning of ‘sense of honor’, subsequently used to refer to the
fitting or right way of conducting oneself when so used, it is often translated
as ‘rightness’ or ‘duty’, as well as to a commitment to doing what is fitting
or right when so used, it is often translated as ‘righteousness’ or
‘dutifulness’. For Mohists, yi is determined by what benefits li the public,
where benefit is understood in terms of such things as order and increased
resources in society. For Confucians, while yi behavior is often behavior in
accordance with traditional norms, it may also call for departure from such
norms. Yi is determined not by specific rules of conduct, but by the proper
weighing chüan of relevant considerations in a given context of action. Yi in
the sense of a firm commitment to doing what is fitting or right, even in
adverse circumstances, is an important component of the Confucian ethical
ideal.
yin, yang, metaphors used
in the classical tradition of Chinese philosophy to express contrast and
difference. Originally they designated the shady side and the sunny side of a
hill, and gradually came to suggest the way in which one thing “overshadows”
another in some particular aspect of their relationship. Yin and yang are not
“principles” or “essences” that help classify things; rather, they are ad hoc
explanatory categories that report on relationships and interactions among
immediate concrete things of the world. Yin and yang always describe the
relationships that are constitutive of unique particulars, and provide a
vocabulary for “reading” the distinctions that obtain among them. The
complementary nature of the opposition captured in this pairing expresses the
mutuality, interdependence, diversity, and creative efficacy of the dynamic
relationships that are deemed immanent in and valorize the world. The full
range of difference in the world is deemed explicable 985 Y 985 through this pairing.
yü, Chinese term meaning
‘desire’. One can feel yü toward sex objects or food, but one can also yü to be
a more virtuous person. Yü is paired contrastively with wu aversion, which has
a similarly broad range of objects. After the introduction of Buddhism into
China, some thinkers contended that the absence of yü and wu was the goal of
self-cultivation. Generally, however, the presence of at least some yü and wu
has been thought to be essential to moral perfection.
yu, wu, Chinese terms
literally meaning ‘having’ and ‘nothing’, respectively; they are often rendered
into English as ‘being’ and ‘non-being’. But the Chinese never developed the
mutually contradictory concepts of Being and Non-Being in Parmenides’ sense. In
chapter 2 of Tao Te Ching, Lao Tzu says that “being yu and non-being wu produce
each other.” They appear to be a pair of interdependent concepts. But in
chapter 40 Lao Tzu also says that “being comes from non-being.” It seems that
for Taoism non-being is more fundamental than being, while for Confucianism the
opposite is true. The two traditions were seen to be complementary by later
scholars.
yung, Chinese term usually translated as
‘courage’ or ‘bravery’. Different forms of yung are described in Chinese
philosophical texts, such as a readiness to avenge an insult or to compete with
others, or an absence of fear. Confucians advocate an ideal form of yung guided
by rightness yi. A person with yung of the ideal kind is fully committed to
rightness, and will abide by rightness even at the risk of death. Also,
realizing upon self-examination that there is no fault in oneself, the person
will be without fear or uncertainty.
zabarella:
a proto-Griceain H. P. Grice. Jacopo
153289, Italian Aristotelian philosopher who taught at the of Padua. He wrote extensive commentaries on
Aristotle’s Physics and On the Soul and also discussed other interpreters such
as Averroes. However, his most original contribution was his work in logic,
Opera logica 1578. Zabarella regards logic as a preliminary study that provides
the tools necessary for philosophical analysis. Two such tools are order and
method: order teaches us how to organize the content of a discipline to
apprehend it more easily; method teaches us how to draw syllogistic inferences.
Zabarella reduces the varieties of orders and methods classified by other
interpreters to compositive and resolutive orders and methods. The compositive order
from first principles to their consequences applies to theoretical disciplines.
The resolutive order from a desired end to means appropriate to its achievement
applies to practical disciplines. This much was already in Aristotle. Zabarella
offers an original analysis of method. The compositive method infers particular
consequences from general principles. The resolutive method infers originating
principles from particular consequences, as in inductive reasoning or in
reasoning from effect to cause. It has been suggested that Zabarella’s
terminology might have influenced Galileo’s mechanics.
Zeigarnik effect:
‘Conversation as a compete task and the Zeigmaik effect’ H. P. Grice. the selective recall of
uncompleted tasks in comparison to completed tasks. The effect was named for
Bluma Zeigarnik, a student of K. Lewin, who discovered it and described it in a
paper published in the Psychologische Forschung in 1927. Subjects received an
array of short tasks, such as counting backward and stringing beads, for rapid
completion. Performance on half of these was interrupted. Subsequent recall for
the tasks favored the interrupted tasks. Zeigarnik concluded that recall is
influenced by motivation and not merely associational strength. The effect was
thought relevant to Freud’s claim that unfulfilled wishes are persistent. Lewin
attempted to derive the effect from field theory, suggesting that an attempt to
reach a goal creates a tension released only when that goal is reached;
interruption of the attempt produces a tension favoring recall. Conditions
affecting the Zeigarnik effect are incompletely understood, as is its
significance.
Zeno’s
paradoxes: “Linguistic puzzles, in nature.” H. P. Grice. four paradoxes relating to space
and motion attributed to Zeno of Elea fifth century B.C.: the racetrack,
Achilles and the tortoise, the stadium, and the arrow. Zeno’s work is known to
us through secondary sources, in particular Aristotle. The racetrack paradox.
If a runner is to reach the end of the track, he must first complete an
infinite number of different journeys: getting to the midpoint, then to the
point midway between the midpoint and the end, then to the point midway between
this one and the end, and so on. But it is logically impossible for someone to
complete an infinite series of journeys. Therefore the runner cannot reach the
end of the track. Since it is irrelevant to the argument how far the end of the
track is it could be a foot or an inch
or a micron away this argument, if
sound, shows that all motion is impossible. Moving to any point will involve an
infinite number of journeys, and an infinite number of journeys cannot be
completed. The paradox of Achilles and the tortoise. Achilles can run much
faster than the tortoise, so when a race is arranged between them the tortoise
is given a lead. Zeno argued that Achilles can never catch up with the tortoise
no matter how fast he runs and no matter how long the race goes on. For the
first thing Achilles has to do is to get to the place from which the tortoise started.
But the tortoise, though slow, is unflag987 Z
987 ging: while Achilles was occupied in making up his handicap, the
tortoise has advanced a little farther. So the next thing Achilles has to do is
to get to the new place the tortoise occupies. While he is doing this, the
tortoise will have gone a little farther still. However small the gap that
remains, it will take Achilles some time to cross it, and in that time the
tortoise will have created another gap. So however fast Achilles runs, all that
the tortoise has to do, in order not to be beaten, is not to stop. The stadium
paradox. Imagine three equal cubes, A, B, and C, with sides all of length l,
arranged in a line stretching away from one. A is moved perpendicularly out of
line to the right by a distance equal to l. At the same time, and at the same
rate, C is moved perpendicularly out of line to the left by a distance equal to
l. The time it takes A to travel l/2 relative to B equals the time it takes A
to travel to l relative to C. So, in Aristotle’s words, “it follows, he [Zeno]
thinks, that half the time equals its double” Physics 259b35. The arrow
paradox. At any instant of time, the flying arrow “occupies a space equal to
itself.” That is, the arrow at an instant cannot be moving, for motion takes a
period of time, and a temporal instant is conceived as a point, not itself
having duration. It follows that the arrow is at rest at every instant, and so
does not move. What goes for arrows goes for everything: nothing moves.
Scholars disagree about what Zeno himself took his paradoxes to show. There is
no evidence that he offered any “solutions” to them. One view is that they were
part of a program to establish that multiplicity is an illusion, and that
reality is a seamless whole. The argument could be reconstructed like this: if
you allow that reality can be successively divided into parts, you find
yourself with these insupportable paradoxes; so you must think of reality as a
single indivisible One.
zoroastrianism: H.
P. Grice wrote, “Thus Implicated Zarahustra,” the national religion of ancient
Iran. Zoroastrianism suffered a steep decline after the seventh century A.D.
because of conversion to Islam. Of a remnant of roughly 100,000 adherents
today, three-fourths are Parsis “Persians” in or from western India; the others
are Iranian Zoroastrians. The tradition is identified with its prophet; his
name in Persian, Zarathushtra, is preserved in German, but the ancient Grecian
rendering of that name, Zoroaster, is the form used in most other modern European
languages. Zoroaster’s hymns to Ahura Mazda “the Wise Lord”, called the Gathas,
are interspersed among ritual hymns to other divine powers in the collection
known as the Avesta. In them, Zoroaster seeks reassurance that good will
ultimately triumph over evil and that Ahura Mazda will be a protector to him in
his prophetic mission. The Gathas expect that humans, by aligning themselves
with the force of righteousness and against evil, will receive bliss and
benefit in the next existence. The dating of the texts and of the prophet
himself is an elusive matter for scholars, but it is clear that Zoroaster lived
somewhere in Iran sometime prior to the emergence of the Achaemenid empire in
the sixth century B.C. His own faith in Ahura Mazda, reflected in the Gathas,
came to be integrated with other strains of old Indo-Iranian religion. We see
these in the Avesta’s hymns and the religion’s ritual practices. They venerate
an array of Iranian divine powers that resemble in function the deities found
in the Vedas of India. A common Indo-Iranian heritage is indicated conclusively
by similarities of language and of content between the Avesta and the Vedas.
Classical Zoroastrian orthodoxy does not replace the Indo-Iranian divinities
with Ahura Mazda, but instead incorporates them into its thinking more or less
as Ahura Mazda’s agents. The Achaemenid kings from the sixth through the fourth
centuries B.C. mention Ahura Mazda in their inscriptions, but not Zoroaster.
The Parthians, from the third century B.C. to the third century A.D.,
highlighted Mithra among the Indo-Iranian pantheon. But it was under the
Sasanians, who ruled Iran from the third to the seventh centuries, that
Zoroastrianism became the established religion. A salient doctrine is the
teaching concerning the struggle between good and evil. The time frame from the
world’s creation to the final resolution or judgment finds the Wise Lord, Ahura
Mazda or Ohrmazd, in the Pahlavi language of Sasanian times, locked in a
struggle with the evil spirit, Angra Mainyu in Pahlavi, Ahriman. The teaching
expands on an implication in the text of the Gathas, particularly Yasna 30,
that the good and evil spirits, coming together in the beginning and
establishing the living and inanimate realms, determined that at the end benefit
would accrue to the righteous but not the wicked. In Sasanian times, there was
speculative concern to assert Ahura Mazda’s infinity, omnipotence, and
omniscience, qualities that may indicate an impact of Mediterranean philosophy.
For example, the Bundahishn, a Pahlavi cosmological and eschatological
narrative, portrays Ahura Mazda as infinite in all four compass directions but
the evil spirit as limited in one and therefore doomed to ultimate defeat. Such
doctrine has been termed by some dualistic, in that it has at least in Sasanian
times seen the power of God rivaled by that of an evil spirit. Zoroastrians
today assert that they are monotheists, and do not worship the evil spirit. But
to the extent that the characterization may hold historically, Zoroastrianism
has manifested an “ethical” dualism, of good and evil forces. Although capable
of ritual pollution through waste products and decay, the physical world, God’s
creation, remains potentially morally good. Contrast “ontological” dualism, as
in gnostic and Manichaean teaching, where the physical world itself is the
result of the fall or entrapment of spirit in matter. In the nineteenth
century, Zoroastrian texts newly accessible to Europe produced an awareness of
the prophet’s concern for ethical matters. Nietzsche’s values in his work Thus
Spake Zarathustra, however, are his own, not those of the ancient prophet. The
title is arresting, but the connection of Nietzsche with historical
Zoroastrianism is a connection in theme only, in that the work advances ideas
about good and evil in an oracular style.
barrel sauna wood stove
ReplyDeleteWAJA sauna is specialist manufacturer of top quality sauna products. Products include sauna rooms, steam rooms, barrel saunas, wooden hot tubs, and all kinds of sauna accessories.