SPEECH ACT THEORY.
feminist epistemology, epistemology from a feminist perspective. It
investigates the relevance that the gender of the inquirer/knower has to epistemic
practices, including the theoretical practice of epistemology. It is typified
both by themes that are exclusively feminist in that they could arise only from
a critical attention to gender, and by themes that are non-exclusively feminist
in that they might arise from other politicizing theoretical perspectives
besides feminism. A central, exclusively feminist theme is the relation between
philosophical conceptions of reason and cultural conceptions of masculinity.
Here a historicist stance must be adopted, so that philosophy is conceived as
the product of historically and culturally situated (hence gendered) authors.
This stance brings certain patterns of intellectual association into view –
patterns, perhaps, of alignment between philosophical conceptions of reason as
contrasted with emotion or intuition, and cultural conceptions of masculinity
as contrasted with femininity. A central, non-exclusively feminist theme might
be called “social-ism” in epistemology. It has two main tributaries: political
philosophy, in the form of Marx’s historical materialism; and philosophy of
science, in the form of either Quinean naturalism or Kuhnian historicism. The
first has resulted in feminist standpoint theory, which adapts and develops the
Marxian idea that different social groups have different epistemic standpoints,
where the material positioning of one of the groups is said to bestow an
epistemic privilege. The second has resulted in feminist work in philosophy of
science which tries to show that not only epistemic values but also
non-epistemic (e.g. gendered) values are of necessity sometimes an influence in
the generation of scientific theories. If this can be shown, then an important
feminist project suggests itself: to work out a rationale for regulating the influence
of these values so that science may be more self-transparent and more
responsible. By attempting to reveal the epistemological implications of the
fact that knowers are diversely situated in social relations of identity and
power, feminist epistemology represents a radicalizing innovation in the
analytic tradition, which has typically assumed an asocial conception of the
epistemic subject, and of the philosopher.
EPISTEMOLOGY, FEMINIST PHILOSOPHY, KUHN, MARXISM, QUINE. M.F. feminist
philosophy, a discussion of philosophical concerns that refuses to identify the
human experience with the male experience. Writing from a variety of
perspectives, feminist philosophers challenge several areas of traditional
philosophy on the grounds that they fail (1) to take seriously women’s
interests, identities, and issues; and (2) to recognize women’s ways of being,
thinking, and doing as valuable as those of men. Feminist philosophers fault
traditional metaphysics for splitting the self from the other and the mind from
the body; for wondering whether “other minds” exist and whether personal
identity depends more on memories or on physical characteristics. Because
feminist philosophers reject all forms of ontological dualism, they stress the
ways in which individuals interpenetrate each other’s psyches through empathy,
and the ways in which the mind and body coconstitute each other. Because
Western culture has associated rationality with “masculinity” and emotionality
with “femininity,” traditional epistemologists have often concluded that women
are less human than men. For this reason, feminist philosophers argue that
reason and emotion are symbiotically related, coequal sources of knowledge.
Feminist philosophers also argue that Cartesian knowledge, for all its certainty
and clarity, is very limFechner’s law feminist philosophy 305 4065A- AM 305
ited. People want to know more than that they exist; they want to know what
other people are thinking and feeling. Feminist philosophers also observe that
traditional philosophy of science is not as objective as it claims to be.
Whereas traditional philosophers of science often associate scientific success
with scientists’ ability to control, rule, and otherwise dominate nature,
feminist philosophers of science associate scientific success with scientists’
ability to listen to nature’s self-revelations. Since it willingly yields
abstract theory to the testimony of concrete fact, a science that listens to
what nature says is probably more objective than one that does not. Feminist
philosophers also criticize traditional ethics and traditional social and
political philosophy. Rules and principles have dominated traditional ethics.
Whether agents seek to maximize utility for the aggregate or do their duty for
the sake of duty, they measure their conduct against a set of universal,
abstract, and impersonal norms. Feminist philosophers often call this
traditional view of ethics a “justice” perspective, contrasting it with a
“care” perspective that stresses responsibilities and relationships rather than
rights and rules, and that attends more to a moral situation’s particular
features than to its general implications. Feminist social and political
philosophy focus on the political institutions and social practices that
perpetuate women’s subordination. The goals of feminist social and political
philosophy are (1) to explain why women are suppressed, repressed, and/or
oppressed in ways that men are not; and (2) to suggest morally desirable and
politically feasible ways to give women the same justice, freedom, and equality
that men have. Liberal feminists believe that because women have the same
rights as men do, society must provide women with the same educational and
occupational opportunities that men have. Marxist feminists believe that women
cannot be men’s equals until women enter the work force en masse and domestic
work and child care are socialized. Radical feminists believe that the
fundamental causes of women’s oppression are sexual. It is women’s reproductive
role and/or their sexual role that causes their subordination. Unless women set
their own reproductive goals (childlessness is a legitimate alternative to
motherhood) and their own sexual agendas (lesbianism, autoeroticism, and
celibacy are alternatives to heterosexuality), women will remain less than
free. Psychoanalytic feminists believe that women’s subordination is the result
of earlychildhood experiences that cause them to overdevelop their abilities to
relate to other people on the one hand and to underdevelop their abilities to
assert themselves as autonomous agents on the other. Women’s greatest strength,
a capacity for deep relationships, may also be their greatest weakness: a
tendency to be controlled by the needs and wants of others. Finally,
existentialist feminists claim that the ultimate cause of women’s subordination
is ontological. Women are the Other; men are the Self. Until women define
themselves in terms of themselves, they will continue to be defined in terms of
what they are not: men. Recently, socialist feminists have attempted to weave
these distinctive strands of feminist social and political thought into a
theoretical whole. They argue that women’s condition is overdetermined by the
structures of production, reproduction and sexuality, and the socialization of
children. Women’s status and function in all of these structures must change if
they are to achieve full liberation. Furthermore, women’s psyches must also be
transformed. Only then will women be liberated from the kind of patriarchal
thoughts that undermine their self-concept and make them always the Other.
Interestingly, the socialist feminist effort to establish a specifically
feminist standpoint that represents how women see the world has not gone
without challenge. Postmodern feminists regard this effort as an instantiation
of the kind of typically male thinking that tells only one story about reality,
truth, knowledge, ethics, and politics. For postmodern feminists, such a story
is neither feasible nor desirable. It is not feasible because women’s
experiences differ across class, racial, and cultural lines. It is not
desirable because the “One” and the “True” are philosophical myths that
traditional philosophy uses to silence the voices of the many. Feminist
philosophy must be many and not One because women are many and not One. The
more feminist thoughts, the better. By refusing to center, congeal, and cement
separate thoughts into a unified and inflexible truth, feminist philosophers
can avoid the pitfalls of traditional philosophy. As attractive as the
postmodern feminist approach to philosophy may be, some feminist philosophers
worry that an overemphasis on difference and a rejection of unity may lead to
intellectual as well as political disintegration. If feminist philosophy is to
be without any standpoint whatsoever, it becomes difficult to ground claims
about what is good for women in particufeminist philosophy feminist philosophy
306 4065A- AM 306 lar and for human beings in general. It
is a major challenge to contemporary feminist philosophy, therefore, to
reconcile the pressures for diversity and difference with those for integration
and commonality. ETHICS, EXISTENTIALISM,
MARXISM, POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY, POSTMODERN. R.T. Ferguson, Adam (1723–1816),
Scottish philosopher and historian. His main theme was the rise and fall of
virtue in individuals and societies. In his most important work, An Essay on
the History of Civil Society (1766), he argued that human happiness (of which
virtue is a constituent) is found in pursuing social goods rather than private
ends. Ferguson thought that ignoring social goods not only prevented social
progress but led to moral corruption and political despotism. To support this
he used classical texts and travelers’ writings to reconstruct the history of
society from “rude nations” through barbarism to civilization. This allowed him
to express his concern for the danger of corruption inherent in the increasing
selfinterest manifested in the incipient commercial civilization of his day. He
attempted to systematize his moral philosophy in The Principles of Moral and
Social Science (1792). J.W.A. Fermat’s last theorem.CHOICE SEQUENCE. Feuerbach,
Ludwig Andreas (1804–72), German materialist philosopher and critic of
religion. He provided the major link between Hegel’s absolute idealism and such
later theories of historical materialism as those of Marx and other “young (or
new) Hegelians.” Feuerbach was born in Bavaria and studied theology, first at
Heidelberg and then Berlin, where he came under the philosophical influence of
Hegel. He received his doctorate in 1828 and, after an early publication
severely critical of Christianity, retired from official German academic life.
In the years between 1836 and 1846, he produced some of his most influential
works, which include “Towards a Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy” (1839), The
Essence of Christianity (1841), Principles of the Philosophy of the Future
(1843), and The Essence of Religion (1846). After a brief collaboration with
Marx, he emerged as a popular champion of political liberalism in the
revolutionary period of 1848. During the reaction that followed, he again left
public life and died dependent upon the support of friends. Feuerbach was
pivotal in the intellectual history of the nineteenth century in several
respects. First, after a half-century of metaphysical system construction by
the German idealists, Feuerbach revived, in a new form, the original Kantian
project of philosophical critique. However, whereas Kant had tried “to limit
reason in order to make room for faith,” Feuerbach sought to demystify both
faith and reason in favor of the concrete and situated existence of embodied
human consciousness. Second, his “method” of “transformatory criticism” –
directed, in the first instance, at Hegel’s philosophical pronouncements – was
adopted by Marx and has retained its philosophical appeal. Briefly, it
suggested that “Hegel be stood on his feet” by “inverting” the subject and
predicate in Hegel’s idealistic pronouncements. One should, e.g., rewrite “The
individual is a function of the Absolute” as “The Absolute is a function of the
individual.” Third, Feuerbach asserted that the philosophy of German idealism
was ultimately an extenuation of theology, and that theology was merely
religious consciousness systematized. But since religion itself proves to be
merely a “dream of the human mind,” metaphysics, theology, and religion can be
reduced to “anthropology,” the study of concrete embodied human consciousness
and its cultural products. The philosophical influence of Feuerbach flows
through Marx into virtually all later historical materialist positions;
anticipates the existentialist concern with concrete embodied human existence;
and serves as a paradigm for all later approaches to religion on the part of
the social sciences. HEGEL, KANT, MARX,
MARXISM. J.P.Su. Fichte, Johann Gottlieb (1762–1814), German philosopher. He
was a proponent of an uncompromising system of transcendental idealism, the
Wissenschaftslehre, which played a key role in the development of post-Kantian philosophy.
Born in Saxony, Fichte studied at Jena and Leipzig. The writings of Kant led
him to abandon metaphysical determinism and to embrace transcendental idealism
as “the first system of human freedom.” His first book, Versuch einer Kritik
aller Offenbarung (“Attempt at a Critique of all Revelations,” 1792), earned
him a reputation as a brilliant exponent of Kantianism, while his early
political writings secured him a reputation as a Jacobin. Inspired by Reinhold,
Jacobi, Maimon, and Schulze, Fichte rejected the “letter” of Kantianism and, in
the lectures and writings he produced at Jena (1794–99), advanced a new,
rigorously systematic presentation of what he took to be its Ferguson, Adam
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb 307 4065A-
AM 307 “spirit.” He dispensed
with Kant’s things-inthemselves, the original duality of faculties, and the
distinction between the transcendental aesthetic and the transcendental
analytic. By emphasizing the unity of theoretical and practical reason in a way
consistent with “the primacy of practical reason,” Fichte sought to establish
the unity of the critical philosophy as well as of human experience. In Ueber
den Begriff der Wissenschaftslehre (“On the Concept of the Wissenschaftslehre,”
1794) he explained his conception of philosophy as “the science of science,” to
be presented in a deductive system based on a self-evident first principle. The
basic “foundations” of this system, which Fichte called Wissenschaftslehre
(theory of science), were outlined in his Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre
(“Foundations of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre,” 1794–95) and Grundriß der
Eigentümlichen der Wissenschaftslehre in Rücksicht auf das theoretische
Vermögen (“Outline of the Distinctive Character of the Wissenschaftslehre with
respect to the Theoretical Faculty,” 1795) and then, substantially revised, in
his lectures on Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo (1796–99). The “foundational”
portion of the Wissenschaftslehrelinks our affirmation of freedom to our
experience of natural necessity. Beginning with the former (“the I simply
posits itself”), it then demonstrates how a freely self-positing subject must
be conscious not only of itself, but also of “representations accompanied by a
feeling of necessity” and hence of an objective world. Fichte insisted that the
essence of selfhood lies in an active positing of its own self-identity and
hence that self-consciousness is an auto-productive activity: a Tathandlung or
“fact/act.” However, the I can posit itself only as limited; in order for the
originally posited act of “sheer self-positing” to occur, certain other mental
acts must occur as well, acts through which the I posits for itself an
objective, spatiotemporal world, as well as a moral realm of free, rational
beings. The I first posits its own limited condition in the form of “feeling”
(occasioned by an inexplicable Anstob or “check” upon its own practical
striving), then as a “sensation,” then as an “intuition” of a thing, and
finally as a “concept.” The distinction between the I and the not-I arises only
in these reiterated acts of self-positing, a complete description of which thus
amounts to a “genetic deduction” of the necessary conditions of experience.
Freedom is thereby shown to be possible only in the context of natural
necessity, where it is limited and finite. At the same time “our freedom is a
theoretical determining principle of our world.” Though it must posit its
freedom “absolutely” – i.e., schlechthin or “for no reason” – a genuinely free
agent can exist only as a finite individual endlessly striving to overcome its
own limits. After establishing its “foundations,” Fichte extended his
Wissenschaftslehre into social and political philosophy and ethics.
Subjectivity itself is essentially intersubjective, inasmuch as one can be
empirically conscious of oneself only as one individual among many and must
thus posit the freedom of others in order to posit one’s own freedom. But for
this to occur, the freedom of each individual must be limited; indeed, “the
concept of right or justice (Recht) is nothing other than the concept of the
coexistence of the freedom of several rational/sensuous beings.” The Grundlage
des Naturrechts (“Foundations of Natural Right,” 1796–97) examines how
individual freedom must be externally limited if a community of free
individuals is to be possible, and demonstrates that a just political order is
a demand of reason itself, since “the concept of justice or right is a
condition of self-consciousness.” “Natural rights” are thus entirely
independent of moral duties. Unlike political philosophy, which purely concerns
the public realm, ethics, which is the subject of Das System der Sittenlehre
(“The System of Ethical Theory,” 1798), concerns the inner realm of conscience.
It views objects not as given to consciousness but as produced by free action,
and concerns not what is, but what ought to be. The task of ethics is to
indicate the particular duties that follow from the general obligation to
determine oneself freely (the categorical imperative). Before Fichte could extend
the Wissenschaftslehre into the philosophy of religion, he was accused of
atheism and forced to leave Jena. The celebrated controversy over his alleged
atheism (the Atheismusstreit) was provoked by “Ueber den Grund unseres Glaubens
in einer göttliche Weltregierung” (“On the Basis of our Belief in a Divine
Governance of the World,” 1798), in which he sharply distinguished between
philosophical and religious questions. While defending our right to posit a
“moral world order,” Fichte insisted that this order does not require a
personal deity or “moral lawgiver.” After moving to Berlin, Fichte’s first
concern was to rebut the charge of atheism and to reply to the indictment of
philosophy as “nihilism” advanced in Jacobi’s Open Letter to Fichte (1799).
This was the task of Die Bestimmung des Menschen (“The Vocation of Man,” 1800).
During the French occupation, he delivered Reden an die deutsche Nation
(“Addresses to the German Fichte, Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Johann Gottlieb 308
4065A- AM 308 Nation,” 1808), which proposed a program
of national education and attempted to kindle German patriotism. The other
publications of his Berlin years include a foray into political economy, Der
geschlossene Handelstaat (“The Closed Commercial State,” 1800); a speculative interpretation
of human history, Die Grundzüge des gegenwärtiges Zeitalters (“The
Characteristics of the Present Age,” 1806); and a mystically tinged treatise on
salvation, Die Anweisung zum seligen Leben (“Guide to the Blessed Life,” 1806).
In unpublished private lectures he continued to develop radically new versions
of the Wissenschaftslehre. Fichte’s substantial influence was not limited to
his well-known influence on Schelling and Hegel (both of whom criticized the
“subjectivism” of the early Wissenschaftslehre). He is also important in the
history of German nationalism and profoundly influenced the early Romantics,
especially Novalis and Schlegel. Recent decades have seen renewed interest in
Fichte’s transcendental philosophy, expecially the later, unpublished versions
of the Wissenschaftslehre. This century’s most significant contribution to
Fichte studies, however, is the ongoing publication of the first critical
edition of his complete works. HEGEL,
IDEALISM, KANT. D.Br. Ficino, Marsilio (1433–99), Italian Neoplatonic
philosopher who played a leading role in the cultural life of Florence.
Ordained a priest in 1473, he hoped to draw people to Christ by means of
Platonism. It was through Ficino’s translation and commentaries that the works
of Plato first became accessible to the Latin-speaking West, but the impact of
Plato’s work was considerably affected by Ficino’s other interests. He accepted
Neoplatonic interpretations of Plato, including those of Plotinus, whom he
translated; and he saw Plato as the heir of Hermes Trismegistus, a mythical
Egyptian sage and supposed author of the hermetic corpus, which he translated
early in his career. He embraced the notion of a prisca theologia, an ancient
wisdom that encapsulated philosophic and religious truth, was handed on to
Plato, and was later validated by the Christian revelation. The most popular of
his original works was Three Books on Life (1489), which contains the fullest
Renaissance exposition of a theory of magic, based mainly on Neoplatonic
sources. He postulated a living cosmos in which the World-Soul is linked to the
world-body by spirit. This relationship is mirrored in man, whose spirit (or
astral body) links his body and soul, and the resulting correspondence between
microcosm and macrocosm allows both man’s control of natural objects through
magic and his ascent to knowledge of God. Other popular works were his
commentary on Plato’s Symposium (1469), which presents a theory of Platonic
love; and his Platonic Theology (1474), in which he argues for the immortality
of the soul. NEOPLATONISM. E.J.A.
fiction, in the widest usage, whatever contrasts with what is a matter of fact.
As applied to works of fiction, however, this is not the appropriate contrast.
For a work of fiction, such as a historical novel, might turn out to be true
regarding its historical subject, without ceasing to be fiction. The correct
contrast of fiction is to non-fiction. If a work of fiction might turn out to
be true, how is ‘fiction’ best defined? According to some philosophers, such as
Searle, the writer of nonfiction performs illocutionary speech acts, such as
asserting that such-and-such occurred, whereas the writer of fiction
characteristically only pretends to perform these illocutionary acts. Others
hold that the core idea to which appeal should be made is that of
making-believe or imagining certain states of affairs. Kendall Walton (Mimesis
as Make-Believe, 1990), for instance, holds that a work of fiction is to be
construed in terms of a prop whose function is to serve in games of
make-believe. Both kinds of theory allow for the possibility that a work of
fiction might turn out to be true.
AESTHETICS, IMAGINATION, PHILOSOPHY OF LITERATURE, SPEECH ACT THEORY.
B.Ga. fiction, logical.LOGICAL CONSTRUCTION. fictionalism.DUHEM.
fideism.EVIDENTIALISM. “Fido” – Fido theory of meaning.MEANING. field (of a
relation).RELATION. field theory, a theory that proceeds by assigning values of
physical quantities to the points of space, or of space-time, and then lays
down laws relating these values. For example, a field theory might suppose a
value for matter density, or a temperature for each space-time point, and then
relate these values, usually in terms of differential equations. In these
examples there is at least the tacit assumption of a physical substance that
fills the relevant region of space-time. But no such assumption need be made.
For instance, in Ficino, Marsilio field theory 309 4065A- AM 309
Maxwell’s theory of the electromagnetic field, each point of space-time carries
a value for an electric and a magnetic field, and these values are then
governed by Maxwell’s equations. In general relativity, the geometry (e.g., the
curvature) of space-time is itself treated as a field, with lawlike connections
with the distribution of energy and matter. Formulation in terms of a field
theory resolves the problem of action at a distance that so exercised Newton
and his contemporaries. We often take causal connection to require spatial
contiguity. That is, for one entity to act causally on another, the two
entities need to be contiguous. But in Newton’s description gravitational
attraction acts across spatial distances. Similarly, in electrostatics the
mutual repulsion of electric charges is described as acting across spatial
distances. In the times of both Newton and Maxwell numerous efforts to
understand such action at a distance in terms of some space-filling mediating
substance produced no viable theory. Field theories resolve the perplexity. By
attributing values of physical quantities directly to the space-time points one
can describe gravitation, electrical and magnetic forces, and other
interactions without action at a distance or any intervening physical medium.
One describes the values of physical quantities, attributed directly to the
space-time points, as influencing only the values at immediately neighboring
points. In this way the influences propagate through space-time, rather than
act instantaneously across distances or through a medium. Of course there is a
metaphysical price: on such a description the space-time points themselves take
on the role of a kind of dematerialized ether. Indeed, some have argued that
the pervasive role of field theory in contemporary physics and the need for
space-time points for a field-theoretic description constitute a strong
argument for the existence of the space-time points. This conclusion
contradicts “relationalism,” which claims that there are only spatiotemporal
relations, but no space-time points or regions thought of as particulars. Quantum
field theory appears to take on a particularly abstract form of field theory,
since it associates a quantum mechanical operator with each space-time point.
However, since operators correspond to physical magnitudes rather than to
values of such magnitudes, it is better to think of the field-theoretic aspect
of quantum field theory in terms of the quantum mechanical amplitudes that it
also associates with the space-time points.
EINSTEIN, NEWTON, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, QUANTUM MECHANICS, SPACETIME.
P.Te. figure.SYLLOGISM. figure–ground, the discrimination of an object or
figure from the context or background against which it is set. Even when a
connected region is grouped together properly, as in the famous figure that can
be seen either as a pair of faces or as a vase, it is possible to interpret the
region alternately as figure and as ground. This fact was originally elaborated
in 1921 by Edgar Rubin (1886– 1951). Figure–ground effects and the existence of
other ambiguous figures such as the Necker cube and the duck–rabbit challenged
the prevailing assumption in classical theories of perception – maintained,
e.g., by J. S. Mill and H. von Helmholtz – that complex perceptions could be
understood in terms of primitive sensations constituting them. The underdetermination
of perception by the visual stimulus, noted by Berkeley in his Essay of 1709,
takes account of the fact that the retinal image is impoverished with respect
to threedimensional information. Identical stimulation at the retina can result
from radically different distal sources. Within Gestalt psychology, the
Gestalt, or pattern, was recognized to be underdetermined by constituent parts
available in proximal stimuli. M. Wertheimer (1880–1943) observed in 1912 that
apparent motion could be induced by viewing a series of still pictures in rapid
succession. He concluded that perception of the whole, as involving movement,
was fundamentally different from the perception of the static images of which
it is composed. W. Köhler An example of visual reversal from Edgar Rubin: the
object depicted can be seen alternately as a vase or as a pair of faces. The
reversal occurs whether there is a black ground and white figure or white
figure and black ground. figure figure – ground 310 4065A- AM 310
(1887–1967) observed that there was no figure– ground articulation in the
retinal image, and concluded that inherently ambiguous stimuli required some
autonomous selective principles of perceptual organization. As subsequently
developed by Gestalt psychologists, form is taken as the primitive unit of
perception. In philosophical treatments, figure–ground effects are used to
enforce the conclusion that interpretation is central to perception, and that
perceptions are no more than hypotheses based on sensory data. KÖHLER, PERCEPTION. R.C.R. Filmer, Robert
(1588–1653), English political writer who produced, most importantly, the
posthumous Patriarcha (1680). It is remembered because Locke attacked it in the
first of his Two Treatises of Government (1690). Filmer argued that God gave
complete authority over the world to Adam, and that from him it descended to
his eldest son when he became the head of the family. Thereafter only fathers
directly descended from Adam could properly be rulers. Just as Adam’s rule was
not derived from the consent of his family, so the king’s inherited authority
is not dependent on popular consent. He rightly makes laws and imposes taxes at
his own good pleasure, though like a good father he has the welfare of his
subjects in view. Filmer’s patriarchalism, intended to bolster the absolute
power of the king, is the classic English statement of the doctrine.
POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY.
J.B.S. final cause.ARISTOTLE. finitary proof.HILBERT’S PROGRAM. finite
automaton.COMPUTER THEORY, TURING MACHINE. finitism.HILBERT, PHILOSOPHY OF
MATHEMATICS. first actualization.ARISTOTLE. first cause.PRIME MOVER. first
cause argument.PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. first imposition.IMPOSITION. first
intention.IMPOSITION. first law of thermodynamics.ENTROPY. first limit
theorem.PROBABILITY. first mover.PRIME MOVER. firstness.PEIRCE.
first-order.ORDER. first-order logic.FORMAL LOGIC, ORDER, SECOND-ORDER LOGIC.
first philosophy, in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, the study of being qua being,
including the study of theology (as understood by him), since the divine is
being par excellence. Descartes’s Meditations on First Philosophy was concerned
chiefly with the existence of God, the immortality of the soul, and the nature
of matter and of the mind. METAPHYSICS.
P.Bu. first potentiality.ARISTOTLE. fitness.PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY. five
phases.WU-HSING. Five Ways.AQUINAS. Fludd, Robert (1574–1637), English
physician and writer. Influenced by Paracelsus, hermetism, and the cabala,
Fludd defended a Neoplatonic worldview on the eve of its supersession by the
new mechanistic philosophy. He produced improvements in the manufacture of
steel and invented a thermometer, though he also used magnets to cure disease
and devised a salve to be applied to a weapon to cure the wound it had
inflicted. He held that science got its ideas from Scripture allegorically
interpreted, when they were of any value. His works combine theology with an
occult, Neoplatonic reading of the Bible, and contain numerous fine diagrams
illustrating the mutual sympathy of human beings, the natural world, and the
supernatural world, each reflecting the others in parallel harmonic structures.
In controversy with Kepler, Fludd claimed to uncover essential natural
processes rooted in natural sympathies and the operation of God’s light, rather
than merely describing the external movements of the heavens. Creation is the
extension of divine light into matter. Evil arises from a darkness in God, his
failure to will. Matter is uncreated, but this poses no problem for orthodoxy,
since matter is nothing, a mere possibility without the least actuality, not
something Filmer, Robert Fludd, Robert 311 4065A- AM 311
coeternal with the Creator.
NEOPLATONISM. J.Lo. fluxion.CALCULUS. flying arrow paradox.ZENO’S
PARADOXES. focal meaning.ARISTOTLE. Fodor, Jerry A. (b.1935), influential
contemporary American philosopher of psychology, known for his energetic (and
often witty) defense of intensional realism, a computationalrepresentational
model of thought, and an atomistic, externalist theory of content determination
for mental states. Fodor’s philosophical writings fall under three headings.
First, he has defended the theory of mind implicit in contemporary cognitive
psychology, that the cognitive mind-brain is both a
representational/computational device and, ultimately, physical. He has taken
on behaviorists (Ryle), psychologists in the tradition of J. J. Gibson, and
eliminative materialists (P. A. Churchland). Second, he has engaged in various
theoretical disputes within cognitive psychology, arguing for the modularity of
the perceptual and language systems (roughly, the view that they are
domain-specific, mandatory, limited-access, innately specified, hardwired, and
informationally encapsulated) (The Modularity of Mind, 1983); for a strong form
of nativism (that virtually all of our concepts are innate); and for the
existence of a “language of thought” (The Language of Thought, 1975). The
latter has led him to argue against connectionism as a psychological theory (as
opposed to an implementation theory). Finally, he has defended the views of
ordinary propositional attitude psychology that our mental states (1) are
semantically evaluable (intentional), (2) have causal powers, and (3) are such
that the implicit generalizations of folk psychology are largely true of them.
His defense is twofold. Folk psychology is unsurpassed in explanatory power;
furthermore, it is vindicated by contemporary cognitive psychology insofar as
ordinary propositional attitude states can be identified with
information-processing states, those that consist in a computational relation
to a representation. The representational component of such states allows us to
explain the semantic evaluability of the attitudes; the computational
component, their causal efficacy. Both sorts of accounts raise difficulties.
The first is satisfactory only if supplemented by a naturalistic account of
representational content. Here Fodor has argued for an atomistic, externalist
causal theory (Psychosemantics, 1987) and against holism (the view that no mental
representation has content unless many other non-synonymous mental
representations also have content) (Holism: A Shopper’s Guide, 1992), against
conceptual role theories (the view that the content of a representation is
determined by its conceptual role) (Ned Block, Brian Loar), and against
teleofunctional theories (teleofunctionalism is the view that the content of a
representation is determined, at least in part, by the biological functions of
the representations themselves or systems that produce or use those
representations) (Ruth Millikan, David Papineau). The second sort is
satisfactory only if it does not imply epiphenomenalism with respect to content
properties. To avoid such epiphenomenalism, Fodor has argued that not only
strict laws but also ceteris paribus laws can be causal. In addition, he has
sought to reconcile his externalism vis-à-vis content with the view that causal
efficacy requires an individualistic individuation of states. Two solutions
have been explored: the supplementation of broad (externally determined)
content with narrow content, where the latter supervenes on what is “in the
head” (Psychosemantics, 1987), and its supplementation with modes of
presentation identical to sentences of the language of thought (The Elm and the
Expert, 1995). COGNITIVE SCIENCE,
CONNECTIONISM, FOLK PSYCHOLOGY, HOLISM, LANGUAGE OF THOUGHT, MEANING,
PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. B.V.E. folk psychology, in one sense, a putative network of
principles constituting a commonsense theory that allegedly underlies everyday
explanations of human behavior; the theory assigns a central role to mental
states like belief, desire, and intention. Consider an example of an everyday
commonsense psychological explanation: Jane went to the refrigerator because
she wanted a beer and she believed there was beer in the refrigerator. Like
many such explanations, this adverts to a so-called propositional attitude – a
mental state, expressed by a verb (‘believe’) plus a that-clause, whose
intentional content is propositional. It also adverts to a mental state,
expressed by a verb (‘want’) plus a direct-object phrase, whose intentional
content appears not to be propositional. In another, related sense, folk
psychology is a network of social practices that includes ascribing such mental
states to ourselves and others, and proffering explanations of human behavior
that advert to these states. The two senses need fluxion folk psychology 312
4065A- AM 312 distinguishing because some philosophers
who acknowledge the existence of folk psychology in the second sense hold that
commonsense psychological explanations do not employ empirical generalizations,
and hence that there is no such theory as folk psychology. (Henceforth, ‘FP’
will abbreviate ‘folk psychology’ in the first sense; the unabbreviated phrase
will be used in the second sense.) Eliminativism in philosophy of mind asserts
that FP is an empirical theory; that FP is therefore subject to potential
scientific falsification; and that mature science very probably will establish
that FP is so radically false that humans simply do not undergo mental states
like beliefs, desires, and intentions. One kind of eliminativist argument first
sets forth certain methodological strictures about how FP would have to
integrate with mature science in order to be true (e.g., being smoothly
reducible to neuroscience, or being absorbed into mature cognitive science),
and then contends that these strictures are unlikely to be met. Another kind of
argument first claims that FP embodies certain strong empirical commitments
(e.g., to mental representations with languagelike syntactic structure), and
then contends that such empirical presuppositions are likely to turn out false.
One influential version of folk psychological realism largely agrees with
eliminativism about what is required to vindicate folk psychology, but also
holds that mature science is likely to provide such vindication. Realists of
this persuasion typically argue, for instance, that mature cognitive science
will very likely incorporate FP, and also will very likely treat beliefs,
desires, and other propositional attitudes as states with languagelike
syntactic structure. Other versions of folkpsychological realism take issue, in
one way or another, with either (i) the eliminativists’ claims about FP’s
empirical commitments, or (ii) the eliminativists’ strictures about how FP must
mesh with mature science in order to be true, or both. Concerning (i), for
instance, some philosophers maintain that FP per se is not committed to the
existence of languagelike mental representations. If mature cognitive science
turns out not to posit a “language of thought,” they contend, this would not
necessarily show that FP is radically false; instead it might only show that
propositional attitudes are subserved in some other way than via languagelike
representational structures. Concerning (ii), some philosophers hold that FP
can be true without being as tightly connected to mature scientific theories as
the eliminativists require. For instance, the demand that the special sciences
be smoothly reducible to the fundamental natural sciences is widely considered
an excessively stringent criterion of intertheoretic compatibility; so perhaps
FP could be true without being smoothly reducible to neuroscience. Similarly,
the demand that FP be directly absorbable into empirical cognitive science is
sometimes considered too stringent as a criterion either of FP’s truth, or of
the soundness of its ontology of beliefs, desires, and other propositional
attitudes, or of the legitimacy of FP-based explanations of behavior. Perhaps
FP is a true theory, and explanatorily legitimate, even if it is not destined
to become a part of science. Even if FP’s ontological categories are not
scientific natural kinds, perhaps its generalizations are like generalizations
about clothing: true, explanatorily usable, and ontologically sound. (No one
doubts the existence of hats, coats, or scarves. No one doubts the truth or
explanatory utility of generalizations like ‘Coats made of heavy material tend
to keep the body warm in cold weather’, even though these generalizations are
not laws of any science.) Yet another approach to folk psychology, often wedded
to realism about beliefs and desires (although sometimes wedded to
instrumentalism), maintains that folk psychology does not employ empirical
generalizations, and hence is not a theory at all. One variant denies that folk
psychology employs any generalizations, empirical or otherwise. Another variant
concedes that there are folk-psychological generalizations, but denies that
they are empirical; instead they are held to be analytic truths, or norms of
rationality, or both at once. Advocates of non-theory views typically regard
folk psychology as a hermeneutic, or interpretive, enterprise. They often claim
too that the attribution of propositional attitudes, and also the proffering
and grasping of folk-psychological explanations, is a matter of imaginatively
projecting oneself into another person’s situation, and then experiencing a
kind of empathic understanding, or Verstehen, of the person’s actions and the
motives behind them. A more recent, hi-tech, formulation of this idea is that
the interpreter “runs a cognitive simulation” of the person whose actions are
to be explained. Philosophers who defend folk-psychological realism, in one or
another of the ways just canvassed, also sometimes employ arguments based on
the allegedly self-stultifying nature of eliminativism. One such argument
begins from the premise that the notion of action is folk-psychofolk psychology
folk psychology 313 4065A- AM 313 logical – that a behavioral event counts
as an action only if it is caused by propositional attitudes that rationalize
it (under some suitable actdescription). If so, and if humans never really
undergo propositional attitudes, then they never really act either. In
particular, they never really assert anything, or argue for anything (since
asserting and arguing are species of action). So if eliminativism is true, the
argument concludes, then eliminativists can neither assert it nor argue for it
– an allegedly intolerable pragmatic paradox. Eliminativists generally react to
such arguments with breathtaking equanimity. A typical reply is that although
our present concept of action might well be folk-psychological, this does not
preclude the possibility of a future successor concept, purged of any
commitment to beliefs and desires, that could inherit much of the role of our
current, folk-psychologically tainted, concept of action. COGNITIVE SCIENCE, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND, REDUCTION,
SIMULATION THEORY. T.E.H. Fonseca, Pedro da (1528–99), Portuguese philosopher
and logician. He entered the Jesuit order in 1548. Apart from a period
(1572–82) in Rome, he lived in Portugal, teaching philosophy and theology at
the universities of Evora and Coimbra and performing various administrative
duties for his order. He was responsible for the idea of a published course on
Aristotelian philosophy, and the resulting series of Coimbra commentaries, the
Cursus Conimbricensis, was widely used in the seventeenth century. His own
logic text, the Institutes of Dialectic (1564), went into many editions. It is
a good example of Renaissance Aristotelianism, with its emphasis on Aristotle’s
syllogistic, but it retains some material on medieval developments, notably
consequences, exponibles, and supposition theory. Fonseca also wrote a
commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics (published in parts from 1577 on), which
contains the Greek text, a corrected Latin translation, comments on textual
matters, and an extensive exploration of selected philosophical problems. He
cites a wide range of medieval philosophers, both Christian and Arab, as well
as the newly published Greek commentators on Aristotle. His own position is
sympathetic to Aquinas, but generally independent. Fonseca is important not so
much for any particular doctrines, though he did hold original views on such
matters as analogy, but for his provision of fully documented, carefully
written and carefully argued books that, along with others in the same tradition,
were read at universities, both Catholic and Protestant, well into the
seventeenth century. He represents what is often called the Second
Scholasticism. E.J.A. Fontenelle, Bernard Le Bovier de (1657–1757), French
writer who heralded the age of the philosophes. A product of Jesuit education,
he was a versatile freethinker with skeptical inclinations. Dialogues of the
Dead (1683) showed off his analytical mind and elegant style. In 1699, he was
appointed secretary of the Academy of Sciences. He composed famous eulogies of
scientists; defended the superiority of modern science over tradition in
Digression on Ancients and Moderns (1688); popularized Copernican astronomy in
Conversations on the Plurality of Worlds (1686) – famous for postulating the
inhabitation of planets; stigmatized superstition and credulity in History of
Oracles (1687) and The Origin of Fables (1724); promoted Cartesian physics in
The Theory of Cartesian Vortices (1752); and wrote Elements of Infinitesimal
Calculus (1727) in the wake of Newton and Leibniz. J.-L.S. Foot, Philippa
(b.1920), British philosopher who exerted a lasting influence on the
development of moral philosophy in the second half of the twentieth century.
Her persisting, intertwined themes are opposition to all forms of subjectivism
in ethics, the significance of the virtues and vices, and the connection
between morality and rationality. In her earlier papers, particularly “Moral
Beliefs” (1958) and “Goodness and Choice” (1961), reprinted in Virtues and
Vices (1978), she undermines the subjectivist accounts of moral “judgment”
derived from C. L. Stevenson and Hare by arguing for many logical or conceptual
connections between evaluations and the factual statements on which they must
be based. Lately she has developed this kind of thought into the naturalistic
claim that moral evaluations are determined by facts about our life and our
nature, as evaluations of features of plants and animals (as good or defective
specimens of their kind) are determined by facts about their nature and their
life. Foot’s opposition to subjectivism has remained constant, but her views on
the virtues in relation to rationality have undergone several changes. In
“Moral Beliefs” she relates them to self-interest, maintaining that a virtue
must benefit its possessor; in the (subsequently repudiated) “Morality as a
System of Hypothetical Imperatives” (1972) she went as far as to deny that
there was necessarily anything contrary to reason in Fonseca, Pedro da Foot,
Philippa 314 4065A- AM 314 being uncharitable or unjust. In “Does
Moral Subjectivism Rest on a Mistake?” (Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 1995)
the virtues themselves appear as forms of practical rationality. Her most
recent work, soon to be published as The Grammar of Goodness, preserves and
develops the latter claim and reinstates ancient connections between virtue,
rationality, and happiness. ETHICS,
HARE, VIRTUE ETHICS. R.Hu. force, illocutionary.PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE, SPEECH
ACT THEORY. forcing, a method introduced by Paul J. Cohen – see his Set Theory
and the Continuum Hypothesis (1966) – to prove independence results in
Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory (ZF). Cohen proved the independence of the axiom of
choice (AC) from ZF, and of the continuum hypothesis (CH) from ZF ! AC. The
consistency of AC with ZF and of CH with ZF ! AC had previously been proved by
Gödel by the method of constructible sets. A model of ZF consists of layers,
with the elements of a set at one layer always belonging to lower layers.
Starting with a model M, Cohen’s method produces an “outer model” N with no
more levels but with more sets at each level (whereas Gödel’s method produces
an ‘inner model’ L): much of what will become true in N can be “forced” from
within M. The method is applicable only to hypotheses in the more “abstract”
branches of mathematics (infinitary combinatorics, general topology, measure
theory, universal algebra, model theory, etc.); but there it is ubiquitous.
Applications include the proof by Robert M. Solovay of the consistency of the
measurability of all sets (of all projective sets) with ZF (with ZF ! AC); also
the proof by Solovay and Donald A. Martin of the consistency of Martin’s axiom
(MA) plus the negation of the continuum hypothesis (-CH) with ZF ! AC. (CH
implies MA; and of known consequences of CH about half are implied by MA, about
half refutable by MA ! -CH.) Numerous simplifications, extensions, and variants
(e.g. Boolean-valued models) of Cohen’s method have been introduced. INDEPENDENCE RESULTS, SET THEORY. J.Bur.
Fordyce, David (1711–51), Scottish philosopher and educational theorist whose
writings were influential in the eighteenth century. His lectures formed the
basis of his Elements of Moral Philosophy, written originally for The Preceptor
(1748), later translated into German and French, and abridged for the articles
on moral philosophy in the first Encylopaedia Britannica (1771). Fordyce
combines the preacher’s appeal to the heart in the advocacy of virtue with a
moral “scientist’s” appraisal of human psychology. He claims to derive our
duties experimentally from a study of the prerequisites of human happiness.
M.A.St. foreknowledge, divine.DIVINE FOREKNOWLEDGE. form, in metaphysics,
especially Plato’s and Aristotle’s, the structure or essence of a thing as
contrasted with its matter. (1) Plato’s theory of Forms is a realistic ontology
of universals. In his elenchus, Socrates sought what is common to, e.g., all
chairs. Plato believed there must be an essence – or Form – common to
everything falling under one concept, which makes anything what it is. A chair
is a chair because it “participates in” the Form of Chair. The Forms are ideal
“patterns,” unchanging, timeless, and perfect. They exist in a world of their
own (cf. the Kantian noumenal realm). Plato speaks of them as self-predicating:
the Form of Beauty is perfectly beautiful. This led, as he realized, to the
Third Man argument that there must be an infinite number of Forms. The only
true understanding is of the Forms. This we attain through anamnesis,
“recollection.” (2) Aristotle agreed that forms are closely tied to
intelligibility, but denied their separate existence. Aristotle explains change
and generation through a distinction between the form and matter of substances.
A lump of bronze (matter) becomes a statue through its being molded into a
certain shape (form). In his earlier metaphysics, Aristotle identified primary
substance with the composite of matter and form, e.g. Socrates. Later, he
suggests that primary substance is form – what makes Socrates what he is (the form
here is his soul). This notion of forms as essences has obvious similarities
with the Platonic view. They became the “substantial forms” of Scholasticism,
accepted until the seventeenth century. (3) Kant saw form as the a priori
aspect of experience. We are presented with phenomenological “matter,” which
has no meaning until the mind imposes some form upon it. ARISTOTLE, KANT, METAPHYSICS, PLATO. R.C.
form, aesthetic.
AESTHETIC FORMALISM,
AESTHETICS. force, illocutionary form, aesthetic 315 4065A- AM 315
form, grammatical.LOGICAL FORM. form, logical.LOGICAL FORM. form,
Platonic.FORM, PLATO. form, schematic.LOGICAL FORM. form, substantial.FORM,
HYLOMORPHISM. formal cause.ARISTOTLE. formal distinction.FUNDAMENTUM
DIVISIONIS. formal fallacy, an invalid inference pattern that is described in
terms of a formal logic. There are three main cases: (1) an invalid (or
otherwise unacceptable) argument identified solely by its form or structure,
with no reference to the content of the premises and conclusion (such as
equivocation) or to other features, generally of a pragmatic character, of the
argumentative discourse (such as unsuitability of the argument for the purposes
for which it is given, failure to satisfy inductive standards for acceptable
argument, etc.; the latter conditions of argument evaluation fall into the
purview of informal fallacy); (2) a formal rule of inference, or an argument
form, that is not valid (in the logical system on which the evaluation is
made), instances of which are sufficiently frequent, familiar, or deceptive to
merit giving a name to the rule or form; and (3) an argument that is an
instance of a fallacious rule of inference or of a fallacious argument form and
that is not itself valid. The criterion of satisfactory argument typically
taken as relevant in discussing formal fallacies is validity. In this regard,
it is important to observe that rules of inference and argument forms that are
not valid may have instances (which may be another rule or argument form, or
may be a specific argument) that are valid. Thus, whereas the argument form (i)
P, Q; therefore R (a form that every argument, including every valid argument,
consisting of two premises shares) is not valid, the argument form (ii),
obtained from (i) by substituting P&Q for R, is a valid instance of (i):
(ii) P, Q; therefore P&Q. Since (ii) is not invalid, (ii) is not a formal
fallacy though it is an instance of (i). Thus, some instances of formally
fallacious rules of inference or argument-forms may be valid and therefore not
be formal fallacies. Examples of formal fallacies follow below, presented
according to the system of logic appropriate to the level of description of the
fallacy. There are no standard names for some of the fallacies listed below.
Fallacies of sentential (propositional) logic. Affirming the consequent: If p
then q; q / , p. ‘If Richard had his nephews murdered, then Richard was an evil
man; Richard was an evil man. Therefore, Richard had his nephews murdered.’
Denying the antecedent: If p then q; not-p / , not-q. ‘If North was found
guilty by the courts, then North committed the crimes charged of him; North was
not found guilty by the courts. Therefore, North did not commit the crimes
charged of him.’ Commutation of conditionals: If p then q / , If q then p. ‘If
Reagan was a great leader, then so was Thatcher. Therefore, if Thatcher was a
great leader, then so was Reagan.” Improper transposition: If p then q / , If
not-p then not-q. ‘If the nations of the Middle East disarm, there will be
peace in the region. Therefore, if the nations of the Middle East do not
disarm, there will not be peace in the region.’ Improper disjunctive syllogism
(affirming one disjunct): p or q; p / ,, not-q. ‘Either John is an alderman or
a ward committeeman; John is an alderman. Therefore, John is not a ward
committeeman.’ (This rule of inference would be valid if ‘or’ were interpreted
exclusively, where ‘p or EXq’ is true if exactly one constituent is true and is
false otherwise. In standard systems of logic, however, ‘or’ is interpreted
inclusively.) Fallacies of syllogistic logic. Fallacies of distribution (where
M is the middle term, P is the major term, and S is the minor term).
Undistributed middle term: the middle term is not distributed in either premise
(roughly, nothing is said of all members of the class it designates), as in
form, grammatical formal fallacy 316 4065A-
AM 316 Some P are M ‘Some
politicians are crooks. Some M are S Some crooks are thieves. ,Some S are P.
,Some politicians are thieves.’ Illicit major (undistributed major term): the
major term is distributed in the conclusion but not in the major premise, as in
All M are P ‘All radicals are communists. No S are M No socialists are
radicals. ,Some S are ,Some socialists are not not P. communists.’ Illicit minor
(undistributed minor term): the minor term is distributed in the conclusion but
not in the minor premise, as in All P are M ‘All neo-Nazis are radicals. All M
are S All radicals are terrorists. ,All S are P. ,All terrorists are neoNazis.’
Fallacies of negation. Two negative premises (exclusive premises): the
syllogism has two negative premises, as in No M are P ‘No racist is just. Some
M are not S Some racists are not police. ,Some S are not P. ,Some police are
not just. Illicit negative/affirmative: the syllogism has a negative premise
(conclusion) but no negative conclusion (premise), as in All M are P ‘All liars
are deceivers. Some M are not S Some liars are not aldermen. ,Some S are P.
,Some aldermen are deceivers.’ and All P are M ‘All vampires are monsters. All
M are S All monsters are creatures. ,Some S are not P. ,Some creatures are not
vampires.’ Fallacy of existential import: the syllogism has two universal
premises and a particular conclusion, as in All P are M ‘All horses are
animals. No S are M No unicorns are animals. ,Some S are not P. ,Some unicorns
are not horses.’ A syllogism can commit more than one fallacy. For example, the
syllogism Some P are M Some M are S ,No S are P commits the fallacies of
undistributed middle, illicit minor, illicit major, and illicit
negative/affirmative. Fallacies of predicate logic. Illicit quantifier shift:
inferring from a universally quantified existential proposition to an
existentially quantified universal proposition, as in (Ex) (Dy) Fxy / , (Dy)
(Ex) Fxy ‘Everyone is irrational at some time (or other) /, At some time,
everyone is irrational.’ Some are/some are not (unwarranted contrast):
inferring from ‘Some S are P’ that ‘Some S are not P’ or inferring from ‘Some S
are not P’ that ‘Some S are P’, as in (Dx) (Sx & Px) / , (Dx) (Sx &
-Px) ‘Some people are left-handed / , Some people are not left-handed.’ Illicit
substitution of identicals: where f is an opaque (oblique) context and a and b
are singular terms, to infer from fa; a = b / , fb, as in ‘The Inspector
believes Hyde is Hyde; Hyde is Jekyll / , The Inspector believes Hyde is
Jekyll.’ EXISTENTIAL IMPORT, LOGICAL
FORM, MODAL LOGIC, SYLLOGISM. W.K.W. formalism, the view that mathematics
concerns manipulations of symbols according to prescribed structural rules. It
is cousin to nominalism, the older and more general metaphysical view that
denies the existence of all abstract objects and is often contrasted with
Platonism, which takes mathematics to be the study of a special class of
non-linguistic, non-mental objects, and intuitionism, which takes it to be the
study of certain mental constructions. In sophisticated versions, mathematical
activity can comprise the study of possible formal manipulations within a
system as well as the manipulations themselves, and the “symbols” need not be
regarded as either linguistic or concrete. Formalism is often associated with
the mathematician formalism formalism 317 4065A- AM 317
David Hilbert. But Hilbert held that the “finitary” part of mathematics,
including, for example, simple truths of arithmetic, describes indubitable
facts about real objects and that the “ideal” objects that feature elsewhere in
mathematics are introduced to facilitate research about the real objects.
Hilbert’s formalism is the view that the foundations of mathematics can be
secured by proving the consistency of formal systems to which mathematical
theories are reduced. Gödel’s two incompleteness theorems establish important
limitations on the success of such a project.
ABSTRACT ENTITY, AESTHETIC FORMALISM, HILBERT’s PROGRAM, MATHEMATICAL
INTUITIONISM, PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS. S.T.K. formalism, aesthetic.AESTHETIC
FORMALISM. formalism, ethical.ETHICS. formalism, jurisprudential.JURISPRUDENCE.
formalism, legal.JURISPRUDENCE. formalization, an abstract representation of a
theory that must satisfy requirements sharper than those imposed on the
structure of theories by the axiomatic-deductive method. That method can be
traced back to Euclid’s Elements. The crucial additional requirement is the regimentation
of inferential steps in proofs: not only do axioms have to be given in advance,
but the rules representing argumentative steps must also be taken from a
predetermined list. To avoid a regress in the definition of proof and to
achieve intersubjectivity on a minimal basis, the rules are to be “formal” or
“mechanical” and must take into account only the form of statements. Thus, to
exclude any ambiguity, a precise and effectively described language is needed
to formalize particular theories. The general kind of requirements was clear to
Aristotle and explicit in Leibniz; but it was only Frege who, in his
Begriffsschrift (1879), presented, in addition to an expressively rich language
with relations and quantifiers, an adequate logical calculus. Indeed, Frege’s
calculus, when restricted to the language of predicate logic, turned out to be
semantically complete. He provided for the first time the means to formalize
mathematical proofs. Frege pursued a clear philosophical aim, namely, to
recognize the “epistemological nature” of theorems. In the introduction to his
Grundgesetze der Arithmetik (1893), Frege wrote: “By insisting that the chains
of inference do not have any gaps we succeed in bringing to light every axiom,
assumption, hypothesis or whatever else you want to call it on which a proof
rests; in this way we obtain a basis for judging the epistemological nature of
the theorem.” The Fregean frame was used in the later development of
mathematical logic, in particular, in proof theory. Gödel established through
his incompleteness theorems fundamental limits of formalizations of particular
theories, like the system of Principia Mathematica or axiomatic set theories.
The general notion of formal theory emerged from the subsequent investigations
of Church and Turing clarifying the concept of ‘mechanical procedure’ or
‘algorithm.’ Only then was it possible to state and prove the incompleteness
theorems for all formal theories satisfying certain very basic representability
and derivability conditions. Gödel emphasized repeatedly that these results do
not establish “any bounds for the powers of human reason, but rather for the
potentialities of pure formalism in mathematics.” CHURCH’S THESIS, FREGE, GÖDEL’S INCOMPLETENESS
THEOREMS, PROOF THEORY. W.S. formalize, narrowly construed, to formulate a
subject as a theory in first-order predicate logic; broadly construed, to
describe the essentials of the subject in some formal language for which a
notion of consequence is defined. For Hilbert, formalizing mathematics requires
at least that there be finite means of checking purported proofs. FORMALIZATION, PROOF THEORY. S.T.K. formal
justice.JUSTICE. formal language, a language in which an expression’s
grammaticality and interpretation (if any) are determined by precisely defined
rules that appeal only to the form or shape of the symbols that constitute it
(rather than, for example, to the intention of the speaker). It is usually
understood that the rules are finite and effective (so that there is an
algorithm for determining whether an expression is a formula) and that the
grammatical expressions are uniquely readable, i.e., they are generated by the
rules in only one way. A paradigm example is the language of firstorder
predicate logic, deriving principally from the Begriffsschrift of Frege. The
grammatical formulas of this language can be delineated by an inductive
definition: (1) a capital letter ‘F’, ‘G’, or ‘H’, with or without a numerical
subscript, folformalism, aesthetic formal language 318 4065A- AM 318
lowed by a string of lowercase letters ‘a’, ‘b’, or ‘c’, with or without
numerical subscripts, is a formula; (2) if A is a formula, so is -A; (3) if A
and B are formulas, so are (A & B), (A P B), and (A 7 B); (4) if A is a
formula and v is a lowercase letter ‘x’, ‘y’, or ‘z’, with or without numerical
subscripts, then DvA' and EvA' are formulas where A' is obtained by replacing
one or more occurrences of some lowercase letter in A (together with its
subscripts if any) by v; (5) nothing is a formula unless it can be shown to be
one by finitely many applications of the clauses 1–4. The definition uses the
device of metalinguistic variables: clauses with ‘A’ and ‘B’ are to be regarded
as abbreviations of all the clauses that would result by replacing these letters
uniformly by names of expressions. It also uses several naming conventions: a
string of symbols is named by enclosing it within single quotes and also by
replacing each symbol in the string by its name; the symbols ‘7’, ‘(‘,’)’,
‘&’, ‘P’, ‘-’ are considered names of themselves. The interpretation of
predicate logic is spelled out by a similar inductive definition of truth in a
model. With appropriate conventions and stipulations, alternative definitions
of formulas can be given that make expressions like ‘(P 7 Q)’ the names of
formulas rather than formulas themselves. On this approach, formulas need not
be written symbols at all and form cannot be identified with shape in any
narrow sense. For Tarski, Carnap, and others a formal language also included
rules of “transformation” specifying when one expression can be regarded as a
consequence of others. Today it is more common to view the language and its
consequence relation as distinct. Formal languages are often contrasted with
natural languages, like English or Swahili. Richard Montague, however, has
tried to show that English is itself a formal language, whose rules of grammar
and interpretation are similar to – though much more complex than – predicate
logic. FORMAL LOGIC. S.T.K. formal
learnability theory, the study of human language learning through explicit
formal models typically employing artifical languages and simplified learning
strategies. The fundamental problem is how a learner is able to arrive at a
grammar of a language on the basis of a finite sample of presented sentences
(and perhaps other kinds of information as well). The seminal work is by E.
Gold (1967), who showed, roughly, that learnability of certain types of
grammars from the Chomsky hierarchy by an unbiased learner required the presentation
of ungrammatical strings, identified as such, along with grammatical strings.
Recent studies have concentrated on other types of grammar (e.g., generative
transformational grammars), modes of presentation, and assumptions about
learning strategies in an attempt to approximate the actual situation more
closely. GRAMMAR. R.E.W. formal logic,
the science of correct reasoning, going back to Aristotle’s Prior Analytics,
based upon the premise that the validity of an argument is a function of its
structure or logical form. The modern embodiment of formal logic is symbolic
(mathematical) logic. This is the study of valid inference in artificial,
precisely formulated languages, the grammatical structure of whose sentences or
well-formed formulas is intended to mirror, or be a regimentation of, the
logical forms of their natural language counterparts. These formal languages
can thus be viewed as (mathematical) models of fragments of natural language.
Like models generally, these models are idealizations, typically leaving out of
account such phenomena as vagueness, ambiguity, and tense. But the idea
underlying symbolic logic is that to the extent that they reflect certain
structural features of natural language arguments, the study of valid inference
in formal languages can yield insight into the workings of those arguments. The
standard course of study for anyone interested in symbolic logic begins with
the (classical) propositional calculus (sentential calculus), or PC. Here one
constructs a theory of valid inference for a formal language built up from a
stock of propositional variables (sentence letters) and an expressively
complete set of connectives. In the propositional calculus, one is therefore
concerned with arguments whose validity turns upon the presence of (two-valued)
truth-functional sentence-forming operators on sentences such as (classical)
negation, conjunction, disjunction, and the like. The next step is the
predicate calculus (lower functional calculus, first-order logic, elementary
quantification theory), the study of valid inference in first-order languages.
These are languages built up from an expressively complete set of connectives,
first-order universal or existential quantifiers, individual variables, names,
predicates (relational symbols), and perhaps function symbols. Further, and
more specialized, work in symbolic logic might involve looking at fragments of
the language of the propositional or predicate calculus, changing the semantics
that the language is standardly given (e.g., by allowing formal learnability
theory formal logic 319 4065A- AM 319 truth-value gaps or more than two
truth-values), further embellishing the language (e.g., by adding modal or other
non-truth-functional connectives, or higher-order quantifiers), or liberalizing
the grammar or syntax of the language (e.g., by permitting infinitely long
well-formed formulas). In some of these cases, of course, symbolic logic
remains only marginally connected with natural language arguments as the
interest shades off into one in formal languages for their own sake, a mark of
the most advanced work being done in formal logic today. DEONTIC LOGIC, EPISTEMIC LOGIC, FREE LOGIC,
INFINITARY LOGIC, MANY-VALUED LOGIC, MATHEMATICAL INTUITIONISM, MODAL LOGIC,
RELEVANCE LOGIC, SECONDORDER LOGIC. G.F.S. formal mode.METALANGUAGE. formal
reality.REALITY. formal semantics, the study of the interpretations of formal
languages. A formal language can be defined apart from any interpretation of
it. This is done by specifying a set of its symbols and a set of formation
rules that determine which strings of symbols are grammatical or well formed.
When rules of inference (transformation rules) are added and/or certain
sentences are designated as axioms a logical system (also known as a logistic
system) is formed. An interpretation of a formal language is (roughly) an
assignment of meanings to its symbols and truth conditions to its sentences.
Typically a distinction is made between a standard interpretation of a formal
language and a non-standard interpretation. Consider a formal language in which
arithmetic is formulable. In addition to the symbols of logic (variables,
quantifiers, brackets, and connectives), this language will contain ‘0’, ‘!’,
‘•’, and ‘s’. A standard interpretation of it assigns the set of natural
numbers as the domain of discourse, zero to ‘0’, addition to ‘!’,
multiplication to ‘•’, and the successor function to ‘s’. Other standard
interpretations are isomorphic to the one just given. In particular, standard
interpretations are numeral-complete in that they correlate the numerals
one-to-one with the domain elements. A result due to Gödel and Rosser is that
there are universal quantifications (x)A(x) that are not deducible from the
Peano axioms (if those axioms are consistent) even though each A(n) is
provable. The Peano axioms (if consistent) are true on each standard
interpretation. Thus each A(n) is true on such an interpretation. Thus (x)A(x)
is true on such an interpretation since a standard interpretation is
numeral-complete. However, there are non-standard interpretations that do not
correlate the numerals one-to-one with domain elements. On some of these
interpretations each A(n) is true but (x)A(x) is false. In constructing and
interpreting a formal language we use a language already known to us, say,
English. English then becomes our metalanguage, which we use to talk about the
formal language, which is our object language. Theorems proven within the
object language must be distinguished from those proven in the metalanguage.
The latter are metatheorems. One goal of a semantical theory of a formal
language is to characterize the consequence relation as expressed in that
language and prove semantical metatheorems about that relation. A sentence S is
said to be a consequence of a set of sentences K provided S is true on every
interpretation on which each sentence in K is true. This notion has to be kept
distinct from the notion of deduction. The latter concept can be defined only
by reference to a logical system associated with a formal language.
Consequence, however, can be characterized independently of a logical system,
as was just done. DEDUCTION, LOGICAL
SYNTAX, METALANGUAGE, PROOF THEORY, TRANSFORMATION RULE. C.S. formal
sign.SEMIOSIS. formation rule.WELL-FORMED FORMULA. form of life.WITTGENSTEIN.
Forms, theory of.PLATO. formula.WELL-FORMED FORMULA. formula, closed.OPEN
FORMULA, WELL-FORMED FORMULA. formula, open.OPEN FORMULA, WELL-FORMED FORMULA.
Foucault, Michel (1926–84), French philosopher and historian of thought. Foucault’s
earliest writings (e.g., Maladie mentale et personnalité [“Mental Illness and
Personality”], 1954) focused on psychology and developed within the frameworks
of Marxism and existential phenomenology. He soon moved beyond these
frameworks, in directions suggested by two fundamental influences: formal mode
Foucault, Michel 320 4065A- AM 320 history and philosophy of science, as
practiced by Bachelard and (especially) Canguilhem, and the modernist
literature of, e.g., Raymond Roussel, Bataille, and Maurice Blanchot. In
studies of psychiatry (Histoire de la folie [“History of Madness in the
Classical Age”], 1961), clinical medicine (The Birth of the Clinic, 1963), and
the social sciences (The Order of Things, 1966), Foucault developed an approach
to intellectual history, “the archaeology of knowledge,” that treated systems
of thought as “discursive formations” independent of the beliefs and intentions
of individual thinkers. Like Canguilhem’s history of science and like modernist
literature, Foucault’s archaeology displaced the human subject from the central
role it played in the humanism dominant in our culture since Kant. He reflected
on the historical and philosophical significance of his archaeological method
in The Archaeology of Knowledge (1969). Foucault recognized that archaeology
provided no account of transitions from one system to another. Accordingly, he
introduced a “genealogical” approach, which does not replace archaeology but
goes beyond it to explain changes in systems of discourse by connecting them to
changes in the non-discursive practices of social power structures. Foucault’s
genealogy admitted the standard economic, social, and political causes but, in
a non-standard, Nietzschean vein, refused any unified teleological explanatory
scheme (e.g., Whig or Marxist histories). New systems of thought are seen as
contingent products of many small, unrelated causes, not fulfillments of grand
historical designs. Foucault’s geneaological studies emphasize the essential
connection of knowledge and power. Bodies of knowledge are not autonomous
intellectual structures that happen to be employed as Baconian instruments of
power. Rather, precisely as bodies of knowledge, they are tied (but not
reducible) to systems of social control. This essential connection of power and
knowledge reflects Foucault’s later view that power is not merely repressive
but a creative, if always dangerous, source of positive values. Discipline and
Punish (1975) showed how prisons constitute criminals as objects of disciplinary
knowledge. The first volume of the History of Sexuality (1976) sketched a
project for seeing how, through modern biological and psychological sciences of
sexuality, individuals are controlled by their own knowledge as
self-scrutinizing and self-forming subjects. The second volume was projected as
a study of the origins of the modern notion of a subject in practices of
Christian confession. Foucault wrote such a study (The Confessions of the
Flesh) but did not publish it because he decided that a proper understanding of
the Christian development required a comparison with ancient conceptions of the
ethical self. This led to two volumes (1984) on Greek and Roman sexuality: The
Use of Pleasure and The Care of the Self. These final writings make explicit
the ethical project that in fact informs all of Foucault’s work: the liberation
of human beings from contingent conceptual constraints masked as unsurpassable
a priori limits and the adumbration of alternative forms of existence. BACHELARD, CANGUILHEM, NIETZSCHE. G.G.
foundationalism, the view that knowledge and epistemic (knowledge-relevant)
justification have a two-tier structure: some instances of knowledge and
justification are non-inferential, or foundational; and all other instances
thereof are inferential, or non-foundational, in that they derive ultimately
from foundational knowledge or justification. This structural view originates
in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics (at least regarding knowledge), receives an
extreme formulation in Descartes’s Meditations, and flourishes, with varying
details, in the works of such twentieth-century philosophers as Russell, C. I.
Lewis, and Chisholm. Versions of foundationalism differ on two main projects:
(a) the precise explanation of the nature of non-inferential, or foundational,
knowledge and justification, and (b) the specific explanation of how
foundational knowledge and justification can be transmitted to non-foundational
beliefs. Foundationalism allows for differences on these projects, since it is
essentially a view about the structure of knowledge and epistemic
justification. The question whether knowledge has foundations is essentially
the question whether the sort of justification pertinent to knowledge has a
twotier structure. Some philosophers have construed the former question as
asking whether knowledge depends on beliefs that are certain in some sense
(e.g., indubitable or infallible). This construal bears, however, on only one
species of foundationalism: radical foundationalism. Such foundationalism,
represented primarily by Descartes, requires that foundational beliefs be
certain and able to guarantee the certainty of the non-foundational beliefs
they support. Radical foundationalism is currently unpopular for two main
reasons. First, very few, if any, of our perceptual beliefs are certain (i.e.,
indubitable); and, second, those of our beliefs that might be
candifoundationalism foundationalism 321 4065A-
AM 321 dates for certainty (e.g.,
the belief that I am thinking) lack sufficient substance to guarantee the
certainty of our rich, highly inferential knowledge of the external world
(e.g., our knowledge of physics, chemistry, and biology). Contemporary
foundationalists typically endorse modest foundationalism, the view that
non-inferentially justified, foundational beliefs need not possess or provide
certainty and need not deductively support justified non-foundational beliefs.
Foundational beliefs (or statements) are often called basic beliefs (or
statements), but the precise understanding of ‘basic’ here is controversial
among foundationalists. Foundationalists agree, however, in their general
understanding of non-inferentially justified, foundational beliefs as beliefs
whose justification does not derive from other beliefs, although they leave
open whether the causal basis of foundational beliefs includes other beliefs.
(Epistemic justification comes in degrees, but for simplicity we can restrict
discussion to justification sufficient for satisfaction of the justification
condition for knowledge; we can also restrict discussion to what it takes for a
belief to have justification, omitting issues of what it takes to show that a
belief has it.) Three prominent accounts of non-inferential justification are
available to modest foundationalists: (a) self-justification, (b) justification
by non-belief, non-propositional experiences, and (c) justification by a
non-belief reliable origin of a belief. Proponents of self-justification
(including, at one time, Ducasse and Chisholm) contend that foundational
beliefs can justify themselves, with no evidential support elsewhere.
Proponents of foundational justification by non-belief experiences shun literal
self-justification; they hold, following C. I. Lewis, that foundational
perceptual beliefs can be justified by non-belief sensory or perceptual
experiences (e.g., seeming to see a dictionary) that make true, are best
explained by, or otherwise support, those beliefs (e.g., the belief that there
is, or at least appears to be, a dictionary here). Proponents of foundational justification
by reliable origins find the basis of non-inferential justification in
belief-forming processes (e.g., perception, memory, introspection) that are
truth-conducive, i.e., that tend to produce true rather than false beliefs.
This view thus appeals to the reliability of a belief’s nonbelief origin,
whereas the previous view appeals to the particular sensory or perceptual
experiences that correspond to (e.g., make true or are best explained by) a
foundational belief. Despite disagreements over the basis of foundational
justification, modest foundationalists typically agree that foundational
justification is characterized by defeasibility, i.e., can be defeated,
undermined, or overridden by a certain sort of expansion of one’s evidence or
justified beliefs. For instance, your belief that there is a blue dictionary
before you could lose its justification (e.g., the justification from your
current perceptual experiences) if you acquired new evidence that there is a
blue light shining on the dictionary before you. Foundational justification,
therefore, can vary over time if accompanied by relevant changes in one’s
perceptual evidence. It does not follow, however, that foundational
justification positively depends, i.e., is based, on grounds for denying that
there are defeaters. The relevant dependence can be regarded as negative in
that there need only be an absence of genuine defeaters. Critics of
foundationalism sometimes neglect that latter distinction regarding epistemic
dependence. The second big task for foundationalists is to explain how
justification transmits from foundational beliefs to inferentially justified,
non-foundational beliefs. Radical foundationalists insist, for such
transmission, on entailment relations that guarantee the truth or the certainty
of nonfoundational beliefs. Modest foundationalists are more flexible, allowing
for merely probabilistic inferential connections that transmit justification.
For instance, a modest foundationalist can appeal to explanatory inferential
connections, as when a foundational belief (e.g., I seem to feel wet) is best
explained for a person by a particular physical-object belief (e.g., the belief
that the air conditioner overhead is leaking on me). Various other forms of
probabilistic inference are available to modest foundationalists; and nothing
in principle requires that they restrict foundational beliefs to what one
“seems” to sense or to perceive. The traditional motivation for foundationalism
comes largely from an eliminative regress argument, outlined originally
(regarding knowledge) in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics. The argument, in
shortest form, is that foundationalism is a correct account of the structure of
justification since the alternative accounts all fail. Inferential
justification is justification wherein one belief, B1, is justified on the
basis of another belief, B2. How, if at all, is B2, the supporting belief,
itself justified? Obviously, Aristotle suggests, we cannot have a circle here,
where B2 is justified by B1; nor can we allow the chain of support to extend
endlessly, with no ultimate basis for justification. We cannot, moreover, allow
B2 to remain unjustified, foundationalism foundationalism 322 4065A- AM 322
lest it lack what it takes to support B1. If this is right, the structure of
justification does not involve circles, endless regresses, or unjustified
starter-beliefs. That is, this structure is evidently foundationalist. This is,
in skeletal form, the regress argument for foundationalism. Given appropriate
flesh, and due attention to skepticism about justification, this argument poses
a serious challenge to non-foundationalist accounts of the structure of
epistemic justification, such as epistemic coherentism. More significantly,
foundationalism will then show forth as one of the most compelling accounts of
the structure of knowledge and justification. This explains, at least in part,
why foundationalism has been very prominent historically and is still widely
held in contemporary epistemology.
COHERENTISM, EPISTEMOLOGY, JUSTIFICATION. P.K.M. foundation axiom.SET
THEORY. Four Books, a group of Confucian texts including the Ta-hsüeh (Great
Learning), Chung-Yung (Doctrine of the Mean), Lun Yü (Analects), and Meng Tzu
(Book of Mencius), the latter two containing respectively the teachings of
Confucius (sixth– fifth century B.C.) and Mencius (fourth century B.C.), and
the former two being chapters from the Li-Chi (Book of Rites). Chu Hsi
(1130–1200) selected the texts as basic ones for Confucian education, and wrote
influential commentaries on them. The texts served as the basis of civil
service examinations from 1313 to 1905; as a result, they exerted great
influence both on the development of Confucian thought and on Chinese life in
general. K.-l.S. four causes.ARISTOTLE. four elements.EMPEDOCLES. four
humors.GALEN. Fourier, François-Marie-Charles (1772–1837), French social
theorist and radical critic, often called a utopian socialist. His main works
were The Theory of Universal Unity (1822) and The New Industrial and Societal World
(1829). He argued that since each person has, not an integral soul but only a
partial one, personal integrity is possible only in unity with others. Fourier
thought that all existing societies were antagonistic. (Following Edenism, he
believed societies developed through stages of savagery, patriarchalism,
barbarianism, and civilization.) He believed this antagonism could be
transcended only in Harmony. It would be based on twelve kinds of passions.
(Five were sensual, four affective, and three distributive; and these in turn
encouraged the passion for unity.) The basic social unit would be a phalanx
containing 300– 400 families (about 1,600–1,800 people) of scientifically
blended characters. As a place of production but also of maximal satisfaction of
the passions of every member, Harmony should make labor attractive and
pleasurable. The main occupations of its members should be gastronomy, opera,
and horticulture. It should also establish a new world of love (a form of
polygamy) where men and women would be equal in rights. Fourier believed that
phalanxes would attract members of all other social systems, even the less
civilized, and bring about this new world system. Fourier’s vision of
cooperation (both in theory and experimental practice) influenced some
anarchists, syndicalists, and the cooperationist movement. His radical social
critique was important for the development of political and social thought in
France, Europe, and North America.
POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. G.Fl. fourth condition.EPISTEMOLOGY. fourth
condition problem.EPISTEMOLOGY. frame.COGNITIVE SCIENCE. Frankena, William K.
(1908–94), American moral philosopher who wrote a series of influential
articles and a text, Ethics (1963), which was translated into eight languages
and remains in use today. Frankena taught at the University of Michigan
(1937–78), where he and his colleagues Charles Stevenson (1908–79), a leading
noncognitivist, and Richard Brandt, an important ethical naturalist, formed for
many years one of the most formidable faculties in moral philosophy in the
world. Frankena was known for analytical rigor and sharp insight, qualities
already evident in his first essay, “The Naturalistic Fallacy” (1939), which
refuted Moore’s influential claim that ethical naturalism (or any other reductionist
ethical theory) could be convicted of logical error. At best, Frankena showed,
reductionists could be said to conflate or misidentify ethical properties with
properties of some other kind. Even put this way, such assertions were
question-begging, Frankena argued. Where Moore claimed to see propfoundation
axiom Frankena, William K. 323 4065A-
AM 323 erties of two different
kinds, naturalists and other reductionists claimed to be able to see only one.
Many of Frankena’s most important papers concerned similarly fundamental issues
about value and normative judgment. “Obligation and Motivation in Recent Moral
Philosophy” (1958), for example, is a classic treatment of the debate between
internalism, which holds that motivation is essential to obligation or to the
belief or perception that one is obligated, and externalism, which holds that
motivation is only contingently related to these. In addition to metaethics,
Frankena’s published works ranged broadly over normative ethical theory, virtue
ethics, moral psychology, religious ethics, moral education, and the philosophy
of education. Although relatively few of his works were devoted exclusively to
the area, Frankena was also known as the preeminent historian of ethics of his
day. More usually, Frankena used the history of ethics as a framework within
which to discuss issues of perennial interest. It was, however, for Ethics, one
of the most widely used and frequently cited philosophical ethics textbooks of
the twentieth century, that Frankena was perhaps best known. Ethics continues
to provide an unparalleled introduction to the subject, as useful in a first
undergraduate course as it is to graduate students and professional
philosophers looking for perspicuous ways to frame issues and categorize alternative
solutions. For example, when in the 1970s philosophers came to systematically
investigate normative ethical theories, it was Frankena’s distinction in Ethics
between deontological and teleological theories to which they referred. ETHICS, MORAL PSYCHOLOGY, MOTIVATIONAL
INTERNALISM, NATURALISM. S.L.D. Frankfurt School, a group of philosophers,
cultural critics, and social scientists associated with the Institute for
Social Research, which was founded in Frankfurt in 1929. Its prominent members
included, among others, the philosophers Horkheimer, Adorno, and Marcuse, as
well as the psychoanalyst Erich Fromm (1900–80) and the literary critic Walter
Benjamin (1892– 1940). Habermas is the leading representative of its second
generation. The Frankfurt School is less known for particular theories or
doctrines than for its program of a “critical theory of society.” Critical
theory represents a sophisticated effort to continue Marx’s transformation of
moral philosophy into social and political critique, while rejecting orthodox
Marxism as a dogma. Critical theory is primarily a way of doing philosophy,
integrating the normative aspects of philosophical reflection with the
explanatory achievements of the social sciences. The ultimate goal of its
program is to link theory and practice, to provide insight, and to empower
subjects to change their oppressive circumstances and achieve human
emancipation, a rational society that satisfies human needs and powers. The
first generation of the Frankfurt School went through three phases of
development. The first, lasting from the beginning of the Institute until the
end of the 1930s, can be called “interdisciplinary historical materialism” and
is best represented in Horkheimer’s programmatic writings. Horkheimer argued
that a revised version of historical materialism could organize the results of
social research and give it a critical perspective. The second, “critical
theory” phase saw the abandonment of Marxism for a more generalized notion of
critique. However, with the near-victory of the Nazis in the early 1940s,
Horkheimer and Adorno entered the third phase of the School, “the critique of
instrumental reason.” In their Dialectic of Enlightenment (1941) as well as in
Marcuse’s One Dimensional Man (1964), the process of instrumentally dominating
nature leads to dehumanization and the domination of human beings. In their
writings after World War II, Adorno and Horkheimer became increasingly
pessimistic, seeing around them a “totally administered society” and a
manipulated, commodity culture. Horkheimer’s most important essays are from the
first phase and focus on the relation of philosophy and social science. Besides
providing a clear definition and program for critical social science, he
proposes that the normative orientation of philosophy should be combined with
the empirical research in the social sciences. This metaphilosophical
orientation distinguishes a “critical,” as opposed to “traditional,” theory.
For example, such a program demands rethinking the relation of epistemology to
the sociology of science. A critical theory seeks to show how the norm of truth
is historical and practical, without falling into the skepticism or relativism
of traditional sociologies of knowledge such as Mannheim’s. Adorno’s major
writings belong primarily to the second and third phases of the development of
the Frankfurt School. As the possibilities for criticism appeared to him
increasingly narrow, Adorno sought to discover them in aesthetic experience and
the mimetic relation to nature. Adorno’s approach was motivated by his view
Frankfurt School Frankfurt School 324 4065A-
AM 324 that modern society is a
“false totality.” His diagnosis of the causes traced this trend back to the
spread of a one-sided, instrumental reason, based on the domination of nature
and other human beings. For this reason, he sought a noninstrumental and
non-dominating relation to nature and to others, and found it in diverse and
fragmentary experiences. Primarily, it is art that preserves this possibility
in contemporary society, since in art there is a possibility of mimesis, or the
“non-identical” relation to the object. Adorno’s influential attempt to avoid
“the logic of identity” gives his posthumous Aesthetic Theory (1970) and other
later works a paradoxical character. It was in reaction to the third phase that
the second generation of the Frankfurt School recast the idea of a critical
theory. Habermas argued for a new emphasis on normative foundations as well as
a return to an interdisciplinary research program in the social sciences. After
first developing such a foundation in a theory of cognitive interests
(technical, practical, and emancipatory), Habermas turned to a theory of the
unavoidable presuppositions of communicative action and an ethics of discourse.
The potential for emancipatory change lies in communicative, or discursive,
rationality and practices that embody it, such as the democratic public sphere.
Habermas’s analysis of communication seeks to provide norms for non-dominating
relations to others and a broader notion of reason.
ADORNO, CONTINENTAL
PHILOSOPHY, CRITICAL THEORY, MARXISM, PHILOSOPHY OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES,
PRAXIS, WEBER. J.Bo. Frankfurt-style case.FREE WILL PROBLEM. free
beauty.BEAUTY. freedom, negative.POSITIVE AND NEGATIVE FREEDOM. freedom,
positive.POSITIVE AND NEGATIVE FREEDOM. freedom, practical.FREE WILL PROBLEM.
free logic, a system of quantification theory, with or without identity, that
allows for non-denoting singular terms. In classical quantification theory, all
singular terms (free variables and individual constants) are assigned a
denotation in all models. But this condition appears counterintuitive when such
systems are applied to natural language, where many singular terms seem to be
non-denoting (‘Pegasus’, ‘Sherlock Holmes’, and the like). Various solutions of
this problem have been proposed, ranging from Frege’s chosen object theory
(assign an arbitrary denotation to each non-denoting singular term) to
Russell’s description theory (deny singular term status to most expressions
used as such in natural language, and eliminate them from the “logical form” of
that language) to a weakening of the quantifiers’ “existential import,” which
allows for denotations to be possible, but not necessarily actual, objects. All
these solutions preserve the structure of classical quantification theory and
make adjustments at the level of application. Free logic is a more radical
solution: it allows for legitimate singular terms to be denotationless,
maintains the quantifiers’ existential import, but modifies both the proof
theory and the semantics of first-order logic. Within proof theory, the main
modification consists of eliminating the rule of existential generalization,
which allows one to infer ‘There exists a flying horse’ from ‘Pegasus is a
flying horse’. Within semantics, the main problem is giving truth conditions
for sentences containing non-denoting singular terms, and there are various
ways of accomplishing this. Conventional semantics assigns truth-values to
atomic sentences containing non-denoting singular terms by convention, and then
determines the truth-values of complex sentences as usual. Outer domain
semantics divides the domain of interpretation into an inner and an outer part,
using the inner part as the range of quantifiers and the outer part to provide
for “denotations” for non-denoting singular terms (which are then not literally
denotationless, but rather left without an existing denotation).
Supervaluational semantics, when considering a sentence A, assigns all possible
combinations of truth-values to the atomic components of A containing
non-denoting singular terms, evaluates A on the basis of each of those
combinations, and then assigns to A the logical product of all such
evaluations. (Thus both ‘Pegasus flies’ and ‘Pegasus does not fly’ turn out
truth-valueless, but ‘Pegasus flies or Pegasus does not fly’ turns out true
since whatever truth-value is assigned to its atomic component ‘Pegasus flies’
the truth-value for the whole sentence is true.) A free logic is inclusive if
it allows for the possibility that the range of quantifiers be empty (that
there exists nothing at all); it is exclusive otherwise. FORMAL SEMANTICS, PROOF THEORY,
QUANTIFICATION. E.Ben. Frankfurt-style case free logic 325 4065A- AM 325
free rider, a person who benefits from a social arrangement without bearing an
appropriate share of the burdens of maintaining that arrangement, e.g. one who
benefits from government services without paying one’s taxes that support them.
The arrangements from which a free rider benefits may be either formal or
informal. Cooperative arrangements that permit free riders are likely to be
unstable; parties to the arrangement are unlikely to continue to bear the
burdens of maintaining it if others are able to benefit without doing their
part. As a result, it is common for cooperative arrangements to include
mechanisms to discourage free riders, e.g. legal punishment, or in cases of
informal conventions the mere disapproval of one’s peers. It is a matter of
some controversy as to whether it is always morally wrong to benefit from an
arrangement without contributing to its maintenance. JUSTICE, SOCIAL CHOICE THEORY,
UTILITARIANISM. W.T. free variable.VARIABLE. free will defense.PHILOSOPHY OF
RELIGION. free will problem, the problem of the nature of free agency and its
relation to the origins and conditions of responsible behavior. For those who
contrast ‘free’ with ‘determined’, a central question is whether humans are
free in what they do or determined by external events beyond their control. A
related concern is whether an agent’s responsibility for an action requires
that the agent, the act, or the relevant decision be free. This, in turn,
directs attention to action, motivation, deliberation, choice, and intention, and
to the exact sense, if any, in which our actions are under our control. Use of
‘free will’ is a matter of traditional nomenclature; it is debated whether
freedom is properly ascribed to the will or the agent, or to actions, choices,
deliberations, etc. Controversy over conditions of responsible behavior forms
the predominant historical and conceptual background of the free will problem.
Most who ascribe moral responsibility acknowledge some sense in which agents
must be free in acting as they do; we are not responsible for what we were
forced to do or were unable to avoid no matter how hard we tried. But there are
differing accounts of moral responsibility and disagreements about the nature
and extent of such practical freedom (a notion also important in Kant).
Accordingly, the free will problem centers on these questions: Does moral
responsibility require any sort of practical freedom? If so, what sort? Are
people practically free? Is practical freedom consistent with the antecedent
determination of actions, thoughts, and character? There is vivid debate about
this last question. Consider a woman deliberating about whom to vote for. From
her first-person perspective, she feels free to vote for any candidate and is
convinced that the selection is up to her regardless of prior influences. But
viewing her eventual behavior as a segment of larger natural and historical
processes, many would argue that there are underlying causes determining her
choice. With this contrast of intuitions, any attempt to decide whether the
voter is free depends on the precise meanings associated with terms like
‘free’, ‘determine’, and ‘up to her’. One thing (event, situation) determines
another if the latter is a consequence of it, or necessitated by it, e.g., the
voter’s hand movements by her intention. As usually understood, determinism
holds that whatever happens is determined by antecedent conditions, where
determination is standardly conceived as causation by antecedent events and
circumstances. So construed, determinism implies that at any time the future is
already fixed and unique, with no possibility of alternative development.
Logical versions of determinism declare each future event to be determined by
what is already true, specifically, by the truth that it will occur then.
Typical theological variants accept the predestination of all circumstances and
events inasmuch as a divine being knows in advance (or even from eternity) that
they will obtain. Two elements are common to most interpretations of ‘free’.
First, freedom requires an absence of determination or certain sorts of
determination, and second, one acts and chooses freely only if these endeavors
are, properly speaking, one’s own. From here, accounts diverge. Some take
freedom (liberty) of indifference or the contingency of alternative courses of
action to be critical. Thus, for the woman deliberating about which candidate
to select, each choice is an open alternative inasmuch as it is possible but
not yet necessitated. Indifference is also construed as motivational equilibrium,
a condition some find essential to the idea that a free choice must be
rational. Others focus on freedom (liberty) of spontaneity, where the voter is
free if she votes as she chooses or desires, a reading that reflects the
popular equation of freedom with “doing what you want.” Associated with both
analyses is a third by which the woman acts freely if she exercises her
control, implying responsiveness to free rider free will problem 326
4065A- AM 326 intent as well as both abilities to
perform an act and to refrain. A fourth view identifies freedom with autonomy,
the voter being autonomous to the extent that her selection is self-determined,
e.g., by her character, deeper self, higher values, or informed reason. Though
distinct, these conceptions are not incompatible, and many accounts of
practical freedom include elements of each. Determinism poses problems if
practical freedom requires contingency (alternate possibilities of action).
Incompatibilism maintains that determinism precludes freedom, though
incompatibilists differ whether everything is determined. Those who accept
determinism thereby endorse hard determinism (associated with eighteenthcentury
thinkers like d’Holbach and, recently, certain behaviorists), according to
which freedom is an illusion since behavior is brought about by environmental
and genetic factors. Some hard determinists also deny the existence of moral
responsibility. At the opposite extreme, metaphysical libertarianism asserts
that people are free and responsible and, a fortiori, that the past does not
determine a unique future – a position some find enhanced by developments in
quantum physics. Among adherents of this sort of incompatibilism are those who
advocate a freedom of indifference by describing responsible choices as those
that are undetermined by antecedent circumstances (Epicureans). To rebut the
charge that choices, so construed, are random and not really one’s “own,” it
has been suggested that several elements, including an agent’s reasons, delimit
the range of possibilities and influence choices without necessitating them (a
view held by Leibniz and, recently, by Robert Kane). Libertarians who espouse
agency causation, on the other hand, blend contingency with autonomy in
characterizing a free choice as one that is determined by the agent who, in
turn, is not caused to make it (a view found in Carneades and Reid). Unwilling
to abandon practical freedom yet unable to understand how a lack of
determination could be either necessary or desirable for responsibility, many
philosophers take practical freedom and responsibility to be consistent with
determinism, thereby endorsing compatibilism. Those who also accept determinism
advocate what James called soft determinism. Its supporters include some who
identify freedom with autonomy (the Stoics, Spinoza) and others who champion
freedom of spontaneity (Hobbes, Locke, Hume). The latter speak of liberty as
the power of doing or refraining from an action according to what one wills, so
that by choosing otherwise one would have done otherwise. An agent fails to
have liberty when constrained, that is, when either prevented from acting as
one chooses or compelled to act in a manner contrary to what one wills.
Extending this model, liberty is also diminished when one is caused to act in a
way one would not otherwise prefer, either to avoid a greater danger (coercion)
or because there is deliberate interference with the envisioning of
alternatives (manipulation). Compatibilists have shown considerable ingenuity
in responding to criticisms that they have ignored freedom of choice or the
need for open alternatives. Some apply the spontaneity, control, or autonomy
models to decisions, so that the voter chooses freely if her decision accords
with her desires, is under her control, or conforms to her higher values,
deeper character, or informed reason. Others challenge the idea that
responsibility requires alternative possibilities of action. The so-called
Frankfurt-style cases (developed by Harry G. Frankfurt) are situations where an
agent acts in accord with his desires and choices, but because of the presence
of a counterfactual intervener – a mechanism that would have prevented the
agent from doing any alternative action had he shown signs of acting
differently – the agent could not have done otherwise. Frankfurt’s intuition is
that the agent is as responsible as he would have been if there were no
intervener, and thus that responsible action does not require alternative
possibilities. Critics have challenged the details of the Frankfurt-style cases
in attempting to undermine the appeal of the intuition. A different
compatibilist tactic recognizes the need for open alternatives and employs
versions of the indifference model in describing practical freedom. Choices are
free if they are contingent relative to certain subsets of circumstances, e.g.
those the agent is or claims to be cognizant of, with the openness of
alternatives grounded in what one can choose “for all one knows.” Opponents of
compatibilism charge that since these refinements leave agents subject to
external determination, even by hidden controllers, compatibilism continues to
face an insurmountable challenge. Their objections are sometimes summarized by
the consequence argument (so called by Peter van Inwagen, who has prominently
defended it): if everything were determined by factors beyond one’s control,
then one’s acts, choices, and character would also be beyond one’s control, and
consequently, agents would never be free and there would be nothing free will
problem free will problem 327 4065A-
AM 327 for which they are
responsible. Such reasoning usually employs principles asserting the closure of
the practical modalities (ability, control, avoidability, inevitability, etc.)
under consequence relations. However, there is a reason to suppose that the
sort of ability and control required by responsibility involve the agent’s
sense of what can be accomplished. Since cognitive states are typically not
closed under consequence, the closure principles underlying the consequence
argument are disputable.
ACTION THEORY, CLOSURE,
DETERMINISM, DIMINISHED CAPACITY, MIDDLE KNOWLEDGE, RESPONSIBILITY. T.K. Frege,
Gottlob (1848–1925), German mathematician and philosopher. A founder of modern
mathematical logic, an advocate of logicism, and a major source of
twentieth-century analytic philosophy, he directly influenced Russell,
Wittgenstein, and Carnap. Frege’s distinction between the sense and the
reference of linguistic expressions continues to be debated. His first
publication in logic was his strikingly original 1879 Begriffsschrift
(Concept-notation). Here he devised a formal language whose central innovation
is the quantifier-variable notation to express generality; he set forth in this
language a version of second-order quantificational logic that he used to
develop a logical definition of the ancestral of a relation. Frege invented his
Begriffsschrift in order to circumvent drawbacks of the use of colloquial
language to state proofs. Colloquial language is irregular, unperspicuous, and
ambiguous in its expression of logical relationships. Moreover, logically
crucial features of the content of statements may remain tacit and unspoken. It
is thus impossible to determine exhaustively the premises on which the
conclusion of any proof conducted within ordinary language depends. Frege’s
Begriffsschrift is to force the explicit statement of the logically relevant
features of any assertion. Proofs in the system are limited to what can be
obtained from a body of evidently true logical axioms by means of a small
number of truth-preserving notational manipulations (inference rules). Here is
the first hallmark of Frege’s view of logic: his formulation of logic as a
formal system and the ideal of explicitness and rigor that this presentation subserves.
Although the formal exactitude with which he formulates logic makes possible
the metamathematical investigation of formalized theories, he showed almost no
interest in metamathematical questions. He intended the Begriffsschrift to be
used. How though does Frege conceive of the subject matter of logic? His
orientation in logic is shaped by his anti-psychologism, his conviction that
psychology has nothing to do with logic. He took his notation to be a
full-fledged language in its own right. The logical axioms do not mention
objects or properties whose investigation pertains to some special science; and
Frege’s quantifiers are unrestricted. Laws of logic are, as he says, the laws
of truth, and these are the most general truths. He envisioned the supplementation
of the logical vocabulary of the Begriffsschrift with the basic vocabulary of
the special sciences. In this way the Begriffsschrift affords a framework for
the completely rigorous deductive development of any science whatsoever. This
resolutely nonpsychological universalist view of logic as the most general
science is the second hallmark of Frege’s view of logic. This universalist view
distinguishes his approach sharply from the coeval algebra of logic approach of
George Boole and Ernst Schröder. Wittgenstein, both in the Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus (1921) and in later writings, is very critical of Frege’s
universalist view. Logical positivism – most notably Carnap in The Logical
Syntax of Language (1934) – rejected it as well. Frege’s universalist view is
also distinct from more contemporary views. With his view of quantifiers as
intrinsically unrestricted, he saw little point in talking of varying
interpretations of a language, believing that such talk is a confused way of
getting at what is properly said by means of second-order generalizations. In
particular, the semantical conception of logical consequences that becomes
prominent in logic after Kurt Gödel’s and Tarski’s work is foreign to Frege.
Frege’s work in logic was prompted by an inquiry after the ultimate foundation
for arithmetic truths. He criticized J. S. Mill’s empiricist attempt to ground
knowledge of the arithmetic of the positive integers inductively in our
manipulations of small collections of things. He also rejected crudely formalist
views that take pure mathematics to be a sort of notational game. In contrast
to these views and Kant’s, he hoped to use his Begriffsschrift to define
explicitly the basic notions of arithmetic in logical terms and to deduce the
basic principles of arithmetic from logical axioms and these definitions. The
explicitness and rigor of his formulation of logic will guarantee that there
are no implicit extralogical premises on which the arithmetical conclusions
depend. Such proofs, he believed, would show arithmetic to be analytic, not
synthetic as Kant had claimed. However, Frege redefined ‘analytic’ to mean
‘provable from Frege, Gottlob Frege, Gottlob 328 4065A- AM 328
logical laws’ (in his rather un-Kantian sense of ‘logic’) and definitions.
Frege’s strategy for these proofs rests on an analysis of the concept of
cardinal number that he presented in his nontechnical 1884 book, The
Foundations of Arithmetic. Frege, attending to the use of numerals in
statements like ‘Mars has two moons’, argued that it contains an assertion
about a concept, that it asserts that there are exactly two things falling
under the concept ‘Martian moon’. He also noted that both numerals in these
statements and those of pure arithmetic play the logical role of singular
terms, his proper names. He concluded that numbers are objects so that a
definition of the concept of number must then specify what objects numbers are.
He observed that (1) the number of F % the number of G just in case there is a
one-to-one correspondence between the objects that are F and those that are G.
The right-hand side of (1) is statable in purely logical terms. As Frege
recognized, thanks to the definition of the ancestral of a relation, (1)
suffices in the second-order setting of the Begriffsschrift for the derivation
of elementary arithmetic. The vindication of his logicism requires, however,
the logical definition of the expression ‘the number of’. He sharply criticized
the use in mathematics of any notion of set or collection that views a set as
built up from its elements. However, he assumed that, corresponding to each
concept, there is an object, the extension of the concept. He took the notion
of an extension to be a logical one, although one to which the notion of a
concept is prior. He adopted as a fundamental logical principle the ill-fated
biconditional: the extension of F % the extension of G just in case every F is
G, and vice versa. If this principle were valid, he could exploit the
equivalence relation over concepts that figures in the right-hand side of (1)
to identify the number of F with a certain extension and thus obtain (1) as a
theorem. In The Basic Laws of Arithmetic (vol. 1, 1893; vol. 2, 1903) he
formalized putative proofs of basic arithmetical laws within a modified version
of the Begriffsschrift that included a generalization of the law of extensions.
However, Frege’s law of extensions, in the context of his logic, is
inconsistent, leading to Russell’s paradox, as Russell communicated to Frege in
1902. Frege’s attempt to establish logicism was thus, on its own terms,
unsuccessful. In Begriffsschrift Frege rejected the thesis that every
uncompound sentence is logically segmented into a subject and a predicate.
Subsequently, he said that his approach in logic was distinctive in starting
not from the synthesis of concepts into judgments, but with the notion of truth
and that to which this notion is applicable, the judgeable contents or thoughts
that are expressed by statements. Although he said that truth is the goal of
logic, he did not think that we have a grasp of the notion of truth that is
independent of logic. He eschewed a correspondence theory of truth, embracing
instead a redundancy view of the truth-predicate. For Frege, to call truth the
goal of logic points toward logic’s concern with inference, with the
recognition-of-thetruth (judging) of one thought on the basis of the
recognition-of-the-truth of another. This recognition-of-the-truth-of is not
verbally expressed by a predicate, but rather in the assertive force with which
a sentence is uttered. The starting point for logic is then reflection on
elementary inference patterns that analyze thoughts and reveal a logical
segmentation in language. This starting point, and the fusion of logical and
ontological categories it engenders, is arguably what Frege is pointing toward
by his enigmatic context principle in Foundations: only in the context of a
sentence does a word have a meaning. He views sentences as having a
function-argument segmentation like that manifest in the terms of arithmetic,
e.g., (3 $ 4) ! 2. Truth-functional inference patterns, like modus ponens,
isolate sentences as logical units in compound sentences. Leibniz’s law – the
substitution of one name for another in a sentence on the basis of an equation
– isolates proper names. Proper names designate objects. Predicates, obtainable
by removing proper names from sentences, designate concepts. The removal of a
predicate from a sentence leaves a higher level predicate that signifies a
second-level concept under which first-level concepts fall. An example is the
universal quantifier over objects: it designates a second-level concept under
which a first-level concept falls, if every object falls under it. Frege takes
each first-level concept to be determinately true or false of each object.
Vague predicates, like ‘is bald’, thus fail to signify concepts. This
requirement of concept determinacy is a product of Frege’s construal of
quantification over objects as intrinsically unrestricted. Thus, concept
determinacy is simply a form of the law of the excluded middle: for any concept
F and any object x, either x is F or x is not F. Frege elaborates and modifies
his basic logical ideas in three seminal papers from 1891–92, “Function and
Concept,” “On Concept and Frege, Gottlob Frege, Gottlob 329 4065A- AM 329
Object,” and “On Sense and Meaning.” In “Function and Concept,” Frege sharpens
his conception of the function-argument structure of language. He introduces
the two truth-values, the True and the False, and maintains that sentences are
proper names of these objects. Concepts become functions that map objects to
either the True or the False. The course-of-values of a function is introduced
as a generalization of the notion of an extension. Generally then, an object is
anything that might be designated by a proper name. There is nothing more basic
to be said by way of elucidating what an object is. Similarly, first-level
functions are what are designated by the expressions that result from removing
names from compound proper names. Frege calls functions unsaturated or
incomplete, in contrast to objects, which are saturated. Proper names and
function names are not intersubstitutable so that the distinction between
objects and functions is a type-theoretic, categorial distinction. No function
is an object; no function name designates an object; there are no quantifiers
that simultaneously generalize over both functions and concepts. Just here
Frege’s exposition of his views, if not the views themselves, encounter a
difficulty. In explaining his views, he uses proper names of the form ‘the
concept F’ to talk about concepts; and in contrasting unsaturated functions
with saturated objects, apepars to generalize over both with a single
quantifier. Benno Kerry, a contemporary of Frege, charged Frege’s views with
inconsistency. Since the phrase ‘the concept horse’ is a proper name, it must
designate an object. On Frege’s view, it follows that the concept ‘horse’ is
not a concept, but an object, an apparent inconsistency. Frege responded to Kerry’s
criticism in “On Concept and Object.” He embraced Kerry’s paradox, denying that
it represents a genuine inconsistency, while admitting that his remarks about
the function–object distinction are, as the result of an unavoidable
awkwardness of language, misleading. Frege maintained that the distinction
between function and object is logically simple and so cannot be properly
defined. His remarks on the distinction are informal handwaving designed to
elucidate what is captured within the Begriffsschrift by the difference between
proper names and function names together with their associated distinct
quantifiers. Frege’s handling of the function– object distinction is a likely
source for Wittgenstein’s say–show distinction in the Tractatus. At the beginning
of “On Sense and Meaning,” Frege distinguishes between the reference or meaning
(Bedeutung) of a proper name and its sense (Sinn). He observes that the
sentence ‘The Morning Star is identical with the Morning Star’ is a trivial
instance of the principle of identity. In contrast, the sentence ‘The Morning
Star is identical with the Evening Star’ expresses a substantive astronomical
discovery. The two sentences thus differ in what Frege called their cognitive
value: someone who understood both might believe the first and doubt the
second. This difference cannot be explained in terms of any difference in
reference between names in these sentences. Frege explained it in terms of a
difference between the senses expressed by ‘the Morning Star’ and ‘the Evening Star’.
In posthumously published writings, he indicated that the sense–reference
distinction extends to function names as well. In this distinction, Frege
extends to names the notion of the judgeable content expressed by a sentence:
the sense of a name is the contribution that the name makes to the thought
expressed by sentences in which it occurs. Simultaneously, in classifying
sentences as proper names of truth-values, he applies to sentences the notion
of a name’s referring to something. Frege’s function-argument view of logical
segmentation constrains his view of both the meaning and the sense of compound
names: the substitution for any name occurring in a compound expression of a
name with the same reference (sense) yields a new compound expression with the
same reference (sense) as the original. Frege advances several theses about
sense that individually and collectively have been a source of debate in
philosophy of language. First, the sense of an expression is what is grasped by
anyone who understands it. Despite the connection between understanding and
sense, Frege provides no account of synonymy, no identity criteria for senses.
Second, the sense of an expression is not something psychological. Senses are
objective. They exist independently of anyone’s grasping them; their
availability to different thinkers is a presupposition for communication in
science. Third, the sense expressed by a name is a mode of presentation of the
name’s reference. Here Frege’s views contrast with Russell’s. Corresponding to
Frege’s thoughts are Russell’s propositions. In The Principles of Mathematics
(1903), Russell maintained that the meaningful words in a sentence designate
things, properties, and relations that are themselves constituents of the
proposition expressed by the sentence. For Frege, our access through judgment
to objects and functions is via Frege, Gottlob Frege, Gottlob 330 4065A- AM 330
the senses that are expressed by names that mean these items. These senses, not
the items they present, occur in thoughts. Names expressing different senses
may refer to the same item; and some names, while expressing a sense, refer to
nothing. Any compound name containing a name that has a sense, but lacks a
reference, itself lacks a meaning. A person may fully understand an expression
without knowing whether it means anything and without knowing whether it
designates what another understood name does. Fourth, the sense ordinarily
expressed by a name is the reference of the name, when the name occurs in
indirect discourse. Although the Morning Star is identical with the Evening
Star, the inference from the sentence ‘Smith believes that the Morning Star is
a planet’ to ‘Smith believes that the Evening Star is a planet’ is not sound.
Frege, however, accepts Leibniz’s law without restriction. He accordingly takes
such seeming failures of Leibniz’s law to expose a pervasive ambiguity in
colloquial language: names in indirect discourse do not designate what they
designate outside of indirect discourse. The fourth thesis is offered as an
explanation of this ambiguity.
LOGICISM, MEANING,
RUSSELL, SET-THEORETIC PARADOXES, SET THEORY. T.R. Frege-Geach point.GEACH.
frequency theory of probability.PROBABILITY. French personalism, a Christian
socialism stressing social activism and personal responsibility, the
theoretical basis for the Christian workers’ Esprit movement begun in the 1930s
by Emmanuel Mounier (1905–50), a Christian philosopher and activist. Influenced
by both the religious existentialism of Kierkegaard and the radical social
action called for by Marx and in part taking direction from the earlier work of
Charles Péguy, the movement strongly opposed fascism and called for worker
solidarity during the 1930s and 1940s. It also urged a more humane treatment of
France’s colonies. Personalism allowed for a Christian socialism independent of
both more conservative Christian groups and the Communist labor unions and
party. Its most important single book is Mounier’s Personalism. The quarterly
journal Esprit has regularly published contributions of leading French and
international thinkers. Such well-known Christian philosophers as Henry Duméry,
Marcel, Maritain, and Ricoeur were attracted to the movement. MARCEL, MARITAIN, PERSONALISM, RICOEUR. J.Bi.
Freud, Sigmund (1856–1939), Austrian neurologist and psychologist, the founder
of psychoanalysis. Starting with the study of hysteria in late
nineteenth-century Vienna, Freud developed a theory of the mind that has come
to dominate modern thought. His notions of the unconscious, of a mind divided
against itself, of the meaningfulness of apparently meaningless activity, of
the displacement and transference of feelings, of stages of psychosexual
development, of the pervasiveness and importance of sexual motivation, as well
as of much else, have helped shape modern consciousness. His language (and that
of his translators), whether specifying divisions of the mind (e.g. id, ego,
and superego), types of disorder (e.g. obsessional neurosis), or the structure
of experience (e.g. Oedipus complex, narcissism), has become the language in
which we describe and understand ourselves and others. As the poet W. H. Auden
wrote on the occasion of Freud’s death, “if often he was wrong and, at times,
absurd, / to us he is no more a person / now but a whole climate of opinion /
under whom we conduct our different lives. . . .” Hysteria is a disorder
involving organic symptoms with no apparent organic cause. Following early work
in neurophysiology, Freud (in collaboration with Josef Breuer) came to the view
that “hysterics suffer mainly from reminiscences,” in particular buried
memories of traumatic experiences, the strangulated affect of which emerged (in
conversion hysteria) in the distorted form of physical symptoms. Treatment
involved the recovery of the repressed memories to allow the cathartic
discharge or abreaction of the previously displaced and strangulated affect.
This provided the background for Freud’s seduction theory, which traced
hysterical symptoms to traumatic prepubertal sexual assaults (typically by
fathers). But Freud later abandoned the seduction theory because the energy
assumptions were problematic (e.g., if the only energy involved was
strangulated affect from long-past external trauma, why didn’t the symptom
successfully use up that energy and so clear itself up?) and because he came to
see that fantasy could have the same effects as memory of actual events:
“psychical reality was of more importance than material reality.” What was
repressed was not memories, but desires. He came to see the repetition of
symptoms as fueled by internal, in particular sexual, energy. While it is
certainly true that Freud saw the Frege-Geach point Freud, Sigmund 331
4065A- AM 331 working of sexuality almost everywhere,
it is not true that he explained everything in terms of sexuality alone.
Psychoanalysis is a theory of internal psychic conflict, and conflict requires
at least two parties. Despite developments and changes, Freud’s instinct theory
was determinedly dualistic from beginning to end – at the beginning, libido
versus ego or self-preservative instincts, and at the end Eros versus Thanatos,
life against death. Freud’s instinct theory (not to be confused with standard
biological notions of hereditary behavior patterns in animals) places instincts
on the borderland between the mental and physical and insists that they are
internally complex. In particular, the sexual instinct must be understood as
made up of components that vary along a number of dimensions (source, aim, and
object). Otherwise, as Freud argues in his Three Essays on the Theory of
Sexuality (1905), it would be difficult to understand how the various
perversions are recognized as “sexual” despite their distance from the “normal”
conception of sexuality (heterosexual genital intercourse between adults). His
broadened concept of sexuality makes intelligible sexual preferences
emphasizing different sources (erotogenic zones or bodily centers of arousal),
aims (acts, such as intercourse and looking, designed to achieve pleasure and
satisfaction), and objects (whether of the same or different gender, or even
other than whole living persons). It also allows for the recognition of
infantile sexuality. Phenomena that might not on the surface appear sexual
(e.g. childhood thumbsucking) share essential characteristics with obviously
sexual activity (infantile sensual sucking involves pleasurable stimulation of
the same erotogenic zone, the mouth, stimulated in adult sexual activities such
as kissing), and can be understood as earlier stages in the development of the
same underlying instinct that expresses itself in such various forms in adult
sexuality. The standard developmental stages are oral, anal, phallic, and
genital. Neuroses, which Freud saw as “the negative of perversions” (i.e., the
same desires that might in some lead to perverse activity, when repressed,
result in neurosis), could often be traced to struggles with the Oedipus
complex: the “nucleus of the neuroses.” The Oedipus complex, which in its
positive form postulates sexual feelings toward the parent of the opposite sex
and ambivalently hostile feelings toward the parent of the same sex, suggests
that the universal shape of the human condition is a triangle. The conflict
reaches its peak between the ages of three and five, during the phallic stage
of psychosexual development. The fundamental structuring of emotions has its
roots in the prolonged dependency of the human infant, leading to attachment –
a primary form of love – to the primary caregiver, who (partly for biological
reasons such as lactation) is most often the mother, and the experience of
others as rivals for the time, attention, and concern of the primary caregiver.
Freud’s views of the Oedipus complex should not be oversimplified. The sexual
desires involved, e.g., are typically unconscious and necessarily infantile,
and infantile sexuality and its associated desires are not expressed in the
same form as mature genital sexuality. His efforts to explain the distinctive
features of female psychosexual development in particular led to some of his
most controversial views, including the postulation of penis envy to explain
why girls but not boys standardly experience a shift in gender of their primary
love object (both starting with the mother as the object). Later love objects,
including psychoanalysts as the objects of transference feelings (in the
analytic setting, the analyst functions as a blank screen onto which the
patient projects feelings), are the results of displacement or transference
from earlier objects: “The finding of an object is in fact a refinding of it.”
Freud used the same structure of explanation for symptoms and for more normal
phenomena, such as dreams, jokes, and slips of the tongue. All can be seen as
compromise formations between forces pressing for expression (localized by
Freud’s structural theory in the id, understood as a reservoir of unconscious
instinct) and forces of repression (some also unconscious, seeking to meet the
constraints of morality and reality). On Freud’s underlying model, the
fundamental process of psychic functioning, the primary process, leads to the
uninhibited discharge of psychic energy. Such discharge is experienced as
pleasurable, hence the governing principle of the fundamental process is called
the pleasure principle. Increase of tension is experienced as unpleasure, and
the psychic apparatus aims at a state of equilibrium or constancy (sometimes
Freud writes as if the state aimed at is one of zero tension, hence the Nirvana
principle associated with the death instinct in Freud’s Beyond the Pleasure
Principle [1920]). But since pleasure can in fact only be achieved under
specific conditions, which sometimes require arrangement, planning, and delay,
individuals must learn to inhibit discharge, and this secondary process
thinking is governed by what Freud came to call the reality principle. The aim
is still satisfaction, but the “exigencies of life” require attention,
reasoning, and Freud, Sigmund Freud, Sigmund 332 4065A- AM 332
judgment to avoid falling into the fantasy wishfulfillment of the primary
process. Sometimes defense mechanisms designed to avoid increased tension or
unpleasure can fail, leading to neurosis (in general, under the theory, a
neurosis is a psychological disorder rooted in unconscious conflict –
particular neuroses being correlated with particular phases of development and
particular mechanisms of defense). Repression, involving the confining of
psychic representations to the unconscious, is the most important of the
defense mechanisms. It should be understood that unlike preconscious ideas,
which are merely descriptively unconscious (though one may not be aware of them
at the moment, they are readily accessible to consciousness), unconscious ideas
in the strict sense are kept from awareness by forces of repression, they are
dynamically unconscious – as evidenced by the resistance to making the
unconscious conscious in therapy. Freud’s deep division of the mind between
unconscious and conscious goes beyond neurotic symptoms to help make sense of
familiar forms of irrationality (such as selfdeception, ambivalence, and
weakness of the will) that are highly problematical on Cartesian models of an
indivisible unitary consciousness. Perhaps the best example of the primary
process thinking that characterizes the unconscious (unconstrained by the
realities of time, contradiction, causation, etc.) can be found in dreaming.
Freud regarded dreams as “the royal road to a knowledge of the unconscious.”
Dreams are the disguised fulfillment of unconscious wishes. In extracting the
meaning of dreams through a process of interpretation, Freud relied on a
central distinction between the manifest content (the dream as dreamt or as
remembered on waking) and the latent content (the unconscious dreamthoughts).
Freud held that interpretation via association to particular elements of the
manifest content reversed the process of dream construction, the dream-work in
which various mechanisms of distortion operated on the day’s residues
(perceptions and thoughts stemming from the day before the dream was dreamt)
and the latent dream-thoughts to produce the manifest dream. Prominent among
the mechanisms are the condensation (in which many meanings are represented by
a single idea) and displacement (in which there is a shift of affect from a significant
and intense idea to an associated but otherwise insignificant one) also typical
of neurotic symptoms, as well as considerations of representability and
secondary revision more specific to dream formation. Symbolism is less
prominent in Freud’s theory of dreams than is often thought; indeed, the
section on symbols appeared only as a later addition to The Interpretation of
Dreams (1900). Freud explicitly rejected the ancient “dream book” mode of
interpretation in terms of fixed symbols, and believed one had to recover the
hidden meaning of a dream through the dreamer’s (not the interpreter’s)
associations to particular elements. Such associations are a part of the
process of free association, in which a patient is obliged to report to the
analyst all thoughts without censorship of any kind. The process is crucial to
psychoanalysis, which is both a technique of psychotherapy and a method of
investigation of the workings of the mind. Freud used the results of his
investigations to speculate about the origins of morality, religion, and
political authority. He tended to find their historical and psychological roots
in early stages of the development of the individual. Morality in particular he
traced to the internalization (as one part of the resolution of the Oedpius
complex) of parental prohibitions and demands, producing a conscience or
superego (which is also the locus of self-observation and the ego-ideal). Such
identification by incorporation – introjection – plays an important role in
character formation in general. The instinctual renunciation demanded by
morality and often achieved by repression Freud regarded as essential to the
order society needs to conduct its business. Civilization gets the energy for
the achievements of art and science by sublimation of the same instinctual
drives. But the costs of society and civilization to the individual in
frustration, unhappiness, and neurosis can be too high. Freud’s individual
therapy was meant to lead to the liberation of repressed energies (which would not
by itself guarantee happiness); he hoped it might also provide energy to
transform the world and moderate its excess demands for restraint. But just as
his individual psychology was founded on the inevitability of internal
conflict, in his social thought he saw some limits (especially on aggression –
the death instinct turned outward) as necessary and he remained pessimistic
about the apparently endless struggle reason must wage (Civilization and Its
Discontents, 1930).
JUNG, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND,
PHILOSOPHY OF PSYCHOLOGY, SELF-DECEPTION. J.Ne. Fries, Jakob
Friedrich.NEO-KANTIANISM. full subset algebra.BOOLEAN ALGEBRA. Fries, Jakob
Friedrich full subset algebra 333 4065A-
AM 333 function,
mathematical.ALGORITHM, MATHEMATICAL FUNCTION. function, probability.BAYESIAN
RATIONALITY. function, state.QUANTUM MECHANICS. function,
teleological.TELEOLOGY. functional.RELATION. functional abstraction.
COMBINATORY LOGIC.
functional calculus, lower.FORMAL LOGIC. functional completeness.COMPLETENESS.
functional dependence, a relationship between variable magnitudes (especially
physical magnitudes) and certain properties or processes. In modern physical
science there are two types of laws stating such relationships. (1) There are
numerical laws stating concomitant variation of certain quantities, where a
variation in any one is accompanied by variations in the others. An example is
the law for ideal gases: pV % aT, where p is the pressure of the gas, V its
volume, T its absolute temperature, and a a constant derived from the mass and
the nature of the gas. Such laws say nothing about the temporal order of the
variations, and tests of the laws can involve variation of any of the relevant
magnitudes. Concomitant variation, not causal sequence, is what is tested for.
(2) Other numerical laws state variations of physical magnitudes correlated
with times. Galileo’s law of free fall asserts that the change in the unit time
of a freely falling body (in a vacuum) in the direction of the earth is equal
to gt, where g is a constant and t is the time of the fall, and where the rate
of time changes of g is correlative with the temporal interval t. The law is
true of any body in a state of free fall and for any duration. Such laws are
also called “dynamical” because they refer to temporal processes usually
explained by the postulation of forces acting on the objects in question.
R.E.B. functional explanation.PHILOSOPHY OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES. functionalism,
the view that mental states are defined by their causes and effects. As a
metaphysical thesis about the nature of mental states, functionalism holds that
what makes an inner state mental is not an intrinsic property of the state, but
rather its relations to sensory stimulation (input), to other inner states, and
to behavior (output). For example, what makes an inner state a pain is its
being a type of state (typically) caused by pinpricks, sunburns, and so on, a
type that causes other mental states (e.g., worry), and a type that causes
behavior (e.g., saying “ouch”). Propositional attitudes also are identified
with functional states: an inner state is a desire for water partly in virtue
of its causing a person to pick up a glass and drink its contents when the
person believes that the glass contains water. The basic distinction needed for
functionalism is that between role (in terms of which a type of mental state is
defined) and occupant (the particular thing that occupies a role). Functional
states exhibit multiple realizability: in different kinds of beings (humans,
computers, Martians), a particular kind of causal role may have different
occupants – e.g., the causal role definitive of a belief that p, say, may be
occupied by a neural state in a human, but occupied (perhaps) by a hydraulic
state in a Martian. Functionalism, like behaviorism, thus entails that mental
states may be shared by physically dissimilar systems. Although functionalism
does not automatically rule out the existence of immaterial souls, its
motivation has been to provide a materialistic account of mentality. The advent
of the computer gave impetus to functionalism. First, the distinction between
software and hardware suggested the distinction between role (function) and
occupant (structure). Second, since computers are automated, they demonstrate
how inner states can be causes of output in the absence of a homunculus (i.e.,
a “little person” intelligently directing output). Third, the Turing machine
provided a model for one of the earliest versions of functionalism. A Turing
machine is defined by a table that specifies transitions from current state and
input to next state (or to output). According to Turing machine functionalism,
any being with pscychological states has a unique best description, and each
psychological state is identical to a machine table state relative to that
description. To be in mental state type M is to instantiate or realize Turing
machine T in state S. Turing machine functionalism, developed largely by
Putnam, has been criticized by Putnam, Ned Block, and Fodor. To cite just one
serious problem: two machine table states – and hence, according to Turing
machine functionalism, two psychological states – are distinct if they are
followed by different states or by different outputs. So, if a pinprick causes
A to say “Ouch” function, mathematical functionalism 334 4065A- AM 334
and causes B to say “Oh,” then, if Turing machine functionalism were true, A’s
and B’s states of pain would be different psychological states. But we do not
individuate psychological states so finely, nor should we: such fine-grained
individuation would be unsuitable for psychology. Moreover, if we assume that
there is a path from any state to any other state, Turing machine functionalism
has the unacceptable consequence that no two systems have any of their states
in common unless they have all their states in common. Perhaps the most
prominent version of functionalism is the causal theory of mind. Whereas Turing
machine functionalism is based on a technical computational or psychological
theory, the causal theory of mind relies on commonsense understanding:
according to the causal theory of mind, the concept of a mental state is the
concept of a state apt for bringing about certain kinds of behavior
(Armstrong). Mental state terms are defined by the commonsense platitudes in which
they appear (David Lewis). Philosophers can determine a priori what mental
states are (by conceptual analysis or by definition). Then scientists determine
what physical states occupy the causal roles definitive of mental states. If it
turned out that there was no physical state that occupied the causal role of,
say, pain (i.e., was caused by pinpricks, etc., and caused worry, etc.), it
would follow, on the causal theory, that pain does not exist. To be in mental
state type M is to be in a physical state N that occupies causal role R. A
third version is teleological or “homuncular” functionalism, associated with
William G. Lycan and early Dennett. According to homuncular functionalism, a
human being is analogous to a large corporation, made up of cooperating
departments, each with its own job to perform; these departments interpret
stimuli and produce behavioral responses. Each department (at the highest
subpersonal level) is in turn constituted by further units (at a
sub-subpersonal level) and so on down until the neurological level is reached.
The role–occupant distinction is thus relativized to level: an occupant at one
level is a role at the next level down. On this view, to be in a mental state
type M is to have a sub- . . . subpersonal f-er that is in its characteristic
state S(f). All versions of functionalism face problems about the qualitative
nature of mental states. The difficulty is that functionalism individuates
states in purely relational terms, but the acrid odor of, say, a paper mill
seems to have a non-relational, qualitative character that functionalism misses
altogether. If two people, on seeing a ripe banana, are in states with the same
causes and effects, then, by functionalist definition, they are in the same
mental state – say, having a sensation of yellow. But it seems possible that
one has an “inverted spectrum” relative to the other, and hence that their
states are qualitatively different. Imagine that, on seeing the banana, one of
the two is in a state qualitatively indistinguishable from the state that the
other would be in on seeing a ripe tomato. Despite widespread intuitions that
such inverted spectra are possible, according to functionalism, they are not. A
related problem is that of “absent qualia.” The population of China, or even
the economy of Bolivia, could be functionally equivalent to a human brain –
i.e., there could be a function that mapped the relations between inputs,
outputs, and internal states of the population of China onto those of a human
brain; yet the population of China, no matter how its members interact with one
another and with other nations, intuitively does not have mental states. The
status of these arguments remains controversial.
BEHAVIORISM,
INTENTIONALITY, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND, TURING MACHINE. L.R.B. functionalism,
analytical.PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. functionalism, machine state.PHILOSOPHY OF MIND.
functionalism, Turing machine.FUNCTIONALISM. functional
jurisprudence.JURISPRUDENCE. functor.FORMAL LOGIC. fundamentum divisionis
(Latin, ‘foundation of a division’), term in Scholastic logic and ontology
meaning ‘grounds for a distinction’. Some distinctions categorize separately
existing things, such as men and beasts. This is a real distinction, and the
fundamentum divisionis exists in reality. Some distinctions categorize things
that cannot exist separately but can be distinguished mentally, such as the
difference between being a human being and having a sense of humor, or the
difference between a soul and one of its powers, say, the power of thinking. A
mental distinction is also called a formal distinction. Duns Scotus is well
known for the idea of formalis distinctio cum fundamento ex parte rei (a formal
distinction with a foundation in the thing), primarily in order to handle
logical problems with functionalism, analytical fundamentum divisionis 335
4065A- AM 335 the Christian concept of God. God is
supposed to be absolutely simple; i.e., there can be no multiplicity of
composition in him. Yet, according to traditional theology, many properties can
be truly attributed to him. He is wise, good, and powerful. In order to
preserve the simplicity of God, Duns Scotus claimed that the difference between
wisdom, goodness, and power was only formal but still had some foundation in
God’s own being. A.P.M. Fung Yu-lan (1895–1990), Chinese philosopher. He was
educated at Peking University and earned his Ph.D. from Columbia University.
His History of Chinese Philosophy was the first such complete history of high
quality by a contemporary scholar. During World War II he attempted to
reconstruct Chu Hsi’s philosophy in terms of the New Realism that he had
learned from the West, and developed his own system of thought, a new
philosophy of li (principle). After the Communist takeover in 1949, he gave up
his earlier thought, denouncing Confucian philosophy during the Cultural
Revolution. After the Cultural Revolution he changed his position again and
rewrote his History of Chinese Philosophy in seven volumes. CHINESE PHILOSOPHY, CHU HSI. S.-h.L. future
contingents, singular events or states of affairs that may come to pass, and
also may not come to pass, in the future. There are three traditional problems
involving future contingents: the question of universal validity of the
principle of bivalence, the question of free will and determinism, and the
question of foreknowledge. The debate about future contingents in modern
philosophical logic was revived by Lukasiewicz’s work on three-valued logic. He
thought that in order to avoid fatalistic consequences, we must admit that the
principle of bivalence (for any proposition, p, either p is true or not-p is
true) does not hold good for propositions about future contingents. Many
authors have considered this view confused. According to von Wright, e.g., when
propositions are said to be true or false and ‘is’ in ‘it is true that’ is
tenseless or atemporal, the illusion of determinism does not arise. It has its
roots in a tacit oscillation between a temporal and an atemporal reading of the
phrase ‘it is true’. In a temporalized reading, or in its tensed variants such
as ‘it was/will be/is already true’, one can substitute, for ‘true’, other
words like ‘certain’, ‘fixed’, or ‘necessary’. Applying this diachronic
necessity to atemporal predications of truth yields the idea of logical determinism.
In contemporary discussions of tense and modality, future contingents are often
treated with the help of a model of time as a line that breaks up into branches
as it moves from left to right (i.e., from past to future). Although the
conception of truth at a moment has been found philosophically problematic, the
model of historical modalities and branching time as such is much used in works
on freedom and determination. Aristotle’s On Interpretation IX contains a
classic discussion of future contingents with the famous example of tomorrow’s
sea battle. Because of various ambiguities in the text and in Aristotle’s modal
conceptions in general, the meaning of the passage is in dispute. In the
Metaphysics VI.3 and in the Niocmachean Ethics III.5, Aristotle tries to show
that not all things are predetermined. The Stoics represented a causally
deterministic worldview; an ancient example of logical determinism is Diodorus
Cronus’s famous master argument against contingency. Boethius thought that
Aristotle’s view can be formulated as follows: the principle of bivalence is
universally valid, but propositions about future contingents, unlike those
about past and present things, do not obey the stronger principle according to
which each proposition is either determinately true or determinately false. A
proposition is indeterminately true as long as the conditions that make it true
are not yet fixed. This was the standard Latin doctrine from Abelard to
Aquinas. Similar discussions occurred in Arabic commentaries on On
Interpretation. In the fourteenth century, many thinkers held that Aristotle
abandoned bivalence for future contingent propositions. This restriction was
usually refuted, but it found some adherents like Peter Aureoli. Duns Scotus
and Ockham heavily criticized the Boethian-Thomistic view that God can know
future contingents only because the flux of time is present to divine eternity.
According to them, God contingently foreknows free acts. Explaining this proved
to be a very cumbersome task. Luis de Molina (1535–1600) suggested that God
knows what possible creatures would do in any possible situation. This “middle
knowledge” theory about counterfactuals of freedom has remained a living theme
in philosophy of religion; analogous questions are treated in theories of
subjunctive reasoning. ARISTOTLE,
BOETHIUS, FREE WILL PROBLEM, MANY-VALUED LOGIC,
TENSE LOGIC, VAGUENESS.
S.K. Fung Yu-lan future contingents 336 4065A-
AM 336 fuzzy logic.FUZZY SET,
VAGUENESS. fuzzy set, a set in which membership is a matter of degree. In
classical set theory, for every set S and thing x, either x is a member of S or
x is not. In fuzzy set theory, things x can be members of sets S to any degree
between 0 and 1, inclusive. Degree 1 corresponds to ‘is a member of’ and 0
corresponds to ‘is not’; the intermediate degrees are degrees of vagueness or
uncertainty. (Example: Let S be the set of men who are bald at age forty.) L.
A. Zadeh developed a logic of fuzzy sets as the basis for a logic of vague
predicates. A fuzzy set can be represented mathematically as a function from a
given universe into the interval [0, 1].
SET THEORY, VAGUENESS. D.H. fuzzy logic fuzzy set 337 4065A- AM 337
Gadamer, Hans-Georg (b.1900), German philosopher, the leading proponent of
hermeneutics in the second half of the twentieth century. He studied at Marburg
in the 1920s with Natorp and Heidegger. His first book, Plato’s Dialectical
Ethics (1931), bears their imprint and reflects his abiding interest in Greek
philosophy. Truth and Method (1960) established Gadamer as an original thinker
and had an impact on a variety of disciplines outside philosophy, including
theology, legal theory, and literary criticism. The three parts of Truth and
Method combine to displace the scientific conceptions of truth and method as
the model for understanding in the human sciences. In the first part, which
presents itself as a critique of the abstraction inherent in aesthetic
consciousness, Gadamer argues that artworks make a claim to truth. Later
Gadamer draws on the play of art in the experience of the beautiful to offer an
analogy to how a text draws its readers into the event of truth by making a
claim on them. In the central portion of the book Gadamer presents tradition as
a condition of understanding. Tradition is not for him an object of historical
knowledge, but part of one’s very being. The final section of Truth and Method
is concerned with language as the site of tradition. Gadamer sought to shift
the focus of hermeneutics from the problems of obscurity and misunderstanding
to the community of understanding that the participants in a dialogue share
through language. Gadamer was involved in three debates that define his
philosophical contribution. The first was an ongoing debate with Heidegger
reflected throughout Gadamer’s corpus. Gadamer did not accept all of the
innovations that Heidegger introduced into his thinking in the 1930s,
particularly his reconstruction of the history of philosophy as the history of
being. Gadamer also rejected Heidegger’s elevation of Hölderlin to the status
of an authority. Gadamer’s greater accessibility led Habermas to characterize
Gadamer’s contribution as that of having “urbanized the Heideggerian province.”
The second debate was with Habermas himself. Habermas criticized Gadamer’s rejection
of the Enlightenment’s “prejudice against prejudice.” Whereas Habermas objected
to the conservatism inherent in Gadamer’s rehabilitation of prejudice, Gadamer
explained that he was only setting out the conditions for understanding,
conditions that did not exclude the possibility of radical change. The third
debate, which formed the basis of Dialogue and Deconstruction (1989), was with
Derrida. Derridean deconstruction is indebted to Heidegger’s later philosophy
and so this debate was in part about the direction philosophy should take after
Heidegger. However, many observers concluded that there was no real engagement
between Gadamer and Derrida. To some it seemed that Derrida, by refusing to
accept the terms on which Gadamer insisted dialogue should take place, had
exposed the limits imposed by hermeneutics. To others it was confirmation that
any attempt to circumvent the conditions of dialogue specified by Gadamerian
hermeneutics is selfdefeating. DERRIDA,
HEIDEGGER, HERMENEUTICS. R.L.B. Gaius.COMMENTARIES ON PLATO,
MIDDLE PLATONISM. Galen
(A.D. 129–c.215), physician and philosopher from Greek Asia Minor. He traveled
extensively in the Greco-Roman world before settling in Rome and becoming court
physician to Marcus Aurelius. His philosophical interests lay mainly in the
philosophy of science (On the Therapeutic Method) and nature (On the Function
of Parts), and in logic (Introduction to Logic, in which he develops a crude
but pioneering treatment of the logic of relations). Galen espoused an extreme
form of directed teleology in natural explanation, and sought to develop a
syncretist picture of cause and explanation drawing on Plato, Aristotle, the
Stoics, and preceding medical writers, notably Hippocrates, whose views he
attempted to harmonize with those of Plato (On the Doctrines of Hippocrates and
Plato). He wrote on philosophical psychology (On the Passions and Errors of the
Soul); his materialist account of mind (Mental Characteristics Are Caused by
Bodily Conditions) is notable for its caution in approaching issues (such as
the actual nature of the substance of the soul and the age and structure of the
universe) that he regarded as unde338 G 4065A-
AM 338 cidable. In physiology, he
adopted a version of the four-humor theory, that health consists in an
appropriate balance of four basic bodily constituents (blood, black bile,
yellow bile, and phlegm), and disease in a corresponding imbalance (a view owed
ultimately to Hippocrates). He sided with the rationalist physicians against
the empiricists, holding that it was possible to elaborate and to support
theories concerning the fundamentals of the human body; but he stressed the
importance of observation and experiment, in particular in anatomy (he
discovered the function of the recurrent laryngeal nerve by dissection and
ligation). Via the Arabic tradition, Galen became the most influential doctor
of the ancient world; his influence persisted, in spite of the discoveries of
the seventeenth century, until the end of the nineteenth century. He also wrote
extensively on semantics, but these texts are lost. R.J.H. Galileo Galilei
(1564–1642), Italian astronomer, natural philosopher, and physicist. His
Dialogue concerning the Two Chief World Systems (1632) defended Copernicus by
arguing against the major tenets of the Aristotelian cosmology. On his view,
one kind of motion replaces the multiple distinct celestial and terrestrial
motions of Aristotle; mathematics is applicable to the real world; and
explanation of natural events appeals to efficient causes alone, not to
hypothesized natural ends. Galileo was called before the Inquisition, was made
to recant his Copernican views, and spent the last years of his life under
house arrest. Discourse concerning Two New Sciences (1638) created the modern
science of mechanics: it proved the laws of free fall, thus making it possible
to study accelerated motions; asserted the principle of the independence of
forces; and proposed a theory of parabolic ballistics. His work was developed
by Huygens and Newton. Galileo’s scientific and technological achievements were
prodigious. He invented an air thermoscope, a device for raising water, and a
computer for calculating quantities in geometry and ballistics. His discoveries
in pure science included the isochronism of the pendulum and the hydrostatic
balance. His telescopic observations led to the discovery of four of Jupiter’s
satellites (the Medicean Stars), the moon’s mountains, sunspots, the moon’s
libration, and the nature of the Milky Way. In methodology Galileo accepted the
ancient Greek ideal of demonstrative science, and employed the method of
retroductive inference, whereby the phenomena under investigation are
attributed to remote causes. Much of his work utilizes the
hypothetico-deductive method. R.E.B. gambler’s fallacy, also called Monte Carlo
fallacy, the fallacy of supposing, of a sequence of independent events, that
the probabilities of later outcomes must increase or decrease to “compensate”
for earlier outcomes. For example, since (by Bernoulli’s theorem) in a long run
of tosses of a fair coin it is very probable that the coin will come up heads
roughly half the time, one might think that a coin that has not come up heads
recently must be “due” to come up heads – must have a probability greater than
one-half of doing so. But this is a misunderstanding of the law of large
numbers, which requires no such compensating tendencies of the coin. The
probability of heads remains one-half for each toss despite the preponderance,
so far, of tails. In the sufficiently long run what “compensates” for the
presence of improbably long subsequences in which, say, tails strongly
predominate, is simply that such subsequences occur rarely and therefore have
only a slight effect on the statistical character of the whole. BERNOULLI’S THEOREM, PROBABILITY. R.Ke. game
theory, the theory of the structure of, and the rational strategies for
performing in, games or gamelike human interactions. Although there were
forerunners, game theory was virtually invented by the mathematician John von Neumann
and the economist Oskar Morgenstern in the early 1940s. Its most striking
feature is its compact representation of interactions of two or more choosers,
or players. For example, two players may face two choices each, and in
combination these choices produce four possible outcomes. Actual choices are of
strategies, not of outcomes, although it is assessments of outcomes that
recommend strategies. To do well in a game, even for all choosers to do well,
as is often possible, generally requires taking all other players’ positions
and interests into account. Hence, to evaluate strategies directly, without
reference to the outcomes they might produce in interaction with others, is
conspicuously perverse. It is not surprising, therefore, that in ethics, game
theory has been preeminently applied to utilitarian moral theory. As the
numbers of players and strategies rise, the complexity of games increases
geometrically. If two players have two strategies each and each ranks the four
possible outcomes without ties, there are already seventy-eight strategically
disGalileo Galilei game theory 339 4065A-
AM 339 tinct games. Even minor
real-life interactions may have astronomically greater complexity. One might
complain that this makes game theory useless. Alternatively, one can note that
this makes it realistic and helps us understand why real-life choices are at
least as complex as they sometimes seem. To complicate matters further, players
can choose over probabilistic combinations of their “pure” strategies. Hence,
the original four outcomes in a simple 2 $ 2 game define a continuum of
potential outcomes. After noting the structure of games, one might then be
struck by an immediate implication of this mere description. A rational
individual may be supposed to attempt to maximize her potential or expected
outcome in a game. But if there are two or more choosers in a game, in general
they cannot all maximize simultaneously over their expected outcomes while
assuming that all others are doing likewise. This is a mathematical principle:
in general, we cannot maximize over two functions simultaneously. For example,
the general notion of the greatest good of the greatest number is incoherent.
Hence, in interactive choice contexts, the simple notion of economic rationality
is incoherent. Virtually all of early game theory was dedicated to finding an
alternative principle for resolving game interactions. There are now many
so-called solution theories, most of which are about outcomes rather than
strategies (they stipulate which outcomes or range of outcomes is
game-theoretically rational). There is little consensus on how to generalize
from the ordinary rationality of merely choosing more rather than less (and of
displaying consistent preferences) to the general choice of strategies in
games. Payoffs in early game theory were almost always represented in cardinal,
transferable utilities. Transferable utility is an odd notion that was
evidently introduced to avoid the disdain with which economists then treated
interpersonal comparisons of utility. It seems to be analogous to money. In the
language of contemporary law and economics, one could say the theory is one of
wealth maximization. In the early theory, the rationality conditions were as
follows. (1) In general, if the sums of the payoffs to all players in various
outcomes differ, it is assumed that rational players will manage to divide the
largest possible payoff among themselves. (2) No individual will accept a
payoff below the “security level” obtainable even if all the other players form
a coalition against the individual. (3) Finally, sometimes it is also assumed
that no group of players will rationally accept less than it could get as its
group security level – but in some games, no outcome can meet this condition.
This is an odd combination of individual and collective elements. The
collective elements are plausibly thought of as merely predictive: if we
individually wish to do well, we should combine efforts to help us do best as a
group. But what we want is a theory that converts individual preferences into
collective results. Unfortunately, to put a move doing just this in the
foundations of the theory is questionbegging. Our fundamental burden is to
determine whether a theory of individual rationality can produce collectively
good results, not to stipulate that it must. In the theory with cardinal,
additive payoffs, we can divide games into constant sum games, in which the sum
of all players’ payoffs in each outcome is a constant, and variable sum games.
Zerosum games are a special case of constant sum games. Two-person constant sum
games are games of pure conflict, because each player’s gain is the other’s
loss. In constant sum games with more than two players and in all variable sum
games, there is generally reason for coalition formation to improve payoffs to
members of the coalition (hence, the appeal of assumptions 1 and 3 above).
Games without transferable utility, such as games in which players have only
ordinal preferences, may be characterized as games of pure conflict or of pure
coordination when players’ preference orderings over outcomes are opposite or
identical, respectively, or as games of mixed motive when their orderings are
partly the same and partly reversed. Mathematical analysis of such games is evidently
less tractable than that of games with cardinal, additive utility, and their
theory is only beginning to be extensively developed. Despite the apparent
circularity of the rationality assumptions of early game theory, it is the game
theorists’ prisoner’s dilemma that makes clear that compelling individual
principles of choice can produce collectively deficient outcomes. This game was
discovered about 1950 and later given its catchy but inapt name. If they play
it in isolation from any other interaction between them, two players in this
game can each do what seems individually best and reach an outcome that both
consider inferior to the outcome that results from making opposite strategy
choices. Even with the knowledge that this is the problem they face, the
players still have incentive to choose the strategies that jointly produce the
inferior outcome. Prisoner’s dilemma involves both coordination and conflict.
It has played a central role in contemporary discusgame theory game theory 340
4065A- AM 340 sions of moral and political philosophy.
Games that predominantly involve coordination, such as when we coordinate in
all driving on the right or all on the left, have a similarly central role. The
understanding of both classes of games has been read into the political
philosophies of Hobbes and Hume and into mutual advantage theories of
justice. DECISION THEORY, PRISONER’S
DILEMMA, UTILITARIANISM. R.Har. Gandhi, Mohandas Karamchand, called Mahatma
(1869–1948), Indian nationalist leader, an advocate of nonviolent mass
political action who opposed racial discrimination in South Africa (1893–1914)
and British colonial rule in India. He called his approach Satyagraha (Sanskrit
satya, ‘truth’, and agraha, ‘force’), considering it a science whose end is
truth (which he identified with God) and method nonviolence (ahimsa). He
emphasized constructive resolution, rather than elimination, of conflict, the
interrelatedness of means and ends (precluding evil means to good ends), and
the importance of enduring suffering oneself rather than inflicting it upon
adversaries. Gandhi believed limited knowledge of truth deprives us of a
warrant to use violence. He took nonviolence to be more than mere abstention
from violence and to call for courage, discipline, and love of an opponent.
Ordinary persons can practice it without full understanding of Satyagraha,
which he himself disclaimed. He came to distinguish Satyagraha from passive
resistance, a weapon of the weak that can turn to violence when faced with
failure. Satyagraha requires strength and consistency and cannot be used in an
unjust cause. Not an absolutist, Gandhi said that though nonviolence is always
preferable, when forced to choose between violence and cowardice one might
better choose violence. He was a man of practice more than a theoretician and
claimed the superiority of Satyagraha to violence could be proven only be
demonstration, not argument. He saw his work as an experiment with truth. He
was influenced particularly by the Bhagavad Gita from Hindu thought, the Sermon
on the Mount from Christianity, and the writings of Tolstoy, Ruskin, Emerson,
and Thoreau. BHAGAVAD GITA, NONVIOLENCE,
PACIFISM. R.L.H. Gassendi, Pierre (1592–1655), French philosopher and scientist
who advocated a via media to scientific knowledge about the empirically
observable material world that avoids both the dogmatism of Cartesians, who
claimed to have certain knowledge, and the skepticism of Montaigne and Charron,
who doubted that we have knowledge about anything. Gassendi presented Epicurean
atomism as a model for explaining how bodies are structured and interact. He
advanced a hypothetico-deductive method by proposing that experiments should be
used to test mechanistic hypotheses. Like the ancient Pyrrhonian Skeptics, he
did not challenge the immediate reports of our senses; but unlike them he
argued that while we cannot have knowledge of the inner essences of things, we
can develop a reliable science of the world of appearances. In this he
exemplified the mitigated skepticism of modern science that is always open to
revision on the basis of empirical evidence. Gassendi’s first book,
Exercitationes Paradoxicae Adversis Aristoteleos (1624), is an attack on
Aristotle. He is best known as the author of the fifth set of objections to
Descartes’s Meditations(1641), in which Gassendi proposed that even clear and
distinct ideas may represent no objects outside our minds, a possibility that
Descartes called the objection of objections, but dismissed as destructive of
all reason. Gassendi’s Syntagma Philosophiae Epicuri (1649) contains his
development of Epicurean philosophy and science. His elaboration of the
mechanistic atomic model and his advocacy of experimental testing of hypotheses
were crucially important in the rise of modern science. Gassendi’s career as a
Catholic priest, Epicurean atomist, mitigated skeptic, and mechanistic
scientist presents a puzzle – as do the careers of several other
philosopher-priests in the seventeenth century – concerning his true beliefs.
On the one hand, he professed faith and set aside Christian doctrine as not
open to challenge. On the other hand, he utilized an arsenal of skeptical
arguments that was beginning to undermine and would eventually destroy the
rational foundations of the church. Gassendi thus appears to be of a type
almost unknown today, a thinker indifferent to the apparent discrepancy between
his belief in Christian doctrine and his advocacy of materialist science. DESCARTES, EPICUREANISM, SKEPTICS. R.A.W.
Gauss, Carl Friedrich.NON-EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY. Gay, John (1699–1745), British
moralist who tried to reconcile divine command theory and utilitarianism. The
son of a minister, Gay was Gandhi, Mohandas Karamchand Gay, John 341
4065A- AM 341 elected a fellow of Sidney Sussex
College, Cambridge, where he taught church history, Hebrew, and Greek. His one
philosophical essay, “Dissertation Concerning the Fundamental Principle of
Virtue or Morality” (1731), argues that obligation is founded on the will of
God, which, because people are destined to be happy, directs us to act to
promote the general happiness. Gay offers an associationist psychology
according to which we pursue objects that have come to be associated with
happiness (e.g. money), regardless of whether they now make us happy, and
argues, contra Hutcheson, that our moral sense is conditioned rather than
natural. Gay’s blend of utilitarianism with associationist psychology gave
David Hartley the basis for his moral psychology, which later influenced
Bentham in his formulation of classical utilitarianism. HARTLEY, HUTCHESON, MORAL SENSE THEORY.
E.S.R. GCH.Appendix of Special Symbols. Geach, Peter (b.1916), English
philosopher and logician whose main work has been in logic and philosophy of
language. A great admirer of McTaggart, he has published a sympathetic
exposition of the latter’s work (Truth, Love and Immortality, 1979), and has
always aimed to emulate what he sees as the clarity and rigor of the Scottish
idealist’s thought. Greatly influenced by Frege and Wittgenstein, Geach is
particularly noted for his powerful use of what he calls “the Frege point,”
better called “the Frege-Geach point,” that the same thought may occur as
asserted or unasserted and yet retain the same truth-value. The point has been
used by Geach to refute ascriptivist theories of responsibility, and can be
employed against noncognitivist theories of ethics, which are said to face the
Frege-Geach problem of accounting for the sense of moral ascriptions in
contexts like ‘If he did wrong, he will be punished’. He is also noted for
helping to bring Frege to the English-speaking world, through co-translations
with Max Black (1909– 88). In logic he is known for proving, independently of
Quine, a contradiction in Frege’s way out of Russell’s paradox (Mind, 1956),
and for his defense of modern Fregean-Russellian logic against traditional
Aristotelian-Scholastic logic. He also has a deep admiration for the Polish
logicians. In metaphysics, Geach is known for his defense of relative identity,
the thesis that an object a can be the same F (where F is a kind-term) as an
object b while not being the same G, even though a and b are both G’s. His
spirited defense of the thesis has been met by equally vigorous attacks, and it
has not received wide acceptance. An obvious application of the thesis is to
the defense of the doctrine of the Trinity (e.g., the Father is the same god as
the Son but not the same person), which has caught the attention of some
philosophers of religion. Geach’s main works include Mental Acts (1958), which
attacks dispositional theories of mind, Reference and Generality (1962), which
contains much important work on logic, and the collection Logic Matters (1972).
A notable defender of Catholicism (despite his animadversions against
Scholastic logic), his religious views find their greatest exposure in God and
the Soul (1969), Providence and Evil (1977), and The Virtues (1977). He is
married to the philosopher Elizabeth Anscombe.
ASCRIPTIVISM, FREGE, IDENTITY, MCTAGGART, RUSSELL, WITTGENSTEIN. D.S.O.
Gegenstandstheorie.ACT-OBJECT PSYCHOLOGY. Geist.HEGEL.
Geisteswissenschaften.WEBER. Gemeinschaft.SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY. gender
theory.POSTMODERN. genealogy.FOUCAULT, NIETZSCHE. generality.VAGUENESS.
generalizability.UNIVERSALIZABILITY. generalization, existential.EXISTENTIAL GENERALIZATION.
generalization, universal.UNIVERSALIZABILITY. generalization
argument.UNIVERSALIZABILITY. generalization principle.UNIVERSALIZABILITY.
generalized continuum hypothesis.Appendix of Special Symbols. generalized
quantifier.FORMAL LOGIC. general jurisprudence.JURISPRUDENCE, PHILOSOPHY OF
LAW. GCH general jurisprudence 342 4065A-
AM 342 general
relativity.RELATIVITY. general systems theory.SYSTEMS THEORY. general term.
SINGULAR TERM. general
will.ROUSSEAU. generative grammar.GRAMMAR. generic consistency, principle
of.UNIVERSALIZABILITY. generic sentence.PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE. genetic
epistemology.PIAGET. genetic fallacy.INFORMAL FALLACY. genotext.KRISTEVA.
Gentile, Giovanni (1875–1944), Italian idealist philosopher and educational
reformer. He taught at the universities of Palermo, Pisa, and Rome, and became
minister of education in the first years of Mussolini’s government (1922–24).
He was the most influential intellectual of the Fascist regime and promoted a
radical transformation of the Italian school system, most of which did not
survive that era. Gentile rejected Hegel’s dialectics as the process of an
objectified thought. His actualism (or actual idealism) claims that only the
pure act of thinking or the Transcendental Subject can undergo a dialectical
process. All reality, such as nature, God, good, and evil, is immanent in the
dialectics of the Transcendental Subject, which is distinct from Empirical
Subjects. Among his major works are La teoria generale dello spirito come atto
puro (1916; translated as The Theory of Mind as Pure Act, 1922) and Sistema di
logica come teoria del conoscere (“System of Logic as a Theory of Knowledge,”
1917). Gentile’s pedagogical views were also influenced by actualism. Education
is an act that overcomes the difficulties of intersubjective communication and
realizes the unity of the pupil and the teacher within the Transcendental
Subject (Sommario di pedagogia come scienza filosofica, “Summary of Pedagogy as
a Philosophical Science,” 1913–14). Actualism was influential in Italy during
Gentile’s life. With Croce’s historicism, it influenced British idealists like
Bosanquet and Collingwood. IDEALISM.
P.Gar. genus.DEFINITION. genus, summum.GENUS GENERALISSIMUM. genus generalissimum
(Latin, ‘most general genus’), a genus that is not a species of some higher
genus; a broadest natural kind. One of the ten Aristotelian categories, it is
also called summum genus (highest genus). For Aristotle and many of his
followers, the ten categories are not species of some higher all-inclusive
genus – say, being. Otherwise, that all-inclusive genus would wholly include
its differences, and would be universally predicable of them. But no genus is
predicable of its differences in this manner. Few authors explained this
reasoning clearly, but some pointed out that if the difference ‘rational’ just
meant ‘rational animal’, then to define ‘man’ as ‘rational animal’ would be to
define him as ‘rational animal animal’, which is ill formed. So too generally:
no genus can include its differences in this way. Thus there is no
all-inclusive genus; the ten categories are the most general genera. DEFINITION, PRAEDICAMENTA, PREDICABLES.
P.V.S. geometric conventionalism.POINCARÉ. geometry, Euclidean.EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY.
geometry, non-Euclidean.NON-EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY. Gerson, Jean de, original name,
Jean Charlier (1363–1429), French theologian, philosopher, and ecclesiastic. He
studied in Paris, and succeeded the nominalist Pierre d’Ailly as chancellor of
the university in 1395. Both d’Ailly and Gerson played a prominent part in the
work of the Council of Constance (1414–18). Much of Gerson’s influence on later
thinkers arose from his conciliarism, the view that the church is a political
society and that a general council, acting on behalf of the church, has the
power to depose a pope who fails to promote the church’s welfare, for it seemed
that similar arguments could apply to other forms of political society.
Gerson’s conciliarism was not constitutionalism in the modern sense, for he
appealed to corporate and hierarchical ideas of church government, and did not
rest his case on any principle of individual rights. His main writings dealt
with mystical theology, which, he thought, brings the believer closer to the
beatific vision of God than do other forms of theology. He was influenced by
general relativity Gerson, Jean de 343 4065A-
AM 343 St. Bonaventure and
Albertus Magnus, but especially by Pseudo-Dionysius, whom he saw as a disciple
of St. Paul and not as a Platonist. He was thus able to adopt an anti-Platonic
position in his attacks on the mystic Ruysbroeck and on contemporary followers
of Duns Scotus, such as Jean de Ripa. In dismissing Scotist realism, he made
use of nominalist positions, particularly those that emphasized divine freedom.
He warned theologians against being misled by pride into supposing that natural
reason alone could solve metaphysical problems; and he emphasized the
importance of a priest’s pastoral duties. Despite his early prominence, he
spent the last years of his life in relative obscurity. E.J.A. Gersonides, also
called Levi ben Gershom (1288–1344), French Jewish philosopher and
mathematician, the leading Jewish Aristotelian after Maimonides. Gersonides was
also a distinguished Talmudist, Bible commentator, and astronomer. His
philosophical writings include supercommentaries on most of Averroes’
commentaries on Aristotle (1319–24); On the Correct Syllogism (1319), a
treatise on the modal syllogism; and a major Scholastic treatise, The Wars of
the Lord (1317–29). In addition, his biblical commentaries rank among the best
examples of philosophical scriptural exegesis; especially noteworthy is his
interpretation of the Song of Songs as an allegory describing the ascent of the
human intellect to the agent intellect. Gersonides’ mentors in the Aristotelian
tradition were Maimonides and Averroes. However, more than either of them,
Gersonides held philosophical truth and revealed truth to be coextensive: he
acknowledged neither the conflict that Averroes saw between reason and revelation
nor Maimonides’ critical view of the limitations of the human intellect.
Furthermore, while remaining within the Aristotelian framework, Gersonides was
not uncritical of it; his independence can be illustrated by two of his most
distinctive positions. First, against Maimonides, Gersonides claimed that it is
possible to demonstrate both the falsity of the Aristotelian theory of the
eternity of the world (Averroes’ position) and the absurdity of creation ex
nihilo, the traditional rabbinic view that Maimonides adopted, though for
nondemonstrative reasons. Instead Gersonides advocated the Platonic theory of
temporal creation from primordial matter. Second, unlike Maimonides and
Averroes, who both held that the alleged contradiction between divine foreknowledge
of future contingent particulars and human freedom is spurious, Gersonides took
the dilemma to be real. In defense of human freedom, he then argued that it is
logically impossible even for God to have knowledge of particulars as
particulars, since his knowledge is only of general laws. At the same time, by
redefining ‘omniscience’ as knowing everything that is knowable, he showed that
this impossibility is no deficiency in God’s knowledge. Although Gersonides’
biblical commentaries received wide immediate acceptance, subsequent medieval
Jewish philosophers, e.g., Hasdai Crescas, by and large reacted negatively to
his rigorously rationalistic positions. Especially with the decline of
Aristotelianism within the philosophical world, both Jewish and Christian, he
was either criticized sharply or simply ignored. ARISTOTLE, AVERROES, JEWISH PHILOSOPHY,
MAIMONIDES, PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. J.Ste. Gesellschaft.SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY.
Gestalt.FIGURE–GROUND, KÖHLER. Gestalt psychology.KÖHLER. Gettier
problem.EPISTEMOLOGY. Gettier-style example.EPISTEMOLOGY. Geulincx, Arnold
(1624–69), Dutch philosopher. Born in Antwerp, he was educated at Louvain and
there became professor of philosophy (1646) and dean (1654). In 1657 he was
forced out of Louvain, perhaps for his Jansenist or Cartesian tendencies, and
in 1658 he moved to Leyden and became a Protestant. Though he taught there
until his death, he never attained a regular professorship at the university.
His main philosophical work is his Ethica (1675), only Part I of which appeared
during his lifetime as De virtute et primis ejus proprietatibus (1665). Also
published during his lifetime were the Questiones quodlibeticae (1652; later
editions published as Saturnalia), a Logica (1661), and a Methodus inveniendi
argumenta (1665). His most important works, though, were published
posthumously; in addition to the Ethica, there is the Physica vera (1688), the
Physica peripatetica (1690), the Metaphysica vera (1691), and the Metaphysica
ad mentem peripateticam (1691). There are also two posthumous commentaries on
Descartes’s Principia Philosophiae (1690 and 1691). Geulincx was deeply
influenced by Descartes, and had many ideas that closely resemble those
Gersonides Geulincx, Arnold 344 4065A- AM 344 of the later Cartesians as well as those
of more independent thinkers like Spinoza and Leibniz. Though his grounds were
original, like many later Cartesians, Geulincx upheld a version of
occasionalism; he argued that someone or something can only do what it knows
how to do, inferring from that that we cannot be the genuine causes of our own
bodily movements. In discussing the mind–body relation, Geulincx used a clock
analogy similar to one Leibniz used in connection with his preestablished
harmony. Geulincx also held a view of mental and material substance reminiscent
of that of Spinoza. Finally, he proposed a system of ethics grounded in the
idea of a virtuous will. Despite the evident similarities between Geulincx’s
views and the views of his more renowned contemporaries, it is very difficult
to determine exactly what influence Geulincx may have had on them, and they may
have had on him. DESCARTES, LEIBNIZ,
OCCASIONALISM. D.Garb. Ghazali, al-.AL-GHAZALI. ghost in the machine.RYLE.
Giles of Rome, original name, Egidio Colonna (c.1243–1316), Italian theologian
and ecclesiastic. A member of the order of the Hermits of St. Augustine, he
studied arts at Augustinian house and theology at the University in Paris
(1260– 72) but was censured by the theology faculty (1277) and denied a license
to teach as master. Owing to the intervention of Pope Honorius IV, he later
returned from Italy to Paris to teach theology (1285–91), was appointed general
of his order (1292), and became archbishop of Bourges (1295). Giles both
defended and criticized views of Aquinas. He held that essence and existence
are really distinct in creatures, but described them as “things”; that prime
matter cannot exist without some substantial form; and, early in his career,
that an eternally created world is possible. He defended only one substantial
form in composites, including man. He supported Pope Boniface VIII in his
quarrel with Philip IV of France. J.F.W. Gilson, Étienne (1884–1978), French
Catholic philosopher, historian, cofounder of the Pontifical Institute of
Medieval Studies in Toronto, and a major figure in Neo-Thomism. Gilson
discovered medieval philosophy through his pioneering work on Descartes’s
Scholastic background. As a historian, he argued that early modern philosophy
was incomprehensible without medieval thought, and that medieval philosophy
itself did not represent the unified theory of reality that some Thomists had
supposed. His studies of Duns Scotus, Augustine, Bernard, Aquinas, Bonaventure,
Dante, and Abelard and Héloïse explore this diversity. But in his Gifford
lectures (1931–32), The Spirit of Medieval Philosophy, Gilson attempted a broad
synthesis of medieval teaching on philosophy, metaphysics, ethics, and
epistemology, and employed it in his critique of modern philosophy, The Unity
of Philosophical Experience (1937). Most of all, Gilson attempted to
reestablish Aquinas’s distinction between essence and existence in created
being, as in Being and Some Philosophers (1949). NEO-THOMISM, THOMISM. D.W.H. Gioberti, Vincenzo
(1801–52), Italian philosopher and statesman. He was an ordained priest, was
imprisoned and exiled for advocating Italian unification, and became a central
political figure during the Risorgimento. His major political work, Del primato
morale e civile degli Italiani (“On the Moral and Civil Primacy of Italians,”
1843), argues for a federation of the Italian states with the pope as its
leader. Gioberti’s philosophical theory, ontologism, in contrast to Hegel’s
idealism, identifies the dialectics of Being with God’s creation. He condensed
his theory in the formula: “Being creates the existent.” The dialectics of
Being, which is the only necessary substance, is a palingenesis, or a return to
its origin, in which the existent first departs from and imitates its creator
(mimesis), and then returns to its creator (methexis). By intuition, the human
mind comes in contact with God and discovers truth by retracing the dialectics
of Being. However, knowledge of supernatural truths is given only by God’s
revelation (Teorica del soprannaturale [“Theory of the Supernatural,” 1838] and
Introduzione allo studio della filosofia [“Introduction to the Study of
Philosophy,” 1841]). Gioberti criticized modern philosophers such as Descartes
for their psychologism – seeking truth from the human subject instead of from
Being itself and its revelation. His thought is still influential in Italy,
especially in Christian spiritualism. P.Gar. given, in epistemology, the “brute
fact” element to be found or postulated as a component of perceptual
experience. Some theorists who endorse the existence of a given element in
experience think that we can find this element by careful Ghazali, al- given
345 4065A- AM 345 introspection of what we experience
(Moore, H. H. Price). Such theorists generally distinguish between those components
of ordinary perceptual awareness that constitute what we believe or know about
the objects we perceive and those components that we strictly perceive. For
example, if we analyze introspectively what we are aware of when we see an
apple we find that what we believe of the apple is that it is a
three-dimensional object with a soft, white interior; what we see of it,
strictly speaking, is just a red-shaped expanse of one of its facing sides.
This latter is what is “given” in the intended sense. Other theorists treat the
given as postulated rather than introspectively found. For example, some
theorists treat cognition as an activity imposing form on some material given
in conscious experience. On this view, often attributed to Kant, the given and
the conceptual are interdefined and logically inseparable. Sometimes this
interdependence is seen as rendering a description of the given as impossible;
in this case the given is said to be ineffable (C. I. Lewis, Mind and the World
Order, 1929). On some theories of knowledge (foundationalism) the first variant
of the given – that which is “found” rather than “postulated” – provides the
empirical foundations of what we might know or justifiably believe. Thus, if I
believe on good evidence that there is a red apple in front of me, the evidence
is the non-cognitive part of my perceptual awareness of the red appleshaped
expanse. Epistemologies postulating the first kind of givenness thus require a
single entity-type to explain the sensorial nature of perception and to provide
immediate epistemic foundations for empirical knowledge. This requirement is
now widely regarded as impossible to satisfy; hence Wilfred Sellars describes
the discredited view as the myth of the given.
PERCEPTION; PHENOMENALISM; SELLARS, WILFRID. T.V. given, myth of
the.SELLARS, WILFRID. Glanvill, Joseph (1636–80), English philosopher and
Anglican minister who defended the Royal Society against Scholasticism.
Glanvill believed that certainty was possible in mathematics and theology, but
not in empirical knowledge. In his most important philosophical work, The
Vanity of Dogmatizing (1661), he claimed that the human corruption that
resulted from Adam’s fall precludes dogmatic knowledge of nature. Using
traditional skeptical arguments as well as an analysis of causality that
partially anticipated Hume, Glanvill argued that all empirical knowledge is the
probabilistic variety acquired by piecemeal investigation. Despite his
skepticism he argued for the existence of witches in Witches and Witchcraft (1668).
J.W.A. Gleason’s theorem.QUANTUM LOGIC. global supervenience.SUPERVENIENCE.
gnosticism, a dualistic religious and philosophical movement in the early
centuries of the Christian church, especially important in the second century
under the leadership of Valentinus and Basilides. They taught that matter was
evil, the result of a cosmic disruption in which an evil archon (often
associated with the god of the Old Testament, Yahweh) rebelled against the
heavenly pleroma (the complete spiritual world). In the process divine sparks
were unleashed from the pleroma and lodged in material human bodies. Jesus was
a high-ranking archon (Logos) sent to restore those souls with divine sparks to
the pleroma by imparting esoteric knowledge (gnosis) to them. Gnosticism
influenced and threatened the orthodox church from within and without.
NonChristian gnostic sects rivaled Christianity, and Christian gnostics
threatened orthodoxy by emphasizing salvation by knowledge rather than by
faith. Theologians like Clement of Alexandria and his pupil Origen held that
there were two roads to salvation, the way of faith for the masses and the way
of esoteric or mystical knowledge for the philosophers. Gnosticism profoundly
influenced the early church, causing it to define its scriptural canon and to
develop a set of creeds and an episcopal organization. CLEMENT OF ALEXANDRIA, ORIGEN. L.P.P.
goal-directed system.
COMPUTER THEORY,
CYBERNETICS. Göckel, Rudolph.GOCLENIUS. Goclenius, Rudolphus, in Germany,
Rudolf Göckel (1547–1628), German philosopher. After holding some minor posts
elsewhere, Goclenius became professor at the University of Marburg in 1581,
where he remained until his death, teaching physics, logic, mathematics, and
ethics. Though he was well read and knowledgeable of later trends in these
disciplines, his basic sympathies were Aristotelian. Goclenius was very well
given, myth of the Goclenius, Rudolphus 346 4065A- AM 346
regarded by his contemporaries, who called him the Plato of Marburg, the
Christian Aristotle, and the Light of Europe, among other things. He published
an unusually large number of books, including the Psychologia, hoc est de
hominis perfectione . . . (1590), the Conciliator philosophicus (1609), the
Controversiae logicae et philosophicae (1609), and numerous other works on
logic, rhetoric, physics, metaphysics, and the Latin language. But his most
lasting work was his Lexicon Philosophicum (1613), together with its companion,
the Lexicon Philosophicum Graecum (1615). These lexicons provide clear
definitions of the philosophical terminology of late Scholastic philosophy, and
are still useful as reference works for sixteenth- and early seventeenth-century
thought. D.Garb. God.DIVINE ATTRIBUTES, PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. God, arguments
for the existence of.DIVINE ATTRIBUTES, ENS A SE, PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION.
Gödel, Kurt.GÖDEL’S INCOMPLETENESS THEOREMS. Gödel numbering.GÖDEL’S
INCOMPLETENESS THEOREMS. Gödel’s incompleteness theorems, two theorems
formulated and proved by the Austrian logician Kurt Gödel (1906–78) in his
famous 1931 paper “Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica
und vervandter Systeme I,” probably the most celebrated results in the whole of
logic. They are aptly referred to as “incompleteness” theorems since each
shows, for any member of a certain class of formal systems, that there is a
sentence formulable in its language that it cannot prove, but that it would be
desirable for it to prove. In the case of the first theorem (G1), what cannot
be proved is a true sentence of the language of the given theory. G1 is thus a
disappointment to any theory constructor who wants his theory to tell the whole
truth about its subject. In the case of the second theorem (G2), what cannot be
proved is a sentence of the theory that “expresses” its consistency. G2 is thus
a disappointment to those who desire a straightforward execution of Hilbert’s
Program. The proofs of the incompleteness theorems can be seen as based on
three main ideas. The first is that of a Gödel numbering, i.e., an assignment
of natural numbers to each of the various objects (i.e., the terms, formulas,
axioms, proofs, etc.) belonging to the various syntactical categories of the
given formal system T (referred to here as the “represented theory”) whose
metamathematics is under consideration. The second is that of a
representational scheme. This includes (i) the use of the Gödel numbering to
develop number-theoretic codifications of various of the metamathematical
properties pertaining to the represented theory, and (ii) the selection of a
theory S (hereafter, the “representing theory”) and a family of formulas from
that theory (the “representing formulas”) in terms of which to register as
theorems various of the facts concerning the metamathematical properties of the
represented theory thus encoded. The basic result of this representational
scheme is the weak representation of the set of (Gödel numbers of) theorems of
T, where a set L of numbers is said to be weakly represented in S by a formula
‘L(x)’ of S just in case for every number n, n1 L if and only if ‘L([n])’ is a
theorem of S, where ‘[n]’ is the standard term of S that, under the intended
interpretation of S, designates the number n. Since the set of (Gödel numbers
of) theorems of the represented theory T will typically be recursively
enumerable, and the representing theory S must be capable of weakly
representing this set, the basic strength requirement on S is that it be
capable of weakly representing the recursively enumerable sets of natural
numbers. Because basic systems of arithmetic (e.g. Robinson’s arithmetic and
Peano arithmetic) all have this capacity, Gödel’s theorems are often stated
using containment of a fragment of arithmetic as the basic strength requirement
governing the capacities of the representing theory (which, of course, is also
often the represented theory). More on this point below. The third main idea
behind the incompleteness theorems is that of a diagonal or fixed point
construction within S for the notion of unprovability-in-T; i.e., the
formulation of a sentence Gödel of S which, under the given Gödel numbering of
T, the given representation of T’s metamathematical notions in S, and the
intended interpretation of the language of S, says of itself that it is not
provable-in-T. Gödel is thus false if provable and unprovable if true. More
specifically, if ‘ProvT(x)’ is a formula of S that weakly represents the set of
(Gödel numbers of) theorems of T in S, then Gödel can be any formula of S that
is provably equivalent in S to the formula ‘- ProvT ([Gödel])’. Given this
background, G1 can be stated as follows: If (a) the representing theory S is
any subtheory of the represented theory T (up to and God Gödel’s incompleteness
theorems 347 4065A- AM 347 including the represented theory itself),
(b) the representing theory S is consistent, (c) the formula ‘ProvT (x)’ weakly
represents the set of (Gödel numbers of) theorems of the represented theory T
in the representing theory S, and (d) Gödel is any sentence provably equivalent
in the representing theory S to ‘ProvT ([Gödel])’, then neither Gödel nor
-Gödel is a theorem of the representing theory S. The proof proceeds in two
parts. In the first part it is shown that, for any representing theory S (up to
and including the case where S % T ), if S is consistent, then -Gödel is not a
theorem of S. To obtain this in its strongest form, we pick the strongest
subtheory S of T possible, namely S % T, and construct a reductio. Thus,
suppose that (1) -Gödel is a theorem of T. From (1) and (d) it follows that (2)
‘ProvT([Gödel])’ is a theorem of T. And from (2) and (c) (in the “if”
direction) it follows that (3) Gödel is a theorem of T. But (1) and (3)
together imply that the representing theory T is inconsistent. Hence, if T is
consistent, -Gödel cannot be a theorem of T. In the second part of the proof it
is argued that if the representing theory S is consistent, then Gödel is not a
theorem of it. Again, to obtain the strongest result, we let S be the strongest
subtheory of T possible (namely T itself) and, as before, argue by reductio.
Thus we suppose that (A) Gödel is a theorem of S (% T ). From this assumption
and condition (d) it follows that (B) ‘-Provr ([Gödel])’ is a theorem of S (% T
). By (A) and (c) (in the “only if” direction) it follows that (C) ‘ProvT
([Gödel])’ is a theorem of S (% T ). But from (B) and (C) it follows that S (%
T ) is inconsistent. Hence, Gödel is not provable in any consistent
representing theory S up to and including T itself. The above statement of G1
is, of course, not the usual one. The usual statement suppresses the
distinction stressed above between the representing and represented theories
and collaterally replaces our condition (c) with a clause to the effect that T
is a recursively axiomatizable extension of some suitably weak system of
arithmetic (e.g. Robinson’s arithmetic, primitive recursive arithmetic, or
Peano arithmetic). This puts into a single clause what, metamathematically
speaking, are two separate conditions – one pertaining to the representing
theory, the other to the represented theory. The requirement that T be an
extension of the selected weak arithmetic addresses the question of T’s
adequacy as a representing theory, since the crucial fact about extensions of
the weak arithmetic chosen is that they are capable of weakly representing all
recursively enumerable sets. This constraint on T’s capabilities as a
representing theory is in partnership with the usual requirement that, in its
capacity as a represented theory, T be recursively axiomatizable. For T’s
recursive axiomatizability ensures (under ordinary choices of logic for T )
that its set of theorems will be recursively enumerable – and hence weakly
representable in the kind of representing theory that it itself (by virtue of
its being an extension of the weak arithmetic specified) is. G1 can, however,
be extended to certain theories whose sets of (Gödel numbers of) theorems are
not recursively enumerable. When this is done, the basic capacity required of
the representing theory is no longer merely that the recursively enumerable
sets of natural numbers be representable in it, but that it also be capable of
representing various non-recursively enumerable sets, and hence that it go
beyond the weak arithmetics mentioned earlier. G2 is a more demanding result
that G1 in that it puts significantly stronger demands on the formula ‘ProvT
(x)’ used to express the notion of provability for the represented theory T. In
proving G1 all that is required of ‘ProvT (x)’ is that it weakly represent θ (%
the set of Gödel numbers of theorems of T); i.e., that it yield an
extensionally accurate registry of the theorems of the represented theory in
the representing theory. G2 places additional conditions on ‘ProvT (x)’;
conditions which result from the fact that, to prove G2, we must codify the
second part of the proof of G1 in T itself. To do this, ‘ProvT (x)’ must be a
provability predicate for T. That is, it must satisfy the following
constraints, commonly referred to as the Derivability Conditions (for ‘ProvT
(x)’): (I) If A is a theorem of the represented theory, then ‘ProvT ([A])’ must
be a theorem of the representing theory. (II) Every instance of the formula ‘ProvT
([A P B]) P (ProvT ([A]) P ProvT ([B]))’ must be a theorem of T. (III) Every
instance of the formula ‘ProvT ([A]) P ProvT ([ProvT ([A])])’ must be a theorem
of T. (I), of course, is just part of the requirement that ‘ProvT ([A])’ weakly
represent T’s theoremset in T. So it does not go beyond what is required for
the proof of G1. (II) and (III), however, do. They make it possible to
“formalize” the second part of the proof of G1 in T itself. (II) captures, in
terms of ‘ProvT (X)’, the modus ponens inference by which (B) is derived from
(A), and (III) codiGödel’s incompleteness theorems Gödel’s incompleteness
theorems 348 4065A- AM 348 fies in T the appeal to (c) used in deriving
(C) from (A). The result of this “formalization” process is a proof within T of
the formula ‘ConT P Gödel’ (where ConT is a formula of the form ‘- ProvT
([#])’, with ‘ProvT (x)’ a provability predicate for T and ‘[#]’ the standard
numeral denoting the Gödel number # of some formula refutable in T ). From
this, and the proof of the second part of G1 itself (in which the first
Derivability Condition, which is just the “only if” direction of (c), figures
prominently), we arrive at the following result, which is a generalized form of
G2: If S is any consistent representing theory up to and including the
represented theory T itself, ‘ProvT (x)’ any provability predicate for T, and
ConT any formula of T of the form ‘- ProvT ([#])’, then ConT is not a theorem
of S. To the extent that, in being a provability predicate for T, ‘ProvT (x)’ “expresses”
the notion of provability of the represented theory T, it seems fair to say
that ConT expresses its consistency. And to the extent that this is true, it is
sensible to read G2 as saying that for any representing theory S and any
represented theory T extending S, if S is consistent, then the consistency of T
is not provable in S. COMPUTER THEORY,
CONSISTENCY, HILBERT’S PROGRAM, PROOF THEORY. M.D. Godfrey of Fontaines
(probably before 1250– 1306 or 1309), French philosopher. He taught theology at
Paris (1285–c.1299; 1303–04). Among his major writings are fifteen Quodlibetal
Questions and other disputations. He was strongly Aristotelian in philosophy,
with Neoplatonic influences in metaphysics. He defended identity of essence and
existence in creatures against theories of their real or intentional
distinction, and argued for the possibility of demonstrating God’s existence
and of some quidditative knowledge of God. He admitted divine ideas for species
but not for individuals within species. He made wide applications of
Aristotelian actpotency theory – e.g., to the distinction between the soul and
its powers, to the explanation of intellection and volition, to the general
theory of substance and accident, and in unusual fashion to essence-existence “composition”
of creatures. J.F.W. Godwin, William (1756–1836), English philosopher,
novelist, and political writer. Godwin’s main philosophical treatise, Enquiry
concerning Political Justice (1793), aroused heated debate. He argued for
radical forms of determinism, anarchism, and utilitarianism. Government
corrupts everyone by encouraging stereotyped thinking that prevents us from
seeing each other as unique individuals. Godwin’s novel Caleb Williams (1794)
portrays a good man corrupted by prejudice. Once we remove prejudice and
artificial inequality we will see that our acts are wholly determined. This
makes punishment pointless. Only in small, anarchic societies can people see
others as they really are and thus come to feel sympathetic concern for their wellbeing.
Only so can we be virtuous, because virtue is acting from sympathetic feelings
to bring the greatest happiness to all affected. Godwin took this principle
quite literally, and accepted all its consequences. Truthfulness has no claim
on us other than the happiness it brings. If keeping a promise causes less good
than breaking it, there is no reason at all to keep it. If one must choose
between saving the life either of a major human benefactor or of one’s mother,
one must choose the benefactor. Ideally we would need no rules in morals at
all. They prevent us from seeing others properly, thereby impairing the
sympathetic feelings that constitute virtue. Rights are pointless since
sympathetic people will act to help others. Later utilitarians like Bentham had
difficulty in separating their positions from Godwin’s notorious views. BENTHAM. J.B.S. Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von
(1749–1832), German writer often considered the leading cultural figure of his
age. He wrote lyric poetry, dramas, and fictional, essayistic, and aphoristic
prose as well as works in various natural sciences, including anatomy, botany,
and optics. A lawyer by training, for most of his life Goethe was a government
official at the provincial court of Saxony-Weimar. In his numerous contributions
to world literature, such as the novels The Sorrows of Young Werther (1774),
Wilhelm Meister’s Years of Apprenticeship (1795/96), Elective Affinities
(1809), and Wilhelm Meister’s Years of Pilgrimage (1821/29), and the two-part
tragedy Faust (1808/32), Goethe represented the tensions between individual and
society as well as between culture and nature, with increased recognition of
their tragic opposition and the need to cultivate a resigned self-discipline in
artistic and social matters. In his poetic and scientific treatment of nature
he was influenced by Spinoza’s pantheist identification of nature and God and
maintained that everything in nature is animate and expressive of divine
presence. In his theory and practice of science he opposed the quantitative and
experimental method and Godfrey of Fontaines Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von 349
4065A- AM 349 insisted on a description of the
phenomena that was to include the intuitive grasp of the archetypal forms or
shapes underlying all development in nature.
PANTHEISM, SPINOZA. G.Z. Goldbach’s conjecture.CHOICE SEQUENCE. golden
mean.ARISTOTLE. Goldman, Alvin I(ra) (b.1938), American philosopher who has
made notable contributions to action theory, naturalistic and social
epistemology, philosophy of mind, and cognitive science. He has persistently
urged the relevance of cognitive and social science to problems in
epistemology, metaphysics, the philosophy of mind, and ethics. A Theory of
Human Action (1970) proposes a causal theory of action, describes the generative
structure of basic and non-basic action, and argues for the compatibility of
free will and determinism. In “Epistemics: The Regulative Theory of Cognition”
(1978), he argued that traditional epistemology should be replaced by
‘epistemics’, which differs from traditional epistemology in characterizing
knowledge, justified belief, and rational belief in light of empirical
cognitive science. Traditional epistemology has used a coarse-grained notion of
belief, taken too restrictive a view of cognitive methods, offered advice for
ideal cognizers rather than for human beings with limited cognitive resources,
and ignored flaws in our cognitive system that must be recognized if cognition
is to be improved. Epistemologists must attend to the results of cognitive
science if they are to remedy these deficiencies in traditional epistemology.
Goldman later developed epistemics in Epistemology and Cognition (1986), in
which he developed a historical, reliabilist theory of knowledge and epistemic
justification and employed empirical cognitive science to characterize
knowledge, evaluate skepticism, and assess human cognitive resources. In
Liaisons: Philosophy Meets the Cognitive and Social Sciences (1992) and in
Knowledge in a Social World (1999), he defended and elaborated a veritistic
(i.e., truth-oriented) evaluation of communal beliefprofiles, social
institutions, and social practices (e.g., the practice of restricting evidence
admissible in a jury trial). He has opposed the widely accepted view that
mental states are functional states (“The Psychology of Folk Psychology,”
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1993) and defended a simulation theory of mental
state attribution, on which one attributes mental states to another by
imagining what mental state one would be in if one were in the other’s
situation (“In Defense of the Simulation Theory,” 1992). He has also argued
that cognitive science bears on ethics by providing information relevant to the
nature of moral evaluation, moral choice, and hedonic states associated with
the good (e.g., happiness) (“Ethics and Cognitive Science,” 1993). ACTION THEORY, COGNITIVE SCIENCE,
EPISTEMOLOGY, RELIABILISM, SIMULATION THEORY, SOCIAL EPISTEMOLOGY. F.F.S.
good.ETHICS. good, common.COMMON GOOD. good-making characteristic, a characteristic
that makes whatever is intrinsically or inherently good, good. Hedonists hold
that pleasure and conducing to pleasure are the sole good-making
characteristics. Pluralists hold that those characteristics are only some among
many other goodmaking characteristics, which include, for instance, knowledge,
friendship, beauty, and acting from a sense of duty. ETHICS, HEDONISM. B.R. Goodman, Nelson
(1906–98), American philosopher who made seminal contributions to metaphysics,
epistemology, and aesthetics. Like Quine, Goodman repudiates analyticity and
kindred notions. Goodman’s work can be read as a series of investigations into
how to do philosophy without them. A central concern is how symbols structure
facts and our understanding of them. The Structure of Appearance (1952)
presents Goodman’s constructionalism. Pretheoretical beliefs are vague and
mutually inconsistent. By devising an interpreted formal system that derives
them from or explicates them in terms of suitable primitives, we bring them
into logical contact, eliminate inconsistencies, and disclose unanticipated
logical and theoretical connections. Multiple, divergent systems do justice to
the same pretheoretical beliefs. All systems satisfying our criteria of
adequacy are equally acceptable. Nothing favors any one of them over the
others. Ways of Worldmaking (1978) provides a less formal treatment of the same
themes. Category schemes dictate criteria of identity for their objects. So
mutually irreducible category schemes do not treat of the same things. Since a
world consists of the things it comprises, irreducible schemes mark out
different worlds. There are, Goodman concludes, many worlds if any. Inasmuch as
the categories that define identity Goldbach’s conjecture Goodman, Nelson 350
4065A- AM 350 conditions on objects are human
constructs, we make worlds. Languages of Art (1968) argues that art, like
science, makes and reveals worlds. Aesthetics is the branch of epistemology
that investigates art’s cognitive functions. Goodman analyzes the syntactic and
semantic structures of symbol systems, both literal and figurative, and shows
how they advance understanding in art and elsewhere. Fact, Fiction, and
Forecast(1954) poses the new riddle of induction. An item is grue if and only
if it is examined before future time t and found to be green or is not so
examined and is blue. All hitherto examined emeralds are both green and grue.
What justifies our expecting future emeralds to be green, not grue? Inductive
validity, the riddle demonstrates, depends on the characterization as well as
the classification of the evidence class. ‘Green’ is preferable, Goodman
maintains, because it is entrenched in inductive practice. This does not
guarantee that inferences using ‘green’ will yield truths. Nothing guarantees
that. But entrenched predicates are pragmatically advantageous, because they
mesh with our habits of thought and other cognitive resources. Goodman’s other
works include Problems and Projects (1972), Of Mind and Other Matters (1984),
and Reconceptions (1988), written with Catherine Z. Elgin. AESTHETICS, ANALYTIC –SYNTHETIC DISTINCTION,
GRUE PARADOX. C.Z.E. Gorgias (c.483–c.376 B.C.), Greek Sophist. A teacher of
rhetoric from Leontini in Syracuse, Gorgias came to Athens in 427 B.C. as an
ambassador from his city and caused a sensation with his artful oratory. He is
known through references and short quotations in later writers, and through a
few surviving texts – two speeches and a philosophical treatise. He taught a
rhetorical style much imitated in antiquity, by delivering model speeches to
paying audiences. Unlike other Sophists he did not give formal instruction in
other topics, nor prepare a formal rhetorical manual. He was known to have had
views on language, on the nature of reality, and on virtue. Gorgias’s style was
remarkable for its use of poetic devices such as rhyme, meter, and elegant
words, as well as for its dependence on artificial parallelism and balanced
antithesis. His surviving speeches, defenses of Helen and Palamedes, display a
range of arguments that rely heavily on what the ancients called eikos
(‘likelihood’ or ‘probability’). Gorgias maintained in his “Helen” that a
speech can compel its audience to action; elsewhere he remarked that in the
theater it is wiser to be deceived than not. Gorgias’s short book On Nature (or
On What Is Not) survives in two paraphrases, one by Sextus Empiricus and the
other (now considered more reliable) in an Aristotelian work, On Melissus,
Xenophanes, and Gorgias. Gorgias argued for three theses: that nothing exists;
that even if it did, it could not be known; and that even if it could be known,
it could not be communicated. Although this may be in part a parody, most
scholars now take it to be a serious philosophical argument in its own right.
In ethics, Plato reports that Gorgias thought there were different virtues for
men and for women, a thesis Aristotle defends in the Politics. SOPHISTS. P.Wo. Göttingen
School.NEO-KANTIANISM. grace, efficacious.ARNAULD. Gracián y Morales, Baltasar
(1601–58), Spanish writer, moralist, and a leading literary theorist of the
Spanish baroque. Born in Belmonte, he entered the Jesuit order in 1619 and
became rector of the Jesuit College at Tarragona and a favorite of King Philip
III. Gracián’s most important works are Agudeza y arte de ingenio (“The Art of
Worldly Wisdom,” 1642–48) and El criticón (“The Critic,” 1651–57). The first
provides philosophical support for conceptismo, a Spanish literary movement
that sought to create new concepts through the development of an elaborate
style, characterized by subtlety (agudeza) and ingenious literary artifices. El
criticón, written in the conceptist style, is a philosophical novel that
pessimistically criticizes the evils of civilization. Gracián anticipates
Rousseau’s noble savage in claiming that, although human beings are
fundamentally good in the state of nature, they are corrupted by civilization.
Echoing a common theme of Spanish thought at the time, he attributes the
nefarious influence of civilization to the confusion it creates between
appearance and reality. But Gracián’s pessimism is tempered by faith: man has
hope in the afterlife, when reality is finally revealed. Gracián wrote several
other influential books. In El héroe (“The Hero,” 1637) and El político (“The
Politician,” 1640), he follows Machiavelli in discussing the attributes of the
ideal prince; El discreto (“The Man of Discretion,” 1646) explores the ideal
gentleman, as judged by Spanish society. Most of Gracián’s books were published
under pseudonyms to avoid censure by his order. Gorgias Gracián y Morales,
Baltasar 351 4065A- AM 351 Among authors outside Spain who used his
ideas are Nietzsche, Schopenhauer, Voltaire, and Rousseau. J.J.E.G. grammar, a
system of rules specifying a language. The term has often been used
synonymously with ‘syntax’, the principles governing the construction of
sentences from words (perhaps also including the systems of word derivation and
inflection – case markings, verbal tense markers, and the like). In modern
linguistic usage the term more often encompasses other components of the
language system such as phonology and semantics as well as syntax. Traditional
grammars that we may have encountered in our school days, e.g., the grammars of
Latin or English, were typically fragmentary and often prescriptive – basically
a selective catalog of forms and sentence patterns, together with constructions
to be avoided. Contemporary linguistic grammars, on the other hand, aim to be
descriptive, and even explanatory, i.e., embedded within a general theory that
offers principled reasons for why natural languages are the way they are. This
is in accord with the generally accepted view of linguistics as a science that
regards human language as a natural phenomenon to be understood, just as physicists
attempt to make sense of the world of physical objects. Since the publication
of Syntactic Structures (1957) and Aspects of the Theory of Syntax (1965) by
Noam Chomsky, grammars have been almost universally conceived of as generative
devices, i.e., precisely formulated deductive systems – commonly called
generative grammars – specifying all and only the well-formed sentences of a
language together with a specification of their relevant structural properties.
On this view, a grammar of English has the character of a theory of the English
language, with the grammatical sentences (and their structures) as its theorems
and the grammar rules playing the role of the rules of inference. Like any
empirical theory, it is subject to disconfirmation if its predictions do not
agree with the facts – if, e.g., the grammar implies that ‘white or snow the
is’ is a wellformed sentence or that ‘The snow is white’ is not. The object of
this theory construction is to model the system of knowledge possessed by those
who are able to speak and understand an unlimited number of novel sentences of
the language specified. Thus, a grammar in this sense is a psychological entity
– a component of the human mind – and the task of linguistics (avowedly a
mentalistic discipline) is to determine exactly of what this knowledge
consists. Like other mental phenomena, it is not observable directly but only
through its effects. Thus, underlying linguistic competence is to be
distinguished from actual linguistic performance, which forms part of the
evidence for the former but is not necessarily an accurate reflection of it,
containing, as it does, errors, false starts, etc. A central problem is how
this competence arises in the individual, i.e., how a grammar is inferred by a
child on the basis of a finite, variable, and imperfect sample of utterances
encountered in the course of normal development. Many sorts of observations
strongly suggest that grammars are not constructed de novo entirely on the
basis of experience, and the view is widely held that the child brings to the
task a significant, genetically determined predisposition to construct grammars
according to a well-defined pattern. If this is so, and since apparently no one
language has an advantage over any other in the learning process, this inborn
component of linguistic competence can be correctly termed a universal grammar.
It represents whatever the grammars of all natural languages, actual or
potential, necessarily have in common because of the innate linguistic
competence of human beings. The apparent diversity of natural languages has
often led to a serious underestimation of the scope of universal grammar. One
of the most influential proposals concerning the nature of universal grammar
was Chomsky’s theory of transformational grammar. In this framework the
syntactic structure of a sentence is given not by a single object (e.g., a
parse tree, as in phrase structure grammar), but rather by a sequence of trees
connected by operations called transformations. The initial tree in such a
sequence is specified (generated) by a phrase structure grammar, together with
a lexicon, and is known as the deep structure. The final tree in the sequence,
the surface structure, contains the morphemes (meaningful units) of the
sentence in the order in which they are written or pronounced. For example, the
English sentences ‘John hit the ball’ and its passive counterpart ‘The ball was
hit by John’ might be derived from the same deep structure (in this case a tree
looking very much like the surface structure for the active sentence) except
that the optional transformational rule of passivization has been applied in
the derivation of the latter sentence. This rule rearranges the constituents of
the tree in such a way that, among other changes, the direct object (‘the
ball’) in deep structure becomes the surface-structure subject of the passive
sentence. It is thus an important feature of this theory that grammatical
grammar grammar 352 4065A- AM 352 relations such as subject, object, etc.,
of a sentence are not absolute but are relative to the level of structure. This
accounts for the fact that many sentences that appear superficially similar in
structure (e.g., ‘John is easy to please’, ‘John is eager to please’) are
nonetheless perceived as having different underlying (deep-structure)
grammatical relations. Indeed, it was argued that any theory of grammar that
failed to make a deep-structure/surface-structure distinction could not be
adequate. Contemporary linguistic theories have, nonetheless, tended toward
minimizing the importance of the transformational rules with corresponding
elaboration of the role of the lexicon and the principles that govern the
operation of grammars generally. Theories such as generalized phrase-structure
grammar and lexical function grammar postulate no transformational rules at all
and capture the relatedness of pairs such as active and passive sentences in
other ways. Chomsky’s principles and parameters approach (1981) reduces the
transformational component to a single general movement operation that is
controlled by the simultaneous interaction of a number of principles or
subtheories: binding, government, control, etc. The universal component of the
grammar is thus enlarged and the contribution of languagespecific rules is correspondingly
diminished. Proponents point to the advantages this would allow in language
acquisition. Presumably a considerable portion of the task of grammar
construction would consist merely in setting the values of a small number of
parameters that could be readily determined on the basis of a small number of
instances of grammatical sentences. A rather different approach that has been
influential has arisen from the work of Richard Montague, who applied to
natural languages the same techniques of model theory developed for logical
languages such as the predicate calculus. This so-called Montague grammar uses
a categorial grammar as its syntactic component. In this form of grammar,
complex lexical and phrasal categories can be of the form A/B. Typically such
categories combine by a kind of “cancellation” rule: A/B ! B P A (something of
category A/B combines with something of category B to yield something of
category A). In addition, there is a close correspondence between the syntactic
category of an expression and its semantic type; e.g., common nouns such as
‘book’ and ‘girl’ are of type e/t, and their semantic values are functions from
individuals (entities, or e-type things) to truth-values (T-type things), or
equivalently, sets of individuals. The result is an explicit, interlocking
syntax and semantics specifying not only the syntactic structure of grammatical
sentences but also their truth conditions. Montague’s work was embedded in his
own view of universal grammar, which has not, by and large, proven persuasive
to linguists. A great deal of attention has been given in recent years to
merging the undoubted virtues of Montague grammar with a linguistically more
palatable view of universal grammar.
CHOMSKY, LOGICAL FORM, PARSING, PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE. R.E.W. grammar,
categorial.GRAMMAR. grammar, Montague.GRAMMAR. grammar,
transformational.GRAMMAR. grammar, universal.GRAMMAR. grammatical form.LOGICAL
FORM. grammaticality intuitions.INTUITION. grammatical predicate.LOGICAL
SUBJECT. grammatical subject.LOGICAL SUBJECT. Gramsci, Antonio (1891–1937),
Italian political leader whose imprisonment by the Fascists for his involvement
with the Italian Communist Party had the ironical result of sparing him from
Stalinism and enabling him to better articulate his distinctive political
philosophy. In 1917 he welcomed the Bolshevik Revolution as a “revolution
against Capital” rather than against capitalism: as a revolution refuting the
deterministic Marxism according to which socialism could arise only by the
gradual evolution of capitalism, and confirming the possibility of the radical
transformation of social institutions. In 1921 he supported creation of the
Italian Communist Party; as its general secretary from 1924, he tried to
reorganize it along more democratic lines. In 1926 the Fascists outlawed all
opposition parties. Gramsci spent the rest of his life in various prisons,
where he wrote more than a thousand s of notes ranging from a few lines to
chapterlength essays. These Prison Notebooks pose a major interpretive
challenge, but they reveal a keen, insightful, and open mind grappling with
important social and political problems. The most common interpretation stems
from Palmiro Togliatti, Gramsci’s successor as leader of grammar, categorial
Gramsci, Antonio 353 4065A- AM 353 the Italian Communists. After the fall of
Fascism and the end of World War II, Togliatti read into Gramsci the so-called
Italian road to socialism: a strategy for attaining the traditional Marxist
goals of the classless society and the nationalization of the means of
production by cultural means, such as education and persuasion. In contrast to
Bolshevism, one had to first conquer social institutions, and then their
control would yield the desired economic and political changes. This democratic
theory of Marxist revolution was long regarded by many as especially relevant
to Western industrial societies, and so for this and other reasons Gramsci is a
key figure of Western Marxism. The same theory is often called Gramsci’s theory
of hegemony, referring to a relationship between two political units where one
dominates the other with the consent of that other. This interpretation was a
political reconstruction, based primarily on Gramsci’s Communist involvement
and on highly selective passages from the Notebooks. It was also based on
exaggerating the influence on Gramsci of Marx, Engels, Lenin, and Gentile, and
minimizing influences like Croce, Mosca, Machiavelli, and Hegel. No new
consensus has emerged yet; it would have to be based on analytical and
historical spadework barely begun. One main interpretive issue is whether
Gramsci, besides questioning the means, was also led to question the ends of
traditional Marxism. In one view, his commitment to rational persuasion,
political realism, methodological fallibilism, democracy, and pluralism is much
deeper than his inclinations toward the classless society, the abolition of
private property, the bureaucratically centralized party, and the like; in
particular, his pluralism is an aspect of his commitment to the dialectic as a
way of thinking, a concept he adapted from Hegel through Croce. MARXISM. M.A.F. great chain of
being.PRINCIPLE OF PLENITUDE. greatest happiness principle.UTILITARIANISM.
Great Learning.TA-HSÜEH. Greek Skepticism.SKEPTICS. Green, T(homas) H(ill)
(1836–82), British absolute idealist and social philosopher. The son of a
clergyman, Green studied and taught at Oxford. His central concern was to
resolve what he saw as the spiritual crisis of his age by analyzing knowledge
and morality in ways inspired by Kant and Hegel. In his lengthy introduction to
Hume’s Treatise, he argued that Hume had shown knowledge and morality to be
impossible on empiricist principles. In his major work, Prolegomena to Ethics
(1883), Green contended that thought imposed relations on sensory feelings and
impulses (whose source was an eternal consciousness) to constitute objects of
knowledge and of desire. Furthermore, in acting on desires, rational agents
seek the satisfaction of a self that is realized through their own actions.
This requires rational agents to live in harmony among themselves and hence to
act morally. In Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation (1885) Green
transformed classical liberalism by arguing that even though the state has no intrinsic
value, its intervention in society is necessary to provide the conditions that
enable rational beings to achieve self-satisfaction. HUME, IDEALISM, POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. J.W.A.
Gregory I, Saint, called Gregory the Great (c.540–604), a pope and Roman
political leader. Born a patrician, he was educated for public office and
became prefect of Rome in 570. In 579, he was appointed papal representative in
Constantinople, returning to Rome as counselor to Pope Pelagius II in 586. He
was elected Pope Gregory I in 590. When the Lombards attacked Rome in 594,
Gregory bought them off. Constantinople would neither cede nor defend Italy,
and Gregory stepped in as secular ruler of what became the Papal States. He
asserted the universal jurisdiction of the bishop of Rome, and claimed
patriarchy of the West. His writings include important letters; the Moralia, an
exposition of the Book of Job summarizing Christian theology; Pastoral Care,
which defined the duties of the clergy for the Middle Ages; and Dialogues, which
deals chiefly with the immortality of the soul, holding it could enter heaven
immediately without awaiting the Last Judgment. His thought, largely
Augustinian, is unoriginal, but was much quoted in the Middle Ages. AUGUSTINE. J.Lo. Gregory of Nyssa, Saint
(335–98), Greek theologian and mystic who tried to reconcile Platonism with
Christianity. As bishop of Cappadocia in eastern Asia Minor, he championed
orthodoxy and was prominent at the First Council of Constantinople. He related
the doctrine of the Trinity to Plato’s ideas of the One and the Many. He
followed Origen in believing that man’s material great chain of being Gregory
of Nyssa 354 4065A- AM 354 nature was due to the fall and in
believing in the Apocatastasis, the universal restoration of all souls,
including Satan’s, in the kingdom of God.
APOCATASTASIS, ORIGEN. L.P.P. Gregory of Rimini (c.1300–58), Italian
philosopher and monk. He studied in Italy, England, and France, and taught at
the universities of Bologna, Padua, Perugia, and Paris before becoming prior
general of the Hermits of St. Augustine in his native city of Rimini, about
eighteen months before he died. Gregory earned the honorific title “the
Authentic Doctor” because he was considered by many of his contemporaries to be
a faithful interpreter of Augustine, and thus a defender of tradition, in the
midst of the skepticism of Ockham and his disciples regarding what could be
known in natural philosophy and theology. Thus, in his commentary on Books I
and II of Peter Lombard’s Sentences, Gregory rejected the view that because of
God’s omnipotence he can do anything and is therefore unknowable in his nature
and his ways. Gregory also maintained that after Adam’s fall from
righteousness, men need, in conjunction with their free will, God’s help
(grace) to perform morally good actions. In non-religious matters Gregory is
usually associated with the theory of the complexe significabile, according to
which the object of knowledge acquired by scientific proof is neither an object
existing outside the mind, nor a word (simplex) or a proposition (complexum),
but rather the complexe significabile, that which is totally and adequately
signified by the proposition expressed in the conclusion of the proof in
question. COMPLEXE SIGNIFICABILE. G.S. Grelling’s
paradox.SET-THEORETIC PARADOXES.
Grice: English philosopher
whose work concerns perception and philosophy of language, and whose most
influential contribution is the concept of a conversational implicature and the
associated theoretical machinery of conversational ‘postulates.’ The concept of
a conversational implicature is first used in his ‘presentation’ on the causal
theory of perception and reference. Grice distinguishes between the ‘meaning’ of
the words used in a sentence and what is implied by the utterer’s choice of
words. If someone says “It looks as if there is a red pillar box in front of
me,” the choice of words implies that there is some doubt about the pillar box
being red. But, Grice argues, that is a matter of word choice and the sentence
itself does not ‘impl’ that there is
doubt. The term ‘conversational implicature’ was introduced in Grice’s William
James lectures (published in 1988) and used to defend the use of the material
implication as a logical translation of ‘if’. With Strawson (“In Defence of
Dogma”), Grice gives a spirited defense of the analytic–synthetic distinction
against Quine’s criticisms. In subsequent systematic papers Grice attempts,
among other things, to give a theoretical grounding of the distinction. Grice’s
oeuvre is part of the Oxford ordinary language tradition, if formal and theoretical.
He also explores metaphysics, especially the concept of absolute value. ANALYTIC –SYNTHETIC DISTINCTION, IMPLICATURE,
ORDINARY LANGUAGE PHILOSOPHY.
Groot, Huigh de.GROTIUS.
Grosseteste, Robert (c.1168–1253), English theologian who began life on the
bottom rung of feudal society in Suffolk and became one of the most influential
philosophers in pre-Reformation England. He studied at Oxford, becoming a
master of arts between 1186 and 1189. Sometime after this period he joined the
household of William de Vere, bishop of Hereford. Grosseteste may have been
associated with the local cathedral school in Hereford, several of whose
members were part of a relatively advanced scientific tradition. It was a
center for the study of natural science and astrology as well as liberal arts
and theology. If so, this would explain, at least in part, his lifelong
interest in work in natural philosophy. Between 1209 and 1214 Grosseteste became
a master of theology, probably in Paris. In 1221 he became the first chancellor
of Oxford. From 1229 to 1235 he was secular lecturer in theology to the
recently established Franciscan order at Oxford. It was during his tenure with
the Franciscans that he studied Greek – an unusual endeavor for a medieval
schoolman. He spent the last eighteen years of his life as bishop of Lincoln.
As a university scholar, Grosseteste was an original thinker who used
Aristotelian and Augustinian theses as points of departure. He believed, with
Aristotle, that sense knowledge is the basis of all knowledge, and that the
basis for sense knowledge is our discovery of the cause of what is experienced
or revealed by experiment. He also believed, with Augustine, that light plays Gregory
of Rimini Grosseteste, Robert 355 4065A-
AM 355 an important role in
creation. Thus he maintained that God produced the world by first creating
prime matter from which issued a point of light (lux), the first corporeal form
or power, one of whose manifestations is visible light. The diffusion of this
light resulted in extension or tridimensionality in the form of the nine
concentric celestial spheres and the four terrestrial spheres of fire, air,
water, and earth. According to Grosseteste, the diffusion of light takes place
in accordance with laws of mathematical proportionality (geometry). Everything,
therefore, is a manifestation of light, and mathematics is consequently
indispensable to science and knowledge generally. The principles Grosseteste employs
to support his views are presented in, e.g., his commentary on Aristotle’s
Posterior Analytics, the De luce (“Of Light”), and the De lineis, angulis et
figuris (“Of Lines, Angles, and Figures”). He worked in areas as seemingly
disparate as optics and angelology. Grosseteste was one of the first to take an
interest in and introduce into the Oxford curriculum newly recovered
Aristotelian texts – some of which he translated, along with Greek commentaries
on them. His work and interest in natural philosophy, mathematics, the Bible,
and languages profoundly influenced his younger contemporary, Roger Bacon, and
the educational goals of the Franciscan order. It also helped to stimulate work
in these areas during the fourteenth century.
COMMENTARIES ON ARISTOTLE. G.S. Grotius, Hugo, in Dutch, Huigh de Groot
(1583– 1645), Dutch humanist, a founder of modern views of international law
and a major theorist of natural law. A lawyer and Latinist, Grotius developed a
new view of the law of nature in order to combat moral skepticism and to show
how there could be rational settlement of moral disputes despite religious
disagreements. He argued in The Law of War and Peace (1625) that humans are
naturally both competitive and sociable. The laws of nature show us how we can
live together despite our propensity to conflict. They can be derived from
observation of our nature and situation. These laws reflect the fact that each
individual possesses rights, which delimit the social space within which we are
free to pursue our own goals. Legitimate government arises when we give up some
rights in order to save or improve our lives. The obligations that the laws of
nature impose would bind us, Grotius notoriously said, even if God did not
exist; but he held that God does enforce the laws. They set the limits on the
laws that governments may legitimately impose. The laws of nature reflect our
possession of both precise perfect rights of justice, which can be protected by
force, and imperfect rights, which are not enforceable, nor even statable very
precisely. Grotius’s views on our combative but sociable nature, on the
function of the law of nature, and on perfect and imperfect rights were of
central importance in later discussions of morality and law. NATURAL LAW, RIGHTS. J.B.S. ground
rule.THEMA. grue paradox, a paradox in the theory of induction, according to
which every intuitively acceptable inductive argument, A, may be mimicked by
indefinitely many other inductive arguments – each seemingly quite analogous to
A and therefore seemingly as acceptable, yet each nonetheless intuitively
unacceptable, and each yielding a conclusion contradictory to that of A, given
the assumption that sufficiently many and varied of the sort of things induced
upon exist as yet unexamined (which is the only circumstance in which A is of
interest). Suppose the following is an intuitively acceptable inductive
argument: (A1) All hitherto observed emeralds are green; therefore, all
emeralds are green. Now introduce the colorpredicate ‘grue’, where (for some
given, as yet wholly future, temporal interval T) an object is grue provided it
has the property of being either green and first examined before T, or blue and
not first examined before T. Then consider the following inductive argument:
(A2) All hitherto observed emeralds are grue; therefore, all emeralds are grue.
The premise is true, and A2 is formally analogous to A1. But A2 is intuitively
unacceptable; if there are emeralds unexamined before T, then the conclusion of
A2 says that these emeralds are blue, whereas the conclusion of A1 says that
they are green. Other counterintuitive competing arguments could be given,
e.g.: (A3) All hitherto observed emeralds are grellow; therefore, all emeralds
are grellow (where an object is grellow provided it is green and located on the
earth, or yellow otherwise). It would seem, therefore, that some restriction on
induction is required. The new riddle of induction offers two challenges.
First, state the restriction – i.e., demarcate the intuitively acceptable inductions
from the unacceptable ones, in some general way, without constant appeal to
intuition. Second, justify our preference for the Grotius, Hugo grue paradox
356 4065A- AM 356 one group of inductions over the other.
(These two parts of the new riddle are often conflated. But it is at least
conceivable that one might solve the analytical, demarcative part without
solving the justificatory part, and, perhaps, vice versa.) It will not do to
rule out, a priori, “gruelike” (now commonly called “gruesome”) variances in
nature. Water (pure H2O) varies in its physical state along the parameter of
temperature. If so, why might not emeralds vary in color along the parameter of
time of first examination? One approach to the problem of restriction is to
focus on the conclusions of inductive arguments (e.g., All emeralds are green,
All emeralds are grue) and to distinguish those which may legitimately so serve
(called “projectible hypotheses”) from those which may not. The question then
arises whether only non-gruesome hypotheses (those which do not contain
gruesome predicates) are projectible. Aside from the task of defining ‘gruesome
predicate’ (which could be done structurally relative to a preferred language),
the answer is no. The English predicate ‘solid and less than 0; C, or liquid
and more than 0; C but less than 100; C, or gaseous and more than 100; C’ is
gruesome on any plausible structural account of gruesomeness (note the
similarity to the English ‘grue’ equivalent: green and first examined before T,
or blue and not first examined before T). Nevertheless, where nontransitional
water is pure H2O at one atmosphere of pressure (save that which is in a
transitional state, i.e., melting/freezing or boiling/condensing, i.e., at 0°C
or 100; C), we happily project the hypothesis that all non-transitional water
falls under the above gruesome predicate. Perhaps this is because, if we
rewrite the projection about non-transitional water as a conjunction of
non-gruesome hypotheses – (i) All water at less than 0; C is solid, (ii) All
water at more than 0; C but less than 100; C is liquid, and (iii) All water at
more than 100; C is gaseous – we note that (i)–(iii) are all supported (there
are known positive instances); whereas if we rewrite the gruesome projection
about emeralds as a conjunction of non-gruesome hypotheses – (i*) All emeralds
first examined before T are green, and (ii*) All emeralds not first examined
before T are blue – we note that (ii*) is as yet unsupported. It would seem
that, whereas a non-gruesome hypothesis is projectible provided it is
unviolated and supported, a gruesome hypothesis is projectible provided it is
unviolated and equivalent to a conjunction of non-gruesome hypotheses, each of
which is supported. The grue paradox was discovered by Nelson Goodman. It is
most fully stated in his Fact, Fiction and Forecast (1955). PROBLEM OF INDUCTION, QUALITATIVE PREDICATE.
D.A.J. Grundnorm.BASIC NORM. guise theory, a system developed by Castañeda to
resolve a number of issues concerning the content of thought and experience,
including reference, identity statements, intensional contexts, predication,
existential claims, perception, and fictional discourse. For example, since (i)
Oedipus believed that he killed the man at the crossroads, and (ii) the man at
the crossroads was his (Oedipus’s) father, it might seem that (iii) Oedipus
believed that he killed his father. Guise theory blocks this derivation by
taking ‘was’ in (ii) to express, not genuine identity, but a contingent
sameness relation betweeen the distinct referents of the descriptions. Definite
descriptions are typically treated as referential, contrary to Russell’s theory
of descriptions, and their referents are identical in both direct and indirect
discourse, contrary to Frege’s semantics. To support this solution, guise
theory offers unique accounts of predication and singular referents. The latter
are individual guises, which, like Fregean senses and Meinong’s incomplete
objects, are thinly individuated aspects or “slices” of ordinary objects at best.
Every guise is a structure c{F1 . . . , Fn} where c is an operator expressed by
‘the’ in English – transforming a set of properties {F1, . . . , Fn} into a
distinct concrete individual, each property being an internal property of the
guise. Guises have external properties by standing in various sameness
relations to other guises that have these properties internally. There are four
such relations, besides genuine identity, each an equivalence relation in its
field. If the oldest philosopher happens to be wise, e.g., wisdom is factually
predicated of the guise ‘the oldest philosopher’ because it is consubstantiated
with ‘the oldest wise philosopher’. Other sameness relations account for
fictional predication (consociation) and necessary external predication
(conflation). Existence is self-consubstantiation. An ordinary physical object
is, at any moment, a cluster of consubstantiated (hence, existing) guises,
while continuants are formed through the transubstantiation of guises within
temporally distinct clusters. There are no substrates, and while every guise
“subsists,” not all exist, e.g., the Norse God of Thunder. The posiGrundnorm
guise theory 357 4065A- AM 357 tion thus permits a unified account of
singular reference. One task for guise theory is to explain how a “concretized”
set of properties differs internally from a mere set. Perhaps guises are façons
de penser whose core sets are concretized if their component properties are
conceived as coinstantiated, with non-existents analyzable in terms of the
failure of the conceived properties to actually be coinstantiated. However, it
is questionable whether this approach can achieve all that Castañeda demands of
guise theory. CASTAÑEDA, PRACTITION.
T.K. guise theory guise theory 358 4065A-
AM 358 Habermas, Jürgen (b.1929),
German philosopher and social theorist, a leading representative of the second
generation of the Frankfurt School of critical theory. His work has
consistently returned to the problem of the normative foundations of social
criticism and critical social inquiry not supplied in traditional Marxism and
other forms of critical theory, such as postmodernism. His habilitation, The
Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere (1961), is an influential
historical analysis of the emergence of the ideal of a public sphere in the
eighteenth century and its subsequent decline. Habermas turned then to the
problems of the foundations and methodology of the social sciences, developing
a criticism of positivism and his own interpretive explanatory approach in The
Logic of the Social Sciences (1963) and his first major systematic work,
Knowledge and Human Interests (1967). Rejecting the unity of method typical of
positivism, Habermas argues that social inquiry is guided by three distinct
interests: in control, in understanding, and in emancipation. He is especially
concerned to use emancipatory interest to overcome the limitations of the model
of inquiry based on understanding and argues against “universality of
hermeneutics” (defended by hermeneuticists such as Gadamer) and for the need to
supplement interpretations with explanations in the social sciences. As he came
to reject the psychoanalytic vocabulary in which he formulated the interest in
emancipation, he turned to finding the basis for understanding and social
inquiry in a theory of rationality more generally. In the next phase of his
career he developed a comprehensive social theory, culminating in his
two-volume The Theory of Communicative Action (1982). The goal of this theory
is to develop a “critical theory of modernity,” on the basis of a comprehensive
theory of communicative (as opposed to instrumental) rationality. The first
volume develops a theory of communicative rationality based on “discourse,” or
second-order communication that takes place both in everyday interaction and in
institutionalized practices of argumentation in science, law, and criticism.
This theory of rationality emerges from a universal or “formal” pragmatics, a
speech act theory based on making explicit the rules and norms of the
competence to communicate in linguistic interaction. The second volume develops
a diagnosis of modern society as suffering from “onesided rationalization,”
leading to disruptions of the communicative lifeworld by “systems” such as
markets and bureaucracies. Finally, Habermas applies his conception of
rationality to issues of normative theory, including ethics, politics, and the
law. “Discourse Ethics: Notes on a Program of Moral Justification” (1982)
argues for an intersubjective notion of practical reason and discursive
procedure for the justification of universal norms. This “discourse principle”
provides a dialogical version of Kant’s idea of universalization; a norm is
justified if and only if it can meet with the reasoned agreement of all those
affected. Between Facts and Norms (1992) combines his social and normative
theories to give a systematic account of law and democracy. His contribution
here is an account of deliberative democracy appropriate to the complexity of
modern society. His work in all of these phases provides a systematic defense
and critique of modern institutions and a vindication of the universal claims
of public practical reason. CRITICAL
THEORY, FRANKFURT SCHOOL, HERMENEUTICS. J.B. haecceity (from Latin haec,
‘this’), (1) loosely, thisness; more specifically, an irreducible category of
being, the fundamental actuality of an existent entity; or (2) an individual
essence, a property an object has necessarily, without which it would not be or
would cease to exist as the individual it is, and which, necessarily, no other
object has. There are in the history of philosophy two distinct concepts of
haecceity. The idea originated with the work of the thirteenthcentury
philosopher Duns Scotus, and was discussed in the same period by Aquinas, as a
positive perfection that serves as a primitive existence and individuation
principle for concrete existents. In the seventeenth century Leibniz
transformed the concept of haecceity, which Duns Scotus had explicitly denied
to be a form or universal, into the notion of an individual essence, a
distinctive nature or set of necessary characteristics uniquely identifying it
under the principle of the identity of indiscernibles. 359 H 4065h-l.qxd 7:39 AM
359 Duns Scotus’s haecceitas applies only to the being of contingently
existent entities in the actual world, but Leibniz extends the principle to
individuate particular things not only through the changes they may undergo in
the actual world, but in any alternative logically possible world. Leibniz
admitted as a consequence the controversial thesis that every object by virtue
of its haecceity has each of its properties essentially or necessarily, so that
only the counterparts of individuals can inhabit distinct logically possible
worlds. A further corollary – since the possession of particular parts in a
particular arrangement is also a property and hence involved in the individual
essence of any complex object – is the doctrine of mereological essentialism:
every composite is necessarily constituted by a particular configuration of
particular proper parts, and loses its self-identity if any parts are removed
or replaced. DUNS SCOTUS, ESSENTIALISM,
IDENTITY OF INDISCERNIBLES, METAPHYSICS. D.J. Haeckel, Ernst (1834–1919),
German zoologist, an impassioned adherent of Darwin’s theory of evolution. His
popular work Die Welträtsel (The Riddle of the Universe, 1899) became a
best-seller and was very influential in its time. Lenin is said to have admired
it. Haeckel’s philosophy, which he called monism, is characterized negatively
by his rejection of free will, immortality, and theism, as well as his
criticisms of the traditional forms of materialism and idealism. Positively it
is distinguished by passionate arguments for the fundamental unity of organic and
inorganic nature and a form of pantheism. M.K. Ha-Levi, Judah (c.1075–1141),
Spanish Jewish philosopher and poet. Born in Toledo, he studied biblical and
rabbinical literature as well as philosophy. His poetry introduces Arabic forms
in Hebrew religious expression. He was traveling to Jerusalem on a pilgrimage
when he died. His most important philosophical work is Kuzari: The Book of
Proof and Argument of the Despised Faith, which purports to be a discussion of
a Christian, a Muslim, and a Jew, each offering the king of the Khazars (in
southern Russia) reasons for adopting his faith. Around 740 the historical king
and most of his people converted to Judaism. HaLevi presents the Christian and
the Muslim as Aristotelian thinkers, who fail to convince the king. The Jewish
spokesman begins by asserting his belief in the God of Abraham, Isaac, and
Jacob, the God of history who is continuously active in history, rather than
the God of the philosophers. Jewish history is the inner core of world history.
From the revelation at Sinai, the most witnessed divine event claimed by any
religion, the Providential history of the Jews is the way God has chosen to
make his message clear to all humankind. Ha-Levi’s view is the classical
expression of Jewish particularism and nationalism. His ideas have been
influential in Judaism and were early printed in Latin and Spanish. JEWISH PHILOSOPHY. R.H.P.
Halldén-complete.COMPLETENESS. hallucination.PSEUDOHALLUCINATION.
hallucination, argument from.PERCEPTION. halting problem.COMPUTABILITY. Hamann,
Johann Georg (1730–88), German philosopher. Born and educated in Königsberg,
Hamann, known as the Magus of the North, was one of the most important
Christian thinkers in Germany during the second half of the eighteenth century.
Advocating an irrationalistic theory of faith (inspired by Hume), he opposed
the prevailing Enlightenment philosophy. He was a mentor of the Sturm und Drang
literary movement and had a significant influence on Jacobi, Hegel, and
Kierkegaard. As a close acquaintance of Kant, he also had a great impact on the
development of Kant’s critical philosophy through his Hume translations.
Hamann’s most important works, criticized and admired for their difficult and
obscure style, were the Socratic Memorabilia (1759), Aesthetica in nuce
(“Aesthetics in a Nutshell,” 1762), and several works on language. He
suppressed his “metacritical” writings out of respect for Kant. However, they
were published after his death and now constitute the bestknown part of his
work. M.K. Hamilton, William (1788–1856), Scottish philosopher and logician.
Born in Glasgow and educated at Glasgow, Edinburgh, and Oxford, he was for most
of his life professor at the University of Edinburgh (1821–56). Though hardly
an orthodox or uncritical follower of Reid and Stewart, he became one of the
most important members of the school of Scottish common sense philosophy. His
“philosophy of the conditioned” has a somewhat Kantian flavor. Like Kant, he
held that we can have knowledge only of “the relative manifestations of an
existence, which in itself it is our highest wisdom to recogHaeckel, Ernst
Hamilton, William 360 4065h-l.qxd 7:39
AM 360 nize as beyond the reach of
philosophy.” Unlike Kant, however, he argued for the position of a “natural
realism” in the Reidian tradition. The doctrine of the relativity of knowledge
has seemed to many – including J. S. Mill – contradictory to his realism. For
Hamilton, the two are held together by a kind of intuitionism that emphasizes
certain facts of consciousness that are both primitive and incomprehensible.
They are, though constitutive of knowledge, “less forms of cognitions than of
beliefs.” In logic he argued for a doctrine involving quantification of
predicates and the view that propositions can be reduced to equations. SCOTTISH COMMON SENSE PHILOSOPHY. M.K. Han Fei
Tzu, also called Master Han Fei (third century B.C.), Chinese Legalist
political theorist. He was a prince of the state of Han and a student of Hsün
Tzu. His thought, recorded in the text Han Fei Tzu, mainly concerned the method
of government and was addressed primarily to rulers. Han Fei Tzu believed that
human beings are self-seeking by nature, and that they can rarely be
transformed by education and moral examples. Accordingly, the ruler should
institute a precisely formulated and clearly propagated system of laws (fa) to
regulate their behavior, and enforce it with punishment. Officials, in addition
to being governed by laws, are to be rewarded and punished according to whether
their performance coincides with their official duties and proposed plans. The
ruler should enforce this system strictly without favoritism, should shun
contact with subordinates to avoid breeding familiarity, and should conceal his
personal likes and dislikes to avoid their being exploited. Having properly set
up the machinary of government, the government will run smoothly with minimal
intervention by the ruler. CHINESE
LEGALISM. K.-l.S. Han Yü (768–824), Chinese poet and essayist who, though his
thoughts lacked philosophical depth, was the first to emphasize “correct
transmission” of the Way from the sage-emperors to Confucius and Mencius. His
views later profoundly influenced Neo-Confucian philosophers in the Sung
dynasty. He vigorously defended Confucianism against Buddhism and Taoism on
cultural grounds: the monks and nuns were parasites on society. He also
formulated a threefold theory on which human nature has superior, medium, and
inferior grades. CONFUCIANISM,
CONFUCIUS, MENCIUS, NEO-CONFUCIANISM, TAO-T’UNG. S.-h.L. happiness.ARISTOTLE,
HEDONISM, UTILITARIANISM. hard determinism.FREE WILL PROBLEM. Hardenberg,
Friedrich von.NOVALIS. hardware.COMPUTER THEORY. Hare, R(ichard) M(ervyn)
(b.1919), English philosopher who is one of the most influential moral
philosophers of the twentieth century and the developer of prescriptivism in
metaethics. Hare was educated at Rugby and Oxford, then served in the British
army during World War II and spent years as a prisoner of war in Burma. In 1947
he took a position at Balliol College and was appointed White’s Professor of
Moral Philosophy at the University of Oxford in 1966. On retirement from
Oxford, he became Graduate Research Professor at the University of Florida
(1983–93). His major books are Language of Morals (1953), Freedom and Reason (1963),
Moral Thinking (1981), and Sorting Out Ethics (1997). Many collections of his
essays have also appeared, and a collection of other leading philosophers’
articles on his work was published in 1988 (Hare and Critics, eds. Seanor and
Fotion). According to Hare, a careful exploration of the nature of our moral
concepts reveals that (nonironic) judgments about what one morally ought to do
are expressions of the will, or commitments to act, that are subject to certain
logical constraints. Because moral judgments are prescriptive, we cannot
sincerely subscribe to them while refusing to comply with them in the relevant
circumstances. Because moral judgments are universal prescriptions, we cannot
sincerely subscribe to them unless we are willing for them to be followed were
we in other people’s positions with their preferences. Hare later contended
that vividly to imagine ourselves completely in other people’s positions
involves our acquiring preferences about what should happen to us in those
positions that mirror exactly what those people now want for themselves. So,
ideally, we decide on a universal prescription on the basis of not only our
existing preferences about the actual situation but also the new preferences we
would have if we were wholly in other people’s positions. What we can prescribe
universally is what maximizes net satisfaction of this amalgamated set of
preferences. Hence, Hare concluded that his theory of moral judgment leads to
preference-satisfaction act utilitarianism. However, like most other
utilitarians, he argued that the Han Fei Tzu Hare, R(ichard) M(ervyn) 361
4065h-l.qxd 7:39 AM 361 best way to maximize utility is to have,
and generally to act on, certain not directly utilitarian dispositions – such
as dispositions not to hurt others or steal, to keep promises and tell the
truth, to take special responsibility for one’s own family, and so on. EMOTIVISM, ETHICS, PRESCRIPTIVISM,
UTILITARIANISM. B.W.H. harmony, preestablished.LEIBNIZ. harmony of the
spheres.PYTHAGORAS. Hart, H(erbert) L(ionel) A(dolphus) (1907–92), English
philosopher principally responsible for the revival of legal and political
philosophy after World War II. After wartime work with military intelligence,
Hart gave up a flourishing law practice to join the Oxford faculty, where he
was a brilliant lecturer, a sympathetic and insightful critic, and a generous
mentor to many scholars. Like the earlier “legal positivists” Bentham and John
Austin, Hart accepted the “separation of law and morals”: moral standards can
deliberately be incorporated in law, but there is no automatic or necessary
connection between law and sound moral principles. In The Concept of Law (1961)
he critiqued the Bentham-Austin notion that laws are orders backed by threats
from a political community’s “sovereign” – some person or persons who enjoy
habitual obedience and are habitually obedient to no other human – and
developed the more complex idea that law is a “union of primary and secondary
rules.” Hart agreed that a legal system must contain some “obligation-imposing”
“primary” rules, restricting freedom. But he showed that law also includes
independent “power-conferring” rules that facilitate choice, and he
demonstrated that a legal system requires “secondary” rules that create public
offices and authorize official action, such as legislation and adjudication, as
well as “rules of recognition” that determine which other rules are valid in
the system. Hart held that rules of law are “open-textured,” with a core of
determinate meaning and a fringe of indeterminate meaning, and thus capable of
answering some but not all legal questions that can arise. He doubted courts’
claims to discover law’s meaning when reasonable competing interpretations are
available, and held that courts decide such “hard cases” by first performing
the important “legislative” function of filling gaps in the law. Hart’s first
book was an influential study (with A. M. Honoré) of Causation in the Law
(1959). His inaugural lecture as Professor of Jurisprudence, “Definition and
Theory in Jurisprudence” (1953), initiated a career-long study of rights,
reflected also in Essays on Bentham: Studies in Jurisprudence and Political
Theory (1982) and in Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (1983). He defended
liberal public policies. In Law, Liberty and Morality (1963) he refuted Lord
Devlin’s contention that a society justifiably enforces the code of its moral
majority, whatever it might be. In The Morality of the Criminal Law (1965) and
in Punishment and Responsibility (1968), Hart contributed substantially to both
analytic and normative theories of crime and punishment. LIBERALISM, PHILOSOPHY OF LAW, POLITICAL
PHILOSOPHY, RIGHTS. D.Ly. Hartley, David (1705–57), British physician and
philosopher. Although the notion of association of ideas is ancient, he is
generally regarded as the founder of associationism as a self-sufficient
psychology. Despite similarities between his association psychology and Hume’s,
Hartley developed his system independently, acknowledging only the writings of
clergyman John Gay (1699– 1745). Hartley was one of many Enlightenment thinkers
aspiring to be “Newtons of the mind,” in Peter Gay’s phrase. In Hartley, this
took the form of uniting association philosophy with physiology, a project
later brought to fruition by Bain. His major work, Observations on Man (1749),
pictured mental events and neural events as operating on parallel tracks in
which neural events cause mental events. On the mental side, Hartley
distinguished (like Hume) between sensation and idea. On the physiological
side, Hartley adopted Newton’s conception of nervous transmission by vibrations
of a fine granular substance within nerve-tubes. Vibrations within sensory
nerves peripheral to the brain corresponded to the sensations they caused,
while small vibrations in the brain, vibratiuncles, corresponded to ideas.
Hartley proposed a single law of association, contiguity modified by frequency,
which took two forms, one for the mental side and one for the neural: ideas, or
vibratiuncles, occurring together regularly become associated. Hartley
distinguished between simultaneous association, the link between ideas that
occur at the same harmony, preestablished Hartley, David 362 4065h-l.qxd 7:39 AM
362 moment, and successive association, between ideas that closely
succeed one another. Successive associations occur only in a forward direction;
there are no backward associations, a thesis generating much controversy in the
later experimental study of memory.
ASSOCIATIONISM. T.H.L. Hartmann, Eduard von (1842–1906), German
philosopher who sought to synthesize the thought of Schelling, Hegel, and
Schopenhauer. The most important of his fifteen books was Philosophie des
Unbewussten (Philosophy of the Unconscious, 1869). For Hartmann both will and
idea are interrelated and are expressions of an absolute “thing-in-itself,” the
unconscious. The unconscious is the active essence in natural and psychic
processes and is the teleological dynamic in organic life. Paradoxically, he
claimed that the teleology immanent in the world order and the life process
leads to insight into the irrationality of the “will-to-live.” The maturation
of rational consciousness would, he held, lead to the negation of the total
volitional process and the entire world process would cease. Ideas indicate the
“what” of existence and constitute, along with will and the unconscious, the
three modes of being. Despite its pessimism, this work enjoyed considerable
popularity. Hartmann was an unusual combination of speculative idealist and
philosopher of science (defending vitalism and attacking mechanistic
materialism); his pessimistic ethics was part of a cosmic drama of redemption.
Some of his later works dealt with a critical form of Darwinism that led him to
adopt a positive evolutionary stance that undermined his earlier pessimism. His
general philosophical position was selfdescribed as “transcendental realism.”
His Philosophy of the Unconscious was translated into English by W. C. Coupland
in three volumes in 1884. There is little doubt that his metaphysics of the
unconscious prepared the way for Freud’s later theory of the unconscious
mind. FREUD, HEGEL, SCHELLING,
SCHOPENHAUER. G.J.S. Hartmann, Nicolai (1882–1950), Latvian-born German
philosopher. He taught at the universities of Marburg, Cologne, Berlin, and
Göttingen, and wrote more than a dozen major works on the history of
philosophy, ontology, epistemology, ethics, and aesthetics. A realist in
epistemology and ontology, Hartmann held that cognition is the apprehension of
something independent of the act of apprehension or any other mental events. An
accurate phenomenology, such as Husserl’s, would acknowledge, according to him,
that we apprehend not only particular, spatiotemporal objects, but also “ideal
objects,” “essences,” which Hartmann explicitly identified with Platonic Forms.
Among these are ethical values and the objects of mathematics and logic. Our
apprehension of values is emotional in character, as Scheler had held. This
point is compatible with their objectivity and their mindindependence, since
the emotions are just another mode of apprehension. The point applies, however,
only to ethical values. Aesthetic values are essentially subjective; they exist
only for the subject experiencing them. The number of ethical values is far
greater than usually supposed, nor are they derivable from a single fundamental
value. At best we only glimpse some of them, and even these may not be
simultaneously realizable. This explains and to some extent justifies the
existence of moral disagreement, between persons as well as between whole
cultures. Hartmann was most obviously influenced by Plato, Husserl, and
Scheler. But he was a major, original philosopher in his own right. He has
received less recognition than he deserves probably because his views were
quite different from those dominant in recent Anglo-American philosophy or in
recent Continental philosophy. What is perhaps his most important work, Ethics,
was published in German in 1926, one year before Heidegger’s Being and Time,
and appeared in English in 1932. A
PRIORI, HUSSERL, MORAL REALISM, PLATO, SCHELER. P.B.u Hartshorne, Charles
(b.1897), chief American exponent of process philosophy and theology in the
late twentieth century. After receiving the Ph.D. at Harvard in 1923 he came
under the influence of Whitehead, and later, with Paul Weiss, edited The
Collected Papers of C. S. Peirce (1931–35). In The Philosophy and Psychology of
Sensation (1934) Hartshorne argued that all sensations are feelings on an
affective continuum. These ideas were later incorporated into a neoclassical
metaphysic that is panpsychist, indeterministic, and theistic. Nature is a
theater of interactions among ephemeral centers of creative activity, each of
which becomes objectively immortal in the memory of God. In Man’s Vision of God
(1941) Hartshorne chastised philosophers for being insufficiently attentive to
the varieties of theism. His alternative, called dipolar theism, also defended
in The Divine Hartmann, Eduard von Hartshorne, Charles 363 4065h-l.qxd 7:39 AM
363 Relativity (1948), pictures God as supremely related to and
perfectly responding to every actuality. The universe is God’s body. The divine
is, in different respects, infinite and finite, eternal and temporal, necessary
and contingent. Establishing God’s existence is a metaphysical project, which
Hartshorne characterizes in Creative Synthesis (1970) as the search for
necessary truths about existence. The central element in his cumulative case
for God’s existence, called the global argument, is a modal version of the
ontological argument, which Hartshorne was instrumental in rehabilitating in
The Logic of Perfection (1962) and Anselm’s Discovery (1965). Creative
Synthesis also articulated the theory that aesthetic values are the most
universal and that beauty is a mean between the twin extremes of order/disorder
and simplicity/complexity. The Zero Fallacy (1997), Hartshorne’s twentieth
book, summarized his assessment of the history of philosophy – also found in
Insights and Oversights of Great Thinkers (1983) and Creativity in American
Philosophy (1984) – and introduced important refinements of his
metaphysics. PANPSYCHISM, PHILOSOPHY OF
RELIGION, PROCESS PHILOSOPHY, WHITEHEAD. D.W.V. hasty generalization, fallacy
of.INFORMAL FALLACY. heap paradox.SORITES PARADOX. heart.HSIN1. Heaven.T’IEN.
hedonic calculus.BENTHAM. hedonism, the view that pleasure (including the
absence of pain) is the sole intrinsic good in life. The hedonist may hold
that, questions of morality aside, persons inevitably do seek pleasure (psychological
hedonism); that, questions of psychology aside, morally we should seek pleasure
(ethical hedonism); or that we inevitably do, and ought to, seek pleasure
(ethical and psychological hedonism combined). Psychological hedonism itself
admits of a variety of possible forms. One may hold, e.g., that all motivation
is based on the prospect of present or future pleasure. More plausibly, some
philosophers have held that all choices of future actions are based on one’s
presently taking greater pleasure in the thought of doing one act rather than
another. Still a third type of hedonism – with roots in empirical psychology –
is that the attainment of pleasure is the primary drive of a wide range of
organisms (including human beings) and is responsible, through some form of
conditioning, for all acquired motivations. Ethical hedonists may, but need
not, appeal to some form of psychological hedonism to buttress their case. For,
at worst, the truth of some form of psychological hedonism makes ethical
hedonism empty or inescapable – but not false. As a value theory (a theory of
what is ultimately good), ethical hedonism has typically led to one or the
other of two conceptions of morally correct action. Both of these are
expressions of moral consequentialism in that they judge actions strictly by
their consequences. On standard formulations of utilitarianism, actions are
judged by the amount of pleasure they produce for all (sentient beings); on
some formulations of egoist views, actions are judged by their consequences for
one’s own pleasure. Neither egoism nor utilitarianism, however, must be wedded
to a hedonistic value theory. A hedonistic value theory admits of a variety of
claims about the characteristic sources and types of pleasure. One contentious
issue has been what activities yield the greatest quantity of pleasure – with
prominent candidates including philosophical and other forms of intellectual
discourse, the contemplation of beauty, and activities productive of “the
pleasures of the senses.” (Most philosophical hedonists, despite the popular
associations of the word, have not espoused sensual pleasure.) Another issue,
famously raised by J. S. Mill, is whether such different varieties of pleasure
admit of differences of quality (as well as quantity). Even supposing them to
be equal in quantity, can we say, e.g., that the pleasures of intellectual
activity are superior in quality to those of watching sports on television? And
if we do say such things, are we departing from strict hedonism by introducing
a value distinction not really based on pleasure at all? Most philosophers have
found hedonism – both psychological and ethical – exaggerated in its claims.
One difficulty for both sorts of hedonism is the hedonistic paradox, which may
be put as follows. Many of the deepest and best pleasures of life (of love, of
child rearing, of work) seem to come most often to those who are engaging in an
activity for reasons other than pleasure seeking. Hence, not only is it dubious
that we always in fact seek (or value only) pleasure, but also dubious that the
best way to achieve pleasure is to seek it. Another area of difficulty concerns
happihasty, generalization, fallacy of hedonism 364 4065h-l.qxd 7:39 AM
364 ness – and its relation to pleasure. In the tradition of Aristotle,
happiness is broadly understood as something like well-being and has been
viewed, not implausibly, as a kind of natural end of all human activities. But
‘happiness’ in this sense is broader than ‘pleasure’, insofar as the latter
designates a particular kind of feeling, whereas ‘well-being’ does not.
Attributions of happiness, moreover, appear to be normative in a way in which
attributions of pleasure are not. It is thought that a truly happy person has
achieved, is achieving, or stands to achieve, certain things respecting the
“truly important” concerns of human life. Of course, such achievements will
characteristically produce pleasant feelings; but, just as characteristically,
they will involve states of active enjoyment of activities – where, as
Aristotle first pointed out, there are no distinctive feelings of pleasure
apart from the doing of the activity itself. In short, the Aristotelian thesis
that happiness is the natural end of all human activities, even if it is true,
does not seem to lend much support to hedonism – psychological or ethical. ARISTOTLE, ETHICS, EUDAIMONISM,
UTILITARIANISM, VALUE. J.A.M. hedonistic paradox.HEDONISM. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm
Friedrich (1770–1831), one of the most influential and systematic of the German
idealists, also well known for his philosophy of history and philosophy of
religion. Life and works. Hegel, the eldest of three children, was born in
Stuttgart, the son of a minor financial official in the court of the Duchy of
Württemberg. His mother died when he was eleven. At eighteen, he began
attending the theology seminary or Stift attached to the University at
Tübingen; he studied theology and classical languages and literature and became
friendly with his future colleague and adversary, Schelling, as well as the
great genius of German Romantic poetry, Hölderlin. In 1793, upon graduation, he
accepted a job as a tutor for a family in Bern, and moved to Frankfurt in 1797
for a similar post. In 1799 his father bequeathed him a modest income and the
freedom to resign his tutoring job, pursue his own work, and attempt to
establish himself in a university position. In 1801, with the help of
Schelling, he moved to the university town of Jena, already widely known as the
home of Schiller, Fichte, and the Schlegel brothers. After lecturing for a few
years, he became a professor in 1805. Prior to the move to Jena, Hegel’s essays
had been chiefly concerned with problems in morality, the theory of culture,
and the philosophy of religion. Hegel shared with Rousseau and the German
Romantics many doubts about the political and moral implications of the
European Enlightenment and modern philosophy in general, even while he still
enthusiastically championed what he termed the principle of modernity,
“absolute freedom.” Like many, he feared that the modern attack on feudal
political and religious authority would merely issue in the reformulation of
new internalized and still repressive forms of authority. And he was among that
legion of German intellectuals infatuated with ancient Greece and the
superiority of their supposedly harmonious social life, compared with the
authoritarian and legalistic character of the Jewish and later Christian
religions. At Jena, however, he coedited a journal with Schelling, The Critical
Journal of Philosophy, and came to work much more on the philosophic issues
created by the critical philosophy or “transcendental idealism” of Kant, and
its legacy in the work of Rheinhold, Fichte, and Schelling. His written work
became much more influenced by these theoretical projects and their attempt to
extend Kant’s search for the basic categories necessary for experience to be
discriminated and evaluated, and for a theory of the subject that, in some
non-empirical way, was responsible for such categories. Problems concerning the
completeness, interrelation, and ontological status of such a categorial
structure were quite prominent, along with a continuing interest in the
relation between a free, self-determining agent and the supposed constraints of
moral principles and other agents. In his early years at Jena (especially
before Schelling left in 1803), he was particularly preoccupied with this
problem of a systematic philosophy, a way of accounting for the basic
categories of the natural world and for human practical activity that would
ground all such categories on commonly presupposed and logically interrelated,
even interdeducible, principles. (In Hegel’s terms, this was the problem of the
relation between a “Logic” and a “Philosophy of Nature” and “Philosophy of Spirit.”)
After 1803, however, while he was preparing his own systematic philosophy for
publication, what had been planned as a short introduction to this system took
on a life of its own and grew into one of Hegel’s most provocative and
influential books. Working at a furious pace, he finished hedonistic paradox
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 365 4065h-l.qxd
7:39 AM 365 what would be
eventually called The Phenomenology of Spirit in a period of great personal and
political turmoil. During the final writing of the book, he had learned that
Christina Burkhard would give birth to his illegitimate son. (Ludwig was born
in February 1807.) And he is supposed to have completed the text on October 13,
1807, the day Napoleon’s armies captured Jena. It was certainly an
unprecedented work. In conception, it is about the human race itself as a
developing, progressively more self-conscious subject, but its content seems to
take in a vast, heterogeneous range of topics, from technical issues in
empiricist epistemology to the significance of burial rituals. Its range is so
heterogeneous that there is controversy to this day about whether it has any
overall unity, or whether it was pieced together at the last minute. Adding to
the interpretive problem, Hegel often invented his own striking language of
“inverted worlds,” “struggles to the death for recognition,” “unhappy
consciousness,” “spiritual animal kingdoms,” and “beautiful souls.” Continuing
his university career at Jena in those times looked out of the question, so Hegel
accepted a job at Bamberg editing a newspaper, and in the following year began
an eight-year stint (1808–16) as headmaster and philosophy teacher at a
Gymnasium (or secondary school) at Nürnberg. During this period, at forty-one,
he married the twenty-year-old Marie von Tucher. He also wrote what is easily
his most difficult work, and the one he often referred to as his most
important, a magisterial two-volume Science of Logic, which attempts to be a
philosophical account of the concepts necessary in all possible kinds of
account-givings. Finally, in 1816, Hegel was offered a chair in philosophy at
the University of Heidelberg, where he published the first of several versions
of his Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences, his own systematic account of
the relation between the “logic” of human thought and the “real” expression of
such interrelated categories in our understanding of the natural world and in
our understanding and evaluation of our own activities. In 1818, he accepted
the much more prestigious post in philosophy at Berlin, where he remained until
his death in 1831. Soon after his arrival in Berlin, he began to exert a
powerful influence over German letters and intellectual life. In 1821, in the
midst of a growing political and nationalist crisis in Prussia, he published
his controversial book on political philosophy, The Philosophy of Right. His
lectures at the university were later published as his philosophy of history,
of aesthetics, and of religion, and as his history of philosophy. Philosophy.
Hegel’s most important ideas were formed gradually, in response to a number of
issues in philosophy and often in response to historical events. Moreover, his
language and approach were so heterodox that he has inspired as much
controversy about the meaning of his position as about its adequacy. Hence any
summary will be as much a summary of the controversies as of the basic
position. His dissatisfactions with the absence of a public realm, or any forms
of genuine social solidarity in the German states and in modernity generally,
and his distaste with what he called the “positivity” of the orthodox religions
of the day (their reliance on law, scripture, and abstract claims to
authority), led him to various attempts to make use of the Greek polis and classical
art, as well as the early Christian understanding of love and a renewed “folk
religion,” as critical foils to such tendencies. For some time, he also
regarded much traditional and modern philosophy as itself a kind of lifeless
classifying that only contributed to contemporary fragmentation, myopia, and
confusion. These concerns remained with him throughout his life, and he is thus
rightly known as one of the first modern thinkers to argue that what had come
to be accepted as the central problem of modern social and political life, the
legitimacy of state power, had been too narrowly conceived. There are now all
sorts of circumstances, he argued, in which people might satisfy the modern
criterion of legitimacy and “consent” to the use of some power, but not fully
understand the terms within which such issues are posed, or assent in an
attenuated, resentful, manipulated, or confused way. In such cases they would
experience no connection between their individual will and the actual content
of the institutions they are supposed to have sanctioned. The modern problem is
as much alienation (Entfremdung) as sovereignty, an exercise of will in which
the product of one’s will appears “strange” or “alien,” “other,” and which
results in much of modern life, however chosen or willed, being fundamentally
unsatisfying. However, during the Jena years, his views on this issue changed.
Most importantly, philosophical issues moved closer to center stage in the
Hegelian drama. He no longer regarded philosophy as some sort of
self-undermining activity that merely prepared one for some leap into genuine
“speculation” (roughly Schelling’s position) Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 366 4065h-l.qxd
7:39 AM 366 and began to champion
a unique kind of comprehensive, very determinate reflection on the
interrelations among all the various classical alternatives in philosophy. Much
more controversially, he also attempted to understand the way in which such
relations and transitions were also reflected in the history of the art,
politics, and religions of various historical communities. He thus came to
think that philosophy should be some sort of recollection of its past history,
a realization of the mere partiality, rather than falsity, of its past attempts
at a comprehensive teaching, and an account of the centrality of these
continuously developing attempts in the development of other human practices.
Through understanding the “logic” of such a development, a reconciliation of
sorts with the implications of such a rational process in contemporary life, or
at least with the potentialities inherent in contemporary life, would be
possible. In all such influences and developments, one revolutionary aspect of
Hegel’s position became clearer. For while Hegel still frequently argued that
the subject matter of philosophy was “reason,” or “the Absolute,” the
unconditioned presupposition of all human account-giving and evaluation, and
thereby an understanding of the “whole” within which the natural world and human
deeds were “parts,” he also always construed this claim to mean that the
subject matter of philosophy was the history of human experience itself.
Philosophy was about the real world of human change and development, understood
by Hegel to be the collective self-education of the human species about itself.
It could be this, and satisfy the more traditional ideals because, in one of
his most famous phrases, “what is actual is rational,” or because some full
account could be given of the logic or teleological order, even the necessity,
for the great conceptual and political changes in human history. We could
thereby finally reassure ourselves that the way our species had come to
conceptualize and evaluate is not finite or contingent, but is “identical” with
“what there is, in truth.” This identity theory or Absolute Knowledgemeans that
we will then be able to be “at home” in the world and so will have understood
what philosophers have always tried to understand, “how things in the broadest
possible sense of the term hang together in the broadest possible sense of the
term.” The way it all hangs together is, finally, “due to us,” in some
collective and historical and “logical” sense. (In a much disputed passage in
his Philosophy of Religion lectures, Hegel even suggested that with such an
understanding, history itself would be over.) Several elements in this general
position have inspired a good deal of excitement and controversy. To advance
claims such as these Hegel had to argue against a powerful, deeply influential
assumption in modern thought: the priority of the individual, self-conscious
subject. Such an assumption means, for example, that almost all social
relations, almost all our bonds to other human beings, exist because and only
because they are made, willed into existence by individuals otherwise naturally
unattached to each other. With respect to knowledge claims, while there may be
many beliefs in a common tradition that we unreflectively share with others,
such shared beliefs are also taken primarily to be the result of individuals
continuously affirming such beliefs, however implicitly or unreflectively.
Their being shared is simply a consequence of their being simultaneously
affirmed or assented to by individuals. Hegel’s account requires a different picture,
an insistence on the priority of some kind of collective subject, which he
called human “spirit” or Geist. His general theory of conceptual and historical
change requires the assumption of such a collective subject, one that even can
be said to be “coming to self-consciousness” about itself, and this required
that he argue against the view that so much could be understood as the result
of individual will and reflection. Rather, he tried in many different ways to
show that the formation of what might appear to an individual to be his or her
own particular intention or desire or belief already reflected a complex social
inheritance that could itself be said to be evolving, even evolving
progressively, with a “logic” of its own. The completion of such collective
attempts at self-knowledge resulted in what Hegel called the realization of
Absolute Spirit, by which he either meant the absolute completion of the human
attempt to know itself, or the realization in human affairs of some sort of
extrahuman transcendence, or full expression of an infinite God. Hegel tried to
advance all such claims about social subjectivity without in some way
hypostatizing or reifying such a subject, as if it existed independently of the
actions and thoughts of individuals. This claim about the deep dependence of
individuals on one another (even for their very identity), even while they
maintain their independence, is one of the best-known examples of Hegel’s
attempt at a dialectical resolution of many of the traditional oppositions and
antinomies of past thought. Hegel often argued that what appeared to be
contraries in philosophy, such as mind/body, freedom/determinism, Hegel, Georg
Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 367 4065h-l.qxd 7:39 AM
367 idealism/materialism, universal/particular, the state/the
individual, or even God/man, appeared such incompatible alternatives only
because of the undeveloped and so incomplete perspective within which the
oppositions were formulated. So, in one of his more famous attacks on such
dualisms, human freedom according to Hegel could not be understood coherently
as some purely rational self-determination, independent of heteronomous
impulses, nor the human being as a perpetual opposition between reason and
sensibility. In his moral theory, Kant had argued for the latter view and Hegel
regularly returned to such Kantian claims about the opposition of duty and
inclination as deeply typical of modern dualism. Hegel claimed that Kant’s
version of a rational principle, the “categorical imperative,” was so formal
and devoid of content as not to be action-guiding (it could not coherently rule
in or rule out the appropriate actions), and that the “moral point of view”
rigoristically demanded a pure or dutiful motivation to which no human agent
could conform. By contrast, Hegel claimed that the dualisms of morality could
be overcome in ethical life (Sittlichkeit), those modern social institutions
which, it was claimed, provided the content or true “objects” of a rational
will. These institutions, the family, civil society, and the state, did not
require duties in potential conflict with our own substantive ends, but were
rather experienced as the “realization” of our individual free will. It has
remained controversial what for Hegel a truly free, rational
self-determination, continuous with, rather than constraining, our desire for
happiness and self-actualization, amounted to. Many commentators have noted
that, among modern philosophers, only Spinoza, whom Hegel greatly admired, was
as insistent on such a thoroughgoing compatibilism, and on a refusal to adopt
the Christian view of human beings as permanently divided against themselves.
In his most ambitious analysis of such oppositions Hegel went so far as to
claim that, not only could alternatives be shown to be ultimately compatible
when thought together within some higher-order “Notion” (Begriff) that resolved
or “sublated” the opposition, but that one term in such opposition could
actually be said to imply or require its contrary, that a “positing” of such a
notion would, to maintain consistency, require its own “negating,” and that it
was this sort of dialectical opposition that could be shown to require a
sublation, or Aufhebung (a term of art in Hegel that simultaneously means in
German ‘to cancel’, ‘to preserve’, and ‘to raise up’). This claim for a
dialectical development of our fundamental notions has been the most severely
criticized in Hegel’s philosophy. Many critics have doubted that so much basic
conceptual change can be accounted for by an internal critique, one that merely
develops the presuppositions inherent in the affirmation of some notion or
position or related practice. This issue has especially attracted critics of
Hegel’s Science of Logic, where he tries first to show that the attempt to
categorize anything that is, simply and immediately, as “Being,” is an attempt
that both “negates itself,” or ends up categorizing everything as “Nothing,”
and then that this self-negation requires a resolution in the higher-order
category of “Becoming.” This analysis continues into an extended argument that
purports to show that any attempt to categorize anything at all must ultimately
make use of the distinctions of “essence” and “appearance,” and elements of
syllogistic and finally Hegel’s own dialectical logic, and both the details and
the grand design of that project have been the subject of a good deal of
controversy. (Unfortunately, much of this controversy has been greatly confused
by the popular association of the terms “thesis,” “antithesis,” and “synthesis”
with Hegel’s theory of dialectic. These crude, mechanical notions were invented
in 1837 by a less-than-sensitive Hegel expositor, Heinrich Moritz Chalybäus,
and were never used as terms of art by Hegel.) Others have argued that the
tensions Hegel does identify in various positions and practices require a much
broader analysis of the historical, especially economic, context within which
positions are formulated and become important, or some more detailed attention
to the empirical discoveries or paradoxes that, at the very least, contribute
to basic conceptual change. Those worried about the latter problem have also
raised questions about the logical relation between universal and particular
implied in Hegel’s account. Hegel, following Fichte, radicalizes a Kantian
claim about the inaccessibility of pure particularity in sensations (Kant had
written that “intuitions without concepts are blind”). Hegel charges that Kant
did not draw sufficiently radical conclusions from such an antiempiricist
claim, that he should have completely rethought the traditional distinction
between “what was given to the mind” and “what the mind did with the given.” By
contrast Hegel is confident that he has a theory of a “concrete universal,”
concepts that cannot be understood as pale generalizations or abstract
representations of given particulars, because they are required for particulars
to Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 368
4065h-l.qxd 7:39 AM 368 be apprehended in the first place. They
are not originally dependent on an immediate acquaintance with particulars;
there is no such acquaintance. Critics wonder if Hegel has much of a theory of
particularity left, if he does not claim rather that particulars, or whatever
now corresponds to them, are only interrelations of concepts, and in which the
actual details of the organization of the natural world and human history are
deduced as conceptual necessities in Hegel’s Encyclopedia. (This interpretation
of Hegel, that he believes all entities are really the thoughts, expressions,
or modes of a single underlying mental substance, and that this mind develops
and posits itself with some sort of conceptual necessity, has been termed a
panlogicism, a term of art coined by Hermann Glockner, a Hegel commentator in
the first half of the twentieth century. It is a much-disputed reading.) Such
critics are especially concerned with the implications of this issue in Hegel’s
political theory, where the great modern opposition between the state and the
individual seems subjected to this same logic, and the individual’s true
individuality is said to reside in and only in the political universal, the
State. Thus, on the one hand, Hegel’s political philosophy is often praised for
its early identification and analysis of a fundamental, new aspect of
contemporary life – the categorically distinct realm of political life in
modernity, or the independence of the “State” from the social world of private
individuals engaged in competition and private association (“civil society”).
But, on the other hand, his attempt to argue for a completion of these domains
in the State, or that individuals could only be said to be free in allegiance
to a State, has been, at least since Marx, one of the most criticized aspects
of his philosophy. Finally, criticisms also frequently target the underlying
intention behind such claims: Hegel’s career-long insistence on finding some
basic unity among the many fragmented spheres of modern thought and existence,
and his demand that this unity be articulated in a discursive account, that it
not be merely felt, or gestured at, or celebrated in edifying speculation.
PostHegelian thinkers have tended to be suspicious of any such intimations of a
whole for modern experience, and have argued that, with the destruction of the
premodern world, we simply have to content ourselves with the disconnected,
autonomous spheres of modern interests. In his lecture courses these basic
themes are treated in wide-ranging accounts of the basic institutions of
cultural history. History itself is treated as fundamentally political history,
and, in typically Hegelian fashion, the major epochs of political history are
claimed to be as they were because of the internal inadequacies of past epochs,
all until some final political semiconsciousness is achieved and realized. Art
is treated equally developmentally, evolving from symbolic, through
“classical,” to the most intensely self-conscious form of aesthetic
subjectivity, romantic art. The Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion embody
these themes in some of the most controversial ways, since Hegel often treats
religion and its development as a kind of picture or accessible
“representation” of his own views about the relation of thought to being, the
proper understanding of human finitude and “infinity,” and the essentially
social or communal nature of religious life. This has inspired a characteristic
debate among Hegel scholars, with some arguing that Hegel’s appropriation of
religion shows that his own themes are essentially religious (if an odd,
pantheistic version of Christianity), while others argue that he has so
Hegelianized religious issues that there is little distinctively religious
left. Influence. This last debate is typical of that prominent in the post-Hegelian
tradition. Although, in the decades following his death, there was a great deal
of work by self-described Hegelians on the history of law, on political
philosophy, and on aesthetics, most of the prominent academic defenders of
Hegel were interested in theology, and many of these were interested in
defending an interpretation of Hegel consistent with traditional Christian
views of a personal God and personal immortality. This began to change with the
work of “young Hegelians” such as D. F. Strauss (1808–74), Feuerbach (1804–72),
Bruno Bauer (1809–82), and Arnold Ruge (1803–80), who emphasized the humanistic
and historical dimensions of Hegel’s account of religion, rejected the Old
Hegelian tendencies toward a reconciliation with contemporary political life,
and began to reinterpret and expand Hegel’s account of the productive activity
of human spirit (eventually focusing on labor rather than intellectual and
cultural life). Strauss himself characterized the fight as between “left,”
“center,” and “right” Hegelians, depending on whether one was critical or
conservative politically, or had a theistic or a humanistic view of Hegelian
Geist. The most famous young or left Hegelian was Marx, especially during his
days in Paris as coeditor, with Ruge, of the Deutsch-französischen Jahrbücher
(1844). Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 369
4065h-l.qxd 7:39 AM 369 In Great Britain, with its long
skeptical, empiricist, and utilitarian tradition, Hegel’s work had little
influence until the latter part of the nineteenth century, when philosophers
such as Green and Caird took up some of the holistic themes in Hegel and
developed a neo-Hegelian reading of issues in politics and religion that began
to have influence in the academy. The most prominent of the British
neo-Hegelians of the next generation were Bosanquet, McTaggart, and especially
Bradley, all of whom were interested in many of the metaphysical implications
of Hegel’s idealism, what they took to be a Hegelian claim for the “internally
related” interconnection of all particulars within one single, ideal or mental,
substance. Moore and Russell waged a hugely successful counterattack in the
name of traditional empiricism and what would be called “analytic philosophy”
against such an enterprise and in this tradition largely finished off the
influence of Hegel (or what was left of the historical Hegel in these
neo-Hegelian versions). In Germany, Hegel has continued to influence a number
of different schools of neo-Marxism, sometimes itself simply called “Hegelian
Marxism,” especially the Frankfurt School, or “critical theory” group
(especially Adorno, Horkheimer, and Marcuse). And he has been extremely
influential in France, particularly thanks to the lectures of a brilliant if
idiosyncratic Russian émigré, Alexander Kojève, who taught Hegel in the 1930s
at the École Pratique des Hautes Études to the likes of Merleau-Ponty and
Lacan. Kojève was as much influenced by Marx and Heidegger as Hegel, but his
lectures inspired many thinkers to turn again to Hegel’s account of human
selfdefinition in time and to the historicity of all institutions and practices
and so forged an unusual link between Hegel and postwar existentialism.
Hegelian themes continue to resurface in contemporary hermeneutics, in
“communitarianism” in ethics, and in the increasing attention given to
conceptual change and history in the philosophy of science. This has meant for
many that Hegel should now be regarded not only as the origin of a distinctive
tradition in European philosophy that emphasizes the historical and social
nature of human existence, but as a potential contributor to many new and often
interdisciplinary approaches to philosophy.
FRANKFURT SCHOOL, IDEALISM, KANT, PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. R.B.P.
Hegelians, Young.HEGEL. Hegesias.CYRENAICS. Heidegger, Martin (1889–1976),
German philosopher whose early works contributed to phenomenology and
existentialism (e.g., Sartre) and whose later works paved the way to
hermeneutics (Gadamer) and post-structuralism (Derrida and Foucault). Born in
Messkirch in the Black Forest region, Heidegger first trained to be a Jesuit,
but switched to mathematics and philosophy in 1911. As an instructor at
Freiburg University, he worked with the founder of phenomenology, Husserl. His
masterwork, Sein und Zeit (Being and Time, 1927), was published while he was
teaching at Marburg University. This work, in opposition to the preoccupation
with epistemology dominant at the time, focused on the traditional question of
metaphysics: What is the being of entities in general? Rejecting abstract
theoretical approaches to this question, Heidegger drew on Kierkegaard’s
religious individualism and the influential movement called life-philosophy –
Lebensphilosophie, then identified with Nietzsche, Bergson, and Dilthey – to
develop a highly original account of humans as embedded in concrete situations
of action. Heidegger accepted Husserl’s chair at Freiburg in 1928; in 1933,
having been elected rector of the University, he joined the Nazi party. Although
he stepped down as rector one year later, new evidence suggests complicity with
the Nazis until the end of the war. Starting in the late thirties, his writings
started to shift toward the “antihumanist” and “poetic” form of thinking
referred to as “later Heidegger.” Heidegger’s lifelong project was to answer
the “question of being” (Seinsfrage). This question asks, concerning things in
general (rocks, tools, people, etc.), what is it to be an entity of these
sorts? It is the question of ontology first posed by ancient Greek philosophers
from Anaximander to Aristotle. Heidegger holds, however, that philosophers
starting with Plato have gone astray in trying to answer this question because
they have tended to think of being as a property or essence enduringly present
in things. In other words, they have fallen into the “metaphysics of presence,”
which thinks of being as substance. What is overlooked in traditional
metaphysics is the background conditions that enable entities to show up as
counting or mattering in some specific way in the first place. In his early
works, Heidegger tries to bring this concealed dimension of things to light by
recasting the question of being: What is the meaning of being? Or, put
differently, how do entities come to show up as intelligible to Hegelians,
Young Heidegger, Martin 370 4065h-l.qxd
7:39 AM 370 us in some
determinate way? And this question calls for an analysis of the entity that has
some prior understanding of things: human existence or Dasein (the German word
for “existence” or “being-there,” used to refer to the structures of humans
that make possible an understanding of being). Heidegger’s claim is that
Dasein’s pretheoretical (or “preontological”) understanding of being, embodied
in its everyday practices, opens a “clearing” in which entities can show up as,
say, tools, protons, numbers, mental events, and so on. This historically
unfolding clearing is what the metaphysical tradition has overlooked. In order
to clarify the conditions that make possible an understanding of being, then,
Being and Time begins with an analytic of Dasein. But Heidegger notes that
traditional interpretations of human existence have been one-sided to the
extent that they concentrate on our ways of existing when we are engaged in
theorizing and detached reflection. It is this narrow focus on the spectator
attitude that leads to the picture, found in Descartes, of the self as a mind
or subject representing material objects – the so-called subjectobject model.
In order to bypass this traditional picture, Heidegger sets out to describe
Dasein’s “average everydayness,” i.e., our ordinary, prereflective agency when
we are caught up in the midst of practical affairs. The “phenomenology of
everydayness” is supposed to lead us to see the totality of human existence,
including our moods, our capacity for authentic individuality, and our full
range of involvements with the world and with others. The analytic of Dasein is
also an ontological hermeneutics to the extent that it provides an account of
how understanding in general is possible. The result of the analytic is a
portrayal of human existence that is in accord with what Heidegger regards as
the earliest Greek experience of being as an emerging-into-presence (physis):
to be human is to be a temporal event of self-manifestation that lets other
sorts of entities first come to “emerge and abide” in the world. From the
standpoint of this description, the traditional concept of substance – whether
mental or physical – simply has no role to play in grasping humans. Heidegger’s
brilliant diagnoses or “de-structurings” of the tradition suggest that the idea
of substance arises only when the conditions making entities possible are
forgotten or concealed. Heidegger holds that there is no pregiven human
essence. Instead, humans, as self-interpreting beings, just are what they make
of themselves in the course of their active lives. Thus, as everyday agency,
Dasein is not an object with properties, but is rather the “happening” of a
life course “stretched out between birth and death.” Understood as the
“historicity” of a temporal movement or “becoming,” Dasein is found to have
three main “existentials” or basic structures shared by every “existentiell”
(i.e., specific and local) way of living. First, Dasein finds itself thrown
into a world not of its choosing, already delivered over to the task of living
out its life in a concrete context. This “facticity” of our lives is revealed
in the moods that let things matter to us in some way or other – e.g., the
burdensome feelings of concern that accompany being a parent in our culture.
Second, as projection, Dasein is always already taking some stand on its life
by acting in the world. Understood as agency, human existence is “ahead of
itself” in two senses: (1) our competent dealings with familiar situations
sketch out a range of possibilities for how things may turn out in the future,
and (2) each of our actions is contributing to shaping our lives as people of
specific sorts. Dasein is futuredirected in the sense that the ongoing
fulfillment of possibilities in the course of one’s active life constitutes
one’s identity (or being). To say that Dasein is “being-toward-death” is to say
that the stands we take (our “understanding”) define our being as a totality.
Thus, my actual ways of treating my children throughout my life define my being
as a parent in the end, regardless of what good intentions I might have.
Finally, Dasein is discourse in the sense that we are always articulating – or
“addressing and discussing” – the entities that show up in our concernful
absorption in current situations. These three existentials define human
existence as a temporal unfolding. The unity of these dimensions – being
already in a world, ahead of itself, and engaged with things – Heidegger calls
care. This is what it means to say that humans are the entities whose being is
at issue for them. Taking a stand on our own being, we constitute our identity
through what we do. The formal structure of Dasein as temporality is made
concrete through one’s specific involvements in the world (where ‘world’ is
used in the life-world sense in which we talk about the business world or the
world of academia). Dasein is the unitary phenomenon of being-in-the-world. A
core component of Heidegger’s early works is his description of how Dasein’s
practical dealings with equipment define the being of the entities that show up
in the world. In hammering in a workshop, e.g., what ordinarily shows up for us
is not a hammer-thing with properties, but rather a web of significance
relations shaped by Heidegger, Martin Heidegger, Martin 371 4065h-l.qxd 7:39 AM
371 our projects. Hammering is “in order to” join boards, which is “for”
building a bookcase, which is “for the sake of” being a person with a neat
study. The hammer is encountered in terms of its place in this holistic context
of functionality – the “ready-to-hand.” In other words, the being of the
equipment – its “ontological definition” – consists of its relations to other
equipment and its actual use within the entire practical context. Seen from
this standpoint, the brute, meaningless objects assumed to be basic by the
metaphysical tradition – the “present-at-hand” – can show up only when there is
a breakdown in our ordinary dealings with things, e.g., when the hammer breaks
or is missing. In this sense, the ready-to-hand is said to be more primordial
than the material objects treated as basic by the natural sciences. It follows,
then, that the being of entities in the world is constituted by the framework
of intelligibility or “disclosedness” opened by Dasein’s practices. This
clearing is truth in the original meaning of the Greek word aletheia, which
Heidegger renders as ‘un-concealment’. But it would be wrong to think that what
is claimed here is that humans are initially just given, and that they then go
on to create a clearing. For, in Heidegger’s view, our own being as agents of
specific types is defined by the world into which we are thrown: in my
workshop, I can be a craftsman or an amateur, but not a samurai paying court to
a daimyo. Our identity as agents is made possible by the context of shared
forms of life and linguistic practices of a public life-world. For the most
part, we exist as the “they” (das Man), participants in the historically
constituted “cohappening of a people” (Volk). The embeddedness of our existence
in a cultural context explains our inveterate tendency toward inauthenticity.
As we become initiated into the practices of our community, we are inclined to
drift along with the crowd, doing what “one” does, enacting stereotyped roles,
and thereby losing our ability to seize on and define our own lives. Such
falling into public preoccupations Heidegger sees as a sign that we are fleeing
from the fact that we are finite beings who stand before death (understood as
the culmination of our possibilities). When, through anxiety and hearing the
call of conscience, we face up to our being-toward-death, our lives can be
transformed. To be authentic is to clear-sightedly face up to one’s
responsibility for what one’s life is adding up to as a whole. And because our
lives are inseparable from our community’s existence, authenticity involves
seizing on the possibilities circulating in our shared “heritage” in order to
realize a communal “destiny.” Heidegger’s ideal of resolute “taking action” in
the current historical situation no doubt contributed to his leap into politics
in the 1930s. According to his writings of that period, the ancient Greeks
inaugurated a “first beginning” for Western civilization, but centuries of
forgetfulness (beginning with the Latinization of Greek words) have torn us
away from the primal experience of being rooted in that initial setting.
Heidegger hoped that, guided by the insights embodied in great works of art
(especially Hölderlin’s poetry), National Socialism would help bring about a
world-rejuvenating “new beginning” comparable to the first beginning in ancient
Greece. Heidegger’s later writings attempt to fully escape the subjectivism he
sees dominating Western thought from its inception up to Nietzsche. “The Origin
of the Work of Art” (1935), for example, shows how a great work of art such as
a Greek temple, by shaping the world in which a people live, constitutes the
kinds of people that can live in that world. An Introduction to Metaphysics
(1935) tries to recover the Greek experience of humans as beings whose
activities of gathering and naming (logos) are above all a response to what is
more than human. The later writings emphasize that which resists all human
mastery and comprehension. Such terms as ‘nothingness’, ‘earth’, and ‘mystery’
suggest that what shows itself to us always depends on a background of what
does not show itself, what remains concealed. Language comes to be understood
as the medium through which anything, including the human, first becomes
accessible and intelligible. Because language is the source of all
intelligibility, Heidegger says that humans do not speak, but rather language
speaks us – an idea that became central to poststructuralist theories. In his
writings after the war, Heidegger replaces the notions of resoluteness and
political activism with a new ideal of letting-be or releasement
(Gelassenheit), a stance characterized by meditative thinking, thankfulness for
the “gift” of being, and openness to the silent “call” of language. The
technological “enframing” (Gestell) of our age – encountering everything as a
standing reserve on hand for our use – is treated not as something humans do,
but instead as a manifestation of being itself. The “anti-humanism” of these
later works is seen in the description of technology (the mobilization of
everything for the sole purpose of greater efficiency) as an Heidegger, Martin
Heidegger, Martin 372 4065h-l.qxd 7:39
AM 372 epochal event in the “history of
being,” a way things have come-into-their-own (Ereignis) rather than as a human
accomplishment. The history or “sending” (Geschick) of being consists of epochs
that have all gone increasingly astray from the original beginning inaugurated
by the pre-Socratics. Since human willpower alone cannot bring about a new
epoch, technology cannot be ended by our efforts. But a non-technological way
of encountering things is hinted at in a description of a jug as a fourfold of
earth, sky, mortals, and gods, and Heidegger reflects on forms of poetry that
point to a new, non-metaphysical way of experiencing being. Through a
transformed relation to language and art, and by abandoning “onto-theology”
(the attempt to ground all entities in one supreme entity), we might prepare ourselves
for a transformed way of understanding being.
Hellenistic philosophy,
the philosophical systems of the Hellenistic age (323–30 B.C., although 311–87
B.C. better defines it as a philosophical era), notably Epicureanism, Stoicism,
and Skepticism. These all emerged in the generation after Aristotle’s death
(322 B.C.), and dominated philosophical debate until the first century B.C.,
during which there were revivals of traditional Platonism and of
Aristotelianism. The age was one in which much of the eastern Mediterranean
world absorbed Greek culture (was “Hellenized,” hence “Hellenistic”), and
recruits to philosophy flocked from this region to Athens, which remained the
center of philosophical activity until 87 B.C. Then the Roman sack of Athens
drove many philosophers into exile, and neither the schools nor the styles of
philosophy that had grown up there ever fully recovered. Very few philosophical
writings survive intact from the period. Our knowledge of Hellenistic
philosophers depends mainly on later doxography, on the Roman writers Lucretius
and Cicero (both mid-first century B.C.), and on what we learn from the
schools’ critics in later centuries, e.g. Sextus Empiricus and Plutarch.
’Skeptic’, a term not actually current before the very end of the Hellenistic
age, serves as a convenient label to characterize two philosophical movements.
The first is the New Academy: the school founded by Plato, the Academy, became
in this period a largely dialectical one, conducting searching critiques of
other schools’ doctrines without declaring any of its own, beyond perhaps the
assertion (however guarded) that nothing could be known and the accompanying
recommendation of “suspension of judgment” (epoche). The nature and vivacity of
Stoicism owed much to its prolonged debates with the New Academy. The founder
of this Academic phase was Arcesilaus (school head c.268– c.241); its most
revered and influential protagonist was Carneades (school head in the
mid-second century); and its most prestigious voice was that of Cicero (106–43
B.C.), whose highly influential philosophical works were written mainly from a
New Academic stance. But by the early first century B.C. the Academy was
drifting back to a more doctrinal stance, and in the later part of the century
it was largely eclipsed by a second “skeptic” movement, Pyrrhonism. This was
founded by Aenesidemus, a pioneering skeptic despite his claim to be merely
reviving the philosophy of Pyrrho, a philosophical guru of the early
Hellenistic period. His neo-Pyrrhonism survives today mainly through the
writings of Sextus Empiricus (second century A.D.), an adherent of the school
who, strictly speaking, represents its post-Hellenistic phase. The Peripatos,
Aristotle’s school, officially survived throughout the era, but it is not
regarded as a distinctively “Hellenistic” movement. Despite the eminence of
Aristotle’s first successor, Theophrastus (school head 322–287), it thereafter
fell from prominence, its fortunes only reviving around the mid-first century
B.C. It is disputed how far the other Hellenistic philosophers were even aware
of Aristotle’s treatises, which should not in any case be regarded as a primary
influence on them. Each school had a location in Athens to which it could draw
pupils. The Epicurean school was a relatively private institution, its “Garden”
outside the city walls housing a close-knit philosophical community. The Stoics
took their name from the Stoa Poikile, the “Painted Colonnade” in central
Athens where they gathered. The Academics were based in the Academy, a public
grove just outside the city. Philosophers were public figures, a familiar sight
around town. Each school’s philosophical identity was further clarified by its
absolute loyalty to the name of its Heidelberg School Hellenistic philosophy 373
4065h-l.qxd 7:39 AM 373 founder – respectively Epicurus, Zeno of
Citium, and Plato – and by the polarities that developed in interschool
debates. Epicureanism is diametrically opposed on most issues to Stoicism.
Academic Skepticism provides another antithesis to Stoicism, not through any
positions of its own (it had none), but through its unflagging critical
campaign against every Stoic thesis. It is often said that in this age the old
Greek political institution of the city-state had broken down, and that the
Hellenistic philosophies were an answer to the resulting crisis of values.
Whether or not there is any truth in this, it remains clear that moral concerns
were now much less confined to the individual city-state than previously, and
that at an extreme the boundaries had been pushed back to include all mankind
within the scope of an individual’s moral obligations. Our “affinity”
(oikeiosis) to all mankind is an originally Stoic doctrine that acquired
increasing currency with other schools. This attitude partly reflects the
weakening of national and cultural boundaries in the Hellenistic period, as
also in the Roman imperial period that followed it. The three recognized
divisions of philosophy were ethics, logic, and physics. In ethics, the central
objective was to state and defend an account of the “end” (telos), the moral
goal to which all activity was subordinated: the Epicureans named pleasure, the
Stoics conformity with nature. Much debate centered on the semimythical figure
of the wise man, whose conduct in every conceivable circumstance was debated by
all schools. Logic in its modern sense was primarily a Stoic concern, rejected
as irrelevant by the Epicureans. But Hellenistic logic included epistemology,
where the primary focus of interest was the “criterion of truth,” the ultimate
yardstick against which all judgments could be reliably tested. Empiricism was
a surprisingly uncontroversial feature of Hellenistic theories: there was
little interest in the Platonic-Aristotelian idea that knowledge in the strict
sense is non-sensory, and the debate between dogmatists and Skeptics was more
concerned with the question whether any proposed sensory criterion was
adequate. Both Stoics and Epicureans attached especial importance to prolepsis,
the generic notion of a thing, held to be either innate or naturally acquired
in a way that gave it a guaranteed veridical status. Physics saw an opposition
between Epicurean atomism, with its denial of divine providence, and the Stoic
world-continuum, imbued with divine rationality. The issue of determinism was
also placed on the philosophical map: Epicurean morality depends on the denial
of (both physical and logical) determinism, whereas Stoic morality is
compatible with, indeed actually requires, the deterministic causal nexus
through which providence operates.
Helmholtz, Hermann von
(1821–94), German physiologist and physicist known for groundbreaking work in
physics, physiological optics, perceptual psychology, and the philosophy of
geometry. Formally trained as a physician, he distinguished himself in physics
in 1848 as a codiscoverer of the law of conservation of energy, and by the end
of his life was perhaps the most influential figure in German physical
research. Philosophically, his most important influence was on the study of
space. Intuitionist psychologists held that the geometrical structure of
three-dimensional space was given directly in sensation by innate physiological
mechanisms; Helmholtz brought this theory to severe empirical trials and
argued, on the contrary, that our knowledge of space consists of inferences
from accumulated experience. On the mathematical side, he attacked Kant’s view
that Euclidean geometry is the a priori form of outer intuition by showing that
it is possible to have visual experience of non-Euclidean space (“On the
Origins and Meaning of Geometrical Axioms,” 1870). His crucial insight was that
empirical geometry depends on physical assumptions about the behavior of
measuring instruments. This inspired the view of Poincaré and logical
empiricism that the empirical content of geometry is fixed by physical
definitions, and made possible Einstein’s use of non-Euclidean geometry in
physics. PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS,
POINCARÉ. R.D. Helvétius, Claude Adrien (1715–71), French philosopher prominent
in the formative phases of eighteenth-century materialism in France. His De
l’esprit (1758) was widely discussed internationally, but condemned by the
University of Paris and burned by the government. Helvétius attempted to
clarify his doctrine in his posthumously published De l’homme. Following
Locke’s criticism of the innate ideas, Helvétius stressed the function of
experience in our acquisition of knowledge. In accord with the doctrines of
d’Holbach, Condillac, and La Mettrie, the materialist Helvétius regarded the
sensations as the basis of all our knowledge. Only by Helmholtz, Hermann von
Helvétius, Claude Adrien 374 4065h-l.qxd
7:39 AM 374 comparison, abstraction,
and combination of sensations do we reach the level of concepts. Peculiar to
Helvétius, however, is the stress on the social determinations of our
knowledge. Specific interests and passions are the starting point of all our
striving for knowledge. Egoism is the spring of our desires and actions. The
civil laws of the enlightened state enabled egoism to be transformed into
social competition and thereby diverted toward public benefits. Like his
materialist contemporary d’Holbach and later Condorcet, Helvétius sharply
criticized the social function of the church. Priests, he claimed, provided
society with wrong moral ideas. He demanded a thorough reform of the
educational system for the purpose of individual and social emancipation. In
contrast to the teachings of Rousseau, Helvétius praised the further
development of science, art, and industry as instruments for the historical
progress of mankind. The ideal society consists of enlightened because
well-educated citizens living in comfortable and even moderately luxurious
circumstances. All people should participate in the search for truth, by means
of public debates and discussions. Truth is equated with the moral good.
Helvétius had some influence on Marxist historical materialism. H.P. Hempel,
Carl G(ustav) (1905–97), eminent philosopher of science associated with the
Vienna Circle of logical empiricist philosophers in the early 1930s, before his
emigration to the United States; thereafter he became one of the most
influential philosophers of science of his time, largely through groundbreaking
work on the logical analysis of the concepts of confirmation and scientific
explanation. Hempel received his doctorate under Reichenbach at the University
of Berlin in 1934 with a dissertation on the logical analysis of probability.
He studied with Carnap at the University of Vienna in 1929–30, where he
participated in the “protocol-sentence debate” concerning the observational
basis of scientific knowledge raging within the Vienna Circle between Moritz
Schlick (1882–1936) and Otto Neurath (1882–1945). Hempel was attracted to the
“radical physicalism” articulated by Neurath and Carnap, which denied the
foundational role of immediate experience and asserted that all statements of
the total language of science (including observation reports or
protocol-sentences) can be revised as science progresses. This led to Hempel’s
first major publication, “On the Logical Positivists’ Theory of Truth” (1935).
He moved to the United States to work with Carnap at the University of Chicago
in 1937–38. He also taught at Queens College and Yale before his long career at
Princeton (1955–1975). In the 1940s he collaborated with his friends Olaf
Helmer and Paul Oppenheim on a celebrated series of papers, the most
influential of which are “Studies in the Logic of Confirmation” (1945) and
“Studies in the Logic of Explanation” (1948, coauthored with Oppenheim). The
latter paper articulated the deductive-nomological model, which characterizes
scientific explanations as deductively valid arguments proceeding from general
laws and initial conditions to the fact to be explained, and served as the
basis for all future work on the subject. Hempel’s papers on explanation and
confirmation (and also related topics such as concept formation, criteria of
meaningfulness, and scientific theories) were collected together in Aspects of Scientific
Explanation (1965), one of the most important works in postwar philosophy of
science. He also published a more popular, but extremely influential
introduction to the field, Philosophy of Natural Science (1966). Hempel and
Kuhn became colleagues at Princeton in the 1960s. Another fruitful
collaboration ensued, as a result of which Hempel moved away from the Carnapian
tradition of logical analysis toward a more naturalistic and pragmatic
conception of science in his later work. As he himself explains, however, this
later turn can also be seen as a return to a similarly naturalistic conception
Neurath had earlier defended within the Vienna Circle.
henotheism, allegiance to
one supreme deity while conceding existence to others; also described as monolatry,
incipient monotheism, or practical monotheism. It occupies a middle ground
between polytheism and radical monotheism, which denies reality to all gods
save one. It has been claimed that early Judaism passed through a henotheistic
phase, acknowledging other Middle Eastern deities (albeit condemning their
worship), en route to exclusive recognition of Yahweh. But the concept of
progress from polytheism through henotheism Hempel, Carl G(ustav) henotheism
375 4065h-l.qxd 7:39 AM 375 to monotheism is a rationalizing
construct, and cannot be supposed to capture the complex development of any
historical religion, including that of ancient Israel. A.E.L. Henry of Ghent
(c.1217–93), Belgian theologian and philosopher. After serving as a church
official at Tournai and Brugge, he taught theology at Paris from 1276. His
major writings were Summa quaestionum ordinariarum (Summa of Ordinary
Questions) and Quodlibeta (Quodlibetal Questions). He was the leading
representative of the neoAugustinian movement at Paris in the final quarter of
the thirteenth century. His theory of knowledge combines Aristotelian elements
with Augustinian illuminationism. Heavily dependent on Avicenna for his view of
the reality enjoyed by essences of creatures (esse essentiae) from eternity, he
rejected both real distinction and real identity of essence and existence in
creatures, and defended their intentional distinction. He also rejected a real
distinction between the soul and its powers and rejected the purely potential
character of prime matter. He defended the duality of substantial form in man,
the unicity of form in other material substances, and the primacy of will in
the act of choice. J.F.W. Hentisberi, Hentisberus.
Heraclitus (fl. c.500
B.C.), Greek philosopher. A transition figure between the Milesian philosophers
and the later pluralists, Heraclitus stressed unity in the world of change. He
follows the Milesians in positing a series of cyclical transformations of basic
stuffs of the world; for instance, he holds that fire changes to water and
earth in turn. Moreover, he seems to endorse a single source or arche of
natural substances, namely fire. But he also observes that natural
transformations necessarily involve contraries such as hot and cold, wet and
dry. Indeed, without the one contrary the other would not exist, and without
contraries the cosmos would not exist. Hence strife is justice, and war is the
father and king of all. In the conflict of opposites there is a hidden harmony
that sustains the world, symbolized by the tension of a bow or the attunement
of a lyre. Scholars disagree about whether Heraclitus’s chief view is that
there is a one in the many or that process is reality. Clearly the underlying
unity of phenomena is important for him. But he also stresses the transience of
physical substances and the importance of processes and qualities. Moreover,
his underlying source of unity seems to be a law of process and opposition;
thus he seems to affirm both the unity of phenomena and the reality of process.
Criticizing his predecessors such as Pythagoras and Xenophanes for doing
research without insight, Heraclitus claims that we should listen to the logos,
which teaches that all things are one. The logos, a principle of order and
knowledge, is common to all, but the many remain ignorant of it, like
sleepwalkers unaware of the reality around them. All things come to pass
according to the logos; hence it is the law of change, or at least its
expression. Heraclitus wrote a single book, perhaps organized into sections on cosmology,
politics and ethics, and theology. Apparently, however, he did not provide a
continuous argument but a series of epigrammatic remarks meant to reveal the
nature of reality through oracular and riddling language. Although he seems to
have been a recluse without immediate disciples, he may have stirred Parmenides
to his reaction against contraries. In the late fifth century B.C. Cratylus of
Athens preached a radical Heraclitean doctrine according to which everything is
in flux and there is accordingly no knowledge of the world. This version of
Heracliteanism influenced Plato’s view of the sensible world and caused Plato
and Aristotle to attribute a radical doctrine of flux to Heraclitus. Democritus
imitated Heraclitus’s ethical sayings, and in Hellenistic times the Stoics
appealed to him for their basic principles.
Herbart, Johann Friedrich
(1776–1841), German philosopher who significantly contributed to psychology and
the theory of education. Rejecting the idealism of Fichte and Hegel, he
attempted to establish a form of psychology founded on experience. The task of
philosophy is the analysis of concepts given in ordinary experience. Logic must
clarify these concepts, Metaphysics should correct them, while Aesthetics and
Ethics are to complement them by an analysis of values. Herbart advocated a
form of determinism in psychology and ethics. The laws that govern
psychological processes are identical with those that govern the heavens. He
subordinated ethics to aesthetics, arguing that our moral values originate from
certain immediate and involuntary judgments of like and dislike. The five basic
ideas of morality are inner freedom, perfection, benevolence, law, and justice
or equity. Herbart’s view of education – that it should aim at producing
individuals who possess inner freedom and strength of character – was highly
influential in nineteenth-century Germany. M.K. Henry of Ghent Herbart, Johann
Friedrich 376 4065h-l.qxd 7:39 AM 376 Herder, Johann Gottfried von (1744–1803),
German philosopher, an intellectual and literary figure central to the
transition from the German Enlightenment to Romanticism. He was born in East
Prussia and received an early classical education. About 1762, while studying
theology at the University of Königsberg, he came under the influence of Kant.
He also began a lifelong friendship with Hamann, who especially stimulated his
interests in the interrelations among language, culture, and history. After
ordination as a Lutheran minister in 1765, he began his association with the Berlin
Academy, earning its prestigious “prize” for his “Essay on the Origin of
Language” (1772). In 1776 he was appointed Generalsuperintendent of the
Lutheran clergy at Weimar through the intercession of Goethe. He was then able
to focus his intellectual and literary powers on most of the major issues of
his time. Of particular note are his contributions to psychology in Of the
Cognition and Sensation of the Human Soul (1778); to the philosophy of history
and culture in Ideas for the Philosophy of the History of Mankind (1784–91),
perhaps his most influential work; and to philosophy in Understanding and
Experience (1799), which contains his extensive Metakritik of Kant’s Critique
of Pure Reason. Herder was an intellectual maverick and provocateur, writing when
the Enlightenment conception of reason was in decline but before its limited
defense by Kant or its total rejection by Romanticism had become entrenched in
the German-speaking world. Rejecting any rational system, Herder’s thought is
best viewed as a mosaic of certain ideas that reemerge in various guises
throughout his writings. Because of these features, Herder’s thought has been
compared with that of Rousseau. Herder’s philosophy can be described as
involving elements of naturalism, organicism, and vitalism. He rejected
philosophical explanations, appealing to the supernatural or divine, such as
the concept of the “immortal soul” in psychology, a “divine origin” of
language, or “providence” in history. He sought to discern an underlying
primordial force to account for the psychological unity of the various
“faculties.” He viewed this natural tendency toward “organic formation” as also
operative in language and culture, and as ultimately manifested in the dynamic
development of the various cultures in the form of a universal history.
Finally, he often wrote in a way that suggested the dynamic process of life
itself as the basic metaphor undergirding his thought. His influence can be
traced through Humboldt into later linguistics and through Schelling and Hegel
in the philosophy of history and later German historicism. He anticipated
elements of vitalism in Schopenhauer and Bergson. NATURALISM, ORGANICISM, PHILOSOPHY OF
BIOLOGY. J.P.Su. hereditary property.RELATION. Hermarchus.EPICUREANISM.
hermeneutic circle.HERMENEUTICS. hermeneutics, the art or theory of
interpretation, as well as a type of philosophy that starts with questions of
interpretation. Originally concerned more narrowly with interpreting sacred
texts, the term acquired a much broader significance in its historical
development and finally became a philosophical position in twentieth-century
German philosophy. There are two competing positions in hermeneutics: whereas
the first follows Dilthey and sees interpretation or Verstehen as a method for the
historical and human sciences, the second follows Heidegger and sees it as an
“ontological event,” an interaction between interpreter and text that is part
of the history of what is understood. Providing rules or criteria for
understanding what an author or native “really” meant is a typical problem for
the first approach. The interpretation of the law provides an example for the
second view, since the process of applying the law inevitably transforms it. In
general, hermeneutics is the analysis of this process and its conditions of
possibility. It has typically focused on the interpretation of ancient texts
and distant peoples, cases where the unproblematic everyday understanding and
communication cannot be assumed. Schleiermacher’s analysis of understanding and
expression related to texts and speech marks the beginning of hermeneutics in
the modern sense of a scientific methodology. This emphasis on methodology
continues in nineteenth-century historicism and culminates in Dilthey’s attempt
to ground the human sciences in a theory of interpretation, understood as the
imaginative but publicly verifiable reenactment of the subjective experiences
of others. Such a method of interpretation reveals the possibility of an
objective knowledge of human beings not accessible to empiricist inquiry and
thus of a distinct methodology for the human sciences. One result of the
analysis of interpretation in the nineteenth century was the recognition of
“the hermeneutic circle,” first developed by SchleierHerder, Johann Gottfried
von hermeneutics 377 4065h-l.qxd 7:39
AM 377 macher. The circularity of
interpretation concerns the relation of parts to the whole: the interpretation
of each part is dependent on the interpretation of the whole. But
interpretation is circular in a stronger sense: if every interpretation is
itself based on interpretation, then the circle of interpretation, even if it
is not vicious, cannot be escaped. Twentieth-century hermeneutics advanced by
Heidegger and Gadamer radicalize this notion of the hermeneutic circle, seeing
it as a feature of all knowledge and activity. Hermeneutics is then no longer
the method of the human sciences but “universal,” and interpretation is part of
the finite and situated character of all human knowing. “Philosophical hermeneutics”
therefore criticizes Cartesian foundationalism in epistemology and
Enlightenment universalism in ethics, seeing science as a cultural practice and
prejudices (or prejudgments) as ineliminable in all judgments. Positively, it
emphasizes understanding as continuing a historical tradition, as well as
dialogical openness, in which prejudices are challenged and horizons
broadened.
hermetism, also
hermeticism, a philosophical theology whose basic impulse was the gnostic
conviction that human salvation depends on revealed knowledge (gnosis) of God
and of the human and natural creations. Texts ascribed to Hermes Trismegistus,
a Greco-Egyptian version of the Egyptian god Thoth, may have appeared as early
as the fourth century B.C., but the surviving Corpus Hermeticum in Greek and
Latin is a product of the second and third centuries A.D. Fragments of the same
literature exist in Greek, Armenian, and Coptic as well; the Coptic versions
are part of a discovery made at Nag Hammadi after World War II. All these
Hermetica record hermetism as just described. Other Hermetica traceable to the
same period but surviving in later Arabic or Latin versions deal with
astrology, alchemy, magic, and other kinds of occultism. Lactantius, Augustine,
and other early Christians cited Hermes but disagreed on his value; before
Iamblichus, pagan philosophers showed little interest. Muslims connected Hermes
with a Koranic figure, Idris, and thereby enlarged the medieval hermetic
tradition, which had its first large effects in the Latin West among the
twelfth-century Platonists of Chartres. The only ancient hermetic text then
available in the West was the Latin Asclepius, but in 1463 Ficino interrupted
his epochal translation of Plato to Latinize fourteen of the seventeen Greek
discourses in the main body of the Corpus Hermeticum (as distinct from the many
Greek fragments preserved by Stobaeus but unknown to Ficino). Ficino was
willing to move so quickly to Hermes because he believed that this Egyptian
deity stood at the head of the “ancient theology” (prisca theologia), a
tradition of pagan revelation that ran parallel to Christian scripture,
culminated with Plato, and continued through Plotinus and the later
Neoplatonists. Ficino’s Hermes translation, which he called the Pimander, shows
no interest in the magic and astrology about which he theorized later in his
career. Trinitarian theology was his original motivation. The Pimander was
enormously influential in the later Renaissance, when Giovanni Pico della
Mirandola, Lodovico Lazzarelli, Jacques Lefèvre d’Etaples, Symphorien Champier,
Francesco Giorgi, Agostino Steuco, Francesco Patrizi, and others enriched
Western appreciation of Hermes. The first printed Greek Hermetica was the 1554
edition of Adrien Turnebus. The last before the nineteenth century appeared in
1630, a textual hiatus that reflected a decline in the reputation of Hermes
after Isaac Casaubon proved philologically in 1614 that the Greek Hermetica had
to be post-Christian, not the remains of primeval Egyptian wisdom. After
Casaubon, hermetic ideas fell out of fashion with most Western philosophers of
the current canon, but the historiography of the ancient theology remained
influential for Newton and for lesser figures even later. The content of the
Hermetica was out of tune with the new science, so Casaubon’s redating left
Hermes to the theosophical heirs of Robert Fludd, whose opponents (Kepler,
Mersenne, Gassendi) turned away from the Hermetica and similar fascinations of
Renaissance humanist culture. By the nineteenth century, only theosophists took
Hermes seriously as a prophet of pagan wisdom, but he was then rediscovered by
German students of Christianity and Hellenistic religions, especially Richard
Reitzenstein, who published his Poimandres in 1904. The ancient Hermetica are
now read in the 1946–54 edition of A. D. Nock and A. J. Festugière. FICINO. B.P.C. Herzen, Alexander (1812–70),
Russian editor, memoirist, and social philosopher, in exile in Western Europe
from 1847. Herzen moved in his philosophy of history from an early Hegelian
hermeticism Herzen, Alexander 378 4065h-l.qxd
7:39 AM 378 rationalism to a
“philosophy of contingency,” stressing the “whirlwind of chances” in nature and
in human life and the “tousled improvisation” of the historical process. He
rejected determinism, emphasizing the “phenomenological fact” of the
experienced “sense of freedom.” Anticipating the Dostoevsky of the “Legend of
the Grand Inquisitor,” he offered an original analysis of the “escape from
freedom” and the cleaving to moral and political authority, and sketched a
curiously contemporary-sounding “emotivist” ethical theory. After 1848,
disillusioned with “bourgeois” Europe and its “selfenclosed individualism,” but
equally disillusioned with what he had come to see as the bourgeois ideal of
many European socialists, Herzen turned to the Russian peasant and the peasant
village commune as offering the best hope for a humane development of society.
In this “Russian socialism” he anticipated a central doctrine of the Russian
populists of the 1870s. Herzen stood alone in resisting the common tendency of
such otherwise different thinkers as Feuerbach, Marx, and J. S. Mill to
undervalue the historical present, to overvalue the historical future, and to
treat actual persons as means in the service of remote, merely possible
historical ends. Herzen’s own central emphasis fell powerfully and consistently
on the freedom, independence, and non-instrumentalizable value of living
persons. And he saw more clearly than any of his contemporaries that there are
no future persons, that it is only in the present that free human individuals
live and move and have their being.
heuristics, a rule or
solution adopted to reduce the complexity of computational tasks, thereby
reducing demands on resources such as time, memory, and attention. If an
algorithm is a procedure yielding a correct solution to a problem, then a
heuristic procedure may not reach a solution even if there is one, or may
provide an incorrect answer. The reliability of heuristics varies between
domains; the resulting biases are predictable, and provide information about
system design. Chess, for example, is a finite game with a finite number of
possible positions, but there is no known algorithm for finding the optimal
move. Computers and humans both employ heuristics in evaluating intermediate
moves, relying on a few significant cues to game quality, such as safety of the
king, material balance, and center control. The use of these criteria
simplifies the problem, making it computationally tractable. They are heuristic
guides, reliable but limited in success. There is no guarantee that the result
will be the best move or even good. They are nonetheless satisfactory for
competent chess. Work on human judgment indicates a similar moral. Examples of
judgmental infelicities support the view that human reasoning systematically
violates standards for statistical reasoning, ignoring base rates, sample size,
and correlations. Experimental results suggest that humans utilize judgmental
heuristics in gauging probabilities, such as representativeness, or the degree
to which an individual or event resembles a prototypical member of a category.
Such heuristics produce reasonable judgments in many cases, but are of limited
validity when measured by a Bayesian standard. Judgmental heuristics are biased
and subject to systemic errors. Experimental support for the importance of
these heuristics depends on cases in which subjects deviate from the normative
standard. BAYESIAN RATIONALITY,
EMPIRICAL DECISION THEORY. R.C.R. hexis (Greek, from hexo, ‘to have’, ‘to be
disposed’), a (good or bad) condition, disposition, or state. The traditional rendering,
‘habit’ (Latin habitus), is misleading, for it tends to suggest the idea of an
involuntary and merely repetitious pattern of behavior. A hexis is rather a
state of character or of mind that disposes us to deliberately choose to act or
to think in a certain way. The term acquired a quasi-technical status after
Aristotle advanced the view that hexis is the genus of virtue, both moral and
intellectual. In the Nicomachean Ethics he distinguishes hexeis from passions
(pathe) and faculties (dunamis) of the soul. If a man fighting in the front
ranks feels afraid when he sees the enemy approaching, he is undergoing an
involuntary passion. His capacity to be affected by fear on this or other
occasions is part of his makeup, one of his faculties. If he chooses to stay
where his commanders placed him, this is due to the hexis or state of character
we call courage. Likewise, one who is consistently good at identifying what is
best for oneself can be said to possess a hexis called prudence. Not all states
and dispositions are commendable. Cowardice and stupidity are also hexeis. Both
in the sense of ‘state’ and of ‘possession’ hexis plays a role in Aristotle’s
Categories. ARISTOTLE, VIRTUE ETHICS.
A.G.-L. heterological hexis 379 4065h-l.qxd
7:39 AM 379 Heytesbury, William,
also called Hentisberus, Hentisberi, Tisberi (before 1313–c.1372), English
philosopher and chancellor of Oxford University. He wrote Sophismata
(“Sophisms”), Regulae solvendi sophismata (“Rules for Solving Sophisms”), and
De sensu composito et diviso (“On the Composite and Divided Sense”). Other
works are doubtfully attributed to him. Heytesbury belonged to the generation
immediately after Thomas Bradwardine and Kilvington, and was among the most
significant members of the Oxford Calculators, important in the early
developemnt of physics. Unlike Kilvington but like Bradwardine, he appealed to
mathematical calculations in addition to logical and conceptual analysis in the
treatment of change, motion, acceleration, and other physical notions. His
Regulae includes perhaps the most influential treatment of the liar paradox in
the Middle Ages. Heytesbury’s work makes widespread use of “imaginary” thought
experiments assuming physical impossibilities that are yet logically
consistent. His influence was especially strong in Italy in the fifteenth
century, where his works were studied widely and commented on many times.
OXFORD CALCULATORS.
P.V.S. hidden variable.PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, QUANTUM MECHANICS. hierarchical
system.COMPUTER THEORY. hierarchy, a division of mathematical objects into
subclasses in accordance with an ordering that reflects their complexity.
Around the turn of the century, analysts interested in the “descriptive set
theory” of the real numbers defined and studied two systems of classification
for sets of reals, the Borel (due to Emil Borel) and the G hierarchies. In the
1940s, logicians interested in recursion and definability (most importantly,
Stephen Kleene) introduced and studied other hierarchies (the arithmetic, the
hyperarithmetic, and the analytical hierarchies) of reals (identified with sets
of natural numbers) and of sets of reals; the relations between this work and
the earlier work were made explicit in the 1950s by J. Addison. Other sorts of
hierarchies have been introduced in other corners of logic. All these so-called
hierarchies have at least this in common: they divide a class of mathematical
objects into subclasses subject to a natural well-founded ordering (e.g., by
subsethood) that reflects the complexity (in a sense specific to the hierarchy
under consideration) of the objects they contain. What follows describes
several hierarchies from the study of definability. (For more historical and
mathematical information see Descriptive Set Theory by Y. Moschovakis, North-Holland
Publishing Co., 1980.) (1) Hierarchies of formulas. Consider a formal language
L with quantifiers ‘E’ and ‘D’. Given a set B of formulas in L, we inductively
define a hierarchy that treats the members of B as “basic.” Set P0 % S0 % B.
Suppose sets Pn and Sn of formulas have been defined. Let Pn!1 % the set of all
formulas of the form Q1u1 . . . Qmumw when u1, . . . , um are distinct
variables, Q1, . . . , Qm are all ‘E’, m M 1, and w 1 Sn. Let Sn+1 % the set of
all formulas of that form for Q1, . . . , Qm all ‘D’, and w 1 Pn. Here are two
such hierarchies for languages of arithmetic. Take the logical constants to be
truthfunctions, ‘E’ and ‘D’. (i) Let L0 % the first-order language of
arithmetic, based on ‘%’, a two-place predicate-constant ‘‹’, an individual-constant
for 0, functionconstants for successor, addition, and multiplication;
‘first-order’ means that bound variables are all first-order (ranging over
individuals); we’ll allow free second-order variables (ranging over properties
or sets of individuals). Let B % the set of bounded formulas, i.e. those formed
from atomic formulas using connectives and bounded quantification: if w is
bounded so are Eu(u ‹ t / w) and Du(u ‹ t & w). (ii) Let L1 % the
second-order language of arithmetic (formed from L0 by allowing bound
second-order variables); let B % the set of formulas in which no second-order
variable is bound, and take all u1, . . . , um as above to be second-order
variables. (2) Hierarchies of definable sets. (i) The Arithmetic Hierarchy. For
a set of natural numbers (call such a thing ‘a real’) A : A 1 P0 n [ or S0 n ]
if and only if A is defined over the standard model of arithmetic (i.e., with
the constant for 0 assigned to 0, etc., and with the first-order variables
ranging over the natural numbers) by a formula of L0 in Pn [respectively Sn] as
described in (1.i). Set D0 n % P0 n Thus: In fact, all these inclusions are
proper. This hierarchy classifies the reals simple enough to be defined by
arithmetic formulas. Example: ‘Dy x % y ! y’ defines the set even of even
natural numHeytesbury, William hierarchy 380 4065h-l.qxd 7:39 AM
380 bers; the formula 1 S1, so even 1 S0 1; even is also defined by a
formula in P1; so even 1 P0 1, giving even 1 D0 1. In fact, S0 1 % the class of
recursively enumerable reals, and D0 1 % the class of recursive reals. The
classification of reals under the arithmetic hierarchy reflects complexity of
defining formulas; it differs from classification in terms of a notion of
degree of unsolvability, that reflecting a notion of comparative computational
complexity; but there are connections between these classifications. The
Arithmetic Hierarchy extends to sets of reals (using a free second-order
variable in defining sentences). Example: ‘Dx (Xx & Dy y % x ! x)’ 1 S1 and
defines the set of those reals with an even number; so that set 1 S0 1. (ii)
The Analytical Hierarchy. Given a real A : A 1 P1 n [S1 1] if and only if A is
defined (over the standard model of arithmetic with second-order variables
ranging over all sets of natural numbers) by a formula of L1 in Pn
(respectively Sn) as described in (1.ii); D1 n % P1 n 3 S1 n. Similarly for a
set of reals. The inclusions pictured above carry over, replacing superscripted
0’s by 1’s. This classifies all reals and sets of reals simple enough to have
analytical (i.e., second-order arithmetic) definitions. The subscripted ‘n’ in
‘P0 n’, etc., ranged over natural numbers. But the Arithmetic Hierarchy is
extended “upward” into the transfinite by the ramified-analytical hierarchy. Let
R0 % the class of all arithmetical reals. For an ordinal a let Ra!1 % the class
of all sets of reals definable by formulas of L1 in which second-order
variables range only over reals in Ra – this constraint imposes ramification.
For a limit-ordinal l, let Rl % Ua where n % m ! 1. So to determine relative
possibility in a model, we identify R with a collection of pairs of the form
where each of u and v is in W. If a pair is in R, v is possible relative to u,
and if is not in R, v is impossible relative to u. The relative possibility
relation then enters into the rules for evaluating modal operators. For
example, we do not want to say that at the actual world, it is possible for me
to originate from a different sperm and egg, since the only worlds where this takes
place are impossible relative to the actual world. So we have the rule that B f
is true at a world u if f is true at some world v such that v is possible
relative to u. Similarly, Af is true at a world u if f is true at every world v
which is possible relative to u. R may have simple first-order properties such
as reflexivity, (Ex)Rxx, symmetry, (Ex)(Ey)(Rxy P Ryx), and transitivity,
(Ex)(Ey)(Ez)((Rxy & Ryz) P Rxz), and different modal systems can be modal
logic modal logic 575 575 obtained by
imposing different combinations of these on R (other systems can be obtained
from higher-order constraints). The least constrained system is the system K,
in which no structural properties are put on R. In K we have B (B & C) X B
B, since if B (B & C) holds at w* then (B & C) holds at some world w
possible relative to w*, and thus by the truth-function for &, B holds at w
as well, so B B holds at w*. Hence any interpretation that makes B (B & C)
true (% true at w*) also makes B B true. Since there are no restrictions on R
in K, we can expect B (B & C) X B B in every system of modal logic
generated by constraining R. However, for K we also have C Z B C. For suppose C
holds at w*. B C holds at w* only if there is some world possible relative to
w* where C holds. But there need be no such world. In particular, since R need
not be reflexive, w* itself need not be possible relative to w*. Concomitantly,
in any system for which we stipulate a reflexive R, we will have C X B C. The
simplest such system is known as T, which has the same semantics as K except
that R is stipulated to be reflexive in every interpretation. In other systems,
further or different constraints are put on R. For example, in the system B,
each interpretation must have an R that is reflexive and symmetric, and in the
system S4, each interpretation must have an R that is reflexive and transitive.
In B we have B C Z B B C, as can be shown by an interpretation with
nontransitive R, while in S4 we have B AC Z C, as can be shown by an
interpretation with non-symmetric R. Correspondingly, in S4, B C X B B C, and
in B, B AC X C. The system in which R is reflexive, transitive, and symmetric
is called S5, and in this system, R can be omitted. For if R has all three
properties, R is an equivalence relation, i.e., it partitions W into mutually
exclusive and jointly exhaustive equivalence classes. If Cu is the equivalence
class to which u belongs, then the truthvalue of a formula at u is independent
of the truth-values of sentence letters at worlds not in Cu, so only the worlds
in Cw* are relevant to the truth-values of sentences in an S5 interpretation.
But within Cw* R is universal: every world is possible relative to every other.
Consequently, in an S5 interpretation, we need not specify a relative
possibility relation, and the evaluation rules for B and A need not mention
relative possibility; e.g., we can say that B f is true at a world u if there
is at least one world v at which f is true. Note that by the characteristics of
R, whenever 9 X s in K, T, B, or S4, then 9 X s in S5: the other systems are
contained in S5. K is contained in all the systems we have mentioned, while T
is contained in B and S4, neither of which is contained in the other.
Sentential modal logics give rise to quantified modal logics, of which
quantified S5 is the bestknown. Just as, in the sentential case, each world in
an interpretation is associated with a valuation of sentence letters as in
non-modal sentential logic, so in quantified modal logic, each world is
associated with a valuation of the sort familiar in non-modal first-order
logic. More specifically, in quantified S5, each world w is assigned a domain
Dw – the things that exist at w – such that at least one Dw is non-empty, and
each atomic n-place predicate of the language is assigned an extension Extw of
n-tuples of objects that satisfy the predicate at w. So even restricting
ourselves to just the one first-order extension of a sentential system, S5,
various degrees of freedom are already evident. We discuss the following: (a) variability
of domains, (b) interpretation of quantifiers, and (c) predication. (a) Should
all worlds have the same domain or may the domains of different worlds be
different? The latter appears to be the more natural choice; e.g., if neither
of of Dw* and Du are subsets of the other, this represents the intuitive idea
that some things that exist might not have, and that there could have been
things that do not actually exist (though formulating this latter claim
requires adding an operator for ‘actually’ to the language). So we should
distinguish two versions of S5, one with constant domains, S5C, and the other
with variable domains, S5V. (b) Should the truth of (Dn)f at a world w require
that f is true at w of some object in Dw or merely of some object in D (D is
the domain of all possible objects, 4weWDw)? The former treatment is called the
actualist reading of the quantifiers, the latter, the possibilist reading. In
S5C there is no real choice, since for any w, D % Dw, but the issue is live in
S5V. (c) Should we require that for any n-place atomic predicate F, an n-tuple
of objects satisfies F at w only if every member of the n-tuple belongs to Dw,
i.e., should we require that atomic predicates be existence-entailing? If we
abbreviate (Dy) (y % x) by Ex (for ‘x exists’), then in S5C, A(Ex)AEx is
logically valid on the actualist reading of E (%-D-) and on the possibilist. On
the former, the formula says that at each world, anything that exists at that
world exists at every world, which is true; while on the latter, using the
definition of ‘Ex’, it says that at each world, anything that exists at some
world or other is such that at every world, it exists at some world or other,
which is also true; indeed, the formula stays valid in S5C with possibilist
quantifiers even if we make E a primitive logical constant, stipulated to be
true at every w of modal logic modal logic 576 576 exactly the things that exist at w. But
in S5V with actualist quantifiers, A(Ex)AEx is invalid, as is (Ex)AEx –
consider an interpretation where for some u, Du is a proper subset of Dw*.
However, in S5V with possibilist quantifiers, the status of the formula, if
‘Ex’ is defined, depends on whether identity is existence-entailing. If it is
existenceentailing, then A(Ex)AEx is invalid, since an object in D satisfies
(Dy)(y % x) at w only if that object exists at w, while if identity is not
existence-entailing, the formula is valid. The interaction of the various
options is also evident in the evaluation of two well-known schemata: the Barcan
formula, B (Dx)fx P (Dx) B fx; and its converse, (Dx) B fx P B (Dx)fx. In S5C
with ‘Ex’ either defined or primitive, both schemata are valid, but in S5V with
actualist quantifiers, they both fail. For the latter case, if we substitute -E
for f in the converse Barcan formula we get a conditional whose antecedent
holds at w* if there is u with Du a proper subset of Dw*, but whose consequent
is logically false. The Barcan formula fails when there is a world u with Du
not a subset of Dw*, and the condition f is true of some non-actual object at u
and not of any actual object there. For then B (Dx)f holds at w* while (Dx) B
fx fails there. However, if we require atomic predicates to be
existence-entailing, then instances of the converse Barcan formula with f atomic
are valid. In S5V with possibilist quantifiers, all instances of both schemata
are valid, since the prefixes (Dx) B and B (Dx) correspond to (Dx) (Dw) and
(Dw) (Dx), which are equivalent (with actualist quantifiers, the prefixes
correspond to (Dx 1 Dw*), and (Dw) (Dx 1 Dw) which are non-equivalent if Dw and
Dw* need not be the same set). Finally in S5V with actualist quantifiers, the
standard quantifier introduction and elimination rules must be adjusted.
Suppose c is a name for an object that does not actually exist; then - Ec is
true but (Dx) - Ex is false. The quantifier rules must be those of free logic:
we require Ec & fc before we infer (Dv)fv and Ec P fc, as well as the usual
EI restrictions, before we infer (Ev)fv.
mode (from Latin modus,
‘way’, ‘fashion’), a term used in many senses in philosophy. In Aristotelian
logic, it refers either to the arrangement of universal, particular,
affirmative, or negative propositions within a syllogism, only certain of which
are valid (this is often translated as ‘mood’ in English), or to the property a
proposition has by virtue of which it is necessary or contingent, possible or
impossible. In Scholastic metaphysics, it was often used in a not altogether
technical sense to mean that which characterizes a thing and distinguishes it
from others. Micraelius (Lexicon philosophicum, 1653) writes that “a mode does
not compose a thing, but distinguishes it and makes it determinate.” It was
also used in the context of the modal distinction in the theory of distinctions
to designate the distinction that holds between a substance and its modes or
between two modes of a single substance. The term ‘mode’ also appears in the
technical vocabulary of medieval speculative grammar in connection with the
notions of modes of signifying (modi significandi), modes of understanding
(modi intelligendi), and modes of being (modi essendi). The term ‘mode’ became
especially important in the seventeenth century, when Descartes, Spinoza, and
Locke each took it up, giving it three somewhat different special meanings
within their respective systems. Descartes makes ‘mode’ a central notion in his
metaphysics in his Principia philosophiae. For Descartes, each substance is
characterized by a principal attribute, thought for mind and extension for
body. Modes, then, are particular ways of being extended or thinking, i.e.,
particular sizes, shapes, etc., or particular thoughts, properties (in the
broad sense) that individual things (substances) have. In this way, ‘mode’
occupies the role in Descartes’s philosophy that ‘accident’ does in
Aristotelian philosophy. But for Descartes, each mode must be connected with
the principal attribute of a substance, a way of being extended or a way of
thinking, whereas for the Aristotelian, accidents may or may not be connected
with the essence of the substance in which they inhere. Like Descartes, Spinoza
recognizes three basic metaphysical terms, ‘substance,’ ‘attribute’, and
‘mode’. Recalling Descartes, he defines ‘mode’ as “the affections of a
substance, or that which is in another, and which is also conceived through
another” (Ethics I). But for Spinoza, there is only one substance, which has
all possible attributes. This makes it somewhat difficult to determine exactly
what Spinoza means by ‘modes’, whether they are to be construed as being in
some sense “properties” of God, the one infinite modal logic of programs mode
577 577 substance, or whether they are
to be construed more broadly as simply individual things that depend for their
existence on God, just as Cartesian modes depend on Cartesian substance.
Spinoza also introduces somewhat obscure distinctions between infinite and
finite modes, and between immediate and mediate infinite modes. Locke uses
‘mode’ in a way that evidently derives from Descartes’s usage, but that also
differs from it. For Locke, modes are “such complex Ideas, which however
compounded, contain not in them the supposition of subsisting by themselves,
but are considered as Dependences on, or Affections of Substances” (Essay II).
Modes are thus ideas that represent to us the complex properties of things,
ideas derived from what Locke calls the simple ideas that come to us from
experience. Locke distinguishes between simple modes like number, space, and
infinity, which are supposed to be constructed by compounding the same idea
many times, and mixed modes like obligation or theft, which are supposed to be
compounded of many simple ideas of different sorts. DESCARTES, LOCKE, METAPHYSICS, PROPERTY, SPINOZA.
D.Garb. model.COMPUTER THEORY, MODEL THEORY. modeling, computer.COMPUTER
THEORY. model set.HINTIKKA SET. model theory, a branch of mathematical logic
that deals with the connection between a language and its interpretations or
structures. Basic to it is the characterization of the conditions under which a
sentence is true in structure. It is confusing that the term ‘model’ itself is
used slightly differently: a model for a sentence is a structure for the
language of the sentence in which it is true. Model theory was originally
developed for explicitly constructed, formal languages, with the purpose of
studying foundational questions of mathematics, but was later applied to the
semantical analysis of empirical theories, a development initiated by the Dutch
philosopher Evert Beth, and of natural languages, as in Montague grammar. More
recently, in situation theory, we find a theory of semantics in which not the
concept of truth in a structure, but that of information carried by a statement
about a situation, is central. The term ‘model theory’ came into use in the
1930s, with the work on first-order model theory by Tarski, but some of the
most central results of the field date from before that time. The history of
the field is complicated by the fact that in the 1910s and 1920s, when the first
model-theoretic findings were obtained, the separation between first-order
logic and its extensions was not yet completed. Thus, in 1915, there appeared
an article by Leopold Löwenheim, containing the first version of what is now
called the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem. Löwenheim proved that every satisfiable
sentence has a countable model, but he did not yet work in firstorder logic as
we now understand it. One of the first who did so was the Norwegian logician
Thoralf Skolem, who showed in 1920 that a set of first-order sentences that has
a model, has a countable model, one form of the LöwenheimSkolem theorem. Skolem
argued that logic was first-order logic and that first-order logic was the
proper basis for metamathematical investigations, fully accepting the
relativity of set-theoretic notions in first-order logic. Within philosophy
this thesis is still dominant, but in the end it has not prevailed in
mathematical logic. In 1930 Kurt Gödel solved an open problem of
Hilbert-Ackermann and proved a completeness theorem for first-order logic. This
immediately led to another important model-theoretic result, the compactness
theorem: if every finite subset of a set of sentences has a model then the set
has a model. A good source for information about the model theory of
first-order logic, or classical model theory, is still Model Theory by C. C.
Chang and H. J. Keisler (1973). When the separation between first-order logic
and stronger logics had been completed and the model theory of first-order
logic had become a mature field, logicians undertook in the late 1950s the
study of extended model theory, the model theory of extensions of first-order
logic: first of cardinality quantifiers, later of infinitary languages and of
fragments of second-order logic. With so many examples of logics around – where
sometimes classical theorems did generalize, sometimes not – Per Lindström
showed in 1969 what sets first-order logic apart from its extensions: it is the
strongest logic that is both compact and satisfies the LöwenheimSkolem theorem.
This work has been the beginning of a study of the relations between various
properties logics may possess, the so-called abstract model. FORMAL SEMANTICS, LÖWENHEIMSKOLEM THEOREM,
SATISFACTION. Z.G.S. model model theory 578
578 modernism.POSTMODERN. modest foundationalism.FOUNDATIONALISM.
modularity, the commitment to functionally independent and specialized
cognitive systems in psychological organization, or, more generally, in the
organization of any complex system. Modularity entails that behavior is the
product of components with subordinate functions, that these functions are
realized in discrete physical systems, and that the subsystems are minimally
interactive. Modular organization varies from simple decomposability to what
Herbert Simon calls near decomposability. In the former, component systems are
independent, operating according to intrinsically determined principles; system
behavior is an additive or aggregative function of these independent
contributions. In the latter, the short-run behavior of components is
independent of the behavior of other components; the system behavior is a
relatively simple function of component contributions. In the early nineteenth
century, Franz Joseph Gall (1758–1828) defended a modular organization for the
mind/brain, holding that the cerebral hemispheres consist of a variety of
organs, or centers, each subserving specific intellectual and moral functions.
This picture of the brain as a collection of relatively independent organs
contrasts sharply with the traditional view that intellectual activity involves
the exercise of a general faculty in a variety of domains, a view that was
common to Descartes and Hume as well as Gall’s major opponents such as Pierre
Flourens (1794–1867). By the middle of the nineteenth century, the French
physicians Jean-Baptiste Bouillaud (1796–1881) and Pierre-Paul Broca (1824–80)
defended the view that language is controlled by localized structures in the
left hemisphere and is relatively independent of other cognitive activities. It
was later discovered by Karl Wernicke (1848–1905) that there are at least two
centers for the control of language, one more posterior and one more anterior.
On these views, there are discrete physical structures responsible for
language, which are largely independent of one another and of structures
responsible for other psychological functions. This is therefore a modular
organization. This view of the neurophysiological organization of language
continues to have advocates into the late twentieth century, though the precise
characterization of the functions these two centers serve is controversial.
Many more recent views have tended to limit modularity to more peripheral
functions such as vision, hearing, and motor control and speech, but have
excluded so-called higher cognitive processes.
modus ponens, in full,
modus ponendo ponens (Latin, ‘proposing method’), (1) the argument form ‘If A
then B; A; therefore, B’, and arguments of this form (compare fallacy of
affirming the consequent); (2) the rule of inference that permits one to infer
the consequent of a conditional from that conditional and its antecedent. This
is also known as the rule of /-elimination or rule of /- detachment. COUNTERFACTUALS, FORMAL FALLACY. G.F.S. modus
tollendo ponens.SYLLOGISM. modus tollens, in full, modus tollendo tollens
(Latin, ‘removing method’), (1) the argument form ‘If A then B; not-B;
therefore, not-A’, and arguments of this form (compare fallacy of denying the
antecedent); (2) the rule of inference that permits one to infer the negation
of the antecedent of a conditional from that conditional and the negation of
its consequent. COUNTERFACTUALS, FORMAL
FALLACY. G.F.S. Mohism, a school of classical Chinese thought founded by Mo Tzu
(fl. 479–438 B.C.). Mo Tzu was the first major philosopher to challenge Confucius.
Whereas Confucius believed a moral life was an end in itself, Mo Tzu advocated
a form of utilitarianism wherein the test of moral rightness (yi) was the
amount of benefit (li) to the gods, state, and people. Accordingly, Mo Tzu
condemned war as harmful, criticized Confucians for their elaborate funerals
and wasteful indulgence in music, and promoted a hierarchical meritocracy
dominated by a powerful ruler as the most efficient way to unify the
conflicting moral views and interests of the people, and thereby achieve social
order. Mo Tzu also attacked fatalism, and unlike the agnostic Confucius, firmly
believed in spirits and an anthropomorphic Heaven (t’ien) that rewarded those
who benefited others and punished those who did not. He is most famous for his
doctrine of chien ai or impartial concern (often translated as universal love).
Whereas Confucius espoused a relational morality in which one’s obligations
modernism Mohism 579 579 varied
depending on the status of the parties and the degree of closeness, Mo Tzu
insisted that each person be treated equally as an object of moral concern.
During the Warring States period (403–221 B.C.), the Mohists split into three
factions. The Later Mohist Canons, most of which were written as late as the
third century B.C., are characterized by analytical reasoning and logical
sophistication. Later Mohists sought to provide a rational rather than a
religious basis for Mo Tzu’s utilitarianism based upon logical (and causal)
necessity (pi). Treating a wide variety of subjects from politics to optics to
economics, the Canons are organized around four topics: discourse, or knowledge
of the relation between names and objects; ethics, or knowledge of how to act;
sciences, or knowledge of objects; and argumentation, or knowledge of names. As
Confucianism emerged to become the state ideology, the Mohists disappeared
sometime in the early Han dynasty (206 B.C.–A.D. 220), having been in important
measure co-opted by the leading interpreter of Confucianism of the period, Hsün
Tzu (c.298–238 B.C.).
CONFUCIANISM, LI3, MO
TZU, YI. R.P.P. & R.T.A. Mohist School.MOHISM, MO TZU. moksha.MAYA. Molina,
Luis de (1535–1600), Spanish Jesuit theologian and philosopher. He studied and
taught at Coimbra and Évora and also taught in Lisbon and Madrid. His most
important works are the Concordia liberi arbitrii cum gratiae donis(“Free Will
and Grace,” 1588), Commentaria in primam divi Thomae partem (“Commentary on the
First Part of Thomas’s Summa,” 1592), and De justitia et jure (“On Justice and Law,”
1592–1613). Molina is best known for his doctrine of middle knowledge (scientia
media). Its aim was to preserve free will while maintaining the Christian
doctrine of the efficacy of divine grace. It was opposed by Thomists such as
Bañez, who maintained that God exercises physical predetermination over
secondary causes of human action and, thus, that grace is intrinsically
efficacious and independent of human will and merits. For Molina, although God
has foreknowledge of what human beings will choose to do, neither that
knowledge nor God’s grace determine human will; the cooperation (concursus) of
divine grace with human will does not determine the will to a particular
action. This is made possible by God’s middle knowledge, which is a knowledge
in between the knowledge God has of what existed, exists, and will exist, and
the knowledge God has of what has not existed, does not exist, and will not
exist. Middle knowledge is God’s knowledge of conditional future contingent
events, namely, of what persons would do under any possible set of
circumstances. Thanks to this knowledge, God can arrange for certain human acts
to occur by prearranging the circumstances surrounding the choice without
determining the human will. Thus, God’s grace is concurrent with the act of the
will and does not predetermine it, rendering the Thomistic distinction between
sufficient and efficacious grace superfluous.
AQUINAS, FREE WILL PROBLEM, FUTURE CONTINGENTS, MIDDLE KNOWLEDGE.
J.J.E.G. Molyneux question, also called Molyneux’s problem, the question that,
in correspondence with Locke, William Molyneux (or Molineux, 1656– 98), a
Dublin lawyer and member of the Irish Parliament, posed and Locke inserted in
the second edition of his Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1694; book 2, chap.
9, section 8): Suppose a Man born blind, and now adult, and taught by his touch
to distinguish a Cube, and a Sphere of the same metal, and nighly of the same
bigness, so as to tell, when he felt one and t’other, which is the Cube, which
the Sphere. Suppose then the Cube and Sphere placed on a Table, and the Blind
Man to be made to see. Quære, Whether by his sight, before he touch’d them, he
could now distinguish, and tell, which is the Globe, which the Cube. Although
it is tempting to regard Molyneux’s question as straightforwardly empirical,
attempts to gauge the abilities of newly sighted adults have yielded
disappointing and ambiguous results. More interesting, perhaps, is the way in
which different theories of perception answer the question. Thus, according to
Locke, sensory modalities constitute discrete perceptual channels, the contents
of which perceivers must learn to correlate. Such a theory answers the question
in the negative (as did Molyneux himself). Other theories encourage different
responses.
Montaigne, Michel de
(1533–92), French essayist and philosopher who set forth the Renaissance
version of Greek skepticism. Born and raised in Bordeaux, he became its mayor,
and was an adviser to leaders of the Reformation and Counter-Reformation. In
1568 he translated the work of the Spanish rationalist theologian Raimund
Sebond on natural theology. Shortly thereafter he began writing essais,
attempts, as the author said, to paint himself. These, the first in this genre,
are rambling, curious discussions of various topics, suggesting tolerance and
an undogmatic Stoic morality. The longest essai, the “Apology for Raimund
Sebond,” “defends” Sebond’s rationalism by arguing that since no adequate
reasons or evidence could be given to support any point of view in theology,
philosophy, or science, one should not blame Sebond for his views. Montaigne
then presents and develops the skeptical arguments found in Sextus Empiricus
and Cicero. Montaigne related skeptical points to thencurrent findings and
problems. Data of explorers, he argues, reinforce the cultural and ethical
relativism of the ancient Skeptics. Disagreements between Scholastics,
Platonists, and Renaissance naturalists on almost everything cast doubt on
whether any theory is correct. Scientists like Copernicus and Paracelsus
contradict previous scientists, and will probably be contradicted by future
ones. Montaigne then offers the more theoretical objections of the Skeptics,
about the unreliability of sense experience and reasoning and our inability to
find an unquestionable criterion of true knowledge. Trying to know reality is
like trying to clutch water. What should we then do? Montaigne advocates
suspending judgment on all theories that go beyond experience, accepting
experience undogmatically, living according to the dictates of nature, and
following the rules and customs of one’s society. Therefore one should remain
in the religion in which one was born, and accept only those principles that
God chooses to reveal to us. Montaigne’s skepticism greatly influenced European
thinkers in undermining confidence in previous theories and forcing them to
seek new ways of grounding knowledge. His acceptance of religion on custom and
faith provided a way of living with total skepticism. His presentation of skepticism
in a modern language shaped the vocabulary and the problems of philosophy in
modern times.
SKEPTICISM, SKEPTICS.
R.H.P. Montanism, a charismatic, schismatic movement in early Christianity,
originating in Phrygia in the late second century. It rebuked the mainstream
church for laxity and apathy, and taught moral purity, new, i.e. postbiblical,
revelation, and the imminent end of the world. Traditional accounts, deriving
from critics of the movement, contain exaggerations and probably some fabrications.
Montanus himself, abetted by the prophetesses Maximilla and Prisca, announced
in ecstatic speech a new, final age of prophecy. This fulfilled the biblical
promises that in the last days the Holy Spirit would be poured out universally
(Joel 2: 28ff.; Acts 2: 16ff.) and would teach “the whole truth” (Jon. 14:26;
16:13). It also empowered the Montanists to enjoin more rigorous discipline
than that required by Jesus. The sect denied that forgiveness through baptism
covered serious subsequent sin; forbade remarriage for widows and widowers;
practiced fasting; and condemned believers who evaded persecution. Some later
followers may have identified Montanus with the Holy Spirit itself, though he
claimed only to be the Spirit’s mouthpiece. The “new prophecy” flourished for a
generation, especially in North Africa, gaining a famous convert in Tertullian.
But the church’s bishops repudiated the movement’s criticisms and innovations,
and turned more resolutely against postapostolic revelation, apocalyptic expectation,
and ascetic extremes.
Montesquieu, Baron de La
Brède et de, title of Charles-Louis de Secondat (1689–1755), French political
philosopher, the political philosophe of the Enlightenment. He was born at La
Brède, educated at the Oratorian Collège de Juilly (1700–05), and received law
degrees from the University of Bordeaux (1708). From his uncle he inherited the
barony of Montesquieu (1716) and the office of Président à Mortier at the
Parliament of Guyenne at Bordeaux. Fame, national monism Montesquieu 581 581 and international, came suddenly (1721)
with the Lettres persanes (“The Persian Letters”), published in Holland and
France, a landmark of the Enlightenment. His Réflexions sur la monarchie
universelle en Europe, written and printed (1734) to remind the authorities of
his qualifications and availability, delivered the wrong message at the wrong
time (anti-militarism, pacifism, free trade, while France supported Poland’s
King Stanislas, dethroned by Russia and Austria). Montesquieu withdrew the Réflexions
before publication and substituted the Considerations on the Romans: the same
thesis is expounded here, but in the exclusively classical context of ancient
history. The stratagem succeeded: the Amsterdam edition was freely imported;
the Paris edition appeared with a royal privilège (1734). A few months after
the appearance of the Considerations, he undertook L’Esprit des lois, the
outline of a modern political science, conceived as the foundation of an
effective governmental policy. His optimism was shaken by the disasters of the
War of Austrian Succession (1740–48); the Esprit des lois underwent hurried
changes that upset its original plan. During the very printing process, the
author was discovering the true essence of his philosophie pratique: it would
never culminate in a final, invariable program, but in an orientation,
continuously, intelligently adapting to the unpredictable circumstances of
historical time in the light of permanent values. According to L’Esprit des
lois, governments are either republics, monarchies, or despotisms. The
principles, or motivational forces, of these types of government are,
respectively, political virtue, honor, and fear. The type of government a
people has depends on its character, history, and geographical situation. Only
a constitutional government that separates its executive, legislative, and
judicial powers preserves political liberty, taken as the power to do what one
ought to will. A constitutional monarchy with separation of powers is the best
form of government. Montesquieu influenced the authors of the U.S. Constitution
and the political philosophers Burke and Rousseau.
BURKE, ENCYCLOPEDIA,
POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY, ROUSSEAU. C.J.B. mood.
SYLLOGISM. Moore,
G(eorge) E(dward) (1873–1958), English philosopher who spearheaded the attack
on idealism and was a major supporter of realism in all its forms:
metaphysical, epistemological, and axiological. He was born in Upper Norwood, a
suburb of London; did his undergraduate work at Cambridge University; spent
1898–1904 as a fellow of Trinity College; returned to Cambridge in 1911 as a
lecturer; and was granted a professorship there in 1925. He also served as
editor of Mind. The bulk of his work falls into four categories: metaphysics,
epistemology, ethics, and philosophical methodology. Metaphysics. In this area,
Moore is mainly known for his attempted refutation of idealism and his defense
thereby of realism. In his “The Refutation of Idealism” (1903), he argued that
there is a crucial premise that is essential to all possible arguments for the
idealistic conclusion that “All reality is mental (spiritual).” This premise
is: “To be is to be perceived” (in the broad sense of ‘perceive’). Moore argued
that, under every possible interpretation of it, that premise is either a
tautology or false; hence no significant conclusion can ever be inferred from
it. His positive defense of realism had several prongs. One was to show that
there are certain claims held by non-realist philosophers, both idealist ones
and skeptical ones. Moore argued, in “A Defense of Common Sense” (1925), that
these claims are either factually false or self-contradictory, or that in some
cases there is no good reason to believe them. Among the claims that Moore
attacked are these: “Propositions about (purported) material facts are false”;
“No one has ever known any such propositions to be true”; “Every (purported)
physical fact is logically dependent on some mental fact”; and “Every physical
fact is causally dependent on some mental fact.” Another major prong of Moore’s
defense of realism was to argue for the existence of an external world and
later to give a “Proof of an External World” (1933). Epistemology. Most of
Moore’s work in this area dealt with the various kinds of knowledge we have,
why they must be distinguished, and the problem of perception and our knowledge
of an external world. Because he had already argued for the existence of an
external world in his metaphysics, he here focused on how we know it. In many
papers and chapters (e.g., “The Nature and Reality of Objects of Perception,”
1906) he examined and at times supported three main positions: naive or direct
realism, representative or indirect realism, and phenomenalism. Although he
seemed to favor direct realism at first, in the majority of his papers he found
representative realism to be the most supportable position despite its
problems. It should also be noted that, in connection with his leanings mood toward
representative realism, Moore maintained the existence of sense-data and argued
at length for an account of just how they are related to physical objects. That
there are sense-data Moore never doubted. The question was, What is their
(ontological) status? With regard to the various kinds of knowledge (or ways of
knowing), Moore made a distinction between dispositional (or non-actualized)
and actualized knowledge. Within the latter Moore made distinctions between
direct apprehension (often known as knowledge by acquaintance), indirect
apprehension, and knowledge proper (or propositional knowledge). He devoted
much of his work to finding the conditions for knowledge proper. Ethics. In his
major work in ethics, Principia Ethica (1903), Moore maintained that the
central problem of ethics is, What is good? – meaning by this, not what things
are good, but how ‘good’ is to be defined. He argued that there can be only one
answer, one that may seem disappointing, namely: good is good, or,
alternatively, ‘good’ is indefinable. Thus ‘good’ denotes a “unique, simple
object of thought” that is indefinable and unanalyzable. His first argument on
behalf of that claim consisted in showing that to identify good with some other
object (i.e., to define ‘good’) is to commit the naturalistic fallacy. To
commit this fallacy is to reduce ethical propositions to either psychological
propositions or reportive definitions as to how people use words. In other
words, what was meant to be an ethical proposition, that X is good, becomes a
factual proposition about people’s desires or their usage of words. Moore’s second
argument ran like this: Suppose ‘good’ were definable. Then the result would be
even worse than that of reducing ethical propositions to non-ethical
propositions – ethical propositions would be tautologies! For example, suppose
you defined ‘good’ as ‘pleasure’. Then suppose you maintained that pleasure is
good. All you would be asserting is that pleasure is pleasure, a tautology. To
avoid this conclusion ‘good’ must mean something other than ‘pleasure’. Why is
this the naturalistic fallacy? Because good is a non-natural property. But even
if it were a natural one, there would still be a fallacy. Hence some have
proposed calling it the definist fallacy – the fallacy of attempting to define
‘good’ by any means. This argument is often known as the open question argument
because whatever purported definition of ‘good’ anyone offers, it would always
be an open question whether whatever satisfies the definition really is good.
In the last part of Principia Ethica Moore turned to a discussion of what sorts
of things are the greatest goods with which we are acquainted. He argued for
the view that they are personal affection and aesthetic enjoyments.
Philosophical methodology. Moore’s methodology in philosophy had many
components, but two stand out: his appeal to and defense of common sense and
his utilization of various methods of (philosophical/conceptual) analysis. “A
Defense of Common Sense” argued for his claim that the commonsense view of the
world is wholly true, and for the claim that any view which opposed that view
is either factually false or self-contradictory. Throughout his writings Moore
distinguished several kinds of analysis and made use of them extensively in
dealing with philosophical problems. All of these may be found in the works
cited above and other essays gathered into Moore’s Philosophical Studies(1922)
and Philosophical Papers (1959). These have been referred to as refutational
analysis, with two subforms, showing contradictions and “translation into the
concrete”; distinctional analysis; decompositional analysis (either
definitional or divisional); and reductional analysis. Moore was greatly
revered as a teacher. Many of his students and colleagues have paid high
tribute to him in very warm and grateful terms.
.
Moore’s paradox, as first
discussed by G. E. Moore, the perplexity involving assertion of what is
expressed by conjunctions such as ‘It’s raining, but I believe it isn’t’ and
‘It’s raining, but I don’t believe it is’. The oddity of such presenttense
first-person uses of ‘to believe’ seems peculiar to those conjunctions just
because it is assumed both that, when asserting – roughly, representing as true
– a conjunction, one also asserts its conjuncts, and that, as a rule, the
assertor believes the asserted proposition. Thus, no perplexity arises from
assertions of, for instance, ‘It’s raining today, but I (falsely) believed it
wasn’t until I came out to the porch’ and ‘If it’s raining but I believe it
isn’t, I have been misled by the weather report’. However, there are reasons to
think that, if we rely only on these assumptions and examples, our
characterization of the problem is unduly narrow. First, assertion seems
relevant only because we are interested in what the assertor believes.
Secondly, those conjunctions are disturbing only insofar as they show that
Moore’s paradox Moore’s paradox 583
583 some of the assertor’s beliefs, though contingent, can only be
irrationally held. Thirdly, autobiographical reports that may justifiably be
used to charge the reporter with irrationality need be neither about his belief
system, nor conjunctive, nor true (e.g., ‘I don’t exist’, ‘I have no beliefs’),
nor false (e.g., ‘It’s raining, but I have no evidence that it is’). So,
Moore’s paradox is best seen as the problem posed by contingent propositions
that cannot be justifiably believed. Arguably, in forming a belief of those
propositions, the believer acquires non-overridable evidence against believing
them. A successful analysis of the problem along these lines may have important
epistemological consequences.
moral dilemma. (1) Any
problem where morality is relevant. This broad use includes not only conflicts
among moral reasons but also conflicts between moral reasons and reasons of
law, religion, or self-interest. In this sense, Abraham is in a moral dilemma
when God commands him to sacrifice his son, even if he has no moral reason to
obey. Similarly, I am in a moral dilemma if I cannot help a friend in trouble
without forgoing a lucrative but morally neutral business opportunity. ’Moral
dilemma’ also often refers to (2) any topic area where it is not known what, if
anything, is morally good or right. For example, when one asks whether abortion
is immoral in any way, one could call the topic “the moral dilemma of
abortion.” This epistemic use does not imply that anything really is immoral at
all. Recently, moral philosophers have discussed a much narrower set of
situations as “moral dilemmas.” They usually define ‘moral dilemma’ as (3) a
situation where an agent morally ought to do each of two acts but cannot do
both. The bestknown example is Sartre’s student who morally ought to care for
his mother in Paris but at the same time morally ought to go to England to join
the Free French and fight the Nazis. However, ‘ought’ covers ideal actions that
are not morally required, such as when someone ought to give to a certain
charity but is not required to do so. Since most common examples of moral
dilemmas include moral obligations or duties, or other requirements, it is more
accurate to define ‘moral dilemma’ more narrowly as (4) a situation where an
agent has a moral requirement to do each of two acts but cannot do both. Some
philosophers also refuse to call a situation a moral dilemma when one of the
conflicting requirements is clearly overridden, such as when I must break a
trivial promise in order to save a life. To exclude such resolvable conflicts,
‘moral dilemma’ can be defined as (5) a situation where an agent has a moral
requirement to adopt each of two alternatives, and neither requirement is overridden,
but the agent cannot fulfill both. Another common move is to define ‘moral
dilemma’ as (6) a situation where every alternative is morally wrong. This is
equivalent to (4) or (5), respectively, if an act is morally wrong whenever it
violates any moral requirement or any non-overridden moral requirement.
However, we usually do not call an act wrong unless it violates an overriding
moral requirement, and then (6) rules out moral dilemmas by definition, since
overriding moral requirements clearly cannot conflict. Although (5) thus seems
preferable, some would object that (5) includes trivial requirements and
conflicts, such as conflicts between trivial promises. To include only tragic
situations, we could define ‘moral dilemma’ as (7) a situation where an agent
has a strong moral obligation or requirement to adopt each of two alternatives,
and neither is overridden, but the agent cannot adopt both alternatives. This
definition is strong enough to raise the important controversies about moral
dilemmas without being so strong as to rule out their possibility by
definition.
moral epistemology, the
discipline, at the intersection of ethics and epistemology, that studies the
epistemic status and relations of moral judgments and principles. It has
developed out of an interest, common to both ethics and epistemology, in
questions of justification and justifiability – in epistemology, of statements
or beliefs, and in ethics, of actions as well as judgments of actions and also
general principles of judgment. Its most prominent questions include the
following. Can normative claims be true or false? If so, how can they be known
to be true or false? If not, what status do they have, and are they capable of
justification? If they are capable of moral argument for God’s existence moral
epistemology 584 584 justification,
how can they be justified? Does the justification of normative claims differ
with respect to particular claims and with respect to general principles? In
epistemology recent years have seen a tendency to accept as valid an account of
knowledge as entailing justified true belief, a conception that requires an
account not just of truth but also of justification and of justified belief.
Thus, under what conditions is someone justified, epistemically, in believing
something? Justification, of actions, of judgments, and of principles, has long
been a central element in ethics. It is only recently that justification in
ethics came to be thought of as an epistemological problem, hence ‘moral
epistemology’, as an expression, is a fairly recent coinage, although its
problems have a long lineage. One long-standing linkage is provided by the
challenge of skepticism. Skepticism in ethics can be about the existence of any
genuine distinction between right and wrong, or it can focus on the possibility
of attaining any knowledge of right and wrong, good or bad. Is there a right
answer? is a question in the metaphysics of ethics. Can we know what the right
answer is, and if so how? is one of moral epistemology. Problems of perception
and observation and ones about observation statements or sense-data play an
important role in epistemology. There is not any obvious parallel in moral
epistemology, unless it is the role of prereflective moral judgments, or
commonsense moral judgments – moral judgments unguided by any overt moral
theory – which can be taken to provide the data of moral theory, and which need
to be explained, systematized, coordinated, or revised to attain an appropriate
relation between theory and data. This would be analogous to taking the data of
epistemology to be provided, not by sense-data or observations but by judgments
of perception or observation statements. Once this step is taken the parallel
is very close. One source of moral skepticism is the apparent lack of any
observational counterpart for moral predicates, which generates the question
how moral judgments can be true if there is nothing for them to correspond to.
Another source of moral skepticism is apparently constant disagreement and
uncertainty, which would appear to be explained by the skeptical hypothesis
denying the reality of moral distinctions. Noncognitivism in ethics maintains
that moral judgments are not objects of knowledge, that they make no statements
capable of truth or falsity, but are or are akin to expressions of attitudes.
Some other major differences among ethical theories are largely epistemological
in character. Intuitionism maintains that basic moral propositions are knowable
by intuition. Empiricism in ethics maintains that moral propositions can be
established by empirical means or are complex forms of empirical statements.
Ethical rationalism maintains that the fundamental principle(s) of morality can
be established a priori as holding of necessity. This is exemplified by Kant’s
moral philosophy, in which the categorical imperative is regarded as synthetic
a priori; more recently by what Alan Gewirth (b.1912) calls the “principle of
generic consistency,” which he claims it is selfcontradictory to deny. Ethical
empiricism is exemplified by classical utilitarianism, such as that of Bentham,
which aspires to develop ethics as an empirical science. If the consequences of
actions can be scientifically predicted and their utilities calculated, then
ethics can be a science. Situationism is equivalent to concrete case
intuitionism in maintaining that we can know immediately what ought to be done
in specific cases, but most ethical theories maintain that what ought to be
done is, in J. S. Mill’s words, determined by “the application of a law to an
individual case.” Different theories differ on the epistemic status of these
laws and on the process of application. Deductivists, either empiricistic or
rationalistic, hold that the law is essentially unchanged in the application;
non-deductivists hold that the law is modified in the process of application.
(This distinction is explained in F. L. Will [1909–98], Beyond Deduction,
1988.) There is similar variation about what if anything is selfevident,
Sidgwick maintaining that only certain highly abstract principles are
self-evident, Ross that only general rules are, and Prichard that only concrete
judgments are, “by an act of moral thinking.” Other problems in moral
epistemology are provided by the fact–value distinction – and controversies about
whether there is any such distinction – and the is–ought question, the question
how a moral judgment can be derived from statements of fact alone. Naturalists
affirm the possibility, non-naturalists deny it. Prescriptivists claim that
moral judgments are prescriptions and cannot be deduced from descriptive
statements alone. This question ultimately leads to the question how an
ultimate principle can be justified. If it cannot be deduced from statements of
fact, that route is out; if it must be deduced from some other moral principle,
then the principle deduced cannot be ultimate and in any case this process is
either circular or leads to an infimoral epistemology moral epistemology
585 585 nite regress. If the ultimate
principle is self-evident, then the problem may have an answer. But if it is
not it would appear to be arbitrary. The problem of the justification of an
ultimate principle continues to be a leading one in moral epistemology.
Recently there has been much interest in the status and existence of “moral
facts.” Are there any, what are they, and how are they established as “facts”?
This relates to questions about moral realism. Moral realism maintains that
moral predicates are real and can be known to be so; anti-realists deny this.
This denial links with the view that moral properties supervene on natural
ones, and the problem of supervenience is another recent link between ethics
and epistemology. Pragmatism in ethics maintains that a moral problem is like
any problem in that it is the occasion for inquiry and moral judgments are to
be regarded as hypotheses to be tested by how well they resolve the problem.
This amounts to an attempt to bypass the is–ought problem and all such
“dualisms.” So is constructivism, a development owing much to the work of
Rawls, which contrasts with moral realism. Constructivism maintains that moral
ideas are human constructs and the task is not epistemological or metaphysical
but practical and theoretical – that of attaining reflective equilibrium
between considered moral judgments and the principles that coordinate and
explain them. On this view there are no moral facts. Opponents maintain that
this only replaces a foundationalist view of ethics with a coherence
conception. The question whether questions of moral epistemology can in this
way be bypassed can be regarded as itself a question of moral epistemology. And
the question of the foundations of morality, and whether there are foundations,
can still be regarded as a question of moral epistemology, as distinct from a
question of the most convenient and efficient arrangement of our moral
ideas.
morality, an informal
public system applying to all rational persons, governing behavior that affects
others, having the lessening of evil or harm as its goal, and including what
are commonly known as the moral rules, moral ideals, and moral virtues. To say
that it is a public system means that all those to whom it applies must
understand it and that it must not be irrational for them to use it in deciding
what to do and in judging others to whom the system applies. Games are the
paradigm cases of public systems; all games have a point and the rules of a
game apply to all who play it. All players know the point of the game and its
rules, and it is not irrational for them to be guided by the point and rules
and to judge the behavior of other players by them. To say that morality is
informal means that there is no decision procedure or authority that can settle
all its controversial questions. Morality thus resembles a backyard game of
basketball more than a professional game. Although there is overwhelming
agreement on most moral matters, certain controversial questions must be
settled in an ad hoc fashion or not settled at all. For example, when, if ever,
abortion is acceptable is an unresolvable moral matter, but each society and
religion can adopt its own position. That morality has no one in a position of
authority is one of the most important respects in which it differs from law
and religion. Although morality must include the commonly accepted moral rules
such as those prohibiting killing and deceiving, different societies can
interpret these rules somewhat differently. They can also differ in their views
about the scope of morality, i.e., about whether morality protects newborns,
fetuses, or non-human animals. Thus different societies can have somewhat
different moralities, although this difference has limits. Also within each
society, a person may have his own view about when it is justified to break one
of the rules, e.g., about how much harm would have to be prevented in order to
justify deceiving someone. Thus one person’s morality may differ somewhat from
another’s, but both will agree on the overwhelming number of non-controversial
cases. A moral theory is an attempt to describe, explain, and if possible
justify, morality. Unfortunately, most moral theories attempt to generate some
simplified moral code, rather than to describe the complex moral system that is
already in use. Morality does not resolve all disputes. Morality does not
require one always to act so as to produce the best consequences or to act only
in those ways that one would will everyone to act. Rather morality includes
both moral rules that no one should transgress and moral ideals that all are
encouraged to follow, but much of what one does will not be governed by
morality.
moral psychology, (1) the
subfield of psychology that traces the development over time of moral reasoning
and opinions in the lives of individuals (this subdiscipline includes work of
Jean Piaget, Lawrence Kohlberg, and Carol Gilligan); (2) the part of philosophy
where philosophy of mind and ethics overlap, which concerns all the
psychological issues relevant to morality. There are many different
psychological matters relevant to ethics, and each may be relevant in more than
one way. Different ethical theories imply different sorts of connections. So
moral psychology includes work of many and diverse kinds. But several
traditional clusters of concern are evident. Some elements of moral psychology
consider the psychological matters relevant to metaethical issues, i.e., to
issues about the general nature of moral truth, judgment, and knowledge.
Different metaethical theories invoke mental phenomena in different ways:
noncognitivism maintains that sentences expressing moral judgments do not
function to report truths or falsehoods, but rather, e.g., to express certain
emotions or to prescribe certain actions. So some forms of noncognitivism imply
that an understanding of certain sorts of emotions, or of special activities
like prescribing that may involve particular psychological elements, is crucial
to a full understanding of how ethical sentences are meaningful. Certain forms
of cognitivism, the view that moral (declarative) sentences do express truths
or falsehoods, imply that moral facts consist of psychological facts, that for
instance moral judgments consist of expressions of positive psychological
attitudes of some particular kind toward the objects of those judgments. And an
understanding of psychological phenomena like sentiment is crucial according to
certain sorts of projectivism, which hold that the supposed moral properties of
things are mere misleading projections of our sentiments onto the objects of
those sentiments. Certain traditional moral sense theories and certain
traditional forms of intuitionism have held that special psychological
faculties are crucial for our epistemic access to moral truth. Particular views
in normative ethics, particular views about the moral status of acts, persons,
and other targets of normative evaluation, also often suggest that an
understanding of certain psychological matters is crucial to ethics. Actions,
intentions, and character are some of the targets of evaluation of normative
ethics, and their proper understanding involves many issues in philosophy of
mind. Also, many normative theorists have maintained that there is a close
connection between pleasure, happiness, or desiresatisfaction and a person’s
good, and these things are also a concern of philosophy of mind. In addition,
the rightness of actions is often held to be closely connected to the motives,
beliefs, and other psychological phenomena that lie behind those actions.
Various other traditional philosophical concerns link ethical and psychological
issues: the nature of the patterns in the long-term development in individuals
of moral opinions and reasoning, the appropriate form for moral education and
punishment, the connections between obligation and motivation, i.e., between
moral reasons and psychological causes, and the notion of free will and its
relation to moral responsibility and autonomy. Some work in philosophy of mind
also suggests that moral phenomena, or at least normative phenomena of some
kind, play a crucial role in illuminating or constituting psychological
phenomena of various kinds, but the traditional concern of moral psychology has
been with the articulation of the sort of philosophy of mind that can be useful
to ethics. AKRASIA, ETHICS, PRACTICAL
REASONING, SELF-DECEPTION. J.R.M. moral rationalism, the view that the
substance of morality, usually in the form of general moral principles, can be
known a priori. The view is defended by Kant in Groundwork of the Metaphysic of
Morals, but it goes back at least to Plato. Both Plato and Kant thought that a
priori moral knowledge could have an impact on what we do quite independently
of any desire that we happen to have. This motivational view is also ordinarily
associated with moral rationalism. It comes in two quite different forms. The
first is that a priori moral knowledge consists in a sui generis mental state
that is both belief-like and desire-like. This seems to have been Plato’s view,
for he held that the belief that something is good is itself a disposition to promote
that thing. The second is that a priori moral knowledge consists in a belief
that is capable of rationally producing a distinct desire. morality, slave
moral rationalism 587 587 Rationalists
who make the first claim have had trouble accommodating the possibility of
someone’s believing that something is good but, through weakness of will, not
mustering the desire to do it. Accordingly, they have been forced to assimilate
weakness of will to ignorance of the good. Rationalists who make the second claim
about reason’s action-producing capacity face no such problem. For this reason,
their view is often preferred. The best-known anti-rationalist about morality
is Hume. His Treatise of Human Nature denies both that morality’s substance can
be known by reason alone and that reason alone is capable of producing
action.
moral realism, a
metaethical view committed to the objectivity of ethics. It has (1)
metaphysical, (2) semantic, and (3) epistemological components. (1) Its
metaphysical component is the claim that there are moral facts and moral
properties whose existence and nature are independent of people’s beliefs and
attitudes about what is right or wrong. In this claim, moral realism contrasts
with an error theory and with other forms of nihilism that deny the existence
of moral facts and properties. It contrasts as well with various versions of
moral relativism and other forms of ethical constructivism that make moral
facts consist in facts about people’s moral beliefs and attitudes. (2) Its
semantic component is primarily cognitivist. Cognitivism holds that moral
judgments should be construed as assertions about the moral properties of
actions, persons, policies, and other objects of moral assessment, that moral
predicates purport to refer to properties of such objects, that moral judgments
(or the propositions that they express) can be true or false, and that
cognizers can have the cognitive attitude of belief toward the propositions
that moral judgments express. These cognitivist claims contrast with the
noncognitive claims of emotivism and prescriptivism, according to which the
primary purpose of moral judgments is to express the appraiser’s attitudes or
commitments, rather than to state facts or ascribe properties. Moral realism
also holds that truth for moral judgments is non-epistemic; in this way it
contrasts with moral relativism and other forms of ethical constructivism that
make the truth of a moral judgment epistemic. The metaphysical and semantic
theses imply that there are some true moral propositions. An error theory
accepts the cognitivist semantic claims but denies the realist metaphysical
thesis. It holds that moral judgments should be construed as containing
referring expressions and having truth-values, but insists that these referring
expressions are empty, because there are no moral facts, and that no moral
claims are true. Also on this theory, commonsense moral thought presupposes the
existence of moral facts and properties, but is systematically in error. In
this way, the error theory stands to moral realism much as atheism stands to
theism in a world of theists. (J. L. Mackie introduced and defended the error
theory in his Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, 1977.) (3) Finally, if moral
realism is to avoid skepticism it must claim that some moral beliefs are true,
that there are methods for justifying moral beliefs, and that moral knowledge
is possible. While making these metaphysical, semantic, and epistemological
claims, moral realism is compatible with a wide variety of other metaphysical,
semantic, and epistemological principles and so can take many different forms.
The moral realists in the early part of the twentieth century were generally
intuitionists. Intuitionism combined a commitment to moral realism with a
foundationalist moral epistemology according to which moral knowledge must rest
on self-evident moral truths and with the nonnaturalist claim that moral facts
and properties are sui generis and not reducible to any natural facts or
properties. Friends of noncognitivism found the metaphysical and
epistemological commitments of intuitionism extravagant and so rejected moral
realism. Later moral realists have generally sought to defend moral realism
without the metaphysical and epistemological trappings of intuitionism. One such
version of moral realism takes a naturalistic form. This form of ethical
naturalism claims that our moral beliefs are justified when they form part of
an explanatorily coherent system of beliefs with one another and with various
non-moral beliefs, and insists that moral properties are just natural
properties of the people, actions, and policies that instantiate them. Debate
between realists and anti-realists and within the realist camp centers on such
issues as the relation between moral judgment and action, the rational
authority of morality, moral epistemology and methodology, the relation between
moral and non-moral natural properties, the place of ethics in a naturalismoral
realism moral realism 588 588 tic worldview,
and the parity of ethics and the sciences.
EMOTIVISM, ETHICAL
CONSTRUCTIVISM, ETHICAL OBJECTIVISM, ETHICS, NATURALISM. D.O.B. Moral
Rearmament Movement.BUCHMANISM. moral sense theory, an ethical theory,
developed by eighteenth-century British philosophers – notably Shaftesbury,
Hutcheson, and Hume – according to which the pleasure or pain a person feels
upon thinking about (or “observing”) certain character traits is indicative of
the virtue or vice, respectively, of those features. It is a theory of “moral
perception,” offered in response to moral rationalism, the view that moral
distinctions are derived by reason alone, and combines Locke’s empiricist
doctrine that all ideas begin in experience with the belief, widely shared at
the time, that feelings play a central role in moral evaluation and motivation.
On this theory, our emotional responses to persons’ characters are often
“perceptions” of their morality, just as our experiences of an apple’s redness
and sweetness are perceptions of its color and taste. These ideas of morality
are seen as products of an “internal” sense, because they are produced in the
“observer” only after she forms a concept of the conduct or trait being
observed (or contemplated) – as when a person realizes that she is seeing
someone intentionally harm another and reacts with displeasure at what she
sees. The moral sense is conceived as being analogous to, or possibly an aspect
of, our capacity to recognize varying degrees of beauty in things, which modern
writers call “the sense of beauty.” Rejecting the popular view that morality is
based on the will of God, Shaftesbury maintains rather that morality depends on
human nature, and he introduces the notion of a sense of right and wrong,
possessed uniquely by human beings, who alone are capable of reflection.
Hutcheson argues that to approve of a character is to regard it as virtuous.
For him, reason, which discovers relations of inanimate objects to rational
agents, is unable to arouse our approval in the absence of a moral sense.
Ultimately, we can explain why, for example, we approve of someone’s temperate
character only by appealing to our natural tendency to feel pleasure (sometimes
identified with approval) at the thought of characters that exhibit
benevolence, the trait to which all other virtues can be traced. This disposition
to feel approval (and disapproval) is what Hutcheson identifies as the moral
sense. Hume emphasizes that typical human beings make moral distinctions on the
basis of their feelings only when those sentiments are experienced from a
disinterested or “general” point of view. In other words, we turn our initial
sentiments into moral judgments by compensating for the fact that we feel more
strongly about those to whom we are emotionally close than those from whom we
are more distant. On a widely held interpretation of Hume, the moral sense
provides not only judgments, but also motives to act according to those
judgments, since its feelings may be motivating passions or arouse such
passions. Roderick Firth’s (1917–87) twentieth-century ideal observer theory, according
to which moral good is designated by the projected reactions of a
hypothetically omniscient, disinterested observer possessing other ideal
traits, as well as Brandt’s contemporary moral spectator theory, are direct
descendants of the moral sense theory.
BUTLER, HUME, HUTCHESON, SHAFTESBURY. E.S.R. moral skepticism, any
metaethical view that raises fundamental doubts about morality as a whole.
Different kinds of doubts lead to different kinds of moral skepticism. The
primary kinds of moral skepticism are epistemological. Moral justification
skepticism is the claim that nobody ever has (any or adequate) justification
for believing any substantive moral claim. Moral knowledge skepticism is the
claim that nobody ever knows that any substantive moral claim is true. If
knowledge implies justification, as is often assumed, then moral justification
skepticism implies moral knowledge skepticism. But even if knowledge requires
justification, it requires more, so moral knowledge skepticism does not imply
moral justification skepticism. Another kind of skeptical view in metaethics
rests on linguistic analysis. Some emotivists, expressivists, and
prescriptivists argue that moral claims (like “Cheating is morally wrong”)
resemble expressions of emotion or desire (like “Boo, cheating”) or
prescriptions for action (like “Don’t cheat”), which are neither true nor
false, so moral claims themselves are neither true nor false. This linguistic
moral skepticism, which is sometimes called noncognitivism, implies moral knowledge
skepticism if knowledge implies truth. Even if such linguistic analyses are
rejected, Moral Rearmament Movement moral skepticism 589 589 one can still hold that no moral
properties or facts really exist. This ontological moral skepticism can be combined
with the linguistic view that moral claims assert moral properties and facts to
yield an error theory that all positive moral claims are false. A different
kind of doubt about morality is often raised by asking, “Why should I be
moral?” Practical moral skepticism answers that there is not always any reason
or any adequate reason to be moral or to do what is morally required. This view
concerns reasons to act rather than reasons to believe. Moral skepticism of all
these kinds is often seen as immoral, but moral skeptics can act and be
motivated and even hold moral beliefs in much the same way as non-skeptics.
Moral skeptics just deny that their or anyone else’s moral beliefs are
justified or known or true, or that they have adequate reason to be moral.
EMOTIVISM, ETHICS,
JUSTIFICATION, MORAL EPISTEMOLOGY, PRESCRIPTIVISM, SKEPTICISM. W.S.-A. moral
status, the suitability of a being to be viewed as an appropriate object of
direct moral concern; the nature or degree of a being’s ability to count as a
ground of claims against moral agents; the moral standing, rank, or importance
of a (kind of) being; the condition of being a moral patient; moral
considerability. Ordinary moral reflection involves considering others. But
which others ought to be considered? And how are the various objects of moral
consideration to be weighed against one another? Anything might be the topic of
moral discussion, but not everything is thought to be an appropriate object of
direct moral concern. If there are any ethical constraints on how we may treat
a ceramic plate, these seem to derive from considerations about other beings,
not from the interests or good or nature of the plate. The same applies,
presumably, to a clod of earth. Many philosophers view a living but insentient being,
such as a dandelion, in the same way; others have doubts. According to some,
even sentient animal life is little more deserving of moral consideration than
the clod or the dandelion. This tradition, which restricts significant moral
status to humans, has come under vigorous and varied attack by defenders of
animal liberation. This attack criticizes speciesism, and argues that
“humanism” is analogous to theories that illegitimately base moral status on
race, gender, or social class. Some philosophers have referred to beings that
are appropriate objects of direct moral concern as “moral patients.” Moral
agents are those beings whose actions are subject to moral evaluation;
analogously, moral patients would be those beings whose suffering (in the sense
of being the objects of the actions of moral agents) permits or demands moral
evaluation. Others apply the label ‘moral patients’ more narrowly, just to
those beings that are appropriate objects of direct moral concern but are not
(also) moral agents. The issue of moral status concerns not only whether beings
count at all morally, but also to what degree they count. After all, beings who
are moral patients might still have their claims outweighed by the preferred
claims of other beings who possess some special moral status. We might, with
Nozick, propose “utilitarianism for animals, Kantianism for people.” Similarly,
the bodily autonomy argument in defense of abortion, made famous by Thomson,
does not deny that the fetus is a moral patient, but insists that her/his/its
claims are limited by the pregnant woman’s prior claim to control her bodily
destiny. It has often been thought that moral status should be tied to the
condition of “personhood.” The idea has been either that only persons are moral
patients, or that persons possess a special moral status that makes them
(morally) more important than nonpersons. Personhood, on such theories, is a
minimal condition for moral patiency. Why? Moral patiency is said to be
“correlative” with moral agency: a creature has both or neither. Alternatively,
persons have been viewed not as the only moral patients, but as a specially
privileged elite among moral patients, possessing rights as well as
interests. ETHICS, KANT, PERSONAL IDENTITY,
PERSONHOOD, RIGHTS. E.J. moral subjectivism.ETHICS. More, Henry (1614–87),
English philosopher, theologian, and poet, the most prolific of the Cambridge
Platonists. In 1631 he entered Christ’s College, where he spent the rest of his
life after becoming Fellow in 1641. He was primarily an apologist of
anti-Calvinist, latitudinarian stamp whose inalienable philosophico-
theological purpose was to demonstrate the existence and immortality of the
soul and to cure “two enormous distempers of the mind,” atheism and
“enthusiasm.” He described himself as “a Fisher for Philosophers, desirous to
draw them to or retain them in the Christian Faith.” His eclectic method
deployed Neoplatonism (notably Plotinus and Ficino), mystical theologies,
cabamoral status More, Henry 590 590
listic doctrines (as More misconceived them), empirical findings (including
reports of witchcraft and ghosts), the new science, and the new philosophy,
notably the philosophy of Descartes. Yet he rejected Descartes’s beast-machine
doctrine, his version of dualism, and the pretensions of Cartesian mechanical
philosophy to explain all physical phenomena. Animals have souls; the universe
is alive with souls. Body and spirit are spatially extended, the former being
essentially impenetrable, inert, and discerpible (divisible into parts), the
latter essentially penetrable, indiscerpible, active, and capable of a
spiritual density, which More called essential spissitude, “the redoubling or
contracting of substance into less space than it does sometimes occupy.”
Physical processes are activated and ordered by the spirit of nature, a
hylarchic principle and “the vicarious power of God upon this great automaton,
the world.” More’s writings on natural philosophy, especially his doctrine of
infinite space, are thought to have influenced Newton. More attacked Hobbes’s
materialism and, in the 1660s and 1670s, the impieties of Dutch Cartesianism,
including the perceived atheism of Spinoza and his circle. He regretted the
“enthusiasm” for and conversion to Quakerism of Anne Conway, his “extramural” tutee
and assiduous correspondent. More had a partiality for coinages and linguistic
exotica. We owe to him ‘Cartesianism’ (1662), coined a few years before the
first appearance of the French equivalent, and the substantive ‘materialist’
(1668).
BOYLE, CAMBRIDGE PLATONISTS, DESCARTES,
NEOPLATONISM. A.G. More, Sir Thomas (1477 or 1478–1535), English humanist,
statesman, martyr, and saint. A lawyer by profession, he entered royal service
in 1517 and became lord chancellor in 1529. After refusing to swear to the Act
of Supremacy, which named Henry VIII the head of the English church, More was
beheaded as a traitor. Although his writings include biography, poetry,
letters, and anti-heretical tracts, his only philosophical work, Utopia
(published in Latin, 1516), is his masterpiece. Covering a wide variety of
subjects including government, education, punishment, religion, family life,
and euthanasia, Utopia contrasts European social institutions with their
counterparts on the imaginary island of Utopia. Inspired in part by Plato’s
Republic, the Utopian communal system is designed to teach virtue and reward it
with happiness. The absence of money, private property, and most social
distinctions allows Utopians the leisure to develop the faculties in which
happiness consists. Because of More’s love of irony, Utopia has been subject to
quite different interpretations. J.W.A. Mosca, Gaetano (1858–1941), Italian
political scientist who made pioneering contributions to the theory of
democratic elitism. Combining the life of a university professor with that of a
politician, he taught such subjects as constitutional law, public law,
political science, and history of political theory; at various times he was
also an editor of the Parliamentary proceedings, an elected member of the
Chamber of Deputies, an under-secretary for colonial affairs, a newspaper
columnist, and a member of the Senate. For Mosca ‘elitism’ refers to the
empirical generalization that every society is ruled by an organized minority.
His democratic commitment is embodied in what he calls juridical defense: the
normative principle that political developments are to be judged by whether and
how they prevent any one person, class, force, or institution from dominating
the others. His third main contribution is a framework consisting of two
intersecting distinctions that yield four possible ideal types, defined as
follows: in autocracy, authority flows from the rulers to the ruled; in
liberalism, from the ruled to the rulers; in democracy, the ruling class is open
to renewal by members of other classes; in aristocracy it is not. He was
influenced by, and in turn influenced, positivism, for the elitist thesis
presumably constitutes the fundamental “law” of political “science.” Even
deeper is his connection with the tradition of Machiavelli’s political realism.
There is also no question that he practiced an empirical approach. In the
tradition of elitism, he may be compared and contrasted with Pareto, Michels,
and Schumpeter; and in the tradition of Italian political philosophy, to Croce,
Gentile, and Gramsci. CROCE, GENTILE,
GRAMSCI, MACHIAVELLI, WEBER. M.A.F. Moses ben Maimon.MAIMONIDES. Mo Ti.MO TZU.
motion.NEWTON. motivation, a property central in motivational explanations of
intentional conduct. To assert that Ann is driving to Boston today because she
wants to see the Red Sox play and believes that they are playing today in
Boston is to offer a More, Sir Thomas motivation 591 591 motivational explanation of this
action. On a popular interpretation, the assertion mentions a pair of
attitudes: a desire and a belief. Ann’s desire is a paradigmatic motivational
attitude in that it inclines her to bring about the satisfaction of that very
attitude. The primary function of motivational attitudes is to bring about their
own satisfaction by inducing the agent to undertake a suitable course of
action, and, arguably, any attitude that has that function is, ipso facto, a
motivational one. The related thesis that only attitudes having this function
are motivational – or, more precisely, motivation-constituting – is
implausible. Ann hopes that the Sox won yesterday. Plainly, her hope cannot
bring about its own satisfaction, since Ann has no control over the past. Even
so, the hope seemingly may motivate action (e.g., Ann’s searching for sports
news on her car radio), in which case the hope is motivation-constituting. Some
philosophers have claimed that our beliefs that we are morally required to take
a particular course of action are motivation-constituting, and such beliefs obviously
do not have the function of bringing about their own satisfaction (i.e., their
truth). However, the claim is controversial, as is the related claim that
beliefs of this kind are “besires” – that is, not merely beliefs but desires as
well.
ACCIDIE, ACTION THEORY,
MOTIVATIONAL EXPLANATION, MOTIVATIONAL INTERNALISM. A.R.M. motivational
explanation, a type of explanation of goal-directed behavior where the
explanans appeals to the motives of the agent. The explanation usually is in
the following form: Smith swam hard in order to win the race. Here the
description of what Smith did identifies the behavior to be explained, and the
phrase that follows ‘in order to’ identifies the goal or the state of affairs
the obtaining of which was the moving force behind the behavior. The general
presumption is that the agent whose behavior is being explained is capable of
deliberating and acting on the decisions reached as a result of the
deliberation. Thus, it is dubious whether the explanation contained in ‘The plant
turned toward the sun in order to receive more light’ is a motivational
explanation. Two problems are thought to surround motivational explanations.
First, since the state of affairs set as the goal is, at the time of the
action, non-existent, it can only act as the “moving force” by appearing as the
intentional object of an inner psychological state of the agent. Thus, motives
are generally desires for specific objects or states of affairs on which the
agent acts. So motivational explanation is basically the type of explanation
provided in folk psychology, and as such it inherits all the alleged problems
of the latter. And second, what counts as a motive for an action under one
description usually fails to be a motive for the same action under a different
description. My motive for saying “hello” may have been my desire to answer the
phone, but my motive for saying “hello” loudly was to express my irritation at
the person calling me so late at night.
ACTION THEORY,
EXPLANATION, FOLK PSYCHOLOGY, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. B.E. motivational
internalism, the view that moral motivation is internal to moral duty (or the
sense of duty). The view represents the contemporary understanding of Hume’s
thesis that morality is essentially practical. Hume went on to point out the
apparent logical gap between statements of fact, which express theoretical
judgments, and statements about what ought to be done, which express practical
judgments. Motivational internalism offers one explanation for this gap. No
motivation is internal to the recognition of facts. The specific internal
relation the view affirms is that of necessity. Thus, motivational internalists
hold that if one sees that one has a duty to do a certain action or that it
would be right to do it, then necessarily one has a motive to do it. For
example, if one sees that it is one’s duty to donate blood, then necessarily
one has a motive to donate blood. Motivational externalism, the opposing view,
denies this relation. Its adherents hold that it is possible for one to see
that one has a duty to do a certain action or that it would be right to do it
yet have no motive to do it. Motivational externalists typically, though not
universally, deny any real gap between theoretical and practical judgments.
Motivational internalism takes either of two forms, rationalist and
anti-rationalist. Rationalists, such as Plato and Kant, hold that the content
or truth of a moral requirement guarantees in those who understand it a motive
of compliance. Anti-rationalists, such as Hume, hold that moral judgment
necessarily has some affective or volitional component that supplies a motive
for the relevant action but that renders morality less a matter of reason and
truth than of feeling or commitment. It is also possible in the abstract to motivational
explanation motivational internalism 592
592 Mo Tzu mysticism 593 draw an analogous distinction between two forms
of motivational externalism, cognitivist and noncognitivist, but because the
view springs from an interest in assimilating practical judgment to theoretical
judgment, its only influential form has been cognitivist. EMOTIVISM, ETHICS, HUME. J.D. Mo Tzu, also
known as Master Mo, Mo Ti (fifth century B.C.), Chinese philosopher and founder
of the Mohist school of thought, which was a major rival to Confucianism in
ancient China. The text Mo Tzu contains different versions of his teachings as
well as subsequent developments of his thought. Mo Tzu regarded rightness (yi)
as determined by what benefits (li) the public, where benefit is understood in
terms of such things as order and increased resources in society. He opposed
the musical activities and ritual practices of the Confucians on the ground
that such practices are detrimental to the public good. He is probably best
known for advocating the ideal of an equal concern to benefit and avoid harm to
every human being. Practicing this ideal is to the public good, since strife
and disorder stem from partiality toward oneself or one’s family or social
group. Also, it being the will of Heaven (t’ien) that people have equal concern
for all, one will be rewarded or punished by Heaven according to whether one
practices this ideal. In response to worries about the practicability of the
ideal, Mo Tzu insisted that it was simple and easy to put the ideal into
practice, leaving himself open to the charge that he neglected the complexities
of emotional management. CONFUCIANISM,
MOHISM. K.-l.S. Mou Tsung-san (1909–95), Chinese philosopher, perhaps the most
original thinker among contemporary Neo-Confucians. Educated at Peking
University, he first studied Western philosophy but was converted to Chinese
philosophy under the influence of Hsiung Shih-li. He made a great breakthrough
in his study of Sung–Ming NeoConfucian philosophy, arguing that Chu Hsi was
really a side branch that took the position of the orthodoxy. He maintained
that all three major Chinese traditions, Confucian, Taoist, and Buddhist,
assert that humans have the endowment for intellectual intuition, meaning
personal participation in tao (the Way).
CHINESE PHILOSOPHY, HSIUNG SHIH-LI, HSÜ FU-KUAN, NEO-CONFUCIANISM, T’ANG
CHÜN-I. S.-h.L. moving rows paradox.ZENO’s PARADOXES. multiple
realizability.FUNCTIONALISM. multiple-relation theory.PERCEPTION. mystical
experience, an experience alleged to reveal some aspect of reality not normally
accessible to sensory experience or cognition. The experience – typically
characterized by its profound emotional impact on the one who experiences it,
its transcendence of spatial and temporal distinctions, its transitoriness, and
its ineffability – is often but not always associated with some religious
tradition. In theistic religions, mystical experiences are claimed to be
brought about by God or by some other superhuman agent. Theistic mystical
experiences evoke feelings of worshipful awe. Their content can vary from
something no more articulate than a feeling of closeness to God to something as
specific as an item of revealed theology, such as, for a Christian mystic, a
vision of the Trinity. Non-theistic mystical experiences are usually claimed to
reveal the metaphysical unity of all things and to provide those who experience
them with a sense of inner peace or bliss.
MYSTICISM. W.E.M. mysticism, a doctrine or discipline maintaining that
one can gain knowledge of reality that is not accessible to sense perception or
to rational, conceptual thought. Generally associated with a religious
tradition, mysticism can take a theistic form, as it has in Jewish, Christian,
and Islamic traditions, or a non-theistic form, as it has in Buddhism and some
varieties of Hinduism. Mystics claim that the mystical experience, the vehicle
of mystical knowledge, is usually the result of spiritual training, involving
some combination of prayer, meditation, fasting, bodily discipline, and
renunciation of worldly concerns. Theistic varieties of mysticism describe the
mystical experience as granted by God and thus not subject to the control of
the mystic. Although theists claim to feel closeness to God during the mystical
experience, they regard assertions of identity of the self with God as
heretical. Non-theistic varieties are more apt to describe the experience as
one that can be induced and controlled by the mystic and in which distinctions
between the self and reality, or subject and object, are revealed to be
illusory. Mystics claim that, although veridical, their experiences cannot be
adequately described in language, because ordinary communication is based on
sense experience and conceptual differentiation: mystical writings are thus
characterized by metaphor and simile. It is con 593 troversial whether all mystical
experiences are basically the same, and whether the apparent diversity among
them is the result of interpretations influenced by different cultural
traditions. MYSTICAL EXPERIENCE,
PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. W.E.M. myth of Er, a tale at the end of Plato’s
Republic dramatizing the rewards of justice and philosophy by depicting the
process of reincarnation. Complementing the main argument of the work, that it
is intrinsically better to be just than unjust, this longest of Plato’s myths
blends traditional lore with speculative cosmology to show that justice also
pays, usually in life and certainly in the afterlife. Er, a warrior who revived
shortly after death, reports how judges assign the souls of the just to heaven
but others to punishment in the underworld, and how most return after a
thousand years to behold the celestial order, to choose their next lives, and
to be born anew. PLATO. S.A.W. myth of
the given.SELLARS, WILFRID. myth of Er myth of the given 594 594 Nagarjuna (fl. early second century
A.D.), Indian Mahayana Buddhist philosopher, founder of the Madhyamika view.
The Mulanadhyamakarika Prajña (“The Fundamental Verses on the Middle Way”) and
the Sunyatasaptati (“The Septuagint on Emptiness”) are perhaps his major works.
He distinguishes between “two truths”: a conditional truth, which is
provisional and reflects the sort of distinctions we make in everyday speech
and find in ordinary experience; and a final truth, which is that there exists
only an ineffable independent reality. Overcoming acceptance of the
conventional, conditional truth is requisite for seeing the final truth in
enlightenment. MADHYAMIKA. K.E.Y. Nagel,
Ernest (1901–85), Czech-born American philosopher, the preeminent American
philosopher of science in the period from the mid-1930s to the 1960s. Arriving
in New York as a ten-yearold immigrant, he earned his B.S. degree from the
College of the City of New York and his Ph.D. from Columbia University in 1931.
He was a member of the Philosophy Department at Columbia from 1930 to 1970. He
coauthored the influential An Introduction to Logic and Scientific Method with
his former teacher, M. R. Cohen. His many publications include two well-known
classics: Principles of the Theory of Probability (1939) and Structure of
Science (1960). Nagel was sensitive to developments in logic, foundations of
mathematics, and probability theory, and he shared with Russell and with
members of the Vienna Circle like Carnap and Phillip Frank a respect for the
relevance of scientific inquiry for philosophical reflection. But his writing
also reveals the influences of M. R. Cohen and that strand in the thinking of
the pragmatism of Peirce and Dewey which Nagel himself called “contextualist
naturalism.” He was a persuasive critic of Russell’s views of the data of
sensation as a source of non-inferential premises for knowledge and of cognate
views expressed by some members of the Vienna Circle. Unlike Frege, Russell,
Carnap, Popper, and others, he rejected the view that taking account of context
in characterizing method threatened to taint philosophical reflection with an
unacceptable psychologism. This stance subsequently allowed him to oppose
historicist and sociologist approaches to the philosophy of science. Nagel’s
contextualism is reflected in his contention that ideas of determinism,
probability, explanation, and reduction “can be significantly discussed only if
they are directed to the theories or formulations of a science and not its
subject matter” (Principles of the Theory of Probability, 1939). This attitude
infused his influential discussions of covering law explanation, statistical
explanation, functional explanation, and reduction of one theory to another, in
both natural and social science. Similarly, his contention that participants in
the debate between realism and instrumentalism should clarify the import of
their differences for (context-sensitive) scientific methodology served as the
core of his argument casting doubt on the significance of the dispute. In
addition to his extensive writings on scientific knowledge methodology, Nagel
wrote influential essays on measurement, the history of mathematics, and the
philosophy of law. COVERING LAW MODEL,
PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, REDUCTION, VIENNA CIRCLE. I.L. Nagel, Thomas (b.1937),
American professor of philosophy and of law at New York University, known for
his important contributions in the fields of metaphysics, epistemology, ethics,
and political philosophy. Nagel’s work in these areas is unified by a
particular vision of perennial philosophical problems, according to which they
emerge from a clash between two perspectives from which human beings can view
themselves and the world. From an impersonal perspective, which results from
detaching ourselves from our particular viewpoints, we strive to achieve an
objective view of the world, whereas from a personal perspective, we see the
world from our particular point of view. According to Nagel, dominance of the
impersonal perspective in trying to understand reality leads to implausible
philosophical views because it fails to accommodate facts about the self,
minds, agency, and values that are revealed through engaged personal
perspectives. In the philosophy of mind, for instance, Nagel criticizes various
reductive accounts of mentality 595 N
595 resulting from taking an exclusively impersonal standpoint because
they inevitably fail to account for the irreducibly subjective character of
consciousness. In ethics, consequentialist moral theories (like
utilitarianism), which feature strong impartialist demands that stem from
taking a detached, impersonal perspective, find resistance from the personal
perspective within which individual goals and motives are accorded an importance
not found in strongly impartialist moral theories. An examination of such
problems in metaphysics, epistemology, and ethics is found in his Moral
Questions (1979) and The View from Nowhere (1986). In Equality and Partiality
(1990) Nagel argues that the impersonal standpoint gives rise to an egalitarian
form of impartial regard for all people that often clashes with the goals,
concerns, and affections that individuals experience from a personal
perspective. Quite generally, then, as Nagel sees it, one important
philosophical task is to explore ways in which these two standpoints on both
theoretical and practical matters might be integrated. Nagel has also made
important contributions regarding the nature and possibility of reason or
rationality in both its theoretical and its practical uses. The Possibility of
Altruism (1970) is an exploration of the structure of practical reason in which
Nagel defends the rationality of prudence and altruism, arguing that the
possibility of such behavior is connected with our capacities to view ourselves
respectively persisting through time and recognizing the reality of other
persons. The Last Word (1998) is a defense of reason against skeptical views,
according to which reason is a merely contingent, locally conditioned feature
of particular cultures and hence relative.
ETHICS, MORAL RATIONALISM, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND, PRACTICAL REASON. M.C.T.
naive realism.PERCEPTION. name, logically proper.RUSSELL. names, causal theory
of.CAUSAL THEORY OF PROPER NAMES. names, descriptivist theory of.CAUSAL THEORY
OF PROPER NAMES. narrow content.PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. narrow reflective
equilibrium.REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM. nativism.FODOR. Natorp, Paul Gerhard.
NEO-KANTIANISM. natural
deduction.DEDUCTION. natural duty.DUTY. natural evil.PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION.
naturalism, the twofold view that (1) everything is composed of natural
entities – those studied in the sciences (on some versions, the natural
sciences) – whose properties determine all the properties of things, persons
included (abstracta like possibilia and mathematical objects, if they exist,
being constructed of such abstract entities as the sciences allow); and (2)
acceptable methods of justification and explanation are continuous, in some
sense, with those in science. Clause (1) is metaphysical or ontological, clause
(2) methodological and/or epistemological. Often naturalism is formulated only
for a specific subject matter or domain. Thus ethical naturalism holds that
moral properties are equivalent to or at least determined by certain natural
properties, so that moral judgments either form a subclass of, or are
(non-reductively) determined by the factual or descriptive judgments, and the
appropriate methods of moral justification and explanation are continuous with
those in science. Aristotle and Spinoza sometimes are counted among the
ancestors of naturalism, as are Democritus, Epicurus, Lucretius, and Hobbes.
But the major impetus to naturalism in the last two centuries comes from
advances in science and the growing explanatory power they signify. By the
1850s, the synthesis of urea, reflections on the conservation of energy, work
on “animal electricity,” and discoveries in physiology suggested to Feuerbach,
L. Buchner, and others that all aspects of human beings are explainable in purely
natural terms. Darwin’s theory had even greater impact, and by the end of the
nineteenth century naturalist philosophies were making inroads where idealism
once reigned unchallenged. Naturalism’s ranks now included H. Spencer, J.
Tyndall, T. H. Huxley, W. K. Clifford, and E. Haeckel. Early in the twentieth
century, Santayana’s naturalism strongly influenced a number of American
philosophers, as did Dewey’s. Still other versions of naturalism flourished in
America in the 1930s and 1940s, including those of R. W. Sellars and M. Cohen.
Today most American and other philosophers of mind naive realism naturalism
596 596 are naturalists of some
stripe, largely because of what they see as the lessons of continuing scientific
advances, some of them spectacular, particularly in the brain sciences.
Nonetheless, twentieth-century philosophy has been largely anti-naturalist.
Both phenomenology in the Husserlian tradition and analytic philosophy in the
Fregean tradition, together with their descendants, have been united in
rejecting psychologism, a species of naturalism according to which empirical
discoveries about mental processes are crucial for understanding the nature of
knowledge, language, and logic. In order to defend the autonomy of philosophy
against inroads from descriptive science, many philosophers have tried to turn
the tables by arguing for the priority of philosophy over science, hence over
any of its alleged naturalist implications. Many continue to do so, often on
the ground that philosophy alone can illuminate the normativity and
intentionality involved in knowledge, language, and logic; or on the ground
that philosophy can evaluate the normative and regulative presuppositions of
scientific practice which science itself is either blind to or unequipped to
analyze; or on the ground that phi- losophy understands how the language of
science can no more be used to get outside itself than any other, hence can no
more be known to be in touch with the world and ourselves than any other; or on
the ground that would-be justifications of fundamental method, naturalist
method certainly included, are necessarily circular because they must employ
the very method at issue. Naturalists may reply by arguing that naturalism’s
methodological clause (2) entails the opposite of dogmatism, requiring as it
does an uncompromising fallibilism about philosophical matters that is
continuous with the open, selfcritical spirit of science. If evidence were to
accumulate against naturalism’s metaphysical clause (1), (1) would have to be
revised or rejected, and there is no a priori reason such evidence could in
principle never be found; indeed many naturalists reject the a priori
altogether. Likewise, (2) itself might have to be revised or even rejected in
light of adverse argument, so that in this respect (2) is self-referentially
consistent. Until then, (2)’s having survived rigorous criticism to date is
justification enough, as is the case with hypotheses in science, which often
are deployed without circularity in the course of their own evaluation, whether
positive or negative (H. I. Brown, “Circular Justifications,” 1994). So too can
language be used without circularity in expressing hypotheses about the
relations between language and the prelinguistic world (as illustrated by R.
Millikan’s Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories, 1984; cf. Post,
“Epistemology,” 1996). As for normativity and intentionality, naturalism does
not entail materialism or physicalism, according to which everything is
composed of the entities or processes studied in physics, and the properties of
these basic physical affairs determine all the properties of things (as in
Quine). Some naturalists deny this, holding that more things than are dreamt of
in physics are required to account for normativity and intentionality – and
consciousness. Nor need naturalism be reductive, in the sense of equating every
property with some natural property. Indeed many physicalists themselves
explain how the physical, hence natural, properties of things might determine
other, non-natural properties without being equivalent to them (G. Hellman, T.
Horgan, D. Lewis; see J. Post, The Faces of Existence, 1987). Often the
determining physical properties are not all properties of the thing x that has
the non-natural properties, but include properties of items separated from x in
space and time or in some cases bearing no physical relation to x that does any
work in determining x’s properties (Post, “ ‘Global’ Supervenient
Determination: Too Permissive?” 1995). Thus naturalism allows a high degree of
holism and historicity, which opens the way for a non-reductive naturalist
account of intentionality and normativity, such as Millikan’s, that is immune
to the usual objections, which are mostly objections to reduction. The alternative
psychosemantic theories of Dretske and Fodor, being largely reductive, remain
vulnerable to such objections. In these and other ways non-reductive naturalism
attempts to combine a monism of entities – the natural ones of which everything
is composed – with a pluralism of properties, many of them irreducible or
emergent. Not everything is nothing but a natural thing, nor need naturalism
accord totalizing primacy to the natural face of existence. Indeed, some
naturalists regard the universe as having religious and moral dimensions that
enjoy a crucial kind of primacy; and some offer theologies that are more
traditionally theist (as do H. N. Wieman, C. Hardwick, J. Post). So far from
exhibiting “reptilian indifference” to humans and their fate, the universe can
be an enchanted place of belonging.
THEOLOGICAL NATURALISM.
naturalistic epistemology, an approach to epistemology that views the human
subject as a natural phenomenon and uses empirical science to study epistemic
activity. The phrase was introduced by Quine (“Epistemology Naturalized,” in
Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, 1969), who proposed that epistemology
should be a chapter of psychology. Quine construed classical epistemology as
Cartesian epistemology, an attempt to ground all knowledge in a firmly logical
way on immediate experience. In its twentieth-century embodiment, it hoped to
give a translation of all discourse and a deductive validation of all science
in terms of sense experience, logic, and set theory. Repudiating this dream as
forlorn, Quine urged that epistemology be abandoned and replaced by psychology.
It would be a scientific study of how the subject takes sensory stimulations as
input and delivers as output a theory of the three-dimensional world. This
formulation appears to eliminate the normative mission of epistemology. In
later writing, however, Quine has suggested that normative epistemology can be
naturalized as a chapter of engineering: the technology of predicting
experience, or sensory stimulations. Some theories of knowledge are
naturalistic in their depiction of knowers as physical systems in causal
interaction with the environment. One such theory is the causal theory of
knowing, which says that a person knows that p provided his belief that p has a
suitable causal connection with a corresponding state of affairs. Another
example is the information-theoretic approach developed by Dretske (Knowledge
and the Flow of Information, 1981). This says that a person knows that p only
if some signal “carries” this information (that p) to him, where information is
construed as an objective commodity that can be processed and transmitted via
instruments, gauges, neurons, and the like. Information is “carried” from one
site to another when events located at those sites are connected by a suitable
lawful dependence. The normative concept of justification has also been the
subject of naturalistic construals. Whereas many theories of justified belief
focus on logical or probabilistic relations between evidence and hypothesis, naturalistic
theories focus on the psychological processes causally responsible for the
belief. The logical status of a belief does not fix its justificational status.
Belief in a tautology, for instance, is not justified if it is formed by blind
trust in an ignorant guru. According to Goldman (Epistemology and Cognition,
1986), a belief qualifies as justified only if it is produced by reliable
belief-forming processes, i.e., processes that generally have a high truth
ratio. Goldman’s larger program for naturalistic epistemology is called
“epistemics,” an interdisciplinary enterprise in which cognitive science would
play a major role. Epistemics would seek to identify the subset of cognitive
operations available to the human cognizer that are best from a truth-bearing
standpoint. Relevant truth-linked properties include problem-solving power and
speed, i.e., the abilities to obtain correct answers to questions of interest
and to do so quickly. Close connections between epistemology and artificial
intelligence have been proposed by Clark Glymour, Gilbert Harman, John Pollock,
and Paul Thagard. Harman stresses that principles of good reasoning are not
directly given by rules of logic. Modus ponens, e.g., does not tell you to
infer q if you already believe p and ‘if p then q’. In some cases it is better
to subtract a belief in one of the premises rather than add a belief in q.
Belief revision also requires attention to the storage and computational
limitations of the mind. Limits of memory capacity, e.g., suggest a principle
of clutter avoidance: not filling one’s mind with vast numbers of useless
beliefs (Harman, Change in View, 1986). Other conceptions of naturalistic
epistemology focus on the history of science. Larry Laudan conceives of
naturalistic epistemology as a scientific inquiry that gathers empirical
evidence concerning the past track records of various scientific methodologies,
with the aim of determining which of these methodologies can best advance the
chosen cognitive ends. Naturalistic epistemology need not confine its attention
to individual epistemic agents; it can also study communities of agents. This
perspective invites contributions from sciences that address the social side of
the knowledge-seeking enterprise. If naturalistic epistemology is a normative
inquiry, however, it must not simply naturalism, biological naturalistic
epistemology 598 598 describe social
practices or social influences; it must analyze the impact of these factors on
the attainment of cognitive ends. Philosophers such as David Hull, Nicholas
Rescher, Philip Kitcher, and Alvin Goldman have sketched models inspired by
population biology and economics to explore the epistemic consequences of
alternative distributions of research activity and different ways that
professional rewards might influence the course of research. ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE, EPISTEMOLOGY,
NATURALISM, RELIABILISM. A.I.G. naturalistic fallacy.MOORE. natural kind, a
category of entities classically conceived as having modal implications; e.g.,
if Socrates is a member of the natural kind human being, then he is necessarily
a human being. The idea that nature fixes certain sortals, such as ‘water’ and
‘human being’, as correct classifications that appear to designate kinds of
entities has roots going back at least to Plato and Aristotle. Anil Gupta has
argued that sortals are to be distinguished from properties designated by such
predicates as ‘red’ by including criteria for individuating the particulars
(bits or amounts for mass nouns) that fall under them as well as criteria for
sorting those particulars into the class. Quine is salient among those who find
the modal implications of natural kinds objectionable. He has argued that the
idea of natural kinds is rooted in prescientific intuitive judgments of comparative
similarity, and he has suggested that as these intuitive classifications are
replaced by classifications based on scientific theories these modal
implications drop away. Kripke and Putnam have argued that science in fact uses
natural kind terms having the modal implications Quine finds so objectionable.
They see an important role in scientific methodology for the capacity to refer
demonstratively to such natural kinds by pointing out particulars that fall
under them. Certain inferences within science – such as the inference to the
charge for electrons generally from the measurement of the charge on one or a
few electrons – seem to be additional aspects of a role for natural kind terms
in scientific practice. Other roles in the methodology of science for natural
kind concepts have been discussed in recent work by Ian Hacking and Thomas
Kuhn. COUNT NOUN, ESSENTIALISM,
PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, QUALITATIVE PREDICATE. W.Har. natural language.FORMAL
LANGUAGE, PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE. natural law, also called law of nature, in
moral and political philosophy, an objective norm or set of objective norms
governing human behavior, similar to the positive laws of a human ruler, but
binding on all people alike and usually understood as involving a superhuman
legislator. Ancient Greek and Roman thought, particularly Stoicism, introduced
ideas of eternal laws directing the actions of all rational beings and built
into the very structure of the universe. Roman lawyers developed a doctrine of
a law that all civilized peoples would recognize, and made some effort to
explain it in terms of a natural law common to animals and humans. The most
influential forms of natural law theory, however, arose from later efforts to
use Stoic and legal language to work out a Christian theory of morality and
politics. The aim was to show that the principles of morals could be known by
reason alone, without revelation, so that the whole human race could know how
to live properly. The law of nature applies, on this understanding, only to
rational beings, who can obey or disobey it deliberately and freely. It is thus
different in kind from the laws God laid down for the inanimate and irrational
parts of creation. Natural law theorists often saw continuities and analogies
between natural laws for humans and those for the rest of creation but did not
confuse them. The most enduringly influential natural law writer was Aquinas.
On his view God’s eternal reason ordains laws directing all things to act for
the good of the community of the universe, the declaration of His own glory.
Human reason can participate sufficiently in God’s eternal reason to show us
the good of the human community. The natural law is thus our sharing in the
eternal law in a way appropriate to our human nature. God lays down certain
other laws through revelation; these divine laws point us toward our eternal
goal. The natural law concerns our earthly good, and needs to be supplemented
by human laws. Such laws can vary from community to community, but to be
binding they must always stay within the limits of the law of nature. God
engraved the most basic principles of the natural law in the minds of all
people alike, but their detailed application takes reasoning powers that not
everyone may have. Opponents of Aquinas – called voluntarists – argued that
God’s will, not his intellect, is the source of law, and that God could have
laid down different natural laws for us. Hugo Grotius naturalistic fallacy
natural law 599 599 rejected their
position, but unlike Aquinas he conceived of natural law as meant not to direct
us to bring about some definite common good but to set the limits on the ways
in which each of us could properly pursue our own personal aims. This Grotian
outlook was developed by Hobbes, Pufendorf, and Locke along voluntarist lines.
Thomistic views continued to be expounded by Protestant as well as Roman
Catholic writers until the end of the seventeenth century. Thereafter, while
natural law theory remained central to Catholic teaching, it ceased to attract
major new non-Catholic proponents. Natural law doctrine in both Thomistic and
Grotian versions treats morality as basically a matter of compliance with law.
Obligation and duty, obedience and disobedience, merit and guilt, reward and
punishment, are central notions. Virtues are simply habits of following laws.
Though the law is suited to our distinctive human nature and can be discovered
by the proper use of reason, it is not a self-imposed law. In following it we
are obeying God. Since the early eighteenth century, philosophical discussions
of whether or not there is an objective morality have largely ceased to center
on natural law. The idea remains alive, however, in jurisprudence. Natural law
theories are opposed to legal positivism, the view that the only binding laws
are those imposed by human sovereigns, who cannot be subject to higher legal
constraints. Legal theorists arguing that there are rational objective limits
to the legislative power of rulers often think of these limits in terms of
natural law, even when their theories do not invoke or imply any of the
religious aspects of earlier natural law positions. AQUINAS, GROTIUS, HOBBES, PHILOSOPHY OF LAW,
PUFENDORF. J.B.S. natural light.DESCARTES. natural meaning.MEANING. naturalness.JUAN
CHI. natural number.MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS, MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION. natural
philosophy, the study of nature or of the spatiotemporal world. This was
regarded as a task for philosophy before the emergence of modern science,
especially physics and astronomy, and the term is now only used with reference
to premodern times. Philosophical questions about nature still remain, e.g.,
whether materialism is true, but they would usually be placed in metaphysics or
in a branch of it that may be called philosophy of nature. Natural philosophy is
not to be confused with metaphysical naturalism, which is the metaphysical view
(no part of science itself) that all that there is is the spatiotemporal world
and that the only way to study it is that of the empirical sciences. It is also
not to be confused with natural theology, which also may be considered part of
metaphysics. METAPHYSICS. P.Bu. natural
religion, a term first occurring in the second half of the seventeenth century,
used in three related senses, the most common being (1) a body of truths about
God and our duty that can be discovered by natural reason. These truths are
sufficient for salvation or (according to some orthodox Christians) would have
been sufficient if Adam had not sinned. Natural religion in this sense should
be distinguished from natural theology, which does not imply this. A natural
religion may also be (2) one that has a human, as distinct from a divine,
origin. It may also be (3) a religion of human nature as such, as distinguished
from religious beliefs and practices that have been determined by local
circumstances. Natural religion in the third sense is identified with
humanity’s original religion. In all three senses, natural religion includes a
belief in God’s existence, justice, benevolence, and providential government;
in immortality; and in the dictates of common morality. While the concept is
associated with deism, it is also sympathetically treated by Christian writers
like Clarke, who argues that revealed religion simply restores natural religion
to its original purity and adds inducements to compliance.
CLARKE, PHILOSOPHY OF
RELIGION. W.J.Wa. natural right.RIGHTS. natural selection.DARWINISM. natural
sign.THEORY OF SIGNS. natural theology.PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION, THEOLOGIA
NATURALIS. natura naturans.SPINOZA. natura naturata.SPINOZA. nature, law
of.NATURAL LAW, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. natural light nature, law of 600 600 nature, right of.HOBBES. nature, state
of.HOBBES. Naturphilosophie.SCHELLING. Naturwissenschaften.WEBER. Néant.SARTRE.
necessary.CONTINGENT. necessary condition.CONDITION. necessary truth.NECESSITY.
necessitarianism, the doctrine that necessity is an objective feature of the
world. Natural language permits speakers to express modalities: a state of
affairs can be actual (Paris’s being in France), merely possible (chlorophyll’s
making things blue), or necessary (2 ! 2 % 4). Anti-necessitarians believe that
these distinctions are not grounded in the nature of the world. Some of them
claim that the distinctions are merely verbal. Others, e.g., Hume, believed
that psychological facts, like our expectations of future events, explain the
idea of necessity. Yet others contend that the modalities reflect epistemic
considerations; necessity reflects the highest level of an inquirer’s
commitment. Some necessitarians believe there are different modes of
metaphysical necessity, e.g., causal and logical necessity. Certain proponents
of idealism believe that each fact is necessarily connected with every other
fact so that the ultimate goal of scientific inquiry is the discovery of a
completely rigorous mathematical system of the world. DETERMINISM, FREE WILL PROBLEM. B.B.
necessity, a modal property attributable to a whole proposition (dictum) just
when it is not possible that the proposition be false (the proposition being de
dicto necessary). Narrowly construed, a proposition P is logically necessary
provided P satisfies certain syntactic conditions, namely, that P’s denial is
formally self-contradictory. More broadly, P is logically necessary just when P
satisfies certain semantic conditions, namely, that P’s denial is false, and P
true, in all possible worlds. These semantic conditions were first suggested by
Leibniz, refined by Wittgenstein and Carnap, and fully developed as the
possible worlds semantics of Kripke, Hintikka, et al., in the 1960s.
Previously, philosophers had to rely largely on intuition to determine the
acceptability or otherwise of formulas involving the necessity operator, A, and
were at a loss as to which of various axiomatic systems for modal logic, as
developed in the 1930s by C. I. Lewis, best captured the notion of logical
necessity. There was much debate, for instance, over the characteristic (NN)
thesis of Lewis’s system S4, namely, AP / A AP (if P is necessary then it is
necessarily necessary). But given a Leibnizian account of the truth conditions
for a statement of the form Aa namely (R1) that Aa is true provided a is true
in all possible worlds, and (R2) that Aa is false provided there is at least
one possible world in which a is false, a proof can be constructed by reductio
ad absurdum. For suppose that AP / AAP is false in some arbitrarily chosen
world W. Then its antecedent will be true in W, and hence (by R1) it follows
(a) that P will be true in all possible worlds. But equally its consequent will
be false in W, and hence (by R2) AP will be false in at least one possible
world, from which (again by R2) it follows (b) that P will be false in at least
one possible world, thus contradicting (a). A similar proof can be constructed
for the characteristic thesis of S5, namely, -A-P / A-A-P (if P is possibly
true then it is necessarily possible). Necessity is also attributable to a
property F of an object O provided it is not possible that (there is no
possible world in which) O exists and lacks F – F being de re necessary,
internal or essential to O. For instance, the non-repeatable (haecceitist)
property of being identical to O is de re necessary (essential) to O, and
arguably the repeatable property of being extended is de re necessary to all
colored objects. CONTINGENT,
ESSENTIALISM, HAECCEITY, MODAL LOGIC, POSSIBLE WORLDS. R.D.B. necessity,
metaphysical.NECESSITY, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. necessity, nomic.LAWLIKE
GENERALIZATION. negation, the logical operation on propositions that is indicated,
e.g., by the prefatory clause ‘It is not the case that . . .’. Negation is
standardly distinguished sharply from the operation on predicates that is
called complementation and that is indicated by the prefix ‘non-’. Because
negation can also be indicated by the adverb ‘not’, a distinction is often
drawn between external negation, which is indicated by attaching the prefatory
‘It is not the case that . . .’ to an assertion, and internal negation, which
is indicated by inserting the adverb ‘not’ (along with, perhaps, nature, right
of negation 601 601 grammatically
necessary words like ‘do’ or ‘does’) into the assertion in such a way as to
indicate that the adverb ‘not’ modifies the verb. In a number of cases, the question
arises as to whether external and internal negation yield logically equivalent
results. For example, ‘It is not the case that Santa Claus exists’ would seem
obviously to be true, whereas ‘Santa Claus does not exist’ seems to some
philosophers to presuppose what it denies, on the ground that nothing could be
truly asserted of Santa Claus unless he existed. DOUBLE NEGATION, TRUTH TABLE. R.W.B.
negation-complete.COMPLETENESS. negative duty.DUTY. negative
feedback.CYBERNETICS. negative freedom.
Nemesius of Emesa (fl.
c.390–400), Greek Christian philosopher. His treatise on the soul, On the
Nature of Man, translated from Greek into Latin by Alphanus of Salerno and
Burgundio of Pisa (c.1160), was attributed to Gregory of Nyssa in the Middle
Ages, and enjoyed some authority; the treatise rejects Plato for underplaying
the unity of soul and body, and Aristotle for making the soul essentially
corporeal. The soul is selfsubsistent, incorporeal, and by nature immortal, but
naturally suited for union with the body. Nemesius draws on Ammonius Saccas and
Porphyry, as well as analogy to the union of divine and human nature in Christ,
to explain the incorruptible soul’s perfect union with the corruptible body.
His review of the powers of the soul draws especially on Galen on the brain.
His view that rational creatures possess free will in virtue of their
rationality influenced Maximus the Confessor and John of Damascus. J.Lo.
Neo-Confucianism, Confucianism as revived in China during the late tenth to
mid-seventeenth centuries. It has also been called Tao-hsüeh (learning of the
Way) or Li-hsüeh (learning of principles) in the broader sense. It is without
any doubt Confucianism, since Sung–Ming Confucianists also found their ultimate
commitment in jen (humanity or human-heartedness) and regulated their behavior
by li (propriety). But it acquired new features, since it was a movement in
response to the challenges from Buddhism and Neo-Taoism. Therefore it developed
sophisticated theories of human mind and nature and also cosmology and
metaphysics far beyond the scope of Pre-Ch’in Confucianism. If the Confucian
ideal may be characterized by nei-sheng-waiwang (inward sageliness and outward
kingliness), then the Neo-Confucianists certainly made greater contributions to
the nei-sheng side, as they considered wei-chi-chih-hsüeh (learning for one’s
self) as their primary concern, and developed sophisticated discipline of the
mind comparable to the kind of transcendental meditation practiced by Buddhists
and Taoists. They put emphasis on finding resources within the self. Hence they
moved away from the Han tradition of writing extensive commentaries on the Five
Classics. Instead, they looked for guidance to the so-called Four Books: the
Analects, the Mencius, The Great Learning, and The Doctrine of the Mean. They
also believed that they should put what they had learned from the words of the
sages and worthies into practice in order to make themselves better. This was
to start a new trend in sharp contrast to the earlier Five Dynasties period
(907–60), when moral standards had fallen to a new low. According to Chu Hsi,
the movement started with Chou Tun-yi (1017–73), who, along with Chang Tsai
(1020–77), gave new interpretations to the I-Ching (the Book of Changes) and
The Doctrine of the Mean in combination with the Analects and the Mencius so as
to develop new cosmologies and metaphysics in response to the challenges from
Buddhism and Taoism. The name of Shao Yung (1011–77), an expert on the I-Ching,
was excluded, as his views were considered too Taoistic. But the true founders
and leaders of the movement were the two Ch’eng brothers – Ch’eng Hao (1032–85)
and Ch’eng Yi (1033– 1107). Onetime pupils of Chou, they developed li
(principle) into a philosophical concept. Even though Hua-yen Buddhism had used
the term first, the Ch’eng brothers gave it a totally new interpretation from a
Confucian perspective. Later scholars find that the thoughts of the two
brothers differed both in style and in substance. Ch’eng Hao believed in i-pen
(one foundation), while Ch’eng Yi developed a dualistic metaphysics of li
(principle) and ch’i (material force). On the surface Chu Hsi was the follower
of the Ch’eng brothers, but in fact he was only following the lead of Ch’eng
Yi, and promoted the socalled Li-hsüeh (learning of principles) in the narrower
sense. His younger contemporary negation-complete Neo-Confucianism 602 602 Lu Hsiang-shan (1139–93) objected to
Chu’s method of looking for principles among things. He urged us to realize
principle within one’s own mind, went back to Mencius’s teaching to establish
the greater part of the self first, and promoted the so-called hsin-hsüeh
(learning of the mind). But Chu Hsi’s commentaries on the Four Books were
adopted as the basis of civil service examinations in the Yüan dynasty; Lu’s
views were largely ignored until there were revived in the Ming dynasty
(1368–1644) by Wang Yang-ming (1472–1529), who identified the mind with
principle and advocated that knowledge and action are one. Since Lu–Wang’s
thoughts were closer to Mencius, who was honored to have represented the
orthodox line of transmission of the Way, Mou Tsung-san advanced the theory
that Chu Hsi was the side branch taking over the orthodoxy; he also believed
that Hu Hung (1100–55) and Liu Tsung-chou (1578–1645) developed a third branch
of Neo-Confucianism in addition to that of Ch’eng and Chu and that of Lu and
Wang. His views have generated many controversies. Sung–Ming Neo-Confucianism
was hailed as creating the second golden period of Chinese philosophy since the
late Chou. Huang Tsung-hsi (1610–95), a pupil of Liu Tsung-chou and the last
important figure in Sung–Ming Neo-Confucianism, extensively studied the
movement and wrote essential works on it.
neo-Kantianism, the
diverse Kantian movement that emerged within German philosophy in the 1860s,
gained a strong academic foothold in the 1870s, reached its height during the
three decades prior to World War I, and disappeared with the rise of Nazism.
The movement was initially focused on renewed study and elaboration of Kant’s
epistemology in response to the growing epistemic authority of the natural
sciences and as an alternative to both Hegelian and speculative idealism and
the emerging materialism of, among others, Ludwig Büchner (1824–99). Later
neo-Kantianism explored Kant’s whole philosophy, applied his critical method to
disciplines other than the natural sciences, and developed its own
philosophical systems. Some originators and/or early contributors were Kuno
Fischer (1824–1907), Hermann von Helmholtz (1821–94), Friedrich Albert Lange
(1828–75), Eduard Zeller (1814–1908), and Otto Liebmann (1840–1912), whose Kant
und die Epigonen (1865) repeatedly stated what became a neoKantian motto, “Back
to Kant!” Several forms of neo-Kantianism are to be distinguished. T. K.
Oesterreich (1880–1949), in Friedrich Ueberwegs Grundriss der Geschichte der
Philosophie (“F.U.’s Compendium of the History of Philosophy,” 1923), developed
the standard, somewhat chronological, classification: (1) The physiological
neo-Kantianism of Helmholtz and Lange, who claimed that physiology is
“developed or corrected Kantianism.” (2) The metaphysical neo-Kantianism of the
later Liebmann, who argued for a Kantian “critical metaphysics” (beyond
epistemology) in the form of “hypotheses” about the essence of things. (3) The
realist neo-Kantianism of Alois Riehl (1844–1924), who emphasized the real
existence of Kant’s thing-in-itself. (4) The logistic-methodological
neo-Kantianism of the Marburg School of Hermann Cohen (1842–1918) and Paul
Natorp (1854–1924). (5) The axiological neo-Kantianism of the Baden or
Southwest German School of Windelband (1848–1915) and Heinrich Rickert
(1863–1936). (6) The relativistic neo-Kantianism of Georg Simmel (1858–1918),
who argued for Kantian categories relative to individuals and cultures. (7) The
psychological neo-Kantianism of Leonard Nelson (1882–1927), originator of the
Göttingen School; also known as the neo-Friesian School, after Jakob Friedrich
Fries (1773–1843), Nelson’s self-proclaimed precursor. Like Fries, Nelson held
that Kantian a priori principles cannot be transcendentally justified, but can
be discovered only through introspection. Oesterreich’s classification has been
narrowed or modified, partly because of conflicting views on how distinctly
“Kantian” a philosopher must have been to be called “neo-Kantian.” The very
term ‘neo-Kantianism’ has even been called into question, as suggesting real
intellectual commonality where little or none is to be found. There is,
however, growing consensus that Marneo-Euclidean geometry neo-Kantianism
603 603 burg and Baden neo-Kantianism
were the most important and influential. Marburg School. Its founder, Cohen,
developed its characteristic Kantian idealism of the natural sciences by
arguing that physical objects are truly known only through the laws of these
sciences and that these laws presuppose the application of Kantian a priori
principles and concepts. Cohen elaborated this idealism by eliminating Kant’s
dualism of sensibility and understanding, claiming that space and time are construction
methods of “pure thought” rather than a priori forms of perception and that the
notion of any “given” (perceptual data) prior to the “activity” of “pure
thought” is meaningless. Accordingly, Cohen reformulated Kant’s thing-in-itself
as the regulative idea that the mathematical description of the world can
always be improved. Cohen also emphasized that “pure thought” refers not to
individual consciousess – on his account Kant had not yet sufficiently left
behind a “subject–object” epistemology – but rather to the content of his own
system of a priori principles, which he saw as subject to change with the
progress of science. Just as Cohen held that epistemology must be based on the
“fact of science,” he argued, in a decisive step beyond Kant, that ethics must
transcendentally deduce both the moral law and the ideal moral subject from a
humanistic science – more specifically, from jurisprudence’s notion of the
legal person. This analysis led to the view that the moral law demands that all
institutions, including economic enterprises, become democratic – so that they
display unified wills and intentions as transcendental conditions of the legal
person – and that all individuals become colegislators. Thus Cohen arrived at
his frequently cited claim that Kant “is the true and real originator of German
socialism.” Other important Marburg Kantians were Cohen’s colleague Natorp,
best known for his studies on Plato and philosophy of education, and their
students Karl Vorländer (1860–1928), who focused on Kantian socialist ethics as
a corrective of orthodox Marxism, and Ernst Cassirer (1874–1945). Baden School.
The basic task of philosophy and its transcendental method is seen as
identifying universal values that make possible culture in its varied expressions.
This focus is evident in Windelband’s influential insight that the natural
sciences seek to formulate general laws – nomothetic knowledge – while the
historical sciences seek to describe unique events – idiographic knowledge.
This distinction is based on the values (interests) of mastery of nature and
understanding and reliving the unique past in order to affirm our
individuality. Windelband’s view of the historical sciences as idiographic
raised the problem of selection central to his successor Rickert’s writings:
How can historians objectively determine which individual events are
historically significant? Rickert argued that this selection must be based on
the values that are generally recognized within the cultures under
investigation, not on the values of historians themselves. Rickert also
developed the transcendental argument that the objectivity of the historical
sciences necessitates the assumption that the generally recognized values of
different cultures approximate in various degrees universally valid values.
This argument was rejected by Weber, whose methodological work was greatly
indebted to Rickert. CASSIRER, COHEN,
KANT, LANGE, TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENT, WINDELBAND. H.v.d.L. Neoplatonism, that
period of Platonism following on the new impetus provided by the philosophical
speculations of Plotinus (A.D. 204–69). It extends, as a minimum, to the
closing of the Platonic School in Athens by Justinian in 529, but maximally
through Byzantium, with such figures as Michael Psellus (1018–78) and Pletho
(c.1360–1452), the Renaissance (Ficino, Pico, and the Florentine Academy), and
the early modern period (the Cambridge Platonists, Thomas Taylor), to the
advent of the “scientific” study of the works of Plato with Schleiermacher
(1768–1834) at the beginning of the nineteenth century. The term was formerly
also used to characterize the whole period from the Old Academy of Plato’s
immediate successors, Speusippus and Xenocrates, through what is now termed
Middle Platonism (c.80 B.C.–A.D. 220), down to Plotinus. This account confines
itself to the “minimum” interpretation. Neoplatonism proper may be divided into
three main periods: that of Plotinus and his immediate followers (third
century); the “Syrian” School of Iamblichus and his followers (fourth century);
and the “Athenian” School begun by Plutarch of Athens, and including Syrianus,
Proclus, and their successors, down to Damascius (fifth–sixth centuries).
Plotinus and his school. Plotinus’s innovations in Platonism (developed in his
essays, the Enneads, collected and edited by his pupil Porphyry after his
death), are mainly two: (a) above Neoplatonism Neoplatonism 604 604 the traditional supreme principle of
earlier Platonism (and Aristotelianism), a self-thinking intellect, which was
also regarded as true being, he postulated a principle superior to intellect
and being, totally unitary and simple (“the One”); (b) he saw reality as a
series of levels (One, Intelligence, Soul), each higher one outflowing or
radiating into the next lower, while still remaining unaffected in itself, and
the lower ones fixing themselves in being by somehow “reflecting back” upon
their priors. This eternal process gives the universe its existence and
character. Intelligence operates in a state of non-temporal simultaneity, holding
within itself the “forms” of all things. Soul, in turn, generates time, and
receives the forms into itself as “reason principles” (logoi). Our physical
three-dimensional world is the result of the lower aspect of Soul (nature)
projecting itself upon a kind of negative field of force, which Plotinus calls
“matter.” Matter has no positive existence, but is simply the receptacle for
the unfolding of Soul in its lowest aspect, which projects the forms in
three-dimensional space. Plotinus often speaks of matter as “evil” (e.g.
Enneads II.8), and of the Soul as suffering a “fall” (e.g. Enneads V.1, 1), but
in fact he sees the whole cosmic process as an inevitable result of the
superabundant productivity of the One, and thus “the best of all possible
worlds.” Plotinus was himself a mystic, but he arrived at his philosophical
conclusions by perfectly logical means, and he had not much use for either
traditional religion or any of the more recent superstitions. His immediate
pupils, Amelius (c.225–90) and Porphyry (234–c.305), while somewhat more
hospitable to these, remained largely true to his philosophy (though Amelius
had a weakness for triadic elaborations in metaphysics). Porphyry was to have
wide influence, both in the Latin West (through such men as Marius Victorinus,
Augustine, and Boethius), and in the Greek East (and even, through
translations, on medieval Islam), as the founder of the Neoplatonic tradition
of commentary on both Plato and Aristotle, but it is mainly as an expounder of
Plotinus’s philosophy that he is known. He added little that is distinctive,
though that little is currently becoming better appreciated. Iamblichus and the
Syrian School. Iamblichus (c.245–325), descendant of an old Syrian noble
family, was a pupil of Porphyry’s, but dissented from him on various important
issues. He set up his own school in Apamea in Syria, and attracted many pupils.
One chief point of dissent was the role of theurgy (really just magic, with
philosophical underpinnings, but not unlike Christian sacramental theology).
Iamblichus claimed, as against Porphyry, that philosophical reasoning alone
could not attain the highest degree of enlightenment, without the aid of
theurgic rites, and his view on this was followed by all later Platonists. He
also produced a metaphysical scheme far more elaborate than Plotinus’s, by a
Scholastic filling in, normally with systems of triads, of gaps in the “chain
of being” left by Plotinus’s more fluid and dynamic approach to philosophy. For
instance, he postulated two Ones, one completely transcendent, the other the
source of all creation, thus “resolving” a tension in Plotinus’s metaphysics.
Iamblichus was also concerned to fit as many of the traditional gods as
possible into his system, which later attracted the attention of the Emperor
Julian, who based himself on Iamblichus when attempting to set up a Hellenic
religion to rival Christianity, a project which, however, died with him in 363.
The Athenian School. The precise links between the pupils of Iamblichus and
Plutarch (d.432), founder of the Athenian School, remain obscure, but the
Athenians always retained a great respect for the Syrian. Plutarch himself is a
dim figure, but Syrianus (c.370–437), though little of his writings survives,
can be seen from constant references to him by his pupil Proclus (412– 85) to
be a major figure, and the source of most of Proclus’s metaphysical
elaborations. The Athenians essentially developed and systematized further the
doctrines of Iamblichus, creating new levels of divinity (e.g. intelligibleintellectual
gods, and “henads” in the realm of the One – though they rejected the two
Ones), this process reaching its culmination in the thought of the last head of
the Athenian Academy, Damascius (c.456–540). The drive to systematize reality
and to objectivize concepts, exhibited most dramatically in Proclus’s Elements
of Theology, is a lasting legacy of the later Neoplatonists, and had a
significant influence on the thought, among others, of Hegel.
neo-Scholasticism, the
movement given impetus Neoplatonism, Islamic neo-Scholasticism 605 605 by Pope Leo XIII’s encyclical Aeterni
Patris (1879), which, while stressing Aquinas, was a general recommendation of
the study of medieval Scholasticism as a source for the solution of vexing
modern problems. Leo assumed that there was a doctrine common to Aquinas,
Bonaventure, Albertus Magnus, and Duns Scotus, and that Aquinas was a
preeminent spokesman of the common view. Maurice De Wulf employed the phrase
‘perennial philosophy’ to designate this common medieval core as well as what
of Scholasticism is relevant to later times. Historians like Mandonnet,
Grabmann, and Gilson soon contested the idea that there was a single medieval
doctrine and drew attention to the profound differences between the great medieval
masters. The discussion of Christian philosophy precipitated by Brehier in 1931
generated a variety of suggestions as to what medieval thinkers and later
Christian philosophers have in common, but this was quite different from the
assumption of Aeterni Patris. The pedagogical directives of this and later
encyclicals brought about a revival of Thomism rather than of Scholasticism,
generally in seminaries, ecclesiastical colleges, and Catholic universities.
Louvain’s Higher Institute of Philosophy under the direction of Cardinal
Mercier and its Revue de Philosophie Néoscolastique were among the first fruits
of the Thomistic revival. The studia generalia of the Dominican order continued
at a new pace, the Saulchoir publishing the Revue thomiste. In graduate centers
in Milan, Madrid, Latin America, Paris, and Rome, men were trained for the task
of teaching in colleges and seminaries, and scholarly research began to
flourish as well. The Leonine edition of the writings of Aquinas was soon
joined by new critical editions of Bonaventure, Duns Scotus, and Ockham, as
well as Albertus Magnus. Medieval studies in the broader sense gained from the
quest for manuscripts and the growth of paleography and codicology. Besides the
historians mentioned above, Jacques Maritain (1882–1973), a layman and convert
to Catholicism, did much both in his native France and in the United States to
promote the study of Aquinas. The Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies at
Toronto, with Gilson regularly and Maritain frequently in residence, became a
source of college and university teachers in Canada and the United States, as
Louvain and, in Rome, the Jesuit Gregorianum and the Dominican Angelicum
already were. In the 1940s Americans took doctorates in theology and philosophy
at Laval in Quebec and soon the influence of Charles De Koninck was felt.
Jesuits at St. Louis University began to publish The Modern Schoolman,
Dominicans in Washington The Thomist, and the American Catholic Philosophical
Association The New Scholasticism. The School of Philosophy at Catholic
University, long the primary domestic source of professors and scholars, was
complemented by graduate programs at St. Louis, Georgetown, Notre Dame,
Fordham, and Marquette. In the golden period of the Thomistic revival in the
United States, from the 1930s until the end of the Vatican Council II in 1965,
there were varieties of Thomism based on the variety of views on the relation
between philosophy and science. By the 1960s Thomistic philosophy was a
prominent part of the curriculum of all Catholic colleges and universities. By
1970, it had all but disappeared under the mistaken notion that this was the
intent of Vatican II. This had the effect of releasing Aquinas into the wider
philosophical world. AQUINAS,
NEO-THOMISM, SCHOLASTICISM. R.M. Neo-Taoism, in Chinese, hsüan-hsüeh (‘Profound
Learning’, ‘Mysterious Learning’, or ‘Dark Learning’), a broad, multifaceted
revival of Taoist learning that dominated Chinese philosophy from the third to
the sixth century A.D. Literally ‘dark red’, hsüan is used in the Lao Tzu (Tao
Te Ching) to describe the sublime mystery of the tao. Historically, hsüan-hsüeh
formed a major topic of “Pure Conversation” (ch’ing-t’an), where scholars in a
time of political upheaval sought to arrest the perceived decline of the tao.
When the Wei dynasty replaced the Han in A.D. 220, a first wave of Neo-Taoist
philosophers represented by Ho Yen (c.190–249) and Wang Pi (226–49) radically
reinterpreted the classical heritage to bring to light its profound meaning.
The Confucian orthodoxy – as distinguished from the original teachings of
Confucius – was deemed ineffectual and an obstacle to renewal. One of the most
important debates in Profound Learning – the debate on “words and meaning” –
criticizes Han scholarship for its literal imagination and confronts the
question of interpretation. Words are necessary but not sufficient for
understanding. The ancient sages had a unified view of the Tao, articulated
most clearly in the I-Ching, Lao Tzu, and Chuang Tzu, but distorted by Han
scholars. Most Neo-Taoists concentrated on these “Three Profound Treatises”
(san-hsüan). Wang Pi is best known for his commentaries on the I-Ching and the
Lao Tzu; and Kuo Hsiang (d.312), another Neo-Taoism Neo-Taoism 606 606 leading Neo-Taoist, is arguably the
most important Chuang Tzu commentator in Chinese history. The tao is the source
of all being, but against identifying the tao with a creator “heaven” or an
original “vital energy” (ch’i), Wang Pi argues that being originates from “non-being”
(wu). The concept of non-being, taken from the Lao Tzu, brings out the
transcendence of the tao. Nameless and without form, the tao as such can be
described only negatively as wu, literally “not having” any characteristics. In
contrast, for Kuo Hsiang, non-being does not explain the origin of being
because, as entirely conceptual, it cannot create anything. If non-being cannot
bring forth being, and if the idea of a creator remains problematic, the only
alternative is to regard the created order as coming into existence
spontaneously. This implies that being is eternal. Particular beings can be
traced to contingent causes, but ultimately the origin of being can be
understood only in terms of a process of “selftransformation.” Chinese sources
often contrast Wang Pi’s “valuing non-being” (kuei-wu) with Kuo Hsiang’s
“exaltation of being” (ch’ung-yu). In ethics and politics, Wang stresses that
the tao is manifest in nature as constant principles (li). This is what the
classics mean by tzu-jan, naturalness or literally what is of itself so. The
hierarchical structure of sociopolitical relations also has a basis in the
order of nature. While Wang emphasizes unity, Kuo Hsiang champions diversity.
The principle of nature dictates that everyone has a particular “share” of
vital energy, the creative power of the tao that determines one’s physical,
intellectual, and moral capacity. Individual differences ought to be accepted,
but do not warrant value discrimination. Each individual is in principle
complete in his/her own way, and constitutes an indispensable part in a larger
whole. Taoist ethics thus consists in being true to oneself, and nourishing
one’s nature. In government, naturalness finds expression in non-action
(wu-wei), which may be contrasted with Legalist policies emphasizing punishment
and control. For Wang Pi, wu-wei aims at preserving the natural order so that
the myriad things can flourish. Practically, it involves the elimination of
willful intervention and a return to “emptiness and quiescence”; i.e., freedom
from the dictates of desire and a life of guileless simplicity. Not to be
confused with total inaction, according to Kuo Hsiang, wu-weisignifies a mode
of being that fully uses one’s natural endowment. When one is guided by
inherent moral principles, there is no place for artificiality or
self-deception in the Taoist way of life. Ethical purity does not entail
renunciation. Though the sage finds himself along the corridors of power, he
safeguards his nature and remains empty of desire. In government, the sage
ruler naturally reduces arbitrary restrictions, adjusts policies to suit
changing needs, identifies the right people for office, and generally creates
an environment in which all under heaven can dwell in peace and realize their
potential. Ho Yen died a victim of political intrigue, at the close of the
Cheng-shih reign period (240–49) of the Wei dynasty. Wang Pi died later in the
same year. Historians refer to “Cheng-shih hsüanhsüeh” to mark the first phase
of Neo-Taoism. Later, political power was controlled by the Ssuma family, who
eventually founded the Chin dynasty in A.D. 265. During the Wei–Chin
transition, a group of intellectuals, the “Seven Worthies of the Bamboo Grove,”
came to represent the voice of Profound Learning. Among them, Hsi K’ang
(223–62), Juan Chi (210–63), and Hsiang Hsiu (c.227–80) are of particular
interest to philosophy. In different ways, they look to naturalness as a basis
for renewal. Debates in Profound Learning often revolve around the relationship
between “orthodox teachings” (ming-chiao) and tzu-jan. For Wang Pi and Kuo
Hsiang, government and society should ideally conform to nature. Both Hsi K’ang
and Juan Chi found ming-chiao impinging on naturalness. This also gave impetus
to the development of a counterculture. Central to this is the place of emotion
in the ethical life. Ho Yen is credited with the view that sages are without
emotions (ch’ing), whose exceptional ch’i-endowment translates into a purity of
being that excludes emotional disturbance. Hsi K’ang also values dispassion,
and Hsiang Hsiu urges putting passion under the rule of ritual; but many
appreciated strong emotion as a sign of authenticity, which often contravened
orthodox teachings. As Pure Conversation gained currency, it became fashionable
to give free rein to one’s impulses; and many hoped to establish a reputation
by opposing orthodoxy. The debate on naturalness raises the further question of
talent or capacity (ts’ai) and its relationship to human nature (hsing). In
Profound Learning, four distinct positions have been proposed: that talent and
nature are identical (t’ung); different (i); harmonious (ho); and separate
(li). This is important because the right talent must be identified to serve
political ends. In the early fourth century, the Chin dynasty had to flee its
capital and rebuild in south China. As the literati resettled, they looked back
to the Neo-Taoism Neo-Taoism 607 607
time of Ho Yen and Wang Pi as the golden age of Profound Learning. Although
Pure Conversation continued with undiminished vigor, it did not introduce many
new ideas. As it entered its last phase, another Taoist work, the Lieh-tzu,
came to rival the “Three Profound Treatises.” Chang Chan (c.330–400) wrote an
important commentary on the work, which not only recapitulated many of the
ideas that spanned the spectrum of Neo-Taoist philosophy but also borrowed
Buddhist ideas. From the fourth century onward, Buddhist masters frequently
engaged in Pure Conversation and challenged hsüan-hsüeh scholars at their own
game. BUDDHISM, CHINESE LEGALISM,
CHINESE PHILOSOPHY. A.K.L.C. Neo-Thomism, a philosophical-theological movement
in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries manifesting a revival of interest in
Aquinas. It was stimulated by Pope Leo XIII’s encyclical Aeterni Patris (1879)
calling for a renewed emphasis on the teaching of Thomistic principles to meet
the intellectual and social challenges of modernity. The movement reached its
peak in the 1950s, though its influence continues to be seen in organizations
such as the American Catholic Philosophical Association. Among its major
figures are Joseph Kleutgen, Désiré Mercier, Joseph Maréchal, Pierre Rousselot,
Réginald Garrigou-LaGrange, Martin Grabmann, M.-D. Chenu, Jacques Maritain,
Étienne Gilson, Yves R. Simon, Josef Pieper, Karl Rahner, Cornelio Fabro,
Emerich Coreth, Bernard Lonergan, and W. Norris Clarke. Few, if any, of these
figures have described themselves as NeoThomists; some explicitly rejected the
designation. Neo-Thomists have little in common except their commitment to
Aquinas and his relevance to the contemporary world. Their interest produced a
more historically accurate understanding of Aquinas and his contribution to
medieval thought (Grabmann, Gilson, Chenu), including a previously ignored use
of the Platonic metaphysics of participation (Fabro). This richer understanding
of Aquinas, as forging a creative synthesis in the midst of competing
traditions, has made arguing for his relevance easier. Those Neo-Thomists who
were suspicious of modernity produced fresh readings of Aquinas’s texts applied
to contemporary problems (Pieper, Gilson). Their influence can be seen in the
revival of virtue theory and the work of Alasdair MacIntyre. Others sought to
develop Aquinas’s thought with the aid of later Thomists (Maritain, Simon) and
incorporated the interpretations of Counter-Reformation Thomists, such as
Cajetan and Jean Poinsot, to produce more sophisticated, and controversial,
accounts of the intelligence, intentionality, semiotics, and practical
knowledge. Those Neo-Thomists willing to engage modern thought on its own terms
interpreted modern philosophy sympathetically using the principles of Aquinas
(Maréchal, Lonergan, Clarke), seeking dialogue rather than confrontation.
However, some readings of Aquinas are so thoroughly integrated into modern
philosophy that they can seem assimilated (Rahner, Coreth); their highly
individualized metaphysics inspired as much by other philosophical influences,
especially Heidegger, as Aquinas. Some of the labels currently used among
Neo-Thomists suggest a division in the movement over critical, postKantian
methodology. ‘Existential Thomism’ is used for those who emphasize both the
real distinction between essence and existence and the role of the sensible in
the mind’s first grasp of being. ‘Transcendental Thomism’ applies to figures
like Maréchal, Rousselot, Rahner, and Coreth who rely upon the inherent
dynamism of the mind toward the real, rooted in Aquinas’s theory of the active
intellect, from which to deduce their metaphysics of being. AQUINAS, GILSON, MARITAIN, MERCIER, THOMISM.
D.W.H. Neumann, John von.VON NEUMANN. neural net.CONNECTIONISM. neural network
modeling.CONNECTIONISM. Neurath, Otto.VIENNA CIRCLE. neurophilosophy.CHURCHLAND,
PATRICIA. neuroscience.COGNITIVE SCIENCE. neustic.PRESCRIPTIVISM.
neutrality.LIBERALISM. neutral monism.PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. New Academy, the name
given the Academy, the school founded by Plato in Athens, during the time it
was controlled by Academic Skeptics after about 265 B.C. Its principal leaders
in this period were Arcesilaus (315–242) and Carneades (219– 129); our most
accessible source for the New Academy is Cicero’s Academica. A master of
logical techniques such as sorites Neo-Thomism New Academy 608 608 (which he learned from Diodorus),
Arcesilaus attempted to revive the dialectic of Plato, using it to achieve the
suspension of belief he learned to value from Pyrrho. Later, and especially
under the leadership of Carneades, the New Academy developed a special
relationship with Stoicism: as the Stoics found new ways to defend their
doctrine of the criterion, Carneades found new ways to refute it in the Stoics’
own terms. Carneades’ visit to Rome in 155 B.C. with a Stoic and a Peripatetic
marks the beginning of Rome’s interest in Greek philosophy. His anti-Stoic
arguments were recorded by his successor Clitomachus (d. c.110 B.C.), whose
work is known to us through summaries in Cicero. Clitomachus was succeeded by
Philo of Larisa (c.160–79 B.C.), who was the teacher of Antiochus of Ascalon
(c.130–c.67 B.C.). Philo later attempted to reconcile the Old and the New
Academy by softening the Skepticism of the New and by fostering a Skeptical
reading of Plato. Angered by this, Antiochus broke away in about 87 B.C. to
found what he called the Old Academy, which is now considered to be the
beginning of Middle Platonism. Probably about the same time, Aenesidemus (dates
unknown) revived the strict Skepticism of Pyrrho and founded the school that is
known to us through the work of Sextus Empiricus. Academic Skepticism differed
from Pyrrhonism in its sharp focus on Stoic positions, and possibly in allowing
for a weak assent (as opposed to belief, which they suspended) in what is
probable; and Pyrrhonians accused Academic Skeptics of being dogmatic in their
rejection of the possibility of knowledge. The New Academy had a major
influence on the development of modern philosophy, most conspicuously through
Hume, who considered that his brand of mitigated skepticism belonged to this
school.
ACADEMY, ISLAMIC NEOPLATONISM,
SKEPTICS. P.Wo. Newcomb’s paradox, a conflict between two widely accepted
principles of rational decision, arising in the following decision problem,
known as Newcomb’s problem. Two boxes are before you. The first contains either
$1,000,000 or nothing. The second contains $1,000. You may take the first box
alone or both boxes. Someone with uncanny foresight has predicted your choice
and fixed the content of the first box according to his prediction. If he has
predicted that you will take only the first box, he has put $1,000,000 in that
box; and if he has predicted that you will take both boxes, he has left the
first box empty. The expected utility of an option is commonly obtained by
multiplying the utility of its possible outcomes by their probabilities given
the option, and then adding the products. Because the predictor is reliable,
the probability that you receive $1,000,000 given that you take only the first
box is high, whereas the probability that you receive $1,001,000 given that you
take both boxes is low. Accordingly, the expected utility of taking only the
first box is greater than the expected utility of taking both boxes. Therefore
the principle of maximizing expected utility says to take only the first box.
However, the principle of dominance says that if the states determining the
outcomes of options are causally independent of the options, and there is one
option that is better than the others in each state, then you should adopt it.
Since your choice does not causally influence the contents of the first box,
and since choosing both boxes yields $1,000 in addition to the contents of the
first box whatever they are, the principle says to take both boxes. Newcomb’s
paradox is named after its formulator, William Newcomb. Nozick publicized it in
“Newcomb’s Problem and Two Principles of Choice” (1969). Many theorists have
responded to the paradox by changing the definition of the expected utility of
an option so that it is sensitive to the causal influence of the option on the
states that determine its outcome, but is insensitive to the evidential bearing
of the option on those states. DECISION
THEORY, UTILITARIANISM. P.We. Newcomb’s problem.NEWCOMB’S PARADOX. Newman, John
Henry (1801–90), English prelate and philosopher of religion. As fellow at
Oriel College, Oxford, he was a prominent member of the Anglican Oxford
Movement. He became a Roman Catholic in 1845, took holy orders in 1847, and was
made a cardinal in 1879. His most important philosophical work is the Grammar
of Assent (1870). Here Newman explored the difference between formal reasoning
and the informal or natural movement of the mind in discerning the truth about
the concrete and historical. Concrete reasoning in the mode of natural
inference is implicit and unreflective; it deals not with general principles as
such but with their employment in particular circumstances. Thus a scientist
must judge whether the phenomenon he confronts is a novel significant datum, a
coincidence, or merely an insignificant variation in the data. The acquired
capacity to make judgments of Newcomb’s paradox Newman, John Henry 609 609 this sort Newman called the illative
sense, an intellectual skill shaped by experience and personal insight and
generally limited for individuals to particular fields of endeavor. The
illative sense makes possible a judgment of certitude about the matter
considered, even though the formal argument that partially outlines the process
possesses only objective probability for the novice. Hence probability is not
necessarily opposed to certitude. In becoming aware of its tacit dimension,
Newman spoke of recognizing a mode of informal inference. He distinguished such
reasoning, which, by virtue of the illative sense, culminates in a judgment of
certitude about the way things are (real assent), from formal reasoning
conditioned by the certainty or probability of the premises, which assents to
the conclusion thus conditioned (notional assent). In real assent, the
proposition functions to “image” the reality, to make its reality present. In
the Development of Christian Doctrine (1845), Newman analyzed the ways in which
some ideas unfold themselves only through historical development, within a
tradition of inquiry. He sought to delineate the common pattern of such
development in politics, science, philosophy, and religion. Although his focal
interest was in how religious doctrines develop, he emphasizes the general
character of such a pattern of progressive articulation. F.J.C. New Realism, an
early twentieth-century revival, both in England and in the United States, of
various forms of realism in reaction to the dominant idealisms inherited from
the nineteenth century. In America this revival took a cooperative form when
six philosophers (Ralph Barton Perry, Edwin Holt, William Pepperell Montague,
Walter Pitkin, Edward Spaulding, and Walter Marvin) published “A Program and
First Platform of Six Realists” (1910), followed two years later by the
cooperative volume The New Realism, in which each authored an essay. This
volume gave rise to the designation ‘New Realists’ for these six philosophers.
Although they clearly disagreed on many particulars, they concurred on several
matters of philosophical style and epistemological substance. Procedurally they
endorsed a cooperative and piecemeal approach to philosophical problems, and
they were constitutionally inclined to a closeness of analysis that would
prepare the way for later philosophical tendencies. Substantively they agreed
on several epistemological stances central to the refutation of idealism. Among
the doctrines in the New Realist platform were the rejection of the fundamental
character of epistemology; the view that the entities investigated in logic,
mathematics, and science are not “mental” in any ordinary sense; the view that the
things known are not the products of the knowing relation nor in any
fundamental sense conditioned by their being known; and the view that the
objects known are immediately and directly present to consciousness while being
independent of that relation. New Realism was a version of direct realism,
which viewed the notions of mediation and representation in knowledge as
opening gambits on the slippery slope to idealism. Their refutation of idealism
focused on pointing out the fallacy of moving from the truism that every object
of knowledge is known to the claim that its being consists in its being known.
That we are obviously at the center of what we know entails nothing about the
nature of what we know. Perry dubbed this fact “the egocentric predicament,”
and supplemented this observation with arguments to the effect that the objects
of knowledge are in fact independent of the knowing relation. New Realism as a
version of direct realism had as its primary conceptual obstacle “the facts of
relativity,” i.e., error, illusion, perceptual variation, and valuation.
Dealing with these phenomena without invoking “mental intermediaries” proved to
be the stumbling block, and New Realism soon gave way to a second cooperative
venture by another group of American philosophers that came to be known as
Critical Realism. The term ‘new realism’ is also occasionally used with regard
to those British philosophers (principal among them Moore and Russell)
similarly involved in refuting idealism. Although individually more significant
than the American group, theirs was not a cooperative effort, so the group term
came to have primarily an American referent.
CRITICAL REALISM,
IDEALISM, PERCEPTION. C.F.D. new riddle of induction.GRUE PARADOX. new theory
of reference.PUTNAM. Newton, Sir Isaac (1642–1727), English physicist and
mathematician, one of the greatest scientists of all time. Born in Woolsthorpe,
Lincolnshire, he attended Cambridge University, receiving the B.A. in 1665; he
became a fellow of Trinity in New Realism Newton, Sir Isaac 610 610 1667 and Lucasian Professor of
Mathematics in 1669. He was elected fellow of the Royal Society in 1671 and
served as its president from 1703 until his death. In 1696 he was appointed
warden of the mint. In his later years he was involved in political and
governmental affairs rather than in active scientific work. A sensitive,
secretive person, he was prone to irascibility – most notably in a dispute with
Leibniz over priority of invention of the calculus. His unparalleled scientific
accomplishments overshadow a deep and sustained interest in ancient chronology,
biblical study, theology, and alchemy. In his early twenties Newton’s genius
asserted itself in an astonishing period of mathematical and experimental
creativity. In the years 1664– 67, he discovered the binomial theorem; the
“method of fluxions” (calculus); the principle of the composition of light; and
fundamentals of his theory of universal gravitation. Newton’s masterpiece,
Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (“The Mathematical Principles of
Natural Philosophy”), appeared in 1687. This work sets forth the mathematical
laws of physics and “the system of the world.” Its exposition is modeled on
Euclidean geometry: propositions are demonstrated mathematically from definitions
and mathematical axioms. The world system consists of material bodies (masses
composed of hard particles) at rest or in motion and interacting according to
three axioms or laws of motion: (1) Every body continues in its state of rest
or of uniform motion in a straight line unless it is compelled to change that
state by forces impressed upon it. (2) The change of motion is proportional to
the motive force impressed and is made in the direction of the straight line in
which that force is impressed. [Here, the impressed force equals mass times the
rate of change of velocity, i.e., acceleration. Hence the familiar formula, F %
ma.] (3) To every action there is always opposed an equal reaction; or, the
mutual action of two bodies upon each other is always equal and directed to
contrary parts. Newton’s general law of gravitation (in modern restatement) is:
Every particle of matter attracts every other particle with a force varying
directly as the product of their masses and inversely as the square of the distance
between them. The statement of the laws of motion is preceded by an equally
famous scholium in which Newton enunciates the ultimate conditions of his
universal system: absolute time, space, place, and motion. He speaks of these
as independently existing “quantities” according to which true measurements of
bodies and motions can be made as distinct from relative “sensible measures”
and apparent observations. Newton seems to have thought that his system of
mathematical principles presupposed and is validated by the absolute framework.
The scholium has been the subject of much critical discussion. The main problem
concerns the justification of the absolute framework. Newton commends adherence
to experimental observation and induction for advancing scientific knowledge,
and he rejects speculative hypotheses. But absolute time and space are not
observable. (In the scholium Newton did offer a renowned experiment using a
rotating pail of water as evidence for distinguishing true and apparent motions
and proof of absolute motion.) It has been remarked that conflicting strains of
a rationalism (anticipating Kant) and empiricism (anticipating Hume) are
present in Newton’s conception of science. Some of these issues are also
evident in Newton’s Optics (1704, especially the fourth edition, 1730), which
includes a series of suggestive “Queries” on the nature of light, gravity,
matter, scientific method, and God. The triumphant reception given to Newton’s
Principia in England and on the Continent led to idealization of the man and
his work. Thus Alexander Pope’s famous epitaph: Nature and Nature’s laws lay
hid in night; God said, “Let Newton be!” and all was light. The term
‘Newtonian’, then, denoted the view of nature as a universal system of
mathematical reason and order divinely created and administered. The metaphor
of a “universal machine” was frequently applied. The view is central in the
eighteenth-century Enlightenment, inspiring a religion of reason and the
scientific study of society and the human mind. More narrowly, ‘Newtonian’
suggests a reduction of any subject matter to an ontology of individual
particles and the laws and basic terms of mechanics: mass, length, and
time. FIELD THEORY, PHILOSOPHY OF
SCIENCE, QUANTUM MECHANICS, SPACE, TIME. H.S.T. Newtonian.NEWTON. Newton, Sir
Isaac Newtonian 611 611 Nicholas
Kryfts.NICHOLAS OF CUSA. Nicholas of Autrecourt (c.1300–after 1350), French
philosopher and theologian. Born in Autrecourt, he was educated at Paris and
earned bachelor’s degrees in theology and law and a master’s degree in arts.
After a list of propositions from his writings was condemned in 1346, he was
sentenced to burn his works publicly and recant, which he did in Paris the
following year. He was appointed dean of Metz cathedral in 1350. Nicholas’s ecclesiastical
troubles arose partly from nine letters (two of which survive) which reduce to
absurdity the view that appearances provide a sufficient basis for certain and
evident knowledge. On the contrary, except for “certitude of the faith,” we can
be certain only of what is equivalent or reducible to the principle of
noncontradiction. He accepts as a consequence of this that we can never validly
infer the existence of one distinct thing from another, including the existence
of substances from qualities, or causes from effects. Indeed, he finds that “in
the whole of his natural philosophy and metaphysics, Aristotle had such
[evident] certainty of scarcely two conclusions, and perhaps not even of one.”
Nicholas devotes another work, the Exigit ordo executionis (also known as The
Universal Treatise), to an extended critique of Aristotelianism. It attacks
what seemed to him the blind adherence given by his contemporaries to Aristotle
and Averroes, showing that the opposite of many conclusions alleged to have
been demonstrated by the Philosopher – e.g., on the divisibility of continua,
the reality of motion, and the truth of appearances – are just as evident or
apparent as those conclusions themselves. Because so few of his writings are
extant, however, it is difficult to ascertain just what Nicholas’s own views
were. Likewise, the reasons for his condemnation are not well understood,
although recent studies have suggested that his troubles might have been due to
a reaction to certain ideas that he appropriated from English theologians, such
as Adam de Wodeham. Nicholas’s views elicited comment not only from church
authorities, but also from other philosophers, including Buridan, Marsilius of
Inghen, Albert of Saxony, and Nicholas of Oresme. Despite a few surface
similarities, however, there is no evidence that his teachings on certainty or
causality had any influence on modern philosophers, such as Descartes or
Hume.
ARISTOTLE, OCKHAM,
RATIONALISM. J.A.Z. Nicholas of Cusa, also called Nicolaus Cusanus, Nicholas
Kryfts (1401–64), German philosopher, an important Renaissance Platonist. Born
in Kues on the Moselle, he earned a doctorate in canon law in 1423. He became known
for his De concordantia catholica, written at the Council of Basel in 1432, a
work defending the conciliarist position against the pope. Later, he decided
that only the pope could provide unity for the church in its negotiations with
the East, and allied himself with the papacy. In 1437–38, returning from a
papal legation to Constantinople, he had his famous insight into the
coincidence of opposites (coincidentia oppositorum) in the infinite, upon which
his On Learned Ignorance is based. His unceasing labor was chiefly responsible
for the Vienna Concordat with the Eastern church in 1448. He was made cardinal
in 1449 as a reward for his efforts, and bishop of Brixen (Bressanone) in 1450.
He traveled widely in Germany as a papal legate (1450–52) before settling down
in his see. Cusa’s central insight was that all oppositions are united in their
infinite measure, so that what would be logical contradictions for finite
things coexist without contradiction in God, who is the measure of (i.e., is
the form or essence of) all things, and identical to them inasmuch as he is
identical with their reality, quiddity, or essence. Considered as it is
contracted to the individual, a thing is only an image of its measure, not a
reality in itself. His position drew on mathematical models, arguing, for
instance, that an infinite straight line tangent to a circle is the measure of
the curved circumference, since a circle of infinite diameter, containing all
the being possible in a circle, would coincide with the tangent. In general,
the measure of a thing must contain all the possible being of that sort of
thing, and so is infinite, or unlimited, in its being. Cusa attacked
Aristotelians for their unwillingness to give up the principle of
non-contradiction. His epistemology is a form of Platonic skepticism. Our
knowledge is never of reality, the infinite measure of things that is their
essence, but only of finite images of reality corresponding to the finite
copies with which we must deal. These images are constructed by our own minds,
and do not represent an immediate grasp of any reality. Their highest form is
found in mathematics, and it is only through mathematics that reason can
understand the world. In relation to the infinite real, these images and the
contracted realities they enable us to know have only an infinitesimal reality.
Our knowledge is only a mass of conjectures, i.e., assertions that are true
insofar as Nicholas Kryfts Nicholas of Cusa 612 612 they capture some part of the truth,
but never the whole truth, the infinite measure, as it really is in itself.
Cusa was much read in the Renaissance, and is somethimes said to have had
significant influence on German thought of the eighteenth century, in
particular on Leibniz, and German idealism, but it is uncertain, despite the
considerable intrinsic merit of his thought, if this is true. PLATO. J.Lo. Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm
(1844–1900), German philosopher and cultural critic. Born in a small town in
the Prussian province of Saxony, Nietzsche’s early education emphasized
religion and classical languages and literature. After a year at the university
at Bonn he transferred to Leipzig, where he pursued classical studies. There he
happened upon Schopenhauer’s The World as Will and Representation, which
profoundly influenced his subsequent concerns and early philosophical thinking.
It was as a classical philologist, however, that he was appointed professor at
the Swiss university at Basel, before he had even received his doctorate, at
the astonishingly early age of twenty-four. A mere twenty years of productive
life remained to him, ending with a mental and physical collapse in January
1889, from which he never recovered. He held his position at Basel for a
decade, resigning in 1879 owing to the deterioration of his health from
illnesses he had contracted in 1870 as a volunteer medical orderly in the
Franco-Prussian war. At Basel he lectured on a variety of subjects chiefly
relating to classical studies, including Greek and Roman philosophy as well as
literature. During his early years there he also became intensely involved with
the composer Richard Wagner; and his fascination with Wagner was reflected in
several of his early works – most notably his first book, The Birth of Tragedy
(1872), and his subsequent essay Richard Wagner in Bayreuth (1876). His later
break with Wagner, culminating in his polemic The Case of Wagner(1888), was
both profound and painful to him. While at first regarding Wagner as a creative
genius showing the way to a cultural and spiritual renewal, Nietzsche came to
see him and his art as epitomizing and exacerbating the fundamental problem
with which he became increasingly concerned. This problem was the pervasive
intellectual and cultural crisis Nietzsche later characterized in terms of the
“death of God” and the advent of “nihilism.” Traditional religious and
metaphysical ways of thinking were on the wane, leaving a void that modern
science could not fill, and endangering the health of civilization. The
discovery of some life-affirming alternative to Schopenhauer’s radically
pessimistic response to this disillusionment became Nietzsche’s primary
concern. In The Birth of Tragedy he looked to the Greeks for clues and to
Wagner for inspiration, believing that their art held the key to renewed human flourishing
for a humanity bereft both of the consolations of religious faith and of
confidence in reason and science as substitutes for it. In his subsequent
series of Untimely Meditations (1873–76) he expanded upon his theme of the need
to reorient human thought and endeavor to this end, and criticized a variety of
tendencies detrimental to it that he discerned among his contemporaries. Both
the deterioration of Nietzsche’s health and the shift of his interest away from
his original discipline prevented retention of his position at Basel. In the
first years after his retirement, he completed his transition from philologist
to philosopher and published the several parts of Human, All-Too-Human
(1878–90), Daybreak (1881), and the first four parts of The Gay Science (1882).
These aphoristic writings sharpened and extended his analytical and critical
assessment of various human tendencies and social, cultural, and intellectual
phenomena. During this period his thinking became much more sophisticated; and
he developed the philosophical styles and concerns that found mature expression
in the writings of the final years of his brief active life, following the
publication of the four parts of Thus Spoke Zarathustra (1883–85). These last
remarkably productive years saw the appearance of Beyond Good and Evil (1886),
a fifth part of The Gay Science, On the Genealogy of Morals (1887), The Case of
Wagner (1888), and a series of prefaces to his earlier works (1886–87), as well
as the completion of several books published after his collapse – Twilight of
the Idols (1889), The Antichrist (1895), and Ecce Homo (1908). He was also
amassing a great deal of material in notebooks, of which a selection was later
published under the title The Will to Power. (The status and significance of
this mass of Nachlass material are matters of continuing controversy.) In the
early 1880s, when he wrote Thus Spoke Zarathustra, Nietzsche arrived at a
conception of human life and possibility – and with it, of value and meaning –
that he believed could overcome the Schopenhauerian pessimism and nihilism that
he saw as outcomes of the collapse of traditional modes of religious and
philosophical interNietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm
613 613 pretation. He prophesied a
period of nihilism in the aftermath of their decline and fall; but this
prospect deeply distressed him. He was convinced of the untenability of the
“God hypothesis,” and indeed of all religious and metaphysical interpretations
of the world and ourselves; and yet he was well aware that the very possibility
of the affirmation of life was at stake, and required more than the mere
abandonment of all such “lies” and “fictions.” He took the basic challenge of
philosophy now to be to reinterpret life and the world along more tenable lines
that would also overcome nihilism. What Nietzsche called “the death of God” was
both a cultural event – the waning and impending demise of the
“Christian-moral” interpretation of life and the world – and also a
philosophical development: the abandonment of anything like the God-hypothesis
(all demidivine absolutes included). As a cultural event it was a phenomenon to
be reckoned with, and a source of profound concern; for he feared a “nihilistic
rebound” in its wake, and worried about the consequences for human life and
culture if no countermovement to it were forthcoming. As a philosophical
development, on the other hand, it was his point of departure, which he took to
call for a radical reconsideration of everything from life and the world and
human existence and knowledge to value and morality. The “de-deification of
nature,” the “translation of man back into nature,” the “revaluation of
values,” the tracing of the “genealogy of morals” and their critique, and the
elaboration of “naturalistic” accounts of knowledge, value, morality, and our
entire “spiritual” nature thus came to be his main tasks. His published and
unpublished writings contain a wealth of remarks, observations, and suggestions
contributing importantly to them. It is a matter of controversy, even among
those with a high regard for Nietzsche, whether he tried to work out positions
on issues bearing any resemblance to those occupying other philosophers before
and after him in the mainstream of the history of philosophy. He was harshly
critical of most of his predecessors and contemporaries; and he broke
fundamentally with them and their basic ideas and procedures. His own writings,
moreover, bear little resemblance to those of most other philosophers. Those he
himself published (as well as his reflections in his notebooks) do not
systematically set out and develop views. Rather, they consist for the most
part in collections of short paragraphs and sets of aphorisms, often only
loosely if at all connected. Many deal with philosophical topics, but in very
unconventional ways; and because his remarks about these topics are scattered
through many different works, they are all too easily taken in isolation and
misunderstood. On some topics, moreover, much of what he wrote is found only in
his very rough notebooks, which he filled with thoughts without indicating the
extent of his reflected commitment to them. His language, furthermore, is by
turns coolly analytical, heatedly polemical, sharply critical, and highly
metaphorical; and he seldom indicates clearly the scope of his claims and what
he means by his terms. It is not surprising, therefore, that many philosophers
have found it difficult to know what to make of him and to take him seriously –
and that some have taken him to repudiate altogether the traditional
philosophical enterprise of seeking reasoned conclusions with respect to
questions of the kind with which philosophers have long been concerned,
heralding the “death” not only of religious and metaphysical thinking, but also
of philosophy itself. Others read him very differently, as having sought to
effect a fundamental reorientation of philosophical thinking, and to indicate
by both precept and example how philosophical inquiry might better be pursued.
Those who regard Nietzsche in the former way take his criticisms of his
philosophical predecessors and contemporaries to apply to any attempt to
address such matters. They seize upon and construe some of his more sweeping
negative pronouncements on truth and knowledge as indicating that he believed
we can only produce fictions and merely expedient (or possibly creative)
perspectival expressions of our needs and desires, as groups or as individuals.
They thus take him as a radical nihilist, concerned to subvert the entire
philosophical enterprise and replace it with a kind of thinking more akin to
the literary exploration of human possibilities in the service of life – a kind
of artistic play liberated from concern with truth and knowledge. Those who
view him in the latter way, on the other hand, take seriously his concern to
find a way of overcoming the nihilism he believed to result from traditional
ways of thinking; his retention of recast notions of truth and knowledge; and
his evident concern – especially in his later writings – to contribute to the
comprehension of a broad range of phenomena. This way of understanding him,
like the former, remains controversial; but it permits an interpretation of his
writings that is philosophically more fruitful. Nietzsche indisputably insisted
upon the interpretive character of all human thought; and he called for “new
philosophers” who would follow him in engaging in more self-conscious and
intellectually responsible attempts to assess and improve upon prevailing
interpretations of human life. He also was deeply concerned with how these
matters might better be evaluated, and with the values by which human beings
live and might better do so. Thus he made much of the need for a revaluation of
all received values, and for attention to the problems of the nature, status,
and standards of value and evaluation. One form of inquiry he took to be of
great utility in connection with both of these tasks is genealogical inquiry
into the conditions under which various modes of interpretation and evaluation
have arisen. It is only one of the kinds of inquiry he considered necessary in
both cases, however, serving merely to prepare for others that must be brought
to bear before any conclusions are warranted. Nietzsche further emphasized the
perspectival character of all thinking and the merely provisional character of
all knowing, rejecting the idea of the very possibility of absolute knowledge
transcending all perspectives. However, because he also rejected the idea that
things (and values) have absolute existence “in themselves” apart from the
relations in which he supposes their reality to consist, he held that, if
viewed in the multiplicity of perspectives from which various of these
relations come to light, they admit of a significant measure of comprehension.
This perspectivism thus does not exclude the possibility of any sort of
knowledge deserving of the name, but rather indicates how it is to be conceived
and achieved. His kind of philosophy, which he characterizes as fröhliche
Wissenschaft (cheerful science), proceeds by way of a variety of such
“perspectival” approaches to the various matters with which he deals. Thus for
Nietzsche there is no “truth” in the sense of the correspondence of anything we
might think or say to “being,” and indeed no “true world of being” to which it
may even be imagined to fail to correspond; no “knowledge” conceived in terms
of any such truth and reality; and, further, no knowledge at all – even of
ourselves and the world of which we are a part – that is absolute, non-perspectival,
and certain. But that is not the end of the matter. There are, e.g., ways of
thinking that may be more or less well warranted in relation to differing sorts
of interest and practice, not only within the context of social life but also
in our dealings with our environing world. Nietzsche’s reflections on the
reconceptualization of truth and knowledge thus point in the direction of a
naturalistic epistemology that he would have replace the conceptions of truth
and knowledge of his predecessors, and fill the nihilistic void seemingly left
by their bankruptcy. There is, moreover, a good deal about ourselves and our
world that he became convinced we can comprehend. Our comprehension may be
restricted to what life and the world show themselves to be and involve in our
experience; but if they are the only kind of reality, there is no longer any
reason to divorce the notions of truth, knowledge, and value from them. The
question then becomes how best to interpret and assess what we find as we
proceed to explore them. It is to these tasks of interpretation and
“revaluation” that Nietzsche devoted his main efforts in his later writings. In
speaking of the death of God, Nietzsche had in mind not only the abandonment of
the Godhypothesis (which he considered to be utterly “unworthy of belief,”
owing its invention and appeal entirely to naïveté, error, all-too-human need,
and ulterior motivation), but also the demise of all metaphysical substitutes
for it. He likewise criticized and rejected the related postulations of
substantial “souls” and self-contained “things,” taking both notions to be
ontological fictions merely reflecting our artificial (though convenient)
linguistic-conceptual shorthand for functionally unitary products, processes,
and sets of relations. In place of this cluster of traditional ontological
categories and interpretations, he conceived the world in terms of an interplay
of forces without any inherent structure or final end. It ceaselessly organizes
and reorganizes itself, as the fundamental disposition he called will to power
gives rise to successive arrays of power relationships. “This world is the will
to power – and nothing besides,” he wrote; “and you yourselves are also this
will to power – and nothing besides!” Nietzsche’s idea of the eternal return
(or eternal recurrence) underscores this conception of a world without
beginning or end, in which things happen repeatedly in the way they always
have. He first introduced this idea as a test of one’s ability to affirm one’s
own life and the general character of life in this world as they are, without
reservation, qualification, or appeal to anything transcending them. He later
entertained the thought that all events might actually recur eternally in
exactly the same sequence, and experimented in his unpublished writings with
arguments to this effect. For the most part, however, he restricted himself to
less problematic 615 Neitzsche,
Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm 616 uses of the idea that do not
presuppose its literal truth in this radical form. His rhetorical
embellishments and experimental elaborations of the idea may have been intended
to make it more vivid and compelling; but he employed it chiefly to depict his
conception of the radically non-linear character of events in this world and
their fundamental homogeneity, and to provide a way of testing our ability to
live with it. If we are sufficiently strong and well disposed to life to affirm
it even on the supposition that it will only be the same sequence of events
repeated eternally, we have what it takes to endure and flourish in the kind of
world in which Nietzsche believed we find ourselves in the aftermath of
disillusionment. Nietzsche construed human nature and existence
naturalistically, in terms of the will to power and its ramifications in the
establishment and expression of the kinds of complex systems of dynamic quanta
in which human beings consist. “The soul is only a word for something about the
body,” he has Zarathustra say; and the body is fundamentally a configuration of
natural forces and processes. At the same time, he insisted on the importance
of social arrangements and interactions in the development of human forms of
awareness and activity. He also emphasized the possibility of the emergence of
exceptional human beings capable of an independence and creativity elevating
them above the level of the general human rule. So he stressed the difference
between “higher men” and “the herd,” and through Zarathustra proclaimed the
Übermensch (‘overman’ or ‘superman’) to be “the meaning of the earth,”
employing this image to convey the ideal of the overcoming of the
“all-too-human” and the fullest possible creative “enhancement of life.” Far
from seeking to diminish our humanity by stressing our animality, he sought to
direct our efforts to the emergence of a “higher humanity” capable of endowing
existence with a human redemption and justification, above all through the
enrichment of cultural life. Notwithstanding his frequent characterization as a
nihilist, therefore, Nietzsche in fact sought to counter and overcome the
nihilism he expected to prevail in the aftermath of the collapse and
abandonment of traditional religious and metaphysical modes of interpretation
and evaluation. While he was highly critical of the latter, it was not his
intention merely to oppose them; for he further attempted to make out the
possibility of forms of truth and knowledge to which philosophical interpreters
of life and the world might aspire, and espoused a “Dionysian value-standard” in
place of all non-naturalistic modes of valuation. In keeping with his
interpretation of life and the world in terms of his conception of will to
power, Nietzsche framed this standard in terms of his interpretation of them.
The only tenable alternative to nihilism must be based upon a recognition and
affirmation of the world’s fundamental character. This meant positing as a
general standard of value the attainment of a kind of life in which the will to
power as the creative transformation of existence is raised to its highest
possible intensity and qualitative expression. This in turn led him to take the
“enhancement of life” and creativity to be the guiding ideas of his revaluation
of values and development of a naturalistic value theory. This way of thinking
carried over into Nietzsche’s thinking about morality. Insisting that
moralities as well as other traditional modes of valuation ought to be assessed
“in the perspective of life,” he argued that most of them were contrary to the
enhancement of life, reflecting the all-too-human needs and weaknesses and
fears of less favored human groups and types. Distinguishing between “master”
and “slave” moralities, he found the latter to have become the dominant type of
morality in the modern world. He regarded present-day morality as a
“herd-animal morality,” well suited to the requirements and vulnerabilities of
the mediocre who are the human rule, but stultifying and detrimental to the
development of potential exceptions to that rule. Accordingly, he drew attention
to the origins and functions of this type of morality (as a social-control
mechanism and device by which the weak defend and avenge and assert themselves
against the actually or potentially stronger). He further suggested the
desirability of a “higher morality” for the exceptions, in which the contrast
of the basic “slave/herd morality” categories of “good and evil” would be
replaced by categories more akin to the “good and bad” contrast characteristic
of “master morality,” with a revised (and variable) content better attuned to
the conditions and attainable qualities of the enhanced forms of life such
exceptional human beings can achieve. The strongly creative flavor of
Nietzsche’s notions of such a “higher humanity” and associated “higher
morality” reflects his linkage of both to his conception of art, to which he
attached great importance. Art, for Nietzsche, is fundamentally creative
(rather than cognitive), serving to prepare for the emergence of a sensi 616 bility and manner of life reflecting the
highest potentiality of human beings. Art, as the creative transformation of
the world as we find it (and of ourselves thereby) on a small scale and in
particular media, affords a glimpse of a kind of life that would be lived more
fully in this manner, and constitutes a step toward emergence. In this way,
Nietzsche’s mature thought thus expands upon the idea of the basic connection
between art and the justification of life that was his general theme in his
first major work, The Birth of Tragedy.
EXISTENTIALISM, HEGEL, KANT, SCHOPENHAUER. R.Sc. Nihil est in intellectu
quod non prius fuerit in sensu (Latin, ‘Nothing is in the understanding that
had not previously been in the senses’), a principal tenet of empiricism. A
weak interpretation of the principle maintains that all concepts are acquired
from sensory experience; no concepts are innate or a priori. A stronger
interpretation adds that all propositional knowledge is derived from sense
experience. The weak interpretation was held by Aquinas and Locke, who thought
nevertheless that we can know some propositions to be true in virtue of the
relations between the concepts involved. The stronger interpretation was
endorsed by J. S. Mill, who argued that even the truths of mathematics are
inductively based on experience.
EMPIRICISM. W.E.M. Nihil ex nihilo fit (Latin,
‘Nothing arises from nothing’), an intuitive metaphysical principle first
enunciated in the West by Parmenides, often held equivalent to the proposition
that nothing arises without a cause. Creation ex nihilo is God’s production of
the world without any natural or material cause, but involves a supernatural
cause, and so it would not violate the principle. J.Lo. nihilism,
ethical.RELATIVISM. nihilism, philosophical.NIETZSCHE, RUSSIAN NIHILISM. nihilism,
Russian.RUSSIAN NIHILISM. nihilism, semantic.SEMANTIC HOLISM.
nirodha-samapatti, also known as samjnavedayita-nirodha (Sanskrit, ‘attainment
of cessation’), a term used by Indian Buddhists to denote a state produced by
meditation in which no mental events of any kind occur. What ceases in
nirodha-samapatti is all the operations of the mind; all that remains is the
mindless body. Some Buddhists took this state to have salvific significance,
and so likened it to Nirvana. But its principal philosophical interest lies in
the puzzle it produced for Buddhist theorists: What causal account can be given
that will make sense of the reemergence of mental events from a continuum in
which none exist, given the pan-Buddhist assumption that all existents are
momentary? P.J.G. NN thesis.NECESSITY. noema.HUSSERL, NOETIC. noemata
moralia.MORE, THOMAS. noematic analysis.HUSSERL. noesis.DIVIDED LINE, HUSSERL.
noetic (from Greek noetikos, from noetos, ‘perceiving’), of or relating to
apprehension by the intellect. In a strict sense the term refers to nonsensuous
data given to the cognitive faculty, which discloses their intelligible meaning
as distinguished from their sensible apprehension. We hear a sentence spoken,
but it becomes intelligible for us only when the sounds function as a
foundation for noetic apprehension. For Plato, the objects of such apprehension
(noetá) are the Forms (eide) with respect to which the sensible phenomena are
only occasions of manifestation: the Forms in themselves transcend the sensible
and have their being in a realm apart. For empiricist thinkers, e.g., Locke,
there is strictly speaking no distinct noetic aspect, since “ideas” are only
faint sense impressions. In a looser sense, however, one may speak of ideas as
independent of reference to particular sense impressions, i.e. independent of
their origin, and then an idea can be taken to signify a class of objects.
Husserl uses the term to describe the intentionality or dyadic character of
consciousness in general, i.e. including both eidetic or categorial and
perceptual knowing. He speaks of the correlation of noesis or intending and
noema or the intended object of awareness. The categorial or eidetic is the
perceptual object as intellectually cognized; it is not a realm apart, but
rather what is disclosed or made present (“constituted”) Nihil est in
intellectu quod non prius fuerit in sensu noetic 617 617 when the mode of appearance of the
perceptual object is intended by a categorial noesis.
.
non-Euclidean geometry,
those axiomatized versions of geometry in which the parallel axiom of Euclidean
geometry is rejected, after so many unsuccessful attempts to prove it. As in so
many branches of mathematics, C. F. Gauss had thought out much of the matter
first, but he kept most of his ideas to himself. As a result, credit is given
to J. Bolyai and N. Lobachevsky, who worked independently from the late 1820s.
Instead of assuming that just one line passes through a point in a plane
parallel to a non-coincident coplanar line, they offered a geometry in which a
line admits more than one parallel, and the sum of the “angles” between the
“sides” of a “triangle” lies below 180°. Then in mid-century G. F. B. Riemann
conceived of a geometry in which lines always meet (so no parallels), and the
sum of the “angles” exceeds 180°. In this connection he distinguished between
the unboundedness of space as a property of its extent, and the special case of
the infinite measure over which distance might be taken (which is dependent
upon the curvature of that space). Pursuing the (published) insight of Gauss,
that the curvature of a surface could be defined in terms only of properties
dependent solely on the surface itself (and later called “intrinsic”), Riemann
also defined the metric on a surface in a very general and intrinsic way, in
terms of the differential arc length. Thereby he clarified the ideas of
“distance” that his non-Euclidean precursors had introduced (drawing on
trigonometric and hyperbolic functions); arc length was now understood
geodesically as the shortest “distance” between two “points” on a surface, and
was specified independent of any assumptions of a geometry within which the
surface was embedded. Further properties, such as that pertaining to the
“volume” of a three-“dimensional” solid, were also studied. The two main types
of non-Euclidean geometry, and its Euclidean parent, may be summarized as
follows: Reaction to these geometries was slow to develop, but their impact
gradually emerged. As mathematics, their legitimacy was doubted; but in 1868 E.
Beltrami produced a model of a Bolyai-type two-dimensional space inside a
planar circle. The importance of this model was to show that the consistency of
this geometry depended upon that of the Euclidean version, thereby dispelling
the fear that it was an inconsistent flash of the imagination. During the last
thirty years of the nineteenth century a variety of variant geometries were
proposed, and the relationships between them were studied, together with
consequences for projective geometry. On the empirical side, these geometries,
and especially Riemann’s approach, affected the understanding of the
relationship between geometry and space; in particular, it posed the question
whether space is curved or not (the latnoetic analysis non-Euclidean geometry 618 618 non-monotonic logic nonviolence 619 ter
being the Euclidean answer). The geometries thus played a role in the emergence
and articulation of relativity theory, especially the differential geometry and
tensorial calculus within which its mathematical properties could be expressed.
Philosophically the new geometries stressed the hypothetical nature of
axiomatizing, in contrast to the customary view of mathematical theories as
true in some (usually) unclear sense. This feature led to the name ‘metageometry’
for them; it was intended (as an ironical proposal of opponents) to be in line
with the hypothetical character of metaphysics in philosophy. They also helped
to encourage conventionalist philosophy of science (with Poincaré, e.g.), and
put fresh light on the age-old question of the (im)possibility of a priori
knowledge.
non-monotonic logic, a
logic that fails to be monotonic, i.e., in proof-theoretic terms, fails to meet
the condition that for all statements u1, . . . un,f,y, if ‘u1, . . . un Yf’, then,
for any y, ‘u1 , . . . un, y Y f’. (Equivalently, let Γ represent a collection
of statements, u1 . . . un, and say that in monotonic logic, if ‘Γ Y f’, then,
for any y, ‘Γ, y Y f’ and similarly in other cases.) A non-monotonic logic is
any logic with the following property: For some Γ, f, and y, ‘ΓNML f’ but ‘Γ, y
K!NML f’. This is a weak non-monotonic logic. In a strong non-monotonic logic,
we might have, again for some Γ, f, y, where Γ is consistent and Γ 8 f is
consistent: ‘Γ, y YNML > f’. A primary motivation (among AI researchers) for
non-monotonic logic or defeasible reasoning, which is so evident in commonsense
reasoning, is to produce a machine representation for default reasoning or
defeasible reasoning. The interest in defeasible reasoning readily spreads to
epistemology, logic, and ethics. The exigencies of practical affairs requires
leaping to conclusions, going beyond available evidence, making assumptions. In
doing so, we often err and must leap back from our conclusions, undo our assumptions,
revise our beliefs. In the literature’s standard example, Tweety is a bird and
all birds fly, except penguins and ostriches. Does Tweety fly? If pressed, we
may need to form a belief about this matter. Upon discovering that Tweety is a
penguin, we may have to retract our conclusion. Any representation of
defeasible reasoning must capture the nonmonotonicity of this reasoning.
Non-monotonic logic is an attempt to do this within logic itself – by adding
rules of inference that do not preserve monotonicity. Although practical
affairs require us to reason defeasibly, the best way to achieve
non-monotonicity may not be to add non-monotonic rules of inference to standard
logic. What one gives up in such systems may well not be worth the cost: loss
of the deduction theorem and of a coherent notion of consistency. Therefore,
the challenge of non-monotonic logic (or defeasible reasoning, generally) is to
develop a rigorous way to represent the structure of non-monotonic reasoning
without losing or abandoning the historically hard-won properties of monotonic
(standard) logic.
nonviolence, the
renunciation of violence in personal, social, or international affairs. It
often includes a commitment (called active nonviolence or nonviolent direct
action) actively to oppose violence (and usually evil or injustice as well) by
nonviolent means. Nonviolence may renounce physical violence alone or both
physical and psychological violence. It may represent a purely personal
commitment or be intended to be normative for others as well. When
unconditional – absolute 619 norm
normative relativism 620 nonviolence – it renounces violence in all actual and
hypothetical circumstances. When conditional – conditional nonviolence – it
concedes the justifiability of violence in hypothetical circumstances but
denies it in practice. Held on moral grounds (principled nonviolence), the
commitment belongs to an ethics of conduct or an ethics of virtue. If the
former, it will likely be expressed as a moral rule or principle (e.g., One
ought always to act nonviolently) to guide action. If the latter, it will urge
cultivating the traits and dispositions of a nonviolent character (which
presumably then will be expressed in nonviolent action). As a principle,
nonviolence may be considered either basic or derivative. Either way, its
justification will be either utilitarian or deontological. Held on non-moral
grounds (pragmatic nonviolence), nonviolence is a means to specific social,
political, economic, or other ends, themselves held on non-moral grounds. Its
justification lies in its effectiveness for these limited purposes rather than
as a way of life or a guide to conduct in general. An alternative source of
power, it may then be used in the service of evil as well as good. Nonviolent
social action, whether of a principled or pragmatic sort, may include
noncooperation, mass demonstrations, marches, strikes, boycotts, and civil
disobedience – techniques explored extensively in the writings of Gene Sharp.
Undertaken in defense of an entire nation or state, nonviolence provides an
alternative to war. It seeks to deny an invading or occupying force the
capacity to attain its objectives by withholding the cooperation of the
populace needed for effective rule and by nonviolent direct action, including civil
disobedience. It may also be used against oppressive domestic rule or on behalf
of social justice. Gandhi’s campaign against British rule in India,
Scandinavian resistance to Nazi occupation during World War II, and Martin
Luther King, Jr.’s actions on behalf of civil rights in the United States are
illustrative. Nonviolence has origins in Far Eastern thought, particularly
Taoism and Jainism. It has strands in the Jewish Talmud, and many find it
implied by the New Testament’s Sermon on the Mount. CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE, GANDHI, PACIFISM. R.L.H.
norm.BASIC NORM. normal form, a formula equivalent to a given logical formula,
but having special properties. The main varieties follow. Conjunctive normal
form. If D1 . . . Dn are disjunctions of sentential variables or their
negations, such as (p 7 -q 7 r), then a formula F is in conjunctive normal form
provided F % D1 & D2 & . . & Dn. The following are in conjunctive
normal form: (-p 7 q); (p 7 q 7 r) & (-p 7 -q 7 -r) & (-q 7 r). Every
formula of sentential logic has an equivalent conjunctive normal form; this
fact can be used to prove the completeness of sentential logic. Disjunctive
normal form. If C1 . . . Cn are conjunctions of sentential variables or their
negations, such as p & -q & -r, then a formula F is in disjunctive
normal form provided F % C1 7 C27 . . Cn. The following are thus in disjunctive
normal form: (p & -q) 7 (-p & q); (p & q & -r) 7 (-p & -q
& -r). Every formula of sentential logic has an equivalent disjunctive
normal form. Prenex normal form. A formula of predicate logic is in prenex
normal form if (1) all quantifiers occur at the beginning of the formula, (2)
the scope of the quantifiers extends to the end of the formula, and (3) what
follows the quantifiers contains at least one occurrence of every variable that
appears in the set of quantifiers. Thus, (Dx)(Dy)(Fx / Gy) and (x)(Dy)(z)((Fxy
7 Gyz) / Dxyz) are in prenex normal form. The formula may contain free
variables; thus, (Dx)(y) (Fxyz / Gwyx) is also in prenex normal form. The
following, however, are not in prenex normal form: (x)(Dy) (Fx / Gx); (x)(y)
Fxy / Gxy. Every formula of predicate logic has an equivalent formula in prenex
normal form. Skolem normal form. A formula F in predicate logic is in Skolem
normal form provided (1) F is in prenex normal form, (2) every existential
quantifier precedes any universal quantifier, (3) F contains at least one
existential quantifier, and (4) F contains no free variables. Thus, (Dx)(Dy)
(z)(Fxy / Gyz) and (Dx)(Dy)(Dz)(w)(Fxy 7 Fyz 7 Fzw) are in Skolem normal form;
however, (Dx) (y) Fxyz and (x) (y) (Fxy 7 Gyx) are not. Any formula has an
equivalent Skolem normal form; this has implications for the completeness of
predicate logic.
notum per se (Latin,
‘known through itself’), self-evident. This term corresponds roughly to the
term ‘analytic’. In Thomistic theology, there are two ways for a thing to be
self-evident, secundum se (in itself) and quoad nos (to us). The proposition
that God exists is self-evident in itself, because God’s existence is identical
with his essence; but it is not self-evident to us (humans), because humans are
not directly acquainted with God’s essence.Aquinas’s Summa theologiae I,
q.2,a.1,c.
noûs, Greek term for mind
or the faculty of reason. Noûs is the highest type of thinking, the kind a god
would do. Sometimes called the faculty of intellectual intuition, it is at work
when someone understands definitions, concepts, and anything else that is
grasped all at once. Noûs stands in contrast with another intellectual faculty,
dianoia. When we work through the steps of an argument, we exercise dianoia; to
be certain the conclusion is true without argument – to just “see” it, as,
perhaps, a god might – is to exercise noûs. Just which objects could be
apprehended by noûs was controversial. E.C.H. Novalis, pseudonym of Friedrich
von Hardenberg (1772–1801), German poet and philosopher of early German
Romanticism. His starting point was Fichte’s reflective type of transcendental
philosophy; he attempted to complement Fichte’s focus on philosophical
speculation by including other forms of intellectual experience such as faith,
love, poetry, and religion, and exhibit their equally autonomous status of existence.
Of special importance in this regard is his analysis of the imagination in
contrast to reason, of the poetic power in distinction from the reasonable
faculties. Novalis insists on a complementary interaction between these two
spheres, on a union of philosophy and poetry. Another important aspect of his
speculation concerns the relation between the inner and the outer world,
subject and object, the human being and nature. Novalis attempted to reveal the
correspondence, even unity between these two realms and to present the world as
a “universal trope” or a “symbolic image” of the human mind and vice versa. He
expressed his philosophical thought mostly in fragments. FICHTE. E.Beh. Nozick, Robert (b.1938),
American philosopher currently at Harvard University, best known for Anarchy,
State, and Utopia (1974), which defends the libertarian position that only a
minimal state (limited to protecting rights) is just. Nozick argues that a
minimal state, but not a more extensive state, could arise without violating
rights. Drawing on Kant’s dictum that people may not be used as mere means,
Nozick says that people’s rights are inviolable, no matter how useful
violations might be to the state. He criticizes principles of redistributive
justice on which theorists base defenses of extensive states, such as the
principle of utility, and Rawls’s principle that goods should be distributed in
favor of the least well-off. Enforcing these principles requires eliminating
the cumulative effects of free exchanges, which violates (permanent,
bequeathable) property rights. Nozick’s own entitlement theory says that a
distribution of holdings is just if people under that distribution are entitled
to what they hold. Entitlements, in turn, would be clarified using principles
of justice in acquisition, transfer, and rectification. Nozick’s other works
include Philosophical Explanations (1981), The Examined Life (1989), The Nature
of Rationality (1993), and Socratic Puzzles (1997). These are contributions to
rational choice theory, epistemology, metaphysics, philosophy of mind,
philosophy of religion, and ethics. Philosophical Explanations features two
especially important contributions. The first is Nozick’s (reliabilist, causal)
view that beliefs that constitute knowledge must track the truth. My belief
that (say) a cat is on the mat tracks the truth only if (a) I would not believe
this if a cat were not on the mat, and (b) I would believe this if a cat were
there. The tracking account positions Nozick to reject the principle that people
know all of the things they believe via deductions from things they know, and
to reject versions of skepticism based on this principle of closure. The second
is Nozick’s closest continuer theory of identity, according to which A’s
identity at a later time can depend on facts about other existing things, for
it depends on (1) what continues A closely enough to be A and (2) what 621 n-tuple Nussbaum, Martha C(raven) 622
continues A more closely than any other existing thing. Nozick’s 1969 essay
“Newcomb’s Problem and Two Principles of Choice” is another important
contribution. It is the first discussion of Newcomb’s problem, a problem in
decision theory, and presents many positions prominent in subsequent
debate.
Numenius of Apamea (fl.
mid-second century A.D.), Greek Platonist philosopher of neoPythagorean
tendencies. Very little is known of his life apart from his residence in
Apamea, Syria, but his philosophical importance is considerable. His system of
three levels of spiritual reality – a primal god (the Good, the Father), who is
almost supra-intellectual; a secondary, creator god (the demiurge of Plato’s
Timaeus); and a world soul – largely anticipates that of Plotinus in the next
century, though he was more strongly dualist than Plotinus in his attitude to
the physical world and matter. He was much interested in the wisdom of the
East, and in comparative religion. His most important work, fragments of which
are preserved by Eusebius, is a dialogue On the Good, but he also wrote a
polemic work On the Divergence of the Academics from Plato, which shows him to
be a lively controversialist. J.M.D. numerical identity.
Nussbaum, Martha C(raven)
(b.1947), American philosopher, classicist, and public intellectual with
influential views on the human good, the emotions and their place in practical
reasoning, and the rights of women and homosexuals. After training at Harvard
in classical philology, she published a critical edition, with translation and
commentary, of Aristotle’s Motion of Animals (1978). Its essays formulated
ideas that she has continued to articulate: that perception is trainable,
imagination interpretive, and desire a reaching out for the good. Via
provocative readings of Plato, Aristotle, Aeschylus, Sophocles, and Euripides,
The Fragility of Goodness (1986) argues that many true goods succumb to
fortune, lack any common measure, and demand finetuned discernment. The essays
in Love’s Knowledge (1990) – on Proust, Dickens, Beckett, Henry James, and
others – explore the emotional implications of our fragility and the
particularism of practical reasoning. They also undertake a brief against
Plato’s ancient criticism of the poets, an argument that Nussbaum carried on
years later in debates with Judge Richard Posner. The Therapy of Desire (1994)
dissects the Stoics’ conviction that our vulnerability calls for philosophical
therapy to extirpate the emotions. While Nussbaum holds that the Stoics were
mistaken about the good, she has adopted and strengthened their view that
emotions embody judgments – most notably in her Gifford Lectures of 1993,
Upheavals of Thought. A turning point in Nussbaum’s career came in 1987, when
she became a part-time research adviser at the United Nations–sponsored World
Institute for Development Economics Research. She there adapted her
Aristotelian account of the human good to help ground the “capabilities
approach” that the economist and philosopher Amartya Sen was developing for
policymakers to use in assessing individuals’ well-being. Nussbaum spells out
the human capabilities essential to leading a good life, integrating them
within a nuanced liberalism of universalist appeal. This view has ramified:
Poetic Justice (1996) argues that its legal realization must avoid the
oversimplifications that utilitarianism and economics encourage and instead
balance generality with emotionally sensitive imagination. Sex and Social
Justice (1998) explores her view’s implications for problems of sexual
inequality, gay rights, and sexual objectification. Feminist Internationalism,
her 1998 Seeley Lec 622 tures, argues
that an effective international feminism must champion rights, eschew
relativism, and study local traditions sufficiently closely to see their
diversity.
Nyaya-Vaishesika, one of
the orthodox schools of Hinduism. It holds that earth, air, fire, and water are
the four types of atoms. Space is a substance and a container of atoms. The
atoms are everlasting and eternal, though their combinations are neither.
Properties of complexes are explained in terms of the properties of their
components. There are emergent properties the causation of which does not
require that something come from nothing; one need only grant brute causal
connections. Nyaya is a monotheistic perspective and Nyaya philosopher Udana
wrote a text – Kusmañjali (“The Handful of Flowers”) – in natural theology;
this tenth-century work is an Indian classic on the subject. In addition to
material things composed of atoms, there are immaterial persons. Each person is
an enduring, substantial self whose nature is to be conscious and who is
capable of love and aversion, of feeling pleasure and pain, and of making
choices; selves differ from one another even when not embodied by virtue of
being different centers of consciousness, not merely in terms of having had
diverse transmigratory biographies. Nyaya-Vaishesika is the Hindu school most
like Anglo-American philosophy, as evidenced in its studies of inference and
perception. HINDUISM. K.E.Y.
Nyaya-Vaishesika Nyaya-Vaishesika 623
623 Oakeshott, Michael (1900–91), British philosopher and political
theorist trained at Cambridge and in Germany. He taught first at Cambridge and
Oxford; from 1951 he was professor of political science at the London School of
Economics and Political Science. His works include Experience and Its Modes
(1933), Rationalism in Politics (1962), On Human Conduct (1975), and On History
(1983). Oakeshott’s misleading general reputation, based on Rationalism in
Politics, is as a conservative political thinker. Experience and Its Modes is a
systematic work in the tradition of Hegel. Human experience is exclusively of a
world of ideas intelligible insofar as it is coherent. This world divides into
modes (historical, scientific, practical, and poetic experience), each being
partly coherent and categorially distinct from all others. Philosophy is the
never entirely successful attempt to articulate the coherence of the world of
ideas and the place of modally specific experience within that whole. His later
works examine the postulates of historical and practical experience,
particularly those of religion, morality, and politics. All conduct in the
practical mode postulates freedom and is an “exhibition of intelligence” by
agents who appropriate inherited languages and ideas to the generic activity of
self-enactment. Some conduct pursues specific purposes and occurs in
“enterprise associations” identified by goals shared among those who
participate in them. The most estimable forms of conduct, exemplified by
“conversation,” have no such purpose and occur in “civil societies” under the
purely “adverbial” considerations of morality and law. “Rationalists” illicitly
use philosophy to dictate to practical experience and subordinate human conduct
to some master purpose. Oakeshott’s distinctive achievement is to have melded
holistic idealism with a morality and politics radical in their affirmation of
individuality. POLITICAL THEORY. R.E.F.
obiectum quo (Latin, ‘object by which’), in medieval and Scholastic
epistemology, the object by which an object is known. It should be understood
in contrast with obiectum quod, which refers to the object that is known. For
example, when a person knows what an apple is, the apple is the obiectum quod
and his concept of the apple is the obiectum quo. That is, the concept is
instrumental to knowing the apple, but is not itself what is known. Human
beings need concepts in order to have knowledge, because their knowledge is
receptive, in contrast with God’s which is productive. (God creates what he
knows.) Human knowledge is mediated; divine knowledge is immediate. Scholastic
philosophers believe that the distinction between obiectum quod and obiectum
quo exposes the crucial mistake of idealism. According to idealists, the object
of knowledge, i.e., what a person knows, is an idea. In contrast, the
Scholastics maintain that idealists conflate the object of knowledge with the
means by which human knowledge is made possible. Humans must be connected to
the object of knowledge by something (obiectum quo), but what connects them is
not that to which they are connected. A.P.M. object, intentional.BRENTANO.
object, propositional.PROPOSITION. objective body.EMBODIMENT. objective
probability.PROBABILITY. objective reality.DESCARTES, REALITY. objective
reason.REASONS FOR ACTION. objective rightness. In ethics, an action is
objectively right for a person to perform (on some occasion) if the agent’s
performing it (on that occasion) really is right, whether or not the agent, or
anyone else, believes it is. An action is subjectively right for a person to perform
(on some occasion) if the agent believes, or perhaps justifiably believes, of
that action that it is (objectively) right. For example, according to a version
of utilitarianism, an action is objectively right provided the action is
optimific in the sense that the consequences that would result from its per624
O 624 formance are at least as good as
those that would result from any alternative action the agent could instead
perform. Were this theory correct, then an action would be an objectively right
action for an agent to perform (on some occasion) if and only if that action is
in fact optimific. An action can be both objectively and subjectively right or
neither. But an action can also be subjectively right, but fail to be
objectively right, as where the action fails to be optimific (again assuming
that a utilitarian theory is correct), yet the agent believes the action is
objectively right. And an action can be objectively right but not subjectively
right, where, despite the objective rightness of the action, the agent has no
beliefs about its rightness or believes falsely that it is not objectively
right. This distinction is important in our moral assessments of agents and
their actions. In cases where we judge a person’s action to be objectively
wrong, we often mitigate our judgment of the agent when we judge that the
action was, for the agent, subjectively right. This same objective–subjective
distinction applies to other ethical categories such as wrongness and
obligatoriness, and some philosophers extend it to items other than actions,
e.g., emotions.
obligationes, the study
of inferentially inescapable, yet logically odd arguments, used by late
medieval logicians in analyzing inferential reasoning. In Topics VIII.3
Aristotle describes a respondent’s task in a philosophical argument as
providing answers so that, if they must defend the impossible, the
impossibility lies in the nature of the position, and not in its logical
defense. In Prior Analytics I.13 Aristotle argues that nothing impossible
follows from the possible. Burley, whose logic exemplifies early
fourteenth-century obligationes literature, described the resulting logical
exercise as a contest between interlocutor and respondent. The interlocutor
must force the respondent into maintaining contradictory statements in
defending a position, and the respondent must avoid this while avoiding
maintaining the impossible, which can be either a position logically
incompatible with the position defended or something impossible in itself. Especially
interesting to Scholastic logicians were the paradoxes of disputation inherent
in such disputes. Assuming that a respondent has successfully defended his
position, the interlocutor may be able to propose a commonplace position that
the respondent can neither accept nor reject, given the truth of the first,
successfully defended position. Roger Swineshead introduced a controversial
innovation to obligationes reasoning, later rejected by Paul of Venice. In the
traditional style of obligation, a premise was relevant to the argument only if
it followed from or was inconsistent with either (a) the proposition defended
or (b) all the premises consequent to the former and prior to the premise in
question. By admitting any premise that was either consequent to or
inconsistent with the proposition defended alone, without regard to
intermediate premises, Swineshead eliminated concern with the order of
sentences proposed by the interlocutor, making the respondent’s task
harder. ARISTOTLE, BURLEY, KILVINGTON,
OXFORD CALCULATORS, PAUL OF VENICE. S.E.L. oblique context. As explained by
Frege in “Über Sinn und Bedeutung” (1892), a linguistic context is oblique
(ungerade) if and only if an expression (e.g., proper name, dependent clause,
or sentence) in that context does not express its direct (customary) sense. For
Frege, the sense of an expression is the mode of presentation of its nominatum,
if any. Thus in direct speech, the direct (customary) sense of an expression
designates its direct (customary) nominatum. For example, the context of the
proper name ‘Kepler’ in (1) Kepler died in misery. is non-oblique (i.e.,
direct) since the proper name expresses its direct (customary) sense, say, the
sense of ‘the man who discovered the elliptical planetary orbits’, thereby designating
its direct (customary) nominatum, Kepler himself. Moreover, the entire sentence
expresses its direct sense, namely, the proposition that Kepler died in misery,
thereby designating its direct nominatum, a truth-value, namely, the true. By
contrast, objectivism oblique context 625
625 in indirect speech an expression neither expresses its direct sense
nor, therefore, designates its direct nominatum. One such sort of oblique
context is direct quotation, as in (2) ‘Kepler’ has six letters. The word
appearing within the quotation marks neither expresses its direct (customary)
sense nor, therefore, designates its direct (customary) nominatum, Kepler.
Rather, it designates a word, a proper name. Another sort of oblique context is
engendered by the verbs of propositional attitude. Thus, the context of the
proper name ‘Kepler’ in (3) Frege believed Kepler died in misery. is oblique,
since the proper name expresses its indirect sense, say, the sense of the words
‘the man widely known as Kepler’, thereby designating its indirect nominatum,
namely, the sense of ‘the man who discovered the elliptical planetary orbits’.
Note that the indirect nominatum of ‘Kepler’ in (3) is the same as the direct
sense of ‘Kepler’ in (1). Thus, while ‘Kepler’ in (1) designates the man
Kepler, ‘Kepler’ in (3) designates the direct (customary) sense of the word
‘Kepler’ in (1). Similarly, in (3) the context of the dependent clause ‘Kepler
died in misery’ is oblique since the dependent clause expresses its indirect
sense, namely, the sense of the words ‘the proposition that Kepler died in
misery’, thereby designating its indirect nominatum, namely, the proposition
that Kepler died in misery. Note that the indirect nominatum of ‘Kepler died in
misery’ in (3) is the same as the direct sense of ‘Kepler died in misery’ in
(1). Thus, while ‘Kepler died in misery’ in (1) designates a truthvalue,
‘Kepler died in misery’ in (3) designates a proposition, the direct (customary)
sense of the words ‘Kepler died in misery’ in (1).
obversion, a sort of
immediate inference that allows a transformation of affirmative categorical
A-propositions and I-propositions into the corresponding negative
E-propositions and O-propositions, and of E- and O-propositions into the
corresponding A- and I-propositions, keeping in each case the order of the
subject and predicate terms, but changing the original predicate into its
complement, i.e., into a negated term. For example, ‘Every man is mortal’ – ’No
man is non-mortal’; ‘Some students are happy’ – ‘Some students are not
non-happy’; ‘No dogs are jealous’ – ‘All dogs are non-jealous’; and ‘Some
bankers are not rich’ – ‘Some bankers are not non-rich’. SQUARE OF OPPOSITION, SYLLOGISM. I.Bo.
obviousness.SELF-EVIDENCE. Occam, William.OCKHAM. occasionalism, a theory of
causation held by a number of important seventeenth-century Cartesian
philosophers, including Johannes Clauberg (1622–65), Géraud de Cordemoy (1626–
84), Arnold Geulincx (1624–69), Louis de la Forge (1632–66), and Nicolas
Malebranche (1638–1715). In its most extreme version, occasionalism is the
doctrine that all finite created entities are devoid of causal efficacy, and
that God is the only true causal agent. Bodies do not cause effects in other
bodies nor in minds; and minds do not cause effects in bodies nor even within
themselves. God is directly, immediately, and solely responsible for bringing
about all phenomena. When a needle pricks the skin, the physical event is
merely an occasion for God to cause the relevant mental state (pain); a
volition in the soul to raise an arm or to think of something is only an
occasion for God to cause the arm to rise or the ideas to be present to the
mind; and the impact of one billiard ball upon another is an occasion for God
to move the second ball. In all three contexts – mind–body, body–body, and mind
alone – God’s ubiquitous causal activity proceeds in accordance with certain
general laws, and (except for miracles) he acts only when the requisite
material or psychic conditions obtain. Less thoroughgoing forms of occasionalism
limit divine causation (e.g., to mind–body or body–body alone). Far from being
an ad hoc solution to a Cartesian mind–body problem, as it is often considered,
occasionalism is argued for from general philosophical considerations regarding
the nature of causal relations (considerations that later appear, modified, in
Hume), from an analysis of the Cartesian concept of matoblique intention
occasionalism 626 626 ter and of the
necessary impotence of finite substance, and, perhaps most importantly, from
theological premises about the essential ontological relation between an
omnipotent God and the created world that he sustains in existence.
Occasionalism can also be regarded as a way of providing a metaphysical
foundation for explanations in mechanistic natural philosophy. Occasionalists
are arguing that motion must ultimately be grounded in something higher than
the passive, inert extension of Cartesian bodies (emptied of the substantial
forms of the Scholastics); it needs a causal ground in an active power. But if
a body consists in extension alone, motive force cannot be an inherent property
of bodies. Occasionalists thus identify force with the will of God. In this
way, they are simply drawing out the implications of Descartes’s own metaphysics
of matter and motion. CORDEMOY,
GEULINCX,
Occam, William
(c.1285–1347), also written William Occam, known as the More than Subtle
Doctor, English Scholastic philosopher known equally as the father of
nominalism and for his role in the Franciscan dispute with Pope John XXII over
poverty. Born probably in the village of Ockham near London, William Ockham
entered the Franciscan order at an early age and studied at Oxford, attaining
the rank of baccalarius formatus. His brilliant but controversial career was
cut short when John Lutterell, former chancellor of Oxford University,
presented the pope with a list of fifty-six allegedly heretical theses
extracted from Ockham’s writings. The papal commission studied them for two
years and found fifty-one open to censure, but none was formally condemned.
While in Avignon, Ockham researched previous papal concessions to the
Franciscans regarding collective poverty, eventually concluding that John XXII
contradicted his predecessors and hence was “no true pope.” After committing
these charges to writing, Ockham fled with Michael of Cesena, then minister
general of the order, first to Pisa and ultimately to Munich, where he lived
until his death, writing many treatises about church–state relations. Although
departures from his eminent predecessors have combined with ecclesiastical
difficulties to make Ockham unjustly notorious, his thought remains, by current
lights, philosophically and theologically conservative. On most metaphysical
issues, Ockham fancied himself the true interpreter of Aristotle. Rejecting the
doctrine that universals are real things other than names or concepts as “the
worst error of philosophy,” Ockham dismissed not only Platonism, but also
“modern realist” doctrines according to which natures enjoy a double mode of
existence and are universal in the intellect but numerically multiplied in
particulars. He argues that everything real is individual and particular, while
universality is a property pertaining only to names and that by virtue of their
signification relations. Because Ockham understands the primary names to be
mental (i.e., naturally significant concepts), his own theory of universals is
best classified as a form of conceptualism. Ockham rejects atomism, and defends
Aristotelian hylomorphism in physics and metaphysics, complete with its
distinction between substantial and accidental forms. Yet, he opposes the
reifying tendency of the “moderns” (unnamed contemporary opponents), who
posited a distinct kind of thing (res) for each of Aristotle’s ten categories;
he argues that – from a purely philosophical point of view – it is indefensible
to posit anything besides particular substances and qualities. Ockham followed
the Franciscan school in recognizing a plurality of substantial forms in living
things (in humans, the forms of corporeity, sensory soul, and intellectual
soul), but diverged from Duns Scotus in asserting a real, not a formal,
distinction among them. Aristotle had reached behind regular correlations in
nature to posit substance-things and accident-things as primitive explanatory
entities that essentially are or give rise to powers (virtus) that produce the
regularities; similarly, Ockham distinguishes efficient causality properly
speaking from sine qua non causality, depending on whether the correlation
between A’s and B’s is produced by the power of A or by the will of another,
and explicitly denies the existence of any sine qua non causation in nature.
Further, Ockham insists, in Aristotelian fashion, that created substance- and
accident-natures are essentially the causal powers they are in and of
themselves and hence independently of their relations to anything else; so that
not even God can make heat naturally a coolant. Yet, if God cannot change, He
shares with created things the occurrent Ockham, William 627 627 ability to obstruct such “Aristotelian”
productive powers and prevent their normal operation. Ockham’s nominalistic
conceptualism about universals does not keep him from endorsing the uniformity
of nature principle, because he holds that individual natures are powers and
hence that co-specific things are maximally similar powers. Likewise, he is
conventional in appealing to several other a priori causal principles:
“Everything that is in motion is moved by something,” “Being cannot come from
non-being,” “Whatever is produced by something is really conserved by something
as long as it exists.” He even recognizes a kind of necessary connection
between created causes and effects – e.g., while God could act alone to produce
any created effect, a particular created effect could not have had another
created cause of the same species instead. Ockham’s main innovation on the
topic of causality is his attack on Duns Scotus’s distinction between
“essential” and “accidental” orders and contrary contention that every genuine
efficient cause is an immediate cause of its effects. Ockham is an Aristotelian
reliabilist in epistemology, taking for granted as he does that human cognitive
faculties (the senses and intellect) work always or for the most part. Ockham
infers that since we have certain knowledge both of material things and of our
own mental acts, there must be some distinctive species of acts of awareness
(intuitive cognitions) that are the power to produce such evident judgments. Ockham
is matter-of-fact both about the disruption of human cognitive functions by
created obstacles (as in sensory illusion) and about divine power to intervene
in many ways. Such facts carry no skeptical consequences for Ockham, because he
defines certainty in terms of freedom from actual doubt and error, not from the
logical, metaphysical, or natural possibility of error. In action theory,
Ockham defends the liberty of indifference or contingency for all rational
beings, created or divine. Ockham shares Duns Scotus’s understanding of the
will as a self-determining power for opposites, but not his distaste for causal
models. Thus, Ockham allows that (1) unfree acts of will may be necessitated,
either by the agent’s own nature, by its other acts, or by an external cause;
and that (2) the efficient causes of free acts may include the agent’s
intellectual and sensory cognitions as well as the will itself. While
recognizing innate motivational tendencies in the human agent – e.g., the
inclination to seek sensory pleasure and avoid pain, the affectio commodi
(tendency to seek its own advantage), and the affectio iustitiae (inclination
to love things for their own intrinsic worth) – he denies that these limit the
will’s scope. Thus, Ockham goes beyond Duns Scotus in assigning the will the
power, with respect to any option, to will for it (velle), to will against it
(nolle), or not to act at all. In particular, Ockham concludes that the will
can will against (nolle) the good, whether ignorantly or perversely – by hating
God or by willing against its own happiness, the good-in-general, the enjoyment
of a clear vision of God, or its own ultimate end. The will can also will
(velle) evils – the opposite of what right reason dictates, unjust deeds qua
unjust, dishonest, and contrary to right reason, and evil under the aspect of
evil. Ockham enforces the traditional division of moral science into
non-positive morality or ethics, which directs acts apart from any precept of a
superior authority and draws its principles from reason and experience; and
positive morality, which deals with laws that oblige us to pursue or avoid
things, not because they are good or evil in themselves, but because some
legitimate superior commands them. The notion that Ockham sponsors an
unmodified divine command theory of ethics rests on conflation and confusion.
Rather, in the area of non-positive morality, Ockham advances what we might
label a “modified right reason theory,” which begins with the Aristotelian
ideal of rational self-government, according to which morally virtuous action
involves the agent’s free coordination of choice with right reason. He then
observes that suitably informed right reason would dictate that God, as the
infinite good, ought to be loved above all and for his own sake, and that such
love ought to be expressed by the effort to please him in every way (among
other things, by obeying all his commands). Thus, if right reason is the
primary norm in ethics, divine commands are a secondary, derivative norm. Once
again, Ockham is utterly unconcerned about the logical possibility opened by
divine liberty of indifference, that these twin norms might conflict (say, if
God commanded us to act contrary to right reason); for him, their de facto
congruence suffices for the moral life. In the area of soteriological merit and
demerit (a branch of positive morality), things are the other way around:
divine will is the primary norm; yet because God includes following the
dictates of right reason among the criteria for divine acceptance (thereby
giving the moral life eternal significance), right reason becomes a secondary
and derivative norm there.
Occam’s razor, also
called the principle of parsimony, a methodological principle commending a bias
toward simplicity in the construction of theories. The parameters whose
simplicity is singled out for attention have varied considerably, from kinds of
entities to the number of presupposed axioms to the nature of the curve drawn
between data points. Found already in Aristotle, the tag “entities should not
be multiplied beyond necessity” became associated with William Ockham (although
he never states that version, and even if non-contradiction rather than
parsimony is his favorite weapon in metaphysical disputes), perhaps because it
characterized the spirit of his philosophical conclusions. Opponents, who
thought parsimony was being carried too far, formulated an “anti-razor”: where
fewer entities do not suffice, posit more!
Olivi, Peter John
(c.1247–98), French philosopher-theologian whose views on the theory and
practice of Franciscan poverty led to a long series of investigations of his
orthodoxy. Olivi’s preference for humility, as well as the suspicion with which
he was regarded, prevented his becoming a master of theology at Paris. After
1285, he was effectively vindicated and permitted to teach at Florence and
Montpellier. But after his death, probably in part because his remains were
venerated and his views were championed by the Franciscan Spirituals, his
orthodoxy was again examined. The Council of Vienne (1311–12) condemned three
unrelated tenets associated with Olivi. Finally, in 1326, Pope John XXII
condemned a series of statements based on Olivi’s Apocalypse commentary. Olivi
thought of himself chiefly as a theologian, writing copious biblical
commentaries; his philosophy of history was influenced by Joachim of Fiore. His
views on poverty inspired the leader of the Franciscan Observant reform
movement, St. Bernardino of Siena. Apart from his views on poverty, Olivi is
best known for his philosophical independence from Aristotle, whom he condemned
as a materialist. Contrary to Aristotle’s theory of projectile motion, Olivi
advocated a theory of impetus. He undermined orthodox views on Aristotelian
categories. His attack on the category of relation was thought to have
dangerous implications in Trinitarian theology. Ockham’s theory of quantity is
in part a defense of views presented by Olivi. Olivi was critical of
Augustinian as well as Aristotelian views; he abandoned the theories of seminal
reason and divine illumination. He also argued against positing impressed
sensible and intelligible species, claiming that only the soul, not perceptual
objects, played an active role in perception. Bold as his philosophical views
were, he presented them tentatively. A voluntarist, he emphasized the
importance of will. He claimed that an act of understanding was not possible in
the absence of an act of will. He provided an important experiential argument
for the freedom of the will. His treatises on contracts revealed a
sophisticated understanding of economics. His treatise on evangelical poverty
includes the first defense of a theory of papal infallibility. R.W.
Olympiodorus.
NEOPLATONISM. omega, the
last letter of the Greek alphabet (w). Following Cantor (1845–1911), it is used
in lowercase as a proper name for the first infinite ordinal number, which is
the ordinal of the natural ordering of the set of finite ordinals. By extension
it is also used as a proper name for the set of finite ordinals itself or even
for the set of natural numbers. Following Gödel (1906–78), it is used as a
prefix in names of various logical properties of sets of sentences, most
notably omega-completeness and omega-consistency. Omega-completeness, in the
original sense due to Tarski, is a syntactical property of sets of sentences in
a formal arithmetic language involving a symbol ‘0’ for the number zero and a
symbol ‘s’ for the so-called successor function, resulting in each natural
number being named by an expression, called a numeral, in the following series:
‘0’, ‘s0’, ‘ss0’, and so on. For example, five is denoted by ‘sssss0’. A set of
sentences is said to be omegacomplete if it (deductively) yields every
universal sentence all of whose singular instances it yields. In this framework,
as usual, every universal sentence, ‘for every n, n has P’ yields each and
every one of its singular instances, ‘0 has P’, ‘s0 has P’, ‘ss0 has P’, etc.
However, as had been known by logicians at least since the Middle Ages, the
converse is not true, i.e., it is not in general the case that a universal
sentence is deducible from the set of its singular instances. Thus one should
not expect to find omega-completeness except in exceptional sets. The set of
all true sentences of arithmetic is such an exceptional set; the reason is the
semantic fact that every universal sentence (whether or not in arithmetic) is
materially equivalent to the set of all its singular instances. A set of
sentences that is not omega-complete is Ockham’s razor omega 629 629 said to be omega-incomplete. The
existence of omega-incomplete sets of sentences is a phenomenon at the core of
the 1931 Gödel incompleteness result, which shows that every “effective” axiom
set for arithmetic is omega-incomplete and thus has as theorems all singular
instances of a universal sentence that is not one of its theorems. Although
this is a remarkable fact, the existence of omega-incomplete sets per se is far
from remarkable, as suggested above. In fact, the empty set and equivalently
the set of all tautologies are omega-incomplete because each yields all
singular instances of the non-tautological formal sentence, here called FS,
that expresses the proposition that every number is either zero or a successor.
Omega-consistency belongs to a set that does not yield the negation of any
universal sentence all of whose singular instances it yields. A set that is not
omega-consistent is said to be omega-inconsistent. Omega-inconsistency of
course implies consistency in the ordinary sense; but it is easy to find
consistent sets that are not omega-consistent, e.g., the set whose only member
is the negation of the formal sentence FS mentioned above. Corresponding to the
syntactical properties just mentioned there are analogous semantic properties
whose definitions are obtained by substituting ‘(semantically) implies’ for
‘(deductively) yields’. The Greek letter omega and its English name have many
other uses in modern logic. Carnap introduced a non-effective, non-logical
rule, called the omega rule, for “inferring” a universal sentence from its
singular instances; adding the omega rule to a standard axiomatization of
arithmetic produces a complete but non-effective axiomatization. An
omega-valued logic is a many-valued logic whose set of truth-values is or is
the same size as the set of natural numbers.
one–many problem, also
called one-and-many problem, the question whether all things are one or many.
According to both Plato and Aristotle this was the central question for
pre-Socratic philosophers. Those who answered “one,” the monists, ascribed to
all things a single nature such as water, air, or oneness itself. They appear
not to have been troubled by the notion that numerically many things would have
this one nature. The pluralists, on the other hand, distinguished many
principles or many types of principles, though they also maintained the unity
of each principle. Some monists understood the unity of all things as a denial
of motion, and some pluralists advanced their view as a way of refuting this
denial. To judge from our sources, early Greek metaphysics revolved around the
problem of the one and the many. In the modern period the dispute between
monists and pluralists centered on the question whether mind and matter
constitute one or two substances and, if one, what its nature is. PRE-SOCRATICS, SPINOZA. E.C.H. one over many,
a universal; especially, a Platonic Form. According to Plato, if there are,
e.g., many large things, there must be some one largeness itself in respect of
which they are large; this “one over many” (hen epi pollon) is an intelligible
entity, a Form, in contrast with the sensible many. Plato himself recognizes
difficulties explaining how the one character can be present to the many and
why the one and the many do not together constitute still another many (e.g.,
Parmenides 131a–133b). Aristotle’s sustained critique of Plato’s Forms
(Metaphysics A 9, Z 13–15) includes these and other problems, and it is he,
more than Plato, who regularly uses ‘one over many’ to refer to Platonic Forms.
ARISTOTLE, ONE–MANY
PROBLEM, PLATO. E.C.H. omega, order type one over many 630 630 one-way reduction sentence.REDUCTION
SENTENCE. ontological argument.PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. ontological commitment,
the object or objects common to the ontology fulfilling some (regimented)
theory (a term fashioned by Quine). The ontology of a (regimented) theory
consists in the objects the theory assumes there to be. In order to show that a
theory assumes a given object, or objects of a given class, we must show that
the theory would be true only if that object existed, or if that class is not
empty. This can be shown in two different but equivalent ways: if the notation
of the theory contains the existential quantifier ‘(Ex)’ of first-order
predicate logic, then the theory is shown to assume a given object, or objects
of a given class, provided that object is required among the values of the
bound variables, or (additionally) is required among the values of the domain
of a given predicate, in order for the theory to be true. Thus, if the theory
entails the sentence ‘(Ex)(x is a dog)’, then the values over which the bound
variable ‘x’ ranges must include at least one dog, in order for the theory to
be true. Alternatively, if the notation of the theory contains for each predicate
a complementary predicate, then the theory assumes a given object, or objects
of a given class, provided some predicate is required to be true of that
object, in order for the theory to be true. Thus, if the theory contains the
predicate ‘is a dog’, then the extension of ‘is a dog’ cannot be empty, if the
theory is to be true. However, it is possible for different, even mutually
exclusive, ontologies to fulfill a theory equally well. Thus, an ontology
containing collies to the exclusion of spaniels and one containing spaniels to
the exclusion of collies might each fulfill a theory that entails ‘(Ex) (x is a
dog)’. It follows that some of the objects a theory assumes (in its ontology)
may not be among those to which the theory is ontologically committed. A theory
is ontologically committed to a given object only if that object is common to
all of the ontologies fulfilling the theory. And the theory is ontologically
committed to objects of a given class provided that class is not empty
according to each of the ontologies fulfilling the theory.
open formula, also called
open sentence, a sentence with a free occurrence of a variable. A closed
sentence, sometimes called a statement, has no free occurrences of variables.
In a language whose only variable-binding operators are quantifiers, an
occurrence of a variable in a formula is bound provided that occurrence either
is within the scope of a quantifier employing that variable or is the
occurrence in that quantifier. An occurrence of a variable in a formula is free
provided it is not bound. The formula ‘xy ( O’ is open because both ‘x’ and ‘y’
occur as free variables. In ‘For some real number y, xy ( O’, no occurrence of
‘y’ is free; but the occurrence of ‘x’ is free, so the formula is open. The
sentence ‘For every real number x, for some real number y, xy ( O’ is closed,
since none of the variables occur free. Semantically, an open formula such as
‘xy ( 0’ is neither true nor false but rather true of or false of each
assignment of values to its free-occurring variables. For example, ‘xy ( 0’ is
true of each assignment of two positive or two negative real numbers to ‘x’ and
to ‘y’ and it is false of each assignment of 0 to either and false at each
assignment of a positive real to one of the variables and a negative to the
other.
open texture, the
possibility of vagueness. Frieone-way reduction sentence open texture 631 631 drich Waismann (“Verifiability,”
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 1945) introduced the concept, claiming
that open texture is a universal property of empirical terms. Waismann claimed
that an inexhaustible source of vagueness remains even after measures are taken
to make an expression precise. His grounds were, first, that there are an
indefinite number of possibilities for which it is indeterminate whether the
expression applies (i.e., for which the expression is vague). There is, e.g.,
no definite answer whether a catlike creature that repeatedly vanishes into
thin air, then reappears, is a cat. Waismann’s explanation is that when we
define an empirical term, we frame criteria of its applicability only for
foreseeable circumstances. Not all possible situations in which we may use the
term, however, can be foreseen. Thus, in unanticipated circumstances, real or
merely possible, a term’s criteria of applicability may yield no definite
answer to whether it applies. Second, even for terms such as ‘gold’, for which
there are several precise criteria of application (specific gravity, X-ray
spectrograph, solubility in aqua regia), applying different criteria can yield
divergent verdicts, the result being vagueness. Waismann uses the concept of
open texture to explain why experiential statements are not conclusively
verifiable, and why phenomenalist attempts to translate material object statements
fail.
PHENOMENALISM, VAGUENESS,
VERIFICATIONISM. W.K.W. operant conditioning.CONDITIONING. operational
definition.OPERATIONALISM. operationalism, a program in philosophy of science
that aims to interpret scientific concepts via experimental procedures and
observational outcomes. P. W. Bridgman introduced the terminology when he
required that theoretical concepts be identified with the operations used to
measure them. Logical positivism’s criteria of cognitive significance
incorporated the notion: Bridgman’s operationalism was assimilated to the
positivistic requirement that theoretical terms T be explicitly defined via
(logically equivalent to) directly observable conditions O. Explicit
definitions failed to accommodate alternative measurement procedures for the
same concept, and so were replaced by reduction sentences that partially
defined individual concepts in observational terms via sentences such as ‘Under
observable circumstances C, x is T if and only if O’. Later this was weakened
to allow ensembles of theoretical concepts to be partially defined via
interpretative systems specifying collective observable effects of the concepts
rather than effects peculiar to single concepts. These cognitive significance
notions were incorporated into various behaviorisms, although the term
‘operational definition’ is rarely used by scientists in Bridgman’s or the
explicit definition senses: intervening variables are theoretical concepts
defined via reduction sentences and hypothetical constructs are definable by
interpretative systems but not reduction sentences. In scientific contexts
observable terms often are called dependent or independent variables. When, as
in science, the concepts in theoretical assertions are only partially defined,
observational consequences do not exhaust their content, and so observational
data underdetermines the truth of such assertions in the sense that more than
one theoretical assertion will be compatible with maximal observational
data.
operator, a one-place
sentential connective; i.e., an expression that may be prefixed to an open or
closed sentence to produce, respectively, a new open or closed sentence. Thus
‘it is not the case that’ is a (truth-functional) operator. The most thoroughly
investigated operators are the intensional ones; an intensional operator O,
when prefixed to an open or closed sentence E, produces an open or closed
sentence OE, whose extension is determined not by the extension of E but by
some other property of E, which varies with the choice of O. For example, the
extension of a closed sentence is its truth-value A, but if the modal operator
‘it is necessary that’ is prefixed to A, the extension of the result depends on
whether A’s extension belongs to it necessarily or contingently. This property
of A is usually modeled by assigning to A a subset X of a domain of possible
worlds W. If X % W then ‘it is necessary that A’ is true, but if X is a proper
subset of W, it is false. Another example involves the epistemic operator ‘it
is plausible that’. Since a true sentence may be either plausible or
implausible, the truth-value of ‘it is plausible that A’ is not fixed by the
truth-value of A, but rather by the body of evidence that supports A relative
to a thinker in a given context. This may also be modeled in a possible worlds
framework, by operant conditioning operator 632 632 stipulating, for each world, which
worlds, if any, are plausible relative to it. The topic of intensional
operators is controversial, and it is even disputable whether standard examples
really are operators at the correct level of logical form. For instance, it can
be argued that ‘it is necessary that’, upon analysis, turns out to be a
universal quantifier over possible worlds, or a predicate of expressions. On
the former view, instead of ‘it is necessary that A’ we should write ‘for every
possible world w, A(w)’, and, on the latter, ‘A is necessarily true’.
.
operator theory of
adverbs, a theory that treats adverbs and other predicate modifiers as
predicate-forming operators on predicates. The theory expands the syntax of
first-order logic by adding operators of various degrees, and makes
corresponding additions to the semantics. Romane Clark, Terence Parsons, and
Richard Montague (with Hans Kamp) developed the theory independently in the
early 1970s. For example: ‘John runs quickly through the kitchen’ contains a
simple one-place predicate, ‘runs’ (applied to John); a zero-place operator,
‘quickly’, and a one-place operator, ‘through ()’ (with ‘the kitchen’ filling
its place). The logical form of the sentence becomes [O1 1(a) [O2 0 [P(b)]]],
which can be read: [through (the kitchen) [quickly [runs (John)]]].
Semantically ‘quickly’ will be associated with an operation that takes us from
the extension of ‘runs’ to a subset of that extension. ‘John runs quickly’ will
imply ‘John runs’. ‘Through (the kitchen)’ and other operators are handled
similarly. The wide variety of predicate modifiers complicates the inferential
conditions and semantics of the operators. ‘John is finally done’ implies ‘John
is done’. ‘John is nearly done’ implies ‘John is not done’. Clark tries to
distinguish various types of predicate modifiers and provides a different
semantic analysis for operators of different sorts. The theory can easily
characterize syntactic aspects of predicate modifier iteration. In addition,
after being modified the original predicates remain as predicates, and maintain
their original degree. Further, there is no need to force John’s running into
subject position as might be the case if we try to make ‘quickly’ an ordinary
predicate. T.J.D. O-proposition.
.
order, the level of a
logic as determined by the type of entity over which the free variables of that
logic range. Entities of the lowest type, usually called type O, are known as
individuals, and entities of higher type are constructed from entities of lower
type. For example, type 1 entities are (i) functions from individuals or
n-tuples of individuals to individuals, and (ii) n-place relations on
individuals. First-order logic is that logic whose variables range over
individuals, and a model for first-order logic includes a domain of
individuals. The other logics are known as higher-order logics, and the first
of these is second-order logic, in which there are variables that range over
type 1 entities. In a model for second-order logic, the first-order domain
determines the second-order domain. For every sentence to have a definite
truth-value, only totally defined functions are allowed in the range of
second-order function variables, so these variables range over the collection
of total functions from n-tuples of individuals to individuals, for every value
of n. The second-order predicate variables range over all subsets of n-tuples
of individuals. Thus if D is the domain of individuals of a model, the type 1
entities are the union of the two sets {X: Dn: X 0 Dn$D}, {X: Dn: X 0 Dn}.
Quantifiers may bind second-order variables and are subject to introduction and
elimination rules. Thus whereas in first-order logic one may infer ‘Someone is
wise, ‘(Dx)Wx’, from ‘Socrates is wise’, ‘Ws’, in second-order logic one may
also infer ‘there is something that Socrates is’, ‘(DX)Xs’. The step from
first- to second-order logic iterates: in general, type n entities are the
domain of n ! 1th–order variables in n ! 1th– order logic, and the whole
hierarchy is known as the theory of types.
TYPE THEORY. G.Fo. ordered n-tuple.SET THEORY. ordered pair.SET THEORY.
operator, deontic ordered pair 633 633
ordering, an arrangement of the elements of a set so that some of them come
before others. If X is a set, it is useful to identify an ordering R of X with
a subset R of X$X, the set of all ordered pairs with members in X. If ‹ x,y ( 1
R then x comes before y in the ordering of X by R, and if ‹ x,y ( 2 R and ‹ y,x
( 2 R, then x and y are incomparable. Orders on X are therefore relations on X,
since a relation on a set X is any subset of X $ X. Some minimal conditions a
relation must meet to be an ordering are (i) reflexivity: (Ex)Rxx; (ii)
antisymmetry: (Ex)(Ey)((Rxy & Ryx) / x % y); and (iii) transitivity:
(Ex)(Ey)(Ez)((Rxy & Ryz) / Rxz). A relation meeting these three conditions
is known as a partial order (also less commonly called a semi-order), and if
reflexivity is replaced by irreflexivity, (Ex)-Rxx, as a strict partial order.
Other orders are strengthenings of these. Thus a tree-ordering of X is a
partial order with a distinguished root element a, i.e. (Ex)Rax, and that
satisfies the backward linearity condition that from any element there is a
unique path back to a: (Ex)(Ey)(Ez)((Ryx & Rzx) / (Ryz 7 Rzy). A total order
on X is a partial order satisfying the connectedness requirement: (Ex)(Ey)(Rxy
7 Ryx). Total orderings are sometimes known as strict linear orderings,
contrasting with weak linear orderings, in which the requirement of
antisymmetry is dropped. The natural number line in its usual order is a strict
linear order; a weak linear ordering of a set X is a strict linear order of
levels on which various members of X may be found, while adding antisymmetry
means that each level contains only one member. Two other important orders are
dense (partial or total) orders, in which, between any two elements, there is a
third; and well-orders. A set X is said to be well-ordered by R if R is total
and every non-empty subset of Y of X has an R-least member: (EY 0 X)[Y & /
/ (Dz 1 Y)(Ew 1 Y)Rzw]. Well-ordering rules out infinite descending sequences,
while a strict well-ordering, which is irreflexive rather than reflexive, rules
out loops. The best-known example is the membership relation of axiomatic set
theory, in which there are no loops such as x 1 y 1 x or x 1 x, and no infinite
descending chains . . . x2 1 x1 1 x0.
RELATION, SET THEORY. G.Fo. ordering, Archimedian.LEXICAL ORDERING.
order type omega, in mathematics, the order type of the infinite set of natural
numbers. The last letter of the Greek alphabet, w, is used to denote this order
type; w is thus the first infinite ordinal number. It can be defined as the set
of all finite ordinal numbers ordered by magnitude; that is, w % {0,1,2,3 . . .
}. A set has order type w provided it is denumerably infinite, has a first
element but not a last element, has for each element a unique successor, and
has just one element with no immediate predecessor. The set of even numbers
ordered by magnitude, {2,4,6,8 . . . }, is of order type w. The set of natural
numbers listing first all even numbers and then all odd numbers, {2,4,6,8 . .
.; 1,3,5,7 . . . }, is not of order type w, since it has two elements, 1 and 2,
with no immediate predecessor. The set of negative integers ordered by magnitude,
{ . . . –3,–2,–1}, is also not of order type w, since it has no first element.
V.K. ordinal logic, any means of associating effectively and uniformly a logic
(in the sense of a formal axiomatic system) Sa with each constructive ordinal
notation a. This notion and term for it was introduced by Alan Turing in his
paper “Systems of Logic Based on Ordinals” (1939). Turing’s aim was to try to
overcome the incompleteness of formal systems discovered by Gödel in 1931, by
means of the transfinitely iterated, successive adjunction of unprovable but
correct principles. For example, according to Gödel’s second incompleteness
theorem, for each effectively presented formal system S containing a modicum of
elementary number theory, if S is consistent then S does not prove the purely
universal arithmetical proposition Cons expressing the consistency of S (via
the Gödelnumbering of symbolic expressions), even though Cons is correct.
However, it may be that the result S’ of adjoining Cons to S is inconsistent.
This will not happen if every purely existential statement provable in S is
correct; call this condition (E-C). Then if S satisfies (E-C), so also does S;
% S ! Cons ; now S; is still incomplete by Gödel’s theorem, though it is more
complete than S. Clearly the passage from S to S; can be iterated any finite
number of times, beginning with any S0 satisfying (E-C), to form S1 % S; 0, S2
% S; 1, etc. But this procedure can also be extended into the transfinite, by
taking Sw to be the union of the systems Sn for n % 0,1, 2 . . . and then Sw!1
% S;w, Sw!2 % S;w!1, etc.; condition (EC) is preserved throughout. To see how
far this and other effective extension procedures of any effectively presented
system S to another S; can be iterated into the transfinite, one needs the notion
of the set O of constructive ordinal notations, due to Alonzo Church and
Stephen C. Kleene in 1936. O is a set ordering ordinal logic 634 634 of natural numbers, and each a in O
denotes an ordinal a, written as KaK. There is in O a notation for 0, and with
each a in O is associated a notation sc(a) in O with Ksc(a)K % KaK ! 1;
finally, if f is a number of an effective function {f} such that for each n,
{f}(n) % an is in O and KanK < Kan!1K, then we have a notation ø(f) in O
with Kø(f)K % limnKanK. For quite general effective extension procedures of S
to S; and for any given S0, one can associate with each a in O a formal system
Sa satisfying Ssc(a) % S;a and Sø(f) % the union of the S{f}(n) for n % 0,1, 2.
. . . However, as there might be many notations for each constructive ordinal,
this ordinal logic need not be invariant, in the sense that one need not have:
if KaK % KbK then Sa and Sb have the same consequences. Turing proved that an
ordinal logic cannot be both complete for true purely universal statements and
invariant. Using an extension procedure by certain proof-theoretic reflection
principles, he constructed an ordinal logic that is complete for true purely
universal statements, hence not invariant. (The history of this and later work
on ordinal logics is traced by the undersigned in “Turing in the Land of O(z),”
in The Universal Turing Machine: A Half Century Survey, edited by Rolf Herken
[1988].)
ordinary language
philosophy, a loosely structured philosophical movement holding that the
significance of concepts, including those central to traditional philosophy –
e.g., the concepts of truth and knowledge – is fixed by linguistic practice.
Philosophers, then, must be attuned to the actual uses of words associated with
these concepts. The movement enjoyed considerable prominence chiefly among
English-speaking philosophers between the mid-1940s and the early 1960s. It was
initially inspired by the work of Wittgenstein, and later by John Wisdom,
Gilbert Ryle, Norman Malcolm, and J. L. Austin, though its roots go back at
least to Moore and arguably to Socrates. Ordinary language philosophers do not
mean to suggest that, to discover what truth is, we are to poll our fellow
speakers or consult dictionaries. Rather, we are to ask how the word ‘truth’
functions in everyday, nonphilosophical settings. A philosopher whose theory of
truth is at odds with ordinary usage has simply misidentified the concept.
Philosophical error, ironically, was thought by Wittgenstein to arise from our
“bewitchment” by language. When engaging in philosophy, we may easily be misled
by superficial linguistic similarities. We suppose minds to be special sorts of
entity, for instance, in part because of grammatical parallels between ‘mind’
and ‘body’. When we fail to discover any entity that might plausibly count as a
mind, we conclude that minds must be nonphysical entities. The cure requires
that we remind ourselves how ‘mind’ and its cognates are actually used by
ordinary speakers. ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY;
AUSTIN, J. J.F.H. organic, having parts that are organized and interrelated in
a way that is the same as, or analogous to, the way in which the parts of a
living animal or other biological organism are organized and interrelated.
Thus, an organic unity or organic whole is a whole that is organic in the above
sense. These terms are primarily used of entities that are not literally
organisms but are supposedly analogous to them. Among the applications of the
concept of an organic unity are: to works of art, to the state (e.g., by
Hegel), and to the universe as a whole (e.g., in absolute idealism). The
principal element in the concept is perhaps the notion of an entity whose parts
cannot be understood except by reference to their contribution to the whole
entity. Thus to describe something as an organic unity is typically to imply
that its properties cannot be given a reductive explanation in terms of those
of its parts; rather, at least some of the properties of the parts must
themselves be explained by reference to the properties of the whole. Hence it
usually involves a form of holism. Other features sometimes attributed to
organic unities include a mutual dependence between the existence of the parts
and that of the whole and the need for a teleological explanation of properties
of the parts in terms of some end or purpose associated with the whole. To what
extent these characteristics belong to genuine biological organisms is
disputed.
organicism, a theory that
applies the notion of an organic unity, especially to things that are not
literally organisms. G. E. Moore, in Principia Ethica, proposed a principle of
organic unities, concerning intrinsic value: the (intrinsic) value of a whole need
not be equivalent to the sum of the (intrinsic) values of its parts. Moore
applies the principle in arguing that there is no systematic relation between
ordinal utility organicism 635 635 the
intrinsic value of an element of a complex whole and the difference that the
presence of that element makes to the value of the whole. E.g., he holds that
although a situation in which someone experiences pleasure in the contemplation
of a beautiful object has far greater intrinsic goodness than a situation in which
the person contemplates the same object without feeling pleasure, this does not
mean that the pleasure itself has much intrinsic value.
organism, a carbon-based
living thing or substance, e.g., a paramecium, a tree, or an ant.
Alternatively, ‘organism’ can mean a hypothetical living thing of another
natural kind, e.g., a silicon-based living thing. Defining conditions of a
carbon-based living thing, x, are as follows. (1) x has a layer made of
m-molecules, i.e., carbonbased macromolecules of repeated units that have a
high capacity for selective reactions with other similar molecules. x can
absorb and excrete through this layer. (2) x can metabolize m-molecules. (3) x
can synthesize m-molecular parts of x by means of activities of a proper part
of x that is a nuclear molecule, i.e., an m-molecule that can copy itself. (4)
x can exercise the foregoing capacities in such a way that the corresponding
activities are causally interrelated as follows: x’s absorption and excretion
causally contribute to x’s metabolism; these processes jointly causally
contribute to x’s synthesizing; and x’s synthesizing causally contributes to
x’s absorption, excretion, and metabolism. (5) x belongs to a natural kind of
compound physical substance that can have a member, y, such that: y has a
proper part, z; z is a nuclear molecule; and y reproduces by means of z’s
copying itself. (6) x is not possibly a proper part of something that satisfies
(1)–(6). The last condition expresses the independence and autonomy of an
organism. For example, a part of an organism, e.g., a heart cell, is not an
organism. It also follows that a colony of organisms, e.g., a colony of ants,
is not an organism.
LIFE, ORGANIC,
ORGANICISM. J.Ho. & G.Ro. Organon.ARISTOTLE. Origen (A.D. 185–253), Christian
theologian and biblical scholar in the Alexandrian church. Born in Egypt, he
became head of the catechetical school in Alexandria. Like his mentor, Clement
of Alexandria, he was influenced by Middle Platonism. His principal works were
Hexapla, On First Principles, and Contra Celsum. The Hexapla, little of which
survives, consisted of six Hebrew and two Greek versions of the Old Testament
with Origen’s commentary. On First Principles sets forth the most systematic
Christian theology of the early church, including some doctrines subsequently
declared heretical, such as the subordination of the Son (“a secondary god”)
and Spirit to the Father, preexisting human souls (but not their
transmigration), and a premundane fall from grace of each human soul. The most
famous of his views was the notion of apocatastasis, universal salvation, the
universal restoration of all creation to God in which evil is defeated and the
devil and his minions repent of their sins. He interpreted hell as a temporary
purgatory in which impure souls were purified and made ready for heaven. His
notion of subordination of the Son of God to the Father was condemned by the
church in 533. Origen’s Contra Celsum is the first sustained work in Christian
apologetics. It defends Christianity before the pagan world. Origen was a
leading exponent of the allegorical interpretation of the Scriptures, holding
that the text had three levels of meaning corresponding to the three parts of
human nature: body, soul, and spirit. The first was the historical sense,
sufficient for simple people; the second was the moral sense; and the third was
the mystical sense, open only to the deepest souls. L.P.P. original position.
LIBERALISM, RAWLS.
Orpheus.ORPHISM. Orphism, a religious movement in ancient Greece that may have
influenced Plato and some of the pre-Socratics. Neither the nature of the
movement nor the scope of its influence is adequately understood: ancient
sources and modern scholars tend to confuse Orphism with Pythagoreanism and
with ancient mystery cults, especially the Bacchic or Dionysiac mysteries.
“Orphic poems,” i.e., poems attributed to Orpheus (a mythic figure), circulated
as early as the mid-sixth century B.C. We have only indirect evidence of the
early Orphic poems; but we do have a sizable body of fragments from poems
composed in later antiquity. Central to both early and later versions is a
theogonic-cosmogonic narrative that posits Night as the primal entity –
ostensibly a revision of the account offered by Hesiod – and gives major
emphasis to organic unity Orphism 636
636 Ortega y Gasset, José outer converse 637 the birth, death through
dismemberment, and rebirth of the god Dionysus. Plato gives us clear evidence
of the existence in his time of itinerant religious teachers who, drawing on the
“books of Orpheus,” performed and taught rituals of initiation and purification
intended to procure divine favor either in this life or in an afterlife. The
extreme skepticism of such scholars as Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff and
I. M. Linforth concerning the importance of early Orphism for Greek religion
and Greek philosophy has been undermined by archaeological findings in recent
decades: the Derveni papyrus, which is a fragment of a philosophical commentary
on an Orphic theogony; and inscriptions with Orphic instructions for the dead,
from funerary sites in southern Italy, mainland Greece, and the Crimea.
A.P.D.M. Ortega y Gasset, José (1883–1955), Spanish philosopher and essayist.
Born in Madrid, he studied there and in Leipzig, Berlin, and Marburg. In 1910
he was named professor of metaphysics at the University of Madrid and taught
there until 1936, when he was forced to leave because of his political
involvement in and support for the Spanish Republic. He returned to Spain in
1945. Ortega was a prolific writer whose works fill nine thick volumes. Among
his most influential books are Meditaciones del Quijote (“Meditations on the
Quixote,” 1914), El tema de nuestro tiempo (“The Modern Theme,” 1923), La
revolución de las masas (“The Revolt of the Masses,” 1932), La deshumanización
del arte (“The Dehumanization of Art,” 1925), Historia como sistema (“History
as a System,” 1941), and the posthumously published El hombre y la gente (“Man
and People,” 1957) and La idea de principio en Leibniz(“The Idea of Principle
in Leibniz,” 1958). His influence in Spain and Latin America was enormous, in
part because of his brilliant style of writing and lecturing. He avoided jargon
and rejected systematization; most of his works were first written as articles
for newspapers and magazines. In 1923 he founded the Revista de Occidente, a
cultural magazine that helped spread his ideas and introduced German thought
into Spain and Latin America. Ortega ventured into nearly every branch of
philosophy, but the kernel of his views is his metaphysics of vital reason
(rasón vital) and his perspectival epistemology. For Ortega, reality is
identified with “my life”; something is real only insofar as it is rooted and
appears in “my life.” “My life” is further unpacked as “myself” and “my
circumstances” (“yo soy yo y mi circumstancia“). The self is not an entity
separate from what surrounds it; there is a dynamic interaction and
interdependence of self and things. These and the self together constitute
reality. Because every life is the result of an interaction between self and
circumstances, every self has a unique perspective. Truth, then, is
perspectival, depending on the unique point of view from which it is
determined, and no perspective is false except one that claims exclusivity.
This doctrine is known as Ortega’s perspectivism. J.J.E.G. ostensive
definition.DEFINITION. Ostwald, Wilhelm.ENERGETICISM. other minds, problem of.
PROBLEM OF OTHER MINDS.
ought–is problem.FACT–VALUE DISTINCTION. ousia, ancient Greek term
traditionally translated as ‘substance’. Formed from the participle for
‘being’, the term ousia refers to the character of being, beingness, as if this
were itself an entity. Just as redness is the character that red things have,
so ousia is the character that beings have. Thus, the ousia of something is the
character that makes it be, its nature. But ousia also refers to an entity that
possesses being in its own right; for consider a case where the ousia of
something is just the thing itself. Such a thing possesses being by virtue of
itself; because its being depends on nothing else, it is self-subsistent and
has a higher degree of being than things whose being depends on something else.
Such a thing would be an ousia. Just which entities meet the criteria for ousia
is a question addressed by Aristotle. Something such as redness that exists
only as an attribute would not have being in its own right. An individual
person is an ousia, but Aristotle also argues that his form is more properly an
ousia; and an unmoved mover is the highest type of ousia. The traditional
rendering of the term into Latin as substantia and English as ‘substance’ is
appropriate only in contexts like Aristotle’s Categories where an ousia “stands
under” attributes. In his Metaphysics, where Aristotle argues that being a
substrate does not characterize ousia, and in other Greek writers, ‘substance’
is often not an apt translation.
SUBSTANCE. E.C.H. outer converse.CONVERSE, OUTER AND INNER. 637 outer domain semantics.
FREE LOGIC.
overdetermination.CAUSATION. overman.NIETZSCHE. overriding reason.REASONS FOR
ACTION. Oxford Calculators, a group of natural philosophers, mathematicians,
and logicians who flourished at Oxford University in the second quarter of the
fourteenth century. The name derives from the Liber calculationum (Book of
Calculations), written some time before 1350. The author of this work, often
called “Calculator” by later Continental authors, was probably named Richard
Swineshead. The Book of Calculations discussed a number of issues related to
the quantification or measurement of local motion, alteration, and augmentation
(for a fuller description, see John Murdoch and Edith Sylla, “Swineshead,
Richard,” in Dictionary of Scientific Biography, Vol. 13, 1976). The Book of
Calculations has been studied mainly by historians of science and grouped
together with a number of other works discussing natural philosophical topics
by such authors as Thomas Bradwardine, William Heytesbury, and John Dumbleton.
In earlier histories many of the authors now referred to as Oxford Calculators
are referred to as the Merton School, since many of them were fellows of Merton
College. But since some authors whose work appears to fit into the same
intellectual tradition (e.g., Richard Kilvington, whose Sophismata represents
an earlier stage of the tradition later epitomized by William Heytesbury’s
Sophismata) have no known connection with Merton College, the name ‘Oxford
Calculators’ would appear to be a more accurate appellation. The works of the
Oxford Calculators were produced in the context of education in the Oxford arts
faculty (see Edith Sylla, “The Oxford Calculators,” in Norman Kretzmann,
Anthony Kenny, and Jan Pinborg, eds., The Cambridge History of Later Medieval
Philosophy, 1982). In Oxford at this time logic was the centerpiece of the
early years of undergraduate education. After logic, Oxford came to be known
for its work in mathematics, astronomy, and natural philosophy. Students
studying under the Oxford faculty of arts not only heard lectures on the liberal
arts and on natural philosophy, moral philosophy, and metaphysics; they were
also required to take part in disputations. William Heytesbury’s Regule
solvendi sophismatum (Rules for Solving Sophismata) explicitly and Swineshead’s
Book of Calculations implicitly are written to prepare students for these
disputations. The three influences most formative on the work of the Oxford
Calculators were (1) the tradition of commentaries on the works of Aristotle;
(2) the developments in logical theory, particularly the theories of
categorematic and syncategorematic terms and the theory of logical supposition;
and (3) developments in mathematics, particularly the theory of ratios as
developed in Thomas Bradwardine’s De proportionibus velocitatum in motibus (On the
Ratios of Velocities in Motions). In addition to Richard Swineshead,
Heytesbury, Bradwardine, Dumbleton, and Kilvington, other authors and works
related to the work of the Oxford Calculators are Walter Burley, De primo et
ultimo instanti, Tractatus Primus (De formis accidentalibus), Tractatus
Secundus (De intensione et remissione formarum); Roger Swineshead,
Descriptiones motuum; and John Bode, A est unum calidum. These and other works
had a considerable later influence on the Continent.
BURLEY, COMMENTARIES ON
ARISTOTLE, HEYTESBURY, KILVINGTON. E.D.S. Oxford philosophy.ANALYTIC
PHILOSOPHY. Oxford school of intuitionism.PRICHARD. outer domain semantics
Oxford school of intuitionism 638 638
PA.APPENDIX OF SPECIAL SYMBOLS. pa.WANG, PA. pacifism, (1) opposition to war,
usually on moral or religious grounds, but sometimes on the practical ground
(pragmatic pacifism) that it is wasteful and ineffective; (2) opposition to all
killing and violence; (3) opposition only to war of a specified kind (e.g.,
nuclear pacifism). Not to be confused with passivism, pacifism usually involves
actively promoting peace, understood to imply cooperation and justice among
peoples and not merely absence of war. But some (usually religious) pacifists
accept military service so long as they do not carry weapons. Many pacifists
subscribe to nonviolence. But some consider violence and/or killing
permissible, say, in personal self-defense, law enforcement, abortion, or
euthanasia. Absolute pacifism rejects war in all circumstances, hypothetical
and actual. Conditional pacifism concedes war’s permissibility in some
hypothetical circumstances but maintains its wrongness in practice. If at least
some hypothetical wars have better consequences than their alternative,
absolute pacifism will almost inevitably be deontological in character, holding
war intrinsically wrong or unexceptionably prohibited by moral principle or
divine commandment. Conditional pacifism may be held on either deontological or
utilitarian (teleological or sometimes consequentialist) grounds. If
deontological, it may hold war at most prima facie wrong intrinsically but
nonetheless virtually always impermissible in practice because of the absence
of counterbalancing right-making features. If utilitarian, it will hold war wrong,
not intrinsically, but solely because of its consequences. It may say either
that every particular war has worse consequences than its avoidance (act
utilitarianism) or that general acceptance of (or following or compliance with)
a rule prohibiting war will have best consequences even if occasional
particular wars have best consequences (rule utilitarianism).
NONVIOLENCE. R.L.H.
Paine, Thomas (1737–1809), American political philosopher, revolutionary
defender of democracy and human rights, and champion of popular radicalism in
three countries. Born in Thetford, England, he emigrated to the American
colonies in 1774; he later moved to France, where he was made a French citizen
in 1792. In 1802 he returned to the United States, where he was rebuffed by the
public because of his support for the French Revolution. Paine was the
bestknown polemicist for the American Revolution. In many incendiary pamphlets,
he called for a new, more democratic republicanism. His direct style and
uncompromising egalitarianism had wide popular appeal. In Common Sense (1776)
Paine asserted that commoners were the equal of the landed aristocracy, thus
helping to spur colonial resentments sufficiently to support independence from
Britain. The sole basis of political legitimacy is universal, active consent;
taxation without representation is unjust; and people have the right to resist
when the contract between governor and governed is broken. He defended the
French Revolution in The Rights of Man (1791–92), arguing against concentrating
power in any one individual and against a property qualification for suffrage.
Since natural law and right reason as conformity to nature are accessible to
all rational persons, sovereignty resides in human beings and is not bestowed
by membership in class or nation. Opposed to the extremist Jacobins, he helped
write, with Condorcet, a constitution to secure the Revolution. The Age of
Reason (1794), Paine’s most misunderstood work, sought to secure the social
cohesion necessary to a well-ordered society by grounding it in belief in a
divinity. But in supporting deism and attacking established religion as a tool
of enslavement, he alienated the very laboring classes he sought to enlighten.
A lifelong adversary of slavery and supporter of universal male suffrage, Paine
argued for redistributing property in Agrarian Justice (1797).
DEISM, POLITICAL
PHILOSOPHY. C.H.S. Paley, William, (1743–1805), English moral philosopher and
theologian. He was born in Peterborough and educated at Cambridge, 639 P 639 where he lectured in moral philosophy,
divinity, and Greek New Testament before assuming a series of posts in the
Church of England, the last as archdeacon of Carlisle. The Principles of Moral
and Political Philosophy (1785) first introduced utilitarianism to a wide
public. Moral obligation is created by a divine command “coupled” with the
expectation of everlasting rewards or punishments. While God’s commands can be
ascertained “from Scripture and the light of nature,” Paley emphasizes the
latter. Since God wills human welfare, the rightness or wrongness of actions is
determined by their “tendency to promote or diminish the general happiness.”
Horae Pauline: Or the Truth of the Scripture History of St Paul Evinced
appeared in 1790, A View of the Evidences of Christianity in 1794. The latter
defends the authenticity of the Christian miracles against Hume. Natural
Theology (1802) provides a design argument for God’s existence and a
demonstration of his attributes. Nature exhibits abundant contrivances whose “several
parts are framed and put together for a purpose.” These contrivances establish
the existence of a powerful, wise, benevolent designer. They cannot show that
its power and wisdom are unlimited, however, and “omnipotence” and
“omniscience” are mere “superlatives.” Paley’s Principles and Evidences served
as textbooks in England and America well into the nineteenth century.
DIVINE ATTRIBUTES, HUME,
MIRACLE, PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION, UTILITARIANISM. W.J.Wa. Panaetius.STOICISM.
panentheism.KRAUSE, PANTHEISM. panlogism.HEGEL.
panpsychism, the doctrine
that the physical world is pervasively psychical, sentient or conscious
(understood as equivalent). The idea, usually, is that it is articulated into
certain ultimate units or particles, momentary or enduring, each with its own
distinct charge of sentience or consciousness, and that some more complex
physical units possess a sentience emergent from the interaction between the
charges of sentience pertaining to their parts, sometimes down through a series
of levels of articulation into sentient units. Animal consciousness is the
overall sentience pertaining to some substantial part or aspect of the brain,
while each neuron may have its own individual charge of sentience, as may each
included atom and subatomic particle. Elsewhere the only sentient units may be
at the atomic and subatomic level. Two differently motivated versions of the
doctrine should be distinguished. The first implies no particular view about
the nature of matter, and regards the sentience pertaining to each unit as an
extra to its physical nature. Its point is to explain animal and human
consciousness as emerging from the interaction and perhaps fusion of more
pervasive sentient units. The better motivated, second version holds that the
inner essence of matter is unknown. We know only structural facts about the
physical or facts about its effects on sentience like our own. Panpsychists
hypothesize that the otherwise unknown inner essence of matter consists in
sentience or consciousness articulated into the units we identify externally as
fundamental particles, or as a supervening character pertaining to complexes of
such or complexes of complexes, etc. Panpsychists can thus uniquely combine the
idealist claim that there can be no reality without consciousness with
rejection of any subjectivist reduction of the physical world to human
experience of it. Modern versions of panpsychism (e.g. of Whitehead,
Hartshorne, and Sprigge) are only partly akin to hylozoism as it occurred in
ancient thought. Note that neither version need claim that every physical
object possesses consciousness; no one supposes that a team of conscious
cricketers must itself be conscious.
HYLOZOISM, WHITEHEAD.
T.L.S.S. pantheism, the view that God is identical with everything. It may be
seen as the result of two tendencies: an intense religious spirit and the
belief that all reality is in some way united. Pantheism should be
distinguished from panentheism, the view that God is in all things. Just as
water might saturate a sponge and in that way be in the entire sponge, but not
be identical with the sponge, God might be in everything without being
identical with everything. Spinoza is the most distinguished pantheist in
Western philosophy. He argued that since substance is completely
self-sufficient, and only God is self-sufficient, God is the only substance. In
other words, God is everything. Hegel is also sometimes considered a pantheist
since he identifies God with the totality of being. Many people think that
pantheism is tantamount to atheism, because they believe that theism requires
that God transcend ordinary, sensible reality at least to some degree. It is
not obvious that theism requires a transcendent or Panaetius pantheism 640 640 personal notion of God; and one might
claim that the belief that it does is the result of an anthropomorphic view of
God. In Eastern philosophy, especially the Vedic tradition of Indian
philosophy, pantheism is part of a rejection of polytheism. The apparent
multiplicity of reality is illusion. What is ultimately real or divine is
Brahman.
BRAHMAN,
PANTHEISMUSSTREIT, PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. A.P.M.
Pantheismusstreit
(German, ‘dispute over pantheism’), a debate primarily between the German
philosophers Jacobi and Mendelssohn, although it also included Lessing, Kant,
and Goethe. The basic issue concerned what pantheism is and whether all
pantheists are atheists. In particular, it concerned whether Spinoza was a
pantheist, and if so, whether he was an atheist; and how close Lessing’s
thought was to Spinoza’s. The standard view, propounded by Bayle and Leibniz,
was that Spinoza’s pantheism was a thin veil for his atheism. Lessing and
Goethe did not accept this harsh interpretation of him. They believed that his
pantheism avoided the alienating transcendence of the standard Judeo-Christian
concept of God. It was debated whether Lessing was a Spinozist or some form of
theistic pantheist. Lessing was critical of dogmatic religions and denied that
there was any revelation given to all people for rational acceptance. He may
have told Jacobi that he was a Spinozist; but he may also have been speaking
ironically or hypothetically. SPINOZA.
A.P.M. Paracelsus, pseudonym of Theophrastus Bombastus von Hohenheim (1493–1541),
Swiss chemist, physician, and natural philosopher. He pursued medical studies
at various German and Austrian universities, probably completing them at
Ferrara (1513–16). Thereafter he had little to do with the academic world,
apart from a brief and stormy period as professor of medicine at Basle
(1527–28). Instead, he worked first as a military surgeon and later as an
itinerant physician in Germany, Austria, and Switzerland. His works were mainly
in German rather than Latin, and only a few were published during his lifetime.
His importance for medical practice lay in his insistence on observation and
experiment, and his use of chemical methods for preparing drugs. The success of
Paracelsian medicine and chemistry in the later sixteenth and seventeenth
centuries was, however, largely due to the theoretical background he provided.
He firmly rejected the classical medical inheritance, particularly Galen’s
explanation of disease as an imbalance of humors; he drew on a combination of
biblical sources, German mysticism, alchemy, and Neoplatonic magic as found in
Ficino to present a unified view of humankind and the universe. He saw man as a
microcosm, reflecting the nature of the divine world through his immortal soul,
the sidereal world through his astral body or vital principle, and the terrestrial
world through his visible body. Knowledge requires union with the object, but
because elements of all the worlds are found in man, he can acquire knowledge
of the universe and of God, as partially revealed in nature. The physician
needs knowledge of vital principles (called astra) in order to heal. Disease is
caused by external agents that can affect the human vital principle as well as
the visible body. Chemical methods are employed to isolate the appropriate
vital principles in minerals and herbs, and these are used as antidotes.
Paracelsus further held that matter contains three principles, sulfur, mercury,
and salt. As a result, he thought it was possible to transform one metal into
another by varying the proportions of the fundamental principles; and that such
transformations could also be used in the production of drugs. ALCHEMY, MYSTICISM. E.J.A. paraconsistency,
the property of a logic in which one cannot derive all statements from a
contradiction. What is objectionable about contradictions, from the standpoint
of classical logic, is not just that they are false but that they imply any
statement whatsoever: one who accepts a contradiction is thereby committed to
accepting everything. In paraconsistent logics, however, such as relevance
logics, contradictions are isolated inferentially and thus rendered relatively
harmless. The interest in such logics stems from the fact that people sometimes
continue to work in inconsistent theories even after the inconsistency has been
exposed, and do so without inferring everything. Whether this phenomenon can be
explained satisfactorily by the classical logician or shows instead that the
underlying logic of, e.g., science and mathematics is some non-classical
paraconsistent logic, is disputed.
CONSISTENCY, RELEVANCE LOGIC. G.F.S. paradigm, as used by Thomas Kuhn
(The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 1962), a set of scientific and
metaphysical beliefs that make up a theoretical framework within which
scientific theories Pantheismusstreit paradigm 641 641 can be tested, evaluated, and if
necessary revised. Kuhn’s principal thesis, in which the notion of a paradigm
plays a central role, is structured around an argument against the logical
empiricist view of scientific theory change. Empiricists viewed theory change
as an ongoing smooth and cumulative process in which empirical facts,
discovered through observation or experimentation, forced revisions in our
theories and thus added to our ever-increasing knowledge of the world. It was
claimed that, combined with this process of revision, there existed a process
of intertheoretic reduction that enabled us to understand the macro in terms of
the micro, and that ultimately aimed at a unity of science. Kuhn maintains that
this view is incompatible with what actually happens in case after case in the
history of science. Scientific change occurs by “revolutions” in which an older
paradigm is overthrown and is replaced by a framework incompatible or even
incommensurate with it. Thus the alleged empirical “facts,” which were adduced
to support the older theory, become irrelevant to the new; the questions asked
and answered in the new framework cut across those of the old; indeed the
vocabularies of the two frameworks make up different languages, not easily
intertranslatable. These episodes of revolution are separated by long periods
of “normal science,” during which the theories of a given paradigm are honed,
refined, and elaborated. These periods are sometimes referred to as periods of
“puzzle solving,” because the changes are to be understood more as fiddling
with the details of the theories to “save the phenomena” than as steps taking
us closer to the truth. A number of philosophers have complained that Kuhn’s
conception of a paradigm is too imprecise to do the work he intended for it. In
fact, Kuhn, fifteen years later, admitted that at least two distinct ideas were
exploited by the term: (i) the “shared elements [that] account for the
relatively unproblematic character of professional communication and for the
relative unanimity of professional judgment,” and (ii) “concrete problem
solutions, accepted by the group [of scientists] as, in a quite usual sense,
paradigmatic” (Kuhn, “Second Thoughts on Paradigms,” 1977). Kuhn offers the
terms ‘disciplinary matrix’ and ‘exemplar’, respectively, for these two
ideas. KUHN, LOGICAL POSITIVISM,
PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, REDUCTION, UNITY OF SCIENCE. B.E. paradigm case
argument, an argument designed to yield an affirmative answer to the following
general type of skeptically motivated question: Are A’s really B? E.g., Do
material objects really exist? Are any of our actions really free? Does
induction really provide reasonable grounds for one’s beliefs? The structure of
the argument is simple: in situations that are “typical,” “exemplary,” or
“paradigmatic,” standards for which are supplied by common sense, or ordinary
language, part of what it is to be B essentially involves A. Hence it is absurd
to doubt if A’s are ever B, or to doubt if in general A’s are B. (More
commonly, the argument is encountered in the linguistic mode: part of what it
means for something to be B is that, in paradigm cases, it be an A. Hence the
question whether A’s are ever B is meaningless.) An example may be found in the
application of the argument to the problem of induction. (See Strawson,
Introduction to Logical Theory, 1952.) When one believes a generalization of
the form ‘All F’s are G’ on the basis of good inductive evidence, i.e.,
evidence constituted by innumerable and varied instances of F all of which are G,
one would thereby have good reasons for holding this belief. The argument for
this claim is based on the content of the concepts of reasonableness and of
strength of evidence. Thus according to Strawson, the following two
propositions are analytic: (1) It is reasonable to have a degree of belief in a
proposition that is proportional to the strength of the evidence in its favor.
(2) The evidence for a generalization is strong in proportion as the number of
instances, and the variety of circumstances in which they have been found, is
great. Hence, Strawson concludes, “to ask whether it is reasonable to place
reliance on inductive procedures is like asking whether it is reasonable to
proportion the degree of one’s convictions to the strength of the evidence.
Doing this is what ‘being reasonable’ means in such a context” (p. 257). In
such arguments the role played by the appeal to paradigm cases is crucial. In
Strawson’s version, paradigm cases are constituted by “innumerable and varied
instances.” Without such an appeal the argument would fail completely, for it
is clear that not all uses of induction are reasonable. Even when this appeal
is made clear though, the argument remains questionable, for it fails to
confront adequately the force of the word ‘really’ in the skeptical challenges.
paradigm case argument paradigm case argument 642 642
ANALYTIC-SYNTHETIC DISTINCTION, PROBLEM OF INDUCTION. B.E.
paradox, a seemingly
sound piece of reasoning based on seemingly true assumptions that leads to a
contradiction (or other obviously false conclusion). A paradox reveals that
either the principles of reasoning or the assumptions on which it is based are
faulty. It is said to be solved when the mistaken principles or assumptions are
clearly identified and rejected. The philosophical interest in paradoxes arises
from the fact that they sometimes reveal fundamentally mistaken assumptions or
erroneous reasoning techniques. Two groups of paradoxes have received a great
deal of attention in modern philosophy. Known as the semantic paradoxes and the
logical or settheoretic paradoxes, they reveal serious difficulties in our
intuitive understanding of the basic notions of semantics and set theory. Other
well-known paradoxes include the barber paradox and the prediction (or hangman
or unexpected examination) paradox. The barber paradox is mainly useful as an
example of a paradox that is easily resolved. Suppose we are told that there is
an Oxford barber who shaves all and only the Oxford men who do not shave
themselves. Using this description, we can apparently derive the contradiction
that this barber both shaves and does not shave himself. (If he does not shave
himself, then according to the description he must be one of the people he
shaves; if he does shave himself, then according to the description he is one
of the people he does not shave.) This paradox can be resolved in two ways.
First, the original claim that such a barber exists can simply be rejected:
perhaps no one satisfies the alleged description. Second, the described barber
may exist, but not fall into the class of Oxford men: a woman barber, e.g.,
could shave all and only the Oxford men who do not shave themselves. The
prediction paradox takes a variety of forms. Suppose a teacher tells her
students on Friday that the following week she will give a single quiz. But it
will be a surprise: the students will not know the evening before that the quiz
will take place the following day. They reason that she cannot give such a
quiz. After all, she cannot wait until Friday to give it, since then they would
know Thursday evening. That leaves Monday through Thursday as the only possible
days for it. But then Thursday can be ruled out for the same reason: they would
know on Wednesday evening. Wednesday, Tuesday, and Monday can be ruled out by
similar reasoning. Convinced by this seemingly correct reasoning, the students
do not study for the quiz. On Wednesday morning, they are taken by surprise
when the teacher distributes it. It has been pointed out that the students’
reasoning has this peculiar feature: in order to rule out any of the days, they
must assume that the quiz will be given and that it will be a surprise. But
their alleged conclusion is that it cannot be given or else will not be a
surprise, undermining that very assumption. Kaplan and Montague have argued (in
“A Paradox Regained,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 1960) that at the
core of this puzzle is what they call the knower paradox – a paradox that
arises when intuitively plausible principles about knowledge (and its relation
to logical consequence) are used in conjunction with knowledge claims whose
content is, or entails, a denial of those very claims.
DEONTIC PARADOXES,
PARADOXES OF OMNIPOTENCE, SEMANTIC PARADOXES, SET-THEORETIC PARADOXES, ZENO’S
PARADOXES. J.Et. paradoxes, deontic.DEONTIC PARADOXES. paradoxes,
logical.SET-THEORETIC PARADOXES. paradoxes, semantic.SEMANTIC PARADOXES.
paradoxes, set-theoretic.SET-THEORETIC PARADOXES. paradoxes of
confirmation.CONFIRMATION. paradoxes of material implication.IMPLICATION.
paradoxes of omnipotence, a series of paradoxes in philosophical theology that
maintain that God could not be omnipotent because the concept is inconsistent,
alleged to result from the intuitive idea that if God is omnipotent, then God
must be able to do anything. (1) Can God perform logically contradictory tasks?
If God can, then God should be able to make himself simultaneously omnipotent
and not omnipotent, which is absurd. If God cannot, then it appears that there
is something God cannot do. Many philosophers have sought to avoid this
consequence by claiming that the notion of performing a logically contradictory
task is empty, and that question (1) specifies no task that God can perform or
fail to perform. (2) Can God cease to be omnipotent? If God can and were to do
so, then at any time thereparadox paradoxes of omnipotence 643 643 after, God would no longer be
completely sovereign over all things. If God cannot, then God cannot do
something that others can do, namely, impose limitations on one’s own powers. A
popular response to question (2) is to say that omnipotence is an essential
attribute of a necessarily existing being. According to this response, although
God cannot cease to be omnipotent any more than God can cease to exist, these
features are not liabilities but rather the lack of liabilities in God. (3) Can
God create another being who is omnipotent? Is it logically possible for two
beings to be omnipotent? It might seem that there could be, if they never
disagreed in fact with each other. If, however, omnipotence requires control
over all possible but counterfactual situations, there could be two omnipotent
beings only if it were impossible for them to disagree. (4) Can God create a
stone too heavy for God to move? If God can, then there is something that God
cannot do – move such a stone – and if God cannot, then there is something God
cannot do – create such a stone. One reply is to maintain that ‘God cannot
create a stone too heavy for God to move’ is a harmless consequence of ‘God can
create stones of any weight and God can move stones of any weight.’ DIVINE ATTRIBUTES, PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION.
W.E.M. paradoxes of self-reference.RUSSELL, TYPE THEORY. paradoxes of set
theory.SET-THEORETIC PARADOXES, SET THEORY. paradoxes of strict
implication.IMPLICATION. paradox of analysis, an argument that it is impossible
for an analysis of a meaning to be informative for one who already understands
the meaning. Consider: ‘An F is a G’ (e.g., ‘A circle is a line all points on
which are equidistant from some one point’) gives a correct analysis of the
meaning of ‘F’ only if ‘G’ means the same as ‘F’; but then anyone who already
understands both meanings must already know what the sentence says. Indeed,
that will be the same as what the trivial ‘An F is an F’ says, since replacing
one expression by another with the same meaning should preserve what the
sentence says. The conclusion that ‘An F is a G’ cannot be informative (for one
who already understands all its terms) is paradoxical only for cases where ‘G’
is not only synonymous with but more complex than ‘F’, in such a way as to give
an analysis of ‘F’. (‘A first cousin is an offspring of a parent’s sibling’
gives an analysis, but ‘A dad is a father’ does not and in fact could not be
informative for one who already knows the meaning of all its words.) The
paradox appears to fail to distinguish between different sorts of knowledge.
Encountering for the first time (and understanding) a correct analysis of a
meaning one already grasps brings one from merely tacit to explicit knowledge
of its truth. One sees that it does capture the meaning and thereby sees a way
of articulating the meaning one had not thought of before. ANALYSIS, DEFINITION, MEANING. C.G. paradox
of omniscience, an objection to the possibility of omniscience, developed by
Patrick Grim, that appeals to an application of Cantor’s power set theorem.
Omniscience requires knowing all truths; according to Grim, that means knowing
every truth in the set of all truths. But there is no set of all truths.
Suppose that there were a set T of all truths. Consider all the subsets of T,
that is, all members of the power set 3T. Take some truth T1. For each member
of 3T either T1 is a member of that set or T1 is not a member of that set.
There will thus correspond to each member of 3T a further truth specifying
whether T1 is or is not a member of that set. Therefore there are at least as
many truths as there are members of 3T. By the power set theorem, there are
more members of 3T than there are of T. So T is not the set of all truths. By a
parallel argument, no other set is, either. So there is no set of all truths,
after all, and therefore no one who knows every member of that set. The
objection may be countered by denying that the claim ‘for every proposition p,
if p is true God knows that p’ requires that there be a set of all true
propositions. CANTOR, DIVINE ATTRIBUTES.
E.R.W. paradox of self-deception.SELF-DECEPTION. paradox of the
examination.UNEXPECTED EXAMINATION PARADOX. paradox of the heap.SORITES
PARADOX. paradox of the knower.DEONTIC PARADOXES. paradox of the
ravens.CONFIRMATION. paradox of the stone.PARADOXES OF OMNIPOTENCE. paradoxes
of self-reference paradox of the stone 644
644 parallel distributed processing.CONNECTIONISM. parallelism.PHILOSOPHY
OF MIND. parallelism, psychophysical.PHILOSOPHY OF MIND.
parapsychology, the study
of certain anomalous phenomena and ostensible causal connections neither
recognized nor clearly rejected by traditional science. Parapsychology’s
principal areas of investigation are extrasensory perception (ESP),
psychokinesis (PK), and cases suggesting the survival of mental functioning
following bodily death. The study of ESP has traditionally focused on two sorts
of ostensible phenomena, telepathy (the apparent anomalous influence of one
person’s mental states on those of another, commonly identified with apparent
communication between two minds by extrasensory means) and clairvoyance (the
apparent anomalous influence of a physical state of affairs on a person’s
mental states, commonly identified with the supposed ability to perceive or
know of objects or events not present to the senses). The forms of ESP may be
viewed either as types of cognition (e.g., the anomalous knowledge of another
person’s mental states) or as merely a form of anomalous causal influence
(e.g., a distant burning house causing one to have – possibly incongruous –
thoughts about fire). The study of PK covers the apparent ability to produce
various physical effects independently of familiar or recognized intermediate
sorts of causal links. These effects include the ostensible movement of remote
objects, materializations (the apparently instantaneous production of matter),
apports (the apparently instantaneous relocation of an object), and (in
laboratory experiments) statistically significant non-random behavior of
normally random microscopic processes (such as radioactive decay). Survival
research focuses on cases of ostensible reincarnation and mental mediumship
(i.e., “channeling” of information from an apparently deceased communicator).
Cases of ostensible precognition may be viewed as types of telepathy and
clairvoyance, and suggest the causal influence of some state of affairs on an
earlier event (an agent’s ostensible precognitive experience). However, those
opposed to backward causation may interpret ostensible precognition either as a
form of unconscious inference based on contemporaneous information acquired by
ESP, or else as a form of PK (possibly in conjunction with telepathic
influence) by which the precognizer brings about the events apparently
precognized. The data of parapsychology raise two particularly deep issues. The
evidence suggesting survival poses a direct challenge to materialist theories
of the mental. And the evidence for ESP and PK suggests the viability of a
“magical” worldview associated usually with so-called primitive societies,
according to which we have direct and intimate access to and influence on the
thoughts and bodily states of others.
PHILOSOPHY OF MIND, PHILOSOPHY OF PSYCHOLOGY. S.E.B. Pareto efficiency,
also called Pareto optimality, a state of affairs in which no one can be made
better off without making someone worse off. The Italian economist Vilfredo
Pareto (1848–1923) referred to optimality rather than efficiency, but usage has
drifted toward the less normative term. Pareto supposed that utilitarian
addition of welfare across individuals is meaningless. He concluded that the
only useful aggregate measures of welfare must be ordinal. One state of affairs
is Pareto-superior to another if we cannot move to the second state without
making someone worse off. Although the Pareto criteria are generally thought to
be positive rather than normative, they are often used as normative principles
for justifying particular changes or refusals to make changes. For example,
some economists and philosophers take the Pareto criteria as moral constraints
and therefore oppose certain government policies. In market and voluntary
exchange contexts, it makes sense to suppose every exchange will be
Pareto-improving, at least for the direct parties to the exchange. If, however,
we fail to account for external effects of our exchange on other people, it may
not be Pareto-improving. Moreover, we may fail to provide collective benefits
that require the cooperation or coordination of many individuals’ efforts.
Hence, even in markets, we cannot expect to achieve Pareto efficiency. We might
therefore suppose we should invite government intervention to help us. But in
typical social contexts, it is often hard to believe that significant policy
changes can be Paretoimproving: there are sure to be losers from any
change. PERFECT COMPETITION, SOCIAL
CHOICE THEORY, UTILITARIANISM. R.Har. Pareto optimality.PARETO EFFICIENCY.
Pareto-superior.PARETO EFFICIENCY. parallel distributed processing
Pareto-superior 645 645 Parfit, Derek
(b.1942), British philosopher internationally known for his major contributions
to the metaphysics of persons, moral theory, and practical reasoning. Parfit first
rose to prominence by challenging the prevalent view that personal identity is
a “deep fact” that must be all or nothing and that matters greatly in rational
and moral deliberations. Exploring puzzle cases involving fission and fusion,
Parfit propounded a reductionist account of personal identity, arguing that
what matters in survival are physical and psychological continuities. These are
a matter of degree, and sometimes there may be no answer as to whether some
future person would be me. Parfit’s magnum opus, Reasons and Persons (1984), is
a strikingly original book brimming with startling conclusions that have
significantly reshaped the philosophical agenda. Part One treats different
theories of morality, rationality, and the good; blameless wrongdoing; moral
immorality; rational irrationality; imperceptible harms and benefits; harmless
torturers; and the self-defeatingness of certain theories. Part Two introduces
a critical present-aim theory of individual rationality, and attacks the
standard selfinterest theory. It also discusses the rationality of different
attitudes to time, such as caring more about the future than the past, and more
about the near than the remote. Addressing the age-old conflict between
self-interest and morality, Parfit illustrates that contrary to what the
self-interest theory demands, it can be rational to care about certain other
aims as much as, or more than, about our own future well-being. In addition,
Parfit notes that the self-interest theory is a hybrid position, neutral with
respect to time but partial with respect to persons. Thus, it can be challenged
from one direction by morality, which is neutral with respect to both persons
and time, and from the other by a present-aim theory, which is partial with
respect to both persons and time. Part Three refines Parfit’s views regarding
personal identity and further criticizes the self-interest theory: personal
identity is not what matters, hence reasons to be specially concerned about our
future are not provided by the fact that it will be our future. Part Four
presents puzzles regarding future generations and argues that the moral
principles we need when considering future people must take an impersonal form.
Parfit’s arguments deeply challenge our understanding of moral ideals and, some
believe, the possibility of comparing outcomes. Parfit has three forthcoming
manuscripts, tentatively titled Rediscovering Reasons, The Metaphysics of the
Self, and On What Matters. His current focus is the normativity of reasons. A
reductionist about persons, he is a non-reductionist about reasons. He believes
in irreducibily normative beliefs that are in a strong sense true. A realist
about reasons for acting and caring, he challenges the views of naturalists,
noncognitivists, and constructivists. Parfit contends that internalists
conflate normativity with motivating force, that contrary to the prevalent view
that all reasons are provided by desires, no reasons are, and that Kant poses a
greater threat to rationalism than Hume. Parfit is Senior Research Fellow of
All Souls College, Oxford, and a regular visiting professor at both Harvard and
New York University. Legendary for monograph-length criticisms of book
manuscripts, he is editor of the Oxford Ethics Series, whose goal is to make
definite moral progress, a goal Parfit himself is widely believed to have
attained.
ETHICS, EXTERNALISM,
MORAL REALISM, MOTIVATIONAL INTERNALISM, PERSONAL IDENTITY, PRACTICAL REASON.
L.S.T. parity of reasons.PRINCIPLE OF INDIFFERENCE. Parmenides (early fifth century
B.C.), Greek philosopher, the most influential of the preSocratics, active in
Elea (Roman and modern Velia), an Ionian Greek colony in southern Italy. He was
the first Greek thinker who can properly be called an ontologist or
metaphysician. Plato refers to him as “venerable and awesome,” as “having
magnificent depth” (Theaetetus 183e– 184a), and presents him in the dialogue
Parmenides as a searching critic – in a fictional and dialectical transposition
– of Plato’s own theory of Forms. Nearly 150 lines of a didactic poem by
Parmenides have been preserved, assembled into about twenty fragments. The
first part, “Truth,” provides the earliest specimen in Greek intellectual
history of a sustained deductive argument. Drawing on intuitions concerning
thinking, knowing, and language, Parmenides argues that “the real” or “what-is”
or “being” (to eon) must be ungenerable and imperishable, indivisible, and
unchanging. According to a Plato-inspired tradition, Parmenides held that “all
is one.” But the phrase does not occur in the fragments; Parmenides does not
even speak of “the One”; and it is possible that either a holistic One or a
plurality of absolute monads might conform to Parmenides’ deduction.
Nonetheless, it is difficult to resist the impression that the argument
converges on a unique entity, which may indifferParfit, Derek Parmenides
646 646 ently be referred to as Being,
or the All, or the One. Parmenides embraces fully the paradoxical consequence
that the world of ordinary experience fails to qualify as “what-is.”
Nonetheless, in “Opinions,” the second part of the poem, he expounds a dualist
cosmology. It is unclear whether this is intended as candid phenomenology – a
doctrine of appearances – or as an ironic foil to “Truth.” It is noteworthy
that Parmenides was probably a physician by profession. Ancient reports to this
effect are borne out by fragments (from “Opinions”) with embryological themes,
as well as by archaeological findings at Velia that link the memory of
Parmenides with Romanperiod remains of a medical school at that site.
Parmenides’ own attitude notwithstanding, “Opinions” recorded four major
scientific breakthroughs, some of which, doubtless, were Parmenides’ own
discoveries: that the earth is a sphere; that the two tropics and the Arctic
and Antarctic circles divide the earth into five zones; that the moon gets its
light from the sun; and that the morning star and the evening star are the same
planet. The term Eleatic School is misleading when it is used to suggest a
common doctrine supposedly held by Parmenides, Zeno of Elea, Melissus of Samos,
and (anticipating Parmenides) Xenophanes of Colophon. The fact is, many
philosophical groups and movements, from the middle of the fifth century
onward, were influenced, in different ways, by Parmenides, including the
“pluralists,” Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and Democritus. Parmenides’ deductions,
transformed by Zeno into a repertoire of full-blown paradoxes, provided the
model both for the eristic of the Sophists and for Socrates’ elenchus. Moreover,
the Parmenidean criteria for “whatis” lie unmistakably in the background not
only of Plato’s theory of Forms but also of salient features of Aristotle’s
system, notably, the priority of actuality over potentiality, the unmoved
mover, and the man-begets-man principle. Indeed, all philosophical and
scientific systems that posit principles of conservation (of substance, of
matter, of matter-energy) are inalienably the heirs to Parmenides’
deduction. ELEATIC SCHOOL, MELISSUS OF
SAMOS, PRE-SOCRATICS. A.P.D.M. parousia.PLATO. parse tree.PARSING. parsimony,
principle of.OCKHAM’S RAZOR.
parsing, the process of
determining the syntactic structure of a sentence according to the rules of a
given grammar. This is to be distinguished from the generally simpler task of
recognition, which is merely the determination of whether or not a given string
is well-formed (grammatical). In general, many different parsing strategies can
be employed for grammars of a particular type, and a great deal of attention
has been given to the relative efficiencies of these techniques. The most
thoroughly studied cases center on the contextfree phrase structure grammars,
which assign syntactic structures in the form of singly-rooted trees with a
left-to-right ordering of “sister” nodes. Parsing procedures can then be
broadly classified according to the sequence of steps by which the parse tree
is constructed: top-down versus bottom-up; depth-first versus breadthfirst;
etc. In addition, there are various strategies for exploring alternatives
(agendas, backtracking, parallel processing) and there are devices such as
“charts” that eliminate needless repetitions of previous steps. Efficient
parsing is of course important when language, whether natural or artificial
(e.g., a programming language), is being processed by computer. Human beings
also parse rapidly and with apparently little effort when they comprehend
sentences of a natural language. Although little is known about the details of
this process, psycholinguists hope that study of mechanical parsing techniques
might provide insights. GRAMMAR. R.E.W.
partial belief.PROBABILITY. partial function.MATHEMATICAL FUNCTION. partial
order.RELATION. partial ordering.ORDERING. participation.PLATO. particular.CONCEPTUALISM,
INDIVIDUATION, METAPHYSICS. particular, bare.METAPHYSICS. particular,
basic.STRAWSON. particularism.PROBLEM OF THE CRITERION.
particular
proposition.SYLLOGISM. partition, division of a set into mutually exclusive and
jointly exhaustive subsets. Derivatively, parousia partition 647 647 ‘partition’ can mean any set P whose
members are mutually exclusive and jointly exhaustive subsets of set S. Each
subset of a partition P is called a partition class of S with respect to P.
Partitions are intimately associated with equivalence relations, i.e. with
relations that are transitive, symmetric, and reflexive. Given an equivalence
relation R defined on a set S, R induces a partition P of S in the following
natural way: members s1 and s2 belong to the same partition class of P if and
only if s1 has the relation R to s2. Conversely, given a partition P of a set
S, P induces an equivalence relation R defined on S in the following natural
way: members s1 and s2 are such that s1 has the relation R to s2 if and only if
s1 and s2 belong to the same partition class of P. For obvious reasons, then,
partition classes are also known as equivalence classes. RELATION, SET THEORY. R.W.B. Parva
naturalia.ARISTOTLE. Pascal, Blaise (1623–62), French philosopher known for his
brilliance as a mathematician, physicist, inventor, theologian, polemicist, and
French prose stylist. Born at Clermont-Ferrand in the Auvergne, he was educated
by his father, Étienne, and first gained note for his contribution to
mathematics when at sixteen he produced, under the influence of Desargues, a
work on the projective geometry of the cone. This was published in 1640 under
the title Essai pour les coniques and includes what has since become known as
Pascal’s theorem. Pascal’s other mathematical accomplishments include the original
development of probability theory, worked out in correspondence with Fermat,
and a method of infinitesimal analysis to which Leibniz gave credit for
inspiring his own development of the calculus. Pascal’s early scientific fame
rests also on his work in physics, which includes a treatise on hydrostatics
(Traités de l’équilibre des liqueurs et de la pesanteur de la masse de l’air)
and his experiments with the barometer, which attempted to establish the
possibility of a vacuum and the weight of air as the cause of the mercury’s
suspension. Pascal’s fame as a stylist rests primarily on his Lettres
provinciales (1656–57), which were an anonymous contribution to a dispute
between the Jansenists, headed by Arnauld, and the Jesuits. Jansenism was a
Catholic religious movement that emphasized an Augustinian position on
questions of grace and free will. Pascal, who was not himself a Jansenist,
wrote a series of scathing satirical letters ridiculing both Jesuit casuistry
and the persecution of the Jansenists for their purported adherence to five
propositions in Jansen’s Augustinus. Pascal’s philosophical contributions are
found throughout his work, but primarily in his Pensées (1670), an intended
apology for Christianity left incomplete and fragmentary at his death. The
influence of the Pensées on religious thought and later existentialism has been
profound because of their extraordinary insight, passion, and depth. At the
time of Pascal’s death some of the fragments were sewn together in clusters;
many others were left unorganized, but recent scholarship has recovered much of
the original plan of organization. The Pensées raise skeptical arguments that
had become part of philosophical parlance since Montaigne. While these
arguments were originally raised in order to deny the possibility of knowledge,
Pascal, like Descartes in the Meditations, tries to utilize them toward a
positive end. He argues that what skepticism shows us is not that knowledge is
impossible, but that there is a certain paradox about human nature: we possess
knowledge yet recognize that this knowledge cannot be rationally justified and
that rational arguments can even be directed against it (fragments 109, 131,
and 110). This peculiarity can be explained only through the Christian doctrine
of the fall (e.g., fragment 117). Pascal extends his skeptical considerations
by undermining the possibility of demonstrative proof of God’s existence. Such
knowledge is impossible on philosophical grounds because such a proof could be
successful only if an absurdity followed from denying God’s existence, and
nature furnishes us with no knowledge incompatible with unbelief (fragments 429
and 781). Furthermore, demonstrative proof of God’s existence is incompatible
with the epistemological claims of Christianity, which make God’s personal
agency essential to religious knowledge (fragments 460, 449). Pascal’s use of
skepticism and his refusal to admit proofs of God’s existence have led some
commentators, like Richard Popkin (“Fideism,” 1967) and Terence Penelhum
(“Skepticism and Fideism,” 1983) to interpret Pascal as a fideist, i.e., one
who denies that religious belief can be based on anything other than pragmatic
reasons. But such an interpretation disregards Pascal’s attempts to show that
Christian belief is rational because of the explanatory power of its doctrines,
particularly its doctrine of the fall (e.g., fragments 131, 137, 149, 431, 449,
and 482). These purported demonstrations of the explanatory superiority of
Christianity prepare Parva naturalia Pascal, Blaise 648 648 the way for Pascal’s famous “wager”
(fragment 418). The wager is among the fragments that Pascal had not classified
at the time of his death, but textual evidence shows that it would have been
included in Section 12, entitled “Commencement,” after the demonstrations of
the superior explanatory power of Christianity. The wager is a direct
application of the principles developed in Pascal’s earlier work on
probability, where he discovered a calculus that could be used to determine the
most rational action when faced with uncertainty about future events, or what
is now known as decision theory. In this case the uncertainty is the truth of
Christianity and its claims about afterlife; and the actions under
consideration are whether to believe or not. The choice of the most rational
action depends on what would now be called its “expected value.” The expected
value of an action is determined by (1) assigning a value, s, to each possible
outcome of the action, (2) subtracting the cost of the action, c, from this
value, and (3) multiplying the difference by the probability of the respective
outcomes and adding these products together. Pascal invites the reader to
consider Christian faith and unbelief as if they were acts of wagering on the
truth of Christianity. If one believes, then there are two possible outcomes –
either God exists or not. If God does exist, the stake to be gained is infinite
life. If God does not exist, there are no winnings. Because the potential
winnings are infinite, religious belief is more rational than unbelief because
of its greater expected value. The wager has been subjected to numerous
criticisms. William James argued that it is indecisive, because it would apply
with equal validity to any religion that offers a promise of infinite rewards
(The Will to Believe, 1897). But this ignores Pascal’s careful attempt to show
that only Christianity has adequate explanatory power, so that the choice is
intended to be between Christianity and unbelief. A stronger objection to the
wager arises from contemporary work in decision theory that prohibits the
introduction of infinite values because they have the counterintuitive result
of making even the slightest risk irrational. But while these objections are
valid, they do not refute Pascal’s strategy in the Pensées, in which the proofs
of Christianity’s explanatory power and the wager have only the preliminary
role of inducing the reader to seek the religious certainty that comes only
from a saving religious experience which he calls “inspiration” (fragments 110,
381, 382, 588, 808). DECISION THEORY,
PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION, PROBABILITY. D.F. Pascal’s wager.PASCAL.
passion.EMOTION, HUME, PRACTICAL REASONING. passions.EMOTION. passions,
direct.HUME. passions, indirect.HUME. passive euthanasia.
paternalism, interference
with the liberty or autonomy of another person, with justifications referring
to the promotion of the person’s good or the prevention of harm to the person.
More precisely, P acts paternalistically toward Q if and only if (a) P acts with
the intent of averting some harm or promoting some benefit for Q; (b) P acts
contrary to (or is indifferent to) the current preferences, desires or values
of Q; and (c) P’s act is a limitation on Q’s autonomy or liberty. The presence
of both autonomy and liberty in clause (c) is to allow for the fact that lying
to someone is not clearly an interference with liberty. Notice that one can act
paternalistically by telling people the truth (as when a doctor insists that a
patient know the exact nature of her illness, contrary to her wishes). Note
also that the definition does not settle any questions about the legitimacy or
illegitimacy of paternalistic interventions. Typical examples of paternalistic
actions are (1) laws requiring motorcyclists to wear helmets; (2) court orders
allowing physicians to transfuse Jehovah’s Witnesses against their wishes; (3)
deception of a patient by physicians to avoid upsetting the patient; (4) civil
commitment of persons judged dangerous to themselves; and (5) laws forbidding
swimming while lifeguards are not on duty. Soft (weak) paternalism is the view
that paternalism is justified only when a person is acting non-voluntarily or
one needs time to determine whether the person is acting voluntarily or not.
Hard (strong) paternalism is the view that paternalism is sometimes justified
even when the person being interfered with is acting voluntarily. The analysis
of the term is relative to some set of problems. If one were interested in the
orgaPascal’s wager paternalism 649 649
nizational behavior of large corporations, one might adopt a different
definition than if one were concerned with limits on the state’s right to
exercise coercion. The typical normative problems about paternalistic actions
are whether, and to what extent, the welfare of individuals may outweigh the
need to respect their desire to lead their own lives and make their own
decisions (even when mistaken). J. S. Mill is the best example of a virtually
absolute antipaternalism, at least with respect to the right of the state to
act paternalistically. He argued that unless we have reason to believe that a
person is not acting voluntarily, as in the case of a man walking across a
bridge that, unknown to him, is about to collapse, we ought to allow adults the
freedom to act even if their acts are harmful to themselves. FREE WILL PROBLEM; MILL, J. S.; POLITICAL
PHILOSOPHY; POSITIVE AND NEGATIVE FREEDOM; RIGHTS. G.D. patriarchalism.
patristic authors, also
called church fathers, a group of early Christian authors originally so named
because they were considered the “fathers” (patres) of the orthodox Christian
churches. The term is now used more broadly to designate the Christian writers,
orthodox or heterodox, who were active in the first six centuries or so of the
Christian era. The chronological division is quite flexible, and it is
regularly moved several centuries later for particular purposes. Moreover, the
study of these writers has traditionally been divided by languages, of which
the principal ones are Greek, Latin, and Syriac. The often sharp divisions
among patristic scholarships in the different languages are partly a reflection
of the different histories of the regional churches, partly a reflection of the
sociology of modern scholarship. Greeks. The patristic period in Greek is
usually taken as extending from the first writers after the New Testament to
such figures as Maximus the Confessor (579/580–662) or John of Damascus
(c.650–c.750). The period is traditionally divided around the Council of Nicea
(325). PreNicean Greek authors of importance to the history of philosophy
include Irenaeus (130/140– after 198?), Clement of Alexandria (c.150–after
215), and Origen (c.180–c.254). Important Nicean and post-Nicean authors
include Athanasius (c.295–373); the Cappadocians, i.e., Gregory of Nazianzus
(c.330–90), Basil of Cesarea (c.330–79), and his brother, Gregory of Nyssa
(335/340–c.394); and John Chrysostom (c.350– 407). Philosophical topics and
practices are constantly engaged by these Greek authors. Justin Martyr (second
century), e.g., describes his conversion to Christianity quite explicitly as a
transit through lower forms of philosophy into the true philosophy. Clement of
Alexandria, again, uses the philosophic genre of the protreptic and a host of
ancient texts to persuade his pagan readers that they ought to come to
Christianity as to the true wisdom. Origen devotes his Against Celsus to the
detailed rebuttal of one pagan philosopher’s attack on Christianity. More
importantly, if more subtly, the major works of the Cappadocians appropriate
and transform the teachings of any number of philosophic authors – Plato and
the Neoplatonists in first place, but also Aristotle, the Stoics, and Galen.
Latins. The Latin churches came to count four post-Nicean authors as its chief
teachers: Ambrose (337/339–97), Jerome (c.347–419), Augustine (354–430), and
Gregory the Great (c.540–604). Other Latin authors of philosophical interest
include Tertullian (fl. c.195–c.220), Lactantius (c.260–c.330), Marius
Victorinus (280/285–before 386), and Hilary of Poitiers (fl. 356–64). The Latin
patristic period is typically counted from the second century to the fifth or
sixth, i.e., roughly from Tertullian to Boethius. The Latin authors share with
their Greek contemporaries a range of relations to the pagan philosophic
schools, both as rival institutions and as sources of useful teaching.
Tertullian’s Against the Nations and Apology, for example, take up pagan
accusations against Christianity and then counterattack a number of pagan beliefs,
including philosophical ones. By contrast, the writings of Marius Victorinus,
Ambrose, and Augustine enact transformations of philosophic teachings,
especially from the Neoplatonists. Because philosophical erudition was
generally not as great among the Latins as among the Greeks, they were both
more eager to accept philosophical doctrines and freer in improvising
variations on them.
AUGUSTINE, BOETHIUS,
CLEMENT OF ALEXANDRIA, GREGORY OF NYSSA, TERTULLIAN. M.D.J. Paul of Venice
(c.1368–1429), Italian philosopher and theologian. A Hermit of Saint Augustine
(O.E.S.A.), he spent three years as a student patriarchalism Paul of Venice
650 650 in Oxford (1390–93) and taught
at the University of Padua, where he became a doctor of arts and theology in
1408. He also held appointments at the universities of Parma, Siena, and
Bologna. He was active in the administration of his order, holding various high
offices. Paul of Venice wrote commentaries on several logical, ethical, and
physical works of Aristotle, but his name is connected especially with an
extremely popular textbook, Logica parva (over 150 manuscripts survive, and
more than forty printed editions of it were made), and with a huge Logica
magna. These Oxford-influenced works contributed to the favorable climate
enjoyed by the English logic in northern Italian universities from the late
fourteenth century through the fifteenth century. I.Bo. Peano, Giuseppe.LOGICAL
FORM, PEANO POSTULATES. Peano postulates, also called Peano axioms, a list of
assumptions from which the integers can be defined from some initial integer,
equality, and successorship, and usually seen as defining progressions. The
Peano postulates for arithmetic were produced by G. Peano in 1889. He took the
set N of integers with a first term 1 and an equality relation between them,
and assumed these nine axioms: 1 belongs to N; N has more than one member;
equality is reflexive, symmetric, and associative, and closed over N; the
successor of any integer in N also belongs to N, and is unique; and a principle
of mathematical induction applying across the members of N, in that if 1
belongs to some subset M of N and so does the successor of any of its members,
then in fact M % N. In some ways Peano’s formulation was not clear. He had no
explicit rules of inference, nor any guarantee of the legitimacy of inductive
definitions (which Dedekind established shortly before him). Further, the four
properties attached to equality were seen to belong to the underlying “logic”
rather than to arithmetic itself; they are now detached. It was realized (by
Peano himself) that the postulates specified progressions rather than integers
(e.g., 1, ½, ¼, 1 /8, . . . , would satisfy them, with suitable interpretations
of the properties). But his work was significant in the axiomatization of
arithmetic; still deeper foundations would lead with Russell and others to a
major role for general set theory in the foundations of mathematics. In
addition, with O. Veblen, T. Skolem, and others, this insight led in the early
twentieth century to “non-standard” models of the postulates being developed in
set theory and mathematical analysis; one could go beyond the ‘. . .’ in the
sequence above and admit “further” objects, to produce valuable alternative
models of the postulates. These procedures were of great significance also to
model theory, in highlighting the property of the non-categoricity of an axiom
system. A notable case was the “non-standard analysis” of A. Robinson, where
infinitesimals were defined as arithmetical inverses of transfinite numbers
without incurring the usual perils of rigor associated with them. PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS. I.G.-G. Peirce,
Charles S(anders) (1839–1914), American philosopher, scientist, and
mathematician, the founder of the philosophical movement called pragmatism.
Peirce was born in Cambridge, Massachusetts, the second son of Benjamin Peirce,
who was professor of mathematics and astronomy at Harvard and one of America’s
leading mathematicians. Charles Peirce studied at Harvard University and in
1863 received a degree in chemistry. In 1861 he began work with the U.S. Coast
and Geodetic Survey, and remained in this service for thirty years.
Simultaneously with his professional career as a scientist, Peirce worked in
logic and philosophy. He lectured on philosophy and logic at various
universities and institutes, but was never able to obtain a permanent academic
position as a teacher of philosophy. In 1887 he retired to Milford,
Pennsylvania, and devoted the rest of his life to philosophical work. He earned
a meager income from occasional lectures and by writing articles for
periodicals and dictionaries. He spent his last years in extreme poverty and
ill health. Pragmatism. Peirce formulated the basic principles of pragmatism in
two articles, “The Fixation of Belief” and “How to Make Our Ideas Clear”
(1877–78). The title of the latter paper refers to Descartes’s doctrine of
clear and distinct ideas. According to Peirce, the criteria of clarity and
distinctness must be supplemented by a third condition of meaningfulness, which
states that the meaning of a proposition or an “intellectual conception” lies
in its “practical consequences.” In his paper “Pragmatism” (1905) he formulated
the “Principle of Pragmatism” or the “Pragmatic Maxim” as follows: In order to
ascertain the meaning of an intellectual conception we should consider what
Peano, Giuseppe Peirce, Charles S(anders) 651
651 practical consequences might conceivably result by necessity from
the truth of that conception; and the sum of these consequences will constitute
the entire meaning of the conception. By “practical consequences” Peirce means
conditional propositions of the form ‘if p, then q’, where the antecedent
describes some action or experimental condition, and the consequent describes
an observable phenomenon or a “sensible effect.” According to the Pragmatic
Maxim, the meaning of a proposition (or of an “intellectual conception”) can be
expressed as a conjunction of such “practical conditionals.” The Pragmatic
Maxim might be criticized on the ground that many meaningful sentences (e.g.,
theoretical hypotheses) do not entail any “practical consequences” in
themselves, but only in conjunction with other hypotheses. Peirce anticipated
this objection by observing that “the maxim of pragmatism is that a conception
can have no logical effect or import differing from that of a second conception
except so far as, taken in connection with other conceptions and intentions, it
might conceivably modify our practical conduct differently from that of the
second conception” (“Pragmatism and Abduction,” 1903). Theory of inquiry and
philosophy of science. Peirce adopted Bain’s definition of belief as “that
which a man is prepared to act upon.” Belief guides action, and as a content of
belief a proposition can be regarded as a maxim of conduct. According to
Peirce, belief is a satisfactory and desirable state, whereas the opposite of
belief, the state of doubt, is an unsatisfactory state. The starting point of
inquiry is usually some surprising phenomenon that is inconsistent with one’s
previously accepted beliefs, and that therefore creates a state of doubt. The
purpose of inquiry is the replacement of this state by that of belief: “the
sole aim of inquiry is the settlement of opinion.” A successful inquiry leads
to stable opinion, a state of belief that need not later be given up. Peirce
regarded the ultimate stability of opinion as a criterion of truth and reality:
“the real . . . is that which, sooner or later, information and reasoning would
finally result in, and which is therefore independent of the vagaries of you
and me.” He accepted, however, an objectivist conception of truth and reality:
the defining characteristic of reality is its independence of the opinions of
individual persons. In “The Fixation of Belief” Peirce argued that the
scientific method, a method in which we let our beliefs be determined by
external reality, “by something upon which our thinking has no effect,” is the
best way of settling opinion. Much of his philosophical work was devoted to the
analysis of the various forms of inference and argument employed in science. He
studied the concept of probability and probabilistic reasoning in science,
criticized the subjectivist view of probability, and adopted an objectivist
conception, according to which probability can be defined as a relative
frequency in the long run. Peirce distinguished between three main types of
inference, which correspond to three stages of inquiry: (i) abduction, a
tentative acceptance of an explanatory hypothesis which, if true, would make
the phenomenon under investigation intelligible; (ii) deduction, the derivation
of testable consequences from the explanatory hypothesis; and (iii) induction,
the evaluation of the hypothesis in the light of these consequences. He called
this method of inquiry the inductive method; in the contemporary philosophy of
science it is usually called the hypothetico-deductive method. According to
Peirce, the scientific method can be viewed as an application of the pragmatic
maxim: the testable consequences derived from an explanatory hypothesis
constitute its concrete “meaning” in the sense of the Pragmatic Maxim. Thus the
Maxim determines the admissibility of a hypothesis as a possible (meaningful)
explanation. According to Pierce, inquiry is always dependent on beliefs that
are not subject to doubt at the time of the inquiry, but such beliefs might be
questioned on some other occasion. Our knowledge does not rest on indubitable
“first premises,” but all beliefs are dependent on other beliefs. According to
Peirce’s doctrine of fallibilism, the conclusions of science are always
tentative. The rationality of the scientific method does not depend on the
certainty of its conclusions, but on its self-corrective character: by
continued application of the method science can detect and correct its own
mistakes, and thus eventually lead to the discovery of truth. Logic, the theory
of signs, and the philosophy of language. In “The Logic of Relatives,”
published in 1883 in a collection of papers by himself and his students at the
Johns Hopkins University (Studies in Logic by Members of the Johns Hopkins
University), Peirce formalized relational statements by using subscript indices
for individuals (individual variables), and construed the quantifiers ‘some’
and ‘every’ as variable binding operators; thus Peirce can be regarded
(together Peirce, Charles S(anders) Peirce, Charles S(anders) 652 652 with the German logician Frege) as one
of the founders of quantification theory (predicate logic). In his paper “On
the Algebra of Logic – A Contribution to the Philosophy of Notation” (1885) he
interpreted propositional logic as a calculus of truth-values, and defined
(logically) necessary truth (in propositional logic) as truth for all
truth-value assignments to sentential letters. He studied the logic of
modalities and in the 1890s he invented a system of logical graphs (called
“existential graphs”), based on a diagrammatic representation of propositions,
in which he anticipated some basic ideas of the possible worlds semantics of
modal logic. Peirce’s letters and notebooks contain significant logical and
philosophical insights. For example, he examined three-valued truth tables
(“Triadic Logic”), and discovered (in 1886) the possibility of representing the
truth-functional connectives of propositional logic by electrical switching
circuits. Peirce regarded logic as a part of a more general area of inquiry,
the theory of signs, which he also called semeiotic (nowadays usually spelled
‘semiotic(s)’). According to Peirce, sign relations are triadic, involving the
sign itself, its object (or what the sign stands for), and an interpretant
which determines how the sign represents the object; the interpretant can be
regarded as the meaning of the sign. The interpretant of a sign is another sign
which in turn has its own interpretant (or interpretants); such a sequence of
interpretants ends in an “ultimate logical interpretant,” which is “a change of
habit of conduct.” On the basis of the triadic character of the sign relation
Peirce distinguished three divisions of signs. These divisions were based on
(i) the character of the sign itself, (ii) the relation between the sign and
its object, and (iii) the way in which the interpretant represents the object.
These divisions reflect Peirce’s system of three fundamental ontological
categories, which he termed Quality or Firstness, Relation or Secondness, and
Representation or Thirdness. Thus, according to the first division, a sign can
be (a) a qualisign, a mere quality or appearance (a First); (b) a sinsign or
token, an individual object, or event (a Second); or (c) a legisign or a
general type (a Third). Secondly, signs can be divided into icons, indices, and
symbols on the basis of their relations to their objects: an icon refers to an
object on the basis of its similarity to the object (in some respect); an index
stands in a dynamic or causal relation to its object; whereas a symbol
functions as a sign of an object by virtue of a rule or habit of
interpretation. Peirce’s third division divides signs into rhemes (predicative
signs), propositional signs (propositions), and arguments. Some of the concepts
and distinctions introduced by Peirce, e.g., the distinction between “types”
and “tokens” and the division of signs into “icons,” “indices,” and “symbols,”
have become part of the standard conceptual repertoire of philosophy and
semiotics. In his philosophy of language Peirce made a distinction between a
proposition and an assertion, and studied the logical character of assertive
speech acts. Metaphysics. In spite of his critical attitude toward traditional
metaphysics, Peirce believed that metaphysical questions can be discussed in a
meaningful way. According to Peirce, metaphysics studies the most general
traits of reality, and “kinds of phenomena with which every man’s experience is
so saturated that he usually pays no particular attention to them.” The basic
categories of Firstness, Secondness, and Thirdness mentioned above occupy a
central position in Peirce’s metaphysics. Especially in his later writings he
emphasized the reality and metaphysical irreducibility of Thirdness, and
defended the view that general phenomena (for example, general laws) cannot be
regarded as mere conjunctions of their actual individual instances. This view
was associated with Peirce’s synechism, the doctrine that the world contains
genuinely continuous phenomena. He regarded synechism as a new form of
Scholastic realism. In the area of modalities Peirce’s basic categories appear
as possibility, actuality, and necessity. Here he argued that reality cannot be
identified with existence (or actuality), but comprises real (objective)
possibilities. This view was partly based on his realization that many
conditional statements, for instance the “practical” conditionals expressing
the empirical import of a proposition (in the sense of the Pragmatic Maxim),
cannot be construed as material or truth-functional conditionals, but must be
regarded as modal (subjunctive) conditionals. In his cosmology Peirce propounded
the doctrine of tychism, according to which there is absolute chance in the
universe, and the basic laws of nature are probabilistic and inexact. Peirce’s
position in contemporary philosophy. Peirce had few disciples, but some of his
students and colleagues became influential figures in American philosophy and
science, e.g., the philosophers James, Royce, and Dewey and the economist
Thorstein Veblen. Peirce’s pragmatism Peirce, Charles S(anders) Peirce, Charles
S(anders) 653 653 became widely known
through James’s lectures and writings, but Peirce was dissatisfied with James’s
version of pragmatism, and renamed his own form of it ‘pragmaticism’, which
term he considered to be “ugly enough to keep it safe from kidnappers.”
Pragmatism became an influential philosophical movement during the twentieth
century through Dewey (philosophy of science and philosophy of education), C.
I. Lewis (theory of knowledge), Ramsey, Ernest Nagel, and Quine (philosophy of
science). Peirce’s work in logic influenced, mainly through his contacts with
the German logician Ernst Schröder, the model-theoretic tradition in
twentieth-century logic. There are three comprehensive collections of Peirce’s
papers: Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (1931–58), vols. 1–6 edited
by Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss, vols. 7–8 edited by Arthur Burks; The New
Elements of Mathematics by Charles S. Peirce (1976), edited by Carolyn Eisele;
and Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition (1982–). DEWEY, JAMES, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE,
PRAGMATISM, TRUTH, TYCHISM. R.Hi. Peirce’s law, the principle ‘((A P B) P A) P
A’, which holds in classical logic but fails in the eyes of relevance logicians
when ‘ P’ is read as ‘entails’. IMPLICATION,
Pelagianism, the doctrine
in Christian theology that, through the exercise of free will, human beings can
attain moral perfection. A broad movement devoted to this proposition was only
loosely associated with its eponymous leader. Pelagius (c.354–c.425), a lay
theologian from Britain or Ireland, taught in Rome prior to its sacking in 410.
He and his disciple Celestius found a forceful adversary in Augustine, whom
they provoked to stiffen his stance on original sin, the bondage of the will,
and humanity’s total reliance upon God’s grace and predestination for
salvation. To Pelagius, this constituted fatalism and encouraged moral apathy.
God would not demand perfection, as the Bible sometimes suggested, were that
impossible to attain. Rather grace made the struggle easier for a sanctity that
would not be unreachable even in its absence. Though in the habit of sinning,
in consequence of the fall, we have not forfeited the capacity to overcome that
habit nor been released from the imperative to do so. For all its moral
earnestness this teaching seems to be in conflict with much of the New
Testament, especially as interpreted by Augustine, and it was condemned as
heresy in 418. The bondage of the will has often been reaffirmed, perhaps most
notably by Luther in dispute with Erasmus. Yet Christian theology and practice
have always had their sympathizers with Pelagianism and with its reluctance to
attest the loss of free will, the inevitability of sin, and the utter necessity
of God’s grace. A.E.L. Pelagius.PELAGIANISM. per accidens (Latin, ‘by accident’),
by, as, or being an accident or non-essential feature. A per accidens
predication is one in which an accident is predicated of a substance. (The
terminology is medieval. Note that the accident and substance themselves, not
words standing for them, are the terms of the predication relation.) An ens
(entity) per accidens is either an accident or the “accidental unity” of a
substance and an accident (Descartes, e.g., insists that a person is not a per
accidens union of body and mind.)
perception, the extraction
and use of information about one’s environment (exteroception) and one’s own
body (interoception). The various external senses – sight, hearing, touch,
smell, and taste – though they overlap to some extent, are distinguished by the
kind of information (e.g., about light, sound, temperature, pressure) they
deliver. Proprioception, perception of the self, concerns stimuli arising
within, and carrying information about, one’s own body – e.g., acceleration,
position, and orientation of the limbs. There are distinguishable stages in the
extraction and use of sensory information, one (an earlier stage) corresponding
to our perception of objects (and events), the other, a later stage, to the
perception of facts about these objects. We see, e.g., both the cat on the sofa
(an object) and that the cat is on the sofa (a fact). Seeing an object (or
event) – a cat on the sofa, a person on the street, or a vehicle’s movement –
does not require that the object (event) be identified or recognized in any
particular way (perhaps, though this is controversial, in any way whatsoever).
One can, e.g., see a cat on the sofa and mistake it for a rumpled sweater.
Airplane lights are often misidentified as stars, and one can see the movement
of an object either as the movement of oneself or (under some viewing
conditions) as Peirce’s law perception 654
654 expansion (or contraction). Seeing objects and events is, in this
sense, non-epistemic: one can see O without knowing (or believing) that it is O
that one is seeing. Seeing facts, on the other hand, is epistemic; one cannot
see that there is a cat on the sofa without, thereby, coming to know that there
is a cat on the sofa. Seeing a fact is coming to know the fact in some visual
way. One can see objects – the fly in one’s soup, e.g., – without realizing
that there is a fly in one’s soup (thinking, perhaps, it is a bean or a
crouton); but to see a fact, the fact that there is a fly in one’s soup is,
necessarily, to know it is a fly. This distinction applies to the other sense modalities
as well. One can hear the telephone ringing without realizing that it is the
telephone (perhaps it’s the TV or the doorbell), but to hear a fact, that it is
the telephone (that is ringing), is, of necessity, to know that it is the
telephone that is ringing. The other ways we have of describing what we
perceive are primarily variations on these two fundamental themes. In seeing
where (he went), when (he left), who (went with him), and how he was dressed,
e.g., we are describing the perception of some fact of a certain sort without
revealing exactly which fact it is. If Martha saw where he went, then Martha
saw (hence, came to know) some fact having to do with where he went, some fact
of the form ‘he went there’. In speaking of states and conditions (the
condition of his room, her injury), and properties (the color of his tie, the
height of the building), we sometimes, as in the case of objects, mean to be
describing a non-epistemic perceptual act, one that carries no implications for
what (if anything) is known. In other cases, as with facts, we mean to be
describing the acquisition of some piece of knowledge. One can see or hear a
word without recognizing it as a word (it might be in a foreign language), but
can one see a misprint and not know it is a misprint? It obviously depends on
what one uses ‘misprint’ to refer to: an object (a word that is misprinted) or
a fact (the fact that it is misprinted). In examining and evaluating theories
(whether philosophical or psychological) of perception it is essential to
distinguish fact perception from object perception. For a theory might be a
plausible theory about the perception of objects (e.g., psychological theories
of “early vision”) but not at all plausible about our perception of facts. Fact
perception, involving, as it does, knowledge (and, hence, belief) brings into
play the entire cognitive system (memory, concepts, etc.) in a way the former
does not. Perceptual relativity – e.g., the idea that what we perceive is
relative to our language, our conceptual scheme, or the scientific theories we
have available to “interpret” phenomena – is quite implausible as a theory
about our perception of objects. A person lacking a word for, say, kumquats,
lacking this concept, lacking a scientific way of classifying these objects
(are they a fruit? a vegetable? an animal?), can still see, touch, smell, and
taste kumquats. Perception of objects does not depend on, and is therefore not
relative to, the observer’s linguistic, conceptual, cognitive, and scientific
assets or shortcomings. Fact perception, however, is another matter. Clearly
one cannot see that there are kumquats in the basket (as opposed to seeing the
objects, the kumquats, in the basket) if one has no idea of, no concept of,
what a kumquat is. Seeing facts is much more sensitive (and, hence, relative)
to the conceptual resources, the background knowledge and scientific theories,
of the observer, and this difference must be kept in mind in evaluating claims
about perceptual relativity. Though it does not make objects invisible,
ignorance does tend to make facts perceptually inaccessible. There are
characteristic experiences associated with the different senses. Tasting a
kumquat is not at all like seeing a kumquat although the same object is
perceived (indeed, the same fact – that it is a kumquat – may be perceived).
The difference, of course, is in the subjective experience one has in
perceiving the kumquat. A causal theory of perception (of objects) holds that
the perceptual object, what it is we see, taste, smell, or whatever, is that
object that causes us to have this subjective experience. Perceiving an object
is that object’s causing (in the right way) one to have an experience of the
appropriate sort. I see a bean in my soup if it is, in fact (whether I know it
or not is irrelevant), a bean in my soup that is causing me to have this visual
experience. I taste a bean if, in point of fact, it is a bean that is causing
me to have the kind of taste experience I am now having. If it is (unknown to
me) a bug, not a bean, that is causing these experiences, then I am
(unwittingly) seeing and tasting a bug – perhaps a bug that looks and tastes
like a bean. What object we see (taste, smell, etc.) is determined by the
causal facts in question. What we know and believe, how we interpret the
experience, is irrelevant, although it will, of course, determine what we say
we see and taste. The same is to be said, with appropriate changes, for our
perception of facts (the most significant change being the replacement of belief
for experience). I see that there is a bug in my soup if the fact that there is
a bug in my soup causes me to perception perception 655 655 believe that there is a bug in my soup.
I can taste that there is a bug in my soup when this fact causes me to have
this belief via some taste sensation. A causal theory of perception is more
than the claim that the physical objects we perceive cause us to have
experiences and beliefs. This much is fairly obvious. It is the claim that this
causal relation is constitutive of perception, that necessarily, if S sees O,
then O causes a certain sort of experience in S. It is, according to this
theory, impossible, on conceptual grounds, to perceive something with which one
has no causal contact. If, e.g., future events do not cause present events, if
there is no backward causation, then we cannot perceive future events and
objects. Whether or not future facts can be perceived (or known) depends on how
liberally the causal condition on knowledge is interpreted. Though conceding
that there is a world of mind-independent objects (trees, stars, people) that
cause us to have experiences, some philosophers – traditionally called
representative realists – argue that we nonetheless do not directly perceive
these external objects. What we directly perceive are the effects these objects
have on us – an internal image, idea, or impression, a more or less (depending
on conditions of observation) accurate representation of the external reality
that helps produce it. This subjective, directly apprehended object has been
called by various names: a sensation, percept, sensedatum, sensum, and
sometimes, to emphasize its representational aspect, Vorstellung (German,
‘representation’). Just as the images appearing on a television screen represent
their remote causes (the events occurring at some distant concert hall or
playing field), the images (visual, auditory, etc.) that occur in the mind, the
sensedata of which we are directly aware in normal perception, represent (or
sometimes, when things are not working right, misrepresent) their external
physical causes. The representative realist typically invokes arguments from
illusion, facts about hallucination, and temporal considerations to support his
view. Hallucinations are supposed to illustrate the way we can have the same
kind of experience we have when (as we commonly say) we see a real bug without
there being a real bug (in our soup or anywhere else) causing us to have the
experience. When we hallucinate, the bug we “see” is, in fact, a figment of our
own imagination, an image (i.e., sense-datum) in the mind that, because it
shares some of the properties of a real bug (shape, color, etc.), we might
mistake for a real bug. Since the subjective experiences can be
indistinguishable from that which we have when (as we commonly say) we really
see a bug, it is reasonable to infer (the representative realist argues) that
in normal perception, when we take ourselves to be seeing a real bug, we are
also directly aware of a buglike image in the mind. A hallucination differs
from a normal perception, not in what we are aware of (in both cases it is a
sense-datum) but in the cause of these experiences. In normal perception it is
an actual bug; in hallucination it is, say, drugs in the bloodstream. In both cases,
though, we are caused to have the same thing: an awareness of a buglike
sense-datum, an object that, in normal perception, we naively take to be a real
bug (thus saying, and encouraging our children to say, that we see a bug). The
argument from illusion points to the fact that our experience of an object
changes even when the object that we perceive (or say we perceive) remains
unchanged. Though the physical object (the bug or whatever) remains the same
color, size, and shape, what we experience (according to this argument) changes
color, shape, and size as we change the lighting, our viewing angle, and
distance. Hence, it is concluded, what we experience cannot really be the
physical object itself. Since it varies with changes in both object and viewing
conditions, what we experience must be a causal result, an effect, of both the
object we commonly say we see (the bug) and the conditions in which we view it.
This internal effect, it is concluded, is a sense-datum. Representative
realists have also appealed to the fact that perceiving a physical object is a
causal process that takes time. This temporal lag is most dramatic in the case
of distant objects (e.g., stars), but it exists for every physical object (it
takes time for a neural signal to be transmitted from receptor surfaces to the
brain). Consequently, at the moment (a short time after light leaves the
object’s surface) we see a physical object, the object could no longer exist.
It could have ceased to exist during the time light was being transmitted to
the eye or during the time it takes the eye to communicate with the brain. Yet,
even if the object ceases to exist before we become aware of anything (before a
visual experience occurs), we are, or so it seems, aware of something when the
causal process reaches its climax in the brain. This something of which we are
aware, since it cannot be the physical object (it no longer exists), must be a
sense-datum. The representationalist concludes in this “time-lag argument,”
therefore, that even when the physperception perception 656 656 ical object does not cease to exist
(this, of course, is the normal situation), we are directly aware, not of it,
but of its (slightly later-occurring) representation. Representative realists
differ among themselves about the question of how much (if at all) the
sense-data of which we are aware resemble the external objects (of which we are
not aware). Some take the external cause to have some of the properties (the
so-called primary properties) of the datum (e.g., extension) and not others
(the so-called secondary properties – e.g., color). Direct (or naive) realism
shares with representative realism a commitment to a world of independently
existing objects. Both theories are forms of perceptual realism. It differs, however,
in its view of how we are related to these objects in ordinary perception.
Direct realists deny that we are aware of mental intermediaries (sensedata)
when, as we ordinarily say, we see a tree or hear the telephone ring. Though
direct realists differ in their degree of naïveté about how (and in what
respect) perception is supposed to be direct, they need not be so naive (as
sometimes depicted) as to deny the scientific facts about the causal processes
underlying perception. Direct realists can easily admit, e.g., that physical
objects cause us to have experiences of a particular kind, and that these
experiences are private, subjective, or mental. They can even admit that it is
this causal relationship (between object and experience) that constitutes our
seeing and hearing physical objects. They need not, in other words, deny a
causal theory of perception. What they must deny, if they are to remain direct
realists, however, is an analysis of the subjective experience (that objects
cause us to have) into an awareness of some object. For to understand this
experience as an awareness of some object is, given the wholly subjective
(mental) character of the experience itself, to interpose a mental entity (what
the experience is an awareness of) between the perceiver and the physical
object that causes him to have this experience, the physical object that is
supposed to be directly perceived. Direct realists, therefore, avoid analyzing
a perceptual experience into an act (sensing, being aware of, being acquainted
with) and an object (the sensum, sense-datum, sensation, mental
representation). The experience we are caused to have when we perceive a
physical object or event is, instead, to be understood in some other way. The
adverbial theory is one such possibility. As the name suggests, this theory
takes its cue from the way nouns and adjectives can sometimes be converted into
adverbs without loss of descriptive content. So, for instance, it comes to
pretty much the same thing whether we describe a conversation as animated
(adjective) or say that we conversed animatedly (an adverb). So, also,
according to an adverbialist, when, as we commonly say, we see a red ball, the
red ball causes in us (a moment later) an experience, yes, but not (as the
representative realist says) an awareness (mental act) of a sense-datum (mental
object) that is red and circular (adjectives). The experience is better
understood as one in which there is no object at all, as sensing redly and
circularly (adverbs). The adverbial theorist insists that one can experience
circularly and redly without there being, in the mind or anywhere else, red
circles (this, in fact, is what the adverbialist thinks occurs in dreams and
hallucinations of red circles). To experience redly is not to have a red experience;
nor is it to experience redness (in the mind). It is, says the adverbialist, a
way or a manner of perceiving ordinary objects (especially red ones seen in
normal light). Just as dancing gracefully is not a thing we dance, so
perceiving redly is not a thing – and certainly not a red thing in the mind –
that we experience. The adverbial theory is only one option the direct realist
has of acknowledging the causal basis of perception while, at the same time,
maintaining the directness of our perceptual relation with independently
existing objects. What is important is not that the experience be construed
adverbially, but that it not be interpreted, as representative realists
interpret it, as awareness of some internal object. For a direct realist, the appearances,
though they are subjective (mind-dependent) are not objects that interpose
themselves between the conscious mind and the external world. As classically
understood, both naive and representative realism are theories about object
perception. They differ about whether it is the external object or an internal
object (an idea in the mind) that we (most directly) apprehend in ordinary
sense perception. But they need not (although they usually do) differ in their
analysis of our knowledge of the world around us, in their account of fact
perception. A direct realist about object perception may, e.g., be an indirect
realist about the facts that we know about these objects. To see, not only a
red ball in front of one, but that there is a red ball in front of one, it may
be necessary, even on a direct theory of (object) perception, to infer (or in
some way derive) this fact from facts that are known more directly perception
perception about one’s experiences of the ball. Since, e.g., a direct theorist
may be a causal theorist, may think that seeing a red ball is (in part)
constituted by the having of certain sorts of experience, she may insist that
knowledge of the cause of these experiences must be derived from knowledge of
the experience itself. If one is an adverbialist, e.g., one might insist that
knowledge of physical objects is derived from knowledge of how (redly? bluely?
circularly? squarely?) one experiences these objects. By the same token, a
representative realist could adopt a direct theory of fact perception. Though
the objects we directly see are mental, the facts we come to know by
experiencing these subjective entities are facts about ordinary physical
objects. We do not infer (at least at no conscious level) that there is a bug
in our soup from facts (known more directly) about our own conscious
experiences (from facts about the sensations the bug causes in us). Rather, our
sensations cause us, directly, to have beliefs about our soup. There is no
intermediate belief; hence, there is no intermediate knowledge; hence, no
intermediate fact perception. Fact perception is, in this sense, direct. Or so
a representative realist can maintain even though committed to the indirect
perception of the objects (bug and soup) involved in this fact. This merely
illustrates, once again, the necessity of distinguishing object perception from
fact perception. DIRECT REALISM,
EPISTEMOLOGY, METAPHYSICAL REALISM, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND, SKEPTICISM,
Percival, Thomas
(1740–1804), English physician and author of Medical Ethics (1803). He was
central in bringing the Western traditions of medical ethics from prayers and
oaths (e.g., the Hippocratic oath) toward more detailed, modern codes of proper
professional conduct. His writing on the normative aspects of medical practice
was part ethics, part prudential advice, part professional etiquette, and part
jurisprudence. Medical Ethics treated standards for the professional conduct of
physicians relative to surgeons and apothecaries (pharmacists and general
practitioners), as well as hospitals, private practice, and the law. The issues
Percival addressed include privacy, truth telling, rules for professional
consultation, human experimentation, public and private trust, compassion,
sanity, suicide, abortion, capital punishment, and environmental nuisances.
Percival had his greatest influence in England and America. At its founding in
1847, the American Medical Association used Medical Ethics to guide its own
first code of medical ethics.
perdurance, in one common
philosophical use, the property of being temporally continuous and having
temporal parts. There are at least two conflicting theories about temporally
continuous substances. According to the first, temporally continuous substances
have temporal parts (they perdure), while according to the second, they do not.
In one ordinary philosophical use, endurance is the property of being
temporally continuous and not having temporal parts. There are modal versions
of the aforementioned two theories: for example, one version of the first
theory is that necessarily, temporally continuous substances have temporal
parts, while another version implies that possibly, they do not. Some versions
of the first theory hold that a temporally continuous substance is composed of
instantaneous temporal parts or “object-stages,” while on other versions these
object-stages are not parts but boundaries.
IDENTITY, METAPHYSICS, PERSONAL
perfect competition, the
state of an ideal market under the following conditions: (a) every consumer in
the market is a perfectly rational maximizer of utility; (b) every producer is
a perfect maximizer of profit; (c) there is a very large (ideally infinite)
number of producers of the good in question, which ensures that no producer can
set the price for its output (otherwise, an imperfect competitive state of
oligopoly or monopoly obtains); and (d) every producer provides a product
perfectly indistinguishable from that of other producers (if consumers could
distinguish products to the point that there was no longer a very large number
of producers for each distinguishable good, competition would again be
imperfect). Under these conditions, the market price is equal to the marginal
cost of producing the last unit. This in turn determines the market supply of
the good, since each producer will gain by increasing production when price
exceeds marginal cost and will generally cut losses by decreasing production
when marginal cost exceeds price. Perfect competition is sometimes perceptual
realism perfect competition 658 658 thought
to have normative implications for political philosophy, since it results in
Pareto optimality. The concept of perfect competition becomes extremely
complicated when a market’s evolution is considered. Producers who cannot
equate marginal cost with the market price will have negative profit and must
drop out of the market. If this happens very often, then the number of
producers will no longer be large enough to sustain perfect competition, so new
producers will need to enter the market.
PHILOSOPHY OF ECONOMICS, PRODUCTION
perfectionism, an ethical
view according to which individuals and their actions are judged by a maximal
standard of achievement – specifically, the degree to which they approach
ideals of aesthetic, intellectual, emotional, or physical “perfection.”
Perfectionism, then, may depart from, or even dispense with, standards of
conventional morality in favor of standards based on what appear to be
non-moral values. These standards reflect an admiration for certain very rare
levels of human achievement. Perhaps the most characteristic of these standards
are artistic and other forms of creativity; but they prominently include a
variety of other activities and emotional states deemed “noble” – e.g., heroic
endurance in the face of great suffering. The perfectionist, then, would also
tend toward a rather non-egalitarian – even aristocratic – view of humankind.
The rare genius, the inspired few, the suffering but courageous artist – these
examples of human perfection are genuinely worthy of our estimation, according
to this view. Although no fully worked-out system of “perfectionist philosophy”
has been attempted, aspects of all of these doctrines may be found in such
philosophers as Nietzsche. Aristotle, as well, appears to endorse a perfectionist
idea in his characterization of the human good. Just as the good lyre player
not only exhibits the characteristic activities of this profession but achieves
standards of excellence with respect to these, the good human being, for
Aristotle, must achieve standards of excellence with respect to the virtue or
virtues distinctive of human life in general.
ARISTOTLE, NIETZSCHE, VIRTUE ETHICS. J.A.M. perfectionism, Emersonian.
THEORY. performative fallacy.INFORMAL FALLACY. per genus et differentiam.
DEFINITION. Peripatetic
School, also called Peripatos, the philosophical community founded by Aristotle
at a public gymnasium (the Lyceum) after his return to Athens in c.335 B.C. The
derivation of ‘Peripatetic’ from the alleged Aristotelian custom of “walking about”
(peripatein) is probably wrong. The name should be explained by reference to a
“covered walking hall” (peripatos) among the school facilities. A scholarch or
headmaster presided over roughly two classes of members: the presbyteroi or
seniors, who probably had some teaching duties, and the neaniskoi or juniors.
No evidence of female philosophers in the Lyceum has survived. During
Aristotle’s lifetime his own lectures, whether for the inner circle of the
school or for the city at large, were probably the key attraction and core
activity; but given Aristotle’s knack for organizing group research projects,
we may assume that young and old Peripatetics spent much of their time working
on their own specific assignments either at the library, where they could consult
works of earlier writers, or at some kind of repository for specimens used in
zoological and botanical investigations. As a resident alien, Aristotle could
not own property in Athens and hence was not the legal owner of the school.
Upon his final departure from Athens in 322, his longtime collaborator
Theophrastus of Eresus in Lesbos (c.370–287) succeeded him as scholarch.
Theophrastus was an able Aristotelian who wrote extensively on metaphysics,
psychology, physiology, botany, ethics, politics, and the history of
philosophy. With the help of the Peripatetic dictator Demetrius of Phaleron, he
was able to secure property rights over the physical facilities of the school.
Under Theophrastus, the Peripatos continued to flourish and is said to have had
2,000 students, surely not all at the same time. His successor, Strato of
Lampsakos (c.335–269), had narrower interests and abandoned key Aristotelian
tenets. With him a progressive decline set in, to which the early loss of
Aristotle’s personal library, taken to Asia Minor perfect duty Peripatetic
School 659 659 by Neleus of Skepsis,
certainly contributed. By the first century B.C. the Peripatos had ceased to
exist. Philosophers of later periods sympathetic to Aristotle’s views have also
been called Peripatetics. PERIPATETIC
SCHOOL. perlocutionary act.SPEECH ACT THEORY. permissibility.DEONTIC LOGIC,
EPISTEMOLOGY. Perry, Ralph Barton (1876–1957), American philosopher who taught
at Harvard University and wrote extensively in ethics, social philosophy, and the
theory of knowledge. He received a Pulitzer Prize in 1936 for The Thought and
Character of William James, a biography of his teacher and colleague. Perry’s
other major works include: The Moral Economy (1909), General Theory of Value
(1926), Puritanism and Democracy (1944), and Realms of Value (1954). He is
perhaps best known for his views on value. He writes in General Theory of
Value, “Any object, whatever it be, acquires value when any interest, whatever
it be, is taken in it; just as anything whatsoever becomes a target when anyone
whosoever aims at it.” Something’s having value is nothing but its being the
object of some interest, and to know whether it has value one need only know
whether it is the object of someone’s interest. Morality aims at the promotion
of the moral good, which he defines as “harmonious happiness.” This consists in
the reconciliation, harmonizing, and fulfillment of all interests. Perry’s
epistemological and metaphysical views were part of a revolt against idealism
and dualism. Along with five other philosophers, he wrote The New Realism
(1912). The “New Realists” held that the objects of perception and memory are
directly presented to consciousness and are just what they appear to be;
nothing intervenes between the knower and the external world. The view that the
objects of perception and memory are presented by means of ideas leads, they
argued, to idealism, skepticism, and absurdity. Perry is also known for having
developed, along with E. B. Holt, the “specific response” theory, which is an
attempt to construe belief and perception in terms of bodily adjustment and
behavior. NEW REALISM, VALUE. N.M.L. per
se.ESSENTIALISM, PER
personal identity, the
(numerical) identity over time of persons. The question of what personal
identity consists in is the question of what it is (what the necessary and
sufficient conditions are) for a person existing at one time and a person
existing at another time to be one and the same person. Here there is no
question of there being any entity that is the “identity” of a person; to say
that a person’s identity consists in such and such is just shorthand for saying
that facts about personal identity, i.e., facts to the effect that someone
existing at one time is the same as someone existing at another time, consist
in such and such. (This should not be confused with the usage, common in
ordinary speech and in psychology, in which persons are said to have
identities, and, sometimes, to seek, lose, or regain their identities, where
one’s “identity” intimately involves a set of values and goals that structure
one’s life.) The words ‘identical’ and ‘same’ mean nothing different in
judgments about persons than in judgments about other things. The problem of
personal identity is therefore not one of defining a special sense of
‘identical,’ and it is at least misleading to characterize it as defining a
particular kind of identity. Applying Quine’s slogan “no entity without
identity,” one might say that characterizing any sort of entity involves
indicating what the identity conditions for entities of that sort are (so,
e.g., part of the explanation of the concept of a set is that sets having the
same members are identical), and that asking what the identity of persons
consists in is just a way of asking what sorts of things persons are. But the
main focus in traditional discussions of the topic has been on one kind of
identity judgment about persons, namely those asserting “identity over time”;
the question has been about what the persistence of persons over time consists
in. What has made the identity (persistence) of persons of special
philosophical interest is partly its epistemology and partly its connections
with moral and evaluative matters. The crucial epistemological fact is that
persons have, in memory, an access to their own past histories that is unlike
the access they have to the histories of other things (including other
persons); when one remembers doing or experiencing something, one normally has
no need to employ any criterion of identity in order to know that the subject
of the remembered action or experience is (i.e., is identical with) oneself.
The moral and evaluative matters include moral responsibility (someone can be
held responsible for a past action only Peripatos personal identity 660 660 if he or she is identical to the person
who did it) and our concern for our own survival and future well-being (since
it seems, although this has been questioned, that what one wants in wanting to
survive is that there should exist in the future someone who is identical to
oneself). The modern history of the topic of personal identity begins with
Locke, who held that the identity of a person consists neither in the identity
of an immaterial substance (as dualists might be expected to hold) nor in the
identity of a material substance or “animal body” (as materialists might be
expected to hold), and that it consists instead in “same consciousness.” His
view appears to have been that the persistence of a person through time
consists in the fact that certain actions, thoughts, experiences, etc.,
occurring at different times, are somehow united in memory. Modern theories
descended from Locke’s take memory continuity to be a special case of something
more general, psychological continuity, and hold that personal identity
consists in this. This is sometimes put in terms of the notion of a
“person-stage,” i.e., a momentary “time slice” of the history of a person. A
series of person-stages will be psychologically continuous if the psychological
states (including memories) occurring in later members of the series grow out
of, in certain characteristic ways, those occurring in earlier members of it;
and according to the psychological continuity view of personal identity,
person-stages occurring at different times are stages of the same person
provided they belong to a single, non-branching, psychologically continuous
series of person-stages. Opponents of the Lockean and neo-Lockean
(psychological continuity) view tend to fall into two camps. Some, following
Butler and Reid, hold that personal identity is indefinable, and that nothing
informative can be said about what it consists in. Others hold that the
identity of a person consists in some sort of physical continuity – perhaps the
identity of a living human organism, or the identity of a human brain. In the
actual cases we know about (putting aside issues about non-bodily survival of
death), psychological continuity and physical continuity go together. Much of
the debate between psychological continuity theories and physical continuity
theories has centered on the interpretation of thought experiments involving
brain transplants, brain-state transfers, etc., in which these come apart. Such
examples make vivid the question of whether our fundamental criteria of
personal identity are psychological, physical, or both. Recently philosophical
attention has shifted somewhat from the question of what personal identity
consists in to questions about its importance. The consideration of
hypothetical cases of “fission” (in which two persons at a later time are
psychologically continuous with one person at an earlier time) has suggested to
some that we can have survival – or at any rate what matters in survival –
without personal identity, and that our self-interested concern for the future
is really a concern for whatever future persons are psychologically continuous
with us.
personalism, a version of
personal idealism that flourished in the United States (principally at Boston
University) from the late nineteenth century to the mid-twentieth century. Its
principal proponents were Borden Parker Bowne (1847– 1910) and three of his
students: Albert Knudson (1873–1953); Ralph Flewelling (1871–1960), who founded
The Personalist; and, most importantly, Edgar Sheffield Brightman (1884–1953).
Their personalism was both idealistic and theistic and was influential in
philosophy and in theology. Personalism traced its philosophical lineage to
Berkeley and Leibniz, and had as its foundational insight the view that all
reality is ultimately personal. God is the transcendent person and the ground
or creator of all other persons; nature is a system of objects either for or in
the minds of persons. Both Bowne and Brightman considered themselves
empiricists in the tradition of Berkeley. Immediate experience is the starting
point, but this experience involves a fundamental knowledge of the self as a
personal being with changing states. Given this pluralism, the coherence,
order, and intelligibility of the universe are seen to derive from God, the
uncreated person. Bowne’s God is the eternal and omnipotent being of classical
theism, but Brightman argued that if God is a real person he must be construed
as both temporal and finite. Given the fact of evil, God is seen as gradually
gaining control over his created world, with regard to which his will is
intrinsically limited. Another version of personalism developed in France out
of the neo-Scholastic tradition. E. Mounier (1905–50), Maritain, and Gilson
identified themselves as personalists, inasmuch as they viewed the infinite
person (God) and finite persons as the source and locus of intrinsic value.
They did not, however, view the natural order as intrinsically personal.
IDEALISM, NEO-THOMISM. C.F.D. personalism
personalism 661 661
personality.CHARACTER. personal supposition.
SUPPOSITIO. personhood,
the condition or property of being a person, especially when this is considered
to entail moral and/or metaphysical importance. Personhood has been thought to
involve various traits, including (moral) agency; reason or rationality;
language, or the cognitive skills language may support (such as intentionality
and self-consciousness); and ability to enter into suitable relations with
other persons (viewed as members of a self-defining group). Buber emphasized the
difference between the I-It relationship holding between oneself and an object,
and the IThou relationship, which holds between oneself and another person (who
can be addressed). Dennett has construed persons in terms of the “intentional
stance,” which involves explaining another’s behavior in terms of beliefs,
desires, intentions, etc. Questions about when personhood begins and when it
ends have been central to debates about abortion, infanticide, and euthanasia,
since personhood has often been viewed as the mark, if not the basis, of a
being’s possession of special moral status.
Peter Lombard
(c.1095–1160), Italian theologian and author of the Book of Sentences (Liber
sententiarum), a renowned theological sourcebook in the later Middle Ages.
Peter was educated at Bologna, Reims, and Paris before teaching in the school
of Notre Dame in Paris. He became a canon at Notre Dame in 1144–45 and was
elected bishop of Paris in 1159. His extant works include commentaries on the
Psalms (written in the mid-1130s) and on the epistles of Paul (c.1139–41); a
collection of sermons; and his one-volume summary of Christian doctrine, the
Sentences (completed by 1158). The Sentences consists of four books: Book I, On
the Trinity; Book II, On the Creation of Things; Book III, On the Incarnation;
and Book IV, On the Doctrine of Signs (or Sacraments). His discussion is
organized around particular questions or issues e.g., “On Knowledge,
Foreknowledge, and Providence” (Book I), “Is God the Cause of Evil and Sin?”
(Book II). For a given issue Peter typically presents a brief summary,
accompanied by short quotations, of main positions found in Scripture and in
the writings of the church fathers and doctors, followed by his own
determination or adjudication of the matter. Himself a theological
conservative, Peter seems to have intended this sort of compilation of
scriptural and ancient doctrinal teaching as a counter to the popularity,
fueled by the recent recovery of important parts of Aristotle’s logic, of the
application of dialectic to theological matters. The Sentences enjoyed wide
circulation and admiration from the beginning, and within a century of its
composition it became a standard text in the theology curriculum. From the
midthirteenth through the mid-fourteenth century every student of theology was
required, as the last stage in obtaining the highest academic degree, to
lecture and comment on Peter’s text. Later medieval thinkers often referred to
Peter as “the Master” (magister), thereby testifying to the Sentences’ preeminence
in theological training. In lectures and commentaries, the greatest minds of
this period used Peter’s text as a framework in which to develop their own
original positions and debate with their contemporaries. As a result the
Sentences-commentary tradition is an extraordinarily rich repository of later
medieval philosophical and theological thought. S.Ma. Peter of Spain. It is now
thought that there were two Peters of Spain. The Spanish prelate and
philosopher (c.1205–77) was born in Lisbon, studied at Paris, and taught
medicine at Siena (1248–50). He served in various ecclesiastical posts in
Portugal and Italy (1250–73) before being elected pope as John XXI in 1276. He
wrote several books on philosophical psychology and compiled the famous medical
work Thesaurus pauperum. The second Peter of Spain was a Spanish Dominican who
lived during the first half of the thirteenth century. His Tractatus, later
called Summulae logicales, received over 166 printings during subsequent
centuries. The Tractatus presents the essentials of Aristotelian logic
(propositions, universals, categories, syllogism, dialectical topics, and the
sophistical fallacies) and improves on the mnemonic verses of William Sherwood;
he then introduces the subjects of the so-called parva logicalia (supposition,
relatives, ampliation, personality Peter of Spain 662 662 appellation, restriction,
distribution), all of which were extensively developed in the later Middle
Ages. There is not sufficient evidence to claim that Peter wrote a special
treatise on consequences, but his understanding of conditionals as assertions
of necessary connection undoubtedly played an important role in the rules of
simple, as opposed to as-of-now, consequences. I.Bo. petitio principii.
phantasia (Greek,
‘appearance’, ‘imagination’), (1) the state we are in when something appears to
us to be the case; (2) the capacity in virtue of which things appear to us.
Although frequently used of conscious and imagistic experiences, ‘phantasia’ is
not limited to such states; in particular, it can be applied to any
propositional attitude where something is taken to be the case. But just as the
English ‘appears’ connotes that one has epistemic reservations about what is
actually the case, so ‘phantasia’ suggests the possibility of being misled by
appearances and is thus often a subject of criticism. According to Plato,
phantasia is a “mixture” of sensation and belief; in Aristotle, it is a
distinct faculty that makes truth and falsehood possible. The Stoics take a
phantasia to constitute one of the most basic mental states, in terms of which
other mental states are to be explained, and in rational animals it bears the
propositional content expressed in language. This last use becomes prominent in
ancient literary and rhetorical theory to designate the ability of language to
move us and convey subjects vividly as well as to range beyond the bounds of
our immediate experience. Here lie the origins of the modern concept of
imagination (although not the Romantic distinction between fancy and
imagination). Later Neoplatonists, such as Proclus, take phantasia to be
necessary for abstract studies such as geometry, by enabling us to envision
spatial relations.
STATE. phenomena.KANT.
phenomenal body.EMBODIMENT. phenomenalism, the view that propositions asserting
the existence of physical objects are equivalent in meaning to propositions
asserting that subjects would have certain sequences of sensations were they to
have certain others. The basic idea behind phenomenalism is compatible with a
number of different analyses of the self or conscious subject. A phenomenalist
might understand the self as a substance, a particular, or a construct out of
actual and possible experience. The view also is compatible with any number of
different analyses of the visual, tactile, auditory, olfactory, gustatory, and
kinesthetic sensations described in the antecedents and consequents of the
subjunctive conditionals that the phenomenalist uses to analyze physical object
propositions (as illustrated in the last paragraph). Probably the most common
analysis of sensations adopted by traditional phenomenalists is a sense-datum
theory, with the sense-data construed as mind-dependent entities. But there is
nothing to prevent a phenomenalist from accepting an adverbial theory or theory
of appearing instead. The origins of phenomenalism are difficult to trace, in
part because early statements of the view were usually not careful. In his
Dialogues, Berkeley hinted at phenomenalism when he had Philonous explain how
he could reconcile an ontology containing only minds and ideas with the story
of a creation that took place before the existence of people. Philonous
imagines that if he had been present at the creation he should have seen
things, i.e., had sensations, in the order described in the Bible. It can also
be argued, however, that J. S. Mill in An Examination of Sir William Hamilton’s
Philosophy was the first to put forth a clearly phenomenalistic analysis when
he identified matter with the “permanent possibility of sensation.” When Mill
explained what these permanent possibilities are, he typically used
conditionals that describe the sensations one would have if one were placed in
certain conditions. The attraction of classical phenomenalism grew with the
rise of logical positivism and its acceptance of the verifiability criterion of
meaning. Phenomenalists were usually foundationalists who were convinced that
justified belief in the physical world rested ultimately on our
noninferentially justified beliefs about our sensations. Implicitly committed
to the view that only deductive and inductive inferences are legitimate, and
further assuming that to be justified in believing one proposition P on the
basis of another E, one must be justified in believing both E and that E makes
P probable, the phenomenalist saw an insuperable difficulty in justifying
belief in ordinary statements about the physical world given prevalent
conceptions of physical petitio principii phenomenalism 663 663 objects. If all we ultimately have as
our evidence for believing in physical objects is what we know about the
occurrence of sensation, how can we establish sensation as evidence for the
existence of physical objects? We obviously cannot deduce the existence of
physical objects from any finite sequence of sensations. The sensations could,
e.g., be hallucinatory. Nor, it seems, can we observe a correlation between
sensation and something else in order to generate the premises of an inductive
argument for the conclusion that sensations are reliable indicators of physical
objects. The key to solving this problem, the phenomenalist argues, is to
reduce assertions about the physical world to complicated assertions about the
sequences of sensations a subject would have were he to have certain others.
The truth of such conditionals, e.g., that if I have the clear visual
impression of a cat, then there is one before me, might be mind-independent in
the way in which one wants the truth of assertions about the physical world to
be mind-independent. And to the phenomenalist’s great relief, it would seem
that we could justify our belief in such conditional statements without having
to correlate anything but sensations. Many philosophers today reject some of
the epistemological, ontological, and metaphilosophical presuppositions with
which phenomenalists approached the problem of understanding our relation to
the physical world through sensation. But the argument that was historically
most decisive in convincing many philosophers to abandon phenomenalism was the
argument from perceptual relativity first advanced by Chisholm in “The Problem
of Perception.” Chisholm offers a strategy for attacking any phenomenalistic
analysis. The first move is to force the phenomenalist to state a conditional
describing only sensations that is an alleged consequence of a physical object
proposition. C. I. Lewis, e.g., in An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation,
claims that the assertion (P) that there is a doorknob before me and to the
left entails (C) that if I were to seem to see a doorknob and seem to reach out
and touch it then I would seem to feel it. Chisholm argues that if P really did
entail C then there could be no assertion R that when conjoined with P did not
entail C. There is, however, such an assertion: I am unable to move my limbs
and my hands but am subject to delusions such that I think I am moving them; I
often seem to be initiating a grasping motion but with no feeling of contacting
anything. Chisholm argues, in effect, that what sensations one would have if
one were to have certain others always depends in part on the internal and
external physical conditions of perception and that this fact dooms any attempt
to find necessary and sufficient conditions for the truth of a physical object
proposition couched in terms that describe only connections between
sensations.
BERKELEY; LEWIS, C. I.;
LOGICAL POSITIVISM; PERCEPTION. R.A.F. phenomenal property.QUALIA. phenomenal
world.KANT. phenomenological attitude.HUSSERL. phenomenological
reduction.HUSSERL. phenomenology, in the twentieth century, the philosophy
developed by Husserl and some of his followers. The term has been used since
the mideighteenth century and received a carefully defined technical meaning in
the works of both Kant and Hegel, but it is not now used to refer to a
homogeneous and systematically developed philosophical position. The question
of what phenomenology is may suggest that phenomenology is one among the many
contemporary philosophical conceptions that have a clearly delineated body of
doctrines and whose essential characteristics can be expressed by a set of
wellchosen statements. This notion is not correct, however. In contemporary
philosophy there is no system or school called “phenomenology,” characterized
by a clearly defined body of teachings. Phenomenology is neither a school nor a
trend in contemporary philosophy. It is rather a movement whose proponents, for
various reasons, have propelled it in many distinct directions, with the result
that today it means different things to different people. While within the
phenomenological movement as a whole there are several related currents, they,
too, are by no means homogeneous. Though these currents have a common point of
departure, they do not project toward the same destination. The thinking of most
phenomenologists has changed so greatly that their respective views can be
presented adequately only by showing them in their gradual development. This is
true not only for Husserl, founder of the phenomenological movement, but also
for such later phenomenologists as Scheler, N. Hartmann, Heidegger, Sartre, and
Merleau-Ponty. To anyone who studies the phenomenological movement without
prejudice the differences among its many currents are obvious. It has been
phenomenal property phenomenology 664
664 said that phenomenology consists in an analysis and description of
consciousness; it has been claimed also that phenomenology simply blends with
existentialism. Phenomenology is indeed the study of essences, but it also
attempts to place essences back into existence. It is a transcendental
philosophy interested only in what is “left behind” after the phenomenological
reduction is performed, but it also considers the world to be already there
before reflection begins. For some philosophers phenomenology is speculation on
transcendental subjectivity, whereas for others it is a method for approaching
concrete existence. Some use phenomenology as a search for a philosophy that
accounts for space, time, and the world, just as we experience and “live” them.
Finally, it has been said that phenomenology is an attempt to give a direct
description of our experience as it is in itself without taking into account
its psychological origin and its causal explanation; but Husserl speaks of a
“genetic” as well as a “constitutive” phenomenology. To some people, finding
such an abundance of ideas about one and the same subject constitutes a strange
situation; for others it is annoying to contemplate the “confusion”; and there
will be those who conclude that a philosophy that cannot define its own scope
does not deserve the discussion that has been carried on in its regard. In the
opinion of many, not only is this latter attitude not justified, but precisely
the opposite view defended by Thevenaz should be adopted. As the term ‘phenomenology’
signifies first and foremost a methodical conception, Thevenaz argues that
because this method, originally developed for a very particular and limited
end, has been able to branch out in so many varying forms, it manifests a
latent truth and power of renewal that implies an exceptional fecundity.
Speaking of the great variety of conceptions within the phenomenological
movement, Merleau-Ponty remarked that the responsible philosopher must
recognize that phenomenology may be practiced and identified as a manner or a
style of thinking, and that it existed as a movement before arriving at a
complete awareness of itself as a philosophy. Rather than force a living
movement into a system, then, it seems more in keeping with the ideal of the
historian as well as the philosopher to follow the movement in its development,
and attempt to describe and evaluate the many branches in and through which it
has unfolded itself. In reality the picture is not as dark as it may seem at
first sight. Notwithstanding the obvious differences, most phenomenologists
share certain insights that are very important for their mutual philosophical
conception as a whole. In this connection the following must be mentioned: (1)
Most phenomenologists admit a radical difference between the “natural” and the
“philosophical” attitude. This leads necessarily to an equally radical
difference between philosophy and science. In characterizing this difference
some phenomenologists, in agreement with Husserl, stress only epistemological issues,
whereas others, in agreement with Heidegger, focus their attention exclusively
on ontological topics. (2) Notwithstanding this radical difference, there is a
complicated set of relationships between philosophy and science. Within the
context of these relationships philosophy has in some sense a foundational task
with respect to the sciences, whereas science offers to philosophy at least a
substantial part of its philosophical problematic. (3) To achieve its task
philosophy must perform a certain reduction, or epoche, a radical change of
attitude by which the philosopher turns from things to their meanings, from the
ontic to the ontological, from the realm of the objectified meaning as found in
the sciences to the realm of meaning as immediately experienced in the
“life-world.” In other words, although it remains true that the various
phenomenologists differ in characterizing the reduction, no one seriously
doubts its necessity. (4) All phenomenologists subscribe to the doctrine of
intentionality, though most elaborate this doctrine in their own way. For
Husserl intentionality is a characteristic of conscious phenomena or acts; in a
deeper sense, it is the characteristic of a finite consciousness that
originally finds itself without a world. For Heidegger and most existentialists
it is the human reality itself that is intentional; as Being-in-the-world its
essence consists in its ek-sistence, i.e., in its standing out toward the
world. (5) All phenomenologists agree on the fundamental idea that the basic concern
of philosophy is to answer the question concerning the “meaning and Being” of
beings. All agree in addition that in trying to materialize this goal the
philosopher should be primarily interested not in the ultimate cause of all
finite beings, but in how the Being of beings and the Being of the world are to
be constituted. Finally, all agree that in answering the question concerning
the meaning of Being a privileged position is to be attributed to subjectivity,
i.e., to that being which questions the Being of beings. Phenomenologists
differ, phenomenology phenomenology 665
665 however, the moment they have to specify what is meant by
subjectivity. As noted above, whereas Husserl conceives it as a worldless monad,
Heidegger and most later phenomenologists conceive it as being-in-the-world.
Referring to Heidegger’s reinterpretation of his phenomenology, Husserl writes:
one misinterprets my phenomenology backwards from a level which it was its very
purpose to overcome, in other words, one has failed to understand the
fundamental novelty of the phenomenological reduction and hence the progress
from mundane subjectivity (i.e., man) to transcendental subjectivity;
consequently one has remained stuck in an anthropology . . . which according to
my doctrine has not yet reached the genuine philosophical level, and whose
interpretation as philosophy means a lapse into “transcendental
anthropologism,” that is, “psychologism.” (6) All phenomenologists defend a
certain form of intuitionism and subscribe to what Husserl calls the “principle
of all principles”: “whatever presents itself in ‘intuition’ in primordial form
(as it were in its bodily reality), is simply to be accepted as it gives itself
out to be, though only within the limits in which it then presents itself.”
Here again, however, each phenomenologist interprets this principle in keeping
with his general conception of phenomenology as a whole. Thus, while
phenomenologists do share certain insights, the development of the movement has
nevertheless been such that it is not possible to give a simple definition of
what phenomenology is. The fact remains that there are many phenomenologists
and many phenomenologies. Therefore, one can only faithfully report what one
has experienced of phenomenology by reading the phenomenologists.
SARTRE, SCHELER. J.J.K.
phenotext.KRISTEVA. Philodemus.EPICUREANISM. Philo Judaeus (c.20 B.C.–A.D. 40),
Jewish Hellenistic philosopher of Alexandria who composed the bulk of his work
in the form of commentaries and discourses on Scripture. He made the first
known sustained attempt to synthesize its revealed teachings with the doctrines
of classical philosophy. Although he was not the first to apply the methods of
allegorical interpretation to Scripture, the number and variety of his interpretations
make Philo unique. With this interpretive tool, he transformed biblical
narratives into Platonic accounts of the soul’s quest for God and its struggle
against passion, and the Mosaic commandments into specific manifestations of
general laws of nature. Philo’s most influential idea was his conception of
God, which combines the personal, ethical deity of the Bible with the abstract,
transcendentalist theology of Platonism and Pythagoreanism. The Philonic deity
is both the loving, just God of the Hebrew Patriarchs and the eternal One whose
essence is absolutely unknowable and who creates the material world by will
from primordial matter which He creates ex nihilo. Besides the intelligible
realm of ideas, which Philo is the earliest known philosopher to identify as
God’s thoughts, he posited an intermediate divine being which he called,
adopting scriptural language, the logos. Although the exact nature of the logos
is hard to pin down – Philo variously and, without any concern for consistency,
called it the “first-begotten Son of the uncreated Father,” “Second God,” “idea
of ideas,” “archetype of human reason,” and “pattern of creation” – its main
functions are clear: to bridge the huge gulf between the transcendent deity and
the lower world and to serve as the unifying law of the universe, the ground of
its order and rationality. A philosophical eclectic, Philo was unknown to
medieval Jewish philosophers but, beyond his anticipations of Neoplatonism, he
had a lasting impact on Christianity through Clement of Alexandria, Origen, and
Ambrose. HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY. J.Ste.
Philolaus (470?–390? B.C.), pre-Socratic Greek philosopher from Croton in
southern Italy, the first Pythagorean to write a book. The surviving fragments
of it are the earliest primary texts for Pythagoreanism, but numerous spurious
fragments have also been preserved. Philolaus’s book begins with a cosmogony
and includes astronomical, medical, and psychological doctrines. His major
innovation was to argue that the cosmos and everything in it is a combination
not just of unlimiteds (what is structured and ordered, e.g. material elements)
but also of limiters (structural and ordering elements, e.g. shapes). These
elements are held together in a harmonia (fitting together), which comes to be
in accord with perspicuous mathematical relationships, such as the whole number
ratios that correspond to the harmonic intervals (e.g. octave % phenotext
Philolaus 666 666 1 : 2). He argued
that secure knowledge is possible insofar as we grasp the number in accordance
with which things are put together. His astronomical system is famous as the
first to make the earth a planet. Along with the sun, moon, fixed stars, five
planets, and counter-earth (thus making the perfect number ten), the earth
circles the central fire (a combination of the limiter “center” and the
unlimited “fire”). Philolaus’s influence is seen in Plato’s Philebus; he is the
primary source for Aristotle’s account of Pythagoreanism. PYTHAGORAS. C.A.H. Philo of Larisa.ACADEMY.
Philoponus, John.JOHANNES PHILOPONUS. philosopher’s stone.
philosophia perennis, a
supposed body of truths that appear in the writings of the great philosophers,
or the truths common to opposed philosophical viewpoints. The term is derived
from the title of a book (De perenni philosophia) published by Agostino Steuco
of Gubbio in 1540. It suggests that the differences between philosophers are
inessential and superficial and that the common essential truth emerges,
however partially, in the major philosophical schools. Aldous Huxley employed
it as a title. L. Lavelle, N. Hartmann, and K. Jaspers also employ the phrase.
M. De Wulf and many others use the phrase to characterize Neo-Thomism as the
chosen vehicle of essential philosophical truths. R.M. philosophical anthropology,
philosophical inquiry concerning human nature, often starting with the question
of what generally characterizes human beings in contrast to other kinds of
creatures and things. Thus broadly conceived, it is a kind of inquiry as old as
philosophy itself, occupying philosophers from Socrates to Sartre; and it
embraces philosophical psychology, the philosophy of mind, philosophy of
action, and existentialism. Such inquiry presupposes no immutable “essence of
man,” but only the meaningfulness of distinguishing between what is “human” and
what is not, and the possibility that philosophy as well as other disciplines
may contribute to our self-comprehension. It leaves open the question of
whether other kinds of naturally occurring or artificially produced entity may
possess the hallmarks of our humanity, and countenances the possibility of the
biologically evolved, historically developed, and socially and individually
variable character of everything about our attained humanity. More narrowly
conceived, philosophical anthropology is a specific movement in recent European
philosophy associated initially with Scheler and Helmuth Plessner, and
subsequently with such figures as Arnold Gehlen, Cassirer, and the later
Sartre. It initially emerged in the late 1920s in Germany, simultaneously with
the existential philosophy of Heidegger and the critical social theory of the
Frankfurt School, with which it competed as German philosophers turned their
attention to the comprehension of human life. This movement was distinguished
from the outset by its attempt to integrate the insights of phenomenological
analysis with the perspectives attainable through attention to human and
comparative biology, and subsequently to social inquiry as well. This turn to a
more naturalistic approach to the understanding of ourselves, as a particular
kind of living creature among others, is reflected in the titles of the two
works published in 1928 that inaugurated the movement: Scheler’s Man’s Place in
Nature and Plessner’s The Levels of the Organic and Man. For both Scheler and
Plessner, however, as for those who followed them, our nature must be
understood by taking further account of the social, cultural, and intellectual
dimensions of human life. Even those like Gehlen, whose Der Mensch (1940)
exhibits a strongly biological orientation, devoted much attention to these
dimensions, which our biological nature both constrains and makes possible. For
all of them, the relation between the biological and the social and cultural
dimensions of human life is a central concern and a key to comprehending our
human nature. One of the common themes of the later
philosophical-anthropological literature – e.g., Cassirer’s An Essay on Man
(1945) and Sartre’s Critique of Dialectical Reason (1960) as well as Plessner’s
Contitio Humana (1965) and Gehlen’s Early Man and Late Culture (1963) – is the
plasticity of human nature, made possible by our biological constitution, and
the resulting great differences in the ways human beings live. Yet this is not
taken to preclude saying anything meaningful about human nature generally;
rather, it merely requires attention to the kinds of general features involved
and reflected in human diversity and variability. Critics of the very idea and
possibility of a philosophical anthropology (e.g., Althusser and Foucault)
typically either deny that there are any Philo of Larisa philosophical
anthropology 667 667 such general
features or maintain that there are none outside the province of the biological
sciences (to which philosophy can contribute nothing substantive). Both claims,
however, are open to dispute; and the enterprise of a philosophical
anthropology remains a viable and potentially significant one. FRANKFURT SCHOOL, NIETZSCHE. R.Sc.
philosophical behaviorism.BEHAVIORISM. philosophical psychology.PHILOSOPHY OF
MIND. philosophical theology.METAPHYSICS. philosophy, critical.BROAD, KANT.
philosophy, Laphilosophy, speculative.SPECULATIVE PHILOSOPHY. philosophy of
action.ACTION THEORY. philosophy of art.AESTHETICS. philosophy of biology, the
philosophy of science applied to biology. On a conservative view of the
philosophy of science, the same principles apply throughout science. Biology
supplies additional examples but does not provide any special problems or
require new principles. For example, the reduction of Mendelian genetics to
molecular biology exemplifies the same sort of relation as the reduction of
thermodynamics to statistical mechanics, and the same general analysis of
reduction applies equally to both. More radical philosophers argue that the
subject matter of biology has certain unique features; hence, the philosophy of
biology is itself unique. The three features of biology most often cited by
those who maintain that philosophy of biology is unique are functional
organization, embryological development, and the nature of selection. Organisms
are functionally organized. They are capable of maintaining their overall
organization in the face of fairly extensive variation in their envisonments.
Organisms also undergo ontogenetic development resulting from extremely complex
interactions between the genetic makeup of the organism and its successive
environments. At each step, the course that an organism takes is determined by
an interplay between its genetic makeup, its current state of development, and
the environment it happens to confront. The complexity of these interactions
produces the nature–nurture problem. Except for human artifacts, similar
organization does not occur in the non-living world. The species problem is
another classic issue in the philosophy of biology. Biological species have
been a paradigm example of natural kinds since Aristotle. According to nearly
all pre-Darwinian philosophers, species are part of the basic makeup of the
universe, like gravity and gold. They were held to be as eternal, immutable,
and discrete as these other examples of natural kinds. If Darwin was right,
species are not eternal. They come and go, and once gone can no more reemerge
than Aristotle can once again walk the streets of Athens. Nor are species
immutable. A sample of lead can be transmuted into a sample of gold, but these
elements as elements remain immutable in the face of such changes. However,
Darwin insisted that species themselves, not merely their instances, evolved.
Finally, because Darwin thought that species evolved gradually, the boundaries
between species are not sharp, casting doubt on the essentialist doctrines so
common in his day. In short, if species evolve, they have none of the
traditional characteristics of species. Philosophers and biologists to this day
are working out the consequences of this radical change in our worldview. The
topic that has received the greatest attention by philosophers of biology in
the recent literature is the nature of evolutionary theory, in particular
selection, adaptation, fitness, and the population structure of species. In
order for selection to operate, variation is necessary, successive generations
must be organized genealogically, and individuals must interact differentially
with their environments. In the simplest case, genes pass on their structure
largely intact. In addition, they provide the information necessary to produce
organisms. Certain of these organisms are better able to cope with their
environments and reproduce than are other organisms. As a result, genes are
perpetuated differentially through successive generations. Those
characteristics that help an organism cope with its environments are termed
adaptations. In a more restricted sense, only those characteristics that arose
through past selective advantage count as adaptations. Just as the notion of IQ
was devised as a single measure for a combination of the factors that influence
our mental abilities, fitness is a measure of relative reproductive success.
Claims about the tautological character of the principle philosophical
behaviorism philosophy of biology of the survival of the fittest stem from the
blunt assertion that fitness just is relative reproductive success, as if
intelligence just is what IQ tests measure. Philosophers of biology have
collaborated with biologists to analyze the notion of fitness. This literature
has concentrated on the role that causation plays in selection and, hence, must
play in any adequate explication of fitness. One important distinction that has
emerged is between replication and differential interaction with the
environment. Selection is a function of the interplay between these two
processes. Because of the essential role of variation in selection, all the
organisms that belong to the same species either at any one time or through
time cannot possibly be essentially the same. Nor can species be treated
adequately in terms of the statistical covariance of either characters or
genes. The populational structure of species is crucial. For example, species
that form numerous, partially isolated demes are much more likely to speciate
than those that do not. One especially controversial question is whether
species themselves can function in the evolutionary process rather than simply
resulting from it. Although philosophers of biology have played an increasingly
important role in biology itself, they have also addressed more traditional
philosophical questions, especially in connection with evolutionary
epistemology and ethics. Advocates of evolutionary epistemology argue that
knowledge can be understood in terms of the adaptive character of accurate
knowledge. Those organisms that hold false beliefs about their environment,
including other organisms, are less likely to reproduce themselves than those
with more accurate beliefs. To the extent that this argument has any force at
all, it applies only to humansized entities and events. One common response to
evolutionary epistemology is that sometimes people who hold manifestly false
beliefs flourish at the expense of those who hold more realistic views of the
world in which we live. On another version of evolutionary epistemology,
knowledge acquisition is viewed as just one more instance of a selection
process. The issue is not to justify our beliefs but to understand how they are
generated and proliferated. Advocates of evolutionary ethics attempt to justify
certain ethical principles in terms of their survival value. Any behavior that
increases the likelihood of survival and reproduction is “good,” and anything
that detracts from these ends is “bad.” The main objection to evolutionary
ethics is that it violates the is–ought distinction. According to most ethical
systems, we are asked to sacrifice ourselves for the good of others. If these
others were limited to our biological relatives, then the biological notion of
inclusive fitness might be adequate to account for such altruistic behavior,
but the scope of ethical systems extends past one’s biological relatives.
Advocates of evolutionary ethics are hard pressed to explain the full range of
behavior that is traditionally considered as virtuous. Either biological
evolution cannot provide an adequate justification for ethical behavior or else
ethical systems must be drastically reduced in their scope. DARWINISM, ESSENTIALISM, MECHANISTIC
EXPLANATIONS, MENDEL, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. D.L.H. philosophy of economics,
the study of methodological issues facing positive economic theory and
normative problems on the intersection of welfare economics and political
philosophy. Methodological issues. Applying approaches and questions in the
philosophy of science specifically to economics, the philosophy of economics
explores epistemological and conceptual problems raised by the explanatory aims
and strategy of economic theory: Do its assumptions about individual choice
constitute laws, and do they explain its derived generalizations about markets
and economies? Are these generalizations laws, and if so, how are they tested
by observation of economic processes, and how are theories in the various
compartments of economics – microeconomics, macroeconomics – related to one
another and to econometrics? How are the various schools – neoclassical,
institutional, Marxian, etc. – related to one another, and what sorts of tests
might enable us to choose between their theories? Historically, the chief issue
of interest in the development of the philosophy of economics has been the
empirical adequacy of the assumptions of rational “economic man”: that all agents
have complete and transitive cardinal or ordinal utility rankings or preference
orders and that they always choose that available option which maximizes their
utility or preferences. Since the actual behavior of agents appears to
disconfirm these assumptions, the claim that they constitute causal laws
governing economic behavior is difficult to sustain. On the other hand, the
assumption of preference-maximizing behavior is indispensable to
twentieth-century economics. These two considerations jointly undermine the
claim that economic theory honors criteria on explanatory power and evidential
probity drawn philosophy of economics philosophy of economics 669 669 from physical science. Much work by
economists and philosophers has been devoted therefore to disputing the claim
that the assumptions of rational choice theory are false or to disputing the
inference from this claim to the conclusion that the cognitive status of
economic theory as empirical science is thereby undermined. Most frequently it
has been held that the assumptions of rational choice are as harmless and as
indispensable as idealizations are elsewhere in science. This view must deal
with the allegation that unlike theories embodying idealization elsewhere in
science, economic theory gains little more in predictive power from these
assumptions about agents’ calculations than it would secure without any
assumptions about individual choice. Normative issues. Both economists and
political philosophers are concerned with identifying principles that will
ensure just, fair, or equitable distributions of scarce goods. For this reason
neoclassical economic theory shares a history with utilitarianism in moral
philosophy. Contemporary welfare economics continues to explore the limits of
utilitarian prescriptions that optimal economic and political arrangements
should maximize and/or equalize utility, welfare, or some surrogate. It also
examines the adequacy of alternatives to such utilitarian principles. Thus,
economics shares an agenda of interests with political and moral philosophy.
Utilitarianism in economics and philosophy has been constrained by an early
realization that utilities are neither cardinally measurable nor
interpersonally comparable. Therefore the prescription to maximize and/or
equalize utility cannot be determinatively obeyed. Welfare theorists have
nevertheless attempted to establish principles that will enable us to determine
the equity, fairness, or justice of various economic arrangements, and that do
not rely on interpersonal comparisons required to measure whether a
distribution is maximal or equal in the utility it accords all agents. Inspired
by philosophers who have surrendered utilitarianism for other principles of
equality, fairness, or justice in distribution, welfare economists have
explored Kantian, social contractarian, and communitarian alternatives in a
research program that cuts clearly across both disciplines. Political
philosophy has also profited as much from innovations in economic theory as
welfare economics has benefited from moral philosophy. Theorems from welfare
economics that establish the efficiency of markets in securing distributions
that meet minimal conditions of optimality and fairness have led moral
philosophers to reexamine the moral status of free-market exchange. Moreover,
philosophers have come to appreciate that coercive social institutions are
sometimes best understood as devices for securing public goods – goods like
police protection that cannot be provided to those who pay for them without
also providing them to free riders who decline to do so. The recognition that
everyone would be worse off, including free riders, were the coercion required
to pay for these goods not imposed, is due to welfare economics and has led to
a significant revival of interest in the work of Hobbes, who appears to have
prefigured such arguments. DECISION
THEORY, PHILOSOPHY OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES, POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY,
SOCIAL CHOICE THEORY,
UTILITARIANISM. A.R. philosophy of education, a branch of philosophy concerned
with virtually every aspect of the educational enterprise. It significantly
overlaps other, more mainstream branches (especially epistemology and ethics,
but even logic and metaphysics). The field might almost be construed as a
“series of footnotes” to Plato’s Meno, wherein are raised such fundamental
issues as whether virtue can be taught; what virtue is; what knowledge is; what
the relation between knowledge of virtue and being virtuous is; what the
relation between knowledge and teaching is; and how and whether teaching is
possible. While few people would subscribe to Plato’s doctrine (or convenient
fiction, perhaps) in Meno that learning by being taught is a process of
recollection, the paradox of inquiry that prompts this doctrine is at once the
root text of the perennial debate between rationalism and empiricism and a
profoundly unsettling indication that teaching passeth understanding.
Mainstream philosophical topics considered within an educational context tend
to take on a decidedly genetic cast. So, e.g., epistemology, which analytic
philosophy has tended to view as a justificatory enterprise, becomes concerned
if not with the historical origins of knowledge claims then with their genesis
within the mental economy of persons generally – in consequence of their
educations. And even when philosophers of education come to endorse something
akin to Plato’s classic account of knowledge as justified true belief, they are
inclined to suggest, then, that the conveyance of knowledge via instruction
must somehow provide the student with the justification along with the true
philosophy of education philosophy of education 670 670 belief – thereby reintroducing a
genetic dimension to a topic long lacking one. Perhaps, indeed, analytic
philosophy’s general (though not universal) neglect of philosophy of education
is traceable in some measure to the latter’s almost inevitably genetic
perspective, which the former tended to decry as armchair science and as a
threat to the autonomy and integrity of proper philosophical inquiry. If this
has been a basis for neglect, then philosophy’s more recent, postanalytic turn
toward naturalized inquiries that reject any dichotomy between empirical and
philosophical investigations may make philosophy of education a more inviting
area. Alfred North Whitehead, himself a leading light in the philosophy of
education, once remarked that we are living in the period of educational
thought subject to the influence of Dewey, and there is still no denying the
observation. Dewey’s instrumentalism, his special brand of pragmatism, informs
his extraordinarily comprehensive progressive philosophy of education; and he
once went so far as to define all of philosophy as the general theory of
education. He identifies the educative process with the growth of experience,
with growing as developing – where experience is to be understood more in
active terms, as involving doing things that change one’s objective environment
and internal conditions, than in the passive terms, say, of Locke’s
“impression” model of experience. Even traditionalistic philosophers of
education, most notably Maritain, have acknowledged the wisdom of Deweyan
educational means, and have, in the face of Dewey’s commanding philosophical
presence, reframed the debate with progressivists as one about appropriate
educational ends – thereby insufficiently acknowledging Dewey’s trenchant
critique of the means–end distinction. And even some recent analytic
philosophers of education, such as R. S. Peters, can be read as if translating
Deweyan insights (e.g., about the aim of education) into an analytic idiom.
Analytic philosophy of education, as charted by Peters, Israel Scheffler, and
others in the Anglo-American philosophical tradition, has used the tools of
linguistic analysis on a wide variety of educational concepts (learning,
teaching, training, conditioning, indoctrinating, etc.) and investigated their
interconnections: Does teaching entail learning? Does teaching inevitably
involve indoctrinating? etc. This careful, subtle, and philosophically
sophisticated work has made possible a much-needed conceptual precision in
educational debates, though the debaters who most influence public opinion and
policy have rarely availed themselves of that precisification. Recent work in
philosophy of education, however, has taken up some major educational
objectives – moral and other values, critical and creative thinking – in a way
that promises to have an impact on the actual conduct of education. Philosophy
of education, long isolated (in schools of education) from the rest of the
academic philosophical community, has also been somewhat estranged from the
professional educational mainstream. Dewey would surely have approved of a
change in this status quo.
DEWEY, EPISTEMOLOGY,
PIAGET, PLATO, PRAGMATISM, VIRTUE ETHICS. D.M.S. philosophy of history, the
philosophical study of human history and of attempts to record and interpret
it. ‘History’ in English (and its equivalent in most modern European languages)
has two primary senses: (1) the temporal progression of large-scale human
events and actions, primarily but not exclusively in the past; and (2) the
discipline or inquiry in which knowledge of the human past is acquired or
sought. This has led to two senses of ‘philosophy of history’, depending on
which “history” has been the object of philosophers’ attentions. Philosophy of
history in the first sense is often called substantive (or speculative), and
placed under metaphysics. Philosophy of history in the second sense is called
critical (or analytic) and can be placed in epistemology. Substantive
philosophy of history. In the West, substantive philosophy of history is
thought to begin only in the Christian era. In the City of God, Augustine
wonders why Rome flourished while pagan, yet fell into disgrace after its
conversion to Christiantity. Divine reward and punishment should apply to whole
peoples, not just to individuals. The unfolding of events in history should
exhibit a plan that is intelligible rationally, morally, and (for Augustine)
theologically. As a believer Augustine is convinced that there is such a plan,
though it may not always be evident. In the modern period, philosophers such as
Vico and Herder also sought such intelligibility in history. They also believed
in a long-term direction or purpose of history that is often opposed to and
makes use of the purposes of individuals. The most elaborate and best-known
example of this approach is found in Hegel, who thought that the gradual
realization of human freedom could be discerned in history even if much
slavery, tyranny, and suffering are necessary in the philosophy of history
philosophy of history 671 671 process.
Marx, too, claimed to know the laws – in his case economic – according to which
history unfolds. Similar searches for overall “meaning” in human history have
been undertaken in the twentieth century, notably by Arnold Toynbee
(1889–1975), author of the twelve-volume Study of History, and Oswald Spengler
(1880–1936), author of Decline of the West. But the whole enterprise was
denounced by the positivists and neo-Kantians of the late nineteenth century as
irresponsible metaphysical speculation. This attitude was shared by
twentieth-century neopositivists and some of their heirs in the analytic
tradition. There is some irony in this, since positivism, explicitly in
thinkers like Comte and implicitly in others, involves belief in progressively
enlightened stages of human history crowned by the modern age of science.
Critical philosophy of history. The critical philosophy of history, i.e., the
epistemology of historical knowledge, can be traced to the late nineteenth
century and has been dominated by the paradigm of the natural sciences. Those
in the positivist, neopositivist, and postpositivist tradition, in keeping with
the idea of the unity of science, believe that to know the historical past is
to explain events causally, and all causal explanation is ultimately of the
same sort. To explain human events is to derive them from laws, which may be
social, psychological, and perhaps ultimately biological and physical. Against
this reductionism, the neo-Kantians and Dilthey argued that history, like other
humanistic disciplines (Geisteswissenschaften), follows irreducible rules of
its own. It is concerned with particular events or developments for their own
sake, not as instances of general laws, and its aim is to understand, rather
than explain, human actions. This debate was resurrected in the twentieth
century in the English-speaking world. Philosophers like Hempel and Morton
White (b.1917) elaborated on the notion of causal explanation in history, while
Collingwood and William Dray (b.1921) described the “understanding” of
historical agents as grasping the thought behind an action or discovering its
reasons rather than its causes. The comparison with natural science, and the
debate between reductionists and antireductionists, dominated other questions
as well: Can or should history be objective and valuefree, as science
purportedly is? What is the significance of the fact that historians can never
perceive the events that interest them, since they are in the past? Are they
not limited by their point of view, their place in history, in a way scientists
are not? Some positivists were inclined to exclude history from science, rather
than make it into one, relegating it to “literature” because it could never
meet the standards of objectivity and genuine explanation; it was often the
anti-positivists who defended the cognitive legitimacy of our knowledge of the
past. In the non-reductionist tradition, philosophers have increasingly
stressed the narrative character of history: to understand human actions
generally, and past actions in particular, is to tell a coherent story about
them. History, according to W. B. Gallie (b.1912), is a species of the genus
Story. History does not thereby become fiction: narrative remains a “cognitive
instrument” (Louis Mink, 1921–83) just as appropriate to its domain as theory
construction is to science. Nevertheless, concepts previously associated with
fictional narratives, such as plot structure and beginning-middle-end, are seen
as applying to historical narratives as well. This tradition is carried further
by Hayden White (b.1928), who analyzes classical nineteenth-century histories
(and even substantive philosophies of history such as Hegel’s) as instances of
romance, comedy, tragedy, and satire. In White’s work this mode of analysis
leads him to some skepticism about history’s capacity to “represent” the
reality of the past: narratives seem to be imposed upon the data, often for
ideological reasons, rather than drawn from them. To some extent White’s view
joins that of some positivists who believe that history’s literary character
excludes it from the realm of science. But for White this is hardly a defect.
Some philosophers have criticized the emphasis on narrative in discussions of
history, since it neglects search and discovery, deciphering and evaluating
sources, etc., which is more important to historians than the way they “write
up” their results. Furthermore, not all history is presented in narrative form.
The debate between pro- and anti-narrativists among philosophers of history has
its parallel in a similar debate among historians themselves. Academic history
in recent times has seen a strong turn away from traditional political history
toward social, cultural, and economic analyses of the human past. Narrative is
associated with the supposedly outmoded focus on the doings of kings, popes,
and generals. These are considered (e.g. by the French historian Fernand Braudel,
1902–85) merely surface ripples compared to the deeper-lying and slower-moving
currents of social and economic change. It is the methods and concepts of the
social sciences, not philosophy of history philosophy of history 672 672 the art of the storyteller, on which
the historian must draw. This debate has now lost some of its steam and
narrative history has made something of a comeback among historians. Among
philosophers Paul Ricoeur has tried to show that even ostensibly non-narrative
history retains narrative features. Historicity. Historicity (or historicality:
Geschichtlichkeit) is a term used in the phenomenological and hermeneutic
tradition (from Dilthey and Husserl through Heidegger and Gadamer) to indicate
an essential feature of human existence. Persons are not merely in history;
their past, including their social past, figures in their conception of
themselves and their future possibilities. Some awareness of the past is thus
constitutive of the self, prior to being formed into a cognitive discipine.
Modernism and the postmodern. It is possible to view some of the debates over
the modern and postmodern in recent Continental philosophy as a new kind of
philosophy of history. Philosophers like Lyotard and Foucault see the modern as
the period from the Enlightenment and Romanticism to the present, characterized
chiefly by belief in “grand narratives” of historical progress, whether
capitalist, Marxist, or positivist, with “man” as the triumphant hero of the
story. Such belief is now being (or should be) abandoned, bringing modernism to
an end. In one sense this is like earlier attacks on the substantive philosophy
of history, since it unmasks as unjustified moralizing certain beliefs about
large-scale patterns in history. It goes even further than the earlier attack,
since it finds these beliefs at work even where they are not explicitly
expressed. In another sense this is a continuation of the substantive
philosophy of history, since it makes its own grand claims about largescale
historical patterns. In this it joins hands with other philosophers of our day
in a general historicization of knowledge (e.g., the philosophy of science
merges with the history of science) and even of philosophy itself. Thus the
later Heidegger – and more recently Richard Rorty – view philosophy itself as a
large-scale episode in Western history that is nearing or has reached its end.
Philosophy thus merges with the history of philosophy, but only thanks to a
philosophical reflection on this history as part of history as a whole. EXPLANATION, HEGEL, HISTORICISM, PHILOSOPHY
OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES, VERSTEHEN. D.C.
philosophy of language,
the philosophical study of natural language and its workings, particularly of
linguistic meaning and the use of language. A natural language is any one of
the thousands of various tongues that have developed historically among populations
of human beings and have been used for everyday purposes – including English,
Italian, Swahili, and Latin – as opposed to the formal and other artificial
“languages” invented by mathematicians, logicians, and computer scientists,
such as arithmetic, the predicate calculus, and LISP or COBOL. There are
intermediate cases, e.g., Esperanto, Pig Latin, and the sort of “philosophese”
that mixes English words with logical symbols. Contemporary philosophy of
language centers on the theory of meaning, but also includes the theory of
reference, the theory of truth, philosophical pragmatics, and the philosophy of
linguistics. The main question addressed by the theory of meaning is: In virtue
of what are certain physical marks or noises meaningful linguistic expressions,
and in virtue of what does any particular set of marks or noises have the
distinctive meaning it does? A theory of meaning should also give a
comprehensive account of the “meaning phenomena,” or general semantic
properties of sentences: synonymy, ambiguity, entailment, and the like. Some
theorists have thought to express these questions and issues in terms of
languageneutral items called propositions: ‘In virtue of what does a particular
set of marks or noises express the proposition it does?’; cf. ‘ “La neige est
blanche” expresses the proposition that snow is white’, and ‘Synonymous
sentences express the same proposition’. On this view, to understand a sentence
is to “grasp” the proposition expressed by that sentence. But the explanatory
role and even the existence of such entities are disputed. It has often been
maintained that certain special sentences are true solely in virtue of their
meanings and/or the meanings of their component expressions, without regard to
what the nonlinguistic world is like (‘No bachelor is married’; ‘If a thing is
blue it is colored’). Such vacuously true sentences are called analytic.
However, Quine and others have disputed whether there really is such a thing as
analyticity. Philosophers have offered a number of sharply competing hypotheses
as to the nature of meaning, including: (1) the referential view that words
mean by standing for things, and that a sentence means what it does because its
parts correspond referentially to the elements of an actual or possible state
of affairs in the world; (2) ideational or mentalist theories, according to
philosophy of language philosophy of language 673 673 which meanings are ideas or other
psychological phenomena in people’s minds; (3) “use” theories, inspired by
Wittgenstein and to a lesser extent by J. L. Austin: a linguistic expression’s
“meaning” is its conventionally assigned role as a game-piece-like token used
in one or more existing social practices;
No comments:
Post a Comment