philosophy of language,
the philosophical study of natural language and its workings, particularly of
linguistic meaning and the use of language. A natural language is any one of
the thousands of various tongues that have developed historically among
populations of human beings and have been used for everyday purposes –
including English, Italian, Swahili, and Latin – as opposed to the formal and
other artificial “languages” invented by mathematicians, logicians, and
computer scientists, such as arithmetic, the predicate calculus, and LISP or
COBOL. There are intermediate cases, e.g., Esperanto, Pig Latin, and the sort
of “philosophese” that mixes English words with logical symbols. Contemporary
philosophy of language centers on the theory of meaning, but also includes the
theory of reference, the theory of truth, philosophical pragmatics, and the
philosophy of linguistics. The main question addressed by the theory of meaning
is: In virtue of what are certain physical marks or noises meaningful
linguistic expressions, and in virtue of what does any particular set of marks
or noises have the distinctive meaning it does? A theory of meaning should also
give a comprehensive account of the “meaning phenomena,” or general semantic
properties of sentences: synonymy, ambiguity, entailment, and the like. Some
theorists have thought to express these questions and issues in terms of
languageneutral items called propositions: ‘In virtue of what does a particular
set of marks or noises express the proposition it does?’; cf. ‘ “La neige est
blanche” expresses the proposition that snow is white’, and ‘Synonymous
sentences express the same proposition’. On this view, to understand a sentence
is to “grasp” the proposition expressed by that sentence. But the explanatory
role and even the existence of such entities are disputed. It has often been
maintained that certain special sentences are true solely in virtue of their
meanings and/or the meanings of their component expressions, without regard to
what the nonlinguistic world is like (‘No bachelor is married’; ‘If a thing is
blue it is colored’). Such vacuously true sentences are called analytic.
However, Quine and others have disputed whether there really is such a thing as
analyticity. Philosophers have offered a number of sharply competing hypotheses
as to the nature of meaning, including: (1) the referential view that words
mean by standing for things, and that a sentence means what it does because its
parts correspond referentially to the elements of an actual or possible state
of affairs in the world; (2) ideational or mentalist theories, according to
philosophy of language philosophy of language 673 673 which meanings are ideas or other
psychological phenomena in people’s minds; (3) “use” theories, inspired by Wittgenstein
and to a lesser extent by J. L. Austin: a linguistic expression’s “meaning” is
its conventionally assigned role as a game-piece-like token used in one or more
existing social practices; (4) Grice’s hypothesis that a sentence’s or word’s
meaning is a function of what audience response a typical utterer would intend
to elicit in uttering it.(5) inferential role theories, as developed by Wilfrid
Sellars out of Carnap’s and Wittgenstein’s views: a sentence’s meaning is
specified by the set of sentences from which it can correctly be inferred and
the set of those which can be inferred from it (Sellars himself provided for
“language-entry” and “language-exit” moves as partly constitutive of meaning,
in addition to inferences); (6) verificationism, the view that a sentence’s
meaning is the set of possible experiences that would confirm it or provide
evidence for its truth; (7) the truth-conditional theory: a sentence’s meaning
is the distinctive condition under which it is true, the situation or state of
affairs that, if it obtained, would make the sentence true; (8) the null
hypothesis, or eliminativist view, that “meaning” is a myth and there is no
such thing – a radical claim that can stem either from Quine’s doctrine of the
indeterminacy of translation or from eliminative materialism in the philosophy
of mind. Following the original work of Carnap, Alonzo Church, Hintikka, and
Richard Montague in the 1950s, the theory of meaning has made increasing use of
“possible worlds”–based intensional logic as an analytical apparatus.
Propositions (sentence meanings considered as entities), and truth conditions
as in (7) above, are now commonly taken to be structured sets of possible
worlds – e.g., the set of worlds in which Aristotle’s maternal grandmother
hates broccoli. And the structure imposed on such a set, corresponding to the
intuitive constituent structure of a proposition (as the concepts ‘grandmother’
and ‘hate’ are constituents of the foregoing proposition), accounts for the
meaning-properties of sentences that express the proposition. Theories of
meaning can also be called semantics, as in “Gricean semantics” or
“Verificationist semantics,” though the term is sometimes restricted to
referential and/or truth-conditional theories, which posit meaning-constitutive
relations between words and the nonlinguistic world. Semantics is often
contrasted with syntax, the structure of grammatically permissible ordering
relations between words and other words in well-formed sentences, and with
pragmatics, the rules governing the use of meaningful expressions in particular
speech contexts; but linguists have found that semantic phenomena cannot be
kept purely separate either from syntactic or from pragmatic phenomena. In a
still more specialized usage, linguistic semantics is the detailed study
(typically within the truth-conditional format) of particular types of
construction in particular natural languages, e.g., belief-clauses in English
or adverbial phrases in Kwakiutl. Linguistic semantics in that sense is
practiced by some philosophers of language, by some linguists, and occasionally
by both working together. Montague grammar and situation semantics are common
formats for such work, both based on intensional logic. The theory of
referenceis pursued whether or not one accepts either the referential or the
truthconditional theory of meaning. Its main question is: In virtue of what
does a linguistic expression designate one or more things in the world? (Prior
to theorizing and defining of technical uses, ‘designate’, ‘denote’, and
‘refer’ are used interchangeably.) Denoting expressions are divided into
singular terms, which purport to designate particular individual things, and
general terms, which can apply to more than one thing at once. Singular terms
include proper names (‘Cindy’, ‘Bangladesh’), definite descriptions (‘my
brother’, ‘the first baby born in the New World’), and singular pronouns of
various types (‘this’, ‘you’, ‘she’). General terms include common nouns
(‘horse’, ‘trash can’), mass terms (‘water’, ‘graphite’), and plural pronouns
(‘they’, ‘those’). The twentieth century’s dominant theory of reference has
been the description theory, the view that linguistic terms refer by expressing
descriptive features or properties, the referent being the item or items that
in fact possess those properties. For example, a definite description does that
directly: ‘My brother’ denotes whatever person does have the property of being
my brother. According to the description theory of proper names, defended most
articulately by Russell, such names express identifying properties indirectly
by abbreviating definite descriptions. A general term such as ‘horse’ was
thought of as expressing a cluster of properties distinctive of horses; and so
forth. But the description theory came under heavy attack in the late 1960s,
from Keith Donnellan, Kripke, and Putnam, and was generally abandoned on each
of several grounds, in favor of the causal-historical theory of reference. The
causal-historical idea is that a particular use of a linguistic expression
denotes by being etiologically grounded in the thing or philosophy of language
philosophy of language 674 674 group
that is its referent; a historical causal chain of a certain shape leads
backward in time from the act of referring to the referent(s). More recently,
problems with the causal-historical theory as originally formulated have led
researchers to backpedal somewhat and incorporate some features of the
description theory. Other views of reference have been advocated as well,
particularly analogues of some of the theories of meaning listed above –
chiefly (2)–(6) and (8). Modal and propositional-attitude contexts create
special problems in the theory of reference, for referring expressions seem to
alter their normal semantic behavior when they occur within such contexts. Much
ink has been spilled over the question of why and how the substitution of a
term for another term having exactly the same referent can change the
truth-value of a containing modal or propositional-attitude sentence.
Interestingly, the theory of truth historically predates articulate study of
meaning or of reference, for philosophers have always sought the nature of
truth. It has often been thought that a sentence is true in virtue of
expressing a true belief, truth being primarily a property of beliefs rather
than of linguistic entities; but the main theories of truth have also been
applied to sentences directly. The correspondence theory maintains that a
sentence is true in virtue of its elements’ mirroring a fact or actual state of
affairs. The coherence theory instead identifies truth as a relation of the
true sentence to other sentences, usually an epistemic relation. Pragmatic
theories have it that truth is a matter either of practical utility or of
idealized epistemic warrant. Deflationary views, such as the traditional
redundancy theory and D. Grover, J. Camp, and N. D. Belnap’s prosentential
theory, deny that truth comes to anything more important or substantive than
what is already codified in a recursive Tarskian truth-definition for a language.
Pragmatics studies the use of language in context, and the context-dependence
of various aspects of linguistic interpretation. First, one and the same
sentence can express different meanings or propositions from context to
context, owing to ambiguity or to indexicality or both. An ambiguous sentence
has more than one meaning, either because one of its component words has more
than one meaning (as ‘bank’ has) or because the sentence admits of more than
one possible syntactic analysis (‘Visiting doctors can be tedious’, ‘The mouse
tore up the street’). An indexical sentence can change in truth-value from
context to context owing to the presence of an element whose reference
fluctuates, such as a demonstrative pronoun (‘She told him off yesterday’,
‘It’s time for that meeting now’). One branch of pragmatics investigates how
context determines a single propositional meaning for a sentence on a
particular occasion of that sentence’s use. Speech act theory is a second
branch of pragmatics that presumes the propositional or “locutionary” meanings
of utterances and studies what J. L. Austin called the illocutionary forces of
those utterances, the distinctive types of linguistic act that are performed by
the speaker in making them. (E.g., in uttering ‘I will be there tonight’, a
speaker might be issuing a warning, uttering a threat, making a promise, or
merely offering a prediction, depending on conventional and other social
features of the situation. A crude test of illocutionary force is the “hereby”
criterion: one’s utterance has the force of, say, a warning, if it could fairly
have been paraphrased by the corresponding “explicitly performative” sentence
beginning ‘I hereby warn you that . . .’.).Speech act theory interacts to some
extent with semantics, especially in the case of explicit performatives, and it
has some fairly dramatic syntactic effects as well. A third branch of
pragmatics (not altogether separate from the second) is the theory of
conversation or theory of implicature, founded by Grice. Grice notes that
sentences, when uttered in particular contexts, often generate “implications”
that are not logical consequences of those sentences (‘Is Jones a good
philosopher?’ – ’He has very neat handwriting’). Such implications can usually
be identified as what the speaker meant in uttering her sentence; thus (for
that reason and others), what Grice calls utterer’s meaning can diverge sharply
from sentence-meaning or “timeless” meaning. To explain those non-logical
implications, Grice offered a now widely accepted theory of conversational
implicature. Conversational implicatures arise from the interaction of the
sentence uttered with mutually shared background assumptions and certain
principles of efficient and cooperative conversation. The philosophy of
linguistics studies the academic discipline of linguistics, particularly
theoretical linguistics considered as a science or purported science; it
examines methodology and fundamental assumptions, and also tries to incorporate
linguists’ findings into the rest of philosophy of language. Theoretical
linguistics concentrates on syntax, and took its contempophilosophy of language
philosophy of language 675 675 rary
form in the 1950s under Zellig Harris and Chomsky: it seeks to describe each
natural language in terms of a generative grammar for that language, i.e., a
set of recursive rules for combining words that will generate all and only the
“well-formed strings” or grammatical sentences of that language. The set must
be finite and the rules recursive because, while our informationprocessing
resources for recognizing grammatical strings as such are necessarily finite
(being subagencies of our brains), there is no limit in any natural language
either to the length of a single grammatical sentence or to the number of grammatical
sentences; a small device must have infinite generative and parsing capacity.
Many grammars work by generating simple “deep structures” (a kind of tree
diagram), and then producing multiple “surface structures” as variants of those
deep structures, by means of rules that rearrange their parts. The surface
structures are syntactic parsings of natural-language sentences, and the deep
structures from which they derive encode both basic grammatical relations
between the sentences’ major constituents and, on some theories, the sentences’
main semantic properties as well; thus, sentences that share a deep structure
will share some fundamental grammatical properties and all or most of their
semantics. As Paul Ziff and Davidson saw in the 1960s, the foregoing syntactic
problem and its solution had semantic analogues. From small resources, human
speakers understand – compute the meanings of – arbitrarily long and novel
sentences without limit, and almost instantaneously. This ability seems to
require semantic compositionality, the thesis that the meaning of a sentence is
a function of the meanings of its semantic primitives or smallest meaningful
parts, built up by way of syntactic compounding. Compositionality also seems to
be required by learnability, since a normal child can learn an infinitely
complex dialect in at most two years, but must learn semantic primitives one at
a time. A grammar for a natural language is commonly taken to be a piece of
psychology, part of an explanation of speakers’ verbal abilities and behavior.
As such, however, it is a considerable idealization: it is a theory of
speakers’ linguistic “competence” rather than of their actual verbal
performance. The latter distinction is required by the fact that speakers’
considered, reflective judgments of grammatical correctness do not line up very
well with the class of expressions that actually are uttered and understood
unreflectively by those same speakers. Some grammatical sentences are too hard
for speakers to parse quickly; some are too long to finish parsing at all;
speakers commonly utter what they know to be formally ungrammatical strings;
and real speech is usually fragmentary, interspersed with vocalizations, false
starts, and the like. Actual departures from formal grammaticality are ascribed
by linguists to “performance limitations,” i.e., psychological factors such as
memory failure, weak computational capacity, or heedlessness; thus, actual
verbal behavior is to be explained as resulting from the perturbation of
competence by performance limitations.
Wednesday, May 20, 2020
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment