Hilbert, David
(1862–1943), German mathematician and philosopher of mathematics. Born in
Königsberg, he also studied and served on the faculty there, accepting Weber’s
chair in mathematics at Göttingen in 1895. He made important contributions to
many different areas of mathematics and was renowned for his grasp of the
entire discipline. His more philosophical work was divided into two parts. The
focus of the first, which occupied approximately ten years beginning in the
early 1890s, was the foundations of geometry and culminated in his celebrated
Grundlagen der Geometrie (1899). This is a rich and complex work that pursues a
variety of different projects simultaneously. Prominent among these is one
whose aim is to determine the role played in geometrical reasoning by
principles of continuity. Hilbert’s interest in this project was rooted in
Kantian concerns, as is confirmed by the inscription, in the Grundlagen, of
Kant’s synopsis of his critical philosophy: “Thus all human knowledge begins
with intuition, goes from there to concepts and ends with ideas.” Kant believed
that the continuous could not be represented in intuition and must therefore be
regarded as an idea of pure reason – i.e., as a device playing a purely
regulative role in the development of our geometrical knowledge (i.e., our
knowledge of the spatial manifold of sensory experience). Hilbert was deeply
influenced by this view of Kant’s and his work in the foundations of geometry
can be seen, in large part, as an attempt to test it by determining whether (or
to what extent) pure geometry can be developed without appeal to principles
concerning the nature of the continuous. To a considerable extent, Hilbert’s
work confirmed Kant’s view – showing, in a manner more precise than any Kant
had managed, that appeals to the continuous can indeed be eliminated from much
of our geometrical reasoning. The same basic Kantian orientation also governed
the second phase of Hilbert’s foundational work, where the focus was changed
from geometry to arithmetic and analysis. This is the phase during which
Hilbert’s Program was developed. This project began to take shape in the 1917
essay “Axiomatisches Denken.” (The 1904 paper “Über die Grundlagen der Logik
und Arithmetik,” which turned away from geometry and toward arithmetic, does
not yet contain more than a glimmer of the ideas that would later become
central to Hilbert’s proof theory.) It higher order Hilbert, David 381
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 381 reached its philosophically most mature
form in the 1925 essay “Über das Unendliche,” the 1926 address “Die Grundlagen
der Mathematik,” and the somewhat more popular 1930 paper “Naturerkennen und
Logik.” (From a technical as opposed to a philosophical vantage, the classical
statement is probably the 1922 essay “Neubegründung der Mathematik. Erste
Mitteilung.”) The key elements of the program are (i) a distinction between
real and ideal propositions and methods of proof or derivation; (ii) the idea
that the so-called ideal methods, though, again, playing the role of Kantian
regulative devices (as Hilbert explicitly and emphatically declared in the 1925
paper), are nonetheless indispensable for a reasonably efficient development of
our mathematical knowledge; and (iii) the demand that the reliability of the ideal
methods be established by real (or finitary) means. As is well known, Hilbert’s
Program soon came under heavy attack from Gödel’s incompleteness theorems
(especially the second), which have commonly been regarded as showing that the
third element of Hilbert’s Program (i.e., the one calling for a finitary proof
of the reliability of the ideal systems of classical mathematics) cannot be
carried out. See also GÖDEL’S INCOMPLETENESS THEOREMS, HILBERT’s PROGRAM, PROOF
THEORY. M.D. Hilbert’s Program, a proposal in the foundations of mathematics,
named for its developer, the German mathematician-philosopher David Hilbert,
who first formulated it fully in the 1920s. Its aim was to justify classical
mathematics (in particular, classical analysis and set theory), though only as
a Kantian regulative device and not as descriptive science. The justification
thus presupposed a division of classical mathematics into two parts: the part
(termed real mathematics by Hilbert) to be regulated, and the part (termed
ideal mathematics by Hilbert) serving as regulator. Real mathematics was taken
to consist of the meaningful, true propositions of mathematics and their
justifying proofs. These proofs – commonly known as finitary proofs – were
taken to be of an especially elementary epistemic character, reducing,
ultimately, to quasi-perceptual intuitions concerning finite assemblages of
perceptually intuitable signs regarded from the point of view of their shapes
and sequential arrangement. Ideal mathematics, on the other hand, was taken to
consist of sentences that do not express genuine propositions and derivations
that do not constitute genuine proofs or justifications. The epistemic utility
of ideal sentences (typically referred to as ideal propositions, though, as
noted above, they do not express genuine propositions at all) and proofs was
taken to derive not from their meaning and/or evidentness, but rather from the
role they play in some formal algebraic or calculary scheme intended to
identify or locate the real truths. It is thus a metatheoretic function of the
formal or algebraic properties induced on those propositions and proofs by
their positions in a larger derivational scheme. Hilbert’s ideal mathematics
was thus intended to bear the same relation to his real mathematics as Kant’s
faculty of pure reason was intended to bear to his faculty of understanding. It
was to be a regulative device whose proper function is to guide and facilitate
the development of our system of real judgments. Indeed, in his 1925 essay
“Über das Unendliche,” Hilbert made just this point, noting that ideal elements
do not correspond to anything in reality but serve only as ideas “if, following
Kant’s terminology, one understands as an idea a concept of reason which
transcends all experience and by means of which the concrete is to be completed
into a totality.” The structure of Hilbert’s scheme, however, involves more
than just the division of classical mathematics into real and ideal
propositions and proofs. It uses, in addition, a subdivision of the real
propositions into the problematic and the unproblematic. Indeed, it is this
subdivision of the reals that is at bottom responsible for the introduction of
the ideals. Unproblematic real propositions, described by Hilbert as the basic
equalities and inequalities of arithmetic (e.g., ‘3 ( 2’, ‘2 ‹ 3’, ‘2 ! 3 % 3 !
2’) together with their sentential (and certain of their bounded
quantificational) compounds, are the evidentially most basic judgments of
mathematics. They are immediately intelligible and decidable by finitary
intuition. More importantly, they can be logically manipulated in all the ways
that classical logic allows without leading outside the class of real
propositions. The characteristic feature of the problematic reals, on the other
hand, is that they cannot be so manipulated. Hilbert gave two kinds of examples
of problematic real propositions. One consisted of universal generalizations
like ‘for any non-negative integer a, a ! 1 % 1 ! a’, which Hilbert termed
hypothetical judgments. Such propositions are problematic because their denials
do not bound the search for counterexamples. Hence, the instance of the
(classical) law of excluded middle that is obtained by disjoining it with its
denial Hilbert’s Program Hilbert’s Program 382 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM
Page 382 is not itself a real proposition. Consequently, it cannot be
manipulated in all the ways permitted by classical logic without going outside
the class of real propositions. Similarly for the other kind of problematic
real discussed by Hilbert, which was a bounded existential quantification.
Every such sentence has as one of its classical consequents an unbounded
existential quantification of the same matrix. Hence, since the latter is not a
real proposition, the former is not a real proposition that can be fully
manipulated by classical logical means without going outside the class of real
propositions. It is therefore “problematic.” The question why full classical
logical manipulability should be given such weight points up an important
element in Hilbert’s thinking: namely, that classical logic is regarded as the
preferred logic of human thinking – the logic of the optimally functioning
human epistemic engine, the logic according to which the human mind most
naturally and efficiently conducts its inferential affairs. It therefore has a
special psychological status and it is because of this that the right to its
continued use must be preserved. As just indicated, however, preservation of
this right requires addition of ideal propositions and proofs to their real
counterparts, since applying classical logic to the truths of real mathematics
leads to a system that contains ideal as well as real elements. Hilbert
believed that to justify such an addition, all that was necessary was to show
it to be consistent with real mathematics (i.e., to show that it proves no real
proposition that is itself refutable by real means). Moreover, Hilbert believed
that this must be done by finitary means. The proof of Gödel’s second
incompleteness theorem in 1931 brought considerable pressure to bear on this
part of Hilbert’s Program even though it may not have demonstrated its
unattainability. See also BROUWER, GÖDEL’S INCOMPLETENESS THEOREMS, HILBERT,
PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS. M.D. Hinayana Buddhism. See BUDDHISM. Hinduism, the
group of religious and philosophical traditions of India that accept the
doctrinal authority of the Vedas and Upanishads, comprising the schools
Mimamsa, Sankhya-Yoga, Nyaya-Vaishesika, and Vedanta (six in number, with the
connection within pairs of schools, indicated by hyphenation, based on
historical and conceptual linkages). Most of the standard issues in
Greco-European philosophy receive independent discussion in classical Indian
thought. Perhaps the closest Indian term to ‘philosophy’ is darsana (seeing);
the goal of philosophy is typically taken to be not simply understanding, but
enlightenment (moksha), which involves escape from the reincarnation cycle and
from karma. All of the orthodox schools formally accept the doctrines that the
individual Atman beginninglessly transmigrates from body to body unless it
attains enlightenment and that in each lifetime the Atman acts and hence
accumulates consequences of its actions that will accrue to it in future
lifetimes (karma), though some schools (notably Advaita Vedanta) hold
metaphysical views that radically alter any meaning that the doctrines of
transmigration and karma can have. The “seeing” typically involves embracing
the content of the sacred texts and being transformed by it. In the same
general cultural and intellectual context as Hinduism, Carvaka rejects any such
notion of philosophy, and Jainism, Buddhism, and some varieties of Hinduism
reject monotheism though all but Carvaka accept some sort of religious
perspective and center on some notion of enlightenment. Metaphysics,
epistemology, logic, and ethics are richly represented in Hinduism. As is
typical in Greco-European philosophy, apart from (e.g.) some of the medieval
Scholastics and contemporary symbolic logicians, study of deductive inference
and probability is not sharply distinguished from epistemology, though in
Hinduism it is typically marked off from psychological considerations. There
are debates about the success of natural theology, with versions (e.g.) of teleological
and contingency arguments and discussions of the problem of evil, the latter
typically being related to a consideration of justice and karma. Monotheistic
views typically regard the world as everlastingly dependent on Brahman rather
than as having been created after a period in which nothing dependent existed
or as a condition of there being time at all. Typically, the universe is seen
as oscillating between states in which atoms have come together into bodies
that provide embodiment for transmigrating souls and states in which atoms come
apart and souls remain inactive. Disputes occur concerning the nature of
persons and personal identity, pluralism versus monism, and a personal Deity
versus an Absolute. Advaita Vedanta apparently holds that it is logically
impossible for B to depend upon A and for B also to be an individual distinct
from A, Hinayana Buddhism Hinduism 383 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 383
whereas the other varieties of Vedanta hold (in different ways) that dependence
does not rule out distinct individuality. The former assumption is compatible
with (though it does not entail) monism and the latter allows for (but does not
require) monotheism. There are pluralistic (thus non-monistic) schools that are
not monotheistic. Schools differ about whether the variety of conscious and
self-conscious states belongs intrinsically to souls or only to soul-body
composites; those holding the former view think of persons or minds as
transmigrating from life to life, whereas those holding the latter view have a
thinner notion of the traveler. There are debates among schools of Hinduism,
Buddhism, and Jainism over whether a substantival or an event or state account
of persons and objects is more defensible. For some schools, immaterial souls and
material atoms exist both beginninglessly and independently. For others they
exist beginninglessly and dependently. For still others, no such things exist
at all. Epistemology, logic, and philosophy of language flourish. Questions
concerning evidence are discussed along the lines of what counts as a valid
source of knowledge (e.g., perception, inference, testimony). Indian
grammarians developed techniques of reducing complex expressions to simple ones
and developed a use–mention distinction. Mimamsa philosophers were concerned
with the logical analysis of prescriptions. Vaishesika thinkers were concerned
to classify the meanings of words, offering the categories of substance,
quality, action, universal, ultimate difference, inherence, and absence, and
found the result of both logical and ontological significance. Ethics is also
richly represented, typically within a perspective in which the highest good
(moksha, enlightenment) is viewed as escape from the beginningless cycle of
rebirth and the clutches of karma, with the content of the highest good being
very diversely conceived. Sometimes enlightenment is conceived as involving
retention of personal identity, sometimes as involving loss thereof; sometimes
a view is held that denies that there is anything to preserve. Thus moral
philosophy is typically done in the light of explicitly religious, or at least
metaphysical, doctrines. The Carvaka perspectives, at least as interpreted by
their opponents, either accept hedonism or eschew ethics entirely. For some metaphysical
and religious views, morality has to do only with those activities that one
must engage in or refuse to engage in to achieve an enlightenment that contains
no moral component and perhaps involves nothing along the lines of one’s
identity as a person; in such contexts, moral values serve religious values
that themselves contain no moral element. In other perspectives, the status of
persons is such that their continued existence as distinct persons is required
in order for enlightenment to occur and moral elements enter intrinsically into
the nature of the highest good. The classical Hindu philosopher typically in
effect accepts some such proposition as the following: The Hindu scriptures
contain the truth about the nature of what is ultimately real, about the nature
of the human self, and about how to obtain the highest good. Some critics –
including Indian unorthodox materialists – argue that there cannot be any
genuine philosophy in Hinduism. (Similar questions are raised concerning
Jewish, Christian, and Muslim medieval philosophers.) The acceptance of the
indicated proposition does not tell one what the truth about ultimate reality,
the self, or the highest good is; various quite different accounts of these
matters are presented within the Hindu scriptures. This creates a problem:
since the texts are authoritative their teachings must be true. Inconsistent
propositions cannot be true; showing that your opponent’s views are
self-contradictory is a refutation within philosophical Hinduism as much as in
Anglo-American analytic circles. Hence the teachings of the texts must be
consistent, and so not everything in them can be read literally. In sum, it is
not obvious what in the authoritative texts is to be read literally and what
non-literally, but since patently contradictory doctrines are offered if one
reads everything literally, something must be read non-literally (or as
provisional, the best that some people can understand until they become more
capable). Thus if one accepts the indicated proposition one must decide which
of the textual accounts is the right one – the one ex hypothesi intended by the
texts to be taken as their literal doctrine. Deciding this typically is not a
matter of simple exegesis. Thus one must decide what grounds are required in
order to establish that it is one rather than another of these views that is
intended literally. Often the de facto answer is that the intended view is the
true view, with the issue as to which view is true being decided in substantial
part by reference to reason and experience and by “how the argument goes.”
Further, the views presented in the authoritative text, once one has decided
what they literally are, will likely have various philosophical implications.
(For example, perhaps surprisingly, Ramanuja’s theory of perceptual error
relates intimately to his views Hinduism Hinduism 384 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999
7:39 AM Page 384 on the divine attributes.) Some of these implications may seem
false, and if this happens there is a modus tollens consideration that leads to
asking again what the text really means. But even if no such consideration
arises, the philosophical implications of a position are likely themselves to
need explication if they are to be clearly understood. In Hinduism philosophy
typically is done in a commentarial setting, though (as in European medieval
contexts) once the commentator is doing philosophy he often goes on to topics
very far indeed from the views discussed in the texts. Of course, the more
wide-ranging a commentary is, the less unnatural it is that a commentary on
that commentary be even more wide-ranging; thus a relatively independent
philosophical tradition arises. The result is a very considerable body of
philosophical literature and tradition in India that can be approached without
assuming anything about the indicated proposition, one way or another. See also
ATMAN, BRAHMAN, KARMA, UPANISHADS, VEDAS. K.E.Y. Hintikka, Jaakko (b.1929),
Finnish philosopher with contributions to logic, philosophy of mathematics,
epistemology, linguistics and philosophy of language, philosophy of science,
and history of philosophy. His work on distributive normal forms and model set
techniques yielded an improved inductive logic. Model sets differ from Carnap’s
state-descriptions in being partial and not complete descriptions of “possible
worlds.” The techniques simplified metatheoretical proofs and led to new
results in e.g. probability theory and the semantic theory of information.
Their main philosophical import nevertheless is in bridging the gap between
proof theory and model theory. Model sets that describe several possible
“alternative” worlds lead to the possible worlds semantics for modal and
intensional logics. Hintikka has used them as a foundation for the logic of
propositional attitudes (epistemic logic and the logic of perception), and in
studies on individuation, identification, and intentionality. Epistemic logic
also provides a basis for Hintikka’s logic of questions, in which
conclusiveness conditions for answers can be defined. This has resulted in an
interrogative model of inquiry in which knowledge-seeking is viewed as a
pursuit of conclusive answers to initial “big” questions by strategically
organized series of “small” questions (put to nature or to another source of
information). The applications include scientific discovery and explanation.
Hintikka’s independence-friendly logic gives the various applications a unified
basis. Hintikka’s background philosophy and approach to formal semantics and
its applications is broadly Kantian with emphasis on seeking-andfinding methods
and the constitutive activity of the inquirer. Apart from a series of studies
inspired by Kant, he has written extensively on Aristotle, Plato, Descartes,
Leibniz, Frege, and Wittgenstein. Hintikka’s academic career has been not only
in Finland, chiefly at the University of Helsinki, but (especially) in the
United States, where he has held professorships at Stanford, Florida State, and
(currently) Boston University. His students and co-workers in the Finnish school
of inductive logic and in other areas include Leila Haaparanta (b.1954), Risto
Hilpinen (b.1943), Simo Knuuttila (b.1946), Martin Kusch (b.1959), Ilkka
Niiniluoto (b.1946), Juhani Pietarinen (b.1938), Veikko Rantala (b.1933),
Gabriel Sandu (b.1954), Matti Sintonen (b.1951), and Raimo Tuomela (b.1940).
See also EROTETIC LOGIC, HINTIKKA SET, INDUCTIVE LOGIC, MODEL THEORY, POSSIBLE
WORLDS, PROOF THEORY. M.T.S. Hintikka set, also called model set, downward
saturated set, a set (of a certain sort) of well-formed formulas that are all
true under a single interpretation of their non-logical symbols (named after
Jaakko Hintikka). Such a set can be thought of as a (partial) description of a
logically possible state of affairs, or possible world, full enough to make
evident that the world described is indeed possible. Thus it is required of a
Hintikka set G that it contain no atomic formula and its negation, that A, B 1
G if A 8 B 1 G, that A 1 G or B 1 G if A 7 B 1 G, and so forth, for each
logical constant. See also POSSIBLE WORLDS, SET THEORY. G.F.S. Hippias of Elis.
See SOPHISTS. Hippocrates (fifth century B.C.), semilegendary Greek physician
from Cos. Some sixty treatises survive under his name, but it is doubtful
whether he was the author of any of them. The Hippocratic corpus contains
material from a wide variety of standpoints, ranging from an extreme empiricism
that rejected all grand theory (On Ancient Medicine) to highly speculative
theoretical physiology (On the Nature of Man, On Regimen). Many treatises were
concerned with the accurate observation and classification of diseases
(EpiHintikka, Jaakko Hippocrates 385 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 385
demics) rather than treatment. Some texts (On the Art) defended the claims of
medicine to scientific status against those who pointed to its inaccuracies and
conjectural status; others (Oath, On Decorum) sketch a code of professional
ethics. Almost all his treatises were notable for their materialism and
rejection of supernatural “explanations”; their emphasis on observation; and
their concern with the isolation of causal factors. A large number of texts are
devoted to gynecology. The Hippocratic corpus became the standard against which
later doctors measured themselves; and, via Galen’s rehabilitation and
extension of Hippocratic method, it became the basis for Western medicine for
two millennia. R.J.H. historical determinism. See MARXISM. historicality. See
PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. historical jurisprudence. See JURISPRUDENCE. historical
materialism. See ENGELS. historical theory of reference. See PHILOSOPHY OF
LANGUAGE. historicism, the doctrine that knowledge of human affairs has an
irreducibly historical character and that there can be no ahistorical
perspective for an understanding of human nature and society. What is needed
instead is a philosophical explication of historical knowledge that will yield
the rationale for all sound knowledge of human activities. So construed,
historicism is a philosophical doctrine originating in the methodological and
epistemological presuppositions of critical historiography. In the
mid-nineteenth century certain German thinkers (Dilthey most centrally),
reacting against positivist ideals of science and knowledge, rejected
scientistic models of knowledge, replacing them with historical ones. They
applied this not only to the discipline of history but to economics, law,
political theory, and large areas of philosophy. Initially concerned with
methodological issues in particular disciplines, historicism, as it developed,
sought to work out a common philosophical doctrine that would inform all these
disciplines. What is essential to achieve knowledge in the human sciences is to
employ the ways of understanding used in historical studies. There should in
the human sciences be no search for natural laws; knowledge there will be
interpretive and rooted in concrete historical occurrences. As such it will be
inescapably perspectival and contextual (contextualism). This raises the issue
of whether historicism is a form of historical relativism. Historicism appears
to be committed to the thesis that what for a given people is warrantedly
assertible is determined by the distinctive historical perspective in which
they view life and society. The stress on uniqueness and concrete specificity
and the rejection of any appeal to universal laws of human development
reinforce that. But the emphasis on cumulative development into larger contexts
of our historical knowledge puts in doubt an identification of historicism and
historical relativism. The above account of historicism is that of its main
proponents: Meinecke, Croce, Collingwood, Ortega y Gasset, and Mannheim. But in
the twentieth century, with Popper and Hayek, a very different conception of
historicism gained some currency. For them, to be a historicist is to believe
that there are “historical laws,” indeed even a “law of historical
development,” such that history has a pattern and even an end, that it is the
central task of social science to discover it, and that these laws should determine
the direction of political action and social policy. They attributed
(incorrectly) this doctrine to Marx but rightly denounced it as pseudo-science.
However, some later Marxists (Lukács, Korsch, and Gramsci) were historicists in
the original nonPopperian sense as was the critical theorist Adorno and
hermeneuticists such as Gadamer. See also COLLINGWOOD, CROCE, DILTHEY, ENGELS,
PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. K.N. historicity. See PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. history,
philosophy of. See PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY.
Hobbes, Thomas
(1588–1679), English philosopher whose writings, especially the English version
of Leviathan (1651), strongly influenced all of subsequent English moral and
political philosophy. He also wrote a trilogy comprising De Cive (1642; English
version, Philosophical Rudiments Concerning Government and Society, 1651), De
Corpore (On the Body, 1655), and De Homine (On Man, 1658). Together with
Leviathan (the revised Latin version of which was published in 1668), these are
his major philosophical works. However, an early draft of his thoughts, The
Elements of Law, Natural and Political(also known as Human Nature and De
Corpore Politico), was published without permission in 1650. Many of the
misinterpretations of Hobbes’s views on human nature come historical determinism
Hobbes, Thomas 386 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 386 from mistaking this
early work as representing his mature views. Hobbes was influential not only in
England, but also on the Continent. He is the author of the third set of
objections to Descartes’s Meditations. Spinoza’s Tractatus Theologico-politicus
was deeply influenced by Hobbes, not only in its political views but also in
the way it dealt with Scripture. Hobbes was not merely a philosopher; he was
mathematical tutor to Charles II and also a classical scholar. His first
published work was a translation of Thucydides (1628), and among his latest,
about a half-century later, were translations of Homer’s Iliad and Odyssey.
Hobbes’s philosophical views have a remarkably contemporary sound. In
metaphysics, he holds a strong materialist view, sometimes viewing mental
phenomena as epiphenomenal, but later moving toward a reductive or eliminative
view. In epistemology he held a sophisticated empiricism, which emphasized the
importance of language for knowledge. If not the originator of the contemporary
compatibilist view of the relationship between free will and determinism (see
The Questions Concerning Liberty, Necessity and Chance, 1656), he was one of
the primary influences. He also was one of the most important philosophers of
language, explicitly noting that language is used not only to describe the
world but to express attitudes and, performatively, to make promises and
contracts. One of Hobbes’s outstanding characteristics is his intellectual
honesty. Though he may have been timid (he himself claims that he was,
explaining that his mother gave birth to him because of fright over the coming
of the Spanish Armada), his writing shows no trace of it. During more than half
his long lifetime he engaged in many philosophical controversies, which
required considerably more courage in Hobbes’s day than at present. Both the
Roman Catholic church and Oxford University banned the reading of his books and
there was talk not only of burning his books but of burning Hobbes himself. An
adequate interpretation of Hobbes requires careful attention to his accounts of
human nature, reason, morality, and law. Although he was not completely
consistent, his moral and political philosophy is remarkably coherent. His
political theory is often thought to require an egoistic psychology, whereas it
actually requires only that most persons be concerned with their own
self-interest, especially their own preservation. It does not require that most
not be concerned with other persons as well. All that Hobbes denies is an
undifferentiated natural benevolence: “For if by nature one man should love
another (that is) as man, there could no reason be returned why every man
should not equally love every man, as being equally man.” His argument is that
limited benevolence is not an adequate foundation upon which to build a state.
Hobbes’s political theory does not require the denial of limited benevolence,
he indeed includes benevolence in his list of the passions in Leviathan: “Desire
of good to another, BENEVOLENCE, GOOD WILL, CHARITY. If to man generally, GOOD
NATURE.” Psychological egoism not only denies benevolent action, it also denies
action done from a moral sense, i.e., action done because one believes it is
the morally right thing to do. But Hobbes denies neither kind of action. But
when the words [’just’ and ‘unjust’] are applied to persons, to be just
signifies as much as to be delighted in just dealing, to study how to do
righteousness, or to endeavor in all things to do that which is just; and to be
unjust is to neglect righteous dealing, or to think it is to be measured not
according to my contract, but some present benefit. Hobbes’s pessimism about
the number of just people is primarily due to his awareness of the strength of
the passions and his conviction that most people have not been properly
educated and disciplined. Hobbes is one of the few philosophers to realize that
to talk of that part of human nature which involves the passions is to talk
about human populations. He says, “though the wicked were fewer than the
righteous, yet because we cannot distinguish them, there is a necessity of
suspecting, heeding, anticipating, subjugating, self-defending, ever incident
to the most honest and fairest conditioned.” Though we may be aware of small
communities in which mutual trust and respect make law enforcement unnecessary,
this is never the case when we are dealing with a large group of people.
Hobbes’s point is that if a large group of people are to live together, there
must be a common power set up to enforce the rules of the society. That there
is not now, nor has there ever been, any large group of people living together
without such a common power is sufficient to establish his point. Often
overlooked is Hobbes’s distinction between people considered as if they were
simply animals, not modified in any way by education or discipline, and
civilized people. Though obviously an abstraction, people as animals are fairly
well exemplified by children. “Unless you Hobbes, Thomas Hobbes, Thomas 387
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 387 give children all they ask for, they
are peevish, and cry, aye and strike their parents sometimes; and all this they
have from nature.” In the state of nature, people have no education or training,
so there is “continual fear, and danger of violent death, and the life of man,
[is] solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.” But real people have been
brought up in families; they are, at least to some degree, civilized persons,
and how they will behave depends on how they are brought up. Hobbes does not
say that society is a collection of misfits and that this is why we have all
the trouble that we do – a position congenial to the psychological egoist. But
he does acknowledge that “many also (perhaps most men) either through defect of
mind, or want of education, remain unfit during the whole course of their
lives; yet have they, infants as well as those of riper years, a human nature;
wherefore man is made fit for society not by nature, but by education.”
Education and training may change people so that they act out of genuine moral
motives. That is why it is one of the most important functions of the sovereign
to provide for the proper training and education of the citizens. In the
current debate between nature and nurture, on the question of behavior Hobbes
would come down strongly on the side of nurture. Hobbes’s concept of reason has
more in common with the classical philosophical tradition stemming from Plato
and Aristotle, where reason sets the ends of behavior, than with the modern
tradition stemming from Hume where the only function of reason is to discover
the best means to ends set by the passions. For Hobbes, reason is very complex;
it has a goal, lasting selfpreservation, and it seeks the way to this goal. It
also discovers the means to ends set by the passions, but it governs the
passions, or tries to, so that its own goal is not threatened. Since its goal
is the same in all people, it is the source of rules applying to all people.
All of this is surprisingly close to the generally accepted account of
rationality. We generally agree that those who follow their passions when they
threaten their life are acting irrationally. We also believe that everyone
always ought to act rationally, though we know that few always do so. Perhaps
it was just the closeness of Hobbes’s account of reason to the ordinary view of
the matter that has led to its being so completely overlooked. The failure to
recognize that the avoidance of violent death is the primary goal of reason has
distorted almost all accounts of Hobbes’s moral and political philosophy, yet
it is a point on which Hobbes is completely clear and consistent. He explicitly
says that reason “teaches every man to fly a contra-natural dissolution [mortem
violentam] as the greatest mischief that can arrive to nature.” He continually
points out that it is a dictate of right reason to seek peace when possible
because people cannot “expect any lasting preservation continuing thus in the
state of nature, that is, of war.” And he calls temperance and fortitude
precepts of reason because they tend to one’s preservation. It has not
generally been recognized that Hobbes regarded it as an end of reason to avoid
violent death because he often talks of the avoidance of death in a way that
makes it seem merely an object of a passion. But it is reason that dictates
that one take all those measures necessary for one’s preservation; peace if
possible, if not, defense. Reason’s dictates are categorical; it would be a travesty
of Hobbes’s view to regard the dictates of reason as hypothetical judgments
addressed to those whose desire for their own preservation happens to be
greater than any conflicting desire. He explicitly deplores the power of the
irrational appetites and expressly declares that it is a dictate of reason that
one not scorn others because “most men would rather lose their lives (that I
say not, their peace) than suffer slander.” He does not say if you would rather
die than suffer slander, it is rational to do so. Hobbes, following Aristotle,
regards morality as concerned with character traits or habits. Since morality
is objective, it is only those habits that are called good by reason that are
moral virtues. “Reason declaring peace to be good, it follows by the same
reason, that all the necessary means to peace be good also; and therefore that
modesty, equity, trust, humanity, mercy (which we have demonstrated to be
necessary to peace), are good manners or habits, that is, virtues.” Moral
virtues are those habits of acting that the reason of all people must praise.
It is interesting to note that it is only in De Homine that Hobbes explicitly
acknowledges that on this account, prudence, temperance, and courage are not
moral virtues. In De Cive he distinguishes temperance and fortitude from the
other virtues and does not call them moral, but he does not explicitly deny
that they are moral virtues. But in De Homine, he explicitly points out that
one should not “demand that the courage and prudence of the private man, if
useful only to himself, be praised or held as a virtue by states or by any
other men whatsoever to whom these same are not useful.” That morality is
determined by reason and that reason has as its goal self-preservation seems to
Hobbes, Thomas Hobbes, Thomas 388 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 388 lead
to the conclusion that morality also has as its goal self-preservation. But it
is not the selfpreservation of an individual person that is the goal of
morality, but of people as citizens of a state. That is, moral virtues are
those habits of persons that make it rational for all other people to praise
them. These habits are not those that merely lead to an individual’s own
preservation, but to the preservation of all; i.e., to peace and a stable society.
Thus, “Good dispositions are those that are suitable for entering into civil
society; and good manners (that is, moral virtues) are those whereby what was
entered upon can be best preserved.” And in De Cive, when talking of morality,
he says, “The goodness of actions consist[s] in this, that it [is] in order to
peace, and the evil in this, that it [is] related to discord.” The nature of
morality is a complex and vexing question. If, like Hobbes, we regard morality
as applying primarily to those manners or habits that lead to peace, then his
view seems satisfactory. It yields, as he notes, all of the moral virtues that
are ordinarily considered such, and further, it allows one to distinguish
courage, prudence, and temperance from the moral virtues. Perhaps most
important, it provides, in almost self-evident fashion, the justification of
morality. For what is it to justify morality but to show that reason favors it?
Reason, seeking self-preservation, must favor morality, which seeks peace and a
stable society. For reason knows that peace and a stable society are essential
for lasting preservation. This simple and elegant justification of morality
does not reduce morality to prudence; rather it is an attempt, in a great
philosophical tradition stemming from Plato, to reconcile reason or rational
self-interest and morality. In the state of nature every person is and ought to
be governed only by their own reason. Reason dictates that they seek peace,
which yields the laws of nature, but it also allows them to use any means they
believe will best preserve themselves, which is what Hobbes calls The Right of
Nature. Hobbes’s insight is to see that, except when one is in clear and
present danger, in which case one has an inalienable right to defend oneself,
the best way to guarantee one’s longterm preservation is to give up one’s right
to act on one’s own decisions about what is the best way to guarantee one’s
long-term preservation and agree to act on the decisions of that single person
or group who is the sovereign. If all individuals and groups are allowed to act
on the decisions they regard as best, not accepting the commands of the
sovereign, i.e., the laws, as the overriding guide for their actions, the
result is anarchy and civil war. Except in rare and unusual cases, uniformity
of action following the decision of the sovereign is more likely to lead to
long-term preservation than diverse actions following diverse decisions. And
this is true even if each one of the diverse decisions, if accepted by the
sovereign as its decision, would have been more likely to lead to long-term
preservation than the actual decision that the sovereign made. This argument
explains why Hobbes holds that sovereigns cannot commit injustice. Only
injustice can properly be punished. Hobbes does not deny that sovereigns can be
immoral, but he does deny that the immorality of sovereigns can properly be
punished. This is important, for otherwise any immoral act by the sovereign
would serve as a pretext for punishing the sovereign, i.e., for civil war. What
is just and unjust is determined by the laws of the state, what is moral and
immoral is not. Morality is a wider concept than that of justice and is
determined by what leads to peace and stability. However, to let justice be
determined by what the reason of the people takes to lead to peace and
stability, rather than by what the reason of the sovereign decides, would be to
invite discord and civil war, which is contrary to the goal of morality: a
stable society and peace. One can create an air of paradox by saying that for
Hobbes it is immoral to attempt to punish some immoral acts, namely, those of
the sovereign. Hobbes is willing to accept this seeming paradox for he never
loses sight of the goal of morality, which is peace. To summarize Hobbes’s
system: people, insofar as they are rational, want to live out their natural
lives in peace and security. To do this, they must come together into cities or
states of sufficient size to deter attack by any group. But when people come
together in such a large group there will always be some that cannot be
trusted, and thus it is necessary to set up a government with the power to make
and enforce laws. This government, which gets both its right to govern and its
power to do so from the consent of the governed, has as its primary duty the
people’s safety. As long as the government provides this safety the citizens
are obliged to obey the laws of the state in all things. Thus, the rationality
of seeking lasting preservation requires seeking peace; this in turn requires
setting up a state with sufficient power to keep the peace. Anything that
threatens the stability of the state is to be avoided. As a practical matter,
Hobbes took God and religion very seriously, for he thought they provided some
of the strongest motives for action. Half of Leviathan is devoted to trying to
show that Hobbes, Thomas Hobbes, Thomas 389 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page
389 his moral and political views are supported by Scripture, and to discredit
those religious views that may lead to civil strife. But accepting the
sincerity of Hobbes’s religious views does not require holding that Hobbes
regarded God as the foundation of morality. He explicitly denies that atheists
and deists are subject to the commands of God, but he never denies that they
are subject to the laws of nature or of the civil state. Once one recognizes
that, for Hobbes, reason itself provides a guide to conduct to be followed by
all people, there is absolutely no need to bring in God. For in his moral and political
theory there is nothing that God can do that is not already done by reason. See
also CONTRACTARIANISM, NATURAL LAW, POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. B.Ge. Hohenheim,
Theophrastus Bombastus von. See PARACELSUS. Hohfeld, Wesley Newcomb
(1879–1918), American jurist who taught at Stanford and Yale. His main
contribution to legal and moral theory was his identification of eight
fundamental legal conceptions: One person X has a legal duty to a second person
Y to do some act A when the law requires X to do A for Y. X has a legal
privilege (or liberty) in face of Y to do A when X has no legal duty to Y not
to do A. X has a legal right (or claim) against Y that Y do A when Y has a
legal duty to X to do A. X has a legal no-right against Y that Y not do A when
Y has a legal liberty in face of X to do A. X has a legal power over Y to
effect some legal consequence C for Y when there is some voluntary action of X
that will bring about C for Y. X has a legal disability in face of Y to effect
C when there is no action X can perform that will bring about C for Y. X has a
legal liability in face of Y to effect C when Y has a legal power to effect C
for X. X has a legal immunity against Y from C when Y has no legal power over X
to effect C. Moral philosophers have adapted Hohfeld’s terminology to express
analogous moral conceptions. In jurisprudence or ethics, these fundamental
conceptions provide something like atoms into which all more complex legal or
moral relationships can be analyzed. In logic, these conceptions reveal pairs of
correlatives, such as a claim of X against Y and a duty of Y to X, each of
which implies the other, and pairs of opposites, such as a duty of X to Y and a
liberty of Y in face of X, which are contradictories. In the theory of rights,
his distinctions between liberties, claims, powers, and immunities are often
used to reveal ambiguities in the language of rights or to classify species of
rights. See also DUTY, ETHICS, RIGHTS. C.We. Holbach, Paul-Henri-Dietrich d’.
See D’HOLBACH. Hölderlin, Johann Christian Friedrich (1770– 1843), German poet,
novelist, and dramatist. He studied at Tübingen, where he befriended Schelling
and Hegel, and at Jena, where he met Schiller and Fichte. Since Hölderlin never
held an academic position or published any of his philosophical writings, his
influence on philosophy was primarily through his personality, conversations,
and letters. He is widely viewed as the author of the so-called “Oldest
System-Program of German Idealism,” a fragment that culminates in an exaltation
of poetry and a call for a new “mythology of reason.” This theme is illustrated
in the novel Hyperion (1797/99), which criticizes the subjective heroism of
ethical idealism, emphasizes the sacred character of nature, and attempts to
conflate religion and art as “overseers of reason.” In his veneration of nature
and objections to Fichte’s treatment of the “Not-I,” Hölderlin echoed
Schelling’s Naturphilosophie. In his Hellenism and his critique of the
“philosophy of reflection” (see Ueber Sein und Urteil [“On Being and
Judgment”]) he anticipated and influenced Hegel. In Hölderlin’s exaltation of
art as alone capable of revealing the nature of reality, he betrayed a debt to
Schiller and anticipated Romanticism. However, his view of the poet possesses a
tragic dimension quite foreign to Schelling and the younger Romantics. The
artist, as the interpreter of divine nature, mediates between the gods and men,
but for this very reason is estranged from his fellows. This aspect of
Hölderlin’s thought influenced Heidegger. D.Br. holism, any of a wide variety
of theses that in one way or another affirm the equal or greater reality or the
explanatory necessity of the whole of some system in relation to its parts. In
philosophy, the issues of holism (the word is more reasonably, but less often,
spelled ‘wholism’) have appeared Hohenheim, Theophrastus Bombastus von holism
390 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 390 traditionally in the philosophy of
biology, of psychology, and especially of the human sciences. In the context of
description, holism with respect to some system maintains that the whole has
some properties that its parts lack. This doctrine will ordinarily be trivially
true unless it is further held, in the thesis of descriptive emergentism, that
these properties of the whole cannot be defined by properties of the parts. The
view that all properties of the wholes in question can be so defined is
descriptive individualism. In the context of explanation, holism with respect
to some object or system maintains either (1) that the laws of the more complex
cases in it are not deducible by way of any composition laws or laws of
coexistence from the laws of the less complex cases (e.g., that the laws of the
behavior of people in groups are not deducible by composition laws or laws of
coexistence from the laws of solitary behavior), or (2) that all the variables
that constitute the system interact with each other. This denial of
deducibility is known also as metaphysical or methodological holism, whereas
affirming the deducibility is methodological individualism. In a special case
of explanatory holism that presupposes descriptive emergentism, holism is
sometimes understood as the thesis that with respect to some system the whole
has properties that interact “back” with the properties of its parts. In the
philosophy of biology, any of these forms of holism may be known as vitalism,
while in the philosophy of psychology they have been called Gestalt doctrine.
In the philosophy of the social sciences, where ‘holism’ has had its most common
use in philosophy, the many issues have often been reduced to that of
metaphysical holism versus methodological individualism. This terminology
reflected the positivists’ belief that holism was non-empirical in postulating
social “wholes” or the reality of society beyond individual persons and their
properties and relations (as in Durkheim and other, mostly Continental,
thinkers), while individualism was non-metaphysical (i.e., empirical) in
relying ultimately only on observable properties in describing and explaining
social phenomena. More recently, ‘holism’ has acquired additional uses in
philosophy, especially in epistemology and philosophy of language. Doxastic or
epistemic holism are theses about the “web of belief,” usually something to the
effect that a person’s beliefs are so connected that their change on any topic
may affect their content on any other topic or, perhaps, that the beliefs of a
rational person are so connected. Semantic or meaning holism have both been
used to denote either the thesis that the meanings of all terms (or sentences)
in a language are so connected that any change of meaning in one of them may
change any other meaning, or the thesis that changes of belief entail changes
of meaning. See also KÖHLER, METHODOLOGICAL HOLISM, PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY,
PHILOSOPHY OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES, SEMANTIC HOLISM. L.A. holism,
confirmational. See PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. holism, doxastic. See HOLISM.
holism, epistemic. See HOLISM. holism, methodological. See METHODOLOGICAL
HOLISM. holism, semantic. See SEMANTIC HOLISM. holistic system. See COMPUTER
THEORY. hologram, the image of an object in three dimensions created and
reproduced by the use of lasers. Holography is a method for recording and
reproducing such images. Holograms are remarkable in that, unlike normal
photographs, every part of them contains the complete image but in reduced
detail. Thus a small square cut from a hologram can still be laser-illuminated
to reveal the whole scene originally holographed, albeit with loss of
resolution. This feature made the hologram attractive to proponents of the
thesis of distribution of function in the brain, who argued that memories are
like holograms, not being located in a single precise engram – as claimed by
advocates of localization of function – but distributed across perhaps all of
the cortex. Although intriguing, the holographic model of memory storage failed
to gain acceptance. Current views favor D. O. Hebb’s “cell assembly” concept,
in which memories are stored in the connections between a group of neurons. See
also CONNECTIONISM, PERCEPTION. T.H.L. homoeomerity. See HOMOEOMEROUS.
homoeomerous (from Greek homoiomeres, ‘of like parts’), having parts, no matter
how small, that share the constitutive properties of the whole. The derivative
abstract noun is ‘homoeomery’. The Greek forms of the adjective and of its
corholism, confirmational homoeomerous 391 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page
391 responding privative ‘anhomoeomerous’ are used by Aristotle to distinguish
between (a) nonuniform parts of living things, e.g., limbs and organs, and (b)
biological stuffs, e.g., blood, bone, sap. In spite of being composed of the
four elements, each of the biological stuffs, when taken individually and
without admixtures, is through-and-through F, where F represents the cluster of
the constitutive properties of that stuff. Thus, if a certain physical volume
qualifies as blood, all its mathematically possible subvolumes, regardless of
size, also qualify as blood. Blood is thus homoeomerous. By contrast, a face or
a stomach or a leaf are anhomoeomerous: the parts of a face are not a face,
etc. In Aristotle’s system, the homoeomery of the biological stuffs is tied to
his doctrine of the infinite divisibility of matter. The distinction is
prefigured in Plato (Protagoras 329d). The term ‘homoeomerous’ is stricter in
its application than the ordinary terms ‘homogeneous’ and ‘uniform’. For we may
speak of a homogeneous entity even if the properties at issue are identically
present only in samples that fall above a certain size: the color of the sea
can be homogeneously or uniformly blue; but it is not homoeomerously blue. The
adjective homoiomeres, -es, and the noun homoiomereia also occur – probably
tendentiously, under the influence of Aristotle’s usage – in our ancient
sources for a pre-Aristotelian philosopher, Anaxagoras of Clazomenae, with
reference to the constituent “things” (chremata) involved in the latter’s
scheme of universal mixture. Moreover, the concept of homoeomery has played a
significant role outside ancient Greek philosophy, notably in twentieth-century
accounts of the contrast between mass terms and count terms or sortals. See
also ANAXAGORAS, ARISTOTLE, COUNT NOUN, SORTAL PREDICATE. A.P.D.M. homoeomery.
See HOMOEOMEROUS. homoiousian. See HOMOOUSIOS. homological. See SET-THEORETIC
PARADOXES. homomorphism, in model theory, a structurepreserving mapping from
one structure to another. A structure consists of a domain of objects together
with a function specifying interpretations, with respect to that domain, of the
relation symbols, function symbols, and individual symbols of a given language.
Relations, functions, and individuals in different structures for a language L
correspond to one another if they are interpretations of the same symbol of L.
To call a mapping “structure-preserving” is to say (1) that if objects in the
first structure bear a certain relation to one another, then their images in
the second structure (under the mapping) bear the corresponding relation to one
another, (2) that the value of a function for a given object (or ntuple of
objects) in the first structure has as its image under the mapping the value of
the corresponding function for the image of the object (or n-tuple of images)
in the second structure, and (3) that the image in the second structure of an
object in the first is the corresponding object. An isomorphism is a
homomorphism that is oneto-one and whose inverse is also a homomorphism. See
also MODEL THEORY. R.Ke. homonymy. See AMBIGUITY. homoousian. See HOMOOUSIOS. homoousios
(Greek, ‘of the same substance’), a concept central to the Christian doctrine
of the Trinity, enshrined in the Nicene Creed of A.D. 381. It attests that God
the Son (and by extension the Spirit) is of one and the same being or substance
(ousia) as the Father. Reflecting the insistence of Athanasius against Arianism
that Christ is God’s eternal, coequal Son and not a creature, the Nicene
homoousios is also to be differentiated from a rival formula, homoiousios
(Greek, ‘of similar substance’), which affirms merely the Son’s likeness in
being to God. Though notoriously and superficially an argument over one Greek
iota, the issue was philosophically profound and theologically crucial whether
or not Jesus of Nazareth incarnated God’s own being, revealed God’s own truth,
and mediated God’s own salvation. See also TRINITARIANISM. A.E.L. homuncular
functionalism. See FUNCTIONALISM. homunculus (from Latin, ‘little man’), a
miniature adult held to inhabit the brain (or some other organ) who perceives
all the inputs to the sense organs and initiates all the commands to the
muscles. Any theory that posits such an internal agent risks an infinite
regress (sometimes called the homunculus fallacy), since we can ask whether
there is a little man in the little man’s head, responsible for his perception
and action, and so on. Many familiar views of the mind and its activities seem
to require a homunculus. For instance, models of visual perception that posit
an inner picture as its product homoromery homunculus 392 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 392 apparently require a homunculus to look at the
picture, and models of action that treat intentions as commands to the muscles
apparently require a homunculus to issue the commands. It is never an easy
matter to determine whether a theory is committed to the existence of a
homunculus that vitiates the theory, and in some circumstances, homunculi can
be legitimately posited at intermediate levels of theory: “Homunculi are
bogeymen only if they duplicate entire the talents they are rung in to explain.
If one can get a team or committee of relatively ignorant, narrow-minded, blind
homunculi to produce the intelligent behavior of the whole, this is progress”
(Dennett, Brainstorms, 1978). Theories (in philosophy of mind or artificial
intelligence or cognitive science) that posit such teams of homunculi have been
called homuncular functionalism by William Lycan. D.C.D. Horkheimer, Max
(1895–1973), German philosopher, the leading theorist of the first generation
of the Frankfurt School of critical theory. Both as director of the Institute
for Social Research and in his early philosophical essays published in the
Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung, Horkheimer set the agenda for the
collaborative work of the Frankfurt School in the social sciences, including
analyses of the developments of state capitalism, the family, modern culture,
and fascism. His programmatic essays on the relation of philosophy and the
social sciences long provided the philosophical basis for Frankfurt School social
criticism and research and have profoundly influenced Habermas’s reformulation
of Frankfurt School critical theory. In these essays, such as “The Present
Situation of Social Philosophy and the Tasks of an Institute for Social
Research” (1931), Horkheimer elaborated a cooperative relation between
philosophy and the social sciences through an interdisciplinary historical
materialism. His “Traditional and Critical Theory” (1937) develops the
distinction between “critical” and “traditional” theories in terms of basic
goals: critical theories aim at emancipating human beings rather than
describing reality as it is now. In the darkest days of World War II Horkheimer
began collaborating with Adorno on The Dialectic of Enlightenment (1941), in
which they see the origins of modern reason and autonomy in the domination of
nature and the inner self. This genealogy of modern reason argues that myth and
enlightenment are inseparably “entwined,” a view proposed primarily to explain
the catastrophe in which Europe found itself. While Horkheimer thought that a
revised notion of Hegelian dialectics might lead beyond this impasse, he never
completed this positive project. Instead, he further developed the critique of
instrumental reason in such works as Eclipse of Reason (1947), where he argues
that modern institutions, including democracy, are under the sway of formal and
instrumental rationality and the imperatives of self-preservation. While he did
little new work after this period, he turned at the end of his life to a philosophical
reinterpretation of religion and the content of religious experience and
concepts, developing a negative theology of the “completely Other.” His most
enduring influence is his clear formulation of the epistemology of practical
and critical social inquiry oriented to human emancipation. See also CRITICAL
THEORY, FRANKFURT SCHOOL. J.Bo. hormic psychology. See MCDOUGALL. Ho Yen
(d.A.D. 249), Chinese philosopher, an early leader of the Neo-Taoist movement.
Ho Yen brought into currency the idea of “non-being” (wu) in explaining the tao
and the origin of being. Without limit and inexhaustible, the tao constitutes
the totality of all there is. Formless and nameless, it is a creative vital
energy (ch’i) that through a process of differentiation produces heaven and
earth and the myriad creatures. Ho Yen is also famous for his view that the
sage does not have emotions (ch’ing). This is because the sage is exceptionally
endowed with pure ch’ienergy, which precludes emotional disturbance. Ethically,
this further translates into a critique of hypocrisy and the abuse of power
that Ho Yen considered the bane of Chinese society. See also CH’ING,
NEO-TAOISM. A.K.L.C. hsiao, Chinese team meaning ‘filial piety’. Hsiao refers
both to a virtue and to acts manifesting that virtue. Originally, hsiao had to
do with the proper performance of one’s parents’ funeral rituals and sacrifices
to one’s ancestors. Later, hsiao came to encompass the proper treatment of
one’s parents while they are alive. Hsiao is fundamental to Confucianism in
that showing proper respect for one’s parents is thought to be related to
respect for legitimate political authority. See also CONFUCIANISM, LI2.
B.W.V.N. hsien, in Chinese philosophy, divine “immortals” or “transcendents” –
spiritual beings who have attained the tao and are characterized by
transcendence and immortality; a central ideal in Horkheimer, Max hsien 393
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 393 religious Taoism. The idea has its
roots in ancient Chinese religion; in its mature form, it signifies a being
constituted by the purest and most potent form of vital energy (ch’i), which
renders him/ her beyond the limitations of mundane life. Thus, hsien are often
characterized by the power of flight. In poetry and philosophic discourse,
hsien evokes fulfillment and freedom, especially from desire and the vagaries
of human striving. In religious Taoism, there is an important debate whether
immortality can be achieved through effort. Various methods that fall under the
general rubrics of “internal alchemy” (nei-tan) and “external alchemy”
(wai-tan) have been devised to bring about the perfected state. See also CH’I,
TAOISM. A.K.L.C. Hsi K’ang (A.D.223–62), Chinese philosopher, a key
representative of Neo-Taoism. Hsi K’ang’s philosophy centers on the concept of
tzu-jan – naturalness or, literally, what is of itself so – which depicts the
inherent order of the Taoist universe. Nature conforms to “necessary
principles” (pi-jan chih li); individuals receive an energy endowment (ch’i) at
birth of varying richness that defines their nature and capacity. While
endowment is inborn, self-cultivation directed at dispelling self-interest can
substantially enhance one’s physical and spiritual well-being. In ethics and
politics, Hsi K’ang thus advocates going beyond the orthodox teachings of
Confucianism (ming-chiao), which emphasize learning, conformity, and tradition.
Hsi is also famous for his musical theory that “sounds do not have sorrow or
joy” (sheng wu ai-lo): while sounds are naturally produced, emotions involve
subjective and cognitive reactions. See also CH’I, NEO-TAOISM. A.K.L.C. hsin1,
Chinese term meaning ‘heart’, ‘mind’, ‘feeling’. Generally, the hsin is both
the physical organ we call the heart, and the faculty of appetition, cognition,
and emotion, but the precise nature and proper role of hsin is one of the
fundamental issues dividing Chinese philosophers. Mencius speaks of “four
hearts,” associating a particular virtue and set of emotional and cognitive
capacities with each. Chuang Tzu suggests that we “fast” (chai), rather than
cultivate, the hsin, letting ourselves be guided instead by the ch’i. Hsün Tzu
holds that the hsin should control and sublimate the desires. In
Neo-Confucianism, the hsin is conceived as a fully developed moral sense, present
in every human, whose proper functioning is obscured by selfish desires.
NeoConfucians differ over whether hsin is identical with principle (li) and
nature (hsing). See also CONFUCIANISM, LI1, MENCIUS, NEO-CONFUCIANISM. B.W.V.N.
hsin2, Chinese term meaning ‘trust’, ‘faith’, ‘trustworthiness’, ‘honest’. In
early texts, hsin is the mutual trust of sincerity between worshiper and
spirit. The Chinese character for this word consists of two elements
representing ‘person’ and ‘speech’, and this provides a reliable guide to its
root sense: being true to one’s word. Hsin became one of the cardinal Confucian
virtues: trustworthiness or honesty (but only in service to what is right). In
Buddhist contexts, hsin can mean ‘faith’ in the religious sense, e.g., the Pure
Land School’s practice of faith in Amitabha Buddha. This influenced
Neo-Confucianism and is manifested in their faith in a perfect, innate moral
faculty. See also CHINESE PHILOSOPHY, NEO-CONFUCIANISM. P.J.I. hsing, Chinese
philosophical term generally agreed to be derived from ‘sheng’ (life, growth),
and usually translated as ‘nature’. In its earliest use as a term distinct from
‘sheng’, it probably referred to the tendency or direction of development that
a thing will realize if unobstructed (e.g. it is the hsing of a sprout to grow
into a fullgrown plant and the hsing of water to flow downward), and the hsing
of human beings is also supposed to be their proper course of development. The
concept hsing probably entered philosophical discourse with the development of
the school of thought associated with Yang Chu (fifth–fourth century B.C.),
which regarded the hsing of human beings as the tendency to live a life of a
certain span in good health and with sensory desires appropriately satisfied.
It subsequently became a central concept in Confucian thought, though
understood differently by different Confucian thinkers. Mencius (fourth century
B.C.) regarded the moral way of life as a full realization of the hsing of
human beings, which is constituted by the direction of development indicated by
certain incipient moral inclinations of the heart/mind (hsin); hsing is good in
that it has a moral direction. Hsün Tzu (third century B.C.) regarded the moral
way of life as a transformation of the hsing of human beings, which comprises
primarily self-regarding desires human beings have by birth; hsing is evil in
that unregulated pursuit of satisfaction of such desires leads to strife and
disorder. Different views of hsing continued to evolve; but ever since the view
that Mencius was the true transmitter of Confucius’s teachings became
established, Hsi K’ang hsing 394 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 394
largely through the efforts of Chu Hsi (1130– 1200), the idea that the hsing of
human beings is good has been a central tenet of Confucian thought. See also
CONFUCIANISM. K.-l.S. hsing-erh-shang, in Chinese philosophy, formless or
metaphysical. In part one of the I-Ching (the Book of Changes) there is a
statement that what is hsing-erh-shang is called tao (the Way), and what is
hsing-er-hsia (with form) is called ch’i, a concrete thing. In the Chinese way
of thinking, tao and ch’i are understood to be inseparable from each other; as
tao is both transcendent and immanent, it permeates things, and things must not
be cut off and alienated from their metaphysical origin. See also CHINESE
PHILOSOPHY. S.-h.L. hsing-ming, in Chinese philosophy, “forms and names,” an
important philosophical concept associated with Legalism and the Huang–Lao
School (the school of the Yellow Emperor and Lao Tzu), which flourished during
the Warring States period and the early Han dynasty (third– second century
B.C.). The narrower meaning of the term has to do with a system of law and
punishment, designed especially to keep state officials in check. More broadly,
hsing-ming points to a vision of order, in which all “names” (ming) should
correspond to their underlying “form” (hsing) or reality. Applied to politics,
this suggests that the ruler must discern the workings of the cosmos, ensure
that officials perform their assigned duties, and allow the people to prosper
in the perceived natural order of things. See also CHINESE LEGALISM. A.K.L.C.
Hsiung Shih-li (1885–1968), Chinese contemporary New Confucian philosopher. He
was a revolutionary when young and later studied Wei-shih (Vijnanavada,
‘Consciousness-Only’) philosophy at the China Buddhist Institute under Ou-yang
Ching-wu (1871–1943). But, dissatisfied, he developed his New Wei-shih
philosophy of creativity based on the insights he derived from the I-Ching. He
became influential and had Mou Tsung-san, T’ang Chün-i, and Hsü Fu-kuan among
his disciples. After the Communist takeover in 1949, he still rejected
materialism, but embraced a radical social philosophy that was not shared by
most of his former disciples. See also CHINESE PHILOSOPHY, HSÜ FUKUAN, I-CHING,
T’ANG CHÜN-I. S.-h.L. hsü, Chinese term meaning ‘void’, ‘vacuity’, ‘the
tenuous’. Hsü is not the absence of all things but a state in which things lack
distinctions. For Chuang Tzu, hsü is the ideal state of mind, in which the mind
is receptive to all things, perceives clearly, and responds effortlessly, as a
clean mirror reflects the images before it. Hsün Tzu develops this ideal,
characterizing a mind that is hsü (tenuous), unified and still. Extending later
Taoist views, Neo-Confucians regard hsü as the original, inchoate state of the
cosmos, out of which all things continually emerge and into which they
eventually dissolve. Neo-Confucians distinguish hsü from the Buddhist concept
k’ung (emptiness), which they see as denying the ultimate reality of the world.
See also NEO-CONFUCIANISM. P.J.I. Hsü Fu-kuan (1903–82), Chinese intellectual
and historian who served directly under Chiang Kai-shek at one time, but became
a critic of the Nationalist government after it moved to Taiwan in 1949. He
founded Democratic Review, the influential magazine that spread the ideas of
contemporary New Confucians. He also started the Department of Chinese at
Tunghai University in 1955 and invited Mou Tsung-san to join the staff to form
another center of New Confucianism other than New Asia College in Hong Kong. He
characterized his own position as between academic studies and politics, and
between historical scholarship and philosophical understanding. His magnum opus
was the three-volume History of Han Thought; his works on Chinese literature
and art were also widely quoted. See also CH’IEN MU, HSIUNG SHIH-LI, T’ANG
CHÜN-I. S.-h.L. Hsü Hsing (c.315 B.C.), Chinese philosopher, a member of the
Tillers or Agriculture School (Nung Chia). The Tillers believed that in
antiquity Shen Nung, the Divine Farmer, had ruled without reward, punishment,
or administration over a decentralized utopia of small communities where all,
including the ruler, lived by their own labor. Accordingly, Hsü Hsing attacked
contemporary rulers who did not plow the fields but rather lived off the labor
of others. He also sought to stabilize grain prices by controlling supply:
grain would be stored in good years and distributed in bad ones. R.P.P. &
R.T.A. Hsün Tzu (third century B.C.), a tough-minded Confucian philosopher best
known for his opposition to Mencius’s conception of the inherent goodness of
human nature. For Hsün Tzu, the essential nature of human beings is bad in the
sense of possessing a problematical motivational hsing-erh-shang Hsün Tzu 395
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 395 structure: every human seeks to satisfy
his/her desires; unless guided by li (propriety) and i (rightness), these
desires inevitably lead to conflict especially in view of the scarcity of goods
and the native human tendency toward partiality for one’s own benefits and for
those of one’s close relations. Significantly, the li or rules of proper
behavior perform three basic functions: delimiting, supportive, and ennobling.
The first draws the boundaries of proper conduct; the second provides channels
for satisfaction of desires within these boundaries; and the third provides
sources for ennobling personal character in accordance with jen (benevolence)
and i (rightness). Hsün Tzu is also noted for emphasizing law as a supplement
to li (rules of proper conduct); the need of argumentation to resolve ethical
disagreement; the importance of clarity of mind, as opposed to pi (obscuration)
in the pursuit of ethical knowledge; and the importance of Confucian classics
in character education. See also MENCIUS. A.S.C. Huai Nan Tzu, an ancient
Chinese syncretic compendium of knowledge. It was compiled by an academy of
scholars residing under the patronage of one of the most prominent literary
figures of the age, Liu An, Prince of Huai Nan, and presented to the imperial
court of Emperor Wu in about 140 B.C. The twenty treatises that make up the
text include technical tracts on astronomy, topography, and calendrics, as well
as original reconfigurations of the ideas and beliefs that flourished in the
formative period of classical Chinese philosophy. In many ways, it is a Han
dynasty (206 B.C.–A.D. 220) summary of existing knowledge, and like most
Chinese documents it is practical and prescriptive. As a political document, it
is syncretic, blending Confucian, Legalist, and Taoist precepts to recommend a
kind of practicable Taoist alternative to political centralism. R.P.P. &
R.T.A
Huang–Lao (Chinese,
‘School of the Yellow Emperor and Lao Tzu’), an eclectic school (c. third
century B.C.) purportedly based on the teachings of the mythic Yellow Emperor
and Lao Tzu, advocating a kind of Realpolitik Taoism stressing reliance on
methods of ruling (e.g., rewards and punishments) and the power of political
and social structures. Huang–Lao sought to establish a perfectly organized
state, which tzu jan (naturally) runs smoothly, in which the ruler reigns (not
rules) through wu wei (non-action). Huang–Lao’s mystical side concerns its
claim that only the ruler can attain the unifying vision needed for such
organization and that this vision is achieved through the practice of stillness
and hsü (tenuousness). P.J.I. Huang Tsung-hsi (1610–95), Chinese philosopher
and historian. A student of Liu Tsung-chou (1578–1645), the last great
Neo-Confucian philosopher in the Ming dynasty, he compiled Ming-ju-hsüeh-an and
Sung-Yüan-hsüeh-an, important anthologies and critical accounts of the
Neo-Confucianists of the Ming dynasty and Sung and Yüan dynasties. He also wrote
Ming-i-taifang-lu (“Waiting for the Dawn: A Plan for the Prince”), in which he
denounced the system of government working only for the selfish interest of the
ruler. This work exerted great influence in the last days of the Chinese
empire. See also CHINESE PHILOSOPHY, CHU HSI, WANG YANGMING. S.-h.L. Hu Hung,
also called Wu-feng (1100–55), Chinese Neo-Confucian philosopher and an
important figure in the Hunan School. According to him, hsin (mind/heart) is
the outward manifestation of hsing (human nature); one must first understand
the nature of jen (humanity) before one can practice moral cultivation.
Professor Mou Tsung-san believed that Hu Hung succeeded Chou Tun-yi, Chang
Tsai, and Ch’eng Hao, representing a third line of thought other than those of Ch’eng–Chu
and Lu–Wang. See also CHANG TSAI, CH’ENG HAO, CHOU TUN-YI, CHU HSI,
NEO-CONFUCIANISM. S.-h.L. Hui Shih (c.380–305 B.C.), Chinese philosopher, prime
minister of the state of Wei, and a leading member of the School of Names (ming
chia, also referred to as pien che, the Dialecticians or Sophists). As a friend
and debating partner of the Taoist philosopher Chuang Tzu, Hui Shih parried
Chuang Tzu’s poetic, rhapsodic, and meditationbased intuitions with
sophisticated logic and analytic rigor. An advocate of the Mohist idea of
impartial concern for others (chien ai) and an opponent of war, he is most
famous for his Ten Paradoxes, collected in the Chuang Tzu. Though Hui Shih’s
explanations are no longer extant, paradoxes such as “I go to Yüeh today but arrived
yesterday” and “The south has no limit yet has a limit” raise issues of
relativity and perspectivism with respect to language, values, and concepts
such as space and time. See also CHUANG TZU. R.P.P. & R.T.A. humanism, a
set of presuppositions that assigns to human beings a special position in the
scheme Huai Nan Tzu humanism 396 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 396 of
things. Not just a school of thought or a collection of specific beliefs or
doctrines, humanism is rather a general perspective from which the world is
viewed. That perspective received a gradual yet persistent articulation during
different historical periods and continues to furnish a central leitmotif of
Western civilization. It comes into focus when it is compared with two competing
positions. On the one hand, it can be contrasted with the emphasis on the
supernatural, transcendent domain, which considers humanity to be radically
dependent on divine order. On the other hand, it resists the tendency to treat
humanity scientifically as part of the natural order, on a par with other
living organisms. Occupying the middle position, humanism discerns in human
beings unique capacities and abilities, to be cultivated and celebrated for
their own sake. The word ‘humanism’ came into general use only in the
nineteenth century but was applied to intellectual and cultural developments in
previous eras. A teacher of classical languages and literatures in Renaissance
Italy was described as umanista (contrasted with legista, teacher of law), and
what we today call “the humanities,” in the fifteenth century was called studia
humanitatis, which stood for grammar, rhetoric, history, literature, and moral
philosophy. The inspiration for these studies came from the rediscovery of
ancient Greek and Latin texts; Plato’s complete works were translated for the
first time, and Aristotle’s philosophy was studied in more accurate versions
than those available during the Middle Ages. The unashamedly humanistic flavor
of classical writings had a tremendous impact on Renaissance scholars. Here,
one felt no weight of the supernatural pressing on the human mind, demanding
homage and allegiance. Humanity – with all its distinct capacities, talents,
worries, problems, possibilities – was the center of interest. It has been said
that medieval thinkers philosophized on their knees, but, bolstered by the new
studies, they dared to stand up and to rise to full stature. Instead of
devotional Church Latin, the medium of expression was the people’s own language
– Italian, French, German, English. Poetical, lyrical self-expression gained
momentum, affecting all areas of life. New paintings showed great interest in
human form. Even while depicting religious scenes, Michelangelo celebrated the
human body, investing it with instrinsic value and dignity. The details of
daily life – food, clothing, musical instruments – as well as nature and
landscape – domestic and exotic – were lovingly examined in paintings and
poetry. Imagination was stirred by stories brought home by the discoverers of
new lands and continents, enlarging the scope of human possibilities as
exhibited in the customs and the natural environments of strange, remote
peoples. The humanist mode of thinking deepened and widened its tradition with
the advent of eighteenth-century thinkers. They included French philosophes
like Voltaire, Diderot, and Rousseau, and other European and American figures –
Bentham, Hume, Lessing, Kant, Franklin, and Jefferson. Not always agreeing with
one another, these thinkers nevertheless formed a family united in support of
such values as freedom, equality, tolerance, secularism, and cosmopolitanism.
Although they championed untrammeled use of the mind, they also wanted it to be
applied in social and political reform, encouraging individual creativity and
exalting the active over the contemplative life. They believed in the
perfectibility of human nature, the moral sense and responsibility, and the
possibility of progress. The optimistic motif of perfectibility endured in the
thinking of nineteenth- and twentiethcentury humanists, even though the
accelerating pace of industrialization, the growth of urban populations, and
the rise in crime, nationalistic squabbles, and ideological strife leading to
largescale inhumane warfare often put in question the efficacy of humanistic
ideals. But even the depressing run of human experience highlighted the appeal
of those ideals, reinforcing the humanistic faith in the values of endurance,
nobility, intelligence, moderation, flexibility, sympathy, and love. Humanists
attribute crucial importance to education, conceiving of it as an all-around
development of personality and individual talents, marrying science to poetry
and culture to democracy. They champion freedom of thought and opinion, the use
of intelligence and pragmatic research in science and technology, and social
and political systems governed by representative institutions. Believing that
it is possible to live confidently without metaphysical or religious certainty
and that all opinions are open to revision and correction, they see human
flourishing as dependent on open communication, discussion, criticism, and
unforced consensus. See also ENCYCLOPEDIA, POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY, SOCIAL
PHILOSOPHY. K.K. humanism, civic. See CLASSICAL REPUBLICANISM. humanism, civic
humanism, civic 397 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 397 human nature, a
quality or group of qualities, belonging to all and only humans, that explains
the kind of being we are. We are all two-footed and featherless, but
‘featherless biped’ does not explain our socially significant characteristics.
We are also all both animals and rational beings (at least potentially), and
‘rational animal’ might explain the special features we have that other kinds
of beings, such as angels, do not. The belief that there is a human nature is
part of the wider thesis that all natural kinds have essences. Acceptance of
this position is compatible with many views about the specific qualities that
constitute human nature. In addition to rationality and embodiment, philosophers
have said that it is part of our nature to be wholly selfinterested,
benevolent, envious, sociable, fearful of others, able to speak and to laugh,
and desirous of immortality. Philosophers disagree about how we are to discover
our nature. Some think metaphysical insight into eternal forms or truths is
required, others that we can learn it from observation of biology or of
behavior. Most have assumed that only males display human nature fully, and
that females, even at their best, are imperfect or incomplete exemplars.
Philosophers also disagree on whether human nature determines morality. Some
think that by noting our distinctive features we can infer what God wills us to
do. Others think that our nature shows at most the limits of what morality can
require, since it would plainly be pointless to direct us to ways of living
that our nature makes impossible. Some philosophers have argued that human
nature is plastic and can be shaped in different ways. Others hold that it is
not helpful to think in terms of human nature. They think that although we
share features as members of a biological species, our other qualities are
socially constructed. If the differences between male and female reflect
cultural patterns of child rearing, work, and the distribution of power, our
biologically common features do not explain our important characteristics and
so do not constitute a nature. See also EMBODIMENT, ESSENTIALISM, PHILOSOPHY OF
MIND. J.B.S. human rights. See RIGHTS. human sciences. See WEBER. Humboldt, Wilhelm
von (1767–1835), German statesman, scholar, and educator, often regarded as the
father of comparative linguistics. Born in Potsdam, Wilhelm, with his younger
brother Alexander, was educated by private tutors in the “enlightened” style
thought suitable for future Prussian diplomats. This included classical
languages, history, philosophy, and political economy. After his university
studies in law at Frankfurt an der Oder and Göttingen, his career was divided
among assorted diplomatic posts, writing on a broad range of topics, and (his
first love) the study of languages. His broad-ranging works reveal the
important influences of Herder in his conception of history and culture, Kant
and Fichte in philosophy, and the French “Ideologues” in linguistics. His most
enduring work has proved to be the Introduction (published in 1836) to his
massive study of the Kawi language spoken on Java. Humboldt maintained that
language, as a vital and dynamic “organism,” is the key to understanding both
the operations of the human mind and the distinctive differences characteristic
of various national cultures. Every language possesses a distinctive inner form
that shapes, in a way reminiscent of Kant’s more general categories, the
subjective experiences, the worldview, and ultimately the institutions of a
given nation and its culture. While all later comparative linguists are
indebted to both his empirical studies and his theoretical insights, such
philosophers of culture as Dilthey and Cassirer acknowledge him as establishing
language as a central concern for the human sciences. J.P.Su. Hume, David
(1711–76), Scottish philosopher and historian who may be aptly considered the
leading neo-skeptic of the early modern period. Many of Hume’s immediate
predecessors (Descartes, Bayle, and Berkeley) had grappled with important
elements of skepticism. Hume consciously incorporated many of these same
elements into a philosophical system that manages to be both skeptical and
constructive. Born and educated in Edinburgh, Hume spent three years (1734–37)
in France writing the penultimate draft of A Treatise of Human Nature. In
middle life, in addition to writing a wide-ranging set of essays and short
treatises and a long History of England, he served briefly as companion to a
mad nobleman, then as a military attaché, before becoming librarian of the
Advocates Library in Edinburgh. In 1763 he served as private secretary to Lord
Hertford, the British ambassador in Paris; in 1765 he became secretary to the
embassy there and then served as chargé d’affaires. In 1767–68 he served in
Lonhuman nature Hume, David 398 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 398 don as
under-secretary of state for the Northern Department. He retired to Edinburgh
in 1769 and died there. Hume’s early care was chiefly in the hands of his
widowed mother, who reported that young David was “uncommon wake-minded” (i.e.,
uncommonly acute, in the local dialect of the period). His earliest surviving
letter, written in 1727, indicates that even at sixteen he was engaged in the
study that resulted in the publication (1739) of the first two volumes of A
Treatise of Human Nature. By the time he left college (c.1726) he had a
thorough grounding in classical authors, especially Cicero and the major Latin
poets; in natural philosophy (particularly that of Boyle) and mathematics; in
logic or theory of knowledge, metaphysics, and moral philosophy; and in
history. His early reading included many of the major English and French poets
and essayists of the period. He reports that in the three years ending about
March 1734, he read “most of the celebrated Books in Latin, French &
English,” and also learned Italian. Thus, although Hume’s views are often
supposed to result from his engagement with only one or two philosophers (with
either Locke and Berkeley, or Hutcheson or Newton), the breadth of his reading
suggests that no single writer or philosophical tradition provides the
comprehensive key to his thought. Hume’s most often cited works include A
Treatise of Human Nature (three volumes, 1739–40); an Abstract (1740) of
volumes 1 and 2 of the Treatise; a collection of approximately forty essays
(Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, first published, for the most part,
between 1741 and 1752); An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding (1748); An
Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals (1751); The Natural History of
Religion (1757); a six-volume History of England from Roman times to 1688
(1754–62); a brief autobiography, My Own Life (1777); and Dialogues concerning
Natural Religion (1778). Hume’s neo-skeptical stance manifests itself in each
of these works. He insists that philosophy “cannot go beyond experience; and
any hypothesis, that pretends to discover the ultimate original qualities of
human nature, ought at first to be rejected as presumptuous and chimerical.” He
says of the Treatise that it “is very sceptical, and tends to give us a notion
of the imperfections and narrow limits of the human understanding.” But he goes
well beyond the conventional recognition of human limitations; from his skeptical
starting place he projects an observationally based science of human nature,
and produces a comprehensive and constructive account of human nature and
experience. Hume begins the Treatise with a discussion of the “elements” of his
philosophy. Arguing that it is natural philosophers (scientists) who should
explain how sensation works, he focuses on those entities that are the
immediate and only objects present to the mind. These he calls “perceptions”
and distinguishes into two kinds, “impressions” and “ideas.” Hume initially
suggests that impressions (of which there are two kinds: of sensation and of
reflection) are more forceful or vivacious than ideas, but some ideas (those of
memory, e.g.) do sometimes take on enough force and vivacity to be called
impressions, and belief also adds sufficient force and vivacity to ideas to
make them practically indistinguishable from impressions. In the end we find
that impressions are clearly distinguished from ideas only insofar as ideas are
always causally dependent on impressions. Thomas Reid charged that the
allegedly representative theory of perception found in Descartes and Locke had
served as a philosophical Trojan horse leading directly to skeptical despair.
Hume was fully aware of the skeptical implications of this theory. He knew well
those sections of Bayle and Locke that reveal the inadequacy of Descartes’s
attempts to prove that there is an external world, and also appreciated the
force of the objections brought by Bayle and Berkeley against the primary–secondary
quality distinction championed by Locke. Hume adopted the view that the
immediate objects of the mind are always “perceptions” because he thought it
correct, and in spite of the fact that it leads to skepticism about the
external world. Satisfied that the battle to establish absolutely reliable
links between thought and reality had been fought and lost, Hume made no
attempt to explain how our impressions of sensation are linked to their
entirely “unknown causes.” He instead focused exclusively on perceptions qua
objects of mind: As to those impressions, which arise from the senses, their
ultimate cause is, in my opinion, perfectly inexplicable by human reason, and
‘twill always be impossible to decide with certainty, whether they arise
immediately from the object, or are produc’d by the creative power of the mind,
or are deriv’d from the author of our being. Nor is such a question any way
material to our present purpose. We may draw inferences from the coherence of
our perceptions, whether they be true or Hume, David Hume, David 399
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 399 false; whether they represent nature
justly, or be mere illusions of the senses. Book I of the Treatise is an effort
to show how our perceptions cohere to form certain fundamental notions (those
of space and time, causal connection, external and independent existence, and
mind) in which, skeptical doubts notwithstanding, we repose belief and on which
“life and action entirely depend.” According to Hume, we have no direct
impressions of space and time, and yet the ideas of space and time are
essential to our existence. This he explains by tracing our idea of space to a
“manner of appearance”: by means of two senses, sight and touch, we have
impressions that array themselves as so many points on a contrasting
background; the imagination transforms these particulars of experience into a
“compound impression, which represents extension” or the abstract idea of space
itself. Our idea of time is, mutatis mutandis, accounted for in the same way:
“As ‘tis from the disposition of visible and tangible objects we receive the
idea of space, so from the succession of ideas and impressions we form the idea
of time.” The abstract idea of time, like all other abstract ideas, is
represented in the imagination by a “particular individual idea of a
determinate quantity and quality” joined to a term, ‘time’, that has general
reference. Hume is often credited with denying there is physical necessity and
that we have any idea of necessary connection. This interpretation
significantly distorts his intent. Hume was convinced by the Cartesians, and
especially by Malebranche, that neither the senses nor reason can establish
that one object (a cause) is connected together with another object (an effect)
in such a way that the presence of the one entails the existence of the other.
Experience reveals only that objects thought to be causally related are
contiguous in time and space, that the cause is prior to the effect, and that
similar objects have been constantly associated in this way. These are the
defining, perceptible features of the causal relation. And yet there seems to
be more to the matter. “There is,” he says, a “NECESSARY CONNECTION to be taken
into consideration,” and our belief in that relation must be explained. Despite
our demonstrated inability to see or prove that there are necessary causal
connections, we continue to think and act as if we had knowledge of them. We
act, for example, as though the future will necessarily resemble the past, and
“wou’d appear ridiculous” if we were to say “that ‘tis only probable the sun
will rise to-morrow, or that all men must dye.” To explain this phenomenon Hume
asks us to imagine what life would have been like for Adam, suddenly brought to
life in the midst of the world. Adam would have been unable to make even the
simplest predictions about the future behavior of objects. He would not have
been able to predict that one moving billiard ball, striking a second, would
cause the second to move. And yet we, endowed with the same faculties, can not
only make, but are unable to resist making, this and countless other such
predictions. What is the difference between ourselves and this putative Adam?
Experience. We have experienced the constant conjunction (the invariant succession
of paired objects or events) of particular causes and effects and, although our
experience never includes even a glimpse of a causal connection, it does arouse
in us an expectation that a particular event (a “cause”) will be followed by
another event (an “effect”) previously and constantly associated with it.
Regularities of experience give rise to these feelings, and thus determine the
mind to transfer its attention from a present impression to the idea of an
absent but associated object. The idea of necessary connection is copied from
these feelings. The idea has its foundation in the mind and is projected onto
the world, but there is nonetheless such an idea. That there is an objective
physical necessity to which this idea corresponds is an untestable hypothesis,
nor would demonstrating that such necessary connections had held in the past
guarantee that they will hold in the future. Thus, while not denying that there
may be physical necessity or that there is an idea of necessary connection, Hume
remains a skeptic about causal necessity. Hume’s account of our belief in
future effects or absent causes – of the process of mind that enables us to
plan effectively – is a part of this same explanation. Such belief involves an
idea or conception of the entity believed in, but is clearly different from
mere conception without belief. This difference cannot be explained by
supposing that some further idea, an idea of belief itself, is present when we
believe, but absent when we merely conceive. There is no such idea. Moreover,
given the mind’s ability to freely join together any two consistent ideas, if
such an idea were available we by an act of will could, contrary to experience,
combine the idea of belief with any other idea, and by so doing cause ourselves
to believe anything. Consequently, Hume concludes that belief can only be a
“different MANNER of conceiving an object”; it is a livelier, Hume, David Hume,
David 400 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 400 firmer, more vivid and
intense conception. Belief in certain “matters of fact” – the belief that
because some event or object is now being experienced, some other event or
object not yet available to experience will in the future be experienced – is
brought about by previous experience of the constant conjunction of two
impressions. These two impressions have been associated together in such a way
that the experience of one of them automatically gives rise to an idea of the
other, and has the effect of transferring the force or liveliness of the impression
to the associated idea, thereby causing this idea to be believed or to take on
the lively character of an impression. Our beliefs in continuing and
independently existing objects and in our own continuing selves are, on Hume’s
account, beliefs in “fictions,” or in entities entirely beyond all experience.
We have impressions that we naturally but mistakenly suppose to be continuing,
external objects, but analysis quickly reveals that these impressions are by
their very nature fleeting and observer-dependent. Moreover, none of our
impressions provides us with a distinctive mark or evidence of an external
origin. Similarly, when we focus on our own minds, we experience only a
sequence of impressions and ideas, and never encounter the mind or self in
which these perceptions are supposed to inhere. To ourselves we appear to be
merely “a bundle or collection of different perceptions, which succeed each
other with an inconceivable rapidity, and are in a perpetual flux and
movement.” How do we, then, come to believe in external objects or our own
selves and self-identity? Neither reason nor the senses, working with
impressions and ideas, provide anything like compelling proof of the existence
of continuing, external objects, or of a continuing, unified self. Indeed,
these two faculties cannot so much as account for our belief in objects or
selves. If we had only reason and the senses, the faculties championed by,
respectively, the rationalists and empiricists, we would be mired in a
debilitating and destructive uncertainty. So unfortunate an outcome is avoided
only by the operation of an apparently unreliable third faculty, the
imagination. It, by means of what appear to be a series of outright mistakes
and trivial suggestions, leads us to believe in our own selves and in
independently existing objects. The skepticism of the philosophers is in this
way both confirmed (we can provide no arguments, e.g., proving the existence of
the external world) and shown to be of little practical import. An irrational
faculty, the imagination, saves us from the excesses of philosophy: “Philosophy
wou’d render us entirely Pyrrhonian,” says Hume, were not nature, in the form
of the imagination, too strong for it. Books II and III of the Treatise and the
Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals reveal Hume’s concern to explain
our moral behavior and judgments in a manner that is consistent with his
science of human nature, but which nonetheless recognizes the irreducible moral
content of these judgments. Thus he attempted to rescue the passions from the
ad hoc explanations and negative assessments of his predecessors. From the time
of Plato and the Stoics the passions had often been characterized as irrational
and unnatural animal elements that, given their head, would undermine humankind’s
true, rational nature. Hume’s most famous remark on the subject of the
passions, “Reason is, and ought only to be, the slave of the passions,” will be
better understood if read in this context (and if it is remembered that he also
claims that reason can and does extinguish some passions). In contrast to the
long-standing orthodoxy, Hume assumes that the passions constitute an integral
and legitimate part of human nature, a part that can be explained without
recourse to physical or metaphysical speculation. The passions can be treated
as of a piece with other perceptions: they are secondary impressions
(“impressions of reflection”) that derive from prior impressions and ideas.
Some passions (pride and humility, love and hatred) may be characterized as indirect;
i.e., they arise as the result of a double relation of impressions and ideas
that gives them one form of intentional character. These passions have both
assignable causes (typically, the qualities of some person or some object
belonging to a person) and a kind of indirect object (the person with the
qualities or objects just mentioned); the object of pride or humility is always
oneself, while the object of love or hatred is always another. The direct
passions (desire, aversion, hope, fear, etc.) are feelings caused immediately
by pleasure or pain, or the prospect thereof, and take entities or events as
their intentional objects. In his account of the will Hume claims that while
all human actions are caused, they are nonetheless free. He argues that our
ascriptions of causal connection have all the same foundation, namely, the
observation of a “uniform and regular conjunction” of one object with another.
Given that in the course of human affairs we observe “the same uniformity and
regular operation of natural principles” found in the physical world, and that
this uniformity results in an expectation of exactly the sort produced by
physHume, David Hume, David 401 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 401 ical
regularities, it follows that there is no “negation of necessity and causes,”
or no liberty of indifference. The will, that “internal impression we feel and
are conscious of when we knowingly give rise to” any action or thought, is an
effect always linked (by constant conjunction and the resulting feeling of
expectation) to some prior cause. But, insofar as our actions are not forcibly
constrained or hindered, we do remain free in another sense: we retain a
liberty of spontaneity. Moreover, only freedom in this latter sense is
consistent with morality. A liberty of indifference, the possibility of
uncaused actions, would undercut moral assessment, for such assessments
presuppose that actions are causally linked to motives. Morality is for Hume an
entirely human affair founded on human nature and the circumstances of human
life (one form of naturalism). We as a species possess several notable
dispositions that, over time, have given rise to morality. These include a
disposition to form bonded family groups, a disposition (sympathy) to
communicate and thus share feelings, a disposition – the moral sense – to feel
approbation and disapprobation in response to the actions of others, and a
disposition to form general rules. Our disposition to form family groups
results in small social units in which a natural generosity operates. The fact
that such generosity is possible shows that the egoists are mistaken, and
provides a foundation for the distinction between virtue and vice. The fact
that the moral sense responds differently to distinctive motivations – we feel
approbation in response to well-intended actions, disapprobation in response to
ill-intended ones – means that our moral assessments have an affective but
nonetheless cognitive foundation. To claim that Nero was vicious is to make a
judgment about Nero’s motives or character in consequence of an observation of
him that has caused an impartial observer to feel a unique sentiment of
disapprobation. That our moral judgments have this affective foundation
accounts for the practical and motivational character of morality. Reason is
“perfectly inert,” and hence our practical, actionguiding moral distinctions
must derive from the sentiments or feelings provided by our moral sense. Hume
distinguishes, however, between the “natural virtues” (generosity, benevolence,
e.g.) and the “artificial virtues” (justice, allegiance, e.g.). These differ in
that the former not only produce good on each occasion of their practice, but
are also on every occasion approved. In contrast, any particular instantiation
of justice may be “contrary to the public good” and be approved only insofar as
it is entailed by “a general scheme or system of action, which is
advantageous.” The artificial virtues differ also in being the result of
contrivance arising from “the circumstances and necessities of life.” In our
original condition we did not need the artificial virtues because our natural
dispositions and responses were adequate to maintain the order of small,
kinshipbased units. But as human numbers increased, so too did the scarcity of
some material goods lead to an increase in the possibility of conflict,
particularly over property, between these units. As a consequence, and out of
self-interest, our ancestors were gradually led to establish conventions
governing property and its exchange. In the early stages of this necessary
development our disposition to form general rules was an indispensable
component; at later stages, sympathy enables many individuals to pursue the
artificial virtues from a combination of self-interest and a concern for
others, thus giving the fully developed artificial virtues a foundation in two
kinds of motivation. Hume’s Enquiry concerning Human Understanding and his
Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals represent his effort to “recast”
important aspects of the Treatise into more accessible form. His Essays extend
his human-centered philosophical analysis to political institutions, economics,
and literary criticism. His best-selling History of England provides, among
much else, an extended historical analysis of competing Whig and Tory claims
about the origin and nature of the British constitution. Hume’s trenchant
critique of religion is found principally in his Enquiry concerning Human
Understanding, Natural History of Religion, and Dialogues. In an effort to curb
the excesses of religious dogmatism, Hume focuses his attention on miracles, on
the argument from design, and on the origin of the idea of monotheism. Miracles
are putative facts used to justify a commitment to certain creeds. Such
commitments are often maintained with a mind-numbing tenacity and a disruptive
intolerance toward contrary views. Hume argues that the widely held view of
miracles as violations of a law of nature is incoherent, that the evidence for
even the most likely miracle will always be counterbalanced by the evidence
establishing the law of nature that the miracle allegedly violates, and that
the evidence supporting any given miracle is necessarily suspect. His argument
leaves open the possibility that violations of the laws of nature may have
occurred, but shows that beliefs about such events lack the force of evidence
needed to jusHume, David Hume, David 402 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page
402 tify the arrogance and intolerance that characterizes so many of the
religious. Hume’s critique of the argument from design has a similar effect.
This argument purports to show that our well-ordered universe must be the
effect of a supremely intelligent cause, that each aspect of this divine
creation is well designed to fulfill some beneficial end, and that these
effects show us that the Deity is caring and benevolent. Hume shows that these
conclusions go well beyond the available evidence. The pleasant and
well-designed features of the world are balanced by a good measure of the
unpleasant and the plainly botched. Our knowledge of causal connections depends
on the experience of constant conjunctions. Such connections cause the vivacity
of a present impression to be transferred to the idea associated with it, and
leave us believing in that idea. But in this case the effect to be explained,
the universe, is unique, and its cause unknown. Consequently, we cannot
possibly have experiential grounds for any kind of inference about this cause.
On experiential grounds the most we can say is that there is a massive, mixed
effect, and, as we have through experience come to believe that effects have
causes commensurate to them, this effect probably does have a commensurately
large and mixed cause. Furthermore, as the effect is remotely like the products
of human manufacture, we can say “that the cause or causes of order in the
universe probably bear some remote analogy to human intelligence.” There is
indeed an inference to be drawn from the unique effect in question (the
universe) to the cause of that effect, but it is not the “argument” of the
theologians nor does it in any way support sectarian pretension or intolerance.
The Natural History of Religion focuses on the question of the origin of
religion in human nature, and delivers a thoroughly naturalistic answer: the
widespread but not universal belief in invisible and intelligent power can be
traced to derivative and easily perverted principles of our nature. Primitive
peoples found physical nature not an orderly whole produced by a beneficent
designer, but arbitrary and fearsome, and they came to understand the
activities of nature as the effect of petty powers that could, through
propitiating worship, be influenced to ameliorate their lives. Subsequently,
the same fears and perceptions transformed polytheism into monotheism, the view
that a single, omnipotent being created and still controls the world and all
that transpires in it. From this conclusion Hume goes on to argue that
monotheism, apparently the more sophisticated position, is morally retrograde.
Monotheism tends naturally toward zeal and intolerance, encourages debasing,
“monkish virtues,” and proves itself a danger to society: it is a source of
violence and a cause of immorality. In contrast, polytheism, which Hume here
regards as a form of atheism, is tolerant of diversity and encourages genuine
virtues that improve humankind. From a moral point of view, at least this one
form of atheism is superior to theism. See also BUNDLE THEORY, CAUSATION,
EMPIRICISM, ETHICS, PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION, PROBLEM OF INDUCTION, SKEPTICISM.
D.F.N. humors. See GALEN. Hu Shih (1891–1962), Chinese philosopher and
historian and a famous liberal intellectual in contemporary China. He studied
at Columbia University under Dewey, and brought pragmatism to China. He was the
Chinese ambassador to the United States during World War II and later headed
the Academia Sinica in Taipei. A versatile writer, he helped to initiate the
vernacular movement in Chinese literature; published his Ancient History of
Chinese Philosophy in 1919, the first history of Chinese philosophy written
from a modern point of view; and advocated wholesale Westernization or
modernization of China. A reformist committed to the democratic ideal, he
remained an anti-Communist throughout his life. See also CHINESE PHILOSOPHY,
LIANG SOU-MING. S.-h.L
Husserl, Edmund
(1859–1938), German philosopher and founder of phenomenology. Born in Prossnits
(now Proste v jov in the Czech Republic), he studied science and philosophy at
Leipzig, mathematics and philosophy at Berlin, and philosophy and psychology at
Vienna and Halle. He taught at Halle (1887–1901), Göttingen (1901– 16), and
Freiburg (1916–28). Husserl and Frege were the founders of the two major
twentiethcentury trends. Through his work and his influence on Russell,
Wittgenstein, and others, Frege inspired the movement known as analytic
philosophy, while Husserl, through his work and his influence on Heidegger,
Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, and others, established the movement known as
phenomenology. Husserl began his academic life as a mathematician. He studied
at Berlin with Kronecker and Weierstrass and wrote a dissertation in
mathematics at Vienna. There, influenced by Brentano, his interests turned
toward philosohumors Husserl, Edmund 403 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page
403 phy and psychology but remained related to mathematics. His habilitation,
written at Halle, was a psychological-philosophical study of the concept of
number and led to his first book, The Philosophy of Arithmetic (1891). Husserl
distinguishes between numbers given intuitively and those symbolically
intended. The former are given as the objective correlates of acts of counting;
when we count things set out before us, we constitute groups, and these groups
can be compared with each other as more and less. In this way the first few
numbers in the number series can be intuitively presented. Although most
numbers are only symbolically intended, their sense as numbers is derived from
those that are intuitively given. During 1890–1900 Husserl expanded his
philosophical concerns from mathematics to logic and the general theory of
knowledge, and his reflections culminated in his Logical Investigations
(1900–01). The work is made up of six investigations preceded by a volume of
prolegomena. The prolegomena are a sustained and effective critique of
psychologism, the doctrine that reduces logical entities, such as propositions,
universals, and numbers, to mental states or mental activities. Husserl insists
on the objectivity of such targets of consciousness and shows the incoherence
of reducing them to the activities of mind. The rest of the work examines signs
and words, abstraction, parts and wholes, logical grammar, the notion of
presentation, and truth and evidence. His earlier distinction between intuitive
presentation and symbolic intention is now expanded from our awareness of
numbers to the awareness of all sorts of objects of consciousness. The contrast
between empty intention and fulfillment or intuition is applied to perceptual
objects, and it is also applied to what he calls categorial objects: states of
affairs, relationships, causal connections, and the like. Husserl claims that
we can have an intellectual intuition of such things and he describes this
intuition; it occurs when we articulate an object as having certain features or
relationships. The formal structure of categorial objects is elegantly related
to the grammatical parts of language. As regards simple material objects,
Husserl observes that we can intend them either emptily or intuitively, but
even when they are intuitively given, they retain sides that are absent and
only cointended by us, so perception itself is a mixture of empty and filled
intentions. The term ‘intentionality’ refers to both empty and filled, or
signitive and intuitive, intentions. It names the relationship consciousness
has toward things, whether those things are directly given or meant only in
their absence. Husserl also shows that the identity of things is given to us
when we see that the object we once intended emptily is the same as what is
actually given to us now. Such identities are given even in perceptual
experience, as the various sides and aspects of things continue to present one
and the same object, but identities are given even more explicitly in categorial
intuition, when we recognize the partial identity between a thing and its
features, or when we directly focus on the identity a thing has with itself.
These phenomena are described under the general rubric of identitysynthesis. A
weakness in the first edition of Logical Investigations was the fact that
Husserl remained somewhat Kantian in it and distinguished sharply between the
thing as it is given to us and the thing-in-itself; he claimed that in his
phenomenology he described only the thing as it is given to us. In the decade
1900–10, through deeper reflection on our experience of time, on memory, and on
the nature of philosophical thinking, he overcame this Kantian distinction and
claimed that the thing-in-itself can be intuitively given to us as the identity
presented in a manifold of appearances. His new position was expressed in Ideas
Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy (1913). The
book was misinterpreted by many as adopting a traditional idealism, and many
thinkers who admired Husserl’s earlier work distanced themselves from what he
now taught. Husserl published three more books. Formal and Transcendental Logic
(1929) was written right after his retirement; Cartesian Meditations (1931),
which appeared in French translation, was an elaboration of some lectures he
gave in Paris. In addition, some earlier manuscripts on the experience of time
were assembled by Edith Stein and edited by Heidegger in 1928 as Lectures on
the Phenomenology of Inner Time-Consciousness. Thus, Husserl published only six
books, but he amassed a huge amount of manuscripts, lecture notes, and working
papers. He always retained the spirit of a scientist and did his philosophical
work in the manner of tentative experiments. Many of his books can be seen as
compilations of such experiments rather than as systematic treatises. Because
of its exploratory and developmental character, his thinking does not lend
itself to doctrinal summary. Husserl was of Jewish ancestry, and after his
death his papers were in danger from the Nazi regime; they were covertly taken
out of Germany by a Belgian scholar, Herman Husserl, Edmund Husserl, Edmund 404
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 404 Leo Van Breda, who, after World War II,
established the Husserl Archives at Louvain. This institution, with centers at
Cologne, Freiburg, Paris, and New York, has since supervised the critical
edition of many volumes of Husserl’s writings in the series Husserliana.
Husserl believes that things are presented to us in various ways, and that
philosophy should be engaged in precise description of these appearances. It
should avoid constructing large-scale theories and defending ideologies. It
should analyze, e.g., how visual objects are perceived and how they depend on
our cognitive activity of seeing, focusing, moving about, on the correlation of
seeing with touching and grasping, and so on. Philosophy should describe the
different ways in which such “regions of being” as material objects, living
things, other persons, and cultural objects are given, how the past and the
present are intended, how speech, numbers, time and space, and our own bodies
are given to us, and so on. Husserl carries out many such analyses himself and
in all of them distinguishes between the object given and the subjective
conscious activity we must perform to let it be given. The phenomenological
description of the object is called noematic analysis and that of the
subjective intentions is called noetic analysis. The noema is the object as
described phenomenologically, the noesis is the corresponding mental activity,
also as described by phenomenology. The objective and the subjective are
correlative but never reducible to one another. In working out such
descriptions we must get to the essential structures of things. We do so not by
just generalizing over instances we have experienced, but by a process he calls
“free variation” or “imaginative variation.” We attempt in our imagination to
remove various features from the target of our analysis; the removal of some
features would leave the object intact, but the removal of other features would
destroy the object; hence, when we come upon the latter we know we have hit on
something essential to the thing. The method of imaginative variation thus
leads to eidetic intuition, the insight that this or that feature belongs to
the eidos, the essence, of the thing in question. Eidetic intuition is directed
not only toward objects but also toward the various forms of intentionality, as
we try to determine the essence of perception, memory, judging, and the like.
Husserl thinks that the eidetic analysis of intentionality and its objects
yields apodictic truths, truths that can be seen to be necessary. Examples
might be that human beings could not be without a past and future, and that
each material perceptual object has sides and aspects other than those
presented at any moment. Husserl admits that the objects of perceptual
experience, material things, are not given apodictically to perception because
they contain parts that are only emptily intended, but he insists that the
phenomenological reflection on perceptual experience, the reflection that
yields the statement that perception involves a mixture of empty and filled
intentions, can be apodictic: we know apodictically that perception must have a
mixture of empty and filled intentions. Husserl did admit in the 1920s that
although phenomenological experience and statements could be apodictic, they
would never be adequate to what they describe, i.e., further clarifications of
what they signify could always be carried out. This would mean, e.g., that we
can be apodictically sure that human beings could not be what they are if they
did not have a sense of past and future, but what it is to have a past and
future always needs deeper clarification. Husserl has much to say about
philosophical thinking. He distinguishes between the “natural attitude,” our
straightforward involvement with things and the world, and the
“phenomenological attitude,” the reflective point of view from which we carry
out philosophical analysis of the intentions exercised in the natural attitude
and the objective correlates of these intentions. When we enter the
phenomenological attitude, we put out of action or suspend all the intentions
and convictions of the natural attitude; this does not mean that we doubt or
negate them, only that we take a distance from them and contemplate their
structure. Husserl calls this suspension the phenomenological epoché. In our
human life we begin, of course, in the natural attitude, and the name for the
processs by which we move to the phenomenological attitude is called the
phenomenological reduction, a “leading back” from natural beliefs to the
reflective consideration of intentions and their objects. In the
phenomenological attitude we look at the intentions that we normally look
through, those that function anonymously in our straightforward involvement
with the world. Throughout his career, Husserl essayed various “ways to
reduction” or arguments to establish philosophy. At times he tried to model the
argument on Descartes’s methodical doubt; at times he tried to show that the
world-directed sciences need the further supplement of phenomenological
reflection if they are to be truly scientific. One of the special features of the
natural attiHusserl, Edmund Husserl, Edmund 405 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM
Page 405 tude is that it simply accepts the world as a background or horizon
for all our more particular experiences and beliefs. The world is not a large
thing nor is it the sum total of things; it is the horizon or matrix for all
particular things and states of affairs. The world as noema is correlated to
our world-belief or world-doxa as noesis. In the phenomenological attitude we
take a distance even toward our natural being in the world and we describe what
it is to have a world. Husserl thinks that this sort of radical reflection and
radical questioning is necessary for beginning philosophy and entering into
what he calls pure or transcendental phenomenology; so long as we fail to
question our world-belief and the world as such, we fail to reach philosophical
purity and our analyses will in fact become parts of worldly sciences (such as
psychology) and will not be philosophical. Husserl distinguishes between the
apophantic and the ontological domains. The apophantic is the domain of senses
and propositions, while the ontological is the domain of things, states of
affairs, relations, and the like. Husserl calls “apophantic analytics” the
science that examines the formal, logical structures of the apophantic domain
and “formal ontology” the science that examines the formal structures of the
ontological domain. The movement between focusing on the ontological domain and
focusing on the apophantic domain occurs within the natural attitude, but it is
described from the phenomenological attitude. This movement establishes the
difference between propositions and states of affairs, and it permits
scientific verification; science is established in the zigzag motion between
focusing on things and focusing on propositions, which are then verified or
falsified when they are confirmed or disconfirmed by the way things appear.
Evidence is the activity of either having a thing in its direct presence or
experiencing the conformity or disconformity between an empty intention and the
intuition that is to fulfill it. There are degrees of evidence; things can be
given more or less fully and more or less distinctly. Adequation occurs when an
intuition fully satisfies an empty intention. Husserl also makes a helpful
distinction between the passive, thoughtless repetition of words and the
activity of explicit judging, in which we distinctly make judgments on our own.
Explicit thinking can itself fall back into passivity or become “sedimented” as
people take it for granted and go on to build further thinking upon it. Such
sedimented thought must be reactivated and its meanings revived. Passive
thinking may harbor contradictions and incoherences; the application of formal
logic presumes judgments that are distinctly executed. In our reflective
phenomenological analyses we describe various intentional acts, but we also
discover the ego as the owner or agent behind these acts. Husserl distinguishes
between the psychological ego, the ego taken as a part of the world, and the
transcendental ego, the ego taken as that which has a world and is engaged in
truth, and hence to some extent transcends the world. He often comments on the
remarkable ambiguity of the ego, which is both a part of the world (as a human
being) and yet transcends the world (as a cognitive center that possesses or
intends the world). The transcendental ego is not separable from individuals;
it is a dimension of every human being. We each have a transcendental ego,
since we are all intentional and rational beings. Husserl also devoted much
effort to analyzing intersubjectivity and tried to show how other egos and
other minds, other centers of conscious and rational awareness, can be
presented and intended. The role of the body, the role of speech and other
modes of communication, and the fact that we all share things and a world in
common are important elements in these analyses. The transcendental ego, the
source of all intentional acts, is constituted through time: it has its own
identity, which is different from that of the identity of things or states of
affairs. The identity of the ego is built up through the flow of experiences
and through memory and anticipation. One of Husserl’s major contributions is
his analysis of time-consciousness and its relation to the identity of the
self, a topic to which he often returns. He distinguishes among the objective
time of the world, the inner time of the flow of our experiences (such as acts
of perception, judgments, and memories), and a third, still deeper level that
he calls “the consciousness of inner time.” It is this third, deepest level,
the consciousness of inner time, that permits even our mental acts to be
experienced as temporal. This deepest level also provides the ultimate context
in which the identity of the ego is constituted. In one way, we achieve our
conscious identity through the memories that we store and recall, but these
memories themselves have to be stitched together by the deepest level of
temporality in order to be recoverable as belonging to one and the same self.
Husserl observes that on this deepest level of the consciousness of inner time,
we never have a simple atomic present: what we come to as ultimate is a moving
form Husserl, Edmund Husserl, Edmund 406 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page
406 that has a retention of the immediate past, a protention of that which is
coming, and a central core. This form of inner time-consciousness, the form of
what Husserl calls “the living present,” is prior even to the ego and is a kind
of apex reached by his philosophical analysis. One of the important themes that
Husserl developed in the last decade of his work is that of the life-world or
Lebenswelt. He claims that scientific and mathematical abstraction has roots in
the prescientific world, the world in which we live. This world has its own
structures of appearance, identification, evidence, and truth, and the
scientific world is established on its basis. One of the tasks of phenomenology
is to show how the idealized entities of science draw their sense from the
life-world. Husserl claims, e.g., that geometrical forms have their roots in
the activity of measuring and in the idealization of the volumes, surfaces,
edges, and intersections we experience in the life-world. The sense of the scientific
world and its entities should not be placed in opposition to the life-world,
but should be shown, by phenomenological analysis, to be a development of
appearances found in it. In addition, the structures and evidences of the
lifeworld itself must be philosophically described. Husserl’s influence in
philosophy has been very great during the entire twentieth century, especially
in Continental Europe. His concept of intentionality is understood as a way of
overcoming the Cartesian dualism between mind and world, and his study of
signs, formal systems, and parts and wholes has been valuable in structuralism
and literary theory. His concept of the life-world has been used as a way of
integrating science with wider forms of human activity, and his concepts of
time and personal identity have been useful in psychoanalytic theory and
existentialism. He has inspired work in the social sciences and recently his
ideas have proved helpful to scholars in cognitive science and artificial
intelligence. See also BRENTANO, INTENTIONALITY, KANT, PHENOMENOLOGY. R.So.
Hutcheson, Francis (1694–1746), Scottish philosopher who was the chief exponent
of the early modern moral sense theory and of a similar theory postulating a
sense of beauty. He was born in Drumalig, Ireland, and completed his
theological training in 1717 at the University of Glasgow, where he later
taught moral philosophy. He was a Presbyterian minister and founded an academy
for Presbyterian youth in Dublin. Sparked by Hobbes’s thesis, in Leviathan
(1651), that human beings always act out of selfinterest, moral debate in the
eighteenth century was preoccupied with the possibility of a genuine
benevolence. Hutcheson characterized his first work, An Inquiry into the
Original of our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue (1725), as a defense of the
nonegoistic moral sense theory of his more immediate predecessor, Shaftesbury,
against the egoism of Bernard Mandeville (1670–1733). His second work, An Essay
on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections with Illustrations on
the Moral Sense (1728), explores the psychology of human action, apparently
influenced by Butler’s classification of the passions (in his Sermons, 1726).
Hutcheson asserts the existence of several “internal” senses – i.e., capacities
for perceptual responses to concepts (such as one’s idea of Nero’s character),
as opposed to perceptions of physical objects. Among these internal senses are
those of honor, sympathy, morality, and beauty. Only the latter two, however,
are discussed in detail by Hutcheson, who develops his account of each within
the framework of Locke’s empiricist epistemology. For Hutcheson, the idea of
beauty is produced in us when we experience pleasure upon thinking of certain
natural objects or artifacts, just as our idea of moral goodness is occasioned
by the approval we feel toward an agent when we think of her actions, even if
they in no way benefit us. Beauty and goodness (and their opposites) are
analogous to Lockean secondary qualities, such as colors, tastes, smells, and
sounds, in that their existence depends somehow on the minds of perceivers. The
quality the sense of beauty consistently finds pleasurable is a pattern of
“uniformity amidst variety,” while the quality the moral sense invariably
approves is benevolence. A principal reason for thinking we possess a moral
sense, according to Hutcheson, is that we approve of many actions unrelated or
even contrary to our interests – a fact that suggests not all approval is
reason-based. Further, he argues that attempts to explain our feelings of
approval or disapproval without referring to a moral sense are futile: our
reasons are ultimately grounded in the fact that we simply are constituted to
care about others and take pleasure in benevolence (the quality of being
concerned about others for their own sakes). For instance, we approve of
temperance because overindulgence signifies selfishness, and selfishness is
contrary to benevolence. Hutcheson also finds that the ends promoted by the
benevolent person have a tendency to produce the greatest happiness for the
greatest number. Thus, since he regards Hutcheson, Francis Hutcheson, Francis
407 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 407 being motivated by benevolence as
what makes actions morally good, Hutcheson’s theory is a version of motive
utilitarianism. On Hutcheson’s moral psychology, we are motivated, ultimately,
not by reason alone, but by desires that arise in us at the prospect of our own
or others’ pleasure. Hutcheson formulates several quantitative maxims that
purport to relate the strength of motivating desires to the degrees of good, or
benefit, projected for different actions – an analysis that anticipates
Bentham’s hedonic calculus. Hutcheson was also one of the first philosophers to
recognize and make use of the distinction between exciting, or motivating,
reasons and justifying reasons. Exciting reasons are affections, or desires,
ascribed to an agent as motives that explain particular actions. Justifying
reasons derive from the approval of the moral sense and serve to indicate why a
certain action is morally good. The connection between these two kinds of
reasons has been a source of considerable debate. Contemporary critics included
John Balguy (1686–1748), who charged that Hutcheson’s moral theory renders
virtue arbitrary, since it depends on whatever human nature God happened to
give us, which could just as well have been such as to make us delight in
malice. Hutcheson discussed his views in correspondence with Hume, who later
sent Hutcheson the unpublished manuscript of his own account of moral sentiment
(Book III of A Treatise of Human Nature). As a teacher of Adam Smith, Hutcheson
helped shape Smith’s widely influential economic and moral theories.
Hutcheson’s major works also include A Short Introduction to Moral Philosophy
(originally published in Latin in 1742) and A System of Moral Philosophy
(1755). See also BENTHAM, HUME, MORAL SENSE THEORY, SMITH. E.S.R. Huygens,
Christiaan (1629–95), Dutch physicist and astronomer who ranked among the
leading experimental scientists of his time and influenced many other thinkers,
including Leibniz. He wrote on physics and astronomy in Latin (Horologium
Oscillatorium, 1673; De Vi Centrifuga, 1703) and in French for the Journal des
Scavans. He became a founding member of the French Academy of Sciences. Huygens
ground lenses, built telescopes, discovered the rings of Saturn, and invented
the pendulum clock. His most popular composition, Cosmotheoros (1699), inspired
by Fontenelle, praises a divine architect and conjectures the possible
existence of rational beings on other planets. J.-L.S. Hwajaeng-non. See KOREAN
PHILOSOPHY. hyle, ancient Greek term for matter. Aristotle brought the word
into use in philosophy by contrast with the term for form, and as designating
one of the four causes. By hyle Aristotle usually means ‘that out of which
something has been made’, but he can also mean by it ‘that which has form’. In
Aristotelian philosophy hyle is sometimes also identified with potentiality and
with substrate. Neoplatonists identified hyle with the receptacle of Plato. See
also ARISTOTLE, FORM, HYLOMORPHISM, METAPHYSICS, SUBSTANCE. P.Wo. hylomorphism,
the doctrine, first taught by Aristotle, that concrete substance consists of
form in matter (hyle). The details of this theory are explored in the central
books of Aristotle’s Metaphysics (Zeta, Eta, and Theta). See also ARISTOTLE,
FORM, HYLE, SUBSTANCE. P.Wo. hylozoism (from Greek hyle, ‘matter’, and zoe,
‘life’), the doctrine that matter is intrinsically alive, or that all bodies,
from the world as a whole down to the smallest corpuscle, have some degree or
some kind of life. It differs from panpsychism though the distinction is
sometimes blurred – in upholding the universal presence of life per se, rather
than of soul or of psychic attributes. Inasmuch as it may also hold that there
are no living entities not constituted of matter, hylozoism is often criticized
by theistic philosophers as a form of atheism. The term was introduced
polemically by Ralph Cudworth, the seventeenth-century Cambridge Platonist, to
help define a position that is significantly in contrast to soul–body dualism
(Pythagoras, Plato, Descartes), reductive materialism (Democritus, Hobbes), and
Aristotelian hylomorphism. So understood, hylozoism had many advocates in the eighteenth
and nineteenth centuries, among both scientists and naturalistically minded
philosophers. In the twentieth century, the term has come to be used, rather
unhelpfully, to characterize the animistic and naive-vitalist views of the
early Greek philosophers, especially Thales, Anaximenes, Heraclitus, and
Empedocles – who could hardly count as hylozoists in Cudworth’s sophisticated
sense. See also ARTIFICIAL LIFE, CAMBRIDGE PLATONISTS, HYLOMORPHISM,
PANPSYCHISM. A.P.D.M. Hypatia (c.370–415), Greek Neoplatonist philosopher who
lived and taught in Alexandria. She was brutally murdered by a Christian mob
Huygens, Christiaan Hypatia 408 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 408 because
of her associations with the city’s prefect, who was in conflict with its aggressive
archbishop, Cyril. She is said to have written commentaries on certain
mathematical works, but the only certain trace of her literary activity is in
her father Theon’s commentary on book 3 of Ptolemy’s Almagest, which Theon says
is Hypatia’s redaction. Hypatia appears to have been a very popular philosophy
teacher. She presumably professed a standard Neoplatonist curriculum, using
mathematics as a ladder to the intelligible world. A good sense of her views
can be gained from the essays, hymns, and letters of her pupil Synesius, bishop
of Ptolemais and an eclectic man of letters. Hypatia’s modern fame can be
traced back to the anticlericalism of the Enlightenment; see, e.g., chapter 47
of Edward Gibbon’s History of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire (1778).
The most influential representation of her appeared in Charles Kingsley’s
didactic historical novel Hypatia or New Foes with an Old Face (1853). The
facts that – according to ancient report – Hypatia was not only a brilliant
person, but a beautiful one who aroused the erotic passion of (at least) one
student, and that she was stripped naked before being slaughtered, seem to have
contributed to the revival of interest in her. See also NEOPLATONISM. I.M.
hypostasis (from Latin, ‘substance’), the process of regarding a concept or
abstraction as an independent or real entity. The verb forms ‘hypostatize’ and
‘reify’ designate the acts of positing objects of a certain sort for the
purposes of one’s theory. It is sometimes implied that a fallacy is involved in
so describing these processes or acts, as in ‘Plato was guilty of the
reification of universals’. The issue turns largely on criteria of ontological
commitment. See also METAPHYSICS, ONTOLOGICAL COMMITMENT. C.F.D. hypostatize.
See HYPOSTASIS. hypothetical consent. See CONTRACTARIANISM. hypothetical
construct. See OPERATIONALISM. hypothetical imperative. See KANT. hypothetical
syllogism. See SYLLOGISM. hypothetico-deductive method, a method of testing
hypotheses. Thought to be preferable to the method of enumerative induction,
whose limitations had been decisively demonstrated by Hume, the
hypothetico-deductive (H-D) method has been viewed by many as the ideal
scientific method. It is applied by introducing an explanatory hypothesis
resulting from earlier inductions, a guess, or an act of creative imagination.
The hypothesis is logically conjoined with a statement of initial conditions.
The purely deductive consequences of this conjunction are derived as
predictions, and the statements asserting them are subjected to experimental or
observational test. More formally, given (H • A) P O, H is the hypothesis, A a
statement of initial conditions, and O one of the testable consequences of (H •
A). If the hypothesis is ‘all lead is malleable’, and ‘this piece of lead is
now being hammered’ states the initial conditions, it follows deductively that
‘this piece of lead will change shape’. In deductive logic the schema is
formally invalid, committing the logical fallacy of affirming the consequent.
But repeated occurrences of O can be said to confirm the conjunction of H and
A, or to render it more probable. On the other hand, the schema is deductively
valid (the argument form modus tollens). For this reason, Karl Popper and his
followers think that the H-D method is best employed in seeking falsifications
of theoretical hypotheses. Criticisms of the method point out that infinitely
many hypotheses can explain, in the H-D mode, a given body of data, so that
successful predictions are not probative, and that (following Duhem) it is
impossible to test isolated singular hypotheses because they are always
contained in complex theories any one of whose parts is eliminable in the face
of negative evidence. See also CURVE-FITTING PROBLEM, DUHEM, TESTABILITY.
R.E.B.
Iamblichus. See
COMMENTARIES ON PLATO, NEOPLATONISM. Ibn Bajja, Abu Bakr, in Latin, Avempace
(d.1139), Spanish Islamic philosopher who was exceptionally well regarded by
later Arabic authorities. During a career as a government official and vizier
he wrote important treatises on philosophy but appears to have left most of
them unfinished. One of them provides an important theory of the conjunction of
the intellect with the human, based in part on notions of progressive
abstraction of specific forms and the universality of the Active Intellect.
Another offers a political philosophy grounded in assumptions about a
representative of the virtuous city who exists within a hostile, erring city as
a solitary or aberrant “weed.” P.E.W. Ibn Daud, Abraham, also called Rabad
(c.1110– 80), Spanish Jewish historian and astronomer, a philosophic precursor
of Maimonides. Born in Córdova and schooled by a beloved uncle, Baruch Albalia,
in Jewish and Greco-Arabic learning, he fled the Almohad invasion of 1146,
settling in Christian Toledo, where he was martyred. His Sefer ha-Qabbalah
(1161; translated by Gerson Cohen as The Book of Tradition, 1967) finds
providential continuity in Jewish intellectual history. His Emunah Ramah (1161;
translated by Norbert Samuelson as The Exalted Faith, 1986) was written in
Arabic but preserved in Hebrew. It anchors Jewish natural theology and ethics
in Avicennan metaphysics, mitigated by a voluntaristic account of emanation and
by the assertion that God created matter. Ibn Daud saves human freedom by
holding that God knows undetermined events as possible. He defends prophecy as
an outpouring of the Active Intellect – or of God – on those whose natures and
circumstances permit their inspiration. Prophetic miracles are perfectly
natural alterations of the familiar characters of things. See also AVICENNA.
L.E.G. Ibn Gabirol, Solomon, in Latin, Avicebron (c.1020–c.1057), Spanish
Jewish philosopher and poet, the author (in Arabic) of The Source of Life, a
classic of Neoplatonic thought. This work was written without any explicit
Jewish associations, and was preserved only in a twelfth-century Latin
translation, the Fons vitae. Consequently, its author was assumed until the
last century to be Muslim or Christian. Jewish Neoplatonists and mystics until
the Renaissance were familiar with the work and its author, and its influence
was felt in Christian Scholastic circles as well. Ibn Gabirol’s philosophy is
also reflected in his epic Hebrew poem “The Royal Crown,” which merges the
personal and religious feelings of the poet with a verse summary of his
metaphysical and astronomical beliefs. The Fons vitae is a prolix and often
inconsistent treatise, but exhibits radical creativity. The influence of
Proclus and of the first Jewish Neoplatonist, the tenth-century Isaac Israeli,
is also evident. Ibn Gabirol superimposes on the traditional Neoplatonic triad
of universal substances, the Intellect, Soul, and Nature, another set of
creative and more fundamental hypostases, the One, Divine Will, and Form and
Matter. In one of his most radical formulations, this primordial Form and
Matter are thought to suffuse not only the entire world that proceeds from
them, but to be found within the One itself, Matter being identified with the
divine essence, Form with Divine Will. Matter here emerges as prior and more
essential to the divine being than Form; God by implication is identified
primarily with potentiality and becoming, a point not lost upon the mystics.
See also JEWISH PHILOSOPHY. A.L.I. Ibn Khaldun, ‘Abdurrahman (1332–1406), Arab
historian, scholar, and politician, the first thinker to articulate a
comprehensive theory of historiography and philosophy of history in his
Muqaddima (final revision 1402), the introductory volume to his Universal
History (Kitab al-’ibar, 1377–82). Born and raised in Tunis, he spent the
politically active first part of his life in northwestern Africa and Muslim
Spain. He moved to Cairo in 1382 to pursue a career as professor of Maliki law
and judge. Ibn Khaldun created in the Muqaddima (English translation by F.
Rosenthal, 1967) what he called an “entirely original science.” He established
a scientific methodology for historiogra410 I phy by providing a theory of the
basic laws operating in history so that not only could the occurrences of the past
be registered but also “the how and why of events” could be understood.
Historiography is based on the criticism of sources; the criteria to be used
are inherent probability of the historical reports (khabar; plural: akhbar) –
to be judged on the basis of an understanding of significant political,
economic, and cultural factors – and their conformity with reality and the
nature of the historical process. The latter he analyzed as the cyclical (every
three generations, c.120 years) rise and decline of human societies (‘umran)
insofar as they exhibit a political cohesiveness (‘afabiya) in accepting the
authority of a dynastic head of state. Ibn Khaldun’s sources were the actual
course of Islamic history and the injunctions about political and social behavior
found in the Greek/Persian/Arab mirrors for princes and wisdom literature,
welded together by an Aristotelian teleological realism/empiricism; by
contrast, he was critical of the metaphysical Platonic utopias of thinkers like
al-Farabi. His influence is to be felt in later Arab authors and in particular
in Ottoman historiography. In the West, where he has been intensely studied
since the eighteenth century, he has been variously seen as the founder of
sociology, economic history, and other modern theories of state. (See A.
Al-Azmeh, Ibn Khaldun, 1989.) See also ARABIC PHILOSOPHY. D.Gu. Ibn Rushd. See
AVERROES. Ibn Sina. See AVICENNA. Ibn Tufayl, Abu Bakr (d.1186), Spanish
Islamic philosopher who played an important role in promoting the philosophical
career of Averroes. His own contribution, however, is a famous philosophical
fantasy, Hayy ibn Yaqzan – an account of a solitary autodidact who grows up on
a deserted island yet discovers by his own unaided efforts a philosophical
(Aristotelian) explanation of the world and of divine truths. Later, having
finally come in contact with human civilization, this character also recognizes
the necessity of religious law and regulation for that other, essentially
imperfect, society, although he holds himself personally above this
requirement. The work attracted considerable attention in late
seventeenth-century Europe following its publication in 1671. See also ARABIC
PHILOSOPHY. P.E.W. I-Ching (“Book of Changes”), a Chinese divination manual
that may have existed in some form as early as the seventh century B.C. It was
not philosophically significant until augmented by a group of appendices, the
“Ten Wings,” around 200 B.C. The book has tremendously influenced Chinese
thought since the Han dynasty, for at least two reasons. First, it provided a
cosmology that systematically grounded certain ideas, particularly Confucian
ethical claims, in the nature of the cosmos. Second, it presented this
cosmology through a system of loosely described symbols that provided virtually
limitless interpretive possibilities. In order to “read” the text properly, one
needed to be a certain kind of person. In this way, the I-Ching accommodated
both intuitionism and self-cultivationism, two prominent characteristics of
early Chinese thought. At the same time, the text’s endless interpretive
possibilities allowed it to be used in widely different ways by a variety of
thinkers. See also CHINESE PHILOSOPHY, CONFUCIANISM. P.J.I. icon. See PEIRCE.
id. See FREUD. idea, in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, whatever is
immediately before the mind when one thinks. The notion of thinking was taken
in a very broad sense; it included perception, memory, and imagination, in
addition to thinking narrowly construed. In connection with perception, ideas
were often (though not always – Berkeley is the exception) held to be
representational images, i.e., images of something. In other contexts, ideas
were taken to be concepts, such as the concept of a horse or of an infinite
quantity, though concepts of these sorts certainly do not appear to be images.
An innate idea was either a concept or a general truth, such as ‘Equals added
to equals yield equals’, that was allegedly not learned but was in some sense
always in the mind. Sometimes, as in Descartes, innate ideas were taken to be
cognitive capacities rather than concepts or general truths, but these
capacities, too, were held to be inborn. An adventitious idea, either an image
or a concept, was an idea accompanied by a judgment concerning the non-mental cause
of that idea. So, a visual image was an adventitious idea provided one judged
of that idea that it was caused by something outside one’s mind, presumably by
the object being seen. Ibn Rushd idea 411 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page
411 See also BERKELEY, DESCARTES, HUME, LOCKE, PERCEPTION. G.S.P. idea, clear
and distinct. See DESCARTES. idea, innate. See IDEA. idealism, the
philosophical doctrine that reality is somehow mind-correlative or
mind-coordinated – that the real objects constituting the “external world” are
not independent of cognizing minds, but exist only as in some way correlative
to mental operations. The doctrine centers on the conception that reality as we
understand it reflects the workings of mind. Perhaps its most radical version is
the ancient Oriental spiritualistic or panpsychistic idea, renewed in Christian
Science, that minds and their thoughts are all there is – that reality is
simply the sum total of the visions (or dreams?) of one or more minds. A
dispute has long raged within the idealist camp over whether “the mind” at
issue in such idealistic formulas was a mind emplaced outside of or behind
nature (absolute idealism), or a nature-pervasive power of rationality of some
sort (cosmic idealism), or the collective impersonal social mind of people in
general (social idealism), or simply the distributive collection of individual
minds (personal idealism). Over the years, the less grandiose versions of the
theory came increasingly to the fore, and in recent times virtually all idealists
have construed “the minds” at issue in their theory as separate individual
minds equipped with socially engendered resources. There are certainly versions
of idealism short of the spiritualistic position of an ontological idealism
that (as Kant puts it at Prolegomena, section 13, n. 2) holds that “there are
none but thinking beings.” Idealism need certainly not go so far as to affirm
that mind makes or constitutes matter; it is quite enough to maintain (e.g.)
that all of the characterizing properties of physical existents resemble
phenomenal sensory properties in representing dispositions to affect
mind-endowed creatures in a certain sort of way, so that these properties have
no standing without reference to minds. Weaker still is an explanatory idealism
which merely holds that an adequate explanation of the real always requires
some recourse to the operations of mind. Historically, positions of the
generally idealistic type have been espoused by numerous thinkers. For example,
Berkeley maintained that “to be [real] is to be perceived” (esse est percipi).
And while this does not seem particularly plausible because of its inherent
commitment to omniscience, it seems more sensible to adopt “to be is to be
perceivable” (esse est percipile esse). For Berkeley, of course, this was a
distinction without a difference: if something is perceivable at all, then God
perceives it. But if we forgo philosophical reliance on God, the matter looks
different, and pivots on the question of what is perceivable for perceivers who
are physically realizable in “the real world,” so that physical existence could
be seen – not so implausibly – as tantamount to observability-in-principle. The
three positions to the effect that real things just exactly are things as
philosophy or as science or as “common sense” takes them to be – positions
generally designated as Scholastic, scientific, and naive realism, respectively
– are in fact versions of epistemic idealism exactly because they see reals as
inherently knowable and do not contemplate mind-transcendence for the real.
Thus, the thesis of naive (“commonsense”) realism that ‘External things exist
exactly as we know them’ sounds realistic or idealistic according as one
stresses the first three words of the dictum or the last four. Any theory of
natural teleology that regards the real as explicable in terms of value could
to this extent be counted as idealistic, in that valuing is by nature a mental
process. To be sure, the good of a creature or species of creatures (e.g.,
their well-being or survival) need not be something mind-represented. But
nevertheless, goods count as such precisely because if the creatures at issue
could think about it, they would adopt them as purposes. It is this
circumstance that renders any sort of teleological explanation at least
conceptually idealistic in nature. Doctrines of this sort have been the
stock-in-trade of philosophy from the days of Plato (think of the Socrates of
the Phaedo) to those of Leibniz, with his insistence that the real world must
be the best possible. And this line of thought has recently surfaced once more
in the controversial “anthropic principle” espoused by some theoretical
physicists. Then too it is possible to contemplate a position along the lines
envisioned in Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre (The Science of Knowledge), which
sees the ideal as providing the determining factor for the real. On such a
view, the real is not characterized by the science we actually have but by the
ideal science that is the telos of our scientific efforts. On this approach,
which Wilhelm Wundt characterized as “ideal-realism” (Idealrealismus; see his
Logik, vol. 1, 2d ed., 1895), the knowledge that achieves adequation to the
real idea, clear and distinct idealism 412 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page
412 (adaequatio ad rem) by adequately characterizing the true facts in
scientific matters is not the knowledge actually afforded by present-day
science, but only that of an ideal or perfected science. Over the years, many
objections to idealism have been advanced. Samuel Johnson thought to refute
Berkeley’s phenomenalism by kicking a stone. He conveniently forgot that
Berkeley goes to great lengths to provide for stones – even to the point of
invoking the aid of God on their behalf. Moore pointed to the human hand as an
undeniably mind-external material object. He overlooked that, gesticulate as he
would, he would do no more than induce people to accept the presence of a hand
on the basis of the handorientation of their experience. Peirce’s “Harvard
Experiment” of letting go of a stone held aloft was supposed to establish
Scholastic realism because his audience could not control their expectation of
the stone’s falling to earth. But an uncontrollable expectation is still an
expectation, and the realism at issue is no more than a realistic
thought-exposure. Kant’s famous “Refutation of Idealism” argues that our
conception of ourselves as mindendowed beings presupposes material objects
because we view our mind-endowed selves as existing in an objective temporal
order, and such an order requires the existence of periodic physical processes
(clocks, pendula, planetary regularities) for its establishment. At most,
however, this argument succeeds in showing that such physical processes have to
be assumed by minds, the issue of their actual mind-independent existence
remaining unaddressed. (Kantian realism is an intraexperiential “empirical”
realism.) It is sometimes said that idealism confuses objects with our
knowledge of them and conflates the real with our thought about it. But this
charge misses the point. The only reality with which we inquirers can have any
cognitive commerce is reality as we conceive it to be. Our only information
about reality is via the operation of mind – our only cognitive access to
reality is through the mediation of mind-devised models of it. Perhaps the most
common objection to idealism turns on the supposed mind-independence of the
real: “Surely things in nature would remain substantially unchanged if there
were no minds.” This is perfectly plausible in one sense, namely the causal one
– which is why causal idealism has its problems. But it is certainly not true
conceptually. The objector has to specify just exactly what would remain the
same. “Surely roses would smell just as sweet in a minddenuded world!” Well . .
. yes and no. To be sure, the absence of minds would not change roses. But
roses and rose fragrance and sweetness – and even the size of roses – are all
factors whose determination hinges on such mental operations as smelling, scanning,
measuring, and the like. Mind-requiring processes are needed for something in
the world to be discriminated as a rose and determined to bear certain
features. Identification, classification, property attribution are all required
and by their very nature are all mental operations. To be sure, the role of
mind is here hypothetical. (“If certain interactions with duly constituted
observers took place, then certain outcomes would be noted.”) But the fact
remains that nothing could be discriminated or characterized as a rose in a
context where the prospect of performing suitable mental operations (measuring,
smelling, etc.) is not presupposed. Perhaps the strongest argument favoring
idealism is that any characterization of the real that we can devise is bound to
be a mind-constructed one: our only access to information about what the real
is is through the mediation of mind. What seems right about idealism is
inherent in the fact that in investigating the real we are clearly constrained
to use our own concepts to address our own issues – that we can learn about the
real only in our own terms of reference. But what seems right about realism is
that the answers to the questions we put to the real are provided by reality
itself – whatever the answers may be, they are substantially what they are
because it is reality itself that determines them to be that way. See also
BERKELEY, FICHTE, HEGEL, KANT, METAPHYSICS. N.R. idealism, Critical. See KANT.
idealism, transcendental. See KANT. ideal language, a system of notation that
would correct perceived deficiencies of ordinary language by requiring the
structure of expressions to mirror the structure of that which they represent.
The notion that conceptual errors can be corrected and philosophical problems
solved (or dissolved) by properly representing them in some such system figured
prominently in the writings of Leibniz, Carnap, Russell, Wittgenstein, and
Frege, among others. For Russell, the ideal, or “logically perfect,” language
is one in which grammatical form coincides with logical form, there are no
vague or ambiguous expresidealism, Critical ideal language 413 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 413 sions, and no proper names that fail to denote.
Frege’s Begriffsschrift is perhaps the most thorough and successful execution
of the ideal language project. Deductions represented within this system (or
its modern descendants) can be effectively checked for correctness. See also
CARNAP, FORMAL LANGUAGE, LOGICAL FORM, RUSSELL. S.T.K. ideal market, a
hypothetical market, used as a tool of economic analysis, in which all relevant
agents are perfectly informed of the price of the good in question and the cost
of its production, and all economic transactions can be undertaken with no
cost. A specific case is a market exemplifying perfect competition. The term is
sometimes extended to apply to an entire economy consisting of ideal markets
for every good. See also PERFECT COMPETITION, PHILOSOPHY OF ECONOMICS. A.N.
ideal mathematics. See HILBERT’S PROGRAM. ideal observer, a hypothetical being,
possessed of various qualities and traits, whose moral reactions (judgments or
attitudes) to actions, persons, and states of affairs figure centrally in
certain theories of ethics. There are two main versions of ideal observer
theory: (a) those that take the reactions of ideal observers as a standard of
the correctness of moral judgments, and (b) those that analyze the meanings of
moral judgments in terms of the reactions of ideal observers. Theories of the
first sort – ideal observer theories of correctness – hold, e.g., that
judgments like ‘John’s lying to Brenda about her father’s death was wrong
(bad)’ are correct provided any ideal observer would have a negative attitude
toward John’s action. Similarly, ‘Alison’s refusal to divulge confidential
information about her patient was right (good)’ is correct provided any ideal
observer would have a positive attitude toward that action. This version of the
theory can be traced to Adam Smith, who is usually credited with introducing
the concept of an ideal observer into philosophy, though he used the expression
‘impartial spectator’ to refer to the concept. Regarding the correctness of
moral judgments, Smith wrote: “That precise and distinct measure can be found
nowhere but in the sympathetic feelings of the impartial and well-informed
spectator” (A Theory of Moral Sentiments, 1759). Theories of a second sort –
ideal observer theories of meaning – take the concept of an ideal observer as
part of the very meaning of ordinary moral judgments. Thus, according to
Roderick Firth (“Ethical Absolutism and the Ideal Observer,” Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 1952), moral judgments of the form ‘x is good
(bad)’, on this view, mean ‘All ideal observers would feel moral approval
(disapproval) toward x’, and similarly for other moral judgments (where such
approvals and disapprovals are characterized as felt desires having a “demand
quality”). Different conceptions of an ideal observer result from variously
specifying those qualities and traits that characterize such beings. Smith’s
characterization includes being well informed and impartial. However, according
to Firth, an ideal observer must be omniscient; omnipercipient, i.e., having
the ability to imagine vividly any possible events or states of affairs,
including the experiences and subjective states of others; disinterested, i.e.,
having no interests or desires that involve essential reference to any
particular individuals or things; dispassionate; consistent; and otherwise a
“normal” human being. Both versions of the theory face a dilemma: on the one
hand, if ideal observers are richly characterized as impartial, disinterested,
and normal, then since these terms appear to be moral-evaluative terms, appeal
to the reactions of ideal observers (either as a standard of correctness or as
an analysis of meaning) is circular. On the other hand, if ideal observers
receive an impoverished characterization in purely non-evaluative terms, then
since there is no reason to suppose that such ideal observers will often all
agree in their reactions to actions, people, and states of affairs, most moral
judgments will turn out to be incorrect. See also ETHICAL OBJECTIVISM, ETHICS,
RELATIVISM. M.C.T. ideal proposition. See HILBERT’s PROGRAM. ideal type. See
MOSCA, WEBER. ideal utilitarianism. See RASHDALL, UTILITARIANISM. ideas of
practical reason. See KANT. ideas of pure reason. See KANT. ideas of
reflection. See LOCKE. ideas of sensation. See LOCKE. idea theory of meaning.
See MEANING. ideational theory of meaning. See PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE. ideal
market ideational theory of meaning 414 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 414
identity, the relation each thing bears just to itself. Formally, a % b Q EF(Fa
P Fb); informally, the identity of a and b implies and is implied by their
sharing of all their properties. Read from left to right, this biconditional
asserts the indiscernibility of identicals; from right to left, the identity of
indiscernibles. The indiscernibility of identicals is not to be confused with a
metalinguistic principle to the effect that if a and b are names of the same
object, then each may be substituted for the other in a sentence without change
of truth-value: that may be false, depending on the semantics of the language
under discussion. Similarly, the identity of indiscernibles is not the claim
that if a and b can be exchanged in all sentential contexts without affecting
truth-value, then they name the same object. For such intersubstitutability may
arise when the language in question simply lacks predicates that could
discriminate between the referents of a and b. In short, the identity of things
is not a relation among names. Identity proper is numerical identity, to be
distinguished from exact similarity (qualitative identity). Intuitively, two
exactly similar objects are “copies” of each other; still they are two, hence
not identical. One way to express this is via the notions of extrinsic and
intrinsic properties: exactly similar objects differ in respect of the former
only. But we can best explain ‘instrinsic property’ by saying that a thing’s
intrinsic properties are those it shares with its copies. These notions appear
virtually interdefinable. (Note that the concept of an extrinsic property must
be relativized to a class or kind of things. Not being in San Francisco is an
extrinsic property of persons but arguably an intrinsic property of cities.)
While qualitative identity is a familiar notion, its theoretical utility is
unclear. The absolute notion of qualitative identity should, however, be distinguished
from an unproblematic relative notion: if some list of salient properties is
fixed in a given context (say, in mechanics or normative ethics), then the
exactly similar things, relative to that context, are those that agree on the
properties listed. Both the identity of indiscernibles and (less frequently)
the indiscernibility of identicals are sometimes called Leibniz’s law. Neither
attribution is apt. Although Leibniz would have accepted the former principle,
his distinctive claim was the impossibility of exactly similar objects:
numerically distinct individuals cannot even share all intrinsic properties.
Moreover, this was not, for him, simply a law of identity but rather an
application of his principle of sufficient reason. And the indiscernibility of
identicals is part of a universal understanding of identity. What distinguishes
Leibniz is the prominence of identity statements in his metaphysics and logical
theory. Although identity remains a clear and basic logical notion, identity
questions about problematic kinds of objects raise difficulties. One example is
the identification of properties, particularly in contexts involving reduction.
Although we know what identity is, the notion of a property is unclear enough
to pose systematic obstacles to the evaluation of theoretically significant
identity statements involving properties. Other difficulties involve personal
identity or the possible identification of numbers and sets in the foundations
of mathematics. In these cases, the identity questions simply inherit – and
provide vivid ways of formulating – the difficulties pertaining to such
concepts as person, property, or number; no rethinking of the identity concept
itself is indicated. But puzzles about the relation of an ordinary material
body to its constituent matter may suggest that the logician’s analysis of
identity does not cleanly capture our everyday notion(s). Consider a bronze
statue. Although the statue may seem to be nothing besides its matter,
reflection on change over time suggests a distinction. The statue may be melted
down, hence destroyed, while the bronze persists, perhaps simply as a mass or
perhaps as a new statue formed from the same bronze. Alternatively, the statue
may persist even as some of its bronze is dissolved in acid. So the statue
seems to be one thing and the bronze another. Yet what is the bronze besides a
statue? Surely we do not have two statues (or statuelike objects) in one place?
Some authors feel that variants of the identity relation may permit a perspicuous
description of the relation of statue and bronze: (1) tensed identity: Assume a
class of timebound properties – roughly, properties an object can have at a
time regardless of what properties it has at other times. (E.g., a statue’s
shape, location, or elegance.) Then a % t b provided a and b share all
timebound properties at time t. Thus, the statue and the bronze may be
identical at time t 1 but not at t 2. (2) relative identity: a and b may be
identical relative to one concept (or predicate) but not to another. Thus, the
statue may be held to be the same lump of matter as the bronze but not the same
object of art. identity identity 415 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 415 In
each case, only detailed study will show whether the variant notion can at once
offer a natural description of change and qualify as a viable identity concept.
(Strong doubts arise about (2).) But it seems likely that our everyday talk of
identity has a richness and ambiguity that escapes formal characterization. See
also ESSENTIALISM, IDENTITY OF INDISCERNIBLES, PERSONAL IDENTITY, PROPERTY,
TIME. S.J.W. identity, ‘is’ of. See IS. identity, psychophysical. See
PHYSICALISM. identity, theoretical. See PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. identity of
indiscernibles, any of a family of principles, important members of which
include the following: (1) If objects a and b have all properties in common,
then a and b are identical. (2) If objects a and b have all their qualitative
properties in common, then a and b are identical. (3) If objects a and b have all
their non-relational qualitative properties in common, then a and b are
identical. Two questions regarding these principles are raised: Which, if any,
are true? If any are true, are they necessarily true? Discussions of the
identity of indiscernibles typically restrict the scope of the principle to
concrete objects. Although the notions of qualitative and non-relational
properties play a prominent role in these discussions, they are notoriously
difficult to define. Intuitively, a qualitative property is one that can be
instantiated by more than one object and does not involve being related to
another particular object. It does not follow that all qualitative properties
are non-relational, since some relational properties, such as being on top of a
brown desk, do not involve being related to some particular object. (1) is
generally regarded as necessarily true but trivial, since if a and b have all
properties in common then a has the property of being identical with b and b
has the property of being identical with a. Hence, most discussions focus on
(2) and (3). (3) is generally regarded as, at best, a contingent truth since it
appears possible to conceive of two distinct red balls of the same size, shade
of color, and composition. Some have argued that elementary scientific
particles, such as electrons, are counterexamples to even the contingent truth
of (3). (2) appears defensible as a contingent truth since, in the actual
world, objects such as the red balls and the electrons differ in their
relational qualitative properties. It has been argued, however, that (2) is not
a necessary truth since it is possible to conceive of a world consisting of
only the two red balls. In such a world, any qualitative relational property
possessed by one ball is also possessed by the other. Defenders of the
necessary truth of (2) have argued that a careful examination of such
counterexamples reveals hidden qualitative properties that differentiate the
objects. See also IDENTITY, INDIVIDUATION, LEIBNIZ, PROPERTY, SUBSTANCE. A.C.
identity of persons. See PERSONAL IDENTITY. identity theory. See PHILOSOPHY OF
MIND. identity thesis. See PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. ideographic. See WINDELBAND.
ideology, generally a disparaging term used to describe someone else’s
political views which one regards as unsound. This use derives from Marx’s
employment of the term to signify a false consciousness shared by the members
of a particular social class. For example, according to Marx, members of the
capitalist class share the ideology that the laws of the competitive market are
natural and impersonal, that workers in a competitive market are paid all that
they can be paid, and that the institutions of private property in the means of
production are natural and justified. See also MARXISM, POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY.
J.P.St. ideo-motor action, a theory of the will according to which “every
representation of a movement awakens in some degree the actual movement which
is its object” (William James). Proposed by physiologist W. B. Carpenter, and
taught by Lotze and Renouvier, ideo-motor action was developed by James. He
rejected the regnant analysis of voluntary behavior, which held that will
operates by reinstating “feelings of innervation” (Wundt) in the efferent
nerves. Deploying introspection and physiology, James showed that feelings of
innervation do not exist. James advanced ideo-motor action as the psychological
basis of volition: actions tend to occur automatically when thought, unless
inhibited by a contrary idea. Will consists in fixing attention on a identity,
‘is’ of ideo-motor action 416 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 416 desired
idea until it dominates consciousness, the execution of movement following
automatically. James also rejected Bain’s associationist thesis that pleasure
or pain is the necessary spring of action, since according to ideo-motor theory
thought of an action by itself produces it. James’s analysis became dogma, but
was effectively attacked by psychologist E. L. Thorndike (1874– 1949), who
proposed in its place the behavioristic doctrine that ideas have no power to
cause behavior, and argued that belief in ideo-motor action amounted to belief
in sympathetic magic. Thus did will leave the vocabulary of psychology. See
also JAMES, VOLITION. T.H.L. idols of the cave. See BACON, FRANCIS. idols of
the marketplace. See BACON, FRANCIS. idols of the mind. See BACON, FRANCIS.
idols of the theater. See BACON, FRANCIS. idols of the tribe. See BACON,
FRANCIS. iff, an abbreviation for ‘if and only if’ that is used as if it were a
single propositional operator (connective). Another synonym for ‘iff’ is ‘just
in case’. The justification for treating ‘iff’ as if it were a single
propositional connective is that ‘P if and only if Q’ is elliptical for ‘P if
Q, and P only if Q’, and this assertion is logically equivalent to ‘P
biconditional Q’. See also BICONDITIONAL. R.W.B. ignoratio elenchi. See
INFORMAL FALLACY. Il’in, Ivan Aleksandrovich (1883–1954), Russian philosopher
and conservative legal and political theorist. He authored an important two-volume
commentary on Hegel (1918), plus extensive writings in ethics, political
theory, aesthetics, and spirituality. Exiled in 1922, he was known for his
passionate opposition to Bolshevism, his extensive proposals for rebuilding a
radically reformed Russian state, church, and society in a post-Communist
future, and his devout Russian Orthodox spirituality. He is widely regarded as
a master of Russian language and a penetrating interpreter of the history of
Russian culture. His collected works are currently being published in Moscow.
See also RUSSIAN PHILOSOPHY. P.T.G. illation. See INDUCTION. illative. See
INDUCTION. illative sense. See NEWMAN. illicit process of the major. See
SYLLOGISM. illicit process of the minor. See SYLLOGISM. illocutionary act. See
SPEECH ACT THEORY. illocutionary force. See PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE, SPEECH ACT
THEORY. illocutionary force potential. See SPEECH ACT THEORY. illusion,
argument from. See PERCEPTION. image theory of meaning. See MEANING. image
theory of memory. See MEMORY. imagination, the mental faculty sometimes thought
to encompass all acts of thinking about something novel, contrary to fact, or
not currently perceived; thus: “Imagine that Lincoln had not been
assassinated,” or “Use your imagination to create a new design for roller
skates.” ‘Imagination’ also denotes an important perception-like aspect of some
such thoughts, so that to imagine something is to bring to mind what it would
be like to perceive it. Philosophical theories of imagination must explain its
apparent intentionality: when we imagine, we always imagine something.
Imagination is always directed toward an object, even though the object may not
exist. Moreover, imagination, like perception, is often seen as involving
qualia, or special subjective properties that are sometimes thought to
discredit materialist, especially functionalist, theories of mind. The
intentionality of imagination and its perceptual character lead some theories
to equate imagination with “imaging”: being conscious of or perceiving a mental
image. However, because the ontological status of such images and the nature of
their properties are obscure, many philosophers have rejected mental images in
favor of an adverbial theory on which to imagine something red is best analyzed
as imagining “redly.” Such theories avoid the difficulties associated with
mental images, but must offer some other way to account for the apparent
intentionality of imagination as well as its perceptual character. Imagination,
in the hands of Husserl and Sartre, becomes a particularly apt subject for
phenomenology. It is also cited as a faculty that idols of the cave imagination
417 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 417 separates human thought from any
form of artificial intelligence. Finally, imagination often figures prominently
in debates about possibility, in that what is imaginable is often taken to be
coextensive with what is possible. See also CONCEIVABILITY, IDEA,
INTENTIONALITY, PERCEPTION, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. L.-M.R. imaging. See
IMAGINATION. immanence, a term most often used in contrast to ‘transcendence’
to express the way in which God is thought to be present in the world. The most
extreme form of immanence is expressed in pantheism, which identifies God’s
substance either partly or wholly with the world. In contrast to pantheism,
Judaism and Christianity hold God to be a totally separate substance from the
world. In Christianity, the separateness of God’s substance from that of the
world is guaranteed by the doctrine of creation ex nihilo. Aquinas held that God
is in the world as an efficient cause is present to that on which it acts.
Thus, God is present in the world by continuously acting on it to preserve it
in existence. Perhaps the weakest notion of immanence is expressed in
eighteenth- and nineteenthcentury deism, in which God initially creates the
world and institutes its universal laws, but is basically an absentee landlord,
exercising no providential activity over its continuing history. See also
DEISM, NATURAL RELIGION, PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION, TRANSCENDENCE. W.L.R. immanent
causation. See AGENT CAUSATION. immaterial. See DISEMBODIMENT. immaterialism,
the view that objects are best characterized as mere collections of qualities:
“a certain colour, taste, smell, figure and consistence having been observed to
go together, are accounted one distinct thing, signified by the name apple”
(Berkeley, Principles, 1). So construed, immaterialism anticipates by some two
hundred years a doctrine defended in the early twentieth century by Russell.
The negative side of the doctrine comes in the denial of material substance or
matter. Some philosophers had held that ordinary objects are individual
material substances in which qualities inhere. The account is mistaken because,
according to immaterialism, there is no such thing as material substance, and
so qualities do not inhere in it. Immaterialism should not be confused with
Berkeley’s idealism. The latter, but not the former, implies that objects and
their qualities exist if and only if they are perceived. See also BERKELEY,
IDEALISM, PHENOMENALISM. G.S.P. immediacy, presence to the mind without
intermediaries. The term ‘immediate’ and its cognates have been used
extensively throughout the history of philosophy, generally without much
explanation. Descartes, e.g., explains his notion of thought thus: “I use this
term to include everything that is within us in a way that we are immediately
aware of it” (Second Replies). He offers no explanation of immediate awareness.
However, when used as a primitive in this way, the term may simply mean that
thoughts are the immediate objects of perception because thoughts are the only
things perceived in the strict and proper sense that no perception of an
intermediary is required for the person’s awareness of them. Sometimes ‘immediate’
means ‘not mediated’. (1) An inference from a premise to a conclusion can
exhibit logical immediacy because it does not depend on other premises. This is
a technical usage of proof theory to describe the form of a certain class of
inference rules. (2) A concept can exhibit conceptual immediacy because it is
definitionally primitive, as in the Berkeleian doctrine that perception of
qualities is immediate, and perception of objects is defined by the perception
of their qualities, which is directly understood. (3) Our perception of
something can exhibit causal immediacy because it is not caused by intervening
acts of perception or cognition, as with seeing someone immediately in the
flesh rather than through images on a movie screen. (4) A belief-formation process
can possess psychological immediacy because it contains no subprocess of
reasoning and in that sense has no psychological mediator. (5) Our knowledge of
something can exhibit epistemic immediacy because it is justified without
inference from another proposition, as in intuitive knowledge of the existence
of the self, which has no epistemic mediator. A noteworthy special application
of immediacy is to be found in Russell’s notion of knowledge by acquaintance.
This notion is a development of the venerable doctrine originating with Plato,
and also found in Augustine, that understanding the nature of some object
requires that we can gain immediate cognitive access to that object. Thus, for
Plato, to understand the nature imaging immediacy 418 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999
7:39 AM Page 418 of beauty requires acquaintance with beauty itself. This view
contrasts with one in which understanding the nature of beauty requires
linguistic competence in the use of the word ‘beauty’ or, alternatively, with
one that requires having a mental representation of beauty. Russell offers
sense-data and universals as examples of things known by acquaintance. To these
senses of immediacy we may add another category whose members have acquired
special meanings within certain philosophical traditions. For example, in
Hegel’s philosophy if (per impossibile) an object were encountered “as existing
in simple immediacy” it would be encountered as it is in itself, unchanged by
conceptualization. In phenomenology “immediate” experience is, roughly,
bracketed experience. See also BERKELEY, EPISTEMOLOGY, IDEA, INFERENTIAL
KNOWLEDGE, PERCEPTION, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. T.V. immediate inference. See
INFERENCE. immortality. See DISEMBODIMENT, SOUL. impartiality, a state or
disposition achieved to the degree that one’s actions or attitudes are not
influenced in a relevant respect by which members of a relevant group are
benefited or harmed by one’s actions or by the object of one’s attitudes. For
example, a basketball referee and that referee’s calls are impartial when the
referee’s applications of the rules are not affected by whether the calls help
one team or the other. A fan’s approval of a call lacks impartiality if that
attitude results from the fan’s preference for one team over the other. Impartiality
in this general sense does not exclude arbitrariness or guarantee fairness; nor
does it require neutrality among values, for a judge can be impartial between
parties while favoring liberty and equality for all. Different situations might
call for impartiality in different respects toward different groups, so
disagreements arise, for example, about when morality requires or allows
partiality toward friends or family or country. Moral philosophers have
proposed various tests of the kind of impartiality required by morality,
including role reversibility (Kurt Baier), universalizability (Hare), a veil of
ignorance (Rawls), and a restriction to beliefs shared by all rational people
(Bernard Gert). See also ETHICS, HARE, RAWLS, UNIVERSALIZABILITY. W.S.-A. imperative,
categorical. See KANT. imperative, hypothetical. See KANT. imperfect duty. See
DUTY, KANT. imperfect rights. See GROTIUS. implication, a relation that holds
between two statements when the truth of the first ensures the truth of the
second. A number of statements together imply Q if their joint truth ensures
the truth of Q. An argument is deductively valid exactly when its premises
imply its conclusion. Expressions of the following forms are often interchanged
one for the other: ‘P implies Q’, ‘Q follows from P’, and ‘P entails Q’.
(‘Entailment’ also has a more restricted meaning.) In ordinary discourse,
‘implication’ has wider meanings that are important for understanding reasoning
and communication of all kinds. The sentence ‘Last Tuesday, the editor remained
sober throughout lunch’ does not imply that the editor is not always sober. But
one who asserted the sentence typically would imply this. The theory of
conversational implicature explains how speakers often imply more than their
sentences imply. The term ‘implication’ also applies to conditional statements.
A material implication of the form ‘if P, then Q’ (often symbolized ‘P P Q’ or
‘P / Q’) is true so long as either the if-clause P is false or the main clause
Q is true; it is false only if P is true and Q is false. A strict implication
of the form ‘if P, then Q’ (often symbolized ‘P Q’) is true exactly when the
corresponding material implication is necessarily true; i.e., when it is
impossible for P to be true when Q is false. The following valid forms of
argument are called paradoxes of material implication: Q. Therefore, P / Q.
Not-P. Therefore, P / Q. The appearance of paradox here is due to using
‘implication’ as a name both for a relation between statements and for
statements of conditional form. A conditional statement can be true even though
there is no relation between its components. Consider the following valid
inference: Butter floats in milk. Therefore, fish sleep at night / butter
floats in milk. Since the simple premise is true, the conditional conclusion is
also true despite the fact that the nocturnal activities of fish and the
comparative densities of milk and butter are completely unreimmediate inference
implication 419 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 419 lated. The statement
‘Fish sleep at night’ does not imply that butter floats in milk. It is better
to call a conditional statement that is true just so long as it does not have a
true if-clause and a false main clause a material conditional rather than a
material implication. Strict conditional is similarly preferable to ‘strict
implication’. Respecting this distinction, however, does not dissolve all the
puzzlement of the so-called paradoxes of strict implication: Necessarily Q.
Therefore, P Q. Impossible that P. Therefore, P Q. Here is an example of the
first pattern: Necessarily, all rectangles are rectangles. Therefore, fish
sleep at night all rectangles are rectangles. ‘All rectangles are rectangles’
is an example of a vacuous truth, so called because it is devoid of content.
‘All squares are rectangles’ and ‘5 is greater than 3’ are not so obviously
vacuous truths, although they are necessary truths. Vacuity is not a sharply
defined notion. Here is an example of the second pattern: It is impossible that
butter always floats in milk yet sometimes does not float in milk. Therefore,
butter always floats in milk yet sometimes does not float in milk fish sleep at
night. Does the if-clause of the conclusion imply (or entail) the main clause?
On one hand, what butter does in milk is, as before, irrelevant to whether fish
sleep at night. On this ground, relevance logic denies there is a relation of
implication or entailment. On the other hand, it is impossible for the
if-clause to be true when the main clause is false, because it is impossible
for the if-clause to be true in any circumstances whatever. See also
COUNTERFACTUALS, FORMAL LOGIC, IMPLICATURE, PRESUPPOSITION, RELEVANCE LOGIC.
D.H.S. implication, paradoxes of. See IMPLICATION. implication, strict. See
IMPLICATION. implicature, a pragmatic relation different from, but easily
confused with, the semantic relation of entailment. This concept was first
identified, explained, and used by H. P. Grice (Studies in the Way of Words,
1989). Grice identified two main types of implicature, conventional and
conversational. A speaker is said to conversationally implicate a proposition P
in uttering a given sentence, provided that, although P is not logically
implied by what the speaker says, the assumption that the speaker is attempting
cooperative communication warrants inferring that the speaker believes p. If B
says, “There is a garage around the corner” in response to A’s saying, “I am
out of gas,” B conversationally implicates that the garage is open and has gas
to sell. Grice identifies several conversational maxims to which cooperative
speakers may be expected to conform, and which justify inferences about
speakers’ implicatures. In the above example, the implicatures are due to the
Maxim of Relevance. Another important maxim is that of Quantity (“Make your
contribution as informative as is required”). Among implicatures due to the
Maxim of Quantity are scalar implicatures, wherein the sentence uttered
contains an element that is part of a quantitative scale. Utterance of such a
sentence conversationally implicates that the speaker does not believe related
propositions higher on the scale of informativeness. For instance, speakers who
say, “Some of the zoo animals escaped,” implicate that they do not believe that
most of the zoo animals escaped, or that all of the zoo animals escaped. Unlike
conversational implicatures, conventional implicatures are due solely to the
meaning of the sentence uttered. A sentence utterance is said by Grice to
conventionally implicate a proposition, p, if the meaning of the sentence
commits the speaker to p, even though what the sentence says does not entail p.
Thus, uttering “She was poor but she was honest” implicates, but does not say,
that there is a contrast between poverty and honesty. See also PRESUPPOSITION.
M.M. implicit definition. See BETH’s DEFINABILITY THEOREM, DEFINITION.
imposition, a property of terms resulting from a linguistic convention to
designate something. Terms are not mere noises but significant sounds. Those
designating extralinguistic entities, such as ‘tree’, ‘stone’, ‘blue’, and the
like, were classified by the tradition since Boethius as terms of first
imposition; those designating other terms or other linguistic items, such as
‘noun’, ‘declension’, and the like, were classified as terms of second
imposition. The distinction between terms of first and second imposition
belongs to the realm of written and spoken language, while the parallel
distinction between terms of first and second implication, paradoxes of
imposition 420 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 420 intention belongs to the
realm of mental language: first intentions are, broadly, thoughts about trees,
stones, colors, etc.; second intentions are thoughts about first intentions.
See also INTENTIONALITY, METALANGUAGE. I.Bo. impredicative definition, the
definition of a concept in terms of the totality to which it belongs. Russell,
in the second (1925) edition of Principia Mathematica, introduced the term
‘impredicative’, prohibiting this kind of definition from the conceptual
foundations of mathematics, on the grounds that they imply formal logical
paradoxes. The impredicative definition of the set R of all sets that are not
members of themselves in Russell’s paradox leads to the self-contradictory
conclusion that R is a member of itself if and only if it is not a member of
itself. To avoid antinomies of this kind in the formalization of logic, Russell
first implemented in his ramified type theory the vicious circle principle,
that no whole may contain parts that are definable only in terms of that whole.
The limitation of ramified type theory is that without use of impredicative
definitions it is impossible to quantify over all mathematical objects, but
only over all mathematical objects of a certain order or type. Without being
able to quantify over all real numbers generally, many of the most important
definitions and theorems of classical real number theory cannot be formulated.
Russell for this reason later abandoned ramified in favor of simple type
theory, which avoids the logical paradoxes without outlawing impredicative
definition by forbidding the predication of terms of any type (object, property
and relation, higher-order properties and relations of properties and
relations, etc.) to terms of the same type. See also DEFINITION, PHILOSOPHY OF
MATHEMATICS, QUANTIFICATION, SET-THEORETIC PARADOXES, TYPE THEORY. D.J.
impredicative property. See TYPE THEORY. impression. See HUME. improper symbol.
See SYNCATEGOREMATA. inclusive disjunction. See DISJUNCTIVE PROPOSITION. incoherence,
self-referential. See SELF-REFERENTIAL INCOHERENCE. incommensurability, in the
philosophy of science, the property exhibited by two scientific theories
provided that, even though they may not logically contradict one another, they
have reference to no common body of data. Positivist and logical empiricist
philosophers of science like Carnap had long sought an adequate account of a
theoryneutral language to serve as the basis for testing competing theories.
The predicates of this language were thought to refer to observables; the
observation language described the observable world or (in the case of
theoretical terms) could do so in principle. This view is alleged to suffer
from two major defects. First, observation is infected with theory – what else
could specify the meanings of observation terms except the relevant theory?
Even to perceive is to interpret, to conceptualize, what is perceived. And what
about observations made by instruments? Are these not completely constrained by
theory? Second, studies by Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend, and others argued that in
periods of revolutionary change in science the adoption of a new theory
includes acceptance of a completely new conceptual scheme that is
incommensurable with the older, now rejected, theory. The two theories are
incommensurable because their constituent terms cannot have reference to a
theory-neutral set of observations; there is no overlap of observational
meaning between the competitor theories; even the data to be explained are
different. Thus, when Galileo overthrew the physics of Aristotle he replaced
his conceptual scheme – his “paradigm” – with one that is not logically
incompatible with Aristotle’s, but is incommensurable with it because in a
sense it is about a different world (or the world conceived entirely
differently). Aristotle’s account of the motion of bodies relied upon occult
qualities like natural tendencies; Galileo’s relied heavily upon contrived
experimental situations in which variable factors could be mathematically
calculated. Feyerabend’s even more radical view is that unless scientists
introduce new theories incommensurable with older ones, science cannot possibly
progress, because falsehoods will never be uncovered. It is an important
implication of these views about incommensurability that acceptance of theories
has to do not only with observable evidence, but also with subjective factors,
social pressures, and expectations of the scientific community. Such acceptance
appears to threaten the very possibility of developing a coherent methodology
for science. See also PARADIGM, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, THEORETICAL TERM. R.E.B.
incompatibilism. See FREE WILL PROBLEM. impredicative definition
incompatibilism 421 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 421 incompleteness. See
COMPLETENESS. incompleteness theorem. See GöDEL’s INCOMPLETENESS THEOREMS.
incomplete symbol. See LOGICAL CONSTRUCTION, RUSSELL, SYNCATEGOREMATA, THEORY
OF DESCRIPTIONS. incompossible. See COMPOSSIBLE. inconsistent triad, (1) most
generally, any three propositions such that it cannot be the case that all
three of them are true; (2) more narrowly, any three categorical propositions
such that it cannot be the case that all three of them are true. A categorical
syllogism is valid provided the three propositions that are its two premises
and the negation (contradiction) of its conclusion are an inconsistent triad;
this fact underlies various tests for the validity of categorical syllogisms,
which tests are often called “methods of” inconsistent triads. See also ANTILOGISM,
SYLLOGISM. R.W.B. incontinence. See AKRASIA. incorrigibility. See PRIVILEGED
ACCESS. indenumerable. See INFINITY. independence. See DEPENDENCE.
independence, logical. See INDEPENDENCE RESULTS. independence, probabilistic.
See PROBABILITY. independence, statistical. See PROBABILITY. independence
results, proofs of non-deducibility. Any of the following equivalent conditions
may be called independence: (1) A is not deducible from B; (2) its negation - A
is consistent with B; (3) there is a model of B that is not a model of A; e.g.,
the question of the non-deducibility of the parallel axiom from the other
Euclidean axioms is equivalent to that of the consistency of its negation with
them, i.e. of non-Euclidean geometry. Independence results may be not absolute
but relative, of the form: if B is consistent (or has a model), then B together
with - A is (or does); e.g. models of non-Euclidean geometry are built within
Euclidean geometry. In another sense, a set B is said to be independent if it
is irredundant, i.e., each hypothesis in B is independent of the others; in yet
another sense, A is said to be independent of B if it is undecidable by B,
i.e., both independent of and consistent with B. The incompleteness theorems of
Gödel are independence results, prototypes for many further proofs of
undecidability by subsystems of classical mathematics, or by classical
mathematics as a whole, as formalized in ZermeloFraenkel set theory with the
axiom of choice (ZF ! AC or ZFC). Most famous is the undecidability of the continuum
hypothesis, proved consistent relative to ZFC by Gödel, using his method of
constructible sets, and independent relative to ZFC by Paul J. Cohen, using his
method of forcing. Rather than build models from scratch by such methods,
independence (consistency) for A can also be established by showing A implies
(is implied by ) some A* already known independent (consistent). Many suitable
A* (Jensen’s Diamond, Martin’s Axiom, etc.) are now available. Philosophically,
formalism takes A’s undecidability by ZFC to show the question of A’s truth
meaningless; Platonism takes it to establish the need for new axioms, such as
those of large cardinals. (Considerations related to the incompleteness
theorems show that there is no hope even of a relative consistency proof for
these axioms, yet they imply, by way of determinacy axioms, many important
consequences about real numbers that are independent of ZFC.) With
non-classical logics, e.g. second-order logic, (1)–(3) above may not be
equivalent, so several senses of independence become distinguishable. The
question of independence of one axiom from others may be raised also for
formalizations of logic itself, where many-valued logics provide models. See
also FORCING, GÖDEL’s INCOMPLETENESS THEOREMS, SET THEORY. J.Bur. indeterminacy
argument. See SKEPTICISM. indeterminacy of translation, a pair of theses
derived, originally, from a thought experiment regarding radical translation
first propounded by Quine in Word and Object (1960) and developed in his
Ontological Relativity (1969), Theories and Things (1981), and Pursuit of Truth
(1990). Radical translation is an imaginary context in which a field linguist
is faced with the challenge of translating a hitherto unknown language.
Furthermore, it is stipulated that the linguist has no access to bilinguals and
that the language to be translated is historically unrelated to that of the
linguist. Presumably, the only data the linguist has to go on are the
observable behaviors of incompleteness indeterminacy of translation 422 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 422 native speakers amid the publicly observable
objects of their environment. (1) The strong thesis of indeterminacy,
indeterminacy of translation of theoretical sentences as wholes, is the claim
that in the context of radical translation a linguist (or linguists) could
construct a number of manuals for translating the (natives’) source language
into the (linguists’) target language such that each manual could be consistent
with all possible behavior data and yet the manuals could diverge with one
another in countless places in assigning different target-language sentences
(holophrastically construed) as translations of the same source-language
sentences (holophrastically construed), diverge even to the point where the sentences
assigned have conflicting truth-values; and no further data, physical or
mental, could single out one such translation manual as being the uniquely
correct one. All such manuals, which are consistent with all the possible
behavioral data, are correct. (2) The weak thesis of indeterminacy,
indeterminacy of reference (or inscrutability of reference), is the claim that
given all possible behavior data, divergent target-language interpretations of
words within a source-language sentence could offset one another so as to
sustain different targetlanguage translations of the same source-language
sentence; and no further data, physical or mental, could single out one such
interpretation as the uniquely correct one. All such interpretations, which are
consistent with all the possible behavioral data, are correct. This weaker sort
of indeterminacy takes two forms: an ontic form and a syntactic form. Quine’s
famous example where the source-language term ‘gavagai’ could be construed
either as ‘rabbit’, ‘undetached rabbit part’, ‘rabbithood’, etc. (see Word and
Object), and his proxy function argument where different ontologies could be
mapped onto one another (see Ontological Relativity, Theories and Things, and
Pursuit of Truth), both exemplify the ontic form of indeterminacy of reference.
On the other hand, his example of the Japanese classifier, where a particular
three-word construction of Japanese can be translated into English such that
the third word of the construction can be construed with equal justification
either as a term of divided reference or as a mass term (see Ontological
Relativity and Pursuit of Truth), exemplifies the syntactic form of
indeterminacy of reference. See also MEANING, PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE,
PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. R.F.G. indeterminacy principle. See QUANTUM MECHANICS.
indeterminate. See VAGUENESS. index. See PEIRCE. indexical, a type of
expression whose semantic value is in part determined by features of the
context of utterance, and hence may vary with that context. Among indexicals are
the personal pronouns, such as ‘I’, ‘you’, ‘he’, ‘she’, and ‘it’;
demonstratives, such as ‘this’ and ‘that’; temporal expressions, such as ‘now’,
‘today’, ‘yesterday’; and locative expressions, such as ‘here’, ‘there’, etc.
Although classical logic ignored indexicality, many recent practitioners,
following Richard Montague, have provided rigorous theories of indexicals in
the context of formal semantics. Perhaps the most plausible and thorough
treatment of indexicals is by David Kaplan (b.1933; a prominent American
philosopher of language and logic whose long-unpublished “Demonstratives” was
especially influential; it eventually appeared in J. Almog, J. Perry, and H.
Wettstein, eds., Themes from Kaplan, 1988). Kaplan argues persuasively that
indexical singular terms are directly referential and a species of rigid
designator. He also forcefully brings out a crucial lesson to be learned from
indexicals, namely, that there are two types of meaning, which Kaplan calls
“content” and “character.” A sentence containing an indexical, such as ‘I am
hungry’, can be used to say different things in different contexts, in part
because of the different semantic contributions made by ‘I’ in these contexts.
Kaplan calls a term’s contribution to what is said in a context the term’s
content. Though the content of an indexical like ‘I’ varies with its context,
it will nevertheless have a single meaning in the language, which Kaplan calls
the indexical’s character. This character may be conceived as a rule of
function that assigns different contents to the indexical in different
contexts. See also PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE, TOKEN-REFLEXIVE. M.M. Indian
philosophy. See BUDDHISM, HINDUISM, JAINISM. indicator, logical. See LOGICAL
INDICATOR. indicator word. See LOGICAL INDICATOR. indifference, liberty of. See
FREE WILL PROBLEM, HUME. indifference, principle of. See PRINCIPLE OF
INDIFFERENCE. indeterminacy principle indifference, principle of 423
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 423 indirect consequentialism. See BUTLER.
indirect discourse, also called oratio obliqua, the use of words to report what
others say, but without direct quotation. When one says “John said, ‘Not every
doctor is honest,’ “ one uses the words in one’s quotation directly – one uses
direct discourseto make an assertion about what John said. Accurate direct
discourse must get the exact words. But in indirect discourse one can use other
words than John does to report what he said, e.g., “John said that some
physicians are not honest.” The words quoted here capture the sense of John’s
assertion (the proposition he asserted). By extension, ‘indirect discourse’
designates the use of words in reporting beliefs. One uses words to
characterize the proposition believed rather than to make a direct assertion.
When Alice says, “John believes that some doctors are not honest,” she uses the
words ‘some doctors are not honest’ to present the proposition that John
believes. She does not assert the proposition. By contrast, direct discourse,
also called oratio recta, is the ordinary use of words to make assertions. See
also INTENSIONALITY, QUANTIFYING IN, REFERENTIALLY TRANSPARENT. T.M. indirect
intention. See INTENTION. indirect knowledge. See BASING RELATION. indirect
passions. See HUME. indirect proof. See REDUCTIO AD ABSURDUM. indirect sense.
See OBLIQUE CONTEXT. indirect speech act. See SPEECH ACT THEORY.
indiscernibility of identicals, the principle that if A and B are identical,
there is no difference between A and B: everything true of A is true of B, and
everything true of B is true of A; A and B have just the same properties; there
is no property such that A has it while B lacks it, or B has it while A lacks
it. A tempting formulation of this principle, ‘Any two things that are
identical have all their properties in common’, verges on nonsense; for two
things are never identical. ‘A is numerically identical with B’ means that A
and B are one and the same. A and B have just the same properties because A,
that is, B, has just the properties that it has. This principle is sometimes
called Leibniz’s law. It should be distinguished from its converse, Leibniz’s
more controversial principle of the identity of indiscernibles. A contraposed
form of the indiscernibility of identicals – call it the distinctness of
discernibles – reveals its point in philosophic dialectic. If something is true
of A that is not true of B, or (to say the same thing differently) if something
is true of B that is not true of A, then A and B are not identical; they are
distinct. One uses this principle to attack identity claims. Classical
arguments for dualism attempt to find something true of the mind that is not
true of anything physical. For example, the mind, unlike everything physical,
is indivisible. Also, the existence of the mind, unlike the existence of everything
physical, cannot be doubted. This last argument shows that the distinctness of
discernibles requires great care of application in intentional contexts. See
also IDENTITY, INTENSIONALITY. D.H.S. individual. See METAPHYSICS.
individualism. See POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. individualism, descriptive. See
HOLISM. individualism, methodological. See METHODOLOGICAL HOLISM.
individuation, (1) in metaphysics, a process whereby a universal, e.g., cat,
becomes instantiated in an individual – also called a particular e.g., Minina;
(2) in epistemology, a process whereby a knower discerns an individual, e.g.,
someone discerns Minina. The double understanding of individuation raises two
distinct problems: identifying the causes of metaphysical individuation, and of
epistemological individuation. In both cases the causes are referred to as the
principle of individuation. Attempts to settle the metaphysical and
epistemological problems of individuation presuppose an understanding of the
nature of individuality. Individuality has been variously interpreted as
involving one or more of the following: indivisibility, difference, division
within a species, identity through time, impredicability, and
non-instantiability. In general, theories of individuation try to account variously
for one or more of these. Individuation may apply to both substances (e.g.,
Minina) and their features (e.g., Minina’s fur color), generating two different
sorts of theories. The theories of the metaphysical individuation of substances
most often proposed identify six types of principles: a bundle of features
(Russell); space indirect consequentialism individuation 424 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 424 and/or time (Boethius); matter (Aristotle); form
(Averroes); a decharacterized, sui generis component called bare particular
(Bergmann) or haecceity (Duns Scotus); and existence (Avicenna). Sometimes
several principles are combined. For example, for Aquinas the principle of
individuation is matter under dimensions (materia signata). Two sorts of objections
are often brought against these views of the metaphysical individuation of
substances. One points out that some of these theories violate the principle of
acquaintance,since they identify as individuators entities for which there is
no empirical evidence. The second argues that some of these theories explain
the individuation of substances in terms of accidents, thus contradicting the
ontological precedence of substance over accident. The two most common theories
of the epistemological individuation of substances identify spatiotemporal
location and/or the features of substances as their individuators; we know a
thing as an individual by its location in space and time or by its features.
The objections that are brought to bear against these theories are generally
based on the ineffectiveness of those principles in all situations to account
for the discernment of all types of individuals. The theories of the
metaphysical individuation of the features of substances fall into two groups.
Some identify the substance itself as the principle of individuation; others
identify some feature(s) of the substance as individuator(s). Most accounts of
the epistemological individuation of the features of substances are similar to
these views. The most common objections to the metaphysical theories of the
individuation of features attempt to show that these theories are either
incomplete or circular. It is argued, e.g., that an account of the
individuation of features in terms of substance is incomplete because the individuation
of the substance must also be accounted for: How would one know what tree one
sees, apart from its features? However, if the substance is individuated by its
features, one falls into a vicious circle. Similar points are made with respect
to the epistemological theories of the individuation of features. Apart from
the views mentioned, some philosophers hold that individuals are individual
essentially (per se), and therefore that they do not undergo individuation.
Under those conditions either there is no need for a metaphysical principle of
individuation (Ockham), or else the principle of individuation is identified as
the individual entity itself (Suárez). See also BUNDLE THEORY, IDENTITY,
METAPHYSICS, PRINCIPIUM INDIVIDUATIONIS. J.J.E.G. indubitability. See
PRIVILEGED ACCESS. induction, (1) in the narrow sense, inference to a
generalization from its instances; (2) in the broad sense, any ampliative
inference – i.e., any inference where the claim made by the conclusion goes
beyond the claim jointly made by the premises. Induction in the broad sense
includes, as cases of particular interest: argument by analogy, predictive
inference, inference to causes from signs and symptoms, and confirmation of
scientific laws and theories. The narrow sense covers one extreme case that is
not ampliative. That is the case of mathematical induction, where the premises
of the argument necessarily imply the generalization that is its conclusion.
Inductive logic can be conceived most generally as the theory of the evaluation
of ampliative inference. In this sense, much of probability theory, theoretical
statistics, and the theory of computability are parts of inductive logic. In
addition, studies of scientific method can be seen as addressing in a less
formal way the question of the logic of inductive inference. The name
‘inductive logic’ has also, however, become associated with a specific approach
to these issues deriving from the work of Bayes, Laplace, De Morgan, and
Carnap. On this approach, one’s prior probabilities in a state of ignorance are
determined or constrained by some principle for the quantification of ignorance
and one learns by conditioning on the evidence. A recurrent difficulty with
this line of attack is that the way in which ignorance is quantified depends on
how the problem is described, with different logically equivalent descriptions
leading to different prior probabilities. Carnap laid down as a postulate for
the application of his inductive logic that one should always condition on
one’s total evidence. This rule of total evidence is usually taken for granted,
but what justification is there for it? Good pointed out that the standard
Bayesian analysis of the expected value of new information provides such a
justification. Pure cost-free information always has non-negative expected
value, and if there is positive probability that it will affect a decision, its
expected value is positive. Ramsey made the same point in an unpublished
manuscript. The proof generalizes to various models of learning uncertain
evidence. A deductive account is sometimes presented indubitability induction
425 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 425 where induction proceeds by
elimination of possibilities that would make the conclusion false. Thus Mill’s
methods of experimental inquiry are sometimes analyzed as proceeding by
elimination of alternative possibilities. In a more general setting, the
hypothetico-deductive account of science holds that theories are confirmed by
their observational consequences – i.e., by elimination of the possibilities
that this experiment or that observation falsifies the theory. Induction by
elimination is sometimes put forth as an alternative to probabilistic accounts
of induction, but at least one version of it is consistent with – and indeed a consequence
of – probabilistic accounts. It is an elementary fact of probability that if F,
the potential falsifier, is inconsistent with T and both have probability
strictly between 0 and 1, then the probability of T conditional on not-F is
higher than the unconditional probability of T. In a certain sense, inductive
support of a universal generalization by its instances may be a special case of
the foregoing, but this point must be treated with some care. In the first
place, the universal generalization must have positive prior probability. (It
is worth noting that Carnap’s systems of inductive logic do not satisfy this
condition, although systems of Hintikka and Niiniluoto do.) In the second
place, the notion of instance must be construed so the “instances” of a
universal generalization are in fact logical consequences of it. Thus ‘If A is
a swan then A is white’ is an instance of ‘All swans are white’ in the
appropriate sense, but ‘A is a white swan’ is not. The latter statement is
logically stronger than ‘If A is a swan then A is white’ and a complete report
on species, weight, color, sex, etc., of individual A would be stronger still.
Such statements are not logical consequences of the universal generalization,
and the theorem does not hold for them. For example, the report of a man 7 feet
11¾ inches tall might actually reduce the probability of the generalization
that all men are under 8 feet tall. Residual queasiness about the foregoing may
be dispelled by a point made by Carnap apropos of Hempel’s discussion of
paradoxes of confirmation. ‘Confirmation’ is ambiguous. ‘E confirms H’ may mean
that the probability of H conditional on E is greater than the unconditional
probability of H, in which case deductive consequences of H confirm H under the
conditions set forth above. Or ‘E confirms H’ may mean that the probability of
H conditional on E is high (e.g., greater than .95), in which case if E
confirms H, then E confirms every logical consequence of H. Conflation of the
two senses can lead one to the paradoxical conclusion that E confirms E & P
and thus P for any statement, P. See also CONFIRMATION, MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION,
MILL’s METHODS, PROBLEM OF INDUCTION. B.Sk. induction, eliminative. See
INDUCTION. induction, intuitive. See ROSS. induction, mathematical. See
MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION. induction, new riddle of. See GRUE PARADOX. induction,
problem of. See PROBLEM OF INDUCTION. inductive clause. See MATHEMATICAL
INDUCTION. inductive definition. See DEFINITION. inductive explanation. See
COVERING LAW MODEL. inductive justification. See JUSTIFICATION. inductive
probability. See PROBABILITY. inductivism, a philosophy of science invented by
Popper and P. K. Feyerabend as a foil for their own views. According to
inductivism, a unique a priori inductive logic enables one to construct an
algorithm that will compute from any input of data the best scientific theory
accounting for that data. See also ALGORITHM, DUHEM, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE.
B.Sk. infallibility. See PRIVILEGED ACCESS. inference, the process of drawing a
conclusion from premises or assumptions, or, loosely, the conclusion so drawn.
An argument can be merely a number of statements of which one is designated the
conclusion and the rest are designated premises. Whether the premises imply the
conclusion is thus independent of anyone’s actual beliefs in either of them.
Belief, however, is essential to inference. Inference occurs only if someone,
owing to believing the premises, begins to believe the conclusion or continues
to believe the conclusion with greater confidence than before. Because
inference requires a subject who has beliefs, some requirements of (an ideally)
acceptable inference do not apply to abstract arguments: one must believe the
premises; one must believe that the premises support the conclusion; neither of
these beliefs induction, eliminative inference 426 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39
AM Page 426 may be based on one’s prior belief in the conclusion. W. E. Johnson
called these the epistemic conditions of inference. In a reductio ad absurdum argument
that deduces a self-contradiction from certain premises, not all steps of the
argument will correspond to steps of inference. No one deliberately infers a
contradiction. What one infers, in such an argument, is that certain premises
are inconsistent. Acceptable inferences can fall short of being ideally
acceptable according to the above requirements. Relevant beliefs are sometimes
indefinite. Infants and children infer despite having no grasp of the
sophisticated notion of support. One function of idealization is to set
standards for that which falls short. It is possible to judge how nearly
inexplicit, automatic, unreflective, lessthan-ideal inferences meet ideal
requirements. In ordinary speech, ‘infer’ often functions as a synonym of
‘imply’, as in ‘The new tax law infers that we have to calculate the value of
our shrubbery’. Careful philosophical writing avoids this usage. Implication
is, and inference is not, a relation between statements. Valid deductive
inference corresponds to a valid deductive argument: it is logically impossible
for all the premises to be true when the conclusion is false. That is, the
conjunction of all the premises and the negation of the conclusion is
inconsistent. Whenever a conjunction is inconsistent, there is a valid argument
for the negation of any conjunct from the other conjuncts. (Relevance logic
imposes restrictions on validity to avoid this.) Whenever one argument is
deductively valid, so is another argument that goes in a different direction.
(1) ‘Stacy left her slippers in the kitchen’ implies (2) ‘Stacy had some
slippers’. Should one acquainted with Stacy and the kitchen infer (2) from (1),
or infer not-(1) from not-(2), or make neither inference? Formal logic tells us
about implication and deductive validity, but it cannot tell us when or what to
infer. Reasonable inference depends on comparative degrees of reasonable
belief. An inference in which every premise and every step is beyond question
is a demonstrative inference. (Similarly, reasoning for which this condition
holds is demonstrative reasoning.) Just as what is beyond question can vary
from one situation to another, so can what counts as demonstrative. The term
presumably derives from Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics. Understanding
Aristotle’s views on demonstration requires understanding his general scheme
for classifying inferences. Not all inferences are deductive. In an inductive
inference, one infers from an observed combination of characteristics to some
similar unobserved combination. ‘Reasoning’ like ‘painting’, and ‘frosting’,
and many other words, has a process–product ambiguity. Reasoning can be a
process that occurs in time or it can be a result or product. A letter to the
editor can both contain reasoning and be the result of reasoning. It is often
unclear whether a word such as ‘statistical’ that modifies the words
‘inference’ or ‘reasoning’ applies primarily to stages in the process or to the
content of the product. One view, attractive for its simplicity, is that the
stages of the process of reasoning correspond closely to the parts of the
product. Examples that confirm this view are scarce. Testing alternatives,
discarding and reviving, revising and transposing, and so on, are as common to
the process of reasoning as to other creative activities. A product seldom
reflects the exact history of its production. In An Examination of Sir William
Hamilton’s Philosophy, J. S. Mill says that reasoning is a source from which we
derive new truths (Chapter 14). This is a useful saying so long as we remember
that not all reasoning is inference. See also DEDUCTION, IMPLICATION,
INDUCTION. D.H.S. inference rule. See LOGISTIC SYSTEM. inference to the best
explanation, an inference by which one concludes that something is the case on
the grounds that this best explains something else one believes to be the case.
Paradigm examples of this kind of inference are found in the natural sciences,
where a hypothesis is accepted on the grounds that it best explains relevant
observations. For example, the hypothesis that material substances have atomic
structures best explains a range of observations concerning how such substances
interact. Inferences to the best explanation occur in everyday life as well.
Upon walking into your house you observe that a lamp is lying broken on the
floor, and on the basis of this you infer that the cat has knocked it over.
This is plausibly analyzed as an inference to the best explanation; you believe
that the cat has knocked over the lamp because this is the best explanation for
the lamp’s lying broken on the floor. The nature of inference to the best
explanation and the extent of its use are both controversial. Positions that
have been taken include: (a) that it is a distinctive kind of inductive
reasoning; (b) inference rule inference to the best explanation 427 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 427 that all good inductive inferences involve
inference to the best explanation; and (c) that it is not a distinctive kind of
inference at all, but is rather a special case of enumerative induction.
Another controversy concerns the criteria for what makes an explanation best.
Simplicity, cognitive fit, and explanatory power have all been suggested as
relevant merits, but none of these notions is well understood. Finally, a
skeptical problem arises: inference to the best explanation is plausibly
involved in both scientific and commonsense knowledge, but it is not clear why
the best explanation that occurs to a person is likely to be true. See also
ABDUCTION, EXPLANATION, INDUCTION, INFERENCE, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. J.G.
inferential justification. See FOUNDATIONALISM. inferential knowledge, a kind
of “indirect” knowledge, namely, knowledge based on or resulting from
inference. Assuming that knowledge is at least true, justified belief,
inferential knowledge is constituted by a belief that is justified because it
is inferred from certain other beliefs. The knowledge that 7 equals 7 seems
non-inferential. We do not infer from anything that 7 equals 7 – it is obvious
and self-evident. The knowledge that 7 is the cube root of 343, in contrast,
seems inferential. We cannot know this without inferring it from something
else, such as the result obtained when multiplying 7 times 7 times 7. Two sorts
of inferential relations may be distinguished. ‘I inferred that someone died
because the flag is at half-mast’ may be true because yesterday I acquired the
belief about the flag, which caused me to acquire the further belief that
someone died. ‘I inferentially believe that someone died because the flag is at
halfmast’ may be true now because I retain the belief that someone died and it
remains based on my belief about the flag. My belief that someone died is thus
either episodically or structurally inferential. The episodic process is an
occurrent, causal relation among belief acquisitions. The structural basing
relation may involve the retention of beliefs, and need not be occurrent. (Some
reserve ‘inference’ for the episodic relation.) An inferential belief acquired
on one basis may later be held on a different basis, as when I forget I saw a
flag at half-mast but continue to believe someone died because of news reports.
That “How do you know?” and “Prove it!” always seem pertinent suggests that all
knowledge is inferential, a version of the coherence theory. The well-known
regress argument seems to show, however, that not all knowledge can be
inferential, which is a version of foundationalism. For if S knows something
inferentially, S must infer it correctly from premises S knows to be true. The
question whether those premises are also known inferentially begins either an
infinite regress of inferences (which is humanly impossible) or a circle of
justification (which could not constitute good reasoning). Which sources of
knowledge are non-inferential remains an issue even assuming foundationalism.
When we see that an apple is red, e.g., our knowledge is based in some manner
on the way the apple looks. “How do you know it is red?” can be answered: “By
the way it looks.” This answer seems correct, moreover, only if an inference
from the way the apple looks to its being red would be warranted. Nevertheless,
perceptual beliefs are formed so automatically that talk of inference seems
inappropriate. In addition, inference as a process whereby beliefs are acquired
as a result of holding other beliefs may be distinguished from inference as a
state in which one belief is sustained on the basis of others. Knowledge that
is inferential in one way need not be inferential in the other. See also
FOUNDATIONALISM, INFERENCE, PRACTICAL REASONING. W.A.D. infima species (Latin,
‘lowest species’), a species that is not a genus of any other species.
According to the theory of classification, division, and definition that is
part of traditional or Aristotelian logic, every individual is a specimen of
some infima species. An infima species is a member of a genus that may in turn
be a species of a more inclusive genus, and so on, until one reaches a summum
genus, a genus that is not a species of a more inclusive genus. Socrates and
Plato are specimens of the infima specis human being (mortal rational animal),
which is a species of the genus rational animal, which is a species of the
genus animal, and so on, up to the summum genus substance. Whereas two
specimens of animal – e.g., an individual human and an individual horse – can
differ partly in their essential characteristics, no two specimens of the
infima species human being can differ in essence. See also ARISTOTLE,
ESSENTIALISM, GENUS GENERALISSIMUM, TREE OF PORPHYRY. W.E.M. infinitary logic, the
logic of expressions of infinite length. Quine has advanced the claim that
firstorder logic (FOL) is the language of science, a position accepted by many
of his followers. Howinferential justification infinitary logic 428 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 428 ever, many important notions of mathematics and
science are not expressible in FOL. The notion of finiteness, e.g., is central
in mathematics but cannot be expressed within FOL. There is no way to express
such a simple, precise claim as ‘There are only finitely many stars’ in FOL.
This and related expressive limitations in FOL seriously hamper its
applicability to the study of mathematics and have led to the study of stronger
logics. There have been various approaches to getting around the limitations by
the study of so-called strong logics, including second-order logic (where one
quantifies over sets or properties, not just individuals), generalized
quantifiers (where one adds quantifiers in addition to the usual ‘for all’ and
‘there exists’), and branching quantifiers (where notions of independence of
variables is introduced). One of the most fruitful methods has been the
introduction of idealized “infinitely long” statements. For example, the above
statement about the stars would be formalized as an infinite disjunction: there
is at most one star, or there are at most two stars, or there are at most three
stars, etc. Each of these disjuncts is expressible in FOL. The expressive
limitations in FOL are closely linked with Gödel’s famous completeness and
incompleteness theorems. These results show, among other things, that any
attempt to systematize the laws of logic is going to be inadequate, one way or
another. Either it will be confined to a language with expressive limitations,
so that these notions cannot even be expressed, or else, if they can be
expressed, then an attempt at giving an effective listing of axioms and rules
of inference for the language will fall short. In infinitary logic, the rules
of inference can have infinitely many premises, and so are not effectively
presentable. Early work in infinitary logic used cardinality as a guide:
whether or not a disjunction, conjunction, or quantifier string was permitted
had to do only with the cardinality of the set in question. It turned out that the
most fruitful of these logics was the language with countable conjunctions and
finite strings of first-order quantifiers. This language had further
refinements to socalled admissible languages, where more refined set-theoretic
considerations play a role in determining what counts as a formula. Infinitary
languages are also connected with strong axioms of infinity, statements that do
not follow from the usual axioms of set theory but for which one has other
evidence that they might well be true, or at least consistent. In particular,
compact cardinals are infinite cardinal numbers where the analogue of the
compactness theorem of FOL generalizes to the associated infinitary language.
These cardinals have proven to be very important in modern set theory. During
the 1990s, some infinitary logics played a surprising role in computer science.
By allowing arbitrarily long conjunctions and disjunctions, but only finitely
many variables (free or bound) in any formula, languages with attractive
closure properties were found that allowed the kinds of inductive procedures of
computer science, procedures not expressible in FOL. See also COMPACTNESS
THEOREM, COMPLETENESS, GÖDEL’S INCOMPLETENESS THEOREMS, INFINITY, SECOND-ORDER
LOGIC. J.Ba. infinite, actual. See ARISTOTLE. infinite analysis, doctrine of.
See LEIBNIZ. infinite regress argument, a distinctively philosophical kind of
argument purporting to show that a thesis is defective because it generates an
infinite series when either (form A) no such series exists or (form B) were it
to exist, the thesis would lack the role (e.g., of justification) that it is
supposed to play. The mere generation of an infinite series is not
objectionable. It is misleading therefore to use ‘infinite regress’ (or
‘regress’) and ‘infinite series’ equivalently. For instance, both of the
following claims generate an infinite series: (1) every natural number has a
successor that itself is a natural number, and (2) every event has a causal
predecessor that itself is an event. Yet (1) is true (arguably, necessarily
true), and (2) may be true for all that logic can say about the matter.
Likewise, there is nothing contrary to logic about any of the infinite series
generated by the suppositions that (3) every free act is the consequence of a
free act of choice; (4) every intelligent operation is the result of an
intelligent mental operation; (5) whenever individuals x and y share a property
F there exists a third individual z which paradigmatically has F and to which x
and y are somehow related (as copies, by participation, or whatnot); or (6)
every generalization from experience is inductively inferable from experience
by appeal to some other generalization from experience. What Locke (in the
Essay concerning Human Understanding) objects to about the theory of free will
embodied in (3) and Ryle (in The Concept of Mind) objects to about the
“intellectualist leginfinite, actual infinite regress argument 429 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 429 end” embodied in (4) can therefore be only that it
is just plain false as a matter of fact that we perform an infinite number of
acts of choice or operations of the requisite kinds. In effect their infinite
regress arguments are of form A: they argue that the theories concerned must be
rejected because they falsely imply that such infinite series exist. Arguably
the infinite regress arguments employed by Plato (in the Parmenides) regarding
his own theory of Forms and by Popper (in the Logic of Scientific Discovery)
regarding the principle of induction proposed by Mill, are best construed as
having form B, their objections being less to (5) or (6) than to their
epistemic versions: (5*) that we can understand how x and y can share a
property F only if we understand that there exists a third individual (the
“Form” z) which paradigmatically has F and to which x and y are related; and
(6*) that since the principle of induction must itself be a generalization from
experience, we are justified in accepting it only if it can be inferred from
experience by appeal to a higherorder, and justified, inductive principle. They
are arguing that because the series generated by (5) and (6) are infinite, the
epistemic enlightenment promised by (5*) and (6*) will forever elude us. When
successful, infinite regress arguments can show us that certain sorts of
explanation, understanding, or justification are will-o’-thewisps. As Passmore
has observed (in Philosophical Reasoning) there is an important sense of
‘explain’ in which it is impossible to explain predication. We cannot explain x’s
and y’s possession of the common property F by saying that they are called by
the same name (nominalism) or fall under the same concept (conceptualism) any
more than we can by saying that they are related to the same form (Platonic
realism), since each of these is itself a property that x and y are supposed to
have in common. Likewise, it makes no sense to try to explain why anything at
all exists by invoking the existence of something else (such as the theist’s
God). The general truths that things exist, and that things may have properties
in common, are “brute facts” about the way the world is. Some infinite regress
objections fail because they are directed at “straw men.” Bradley’s regress
argument against the pluralist’s “arrangement of given facts into relations and
qualities,” from which he concludes that monism is true, is a case in point. He
correctly argues that if one posits the existence of two or more things, then
there must be relations of some sort between them, and then (given his covert
assumption that these relations are things) concludes that there must be
further relations between these relations ad infinitum. Bradley’s regress
misfires because a pluralist would reject his assumption. Again, some regress
arguments fail because they presume that any infinite series is vicious.
Aquinas’s regress objection to an infinite series of movers, from which he
concludes that there must be a prime mover, involves this sort of confusion.
See also EPISTEMIC REGRESS ARGUMENT, INFINITY, VICIOUS REGRESS. R.D.B.
infinity, in set theory, the property of a set whereby it has a proper subset
whose members can be placed in one-to-one correspondence with all the members
of the set, as the even integers can be so arranged in respect to the natural
numbers by the function f(x) = x/2, namely: Devised by Richard Dedekind in
defiance of the age-old intuition that no part of a thing can be as large as
the thing, this set-theoretical definition of ‘infinity’, having been much
acclaimed by philosophers like Russell as a model of conceptual analysis that
philosophers were urged to emulate, can elucidate the putative infinity of
space, time, and even God, his power, wisdom, etc. If a set’s being denumerable
– i.e., capable of having its members placed in one-to-one correspondence with
the natural numbers – can well appear to define much more simply what the
infinity of an infinite set is, Cantor exhibited the real numbers (as expressed
by unending decimal expansions) as a counterexample, showing them to be
indenumerable by means of his famous diagonal argument. Suppose all the real
numbers between 0 and 1 are placed in one-to-one correspondence with the
natural numbers, thus: Going down the principal diagonal, we can construct a
new real number, e.g., .954 . . . , not found in the infinite “square array.”
The most important result in set theory, Cantor’s theorem, is denied its full
force by the maverick followers infinity infinity 430 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999
7:39 AM Page 430 of Skolem, who appeal to the fact that, though the real numbers
constructible in any standard axiomatic system will be indenumerable relative
to the resources of the system, they can be seen to be denumerable when viewed
from outside it. Refusing to accept the absolute indenumerability of any set,
the Skolemites, in relativizing the notion to some system, provide one further
instance of the allure of relativism. More radical still are the nominalists
who, rejecting all abstract entities and sets in particular, might be supposed
to have no use for Cantor’s theorem. Not so. Assume with Democritus that there
are infinitely many of his atoms, made of adamant. Corresponding to each
infinite subset of these atoms will be their mereological sum or “fusion,”
namely a certain quantity of adamant. Concrete entities acceptable to the
nominalist, these quantities can be readily shown to be indenumerable. Whether
Cantor’s still higher infinities beyond F1 admit of any such nominalistic
realization remains a largely unexplored area. Aleph-zero or F0 being taken to
be the transfinite number of the natural numbers, there are then F1 real
numbers (assuming the continuum hypothesis), while the power set of the reals
has F2 members, and the power set of that F3 members, etc. In general, K2 will
be said to have a greater number (finite or transfinite) of members than K1
provided the members of K1 can be put in one-to-one correspondence with some
proper subset of K2 but not vice versa. Skepticism regarding the higher
infinities can trickle down even to F0, and if both Aristotle and Kant, the
former in his critique of Zeno’s paradoxes, the latter in his treatment of
cosmological antinomies, reject any actual, i.e. completed, infinite, in our
time Dummett’s return to verificationism, as associated with the mathematical
intuitionism of Brouwer, poses the keenest challenge. Recognition-transcendent
sentences like ‘The total number of stars is infinite’ are charged with
violating the intersubjective conditions required for a speaker of a language
to manifest a grasp of their meaning. See also CONTINUUM PROBLEM, SET THEORY.
J.A.B. infinity, axiom of. See SET THEORY. informal fallacy, an error of
reasoning or tactic of argument that can be used to persuade someone with whom
you are reasoning that your argument is correct when really it is not. The
standard treatment of the informal fallacies in logic textbooks draws heavily
on Aristotle’s list, but there are many variants, and new fallacies have often
been added, some of which have gained strong footholds in the textbooks. The
word ‘informal’ indicates that these fallacies are not simply localized faults
or failures in the given propositions (premises and conclusion) of an argument
to conform to a standard of semantic correctness (like that of deductive
logic), but are misuses of the argument in relation to a context of reasoning
or type of dialogue that an arguer is supposed to be engaged in. Informal logic
is the subfield of logical inquiry that deals with these fallacies. Typically,
informal fallacies have a pragmatic (practical) aspect relating to how an
argument is being used, and also a dialectical aspect, pertaining to a context
of dialogue – normally an exchange between two participants in a discussion.
Both aspects are major concerns of informal logic. Logic textbooks classify
informal fallacies in various ways, but no clear and widely accepted system of
classification has yet become established. Some textbooks are very inventive
and prolific, citing many different fallacies, including novel and exotic ones.
Others are more conservative, sticking with the twenty or so mainly featured in
or derived from Aristotle’s original treatment, with a few widely accepted
additions. The paragraphs below cover most of these “major” or widely featured
fallacies, the ones most likely to be encountered by name in the language of
everyday educated conversation. The genetic fallacy is the error of drawing an
inappropriate conclusion about the goodness or badness of some property of a
thing from the goodness or badness of some property of the origin of that thing.
For example, ‘This medication was derived from a plant that is poisonous;
therefore, even though my physician advises me to take it, I conclude that it
would be very bad for me if I took it.’ The error is inappropriately arguing
from the origin of the medication to the conclusion that it must be poisonous
in any form or situation. The genetic fallacy is often construed very broadly
making it coextensive with the personal attack type of argument (see the
description of argumentum ad hominem below) that condemns a prior argument by
condemning its source or proponent. Argumentum ad populum (argument to the
people) is a kind of argument that uses appeal to popular sentiments to support
a conclusion. Sometimes called “appeal to the gallery” or “appeal to popular
pieties” or even “mob appeal,” this kind of argument has traditionally been
portrayed as fallacious. However, there infinity, axiom of informal fallacy 431
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 431 need be nothing wrong with appealing to
popular sentiments in argument, so long as their evidential value is not
exaggerated. Even so, such a tactic can be fallacious when the attempt to
arouse mass enthusiasms is used as a substitute to cover for a failure to bring
forward the kind of evidence that is properly required to support one’s
conclusion. Argumentum ad misericordiam (argument to pity) is a kind of
argument that uses an appeal to pity, sympathy, or compassion to support its
conclusion. Such arguments can have a legitimate place in some discussions –
e.g., in appeals for charitable donations. But they can also put emotional
pressure on a respondent in argument to try to cover up a weak case. For
example, a student who does not have a legitimate reason for a late assignment
might argue that if he doesn’t get a high grade, his disappointed mother might
have a heart attack. The fallacy of composition is the error of arguing from a
property of parts of a whole to a property of the whole – e.g., ‘The important
parts of this machine are light; therefore this machine is light.’ But a
property of the parts cannot always be transferred to the whole. In some cases,
examples of the fallacy of composition are arguments from all the parts to a
whole, e.g. ‘Everybody in the country pays her debts. Therefore the country pays
its debts.’ The fallacy of division is the converse of that of composition: the
error of arguing from a property of the whole to a property of its parts –
e.g., ‘This machine is heavy; therefore all the parts of this machine are
heavy.’ The problem is that the property possessed by the whole need not
transfer to the parts. The fallacy of false cause, sometimes called post hoc,
ergo propter hoc (after this, therefore because of this), is the error of
arguing that because two events are correlated with one another, especially
when they vary together, the one is the cause of the other. For example, there
might be a genuine correlation between the stork population in certain areas of
Europe and the human birth rate. But it would be an error to conclude, on that
basis alone, that the presence of storks causes babies to be born. In general,
however, correlation is good, if sometimes weak, evidence for causation. The
problem comes in when the evidential strength of the correlation is exaggerated
as causal evidence. The apparent connection could just be coincidence, or due
to other factors that have not been taken into account, e.g., some third factor
that causes both the events that are correlated with each other. The fallacy of
secundum quid (neglecting qualifications) occurs where someone is arguing from
a general rule to a particular case, or vice versa. One version of it is
arguing from a general rule while overlooking or suppressing legitimate
exceptions. This kind of error has also often been called the fallacy of
accident. An example would be the argument ‘Everyone has the right to freedom
of speech; therefore it is my right to shout “Fire” in this crowded theater if
I want to.’ The other version of secundum quid, sometimes also called the
fallacy of converse accident, or the fallacy of hasty generalization, is the
error of trying to argue from a particular case to a general rule that does not
properly fit that case. An example would be the argument ‘Tweetie [an ostrich]
is a bird that does not fly; therefore birds do not fly’. The fault is the
failure to recognize or acknowledge that Tweetie is not a typical bird with
respect to flying. Argumentum consensus gentium (argument from the consensus of
the nations) is a kind that appeals to the common consent of mankind to support
a conclusion. Numerous philosophers and theologians in the past have appealed
to this kind of argument to support conclusions like the existence of God and
the binding character of moral principles. For example, ‘Belief in God is
practically universal among human beings past and present; therefore there is a
practical weight of presumption in favor of the truth of the proposition that
God exists’. A version of the consensus gentium argument represented by this
example has sometimes been put forward in logic textbooks as an instance of the
argumentum ad populum (described above) called the argument from popularity:
‘Everybody believes (accepts) P as true; therefore P is true’. If interpreted
as applicable in all cases, the argument from popularity is not generally
sound, and may be regarded as a fallacy. However, if regarded as a presumptive
inference that only applies in some cases, and as subject to withdrawal where
evidence to the contrary exists, it can sometimes be regarded as a weak but plausible
argument, useful to serve as a provisional guide to prudent action or reasoned
commitment. Argumentum ad hominem (literally, argument against the man) is a
kind of argument that uses a personal attack against an arguer to refute her
argument. In the abusive or personal variant, the character of the arguer
(especially character for veracity) is attacked; e.g., ‘You can’t believe what
Smith says – he is a liar’. In evaluating testimony (e.g., in legal
cross-examination), attacking an arguer’s character can be legitimate in some
cases. Also in political debate, character can be a legitimate issue. However,
ad hominem arguinformal fallacy informal fallacy 432 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999
7:39 AM Page 432 ments are commonly used fallaciously in attacking an opponent
unfairly – e.g., where the attack is not merited, or where it is used to
distract an audience from more relevant lines of argument. In the
circumstantial variant, an arguer’s personal circumstances are claimed to be in
conflict with his argument, implying that the arguer is either confused or
insincere; e.g., ‘You don’t practice what you preach’. For example, a
politician who has once advocated not raising taxes may be accused of
“flip-flopping” if he himself subsequently favors legislation to raise taxes.
This type of argument is not inherently fallacious, but it can go badly wrong,
or be used in a fallacious way, for example if circumstances changed, or if the
alleged conflict was less serious than the attacker claimed. Another variant is
the “poisoning the well” type of ad hominem argument, where an arguer is said
to have shown no regard for the truth, the implication being that nothing he
says henceforth can ever be trusted as reliable. Yet another variant of the ad
hominem argument often cited in logic textbooks is the tu quoque (you-too
reply), where the arguer attacked by an ad hominem argument turns around and
says, “What about you? Haven’t you ever lied before? You’re just as bad.” Still
another variant is the bias type of ad hominem argument, where one party in an
argument charges the other with not being honest or impartial or with having
hidden motivations or personal interests at stake. Argumentum ad baculum
(argument to the club) is a kind of argument that appeals to a threat or to
fear in order to support a conclusion, or to intimidate a respondent into
accepting it. Ad baculum arguments often take an indirect form; e.g., ‘If you
don’t do this, harmful consequences to you might follow’. In such cases the
utterance can often be taken as a threat. Ad baculum arguments are not
inherently fallacious, because appeals to threatening or fearsome sanctions –
e.g., harsh penalties for drunken driving – are not necessarily failures of
critical argumentation. But because ad baculum arguments are powerful in
eliciting emotions, they are often used persuasively as sophistical tactics in
argumentation to avoid fulfilling the proper requirements of a burden of proof.
Argument from authority is a kind of argument that uses expert opinion (de
facto authority) or the pronouncement of someone invested with an institutional
office or title (de jure authority) to support a conclusion. As a practical but
fallible method of steering discussion toward a presumptive conclusion, the
argument from authority can be a reasonable way of shifting a burden of proof.
However, if pressed too hard in a discussion or portrayed as a better
justification for a conclusion than the evidence warrants, it can become a
fallacious argumentum ad verecundiam (see below). It should be noted, however,
that arguments based on expert opinions are widely accepted both in artificial
intelligence and everyday argumentation as legitimate and sound under the right
conditions. Although arguments from authority have been strongly condemned
during some historical periods as inherently fallacious, the current climate of
opinion is to think of them as acceptable in some cases, even if they are
fallible arguments that can easily go wrong or be misused by sophistical
persuaders. Argumentum ad judicium represents a kind of knowledge-based
argumentation that is empirical, as opposed to being based on an arguer’s
personal opinion or viewpoint. In modern terminology, it apparently refers to
an argument based on objective evidence, as opposed to somebody’s subjective
opinion. The term appears to have been invented by Locke to contrast three
commonly used kinds of arguments and a fourth special type of argument. The
first three types of argument are based on premises that the respondent of the
argument is taken to have already accepted. Thus these can all be called
“personal” in nature. The fourth kind of argument – argumentum ad judicium –
does not have to be based on what some person accepts, and so could perhaps be
called “impersonal.” Locke writes that the first three kinds of arguments can
dispose a person for the reception of truth, but cannot help that person to the
truth. Only the argumentum ad judicium can do that. The first three types of
arguments come from “my shamefacedness, ignorance or error,” whereas the
argumentum ad judicium “comes from proofs and arguments and light arising from
the nature of things themselves.” The first three types of arguments have only
a preparatory function in finding the truth of a matter, whereas the argumentum
ad judicium is more directly instrumental in helping us to find the truth.
Argumentum ad verecundiam (argument to reverence or respect) is the fallacious
use of expert opinion in argumentation to try to persuade someone to accept a
conclusion. In the Essay concerning Human Understanding (1690) Locke describes
such arguments as tactics of trying to prevail on the assent of someone by
portraying him as irreverent or immodest if he does not readily yield to the
authority of some learned informal fallacy informal fallacy 433 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:39 AM Page 433 opinion cited. Locke does not claim, however, that
all appeals to expert authority in argument are fallacious. They can be
reasonable if used judiciously. Argumentum ad ignorantiam (argument to
ignorance) takes the following form: a proposition a is not known or proved to
be true (false); therefore A is false (true). It is a negative type of
knowledge-based or presumptive reasoning, generally not conclusive, but it is
nevertheless often non-fallacious in balance-of-consideration cases where the
evidence is inconclusive to resolve a disputed question. In such cases it is a
kind of presumption-based argumentation used to advocate adopting a conclusion
provisionally, in the absence of hard knowledge that would determine whether
the conclusion is true or false. An example would be: Smith has not been heard
from for over seven years, and there is no evidence that he is alive; therefore
it may be presumed (for the purpose of settling Smith’s estate) that he is
dead. Arguments from ignorance ought not to be pressed too hard or used with
too strong a degree of confidence. An example comes from the U.S. Senate
hearings in 1950, in which Senator Joseph McCarthy used case histories to argue
that certain persons in the State Department should be considered Communists.
Of one case he said, “I do not have much information on this except the general
statement of the agency that there is nothing in the files to disprove his
Communist connections.” The strength of any argument from ignorance depends on
the thoroughness of the search made. The argument from ignorance can be used to
shift a burden of proof merely on the basis of rumor, innuendo, or false
accusations, instead of real evidence. Ignoratio elenchi (ignorance of
refutation) is the traditional name, following Aristotle, for the fault of
failing to keep to the point in an argument. The fallacy is also called
irrelevant conclusion or missing the point. Such a failure of relevance is
essentially a failure to keep closely enough to the issue under discussion.
Suppose that during a criminal trial, the prosecutor displays the victim’s
bloody shirt and argues at length that murder is a horrible crime. The
digression may be ruled irrelevant to the question at issue of whether the
defendant is guilty of murder. Alleged failures of this type in argumentation
are sometimes quite difficult to judge fairly, and a ruling should depend on
the type of discussion the participants are supposed to be engaged in. In some
cases, conventions or institutional rules of procedure – e.g. in a criminal
trial – are aids to determining whether a line of argumentation should be
judged relevant or not. Petitio principii (asking to be granted the “principle”
or issue of the discussion to be proved), also called begging the question, is
the fallacy of improperly arguing in a circle. Circular reasoning should not be
presumed to be inherently fallacious, but can be fallacious where the circular
argument has been used to disguise or cover up a failure to fulfill a burden of
proof. The problem arises where the conclusion that was supposed to be proved
is presumed within the premises to be granted by the respondent of the
argument. Suppose I ask you to prove that this bicycle (the ownership of which
is subject to dispute) belongs to Hector, and you reply, “All the bicycles
around here belong to Hector.” The problem is that without independent evidence
that shows otherwise, the premise that all the bicycles belong to Hector takes
for granted that this bicycle belongs to Hector, instead of proving it by
properly fulfilling the burden of proof. The fallacy of many questions (also
called the fallacy of complex question) is the tactic of packing unwarranted
presuppositions into a question so that any direct answer given by the respondent
will trap her into conceding these presuppositions. The classical case is the
question, “Have you stopped beating your spouse?” No matter how the respondent
answers, yes or no, she concedes the presuppositions that (a) she has a spouse,
and (b) she has beaten that spouse at some time. Where one or both of these
presumptions are unwarranted in the given case, the use of this question is an
instance of the fallacy of many questions. The fallacy of equivocation occurs
where an ambiguous word has been used more than once in an argument in such a
way that it is plausible to interpret it in one way in one instance of its use
and in another way in another instance. Such an argument may seem persuasive if
the shift in the context of use of the word makes these differing
interpretations plausible. Equivocation, however, is generally seriously
deceptive only in longer sequences of argument where the meaning of a word or
phrase shifts subtly but significantly. A simplistic example will illustrate
the gist of the fallacy: ‘The news media should present all the facts on
anything that is in the public interest; the public interest in lives of movie
stars is intense; therefore the news media should present all the facts on the
private lives of movie stars’. This argument goes from plausible premises to an
implausible conclusion by trading on the ambiguity of ‘public interest’. In one
sense informal fallacy informal fallacy 434 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page
434 it means ‘public benefit’ while in another sense it refers to something
more akin to curiosity. Amphiboly (double arrangement) is a type of traditional
fallacy (derived from Aristotle’s list of fallacies) that refers to the use of
syntactically ambiguous sentences like ‘Save soap and waste paper’. Although the
logic textbooks often cite examples of such sentences as fallacies, they have
never made clear how they could be used to deceive in a serious discussion.
Indeed, the example cited is not even an argument, but simply an ambiguous
sentence. In cases of some advertisements like ‘Two pizzas for one special
price’, however, one can see how the amphiboly seriously misleads readers into
thinking they are being offered two pizzas for the regular price of one. Accent
is the use of shifting stress or emphasis in speech as a means of deception.
For example, if a speaker puts stress on the word ‘created’ in ‘All men were
created equal’ it suggests (by implicature) the opposite proposition to ‘All
men are equal’, namely ‘Not all men are (now) equal’. The oral stress allows
the speaker to covertly suggest an inference the hearer is likely to draw, and
to escape commitment to the conclusion suggested by later denying he said it.
The slippery slope argument, in one form, counsels against some contemplated
action (or inaction) on the ground that, once taken, it will be a first step in
a sequence of events that will be difficult to resist and will (or may or must)
lead to some dangerous (or undesirable or disastrous) outcome in the end. It is
often argued, e.g., that once you allow euthanasia in any form, such as the
withdrawal of heroic treatments of dying patients in hospitals, then (through
erosion of respect for human life), you will eventually wind up with a
totalitarian state where old, feeble, or politically troublesome individuals
are routinely eliminated. Some slippery slope arguments can be reasonable, but
they should not be put forward in an exaggerated way, supported with
insufficient evidence, or used as a scare tactic. See also CIRCULAR REASONING,
FORMAL FALLACY, IMPLICATURE, INFORMAL LOGIC, PRAGMATIC CONTRADICTION, VALID.
D.W. informal logic, also called practical logic, the use of logic to identify,
analyze, and evaluate arguments as they occur in contexts of discourse in
everyday conversations. In informal logic, arguments are assessed on a
case-by-case basis, relative to how the argument was used in a given context to
persuade someone to accept the conclusion, or at least to give some reason
relevant to accepting the conclusion. See also CIRCULAR REASONING, FORMAL
FALLACY, IMPLICATURE, INFORMAL FALLACY, PRAGMATIC CONTRADICTION, VALID. D.W.
information-theoretic semantics. See PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. information theory,
also called communication theory, a primarily mathematical theory of
communication. Prime movers in its development include Claude Shannon, H.
Nyquist, R. V. L. Hartley, Norbert Wiener, Boltzmann, and Szilard. Original
interests in the theory were largely theoretical or applied to telegraphy and
telephony, and early development clustered around engineering problems in such
domains. Philosophers (Bar-Hillel, Dretske, and Sayre, among others) are mainly
interested in information theory as a source for developing a semantic theory
of information and meaning. The mathematical theory has been less concerned
with the details of how a message acquires meaning and more concerned with what
Shannon called the “fundamental problem of communication” – reproducing at one
point either exactly or approximately a message (that already has a meaning)
selected at another point. Therefore, the two interests in information – the
mathematical and the philosophical – have remained largely orthogonal.
Information is an objective (mind-independent) entity. It can be generated or
carried by messages (words, sentences) or other products of cognizers
(interpreters). Indeed, communication theory focuses primarily on conditions
involved in the generation and transmission of coded (linguistic) messages.
However, almost any event can (and usually does) generate information capable
of being encoded or transmitted. For example, Colleen’s acquiring red spots can
contain information about Colleen’s having the measles and graying hair can
carry information about her grandfather’s aging. This information can be
encoded into messages about measles or aging (respectively) and transmitted,
but the information would exist independently of its encoding or transmission.
That is, this information would be generated (under the right conditions) by
occurrence of the measles-induced spots and the age-induced graying themselves
– regardless of anyone’s actually noticing. This objective feature of
information explains its potential for epistemic and semantic development by
philosophers and cognitive scientists. For example, in its epistemic dimension,
a single (event, message, or Colleen’s spots) that contains informal logic
information theory 435 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 435 (carries) the
information that Colleen has the measles is something from which one (mom,
doctor) can come to know that Colleen has the measles. Generally, an event
(signal) that contains the information that p is something from which one can
come to know that p is the case – provided that one’s knowledge is indeed based
on the information that p. Since information is objective, it can generate what
we want from knowledge – a fix on the way the world objectively is configured.
In its semantic dimension, information can have intentionality or aboutness.
What is happening at one place (thermometer reading rising in Colleen’s mouth)
can carry information about what is happening at another place (Colleen’s body
temperature rising). The fact that messages (or mental states, for that matter)
can contain information about what is happening elsewhere, suggests an exciting
prospect of tracing the meaning of a message (or of a thought) to its
informational origins in the environment. To do this in detail is what a
semantic theory of information is about. The mathematical theory of information
is purely concerned with information in its quantitative dimension. It deals
with how to measure and transmit amounts of information and leaves to others
the work of saying what (how) meaning or content comes to be associated with a
signal or message. In regard to amounts of information, we need a way to
measure how much information is generated by an event (or message) and how to
represent that amount. Information theory provides the answer. Since
information is an objective entity, the amount of information associated with
an event is related to the objective probability (likelihood) of the event.
Events that are less likely to occur generate more information than those more
likely to occur. Thus, to discover that the toss of a fair coin came up heads
contains more information than to discover this about the toss of a coin biased
(.8) toward heads. Or, to discover that a lie was knowingly broadcast by a
censored, state-run radio station, contains less information than that a lie
was knowingly broadcast by a non-censored, free radio station (say, the BBC). A
(perhaps surprising) consequence of associating amounts of information with
objective likelihoods of events is that some events generate no information at
all. That is, that 55 % 3125 or that water freezes at 0oC. (on a specific
occasion) generates no information at all – since these things cannot be
otherwise (their probability of being otherwise is zero). Thus, their
occurrence generates zero information. Shannon was seeking to measure the
amount of information generated by a message and the amount transmitted by its
reception (or about average amounts transmissible over a channel). Since his
work, it has become standard to think of the measure of information in terms of
reductions of uncertainty. Information is identified with the reduction of uncertainty
or elimination of possibilities represented by the occurrence of an event or
state of affairs. The amount of information is identified with how many
possibilities are eliminated. Although other measures are possible, the most
convenient and intuitive way that this quantity is standardly represented is as
a logarithm (to the base 2) and measured in bits (short for how many binary
digits) needed to represent binary decisions involved in the reduction or
elimination of possibilities. If person A chooses a message to send to person
B, from among 16 equally likely alternative messages (say, which number came up
in a fair drawing from 16 numbers), the choice of one message would represent 4
bits of information (16 % 24 or log2 16 % 4). Thus, to calculate the amount of
information generated by a selection from equally likely messages (signals,
events), the amount of information I of the message s is calculated I(s) %
logn. If there is a range of messages (s1 . . . sN) not all of which are
equally likely (letting (p (si) % the probability of any si’s occurrence), the
amount of information generated by the selection of any message si is
calculated I(si) % log 1/p(si) % –log p(si) [log 1/x % –log x] While each of
these formulas says how much information is generated by the selection of a
specific message, communication theory is seldom primarily interested in these
measures. Philosophers are interested, however. For if knowledge that p
requires receiving the information that p occurred, and if p’s occurrence represents
4 bits of information, then S would know that p occurred only if S received
information equal to (at least) 4 bits. This may not be sufficient for S to
know p – for S must receive the right amount of information in a non-deviant
causal way and S must be able to extract the content of the information – but
this seems clearly necessary. Other measures of information of interest in
communication theory include the average information, or entropy, of a source,
information theory information theory 436 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page
436 I(s) % 9p(si) $ I(si), a measure for noise (the amount of information that
person B receives that was not sent by person A), and for equivocation (the
amount of information A wanted or tried to send to B that B did not receive).
These concepts from information theory and the formulas for measuring these
quantities of information (and others) provide a rich source of tools for
communication applications as well as philosophical applications. See also
COMPUTER THEORY, EPISTEMOLOGY, PERCEPTION. F.A. informed consent, voluntary
agreement in the light of relevant information, especially by a patient to a
medical procedure. An example would be consent to a specific medical procedure
by a competent adult patient who has an adequate understanding of all the
relevant treatment options and their risks. It is widely held that both
morality and law require that no medical procedures be performed on competent
adults without their informed consent. This doctrine of informed consent has been
featured in case laws since the 1950s, and has been a focus of much discussion
in medical ethics. Underwritten by a concern to protect patients’ rights to
self-determination and also by a concern with patients’ well-being, the
doctrine was introduced in an attempt to delineate physicians’ duties to inform
patients of the risks and benefits of medical alternatives and to obtain their
consent to a particular course of treatment or diagnosis. Interpretation of the
legitimate scope of the doctrine has focused on a variety of issues concerning
what range of patients is competent to give consent and hence from which ones
informed consent must be required; concerning how much, how detailed, and what
sort of information must be given to patients to yield informed consent; and
concerning what sorts of conditions are required to ensure both that there is
proper understanding of the information and that consent is truly voluntary
rather than unduly influenced by the institutional authority of the physician.
See also ETHICS. J.R.M. Ingarden, Roman Witold (1893–1970), the leading Polish
phenomenologist, who taught in Lvov and Cracow and became prominent in the
English-speaking world above all through his work in aesthetics and philosophy
of literature. His Literary Work of Art (German 1931, English 1973) presents an
ontological account of the literary work as a stratified structure, including
word sounds and meanings, represented objects and aspects, and associated
metaphysical and aesthetic qualities. The work forms part of a larger
ontological project of combating the transcendental idealism of his teacher
Husserl, and seeks to establish the essential difference in structure between
minddependent ‘intentional’ objects and objects in reality. Ingarden’s
ontological investigations are set out in his The Controversy over the
Existence of the World (Polish 1947/48, German 1964–74, partial English
translation as Time and Modes of Being, 1964). The work rests on a tripartite
division of formal, material, and existential ontology and contains extensive
analyses of the ontological structures of individual things, events, processes,
states of affairs, properties and relations. It culminates in an attempted
refutation of idealism on the basis of an exhaustive account of the possible
relations between consciousness and reality. See also PHENOMENOLOGY. B.Sm.
inherent value. See VALUE. innate idea. See IDEA. innatism. See CAMBRIDGE
PLATONISTS. inner converse. See CONVERSE, OUTER AND INNER. in rebus realism.
See METAPHYSICAL REALISM. inscrutability of reference. See INDETERMINACY OF
TRANSLATION. insolubilia, sentences embodying a semantic antinomy such as the
liar paradox. Insolubilia were used by late medieval logicians to analyze
self-nullifying sentences, the possibility that all sentences imply that they
are true, and the relation between spoken, written, and mental language. At
first, theorists focused on nullification to explicate a sentence like ‘I am
lying’, which, when spoken, entails that the speaker “says nothing.” Bradwardine
suggested that such sentences signify that they are at once true and false,
prompting Burley to argue that all sentences imply that they are true. Roger
Swineshead used insolubilia to distinguish between truth and correspondence to
reality; while ‘This sentence is false’ is itself false, it corresponds to
reality, while its contradiction, ‘This sentence is not false,’ does not,
although the latter is also false. Later, Wyclif used insolubilia to describe
the senses in which a sentence can be true, which led to his belief in informed
consent insolubilia 437 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 437 the reality of
logical beings or entities of reason, a central tenet of his realism. Pierre
d’Ailly used insolubilia to explain how mental language differs from spoken and
written language, holding that there are no mental language insolubles, but
that spoken and written language lend themselves to the phenomenon by admitting
a single sentence corresponding to two distinct mental sentences. See also
BURLEY, D’AILLY, OXFORD CALCULATORS, SEMANTIC PARADOXES, WYCLIF. S.E.L.
instantiation. See PROPERTY. instantiation, universal. See UNIVERSAL
INSTANTIATION. institution. (1) An organization such as a corporation or
college. (2) A social practice such as marriage or making promises. (3) A
system of rules defining a possible form of social organization, such as
capitalist versus Communist principles of economic exchange. In light of the
power of institutions to shape societies and individual lives, writers in
professional ethics have explored four main issues. First, what political and
legal institutions are feasible, just, and otherwise desirable (Plato,
Republic; Rawls, A Theory of Justice)? Second, how are values embedded in
institutions through the constitutive rules that define them (for example, “To
promise is to undertake an obligation”), as well as through regulatory rules
imposed on them from outside, such that to participate in institutions is a
value-laden activity (Searle, Speech Acts, 1969)? Third, do institutions have
collective responsibilities or are the only responsibilities those of
individuals, and in general how are the responsibilities of individuals,
institutions, and communities related? Fourth, at a more practical level, how
can we prevent institutions from becoming corrupted by undue regard for money
and power (MacIntyre, After Virtue, 1981) and by patriarchal prejudices (Susan
Moller Okin, Justice, Gender, and the Family, 1989)? See also PHILOSOPHY OF
LAW, PROFESSIONAL ETHICS, RESPONSIBILITY. M.W.M. institutional theory of art,
the view that something becomes an artwork by virtue of occupying a certain
position within the context of a set of institutions. George Dickie originated
this theory of art (Art and the Aesthetic, 1974), which was derived loosely from
Arthur Danto’s “The Artworld” (Journal of Philosophy, 1964). In its original
form it was the view that a work of art is an artifact that has the status of
candidate for appreciation conferred upon it by some person acting on behalf of
the art world. That is, there are institutions – such as museums, galleries,
and journals and newspapers that publish reviews and criticism – and there are
individuals who work within those institutions – curators, directors, dealers,
performers, critics – who decide, by accepting objects or events for discussion
and display, what is art and what is not. The concept of artifactuality may be
extended to include found art, conceptual art, and other works that do not
involve altering some preexisting material, by holding that a use, or context
for display, is sufficient to make something into an artifact. This definition
of art raises certain questions. What determines – independently of such
notions as a concern with art – whether an institution is a member of the art
world? That is, is the definition ultimately circular? What is it to accept
something as a candidate for appreciation? Might not this concept also threaten
circularity, since there could be not only artistic but also other kinds of
appreciation? See also AESTHETICS, EXPRESSION THEORY OF ART. S.L.F.
instrumental conditioning. See CONDITIONING. instrumentalism, in its most
common meaning, a kind of anti-realistic view of scientific theories wherein
theories are construed as calculating devices or instruments for conveniently
moving from a given set of observations to a predicted set of observations. As
such the theoretical statements are not candidates for truth or reference, and
the theories have no ontological import. This view of theories is grounded in a
positive distinction between observation statements and theoretical statements,
and the according of privileged epistemic status to the former. The view was
fashionable during the era of positivism but then faded; it was recently
revived, in large measure owing to the genuinely perplexing character of
quantum theories in physics. ’Instrumentalism’ has a different and much more
general meaning associated with the pragmatic epistemology of Dewey. Deweyan
instrumentalism is a general functional account of all concepts (scientific
ones included) wherein the epistemic status of concepts and the rationality
status of actions are seen as a function of their role in integrating,
predicting, and controlling our concrete interactions with our experienced
world. There is no positivistic distinction instantiation instrumentalism 438
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 438 between observation and theory, and
truth and reference give way to “warranted assertability.” See also DEWEY,
METAPHYSICAL REALISM, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, THEORETICAL TERM. C.F.D.
instrumental rationality. See RATIONALITY. instrumental sign. See SEMIOSIS.
instrumental value. See VALUE. insufficient reason. See PRINCIPLE OF
INSUFFICIENT REASON. intelligible world. See KANT. intension, the meaning or
connotation of an expression, as opposed to its extension or denotation, which
consists of those things signified by the expression. The intension of a
declarative sentence is often taken to be a proposition and the intension of a
predicate expression (common noun, adjective) is often taken to be a concept.
For Frege, a predicate expression refers to a concept and the intension or Sinn
(“sense”) of a predicate expression is a mode of presentation distinct from the
concept. Objects like propositions or concepts that can be the intension of
terms are called intensional objects. (Note that ‘intensional’ is not the same
word as ‘intentional’, although the two are related.) The extension of a
declarative sentence is often taken to be a state of affairs and that of a
predicate expression to be the set of objects that fall under the concept which
is the intension of the term. Extension is not the same as reference. For
example, the term ‘red’ may be said to refer to the property redness but to
have as its extension the set of all red things. Alternatively properties and
relations are sometimes taken to be intensional objects, but the property
redness is never taken to be part of the extension of the adjective ‘red’. See
also EXTENSIONALISM, INTENSIONALITY, INTENSIONAL LOGIC, MEANING. D.N.
intension, compositional. See LEWIS, DAVID. intensionality, failure of
extensionality. A linguistic context is extensional if and only if the
extension of the expression obtained by placing any subexpression in that
context is the same as the extension of the expression obtained by placing in
that context any subexpression with the same extension as the first
subexpression. Modal, intentional, and direct quotational contexts are main
instances of intensional contexts. Take, e.g., sentential contexts. The
extension of a sentence is its truth or falsity (truth-value). The extension of
a definite description is what it is true of: ‘the husband of Xanthippe’ and
‘the teacher of Plato’ have the same extension, for they are true of the same
man, Socrates. Given this, it is easy to see that ‘Necessarily, . . . was
married to Xanthippe’ is intensional, for ‘Necessarily, the husband of
Xanthippe was married to Xanthippe’ is true, but ‘Necessarily, the teacher of
Plato was married to Xanthippe’ is not. Other modal terms that generate
intensional contexts include ‘possibly’, ‘impossibly’, ‘essentially’,
‘contingently’, etc. Assume that Smith has heard of Xanthippe but not Plato.
‘Smith believes that . . . was married to Xanthippe’ is intensional, for ‘Smith
believes that the husband of Xanthippe was married to Xanthippe’ is true, but
‘Smith believes that the teacher of Plato was married to Xanthippe’ is not.
Other intentional verbs that generate intensional contexts include ‘know’,
‘doubt’, ‘wonder’, ‘fear’, ‘intend’, ‘state’, and ‘want’. ‘The fourth word in
“. . . “ has nine letters’ is intensional, for ‘The fourth word in “the husband
of Xanthippe” has nine letters’ is true but ‘the fourth word in “the teacher of
Plato” has nine letters’ is not. See also EXTENSIONALISM, MEANING, QUANTIFYING
IN, REFERENTIALLY TRANSPARENT. T.Y. intensional logic, that part of deductive
logic which treats arguments whose validity or invalidity depends on strict
difference, or identity, of meaning. The denotation of a singular term (i.e., a
proper name or definite description), the class of things of which a predicate
is true, and the truth or falsity (the truth-value) of a sentence may be called
the extensions of these respective linguistic expressions. Their intensions are
their meanings strictly so called: the (individual) concept conveyed by the
singular term, the property expressed by the predicate, and the proposition
asserted by the sentence. The most extensively studied part of formal logic
deals largely with inferences turning only on extensions. One principle of
extensional logic is that if two singular terms have identical denotations, the
truth-values of corresponding sentences containing the terms are identical.
Thus the inference from ‘Bern is the capital of Switzerland’ to ‘You are in
Bern if and only if you are in the capital of Switzerland’ is valid. But this
is invalid: ‘Bern is the capital of Switzerland. Therefore, you believe that
you are in Bern if and only if you believe that you are in the capital of
Switzerland.’ For one may lack the belief instrumental rationality intensional
logic 439 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 439 that Bern is the capital of
Switzerland. It seems that we should distinguish between the intensional
meanings of ‘Bern’ and of ‘the capital of Switzerland’. One supposes that only
a strict identity of intension would license interchange in such a context, in
which they are in the scope of a propositional attitude. It has been questioned
whether the idea of an intension really applies to proper names, but parallel
examples are easily constructed that make similar use of the differences in the
meanings of predicates or of whole sentences. Quite generally, then, the
principle that expressions with the same extension may be interchanged with preservation
of extension of the containing expression, seems to fail for such “intensional
contexts.” The range of expressions producing such sensitive contexts includes
psychological verbs like ‘know’, ‘believe’, ‘suppose’, ‘assert’, ‘desire’,
‘allege’, ‘wonders whether’; expressions conveying modal ideas such as
necessity, possibility, and impossibility; some adverbs, e.g. ‘intentionally’;
and a large number of other expressions – ’prove’, ‘imply’, ‘make probable’,
etc. Although reasoning involving some of these is well understood, there is
not yet general agreement on the best methods for dealing with arguments
involving many of these notions. See also MODAL LOGIC. C.A.A. intensive
magnitude. See MAGNITUDE. intention, (1) a characteristic of action, as when one
acts intentionally or with a certain intention; (2) a feature of one’s mind, as
when one intends (has an intention) to act in a certain way now or in the
future. Betty, e.g., intentionally walks across the room, does so with the
intention of getting a drink, and now intends to leave the party later that
night. An important question is: how are (1) and (2) related? (See Anscombe,
Intention, 1963, for a groundbreaking treatment of these and other basic
problems concerning intention.) Some philosophers see acting with an intention
as basic and as subject to a three-part analysis. For Betty to walk across the
room with the intention of getting a drink is for Betty’s walking across the
room to be explainable (in the appropriate way) by her desire or (as is sometimes
said) pro-attitude in favor of getting a drink and her belief that walking
across the room is a way of getting one. On this desire-belief model (or
wantbelief model) the main elements of acting with an intention are (a) the
action, (b) appropriate desires (pro-attitudes) and beliefs, and (c) an
appropriate explanatory relation between (a) and (b). (See Davidson, “Actions,
Reasons, and Causes” in Essays on Actions and Events, 1980.) In explaining (a)
in terms of (b) we give an explanation of the action in terms of the agent’s
purposes or reasons for so acting. This raises the fundamental question of what
kind of explanation this is, and how it is related to explanation of Betty’s
movements by appeal to their physical causes. What about intentions to act in
the future? Consider Betty’s intention to leave the party later. Though the
intended action is later, this intention may nevertheless help explain some of
Betty’s planning and acting between now and then. Some philosophers try to fit
such futuredirected intentions directly into the desire-belief model. John
Austin, e.g., would identify Betty’s intention with her belief that she will
leave later because of her desire to leave (Lectures on Jurisprudence, vol. I,
1873). Others see futuredirected intentions as distinctive attitudes, not to be
reduced to desires and/or beliefs. How is belief related to intention? One
question here is whether an intention to A requires a belief that one will A. A
second question is whether a belief that one will A in executing some intention
ensures that one intends to A. Suppose that Betty believes that by walking
across the room she will interrupt Bob’s conversation. Though she has no desire
to interrupt, she still proceeds across the room. Does she intend to interrupt
the conversation? Or is there a coherent distinction between what one intends
and what one merely expects to bring about as a result of doing what one
intends? One way of talking about such cases, due to Bentham (An Introduction
to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, 1789), is to say that Betty’s
walking across the room is “directly intentional,” whereas her interrupting the
conversation is only “obliquely intentional” (or indirectly intentional). See
also ACTION THEORY, PRINCIPLE OF DOUBLE EFFECT. M.E.B. intention, direct. See
INTENTION. intention, first. See IMPOSITION. intention, indirect. See
INTENTION. intention, oblique. See INTENTION. intention, second. See
IMPOSITION. intentional fallacy, the (purported) fallacy of holding that the
meaning of a work of art is fixed by the artist’s intentions. (Wimsatt and
Beardsintensive magnitude intentional fallacy 440 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40
AM Page 440 ley, who introduced the term, also used it to name the [purported]
fallacy that the artist’s aims are relevant to determining the success of a
work of art; however, this distinct usage has not gained general currency.)
Wimsatt and Beardsley were formalists; they held that interpretation should
focus purely on the work of art itself and should exclude appeal to biographical
information about the artist, other than information concerning the private
meanings the artist attached to his words. Whether the intentional fallacy is
in fact a fallacy is a much discussed issue within aesthetics. Intentionalists
deny that it is: they hold that the meaning of a work of art is fixed by some
set of the artist’s intentions. For instance, Richard Wollheim (Painting as an
Art) holds that the meaning of a painting is fixed by the artist’s fulfilled
intentions in making it. Other intentionalists appeal not to the actual
artist’s intentions, but to the intentions of the implied or postulated artist,
a construct of criticism, rather than a real person. See also AESTHETIC
FORMALISM, AESTHETICS, INTENTION. B.Ga. intentionality, aboutness. Things that
are about other things exhibit intentionality. Beliefs and other mental states
exhibit intentionality, but so, in a derived way, do sentences and books, maps
and pictures, and other representations. The adjective ‘intentional’ in this
philosophical sense is a technical term not to be confused with the more
familiar sense, characterizing something done on purpose. Hopes and fears, for
instance, are not things we do, not intentional acts in the latter, familiar
sense, but they are intentional phenomena in the technical sense: hopes and
fears are about various things. The term was coined by the Scholastics in the
Middle Ages, and derives from the Latin verb intendo, ‘to point (at)’ or ‘aim
(at)’ or ‘extend (toward)’. Phenomena with intentionality thus point outside of
themselves to something else: whatever they are of or about. The term was
revived by the nineteenth-century philosopher and psychologist Franz Brentano,
who claimed that intentionality defines the distinction between the mental and the
physical; all and only mental phenomena exhibit intentionality. Since
intentionality is an irreducible feature of mental phenomena, and since no
physical phenomena could exhibit it, mental phenomena could not be a species of
physical phenomena. This claim, often called the Brentano thesis or Brentano’s
irreducibility thesis, has often been cited to support the view that the mind
cannot be the brain, but this is by no means generally accepted today. There
was a second revival of the term in the 1960s and 1970s by analytic
philosophers, in particular Chisholm, Sellars, and Quine. Chisholm attempted to
clarify the concept by shifting to a logical definition of intentional idioms,
the terms used to speak of mental states and events, rather than attempting to
define the intentionality of the states and events themselves. Intentional
idioms include the familiar “mentalistic” terms of folk psychology, but also
their technical counterparts in theories and discussions in cognitive science,
‘X believes that p,’ and ‘X desires that q’ are paradigmatic intentional
idioms, but according to Chisholm’s logical definition, in terms of referential
opacity (the failure of substitutivity of coextensive terms salva veritate), so
are such less familiar idioms as ‘X stores the information that p’ and ‘X gives
high priority to achieving the state of affairs that q’. Although there
continue to be deep divisions among philosophers about the proper definition or
treatment of the concept of intentionality, there is fairly widespread agreement
that it marks a feature – aboutness or content – that is central to mental
phenomena, and hence a central, and difficult, problem that any theory of mind
must solve. See also BRENTANO, FOLK PSYCHOLOGY, QUANTIFYING IN, REFERENTIALLY
TRANSPARENT. D.C.D. intentional object. See BRENTANO. intentional species. See
AQUINAS, ARISTOTLE. interchangeability salva veritate. See SUBSTITUTIVITY SALVA
VERITATE. internalism, epistemological. See EPISTEMOLOGY. internalism,
motivational. See MOTIVATIONAL INTERNALISM. internalism, reasons. See
EXTERNALISM. internal necessity. See NECESSITY. internal negation. See
NEGATION. internal realism. See PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. internal reason. See
EXTERNALISM. internal relation. See RELATION. intentionality internal relation 441
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 441 interoception. See PERCEPTION.
interpersonal utility. See UTILITARIANISM. interpretant. See PEIRCE.
interpretation. See MODAL LOGIC. interpretation, non-standard. See FORMAL
SEMANTICS. interpretation, standard. See FORMAL SEMANTICS. interpretive system.
See OPERATIONALISM. intersection. See SET THEORY. intersubjectivity. See
MERLEAU-PONTY. intersubstitutivity salva veritate. See SUBSTITUTIVITY SALVA
VERITATE. interval scale. See MAGNITUDE. intervening variable, in psychology, a
state of an organism or person postulated to explain behavior and defined in
terms of its causes and effects rather than its intrinsic properties. A food
drive, conceived as an intervening variable, may be defined in terms of the
number of hours without food (causes) and the strength or robustness of efforts
to secure it (effects) rather than in terms of hungry feeling (intrinsic
property). There are at least three reasons for postulating intervening
variables. First, time lapse between stimulus and behavior may be large, as
when an animal eats food found hours earlier. Why didn’t the animal eat when it
first discovered food? Perhaps at the time of discovery, it had already eaten,
so food drive was reduced. Second, the same animal or person may act
differently in the same sort of situation, as when we eat at noon one day but
delay until 3 p.m. the next. Again, this may be because of variation in food
drive. Third, behavior may occur in the absence of external stimulation, as
when an animal forages for food. This, too, may be explained by the strength of
the food drive. Intervening variables have been viewed, depending on the
background theory, as convenient fictions or as psychologically real states.
See also THEORETICAL TERM. G.A.G. intrapersonal utility. See UTILITARIANISM.
intrinsic desire. See EXTRINSIC DESIRE. intrinsic property. See RELATION.
intrinsic relation. See RELATION. intrinsic value. See VALUE. introjection. See
FREUD. introspection. See AWARENESS. intuition, a non-inferential knowledge or
grasp, as of a proposition, concept, or entity, that is not based on
perception, memory, or introspection; also, the capacity in virtue of which
such cognition is possible. A person might know that 1 ! 1 % 2 intuitively,
i.e., not on the basis of inferring it from other propositions. And one might
know intuitively what yellow is, i.e., might understand the concept, even
though ‘yellow’ is not definable. Or one might have intuitive awareness of God
or some other entity. Certain mystics hold that there can be intuitive, or
immediate, apprehension of God. Ethical intuitionists hold both that we can
have intuitive knowledge of certain moral concepts that are indefinable, and
that certain propositions, such as that pleasure is intrinsically good, are knowable
through intuition. Self-evident propositions are those that can be seen
(non-inferentially) to be true once one fully understands them. It is often
held that all and only self-evident propositions are knowable through
intuition, which is here identified with a certain kind of intellectual or
rational insight. Intuitive knowledge of moral or other philosophical
propositions or concepts has been compared to the intuitive knowledge of
grammaticality possessed by competent users of a language. Such language users
can know immediately whether certain sentences are grammatical or not without
recourse to any conscious reasoning. See also A PRIORI, EPISTEMOLOGY. B.R.
intuition, eidetic. See HUSSERL. intuition, sensible. See KANT. intuitionism,
ethical. See ETHICS. intuitionism, mathematical. See MATHEMATICAL INTUITIONISM.
intuitionism, Oxford school of. See PRICHARD. intuitionist logic. See FORMAL
LOGIC, PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC. interoception intuitionist logic 442 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 442 intuitions. See PREANALYTIC. intuitive induction.
See ROSS. inversion, spectrum. See QUALIA. inverted qualia. See PHILOSOPHY OF
MIND, QUALIA. invisible hand. See SMITH, SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY. involuntary
euthanasia. See EUTHANASIA. inwardness. See TAYLOR, CHARLES. Ionian philosophy,
the characteristically naturalist and rationalist thought of Greek philosophers
of the sixth and fifth centuries B.C. who were active in Ionia, the region of
ancient Greek colonies on the coast of Asia Minor and adjacent islands. First
of the Ionian philosophers were the three Milesians. See also MILESIANS,
PRESOCRATICS. A.P.D.M. iota operator. See Appendix of Special Symbols.
I-proposition. See SYLLOGISM. Irigaray, Luce (b.1930), French feminist
philosopher and psychoanalyst. Her earliest work was in psychoanalysis and
linguistics, focusing on the role of negation in the language of schizophrenics
(Languages, 1966). A trained analyst with a private practice, she attended
Lacan’s seminars at the École Normale Supérieure and for several years taught a
course in the psychoanalysis department at Vincennes. With the publication of
Speculum, De l’autre femme(Speculum of the Other Woman) in 1974 she was
dismissed from Vincennes. She argues that psychoanalysis, specifically its
attitude toward women, is historically and culturally determined and that its
phallocentric bias is treated as universal truth. With the publication of
Speculum and Ce Sexe qui n’en est pas un (This Sex Which Is Not One) in 1977,
her work extends beyond psychoanalysis and begins a critical examination of
philosophy. Influenced primarily by Hegel, Nietzsche, and Heidegger, her work
is a critique of the fundamental categories of philosophical thought: one/many,
identity/difference, being/non-being, rational/irrational, mind/body, form/matter,
transcendental/sensible. She sets out to show the concealed aspect of
metaphysical constructions and what they depend on, namely, the unacknowledged
mother. In Speculum, the mirror figures as interpretation and criticism of the
enclosure of the Western subject within the mirror’s frame, constituted solely
through the masculine imaginary. Her project is one of constituting the world –
and not only the specular world – of the other as woman. This engagement with
the history of philosophy emphasizes the historical and sexual determinants of
philosophical discourse, and insists on bringing the transcendental back to the
elements of the earth and embodiment. Her major contribution to philosophy is
the notion of sexual difference. An Ethics of Sexual Difference (1984) claims
that the central contemporary philosophical task is to think through sexual
difference. Although her notion of sexual difference is sometimes taken to be
an essentialist view of the feminine, in fact it is an articulation of the difference
between the sexes that calls into question an understanding of either the
feminine or masculine as possessing a rigid gender identity. Instead, sexual
difference is the erotic desire for otherness. Insofar as it is an origin that
is continuously differentiating itself from itself, it challenges Aristotle’s
understanding of the arche as solid ground or hypokeimenon. As aition or first
cause, sexual difference is responsible for something coming into being and is
that to which things are indebted for their being. This indebtedness allows
Irigaray to formulate an ethics of sexual difference. Her latest work continues
to rethink the foundations of ethics. Both Towards a Culture of Difference
(1990) and I Love To You (1995) claim that there is no civil identity proper to
women and therefore no possibility of equivalent social and political status
for men and women. She argues for a legal basis to ground the reciprocity
between the sexes; that there is no living universal, that is, a universal that
reflects sexual difference; and that this lack of a living universal leads to
an absence of rights and responsibilities which reflects both men and women.
She claims, therefore, that it is necessary to “sexuate” rights. These latest
works continue to make explicit the erotic and ethical project that informs all
her work: to think through the dimension of sexual difference that opens up
access to the alliances between living beings who are engendered and not
fabricated, and who refuse to sacrifice desire for death, power, or money. See
also FREUD, HEGEL, HEIDEGGER, NIETZSCHE, POSTMODERN. P.Bi. irrationality,
unreasonableness. Whatever it entails, irrationality can characterize belief,
desire, intention, and action. intuitions irrationality 443 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 443 Irrationality is often explained in instrumental,
or goal-oriented, terms. You are irrational if you (knowingly) fail to do your
best, or at least to do what you appropriately think adequate, to achieve your
goals. If ultimate goals are rationally assessable, as Aristotelian and Kantian
traditions hold, then rationality and irrationality are not purely
instrumental. The latter traditions regard certain specific (kinds of) goals,
such as human well-being, as essential to rationality. This substantialist
approach lost popularity with the rise of modern decision theory, which implies
that, in satisfying certain consistency and completeness requirements, one’s
preferences toward the possible outcomes of available actions determine what
actions are rational and irrational for one by determining the personal utility
of their outcomes. Various theorists have faulted modern decision theory on two
grounds: human beings typically lack the consistent preferences and reasoning
power required by standard decision theory but are not thereby irrational, and
rationality requires goods exceeding maximally efficient goal satisfaction.
When relevant goals concern the acquisition of truth and the avoidance of
falsehood, epistemic rationality and irrationality are at issue. Otherwise,
some species of non-epistemic rationality or irrationality is under
consideration. Species of non-epistemic rationality and irrationality
correspond to the kind of relevant goal: moral, prudential, political,
economic, aesthetic, or some other. A comprehensive account of irrationality
will elucidate epistemic and non-epistemic irrationality as well as such
sources of irrationality as weakness of will and ungrounded belief. See also
DECISION THEORY, JUSTIFICATION, RATIONALITY. P.K.M. irredundant. See
INDEPENDENCE RESULTS. irreflexive. See RELATION. irrelevant conclusion, fallacy
of. See INFORMAL FALLACY. is, third person singular form of the verb ‘be’, with
at least three fundamental senses that philosophers distinguish according to
the resources required for a proper logical representation. The ‘is’ of
existence (There is a unicorn in the garden: Dx (Ux8Gx)) uses the existential
quantifier. The ‘is’ of identity (Hesperus is Phosphorus: j % k) employs the
predicate of identity. The ‘is’ of predication (Samson is strong: Sj) merely
juxtaposes predicate symbol and proper name. Some controversy attends the first
sense. Some (notably Meinong) maintain that ‘is’ applies more broadly than
‘exists,’ the former producing truths when combined with ‘deer’ and ‘unicorn’
and the latter producing truths when combined with ‘deer’ but not ‘unicorn’.
Others (like Aquinas) take ‘being’ (esse) to denote some special activity that
every existing object necessarily performs, which would seem to imply that with
‘is’ they attribute more to an object than we do with ‘exists’. Other issues
arise in connection with the second sense. Does Hesperus is Phosphorus, for
example, attribute anything more to the heavenly body than its identity with
itself? Consideration of such a question led Frege to conclude that names (and
other meaningful expressions) of ordinary language have a “sense” or “mode of
presenting” the object to which they refer that representations within our
standard, extensional logical systems fail to expose. The distinction between
the ‘is’ of identity and the ‘is’ of predication parallels Frege’s distinction
between object and concept: words signifying objects stand to the right of the
‘is’ of identity and those signifying concepts stand to the right of the ‘is’
of predication. Although it seems remarkable that so many deep and difficult
philosophical concepts should link to a single short and commonplace word, we
should perhaps not read too much into that observation. Some languages divide
the various roles played by English’s compact copula among several
constructions, and others use the corresponding word for other purposes. See
also EXISTENTIAL IMPORT, IDENTITY, QUALITIES. S.T.K. Isaac Israeli. See JEWISH
PHILOSOPHY. Isagoge. See PORPHYRY. Islamic Neoplatonism, a Neoplatonism
constituting one of several philosophical tendencies adopted by Muslim
philosophers. Aristotle was well known and thoroughly studied among those
thinkers in the Islamic world specifically influenced by ancient Greek
philosophy; Plato less so. In part both were understood in Neoplatonic terms.
But, because the Enneads came to be labeled mistakenly the Theology of
Aristotle, the name of ‘Plotinus’ had no significance. A similar situation
befell the other ancient Neoplatonists. The Theology and other important
sources of Neoirredundant Islamic Neoplatonism 444 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40
AM Page 444 platonic thinking were, therefore, often seen as merely the
“theological” speculations of the two major Greek philosophical authorities –
mainly Aristotle: all of this material being roughly equivalent to something
Islamic Neoplatonists called the “divine Plato.” For a few Islamic
philosophers, moreover, such as the critically important al-Farabi,
Neoplatonism had little impact. They followed a tradition of philosophical
studies based solely on an accurate knowledge of Aristotle plus the political
teachings of Plato without this “theology.” In the works of less avowedly
“philosophical” thinkers, however, a collection of falsely labeled remnants of
ancient Neoplatonism – bits of the Enneads, pieces of Proclus’s Elements of
Theology (notably the Arabic version of the famous Liber de causis), and
various pseudo-epigraphic doxographies full of Neoplatonic ideas – gave rise to
a true Islamic Neoplatonism. This development followed two distinct paths. The
first and more direct route encompassed a number of tenth-century authors who
were attracted to Neoplatonic theories about God’s or the One’s complete and
ineffable transcendence, about intellect’s unity and universality, and about
soul as a hypostatic substance having continual existence in a universal as
well as a particular being, the latter being the individual human soul. These
doctrines held appeal as much for their religious as for their philosophical
utility. A second form of Neoplatonism arose in the intellectual elements of
Islamic mysticism, i.e., Sufism. There, the influence of Plotinus’s concept of
the ecstatic confrontation and ultimate union with the One found a clear,
although unacknowledged, echo. In later periods, too, the “divine Plato”
enjoyed a revival of importance via a number of influential philosophers, such
as Suhrawardi of Aleppo (twelfth century) and Mulla Fadra (seventeenth
century), who were interested in escaping the narrow restrictions of
Peripatetic thought. See also ARABIC PHILOSOPHY, NEOPLATONISM, SUFISM. P.E.W.
Islamic philosophy. See ARABIC PHILOSOPHY. Isocrates (436–338 B.C.), Greek
rhetorician and teacher who was seen as the chief contemporary rival of Plato.
A pupil of Socrates and also of Gorgias, he founded a school in about 392 that
attracted many foreign students to Athens and earned him a sizable income. Many
of his works touch on his theories of education; Against the Sophists and On
the Antidosis are most important in this respect. The latter stands to
Isocrates as the Apology of Plato stands to Socrates, a defense of his life’s
work against an attack not on his life, but on his property. The aim of his
teaching was good judgment in practical affairs, and he believed his
contribution to Greece through education more valuable than legislation could
possibly be. He repudiated instruction in theoretical philosophy, and insisted
on distinguishing his teaching of rhetoric from the sophistry that gives clever
speakers an unfair advantage. In politics he was a Panhellenic patriot, and
urged the warring Greek city-states to unite under strong leadership and take
arms against the Persian Empire. His most famous work, and the one in which he
took the greatest pride, was the Panegyricus, a speech in praise of Athens. In
general, he supported democracy in Athens, but toward the end of his life
complained bitterly of abuses of the system. P.Wo. isolation argument. See
EPISTEMOLOGY. isomorphism. See CATEGORICITY, HOMOMORPHISM, KÖHLER. is–ought
distinction. See FACT–VALUE DISTINCTION. is–ought problem. See FACT–VALUE
DISTINCTION. Israeli, Isaac. See JEWISH PHILOSOPHY. iterated modality. See
ALETHIC MODALITIES. iterative hierarchy. See SET THEORY. I-Thou relationship.
See BUBER.
Jacobi, Friedrich
Heinrich (1743–1819), German man of letters, popular novelist, and author of
several influential philosophical works. His Ueber die Lehre des Spinoza (1785)
precipitated a dispute with Mendelssohn on Lessing’s alleged pantheism. The
ensuing Pantheismusstreit (pantheism controversy) focused attention on the
apparent conflict between human freedom and any systematic, philosophical
interpretation of reality. In the appendix to his David Hume über den Glauben,
oder Idealismus und Realismus (“David Hume on Belief, or Idealism and Realism,”
1787), Jacobi scrutinized the new transcendental philosophy of Kant, and
subjected Kant’s remarks concerning “things-in-themselves” to devastating
criticism, observing that, though one could not enter the critical philosophy
without presupposing the existence of things-in-themselves, such a belief is
incompatible with the tenets of that philosophy. This criticism deeply
influenced the efforts of post-Kantians (e.g., Fichte) to improve
transcendental idealism. In 1799, in an “open letter” to Fichte, Jacobi
criticized philosophy in general and transcendental idealism in particular as
“nihilism.” Jacobi espoused a fideistic variety of direct realism and
characterized his own standpoint as one of “nonknowing.” Employing the
arguments of “Humean skepticism,” he defended the necessity of a “leap of
faith,” not merely in morality and religion, but in every area of human life.
Jacobi’s criticisms of reason and of science profoundly influenced German
Romanticism. Near the end of his career he entered bitter public controversies
with Hegel and Schelling concerning the relationship between faith and
knowledge. See also KANT. D.Br. Jainism, an Indian religious and philosophical
tradition established by Mahavira, a contemporary of the historical Buddha, in
the latter half of the sixth and the beginning of the fifth century B.C. The
tradition holds that each person (jiva) is everlasting and indestructible, a
self-conscious identity surviving as a person even in a state of final enlightenment.
It accepts personal immortality without embracing any variety of monotheism. On
the basis of sensory experience it holds that there exist mind-independent
physical objects, and it regards introspective experience as establishing the
existence of enduring selves. It accepts the doctrines of rebirth and karma and
conceives the ultimate good as escape from the wheel of rebirth. It rejects all
violence as incompatible with achieving enlightenment. See also BUDDHISM.
K.E.Y. James, William (1842–1910), American philosopher, psychologist, and one
of the founders of pragmatism. He was born in New York City, the oldest of five
children and elder brother of the novelist Henry James and diarist Alice James.
Their father, Henry James, Sr., was an unorthodox religious philosopher, deeply
influenced by the thought of Swedenborg, some of which seeped into William’s
later fascination with psychical research. The James family relocated to
Cambridge, Massachusetts, but the father insisted on his children obtaining a
European education, and prolonged trips to England and the Continent were
routine, a procedure that made William multilingual and extraordinarily
cosmopolitan. In fact, a pervasive theme in James’s personal and creative life
was his deep split between things American and European: he felt like a
bigamist “coquetting with too many countries.” As a person, James was
extraordinarily sensitive to psychological and bodily experiences. He could be
described as “neurasthenic” – afflicted with constant psychosomatic symptoms
such as dyspepsia, vision problems, and clinical depression. In 1868 he
recorded a profound personal experience, a “horrible fear of my own existence.”
In two 1870 diary entries, James first contemplates suicide and then pronounces
his belief in free will and his resolve to act on that belief in “doing,
suffering and creating.” Under the influence of the then burgeoning work in
experimental psychology, James attempted to sustain, on empirical grounds, his
belief in the self as Promethean, as self-making rather than as a playing out
of inheritance or the influence of social context. This bold and extreme
doctrine of individuality is bolstered by his attack on both the neo-Hegelian
and associationist doctrines. He held that both approaches miss the empirical
reality of relations as affec446 J 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 446
tively experienced and the reality of consciousness as a “stream,” rather than
an aspect of an Absolute or simply a box holding a chain of concepts
corresponding to single sense impressions. In 1890, James published his
masterpiece, The Principles of Psychology, which established him as the premier
psychologist of the Euro-American world. It was a massive compendium and
critique of virtually all of the psychology literature then extant, but it also
claimed that the discipline was in its infancy. James believed that the
problems he had unearthed could only be understood by a philosophical approach.
James held only one academic degree, an M.D. from Harvard, and his early teaching
at Harvard was in anatomy and physiology. He subsequently became a professor of
psychology, but during the writing of the Principles, he began to teach
philosophy as a colleague of Royce and Santayana. From 1890 forward James saw
the fundamental issues as at bottom philosophical and he undertook an intense
inquiry into matters epistemological and metaphysical; in particular, “the
religious question” absorbed him. The Will to Believe and Other Essays in
Popular Philosophy was published in 1897. The lead essay, “The Will to
Believe,” had been widely misunderstood, partly because it rested on
unpublished metaphysical assumptions and partly because it ran aggressively
counter to the reigning dogmas of social Darwinism and neo-Hegelian absolutism,
both of which denigrated the personal power of the individual. For James, one
cannot draw a conclusion, fix a belief, or hold to a moral or religious maxim
unless all suggestions of an alternative position are explored. Further, some
alternatives will be revealed only if one steps beyond one’s frame of
reference, seeks novelty, and “wills to believe” in possibilities beyond
present sight. The risk taking in such an approach to human living is further
detailed in James’s essays “The Dilemma of Determinism” and “The Moral
Philosopher and the Moral Life,” both of which stress the irreducibility of
ambiguity, the presence of chance, and the desirability of tentativeness in our
judgments. After presenting the Gifford Lectures in 1901– 02, James published
his classic work, The Varieties of Religious Experience, which coalesced his
interest in psychic states both healthy and sick and afforded him the
opportunity to present again his firm belief that human life is characterized
by a vast array of personal, cultural, and religious approaches that cannot and
should not be reduced one to the other. For James, the “actual peculiarities of
the world” must be central to any philosophical discussion of truth. In his
Hibbert Lectures of 1909, published as A Pluralistic Universe, James was to
represent this sense of plurality, openness, and the variety of human
experience on a wider canvas, the vast reach of consciousness, cosmologically
understood. Unknown to all but a few philosophical correspondents, James had
been assiduously filling notebooks with reflections on the mind–body problem
and the relationship between meaning and truth and with a philosophical
exploration and extension of his doctrine of relations as found earlier in the
Principles. In 1904–05 James published a series of essays, gathered
posthumously in 1912, on the meaning of experience and the problem of
knowledge. In a letter to François Pillon in 1904, he writes: “My philosophy is
what I call a radical empiricism, a pluralism, a ‘tychism,’ which represents
order as being gradually won and always in the making.” Following his 1889
essay “On Some Omissions of Introspective Psychology” and his chapter on “The
Stream of Thought” in the Principles, James takes as given that relations
between things are equivalently experienced as the things themselves.
Consequently, “the only meaning of essence is teleological, and that
classification and conception are purely teleological weapons of the mind.” The
description of consciousness as a stream having a fringe as well as a focus,
and being selective all the while, enables him to take the next step, the
formulation of his pragmatic epistemology, one that was influenced by, but is
different from, that of Peirce. Published in 1907, Pragmatism generated a
transatlantic furor, for in it James unabashedly states that “Truth happens to
be an idea. It becomes true, is made true by events.” He also introduces the
philosophically notorious claim that “theories” must be found that will “work.”
Actually, he means that a proposition cannot be judged as true independently of
its consequences as judged by experience. James’s prose, especially in
Pragmatism, alternates between scintillating and limpid. This quality led to
both obfuscation of his intention and a lulling of his reader into a false sense
of simplicity. He does not deny the standard definition of truth as a
propositional claim about an existent, for he writes “woe to him whose beliefs
play fast and loose with the order which realities follow in his experience;
they will lead him nowhere or else make false connexions.” Yet he regards this
structure as but a prologue to the creative activJames, William James, William
447 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 447 ity of the human mind. Also in
Pragmatism, speaking of the world as “really malleable,” he argues that man
engenders truths upon reality. This tension between James as a radical
empiricist with the affirmation of the blunt, obdurate relational manifold
given to us in our experience and James as a pragmatic idealist holding to the
constructing, engendering power of the Promethean self to create its own
personal world, courses throughout all of his work. James was chagrined and
irritated by the quantity, quality, and ferocity of the criticism leveled at
Pragmatism. He attempted to answer those critics in a book of disparate essays,
The Meaning of Truth (1909). The book did little to persuade his critics; since
most of them were unaware of his radically empirical metaphysics and certainly
of his unpublished papers, James’s pragmatism remained misunderstood until the
publication of Perry’s magisterial two-volume study, The Thought and Character
of William James (1935). By 1910, James’s heart disease had worsened; he
traveled to Europe in search of some remedy, knowing full well that it was a
farewell journey. Shortly after returning to his summer home in Chocorua, New
Hampshire, he died. One month earlier he had said of a manuscript (posthumously
published in 1911 as Some Problems in Philosophy), “say that by it I hoped to
round out my system, which is now too much like an arch only on one side.” Even
if he had lived much longer, it is arguable that the other side of the arch
would not have appeared, for his philosophy was ineluctably geared to seeking
out the novel, the surprise, the tychistic, and the plural, and to denying the
finality of all conclusions. He warned us that “experience itself, taken at
large, can grow by its edges” and no matter how laudable or seductive our
personal goal, “life is in the transitions.” The Works of William James,
including his unpublished manuscripts, have been collected in a massive
nineteen-volume critical edition by Harvard University Press (1975–88). His
work can be seen as an imaginative vestibule into the twentieth century. His
ideas resonate in the work of Royce, Unamuno, Niels Bohr, Husserl, M.
Montessori, Dewey, and Wittgenstein. See also DEWEY, PEIRCE, PRAGMATISM. J.J.M.
James-Lange theory, the theory, put forward by William James and independently
by C. Lange, a Danish anatomist, that an emotion is the felt awareness of
bodily reactions to something perceived or thought (James) or just the bodily
reactions themselves (Lange). According to the more influential version (James,
“What Is an Emotion?” Mind, 1884), “our natural way of thinking” mistakenly supposes
that the perception or thought causes the emotion, e.g., fear or anger, which
in turn causes the bodily reactions, e.g., rapid heartbeat, weeping, trembling,
grimacing, and actions such as running and striking. In reality, however, the
fear or anger consists in the bodily sensations caused by these reactions. In
support of this theory, James proposed a thought experiment: Imagine feeling
some “strong” emotion, one with a pronounced “wave of bodily disturbance,” and
then subtract in imagination the felt awareness of this disturbance. All that
remains, James found, is “a cold and neutral state of intellectual perception,”
a cognition lacking in emotional coloration. Consequently, it is our bodily
feelings that emotionalize consciousness, imbuing our perceptions and thoughts
with emotional qualities and endowing each type of emotion, such as fear,
anger, and joy, with its special feeling quality. But this does not warrant
James’s radical conclusion that emotions or emotional states are effects rather
than causes of bodily reactions. That conclusion requires the further
assumption, which James shared with many of his contemporaries, that the
various emotions are nothing but particular feeling qualities. Historically,
the James-Lange theory led to further inquiries into the physiological and
cognitive causes of emotional feelings and helped transform the psychology of
emotions from a descriptive study relying on introspection to a broader
naturalistic inquiry. See also EMOTION. R.M.G. Jansenism, a set of doctrines
advanced by European Roman Catholic reformers, clergy, and scholars in the
seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, characterized by a predestinarianism that
emphasized Adam’s fall, irresistible efficacious grace, limited atonement,
election, and reprobation. Addressing the issue of free will and grace left
open by the Council of Trent (1545–63), a Flemish bishop, Cornelius Jansen
(1585–1638), crystallized the seventeenth-century Augustinian revival,
producing a compilation of Augustine’s anti-Pelagian teachings (Augustinus).
Propagated by Saint Cyran and Antoine Arnauld (On Frequent Communion, 1643),
adopted by the nuns of Port-Royal, and defended against Jesuit attacks by
Pascal (Provincial Letters, 1656–57), Jansenism pervaded Roman Catholicism from
Utrecht to Rome for over 150 years. Condemned James-Lange theory Jansenism 448
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 448 by Pope Innocent X (Cum Occasione,
1653) and crushed by Louis XIV and the French clergy (the 1661 formulary), it
survived outside France and rearmed for a counteroffensive. Pasquier Quesnel’s
(1634–1719) “second Jansenism,” condemned by Pope Clement XI (Unigenitus,
1713), was less Augustinian, more rigorist, and advocated Presbyterianism and
Gallicanism. J.-L.S. Japanese philosophy, philosophy in Japan, beginning with
Buddhist thought and proceeding to academic “philosophy” (tetsugaku), which
emerged in Japan only during the Meiji Restoration period beginning in 1868.
Among representatives of traditional Japanese Buddhist philosophical thought
should be mentioned Saicho (767–822) of Tendai; Kukai (774–835) of Shingon;
Shinran (1173–1262) of Jodo Shinshu; Dogen (1200–53) of Soto Zen; and Nichiren
(1222–82) of Nichiren Buddhism. During the medieval period a duty-based warrior
ethic of loyalty and self-sacrifice emerged from within the Bushido tradition
of the Samurai, developed out of influences from Confucianism and Zen. Also,
the Zen-influenced path of Geido or way of the artist produced an important
religio-aesthetic tradition with ideas of beauty like aware (sad beauty), yugen
(profundity), ma (interval), wabi (poverty), sabi (solitariness), and shibui
(understatement). While each sect developed its own characteristics, a general
feature of traditional Japanese Buddhist philosophy is its emphasis on
“impermanence” (mujo), the transitoriness of all non-substantial phenomena as
expressed through the aesthetic of perishability in Geido and the constant
remembrance of death in the warrior ethic of Bushido. Much of twentieth-century
Japanese philosophy centers around the development of, and critical reaction
against, the thought of Nishida Kitaro (1870–1945) and the “Kyoto School”
running through Tanabe Hajime, Nishitani Keiji, Hisamatsu Shin’ichi, Takeuchi
Yoshinori, Ueda Shizuteru, Abe Masao, and, more peripherally, Watsuji Tetsuro,
Kuki Shuzo, and D. T. Suzuki. The thought of Nishida is characterized by the
effort to articulate an East-West philosophy and interfaith dialogue within a
Buddhist framework of “emptiness” (ku) or “nothingness” (mu). In his maiden
work, A Study of Good (1911), Nishida elaborates a theory of “pure experience”
(junsui keiken) influenced especially by William James. Like James, Nishida
articulates “pure experience” as an immediate awareness in the stream of
consciousness emerging prior to subject– object dualism. Yet it is widely
agreed that Nishida reformulates “pure experience” in light of his own study of
Zen Buddhism. Throughout his career Nishida continuously reworked the idea of
“pure experience” in terms of such notions as “self-awareness,” “absolute
will,” “acting intuition,” “absolute nothingness,” and the “social-historical
world.” From the Acting to the Seeing (1927) signifies a turning point in
Nishida’s thought in that it introduces his new concept of basho, the “place”
of “absolute Nothingness” wherein the “true self” arises as a “selfidentity of
absolute contradictions.” Nishida’s penultimate essay, “The Logic of Place and
a Religious Worldview” (1945), articulates a theory of religious experience
based upon the “self-negation” of both self and God in the place of
Nothingness. In this context he formulates an interfaith dialogue between the
Christian kenosis (self-emptying) and Buddhist sunyata (emptiness) traditions.
In Religion and Nothingness (1982), Nishitani Keiji develops Nishida’s
philosophy in terms of a Zen logic wherein all things at the eternalistic
standpoint of Being are emptied in the nihilistic standpoint of Relative
Nothingness, which in turn is emptied into the middle way standpoint of
Emptiness or Absolute Nothingness represented by both Buddhist sunyata and
Christian kenosis. For Nishitani, this shift from Relative to Absolute
Nothingness is the strategy for overcoming nihilism as described by Nietzsche.
Hisamatsu Shin’ichi interprets Japanese aesthetics in terms of Nishida’s Self
of Absolute Nothingness in Zen and the Fine Arts (1971). The encounter of
Western philosophy with Zen Nothingness is further developed by Abe Masao in
Zen and Western Thought (1985). Whereas thinkers like Nishida, Nishitani,
Hisamatsu, Ueda, and Abe develop a Zen approach based upon the immediate
experience of Absolute Nothingness through the “self-power” (jiriki) of
intuition, Philosophy as Metanoetics (1986) by Tanabe Hajime instead takes up
the stance of Shinran’s Pure Land Buddhism, according to which Nothingness is
the transforming grace of absolute “Other-power” (tariki) operating through
faith. Watsuji Tetsuro’s Ethics (1937), the premier work in modern Japanese
moral theory, develops a communitarian ethics in terms of the “betweenness”
(aidagara) of persons based on the Japanese notion of self as ningen, whose two
characters reveal the double structure of personhood as both individual and
social. Kuki Shuzo’s The Structure of Iki (1930), often regarded as the most creative
work in modern Japanese aesthetJapanese philosophy Japanese philosophy 449
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 449 ics, analyzes the Edo ideal of iki or
“chic” as having a threefold structure representing the fusion of the
“amorousness” (bitai) of the Geisha, the “valor” (ikuji) of the Samurai, and
the “resignation” (akirame) of the Buddhist priest. Marxist thinkers like
Tosaka Jun (1900–45) have developed strong ideological critiques of the
philosophy articulated by Nishida and the Kyoto School. In summary, the
outstanding contribution of modern Japanese philosophy has been the effort to
forge a synthesis of Eastern and Western values within the overall framework of
an Asian worldview. See also BUDDHISM, CONFUCIANISM. S.O. Jaspers, Karl Theodor
(1883–1969), German psychologist and philosopher, one of the main
representatives of the existentialist movement (although he rejected
‘existentialism’ as a distortion of the philosophy of existence). From 1901
until 1908 Jaspers studied law and medicine at the universities of Heidelberg,
Munich, Berlin, and Göttingen. He concluded his studies with an M.D.
(Homesickness and Crime) from the University of Heidelberg (where he stayed
until 1948). From 1908 until 1915 he worked as a voluntary assistant in the
psychiatric clinic, and published his first major work (Allgemeine
Psychopathologie, 1913; General Psychopathology, 1965). After his habilitation
in psychology (1913) Jaspers lectured as Privatdocent. In 1919 he published
Psychologie der Weltanschauung (“Psychology of Worldviews”). Two years later he
became professor in philosophy. Because of his personal convictions and
marriage with Gertrud Mayer (who was Jewish) the Nazi government took away his
professorship in 1937 and suppressed all publications. He and his wife were
saved from deportation because the American army liberated Heidelberg a few
days before the fixed date of April 14, 1945. In 1948 he accepted a
professorship from the University of Basel. As a student, Jaspers felt a strong
aversion to academic philosophy. However, as he gained insights in the fields
of psychiatry and psychology, he realized that both the study of human beings
and the meaning of scientific research pointed to questions and problems that
demanded their own thoughts and reflections. Jaspers gave a systematic account
of them in his three-volume Philosophie (1931; with postscript, 1956;
Philosophy, 1969–71), and in the 1,100 pages of Von der Wahrheit (On Truth,
1947). In the first volume (“Philosophical World-orientation”) he discusses the
place and meaning of philosophy with regard to the human situation in general
and scientific disciplines in particular. In the second (“Clarification of
Existence”), he contrasts the compelling modes of objective (scientific)
knowledge with the possible (and in essence non-objective) awareness of being
in self-relation, communication, and historicity, both as being oneself
presents itself in freedom, necessity, and transcendence, and as existence
encounters its unconditionality in limit situations (of death, suffering,
struggle, guilt) and the polar intertwining of subjectivity and objectivity. In
the third volume (“Metaphysics”) he concentrates on the meaning of
transcendence as it becomes translucent in appealing ciphers (of nature,
history, consciousness, art, etc.) to possible existence under and against the
impact of stranding. His Von der Wahrheit is the first volume of a projected
work on philosophical logic (cf. Nachlaß zur philosophischen Logik, ed. H.
Saner and M. Hänggi, 1991) in which he develops the more formal aspects of his
philosophy as “periechontology” (ontology of the encompassing, des
Umgreifenden, with its modes of being there, consciousness, mind, existence,
world, transcendence, reason) and clarification of origins. In both works Jaspers
focuses on “existential philosophy” as “that kind of thinking through which man
tries to become himself both as thinking makes use of all real knowledge and as
it transcends this knowledge. This thinking does not recognize objects, but
clarifies and enacts at once the being of the one who thinks in this way”
(Philosophische Autobiographie, 1953). In his search for authentic existence in
connection with the elaboration of “philosophical faith” in reason and truth,
Jaspers had to achieve a thorough understanding of philosophical, political,
and religious history as well as an adequate assessment of the present
situation. His aim became a world philosophy as a possible contribution to
universal peace out of the spirit of free and limitless communication,
unrestricted open-mindedness, and unrelenting truthfulness. Besides a
comprehensive history of philosophy (Die groben Philosophen I, 1957; II and
III, 1981; The Great Philosophers, 2 vols., 1962, 1966) and numerous monographs
(on Cusanus, Descartes, Leonardo da Vinci, Schelling, Nietzsche, Strindberg,
van Gogh, Weber) he wrote on subjects such as the university (Die Idee der
Universität, 1946; The Idea of the University, 1959), the spiritual situation
of the age (Die geistige Situation der Zeit, 1931; Man in the Modern Age,
1933), the meaning of history (Vom Ursprung und Ziel der Geschichte, 1949; The
Origin and Goal of History, Jaspers, Karl Theodor Jaspers, Karl Theodor 450
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 450 1953, in which he developed the idea of
an “axial period”), the guilt question (Die Schuldfrage, 1946; The Question of
German Guilt, 1947), the atomic bomb (Die Atombombe und die Zukunft des
Menschen, 1958; The Future of Mankind, 1961), German politics (Wohin treibt die
Bundesrepublik? 1966; The Future of Germany, 1967). He also wrote on theology
and religious issues (Die Frage der Entymythologisierung. Eine Diskussion mit
Rudolf Bultmann, 1954; Myth and Christianity, 1958; Der philosophische Glaube
angesichts der Offenbarung, 1962; Philosophical Faith and Revelation, 1967).
See also EXISTENTIALISM, METAPHYSICS. W.D. Jean Poinsot. See JOHN OF SAINT
THOMAS. jen, Chinese philosophical term, important in Confucianism, variously
translated as ‘kindness’, ‘humanity’, or ‘benevolence’. Scholars disagree as to
whether it has the basic meaning of an attribute distinctive of certain
aristocratic clans, or the basic meaning of kindness, especially kindness of a
ruler to his subjects. In Confucian thought, it is used to refer both to an
all-encompassing ethical ideal for human beings (when so used, it is often
translated as ‘humanity’, ‘humaneness’, or ‘goodness’), and more specifically
to the desirable attribute of an emotional concern for all living things, the
degree and nature of such concern varying according to one’s relation to such
things (when so used, it is often translated as ‘benevolence’). Later
Confucians explain jen in terms of one’s being of one body with all things, and
hence one’s being sensitive and responsive to their well-being. In the political
realm, Confucians regard jen as ideally the basis of government. A ruler with
jen will care about and provide for the people, and people will be attracted to
the ruler and be inspired to reform themselves. Such a ruler will succeed in
bringing order and be without rivals, and will become a true king (wang). See
also CONFUCIANISM. K.-l.S. jen hsin. See TAO-HSIN, JEN-HSIN. jen-yü. See T’IEN
LI, JEN-YÜ. Jevons, William Stanley (1835–82), British economist, logician, and
philosopher of science. In economics, he clarified the idea of value, arguing
that it is a function of utility. Later theorists imitated his use of the
calculus and other mathematical tools to reach theoretical results. His
approach anticipated the idea of marginal utility, a notion basic in modern
economics. Jevons regarded J. S. Mill’s logic as inadequate, preferring the new
symbolic logic of Boole. One permanent contribution was his introduction of the
concept of inclusive ‘or’, with ‘or’ meaning ‘either or, or both’. To aid in
teaching the new logic of classes and propositions, Jevons invented his
“logical piano.” In opposition to the confidence in induction of Mill and
Whewell, both of whom thought, for different reasons, that induction can arrive
at exact and necessary truths, Jevons argued that science yields only
approximations, and that any perfect fit between theory and observation must be
grounds for suspicion that we are wrong, not for confidence that we are right.
Jevons introduced probability theory to show how rival hypotheses are
evaluated. He was a subjectivist, holding that probability is a measure of what
a perfectly rational person would believe given the available evidence. See
also INDUCTION, PROBABILITY, UTILITARIANISM. R.E.B. Jewish philosophy. The
subject begins with Philo Judaeus (c.20 B.C.–A.D. 40) of Alexandria. Applying
Stoic techniques of allegory, he developed a philosophical hermeneutic that
transformed biblical persons and places into universal symbols and virtues;
retaining the Hebrew Bible’s view of a transcendent God, Philo identified
Plato’s world of ideas with the mind or word of God, construing it as the
creative intermediary to the world. This logos doctrine influenced Christian
theology strongly, but had little effect upon Jewish thought. Rabbinic Judaism
was indifferent and probably hostile to all expressions of Greek philosophy,
Philo’s writings included. The tradition of philosophical theology that can be
traced to Philo took hold in Judaism only in the ninth century, and only after
it became accepted in the Islamic world, which Jews then inhabited. Saadiah
Gaon (882–942) modeled his philosophical work The Book of Critically Chosen
Beliefs and Convictions on theological treatises written by Muslim free will
theologians. Unlike them, however, and in opposition to Jewish Karaites,
Saadiah rejected atomistic occasionalism and accepted the philosophers’ view of
a natural order, though one created by God. Saadiah’s knowledge of Greek
philosophy was imperfect and eclectic, yet he argued impressively against the notion
of infinite duration, in order to affirm the necessity of believing in a
created universe and hence in a Creator. Saadiah accepted the historicity of
revelation at Sinai and the validity of Jewish law on more dogmatic grounds,
though Jean Poinsot Jewish philosophy 451 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page
451 he developed a classification of the commandments that distinguished
between them on grounds of greater and lesser rationality. Isaac Israeli
(850–950), while a contemporary of Saadiah’s, was as different from him as East
(Baghdad for Saadiah) is from West (for Israeli, Qayrawan, North Africa).
Israeli showed no interest in theology, and was attracted to Neoplatonism and
the ideas advanced by the first Muslim philosopher, al-Kindi. The strictly philosophical
and essentially Neoplatonic approach in Jewish philosophy reached a high point
with the Fons Vitae of Solomon Ibn Gabirol (1020–57). He followed Israeli in
emphasizing form and matter’s priority over that of the universal mind or noûs.
This heralds the growing dominance of Aristotelian concepts in medieval Jewish
philosophy, in all but political thought, a dominance first fully expressed, in
Spain, in The Exalted Faith of Abraham Ibn Daud (c.1110–80). Many of the themes
and perspectives of Neoplatonism are here retained, particularly that of
emanation and the return of the soul to its source via intellectual
conjunction, as well as the notion of the unknowable and strict unity of God;
but the specific structures of Neoplatonic thought give way to those of
Aristotle and his commentators. This mix of approaches was perfected by the
Muslim falasifa al-Farabi (872–950) and Avicenna (980– 1037), who became the
main authorities for most Jewish philosophers through the twelfth century,
competing afterward with Averroes (1126–98) for the minds of Jewish
philosophers. Judah Ha-Levi (1075–1141), in The Kuzari, also written in Spain,
fought this attraction to philosophy with an informed critique of its
Aristotelian premises. But Moses Maimonides (1138–1204), in his Guide to the
Perplexed, written in Egypt and destined to become the major work of medieval
Jewish philosophy, found little reason to fault the philosophers other than for
accepting an eternal universe. His reservations on this subject, and his reticence
in discussing some other tenets of Jewish faith, led many to suspect his
orthodoxy and to seek esoteric meanings in all his philosophical views, a
practice that continues today. Whatever his philosophical allegiance,
Maimonides viewed Judaism as the paradigmatic philosophical religion, and saw
the ideal philosopher as one who contributes to the welfare of his community,
however much personal happiness is to be found ultimately only in contemplation
of God. Gersonides (1288–1344), living in Provence, responded fully to both
Maimonides’ and Averroes’ teachings, and in his Wars of the Lord denied the
personal providence of popular faith. These sorts of assertions led Hasdai
Crescas (1340–1410) to attack the philosophers on their own premises, and to
offer a model of divine love instead of intelligence as the controlling concept
for understanding oneself and God. Modern Jewish philosophy begins in Germany
with Moses Mendelssohn (1729–86), who attempted philosophically to remove from
Judaism its theocratic and politically compelling dimensions. Hermann Cohen
(1842–1918) further emphasized, under the influence of Kant and Hegel, what he
perceived as the essentially ethical and universal rational teachings of
Judaism. Martin Buber (1878–1965) dramatically introduced an existential
personalism into this ethicist reading of Judaism, while Franz Rosenzweig
(1886–1929) attempted to balance existential imperatives and ahistorical
interpretations of Judaism with an appreciation for the phenomenological
efficacy of its traditional beliefs and practices. The optimistic and universal
orientation of these philosophies was severely tested in World War II, and
Jewish thinkers emerged after that conflict with more assertive national
philosophies. See also BUBER, CRESCAS, GERSONIDES, MAIMONIDES, PHILO JUDAEUS,
SAADIAH. A.L.I. jhana, a term used by Theravada Buddhists meaning ‘pondering’
or ‘contemplation’ and often translated into English as ‘meditation’. This is
one of many terms used to describe both techniques of meditation and the states
of consciousness that result from the use of such techniques. Jhana has a
specific technical use: it denotes a hierarchically ordered series of four (or
sometimes five) states of consciousness, states produced by a gradual reduction
in the range of affective experience. The first of these states is said to
include five mental factors, which are various kinds of affect and cognitive
function, while the last consists only of equanimity, a condition altogether
free from affect. See also SAMATHA, VIPASSANA. P.J.G. Joachim of Floris
(c.1132/35–1202), Italian mystic who traveled to the Holy Land and, upon his
return, became a Cistercian monk and abbot. He later retired to Calabria, in
southern Italy, where he founded the order of San Giovanni in Fiore. He devoted
the rest of his life to meditation and the recording of his prophetic visions.
In his major works Liber concordiae Novi ac Veteri Testamenti (“Book of the
Concordances between the New and the Old Testament,” 1519), Expositio jhana
Joachim of Floris 452 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 452 in Apocalypsim
(1527), and Psalterium decem chordarum (1527), Joachim illustrates the deep
meaning of history as he perceived it in his visions. History develops in
coexisting patterns of twos and threes. The two testaments represent history as
divided in two phases ending in the First and Second Advent, respectively.
History progresses also through stages corresponding to the Holy Trinity. The
age of the Father is that of the law; the age of the Son is that of grace,
ending approximately in 1260; the age of the Spirit will produce a
spiritualized church. Some monastic orders like the Franciscans and Dominicans
saw themselves as already belonging to this final era of spirituality and
interpreted Joachim’s prophecies as suggesting the overthrow of the
contemporary ecclesiastical institutions. Some of his views were condemned by
the Lateran Council in 1215. P.Gar. Johannes Philoponus (c.490–575), Greek
philosopher and theologian, who worked in Alexandria (philoponus, ‘workaholic’,
just a nickname). A Christian from birth, he was a pupil of the Platonist
Ammonius, and is the first Christian Aristotelian. As such, he challenged
Aristotle on many points where he conflicted with Christian doctrine, e.g. the
eternity of the world, the need for an infinite force, the definition of place,
the impossibility of a vacuum, and the necessity for a fifth element to be the
substance of the heavens. Johannes composed commentaries on Aristotle’s
Categories, Prior and Posterior Analytics, Meteorologics, and On the Soul; and
a treatise Against Proclus: On the Eternity of the World. There is dispute as
to whether the commentaries exhibit a change of mind (away from orthodox
Aristotelianism) on these questions. J.M.D. John Damascene. See JOHN OF
DAMASCUS. John of Damascus, Saint, also called John Damascene and Chrysorrhoas
(Golden Speaker) (c.675–c.750), Greek theologian and Eastern church doctor.
Born of a well-to-do family in Damascus, he was educated in Greek, Arabic, and
Islamic thought. He attained a high position in government but resigned under
the antiChristian Caliph Abdul Malek and became a monk about 700, living
outside Jerusalem. He left extensive writings, most little more than
compilations of older texts. The Iconoclastic Synod of 754 condemned his
arguments in support of the veneration of images in the three Discourses
against the Iconoclasts (726–30), but his orthodoxy was confirmed in 787 at the
Second Council of Nicaea. His Sources of Knowledge consists of a Dialectic, a
history of heresies, and an exposition of orthodoxy. Considered a saint from
the end of the eighth century, he was much respected in the East and was
regarded as an important witness to Eastern Orthodox thought by the West in the
Middle Ages. J.Lo. John of Saint Thomas, also known as John Poinsot
(1589–1644), Portuguese theologian and philosopher. Born in Lisbon, he studied
at Coimbra and Louvain, entered the Dominican order (1610), and taught at
Alcalá de Henares, Piacenza, and Madrid. His most important works are the
Cursus philosophicus (“Course of Philosophy,” 1632–36), a work on logic and
natural philosophy; and the Cursus theologicus (“Course of Theology,” 1637–44),
a commentary on Aquinas’s Summa theologiae. John considered himself a Thomist,
but he modified Aquinas’s views in important ways. The “Ars Logica,” the first
part of the Cursus philosophicus, is the source of much subsequent Catholic
teaching in logic. It is divided into two parts: the first deals with formal
logic and presents a comprehensive theory of terms, propositions, and
reasoning; the second discusses topics in material logic, such as predicables,
categories, and demonstration. An important contribution in the first is a
comprehensive theory of signs that has attracted considerable attention in the
twentieth century among such philosophers as Maritain, Yves Simon, John Wild,
and others. An important contribution in the second part is the division of
knowledge according to physical, mathematical, and metaphysical degrees, which
was later adopted by Maritain. John dealt with metaphysical problems in the
second part of the Cursus philosophicus and in the Cursus theologicus. His
views are modifications of Aquinas’s. For example, Aquinas held that the
principle of individuation is matter designated by quantity; John interpreted
this as matter radically determined by dimensions, where the dimensions are
indeterminate. In contrast to other major figures of the Spanish Scholasticism
of the times, John did not write much in political and legal theory. He
considered ethics and political philosophy to be speculative rather than
practical sciences, and adopted a form of probabilism. Moreover, when in doubt
about a course of action, one may simply adopt any pertinent view proposed by a
prudent moralist. See also AQUINAS, PEIRCE, SEMIOSIS. J.J.E.G. Johannes
Philoponus John of Saint Thomas 453 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 453
John of Salisbury (c.1120–80), English prelate and humanist scholar. Between
1135 and 1141 he studied dialectic with Peter Abelard and theology with Gilbert
of Poitiers in Paris. It is possible that during this time he also studied
grammar, rhetoric, and part of the quadrivium with William of Conches at the
Cathedral School of Chartres. After 1147 he was for a time a member of the
Roman Curia, secretary to Theobald, archbishop of Canterbury, and friend of
Thomas Becket. For his role in Becket’s canonization, Louis VII of France
rewarded him with the bishopric of Chartres in 1176. Although John was a
dedicated student of philosophy, it would be misleading to call him a
philosopher. In his letters, biographies of Anselm and Becket, and Memoirs of
the Papal Court (1148– 52), he provides, in perhaps the best medieval imitation
of classical Latin style, an account of some of the most important ideas,
events, and personalities of his time. Neither these works nor his Polycraticus
and Metalogicon, for which he is most celebrated, are systematic philosophical
treatises. The Polycraticus is, however, considered one of the first medieval treatises
to take up political theory in any extended way. In it John maintains that if a
ruler does not legislate in accordance with natural moral law, legitimate
resistance to him can include his assassination. In the Metalogicon, on the
other hand, John discusses, in a humanist spirit, the benefits for a civilized
world of philosophical training based on Aristotle’s logic. He also presents
current views on the nature of universals, and, not surprisingly, endorses an
Aristotelian view of them as neither extramental entities nor mere words, but
mental concepts that nevertheless have a basis in reality insofar as they are
the result of the mind’s abstracting from extramental entities what those
entities have in common. G.S. Johnson, W(illiam) E(rnest) (1858–1931), British
philosopher who lectured on psychology and logic at Cambridge University. His
Logic was published in three parts: Part I (1921); Part II, Demonstrative
Inference: Deductive and Inductive (1922); and Part III, The Logical
Foundations of Science (1924). He did not complete Part IV on probability, but
in 1932 Mind published three of its intended chapters. Johnson’s other
philosophical publications, all in Mind, were not abundant. The discussion note
“On Feeling as Indifference” (1888) deals with problems of classification. “The
Logical Calculus” (three parts, 1892) anticipates the “Cambridge” style of
logic while continuing the tradition of Jevons and Venn; the same is true of
treatments of formal logic in Logic. “Analysis of Thinking” (two parts, 1918)
advances an adverbial theory of experience. Johnson’s philosophic influence at
Cambridge exceeded the influence of these publications, as one can see from the
references to him by John Neville Keynes in Studies and Exercises in Formal
Logic and by his son John Maynard Keynes in A Treatise on Probability. Logic
contains original and distinctive treatments of induction, metaphysics, the
philosophy of mind, and philosophical logic. Johnson’s theory of inference
proposes a treatment of implication that is an alternative to the view of
Russell and Whitehead in Principia Mathematica. He coined the term ‘ostensive
definition’ and introduced the distinction between determinates and
determinables. See also DETERMINABLE, INFERENCE. D.H.S. John the Scot. See ERIGENA.
joint method of agreement and difference. See MILL’s METHODS. ju. See
CONFUCIANISM. Juan Chi (210–63), Chinese Neo-Taoist philosopher. Among his
extant writings the most important are Ta-Chuang lun (“Discourse on the Chuang
Tzu”) and Ta-jen hsien-sheng chuan (“Biography of Master Great Man”). The
concept of naturalness (tzu-jan) underpins Juan’s philosophy. The “great man”
is devoid of self-interest, completely at ease with his own nature and the
natural order at large. In contrast, orthodox tradition (mingchiao) suppresses
openness and sincerity to secure benefit. Politically tzu-jan envisages a
selfgoverning pristine state, a Taoist version of anarchism. However, the
“great man” furnishes a powerful symbol not because he plots to overthrow the
monarchy or withdraws from the world to realize his own ambition, but because
he is able to initiate a process of healing that would revitalize the rule of
the tao. See also NEO-TAOISM. A.K.L.C. judgment. See AKRASIA, FACULTY
PSYCHOLOGY, KANT. Jung, Carl Gustav (1875–1961), Swiss psychologist and founder
of analytical psychology, a form of psychoanalysis that differs from Freud’s
chiefly by an emphasis on the collective character of the unconscious and on
archetypes as its privileged contents. Jung, like Freud, was deeply influJohn
of Salisbury Jung, Carl Gustav 454 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 454
enced by philosophy in his early years. Before his immersion in psychiatry, he
wrote several essays of explicitly philosophical purport. Kant was doubtless the
philosopher who mattered most to Jung, for whom archetypes were conceived as a
priori structures of the human psyche. Plato and Neoplatonists, Schopenhauer
and especially Nietzsche (to whose Zarathustra he devoted a seminar of several
years’ duration) were also of critical importance. Jung was a close reader of
James, and his Psychological Types (1921) – in addition to an extended
discussion of nominalism versus realism – contains a detailed treatment of
Jamesian typologies of the self. Jung considered the self to be an amalgamation
of an “ectopsyche” – consisting of four functions (intuition, sensation,
feeling, and thinking) that surround an ego construed not as a singular entity
but as a “complex” of ideas and emotions – and an “endosphere” (i.e., consciousness
turned inward in memory, affect, etc.). The personal unconscious, which
preoccupied Freud, underlies the endosphere and its “invasions,” but it is in
turn grounded in the collective unconscious shared by all humankind. The
collective unconscious was induced by Jung from his analysis of dream symbols
and psychopathological symptoms. It is an inherited archive of archaic-mythic
forms and figures that appear repeatedly in the most diverse cultures and
historical epochs. Such forms and figures – also called archetypes – are
considered “primordial images” preceding the “ideas” that articulate rational
thought. As a consequence, the self, rather than being autonomous, is embedded
in a prepersonal and prehistoric background from which there is no effective escape.
However, through prolonged psychotherapeutically guided “individuation,” a slow
assimilation of the collective unconscious into daily living can occur, leading
to an enriched and expanded sense of experience and selfhood. See also FREUD,
JAMES, NIETZSCHE. E.S.C. jung, ju, Chinese terms that express the Confucian
distinction between honor and shame or disgrace. The locus classicus of the
discussion is found in Hsün Tzu’s works. While the distinction between jung
(honor) and ju (disgrace, shame) pertains to the normal, human conditions of
security and danger, harm and benefit, it is crucial to distinguish honor as
derived from mere external recognition and honor justly deserved, and to
distinguish shame or disgrace due to circumstance, as in poverty, from that due
to one’s own ethical misconduct. The chün-tzu (paradigmatic individual) should
be content with the shame due to circumstance but not with shame justly
deserved because of misconduct. The key issue is shame or honor justly deserved
from the point of view of jen (benevolence) and yi (rightness), and not shame
or honor resting on contingencies beyond one’s control. See also HSÜN TZU.
A.S.C. jurisprudence, the science or knowledge of law; thus, in its widest
sense, the study of the legal doctrines, rules, and principles of any legal
system. More commonly, however, the term designates the study not of the actual
laws of particular legal systems, but of the general concepts and principles
that underlie a legal system or that are common to all such systems (general
jurisprudence). Jurisprudence in this sense, sometimes also called the
philosophy of law, may be further subdivided according to the major focus of a
particular study. Examples include historical jurisprudence (a study of the
development of legal principles over time, often emphasizing the origin of law
in custom or tradition rather than in enacted rules), sociological
jurisprudence (an examination of the relationship between legal rules and the
behavior of individuals, groups, or institutions), functional jurisprudence (an
inquiry into the relationship between legal norms and underlying social
interests or needs), and analytical jurisprudence (an investigation into the
meaning of, and conceptual connections among, legal concepts). Within analytical
jurisprudence the most substantial body of thought focuses on the meaning of
the concept of law itself (legal theory) and the relationship between that
concept and the concept of morality. Legal positivism, the view that there is
no necessary connection between law and morality, opposes the natural law view
that no sharp distinction between these concepts can be drawn. The former view
is sometimes thought to be a consequence of positivism’s insistence that legal
validity is determined ultimately by reference to certain basic social facts:
“the command of the sovereign” (John Austin), the Grundnorm (Hans Kelsen), or
“the rule of recognition” (H. L. A. Hart). These different positivist
characterizations of the basic, law-determining fact yield different claims
about the normative character of law, with classical positivists (e.g., John
Austin) insisting that legal systems are essentially coercive, whereas modern
positivists (e.g., Hans Kelsen) maintain that they are normative. Disputes
within legal theory often generate or arise out of disputes about theories of
adjudicajung, ju jurisprudence 455 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 455
tion, or how judges do or should decide cases. Mechanical jurisprudence, or
formalism, the theory that all cases can be decided solely by analyzing legal
concepts, is thought by many to have characterized judicial decisions and legal
reasoning in the nineteenth century; that theory became an easy target in the
twentieth century for various forms of legal realism, the view that law is
better determined by observing what courts and citizens actually do than by
analyzing stated legal rules and concepts. Recent developments in the natural
law tradition also focus on the process of adjudication and the normative
claims that accompany the judicial declaration of legal rights and obligations.
These normative claims, natural law theorists argue, show that legal rights are
a species of political or moral rights. In consequence, one must either revise
prevailing theories of adjudication and abandon the social-fact theory of law
(Ronald Dworkin), or explore the connection between legal theory and the
classical question of political theory: Under what conditions do legal
obligations, even if determined by social facts, create genuine political
obligations (e.g., the obligation to obey the law)? Other jurisprudential
notions that overlap topics in political theory include rule of law, legal
moralism, and civil disobedience. The disputes within legal theory about the
connection between law and morality should not be confused with discussions of
“natural law” within moral theory. In moral theory, the term denotes a
particular view about the objective status of moral norms that has produced a
considerable literature, extending from ancient Greek and Roman thought,
through medieval theological writings, to contemporary ethical thought. Though
the claim that one cannot sharply separate law and morality is often made as
part of a general natural law moral theory, the referents of the term ‘natural
law’ in legal and moral theory do not share any obvious logical relationship. A
moral theorist could conclude that there is no necessary connection between law
and morality, thus endorsing a positivist view of law, while consistently
advocating a natural law view of morality itself; conversely, a natural law
legal theorist, in accepting the view that there is a connection between law
and morality, might nonetheless endorse a substantive moral theory different
from that implied by a natural law moral theory. See also LEGAL REALISM,
NATURAL LAW, PHILOSOPHY OF LAW, POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY, RIGHTS. P.S. jury
nullification, a jury’s ability, or the exercise of that ability, to acquit a
criminal defendant despite finding facts that leave no reasonable doubt about
violation of a criminal statute. This ability is not a right, but an artifact
of criminal procedure. In the common law, the jury has sole authority to
determine the facts, and the judge to determine the law. The jury’s findings of
fact cannot be reviewed. The term ‘nullification’ suggests that jury
nullification is opposed to the rule of law. This thought would be sound only
if an extreme legal positivism were true – that the law is nothing but the
written law and the written law covers every possible fact situation. Jury
nullification is better conceived as a form of equity, a rectification of the
inherent limits of written law. In nullifying, juries make law. To make jury
nullification a right, then, raises problems of democratic legitimacy, such as
whether a small, randomly chosen group of citizens has authority to make law.
See also JURISPRUDENCE, LEGAL POSITIVISM, NATURAL LAW, POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY.
R.A.Sh. jury theorem. See CONDORCET. jus ad bellum. See JUST WAR THEORY. jus in
bello. See JUST WAR THEORY. justice, each getting what he or she is due. Formal
justice is the impartial and consistent application of principles, whether or
not the principles themselves are just. Substantive justice is closely
associated with rights, i.e., with what individuals can legitimately demand of
one another or what they can legitimately demand of their government (e.g.,
with respect to the protection of liberty or the promotion of equality).
Retributive justice concerns when and why punishment is justified. Debate
continues over whether punishment is justified as retribution for past
wrongdoing or because it deters future wrongdoing. Those who stress retribution
as the justification for punishment usually believe human beings have
libertarian free will, while those who stress deterrence usually accept
determinism. At least since Aristotle, justice has commonly been identified
both with obeying law and with treating everyone with fairness. But if law is,
and justice is not, entirely a matter of convention, then justice cannot be identified
with obeying law. The literature on legal positivism and natural law theory
contains much debate about jury nullification justice 456 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 456 whether there are moral limits on what conventions
could count as law. Corrective justice concerns the fairness of demands for
civil damages. Commutative justice concerns the fairness of wages, prices, and
exchanges. Distributive justice concerns the fairness of the distribution of
resources. Commutative justice and distributive justice are related, since
people’s wages influence how much resources they have. But the distinction is
important because it may be just to pay A more than B (because A is more
productive than B) but just that B is left with more after-tax resources (because
B has more children to feed than A does). In modern philosophy, however, the
debate about just wages and prices has been overshadowed by the larger question
of what constitutes a just distribution of resources. Some (e.g., Marx) have
advocated distributing resources in accordance with needs. Others have
advocated their distribution in whatever way maximizes utility in the long run.
Others have argued that the fair distribution is one that, in some sense, is to
everyone’s advantage. Still others have maintained that a just distribution is
whatever results from the free market. Some theorists combine these and other
approaches. See also ETHICS, KANT, RIGHTS, UTILITARIANISM. B.W.H. justice as
fairness. See RAWLS. justification, a concept of broad scope that spans
epistemology and ethics and has as special cases the concepts of apt belief and
right action. The concept has, however, highly varied application. Many things,
of many different sorts, can be justified. Prominent among them are beliefs and
actions. To say that X is justified is to say something positive about X. Other
things being equal, it is better that X be justified than otherwise. However,
not all good entities are justified. The storm’s abating may be good since it
spares some lives, but it is not thereby justified. What we can view as
justified or unjustified is what we can relate appropriately to someone’s
faculties or choice. (Believers might hence view the storm’s abating as
justified after all, if they were inclined to judge divine providence.) Just as
in epistemology we need to distinguish justification from truth, since either
of these might apply to a belief in the absence of the other, so in ethics we
must distinguish justification from utility: an action might be optimific but
not justified, and justified but not optimific. What is distinctive of
justification is then the implied evaluation of an agent (thus the connection,
however remote, with faculties of choice). To say that a belief is
(epistemically) justified (apt) or to say that an action is (ethically)
justified (“right” – in one sense) is to make or imply a judgment on the
subject and how he or she has arrived at that action or belief. Often a much
narrower concept of justification is used, one according to which X is justified
only if X has been or at least can be justified through adducing reasons. Such
adducing of reasons can be viewed as the giving of an argument of any of
several sorts: e.g., conclusive, prima facie, inductive, or deductive. A
conclusive justification or argument adduces conclusive reasons for the
possible (object of) action or belief that figures in the conclusion. In turn,
such reasons are conclusive if and only if they raise the status of the
conclusion action or belief so high that the subject concerned would be well
advised to conclude deliberation or inquiry. A prima facie justification or
argument adduces a prima facie reason R (or more than one) in favor of the
possible (object of) action or belief O that figures in the conclusion. In
turn, R is a prima facie reason for O if and only if R specifies an advantage
or positive consideration in favor of O, one that puts O in a better light than
otherwise. Even if R is a prima facie reason for O, however, R can be
outweighed, overridden, or defeated by contrary considerations RH. Thus my
returning a knife that I promised to return to its rightful owner has in its
favor the prima facie reason that it is my legal obligation and the fulfillment
of a promise, but if the owner has gone raving mad, then there may be reasons
against returning the knife that override, outweigh, or defeat. (And there may
also be reasons that defeat a positive prima facie reason without amounting to
reasons for the opposite course. Thus it may emerge that the promise to return
the knife was extracted under duress.) A (valid) deductive argument for a
certain conclusion C is a sequence of thoughts or statements whose last member
is C (not necessarily last temporally, but last in the sequence) and each
member of which is either an assumption or premise of the argument or is based
on earlier members of the sequence in accordance with a sound principle of
necessary inference, such as simplification: from (P & Q) to P; or
addition: from P to (P or Q); or modus ponens: from P and (P only if Q) to Q.
Whereas the premises of a deductive argument necessarily entail the conclusion,
which cannot possibly fail to be true when the justice as fairness
justification 457 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 457 premises are all
true, the premises of an inductive argument do not thus entail its conclusion
but offer considerations that only make the conclusion in some sense more
probable than it would be otherwise. From the premises that it rains and that
if it rains the streets are wet, one may deductively derive the conclusion that
the streets are wet. However, the premise that I have tried to start my car on
many, many winter mornings during the two years since I bought it and that it
has always started, right up to and including yesterday, does not deductively
imply that it will start when I try today. Here the conclusion does not follow
deductively. Though here the reason provided by the premise is only an
inductive reason for believing the conclusion, and indeed a prima facie and
defeasible reason, nevertheless it might well be in our sense a conclusive
reason. For it might enable us rightfully to conclude inquiry and/or
deliberation and proceed to (action or, in this case) belief, while turning our
attention to other matters (such as driving to our destination). See also
EPISTEMOLOGY, ETHICS, SKEPTICISM. E.S. justification, conclusive. See
JUSTIFICATION. justification, deductive. See JUSTIFICATION. justification,
epistemic. See EPISTEMOLGY. justification, inductive. See JUSTIFICATION.
justification, inferential. See FOUNDATIONALISM. justification, propositional.
See EPISTEMOLOGY. justification by faith, the characteristic doctrine of the
Protestant Reformation that sinful human beings can be justified before God
through faith in Jesus Christ. ‘Being justified’ is understood in forensic
terms: before the court of divine justice humans are not considered guilty
because of their sins, but rather are declared by God to be holy and righteous
in virtue of the righteousness of Christ, which God counts on their behalf.
Justification is received by faith, which is not merely belief in Christian
doctrine but includes a sincere and heartfelt trust and commitment to God in
Christ for one’s salvation. Such faith, if genuine, leads to the reception of
the transforming influences of God’s grace and to a life of love, obedience,
and service to God. These consequences of faith, however, are considered under
the heading of sanctification rather than justification. The rival Roman
Catholic doctrine of justification – often mislabeled by Protestants as
“justification by works” – understands key terms differently. ‘Being just’ is
understood not primarily in forensic terms but rather as a comprehensive state
of being rightly related to God, including the forgiveness of sins, the reception
of divine grace, and inner transformation. Justification is a work of God
initially accomplished at baptism; among the human “predispositions” for
justification are faith (understood as believing the truths God has revealed),
awareness of one’s sinfulness, hope in God’s mercy, and a resolve to do what
God requires. Salvation is a gift of God that is not deserved by human beings,
but the measure of grace bestowed depends to some extent on the sincere efforts
of the sinner who is seeking salvation. The Protestant and Catholic doctrines
are not fully consistent with each other, but neither are they the polar
opposites they are often made to appear by the caricatures each side offers of
the other. See also PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. W.Has. justification by works. See
JUSTIFICATION BY FAITH. justifying reason. See HUTCHESON. just in case. See
IFF. just war theory, a set of conditions justifying the resort to war (jus ad
bellum) and prescribing how war may permissibly be conducted (jus in bello).
The theory is a Western approach to the moral assessment of war that grew out
of the Christian tradition beginning with Augustine, later taking both
religious and secular (including legalist) forms. Proposed conditions for a
just war vary in both number and interpretation. Accounts of jus ad bellum
typically require: (1) just cause: an actual or imminent wrong against the
state, usually a violation of rights, but sometimes provided by the need to
protect innocents, defend human rights, or safeguard the way of life of one’s
own or other peoples; (2) competent authority: limiting the undertaking of war
to a state’s legitimate rulers; (3) right intention: aiming only at peace and
the ends of the just cause (and not war’s attendant suffering, death, and
destruction); (4) proportionality: ensuring that anticipated good not be
outweighed by bad; (5) last resort: exhausting peaceful alternatives before
going to war; and (6) probability of success: a reasonable prospect that war
will succeed. Jus in bello justification, conclusive just war theory 458
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 458 requires: (7) proportionality: ensuring
that the means used in war befit the ends of the just cause and that their
resultant good and bad, when individuated, be proportionate in the sense of (4);
and (8) discrimination: prohibiting the killing of noncombatants and/or
innocents. Sometimes conditions (4), (5), and (6) are included in (1). The
conditions are usually considered individually necessary and jointly sufficient
for a fully just war. But sometimes strength of just cause is taken to offset
some lack of proportion in means, and sometimes absence of right intention is
taken to render a war evil though not necessarily unjust. Most just war
theorists take jus ad bellum to warrant only defensive wars. But some follow
earlier literature and allow for just offensive wars. Early theorists deal
primarily with jus ad bellum, later writers with both jus ad bellum and jus in
bello. Recent writers stress jus in bello, with particular attention to
deterrence: the attempt, by instilling fear of retaliation, to induce an
adversary to refrain from attack. Some believe that even though large-scale use
of nuclear weapons would violate requirements of proportionality and
discrimination, the threatened use of such weapons can maintain peace, and
hence justify a system of nuclear deterrence. See also POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY.
R.L.H.
Kabala
Kala, in Indian thought,
time. The universe frequently is seen as forever oscillating between order and
chaos. Thus the goal of human existence, religiously conceived, tends to
involve escape from time. Jainism views time as immaterial, beginningless, and
continuous (without parts), distinguishing between time as perceived (in
divisions of units of our temporal measurement) and time as it inherently is
(unitless). For Sankhya-Yoga, there is no time distinct from atoms, and the
minimum temporal unit is the duration of an atom’s transverse of its own
spatial unit. For Nyaya-Vaishesika, time is a particular substance that exists
independently and appears to have parts only because we perceive it through
noticing distinct changes. Advaita Vedanta takes time to be only phenomenal and
apparent. Visistadvaita Vedanta takes time to be an inert substance dependent
on Brahman, coordinate with prakrti (material stuff), and beginningless. K.E.Y.
kalam, an Arabic term denoting a form of religious and theological discourse.
The word itself literally means ‘argue’ or ‘discuss’; although often translated
as ‘theology’ or ‘dialectical theology’, the Muslim usage does not correspond
exactly. In origin kalam was an argumentative reaction to certain perceived
doctrinal deviations on key issues – e.g., the status of the sinner, the
justice of God, attributes of God. Thus themes and content in kalam were normally
historically specific and not generally speculative. Later, in a formal
confrontation with philosophy, the predominantly dialectical mode of reasoning
employed until the twelfth century was replaced by full use of syllogistic
methods. Ultimately, the range of speculation grew until, in the sophisticated
compendiums of the major authorities, kalam became intellectually speculative
as well as doctrinally defensive. In a major development, one school of kalam –
the Ash‘arites – adopted an atomistic theory that rejected the necessity of
immediate or proximate causation, arguing instead that patterns perceived in
nature are merely the habitual actions of God as he constantly re-creates and
refashions the universe. See also ARABIC PHILOSOPHY. P.E.W. K’ang Yu-wei
(1858–1927), Chinese scholar who pushed for radical reforms under Emperor
Kuan-hsü and was forced into exile. He belonged to the modern-script school
with respect to studies of the Spring and Autumn Annals, and believed that
Confucius was only borrowing the names and authority of the ancient
sage-emperors to push for reform in his own days. K’ang gave expression to
utopian ideals in his book Ta-tung (Great Unity). Among his disciples were T’an
Ssut’ung (1865–98) and Liang Ch’i-ch’ao (1873– 1929). He became a reactionary
in his old age and refused to accept the fact that China had become a republic.
See also CONFUCIUS, LIANG CH’I-CH’AO. S.-h.L. Kant, Immanuel (1724–1804),
preeminent German philosopher whose distinctive concern was to vindicate the
authority of reason. He believed that by a critical examination of its own
powers, reason can distinguish unjustifiable traditional metaphysical claims
from the principles that are required by our theoretical need to determine
ourselves within spatiotemporal experience and by our practical need to
legislate consistently with all other rational wills. Because these principles
are necessary and discoverable, they defeat empiricism and skepticism, and
because they are disclosed as simply the conditions of orienting ourselves
coherently within experience, they contrast with traditional rationalism and
dogmatism. Kant was born and raised in the eastern Prussian university town of
Königsberg (today Kaliningrad), where, except for a short period during which
he worked as a tutor in the nearby countryside, he spent his life as student
and teacher. He was trained by Pietists and followers of Leibniz and Wolff, but
he was also heavily influenced by Newton and Rousseau. In the 1750s his
theoretical philosophy began attempting to show how metaphysics must
accommodate as certain the fundamental principles underlying modern science; in
the 1760s his 460 K 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 460 practical
philosophy began attempting to show (in unpublished form) how our moral life must
be based on a rational and universally accessible self-legislation analogous to
Rousseau’s political principles. The breakthrough to his own distinctive
philosophy came in the 1770s, when he insisted on treating epistemology as
first philosophy. After arguing in his Inaugural Dissertation (On the Form and
Principles of the Sensible and Intelligible World, 1770) both that our
spatiotemporal knowledge applies only to appearances and that we can still make
legitimate metaphysical claims about “intelligible” or non-spatiotemporal
features of reality (e.g., that there is one world of substances interconnected
by the action of God), there followed a “silent decade” of preparation for his
major work, the epoch-making Critique of Pure Reason (first or “A” edition,
1781; second or “B” edition, with many revisions, 1787; Kant’s initial reaction
to objections to the first edition dominate his short review, Prolegomena to
any Future Metaphysics, 1783; the full title of which means ‘preliminary
investigations for any future metaphysics that will be able to present itself
as a science’, i.e., as a body of certain truths). This work resulted in his
mature doctrine of transcendental idealism, namely, that all our theoretical
knowledge is restricted to the systematization of what are mere spatiotemporal
appearances. This position is also called formal or Critical idealism, because
it criticizes theories and claims beyond the realm of experience, while it also
insists that although the form of experience is ideal, or relative to us, this
is not to deny the reality of something independent of this form. Kant’s
earlier works are usually called pre-Critical not just because they precede his
Critique but also because they do not include a full commitment to this
idealism. Kant supplemented his “first Critique” (often cited just as “the”
Critique) with several equally influential works in practical philosophy –
Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785), Critique of Practical Reason
(the “second Critique,” 1788), and Metaphysics of Morals (consisting of
“Doctrine of Justice” and “Doctrine of Virtue,” 1797). Kant’s philosophy
culminated in arguments advancing a purely moral foundation for traditional
theological claims (the existence of God, immortality, and a transcendent reward
or penalty proportionate to our goodness), and thus was characterized as
“denying knowledge in order to make room for faith.” To be more precise, Kant’s
Critical project was to restrict theoretical knowledge in such a way as to make
it possible for practical knowledge to reveal how pure rational faith has an
absolute claim on us. This position was reiterated in the Critique of Judgment
(the “third Critique,” 1790), which also extended Kant’s philosophy to
aesthetics and scientific methodology by arguing for a priori but limited
principles in each of these domains. Kant was followed by radical idealists
(Fichte, Schelling), but he regarded himself as a philosopher of the
Enlightenment, and in numerous shorter works he elaborated his belief that
everything must submit to the “test of criticism,” that human reason must face
the responsibility of determining the sources, extent, and bounds of its own
principles. The Critique concerns pure reason because Kant believes all these
determinations can be made a priori, i.e., such that their justification does
not depend on any particular course of experience (‘pure’ and ‘a priori’ are
thus usually interchangeable). For Kant ‘pure reason’ often signifies just pure
theoretical reason, which determines the realm of nature and of what is, but
Kant also believes there is pure practical reason (or Wille), which determines
a priori and independently of sensibility the realm of freedom and of what
ought to be. Practical reason in general is defined as that which determines rules
for the faculty of desire and will, as opposed to the faculties of cognition
and of feeling. On Kant’s mature view, however, the practical realm is
necessarily understood in relation to moral considerations, and these in turn
in terms of laws taken to have an unconditional imperative force whose validity
requires presuming that they are addressed to a being with absolute freedom,
the faculty to choose (Willkür) to will or not to will to act for their sake.
Kant also argues that no evidence of human freedom is forthcoming from
empirical knowledge of the self as part of spatiotemporal nature, and that the
belief in our freedom, and thus the moral laws that presuppose it, would have
to be given up if we thought that our reality is determined by the laws of spatiotemporal
appearances alone. Hence, to maintain the crucial practical component of his
philosophy it was necessary for Kant first to employ his theoretical philosophy
to show that it is at least possible that the spatiotemporal realm does not
exhaust reality, so that there can be a non-empirical and free side to the
self. Therefore Kant’s first Critique is a theoretical foundation for his
entire system, which is devoted to establishing not just (i) what the most
general necessary principles for the spaKant, Immanuel Kant, Immanuel 461
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 461 tiotemporal domain are – a project that
has been called his “metaphysics of experience” – but also (ii) that this
domain cannot without contradiction define ultimate reality (hence his
transcendental idealism). The first of these claims involves Kant’s primary use
of the term ‘transcendental’, namely in the context of what he calls a
transcendental deduction, which is an argument or “exposition” that establishes
a necessary role for an a priori principle in our experience. As Kant explains,
while mathematical principles are a priori and are necessary for experience,
the mathematical proof of these principles is not itself transcendental; what
is transcendental is rather the philosophical argument that these principles
necessarily apply in experience. While in this way some transcendental
arguments may presume propositions from an established science (e.g.,
geometry), others can begin with more modest assumptions – typically the
proposition that there is experience or empirical knowledge at all – and then
move on from there to uncover a priori principles that appear required for
specific features of that knowledge. Kant begins by connecting metaphysics with
the problem of synthetic a priori judgment. As necessary, metaphysical claims
must have an a priori status, for we cannot determine that they are necessary
by mere a posteriori means. As objective rather than merely formal,
metaphysical judgments (unlike those of logic) are also said to be synthetic.
This synthetic a priori character is claimed by Kant to be mysterious and yet
shared by a large number of propositions that were undisputed in his time. The
mystery is how a proposition can be known as necessary and yet be objective or
“ampliative” or not merely “analytic.” For Kant an analytic proposition is one
whose predicate is “contained in the subject.” He does not mean this
“containment” relation to be understood psychologically, for he stresses that
we can be psychologically and even epistemically bound to affirm non-analytic
propositions. The containment is rather determined simply by what is contained
in the concepts of the subject term and the predicate term. However, Kant also
denies that we have ready real definitions for empirical or a priori concepts,
so it is unclear how one determines what is really contained in a subject or
predicate term. He seems to rely on intuitive procedures for saying when it is
that one necessarily connects a subject and predicate without relying on a hidden
conceptual relation. Thus he proposes that mathematical constructions, and not
mere conceptual elucidations, are what warrant necessary judgments about
triangles. In calling such judgments ampliative, Kant does not mean that they
merely add to what we may have explicitly seen or implicitly known about the
subject, for he also grants that complex analytic judgments may be quite
informative, and thus “new” in a psychological or epistemic sense. While Kant
stresses that non-analytic or synthetic judgments rest on “intuition”
(Anschauung), this is not part of their definition. If a proposition could be
known through its concepts alone, it must be analytic, but if it is not
knowable in this way it follows only that we need something other than
concepts. Kant presumed that this something must be intuition, but others have
suggested other possibilities, such as postulation. Intuition is a technical
notion of Kant, meant for those representations that have an immediate relation
to their object. Human intuitions are also all sensible (or sensuous) or
passive, and have a singular rather than general object, but these are less
basic features of intuition, since Kant stresses the possibility of (nonhuman)
non-sensible or “intellectual” intuition, and he implies that singularity of
reference can be achieved by non-intuitive means (e.g., in the definition of
God). The immediacy of intuition is crucial because it is what sets them off
from concepts, which are essentially representations of representations, i.e.,
rules expressing what is common to a set of representations. Kant claims that
mathematics, and metaphysical expositions of our notions of space and time, can
reveal several evident synthetic a priori propositions, e.g., that there is one
infinite space. In asking what could underlie the belief that propositions like
this are certain, Kant came to his Copernican revolution. This consists in
considering not how our representations may necessarily conform to objects as
such, but rather how objects may necessarily conform to our representations. On
a “pre-Copernican” view, objects are considered just by themselves, i.e., as
“things-in-themselves” (Dinge an sich) totally apart from any intrinsic
cognitive relation to our representations, and thus it is mysterious how we could
ever determine them a priori. If we begin, however, with our own faculties of
representation we might find something in them that determines how objects must
be – at least when considered just as phenomena (singular: phenomenon), i.e.,
as objects of experience rather than as noumena (singular: noumenon), i.e.,
things-inthemselves specified negatively as unknown and beyond our experience,
or positively as knowable in some absolute non-sensible way – which Kant,
Immanuel Kant, Immanuel 462 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 462 Kant
insists is theoretically impossible for sensible beings like us. For example,
Kant claims that when we consider our faculty for receiving impressions, or
sensibility, we can find not only contingent contents but also two necessary
forms or “pure forms of intuition”: space, which structures all outer
representations given us, and time, which structures all inner representations.
These forms can explain how the synthetic a priori propositions of mathematics
will apply with certainty to all the objects of our experience. That is, if we
suppose that in intuiting these propositions we are gaining a priori insight
into the forms of our representation that must govern all that can come to our
sensible awareness, it becomes understandable that all objects in our
experience will have to conform with these propositions. Kant presented his
transcendental idealism as preferable to all the alternative explanations that
he knew for the possibility of mathematical knowledge and the metaphysical
status of space and time. Unlike empiricism, it allowed necessary claims in
this domain; unlike rationalism, it freed the development of this knowledge
from the procedures of mere conceptual analysis; and unlike the Newtonians it
did all this without giving space and time a mysterious status as an absolute
thing or predicate of God. With proper qualifications, Kant’s doctrine of the
transcendental ideality of space and time can be understood as a radicalization
of the modern idea of primary and secondary qualities. Just as others had
contended that sensible color and sound qualities, e.g., can be
intersubjectively valid and even objectively based while existing only as
relative to our sensibility and not as ascribable to objects in themselves, so
Kant proposed that the same should be said of spatiotemporal predicates. Kant’s
doctrine, however, is distinctive in that it is not an empirical hypothesis
that leaves accessible to us other theoretical and non-ideal predicates for
explaining particular experiences. It is rather a metaphysical thesis that
enriches empirical explanations with an a priori framework, but begs off any
explanation for that framework itself other than the statement that it lies in
the “constitution” of human sensibility as such. This “Copernican” hypothesis
is not a clear proof that spatiotemporal features could not apply to objects
apart from our forms of intuition, but more support for this stronger claim is
given in Kant’s discussion of the “antinomies” of rational cosmology. An antinomy
is a conflict between two a priori arguments arising from reason when, in its
distinctive work as a higher logical faculty connecting strings of judgments,
it posits a real unconditioned item at the origin of various hypothetical
syllogisms. There are antinomies of quantity, quality, relation, and modality,
and they each proceed by pairs of dogmatic arguments which suppose that since
one kind of unconditioned item cannot be found, e.g., an absolutely first
event, another kind must be posited, e.g., a complete infinite series of past
events. For most of the other antinomies, Kant indicates that contradiction can
be avoided by allowing endless series in experience (e.g., of chains of
causality, of series of dependent beings), series that are compatible with –
but apparently do not require – unconditioned items (uncaused causes, necessary
beings) outside experience. For the antinomy of quantity, however, he argues
that the only solution is to drop the common dogmatic assumption that the set
of spatiotemporal objects constitutes a determinate whole, either absolutely
finite or infinite. He takes this to show that spatiotemporality must be
transcendentally ideal, only an indeterminate feature of our experience and not
a characteristic of things-in-themselves. Even when structured by the pure
forms of space and time, sensible representations do not yield knowledge until
they are grasped in concepts and these concepts are combined in a judgment.
Otherwise, we are left with mere impressions, scattered in an unintelligible
“multiplicity” or manifold; in Kant’s words, “thoughts without content are
empty, intuitions without concepts are blind.” Judgment requires both concepts
and intuitions; it is not just any relation of concepts, but a bringing
together of them in a particular way, an “objective” unity, so that one concept
is predicated of another – e.g., “all bodies are divisible” – and the latter
“applies to certain appearances that present themselves to us,” i.e., are
intuited. Because any judgment involves a unity of thought that can be prefixed
by the phrase ‘I think’, Kant speaks of all representations, to the extent that
they can be judged by us, as subject to a necessary unity of apperception. This
term originally signified self-consciousness in contrast to direct
consciousness or perception, but Kant uses it primarily to contrast with ‘inner
sense’, the precognitive manifold of temporal representations as they are
merely given in the mind. Kant also contrasts the empirical ego, i.e., the self
as it is known contingently in experience, with the transcendental ego, i.e.,
the self thought of as the subject of structures of intuiting and thinking that
are necessary throughout experience. Kant, Immanuel Kant, Immanuel 463
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 463 The fundamental need for concepts and
judgments suggests that our “constitution” may require not just intuitive but
also conceptual forms, i.e., “pure concepts of the understanding,” or
“categories.” The proof that our experience does require such forms comes in the
“deduction of the objective validity of the pure concepts of the
understanding,” also called the transcendental deduction of the categories, or
just the deduction. This most notorious of all Kantian arguments appears to be
in one way harder and in one way easier than the transcendental argument for
pure intuitions. Those intuitions were held to be necessary for our experience
because as structures of our sensibility nothing could even be imagined to be
given to us without them. Yet, as Kant notes, it might seem that once
representations are given in this way we can still imagine that they need not
then be combined in terms of such pure concepts as causality. On the other
hand, Kant proposed that a list of putative categories could be derived from a
list of the necessary forms of the logical table of judgments, and since these
forms would be required for any finite understanding, whatever its mode of
sensibility is like, it can seem that the validity of pure concepts is even
more inescapable than that of pure intuitions. That there is nonetheless a
special difficulty in the transcendental argument for the categories becomes
evident as soon as one considers the specifics of Kant’s list. The logical
table of judgments is an a priori collection of all possible judgment forms
organized under four headings, with three subforms each: quantity (universal,
particular, singular), quality (affirmative, negative, infinite), relation
(categorical, hypothetical, disjunctive), and modality (problematic,
assertoric, apodictic). This list does not map exactly onto any one of the
logic textbooks of Kant’s day, but it has many similarities with them; thus
problematic judgments are simply those that express logical possibility, and
apodictic ones are those that express logical necessity. The table serves Kant
as a clue to the “metaphysical deduction” of the categories, which claims to
show that there is an origin for these concepts that is genuinely a priori,
and, on the premise that the table is proper, that the derived concepts can be
claimed to be fundamental and complete. But by itself the list does not show
exactly what categories follow from, i.e., are necessarily used with, the
various forms of judgment, let alone what their specific meaning is for our
mode of experience. Above all, even when it is argued that each experience and
every judgment requires at least one of the four general forms, and that the
use of any form of judgment does involve a matching pure concept (listed in the
table of categories: reality, negation, limitation; unity, plurality, totality;
inherence and subsistence, causality and dependence, community; possibility –
impossibility, existence –non-existence, and necessity–contingency) applying to
the objects judged about, this does not show that the complex relational forms
and their corresponding categories of causality and community are necessary
unless it is shown that these specific forms of judgment are each necessary for
our experience. Precisely because this is initially not evident, it can appear,
as Kant himself noted, that the validity of controversial categories such as
causality cannot be established as easily as that of the forms of intuition.
Moreover, Kant does not even try to prove the objectivity of the traditional
modal categories but treats the principles that use them as mere definitions
relative to experience. Thus a problematic judgment, i.e., one in which
“affirmation or negation is taken as merely possible,” is used when something
is said to be possible in the sense that it “agrees with the formal conditions
of experience, i.e., with the conditions of intuition and of concepts.” A clue
for rescuing the relational categories is given near the end of the
Transcendental Deduction (B version), where Kant notes that the a priori
all-inclusiveness and unity of space and time that is claimed in the treatment
of sensibility must, like all cognitive unity, ultimately have a foundation in
judgment. Kant expands on this point by devoting a key section called the
analogies of experience to arguing that the possibility of our judging objects
to be determined in an objective position in the unity of time (and,
indirectly, space) requires three a priori principles (each called an
“Analogy”) that employ precisely the relational categories that seemed especially
questionable. Since these categories are established as needed just for the
determination of time and space, which themselves have already been argued to
be transcendentally ideal, Kant can conclude that for us even a priori claims
using pure concepts of the understanding provide what are only transcendentally
ideal claims. Thus we cannot make determinate theoretical claims about
categories such as substance, cause, and community in an absolute sense that
goes beyond our experience, but we can establish principles for their
spatiotemporal specifications, called schemata, namely, the three Analogies:
“in all change of appearance substance is permanent,” “all alterations take
place in conformity with the law of the connection of cause and Kant, Immanuel
Kant, Immanuel 464 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 464 effect,” and “all
substances, insofar as they can be perceived to coexist in space, are in
thoroughgoing reciprocity.” Kant initially calls these regulative principles of
experience, since they are required for organizing all objects of our empirical
knowledge within a unity, and, unlike the constitutive principles for the
categories of quantity and quality (namely: “all intuitions [for us] are
extensive magnitudes,” and “in all appearances the real that is an object of
sensation has intensive magnitude, that is, a degree”), they do not
characterize any individual item by itself but rather only by its real relation
to other objects of experience. Nonetheless, in comparison to mere heuristic or
methodological principles (e.g., seek simple or teleological explanations),
these Analogies are held by Kant to be objectively necessary for experience,
and for this reason can also be called constitutive in a broader sense. The
remainder of the Critique exposes the “original” or “transcendental” ideas of
pure reason that pretend to be constitutive or theoretically warranted but
involve unconditional components that wholly transcend the realm of experience.
These include not just the antinomic cosmological ideas noted above (of these
Kant stresses the idea of transcendental freedom, i.e., of uncaused causing),
but also the rational psychological ideas of the soul as an immortal substance
and the rational theological idea of God as a necessary and perfect being. Just
as the pure concepts of the understanding have an origin in the necessary forms
of judgments, these ideas are said to originate in the various syllogistic
forms of reason: the idea of a soul-substance is the correlate of an
unconditioned first term of a categorical syllogism (i.e., a subject that can
never be the predicate of something else), and the idea of God is the correlate
of the complete sum of possible predicates that underlies the unconditioned
first term of the disjunctive syllogism used to give a complete determination
of a thing’s properties. Despite the a priori origin of these notions, Kant
claims we cannot theoretically establish their validity, even though they do
have regulative value in organizing our notion of a human or divine spiritual
substance. Thus, even if, as Kant argues, traditional proofs of immortality,
and the teleological, cosmological, and ontological arguments for God’s
existence, are invalid, the notions they involve can be affirmed as long as
there is, as he believes, a sufficient non-theoretical, i.e., moral argument
for them. When interpreted on the basis of such an argument, they are
transformed into ideas of practical reason, ideas that, like perfect virtue,
may not be verified or realized in sensible experience, but have a rational
warrant in pure practical considerations. Although Kant’s pure practical
philosophy culminates in religious hope, it is primarily a doctrine of
obligation. Moral value is determined ultimately by the nature of the intention
of the agent, which in turn is determined by the nature of what Kant calls the
general maxim or subjective principle underlying a person’s action. One follows
a hypothetical imperative when one’s maxim does not presume an unconditional
end, a goal (like the fulfillment of duty) that one should have irrespective of
all sensible desires, but rather a “material end” dependent on contingent
inclinations (e.g., the directive “get this food,” in order to feel happy). In
contrast, a categorical imperative is a directive saying what ought to be done
from the perspective of pure reason alone; it is categorical because what this
perspective commands is not contingent on sensible circumstances and it always
carries overriding value. The general formula of the categorical imperative is
to act only according to those maxims that can be consistently willed as a
universal law – something said to be impossible for maxims aimed merely at
material ends. In accepting this imperative, we are doubly self-determined, for
we are not only determining our action freely, as Kant believes humans do in
all exercises of the faculty of choice; we are also accepting a principle whose
content is determined by that which is absolutely essential to us as agents,
namely our pure practical reason. We thus are following our own law and so have
autonomy when we accept the categorical imperative; otherwise we fall into
heteronomy, or the (free) acceptance of principles whose content is determined
independently of the essential nature of our own ultimate being, which is
rational. Given the metaphysics of his transcendental idealism, Kant can say
that the categorical imperative reveals a supersensible power of freedom in us
such that we must regard ourselves as part of an intelligible world, i.e., a
domain determined ultimately not by natural laws but rather by laws of reason.
As such a rational being, an agent is an end in itself, i.e., something whose
value is not dependent on external material ends, which are contingent and
valued only as means to the end of happiness – which is itself only a
conditional value (since the satisfaction of an evil will would be improper).
Kant regards accepting the categorical imperative as tantamount to respecting
rational nature as an end in itself, and to willing as if we were legislating a
kingdom of ends. This is to will that the world become a “systematic Kant,
Immanuel Kant, Immanuel 465 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 465 union of
different rational beings through common laws,” i.e., laws that respect and
fulfill the freedom of all rational beings. Although there is only one
fundamental principle of morality, there are still different types of specific
duties. One basic distinction is between strict duty and imperfect duty. Duties
of justice, of respecting in action the rights of others, or the duty not to
violate the dignity of persons as rational agents, are strict because they
allow no exception for one’s inclination. A perfect duty is one that requires a
specific action (e.g. keeping a promise), whereas an imperfect duty, such as
the duty to perfect oneself or to help others, cannot be completely discharged
or demanded by right by someone else, and so one has considerable latitude in
deciding when and how it is to be respected. A meritorious duty involves going
beyond what is strictly demanded and thereby generating an obligation in
others, as when one is extraordinarily helpful to others and “merits” their
gratitude. See also EPISTEMOLOGY, ETHICS, IDEALISM, METAPHYSICS, RATIONALISM,
TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENT. K.A. Kao Tzu (fifth–fourth century B.C.), Chinese
thinker and philosophical adversary of Mencius (4th century B.C.). He is
referred to in the Meng Tzu (Book of Mencius). A figure of the same name
appeared in the Mo Tzu as a (probably younger) contemporary of Mo Tzu (fifth
century B.C.), but it is unclear if the two were the same individual. As
presented in the Meng Tzu, Kao Tzu held that human nature (hsing) is morally
neutral, and that living morally requires learning rightness (yi) from sources
(such as philosophical doctrines) outside the heart/mind (hsin), and shaping
one’s way of life accordingly. These ideas are opposed to Mencius’s belief that
the heart/mind has incipient moral inclinations from which rightness can be
derived, and that living morally involves one’s fully developing such
inclinations. Ever since the view that Mencius was the true transmitter of
Confucius’s teachings became established, largely through the efforts of Chu
Hsi (1130–1200), Confucians have distanced themselves from Kao Tzu’s position and
even criticized philosophical opponents for holding positions similar to Kao
Tzu’s. See also CONFUCIANISM, MENCIUS. K.-l.S. karma, in Indian thought, the
force whereby right and wrong actions bring benefits and punishments in this or
a future existence. This occurs not arbitrarily, but by law. The conditions of
birth (one’s sex, caste, circumstances of life) are profoundly affected by
one’s karmic “bank account.” A typical Buddhist perspective is that the state
of the non-conscious world at any given time is largely determined by the total
karmic situation that then holds. For all of the Indian perspectives that
accept the karma-and-transmigration perspective, religious enlightenment, the
highest good, includes escape from karma. Were it absolutely impossible to act
without karmic consequences, obviously such escape would be impossible.
(Suicide is viewed as merely ending the life of one’s current body, and
typically is viewed as wrong, so that the cosmic effect of one’s suicide will
be more punishment.) Thus non-theistic views hold that one who has achieved a
pre-enlightenment status – typically reached by meditation, alms-giving,
ascetic discipline, or the achieving of esoteric knowledge – can act so as to
maintain life without collecting karmic consequences so long as one’s actions
are not morally wrong and are done disinterestedly. In theistic perspectives,
where moral wrongdoing is sin and acting rightly is obedience to God, karma is
the justice of Brahman in action and Brahman may pardon a repentant sinner from
the results of wrong actions and place the forgiven sinner in a relation to
Brahman that, at death, releases him or her from the transmigratory wheel. See
also BRAHMAN, BUDDHISM. K.E.Y. karmic. See KARMA. katastematic pleasure. See
EPICUREANISM. Kepler, Johannes (1571–1630), German mathematical astronomer,
speculative metaphysician, and natural philosopher. He was born in Weil der
Stadt, near Stuttgart. He studied astronomy with Michael Maestlin at the
University of Tübingen, and then began the regular course of theological
studies that prepared him to become a Lutheran pastor. Shortly before
completing these studies he accepted the post of mathematician at Graz.
“Mathematics” was still construed as including astronomy and astrology. There
he published the Mysterium cosmographicum (1596), the first mjaor astronomical
work to utilize the Copernican system since Copernicus’s own De revolutionibus
half a century before. The Copernican shift of the sun to the center allowed
Kepler to propose an explanation for the spacing of the planets (the Creator
inscribed the successive planetary orbits in the five regular polyhedra) and
for their motions (a sun-centered driving force diminishing with disKao Tzu
Kepler, Johannes 466 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 466 tance from the
sun). In this way, he could claim to have overcome the traditional prohibition
against the mathematical astronomer’s claiming reality for the motion he
postulates. Ability to explain had always been the mark of the philosopher.
Kepler, a staunch Lutheran, was forced to leave Catholic Graz as bitter
religious and political disputes engulfed much of northern Europe. He took
refuge in the imperial capital, Prague, where Tycho Brahe, the greatest
observational astronomer of the day, had established an observatory. Tycho
asked Kepler to compose a defense of Tycho’s astronomy against a critic,
Nicolaus Ursus, who had charged that it was “mere hypothesis.” The resulting
Apologia (1600) remained unpublished; it contains a perceptive analysis of the
nature of astronomical hypothesis. Merely saving the phenomena, Kepler argues,
is in general not sufficient to separate two mathematical systems like those of
Ptolemy and Copernicus. Other more properly explanatory “physical” criteria
will be needed. Kepler was allowed to begin work on the orbit of Mars, using
the mass of data Tycho had accumulated. But shortly afterward, Tycho died
suddenly (1601). Kepler succeeded to Tycho’s post as Imperial Mathematician;
more important, he was entrusted with Tycho’s precious data. Years of labor led
to the publication of the Astronomia nova (1609), which announced the discovery
of the elliptical orbit of Mars. One distinctive feature of Kepler’s long quest
for the true shape of the orbit was his emphasis on finding a possible physical
evaluation for any planetary motion he postulated before concluding that it was
the true motion. Making the sun’s force magnetic allowed him to suppose that
its effect on the earth would vary as the earth’s magnetic axis altered its
orientation to the sun, thus perhaps explaining the varying distances and
speeds of the earth in its elliptical orbit. The full title of his book makes
his ambition clear: A New Astronomy Based on Causes, or A Physics of the Sky.
Trouble in Prague once more forced Kepler to move. He eventually found a place
in Linz (1612), where he continued his exploration of cosmic harmonies, drawing
on theology and philosophy as well as on music and mathematics. The Harmonia
mundi (1618) was his favorite among his books: “It can wait a century for a
reader, as God himself has waited six thousand years for a witness.” The
discovery of what later became known as his third law, relating the periodic
times of any two planets as the ratio of the 3 /2 power of their mean
distances, served to confirm his long-standing conviction that the universe is
fashioned according to ideal harmonic relationships. In the Epitome astronomiae
Copernicanae (1612), he continued his search for causes “either natural or
archetypal,” not only for the planetary motions, but for such details as the
size of the sun and the densities of the planets. He was more convinced than
ever that a physics of the heavens had to rest upon its ability to explain (and
not just to predict) the peculiarities of the planetary and lunar motions. What
prevented him from moving even further than he did toward a new physics was
that he had not grasped what later came to be called the principle of inertia.
Thus he was compelled to postulate not only an attractive force between planet
and sun but also a second force to urge the planet onward. It was Newton who
showed that the second force is unnecessary, and who finally constructed the
“physics of the sky” that had been Kepler’s ambition. But he could not have
done it without Kepler’s notion of a quantifiable force operating between
planet and sun, an unorthodox notion shaped in the first place by an
imagination steeped in Neoplatonic metaphysics and the theology of the Holy
Spirit. See also NEWTON. E.M. Kerry’s paradox. See FREGE. Keynes, John Maynard
(1883–1946), English economist and public servant who revolutionized economic
theory and the application of economic theory in government policy. His most
philosophically important works were The General Theory of Employment, Interest
and Money (1936) and A Treatise on Probability (1921). Keynes was also active
in English philosophical life, being well acquainted with such thinkers as
Moore and Ramsey. In the philosophy of probability, Keynes pioneered the
treatment of propositions as the bearers of probability assignments. Unlike
classical subjectivists, he treated probabilities as objective evidential
relations among propositions. These relations were to be directly epistemically
accessible to an intuitive faculty. An idiosyncratic feature of Keynes’s system
is that different probability assignments cannot always be compared (ordered as
equal, less than, or greater than one another). Keynesian economics is still
presented in introductory textbooks and it has permanently affected both theory
and practice. Keynes’s economic thought had a number of philosophically Kerry’s
paradox Keynes, John Maynard 467 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 467
important dimensions. While his theorizing was in the capitalistic tradition,
he rejected Smith’s notion of an invisible hand that would optimize the
performance of an economy without any intentional direction by individuals or
by the government. This involved rejection of the economic policy of
laissez-faire, according to which government intervention in the economy’s
operation is useless, or worse. Keynes argued that natural forces could deflect
an economy from a course of optimal growth and keep it permanently out of
equilibria. In the General Theory he proposed a number of mechanisms for
adjusting its performance. He advocated programs of government taxation and
spending, not primarily as a means of providing public goods, but as a means of
increasing prosperity and avoiding unemployment. Political philosophers are
thereby provided with another means for justifying the existence of strong
governments. One of the important ways that Keynes’s theory still directs much
economic theorizing is its deep division between microeconomics and
macroeconomics. Keynes argued, in effect, that microeconomic analysis with its
emphasis on ideal individual rationality and perfect competition was inadequate
as a tool for understanding such important macrophenomena as employment,
interest, and money. He tried to show how human psychological foibles and
market frictions required a qualitatively different kind of analysis at the
macro level. Much current economic theorizing is concerned with understanding
the connections between micro- and macrophenomena and micro- and macroeconomics
in an attempt to dissolve or blur the division. This issue is a philosophically
important instance of a potential theoretical reduction. See also PHILOSOPHY OF
ECONOMICS, PROBABILITY. A.N. Kierkegaard, Søren Aabye (1813–55), Danish writer
whose “literature,” as he called it, includes philosophy, psychology, theology
and devotional literature, fiction, and literary criticism. Born to a
well-to-do middle class family, he consumed his inheritance while writing a
large corpus of books in a remarkably short time. His life was marked by an
intense relationship with a devout but melancholy father, from whom he
inherited his own bent to melancholy, with which he constantly struggled. A
decisive event was his broken engagement from Regine Olsen, which precipitated
the beginning of his authorship; his first books are partly an attempt to
explain, in a covert and symbolic way, the reasons why he felt he could not
marry. Later Kierkegaard was involved in a controversy in which he was
mercilessly attacked by a popular satirical periodical; this experience deepened
his understanding of the significance of suffering and the necessity for an
authentic individual to stand alone if necessary against “the crowd.” This
caused him to abandon his plans to take a pastorate, a post for which his
theological education had prepared him. At the end of his life, he waged a
lonely, public campaign in the popular press and in a magazine he founded
himself, against the Danish state church. He collapsed on the street with the
final issue of this magazine, The Instant, ready for the printer, and was
carried to a hospital. He died a few weeks later, affirming a strong Christian
faith, but refusing to take communion from the hands of a priest of the
official church. Though some writers have questioned whether Kierkegaard’s
writings admit of a unified interpretation, he himself saw his literature as
serving Christianity; he saw himself as a “missionary” whose task was to
“reintroduce Christianity into Christendom.” However, much of this literature
does not address Christianity directly, but rather concerns itself with an
analysis of human existence. Kierkegaard saw this as necessary, because
Christianity is first and foremost a way of existing. He saw much of the
confusion about Christian faith as rooted in confusion about the nature of existence;
hence to clear up the former, the latter must be carefully analyzed. The great
misfortune of “Christendom” and “the present age” is that people “have
forgotten what it means to exist,” and Kierkegaard sees himself as a modern
Socrates sent to “remind” others of what they know but have forgotten. It is
not surprising that the analyses of human existence he provides have been of
great interest to non-Christian writers as well. Kierkegaard frequently uses
the verb ‘to exist’ (at existere) in a special sense, to refer to human
existence. In this sense God is said not to exist, even though God has eternal
reality. Kierkegaard describes human existence as an unfinished process, in
which “the individual” (a key concept in his thought) must take responsibility
for achieving an identity as a self through free choices. Such a choice is
described as a leap, to highlight Kierkegaard’s view that intellectual
reflection alone can never motivate action. A decision to end the process of
reflection is necessary and such a decision must be generated by passion. The
passions that shape a person’s self are referred to by Kierkegaard as the
individual’s “inwardness” or “subjectivity.” The most signifiKierkegaard, Søren
Aabye Kierkegaard, Søren Aabye 468 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 468 cant
passions, such as love and faith, do not merely happen; they must be cultivated
and formed. The process by which the individual becomes a self is described by
Kierkegaard as ideally moving through three stages, termed the “stages on
life’s way.” Since human development occurs by freedom and not automatically,
however, the individual can become fixated in any of these stages. Thus the
stages also confront each other as rival views of life, or “spheres of
existence.” The three stages or spheres are the aesthetic, the ethical, and the
religious. A distinctive feature of Kierkegaard’s literature is that these
three lifeviews are represented by pseudonymous “characters” who actually
“author” some of the books; this leads to interpretive difficulties, since it
is not always clear what to attribute to Kierkegaard himself and what to the
pseudonymous character. Fortunately, he also wrote many devotional and
religious works under his own name, where this problem does not arise. The
aesthetic life is described by Kierkegaard as lived for and in “the moment.” It
is a life governed by “immediacy,” or the satisfaction of one’s immediate
desires, though it is capable of a kind of development in which one learns to
enjoy life reflectively, as in the arts. What the aesthetic person lacks is
commitment, which is the key to the ethical life, a life that attempts to
achieve a unified self through commitment to ideals with enduring validity,
rather than simply momentary appeal. The religious life emerges from the
ethical life when the individual realizes both the transcendent character of
the true ideals and also how far short of realizing those ideals the person is.
In Concluding Unscientific Postscript two forms of the religious life are
distinguished: a “natural” religiosity (religiousness “A”) in which the person
attempts to relate to the divine and resolve the problem of guilt, relying
solely on one’s natural “immanent” idea of the divine; and Christianity
(religiousness “B”), in which God becomes incarnate as a human being in order
to establish a relation with humans. Christianity can be accepted only through
the “leap of faith.” It is a religion not of “immanence” but of
“transcendence,” since it is based on a revelation. This revelation cannot be
rationally demonstrated, since the incarnation is a paradox that transcends
human reason. Reason can, however, when the passion of faith is present, come
to understand the appropriateness of recognizing its own limits and accepting
the paradoxical incarnation of God in the form of Jesus Christ. The true
Christian is not merely an admirer of Jesus, but one who believes by becoming a
follower. The irreducibility of the religious life to the ethical life is
illustrated for Kierkegaard in the biblical story of Abraham’s willingness to
sacrifice his son Isaac to obey the command of God. In Fear and Trembling
Kierkegaard (through his pseudonym Johannes de Silentio) analyzes this act of
Abraham’s as involving a “teleological suspension of the ethical.” Abraham’s
act cannot be understood merely in ethical terms as a conflict of duties in
which one rationally comprehensible duty is superseded by a higher one. Rather,
Abraham seems to be willing to “suspend” the ethical as a whole in favor of a
higher religious duty. Thus, if one admires Abraham as “the father of faith,”
one admires a quality that cannot be reduced to simply moral virtue. Some have
read this as a claim that religious faith may require immoral behavior; others
argue that what is relativized by the teleological suspension of the ethical is
not an eternally valid set of moral requirements, but rather ethical
obligations as these are embedded in human social institutions. Thus, in
arguing that “the ethical” is not the highest element in existence, Kierkegaard
leaves open the possibility that our social institutions, and the ethical
ideals that they embody, do not deserve our absolute and unqualified
allegiance, an idea with important political implications. In accord with his
claim that existence cannot be reduced to intellectual thought, Kierkegaard
devotes much attention to emotions and passions. Anxiety is particularly
important, since it reflects human freedom. Anxiety involves a “sympathetic
antipathy and an antipathetic sympathy”; it is the psychological state that
precedes the basic human fall into sin, but it does not explain this “leap,”
since no final explanation of a free choice can be given. Such negative
emotions as despair and guilt are also important for Kierkegaard; they reveal
the emptiness of the aesthetic and the ultimately unsatisfactory character of
the ethical, driving individuals on toward the religious life. Irony and humor
are also seen as important “boundary zones” for the stages of existence. The
person who has discovered his or her own “eternal validity” can look ironically
at the relative values that capture most people, who live their lives
aesthetically. Similarly, the “existential humorist” who has seen the
incongruities that necessarily pervade our ethical human projects is on the border
of the religious life. Kierkegaard also analyzes the passions of faith
Kierkegaard, Søren Aabye Kierkegaard, Søren Aabye 469 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999
7:40 AM Page 469 and love. Faith is ultimately understood as a “willing to be
oneself” that is made possible by a transparent, trusting relationship to the
“power that created the self.” Kierkegaard distinguishes various forms of love,
stressing that Christian love must be understood as neighbor love, a love that
is combined and is not rooted in any natural relationship to the self, such as
friendship or kinship, but ultimately is grounded in the fact that all humans
share a relationship to their creator. Kierkegaard is well known for his
critique of Hegel’s absolute idealism. Hegel’s claim to have written “the
system” is ridiculed for its pretensions of finality. From the Dane’s
perspective, though reality may be a system for God, it cannot be so for any
existing thinker, since both reality and the thinker are incomplete and system
implies completeness. Hegelians are also criticized for pretending to have
found a presuppositionless or absolute starting point; for Kierkegaard,
philosophy begins not with doubt but with wonder. Reflection is potentially
infinite; the doubt that leads to skepticism cannot be ended by thought alone
but only by a resolution of the will. Kierkegaard also defends traditional
Aristotelian logic and the principle of non-contradiction against the Hegelian
introduction of “movement” into logic. Kierkegaard is particularly disturbed by
the Hegelian tendency to see God as immanent in society; he thought it
important to understand God as “wholly other,” the “absolutely different” who
can never be exhaustively embodied in human achievement or institutions. To
stand before God one must stand as an individual, in “fear and trembling,”
conscious that this may require a break with the given social order.
Kierkegaard is often characterized as the father of existentialism. There are
reasons for this; he does indeed philosophize existentially, and he undoubtedly
exercised a deep influence on many twentieth-century existentialists such as
Sartre and Camus. But the characterization is anachronistic, since
existentialism as a movement is a twentieth-century phenomenon, and the
differences between Kierkegaard and those existentialists are also profound. If
existentialism is defined as the denial that there is such a thing as a human
essence or nature, it is unlikely that Kierkegaard is an existentialist. More
recently, the Dane has also been seen as a precursor of postmodernism. His
rejection of classical foundationalist epistemologies and employment of elusive
literary techniques such as his pseudonyms again make such associations
somewhat plausible. However, despite his rejection of the system and criticism of
human claims to finality and certitude, Kierkegaard does not appear to espouse
any form of relativism or have much sympathy for “anti-realism.” He has the
kind of passion for clarity and delight in making sharp distinctions that are
usually associated with contemporary “analytic” philosophy. In the end he must
be seen as his own person, a unique Christian presence with sensibilities that
are in many ways Greek and premodern rather than postmodern. He has been
joyfully embraced and fervently criticized by thinkers of all stripes. He
remains “the individual” he wrote about, and to whom he dedicated many of his
works. See also CAMUS, EXISTENTIALISM, HEGEL, POSTMODERN, SARTRE. C.S.E.
Kilvington, Richard, surname also spelled Kilmington, Chillington (1302/05–61),
English philosopher, theologian, and ecclesiastic. He was a scholar associated
with the household of Richard de Bury and an early member of the Oxford
Calculators, important in the early development of physics. Kilvington’s
Sophismata (early 1320s) is the only work of his studied extensively to date.
It is an investigation of puzzles regarding change, velocity and acceleration,
motive power, beginning and ceasing, the continuum, infinity, knowing and
doubting, and the liar and related paradoxes. His approach is peculiar insofar
as all these are treated in a purely logical or conceptual way, in contrast to
the mathematical “calculations” used by Bradwardine, Heytesbury, and other
later Oxford Calculators to handle problems in physics. Kilvington also wrote a
commentary on Peter Lombard’s Sentences and questions on Aristotle’s On
Generation and Corruption, Physics, and Nicomachean Ethics. See also OXFORD
CALCULATORS. P.V.S. Kilwardby, Robert (d.1279), English philosopher and
theologian. He apparently studied and perhaps taught at the University of
Paris, later joining the Dominicans and perhaps lecturing at Oxford. He became
archbishop of Canterbury in 1272 and in 1277 condemned thirty propositions,
among them Aquinas’s position that there is a single substantial form in a
human being. Kilwardby resigned his archbishopric in 1278 and was appointed to
the bishopric of Santa Rufina in Italy, where he died. Kilwardby wrote
extensively and had considerable medieval influence, especially in philosophy
of language; but it is now unusually difficult to determine which works are
authentically his. De Ortu Scientiarum advanced a sophisticated Kilvington,
Richard Kilwardby, Robert 470 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 470 account
of how names are imposed and a detailed account of the nature and role of
logic. In metaphysics he insisted that things are individual and that
universality arises from operations of the soul. He wrote extensively on
happiness and was concerned to show that some happiness is possible in this life.
In psychology he argued that freedom of decision is a disposition arising from
the cooperation of the intellect and the will. C.G.Norm. Kim, Jaegwon (b.1934),
Korean-American philosopher, writing in the analytic tradition, author of
important works in metaphysics and the philosophy of mind. Kim has defended a
“fine-grained” conception of events according to which an event is the
possessing of a property by an object at a time (see “Causation, Nomic
Subsumption, and the Concept of Event,” 1973; this and other papers referred to
here are collected in Supervenience and Mind, 1993). This view has been a
prominent rival of the “coarse-grained” account of events associated with
Davidson. Kim’s work on the concept of supervenience has been widely
influential, especially in the philosophy of mind (see “Supervenience as a
Philosophical Concept,” 1990). He regards supervenience (or, as he now prefers,
“property covariation”) as a relation holding between property families (mental
properties and physical properties, for instance). If A-properties supervene on
B-properties, then, necessarily, for any A-property, a, if an object, o, has a,
there is some B-property, b, such that o has b, and (necessarily) anything that
has b has a. Stronger or weaker versions of supervenience result from varying
the modal strength of the parenthetical ‘necessarily’, or omitting it entirely.
Although the notion of supervenience has been embraced by philosophers who
favor some form of “non-reductive physicalism” (the view that the mental depends
on, but is not reducible to, the physical), Kim himself has expressed doubts
that physicalism can avoid reduction (“The Myth of Nonreductive Materialism,”
1989). If mental properties supervene on, but are distinct from, physical
properties, then it is hard to see how mental properties could have a part in
the production of physical effects – or mental effects, given the dependence of
the mental on the physical. More recently, Kim has developed an account of
“functional reduction” according to which supervenient properties are causally
efficacious if and only if they are functionally reducible to properties
antecedently accepted as causally efficacious (Mind in a Physical World, 1998).
Properties, including properties of conscious experiences, not so reducible are
“epiphenomenal.” See also DAVIDSON, EVENT, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND, REDUCTION,
SUPERVENIENCE. J.F.H. Kindi, al-. See AL-KINDi. kinesis. See ARISTOTLE. kinetic
pleasure. See EPICUREANISM. kingdom of ends. See KANT. KK-thesis, the thesis
that knowing entails knowing that one knows, symbolized in propositional
epistemic logic as Kp P KKp, where ‘K’ stands for knowing. According to the
KK-thesis, the (propositional) logic of knowledge resembles the modal system
S4. The KK-thesis was introduced into epistemological discussion by Hintikka in
Knowledge and Belief (1962). He calls the KKthesis a “virtual implication,” a
conditional whose negation is “indefensible.” A tacit or an explicit acceptance
of the thesis has been part of many philosophers’ views about knowledge since
Plato and Aristotle. If the thesis is formalized as Kap P KaKap, where ‘Ka’ is
read as ‘a knows that’, it holds only if the person a knows that he is referred
to by ‘a’; this qualification is automatically satisfied for the first-person case.
The validity of the thesis seems sensitive to variations in the sense of
‘know’; it has sometimes been thought to characterize a strong concept of
knowledge, e.g., knowledge based on (factually) conclusive reasons, or active
as opposed to implicit knowledge. If knowledge is regarded as true belief based
on conclusive evidence, the KKthesis entails that a person knows that p only if
his evidence for p is also sufficient to justify the claim that he knows that
p; the epistemic claim should not require additional evidence. See also
EPISTEMOLOGY. R.Hi. Kleist, Heinrich von (1771–1811), German philosopher and
literary figure whose entire work is based on the antinomy of reason and
sentiment, one as impotent as the other, and reflects the Aufklärung crisis at
the turn of the century. In 1799 he resigned from the Prussian army. Following
a reading of Kant, he lost faith in a “life’s plan” as inspired by Leibniz’s,
Wolff’s, and Shaftesbury’s rationalism. He looked for salvation in Rousseau but
concluded that sentiment Kim, Jaegwon Kleist, Heinrich von 471 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 471 revealed itself just as untrustworthy as reason as
soon as man left the state of original grace and realized himself to be neither
a puppet nor a god (see Essay on the Puppet Theater, 1810). The Schroffenstein
Family, Kleist’s first play (1802), repeats the Shakespearian theme of two
young people who love each other but belong to warring families. One already
finds in it the major elements of Kleist’s universe: the incapacity of the
individual to master his fate, the theme of the tragic error, and the
importance of the juridical. In 1803, Kleist returned to philosophy and
literature and realized in Amphitryon (1806) the impossibility of the
individual knowing himself and the world and acting deliberately in it. The
divine order that is the norm of tragic art collapses, and with it, the
principle of identity. Kleistian characters, “modern” individuals, illustrate
this normative chaos. The Broken Jug (a comedy written in 1806) shows Kleist’s
interest in law. In his two parallel plays, Penthesilea and The Young Catherine
of Heilbronn, Kleist presents an alternative: either “the marvelous order of
the world” and the theodicy that carries Catherine’s fate, or the sublime and
apocryphal mission of the Christlike individual who must redeem the corrupt
order. Before his suicide in 1811, Kleist looked toward the renaissance of the
German nation for a historical way out of this metaphysical conflict. See also
LEIBNIZ, SHAFTESBURY, WOLFF. G.Ra. knower, paradox of the. See DEONTIC
PARADOXES. knowledge, tacit. See EPISTEMOLOGY. knowledge, causal theory of. See
EPISTEMOLOGY, NATURALISTIC EPISTEMOLOGY. knowledge, direct. See BASING
RELATION. knowledge, indirect. See BASING RELATION. knowledge, inferential. See
INFERENTIAL KNOWLEDGE. knowledge, propositional. See EPISTEMOLOGY. knowledge,
relativity of. See MANNHEIM.
knowledge by
acquaintance, knowledge of objects by means of direct awareness of them. The
notion of knowledge by acquaintance is primarily associated with Russell (The
Problems of Philosophy, 1912). Russell first distinguishes knowledge of truths
from knowledge of things. He then distinguishes two kinds of knowledge of
things: knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description. Ordinary speech
suggests that we are acquainted with the people and the physical objects in our
immediate environments. On Russell’s view, however, our contact with these
things is indirect, being mediated by our mental representations of them. He
holds that the only things we know by acquaintance are the content of our
minds, abstract universals, and, perhaps, ourselves. Russell says that
knowledge by description is indirect knowledge of objects, our knowledge being
mediated by other objects and truths. He suggests that we know external
objects, such as tables and other people, only by description (e.g., the cause
of my present experience). Russell’s discussion of this topic is quite
puzzling. The considerations that lead him to say that we lack acquaintance
with external objects also lead him to say that, strictly speaking, we lack
knowledge of such things. This seems to amount to the claim that what he has
called “knowledge by description” is not, strictly speaking, a kind of
knowledge at all. Russell also holds that every proposition that a person
understands must be composed entirely of elements with which the person is
acquainted. This leads him to propose analyses of familiar propositions in
terms of mental objects with which we are acquainted. See also PERCEPTION,
RUSSELL. R.Fe. knowledge by description. See KNOWLEDGE BY ACQUAINTANCE.
knowledge de dicto. See KNOWLEDGE DE RE. knowledge de re, knowledge, with
respect to some object, that it has a particular property, or knowledge, of a
group of objects, that they stand in some relation. Knowledge de re is
typically contrasted with knowledge de dicto, which is knowledge of facts or
propositions. If persons A and B know that a winner has been declared in an
election, but only B knows which candidate has won, then both have de dicto
knowledge that someone has won, but only B has de re knowledge about some
candidate that she is the winner. Person B can knowingly attribute the property
of being the winner to one of the candidates. It is generally held that to have
de re knowledge about an object one must at least be in some sense familiar
with or causally connected to the object. knower, paradox of the knowledge de
re 472 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 472 A related concept is knowledge
de se. This is self-knowledge, of the sort expressed by ‘I am —— ’. Knowledge
de se is not simply de re knowledge about oneself. A person might see a group
of people in a mirror and notice that one of the people has a red spot on his
nose. He then has de dicto knowledge that someone in the group has a red spot
on his nose. On most accounts, he also has de re knowledge with respect to that
individual that he has a spot. But if he has failed to recognize that he
himself is the one with the spot, then he lacks de se knowledge. He doesn’t
know (or believe) what he would express by saying “I have a red spot.” So,
according to this view, knowledge de se is not merely knowledge de re about
oneself. See also DE DICTO. R.Fe. knowledge de se. See KNOWLEDGE DE RE.
knowledge, tacit. See EPISTEMOLOGY. Köhler, Wolfgang (1887–1967), German and
American (after 1935) psychologist who, with Wertheimer and Koffka, founded
Gestalt psychology. Köhler made two distinctive contributions to Gestalt
doctrine, one empirical, one theoretical. The empirical contribution was his
study of animal thinking, performed on Tenerife Island from 1913 to 1920 (The
Mentality of Apes, 1925). The then dominant theory of problem solving was E. L.
Thorndike’s (1874–1949) associationist trial-and-error learning theory, maintaining
that animals attack problems by trying out a series of behaviors, one of which
is gradually “stamped in” by success. Köhler argued that trial-and-error
behavior occurred only when, as in Thorndike’s experiments, part of the problem
situation was hidden. He arranged more open puzzles, such as getting bananas
hanging from a ceiling, requiring the ape to get a (visible) box to stand on.
His apes showed insight – suddenly arriving at the correct solution. Although
he demonstrated the existence of insight, its nature remains elusive, and
trial-and-error learning remains the focus of research. Köhler’s theoretical
contribution was the concept of isomorphism, Gestalt psychology’s theory of
psychological representation. He held an identity theory of mind and body, and
isomorphism claims that a topological mapping exists between the behavioral
field in which an organism is acting (cf. Lewin) and fields of electrical
currents in the brain (not the “mind”). Such currents have not been discovered.
Important works by Köhler include Gestalt Psychology (1929), The Place of Value
in a World of Facts (1938), Dynamics in Psychology (1940), and Selected Papers
(1971, ed. M. Henle). See also FIGURE–GROUND. T.H.L. Ko Hung (fourth century
A.D.), Chinese Taoist philosopher, also known as the Master Who Embraced
Simplicity (Pao-p’u tzu). Ko Hung is a pivotal figure in the development of
Taoism. His major work, the Pao-p’u tzu, emphasizes the importance of moral
cultivation as a necessary step to spiritual liberation. In this Ko is often
said to have synthesized Confucian concerns with Taoist aspirations. He
champions the use of special drugs that would purify the body and spirit in the
quest for Taoist transcendence. A firm believer in the existence of immortals
(hsien) and the possibility of joining the ranks of the perfected, Ko
experimented with different methods that fall under the rubric of “external
alchemy” (wai-tan), which merits attention also in the history of Chinese
science. See also HSIEN. A.K.L.C. Korean philosophy, philosophy in traditional
Korea. Situated on the eastern periphery of the Asian mainland and cut off by
water on three sides from other potential countervailing influences, Korea,
with its more than two millennia of recorded history and a long tradition of
philosophical reflection, was exposed from early on to the pervasive influence
of China. The influences and borrowings from China – among the most pervasive
of which have been the three major religiophilosophic systems of the East,
Taoism, Buddhism, and Confucianism – were, in time, to leave their indelible
marks on the philosophical, cultural, religious, linguistic, and social forms
of Korean life. These influences from the Asian continent, which began to
infiltrate Korean culture during the Three Kingdoms era (57 B.C. to A.D. 558),
did not, however, operate in a vacuum. Even in the face of powerful and
pervasive exogenous influences, shamanism – an animistic view of man and nature
– remained the strong substratum of Korean culture, influencing and modifying
the more sophisticated religions, philosophies, and ideologies that found entry
into Korea during the last two thousand years. Originally a philosophical
formula for personal salvation through the renunciation of worldly desire,
Buddhism, in the course of propagation from its point of origin, had absorbed
enough esoteric deities and forms of worship to constitute a new school,
Mahayana, and it was this type of Buddhism that found ready acceptance in
Korea. Its beliefs were, at the plebeian level, furknowledge de se Korean
philosophy 473 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 473 ther mixed with native
shamanism and integrated into a shamanistic polytheism. The syncretic nature of
Korean Buddhism manifests itself at the philosophical level in a tendency toward
a reconciliatory synthesis of opposing doctrines. Korean Buddhism produced a
number of monk-philosophers, whose philosophical writings were influential
beyond the boundaries of Korea. Wonhyo (617–86) of Silla and Pojo Chinul
(1158–1210) of Koryo may be singled out as the most original and representative
of those Buddhist philosophers. As Buddhism became more entrenched, a number of
doctrinal problems and disputes began to surface. The most basic and serious
was the dispute between the Madhyamika and Vijnaptimatrata-vadin schools of
thought within Mahayana Buddhism. At the metaphysical level the former tended
to negate existence, while the latter affirmed existence. An epistemological
corollary of this ontological dispute was a dispute concerning the possibility
of secular truth as opposed to transcendental truth. The former school denied
its possibility, while the latter affirmed it. No mediation between these two
schools of thought, either in their country of origin, India, or Korea, seemed
possible. It was to this task of reconciling these two opposed schools that
Wonhyo dedicated himself. In a series of annotations and interpretations of the
Buddhist scriptures, particularly of the Taeseung Kishin-non (“The Awakening of
Faith in Mahayana”), he worked out a position that became subsequently known as
Hwajaengnon – a theory of reconciliation of dispute. It consisted in essence of
seeing the two opposed schools as two different aspects of one mind. Wonhyo’s
Hwajaeng-non, as the first full-scale attempt to reconcile the opposing
doctrines in Mahayana Buddhism, was referred to frequently in both Chinese and
Japanese Buddhist exegetical writings. The same spirit of reconciliation is
also manifest later during the Koryo dynasty (918–1392) in Chinul’s Junghae-ssangsu,
in which the founder of Korean Son Buddhism attempts a reconciliation between
Kyo-hak (Scriptural school of Buddhism) and Son-ga (Meditation school of
Buddhism), which were engaged in a serious confrontation with each other.
Although many of its teachings were derivations from Mahayana Buddhist
metaphysics, the Son school of Buddhism emphasized the realization of
enlightenment without depending upon scriptural teachings, while the Scriptural
school of Buddhism emphasized a gradual process of enlightenment through faith
and the practice of understanding scriptures. Himself a Son master, Chinul
provided a philosophical foundation for Korean Son by incorporating the
doctrines of Scriptural Buddhism as the philosophical basis for the practices
of Son. Chinul’s successful synthesis of Kyo and Son served as the basis for
the development of an indigenous form of Son Buddhism in Korea. It is primarily
this form of Buddhism that is meant when one speaks of Korean Buddhism today.
Ethical self-cultivation stands at the core of Confucianism. Confucian theories
of government and social relationships are founded upon it, and the
metaphysical speculations have their place in Confucianism insofar as they are
related to this overriding concern. The establishment in A.D. 372 of Taehak, a
state-oriented Confucian institute of higher learning in the kingdom of
Kokuryo, points to a well-established tradition of Confucian learning already
in existence on the Korean peninsula during the Three Kingdoms era. Although
Buddhism was the state religion of the Unified Silla period (668–918),
Confucianism formed its philosophical and structural backbone. From 682, when a
national academy was established in the Unified Silla kingdom as a training
ground for high-level officials, the content of formal education in Korea
consisted primarily of Confucian and other related Chinese classics; this
lasted well into the nineteenth century. The preeminence of Confucianism in
Korean history was further enhanced by its adoption by the founders of the
Choson dynasty (1392–1910) as the national ideology. The Confucianism that
flourished during the Choson period was Neo-Confucianism, a philosophical
synthesis of original Confucianism, Buddhism, and Taoism achieved by the
Chinese philosopher Chu Hsi in the twelfth century. During the five hundred
years of Neo-Confucian orthodoxy, a number of Korean scholars succeeded in
bringing Neo-Confucian philosophical speculation to new heights of originality
and influence both at home and abroad. Yi Hwang (better known by his pen name
T’oegye, 1501– 70) and his adversary Yi I (Yulgok, 1536–84) deserve special
mention. T’oegye interpreted the origin of the four cardinal virtues
(benevolence, righteousness, propriety, and knowledge) and the seven emotions
(pleasure, anger, sorrow, joy, love, hate, and desire) in such a way as to
accord priority to the principle of reason I over the principle of material
force Ki. T’oegye went a step further than his Sung mentor Chu Hsi by claiming
that the prinKorean philosophy Korean philosophy 474 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999
7:40 AM Page 474 ciple of reason includes within itself the generative power
for matter. This theory was criticized by Yulgok, who claimed that the source
of generative power in the universe lay in the matter of material force itself.
The philosophical debate carried on by these men and its implications for
ethics and statecraft are generally considered richer in insight and more
intricate in argumentation than that in China. T’oegye’s ideas in particular
were influential in spreading NeoConfucianism in Japan. Neo-Confucian
philosophical speculation in the hands of those lesser scholars who followed
T’oegye and Yulgok, however, became overly speculative and impractical. It
evolved, moreover, into a rigid national orthodoxy by the middle of the
seventeenth century. Dissatisfaction with this intellectual orthodoxy was
further deepened by Korea’s early encounter with Christianity and Western
science, which had been reaching Korea by way of China since the beginning of
the seventeenth century. Coupled with the pressing need for administrative and
economic reforms subsequent to the Japanese invasion (1592–97), these
tendencies gave rise to a group of illustrious Confucian scholars who, despite
the fact that their individual lives spanned a 300-year period from 1550 to
1850, were subsequently and collectively given the name Silhak. Despite their
diverse interests and orientations, these scholars were bound by their devotion
to the spirit of practicality and utility as well as to seeking facts grounded
in evidence in all scholarly endeavors, under the banner of returning to the
spirit of the original Confucianism. Chong Yag-yong (1762–1836), who may be
said to be the culmination of the Silhak movement, was able to transform these elements
and tendencies into a new Confucian synthesis. See also BUDDHISM, CHINESE
PHILOSOPHY, CONFUCIANISM, JAPANESE PHILOSOPHY, NEOCONFUCIANISM. Y.K.
Kotarbigski, Tadeusz (1886–1981), Polish philosopher, cofounder, with
Lukasiewicz and Lesniewski, of the Warsaw Center of Logical Research. His broad
philosophical interests and humanistic concerns, probity, scholarship, and
clarity in argument, consequent persuasiveness, and steadfast championship of
human rights made him heir to their common mentor Kasimir Twardowski, father of
modern Polish philosophy. In philosophical, historical, and methodological
works like his influential Elements of Theory of Knowledge, Formal Logic, and
Scientific Methodology (1929; mistitled Gnosiology in English translation), he
popularized the more technical contributions of his colleagues, and carried on
Twardowski’s objectivist and “anti-irrationalist” critical tradition, insisting
on accuracy and clarity, holding that philosophy has no distinctive method
beyond the logical and analytical methods of the empirical and deductive
sciences. As a free-thinking liberal humanist socialist, resolved to be “a true
compass, not a weathervane,” he defended autonomous ethics against
authoritarianism, left or right. His lifelong concern with community and social
practice led him to develop praxiology as a theory of efficacious action.
Following Lesniewsi’s “refutation” of Twardowski’s Platonism, Kotarbigski
insisted on translating abstractions into more concrete terms. The principal
tenets of his “reist, radical realist, and imitationist” rejection of
Platonism, phenomenalism, and introspectionism are (1) pansomatism or
ontological reism as modernized monistic materialism: whatever is anything at
all (even a soul) is a body – i.e., a concrete individual object, resistant and
spatiotemporally extended, enduring at least a while; (2) consequent radical
realism: no object is a “property,” “relation,” “event,” “fact,” or “abstract
entity” of any other kind, nor “sense-datum,” “phenomenon,” or essentially
“private mental act” or “fact” accessible only to “introspection”; (3)
concretism or semantic reism and imitationism as a concomitant “nominalist”
program – thus, abstract terms that, hypostatized, might appear to name
“abstract entities” are pseudo-names or onomatoids to be eliminated by
philosophical analysis and elucidatory paraphrase. Hypostatizations that might
appear to imply existence of such Platonic universals are translatable into
equivalent generalizations characterizing only bodies. Psychological
propositions are likewise reducible, ultimately to the basic form: Individual
So-and-so experiences thus; Such-and-such is so. Only as thus reduced can such
potentially misleading expressions be rightly understood and judged true or
false. See also POLISH LOGIC. E.C.L. ko wu, chih chih, Chinese philosophical
terms used in the Ta-hsüeh (Great Learning) to refer to two related stages or
aspects of the self-cultivation process, subsequently given different
interpretations by later Confucian thinkers. ‘Ko’ can mean ‘correct’, ‘arrive
at’ or ‘oppose’; ‘wu’ means ‘things’. The first ‘chih’ can mean ‘expand’ or
‘reach out’; the second ‘chih’ means ‘knowledge’. Chu Hsi (1130–1200) took ‘ko
wu’ to mean arrivKotarbigski, Tadeusz ko wu, chih chih 475 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999
7:40 AM Page 475 ing at li (principle, pattern) in human affairs and ‘chih
chih’ to mean the expansion of knowledge; an important part of the
self-cultivation process involves expanding one’s moral knowledge by examining
daily affairs and studying classics and historical documents. Wang Yang-ming
(1472– 1529) took ‘ko wu’ to mean correcting the activities of one’s heart/mind
(hsin), and ‘chih chih’ the reaching out of one’s innate knowledge (liang
chih); an important part of the self-cultivation process involves making fully
manifest one’s innate knowledge by constantly watching out for and eliminating
distortive desires. K.-l.S. Krause, Karl Christian Friedrich (1781–1832),
German philosopher representative of a tendency to develop Kant’s views in the
direction of pantheism and mysticism. Educated at Jena, he came under the
influence of Fichte and Schelling. Taking his philosophical starting point as
Fichte’s analysis of self-consciousness, and adopting as his project a
“spiritualized” systematic elaboration of the philosophy of Spinoza (somewhat
like the young Schelling), he arrived at a position that he called panentheism.
According to this, although nature and human consciousness are part of God or
Absolute Being, the Absolute is neither exhausted in nor identical with them.
To some extent, he anticipated Hegel in invoking an “end of history” in which
the finite realm of human affairs would reunite with the infinite essence in a
universal moral and “spiritual” order. See also FICHTE, PANTHEISM, SCHELLING.
J.P.Su. Krebs. See NICHOLAS OF CUSA. Kripke, Saul A(aron) (b.1940), American
mathematician and philosopher, considered one of the most deeply influential
contemporary figures in logic and philosophy. While a teenager, he formulated a
semantics for modal logic (the logic of necessity and possibility) based on
Leibniz’s notion of a possible world, and, using the apparatus, proved
completeness for a variety of systems (1959, 1963). Possible world semantics
(due in part also to Carnap and others) has proved to be one of the most
fruitful developments in logic and philosophy. Kripke’s 1970 Princeton
lectures, Naming and Necessity (1980), were a watershed. The work primarily
concerns proper names of individuals (e.g., ‘Aristotle’) and, by extension, terms
for natural kinds (‘water’) and similar expressions. Kripke uses his thesis
that any such term is a rigid designator – i.e., designates the same thing with
respect to every possible world in which that thing exists (and does not
designate anything else with respect to worlds in which it does not exist) – to
argue, contrary to the received Fregean view, that the designation of a proper
name is not semantically secured by means of a description that gives the sense
of the name. On the contrary, the description associated with a particular use
of a name will frequently designate something else entirely. Kripke derives
putative examples of necessary a posteriori truths, as well as contingent a
priori truths. In addition, he defends essentialism – the doctrine that some
properties of things are properties that those things could not fail to have
(except by not existing) – and uses it, together with his account of
natural-kind terms, to argue against the identification of mental entities with
their physical manifestations (e.g., sensations with specific neural events).
In a sequel, “A Puzzle about Belief” (1979), Kripke addresses the problem of
substitution failure in sentential contexts attributing belief or other
propositional attitudes. Kripke’s interpretation of the later Wittgenstein as a
semantic skeptic has also had a profound impact (Wittgenstein on Rules and
Private Language, 1980, 1982). His semantic theory of truth (“Outline of a
Theory of Truth,” 1975) has sparked renewed interest in the liar paradox (‘This
statement is false’) and related paradoxes, and in the development of
non-classical languages containing their own truth predicates as possible
models for natural language. In logic, he is also known for his work in
intuitionism and on his theory of transfinite recursion on admissible ordinals.
Kripke, McCosh Professor of Philosophy (emeritus) at Princeton, frequently
lectures on numerous further significant results in logic and philosophy, but
those results have remained unpublished. See also A PRIORI, CAUSAL THEORY OF
PROPER NAMES, MEANING, PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE, WITTGENSTEIN. N.S. Kripke
semantics, a type of formal semantics for languages with operators A and B for
necessity and possibility (‘possible worlds semantics’ and ‘relational
semantics’ are sometimes used for the same notion); also, a similar semantics
for intuitionistic logic. In a basic version a framefor a sentential language
with A and B is a pair (W,R) where W is a non-empty set (the “possible worlds”)
and R is a binary relation on W – the relation of “relative possibility” or
“accessibility.” A model on the frame (W,R) is a triple (W,R,V), Krause, Karl
Christian Friedrich Kripke semantics 476 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page
476 where V is a function (the “valuation function”) that assigns truth-values
to sentence letters at worlds. If w 1 W then a sentence AA is true at world w
in the model (W,R,V) if A is true at all worlds v 1 W for which wRv.
Informally, AA is true at world w if A is true at all the worlds that would be
possible if w were actual. This is a generalization of the doctrine commonly
attributed to Leibniz that necessity is truth in all possible worlds. A is
valid in the model (W,R,V) if it is true at all worlds w 1 W in that model. It
is valid in the frame (W,R) if it is valid in all models on that frame. It is
valid if it is valid in all frames. In predicate logic versions, a frame may
include another component D, that assigns a non-empty set Dw of objects (the
existents at w) to each possible world w. Terms and quantifiers may be treated
either as objectual (denoting and ranging over individuals) or conceptual
(denoting and ranging over functions from possible worlds to individuals) and
either as actualist or possibilist(denoting and ranging over either existents
or possible existents). On some of these treatments there may arise further
choices about whether and how truth-values should be assigned to sentences that
assert relations among non-existents. The development of Kripke semantics marks
a watershed in the modern study of modal systems. In the 1930s, 1940s, and
1950s a number of axiomatizations for necessity and possibility were proposed
and investigated. Carnap showed that for the simplest of these systems, C. I.
Lewis’s S5, AA can be interpreted as saying that A is true in all “state
descriptions.” Answering even the most basic questions about the other systems,
however, required effort and ingenuity. In the late fifties and early sixties
Stig Kanger, Richard Montague, Saul Kripke, and Jaakko Hintikka each formulated
interpretations for such systems that generalized Carnap’s semantics by using
something like the accessibility relation described above. Kripke’s semantics
was more natural than the others in that accessibility was taken to be a
relation among mathematically primitive “possible worlds,” and, in a series of
papers, Kripke demonstrated that versions of it provide characteristic
interpretations for a number of modal systems. For these reasons Kripke’s
formulation has become standard. Relational semantics provided simple solutions
to some older problems about the distinctness and relative strength of the
various systems. It also opened new areas of investigation, facilitating
general results (establishing decidability and other properties for infinite
classes of modal systems), incompleteness results (exhibiting systems not
determined by any class of frames), and correspondence results (showing that
the frames verifying certain modal formulas were exactly the frames meeting
certain conditions on R). It suggested parallel interpretations for notions
whose patterns of inference were known to be similar to that of necessity and
possibility, including obligation and permission, epistemic necessity and
possibility, provability and consistency, and, more recently, the notion of a
computation’s inevitably or possibly terminating in a particular state. It
inspired similar semantics for nonclassical conditionals and the more general
neighborhood or functional variety of possible worlds semantics. The
philosophical utility of Kripke semantics is more difficult to assess. Since
the accessibility relation is often explained in terms of the modal operators,
it is difficult to maintain that the semantics provides an explicit analysis of
the modalities it interprets. Furthermore, questions about which version of the
semantics is correct (particularly for quantified modal systems) are themselves
tied to substantive questions about the nature of things and worlds. The
semantics does impose important constraints on the meaning of modalities, and
it provides a means for many philosophical questions to be posed more clearly
and starkly. See also FORMAL SEMANTICS, MODAL LOGIC, NECESSITY, POSSIBLE
WORLDS. S.T.K. Kristeva, Julia (b.1941), Bulgarian-born French linguist,
practicing psychoanalyst, widely influential social theorist, and novelist. The
centerpiece of Kristeva’s semiotic theory has two correlative moments: a focus
on the speaking subject as embodying unconscious motivations (and not simply
the conscious intentionality of a Husserlian transcendental ego) and an
articulation of the signifying phenomenon as a dynamic, productive process (not
a static sign-system). Kristeva’s most systematic philosophical work, La
Révolution du langage poétique (1974), brings her semiotics to mature
expression through an effective integration of psychoanalysis (Freud and
Lacan), elements of linguistic models (from Roman Jakobson to Chomskyan
generative grammar) and semiology (from Saussure to Peirce and Louis
Hjelmslev), and a literary approach to text (influenced by Bakhtin). Together
the symbolic and the semiotic, two dialectical and irreconcilable modalities of
meaning, constitute the signifying process. The symbolic designates the
systematic rules governing denotative and propositional speech, while the
Kristeva, Julia Kristeva, Julia 477 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 477
semiotic isolates an archaic layer of meaning that is neither representational
nor based on relations among signs. The concept of the chora combines the
semiotic, translinguistic layer of meaning (genotext) with a psychoanalytic,
drive-based model of unconscious sound production, dream logic, and fantasy
life that defy full symbolic articulation. Drawing on Plato’s non-unified
notion of the maternal receptacle (Timaeus), the chora constitutes the space
where subjectivity is generated. Drives become “ordered” in rhythmic patterns
during the pre-Oedipal phase before the infant achieves reflexive capacity,
develops spatial intuition and time consciousness, and posits itself as an
enunciating subject. Ordered, but not according to symbolic laws, semiotic
functions arise when the infant forms associations between its vocal
gesticulations and sensorimotor development, and patterns these associations
after the mother’s corporeal modulations. The semiotic chora, while partly
repressed in identity formation, links the subject’s preverbal yet functional
affective life to signification. All literary forms – epic narrative,
metalanguage, contemplation or theoria and text-practice – combine two
different registers of meaning, phenotext and genotext. Yet they do so in
different ways and none encompasses both registers in totality. The phenotext
refers to language in its function “to communicate” and can be analyzed in
terms of syntax and semantics. Though not itself linguistic, the genotext
reveals itself in the way that “phonematic” and “melodic devices” and
“syntactic and logical” features establish “semantic” fields. The genotext
isolates the specific mode in which a text sublimates drives; it denotes the
“process” by which a literary form generates a particular type of subjectivity.
Poetic language is unique in that it largely reveals the genotext. This linkage
between semiotic processes, genotext, and poetic language fulfills the early linguistic
project (1967–73) and engenders a novel post-Hegelian social theory.
Synthesizing semiotics and the destructive death drive’s attack against stasis
artfully restores permanence to Hegelian negativity. Poetic mimesis, because it
transgresses grammatical rules while sustaining signification, reactivates the
irreducible negativity and heterogeneity of drive processes. So effectuating
anamnesis, poetry reveals the subject’s constitution within language and, by
holding open rather than normalizing its repressed desire, promotes critical
analysis of symbolic and institutionalized values. Later works like Pouvoirs de
l’horreur (1980), Etrangers à nous-mêmes (1989), Histoires d’amour (1983), and
Les Nouvelles maladies de l’âme (1993) shift away from collective political
agency to a localized, culturally therapeutic focus. Examining xenophobic
social formations, abjection and societal violence, romantic love, grief,
women’s melancholic poison in patriarchy, and a crisis of moral values in the
postmetaphysical age, they harbor forceful implications for ethics and social
theory. See also BAKHTIN, FEMINISM, FREUD, POSTMODERN, SEMIOTICS,
STRUCTURALISM. P.Hu. Kropotkin, Petr Alekseevich (1842–1921), Russian
geographer, geologist, naturalist, and philosopher, best remembered for his
anarchism and his defense of mutual aid as a factor of evolution. Traveling
extensively in Siberia on scientific expeditions (1862–67), he was stimulated
by Darwin’s newly published theory of evolution and sought, in the Siberian
landscape, confirmation of Darwin’s Malthusian principle of the struggle for
survival. Instead Kropotkin found that underpopulation was the rule, that
climate was the main obstacle to survival, and that mutual aid was a far more
common phenomenon than Darwin recognized. He soon generalized these findings to
social theory, opposing social Darwinism, and also began to espouse anarchist
theory. See also ANARCHISM, DARWINISM, RUSSIAN PHILOSOPHY. P.T.G. Kuan Tzu,
also called Kuan Chung (d.645 B.C.), Chinese statesman who was prime minister
of Ch’i and considered a forefather of Legalism. He was traditionally albeit
spuriously associated with the Kuan Tzu, an eclectic work containing Legalist,
Confucian, Taoist, five phases, and Huang–Lao ideas from the fourth to the second
centuries B.C. As minister, Kuan Tzu achieved peace and social order through
the hegemonic system (pa), wherein the ruling Chou king ratified a collective
power-sharing arrangement with the most powerful feudal lords. R.P.P. &
R.T.A. Kuhn, Thomas S(amuel) (1922–96), American historian and philosopher of
science. Kuhn studied at Harvard, where he received degrees in physics (1943,
1946) and a doctorate in the history of science (1949). He then taught history
of science or philosophy of science at Harvard (1951–56), Berkeley (1956–64),
Princeton (1964–79), and M.I.T. (1979–91). Kuhn traced his shift from physics
to the history and philosophy of science to a moment in 1947 when he was
Kropotkin, Petr Alekseevich Kuhn, Thomas S(amuel) 478 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999
7:40 AM Page 478 asked to teach some science to humanities majors. Searching
for a case study to illuminate the development of Newtonian mechanics, Kuhn
opened Aristotle’s Physics and was astonished at how “simply wrong” it was.
After a while, Kuhn came to “think like an Aristotelian physicist” and to
realize that Aristotle’s basic concepts were totally unlike Newton’s, and that,
understood on its own terms, Aristotle’s Physics was not bad Newtonian
mechanics. This new perspective resulted in The Copernican Revolution (1957), a
study of the transformation of the Aristotelian geocentric image of the world
to the modern heliocentric one. Pondering the structure of these changes, Kuhn
produced his immensely influential second book, The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions (1962). He argued that scientific thought is defined by
“paradigms,” variously describing these as disciplinary matrixes or exemplars,
i.e., conceptual world-views consisting of beliefs, values, and techniques
shared by members of a given community, or an element in that constellation:
concrete achievements used as models for research. According to Kuhn,
scientists accept a prevailing paradigm in “normal science” and attempt to
articulate it by refining its theories and laws, solving various puzzles, and
establishing more accurate measurements of constants. Eventually, however,
their efforts may generate anomalies; these emerge only with difficulty,
against a background of expectations provided by the paradigm. The accumulation
of anomalies triggers a crisis that is sometimes resolved by a revolution that
replaces the old paradigm with a new one. One need only look to the
displacement of Aristotelian physics and geocentric astronomy by Newtonian
mechanics and heliocentrism for instances of such paradigm shifts. In this way,
Kuhn challenged the traditional conception of scientific progress as gradual,
cumulative acquisition of knowledge. He elaborated upon these themes and
extended his historical inquiries in his later works, The Essential Tension
(1977) and Black-Body Theory and the Quantum Discontinuity (1978). See also
PARADIGM, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. R.Ar. k’un. See CH’IEN, K’UN. kung, szu, a
Chinese distinction corresponding to the opposition between “public” and
“private” interests, a key feature of Confucian and Legalist ethics. The
distinction is sometimes expressed by other terms suggestive of distinction
between impartiality and partiality, as in the Mo Tzu, or the Neo-Confucian
distinction between Heavenly principle (t’ien-li) and selfish desires. For the
Confucians, private and personal concerns are acceptable only insofar as they
do not conflict with the rules of propriety (li) and righteousness (i).
Partiality toward one’s personal relationships is also acceptable provided that
such partiality admits of reasonable justification, especially when such a
concern is not incompatible with jen or the ideal of humanity. This view
contrasts with egoism, altruism, and utilitarianism. See also CHINESE LEGALISM,
CONFUCIANISM. A.S.C. K’ung Ch’iu. See CONFUCIUS. Kung Fu-tzu. See CONFUCIUS.
Kung-sun Lung Tzu (fl. 300 B.C.), Chinese philosopher best known for his
dialogue defending the claim “A white horse is not a horse.” Kung-sun probably
regarded his paradox only as an entertaining exercise in disputation (pien),
and not as philosophically illuminating. Nonetheless, it may have had the
serious effect of helping to bring disputation into disrepute in China.
Numerous interpretations of the “white horse” dialogue have been proposed. One
recent theory is that Kung-sun Lung Tzu is assuming that ‘white horse’ refers
to two things (an equine shape and a color) while ‘horse’ refers only to the
shape, and then simply observing that the whole (shape and color) is not
identical with one of its parts (the shape). See also PIEN. B.W.V.N. K’ung Tzu.
See CONFUCIUS. Kuo Hsiang (died A.D. 312), Chinese thinker of the Hsüan Hsüeh
(Mysterious Learning) School. He is described, along with thinkers like Wang
Pi, as a Neo-Taoist. Kuo helped develop the notion of li (pattern) as the
underlying structure of the cosmos, of which each thing receives an individual
fen (allotment). All things are “one” in having such “natural” roles to play,
and by being tzu jan (spontaneous), can attain a mystical oneness with all
things. For Kuo, the fen of human beings included standard Confucian virtues.
Kuo is credited with editing the current edition of the Chuang Tzu and
composing what is now the oldest extant commentary on it. See also NEOTAOISM.
P.J.I. Kyo-hak Buddhism. See KOREAN PHILOSOPHY. Kyoto School. See JAPANESE
PHILOSOPHY. k’un Kyoto School 479 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 479
Labriola, Antonio (1843–1904), Italian Marxist philosopher who studied Hegel
and corresponded with Engels for several years (Lettere a Engels, 1949). His
essays on Marxism appeared first in French in the collection Essais sur la
conception matérialiste de l’histoire (“Essays on the Materialist Conception of
History,” 1897). Another influential work, Discorrendo di socialismo e di
filosofia (“Talks about Socialism and Philosophy,” 1897), collects ten letters
to Georges Sorel on Marxism. Labriola did not intend to develop an original
Marxist theory but only to give an accurate exposition of Marx’s thought. He
believed that socialism would inevitably ensue from the inner contradictions of
capitalist society and defended Marx’s views as objective scientific truths. He
criticized revisionism and defended the need to maintain the orthodoxy of
Marxist thought. His views and works were publicized by two of his students,
Sorel in France and Croce in Italy. In the 1950s Antonio Gramsci brought new
attention to Labriola as an example of pure and independent Marxism. See also
MARXISM, SOREL. P.Gar. Lacan, Jacques (1901–81), French practitioner and
theorist of psychoanalysis. Lacan developed and transformed Freudian theory and
practice on the basis of the structuralist linguistics originated by Saussure.
According to Lacan, the unconscious is not a congeries of biological instincts
and drives, but rather a system of linguistic signifiers. He construes, e.g.,
the fundamental Freudian processes of condensation and displacement as
instances of metaphor and metonymy. Lacan proposed a Freudianism in which any
traces of the substantial Cartesian self are replaced by a system of symbolic
functions. Contrary to standard views, the ego is an imaginary projection, not
our access to the real (which, for Lacan, is the unattainable and inexpressible
limit of language). In accord with his theoretical position, Lacan developed a
new form of psychoanalytic practice that tried to avoid rather than achieve the
“transference” whereby the analysand identifies with the mature ego of the
analyst. Lacan’s writings (e.g., Écrits and the numerous volumes of his
Séminaires) are of legendary difficulty, offering idiosyncratic networks of
allusion, word play, and paradox, which some find rich and stimulating and
others irresponsibly obscure. Beyond psychoanalysis, Lacan has been
particularly influential on literary theorists and on poststructuralist philosophers
such as Foucault, Derrida, and Deleuze. See also FOUCAULT, FREUD. G.G.
Laffitte, Pierre (1823–1903), French positivist philosopher, a disciple of
Comte and founder (1878) of the Revue Occidentale. Laffitte spread positivism
by adopting Comte’s format of “popular” courses. He faithfully acknowledged
Comte’s objective method and religion of humanity. Laffitte wrote Great Types
of Humanity (1875–76). In Positive Ethics (1881), he distinguishes between
theoretical and practical ethics. His Lectures on First Philosophy (1889–95)
sets forth a metaphysics, or a body of general and abstract laws, that attempts
to complete positivism, to resolve the conflict between the subjective and the
objective, and to avert materialism. See also COMTE, LOGICAL POSITIVISM.
J.-L.S. La Forge, Louis de (1632–66), French philosopher and member of the
Cartesian school. La Forge seems to have become passionately interested in
Descartes’s philosophy in about 1650, and grew to become one of its most
visible and energetic advocates. La Forge (together with Gérard van Gutschoven)
illustrated the 1664 edition of Descartes’s L’homme and provided an extensive
commentary; both illustrations and commentary were often reprinted with the
text. His main work, though, is the Traité de l’esprit de l’homme (1665):
though not a commentary on Descartes, it is “in accordance with the principles
of René Descartes,” according to its subtitle. It attempts to continue
Descartes’s program in L’homme, left incomplete at his death, by discussing the
mind and its union with the body. In many ways La Forge’s work is quite
orthodox; he carefully follows Descartes’s opinions on the nature of body, the
nature of soul, etc., as they appear in the extant writings to which he had
access. But with others in the Cartesian school, La Forge’s work contributed to
the establishment of the doctrine of occasionalism as 480 L 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 480 Cartesian orthodoxy, a doctrine not explicitly
found in Descartes’s writings. See also DESCARTES, OCCASIONALISM. D.Garb.
Lambda-abstraction. See COMBINATORY LOGIC, LAMBDA-CALCULUS. lambda-calculus,
also l-calculus, a theory of mathematical functions that is (a) “logic-free,”
i.e. contains no logical constants (formula-connectives or
quantifier-expressions), and (b) equational, i.e. ‘%’ is its sole predicate
(though its metatheory refers to relations of reducibility between terms).
There are two species, untyped and typed, each with various subspecies.
Termhood is always inductively defined (as is being a type-expression, if the
calculus is typed). A definition of being a term will contain at least these
clauses: take infinitely many variables (of each type if the calculus is typed)
to be terms; for any terms t and s (of appropriate type if the calculus is
typed), (ts) is a term (of type determined by that of t and s if the calculus
is typed); for any term t and a variable u (perhaps meeting certain
conditions), (lut) is a term (“of” type determined by that of t and u if the
calculus is typed). (ts) is an application-term; (lut) is a l-term, the
labstraction of t, and its l-prefix binds all free occurrences of u in t.
Relative to any assignment a of values (of appropriate type if the calculus is
typed) to its free variables, each term denotes a unique entity. Given a term
(ts), t denotes a function and (ts) denotes the output of that function when it
is applied to the denotatum of s, all relative to a. (lut) denotes relative to
a that function which when applied to any entity x (of appropriate type if the
calculus is typed) outputs the denotatum of t relative to the variant of a
obtained by assigning u to the given x. Alonzo Church introduced the untyped
l-calculus around 1932 as the basis for a foundation for mathematics that took
all mathematical objects to be functions. It characterizes a universe of
functions, each with that universe as its domain and each yielding values in
that universe. It turned out to be almost a notational variant of combinatory
logic, first presented by Moses Schonfinkel (1920, written up and published by
Behmann in 1924). Church presented the simplest typed l calculus in 1940. Such
a calculus characterizes a domain of objects and functions, each “of” a unique
type, so that the type of any given function determines two further types, one
being the type of all and only those entities in the domain of that function,
the other being the type of all those entities output by that function. In 1972
Jean-Yves Girard presented the first second-order (or polymorphic) typed
l-calculus. It uses additional type-expressions themselves constructed by
second-order l-abstraction, and also more complicated terms constructed by
labstracting with respect to certain type-variables, and by applying such terms
to type-expressions. The study of l-calculi has deepened our understanding of
constructivity in mathematics. They are of interest in proof theory, in
category theory, and in computer science. See also CATEGORY THEORY, COMBINATORY
LOGIC, PROOF THEORY. H.T.H. lambda-operator. See LAMBDA-CALCULUS. lambda-term.
See COMBINATORY LOGIC, LAMBDACALCULUS. Lambert, Johann Heinrich (1728–77),
German natural philosopher, logician, mathematician, and astronomer. Born in
Mulhouse (Alsace), he was an autodidact who became a prominent member of the
Munich Academy (1759) and the Berlin Academy (1764). He made significant
discoveries in physics and mathematics. His most important philosophical works
were Neues Organon (“New Organon, or Thoughts on the Investigation and
Induction of Truth and the Distinction Between Error and Appearances,” 1764)
and Anlage zur Architectonic (“Plan of an Architectonic, or Theory of the
Simple and Primary Elements in Philosophical and Mathematical Knowledge,”
1771). Lambert attempted to revise metaphysics. Arguing against both German
rationalism and British empiricism, he opted for a form of phenomenalism
similar to that of Kant and Tetens. Like his two contemporaries, he believed
that the mind contains a number of basic concepts and principles that make
knowledge possible. The philosopher’s task is twofold: first, these fundamental
concepts and principles have to be analyzed; second, the truths of science have
to be derived from them. In his own attempt at accomplishing this, Lambert
tended more toward Leibniz than Locke. M.K. La Mettrie, Julien Offroy de
(1707–51), French philosopher who was his generation’s most notorious
materialist, atheist, and hedonist. Raised in Brittany, he was trained at
Leiden by Hermann Boerhaave, an iatromechanist, whose works he translated into
French. As a Lockean sensationalist who read Gassendi and followed
Lambda-abstraction La Mettrie, Julien Offroy de 481 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40
AM Page 481 the Swiss physiologist Haller, La Mettrie took nature to be life’s
dynamic and ultimate principle. In 1745 he published Natural History of the
Soul, which attacked Cartesian dualism and dispensed with God. Drawing from
Descartes’s animal-machine, his masterpiece, Man the Machine(1747), argued that
the organization of matter alone explains man’s physical and intellectual
faculties. Assimilating psychology to mechanistic physiology, La Mettrie
integrated man into nature and proposed a materialistic monism. An Epicurean
and a libertine, he denied any religious or rational morality in Anti-Seneca
(1748) and instead accommodated human behavior to natural laws. Anticipating
Sade’s nihilism, his Art of Enjoying Pleasures and Metaphysical Venus (1751)
eulogized physical passions. Helvétius, d’Holbach, Marx, Plekhanov, and Lenin
all acknowledged a debt to his belief that “to write as a philosopher is to
teach materialism.” J.-L.S. Lange, Friedrich Albert (1828–75), German
philosopher and social scientist. Born at Wald near Solingen, he became a
university instructor at Bonn in 1851, professor of inductive logic at Zürich
in 1870, and professor at Marburg in 1873, establishing neo-Kantian studies
there. He published three books in 1865: Die Arbeiterfrage (The Problem of the
Worker), Die Grundlegung der mathematischen Psychologie (The Foundation of
Mathematical Psychology), and J. S. Mills Ansichten über die sociale Frage und
die angebliche Umwälzung der Socialwissenschaftlichen durch Carey (J. S. Mill’s
Views of the Social Question and Carey’s Supposed Social-Scientific
Revolution). Lange’s most important work, however, Geschichte des Materialismus
(History of Materialism), was published in 1866. An expanded second edition in
two volumes appeared in 1873–75 and in three later editions. The History of
Materialism is a rich, detailed study not only of the development of
materialism but of then-recent work in physical theory, biological theory, and
political economy; it includes a commentary on Kant’s analysis of knowledge.
Lange adopts a restricted positivistic approach to scientific interpretations
of man and the natural world and a conventionalism in regard to scientific
theory, and also encourages the projection of aesthetic interpretations of “the
All” from “the standpoint of the ideal.” Rejecting reductive materialism, Lange
argues that a strict analysis of materialism leads to ineliminable idealist
theoretical issues, and he adopts a form of materio-idealism. In his Geschichte
are anticipations of instrumental fictionalism, pragmatism, conventionalism,
and psychological egoism. Following the skepticism of the scientists he
discusses, Lange adopts an agnosticism about the ultimate constituents of
actuality and a radical phenomenalism. His major work was much admired by
Russell and significantly influenced the thought of Nietzsche. History of
Materialism predicted coming sociopolitical “earthquakes” because of the rise
of science, the decline of religion, and the increasing tensions of “the social
problem.” Die Arbeiterfrage explores the impact of industrialization and
technology on the “social problem” and predicts a coming social “struggle for
survival” in terms already recognizable as Social Darwinism. Both theoretically
and practically, Lange was a champion of workers and favored a form of
democratic socialism. His study of J. S. Mill and the economist Henry Carey was
a valuable contribution to social science and political economic theory. See
also JAMES-LANGE THEORY, NEOKANTIANISM. G.J.S. language, artificial. See FORMAL
LANGUAGE, PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE. language, natural. See FORMAL LANGUAGE,
PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE. language, philosophy of. See PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE.
language game. See WITTGENSTEIN. language of thought. See MEANING, MENTALESE,
PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE. Lao Tzu (sixth century B.C.), Chinese philosopher
traditionally thought to be a contemporary of Confucius and the author of the Tao
Te Ching (“Classic of tao and te“). Most contemporary scholars hold that “Lao
Tzu” is a composite of legendary early sages, and that the Tao Te Ching is an
anthology, a version of which existed no earlier than the third century B.C.
The Tao Te Ching combines paradoxical mysticism with hardheaded political
advice (Han Fei Tzu wrote a commentary on it) and a call to return to a
primitive utopia, without the corrupting accoutrements of civilization, such as
ritual (li), luxury items, and even writing. In its exaltation of spontaneous
action and denigration of Confucian virtues such as jen, the text is
reminiscent of Chuang Tzu, but it is distinctive both for its style (which is
lapidary to the point of obscurity) and its political orienLange, Friedrich
Albert Lao Tzu 482 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 482 tation. Translations
of the Tao Te Ching are based on either the Wang Pi text or the recently
discovered Ma-wang-tui text. See also NEO-TAOISM, TAOISM. B.W.V.N. La Peyrère,
Isaac (1596–1676), French religious writer, a Calvinist of probable Marrano
extraction and a Catholic convert whose messianic and anthropological work (Men
Before Adam, 1656) scandalized Jews, Catholics, and Protestants alike.
Anticipating both ecumenism and Zionism, The Recall of the Jews (1643) claims
that, together, converted Jews and Christians will usher in universal
redemption. A threefold “salvation history” undergirds La Peyrère’s “Marrano
theology”: (1) election of the Jews; (2) their rejection and the election of
the Christians; (3) the recall of the Jews. J.-L.S. Laplace, Pierre Simon de
(1749–1827), French mathematician and astronomer who produced the definitive
formulation of the classical theory of probability. He taught at various
schools in Paris, including the École Militaire; one of his students was
Napoleon, to whom he dedicated his work on probability. According to Laplace,
probabilities arise from our ignorance. The world is deterministic, so the
probability of a possible event depends on our limited information about it
rather than on the causal forces that determine whether it shall occur. Our
chief means of calculating probabilities is the principle of insufficient
reason, or the principle of indifference. It says that if there is no reason to
believe that one of n mutually exclusive and jointly exhaustive possible cases
will obtain rather than some other, so that the cases are equally possible,
then the probability of each case is 1/n. In addition, the probability of a
possible event equivalent to a disjunction of cases is the number of cases
favorable to the event divided by the total number of cases. For instance, the
probability that the top card of a well-shuffled deck is a diamond is
13/52.Laplace’s chief work on probability is Théorie analytique des probabilités(Analytic
Theory of Probabilities, 1812). See also PROBABILITY. P.We. La Ramée, Pierre.
See RAMUS. large numbers, law of. See BERNOULLI’s THEOREM. latent content. See
FREUD. Latin American philosophy, the philosophy of Latin America, which is
European in origin and constitutes a chapter in the history of Western
philosophy. Pre-Columbian indigenous cultures had developed ideas about the
world that have been interpreted by some scholars as philosophical, but there
is no evidence that any of those ideas were incorporated into the philosophy
later practiced in Latin America. It is difficult to characterize Latin
American philosophy in a way applicable to all of its 500-year history. The
most one can say is that, in contrast with European and Anglo-American philosophy,
it has maintained a strong human and social interest, has been consistently
affected by Scholastic and Catholic thought, and has significantly affected the
social and political institutions in the region. Latin American philosophers
tend to be active in the educational, political, and social lives of their
countries and deeply concerned with their own cultural identity. The history of
philosophy in Latin America can be divided into four periods: colonial,
independentist, positivist, and contemporary. Colonial period (c.1550–c.1750).
This period was dominated by the type of Scholasticism officially practiced in
the Iberian peninsula. The texts studied were those of medieval Scholastics,
primarily Aquinas and Duns Scotus, and of their Iberian commentators, Vitoria,
Soto, Fonseca, and, above all, Suárez. The university curriculum was modeled on
that of major Iberian universities (Salamanca, Alcalá, Coimbra), and
instructors produced both systematic treatises and commentaries on classical,
medieval, and contemporary texts. The philosophical concerns in the colonies
were those prevalent in Spain and Portugal and centered on logical and
metaphysical issues inherited from the Middle Ages and on political and legal
questions raised by the discovery and colonization of America. Among the former
were issues involving the logic of terms and propositions and the problems of
universals and individuation; among the latter were questions concerning the
rights of Indians and the relations of the natives with the conquerors. The
main philosophical center during the early colonial period was Mexico; Peru
became important in the seventeenth century. Between 1700 and 1750 other
centers developed, but by that time Scholasticism had begun to decline. The
founding of the Royal and Pontifical University of Mexico in 1553 inaugurated
Scholastic instruction in the New World. The first teacher of philosophy at the
university was Alonso de la Vera Cruz (c.1504–84), an Augustinian and disciple
of Soto. He composed several didactic treatises on La Peyrère, Isaac Latin
American philosophy 483 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 483 logic,
metaphysics, and science, including Recognitio summularum (“Introductory
Logic,” 1554), Dialectica resolutio (“Advanced Logic,” 1554), and Physica speculatio
(“Physics,” 1557). He also wrote a theologico-legal work, the Speculum
conjugiorum (“On Marriage,” 1572), concerned with the status of precolonial
Indian marriages. Alonso’s works are eclectic and didactic and show the
influence of Aristotle, Peter of Spain, and Vitoria in particular. Another
important Scholastic figure in Mexico was the Dominican Tomás de Mercado
(c.1530–75). He produced commentaries on the logical works of Peter of Spain
and Aristotle and a treatise on international commerce, Summa de tratos y
contratos (“On Contracts,” 1569). His other sources are Porphyry and Aquinas.
Perhaps the most important figure of the period was Antonio Rubio (1548–1615),
author of the most celebrated Scholastic book written in the New World, Logica
mexicana (“Mexican Logic,” 1605). It underwent seven editions in Europe and
became a logic textbook in Alcalá. Rubio’s sources are Aristotle, Porphyry, and
Aquinas, but he presents original treatments of several logical topics. Rubio
also commented on several of Aristotle’s other works. In Peru, two authors
merit mention. Juan Pérez Menacho (1565–1626) was a prolific writer, but only a
moral treatise, Theologia et moralis tractatus (“Treatise on Theology and
Morals”), and a commentary on Aquinas’s Summa theologiae remain. The
Chilean-born Franciscan, Alfonso Briceño (c.1587–1669), worked in Nicaragua and
Venezuela, but the center of his activities was Lima. In contrast with the
Aristotelian-Thomistic flavor of the philosophy of most of his contemporaries,
Briceño was a Scotistic Augustinian. This is evident in Celebriores
controversias in primum sententiarum Scoti (“On Scotus’s First Book of the
Sentences,” 1638) and Apologia de vita et doctrina Joannis Scotti (“Apology for
John Scotus,” 1642). Although Scholasticism dominated the intellectual life of
colonial Latin America, some authors were also influenced by humanism. Among
the most important in Mexico were Juan de Zumárraga (c.1468–1548); the
celebrated defender of the Indians, Bartolomé de Las Casas (1474–1566); Carlos
Sigüenza y Góngora (1645–1700); and Sor Juana Inés de La Cruz (1651–95). The
last one is a famous poet, now considered a precursor of the feminist movement.
In Peru, Nicolás de Olea (1635–1705) stands out. Most of these authors were
trained in Scholasticism but incorporated the concerns and ideas of humanists
into their work. Independentist period (c.1750–c.1850). Just before and
immediately after independence, leading Latin American intellectuals lost
interest in Scholastic issues and became interested in social and political
questions, although they did not completely abandon Scholastic sources. Indeed,
the theories of natural law they inherited from Vitoria and Suárez played a
significant role in forming their ideas. But they also absorbed non-Scholastic
European authors. The rationalism of Descartes and other Continental
philosophers, together with the empiricism of Locke, the social ideas of
Rousseau, the ethical views of Bentham, the skepticism of Voltaire and other
Encyclopedists, the political views of Condorcet and Montesquieu, the
eclecticism of Cousin, and the ideology of Destutt de Tracy, all contributed to
the development of liberal ideas that were a background to the independentist
movement. Most of the intellectual leaders of this movement were men of action
who used ideas for practical ends, and their views have limited theoretical
value. They made reason a measure of legitimacy in social and governmental
matters, and found the justification for revolutionary ideas in natural law.
Moreover, they criticized authority; some, regarding religion as superstitious,
opposed ecclesiastical power. These ideas paved the way for the later
development of positivism. The period begins with the weakening hold of
Scholasticism on Latin American intellectuals and the growing influence of
early modern philosophy, particularly Descartes. Among the first authors to
turn to modern philosophy was Juan Benito Díaz de Gamarra y Dávalos (1745–83)
in Mexico who wrote Errores del entendimiento humano (“Errors of Human
Understanding,” 1781) and Academias filosóficas (“Philosophical Academies,”
1774). Also in Mexico was Francisco Javier Clavijero (1731–87), author of a
book on physics and a general history of Mexico. In Brazil the turn away from
Scholasticism took longer. One of the first authors to show the influence of
modern philosophy was Francisco de Mont’Alverne (1784– 1858) in Compêndio de
filosofia (1883). These first departures from Scholasticism were followed by
the more consistent efforts of those directly involved in the independentist
movement. Among these were Simón Bolívar (1783–1830), leader of the rebellion
against Spain in the Andean countries of South America, and the Mexicans Miguel
Hidalgo y Costilla (1753– 1811), José María Morelos y Paván (1765– 1815), and
José Joaquín Fernández de Lizardi Latin American philosophy Latin American
philosophy 484 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 484 (1776–1827). In
Argentina, Mariano Moreno (1778–1811), Juan Crisóstomo Lafimur (d. 1823), and
Diego Alcorta (d. 1808), among others, spread the liberal ideas that served as
a background for independence. Positivist period (c.1850–c.1910). During this
time, positivism became not only the most popular philosophy in Latin America
but also the official philosophy of some countries. After 1910, however,
positivism declined drastically. Latin American positivism was eclectic,
influenced by a variety of thinkers, including Comte, Spencer, and Haeckel.
Positivists emphasized the explicative value of empirical science while rejecting
metaphysics. According to them, all knowledge is based on experience rather
than theoretical speculation, and its value lies in its practical applications.
Their motto, preserved on the Brazilian flag, was “Order and Progress.” This
positivism left little room for freedom and values; the universe moved
inexorably according to mechanistic laws. Positivism was a natural extension of
the ideas of the independentists. It was, in part, a response to the needs of
the newly liberated countries of Latin America. After independence, the
concerns of Latin American intellectuals shifted from political liberation to
order, justice, and progress. The beginning of positivism can be traced to the
time when Latin America, responding to these concerns, turned to the views of
French socialists such as Saint-Simon and Fourier. The Argentinians Esteban
Echevarría (1805–51) and Juan Bautista Alberdi (1812–84) were influenced by
them. Echevarría’s Dogma socialista (“Socialist Dogma,” 1846) combines
socialist ideas with eighteenth-century rationalism and literary Romanticism,
and Alberdi follows suit, although he eventually turned toward Comte. Alberdi
is, moreover, the first Latin American philosopher to worry about developing a
philosophy adequate to the needs of Latin America. In Ideas (1842), he stated
that philosophy in Latin America should be compatible with the economic,
political, and social requirements of the region. Another transitional thinker,
influenced by both Scottish philosophy and British empiricism, was the Venezuelan
Andrés Bello (1781–1865). A prolific writer, he is the most important Latin
American philosopher of the nineteenth century. His Filosofía del entendimiento
(“Philosophy of Understanding,” 1881) reduces metaphysics to psychology. Bello
also developed original ideas about language and history. After 1829, he worked
in Chile, where his influence was strongly felt. The generation of Latin
American philosophers after Alberdi and Bello was mostly positivistic.
Positivism’s heyday was the second half of the nineteenth century, but two of
its most distinguished advocates, the Argentinian José Ingenieros (1877–1925)
and the Cuban Enrique José Varona (1849–1933), worked well into the twentieth
century. Both modified positivism in important ways. Ingenieros left room for
metaphysics, which, according to him, deals in the realm of the
“yet-to-be-experienced.” Among his most important books are Hacia una moral sin
dogmas (“Toward a Morality without Dogmas,” 1917), where the influence of
Emerson is evident, Principios de psicologia (“Principles of Psychology,”
1911), where he adopts a reductionist approach to psychology, and El hombre
mediocre (“The Mediocre Man,” 1913), an inspirational book popular among Latin
American youths. In Conferencias filosóficas (“Philosophical Lectures,”
1880–88), Varona went beyond the mechanistic explanations of behavior common
among positivists. In Mexico the first and leading positivist was Gabino
Barreda (1818–81), who reorganized Mexican education under President Juárez. An
ardent follower of Comte, Barreda made positivism the basis of his educational
reforms. He was followed by Justo Sierra (1848–1912), who turned toward Spencer
and Darwin and away from Comte, criticizing Barreda’s dogmatism. Positivism was
introduced in Brazil by Tobias Barreto (1839–89) and Silvio Romero (1851– 1914)
in Pernambuco, around 1869. In 1875 Benjamin Constant (1836–91) founded the
Positivist Society in Rio de Janeiro. The two most influential exponents of
positivism in the country were Miguel Lemos (1854–1916) and Raimundo Teixeira
Mendes (1855–1927), both orthodox followers of Comte. Positivism was more than
a technical philosophy in Brazil. Its ideas spread widely, as is evident from
the inclusion of positivist ideas in the first republican constitution. The
most prominent Chilean positivists were José Victorino Lastarria (1817–88) and
Valentín Letelier (1852–1919). More dogmatic adherents to the movement were the
Lagarrigue brothers, Jorge (d. 1894), Juan Enrique (d. 1927), and Luis (d.
1953), who promoted positivism in Chile well after it had died everywhere else
in Latin America. Contemporary period (c.1910–present). Contemporary Latin
American philosophy began Latin American philosophy Latin American philosophy
485 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 485 with the demise of positivism. The
first part of the period was dominated by thinkers who rebelled against
positivism. The principal figures, called the Founders by Francisco Romero,
were Alejandro Korn (1860–1936) in Argentina, Alejandro Octavio Deústua
(1849–1945) in Peru, José Vasconcelos (1882–1959) and Antonio Caso (1883–1946)
in Mexico, Enrique Molina (1871– 1964) in Chile, Carlos Vaz Ferreira
(1872–1958) in Uruguay, and Raimundo de Farias Brito (1862–1917) in Brazil. In
spite of little evidence of interaction among these philosophers, their aims
and concerns were similar. Trained as positivists, they became dissatisfied
with positivism’s dogmatic intransigence, mechanistic determinism, and emphasis
on pragmatic values. Deústua mounted a detailed criticism of positivistic
determinism in Las ideas de orden y de libertad en la historia del pensamiento
humano (“The Ideas of Order and Freedom in the History of Human Thought,”
1917–19). About the same time, Caso presented his view of man as a spiritual
reality that surpasses nature in La existencia como economía, como desinterés y
como caridad (“Existence as Economy, Disinterestedness, and Charity,” 1916).
Following in Caso’s footsteps and inspired by Pythagoras and the Neoplatonists,
Vasconcelos developed a metaphysical system with aesthetic roots in El monismo
estético (“Aesthetic Monism,” 1918). An even earlier criticism of positivism is
found in Vaz Ferreira’s Lógica viva (“Living Logic,” 1910), which contrasts the
abstract, scientific logic favored by positivists with a logic of life based on
experience, which captures reality’s dynamic character. The earliest attempt at
developing an alternative to positivism, however, is found in Farias Brito.
Between 1895 and 1905 he published a trilogy, Finalidade do mundo (“The World’s
Goal”), in which he conceived the world as an intellectual activity which he
identified with God’s thought, and thus as essentially spiritual. The intellect
unites and reflects reality but the will divides it. Positivism was superseded
by the Founders with the help of ideas imported first from France and later
from Germany. The process began with the influence of Étienne Boutroux
(1845–1921) and Bergson and of French vitalism and intuitionism, but it was
cemented when Ortega y Gasset introduced into Latin America the thought of
Scheler, Nicolai Hartmann, and other German philosophers during his visit to
Argentina in 1916. The influence of Bergson was present in most of the
founders, particularly Molina, who in 1916 wrote La filosofía de Bergson (“The
Philosophy of Bergson”). Korn was exceptional in turning to Kant in his search
for an alternative to positivism. In La libertad creadora (“Creative Freedom,”
1920–22), he defends a creative concept of freedom. In Axiología (“Axiology,” 1930),
his most important work, he defends a subjectivist position. The impact of
German philosophy, including Hegel, Marx, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and the
neo-Kantians, and of Ortega’s philosophical perspectivism and historicism, were
strongly felt in the generation after the founders. The Mexican Samuel Ramos
(1897–1959), the Argentinians Francisco Romero (1891–1962) and Carlos Astrada
(1894–1970), the Brazilian Alceu Amoroso Lima (1893–1982), the Peruvian José
Carlos Mariátegui (1895–1930), and others followed the Founders’ course,
attacking positivism and favoring, in many instances, a philosophical style
that contrasted with its scientistic emphasis. The most important of these
figures was Romero, whose Theory of Man (1952) developed a systematic philosophical
anthropology in the context of a metaphysics of transcendence. Reality is
arranged according to degrees of transcendence, the lowest of which is the
physical and the highest the spiritual. The bases of Ramos’s thought are found
in Ortega as well as in Scheler and N. Hartmann. Ramos appropriated Ortega’s
perspectivism and set out to characterize the Mexican situation in Profile of
Man and Culture in Mexico (1962). Some precedent existed for the interest in
the culturally idiosyncratic in Vasconcelos’s Raza cósmica (“Cosmic Race,”
1925), but Ramos opened the doors to a philosophical awareness of Latin
American culture that has been popular ever since. Ramos’s most traditional
work, Hacia un nuevo humanismo (“Toward a New Humanism,” 1940), presents a philosophical
anthropology of Orteguean inspiration. Astrada studied in Germany and adopted
existential and phenomenological ideas in El juego existential (“The
Existential Game,” 1933), while criticizing Scheler’s axiology. Later, he
turned toward Hegel and Marx in Existencialismo y crisis de la filosofía
(“Existentialism and the Crisis of Philosophy,” 1963). Amoroso Lima worked in
the Catholic tradition and his writings show the influence of Maritain. His O
espírito e o mundo (“Spirit and World,” 1936) and Idade, sexo e tempo (“Age,
Sex, and Time,” 1938) present a spiritual view of human beings, which he
contrasted with Marxist and existentialist views. Mariátegui is the most
distinguished representative of MarxLatin American philosophy Latin American
philosophy 486 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 486 ism in Latin America.
His Siete ensayos de interpretación de la realidad peruana (“Seven Essays on
the Interpretation of Peruvian Reality,” 1928) contains an important statement
of social philosophy, in which he uses Marxist ideas freely to analyze the
Peruvian sociopolitical situation. In the late 1930s and 1940s, as a
consequence of the political upheaval created by the Spanish Civil War, a
substantial group of peninsular philosophers settled in Latin America. Among
the most influential were Joaquín Xirau (1895– 1946), Eduardo Nicol (b.1907),
Luis Recaséns Siches (b.1903), Juan D. García Bacca (b.1901), and, perhaps most
of all, José Gaos (1900–69). Gaos, like Caso, was a consummate teacher,
inspiring many students. Apart from the European ideas they brought, these
immigrants introduced methodologically more sophisticated ways of doing
philosophy, including the practice of studying philosophical sources in the
original languages. Moreover, they helped to promote Pan-American
communication. The conception of hispanidad they had inherited from Unamuno and
Ortega helped the process. Their influence was felt particularly by the
generation born around 1910. With this generation, Latin American philosophy
established itself as a professional and reputable discipline, and
philosophical organizations, research centers, and journals sprang up. The core
of this generation worked in the German tradition. Risieri Frondizi (Argentina,
1910–83), Eduardo García Máynez (Mexico, b.1908), Juan Llambías de Azevedo
(Uruguay, 1907–72), and Miguel Reale (Brazil, b.1910) were all influenced by
Scheler and N. Hartmann and concerned themselves with axiology and
philosophical anthropology. Frondizi, who was also influenced by Anglo-American
philosophy, defended a functional view of the self in Substancia y función en
el problema del yo (“The Nature of the Self,” 1952) and of value as a Gestalt
quality in Qué son los valores? (“What is Value?” 1958). Apart from these
thinkers, there were representatives of other traditions in this generation.
Following Ramos, Leopoldo Zea (Mexico, b.1912) stimulated the study of the
history of ideas in Mexico and initiated a controversy that still rages
concerning the identity and possibility of a truly Latin American philosophy.
Representing existentialism was Vicente Ferreira da Silva (Brazil, b.1916), who
did not write much but presented a vigorous criticism of what he regarded as
Hegelian and Marxist subjectivism in Ensaios filosóficos (“Philosophical Essays,”
1948). Before he became interested in existentialism, he had been interested in
logic, publishing the first textbook of mathematical logic written in Latin
America – Elementos de lógica matemática (“Elements of Mathematical Logic,”
1940). A philosopher whose interest in mathematical logic moved him away from
phenomenology is Francisco Miró Quesada (Peru, b.1918). He explored rationality
and eventually the perspective of analytic philosophy. Owing to the influence
of Maritain, several members of this generation adopted a NeoThomistic or
Scholastic approach. The main figures to do so were Oswaldo Robles (b.1904) in
Mexico, Octavio Nicolás Derisi (b.1907) in Argentina, Alberto Wagner de Reyna
(b.1915) in Peru, and Clarence Finlayson (1913–54) in Chile and Colombia. Even
those authors who worked in this tradition addressed issues of axiology and
philosophical anthropology. There was, therefore, considerable thematic unity
in Latin American philosophy between 1940 and 1960. The overall orientation was
not drastically different from the preceding period. The Founders used French
vitalism against positivism, and the following generation, with Ortega’s help,
took over the process, incorporating German spiritualism and the new ideas
introduced by phenomenology and existentialism to continue in a similar
direction. As a result, the phenomenology of Scheler and N. Hartmann and the
existentialism of Heidegger and Sartre dominated philosophy in Latin America
between 1940 and 1960. To this must be added the renewed impetus of
neoScholasticism. Few philosophers worked outside these philosophical currents,
and those who did had no institutional power. Among these were sympathizers of
philosophical analysis, and those who contributed to the continuing development
of Marxism. This situation has begun to change since 1960, substantially as a
result of a renewed interest in Marxism, the progressive influence of analytic
philosophy, and the development of a new philosophical current called the
philosophy of liberation. Moreover, the question raised by Zea in the 1940s
concerning the identity and possibility of a Latin American philosophy remains
a focus of attention and controversy. And, more recently, there has been
interest in such Continental philosophers as Foucault, Habermas, and Derrida,
in neopragmatists like Rorty, and in feminist philosophy. Socialist thought is
not new to Latin America. In this century, Emilio Frugoni (1880–1969) in
Uruguay and Mariátegui in Peru, among others, adopted a Marxist perspecLatin
American philosophy Latin American philosophy 487 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40
AM Page 487 tive, although a heterodox one. But only in the last three decades
has Marxism been taken seriously in Latin American academic circles. Indeed,
until recently Marxism was a marginal philosophical movement in Latin America.
The popularity of the Marxist perspective has made possible its increasing
institutionalization. Among its most important thinkers are Adolfo Sánchez
Vázquez (Spain, b.1915), Vicente Lombardo Toledano (b.1894) and Eli de Gortari
(b.1918) in Mexico, and Caio Prado Júnior (1909–86) in Brazil. In contrast to
Marxism, philosophical analysis arrived late in Latin America and, owing to its
technical and academic character, has not yet influenced more than a relatively
small number of Latin American philosophers. Nonetheless, and thanks in part to
its high theoretical caliber, analysis has become one of the most forceful
philosophical currents in the region. The publication of journals with an
analytic bent such as Crítica in Mexico, Análisis Filosófico in Argentina, and
Manuscrito in Brazil, the foundation of the Sociedad Argentina de Análisis
Filosófico (SADAF) in Argentina and the Sociedad Filosófica Iberoamericana
(SOFIA) in Mexico, and the growth of analytic publications in high-profile
journals of neutral philosophical orientation, such as Revista Latinoamericana
de Filosofía,indicate that philosophical analysis is well established in Latin
America. The main centers of analytic activity are Buenos Aires, Mexico City,
and Campinas and São Paulo in Brazil. The interests of Latin American analysts
center on questions of ethical and legal philosophy, the philosophy of science,
and more recently cognitive science. Among its most important proponents are
Genaro R. Carrió (b.1922), Gregorio Klimovsky (b.1922), and Tomás Moro Simpson
(b.1929) in Argentina; Luis Villoro (Spain, b. 1922) in Mexico; Francisco Miró
Quesada in Peru; Roberto Torretti (Chile, b.1930) in Puerto Rico; Mario Bunge
(Argentina, b.1919), who works in Canada; and Héctor-Neri Castañeda (Guatemala,
1924–91). The philosophy of liberation is an autochthonous Latin American
movement that mixes an emphasis on Latin American intellectual independence
with Catholic and Marxist ideas. The historicist perspective of Leopoldo Zea,
the movement known as the theology of liberation, and some elements from the
national-popular Peronist ideology prepared the ground for it. The movement
started in the early 1970s with a group of Argentinian philosophers, who, owing
to the military repression of 1976–83 in Argentina, went into exile in various
countries of Latin America. This early diaspora created permanent splits in the
movement and spread its ideas throughout the region. Although proponents of
this viewpoint do not always agree on their goals, they share the notion of
liberation as a fundamental concept: the liberation from the slavery imposed on
Latin America by imported ideologies and the development of a genuinely
autochthonous thought resulting from reflection on the Latin American reality.
As such, their views are an extension of the thought of Ramos and others who
earlier in the century initiated the discussion of the cultural identity of
Latin America. J.J.E.G. lattice theory. See BOOLEAN ALGEBRA. law, bridge. See
REDUCTION. law, natural. See NATURAL LAW. law, philosophy of. See PHILOSOPHY OF
LAW. lawlike generalization, also called nomological (or nomic), a
generalization that, unlike an accidental generalization, possesses nomic
necessity or counterfactual force. Compare (1) ‘All specimens of gold have a
melting point of 1,063o C’ with (2) ‘All the rocks in my garden are
sedimentary’. (2) may be true, but its generality is restricted to rocks in my
garden. Its truth is accidental; it does not state what must be the case. (1)
is true without restriction. If we write (1) as the conditional ‘For any x and
for any time t, if x is a specimen of gold subjected to a temperature of 1,063o
C, then x will melt’, we see that the generalization states what must be the
case. (1) supports the hypothetical counterfactual assertion ‘For any specimen
of gold x and for any time t, if x were subjected to a temperature of 1,063o C,
then x would melt’, which means that we accept (1) as nomically necessary: it
remains true even if no further specimens of gold are subjected to the required
temperature. This is not true of (2), for we know that at some future time an
igneous rock might appear in my garden. Statements like (2) are not lawlike;
they do not possess the unrestricted necessity we require of lawlike
statements. Ernest Nagel has claimed that a nomological statement must satisfy
two other conditions: it must deductively entail or be deductively entailed by
other laws, and its scope of prediction must exceed the known evidence for it.
See also CAUSAL LAW. R.E.B. lawlike statement. See LAWLIKE GENERALIZATION.
lattice theory lawlike statement 488 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 488
law of double negation. See DOUBLE NEGATION. law of eternal return. See
COMPUTER THEORY. law of identity. See IDENTITY. law of large numbers. See
BERNOULLI’s THEOREM. law of nature. See NATURAL LAW, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. law
of succession. See CAUSAL LAW. law of trichotomy. See CHOICE SEQUENCE,
RELATION. laws of thought, laws by which or in accordance with which valid
thought proceeds, or that justify valid inference, or to which all valid
deduction is reducible. Laws of thought are rules that apply without exception
to any subject matter of thought, etc.; sometimes they are said to be the
object of logic. The term, rarely used in exactly the same sense by different
authors, has long been associated with three equally ambiguous expressions: the
law of identity (ID), the law of contradiction (or non-contradiction; NC), and
the law of excluded middle (EM). Sometimes these three expressions are taken as
propositions of formal ontology having the widest possible subject matter,
propositions that apply to entities per se: (ID) every thing is (i.e., is
identical to) itself; (NC) no thing having a given quality also has the
negative of that quality (e.g., no even number is non-even); (EM) every thing
either has a given quality or has the negative of that quality (e.g., every
number is either even or non-even). Equally common in older works is use of
these expressions for principles of metalogic about propositions: (ID) every
proposition implies itself; (NC) no proposition is both true and false; (EM)
every proposition is either true or false. Beginning in the middle to late
1800s these expressions have been used to denote propositions of Boolean
Algebra about classes: (ID) every class includes itself; (NC) every class is
such that its intersection (“product”) with its own complement is the null
class; (EM) every class is such that its union (“sum”) with its own complement is
the universal class. More recently the last two of the three expressions have
been used in connection with the classical propositional logic and with the
socalled protothetic or quantified propositional logic; in both cases the law
of non-contradiction involves the negation of the conjunction (‘and’) of
something with its own negation and the law of excluded middle involves the
disjunction (‘or’) of something with its own negation. In the case of
propositional logic the “something” is a schematic letter serving as a
place-holder, whereas in the case of protothetic logic the “something” is a
genuine variable. The expressions ‘law of non-contradiction’ and ‘law of
excluded middle’ are also used for semantic principles of model theory
concerning sentences and interpretations: (NC) under no interpretation is a
given sentence both true and false; (EM) under any interpretation, a given
sentence is either true or false. The expressions mentioned above all have been
used in many other ways. Many other propositions have also been mentioned as
laws of thought, including the dictum de omni et nullo attributed to Aristotle,
the substitutivity of identicals (or equals) attributed to Euclid, the socalled
identity of indiscernibles attributed to Leibniz, and other “logical truths.”
The expression “laws of thought” gained added prominence through its use by
Boole (1815–64) to denote theorems of his “algebra of logic”; in fact, he named
his second logic book An Investigation of the Laws of Thought (1854). Modern
logicians, in almost unanimous disagreement with Boole, take this expression to
be a misnomer; none of the above propositions classed under ‘laws of thought’
are explicitly about thought per se, a mental phenomenon studied by psychology,
nor do they involve explicit reference to a thinker or knower as would be the
case in pragmatics or in epistemology. The distinction between psychology (as a
study of mental phenomena) and logic (as a study of valid inference) is widely
accepted. See also CONVENTIONALISM, DICTUM DE OMNI ET NULLO, PHILOSOPHY OF
LOGIC, SET THEORY. J.Cor. leap of faith. See KIERKEGAARD. least squares method.
See REGRESSION ANALYSIS. Lebensphilosophie, German term, translated as
‘philosophy of life’, that became current in a variety of popular and philosophical
inflections during the second half of the nineteenth century. Such philosophers
as Dilthey and Eucken (1846– 1926) frequently applied it to a general
philosophical approach or attitude that distinguished itself, on the one hand,
from the construction of comprehensive systems by Hegel and his followers and,
on the other, from the tendency of empiricism and early positivism to reduce
law of double negation Lebensphilosophie 489 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM
Page 489 human experience to epistemological questions about sensations or
impressions. Rather, a Lebensphilosophie should begin from a recognition of the
variety and complexity of concrete and already meaningful human experience as
it is “lived”; it should acknowledge that all human beings, including the
philosopher, are always immersed in historical processes and forms of
organization; and it should seek to understand, describe, and sometimes even
alter these and their various patterns of interrelation without abstraction or
reduction. Such “philosophies of life” as those of Dilthey and Eucken provided
much of the philosophical background for the conception of the social sciences
as interpretive rather than explanatory disciplines. They also anticipated some
central ideas of phenomenology, in particular the notion of the Life-World in
Husserl, and certain closely related themes in Heidegger’s version of
existentialism. See also DILTHEY, HUSSERL, VERSTEHEN. J.P.Su. Lebenswelt. See
HUSSERL. legal disability. See HOHFELD. legal duty. See HOHFELD. legal ethics.
See ETHICS. legal formalism. See JURISPRUDENCE. legal immunity. See HOHFELD.
Legalism, Chinese. See CHINESE LEGALISM. legal liability. See HOHFELD. legal
moralism, the view (defended in this century by, e.g., Lord Patrick Devlin)
that law may properly be used to enforce morality, including notably “sexual
morality.” Contemporary critics of the view (e.g., Hart) expand on the argument
of Mill that law should only be used to prevent harm to others. See also MILL,
J. S.; PHILOSOPHY OF LAW; POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. P.S. legal no-right. See
HOHFELD. legal positivism, a theory about the nature of law, commonly thought
to be characterized by two major tenets: (1) that there is no necessary
connection between law and morality; and (2) that legal validity is determined
ultimately by reference to certain basic social facts, e.g., the command of the
sovereign (John Austin), the Grundnorm (Hans Kelsen), or the rule of
recognition (Hart). These different descriptions of the basic law-determining
facts lead to different claims about the normative character of law, with
classical positivists (e.g., John Austin) insisting that law is essentially
coercive, and modern positivists (e.g., Hans Kelsen) maintaining that it is
normative. The traditional opponent of the legal positivist is the natural law
theorist, who holds that no sharp distinction can be drawn between law and
morality, thus challenging positivism’s first tenet. Whether that tenet follows
from positivism’s second tenet is a question of current interest and leads inevitably
to the classical question of political theory: Under what conditions might
legal obligations, even if determined by social facts, create genuine political
obligations (e.g., the obligation to obey the law)? See also JURISPRUDENCE,
PHILOSOPHY OF LAW. P.S. legal power. See HOHFELD. legal principle. See DWORKIN.
legal privilege. See HOHFELD. legal realism, a theory in philosophy of law or
jurisprudence broadly characterized by the claim that the nature of law is
better understood by observing what courts and citizens actually do than by
analyzing stated legal rules and legal concepts. The theory is also associated
with the thoughts that legal rules are disguised predictions of what courts
will do, and that only the actual decisions of courts constitute law. There are
two important traditions of legal realism, in Scandinavia and in the United
States. Both began in the early part of the century, and both focus on the
reality (hence the name ‘legal realism’) of the actual legal system, rather
than on law’s official image of itself. The Scandinavian tradition is more
theoretical and presents its views as philosophical accounts of the normativity
of law based on skeptical methodology – the normative force of law consists in
nothing but the feelings of citizens or officials or both about or their
beliefs in that normative force. The older, U.S. tradition is more empirical or
sociological or instrumentalist, focusing on how legislation is actually
enacted, how rules are actually applied, how courts’ decisions are actually
taken, and so forth. U.S. legal realism in its contemporary form is known as
critical legal studies. Its argumentation is both empirical (law as experienced
to be and Lebenswelt legal realism 490 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 490
as being oppressive by gender, race, and class) and theoretical (law as
essentially indeterminate, or interpretative – properties that prime law for
its role in political manipulation). See also CRITICAL LEGAL STUDIES,
JURISPRUDENCE, LEGAL POSITIVISM, PHILOSOPHY OF LAW. R.A.Sh. legal right. See
HOHFELD, RIGHTS. legal rule. See DWORKIN. legisign. See PEIRCE. Leibniz,
Gottfried Wilhelm (1646–1716), German rationalist philosopher who made seminal
contributions in geology, linguistics, historiography, mathematics, and
physics, as well as philosophy. He was born in Leipzig and died in Hanover.
Trained in the law, he earned a living as a councilor, diplomat, librarian, and
historian, primarily in the court of Hanover. His contributions in mathematics,
physics, and philosophy were known and appreciated among his educated
contemporaries in virtue of his publication in Europe’s leading scholarly
journals and his vast correspondence with intellectuals in a variety of fields.
He was best known in his lifetime for his contributions to mathematics,
especially to the development of the calculus, where a debate raged over
whether Newton or Leibniz should be credited with priority for its discovery.
Current scholarly opinion seems to have settled on this: each discovered the
basic foundations of the calculus independently; Newton’s discovery preceded
that of Leibniz; Leibniz’s publication of the basic theory of the calculus
preceded that of Newton. Leibniz’s contributions to philosophy were known to
his contemporaries through articles published in learned journals,
correspondence, and one book published in his lifetime, the Theodicy (1710). He
wrote a book-length study of Locke’s philosophy, New Essays on Human
Understanding, but decided not to publish it when he learned of Locke’s death.
Examination of Leibniz’s papers after his own death revealed that what he
published during his lifetime was but the tip of the iceberg. Perhaps the most
complete formulation of Leibniz’s mature metaphysics occurs in his
correspondence (1698–1706) with Burcher De Volder, a professor of philosophy at
the University of Leyden. Leibniz therein formulated his basic ontological
thesis: Considering matters accurately, it must be said that there is nothing
in things except simple substances, and, in them, nothing but perception and
appetite. Moreover, matter and motion are not so much substances or things as
they are the phenomena of percipient beings, the reality of which is located in
the harmony of each percipient with itself (with respect to different times)
and with other percipients. In this passage Leibniz asserts that the basic
individuals of an acceptable ontology are all monads, i.e., immaterial entities
lacking spatial parts, whose basic properties are a function of their
perceptions and appetites. He held that each monad perceives all the other
monads with varying degrees of clarity, except for God, who perceives all
monads with utter clarity. Leibniz’s main theses concerning causality among the
created monads are these: God creates, conserves, and concurs in the actions of
each created monad. Each state of a created monad is a causal consequence of
its preceding state, except for its state at creation and any of its states due
to miraculous divine causality. Intrasubstantial causality is the rule with
respect to created monads, which are precluded from intersubstantial causality,
a mode of operation of which God alone is capable. Leibniz was aware that
elements of this monadology may seem counterintuitive, that, e.g., there appear
to be extended entities composed of parts, existing in space and time, causally
interacting with each other. In the second sentence of the quoted passage
Leibniz set out some of the ingredients of his theory of the preestablished
harmony, one point of which is to save those appearances that are sufficiently
well-founded to deserve saving. In the case of material objects, Leibniz
formulated a version of phenomenalism, based on harmony among the perceptions
of the monads. In the case of apparent intersubstantial causal relations among
created monads, Leibniz proposed an analysis according to which the underlying
reality is an increase in the clarity of relevant perceptions of the apparent
causal agent, combined with a corresponding decrease in the clarity of the
relevant perceptions of the apparent patient. Leibniz treated material objects
and intersubstantial causal relations among created entities as well-founded
phenomena. By contrast, he treated space and time as ideal entities. Leibniz’s
mature metaphysics includes a threefold classifilegal right Leibniz, Gottfried
Wilhelm 491 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 491 cation of entities that
must be accorded some degree of reality: ideal entities, well-founded
phenomena, and actual existents, i.e., the monads with their perceptions and
appetites. In the passage quoted above Leibniz set out to distinguish the
actual entities, the monads, from material entities, which he regarded as
well-founded phenomena. In the following passage from another letter to De
Volder he formulated the distinction between actual and ideal entities: In
actual entities there is nothing but discrete quantity, namely, the multitude
of monads, i.e., simple substances. . . . But continuous quantity is something
ideal, which pertains to possibles, and to actuals, insofar as they are
possible. Indeed, a continuum involves indeterminate parts, whereas, by
contrast, there is nothing indefinite in actual entities, in which every
division that can be made, is made. Actual things are composed in the manner
that a number is composed of unities, ideal things are composed in the manner
that a number is composed of fractions. The parts are actual in the real whole,
but not in the ideal. By confusing ideal things with real substances when we
seek actual parts in the order of possibles and indeterminate parts in the
aggregate of actual things, we entangle ourselves in the labyrinth of the
continuum and in inexplicable contradictions. The labyrinth of the continuum
was one of two labyrinths that, according to Leibniz, vex the philosophical
mind. His views about the proper course to take in unraveling the labyrinth of
the continuum are one source of his monadology. Ultimately, he concluded that
whatever may be infinitely divided without reaching indivisible entities is not
something that belongs in the basic ontological category. His investigations of
the nature of individuation and identity over time provided premises from which
he concluded that only indivisible entities are ultimately real, and that an
individual persists over time only if its subsequent states are causal
consequences of its preceding states. In refining the metaphysical insights
that yielded the monadology, Leibniz formulated and defended various important
metaphysical theses, e.g.: the identity of indiscernibles – that individual
substances differ with respect to their intrinsic, non-relational properties;
and the doctrine of minute perceptions – that each created substance has some
perceptions of which it lacks awareness. In the process of providing what he took
to be an acceptable account of well-founded phenomena, Leibniz formulated
various theses counter to the then prevailing Cartesian orthodoxy, concerning
the nature of material objects. In particular, Leibniz argued that a correct
application of Galileo’s discoveries concerning acceleration of freely falling
bodies of the phenomena of impact indicates that force is not to be identified
with quantity of motion, i.e., mass times velocity, as Descartes held, but is
to be measured by mass times the square of the velocity. Moreover, Leibniz
argued that it is force, measured as mass times the square of the velocity,
that is conserved in nature, not quantity of motion. From these results Leibniz
drew some important metaphysical conclusions. He argued that force, unlike
quantity of motion, cannot be reduced to a conjunction of modifications of
extension. But force is a central property of material objects. Hence, he
concluded that Descartes was mistaken in attempting to reduce matter to
extension and its modifications. Leibniz concluded that each material substance
must have a substantial form that accounts for its active force. These
conclusions have to do with entities that Leibniz viewed as phenomenal. He drew
analogous conclusions concerning the entities he regarded as ultimately real,
i.e., the monads. Thus, although Leibniz held that each monad is absolutely
simple, i.e., without parts, he also held that the matter–form distinction has
an application to each created monad. In a letter to De Volder he wrote: Therefore,
I distinguish (1) the primitive entelechy or soul, (2) primary matter, i.e.,
primitive passive power, (3) monads completed from these two, (4) mass, i.e.,
second matter . . . in which innumerable subordinate monads come together, (5)
the animal, i.e., corporeal substance, which a dominating monad makes into one
machine. The second labyrinth vexing the philosophical mind, according to
Leibniz, is the labyrinth of freedom. It is fair to say that for Leibniz the
labyrinth of freedom is fundamentally a matter of how it is possible that some
states of affairs obtain contingently, i.e., how it is possible that some
propositions are true that might have been false. There are two distinct
sources of the problem of contingency in Leibniz’s philosophy, one theological,
and the other metaphysical. Each source may be grasped by considering an
argument that appears to have premises to which Leibniz was predisposed and the
conclusion that every state of affairs that obtains, obtains necessarily, and
hence that there are no contingent propositions. Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm 492 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 492 The
metaphysical argument is centered on some of Leibniz’s theses about the nature
of truth. He held that the truth-value of all propositions is settled once
truth-values have been assigned to the elementary propositions, i.e., those
expressed by sentences in subject-predicate form. And he held that a sentence
in subject-predicate form expresses a true proposition if and only if the
concept of its predicate is included in the concept of its subject. But this
makes it sound as if Leibniz were committed to the view that an elementary
proposition is true if and only if it is conceptually true, from which it seems
to follow that an elementary proposition is true if and only if it is
necessarily true. Leibniz’s views concerning the relation of the truthvalue of
non-elementary propositions to the truth-value of elementary propositions,
then, seem to entail that there are no contingent propositions. He rejected
this conclusion in virtue of rejecting the thesis that if an elementary
proposition is conceptually true then it is necessarily true. The materials for
his rejection of this thesis are located in theses connected with his program for
a universal science (scientia universalis). This program had two parts: a
universal notation (characteristica universalis), whose purpose was to provide
a method for recording scientific facts as perspicuous as algebraic notation,
and a formal system of reasoning (calculus ratiocinator) for reasoning about
the facts recorded. Supporting Leibniz’s belief in the possibility and utility
of the characteristica universalis and the calculus ratiocinator is his thesis
that all concepts arise from simple primitive concepts via concept conjunction
and concept complementation. In virtue of this thesis, he held that all
concepts may be analyzed into their simple, primitive components, with this
proviso: in some cases there is no finite analysis of a concept into its
primitive components; but there is an analysis that converges on the primitive
components without ever reaching them. This is the doctrine of infinite
analysis, which Leibniz applied to ward off the threat to contingency
apparently posed by his account of truth. He held that an elementary
proposition is necessarily true if and only if there is a finite analysis that
reveals that its predicate concept is included in its subject concept. By
contrast, an elementary proposition is contingently true if and only if there
is no such finite analysis, but there is an analysis of its predicate concept
that converges on a component of its subject concept. The theological argument
may be put this way. There would be no world were God not to choose to create a
world. As with every choice, as, indeed, with every state of affairs that
obtains, there must be a sufficient reason for that choice, for the obtaining
of that state of affairs – this is what the principle of sufficient reason
amounts to, according to Leibniz. The reason for God’s choice of a world to
create must be located in God’s power and his moral character. But God is
allpowerful and morally perfect, both of which attributes he has of necessity.
Hence, of necessity, God chose to create the best possible world. Whatever
possible world is the best possible world, is so of necessity. Hence, whatever
possible world is actual, is so of necessity. A possible world is defined with
respect to the states of affairs that obtain in it. Hence, whatever states of
affairs obtain, do so of necessity. Therefore, there are no contingent
propositions. Leibniz’s options here were limited. He was committed to the
thesis that the principle of sufficient reason, when applied to God’s choice of
a world to create, given God’s attributes, yields the conclusion that this is
the best possible world – a fundamental component of his solution to the
problem of evil. He considered two ways of avoiding the conclusion of the
argument noted above. The first consists in claiming that although God is
metaphysically perfect of necessity, i.e., has every simple, positive
perfection of necessity, and although God is morally perfect, nonetheless he is
not morally perfect of necessity, but rather by choice. The second consists in
denying that whatever possible world is the best, is so of necessity, relying
on the idea that the claim that a given possible world is the best involves a
comparison with infinitely many other possible worlds, and hence, if true, is
only contingently true. Once again the doctrine of infinite analysis served as
the centerpiece of Leibniz’s efforts to establish that, contrary to
appearances, his views do not lead to necessitarianism, i.e., to the thesis
that there is no genuine contingency. Much of Leibniz’s work in philosophical theology
had as a central motivation an effort to formulate a sound philosophical and
theological basis for various church reunion projects – especially reunion
between Lutherans and Calvinists on the Protestant side, and ultimately,
reunion between Protestants and Catholics. He thought that most of the
classical arguments for the existence of God, if formulated with care, i.e., in
the way in which Leibniz formulated them, succeeded in proving what they set
out to prove. For example, Leibniz thought that Descartes’s version of the
ontological argument established the existence of a perfect being, with one
crucial proviso: that an absolutely perfect being is possible. Leibniz,
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm 493 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM
Page 493 Leibniz believed that none of his predecessors had established this
premise, so he set out to do so. The basic idea of his purported proof is this.
A perfection is a simple, positive property. Hence, there can be no
demonstration that there is a formal inconsistency in asserting that various
collections of them are instantiated by the same being. But if there is no such
demonstration, then it is possible that something has them all. Hence, a
perfect being is possible. Leibniz did not consider in detail many of the
fundamental epistemological issues that so moved Descartes and the British
empiricists. Nonetheless, Leibniz made significant contributions to the theory
of knowledge. His account of our knowledge of contingent truths is much like
what we would expect of an empiricist’s epistemology. He claimed that our
knowledge of particular contingent truths has its basis in sense perception. He
argued that simple enumerative induction cannot account for all our knowledge
of universal contingent truths; it must be supplemented by what he called the a
priori conjectural method, a precursor of the hypothetico-deductive method. He
made contributions to developing a formal theory of probability, which he
regarded as essential for an adequate account of our knowledge of contingent
truths. Leibniz’s rationalism is evident in his account of our a priori
knowledge, which for him amounted to our knowledge of necessary truths. Leibniz
thought that Locke’s empiricism did not provide an acceptable account of a
priori knowledge, because it attempted to locate all the materials of
justification as deriving from sensory experience, thus overlooking what
Leibniz took to be the primary source of our a priori knowledge, i.e., what is
innate in the mind. He summarized his debate with Locke on these matters thus:
Our differences are on matters of some importance. It is a matter of knowing if
the soul in itself is entirely empty like a writing tablet on which nothing has
as yet been written (tabula rasa), . . . and if everything inscribed there
comes solely from the senses and experience, or if the soul contains originally
the sources of various concepts and doctrines that external objects merely
reveal on occasion. The idea that some concepts and doctrines are innate in the
mind is central not only to Leibniz’s theory of knowledge, but also to his
metaphysics, because he held that the most basic metaphysical concepts, e.g.,
the concepts of the self, substance, and causation, are innate. Leibniz
utilized the ideas behind the characteristica universalis in order to formulate
a system of formal logic that is a genuine alternative to Aristotelian
syllogistic logic and to contemporary quantification theory. Assuming that
propositions are, in some fashion, composed of concepts and that all composite
concepts are, in some fashion, composed of primitive simple concepts, Leibniz
formulated a logic based on the idea of assigning numbers to concepts according
to certain rules. The entire program turns on his concept containment account
of truth previously mentioned. In connection with the metatheory of this logic
Leibniz formulated the principle: “eadem sunt quorum unum alteri substitui
potest salva veritate” (“Those things are the same of which one may be
substituted for the other preserving truth-value”). The proper interpretation
of this principle turns in part on exactly what “things” he had in mind. It is
likely that he intended to formulate a criterion of concept identity. Hence, it
is likely that this principle is distinct from the identity of indiscernibles,
previously mentioned, and also from what has come to be called Leibniz’s law,
i.e., the thesis that if x and y are the same individual then whatever is true
of x is true of y and vice versa. The account outlined above concentrates on Leibniz’s
mature views in metaphysics, epistemology, and logic. The evolution of his
thought in these areas is worthy of close study, which cannot be brought to a
definitive state until all of his philosophical work has been published in the
edition of the Akademie der Wissenschaften in Berlin. See also DESCARTES,
IDENTITY OF INDISCERNIBLES, LOCKE, POSSIBLE WORLDS, RATIONALISM, SPINOZA.
R.C.Sl. Leibniz’s law. See IDENTITY, LEIBNIZ. lekton (Greek, ‘what can be
said’), a Stoic term sometimes translated as ‘the meaning of an utterance’.
Lekta differ from utterances in being what utterances signify: they are said to
be what the Greek grasps and the non-Greek speaker does not when Greek is
spoken. Moreover, lekta are incorporeal, which for the Stoics means they do not,
strictly speaking, exist, but only “subsist,” and so cannot act or be acted
upon. They constitute the content of our mental states: they are what we assent
to and endeavor toward and they “correspond” to the presentations given to
rational animals. The Stoics acknowledged lekta for predicates as well as for
sentences (including questions, oaths, and imperatives); axiomata or Leibniz’s
law lekton 494 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 494 propositions are lekta
that can be assented to and may be true or false (although being essentially
tensed, their truth-values may change). The Stoics’ theory of reference
suggests that they also acknowledged singular propositions, which “perish” when
the referent ceases to exist. See also PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE, PROPOSITION,
STOICISM. V.C. lemmata. See COMMENTARIES ON PLATO. Lenin, Vladimir Ilich
(1870–1924), Russian political leader and Marxist theorist, a principal creator
of Soviet dialectical materialism. In Materialism and Empirio-Criticism (1909),
he attacked Russian contemporaries who sought to interpret Marx’s philosophy in
the spirit of the phenomenalistic positivism of Avenarius and Mach. Rejecting
their position as idealist, Lenin argues that matter is not a construct from
sensations but an objective reality independent of consciousness; because our
sensations directly copy this reality, objective truth is possible. The
dialectical dimension of Lenin’s outlook is best elaborated in his posthumous
Philosophical Notebooks (written 1914–16), a collection of reading notes and
fragments in which he gives close attention to the Hegelian dialectic and
displays warm sympathy toward it, though he argues that the dialectic should be
interpreted materialistically rather than idealistically. Some of Lenin’s most
original theorizing, presented in Imperialism as the Highest Stage of
Capitalism (1916) and State and Revolution (1918), is devoted to analyzing the
connection between monopoly capitalism and imperialism and to describing the
coming violent replacement of bourgeois rule by, first, the “dictatorship of
the proletariat” and, later, stateless communism. Lenin regarded all philosophy
as a partisan weapon in the class struggle, and he wielded his own philosophy
polemically in the interests of Communist revolution. As a result of the
victory of the Bolsheviks in November 1917, Lenin’s ideas were enshrined as the
cornerstone of Soviet intellectual culture and were considered above criticism
until the advent of glasnost in the late 1980s. With the end of Communist rule
following the dissolution of the Soviet Union in 1991, his influence declined
precipitously. See also MARXISM, RUSSIAN PHILOSOPHY. J.P.Sc. Leopold,
Friedrich. See NOVALIS. Lequier, Jules (1814–62), French philosopher, educated
in Paris, whose works were not published in his lifetime. He influenced
Renouvier, who regarded Lequier as his “master in philosophy.” Through
Renouvier, he came to the attention of James, who called Lequier a “philosopher
of genius.” Central to Lequier’s philosophy is the idea of freedom understood
as the power to “create,” or add novelty to the world. Such freedom involves an
element of arbitrariness and is incompatible with determinism. Anticipating
James, Lequier argued that determinism, consistently affirmed, leads to
skepticism about truth and values. Though a devout Roman Catholic, his
theological views were unorthodox for his time. God cannot know future free
actions until they occur and therefore cannot be wholly immutable and eternal.
Lequier’s views anticipate in striking ways some views of James, Bergson,
Alexander, and Peirce, and the process philosophies and process theologies of
Whitehead and Hartshorne. R.H.K. Leroux, Pierre (1797–1871), French philosopher
reputed to have introduced the word socialisme in France (c.1834). He claimed
to be the first to use solidarité as a sociological concept (in his memoirs, La
Grève de Samarez [The Beach at Samarez], 1863). The son of a Parisian café
owner, Leroux centered his life work on journalism, both as a printer
(patenting an advanced procedure for typesetting) and as founder of a number of
significant serial publications. The Encyclopédie Nouvelle (New Encyclopedia,
1833–48, incomplete), which he launched with Jean Reynaud (1806–63), was
conceived and written in the spirit of Diderot’s magnum opus. It aspired to be
the platform for republican and democratic thought during the July Monarchy
(1830–48). The reformer’s influence on contemporaries such as Hugo, Belinsky,
J. Michelet, and Heine was considerable. Leroux fervently believed in Progress,
unlimited and divinely inspired. This doctrine he took to be eighteenth-century
France’s particular contribution to the Enlightenment. Progress must make its
way between twin perils: the “follies of illuminism” or “foolish spiritualism”
and the “abject orgies of materialism.” Accordingly, Leroux blamed Condillac
for having “drawn up the code of materialism” by excluding an innate Subject
from his sensationalism (“Condillac,” Encyclopédie Nouvelle). Cousin’s
eclecticism, state doctrine under the July Monarchy and synonym for immobility
(“Philosophy requires no further development; it is complete as is,” Leroux
wrote sarcastically in 1838, echoing Cousin), was a lemmata Leroux, Pierre 495
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 495 constant target of his polemics. Having
abandoned traditional Christian beliefs, Leroux viewed immortality as an
infinite succession of rebirths on earth, our sense of personal identity being
preserved throughout by Platonic “reminiscences” (De l’Humanité [Concerning
Humanity], 1840). See also CONDILLAC, COUSIN, ENLIGHTENMENT. D.A.G. Lesniewski,
Stanislaw (1886–1939), Polish philosopher-logician, cofounder, with Lukasiewicz
and Kotarbigski, of the Warsaw Center of Logical Research. He perfected the
logical reconstruction of classical mathematics by Frege, Schröder, Whitehead,
and Russell in his synthesis of mathematical with modernized Aristotelian
logic. A pioneer in scientific semantics whose insights inspired Tarski,
Les’niewski distinguished genuine antinomies of belief, in theories intended as
true mathematical sciences, from mere formal inconsistencies in uninterpreted
calculi. Like Frege an acute critic of formalism, he sought to perfect one
comprehensive, logically true instrument of scientific investigation.
Demonstrably consistent, relative to classical elementary logic, and
distinguished by its philosophical motivation and logical economy, his system
integrates his central achievements. Other contributions include his
ideographic notation, his method of natural deduction from suppositions and his
demonstrations of inconsistency of other systems, even Frege’s revised
foundations of arithmetic. Fundamental were (1) his 1913 refutation of
Twardowski’s Platonistic theory of abstraction, which motivated his
“constructive nominalism”; and (2) his deep analyses of Russell’s paradox,
which led him to distinguish distributive from collective predication and (as
generalized to subsume Grelling and Nelson’s paradox of self-reference) logical
from semantic paradoxes, and so (years before Ramsey and Gödel) to
differentiate, not just the correlatives object language and metalanguage, but
any such correlative linguistic stages, and thus to relativize semantic
concepts to successive hierarchical strata in metalinguistic stratification.
His system of logic and foundations of mathematics comprise a hierarchy of
three axiomatic deductive theories: protothetic, ontology, and mereology. Each
can be variously based on just one axiom introducing a single undefined term.
His prototheses are basic to any further theory. Ontology, applying them,
complements protothetic to form his logic. Les’niewski’s ontology develops his
logic of predication, beginning (e.g.) with singular predication characterizing
the individual so-and-so as being one (of the one or more) such-and-such,
without needing classabstraction operators, dispensable here as in Russell’s
“no-class theory of classes.” But this, his logic of nouns, nominal or
predicational functions, etc., synthesizing formulations by Aristotle, Leibniz,
Boole, Schröder, and Whitehead, also represents a universal theory of being and
beings, beginning with related individuals and their characteristics, kinds, or
classes distributively understood to include individuals as singletons or
“one-member classes.” Les’niewski’s directives of definition and logical
grammar for his systems of protothetic and ontology provide for the unbounded
hierarchies of “open,” functional expressions. Systematic conventions of
contextual determinacy, exploiting dependence of meaning on context, permit
unequivocal use of the same forms of expression to bring out systematic
analogies between homonyms as analogues in Aristotle’s and Russell’s sense,
systematically ambiguous, differing in semantic category and hence
significance. Simple distinctions of semantic category within the object
language of the system itself, together with the metalinguistic stratification
to relativize semantic concepts, prevent logical and semantic paradoxes as
effectively as Russell’s ramified theory of types. Lesniewski’s system of
logic, though expressively rich enough to permit Platonist interpretation in
terms of universals, is yet “metaphysically neutral” in being free from ontic
commitments. It neither postulates, presupposes, nor implies existence of
either individuals or abstractions, but relies instead on equivalences without
existential import that merely introduce and explicate new terms. In his
“nominalist” construction of the endless Platonic ladder of abstraction,
logical principles can be elevated step by step, from any level to the next, by
definitions making abstractions eliminable, translatable by definition into
generalizations characterizing related individuals. In this sense it is
“constructively nominalist,” as a developing language always open to
introduction of new terms and categories, without appeal to “convenient
fictions.” Les’niewski’s system, completely designed by 1922, was logically and
chronologically in advance of Russell’s 1925 revision of Principia Mathematica
to accommodate Ramsey’s simplification of Russell’s theory of types. Yet
Les’niewski’s premature death, the ensuing disruption of war, which destroyed
his manuscripts and disLesniewski, Stanislaw Lesniewski, Stanislaw 496
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 496 persed survivors such as Sobocigski and
Lejewski, and the relative inaccessibility of publications delayed by
Les’niewski’s own perfectionism have retarded understanding of his work. See
also POLISH LOGIC. E.C.L. Lessing, Gotthold Ephraim (1729–81), German
philosopher, critic, and literary figure whose philosophical and theological
work aimed to replace the so-called possession of truth by a search for truth
through public debate. The son of a Protestant minister, he studied theology
but gave it up to take part in the literary debate between Gottsched and the
Swiss Bodmer and Breitinger, which dealt with French classicism (Boileau) and
English influences (Shakespeare for theater and Milton for poetry). His
literary criticism (Briefe, die neueste Literatur betreffend [“Letters on the
New Literature”], 1759–65), his own dramatic works, and his
theological-philosophical reflections were united in his conception of a
practical Aufklärung, which opposed all philosophical or religious dogmatism.
Lessing’s creation and direction of the National German Theater of Hamburg
(1767–70) helped to form a sense of German national identity. In 1750 Lessing
published Thoughts on the Moravian Brothers, which contrasted religion as lived
by this pietist community with the ecclesiastical institution. In 1753–54 he
wrote a series of “rehabilitations” (Rettugen) to show that the opposition
between dogmas and heresies, between “truth” and “error,” was incompatible with
living religious thought. This position had the seeds of a historical
conception of religion that Lessing developed during his last years. In 1754 he
again attempted a deductive formulation, inspired by Spinoza, of the
fundamental truths of Christianity. Lessing rejected this rationalism, as
substituting a dogma of reason for one of religion. To provoke public debate on
the issue, be published H. S. Reimarus’s Fragments of an Anonymous Author
(1774–78), which the Protestant hierarchy considered atheistic. The relativism
and soft deism to which his arguments seemed to lead were transformed in his
Education of Mankind (1780) into a historical theory of truth. In Lessing’s
view, all religions have an equal dignity, for none possesses “the” truth; they
represent only ethical and practical moments in the history of mankind.
Revelation is assimilated into an education of mankind and God is compared to a
teacher who reveals to man only what he is able to assimilate. This
secularization of the history of salvation, in which God becomes immanent in
the world, is called pantheism (“the quarrel of pantheism”). For Lessing,
Judaism and Christianity are the preliminary stages of a third gospel, the
“Gospel of Reason.” The Masonic Dialogues (1778) introduced this historical and
practical conception of truth as a progress from “thinking by oneself” to dialogue
(“thinking aloud with a friend”). In the literary domain Lessing broke with the
culture of the baroque: against the giants and martyrs of baroque tragedy, he
offered the tragedy of the bourgeois, with whom any spectator must be able to
identify. After a poor first play in 1755 – Miss Sara Sampson – which only
reflected the sentimentalism of the time, Lessing produced a model of the genre
with Emilia Galotti (1781). The Hamburg Dramaturgy (1767– 68) was supposed to
be influenced by Aristotle, but its union of fear and pity was greatly
influenced by Moses Mendelssohn’s theory of “mixed sensations.” Lessing’s
entire aesthetics was based not on permanent ontological, religious, or moral
rules, but on the spectator’s interest. In Laokoon (1766) he associated this
aesthetics of reception with one of artistic production, i.e., a reflection on
the means through which poetry and the plastic arts create this interest: the
plastic arts by natural signs and poetry through the arbitrary signs that
overcome their artificiality through the imitation not of nature but of action.
Much like Winckelmann’s aesthetics, which influenced German classicism for a
considerable time, Lessing’s aesthetics opposed the baroque, but for a theory
of ideal beauty inspired by Plato it substituted a foundation of the beautiful
in the agreement between producer and receptor. See also MENDELSSOHN. G.Ra.
Leucippus (fl. c.440 B.C.), Greek pre-Socratic philosopher credited with
founding atomism, expounded in a work titled The Great World-system. Positing
the existence of atoms and the void, he answered Eleatic arguments against
change by allowing change of place. The arrangements and rearrangements of
groups of atoms could account for macroscopic changes in the world, and indeed
for the world itself. Little else is known of Leucippus. It is difficult to
distinguish his contributions from those of his prolific follower Democritus.
See also ANCIENT ATOMISM. D.W.G. level. See TYPE THEORY. Levi ben Gershom. See
GERSONIDES. Lessing, Gotthold Ephraim Levi ben Gershom 497 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 497 Levinas, Emmanuel (1906–95), Lithuanian-born French
philosopher. Educated as an orthodox Jew and a Russian citizen, he studied
philosophy at Strasbourg (1924–29) and Freiburg (1928– 29), introduced the work
of Husserl and Heidegger in France, taught philosophy at a Jewish school in
Paris, spent four years in a German labor camp (1940–44), and was a professor
at the universities of Poitiers, Nanterre, and the Sorbonne. To the impersonal
totality of being reduced to “the same” by the Western tradition (including
Hegel’s and Husserl’s idealism and Heidegger’s ontology), Levinas opposes the
irreducible otherness of the human other, death, time, God, etc. In Totalité et
Infini: Essai sur l’extériorité (1961), he shows how the other’s facing and
speaking urge philosophy to transcend the horizons of comprehension, while
Autrement qu’être ou au-delà de l’essence (1974) concentrates on the self of
“me” as one-for-the-other. Appealing to Plato’s form of the Good and
Descartes’s idea of the infinite, Levinas describes the asymmetrical relation
between the other’s “highness” or “infinity” and me, whose self-enjoyment is
thus interrupted by a basic imperative: Do not kill me, but help me to live!
The fact of the other’s existence immediately reveals the basic “ought” of
ethics; it awakens me to a responsibility that I have never been able to choose
or to refuse. My radical “passivity,” thus revealed, shows the anachronic
character of human temporality. It also refers to the immemorial past of “Him”
whose “illeity” is still otherwise other than the human other: God, or the Good
itself, who is neither an object nor a you. Religion and ethics coincide
because the only way to meet with God is to practice one’s responsibility for
the human other, who is “in the trace of God.” Comprehensive thematization and
systematic objectification, though always in danger of reducing all otherness,
have their own relative and subordinate truth, especially with regard to the
economic and political conditions of universal justice toward all individuals
whom I cannot encounter personally. With and through the other I meet all
humans. In this experience lies the origin of equality and human rights.
Similarly, theoretical thematization has a positive role if it remains aware of
its ancillary or angelic role with regard to concern for the other. What is
said in philosophy betrays the saying by which it is communicated. It must
therefore be unsaid in a return to the saying. More than desire for theoretical
wisdom, philosophy is the wisdom of love. See also HEIDEGGER, HUSSERL. A.T.P.
Lewin, Kurt (1890–1947), German and American (after 1932) psychologist, perhaps
the most influential of the Gestalt psychologists in the United States.
Believing traditional psychology was stuck in an “Aristotelian” class-logic
stage of theorizing, Lewin proposed advancing to a “Galilean” stage of field
theory. His central field concept was the “life space, containing the person
and his psychological environment.” Primarily concerned with motivation, he
explained locomotion as caused by life-space objects’ valences, psychological
vectors of force acting on people as physical vectors of force act on physical
objects. Objects with positive valence exert attractive force; objects with
negative valence exert repulsive force; ambivalent objects exert both. To
attain theoretical rigor, Lewin borrowed from mathematical topology, mapping
life spaces as diagrams. For example, this represented the motivational
conflict involved in choosing between pizza and hamburger: Life spaces
frequently contain psychological barriers (e.g., no money) blocking movement
toward or away from a valenced object. Lewin also created the important field
of group dynamics in 1939, carrying out innovative studies on children and
adults, focusing on group cohesion and effects of leadership style. His main
works are A Dynamic Theory of Personality (1935), Principles of Topological
Psychology (1936), and Field Theory in Social Science (1951). See also KÖHLER, MOTIVATIONAL
EXPLANATION. T.H.L. Lewis, C(larence) I(rving) (1883–1964), American
philosopher who advocated a version of pragmatism and empiricism, but was
nonetheless strongly influenced by Kant. Lewis was born in Massachusetts,
educated at Harvard, and taught at the University of California (1911–20) and
Harvard (1920–53). He wrote in logic (A Survey of Symbolic Logic, 1918;
Symbolic Logic, 1932, coauthored with C. H. Langford), in epistemology (Mind
and the World Order, 1929; An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation, 1946), and
in Levinas, Emmanuel Lewis, C(larence) I(rving) 498 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40
AM Page 498 ethical theory (The Ground and Nature of the Right, 1965; Our
Social Inheritance, 1957). General views. Use of the senses involves “presentations”
of sense experiences that signalize external objects. Reflection upon the
relations of sense experiences to psychological “intensions” permits our
thoughts to refer to aspects of objective reality. Consequently, we can
experience those non-presented objective conditions. Intensions, which include
the mind’s categories, are meanings in one ordinary sense, and concepts in a
philosophical sense. When judging counts as knowing, it has the future-oriented
function and sole value of guiding action in pursuit of what one evaluates as
good. Intensions do not fundamentally depend upon being formulated in those
linguistic phrases that may express them and thereby acquire meaning. Pace
Kant, our categories are replaceable when pragmatically unsuccessful, and are sometimes
invented, although typically socially instilled. Kant also failed to realize
that any a priori knowledge concerns only what is expressed by an “analytic
truth,” i.e., what is knowable with certainty via reflection upon intensions
and permits reference to the necessary inclusion (and exclusion) relations
between objective properties. Such inclusion/exclusion relationships are
“entailments” expressible by a use of “if . . . then . . .” different from
material implication. The degree of justification of an empirical judgment
about objective reality (e.g., that there is a doorknob before one) and of any
beliefs in consequences that are probable given the judgment, approximates to
certainty when the judgment stands in a relationship of “congruence” to a
collection of justified judgments (e.g., a collection including the judgments
that one remembers seeing a doorknob a moment before, and that one has not just
turned around). Lewis’s empiricism involves one type of phenomenalism. Although
he treats external conditions as metaphysically distinct from passages of sense
experience, he maintains that the process of learning about the former does not
involve more than learning about the latter. Accordingly, he speaks of the
“sense meaning” of an intension, referring to an objective condition. It
concerns what one intends to count as a process that verifies that the
particular intension applies to the objective world. Sense meanings of a
statement may be conceived as additional “entailments” of it, and are expressible
by conjunctions of an infinite number of statements each of which is “the
general form of a specific terminating judgment” (as defined below). Lewis
wants his treatment of sense meaning to rule out Berkeley’s view that objects
exist only when perceived. Verification of an objective judgment, as Kant
realized, is largely specified by a non-social process expressed by a rule to
act in imaginable ways in response to imaginable present sense experiences
(e.g. seeing a doorknob) and thereupon to have imaginable future sense
experiences (e.g. feeling a doorknob). Actual instances of such passages of
sense experience raise the probability of an objective judgment, whose
verification is always partial. Apprehensions of sense experiences are
judgments that are not reached by basing them on grounds in a way that might
conceivably produce errors. Such apprehensions are “certain.” The latter term
may be employed by Lewis in more than one sense, but here it at least implies
that the judgment is rationally credible and in the above sense not capable of
being in error. So such an apprehension is “datal,” i.e., rationally employed
in judging other matters, and “immediate,” i.e., formed noninferentially in
response to a presentation. These presentations make up “the (sensory) given.”
Sense experience is what remains after everything that is less than certain in
one’s experience of an objective condition is set aside. Lewis thought some
version of the epistemic regress argument to be correct, and defended the
Cartesian view that without something certain as a foundation no judgment has
any degree of justification. Technical terminology. Presentation: something
involved in experience, e.g. a visual impression, in virtue of which one
possesses a non-inferential judgment that it is involved. The given: those
presentations that have the content that they do independently of one’s
intending or deciding that they have it. Terminating: decisively and completely
verifiable or falsifiable in principle. (E.g., where S affirms a present sense
experience, A affirms an experience of seeming to initiate an action, and E
affirms a future instance of sense experience, the judgment ‘S and if A then E’
is terminating.) The general form of the terminating judgment that S and if A
then E: the conditional that if S then (in all probability) E, if A. (An actual
judgment expressed by this conditional is based on remembering passages of
sense experience of type S/A/E and is justified thanks to the principle of
induction and the principle that seeming to remember Lewis, C(larence) I(rving)
Lewis, C(larence) I(rving) 499 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 499 an event
makes the judgment that the event occurred justified at least to some degree.
These statements concern a connection that holds independently of whether
anyone is thinking and underlies the rationality of relying to any degree upon
what is not part of one’s self.) Congruence: the relationship among statements
in a collection when the following conditional is true: If each had some degree
of justification independently of the remaining ones, then each would be made
more justified by the conjoint truth of the remaining ones. (When the
antecedent of this conditional is true, and a statement in the collection is
such that it is highly improbable that the remaining ones all be true unless it
is true, then it is made very highly justified.) Pragmatic a priori: those
judgments that are not based on the use of the senses but on employing a set of
intensions, and yet are susceptible of being reasonably set aside because of a
shift to a different set of intensions whose employment is pragmatically more
useful (roughly, more useful for the attainment of what has intrinsic value).
Valuation: the appraising of something as having value or being morally right.
(What has some value that is not due to its consequences is what has intrinsic
value, e.g., enjoyable experiences of self-realization in living rationally.
Other evaluations of what is good are empirical judgments concerning what may
be involved in actions leading to what is intrinsically good. Rational
reflection permits awareness of various moral principles.) See also
ANALYTIC–SYNTHETIC DISTINCTION; A PRIORI; CERTAINTY; FOUNDATIONALISM;
PHENOMENALISM; PRAGMATISM; SELLARS, WILFRID. R.K.S. Lewis, C(live) S(taples)
(1898–1963), English literary critic, novelist, and Christian apologist. Born
in Belfast, Lewis took three first-class degrees at Oxford, became a tutor at
its Magdalen College in 1925, and assumed the chair of medieval and Renaissance
studies at Cambridge in 1954. While his tremendous output includes important
works on medieval literature and literary criticism, he is best known for his
fiction and Christian apologetics. Lewis combined a poetic sense and
appreciation of argument that allowed him to communicate complex philosophical
and theological material to lay audiences. His popular writings in the
philosophy of religion range over a variety of topics, including the nature and
existence of God (Mere Christianity, 1952), miracles (Miracles, 1947), hell
(The Great Divorce, 1945), and the problem of evil (The Problem of Pain, 1940).
His own conversion to Christianity as an adult is chronicled in his
autobiography (Surprised by Joy, 1955). In defending theism Lewis employed
arguments from natural theology (most notably versions of the moral and
teleological arguments) and arguments from religious experience. Also of
philosophical interest is his defense of moral absolutism in The Abolition of
Man (1943). See also PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. W.J.Wo. Lewis, David K. (b.1941),
American philosopher influential in many areas. Lewis received the B.A. in
philosophy from Swarthmore in 1962 and the Ph.D. in philosophy from Harvard in
1967. He has been a member of the philosophy department at U.C.L.A. (1966–70) and
Princeton (1970–). In philosophy of mind, Lewis is known principally for “An
Argument for the Identity Theory” (1966), “Psychophysical and Theoretical
Identifications” (1972), and “Mad Pain and Martian Pain” (1980). He argues for
the functionalist thesis that mental states are defined by their typical causal
roles, and the materialist thesis that the causal roles definitive of mental
states are occupied by physical states. Lewis develops the view that
theoretical definitions in general are functionally defined, applying the
formal concept of a Ramsey sentence. And he suggests that the platitudes of
commonsense or folk psychology constitute the theory implicitly defining
psychological concepts. In philosophy of language and linguistics, Lewis is
known principally for Convention (1969), “General Semantics” (1970), and
“Languages and Language” (1975). His theory of convention had its source in the
theory of games of pure coordination developed by von Neumann and Morgenstern.
Roughly, conventions are arbitrary solutions to coordination problems that
perpetuate themselves once a precedent is set because they serve a common
interest. Lewis requires it to be common knowledge that people prefer to
conform to a conventional regularity given that others do. He treats linguistic
meanings as compositional intensions. The basic intensions for lexical
constituents are functions assigning extensions to indices, which include
contextual factors and a possible world. An analytic sentence is one true at
every index. Languages are functions from sentences to meanLewis, C(live)
S(taples) Lewis, David K. 500 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 500 ings, and
the language of a population is the one in which they have a convention of
truthfulness and trust. In metaphysics and modal logic, Lewis is known
principally for “Counterpart Theory and Quantified Modal Logic” (1968) and On
the Plurality of Worlds (1986). Based on its theoretical benefits, Lewis argues
for modal realism: other possible worlds and the objects in them are just as real
as the actual world and its inhabitants. Lewis develops a non-standard form of
modal logic in which objects exist in at most one possible world, and for which
the necessity of identity fails. Properties are identified with the set of
objects that have them in any possible world, and propositions as the set of
worlds in which they are true. He also develops a finergrained concept of
structured properties and propositions. In philosophical logic and philosophy
of science, Lewis is best known for Counterfactuals (1973), “Causation” (1973),
and “Probabilities of Conditionals and Conditional Probabilities” (1976). He
developed a formal semantics for counterfactual conditionals that matches their
truth conditions and logic much more adequately than the previously available
material or strict conditional analyses. Roughly, a counterfactual is true if
its consequent is true in every possible world in which its antecedent is true
that is as similar overall to the actual world as the truth of the antecedent
will allow. Lewis then defended an analysis of causation in terms of
counterfactuals: c caused e if e would not have occurred if c had not occurred
or if there is a chain of events leading from e to c each member of which is
counterfactually dependent on the next. He presents a reductio ad absurdum
argument to show that conditional probabilities could not be identified with
the probabilities of any sort of conditional. Lewis has also written on visual
experience, events, holes, parts of classes, time travel, survival and
identity, subjective and objective probability, desire as belief, attitudes de
se, deontic logic, decision theory, the prisoner’s dilemma and the Newcomb
problem, utilitarianism, dispositional theories of value, nuclear deterrence,
punishment, and academic ethics. See also CAUSATION, CONDITIONAL,
FUNCTIONALISM, MEANING, POSSIBLE WORLDS. W.A.D. lexical ambiguity. See
AMBIGUITY. lexical ordering, also called lexicographic ordering, a method,
given a finite ordered set of symbols, such as the letters of the alphabet, of
ordering all finite sequences of those symbols. All finite sequences of
letters, e.g., can be ordered as follows: first list all single letters in
alphabetical order; then list all pairs of letters in the order aa, ab, . . .
az; ba . . . bz; . . . ; za . . . zz. Here pairs are first grouped and
alphabetized according to the first letter of the pair, and then within these
groups are alphabetized according to the second letter of the pair. All
sequences of three letters, four letters, etc., are then listed in order by an
analogous process. In this way every sequence of n letters, for any n, is
listed. Lexical ordering differs from alphabetical ordering, although it makes
use of it, because all sequences with n letters come before any sequence with n
! 1 letters; thus, zzt will come before aaab. One use of lexical ordering is to
show that the set of all finite sequences of symbols, and thus the set of all
words, is at most denumerably infinite. See also INFINITY. V.K. li1, Chinese
term meaning ‘pattern’, ‘principle’, ‘good order’, ‘inherent order’, or ‘to put
in order’. During the Han dynasty, li described not only the pattern of a given
thing, event, or process, but the underlying grand pattern of everything, the
deep structure of the cosmos. Later, Hua-yen Buddhists, working from the
Mahayana doctrine that all things are conditioned and related through past
causal relationships, claimed that each thing reflects the li of all things.
This influenced Neo-Confucians, who developed a metaphysics of li and ch’i
(ether), in which all things possess all li (and hence they are “one” in some
deep sense), but because of the differing quality of their ch’i, things
manifest different and distinct characteristics. The hsin (heart/mind) contains
all li (some insist it is li) but is obscured by “impure” ch’i; hence we
understand some things and can learn others. Through self-cultivation, one can
purify one’s ch’i and achieve complete and perfect understanding. See also
NEO-CONFUCIANISM, TAOISM. P.J.I. li2, Chinese term meaning ‘rite’, ‘ritual’,
‘etiquette’, ‘ritual propriety’. In its earliest use, li refers to
politico-religious rituals such as sacrifices to ancestors or funerals. Soon
the term came to encompass matters of etiquette, such as the proper way to greet
a guest. In some texts the li include even matters of morality or natural law.
Mencius refers to li as a virtue, but it is unclear lexical ambiguity li2 501
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 501 how it is distinct from his other
cardinal virtues. Emphasis upon li is one of the distinctive features of
Confucianism. Critics charge that this emphasis is a conflation of the natural
with the conventional or simply naive traditionalism. Others claim that the
notion of li draws attention to the subtle interdependence of morality and
convention, and points the way to creating genuine communities by treating “the
secular as sacred.” See also CONFUCIANISM, MOHISM, TAOISM. B.W.V.N. li3,
Chinese term meaning ‘profit’ or ‘benefit’, and probably with the basic meaning
of ‘smooth’ or ‘unimpeded’. Mo Tzu (fourth century B.C.) regarded what brings
li (benefit) to the public as the criterion of yi (rightness), and certain
other classical Chinese texts also describe yi as the basis for producing li.
Confucians tend to use ‘li’ pejoratively to refer to what profits oneself or
social groups (e.g., one’s family) to which one belongs, and contrast li with
yi. According to them, one should ideally be guided by yi rather than li, and
in the political realm, a preoccupation with li will lead to strife and
disorder. See also CONFUCIANISM, MOHISM. K.-l.S. liability responsibility. See
RESPONSIBILITY. Liang Ch’i-ch’ao (1873–1929), Chinese scholar and writer. A
disciple of K’ang Yu-wei, the young Liang was a reformist unsympathetic to Sun
Yatsen’s revolutionary activities. But after the republic was founded, he
embraced the democratic ideal. He was eager to introduce ideas from the West to
reform the Chinese people. But after a tour of Europe he had great reservations
about Western civilization. His unfavorable impressions touched off a debate
between science and metaphysics in 1923. His scholarly works include studies of
Buddhism and of Chinese thought in the last three hundred years. See also
CHINESE PHILOSOPHY, K’ANG YU-WEI, SUN YAT-SEN. S.-h.L. liang-chih, Chinese term
commonly rendered as ‘innate knowledge of the good’, although that translation
is quite inadequate to the term’s range of meanings. The term first occurs in
Mencius but becomes a key concept in Wang Yangming’s philosophy. A coherent
explication of liang-chih must attend to the following features. (1) Mencius’s
liang-chih (sense of right and wrong) is the ability to distinguish right from
wrong conduct. For Wang “this sense of right and wrong is nothing but the love [of
good] and the hate [of evil].” (2) Wang’s liang-chih is a moral consciousness
informed by a vision of jen or “forming one body” with all things in the
universe. (3) The exercise of liang-chih involves deliberation in coping with
changing circumstances. (4) The extension of liang-chih is indispensable to the
pursuit of jen. See also MENCIUS. A.S.C. Liang Sou-ming (1893–1988), Chinese
philosopher branded as the last Confucian. He actually believed, however, that
Buddhist philosophy was more profound than Confucian philosophy. Against those
advocating Westernization, Liang pointed out that Western and Indian cultures
went to two extremes; only the Chinese culture took a middle course. But it was
immature, and must learn first from the West, then from India. After the
Communist takeover, he refused to denounce traditional Chinese culture. He
valued human-heartedness, which he felt was neglected by Western science and
Marxism. He was admired overseas for his courage in standing up to Mao
Tse-tung. See also CHINESE PHILOSOPHY, HU SHIH, MAO TSE-TUNG. S.-h.L. Li Ao
(fl. A.D. 798), Chinese philosopher who learned Buddhist dialects and developed
a theory of human nature (hsing) and feelings (ch’ing) more sophisticated than
that of Han Yü, his teacher. He wrote a famous article, “Fu-hsing shu” (“Essay
on returning to Nature”), which exerted profound influence on Sung-Ming
Neo-Confucian philosophers. According to him, there are seven feelings: joy,
anger, pity, fear, love, hate, and desire. These feelings tend to obscure one’s
nature. Only when the feelings do not operate can one’s nature gain its
fulfillment. The sage does possess the feelings, but he remains immovable;
hence in a sense he also has never had such feelings. See also HAN Yü,
NEO-CONFUCIANISM. S.-h.L. liar cycle. See SEMANTIC PARADOXES. liar paradox. See
SEMANTIC PARADOXES. liberalism, a political philosophy first formulated during
the Enlightenment in response to the growth of modern nation-states, which
centralize governmental functions and claim sole authority to exercise coercive
power within their boundaries. One of its central theses has long been that a
government’s claim to this authority is justified only if the government can
show those who live under it that it secures their libli3 liberalism 502 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 502 erty. A central thesis of contemporary liberalism
is that government must be neutral in debates about the good human life. John
Locke, one of the founders of liberalism, tried to show that constitutional
monarchy secures liberty by arguing that free and equal persons in a state of
nature, concerned to protect their freedom and property, would agree with one
another to live under such a regime. Classical liberalism, which attaches great
value to economic liberty, traces its ancestry to Locke’s argument that
government must safeguard property. Locke’s use of an agreement or social
contract laid the basis for the form of liberalism championed by Rousseau and
most deeply indebted to Kant. According to Kant, the sort of liberty that
should be most highly valued is autonomy. Agents enjoy autonomy, Kant said,
when they live according to laws they would give to themselves. Rawls’s A
Theory of Justice (1971) set the main themes of the chapter of liberal thought
now being written. Rawls asked what principles of justice citizens would agree
to in a contract situation he called “the original position.” He argued that
they would agree to principles guaranteeing adequate basic liberties and fair
equality of opportunity, and requiring that economic inequalities benefit the
least advantaged. A government that respects these principles secures the
autonomy of its citizens by operating in accord with principles citizens would
give themselves in the original position. Because of the conditions of the
original position, citizens would not choose principles based on a
controversial conception of the good life. Neutrality among such conceptions is
therefore built into the foundations of Rawls’s theory. Some critics argue that
liberalism’s emphasis on autonomy and neutrality leaves it unable to account
for the values of tradition, community, or political participation, and unable
to limit individual liberty when limits are needed. Others argue that autonomy
is not the notion of freedom needed to explain why common forms of oppression
like sexism are wrong. Still others argue that liberalism’s focus on Western
democracies leaves it unable to address the most pressing problems of
contemporary politics. Recent work in liberal theory has therefore asked
whether liberalism can accommodate the political demands of religious and
ethnic communities, ground an adequate conception of democracy, capture
feminist critiques of extant power structures, or guide nation-building in the
face of secessionist, nationalist, and fundamentalist claims. See also KANT,
LOCKE, POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY, RAWLS, ROUSSEAU, SOCIAL CONTRACT. P.J.W. liberal
theory of the state. See LOCKE, POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. libertarianism,
metaphysical. See FREE WILL PROBLEM. libertarianism, political. See POLITICAL
PHILOSOPHY. liberty. See FREE WILL PROBLEM, HOHFELD, JURISPRUDENCE, POLITICAL
PHILOSOPHY. liberty of indifference. See FREE WILL PROBLEM, HUME. liberty of
spontaneity. See FREE WILL PROBLEM, HUME. liberty of the ancients. See
CONSTANT. liberty of the moderns. See CONSTANT. liberty right. See RIGHTS.
liberum arbitrium, Latin expression meaning ‘free judgment’, often used to
refer to medieval doctrines of free choice or free will. It appears in the
title of Augustine’s seminal work De libero arbitrio voluntatis (usually
translated ‘On the Free Choice of the Will’) and in many other medieval
writings (e.g., Aquinas, in Summa theologiae I, asks “whether man has free
choice [liberum arbitrium]”). For medieval thinkers, a judgment (arbitrium) “of
the will” was a conclusion of practical reasoning – “I will do this” (hence, a
choice or decision) – in contrast to a judgment “of the intellect” (“This is
the case”), which concludes theoretical reasoning. See also FREE WILL PROBLEM,
PRACTICAL REASONING. R.H.K. Li Chi (“Record of Rites”), Chinese Confucian
treatise, one of the three classics of li (rites, rules of proper conduct). For
Confucian ethics, the treatise is important for its focus on the reasoned
justification of li, the role of virtues in human relationships, and the
connection between personal cultivation and the significance of the rites of
mourning and sacrifices. Perhaps even more important, the Li Chi contains two
of the basic Four Books of Confucian ethics: The Great Learning (Ta Hsüeh) and
The Doctrine of the Mean (Chung Yung). It also contains a brief essay on
learning liberal theory of the state Li Chi 503 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM
Page 503 that stresses its interaction with ethical teaching. See also
CONFUCIANISM. A.S.C. li-ch’i, technical term in Chinese Neo-Confucianism
primarily used in the context of speculative cosmology, metaphysics, and
ontology for accounting for changing phenomena and their ethical significance.
Li is often rendered as ‘principle’, ‘order’, ‘pattern’, or ‘reason’; ch’i as
‘material force’, ‘ether’, or ‘energy’. Recent NeoConfucian scholarship
provides no clear guide to the li-ch’i distinction. In ethical contexts,
however, the distinction is used to explain the origin of human good and evil.
In its pure state, ch’i is inseparable from li, in the sense of compliance with
the Confucian ethical norm that can be reasonably justified. In its impure
state, ch’i presumably explains the existence of human evils. This perplexing
distinction remains a subject of scholarly inquiry. See also CH’I, LI1,
NEO-CONFUCIANISM. A.S.C. Lieh Tzu, also called Lieh Yu-K’ou (440?–360? B.C.),
Chinese Taoist philosopher whose name serves as the title of a work of disputed
date. The Lieh Tzu, parts (perhaps most) of which were written as late as the
third or fourth century A.D., is primarily a Taoist work but contains one
chapter reflecting ideas associated with Yang Chu. However, whereas the
original teachings of Yang Chu emphasized one’s duty to preserve bodily
integrity, health, and longevity, a task that may require exercise and
discipline, the Yang Chu chapter advocates hedonism as the means to nourish
life. The primary Taoist teaching of the Lieh Tzu is that destiny trumps will,
fate conquers effort. R.P.P. & R.T.A. life, the characteristic property of
living substances or things; it is associated with either a capacity for mental
activities such as perception and thought (mental life) or physical activities
such as absorption, excretion, metabolism, synthesis, and reproduction (physical
life). Biological or carbon-based lifeis a natural kind of physical life that
essentially involves a highly complex, selfregulating system of carbon-based
macromolecules and water molecules. Silicon-based life is wholly speculative
natural kind of physical life that essentially involves a highly complex,
selfregulating system of silicon-based macromolecules. This kind of life might
be possible, since at high temperatures silicon forms macromolecules with
chemical properties somewhat similar to those of carbon-based macromolecules.
Living organisms have a high degree of functional organization, with a
regulating or controlling master part, e.g., a dog’s nervous system, or the DNA
or nucleus of a single-celled organism. Mental life is usually thought to be
dependent or supervenient upon physical life, but some philosophers have argued
for the possibility at least of purely spiritual mental life, i.e., souls. The
above characterization of biological life appropriately implies that viruses
are not living things, since they lack the characteristic activities of living
things, with the exception of an attenuated form of reproduction. See also
ARTIFICIAL LIFE, ORGANISM. J.Ho. & G.Ro. life space. See LEWIN. life world.
See HUSSERL. light of nature. See DESCARTES. li-i-fen-shu, a Chinese phrase
meaning ‘Principle is one while duties or manifestations are many’. Chang Tsai
(1020–77) wrote the essay “The Western Inscription” in which he said that all
people were his brothers and sisters. Ch’eng Yi’s (1033–1107) disciple Yang
Shih (1053–1135) suspected Chang Tsai of teaching the Mohist doctrine of
universal love. Ch’eng Yi then coined the phrase to clarify the situation:
Chang Tsai was really teaching the Confucian doctrine of graded love – while
principle (li) is one, duties are many. Chu Hsi (1130–1200) further developed
the idea into a metaphysics by maintaining that principle is one while
manifestations are many, just as the same moon shines over different rivers.
See also CHINESE PHILOSOPHY, CHU HSI. S.-h.L. limited variety, principle of.
See MILL’s METHODS. limiting case, an individual or subclass of a given
background class that is maximally remote from “typical” or “paradigm” members
of the class with respect to some ordering that is not always explicitly mentioned.
The number zero is a limiting case of cardinal number. A triangle is a limiting
case of polygon. A square is a limiting case of rectangle when rectangles are
ordered by the ratio of length to width. Certainty is a limiting case of belief
when beliefs are ordered according to “strength of subjective conviction.”
Knowledge is a limiting case of belief when beliefs are ordered according
“adequacy of objective grounds.” A limiting case is necessarily a case (member)
of the background class; in contrast a li-ch’i limiting case 504 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 504 borderline case need not be a case and a degenerate
case may clearly fail to be a case at all. See also BORDERLINE CASE, DEGENERATE
CASE. J.Cor. linear order. See RELATION. linguistic analysis. See ANALYSIS.
linguistic competence. See PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE. linguistic determinism. See
LINGUISTIC RELATIVITY. linguistic performance. See PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE.
linguistic philosophy. See ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY. linguistic relativity, the
thesis that at least some distinctions found in one language are found in no
other language (a version of the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis); more generally, the
thesis that different languages utilize different representational systems that
are at least in some degree informationally incommensurable and hence
non-equivalent. The differences arise from the arbitrary features of languages
resulting in each language encoding lexically or grammatically some
distinctions not found in other languages. The thesis of linguistic determinism
holds that the ways people perceive or think about the world, especially with
respect to their classificatory systems, are causally determined or influenced
by their linguistic systems or by the structures common to all human languages.
Specifically, implicit or explicit linguistic categorization determines or
influences aspects of nonlinguistic categorization, memory, perception, or
cognition in general. Its strongest form (probably a straw-man position) holds
that linguistically unencoded concepts are unthinkable. Weaker forms hold that
concepts that are linguistically encoded are more accessible to thought and
easier to remember than those that are not. This thesis is independent of that
of linguistic relativity. Linguistic determinism plus linguistic relativity as
defined here implies the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis. See also SAPIR-WHORF
HYPOTHESIS. W.K.W. linguistics, philosophy of. See PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE.
linguistic semantics. See PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE. linguistic theory of logical
truth. See CONVENTIONALISM. literal meaning. See MEANING. literary theory, a
reasoned account of the nature of the literary artifact, its causes, effects,
and distinguishing features. So understood, literary theory is part of the
systematic study of literature covered by the term ‘criticism’, which also
includes interpretation of literary works, philology, literary history, and the
evaluation of particular works or bodies of work. Because it attempts to
provide the conceptual foundations for practical criticism, literary theory has
also been called “critical theory.” However, since the latter term has been
appropriated by neo-Marxists affiliated with the Frankfurt School to designate
their own kind of social critique, ‘literary theory’ is less open to
misunderstanding. Because of its concern with the ways in which literary
productions differ from other verbal artifacts and from other works of art,
literary theory overlaps extensively with philosophy, psychology, linguistics,
and the other human sciences. The first ex professo theory of literature in the
West, for centuries taken as normative, was Aristotle’s Poetics. On Aristotle’s
view, poetry is a verbal imitation of the forms of human life and action in
language made vivid by metaphor. It stimulates its audience to reflect on the
human condition, enriches their understanding, and thereby occasions the
pleasure that comes from the exercise of the cognitive faculty. The first real
paradigm shift in literary theory was introduced by the Romantics of the
nineteenth century. The Biographia Literaria (1817) of Samuel Taylor Coleridge,
recounting the author’s conversion from Humean empiricism to a form of German
idealism, defines poetry not as a representation of objective structures, but
as the imaginative self-expression of the creative subject. Its emphasis is not
on the poem as a source of pleasure but on poetry as a heightened form of
spiritual activity. The standard work on the transition from classical
(imitation) theory to Romantic (expression) theory is M. H. Abrams’s The Mirror
and the Lamp (1953). In the present century theory has assumed a place of
prominence in literary studies. In the first half of the century the works of
I. A. Richards – from his early positivist account of linear order literary
theory 505 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 505 poetry in books like Science
and Poetry (1926) to his later idealist views in books like The Philosophy of
Rhetoric (1936) – sponsored the practice of the American New Critics. The most
influential theorist of the period is Northrop Frye, whose formalist manifesto,
Anatomy of Criticism (1957), proposed to make criticism the “science of
literature.” The introduction of Continental thought to the English-speaking
critical establishment in the 1960s and after spawned a bewildering variety of
competing theories of literature: e.g., Russian formalism, structuralism,
deconstruction, new historicism, Marxism, Freudianism, feminism, and even the
anti-theoretical movement called the “new pragmatism.” The best summary account
of these developments is Frank Lentricchia’s After the New Criticism (1980).
Given the present near-chaos in criticism, the future of literary theory is
unpredictable. But the chaos itself offers ample opportunities for
philosophical analysis and calls for the kind of conceptual discrimination such
analysis can offer. Conversely, the study of literary theory can provide
philosophers with a better understanding of the textuality of philosophy and of
the ways in which philosophical content is determined by the literary form of
philosophical texts. See also AESTHETICS, PHILOSOPHY OF LITERATURE. L.H.M.
literature, philosophy of. See PHILOSOPHY OF LITERATURE. Liu Shao-ch’i
(1898–1969), Chinese Communist leader. A close ally of Mao Tse-tung, he was
purged near the end of his life when he refused to follow Mao’s radical
approach during the Cultural Revolution, became an ally of the practical Teng
Hsiao-ping, and was branded the biggest Capitalist Roader in China. In 1939 he
delivered in Yenan the influential speech “How to Be a Good Communist,”
published in 1943 and widely studied by Chinese Communists. As he emphasized
self-discipline, there appeared to be a Confucian dimension in his thought. The
article was banned during the Cultural Revolution, and he was accused of teaching
reactionary Confucianism in the revolutionary camp. He was later rehabilitated.
See also MAO TSE-TUNG. S.-h.L. Liu Tsung-chou, also called Ch’i-shan (1578–
1645), Chinese philosopher commonly regarded as the last major figure in
Sung–Ming Neo-Confucianism. He opposed all sorts of dualist thoughts, including
Chu Hsi’s philosophy. He was also not happy with some of Wang Yangming’s
followers who claimed that men in the streets were all sages. He shifted the
emphasis from rectification of the mind to sincerity of the will, and he gave a
new interpretation to “watchful over the self” in the Doctrine of the Mean.
Among his disciples was the great intellectual historian Huang Tsung-hsi. See
also CHU HSI, HUANG TSUNG-HSI, HU HUNG, NEO-CONFUCIANISM, WANG YANG-MING.
S.-h.L. Llull, Ramon. See LULL. Lobachevsky, Nikolai. See NON-EUCLIDEAN
GEOMETRY. locality assumption. See QUANTUM MECHANICS. Locke, John (1632–1704),
English philosopher and proponent of empiricism, famous especially for his
Essay concerning Human Understanding (1689) and for his Second Treatise of
Government, also published in 1689, though anonymously. He came from a
middle-class Puritan family in Somerset, and became acquainted with Scholastic
philosophy in his studies at Oxford. Not finding a career in church or
university attractive, he trained for a while as a physician, and developed
contacts with many members of the newly formed Royal Society; the chemist
Robert Boyle and the physicist Isaac Newton were close acquaintances. In 1667
he joined the London households of the then Lord Ashley, later first Earl of
Shaftesbury; there he became intimately involved in discussions surrounding the
politics of resistance to the Catholic king, Charles II. In 1683 he fled
England for the Netherlands, where he wrote out the final draft of his Essay.
He returned to England in 1689, a year after the accession to the English
throne of the Protestant William of Orange. In his last years he was the most
famous intellectual in England, perhaps in Europe generally. Locke was not a
university professor immersed in the discussions of the philosophy of “the
schools” but was instead intensely engaged in the social and cultural issues of
his day; his writings were addressed not to professional philosophers but to
the educated public in general. The Essay. The initial impulse for the line of
thought that culminated in the Essay occurred early in 1671, in a discussion
Locke had with some friends in Lord Shaftesbury’s apartments in literature,
philosophy of Locke, John 506 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 506 London on
matters of morality and revealed religion. In his Epistle to the Reader at the
beginning of the Essay Locke says that the discussants found themselves quickly
at a stand by the difficulties that arose on every side. After we had awhile
puzzled ourselves, without coming any nearer a resolution of those doubts which
perplexed us, it came into my thoughts that we took a wrong course, and that
before we set ourselves upon enquiries of that nature it was necessary to examine
our own abilities, and see what objects our understandings were or were not
fitted to deal with. Locke was well aware that for a thousand years European
humanity had consulted its textual inheritance for the resolution of its moral
and religious quandaries; elaborate strategies of interpretation, distinction,
etc., had been developed for extracting from those disparate sources a unified,
highly complex, body of truth. He was equally well aware that by his time, more
than a hundred years after the beginning of the Reformation, the moral and
religious tradition of Europe had broken up into warring and contradictory
fragments. Accordingly he warns his readers over and over against basing their
convictions merely on say-so, on unexamined tradition. As he puts it in a short
late book of his, The Conduct of the Understanding, “We should not judge of
things by men’s opinions, but of opinions by things.” We should look to “the
things themselves,” as he sometimes puts it. But to know how to get at the
things themselves it is necessary, so Locke thought, “to examine our own
abilities.” Hence the project of the Essay. The Essay comes in four books, Book
IV being the culmination. Fundamental to understanding Locke’s thought in Book
IV is the realization that knowledge, as he thinks of it, is a fundamentally
different phenomenon from belief. Locke holds, indeed, that knowledge is
typically accompanied by belief; it is not, though, to be identified with it.
Knowledge, as he thinks of it, is direct awareness of some fact – in his own
words, perception of some agreement or disagreement among things. Belief, by
contrast, consists of taking some proposition to be true – whether or not one
is directly aware of the corresponding fact. The question then arises: Of what
sorts of facts do we human beings have direct awareness? Locke’s answer is:
Only of facts that consist of relationships among our “ideas.” Exactly what
Locke had in mind when he spoke of ideas is a vexed topic; the traditional
view, for which there is a great deal to be said, is that he regarded ideas as
mental objects. Furthermore, he clearly regarded some ideas as being
representations of other entities; his own view was that we can think about
nonmental entities only by being aware of mental entities that represent those
non-mental realities. Locke argued that knowledge, thus understood, is “short
and scanty” – much too short and scanty for the living of life. Life requires
the formation of beliefs on matters where knowledge is not available. Now what
strikes anyone who surveys human beliefs is that many of them are false. What
also strikes any perceptive observer of the scene is that often we can – or
could have – done something about this. We can, to use Locke’s language,
“regulate” and “govern” our belief-forming capacities with the goal in mind of
getting things right. Locke was persuaded that not only can we thus regulate
and govern our belief-forming capacities; we ought to do so. It is a God-given
obligation that rests upon all of us. Specifically, for each human being there
are some matters of such “concernment,” as Locke calls it, as to place the
person under obligation to try his or her best to get things right. For all of
us there will be many issues that are not of such concernment; for those cases,
it will be acceptable to form our beliefs in whatever way nature or custom has
taught us to form them. But for each of us there will be certain practical
matters concerning which we are obligated to try our best – these differing
from person to person. And certain matters of ethics and religion are of such
concern to everybody that we are all obligated to try our best, on these
matters, to get in touch with reality. What does trying our best consist of,
when knowledge – perception, awareness, insight – is not available? One can
think of the practice Locke recommends as having three steps. First one
collects whatever evidence one can find for and against the proposition in
question. This evidence must consist of things that one knows; otherwise we are
just wandering in darkness. And the totality of the evidence must be a reliable
indicator of the probability of the proposition that one is considering.
Second, one analyzes the evidence to determine the probability of the
proposition in question, on that evidence. And last, one places a level of
confidence in the proposition that is proportioned to its probability on that
satisfactory evidence. If the proposition is highly probable on that evidence,
one believes it very firmly; if it only is quite probable, one Locke, John
Locke, John 507 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 507 believes it rather
weakly; etc. The main thrust of the latter half of Book IV of the Essay is
Locke’s exhortation to his readers to adopt this practice in the forming of
beliefs on matters of high concernment – and in particular, on matters of
morality and religion. It was his view that the new science being developed by
his friends Boyle and Newton and others was using exactly this method. Though
Book IV was clearly seen by Locke as the culmination of the Essay, it by no
means constitutes the bulk of it. Book I launches a famous attack on innate
ideas and innate knowledge; he argues that all our ideas and knowledge can be
accounted for by tracing the way in which the mind uses its innate capacities
to work on material presented to it by sensation and reflection (i.e.,
self-awareness). Book II then undertakes to account for all our ideas, on the
assumption that the only “input” is ideas of sensation and reflection, and that
the mind, which at birth is a tabula rasa (or blank tablet), works on these by
such operations as combination, division, generalization, and abstraction. And
then in Book III Locke discusses the various ways in which words hinder us in
our attempt to get to the things themselves. Along with many other thinkers of
the time, Locke distinguished between what he called natural theology and what
he called revealed theology. It was his view that a compelling, demonstrative
argument could be given for the existence of God, and thus that we could have
knowledge of God’s existence; the existence of God is a condition of our own
existence. In addition, he believed firmly that God had revealed things to
human beings. As he saw the situation, however, we can at most have beliefs,
not knowledge, concerning what God has revealed. For we can never just “see”
that a certain episode in human affairs is a case of divine revelation.
Accordingly, we must apply the practice outlined above, beginning by assembling
satisfactory evidence for the conclusion that a certain episode really is a
case of divine revelation. In Locke’s view, the occurrence of miracles provides
the required evidence. An implication of these theses concerning natural and
revealed religion is that it is never right for a human being to believe
something about God without having evidence for its truth, with the evidence
consisting ultimately of things that one “sees” immediately to be true. Locke
held to a divine command theory of moral obligation; to be morally obligated to
do something is for God to require of one that one do that. And since a great
deal of what Jesus taught, as Locke saw it, was a code of moral obligation, it
follows that once we have evidence for the revelatory status of what Jesus
said, we automatically have evidence that what Jesus taught as our moral
obligation really is that. Locke was firmly persuaded, however, that revelation
is not our only mode of access to moral obligation. Most if not all of our
moral obligations can also be arrived at by the use of our natural capacities,
unaided by revelation. To that part of our moral obligations which can in
principle be arrived at by the use of our natural capacities, Locke (in
traditional fashion) gave the title of natural law. Locke’s own view was that
morality could in principle be established as a deductive science, on analogy
to mathematics: one would first argue for God’s existence and for our status as
creatures of God; one would then argue that God was good, and cared for the
happiness of God’s creatures. Then one would argue that such a good God would
lay down commands to his creatures, aimed at their overall happiness. From
there, one would proceed to reflect on what does in fact conduce to human
happiness. And so forth. Locke never worked out the details of such a deductive
system of ethics; late in his life he concluded that it was beyond his
capacities. But he never gave up on the ideal. The Second Treatise and other
writings. Locke’s theory of natural law entered intimately into the theory of
civil obedience that he developed in the Second Treatise of Government.
Imagine, he said, a group of human beings living in what he called a state of
nature – i.e., a condition in which there is no governmental authority and no
private property. They would still be under divine obligation; and much (if not
all) of that obligation would be accessible to them by the use of their natural
capacities. There would be for them a natural law. In this state of nature they
would have title to their own persons and labor; natural law tells us that
these are inherently our “possessions.” But there would be no possessions
beyond that. The physical world would be like a gigantic English commons, given
by God to humanity as a whole. Locke then addresses himself to two questions:
How can we account for the emergence of political obligation from such a
situation, and how can we account for the emergence of private property? As to
the former, his answer is that we in effect make a contract with one another to
institute a government for the Locke, John Locke, John 508 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 508 elimination of certain deficiencies in the state of
nature, and then to obey that government, provided it does what we have
contracted with one another it should do and does not exceed that. Among the
deficiencies of the state of nature that a government can be expected to
correct is the sinful tendency of human beings to transgress on other persons’
properties, and the equally sinful tendency to punish such transgressions more
severely than the law of nature allows. As to the emergence of private
property, something from the world at large becomes a given person’s property
when that person “mixes” his or her labor with it. For though God gave the
world as a whole to all of us together, natural law tells us that each person’s
labor belongs to that person himself or herself – unless he or she freely
contracts it to someone else. Locke’s Second Treatise is thus an articulate
statement of the so-called liberal theory of the state; it remains one of the
greatest of such, and proved enormously influential. It should be seen as
supplemented by the Letters concerning Toleration (1689, 1690, 1692) that Locke
wrote on religious toleration, in which he argued that all theists who have not
pledged civil allegiance to some foreign power should be granted equal
toleration. Some letters that Locke wrote to a friend concerning the education
of the friend’s son should also be seen as supplementing the grand vision. If
we survey the way in which beliefs are actually formed in human beings, we see
that passion, the partisanship of distinct traditions, early training, etc.,
play important obstructive roles. It is impossible to weed out entirely from
one’s life the influence of such factors. When it comes to matters of high
“concernment,” however, it is our obligation to do so; it is our obligation to
implement the three-step practice outlined above, which Locke defends as doing
one’s best. But Locke did not think that the cultural reform he had in mind,
represented by the appropriate use of this new practice, could be expected to
come about as the result just of writing books and delivering exhortations.
Training in the new practice was required; in particular, training of small
children, before bad habits had been ingrained. Accordingly, Locke proposes in
Some Thoughts concerning Education (1693) an educational program aimed at
training children in when and how to collect satisfactory evidence, appraise
the probabilities of propositions on such evidence, and place levels of
confidence in those propositions proportioned to their probability on that
evidence. See also BERKELEY, EPISTEMOLOGY, ETHICS, EVIDENTIALISM, HUME,
POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. N.P.W. locutionary act. See SPEECH ACT THEORY. logic,
combinatory. See COMBINATORY LOGIC. logic, default. See DEFAULT LOGIC. logic,
deontic. See DEONTIC LOGIC. logic, deviant. See PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC. logic,
dynamic. See DYNAMIC LOGIC. logic, epistemic. See EPISTEMIC LOGIC. logic,
erotetic. See EROTETIC. logic, formal. See FORMAL LOGIC. logic, free. See FREE
LOGIC. logic, higher-order. See FORMAL LOGIC, PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC, SECOND-ORDER
LOGIC. logic, infinitary. See INFINITARY LOGIC. logic, informal. See INFORMAL
FALLACY, INFORMAL LOGIC. logic, intensional. See INTENSIONAL LOGIC. logic,
many-valued. See MANY-VALUED LOGIC. logic, mathematical. See FORMAL LOGIC.
logic, modal. See MODAL LOGIC. logic, non-monotonic. See NON-MONOTONIC LOGIC.
logic, ordinal. See ORDINAL LOGIC. logic, philosophy of. See PHILOSOPHY OF
LOGIC. logic, pluralitive. See PLURALITIVE LOGIC. logic, Polish. See POLISH
LOGIC. logic, predicate. See FORMAL LOGIC. logic, quantum. See QUANTUM LOGIC.
logic, relational. See RELATIONAL LOGIC. locutionary act logic, relational 509
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 509 logic, second-order. See SECOND-ORDER
LOGIC. logic, symbolic. See FORMAL LOGIC. logic, tense. See TENSE LOGIC. logic,
terminist. See TERMINIST LOGIC. logic, three-valued. See MANY-VALUED LOGIC.
logical atomism. See RUSSELL. logical behaviorism. See BEHAVIORISM, PHILOSOPHY
OF MIND. logical certainty. See CERTAINTY. logical consequence, a proposition,
sentence, or other piece of information that follows logically from one or more
other propositions, sentences, or pieces of information. A proposition C is
said to follow logically from, or to be a logical consequence of, propositions
P1, P2, . . . , if it must be the case that, on the assumption that P1, P2, . .
. , Pn are all true, the proposition C is true as well. For example, the
proposition ‘Smith is corrupt’ is a logical consequence of the two propositions
‘All politicians are corrupt’ and ‘Smith is a politician’, since it must be the
case that on the assumption that ‘All politicians are corrupt’ and ‘Smith is a
politician’ are both true, ‘Smith is corrupt’ is also true. Notice that
proposition C can be a logical consequence of propositions P1, P2, . . . , Pn,
even if P1, P2, . . . , Pn are not actually all true. Indeed this is the case
in our example. ‘All politicians are corrupt’ is not, in fact, true: there are some
honest politicians. But if it were true, and if Smith were a politician, then
‘Smith is corrupt’ would have to be true. Because of this, it is said to be a
logical consequence of those two propositions. The logical consequence relation
is often written using the symbol X, called the double turnstile. Thus to
indicate that C is a logical consequence of P1, P2, . . . , Pn, we would write:
P1, P2, . . . , Pn X C or: P X C where P stands for the set containing the
propositions p1, P2, . . . , Pn. The term ‘logical consequence’ is sometimes
reserved for cases in which C follows from P1, P2, . . . , Pn solely in virtue
of the meanings of the socalled logical expressions (e.g., ‘some’, ‘all’, ‘or’,
‘and’, ‘not’) contained by these propositions. In this more restricted sense,
‘Smith is not a politician’ is not a logical consequence of the proposition
‘All politicians are corrupt’ and ‘Smith is honest’, since to recognize the
consequence relation here we must also understand the specific meanings of the
non-logical expressions ‘corrupt’ and ‘honest’. See also DEDUCTION,
IMPLICATION, LOGICAL FORM, PROOF THEORY. J.Et. logical constant, a symbol, such
as the connectives -, 8, /, or S or the quantifiers D or E of elementary
quantification theory, that represents logical form. The contrast here is with
expressions such as terms, predicates, and function symbols, which are supposed
to represent the “content” of a sentence or proposition. Beyond this, there is
little consensus on how to understand logical constancy. It is sometimes said,
e.g., that a symbol is a logical constant if its interpretation is fixed across
admissible valuations, though there is disagreement over exactly how to
construe this “fixity” constraint. This account seems to make logical form a
mere artifact of one’s choice of a model theory. More generally, it has been
questioned whether there are any objective grounds for classifying some
expressions as logical and others not, or whether such a distinction is (wholly
or in part) conventional. Other philosophers have suggested that logical
constancy is less a semantic notion than an epistemic one: roughly, that a is a
logical constant if the semantic behavior of certain other expressions together
with the semantic contribution of a determine a priori (or in some other
epistemically privileged fashion) the extensions of complex expressions in
which a occurs. There is also considerable debate over whether particular
symbols, such as the identity sign, modal operators, and quantifiers other than
D and E, are, or should be treated as, logical constants. See also LOGICAL
FORM, MODEL THEORY. G.F.S. logical construction, something built by logical
operations from certain elements. Suppose that any sentence, S, containing
terms apparently referring to objects of type F can be paraphrased without any
essential loss of content into some (possibly much more complicated) sentence,
Sp, containing only terms referring to objects of type G (distinct from F): in
this case, objects of type F may be said to be logical constructions out of
objects of type G. The notion originates with Russell’s concept of an
“incomplete symbol,” which he introduced in connection with his thelogic,
second order logical construction 510 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 510
ory of descriptions. According to Russell, a definite description – i.e., a
descriptive phrase, such as ‘the present king of France’, apparently picking
out a unique object – cannot be taken at face value as a genuinely referential
term. One reason for this is that the existence of the objects seemingly
referred to by such phrases can be meaningfully denied. We can say, “The
present king of France does not exist,” and it is hard to see how this could be
if ‘the present king of France’, to be meaningful, has to refer to the present
king of France. One solution, advocated by Meinong, is to claim that the
referents required by what ordinary grammar suggests are singular terms must
have some kind of “being,” even though this need not amount to actual
existence; but this solution offended Russell’s “robust sense of reality.”
According to Russell, then, ‘The F is G’ is to be understood as equivalent to
(something like) ‘One and only one thing Fs and that thing is G’. (The phrase
‘one and only one’ can itself be paraphrased away in terms of quantifiers and
identity.) The crucial feature of this analysis is that it does not define the
problematic phrases by providing synonyms: rather, it provides a rule, which
Russell called “a definition in use,” for paraphrasing whole sentences in which
they occur into whole sentences in which they do not. This is why definite
descriptions are “incomplete symbols”: we do not specify objects that are their
meanings; we lay down a rule that explains the meaning of whole sentences in
which they occur. Thus definite descriptions disappear under analysis, and with
them the shadowy occupants of Meinong’s realm of being. Russell thought that
the kind of analysis represented by the theory of descriptions gives the clue
to the proper method for philosophy: solve metaphysical and epistemological
problems by reducing ontological commitments. The task of philosophy is to
substitute, wherever possible, logical constructions for inferred entities.
Thus in the philosophy of mathematics, Russell attempted to eliminate numbers,
as a distinct category of objects, by showing how mathematical statements can
be translated into (what he took to be) purely logical statements. But what
really gave Russell’s program its bite was his thought that we can refer only
to objects with which we are directly acquainted. This committed him to holding
that all terms apparently referring to objects that cannot be regarded as
objects of acquaintance should be given contextual definitions along the lines
of the theory of descriptions: i.e., to treating everything beyond the scope of
acquaintance as a logical construction (or a “logical fiction”). Most notably,
Russell regarded physical objects as logical constructions out of sense-data,
taking this to resolve the skeptical problem about our knowledge of the
external world. The project of showing how physical objects can be treated as
logical constructions out of sense-data was a major concern of analytical
philosophers in the interwar period, Carnap’s Der Logische Aufbau der Welt
(“The Logical Structure of the World,” 1928) standing as perhaps its major
monument. However, the project was not a success. Even Carnap’s construction
involves a system of space-time coordinates that is not analyzed in sense-datum
terms and today few, if any, philosophers believe that such ambitious projects
can be carried through. See also DEFINITION, REDUCTION, RUSSELL, SOCIAL
CONSTRUCTIVISM, THEORY OF DESCRIPTIONS. M.W. logical dependence. See
DEPENDENCE. logical empiricism. See LOGICAL POSITIVISM. logical fiction. See LOGICAL
CONSTRUCTION. logical form, the form obtained from a proposition, a set of
propositions, or an argument by abstracting from the subject matter of its
content terms or by regarding the content terms as mere placeholders or blanks
in a form. In a logically perfect language the logical form of a proposition, a
set of propositions, or an argument is determined by the grammatical form of
the sentence, the set of sentences, or the argument-text expressing it. Two
sentences, sets of sentences, or argument-texts are said to have the same
grammatical form, in this sense, if a uniform one-toone substitution of content
words transforms the one exactly into the other. The sentence ‘Abe properly
respects every agent who respects himself’ may be regarded as having the same
grammatical form as the sentence ‘Ben generously assists every patient who
assists himself’. Substitutions used to determine sameness of grammatical form
cannot involve change of form words such as ‘every’, ‘no’, ‘some’, ‘is’, etc.,
and they must be category-preserving, i.e., they must put a proper name for a
proper name, an adverb for an adverb, a transitive verb for a transitive verb,
and so on. Two sentences having the same grammatical form have exactly the same
form words distributed in exactly the same pattern; and although they of course
need not, and usually do not, have the same content words, they do have logical
dependence logical form 511 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 511 exactly the
same number of content words. The most distinctive feature of form words, which
are also called syncategorematic terms or logical terms, is their topic
neutrality; the form words in a sentence are entirely independent of and are in
no way indicative of its content or topic. Modern formal languages used in
formal axiomatizations of mathematical sciences are often taken as examples of
logically perfect languages. Pioneering work on logically perfect languages was
done by George Boole (1815–64), Frege, Giuseppe Peano (1858–1952), Russell, and
Church. According to the principle of logical form, an argument is (formally)
valid or invalid in virtue of logical form. More explicitly, every two
arguments in the same form are both valid or both invalid. Thus, every argument
in the same form as a valid argument is valid and every argument in the same
form as an invalid argument is invalid. The argument form that a given argument
fits (or has) is not determined solely by the logical forms of its constituent
propositions; the arrangement of those propositions is critical because the
process of interchanging a premise with the conclusion of a valid argument can
result in an invalid argument. The principle of logical form, from which formal
logic gets its name, is commonly used in establishing invalidity of arguments
and consistency of sets of propositions. In order to show that a given argument
is invalid it is sufficient to exhibit another argument as being in the same
logical form and as having all true premises and a false conclusion. In order
to show that a given set of propositions is consistent it is sufficient to
exhibit another set of propositions as being in the same logical form and as
being composed exclusively of true propositions. The history of these methods
traces back through non-Cantorian set theory, non-Euclidean geometry, and
medieval logicians (especially Anselm) to Aristotle. These methods must be used
with extreme caution in languages such as English that fail to be logically
perfect as a result of ellipsis, amphiboly, ambiguity, etc. For example, ‘This is
a male dog’ implies ‘This is a dog’ but ‘This is a brass monkey’ does not imply
‘This is a monkey’, as would be required in a logically perfect language.
Likewise, of two propositions commonly expressed by the ambiguous sentence ‘Ann
and Ben are married’ one does and one does not imply the proposition that Ann
is married to Ben. Quine and other logicians are careful to distinguish, in
effect, the (unique) logical form of a proposition from its (many) schematic
forms. The proposition (A) ‘If Abe is Ben, then if Ben is wise Abe is wise’ has
exactly one logical form, which it shares with (B) ‘If Carl is Dan, then if Dan
is kind Carl is kind’, whereas it has all of the following schematic forms: (1)
If P then if Q then R; (2) If P then Q; (3) P. The principle of form for
propositions is that every two propositions in the same logical form are both
tautological (logically necessary) or both non-tautological. Thus, although
propositions A and B are tautological there are non-tautological propositions
that fit the three schematic forms just mentioned. Failure to distinguish
logical form from schematic form has led to fallacies. According to the
principle of logical form quoted above every argument in the same logical form
as an invalid argument is invalid, but it is not the case that every argument
sharing a schematic form with an invalid argument is invalid. Contrary to what
would be fallaciously thought, the conclusion ‘Abe is Ben’ is logically implied
by the following two propositions taken together, ‘If Abe is Ben, then Ben is
Abe’ and ‘Ben is Abe’, even though the argument shares a schematic form with
invalid arguments “committing” the fallacy of affirming the consequent. See
also AMBIGUITY, FORMAL LOGIC, LAWS OF THOUGHT, LOGICAL SYNTAX, TAUTOLOGY.
J.Cor. logical form, principle of. See LOGICAL FORM. logical grammar. See
GRAMMAR. logical graph. See PEIRCE. logical immediacy. See IMMEDIACY. logical
implication. See IMPLICATION. logical independence. See INDEPENDENCE RESULTS.
logical indicator, also called indicator word, an expression that provides some
help in identifying the conclusion of an argument or the premises offered in
support of a conclusion. Common premise indicators include ‘for’, ‘because’,
and ‘since’. Common conclusion indicators include ‘so’, ‘it follows that’,
‘hence’, ‘thus’, and ‘therefore’. Since Tom sat in the back of the room, he
could not hear the performance clearly. Therefore, he could not write a proper
review. ’Since’ makes clear that Tom’s seat location is offered as a reason to
explain his inability to hear the performance. ‘Therefore’ indicates that the
logical form, principle of logical indicator 512 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM
Page 512 proposition that Tom could not write a proper review is the conclusion
of the argument. T.J.D. logically perfect language. See LOGICAL FORM, SCOPE.
logically proper name. See RUSSELL. logical mechanism. See COMPUTER THEORY.
logical necessity. See NECESSITY. logical notation, symbols designed to achieve
unambiguous formulation of principles and inferences in deductive logic. Such
notations involve some regimentation of words, word order, etc., of natural
language. Some schematization was attempted even in ancient times by Aristotle,
the Megarians, the Stoics, Boethius, and the medievals. But Leibniz’s vision of
a universal logical language began to be realized only in the past 150 years.
The notation is not yet standardized, but the following varieties of logical
operators in propositional and predicate calculus may be noted. Given that ‘p’,
‘q’, ‘r’, etc., are propositional variables, or propositions, we find, in the
contexts of their application, the following variety of operators (called
truth-functional connectives). Negation: ‘-p’, ‘Ýp’, ‘p - ’, ‘p’ ’.
Conjunction: ‘p • q’, ‘p & q’, ‘p 8 q’. Weak or inclusive disjunction: ‘p 7
q’. Strong or exclusive disjunction: ‘p V q’, ‘p ! q’, ‘p W q’. Material
conditional (sometimes called material implication): ‘p / q’, ‘p P q’. Material
biconditional (sometimes called material equivalence): ‘p S q’, ‘p Q q’. And,
given that ‘x’, ‘y’, ‘z’, etc., are individual variables and ‘F’, ‘G’, ‘H’,
etc., are predicate letters, we find in the predicate calculus two quantifiers,
a universal and an existential quantifier: Universal quantification: ‘(x)Fx’,
‘(Ex)Fx’, ‘8xFx’. Existential quantification: ‘(Ex)Fx’, ‘(Dx)Fx’, ‘7xFx’. The
formation principle in all the schemata involving dyadic or binary operators
(connectives) is that the logical operator is placed between the propositional
variables (or propositional constants) connected by it. But there exists a
notation, the so-called Polish notation, based on the formation rule
stipulating that all operators, and not only negation and quantifiers, be
placed in front of the schemata over which they are ranging. The following representations
are the result of application of that rule: Negation: ‘Np’. Conjunction: ‘Kpq’.
Weak or inclusive disjunction: ‘Apq’. Strong or exclusive disjunction: ‘Jpq’.
Conditional: ‘Cpq’. Biconditional: ‘Epq’. Sheffer stroke: ‘Dpq’. Universal
quantification: ‘PxFx’. Existential quantifications: ‘9xFx’. Remembering that
‘K’, ‘A’, ‘J’, ‘C’, ‘E’, and ‘D’ are dyadic functors, we expect them to be
followed by two propositional signs, each of which may itself be simple or
compound, but no parentheses are needed to prevent ambiguity. Moreover, this
notation makes it very perspicuous as to what kind of proposition a given
compound proposition is: all we need to do is to look at the leftmost operator.
To illustrate, ‘p7 (q & r) is a disjunction of ‘p’ with the conjunction
‘Kqr’, i.e., ‘ApKqr’, while ‘(p 7 q) & r’ is a conjunction of a disjunction
‘Apq’ with ‘r’, i.e., ‘KApqr’. ‘- p P q’ is written as ‘CNpq’, i.e., ‘if Np,
then q’, while negation of the whole conditional, ‘-(p P q)’, becomes ‘NCpq’. A
logical thesis such as ‘((p & q) P r) P ((s P p) P (s & q) P r))’ is
written concisely as ‘CCKpqrCCspCKsqr’. The general proposition ‘(Ex) (Fx P
Gx)’ is written as ‘PxCFxGx’, while a truth-function of quantified propositions
‘(Ex)Fx P (Dy)Gy’ is written as ‘CPxFx9yGy’. An equivalence such as ‘(Ex) Fx Q
- (Dx) - Fx’ becomes ‘EPxFxN9xNFx’, etc. Dot notation is way of using dots to
construct well-formed formulas that is more thrifty with punctuation marks than
the use of parentheses with their progressive strengths of scope. But dot
notation is less thrifty than the parenthesis-free Polish notation, which
secures well-formed expressions entirely on the basis of the order of logical
operators relative to truth-functional compounds. Various dot notations have
been devised. The convention most commonly adopted is that punctuation dots
always operate away from the connective symbol that they flank. It is best to
explain dot punctuation by examples: (1) ‘p 7 (q - r)’ becomes ‘p 7 .q P - r’;
(2) ‘(p 7 q) P - r’ becomes ‘p 7 q. P - r’; (3) ‘(p P (q Q r)) 7 (p 7 r)’
becomes ‘p P. q Q r: 7. p 7r’; (4) ‘(- pQq)•(rPs)’ becomes ‘-p Q q . r Q s’.
logically perfect language logical notation 513 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM
Page 513 Note that here the dot is used as conjunction dot and is not flanked
by punctuation dots, although in some contexts additional punctuation dots may
have to be added, e.g., ‘p.((q . r) P s), which is rewritten as ‘p : q.r. P s’.
The scope of a group of n dots extends to the group of n or more dots. (5) ‘- p
Q (q.(r P s))’ becomes ‘- p. Q : q.r P s’; (6)‘- pQ((q . r) Ps)’ becomes ‘~p.
Q: q.r.Ps’; (7) ‘(- p Q (q . r)) P s’ becomes ‘- p Q. q.r: P s’. The notation
for modal propositions made popular by C. I. Lewis consisted of the use of ‘B’
to express the idea of possibility, in terms of which other alethic modal
notions were defined. Thus, starting with ‘B p’ for ‘It is possiblethat p’ we
get ‘- B p’ for ‘It is not possible that p’ (i.e., ‘It is impossible that p’),
‘- B - p’ for ‘It is not possible that not p’ (i.e., ‘It is necessary that p’),
and ‘B - p’ for ‘It is possible that not p’ (i.e., ‘It is contingent that p’ in
the sense of ‘It is not necessary that p’, i.e., ‘It is possible that not p’).
Given this primitive or undefined notion of possibility, Lewis proceeded to
introduce the notion of strict implication, represented by ‘ ’ and defined as
follows: ‘p q .% . - B (p. -q)’. More recent tradition finds it convenient to
use ‘A’, either as a defined or as a primitive symbol of necessity. In the
parenthesis-free Polish notation the letter ‘M’ is usually added as the sign of
possibility and sometimes the letter ‘L’ is used as the sign of necessity. No
inconvenience results from adopting these letters, as long as they do not
coincide with any of the existing truthfunctional operators ‘N’, ‘K’, ‘A’, ‘J’,
‘C’, ‘E’, ‘D’. Thus we can express symbolically the sentences ‘If p is
necessary, then p is possible’ as ‘CNMNpMp’ or as ‘CLpMp’; ‘It is necessary
that whatever is F is G’ as ‘NMNPxCFxGx’ or as ‘LPxCFxGx’; and ‘Whatever is F
is necessarily G’ as ‘PxCFxNMNGx’ or as PxCFxLGx; etc. See also IMPLICATION,
MODAL LOGIC, WELL-FORMED FORMULA, Appendix of Special Symbols. I.Bo. logical
paradoxes. See SET-THEORETIC PARADOXES. logical positivism, also called
positivism, a philosophical movement inspired by empiricism and
verificationism; it began in the 1920s and flourished for about twenty or
thirty years. While there are still philosophers who would identify themselves
with some of the logical positivists’ theses, many of the central docrines of
the theory have come under considerable attack in the last half of this
century. In some ways logical positivism can be seen as a natural outgrowth of
radical or British empiricism and logical atomism. The driving force of
positivism may well have been adherence to the verifiability criterion for the
meaningfulness of cognitive statements. Acceptance of this principle led
positivists to reject as problematic many assertions of religion, morality, and
the kind of philosophy they described as metaphysics. The verifiability
criterion of meaning. The radical empiricists took genuine ideas to be composed
of simple ideas traceable to elements in experience. If this is true and if
thoughts about the empirical world are “made up” out of ideas, it would seem to
follow that all genuine thoughts about the world must have as constituents
thoughts that denote items of experience. While not all positivists tied
meaning so clearly to the sort of experiences the empiricists had in mind, they
were convinced that a genuine contingent assertion about the world must be
verifiable through experience or observation. Questions immediately arose
concerning the relevant sense of ‘verify’. Extreme versions of the theory
interpret verification in terms of experiences or observations that entail the
truth of the proposition in question. Thus for my assertion that there is a
table before me to be meaningful, it must be in principle possible for me to
accumulate evidence or justification that would guarantee the existence of the
table, which would make it impossible for the table not to exist. Even this
statement of the view is ambiguous, however, for the impossibility of error
could be interpreted as logical or conceptual, or something much weaker, say,
causal. Either way, extreme verificationism seems vulnerable to objections.
Universal statements, such as ‘All metal expands when heated’, are meaningful,
but it is doubtful that any observations could ever conclusively verify them.
One might modify the criterion to include as meaningful only statements that
can be either conclusively confirmed or conclusively disconfirmed. It is
doubtful, however, that even ordinary statements about the physical world
satisfy the extreme positivist insistence that they admit of conclusive verification
or falsification. If the evidence we have for believing what we do about the
physical world consists of knowledge of fleeting and subjective sensation, the
possibility of hallucination or deception by a malevolent, powerful being seems
to preclude the possibility of any finite sequence of sensations conclusively
establishing the existence or absence of a physical object. logical paradoxes
logical positivism 514 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 514 Faced with these
difficulties, at least some positivists retreated to a more modest form of
verificationism which insisted only that if a proposition is to be meaningful
it must be possible to find evidence or justification that bears on the
likelihood of the proposition’s being true. It is, of course, much more
difficult to find counterexamples to this weaker form of verificationism, but
by the same token it is more difficult to see how the principle will do the
work the positivists hoped it would do of weeding out allegedly problematic
assertions. Necessary truth. Another central tenet of logical positivism is
that all meaningful statements fall into two categories: necessary truths that
are analytic and knowable a priori, and contingent truths that are synthetic
and knowable only a posteriori. If a meaningful statement is not a contingent,
empirical statement verifiable through experience, then it is either a formal
tautology or is analytic, i.e., reducible to a formal tautology through
substitution of synonymous expressions. According to the positivist,
tautologies and analytic truths that do not describe the world are made true
(if true) or false (if false) by some fact about the rules of language. ‘P or
not-P’ is made true by rules we have for the use of the connectives ‘or’ and
‘not’ and for the assignments of the predicates ‘true’ and ‘false’. Again there
are notorious problems for logical positivism. It is difficult to reduce the
following apparently necessary truths to formal tautologies through the
substitution of synonymous expressions: (1) Everything that is blue (all over)
is not red (all over). (2) All equilateral triangles are equiangular triangles.
(3) No proposition is both true and false. Ironically, the positivists had a
great deal of trouble categorizing the very theses that defined their view,
such as the claims about meaningfulness and verifiability and the claims about
the analytic–synthetic distinction. Reductionism. Most of the logical
positivists were committed to a foundationalist epistemology according to which
all justified belief rests ultimately on beliefs that are non-inferentially
justified. These non-inferentially justified beliefs were sometimes described
as basic, and the truths known in such manner were often referred to as
self-evident, or as protocol statements. Partly because the positivists
disagreed as to how to understand the notion of a basic belief or a protocol
statement, and even disagreed as to what would be good examples, positivism was
by no means a monolithic movement. Still, the verifiability criterion of meaning,
together with certain beliefs about where the foundations of justification lie
and beliefs about what constitutes legitimate reasoning, drove many positivists
to embrace extreme forms of reductionism. Briefly, most of them implicitly
recognized only deduction and (reluctantly) induction as legitimate modes of
reasoning. Given such a view, difficult epistemological gaps arise between
available evidence and the commonsense conclusions we want to reach about the
world around us. The problem was particularly acute for empiricists who
recognized as genuine empirical foundations only propositions describing
perceptions or subjective sensations. Such philosophers faced an enormous
difficulty explaining how what we know about sensations could confirm for us assertions
about an objective physical world. Clearly we cannot deduce any truths about
the physical world from what we know about sensations (remember the possibility
of hallucination). Nor does it seem that we could inductively establish
sensation as evidence for the existence of the physical world when all we have
to rely on ultimately is our awareness of sensations. Faced with the
possibility that all of our commonplace assertions about the physical world
might fail the verifiability test for meaningfulness, many of the positivists
took the bold step of arguing that statements about the physical world could
really be viewed as reducible to (equivalent in meaning to) very complicated
statements about sensations. Phenomenalists, as these philosophers were called,
thought that asserting that a given table exists is equivalent in meaning to a
complex assertion about what sensations or sequences of sensations a subject
would have were he to have certain other sensations. The gap between sensation
and the physical world is just one of the epistemic gaps threatening the
meaningfulness of commonplace assertions about the world. If all we know about
the mental states of others is inferred from their physical behavior, we must
still explain how such inference is justified. Thus logical positivists who
took protocol statements to include ordinary assertions about the physical
world were comfortable reducing talk about the mental states of others to talk
about their behavior; this is logical behaviorism. Even some of those
positivists who thought empirical propositions had to be reduced ultimately to
talk about sensations were prepared to translate talk about the mental states
of others into talk about their behavior, which, ironically, would in turn get
translated right back into talk about sensation. logical positivism logical
positivism 515 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 515 Many of the positivists
were primarily concerned with the hypotheses of theoretical physics, which
seemed to go far beyond anything that could be observed. In the context of
philosophy of science, some positivists seemed to take as unproblematic
ordinary statements about the macrophysical world but were still determined
either to reduce theoretical statements in science to complex statements about
the observable world, or to view theoretical entities as a kind of convenient
fiction, description of which lacks any literal truth-value. The limits of a
positivist’s willingness to embrace reductionism are tested, however, when he
comes to grips with knowledge of the past. It seems that propositions
describing memory experiences (if such “experiences” really exist) do not
entail any truths about the past, nor does it seem possible to establish memory
inductively as a reliable indicator of the past. (How could one establish the
past correlations without relying on memory?) The truly hard-core reductionists
actually toyed with the possibility of reducing talk about the past to talk
about the present and future, but it is perhaps an understatement to suggest
that at this point the plausibility of the reductionist program was severely
strained. See also ANALYTIC–SYNTHETIC DISTINCTION, BEHAVIORISM, EMPIRICISM,
FOUNDATIONALISM, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, VERIFICATIONISM, VIENNA CIRCLE. R.A.F.
logical predicate. See LOGICAL SUBJECT. logical priority. See DEPENDENCE.
logical probability. See PROBABILITY. logical product, a conjunction of
propositions or predicates. The term ‘product’ derives from an analogy that
conjunction bears to arithmetic multiplication, and that appears very
explicitly in an algebraic logic such as a Boolean algebra. In the same way,
‘logical sum’ usually means the disjunction of propositions or predicates, and
the term ‘sum’ derives from an analogy that disjunction bears with arithmetic
addition. In the logical literature of the nineteenth century, e.g. in the
works of Peirce, ‘logical product’ and ‘logical sum’ often refer to the
relative product and relative sum, respectively. In the work of George Boole,
‘logical sum’ indicates an operation that corresponds not to disjunction but
rather to the exclusive ‘or’. The use of ‘logical sum’ in its contemporary
sense was introduced by John Venn and then adopted and promulgated by Peirce.
‘Relative product’ was introduced by Augustus De Morgan and also adopted and
promulgated by Peirce. R.W.B. logical reconstruction. See RATIONAL
RECONSTRUCTION. logical subject, in Aristotelian and traditional logic, the
common noun, or sometimes the intension or the extension of the common noun,
that follows the initial quantifier word (‘every’, ‘some’, ‘no’, etc.) of a
sentence, as opposed to the grammatical subject, which is the entire noun
phrase including the quantifier and the noun, and in some usages, any modifiers
that may apply. The grammatical subject of ‘Every number exceeding zero is
positive’ is ‘every number’, or in some usages, ‘every number exceeding zero’,
whereas the logical subject is ‘number’, or the intension or the extension of
‘number’. Similar distinctions are made between the logical predicate and the
grammatical predicate: in the above example, ‘is positive’ is the grammatical
predicate, whereas the logical predicate is the adjective ‘positive’, or
sometimes the property of being positive or even the extension of the word
‘positive’. In standard first-order logic the logical subject of a sentence
under a given interpretation is the entire universe of discourse of the
interpretation. See also GRAMMAR, LOGICAL FORM, SUBJECT, UNIVERSE OF DISCOURSE.
J.Cor. logical sum. See LOGICAL PRODUCT. logical syntax, description of the
forms of the expressions of a language in virtue of which the expressions stand
in logical relations to one another. Implicit in the idea of logical syntax is
the assumption that all – or at least most – logical relations hold in virtue
of form: e.g., that ‘If snow is white, then snow has color’ and ‘Snow is white’
jointly entail ‘Snow has color’ in virtue of their respective forms, ‘If P,
then Q’, ‘P’, and ‘Q’. The form assigned to an expression in logical syntax is
its logical form. Logical form may not be immediately apparent from the surface
form of an expression. Both (1) ‘Every individual is physical’ and (2) ‘Some
individual is physical’ apparently share the subjectpredicate form. But this
surface form is not the form in virtue of which these sentences (or the
propositions they might be said to express) stand in logical relations to other
sentences (or propositions), for if it were, (1) and (2) would have the same
logical relations to all sentences (or propological predicate logical syntax
516 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 516 sitions), but they do not; (1) and
(3) ‘Aristotle is an individual’ jointly entail (4) ‘Aristotle is physical’,
whereas (2) and (3) do not jointly entail (4). So (1) and (2) differ in logical
form. The contemporary logical syntax, devised largely by Frege, assigns very
different logical forms to (1) and (2), namely: ‘For every x, if x is an
individual, then x is physical’ and ‘For some x, x is an individual and x is
physical’, respectively. Another example: (5) ‘The satellite of the moon has
water’ seems to entail ‘There is at least one thing that orbits the moon’ and
‘There is no more than one thing that orbits the moon’. In view of this,
Russell assigned to (5) the logical form ‘For some x, x orbits the moon, and
for every y, if y orbits the moon, then y is identical with x, and for every y,
if y orbits the moon, then y has water’. See also GRAMMAR, LOGICAL FORM, THEORY
OF DESCRIPTIONS. T.Y. logical system. See FORMAL SEMANTICS, LOGISTIC SYSTEM.
logical table of judgments. See KANT. logical truth, linguistic theory of. See
CONVENTIONALISM. logicism, the thesis that mathematics, or at least some
significant portion thereof, is part of logic. Modifying Carnap’s suggestion
(in “The Logicist Foundation for Mathematics,” first published in Erkenntnis,
1931), this thesis is the conjunction of two theses: expressibility logicism:
mathematical propositions are (or are alternative expressions of) purely
logical propositions; and derivational logicism: the axioms and theorems of
mathematics can be derived from pure logic. Here is a motivating example from
the arithmetic of the natural numbers. Let the cardinality-quantifiers be those
expressible in the form ‘there are exactly . . . many xs such that’, which we
abbreviate ¢(. . . x),Ü with ‘. . .’ replaced by an Arabic numeral. These
quantifiers are expressible with the resources of first-order logic with
identity; e.g. ‘(2x)Px’ is equivalent to ‘DxDy(x&y & Ez[Pz S (z%x 7
z%y)])’, the latter involving no numerals or other specifically mathematical
vocabulary. Now 2 ! 3 % 5 is surely a mathematical truth. We might take it to
express the following: if we take two things and then another three things we
have five things, which is a validity of second-order logic involving no
mathematical vocabulary: EXEY ([(2x) Xx & (3x)Yx & ÝDx(Xx & Yx)] /
(5x) (Xx 7 Yx)). Furthermore, this is provable in any formalized fragment of
second-order logic that includes all of first-order logic with identity and
secondorder ‘E’-introduction. But what counts as logic? As a derivation? As a
derivation from pure logic? Such unclarities keep alive the issue of whether
some version or modification of logicism is true. The “classical” presentations
of logicism were Frege’s Grundgesetze der Arithmetik and Russell and
Whitehead’s Principia Mathematica. Frege took logic to be a formalized fragment
of secondorder logic supplemented by an operator forming singular terms from
“incomplete” expressions, such a term standing for an extension of the
“incomplete” expression standing for a concept of level 1 (i.e. type 1). Axiom
5 of Grundgesetze served as a comprehension-axiom implying the existence of
extensions for arbitrary Fregean concepts of level 1. In his famous letter of
1901 Russell showed that axiom to be inconsistent, thus derailing Frege’s
original program. Russell and Whitehead took logic to be a formalized fragment
of a ramified full finite-order (i.e. type w) logic, with higher-order
variables ranging over appropriate propositional functions. The Principia and
their other writings left the latter notion somewhat obscure. As a defense of
expressibility logicism, Principia had this peculiarity: it postulated typical
ambiguity where naive mathematics seemed unambiguous; e.g., each type had its
own system of natural numbers two types up. As a defense of derivational
logicism, Principia was flawed by virtue of its reliance on three axioms, a
version of the Axiom of Choice, and the axioms of Reducibility and Infinity,
whose truth was controversial. Reducibility could be avoided by eliminating the
ramification of the logic (as suggested by Ramsey). But even then, even the
arithmetic of the natural numbers required use of Infinity, which in effect
asserted that there are infinitely many individuals (i.e., entities of type 0).
Though Infinity was “purely logical,” i.e., contained only logical expressions,
in his Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy (p. 141) Russell admits that it
“cannot be asserted by logic to be true.” Russell then (pp. 194–95) forgets this:
“If there are still those who do not admit the identity of logic and
mathematics, we may challenge them to indicate at what point in the successive
definitions and deductions of Principia Mathematica they consider that logic
ends and mathematics begins. It will then be obvious that any answer is
arbitrary.” The answer, “Section 120, in which Infinity is first assumed!,” is
not arbitrary. In Principia Russell and Whitehead logical system logicism 517
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 517 say of Infinity that they “prefer to
keep it as a hypothesis” (Vol. 2, p. 203). Perhaps then they did not really
take logicism to assert the above identity, but rather a correspondence: to
each sentence f of mathematics there corresponds a conditional sentence of
logic whose antecedent is the Axiom of Infinity and whose consequent is a
purely logical reformulation of f. In spite of the problems with the
“classical” versions of logicism, if we count so-called higherorder (at least
second-order) logic as logic, and if we reformulate the thesis to read ‘Each
area of mathematics is, or is part of, a logic’, logicism remains alive and
well. See also FREGE, GÖDEL’S INCOMPLETENESS THEOREMS, PHILOSOPHY OF
MATHEMATICS, SET THEORY. H.T.H. logic of discovery. See ABDUCTION. logic of validation.
See ABDUCTION. logistic system, a formal language together with a set of axioms
and rules of inference, or what many today would call a “logic.” The original
idea behind the notion of a logistic system was that the language, axioms,
rules, and attendant concepts of proof and theorem were to be specified in a
mathematically precise fashion, thus enabling one to make the study of
deductive reasoning an exact science. One was to begin with an effective
specification of the primitive symbols of the language and of which (finite)
sequences of symbols were to count as sentences or wellformed formulas. Next,
certain sentences were to be singled out effectively as axioms. The rules of
inference were also to be given in such a manner that there would be an effective
procedure for telling which rules are rules of the system and what inferences
they license. A proof was then defined as any finite sequence of sentences,
each of which is either an axiom or follows from some earlier line(s) by one of
the rules, with a theorem being the last line of a proof. With the subsequent
development of logic, the requirement of effectiveness has sometimes been
dropped, as has the requirement that sentences and proofs be finite in length.
See also ALGORITHM, INFINITARY LOGIC, PROOF THEORY. G.F.S. logocentric. See
DECONSTRUCTION. logoi. See DECONSTRUCTION, LOGOS. logos(plural: logoi) (Greek,
‘word’, ‘speech’, ‘reason’), term with the following main philosophical senses.
(1) Rule, principle, law. E.g., in Stoicism the logos is the divine order and
in Neoplatonism the intelligible regulating forces displayed in the sensible
world. The term came thus to refer, in Christianity, to the Word of God, to the
instantiation of his agency in creation, and, in the New Testament, to the person
of Christ. (2) Proposition, account, explanation, thesis, argument. E.g.,
Aristotle presents a logos from first principles. (3) Reason, reasoning, the
rational faculty, abstract theory (as opposed to experience), discursive
reasoning (as opposed to intuition). E.g., Plato’s Republic uses the term to
refer to the intellectual part of the soul. (4) Measure, relation, proportion,
ratio. E.g., Aristotle speaks of the logoi of the musical scales. (5) Value,
worth. E.g., Heraclitus speaks of the man whose logos is greater than that of
others. R.C. Lombard, Peter. See PETER LOMBARD. Longinus (late first century
A.D.), Greek literary critic, author of a treatise On the Sublime (Peri
hypsous). The work is ascribed to “Dionysius or Longinus” in the manuscript and
is now tentatively dated to the end of the first century A.D. The author argues
for five sources of sublimity in literature: (a) grandeur of thought and (b)
deep emotion, both products of the writer’s “nature”; (c) figures of speech,
(d) nobility and originality in word use, and (e) rhythm and euphony in
diction, products of technical artistry. The passage on emotion is missing from
the text. The treatise, with Aristotelian but enthusiastic spirit, throws light
on the emotional effect of many great passages of Greek literature; noteworthy
are its comments on Homer (ch. 9). Its nostalgic plea for an almost romantic
independence and greatness of character and imagination in the poet and orator
in an age of dictatorial government and somnolent peace is unique and
memorable. See also AESTHETICS, ARISTOTLE. D.Ar. loop, closed. See CYBERNETICS.
loop, open. See CYBERNETICS. lottery paradox, a paradox involving two plausible
assumptions about justification which yield the conclusion that a fully
rational thinker may justifiably believe a pair of contradictory propositions.
The unattractiveness of this conclusion has led philosophers to deny one or the
other of the assumptions in question. The paradox, which is due to Henry
Kyburg, is generated as follows. Suppose I am contemplating a fair lotlogic of
discovery lottery paradox 518 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 518 tery
involving n tickets (for some suitably large n), and I justifiably believe that
exactly one ticket will win. Assume that if the probability of p, relative to
one’s evidence, meets some given high threshold less than 1, then one has
justification for believing that p (and not merely justification for believing
that p is highly probable). This is sometimes called a rule of detachment for
inductive hypotheses. Then supposing that the number n of tickets is large
enough, the rule implies that I have justification for believing (T1) that the
first ticket will lose (since the probability of T1 (% (n † 1)/n) will exceed
the given high threshold if n is large enough). By similar reasoning, I will
also have justification for believing (T2) that the second ticket will lose,
and similarly for each remaining ticket. Assume that if one has justification
for believing that p and justification for believing that q, then one has
justification for believing that p and q. This is a consequence of what is
sometimes called “deductive closure for justification,” according to which one
has justification for believing the deductive consequences of what one
justifiably believes. Closure, then, implies that I have justification for
believing that T1 and T2 and . . . Tn. But this conjunctive proposition is
equivalent to the proposition that no ticket will win, and we began with the
assumption that I have justification for believing that exactly one ticket will
win. See also CLOSURE, JUSTIFICATION. A.B. Lotze, Rudolf Hermann (1817–81),
German philosopher and influential representative of post-Hegelian German
metaphysics. Lotze was born in Bautzen and studied medicine, mathematics, physics,
and philosophy at Leipzig, where he became instructor, first in medicine and
later in philosophy. His early views, expressed in his Metaphysik (1841) and
Logik (1843), were influenced by C. H. Weisse, a former student of Hegel’s. He
succeeded J. F. Herbart as professor of philosophy at Göttingen, where he
served from 1844 until shortly before his death. Between 1856 and 1864, he
published, in three volumes, his best-known work, Mikrocosmus. Logik (1874) and
Metaphysik (1879) were published as the first two parts of his unfinished
three-volume System der Philosophie. While Lotze shared the metaphysical and
systematic appetites of his German idealist predecessors, he rejected their
intellectualism, favoring an emphasis on the primacy of feeling; believed that
metaphysics must fully respect the methods, results, and “mechanistic”
assumptions of the empirical sciences; and saw philosophy as the never
completed attempt to raise and resolve questions arising from the inevitable
pluralism of methods and interests involved in science, ethics, and the arts. A
strong personalism is manifested in his assertion that feeling discloses to us
a relation to a personal deity and its teleological workings in nature. His
most enduring influences can be traced, in America, through Royce, Santayana,
B. P. Bowne, and James, and, in England, through Bosanquet and Bradley. See
also IDEALISM, PERSONALISM. J.P.Su. love, ethics of. See DIVINE COMMAND ETHICS.
Löwenheim-Skolem theorem, the result that for any set of sentences of standard
predicate logic, if there is any interpretation in which they are all true,
there there is also an interpretation whose domain consists of natural numbers
and in which they are all true. Leopold Löwenheim proved in 1915 that for
finite sets of sentences of standard predicate logic, if there is any
interpretation in which they are true, there is also an interpretation that
makes them true and where the domain is a subset of the domain of the first
interpretation, and the new domain can be mapped one-to-one onto a set of
natural numbers. Löwenheim’s proof contained some gaps and made essential but
implicit use of the axiom of choice, a principle of set theory whose truth was,
and is, a matter of debate. In fact, the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem is equivalent
to the axiom of choice. Thoralf Skolem, in 1920, gave a more detailed proof
that made explicit the appeal to the axiom of choice and that extended the
scope of the theorem to include infinite sets of sentences. In 1922 he gave an
essentially different proof that did not depend on the axiom of choice and in
which the domain consisted of natural numbers rather than being of the same
size as a set of natural numbers. In most contemporary texts, Skolem’s result
is proved by methods later devised by Gödel, Herbrand, or Henkin for proving
other results. If the language does not include an identity predicate, then
Skolem’s result is that the second domain consists of the entire set of natural
numbers; if the language includes an identity predicate, then the second domain
may be a proper subset of the natural numbers. (See van Heijenoort, From Frege
to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic 1879–1931, 1967, for translations
of the original papers.) The original results were of interest because they
showed that in many cases unexpected interpretations with smaller infinite
domains Lotze, Rudolf Hermann Löwenheim-Skolem theorem 519 4065h-l.qxd
08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 519 than those of the initially given interpretation
could be constructed. It was later shown – and this is the Upward
Löwenheim-Skolem theorem – that interpretations with larger domains could also
be constructed that rendered true the same set of sentences. Hence the theorem
as stated initially is sometimes referred to as the Downward Löwenheim-Skolem
theorem. The theorem was surprising because it was believed that certain sets
of axioms characterized domains, such as the continuum of real numbers, that
were larger than the set of natural numbers. This surprise is called Skolem’s
paradox, but it is to be emphasized that this is a philosophical puzzle rather
than a formal contradiction. Two main lines of response to the paradox
developed early. The realist, who believes that the continuum exists
independently of our knowledge or description of it, takes the theorem to show
either that the full truth about the structure of the continuum is ineffable or
at least that means other than standard first-order predicate logic are
required. The constructivist, who believes that the continuum is in some sense
our creation, takes the theorem to show that size comparisons among infinite
sets is not an absolute matter, but relative to the particular descriptions
given. Both positions have received various more sophisticated formulations
that differ in details, but they remain the two main lines of development. See
also SET THEORY. R.E.G. lower functional calculus. See FORMAL LOGIC. Lucretius
(99 or 94–55 B.C.), Roman poet, author of On the Nature of Things (De rerum
natura), an epic poem in six books. Lucretius’s emphasis, as an orthodox
Epicurean, is on the role of even the most technical aspects of physics and
philosophy in helping to attain emotional peace and dismiss the terrors of
popular religion. Each book studies some aspect of the school’s theories, while
purporting to offer elementary instruction to its addressee, Memmius. Each
begins with an ornamental proem and ends with a passage of heightened emotional
impact; the argumentation is adorned with illustrations from personal
observation, frequently of the contemporary Roman and Italian scene. Book 1
demonstrates that nothing exists but an infinity of atoms moving in an infinity
of void. Opening with a proem on the love of Venus and Mars (an allegory of the
Roman peace), it ends with an image of Epicurus as conqueror, throwing the
javelin of war outside the finite universe of the geocentric astronomers. Book
2 proves the mortality of all finite worlds; Book 3, after proving the
mortality of the human soul, ends with a hymn on the theme that there is
nothing to feel or fear in death. The discussion of sensation and thought in
Book 4 leads to a diatribe against the torments of sexual desire. The shape and
contents of the visible world are discussed in Book 5, which ends with an
account of the origins of civilization. Book 6, about the forces that govern
meteorological, seismic, and related phenomena, ends with a frightening picture
of the plague of 429 B.C. at Athens. The unexpectedly gloomy end suggests the
poem is incomplete (also the absence of two great Epicurean themes, friendship
and the gods). See also EPICUREANISM. D.Ar. Lu Hsiang-shan (1139–93), Chinese
Neo-Confucian philosopher, an opponent of Chu Hsi’s metaphysics. For Lu the
mind is quite sufficient for realizing the Confucian vision of the unity and
harmony of man and nature (t’ien-jen ho-i). While Chu Hsi focused on “following
the path of study and inquiry,” Lu stressed “honoring the moral nature (of
humans).” Lu is a sort of metaphysical idealist, as evident in his statement,
“The affairs of the universe are my own affairs,” and in his attitude toward
the Confucian classics: “If in our study we know the fundamentals, then all the
Six Classics [the Book of Odes, Book of History, Book of Rites, Book of
Changes, the Chou-li, and the Spring and Autumn Annals] are my footnotes.” The
realization of Confucian vision is ultimately a matter of self-realization,
anticipating a key feature of Wang Yang-ming’s philosophy. See also
NEO-CONFUCIANISM. A.S.C. Luis de Molina. See MOLINA. Lukács, Georg (1885–1971),
Hungarian Marxist philosopher best known for his History and Class
Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics (1923). In 1918 he joined the
Hungarian Communist Party and for much of the remainder of his career had a
controversial relationship with it. For several months in 1919 he was People’s
Commissar for Education in Béla Kun’s government, until he fled to Vienna and
later moved to Berlin. In 1933 he fled Hitler and moved to Moscow, remaining
there until the end of World War II, when he returned to Budapest as a
university professor. In 1956 he was Minister of Culture in Imre Nagy’s
short-lived government. This led to lower functional calculus Lukacs, Georg 520
4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 520 a brief exile in Rumania. In his later
years he returned to teaching in Budapest and was much celebrated by the
Hungarian government. His Collected Works are forthcoming in both German and
Hungarian. He is equally celebrated for his literary criticism and his
reconstruction of the young Marx’s thought. For convenience his work is often
divided into three periods: the pre-Marxist, the Stalinist, and the
post-Stalinist. What unifies these periods and remains constant in his work are
the problems of dialectics and the concept of totality. He stressed the Marxist
claim of the possibility of a dialectical unity of subject and object. This was
to be obtained through the proletariat’s realization of itself and the
concomitant destruction of economic alienation in society, with the
understanding that truth was a still-to-be-realized totality. (In the
post–World War II period this theme was taken up by the Yugoslavian praxis
theorists.) The young neo-Kantian Lukács presented an aesthetics stressing the
subjectivity of human experience and the emptiness of social experience. This led
several French philosophers to claim that he was the first major existentialist
of the twentieth century; he strongly denied it. Later he asserted that realism
is the only correct way to understand literary criticism, arguing that since
humanity is at the core of any social discussion, form depends on content and
the content of politics is central to all historical social interpretations of
literature. Historically Lukács’s greatest claim to fame within Marxist circles
came from his realization that Marx’s materialist theory of history and the
resultant domination of the economic could be fully understood only if it
allowed for both necessity and species freedom. In History and Class
Consciousness he stressed Marx’s debt to Hegelian dialectics years before the
discovery of Marx’s Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844. Lukács
stresses his Hegelian Marxism as the correct orthodox version over and against
the established Engels-inspired Soviet version of a dialectics of nature. His
claim to be returning to Marx’s methodology emphasizes the primacy of the
concept of totality. It is through Marx’s use of the dialectic that capitalist
society can be seen as essentially reified and the proletariat viewed as the
true subject of history and the only possible salvation of humanity. All truth
is to be seen in relation to the proletariat’s historical mission. Marx’s
materialist conception of history itself must be examined in light of
proletarian knowledge. Truth is no longer given but must be understood in terms
of relative moments in the process of the unfolding of the real union of theory
and praxis: the totality of social relations. This union is not to be realized
as some statistical understanding, but rather grasped through proletarian
consciousness and directed party action in which subject and object are one.
(Karl Mannheim included a modified version of this theory of social-historical
relativism in his work on the sociology of knowledge.) In Europe and America
this led to Western Marxism. In Eastern Europe and the Soviet Union it led to
condemnation. If both the known and the knower are moments of the same thing,
then there is a two-directional dialectical relationship, and Marxism cannot be
understood from Engels’s one-way movement of the dialectic of nature. The
Communist attack on Lukács was so extreme that he felt it necessary to write an
apologetic essay on Lenin’s established views. In The Young Hegel: Studies in
the Relations between Dialectics and Economics (1938), Lukács modified his
views but still stressed the dialectical commonality of Hegel and Marx. In
Lukács’s last years he unsuccessfully tried to develop a comprehensive ethical
theory. The positive result was over two thousand pages of a preliminary study
on social ontology. See also MARXISM, PRAXIS. J.Bi. Lukasiewicz, Jan
(1878–1956), Polish philosopher and logician, the most renowned member of the
Warsaw School. The work for which he is best known is the discovery of
many-valued logics, but he also invented bracket-free Polish notation; obtained
original consistency, completeness, independence, and axiom-shortening results
for sentential calculi; rescued Stoic logic from the misinterpretation and
incomprehension of earlier historians and restored it to its rightful place as
the first formulation of the theory of deduction; and finally incorporated
Aristotle’s syllogisms, both assertoric and modal, into a deductive system in
his work Aristotle’s Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic.
Reflection on Aristotle’s discussion of future contingency in On Interpretation
led Lukasiewicz in 1918 to posit a third truth-value, possible, in addition to
true and false, and to construct a formal three-valued logic. Where in his
notation Cpq denotes ‘if p then q’, Np ‘not p’, Apq ‘either p or q’, and Kpq
‘both p and q’, the system is defined by the following matrices (½ is the third
truthvalue): Lukasiewicz, Jan Lukasiewicz, Jan 521 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40
AM Page 521 Apq is defined as CCpqq, and Kpq as NANpNq. The system was
axiomatized by Wajsberg in 1931. Lukasiewicz’s motivation in constructing a
formal system of three-valued logic was to break the grip of the idea of
universal determinism on the imagination of philosophers and scientists. For
him, there was causal determinism (shortly to be undermined by quantum theory),
but there was also logical determinism, which in accordance with the principle
of bivalence decreed that the statement that J.L. would be in Warsaw at noon on
December 21 next year was either true or false now, and indeed had been either
true or false for all time. In three-valued logic this statement would take the
value ½, thus avoiding any apparent threat to free will posed by the law of
bivalence. See also MANY-VALUED LOGIC, POLISH LOGIC. S.Mc. Lull, Raymond, also
spelled Raymond Lully, Ramon Llull (c.1232–1316), Catalan Christian mystic and
missionary. A polemicist against Islam, a social novelist, and a constructor of
schemes for international unification, Lull is best known in the history of
philosophy for his quasialgebraic or combinatorial treatment of metaphysical
principles. His logic of divine and creaturely attributes is set forth first in
an Ars compendiosa inveniendi veritatem (1274), next in an Ars demonstrativa
(1283–89), then in reworkings of both of these and in the Tree of Knowledge,
and finally in the Ars brevis and the Ars generalis ultima (1309–16). Each of
these contains tables and diagrams that permit the reader to calculate the
interactions of the various principles. Although his dates place him in the
period of mature Scholasticism, the vernacular language and the Islamic or
Judaic construction of Lull’s works relegate him to the margin of Scholastic
debates. His influence is to be sought rather in late medieval and Renaissance
cabalistic or hermetic traditions. See also CABALA, SCHOLASTICISM. M.D.J. lumen
naturale. See DESCARTES. Lun Yu. See CONFUCIUS. Lü-shih ch’un-ch’iu, a Chinese
anthology of late Warring States (403–221 B.C.) philosophical writings. It was
compiled by a patron, Lü Pu-wei, who became chancellor of the state of Ch’in in
about 240 B.C. As the earliest example of the encyclopedic genre, and often
associated with the later Huai Nan Tzu, it includes the full spectrum of
philosophical schools, and covers topics from competing positions on human
nature to contemporary farming procedures. An important feature of this work is
its development of correlative yin–yang and five-phases vocabulary for
organizing the natural and human processes of the world, positing relations
among the various seasons, celestial bodies, tastes, smells, materials, colors,
geographical directions, and so on. See also HUAI NAN TZU; WU-HSING; YIN, YANG.
R.P.P. & R.T.A. Luther, Martin (1483–1546), German religious reformer and
leader of the Protestant Reformation. He was an Augustinian friar and
unsystematic theologian from Saxony, schooled in nominalism (Ockham, Biel,
Staupitz) and trained in biblical languages. Luther initially taught philosophy
and subsequently Scripture (Romans, Galatians, Hebrews) at Wittenberg University.
His career as a church reformer began with his public denunciation, in the 95
theses, of the sale of indulgences in October 1517. Luther produced three
incendiary tracts: Appeal to the Nobility, The Babylonian Captivity of the
Church, and The Freedom of a Christian Man (1520), which prompted his
excommunication. At the 1521 Diet of Worms he claimed: “I am bound by the
Scripture I have quoted and my conscience is captive to the Word of God. I
cannot and will not retract anything since it is neither safe nor right to go
against my conscience. Here I stand, may God help me.” Despite his modernist
stance on the primacy of conscience over tradition, the reformer broke with
Erasmus over free will (De servo Arbitrio, 1525), championing an Augustinian, antihumanist
position. His crowning achievement, the translation of the Bible into German
(1534/45), shaped the modern German language. On the strength of a
biblical-Christocentric, anti-philosophical theology, he proclaimed
justification by faith alone and the priesthood of all believers. He unfolded a
theologia crucis, reformed the Mass, acknowledged only two sacraments (baptism
and the Eucharist), advocated consubstantiation instead of transubstantiation,
and propounded the Two Kingdoms theory in church–state relations. Lull, Raymond
Luther, Martin 522 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 522 See also
JUSTIFICATION BY FAITH, TRANSUBSTANTIATION. J.-L.S. Lyceum, (1) an extensive
ancient sanctuary of Apollo just east of Athens, the site of public athletic
facilities where Aristotle taught during the last decade of his life; (2) a
center for philosophy and systematic research in science and history organized
there by Aristotle and his associates; it began as an informal group and lacked
any legal status until Theophrastus, Aristotle’s colleague and principal heir,
acquired land and buildings there c.315 B.C. By a principle of metonymy common
in philosophy (cf. ‘Academy’, ‘Oxford’, ‘Vienna’), the name ‘Lyceum’ came to
refer collectively to members of the school and their methods and ideas,
although the school remained relatively non-doctrinaire. Another ancient label
for adherents of the school and their ideas, apparently derived from
Aristotle’s habit of lecturing in a portico (peripatos) at the Lyceum, is
‘Peripatetic’. The school had its heyday in its first decades, when members
included Eudemus, author of lost histories of mathematics; Aristoxenus, a
prolific writer, principally on music (large parts of two treatises survive);
Dicaearchus, a polymath who ranged from ethics and politics to psychology and
geography; Meno, who compiled a history of medicine; and Demetrius of Phaleron,
a dashing intellect who wrote extensively and ruled Athens on behalf of foreign
dynasts from 317 to 307. Under Theophrastus and his successor Strato, the
school produced original work, especially in natural science. But by the
midthird century B.C., the Lyceum had lost its initial vigor. To judge from
meager evidence, it offered sound education but few new ideas; some members
enjoyed political influence, but for nearly two centuries, rigorous theorizing
was displaced by intellectual history and popular moralizing. In the first
century B.C., the school enjoyed a modest renaissance when Andronicus oversaw
the first methodical edition of Aristotle’s works and began the exegetical
tradition that culminated in the monumental commentaries of Alexander of
Aphrodisias (fl. A.D. 200). See also ACADEMY, ANDRONICUS OF RHODES, ARISTOTLE,
COMMENTARIES ON ARISTOTLE, STRATO OF LAMPSACUS. S.A.W. Lyotard, Jean-François
(1924–98), French philosopher, a leading representative of the movement known
in the English-speaking world as post-structuralism. Among major
post-structuralist theorists (Gilles Deleuze [1925–97], Derrida, Foucault),
Lyotard is most closely associated with postmodernism. With roots in
phenomenology (a student of Merleau-Ponty, his first book, Phenomenology
[1954], engages phenomenology’s history and engages phenomenology with history)
and Marxism (in the 1960s Lyotard was associated with the Marxist group
Socialisme ou Barbarie, founded by Cornelius Castoriadis [1922–97] and Claude
Lefort [b.1924]), Lyotard’s work has centered on questions of art, language,
and politics. His first major work, Discours, figure (1971), expressed
dissatisfaction with structuralism and, more generally, any theoretical
approach that sought to escape history through appeal to a timeless, universal
structure of language divorced from our experiences. Libidinal Economy (1974)
reflects the passion and enthusiasm of the events of May 1968 along with a
disappointment with the Marxist response to those events. The Postmodern
Condition: A Report on Knowledge (1979), an occasional text written at the
request of the Quebec government, catapulted Lyotard to the forefront of critical
debate. Here he introduced his definition of the postmodern as “incredulity
toward metanarratives”: the postmodern names not a specific epoch but an
antifoundationalist attitude that exceeds the legitimating orthodoxy of the
moment. Postmodernity, then, resides constantly at the heart of the modern,
challenging those totalizing and comprehensive master narratives (e.g., the
Enlightenment narrative of the emancipation of the rational subject) that serve
to legitimate its practices. Lyotard suggests we replace these narratives by
less ambitious, “little narratives” that refrain from totalizing claims in
favor of recognizing the specificity and singularity of events. Many, including
Lyotard, regard The Differend (1983) as his most original and important work.
Drawing on Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations and Kant’s Critique of
Judgment, it reflects on how to make judgments (political as well as aesthetic)
where there is no rule of judgment to which one can appeal. This is the
différend, a dispute between (at least) two parties in which the parties
operate within radically heterogeneous language games so incommensurate that no
consensus can be reached on principles or rules that could govern how their
dispute might be settled. In contrast to litigations, where disputing parties
share a language with rules of judgment to consult to resolve their dispute,
différends defy resolution (an example might be the conflicting Lyceum Lyotard,
Jean-François 523 4065h-l.qxd 08/02/1999 7:40 AM Page 523 claims to land rights
by aboriginal peoples and current residents). At best, we can express
différends by posing the dispute in a way that avoids delegitimating either
party’s claim. In other words, our political task, if we are to be just, is to
phrase the dispute in a way that respects the difference between the competing
claims. In the years following The Differend, Lyotard published several works
on aesthetics, politics, and postmodernism; the most important may well be his
reading of Kant’s third Critique in Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime
(1991). See also DERRIDA, FOUCAULT, POSTMODERN, STRUCTURALISM. A.D.S
McCosh, James (1811–94),
Scottish philosopher, a common sense realist who attempted to reconcile
Christianity with evolution. A prolific writer, McCosh was a pastor in Scotland
and a professor at Queen’s College, Belfast, before becoming president of the
College of New Jersey (now Princeton University). In The Intuitions of the Mind
(1860) he argued that while acts of intelligence begin with immediate knowledge
of the self or of external objects, they also exhibit intuitions in the
spontaneous formation of self-evident convictions about objects. In opposition
to Kant and Hamilton, McCosh treated intuitions not as forms imposed by minds
on objects, but as inductively ascertainable rules that minds follow in forming
convictions after perceiving objects. In his Examination of Mr. J. S. Mill’s
Philosophy (1866) McCosh criticized Mill for denying the existence of
intuitions while assuming their operation. In The Religious Aspects of
Evolution (1885) McCosh defended the design argument by equating Darwin’s
chance variations with supernatural design. J.W.A. McDougall, William
(1871–1938), British and American (after 1920) psychologist. He was probably
the first to define psychology as the science of behavior (Physiological
Psychology, 1905; Psychology: The Science of Behavior, 1912) and he invented
hormic (purposive) psychology. By the early twentieth century, as psychology
strove to become scientific, purpose had become a suspect concept, but
following Stout, McDougall argued that organisms possess an “intrinsic power of
self-determination,” making goal seeking the essential and defining feature of
behavior. In opposition to mechanistic and intellectualistic psychologies,
McDougall, again following Stout, proposed that innate instincts (later,
propensities) directly or indirectly motivate all behavior (Introduction to
Social Psychology, 1908). Unlike more familiar psychoanalytic instincts,
however, many of McDougall’s instincts were social in nature (e.g.
gregariousness, deference). Moreover, McDougall never regarded a person as
merely an assemblage of unconnected and quarreling motives, since people are
“integrated unities” guided by one supreme motive around which others are
organized. McDougall’s stress on behavior’s inherent purposiveness influenced
the behaviorist E. C. Tolman, but was otherwise roundly rejected by more
mechanistic behaviorists and empiricistically inclined sociologists. In his
later years, McDougall moved farther from mainstream thought by championing
Lamarckism and sponsoring research in parapsychology. Active in social causes,
McDougall was an advocate of eugenics (Is America Safe for Democracy?, 1921).
T.H.L. Mach, Ernst(1838–1916), Austrian physicist and influential philosopher
of science. He was born in Turas, Moravia, now part of the Czech Republic, and
studied physics at the University of Vienna. Appointed professor of mathematics
at Graz in 1864, he moved in 1867 to the chair of physics at Prague, where he
came to be recognized as one of the leading scientists in Europe, contributing
not only to a variety of fields of physics (optics, electricity, mechanics,
acoustics) but also to the new field of psychophysics, particularly in the field
of perception. He returned to Vienna in 1895 to a chair in philosophy,
designated for a new academic discipline, the history and theory of inductive
science. His writings on the philosophy of science profoundly affected the
founders of the Vienna Circle, leading Mach to be regarded as a progenitor of
logical positivism. His best-known work, The Science of Mechanics (1883),
epitomized the main themes of his philosophy. He set out to extract the logical
structure of mechanics from an examination of its history and procedures.
Mechanics fulfills the human need to abridge the facts about motion in the most
economical way. It rests on “sensations” (akin to the “ideas” or “sense
impressions” of classical empiricism); indeed, the world may be said to consist
of sensations (a thesis that later led Lenin in a famous polemic to accuse Mach
of idealism). Mechanics is inductive, not demonstrative; it has no a priori
element of any sort. The divisions between the sciences must be recognized to
be arbitrary, a matter of convenience only. The sciences must be regarded as
descriptive, not as explanatory. Theories may appear to explain, but the
underlying entities they postulate, like atoms, for example, are no more than
aids to prediction. To suppose them to represent 525 M 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999
7:41 AM Page 525 reality would be metaphysical and therefore idle. Mach’s most
enduring legacy to philosophy is his enduring suspicion of anything
“metaphysical.” See also LOGICAL POSITIVISM, VIENNA CIRCLE. E.M. Machiavelli,
Niccolò (1469–1527), the Italian political theorist commonly considered the
most influential political thinker of the Renaissance. Born in Florence, he was
educated in the civic humanist tradition. From 1498 to 1512, he was secretary
to the second chancery of the republic of Florence, with responsibilities for
foreign affairs and the revival of the domestic civic militia. His duties
involved numerous diplomatic missions both in and outside Italy. With the fall
of the republic in 1512, he was dismissed by the returning Medici regime. From
1513 to 1527 he lived in enforced retirement, relieved by writing and
occasional appointment to minor posts. Machaivelli’s writings fall into two
genetically connected categories: chancery writings (reports, memoranda,
diplomatic writings) and formal books, the chief among them The Prince (1513),
the Discourses (1517), the Art of War (1520), Florentine Histories (1525), and
the comic drama Mandragola (1518). With Machiavelli a new vision emerges of
politics as autonomous activity leading to the creation of free and powerful
states. This vision derives its norms from what humans do rather than from what
they ought to do. As a result, the problem of evil arises as a central issue:
the political actor reserves the right “to enter into evil when necessitated.”
The requirement of classical, medieval, and civic humanist political
philosophies that politics must be practiced within the bounds of virtue is met
by redefining the meaning of virtue itself. Machiavellian virtù is the ability to
achieve “effective truth” regardless of moral, philosophical, and theological
restraints. He recognizes two limits on virtù: (1) fortuna, understood as
either chance or as a goddess symbolizing the alleged causal powers of the
heavenly bodies; and (2) the agent’s own temperament, bodily humors, and the
quality of the times. Thus, a premodern astrological cosmology and the
anthropology and cyclical theory of history derived from it underlie his
political philosophy. History is seen as the conjoint product of human activity
and the alleged activity of the heavens, understood as the “general cause” of
all human motions in the sublunar world. There is no room here for the
sovereignty of the Good, nor the ruling Mind, nor Providence. Kingdoms,
republics, and religions follow a naturalistic pattern of birth, growth, and
decline. But, depending on the outcome of the struggle between virtù and
fortuna, there is the possibility of political renewal; and Machiavelli saw
himself as the philosopher of political renewal. Historically, Machiavelli’s
philosophy came to be identified with Machiavellianism (also spelled
Machiavellism), the doctrine that the reason of state recognizes no moral
superior and that, in its pursuit, everything is permitted. Although
Machiavelli himself does not use the phrase ‘reason of state’, his principles
have been and continue to be invoked in its defense. See also POLITICAL
PHILOSOPHY, SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY. A.J.P. Machiavellianism. See MACHIAVELLI.
machine state. See PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. machine state functionalism. See
PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. Mach’s principle. See PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. MacIntyre,
Alasdair (b.1929), British-American philosopher and eminent contemporary
representative of Aristotelian ethics. He was born in Scotland, educated in
England, and has taught at universities in both England and (mainly) the United
States. His early work included perceptive critical discussions of Marx and
Freud as well as his influential A Short History of Ethics. His most discussed
work, however, has been After Virtue (1981), an analysis and critique of modern
ethical views from the standpoint of an Aristotelian virtue ethics. MacIntyre
begins with the striking unresolvability of modern ethical disagreements, which
he diagnoses as due to a lack of any shared substantive conception of the
ethical good. This lack is itself due to the modern denial of a human nature
that would provide a meaning and goal for human life. In the wake of the
Enlightenment, MacIntyre maintains, human beings are regarded as merely atomistic
individuals, employing a purely formal reason to seek fulfillment of their
contingent desires. Modern moral theory tries to derive moral values from this
conception of human reality. Utilitarians start from desires, arguing that they
must be fulfilled in such a way as to provide the greatest happiness (utility).
Kantians start from reason, arguing that our commitment to rationality requires
recognizing the rights of others to the same goods that we desire for
ourselves. MacIntyre, however, mainMachiavelli, Niccolò MacIntyre, Alasdair 526
4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:41 AM Page 526 tains that the modern notions of
utility and of rights are fictions: there is no way to argue from individual
desires to an interest in making others happy or to inviolable rights of all
persons. He concludes that Enlightenment liberalism cannot construct a coherent
ethics and that therefore our only alternatives are to accept a Nietzschean
reduction of morality to will-to-power or to return to an Aristotelian ethics
grounded in a substantive conception of human nature. MacIntyre’s positive
philosophical project is to formulate and defend an Aristotelian ethics of the
virtues (based particularly on the thought of Aquinas), where virtues are
understood as the moral qualities needed to fulfill the potential of human
nature. His aim is not the mere revival of Aristotelian thought but a
reformulation and, in some cases, revision of that thought in light of its
history over the last 2,500 years. MacIntyre pays particular attention to formulating
concepts of practice (communal action directed toward a intrinsic good), virtue
(a habit needed to engage successfully in a practice), and tradition (a
historically extended community in which practices relevant to the fulfillment
of human nature can be carried out). His conception of tradition is
particularly noteworthy. His an effort to provide Aristotelianism with a
historical orientation that Aristotle himself never countenanced; and, in
contrast to Burke, it makes tradition the locus of rational reflection on and
revision of past practices, rather than a merely emotional attachment to them.
MacIntyre has also devoted considerable attention to the problem of rationally
adjudicating the claims of rival traditions (especially in Whose Justice? Which
Rationality?, 1988) and to making the case for the Aristotelian tradition as
opposed to that of the Enlightenment and that of Nietzscheanism (especially in
Three Rival Versions of Moral Inquiry, 1990). See also AQUINAS, ARISTOTLE,
ETHICS, KANT, LIBERALISM, VIRTUE ETHICS. G.G. McTaggart, John McTaggart Ellis
(1866–1925), English philosopher, the leading British personal idealist. Aside
from his childhood and two extended visits to New Zealand, McTaggart lived in
Cambridge as a student and fellow of Trinity College. His influence on others
at Trinity, including Russell and Moore, was at times great, but he had no
permanent disciples. He began formulating and defending his views by critically
examining Hegel. In Studies in the Hegelian Dialectic (1896) he argued that
Hegel’s dialectic is valid but subjective, since the Absolute Idea Hegel used
it to derive contains nothing corresponding to the dialectic. In Studies in
Hegelian Cosmology (1901) he applied the dialectic to such topics as sin,
punishment, God, and immortality. In his Commentary on Hegel’s Logic (1910) he
concluded that the task of philosophy is to rethink the nature of reality using
a method resembling Hegel’s dialectic. McTaggart attempted to do this in his
major work, The Nature of Existence (two volumes, 1921 and 1927). In the first
volume he tried to deduce the nature of reality from self-evident truths using
only two empirical premises, that something exists and that it has parts. He
argued that substances exist, that they are related to each other, that they
have an infinite number of substances as parts, and that each substance has a
sufficient description, one that applies only to it and not to any other
substance. He then claimed that these conclusions are inconsistent unless the
sufficient descriptions of substances entail the descriptions of their parts, a
situation that requires substances to stand to their parts in the relation he
called determining correspondence. In the second volume he applied these
results to the empirical world, arguing that matter is unreal, since its parts
cannot be determined by determining correspondence. In the most celebrated part
of his philosophy, he argued that time is unreal by claiming that time
presupposes a series of positions, each having the incompatible qualities of
past, present, and future. He thought that attempts to remove the
incompatibility generate a vicious infinite regress. From these and other
considerations he concluded that selves are real, since their parts can be
determined by determining correspondence, and that reality is a community of
eternal, perceiving selves. He denied that there is an inclusive self or God in
this community, but he affirmed that love between the selves unites the
community producing a satisfaction beyond human understanding. See also HEGEL,
IDEALISM. J.W.A. Madhva (1238–1317), Indian philosopher who founded Dvaita
Vedanta. His major works are the Brahma-Sutra-Bhafya (his commentary,
competitive with Shankara’s and Ramanuja’s, on the Brahma-Sutras of
Badarayana); the Gita-Bhafya and Gitatatparya (commentaries on the Bhagavad
Gita); the Anu-Vyakhyana (an extension of the Brahma-Sutra-Bhafya including a
general critique of Advaita Vedanta); the Pramapa Laksana, an account of his
epistemology; and the TattvaSajkhyana, a presentation of his ontology. He
McTaggart, John McTaggart Ellis Madhva 527 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:41 AM Page
527 distinguishes between an independent Brahman and a dependent world of
persons and bodies and holds that each person has a distinct individual
essence. See also ADVAITA, VEDANTA. K.E.Y. Madhyamika (Sanskrit, ‘middle way’),
a variety of Mahayana Buddhism that is a middle way in the sense that it
neither claims that nothing at all exists nor does it embrace the view that
there is a plurality of distinct things. It embraces the position in the debate
about the nature of things that holds that all things are “empty.” Madhyamika
offers an account of why the Buddha rejected the question of whether the
enlightened one survives death, saying that none of the four answers
(affirmative, negative, affirmative and negative, neither affirmative nor
negative) applies. The typically Buddhist doctrine of codependent arising
asserts that everything that exists depends for its existence on something
else; nothing (nirvana aside) at any time does or can exist on its own. From
this doctrine, together with the view that if A cannot exist independent of B,
A cannot be an individual distinct from B, Madhyamika concludes that in
offering causal descriptions (or spatial or temporal descriptions) we assume
that we can distinguish between individual items. If everything exists
dependently, and nothing that exists dependently is an individual, there are no
individuals. Thus we cannot distinguish between individual items. Hence the
assumption on which we offer causal (or spatial or temporal) descriptions is
false, and thus those descriptions are radically defective. Madhyamika then
adds the doctrine of an ineffable ultimate reality hidden behind our ordinary
experience and descriptions and accessible only in esoteric enlightenment
experience. The Buddha rejected all four answers because the question is raised
in a context that assumes individuation among items of ordinary experience, and
since that assumption is false, all of the answers are misleading; each answer
assumes a distinction between the enlightened one and other things. The
Madhyamika seems, then, to hold that to be real is to exist independently; the
apparent objects of ordinary experience are sunya (empty, void); they lack any
essence or character of their own. As such, they are only apparently knowable,
and the real is seamless. Critics (e.g., Yogacara Mahayana Buddhist
philosophers) deny that this view is coherent, or even that there is any view
here at all. In one sense, the Madhyamika philosopher Nagarjuna himself denies
that there is any position taken, maintaining that his critical arguments are
simply reductions to absurdity of views that his opponents hold and that he has
no view of his own. Still, it seems clear in Nagarjuna’s writings, and plain in
the tradition that follows him, that there is supposed to be something the
realization of which is essential to becoming enlightened, and the Madhyamika
philosopher must walk the (perhaps non-existent) line between saying two
things: first, that final truth concerns an ineffable reality and that this
itself is not a view, and second, that this represents what the Buddha taught
and hence is something different both from other Buddhist perspectives that
offer a mistaken account of the Buddha’s message and from nonBuddhist
alternatives. See also BUDDHISM, NAGARJUNA. K.E.Y. magnitude, extent or size of
a thing with respect to some attribute; technically, a quantity or dimension. A
quantity is an attribute that admits of several or an infinite number of
degrees, in contrast to a quality (e.g., triangularity), which an object either
has or does not have. Measurement is assignment of numbers to objects in such a
way that these numbers correspond to the degree or amount of some quantity
possessed by their objects. The theory of measurement investigates the
conditions for, and uniqueness of, such numerical assignments. Let D be a
domain of objects (e.g., a set of physical bodies) and L be a relation on this
domain; i.e., Lab may mean that if a and b are put on opposite pans of a
balance, the pan with a does not rest lower than the other pan. Let ; be the
operation of weighing two objects together in the same pan of a balance. We
then have an empirical relational system E % ‹ D, L, ; (. One can prove that,
if E satisfies specified conditions, then there exists a measurement function
mapping D to a set Num of real numbers, in such a way that the L and ;
relations between objects in D correspond to the m and ! relations between their
numerical values. Such an existence theorem for a measurement function from an
empirical relational system E to a numerical relational system, N % ‹ Num, m !
(, is called a representation theorem. Measurement functions are not unique,
but a uniqueness theorem characterizes all such functions for a specified kind
of empirical relational system and specified type of numerical image. For
example, suppose that for any measurement functions f, g for E there exists
real number a ( 0 such that for any x in D, f(x) % ag(x). Then it is said that
the measurement is on a ratio scale, Madhyamika magnitude 528 4065m-r.qxd
08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 528 and the function s(x) % ax, for x in the real
numbers, is the scale transformation. For some empirical systems, one can prove
that any two measurement functions are related by f % ag ! b, where a ( 0 and b
are real numbers. Then the measurement is on an interval scale, with the scale
transformation s(x) % ax ! b; e.g., measurement of temperature without an
absolute zero is on an interval scale. In addition to ratio and interval
scales, other scale types are defined in terms of various scale
transformations; many relational systems have been mathematically analyzed for
possible applications in the behavioral sciences. Measurement with weak scale
types may provide only an ordering of the objects, so quantitative measurement
and comparative orderings can be treated by the same general methods. The older
literature on measurement often distinguishes extensive from intensive magnitudes.
In the former case, there is supposed to be an empirical operation (like ;
above) that in some sense directly corresponds to addition on numbers. An
intensive magnitude supposedly has no such empirical operation. It is sometimes
claimed that genuine quantities must be extensive, whereas an intensive
magnitude is a quality. This extensive versus intensive distinction (and its
use in distinguishing quantities from qualities) is imprecise and has been
supplanted by the theory of scale types sketched above. See also
OPERATIONALISM, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. R.L.C. Mahabharata. See BHAGAVAD GITA.
Mahavira, title (‘Great Hero’) of Vardhamana Jnatrputra (sixth century B.C.),
Indian religious leader who founded Jainism. He is viewed within Jainism as the
twenty-fourth and most recent of a series of Tirthankaras or religious
“ford-makers” and conquerors (over ignorance) and as the establisher of the
Jain community. His enlightenment is described in the Jaina Sutras as involving
release of his inherently immortal soul from reincarnation and karma and as
including his omniscience. According to Jaina tradition, Vardhamana Jnatrputra
was born into a warrior class and at age thirty became a wandering ascetic
seeking enlightenment, which he achieved at age forty-two. See also JAINISM.
K.E.Y. Mahayana Buddhism. See BUDDHISM. maieutic. See SOCRATES. Maimon, Salomon
(1753–1800), Lithuanianborn German Jewish philosopher who became the friend and
protégé of Moses Mendelssohn and was an acute early critic and follower of
Kant. His most important works were the Versuch über die
Transzendentalphilosophie. Mit einem Anhang über die symbolische Erkenntnis
(“Essay on Transcendental Philosophy. With an Appendix on Symbolic Cognition,”
1790), the Philosophisches Wörterbuch (“Philosophical Dictionary,” 1791) and
the Versuch einer neuen Logik oder Theorie des Denkens (“Attempt at a New Logic
or Theory of Thought,” 1794). Maimon argued against the “thing-in-itself” as it
was conceived by Karl Leonhard Reinhold and Gottlieb Ernst Schulze. For Maimon,
the thing-in-itself was merely a limiting concept, not a real object “behind”
the phenomena. While he thought that Kant’s system was sufficient as a
refutation of rationalism or “dogmatism,” he did not think that it had – or
could – successfully dispose of skepticism. Indeed, he advanced what can be
called a skeptical interpretation of Kant. On the other hand, he also argued
against Kant’s sharp distinction between sensibility and understanding and for
the necessity of assuming the idea of an “infinite mind.” In this way, he
prepared the way for Fichte and Hegel. However, in many ways his own theory is
more similar to that of the neoKantian Hermann Cohen. See also JEWISH
PHILOSOPHY, NEO-KANTIANISM. M.K. Maimonides, Latinized name of Moses ben Maimon
(1135–1204), Spanish-born Jewish philosopher, physician, and jurist. Born in
Córdova, Maimonides and his family fled the forced conversions of the Almohad
invasion in 1148, living anonymously in Fez before finding refuge in 1165 in
Cairo. There Maimonides served as physician to the vizier of Saladin, who
overthrew the Fatimid dynasty in 1171. He wrote ten medical treatises, but
three works secured his position among the greatest rabbinic jurists: his Book
of the Commandments, cataloguing the 613 biblical laws; his Commentary on the
Mishnah, expounding the rational purposes of the ancient rabbinic code; and the
fourteen-volume Mishneh Torah, a codification of Talmudic law that retains
almost canonical authority. His Arabic philosophic masterpiece The Guide to the
Perplexed mediates between the Scriptural and philosophic idioms, deriving a
sophisticated negative theology by subtly decoding biblical anthropomorphisms.
It defends divine creation against al-Farabi’s and Avicenna’s eternalism, while
rejecting efforts to demonstrate creation Mahabharata Maimonides 529
4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 529 apodictically. The radical
occasionalism of Arabic dialectical theology (kalam) that results from such
attempts, Maimonides argues, renders nature unintelligible and divine
governance irrational: if God creates each particular event, natural causes are
otiose, and much of creation is in vain. But Aristotle, who taught us the very
principles of demonstration, well understood, as his resort to persuasive
language reveals, that his arguments for eternity were not demonstrative. They
project, metaphysically, an analysis of time, matter, and potentiality as they
are now and ignore the possibility that at its origin a thing had a very
different nature. We could allegorize biblical creation if it were demonstrated
to be false. But since it is not, we argue that creation is more plausible
conceptually and preferable theologically to its alternative: more plausible,
because a free creative act allows differentiation of the world’s multiplicity
from divine simplicity, as the seemingly mechanical necessitation of emanation,
strictly construed, cannot do; preferable, because Avicennan claims that God is
author of the world and determiner of its contingency are undercut by the assertion
that at no time was nature other than it is now. Maimonides read the biblical
commandments thematically, as serving to inform human character and
understanding. He followed al-Farabi’s Platonizing reading of Scripture as a
symbolic elaboration of themes best known to the philosopher. Thus he argued
that prophets learn nothing new from revelation; the ignorant remain ignorant,
but the gift of imagination in the wise, if they are disciplined by the moral
virtues, especially courage and contentment, gives wing to ideas, rendering
them accessible to the masses and setting them into practice. In principle, any
philosopher of character and imagination might be a prophet; but in practice
the legislative, ethical, and mythopoeic imagination that serves philosophy
finds fullest articulation in one tradition. Its highest phase, where
imagination yields to pure intellectual communion, was unique to Moses,
elaborated in Judaism and its daughter religions. Maimonides’ philosophy was
pivotal for later Jewish thinkers, highly valued by Aquinas and other
Scholastics, studied by Spinoza in Hebrew translation, and annotated by Leibniz
in Buxtorf’s 1629 rendering, Doctor Perplexorum. See also JEWISH PHILOSOPHY.
L.E.G. Maistre, Joseph-Marie de. See DE MAISTRE. major premise. See SYLLOGISM.
major term. See SYLLOGISM. Malcolm, Norman (1911–90), American philosopher who
was a prominent figure in post– World War II analytic philosophy and perhaps
the foremost American interpreter and advocate of Wittgenstein. His association
with Wittgenstein (vividly described in his Ludwig Wittgenstein, A Memoir,
1958) began when he was a student at Cambridge (1938–40). Other influences were
Bouwsma, Malcolm’s undergraduate teacher at the University of Nebraska, and
Moore, whom he knew at Cambridge. Malcolm taught for over thirty years at
Cornell, and after his retirement in 1978 was associated with King’s College,
London. Malcolm’s earliest papers (e.g., “The Verification Argument,” 1950, and
“Knowledge and Belief,” 1952) dealt with issues of knowledge and skepticism,
and two dealt with Moore. “Moore and Ordinary Language” (1942) interpreted
Moore’s defense of common sense as a defense of ordinary language, but
“Defending Common Sense” (1949) argued that Moore’s “two hands” proof of the
external world involved a misuse of ‘know’. Moore’s proof was the topic of
extended discussions between Malcolm and Wittgenstein during the latter’s 1949
visit in Ithaca, New York, and these provided the stimulus for Wittgenstein’s
On Certainty. Malcolm’s “Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations” (1954)
was a highly influential discussion of Wittgenstein’s later philosophy, and
especially of his “private language argument.” Two other works of that period
were Malcolm’s Dreaming (1958), which argued that dreams do not have genuine
duration or temporal location, and do not entail having genuine experiences,
and “Anselm’s Ontological Arguments” (1960), which defended a version of the
ontological argument. Malcolm wrote extensively on memory, first in his “Three
Lectures on Memory,” published in his Knowledge and Certainty (1963), and then
in his Memory and Mind (1976). In the latter he criticized both philosophical
and psychological theories of memory, and argued that the notion of a memory
trace “is not a scientific discovery . . . [but] a product of philosophical
thinking, of a sort that is natural and enormously tempting, yet thoroughly
muddled.” A recurrent theme in Malcolm’s thought was that philosophical
understanding requires getting to the root of the temptations to advance some
philosophical doctrine, and that once we do so we will see the philosophical
doctrines as Maistre, Joseph-Marie de Malcolm, Norman 530 4065m-r.qxd
08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 530 confused or nonsensical. Although he was convinced
that dualism and other Cartesian views about the mind were thoroughly confused,
he thought no better of contemporary materialist and functionalist views, and
of current theorizing in psychology and linguistics (one paper is entitled “The
Myth of Cognitive Processes and Structures”). He shared with Wittgenstein both
an antipathy to scientism and a respect for religion. He shared with Moore an
antipathy to obscurantism and a respect for common sense. Malcolm’s last
published book, Nothing Is Hidden (1986), examines the relations between
Wittgenstein’s earlier and later philosophies. His other books include Problems
of Mind (1971), Thought and Knowledge (1977), and Consciousness and Causality
(1984), the latter coauthored with Armstrong. His writings are marked by an exceptionally
lucid, direct, and vivid style. See also BOUWSMA, MOORE, ORDINARY LANGUAGE
PHILOSOPHY, WITTGENSTEIN. S.Sho. Malebranche, Nicolas (1638–1715), French
philosopher and theologian, an important but unorthodox proponent of Cartesian
philosophy. Malebranche was a priest of the Oratory, a religious order founded
in 1611 by Cardinal Bérulle, who was favorably inclined toward Descartes.
Malebranche himself became a Cartesian after reading Descartes’s physiological
Treatise on Man in 1664, although he ultimately introduced crucial
modifications into Cartesian ontology, epistemology, and physics. Malebranche’s
most important philosophical work is The Search After Truth (1674), in which he
presents his two most famous doctrines: the vision in God and occasionalism. He
agrees with Descartes and other philosophers that ideas, or immaterial
representations present to the mind, play an essential role in knowledge and
perception. But whereas Descartes’s ideas are mental entities, or modifications
of the soul, Malebranche argues that the ideas that function in human cognition
are in God – they just are the essences and ideal archetypes that exist in the
divine understanding. As such, they are eternal and independent of finite
minds, and make possible the clear and distinct apprehension of objective,
neccessary truth. Malebranche presents the vision in God as the proper
Augustinian view, albeit modified in the light of Descartes’s epistemological
distinction between understanding and sensation. The theory explains both our
apprehension of universals and mathematical and moral principles, as well as
the conceptual element that, he argues, necessarily informs our perceptual
acquaintance with the world. Like Descartes’s theory of ideas, Malebranche’s
doctrine is at least partly motivated by an antiskepticism, since God’s ideas
cannot fail to reveal either eternal truths or the essences of things in the
world created by God. The vision in God, however, quickly became the object of
criticism by Locke, Arnauld, Foucher, and others, who thought it led to a
visionary and skeptical idealism, with the mind forever enclosed by a veil of
divine ideas. Malebranche is also the best-known proponent of occasionalism,
the doctrine that finite created beings have no causal efficacy and that God
alone is a true causal agent. Starting from Cartesian premises about matter,
motion, and causation – according to which the essence of body consists in
extension alone, motion is a mode of body, and a causal relation is a logically
necessary relation between cause and effect – Malebranche argues that bodies
and minds cannot be genuine causes of either physical events or mental states.
Extended bodies, he claims, are essentially inert and passive, and thus cannot
possess any motive force or power to cause and sustain motion. Moreover, there
is no necessary connection between any mental state (e.g. a volition) or
physical event and the bodily motions that usually follow it. Such necessity is
found only between the will of an omnipotent being and its effects. Thus, all
phenomena are directly and immediately brought about by God, although he always
acts in a lawlike way and on the proper occasion. Malebranche’s theory of ideas
and his occasionalism, as presented in the Search and the later Dialogues on Metaphysics
(1688), were influential in the development of Berkeley’s thought; and his
arguments for the causal theory foreshadow many of the considerations regarding
causation and induction later presented by Hume. In addition to these
innovations in Cartesian metaphysics and epistemology, Malebranche also
modified elements of Descartes’s physics, most notably in his account of the
hardness of bodies and of the laws of motion. In his other major work, the
Treatise on Nature and Grace (1680), Malebranche presents a theodicy, an
explanation of how God’s wisdom, goodness, and power are to be reconciled with
the apparent imperfections and evils in the world. In his account, elements of
which Leibniz borrows, Malebranche claims that God could have created a more perfect
world, one without the defects that plague this world, but that this would have
Malebranche, Nicolas Malebranche, Nicolas 531 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM
Page 531 involved greater complexity in the divine ways. God always acts in the
simplest way possible, and only by means of lawlike general volitions; God
never acts by “particular” or ad hoc volitions. But this means that while on
any particular occasion God could intervene and forestall an apparent evil that
is about to occur by the ordinary courses of the laws of nature (e.g. a
drought), God would not do so, for this would compromise the simplicity of
God’s means. The perfection or goodness of the world per se is thus relativized
to the simplicity of the laws of that world (or, which is the same thing, to
the generality of the divine volitions that, on the occasionalist view, govern
it). Taken together, the laws and the phenomena of the world form a whole that
is most worthy of God’s nature – in fact, the best combination possible.
Malebranche then extends this analysis to explain the apparent injustice in the
distribution of grace among humankind. It is just this extension that initiated
Arnauld’s attack and drew Malebranche into a long philosophical and theological
debate that would last until the end of the century. See also ARNAULD,
BERKELEY, OCCASIONALISM. S.N. Mani. See MANICHAEANISM. Manichaeanism, also
Manichaeism, a syncretistic religion founded by the Babylonian prophet Mani
(A.D. 216–77), who claimed a revelation from God and saw himself as a member of
a line that included the Buddha, Zoroaster, and Jesus. In dramatic myths,
Manichaeanism posited the good kingdom of God, associated with light, and the
evil kingdom of Satan, associated with darkness. Awareness of light caused
greed, hate, and envy in the darkness; this provoked an attack of darkness on
light. In response the Father sent Primal Man, who lost the fight so that light
and darkness were mixed. The Primal Man appealed for help, and the Living
Spirit came to win a battle, making heaven and earth out of the corpses of
darkness and freeing some capured light. A Third Messenger was sent; in
response the power of darkness created Adam and Eve, who contained the light
that still remained under his sway. Then Jesus was sent to a still innocent
Adam who nonetheless sinned, setting in motion the reproductive series that
yields humanity. This is the mythological background to the Manichaean account
of the basic religious problem: the human soul is a bit of captured light, and
the problem is to free the soul from darkness through asceticism and esoteric
knowledge. Manichaeanism denies that Jesus was crucified, and Augustine,
himself a sometime Manichaean, viewed the religion as a Docetic heresy that
denies the incarnation of the second person of the Trinity in a real human
body. The religion exhibits the pattern of escape from embodiment as a
condition of salvation, also seen in Hinduism and Buddhism. See also AUGUSTINE,
BUDDHISM, HINDUISM. K.E.Y. manifest content. See FREUD. manifold. See KANT.
Mannheim, Karl (1893–1947), Hungarian-born German social scientist best known
for his sociology of knowledge. Born in Budapest, where he took a university
degree in philosophy, he settled in Heidelberg in 1919 as a private scholar
until his call to Frankfurt as professor of sociology in 1928. Suspended as a
Jew and as foreign-born by the Nazis in 1933, he accepted an invitation from
the London School of Economics, where he was a lecturer for a decade. In 1943,
Mannheim became the first professor of sociology of education at the University
of London, a position he held until his death. Trained in the Hegelian
tradition, Mannheim defies easy categorization: his mature politics became
those of a liberal committed to social planning; with his many studies in the
sociology of culture, of political ideologies, of social organization, of
education, and of knowledge, among others, he founded several subdisciplines in
sociology and political science. While his Man and Society in an Age of
Reconstruction (1940) expressed his own commitment to social planning, his most
famous work, Ideology and Utopia (original German edition, 1929; revised
English edition, 1936), established sociology of knowledge as a scientific
enterprise and simultaneously cast doubt on the possibility of the very
scientific knowledge on which social planning was to proceed. As developed by
Mannheim, sociology of knowledge attempts to find the social causes of beliefs
as contrasted with the reasons people have for them. Mannheim seemed to believe
that this investigation both presupposes and demonstrates the impossibility of
“objective” knowledge of society, a theme that relates sociology of knowledge
to its roots in German philosophy and social theory (especially Marxism) and
earlier in the thought of the idéologues of the immediate post–French
Revolution decades. L.A.
Mansel, Henry Longueville
(1820–71), British philosopher and clergyman, a prominent defender of Scottish
common sense philosophy. Mansel was a professor of philosophy and ecclesiastical
history at Oxford, and the dean of St. Paul’s Cathedral. Much of his philosophy
was derived from Kant as interpreted by Hamilton. In Prolegomena Logica (1851)
he defined logic as the science of the laws of thought, while in
Metaphysics(1860) he argued that human faculties are not suited to know the
ultimate nature of things. He drew the religious implications of these views in
his most influential work, The Limits of Religious Thought (1858), by arguing
that God is rationally inconceivable and that the only available conception of
God is an analogical one derived from revelation. From this he concluded that
religious dogma is immune from rational criticism. In the ensuing controversy
Mansel was criticized by Spenser, Thomas Henry Huxley (1825–95), and J. S.
Mill. J.W.A. many questions, fallacy of. See INFORMAL FALLACY. many-valued
logic, a logic that rejects the principle of bivalence: every proposition is
true or false. However, there are two forms of rejection: the truth-functional
mode (many-valued logic proper), where propositions may take many values beyond
simple truth and falsity, values functionally determined by the values of their
components; and the truth-value gap mode, in which the only values are truth
and falsity, but propositions may have neither. What value they do or do not
have is not determined by the values or lack of values of their constituents.
Many-valued logic has its origins in the work of Lukasiewicz and
(independently) Post around 1920, in the first development of truth tables and
semantic methods. Lukasiewicz’s philosophical motivation for his three-valued
calculus was to deal with propositions whose truth-value was open or “possible”
– e.g., propositions about the future. He proposed they might take a third
value. Let 1 represent truth, 0 falsity, and the third value be, say, ½. We
take Ý (not) and P (implication) as primitive, letting v(ÝA) % 1 † v(A) and v(A
P B) % min(1,1 † v(A)!v(B)). These valuations may be displayed: Lukasiewicz
generalized the idea in 1922, to allow first any finite number of values, and
finally infinitely, even continuum-many values (between 0 and 1). One can then
no longer represent the functionality by a matrix; however, the formulas given
above can still be applied. Wajsberg axiomatized Lukasiewicz’s calculus in
1931. In 1953 Lukasiewicz published a four-valued extensional modal logic. In
1921, Post presented an m-valued calculus, with values 0 (truth), . . . , m † 1
(falsity), and matrices defined on Ý and v (or): v(ÝA) % 1 ! v(A) (modulo m)
and v(AvB) % min (v(A),v(B)). Translating this for comparison into the same
framework as above, we obtain the matrices (with 1 for truth and 0 for
falsity): The strange cyclic character of Ý makes Post’s system difficult to
interpret – though he did give one in terms of sequences of classical
propositions. A different motivation led to a system with three values
developed by Bochvar in 1939, namely, to find a solution to the logical
paradoxes. (Lukasiewicz had noted that his three-valued system was free of
antinomies.) The third value is indeterminate (so arguably Bochvar’s system is
actually one of gaps), and any combination of values one of which is
indeterminate is indeterminate; otherwise, on the determinate values, the
matrices are classical. Thus we obtain for Ý and P, using 1, ½, and 0 as above:
In order to develop a logic of many values, one needs to characterize the
notion of a thesis, or logical truth. The standard way to do this in manyvalued
logic is to separate the values into designated and undesignated. Effectively,
this is to reintroduce bivalence, now in the form: Every proposition is either
designated or undesignated. Thus in Lukasiewicz’s scheme, 1 (truth) is the only
designated value; in Post’s, any initial segment 0, . . . , n † 1, where n‹m (0
as truth). In general, one can think of the various designated values as types
of truth, or ways a proposition may be true, and the undesignated ones as ways
it can be false. Then a proposition is a thesis if and Mansel, Henry
Longueville many-valued logic 533 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 533 only
if it takes only designated values. For example, p P p is, but p 7 Ýp is not, a
Lukasiewicz thesis. However, certain matrices may generate no logical truths by
this method, e.g., the Bochvar matrices give ½ for every formula any of whose
variables is indeterminate. If both 1 and ½ were designated, all theses of
classical logic would be theses; if only 1, no theses result. So the
distinction from classical logic is lost. Bochvar’s solution was to add an
external assertion and negation. But this in turn runs the risk of undercutting
the whole philosophical motivation, if the external negation is used in a
Russell-type paradox. One alternative is to concentrate on consequence: A is a
consequence of a set of formulas X if for every assignment of values either no
member of X is designated or A is. Bochvar’s consequence relation (with only 1
designated) results from restricting classical consequence so that every
variable in A occurs in some member of X. There is little technical difficulty
in extending many-valued logic to the logic of predicates and quantifiers. For
example, in Lukasiewicz’s logic, v(E xA) % min {v(A(a/x)): a 1. D}, where D is,
say, some set of constants whose assignments exhaust the domain. This interprets
the universal quantifier as an “infinite” conjunction. In 1965, Zadeh
introduced the idea of fuzzy sets, whose membership relation allows
indeterminacies: it is a function into the unit interval [0,1], where 1 means
definitely in, 0 definitely out. One philosophical application is to the
sorites paradox, that of the heap. Instead of insisting that there be a sharp
cutoff in number of grains between a heap and a non-heap, or between red and,
say, yellow, one can introduce a spectrum of indeterminacy, as definite
applications of a concept shade off into less clear ones. Nonetheless, many
have found the idea of assigning further definite values, beyond truth and
falsity, unintuitive, and have instead looked to develop a scheme that
encompasses truthvalue gaps. One application of this idea is found in Kleene’s
strong and weak matrices of 1938. Kleene’s motivation was to develop a logic of
partial functions. For certain arguments, these give no definite value; but the
function may later be extended so that in such cases a definite value is given.
Kleene’s constraint, therefore, was that the matrices be regular: no
combination is given a definite value that might later be changed; moreover, on
the definite values the matrices must be classical. The weak matrices are as
for Bochvar. The strong matrices yield (1 for truth, 0 for falsity, and u for
indeterminacy): An alternative approach to truth-value gaps was presented by
Bas van Fraassen in the 1960s. Suppose v(A) is undefined if v(B) is undefined
for any subformula B of A. Let a classical extension of a truth-value
assignment v be any assignment that matches v on 0 and 1 and assigns either 0
or 1 whenever v assigns no value. Then we can define a supervaluation w over v:
w(A) % 1 if the value of A on all classical extensions of v is 1, 0 if it is 0
and undefined otherwise. A is valid if w(A) % 1 for all supervaluations w (over
arbitrary valuations). By this method, excluded middle, e.g., comes out valid,
since it takes 1 in all classical extensions of any partial valuation. Van
Fraassen presented several applications of the supervaluation technique. One is
to free logic, logic in which empty terms are admitted. See also FREE LOGIC,
VAGUENESS. S.L.R. Mao Tse-tung (1893–1976), Chinese Communist leader, founder
of the People’s Republic of China in 1949. He believed that Marxist ideas must
be adapted to China. Contrary to the Marxist orthodoxy, which emphasized
workers, Mao organized peasants in the countryside. His philosophical writings
include On Practice (1937) and On Contradiction (1937), synthesizing
dialectical materialism and traditional Chinese philosophy. In his later years
he departed from the gradual strategy of his On New Democracy (1940) and
adopted increasingly radical means to change China. Finally he started the
Cultural Revolution in 1967 and plunged China into disaster. See also CHINESE
PHILOSOPHY, LIANG SOU-MING, LIU SHAO-CH’I. S.-h.L. Marburg School. See
NEO-KANTIANISM. Marcel, Gabriel (1889–1973), French philosopher and playwright,
a major representative of French existential thought. He was a member of the
Academy of Political and Social Science of the Institute of France. Musician,
drama critic, and lecturer of international renown, he authored thirty plays
and as many philosophic essays. He considered his principal contribution to be
that of a philosopher-dramatist. Together, his dramatic and philosophic works
cut a path for Mao Tse-tung Marcel, Gabriel 534 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM
Page 534 the reasoned exercise of freedom to enhance the dignity of human life.
The conflicts and challenges of his own life he brought to the light of the
theater; his philosophic works followed as efforts to discern critically
through rigorous, reasoned analyses the alternative options life offers. His
dramatic masterpiece, The Broken World, compassionately portrayed the
devastating sense of emptiness, superficial activities, and fractured
relationships that plague the modern era. This play cleared a way for Marcel to
transcend nineteenth-century British and German idealism, articulate his
distinction between problem and mystery, and evolve an existential approach
that reflectively clarified mysteries that can provide depth and meaningfulness
to human life. In the essay “On the Ontological Mystery,” a philosophic sequel
to The Broken World, Marcel confronted the questions “Who am I? – Is Being
empty or full?” He explored the regions of body or incarnate being,
intersubjectivity, and transcendence. His research focused principally on
intersubjectivity clarifying the requisite attitudes and essential
characteristics of I-Thou encounters, interpersonal relations, commitment and
creative fidelity – notions he also developed in Homo Viator (1945) and
Creative Fidelity (1940). Marcel’s thought balanced despair and hope, infidelity
and fidelity, self-deception and a spirit of truth. He recognized both the role
of freedom and the role of fundamental attitudes or prephilosophic
dispositions, as these influence one’s way of being and the interpretation of
life’s meaning. Concern for the presence of loved ones who have died appears in
both Marcel’s dramatic and philosophic works, notably in Presence and
Immortality. This concern, coupled with his reflections on intersubjectivity,
led him to explore how a human subject can experience the presence of God or
the presence of loved ones from beyond death. Through personal experience,
dramatic imagination, and philosophic investigation, he discovered that such
presence can be experienced principally by way of inwardness and depth. “Presence”
is a spiritual influx that profoundly affects one’s being, uplifting it and
enriching one’s personal resources. While it does depend on a person’s being
open and permeable, presence is not something that the person can summon forth.
A conferral or presence is always a gratuitous gift, coauthored and marked by
its signal benefit, an incitement to create. So Marcel’s reflection on
interpersonal communion enabled him to conceive philosophically how God can be
present to a person as a life-giving and personalizing force whose benefit is
always an incitement to create. See also BUBER, EXISTENTIALISM, PHILOSOPHY OF
LITERATURE. K.R.H. Marcus, Ruth Barcan (b.1921), American philosopher best
known for her seminal work in philosophical logic. In 1946 she published the
first systematic treatment of quantified modal logic, thereby turning aside
Quine’s famous attack on the coherence of combining quantifiers with alethic
operators. She later extended the first-order formalization to second order
with identity (1947) and to modalized set theory (1963). Marcus’s writings in
logic either inaugurated or brought to the fore many issues that have loomed
large in subsequent philosophical theorizing. Of particular significance are
the Barcan formula (1946), the theorem about the necessity of identity (1963),
a flexible notion of extensionality (1960, 1961), and the view that ordinary
proper names are contentless directly referential tags (1961). This last laid
the groundwork for the theory of direct reference later advanced by Kripke,
Keith Donnellan, David Kaplan, and others. No less a revolutionary in moral
theory, Marcus undermined the entire structure of standard deontic logic in her
paper on iterated deontic modalities (1966). She later (1980) argued against
some theorists that moral dilemmas are real, and against others that moral
dilemmas need neither derive from inconsistent rules nor imply moral
anti-realism. In her series of papers on belief (1981, 1983, 1990), Marcus
repudiates theories that identify beliefs with attitudes to linguistic or
quasi-linguistic items. She argues instead that for an agent A to believe that
p is for A to be disposed to behave as if p obtains (where p is a possible
state of affairs). Her analysis mobilizes a conception of rational agents as seeking
to maintain global coherence among the verbal and non-verbal indicators of
their beliefs. During much of Marcus’s career she served as Reuben Post Halleck
Professor of Philosophy at Yale University. She has also served as chair of the
Board of Officers of the American Philosophical Association and president of
its Central Division, president of the Association of Symbolic Logic, and
president of the Institut International de Philosophie. See also BELIEF, CAUSAL
THEORY OF PROPER NAMES, MODAL LOGIC, MORAL DILEMMA, PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE,
PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC, QUINE. D.R. & W.S.-A. Marcus, Ruth Barcan Marcus, Ruth
Barcan 535 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 535 Marcus Aurelius (A.D.
121–80), Roman emperor (from 161) and philosopher. Author of twelve books of
Meditations (Greek title, To Himself), Marcus Aurelius is principally
interesting in the history of Stoic philosophy (of which he was a diligent
student) for his ethical self-portrait. Except for the first book, detailing
his gratitude to his family, friends, and teachers, the aphorisms are arranged
in no order; many were written in camp during military campaigns. They reflect
both the Old Stoa and the more eclectic views of Posidonius, with whom he holds
that involvement in public affairs is a moral duty. Marcus, in accord with
Stoicism, considers immortality doubtful; happiness lies in patient acceptance
of the will of the panentheistic Stoic God, the material soul of a material
universe. Anger, like all emotions, is forbidden the Stoic emperor: he exhorts
himself to compassion for the weak and evil among his subjects. “Do not be
turned into ‘Caesar,’ or dyed by the purple: for that happens” (6.30). “It is
the privilege of a human being to love even those who stumble” (7.22). Sayings
like these, rather than technical arguments, give the book its place in
literary history. See also HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY, STOICISM. D.Ar. Marcuse,
Herbert (1898–1979). German-born American political philosopher who
reinterpreted the ideas of Marx and Freud. Marcuse’s work is among the most
systematic and philosophical of the Frankfurt School theorists. After an
initial attempt to unify Hegel, Marx, and Heidegger in an ontology of
historicity in his habilitation on Hegel’s Ontology and the Theory of
Historicity (1932), Marcuse was occupied during the 1930s with the problem of
truth in a critical historical social theory, defending a contextindependent
notion of truth against relativizing tendencies of the sociology of knowledge.
Marcuse thought Hegel’s “dialectics” provided an alternative to relativism,
empiricism, and positivism and even developed a revolutionary interpretation of
the Hegelian legacy in Reason and Revolution (1941) opposed to Popper’s
totalitarian one. After World War II, Marcuse appropriated Freud in the same
way that he had appropriated Hegel before the war, using his basic concepts for
a critical theory of the repressive character of civilization in Eros and
Civilization (1955). In many respects, this book comes closer to presenting a
positive conception of reason and Enlightenment than any other work of the
Frankfurt School. Marcuse argued that civilization has been antagonistic to
happiness and freedom through its constant struggle against basic human
instincts. According to Marcuse, human existence is grounded in Eros, but these
impulses depend upon and are shaped by labor. By synthesizing Marx and Freud,
Marcuse holds out the utopian possibility of happiness and freedom in the unity
of Eros and labor, which at the very least points toward the reduction of
“surplus repression” as the goal of a rational economy and emancipatory social
criticism. This was also the goal of his aesthetic theory as developed in The
Aesthetic Dimension (1978). In One Dimensional Man (1964) and other writings,
Marcuse provides an analysis of why the potential for a free and rational
society has never been realized: in the irrationality of the current social
totality, its creation and manipulation of false needs (or “repressive
desublimation”), and hostility toward nature. Perhaps no other Frankfurt School
philosopher has had as much popular influence as Marcuse, as evidenced by his
reception in the student and ecology movements. See also CRITICAL THEORY,
FRANKFURT SCHOOL. J.Bo. marginal utility. See UTILITARIANISM. Mariana, Juan de
(1536–1624), Spanish Jesuit historian and political philosopher. Born in
Talavera de la Reina, he studied at Alcalá de Henares and taught at Rome,
Sicily, and Paris. His political ideas are contained in De rege et regis
institutione (“On Kingship,” 1599) and De monetae mutatione (“On Currency,”
1609). Mariana held that political power rests on the community of citizens,
and the power of the monarch derives from the people. The natural state of
humanity did not include, as Vitoria held, government and other political
institutions. The state of nature was one of justice in which all possessions
were held in common, and cooperation characterized human relations. Private
property is the result of technological advances that produced jealousy and
strife. Antedating both Hobbes and Rousseau, Mariana argued that humans made a
contract and delegated their political power to leaders in order to eliminate
injustice and strife. However, only the people have the right to change the
law. A monarch who does not follow the law and ceases to act for the citizens’
welfare may be forcibly removed. Tyrannicide is thus justifiable under some
circumstances. See also CONTRACTARIANISM, POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. J.J.E.G. Marcus
Aurelius Mariana, Juan de 536 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 536 Maritain,
Jacques (1882–1973), French Catholic philosopher whose innovative
interpretation of Aquinas’s philosophy made him a central figure in
Neo-Thomism. Bergson’s teaching saved him from metaphysical despair and a
suicide pact with his fiancée. After his discovery of Aquinas, he rejected
Bergsonism for a realistic account of the concept and a unified theory of
knowledge, aligning the empirical sciences with the philosophy of nature,
metaphysics, theology, and mysticism in Distinguish to Unite or The Degrees of
Knowledge (1932). Maritain opposed the skepticism and idealism that severed the
mind from sensibility, typified by the “angelism” of Descartes’s intuitionism.
Maritain traced the practical effects of angelism in art, politics, and religion.
His Art and Scholasticism (1920) employs ancient and medieval notions of art as
a virtue and beauty as a transcendental aspect of being. In politics,
especially Man and the State (1961), Maritain stressed the distinction between
the person and the individual, the ontological foundation of natural rights,
the religious origins of the democratic ideal, and the importance of the common
good. He also argued for the possibility of philosophy informed by the data of
revelation without compromising its integrity, and an Integral Humanism (1936)
that affirms the political order while upholding the eternal destiny of the
human person. See also AQUINAS, NEOTHOMISM. D.W.H. Markov process. See
STOCHASTIC PROCESS. Marsilio dei Mainardine. See MARSILIUS OF PADUA. Marsilius
of Inghen (c.1330–96), Dutch philosopher and theologian. Born near Nijmegen,
Marsilius studied under Buridan, taught at Paris for thirty years, then, in
1383, moved to the newly founded University of Heidelberg, where he and Albert
of Saxony established nominalism in Germany. In logic, he produced an Ockhamist
revision of the Tractatus of Peter of Spain, often published as Textus
dialectices in early sixteenthcentury Germany, and a commentary on Aristotle’s
Prior Analytics. He developed Buridan’s theory of impetus in his own way,
accepted Bradwardine’s account of the proportions of velocities, and adopted
Nicholas of Oresme’s doctrine of intension and remission of forms, applying the
new physics in his commentaries on Aristotle’s physical works. In theology he
followed Ockham’s skeptical emphasis on faith, allowing that one might prove
the existence of God along Scotistic lines, but insisting that, since natural
philosophy could not accommodate the creation of the universe ex nihilo, God’s
omnipotence was known only through faith. J.Lo. Marsilius of Padua, in Italian,
Marsilio dei Mainardini (1275/80–1342), Italian political theorist. He served
as rector of the University of Paris between 1312 and 1313; his anti-papal
views forced him to flee Paris (1326) for Nuremberg, where he was political and
ecclesiastic adviser of Louis of Bavaria. His major work, Defensor pacis
(“Defender of Peace,” 1324), attacks the doctrine of the supremacy of the pope
and argues that the authority of a secular ruler elected to represent the
people is superior to the authority of the papacy and priesthood in both
temporal and spiritual affairs. Three basic claims of Marsilius’s theory are
that reason, not instinct or God, allows us to know what is just and conduces
to the flourishing of human society; that governments need to enforce obedience
to the laws by coercive measures; and that political power ultimately resides
in the people. He was influenced by Aristotle’s ideal of the state as necessary
to foster human flourishing. His thought is regarded as a major step in the
history of political philosophy and one of the first defenses of republicanism.
P.Gar. Martineau, James (1805–1900), English philosopher of religion and
ethical intuitionist. As a minister and a professor, Martineau defended
Unitarianism and opposed pantheism. In A Study of Religion (1888) Martineau
agreed with Kant that reality as we experience it is the work of the mind, but
he saw no reason to doubt his intuitive conviction that the phenomenal world
corresponds to a real world of enduring, causally related objects. He believed
that the only intelligible notion of causation is given by willing and
concluded that reality is the expression of a divine will that is also the
source of moral authority. In Types of Ethical Theory (1885) he claimed that
the fundamental fact of ethics is the human tendency to approve and disapprove
of the motives leading to voluntary actions, actions in which there are two
motives present to consciousness. After freely choosing one of the motives, the
agent can determine which action best expresses it. Since Martineau thought
that agents intuitively know through conscience which motive is higher, the
core of his ethical theory is a ranking of the thirteen principal motives, the
highest of which is reverence. See also INTUITIONISM. J.W.A. Maritain, Jacques
Martineau, James 537 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 537 Marx, Karl
(1818–83), German social philosopher, economic theorist, and revolutionary. He
lived and worked as a journalist in Cologne, Paris, and Brussels. After the
unsuccessful 1848 revolutions in Europe, he settled in London, doing research
and writing and earning some money as correspondent for the New York Tribune.
In early writings, he articulated his critique of the religiously and
politically conservative implications of the then-reigning philosophy of Hegel,
finding there an acceptance of existing private property relationships and of
the alienation generated by them. Marx understood alienation as a state of
radical disharmony (1) among individuals, (2) between them and their own life
activity, or labor, and (3) between individuals and their system of production.
Later, in his masterwork Capital (1867, 1885, 1894), Marx employed Hegel’s
method of dialectic to generate an internal critique of the theory and practice
of capitalism, showing that, under assumptions (notably that human labor is the
source of economic value) found in such earlier theorists as Adam Smith, this
system must undergo increasingly severe crises, resulting in the eventual
seizure of control of the increasingly centralized means of production
(factories, large farms, etc.) from the relatively small class of capitalist
proprietors by the previously impoverished non-owners (the proletariat) in the
interest of a thenceforth classless society. Marx’s early writings, somewhat
utopian in tone, most never published during his lifetime, emphasize social
ethics and ontology. In them, he characterizes his position as a “humanism” and
a “naturalism.” In the Theses on Feuerbach, he charts a middle path between
Hegel’s idealist account of the nature of history as the selfunfolding of
spirit and what Marx regards as the ahistorical, mechanistic, and passive
materialist philosophy of Feuerbach; Marx proposes a conception of history as
forged by human activity, or praxis, within determinate material conditions
that vary by time and place. In later Marxism, this general position is often
labeled dialectical materialism. Marx began radically to question the nature of
philosophy, coming to view it as ideology, i.e., a thought system parading as
autonomous but in fact dependent on the material conditions of the society in
which it is produced. The tone of Capital is therefore on the whole less
philosophical and moralistic, more social scientific and tending toward
historical determinism, than that of the earlier writings, but punctuated by
bursts of indignation against the baneful effects of capitalism’s profit
orientation and references to the “society of associated producers” (socialism
or communism) that would, or could, replace capitalist society. His
enthusiastic predictions of immanent worldwide revolutionary changes, in
various letters, articles, and the famous Communist Manifesto (1848; jointly
authored with his close collaborator, Friedrich Engels), depart from the
generally more hypothetical character of the text of Capital itself. The
linchpin that perhaps best connects Marx’s earlier and later thought and
guarantees his enduring relevance as a social philosopher is his analysis of
the role of human labor power as a peculiar type of commodity within a system
of commodity exchange (his theory of surplus value). Labor’s peculiarity,
according to him, lies in its capacity actively to generate more exchange value
than it itself costs employers as subsistence wages. But to treat human beings
as profit-generating commodities risks neglecting to treat them as human
beings. See also MARXISM, POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY, PRAXIS. W.L.M. Marxism, the
philosophy of Karl Marx, or any of several systems of thought or approaches to
social criticism derived from Marx. The term is also applied, incorrectly, to
certain sociopolitical structures created by dominant Communist parties during
the mid-twentieth century. Karl Marx himself, apprised of the ideas of certain
French critics who invoked his name, remarked that he knew at least that he was
not a Marxist. The fact that his collaborator, Friedrich Engels, a popularizer
with a greater interest than Marx in the natural sciences, outlived him and wrote,
among other things, a “dialectics of nature” that purported to discover certain
universal natural laws, added to the confusion. Lenin, the leading Russian
Communist revolutionary, near the end of his life discovered previously
unacknowledged connections between Marx’s Capital (1867) and Hegel’s Science of
Logic (1812–16) and concluded (in his Philosophical Notebooks) that Marxists
for a half-century had not understood Marx. Specific political agendas of,
among others, the Marxist faction within the turn-of-the-century German Social
Democratic Party, the Bolshevik faction of Russian socialists led by Lenin, and
later governments and parties claiming allegiance to “Marxist-Leninist
principles” have contributed to reinterpretations. For several decades in the
Soviet Union and countries allied with it, a broad agreement concernMarx, Karl
Marxism 538 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 538 ing fundamental Marxist
doctrines was established and politically enforced, resulting in a doctrinaire
version labeled “orthodox Marxism” and virtually ensuring the widespread,
wholesale rejection of Marxism as such when dissidents taught to accept this
version as authentic Marxism came to power. Marx never wrote a systematic
exposition of his thought, which in any case drastically changed emphases
across time and included elements of history, economics, and sociology as well
as more traditional philosophical concerns. In one letter he specifically warns
against regarding his historical account of Western capitalism as a transcendental
analysis of the supposedly necessary historical development of any and all
societies at a certain time. It is thus somewhat paradoxical that Marxism is
often identified as a “totalizing” if not “totalitarian” system by
postmodernist philosophers who reject global theories or “grand narratives” as
inherently invalid. However, the evolution of Marxism since Marx’s time helps
explain this identification. That “orthodox” Marxism would place heavy emphasis
on historical determinism – the inevitability of a certain general sequence of
events leading to the replacement of capitalism by a socialist economic system
(in which, according to a formula in Marx’s Critique of the Gotha Program, each
person would be remunerated according to his/her work) and eventually by a
communist one (remuneration in accordance with individual needs) – was
foreshadowed by Plekhanov. In The Role of the Individual in History, he
portrayed individual idiosyncrasies as accidental: e.g., had Napoleon not
existed the general course of history would not have turned out differently. In
Materialism and Empiriocriticism, Lenin offered epistemological reinforcement
for the notion that Marxism is the uniquely true worldview by defending a
“copy” or “reflection” theory of knowledge according to which true concepts
simply mirror objective reality, like photographs. Elsewhere, however, he
argued against “economism,” the inference that the historical inevitability of
communism’s victory obviated political activism. Lenin instead maintained that,
at least under the repressive political conditions of czarist Russia, only a
clandestine party of professional revolutionaries, acting as the vanguard of
the working class and in its interests, could produce fundamental change.
Later, during the long political reign of Josef Stalin, the hegemonic Communist
Party of the USSR was identified as the supreme interpreter of these interests,
thus justifying totalitarian rule. So-called Western Marxism opposed this
“orthodox” version, although the writings of one of its foremost early
representatives, Georg Lukacs, who brilliantly perceived the close connection
between Hegel’s philosophy and the early thought of Marx before the unpublished
manuscripts proving this connection had been retrieved from archives, actually
tended to reinforce both the view that the party incarnated the ideal interests
of the proletariat (see his History and Class Consciousness) and an aesthetics
favoring the art of “socialist realism” over more experimental forms. His
contemporary, Karl Korsch, in Marxism as Philosophy, instead saw Marxism as
above all a heuristic method, pointing to salient phenomena (e.g., social
class, material conditioning) generally neglected by other philosophies. His
counsel was in effect followed by the Frankfurt School of critical theory,
including Walter Benjamin in the area of aesthetics, Theodor Adorno in social
criticism, and Wilhelm Reich in psychology. A spate of “new Marxisms” – the
relative degrees of their fidelity to Marx’s original thought cannot be weighed
here – developed, especially in the wake of the gradual rediscovery of Marx’s
more ethically oriented, less deterministic early writings. Among the names
meriting special mention in this context are Ernst Bloch, who explored
Marxism’s connection with utopian thinking; Herbert Marcuse, critic of the
“one-dimensionality” of industrial society; the Praxis school (after the name
of their journal and in view of their concern with analyzing social practices)
of Yugoslav philosophers; and the later Jean-Paul Sartre. Also worthy of note
are the writings, many of them composed in prison under Mussolini’s Italian
Fascist rule, of Antonio Gramsci, who stressed the role of cultural factors in
determining what is dominant politically and ideologically at any given time.
Simultaneous with the decline and fall of regimes in which “orthodox Marxism”
was officially privileged has been the recent development of new approaches,
loosely connected by virtue of their utilization of techniques favored by
British and American philosophers, collectively known as analytic Marxism.
Problems of justice, theories of history, and the questionable nature of Marx’s
theory of surplus value have been special concerns to these writers. This
development suggests that the current unfashionableness of Marxism in many
circles, due largely to its understandable but misleading identification with
the aforementioned regimes, is itself only a temporary phenomenon, even if
Marxism Marxism 539 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 539 future Marxisms are
likely to range even further from Marx’s own specific concerns while still
sharing his commitment to identifying, explaining, and criticizing hierarchies
of dominance and subordination, particularly those of an economic order, in
human society. See also CRITICAL THEORY, FRANKFURT SCHOOL, LUKACS, MARX,
PRAXIS, PRAXIS SCHOOL. W.L.M. mass noun. See COUNT NOUN. master argument. See
MEGARIANS. material adequacy, the property that belongs to a formal definition
of a concept when that definition characterizes or “captures” the extension (or
material) of the concept. Intuitively, a formal definition of a concept is
materially adequate if and only if it is neither too broad nor too narrow.
Tarski advanced the state of philosophical semantics by discovering the criterion
of material adequacy of truth definitions contained in his convention T.
Material adequacy contrasts with analytic adequacy, which belongs to
definitions that provide a faithful analysis. Defining an integer to be even if
and only if it is the product of two consecutive integers would be materially
adequate but not analytically adequate, whereas defining an integer to be even
if and only if it is a multiple of 2 would be both materially and analytically
adequate. See also CONVENTION T, DEFINITION, FORMAL SEMANTICS, TARSKI, TRUTH.
J. Cor. material cause. See ARISTOTLE. material conditional. See
COUNTERFACTUALS, IMPLICATION. material equivalence. See EQUIVALENCE. material
implication. See IMPLICATION. material implication, paradoxes of. See
IMPLICATION. materialism. See METAPHYSICS, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. materialism,
Australian. See SMART. materialism, central state. See PHILOSOPHY OF MIND.
materialism, dialectical. See MARX, PLEKHANOV. materialism, emergent. See
PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. materialism, historical. See ENGELS. materialism,
non-reductive. See PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. material mode. See METALANGUAGE.
material supposition. See SUPPOSITIO. mathematical analysis, also called
standard analysis, the area of mathematics pertaining to the so-called real
number system, i.e. the area that can be based on an axiom set whose intended
interpretation (standard model) has the set of real numbers as its domain
(universe of discourse). Thus analysis includes, among its many subbranches,
elementary algebra, differential and integral calculus, differential equations,
the calculus of variations, and measure theory. Analytic geometry involves the
application of analysis to geometry. Analysis contains a large part of the
mathematics used in mathematical physics. The real numbers, which are
representable by the ending and unending decimals, are usefully construed as
(or as corresponding to) distances measured, relative to an arbitrary unit
length, positively to the right and negatively to the left of an arbitrarily
fixed zero point along a geometrical straight line. In particular, the class of
real numbers includes as increasingly comprehensive proper subclasses the
natural numbers, the integers (positive, negative, and zero), the rational
numbers (or fractions), and the algebraic numbers (such as the square root of
two). Especially important is the presence in the class of real numbers of
non-algebraic (or transcendental) irrational numbers such as pi. The set of
real numbers includes arbitrarily small and arbitrarily large, finite
quantities, while excluding infinitesimal and infinite quantities. Analysis,
often conceived as the mathematics of continuous magnitude, contrasts with
arithmetic (natural number theory), which is regarded as the mathematics of
discrete magnitude. Analysis is often construed as involving not just the real
numbers but also the imaginary (complex) numbers. Traditionally analysis is
expressed in a second-order or higher-order language wherein its axiom set has
categoricity; each of its models is isomorphic to (has the same structure as)
the standard model. When analysis is carried out in a first-order language, as
has been increasingly the case since the 1950s, categoricity is impossible and
it has nonstandard mass noun mathematical analysis 540 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999
7:42 AM Page 540 models in addition to its standard model. A nonstandard model
of analysis is an interpretation not isomorphic to the standard model but
nevertheless satisfying the axiom set. Some of the nonstandard models involve
objects reminiscent of the much-despised “infinitesimals” that were essential
to the Leibniz approach to calculus and that were subject to intense criticism
by Berkeley and other philosophers and philosophically sensitive
mathematicians. These non-standard models give rise to a new area of
mathematics, non-standard analysis, within which the fallacious arguments used
by Leibniz and other early analysts form the heuristic basis of new and
entirely rigorous proofs. See also CALCULUS, CATEGORICITY, PHILOSOPHY OF
MATHEMATICS. J.Cor. mathematical constructivism. See PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS.
mathematical function, an operation that, when applied to an entity (set of
entities) called its argument(s), yields an entity known as the value of the
function for that argument(s). This operation can be expressed by a functional
equation of the form y % f(x) such that a variable y is said to be a function
of a variable x if corresponding to each value of x there is one and only one
value of y. The x is called the independent variable (or argument of the
function) and the y the dependent variable (or value of the function). (Some
definitions consider the relation to be the function, not the dependent
variable, and some definitions permit more than one value of y to correspond to
a given value of x, as in x2 ! y2 % 4.) More abstractly, a function can be
considered to be simply a special kind of relation (set of ordered pairs) that
to any element in its domain relates exactly one element in its range. Such a
function is said to be a one-to-one correspondence if and only if the set {x,y}
elements of S and {z,y} elements of S jointly imply x % z. Consider, e.g., the
function {(1,1), (2,4), (3,9), (4,16), (5,25), (6,36)}, each of whose members
is of the form (x,x2) – the squaring function. Or consider the function {(0,1),
(1,0)} – which we can call the negation function. In contrast, consider the
function for exclusive alternation (as in you may have a beer or glass of wine,
but not both). It is not a one-to-one correspondence. For, 0 is the value of
(0,1) and of (1,0), and 1 is the value of (0,0) and of (1,1). If we think of a
function as defined on the natural numbers – functions from Nn to N for various
n (most commonly n % 1 or 2) – a partial function is a function from Nn to N
whose domain is not necessarily the whole of Nn (e.g., not defined for all of
the natural numbers). A total function from Nn to N is a function whose domain
is the whole of Nn (e.g., all of the natural numbers). See also FUNCTIONALISM,
TELEOLOGY. F.A. mathematical induction, a method of definition and a method of
proof. A collection of objects can be defined inductively. All members of such
a collection can be shown to have a property by an inductive proof. The natural
numbers and the set of well-formed formulas of a formal language are familiar
examples of sets given by inductive definition. Thus, the set of natural
numbers is inductively defined as the smallest set, N, such that: (B) 0 is in N
and (I) for any x in N the successor of x is in N. (B) is the basic clause and (I)
the inductive clause of this definition. Or consider a propositional language
built on negation and conjunction. We start with a denumerable class of atomic
sentence symbols ATOM = {A1, A2, . . .}. Then we can define the set of
well-formed formulas, WFF, as the smallest set of expressions such that: (B)
every member of ATOM is in WFF and (I) if x is in WFF then (- x) is in WFF and
if x and y are in WFF then (x & y) is in WFF. We show that all members of
an inductively defined set have a property by showing that the members
specified by the basis have that property and that the property is preserved by
the induction. For example, we show that all WFFs have an even number of
parentheses by showing (i) that all ATOMs have an even number of parentheses
and (ii) that if x and y have an even number of parentheses then so do (- x)
and (x & y). This shows that the set of WFFs with an even number of
parentheses satisfies (B) and (I). The set of WFFs with an even number of
parentheses must then be identical to WFF, since – by definition – WFF is the
smallest set that satisfies (B) and (I). Ordinary proof by mathematical
induction shows that all the natural numbers, or all members of some set with
the order type of the natural numbers, share a property. Proof by transfinite
induction, a more general form of proof by mathematical induction, shows that
all members of some well-ordered set have a certain property. A set is
well-ordered if and only if every non-empty subset of it has a least element.
The natural numbers are well-ordered. It is a consequence of the axiom of
choice that every set can be well-ordered. Suppose that a set, X, is
well-ordered and that P is the subset of X whose mathematical constructivism
mathematical induction 541 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 541 members have
the property of interest. Suppose that it can be shown for any element x of X,
if all members of X less that x are in P, then so is x. Then it follows by
transfinite induction that all members of X have the property, that X % P. For if
X did not coincide with P, then the set of elements of x not in P would be
non-empty. Since X is well-ordered, this set would have a least element, x*.
But then by definition, all members of X less than x* are in P, and by
hypothesis x* must be in P after all. See also INDUCTION, PHILOSOPHY OF
MATHEMATICS, PROOF THEORY. B.Sk. mathematical intuitionism, a twentieth-century
movement that reconstructs mathematics in accordance with an epistemological
idealism and a Kantian metaphysics. Specifically, Brouwer, its founder, held
that there are no unexperienced truths and that mathematical objects stem from
the a priori form of those conscious acts which generate empirical objects.
Unlike Kant, however, Brouwer rejected the apriority of space and based mathematics
solely on a refined conception of the intuition of time. Intuitionistic
mathematics. According to Brouwer, the simplest mathematical act is to
distinguish between two diverse elements in the flow of consciousness. By
repeating and concatenating such acts we generate each of the natural numbers,
the standard arithmetical operations, and thus the rational numbers with their
operations as well. Unfortunately, these simple, terminating processes cannot
produce the convergent infinite sequences of rational numbers that are needed
to generate the continuum (the nondenumerable set of real numbers, or of points
on the line). Some “proto-intuitionists” admitted infinite sequences whose
elements are determined by finitely describable rules. However, the set of all such
algorithmic sequences is denumerable and thus can scarcely generate the
continuum. Brouwer’s first attempt to circumvent this – by postulating a single
intuition of an ever growing continuum – mirrored Aristotle’s picture of the
continuum as a dynamic whole composed of inseparable parts. But this approach
was incompatible with the set-theoretic framework that Brouwer accepted, and by
1918 he had replaced it with the concept of an infinite choice sequence. A
choice sequence of rational numbers is, to be sure, generated by a “rule,” but
the rule may leave room for some degree of freedom in choosing the successive
elements. It might, e.g., simply require that the n ! 1st choice be a rational
number that lies within 1/n of the nth choice. The set of real numbers
generated by such semideterminate sequences is demonstrably non-denumerable.
Following his epistemological beliefs, Brouwer admitted only those properties
of a choice sequence which are determined by its rule and by a finite number of
actual choices. He incorporated this restriction into his version of set theory
and obtained a series of results that conflict with standard (classical)
mathematics. Most famously, he proved that every function that is fully defined
over an interval of real numbers is uniformly continuous. (Pictorially, the
graph of the function has no gaps or jumps.) Interestingly, one corollary of
this theorem is that the set of real numbers cannot be divided into mutually
exclusive subsets, a property that rigorously recovers the Aristotelian picture
of the continuum. The clash with classical mathematics. Unlike his disciple
Arend Heyting, who considered intuitionistic and classical mathematics as
separate and therefore compatible subjects, Brouwer viewed them as incompatible
treatments of a single subject matter. He even occasionally accused classical
mathematics of inconsistency at the places where it differed from intuitionism.
This clash concerns the basic concept of what counts as a mathematical object.
Intuitionism allows, and classical mathematics rejects, objects that may be
indeterminate with respect to some of their properties. Logic and language.
Because he believed that mathematical constructions occur in prelinguistic
consciousness, Brouwer refused to limit mathematics by the expressive capacity
of any language. Logic, he claimed, merely codifies already completed stages of
mathematical reasoning. For instance, the principle of the excluded middle
stems from an “observational period” during which mankind catalogued finite phenomena
(with decidable properties); and he derided classical mathematics for
inappropriately applying this principle to infinitary aspects of mathematics.
Formalization. Brouwer’s views notwithstanding, in 1930 Heyting produced formal
systems for intuitionistic logic (IL) and number theory. These inspired further
formalizations (even of the theory of choice sequences) and a series of
proof-theoretic, semantic, and algebraic studies that related intuitionistic
and classical formal systems. Stephen Kleene, e.g., interpreted IL mathematical
intuitionism mathematical intuitionism 542 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page
542 mathematical logic Maxwell, James Clerk 543 and other intuitionistic formal
systems using the classical theory of recursive functions. Gödel, who showed
that IL cannot coincide with any finite many-valued logic, demonstrated its
relation to the modal logic, S4; and Kripke provided a formal semantics for IL
similar to the possible worlds semantics for S4. For a while the study of
intuitionistic formal systems used strongly classical methods, but since the
1970s intuitionistic methods have been employed as well. Meaning. Heyting’s
formalization reflected a theory of meaning implicit in Brouwer’s epistemology
and metaphysics, a theory that replaces the traditional correspondence notion
of truth with the notion of constructive proof. More recently Michael Dummett
has extended this to a warranted assertability theory of meaning for areas of
discourse outside of mathematics. He has shown how assertabilism provides a
strategy for combating realism about such things as physical objects, mental
objects, and the past. See also BROUWER, CHOICE SEQUENCE, PHILOSOPHY OF
MATHEMATICS, SET THEORY. C.J.P. mathematical logic. See FORMAL LOGIC.
mathematical space. See SPACE. mathematical structuralism, the view that the
subject of any branch of mathematics is a structure or structures. The slogan
is that mathematics is the science of structure. Define a “natural number
system” to be a countably infinite collection of objects with one designated
initial object and a successor relation that satisfies the principle of
mathematical induction. Examples of natural number systems are the Arabic
numerals and an infinite sequence of distinct moments of time. According to
structuralism, arithmetic is about the form or structure common to natural
number systems. Accordingly, a natural number is something like an office in an
organization or a place in a pattern. Similarly, real analysis is about the
real number structure, the form common to complete ordered fields. The
philosophical issues concerning structuralism concern the nature of structures
and their places. Since a structure is a one-over-many of sorts, it is
something like a universal. Structuralists have defended analogues of some of
the traditional positions on universals, such as realism and nominalism. See
also MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION, PEANO POSTULATES, PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS.
S.Sha. mathematics, philosophy of. See PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS. matrix
mechanics. See QUANTUM MECHANICS. matter. See METAPHYSICS. matter, prime. See
HYLOMORPHISM. matter, principle of the conservation of. See PHILOSOPHY OF
SCIENCE. maxim. See KANT. maximal consistent set, in formal logic, any set of
sentences S that is consistent – i.e., no contradiction is provable from S –
and maximally so – i.e., if T is consistent and S 0 T, then S % T. It can be
shown that if S is maximally consistent and s is a sentence in the same
language, then either s or - s (the negation of s) is in S. Thus, a maximally
consistent set is complete: it settles every question that can be raised in the
language. See also COMPLETENESS, SET THEORY. P.Mad. maximal proposition. See
TOPICS. maximin strategy, a strategy that maximizes an agent’s minimum gain, or
equivalently, minimizes his maximum loss. Writers who work in terms of loss
thus call such a strategy a minimax strategy. The term ‘security strategy’,
which avoids potential confusions, is now widely used. For each action, its
security level is its payoff under the worst-case scenario. A security strategy
is one with maximal security level. An agent’s security strategy maximizes his
expected utility if and only if (1) he is certain that “nature” has his worst
interests at heart and (2) he is certain that nature will be certain of his
strategy when choosing hers. The first condition is satisfied in the case of a
two-person zero-sum game where the payoff structure is commonly known. In this
situation, “nature” is the other player, and her gain is equal to the first
player’s loss. Obviously, these conditions do not hold for all decision
problems. See also DECISION THEORY, GAME THEORY. B.Sk. Maxwell, James Clerk
(1831–79), Scottish physicist who made pioneering contributions to the theory
of electromagnetism, the kinetic theory of gases, and the theory of color
vision. His work on electromagnetism is summarized in his Treatise on
Electricity and Magnetism (1873). In 1871 he 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM
Page 543 maya Mead, George Herbert 544 became Cambridge University’s first professor
of experimental physics and founded the Cavendish Laboratory, which he directed
until his death. Maxwell’s most important achievements were his field theory of
electromagnetism and the discovery of the equations that bear his name. The
field theory unified the laws of electricity and magnetism, identified light as
a transverse vibration of the electromagnetic ether, and predicted the
existence of radio waves. The fact that Maxwell’s equations are
Lorentz-invariant and contain the speed of light as a constant played a major
role in the genesis of the special theory of relativity. He arrived at his
theory by searching for a “consistent representation” of the ether, i.e., a
model of its inner workings consistent with the laws of mechanics. His search for
a consistent representation was unsuccessful, but his papers used mechanical
models and analogies to guide his thinking. Like Boltzmann, Maxwell advocated
the heuristic value of model building. Maxwell was also a pioneer in
statistical physics. His derivation of the laws governing the macroscopic
behavior of gases from assumptions about the random collisions of gas molecules
led directly to Boltzmann’s transport equation and the statistical analysis of
irreversibility. To show that the second law of thermodynamics is
probabilistic, Maxwell imagined a “neat-fingered” demon who could cause the
entropy of a gas to decrease by separating the faster-moving gas molecules from
the slower-moving ones. See also PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, RELATIVITY. M.C. maya,
a term with various uses in Indian thought; it expresses the concept of
Brahman’s power to act. One type of Brahmanic action is the assuming of
material forms whose appearance can be changed at will. Demons as well as gods
are said to have maya, understood as power to do things not within a standard
human repertoire. A deeper sense refers to the idea that Brahman has and
exercises the power to sustain everlastingly the entire world of conscious and
non-conscious things. Monotheistically conceived, maya is the power of an
omnipotent and omniscient deity to produce the world of dependent things. This
power typically is conceived as feminine (Sakti) and various representations of
the deity are conceived as male with female consorts, as with Vishnu and Siva.
Without Sakti, Brahman would be masculine and passive and no created world
would exist. By association, maya is the product of created activity. The
created world is conceived as dependent, both a manifestation of divine power
and a veil between Brahman and the devotee. Monistically conceived, maya
expresses the notion that there only seems to be a world composed of distinct
conscious and nonconscious things, and rather than this seeming multiplicity
there exists only ineffable Brahman. Brahman is conceived as somehow producing
the illusion of there being a plurality of persons and objects, and
enlightenment (moksha) is conceived as seeing through the illusion.
Monotheists, who ask who, on the monistic view, has the qualities requisite to
produce illusion and how an illusion can see through itself, regard
enlightenment (moksha) as a matter of devotion to the Brahman whom the created
universe partially manifests, but also veils, whose nature is also revealed in
religious experience. See also BRAHMAN. K.E.Y. Mead, George Herbert
(1863–1931), American philosopher, social theorist, and social reformer. He was
a member of the Chicago school of pragmatism, which included figures such as
James Hayden Tufts and John Dewey. Whitehead agreed with Dewey’s assessment of
Mead: “a seminal mind of the very first order.” Mead was raised in a household
with deep roots in New England puritanism, but he eventually became a confirmed
naturalist, convinced that modern science could make the processes of nature
intelligible. On his path to naturalism he studied with the idealist Josiah
Royce at Harvard. The German idealist tradition of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel
(who were portrayed by Mead as Romantic philosophers in Movements of Thought in
the Nineteenth Century) had a lasting influence on his thought, even though he
became a confirmed empiricist. Mead is considered the progenitor of the school
of symbolic interaction in sociology, and is best known for his explanation of
the genesis of the mind and the self in terms of language development and role
playing. A close friend of Jane Addams (1860–1935), he viewed his theoretical
work in this area as lending weight to his progressive political convictions.
Mead is often referred to as a social behaviorist. He employed the categories
of stimulus and response in order to explain behavior, but contra behaviorists
such as John B. Watson, Mead did not dismiss conduct that was not observed by
others. He examined the nature of self-consciousness, whose development is
depicted in Mind, Self, and Society, from the Standpoint of a Social
Behaviorist. He also addressed 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 544 behavior
in terms of the phases of an organism’s adjustment to its environment in The
Philosophy of the Act. His reputation as a theorist of the social development
of the self has tended to eclipse his original work in other areas of concern
to philosophers, e.g., ethics, epistemology, metaphysics, and the philosophy of
science. Influenced by Darwin, Mead sought to understand nature, as well as
social relationships, in terms of the process of emergence. He emphasized that
qualitatively new forms of life arise through natural and intelligible
processes. When novel events occur the past is transformed, for the past has
now given rise to the qualitatively new, and it must be seen from a different
perspective. Between the arrival of the new order – which the novel event
instigates – and the old order, there is a phase of readjustment, a stage that
Mead describes as one of sociality. Mead’s views on these and related matters
are discussed in The Philosophy of the Present. Mead never published a
book-length work in philosophy. His unpublished manuscripts and students’ notes
were edited and published as the books cited above. See also PHILOSOPHY OF THE
SOCIAL SCIENCES, PRAGMATISM. M.Ab. mean, doctrine of the. See ARISTOTLE,
CHUNG-YUNG. meaning, the conventional, common, or standard sense of an
expression, construction, or sentence in a given language, or of a
non-linguistic signal or symbol. Literal meaning is the non-figurative, strict
meaning an expression or sentence has in a language by virtue of the dictionary
meaning of its words and the import of its syntactic constructions. Synonymy is
sameness of literal meaning: ‘prestidigitator’ means ‘expert at sleight of hand’.
It is said that meaning is what a good translation preserves, and this may or
may not be literal: in French ‘Où sont les neiges d’antan?’ literally means
‘Where are the snows of yesteryear?’ and figuratively means ‘nothing lasts’.
Signal-types and symbols have non-linguistic conventional meaning: the white
flag means truce; the lion means St. Mark. In another sense, meaning is what a
person intends to communicate by a particular utterance – utterer’s meaning, as
Grice called it, or speaker’s meaning, in Stephen Schiffer’s term. A speaker’s
meaning may or may not coincide with the literal meaning of what is uttered,
and it may be non-linguistic. Non-literal: in saying “we will soon be in our
tropical paradise,” Jane meant that they would soon be in Antarctica. Literal:
in saying “that’s deciduous,” she meant that the tree loses its leaves every
year. Non-linguistic: by shrugging, she meant that she agreed. The literal
meaning of a sentence typically does not determine exactly what a speaker says
in making a literal utterance: the meaning of ‘she is praising me’ leaves open
what John says in uttering it, e.g. that Jane praises John at 12:00 p.m., Dec.
21, 1991. A not uncommon – but theoretically loaded – way of accommodating this
is to count the context-specific things that speakers say as propositions,
entities that can be expressed in different languages and that are (on certain
theories) the content of what is said, believed, desired, and so on. On that
assumption, a sentence’s literal meaning is a context-independent rule, or
function, that determines a certain proposition (the content of what the
speaker says) given the context of utterance. David Kaplan has called such a
rule or function a sentence’s “character.” A sentence’s literal meaning also
includes its potential for performing certain illocutionary acts, in J. L.
Austin’s term. The meaning of an imperative sentence determines what orders,
requests, and the like can literally be expressed: ‘sit down there’ can be
uttered literally by Jane to request (or order or urge) John to sit down at
11:59 a.m. on a certain bench in Santa Monica. Thus a sentence’s literal
meaning involves both its character and a constraint on illocutionary acts: it
maps contexts onto illocutionary acts that have (something like) determinate
propositional contents. A context includes the identity of speaker, hearer,
time of utterance, and also aspects of the speaker’s intentions. In ethics the
distinction has flourished between the expressive or emotive meaning of a word
or sentence and its cognitive meaning. The emotive meaning of an utterance or a
term is the attitude it expresses, the pejorative meaning of ‘chiseler’, say.
An emotivist in ethics, e.g. C. L. Stevenson (1908–79), holds that the literal
meaning of ‘it is good’ is identical with its emotive meaning, the positive
attitude it expresses. On Hare’s theory, the literal meaning of ‘ought’ is its
prescriptive meaning, the imperative force it gives to certain sentences that
contain it. Such “noncognitivist” theories can allow that a term like ‘good’
also has non-literal descriptive meaning, implying nonevaluative properties of
an object. By contrast, cognitivists take the literal meaning of an ethical
term to be its cognitive meaning: ‘good’ stands for an objective property, and
in asserting “it is good” one literally expresses, not an attitude, but a true
or false judgment. mean, doctrine of the meaning 545 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999
7:42 AM Page 545 ’Cognitive meaning’ serves as well as any other term to
capture what has been central in the theory of meaning beyond ethics, the
“factual” element in meaning that remains when we abstract from its
illocutionary and emotive aspects. It is what is shared by ‘there will be an
eclipse tomorrow’ and ‘will there be an eclipse tomorrow?’. This common element
is often identified with a proposition (or a “character”), but, once again,
that is theoretically loaded. Although cognitive meaning has been the
preoccupation of the theory of meaning in the twentieth century, it is
difficult to define precisely in non-theoretical terms. Suppose we say that the
cognitive meaning of a sentence is ‘that aspect of its meaning which is capable
of being true or false’: there are non-truth-conditional theories of meaning
(see below) on which this would not capture the essentials. Suppose we say it
is ‘what is capable of being asserted’: an emotivist might allow that one can
assert that a thing is good. Still many philosophers have taken for granted
that they know cognitive meaning (under that name or not) well enough to
theorize about what it consists in, and it is the focus of what follows. The
oldest theories of meaning in modern philosophy are the
seventeenth-to-nineteenth-century idea theory (also called the ideational
theory) and image theory of meaning, according to which the meaning of words in
public language derives from the ideas or mental images that words are used to
express. As for what constitutes the representational properties of ideas,
Descartes held it to be a basic property of the mind, inexplicable, and Locke a
matter of resemblance (in some sense) between ideas and things. Contemporary
analytic philosophy speaks more of propositional attitudes – thoughts, beliefs,
intentions – than of ideas and images; and it speaks of the contents of such attitudes:
if Jane believes that there are lions in Africa, that belief has as its content
that there are lions in Africa. Virtually all philosophers agree that
propositional attitudes have some crucial connection with meaning. A
fundamental element of a theory of meaning is where it locates the basis of
meaning, in thought, in individual speech, or in social practices. (i) Meaning
may be held to derive entirely from the content of thoughts or propositional
attitudes, that mental content itself being constituted independently of public
linguistic meaning. (‘Constituted independently of’ does not imply ‘unshaped
by’.) (ii) It may be held that the contents of beliefs and communicative
intentions themselves derive in part from the meaning of overt speech, or even
from social practices. Then meaning would be jointly constituted by both
individual psychological and social linguistic facts. Theories of the first
sort include those in the style of Grice, according to which sentences’
meanings are determined by practices or implicit conventions that govern what
speakers mean when they use the relevant words and constructions. A speaker’s
meaning is explained in terms of certain propositional attitudes, namely the
speaker’s intentions to produce certain effects in hearers. To mean that it is
raining is to utter or to do something (not necessarily linguistic) with the
intention (very roughly) of getting one’s hearer to believe that it is raining.
Theories of speaker’s meaning have been elaborated by Grice and by Schiffer.
David Lewis has proposed that linguistic meaning is constituted by implicit
conventions that systematically associate sentences with speakers’ beliefs
rather than with communicative intentions. The contents of thought might be
held to be constitutive of linguistic meaning independently of communication.
Russell, and Wittgenstein in his early writings, wrote about meaning as if the
key thing is the propositional content of the belief or thought that a sentence
(somehow) expresses; they apparently regarded this as holding on an individual
basis and not essentially as deriving from communication intentions or social
practices. And Chomsky speaks of the point of language as being “the free
expression of thought.” Such views suggest that ‘linguistic meaning’ may stand
for two properties, one involving communication intentions and practices, the
other more intimately related to thinking and conceiving. By contrast, the
content of propositional attitudes and the meaning of overt speech might be
regarded as coordinate facts neither of which can obtain independently: to
interpret other people one must assign both content to their beliefs/intentions
and meaning to their utterances. This is explicit in Davidson’s
truth-conditional theory (see below); perhaps it is present also in the
post-Wittgensteinian notion of meaning as assertability conditions – e.g., in
the writings of Dummett. On still other accounts, linguistic meaning is
essentially social. Wittgenstein is interpreted by Kripke as holding in his
later writings that social rules are essential to meaning, on the grounds that
they alone explain the normative aspect of meaning, explain the fact that an
expression’s meaning determines that some uses are correct or others incorrect.
Another way in which meaning meaning 546 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page
546 meaning may be essentially social is Putnam’s “division of linguistic
labor”: the meanings of some terms, say in botany or cabinetmaking, are set for
the rest of us by specialists. The point might extend to quite non-technical
words, like ‘red’: a person’s use of it may be socially deferential, in that
the rule which determines what ‘red’ means in his mouth is determined, not by
his individual usage, but by the usage of some social group to which he
semantically defers. This has been argued by Tyler Burge to imply that the
contents of thoughts themselves are in part a matter of social facts. Let us
suppose there is a language L that contains no indexical terms, such as ‘now’,
‘I’, or demonstrative pronouns, but contains only proper names, common nouns,
adjectives, verbs, adverbs, logical words. (No natural language is like this;
but the supposition simplifies what follows.) Theories of meaning differ
considerably in how they would specify the meaning of a sentence S of L. Here
are the main contenders. (i) Specify S’s truth conditions: S is true if and
only if some swans are black. (ii) Specify the proposition that S expresses: S
means (the proposition) that some swans are black. (iii) Specify S’s
assertability conditions: S is assertable if and only if blackswan-sightings
occur or black-swan-reports come in, etc. (iv) Translate S into that sentence
of our language which has the same use as S or the same conceptual role.
Certain theories, especially those that specify meanings in ways (i) and (ii),
take the compositionality of meaning as basic. Here is an elementary fact: a
sentence’s meaning is a function of the meanings of its component words and
constructions, and as a result we can utter and understand new sentences – old
words and constructions, new sentences. Frege’s theory of Bedeutung or
reference, especially his use of the notions of function and object, is about
compositionality. In the Tractatus, Wittgenstein explains compositionality in
his picture theory of meaning and theory of truth-functions. According to
Wittgenstein, a sentence or proposition is a picture of a (possible) state of
affairs; terms correspond to non-linguistic elements, and those terms’
arrangements in sentences have the same form as arrangements of elements in the
states of affairs the sentences stand for. The leading truth-conditional theory
of meaning is the one advocated by Davidson, drawing on the work of Tarski.
Tarski showed that, for certain formalized languages, we can construct a finite
set of rules that entails, for each sentence S of the infinitely many sentences
of such a language, something of the form ‘S is true if and only if . . .’.
Those finitely statable rules, which taken together are sometimes called a
truth theory of the language, might entail ‘ “(x) (Rx P Bx)” is true if and
only if every raven is black’. They would do this by having separately assigned
interpretations to ‘R’, ‘B’, ‘P’, and ‘(x)’. Truth conditions are
compositionally determined in analogous ways for sentences, however complex.
Davidson proposes that Tarski’s device is applicable to natural languages and
that it explains, moreover, what meaning is, given the following setting.
Interpretation involves a principle of charity: interpreting a person N means making
the best possible sense of N, and this means assigning meanings so as to
maximize the overall truth of N’s utterances. A systematic interpretation of
N’s language can be taken to be a Tarski-style truth theory that (roughly)
maximizes the truth of N’s utterances. If such a truth theory implies that a
sentence S is true in N’s language if and only if some swans are black, then
that tells us the meaning of S in N’s language. A propositional theory of
meaning would accommodate compositionality thus: a finite set of rules, which
govern the terms and constructions of L, assigns (derivatively) a proposition
(putting aside ambiguity) to each sentence S of L by virtue of S’s terms and
constructions. If L contains indexicals, then such rules assign to each sentence
not a fully specific proposition but a ‘character’ in the above sense.
Propositions may be conceived in two ways: (a) as sets of possible
circumstances or “worlds” – then ‘Hesperus is hot’ in English is assigned the
set of possible worlds in which Hesperus is hot; and (b) as structured
combinations of elements – then ‘Hesperus is hot’ is assigned a certain ordered
pair of elements ‹M1,M2(. There are two theories about M1 and M2. They may be
the senses of ‘Hesperus’ and ‘(is) hot’, and then the ordered pair is a
“Fregean” proposition. They may be the references of ‘Hesperus’ and ‘(is) hot’,
and then the ordered pair is a “Russellian” proposition. This difference
reflects a fundamental dispute in twentieth-century philosophy of language. The
connotation or sense of a term is its “mode of presentation,” the way it
presents its denotation or reference. Terms with the same reference or
denotation may present their references differently and so differ in sense or
connotation. This is unproblematic for complex terms like ‘the capital of
Italy’ and ‘the city on the Tiber’, which refer to Rome via different
connotations. Controversy arises over simple terms, such as proper meaning
meaning 547 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 547 names and common nouns.
Frege distinguished sense and reference for all expressions; the proper names
‘Phosphorus’ and ‘Hesperus’ express descriptive senses according to how we
understand them – [that bright starlike object visible before dawn in the
eastern sky . . .], [that bright starlike object visible after sunset in the
western sky . . .]; and they refer to Venus by virtue of those senses. Russell
held that ordinary proper names, such as ‘Romulus’, abbreviate definite
descriptions, and in this respect his view resembles Frege’s. But Russell also
held that, for those simple terms (not ‘Romulus’) into which statements are
analyzable, sense and reference are not distinct, and meanings are “Russellian”
propositions. (But Russell’s view of their constituents differs from
present-day views.) Kripke rejected the “Frege-Russell” view of ordinary proper
names, arguing that the reference of a proper name is determined, not by a
descriptive condition, but typically by a causal chain that links name and
reference – in the case of ‘Hesperus’ a partially perceptual relation perhaps,
in the case of ‘Aristotle’ a causal-historical relation. A proper name is
rather a rigid designator: any sentence of the form ‘Aristotle is . . . ‘
expresses a proposition that is true in a given possible world (or set of
circumstances) if and only if our (actual) Aristotle satisfies, in that world,
the condition ‘ . . . ‘. The “Frege-Russell” view by contrast incorporates in
the proposition, not the actual referent, but a descriptive condition
connotated by ‘Aristotle’ (the author of the Metaphysics, or the like), so that
the name’s reference differs in different worlds even when the descriptive
connotation is constant. (Someone else could have written the Metaphysics.)
Some recent philosophers have taken the rigid designator view to motivate the
stark thesis that meanings are Russellian propositions (or characters that map
contexts onto such propositions): in the above proposition/meaning ‹M1,M2(, M1
is simply the referent – the planet Venus – itself. This would be a referential
theory of meaning, one that equates meaning with reference. But we must
emphasize that the rigid designator view does not directly entail a referential
theory of meaning. What about the meanings of predicates? What sort of entity
is M2 above? Putnam and Kripke also argue an anti-descriptive point about
natural kind terms, predicates like ‘(is) gold’, ‘(is a) tiger’, ‘(is) hot’.
These are not equivalent to descriptions – ’gold’ does not mean ‘metal that is
yellow, malleable, etc.’ – but are rigid designators of underlying natural
kinds whose identities are discovered by science. On a referential theory of
meanings as Russellian propositions, the meaning of ‘gold’ is then a natural
kind. (A complication arises: the property or kind that ‘widow’ stands for
seems a good candidate for being the sense or connotation of ‘widow’, for what
one understands by it. The distinction between Russellian and Fregean
propositions is not then firm at every point.) On the standard sense-theory of
meanings as Fregean propositions, M1 and M2 are pure descriptive senses. But a
certain “neo-Fregean” view, suggested but not held by Gareth Evans, would count
M1 and M2 as object-dependent senses. For example, ‘Hesperus’ and ‘Phosphorus’
would rigidly designate the same object but have distinct senses that cannot be
specified without mention of that object. Note that, if proper names or natural
kind terms have meanings of either sort, their meanings vary from speaker to
speaker. A propositional account of meaning (or the corresponding account of
“character”) may be part of a broader theory of meaning; for example: (a) a
Grice-type theory involving implicit conventions; (b) a theory that meaning
derives from an intimate connection of language and thought; (c) a theory that
invokes a principle of charity or the like in interpreting an individual’s
speech; (d) a social theory on which meaning cannot derive entirely from the
independently constituted contents of individuals’ thoughts or uses. A central
tradition in twentieth-century theory of meaning identifies meaning with
factors other than propositions (in the foregoing senses) and truth-conditions.
The meaning of a sentence is what one understands by it; and understanding a
sentence is knowing how to use it – knowing how to verify it and when to assert
it, or being able to think with it and to use it in inferences and practical
reasoning. There are competing theories here. In the 1930s, proponents of
logical positivism held a verification theory of meaning, whereby a sentence’s
or statement’s meaning consists in the conditions under which it can be
verified, certified as acceptable. This was motivated by the positivists’
empiricism together with their view of truth as a metaphysical or non-empirical
notion. A descendant of verificationism is the thesis, influenced by the later
Wittgenstein, that the meaning of a sentence consists in its assertability
conditions, the circumstances under which one is justified in asserting the
sentence. If justification and truth can diverge, as they appear to, then a
meaning meaning 548 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 548 sentence’s
assertability conditions can be distinct from (what non-verificationists see
as) its truth conditions. Dummett has argued that assertability conditions are
the basis of meaning and that truth-conditional semantics rests on a mistake
(and hence also propositional semantics in sense [a] above). A problem with
assertability theories is that, as is generally acknowledged, compositional
theories of the assertability conditions of sentences are not easily
constructed. A conceptual role theory of meaning (also called conceptual role
semantics) typically presupposes that we think in a language of thought (an
idea championed by Fodor), a system of internal states structured like a language
that may or may not be closely related to one’s natural language. The
conceptual role of a term is a matter of how thoughts that contain the term are
dispositionally related to other thoughts, to sensory states, and to behavior.
Hartry Field has pointed out that our Fregean intuitions about ‘Hesperus’ and
‘Phosphorus’ are explained by those terms’ having distinct conceptual roles,
without appeal to Fregean descriptive senses or the like, and that this is
compatible with those terms’ rigidly designating the same object. This
combination can be articulated in two ways. Gilbert Harman proposes that
meaning is “wide” conceptual role, so that conceptual role incorporates not
just inferential factors, etc., but also Kripke-Putnam external reference
relations. But there are also two-factor theories of meaning, as proposed by
Field among others, which recognize two strata of meaning, one corresponding to
how a person understands a term – its narrow conceptual role, the other
involving references, Russellian propositions, or truth-conditions. As the
language-of-thought view indicates, some concerns about meaning have been taken
over by theories of the content of thoughts or propositional attitudes. A
distinction is often made between the narrow content of a thought and its wide
content. If psychological explanation invokes only “what is in the head,” and
if thought contents are essential to psychological explanation, there must be
narrow content. Theories have appealed to the “syntax” or conceptual roles or
“characters” of internal sentences, as well as to images and stereotypes. A
thought’s wide content may then be regarded (as motivated by the Kripke-Putnam
arguments) as a Russellian proposition. The naturalistic reference-relations
that determine the elements of such propositions are the focus of causal,
“informational” and “teleological” theories by Fodor, Dretske, and Ruth
Millikan. Assertability theories and conceptual role theories have been called
use theories of meaning in a broad sense that marks a contrast with
truthconditional theories. On a use theory in this broad sense, understanding
meaning consists in knowing how to use a term or sentence, or being disposed to
use a term or sentence in response to certain external or conceptual factors.
But ‘use theory’ also refers to the doctrine of the later writings of
Wittgenstein, by whom theories of meaning that abstract from the very large
variety of interpersonal uses of language are declared a philosopher’s mistake.
The meanings of terms and sentences are a matter of the language games in which
they play roles; these are too various to have a common structure that can be
captured in a philosopher’s theory of meaning. Conceptual role theories tend
toward meaning holism, the thesis that a term’s meaning cannot be abstracted
from the entirety of its conceptual connections. On a holistic view any belief
or inferential connection involving a term is as much a candidate for
determining its meaning as any other. This could be avoided by affirming the
analytic–synthetic distinction, according to which some of a term’s conceptual
connections are constitutive of its meaning and others only incidental.
(‘Bachelors are unmarried’ versus ‘Bachelors have a tax advantage’.) But many
philosophers follow Quine in his skepticism about that distinction. The
implications of holism are drastic, for it strictly implies that different
people’s words cannot mean the same. In the philosophy of science, meaning
holism has been held to imply the incommensurability of theories, according to
which a scientific theory that replaces an earlier theory cannot be held to
contradict it and hence not to correct or to improve on it – for the two
theories’ apparently common terms would be equivocal. Remedies might include,
again, maintaining some sort of analytic–synthetic distinction for scientific
terms, or holding that conceptual role theories and hence holism itself, as
Field proposes, hold only intrapersonally, while taking interpersonal and
intertheoretic meaning comparisons to be referential and truth-conditional.
Even this, however, leads to difficult questions about the interpretation of
scientific theories. A radical position, associated with Quine, identifies the
meaning of a theory as a whole with its empirical meaning, that is, the set of actual
and possible sensory or perceptual situations that would count as verifying the
theory as a whole. This can be seen as a successor to the verificationist
theory, with theory replacing statement or sentence. Articulations of meaning
meaning meaning 549 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 549 internal to a
theory would then be spurious, as would virtually all ordinary intuitions about
meaning. This fits well Quine’s skepticism about meaning, his thesis of the
indeterminacy of translation, according to which no objective facts distinguish
a favored translation of another language into ours from every apparently
incorrect translation. Many constructive theories of meaning may be seen as
replies to this and other skepticisms about the objective status of semantic
facts. See also FORMAL SEMANTICS, PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND,
SEMANTIC HOLISM, SPEECH ACT THEORY, VERIFICATIONISM. B.L. meaning, conceptual
role theory of. See MEANING. meaning, descriptive. See EMOTIVISM, MEANING.
meaning, dispositional theory of. See MEANING. meaning, emotive. See EMOTIVISM,
MEANING. meaning, focal. See ARISTOTLE. meaning, idea theory of. See MEANING.
meaning, ideational theory of. See PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE. meaning, image
theory of. See MEANING. meaning, picture theory of. See MEANING, WITTGENSTEIN.
meaning, referential theory of. See MEANING, PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE. meaning,
speaker’s. See MEANING. meaning, truth-conditional theory of. See MEANING.
meaning, use theory of. See MEANING, PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE. meaning,
verifiability theory of. See MEANING, PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE, VERIFICATIONISM.
meaning holism. See HOLISM. meaning postulate, a sentence that specifies part
or all of the meaning of a predicate. Meaning postulates would thus include
explicit, contextual, and recursive definitions, reduction sentences for
dispositional predicates, and, more generally, any sentences stating how the
extensions of predicates are interrelated by virtue of the meanings of those
predicates. For example, any reduction sentence of the form (x) (x has f / (x
is malleable S x has y)) could be a meaning postulate for the predicate ‘is
malleable’. The notion of a meaning postulate was introduced by Carnap, whose
original interest stemmed from a desire to explicate sentences that are
analytic (“true by virtue of meaning”) but not logically true. Where G is a set
of such postulates, one could say that A is analytic with respect to G if and
only if A is a logical consequence of G. On this account, e.g., the sentence
‘Jake is not a married bachelor’ is analytic with respect to {’All bachelors
are unmarried’}. See also ANALYTIC– SYNTHETIC DISTINCTION, MEANING, REDUCTION
SENTENCE. G.F.S. measurement. See MAGNITUDE. measurement, theory of. See
MAGNITUDE. mechanical jurisprudence. See JURISPRUDENCE. mechanism, logical. See
COMPUTER THEORY. mechanistic explanation, a kind of explanation countenanced by
views that range from the extreme position that all natural phenomena can be
explained entirely in terms of masses in motion of the sort postulated in
Newtonian mechanics, to little more than a commitment to naturalistic
explanations. Mechanism in its extreme form is clearly false because numerous
physical phenomena of the most ordinary sort cannot be explained entirely in
terms of masses in motion. Mechanics is only one small part of physics.
Historically, explanations were designated as mechanistic to indicate that they
included no reference to final causes or vital forces. In this weak sense, all
present-day scientific explanations are mechanistic. The adequacy of
mechanistic explanation is usually raised in connection with living creatures,
especially those capable of deliberate action. For example, chromosomes lining
up opposite their partners in preparation for meiosis looks like anything but a
purely mechanical process, and yet the more we discover about the process, the
more mechanistic it turns out to be. The mechanisms responsible for meiosis
arose through variation and selection and cannot be totally understood without
reference to the evolutionary process, but meiosis as it takes place at any one
time appears to be a purely mechanistic physicochemical meaning, conceptual
role theory of mechanistic explanation 550 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page
550 process. Intentional behavior is the phenomenon that is most resistant to
explanation entirely in physicochemical terms. The problem is not that we do
not know enough about the functioning of the central nervous system but that no
matter how it turns out to work, we will be disinclined to explain human action
entirely in terms of physicochemical processes. The justification for this
disinclination tends to turn on what we mean when we describe people as
behaving intentionally. Even so, we may simply be mistaken to ascribe more to
human action than can be explained in terms of purely physicochemical
processes. See also BEHAVIORISM, EXPLANATION, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. D.L.H.
mediate inference. See INFERENCE. medical ethics. See ETHICS.
Medina, Bartolomeo
(1527–80), Spanish Dominican theologian who taught theology at Alcalá and then
at Salamanca. His major works are commentaries on Aquinas’s Summa theologica.
Medina is often called the father of probabilism but scholars disagree on the
legitimacy of this attribution. Support for it is contained in Medina’s
commentary on Aquinas’s Prima secundae (1577). Medina denies that it is
sufficient for an opinion to be probable that there are apparent reasons in its
favor and that it is supported by many people. For then all errors would be
probable. Rather, an opinion is probable if it can be followed without censure
and reproof, as when wise persons state and support it with excellent reasons.
Medina suggests the use of these criteria in decisions concerning moral
dilemmas (Suma de casos morales [“Summa of Moral Questions”], 1580). P.Gar.
Megarians, also called Megarics, a loose-knit group of Greek philosophers
active in the fourth and early third centuries B.C., whose work in logic
profoundly influenced the course of ancient philosophy. The name derives from
that of Megara, the hometown of Euclid (died c.365 B.C.; unrelated to the later
mathematician), who was an avid companion of Socrates and author of (lost)
Socratic dialogues. Little is recorded about his views, and his legacy rests
with his philosophical heirs. Most prominent of these was Eubulides, a
contemporary and critic of Aristotle; he devised a host of logical paradoxes,
including the liar and the sorites or heap paradoxes. To many this ingenuity
seemed sheer eristic, a label some applied to him. One of his associates,
Alexinus, was a leading critic of Zeno, the founder of Stoicism, whose
arguments he twitted in incisive parodies. Stilpo (c.380–c.300 B.C.), a native
of Megara, was also famous for disputation but best known for his apatheia
(impassivity). Rivaling the Cynics as a preacher of self-reliance, he once
insisted, after his city and home were plundered, that he lost nothing of his
own since he retained his knowledge and virtue. Zeno the Stoic was one of many
followers he attracted. Most brilliant of the Megarians was Diodorus, nicknamed
Cronus or “Old Fogey” (fl. 300 B.C.), who had an enormous impact on Stoicism
and the skeptical Academy. Among the first explorers of propositional logic, he
and his associates were called “the dialecticians,” a label that referred not
to an organized school or set of doctrines but simply to their highly original
forms of reasoning. Diodorus defined the possible narrowly as what either is or
will be true, and the necessary broadly as what is true and will not be false.
Against his associate Philo, the first proponent of material implication, he
maintained that a conditional is true if and only if it is neverthe case that
its antecedent is true and its consequent false. He argued that matter is
atomic and that time and motion are likewise discrete. With an exhibitionist’s
flair, he demonstrated that meaning is conventional by naming his servants
“But” and “However.” Most celebrated is his Master (or Ruling) Argument, which
turns on three propositions: (1) Every truth about the past is necessary; (2)
nothing impossible follows from something possible; and (3) some things are
possible that neither are nor will be true. His aim was apparently to establish
his definition of possibility by showing that its negation in (3) is
inconsistent with (1) and (2), which he regarded as obvious. Various Stoics,
objecting to the implication of determinism here, sought to uphold a wider form
of possibility by overturning (1) or (2). Diodorus’s fame made him a target of
satire by eminent poets, and it is said that he expired from shame after
failing to solve on the spot a puzzle Stilpo posed at a party. See also
ACADEMY, ARISTOTLE, CYNICS, SOCRATES, SORITES PARADOX, STOICISM. S.A.W.
Meinong, Alexius (1853–1920), Austrian philosopher and psychologist, founder of
Gegenstandstheorie, the theory of (existent and nonexistent intended) objects.
He was the target of Russell’s criticisms of the idea of non-existent objects
in his landmark essay “On Denoting” (1905). mediate inference Meinong, Alexius
551 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 551 Meinong, after eight years at the
Vienna Gymnasium, enrolled in the University of Vienna in 1870, studying German
philology and history and completing a dissertation (1874) on Arnold von
Brescia. After this period he became interested in philosophy as a result of
his critical selfdirected reading of Kant. At the suggestion of his teacher
Franz Brentano, he undertook a systematic investigation of Hume’s empiricism,
culminating in his first publications in philosophy, the Hume-Studien I, II
(1878 and 1882). In 1882, Meinong was appointed Professor Extraordinarius at
the University of Graz (receiving promotion to Ordinarius in 1889), where he
remained until his death. At Graz he established the first laboratory for
experimental psychology in Austria, and was occupied with psychological as well
as philosophical problems throughout his career. The Graz school of
phenomenological psychology and philosophical semantics, which centered on
Meinong and his students, made important contributions to object theory in
philosophical semantics, metaphysics, ontology, value theory, epistemology,
theory of evidence, possibility and probability, and the analysis of emotion,
imagination, and abstraction. Meinong’s object theory is based on a version of
Brentano’s immanent intentionality thesis, that every psychological state
contains an intended object toward which the mental event (or, in a less common
terminology, a mental act) is semantically directed. Meinong, however, rejects
Brentano’s early view of the immanence of the intentional, maintaining that
thought is directed toward transcendent mind-independent existent or
non-existent objects. Meinong distinguishes between judgments about the being
(Sein) of intended objects of thought, and judgments about their “so-being,”
character, or nature (Sosein). He claims that every thought is intentionally
directed toward the transcendent mind-independent object the thought purports
to be “about,” which entails that in at least some cases contingently
non-existent and even impossible objects, for instance Berkeley’s golden
mountain and the round square, must be included as non-existent intended
objects in the object theory semantic domain. Meinong further maintains that an
intended object’s Sosein is independent of its Sein or ontological status, of
whether or not the object happens to exist. This means, contrary to what many
philosophers have supposed, that non-existent objects can truly possess the
constitutive properties predicated of them in thought. Meinong’s object theory
evolved over a period of years, and underwent many additions and revisions. In
its mature form, the theory includes the following principles: (1) Thought can
freely (even if falsely) assume the existence of any describable object
(principle of unrestricted free assumption, or unbeschränkten Annahmefreiheit
thesis); (2) Every thought is intentionally directed toward a transcendent,
mind-independent intended object (modified intentionality thesis); (3) Every
intended object has a nature, character, Sosein, “how-it-is,” “so-being,” or
“being thus-and-so,” regardless of its ontological status (independence of
Sosein from Sein thesis); (4) Being or non-being is not part of the Sosein of
any intended object, nor of an object considered in itself (indifference
thesis, or doctrine of the Aussersein of the homeless pure object); (5) There
are two modes of being or Sein for intended objects: (a) spatiotemporal
existence and (b) Platonic subsistence (Existenz/Bestand thesis); (6) There are
some intended objects that do not have Sein at all, but neither exist nor
subsist (objects of which it is true that there are no such objects). Object
theory, unlike extensionalist semantics, makes it possible, as in much of
ordinary and scientific thought and language, to refer to and truly predicate
properties of non-existent objects. There are many misconceptions about
Meinong’s theory, such as that reflected in the objection that Meinong is a
super-Platonist who inflates ontology with non-existent objects that
nevertheless have being in some sense, that object theory tolerates outright
logical inconsistency rather than mere incompatibility of properties in the
Soseine of impossible intended objects. Russell, in his reviews of Meinong’s
theory in 1904–05, raises the problem of the existent round square, which seems
to be existent by virtue of the independence of Sosein from Sein, and to be
non-existent by virtue of being globally and simultaneously both round and
square. Meinong’s response involves several complex distinctions, but it has
been observed that to avoid the difficulty he need only appeal to the
distinction between konstitutorisch or nuclear and ausserkonstitutorisch or
extranuclear properties, adopted from a suggestion by his student Ernst Mally
(1878–1944), according to which only ordinary nuclear properties like being
red, round, or ten centimeters tall are part of the Sosein of any object, to
the exclusion of categorical or extranuclear properties like being existent,
determinate, possible, or impossible. This avoids counterexamples like the
existent round square, because it limits the independence of Sosein from Sein
exclusively to nuclear properties, Meinong, Alexius Meinong, Alexius 552
4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 552 implying that neither the existent nor
the nonexistent round square can possibly have the (extranuclear) property of
being existent or nonexistent in their respective Soseine, and cannot be said
truly to have the properties of being existent or non-existent merely by free
assumption and the independence of Sosein from Sein. See also BRENTANO,
EXTENSIONALISM, FORMAL SEMANTICS, INTENTIONALITY, METAPHYSICS. D.J. Meister
Eckhart. See ECKHART. Melanchthon, Philip. See SYNERGISM. meliorism (from Latin
melior, ‘better’), the view that the world is neither completely good nor
completely bad, and that incremental progress or regress depend on human
actions. By creative intelligence and education we can improve the environment
and social conditions. The position is first attributed to George Eliot and
William James. Whitehead suggested that meliorism applies to God, who can both
improve the world and draw sustenance from human efforts to improve the world.
See also JAMES, WHITEHEAD. L.P.P. Melissus of Samos (fl. mid-fifth century
B.C.), Greek philosopher, traditionally classified as a member of the Eleatic
School. He was also famous as the victorious commander in a preemptive attack
by the Samians on an Athenian naval force (441 B.C.). Like Parmenides – who
must have influenced Melissus, even though there is no evidence the two ever
met – Melissus argues that “what-is” or “the real” cannot come into being out
of nothing, cannot perish into nothing, is homogeneous, and is unchanging.
Indeed, he argues explicitly (whereas Parmenides only implies) that there is
only one such entity, that there is no void, and that even spatial
rearrangement (metakosmesis) must be ruled out. But unlike Parmenides, Melissus
deduces that what-is is temporally infinite (in significant contrast to Parmenides,
regardless as to whether the latter held that what-is exists strictly in the
“now” or that it exists non-temporally). Moreover, Melissus argues that what-is
is spatially infinite (whereas Parmenides spoke of “bounds” and compared
what-is to a well-made ball). Significantly, Melissus repeatedly speaks of “the
One.” It is, then, in Melissus, more than in Parmenides or in Zeno, that we
find the emphasis on monism. In a corollary to his main argument, Melissus
argues that “if there were many things,” each would have to be – per
impossibile – exactly like “the One.” This remark has been interpreted as
issuing the challenge that was taken up by the atomists. But it is more
reasonable to read it as a philosophical strategist’s preemptive strike:
Melissus anticipates the move made in the pluralist systems of the second half
of the fifth century, viz., positing a plurality of eternal and unchanging
elements that undergo only spatial rearrangement. See also ELEATIC SCHOOL,
PARMENIDES, PRE-SOCRATICS. A.P.D.M. memory, the retention of, or the capacity
to retain, past experience or previously acquired information. There are two
main philosophical questions about memory: (1) In what does memory consist? and
(2) What constitutes knowing a fact on the basis of memory? Not all memory is
remembering facts: there is remembering one’s perceiving or feeling or acting
in a certain way – which, while it entails remembering the fact that one did
experience in that way, must be more than that. And not all remembering of
facts is knowledge of facts: an extremely hesitant attempt to remember an
address, if one gets it right, counts as remembering the address even if one is
too uncertain for this to count as knowing it. (1) Answers to the first
question agree on some obvious points: that memory requires (a) a present and
(b) a past state of, or event in, the subject, and (c) the right sort of
internal and causal relations between the two. Also, we must distinguish
between memory states (remembering for many years the name of one’s first-grade
teacher) and memory occurrences (recalling the name when asked). A memory state
is usually taken to be a disposition to display an appropriate memory
occurrence given a suitable stimulus. But philosophers disagree about further
specifics. On one theory (held by many empiricists from Hume to Russell, among
others, but now largely discredited), occurrent memory consists in images of
past experience (which have a special quality marking them as memory images)
and that memory of facts is read off such image memory. This overlooks the
point that people commonly remember facts without remembering when or how they
learned them. A more sophisticated theory of factual memory (popular nowadays)
holds that an occurrent memory of a fact requires, besides a past learning of
it, (i) some sort of present mental representation of it (perhaps a linguistic
one) and (ii) continuous storage between then and now of a representation of
it. But condition (i) may not be Meister Eckhart memory 553 4065m-r.qxd
08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 553 conceptually necessary: a disposition to dial the
right number when one wants to call home constitutes remembering the number
(provided it is appropriately linked causally to past learning of the number)
and manifesting that disposition is occurrently remembering the fact as to what
the number is even if one does not in the process mentally represent that fact.
Condition (ii) may also be too strong: it seems at least conceptually possible
that a causal link sufficient for memory should be secured by a relation that
does not involve anything continuous between the relevant past and present
occurrences (in The Analysis of Mind, Russell countenanced this possibility and
called it “mnemic causation”). (2) What must be added to remembering that p to
get a case of knowing it because one remembers it? We saw that one must not be
uncertain that p. Must one also have grounds for trusting one’s memory
impression (its seeming to one that one remembers) that p? How could one have
such grounds except by knowing them on the basis of memory? The facts one can
know not on the basis of memory are limited at most to what one presently
perceives and what one presently finds self-evident. If no memory belief
qualifies as knowledge unless it is supported by memory knowledge of the
reliability of one’s memory, then the process of qualifying as memory knowledge
cannot succeed: there would be an endless chain, or loop, of facts – this
belief is memory knowledge if and only if this other belief is, which is if and
only if this other one is, and so on – which never becomes a set that entails
that any belief is memory knowledge. On the basis of such reasoning a skeptic
might deny the possibility of memory knowledge. We may avoid this consequence
without going to the lax extreme of allowing that any correct memory impression
is knowledge; we can impose the (frequently satisfied) requirement that one not
have reasons specific to the particular case for believing that one’s memory
impression might be unreliable. Finally, remembering that p becomes memory
knowledge that p only if one believes that p because it seems to one that one
remembers it. One might remember that p and confidently believe that p, but if
one has no memory impression of having previously learned it, or one has such
an impression but does not trust it and believes that p only for other reasons
(or no reason), then one should not be counted as knowing that p on the basis
of memory. See also EPISTEMOLOGY, PERCEPTION, SKEPTICISM. C.G. memory, image
theory of. See MEMORY. memory, occurrent. See MEMORY. memory, representational
theory of. See MEMORY. Mencius, also known as Meng-tzu, Meng K’o (fl. fourth
century B.C.), Chinese Confucian philosopher, probably the single most
influential philosopher in the Chinese tradition. His sayings, discussions, and
debates were compiled by disciples in the book entitled Meng-tzu. Mencius is
best known for his assertion that human nature is good but it is unclear what
he meant by this. At one point, he says he only means that a human can become
good. Elsewhere, though, he says that human nature is good just as water flows
downward, implying that humans will become good if only their natural
development is unimpeded. Certainly, part of what is implied by the claim that
human nature is good is Mencius’s belief that all humans have what he describes
as four “hearts” or “sprouts” – benevolence (jen), righteousness (yi), ritual
propriety (li), and wisdom (chih). The term ‘sprout’ seems to refer to an
incipient emotional or behavioral reaction of a virtuous nature. Mencius
claims, e.g., that any human who saw a child about to fall into a well would
have a spontaneous feeling of concern, which is the sprout of benevolence.
Although all humans manifest the sprouts, “concentration” (ssu) is required in
order to nurture them into mature virtues. Mencius is not specific about what
concentration is, but it probably involves an ongoing awareness of, and delight
in, the operation of the sprouts. The result of the concentration and
consequent delight in the operation of the sprouts is the “extension” (t’ui,
ta, chi) or “filling out” (k’uo, ch’ung) of the incipient reactions, so that
benevolence, for instance, comes to be manifested to all suffering humans.
Nonetheless, Mencius maintains the belief, typical of Confucianism, that we
have greater moral responsibility for those tied to us because of particular
relationships such as kinship. Mencius is also Confucian in his belief that the
virtues first manifest themselves within the family. Although Mencius is a
self-cultivationist, he also believes that one’s environment can positively or
negatively affect one’s moral development, and encourages rulers to produce
social conditions conducive to virtue. He admits, however, that there are moral
prodigies who have flourished despite deleterious circumstances. memory, image
theory of Mencius 554 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 554 Mencius’s virtue
ethic is like Aristotle’s in combining antinomianism with a belief in the
objectivity of specific moral judgments, but his de-emphasis of intellectual
virtues and emphasis upon benevolence are reminiscent of Joseph Butler. Mencius
differs from Butler, however, in that although he thinks the Confucian way is
the most profitable, he condemns profit or self-love as a motivation. Mencius
saw himself as defending the doctrines of Confucius against the philosophies of
other thinkers, especially Mo Tzu and Yang Chu. In so doing, he often goes
beyond what Confucius said. See also CHUANG TZU, CONFUCIANISM, FOUR BOOKS, HSÜN
TZU. B.W.V.N. Mendel, Gregor (1822–84), Austrian botanist and discoverer of
what are now considered the basic principles of heredity. An Augustinian monk
who conducted plant-breeding experiments in a monastery garden in Brünn (now
Brno, Czech Republic), Mendel discovered that certain characters of a common
variety of garden pea are transmitted in a strikingly regular way. The
characters with which he dealt occur in two distinct states, e.g., pods that
are smooth or ridged. In characters such as these, one state is dominant to its
recessive partner, i.e., when varieties of each sort are crossed, all the
offspring exhibit the dominant character. However, when the offspring of these
crosses are themselves crossed, the result is a ratio of three dominants to one
recessive. In modern terms, pairs of genes (alleles) separate at reproduction
(segregation) and each offspring receives only one member of each pair. Of
equal importance, the recessive character reappears unaffected by its temporary
suppression. Alleles remain pure. Mendel also noted that the pairs of
characters that he studied assort independently of each other, i.e., if two
pairs of characters are followed through successive crosses, no statistical
correlations in their transmission can be found. As genetics developed after
the turn of the century, the simple “laws” that Mendel had set out were
expanded and altered. Only a relatively few characters exhibit two distinct
states, one dominant to the other. In many, the heterozygote exhibits an
intermediate state. In addition, genes do not exist in isolation from each
other but together on chromosomes. Only those genes that reside on different
pairs of chromosomes assort in total independence of each other. During his
research, Mendel corresponded with Karl von Nägeli (1817–91), a major authority
in plant hybridization. Von Nägeli urged Mendel to cross varieties of the
common hawkweed. When Mendel took his advice, he failed to discover the
hereditary patterns that he had found in garden peas. In 1871 Mendel ceased his
research to take charge of his monastery. In 1900 Hugo de Vries (1848–1935)
stumbled upon several instances of three-to-one ratios while developing his own
theory of the origin of species. No sooner did he publish his results than two
young biologists announced independent discovery of what came to be known as
Mendel’s laws. The founders of modern genetics abandoned attempts to work out
the complexities of embryological development and concentrated just on
transmission. As a result of several unfortunate misunderstandings, early
Mendelian geneticists thought that their theory of genetics was incompatible
with Darwin’s theory of evolution. Eventually, however, the two theories were
merged to form the synthetic theory of evolution. In the process, R. A. Fisher
(1890–1962) questioned the veracity of Mendel’s research, arguing that the only
way that Mendel could have gotten data as good as he did was by sanitizing it.
Present-day historians view all of the preceding events in a very different
light. The science of heredity that developed at the turn of the century was so
different from anything that Mendel had in mind that Mendel hardly warrants
being considered its father. The neglect of Mendel’s work is made to seem so
problematic only by reading later developments back into Mendel’s original
paper. Like de Vries, Mendel was interested primarily in developing a theory of
the origin of species. The results of Mendel’s research on the hawkweed brought
into question the generalizability of the regularities that he had found in
peas, but they supported his theory of species formation through hybridization.
Similarly, the rediscovery of Mendel’s laws can be viewed as an instance of
multiple, simultaneous discovery only by ignoring important differences in the
views expressed by these authors. Finally, Mendel certainly did not mindlessly
organize and report his data, but the methods that he used can be construed as
questionable only in contrast to an overly empirical, inductive view of
science. Perhaps Mendel was no Mendelian, but he was not a fraud either. See
also DARWINISM. D.L.H. Mendelian genetics. See MENDEL. Mendelssohn, Moses
(1729–86), German philosopher known as “the Jewish Socrates.” He began as a
Bible and Talmud scholar. After movMendel, Gregor Mendelssohn, Moses 555
4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 555 ing to Berlin he learned Latin and
German, and became a close friend of Lessing, who modeled the Jew in his play
Nathan the Wise after him. Mendelssohn began writing on major philosophical
topics of the day, and won a prize from the Berlin Academy in 1764. He was
actively engaged in discussions about aesthetics, psychology, and religion, and
offered an empirical, subjectivist view that was very popular at the time. His
most famous writings are Morgenstunden (Morning Hours, or Lectures on the
Existence of God, 1785), Phaedon (Phaedo, or on the Immortality of the Soul,
1767), and Jerusalem (1783). He contended that one could prove the existence of
God and the immortality of the soul. He accepted the ontological argument and
the argument from design. In Phaedo he argued that since the soul is a simple
substance it is indestructible. Kant criticized his arguments in the first
Critique. Mendelssohn was pressed by the Swiss scientist Lavater to explain why
he, as a reasonable man, did not accept Christianity. At first he ignored the
challenge, but finally set forth his philosophical views about religion and
Judaism in Jerusalem, where he insisted that Judaism is not a set of doctrines
but a set of practices. Reasonable persons can accept that there is a universal
religion of reason, and there are practices that God has ordained that the Jews
follow. Mendelssohn was a strong advocate of religious toleration and
separation of church and state. His views played an important part in the
emancipation of the Jews, and in the Jewish Enlightenment that flowered in
Germany at the beginning of the nineteenth century. See also JEWISH PHILOSOPHY.
R.H.P. Meng K’o. See MENCIUS. Meng-tzu. See MENCIUS. mens rea, literally,
guilty mind, in law Latin. It is one of the two main prerequisites (along with
actus reus) for prima facie liability to criminal punishment in Anglo-American
legal systems. To be punishable in such systems, one must not only have
performed a legally prohibited action, such as killing another human being; one
must have done so with a culpable state of mind, or mens rea. Such culpable
mental states are of three kinds: they are either motivational states of
purpose, cognitive states of belief, or the non-mental state of negligence. To
illustrate each of these with respect to the act of killing: a killer may kill
either having another’s death as ultimate purpose, or as mediate purpose on the
way to achieving some further, ultimate end. Alternatively, the killer may act believing
to a practical certainty that his act will result in another’s death, even
though such death is an unwanted side effect, or he may believe that there is a
substantial and unjustified risk that his act will cause another’s death. The
actor may also be only negligent, which is to take an unreasonable risk of
another’s death even if the actor is not aware either of such risk or of the
lack of justification for taking it. Mens rea usually does not have to do with
any awareness by the actor that the act done is either morally wrong or legally
prohibited. Neither does mens rea have to do with any emotional state of guilt
or remorse, either while one is acting or afterward. Sometimes in its older
usages the term is taken to include the absence of excuses as well as the
mental states necessary for prima facie liability; in such a usage, the
requirement is helpfully labeled “general mens rea,” and the requirement above
discussed is labeled “special mens rea.” See also DIMINISHED CAPACITY, ETHICS,
INTENTION. M.S.M. mental content, causal theory of. See SKEPTICISM. mental
distinction. See FUNDAMENTUM DIVISIONIS. Mentalese, the language of thought
(the title of a book by Fodor, 1975) or of “brain writing” (a term of
Dennett’s); specifically, a languagelike medium of representation in which the
contents of mental events are supposedly expressed or recorded. (The term was
probably coined by Wilfrid Sellars, with whose views it was first associated.)
If what one believes are propositions, then it is tempting to propose that
believing something is having the Mentalese expression of that proposition
somehow written in the relevant place in one’s mind or brain. Thinking a
thought, at least on those occasions when we think “wordlessly” (without
formulating our thoughts in sentences or phrases composed of words of a public
language), thus appears to be a matter of creating a short-lived Mentalese
expression in a special arena or work space in the mind. In a further
application of the concept, the process of coming to understand a sentence of
natural language can be viewed as one of translating the sentence into
Mentalese. It has often been argued that this view of understanding only
postpones the difficult questions of meaning, for it leaves unanswered the
question of how Mentalese expressions come to have the meanings Meng K’o
Mentalese 556 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 556 they do. There have been
frequent attempts to develop versions of the hypothesis that mental activity is
conducted in Mentalese, and just as frequent criticisms of these attempts. Some
critics deny there is anything properly called representation in the mind or
brain at all; others claim that the system of representation used by the brain
is not enough like a natural language to be called a language. Even among
defenders of Mentalese, it has seldom been claimed that all brains “speak” the
same Mentalese. See also PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE; PHILOSOPHY OF MIND; SELLARS,
WILFRID. D.C.D. mentalism, any theory that posits explicitly mental events and
processes, where ‘mental’ means exhibiting intentionality, not necessarily
being immaterial or non-physical. A mentalistic theory is couched in terms of
belief, desire, thinking, feeling, hoping, etc. A scrupulously non-mentalistic
theory would be couched entirely in extensional terms: it would refer only to
behavior or to neurophysiological states and events. The attack on mentalism by
behaviorists was led by B. F. Skinner, whose criticisms did not all depend on
the assumption that mentalists were dualists, and the subsequent rise of
cognitive science has restored a sort of mentalism (a “thoroughly modern
mentalism,” as Fodor has called it) that is explicitly materialistic. See also
BEHAVIORISM, COGNITIVE SCIENCE, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. D.C.D. mental
representation. See COGNITIVE SCIENCE. Mercier, Désiré-Joseph (1851–1926),
Belgian Catholic philosopher, a formative figure in NeoThomism and founder of
the Institut Supérieur de Philosophie (1889) at Louvain. Created at the request
of Pope Leo XIII, Mercier’s institute treated Aquinas as a subject of
historical research and as a philosopher relevant to modern thought. His
approach to Neo-Thomism was distinctive for its direct response to the
epistemological challenges posed by idealism, rationalism, and positivism. Mercier’s
epistemology was termed a criteriology; it intended to defend the certitude of
the intellect against skepticism by providing an account of the motives and
rules that guide judgment. Truth is affirmed by intellectual judgment by
conforming itself not to the thing-in-itself but to its abstract apprehension.
Since the certitude of judgment is a state of the cognitive faculty in the
human soul, Mercier considered criteriology as psychology; see Critériologie
générale ou Théorie générale de la certitude (1906), Origins of Contemporary
Psychology (trans. 1918), and Manual of Scholastic Philosophy (trans. 1917–18).
See also AQUINAS, NEO-THOMISM. D.W.H. mereological essentialism. See HAECCEITY.
mereological sum. See MEREOLOGY. mereology (from Greek meros, ‘part’), the
mathematical theory of parts; specifically, Lesniewski’s formal theory of
parts. Typically, a mereological theory employs notions such as the following:
proper part, improper part, overlapping (having a part in common), disjoint
(not overlapping), mereological product (the “intersection” of overlapping
objects), mereological sum (a collection of parts), mereological difference,
the universal sum, mereological complement, and atom (that which has no proper
parts). Formal mereologies are axiomatic systems. Lesniewski’s mereology and
Goodman’s formal mereology (which he calls the Calculus of Individuals) are
compatible with nominalism, i.e., no reference is made to sets, properties, or
other abstract entities. Lesniewski hoped that his mereology, with its many
parallels to set theory, would provide an alternative to set theory as a
foundation for mathematics. Fundamental and controversial implications of
Lesniewski’s and Goodman’s theories include their extensionality and
collectivism. Extensional theories imply that for any individuals, x and y, x %
y provided x and y have the same proper parts. One reason extensionality is
controversial is that it rules out an object’s acquiring or losing a part, and
therefore is inconsistent with commonsense beliefs such as that a car has a new
tire or that a table has lost a sliver of wood. A second reason for controversy
is that extensionality is incompatible with the belief that a statue and the
piece of bronze of which it is made have the same parts and yet are diverse
objects. Collectivism implies that any individuals, no matter how scattered,
have a mereological sum or constitute an object. Moreover, according to
collectivism, assembling or disassembling parts does not affect the existence
of things, i.e., nothing is created or destroyed by assembly or disassembly,
respectively. Thus, collectivism is incompatible with commonsense beliefs such
as that when a watch is disassembled, it is destroyed, or that when certain
parts are assembled, a watch is created. Because the aforementioned formal
theories shun modality, they lack the resources to express mentalism mereology
557 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 557 meritarian Merleau-Ponty, Maurice
558 the thesis that a whole has each of its parts necessarily. This thesis of
mereological essentialism has recently been defended by Roderick Chisholm. See
also ESSENTIALISM, EXTENSIONALISM, METAPHYSICS, SET THEORY. J.Ho. & G.Ro.
meritarian, one who asserts the relevance of individual merit, as an
independent justificatory condition, in attempts to design social structures or
distribute goods. ‘Meritarianism’ is a recently coined term in social and
political philosophy, closely related to ‘meritocracy’, and used to identify a
range of related concerns that supplement or oppose egalitarian, utilitarian,
and contractarian principles and principles based on entitlement, right,
interest, and need, among others. For example, one can have a pressing need for
an Olympic medal but not merit it; one can have the money to buy a masterpiece
but not be worthy of it; one can have the right to a certain benefit but not
deserve it. Meritarians assert that considerations of desert are always
relevant and sometimes decisive in such cases. What counts as merit, and how
important should it be in moral, social, and political decisions? Answers to
these questions serve to distinguish one meritarian from another, and sometimes
to blur the distinctions between the meritarian position and others. Merit may
refer to any of these: comparative rank, capacities, abilities, effort,
intention, or achievement. Moreover, there is a relevance condition to be met:
to say that highest honors in a race should go to the most deserving is
presumably to say that the honors should go to those with the relevant sort of
merit – speed, e.g., rather than grace. Further, meritarians may differ about
the strength of the merit principle, and how various political or social
structures should be influenced by it. See also ETHICS, JUSTICE. L.C.B.
meritocracy, in ordinary usage, a system in which advancement is based on
ability and achievement, or one in which leadership roles are held by talented
achievers. The term may also refer to an elite group of talented achievers. In
philosophical usage, the term’s meaning is similar: a meritocracy is a scheme
of social organization in which essential offices, and perhaps careers and jobs
of all sorts are (a) open only to those who have the relevant qualifications
for successful performance in them, or (b) awarded only to the candidates who are
likely to perform the best, or (c) managed so that people advance in and retain
their offices and jobs solely on the basis of the quality of their performance
in them, or (d) all of the above. See also JUSTICE, MERITARIAN. L.C.B.
meritorious duty. See KANT. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1908–61), French
philosopher described by Paul Ricoeur as “the greatest of the French
phenomenologists.” MerleauPonty occupied the chair of child psychology and
pedagogy at the Sorbonne and was later professor of philosophy at the Collège
de France. His sudden death preceded completion of an important manuscript;
this was later edited and published by Claude Lefort under the title The
Visible and the Invisible. The relation between the late, unfinished work and
his early Phenomenology of Perception (1945) has received much scholarly
discussion. While some commentators see a significant shift in direction in his
later thought, others insist on continuity throughout his work. Thus, the exact
significance of his philosophy, which in his life was called both a philosophy
of ambiguity and an ambiguous philosophy, retains to this day its essential
ambiguity. With his compatriot and friend, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty was
responsible for introducing the phenomenology of Edmund Husserl into France.
Impressed above all by the later Husserl and by Husserl’s notion of the
life-world (Lebenswelt), Merleau-Ponty combined Husserl’s transcendental
approach to epistemological issues with an existential orientation derived from
Heidegger and Marcel. Going even further than Heidegger, who had himself sought
to go beyond Husserl by “existentializing” Husserl’s Transcendental Ego
(referring to it as Dasein), MerleauPonty sought to emphasize not only the
existential (worldly) nature of the human subject but, above all, its bodily
nature. Thus his philosophy could be characterized as a philosophy of the lived
body or the body subject (le corps propre). Although Nietzsche called attention
to the all-importance of the body, it was MerleauPonty who first made the body
the central theme of a detailed philosophical analysis. This provided an
original perspective from which to rethink such perennial philosophical issues
as the nature of knowledge, freedom, time (temporality), language, and
intersubjectivity. Especially in his early work, Merleau-Ponty battled against
absolutist thought (“la pensée de l’absolu”), stressing the insurmountable
ambiguity and contingency of all meaning and truth. An archopponent of
Cartesian rationalism, he was an early and ardent spokesman for that position
now called antifoundationalism. 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 558
Merleau-Ponty’s major early work, the Phenomenology of Perception, is best
known for its central thesis concerning “the primacy of perception.” In this
lengthy study he argued that all the “higher” functions of consciousness (e.g.,
intellection, volition) are rooted in and depend upon the subject’s
prereflective, bodily existence, i.e., perception (“All consciousness is
perceptual, even the consciousness of ourselves”). MerleauPonty maintained,
however, that perception had never been adequately conceptualized by
traditional philosophy. Thus the book was to a large extent a dialectical
confrontation with what he took to be the two main forms of objective thinking
– intellectualism and empiricism – both of which, he argued, ignored the
phenomenon of perception. His principal goal was to get beyond the intellectual
constructs of traditional philosophy (such as sense-data) and to effect “a
return to the phenomena,” to the world as we actually experience it as embodied
subjects prior to all theorizing. His main argument (directed against mainline
philosophy) was that the lived body is not an object in the world, distinct
from the knowing subject (as in Descartes), but is the subject’s own point of
view on the world; the body is itself the original knowing subject (albeit a
nonor prepersonal, “anonymous” subject), from which all other forms of
knowledge derive, even that of geometry. As a phenomenological (or, as he also
said, “archaeological”) attempt to unearth the basic (corporeal) modalities of
human existence, emphasizing the rootedness (enracinement) of the personal
subject in the obscure and ambiguous life of the body and, in this way, the
insurpassable contingency of all meaning, the Phenomenology was immediately and
widely recognized as a major statement of French existentialism. In his
subsequent work in the late 1940s and the 1950s, in many shorter essays and
articles, Merleau-Ponty spelled out in greater detail the philosophical
consequences of “the primacy of perception.” These writings sought to respond
to widespread objections that by “grounding” all intellectual and cultural
acquisitions in the prereflective and prepersonal life of the body, the
Phenomenology of Perception results in a kind of reductionism and
anti-intellectualism and teaches only a “bad ambiguity,” i.e., completely
undermines the notions of reason and truth. By shifting his attention from the
phenomenon of perception to that of (creative) expression, his aim was to work
out a “good ambiguity” by showing how “communication with others and thought
take up and go beyond the realm of perception which initiated us to the truth.”
His announced goal after the Phenomenology was “working out in a rigorous way the
philosophical foundations” of a theory of truth and a theory of
intersubjectivity (including a theory of history). No such large-scale work (a
sequel, as it were, to the Phenomenology) ever saw the light of day, although
in pursuing this project he reflected on subjects as diverse as painting,
literary language, Saussurian linguistics, structuralist anthropology,
politics, history, the human sciences, psychoanalysis, contemporary science
(including biology), and the philosophy of nature. Toward the end of his life,
however, MerleauPonty did begin work on a projected large-scale manuscript, the
remnants of which were published posthumously as The Visible and the Invisible.
A remarkable feature of this work (as Claude Lefort has pointed out) is the
resolute way in which Merleau-Ponty appears to be groping for a new
philosophical language. His express concerns in this abortive manuscript are
explicitly ontological (as opposed to the more limited phenomenological
concerns of his early work), and he consistently tries to avoid the subject
(consciousness)–object language of the philosophy of consciousness (inherited
from Husserl’s transcendental idealism) that characterized the Phenomenology of
Perception. Although much of Merleau-Ponty’s later thought was a response to
the later Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty sets himself apart from Heidegger in this
unfinished work by claiming that the only ontology possible is an indirect one
that can have no direct access to Being itself. Indeed, had he completed it,
Merleau-Ponty’s new ontology would probably have been one in which, as Lefort
has remarked, “the word Being would not have to be uttered.” He was always
keenly attuned to “the sensible world”; the key term in his ontological
thinking is not so much ‘Being’ as it is ‘the flesh’, a term with no equivalent
in the history of philosophy. What traditional philosophy referred to as
“subject” and “object” were not two distinct sorts of reality, but merely
“differentiations of one sole and massive adhesion to Being [Nature] which is
the flesh.” By viewing the perceiving subject as “a coiling over of the visible
upon the visible,” Merleau-Ponty was attempting to overcome the subject–object
dichotomy of modern philosophy, which raised the intractable problems of the
external world and other minds. With the notion of the flesh he believed he
could finally overcome the solipsism of modern philosophy and had discovered
the basis for a genuine intersubjectivity (conceived of as basically an
intercorporeity). Merleau-Ponty, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Maurice 559 4065m-r.qxd
08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 559 Mersenne, Marin metalanguage 560 Does ‘flesh’
signify something significantly different from ‘body’ in Merleau-Ponty’s
earlier thought? Did his growing concern with ontology (and the question of nature)
signal abandonment of his earlier phenomenology (to which the question of
nature is foreign)? This has remained a principal subject of conflicting
interpretations in Merleau-Ponty scholarship. As illustrated by his last,
unfinished work, Merleau-Ponty’s oeuvre as a whole is fragmentary. He always
insisted that true philosophy is the enemy of the system, and he disavowed
closure and completion. While Heidegger has had numerous disciples and
epigones, it is difficult to imagine what a “Merleau-Ponty school of
philosophy” would be. This is not to deny that Merleau-Ponty’s work has exerted
considerable influence. Although he was relegated to a kind of intellectual
purgatory in France almost immediately upon his death, the work of his
poststructuralist successors such as Foucault and Jacques Derrida betrays a
great debt to his previous struggles with philosophical modernity. And in
Germany, Great Britain, and, above all, North America, Merleau-Ponty has
continued to be a source of philosophical inspiration and the subject of
extensive scholarship. Although his work does not presume to answer the key
questions of existence, it is a salient model of philosophy conceived of as
unremitting interrogation. It is this questioning (“zetetic”) attitude,
combined with a non-dogmatic humanism, that continues to speak not only to
philosophers but also to a wide audience among practitioners of the human
sciences (phenomenological psychology being a particularly noteworthy example).
See also CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY, EXISTENTIALISM, PHENOMENOLOGY, SUBJECT– OBJECT
DICHOTOMY. G.B.M. Mersenne, Marin (1588–1648), French priest who compiled
massive works on philosophy, mathematics, music, and natural science, and
conducted an enormous correspondence with such figures as Galileo, Descartes,
and Hobbes. He translated Galileo’s Mechanics and Herbert of Cherbury’s De
Veritate and arranged for publication of Hobbes’s De Cive. He is best known for
gathering the objections published with Descartes’s Meditations. Mersenne
served a function in the rise of modern philosophy and science that is today
served by professional journals and associations. His works contain attacks on
deists, atheists, libertines, and skeptics; but he also presents mitigated
skepticism as a practical method for attaining scientific knowledge. He did not
believe that we can attain knowledge of inner essences, but argued – by
displaying it – that we have an immense amount of knowledge about the material
world adequate to our needs. Like Gassendi, Mersenne advocated mechanistic
explanations in science, and following Galileo, he proposed mathematical models
of material phenomena. Like the Epicureans, he believed that mechanism was
adequate to save the phenomena. He thus rejected Aristotelian forms and occult
powers. Mersenne was another of the great philosopher-priests of the
seventeenth century who believed that to increase scientific knowledge is to
know and serve God. See also DESCARTES, EPICUREANISM. R.A.W. Merton School. See
OXFORD CALCULATORS. metaethical relativism. See RELATIVISM. metaethics. See
ETHICS. metalanguage, in formal semantics, a language used to describe another
language (the object language). The object language may be either a natural
language or a formal language. The goal of a formal semantic theory is to
provide an axiomatic or otherwise systematic theory of meaning for the object
language. The metalanguage is used to specify the object language’s symbols and
formation rules, which determine its grammatical sentences or well-formed
formulas, and to assign meanings or interpretations to these sentences or
formulas. For example, in an extensional semantics, the metalanguage is used to
assign denotations to the singular terms, extensions to the general terms, and
truth conditions to sentences. The standard format for assigning truth
conditions, as in Tarski’s formulation of his “semantical conception of truth,”
is a T-sentence, which takes the form ‘S is true if and only if p.’ Davidson
adapted this format to the purposes of his truth-theoretic account of meaning.
Examples of T-sentences, with English as the metalanguage, are ‘ “La neige est
blanche” is true if and only if snow is white’, where the object langauge is
French and the homophonic (Davidson) ‘“Snow is white” is true if and only if
snow is white’, where the object language is English as well. Although for
formal purposes the distinction between metalanguage and object language must
be maintained, in practice one can use a langauge to talk about expressions in
the very same language. One can, in Carnap’s terms, shift 4065m-r.qxd
08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 560 from the material mode to the formal mode, e.g.
from ‘Every veterinarian is an animal doctor’ to ‘ “Veterinarian” means “animal
doctor”.’ This shift is important in discussions of synonymy and of the
analytic–synthetic distinction. Carnap’s distinction corresponds to the
use–mention distinction. We are speaking in the formal mode – we are mentioning
a linguistic expression – when we ascribe a property to a word or other
expression type, such as its spelling, pronunciation, meaning, or grammatical
category, or when we speak of an expression token as misspelled, mispronounced,
or misused. We are speaking in the material mode when we say “Reims is hard to
find” but in the formal mode when we say “ ‘Reims’ is hard to pronounce.” See
also PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE, TYPE– TOKEN DISTINCTION, USE–MENTION DISTINCTION.
K.B. metalogic. See PROOF THEORY. metamathematics, the study and establishment,
by restricted (and, in particular, finitary) means, of the consistency or
reliability of the various systems of classical mathematics. The term was
apparently introduced, with pejorative overtones relating it to ‘metaphysics’,
in the 1870s in connection with the discussion of non-Euclidean geometries. It
was introduced in the sense given here, shorn of negative connotations, by
Hilbert (see his “Neubegründung der Mathematik. Erste Mitteilung,” 1922), who
also referred to it as Beweistheorie or proof theory. A few years later
(specifically, in the 1930 papers “Über einige fundamentale Begriffe der
Metamathematik” and “Fundamentale Begriffe der Methodologie der deduktiven
Wissenschaften. I”) Tarski fitted it with a somewhat broader, less restricted
sense: broader in that the scope of its concerns was increased to include not
only questions of consistency, but also a host of other questions (e.g.
questions of independence, completeness and axiomatizability) pertaining to
what Tarski referred to as the “methodology of the deductive sciences” (which
was his synonym for ‘metamathematics’); less restricted in that the standards
of proof were relaxed so as to permit other than finitary – indeed, other than
constructive – means. On this broader conception of Tarski’s, formalized
deductive disciplines form the field of research of metamathematics roughly in
the same sense in which spatial entities form the field of research in geometry
or animals that of zoology. Disciplines, he said, are to be regarded as sets of
sentences to be investigated from the point of view of their consistency,
axiomatizability (of various types), completeness, and categoricity or degree
of categoricity, etc. Eventually (see the 1935 and 1936 papers “Grundzüge des
Systemenkalkül, Erster Teil” and “Grundzüge der Systemenkalkül, Zweiter Teil”)
Tarski went on to include all manner of semantical questions among the concerns
of metamathematics, thus diverging rather sharply from Hilbert’s original
syntactical focus. Today, the terms ‘metatheory’ and ‘metalogic’ are used to
signify that broad set of interests, embracing both syntactical and semantical
studies of formal languages and systems, which Tarski came to include under the
general heading of metamathematics. Those having to do specifically with
semantics belong to that more specialized branch of modern logic known as model
theory, while those dealing with purely syntactical questions belong to what
has come to be known as proof theory (where this latter is now, however,
permitted to employ other than finitary methods in the proofs of its theorems).
See also CATEGORICITY, COMPLETENESS, CONSISTENCY, MODEL THEORY, PROOF THEORY.
M.D. metaphilosophy, the theory of the nature of philosophy, especially its
goals, methods, and fundamental assumptions. First-order philosophical inquiry
includes such disciplines as epistemology, ontology, ethics, and value theory.
It thus constitutes the main activity of philosophers, past and present. The
philosophical study of firstorder philosophical inquiry raises philosophical
inquiry to a higher order. Such higher-order inquiry is metaphilosophy. The
first-order philosophical discipline of (e.g.) epistemology has the nature of
knowledge as its main focus, but that discipline can itself be the focus of
higher-order philosophical inquiry. The latter focus yields a species of
metaphilosophy called metaepistemology. Two other prominent species are
metaethics and metaontology. Each such branch of metaphilosophy studies the
goals, methods, and fundamental assumptions of a first-order philosophical
discipline. Typical metaphilosophical topics include (a) the conditions under
which a claim is philosophical rather than non-philosophical, and (b) the
conditions under which a first-order philosophical claim is either meaningful,
true, or warranted. Metaepistemology, e.g., pursues not the nature of knowledge
directly, but rather the conditions under which claims are genuinely
epistemetalogic metaphilosophy 561 4065m-r.qxd 08/02/1999 7:42 AM Page 561
mological and the conditions under which epistemological claims are either
meaningful, or true, or warranted. The distinction between philosophy and
metaphilosophy has an analogue in the familiar distinction between mathematics
and metamathematics. Questions about the autonomy, objectivity, relativity, and
modal status of philosophical claims arise in metaphilosophy. Questions about
autonomy concern the relationship of philosophy to such disciplines as those
constituting the natural and social sciences. For instance, is philosophy
methodologically independent of the natural sciences? Questions about objectivity
and relativity concern the kind of truth and warrant available to philosophical
claims. For instance, are philosophical truths characteristically, or ever,
made true by mind-independent phenomena in the way that typical claims of the
natural sciences supposedly are? Or, are philosophical truths unavoidably
conventional, being fully determined by (and thus altogether relative to)
linguistic conventions? Are they analytic rather than synthetic truths, and is
knowledge of them a priori rather than a posteriori? Questions about modal
status consider whether philosophical claims are necessary rather than
contingent. Are philosophical claims necessarily true or false, in contrast to
the contingent claims of the natural sciences? The foregoing questions identify
major areas of controversy in contemporary metaphilosophy. See also
ANALYTIC–SYNTHETIC DISTINCTION, A PRIORI, EPISTEMOLOGY, MEANING. P.K.M
No comments:
Post a Comment