H.
P. Grice, St. John’s, Oxford.
THESAVRVS
GRICEIANVUM
Compiled
by H. P. Grice’s Play Group -- Deposited at the Bodelian, Oxford.
abderites: the
Grecian philosophers Leucippus and Democritus, the two earliest exponents of
atomism, later revived by Baron Russell as “logical” atomism, calling himself a
neo-abderite. Even though Abdera, in Thrace in northern Greece, is home to
three pre-Socratics Leucippus, Democritus,
and Protagoras ‘Abderite’ and the
phrase ‘School of Abdera’ are applied only to Leucippus and Democritus. We can
thus distinguish between early Grecian atomism and Epicureanism, which is the
later version of atomism developed by Epicurus of Athens. This usage is in one
respect inapt: the corresponding Grecian “abderite” is used by some snobs in
antiquity as a synonym of ‘simpleton,’ not in disparagement of any of the three
philosophers of Abdera but as a regional slur, the three philosophers but not
Russell included.
abduction: as
opposed to in-duction and de-duction, abduction refers to canons of reasoning
for the discovery, as opposed to the justification, of scientific hypotheses or
theories. Reichenbach distinguished the context of justification and the
context of discovery, arguing that philosophy legitimately is concerned only
with the former, which concerns verification and confirmation, whereas the
latter is a matter for psychology. Thus he and other logical positivists
claimed there are inductive logics of justification but not logics for
discovery. Both hypotheticodeductive and Bayesian or other probabilistic
inductive logics of justification have been proposed. Close examination of
actual scientific practice increasingly reveals justificatory arguments and
procedures that call into question the adequacy of such logics. N. R. Hanson
distinguishes the reasons for accepting a specific hypothesis from the reasons
for suggesting that the correct hypothesis will be of a particular kind. For
the latter he attempted to develop logics of retroductive or abductive
reasoning that stressed analogical reasoning, but did not succeed in convincing
many that these logics were different in kind from logics of justification.
Today few regard the search for rigorous formal logics of discovery as
promising. Rather, the search has turned to looking for “logics” in some weaker
sense. Heuristic procedures, strategies for discovery, and the like are
explored. Others have focused on investigating rationality in the growth of
scientific knowledge, say, by exploring conditions under which research
traditions or programs are progressive or degenerating. Some have explored
recourse to techniques from cognitive science or artificial intelligence.
Claims of success generally are controversial.
abélard:
pierre abailard, philosopher whose writings, particularly Theologia Christiana,
constitute one of the more impressive attempts of the medieval period to use
logical techniques to explicate Christian dogmas. He was born of a minor noble
family in Brittany and studied logic and theology under some of the most
notable teachers of the early twelfth century, including Roscelin, William of
Champeaux, and Anselm of Laon. He rapidly eclipsed his teachers in logic and
attracted students from all over Europe. His forays into theology were less
enthusiastically received. Twice his views on the Trinity were condemned as
heretical. Abelard led a dramatic life punctuated by bitter disputes with his
opponents and a dangerous and celebrated love affair with Héloïse. Much of this
story is told in his autobiographical work, Historia calamitatum. Abelard’s two
most important Griceian works in logic are his “Logica ingredientibus” and his “Dialectica.”
In these treatises and others he is the first medieval Scholastic to make full
use of Aristotle’s “De interpretation” and Boethius’s commentaries on it to
produce a sophisticated theory of the signification of words and sentences. The
theory distinguishes the signification of an expression both from what the
expression names and the idea in the mind of the emissor associated with the
expression. Abélard allows a role for mental images in thinking, but he
carefully avoids claiming that these are what words signify. In this he is very
much aware of the pitfalls of subjectivist theories of meaning. His positive
doctrines on what words signify tie in closely with his views on the
signification of propositions and universals. For Abelard propositions are
sentences that are either true or false; what they say their dicta is what they
signify and these dicta are the primary bearers of truth and falsity. Abelard
developed a genuinely propositional logic, the first since the Stoics. A
universal, on the other hand, is a common noun or adjective, and what it means
is what the verb phrase part of a proposition signifies. This is a sort of
truncated dictum, which Abelard variously called a status, nature, or property.
Neither status nor dicta are things, Abelard said, but they are
mind-independent objects of thought. Abelard was particularly devastating in
his attacks on realist theories of universals, but his view that universals are
words was not meant to deny the objectivity of our knowledge of the world.
Abelard’s theories in logic and ontology went far beyond the traditional ideas
that had been handed down from Aristotle through the mediation of the late ancient
commentators, Boethius in particular. They could have formed the basis of a
fundamentally new synthesis in Western logic, but when more of the Aristotelian
corpus became available in Western Europe during the twelfth century,
concentration shifted to assimilating this already fully elaborated system of
ideas. Consequently, Abelard’s influence on later Scholastic thought, though
noticeable, is not nearly as great as one might expect, given the acuteness and
originality of his insights. A
abhidharma:
the analytical and systematic presentation of the major conceptual categories
constituting Buddhist doctrine; used as a label for both the texts that contain
such presentations and the content of what is presented. Early abhidharma texts
up to about the second century A.D. are catechetical in form, defining key
doctrinal terms schematically through question and answer; later works are more
discursive, often containing extensive discussions of controverted metaphysical
issues such as the existence of past objects or the nature of reference. The
goal of abhidharma is to make a complete inventory of existents and of the
relations that may hold among them.
abhinivesha: Sanskrit
word meaning ‘self-love’ or ‘will to live’. In Indian philosophy in general and
in the Sankhya-Yoga system in particular, abhinivesha was regarded as an aspect
of avidya ignorance. Some other manifestations of avidya were said to be fear,
attachment, and aversion, all of which were thought to generate karmic bondage
and prevent one from attaining spiritual liberation. Lumped together with
these, abhinivesha obviously has a negative connotation, even though in the
Indian tradition it was not necessarily wrong, and even commendable at times,
to exhibit self-love and a healthy will to live and prosper in the material
world. So presumably the negative connotation of abhinivesha is an indication
that what may be otherwise permissible can be improper or morally wrong if
pursued in excess or for the wrong reason.
Abrabanel,
Isaac ben Judah, philosopher and statesman. On the periphery between late medieval
philosophy and Renaissance humanism, Abrabanel concerned himself with
traditional medieval Jewish subjects such as creation, prophecy, and theodicy.
His works include biblical commentaries as well as philosophical and
theological treatises; his most significant writings constitute his critique of
Maimonides’ Guide of the Perplexed, found in Rosh Amanah 1505 and Mifalot
Elohim 1503. In his criticism of the Aristotelians, Abrabanel was influenced by
Isaac Arama. Endorsing the rabbinic concept of prophecy, Abrabanel attacks
Maimonides’ naturalistic views of prophecy: he argues that Moses is not to be
distinguished from the other prophets and that the knowledge of the prophets is
not merely scientific and metaphysical, but miraculously produced by God. This
emphasis upon the miraculous as opposed to the natural is developed in his
theory of history and politics. His views about the ideal state reflect
humanist leanings. While Abrabanel does see the civilized state of humans as a
rebellion against God resulting from the fall, he is interested in the best
kind of government under these circumstances. Accordingly, unity of society
does not require a concentrated power but can be achieved through a collective will.
This kind of government, Abrabanel claims, is advocated by the Torah and shown
to be effective by the Italian republics of the period. With the coming of the
Messiah, humankind will realize its spiritual potential, and when the corporeal
universe vanishes, each soul will be able to contemplate eternally the essence
of God. Abrabanel’s political views influenced later Jewish messianic
movements, and his biblical commenabhidharma Abrabanel, Isaac ben Judah 2
4065A- 2 taries, translated into Latin,
influenced later Christian humanist circles.
Abrabanel,
Judah, also called Leone Ebreo or Leo Hebraeus, philosopher, poet, and
physician. The oldest son of Isaac Abrabanel, Judah Abrabanel was,
philosophically, a representative of Italian Platonism. He wrote his
predominantly Neoplatonic philosophical work Dialoghi d’Amore Dialogues of Love
in 1535. The original Italian manuscript was translated into French, Latin, and
Hebrew between 1551 and 1560. The interlocutors of this Platonic-style
dialogue, Sophia and Philo, explore the nature of cosmic love. This love not
only exists between God and creatures, but also operates in matter and form,
the four elements, and the entire universe; it reflects both sensuous and
intellectual beauty; in short it is transformed from a relation between God and
the universe into a fundamental force around which all things are ordered.
There is a mystical aspect to Abrabanel’s account of love, and it is not
surprising that reflections on mysticism, in addition to astrology, astronomy,
and aesthetics, emerge throughout the work. Although primarily reflecting
medieval Platonism and Neoplatonism, Abrabanel was also influenced by Marcilio
Ficino, Pico della Mirandola, Maimonides, and Ibn Gabirol. His dialogue was
read by many philosophers, including Giordano Bruno and Spinoza. His concept of
love may be found in lyrical poetry of the period in Italy, France, and Spain,
as well as in Michelangelo’s Sonnets and Torquato Tasso’s Minturno.
absolutum: the,
term used by idealists to describe the one independent reality of which all
things are an expression. Kant used the adjective ‘absolute’ to characterize
what is unconditionally valid. He claimed that pure reason searched for
absolute grounds of the understanding that were ideals only, but that practical
reason postulated the real existence of such grounds as necessary for morality.
This apparent inconsistency led his successors to attempt to systematize his
view of reason. To do this, Schelling introduced the term ‘the Absolute’ for
the unconditioned ground and hence identity of subject and object. Schelling
was criticized by Hegel, who defined the Absolute as spirit: the logical
necessity that embodies itself in the world in order to achieve self-knowledge
and freedom during the course of history. Many prominent nineteenthcentury
British and American idealists, including Bosanquet, Royce, and Bradley,
defended the existence of a quasi-Hegelian absolute.
abstractum:
an
entity object lacking spatiotemporal properties, but supposed to have being, to
exist, or in medieval Scholastic terminology to subsist. Abstracta, sometimes
collected under the category of universals, include mathematical objects, such
as numbers, sets, and geometrical figures, propositions, properties, and
relations. Abstract entities are said to be abstracted from particulars. The
abstract triangle has only the properties common to all triangles, and none
peculiar to any particular triangles; it has no definite color, size, or
specific type, such as isosceles or scalene. Abstracta are admitted to an
ontology by Quine’s criterion if they must be supposed to exist or subsist in
order to make the propositions of an accepted theory true. Properties and
relations may be needed to account for resemblances among particulars, such as
the redness shared by all red things. Propositions as the abstract contents or
meanings of thoughts and expressions of thought are sometimes said to be
necessary to explain translation between languages, and other semantic
properties and relations. Historically, abstract entities are associated with
Plato’s realist ontology of Ideas or Forms. For Plato, these are the abstract
and only real entities, instantiated or participated in by spatiotemporal
objects in the world of appearance or empirical phenomena. Aristotle denied the
independent existence of abstract entities, and redefined a diluted sense of
Plato’s Forms as the secondary substances that inhere in primary substances or
spatiotemporal particulars as the only genuine existents. The dispute persisted
in medieval philosophy between realist metaphysicians, including Augustine and
Aquinas, who accepted the existence of abstracta, and nominalists, such as
Ockham, who maintained that similar objects may simply be referred to by the
same name without participating in an abstract form. In modern philosophy, the
problem of abstracta has been a point of contention between rationalism, which
is generally committed to the existence of abstract entities, and empiricism,
which rejects abstracta because they cannot be experienced by the senses.
Berkeley and Hume argued against Locke’s theory of abstract ideas by observing
that introspection shows all ideas to be particular, from which they concluded
that we can have no adequate concept of an abstract entity; instead, when we
reason about what we call abstracta we are actually thinking about particular
ideas delegated by the mind to represent an entire class of resemblant
particulars, from which we may freely substitute others if we mistakenly draw
conclusions peculiar to the example chosen. Abstract propositions were defended
by Bolzano and Frege in the nineteenth century as the meanings of thought in
language and logic. Dispute persists about the need for and nature of abstract
entities, but many philosophers believe they are indispensable in
metaphysics.
academia,
the school established by Plato around 385 B.C. at his property outside Athens
near the public park and gymnasium known by that name. Although it may not have
maintained a continuous tradition, the many and varied philosophers of the
Academy all considered themselves Plato’s successors, and all of them
celebrated and studied his work. The school survived in some form until A.D.
529, when it was dissolved, along with the other pagan schools, by the Eastern
Roman emperor Justinian I. The history of the Academy is divided by some
authorities into that of the Old Academy Plato, Speusippus, Xenocrates, and
their followers and the New Academy the Skeptical Academy of the third and
second centuries B.C.. Others speak of five phases in its history: Old as
before, Middle Arcesilaus, New Carneades, Fourth Philo of Larisa, and Fifth
Antiochus of Ascalon. For most of its history the Academy was devoted to
elucidating doctrines associated with Plato that were not entirely explicit in
the dialogues. These “unwritten doctrines” were apparently passed down to his
immediate successors and are known to us mainly through the work of Aristotle:
there are two opposed first principles, the One and the Indefinite Dyad Great
and Small; these generate Forms or Ideas which may be identified with numbers,
from which in turn come intermediate mathematicals and, at the lowest level,
perceptible things Aristotle, Metaphysics I.6. After Plato’s death in 347, the
Academy passed to his nephew Speusippus c.407339, who led the school until his
death. Although his written works have perished, his views on certain main
points, along with some quotations, were recorded by surviving authors. Under
the influence of late Pythagoreans, Speusippus anticipated Plotinus by holding
that the One transcends being, goodness, and even Intellect, and that the Dyad
which he identifies with matter is the cause of all beings. To explain the
gradations of beings, he posited gradations of matter, and this gave rise to
Aristotle’s charge that Speusippus saw the universe as a series of disjointed
episodes. Speusippus abandoned the theory of Forms as ideal numbers, and gave
heavier emphasis than other Platonists to the mathematicals. Xenocrates 396314,
who once went with Plato to Sicily, succeeded Speusippus and led the Academy
till his own death. Although he was a prolific author, Xenocrates’ works have
not survived, and he is known only through the work of other authors. He was
induced by Aristotle’s objections to reject Speusippus’s views on some points,
and he developed theories that were a major influence on Middle Platonism, as
well as on Stoicism. In Xenocrates’ theory the One is Intellect, and the Forms
are ideas in the mind of this divine principle; the One is not transcendent,
but it resides in an intellectual space above the heavens. While the One is
good, the Dyad is evil, and the sublunary world is identified with Hades.
Having taken Forms to be mathematical entities, he had no use for intermediate
mathematicals. Forms he defined further as paradigmatic causes of regular
natural phenomena, and soul as self-moving number. Polemon c.350267 led the
Academy from 314 to 267, and was chiefly known for his fine character, which
set an example of self-control for his students. The Stoics probably derived
their concept of oikeiosis an accommodation to nature from his teaching. After
Polemon’s death, his colleague Crates led the Academy until the accession of
Arcesilaus. The New Academy arose when Arcesilaus became the leader of the
school in about 265 B.C. and turned the dialectical tradition of Plato to the
Skeptical aim of suspending belief. The debate between the New Academy and
Stoicism dominated philosophical discussion for the next century and a half. On
the Academic side the most prominent spokesman was Carneades c.213 129 B.C.. In
the early years of the first century B.C., Philo of Larisa attempted to
reconcile the Old and the New Academy. His pupil, the former Skeptic Antiochus
of Ascalon, was enraged by this and broke away to refound the Old Academy in
about 87 B.C. This was the beginning of Middle Platonism c.80 B.C.A.D. 220.
Antiochus’s school was eclectic in combining elements of Platonism, Stoicism,
and Aristotelian philosophy, and is known to us mainly through Cicero’s
Academica. Middle Platonism revived the main themes of Speusippus and
Xenocrates, but often used Stoic or neo-Pythagorean concepts to explain them.
The influence of the Stoic Posidonius 13550/51 B.C. was strongly felt on the
Academy in this period, and Platonism flourished at centers other than the
Academy in Athens, most notably in Alexandria, with Eudorus first century B.C.
and Philo of Alexandria fl. A.D. 39. After the death of Philo, the center of
interest returned to Athens, where Plutarch of Chaeronia A.D. c.45c.125 studied
with Ammonius at the Academy, although Plutarch spent most of his career at his
home in nearby Boeotia. His many philosophical treatises, which are rich
sources for the history of philosophy, are gathered under the title Moralia;
his interest in ethics and moral education led him to write the Parallel Lives
paired biographies of famous Romans and Athenians, for which he is best known.
After this period, the Academy ceased to be the name for a species of Platonic
philosophy, although the school remained a center for Platonism, and was
especially prominent under the leadership of the Neoplatonist Proclus c.410
85. .
accidens: a
feature or property of a substance e.g., an organism or an artifact without
which the substance could still exist. According to a common essentialist view
of persons, Socrates’ size, color, and integrity are among his accidents, while
his humanity is not. For Descartes, thinking is the essence of the soul, while
any particular thought a soul entertains is an accident. According to a common
theology, God has no accidents, since all truths about him flow by necessity
from his nature. These examples suggest the diversity of traditional uses of
the notion of accident. There is no uniform conception; but the Cartesian view,
according to which the accidents are modes of ways of specifying the essence of
a substance, is representative. An important ambiguity concerns the identity of
accidents: if Plato and Aristotle have the same weight, is that weight one accident
say, the property of weighing precisely 70 kilograms or two one accident for
Plato, one for Aristotle? Different theorists give different answers and some
have changed their minds. Issues about accidents have become peripheral in this
century because of the decline of traditional concerns about substance. But the
more general questions about necessity and contingency are very much
alive.
accidentalism: the
metaphysical thesis that the occurrence of some events is either not
necessitated or not causally determined or not predictable. Many determinists
have maintained that although all events are caused, some nevertheless occur
accidentally, if only because the causal laws determining them might have been
different. Some philosophers have argued that even if determinism is true, some
events, such as a discovery, could not have been predicted, on grounds that to
predict a discovery is to make the discovery. The term may also designate a
theory of individuation: that individuals of the same kind or species are
numerically distinct in virtue of possessing some different accidental
properties. Two horses are the same in essence but numerically distinct because
one of them is black, e.g., while the other is white. Accidentalism presupposes
the identity of indiscernibles but goes beyond it by claiming that accidental
properties account for numerical diversity within a species. Peter Abelard
criticized a version of accidentalism espoused by his teacher, William of
Champeaux, on the ground that accidental properties depend for their existence
on the distinct individuals in which they inhere, and so the properties cannot
account for the distinctness of the individuals.
accidie
also acedia, apathy, listlessness, or ennui. This condition is problematic for
the internalist thesis that, necessarily, any belief that one morally ought to
do something is conceptually sufficient for having motivation to do it. Ann has
long believed that she ought, morally, to assist her ailing mother, and she has
dutifully acted accordingly. Seemingly, she may continue to believe this, even
though, owing to a recent personal tragedy, she now suffers from accidie and is
wholly lacking in motivation to assist her mother.
acosmism: a
term formed in analogy to ‘atheism,’ meaning the denial of the ultimate reality
of the world. Ernst Platner used it in 1776 to describe Spinoza’s philosophy,
arguing that Spinoza did not intend to deny “the existence of the Godhead, but
the existence of the world.” Maimon, Fichte, Hegel, and others make the same
claim. By the time of Feuerbach it was also used to characterize a basic
feature of Christianity: the denial of the world or worldliness. .
action theory, the study
of the ontological structure of human action, the process by which it
originates, and the ways in which it is explained. Most human actions are acts
of commission: they constitute a class of events in which a subject the agent
brings about some change or changes. Thus, in moving one’s finger, one brings
it about that one’s finger moves. When the change brought about is an ongoing
process e.g., the continuing appearance of words on a , the behavior is called
an activity writing. An action of omission occurs when an agent refrains from
performing an action of commission. Since actions of commission are events, the
question of their ontology is in part a matter of the general ontology of
change. An important issue here is whether what occurs when an action is
performed should be viewed as abstract or concrete. On the first approach,
actions are understood either as proposition-like entities e.g., Booth’s moving
a finger, or as a species of universal
namely, an act-type moving a finger. What “occurred” when Booth moved
his finger in Ford’s Theater on April 14, 1865, is held to be the abstract
entity in question, and the entity is viewed as repeatable: that is, precisely
the same entity is held to have occurred on every other occasion of Booth’s
moving his finger. When actions are viewed as concrete, on the other hand,
Booth’s moving his finger in Ford’s Theater is understood to be a
non-repeatable particular, accidental property action theory 6 4065A- 6 and the movement of the finger counts as
an acttoken, which instantiates the corresponding acttype. Concrete actions are
time-bound: each belongs to a single behavioral episode, and other
instantiations of the same act-type count as distinct events. A second
important ontological issue concerns the fact that by moving his finger, Booth
also fired a gun, and killed Lincoln. It is common for more than one thing to
be accomplished in a single exercise of agency, and how such doings are related
is a matter of debate. If actions are understood as abstract entities, the
answer is essentially foregone: there must be as many different actions on
Booth’s part as there are types exemplified. But if actions are viewed as
particulars the same token can count as an instance of more than one type, and
identity claims become possible. Here there is disagreement. Fine-grained
theories of act individuation tend to confine identity claims to actions that
differ only in ways describable through different modifications of the same
main verb e.g., where Placido both sings
and sings loudly. Otherwise, different types are held to require different
tokens: Booth’s action of moving his finger is held to have generated or given
rise to distinct actions of firing the gun and killing Lincoln, by virtue of
having had as causal consequences the gun’s discharge and Lincoln’s death. The
opposite, coarse-grained theory, however, views these causal relations as
grounds for claiming Booth’s acts were precisely identical. On this view, for
Booth to kill Lincoln was simply for him to do something that caused Lincoln’s
death which was in fact nothing more
than to move his finger and similarly
for his firing the gun. There is also a compromise account, on which Booth’s
actions are related as part to whole, each consisting in a longer segment of
the causal chain that terminates with Lincoln’s death. The action of killing
Lincoln consisted, on this view, in the entire sequence; but that of firing the
gun terminated with the gun’s discharge, and that of moving the finger with the
finger’s motion. When, as in Booth’s case, more than one thing is accomplished
in a single exercise of agency, some are done by doing others. But if all
actions were performed by performing others, an infinite regress would result.
There must, then, be a class of basic actions
i.e., actions fundamental to the performance of all others, but not
themselves done by doing something else. There is disagreement, however, on
which actions are basic. Some theories treat bodily movements, such as Booth’s
moving his finger, as basic. Others point out that it is possible to engage in
action but to accomplish less than a bodily movement, as when one tries to move
a limb that is restrained or paralyzed, and fails. According to these accounts,
bodily actions arise out of a still more basic mental activity, usually called
volition or willing, which is held to constitute the standard means for
performing all overt actions. The question of how bodily actions originate is
closely associated with that of what distinguishes them from involuntary and
reflex bodily events, as well as from events in the inanimate world. There is
general agreement that the crucial difference concerns the mental states that
attend action, and in particular the fact that voluntary actions typically
arise out of states of intending on the part of the agent. But the nature of
the relation is difficult, and there is the complicating factor that intention
is sometimes held to reduce to other mental states, such as the agent’s desires
and beliefs. That issue aside, it would appear that unintentional actions arise
out of more basic actions that are intentional, as when one unintentionally
breaks a shoelace by intentionally tugging on it. But how intention is first
translated into action is much more problematic, especially when bodily
movements are viewed as basic actions. One cannot, e.g., count Booth’s moving
his finger as an intentional action simply because he intended to do so, or
even on the ground if it is true that his intention caused his finger to move.
The latter might have occurred through a strictly autonomic response had Booth
been nervous enough, and then the moving of the finger would not have counted
as an action at all, much less as intentional. Avoiding such “wayward causal
chains” requires accounting for the agent’s voluntary control over what occurs
in genuinely intentional action a
difficult task when bodily actions are held to be basic. Volitional accounts
have greater success here, since they can hold that movements are intentional
only when the agent’s intention is executed through volitional activity. But
they must sidestep another threatened regress: if we call for an activity of
willing to explain why Booth’s moving his finger counts as intentional action,
we cannot do the same for willing itself. Yet on most accounts volition does
have the characteristics of intentional behavior. Volitional theories of action
must, then, provide an alternative account of how mental activity can be
intentional. Actions are explained by invoking the agent’s reasons for
performing them. Characteristically, a reason may be understood to consist in a
positive attitude of the agent toward one or another action theory action
theory 7 4065A- 7 outcome, and a belief
to the effect that the outcome may be achieved by performing the action in
question. Thus Emily might spend the summer in France out of a desire to learn
French, and a belief that spending time in France is the best way to do so.
Disputed questions about reasons include how confident the agent must be that
the action selected will in fact lead to the envisioned outcome, and whether
obligation represents a source of motivation that can operate independently of
the agent’s desires. Frequently, more than one course of action is available to
an agent. Deliberation is the process of searching out and weighing the reasons
for and against such alternatives. When successfully concluded, deliberation
usually issues in a decision, by which an intention to undertake one of the
contemplated actions is formed. The intention is then carried out when the time
for action comes. Much debate has centered on the question of how reasons are
related to decisions and actions. As with intention, an agent’s simply having a
reason is not enough for the reason to explain her behavior: her desire to
learn French notwithstanding, Emily might have gone to France simply because
she was transferred there. Only when an agent does something for a reason does
the reason explain what is done. It is frequently claimed that this bespeaks a
causal relation between the agent’s strongest reason and her decision or
action. This, however, suggests a determinist stance on the free will problem,
leading some philosophers to balk. An alternative is to treat reason
explanations as teleological explanations, wherein an action is held to be
reasonable or justified in virtue of the goals toward which it was directed.
But positions that treat reason explanations as non-causal require an
alternative account of what it is to decide or act for one reason rather than
another.
action
verb:
a verb applied to an agent and describing an activity, an action, or an attempt
at or a culmination of an action. Verbs applying to agents may be distinguished
in two basic ways: by whether they can take the progressive continuous form and
by whether or not there is a specific moment of occurrence/completion of the
action named by the verb. An activity verb is one describing something that
goes on for a time but with no inherent endpoint, such as ‘drive’, ‘laugh’, or
‘meditate’. One can stop doing such a thing but one cannot complete doing it.
Indeed, one can be said to have done it as soon as one has begun doing it. An
accomplishment verb is one describing something that goes on for a time toward
an inherent endpoint, such as ‘paint’ a fence, ‘solve’ a problem, or ‘climb’ a
mountain. Such a thing takes a certain time to do, and one cannot be said to
have done it until it has been completed. An achievement verb is one describing
either the culmination of an activity, such as ‘finish’ a job or ‘reach’ a
goal; the effecting of a change, such as ‘fire’ an employee or ‘drop’ an egg;
or undergoing a change, such as ‘hear’ an explosion or ‘forget’ a name. An
achievement does not go on for a period of time but may be the culmination of
something that does. Ryle singled out achievement verbs and state verbs see
below partly in order to disabuse philosophers of the idea that what
psychological verbs name must invariably be inner acts or activities modeled on
bodily actions or activities. A task verb is an activity verb that implies
attempting to do something named by an achievement verb. For example, to seek
is to attempt to find, to sniff is to attempt to smell, and to treat is to
attempt to cure. A state verb is a verb not an action verb describing a
condition, disposition, or habit rather than something that goes on or takes
place. Examples include ‘own’, ‘weigh’, ‘want’, ‘hate’, ‘frequent’, and
‘teetotal’. These differences were articulated by Zeno Vendler in Linguistics
and Philosophy 1967. Taking them into account, linguists have classified verbs
and verb phrases into four main aspectual classes, which they distinguish in
respect to the availability and interpretation of the simple present tense, of
the perfect tenses, of the progressive construction, and of various temporal
adverbials, such as adverbs like ‘yesterday’, ‘finally’, and ‘often’, and
prepositional phrases like ‘for a long time’ and ‘in a while’. Many verbs
belong to more than one category by virtue of having several related uses. For
example, ‘run’ is both an activity and an accomplishment verb, and ‘weigh’ is
both a state and an accomplishment verb. Linguists single out a class of
causative verbs, such as ‘force’, ‘inspire’, and ‘persuade’, some of which are
achievement and some accomplishment verbs. Such causative verbs as ‘break’,
‘burn’, and ‘improve’ have a correlative intransitive use, so that, e.g., to
break something is to cause it to break.
act-object
psychology: also called act-contentobject psychology, a
philosophical theory that identifies in every psychological state a mental act,
a lived-through phenomenological content, such as a mental image or description
of properties, and an intended object that the mental act is about or toward
which it is directed by virtue of its content. The distinction between the act,
content, and object of thought originated with Alois Höfler’s Logik 1890,
written in collaboration with Meinong. But the theory is historically most
often associated with its development in Kazimierz Twardowski’s Zur Lehre vom
Inhalt und Gegenstand der Vorstellung “On the Content and Object of
Presentations,” 1894, despite Twardowski’s acknowledgment of his debt to
Höfler. Act-object psychology arose as a reaction to Franz Brentano’s immanent
intentionality thesis in his influential Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt
“Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint,” 1874, in which Brentano maintains
that intentionality is “the mark of the mental,” by contrast with purely
physical phenomena. Brentano requires that intended objects belong immanently
to the mental acts that intend them a
philosophical commitment that laid Brentano open to charges of epistemological
idealism and psychologism. Yet Brentano’s followers, who accepted the
intentionality of thought but resisted what they came to see as its detachable
idealism and psychologism, responded by distinguishing the act-immanent
phenomenological content of a psychological state from its act-transcendent
intended object, arguing that Brentano had wrongly and unnecessarily conflated
mental content with the external objects of thought. Twardowski goes so far as
to claim that content and object can never be identical, an exclusion in turn
that is vigorously challenged by Husserl in his Logische Untersuchungen
“Logical Investigations,” 1913, 1922, and by others in the phenomenological
tradition who acknowledge the possibility that a self-reflexive thought can
sometimes be about its own content as intended object, in which content and
object are indistinguishable. Act-object psychology continues to be of interest
to contemporary philosophy because of its relation to ongoing projects in
phenomenology, and as a result of a resurgence of study of the concept of
intentionality and qualia in philosophy of mind, cognitive psychology, and
Gegenstandstheorie, or existent and non-existent intended object theory, in
philosophical logic and semantics.
adelard
of bath: Benedictine monk notable for his contributions to
the introduction of Arabic science in the West. After studying at Tours, he
taught at Laon, then spent seven years traveling in Italy, possibly Spain, and
Cilicia and Syria, before returning to England. In his dialogue On the Same and
the Different, he remarks, concerning universals, that the names of
individuals, species, and genera are imposed on the same essence regarded in
different respects. He also wrote Seventy-six Questions on Nature, based on
Arabic learning; works on the use of the abacus and the astrolabe; a work on
falconry; and translations of Abu Ma’shar’s Arabic active euthanasia Adelard of
Bath 9 4065A- 9 Shorter Introduction to
Astronomy, al-Khwarizmi’s fl. c.830 astronomical tables, and Euclid’s Elements.
adhyatman Sanskrit,
‘relating to or belonging to the self’, in early Hindu texts concerning such
topics as knowledge of the self, meditating on that which appertains to the
self, or spiritual exercise related to the self adhyatma-yoga. Later, it became
a term for the Supreme Spirit, the Supreme Self, or the soul, which, in Indian
thought, is other than the ego. In monistic systems, e.g. Advaita Vedanta, the
adhyatman is the one Self that is the impersonal Absolute Brahman, a state of
pure consciousness, ultimately the only Real. In dualist systems, e.g. Dvaita
Vedanta, it is the true self or soul of each individual.
adorno,
T. W.: philosopher and aesthetic theorist, one of the main philosophers of the
first generation of the Frankfurt School of critical theory. With Horkheimer,
Adorno gave philosophical direction to the Frankfurt School and its research
projects in its Institute for Social Research. An accomplished musician and
composer, Adorno first focused on the theory of culture and art, working to
develop a non-reductionist but materialist theory of art and music in many
essays from the 1930s. Under the influence of Walter Benjamin, he turned toward
developing a “micrological” account of cultural artifacts, viewing them as
“constellations” of social and historical forces. As his collaboration with
Horkheimer increased, Adorno turned to the problem of a selfdefeating dialectic
of modern reason and freedom. Under the influence of the seemingly imminent
victory of the Nazis in Europe, this analysis focused on the “entwinement of
myth and Enlightenment.” The Dialectic of Enlightenment 1941 argues that
instrumental reason promises the subject autonomy from the forces of nature
only to enslave it again by its own repression of its impulses and
inclinations. The only way around this self-domination is “non-identity
thinking,” found in the unifying tendencies of a non-repressive reason. This
self-defeating dialectic is represented by the striking image of Ulysses tied
to the mast to survive his encounter with the Sirens. Adorno initially hoped
for a positive analysis of the Enlightenment to overcome this genealogy of
modern reason, but it is never developed. Instead, he turned to an increasingly
pessimistic analysis of the growing reification of modern life and of the
possibility of a “totally administered society.” Adorno held that “autonomous
art” can open up established reality and negate the experience of reification.
Aesthetic Theory 1970 develops this idea of autonomous art in terms of
aesthetic form, or the capacity of the internal organization of art to
restructure existing patterns of meaning. Authentic works of art have a
“truth-value” in their capacity to bring to awareness social contradictions and
antinomies. In Negative Dialectics 1966 Adorno provides a more general account
of social criticism under the “fragmenting” conditions of modern
rationalization and domination. These and other writings have had a large
impact on cultural criticism, particularly through Adorno’s analysis of popular
culture and the “culture industry.”
Advaita, also called
Uttara Mimamsa, in Hinduism, the non-dualistic form of Vedanta. Advaita Vedanta
makes an epistemological distinction not a metaphysical one between the level
of appearance and the level of reality. This marks off how things appear versus
how they are; there appear to be a multitude of distinct persons and physical
objects, and a personal deity, whereas there is only ineffable Brahman. This
doctrine, according to Advaita, is taught in the Upanishads and realized in an
esoteric enlightenment experience called moksha. The opposing evidence provided
by all experiences that a have a subject-consciousness-object structure e.g.,
seeing a sunset and evidence a distinction between what one experiences and
oneself, or b have a subject/content structure e.g., feeling pain and evidence
a distinction between oneself and one’s states, is dismissed on the ground that
these experiences involve “the making of distinctions.” Critics claim that
moksha itself, as an experience in which something allegedly is learned or
grasped, also must involve “the making of distinctions.”
aesthetic
attitude, the appropriate attitude or frame of mind for
approaching art or nature or other objects or events so that one might both
appreciate its intrinsic perceptual qualities, and as a result have an
aesthetic experience. The aesthetic attitude has been construed in many ways: 1
as disinterested, so that one’s experience of the work is not affected by any interest
in its possible practical uses, 2 as a “distancing” of oneself from one’s own
personal concerns, 3 as the contemplation of an object, purely as an object of
sensation, as it is in itself, for its own sake, in a way unaffected by any
cognition or knowledge one may have of it. These different notions of aesthetic
attitude have at times been combined within a single theory. There is
considerable doubt about whether there is such a thing as an aesthetic
attitude. There is neither any special kind of action nor any special way of
performing an ordinary action that ensures that we see a work as it “really
is,” and that results in our having an aesthetic experience. Furthermore, there
are no purely sensory experiences, divorced from any cognitive content whatsoever.
Criticisms of the notion of aesthetic attitude have reinforced attacks on
aesthetics as a separate field of study within philosophy.
aesthetic
formalism: the view that in our interactions with works of art,
form should be given primacy. Rather than taking ‘formalism’ as the name of one
specific theory in the arts, it is better and more typical to take it to name
that type of theory which emphasizes the form of the artwork. Or, since
emphasis on form is something that comes in degrees, it is best to think of
theories of art as ranged on a continuum of more formalist and less formalist.
It should be added that theories of art are typically complex, including
definitions of art, recommendations concerning what we should attend to in art,
analyses of the nature of the aesthetic, recommendations concerning the making
of aesthetic evaluations, etc.; and each of these components may be more
formalist or less so. Those who use the concept of form mainly wish to contrast
the artifact itself with its relations to entities outside itself with its representing various things, its
symbolizing various things, its being expressive of various things, its being
the product of various intentions of the artist, its evoking various states in
beholders, its standing in various relations of influence and similarity to
preceding, succeeding, and contemporary works, etc. There have been some,
however, who in emphasizing form have meant to emphasize not just the artifact
but the perceptible form or design of the artifact. Kant, e.g., in his theory
of aesthetic excellence, not only insisted that the only thing relevant to
determining the beauty of an object is its appearance, but within the
appearance, the form, the design: in visual art, not the colors but the design
that the colors compose; in music, not the timbre of the individual sounds but
the formal relationships among them. It comes as no surprise that theories of
music have tended to be much more formalist than theories of literature and
drama, with theories of the visual arts located in between.
aesthetic
property: a property or quality such as being dainty, garish,
graceful, balanced, charming, majestic, trite, elegant, lifeless, ugly, or
beautiful. By contrast, non-aesthetic properties are properties that require no
special sensitivity or perceptiveness to perceive such as a painting’s being predominantly
blue, its having a small red square in a corner or a kneeling figure in the
foreground, or that the music becomes louder at a given point. Sometimes it is
argued that a special perceptiveness or taste is needed to perceive a work’s
aesthetic qualities, and that this is a defining feature of a property’s being
aesthetic. A corollary of this view is that aesthetic qualities cannot be
defined in terms of non-aesthetic qualities, though some have held that
aesthetic qualities supervene on non-aesthetic qualities.
aesthetics: the
branch of philosophy that examines the nature of art and the character of our
adventitious ideas and experience of art and of the natural environment. It
emerged as a separate field of philosophical inquiry during the eighteenth
century in England and on the Continent. Recognition of aesthetics as a
separate branch of philosophy coincided with the development of theories of art
that grouped together painting, poetry, sculpture, music, and dance and often
landscape gardening as the same kind of thing, les beaux arts, or the fine
arts. Baumgarten coined the term ‘aesthetics’ in his Reflections on Poetry 1735
as the name for one of the two branches of the study of knowledge, i.e., for
the study of sensory experience coupled with feeling, which he argued provided
a different type of knowledge from the distinct, abstract ideas studied by
“logic.” He derived it from the ancient Grecian aisthanomai ‘to perceive’, and
“the aesthetic” has always been intimately connected with sensory experience
and the kinds of feelings it arouses. Questions specific to the field of
aesthetics are: Is there a special attitude, the aesthetic attitude, which we
should take toward works of art and the natural environment, and what is it
like? Is there a distinctive type of experience, an aesthetic experience, and
what is it? Is there a special object of attention that we can call the
aesthetic object? Finally, is there a distinctive value, aesthetic value,
comparable with moral, epistemic, and religious values? Some questions overlap
with those in the philosophy of art, such as those concerning the nature of
beauty, and whether there is a faculty of taste that is exercised in judging
the aesthetic character and value of natural objects or works of art.
Aesthetics also encompasses the philosophy of art. The most central issue in
the philosophy of art has been how to define ‘art’. Not all cultures have, or
have had, a concept of art that coincides with the one that emerged in Western
Europe during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. What justifies our
applying our concept to the things people in these other cultures have
produced? There are also many pictures including paintings, songs, buildings,
and bits of writing, that are not art. What distinguishes those pictures,
musical works, etc., that are art from those that are not? Various answers have
been proposed that identify the distinguishing features of art in terms of form,
expressiveness, intentions of the maker, and social roles or uses of the
object. Since the eighteenth century there have been debates about what kinds
of things count as “art.” Some have argued that architecture and ceramics are
not art because their functions are primarily utilitarian, and novels were for
a long time not listed among the “fine arts” because they are not embodied in a
sensuous medium. Debates continue to arise over new media and what may be new
art forms, such as film, video, photography, performance art, found art,
furniture, posters, earthworks, and computer and electronic art. Sculptures
these days may be made out of dirt, feces, or various discarded and
mass-produced objects, rather than marble or bronze. There is often an explicit
rejection of craft and technique by twentieth-century artists, and the subject
matter has expanded to include the banal and everyday, and not merely
mythological, historical, and religious subjects as in years past. All of these
developments raise questions about the relevance of the category of “fine” or
“high” art. Another set of issues in philosophy of art concerns how artworks
are to be interpreted, appreciated, and understood. Some views emphasize that
artworks are products of individual efforts, so that a work should be
understood in light of the producer’s knowledge, skill, and intentions. Others
see the meaning of a work as established by social conventions and practices of
the artist’s own time, but which may not be known or understood by the producer.
Still others see meaning as established by the practices of the users, even if
they were not in effect when the work was produced. Are there objective
criteria or standards for evaluating individual artworks? There has been much
disagreement over whether value judgments have universal validity, or whether
there can be no disputing about taste, if value judgments are relative to the
tastes and interests of each individual or to some group of individuals who
share the same tastes and interests. A judgment such as “This is good”
certainly seems to make a claim about the work itself, though such a claim is
often based on the sort of feeling, understanding, or experience a person has
obtained from the work. A work’s aesthetic or artistic value is generally distinguished
from simply liking it. But is it possible to establish what sorts of knowledge
or experiences any given work should provide to any suitably prepared
perceiver, and what would it be to be suitably prepared? It is a matter of
contention whether a work’s aesthetic and artistic values are independent of
its moral, political, or epistemic stance or impact. Philosophy of art has also
dealt with the nature of taste, beauty, imagination, creativity,
repreaesthetics aesthetics 12 4065A- 12
sentation, expression, and expressiveness; style; whether artworks convey
knowledge or truth; the nature of narrative and metaphor; the importance of
genre; the ontological status of artworks; and the character of our emotional
responses to art. Work in the field has always been influenced by philosophical
theories of language or meaning, and theories of knowledge and perception, and
continues to be heavily influenced by psychological and cultural theory,
including versions of semiotics, psychoanalysis, cognitive psychology,
feminism, and Marxism. Some theorists in the late twentieth century have denied
that the aesthetic and the “fine arts” can legitimately be separated out and
understood as separate, autonomous human phenomena; they argue instead that
these conceptual categories themselves manifest and reinforce certain kinds of
cultural attitudes and power relationships. These theorists urge that
aesthetics can and should be eliminated as a separate field of study, and that
“the aesthetic” should not be conceived as a special kind of value. They favor
instead a critique of the roles that images not only painting, but film,
photography, and advertising, sounds, narrative, and three-dimensional
constructions have in expressing and shaping human attitudes and experiences.
a
fortiori argument: an argument that moves from the premises
that everything which possesses a certain characteristics will possess some
further characteristics and that certain things possess the relevant
characteristics to an eminent degree to the conclusion that a fortiori even
more so these things will possess the further characteristics. The second
premise is often left implicit, so a fortiori arguments are often enthymemes.
An example of an a fortiori argument can be found in Plato’s Crito: We owe gratitude
and respect to our parents and so should do nothing to harm them. Athenians owe
even greater gratitude and respect to the laws of Athens and so a fortiori
should do nothing to harm those laws.
African
philosophy: the philosophy produced by the preliterate cultures
of Africa, distinctive in that African philosophy in the traditional setting is
unwritten. For someone who is interested in studying, say, Chinese or Arabic
philosophy, the written works of the individual thinkers are available; African
philosophy, by contrast with the exception of Ethiopian philosophy, has
produced no written philosophical works. The lack of written philosophical
literature in Africa’s cultural past is the outstanding reason for the
persistent skepticism about the existence of African philosophy often
entertained by scholars. There are some who would withhold the term
‘philosophy’ from African traditional thought and would reserve that term for
the philosophical works being written by individual African philosophers today.
There are others who, on the basis of i their own conception of the nature of
philosophy, ii their sense of the history of the development of philosophical
ideas in other cultures, iii their conviction about the importance of the
universal character of the human capacity to wonder, or of the curiosity that
leads some individuals in various cultures to raise fundamental questions about
human life and experience, or iv their conviction that literacy is not a
necessary condition for philosophizing, would apply ‘philosophy’ to African
traditional thought, even though some of them would want to characterize it
further as ethnophilosophy or folk philosophy. Two assumptions made about the
character of African traditional thought have earned it those labels: one is
the alleged communal collective subscription to a ‘monolithic’ set of ideas or
beliefs; the other is the alleged lack of individualist elements in traditional
thought. These assumptions have led some scholars to believe that African
thought is a system of ideas or beliefs unanimously held by a whole tribe
ethnos, even though it may be argued that thought as such is always the product
of an individual intellect. An individual may refine or build on the
philosophical work of another individual, but the product will still be an
individual intellectual enterprise. What seems to have happened in Africa is
that due to lack of a doxographic tradition, the ideas of unnamable because
unidentifiable individuals that gained currency among the wider community became
part of the pool of communal thought, as if they were the thought or a
production of a whole ethnos, and expressed in its oral literature: in
proverbs, myths and folk tales, rituals, religious beliefs, art symbols,
customs, and traditions. These would, in fact, constitute the warp and woof of
the fabric of traditional philosophy in Africa. An extensive and profound
critical evaluation of concepts and values of traditional thought can be the
starting point of modern African philosophy. The reason is that most of the
traditional concepts, beliefs, and values have not relaxed their grip on modern
African life and thought. But the modern African philosophy will also have to
include the conceptual responses to the circumstances, experiences, and
problems of modern African societies. This aspect of the philosophical
enterprise will have to deal with the critical analysis, interpretation, and
assessment of the changes that traditional values and ideas are going through
in response to the pressures, both internal and external, weighing heavily on
them through the ethos of contemporary life. Thus, African philosophy will not
be a unique system, a windowless monad impervious to external influences. But
it is conceivable perhaps expected that it will have some characteristics of its
own. As to the central themes of African philosophy, what one can appropriately
do at this stage of its development is indicate some of the persistent
assumptions, beliefs, and values embedded in African cultural and historical
experiences. These would undoubtedly include: supernaturalism ideas about God and other spiritual entities
conceived in African ontologies, the dualistic or monistic perception of the
external world, the alleged religiosity or spirituality of the African life,
human destiny, and the moral life; personhood and communitarianism social and humanistic ethics, notions of the
community and the common good, the nature of the good life, the status of
individuality in African socioethical thought; political ideas chiefship and traditional political
authority, traditional ideas of democracy, democratic thought in a
communitarian framework, consensual politics and decision making, political
legitimacy, corruption and political morality; and tradition and modernity the notion of culture, ethnicity and
nationhood, the nature and development of national culture and identity, the
concept of development, technology, society, and values. These themes and
others have generated various ideas that must be critically analyzed and evaluated
by contemporary African philosophers, who would in this way create a modern
African philosophy with origins in the comprehensive culture and many-sided
experiences of the African, yet aspects of which may be considered by other
cultures to be worthwhile. Thanks to the literary culture they have inherited,
contemporary African philosophers, through their own individual analyses and
arguments, are in a position to contribute to the emergence of a modern African
philosophy that would naturally comprise a multiplicity of individual
philosophical ideas, arguments, and positions. K.G. agama Sanskrit, ‘what has
come down’, an authoritative religious text of an Indian sect. There are Hindu,
Jain, and Buddhist agamas. The Hindu agamas fall into three main classes:
Vaifpava texts concerning the worship of Vishnu, Saiva texts dealing with
worship of Siva, and Tantric texts regarding worship of Sakti. Saivism, e.g.,
has twenty-eight agamas. An agama may give instructions regarding making
temples or idols, offer meditation techniques, teach philosophical doctrines,
or commend methods of worship. The Mahayana Buddhist term for the basic
teachings of the Theravada Buddhist tradition is ‘agama’.
agape: unselfish
love for all persons. An ethical theory according to which such love is the
chief virtue, and actions are good to the extent that they express it, is
sometimes called agapism. Agape is the Grecian word most often used for love in
the New Testament, and is often used in modern languages to signify whatever
sort of love the writer takes to be idealized there. In New Testament Grecian,
however, it was probably a quite general word for love, so that any ethical
ideal must be found in the text’s substantive claims, rather than in the
linguistic meaning of the word. R.M.A. agathon, Grecian word meaning ‘a good’
or ‘the good’. From Socrates onward, agathon was taken to be a central object
of philosophical inquiry; it has frequently been assumed to be the goal of all
rational action. Plato in the simile of the sun in the Republic identified it
with the Form of the Good, the source of reality, truth, and intelligibility.
Aristotle saw it as eudaimonia, intellectual or practical virtue, a view that
found its way, via Stoicism and Neoplatonism, into Christianity. Modern theories
of utility can be seen as concerned with essentially the same Socratic
question.
agent
causation: the idea that the primary cause of an event is a
substance; more specifically, causation by a substance, as opposed to an event.
Thus a brick a substance may be said to be the cause of the breaking of the
glass. The expression is also used more narrowly by Reid and others for agama the
view that an action or event is caused by an exertion of power by some agent
endowed with will and understanding. Thus, a person may be said to be the cause
of her action of opening the door. In this restricted sense Reid called it “the
strict and proper sense”, an agent-cause must have the power to cause the
action or event and the power not to cause it. Moreover, it must be “up to” the
agent whether to cause the event or not to cause it. It is not “up to” the
brick whether to cause or not to cause the breaking of the glass. The
restricted sense of agent causation developed by Reid is closely tied to the
view that the agent possesses free will. Medieval philosophers distinguished
the internal activity of the agent from the external event produced by that
activity. The former was called “immanent causation” and the latter “transeunt
causation.” These terms have been adapted by Chisholm and others to mark the
difference between agent causation and event causation. The idea is that the
internal activity is agentcaused by the person whose activity it is; whereas
the external event is event-caused by the internal activity of the agent.
agnoiology
from Grecian agnoia, ‘ignorance’, the study of ignorance, its quality, and its
conditions.
agnosticism
from Grecian a-, ‘not’, and gnastos, ‘known’, term invented by Thomas Henry
Huxley in 1869 to denote the philosophical and religious attitude of those who
claim that metaphysical ideas can be neither proved nor disproved. Huxley
wrote, “I neither affirm nor deny the immortality of man. I see no reason for
believing it, but on the other hand, I have no means of disproving it. I have
no a priori objection to the doctrine.” Agnosticism is a form of skepticism
applied to metaphysics, especially theism. The position is sometimes attributed
to Kant, who held that we cannot have knowledge of God or immortality but must
be content with faith. Agnosticism should not be confused with atheism, the
belief that no god exists.
ahamkara
Sanskrit, ‘I-maker’, ‘I-crier’, in Hindu thought, the ego or faculty that gives
the sense of ‘I’ or individual personality; by extension, egotism, pride,
conceit. In the Sankhya and Yoga systems, it is the third element of
everchanging Nature evolving in creation. From it evolves the remainder of the
phenomenal world. Other than Nature, which includes the individual intellect
buddhi, the faculty of perception manas, the organs, and the senses, is the
unchanging individual self puruca, Atman. The human predicament results from
the ignorant identification of oneself with Nature rather than the true self.
In earlier texts the cosmic sense of ahamkara dominates as the means by which
the Creator formulates Himself to create the world. R.N.Mi. ahanta, Sanskrit
word meaning ‘indestructible’, ‘unchangeable’, ‘eternal’. In traditional Hindu
philosophical thought, the truly real was thought to be indestructible and
eternal. Thus, because the Upanishadic Brahman and its subjective counterpart,
the Atman, were regarded as the truly real, they were thought to be
unchangeable and eternal. The Hindu religious classic, the Bhagavad Gita
probably written between the fifth and the second century B.C., made ahanta a
well-known concept through the teachings of Krishna, who advised Arjuna that
even though one’s body may perish one’s soul is eternal and indestructible,
thus implying that the human soul contains the essence of the divine reality.
ahim
. sa
Sanskrit, traditionally and literally, nonviolence to living creatures; for
modern Indian thinkers, a positive sense of kindness to all creatures. To the
Jains, ahimsa was a vow to injure no living being jiva in thought, word, or
deed. Many Buddhists practice ahimsa as a precept that denies the existence of
the ego, since injuring another is an assertion of egoism. With the modern
period, particularly Gandhi, ahimsa was equated with self-sacrificial love for
all beings. For Gandhi it was the first vow of the satyagrahi, the one who
“held onto Truth,” the nonviolent resister.
aitia Grecian,
cause. Originally referring to responsibility for a crime, this Grecian term
came to be used by philosophers to signify causality in a somewhat broader
sense than the English ‘cause’ the
traditional rendering of aitia can
convey. An aitia is any answer to a why-question. According to Aristotle, how
such questions ought to be answered is a philosophical issue addressed
differently by different philosophers. He himself distinguishes four types of
answers, and thus four aitiai, by distinguishing different types of questions:
1 Why is the statue heavy? Because it is made of bronze material aitia. 2 Why
did Persians invade Athens? Because the Athenians had raided their territory
moving or efficient aitia. 3 Why are the angles of a triangle equal to two
right angles? Because of the triangle’s nature formal aitia. 4 Why did someone
walk after dinner? Because or for the sake of his health final aitia. Only the
second of these would typically be called a cause in English. Though some
render aitia as ‘explanatory principle’ or ‘reason’, these expressions inaptly
suggest a merely mental existence; instead, an aitia is a thing or aspect of a
thing.
akasa,
Sanskrit word translated as ‘ether’ or ‘space’. Indian philosophical systems
recognized various ontological categories, including that of substance. Akasa
was thought of as a substance because it was believed to be the substratum of
sound. Because akasa was understood to transmit sound waves, the term is better
translated as ‘ether’ than ‘space’, but scholars are not unanimous on this.
Akasa, though extended in space, was viewed as a non-material substance. It was
thought of as all-pervading, infinite, indivisible and imperceivable, being
inferred from the sensed quality of sound.
akrasia: also
spelled acrasia, Grecian term for weakness of will. Akrasia is a character
flaw, also called incontinence, exhibited primarily in intentional behavior
that conflicts with the agent’s own values or principles. Its contrary is
enkrateia strength of will, continence, self-control. Both akrasia and
enkrateia, Aristotle says, “are concerned with what is in excess of the state
characteristic of most people; for the continent abide by their resolutions
more, and the incontinent less, than most people can” Nicomachean Ethics
1152a2527. These resolutions may be viewed as judgments that it would be best
to perform an action of a certain sort, or better to do one thing than another.
Enkrateia, on that view, is the power kratos to act as one judges best in the
face of competing motivation. Akrasia is a want or deficiency of such power.
Aristotle himself limited the sphere of both states more strictly than is now
done, regarding both as concerned specifically with “pleasures and pains and
appetites and aversions arising through touch and taste” [1150a910].
Philosophers are generally more interested in incontinent and continent actions
than in the corresponding states of character. Various species of incontinent
or akratic behavior may be distinguished, including incontinent reasoning and
akratic belief formation. The species of akratic behavior that has attracted
most attention is uncompelled, intentional action that conflicts with a better
or best judgment consciously held by the agent at the time of action. If, e.g.,
while judging it best not to eat a second piece of pie, you intentionally eat
another piece, you act incontinently
provided that your so acting is uncompelled e.g., your desire for the
pie is not irresistible. Socrates denied that such action is possible, thereby
creating one of the Socratic paradoxes. In “unorthodox” instances of akratic
action, a deed manifests weakness of will even though it accords with the
agent’s better judgment. A boy who decides, against his better judgment, to
participate in a certain dangerous prank, might
owing to an avoidable failure of nerve
fail to execute his decision. In such a case, some would claim, his
failure to act on his decision manifests weakness of will or akrasia. If,
instead, he masters his fear, his participating in the prank might manifest
strength of will, even though his so acting conflicts with his better judgment.
The occurrence of akratic actions seems to be a fact of life. Unlike many such
apparent facts, this one has received considerable philosophical scrutiny for
nearly two and a half millennia. A major source of the interest is clear:
akratic action raises difficult questions about the connection between thought
and action, a connection of paramount importance for most philosophical
theories of the explanation of intentional behavior. Insofar as moral theory
does not float free of evidence about the etiology of human behavior, the tough
questions arise there as well. Ostensible akratic action, then, occupies a
philosophical space in the intersection of the philosophy of mind and moral
theory.
akcara Sanskrit,
‘imperishable’, the highest reality in a variety of Hindu thought systems. From
earliest times it also meant ‘syllable’, reflecting the search for the ultimate
reality by Vedic priest-thinkers and the early primacy given to the sacred
utterance as the support of the ritual order of the universe, later identified
as the syllable Om. In later texts and the systematic thinkers it refers to the
highest reality, which may be a personal supreme being or an impersonal
absolute, such as the Highest Self paramatman of Shankara 70050.
Non-technically, it can be used in any thought system of any entity believed to
be imperishable. R.N.Mi. alaya-vijñana, Sanskrit term meaning literally
‘storehouse consciousness’, a category developed by Indian Buddhist
metaphysicians to solve some specific philosophical problems, notably those of
delayed karmic effect and causation at a temporal distance. The alaya-vijñana
“stores,” in unactualized but potential form, as “seeds,” the results of an
agent’s volitional actions. These karmic “seeds” may come to fruition at a
later time. Most Buddhists think of moments of consciousness vijñana as
intentional having an object, being of something; the alaya-vijñana is an
exception, allowing for the continuance of consciousness when the agent is
apparently not conscious of anything such as during dreamless sleep, and so
also for the continuance of potential for future action during those
times.
Albert
of Saxony: terminist logician from lower Saxony who taught in
the arts faculty at Paris, 135162. He never finished his theology degree, as,
under the influence of Buridan and Nicholas of Oresme, he turned to
mathematics, physics, and logic. He was a founder of the of Vienna in 1365 and was bishop of
Halberstadt from 1366. His works on logic include Logic, Questions on the
Posterior Analytics, Sophismata, Treatise on Obligations, and Insolubilia. He
also wrote questions on Aristotle’s physical works and on John of Sacrobosco’s
De Sphaera, and short treatises on squaring the circle and on the ratio of the
diameter to the side of a square. His work is competent but rarely
original.
Albertus
Magnus: Dominican philosopher. As a Parisian master of
theology, he served on a commission that condemned the Talmud. He left Paris to
found the first Dominican studium generale in Germany at Cologne in 1248. From
1252 until old age, Albert was repeatedly asked to be an arbiter and
peacemaker. After serving briefly as bishop of Regensburg in 1260, he was
ordered to preach the crusade of 1263 64 in Germany. He spent his last years
writing in Cologne. Albert contributed to philosophy chiefly as a commentator
on Aristotle, although he occasionally reached different conclusions from
Aristotle. Primarily, Albert was a theologian, as is evident from his extensive
commentary on Peter Lombard’s Sentences and his commentaries on the Old and New
Testaments. As a theologian, he customarily developed his thought by commenting
on traditional texts. For Albert, Aristotle offered knowledge ascertainable
using reason, just as Scripture, based on God’s word, tells of the
supernatural. Albert saw Aristotle’s works, many newly available, as an
encyclopedic compendium of information on the natural universe; included here
is the study of social and political conditions and ethical obligations, for
Aristotelian “natural knowledge” deals with human nature as well as natural
history. Aristotle is the Philosopher; however, unlike Holy Scripture, he must
be corrected in places. Like Holy Scripture, though, Aristotle is occasionally
obscure. To rectify these shortcomings one must rely on other authorities: in
the case of Holy Scripture, reference is to the church fathers and established
interpreters; in the case of Aristotle, to the Peripatetics. The term
‘Peripatetics’ extends to modern as well as ancient authors al-Farabi, Avicenna Ibn-Sina, and Averroes
Ibn-Rushd, as well as Themistius and Alexander of Aphrodisias; even Seneca,
Maimonides, and “our” Boethius are included. For the most part, Albert saw
Plato through the eyes of Aristotle and Averroes, since apart from the Timaeus
very little of Plato’s work was available in Latin. Albert considered the Liber
de causis a work of Aristotle, supplemented by alFarabi, Avicenna, and
al-Ghazali and translated into Latin. When he commented on the Liber de causis,
Albert was not aware that this Neoplatonic work
which speaks of the world emanating from the One as from a first
cause was based on Proclus and
ultimately on Plotinus. But Albert’s student, Aquinas, who had better
translations of Aristotle, recognized that the Liber de causis was not an
Aristotelian work. Albert’s metaphysics, which is expounded in his commentaries
on Aristotle’s Metaphysics on the Liber de causis, contains profoundly
contradictory elements. His inclination to synthesis led him to attempt to
reconcile these elements as on social
and ecclesiastical questions he often sought peace through compromise. In his Metaphysics
and Physics and in his On the Heavens and On Generation and Corruption,
Aristotle presented the world as ever-changing and taught that an unmoved mover
“thought thinking itself” maintained everything in movement and animation by
allowing its spiritual nature to be seen in all its cold, unapproachable
beauty. The Liber de causis, on the other hand, develops the theory that the
world emanates from the One, causing everything in the world in its pantheistic
creativity, so that the caused world returns in mystic harmony to the One. Thus
Albert’s Aristotelian commentaries, begun in 125152, culminated in 1265 with
his commentary on a work whose pseudo-Aristotelian character he was unable to
recognize. Nevertheless, the Christian Neoplatonism that Albert placed on an
Aristotelian basis was to exert an influence for centuries. In natural
philosophy, Albert often arrived at views independent of Aristotle. According
to Aristotle’s Physics, motion belongs to no single category; it is incomplete
being. Following Avicenna and Averroes, Albert asks whether “becoming black,”
e.g. which ceases when change ceases and
blackness is finally achieved differs
from blackness essentially essentia or only in its being esse. Albert
establishes, contrary to Avicenna, that the distinction is only one of being.
In his discussions of place and space, stimulated by Avicenna, Albert also
makes an original contribution. Only two dimensions width and breadth are essential to place, so that a fluid in a
bottle is framed by the inner surface of the bottle. According to Albert, the
significance of the third dimension, depth, is more modest, but nonetheless
important. Consider a bucket of water: its base is the essential part, but its
round walls maintain the cohesion of the water. For Aristotle, time’s material
foundation is distinct from its formal definition. Materially, the movement of
the fixed stars is basic, although time itself is neither movement nor change.
Rather, just as before and after are continuous in space and there are earlier
and later moments in movement as it proceeds through space, so time being the number of motion has earlier and later moments or “nows.” The
material of time consists of the uninterrupted flow of the indivisible nows,
while time’s form and essential expression is number. Following al-Farabi and
Avicenna, Albert’s interpretation of these doctrines emphasizes not only the
uninterrupted continuity of the flow of “nows,” but also the quantity of time,
i.e., the series of discrete, separate, and clearly distinct numbers. Albert’s
treatment of time did not lend itself well to later consideration of time as a
dimension; his concept of time is therefore not well suited to accommodate our
unified concept of space-time. The use of the pseudo-Aristotelian De
proprietatibus elementorum in De causis proprietatum elementorum gave Albert’s
worldview a strong astrological flavor. At issue here is how the planets
influence the earth and mankind. Particularly important is the influence of
Jupiter and Saturn on fire and the seas; when increased, it could produce fiery
conflagrations, and when circumscribed, floods. Albert was encyclopedic: a
scientist and scholar as well as a philosopher and theologian. In addition to
the works mentioned, he produced commentaries on Pseudo-Dionysius, a Summa de
creaturis, a Summa Theologica, and many other treatises. Unlike other
commentators, his exposition was continuous, an extensive paraphrase; he
provided a complete Latin and Christian philosophy. Even in his lifetime, he
was a named authority; according to Roger Bacon, his views were often given as
much weight as those of Aristotle, Avicenna, and Averroes. His students or
followers include Aquinas, Ulrich of Strassburg d.1278?, Theodoric of Freiberg
d.1310?, Giles of Lessines d.1304?, Meister Eckhart, Johannes Tauler d.1361,
Henry Suso d.1366, and Jan van Ruysbroeck d.1381.
alchemy: a
quasi-scientific practice and mystical art, mainly ancient and medieval, that
had two broad aims: to change baser metals into gold and to develop the elixir
of life, the means to immortality. Classical Western alchemy probably
originated in Egypt in the first three centuries A.D. with earlier Chinese and
later Islamic and Indian variants and was practiced in earnest in Europe by
such figures as Paracelsus and Newton until the eighteenth century. Western
alchemy addressed concerns of practical metallurgy, but its philosophical
significance derived from an early Grecian theory of the relations among the
basic elements and from a religious-allegorical Albinus alchemy 18 4065A- 18 understanding of the alchemical
transmutation of ores into gold, an understanding that treats this process as a
spiritual ascent from human toward divine perfection. The purification of crude
ores worldly matter into gold material perfection was thought to require a
transmuting agent, the philosopher’s stone, a mystical substance that, when
mixed with alcohol and swallowed, was believed to produce immortality spiritual
perfection. The alchemical search for the philosopher’s stone, though abortive,
resulted in the development of ultimately useful experimental tools e.g., the
steam pump and methods e.g., distillation.
alethic
modalities: historically, the four central ways or modes in
which a given proposition might be true or false: necessity, contingency,
possibility, and impossibility. The term ‘alethic’ derives from Grecian
aletheia, ‘truth’. These modalities, and their logical interconnectedness, can
be characterized as follows. A proposition that is true but possibly false is
contingently true e.g., that Aristotle taught Alexander; one that is true and
not-possibly i.e., “impossibly” false is necessarily true e.g., that red things
are colored. Likewise, a proposition that is false but possibly true is
contingently false e.g., that there are no tigers; and one that is false and
not-possibly true is necessarily false e.g., that seven and five are fourteen.
Though any one of the four modalities can be defined in terms of any other,
necessity and possibility are generally taken to be the more fundamental
notions, and most systems of alethic modal logic take one or the other as
basic. Distinct modal systems differ chiefly in regard to their treatment of
iterated modalities, as in the proposition It is necessarily true that it is possibly
true that it is possibly true that there are no tigers. In the weakest of the
most common systems, usually called T, every iterated modality is distinct from
every other. In the stronger system S4, iterations of any given modality are
redundant. So, e.g., the above proposition is equivalent to It is necessarily
true that it is possibly true that there are no tigers. In the strongest and
most widely accepted system S5, all iteration is redundant. Thus, the two
propositions above are both equivalent simply to It is possibly true that there
are no tigers.
Alexander,
Samuel 18591938, Australian-born British philosopher. Born in Sydney, he was
educated at Balliol, Oxford, and taught for most of his career at the of Manchester. His aim, which he most fully
realized in Space, Time, and Deity 1920, was to provide a realistic account of
the place of mind in nature. He described nature as a series of levels of
existence where irreducible higher-level qualities emerge inexplicably when
lower levels become sufficiently complex. At its lowest level reality consists
of space-time, a process wherein points of space are redistributed at instants
of time and which might also be called pure motion. From complexities in
space-time matter arises, followed by secondary qualities, life, and mind.
Alexander thought that the still-higher quality of deity, which characterizes
the whole universe while satisfying religious sentiments, is now in the process
of emerging from mind.
Alexander
of Aphrodisias: Grecian philosopher, one of the foremost
commentators on Aristotle in late antiquity. He exercised considerable
influence on later Grecian, Arabic, and Latin philosophy through to the
Renaissance. On the problem of universals, Alexander endorses a brand of
conceptualism: although several particulars may share a single, common nature,
this nature does not exist as a universal except while abstracted in thought
from the circumstances that accompany its particular instantiations. Regarding
Aristotle’s notorious distinction between the “agent” and “patient” intellects
in On the Soul III.5, Alexander identifies the agent intellect with God, who,
as the most intelligible entity, makes everything else intelligible. As its own
self-subsistent object, this intellect alone is imperishable; the human
intellect, in contrast, perishes at death. Of Alexander’s many commentaries,
only those on Aristotle’s Metaphysics Ad, Prior Analytics I, Topics, On the
Senses, and Meterologics are extant. We also have two polemical treatises, On
Fate and On Mixture, directed against the Stoics; a psychological treatise, the
De anima based on Aristotle’s; as well as an assortment of essays including the
De intellectu and his Problems and Solutions. Nothing is known of Alexander’s
life apart from his appointment by the emperor Severus to a chair in
Aristotelian philosophy between 198 and 209.
Alexander
of Hales c.11851245, English Franciscan theologian, known as
the Doctor IrrefragaAlcinous Alexander of Hales 19 4065A- 19 bilis. The first to teach theology by lecturing
on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, Alexander’s emphasis on speculative theology
initiated the golden age of Scholasticism. Alexander wrote commentaries on the
Psalms and the Gospels; his chief works include his Glossa in quattuor libros
sententiarum, Quaestiones disputatatae antequam esset frater, and Quaestiones
quodlibetales. Alexander did not complete the Summa fratris Alexandri; Pope
Alexander IV ordered the Franciscans to complete the Summa Halesiana in 1255.
Master of theology in 1222, Alexander played an important role in the history
of the of Paris, writing parts of
Gregory IX’s Parens scientiarum 1231. He also helped negotiate the peace
between England and France in 123536. Later in 1236 he gave up his position as
canon of Lichfield and archdeacon of Coventry to become a Franciscan, the first
Franciscan master of theology; his was the original Franciscan chair of
theology at Paris. Among the Franciscans, his most prominent disciples include
St. Bonaventure, Richard Rufus of Cornwall, and John of La Rochelle, to whom he
resigned his chair in theology near the end of his life. R.W. Alexandrian
School, those Neoplatonic philosophers contemporary with and subsequent to
Proclus A.D. 41285 who settled in Alexandria and taught there. They include Hermeias
fl. c.440, Proclus’s fellow-student of Syrianus; Hermeias’s son Ammonius either
435517 or 445 526; and Ammonius’s three pupils, John Philoponus c.490575,
Simplicius writing after 532, and Asclepius mid-sixth century. Later
Alexandrians include Olympiodorus 495/505 after 565 and the Christians Elias
fl. c.540 and David late sixth century. All these worked exclusively or
primarily on the exegesis of Aristotle. Damascius c.456540 also took lectures
from Ammonius at some time between 475 and 485, but in his doctrine he belongs
much more to the Athenian tradition. Simplicius, on the other hand, while he
moved to Athens to teach, remains more in the Alexandrian tradition. Ever since
Karl Praechter, who was influenced by a Hegelian view of historical development,
the Alexandrian Platonists have been seen as professing a simpler form of
metaphysics than the Athenian School, and deliberately avoiding controversy
with the powerful Christian establishment in Alexandria by confining themselves
largely to logic, mathematics, and the exegesis of Aristotle. There is a
certain manifest truth in this picture, but modern scholarship in particular
Ilsetraut Hadot has done much to show that even in Ammonius’s commentaries on
Aristotle there lurks distinctive Neoplatonic doctrine, so that the contrast
with the Athenian School has become somewhat blurred. The School may be said to
have come to an end with the departure of Stephanus to take up the chair of
philosophy in Constantinople in about 610.
Alpharabius: al-Farabi,
Abu Nasr, also called Abunaser, philosopher. Born in Turkestan, he studied and
taught in Baghdad when it was the cultural capital of the Islamic world,
responsive to the philosophical and scientific legacy of late antiquity.
AlFarabi was highly instrumental in effecting a transition of Grecian
philosophy, last publicly known in its entirety in sixth-century Alexandria,
into Islamic culture. Despite ongoing opposition because of philosophy’s
identification with pagan and Christian authors, al-Farabi succeeded in
naturalizing Western philosophy in the Islamic world, where it retained
vitality for the next three hundred years. Al-Farabi became known as “the
second teacher,” after Aristotle the main source of philosophical information.
His summaries and interpretations of the teachings of Aristotle and Plato were
widely read, and his attempt at synthesizing their views was very influential.
Believing in the universal nature of truth and holding Plato and Aristotle in
the highest esteem, he minimized their differences and adopted Neoplatonic
teachings that incorporated elements of both traditions. Unlike the first
philosopher of the Islamic world, the ninth-century al-Kindi, al-Farabi was in
possession of full Arabic translations of many of the most important texts of
classical times and of some major Hellenistic commentaries on them. His own
commentaries and digests of the works of Plato and Aristotle made them more
accessible to later generations of scholars, even as his relatively independent
treatises established a high standard of logical rigor and subtlety for later
Muslim and Jewish philosophers. Avicenna found his Metaphysics commentary
indispensable for understanding Aristotle’s text, while Maimonides recommended
all his writings, calling them “pure flour.” Medieval Scholastic thought,
however, was more interested in Averroes and Avicenna than in al-Farabi.
Contemporary scholars such as Leo Strauss and Muhsin Mahdi have emphasized the
esoteric nature of al-Farabi’s writings, seen as critical for understanding much
of medieval Islamic and Jewish philosophy. Al-Farabi’s main interests lay in
logic and political theory. He understood that the Organon was just that, a
universal instrument for understanding and improving reasoning and logical
discourse. Against the traditional grammarians of Islam, he argued for the
value-free and neutral nature of Grecian logic, while against the theologians
of Islam, the mutakallimun, he emphasized the difference between their
dialectical type of discourse and the preferred demonstrative syllogism of the
philosophers. Much of the responsibility for the separation between Islamic
theology and philosophy may be attributed to al-Farabi, who avoided engaging
religious dogmas and specifically Muslim beliefs as much as possible. He was able
to accommodate belief in prophecy and revelation to a general theory of
emanation, though he made no special claims for the prophet of Islam. His
general view of religion was that it was a popular and symbolic representation
of philosophical ideas, often designed by philosophers. The influence of
Plato’s Republic in this and other areas of political philosophy is evident,
though al-Farabi’s Principles of the Views of the Citizens of the Best State
manages to give an Islamic coloration to Platonic teachings. Al-Farabi’s
metaphysical beliefs are more problematical still, and he was reputed to have
disowned his earlier belief in the immortality of the soul.
al-Ghazali, Abu Hamid: Islamic
philosopher, theologian, jurist, and mystic. He was born in Khurasan and
educated in Nishapur, then an intellectual center of eastern Islam. He was
appointed the head of a seminary, the newly founded Nizamiyah of Baghdad, in
which he taught law and theology with great success. Yet his exposure to logic
and philosophy led him to seek a certainty in knowledge beyond that assumed by
his profession. At first he attempted to address his problem academically, but
after five years in Baghdad he resigned, left his family, and embarked on the
mystic’s solitary quest for al-Haqq Arabic for ‘the truth’, ‘the True One’. As
a Sufi he wandered for ten years through many of Islam’s major cities and
centers of learning, finally returning to Nishapur and to teaching theology
before his death. Al-Ghazali’s literary and intellectual legacy is particularly
rich and multifaceted. In the catholicity of his work and the esteem in which
he is held within Islam he may be compared to Aquinas and Maimonides in the
Christian and Jewish traditions respectively. His Revivification of the
Religious Sciences is considered to this day a major theological compendium.
His mystical treatises also have retained their popularity, as has his much
celebrated autobiography, The Deliverance from Error. This book chronicles his
lifelong quest for truth and certainty, and his disappointment with the
premises of dogmatic theology, both orthodox Sunni and heterodox Shiite
thought, as well as with the teachings of the philosophers. The light of truth
came to him, he believed, only through divine grace; he considered his senses
and reasoning powers all susceptible to error. It was this pervasive sense of
skepticism that led him, while still in Baghdad, to investigate philosophy’s
claims to knowledge. He first composed a summa of philosophical teachings,
based primarily on the views of Avicenna, and called it The Intentions of the
Philosophers. He later published a detailed and penetrating critique of these
views, The Incoherence of the Philosophers. Averroes arose later in Muslim
Spain to defend philosophy, particularly that of Aristotle, calling his book
The Incoherence of the Incoherence. Averroes’ work was more appreciated in the
West, however, which also preferred al-Ghazali’s Intentions to his Incoherence.
The former, shorn of its polemical purpose and thus appearing as a philosophical
summa, was translated by Dominicus Gundissalinus as Logica et Philosophia
Algazelis, giving al-Ghazali a reputation in the West as at least a sometime
advocate of philosophy. His attack upon the physics and metaphysics of his day,
which was an amalgam of Aristotelian and Neoplatonic doctrines, was firmly
rooted in Aristotelian logic, and anticipates Hume in understanding the
non-necessary nature of causal relationships. For al-Ghazali, the world as a
whole proceeds not by any eternal or logical necessity, but by the will of God.
That will is indefensible on philosophical grounds, he believed, as is the
philosophers’ notion of divine omniscience. Their god cannot on their terms be
related to the world, and is ultimately redundant logically. What is regarded
as miraculous becomes possible, once nature is understood to have no autonomy
or necessary entailments.
algorithm: a
clerical or effective procedure that can be applied to any of a class of
certain symbolic inputs and that will in a finite time and number of steps
eventuate in a result in a corresponding symbolic output. A function for which
an algorithm sometimes more than one can be given is an algorithmic function.
The following are common examples: a given n, finding the nth prime number; b
differentiating a polynomial; c finding the greatest common divisor of x and y
the Euclidean algorithm; and d given two numbers x, y, deciding whether x is a
multiple of y. When an algorithm is used to calculate values of a numerical
function, as in a, b, and c, the function can also be described as
algorithmically computable, effectively computable, or just computable.
Algorithms are generally agreed to have the following properties which made them essential to the theory of
computation and the development of the Church-Turing thesis i an algorithm can be given by a finite
string of instructions, ii a computation device or agent can carry out or
compute in accordance with the instructions, iii there will be provisions for
computing, storing, and recalling steps in a computation, iv computations can
be carried out in a discrete and stepwise fashion in, say, a digital computer,
and v computations can be carried out in a deterministic fashion in, say, a
deterministic version of a Turing machine.
Alkindus: al-Kindi, Abu
Yusuf, philosopher who was an early and prominent supporter of philosophical
studies among the Muslims. He combined a noble Arab lineage with an influential
position in the caliphate during a critical period for the translation and
propagation of Grecian sciences in Arabic. Known as “the philosopher of the
Arabs,” he more than any other scholar of his generation was responsible, as a
patron, book collector, editor, and writer, for the acceptance of philosophy,
despite its foreign and non-Islamic Grecian source. Later writers surpassed him
in knowledge of philosophy, and his numerous epistles, treatises, and books
were eventually left in limbo. Of the 250 titles recorded in his name on an
unusual variety of subjects, most are lost. About forty survive in a poor
state, full of uncertain readings and other textual problems. Nevertheless,
al-Kindi’s works provide ample evidence of his close interest in Aristotle and
to an extent Plato. Unlike later philosophers in the Islamic world, he firmly
believed he could combine literal Koranic religious doctrines and Grecian
philosophical concepts. Among his best-known philosophical works is On First
Philosophy English translation by A. Ivry, 1974, whose theme is that the
noblest part of philosophy is first philosophy, which is knowledge of the First
Truth and the First Cause. Al-Kindi includes an extended demonstration of the
finiteness of the universe, time, and motion and the consequent infinitude of a
creator who was their cause, who is the pure unity that is the ultimate source
of all else and yet who, in al-Kindi’s mind, brings the world into being ex
nihilo. In On the Number of Aristotle’s Books, he separates prophetic knowledge
from ordinary, discursive philosophy: prophets know intuitively without effort
or time.
Allais’s
paradox: a puzzle about rationality devised by Maurice Allais
b. 1911. Leonard Savage 191771 advanced the sure-thing principle, which states
that a rational agent’s ranking of a pair of gambles having the same
consequence in a state S agrees with her ranking of any other pair of gambles
the same as the first pair except for having some other common consequence in
S. Allais devised an apparent counterexample with four gambles involving a
100-ticket lottery. The table lists prizes in units of $100,000. Ticket Numbers
Gambles 1 2 11 12 100 A 5 5 5 B 0 25 5 C 5 5 0 D 0 25 0
Changing A’s and B’s common consequence for tickets 12100 from 5 to 0 yields C
and D respectively. Hence the sure-thing principle prohibits simultaneously
preferring A to B, and D to C. Yet most people have these preferences, which
seem coherent. This conflict generates the paradox. Savage presented the
sure-thing principle in The Foundations of Statistics 1954. Responding to
preliminary drafts of that work, Allais formulated his counterexample in “The
Foundations of a Positive Theory of Choice Involving Risk and a Criticism of
the Postulates and Axioms of the American School” 1952.
Rhazes: al-Razi, Abu
Bakr, physician, philosopher, and chemist. He headed the hospital in Rayy, his
birthplace, and later in Baghdad, often returning to Rayy, where he died. A
learned Galenist and critic of Galen, he brought the same empirical,
Hippocratic spirit to medicine that he had used in transmuting alchemy into a
Neoplatonically naturalistic art. His medical works, including the first
treatise on smallpox, drew on extensive and compassionate clinical experience
and omnivorous reading both reading and
observation preserved in the twenty-five-volume Hawi, translated in 1279 as the
Continens. al-Razi’s mildly ascetic ethics springs from hedonic prudential
considerations and from his atomism. In keeping with the Epicureanism he might
have imbibed from Galenic sources, he rejects special prophecy as imposture,
arguing that reason, God’s gift to all alike, is sufficient guidance. Only
differences of interest and application separate the subtle devices of artisans
from those of intellectuals. God, the world Soul, time, space, and matter are
all eternal substances. Nature originates from Soul’s irrational desire for
embodiment, which is her only way of learning that her true homeland is the
intellectual world. God’s gift of intelligence gave order to the movements she
stirred up at the creation, and allows her escape from a world in which pains
outweigh pleasures and death is surcease. For one who engages in philosophy
“creatively, diligently, and persistently” will inevitably surpass his
predecessors; and anyone who thinks independently is assured of both progress
and immortality
alston:
w. p. cites H. P. Grice as ideationist. Philosopher widely acknowledged as one
of the most important contemporary epistemologists and one of the most
important philosophers of religion of the twentieth century. He is particularly
known for his argument that putative perception of God is epistemologically on
all fours with putative perception of everyday material objects. Alston
graduated from Centenary and the U.S. Army. A fine musician, he had to choose
between philosophy and music. Philosophy won out; he received his Ph.D. from
the of Chicago and began his
philosophical career at the of Michigan,
where he taught for twenty-two years. Since 1980 he has taught at Syracuse .
Although his dissertation and some of his early work were on Whitehead, he soon
turned to philosophy of language Philosophy of Language, 1964. Since the early
1970s Alston has concentrated on epistemology and philosophy of religion. In
epistemology he has defended foundationalism although not classical
foundationalism, investigated epistemic justification with unusual depth and
penetration, and called attention to important levels distinctions. His chief
works here are Epistemic Justification, a collection of essays; and The Reliability
of Sense Perception. His chief work in philosophy of religion is Divine Nature
and Human Language, a collection of essays on metaphysical and epistemological
topics; and Perceiving God. The latter is a magisterial argument for the
conclusion that experiential awareness of God, more specifically perception of
God, makes an important contribution to the grounds of religious belief. In
addition to this scholarly work, Alston was a founder of the Society of
Christian Philosophers, a professional society with more than 1,100 members,
and the founding editor of Faith and Philosophy.
Althusser, LouisL Marxist
philosopher whose publication in 1965 of two collections of essays, Pour Marx
“For Marx” and Lire le Capital “Reading Capital”, made him a sensation in
French intellectual circles and attracted a large international readership. The
English translations of these texts in 1969 and 1970, respectively, helped
shape the development of Marxist thought in the English-speaking world
throughout the 1970s. Drawing on the work of non-positivist French historians
and philosophers of science, especially Bachelard, Althusser proclaimed the
existence of an “epistemological break” in Marx’s work, occurring in the
mid-1840s. What preceded this break was, in Althusser’s view, a prescientific
theoretical humanism derived from Feuerbach and ultimately from Hegel. What
followed it, Althusser maintained, was a science of history a
all-things-considered reason Althusser, Louis 23 4065A- 23 development as monumental, potentially,
as the rise of the new sciences of nature in the seventh century. Althusser
argued that the nature and even the existence of this new kind of science had
yet to be acknowledged, even by Marx himself. It therefore had to be
reconstructed from Marx’s writings, Das Kapital especially, and also discerned
in the political practice of Lenin and other like-minded revolutionaries who
implicitly understood what Marx intended. Althusser did little, however, to
elaborate the content of this new science. Rather, he tirelessly defended it
programmatically against rival construals of Marxism. In so doing, he took
particular aim at neo-Hegelian and “humanistic” currents in the larger Marxist
culture and implicitly in the French Communist Party, to which he belonged
throughout his adult life. After 1968, Althusser’s influence in France faded.
But he continued to teach at l’École Normale Superieure and to write, making
important contributions to political theory and to understandings of “ideology”
and related concepts. He also faced increasingly severe bouts of mania and
depression. In 1980, in what the French courts deemed an episode of “temporary
insanity,” he strangled his wife. Althusser avoided prison, but spent much of
the 1980s in mental institutions. During this period he wrote two extraordinary
memoirs, L’avenir dure longtemps “The Future Lasts Forever” and Les faits “The
Facts”, published posthumously in 1992.
ambiguity,
a phonological or orthographic form having multiple meanings senses,
characters, semantic representations assigned by the language system. A lexical
ambiguity occurs when a lexical item word is assigned multiple meanings by the
language. It includes a homonymy, i.e., distinct lexical items having the same
sound or form but different senses
‘knight’/’night’, ‘lead’ n./‘lead’ v., ‘bear’ n./‘bear’ v.; and b polysemy,
i.e., a single lexical item having multiple senses ‘lamb’ the animal/‘lamb’ the flesh, ‘window’
glass/‘window’ opening. The distinction between homonymy and polysemy is
problematic. A structural ambiguity occurs when a phrase or sentence is
correlated by the grammar of the language with distinct constituent structures
phrase markers or sequences of phrase markers. Example: ‘Competent women and
men should apply’ ‘[NP[NPCompetent
women] and men] . . .’ vs. ‘[NPCompetent[NPwomen and men]] . . .’, where ‘NP’
stands for ‘noun phrase’. A scope ambiguity is a structural ambiguity deriving
from alternative interpretations of scopes of operators see below. Examples:
‘Walt will diet and exercise only if his doctor approves’ sentence operator scope: doctor’s approval is
a necessary condition for both diet and exercise wide scope ‘only if’ vs.
approval necessary for exercise but not for dieting wide scope ‘and’; ‘Bertie
has a theory about every occurrence’
quantifier scope: one grand theory explaining all occurrences ‘a theory’
having wide scope over ‘every occurrence’ vs. all occurrences explained by
several theories together ‘every occurrence’ having wide scope. The scope of an
operator is the shortest full subformula to which the operator is attached.
Thus, in `A & B C’, the scope of ‘&’ is ‘A & B’. For natural
languages, the scope of an operator is what it C-commands. X C-commands Y in a
tree diagram provided the first branching node that dominates X also dominates
Y. An occurrence of an operator has wide scope relative to that of another
operator provided the scope of the former properly includes scope of the
latter. Examples: in ‘~A & B’, ’-’ has wide scope over ‘&’; in ‘Dx Ey
Fxy’, the existential quantifier has wide scope over the universal quantifier.
A pragmatic ambiguity is duality of use resting on pragmatic principles such as
those which underlie reference and conversational implicature; e.g., depending
on contextual variables, ‘I don’t know that he’s right’ can express doubt or
merely the denial of genuine knowledge.
Ambrose, Saint, known as
Ambrose of Milan c.33997, Roman church leader and theologian. While bishop of
Milan, he not only led the struggle against the Arian heresy and its political
manifestations, but offered new models for preaching, for Scriptural exegesis,
and for hymnody. His works also contributed to medieval Latin philosophy.
Ambrose’s appropriation of Neoplatonic doctrines was noteworthy in itself, and
it worked powerfully on and through Augustine. Ambrose’s commentary on the account
of creation in Genesis, his Hexaemeron, preserved for medieval readers many
pieces of ancient natural history and even some altruism Ambrose, Saint 24
4065A- 24 elements of physical
explanation. Perhaps most importantly, Ambrose engaged ancient philosophical
ethics in the search for moral lessons that marks his exegesis of Scripture; he
also reworked Cicero’s De officiis as a treatise on the virtues and duties of
Christian living.
Ammonius Saccas early
third century A.D., Platonist philosopher who taught in Alexandria. He
apparently served early in the century as the teacher of the Christian
philosopher Origen. He attracted the attention of Plotinus, who came to the
city in 232 in search of philosophical enlightenment Porphyry, Life of Plotinus
3. Ammonius the epithet ‘Saccas’ seems to mean ‘the bagman’ was undoubtedly a
charismatic figure, but it is not at all clear what, if any, were his
distinctive doctrines, though he seems to have been influenced by Numenius. He
wrote nothing, and may be thought of, in E. R. Dodds’s words, as the Socrates
of Neoplatonism.
analysis, the process of
breaking up a concept, proposition, linguistic complex, or fact into its simple
or ultimate constituents. That on which the analysis is done is called the
analysandum, and that which does the analysis is called the analysans. A number
of the most important philosophers of the twentieth century, including Russell,
Moore, and the early Wittgenstein, have argued that philosophical analysis is
the proper method of philosophy. But the practitioners of analytic philosophy
have disagreed about what kind of thing is to be analyzed. For example, Moore
tried to analyze sense-data into their constituent parts. Here the analysandum
is a complex psychological fact, the having of a sense-datum. More commonly,
analytic philosophers have tried to analyze concepts or propositions. This is
conceptual analysis. Still others have seen it as their task to give an
analysis of various kinds of sentences
e.g., those involving proper names or definite descriptions. This is
linguistic analysis. Each of these kinds of analysis faces a version of a
puzzle that has come to be called the paradox of analysis. For linguistic
analyses, the paradox can be expressed as follows: for an analysis to be adequate,
the analysans must be synonymous with the analysandum; e.g., if ‘male sibling’
is to analyze ‘brother’, they must mean the same; but if they are synonymous,
then ‘a brother is a male sibling’ is synonymous with ‘a brother is a brother’;
but the two sentences do not seem synonymous. Expressed as a dilemma, the
paradox is that any proposed analysis would seem to be either inadequate
because the analysans and the analysandum are not synonymous or uninformative
because they are synonymous.
analytic
philosophy: an umbrella term currently used to cover a diverse
assortment of philosophical techniques and tendencies. As in the case of
chicken-sexing, it is relatively easy to identify analytic philosophy and
philosophers, though difficult to say with any precision what the criteria are.
Analytic philosophy is sometimes called Oxford philosophy or linguistic
philosophy, but these labels are, at least, misleading. Whatever else it is,
analytic philosophy is manifestly not a school, doctrine, or body of accepted
propositions. At Cambridge, analytic philosophers are the intellectual heirs of
Russell, Moore, and Wittgenstein, philosophers who self-consciously pursued
“philosophical analysis” in the early part of the twentieth century. Analysis,
as practiced by Russell and Moore, concerned not language per se, but concepts
and propositions. In their eyes, while it did not exhaust the domain of
philosophy, analysis provided a vital tool for laying bare the logical form of
reality. Wittgenstein, in the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, contended, though
obliquely, that the structure of language reveals the structure of the world;
every meaningful sentence is analyzable into atomic constituents that designate
the finegrained constituents of reality. This “Tractarian” view was one
Wittgenstein was to renounce in his later work, but it had considerable
influence within the Vienna Circle in the 1920s, and in the subsequent
development of logical positivism in the 1930s and 1940s. Carnap and Ayer, both
exponents of positivism, held that the task of philosophy was not to uncover
elusive metaphysical truths, but to provide analyses of scientific sentences.
Other sentences, those in ethics, for instance, were thought to lack “cognitive
significance.” Their model was Russell’s theory of descriptions, which provided
a technique for analyzing away apparent commitments to suspicious entities.
Meanwhile, a number of former proponents of analysis, influenced by
Wittgenstein, had taken up what came to be called ordinary language philosophy.
Philosophers of this persuasion focused on the role of words in the lives of
ordinary speakers, hoping thereby to escape long-standing philosophical
muddles. These muddles resulted, they thought, from a natural tendency, when
pursuing philosophical theses, to be misled by the grammatical form of
sentences in which those questions were posed. A classic illustration might be
Heidegger’s supposition that ‘nothing’ must designate something, though a very
peculiar something. Today, it is difficult to find much unanimity in the ranks
of analytic philosophers. There is, perhaps, an implicit respect for argument
and clarity, an evolving though informal agreement as to what problems are and
are not tractable, and a conviction that philosophy is in some sense continuous
with science. The practice of analytic philosophers to address one another
rather than the broader public has led some to decry philosophy’s
“professionalization” and to call for a return to a pluralistic,
community-oriented style of philosophizing. Analytic philosophers respond by
pointing out that analytic techniques and standards have been well represented
in the history of philosophy.
analyticity:
H. P. Grice, “In defence of a dogma,” in Studies in the way of words. the analyticsynthetic
distinction, the distinction, made famous by Kant, according to which an
affirmative subject-predicate statement proposition, judgment is called
analytic if the predicate concept is contained in the subject concept, and
synthetic otherwise. The statement ‘All red roses are red’ is analytic, since
the concept ‘red’ is contained in the concept ‘red roses’. ‘All roses are red’
is synthetic, since the concept ‘red’ is not contained in the concept ‘roses’.
The denial of an affirmative subject-predicate statement entails a contradiction
if it is analytic. E.g., ‘Not all red roses are red’ entails ‘Some roses are
both red and not red’. One concept may be contained in another, in Kant’s
sense, even though the terms used to express them are not related as part to
whole. Since ‘biped’ means ‘two-footed animal’, the concept ‘two-footed’ is
contained in the concept ‘biped’. It is accordingly analytic that all bipeds
are two-footed. The same analytic statement is expressed by the synonymous
sentences ‘All bipeds are two-footed’ and ‘All two-footed animals are
two-footed’. Unlike statements, sentences cannot be classified as analytic or
synthetic except relative to an interpretation. analytical jurisprudence
analyticsynthetic distinction 26 4065A-
26 Witness ‘All Russian teachers are Russian’, which in one sense
expresses the analytic statement ‘All teachers that are Russian are Russian’,
and in another the synthetic statement ‘All teachers of Russian are Russian’.
Kant’s innovation over Leibniz and Hume lay in separating the logicosemantic
analyticsynthetic distinction from the epistemological a prioria posteriori
distinction and from the modalmetaphysical necessarycontingent distinction. It
seems evident that any analytic statement is a priori knowable without
empirical evidence and necessary something that could not be false. The
converse is highly controversial. Kant and his rationalist followers maintain
that some a priori and necessary statements are synthetic, citing examples from
logic ‘Contradictions are impossible’, ‘The identity relation is transitive’,
mathematics ‘The sum of 7 and 5 is 12’, ‘The straight line between two points
is the shortest’, and metaphysics ‘Every event is caused’. Empiricists like J.
S. Mill, Carnap, Ayer, and C. I. Lewis argue that such examples are either
synthetic a posteriori or analytic a priori. Philosophers since Kant have tried
to clarify the analyticsynthetic distinction, and generalize it to all
statements. On one definition, a sentence is analytic on a given interpretation
provided it is “true solely in virtue of the meaning or definition of its
terms.” The truth of any sentence depends in part on the meanings of its terms.
`All emeralds are green’ would be false, e.g., if ‘emerald’ meant ‘ruby’. What
makes the sentence synthetic, it is claimed, is that its truth also depends on
the properties of emeralds, namely, their being green. But the same holds for
analytic sentences: the truth of ‘All red roses are red’ depends on the
properties of red roses, namely, their being red. Neither is true solely in
virtue of meaning. A more adequate generalization defines an analytic statement
as a formal logical truth: one “true in virtue of its logical form,” so that
all statements with the same form are true. In terms of sentences under an
interpretation, an analytic truth is an explicit logical truth one whose
surface structure represents its logical form or one that becomes an explicit
logical truth when synonyms are substituted. The negative statement that
tomorrow is not both Sunday and not Sunday is analytic by this definition,
because all statements of the form : p & - p are true. Kant’s definition is
obtained as a special case by stipulating that the predicate of an affirmative
subjectpredicate statement is contained in the subject provided the statement
is logically true. On a third generalization, ‘analytic’ denotes any statement
whose denial entails a contradiction. Subject S contains predicate P provided
being S entails being P. Whether this is broader or narrower than the second
generalization depends on how ‘entailment’, ‘logical form’, and ‘contradiction’
are defined. On some construals, ‘Red is a color’ counts as analytic on the
third generalization its denial entails ‘Something is and is not a color’ but
not on the second ‘red’ and ‘colored’ are logically unstructured, while the
rulings are reversed for a counterfactual conditional like ‘If this were a red
rose it would be red’. Following Quine, many have denied any distinction
between analytic and synthetic statements. Some arguments presume the problematic
“true by meaning” definition. Others are that: 1 the distinction cannot be
defined without using related notions like ‘meaning’, ‘concept’, and
‘statement’, which are neither extensional nor definable in terms of behavior;
2 some statements like ‘All cats are animals’ are hard to classify as analytic
or synthetic; and 3 no statement allegedly is immune from rejection in the face
of new empirical evidence. If these arguments were sound, however, the
distinction between logical truths and others would seem equally dubious, a
conclusion seldom embraced. Some describe a priori truths, both synthetic and
analytic, as conceptual truths, on the theory that they are all true in virtue
of the nature of the concepts they contain. Conceptual truths are said to have
no “factual content” because they are about concepts rather than things in the
actual world. While it is natural to classify a priori truths together, the
proffered theory is questionable. As indicated above, all truths hold in part
because of the identity of their concepts, and in part because of the nature of
the objects they are about. It is a fact that all emeralds are emeralds, and
this proposition is about emeralds, not concepts.
ananke Grecian,
necessity. The term was used by early Grecian philosophers for a constraining
or moving natural force. In Parmenides frg. 8, line 30 ananke encompasses
reality in limiting bonds; according to Diogenes Laertius, Democrianamnesis
ananke 27 4065A- 27 tus calls the
vortex that generates the cosmos ananke; Plato Timaeus 47e ff. refers to ananke
as the irrational element in nature, which reason orders in creating the
physical world. As used by Aristotle Metaphysics V.5, the basic meaning of
‘necessary’ is ‘that which cannot be otherwise’, a sense that includes logical
necessity. He also distinguishes Physics II.9 between simple and hypothetical
necessity conditions that must hold if something is to occur.
anaphora:
a device of reference or cross-reference in which a term called an anaphor,
typically a pronoun, has its semantic properties determined by a term or noun
phrase called the anaphor’s antecedent that occurs earlier. Sometimes the
antecedent is a proper name or other independently referring expression, as in
‘Jill went up the hill and then she came down again’. In such cases, the
anaphor refers to the same object as its antecedent. In other cases, the
anaphor seems to function as a variable bound by an antecedent quantifier, as
in ‘If any miner bought a donkey, he is penniless’. But anaphora is puzzling
because not every example falls neatly into one of these two groups. Thus, in
‘John owns some sheep and Harry vaccinates them’ an example due to Gareth Evans
the anaphor is arguably not bound by its antecedent ‘some sheep’. And in ‘Every
miner who owns a donkey beats it’ a famous type of case discovered by Geach,
the anaphor is arguably neither bound by ‘a donkey’ nor a uniquely referring
expression.
anattavada, the Buddhist
doctrine of no-soul, attributed to the Buddha sixth century B.C.. The Buddha’s
idea of dependent origination pratityasamutpada leads to a process ontology of
change where nothing is absolute, permanent, or substantive. Accordingly, the
Buddha taught that a person’s self consists of a bundle of fleeting
impressions, analyzed into five groups skandhas, rather than a substantive
entity called the “soul.” The Buddha’s method of introspection to find out
whether we can be aware of a soullike substance inside us is remarkably similar
to David Hume’s. The Hindu philosophical schools objected to anattavada because
they thought it could not satisfactorily explain such issues as personal
identity, moral responsibility and karma, and rebirth. D.K.C. Anaxagoras
c.500428 B.C., Grecian philosopher who was the first of the pre-Socratics to
teach in Athens c.480450, where he influenced leading intellectuals such as
Pericles and Euripides. He left Athens when he was prosecuted for impiety.
Writing in response to Parmenides, he elaborated a theory of matter according
to which nothing comes into being or perishes. The ultimate realities are
stuffs such as water and earth, flesh and bone, but so are contraries such as
hot and cold, likewise treated as stuffs. Every phenomenal substance has a
portion of every elemental stuff, and there are no minimal parts of anything,
but matter takes on the phenomenal properties of whatever predominates in the
mixture. Anaxagoras posits an indefinite number of elemental stuffs, in
contrast to his contemporary Empedocles, who requires only four elements; but
Anaxagoras follows Parmenides more rigorously, allowing no properties or
substances to emerge that were not already present in the cosmos as its
constituents. Thus there is no ultimate gap between appearance and reality:
everything we perceive is real. In Anaxagoras’s cosmogony, an initial chaos of
complete mixture gives way to an ordered world when noûs mind begins a vortex
motion that separates cosmic masses of ether the bright upper air, air, water,
and earth. Mind is finer than the stuffs and is found in living things, but it
does not mix with stuffs. Anaxagoras’s theory of mind provides the first hint
of a mindmatter dualism. Plato and Aristotle thought his assigning a cosmic
role to mind made him sound like “a sober man” among his contemporaries, but
they were disappointed that he did not exploit his idea to provide teleological
explanations of natural phenomena.
Anaximander: Grecian
philosopher and cosmologist, reputedly the student and successor of Thales in
the Milesian school. He described the cosmos as originating from apeiron the
boundless by a process of separating off; a disk-shaped earth was formed,
surrounded by concentric heavenly rings of fire enclosed in air. At “breathing
holes” in the air we see jets of fire, which are the stars, moon, and sun. The earth
stays in place because there is no reason for it to tend one way or another.
The seasons arise from alternating periods where hot and dry or wet and anaphor
Anaximander 28 4065A- 28 cold powers
predominate, governed by a temporal process figuratively portrayed as the
judgment of Time. Anaximander drew a map of the world and explained winds,
rain, and lightning by naturalistic hypotheses. He also described the emergence
of life in a way that prefigures the theory of evolution. Anaximander’s interest
in cosmology and cosmogony and his brilliant conjectures set the major
questions for later preSocratics.
Anaximenes of Miletus: Grecian
philosopher, a pre-Socratic who, following in the tradition of the Milesians
Thales and Anaximander, speculated about cosmology and meteorology. The source
arche of the cosmos is air aer, originally mist, which by a process of
rarefaction becomes fire, and by a process of condensation becomes wind,
clouds, water, earth, and stones. Air is divine and causes life. The earth is
flat and rides on a cushion of air, while a heavenly firmament revolves about
it like a felt cap. Anaximenes also explained meteorological phenomena and
earthquakes. Although less innovative than his predecessor Anaximander, he made
progress in naturalistic explanations by appealing to a quantitative process of
rarefaction and condensation rather than to mythical processes involving
quasi-personal agents. D.W.G. ancestralof a given relation R, the relation also
called the transitive closure of R that relates one given individual to a
second if and only if the first can be “reached” from the second by repeated
“applications” of the given relation R. The ancestor relation is the ancestral
of the parent relation since one person is an ancestor of a second if the first
is a parent of the second or the first is a parent of a parent of the second or
the first is a parent of a parent of a parent of the second, and so on. Frege
discovered a simple method of giving a materially adequate and formally correct
definition of the ancestral of a given relation in terms of the relation itself
plus logical concepts. This method is informally illustrated as follows: in
order for one person A to be an ancestor of a second person B it is necessary
and sufficient for A to have every property that belongs to every parent of B
and that belongs to every parent of any person to whom it belongs. This and
other similar methods made possible the reduction of all numerical concepts to
those of zero and successor, which Frege then attempted to reduce to concepts
of pure logic. Frege’s definition of the ancestral has become a paradigm in
modern analytic philosophy as well as a historical benchmark of the watershed
between traditional logic and modern logic. It demonstrates the exactness of
modern logical analysis and, in comparison, the narrowness of traditional
logic.
ancient atomism, the
theory, originated by Leucippus and elaborated by Democritus, that the ultimate
realities are atoms and the void. The theory was later used by Epicurus as the
foundation for a philosophy stressing ethical concerns, Epicureanism.
Andronicus of Rhodes
first century B.C., Grecian philosopher, a leading member of the Lyceum who was
largely responsible for establishing the canon of Aristotle’s works still read
today. He also edited the works of Theophrastus. At the time, Aristotle was
known primarily for his philosophical dialogues, only fragments of which now
survive; his more methodical treatises had stopped circulating soon after his
death. By producing the first systematic edition of Aristotle’s corpus,
Andronicus revived study of the treatises, and the resulting critical debates
dramatically affected the course of philosophy. Little is recorded about
Andronicus’s labors; but besides editing the texts and discussing titles,
arrangement, and authenticity, he sought to explicate and assess Aristotle’s
thought. In so doing, he and his colleagues initiated the exegetical tradition
of Aristotelian commentaries. Nothing he wrote survives; a summary account of emotions
formerly ascribed to him is spurious.
Angst: German term for a
special form of anxiety, an emotion seen by existentialists as both
constituting and revealing the human condition. Angst plays a key role in the
writings of Heidegger, whose concept is closely related to Kierkegaard’s angest
and Sartre’s angoisse. The concept is first treated in this distinctive way in
Kierkegaard’s The Concept of Anxiety 1844, where anxiety is described as “the
dizziness of freedom.” Anxiety here represents freedom’s self-awareness; it is
the psychological precondition for the individual’s attempt to become
autonomous, a possibility that is seen as both alluring and disturbing.
Anniceris, Grecian
philosopher. A pupil of Antipater, he established a separate branch of the
Cyrenaic school known as the Anniceraioi. He subscribed to typical Cyrenaic
hedonism, arguing that the end of each action should be one’s own pleasure,
since we can know nothing of others’ experiences. He tempered the implications
of hedonism with the claim that a wise man attaches weight to respect for
parents, patriotism, gratitude, and friendship, perhaps influencing Epicurus in
this regard. Anniceris also played down the Cyrenaic stress on the intellect’s
role in hedonistic practical rationality, taking the Aristotelian view that
cultivation of the right habits is indispensable.
Anscombe: Gertrude
Elizabeth Margaret, Irish philosopher who has held positions at Oxford and
Cambridge, best known for her work in the philosophy of mind and for her editions
and translations of Wittgenstein’s later writings. Anscombe studied philosophy
with Wittgenstein and became closely associated with him, writing An
Introduction to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus 1959. She is married to Peter Geach.
Anscombe’s first major work was Intention 1957. She argues that the concept of
intention is central to our understanding of ourselves as rational agents. The
basic case is that of the intentions with which we act. These are identified by
the reasons we give in answer to why-questions concerning our actions. Such
reasons usually form a hierarchy that constitutes a practical syllogism of
which action itself is the conclusion. Hence our intentions are a form of
active practical knowledge that normally leads to action. Anscombe compares the
direction of fit of this kind of knowledge with a shopping list’s relation to
one’s purchases, and contrasts it with the direction of fit characteristic of a
list of these purchases drawn up by an observer of the shopper. She maintains
that the deep mistake of modern i.e., post-medieval philosophy has been to
think that all knowledge is of this latter, observational, type. This
conception of active knowledge expressed through an agent’s intentions
conflicts with the passive conception of rationality characteristic of Hume and
his followers, and Anscombe develops this challenge in papers critical of the
isought distinction of Hume and his modern successors. In a famous paper,
“Modern Moral Philosophy” 1958, she also argues that ought-statements make sense
only in the context of a moral theology that grounds morality in divine
commands. Since our culture rejects this theology, it is no surprise that
“modern moral philosophers” cannot find much sense in them. We should therefore
abandon them and return to the older conceptions of practical rationality and
virtue. These conceptions, and the associated conception of natural law,
provide the background to an uncompromising defense of traditional Catholic
morality concerning sexuality, war, and the importance of the distinction
between intention and foresight. Anscombe has never been afraid of unpopular
positions philosophical and ethical. Her
three volumes of Collected Papers 1981 include a defense of singular causation,
an attack on the very idea of a subject of thought, and a critique of pacifism.
She is one of the most original and distinctive English philosophers of her
generation.
Anselm, Saint, called
Anselm of Canterbury 10331109, Italian-born English philosophical theologian. A
Benedictine monk and the second Norman archbishop of Canterbury, he is best
known for his distinctive method fides
quaerens intellectum; his “ontological” argument for the existence of God in
his treatise Proslogion; and his classic formulation of the satisfaction theory
of the Atonement in the Cur Deus homo. Like Augustine before him, Anselm is a
Christian Platonist in metaphysics. He argues that the most accessible proofs
of the existence of God are through value theory: in his treatise Monologion, he
deploys a cosmological argument, showing the existence of a source of all
goods, which is the Good per se and hence supremely good; that same thing
exists per se and is the Supreme Being. In the Proslogion, Anselm begins with
his conception of a being a greater than which cannot be conceived, and mounts
his ontological argument that a being a greater than which cannot be conceived
exists in the intellect, because even the fool understands the phrase when he
hears it; but if it existed in the intellect alone, a greater could be conceived
that existed in reality. This supremely valuable object is essentially whatever
it is other things being equal that is better to be than not to be, and
hence living, wise, powerful, true, just, blessed, immaterial, immutable, and
eternal per se; even the paradigm of sensory goods Beauty, Harmony, Sweetness, and Pleasant
Texture, in its own ineffable manner. Nevertheless, God is supremely simple,
not compounded of a plurality of excellences, but “omne et unum, totum et solum
bonum,” a being a more delectable than which cannot be conceived. Everything
other than God has its being and its well-being through God as efficient cause.
Moreover, God is the paradigm of all created natures, the latter ranking as
better to the extent that they more perfectly resemble God. Thus, it is better
to be human than to be horse, to be horse than to be wood, even though in
comparison with God everything else is “almost nothing.” For every created
nature, there is a that-for-which-it-ismade ad quod factum est. On the one hand,
Anselm thinks of such teleology as part of the internal structure of the
natures themselves: a creature of type F is a true F only insofar as it
is/does/exemplifies that for which F’s were made; a defective F, to the extent
that it does not. On the other hand, for Anselm, the telos of a created nature
is that-for-which-God-made-it. Because God is personal and acts through reason
and will, Anselm infers that prior in the order of explanation to creation,
there was, in the reason of the maker, an exemplar, form, likeness, or rule of
what he was going to make. In De veritate Anselm maintains that such teleology
gives rise to obligation: since creatures owe their being and well-being to God
as their cause, so they owe their being and well-being to God in the sense of
having an obligation to praise him by being the best beings they can. Since
every creature is of some nature or other, each can be its best by being
that-for-which-God-made-it. Abstracting from impediments, non-rational natures
fulfill this obligation and “act rightly” by natural necessity; rational
creatures, when they exercise their powers of reason and will to fulfill God’s
purpose in creating them. Thus, the goodness of a creature how good a being it
is is a function of twin factors: its natural telos i.e., what sort of
imitation of divine nature it aims for, and its rightness in exercising its
natural powers to fulfill its telos. By contrast, God as absolutely independent
owes no one anything and so has no obligations to creatures. In De casu
diaboli, Anselm underlines the optimism of his ontology, reasoning that since
the Supreme Good and the Supreme Being are identical, every being is good and
every good a being. Two further conclusions follow. First, evil is a privation
of being, the absence of good in something that properly ought to have it e.g.,
blindness in normally sighted animals, injustice in humans or angels. Second,
since all genuine powers are given to enable a being to fulfill its natural
telos and so to be the best being it can, all genuine metaphysically basic
powers are optimific and essentially aim at goods, so that evils are merely
incidental side effects of their operation, involving some lack of coordination
among powers or between their exercise and the surrounding context. Thus,
divine omnipotence does not, properly speaking, include corruptibility,
passibility, or the ability to lie, because the latter are defects and/or
powers in other things whose exercise obstructs the flourishing of the
corruptible, passible, or potential liar. Anselm’s distinctive action theory
begins teleologically with the observation that humans and angels were made for
a happy immortality enjoying God, and to that end were given the powers of
reason to make accurate value assessments and will to love accordingly. Anselm
regards freedom and imputability of choice as essential and permanent features
of all rational beings. But freedom cannot be defined as a power for opposites
the power to sin and the power not to sin, both because neither God nor the
good angels have any power to sin, and because sin is an evil at which no
metaphysically basic power can aim. Rather, freedom is the power to preserve
justice for its own sake. Choices and actions are imputable to an agent only if
they are spontaneous, from the agent itself. Creatures cannot act spontaneously
by the necessity of their natures, because they do not have their natures from
themselves but receive them from God. To give them the opportunity to become
just of themselves, God furnishes them with two motivaAnselm Anselm 31 31 tional drives toward the good: an
affection for the advantageous affectio commodi or a tendency to will things
for the sake of their benefit to the agent itself; and an affection for justice
affectio justitiae or a tendency to will things because of their own intrinsic
value. Creatures are able to align these drives by letting the latter temper
the former or not. The good angels, who preserved justice by not willing some
advantage possible for them but forbidden by God for that time, can no longer
will more advantage than God wills for them, because he wills their maximum as
a reward. By contrast, creatures, who sin by refusing to delay gratification in
accordance with God’s will, lose both uprightness of will and their affection
for justice, and hence the ability to temper their pursuit of advantage or to
will the best goods. Justice will never be restored to angels who desert it.
But if animality makes human nature weaker, it also opens the possibility of
redemption. Anselm’s argument for the necessity of the Incarnation plays out
the dialectic of justice and mercy so characteristic of his prayers. He begins
with the demands of justice: humans owe it to God to make all of their choices
and actions conform to his will; failure to render what was owed insults God’s
honor and makes the offender liable to make satisfaction; because it is worse
to dishonor God than for countless worlds to be destroyed, the satisfaction
owed for any small sin is incommensurate with any created good; it would be
maximally indecent for God to overlook such a great offense. Such calculations
threaten certain ruin for the sinner, because God alone can do/be immeasurably
deserving, and depriving the creature of its honor through the eternal
frustration of its telos seems the only way to balance the scales. Yet, justice
also forbids that God’s purposes be thwarted through created resistance, and it
was divine mercy that made humans for a beatific immortality with him.
Likewise, humans come in families by virtue of their biological nature which
angels do not share, and justice allows an offense by one family member to be
compensated by another. Assuming that all actual humans are descended from
common first parents, Anselm claims that the human race can make satisfaction
for sin, if God becomes human and renders to God what Adam’s family owes. When
Anselm insists that humans were made for beatific intimacy with God and
therefore are obliged to strive into God with all of their powers, he
emphatically includes reason or intellect along with emotion and will. God, the
controlling subject matter, is in part permanently inaccessible to us because
of the ontological incommensuration between God and creatures and our progress
is further hampered by the consequences of sin. Our powers will function best,
and hence we have a duty to follow right order in their use: by submitting
first to the holistic discipline of faith, which will focus our souls and point
us in the right direction. Yet it is also a duty not to remain passive in our
appreciation of authority, but rather for faith to seek to understand what it
has believed. Anselm’s works display a dialectical structure, full of
questions, objections, and contrasting opinions, designed to stir up the mind.
His quartet of teaching dialogues De
grammatico, De veritate, De libertate arbitrii, and De casu diaboli as well as
his last philosophical treatise, De concordia, anticipate the genre of the
Scholastic question quaestio so dominant in the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries.
His discussions are likewise remarkable for their attention to modalities and
proper-versus-improper linguistic usage.
antilogism, an
inconsistent triad of propositions, two of which are the premises of a valid
categorical syllogism and the third of which is the contradictory of the
conclusion of this valid categorical syllogism. An antilogism is a special form
of antilogy or self-contradiction.
antinomianism, the view
that one is not bound by moral law; specifically, the view that Christians are
by grace set free from the need to observe moral laws. During the Reformation,
antinomianism was believed by some but not An Sich antinomianism 32 32 Martin Luther to follow from the Lutheran
doctrine of justification by faith alone.
Antiochus of Ascalon
c.130c.68 B.C., Grecian philosopher and the last prominent member of the New
Academy. He played the major role in ending its two centuries of Skepticism and
helped revive interest in doctrines from the Old Academy, as he called Plato,
Aristotle, and their associates. The impulse for this decisive shift came in
epistemology, where the Skeptical Academy had long agreed with Stoicism that
knowledge requires an infallible “criterion of truth” but disputed the Stoic
claim to find this criterion in “cognitive perception.” Antiochus’s teacher,
Philo of Larissa, broke with this tradition and proposed that perception need
not be cognitive to qualify as knowledge. Rejecting this concession, Antiochus
offered new arguments for the Stoic claim that some perception is cognitive,
and hence knowledge. He also proposed a similar accommodation in ethics, where
he agreed with the Stoics that virtue alone is sufficient for happiness but
insisted with Aristotle that virtue is not the only good. These and similar
attempts to mediate fundamental disputes have led some to label Antiochus an
eclectic or syncretist; but some of his proposals, especially his appeal to the
Old Academy, set the stage for Middle Platonism, which also sought to reconcile
Plato and Aristotle. No works by Antiochus survive, but his students included
many eminent Romans, most notably Cicero, who summarizes Antiochus’s
epistemology in the Academica, his critique of Stoic ethics in De finibus IV,
and his purportedly Aristotelian ethics in De finibus V.
anti-realism, rejection,
in one or another form or area of inquiry, of realism, the view that there are
knowable mind-independent facts, objects, or properties. Metaphysical realists
make the general claim that there is a world of mind-independent objects. Realists
in particular areas make more specific or limited claims. Thus moral realists
hold that there are mind-independent moral properties, mathematical realists
that there are mind-independent mathematical facts, scientific realists that
scientific inquiry reveals the existence of previously unknown and unobservable
mind-independent entities and properties. Antirealists deny either that facts
of the relevant sort are mind-independent or that knowledge of such facts is
possible. Berkeley’s subjective idealism, which claims that the world consists
only of minds and their contents, is a metaphysical anti-realism.
Constructivist anti-realists, on the other hand, deny that the world consists
only of mental phenomena, but claim that it is constituted by, or constructed
from, our evidence or beliefs. Many philosophers find constructivism
implausible or even incoherent as a metaphysical doctrine, but much more
plausible when restricted to a particular domain, such as ethics or
mathematics. Debates between realists and anti-realists have been particularly
intense in philosophy of science. Scientific realism has been rejected both by
constructivists such as Kuhn, who hold that scientific facts are constructed by
the scientific community, and by empiricists who hold that knowledge is limited
to what can be observed. A sophisticated version of the latter doctrine is Bas
van Fraassen’s constructive empiricism, which allows scientists free rein in
constructing scientific models, but claims that evidence for such models confirms
only their observable implications.
apeiron, Grecian term
meaning ‘the boundless’ or ‘the unlimited’, which evolved to signify ‘the
infinite’. Anaximander introduced the term to philosophy by saying that the
source of all things was apeiron. There is some disagreement about whether he
meant by this the spatially antinomy apeiron 33 33 unbounded, the temporally unbounded, or
the qualitatively indeterminate. It seems likely that he intended the term to
convey the first meaning, but the other two senses also happen to apply to the
spatially unbounded. After Anaximander, Anaximenes declared as his first
principle that air is boundless, and Xenophanes made his flat earth extend
downward without bounds, and probably outward horizontally without limit as well.
Rejecting the tradition of boundless principles, Parmenides argued that
“what-is” must be held within determinate boundaries. But his follower Melissus
again argued that what-is must be boundless
in both time and space for it can
have no beginning or end. Another follower of Parmenides, Zeno of Elea, argued
that if there are many substances, antinomies arise, including the consequences
that substances are both limited and unlimited apeira in number, and that they
are so small as not to have size and so large as to be unlimited in size.
Rejecting monism, Anaxagoras argued for an indefinite number of elements that
are each unlimited in size, and the Pythagorean Philolaus made limiters
perainonta and unlimiteds apeira the principles from which all things are
composed. The atomists Leucippus and Democritus conceived of a boundless
universe, partly full of an infinite number of atoms and partly void; and in
the universe are countless apeiroi worlds. Finally Aristotle arrived at an
abstract understanding of the apeiron as “the infinite,” claiming to settle
paradoxes about the boundless by allowing for real quantities to be infinitely
divisible potentially, but not actually Physics III.48. The development of the
notion of the apeiron shows how Grecian philosophers evolved ever more abstract
philosophical ideas from relatively concrete conceptions.
apocatastasis from Grecian,
‘reestablishment’, the restoration of all souls, including Satan’s and his
minions’, in the kingdom of God. God’s goodness will triumph over evil, and
through a process of spiritual education souls will be brought to repentance
and made fit for divine life. The theory originates with Origen but was also
held by Gregory of Nyssa. In modern times F. D. Maurice 180572 and Karl Barth
1886 1968 held this position.
aporia plural: aporiai, Grecian
term meaning ‘puzzle’, ‘question for discussion’, ‘state of perplexity’. The
aporetic method the raising of puzzles
without offering solutions is typical of
the elenchus in the early Socratic dialogues of Plato. These consist in the
testing of definitions and often end with an aporia, e.g., that piety is both
what is and what is not loved by the gods. Compare the paradoxes of Zeno, e.g.,
that motion is both possible and impossible. In Aristotle’s dialectic, the
resolution of aporiai discovered in the views on a subject is an important
source of philosophical understanding. The beliefs that one should love oneself
most of all and that self-love is shameful, e.g., can be resolved with the
right understanding of ‘self’. The possibility of argument for two inconsistent
positions was an important factor in the development of Skepticism. In modern
philosophy, the antinomies that Kant claimed reason would arrive at in
attempting to prove the existence of objects corresponding to transcendental
ideas may be seen as aporiai.
applied ethics, the
domain of ethics that includes professional ethics, such as business ethics,
engineering ethics, and medical ethics, as well as practical ethics such as
environmental ethics, which is applied, and thus practical as opposed to
theoretical, but not focused on any one discipline. One of the major disputes
among those who work in applied ethics is whether or not there is a general and
universal account of morality applicable both to the ethical issues in the
professions and to various practical problems. Some philosophers believe that
each of the professions or each field of activity develops an ethical code for
itself and that there need be no apellatio applied ethics 34 34 close relationship between e.g. business
ethics, medical ethics, and environmental ethics. Others hold that the same
moral system applies to all professions and fields. They claim that the
appearance of different moral systems is simply due to certain problems being
more salient for some professions and fields than for others. The former
position accepts the consequence that the ethical codes of different
professions might conflict with one another, so that a physician in business
might find that business ethics would require one action but medical ethics
another. Engineers who have been promoted to management positions sometimes
express concern over the tension between what they perceive to be their
responsibility as engineers and their responsibility as managers in a business.
Many lawyers seem to hold that there is similar tension between what common
morality requires and what they must do as lawyers. Those who accept a
universal morality hold that these tensions are all resolvable because there is
only one common morality. Underlying both positions is the pervasive but false
view of common morality as providing a unique right answer to every moral
problem. Those who hold that each profession or field has its own moral code do
not realize that common morality allows for conflicts of duties. Most of those
who put forward moral theories, e.g., utilitarians, Kantians, and
contractarians, attempt to generate a universal moral system that solves all
moral problems. This creates a situation that leads many in applied ethics to
dismiss theoretical ethics as irrelevant to their concerns. An alternative view
of a moral theory is to think of it on the model of a scientific theory,
primarily concerned to describe common morality rather than generate a new
improved version. On this model, it is clear that although morality rules out
many alternatives as unacceptable, it does not provide unique right answers to
every controversial moral question. On this model, different fields and
different professions may interpret the common moral system in somewhat
different ways. For example, although deception is always immoral if not
justified, what counts as deception is not the same in all professions. Not
informing a patient of an alternative treatment counts as deceptive for a physician,
but not telling a customer of an alternative to what she is about to buy does
not count as deceptive for a salesperson. The professions also have
considerable input into what special duties are incurred by becoming a member
of their profession. Applied ethics is thus not the mechanical application of a
common morality to a particular profession or field, but an independent
discipline that clarifies and analyzes the practices in a field or profession
so that common morality can be applied.
a priori, prior to or
independent of experience; contrasted with ‘a posteriori’ empirical. These two
terms are primarily used to mark a distinction between 1 two modes of epistemic
justification, together with derivative distinctions between 2 kinds of propositions,
3 kinds of knowledge, and 4 kinds of argument. They are also used to indicate a
distinction between 5 two ways in which a concept or idea may be acquired. 1 A
belief or claim is said to be justified a priori if its epistemic
justification, the reason or warrant for thinking it to be true, does not
depend at all on sensory or introspective or other sorts of experience; whereas
if its justification does depend at least in part on such experience, it is
said to be justified a posteriori or empirically. This specific distinction has
to do only with the justification of the belief, and not at all with how the
constituent concepts are acquired; thus it is no objection to a claim of a
priori justificatory status for a particular belief that experience is required
for the acquisition of some of the constituent concepts. It is clear that the
relevant notion of experience includes sensory and introspective experience, as
well as such things as kinesthetic experience. Equally clearly, to construe
experience in the broadest possible sense of, roughly, a conscious undergoing
of any sort would be to destroy the point of the distinction, since even a
priori justification presumably involves some sort of conscious process of
awareness. The construal that is perhaps most faithful to the traditional usage
is that which construes experience as any sort of cognitive input that derives,
presumably causally, from features of the actual world that may not hold in
other possible worlds. Thus, e.g., such things as clairvoyance or telepathy, if
they were to exist, would count as forms of experience and any knowledge
resulting therefrom as a posteriori; but the intuitive apprehension of
properties or numbers or other sorts of abstract entities that are the same in
all possible worlds, would not. Understood in this way, the concept of a priori
justification is an essentially negative concept, specifying as it does what
the justification of the belief does not depend on, but saying nothing a priori
a priori 35 35 about what it does depend
on. Historically, the main positive conception was that offered by proponents
of rationalism such as Plato, Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz, according to
which a priori justification derives from the intuitive apprehension of
necessary facts pertaining to universals and other abstract entities. Although
Kant is often regarded as a rationalist, his restriction of substantive a
priori knowledge to the world of appearances represents a major departure from
the main rationalist tradition. In contrast, proponents of traditional
empiricism, if they do not repudiate the concept of a priori justification
altogether as does Quine, typically attempt to account for such justification
by appeal to linguistic or conceptual conventions. The most standard formulation
of this empiricist view a development of the view of Hume that all a priori
knowledge pertains to “relations of ideas” is the claim typical of logical
positivism that all a priori knowable claims or propositions are analytic. A
rationalist would claim in opposition that at least some a priori claims or
propositions are synthetic. 2 A proposition that is the content of an a priori
justified belief is often referred to as an a priori proposition or an a priori
truth. This usage is also often extended to include any proposition that is
capable of being the content of such a belief, whether it actually has this
status or not. 3 If, in addition to being justified a priori or a posteriori, a
belief is also true and satisfies whatever further conditions may be required
for it to constitute knowledge, that knowledge is derivatively characterized as
a priori or a posteriori empirical, respectively. Though a priori justification
is often regarded as by itself guaranteeing truth, this should be regarded as a
further substantive thesis, not as part of the very concept of a priori
justification. Examples of knowledge that have been classically regarded as a
priori in this sense are mathematical knowledge, knowledge of logical truths,
and knowledge of necessary entailments and exclusions of commonsense concepts
‘Nothing can be red and green all over at the same time’, ‘If A is later than B
and B is later than C, then A is later than C’; but many claims of metaphysics,
ethics, and even theology have also been claimed to have this status. 4 A
deductively valid argument that also satisfies the further condition that each
of the premises or sometimes one or more particularly central premises are
justified a priori is referred to as an a priori argument. This label is also
sometimes applied to arguments that are claimed to have this status, even if
the correctness of this claim is in question. 5 In addition to the uses just
catalogued that derive from the distinction between modes of justification, the
terms ‘a priori’ and ‘a posteriori’ are also employed to distinguish two ways
in which a concept or idea might be acquired by an individual person. An a
posteriori or empirical concept or idea is one that is derived from experience,
via a process of abstraction or ostensive definition. In contrast, an a priori
concept or idea is one that is not derived from experience in this way and thus
presumably does not require any particular experience to be realized though the
explicit realization of such a concept might still require experience as a
“trigger”. The main historical account of such concepts, again held mainly by
rationalists, construes them as innate, either implanted in the mind by God or,
in the more contemporary version of the claim held by Chomsky, Fodor, and
others, resulting from evolutionary development. Concepts typically regarded as
having this sort of status include the concepts of substance, causation, God,
necessity, infinity, and many others. Empiricists, in contrast, typically hold
that all concepts are derived from experience.
Aquinas, Saint Thomas
122574, Italian philosopher-theologian, the most influential thinker of the
medieval period. He produced a powerful philosophical synthesis that combined
Aristotelian and Neoplatonic elements within a Christian context in an original
and ingenious way. Life and works. Thomas was born at Aquino castle in
Roccasecca, Italy, and took early schooling at the Benedictine Abbey of Monte
Cassino. He then studied liberal arts and philosophy at the of Naples 123944 and joined the Dominican
order. While going to Paris for further studies as a Dominican, he was detained
by his family for about a year. Upon being released, he studied with the
Dominicans at Paris, perhaps privately, until 1248, when he journeyed to a
priori argument Aquinas, Saint Thomas 36
36 Cologne to work under Albertus Magnus. Thomas’s own report reportatio
of Albertus’s lectures on the Divine Names of Dionysius and his notes on
Albertus’s lectures on Aristotle’s Ethics date from this period. In 1252 Thomas
returned to Paris to lecture there as a bachelor in theology. His resulting
commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard dates from this period, as do two
philosophical treatises, On Being and Essence De ente et essentia and On the
Principles of Nature De principiis naturae. In 1256 he began lecturing as
master of theology at Paris. From this period 125659 date a series of
scriptural commentaries, the disputations On Truth De veritate, Quodlibetal
Questions VIIXI, and earlier parts of the Summa against the Gentiles Summa
contra gentiles; hereafter SCG. At different locations in Italy from 1259 to
1269, Thomas continued to write prodigiously, including, among other works, the
completion of the SCG; a commentary on the Divine Names; disputations On the
Power of God De potentia Dei and On Evil De malo; and Summa of Theology Summa
theologiae; hereafter ST, Part I. In January 1269, he resumed teaching in Paris
as regent master and wrote extensively until returning to Italy in 1272. From
this second Parisian regency date the disputations On the Soul De anima and On
Virtues De virtutibus; continuation of ST; Quodlibets IVI and XII; On the Unity
of the Intellect against the Averroists De unitate intellectus contra
Averroistas; most if not all of his commentaries on Aristotle; a commentary on
the Book of Causes Liber de causis; and On the Eternity of the World De
aeternitate mundi. In 1272 Thomas returned to Italy where he lectured on
theology at Naples and continued to write until December 6, 1273, when his
scholarly work ceased. He died three months later en route to the Second
Council of Lyons. Doctrine. Aquinas was both a philosopher and a theologian.
The greater part of his writings are theological, but there are many strictly
philosophical works within his corpus, such as On Being and Essence, On the
Principles of Nature, On the Eternity of the World, and the commentaries on
Aristotle and on the Book of Causes. Also important are large sections of
strictly philosophical writing incorporated into theological works such as the
SCG, ST, and various disputations. Aquinas clearly distinguishes between
strictly philosophical investigation and theological investigation. If
philosophy is based on the light of natural reason, theology sacra doctrina
presupposes faith in divine revelation. While the natural light of reason is
insufficient to discover things that can be made known to human beings only
through revelation, e.g., belief in the Trinity, Thomas holds that it is
impossible for those things revealed to us by God through faith to be opposed
to those we can discover by using human reason. For then one or the other would
have to be false; and since both come to us from God, God himself would be the
author of falsity, something Thomas rejects as abhorrent. Hence it is
appropriate for the theologian to use philosophical reasoning in theologizing.
Aquinas also distinguishes between the orders to be followed by the theologian
and by the philosopher. In theology one reasons from belief in God and his
revelation to the implications of this for created reality. In philosophy one
begins with an investigation of created reality insofar as this can be
understood by human reason and then seeks to arrive at some knowledge of divine
reality viewed as the cause of created reality and the end or goal of one’s
philosophical inquiry SCG II, c. 4. This means that the order Aquinas follows
in his theological Summae SCG and ST is not the same as that which he
prescribes for the philosopher cf. Prooemium to Commentary on the Metaphysics.
Also underlying much of Aquinas’s thought is his acceptance of the difference
between theoretical or speculative philosophy including natural philosophy,
mathematics, and metaphysics and practical philosophy. Being and analogy. For
Aquinas the highest part of philosophy is metaphysics, the science of being as
being. The subject of this science is not God, but being, viewed without
restriction to any given kind of being, or simply as being Prooemium to
Commentary on Metaphysics; In de trinitate, qu. 5, a. 4. The metaphysician does
not enjoy a direct vision of God in this life, but can reason to knowledge of
him by moving from created effects to awareness of him as their uncreated
cause. God is therefore not the subject of metaphysics, nor is he included in
its subject. God can be studied by the metaphysician only indirectly, as the
cause of the finite beings that fall under being as being, the subject of the
science. In order to account for the human intellect’s discovery of being as
being, in contrast with being as mobile studied by natural philosophy or being
as quantified studied by mathematics, Thomas appeals to a special kind of
intellectual operation, a negative judgment, technically named by him
“separation.” Through this operation one discovers that being, in order to be
realized as such, need not be material and changAquinas, Saint Thomas Aquinas,
Saint Thomas 37 37 ing. Only as a
result of this judgment is one justified in studying being as being. Following
Aristotle and Averroes, Thomas is convinced that the term ‘being’ is used in
various ways and with different meanings. Yet these different usages are not
unrelated and do enjoy an underlying unity sufficient for being as being to be
the subject of a single science. On the level of finite being Thomas adopts and
adapts Aristotle’s theory of unity by reference to a first order of being. For
Thomas as for Aristotle this unity is guaranteed by the primary referent in our
predication of being substance. Other
things are named being only because they are in some way ordered to and
dependent on substance, the primary instance of being. Hence being is
analogous. Since Thomas’s application of analogy to the divine names
presupposes the existence of God, we shall first examine his discussion of that
issue. The existence of God and the “five ways.” Thomas holds that unaided
human reason, i.e., philosophical reason, can demonstrate that God exists, that
he is one, etc., by reasoning from effect to cause De trinitate, qu. 2, a. 3;
SCG I, c. 4. Best-known among his many presentations of argumentation for God’s
existence are the “five ways.” Perhaps even more interesting for today’s
student of his metaphysics is a brief argument developed in one of his first
writings, On Being and Essence c.4. There he wishes to determine how essence is
realized in what he terms “separate substances,” i.e., the soul, intelligences
angels of the Christian tradition, and the first cause God. After criticizing
the view that created separate substances are composed of matter and form,
Aquinas counters that they are not entirely free from composition. They are
composed of a form or essence and an act of existing esse. He immediately
develops a complex argument: 1 We can think of an essence or quiddity without
knowing whether or not it actually exists. Therefore in such entities essence
and act of existing differ unless 2 there is a thing whose quiddity and act of
existing are identical. At best there can be only one such being, he continues,
by eliminating multiplication of such an entity either through the addition of
some difference or through the reception of its form in different instances of
matter. Hence, any such being can only be separate and unreceived esse, whereas
esse in all else is received in something else, i.e., essence. 3 Since esse in
all other entities is therefore distinct from essence or quiddity, existence is
communicated to such beings by something else, i.e., they are caused. Since
that which exists through something else must be traced back to that which
exists of itself, there must be some thing that causes the existence of
everything else and that is identical with its act of existing. Otherwise one
would regress to infinity in caused causes of existence, which Thomas here
dismisses as unacceptable. In qu. 2, a. 1 of ST I Thomas rejects the claim that
God’s existence is self-evident to us in this life, and in a. 2 maintains that
God’s existence can be demonstrated by reasoning from knowledge of an existing
effect to knowledge of God as the cause required for that effect to exist. The
first way or argument art. 3 rests upon the fact that various things in our
world of sense experience are moved. But whatever is moved is moved by
something else. To justify this, Thomas reasons that to be moved is to be
reduced from potentiality to actuality, and that nothing can reduce itself from
potency to act; for it would then have to be in potency if it is to be moved
and in act at the same time and in the same respect. This does not mean that a
mover must formally possess the act it is to communicate to something else if
it is to move the latter; it must at least possess it virtually, i.e., have the
power to communicate it. Whatever is moved, therefore, must be moved by
something else. One cannot regress to infinity with moved movers, for then there
would be no first mover and, consequently, no other mover; for second movers do
not move unless they are moved by a first mover. One must, therefore, conclude
to the existence of a first mover which is moved by nothing else, and this
“everyone understands to be God.” The second way takes as its point of
departure an ordering of efficient causes as indicated to us by our
investigation of sensible things. By this Thomas means that we perceive in the
world of sensible things that certain efficient causes cannot exercise their
causal activity unless they are also caused by something else. But nothing can
be the efficient cause of itself, since it would then have to be prior to
itself. One cannot regress to infinity in ordered efficient causes. In ordered
efficient causes, the first is the cause of the intermediary, and the
intermediary is the cause of the last whether the intermediary is one or many.
Hence if there were no first efficient cause, there would be no intermediary
and no last cause. Thomas concludes from this that one must acknowledge the
existence of a first efficient cause, “which everyone names God.” The third way
consists of two major parts. Some Aquinas, Saint Thomas Aquinas, Saint Thomas
38 38 textual variants have complicated
the proper interpretation of the first part. In brief, Aquinas appeals to the
fact that certain things are subject to generation and corruption to show that
they are “possible,” i.e., capable of existing and not existing. Not all things
can be of this kind revised text, for that which has the possibility of not
existing at some time does not exist. If, therefore, all things are capable of
not existing, at some time there was nothing whatsoever. If that were so, even
now there would be nothing, since what does not exist can only begin to exist
through something else that exists. Therefore not all beings are capable of
existing and not existing. There must be some necessary being. Since such a
necessary, i.e., incorruptible, being might still be caused by something else,
Thomas adds a second part to the argument. Every necessary being either depends
on something else for its necessity or it does not. One cannot regress to
infinity in necessary beings that depend on something else for their necessity.
Therefore there must be some being that is necessary of itself and that does
not depend on another cause for its necessity, i.e., God. The statement in the
first part to the effect that what has the possibility of not existing at some
point does not exist has been subject to considerable dispute among
commentators. Moreover, even if one grants this and supposes that every
individual being is a “possible” and therefore has not existed at some point in
the past, it does not easily follow from this that the totality of existing
things will also have been nonexistent at some point in the past. Given this,
some interpreters prefer to substitute for the third way the more satisfactory
versions found in SCG I ch. 15 and SCG II ch. 15. Thomas’s fourth way is based
on the varying degrees of perfection we discover among the beings we
experience. Some are more or less good, more or less true, more or less noble,
etc., than others. But the more and less are said of different things insofar
as they approach in varying degrees something that is such to a maximum degree.
Therefore there is something that is truest and best and noblest and hence that
is also being to the maximum degree. To support this Thomas comments that those
things that are true to the maximum degree also enjoy being to the maximum
degree; in other words he appeals to the convertibility between being and truth
of being. In the second part of this argument Thomas argues that what is
supremely such in a given genus is the cause of all other things in that genus.
Therefore there is something that is the cause of being, goodness, etc., for
all other beings, and this we call God. Much discussion has centered on
Thomas’s claim that the more and less are said of different things insofar as
they approach something that is such to the maximum degree. Some find this
insufficient to justify the conclusion that a maximum must exist, and would
here insert an appeal to efficient causality and his theory of participation.
If certan entities share or participate in such a perfection only to a limited
degree, they must receive that perfection from something else. While more
satisfactory from a philosophical perspective, such an insertion seems to
change the argument of the fourth way significantly. The fifth way is based on
the way things in the universe are governed. Thomas observes that certain
things that lack the ability to know, i.e., natural bodies, act for an end.
This follows from the fact that they always or at least usually act in the same
way to attain that which is best. For Thomas this indicates that they reach
their ends by “intention” and not merely from chance. And this in turn implies
that they are directed to their ends by some knowing and intelligent being.
Hence some intelligent being exists that orders natural things to their ends.
This argument rests on final causality and should not be confused with any
based on order and design. Aquinas’s frequently repeated denial that in this
life we can know what God is should here be recalled. If we can know that God
exists and what he is not, we cannot know what he is see, e.g., SCG I, c. 30.
Even when we apply the names of pure perfections to God, we first discover such
perfections in limited fashion in creatures. What the names of such perfections
are intended to signify may indeed be free from all imperfection, but every
such name carries with it some deficiency in the way in which it signifies.
When a name such as ‘goodness’, for instance, is signified abstractly e.g.,
‘God is goodness’, this abstract way of signifying suggests that goodness does
not subsist in itself. When such a name is signified concretely e.g., ‘God is
good’, this concrete way of signifying implies some kind of composition between
God and his goodness. Hence while such names are to be affirmed of God as
regards that which they signify, the way in which they signify is to be denied
of him. This final point sets the stage for Thomas to apply his theory of
analogy to the divine names. Names of pure perfections such as ‘good’, ‘true’,
‘being’, etc., cannot be applied to God with Aquinas, Saint Thomas Aquinas,
Saint Thomas 39 39 exactly the same
meaning they have when affirmed of creatures univocally, nor with entirely
different meanings equivocally. Hence they are affirmed of God and of creatures
by an analogy based on the relationship that obtains between a creature viewed
as an effect and God its uncaused cause. Because some minimum degree of
similarity must obtain between any effect and its cause, Thomas is convinced
that in some way a caused perfection imitates and participates in God, its
uncaused and unparticipated source. Because no caused effect can ever be equal
to its uncreated cause, every perfection that we affirm of God is realized in
him in a way different from the way we discover it in creatures. This dissimilarity
is so great that we can never have quidditative knowledge of God in this life
know what God is. But the similarity is sufficient for us to conclude that what
we understand by a perfection such as goodness in creatures is present in God
in unrestricted fashion. Even though Thomas’s identification of the kind of
analogy to be used in predicating divine names underwent some development, in
mature works such as On the Power of God qu. 7, a. 7, SCG I c.34, and ST I qu.
13, a. 5, he identifies this as the analogy of “one to another,” rather than as
the analogy of “many to one.” In none of these works does he propose using the
analogy of “proportionality” that he had previously defended in On Truth qu. 2,
a. 11. Theological virtues. While Aquinas is convinced that human reason can
arrive at knowledge that God exists and at meaningful predication of the divine
names, he does not think the majority of human beings will actually succeed in
such an effort SCG I, c. 4; ST IIIIae, qu. 2, a. 4. Hence he concludes that it
was fitting for God to reveal such truths to mankind along with others that
purely philosophical inquiry could never discover even in principle. Acceptance
of the truth of divine revelation presupposes the gift of the theological
virtue of faith in the believer. Faith is an infused virtue by reason of which
we accept on God’s authority what he has revealed to us. To believe is an act
of the intellect that assents to divine truth as a result of a command on the
part of the human will, a will that itself is moved by God through grace ST II
IIae, qu. 2, a. 9. For Thomas the theological virtues, having God the ultimate
end as their object, are prior to all other virtues whether natural or infused.
Because the ultimate end must be present in the intellect before it is present
to the will, and because the ultimate end is present in the will by reason of
hope and charity the other two theological virtues, in this respect faith is
prior to hope and charity. Hope is the theological virtue through which we
trust that with divine assistance we will attain the infinite good eternal enjoyment of God ST IIIIae, qu. 17,
aa. 12. In the order of generation, hope is prior to charity; but in the order
of perfection charity is prior both to hope and faith. While neither faith nor
hope will remain in those who reach the eternal vision of God in the life to
come, charity will endure in the blessed. It is a virtue or habitual form that
is infused into the soul by God and that inclines us to love him for his own
sake. If charity is more excellent than faith or hope ST II IIae, qu. 23, a. 6,
through charity the acts of all other virtues are ordered to God, their
ultimate end qu. 23, a. 8.
Arabic philosophy, the
philosophy produced in Arabic by philosophers of various ethnic and religious
backgrounds who lived in societies in which Islamic civilization was dominant
and who identified with its cultural values. The appellation ‘Islamic
philosophy’ is misleading, for it suggests a specific religious content that
was not necessarily there just as
medieval Latin philosophy is not “Christian” philosophy. In the historical
evolution of Western philosophy it is the heir to post-Plotinian late Grecian
philosophy and the immediate precursor of later medieval philosophy, which it
heavily influenced and to which it exhibits a parallel but independent
development after Avicenna well into the twentieth century. The philosophical
curriculum of higher education that had spread among the Hellenized peoples of
Egypt, the Middle East, and Iran in the sixth century followed the
classification of the sciences current in Alexandria, a classification that had
developed from that of Aristotle’s works. Aristotle’s Organon, including the
Rhetoric and Poetics, and prefaced by Porphyry’s Isagoge, constituted the
canonical nine books on logic, the instrument of philosophy. Philosophy proper
was then divided into theoretical and practical: theoretical philosophy was
further subdivided into physics, mathematics, and metaphysics; and practical
into ethics, economics household management, and politics. Carriers of this
higher education were primarily the Eastern churches and monastic centers in
the Fertile Crescent. With the advent of Islam in the seventh Arabic philosophy
Arabic philosophy 40 40 century and the
eventual spread of Arabic as the language of learning, the entire curriculum
was translated upon demand into Arabic by Syriacspeaking Christians in the
eighth through the tenth centuries. The demand from Arab intellectuals, who by
the time of the translations had developed a significant scholarly tradition of
their own and actively commissioned the translations. The entire corpus of
Aristotle’s writings, together with the complete range of commentaries from
Alexander of Aphrodisias onward, constituted in Arabic the standard textbooks
in logic, physics including meteorology, the theory of the soul, and zoology,
metaphysics, and ethics. Metaphysics was also studied as a rule in conjunction
with or in the light of the pseudoAristotelian Theologia Aristotelis selections
from Plotinus’s Enneads, Books 46 and the Liber de causis, along with other
selections from Proclus’s Elements of Theology. Mathematics included geometry
Euclid’s Elements, astronomy Ptolemy’s Almagest, arithmetic Nicomachus’s
Introduction, and music Ptolemy’s Harmonics. Economics was based almost
exclusively on the neo-Pythagorean Bryson’s Oikonomikos, while politics mainly
drew on Plato’s Republic and the Laws and especially on the pseudepigraphic
correspondence between Aristotle and Alexander Aristotle’s Politics was known
in Arabic in fragmentary form. In medicine, which was considered an applied
science and as such remained outside this classification, Galen’s entire works
were translated. His abridgments of Plato and his Stoicizing logic formed the
basic source of knowledge on these subjects in Arabic. The early history of
Arabic philosophy presents two independent lines of development. One is
associated with the first philosopher and Arab polymath al-Kindi d.873 and his
followers, notably as-Sarakhsi d.889, Abu-Zayd alBalkhi d.934, and al-‘Amiri
d.992. These philosophers, who appear to stand closer to the Neoplatonism of
Athens than to the neo-Aristotelianism of Alexandria, sought in their works to
present the various parts of philosophy to an Arab audience, integrate them
into Islamic intellectual life, and solve the philosophical problems that arose
in the process. The famous physician Rhazes Abu-Bakr ar-Razi, d.925 may be
tenuously related to this line, although he appears to be mostly an autodidact
and his philosophy was decidedly more eclectic, leaving no following. The
second is that of the Aristotelians of Baghdad, founded by the Nestorian
scholar and translator Matta Ibn Yanus d.940. His Aristotelianism can be traced
directly to the Alexandrian commentators and reaches beyond them to Alexander
of Aphrodisias and Themistius. His students, al-Farabi d.950 and Yahya Ibn ‘Adi
d.974, and the wide circle of disciples of the latter, prominent among whom are
Abu-Sulayman as-Sijistani d.c.985, ‘Isa Ibn-Zur‘a d.1008, AlHasan Ibn-Suwar
d.c.1030, and Abu-l-Faraj Ibn at-Tayyib d.1043, engaged in rigorous textual
analysis and philosophical interpretation of Aristotle’s works and composed
independent monographs on all branches of philosophy. The Aristotelian line of
Baghdad, and especially the work of al-Farabi, was transmitted to Islamic Spain
al-Andalus toward the end of the tenth century and formed the basis of the
philosophical tradition there, whose major exponents were Ibn Bajja Avempace,
d.1139, Ibn Tufayl d.1186, Averroes Ibn Rushd, d.1198, and Maimonides Ibn
Maymun, d.1204. This tradition came to an end with the reconquista of all
Islamic Spain except Granada about two decades after the death of Ibn Tumlas
d.1223, the last major Andalusian philosopher. These two lines eventually merge
in the work of Avicenna, who set himself the task of synthesizing, in the light
of concerns valid in his time, the divergent tendencies of Aristotelian
philosophy as it had developed throughout the ages. The Alexandrian schema of
the classification of the sciences, which was adopted by Arabic philosophy,
implicitly also presented, by means of the connections it established among the
various subjects, a blueprint of a work that would encompass all philosophy.
Philosophers prior to Avicenna, both the Grecians after Plotinus and the Arabs,
failed to note its potential as an outline for a comprehensive work on all
philosophy, and had worked on different parts of it. Avicenna was the first to
perceive this and to create in his various writings an internally consistent
system having mutually interdependent parts and based on the syllogistic logic
of Aristotle. His philosophical summae thus mark the end of ancient and the
beginning of Scholastic philosophy. In these works Avicenna paid relatively
little attention to certain parts of philosophy, in particular the mathematical
part of theoretical, and virtually the entirety of practical, philosophy. As a
result, Arabic philosophy after him concentrated on three major fields logic, physics, and metaphysics which became the norm. Practical philosophy
developed along different lines, to a large extent divorced from mainstream
philosophy. The highly influential work by Miskawayh d.1030 on ethics provided
a model that was followed by later treatises, which constituted a sepArabic
philosophy Arabic philosophy 41 41
arate genre of philosophical writings. As for mathematics, its different parts
were pursued largely independently of the rest of philosophy. After Avicenna,
Arabic philosophy was dominated by his thought and developed along the lines of
the reconstructed Peripateticism he established. In the first place, his
powerful integrative systematization of philosophy elicited a reaction by
certain philosophers toward a more pristine Aristotelianism, notably by
Averroes, ‘Abd-al-Latif al-Baghdadi d.1231, and the eighteenth-century Ottoman
scholar Yanyali Esat As‘ad of Yanya, d.1730, who even executed new Arabic
translations from the Grecian of some of Aristotle’s physical works. Secondly, it
generated among his followers, notable among whom are Nafir-ad-Din at-Tusi
d.1274 and Qutb-ad-Din ar-Razi d.1364, a long series of philosophically fecund
commentaries and supercommentaries. Thirdly, it forced most theological writing
to adopt logic as its method, and philosophical, rather than theological,
analysis as the means of argumentation, a procedure established by al-Ghazali
d.1111 and consolidated by Fakhr-ad-Din ar-Razi d.1209. And fourthly, it formed
the basis for the further development of his metaphysics in particular the
concepts of essence and existence and the schema of emanation through the
incorporation of the illuminationist philosophy of Suhrawardi of Aleppo d.1193
and the mystical theories of Ibn ‘Arabi d.1240 in the works of Shiite philosophers
active since Safavid times sixteenth century. This movement, initiated by Mir
Damad d.1632 and developed by his pupil Mulla Fadra d.1640, has continued after
the latter’s death among Iranian philosophers writing partly also in Persian.
The colonization of the Arab world by Western powers since the nineteenth
century has resulted in the spread of modern European, and especially French,
philosophy among Arab intellectuals. Modern Arab philosophical thought is now
developing along these lines while at the same time efforts are being made to
relate it to traditional Arabic philosophy.
.
aradhya, Sanskrit word
meaning ‘object of worship or reverence’. In traditional Indian society,
reverence was almost a way of life. Elders, especially one’s parents and
teachers, were held in godlike esteem. The Indians revered life in any form as
sacred; hence, ahimsa nonviolence and vegetarianism were two important features
of the ideal Indian life. In the Hindu polytheistic tradition, which continues
even today, the countless Vedic deities, along with the later gods and
goddesses in the Hindu pantheon, serve as aradhya objects. A popular form of
aradhya in today’s Hindu society is often a chosen deity worshiped in a
household.
Arcesilaus of Pitane
c.315242 B.C., Grecian Skeptic philosopher, founder of the Middle Academy.
Influenced by Socratic elenchus, he claimed that, unlike Socrates, he was not
even certain that he was certain of nothing. He shows the influence of Pyrrho
in attacking the Stoic doctrine that the subjective certainty of the wise is
the criterion of truth. At the theoretical level he advocated epoche,
suspension of rational judgment; at the practical, he argued that eulogon,
probability, can justify action an early
version of coherentism. His ethical views were not extreme; he held, e.g., that
one should attend to one’s own life rather than external objects. Though he
wrote nothing except verse, he led the Academy into two hundred years of
Skepticism. R.C. Archelaus of Athens.
Archytas fl. 400350 B.C.,
Grecian Pythagorean philosopher from Tarentum in southern Italy. He was elected
general seven times and sent a ship to rescue Plato from Dionysius II of
Syracuse in 361. He is famous for solutions to specific mathematical problems,
such as the doubling of the cube, but little is known about his general
philosophical principles. His proof that the numbers in a superparticular ratio
have no mean proportional has relevance to music theory, as does his work with
the arithmetic, geometric, and harmonic means. He gave mathematical accounts of
the diatonic, enharmonic, and chromatic scales and developed a theory of
acoustics. Fragments 1 and 2 and perhaps 3 are authentic, but most material
preserved in his name is spurious.
Arendt, Hannah 190675,
German-born American social and political theorist. She was aradhya Arendt,
Hannah 42 42 educated in her native
Germany, studying with Heidegger and Jaspers; fled to France in 1933; and
emigrated in 1941 to the United States, where she taught at various universities.
Her major works are The Origins of Totalitarianism 1951, The Human Condition
1958, Between Past and Future 1961, On Revolution 1963, Crises of the Republic
1972, and The Life of the Mind 1978. In Arendt’s view, for reasons established
by Kant and deepened by Nietzsche, there is a breach between being and
thinking, one that cannot be closed by thought. Understood as philosophizing or
contemplation, thinking is a form of egoism that isolates us from one another
and our world. Despite Kant, modernity remains mired in egoism, a condition
compounded by the emergence of a “mass” that consists of bodies with needs
temporarily met by producing and consuming and which demands governments that
minister to these needs. In place of thinking, laboring, and the administration
of things now called democracy, all of which are instrumental but futile as
responses to the “thrown” quality of our condition, Arendt proposed to those
capable of it a mode of being, political action, that she found in pronounced
form in pre-Socratic Greece and briefly but gloriously at the founding of the
Roman and American republics. Political action is initiation, the making of
beginnings that can be explained neither causally nor teleologically. It is
done in the space of appearances constituted by the presence of other political
actors whose re-sponses the telling of
equally unpredictable stories concerning one another’s actions determine what actions are taken and give
character to the acting participants. In addition to the refined discernments
already implied, political action requires the courage to initiate one knows
not what. Its outcome is power; not over other people or things but mutual
empowerment to continue acting in concert and thereby to overcome egoism and
achieve positive freedom and humanity.
arete, ancient Grecian
term meaning ‘virtue’ or ‘excellence’. In philosophical contexts, the term was
used mainly of virtues of human character; in broader contexts, arete was
applicable to many different sorts of excellence. The cardinal virtues in the
classical period were courage, wisdom, temperance sophrosune, piety, and
justice. Sophists such as Protagoras claimed to teach such virtues, and
Socrates challenged their credentials for doing so. Several early Platonic
dialogues show Socrates asking after definitions of virtues, and Socrates
investigates arete in other dialogues as well. Conventional views allowed that
a person can have one virtue such as courage but lack another such as wisdom,
but Plato’s Protagoras shows Socrates defending his thesis of the unity of
arete, which implies that a person who has one arete has them all. Platonic
accounts of the cardinal virtues with the exception of piety are given in Book
IV of the Republic. Substantial parts of the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle
are given over to discussions of arete, which he divides into virtues of
character and virtues of intellect. This discussion is the ancestor of most
modern theories of virtue ethics.
argument, a sequence of
statements such that some of them the premises purport to give reason to accept
another of them, the conclusion. Since we speak of bad arguments and weak
arguments, the premises of an argument need not really support the conclusion,
but they must give some appearance of doing so or the term ‘argument’ is
misapplied. Logic is mainly concerned with the question of validity: whether if
the premises are true we would have reason to accept the conclusion. A valid
argument with true premises is called sound. A valid deductive argument is one
such that if we accept the premises we are logically bound to accept the
conclusion and if we reject the conclusion we are logically bound to reject one
or more of the premises. Alternatively, the premises logically entail the
conclusion. A good inductive argument some
would reserve ‘valid’ for deductive arguments
is one such that if we accept the premises we are logically bound to
regard the conclusion as probable, and, in addition, as more probable than it
would be if the premises should be false. A few arguments have only one premise
and/or more than one conclusion.
Arianism, diverse but
related teachings in early Christianity that subordinated the Son to God the
Father. In reaction the church developed its doctrine of the Trinity, whereby
the Son and Holy Spirit, though distinct persons hypostases, share with the
Father, as his ontological equals, the one being or substance ousia of God.
Arius c.250 c.336 taught in Alexandria,
where, on the hierarchical model of Middle Platonism, he sharply distinguished
Scripture’s transcendent God from the Logos or Son incarnate in Jesus. The
latter, subject to suffering and humanly obedient to God, is inferior to the
immutable Creator, the object of that obedience. God alone is eternal and
ungenerated; the Son, divine not by nature but by God’s choosing, is generated,
with a beginning: the unique creature, through whom all else is made. The
Council of Nicea, in 325, condemned Arius and favored his enemy Athanasius,
affirming the Son’s creatorhood and full deity, having the same being or
substance homoousios as the Father. Arianism still flourished, evolving into
the extreme view that the Son’s being was neither the same as the Father’s nor
like it homoiousios, but unlike it anomoios. This too was anathematized, by the
Council of 381 at Constantinople, which, ratifying what is commonly called the
Nicene Creed, sealed orthodox Trinitarianism and the equality of the three
persons against Arian subordinationism.
Aristotle: preeminent Grecian
philosopher born in Stagira, hence sometimes called the Stagirite. Aristotle
came to Athens as a teenager and remained for two decades in Plato’s Academy.
Following Plato’s death in 347, Aristotle traveled to Assos and to Lesbos,
where he associated with Theophrastus and collected a wealth of biological
data, and later to Macedonia, where he tutored Alexander the Great. In 335 he
returned to Athens and founded his own philosophical school in the Lyceum. The
site’s colonnaded walk peripatos conferred on Aristotle and his group the name
‘the Peripatetics’. Alexander’s death in 323 unleashed antiMacedonian forces in
Athens. Charged with impiety, and mindful of the fate of Socrates, Aristotle
withdrew to Chalcis, where he died. Chiefly influenced by his association with
Plato, Aristotle also makes wide use of the preSocratics. A number of works
begin by criticizing and, ultimately, building on their views. The direction of
Plato’s influence is debated. Some scholars see Aristotle’s career as a
measured retreat from his teacher’s doctrines. For others he began as a
confirmed anti-Platonist but returned to the fold as he matured. More likely,
Aristotle early on developed a keenly independent voice that expressed enduring
puzzlement over such Platonic doctrines as the separate existence of Ideas and
the construction of physical reality from two-dimensional triangles. Such
unease was no doubt heightened by Aristotle’s appreciation for the evidential
value of observation as well as by his conviction that long-received and
well-entrenched opinion is likely to contain at least part of the truth.
Aristotle reportedly wrote a few popular works for publication, some of which
are dialogues. Of these we have only fragments and reports. Notably lost are
also his lectures on the good and on the Ideas. Ancient cataloguers also list
under Aristotle’s name some 158 constitutions of Grecian states. Of these, only
the Constitution of Athens has survived, on a papyrus discovered in 1890. What
remains is an enormous body of writing on virtually every topic of
philosophical significance. Much of it consists of detailed lecture notes,
working drafts, and accounts of his lectures written by others. Although
efforts may have been under way in Aristotle’s lifetime, Andronicus of Rhodes,
in the first century B.C., is credited with giving the Aristotelian corpus its
present organization. Virtually no extant manuscripts predate the ninth century
A.D., so the corpus has been transmitted by a complex history of manuscript
transcription. In 1831 the Berlin Academy published the first critical edition
of Aristotle’s work. Scholars still cite Aristotle by , column, and line of
this edition. Logic and language. The writings on logic and language are
concentrated in six early works: Categories, On Interpretation, Prior
Analytics, Posterior Analytics, Topics, and Sophistical Refutations. Known
since late antiquity as the Organon, these works share a concern with what is
now called semantics. The Categories focuses on the relation between uncombined
terms, such as ‘white’ or ‘man’, and the items they signify; On Interpretation
offers an account of how terms combine to yield simple statements; Prior
Analytics provides a systematic account of how three terms must be distributed
in two categorical statements so as to yield logically a third such statement;
Posterior Analytics specifies the conditions that categorical statements must
meet to play a role in scientific explanation. The Topics, sometimes said to
include Sophistical Refutations, is a handbook of “topics” and techniques for
dialectical arguments concerning, principally, the four predicables: accident
what may or may not belong to a subject, as sitting belongs to Socrates;
definition what signifies a subject’s essence, as rational animal is the
essence of man; proprium what is not in the essence of a subject but is unique
to or counterpredicable of it, as all and only persons are risible; and genus
what is in the essence of subjects differing in species, as animal is in the
essence of both men and oxen. Categories treats the basic kinds of things that
exist and their interrelations. Every uncombined term, says Aristotle,
signifies essentially something in one of ten categories a substance, a quantity, a quality, a
relative, a place, a time, a position, a having, a doing, or a being affected. This
doctrine underlies Aristotle’s admonition that there are as many proper or per
se senses of ‘being’ as there are categories. In order to isolate the things
that exist primarily, namely, primary substances, from all other things and to
give an account of their nature, two asymmetric relations of ontological
dependence are employed. First, substance ousia is distinguished from the
accidental categories by the fact that every accident is present in a substance
and, therefore, cannot exist without a substance in which to inhere. Second,
the category of substance itself is divided into ordinary individuals or
primary substances, such as Socrates, and secondary substances, such as the
species man and the genus animal. Secondary substances are said of primary substances
and indicate what kind of thing the subject is. A mark of this is that both the
name and the definition of the secondary substance can be predicated of the
primary substance, as both man and rational animal can be predicated of
Socrates. Universals in non-substance categories are also said of subjects, as
color is said of white. Therefore, directly or indirectly, everything else is
either present in or said of primary substances and without them nothing would
exist. And because they are neither present in a subject nor said of a subject,
primary substances depend on nothing else for their existence. So, in the
Categories, the ordinary individual is ontologically basic. On Interpretation
offers an account of those meaningful expressions that are true or false,
namely, statements or assertions. Following Plato’s Sophist, a simple statement
is composed of the semantically heterogeneous parts, name onoma and verb rhema.
In ‘Socrates runs’ the name has the strictly referential function of signifying
the subject of attribution. The verb, on the other hand, is essentially
predicative, signifying something holding of the subject. Verbs also indicate
when something is asserted to hold and so make precise the statement’s truth
conditions. Simple statements also include general categorical statements.
Since medieval times it has become customary to refer to the basic categoricals
by letters: A Every man is white, E No man is white, I Some man is white, and O
Not every man is white. On Interpretation outlines their logical relations in
what is now called the square of opposition: A & E are contraries, A &
O and E & I are contradictories, and A & I and E & O are
superimplications. That A implies I reflects the no longer current view that
Aristotle Aristotle 45 45 all
affirmative statements carry existential import. One ambition of On
Interpretation is a theory of the truth conditions for all statements that
affirm or deny one thing or another. However, statements involving future
contingencies pose a special problem. Consider Aristotle’s notorious sea
battle. Either it will or it will not happen tomorrow. If the first, then the
statement ‘There will be a sea battle tomorrow’ is now true. Hence, it is now
fixed that the sea battle occur tomorrow. If the second, then it is now fixed
that the sea battle not occur tomorrow. Either way there can be no future
contingencies. Although some hold that Aristotle would embrace the determinism
they find implicit in this consequence, most argue either that he suspends the
law of excluded middle for future contingencies or that he denies the principle
of bivalence for future contingent statements. On the first option Aristotle
gives up the claim that either the sea battle will happen tomorrow or not. On
the second he keeps the claim but allows that future contingent statements are
neither true nor false. Aristotle’s evident attachment to the law of excluded
middle, perhaps, favors the second option. Prior Analytics marks the invention
of logic as a formal discipline in that the work contains the first virtually
complete system of logical inference, sometimes called syllogistic. The fact
that the first chapter of the Prior Analytics reports that there is a syllogism
whenever, certain things being stated, something else follows of necessity,
might suggest that Aristotle intended to capture a general notion of logical
consequence. However, the syllogisms that constitute the system of the Prior
Analytics are restricted to the basic categorical statements introduced in On
Interpretation. A syllogism consists of three different categorical statements:
two premises and a conclusion. The Prior Analytics tells us which pairs of
categoricals logically yield a third. The fourteen basic valid forms are
divided into three figures and, within each figure, into moods. The system is
foundational because second- and third-figure syllogisms are reducible to
first-figure syllogisms, whose validity is self-evident. Although syllogisms
are conveniently written as conditional sentences, the syllogistic proper is,
perhaps, best seen as a system of valid deductive inferences rather than as a
system of valid conditional sentences or sentence forms. Posterior Analytics
extends syllogistic to science and scientific explanation. A science is a
deductively ordered body of knowledge about a definite genus or domain of
nature. Scientific knowledge episteme consists not in knowing that, e.g., there
is thunder in the clouds, but rather in knowing why there is thunder. So the
theory of scientific knowledge is a theory of explanation and the vehicle of
explanation is the first-figure syllogism Barbara: If 1 P belongs to all M and
2 M belongs to all S, then 3 P belongs to all S. To explain, e.g., why there is
thunder, i.e., why there is noise in the clouds, we say: 3H Noise P belongs to
the clouds S because 2H Quenching of fire M belongs to the clouds S and 1H
Noise P belongs to quenching of fire M. Because what is explained in science is
invariant and holds of necessity, the premises of a scientific or demonstrative
syllogism must be necessary. In requiring that the premises be prior to and
more knowable than the conclusion, Aristotle embraces the view that explanation
is asymmetrical: knowledge of the conclusion depends on knowledge of each
premise, but each premise can be known independently of the conclusion. The
premises must also give the causes of the conclusion. To inquire why P belongs
to S is, in effect, to seek the middle term that gives the cause. Finally, the
premises must be immediate and non-demonstrable. A premise is immediate just in
case there is no middle term connecting its subject and predicate terms. Were P
to belong to M because of a new middle, M1, then there would be a new, more
basic premise, that is essential to the full explanation. Ultimately, explanation
of a received fact will consist in a chain of syllogisms terminating in primary
premises that are immediate. These serve as axioms that define the science in
question because they reflect the essential nature of the fact to be explained as in 1H the essence of thunder lies in the
quenching of fire. Because they are immediate, primary premises are not capable
of syllogistic demonstration, yet they must be known if syllogisms containing
them are to constitute knowledge of the conclusion. Moreover, were it necessary
to know the primary premises syllogistically, demonstration would proceed
infinitely or in a circle. The first alternative defeats the very possibility
of explanation and the second undermines its asymmetric character. Thus, the
primary premises must be known by the direct grasp of the mind noûs. This just
signals the appropriate way for the highest principles of a science to be
known even demonstrable propositions can
be known directly, but they are explained only when located within the structure
of the relevant science, i.e., only when demonstrated syllogistically. Although
all sciences exhibit the same formal structure and use Aristotle Aristotle
46 46 certain common principles,
different sciences have different primary premises and, hence, different
subject matters. This “one genus to one science” rule legislates that each
science and its explanations be autonomous. Aristotle recognizes three kinds of
intellectual discipline. Productive disciplines, such as house building,
concern the making of something external to the agent. Practical disciplines,
such as ethics, concern the doing of something not separate from the agent,
namely, action and choice. Theoretical disciplines are concerned with truth for
its own sake. As such, they alone are sciences in the special sense of the
Posterior Analytics. The three main kinds of special science are individuated
by their objects natural science by
objects that are separate but not changeless, mathematics by objects that are
changeless but not separate, and theology by separate and changeless objects.
The mathematician studies the same objects as the natural scientist but in a
quite different way. He takes an actual object, e.g. a chalk figure used in
demonstration, and abstracts from or “thinks away” those of its properties,
such as definiteness of size and imperfection of shape, that are irrelevant to
its standing as a perfect exemplar of the purely mathematical properties under
investigation. Mathematicians simply treat this abstracted circle, which is not
separate from matter, as if it were separate. In this way the theorems they
prove about the object can be taken as universal and necessary. Physics. As the
science of nature physis, physics studies those things whose principles and
causes of change and rest are internal. Aristotle’s central treatise on nature,
the Physics, analyzes the most general features of natural phenomena: cause,
change, time, place, infinity, and continuity. The doctrine of the four causes
is especially important in Aristotle’s work. A cause aitia is something like an
explanatory factor. The material cause of a house, for instance, is the matter
hyle from which it is built; the moving or efficient cause is the builder, more
exactly, the form in the builder’s soul; the formal cause is its plan or form
eidos; and the final cause is its purpose or end telos: provision of shelter.
The complete explanation of the coming to be of a house will factor in all of
these causes. In natural phenomena efficient, formal, and final causes often
coincide. The form transmitted by the father is both the efficient cause and
the form of the child, and the latter is glossed in terms of the child’s end or
complete development. This explains why Aristotle often simply contrasts matter
and form. Although its objects are compounds of both, physics gives priority to
the study of natural form. This accords with the Posterior Analytics’
insistence that explanation proceed through causes that give the essence and
reflects Aristotle’s commitment to teleology. A natural process counts
essentially as the development of, say, an oak or a man because its very
identity depends on the complete form realized at its end. As with all things
natural, the end is an internal governing principle of the process rather than
an external goal. All natural things are subject to change kinesis. Defined as
the actualization of the potential qua potential, a change is not an
ontologically basic item. There is no category for changes. Rather, they are
reductively explained in terms of more basic things substances, properties, and potentialities. A
pale man, e.g., has the potentiality to be or become tanned. If this
potentiality is utterly unactualized, no change will ensue; if completely actualized,
the change will have ended. So the potentiality must be actualized but not, so
to speak, exhausted; i.e., it must be actualized qua potentiality. Designed for
the ongoing operations of the natural world, the Physics’ definition of change
does not cover the generation and corruption of substantial items themselves.
This sort of change, which involves matter and elemental change, receives
extensive treatment in On Generation and Corruption. Aristotle rejects the
atomists’ contention that the world consists of an infinite totality of indivisible
atoms in various arrangements. Rather, his basic stuff is uniform elemental
matter, any part of which is divisible into smaller such parts. Because nothing
that is actually infinite can exist, it is only in principle that matter is
always further dividable. So while countenancing the potential infinite,
Aristotle squarely denies the actual infinite. This holds for the motions of
the sublunary elemental bodies earth, air, fire, and water as well as for the
circular motions of the heavenly bodies composed of a fifth element, aether,
whose natural motion is circular. These are discussed in On the Heavens. The
four sublunary elements are further discussed in Meteorology, the fourth book
of which might be described as an early treatise on chemical combination.
Psychology. Because the soul psyche is officially defined as the form of a body
with the potentiality for life, psychology is a subfield of natural science. In
effect, Aristotle applies the Aristotle Aristotle 47 47 apparatus of form and matter to the
traditional Grecian view of the soul as the principle and cause of life.
Although even the nutritive and reproductive powers of plants are effects of
the soul, most of his attention is focused on topics that are psychological in
the modern sense. On the Soul gives a general account of the nature and number
of the soul’s principal cognitive faculties. Subsequent works, chiefly those
collected as the Parva naturalia, apply the general theory to a broad range of
psychological phenomena from memory and recollection to dreaming, sleeping, and
waking. The soul is a complex of faculties. Faculties, at least those
distinctive of persons, are capacities for cognitively grasping objects. Sight
grasps colors, smell odors, hearing sounds, and the mind grasps universals. An
organism’s form is the particular organization of its material parts that
enable it to exercise these characteristic functions. Because an infant, e.g.,
has the capacity to do geometry, Aristotle distinguishes two varieties of
capacity or potentiality dynamis and actuality entelecheia. The infant is a
geometer only in potentiality. This first potentiality comes to him simply by
belonging to the appropriate species, i.e., by coming into the world endowed
with the potential to develop into a competent geometer. By actualizing,
through experience and training, this first potentiality, he acquires a first
actualization. This actualization is also a second potentiality, since it
renders him a competent geometer able to exercise his knowledge at will. The exercise
itself is a second actualization and amounts to active contemplation of a
particular item of knowledge, e.g. the Pythagorean theorem. So the soul is
further defined as the first actualization of a complex natural body.
Faculties, like sciences, are individuated by their objects. Objects of
perception aisthesis fall into three general kinds. Special proper sensibles,
such as colors and sounds, are directly perceived by one and only one sense and
are immune to error. They demarcate the five special senses: sight, hearing,
smell, taste, and touch. Common sensibles, such as movement and shape, are
directly perceived by more than one special sense. Both special and common
sensibles are proper objects of perception because they have a direct causal
effect on the perceptual system. By contrast, the son of Diares is an
incidental sensible because he is perceived not directly but as a consequence
of directly perceiving something else that happens to be the son of Diares e.g., a white thing. Aristotle calls the mind
noûs the place of forms because it is able to grasp objects apart from matter.
These objects are nothing like Plato’s separately existing Forms. As
Aristotelian universals, their existence is entailed by and depends on their
having instances. Thus, On the Soul’s remark that universals are “somehow in
the soul” only reflects their role in assuring the autonomy of thought. The
mind has no organ because it is not the form or first actualization of any
physical structure. So, unlike perceptual faculties, it is not strongly
dependent on the body. However, the mind thinks its objects by way of images,
which are something like internal representations, and these are physically
based. Insofar as it thus depends on imagination phantasia, the mind is weakly
dependent on the body. This would be sufficient to establish the naturalized
nature of Aristotle’s mind were it not for what some consider an incurably
dualist intrusion. In distinguishing something in the mind that makes all
things from something that becomes all things, Aristotle introduces the
notorious distinction between the active and passive intellects and may even
suggest that the first is separable from the body. Opinion on the nature of the
active intellect diverges widely, some even discounting it as an irrelevant
insertion. But unlike perception, which depends on external objects, thinking
is up to us. Therefore, it cannot simply be a matter of the mind’s being
affected. So Aristotle needs a mechanism that enables us to produce thoughts
autonomously. In light of this functional role, the question of active
intellect’s ontological status is less pressing. Biology. Aristotle’s
biological writings, which constitute about a quarter of the corpus, bring
biological phenomena under the general framework of natural science: the four
causes, form and matter, actuality and potentiality, and especially the
teleological character of natural processes. If the Physics proceeds in an a
priori style, the History of Animals, Parts of Animals, and Generation of
Animals achieve an extraordinary synthesis of observation, theory, and general
scientific principle. History of Animals is a comparative study of generic
features of animals, including analogous parts, activities, and dispositions.
Although its morphological and physiological descriptions show surprisingly
little interest in teleology, Parts of Animals is squarely teleological. Animal
parts, especially organs, are ultimately differentiated by function rather than
morphology. The composition of, e.g., teeth and flesh is determined by their
role in the overall functioning of the organism and, hence, requires Aristotle
Aristotle 48 48 teleology. Generation
of Animals applies the formmatter and actualitypotentiality distinctions to
animal reproduction, inheritance, and the development of accidental
characteristics. The species form governs the development of an organism and
determines what the organism is essentially. Although in the Metaphysics and
elsewhere accidental characteristics, including inherited ones, are excluded
from science, in the biological writings form has an expanded role and explains
the inheritance of non-essential characteristics, such as eye color. The more
fully the father’s form is imposed on the minimally formed matter of the
mother, the more completely the father’s traits are passed on to the offspring.
The extent to which matter resists imposition of form determines the extent to
which traits of the mother emerge, or even those of more distant ancestors.
Aristotle shared the Platonists’ interest in animal classification. Recent
scholarship suggests that this is less an interest in elaborating a
Linnean-style taxonomy of the animal kingdom than an interest in establishing
the complex differentiae and genera central to definitions of living things.
The biological works argue, moreover, that no single differentia could give the
whole essence of a species and that the differentiae that do give the essence
will fall into more than one division. If the second point rejects the method
of dichotomous division favored by Plato and the Academy, the first counters
Aristotle’s own standard view that essence can be reduced to a single final
differentia. The biological sciences are not, then, automatically accommodated
by the Posterior Analytics model of explanation, where the essence or
explanatory middle is conceived as a single causal property. A number of themes
discussed in this section are brought together in a relatively late work,
Motion of Animals. Its psychophysical account of the mechanisms of animal movement
stands at the juncture of physics, psychology, and biology. Metaphysics. In
Andronicus’s edition, the fourteen books now known as the Metaphysics were
placed after the Physics, whence comes the word ‘metaphysics’, whose literal
meaning is ‘what comes after the physics’. Aristotle himself prefers ‘first
philosophy’ or ‘wisdom’ sophia. The subject is defined as the theoretical
science of the causes and principles of what is most knowable. This makes
metaphysics a limiting case of Aristotle’s broadly used distinction between
what is better known to us and what is better known by nature. The genus
animal, e.g., is better known by nature than the species man because it is
further removed from the senses and because it can be known independently of
the species. The first condition suggests that the most knowable objects would
be the separately existing and thoroughly non-sensible objects of theology and,
hence, that metaphysics is a special science. The second condition suggests
that the most knowable objects are simply the most general notions that apply
to things in general. This favors identifying metaphysics as the general
science of being qua being. Special sciences study restricted modes of being.
Physics, for instance, studies being qua having an internal principle of change
and rest. A general science of being studies the principles and causes of
things that are, simply insofar as they are. A good deal of the Metaphysics
supports this conception of metaphysics. For example, Book IV, on the principle
of non-contradiction, and Book X, on unity, similarity, and difference, treat
notions that apply to anything whatever. So, too, for the discussion of form
and actuality in the central books VII, VIII, and IX. Book XII, on the other
hand, appears to regard metaphysics as the special science of theology.
Aristotle himself attempts to reconcile these two conceptions of metaphysics.
Because it studies immovable substance, theology counts as first philosophy.
However, it is also general precisely because it is first, and so it will
include the study of being qua being. Scholars have found this solution as
perplexing as the problem. Although Book XII proves the causal necessity for
motion of an eternal substance that is an unmoved mover, this establishes no
conceptual connection between the forms of sensible compounds and the pure form
that is the unmoved mover. Yet such a connection is required, if a single
science is to encompass both. Problems of reconciliation aside, Aristotle had
to face a prior difficulty concerning the very possibility of a general science
of being. For the Posterior Analytics requires the existence of a genus for
each science but the Metaphysics twice argues that being is not a genus. The
latter claim, which Aristotle never relinquishes, is implicit in the
Categories, where being falls directly into kinds, namely, the categories.
Because these highest genera do not result from differentiation of a single
genus, no univocal sense of being covers them. Although being is, therefore,
ambiguous in as many ways as there are categories, a thread connects them. The
ontological priority accorded primary substance in the Categories is made part
of the very definition of non-substantial entities Aristotle Aristotle 49 49 in the Metaphysics: to be an accident is
by definition to be an accident of some substance. Thus, the different senses
of being all refer to the primary kind of being, substance, in the way that
exercise, diet, medicine, and climate are healthy by standing in some relation
to the single thing health. The discovery of focal meaning, as this is
sometimes called, introduces a new way of providing a subject matter with the
internal unity required for science. Accordingly, the Metaphysics modifies the
strict “one genus to one science” rule of the Posterior Analytics. A single
science may also include objects whose definitions are different so long as
these definitions are related focally to one thing. So focal meaning makes
possible the science of being qua being. Focal meaning also makes substance the
central object of investigation. The principles and causes of being in general
can be illuminated by studying the principles and causes of the primary
instance of being. Although the Categories distinguishes primary substances
from other things that are and indicates their salient characteristics e.g.,
their ability to remain one and the same while taking contrary properties, it
does not explain why it is that primary substances have such characteristics.
The difficult central books of the Metaphysics
VII, VIII, and IX investigate
precisely this. In effect, they ask what, primarily, about the Categories’
primary substances explains their nature. Their target, in short, is the
substance of the primary substances of the Categories. As concrete empirical
particulars, the latter are compounds of form and matter the distinction is not
explicit in the Categories and so their substance must be sought among these
internal structural features. Thus, Metaphysics VII considers form, matter, and
the compound of form and matter, and quickly turns to form as the best
candidate. In developing a conception of form that can play the required
explanatory role, the notion of essence to ti en einai assumes center stage.
The essence of a man, e.g., is the cause of certain matter constituting a man,
namely, the soul. So form in the sense of essence is the primary substance of
the Metaphysics. This is obviously not the primary substance of the Categories
and, although the same word eidos is used, neither is this form the species of
the Categories. The latter is treated in the Metaphysics as a kind of universal
compound abstracted from particular compounds and appears to be denied
substantial status. While there is broad, though not universal, agreement that
in the Metaphysics form is primary substance, there is equally broad
disagreement over whether this is particular form, the form belonging to a
single individual, or species form, the form common to all individuals in the
species. There is also lively discussion concerning the relation of the
Metaphysics doctrine of primary substance to the earlier doctrine of the
Categories. Although a few scholars see an outright contradiction here, most
take the divergence as evidence of the development of Aristotle’s views on
substance. Finally, the role of the central books in the Metaphysics as a whole
continues to be debated. Some see them as an entirely selfcontained analysis of
form, others as preparatory to Book XII’s discussion of non-sensible form and
the role of the unmoved mover as the final cause of motion. Practical
philosophy. Two of Aristotle’s most heralded works, the Nicomachean Ethics and
the Politics, are treatises in practical philosophy. Their aim is effective
action in matters of conduct. So they deal with what is up to us and can be
otherwise because in this domain lie choice and action. The practical nature of
ethics lies mainly in the development of a certain kind of agent. The
Nicomachean Ethics was written, Aristotle reminds us, “not in order to know
what virtue is, but in order to become good.” One becomes good by becoming a
good chooser and doer. This is not simply a matter of choosing and doing right
actions but of choosing or doing them in the right way. Aristotle assumes that,
for the most part, agents know what ought to be done the evil or vicious person
is an exception. The akratic or morally weak agent desires to do other than
what he knows ought to be done and acts on this desire against his better
judgment. The enkratic or morally strong person shares the akratic agent’s
desire but acts in accordance with his better judgment. In neither kind of
choice are desire and judgment in harmony. In the virtuous, on the other hand,
desire and judgment agree. So their choices and actions will be free of the
conflict and pain that inevitably accompany those of the akratic and enkratic
agent. This is because the part of their soul that governs choice and action is
so disposed that desire and right judgment coincide. Acquiring a stable
disposition hexis of this sort amounts to acquiring moral virtue ethike arete.
The disposition is concerned with choices as would be determined by the person
of practical wisdom phronesis; these will be actions lying between extreme
alternatives. They will lie in a mean
popularly called the “golden mean”
relative to the talents and stores of the agent. Choosing in this way is
not easily done. It involves, for instance, feeling anger or extending
Aristotle Aristotle 50 50 generosity at
the right time, toward the right people, in the right way, and for the right
reasons. Intellectual virtues, such as excellence at mathematics, can be
acquired by teaching, but moral virtue cannot. I may know what ought to be done
and even perform virtuous acts without being able to act virtuously. Nonetheless,
because moral virtue is a disposition concerning choice, deliberate performance
of virtuous acts can, ultimately, instill a disposition to choose them in
harmony and with pleasure and, hence, to act virtuously. Aristotle rejected
Plato’s transcendental Form of the Good as irrelevant to the affairs of persons
and, in general, had little sympathy with the notion of an absolute good. The
goal of choice and action is the human good, namely, living well. This,
however, is not simply a matter of possessing the requisite practical
disposition. Practical wisdom, which is necessary for living well, involves
skill at calculating the best means to achieve one’s ends and this is an
intellectual virtue. But the ends that are presupposed by deliberation are
established by moral virtue. The end of all action, the good for man, is
happiness eudaimonia. Most things, such as wealth, are valued only as a means
to a worthy end. Honor, pleasure, reason, and individual virtues, such as
courage and generosity, are deemed worthy in their own right but they can also
be sought for the sake of eudaimonia. Eudaimonia alone can be sought only for
its own sake. Eudaimonia is not a static state of the soul but a kind of
activity energeia of the soul something
like human flourishing. The happy person’s life will be selfsufficient and
complete in the highest measure. The good for man, then, is activity in
accordance with virtue or the highest virtue, should there be one. Here
‘virtue’ means something like excellence and applies to much besides man. The
excellence of an ax lies in its cutting, that of a horse in its equestrian
qualities. In short, a thing’s excellence is a matter of how well it performs
its characteristic functions or, we might say, how well it realizes its nature.
The natural functions of persons reside in the exercise of their natural
cognitive faculties, most importantly, the faculty of reason. So human
happiness consists in activity in accordance with reason. However, persons can
exercise reason in practical or in purely theoretical matters. The first
suggests that happiness consists in the practical life of moral virtue, the
second that it consists in the life of theoretical activity. Most of the
Nicomachean Ethics is devoted to the moral virtues but the final book appears
to favor theoretical activity theoria as the highest and most choiceworthy end.
It is man’s closest approach to divine activity. Much recent scholarship is
devoted to the relation between these two conceptions of the good,
particularly, to whether they are of equal value and whether they exclude or
include one another. Ethics and politics are closely connected. Aristotle
conceives of the state as a natural entity arising among persons to serve a
natural function. This is not merely, e.g., provision for the common defense or
promotion of trade. Rather, the state of the Politics also has eudaimonia as
its goal, namely, fostering the complete and selfsufficient lives of its
citizens. Aristotle produced a complex taxonomy of constitutions but reduced
them, in effect, to three kinds: monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy. Which
best serves the natural end of a state was, to some extent, a relative matter
for Aristotle. Although he appears to have favored democracy, in some
circumstances monarchy might be appropriate. The standard ordering of
Aristotle’s works ends with the Rhetoric and the Poetics. The Rhetoric’s
extensive discussion of oratory or the art of persuasion locates it between
politics and literary theory. The relatively short Poetics is devoted chiefly
to the analysis of tragedy. It has had an enormous historical influence on
aesthetic theory in general as well as on the writing of drama.
Arminius, Jacobus
15601609, Dutch theologian who, as a Dutch Reformed pastor and later professor
at the of Leiden, challenged Calvinist
orthodoxy on predestination and free will. After his death, followers codified
Arminius’s views in a document asserting that God’s grace is necessary for
salvation, but not irresistible: the divine decree depends on human free choice.
This became the basis for Arminianism, which was condemned by the Dutch
ReAristotle, commentaries on Arminius, Jacobus 51 51 formed synod but vigorously debated for
centuries among Protestant theologians of different denominations. The term
‘Arminian’ is still occasionally applied to theologians who defend a free human
response to divine grace against predestinationism.
Armstrong, David M.
b.1926, Australian philosopher of mind and metaphysician, and until his
retirement Challis Professor of Philosophy at Sydney, noted for his allegiance
to a physicalist account of consciousness and to a realist view of properties
conceived as universals. A Materialist Theory of the Mind 1968 develops a
scientifically motivated version of the view that mental states are identical
with physical states of the central nervous system. Universals and Scientific
Realism 1978 and What Is a Law of Nature? argue that a scientifically adequate
ontology must include universals in order to explain the status of natural
laws. Armstrong contends that laws must be construed as expressing relations of
necessitation between universals rather than mere regularities among
particulars. However, he is only prepared to acknowledge the existence of such
universals as are required for the purposes of scientific explanation.
Moreover, he adopts an “immanent” or “Aristotelian” as opposed to a
“transcendent” or “Platonic” realism, refusing to accept the existence of
uninstantiated universals and denying that universals somehow exist “outside”
space and time. More recently, Armstrong has integrated his scientifically
inspired physicalism and property realism within the overall framework of an
ontology of states of affairs, notably in A World of States of Affairs. Here he
advocates the truthmaker principle that every truth must be made true by some
existing state of affairs and contends that states of affairs, rather than the
universals and particulars that he regards as their constituents, are the basic
building blocks of reality. Within this ontology, which in some ways resembles
that of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus, necessity and possibility are accommodated by
appeal to combinatorial principles. As Armstrong explains in A Combinatorial
Theory of Possibility, this approach offers an ontologically economical
alternative to the realist conception of possible worlds defended by David
Lewis.
Arnauld, Antoine: philosopher,
perhaps the most important and best-known intellectual associated with the
Jansenist community at Port-Royal, as well as a staunch and orthodox champion
of Cartesian philosophy. His theological writings defend the Augustinian
doctrine of efficacious grace, according to which salvation is not earned by
one’s own acts, but granted by the irresistible grace of God. He also argues in
favor of a strict contritionism, whereby one’s absolution must be based on a
true, heartfelt repentance, a love of God, rather than a selfish fear of God’s
punishment. These views brought him and Port-Royal to the center of religious
controversy in seventeenth-century France, as Jansenism came to be perceived as
a subversive extension of Protestant reform. Arnauld was also constantly
engaged in philosophical disputation, and was regarded as one of the sharpest
and most philosophically acute thinkers of his time. His influence on several
major philosophers of the period resulted mainly from his penetrating criticism
of their systems. In 1641, Arnauld was asked to comment on Descartes’s
Meditations. The objections he sent
regarding, among other topics, the representational nature of ideas, the
circularity of Descartes’s proofs for the existence of God, and the apparent
irreconcilability of Descartes’s conception of material substance with the
Catholic doctrine of Eucharistic transubstantiation were considered by Descartes to be the most
intelligent and serious of all. Arnauld offered his objections in a
constructive spirit, and soon became an enthusiastic defender of Descartes’s
philosophy, regarding it as beneficial both to the advancement of human
learning and to Christian piety. He insists, for example, that the immortality
of the soul is well grounded in Cartesian mind body dualism. In 1662, Arnauld
composed with Pierre Nicole the Port-Royal Logic, an influential treatise on
language and reasoning. After several decades of theological polemic, during
which he fled France to the Netherlands, Arnauld resumed his public
philosophical activities with the publication in 1683 of On True and False
Ideas and in 1685 of Philosophical and Theological Reflections on the New System
of Nature and Grace. These two works, opening salvos in what would become a
long debate, constitute a detailed attack on Malebranche’s theology and its
philosophical foundations. In the first, mainly philosophical treatise, Arnauld
insists that ideas, or the mental representations that mediate human knowledge,
are nothing but acts of the mind that put us in direct cognitive and perceptual
contact with things in the world. Malebranche, as Arnauld reads him, Armstrong,
David M. Arnauld, Antoine 52 52 argues
that ideas are immaterial but nonmental objects in God’s understanding that we
know and perceive instead of physical things. Thus, the debate is often
characterized as between Arnauld’s direct realism and Malebranche’s
representative theory. Such mental acts also have representational content, or
what Arnauld following Descartes calls “objective reality.” This content
explains the act’s intentionality, or directedness toward an object. Arnauld
would later argue with Pierre Bayle, who came to Malebranche’s defense, over
whether all mental phenomena have intentionality, as Arnauld believes, or, as
Bayle asserts, certain events in the soul e.g., pleasures and pains are
non-intentional. This initial critique of Malebranche’s epistemology and
philosophy of mind, however, was intended by Arnauld only as a prolegomenon to
the more important attack on his theology; in particular, on Malebranche’s
claim that God always acts by general volitions and never by particular
volitions. This view, Arnauld argues, undermines the true Catholic system of
divine providence and threatens the efficacy of God’s will by removing God from
direct governance of the world. In 1686, Arnauld also entered into discussions
with Leibniz regarding the latter’s Discourse on Metaphysics. In the ensuing
correspondence, Arnauld focuses his critique on Leibniz’s concept of substance
and on his causal theory, the preestablished harmony. In this exchange, like
the one with Malebranche, Arnauld is concerned to preserve what he takes to be
the proper way to conceive of God’s freedom and providence; although his
remarks on substance in which he objects to Leibniz’s reintroduction of
“substantial forms” is also clearly motivated by his commitment to a strict
Cartesian ontology bodies are nothing
more than extension, devoid of any spiritual element. Most of his philosophical
activity in the latter half of the century, in fact, is a vigorous defense of
Cartesianism, particularly on theological grounds e.g., demonstrating the
consistency between Cartesian metaphysics and the Catholic dogma of real
presence in the Eucharist, as it became the object of condemnation in both
Catholic and Protestant circles.
Arrow’s paradox, also
called Arrow’s impossibility theorem, a major result in social choice theory,
named for its discoverer, economist Kenneth Arrow. It is intuitive to suppose
that the preferences of individuals in a society can be expressed formally, and
then aggregated into an expression of social preferences, a social choice
function. Arrow’s paradox is that individual preferences having certain
well-behaved formalizations demonstrably cannot be aggregated into a similarly
well-behaved social choice function satisfying four plausible formal
conditions: 1 collective rationality any
set of individual orderings and alternatives must yield a social ordering; 2
Pareto optimality if all individuals
prefer one ordering to another, the social ordering must also agree; 3
non-dictatorship the social ordering
must not be identical to a particular individual’s ordering; and 4 independence
of irrelevant alternatives the social
ordering depends on no properties of the individual orderings other than the
orders themselves, and for a given set of alternatives it depends only on the
orderings of those particular alternatives. Most attempts to resolve the
paradox have focused on aspects of 1 and 4. Some argue that preferences can be
rational even if they are intransitive. Others argue that cardinal orderings,
and hence, interpersonal comparisons of preference intensity, are
relevant.
artificial intelligence,
also called AI, the scientific effort to design and build intelligent
artifacts. Since the effort inevitably presupposes and tests theories about the
nature of intelligence, it has implications for the philosophy of mind perhaps even more than does empirical
psychology. For one thing, actual construction amounts to a direct assault on
the mindbody problem; should it succeed, some form of materialism would seem to
be vindicated. For another, a working model, even a limited one, requires a
more global conception of what intelligence is than do experiments to test
specific hypotheses. In fact, psychology’s own overview of its domain Arouet,
François-Marie artificial intelligence 53
53 has been much influenced by fundamental concepts drawn from AI.
Although the idea of an intelligent artifact is old, serious scientific
research dates only from the 1950s, and is associated with the development of
programmable computers. Intelligence is understood as a structural property or
capacity of an active system; i.e., it does not matter what the system is made
of, as long as its parts and their interactions yield intelligent behavior
overall. For instance, if solving logical problems, playing chess, or
conversing in English manifests intelligence, then it is not important whether
the “implementation” is electronic, biological, or mechanical, just as long as
it solves, plays, or talks. Computers are relevant mainly because of their
flexibility and economy: software systems are unmatched in achievable active
complexity per invested effort. Despite the generality of programmable
structures and the variety of historical approaches to the mind, the bulk of AI
research divides into two broad camps
which we can think of as language-oriented and pattern-oriented,
respectively. Conspicuous by their absence are significant influences from the
conditionedresponse paradigm, the psychoanalytic tradition, the mental picture
idea, empiricist atomistic associationism, and so on. Moreover, both AI camps
tend to focus on cognitive issues, sometimes including perception and motor
control. Notably omitted are such psychologically important topics as affect,
personality, aesthetic and moral judgment, conceptual change, mental illness,
etc. Perhaps such matters are beyond the purview of artificial intelligence;
yet it is an unobvious substantive thesis that intellect can be cordoned off
and realized independently of the rest of human life. The two main AI paradigms
emerged together in the 1950s along with cybernetic and information-theoretic
approaches, which turned out to be dead ends; and both are vigorous today. But
for most of the sixties and seventies, the language-based orientation dominated
attention and funding, for three signal reasons. First, computer data
structures and processes themselves seemed languagelike: data were
syntactically and semantically articulated, and processing was localized
serial. Second, twentieth-century linguistics and logic made it intelligible
that and how such systems might work: automatic symbol manipulation made clear,
powerful sense. Finally, the sorts of performance most amenable to the
approach explicit reasoning and
“figuring out” strike both popular and
educated opinion as particularly “intellectual”; hence, early successes were
all the more impressive, while “trivial” stumbling blocks were easier to
ignore. The basic idea of the linguistic or symbol manipulation camp is that
thinking is like talking inner discourse and, hence, that thoughts are like sentences.
The suggestion is venerable; and Hobbes even linked it explicitly to
computation. Yet, it was a major scientific achievement to turn the general
idea into a serious theory. The account does not apply only, or even
especially, to the sort of thinking that is accessible to conscious reflection.
Nor is the “language of thought” supposed to be much like English, predicate
logic, LISP, or any other familiar notation; rather, its detailed character is
an empirical research problem. And, despite fictional stereotypes, the aim is
not to build superlogical or inhumanly rational automata. Our human tendencies
to take things for granted, make intuitive leaps, and resist implausible
conclusions are not weaknesses that AI strives to overcome but abilities
integral to real intelligence that AI aspires to share. In what sense, then, is
thought supposed to be languagelike? Three items are essential. First, thought
tokens have a combinatorial syntactic structure; i.e., they are compounds of
welldefined atomic constituents in well-defined recursively specifiable
arrangements. So the constituents are analogous to words, and the arrangements
are analogous to phrases and sentences; but there is no supposition that they
should resemble any known words or grammar. Second, the contents of thought
tokens, what they “mean,” are a systematic function of their composition: the
constituents and forms of combination have determinate significances that
together determine the content of any wellformed compound. So this is like the
meaning of a sentence being determined by its grammar and the meanings of its
words. Third, the intelligent progress or sequence of thought is specifiable by
rules expressed syntactically they can
be carried out by processes sensitive only to syntactic properties. Here the
analogy is to proof theory: the formal validity of an argument is a matter of
its according with rules expressed formally. But this analogy is particularly
treacherous, because it immediately suggests the rigor of logical inference;
but, if intelligence is specifiable by formal rules, these must be far more
permissive, context-sensitive, and so on, than those of formal logic. Syntax as
such is perfectly neutral as to how the constituents are identified by sound,
by artificial intelligence artificial intelligence 54 54 shape, by magnetic profile and arranged
in time, in space, via address pointers. It is, in effect, a free parameter:
whatever can serve as a bridge between the semantics and the processing. The account
shares with many others the assumptions that thoughts are contentful meaningful
and that the processes in which they occur can somehow be realized physically.
It is distinguished by the two further theses that there must be some
independent way of describing these thoughts that mediates between
simultaneously determines their contents and how they are processed, and that,
so described, they are combinatorially structured. Such a description is
syntactical. We can distinguish two principal phases in language-oriented AI,
each lasting about twenty years. Very roughly, the first phase emphasized
processing search and reasoning, whereas the second has emphasized
representation knowledge. To see how this went, it is important to appreciate
the intellectual breakthrough required to conceive AI at all. A machine, such
as a computer, is a deterministic system, except for random elements. That is
fine for perfectly constrained domains, like numerical calculation, sorting,
and parsing, or for domains that are constrained except for prescribed randomness,
such as statistical modeling. But, in the general case, intelligent behavior is
neither perfectly constrained nor perfectly constrained with a little random
variation thrown in. Rather, it is generally focused and sensible, yet also
fallible and somewhat variable. Consider, e.g., chess playing an early test bed
for AI: listing all the legal moves for any given position is a perfectly
constrained problem, and easy to program; but choosing the best move is not.
Yet an intelligent player does not simply determine which moves would be legal
and then choose one randomly; intelligence in chess play is to choose, if not
always the best, at least usually a good move. This is something between
perfect determinacy and randomness, a “between” that is not simply a mixture of
the two. How is it achievable in a machine? The crucial innovation that first
made AI concretely and realistically conceivable is that of a heuristic
procedure. The term ‘heuristic’ derives from the Grecian word for discovery, as
in Archimedes’ exclamation “Eureka!” The relevant point for AI is that
discovery is a matter neither of following exact directions to a goal nor of
dumb luck, but of looking around sensibly, being guided as much as possible by
what you know in advance and what you find along the way. So a heuristic
procedure is one for sensible discovery, a procedure for sensibly guided
search. In chess, e.g., a player does well to bear in mind a number of rules of
thumb: other things being equal, rooks are more valuable than knights, it is an
asset to control the center of the board, and so on. Such guidelines, of
course, are not valid in every situation; nor will they all be best satisfied
by the same move. But, by following them while searching as far ahead through
various scenarios as possible, a player can make generally sensible moves much better than random within the constraints of the game. This
picture even accords fairly well with the introspective feel of choosing a
move, particularly for less experienced players. The essential insight for AI
is that such roughand-ready ceteris paribus rules can be deterministically
programmed. It all depends on how you look at it. One and the same bit of
computer program can be, from one point of view, a deterministic, infallible
procedure for computing how a given move would change the relative balance of
pieces, and from another, a generally sensible but fallible procedure for
estimating how “good” that move would be. The substantive thesis about
intelligence human and artificial
alike then is that our powerful but
fallible ability to form “intuitive” hunches, educated guesses, etc., is the
result of largely unconscious search, guided by such heuristic rules. The
second phase of language-inspired AI, dating roughly from the mid-1970s, builds
on the idea of heuristic procedure, but dramatically changes the emphasis. The
earlier work was framed by a conception of intelligence as finding solutions to
problems good moves, e.g.. From such a perspective, the specification of the
problem the rules of the game plus the current position and the provision of
some heuristic guides domain-specific rules of thumb are merely a setting of
the parameters; the real work, the real exercise of intelligence, lies in the
intensive guided search undertaken in the specified terms. The later phase,
impressed not so much by our problem-solving prowess as by how well we get
along with “simple” common sense, has shifted the emphasis from search and
reasoning to knowledge. The motivation for this shift can be seen in the following
two sentences: We gave the monkey the banana because it was ripe. We gave the
monkey the banana because it was hungry. artificial intelligence artificial
intelligence 55 55 The word ‘it’ is
ambiguous, as the terminal adjectives make clear. Yet listeners effortlessly
understand what is meant, to the point, usually, of not even noticing the
ambiguity. The question is, how? Of course, it is “just common sense” that
monkeys don’t get ripe and bananas don’t get hungry, so . . . But three further
observations show that this is not so much an answer as a restatement of the
issue. First, sentences that rely on common sense to avoid misunderstanding are
anything but rare: conversation is rife with them. Second, just about any odd
fact that “everybody knows” can be the bit of common sense that understanding
the next sentence depends on; and the range of such knowledge is vast. Yet,
third, dialogue proceeds in real time without a hitch, almost always. So the
whole range of commonsense knowledge must be somehow at our mental fingertips
all the time. The underlying difficulty is not with speed or quantity alone,
but with relevance. How does a system, given all that it knows about aardvarks,
Alabama, and ax handles, “home in on” the pertinent fact that bananas don’t get
hungry, in the fraction of a second it can afford to spend on the pronoun ‘it’?
The answer proposed is both simple and powerful: common sense is not just
randomly stored information, but is instead highly organized by topics, with
lots of indexes, cross-references, tables, hierarchies, and so on. The words in
the sentence itself trigger the “articles” on monkeys, bananas, hunger, and so
on, and these quickly reveal that monkeys are mammals, hence animals, that
bananas are fruit, hence from plants, that hunger is what animals feel when
they need to eat and that settles it.
The amount of search and reasoning is minimal; the issue of relevance is solved
instead by the antecedent structure in the stored knowledge itself. While this
requires larger and more elaborate systems, the hope is that it will make them
faster and more flexible. The other main orientation toward artificial
intelligence, the pattern-based approach
often called “connectionism” or “parallel distributed processing” reemerged from the shadow of symbol
processing only in the 1980s, and remains in many ways less developed. The
basic inspiration comes not from language or any other psychological phenomenon
such as imagery or affect, but from the microstructure of the brain. The
components of a connectionist system are relatively simple active nodes lots of them
and relatively simple connections between those nodes again, lots of them. One important type and
the easiest to visualize has the nodes divided into layers, such that each node
in layer A is connected to each node in layer B, each node in layer B is
connected to each node in layer C, and so on. Each node has an activation
level, which varies in response to the activations of other, connected nodes;
and each connection has a weight, which determines how strongly and in what
direction the activation of one node affects that of the other. The analogy
with neurons and synapses, though imprecise, is intended. So imagine a layered
network with finely tuned connection weights and random or zero activation
levels. Now suppose the activations of all the nodes in layer A are set in some
particular way some pattern is imposed
on the activation state of this layer. These activations will propagate out along
all the connections from layer A to layer B, and activate some pattern there.
The activation of each node in layer B is a function of the activations of all
the nodes in layer A, and of the weights of all the connections to it from
those nodes. But since each node in layer B has its own connections from the
nodes in layer A, it will respond in its own unique way to this pattern of
activations in layer A. Thus, the pattern that results in layer B is a joint
function of the pattern that was imposed on layer A and of the pattern of
connection weights between the two layers. And a similar story can be told
about layer B’s influence on layer C, and so on, until some final pattern is
induced in the last layer. What are these patterns? They might be any number of
things; but two general possibilities can be distinguished. They might be
tantamount to or substrata beneath representations of some familiar sort, such
as sentencelike structures or images; or they might be a kind or kinds of
representation previously unknown. Now, people certainly do sometimes think in
sentences and probably images; so, to the extent that networks are taken as
complete brain models, the first alternative must be at least partly right.
But, to that extent, the models are also more physiological than psychological:
it is rather the implemented sentences or images that directly model the mind.
Thus, it is the possibility of a new genus of representation sometimes called distributed
representation that is particularly
exciting. On this alternative, the patterns in the mind represent in some way
other than by mimetic imagery or articulate description. How? An important
feature of all network models is that there are two quite different categories
of pattern. On the one hand, there are the relatively ephemeral patterns of
activation in various artificial intelligence artificial intelligence 56 56 groups of nodes; on the other, there are
the relatively stable patterns of connection strength among the nodes. Since
there are in general many more connections than nodes, the latter patterns are
richer; and it is they that determine the capabilities of the network with
regard to the former patterns. Many of the abilities most easily and
“naturally” realized in networks can be subsumed under the heading pattern
completion: the connection weights are adjusted
perhaps via a training regime
such that the network will complete any of the activation patterns from
a predetermined group. So, suppose some fraction say half of the nodes in the
net are clamped to the values they would have for one of those patterns say P
while the remainder are given random or default activations. Then the network,
when run, will reset the latter activations to the values belonging to P thus “completing” it. If the unclamped
activations are regarded as variations or deviations, pattern completion
amounts to normalization, or grouping by similarity. If the initial or input
nodes are always the same as in layered networks, then we have pattern
association or transformation from input to output. If the input pattern is a
memory probe, pattern completion becomes access by content. If the output
pattern is an identifier, then it is pattern recognition. And so on. Note that,
although the operands are activation patterns, the “knowledge” about them, the
ability to complete them, is contained in the connection patterns; hence, that
ability or know-how is what the network represents. There is no obvious upper
bound on the possible refinement or intricacy of these pattern groupings and
associations. If the input patterns are sensory stimuli and the output patterns
are motor control, then we have a potential model of coordinated and even
skillful behavior. In a system also capable of language, a network model or
component might account for verbal recognition and content association, and
even such “nonliteral” effects as trope and tone. Yet at least some sort of
“symbol manipulation” seems essential for language use, regardless of how
networklike the implementation is. One current speculation is that it might
suffice to approximate a battery of symbolic processes as a special subsystem
within a cognitive system that fundamentally works on quite different
principles. The attraction of the pattern-based approach is, at this point, not
so much actual achievement as it is promise
on two grounds. In the first place, the space of possible models, not
only network topologies but also ways of construing the patterns, is vast.
Those built and tested so far have been, for practical reasons, rather small;
so it is possible to hope beyond their present limitations to systems of
significantly greater capability. But second, and perhaps even more attractive,
those directions in which patternbased systems show the most promise skills, recognition, similarity, and the
like are among the areas of greatest
frustration for languagebased AI. Hence it remains possible, for a while at
least, to overlook the fact that, to date, no connectionist network can perform
long division, let alone play chess or solve symbolic logic problems.
artificial life, an
interdisciplinary science studying the most general character of the
fundamental processes of life. These processes include self-organization,
self-reproduction, learning, adaptation, and evolution. Artificial life or
ALife is to theoretical biology roughly what artificial intelligence AI is to
theoretical psychology computer
simulation is the methodology of choice. In fact, since the mind exhibits many
of life’s fundamental properties, AI could be considered a subfield of ALife.
However, whereas most traditional AI models are serial systems with
complicated, centralized controllers making decisions based on global state
information, most natural systems exhibiting complex autonomous behavior are
parallel, distributed networks of simple entities making decisions based solely
on their local state information, so typical ALife models have a corresponding
distributed architecture. A computer simulation of evolving “bugs” can
illustrate what ALife models are like. Moving around in a two-dimensional world
periodically laden with heaps of “food,” these bugs eat, reproduce, and
sometimes perish from starvation. Each bug’s movement is genetically determined
by the quantities of food in its immediate neighborhood, and random mutations
and crossovers modify these genomes during reproduction. Simulations started
with random genes show spontaneous waves of highly adaptive genetic novelties
continuously sweeping through the population at precisely quantifiable rates.C.
Langston et al., eds., Artificial Life II 1991. artificial language artificial
life 57 57 ALife science raises and
promises to inform many philosophical issues, such as: Is functionalism the
right approach toward life? When, if ever, is a simulation of life really
alive? When do systems exhibit the spontaneous emergence of properties?
ascriptivism, the theory
that to call an action voluntary is not to describe it as caused in a certain
way by the agent who did it, but to express a commitment to hold the agent
responsible for the action. Ascriptivism is thus a kind of noncognitivism as
applied to judgments about the voluntariness of acts. Introduced by Hart in
“Ascription of Rights and Responsibilities,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society 1949, ascriptivism was given its name and attacked in Geach’s
“Ascriptivism,” Philosophical Review 1960. Hart recanted in the Preface to his
Punishment and Responsibility 1968.
associationism, the
psychological doctrine that association is the sole or primary basis of
learning as well as of intelligent thought and behavior. Association occurs
when one type of thought, idea, or behavior follows, or is contingent upon,
another thought, idea, or behavior or external event, and the second somehow
bonds with the first. If the idea of eggs is paired with the idea of ham, then
the two ideas may become associated. Associationists argue that complex states
of mind and mental processes can be analyzed into associated elements. The
complex may be novel, but the elements are products of past associations.
Associationism often is combined with hedonism. Hedonism explains why events
associate or bond: bonds are forged by pleasant experiences. If the
pleasantness of eating eggs is combined with the pleasantness of eating ham,
then ideas of ham and eggs associate. Bonding may also be explained by various
non-hedonistic principles of association, as in Hume’s theory of the
association of ideas. One of these principles is contiguity in place or time.
Associationism contributes to the componential analysis of intelligent,
rational activity into non-intelligent, non-rational, mechanical processes.
People believe as they do, not because of rational connections among beliefs,
but because beliefs associatively bond. Thus one may think of London when
thinking of England, not because one possesses an inner logic of geographic
beliefs from which one infers that London is in England. The two thoughts may
co-occur because of contiguity or other principles. Kinds of associationism
occur in behaviorist models of classical and operant conditioning. Certain
associationist ideas, if not associationism itself, appear in connectionist
models of cognition, especially the principle that contiguities breed bonding.
Several philosophers and psychologists, including Hume, Hartley, and J. S. Mill
among philosophers and E. L. Thorndike 18741949 and B. F. Skinner 190490 among
psychologists, are associationists.
Astell, Mary, an early
English feminist and author of A Serious Proposal to the Ladies 1694 and 1697
and Some Reflections on Marriage 1700. These works argue that women’s
shortcomings are not due to a lack of intellectual ability, since women have
rational souls, and present an educational program to fit them rationally for
their religious duties. Astell entered as well into the philosophical,
theological, and political controversies of her day. Her Letters Concerning the
Love of God 1695 is a correspondence with the ascriptivism Astell, Mary 58 58 English Malebranchian, John Norris, over
such issues as Norris’s contention that our duty is to God only. Her most
substantial work, The Christian Religion, as Professed by a Daughter of the
Church of England 1705, lays out her views on the grounds and implications of
natural and revealed religion. This work includes considerable critical
attention to John Locke’s ideas, and both this and the Letters called forth
refutations from Locke’s friend, Damaris Cudworth.
Athanasius c.297373,
early Christian father, bishop in Alexandria though frequently exiled, and a
leading protagonist in the fourth-century disputes concerning Christ’s
relationship to God. Through major works like On the Incarnation, Against the
Arians, and Letters on the Holy Spirit, Athanasius contributed greatly to the
classical doctrines of the Incarnation and the Trinity. Opposing all forms of Arianism,
which denied Christ’s divinity and reduced him to a creature, Athanasius
taught, in the language of the Nicene Creed, that Christ the Son, and likewise
the Holy Spirit, were of the same being as God the Father homoousios. Thus with
terminology and concepts drawn from Grecian philosophy, he helped to forge the
distinctly Christian and un-Hellenistic doctrine of the eternal triune God, who
became enfleshed in time and matter and restored humanity to immortality,
forfeited through sin, by involvement in its condition of corruption and
decay.
atheism from Grecian a-,
‘not’, and theos, ‘god’, the view that there are no gods. A widely used sense
denotes merely not believing in God and is consistent with agnosticism. A
stricter sense denotes a belief that there is no God; this use has become the
standard one. In the Apology Socrates is accused of atheism for not believing
in the official Athenian gods. Some distinguish between theoretical atheism and
practical atheism. A theoretical atheist is one who self-consciously denies the
existence of a supreme being, whereas a practical atheist may believe that a
supreme being exists but lives as though there were no god.
Atman, in Hindu thought,
the individual, viewed by Advaita Vedanta as numerically identical to, and by
other varieties of Vedanta as dependent on and capable of worship of, Brahman.
Sometimes in Hinduism conceived as inherently conscious and possessed of
intrinsic mental qualities, and sometimes viewed as having mental qualities
only in the sense that the composite of Atman-embodied-in-a-physical-body has
this feature, Atman beginninglessly transmigrates from life to life or, for
Advaita, appears to do so. It is embodied in successive bodies, accumulating
karma and possibly achieving enlightenment with its consequent release from
samsara, the transmigratory wheel.
attribution theory, a
theory in social psychology concerned with how and why ordinary people explain
events. People explain by attributing causal powers to certain events rather
than others. The theory attempts to describe and clarify everyday commonsense
explanation, to identify criteria of explanatory success presupposed by common
sense, and to compare and contrast commonsense explanation with scientific
explanation. The heart of attribution theory is the thesis that people tend to
attribute causal power to factors personally important to them, which they
believe covary with alleged effects. For example, a woman may designate sexual
discrimination as the cause of her not being promoted in a corporation. Being
female is important to her and she believes that promotion and failure covary
with gender. Males get promoted; females don’t. Causal attributions tend to
preserve self-esteem, reduce cognitive dissonance, and diminish the
attributor’s personal responsibility for misdeeds. When attributional styles or
habits contribute to emotional ill-being, e.g. to chronic, inappropriate
feelings of depression or guilt, attribution theory offers the following
therapeutic recommendation: change attributions so as to reduce emotional
ill-being and increase well-being. Hence if the woman blames herself for the
failure, and if self-blame is part of her depressive attributional style, she
would be encouraged to look outside herself, perhaps to sexual discrimination,
for the explanation.
Augustine, Saint, known
as Augustine of Hippo 354430, Christian philosopher and church father, one of
the chief sources of Christian thought in the West; his importance for medieval
and modern European philosophy is impossible to describe briefly or ever to
circumscribe. Matters are made more difficult because Augustine wrote
voluminously and dialectically as a Christian theologian, treating
philosophical topics for the most part only as they were helpful to theology or as corrected by it. Augustine fashioned
the narrative of the Confessions 397400 out of the events of the first half of
his life. He thus supplied later biographers with both a seductive selection of
biographical detail and a compelling story of his successive conversions from
adolescent sensuality, to the image-laden religion of the Manichaeans, to a
version of Neoplatonism, and then to Christianity. The story is an unexcelled
introduction to Augustine’s views of philosophy. It shows, for instance, that
Augustine received very little formal education in philosophy. He was trained
as a rhetorician, and the only philosophical work that he mentions among his
early reading is Cicero’s lost Hortensius, an exercise in persuasion to the
study of philosophy. Again, the narrative makes plain that Augustine finally
rejected Manichaeanism because he came to see it as bad philosophy: a set of
sophistical fantasies without rational coherence or explanatory force. More
importantly, Augustine’s final conversion to Christianity was prepared by his
reading in “certain books of the Platonists” Confessions 7.9.13. These Latin
translations, which seem to have been anthologies or manuals of philosophic
teaching, taught Augustine a form of Neoplatonism that enabled him to conceive
of a cosmic hierarchy descending from an immaterial, eternal, and intelligible
God. On Augustine’s judgment, philosophy could do no more than that; it could
not give him the power to order his own life so as to live happily and in a
stable relation with the now-discovered God. Yet in his first years as a
Christian, Augustine took time to write a number of works in philosophical
genres. Best known among them are a refutation of Academic Skepticism Contra
academicos, 386, a theodicy De ordine, 386, and a dialogue on the place of
human choice within the providentially ordered hierarchy created by God De
libero arbitrio, 388/39195. Within the decade of his conversion, Augustine was
drafted into the priesthood 391 and then consecrated bishop 395. The
thirty-five years of his life after that consecration were consumed by labors
on behalf of the church in northern Africa and through the Latin-speaking
portions of the increasingly fragmented empire. Most of Augustine’s episcopal
writing was polemical both in origin and in form; he composed against authors
or movements he judged heretical, especially the Donatists and Pelagians. But
Augustine’s sense of his authorship also led him to write works of fundamental
theology conceived on a grand scale. The most famous of these works, beyond the
Confessions, are On the Trinity 399412, 420, On Genesis according to the Letter
40115, and On the City of God 41326. On the Trinity elaborates in subtle detail
the distinguishable “traces” of Father, Son, and Spirit in the created world and
particularly in the human soul’s triad of memory, intellect, and will. The
commentary on Genesis 13, which is meant to be much more than a “literal”
commentary in the modern sense, treats many topics in philosophical psychology
and anthropology. It also teaches such cosmological doctrines as the
“seed-reasons” rationes seminales by which creatures are given intelligible
form. The City of God begins with a critique of the bankruptcy of pagan civic
religion and its attendant philosophies, but it ends with the depiction of
human history as a combat between forces of self-love, conceived as a diabolic
city of earth, and the graced love of God, which founds that heavenly city
within which alone peace is possible. attributive pluralism Augustine 60 60 A number of other, discrete doctrines
have been attached to Augustine, usually without the dialectical nuances he
would have considered indispensable. One such doctrine concerns divine
“illumination” of the human intellect, i.e., some active intervention by God in
ordinary processes of human understanding. Another doctrine typically
attributed to Augustine is the inability of the human will to do morally good
actions without grace. A more authentically Augustinian teaching is that
introspection or inwardness is the way of discovering the created hierarchies
by which to ascend to God. Another authentic teaching would be that time, which
is a distension of the divine “now,” serves as the medium or narrative
structure for the creation’s return to God. But no list of doctrines or
positions, however authentic or inauthentic, can serve as a faithful
representation of Augustine’s thought, which gives itself only through the
carefully wrought rhetorical forms of his texts.
Austin, John: English
legal philosopher known especially for his command theory of law. His career as
a lawyer was unsuccessful but his reputation as a scholar was such that on the
founding of , London, he was offered the
chair of jurisprudence. In 1832 he published the first ten of his lectures,
compressed into six as The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. Although he
published a few papers, and his somewhat fragmentary Lectures on Jurisprudence
1863 was published posthumously, it is on the Province that his reputation
rests. He and Bentham his friend, London neighbor, and fellow utilitarian were
the foremost English legal philosophers of their time, and their influence on
the course of legal philosophy endures. Austin held that the first task of
legal philosophy, one to which he bends most of his energy, is to make clear
what laws are, and if possible to explain why they are what they are: their
rationale. Until those matters are clear, legislative proposals and legal
arguments can never be clear, since irrelevant considerations will inevitably
creep in. The proper place for moral or theological considerations is in
discussion of what the positive law ought to be, not of what it is. Theological
considerations reduce to moral ones, since God can be assumed to be a good
utilitarian. It is positive laws, “that is to say the laws which are simply and
strictly so called, . . . which form the appropriate matter of general and
particular jurisprudence.” They must also be distinguished from “laws
metaphorical or figurative.” A law in its most general senseis “a rule laid
down for the guidance of an intelligent being by an intelligent being having
power over him.” It is a command, however phrased. It is the commands of men to
men, of political superiors, that form the body of positive law. General or
comparative jurisprudence, the source of the rationale, if any, of particular
laws, is possible because there are commands nearly universal that may be
attributed to God or Nature, but they become positive law only when laid down
by a ruler. The general model of an Austinian analytic jurisprudence built upon
a framework of definitions has been widely followed, but cogent objections,
especially by Hart, have undermined the command theory of law.
Austin: j. l. H. P.
Grice, “The Austinian Code.” English philosopher, a leading exponent of postwar
“linguistic” philosophy. Educated primarily as a classicist at Shrewsbury and
Balliol , Oxford, he taught philosophy at Magdalen . During World War II he
served at a high level in military intelligence, which earned him the O.B.E., Croix
de Guerre, and Legion of Merit. In 1952 he became White’s Professor of Moral
Philosophy at Oxford, and in 1955 and 1958 he held visiting appointments at
Harvard and Berkeley, respectively. In his relatively brief career, Austin
published only a few invited papers; his influence was exerted mainly through
discussion with his colleagues, whom he dominated more by critical intelligence
than by any preconceived view of what philosophy should be. Unlike some others,
Austin did not believe that philosophical problems all arise out of aberrations
from “ordinary language,” nor did he necessarily find solutions there; he
dwelt, rather, on the authority of the vernacular as a source of nice and
pregnant distinctions, and held that it deserves much closer attention than it
commonly receives from philosophers. It is useless, he thought, to pontificate
at large about knowledge, reality, or existence, for example, without first
examining in detail how, and when, the words ‘know’, ‘real’, and ‘exist’ are
employed in daily life. In Sense and Sensibilia 1962; compiled from lecture
notes, the sense-datum theory comes under withering fire for its failings in
this respect. Austin also provoked controversy with his well-known distinction
between “performative” and “constative” utterances ‘I promise’ makes a promise,
whereas ‘he promised’ merely reports one; he later recast this as a threefold
differentiation of locutionary, illocutionary, and perlocutionary “forces” in
utterance, corresponding roughly to the meaning, intention, and consequences of
saying a thing, in one context or another. Though never very stable or fully
worked out, these ideas have since found a place in the still-evolving study of
speech acts.
autarkia, ancient Grecian
term meaning ‘self-sufficiency’. Autarkia was widely regarded as a mark of the
human good, happiness eudaimonia. A life is self-sufficient when it is worthy
of choice and lacks nothing. What makes a life self-sufficient and thereby happy was a matter of controversy. Stoics
maintained that the mere possession of virtue would suffice; Aristotle and the
Peripatetics insisted that virtue must be exercised and even, perhaps,
accompanied by material goods. There was also a debate among later Grecian
thinkers over whether a self-sufficient life is solitary or whether only life
in a community can be self-sufficient.
avatar from Sanskrit
avatara, in Hindu thought, any of the repeated “descents” of the Supreme Being
into the physical world as an animal, human being, or combination thereof, to
destroy evil and restore order. Predominately identified as the actions of the
god Vishnu, these entrances into the world indicate that Vishnu as lord will
adjust the cycle of karma. Its earliest reference is in the Bhagavad Gita 150
B.C., where Krishna says that whenever dharma languishes he incarnates in age
after age to destroy evildoers and promote the good. Later lists of avatars of
Vishnu cite ten, twenty, or more, with Krishna and the Buddha as famous
examples. The inclusion of prominent local deities in the list brought them
under the influence of Vishnu devotees, and today even Jesus and Muhammad may
be included. Modern philosophers such as Radhakrishnan 18881975 redefine the
concept non-theistically, identifying an avatar as a human being who has attained
enlightenment.
Avenarius, Richard
184396, German philosopher. He was born in Paris and educated at the of Leipzig. He became a professor at Leipzig
and succeeded Windelband at the of
Zürich in 1877. For a time he was editor of the Zeitschrift für wissenschaftliche
Philosophie. His earliest work was Über die beiden ersten Phasen des
Spinozischen Pantheismus 1868. His major work, Kritik der reinen Erfahrung
Critique of Pure Experience, 2 vols., 188890, was followed by his last study,
Der menschliche Weltbegriffe 1891. In his post-Kantian Kritik Avenarius
presented a radical positivism that sought to base philosophy on scientific
principles. This “empirio-criticism” emphasized “pure experience” and
descriptive and general definitions of experience. Metaphysical claims to
transcend experience were rejected as mere creations of the mind. Like Hume,
Avenarius denied the ontological validity of substance and causality. Seeking a
scientific empiricism, he endeavored to delineate a descriptive determination
of the form and content of pure experience. He thought that the subAustralian
materialism Avenarius, Richard 62 62
jectobject dichotomy, the separation of inner and outer experiences, falsified
reality. If we could avoid “introjecting” feeling, thought, and will into
experience and thereby splitting it into subject and object, we could attain
the original “natural” view of the world. Although Avenarius, in his Critique
of Pure Experience, thought that changes in brain states parallel states of
consciousness, he did not reduce sensations or states of consciousness to
physiological changes in the brain. Because his theory of pure experience
undermined dogmatic materialism, Lenin attacked his philosophy in Materialism
and Empirio-Criticism 1952. His epistemology influenced Mach and his emphasis
upon pure experience had considerable influence on James.
Averroes, in Arabic, Ibn
Rushd 112698, Islamic philosopher, jurist, and physician. Scion of a long line
of qadis religious judges, he was born at Córdova and educated in Islamic law.
Introduced to the Almohad ruler by Ibn Tufayl, author of the philosophical
allegory Hayy Ibn Yaqzan, he feigned ignorance of philosophy, only to learn
that the leader of the dynasty so feared for its orthodoxy was thoroughly at
home with philosophical issues. He was given a robe of honor and a mount and
later invited to write his famous commentaries on Aristotle and made qadi of
Seville, finally succeeding Ibn Tufayl as royal physician and becoming chief
qadi of Córdova. He was persecuted when the sultan’s successor needed orthodox
support in his war with Christian Spain, but died in the calm of Marrakesh, the
edicts against him rescinded. His works, most often preserved in Hebrew or
Latin translations ‘Averroes’ reflects efforts to Latinize ‘Ibn Rushd’, include
medical and astronomical writings; short, middle, and long commentaries on
Aristotle “his was the ultimate human mind”; a commentary on Plato’s Republic;
and spirited juridical and conceptual defenses of philosophy: The Decisive Treatise
and Incoherence of the Incoherence. The former argues that philosophy, although
restricted to the adept, is mandated by the Koranic 59:2 injunction to reflect
on God’s design. The latter answers alGhazali’s Incoherence of the
Philosophers, defending naturalism and its presumed corollary, the world’s
eternity, but often cutting adrift the more Platonizing and original doctrines
of Avicenna, al-Ghazali’s chief stalking horse. Thus Averroes rejects
Avicenna’s idea that the world itself is contingent if it is necessitated by
its causes, arguing that removing the necessity that is the hallmark of God’s
wisdom would leave us no way of inferring a wise Author of nature. Ultimately
Averroes rejects emanation and seeks to return natural theology to the physics of
matter and motion, discrediting Avicenna’s metaphysical approach and locating
God’s act in the ordering of eternal matter. On bodily resurrection, individual
providence, and miracles, he takes refuge in authority, fudge, and bluff; and
even his defense of causal necessity smacks of a dogmatism expressive of the
awkwardness of his position and the stiffening of Peripatetic thought. Yet he
retains the idea that the intellect is immortal, indeed impersonal: since only
matter differentiates individuals, all minds are ultimately one; they reach
fulfillment and beatitude by making contact ittifal; cf. Plotinus’s aphe with
the Active Intellect. Many Jewish philosophers like Narboni and Albalag
followed Averroes’ arguments explicitly, reinterpreting Maimonides accordingly.
But Averroes’ efforts to accommodate rhetorical and dialectical along with
philosophical discourse led to the branding of his Christian followers as
exponents of a “double truth,” although no text advances such a doctrine. Siger
of Brabant, Boethius of Dacia, and Bernier of Nivelles were condemned for
Averroistic heresies at Paris in the 1270s. But from the thirteenth to
mid-seventeenth centuries Latin scholars regularly read Aristotle with
Averroes’ commentaries. His philosophic respondents include Ibn Taymiyya
d.1327, Gersonides, Albertus Magnus, and Aquinas. Spinoza’s dogged eternalism
links him vividly to Averroes.
Avicenna, in Arabic, Ibn
Sina 9801037, Islamic philosopher and physician. Born near Bukhara, where his
father served as a provincial governor, Avicenna came to manhood as the Persian
Samanid dynasty was crumbling and spent much of his life fleeing from court to
court to avoid the clutches of the rapacious conqueror Mamhmad of Ghazna. His
autobiography describes him as an intuitive student of philosophy and other Grecian
sciences who could not see the point of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, until he read
a tiny essay by al-Farabi870950, who showed him what it means to seek the
nature of being as such. It was in metaphysics that Avicenna made his greatest
contributions to philosophy, brilliantly synthesizing the rival approaches of
the Aristotelian-Neoplatonic tradition with the creationist monotheism of
Islamic dialectical theology kalam. Where Aristotle sought and found being in
its fullest sense in what was changeless in its nature above all, in the
species of things, the heavenly bodies, the cosmos as a whole, kalam understood
being as the immediately given, allowing no inference beyond a single
contingent datum to any necessary properties, correlatives, continuators, or
successors. The result was a stringent atomist occasionalism resting ultimately
on an early version of logical atomism. Avicenna preserved an Aristotelian
naturalism alongside the Scriptural idea of the contingency of the world by
arguing that any finite being is contingent in itself but necessary in relation
to its causes. He adapted al-Farabi’s Neoplatonic emanationism to this
schematization and naturalized in philosophy his own distinctive version of the
kalam argument from contingency: any being must be either necessary or
contingent, but if contingent, it requires a cause; since no infinite causal
regress is possible, there must be a Necessary Being, which is therefore
simple, the ultimate cause of all other things. Avicenna found refuge at the
court of one ‘Ala al-Dawla, who bravely resisted the military pressures of
Mahmud against his lands around Isfahan and made the philosopher and savant his
vizier. Here Avicenna completed his famous philosophic work the Shifa’ known in
Latin as the Sufficientia and his Qanun fi Tibb, the Galenic Canon, which
remained in use as a medical textbook until finally brought down by the weight
of criticisms during the Renaissance. Avicenna’s philosophy was the central
target of the polemical critique of the Muslim theologian al-Ghazali 10581111
in his Incoherence of the Philosophers, mainly on the grounds that the
philosopher’s retention of the Aristotelian doctrine of the eternity of the
world was inconsistent with his claim that God was the author of the world.
Avicenna’s related affirmations of the necessity of causation and universality
of God’s knowledge, al-Ghazali argued, made miracles impossible and divine
governance too impersonal to deserve the name. Yet Avicenna’s philosophic works
numbering over a hundred in their Arabic and sometimes Persian originals
continued to exercise a major influence on Muslim and Jewish philosophers and
through Latin translations on philosophers in the West.
avidya, Sanskrit word
meaning ‘ignorance’, ‘lack of wisdom’. Avidya is a key concept in India’s
philosophical systems, which attempted to explain the reasons for karmic
bondage leading to suffering and release from such bondage through spiritual
liberation. The general idea was that karmic fetters arise because of avidya,
which is ignorance of the true nature of reality. When wisdom dispells avidya,
the individual is freed from bondage. There was intense speculation in Indian
philosophy regarding the nature and the metaphysical status of avidya. If avidya
causes bondage that traps the individual in the transmigratory cycle of life
and death samsara, then where does avidya reside and how does it come into
being? D.K.C. awareness, consciousness, a central feature of our lives that is
notoriously difficult to characterize. You experience goings-on in the world,
and, turning inward “introspecting”, you experience your experiencing. Objects
of awareness can be external or internal. Pressing your finger on the edge of a
table, you can be aware of the table’s edge, and aware of the feeling of
pressure though perhaps not simultaneously. Philosophers from Locke to Nagel
have insisted that our experiences have distinctive qualities: there is
“something it is like” to have them. It would seem important, then, to distinguish
qualities of objects of which you are aware from qualities of your awareness.
Suppose you are aware of a round, red tomato. The tomato, but not your
awareness, is round and red. What then are the qualities of your awareness?
Here we encounter a deep puzzle that divides theorists into intransigent camps.
Some materialists, like Dennett, insist that awareness lacks qualities or lacks
qualities distinct from its objects: the qualities we attribute to experiences
are really those of experienced objects. This opens the way to a dismissal of
“phenomenal” qualities qualia, qualities that seem to have no place in the
material world. Others T. Nagel, Ned Block regard such qualities as patently
genuine, preferring to dismiss any theory unable to accommodate them. Convinced
that the qualities of awareness are ineliminable and irreducible to respectable
material properties, some philosophers, following Frank Jackson, contend they
are “epiphenomenal”: real but causally inefficacious. Still others, including
Searle, point to what they regard as a fundamental distinction between the
“intrinsically subjecavidya awareness 64
64 tive” character of awareness and the “objective,” “public” character
of material objects, but deny that this yields epiphenomenalism.
axiomatic method,
originally, a method for reorganizing the accepted propositions and concepts of
an existent science in order to increase certainty in the propositions and
clarity in the concepts. Application of this method was thought to require the
identification of 1 the “universe of discourse” domain, genus of entities
constituting the primary subject matter of the science, 2 the “primitive
concepts” that can be grasped immediately without the use of definition, 3 the
“primitive propositions” or “axioms”, whose truth is knowable immediately,
without the use of deduction, 4 an immediately acceptable “primitive
definition” in terms of primitive concepts for each non-primitive concept, and
5 a deduction constructed by chaining immediate, logically cogent inferences
ultimately from primitive propositions and definitions for each nonprimitive
accepted proposition. Prominent proponents of more or less modernized versions
of the axiomatic method, e.g. Pascal, Nicod 18931924, and Tarski, emphasizing
the critical and regulatory function of the axiomatic method, explicitly open
the possibility that axiomatization of an existent, preaxiomatic science may
lead to rejection or modification of propositions, concepts, and argumentations
that had previously been accepted. In many cases attempts to realize the ideal
of an axiomatic science have resulted in discovery of “smuggled premises” and
other previously unnoted presuppositions, leading in turn to recognition of the
need for new axioms. Modern axiomatizations of geometry are much richer in
detail than those produced in ancient Greece. The earliest extant axiomatic
text is based on an axiomatization of geometry due to Euclid fl. 300 B.C.,
which itself was based on earlier, nolonger-extant texts. Archimedes 287212
B.C. was one of the earliest of a succession of postEuclidean geometers,
including Hilbert, Oswald Veblen 18801960, and Tarski, to propose modifications
of axiomatizations of classical geometry. The traditional axiomatic method,
often called the geometric method, made several presuppositions no longer
widely accepted. The advent of non-Euclidean geometry was particularly
important in this connection. For some workers, the goal of reorganizing an
existent science was joined to or replaced by a new goal: characterizing or
giving implicit definition to the structure of the subject matter of the
science. Moreover, subsequent innovations in logic and foundations of
mathematics, especially development of syntactically precise formalized
languages and effective systems of formal deductions, have substantially
increased the degree of rigor attainable. In particular, critical axiomatic
exposition of a body of scientific knowledge is now not thought to be fully
adequate, however successful it may be in realizing the goals of the original
axiomatic method, so long as it does not present the underlying logic including
language, semantics, and deduction system. For these and other reasons the
expression ‘axiomatic method’ has undergone many “redefinitions,” some of which
have only the most tenuous connection with the original meaning.
axiom of comprehension,
also called axiom of abstraction, the axiom that for every property, there is a
corresponding set of things having that property; i.e., f DA x x 1 A È f x,
where f is a property and A is a set. The axiom was used in Frege’s formulation
of set theory and is the axiom that yields Russell’s paradox, discovered in
1901. If fx is instantiated as x 2 x, then the result that A 1 A È A 2 A is
easily obtained, which yields, in classical logic, the explicit contradiction A
1 A & A 2 A. The paradox can be avoided by modifying the comprehension
axiom and using instead the separation axiom, f DA x x 1 A Èfx & x 1 B.
This yields only the result that A 1 A ÈA 2 A & A 1 B, which is not a
contradiction. The paradox can also be avoided by retaining the comprehension
axiom but restricting the symbolic language, so that ‘x 1 x’ is not a
meaningful formula. Russell’s type theory, presented in Principia Mathematica,
uses this approach. FREGE, RUSSELL, SET
THEORY, TYPE THEORY. V.K. axiology axiom of comprehension 65 65 axiom of consistency, an axiom stating
that a given set of sentences is consistent. Let L be a formal language, D a
deductive system for L, S any set of sentences of L, and C the statement ‘S is
consistent’ i.e., ‘No contradiction is derivable from S via D’. For certain
sets S e.g., the theorems of D it is interesting to ask: Can C be expressed in
L? If so, can C be proved in D? If C can be expressed in L but not proved in D,
can C be added consistently to D as a new axiom? Example from Gödel: Let L and
D be adequate for elementary number theory, and S be the axioms of D; then C
can be expressed in L but not proved in D, but can be added as a new axiom to
form a stronger system D’. Sometimes we can express in L an axiom of
consistency in the semantic sense i.e., ‘There is a universe in which all the
sentences in S are true’. Trivial example: suppose the only non-logical axiom
in D is ‘For any two sets B and B’, there exists the union of B and B’ ’. Then
C might be ‘There is a set U such that, for any sets B and B’ in U, there
exists in U the union of B and B’ ’.
ayer: a. j. , philosopher
of Swiss ancestry, one of the most important of the Oxford logical positivists.
He continued to occupy a dominant place in analytic philosophy as he gradually
modified his adherence to central tenets of the view. He was educated at Eton
and Oxford, and, after a brief period at the
of Vienna, became a lecturer in philosophy at Christ Church in 1933.
After the war he returned to Oxford as fellow and dean of Wadham . He was Grote
Professor of the Philosophy of Mind and Logic at the of London 194659, Wykeham Professor of Logic
in the of Oxford and a fellow of
New 195978, and a fellow of Wolfson ,
Oxford 197883. Ayer was knighted in 1973 and was a Chevalier de la Légion
d’Honneur. His early work clearly and forcefully developed the implications of
the positivists’ doctrines that all cognitive statements are either analytic
and a priori, or synthetic, contingent, and a posteriori, and that empirically
meaningful statements must be verifiable must admit of confirmation or
disconfirmation. In doing so he defended reductionist analyses of the self, the
external world, and other minds. Value statements that fail the empiricist’s
criterion of meaning but defy naturalistic analysis were denied truth-value and
assigned emotive meaning. Throughout his writings he maintained a
foundationalist perspective in epistemology in which sense-data later more
neutrally described occupied not only a privileged epistemic position but
constituted the subject matter of the most basic statements to be used in
reductive analyses. Although in later works he significantly modified many of
his early views and abandoned much of their strict reductionism, he remained
faithful to an empiricist’s version of foundationalism and the basic idea
behind the verifiability criterion of meaning. His books include Language,
Truth and Logic; The Foundations of Empirical Knowledge; The Problems of Knowledge;
Philosophical Essays; The Concept of a Person; The Origins of Pragmatism;
Metaphysics and Common Sense; Russell and Moore: The Analytical Heritage; The
Central Questions of Philosophy; Probability and Evidence; Philosophy in the
Twentieth Century; Russell; Hume; Freedom and Morality, Ludwig Wittgenstein;
and Voltaire.
Babbage, Charles
17921871, English applied mathematician, inventor, and expert on machinery and
manufacturing. His chief interest was in developing mechanical “engines” to
compute tables of functions. Until the invention of the electronic computer,
printed tables of functions were important aids to calculation. Babbage
invented the difference engine, a machine that consisted of a series of
accumulators each of which, in turn, transmitted its contents to its successor,
which added to them to its own contents. He built only a model, but George and
Edvard Scheutz built difference engines that were actually used. Though tables
of squares and cubes could be calculated by a difference engine, the more
commonly used tables of logarithms and of trigonometric functions could not. To
calculate these and other useful functions, Babbage conceived of the analytical
engine, a machine for numerical analysis. The analytical engine was to have a
store memory and a mill arithmetic unit. The store was to hold decimal numbers
on toothed wheels, and to transmit them to the mill and back by means of wheels
and toothed bars. The mill was to carry out the arithmetic operations of
addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division mechanically, greatly
extending the technology of small calculators. The operations of the mill were
to be governed by pegged drums, derived from the music box. A desired sequence
of operations would be punched on cards, which would be strung together like
the cards of a Jacquard loom and read by the machine. The control mechanisms
could branch and execute a different sequence of cards when a designated
quantity changed sign. Numbers would be entered from punched cards and the
answers punched on cards. The answers might also be imprinted on metal sheets
from which the calculated tables would be printed, thus avoiding the errors of
proofreading. Although Babbage formulated various partial plans for the
analytical engine and built a few pieces of it, the machine was never realized.
Given the limitations of mechanical computing technology, building an
analytical engine would probably not have been an economical way to produce
numerical tables. The modern electronic computer was invented and developed
completely independently of Babbage’s pioneering work. Yet because of it,
Babbage’s work has been publicized and he has become famous.
Bachelard, Gaston
18841962, French philosopher of science and literary analyst. His philosophy of
science developed, e.g., in The New Scientific Spirit, 1934, and Rational
Materialism, 1953 began from reflections on the relativistic and quantum
revolutions in twentieth-century physics. Bachelard viewed science as
developing through a series of discontinuous changes epistemological breaks.
Such breaks overcome epistemological obstacles: methodological and conceptual
features of commonsense or outdated science that block the path of inquiry.
Bachelard’s emphasis on the discontinuity of scientific change strikingly anticipated
Thomas Kuhn’s focus, many years later, on revolutionary paradigm change.
However, unlike Kuhn, Bachelard held to a strong notion of scientific progress
across revolutionary discontinuities. Although each scientific framework
rejects its predecessors as fundamentally erroneous, earlier frameworks may
embody permanent achievements that will be preserved as special cases within
subsequent frameworks. Newton’s laws of motion, e.g., are special limit-cases
of relativity theory. Bachelard based his philosophy of science on a
“non-Cartesian epistemology” that rejects Descartes’s claim that knowledge must
be founded on incorrigible intuitions of first truths. All knowledge claims are
subject to revision in the light of further evidence. Similarly, he rejected a
naive realism that defines reality in terms of givens of ordinary sense
experience and ignores the ontological constructions of scientific concepts and
instrumentation. He maintained, however, that denying this sort of realism did
not entail accepting idealism, which makes only the mental ultimately real.
Instead he argued for an “applied rationalism,” which recognizes the active
role of reason in constituting objects of knowledge while admitting that any
constituting act of reason must be directed toward an antecedently given
object. 67 B 67 Although Bachelard
denied the objective reality of the perceptual and imaginative worlds, he
emphasized their subjective and poetic significance. Complementing his writings
on science are a series of books on imagination and poetic imagery e.g., The
Psychoanalysis of Fire, 1938; The Poetics of Space, 1957 which subtly unpack
the meaning of archetypal in Jung’s sense images. He put forward a “law of the
four elements,” according to which all images can be related to the earth, air,
fire, and water posited by Empedocles as the fundamental forms of matter.
Together with Georges Canguilhem, his successor at the Sorbonne, Bachelard had
an immense impact on several generations of French students of philosophy. He
and Canguilhem offered an important alternative to the more fashionable and
widely known phenomenology and existentialism and were major influences on
among others Althusser and Foucault.
Bacon, Francis: English
philosopher, essayist, and scientific methodologist. In politics Bacon rose to
the position of lord chancellor. In 1621 he retired to private life after
conviction for taking bribes in his official capacity as judge. Bacon
championed the new empiricism resulting from the achievements of early modern
science. He opposed alleged knowledge based on appeals to authority, and on the
barrenness of Scholasticism. He thought that what is needed is a new attitude
and methodology based strictly on scientific practices. The goal of acquiring
knowledge is the good of mankind: knowledge is power. The social order that
should result from applied science is portrayed in his New Atlantis1627. The
method of induction to be employed is worked out in detail in his Novum Organum
1620. This new logic is to replace that of Aristotle’s syllogism, as well as
induction by simple enumeration of instances. Neither of these older logics can
produce knowledge of actual natural laws. Bacon thought that we must intervene
in nature, manipulating it by means of experimental control leading to the
invention of new technology. There are well-known hindrances to acquisition of
knowledge of causal laws. Such hindrances false opinions, prejudices, which
“anticipate” nature rather than explain it, Bacon calls idols idola. Idols of
the tribe idola tribus are natural mental tendencies, among which are the idle
search for purposes in nature, and the impulse to read our own desires and
needs into nature. Idols of the cave idola specus are predispositions of
particular individuals. The individual is inclined to form opinions based on
idiosyncrasies of education, social intercourse, reading, and favored
authorities. Idols of the marketplace idola fori Bacon regards as the most
potentially dangerous of all dispositions, because they arise from common uses
of language that often result in verbal disputes. Many words, though thought to
be meaningful, stand for nonexistent things; others, although they name actual
things, are poorly defined or used in confused ways. Idols of the theater idola
theatri depend upon the influence of received theories. The only authority
possessed by such theories is that they are ingenious verbal constructions. The
aim of acquiring genuine knowledge does not depend on superior skill in the use
of words, but rather on the discovery of natural laws. Once the idols are
eliminated, the mind is free to seek knowledge of natural laws based on
experimentation. Bacon held that nothing exists in nature except bodies
material objects acting in conformity with fixed laws. These laws are “forms.”
For example, Bacon thought that the form or cause of heat is the motion of the
tiny particles making up a body. This form is that on which the existence of
heat depends. What induction seeks to show is that certain laws are perfectly
general, universal in application. In every case of heat, there is a measurable
change in the motion of the particles constituting the moving body. Bacon
thought that scientific induction proceeds as follows. First, we look for those
cases where, given certain changes, certain others invariably follow. In his
example, if certain changes in the form motion of particles take place, heat
always follows. We seek to find all of the “positive instances” of the form
that give rise to the effect of that form. Next, we investigate the “negative
instances,” cases where in the absence of the form, the qualitative change does
not take place. In the operation of these methods it is important to try to
produce experimentally “prerogative instances,” particularly striking or
typical examples of the phenomenon under investigation. Finally, in cases where
the object under study is present to some greater or lesser degree, we must be
able to take into account why these changes occur. In the example, quantitative
changes in degrees of heat will be correlated to quantitative changes in the
speed of the motion of the particles. This method implies that backward
causation Bacon, Francis 68 68 in many
cases we can invent instruments to measure changes in degree. Such inventions
are of course the hoped-for outcome of scientific inquiry, because their
possession improves the lot of human beings. Bacon’s strikingly modern but not
entirely novel empiricist methodology influenced nineteenth-century figures
e.g., Sir John Herschel and J. S. Mill who generalized his results and used
them as the basis for displaying new insights into scientific methodology.
Bacon, Roger
c.1214c.1293, English philosopher who earned the honorific title of Doctor
Mirabilis. He was one of the first medievals in the Latin West to lecture and
comment on newly recovered work by Aristotle in natural philosophy, physics,
and metaphysics. Born in Somerset and educated at both Oxford and the
of Paris, he became by 1273 a master of arts at Paris, where he taught
for about ten years. In 1247 he resigned his teaching post to devote his
energies to investigating and promoting topics he considered neglected but
important insofar as they would lead to knowledge of God. The English
“experimentalist” Grosseteste, the Frenchman Peter of Maricourt, who did
pioneering work on magnetism, and the author of the pseudo-Aristotelian
Secretum secretorum influenced Roger’s new perspective. By 1257, however,
partly from fatigue, Roger had put this work aside and entered the Franciscan
order in England. To his dismay, he did not receive within the order the
respect and freedom to write and teach he had expected. During the early 1260s
Roger’s views about reforming the
curriculum reached Cardinal Guy le Gos de Foulques, who, upon becoming
Pope Clement IV in 1265, demanded to see Roger’s writings. In response, Roger
produced the Opus maius 1267 an
encyclopedic work that argues, among other things, that 1 the study of Hebrew
and Grecian is indispensable for understanding the Bible, 2 the study of
mathematics encompassing geometry, astronomy, and astrology is, with
experimentation, the key to all the sciences and instrumental in theology, and
3 philosophy can serve theology by helping in the conversion of non-believers.
Roger believed that although the Bible is the basis for human knowledge, we can
use reason in the service of knowledge. It is not that rational argument can,
on his view, provide fullblown proof of anything, but rather that with the aid
of reason one can formulate hypotheses about nature that can be confirmed by
experience. According to Roger, knowledge arrived at in this way will lead to
knowledge of nature’s creator. All philosophical, scientific, and linguistic
endeavors are valuable ultimately for the service they can render to theology.
Roger summarizes and develops his views on these matters in the Opus minus and
the Opus tertium, produced within a year of the Opus maius. Roger was
altogether serious in advocating curricular change. He took every opportunity
to rail against many of his celebrated contemporaries e.g., Alexander of Hales,
Bonaventure, Albertus Magnus, and Aquinas for not being properly trained in
philosophy and for contributing to the demise of theology by lecturing on Peter
Lombard’s Sentences instead of the Bible. He also wrote both Grecian and Hebrew
grammars, did important work in optics, and argued for calendar reform on the
basis of his admittedly derivative astronomical research. One should not,
however, think that Roger was a good mathematician or natural scientist. He apparently
never produced a single theorem or proof in mathematics, he was not always a
good judge of astronomical competence he preferred al-Bitruji to Ptolemy, and
he held alchemy in high regard, believing that base metals could be turned into
silver and gold. Some have gone so far as to claim that Roger’s renown in the
history of science is vastly overrated, based in part on his being confusedly
linked with the fourteenthcentury Oxford Calculators, who do deserve credit for
paving the way for certain developments in seventeenth-century science. Roger’s
devotion to curricular reform eventually led to his imprisonment by Jerome of
Ascoli the future Pope Nicholas IV, probably between 1277 and 1279. Roger’s
teachings were said to have contained “suspect novelties.” Judging from the
date of his imprisonment, these novelties may have been any number of
propositions condemned by the bishop of Paris, Étienne Tempier, in 1277. But
his imprisonment may also have had something to do with the anger he
undoubtedly provoked by constantly abusing the members of his order regarding
their approach to education, or with his controversial Joachimite views about
the apocalypse and the imminent coming of the Antichrist. Given Roger’s
interest in educational reform and his knack for systematization, it is not
unlikely that he was abreast of and had something to say about most of the
central philosophical issues of the day. If so, his writings could be Bacon,
Roger Bacon, Roger 69 69 an important
source of information about thirteenth-century Scholastic philosophy generally.
In this connection, recent investigations have revealed, e.g., that he may well
have played an important role in the development of logic and philosophy of
language during the thirteenth and early fourteenth centuries. In the course of
challenging the views of certain people some of whom have been tentatively
identified as Richard of Cornwall, Lambert of Auxerre, Siger of Brabant, Henry
of Ghent, Boethius of Dacia, William Sherwood, and the Magister Abstractionum
on the nature of signs and how words function as signs, Roger develops and
defends views that appear to be original. The pertinent texts include the
Sumule dialectices c.1250, the De signis part of Part III of the Opus maius,
and the Compendium studii theologiae 1292. E.g., in connection with the
question whether Jesus could be called a man during the three-day entombment
and, thus, in connection with the related question whether man can be said to
be animal when no man exists, and with the sophism ‘This is a dead man,
therefore this is a man’, Roger was not content to distinguish words from all
other signs as had been the tradition. He distinguished between signs
originating from nature and from the soul, and between natural signification
and conventional ad placitum signification which results expressly or tacitly
from the imposition of meaning by one or more individuals. He maintained that
words signify existing and non-existing entities only equivocally, because
words conventionally signify only presently existing things. On this view,
therefore, ‘man’ is not used univocally when applied to an existing man and to
a dead man.
bad faith, 1 dishonest
and blameworthy instances of self-deception; 2 inauthentic and self-deceptive
refusal to admit to ourselves and others our full freedom, thereby avoiding
anxiety in making decisions and evading responsibility for actions and
attitudes Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 1943; 3 hypocrisy or dishonesty in
speech and conduct, as in making a promise without intending to keep it. One
self-deceiving strategy identified by Sartre is to embrace other people’s views
in order to avoid having to form one’s own; another is to disregard options so
that one’s life appears predetermined to move in a fixed direction. Occasionally
Sartre used a narrower, fourth sense: self-deceptive beliefs held on the basis
of insincere and unreasonable interpretations of evidence, as contrasted with
the dishonesty of “sincerely” acknowledging one truth “I am disposed to be a
thief” in order to deny a deeper truth “I am free to change”.
Bain, Alexander 18181903,
British philosopher and reformer, biographer of James Mill 1882 and J. S. Mill
1882 and founder of the first psychological journal, Mind 1876. In the
development of psychology, Bain represents in England alongside Continental
thinkers such as Taine and Lotze the final step toward the founding of
psychology as a science. His significance stems from his wish to “unite
psychology and physiology,” fulfilled in The Senses and the Intellect 1855 and
The Emotions and the Will 1859, abridged in one volume, Mental and Moral
Science 1868. Neither Bain’s psychology nor his physiology were particularly
original. His psychology came from English empiricism and associationism, his
physiology from Johannes Muller’s 180158 Elements of Physiology 1842. Muller
was an early advocate of the reflex, or sensorimotor, conception of the nervous
system, holding that neurons conduct sensory information to the brain or motor
commands from the brain, the brain connecting sensation with appropriate motor
response. Like Hartley before him, Bain grounded the laws of mental association
in the laws of neural connection. In opposition to faculty psychology, Bain
rejected the existence of mental powers located in different parts of the brain
On the Study of Character, 1861. By combining associationism with modern
physiology, he virtually completed the movement of philosophical psychology
toward science. In philosophy, his most important concept was his analysis of
belief as “a preparation to act.” By thus entwining conception and action, he
laid the foundation for pragmatism, and for the focus on adaptive behavior
central to modern psychology.
Bakhtin, Mikhail
Mikhailovich 18951975, Russian philosopher and cultural theorist whose
influence is pervasive in a wide range of academic disciplines from literary hermeneutics to the
epistemology of the human sciences, cultural theory, and feminism. He may
legitimately be called a philosophical anthropologist in the venerable
Continental tradition. Because of his seminal work on Rabelais and Dostoevsky’s
poetics, Baden School Bakhtin, Mikhail Mikhailovich 70 70 his influence has been greatest in
literary hermeneutics. Without question dialogism, or the construal of
dialogue, is the hallmark of Bakhtin’s thought. Dialogue marks the existential
condition of humanity in which the self and the other are asymmetrical but
double-binding. In his words, to exist means to communicate dialogically, and
when the dialogue ends, everything else ends. Unlike Hegelian and Marxian
dialectics but like the Chinese correlative logic of yin and yang, Bakhtin’s
dialogism is infinitely polyphonic, open-ended, and indeterminate, i.e.,
“unfinalizable” to use his term. Dialogue
means that there are neither first nor last words. The past and the future are
interlocked and revolve around the axis of the present. Bakhtin’s dialogism is
paradigmatic in a threefold sense. First, dialogue is never abstract but
embodied. The lived body is the material condition of social existence as
ongoing dialogue. Not only does the word become enfleshed, but dialogue is also
the incorporation of the self and the other. Appropriately, therefore,
Bakhtin’s body politics may be called a Slavic version of Tantrism. Second, the
Rabelaisian carnivalesque that Bakhtin’s dialogism incorporates points to the
“jesterly” politics of resistance and protest against the “priestly”
establishment of officialdom. Third, the most distinguishing characteristic of
Bakhtin’s dialogism is the primacy of the other over the self, with a twofold
consequence: one concerns ethics and the other epistemology. In modern
philosophy, the discovery of “Thou” or the primacy of the other over the self
in asymmetrical reciprocity is credited to Feuerbach. It is hailed as the
“Copernican revolution” of mind, ethics, and social thought. Ethically,
Bakhtin’s dialogism, based on heteronomy, signals the birth of a new philosophy
of responsibility that challenges and transgresses the Anglo-American tradition
of “rights talk.” Epistemologically, it lends our welcoming ears to the
credence that the other may be right the
attitude that Gadamer calls the soul of dialogical hermeneutics.
Bakunin, Mikhail 181476,
Russian revolutionary anarchist. He lived in Western Europe in 184049 and again
in 186176 after an intervening period in Western and Russian prisons and
Siberian exile. Bakunin is best known for his vigorous if incoherent
anarchist-socialist views. On the one hand, he claimed that the masses’
“instinct for freedom” would spark the social revolution; on the other, he
claimed that the revolution would be the work of a conspiratorial elite of
disciplined professionals. Still, Bakunin made two significant if limited
philosophic contributions. 1 In the early 1840s he spoke of the “incessant
self-immolation of the positive in the pure flame of the negative,” and came to
see that “flame” as a necessary dialectical component of revolutionary action.
His sharpest criticism was directed not at conservative attempts to defend the
existing order but rather at Hegelian attempts to reconcile positive and
negative and “liberal” efforts to find a “modest and harmless place” for the
negative within the positive. For Bakunin the negative is absolutely justified
in its “constructive” elimination of the positive. Writing in German in 1842 he
exploited both senses of the word Lust, namely “joy” and “urge,” declaring that
the Lust to destroy is at the same time a creative Lust. 2 From 1861 until the
end of his life Bakunin was committed to scientism, materialism, and atheism.
But in the late 1860s he formulated a forceful critique of the political and
social role of scientific elites and institutions. Individual life is concrete
and particular; science is abstract and general and incapable of understanding
or valuing living individuals. Instead, it tends to ignore or to exploit them.
Bakunin, who had preached an anarchist revolt against church and state, now
preached a “revolt of life against science, or rather against government by
science.” This was related to his anarchist critique of Marx’s statism and
technicism; but it raised the more general question one of continuing relevance and urgency of the role of scientific experts in
decisions about public policy.
Bañez, Domingo 15281604,
Spanish Dominican theologian and philosopher. Born in Valladolid, he studied at
Salamanca, where he also taught for many years. As spiritual director of St.
Teresa of Ávila, he exerted considerable influence on her views. He is known
for his disputes with Molina concerning divine grace. Against Molina he held
physical predetermination, the view that God physically determines the
secondary causes of human action. This renders grace intrinsically efficacious
and independent of human will and merits. He is also known for his Bakunin,
Mikhail Bañez, Domingo 71 71
understanding of the centrality of the act of existence esse in Thomistic
metaphysics. Bañez’s most important works are his commentaries on Aquinas’s
Summa theologiae and Aristotle’s On Generation and Corruption.
bargaining theory, the
branch of game theory that treats agreements, e.g., wage agreements between
labor and management. In the simplest bargaining problems there are two
bargainers. They can jointly realize various outcomes, including the outcome that
occurs if they fail to reach an agreement. Each bargainer assigns a certain
amount of utility to each outcome. The question is, what outcome will they
realize if they are rational? Methods of solving bargaining problems are
controversial. The best-known proposals are Nash’s and Kalai and Smorodinsky’s.
Nash proposes maximizing the product of utility gains with respect to the
disagreement point. Kalai and Smorodinsky propose maximizing utility gains with
respect to the disagreement point, subject to the constraint that the ratio of
utility gains equals the ratio of greatest possible gains. These methods of
selecting an outcome have been axiomatically characterized. For each method,
there are certain axioms of outcome selection such that that method alone satisfies
the axioms. The axioms incorporate principles of rationality from cooperative
game theory. They focus on features of outcomes rather than bargaining
strategies. For example, one axiom requires that the outcome selected be
Pareto-optimal, i.e., be an outcome such that no alternative is better for one
of the bargainers and not worse for the other. Bargaining problems may become
more complicated in several ways. First, there may be more than two bargainers.
If unanimity is not required for beneficial agreements, splinter groups or
coalitions may form. Second, the protocol for offers, counteroffers, etc., may
be relevant. Then principles of non-cooperative game theory concerning
strategies are needed to justify solutions. Third, the context of a bargaining
problem may be relevant. For instance, opportunities for side payments,
differences in bargaining power, and interpersonal comparisons of utility may
influence the solution. Fourth, simplifying assumptions, such as the assumption
that bargainers have complete information about their bargaining situation, may
be discarded. Bargaining theory is part of the philosophical study of
rationality. It is also important in ethics as a foundation for contractarian
theories of morality and for certain theories of distributive justice.
Barthes, Roland: post-structuralist
literary critic and essayist. Born in Cherbourg, he suffered from numerous
ailments as a child and spent much of his early life as a semiinvalid. After
leaving the military, he took up several positions teaching subjects like
classics, grammar, and philology. His interest in linguistics finally drew him
to literature, and by the mid-1960s he had already published what would become
a classic in structural analysis, The Elements of Semiology. Its principal
message is that words are merely one kind of sign whose meaning lies in
relations of difference between them. This concept was later amended to include
the reading subject, and the structuring effect that the subject has on the
literary work a concept expressed later
in his S/Z and The Pleasure of the Text. Barthes’s most mature contributions to
the post-structuralist movement were brilliant and witty interpretations of
visual, tactile, and aural sign systems, culminating in the publication of several
books and essays on photography, advertising, film, and cuisine.
Grundnorm: also called basic
norm, in a legal system, the norm that determines the legal validity of all
other norms. The content of such an ultimate norm may provide, e.g., that norms
created by a legislature or by a court are legally valid. The validity of such
an ultimate norm cannot be established as a matter of social fact such as the
social fact that the norm is accepted by some group within a society. Rather,
the validity of the basic norm for any given legal system must be presupposed
by the validity of the norms that it legitimates as laws. The idea of a basic
norm is associated with the legal philosopher Hans Kelsen.
Basilides A.D. c.12040,
Syrian Christian gnostic teacher in Alexandria who rivaled Valentinus. He
improved on Valentinus’s doctrine of emanations, positing 365 the number of
days in a year levels of existence in the Pleroma the fullness of the Godhead,
all descending from the ineffable Father. He taught that the rival God was the
God of the Jews the God of the Old Testament, who created the material world.
Redemption consists in the coming of the first begotten of the Father, Noûs
Mind, in human form in order to release the spiritual element imprisoned within
human bodies. Like other gnostics he taught that we are saved by knowledge, not
faith. He apparently held to the idea of reincarnation before the restoration
of all things to the Pleroma.
basing relation, also
called basis relation, the relation between a belief or item of knowledge and a
second belief or item of knowledge when the latter is the ground basis of the
first. It is clear that some knowledge is indirect, i.e., had or gained on the
basis of some evidence, as opposed to direct knowledge, which assuming there is
any is not so gained, or based. The same holds for justified belief. In one
broad sense of the term, the basing relation is just the one connecting
indirect knowledge or indirectly justified belief to the evidence: to give an
account of either of the latter is to give an account of the basing relation.
There is a narrower view of the basing relation, perhaps implicit in the first.
A person knows some proposition P on the basis of evidence or reasons only if
her belief that P is based on the evidence or reasons, or perhaps on the
possession of the evidence or reasons. The narrow basing relation is indicated
by this question: where a belief that P constitutes indirect knowledge or
justification, what is it for that belief to be based on the evidence or
reasons that support the knowledge or justification? The most widely favored
view is that the relevant belief is based on evidence or reasons only if the
belief is causally related to the belief or reasons. Proponents of this causal
view differ concerning what, beyond this causal relationship, is needed by an
account of the narrow basing relation.
Bataille, Georges
18971962, French philosopher and novelist with enormous influence on
post-structuralist thought. By locating value in expenditure as opposed to
accumulation, Bataille inaugurates the era of the death of the subject. He
insists that individuals must transgress the limits imposed by subjectivity to
escape isolation and communicate. Bataille’s prewar philosophical contributions
consist mainly of short essays, the most significant of which have been
collected in Visions of Excess. These essays introduce the central idea that
base matter disrupts rational subjectivity by attesting to the continuity in
which individuals lose themselves. Inner Experience 1943, Bataille’s first
lengthy philosophical treatise, was followed by Guilty 1944 and On Nietzsche
1945. Together, these three works constitute Bataille’s Summa Atheologica,
which explores the play of the isolation and the dissolution of beings in terms
of the experience of excess laughter, tears, eroticism, death, sacrifice,
poetry. The Accursed Share 1949, which he considered his most important work,
is his most systematic account of the social and economic implications of
expenditure. In Erotism 1957 and The Tears of Eros 1961, he focuses on the
excesses of sex and death. Throughout his life, Bataille was concerned with the
question of value. He located it in the excess that lacerates individuals and
opens channels of communication.
Baumgarten, Alexander
Gottlieb 171462, German philosopher. Born in Berlin, he was educated in Halle
and taught at Halle 173840 and Frankfurt an der Oder 174062. Baumgarten was
brought up in the Pietist circle of A. H. Francke but adopted the anti-Pietist
rationalism of Wolff. He wrote textbooks in metabasic particular Baumgarten,
Alexander Gottlieb 73 73 physics
Metaphysica, 1739 and ethics Ethica Philosophica, 1740; Initia Philosophiae
Practicae Prima [“First Elements of Practical Philosophy”], 1760 on which Kant
lectured. For the most part, Baumgarten did not significantly depart from
Wolff, although in metaphysics he was both further and yet closer to Leibniz
than was Wolff: unlike Leibniz, he argued for real physical influx, but, unlike
Wolff, he did not restrict preestablished harmony to the mindbody relationship
alone, but paradoxically reextended it to include all relations of substances.
Baumgarten’s claim to fame, however, rests on his introduction of the
discipline of aesthetics into German philosophy, and indeed on his introduction
of the term ‘aesthetics’ as well. Wolff had explained pleasure as the response
to the perception of perfection by means of the senses, in turn understood as
clear but confused perception. Baumgarten subtly but significantly departed from
Wolff by redefining our response to beauty as pleasure in the perfection of
sensory perception, i.e., in the unique potential of sensory as opposed to
merely conceptual representation. This concept was first introduced in his
dissertation Meditationes Philosophicae de Nonnullis ad Poema Pertinentibus
“Philosophical Meditations on some Matters pertaining to Poetry,” 1735, which
defined a poem as a “perfect sensate discourse,” and then generalized in his
twovolume but still incomplete Aesthetica 1750 58. One might describe
Baumgarten’s aesthetics as cognitivist but no longer rationalist: while in
science or logic we must always prefer discursive clarity, in art we respond
with pleasure to the maximally dense or “confused” intimation of ideas.
Baumgarten’s theory had great influence on Lessing and Mendelssohn, on Kant’s
theory of aesthetic ideas, and even on the aesthetics of Hegel.
Crazy-bayesy – cited by
H. P. Grice, “Aspects of reason.” Bayesian rationality, minimally, a property a
system of beliefs or the believer has in virtue of the system’s “conforming to
the probability calculus.” “Bayesians” differ on what “rationality” requires,
but most agree that i beliefs come in degrees of firmness; ii these “degrees of
belief” are theoretically or ideally quantifiable; iii such quantification can
be understood in terms of person-relative, time-indexed “credence functions”
from appropriate sets of objects of belief propositions or sentences each set closed under at least finite
truth-functional combinations into the
set of real numbers; iv at any given time t, a person’s credence function at t
ought to be usually: “on pain of a Dutch book argument” a probability function;
that is, a mapping from the given set into the real numbers in such a way that
the “probability” the value assigned to any given object A in the set is
greater than or equal to zero, and is equal to unity % 1 if A is a necessary
truth, and, for any given objects A and B in the set, if A and B are
incompatible the negation of their conjunction is a necessary truth then the
probability assigned to their disjunction is equal to the sum of the
probabilities assigned to each; so that the usual propositional probability
axioms impose a sort of logic on degrees of belief. If a credence function is a
probability function, then it or the believer at the given time is “coherent.”
On these matters, on conditional degrees of belief, and on the further
constraint on rationality many Bayesians impose that change of belief ought to
accord with “conditionalization”, the reader should consult John Earman, Bayes
or Bust? A Critical Examination of Bayesian Confirmation Theory 1992; Colin
Howson and Peter Urbach, Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach 1989; and
Richard Jeffrey, The Logic of Decision 1965.
Bayes’s theorem, any of
several relationships between prior and posterior probabilities or odds,
especially 13 below. All of these depend upon the basic relationship 0 between
contemporaneous conditional and unconditional probabilities. Non-Bayesians
think these useful only in narrow ranges of cases, generally because of
skepticism about accessibility or significance of priors. According to 1,
posterior probability is prior probability times the “relevance quotient”
Carnap’s term. According to 2, posterior odds are Bayesian Bayes’s theorem
74 74 prior odds times the “likelihood
ratio” R. A. Fisher’s term. Relationship 3 comes from 1 by expanding P data via
the law of total probability. Bayes’s rule 4 for updating probabilities has you
set your new unconditional probabilities equal to your old conditional ones
when fresh certainty about data leaves probabilities conditionally upon the
data unchanged. The corresponding rule 5 has you do the same for odds. In
decision theory the term is used differently, for the rule “Choose so as to
maximize expectation of utility.”
Bayle, Pierre 16471706,
French philosopher who also pioneered in disinterested, critical history. A
Calvinist forced into exile in 1681, Bayle nevertheless rejected the prevailing
use of history as an instrument of partisan or sectarian interest. He achieved
fame and notoriety with his multivolume Dictionnaire historique et critique
1695. For each subject covered, Bayle provided a biographical sketch and a
dispassionate examination of the historical record and interpretive
controversies. He also repeatedly probed the troubled and troubling boundary
between reason and faith philosophy and religion. In the article “David,” the
seemingly illicit conduct of God’s purported agent yielded reflections on the
morals of the elect and the autonomy of ethics. In “Pyrrho,” Bayle argued that
self-evidence, the most plausible candidate for the criterion of truth, is
discredited by Christianity because some self-evident principles contradict
essential Christian truths and are therefore false. Finally, provoking
Leibniz’s Theodicy, Bayle argued, most relentlessly in “Manichaeans” and
“Paulicians,” that there is no defensible rational solution to the problem of
evil. Bayle portrayed himself as a Christian skeptic, but others have seen
instead an ironic critic of religion a
precursor of the French Enlightenment. Bayle’s purely philosophical reflections
support his self-assessment, since he consistently maintains that philosophy
achieves not comprehension and contentment, but paradox and puzzlement. In
making this case he proved to be a superb critic of philosophical systems. Some
examples are “Zeno of Elea” on space,
time, and motion; “Rorarius” on mind and
body and animal mechanism; and “Spinoza”
on the perils of monism. Bayle’s skepticism concerning philosophy
significantly influenced Berkeley and Hume. His other important works include
Pensées diverses de la comète de 1683 1683; Commentaire philosophique sur ces
paroles de Jesus Christ: contrain les d’entrer 1686; and Réponse aux questions
d’un provincial1704; and an early learned periodical, the Nouvelles de la
République des Lettres 1684 87.
Beattie, James 17351803,
Scottish philosopher and poet who, in criticizing Hume, widened the latter’s
audience. A member of the Scottish school of common sense philosophy along with
Oswald and Reid, Beattie’s major work was An Essay on the Nature and
Immutability of Truth 1771, in which he criticizes Hume for fostering
skepticism and infidelity. His positive view was that the mind possesses a
common sense, i.e., a power for perceiving self-evident truths. Common sense is
instinctive, unalterable by education; truth is what common sense determines
the mind to believe. Beattie cited Hume and then claimed that his views led to
moral and religious evils. When Beattie’s Essay was translated into German
1772, Kant could read Hume’s discussions of personal identity and causation.
Since these topics were not covered in Hume’s Inquiry Concerning Human
Understanding, Beattie provided Kant access to two issues in the Treatises of
Human Nature critical to the development of transcendental idealism.
beauty, an aesthetic
property commonly thought of as a species of aesthetic value. As such, it has
been variously thought to be 1 a simple, indefinable property that cannot be
defined in terms of any other properties; 2 a property or set of properties of
an object that makes the object capable of producing a certain sort of
pleasurable experience in any suitable perceiver; or 3 whatever produces a
particular sort of pleasurable experience, even though what produces the
experience may vary from individual to individual. It is in this last sense
that beauty is thought to be “in the eye of the beholder.” If beauty is a
simple, indefinable property, as in 1, then it cannot be defined conceptually
and has to be apprehended by intuition or taste. Beauty, on this account, would
be a particular sort of aesthetic property. If beauty is an object’s Bayle,
Pierre beauty 75 75 capacity to produce
a special sort of pleasurable experience, as in 2, then it is necessary to say
what properties provide it with this capacity. The most favored candidates for
these have been formal or structural properties, such as order, symmetry, and
proportion. In the Philebus Plato argues that the form or essence of beauty is
knowable, exact, rational, and measurable. He also holds that simple
geometrical shapes, simple colors, and musical notes all have “intrinsic
beauty,” which arouses a pure, “unmixed” pleasure in the perceiver and is
unaffected by context. In the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries many
treatises were written on individual art forms, each allegedly governed by its
own rules. In the eighteenth century, Hutcheson held that ‘beauty’ refers to an
“idea raised in us,” and that any object that excites this idea is beautiful.
He thought that the property of the object that excites this idea is
“uniformity in variety.” Kant explained the nature of beauty by analyzing
judgments that something is beautiful. Such judgments refer to an experience of
the perceiver. But they are not merely expressions of personal experience; we
claim that others should also have the same experience, and that they should
make the same judgment i.e., judgments that something is beautiful have “universal
validity”. Such judgments are disinterested
determined not by any needs or wants on the part of the perceiver, but
just by contemplating the mere appearance of the object. These are judgments
about an object’s free beauty, and making them requires using only those mental
capacities that all humans have by virtue of their ability to communicate with
one another. Hence the pleasures experienced in response to such beauty can in
principle be shared by anyone. Some have held, as in 3, that we apply the term
‘beautiful’ to things because of the pleasure they give us, and not on the
basis of any specific qualities an object has. Archibald Alison held that it is
impossible to find any properties common to all those things we call beautiful.
Santayana believed beauty is “pleasure regarded as a quality of a thing,” and
made no pretense that certain qualities ought to produce that pleasure. The Grecian
term to kalon, which is often translated as ‘beauty’, did not refer to a
thing’s autonomous aesthetic value, but rather to its “excellence,” which is
connected with its moral worth and/or usefulness. This concept is closer to
Kant’s notion of dependent beauty, possessed by an object judged as a
particular kind of thing such as a beautiful cat or a beautiful horse, than it
is to free beauty, possessed by an object judged simply on the basis of its
appearance and not in terms of any concept of use.
Beccaria, Cesare: criminologist
and judicial and penal reformer. He studied in Parma and Pavia and taught
political economy in Milan. Here, he met Pietro and Alessandro Verri and other
Milanese intellectuals attempting to promote political, economical, and
judiciary reforms. His major work, Dei delitti e delle pene “On Crimes and
Punishments,” 1764, denounces the contemporary methods in the administration of
justice and the treatment of criminals. Beccaria argues that the highest good
is the greatest happiness shared by the greatest number of people; hence,
actions against the state are the most serious crimes. Crimes against
individuals and property are less serious, and crimes endangering public
harmony are the least serious. The purposes of punishment are deterrence and
the protection of society. However, the employment of torture to obtain
confessions is unjust and useless: it results in acquittal of the strong and
the ruthless and conviction of the weak and the innocent. Beccaria also rejects
the death penalty as a war of the state against the individual. He claims that
the duration and certainty of the punishment, not its intensity, most strongly
affect criminals. Beccaria was influenced by Montesquieu, Rousseau, and
Condillac. His major work was translated into many languages and set guidelines
for revising the criminal and judicial systems of several European countries.
behaviorism, broadly, the
view that behavior is fundamental in understanding mental phenomena. The term
applies both to a scientific research Beauvoir, Simone de behaviorism 76 76 program in psychology and to a philosophical
doctrine. Accordingly, we distinguish between scientific psychological,
methodological behaviorism and philosophical logical, analytical behaviorism.
Scientific behaviorism. First propounded by the American psychologist J. B.
Watson who introduced the term in 1913 and further developed especially by C.
L. Hull, E. C. Tolman, and B. F. Skinner, it departed from the introspectionist
tradition by redefining the proper task of psychology as the explanation and
prediction of behavior where to explain
behavior is to provide a “functional analysis” of it, i.e., to specify the
independent variables stimuli of which the behavior response is lawfully a
function. It insisted that all variables
including behavior as the dependent variable must be specifiable by the experimental
procedures of the natural sciences: merely introspectible, internal states of
consciousness are thus excluded from the proper domain of psychology. Although
some behaviorists were prepared to admit internal neurophysiological conditions
among the variables “intervening variables”, others of more radical bent e.g.
Skinner insisted on environmental variables alone, arguing that any relevant
variations in the hypothetical inner states would themselves in general be a
function of variations in past and present environmental conditions as, e.g.,
thirst is a function of water deprivation. Although some basic responses are
inherited reflexes, most are learned and integrated into complex patterns by a
process of conditioning. In classical respondent conditioning, a response already
under the control of a given stimulus will be elicited by new stimuli if these
are repeatedly paired with the old stimulus: this is how we learn to respond to
new situations. In operant conditioning, a response that has repeatedly been
followed by a reinforcing stimulus reward will occur with greater frequency and
will thus be “selected” over other possible responses: this is how we learn new
responses. Conditioned responses can also be unlearned or “extinguished” by
prolonged dissociation from the old eliciting stimuli or by repeated
withholding of the reinforcing stimuli. To show how all human behavior,
including “cognitive” or intelligent behavior, can be “shaped” by such
processes of selective reinforcement and extinction of responses was the ultimate
objective of scientific behaviorism. Grave difficulties in the way of the
realization of this objective led to increasingly radical liberalization of the
distinctive features of behaviorist methodology and eventually to its
displacement by more cognitively oriented approaches e.g. those inspired by
information theory and by Chomsky’s work in linguistics. Philosophical
behaviorism. A semantic thesis about the meaning of mentalistic expressions, it
received its most sanguine formulation by the logical positivists particularly
Carnap, Hempel, and Ayer, who asserted that statements containing mentalistic
expressions have the same meaning as, and are thus translatable into, some set
of publicly verifiable confirmable, testable statements describing behavioral and
bodily processes and dispositions including verbalbehavioral dispositions.
Because of the reductivist concerns expressed by the logical positivist thesis
of physicalism and the unity of science, logical behaviorism as some
positivists preferred to call it was a corollary of the thesis that psychology
is ultimately via a behavioristic analysis reducible to physics, and that all
of its statements, like those of physics, are expressible in a strictly
extensional language. Another influential formulation of philosophical
behaviorism is due to Ryle The Concept of Mind, 1949, whose classic critique of
Cartesian dualism rests on the view that mental predicates are often used to
ascribe dispositions to behave in characteristic ways: but such ascriptions,
for Ryle, have the form of conditional, lawlike statements whose function is
not to report the occurrence of inner states, physical or non-physical, of
which behavior is the causal manifestation, but to license inferences about how
the agent would behave if certain conditions obtained. To suppose that all
declarative uses of mental language have a fact-stating or -reporting role at
all is, for Ryle, to make a series of “category mistakes” of which both Descartes and the logical
positivists were equally guilty. Unlike the behaviorism of the positivists,
Ryle’s behaviorism required no physicalistic reduction of mental language, and
relied instead on ordinary language descriptions of human behavior. A further
version of philosophical behaviorism can be traced to Wittgenstein
Philosophical Investigations, 1953, who argues that the epistemic criteria for
the applicability of mentalistic terms cannot be private, introspectively
accessible inner states but must instead be intersubjectively observable
behavior. Unlike the previously mentioned versions of philosophical
behaviorism, Wittgenstein’s behaviorism seems to be consistent with
metaphysical mindbody dualism, and is thus also non-reductivist. behaviorism
behaviorism 77 77 Philosophical
behaviorism underwent severe criticism in the 1950s and 1960s, especially by
Chisholm, Charles Taylor, Putnam, and Fodor. Nonetheless it still lives on in
more or less attenuated forms in the work of such diverse philosophers as
Quine, Dennett, Armstrong, David Lewis, U. T. Place, and Dummett. Though
current “functionalism” is often referred to as the natural heir to
behaviorism, functionalism especially of the Armstrong-Lewis variety crucially
differs from behaviorism in insisting that mental predicates, while definable
in terms of behavior and behavioral dispositions, nonetheless designate inner
causal states states that are apt to
cause certain characteristic behaviors.
behavior therapy, a
spectrum of behavior modification techniques applied as therapy, such as
aversion therapy, extinction, modeling, redintegration, operant conditioning,
and desensitization. Unlike psychotherapy, which probes a client’s recollected
history, behavior therapy focuses on immediate behavior, and aims to eliminate
undesired behavior and produce desired behavior through methods derived from
the experimental analysis of behavior and from reinforcement theory. A chronic
problem with psychotherapy is that the client’s past is filtered through
limited and biased recollection. Behavior therapy is more mechanical, creating
systems of reinforcement and conditioning that may work independently of the
client’s long-term memory. Collectively, behavior-therapeutic techniques
compose a motley set. Some behavior therapists adapt techniques from
psychotherapy, as in covert desensitization, where verbally induced mental
images are employed as reinforcers. A persistent problem with behavior therapy
is that it may require repeated application. Consider aversion therapy. It
consists of pairing painful or punishing stimuli with unwelcome behavior. In
the absence, after therapy, of the painful stimulus, the behavior may recur
because association between behavior and punishment is broken. Critics charge
that behavior therapy deals with immediate disturbances and overt behavior, to
the neglect of underlying problems and irrationalities.
Belief: H. P. Grice,
“Disposition and belief,” H. P. Grice, “Knowledge and belief.” a dispositional
psychological state in virtue of which a person will assent to a proposition
under certain conditions. Propositional knowledge, traditionally understood,
entails belief. A behavioral view implies that beliefs are just dispositions to
behave in certain ways. Your believing that the stove is hot is just your being
disposed to act in a manner appropriate to its being hot. The problem is that
our beliefs, including their propositional content indicated by a
“that”-clause, typically explain why we do what we do. You avoid touching the
stove because you believe that it’s dangerously hot. Explaining action via
beliefs refers indispensably to propositional content, but the behavioral view
does not accommodate this. A state-object view implies that belief consists of
a special relation between a psychological state and an object of belief, what
is believed. The objects of belief, traditionally understood, are abstract
propositions existing independently of anyone’s thinking of them. The state of
believing is a propositional attitude involving some degree of confidence
toward a propositional object of belief. Such a view allows that two persons,
even separated by a long period of time, can believe the same thing. A
state-object view allows that beliefs be dispositional rather than episodic,
since they can exist while no action is occurring. Such a view grants, however,
that one can have a disposition to act owing to believing something. Regarding
mental action, a belief typically generates a disposition to assent, at least
under appropriate circumstances, to the proposition believed. Given the central
role of propositional content, however, a state-object view denies that beliefs
are just dispositions to act. In addition, such a view should distinguish
between dispositional believing and a mere disposition to believe. One can be
merely disposed to believe many things that one does not actually believe,
owing to one’s lacking the appropriate psychological attitude to relevant
propositional content. Beliefs are either occurrent or non-occurrent. Occurrent
belief, unlike non-occurrent belief, requires current assent to the proposition
believed. If the assent is self-conscious, the belief is an explicit occurrent
belief; if the assent is not self-conscious, the belief is an implicit
occurrent behaviorism, supervenient belief 78
78 belief. Non-occurrent beliefs permit that we do not cease to believe
that 2 ! 2 % 4, for instance, merely because we now happen to be thinking of
something else or nothing at all. .
belief revision, the
process by which cognitive states change in light of new information. This
topic looms large in discussions of Bayes’s Theorem and other approaches in
decision theory. The reasons prompting belief revision are characteristically
epistemic; they concern such notions as quality of evidence and the tendency to
yield truths. Many different rules have been proposed for updating one’s belief
set. In general, belief revision typically balances risk of error against
information increase. Belief revision is widely thought to proceed either by
expansion or by conceptual revision. Expansion occurs in virtue of new
observations; a belief is changed, or a new belief established, when a
hypothesis or provisional belief is supported by evidence whose probability is
high enough to meet a favored criterion of epistemic warrant. The hypothesis
then becomes part of the existing belief corpus, or is sufficient to prompt
revision. Conceptual revision occurs when appropriate changes are made in
theoretical assumptions in accordance
with such principles as simplicity and explanatory or predictive power by which the corpus is organized. In actual
cases, we tend to revise beliefs with an eye toward advancing the best
comprehensive explanation in the relevant cognitive domain.
Beneke: F. E, philosopher
who was influenced by Herbart and English empiricism and criticized
rationalistic metaphysics. He taught at Berlin and published some eighteen
books in philosophy. His major work was Lehrbuch der Psychologie als
Naturwissenschaft 1833. He wrote a critical study of Kant’s Critique of Pure
Reason and another on his moral theory; other works included Psychologie
Skizzen 1825, Metaphysik und Religionphilosophie 1840, and Die neue Psychologie
1845. The “new psychology” developed by Beneke held that the hypostatization of
“faculties” led to a mythical psychology. He proposed a method that would yield
a natural science of the soul or, in effect, an associationist psychology.
Influenced by the British empiricists, he conceived the elements of mental life
as dynamic, active processes or impulses Trieben. These “elementary faculties,”
originally activated by stimuli, generate the substantial unity of the nature
of the psychic by their persistence as traces, as well as by their reciprocal
adjustment in relation to the continuous production of new forces. In what
Beneke called “pragmatic psychology,” the psyche is a bundle of impulses,
forces, and functions. Psychological theory should rest on inductive analyses
of the facts of inner perception. This, in turn, is the foundation of the
philosophical disciplines of logic, ethics, metaphysics, and philosophy of
religion. In this regard, Beneke held a psychologism. He agreed with Herbart
that psychology must be based on inner experience and must eschew metaphysical
speculation, but rejected Hebart’s mathematical reductionism. Beneke sought to
create a “pragmatic philosophy” based on his psychology. In his last years he
contributed to pedagogic theory.
Bentham: j. Engish
philosopher of ethics and political-legal theory. Born in London, he entered
Queen’s, Oxford, at age 12, and after graduation entered Lincoln’s Inn to study
law. He was admitted to the bar in 1767 but never practiced. He spent his life
writing, advocating changes along utilitarian lines maximal happiness for
everyone affected of the whole legal system, especially the criminal law. He
was a strong influence in changes of the British law of evidence; in abolition
of laws permitting imprisonment for indebtedness; in the belief, basic Bentham,
Jeremy 79 79 reform of Parliamentary
representation; in the formation of a civil service recruited by examination;
and in much else. His major work published during his lifetime was An
Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation 1789. He became head
of a “radical” group including James Mill and J. S. Mill, and founded the Westminster
Review and , London where his embalmed
body still reposes in a closet. He was a friend of Catherine of Russia and John
Quincy Adams, and was made a citizen of France in 1792. Pleasure, he said, is
the only good, and pain the only evil: “else the words good and evil have no
meaning.” He gives a list of examples of what he means by ‘pleasure’: pleasures
of taste, smell, or touch; of acquiring property; of learning that one has the
goodwill of others; of power; of a view of the pleasures of those one cares
about. Bentham was also a psychological hedonist: pleasures and pains determine
what we do. Take pain. Your state of mind may be painful now at the time just
prior to action because it includes the expectation of the pain say of being
burned; the present pain or the expectation of later pain Bentham is undecided which motivates action
to prevent being burned. One of a person’s pleasures, however, may be
sympathetic enjoyment of the well-being of another. So it seems one can be
motivated by the prospect of the happiness of another. His psychology here is
not incompatible with altruistic motivation. Bentham’s critical utilitarianism
lies in his claim that any action, or measure of government, ought to be taken
if and only if it tends to augment the happiness of everyone affected not at all a novel principle, historically.
When “thus interpreted, the words ought, and right and wrong . . . have a
meaning: when otherwise, they have none.” Bentham evidently did not mean this
statement as a purely linguistic point about the actual meaning of moral terms.
Neither can this principle be proved; it is a first principle from which all
proofs proceed. What kind of reason, then, can he offer in its support? At one
point he says that the principle of utility, at least unconsciously, governs
the judgment of “every thinking man . . . unavoidably.” But his chief answer is
his critique of a widely held principle that a person properly calls an act
wrong if when informed of the facts he disapproves of it. Bentham cites other
language as coming to the same thesis: talk of a “moral sense,” or common
sense, or the understanding, or the law of nature, or right reason, or the
“fitness of things.” He says that this is no principle at all, since a
“principle is something that points out some external consideration, as a means
of warranting and guiding the internal sentiments of approbation. . . .” The
alleged principle also allows for widespread disagreement about what is moral.
So far, Bentham’s proposal has not told us exactly how to determine whether an
action or social measure is right or wrong. Bentham suggests a hedonic
calculus: in comparing two actions under consideration, we count up the
pleasures or pains each will probably produce
how intense, how long-lasting, whether near or remote, including any
derivative later pleasures or pains that may be caused, and sum them up for all
persons who will be affected. Evidently these directions can provide at best
only approximate results. We are in no position to decide whether one pleasure
for one hour is greater than another pleasure for half an hour, even when they
are both pleasures of one person who can compare them. How much more when the
pleasures are of different persons? Still, we can make judgments important for
the theory of punishment: whether a blow in the face with no lasting damage for
one person is more or less painful than fifty lashes for his assailant! Bentham
has been much criticized because he thought that two pleasures are equal in
value, if they are equally intense, enduring, etc. As he said, “Quantity of
pleasure being equal, pushpin is as good as poetry.” It has been thought e.g.,
by J. S. Mill that some pleasures, especially intellectual ones, are higher and
deserve to count more. But it may be replied that the so-called higher
pleasures are more enduring, are less likely to be followed by satiety, and
open up new horizons of enjoyment; and when these facts are taken into account,
it is not clear that there is need to accord higher status to intellectual
pleasures as such. A major goal of Bentham’s was to apply to the criminal law
his principle of maximizing the general utility. Bentham thought there should
be no punishment of an offense if it is not injurious to someone. So how much
punishment should there be? The least amount the effect of which will result in
a greater degree of happiness, overall. The benefit of punishment is primarily
deterrence, by attaching to the thought of a given act the thought of the
painful sanction which will deter both
the past and prospective lawbreakers. The punishment, then, must be severe
enough to outweigh the benefit of the offense to the agent, making allowance,
by addition, for the uncertainty that the punishment will actually occur. There
are some harmful acts, however, that it is Bentham, Jeremy Bentham, Jeremy
80 80 not beneficial to punish. One is
an act needful to produce a greater benefit, or avoid a serious evil, for the
agent. Others are those which a penal prohibition could not deter: when the law
is unpublished or the agent is insane or an infant. In some cases society need
feel no alarm about the future actions of the agent. Thus, an act is criminal
only if intentional, and the agent is excused if he acted on the basis of
beliefs such that, were they true, the act would have caused no harm, unless
these beliefs were culpable in the sense that they would not have been held by
a person of ordinary prudence or benevolence. The propriety of punishing an act
also depends somewhat on its motive, although no motive e.g., sexual desire,
curiosity, wanting money, love of reputation
is bad in itself. Yet the propriety of punishment is affected by the
presence of some motivations that enhance public security because it is
unlikely that they e.g., sympathetic
concern or concern for reputation will
lead to bad intentional acts. When a given motive leads to a bad intention, it
is usually because of the weakness of motives like sympathy, concern for
avoiding punishment, or respect for law. In general, the sanction of moral
criticism should take lines roughly similar to those of the ideal law. But
there are some forms of behavior, e.g., imprudence or fornication, which the
law is hardly suited to punish, that can be sanctioned by morality. The
business of the moral philosopher is censorial: to say what the law, or
morality, ought to be. To say what is the law is a different matter: what it is
is the commands of the sovereign, defined as one whom the public, in general,
habitually obeys. As consisting of commands, it is imperatival. The imperatives
may be addressed to the public, as in “Let no one steal,” or to judges: “Let a
judge sentence anyone who steals to be hanged.” It may be thought that there is
a third part, an explanation, say, of what is a person’s property; but this can
be absorbed in the imperatival part, since the designations of property are
just imperatives about who is to be free to do what. Why should anyone obey the
actual laws? Bentham’s answer is that one should do so if and only if it
promises to maximize the general happiness. He eschews contract theories of
political obligation: individuals now alive never contracted, and so how are
they bound? He also opposes appeal to natural rights. If what are often
mentioned as natural rights were taken seriously, no government could survive:
it could not tax, require military service, etc. Nor does he accept appeal to
“natural law,” as if, once some law is shown to be immoral, it can be said to
be not really law. That would be absurd.
Berdyaev: N.,
philosopher, he began as a “Kantian Marxist” in epistemology, ethical theory,
and philosophy of history, but soon turned away from Marxism although he
continued to accept Marx’s critique of capitalism toward a theistic philosophy
of existence stressing the values of creativity and “meonic” freedom a freedom allegedly prior to all being,
including that of God. In exile after 1922, Berdyaev appears to have been the
first to grasp clearly in the early 1920s that the Marxist view of historical
time involves a morally unacceptable devaluing and instrumentalizing of the
historical present including living persons for the sake of the remote future
end of a perfected communist society. Berdyaev rejects the Marxist position on
both Christian and Kantian grounds, as a violation of the intrinsic value of
human persons. He sees the historical order as marked by inescapable tragedy,
and welcomes the “end of history” as an “overcoming” of objective historical
time by subjective “existential” time with its free, unobjectified creativity.
For Berdyaev the “world of objects”
physical things, laws of nature, social institutions, and human roles
and relationships is a pervasive threat
to “free spiritual creativity.” Yet such creativity appears to be subject to
inevitable frustration, since its outward embodiments are always “partial and
fragmentary” and no “outward action” can escape ultimate “tragic failure.”
Russian Orthodox traditionalists condemned Berdyaev for claiming that all
creation is a “divine-human process” and for denying God’s omnipotence, but
such Western process theologians as Hartshorne find Berdyaev’s position highly
congenial.
bergmann, gustav:
infamous for calling H. P. Grice “one of them English futilitarians” -- philosopher,
the youngest member of the Vienna Circle. Born in Vienna, he received his
doctorate in mathematics in 1928 from the
of Vienna. Originally influenced by logical positivism, he became a
phenomenalist who also posited mental acts irreducible to sense-data see his
The Metaphysics of Logical Positivism, 1954. Although he eventually rejected
phenomenalism, his ontology of material objects remained structurally
phenomenalistic. Bergmann’s world is one of momentary bare i.e. natureless
particulars exemplifying phenomenally simple Berdyaev, Nicolas Bergmann, Gustav
81 81 universals, relational as well as
non-relational. Some of these universals are non-mental, such as color
properties and spatial relations, while others, such as the “intentional
characters” in virtue of which some particulars mental acts intend or represent
the facts that are their “objects,” are mental. Bergmann insisted that the
world is independent of both our experience of it and our thought and discourse
about it: he claimed that the connection of exemplification and even the
propositional connectives and quantifiers are mind-independent. See Meaning and
Existence, 1959; Logic and Reality, 1964; and Realism: A Critique of Brentano
and Meinong, 1967. Such extreme realism produced many criticisms of his
philosophy that are only finally addressed in Bergmann’s recently, and
posthumously, published book, New Foundations of Ontology 1992, in which he
concedes that his atomistic approach to ontology has inevitable limitations and
proposes a way of squaring this insight with his thoroughgoing realism.
bergson: h. l.: cited by
H. P. Grice in “Personal identity,” philosopher, the most influential of the
first half of the twentieth century. Born in Paris and educated at the
prestigious École Normale Supérieure, he began his teaching career at
Clermont-Ferrand in 1884 and was called in 1900 to the Collège de France, where
his lectures enjoyed unparalleled success until his retirement in 1921. Ideally
placed in la belle époque of prewar Paris, his ideas influenced a broad
spectrum of artistic, literary, social, and political movements. In 1918 he
received the Légion d’honneur and was admitted into the French Academy. From
1922 through 1925 he participated in the League of Nations, presiding over the
creation of what was later to become UNESCO. Forced by crippling arthritis into
virtual seclusion during his later years, Bergson was awarded the Nobel Prize
for literature in 1928. Initially a disciple of Spencer, Bergson broke with him
after a careful examination of Spencer’s concept of time and mechanistic positivism.
Following a deeply entrenched tradition in Western thought, Spencer treats time
on an analogy with space as a series of discrete numerical units: instants,
seconds, minutes. When confronted with experience, however especially with that of our own psychological
states such concepts are, Bergson
concludes, patently inadequate. Real duration, unlike clock time, is
qualitative, dynamic, irreversible. It cannot be “spatialized” without being
deformed. It gives rise in us, moreover, to free acts, which, being qualitative
and spontaneous, cannot be predicted. Bergson’s dramatic contrast of real
duration and geometrical space, first developed in Time and Free Will 1890, was
followed in 1896 by the mind body theory of Matter and Memory. He argues here
that the brain is not a locale for thought but a motor organ that, receiving
stimuli from its environment, may respond with adaptive behavior. To his
psychological and metaphysical distinction between duration and space Bergson
adds, in An Introduction to Metaphysics 1903, an important epistemological
distinction between intuition and analysis. Intuition probes the flow of
duration in its concreteness; analysis breaks up duration into static,
fragmentary concepts. In Creative Evolution 1907, his best-known work, Bergson
argues against both Lamarck and Darwin, urging that biological evolution is
impelled by a vital impetus or élan vital that drives life to overcome the
downward entropic drift of matter. Biological organisms, unlike dice, must
compete and survive as they undergo permutations. Hence the unresolved dilemma
of Darwinism. Either mutations occur one or a few at a time in which case how
can they be “saved up” to constitute new organs? or they occur all at once in
which case one has a “miracle”. Bergson’s vitalism, popular in literary
circles, was not accepted by many scientists or philosophers. His most general
contention, however that biological
evolution is not consistent with or even well served by a mechanistic philosophy was broadly appreciated and to many seemed
convincing. This aspect of Bergson’s writings influenced thinkers as diverse as
Lloyd Morgan, Alexis Carrel, Sewall Wright, Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, and A.
N. Whitehead. The contrasts in terms of which Bergson developed his thought
duration/space, intuition/ analysis, life/entropy are replaced in The Two
Sources of Morality and Religion 1932 by a new duality, that of the “open” and
the “closed.” The Judeo-Christian tradition, he contends, if it has embraced in
its history both the open society and the closed society, exhibits in its great
saints and mystics a profound opening out of the human spirit toward all
humanity. Bergson’s distinction between the open and the closed society was
popularized by Karl Popper in his The Open Society and Its Enemies. While it
has attracted serious criticism, Bergson’s philosophy has also significantly
affected subsequent thinkers. Novelists as diverse as Bergson, Henri Louis
Bergson, Henri Louis 82 82 Nikos
Kazantzakis, Marcel Proust, and William Faulkner; poets as unlike as Charles
Péguy, Robert Frost, and Antonio Machado; and psychologists as dissimilar as
Pierre Janet and Jean Piaget were to profit significantly from his explorations
of duration, conceptualization, and memory. Both French existentialism and
American process philosophy bear the imprint of his thought.
Berkeley: g., Irish
philosopher and bishop in the Anglican Church of Ireland, one of the three
great British empiricists along with Locke and Hume. He developed novel and
influential views on the visual perception of distance and size, and an
idealist metaphysical system that he defended partly on the seemingly
paradoxical ground that it was the best defense of common sense and safeguard
against skepticism. Berkeley studied at Trinity , Dublin, from which he
graduated at nineteen. He was elected to a fellowship at Trinity in 1707, and
did the bulk of his philosophical writing between that year and 1713. He was
made dean of Derry in 1724, following extensive traveling on the Continent; he
spent the years 172832 in Rhode Island, waiting in vain for promised Crown
funds to establish a in Bermuda. He was
made bishop of Cloyne, Ireland, in 1734, and he remained there as a cleric for
nearly the remainder of his life. Berkeley’s first major publication, the Essay
Towards a New Theory of Vision 1709, is principally a work in the psychology of
vision, though it has important philosophical presuppositions and implications.
Berkeley’s theory of vision became something like the received view on the topic
for nearly two hundred years and is a landmark work in the history of
psychology. The work is devoted to three connected matters: how do we see, or
visually estimate, the distances of objects from ourselves, the situation or
place at which objects are located, and the magnitude of such objects? Earlier
views, such as those of Descartes, Malebranche, and Molyneux, are rejected on
the ground that their answers to the above questions allow that a person can
see the distance of an object without having first learned to correlate visual
and other cues. This was supposedly done by a kind of natural geometry, a
computation of the distance by determining the altitude of a triangle formed by
light rays from the object and the line extending from one retina to the other.
On the contrary, Berkeley holds that it is clear that seeing distance is
something one learns to do through trial and error, mainly by correlating cues
that suggest distance: the distinctness or confusion of the visual appearance;
the feelings received when the eyes turn; and the sensations attending the
straining of the eyes. None of these bears any necessary connection to
distance. Berkeley infers from this account that a person born blind and later
given sight would not be able to tell by sight alone the distances objects were
from her, nor tell the difference between a sphere and a cube. He also argues
that in visually estimating distance, one is really estimating which tangible
ideas one would likely experience if one were to take steps to approach the
object. Not that these tangible ideas are themselves necessarily connected to
the visual appearances. Instead, Berkeley holds that tangible and visual ideas
are entirely heterogeneous, i.e., they are numerically and specifically
distinct. The latter is a philosophical consequence of Berkeley’s theory of
vision, which is sharply at odds with a central doctrine of Locke’s Essay,
namely, that some ideas are common to both sight and touch. Locke’s doctrines
also receive a great deal of attention in the Principles of Human Knowledge
1710. Here Berkeley considers the doctrine of abstract general ideas, which he
finds in Book III of Locke’s Essay. He argues against such ideas partly on the
ground that we cannot engage in the process of abstraction, partly on the
ground that some abstract ideas are impossible objects, and also on the ground
that such ideas are not needed for either language learning or language use.
These arguments are of fundamental importance for Berkeley, since he thinks
that the doctrine of abstract ideas helps to support metaphysical realism,
absolute space, absolute motion, and absolute time Principles, 5, 100, 11011,
as well as the view that some ideas are common to sight and touch New Theory,
123. All of these doctrines Berkeley holds to be mistaken, and the first is in
direct conflict with his idealism. Hence, it is important for him to undermine
any support these doctrines might receive from the abstract ideas thesis.
Berkeleyan idealism is the view that the only existing entities are finite and
infinite perceivers each of which is a spirit or mental substance, and entities
that are perceived. Such a thesis implies that ordinary physical objects exist
if and only if they are perceived, something Berkeley encapsulates in the esse
est percipi principle: for all senBerkeley, George Berkeley, George 83 83 sible objects, i.e., objects capable of
being perceived, their being is to be perceived. He gives essentially two
arguments for this thesis. First, he holds that every physical object is just a
collection of sensible qualities, and that every sensible quality is an idea.
So, physical objects are just collections of sensible ideas. No idea can exist
unperceived, something everyone in the period would have granted. Hence, no
physical object can exist unperceived. The second argument is the socalled
master argument of Principles 2224. There Berkeley argues that one cannot
conceive a sensible object existing unperceived, because if one attempts to do
this one must thereby conceive that very object. He concludes from this that no
such object can exist “without the mind,” that is, wholly unperceived. Many of
Berkeley’s opponents would have held instead that a physical object is best
analyzed as a material substratum, in which some sensible qualities inhere. So
Berkeley spends some effort arguing against material substrata or what he
sometimes calls matter. His principal argument is that a sensible quality
cannot inhere in matter, because a sensible quality is an idea, and surely an
idea cannot exist except in a mind. This argument would be decisive if it were
true that each sensible quality is an idea. Unfortunately, Berkeley gives no
argument whatever for this contention in the Principles, and for that reason
Berkeleyan idealism is not there well founded. Nor does the master argument
fare much better, for there Berkeley seems to require a premise asserting that
if an object is conceived, then that object is perceived. Yet such a premise is
highly dubious. Probably Berkeley realized that his case for idealism had not
been successful, and certainly he was stung by the poor reception of the
Principles. His next book, Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous 1713, is
aimed at rectifying these matters. There he argues at length for the thesis
that each sensible quality is an idea. The master argument is repeated, but it
is unnecessary if every sensible quality is an idea. In the Dialogues Berkeley
is also much concerned to combat skepticism and defend common sense. He argues
that representative realism as held by Locke leads to skepticism regarding the
external world and this, Berkeley thinks, helps to support atheism and free
thinking in religion. He also argues, more directly, that representative
realism is false. Such a thesis incorporates the claim that somesensible ideas
represent real qualities in objects, the so-called primary qualities. But
Berkeley argues that a sensible idea can be like nothing but another idea, and
so ideas cannot represent qualities in objects. In this way, Berkeley
eliminates one main support of skepticism, and to that extent helps to support
the commonsensical idea that we gain knowledge of the existence and nature of
ordinary physical objects by means of perception. Berkeley’s positive views in
epistemology are usually interpreted as a version of foundationalism. That is,
he is generally thought to have defended the view that beliefs about currently
perceived ideas are basic beliefs, beliefs that are immediately and
non-inferentially justified or that count as pieces of immediate knowledge, and
that all other justified beliefs in contingent propositions are justified by
being somehow based upon the basic beliefs. Indeed, such a foundationalist
doctrine is often taken to help define empiricism, held in common by Locke,
Berkeley, and Hume. But whatever the merits of such a view as an interpretation
of Locke or Hume, it is not Berkeley’s theory. This is because he allows that
perceivers often have immediate and noninferential justified beliefs, and
knowledge, about physical objects. Hence, Berkeley accepts a version of
foundationalism that allows for basic beliefs quite different from just beliefs
about one’s currently perceived ideas. Indeed, he goes so far as to maintain
that such physical object beliefs are often certain, something neither Locke
nor Hume would accept. In arguing against the existence of matter, Berkeley
also maintains that we literally have no coherent concept of such stuff because
we cannot have any sensible idea of it. Parity of reasoning would seem to
dictate that Berkeley should reject mental substance as well, thereby
threatening his idealism from another quarter. Berkeley is sensitive to this
line of reasoning, and replies that while we have no idea of the self, we do
have some notion of the self, that is, some lessthan-complete concept. He
argues that a person gains some immediate knowledge of the existence and nature
of herself in a reflex act; that is, when she is perceiving something she is
also conscious that something is engaging in this perception, and this is
sufficient for knowledge of that perceiving entity. To complement his idealism,
Berkeley worked out a version of scientific instrumentalism, both in the
Principles and in a later Latin work, De Motu 1721, a doctrine that anticipates
the views of Mach. In the Dialogues he tries to show how his idealism is
consistent with the biblical account of the creation, and consistent as well
with common sense. Berkeley, George Berkeley, George 84 84 Three later works of Berkeley’s gained
him an enormous amount of attention. Alciphron 1734 was written while Berkeley
was in Rhode Island, and is a philosophical defense of Christian doctrine. It
also contains some additional comments on perception, supplementing earlier
work on that topic. The Analyst 1734 contains trenchant criticism of the method
of fluxions in differential calculus, and it set off a flurry of pamphlet
replies to Berkeley’s criticisms, to which Berkeley responded in his A Defense
of Free Thinking in Mathematics. Siris 1744 contains a detailed account of the
medicinal values of tar-water, water boiled with the bark of certain trees.
This book also contains a defense of a sort of corpuscularian philosophy that
seems to be at odds with the idealism elaborated in the earlier works for which
Berkeley is now famous. In the years 170708, the youthful Berkeley kept a
series of notebooks in which he worked out his ideas in philosophy and
mathematics. These books, now known as the Philosophical Commentaries, provide
the student of Berkeley with the rare opportunity to see a great philosopher’s
thought in development.
Berlin: I. Russian-born philosopher
and historian of ideas. He is widely acclaimed for his doctrine of radical
objective pluralism; his writings on liberty; his modification, refinement, and
defense of traditional liberalism against the totalitarian doctrines of the
twentieth century not least Marxism-Leninism; and his brilliant and
illuminating studies in the history of ideas from Machiavelli and Vico to Marx
and Sorel. A founding father with Austin, Ayer, and others of Oxford philosophy
in the 1930s, he published several influential papers in its general spirit,
but, without abandoning its empirical approach, he came increasingly to dissent
from what seemed to him its unduly barren, doctrinaire, and truthdenying
tendencies. From the 1950s onward he broke away to devote himself principally
to social and political philosophy and to the study of general ideas. His two
most important contributions in social and political theory, brought together
with two other valuable essays in Four Essays on Liberty 1969, are “Historical
Inevitability” 1954 and his 1958 inaugural lecture as Chichele Professor of
Social and Political Theory at Oxford, “Two Concepts of Liberty.” The first is
a bold and decisive attack on historical determinism and moral relativism and
subjectivism and a ringing endorsement of the role of free will and
responsibility in human history. The second contains Berlin’s enormously
influential attempt to distinguish clearly between “negative” and “positive”
liberty. Negative liberty, foreshadowed by such thinkers as J. S. Mill,
Constant, and above all Herzen, consists in making minimal assumptions about
the ultimate nature and needs of the subject, in ensuring a minimum of external
interference by authority of any provenance, and in leaving open as large a
field for free individual choice as is consonant with a minimum of social
organization and order. Positive liberty, associated with monist and
voluntarist thinkers of all kinds, not least Hegel, the German Idealists, and
their historical progeny, begins with the notion of self-mastery and proceeds
to make dogmatic and far-reaching metaphysical assumptions about the essence of
the subject. It then deduces from these the proper paths to freedom, and,
finally, seeks to drive flesh-and-blood individuals down these preordained
paths, whether they wish it or not, within the framework of a tight-knit
centralized state under the irrefragable rule of rational experts, thus
perverting what begins as a legitimate human ideal, i.e. positive
self-direction and self-mastery, into a tyranny. “Two Concepts of Liberty” also
sets out to disentangle liberty in either of these senses from other ends, such
as the craving for recognition, the need to belong, or human solidarity,
fraternity, or equality. Berlin’s work in the history of ideas is of a piece
with his other writings. Vico and Herder 1976 presents the emergence of that
historicism and pluralism which shook the two-thousand-yearold monist
rationalist faith in a unified body of truth regarding all questions of fact
and principle in all fields of human knowledge. From this profound intellectual
overturn Berlin traces in subsequent volumes of essays, such as Against the
Current 1979, The Crooked Timber of Humanity 1990, and The Sense of Reality
1996, the growth of some of the principal intellectual movements that mark our
era, among them nationalism, fascism, relativism, subjectivism, nihilism,
voluntarism, and existentialism. He also presents with persuasiveness and
clarity that peculiar objective pluralism which he identified and made his own.
There is an irreducible plurality of objective human values, many of which are
incompatible with one another; hence the ineluctable need for absolute choices
by individuals and groups, a need that confers supreme value upon, and forms
one of the major justifications of, his conception of negative liberty; Berlin,
Isaiah Berlin, Isaiah 85 85 hence, too,
his insistence that utopia, namely a world where all valid human ends and
objective values are simultaneously realized in an ultimate synthesis, is a
conceptual impossibility. While not himself founder of any definable school or
movement, Berlin’s influence as a philosopher and as a human being has been
immense, not least on a variety of distinguished thinkers such as Stuart
Hampshire, Charles Taylor, Bernard Williams, Richard Wollheim, Gerry Cohen,
Steven Lukes, David Pears, and many others. His general intellectual and moral
impact on the life of the twentieth century as writer, diplomat, patron of
music and the arts, international academic elder statesman, loved and trusted
friend to the great and the humble, and dazzling lecturer, conversationalist,
and animateur des idées, will furnish inexhaustible material to future historians.
Bernard of Chartres fl.
111426, French philosopher. He was first a teacher 111419 and later chancellor
111926 of the cathedral school at Chartres, which was then an active center of
learning in the liberal arts and philosophy. Bernard himself was renowned as a
grammarian, i.e., as an expositor of difficult texts, and as a teacher of
Plato. None of his works has survived whole, and only three fragments are
preserved in works by others. He is now best known for an image recorded both
by his student, John of Salisbury, and by William of Conches. In Bernard’s
image, he and all his medieval contemporaries were in relation to the ancient
authors like “dwarfs sitting on the shoulders of giants.” John of Salisbury
takes the image to mean both that the medievals could see more and further than
the ancients, and that they could do so only because they had been lifted up by
such powerful predecessors. M.D.J. Bernard of Clairvaux, Saint 10901153, French
Cistercian monk, mystic, and religious leader. He is most noted for his
doctrine of Christian humility and his depiction of the mystical experience,
which exerted considerable influence on later Christian mystics. Educated in
France, he entered the monastery at Cîteaux in 1112, and three years later
founded a daughter monastery at Clairvaux. According to Bernard, honest
self-knowledge should reveal the extent to which we fail to be what we should
be in the eyes of God. That selfknowledge should lead us to curb our pride and
so become more humble. Humility is necessary for spiritual purification, which
in turn is necessary for contemplation of God, the highest form of which is
union with God. Consistent with orthodox Christian doctrine, Bernard maintains
that mystical union does not entail identity. One does not become God; rather,
one’s will and God’s will come into complete conformity.
Bernoulli’s theorem, also
called the weak law of large numbers, the principle that if a series of trials
is repeated n times where a there are two possible outcomes, 0 and 1, on each
trial, b the probability p of 0 is the same on each trial, and c this
probability is independent of the outcome of other trials, then, for arbitrary
positive e, as the number n of trials is increased, the probability that the
absolute value Kr/n pK of the difference
between the relative frequency r/n of 0’s in the n trials and p is less than e
approaches 1. The first proof of this theorem was given by Jakob Bernoulli in
Part IV of his posthumously published Ars Conjectandi of 1713. Simplifications
were later constructed and his result has been generalized in a series of “weak
laws of large numbers.” Although Bernoulli’s theorem derives a conclusion about
the probability of the relative frequency r/n of 0’s for large n of trials
given the value of p, in Ars Conjectandi and correspondence with Leibniz,
Bernoulli thought it could be used to reason from information about r/n to the
value of p when the latter is unknown. Speculation persists as to whether
Bernoulli anticipated the inverse inference of Bayes, the confidence interval
estimation of Peirce, J. Neyman, and E. S. Pearson, or the fiducial argument of
R. A. Fisher.
Bertrand’s box paradox, a
puzzle concerning conditional probability. Imagine three boxes with two drawers
apiece. Each drawer of the first box contains a gold medal. Each drawer of the
second contains a silver medal. One drawer of the third contains a gold medal,
and the other a silver medal. At random, a box is selected and one of its
drawers is opened. If a gold medal appears, what is the probability that the
third box was selected? The probability seems to be ½, because the box is
either the first or the third, and they seem equally probable. But a gold medal
is less probable from the third box than from the first, Bernard of Chartres
Bertrand’s box paradox 86 86 so the
third box is actually less probable than the first. By Bayes’s theorem its
probability is 1 /3. Joseph Bertrand, a French mathematician, published the
paradox in Calcul des probabilités Calculus of Probabilities, 1889.
Bertrand’s paradox, an
inconsistency arising from the classical definition of an event’s probability
as the number of favorable cases divided by the number of possible cases. Given
a circle, a chord is selected at random. What is the probability that the chord
is longer than a side of an equilateral triangle inscribed in the circle? The
event has these characterizations: 1 the apex angle of an isosceles triangle
inscribed in the circle and having the chord as a leg is less than 60°, 2 the
chord intersects the diameter perpendicular to it less than ½ a radius from the
circle’s center, and 3 the chord’s midpoint lies within a circle concentric
with the original and of ¼ its area. The definition thus suggests that the
event’s probability is 1 /3, 1 /2, and also ¼. Joseph Bertrand, a French
mathematician, published the paradox in Calcul des probabilités 1889.
Beth’s definability
theorem, a theorem for firstorder logic. A theory defines a term t implicitly
if and only if an explicit definition of the term, on the basis of the other
primitive concepts, is entailed by the theory. A theory defines a term
implicitly if any two models of the theory with the same domain and the same
extension for the other primitive terms are identical, i.e., also have the same
extension for the term. An explicit definition of a term is a sentence that
states necessary and sufficient conditions for the term’s applicability. Beth’s
theorem was implicit in a method to show independence of a term that was first
used by the Italian logician Alessandro Padoa 18681937. Padoa suggested, in
1900, that independence of a primitive algebraic term from the other terms
occurring in a set of axioms can be established by two true interpretations of
the axioms that differ only in the interpretation of the term whose
independence has to be proven. He claimed, without proof, that the existence of
two such models is not only sufficient for, but also implied by, independence.
Tarski first gave a proof of Beth’s theorem in 1926 for the logic of the
Principia Mathematica of Whitehead and Russell, but the result was only
obtained for first-order logic in 1953 by the Dutch logician Evert Beth 190864.
In modern expositions Beth’s theorem is a direct implication of Craig’s
interpolation theorem. In a variation on Padoa’s method, Karel de Bouvère
described in 1959 a one-model method to show indefinability: if the set of
logical consequences of a theory formulated in terms of the remaining
vocabulary cannot be extended to a model of the full theory, a term is not explicitly
definable in terms of the remaining vocabulary. In the philosophy of science
literature this is called a failure of Ramsey-eliminability of the term.
Bhagavad Gita from
Sanskrit Bhagavadgita, ‘song of the blessed one/exalted lord’, Hindu devotional
poem composed and edited between the fifth century B.C. and the second century
A.D. It contains eighteen chapters and seven hundred verses, and forms the
sixth book Chapters 23 40 of the Indian epic Mahabharata. In its narrative, the
warrior Arjuna, reluctantly waiting to wage war, receives a revelation from the
Lord Krishna that emphasizes selfless deeds and bhakti, or devotion. Strictly
classified as smrti or fallible tradition, the Gita is typically treated as
shruti or infallible revelation. Such major thinkers as Shankara, Ramanuja, and
Madhva wrote commentaries on this beloved book. Shankara reads it as teaching
that enlightenment comes through right Advaita Vedanta knowledge alone even
without performance of religious duties. Ramanuja takes it to hold that
enlightenment comes through performance of religious duties, particularly
devotion to God for whose sake alone all other duties must be performed if
one’s sins are to be washed away. Such devotion leads to or at its zenith
includes self-knowledge and knowledge of personal Brahman. Madhva sees the Gita
as emphasizing divine uniqueness and the necessity of love and attachment to
God and not to oneself or the consequences of one’s deeds.
bhakti Sanskrit, in Hindu
theistic thought systems, devotion. Bhakti includes the ideas of faith,
surrender, love, affection, and attachment. Its most common form of expression
is worship by means of offerings, puja. Theistic thinkers such as Ramanuja and
Madhva argue that devotion is the key element that solves the human
predicament. As a result the deity responds with grace or kindness prasadam and
thereby causes the devotee to prosper or attain moksha. The Bhakti Sutras
twelfth century A.D. distinguish “lower bhakti,” i.e., devotion with personal
goals in mind, from “higher bhakti,” i.e., selfless devotion practiced only to
please the deity. The latter is libBertrand’s paradox bhakti 87 87 eration. Modern Hindu philosophers,
following Shankara and the modern Hindu apologist Swami Vivekananda 18621902,
often relegate bhakti to a lower path than knowledge jnana for those who are
unable to follow philosophy, but in the philosophical systems of many theists
it is defended as the highest path with the main obstacle as unbelief, not
ignorance.
bhavanga, a subliminal
mode of consciousness, according to Theravada Buddhist philosophers, in which
no mental activity occurs. The continued existence of the bhavanga-mind in
states where there is no intentional mental activity e.g., dreamless sleep is
what guarantees the continuance of a particular mental continuum in such
states. It operates also in ordinary events of sensation and conceptualization,
being connected with such intentional mental events in complex ways, and is
appealed to as an explanatory category in the accounts of the process leading
from death to rebirth. Some Buddhists also use it as a soteriological category,
identifying the bhavanga-mind with mind in its pure state, mind as luminous and
radiant.
biconditional, the
logical operator, usually written with a triple-bar sign S or a doubleheaded
arrow Q, used to indicate that two propositions have the same truth-value: that
either both are true or else both are false. The term also designates a
proposition having this sign, or a natural language expression of it, as its
main connective; e.g., P if and only if Q. The truth table for the
biconditional is The biconditional is so called because its application is
logically equivalent to the conjunction ‘P-conditional-Q-and-Q-conditional-P’.
bioethics, the subfield
of ethics that concerns the ethical issues arising in medicine and from
advances in biological science. One central area of bioethics is the ethical
issues that arise in relations between health care professionals and patients.
A second area focuses on broader issues of social justice in health care. A
third area concerns the ethical issues raised by new biological knowledge or
technology. In relations between health care professionals and patients, a
fundamental issue is the appropriate role of each in decision making about
patient care. More traditional views assigning principal decision-making
authority to physicians have largely been replaced with ideals of shared
decision making that assign a more active role to patients. Shared decision
making is thought to reflect better the importance of patients’
self-determination in controlling their care. This increased role for patients
is reflected in the ethical and legal doctrine of informed consent, which
requires that health care not be rendered without the informed and voluntary
consent of a competent patient. The requirement that consent be informed places
a positive responsibility on health care professionals to provide their
patients with the information they need to make informed decisions about care.
The requirement that consent be voluntary requires that treatment not be
forced, nor that patients’ decisions be coerced or manipulated. If patients
lack the capacity to make competent health care decisions, e.g. young children
or cognitively impaired adults, a surrogate, typically a parent in the case of
children or a close family member in the case of adults, must decide for them.
Surrogates’ decisions should follow the patient’s advance directive if one
exists, be the decision the patient would have made in the circumstances if
competent, or follow the patient’s best interests if the patient has never been
competent or his or her wishes are not known. A major focus in bioethics
generally, and treatment decision making in particular, is care at or near the
end of life. It is now widely agreed that patients are entitled to decide about
and to refuse, according to their own values, any lifesustaining treatment.
They are also entitled to have desired treatments that may shorten their lives,
such as high doses of pain medications necessary to relieve severe pain from
cancer, although in practice pain treatment remains inadequate for many
patients. Much more controversial is whether more active means to end life such
as physician-assisted suicide and voluntary euthanasia are morally permissible
in indibhavanga bioethics 88 88 vidual
cases or justified as public policy; both remain illegal except in a very few
jurisdictions. Several other moral principles have been central to defining
professionalpatient relationships in health care. A principle of truth telling
requires that professionals not lie to patients. Whereas in the past it was
common, especially with patients with terminal cancers, not to inform patients
fully about their diagnosis and prognosis, studies have shown that practice has
changed substantially and that fully informing patients does not have the bad
effects for patients that had been feared in the past. Principles of privacy
and confidentiality require that information gathered in the professionalpatient
relationship not be disclosed to third parties without patients’ consent.
Especially with highly personal information in mental health care, or
information that may lead to discrimination, such as a diagnosis of AIDS,
assurance of confidentiality is fundamental to the trust necessary to a
wellfunctioning professionalpatient relationship. Nevertheless, exceptions to
confidentiality to prevent imminent and serious harm to others are well
recognized ethically and legally. More recently, work in bioethics has focused
on justice in the allocation of health care. Whereas nearly all developed
countries treat health care as a moral and legal right, and ensure it to all
their citizens through some form of national health care system, in the United
States about 15 percent of the population remains without any form of health
insurance. This has fed debates about whether health care is a right or
privilege, a public or individual responsibility. Most bioethicists have
supported a right to health care because of health care’s fundamental impact on
people’s well-being, opportunity, ability to plan their lives, and even lives
themselves. Even if there is a moral right to health care, however, few defend
an unlimited right to all beneficial health care, no matter how small the
benefit and how high the cost. Consequently, it is necessary to prioritize or
ration health care services to reflect limited budgets for health care, and
both the standards and procedures for doing so are ethically controversial.
Utilitarians and defenders of cost-effectiveness analysis in health policy
support using limited resources to maximize aggregate health benefits for the
population. Their critics argue that this ignores concerns about equity,
concerns about how health care resources and health are distributed. For
example, some have argued that equity requires giving priority to treating the
worst-off or sickest, even at a sacrifice in aggregate health benefits;
moreover, taking account in prioritization of differences in costs of different
treatments can lead to ethically problematic results, such as giving higher
priority to providing very small benefits to many persons than very large but
individually more expensive benefits, including life-saving interventions, to a
few persons, as the state of Oregon found in its initial widely publicized
prioritization program. In the face of controversy over standards for rationing
care, it is natural to rely on fair procedures to make rationing decisions.
Other bioethics issues arise from dramatic advances in biological knowledge and
technology. Perhaps the most prominent example is new knowledge of human
genetics, propelled in substantial part by the worldwide Human Genome Project,
which seeks to map the entire human genome. This project and related research
will enable the prevention of genetically transmitted diseases, but already
raises questions about which conditions to prevent in offspring and which
should be accepted and lived with, particularly when the means of preventing
the condition is by abortion of the fetus with the condition. Looking further
into the future, new genetic knowledge and technology will likely enable us to
enhance normal capacities, not just prevent or cure disease, and to manipulate
the genes of future children, raising profoundly difficult questions about what
kinds of persons to create and the degree to which deliberate human design
should replace “nature” in the creation of our offspring. A dramatic example of
new abilities to create offspring, though now limited to the animal realm, was
the cloning in Scotland in 1997 of a sheep from a single cell of an adult
sheep; this event raised the very controversial future prospect of cloning
human beings. Finally, new reproductive technologies, such as oocyte egg
donation, and practices such as surrogate motherhood, raise deep issues about
the meaning and nature of parenthood and families.
bit from binary digit, a
unit or measure of information. Suggested by John W. Tukey, a bit is both an
amount of information a reduction of eight equally likely possibilities to one
generates three bits [% log2 8] of information and a system of representing
that quantity. The binary system uses 1’s and 0’s.
black box, a hypothetical
unit specified only by functional role, in order to explain some effect or
behavior. The term may refer to a single entity with an unknown structure, or
unknown internal organization, which realizes some known function, or to any
one of a system of such entities, whose organization and functions are inferred
from the behavior of an organism or entity of which they are constituents.
Within behaviorism and classical learning theory, the basic functions were
taken to be generalized mechanisms governing the relationship of stimulus to
response, including reinforcement, inhibition, extinction, and arousal. The
organism was treated as a black box realizing these functions. Within
cybernetics, though there are no simple inputoutput rules describing the
organism, there is an emphasis on functional organization and feedback in controlling
behavior. The components within a cybernetic system are treated as black boxes.
In both cases, the details of underlying structure, mechanism, and dynamics are
either unknown or regarded as unimportant.
blindsight, a residual
visual capacity resulting from lesions in certain areas of the brain the
striate cortex, area 17. Under routine clinical testing, persons suffering such
lesions appear to be densely blind in particular regions of the visual field.
Researchers have long recognized that, in primates, comparable lesions do not
result in similar deficits. It has seemed unlikely that this disparity could be
due to differences in brain function, however. And, indeed, when human subjects
are tested in the way non-human subjects are tested, the disparity vanishes.
Although subjects report that they can detect nothing in the blind field, when
required to “guess” at properties of items situated there, they perform
remarkably well. They seem to “know” the contents of the blind field while
remaining unaware that they know, often expressing astonishment on being told
the results of testing in the blind field.
Bloch: e., philosopher, influenced
by Marxism, his views went beyond Marxism as he matured. He fled Germany in the
1930s, but returned after World War II to a professorship in East Germany,
where his increasingly unorthodox ideas were eventually censured by the
Communist authorities, forcing a move to West Germany in the 1960s. His major
work, The Principle of Hope 195459, is influenced by German idealism, Jewish
mysticism, Neoplatonism, utopianism, and numerous other sources besides
Marxism. Humans are essentially unfinished, moved by a cosmic impulse, “hope,”
a tendency in them to strive for the as-yet-unrealized, which manifests itself
as utopia, or vision of future possibilities. Despite his atheism, Bloch wished
to retrieve the sense of self-transcending that he saw in the religious and
mythical traditions of humankind. His ideas have consequently influenced
theology as well as philosophy, e.g. the “theology of hope” of Jurgen Moltmann.
R.H.K. Blondel, Maurice 18611949, French Christian philosopher who discovered
the deist background of human action. In his main work, Action 1893, 2d rev.
ed. 1950, Blondel held that action is part of the very nature of human beings
and as such becomes an object of philosophy; through philosophy, action should
find its meaning, i.e. realize itself rationally. An appropriate phenomenology
of action through phenomenological description uncovers the phenomenal level of
action but points beyond it. Such a supraphenomenal sense of action provides it
a metaphysical status. This phenomenology of action rests on an immanent
dialectics of action: a gap between the aim of the action and its realization.
This gap, while dissatisfying to the actor, also drives him toward new
activities. The only immanent solution of this dialectics and its consequences
is a transcendent one. We have to realize that we, like other humans, cannot
grasp our own activities and must accept our limitations and our finitude as
well as the insufficiency of our philosophy, which is now understood as a
philosophy of insufficiency and points toward the existence of the supernatural
element in every human act, namely God. Human activity is the outcome of divine
grace. Through action bit Blondel, Maurice 90
90 one touches the existence of God, something not possible by logical
argumentation. In the later phase of his development Blondel deserted his early
“anti-intellectualism” and stressed the close relation between thought and
action, now understood as inseparable and mutually interrelated. He came to see
philosophy as a rational instrument of understanding one’s actions as well as
one’s insufficiency.
Bodin, Jean c.152996,
French political philosopher whose philosophy centers on the concept of
sovereignty. His Six livres de la république 1577 defines a state as
constituted by common public interests, families, and the sovereign. The
sovereign is the lawgiver, who stands beyond the absolute rights he possesses;
he must, however, follow the law of God, natural law, and the constitution. The
ideal state was for Bodin a monarchy that uses aristocratic and democratic
structures of government for the sake of the common good. In order to achieve a
broader empirical picture of politics Bodin used historical comparisons. This
is methodologically reflected in his Methodus ad facilem historiarum
cognitionem 1566. Bodin was clearly a theorist of absolutism. As a member of
the Politique group he played a practical role in emancipating the state from
the church. His thinking was influenced by his experience of civil war. In his
Heptaplomeres posthumous he pleaded for tolerance with respect to all
religions, including Islam and Judaism. As a public prosecutor, however, he wrote
a manual for judges in witchcraft trials De la démonomanie des sorciers, 1580.
By stressing the peacemaking role of a strong state Bodin was a forerunner of
Hobbes.
boehme: j. protestant
speculative mystic. Influenced especially by Paracelsus, Boehme received little
formal education, but was successful enough as a shoemaker to devote himself to
his writing, explicating his religious experiences. He published little in his
lifetime, though enough to attract charges of heresy from local clergy. He did
gather followers, and his works were published after his death. His writings
are elaborately symbolic rather than argumentative, but respond deeply to
fundamental problems in the Christian worldview. He holds that the Godhead,
omnipotent will, is as nothing to us, since we can in no way grasp it. The
Mysterium Magnum, the ideal world, is conceived in God’s mind through an
impulse to selfrevelation. The actual world, separate from God, is created
through His will, and seeks to return to the peace of the Godhead. The world is
good, as God is, but its goodness falls away, and is restored at the end of
history, though not entirely, for some souls are damned eternally. Human beings
enjoy free will, and create themselves through rebirth in faith. The Fall is
necessary for the selfknowledge gained in recovery from it. Recognition of
one’s hidden, free self is a recognition of God manifested in the world, so
that human salvation completes God’s act of self-revelation. It is also a
recognition of evil rooted in the blind will underlying all individual
existence, without which there would be nothing except the Godhead. Boehme’s
works influenced Hegel and the later Schelling.
Boethius, Anicius Manlius
Severinus, Roman philosopher and Aristotelian translator and commentator. He
was born into a wealthy patrician family in Rome and had a distinguished
political career under the Ostrogothic king Theodoric before being arrested and
executed on charges of treason. His logic and philosophical theology contain
important contributions to the philosophy of the late classical and early
medieval periods, and his translations of and commentaries on Aristotle
profoundly influenced the history of philosophy, particularly in the medieval
Latin West. His most famous work, The Consolation of Philosophy, composed
during his imprisonment, is a moving reflection on the nature of human
happiness and the problem of evil and contains classic discussions of
providence, fate, chance, and the apparent incompatibility of divine
foreknowledge and human free choice. He was known during his own lifetime,
however, as a brilliant scholar whose knowledge of the Grecian language and
ancient Grecian philosophy set him apart from his Latin contemporaries. He
conceived his scholarly career as devoted to preserving and making accessible
to the Latin West the great philosophical achievement of ancient Greece. To
this end he announced an ambitious plan to translate into Latin and write
commenbodily continuity Boethius, Anicius Manlius Severinus 91 91 taries on all of Plato and Aristotle, but
it seems that he achieved this goal only for Aristotle’s Organon. His extant
translations include Porphyry’s Isagoge an introduction to Aristotle’s
Categories and Aristotle’s Categories, On Interpretation, Prior Analytics, Topics,
and Sophistical Refutations. He wrote two commentaries on the Isagoge and On
Interpretation and one on the Categories, and we have what appear to be his
notes for a commentary on the Prior Analytics. His translation of the Posterior
Analytics and his commentary on the Topics are lost. He also commented on
Cicero’s Topica and wrote his own treatises on logic, including De syllogismis
hypotheticis, De syllogismis categoricis, Introductio in categoricos
syllogismos, De divisione, and De topicis differentiis, in which he elaborates
and supplements Aristotelian logic. Boethius shared the common Neoplatonist
view that the Platonist and Aristotelian systems could be harmonized by
following Aristotle in logic and natural philosophy and Plato in metaphysics
and theology. This plan for harmonization rests on a distinction between two
kinds of forms: 1 forms that are conjoined with matter to constitute
bodies these, which he calls “images”
imagines, correspond to the forms in Aristotle’s hylomorphic account of corporeal
substances; and 2 forms that are pure and entirely separate from matter,
corresponding to Plato’s ontologically separate Forms. He calls these “true
forms” and “the forms themselves.” He holds that the former, “enmattered” forms
depend for their being on the latter, pure forms. Boethius takes these three
sorts of entities bodies, enmattered
forms, and separate forms to be the
respective objects of three different cognitive activities, which constitute
the three branches of speculative philosophy. Natural philosophy is concerned
with enmattered forms as enmattered, mathematics with enmattered forms
considered apart from their matter though they cannot be separated from matter
in actuality, and theology with the pure and separate forms. He thinks that the
mental abstraction characteristic of mathematics is important for understanding
the Peripatetic account of universals: the enmattered, particular forms found
in sensible things can be considered as universal when they are considered
apart from the matter in which they inhere though they cannot actually exist
apart from matter. But he stops short of endorsing this moderately realist
Aristotelian account of universals. His commitment to an ontology that includes
not just Aristotelian natural forms but also Platonist Forms existing apart
from matter implies a strong realist view of universals. With the exception of
De fide catholica, which is a straightforward credal statement, Boethius’s
theological treatises De Trinitate, Utrum Pater et Filius, Quomodo substantiae,
and Contra Euthychen et Nestorium show his commitment to using logic and
metaphysics, particularly the Aristotelian doctrines of the categories and
predicables, to clarify and resolve issues in Christian theology. De Trinitate,
e.g., includes a historically influential discussion of the Aristotelian
categories and the applicability of various kinds of predicates to God. Running
through these treatises is his view that predicates in the category of relation
are unique by virtue of not always requiring for their applicability an
ontological ground in the subjects to which they apply, a doctrine that gave
rise to the common medieval distinction between so-called real and non-real
relations. Regardless of the intrinsic significance of Boethius’s philosophical
ideas, he stands as a monumental figure in the history of medieval philosophy
rivaled in importance only by Aristotle and Augustine. Until the recovery of
the works of Aristotle in the mid-twelfth century, medieval philosophers
depended almost entirely on Boethius’s translations and commentaries for their
knowledge of pagan ancient philosophy, and his treatises on logic continued to
be influential throughout the Middle Ages. The preoccupation of early medieval
philosophers with logic and with the problem of universals in particular is due
largely to their having been tutored by Boethius and Boethius’s Aristotle. The
theological treatises also received wide attention in the Middle Ages, giving
rise to a commentary tradition extending from the ninth century through the
Renaissance and shaping discussion of central theological doctrines such as the
Trinity and Incarnation.
boltzmann, l., physicist
who was a spirited advocate of the atomic theory and a pioneer in developing
the kinetic theory of gases and statistical mechanics. Boltzmann’s most famous
achievements were the transport equation, the H-theorem, and the probabilistic
interpretation of entropy. This work is summarized in his Vorlesungen über
Gastheorie “Lectures on the Theory of Gases,” 189698. He held chairs in physics
at the universities of Graz, Vienna, Munich, and Leipzig before returning to
Vienna as professor of theoretical physics in 1902. In 1903 he succeeded Mach
at Boltzmann, Ludwig Boltzmann, Ludwig 92
92 Vienna and lectured on the philosophy of science. In the 1890s the
atomic-kinetic theory was attacked by Mach and by the energeticists led by
Wilhelm Ostwald. Boltzmann’s counterattack can be found in his Populäre
Schriften “Popular Writings,” 1905. Boltzmann agreed with his critics that many
of his mechanical models of gas molecules could not be true but, like Maxwell,
defended models as invaluable heuristic tools. Boltzmann also insisted that it
was futile to try to eliminate all metaphysical pictures from theories in favor
of bare equations. For Boltzmann, the goal of physics is not merely the
discovery of equations but the construction of a coherent picture of reality.
Boltzmann defended his H-theorem against the reversibility objection of
Loschmidt and the recurrence objection of Zermelo by conceding that a
spontaneous decrease in entropy was possible but extremely unlikely.
Boltzmann’s views that irreversibility depends on the probability of initial
conditions and that entropy increase determines the direction of time are defended
by Reichenbach in The Direction of Time 1956.
bolzano: b., philosopher.
He studied philosophy, mathematics, physics, and theology in Prague; received
the Ph.D.; was ordained a priest 1805; was appointed to a chair in religion at
Charles in 1806; and, owing to his
criticism of the Austrian constitution, was dismissed in 1819. He composed his
two main works from 1823 through 1841: the Wissenschaftslehre 4 vols., 1837 and
the posthumous Grössenlehre. His ontology and logical semantics influenced
Husserl and, indirectly, Lukasiewicz, Tarski, and others of the Warsaw School.
His conception of ethics and social philosophy affected both the cultural life
of Bohemia and the Austrian system of education. Bolzano recognized a profound
distinction between the actual thoughts and judgments Urteile of human beings,
their linguistic expressions, and the abstract propositions Sätze an sich and
their parts which exist independently of those thoughts, judgments, and
expressions. A proposition in Bolzano’s sense is a preexistent sequence of
ideas-as-such Vorstellungen an sich. Only propositions containing finite
ideas-as-such are accessible to the mind. Real things existing concretely in
space and time have subsistence Dasein whereas abstract objects such as
propositions have only logical existence. Adherences, i.e., forces, applied to
certain concrete substances give rise to subjective ideas, thoughts, or
judgments. A subjective idea is a part of a judgment that is not itself a
judgment. The set of judgments is ordered by a causal relation. Bolzano’s
abstract world is constituted of sets, ideas-as-such, certain properties
Beschaffenheiten, and objects constructed from these. Thus, sentence shapes are
a kind of ideas-as-such, and certain complexes of ideas-as-such constitute
propositions. Ideas-as-such can be generated from expressions of a language by
postulates for the relation of being an object of something. Analogously,
properties can be generated by postulates for the relation of something being
applied to an object. Bolzano’s notion of religion is based on his distinction
between propositions and judgments. His Lehrbuch der Religionswissenschaft 4
vols., 1834 distinguishes between religion in the objective and subjective
senses. The former is a set of religious propositions, whereas the latter is
the set of religious views of a single person. Hence, a subjective religion can
contain an objective one. By defining a religious proposition as being moral
and imperatives the rules of utilitarianism, Bolzano integrated his notion of
religion within his ontology. In the Grössenlehre Bolzano intended to give a
detailed, well-founded exposition of contemporary mathematics and also to
inaugurate new domains of research. Natural numbers are defined, half a century
before Frege, as properties of “bijective” sets the members of which can be put
in one-to-one correspondence, and real numbers are conceived as properties of
sets of certain infinite sequences of rational numbers. The analysis of
infinite sets brought him to reject the Euclidean doctrine that the whole is
always greater than any of its parts and, hence, to the insight that a set is
infinite if and only if it is bijective to a proper subset of itself. This
anticipates Peirce and Dedekind. Bolzano’s extension of the linear continuum of
finite numbers by infinitesimals implies a relatively constructive approach to
nonstandard analysis. In the development of standard analysis the most
remarkable result of the Grössenlehre is the anticipation of Weirstrass’s
discovery that there exist nowhere differentiable continuous functions. The
Wissenschaftslehre was intended to lay the logical and epistemological
foundations of Bolzano’s mathematics. A theory of science in Bolzano’s sense is
a collection of rules for delimiting the set of scientific textbooks. Whether a
Bolzano, Bernard Bolzano, Bernard 93 93
class of true propositions is a worthwhile object of representation in a
scientific textbook is an ethical question decidable on utilitarian principles.
Bolzano proceeded from an expanded and standardized ordinary language through
which he could describe propositions and their parts. He defined the semantic
notion of truth and introduced the function corresponding to a “replacement”
operation on propositions. One of his major achievements was his definition of
logical derivability logische Ableitbarkeit between sets of propositions: B is
logically derivable from A if and only if all elements of the sum of A and B
are simultaneously true for some replacement of their non-logical ideas-as-such
and if all elements of B are true for any such replacement that makes all
elements of A true. In addition to this notion, which is similar to Tarski’s
concept of consequence of 1936, Bolzano introduced a notion corresponding to
Gentzen’s concept of consequence. A proposition is universally valid
allgemeingültig if it is derivable from the null class. In his proof theory
Bolzano formulated counterparts to Gentzen’s cut rule. Bolzano introduced a
notion of inductive probability as a generalization of derivability in a
limited domain. This notion has the formal properties of conditional
probability. These features and Bolzano’s characterization of probability
density by the technique of variation are reminiscent of Wittgenstein’s
inductive logic and Carnap’s theory of regular confirmation functions. The
replacement of conceptual complexes in propositions would, if applied to a
formalized language, correspond closely to a substitutionsemantic conception of
quantification. His own philosophical language was based on a kind of free
logic. In essence, Bolzano characterized a substitution-semantic notion of
consequence with a finite number of antecedents. His quantification over
individual and general concepts amounts to the introduction of a non-elementary
logic of lowest order containing a quantification theory of predicate variables
but no set-theoretical principles such as choice axioms. His conception of
universal validity and of the semantic superstructure of logic leads to a
semantically adequate extension of the predicate-logical version of Lewis’s
system S5 of modal logic without paradoxes. It is also possible to simulate
Bolzano’s theory of probability in a substitution-semantically constructed
theory of probability functions. Hence, by means of an ontologically
parsimonious superstructure without possible-worlds metaphysics, Bolzano was
able to delimit essentially the realms of classical logical truth and additive
probability spaces. In geometry Bolzano created a new foundation from a
topological point of view. He defined the notion of an isolated point of a set
in a way reminiscent of the notion of a point at which a set is
well-dimensional in the sense of Urysohn and Menger. On this basis he
introduced his topological notion of a continuum and formulated a recursive
definition of the dimensionality of non-empty subsets of the Euclidean 3-space,
which is closely related to the inductive dimension concept of Urysohn and
Menger. In a remarkable paragraph of an unfinished late manuscript on geometry
he stated the celebrated curve theorem of Jordan.
Bonaventure, Saint
c.122174, Italian theologian. Born John of Fidanza in Bagnorea, Tuscany, he was
educated at Paris, earning a master’s degree in arts and a doctorate in
theology. He joined the Franciscans about 1243, while still a student, and was
elected minister general of the order in 1257. Made cardinal bishop of Albano
by Pope Gregory X in 1274, Bonaventure helped organize the Second Ecumenical
Council of Lyons, during the course of which he died, in July 1274. He was
canonized in 1482 and named a doctor of the church in 1587. Bonaventure wrote
and preached extensively on the relation between philosophy and theology, the
role of reason in spiritual and religious life, and the extent to which
knowledge in God is obtainable by the “wayfarer.” His basic position is nicely
expressed in De reductione artium ad theologiam “On the Reduction of the Arts
to Theology”: “the manifold wisdom of God, which is clearly revealed in sacred
scripture, lies hidden in all knowledge and in all nature.” He adds, “all
divisions of knowledge are handmaids of theology.” But he is critical of those
theologians who wish to sever the connection between faith and reason. As he
argues in another famous work, Itinerarium mentis ad deum “The Mind’s Journey
unto God,” 1259, “since, relative to our life on earth, the world is itself a
ladder for ascending to God, we find here certain traces, certain images” of
the divine hand, in which God himself is mirrored. Although Bonaventure’s own
philosophical outlook is Augustinian, he was also influenced by Aristotle,
whose newly available works he both read and appreciated. Thus, while
upholdBonaventure, Saint Bonaventure, Saint 94
94 ing the Aristotelian ideas that knowledge of the external world is based
on the senses and that the mind comes into existence as a tabula rasa, he also
contends that divine illumination is necessary to explain both the acquisition
of universal concepts from sense images, and the certainty of intellectual
judgment. His own illuminationist epistemology seeks a middle ground between,
on the one hand, those who maintain that the eternal light is the sole reason
for human knowing, providing the human intellect with its archetypal and
intelligible objects, and, on the other, those holding that the eternal light
merely influences human knowing, helping guide it toward truth. He holds that
our intellect has certain knowledge when stable; eternal archetypes are
“contuited by us [a nobis contuita],” together with intelligible species produced
by its own fallible powers. In metaphysics, Bonaventure defends exemplarism,
the doctrine that all creation is patterned after exemplar causes or ideas in
the mind of God. Like Aquinas, but unlike Duns Scotus, he argues that it is
through such ideas that God knows all creatures. He also adopts the
emanationist principle that creation proceeds from God’s goodness, which is
self-diffusive, but differs from other emanationists, such as al-Farabi,
Avicenna, and Averroes, in arguing that divine emanation is neither necessary
nor indirect i.e., accomplished by secondary agents or intelligences. Indeed,
he sees the views of these Islamic philosophers as typical of the errors bound
to follow once Aristotelian rationalism is taken to its extreme. He is also well
known for his anti-Aristotelian argument that the eternity of the world something even Aquinas following Maimonides
concedes as a theoretical possibility is
demonstrably false. Bonaventure also subscribes to several other doctrines
characteristic of medieval Augustinianism: universal hylomorphism, the thesis,
defended by Ibn Gabirol and Avicenna among others, that everything other than
God is composed of matter and form; the plurality of forms, the view that
subjects and predicates in the category of substance are ordered in terms of
their metaphysical priority; and the ontological view of truth, according to
which truth is a kind of rightness perceived by the mind. In a similar vein,
Bonaventure argues that knowledge ultimately consists in perceiving truth
directly, without argument or demonstration. Bonaventure also wrote several
classic works in the tradition of mystical theology. His bestknown and most
popular mystical work is the aforementioned Itinerarium, written in 1259 on a
pilgrimage to La Verna, during which he beheld the six-winged seraph that had
also appeared to Francis of Assisi when Francis received the stigmata.
Bonaventure outlines a seven-stage spiritual journey, in which our mind moves
from first considering God’s traces in the perfections of irrational creatures,
to a final state of peaceful repose, in which our affections are “transferred
and transformed into God.” Central to his writings on spiritual life is the
theme of the “three ways”: the purgative way, inspired by conscience, which
expels sin; the illuminative way, inspired by the intellect, which imitates
Christ; and the unitive way, inspired by wisdom, which unites us to God through
love. Bonaventure’s writings most immediately influenced the work of other
medieval Augustinians, such as Matthew of Aquasparta and John Peckham, and
later, followers of Duns Scotus. But his modern reputation rests on his
profound contributions to philosophical theology, Franciscan spirituality, and
mystical thought, in all three of which he remains an authoritative
source.
book of life, expression
found in Hebrew and Christian scriptures signifying a record kept by the Lord
of those destined for eternal happiness Exodus 32:32; Psalms 68; Malachi 3:16;
Daniel 12:1; Philippians 4:3; Revelation 3:5, 17:8, 20:12, 21:27. Medieval
philosophers often referred to the book of life when discussing issues of
predestination, divine omniscience, foreknowledge, and free will. Figures like
Augustine and Aquinas asked whether it represented God’s unerring foreknowledge
or predestination, or whether some names could be added or deleted from it. The
term is used by some contemporary philosophers to mean a record of all the
events in a person’s life.
Boolean algebra, 1 an
ordered triple B,†,3, where B is a set containing at least two elements and †
and 3 are unary and binary operations in B such that i a 3 b % b 3 a, ii a 3 b
3 c % a 3 b 3 c, iii a 3 † a % b 3 † b, and iv a 3 b = a if and only if a 3 † b
% a 3 † a; 2 the theboo-hurrah theory Boolean algebra 95 95 ory of such algebras. Such structures are
modern descendants of algebras published by the mathematician G. Boole in 1847
and representing the first successful algebraic treatment of logic.
Interpreting † and 3 as negation and conjunction, respectively, makes Boolean
algebra a calculus of propositions. Likewise, if B % {T,F} and † and 3 are the
truth-functions for negation and conjunction, then B,†,3 the truth table for those two connectives forms a two-element Boolean algebra.
Picturing a Boolean algebra is simple. B,†,3 is a full subset algebra if B is
the set of all subsets of a given set and † and 3 are set complementation and
intersection, respectively. Then every finite Boolean algebra is isomorphic to
a full subset algebra, while every infinite Boolean algebra is isomorphic to a
subalgebra of such an algebra. It is for this reason that Boolean algebra is
often characterized as the calculus of classes.
borderline case, in the
logical sense, a case that falls within the “gray area” or “twilight zone” associated
with a vague concept; in the pragmatic sense, a doubtful, disputed, or arguable
case. These two senses are not mutually exclusive, of course. A moment of time
near sunrise or sunset may be a borderline case of daytime or nighttime in the
logical sense, but not in the pragmatic sense. A sufficiently freshly
fertilized ovum may be a borderline case of a person in both senses. Fermat’s
hypothesis, or any of a large number of other disputed mathematical
propositions, may be a borderline case in the pragmatic sense but not in the
logical sense. A borderline case per se in either sense need not be a limiting
case or a degenerate case.
bosanquet: b.: Cited by H. P. Grice. English philosopher,
the most systematic Oxford absolute idealist and, with F. H. Bradley, the
leading Oxford defender of absolute idealism. Although he derived his last name
from Huguenot ancestors, Bosanquet was thoroughly English. Born at Altwick and
educated at Harrow and Balliol, Oxford, he was for eleven years a fellow
of University College, Oxford. The death
of his father in 1880 and the resulting inheritance enabled Bosanquet to leave
Oxford for London and a career as a writer and social activist. While writing,
he taught courses for the London Ethical Society’s Center for Extension and donated time to the Charity
Organization Society. In 1895 he married his coworker in the Charity
Organization Society, Helen Dendy, who was also the translator of Christoph
Sigwart’s Logic. Bosanquet was professor of moral philosophy at St. Andrews
from 1903 to 1908. He gave the Gifford Lectures in 1911 and 1912. Otherwise he
lived in London until his death. Bosanquet’s most comprehensive work, his
two-volume Gifford Lectures, The Principle of Individuality and Value and The
Value and Destiny of the Individual, covers most aspects of his philosophy. In
The Principle of Individuality and Value he argues that the search for truth
proceeds by eliminating contradictions in experience. For Bosanquet a
contradiction arises when there are incompatible interpretations of the same
fact. This involves making distinctions that harmonize the incompatible
interpretations in a larger body of knowledge. Bosanquet thought there was no
way to arrest this process short of recognizing that all human experience forms
a comprehensive whole which is reality. Bosanquet called this totality “the
Absolute.” Just as conflicting interpretations of the same fact find harmonious
places in the Absolute, so conflicting desires are also included. The Absolute
thus satisfies all desires and provides Bosanquet’s standard for evaluating
other objects. This is because in his view the value of an object is determined
by its ability to satisfy desires. From this Bosanquet concluded that human
beings, as fragments of the Absolute, acquire greater value as they realize
themselves by partaking more fully in the Absolute. In The Value and Destiny of
the Individual Bosanquet explained how human beings could do this. As finite,
human beings face obstacles they cannot overcome; yet they desire the good
i.e., the Absolute which for Bosanquet overcomes all obstacles and satisfies
all desires. Humans can best realize a desire for the good, Bosanquet thinks,
by surrendering their private desires for the sake of the good. This attitude
of surrender, which Bosanquet calls the religious consciousness, relates human
beings to what is permanently valuable in reality and increases their own value
and satisfaction accordingly. Bosanquet’s defense of this metaphysical vision
rests heavily on his first major work, Logic or the Morphology of Knowledge
1888; 2d ed., 1911. As the subtitle indicates, Bosanquet took the subject
matter of Logic to be the structure of knowledge. Like Hegel, who was in many
ways his inspiration, Bosanquet thought that the nature of knowledge was
defined by structures repeated in different parts of knowledge. He called these
structures forms of judgment and tried to show that simple judgments are
dependent on increasingly complex ones and finally on an all-inclusive judgment
that defines reality. For example, the simplest element of knowledge is a
demonstrative judgment like “This is hot.” But making such a judgment
presupposes understanding the contrast between ‘this’ and ‘that’. Demonstrative
judgments thus depend on comparative judgments like “This is hotter than that.”
Since these judgments are less dependent on other judgments, they more fully
embody human knowledge. Bosanquet claimed that the series of increasingly
complex judgments are not arranged in a simple linear order but develop along
different branches finally uniting in disjunctive judgments that attribute to
reality an exhaustive set of mutually exclusive alternatives which are
themselves judgments. When one contained judgment is asserted on the basis of
another, a judgment containing both is an inference. For Bosanquet inferences
are mediated judgments that assert their conclusions based on grounds. When
these grounds are made fully explicit in a judgment containing them, that
judgment embodies the nature of inference: that one must accept the conclusion
or reject the whole of knowledge. Since for Bosanquet the difference between
any judgment and the reality it represents is that a judgment is composed of
ideas that abstract from reality, a fully comprehensive judgment includes all
aspects of reality. It is thus identical to reality. By locating all judgments
within this one, Bosanquet claimed to have described the morphology of
knowledge as well as to have shown that thought is identical to reality.
Bosanquet removed an objection to this identification in History of Aesthetics
1892, where he traces the development of the philosophy of the beautiful from
its inception through absolute idealism. According to Plato and Aristotle
beauty is found in imitations of reality, while in objective idealism it is
reality in sensuous form. Drawing heavily on Kant, Bosanquet saw this process
as an overcoming of the opposition between sense and reason by showing how a
pleasurable feeling can partake of reason. He thought that absolute idealism
explained this by showing that we experience objects as beautiful because their
sensible qualities exhibit the unifying activity of reason. Bosanquet treated
the political implications of absolute idealism in his Philosophical Theory of
the State 1898; 3d ed., 1920, where he argues that humans achieve their ends
only in communities. According to Bosanquet, all humans rationally will their
own ends. Because their ends differ from moment to moment, the ends they
rationally will are those that harmonize their desires at particular moments.
Similarly, because the ends of different individuals overlap and conflict, what
they rationally will are ends that harmonize their desires, which are the ends
of humans in communities. They are willed by the general will, the realization
of which is self-rule or liberty. This provides the rational ground of
political obligation, since the most comprehensive system of modern life is the
state, the end of which is the realization of the best life for its citizens.
Boscovich, Roger Joseph,
or Rudjer Josip Bos v kovic’, philosopher. Born of Serbian and Italian parents,
he was a Jesuit and polymath best known for his A Theory of Natural Philosophy
Reduced to a Single Law of the Actions Existing in Nature. This work attempts
to explain all physical phenomena in terms of the attractions and repulsions of
point particles puncta that are indistinguishable in their intrinsic
qualitative properties. According to Boscovich’s single law, puncta at a
certain distance attract, until upon approaching one another they reach a point
at which they repel, and eventually reach equilibrium. Thus, Boscovich defends
a form of dynamism, or the theory that nature is to be understood in terms of
force and not mass where forces are functions of time and distance. By
dispensing with extended substance, Boscovich avoided epistemological
difficulties facing Locke’s natural philosophy and anticipated developments in
modern physics. Among those influenced by Boscovich were Kant who defended a
version of dynamism, Faraday, James Clerk Maxwell, and Lord Kelvin. Boscovich’s
theory has proved to be empirically inadequate to account for phenomena such as
light. A philosophical difficulty for Boscovich’s puncta, which are physical
substances, arises out of their zero-dimensionality. It is plausible that any
power must have a basis in an object’s intrinsic properties, and puncta appear
to lack such support for their powers. However, it is extensional properties
that puncta lack, and Boscovich could argue that the categorial property of
being an unextended spatial substance provides the needed basis.
Bouwsma, Oets Kolk, philosopher,
a practitioner of ordinary language philosophy and celebrated teacher. Through
work on Moore and contact with students such as Norman Malcolm and Morris
Lazerowitz, whom he sent from Nebraska to work with Moore, Bouwsma discovered
Wittgenstein. He became known for conveying an understanding of Wittgenstein’s
techniques of philosophical analysis through his own often humorous grasp of
sense and nonsense. Focusing on a particular pivotal sentence in an argument,
he provided imaginative surroundings for it, showing how, in the philosopher’s
mouth, the sentence lacked sense. He sometimes described this as “the method of
failure.” In connection with Descartes’s evil genius, e.g., Bouwsma invents an
elaborate story in which the evil genius tries but fails to permanently deceive
by means of a totally paper world. Our inability to imagine such a deception
undermines the sense of the evil genius argument. His writings are replete with
similar stories, analogies, and teases of sense and nonsense for such
philosophical standards as Berkeley’s idealism, Moore’s theory of sensedata,
and Anselm’s ontological argument. Bouwsma did not advocate theories nor put
forward refutations of other philosophers’ views. His talent lay rather in
exposing some central sentence in an argument as disguised nonsense. In this,
he went beyond Wittgenstein, working out the details of the latter’s insights
into language. In addition to this appropriation of Wittgenstein, Bouwsma also
appropriated Kierkegaard, understanding him too as one who dispelled
philosophical illusions those arising
from the attempt to understand Christianity. The ordinary language of religious
philosophy was that of scriptures. He drew upon this language in his many
essays on religious themes. His religious dimension made whole this person who
gave no quarter to traditional metaphysics. His papers are published under the
titles Philosophical Essays, Toward a New Sensibility, Without Proof or
Evidence, and Wittgenstein Conversations 194951. His philosophical notebooks
are housed at the Humanities Research Center in Austin, Texas.
Boyle, Robert 162791,
British chemist and physicist who was a major figure in seventeenthcentury
natural philosophy. To his contemporaries he was “the restorer” in England of
the mechanical philosophy. His program was to replace the vacuous explanations
characteristic of Peripateticism the “quality of whiteness” in snow explains why
it dazzles the eyes by explanations employing the “two grand and most catholic
principles of bodies, matter and motion,” matter being composed of corpuscles,
with motion “the grand agent of all that happens in nature.” Boyle wrote
influentially on scientific methodology, emphasizing experimentation a Baconian
influence, experimental precision, and the importance of devising “good and
excellent” hypotheses. The dispute with Spinoza on the validation of
explanatory hypotheses contrasted Boyle’s experimental way with Spinoza’s way
of rational analysis. The 1670s dispute with Henry More on the ontological
grounds of corporeal activity confronted More’s “Spirit of Nature” with the
“essential modifications” motion and the “seminal principle” of activity with
which Boyle claimed God had directly endowed matter. As a champion of the
corpuscularian philosophy, Boyle was an important link in the development
before Locke of the distinction between primary and secondary qualities. A
leading advocate of natural theology, he provided in his will for the
establishment of the Boyle Lectures to defend Protestant Christianity against
atheism and materialism.
Bradley: f. h., the most
original and influential nineteenth-century British idealist. Born at Clapham,
he was the fourth son of an evangelical minister. His younger brother A. C.
Bradley was a well-known Shakespearean critic. From 1870 until his death
Bradley was a fellow of Merton , Oxford. A kidney ailment, which first occurred
in 1871, compelled him to lead a retiring life. This, combined with his
forceful literary style, his love of irony, the dedication of three of his
books to an unknown woman, and acclaim as the greatest British idealist since
Berkeley, has lent an aura of mystery to his personal life. The aim of Bradley’s
first important work, Ethical Studies 1876, is not to offer guidance for
dealing with practical moral problems Bradley condemned this as casuistry, but
rather to explain what makes morality as embodied in the consciousness of
individuals and in social institutions possible. Bradley thought it was the
fact that moral agents take morality as an end in itself which involves
identifying their wills with an ideal provided in part by their stations in society
and then transferring that ideal to reality through action. Bradley called this
process “selfrealization.” He thought that moral agents could realize their
good selves only by suppressing their bad selves, from which he concluded that
morality could never be completely realized, since realizing a good self
requires having a bad one. For this reason Bradley believed that the moral
consciousness would develop into religious consciousness which, in his
secularized version of Christianity, required dying to one’s natural self
through faith in the actual existence of the moral ideal. In Ethical Studies
Bradley admitted that a full defense of his ethics would require a metaphysical
system, something he did not then have. Much of Bradley’s remaining work was an
attempt to provide the outline of such a system by solving what he called “the
great problem of the relation between thought and reality.” He first confronted
this problem in The Principles of Logic1883, which is his description of
thought. He took thought to be embodied in judgments, which are distinguished
from other mental activities by being true or false. This is made possible by
the fact that their contents, which Bradley called ideas, represent reality. A
problem arises because ideas are universals and so represent kinds of things,
while the things themselves are all individuals. Bradley solves this problem by
distinguishing between the logical and grammatical forms of a judgment and
arguing that all judgments have the logical form of conditionals. They assert
that universal connections between qualities obtain in reality. The qualities
are universals, the connections between them are conditional, while reality is
one individual whole that we have contact with in immediate experience. All
judgments, in his view, are abstractions from a diverse but non-relational
immediate experience. Since judgments are inescapably relational, they fail to
represent accurately non-relational reality and so fail to reach truth, which
is the goal of thought. From this Bradley concluded that, contrary to what some
of his more Hegelian contemporaries were saying, thought is not identical to
reality and is never more than partially true. Appearance and Reality 1893 is
Bradley’s description of reality: it is experience, all of it, all at once,
blended in a harmonious way. Bradley defended this view by means of his
criterion for reality. Reality, he proclaimed, does not contradict itself;
anything that does is merely appearance. In Part I of Appearance and Reality
Bradley relied on an infinite regress argument, now called Bradley’s regress,
to contend that relations and all relational phenomena, including thought, are
contradictory. They are appearance, not reality. In Part II he claimed that
appearances are contradictory because they are abstracted by thought from the
immediate experience of which they are a part. Appearances constitute the
content of this whole, which in Bradley’s view is experience. In other words,
reality is experience in its totality. Bradley called this unified, consistent
all-inclusive reality “the Absolute.” Today Bradley is mainly remembered for
his argument against the reality of relations, and as the philosopher who
provoked Russell’s and Moore’s revolution in philosophy. He would be better
remembered as a founder of twentiethcentury philosophy who based metaphysical
conclusions on his account of the logical forms of judgments.
Brahman, in Hinduism, the
ultimate reality, possessed of being, consciousness, and bliss, dependent on
nothing else for existence. Brahman is conceived as a personal deity Brahma in
Vis’istadvaita and Dvaita Vedanta and as apersonal and qualityless in Advaita
Vedanta, in which “being, consciousness, and bliss” are interpreted negatively.
While Brahman is conceived as saguna or “with qualities” in Vis’istadvaita and
Dvaita, for Advaita Brahman is nirguna or qualityless. For Vis’istadvaita,
‘Brahman’ secondarily refers to the world dependent on Brahman strictly so
called, namely all minds and material things that constitute Brahman’s body.
For Advaita, each apparently individual mind or other thing is identical to
Brahman; Dvaita does not construe the world, or anything else, as Brahman’s
body. Enlightenment, or moksha, with its consequent escape from the cycle of
rebirths, for Advaita involves recognizing one’s identity with nirguna Brahman,
and for Dvaita and Vis’istadvaita involves repenting and forsaking one’s sins
and trusting a gracious Brahman for salvation.
brandt: Richard B., moral
philosopher, most closely associated with rule utilitarianism which term he
coined, earned degrees from Denison and
Cambridge , and obtained a Ph.D. from Yale in 1936. He taught at
Swarthmore from 1937 to 1964 and at
the of Michigan from 1964 to 1981. His
six books and nearly one hundred articles included work on philosophy of
religion, epistemology, philosophy of mind, philosophy of action, political
philosophy, and philosophy of law. His greatest contributions were in moral
philosophy. He first defended rule utilitarianism in his textbook Ethical
Theory 1959, but greatly refined his view in the 1960s in a series of articles,
which were widely discussed and reprinted and eventually collected together in
Morality, Utilitarianism, and Rights 1992. Further refinements appear in his A
Theory of the Good and the Right 1979 and Facts, Values, and Morality 1996.
Brandt famously argued for a “reforming definition” of ‘rational person’. He
proposed that we use it to designate someone whose desires would survive
exposure to all relevant empirical facts and to correct logical reasoning. He
also proposed a “reforming definition” of ‘morally right’ that assigns it the
descriptive meaning ‘would be permitted by any moral code that all or nearly
all rational people would publicly favor for the agent’s society if they
expected to spend a lifetime in that society’. In his view, rational choice
between moral codes is determined not by prior moral commitments but by
expected consequences. Brandt admitted that different rational people may favor
different codes, since different rational people may have different levels of
natural benevolence. But he also contended that most rational people would
favor a rule-utilitarian code.
Brentano, Franz: philosopher,
one of the most intellectually influential and personally charismatic of his
time. He is known especially for his distinction between psychological and
physical phenomena on the basis of intentionality or internal
object-directedness of thought, his revival of Aristotelianism and empirical
methods in philosophy and psychology, and his value theory and ethics supported
by the concept of correct pro- and anti-emotions or love and hate attitudes.
Brentano made noted contributions to the theory of metaphysical categories,
phenomenology, epistemology, syllogistic logic, and philosophy of religion. His
teaching made a profound impact on his students in Würzburg and Vienna, many of
whom became internationally respected thinkers in their fields, including
Meinong, Husserl, Twardowski, Christian von Ehrenfels, Anton Marty, and Freud.
Brentano began his study of philosophy at the Aschaffenburg Royal Bavarian
Gymnasium; in 185658 he attended the universities of Munich and Würzburg, and
then enrolled at the of Berlin, where he
undertook his first investigations of Aristotle’s metaphysics under the
supervision of F. A. Trendelenburg. In 1859 60, he attended the Academy in
Münster, reading intensively in the medieval Aristotelians; in 1862 he received
the doctorate in philosophy in absentia from the of Tübingen. He was ordained a Catholic priest
in 1864, and was later involved in a controversy over the doctrine of papal
infallibility, eventually leaving the church in 1873. He taught first as
Privatdozent in the Philosophical Faculty of the of Würzburg 186674, and then accepted a
professorship at the of Vienna. In 1880
he decided to marry, temporarily resigning his position to acquire Saxon
citizenship, in order to avoid legal difficulties in Austria, where marriages
of former priests were not officially recognized. Brentano was promised
restoration of his position after his circumvention of these restrictions, but
although he was later reinstated as lecturer, his appeals for reappointment as
professor were answered only with delay and equivocation. He left Vienna in
1895, retiring to Italy, his family’s country of origin. At last he moved to
Zürich, Switzerland, shortly before Italy entered World War I. Here he remained
active both in philosophy and psychology, despite his ensuing blindness,
writing and revising numerous books and articles, frequently meeting with
former students and colleagues, and maintaining an extensive
philosophical-literary correspondence, until his death. In Psychologie vom
empirischen Standpunkt “Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint,” 1874,
Brentano argued that intentionality is the mark of the mental, that every
psychological experience contains an intended object also called an intentional object which the thought is about or toward which
the thought is directed. Thus, in desire, something is desired. According to
the immanent intentionality thesis, this means that the desired object is
literally contained within the psychological experience of desire. Brentano
claims that this is uniquely true of mental as opposed to physical or
non-psychological phenomena, so that the intentionality of the psychological
distinguishes mental from physical states. The immanent intentionality thesis
proBrentano, Franz Brentano, Franz 100
100 vides a framework in which Brentano identifies three categories of
psychological phenomena: thoughts Vorstellungen, judgments, and emotive
phenomena. He further maintains that every thought is also self-consciously
reflected back onto itself as a secondary intended object in what he called the
eigentümliche Verfleckung. From 1905 through 1911, with the publication in that
year of Von der Klassifikation der psychischen Phänomene, Brentano gradually
abandoned the immanent intentionality thesis in favor of his later philosophy
of reism, according to which only individuals exist, excluding putative
nonexistent irrealia, such as lacks, absences, and mere possibilities. In the
meantime, his students Twardowski, Meinong, and Husserl, reacting negatively to
the idealism, psychologism, and related philosophical problems apparent in the
early immanent intentionality thesis, developed alternative non-immanence
approaches to intentionality, leading, in the case of Twardowski and Meinong
and his students in the Graz school of phenomenological psychology, to the
construction of Gegenstandstheorie, the theory of transcendent existent and
nonexistent intended objects, and to Husserl’s later transcendental
phenomenology. The intentionality of the mental in Brentano’s revival of the
medieval Aristotelian doctrine is one of his most important contributions to
contemporary non-mechanistic theories of mind, meaning, and expression.
Brentano’s immanent intentionality thesis was, however, rejected by
philosophers who otherwise agreed with his underlying claim that thought is
essentially object-directed. Brentano’s value theory Werttheorie offers a
pluralistic account of value, permitting many different kinds of things to be
valuable although, in keeping with his
later reism, he denies the existence of an abstract realm of values. Intrinsic
value is objective rather than subjective, in the sense that he believes the
pro- and anti-emotions we may have toward an act or situation are objectively
correct if they present themselves to emotional preference with the same
apodicity or unquestionable sense of rightness as other selfevident matters of
non-ethical judgment. Among the controversial consequences of Brentano’s value
theory is the conclusion that there can be no such thing as absolute evil. The
implication follows from Brentano’s observation, first, that evil requires evil
consciousness, and that consciousness of any kind, even the worst imaginable
malice or malevolent ill will, is considered merely as consciousness
intrinsically good. This means that necessarily there is always a mixture of
intrinsic good even in the most malicious possible states of mind, by virtue
alone of being consciously experienced, so that pure evil never obtains.
Brentano’s value theory admits of no defense against those who happen not to
share the same “correct” emotional attitudes toward the situations he
describes. If it is objected that to another person’s emotional preferences
only good consciousness is intrinsically good, while infinitely bad
consciousness despite being a state of consciousness appears instead to contain
no intrinsic good and is absolutely evil, there is no recourse within
Brentano’s ethics except to acknowledge that this contrary emotive attitude
toward infinitely bad consciousness may also be correct, even though it
contradicts his evaluations. Brentano’s empirical psychology and articulation
of the intentionality thesis, his moral philosophy and value theory, his
investigations of Aristotle’s metaphysics at a time when Aristotelian realism
was little appreciated in the prevailing climate of post-Kantian idealism, his
epistemic theory of evident judgment, his suggestions for the reform of
syllogistic logic, his treatment of the principle of sufficient reason and
existence of God, his interpretation of a fourstage cycle of successive trends
in the history of philosophy, together with his teaching and personal moral example,
continue to inspire a variety of divergent philosophical traditions.
broad: cited by H. P.
Grice in “Personal identity” and “Prolegomena” (re: Benjamin on Broad on
remembering). Charlie Dunbar 18871971, English epistemologist, metaphysician,
moral philosopher, and philosopher of science. He was educated at Trinity ,
Cambridge, taught at several universities in Scotland, and then returned to
Trinity, first as lecturer in moral science and eventually as Knightbridge
Professor of Moral Philosophy. His philosophical views are in the broadly
realist tradition of Moore and Russell, though with substantial influence also
from his teachers at Cambridge, McTaggart and W. E. Johnson. Broad wrote
voluminously and incisively on an extremely wide range of philosophical topics,
including most prominently the nature of perception, a priori knowledge and
concepts, the problem of induction, the mind Brentano’s thesis Broad, Charlie
Dunbar 101 101 body problem, the free
will problem, various topics in moral philosophy, the nature and philosophical
significance of psychical research, the nature of philosophy itself, and
various historical figures such as Leibniz, Kant, and McTaggart. Broad’s work
in the philosophy of perception centers on the nature of sense-data or sensa,
as he calls them and their relation to physical objects. He defends a rather
cautious, tentative version of the causal theory of perception. With regard to
a priori knowledge, Broad rejects the empiricist view that all such knowledge
is of analytic propositions, claiming instead that reason can intuit necessary
and universal connections between properties or characteristics; his view of
concept acquisition is that while most concepts are abstracted from experience,
some are a priori, though not necessarily innate. Broad holds that the
rationality of inductive inference depends on a further general premise about
the world, a more complicated version of the thesis that nature is uniform,
which is difficult to state precisely and even more difficult to justify.
Broad’s view of the mindbody problem is a version of dualism, though one that
places primary emphasis on individual mental events, is much more uncertain
about the existence and nature of the mind as a substance, and is quite
sympathetic to epiphenomenalism. His main contribution to the free will problem
consists in an elaborate analysis of the libertarian conception of freedom,
which he holds to be both impossible to realize and at the same time quite
possibly an essential precondition of the ordinary conception of obligation.
Broad’s work in ethics is diverse and difficult to summarize, but much of it
centers on the issue of whether ethical judgments are genuinely cognitive in
character. Broad was one of the few philosophers to take psychical research
seriously. He served as president of the Society for Psychical Research and was
an occasional observer of experiments in this area. His philosophical writings
on this subject, while not uncritical, are in the main sympathetic and are
largely concerned to defend concepts like precognition against charges of
incoherence and also to draw out their implications for more familiar
philosophical issues. As regards the nature of philosophy, Broad distinguishes
between “critical” and “speculative” philosophy. Critical philosophy is
analysis of the basic concepts of ordinary life and of science, roughly in the
tradition of Moore and Russell. A very high proportion of Broad’s own work
consists of such analyses, often amazingly detailed and meticulous in
character. But he is also sympathetic to the speculative attempt to arrive at
an overall conception of the nature of the universe and the position of human
beings therein, while at the same time expressing doubts that anything even
remotely approaching demonstration is possible in such endeavors. The foregoing
catalog of views reveals something of the range of Broad’s philosophical
thought, but it fails to bring out what is most strikingly valuable about it.
Broad’s positions on various issues do not form anything like a system he
himself is reported to have said that there is nothing that answers to the
description “Broad’s philosophy”. While his views are invariably subtle,
thoughtful, and critically penetrating, they rarely have the sort of one-sided
novelty that has come to be so highly valued in philosophy. What they do have
is exceptional clarity, dialectical insight, and even-handedness. Broad’s skill
at uncovering and displaying the precise shape of a philosophical issue,
clarifying the relevant arguments and objections, and cataloging in detail the
merits and demerits of the opposing positions has rarely been equaled. One who
seeks a clear-cut resolution of an issue is likely to be impatient and
disappointed with Broad’s careful, measured discussions, in which unusual
effort is made to accord all positions and arguments their due. But one who
seeks a comprehensive and balanced understanding of the issue in question is
unlikely to find a more trustworthy guide.
brouwer, L. E. J: philosopher
and founder of the intuitionist school in the philosophy of mathematics.
Educated at the Municipal of Amsterdam,
where he received his doctorate in 1907, he remained there for his entire
professional career, as Privaat-Docent 190912 and then professor 191255. He was
among the preeminent topologists of his time, proving several important
results. Philosophically, he was also unique in his strongly held conviction
that philosophical ideas and arguments concerning the nature of mathematics
ought to affect and be reflected in its practice. His general orientation in
the philosophy of mathematics was Kantian. This was manifested in his radical
critique of the role accorded to logical reasoning by classical mathematics; a
role that Brouwer, following Kant, believed to be incompatible with the role
that intuition must properly play in mathematical reasoning. The bestknown, if
not the most fundamental, part of his Brouwer, Luitzgen Egbertus Jan Brouwer,
Luitzgen Egbertus Jan 102 102 critique
of the role accorded to logic by classical mathematics was his attack on the
principle of the excluded middle and related principles of classical logic. He
challenged their reliability, arguing that their unrestricted use leads to
results that, intuitionistically speaking, are not true. However, in its
fundaments, Brouwer’s critique was not so much an attack on particular
principles of classical logic as a criticism of the general role that classical
mathematics grants to logical reasoning. He believed that logical structure and
hence logical inference is a product of the linguistic representation of
mathematical thought and not a feature of that thought itself. He stated this
view in the so-called First Act of Intuitionism, which contains not only the
chief critical idea of Brouwer’s position, but also its core positive element.
This positive element says, with Kant, that mathematics is an essentially
languageless activity of the mind. Brouwer went on to say something with which
Kant would only have partially agreed: that this activity has its origin in the
perception of a move of time. The critical element complements this by saying
that mathematics is thus to be kept wholly distinct from mathematical language
and the phenomena of language described by logic. The so-called Second Act of
Intuitionism then extends the positive part of the First Act by stating that
the “self-unfolding” of the primordial intuition of a move of time is the basis
not only of the construction of the natural numbers but also of the
intuitionistic continuum. Together, these two ideas form the basis of Brouwer’s
philosophy of mathematics a philosophy
that is radically at odds with most of twentieth-century philosophy of
mathematics.
bruno, giordano, speculative
philosopher. He was born in Naples, where he entered the Dominican order in
1565. In 1576 he was suspected of heresy and abandoned his order. He studied
and taught in Geneva, but left because of difficulties with the Calvinists.
Thereafter he studied and taught in Toulouse, Paris, England, various German
universities, and Prague. In 1591 he rashly returned to Venice, and was
arrested by the Venetian Inquisition in 1592. In 1593 he was handed over to the
Roman Inquisition, which burned him to death as a heretic. Because of his
unhappy end, his support for the Copernican heliocentric hypothesis, and his
pronounced anti-Aristotelianism, Bruno has been mistakenly seen as the
proponent of a scientific worldview against medieval obscurantism. In fact, he
should be interpreted in the context of Renaissance hermetism. Indeed, Bruno
was so impressed by the hermetic corpus, a body of writings attributed to the
mythical Egyptian sage Hermes Trismegistus, that he called for a return to the
magical religion of the Egyptians. He was also strongly influenced by Lull,
Nicholas of Cusa, Ficino, and Agrippa von Nettesheim, an early
sixteenth-century author of an influential treatise on magic. Several of
Bruno’s works were devoted to magic, and it plays an important role in his
books on the art of memory. Techniques for improving the memory had long been a
subject of discussion, but he linked them with the notion that one could so
imprint images of the universe on the mind as to achieve special knowledge of
divine realities and the magic powers associated with such knowledge. He
emphasized the importance of the imagination as a cognitive power, since it
brings us into contact with the divine. Nonetheless, he also held that human
ideas are mere shadows of divine ideas, and that God is transcendent and hence
incomprehensible. Bruno’s best-known works are the Italian dialogues he wrote
while in England, including the following, all published in 1584: The Ash
Wednesday Supper; On Cause, Principle and Unity; The Expulsion of the
Triumphant Beast; and On the Infinite Universe and Worlds. He presents a vision
of the universe as a living and infinitely extended unity containing
innumerable worlds, each of which is like a great animal with a life of its
own. He maintained the unity of matter with universal form or the World-Soul,
thus suggesting a kind of pantheism attractive to later German idealists, such
as Schelling. However, he never identified the World-Soul with God, who
remained separate from matter and form. He combined his speculative philosophy
of nature with the recommendation of a new naturalistic ethics. Bruno’s support
of Copernicus in The Ash Wednesday Supper was related to his belief that a
living earth must move, and he specifically rejected any appeal to mere
mathematics to prove cosmological hypotheses. In later work he described the monad
as a living version of the Democritean atom. Despite some obvious parallels
with both Spinoza and Leibniz, he seems not to have had much direct influence
on seventeenth-century thinkers. E.J.A. Brunschvicg, Léon 18691944, French
philosopher, an influential professor at the Sorbonne and the École Normale
Supérieure of Paris, and a founder of the Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale
1893 and the Société Française de Bruno, Giordano Brunschvicg, Léon 103 103 Philosophie 1901. In 1940 he was forced
by the Nazis to leave Paris and sought refuge in the nonoccupied zone, where he
died. A monistic idealist, Brunschvicg unfolded a philosophy of mind
Introduction to the Life of the Mind, 1900. His epistemology highlights
judgment. Thinking is judging and judging is acting. He defined philosophy as
“the mind’s methodical self-reflection.” Philosophy investigates man’s growing
self-understanding. The mind’s recesses, or metaphysical truth, are accessible
through analysis of the mind’s timely manifestations. His major works therefore
describe the progress of science as progress of consciousness: The Stages of
Mathematical Philosophy 1912, Human Experience and Physical Causality 1922, The
Progress of Conscience in Western Philosophy 1927, and Ages of Intelligence
1934. An heir of Renouvier, Cournot, and Revaisson, Brunschvicg advocated a
moral and spiritual conception of science and attempted to reconcile idealism
and positivism. J.-L.S. B-series.TIME. B-theory of time.TIME. Buber, Martin
18781965, German Jewish philosopher, theologian, and political leader. Buber’s
early influences include Hasidism and neo-Kantianism. Eventually he broke with
the latter and became known as a leading religious existentialist. His chief
philosophic works include his most famous book, Ich und du “I and Thou,” 1923;
Moses 1946; Between Man and Man 1947; and Eclipse of God 1952. The crux of
Buber’s thought is his conception of two primary relationships: I-Thou and
I-It. IThou is characterized by openness, reciprocity, and a deep sense of
personal involvement. The I confronts its Thou not as something to be studied,
measured, or manipulated, but as a unique presence that responds to the I in
its individuality. I-It is characterized by the tendency to treat something as
an impersonal object governed by causal, social, or economic forces. Buber
rejects the idea that people are isolated, autonomous agents operating
according to abstract rules. Instead, reality arises between agents as they
encounter and transform each other. In a word, reality is dialogical. Buber
describes God as the ultimate Thou, the Thou who can never become an It. Thus
God is reached not by inference but by a willingness to respond to the concrete
reality of the divine presence.
Buchmanism, also called
the Moral Rearmament Movement, a non-creedal international movement that sought
to bring about universal brotherhood through a commitment to an objectivist
moral system derived largely from the Gospels. It was founded by Frank Buchman
18781961, an American Lutheran minister who resigned from his church in 1908 in
order to expand his ministry. To promote the movement, Buchman founded the
Oxford Group at Oxford in 1921.
Buddha from Sanskrit,
‘the enlightened one’, a title but not a name of Siddharta Gotama c.563c.483
B.C., the historical founder of Buddhism, and of any of his later
representations. ‘Buddha’ can also mean anyone who has attained the state of
enlightenment Buddhahood sought in Buddhism. The Pali Canon mentions
twenty-four Buddhas. Siddharta Gotama was the son of the ruler of a small state
in what is now Nepal. Tradition says that he left home at the age of
twenty-nine to seek enlightenment, achieved it at the age of thirty-five, and
was a wandering teacher until his death at eighty. He found ready-made in
Indian culture the ideas of karma ‘fruits of action’ and samsara ‘wheel of
rebirth’ as well as the view that escape from the wheel is the highest good,
and offered his own Buddhist way of escape.
Buddhagosa fourthfifth
century A.D., Theraveda Buddhist philosopher whose major work was the
Visuddhimagga “Path of Purification”. He accepted the typical Buddhist doctrine
that everything that exists Nirvana aside is impermanent and momentary. A mind
at a moment is only a momentary collection of momentary states; over time it is
a series of such collections; similarly for a physical object. He held that,
through sensory perception, physical objects are known to exist
mind-independently. To the objection that perception of an object cannot occur
in a moment since perception requires memory, attention, recognition,
examination, and the like, he theorized that there is physical time and there
is mental time; a single physical moment passes while distinct mental moments
mount to sixteen in number. Hence a complex perceptual process can occur within
a series of mental moments while a single material moment passes. Critics e.g.,
Buddhist Yogacara philosophers saw in this a denial of impermanence.
Buddhism, a religion of
eastern and central Asia founded by Siddharta Gotama Buddha. The Buddha found
ready-made in Indian culture the ideas of karma ‘fruits of action’ and samsara
‘wheel of rebirth’, as well as the view that escape from the wheel is the
highest good. Buddhist doctrine, like that of other Indian religions, offers
its distinctive way to achieve that end. It teaches that at the core of the
problem is desire or craving for wealth,
pleasure, power, continued existence
which fuels the flame of continued life. It adds that the solution is
the snuffing out of craving by following the Eightfold Path right speech,
action, livelihood, effort, mindfulness, concentration, views, and intentions.
The idea is that intuitive wisdom follows upon moral conduct and mental
discipline in accord with Buddhist precepts. This involves accepting these
claims: all existence is unsatisfactory dukkha; all existence is impermanent
anicca; and there is no permanent self anatta. Along with these claims go the
doctrines of momentariness everything that exists is transitory, lasting only a
moment and codependent origination everything that exists does so dependently
on other things. Since God is typically conceived in monotheistic religions as
existing independently and as either eternal or everlasting, there is no room
within a Buddhist perspective for monotheism. Save for a heretical school,
Buddhist traditions also reject all belief in substances. A substance, in this
sense, is something that has properties, is not itself a property or a
collection of properties, and endures through time. The obvious contrast to the
Buddhist perspective is the notion of a self in Hinduism and Jainism, which is
beginningless and endless, an indestructible entity sometimes conceived as
inherently self-conscious and sometimes viewed as conscious only when embodied.
But even the notion of a substance that endured but had a beginning or end or
both, or a substance that existed dependently and endured so long as its
sustaining conditions obtained, would run deep against the grain of typical
Buddhist teaching. The Buddha is said to have offered no opinion, and to have
found no profit in speculation, on certain questions: whether the world is or
is not eternal, whether the world is or is not infinite, and whether the soul
is different from or identical to the body. The religious reason given for this
indifference is that reflection on such matters does not lead to enlightenment.
A philosophical reason sometimes given is that if, as Buddhism claims, there is
no world of substances, whether minds or bodies, then these questions have no straightforward
answer. They are like the question, What does the horn of the hare weigh? Hares
have no horns to be heavy or light. Seen in the context of the assumptions
common in the culture in which they were asked, the questions would suggest
that there are substantival minds and bodies and a world made up of them, and
to answer these questions, even negatively, would have involved at least
implicitly sanctioning that suggestion. Broadly, Indian Buddhism divides into
Theravada “Doctrine of the Elders,” namely those who heard and followed the
Buddha; this school is also called Hinayana, or “Lesser Vehicle” and Mahayana
“Greater Vehicle”. The Sautrantika and Vaibhasika schools belong to Theravada
and the Madhyamika and Yogacara schools are Mahayana. The Theravada schools.
The Sautrantika school holds that while sensory experience justifies belief in
the existence of mind-independent objects, the justification it provides
requires us to infer from our sensory experience physical objects that we do
not directly experience; it embraces representative realism. Thus, while our
seeming to experience mind-independent objects is no illusion, our knowledge
that it is not illusory rests as much on inference as on perception. The
explanation of the fact that we cannot perceive as we wish that we see and taste but rice and water
though we would prefer meat and wine is
that what we see depends on what there is to be represented and what the conditions
are under which we do our perceiving. The Vaibhasika followers of the Vaibhasha
commentary school defends direct realism, contending that if sensory perception
does not justify us in claiming actually to sense objects there is no way in
which we can infer their existence. If what we directly experience are alleged
representations or copies of objects we never see, from which we must then
infer the objects copied, we have no reason to think that the copies are copies
of anything. We do not determine the content of our perception because it
typically is determined for us by the objects that we see. The very
distinctions between dreams and waking perceptions, or veridical perceptions
and illusions, to which idealists appeal, depend for their appropriateness to
the idealist’s purpose on our being able to tell that some perceptual experiences
are reliable and some are not; but then the idealist cannot successfully use
them. For both Theravada schools, there is no need to correct our belief in
physical Buddhism Buddhism 105 105
objects, or in minds, beyond our viewing both minds and objects as collections
of different sorts of momentary states. The Mahayana schools. The Madhyamika
school holds out for a more radical revision. Our experience of physical
objects is reliable only if the beliefs that we properly base on it are true only if things are as they sensorily seem.
These beliefs are true only if we can sensorily distinguish between individual
objects. But everything exists dependently, and nothing that exists dependently
is an individual. So there are no individuals and we cannot distinguish between
individual objects. So our sensory experience is not reliable, but rather is
systematically illusory. Madhyamika then adds the doctrine of an ineffable
ultimate reality hidden behind our ordinary experience and descriptions, which is
accessible only in esoteric enlightenment experience. In this respect it is
like Advaita Vedanta, which it probably influenced. One result of the overall
Madhyamika teaching described here is that Nirvana and samsara,the goal and
ordinary life, are identified; roughly samsara is how Nirvana seems to the
unenlightened as roughly, for Advaita, the world of dependent things is how
qualityless Brahman appears to the unenlightened. The Yogacara perhaps “Yoga”
because it used meditation to remove belief in mind-independent physical
objects school of Mahayana Buddhism contends for a more ambitious revision of
our beliefs about objects than does Sautrantika or Vaibhasika, but a less
radical one than the Madhyamika. Against the latter, it contends that if mind
itself is empty of essence and if all there is is an ineffable reality, then
there is no one to see the truth and no reliable way to discover it. Against
the direct physical-object realism of the Vaibhasika and the representational
realism of the Sautrantika, the Yogacara philosophers argue that dream
experience seems to be of objects that exist mind-independently and in a public
space, and yet there are no such objects and there is no such space. What we
have experiential evidence for is the existence of non-substantival minds and
the experiences that those minds have. There are no substances at all and no
physical states; there are only mental states that compose minds. Yogacara
philosophers too had to explain why our perceptual content is not something we
can decide by whim, and its explanation came in terms of the theory that each
collection of momentary states, and hence each series or stream of such
collections, contains impressions that represent past experiences. These
impressions become potent under certain circumstances and determine the content
of one’s explicit or conscious perception. The stream, or substream, of
representative impressions is a storehouse of memories and plays a role in
Yogacara theory analogous to that of the Atman or Jiva in some of the schools
of Hinduism. Critics suspected it of being a thin surrogate for a substantival
self. AsaNga, Dignaga, and especially Vasubandhu were leading Yogacara
philosophers. Further, critics of the Yogacara idealism argued that while the
view contends that there are minds other than one’s own, it provided no way in
which that belief could be justified. Our discussion has dealt with Indian
Buddhism. Buddhism largely died out in India around the thirteenth century. It
thrived in other places, especially China, Tibet, and Japan. Japanese Pure Land
Buddhism resembles monotheism more than do any of the traditions that we have
discussed. Zen is a form of Mahayana that developed in China in the sixth and
seventh centuries A.D. and spread to Japan. It involves esoteric teachings
outside the sacred writings, following which is believed to lead to realization
of Buddhahood. The metaphysical and epistemological issues briefly discussed
here demonstrate that the Buddhist tradition found it natural to trace the
consequences of views about the nature of objects and persons, and about what
experience teaches, beyond the scope of what Buddhism as a religion might
strictly require. There are direct realists, representational realists, and
idealists, and the question arises as to whether idealism slides into
solipsism. There is no way of telling what a particular religious doctrine may
or may not be related to. Arguably, certain Buddhist doctrines are incompatible
with certain views in contemporary physics and Buddhist apologists have claimed
that contemporary physics provides some sort of confirmation of basic Buddhist
categories. There is no a priori way to limit the relationships that may come
to light between apparently very diverse, and quite unrelated, issues and
doctrines.
bundle theory, a view
that accepts the idea that concrete objects consist of properties but denies
the need for introducing substrata to account for their diversity. By contrast,
one traditional view of concrete particular objects is that they are complexes
consisting of two more fundamental kinds of entities: properties that can be
exemplified by many different objects and a substratum that exemplifies those
properties belonging to a particular object. Properties account for the
qualitative identity of such objects while substrata account for their
numerical diversity. The bundle theory is usually glossed as the view that a
concrete object is nothing but a bundle of properties. This gloss, however, is
inadequate. For if a “bundle” of properties is, e.g., a set of properties, then
bundles of properties differ in significant ways from concrete objects. For
sets of properties are necessary and eternal while concrete objects are
contingent and perishing. A more adequate statement of the theory holds that a concrete
object is a complex of properties which all stand in a fundamental contingent
relation, call it co-instantiation, to one another. On this account, complexes
of properties are neither necessary nor eternal. Critics of the theory,
however, maintain that such complexes have all their properties essentially and
cannot change properties, whereas concrete objects have some of their
properties accidentally and undergo change. This objection fails to recognize
that there are two distinct problems addressed by the bundle theory: a
individuation and b identity through time. The first problem arises for all
objects, both momentary and enduring. The second, however, arises only for
enduring objects. The bundle theory typically offers two different solutions to
these problems. An enduring concrete object is analyzed as a series of
momentary objects which stand in some contingent relation R. Different versions
of the theory offer differing accounts of the relation. For example, Hume holds
that the self is a series of co-instantiated impressions and ideas, whose
members are related to one another by causation and resemblance this is his
bundle theory of the self. A momentary object, however, is analyzed as a
complex of properties all of which stand in the relation of co-instantiation to
one another. Consequently, even if one grants that a momentary complex of
properties has all of its members essentially, it does not follow that an
enduring object, which contains the complex as a temporal part, has those
properties essentially unless one endorses the controversial thesis that an
enduring object has its temporal parts essentially. Similarly, even if one
grants that a momentary complex of properties cannot change in its properties,
it does not follow that an enduring object, which consists of such complexes,
cannot change its properties. Critics of the bundle theory argue that its
analysis of momentary objects is also problematic. For it appears possible that
two different momentary objects have all properties in common, yet there cannot
be two different complexes with all properties in common. There are two
responses available to a proponent of the theory. The first is to distinguish
between a strong and a weak version of the theory. On the strong version, the
thesis that a momentary object is a complex of co-instantiated properties is a
necessary truth, while on the weak version it is a contingent truth. The
possibility of two momentary objects with all properties in common impugns only
the strong version of the theory. The second is to challenge the basis of the
claim that it is possible for two momentary objects to have all their
properties in common. Although critics allege that such a state of affairs is
conceivable, proponents argue that investigation into the nature of
conceivability does not underwrite this claim.
Buridan, Jean c.1300 after
1358, philosopher. He was born in Béthune and educated at the of Paris. Unlike most philosophers of his
time, Buridan spent his academic career as a master in the faculty of arts,
without seeking an advanced degree in theology. He was also unusual in being a
secular cleric rather than a member of a religious order. Buridan wrote
extensively on logic and natural philosophy, although only a few of his works
have appeared in modern editions. The most important on logic are the Summulae
de dialectica “Sum of Dialectic”, an introduction to logic conceived as a
revision of, and extended commentary on, the Summulae logicales of Peter of
Spain, a widely used logic textbook of the period; and the Tractatus de
consequentiis, a treatise on modes of inference. Most of Buridan’s other
Buddhism, Theravada Buridan, Jean 107
107 writings are short literal commentaries expositiones and longer
critical studies quaestiones of Aristotle’s works. Like most medieval
nominalists, Buridan argued that universals have no real existence, except as
concepts by which the mind “conceives of many things indifferently.” Likewise,
he included only particular substances and qualities in his basic ontology. But
his nominalist program is distinctive in its implementation. He differs, e.g.,
from Ockham in his accounts of motion, time, and quantity appealing, in the
latter case, to quantitative forms to explain the impenetrability of bodies. In
natural philosophy, Buridan is best known for introducing to the West the
non-Aristotelian concept of impetus, or impressed force, to explain projectile
motion. Although asses appear often in his examples, the particular example
that has come via Spinoza and others to be known as “Buridan’s ass,” an ass
starving to death between two equidistant and equally tempting piles of hay, is
unknown in Buridan’s writings. It may, however, have originated as a caricature
of Buridan’s theory of action, which attempts to find a middle ground between
Aristotelian intellectualism and Franciscan voluntarism by arguing that the
will’s freedom to act consists primarily in its ability to defer choice in the
absence of a compelling reason to act one way or the other. Buridan’s
intellectual legacy was considerable. His works continued to be read and
discussed in universities for centuries after his death. Three of his students
and disciples, Albert of Saxony, Marsilius of Inghen, and Nicole Oresme, went
on to become distinguished philosophers in their own right.
Burke, Edmund, statesman
and one of the eighteenth century’s greatest political writers. Born in Dublin,
he moved to London to study law, then undertook a literary and political
career. He sat in the House of Commons from 1765 to 1794. In speeches and
pamphlets during these years he offered an ideological perspective on politics
that endures to this day as the fountain of conservative wisdom. The
philosophical stance that pervades Burke’s parliamentary career and writings is
skepticism, a profound distrust of political rationalism, i.e., the achievement
in the political realm of abstract and rational structures, ideals, and
objectives. Burkean skeptics are profoundly anti-ideological, detesting what
they consider the complex, mysterious, and existential givens of political life
distorted, criticized, or planned from a perspective of abstract, generalized,
and rational categories. The seminal expression of Burke’s skeptical
conservatism is found in the Reflections on the Revolution in France 1790. The
conservatism of the Reflections was earlier displayed, however, in Burke’s
response to radical demands in England for democratic reform of Parliament in
the early 1780s. The English radicals assumed that legislators could remake
governments, when all wise men knew that “a prescriptive government never was
made upon any foregone theory.” How ridiculous, then, to put governments on
Procrustean beds and make them fit “the theories which learned and speculative
men have made.” Such prideful presumption required much more rational capacity
than could be found among ordinary mortals. One victim of Burke’s skepticism is
the vaunted liberal idea of the social contract. Commonwealths were neither
constructed nor ought they to be renovated according to a priori principles.
The concept of an original act of contract is just such a principle. The only
contract in politics is the agreement that binds generations past, present, and
future, one that “is but a clause in the great primeval contract of an eternal
society.” Burke rejects the voluntaristic quality of rationalist liberal
contractualism. Individuals are not free to create their own political
institutions. Political society and law are not “subject to the will of those
who, by an obligation above them, and infinitely superior, are bound to submit
their will to that law.” Men and groups “are not morally at liberty, at their
pleasure, and on their speculations of a contingent improvement” to rip apart
their communities and dissolve them into an “unsocial, uncivil, unconnected
chaos.” Burke saw our stock of reason as small; despite this people still fled
their basic limitations in flights of ideological fancy. They recognized no
barrier to their powers and sought in politics to make reality match their
speculative visions. Burke devoutly wished that people would appreciate their
weakness, their “subordinate rank in the creation.” God has “subjected us to
act the part which belongs to the place assigned us.” And that place is to know
the limits of one’s rational and speculative faculties. Instead of relying on
their own meager supply of reason, politicians should avail themselves “of the
general bank and capital of nations and of ages.” Because people forget this
they weave rational schemes of reform far beyond their power to implement.
Buridan’s ass Burke, Edmund 108 108
Burke stands as the champion of political skepticism in revolt against
Enlightenment rationalism and its “smugness of adulterated metaphysics,” which
produced the “revolution of doctrine and theoretic dogma.” The sins of the
French were produced by the “clumsy subtlety of their political metaphysics.”
The “faith in the dogmatism of philosophers” led them to rely on reason and
abstract ideas, on speculation and a priori principles of natural right, freedom,
and equality as the basis for reforming governments. Englishmen, like Burke,
had no such illusions; they understood the complexity and fragility of human
nature and human institutions, they were not “the converts of Rousseau . . .
the disciples of Voltaire; Helvetius [had] made no progress amongst
[them].”
Burley, Walter
c.1275c.1344, English philosopher who taught philosophy at Oxford and theology
at Paris. An orthodox Aristotelian and a realist, he attacked Ockham’s logic
and his interpretation of the Aristotelian categories. Burley commented on
almost of all of Aristotle’s works in logic, natural philosophy, and moral
philosophy. An early Oxford Calculator, Burley began his work as a fellow of
Merton in 1301. By 1310, he was at
Paris. A student of Thomas Wilton, he probably incepted before 1322; by 1324 he
was a fellow of the Sorbonne. His commentary on Peter Lombard’s Sentences has
been lost. After leaving Paris, Burley was associated with the household of
Richard of Bury and the court of Edward III, who sent him as an envoy to the
papal curia in 1327. De vita et moribus philosophorum “On the Life and Manners
of Philosophers”, an influential, popular account of the lives of the
philosophers, has often been attributed to Burley, but modern scholarship
suggests that the attribution is incorrect. Many of Burley’s independent works
dealt with problems in natural philosophy, notably De intensione et remissione
formarum “On the Intension and Remission of Forms”, De potentiis animae “On the
Faculties of the Soul”, and De substantia orbis. De primo et ultimo instanti
“On First and Last Instants” discusses which temporal processes have intrinsic,
which extrinsic limits. In his Tractatus de formis Burley attacks Ockham’s
theory of quantity. Similarly, Burley’s theory of motion opposed Ockham’s
views. Ockham restricts the account of motion to the thing moving, and the
quality, quantity, and place acquired by motion. By contrast, Burley emphasizes
the process of motion and the quantitative measurement of that process. Burley
attacks the view that the forms successively acquired in motion are included in
the form finally acquired. He ridicules the view that contrary qualities hot
and cold could simultaneously inhere in the same subject producing intermediate
qualities warmth. Burley emphasized the formal character of logic in his De
puritate artis logicae “On the Purity of the Art of Logic”, one of the great
medieval treatises on logic. Ockham attacked a preliminary version of De
puritate in his Summa logicae; Burley called Ockham a beginner in logic. In De
puritate artis logicae, Burley makes syllogistics a subdivision of
consequences. His treatment of negation is particularly interesting for his
views on double negation and the restrictions on the rule that notnot-p implies
p. Burley distinguished between analogous words and analogous concepts and
natures. His theory of analogy deserves detailed discussion. These views, like
the views expressed in most of Burley’s works, have seldom been carefully
studied by modern philosophers.
butler: J., cited by H.
P. Grice, principle of conversational benevolence. English theologian and
Anglican bishop who made important contributions to moral philosophy, to the
understanding of moral agency, and to the development of deontological ethics.
Better known in his own time for The Analogy of Religion 1736, a defense, along
broadly empiricist lines, of orthodox, “revealed” Christian doctrine against
deist criticism, Butler’s main philosophical legacy was a series of highly
influential arguments and theses contained in a collection of Sermons 1725 and
in two “Dissertations” appended to The Analogy
one on virtue and the other on personal identity. The analytical method
of these essays “everything is what it is and not another thing” provided a
model for much of English-speaking moral philosophy to follow. For example,
Butler is often credited with refuting psychological hedonism, the view that
all motives can be reduced to the desire for pleasure or happiness. The sources
of human motivation are complex and structurally various, he argued. Appetites
and passions seek their own peculiar objects, and pleasure must itself be
understood as involving an intrinsic positive regard for a particular object.
Other philosophers had maintained, like Butler, that we can desire, e.g., the
happiness of others intrinsically, and not just as a means to our own happiness.
And others had argued that the person who aims singlemindedly at his own
happiness is unlikely to attain it. Butler’s distinctive contribution was to
demonstrate that happiness and pleasure themselves require completion by
specific objects for which we have an intrinsic positive regard. Self-love, the
desire for our own happiness, is a reflective desire for, roughly, the
satisfaction of our other desires. But self-love is not our only reflective
desire; we also have “a settled reasonable principle of benevolence.” We can
consider the goods of others and come on reflection to desire their welfare
more or less independently of particular emotional involvement such as
compassion. In morals, Butler equally opposed attempts to reduce virtue to
benevolence, even of the most universal and impartial sort. Benevolence seeks
the good or happiness of others, whereas the regulative principle of virtue is
conscience, the faculty of moral approval or disapproval of conduct and
character. Moral agency requires, he argued, the capacities to reflect
disinterestedly on action, motive, and character, to judge these in
distinctively moral terms and not just in terms of their relation to the
non-moral good of happiness, and to guide conduct by such judgments. Butler’s
views about the centrality of conscience in the moral life were important in
the development of deontological ethics as well as in the working out of an
associated account of moral agency. Along the first lines, he argued in the
“Dissertation” that what it is right for a person to do depends, not just on
the non-morally good or bad consequences of an action, but on such other
morally relevant features as the relationships the agent bears to affected
others e.g., friend or beneficiary, or whether fraud, injustice, treachery, or
violence is involved. Butler thus distinguished analytically between
distinctively moral evaluation of action and assessing an act’s relation to
such non-moral values as happiness. And he provided succeeding deontological
theorists with a litany of examples where the right thing to do is apparently
not what would have the best consequences. Butler believed God instills a “principle
of reflection” or conscience in us through which we intrinsically disapprove of
such actions as fraud and injustice. But he also believed that God, being
omniscient and benevolent, fitted us with these moral attitudes because “He
foresaw this constitution of our nature would produce more happiness, than
forming us with a temper of mere general benevolence.” This points, however,
toward a kind of anti-deontological or consequentialist view, sometimes called
indirect consequentialism, which readily acknowledges that what it is right to
do does not depend on which act will have the best consequences. It is entirely
appropriate, according to indirect consequentialism, that conscience approve or
disapprove of acts on grounds other than a calculation of consequences
precisely because its doing so has the best consequences. Here we have a
version of the sort of view later to be found, for example, in Mill’s defense
of utilitarianism against the objection that it conflicts with justice and
rights. Morality is a system of social control that demands allegiance to
considerations other than utility, e.g., justice and honesty. But it is
justifiable only to the extent that the system itself has utility. This sets up
something of a tension. From the conscientious perspective an agent must
distinguish between the question of which action would have the best
consequences and the question of what he should do. And from that perspective,
Butler thinks, one will necessarily regard one’s answer to the second question
as authoritative for conduct. Conscience necessarily implicitly asserts its own
authority, Butler famously claimed. Thus, insofar as agents come to regard
their conscience as simply a method of social control with good consequences,
they will come to be alienated from the inherent authority their conscience
implicitly claims. A similar issue arises concerning the relation between
conscience and self-love. Butler says that both self-love and conscience are
“superior principles in the nature of man” in that an action will be unsuitable
to a person’s nature if it is contrary to either. This makes conscience’s
authority conditional on its not conflicting with self-love and vice versa.
Some scholars, moreover, read other passages as implying that no agent could
reasonably follow conscience unless doing so was in the agent’s interest. But
again, it would seem that an agent who internalized such a view would be
alienated from the authority that, if Butler is right, conscience implicitly
claims. For Butler, conscience or the principle of reflection is uniquely the
faculty of practical judgment. Unlike either self-love or benevolence, even
when these are added to the powers of inference and empirical cognition, only
conscience makes moral agency possible. Only a creature with conscience can
accord with or violate his own judgment of what he ought to do, and thereby be
a “law to himself.” This suggests a view that, like Kant’s, seeks to link
deontology to a conception of autonomous moral agency.
cabala from Hebrew
qabbala, ‘tradition’, a system of Jewish mysticism and theosophy practiced from
the thirteenth to the eighteenth century; loosely, all forms of Jewish
mysticism. Believed by its adherents to be a tradition communicated to Moses at
Sinai, the main body of cabalistic writing, the Zohar, is thought to be the
work primarily of Moses de León of Guadalajara, in the thirteenth century,
though he attributed it to the second-century rabbi Simon bar Yohai. The Zohar
builds on earlier Jewish mysticism, and is replete with gnostic and Neoplatonic
themes. It offers the initiated access to the mysteries of God’s being, human
destiny, and the meaning of the commandments. The transcendent and strictly
unitary God of rabbinic Judaism here encounters ten apparently real divine
powers, called sefirot, which together represent God’s being and appearance in
the cosmos and include male and female principles. Evil in the world is seen as
a reflection of a cosmic rupture in this system, and redemption on earth
entails restoration of the divine order. Mankind can assist in this task
through knowledge, piety, and observance of the law. Isaac Luria in the
sixteenth century developed these themes with graphic descriptions of the
dramas of creation, cosmic rupture, and restoration, the latter process requiring
human assistance more than ever.
Caird, Edward 18351908,
Scottish philosopher, a leading absolute idealist. Influential as both a writer
and a teacher, Caird was professor of moral philosophy at Glasgow and master of
Balliol , Oxford. His aim in philosophy was to overcome intellectual
oppositions. In his main work, The Critical Philosophy of Kant 1889, he argued
that Kant had done this by using reason to synthesize rationalism and
empiricism while reconciling science and religion. In Caird’s view, Kant
unfortunately treated reason as subjective, thereby retaining an opposition
between self and world. Loosely following Hegel, Caird claimed that objective
reason, or the Absolute, was a larger whole in which both self and world were
fragments. In his Evolution of Religion 1893 Caird argued that religion
progressively understands God as the Absolute and hence as what reconciles self
and world. This allowed him to defend Christianity as the highest evolutionary
stage of religion without defending the literal truth of Scripture.
Cajetan, original name,
Tommaso de Vio c.1469 1534, Italian prelate and theologian. Born in Gaeta from
which he took his name, he entered the Dominican order in 1484 and studied
philosophy and theology at Naples, Bologna, and Padua. He became a cardinal in
1517; during the following two years he traveled to Germany, where he engaged
in a theological controversy with Luther. His major work is a Commentary on St.
Thomas’ Summa of Theology 1508, which promoted a renewal of interest in
Scholastic and Thomistic philosophy during the sixteenth century. In agreement
with Aquinas, Cajetan places the origin of human knowledge in sense perception.
In contrast with Aquinas, he denies that the immortality of the soul and the
existence of God as our creator can be proved. Cajetan’s work in logic was
based on traditional Aristotelian syllogistic logic but is original in its
discussion of the notion of analogy. Cajetan distinguishes three types: analogy
of inequality, analogy of attribution, and analogy of proportion. Whereas he
rejected the first two types as improper, he regarded the last as the basic
type of analogy and appealed to it in explaining how humans come to know God
and how analogical reasoning applied to God and God’s creatures avoids being
equivocal.
calculus, a central
branch of mathematics, originally conceived in connection with the
determination of the tangent or normal to a curve and of the area between it
and some fixed axis; but it also embraced the calculation of volumes and of
areas of curved surfaces, the lengths of curved lines, and so on. Mathematical
analysis is a still broader branch that subsumed the calculus under its rubric
see below, together with the theories of functions and of infinite series.
Still more general and/or abstract versions of analysis have been developed during
the twentieth century, with applications to other branches of mathematics, such
as probability theory. The origins of the calculus go back to Grecian
mathematics, usually in problems of determining the slope of a tangent to a
curve and the area enclosed underneath it by some fixed axes or by a closed
curve; sometimes related questions such as the length of an arc of a curve, or
the area of a curved surface, were considered. The subject flourished in the
seventeenth century when the analytical geometry of Descartes gave algebraic
means to extend the procedures. It developed further when the problems of slope
and area were seen to require the finding of new functions, and that the
pertaining processes were seen to be inverse. Newton and Leibniz had these
insights in the late seventeenth century, independently and in different forms.
In the Leibnizian differential calculus the differential dx was proposed as an
infinitesimal increment on x, and of the same dimension as x; the slope of the
tangent to a curve with y as a function of x was the ratio dy/dx. The integral,
ex, was infinitely large and of the dimension of x; thus for linear variables x
and y the area ey dx was the sum of the areas of rectangles y high and dx wide.
All these quantities were variable, and so could admit higher-order
differentials and integrals ddx, eex, and so on. This theory was extended
during the eighteenth century, especially by Euler, to functions of several
independent variables, and with the creation of the calculus of variations. The
chief motivation was to solve differential equations: they were motivated
largely by problems in mechanics, which was then the single largest branch of
mathematics. Newton’s less successful fluxional calculus used limits in its
basic definitions, thereby changing dimensions for the defined terms. The
fluxion was the rate of change of a variable quantity relative to “time”;
conversely, that variable was the “fluent” of its fluxion. These quantities
were also variable; fluxions and fluents of higher orders could be defined from
them. A third tradition was developed during the late eighteenth century by J.
L. Lagrange. For him the “derived functions” of a function fx were definable by
purely algebraic means from its Taylorian power-series expansion about any
value of x. By these means it was hoped to avoid the use of both infinitesimals
and limits, which exhibited conceptual difficulties, the former due to their
unclear ontology as values greater than zero but smaller than any orthodox
quantity, the latter because of the naive theories of their deployment. In the
early nineteenth century the Newtonian tradition died away, and Lagrange’s did
not gain general conviction; however, the LeibnizEuler line kept some of its
health, for its utility in physical applications. But all these theories
gradually became eclipsed by the mathematical analysis of A. L. Cauchy. As with
Newton’s calculus, the theory of limits was central, but they were handled in a
much more sophisticated way. He replaced the usual practice of defining the
integral as more or less automatically the inverse of the differential or
fluxion or whatever by giving independent definitions of the derivative and the
integral; thus for the first time the fundamental “theorem” of the calculus,
stating their inverse relationship, became a genuine theorem, requiring
sufficient conditions upon the function to ensure its truth. Indeed, Cauchy
pioneered the routine specification of necessary and/or sufficient conditions
for truth of theorems in analysis. His discipline also incorporated the theory
of discontinuous functions and the convergence or divergence of infinite
series. Again, general definitions were proffered and conditions sought for
properties to hold. Cauchy’s discipline was refined and extended in the second
half of the nineteenth century by K. Weierstrass and his followers at Berlin.
The study of existence theorems as for irrational numbers, and also technical
questions largely concerned with trigonometric series, led to the emergence of
set topology. In addition, special attention was given to processes involving
several variables changing in value together, and as a result the importance of
quantifiers was recognized for example,
reversing their order from ‘there is a y such that for all x . . .’ to ‘for all
x, there is a y . . .’. This developed later into general set theory, and then
to mathematical logic: Cantor was the major figure in the first aspect, while
G. Peano pioneered much for the second. Under this regime of “rigor,”
infinitesimals such as dx became unacceptable as mathematical objects. However,
they always kept an unofficial place because of their utility when applying the
calculus, and since World War II theories have been put forward in which the
established level of rigor and generality are preserved and even improved but
in which infinitesimals are reinstated. The best-known of these theories, the
non-standard analysis of A. Robinson, makes use of model theory by defining
infinitesimals as arithmetical inverses of the transfinite integers generated
by a “non-standard model” of Peano’s postulates for the natural numbers.
calculus calculus
Calvin, John 150964,
French theologian and church reformer, a major figure in the Protestant
Reformation. He was especially important for the so-called Reformed churches in
France, Switzerland, the Netherlands, Germany, Scotland, and England. Calvin
was a theologian in the humanist tradition rather than a philosopher. He valued
philosophy as “a noble gift of God” and cited philosophers especially Plato
when it suited his purposes; but he rejected philosophical speculation about
“higher things” and despised though
sometimes exploiting its resources the
dominant Scholastic philosophy of his time, to which he had been introduced at
the of Paris. His eclectic culture also
included a variety of philosophical ideas, of whose source he was often
unaware, that inevitably helped to shape his thought. His Christianae
religionis institutio first ed. 1536 but repeatedly enlarged; in English
generally cited as Institutes, his theological treatises, his massive biblical
commentaries, and his letters, all of which were translated into most European
languages, thus helped to transmit various philosophical motifs and attitudes
in an unsystematic form both to contemporaries and to posterity. He passed on
to his followers impulses derived from both the antiqui and the moderni. From
the former he inherited an intellectualist anthropology that conceived of the
personality as a hierarchy of faculties properly subordinated to reason, which
was at odds with his evangelical theology; and, though he professed to scorn
Stoicism, a moralism often more Stoic than evangelical. He also relied
occasionally on the Scholastic quaestio, and regularly treated substantives,
like the antiqui, as real entities. These elements in his thought also found
expression in tendencies to a natural theology based on an innate and universal
religious instinct that can discern evidences of the existence and attributes
of God everywhere in nature, and a conception of the Diety as immutable and
intelligible. This side of Calvinism eventually found expression in
Unitarianism and universalism. It was, however, in uneasy tension with other
tendencies in his thought that reflect both his biblicism and a nominalist and
Scotist sense of the extreme transcendence of God. Like other humanists,
therefore, he was also profoundly skeptical about the capacity of the human
mind to grasp ultimate truth, an attitude that rested, for him, on both the
consequences of original sin and the merely conventional origins of language.
Corollaries of this were his sense of the contingency of all human intellectual
constructions and a tendency to emphasize the utility rather than the truth
even of such major elements in his theology as the doctrine of predestination.
It may well be no accident, therefore, that later skepticism and pragmatism
have been conspicuous in thinkers nurtured by later Calvinism, such as Bayle,
Hume, and James.
.
Cambridge change, a
non-genuine change. If I turn pale, I am changing, whereas your turning pale is
only a Cambridge change in me. When I acquire the property of being such that
you are pale, I do not change. In general, an object’s acquiring a new property
is not a sufficient condition for that object to change although some other
object may genuinely change. Thus also, my being such that you are pale counts
only as a Cambridge property of me, a property such that my gaining or losing it
is only a Cambridge change. Cambridge properties are a proper subclass of
extrinsic properties: being south of Chicago is considered an extrinsic
property of me, but since my moving to Canada would be a genuine change, being
south of Chicago cannot, for me, be a Cambridge property. The concept of a
Cambridge change reflects a way of thinking entrenched in common sense, but it
is difficult to clarify, and its philosophical value is controversial. Neither
science nor formal semantics, e.g., supports this viewpoint. Perhaps calculus,
fluxional Cambridge changes and properties are, for better or worse,
inseparable from a vague, intuitive metaphysics.
Cambridge Platonists, a
group of seventeenthcentury philosopher-theologians at the of Cambridge, principally including Benjamin
Whichcote 160983, often designated the father of the Cambridge Platonists;
Henry More; Ralph Cudworth 161788; and John Smith 161652. Whichcote, Cudworth,
and Smith received their education in or
were at some time fellows of Emmanuel , a stronghold of the Calvinism in which
they were nurtured and against which they rebelled under mainly Erasmian,
Arminian, and Neoplatonic influences. Other Cambridge men who shared their
ideas and attitudes to varying degrees were Nathanael Culverwel 1618?51, Peter
Sterry 161372, George Rust d.1670, John Worthington 161871, and Simon Patrick
1625 1707. As a generic label, ‘Cambridge Platonists’ is a handy umbrella term
rather than a dependable signal of doctrinal unity or affiliation. The
Cambridge Platonists were not a self-constituted group articled to an explicit
manifesto; no two of them shared quite the same set of doctrines or values.
Their Platonism was not exclusively the pristine teaching of Plato, but was
formed rather from Platonic ideas supposedly prefigured in Hermes Trismegistus,
in the Chaldean Oracles, and in Pythagoras, and which they found in Origen and
other church fathers, in the Neoplatonism of Plotinus and Proclus, and in the
Florentine Neoplatonism of Ficino. They took contrasting and changing positions
on the important belief originating in Florence with Giovanni Pico della
Mirandola that Pythagoras and Plato derived their wisdom ultimately from Moses
and the cabala. They were not equally committed to philosophical pursuits, nor
were they equally versed in the new philosophies and scientific advances of the
time. The Cambridge Platonists’ concerns were ultimately religious and
theological rather than primarily philosophical. They philosophized as
theologians, making eclectic use of philosophical doctrines whether Platonic or
not for apologetic purposes. They wanted to defend “true religion,” namely,
their latitudinarian vision of Anglican Christianity, against a variety of
enemies: the Calvinist doctrine of predestination; sectarianism; religious
enthusiasm; fanaticism; the “hide-bound, strait-laced spirit” of Interregnum
Puritanism; the “narrow, persecuting spirit” that followed the Restoration;
atheism; and the impieties incipient in certain trends in contemporary science
and philosophy. Notable among the latter were the doctrines of the mechanical
philosophers, especially the materialism and mechanical determinism of Hobbes
and the mechanistic pretensions of the Cartesians. The existence of God, the
existence, immortality, and dignity of the human soul, the existence of spirit
activating the natural world, human free will, and the primacy of reason are
among the principal teachings of the Cambridge Platonists. They emphasized the
positive role of reason in all aspects of philosophy, religion, and ethics,
insisting in particular that it is irrationality that endangers the Christian
life. Human reason and understanding was “the Candle of the Lord” Whichcote’s
phrase, perhaps their most cherished image. In Whichcote’s words, “To go
against Reason, is to go against God . . . Reason is the Divine Governor of
Man’s Life; it is the very Voice of God.” Accordingly, “there is no real
clashing at all betwixt any genuine point of Christianity and what true
Philosophy and right Reason does determine or allow” More. Reason directs us to
the self-evidence of first principles, which “must be seen in their own light,
and are perceived by an inward power of nature.” Yet in keeping with the
Plotinian mystical tenor of their thought, they found within the human soul the
“Divine Sagacity” More’s term, which is the prime cause of human reason and
therefore superior to it. Denying the Calvinist doctrine that revelation is the
only source of spiritual light, they taught that the “natural light” enables us
to know God and interpret the Scriptures. Cambridge Platonism was
uncompromisingly innatist. Human reason has inherited immutable intellectual,
moral, and religious notions, “anticipations of the soul,” which negate the
claims of empiricism. The Cambridge Platonists were skeptical with regard to
certain kinds of knowledge, and recognized the role of skepticism as a critical
instrument in epistemology. But they were dismissive of the idea that
Pyrrhonism be taken seriously in the practical affairs of the philosopher at
work, and especially of the Christian soul in its quest for divine knowledge
and understanding. Truth is not compromised by our inability to devise
apodictic demonstrations. Indeed Whichcote passed a moral censure on those who
pretend “the doubtfulness and uncertainty of reason.” Innatism and the natural
light of reason shaped the Cambridge Platonists’ moral philosophy. The
unchangeable and eternal ideas of good and evil in the divine mind are the
exemplars of ethical axioms or noemata that enable the human mind to make moral
judgments. More argued for a “boniform faculty,” a faculty higher than reason
by which the soul rejoices in reason’s judgment of the good. The most
philosophically committed and systematic of the group were More, Cudworth, and
Culverwel. Smith, perhaps the most intellectually gifted and certainly the most
promising note his dates, defended Whichcote’s Christian teaching, insisting
that theology is more “a Divine Life than a Divine Science.” More exclusively
theological in their leanings were Whichcote, who wrote little of solid
philosophical interest, Rust, who followed Cudworth’s moral philosophy, and
Sterry. Only Patrick, More, and Cudworth all fellows of the Royal Society were
sufficiently attracted to the new science especially the work of Descartes to
discuss it in any detail or to turn it to philosophical and theological
advantage. Though often described as a Platonist, Culverwel was really a
neo-Aristotelian with Platonic embellishments and, like Sterry, a Calvinist. He
denied innate ideas and supported the tabula rasa doctrine, commending “the
Platonists . . . that they lookt upon the spirit of a man as the Candle of the
Lord, though they were deceived in the time when ‘twas lighted.” The Cambridge
Platonists were influential as latitudinarians, as advocates of rational
theology, as severe critics of unbridled mechanism and materialism, and as the
initiators, in England, of the intuitionist ethical tradition. In the England
of Locke they are a striking counterinstance of innatism and non-empirical
philosophy.
camera obscura, a
darkened enclosure that focuses light from an external object by a pinpoint
hole instead of a lens, creating an inverted, reversed image on the opposite
wall. The adoption of the camera obscura as a model for the eye revolutionized
the study of visual perception by rendering obsolete previous speculative
philosophical theories, in particular the emanation theory, which explained
perception as due to emanated copy-images of objects entering the eye, and theories
that located the image of perception in the lens rather than the retina. By
shifting the location of sensation to a projection on the retina, the camera
obscura doctrine helped support the distinction of primary and secondary sense
qualities, undermining the medieval realist view of perception and moving
toward the idea that consciousness is radically split off from the world.
Campanella, Tommaso
15681639, Italian theologian, philosopher, and poet. He joined the Dominican
order in 1582. Most of the years between 1592 and 1634 he spent in prison for
heresy and for conspiring to replace Spanish rule in southern Italy with a
utopian republic. He fled to France in 1634 and spent his last years in
freedom. Some of his best poetry was written while he was chained in a dungeon;
and during less rigorous confinement he managed to write over a hundred books,
not all of which survive. His best-known work, The City of the Sun 1602;
published 1623, describes a community governed in accordance with astrological
principles, with a priest as head of state. In later political writings,
Campanella attacked Machiavelli and called for either a universal Spanish
monarchy with the pope as spiritual head or a universal theocracy with the pope
as both spiritual and temporal leader. His first publication was Philosophy
Demonstrated by the Senses 1591, which supported the theories of Telesio and
initiated his lifelong attack on Aristotelianism. He hoped to found a new
Christian philosophy based on the two books of nature and Scripture, both of
which are manifestations of God. While he appealed to sense experience, he was
not a straightforward empiricist, for he saw the natural world as alive and
sentient, and he thought of magic as a tool for utilizing natural processes. In
this he was strongly influenced by Ficino. Despite his own difficulties with
Rome, he wrote in support of Galileo.
Campbell, Norman Robert
18801949, British physicist and philosopher of science. A successful
experimental physicist, Campbell with A. Wood discovered the radioactivity of
potassium. His analysis of science depended on a sharp distinction between
experimental laws and theories. Experimental laws are generalizations
established by observations. A theory has the following structure. First, it
requires a largely arbitrary hypothesis, which in itself is untestable. To
render it testable, the theory requires a “dictionary” of propositions linking
the hypothesis to scientific laws, which can be established experimentally. But
theories are not merely logical relations between hypotheses and experimental
Cambridge property Campbell, Norman Robert 115
115 laws; they also require concrete analogies or models. Indeed, the
models suggest the nature of the propositions in the dictionary. The analogies
are essential components of the theory, and, for Campbell, are nearly always
mechanical. His theory of science greatly influenced Nagel’s The Structure of
Science 1961.
Camus, Albert 191360,
French philosophical novelist and essayist who was also a prose poet and the
conscience of his times. He was born and raised in Algeria, and his experiences
as a fatherless, tubercular youth, as a young playwright and journalist in
Algiers, and later in the anti-German resistance in Paris during World War II
informed everything he wrote. His best-known writings are not overtly
political; his most famous works, the novel The Stranger written in 1940,
published in 1942 and his book-length essay The Myth of Sisyphus written in
1941, published in 1943 explore the notion of “the absurd,” which Camus
alternatively describes as the human condition and as “a widespread sensitivity
of our times.” The absurd, briefly defined, is the confrontation between
ourselves with our demands for
rationality and justice and an
“indifferent universe.” Sisyphus, who was condemned by the gods to the endless,
futile task of rolling a rock up a mountain whence it would roll back down of
its own weight, thus becomes an exemplar of the human condition, struggling
hopelessly and pointlessly to achieve something. The odd antihero of The
Stranger, on the other hand, unconsciously accepts the absurdity of life. He
makes no judgments, accepts the most repulsive characters as his friends and
neighbors, and remains unmoved by the death of his mother and his own killing
of a man. Facing execution for his crime, he “opens his heart to the benign
indifference of the universe.” But such stoic acceptance is not the message of
Camus’s philosophy. Sisyphus thrives he is even “happy” by virtue of his scorn
and defiance of the gods, and by virtue of a “rebellion” that refuses to give
in to despair. This same theme motivates Camus’s later novel, The Plague1947,
and his long essay The Rebel 1951. In his last work, however, a novel called
The Fall published in 1956, the year before he won the Nobel prize for
literature, Camus presents an unforgettably perverse character named
Jean-Baptiste Clamence, who exemplifies all the bitterness and despair rejected
by his previous characters and in his earlier essays. Clamence, like the character
in The Stranger, refuses to judge people, but whereas Meursault the “stranger”
is incapable of judgment, Clamence who was once a lawyer makes it a matter of
philosophical principle, “for who among us is innocent?” It is unclear where
Camus’s thinking was heading when he was killed in an automobile accident with
his publisher, Gallimard, who survived.
Canguilhem, Georges
190496, French historian and philosopher of science. Canguilhem succeeded
Gaston Bachelard as director of the Institut d’Histoire des Sciences et des
Techniques at the of Paris. He developed
and sometimes revised Bachelard’s view of science, extending it to issues in
the biological and medical sciences, where he focused particularly on the
concepts of the normal and the pathological The Normal and the Pathological,
1966. On his account norms are not objective in the sense of being derived from
value-neutral scientific inquiry, but are rooted in the biological reality of
the organisms that they regulate. Canguilhem also introduced an important
methodological distinction between concepts and theories. Rejecting the common
view that scientific concepts are simply functions of the theories in which
they are embedded, he argued that the use of concepts to interpret data is
quite distinct from the use of theories to explain the data. Consequently, the
same concepts may occur in very different theoretical contexts. Canguilhem made
particularly effective use of this distinction in tracing the origin of the
concept of reflex action.
Cantor, Georg 18451918,
German mathematician, one of a number of late nineteenthcentury mathematicians
and philosophers including Frege, Dedekind, Peano, Russell, and Hilbert who
transformed both mathematics and the study of its philosophical foundations.
The philosophical import of Cantor’s work is threefold. First, it was primarily
Cantor who turned arbitrary collections into objects of mathematical study,
sets. Second, he created a coherent mathematical theory of the infinite, in
particular a theory of transfinite numbers. Third, linking these, he was the
first to indicate that it might be possible to present mathematics as nothing
but the theory of sets, thus making set theory foundational for mathematics.
This contributed to the Camus, Albert Cantor, Georg 116 116 view that the foundations of mathematics
should itself become an object of mathematical study. Cantor also held to a
form of principle of plenitude, the belief that all the infinities given in his
theory of transfinite numbers are represented not just in mathematical or
“immanent” reality, but also in the “transient” reality of God’s created world.
Cantor’s main, direct achievement is his theory of transfinite numbers and
infinity. He characterized as did Frege sameness of size in terms of one-to-one
correspondence, thus accepting the paradoxical results known to Galileo and
others, e.g., that the collection of all natural numbers has the same
cardinality or size as that of all even numbers. He added to these surprising
results by showing 1874 that there is the same number of algebraic and thus
rational numbers as there are natural numbers, but that there are more points
on a continuous line than there are natural or rational or algebraic numbers,
thus revealing that there are at least two different kinds of infinity present
in ordinary mathematics, and consequently demonstrating the need for a
mathematical treatment of these infinities. This latter result is often
expressed by saying that the continuum is uncountable. Cantor’s theorem of 1892
is a generalization of part of this, for it says that the set of all subsets
the power-set of a given set must be cardinally greater than that set, thus
giving rise to the possibility of indefinitely many different infinities. The
collection of all real numbers has the same size as the power-set of natural
numbers. Cantor’s theory of transfinite numbers 1880 97 was his developed
mathematical theory of infinity, with the infinite cardinal numbers the F-, or
aleph-, numbers based on the infinite ordinal numbers that he introduced in
1880 and 1883. The F-numbers are in effect the cardinalities of infinite
well-ordered sets. The theory thus generates two famous questions, whether all
sets in particular the continuum can be well ordered, and if so which of the
F-numbers represents the cardinality of the continuum. The former question was
answered positively by Zermelo in 1904, though at the expense of postulating
one of the most controversial principles in the history of mathematics, the
axiom of choice. The latter question is the celebrated continuum problem.
Cantor’s famous continuum hypothesis CH is his conjecture that the cardinality
of the continuum is represented by F1, the second aleph. CH was shown to be
independent of the usual assumptions of set theory by Gödel 1938 and Cohen
1963. Extensions of Cohen’s methods show that it is consistent to assume that
the cardinality of the continuum is given by almost any of the vast array of
F-numbers. The continuum problem is now widely considered insoluble. Cantor’s
conception of set is often taken to admit the whole universe of sets as a set,
thus engendering contradiction, in particular in the form of Cantor’s paradox.
For Cantor’s theorem would say that the power-set of the universe must be
bigger than it, while, since this powerset is a set of sets, it must be
contained in the universal set, and thus can be no bigger. However, it follows
from Cantor’s early 1883 considerations of what he called the “absolute
infinite” that none of the collections discovered later to be at the base of
the paradoxes can be proper sets. Moreover, correspondence with Hilbert in 1897
and Dedekind in 1899 see Cantor, Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und
philosophischen Inhalts, 1932 shows clearly that Cantor was well aware that
contradictions will arise if such collections are treated as ordinary
sets.
cardinal virtues,
prudence practical wisdom, courage, temperance, and justice. Medievals deemed
them cardinal from Latin cardo, ‘hinge’ because of their important or pivotal
role in human flourishing. In Plato’s Republic, Socrates explains them through
a doctrine of the three parts of the soul, suggesting that a person is prudent
when knowledge of how to live wisdom informs her reason, courageous when
informed reason governs her capacity for wrath, temperate when it also governs
her appetites, and just when each part performs its proper task with informed
reason in control. Development of thought on the cardinal virtues was closely
tied to the doctrine of the unity of the virtues, i.e., that a person
possessing one virtue will have them all.
Carlyle, Thomas 17951881,
Scottish-born essayist, historian, and social critic, one of the most popular
writers and lecturers in nineteenth-century Britain. His works include literary
criticism, history, and cultural criticism. With respect to philosophy, his
views on the theory of history are his most significant contributions.
According to Carlyle, great personages are the most important causal factor in
history. On Heroes, Hero-Worship and the Heroic in History 1841 asserts,
“Universal History, the history of what man has accomplished in this world, is
at bottom the History of the Great Men who have worked here. They were the
leaders of men, these great ones; the modellers, patterns, and in a wide sense
creators, of whatsoever the general mass of men contrived to do or to attain;
all things that we see standing accomplished in the world are properly the
outer material result, the practical realisation and embodiment, of Thoughts
that dwelt in the Great Men sent into the world: the soul of the whole world’s
history, it may justly be considered, were the history of these.” Carlyle’s
doctrine has been challenged from many different directions. Hegelian and
Marxist philosophers maintain that the so-called great men of history are not
really the engine of history, but merely reflections of deeper forces, such as
economic ones, while contemporary historians emphasize the priority of “history
from below” the social history of everyday
people as far more representative of the
historical process.
Carnap, Rudolf 18911970,
German-born American philosopher, one of the leaders of the Vienna Circle, a
movement loosely called logical positivism or logical empiricism. He made
fundamental contributions to semantics and the philosophy of science, as well
as to the foundations of probability and inductive logic. He was a staunch
advocate of, and active in, the unity of science movement. Carnap received his
Ph.D. in philosophy from the of Jena in
1921. His first major work was Die Logische Aufbau der Welt 1928, in which he
sought to apply the new logic recently developed by Frege and by Russell and
Whitehead to problems in the philosophy of science. Although influential, it
was not translated until 1967, when it appeared as The Logical Structure of the
World. It was important as one of the first clear and unambiguous statements
that the important work of philosophy concerned logical structure: that
language and its logic were to be the focus of attention. In 1935 Carnap left
his native Germany for the United States, where he taught at the of Chicago and then at UCLA. Die Logiche
Syntax der Sprach 1934 was rapidly translated into English, appearing as The
Logical Syntax of Language 1937. This was followed in 1941 by Introduction to
Semantics, and in 1942 by The Formalization of Logic. In 1947 Meaning and
Necessity appeared; it provided the groundwork for a modal logic that would
mirror the meticulous semantic development of first-order logic in the first
two volumes. One of the most important concepts introduced in these volumes was
that of a state description. A state description is the linguistic counterpart
of a possible world: in a given language, the most complete description of the
world that can be given. Carnap then turned to one of the most pervasive and
important problems to arise in both the philosophy of science and the theory of
meaning. To say that the meaning of a sentence is given by the conditions under
which it would be verified as the early positivists did or that a scientific
theory is verified by predictions that turn out to be true, is clearly to speak
loosely. Absolute verification does not occur. To carry out the program of
scientific philosophy in a realistic way, we must be able to speak of the
support given by inconclusive evidence, either in providing epistemological
justification for scientific knowledge, or in characterizing the meanings of
many of the terms of our scientific language. This calls for an understanding
of probability, or as Carnap preferred to call it, degree of confirmation. We
must distinguish between two senses of probability: what he called
probability1, corresponding to credibility, and probability2, corresponding to
the frequency or empirical conception of probability defended by Reichenbach
and von Mises. ‘Degree of confirmation’ was to be the formal concept
corresponding to credibility. The first book on this subject, written from the
same point of view as the works on semantics, was The Logical Foundations of
Probability 1950. The goal was a logical definition of ‘ch,e’: the degree of
confirmation of a hypothesis h, relative to a body of evidence e, or the degree
of rational belief that one whose total evidence was e should commit to h. Of
course we must first settle on a formal language in which to express the
hypothesis and the evidence; for this Carnap chooses a first-order language
based on a finite number of one-place predicates, and a countable number of
individual constants. Against this background, we perform the following reductions:
‘ch,e’ represents a conditional probability; thus it can be represented as the
ratio of the absolute probabilCarlyle, Thomas Carnap, Rudolf 118 118 ity of h & e to the absolute
probability of e. Absolute probabilities are represented by the value of a
measure function m, defined for sentences of the language. The problem is to
define m. But every sentence in Carnap’s languages is equivalent to a
disjunction of state descriptions; the measure to be assigned to it must,
according to the probability calculus, be the sum of the measures assigned to
its constituent state descriptions. Now the problem is to define m for state
descriptions. Recall that state descriptions were part of the machinery Carnap
developed earlier. The function c† is a confirmation function based on the
assignment of equal measures to each state description. It is inadequate,
because if h is not entailed by e, c†h,e % m†h, the a priori measure assigned
to h. We cannot “learn from experience.” A measure that does not have that
drawback is m*, which is based on the assignment of equal measures to each
structure description. A structure description is a set of state descriptions;
two state descriptions belong to the same structure description just in case
one can be obtained from the other by a permutation of individual constants.
Within the structure description, equal values are assigned to each state
description. In the next book, The Continuum of Inductive Methods, Carnap takes
the rate at which we learn from experience to be a fundamental parameter of his
assignments of probability. Like measures on state descriptions, the values of
the probability of the singular predictive inference determine all other
probabilities. The “singular predictive inference” is the inference from the
observation that individual 1 has one set of properties, individual 2 has
another set of properties, etc., to the conclusion: individual j will have
property k. Finally, in the last works Studies in Inductive Logic and
Probability, vols. I [1971] and II [1980], edited with Richard Jeffrey Carnap
offered two long articles constituting his Basic System of Inductive Logic.
This system is built around a language having families of attributes e.g.,
color or sound that can be captured by predicates. The basic structure is still
monadic, and the logic still lacks identity, but there are more parameters.
There is a parameter l that reflects the “rate of learning from experience”; a
parameter h that reflects an inductive relation between values of attributes
belonging to families. With the introduction of arbitrary parameters, Carnap
was edging toward a subjective or personalistic view of probability. How far he
was willing to go down the subjectivist garden path is open to question; that
he discovered more to be relevant to inductive logic than the “language” of
science seems clear. Carnap’s work on probability measures on formal languages
is destined to live for a long time. So too is his work on formal semantics. He
was a staunch advocate of the fruitfulness of formal studies in philosophy, of
being clear and explicit, and of offering concrete examples. Beyond the
particular philosophical doctrines he advocated, these commitments characterize
his contribution to philosophy.
Carroll, Lewis, pen name
of Charles Lutwidge Dodgson 183298, English writer and mathematician. The
eldest son of a large clerical family, he was educated at Rugby and Christ
Church, Oxford, where he remained for the rest of his uneventful life, as
mathematical lecturer until 1881 and curator of the senior commonroom. His
mathematical writings under his own name are more numerous than important. He
was, however, the only Oxonian of his day to contribute to symbolic logic, and
is remembered for his syllogistic diagrams, for his methods for constructing and
solving elaborate sorites problems, for his early interest in logical
paradoxes, and for the many amusing examples that continue to reappear in
modern textbooks. Fame descended upon him almost by accident, as the author of
Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland 1865, Through the Looking Glass 1872, The
Hunting of the Snark 1876, and Sylvie and Bruno 1889 93; saving the last, the
only children’s books to bring no blush of embarrassment to an adult reader’s
cheek. Dodgson took deacon’s orders in 1861, and though pastorally inactive,
was in many ways an archetype of the prim Victorian clergyman. His religious
opinions were carefully thought out, but not of great philosophic interest. The
Oxford movement passed him by; he worried about sin though rejecting the doctrine
of eternal punishment, abhorred profanity, and fussed over Sunday observance,
but was oddly tolerant of theatergoing, a lifelong habit of his own. Apart from
the sentimental messages later inserted in them, the Alice books and Snark are
blessedly devoid of religious or moral concern. Full of rudeness, aggression,
and quarrelsome, if fallacious, argument, they have, on the other hand, a
natural attraction for philosophers, who pillage Carneades Carroll, Lewis
119 119 them freely for illustrations.
Humpty-Dumpty, the various Kings and Queens, the Mad Hatter, the Caterpillar,
the White Rabbit, the Cheshire Cat, the Unicorn, the Tweedle brothers, the
Bellman, the Baker, and the Snark make fleeting appearances in the s of
Russell, Moore, Broad, Quine, Nagel, Austin, Ayer, Ryle, Blanshard, and even
Wittgenstein an unlikely admirer of the Mock Turtle. The first such allusion to
the March Hare is in Venn’s Symbolic Logic 1881. The usual reasons for
quotation are to make some point about meaning, stipulative definition, the
logic of negation, time reversal, dream consciousness, the reification of
fictions and nonentities, or the absurdities that arise from taking “ordinary
language” too literally. For exponents of word processing, the effect of
running Jabberwocky through a spell-checker is to extinguish all hope for the
future of Artificial Intelligence. Though himself no philosopher, Carroll’s
unique sense of philosophic humor keeps him and his illustrator, Sir John
Tenniel effortlessly alive in the modern age. Alice has been translated into
seventy-five languages; new editions and critical studies appear every year;
imitations, parodies, cartoons, quotations, and ephemera proliferate beyond
number; and Carroll societies flourish in several countries, notably Britain
and the United States.
Carvaka, Indian
materialism. Its varieties share the view that the mind is simply the body and
its capacities, but differ as to whether every mental property is simply a
physical property under some psychological description reductive materialism or
there are emergent irreducibly mental properties that are caused by physical
properties and themselves have no causal impact epiphenomenalism. Some Carvaka
epistemologists, at least according to their critics, accept only perception as
a reliable source of knowledge, but in its most sophisticated form Carvaka, not
unlike logical positivism, allows inference at least to conclusions that
concern perceptually accessible states of affairs.
Cassirer, Ernst 18741945,
German philosopher and intellectual historian. He was born in the German city
of Breslau now Wroclaw, Poland and educated at various German universities. He
completed his studies in 1899 at Marburg under Hermann Cohen, founder of the
Marburg School of neo-Kantianism. Cassirer lectured at the of Berlin from 1906 to 1919, then accepted a
professorship at the newly founded of
Hamburg. With the rise of Nazism he left Germany in 1933, going first to a visiting
appointment at All Souls , Oxford 1933 35 and then to a professorship at
the of Göteborg, Sweden 193541. In 1941
he went to the United States; he taught first at Yale 194144 and then at
Columbia 194445. Cassirer’s works may be divided into those in the history of
philosophy and culture and those that present his own systematic thought. The
former include major editions of Leibniz and Kant; his four-volume study The
Problem of Knowledge vols. 13, 190620; vol. 4, 1950, which traces the subject
from Nicholas of Cusa to the twentieth century; and individual works on
Descartes, Leibniz, Kant, Rousseau, Goethe, the Renaissance, the Enlightenment,
and English Platonism. The latter include his multivolume The Philosophy of
Symbolic Forms 192329, which presents a philosophy of human culture based on
types of symbolism found in myth, language, and mathematical science; and
individual works concerned with problems in such fields as logic, psychology,
aesthetics, linguistics, and concept formation in the humanities. Two of his
best-known works are An Essay on Man 1944 and The Myth of the State 1946.
Cassirer did not consider his systematic philosophy and his historical studies
as separate endeavors; each grounded the other. Because of his involvement with
the Marburg School, his philosophical position is frequently but mistakenly
typed as neo-Kantian. Kant is an important influence on him, but so are Hegel,
Herder, Wilhelm von Humboldt, Goethe, Leibniz, and Vico. Cassirer derives his
principal philosophical concept, symbolic form, most directly from Heinrich
Hertz’s conception of notation in mechanics and the conception of the symbol in
art of the Hegelian aesthetician, Friedrich Theodor Vischer. In a wider sense
his conception of symbolic form is a transformation of “idea” and “form” within
the whole tradition of philosophical idealism. Cassirer’s conception of
symbolic form is not based on a distinction between the symbolic and the
literal. In his view all human knowledge depends on the power to form
experience through some type of symbolism. The forms of human knowledge are
coextensive with forms of human culture. Those he most often analyzes are myth
and religion, art, language, history, and science. These forms of symbolism
constitute a total system of human knowledge and culture that is the subject
matter of philosophy. Cassirer’s influence is most evident in the aesthetics of
Susanne Langer 18951985, but his conception of the symbol has entered into
theoretical anthropology, psychology, structural linguistics, literary
criticism, myth theory, aesthetics, and phenomenology. His studies of the
Renaissance and the Enlightenment still stand as groundbreaking works in
intellectual history.
Castañeda, Hector-Neri
192491, American analytical philosopher. Heavily influenced by his own critical
reaction to Quine, Chisholm, and his teacher Wilfrid Sellars, Castañeda
published four books and more than 175 essays. His work combines originality,
rigor, and penetration, together with an unusual comprehensiveness his network of theory and criticism reaches
into nearly every area of philosophy, including action theory; deontic logic
and practical reason; ethics; history of philosophy; metaphysics and ontology;
philosophical methodology; philosophy of language, mind, and perception; and
the theory of knowledge. His principal contributions are to metaphysics and
ontology, indexical reference, and deontic logic and practical reasoning. In
metaphysics and ontology, Castañeda’s chief work is guise theory, first
articulated in a 1974 essay, a complex and global account of language, mind,
ontology, and predication. By holding that ordinary concrete individuals,
properties, and propositions all break down or separate into their various
aspects or guises, he theorizes that thinking and reference are directed toward
the latter. Each guise is a genuine item in the ontological inventory, having
properties internally and externally. In addition, guises are related by
standing in various sameness relations, only one of which is the familiar
relation of strict identity. Since every guise enjoys bona fide ontological
standing, whereas only some of these actually exist, Castañeda’s ontology and
semantics are Meinongian. With its intricate account of predication, guise
theory affords a unified treatment of a wide range of philosophical problems
concerning reference to nonexistents, negative existentials, intentional
identity, referential opacity, and other matters. Castañeda also played a
pivotal role in emphasizing the significance of indexical reference. If, e.g.,
Paul assertively utters ‘I prefer Chardonnay’, it would obviously be incorrect
for Bob to report ‘Paul says that I prefer Chardonnay’, since the last
statement expresses Bob’s speaker’s reference, not Paul’s. At the same time,
Castañeda contends, it is likewise incorrect for Bob to report Paul’s saying as
either ‘Paul says that Paul prefers Chardonnay’ or ‘Paul says that Al’s
luncheon guest prefers Chardonnay’ when Paul is Al’s only luncheon guest, since
each of these fail to represent the essentially indexical element of Paul’s
assertion. Instead, Bob may correctly report ‘Paul says that he himself prefers
Chardonnay’, where ‘he himself’ is a quasi-indicator, serving to depict Paul’s
reference to himself qua self. For Castañeda and others, quasi-indicators are a
person’s irreducible, essential means for describing the thoughts and
experiences of others. A complete account of his view of indexicals, together
with a full articulation of guise theory and his unorthodox theories of
definite descriptions and proper names, is contained in Thinking, Language, and
Experience 1989. Castañeda’s main views on practical reason and deontic logic
turn on his fundamental practitionproposition distinction. A number of valuable
essays on these views, together with his important replies, are collected in
James E. Tomberlin, ed., Agent, Language, and the Structure of the World 1983,
and Tomberlin, ed., Hector-Neri Castañeda 1986. The latter also includes
Castañeda’s revealing intellectual autobiography. .
casuistry, the
case-analysis approach to the interpretation of general moral rules. Casuistry
starts with paradigm cases of how and when a given general moral rule should be
applied, and then reasons by analogy to cases in which the proper application
of the rule is less obvious e.g., a case
in which lying is the only way for a priest not to betray a secret revealed in
confession. The point of considering the series of cases is to ascertain the
morally relevant similarities and differences between cases. Casuistry’s heyday
was the first half of the seventeenth century. Reacting against casuistry’s
popularity with the Jesuits and against its tendency to qualify general moral
rules, Pascal penned a polemic against casuistry from which the term never
recovered see his Provincial Letters, 1656. But the kind of reasoning to which
the term refers is flourishing in contemporary practical ethics.
categorical theory, a
theory all of whose models are isomorphic. Because of its weak expressive
power, in first-order logic with identity only theories with a finite model can
be categorical; without identity no theories are categorical. A more
interesting property, therefore, is being categorical in power: a theory is
categorical in power a when the theory has, up to isomorphism, only one model
with a domain of cardinality a. Categoricity in power shows the capacity to
characterize a structure completely, only limited by cardinality. For example,
the first-order theory of dense order without endpoints is categorical in power
w the cardinality of the natural numbers. The first-order theory of simple
discrete orderings with initial element, the ordering of the natural numbers,
is not categorical in power w. There are countable discrete orders, not
isomorphic to the natural numbers, that are elementary equivalent to it, i.e.,
have the same elementary, first-order theory. In first-order logic categorical
theories are complete. This is not necessarily true for extensions of
first-order logic for which no completeness theorem holds. In such a logic a
set of axioms may be categorical without providing an informative
characterization of the theory of its unique model. The term ‘elementary
equivalence’ was introduced around 1936 by Tarski for the property of being
indistinguishable by elementary means. According to Oswald Veblen, who first
used the term ‘categorical’ in 1904, in a discussion of the foundations of
geometry, that term was suggested to him by the American pragmatist John
Dewey.
categoricity, the
semantic property belonging to a set of sentences, a “postulate set,” that
implicitly defines completely describes, or characterizes up to isomorphism the
structure of its intended interpretation or standard model. The best-known
categorical set of sentences is the postulate set for number theory attributed
to Peano, which completely characterizes the structure of an arithmetic
progression. This structure is exemplified by the system of natural numbers
with zero as distinguished element and successor addition of one as
distinguished function. Other exemplifications of this structure are obtained
by taking as distinguished element an arbitrary integer, taking as
distinguished function the process of adding an arbitrary positive or negative
integer and taking as universe of discourse or domain the result of repeated
application of the distinguished function to the distinguished element. See,
e.g., Russell’s Introduction to the Mathematical Philosophy, 1918. More
precisely, a postulate set is defined to be categorical if every two of its
models satisfying interpretations or realizations are isomorphic to each other,
where, of course, two interpretations are isomorphic if between their
respective universes of discourse there exists a one-to-one correspondence by
which the distinguished elements, functions, relations, etc., of the one are
mapped exactly onto those of the other. The importance of the analytic geometry
of Descartes involves the fact that the system of points of a geometrical line
with the “left-of relation” distinguished is isomorphic to the system of real
numbers with the “less-than” relation distinguished. Categoricity, the ideal
limit of success for the axiomatic method considered as a method for
characterizing subject matter rather than for reorganizing a science, is known
to be impossible with respect to certain subject matters using certain formal
languages. The concept of categoricity can be traced back at least as far as
Dedekind; the word is due to Dewey.
Category: H. P. Grice and
J. L. Austin, “Categories.” H. P. Grice and P. F. Strawson, “Categories.” an
ultimate class. Categories are the highest genera of entities in the world.
They may contain species but are not themselves species of any higher genera.
Aristotle, the first philosopher to discuss categories systematically, listed
ten, including substance, quality, quantity, relation, place, and time. If a
set of categories is complete, then each entity in the world will belong to a
category and no entity will belong to more than one category. A prominent
example of a set of categories is Descartes’s dualistic classification of mind
and matter. This example brings out clearly another feature of categories: an
attribute that can belong to entities in one category cannot be an attribute of
entities in any other category. Thus, entities in the category of matter have
extension and color while no entity in the category of mind can have extension
or color.
category mistake, the
placing of an entity in the wrong category. In one of Ryle’s examples, to place
the activity of exhibiting team spirit in the same class with the activities of
pitching, batting, and catching is to make a category mistake; exhibiting team
spirit is not a special function like pitching or batting but instead a way
those special functions are performed. A second use of ‘category mistake’ is to
refer to the attribution to an entity of a property which that entity cannot
have not merely does not happen to have, as in ‘This memory is violet’ or, to
use an example from Carnap, ‘Caesar is a prime number’. These two kinds of
category mistake may seem different, but both involve misunderstandings of the
natures of the things being talked about. It is thought that they go beyond
simple error or ordinary mistakes, as when one attributes a property to a thing
which that thing could have but does not have, since category mistakes involve
attributions of properties e.g., being a special function to things e.g., team
spirit that those things cannot have. According to Ryle, the test for category
differences depends on whether replacement of one expression for another in the
same sentence results in a type of unintelligibility that he calls
“absurdity.”
category theory, a
mathematical theory that studies the universal properties of structures via
their relationships with one another. A category C consists of two collections
Obc and Morc , the objects and the morphisms of C, satisfying the following
conditions: i for each pair a, b of objects there is associated a collection
Morc a, b of morphisms such that each member of Morc belongs to one of these
collections; ii for each object a of Obc , there is a morphism ida , called the
identity on a; iii a composition law associating with each morphism f: a P b
and each morphism g: b P c a morphism gf:a P c, called the composite of f and
g; iv for morphisms f: a P b, g: b P c, and h: c P d, the equation hgf % hgf
holds; v for any morphism f: a P b, we have idbf % f and fida % f. Sets with
specific structures together with a collection of mappings preserving these
structures are categories. Examples: 1 sets with functions between them; 2
groups with group homomorphisms; 3 topological spaces with continuous
functions; 4 sets with surjections instead of arbitrary maps constitute a
different category. But a category need not be composed of sets and
set-theoretical maps. Examples: 5 a collection of propositions linked by the
relation of logical entailment is a category and so is any preordered set; 6 a
monoid taken as the unique object and its elements as the morphisms is a
category. The properties of an object of a category are determined by the
morphisms that are coming out of and going in this object. Objects with a
universal property occupy a key position. Thus, a terminal object a is
characterized by the following universal property: for any object b there is a
unique morphism from b to a. A singleton set is a terminal object in the
category of sets. The Cartesian product of sets, the product of groups, and the
conjunction of propositions are all terminal objects in appropriate categories.
Thus category theory unifies concepts and sheds a new light on the notion of
universality.
causal law, a statement
describing a regular and invariant connection between types of events or
states, where the connections involved are causal in some sense. When one
speaks of causal laws as distinguished from laws that are not 123 category
mistake causal law 123 causal, the
intended distinction may vary. Sometimes, a law is said to be causal if it
relates events or states occurring at successive times, also called a law of
succession: e.g., ‘Ingestion of strychnine leads to death.’ A causal law in
this sense contrasts with a law of coexistence, which connects events or states
occurring at the same time e.g., the Wiedemann-Franz law relating thermal and
electric conductivity in metals. One important kind of causal law is the deterministic
law. Causal laws of this kind state exceptionless connections between events,
while probabilistic or statistical laws specify probability relationships
between events. For any system governed by a set of deterministic laws, given
the state of a system at a time, as characterized by a set of state variables,
these laws will yield a unique state of the system for any later time or,
perhaps, at any time, earlier or later. Probabilistic laws will yield, for a
given antecedent state of a system, only a probability value for the occurrence
of a certain state at a later time. The laws of classical mechanics are often
thought to be paradigmatic examples of causal laws in this sense, whereas the
laws of quantum mechanics are claimed to be essentially probabilistic. Causal
laws are sometimes taken to be laws that explicitly specify certain events as
causes of certain other events. Simple laws of this kind will have the form
‘Events of kind F cause events of kind G’; e.g., ‘Heating causes metals to
expand’. A weaker related concept is this: a causal law is one that states a
regularity between events which in fact are related as cause to effect,
although the statement of the law itself does not say so laws of motion
expressed by differential equations are perhaps causal laws in this sense.
These senses of ‘causal law’ presuppose a prior concept of causation. Finally,
causal laws may be contrasted with teleological laws, laws that supposedly
describe how certain systems, in particular biological organisms, behave so as
to achieve certain “goals” or “end states.” Such laws are sometimes claimed to
embody the idea that a future state that does not as yet exist can exert an
influence on the present behavior of a system. Just what form such laws take
and exactly how they differ from ordinary laws have not been made wholly clear,
however.
causal theory of proper
names, the view that proper names designate what they name by virtue of a kind
of causal connection to it. This view is a special case, and in some instances
an unwarranted interpretation, of a direct reference view of names. On this
approach, proper names, e.g., ‘Machiavelli’, are, as J. S. Mill wrote, “purely
denotative. . . . they denote the individuals who are called by them; but they
do not indicate or imply any attributes as belonging to those individuals” A
System of Logic, 1879. Proper names may suggest certain properties to many
competent speakers, but any such associated information is no part of the
definition of the name. Names, on this view, have no definitions. What connects
a name to what it names is not the latter’s satisfying some condition specified
in the name’s definition. Names, instead, are simply attached to things,
applied as labels, as it were. A proper name, once attached, becomes a socially
available device for making the relevant name bearer a subject of discourse. On
the other leading view, the descriptivist view, a proper name is associated
with something like a definition. ‘Aristotle’, on this view, applies by
definition to whoever satisfies the relevant properties e.g., is ‘the teacher of Alexander the Great,
who wrote the Nicomachean Ethics’. Russell, e.g., maintained that ordinary
proper names which he contrasted with logically proper or genuine names have
definitions, that they are abbreviated definite descriptions. Frege held that
names have sense, a view whose proper interpretation remains in dispute, but is
often supposed to be closely related to Russell’s approach. Others, most
notably Searle, have defended descendants of the descriptivist view. An
important variant, sometimes attributed to Frege, denies that names have
articulable definitions, but nevertheless associates them with senses. And the
bearer will still be, by definition as it were, the unique thing to satisfy the
relevant mode of presentation. causal overdetermination causal theory of proper
names 124 124 The direct reference
approach is sometimes misleadingly called the causal theory of names. But the
key idea need have nothing to do with causation: a proper name functions as a
tag or label for its bearer, not as a surrogate for a descriptive expression.
Whence the allegedly misleading term ‘causal theory of names’? Contemporary
defenders of Mill’s conception like Keith Donnellan and Kripke felt the need to
expand upon Mill’s brief remarks. What connects a present use of a name with a
referent? Here Donnellan and Kripke introduce the notion of a “historical
chains of communication.” As Kripke tells the story, a baby is baptized with a
proper name. The name is used, first by those present at the baptism,
subsequently by those who pick up the name in conversation, reading, and so on.
The name is thus propagated, spread by usage “from link to link as if by a
chain” Naming and Necessity, 1980. There emerges a historical chain of uses of
the name that, according to Donnellan and Kripke, bridges the gap between a
present use of the name and the individual so named. This “historical chain of
communication” is occasionally referred to as a “casual chain of
communication.” The idea is that one’s use of the name can be thought of as a
causal factor in one’s listener’s ability to use the name to refer to the same
individual. However, although Kripke in Naming and Necessity does occasionally
refer to the chain of communication as causal, he more often simply speaks of
the chain of communication, or of the fact that the name has been passed “by
tradition from link to link” p. 106. The causal aspect is not one that Kripke
underscores. In more recent writings on the topic, as well as in lectures,
Kripke never mentions causation in this connection, and Donnellan questions
whether the chain of communication should be thought of as a causal chain. This
is not to suggest that there is no view properly called a “causal theory of
names.” There is such a view, but it is not the view of Kripke and Donnellan.
The causal theory of names is a view propounded by physicalistically minded
philosophers who desire to “reduce” the notion of “reference” to something more
physicalistically acceptable, such as the notion of a causal chain running from
“baptism” to later use. This is a view whose motivation is explicitly rejected
by Kripke, and should be sharply distinguished from the more popular
anti-Fregean approach sketched above.
No comments:
Post a Comment