SOCINIANISM.
sociobiology.SOCIAL BIOLOGY. sociological jurisprudence.JURISPRUDENCE.
sociology of knowledge.MANNHEIM. Socrates (469–399 B.C.), Greek philosopher,
the exemplar of the exined life, best known for his dictum that only such a life
is worth living. Although he wrote nothing, his thoughts and way of life had a
profound impact on many of his contemporaries, and, through Plato’s portrayal
of him in his early writings, he bece a major source of inspiration and ideas
for later generations of philosophers. His daily occupation was adversarial
public conversation with anyone willing to argue with him. A man of great
intellectual brilliance, moral integrity, personal magnetism, and physical
self-command, he challenged the moral complacency of his fellow citizens, and
embarrassed them with their inability to answer such questions as What is
virtue? – questions that he thought we must answer, if we are to know how best
to live our lives. His ideas and personality won him a devoted following ong
the young, but he was far from universally admired. Formal charges were made
against him for refusing to recognize the gods of the city, introducing other
new divinities, and corrupting the youth. Tried on a single day before a large
jury (500 was a typical size), he was found guilty by a small margin: had
thirty jurors voted differently, he would have been acquitted. The punishment
selected by the jury was death and was administered by means of poison,
probably hemlock. Why was he brought to trial and convicted? Part of the answer
lies in Plato’s Apology, which purports to be the defense Socrates gave at his
trial. Here he says that he has for many years been falsely portrayed as
someone whose scientific theories dethrone the traditional gods and put natural
forces in their place, and as someone who charges a fee for offering private
instruction on how to make a weak argument seem strong in the courtroom. This
is the picture of Socrates drawn in a play of Aristophanes, the Clouds, first
presented in 423. It is unlikely that Aristophanes intended his play as an
accurate depiction of Socrates, and the unscrupulous buffoon found in the
Clouds would never have won the devotion of so serious a moralist as Plato.
Aristophanes drew together the assorted characteristics of various
fifth-century thinkers and ned this alg “Socrates” because the real Socrates
was one of several controversial intellectuals of the period. Nonetheless, it
is unlikely that the charges against Socrates or Aristophanes’ caricature were
entirely without foundation. Both Xenophon’s Memorabilia and Plato’s Euthyphro
say that Socrates aroused suspicion because he thought a certain divine sign or
voice appeared to him and gave him useful instruction about how to act. By
claiming a unique and private source of divine inspiration, Socrates may have
been thought to challenge the city’s exclusive control over religious matters.
His willingness to disobey the city is admitted in Plato’s Apology, where he
says that he would have to disobey a hypothetical order to stop asking his
philosophical questions, since he regards them as serving a religious purpose.
In the Euthyphro he seeks a rational basis for making sacrifices and performing
other services to the gods; but he finds none, and implies that no one else has
one. Such a challenge to traditional religious practice could easily have
aroused a suspicion of atheism and lent credibility to the formal charges
against him. Furthermore, Socrates makes statements in Plato’s early dialogues
(and in Xenophon’s Memorabilia) that could easily have offended the political
sensibilities of his contemporaries. He holds that only those who have given
special study to political matters should make decisions. For politics is a
kind of craft, and in all other crafts only those who have shown their mastery
are entrusted with public responsibilities. Athens was a democracy in which
each citizen had an equal legal right to shape policy, and Socrates’ analogy
between the role of an expert in politics and in other crafts may have been
seen as a threat to this egalitarianism. Doubts about his political allegiance,
though not mentioned in the formal charges against him, could easily have
swayed some jurors to vote against him. Socrates is the subject not only of
Plato’s early dialogues but also of Xenophon’s Memorabilia, Socinus, Faustus
Socrates 859 859 and in many respects
their portraits are consistent with each other. But there are also some
important differences. In the Memorabilia, Socrates teaches whatever a
gentleman needs to know for civic purposes. He is filled with platitudinous
advice, and is never perplexed by the questions he raises; e.g., he knows what
the virtues are, equating them with obedience to the law. His views are not
threatening or controversial, and always receive the assent of his
interlocutors. By contrast, Plato’s Socrates presents himself as a perplexed
inquirer who knows only that he knows nothing about moral matters. His
interlocutors are sometimes annoyed by his questions and threatened by their inability
to answer them. And he is sometimes led by force of argument to controversial
conclusions. Such a Socrates could easily have made enemies, whereas Xenophon’s
Socrates is sometimes too “good” to be true. But it is important to bear in
mind that it is only the early works of Plato that should be read as an
accurate depiction of the historical Socrates. Plato’s own theories, as
presented in his middle and late dialogues, enter into philosophical terrain
that had not been explored by the historical Socrates – even though in the
middle (and some of the late) dialogues a figure called Socrates remains the
principal speaker. We are told by Aristotle that Socrates confined himself to
ethical questions, and that he did not postulate a separate realm of imperceptible
and eternal abstract objects called “Forms” or “Ideas.” Although the figure
called Socrates affirms the existence of these objects in such Platonic
dialogues as the Phaedo and the Republic, Aristotle takes this interlocutor to
be a vehicle for Platonic philosophy, and attributes to Socrates only those
positions that we find in Plato’s earlier writing, e.g. in the Apology,
Charmides, Crito, Euthyphro, Hippias Minor, Hippias Major, Ion, Laches, Lysis,
and Protagoras. Socrates focused on moral philosophy almost exclusively;
Plato’s attention was also devoted to the study of metaphysics, epistemology,
physical theory, mathematics, language, and political philosophy. When we
distinguish the philosophies of Socrates and Plato in this way, we find
continuities in their thought – for instance, the questions posed in the early
dialogues receive answers in the Republic – but there are important
differences. For Socrates, being virtuous is a purely intellectual matter: it
simply involves knowing what is good for human beings; once we master this
subject, we will act as we should. Because he equates virtue with knowledge,
Socrates frequently draws analogies between being virtuous and having mastered
any ordinary subject – cooking, building, or geometry, e.g. For mastery of
these subjects does not involve a training of the emotions. By contrast, Plato
affirms the existence of powerful emotional drives that can deflect us from our
own good, if they are not disciplined by reason. He denies Socrates’ assumption
that the emotions will not resist reason, once one comes to understand where
one’s own good lies. Socrates says in Plato’s Apology that the only knowledge
he has is that he knows nothing, but it would be a mistake to infer that he has
no convictions about moral matters – convictions arrived at through a difficult
process of reasoning. He holds that the unexined life is not worth living, that
it is better to be treated unjustly than to do injustice, that understanding of
moral matters is the only unconditional good, that the virtues are all forms of
knowledge and cannot be separated from each other, that death is not an evil,
that a good person cannot be harmed, that the gods possess the wisdom human
beings lack and never act immorally, and so on. He does not accept these
propositions as articles of faith, but is prepared to defend any of them; for
he can show his interlocutors that their beliefs ought to lead them to accept
these conclusions, paradoxical though they may be. Since Socrates can defend
his beliefs and has subjected them to intellectual scrutiny, why does he
present himself as someone who has no knowledge – excepting the knowledge of
his own ignorance? The answer lies in his assumption that it is only a fully
accomplished expert in any field who can claim knowledge or wisdom of that
field; someone has knowledge of navigational matters, e.g., only if he has
mastered the art of sailing, can answer all inquiries about this subject, and
can train others to do the se. Judged by this high epistemic standard, Socrates
can hardly claim to be a moral expert, for he lacks answers to the questions he
raises, and cannot teach others to be virtuous. Though he has exined his moral
beliefs and can offer reasons for them – an accomplishment that gives him an
overbearing sense of superiority to his contemporaries – he takes himself to be
quite distant from the ideal of moral perfection, which would involve a
thorough understanding of all moral matters. This keen sense of the moral and
intellectual deficiency of all human beings accounts for a great deal of
Socrates’ appeal, just as his arrogant disdain for his fellow citizens no doubt
contributed to his demise.
Socratic intellectualism,
the claim that moral goodness or virtue consists exclusively in a kind of
knowledge, with the implication that if one knows what is good and evil, one
cannot fail to be a good person and to act in a morally upright way. The claim
and the term derive from Socrates; a corollary is another claim of Socrates:
there is no moral weakness or akrasia – all wrong action is due to the agent’s
ignorance. Socrates defends this view in Plato’s dialogue Protagoras. There are
two ways to understand Socrates’ view that knowledge of the good is sufficient
for right action. (1) All desires are rational, being focused on what is
believed to be good; thus, an agent who knows what is good will have no desire
to act contrary to that knowledge. (2) There are non-rational desires, but
knowledge of the good has sufficient motivational power to overcome them.
Socratic intellectualism was abandoned by Plato and Aristotle, both of whom
held that emotional makeup is an essential part of moral character. However,
they retained the Socratic idea that there is a kind of knowledge or wisdom
that ensures right action – but this knowledge presupposes antecedent training
and molding of the passions. Socratic intellectualism was later revived and
enjoyed a long life as a key doctrine of the Stoics. MOTIVATIONAL INTERNALISM, SOCRATES, STOICISM.
D.T.D. Socratic irony, a form of indirect communication frequently employed by
Socrates in Plato’s early dialogues, chiefly to praise insincerely the
abilities of his interlocutors while revealing their ignorance; or, to
disparage his own abilities, e.g. by denying that he has knowledge. Interpreters
disagree whether Socrates’ self-disparagement is insincere. PLATO, SOCRATES. W.J.P. Socratic
method.SOCRATES. Socratic paradoxes, a collection of theses associated with
Socrates that contradict opinions about moral or practical matters shared by
most people. Although there is no consensus on the precise number of Socratic
paradoxes, each of the following theses has been identified as one. (1) Because
no one desires evil things, anyone who pursues evil things does so
involuntarily. (2) Because virtue is knowledge, anyone who does something
morally wrong does so involuntarily. (3) It is better to be unjustly treated
than to do what is unjust. The first two theses are associated with weakness of
will or akrasia. It is sometimes claimed that the topic of the first thesis is
prudential weakness, whereas that of the second is moral weakness; the
reference to “evil things” in (1) is not limited to things that are morally
evil. Naturally, various competing interpretations of these theses have been
offered. AKRASIA, PLATO, SOCRATES.
A.R.M. soft determinism.FREE WILL PROBLEM. software.COMPUTER THEORY. solipsism,
the doctrine that there exists a firstperson perspective possessing privileged
and irreducible characteristics, in virtue of which we stand in various kinds
of isolation from any other persons or external things that may exist. This
doctrine is associated with but distinct from egocentricism. On one variant of
solipsism (Thomas Nagel’s) we are isolated from other sentient beings because
we can never adequately understand their experience (empathic solipsism).
Another variant depends on the thesis that the meanings or referents of all
words are mental entities uniquely accessible only to the language user
(semantic solipsism). A restricted variant, due to Wittgenstein, asserts that
first-person ascriptions of psychological states have a meaning fundentally
different from that of second- or thirdperson ascriptions (psychological
solipsism). In extreme forms semantic solipsism can lead to the view that the only
things that can be meaningfully said to exist are ourselves or our mental
states (ontological solipsism). Skepticism about the existence of the world
external to our minds is sometimes considered a form of epistemological
solipsism, since it asserts that we stand in epistemological isolation from
that world, partly as a result of the epistemic priority possessed by
firstperson access to mental states. In addition to these substantive versions
of solipsism, several variants go under the rubric methodological solipsism.
The idea is that when we seek to explain why sentient beings behave in certain
ways by looking to what they believe, desire, hope, and fear, we should
identify these psychological states only with events that occur inside the mind
or brain, not with external events, since the former alone are the proximate
and sufficient causal explanations of bodily behavior. Socratic intellectualism
solipsism 861 861 DESCARTES, EGOCENTRIC PREDICENT, PHILOSOPHY
OF MIND, PRIVATE LANGUAGE ARGUMENT, SKEPTICISM. T.V. Solovyov, Vladimir
(1853–1900), Russian philosopher, theologian, essayist, and poet. In addition
to major treatises and dialogues in speculative philosophy, Solovyov wrote
sensitive literary criticism and influential essays on current social, political,
and ecclesiastical questions. His serious verse is subtle and delicate; his
light verse is rich in comic invention. The mystical image of the “Divine
Sophia,” which Solovyov articulated in theoretical concepts as well as poetic
symbols, powerfully influenced the Russian symbolist poets of the early
twentieth century. His stress on the human role in the “divine-human process”
that creates both cosmic and historical being led to charges of heresy from
Russian Orthodox traditionalists. Solovyov’s rationalistic “justification of
the good” in history, society, and individual life was inspired by Plato,
Spinoza, and especially Hegel. However, at the end of his life Solovyov offered
(in Three Conversations on War, Progress, and the End of History, 1900) a contrasting
apocalyptic vision of historical and cosmic disaster, including the appearance,
in the twenty-first century, of the Antichrist. In ethics, social philosophy,
philosophy of history, and theory of culture, Solovyov was both a vigorous
ecumenist and a “good European” who affirmed the intrinsic value of both the
“individual human person” (Russian lichnost’) and the “individual nation or
people” (narodnost’), but he decisively repudiated the perversions of these
values in egoism and nationalism, respectively. He contrasted the fruits of
English narodnost’ – the works of Shakespeare and Byron, Berkeley and Newton –
with the fruits of English nationalism – the repressive and destructive
expansion of the British Empire. In opposing ethnic, national, and religious
exclusiveness and self-centeredness, Solovyov also, and quite consistently,
opposed the growing xenophobia and antiSemitism of his own time. Since 1988
long-suppressed works by and about Solovyov have been widely republished in
Russia, and fresh interpretations of his philosophy and theology have begun to
appear.
RUSSIAN PHILOSOPHY.
G.L.K. Son Buddhism.KOREAN PHILOSOPHY. sophia.ARISTOTLE. sophismata (singular:
sophisma), sentences illustrating semantic or logical issues associated with
the analysis of syncategorematic terms, or terms lacking independent
signification. Typically a sophisma was used from the thirteenth century into
the sixteenth century to analyze relations holding between logic or semantics
and broader philosophical issues. For exple, the syncategorematic term
‘besides’ (praeter) in ‘Socrates twice sees every man besides Plato’ is
biguous, because it could mean ‘On two occasions Socrates sees
every-man-but-Plato’ and also ‘Except for overlooking Plato once, on two
occasions Socrates sees every man’. Roger Bacon used this sophisma to discuss
the biguity of distribution, in this case, of the scope of the reference of
‘twice’ and ‘besides’. Sherwood used the sophisma to illustrate the
applicability of his rule of the distribution of biguous syncategoremata, while
Pseudo-Peter of Spain uses it to establish the truth of the rule, ‘If a
proposition is in part false, it can be made true by means of an exception, but
not if it is completely false’. In each case, the philosopher uses the biguous
signification of the syncategorematic term to analyze broader logical problems.
The sophisma ‘Every man is of necessity an animal’ has biguity through the
syncategorematic ‘every’ that leads to broader philosophical problems. In the
1270s, Boethius of Dacia analyzed this sophisma in terms of its applicability
when no man exists. Is the knowledge derived from understanding the proposition
destroyed when the object known is destroyed? Does ‘man’ signify anything when
there are no men? If we can correctly predicate a genus of a species, is the
nature of the genus in that species something other than, or distinct from,
what finally differentiates the species? In this case, the sophisma proves a
useful approach to addressing metaphysical and epistemological problems central
to Scholastic discourse.
BACON, ROGER; SHERWOOD;
SYNCATEGOREMATA. S.E.L. Sophists, any of a number of ancient Greeks, roughly
contemporaneous with Socrates, who professed to teach, for a fee, rhetoric,
philosophy, and how to succeed in life. They typically were itinerants,
visiting much of the Greek world, and gave public exhibitions at Olympia and
Delphi. They were part of the general expansion of Greek learning and of the
changing culture in which the previous informal educational methods were
inadequate. For exple, the growing litigiousness of Athenian society demanded
Solovyov, Vladimir Sophists 862 862
instruction in the art of speaking well, which the Sophists helped fulfill. The
Sophists have been portrayed as intellectual charlatans (hence the pejorative
use of ‘sophism’), teaching their sophistical reasoning for money, and (at the
other extreme) as Victorian moralists and educators. The truth is more complex.
They were not a school, and shared no body of opinions. They were typically
concerned with ethics (unlike many earlier philosophers, who emphasized
physical inquiries) and about the relationship between laws and customs (nomos)
and nature (phusis). Protagoras of Abdera (c.490–c.420 B.C.) was the most fous
and perhaps the first Sophist. He visited Athens frequently, and bece a friend
of its leader, Pericles; he therefore was invited to draw up a legal code for
the colony of Thurii (444). According to some late reports, he died in a
shipwreck as he was leaving Athens, having been tried for and found guilty of
impiety. (He claimed that he knew nothing about the gods, because of human
limitations and the difficulty of the question.) We have only a few short
quotations from his works. His “Truth” (also known as the “Throws,” i.e., how
to overthrow an opponent’s arguments) begins with his most fous claim: “Humans
are the measure of all things – of things that are, that they are, of things
that are not, that they are not.” That is, there is no objective truth; the
world is for each person as it appears to that person. Of what use, then, are
skills? Skilled people can change others’ perceptions in useful ways. For
exple, a doctor can change a sick person’s perceptions so that she is healthy.
Protagoras taught his students to “make the weaker argument the stronger,”
i.e., to alter people’s perceptions about the value of arguments. (Aristophanes
satirizes Protagoras as one who would make unjust arguments defeat just
arguments.) This is true for ethical judgments, too: laws and customs are simply
products of human agreement. But because laws and customs result from
experiences of what is most useful, they should be followed rather than nature.
No perception or judgment is more true than another, but some are more useful,
and those that are more useful should be followed. Gorgias (c.483–376) was a
student of Empedocles. His town, Leontini in Sicily, sent him as an bassador to
Athens in 427; his visit was a great success, and the Athenians were azed at
his rhetorical ability. Like other Sophists, he charged for instruction and
gave speeches at religious festivals. Gorgias denied that he taught virtue;
instead, he produced clever speakers. He insisted that different people have
different virtues: for exple, women’s virtue differs from men’s. Since there is
no truth (and if there were we couldn’t know it), we must rely on opinion, and
so speakers who can change people’s opinions have great power – greater than
the power produced by any other skill. (In his “Encomium on Helen” he argues
that if she left Menelaus and went with Paris because she was convinced by
speech, she wasn’t responsible for her actions.) Two paraphrases of Gorgias’s
“About What Doesn’t Exist” survive; in this he argues that nothing exists, that
even if something did, we couldn’t know it, and that even if we could know
anything we couldn’t explain it to anyone. We can’t know anything, because some
things we think of do not exist, and so we have no way of judging whether the
things we think of exist. And we can’t express any knowledge we may have,
because no two people can think of the se thing, since the se thing can’t be in
two places, and because we use words in speech, not colors or shapes or
objects. (This may be merely a parody of Parmenides’ argument that only one
thing exists.) Antiphon the Sophist (fifth century) is probably (although not
certainly) to be distinguished from Antiphon the orator (d. 411), some of whose
speeches we possess. We know nothing about his life (if he is distinct from the
orator). In addition to brief quotations in later authors, we have two papyrus
fragments of his “On Truth.” In these he argues that we should follow laws and
customs only if there are witnesses and so our action will affect our
reputation; otherwise, we should follow nature, which is often inconsistent
with following custom. Custom is established by human agreement, and so
disobeying it is detrimental only if others know it is disobeyed, whereas
nature’s demands (unlike those of custom) can’t be ignored with impunity.
Antiphon assumes that rational actions are selfinterested, and that justice
demands actions contrary to self-interest – a position Plato attacks in the
Republic. Antiphon was also a materialist: the nature of a bed is wood, since
if a buried bed could grow it would grow wood, not a bed. His view is one of
Aristotle’s main concerns in the Physics, since Aristotle admits in the
Categories that persistence through change is the best test for substance, but
won’t admit that matter is substance. Hippias (fifth century) was from Elis, in
the Peloponnesus, which used him as an basSophists Sophists 863 863 sador. He competed at the festival of
Olympus with both prepared and extemporaneous speeches. He had a phenomenal
memory. Since Plato repeatedly makes fun of him in the two dialogues that bear
his ne, he probably was selfimportant and serious. He was a polymath who
claimed he could do anything, including making speeches and clothes; he wrote a
work collecting what he regarded as the best things said by others. According
to one report, he made a mathematical discovery (the quadratrix, the first
curve other than the circle known to the Greeks). In the Protagoras, Plato has
Hippias contrast nature and custom, which often does violence to nature.
Prodicus (fifth century) was from Ceos, in the Cyclades, which frequently
employed him on diplomatic missions. He apparently demanded high fees, but had
two versions of his lecture – one cost fifty drachmas, the other one drachma.
(Socrates jokes that if he could have afforded the fifty-drachma lecture, he
would have learned the truth about the correctness of words, and Aristotle says
that when Prodicus added something exciting to keep his audience’s attention he
called it “slipping in the fifty-drachma lecture for them.”) We have at least
the content of one lecture of his, the “Choice of Heracles,” which consists of
banal moralizing. Prodicus was praised by Socrates for his emphasis on the
right use of words and on distinguishing between synonyms. He also had a
naturalistic view of the origin of theology: useful things were regarded as
gods.
Sorel, Georges (1847–1922), French socialist
activist and philosopher best known for his Reflections on Violence (1906),
which develops the notion of revolutionary syndicalism as seen through
proletarian violence and the interpretation of myth. An early proponent of the
quasiMarxist position of gradual democratic reformism, Sorel eventually
developed a highly subjective interpretation of historical materialism that,
while retaining a conception of proletarian revolution, now understood it
through myth rather than reason. He was in large part reacting to the
empiricism of the French Enlightenment and the statistical structuring of
sociological studies. In contrast to Marx and Engels, who held that revolution
would occur when the proletariat attained its own class consciousness through
an understanding of its true relationship to the means of production in
capitalist society, Sorel introduced myth rather than reason as the correct way
to interpret social totality. Myth allows for the necessary reaction to
bourgeois rationalism and permits the social theorist to negate the status quo
through the authenticity of revolutionary violence. By acknowledging the
irrationality of the status quo, myth permits the possibility of social
understanding and its necessary reaction, human emancipation through
proletarian revolution. Marxism is myth because it juxtaposes the
irreducibility of capitalist organization to its negation – violent proletarian
revolution. The intermediary stage in this development is radical syndicalism,
which organizes workers into groups opposed to bourgeois authority, instills
the myth of proletarian revolution in the workers, and allows them in
postrevolutionary times to work toward a social arrangement of worker and
peasant governance and collaboration. The vehicle through which all this is
accomplished is the general strike, whose aim, through the justified violence
of its ends, is to facilitate the downfall and ultimate elimination of the
bourgeoisie. In doing so the proletariat will lead society to a classless and
harmonious stage in history. By stressing the notion of spontaneity Sorel
thought he had solved the vexing problems of party and future bureaucracy found
in much of the revolutionary literature of his day. In his later years he was
interested in the writings of both Lenin and Mussolini.
sorites, an argument
consisting of categorical propositions that can be represented as (or
decomposed into) a sequence of categorical syllogisms such that the conclusion
of each syllogism except the last one in the sequence is a premise of the next
syllogism in the sequence. An exple is ‘All cats are felines; all felines are
mmals; all mmals are warm-blooded animals; therefore, all cats are warm-blooded
animals’. This sorites may be viewed as composed of the two syllogisms ‘All
cats are felines; all felines are mmals; therefore, all cats are mmals’ and
‘All cats are mmals; all mmals are warm-blooded animals; therefore, all cats
are warm-blooded animals’. A sorites is valid if and only if each categorical
syllogism into which it decomposes is valid. In the exple, the sorites
decomposes into two syllogisms in (the mood) Barbara; since any syllogism in
Barbara is valid, the sorites is valid.
sorites paradox (from
Greek soros, ‘heap’), any of a number of paradoxes about heaps and their Sorel,
Georges sorites paradox 864 864
elements, and more broadly about gradations. A single grain of sand cannot be
arranged so as to form a heap. Moreover, it seems that given a number of grains
insufficient to form a heap, adding just one more grain still does not make a
heap. (If a heap cannot be formed with one grain, it cannot be formed with two;
if a heap cannot be formed with two, it cannot be formed with three; and so on.)
But this seems to lead to the absurdity that however large the number of
grains, it is not large enough to form a heap. A similar paradox can be
developed in the opposite direction. A million grains of sand can certainly be
arranged so as to form a heap, and it is always possible to remove a grain from
a heap in such a way that what is left is also a heap. This seems to lead to
the absurdity that a heap can be formed even from just a single grain. These
paradoxes about heaps were known in antiquity (they are associated with
Eubulides of Miletus, fourth century B.C.), and have since given their ne to a
number of similar paradoxes. The loss of a single hair does not make a man
bald, and a man with a million hairs is certainly not bald. This seems to lead
to the absurd conclusion that even a man with no hairs at all is not bald. Or
consider a long painted wall (hundreds of yards or hundreds of miles long). The
left-hand region is clearly painted red, but there is a subtle gradation of
shades and the right-hand region is clearly yellow. A small double window
exposes a small section of the wall at any one time. It is moved progressively
rightward, in such a way that at each move after the initial position the
left-hand segment of the window exposes just the area that was in the previous
position exposed by the right-hand segment. The window is so small relative to
the wall that in no position can you tell any difference in color between the
exposed areas. When the window is at the extreme left, both exposed areas are
certainly red. But as the window moves to the right, the area in the right
segment looks just the se color as the area in the left, which you have already
pronounced to be red. So it seems that one must call it red too. But then one
is led to the absurdity of calling a clearly yellow area red. As some of these
cases suggest, there is a connection with dynic processes. A tadpole turns
gradually into a frog. Yet if you analyze a motion picture of the process, it
seems that there are no two adjacent fres of which you can say the earlier
shows a tadpole, the later a frog. So it seems that you could argue: if
something is a tadpole at a given moment, it must also be a tadpole (and not a
frog) a millionth of a second later, and this seems to lead to the absurd conclusion
that a tadpole can never turn into a frog. Most responses to this paradox
attempt to deny the “major premise,” the one corresponding to the claim that if
you cannot make a heap with n grains of sand then you cannot make a heap with n
! 1. The difficulty is that the negation of this premise is equivalent, in
classical logic, to the proposition that there is a sharp cutoff: that, e.g.,
there is some number n of grains that are not enough to make a heap, where n !
1 are enough to make a heap. The claim of a sharp cutoff may not be so very
implausible for heaps (perhaps for things like grains of sand, four is the
smallest number which can be formed into a heap) but is very implausible for
colors and tadpoles. There are two main kinds of response to sorites paradoxes.
One is to accept that there is in every such case a sharp cutoff, though
typically we do not, and perhaps cannot, know where it is. Another kind of
response is to evolve a non-classical logic within which one can refuse to
accept the major premise without being committed to a sharp cutoff. At present,
no such non-classical logic is entirely free of difficulties. So sorites
paradoxes are still taken very seriously by contemporary philosophers.
sortal predicate,
roughly, a predicate whose application to an object says what kind of object it
is and implies conditions for objects of that kind to be identical. Person,
green apple, regular hexagon, and pile of coal would generally be regarded as
sortal predicates, whereas tall, green thing, and coal would generally be
regarded as non-sortal predicates. An explicit and precise definition of the
distinction is hard to come by. Sortal predicates are sometimes said to be
distinguished by the fact that they provide a criterion of counting or that they
do not apply to the parts of the objects to which they apply, but there are
difficulties with each of these characterizations. The notion figures in recent
philosophical discussions on various topics. Robert Ackermann and others have
suggested that any scientific law confirmable by observation might require the
use of sortal predicates. Thus ‘all non-black things are non-ravens’, while
logically equivalent to the putative scientific law ‘all ravens are black’, is
not itself confirmable by observation because ‘non-black’ is not a sortal
predicate. David Wiggins and others have discussed the sortal sortal predicate
865 865 idea that all identity claims
are sortal-relative in the sense that an appropriate response to the claim a %
b is always “the se what as b?” John Wallace has argued that there would be
advantages in relativizing the quantifiers of predicate logic to sortals. ‘All
humans are mortal’ would be rendered Ex[m]Dx, rather than Ex(MxPDx). Crispin
Wright has suggested that the view that natural number is a sortal concept is
central to Frege’s (or any other) number-theoretic platonism. The word ‘sortal’
as a technical term in philosophy apparently first occurs in Locke’s Essay
Concerning Human Understanding. Locke argues that the so-called essence of a
genus or sort (unlike the real essence of a thing) is merely the abstract idea
that the general or sortal ne stands for. But ‘sortal’ has only one occurrence
in Locke’s Essay. Its currency in contemporary philosophical idiom probably
should be credited to P. F. Strawson’s Individuals. The general idea may be
traced at least to the notion of second substance in Aristotle’s
Categories.
Soto, Domingo de
(1494–1560), Spanish Dominican theologian and philosopher. Born in Segovia, he
studied in Alcalá de Henares and Paris, taught at Segovia and Salanca, and was
ned official representative of the Holy Roman Empire at the Council of Trent by
Charles V. ong Soto’s many works, his commentaries on Aristotle’s Physics and
On the Soul stand out. He also wrote a book on the nature of grace and an
important treatise on law. Soto was one of the early members of the school of
Spanish Thomism, but he did not always follow Aquinas. He rejected the doctrine
of the real distinction between essence and existence and adopted Duns Scotus’s
position that the primary object of human understanding is indeterminate being
in general. Apart from metaphysics and theology, Soto’s philosophy of law and
political theory are historically important. He maintained, contrary to his
teacher Vitoria, that law originates in the understanding rather than in the
will of the legislator. He also distinguished natural from positive law: the
latter arises from the decision of legislators, whereas the former is based on
nature. Soto was a founder of the general theory of international law. AQUINAS, PHILOSOPHY OF LAW. J.J.E.G. soul,
also called spirit, an entity supposed to be present only in living things,
corresponding to the Greek psyche and Latin anima. Since there seems to be no
material difference between an organism in the last moments of its life and the
organism’s newly dead body, many philosophers since the time of Plato have
claimed that the soul is an immaterial component of an organism. Because only
material things are observed to be subject to dissolution, Plato took the
soul’s immateriality as grounds for its immortality. Neither Plato nor
Aristotle thought that only persons had souls: Aristotle ascribed souls to
animals and plants since they all exhibited some living functions. Unlike Plato,
Aristotle denied the transmigration of souls from one species to another or
from one body to another after death; he was also more skeptical about the
soul’s capacity for disembodiment – roughly, survival and functioning without a
body. Descartes argued that only persons had souls and that the soul’s
immaterial nature made freedom possible even if the human body is subject to
deterministic physical laws. As the subject of thought, memory, emotion,
desire, and action, the soul has been supposed to be an entity that makes
self-consciousness possible, that differentiates simultaneous experiences into
experiences either of the se person or of different persons, and that accounts
for personal identity or a person’s continued identity through time. Dualists
argue that soul and body must be distinct in order to explain consciousness and
the possibility of immortality. Materialists argue that consciousness is
entirely the result of complex physical processes.
soundness, (1) (of an
argument) the property of being valid and having all true premises; (2) (of a
logic) the property of being not too strong in a certain respect. A logic L has
weak soundness provided every theorem of L is valid. And L has strong soundness
if for every set G of sentences, every sentence deducible from G using L is a
logical consequence of G. COMPLETENESS,
LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE, LOGICAL FORM, VALID. G.F.S. soundness, strong.SOUNDNESS.
soundness, weak.SOUNDNESS. sovereignty, divine.DIVINE ATTRIBUTES. space, an
extended manifold of several dimensions, where the number of dimensions
corresponds to the number of variable magnitudes Soto, Domingo de space
866 866 needed to specify a location in
the manifold; in particular, the three-dimensional manifold in which physical
objects are situated and with respect to which their mutual positions and
distances are defined. Ancient Greek atomism defined space as the infinite void
in which atoms move; but whether space is finite or infinite, and whether void
spaces exist, have remained in question. Aristotle described the universe as a
finite plenum and reduced space to the aggregate of all places of physical
things. His view was preeminent until Renaissance Neoplatonism, the Copernican
revolution, and the revival of atomism reintroduced infinite, homogeneous space
as a fundental cosmological assumption. Further controversy concerned whether
the space assumed by early modern astronomy should be thought of as an
independently existing thing or as an abstraction from the spatial relations of
physical bodies. Interest in the relativity of motion encouraged the latter
view, but Newton pointed out that mechanics presupposes absolute distinctions
ong motions, and he concluded that absolute space must be postulated along with
the basic laws of motion (Principia, 1687). Leibniz argued for the relational
view from the identity of indiscernibles: the parts of space are
indistinguishable from one another and therefore cannot be independently
existing things. Relativistic physics has defused the original controversy by
revealing both space and spatial relations as merely observer-dependent
manifestations of the structure of spacetime. Meanwhile, Kant shifted the
metaphysical controversy to epistemological grounds by claiming that space,
with its Euclidean structure, is neither a “thing-in-itself” nor a relation of
thingsin-themselves, but the a priori form of outer intuition. His view was
challenged by the elaboration of non-Euclidean geometries in the nineteenth
century, by Helmholtz’s arguments that both intuitive and physical space are
known through empirical investigation, and finally by the use of non-Euclidean
geometry in the theory of relativity. Precisely what geometrical
presuppositions are inherent in human spatial perception, and what must be
learned from experience, remain subjects of psychological investigation.
RELATIVITY, SPACE-TIME,
TIME. R.D. space, absolute.SPACE. space, life.LEWIN. space, mathematical.SPACE.
space, phase.STATE. space, state.STATE. space-time, a four-dimensional
continuum combining the three dimensions of space with time in order to
represent motion geometrically. Each point is the location of an event, all of
which together represent “the world” through time; paths in the continuum
(worldlines) represent the dynical histories of moving particles, so that
straight worldlines correspond to uniform motions; three-dimensional sections
of constant time value (“spacelike hypersurfaces” or “simultaneity slices”)
represent all of space at a given time. The idea was foreshadowed when Kant
represented “the phenomenal world” as a plane defined by space and time as
perpendicular axes (Inaugural Dissertation, 1770), and when Joseph Louis
Lagrange (1736–1814) referred to mechanics as “the analytic geometry of four
dimensions.” But classical mechanics assumes a universal standard of
simultaneity, and so it can treat space and time separately. The concept of
space-time was explicitly developed only when Einstein criticized absolute
simultaneity and made the velocity of light a universal constant. The mathematician
Hermann Minkowski showed in 1908 that the observer-independent structure of
special relativity could be represented by a metric space of four dimensions:
observers in relative motion would disagree on intervals of length and time,
but agree on a fourdimensional interval combining spatial and temporal
measurements. Minkowski’s model then made possible the general theory of
relativity, which describes gravity as a curvature of spacetime in the presence
of mass and the paths of falling bodies as the straightest worldlines in curved
space-time.
spatiotemporal
continuity, a property of the careers, or space-time paths, of well-behaved
objects. Let a space-time path be a series of possible spatiotemporal
positions, each represented (in a selected coordinate system) by an ordered
pair consisting of a time (its temporal component) and a volume of space (its
spatial component). Such a path will be spatiotemporally continuous provided it
is such that, relative to any inertial fre selected as coordinate system, space,
absolute spatiotemporal continuity 867
867 (1) for every segment of the series, the temporal components of the
members of that segment form a continuous temporal interval; and (2) for any
two members ‹ti, Vi( and ‹tj, Vj( of the series that differ in their temporal
components (ti and tj), if Vi and Vj (the spatial components) differ in either
shape, size, or location, then between these members of the series there will
be a member whose spatial component is more similar to Vi and Vj in these respects
than these are to each other. This notion is of philosophical interest partly
because of its connections with the notions of identity over time and
causality. Putting aside such qualifications as quantum considerations may
require, material objects (at least macroscopic objects of filiar kinds)
apparently cannot undergo discontinuous change of place, and cannot have
temporal gaps in their histories, and therefore the path through space-time
traced by such an object must apparently be spatiotemporally continuous. More
controversial is the claim that spatiotemporal continuity, together with some
continuity with respect to other properties, is sufficient as well as necessary
for the identity of such objects – e.g., that if a spatiotemporally continuous
path is such that the spatial component of each member of the series is
occupied by a table of a certain description at the time that is the temporal
component of that member, then there is a single table of that description that
traces that path. Those who deny this claim sometimes maintain that it is
further required for the identity of material objects that there be causal and
counterfactual dependence of later states on earlier ones (ceteris paribus, if
the table had been different yesterday, it would be correspondingly different
now). Since it appears that chains of causality must trace spatiotemporally
continuous paths, it may be that insofar as spatiotemporal continuity is
required for transtemporal identity, this is because it is required for
transtemporal causality.
specious present, the
supposed time between past and future. The term was first offered by E. R. Clay
in The Alternative: A Study in Psychology (1882), and was cited by Jes in
Chapter XV of his Principles of Psychology (1890). Clay challenges the
assumption that the “present” as a “datum” is given as “present” to us in our
experience. “The present to which the datum refers is really a part of the past
– a recent past – delusively given as benign time that intervenes between the
past and the future. Let it be ned the specious present, and let the past that
is given as being the past be known as the obvious past.” For Jes, this
position is supportive of his contention that consciousness is a stre and can
be divided into parts only by conceptual addition, i.e., only by our ascribing
past, present, and future to what is, in our actual experience, a seless flow.
Jes holds that the “practically cognized present is no knife-edge but a
saddleback,” a sort of “ducatum” which we experience as a whole, and only upon
reflective attention do we “distinguish its beginning from its end.” Whereas
Clay refers to the datum of the present as “delusive,” one might rather say
that it is perpetually elusive, for as we have our experience, now, it is
always bathed retrospectively and prospectively. Contrary to common wisdom, no
single experience ever is had by our consciousness utterly alone, single and
without relations, fore and aft. TIME.
J.J.M. speckled hen.
speculative philosophy, a
form of theorizing that goes beyond verifiable observation; specifically, a
philosophical approach informed by the impulse to construct a grand narrative
of a worldview that encompasses the whole of reality. Speculative philosophy
purports to bind together reflections on the existence and nature of the
cosmos, the psyche, and God. It sets for its goal a unifying matrix and an
overarching system wherespeaker’s meaning speculative philosophy 868 868 with to comprehend the considered
judgments of cosmology, psychology, and theology. Hegel’s absolute idealism,
particularly as developed in his later thought, paradigmatically illustrates
the requirements for speculative philosophizing. His system of idealism offered
a vision of the unity of the categories of human thought as they come to realization
in and through their opposition to each other. Speculative thought tends to
place a premium on universality, totality, and unity; and it tends to
marginalize the concrete particularities of the natural and social world. In
its aggressive use of the systematic principle, geared to a unification of
human experience, speculative philosophy aspires to a comprehensive
understanding and explanation of the structural interrelations of the culture
spheres of science, morality, art, and religion.
speech act theory, the
theory of language use, sometimes called pragmatics, as opposed to the theory
of meaning, or semantics. Based on the meaning–use distinction, it categorizes
systematically the sorts of things that can be done with words and explicates
the ways these are determined, underdetermined, or undetermined by the meanings
of the words used. Relying further on the distinction between speaker meaning
and linguistic meaning, it aims to characterize the nature of communicative
intentions and how they are expressed and recognized. Speech acts are a species
of intentional action. In general, one and the se utterance may comprise a
number of distinct though related acts, each corresponding to a different
intention on the part of the speaker. Beyond intending to produce a certain
sequence of sounds forming a sentence in English, a person who utters the
sentence ‘The door is open’, e.g., is likely to be intending to perform, in the
terminology of J. L. Austin (How to Do Things with Words, 1962), (1) the locutionary
act of saying (expressing the proposition) that a certain door is open, (2) the
illocutionary act of making the statement (expressing the belief) that it is
open, and (3) the perlocutionary act of getting his listener to believe that it
is open. In so doing, he may be performing the indirect speech act of
requesting (illocutionary) the listener to close the door and of getting
(perlocutionary) the hearer to close the door. The primary focus of speech act
theory is on illocutionary acts, which may be classified in a variety of ways.
Statements, predictions, and answers exemplify constatives; requests, commands
and permissions are directives; promises, offers, and bets are commissives;
greetings, apologies, and congratulations are acknowledgments. These are all
communicative illocutionary acts, each distinguished by the type of
psychological state expressed by the speaker. Successful communication consists
in the audience’s recognition of the speaker’s intention to be expressing a
certain psychological state with a certain content. Conventional illocutionary
acts, on the other hand, effect or officially affect institutional states of
affairs. Exples of the former are appointing, resigning, sentencing, and
adjourning; exples of the latter are assessing, acquitting, certifying, and
grading. (See Kent Bach and Robert M. Harnish, Linguistic Communication and
Speech Acts, 1979.) The type of act an utterance exemplifies determines its
illocutionary force. In the exple ‘The door is open’, the utterance has the force
of both a statement and a request. The illocutionary force potential of a
sentence is the force or forces with which it can be used literally, e.g., in
the case of the sentence ‘The door is open’, as a statement but not as a
request. The felicity conditions on an illocutionary act pertain not only to
its communicative or institutional success but also to its sincerity,
appropriateness, and effectiveness. An explicit performative utterance is an
illocutionary act performed by uttering an indicative sentence in the simple
present tense with a verb ning the type of act being performed, e.g., ‘I
apologize for everything I did’ and ‘You are requested not to smoke’. The
adverb ‘hereby’ may be used before the performative verb (‘apologize’ and
‘request’ in these exples) to indicate that the very utterance being made is
the vehicle of the performance of the illocutionary act in question. A good
test for distinguishing illocutionary from perlocutionary acts is to determine
whether a verb ning the act can be used performatively. Austin exploited the
phenomenon of performative utterances to expose the common philosophical error
of assuming that the primary use of language is to make statements.
Spencer, Herbert
(1820–1903), English philosopher, social reformer, and editor of The Economist.
In epistemology, Spencer adopted the ninespeculative reason Spencer, Herbert
869 869 teenth-century trend toward
positivism: the only reliable knowledge of the universe is to be found in the
sciences. His ethics were utilitarian, following Benth and J. S. Mill: pleasure
and pain are the criteria of value as signs of happiness or unhappiness in the
individual. His Synthetic Philosophy, expounded in books written over many
years, assumed (both in biology and psychology) the existence of Larckian
evolution: given a characteristic environment, every animal possesses a
disposition to make itself into what it will, failing maladaptive
interventions, eventually become. The dispositions gain expression as inherited
acquired habits. Spencer could not accept that species originate by chance
variations and natural selection alone: direct adaptation to environmental
constraints is mainly responsible for biological changes. Evolution also
includes the progression of societies in the direction of a dynical equilibrium
of individuals: the human condition is perfectible because human faculties are
completely adapted to life in society, implying that evil and immorality will
eventually disappear. His ideas on evolution predated publication of the major
works of Darwin; A. R. Wallace was influenced by his writings.
Spinoza, Baruch
(1632–77), Dutch metaphysician, epistemologist, psychologist, moral
philosopher, political theorist, and philosopher of religion, generally
regarded as one of the most important figures of seventeenth-century
rationalism. Life and works. Born and educated in the Jewish community of
sterd, he forsook his given ne ‘Baruch’ in favor of the Latin ‘Benedict’ at the
age of twenty-two. Between 1652 and 1656 he studied the philosophy of Descartes
in the school of Francis van den Enden. Having developed unorthodox views of
the divine nature (and having ceased to be fully observant of Jewish practice),
he was excommunicated by the Jewish community in 1656. He spent his entire life
in Holland; after leaving sterd in 1660, he resided successively in Rijnsburg,
Voorburg, and the Hague. He supported himself at least partly through grinding
lenses, and his knowledge of optics involved him in an area of inquiry of great
importance to seventeenth-century science. Acquainted with such leading
intellectual figures as Leibniz, Huygens, and Henry Oldenberg, he declined a
professorship at the University of Heidelberg partly on the grounds that it
might interfere with his intellectual freedom. His premature death at the age
of fortyfour was due to consumption. The only work published under Spinoza’s ne
during his lifetime was his Principles of Descartes’s Philosophy (Renati Des
Cartes Principiorum Philosophiae, Pars I et II, 1663), an attempt to recast and
present Parts I and II of Descartes’s Principles of Philosophy in the manner
that Spinoza called geometrical order or geometrical method. Modeled on the
Elements of Euclid and on what Descartes called the method of synthesis,
Spinoza’s “geometrical order” involves an initial set of definitions and
axioms, from which various propositions are demonstrated, with notes or scholia
attached where necessary. This work, which established his credentials as an
expositor of Cartesian philosophy, had its origins in his endeavor to teach
Descartes’s Principles of Philosophy to a private student. Spinoza’s
TheologicalPolitical Treatise (Tractatus Theologico-Politicus) was published
anonymously in 1670. After his death, his close circle of friends published his
Posthumous Works (Opera Postuma, 1677), which included his masterpieces, Ethic,
Demonstrated in Geometrical Order (Ethica, Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata). The
Posthumous Works also included his early unfinished Treatise on the Emendation
of the Intellect (Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione), his later unfinished
Political Treatise (Tractatus Politicus), a Hebrew Grmar, and Correspondence.
An unpublished early work entitled Short Treatise on God, Man, and His
Well-Being (Korte Vorhandelung van God, de Mensch en deszelvs Welstand), in
many ways a forerunner of the Ethics, was rediscovered (in copied manuscript)
and published in the nineteenth century. Spinoza’s authorship of two brief
scientific treatises, On the Rainbow and On the Calculation of Chances, is
still disputed. Metaphysics. Spinoza often uses the term ‘God, or Nature’
(“Deus, sive Natura“), and this identification of God with Nature is at the
heart of his metaphysics. Because of this identification, his philosophy is
often regarded as a version of pantheism and/or naturalism. But although
philosophy begins with metaphysics for Spinoza, his metaphysics is ultimately
in the service of his ethics. Because his naturalized God has no desires or
purposes, human ethics cannot properly be derived from divine command. Rather,
Spinozistic ethics seeks to demonstrate, from an adequate understanding of the
divine nature and its expression in human nature, the way in which human beings
can maximize their advantage. Central to the successful pursuit of this
Speusippus Spinoza, Baruch 870 870
advantage is adequate knowledge, which leads to increasing control of the
passions and to cooperative action. Spinoza’s ontology, like that of Descartes,
consists of substances, their attributes (which Descartes called principal attributes),
and their modes. In the Ethics, Spinoza defines ‘substance’ as what is “in
itself, and is conceived through itself”; ‘attribute’ as that which “the
intellect perceives of a substance as constituting its essence”; and ‘mode’ as
“the affections of a substance, or that which is in another through which also
it is conceived.” While Descartes had recognized a strict sense in which only
God is a substance, he also recognized a second sense in which there are two
kinds of created substances, each with its own principal attribute: extended
substances, whose only principal attribute is extension; and minds, whose only
principal attribute is thought. Spinoza, in contrast, consistently maintains
that there is only one substance. His metaphysics is thus a form of substantial
monism. This one substance is God, which Spinoza defines as “a being absolutely
infinite, i.e., a substance consisting of an infinity of attributes, of which
each expresses an eternal and infinite essence.” Thus, whereas Descartes
limited each created substance to one principal attribute, Spinoza claims that
the one substance has infinite attributes, each expressing the divine nature
without limitation in its own way. Of these infinite attributes, however,
humans can comprehend only two: extension and thought. Within each attribute,
the modes of God are of two kinds: infinite modes, which are pervasive features
of each attribute, such as the laws of nature; and finite modes, which are
local and limited modifications of substance. There is an infinite sequence of
finite modes. Descartes regarded a human being as a substantial union of two
different substances, the thinking soul and the extended body, in causal
interaction with each other. Spinoza, in contrast, regards a human being as a
finite mode of God, existing simultaneously in God as a mode of thought and as
a mode of extension. He holds that every mode of extension is literally
identical with the mode of thought that is the “idea of” that mode of
extension. Since the human mind is the idea of the human body, it follows that
the human mind and the human body are literally the se thing, conceived under
two different attributes. Because they are actually identical, there is no
causal interaction between the mind and the body; but there is a complete
parallelism between what occurs in the mind and what occurs in the body. Since
every mode of extension has a corresponding and identical mode of thought
(however rudimentary that might be), Spinoza allows that every mode of
extension is “animated to some degree”; his view is thus a form of panpsychism.
Another central feature of Spinoza’s metaphysics is his necessitarianism,
expressed in his claim that “things could have been produced . . . in no other
way, and in no other order” than that in which they have been produced. He
derives this necessitarianism from his doctrine that God exists necessarily
(for which he offers several arguments, including a version of the ontological
argument) and his doctrine that everything that can follow from the divine
nature must necessarily do so. Thus, although he does not use the term, he
accepts a very strong version of the principle of sufficient reason. At the
outset of the Ethics, he defines a thing as free when its actions are
determined by its own nature alone. Only God – whose actions are determined
entirely by the necessity of his own nature, and for whom nothing is external –
is completely free in this sense. Nevertheless, human beings can achieve a
relative freedom to the extent that they live the kind of life described in the
later parts of the Ethics. Hence, Spinoza is a compatibilist concerning the
relation between freedom and determinism. “Freedom of the will” in any sense
that implies a lack of causal determination, however, is simply an illusion based
on ignorance of the true causes of a being’s actions. The recognition that all
occurrences are causally determined, Spinoza holds, has a positive consolatory
power that aids one in controlling the passions. Epistemology and psychology.
Like other rationalists, Spinoza distinguishes two representational faculties:
the imagination and the intellect. The imagination is a faculty of forming
imagistic representations of things, derived ultimately from the mechanisms of
the senses; the intellect is a faculty of forming adequate, nonimagistic
conceptions of things. He also distinguishes three “kinds of knowledge.” The
first or lowest kind he calls opinion or imagination (opinio, imaginatio). It
includes “random or indeterminate experience” (experientia vaga) and also
“hearsay, or knowledge from mere signs”; it thus depends on the confused and
mutilated deliverances of the senses, and is inadequate. The second kind of
knowledge he calls reason (ratio); it depends on common notions (i.e., features
of things that are “common to all, and equally in the part and in the whole”)
or on adequate knowledge of the properties (as opposed to the Spinoza, Baruch
Spinoza, Baruch 871 871 essences) of
things. The third kind of knowledge he calls intuitive knowledge (scientia
intuitiva); it proceeds from adequate knowledge of the essence or attributes of
God to knowledge of the essence of things, and hence proceeds in the proper
order, from causes to effects. Both the second and third kinds of knowledge are
adequate. The third kind is preferable, however, as involving not only certain
knowledge that something is so, but also knowledge of how and why it is so.
Because there is only one substance – God – the individual things of the world
are not distinguished from one another by any difference of substance. Rather,
ong the internal qualitative modifications and differentiations of each divine
attribute, there are patterns that have a tendency to endure; these constitute
individual things. (As they occur within the attribute of extension, Spinoza
calls these patterns fixed proportions of motion and rest.) Although these
individual things are thus modes of the one substance, rather than substances
in their own right, each has a nature or essence describable in terms of the
thing’s particular pattern and its mechanisms for the preservation of its own
being. This tendency toward self-preservation Spinoza calls conatus (sometimes
translated as ‘endeavor’). Every individual thing has some conatus. An
individual thing acts, or is active, to the extent that what occurs can be
explained or understood through its own nature (i.e., its selfpreservatory
mechanism) alone; it is passive to the extent that what happens must be
explained through the nature of other forces impinging on it. Thus, every thing,
to whatever extent it can, actively strives to persevere in its existence; and
whatever aids this self-preservation constitutes that individual’s advantage.
Spinoza’s specifically human psychology is an application of this more general
doctrine of conatus. That application is made through appeal to several
specific characteristics of human beings: they form imagistic representations
of other individuals by means of their senses; they are sufficiently complex to
undergo increases and decreases in their capacity for action; and they are
capable of engaging in reason. The fundental concepts of his psychology are
desire, which is conatus itself, especially as one is conscious of it as
directed toward attaining a particular object; pleasure, which is an increase
in capacity for action; and pain, which is a decrease in capacity for action.
He defines other emotions in terms of these basic emotions, as they occur in
particular combinations, in particular kinds of circumstances, with particular
kinds of causes, and/or with particular kinds of objects. When a person is the
adequate cause of his or her own emotions, these emotions are active emotions;
otherwise, they are passions. Desire and pleasure can be either active emotions
or passions, depending on the circumstances; pain, however, can only be a
passion. Spinoza does not deny the phenomenon of altruism: one’s
self-preservatory mechanism, and hence one’s desire, can become focused on a
wide variety of objects, including the well-being of a loved person or object –
even to one’s own detriment. However, because he reduces all human motivation,
including altruistic motivation, to permutations of the endeavor to seek one’s
own advantage, his theory is arguably a form of psychological egoism. Ethics.
Spinoza’s ethical theory does not take the form of a set of moral commands.
Rather, he seeks to demonstrate, by considering human actions and appetites
objectively – “just as if it were a Question of lines, planes, and bodies” –
wherein a person’s true advantage lies. Readers who genuinely grasp the
demonstrated truths will, he holds, ipso facto be motivated, to at least some
extent, to live their lives accordingly. Thus, Spinozistic ethics seeks to show
how a person acts when “guided by reason“; to act in this way is at the se time
to act with virtue, or power. All actions that result from understanding –
i.e., all virtuous actions – may be attributed to strength of character
(fortitudo). Such virtuous actions may be further divided into two classes:
those due to tenacity (animositas), or “the Desire by which each one strives,
solely from the dictate of reason, to preserve his being”; and those due to
nobility (generositas), or “the Desire by which each one strives, solely from
the dictate of reason, to aid other men and join them to him in friendship.”
Thus, the virtuous person does not merely pursue private advantage, but seeks
to cooperate with others; returns love for hatred; always acts honestly, not
deceptively; and seeks to join himself with others in a political state.
Nevertheless, the ultimate reason for aiding others and joining them to oneself
in friendship is that “nothing is more useful to man than man” – i.e., because
doing so is conducive to one’s own advantage, and particularly to one’s pursuit
of knowledge, which is a good that can be shared without loss. Although Spinoza
holds that we generally use the terms ‘good’ and ‘evil’ simply to report
subjective appearances – so that we call “good” whatever we desire, and “evil”
whatever we seek to avoid – he proposes that we Spinoza, Baruch Spinoza, Baruch
872 872 define ‘good’ philosophically
as ‘what we certainly know to be useful to us’, and ‘evil’ as ‘what we
certainly know prevents us from being masters of some good’. Since God is
perfect and has no needs, it follows that nothing is either good or evil for
God. Spinoza’s ultimate appeal to the agent’s advantage arguably renders his
ethical theory a form of ethical egoism, even though he emphasizes the
existence of common shareable goods and the (instrumental) ethical importance
of cooperation with others. However, it is not a form of hedonism; for despite
the prominence he gives to pleasure, the ultimate aim of human action is a
higher state of perfection or capacity for action, of whose increasing
attainment pleasure is only an indicator. A human being whose self-preservatory
mechanism is driven or distorted by external forces is said to be in bondage to
the passions; in contrast, one who successfully pursues only what is truly
advantageous, in consequence of genuine understanding of where that advantage
properly lies, is free. Accordingly, Spinoza also expresses his conception of a
virtuous life guided by reason in terms of an ideal “free man.” Above all, the
free man seeks understanding of himself and of Nature. Adequate knowledge, and
particularly knowledge of the third kind, leads to blessedness, to peace of
mind, and to the intellectual love of God. Blessedness is not a reward for
virtue, however, but rather an integral aspect of the virtuous life. The human mind
is itself a part of the infinite intellect of God, and adequate knowledge is an
eternal aspect of that infinite intellect. Hence, as one gains knowledge, a
greater part of one’s own mind comes to be identified with something that is
eternal, and one becomes less dependent on – and less disturbed by – the local
forces of one’s immediate environment. Accordingly, the free man “thinks of
nothing less than of death, and his wisdom is a meditation on life, not on
death.” Moreover, just as one’s adequate knowledge is literally an eternal part
of the infinite intellect of God, the resulting blessedness, peace of mind, and
intellectual love are literally aspects of what might be considered God’s own
eternal “emotional” life. Although this endows the free man with a kind of
blessed immortality, it is not a personal immortality, since the sensation and
memory that are essential to personal individuality are not eternal. Rather,
the free man achieves during his lifetime an increasing participation in a body
of adequate knowledge that has itself always been eternal, so that, at death, a
large part of the free man’s mind has become identified with the eternal. It is
thus a kind of “immortality” in which one can participate while one lives, not
merely when one dies. Politics and philosophical theology. Spinoza’s political
theory, like that of Hobbes, treats rights and power as equivalent. Citizens
give up rights to the state for the sake of the protection that the state can
provide. Hobbes, however, regards this social contract as nearly absolute, one
in which citizens give up all of their rights except the right to resist death.
Spinoza, in contrast, emphasizes that citizens cannot give up the right to
pursue their own advantage as they see it, in its full generality; and hence
that the power, and right, of any actual state is always limited by the state’s
practical ability to enforce its dictates so as to alter the citizens’
continuing perception of their own advantage. Furthermore, he has a more
extensive conception of the nature of an individual’s own advantage than
Hobbes, since for him one’s own true advantage lies not merely in fending off
death and pursuing pleasure, but in achieving the adequate knowledge that
brings blessedness and allows one to participate in that which is eternal. In
consequence, Spinoza, unlike Hobbes, recommends a limited, constitutional state
that encourages freedom of expression and religious toleration. Such a state –
itself a kind of individual – best preserves its own being, and provides both
the most stable and the most beneficial form of government for its citizens. In
his Theological-Political Treatise, Spinoza also takes up popular religion, the
interpretation of Scripture, and their bearing on the well-being of the state.
He characterizes the Old Testent prophets as individuals whose vivid
imaginations produced messages of political value for the ancient Hebrew state.
Using a naturalistic outlook and historical hermeneutic methods that anticipate
the later “higher criticism” of the Bible, he seeks to show that Scriptural
writers themselves consistently treat only justice and charity as essential to
salvation, and hence that dogmatic doxastic requirements are not justified by
Scripture. Popular religion should thus propound only these two requirements,
which it may imaginatively represent, to the minds of the many, as the
requirements for rewards granted by a divine Lawgiver. The few, who are more
philosophical, and who thus rely on intellect, will recognize that the natural
laws of human psychology require charity and justice as conditions of
happiness, and that what the vulgar construe as rewards granted by personal
divine intervention are in fact the natural consequences of a virtuous life.
Spinoza, Baruch Spinoza, Baruch 873 873
Because of his identificaton of God with Nature and his treatment of popular
religion, Spinoza’s contemporaries often regarded his philosophy as a thinly
disguised atheism. Paradoxically, however, nineteenth-century Romanticism
embraced him for his pantheism; Novalis, e.g., fously characterized him as “the
God-intoxicated man.” In fact, Spinoza ascribes to Nature most of the
characteristics that Western theologians have ascribed to God: Spinozistic
Nature is infinite, eternal, necessarily existing, the object of an ontological
argument, the first cause of all things, all-knowing, and the being whose
contemplation produces blessedness, intellectual love, and participation in a
kind of immortality or eternal life. Spinoza’s claim to affirm the existence of
God is therefore no mere evasion. However, he emphatically denies that God is a
person or acts for purposes; that anything is good or evil from the divine
perspective; or that there is a personal immortality involving memory. In
addition to his influence on the history of biblical criticism and on
literature (including not only Novalis but such writers as Wordsworth,
Coleridge, Heine, Shelley, George Eliot, George Sand, Somerset Maugh, Jorge
Luis Borges, and Bernard Malud), Spinoza has affected the philosophical outlooks
of such diverse twentieth-century thinkers as Freud and Einstein. Contemporary
physicists have seen in his monistic metaphysics an anticipation of
twentieth-century field metaphysics. More generally, he is a leading
intellectual forebear of twentieth-century determinism and naturalism, and of
the mind–body identity theory.
Spir, Afrikan (1837–90),
German philosopher. He served in the Crimean War as a Russian officer. A
non-academic, he published books in German and French. His major works are Forschung
nach der Gewissheit in der Erkenntnis der Wirklichkeit (Inquiry concerning
Certainty in the Knowledge of Actuality, 1869) and the two-volume Denken und
Wirklichkeit: Versuch einer Erneuerung der kritischen Philosophie (Thought and
Actuality: Attempt at a Revival of Critical Philosophy, 1873). Thought and
Actuality presents a metaphysics based on the radical separation of the
apparent world and an absolute reality. All we can know about the
“unconditioned” is that it must conform with the principle of identity. While
retaining the unknowable thing-in-itself of Kant, Spir argued for the empirical
reality of time, which is given to us in immediate experience and depends on
our experience of a succession of differential states. The aim of philosophy is
to reach fundental and immediate certainties. Of the works included in his
Gesmelte Schriften (1883– 84), only a relatively minor study, Right and Wrong,
was translated into English (in 1954). There are a number of references to Spir
in the writings of Nietzsche, which indicate that some of Nietzsche’s central
notions were influenced, both positively and negatively, by Spir’s analyses of
becoming and temporality, as well as by his concept of the separation of the
world of appearance and the “true world.” G.J.S. spirit.SOUL. spirit,
Absolute.HEGEL. spissitude.MORE, HENRY. split brain effects, a wide array of
behavioral effects consequent upon the severing of the cerebral commisures, and
generally interpreted as indicating asymmetry in cerebral functions. The human
brain has considerable left–right functional differentiation, or asymmetry,
that affects behavior. The most obvious exple is handedness. By the 1860s
Bouillaud, Dax, and Broca had observed that the effects of unilateral dage
indicated that the left hemisphere was preferentially involved in language.
Since the 1960s, this commitment to functional asymmetry has been reinforced by
studies of patients in whom communication between the hemispheres has been
surgically disrupted. Split brain effects depend on severing the cerebral
commisures, and especially the corpus callosum, which are neural structures
mediating communication between the cerebral hemispheres. Commisurotomies have
been performed since the 1940s to control severe epilepsy. This is intended to
leave both hemispheres intact and functioning independently. Beginning in the
1960s, J. E. Bogen, M. S. Gazzaniga, and R. W. Sperry conducted an array of
psychological tests to evaluate the distinctive abilities of the different
hemispheres. Ascertaining the degree of cerebral asymmetry depends on a
carefully controlled experimental design in which access of the disassociated
hemispheres to peripheral cues is limited. The result has been a wide array of
striking results. For exple, patients are unable to match an object such as a
key felt in one hand with a similar object felt in the other; patients are
unable to ne an object Spir, Afrikan split brain effects 874 874 held in the left hand, though they can
ne an object held in the right. Researchers have concluded that these results
confirm a clear lateralization of speech, writing, and calculation in the left
hemisphere (for righthanded patients), leaving the right hemisphere largely
unable to respond in speech or writing, and typically unable to perform even
simple calculations. It is often concluded that the left hemisphere is
specialized for verbal and analytic modes of thinking, while the right
hemisphere is specialized for more spatial and synthetic modes of thinking. The
precise character and extent of these differences in normal subjects are less
clear.
square of opposition, a
graphic representation of various logical relations ong categorical
propositions. (Relations ong modal and even ong hypothetical propositions have
also been represented on the square.) Two propositions are said to be each
other’s (1) contradictories if exactly one of them must be true and exactly one
false; (2) contraries if they could not both be true although they could both
be false; and (3) subcontraries if at least one of them must be true although
both of them may be true. There is a relation of (4) subalternation of one
proposition, called subaltern, to another called superaltern, if the truth of
the latter implies the truth of the former, but not conversely. Applying these definitions
to the four types of categorical propositions, we find that SaP and SoP are
contradictories, and so are SeP and SiP. SaP and SeP are contraries. SiP and
SoP are subcontraries. SiP is subaltern to SaP, and SoP is subaltern to SeP.
These relations can be represented graphically in a square of opposition: The
four relations on the traditional square are expressed in the following theses:
Contradictories: SaP S -SoP, SeP S -SiP Contraries: -(SaP & SeP) or SaP P
-SeP Subcontraries: SiP 7 SoP Subalterns: SaP P SiP, SeP P SoP For these
relations to hold, an underlying existential assumption must be satisfied: the
terms serving as subjects of propositions must be satisfied, not empty (e.g.,
‘man’ is satisfied and ‘elf’ empty). Only the contradictory opposition remains
without that assumption. Modern interpretations of categorical propositions
exclude the existential assumption; thus, only the contradictory opposition
remains in the square. SYLLOGISM. I.Bo.
square of opposition, modal.
standard model, a term
that, like ‘non-standard model’, is used with regard to theories that
systematize (part of) our knowledge of some mathematical structure, for
instance the structure of natural numbers with addition, multiplication, and
the successor function, or the structure of real numbers with ordering,
addition, and multiplication. Models isomorphic to this intended mathematical
structure are the “standard models” of the theory, while any other,
non-isomorphic, model of the theory is a ‘non-standard’ model. Since Peano
arithmetic is incomplete, it has consistent extensions that have no standard
model. But there are also non-standard, countable models of complete number
theory, the set of all true first-order sentences about natural numbers, as was
first shown by Skolem in 1934. Categorical theories do not have a non-standard
model. It is less clear whether there is a standard model of set theory,
although a countable model would certainly count as non-standard. The Skolem
paradox is that any first-order formulation of set theory, like ZF, due to
Zermelo and Fraenkel, has a countable model, while it seems to assert the
existence of non-countable sets. Many other important mathematical structures
cannot be characterized by a categorical set of first-order axioms, and thus
allow non-standard models. The erican philosopher Putn has argued that this
fact has important implications for the debate about realism in the philosophy
of language. If axioms cannot capture the spontaneity, liberty of standard
model 875 875 “intuitive” notion of a
set, what could? Some of his detractors have pointed out that within
second-order logic categorical characterizations are often possible. But Putn
has objected that the intended interpretation of second-order logic itself is
not fixed by the use of the formalism of second-order logic, where “use” is
determined by the rules of inference for second-order logic we know about.
Moreover, categorical theories are sometimes uninformative. .
state, the way an object
or system basically is; the fundental, intrinsic properties of an object or
system, and the basis of its other properties. An instantaneous state is a
state at a given time. State variables are constituents of a state whose values
may vary with time. In classical or Newtonian mechanics the instantaneous state
of an n-particle system consists of the positions and momenta (masses
multiplied by velocities) of the n particles at a given time. Other mechanical
properties are functions of those in states. Fundental and derived properties
are often, though possibly misleadingly, called observables. The set of a
system’s possible states can be represented as an abstract phase space or state
space, with dimensions or coordinates for (the components of) each state
variable. In quantum theory, states do not fix the particular values of
observables, only the probabilities of observables assuming particular values
in particular measurement situations. For positivism or instrumentalism,
specifying a quantum state does nothing more than provide a means for
calculating such probabilities. For realism, it does more – e.g., it refers to
the basis of a quantum system’s probabilistic dispositions or propensities.
Vectors in Hilbert spaces represent possible states, and Hermitian operators on
vectors represent observables.
state of affairs, a
possibility, actuality, or impossibility of the kind expressed by a
nominalization of a declarative sentence. (The declarative sentence ‘This die
comes up six’ can be nominalized either through the construction ‘that this die
comes up six’ or through the likes of ‘this die’s coming up six’. The resulting
nominalizations might be interpreted as ning corresponding propositions or
states of affairs.) States of affairs come in several varieties. Some are
possible states of affairs, or possibilities. Consider the possibility of a
certain die coming up six when rolled next. This possibility is a state of
affairs, as is its “complement” – the die’s not coming up six when rolled next.
There is in addition the state of affairs which conjoins that die’s coming up
six with its not coming up six. And this (contradictory) state of affairs is of
course not a possibility, not a possible state of affairs. Moreover, for every
actual state of affairs there is a non-actual one, its complement. For every
proposition there is hence a state of affairs: possible or impossible, actual
or not. Indeed some consider propositions to be states of affairs. Some take
facts to be actual states of affairs, while others prefer to define them as
true propositions. If propositions are states of affairs, then facts are of
course both actual states of affairs and true propositions. In a very broad
sense, events are just possible states of affairs; in a narrower sense they are
contingent states of affairs; and in a still narrower sense they are contingent
and particular states of affairs, involving just the exemplification of an
nadic property by a sequence of individuals of length n. In a yet narrower
sense events are only those particular and contingent states of affairs that
entail change. A baseball’s remaining round throughout a certain period does
not count as an event in this narrower sense but only as a state of that
baseball, unlike the event of its being hit by a certain bat.
statistical explanation,
an explanation expressed in an explanatory argument containing premises and
conclusions making claims about statistical probabilities. These arguments
include deductions of less general from more general laws and differ from other
such explanations only insofar as the contents of the laws imply claims about
statistical probability. Most philosophical discussion in the latter half of
the twentieth century has focused on statistical explanation of events rather
than laws. This type of argument was discussed by Ernest Nagel (The Structure
of Science, 1961) under the rubric “probabilistic explanation,” and by Hempel
(Aspects of Scientific Explanation, 1965) as “inductive statistical”
explanation. The explanans contains a statement asserting that a given system responds
in one of several ways specified by a sple space of possible outcomes on a
trial or experiment of some type, and that the statistical probability of an
event (represented by a set of points in the sple space) on the given kind of
trial is also given for each such event. Thus, the statement might assert that
the statistical probability is near 1 of the relative frequency r/n of heads in
n tosses being close to the statistical probability p of heads on a single
toss, where the sple space consists of the 2n possible sequences of heads and
tails in n tosses. Nagel and Hempel understood such statistical probability
statements to be covering laws, so that inductive-statistical explanation and
deductivenomological explanation of events are two species of covering law
explanation. The explanans also contains a claim that an experiment of the kind
mentioned in the statistical assumption has taken place (e.g., the coin has
been tossed n times). The explanandum asserts that an event of some kind has
occurred (e.g., the coin has landed heads approximately r times in the n
tosses). In many cases, the kind of experiment can be described equivalently as
an n-fold repetition of some other kind of experiment (as a thousandfold
repetition of the tossing of a given coin) or as the implementation of the kind
of trial (thousand-fold tossing of the coin) one time. Hence, statistical
explanation of events can always be construed as deriving conclusions about
“single cases” from assumptions about statistical probabilities even when the
concern is to explain mass phenomena. Yet, many authors controversially
contrast statistical explanation in quantum mechanics, which is alleged to
require a singlecase propensity interpretation of statistical probability, with
statistical explanation in statistical mechanics, genetics, and the social
sciences, which allegedly calls for a frequency interpretation. The structure
of the explanatory argument of such statistical explanation has the form of a
direct inference from assumptions about statistical probabilities and the kind
of experiment trial which has taken place to the outcome. One controversial
aspect of direct inference is the problem of the reference class. Since the
early nineteenth century, statistical probability has been understood to be
relative to the way the experiment or trial is described. Authors like J. Venn,
Peirce, R. A. Fisher, and Reichenbach, ong many others, have been concerned
with how to decide on which kind of trial to base a direct inference when the
trial under investigation is correctly describable in several ways and the
statistical probabilities of possible outcomes may differ relative to the
different sorts of descriptions. The most comprehensive discussion of this
problem of the reference class is found in the work of H. E. Kyburg (e.g.,
Probability and the Logic of Rational Belief, 1961). Hempel acknowledged its
importance as an “epistemic biguity” in inductive statistical explanation.
Controversy also arises concerning inductive acceptance. May the conclusion of
an explanatory direct inference be a judgment as to the subjective probability
that the outcome event occurred? May a judgment that the outcome event occurred
is inductively “accepted” be made? Is some other mode of assessing the claim
about the outcome appropriate? Hempel’s discussion of the “nonconjunctiveness
of inductivestatistical” explanation derives from Kyburg’s earlier account of
direct inference where high probability is assumed to be sufficient for
acceptance. Non-conjunctiveness has been avoided by abandoning the sufficiency
of high probability (I. Levi, Gbling with Truth, 1967) or by denying that
direct inference in inductive-statistical explanation involves inductive
acceptance at all (R. C. Jeffrey, “Statistical Explanation vs. Statistical Inference,”
in Essays in Honor of C. G. Hempel, 1969).
CAUSATION, EXPLANATION. I.L. statistical independence.
Steiner, Rudolf
(1861–1925), Austrian spiritualist and founder of anthroposophy. Trained as a
scientist, he edited Goethe’s scientific writings and prepared the standard
edition of his complete works from 1889 to 1896. Steiner’s major work, Die
Philosophie der Freiheit, was published in 1894. His Friedrich Nietzsche: Ein
Kämpfer gegen seine Zeit (1895) was translated in 1960 by Margaret deRis as Friedrich
Nietzsche: Fighter for Freedom. Steiner taught at a workingmen’s college and
edited a literary journal, Magazin für Literatur, in Berlin. In 1901 he
embraced a spiritualism which emphasized a form of knowledge that transcended
sensory experience and was attained by the “higher self.” He held that man had
previously been attuned to spiritual processes by virtue of a drelike state of
consciousness, but was diverted from this consciousness by preoccupation with
material entities. Through training, individuals could retrieve their innate
capacity to perceive a spiritual realm. Steiner’s writings on this theme are
The Philosophy of Spiritual Activity (1894), Occult Science: An Outline (1913),
On the Riddle of Man (1916), and On the Riddles of the Soul (1917). His last
work was his autobiography (1924). To advance his teachings, he founded the
Anthroposophical Society (1912) and a school of “spiritual science” called the
Goetheanum near Basel, Switzerland. His work inspired the Waldorf School
movement, which comprises some eighty schools for children. The anthroposophy
movement he established remains active in Europe and the United States. G.J.S.
Stephen, Sir Leslie (1832–1904), English literary critic, editor, intellectual
historian, and philosopher. He was the first chief editor of the great
Dictionary of National Biography, writing hundreds of the entries himself.
Brought up in an intensely religious household, he lost his faith and spent
much of his time trying to construct a moral and intellectual outlook to
replace it. His main works in intellectual history, the two-volume History of
English Thought in the Eighteenth Century (1876) and the three-volume English
Utilitarians (1900), were undertaken as part of this project. So was his one
purely philosophical work, the Science of Ethics (1882), in which he tried to
develop an evolutionary theory of morality. Stephen was impatient of
philosophical technicalities. Hence his treatise on ethics does very little to
resolve the problems – some of them pointed out to him by his friend Henry
Sidgwick – with evolutionary ethics, and does not get beyond the several other
works on the subject published during this period. His histories of thought are
sometimes superficial, and their focus of interest is not ours; but they are
still useful because of their scope and the massive scholarship they put to
use. DARWINISM. J.B.S. Stewart,
Dugald.SCOTTISH COMMON SENSE PHILOSOPHY. Stillingfleet, Edward (1635–99),
English divine and controversialist who first made his ne with Irenicum (1659),
using natural-law doctrines to oppose religious sectarianism. His Origines
Sacrae (1662), ostensibly on the superiority of the Scriptural record over
other forms of ancient history, was for its day a learned study in the moral
certainty of historical evidence, the authority of testimony, and the
credibility of miracles. In drawing eclectically on philosophy from antiquity
to the Cbridge Platonists, he was much influenced by the Cartesian theory of
ideas, but later repudiated Cartesianism for its mechanist tendency. For three
decades he pphleteered on behalf of the moral certainty of orthodox Protestant
belief against what he considered the beliefs “contrary to reason” of Roman
Catholicism. This led to controversy with Unitarian and deist writers who
argued that mysteries like the Trinity were equally contrary to “clear and
distinct” ideas. He was alarmed at the use made of Locke’s “new,” i.e.
nonCartesian, way of ideas by John Toland in Christianity not Mysterious
(1696), and devoted his last years to challenging Locke to prove his orthodoxy.
The debate was largely over the concepts of substance, essence, and person, and
of faith and certainty. Locke gave no quarter in the public controversy, but in
the fourth edition of his Essay (1700) he silently ended some passages that had
provoked Stillingfleet.
Stirner, Max, pseudonym
of Kasper Schmidt (1805–56), German philosopher who proposed a theory of
radical individualism. Born in Bayreuth, he taught in Gymnasiums and later at a
Berlin academy for women. He translated what bece a standard German version of
Smith’s Wealth of Nations and contributed articles to the Rhenische Zeitung.
His most important work was statistical probability Stirner, Max 878 878 Der Einzige und sein Eigenthum (1845),
translated by Steven T. Byington as The Ego and His Own (1907). His second book
was Die Geschichte der Reaktion (1852). Stirner was in reaction to Hegel and
was for a time associated with the left Hegelians. He stressed the priority of
will and instinct over reason and proposed a radical anarchic individualism.
Each individual is unique, and the independent ego is the fundental value and
reality. Stirner attacked the state, religious ideas, and abstractions such as
“humanity” as “spectres” that are deceptive illusions, remnants of erroneous
hypostatizations. His defense of egoism is such that the individual is
considered to have no obligations or duties, and especially not to the state.
Encouraging an individual “rebellion” against state domination and control, Stirner
attracted a following ong nineteenthand twentieth-century anarchists. The sole
goal of life is the cultivation of “uniqueness” or “ownness.” Engels and Marx
attacked his ideas at length (under the rubric “Saint Marx”) in The German
Ideology. Insofar as his theory of radical individualism offers no clearly
stated ethical requirements, it has been characterized as a form of nihilistic
egoism. HEGEL. G.J.S. stochastic
process, a process that evolves, as time goes by, according to a probabilistic
principle rather than a deterministic principle. Such processes are also called
random processes, but ‘stochastic’ does not imply complete disorderliness. The
principle of evolution governing a stochastic or random process is precise,
though probabilistic, in form. For exple, suppose some process unfolds in
discrete successive stages. And suppose that given any initial sequence of
stages, S1, S2, . . . , Sn, there is a precise probability that the next stage
Sn+1 will be state S, a precise probability that it will be SH, and so on for
all possible continuations of the sequence of states. These probabilities are
called transition probabilities. An evolving sequence of this kind is called a
discrete-time stochastic process, or discrete-time random process. A theoretically
important special case occurs when transition probabilities depend only on the
latest stage in the sequence of stages. When an evolving process has this
property it is called a discrete-time Markov process. A simple exple of a
discrete-time Markov process is the behavior of a person who keeps taking
either a step forward or a step back according to whether a coin falls heads or
tails; the probabilistic principle of movement is always applied to the
person’s most recent position. The successive stages of a stochastic process
need not be discrete. If they are continuous, they constitute a
“continuous-time” stochastic or random process. The mathematical theory of
stochastic processes has many applications in science and technology. The
evolution of epidemics, the process of soil erosion, and the spread of cracks
in metals have all been given plausible models as stochastic processes, to
mention just a few areas of research.
Stoicism, one of the
three leading movements constituting Hellenistic philosophy. Its founder was
Zeno of Citium (334–262 B.C.), who was succeeded as school head by Cleanthes
(331– 232). But the third head, Chrysippus (c.280– c.206), was its greatest
exponent and most voluminous writer. These three are the leading
representatives of Early Stoicism. No work by any early Stoic survives intact,
except Cleanthes’ short “Hymn to Zeus.” Otherwise we are dependent on
doxography, on isolated quotations, and on secondary sources, most of them
hostile. Nevertheless, a remarkably coherent account of the system can be
assembled. The Stoic world is an ideally good organism, all of whose parts
interact for the benefit of the whole. It is imbued with divine reason (logos),
its entire development providentially ordained by fate and repeated identically
from one world phase to the next in a never-ending cycle, each phase ending
with a conflagration (ekpyrosis). Only bodies strictly “exist” and can
interact. Body is infinitely divisible, and contains no void. At the lowest
level, the world is analyzed into an active principle, god, and a passive
principle, matter, both probably corporeal. Out of these are generated, at a
higher level, the four elements air, fire, earth, and water, whose own
interaction is analogous to that of god and matter: air and fire, severally or
conjointly, are an active rational force called breath (Greek pneuma, Latin
spiritus), while earth and water constitute the passive substrate on which
these act, totally interpenetrating each other thanks to the non-particulate
structure of body and its capacity to be mixed “through and through.” Most
physical analysis is conducted at this higher level, and pneuma becomes a key
concept in physics and biology. A thing’s qualities are constituted by its
pneuma, which has the additional role of giving it cohestochastic process
Stoicism 879 879 sion and thus an
essential identity. In inanimate objects this unifying pneuma is called a hexis
(state); in plants it is called physis (nature); and in animals “soul.” Even
qualities of soul, e.g. justice, are portions of pneuma, and they too are
therefore bodies: only thus could they have their evident causal efficacy. Four
incorporeals are admitted: place, void (which surrounds the world), time, and
lekta (see below); these do not strictly “exist” – they lack the corporeal
power of interaction – but as items with some objective standing in the world
they are, at least, “somethings.” Universals, identified with Plato’s Forms,
are treated as concepts (ennoemata), convenient fictions that do not even earn
the status of “somethings.” Stoic ethics is founded on the principle that only
virtue is good, only vice bad. Other things conventionally assigned a value are
“indifferent” (adiaphora), although some, e.g., health, wealth, and honor, are
naturally “preferred” (proegmena), while their opposites are “dispreferred”
(apoproegmena). Even though their possession is irrelevant to happiness, from
birth these indifferents serve as the appropriate subject matter of our
choices, each correct choice being a “proper function” (kathekon) – not yet a
morally good act, but a step toward our eventual end (telos) of “living in
accordance with nature.” As we develop our rationality, the appropriate choices
become more complex, less intuitive. For exple, it may sometimes be more in accordance
with nature’s plan to sacrifice your wealth or health, in which case it becomes
your “proper function” to do so. You have a specific role to play in the world
plan, and moral progress (prokope) consists in learning it. This progress
involves widening your natural “affinity” (oikeiosis): an initial concern for
yourself and your parts is later extended to those close to you, and eventually
to all mankind. That is the Stoic route toward justice. However, justice and
the other virtues are actually found only in the sage, an idealized perfectly
rational person totally in tune with the divine cosmic plan. The Stoics doubted
whether any sages existed, although there was a tendency to treat at least
Socrates as having been one. The sage is totally good, everyone else totally
bad, on the paradoxical Stoic principle that all sins are equal. The sage’s
actions, however similar externally to mere “proper functions,” have an
entirely distinct character: they are rened ‘right actions’ (katorthomata).
Acting purely from “right reason,” he is distinguished by his “freedom from
passion” (apatheia): morally wrong impulses, or passions, are at root
intellectual errors of mistaking what is indifferent for good or bad, whereas
the sage’s evaluations are always correct. The sage alone is happy and truly
free, living in perfect harmony with the divine plan. All human lives are
predetermined by the providentially designed, all-embracing causal nexus of
fate; yet being the principal causes of their actions, the good and the bad
alike are responsible for them: determinism and morality are fully compatible.
Stoic epistemology defends the existence of cognitive certainty against the
attacks of the New Academy. Belief is described as assent (synkatathesis) to an
impression (phantasia), i.e. taking as true the propositional content of some
perceptual or reflective impression. Certainty comes through the “cognitive
impression” (phantasia kataleptike), a self-certifying perceptual
representation of external fact, claimed to be commonplace. Out of sets of such
impressions we acquire generic conceptions (prolepseis) and become rational.
The highest intellectual state, knowledge (episteme), in which all cognitions
become mutually supporting and hence “unshakable by reason,” is the prerogative
of the wise. Everyone else is in a state of mere opinion (doxa) or of
ignorance. Nevertheless, the cognitive impression serves as a “criterion of
truth” for all. A further important criterion is prolepseis, also called common
conceptions and common notions (koinai ennoiai), often appealed to in
philosophical argument. Although officially dependent on experience, they often
sound more like innate intuitions, purportedly indubitable. Stoic logic is
propositional, by contrast with Aristotle’s logic of terms. The basic unit is
the simple proposition (axioma), the primary bearer of truth and falsehood.
Syllogistic also employs complex propositions – conditional, conjunctive, and
disjunctive – and rests on five “indemonstrable” inference schemata (to which others
can be reduced with the aid of four rules called themata). All these items
belong to the class of lekta – “sayables” or “expressibles.” Words are bodies
(vibrating portions of air), as are external objects, but predicates like that
expressed by ‘ . . . walks’, and the meanings of whole sentences, e.g.,
‘Socrates walks’, are incorporeal lekta. The structure and content of both
thoughts and sentences are analyzed by mapping them onto lekta, but the lekta
are themselves causally inert. Conventionally, a second phase of the school is
distinguished as Middle Stoicism. It developed largely at Rhodes under
Panaetius and Posidonius, both of whom influenced the presentation of Stoicism
in Cicero’s influential philosophical treatises (mid-first century B.C.). Panaetius
Stoicism Stoicism 880 880 (c.185–c.110)
softened some classical Stoic positions, his ethics being more pragmatic and
less concerned with the idealized sage. Posidonius (c.135–c.50) made Stoicism
more open to Platonic and Aristotelian ideas, reviving Plato’s inclusion of
irrational components in the soul. A third phase, Roman Stoicism, is the only
Stoic era whose writings have survived in quantity. It is represented
especially by the younger Seneca (A.D. c.1–65), Epictetus (A.D. c.55–c.135),
and Marcus Aurelius (A.D. 121–80). It continued the trend set by Panaetius,
with a strong primary focus on practical and personal ethics. Many prominent
Roman political figures were Stoics. After the second century A.D. Stoicism as
a system fell from prominence, but its terminology and concepts had by then
become an ineradicable part of ancient thought. Through the writings of Cicero
and Seneca, its impact on the moral and political thought of the Renaissance
was immense.
Stout, George Frederick
(1860–1944), British psychologist and philosopher. A student of Ward, he was
influenced by Herbart and especially Brentano. He was editor of Mind
(1892–1920). He followed Ward in rejecting associationism and sensationism, and
proposing analysis of mind as activity rather than passivity, consisting of
acts of cognition, feeling, and conation. Stout stressed attention as the
essential function of mind, and argued for the goal-directedness of all mental
activity and behavior, greatly influencing McDougall’s hormic psychology. He
reinterpreted traditional associationist ideas to emphasize primacy of mental
activity; e.g., association by contiguity – a passive mechanical process
imposed on mind – bece association by continuity of attentional interest. With
Brentano, he argued that mental representation involves “thought reference” to
a real object known through the representation that is itself the object of
thought, like Locke’s “idea.” In philosophy he was influenced by Moore and
Russell. His major works are Analytic Psychology (1896) and Manual of
Psychology (1899).
ASSOCIATIONISM, BRENTANO,
SENSATIONALISM. T.H.L. St. Petersburg paradox.SAINT PETERSBURG PARADOX.
strategy.GE THEORY. Straton.PERIPATETIC SCHOOL.
Strato of Lpsacus
(c.335–c.267 B.C.), Greek philosopher and polymath nickned “the Physicist” for
his innovative ideas in natural science. He succeeded Theophrastus as head of
the Lyceum. Earlier he served as royal tutor in Alexandria, where his students
included Aristarchus, who devised the first heliocentric model. Of Strato’s
many writings only fragments and summaries survive. These show him criticizing
the abstract conceptual analysis of earlier theorists and paying closer
attention to empirical evidence. ong his targets were atomist arguments that
motion is impossible unless there is void, and also Aristotle’s thesis that
matter is fully continuous. Strato argued that no large void occurs in nature,
but that matter is naturally porous, laced with tiny pockets of void. His
investigations of compression and suction were influential in ancient
physiology. In dynics, he proposed that bodies have no property of lightness
but only more or less weight.
HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY, LYCEUM. S.A.W. Strawson, Sir Peter (b.1919),
British philosopher who has made major contributions to logic, metaphysics, and
the study of Kant. His career has been at Oxford, where he was the leading
philosopher of his generation. His first important work, “On Referring” (1950),
argues that Russell’s theory of descriptions fails to deal properly with the
role of descriptions as “referring expressions” because Russell assumed the
“bogus trichotomy” that sentences are true, false, or meaningless: for
Strawson, sentences with empty descriptions are meaningful but “neither true
nor false” because the general presuppositions governing the use of referring
expressions are not fulfilled. One aspect of this argument was Russell’s
alleged insensitivity to the ordinary use of definite descriptions. The
contrast between the abstract schemata of formal logic and the manifold
richness of the inferences inherent in ordinary language is the central theme
of Strawson’s first book, Introduction to Logical Theory (1952). In Individuals
(1959) Strawson reintroduced metaphysics as a respectable philosophical
discipline after decades of positivist rhetoric. But his project is only
“descriptive” metaphysics – elucidation of the basic features of our own
conceptual scheme – and his arguments are based on the philosophy of language:
“basic” particulars Stoicism, Middle Strawson, Sir Peter 881 881 are those which are basic objects of
reference, and it is the spatiotemporal and sortal conditions for their
identification and reidentification by speakers that constitute the basic
categories. Three arguments are especially fous: (1) even in a purely auditory
world objective reference on the basis of experience requires at least an
analogue of space; (2) because self-reference presupposes reference to others,
persons, conceived as bearers of both physical and psychological properties, are
a type of basic particular; and (3) “feature-placing” discourse, such as ‘it is
snowing here now’, is “the ultimate propositional level” through which
reference to particulars enters discourse. Strawson’s next book, The Bounds of
Sense (1966), provides a critical reading of Kant’s theoretical philosophy. His
aim is to extricate what he sees as the profound truths concerning the
presuppositions of objective experience and judgment that Kant’s transcendental
arguments establish from the mysterious metaphysics of Kant’s transcendental
idealism. Strawson’s critics have argued, however, that the resulting position
is unstable: transcendental arguments can tell us only what we must suppose to
be the case. So if Kant’s idealism, which restricts such suppositions to things
as they appear to us, is abandoned, we can draw conclusions concerning the way
the world itself must be only if we add the verificationist thesis that ability
to make sense of such suppositions requires ability to verify them. In his next
book, Skepticism and Naturalism: Some Varieties (1985), Strawson conceded this:
transcendental arguments belong within descriptive metaphysics and should not
be regarded as attempts to provide an external justification of our conceptual
scheme. In truth no such external justification is either possible or needed:
instead – and here Strawson invokes Hume rather than Kant – our reasonings come
to an end in natural propensities for belief that are beyond question because
they alone make it possible to raise questions. In a fous earlier paper
Strawson had urged much the se point concerning the free will debate: defenders
of our ordinary attitudes of reproach and gratitude should not seek to ground
them in the “panicky metaphysics” of a supra-causal free will; instead they can
and need do no more than point to our unshakable commitment to these “reactive”
attitudes through which we manifest our attachment to that fundental category
of our conceptual scheme – persons. .
structuralism, a
distinctive yet extremely wide range of productive research conducted in the
social and human sciences from the 1950s through the 1970s, principally in
France. It is difficult to describe structuralism as a movement, because of the
methodological constraints exercised by the various disciplines that ce to be
influenced by structuralism – e.g., anthropology, philosophy, literary theory,
psychoanalysis, political theory, even mathematics. Nonetheless, structuralism
is generally held to derive its organizing principles from the early twentieth-century
work of Saussure, the founder of structural linguistics. Arguing against the
prevailing historicist and philological approaches to linguistics, he proposed
a “scientific” model of language, one understood as a closed system of elements
and rules that account for the production and the social communication of
meaning. Inspired by Durkheim’s notion of a “social fact” – that domain of
objectivity wherein the psychological and the social orders converge – Saussure
viewed language as the repository of discursive signs shared by a given
linguistic community. The particular sign is composed of two elements, a
phonemic signifier, or distinctive sound element, and a corresponding meaning,
or signified element. The defining relation between the sign’s sound and
meaning components is held to be arbitrary, i.e., based on conventional
association, and not due to any function of the speaking substrict conditional
structuralism 882 882 ject’s personal
inclination, or to any external consideration of reference. What lends
specificity or identity to each particular signifier is its differential
relation to the other signifiers in the greater set; hence, each basic unit of
language is itself the product of differences between other elements within the
system. This principle of differential – and structural – relation was extended
by Troubetzkoy to the order of phonemes, whereby a defining set of vocalic
differences underlies the constitution of all linguistic phonemes. Finally, for
Saussure, the closed set of signs is governed by a system of grmatical,
phonemic, and syntactic rules. Language thus derives its significance from its
own autonomous organization, and this serves to guarantee its communicative
function. Since language is the foremost instance of social sign systems in
general, the structural account might serve as an exemplary model for
understanding the very intelligibility of social systems as such – hence, its
obvious relevance to the broader concerns of the social and human sciences.
This implication was raised by Saussure himself, in his Course on General
Linguistics(1916), but it was advanced dratically by the French anthropologist
Claude Lévi-Strauss – who is generally acknowledged to be the founder of modern
structuralism – in his extensive analyses in the area of social anthropology,
beginning with his Elementary Structures of Kinship (1949). Lévi-Strauss argued
that society is itself organized according to one form or another of
significant communication and exchange – whether this be of information, knowledge,
or myths, or even of its members themselves. The organization of social
phenomena could thus be clarified through a detailed elaboration of their
subtending structures, which, collectively, testify to a deeper and
all-inclusive, social rationality. As with the analysis of language, these
social structures would be disclosed, not by direct observation, but by
inference and deduction from the observed empirical data. Furthermore, since
these structures are models of specific relations, which in turn express the
differential properties of the component elements under investigation, the
structural analysis is both readily formalizable and susceptible to a broad
variety of applications. In Britain, e.g., Edmund Leach pursued these analyses
in the domain of social anthropology; in the United States, Chomsky applied
insights of structuralism to linguistic theory and philosophy of mind; in
Italy, Eco conducted extensive structuralist analyses in the fields of social
and literary semiotics. With its acknowledgment that language is a
rule-governed social system of signs, and that effective communication depends
on the resources available to the speaker from within the codes of language
itself, the structuralist approach tends to be less preoccupied with the more
traditional considerations of “subjectivity” and “history” in its treatment of
meaningful discourse. In the post-structuralism that grew out of this approach,
the French philosopher Foucault, e.g., focused on the generation of the
“subject” by the various epistemic discourses of imitation and representation,
as well as on the institutional roles of knowledge and power in producing and
conserving particular “disciplines” in the natural and social sciences. These
disciplines, Foucault suggested, in turn govern our theoretical and practical
notions of madness, criminality, punishment, sexuality, etc., notions that
collectively serve to “normalize” the individual subject to their
determinations. Likewise, in the domain of psychoanalysis, Lacan drew on the work
of Saussure and Lévi-Strauss to emphasize Freud’s concern with language and to
argue that, as a set of determining codes, language serves to structure the
subject’s very unconscious. Problematically, however, it is the very dynism of
language, including metaphor, metonymy, condensation, displacement, etc., that
introduces the social symbolic into the constitution of the subject. Althusser
applied the principles of structuralist methodology to his analysis of Marxism,
especially the role played by contradiction in understanding infrastructural
and superstructural formation, i.e., for the constitution of the historical
dialectic. His account followed Marx’s rejection of Feuerbach, at once denying
the role of traditional subjectivity and humanism, and presenting a
“scientific” analysis of “historical materialism,” one that would be
anti-historicist in principle but attentive to the actual political state of
affairs. For Althusser, such a philosophical analysis helped provide an
“objective” discernment to the historical transformation of social reality. The
restraint the structuralists extended toward the traditional views of
subjectivity and history dratically colored their treatment both of the
individuals who are agents of meaningful discourse and of the linguistically
articulable object field in general. This redirection of research interests
(particularly in France, due to the influential work of Barthes and Michel
Serres in the fields of poetics, cultural semiotics, and communication theory)
has resulted in a series of original analyses and also provoked lively debates
between the adherents of structuralist structuralism structuralism 883 883 methodology and the more conventionally
oriented schools of thought (e.g., phenomenology, existentialism, Marxism, and
empiricist and positivist philosophies of science). These debates served as an
agency to open up subsequent discussions on deconstruction and postmodernist
theory for the philosophical generation of the 1980s and later. These
post-structuralist thinkers were perhaps less concerned with the organization
of social phenomena than with their initial constitution and subsequent dynics.
Hence, the problematics of the subject and history – or, in broader terms,
temporality itself – were again engaged. The new discussions were abetted by a
more critical appraisal of language and tended to be antiHegelian in their
rejection of the totalizing tendency of systematic metaphysics. Heidegger’s
critique of traditional metaphysics was one of the major influences in the
discussions following structuralism, as was the reexination of Nietzsche’s
earlier accounts of “genealogy,” his antiessentialism, and his teaching of a
dynic “will to power.” Additionally, many poststructuralist philosophers
stressed the Freudian notions of the libido and the unconscious as determining
factors in understanding not only the subject, but the deep rhetorical and
affective components of language use. An astonishing variety of philosophers
and critics engaged in the debates initially fred by the structuralist thinkers
of the period, and their extended responses and critical reappraisals formed
the vibrant, poststructuralist period of French intellectual life. Such figures
as Ricoeur, Emmanuel Levinas, Kristeva, Maurice Blanchot, Derrida, Gilles Deleuze,
Félix Guattari, Lyotard, Jean Baudrillard, Philippe LacoueLabarthe, Jean-Luc
Nancy, and Irigaray inaugurated a series of contemporary reflections that have
become international in scope.
Suárez, Francisco, also
known as Doctor Eximius (1548–1617), Spanish Jesuit philosopher and theologian.
Born in Granada, he studied at Salanca and taught there and at Rome, Coimbra,
and other leading universities. Suárez’s most important works are De legibus
(“On Law,” 1612), De Deo uno et trino (“On the Trinity,” 1606), De anima (“On
the Soul,” 1621), and the monumental Disputationes metaphysicae (“Metaphysical
Disputations,” 1597). The Disputationes has a unique place in philosophy, being
the first systematic and comprehensive work of metaphysics written in the West
that is not a commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Divided into fifty-four
disputations, it discusses every metaphysical issue known at the time. Its
influence was immediate and lasting and can be seen in the work of Scholastics
in both Europe and Latin erica, and of modern philosophers such as Descartes,
Leibniz, Wolff, and Schopenhauer. Suárez’s main contributions to philosophy
occurred in metaphysics, epistemology, and the philosophy of law. In all three
areas he was influenced by Aristotle and Aquinas, although he also drew
inspiration from Ockh, Duns Scotus, and others. In metaphysics, Suárez is known
for his views on the nature of metaphysics, being, and individuation.
Metaphysics is the science of “being insofar as it is real being” (ens in quantum
ens reale), and its proper object of study is the object concept of being. This
understanding of the object of metaphysics is often seen as paving the way for
early modern metaphysical theory, in which the object of metaphysics is mental.
For Suárez the concept of being is derived by analogy from the similarity
existing ong things. Existing reality for Suárez is composed of individuals:
everything that exists is individual, including substances and their
properties, accidents, principles, and components. He understands individuality
as incommunicability, nely, the inability of individuals to be divided into
entities of the se specific kind as themselves. The principle of individuation
is “entity,” which he identifies with “essence as it exists.” This principle
applies both to substances and their properties, accidents, principles, and
components. In epistemology, two of Suárez’s views stand out: that the
intellect knows the individual through a proper and separate concept without
structuralism, mathematical Suárez, Francisco 884 884 having to turn to reflection, a position
that supports an empiricist epistemology in which, contrary to Thomism,
knowledge of the individual is not mediated through universals; and (2) his
view of middle knowledge (scientia media), the knowledge God has of what every
free creature would freely do in every possible situation. This notion was used
by Suárez and Molina to explain how God can control human actions without
violating free will. In philosophy of law, Suárez was an innovative thinker
whose ideas influenced Grotius. For him law is fundentally an act of the will
rather than a result of an ordinance of reason, as Aquinas held. Law is divided
into eternal, divine, natural, and human. Human law is based on natural or divine
law and is not the result of human creation.
subdoxastic, pertaining
to states of mind postulated to account for the production and character of
certain apparently non-inferential beliefs. These were first discussed by
Stephen P. Stich in “Beliefs and Subdoxastic States” (1978). I may form the
belief that you are depressed, e.g., on the basis of subtle cues that I unable to articulate. The psychological
mechanism responsible for this belief might be thought to harbor information
concerning these cues subdoxastically. Although subdoxastic states resemble
beliefs in certain respects – they incorporate intentional content, they guide
behavior, they can bestow justification on beliefs – they differ from
fullyfledged doxastic states or beliefs in at least two respects. First, as
noted above, subdoxastic states may be largely inaccessible to introspection; I
may be unable to describe, even on reflection, the basis of my belief that you
are depressed. Second, subdoxastic states seem cut off inferentially from an
agent’s corpus of beliefs; my subdoxastic appreciation that your forehead is
creased may contribute to my believing that you are depressed, but, unlike the
belief that your forehead is creased, it need not, in the presence of other
beliefs, lead to further beliefs about your visage.
subjectivism, any
philosophical view that attempts to understand in a subjective manner what at
first glance would seem to be a class of judgments that are objectively either
true or false – i.e., true or false independently of what we believe, want, or
hope. There are two ways of being a subjectivist. In the first way, one can say
that the judgments in question, despite first appearances, are really judgments
about our own attitudes, beliefs, emotions, etc. In the second way, one can
deny that the judgments are true or false at all, arguing instead that they are
disguised commands or expressions of attitudes. In ethics, for exple, a
subjective view of the second sort is that moral judgments are simply
expressions of our positive and negative attitudes. This is emotivism.
Prescriptivism is also a subjective view of the second sort; it is the view
that moral judgments are really commands – to say “X is good” is to say,
details aside, “Do X.” Views that make morality ultimately a matter of
conventions (or what we or most people agree to) can also be construed as
subjective theories, albeit of the first type. Subjectivism is not limited to
ethics, however. According to a subjective view of epistemic rationality, the
standards of rational belief are the standards that the individual (or perhaps
most members in the individual’s community) would approve of insofar as they
are interested in believing those propositions that are true and not believing
those propositions that are false. Similarly, phenomenalists can be regarded as
proposing a subjective account of material object statements, since according
to them, such statements are best understood as complex statements about the
course of our experiences.
subject–object dichotomy,
the distinction between thinkers and what they think about. The distinction is
not exclusive, since subjects can also be objects, as in reflexive
self-conscious thought, which takes the subject as its intended object. The
dichotomy also need not be an exhaustive distinction in the strong sense that
everything is either a subject or an object, since in a logically possible
world in which there are no thinkers, there may yet be mind-independent
subaltern subject–object dichotomy 885
885 things that are neither subjects nor objects. Whether there are
non-thinking things that are not objects of thought in the actual world depends
on whether or not it is sufficient in logic to intend every individual thing by
such thoughts and expressions as ‘We can think of everything that exists’. The
dichotomy is an interimplicative distinction between thinkers and what they
think about, in which each presupposes the other. If there are no subjects,
then neither are there objects in the true sense, and conversely. A subject–object
dichotomy is acknowledged in most Western philosophical traditions, but
emphasized especially in Continental philosophy, beginning with Kant, and
carrying through idealist thought in Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, and
Schopenhauer. It is also prominent in intentionalist philosophy, in the
empirical psychology of Brentano, the object theory of Meinong, Ernst Mally
(1879–1944), and Twardowski, and the transcendental phenomenology of Husserl.
Subject–object dichotomy is denied by certain mysticisms, renounced as the
philosophical fiction of duality, of which Cartesian mind–body dualism is a
particular instance, and criticized by mystics as a confusion that prevents
mind from recognizing its essential oneness with the world, thereby
contributing to unnecessary intellectual and moral dilemmas.
sublime, a feeling
brought about by objects that are infinitely large or vast (such as the heavens
or the ocean) or overwhelmingly powerful (such as a raging torrent, huge
mountains, or precipices). The former (in Kant’s terminology) is the
mathematically sublime and the latter the dynically sublime. Though the
experience of the sublime is to an important extent unpleasant, it is also
accompanied by a certain pleasure: we enjoy the feeling of being overwhelmed.
On Kant’s view, this pleasure results from an awareness that we have powers of
reason that are not dependent on sensation, but that legislate over sense. The
sublime thus displays both the limitations of sense experience (and hence our
feeling of displeasure) and the power of our own mind (and hence the feeling of
pleasure). The sublime was an especially important concept in the aesthetic
theory of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. Reflection on it was
stimulated by the appearance of a translation of Longinus’s Peri hypsous (On
the Sublime) in 1674. The “postmodern sublime” has in addition emerged in late
twentieth century thought as a basis for raising questions about art. Whereas
beauty is associated with that whose form can be apprehended, the sublime is
associated with the formless, that which is “unpresentable” in sensation. Thus,
it is connected with critiques of “the aesthetic” – understood as that which is
sensuously present – as a way of understanding what is important about art. It
has also been given a political reading, where the sublime connects with
resistance to rule, and beauty connects with conservative acceptance of
existing forms or structures of society.
subsidiarity, a basic
principle of social order and the common good governing the relations between
the higher and lower associations in a political community. Positively, the
principle of subsidiarity holds that the common good, i.e., the ensemble of
social resources and institutions that facilitate human self-realization,
depends on fostering the free, creative initiatives of individuals and of their
voluntary associations; thus, the state, in addition to its direct role in
maintaining public good (which comprises justice, public peace, and public
morality) also has an indirect role in promoting other aspects of the common
good by rendering assistance (subsidium) to those individuals and associations
whose activities facilitate cooperative human self-realization in work, play,
the arts, sciences, and religion. Negatively, the principle of subsidiarity
holds that higher-level (i.e., more comprehensive) associations – while they
must monitor, regulate, and coordinate – ought not to absorb, replace, or
undermine the free initiatives and activities of lower-level associations and
individuals insofar as these are not contrary to the common good. This
presumption favoring free individual and social initiative has been defended on
various grounds, such as the inefficiency of burdening the state with myriad
local concerns, as well as the corresponding efficiency of unleashing the free,
creative potential of subordinate groups and individuals who build up the
shared economic, scientific, and artistic resources of society. But the deeper
ground for this presumption is the view subjunctive conditional subsidiarity
886 886 that human flourishing depends
crucially on freedom for individual self-direction and for the self-government
of voluntary associations and that human beings flourish best through their own
personal and cooperative initiatives rather than as the passive consumers or
beneficiaries of the initiatives of others.
subsistence (translation
of German Bestand), in current philosophy, especially Meinong’s system, the
kind of being that belongs to “ideal” objects (such as mathematical objects,
states of affairs, and abstractions like similarity and difference). By
contrast, the kind of being that belongs to “real” (wirklich) objects, things
of the sorts investigated by the sciences other than psychology and pure
mathematics, is called existence (Existenz). Existence and subsistence together
exhaust the realm of being (Sein). So, e.g., the subsistent ideal figures whose
properties are investigated by geometers do not exist – they are nowhere to be
found in the real world – but it is no less true of them that they have being
than it is of an existent physical object: there are such figures. Being does
not, however, exhaust the realm of objects or things. The psychological
phenomenon of intentionality shows that there are (in some sense of ‘there
are’) objects that neither exist nor subsist. Every intentional state is
directed toward an object. Although one may covet the Hope Diond or desire the
unification of Europe, one may also covet a non-existent material object or
desire a non-subsistent state of affairs. If one covets a non-existent diond,
there is (in some sense of ‘there is’) something that one covets – one’s state
of mind has an object – and it has certain properties: it is, e.g., a diond. It
may therefore be said to inhabit the realm of Sosein (‘being thus’ or
‘predication’ or ‘having properties’), which is the category comprising the
totality of objects. Objects that do not have any sort of being, either
existence or subsistence, belong to non-being (Nichtsein). In general, the
properties of an object do not determine whether it has being or non-being.
(But there are special cases: the round square, by its very nature, cannot
subsist.) Meinong thus maintains that objecthood is ausserseiend, i.e.,
independent of both existence and subsistence.
ABSTRACT ENTITY, MEINONG,
METAPHYSICS. P.v.I. sub specie aeternitatis.SPINOZA. substance, as defined by
Aristotle in the Categories, that which is neither predicable (“sayable”) of
anything nor present in anything as an aspect or property of it. The exples he
gives are an individual man and an individual horse. We can predicate being a
horse of something but not a horse; nor is a horse in something else. He also
held that only substances can remain self-identical through change. All other
things are accidents of substances and exist only as aspects, properties, or
relations of substances, or kinds of substances, which Aristotle called
secondary substances. An exple of an accident would be the color of an
individual man, and an exple of a secondary substance would be his being a man.
For Locke, a substance is that part of an individual thing in which its
properties inhere. Since we can observe, indeed know, only a thing’s
properties, its substance is unknowable. Locke’s sense is obviously rooted in
Aristotle’s but the latter carries no skeptical implications. In fact, Locke’s
sense is closer in meaning to what Aristotle calls matter, and would be better
regarded as a synonym of ‘substratum’, as indeed it is by Locke. Substance may
also be conceived as that which is capable of existing independently of
anything else. This sense is also rooted in Aristotle’s, but, understood quite
strictly, leads to Spinoza’s view that there can be only one substance, nely,
the totality of reality or God. A fourth sense of ‘substance’ is the common,
ordinary sense, ‘what a thing is made of’. This sense is related to Locke’s,
but lacks the latter’s skeptical implications. It also corresponds to what
Aristotle meant by matter, at least proximate matter, e.g., the bronze of a
bronze statue (Aristotle analyzes individual things as composites of matter and
form). This notion of matter, or stuff, has great philosophical importance,
because it expresses an idea crucial to both our ordinary and our scientific
understandings of the world. Philosophers such as Hume who deny the existence
of substances hold that individual things are mere bundles of properties, nely,
the properties ordinarily attributed to them, and usually hold that they are
incapable of change; they are series of momentary events, rather than things
enduring through time. BUNDLE THEORY,
PROPERTY. P.Bu. substance, primary.ARISTOTLE. substance, secondary.ARISTOTLE.
substance causation.AGENT CAUSATION. subsistence substance causation 887 887 substance-function.T’I, YUNG. substantial
form.FORM, HYLOMORPHISM.
substantialism, the view
that the primary, most fundental entities are substances, everything else being
dependent for its existence on them, either as a property of them or a relation
between them. Different versions of the view would correspond to the different
senses of the word ‘substance’.
SUBSTANCE. P.Bu. substantival causation.CAUSATION.
substantivalism.PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. substantive pluralism.PLURALISM.
substitutability salva veritate.
SUBSTITUTIVITY SALVA
VERITATE. substitutional quantification.QUANTIFICATION. substitutivity salva
veritate, a condition met by two expressions when one is substitutable for the
other at a certain occurrence in a sentence and the truth-value (truth or
falsity) of the sentence is necessarily unchanged when the substitution is
made. In such a case the two expressions are said to exhibit substitutivity or
substitutability salva veritate (literally, ‘with truth saved’) with respect to
one another in that context. The expressions are also said to be
interchangeable or intersubstitutable salva veritate in that context. Where it
is obvious from a given discussion that it is the truth-value that is to be
preserved, it may be said that the one expression is substitutable for the
other or exhibits substitutability with respect to the other at that place.
Leibniz proposed to use the universal interchangeability salva veritate of two
terms in every “proposition” in which they occur as a necessary and sufficient
condition for identity – presumably for the identity of the things denoted by
the terms. There are apparent exceptions to this criterion, as Leibniz himself
noted. If a sentence occurs in a context governed by a psychological verb such
as ‘believe’ or ‘desire’, by an expression conveying modality (e.g.,
‘necessarily’, ‘possibly’), or by certain temporal expressions (such as ‘it
will soon be the case that’), then two terms may denote the se thing but not be
interchangeable within such a sentence. Occurrences of expressions within
quotation marks or where the expressions are both mentioned and used (cf.
Quine’s exple, “Giorgione was so-called because of his size”) also exhibit
failure of substitutivity. Frege urged that such failures are to be explained
by the fact that within such contexts an expression does not have its ordinary
denotation but denotes instead either its usual sense or the expression
itself.
QUANTIFYING IN,
REFERENTIALLY TRANSPARENT. C.A.A. substrate.SUBSTANCE. substratum.BERKELEY,
SUBSTANCE. subsumption theory of explanation.COVERING LAW MODEL. sufficient
condition.CONDITION. sufficient reason, principle of.LEIBNIZ. Sufism (from
Arabic fufi, ‘mystic’), Islic mysticism. The Arabic word is tafawwuf. The
philosophically significant aspects of Sufism are its psychology in its early
phase and its epistemology and ontology in its later phase. The early practices
of asceticism, introspection, and meditation on God and the hereafter as
depicted in the Koran eventually developed in classical Sufism (eighth–eleventh
centuries) into the spiritual journey of the mystic, the successive stages of
which were described with a sophisticated psychological terminology. Sufis
differentiated two levels of spiritual attainment: the first was that of
“stations” (maqat) that were reached through individual effort, abnegation, and
spiritual exercises (e.g., tawakkul, ‘selfless trust in God’, fabr, ‘patience’,
etc.). The characteristic they all shared was that the Sufi, through an act of
the will and deliberate deeds, suppressed his individual ego and its concomitant
attachment to worldly things and emotions in order to become receptive to the
following level of “states” (ahwal), which were vouchsafed to him through God’s
grace. These culminated in the goal of the mystical quest, the final states of
bliss, which were variously identified by Sufis, according to their
proclivities, as love (mahabba, later ‘ishq), mystical knowledge (ma‘rifa), and
the total loss of ego consciousness and the concomitant absorption and
subsistence in and through God (fana’ and baqa’). The language describing these
stages and states was allusive and symbolical rather than descriptive. Sufism,
which was viewed initially with suspicion by the authorities and the orthodox,
was substance-function Sufism 888 888
integrated into mainstre belief in the eleventh century, primarily through the
work of al-Ghazali (d.1111). After al-Ghazali, the theoretical and practical
aspects of Sufism, which had previously gone hand in hand, developed in
different ways. At the popular level, Sufi practices and instruction were
institutionalized in fraternities and orders that, ever since, have played a
vital role in all Islic societies, especially ong the disenfranchised. Life in
the orders revolved around the regimented initiation of the novices to the Sufi
path by the master. Although theoretical instruction was also given, the goal
of the mystic was primarily achieved by spiritual practices, chiefly the
repetition of religious formulas (dhikr). ong the intellectuals, Sufism
acquired a philosophical gloss and terminology. All the currents of earlier
Sufism, as well as elements of Neoplatonic emanationism drawn from Arabic
philosophy, were integrated into a complex and multifaceted system of
“theosophy” in the monumental work of Ibn ‘Arabi(d.1240). This system rests on
the pivotal concept of “unity of being” (wahdat al-wujud), according to which
God is the only being and the only reality, while the entire creation
constitutes a series of his dynic and continuous self-manifestations. The
individual who combines in himself the totality of these manifestations to
become the prototype of creation, as well as the medium through which God can
be known, is the Perfect Man, identified with the Prophet Muhmad. The mystic’s
quest consists of an experiential (epistemological) retracing of the levels of
manifestations back to their origin and culminates in the closest possible
approximation to the level of the Perfect Man. Ibn ‘Arabi’s mystical thought,
which completely dominated Sufism, found expression in later times primarily in
the poetry of the various Islic languages, while certain aspects of it were
reintroduced into Arabic philosophy in Safavid times. AL-GHAZALI, ARABIC PHILOSOPHY. D.Gu. suicide,
assisted.
BIOETHICS. summum bonum
(Latin, ‘highest good’), that in relation to which all other things have at
most instrumental value (value only insofar as they are productive of what is
the highest good). Philosophical conceptions of the summum bonum have for the
most part been teleological in character. That is, they have identified the
highest good in terms of some goal or goals that human beings, it is supposed,
pursue by their very nature. These natural goals or ends have differed
considerably. For the theist, this end is God; for the rationalist, it is the
rational comprehension of what is real; for hedonism, it is pleasure; etc. The
highest good, however, need not be teleologically construed. It may simply be
posited, or supposed, that it is known, through some intuitive process, that a
certain type of thing is “intrinsically good.” On such a view, the relevant
contrast is not so much between what is good as an end and what is good as a
means to this end, as between what is good purely in itself and what is good
only in combination with certain other elements (the “extrinsically good”).
Perhaps the best exple of such a view of the highest good would be the position
of Moore. Must the summum bonum be just one thing, or one kind of thing? Yes,
to this extent: although one could certainly combine pluralism (the view that
there are many, irreducibly different goods) with an assertion that the summum
bonum is “complex,” the notion of the highest good has typically been the
province of monists (believers in a single good), not pluralists. J.A.M. summum
genus.GENUS GENERALISSIMUM. Sung Hsing, also called Sung Tzu (c.360–290 B.C.),
Chinese philosopher associated with Mohism and the Huang–Lao school. He was a
member of the Chi-hsia Academy of Ch’i, a late Warring States center that
attracted intellectuals of every persuasion. His Mohist ideas include an
emphasis on utility, thrift, meritocracy, and a reluctance to wage war. He is
praised by the Taoist Chuang Tzu for his beliefs that one’s essential desires
and needs are few and that one should heed internal cultivation rather than
social judgments. The combination of internal tranquillity and political
activism is characteristic of Huang–Lao thought.
MOHISM. R.P.P. &
R.T.A. sunyata (Sanskrit, ‘emptiness’), a property said by some Indian Buddhist
philosophers to be possessed necessarily by everything that exists. If
something is empty it possesses no essential or inherent nature (svabhava),
which is to say that both its existence and its nature are dependent on things
or events other than itself. The thesis ‘everything is empty’ is therefore
approximately equivalent to ‘everything is causally dependent’; the
contradictories of these theses were typically argued by defenders of emptiness
to be incoherent and thus not worthy of assent. To deny emptiness was also
taken to require the affirmasuicide, assisted sunyata 889 889 tion of permanence and non-contingency:
if something is non-empty in any respect, it is in just that respect permanent
and non-contingent. BUDDHISM, MADHYIKA,
NAGARJUNA. P.J.G. Sun Yat-sen (1866–1925), Chinese statesman, founder of the
Republic of China in 1911. Educated as a medical doctor in England, he bece a
revolutionary to end the reign of the last dynasty in China. He founded the
Nationalist Party and developed the so-called Three People’s Principles: the nationalist,
democratic, and socialist principles. He claimed to be transmitting the
Confucian Way. Sun adopted a policy of cooperation with the Communists, but his
successor Chiang Kai-shek (1887–1975) broke with them. He is now also honored
on the mainland as a bourgeois social democrat paving the way for the Communist
Revolution. CHINESE PHILOSOPHY. S.-h.L.
superaltern.SQUARE OF OPPOSITION. superego.FREUD. supererogation, the property
of going beyond the call of duty. Supererogatory actions are sometimes equated
with actions that are morally good in the sense that they are encouraged by
morality but not required by it. Sometimes they are equated with morally
commendable actions, i.e., actions that indicate a superior moral character. It
is quite common for morally good actions to be morally commendable and vice
versa, so that it is not surprising that these two kinds of supererogatory
actions are not clearly distinguished even though they are quite distinct.
Certain kinds of actions are not normally considered to be morally required,
e.g., giving to charity, though morality certainly encourages doing them.
However, if one is wealthy and gives only a small ount to charity, then,
although one’s act is supererogatory in the sense of being morally good, it is
not supererogatory in the sense of being morally commendable, for it does not
indicate a superior moral character. Certain kinds of actions are normally
morally required, e.g., keeping one’s promises. However, when the harm or risk
of harm of keeping one’s promise is sufficiently great compared to the harm
caused by breaking the promise to excuse breaking the promise, then keeping
one’s promise counts as a supererogatory act in the sense of being morally
commendable. Some versions of consequentialism claim that everyone is always
morally required to act so as to bring about the best consequences. On such a
theory there are no actions that are morally encouraged but not required; thus,
for those holding such theories, if there are supererogatory acts, they must be
morally commendable. Many versions of non-consequentialism also fail to provide
for acts that are morally encouraged but not morally required; thus, if they
allow for supererogatory acts, they must regard them as morally required acts
done at such significant personal cost that one might be excused for not doing
them. The view that all actions are either morally required, morally
prohibited, or morally indifferent makes it impossible to secure a place for
supererogatory acts in the sense of morally good acts. This view that there are
no acts that are morally encouraged but not morally required may be the result
of misleading terminology. Both Kant and Mill distinguish between duties of
perfect obligation and duties of imperfect obligation, acknowledging that a
duty of imperfect obligation does not specify any particular act that one is
morally required to do. However, since they use the term ‘duty’ it is very easy
to view all acts falling under these “duties” as being morally required. One
way of avoiding the view that all morally encouraged acts are morally required
is to avoid the common philosophical misuse of the term ‘duty’. One can replace
‘duties of perfect obligation’ with ‘actions required by moral rules’ and
‘duties of imperfect obligation’ with ‘actions encouraged by moral ideals’.
However, a theory that includes the kinds of acts that are supererogatory in
the sense of being morally good has to distinguish between that sense of
‘supererogatory’ and the sense meaning ‘morally commendable’, i.e., indicating
a superior moral character in the agent. For as pointed out above, not all
morally good acts are morally commendable, nor are all morally commendable acts
morally good, even though a particular act may be supererogatory in both
senses.
supervenience, a
dependence relation between properties or facts of one type, and properties or
facts of another type. Moore, for instance, held that the property intrinsic
value is dependent in the relevant way on certain non-moral properties
(although he did not employ the word ‘supervenience’). As he put it, “if a
given thing possesses any kind of intrinsic value in a certain degree, then not
only must that se thing possess it, under all circumstances, in the se degree,
but also anything exactly like it, must, under all circumstances, possess it in
exactly the se degree” (Philosophical Studies, 1922). The concept of
supervenience, as a relation between properties, is essentially this:
Properties of type A are supervenient on properties of type B if and only if two
objects cannot differ with respect to their A-properties without also differing
with respect to their B-properties. Properties that allegedly are supervenient
on others are often called consequential properties, especially in ethics; the
idea is that if something instantiates a moral property, then it does so in
virtue of, i.e., as a (non-causal) consequence of, instantiating some
lower-level property on which the moral property supervenes. In another,
related sense, supervenience is a feature of discourse of one type, vis-à-vis
discourse of another type. The term was so used, again in connection with
morals, by Hare, who wrote: First, let us take that characteristic of “good”
which has been called its supervenience. Suppose that we say, “St. Francis was
a good man.” It is logically impossible to say this and to maintain at the se
time that there might have been another man placed exactly in the se
circumstances as St. Francis, and who behaved in exactly the se way, but who
differed from St. Francis in this respect only, that he was not a good man.
(The Language of Morals, 1952) Here the idea is that it would be a misuse of
moral language, a violation of the “logic of moral discourse,” to apply ‘good’
to one thing but not to something else exactly similar in all pertinent
non-moral respects. Hare is a metaethical irrealist: he denies that there are
moral properties or facts. So for him, moral supervenience is a feature of
moral discourse and judgment, not a relation between properties or facts of two
types. The notion of supervenience has come to be used quite widely in
metaphysics and philosophy of mind, usually in the first sense explained above.
This use was heralded by Davidson in articulating a position about the relation
between physical and mental properties, or statetypes, that eschews the
reducibility of mental properties to physical ones. He wrote: Although the
position I describe denies there are psychophysical laws, it is consistent with
the view that mental characteristics are in some sense dependent, or
supervenient, on physical characteristics. Such supervenience might be taken to
mean that there cannot be two events alike in all physical respects but
differing in some mental respects, or that an object cannot alter in some
mental respects without altering in some physical respects. Dependence or
supervenience of this kind does not entail reducibility through law or
definition. (“Mental Events,” 1970) A variety of supervenience theses have been
propounded in metaphysics and philosophy of mind, usually (although not always)
in conjunction with attempts to formulate metaphysical positions that are
naturalistic, in some sense, without being strongly reductionistic. For
instance, it is often asserted that mental properties and facts are
supervenient on neurobiological properties, and/or on physicochemical
properties and facts. And it is often claimed, more generally, that all
properties and facts are supervenient on the properties and facts of the kind
described by physics. Much attention has been directed at how to formulate the
desired supervenience theses, and thus how to characterize supervenience
itself. A distinction has been drawn between weak supervenience, asserting that
in any single possible world w, any two individuals in w that differ in their
A-properties also differ in their B-properties; and strong supervenience,
asserting that for any two individuals i and j, either within a single possible
world or in two distinct ones, if i and j differ in A-properties then they also
differ in Bproperties. It is sometimes alleged that traditional formulations of
supervenience, like Moore’s or Hare’s, articulate only weak supervenience,
whereas strong supervenience is needed to express the relevant kind of
determination or dependence. It is sometimes replied, however, superset
supervenience 891 891 that the
traditional natural-language formulations do in fact express strong
supervenience – and that formalizations expressing mere weak supervenience are
mistranslations. Questions about how best to formulate supervenience theses
also arise in connection with intrinsic and non-intrinsic properties. For
instance, the property being a bank, instantiated by the brick building on Main
Street, is not supervenient on intrinsic physical properties of the building itself;
rather, the building’s having this social-institutional property depends on a
considerably broader range of facts and features, some of which are involved in
subserving the social practice of banking. The term ‘supervenience base’ is
frequently used to denote the range of entities and happenings whose lowerlevel
properties and relations jointly underlie the instantiation of some
higher-level property (like being a bank) by some individual (like the brick
building on Main Street). Supervenience theses are sometimes formulated so as
to smoothly accommodate properties and facts with broad supervenience bases.
For instance, the idea that the physical facts determine all the facts is
sometimes expressed as global supervenience, which asserts that any two physically
possible worlds differing in some respect also differ in some physical respect.
Or, sometimes this idea is expressed as the stronger thesis of regional
supervenience, which asserts that for any two spatiotemporal regions r and s,
either within a single physically possible world or in two distinct ones, if r
and s differ in some intrinsic respect then they also differ in some intrinsic
physical respect. NATURALISM, PHILOSOPHY
OF MIND,
RESULTANCE. T.E.H.
supervenient behaviorism.PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. suppositio (Latin, ‘supposition’),
in the Middle Ages, reference. The theory of supposition, the central notion in
the theory of proprietates terminorum, was developed in the twelfth century,
and was refined and discussed into early modern times. It has two parts (their
nes are a modern convenience). (1) The theory of supposition proper. This
typically divided suppositio into “personal” reference to individuals (not
necessarily to persons, despite the ne), “simple” reference to species or
genera, and “material” reference to spoken or written expressions. Thus ‘man’
in ‘Every man is an animal’ has personal supposition, in ‘Man is a species’
simple supposition, and in ‘Man is a monosyllable’ material supposition. The
theory also included an account of how the range of a term’s reference is
affected by tense and by modal factors. (2) The theory of “modes” of personal
supposition. This part of supposition theory divided personal supposition
typically into “discrete” (‘Socrates’ in ‘Socrates is a man’), “determinate”
(‘man’ in ‘Some man is a Greek’), “confused and distributive” (‘man’ in ‘Every
man is an animal’), and “merely confused” (‘animal’ in ‘Every man is an
animal’). The purpose of this second part of the theory is a matter of some
dispute. By the late fourteenth century, it had in some authors become a theory
of quantification. The term ‘suppositio’ was also used in the Middle Ages in
the ordinary sense, to mean ‘assumption’, ‘hypothesis’. P.V.S. supposition,
material.SUPPOSITIO. supposition, personal.SUPPOSITIO. supposition,
simple.SUPPOSITIO. sure-thing principle.
survival, continued
existence after one’s biological death. So understood, survival can pertain
only to beings that are organisms at some time or other, not to beings that are
disembodied at all times (as angels are said to be) or to beings that are
embodied but never as organisms (as might be said of computers). Theories that
maintain that one’s individual consciousness is absorbed into a universal
consciousness after death or that one continues to exist only through one’s
descendants, insofar as they deny one’s own continued existence as an
individual, are not theories of survival. Although survival does not entail
immortality or anything about reward or punishment in an afterlife, many theories
of survival incorporate these features. Theories about survival have expressed
differing attitudes about the importance of the body. supervenient behaviorism
survival 892 892 Some philosophers have
maintained that persons cannot survive without their own bodies, typically
espousing a doctrine of resurrection; such a view was held by Aquinas. Others,
including the Pythagoreans, have believed that one can survive in other bodies,
allowing for reincarnation into a body of the se species or even for transmigration
into a body of another species. Some, including Plato and perhaps the
Pythagoreans, have claimed that no body is necessary, and that survival is
fully achieved by one’s escaping embodiment. There is a similar spectrum of
opinion about the importance of one’s mental life. Some, such as Locke, have
supposed that survival of the se person would require memory of one’s having
experienced specific past events. Plato’s doctrine of recollection, in
contrast, supposes that one can survive without any experiential memory; all
that one typically is capable of recollecting are impersonal necessary truths.
Philosophers have tested the relative importance of bodily versus mental
factors by means of various thought experiments, of which the following is
typical. Suppose that a person’s whole mental life – memories, skills, and
character traits – were somehow duplicated into a data bank and erased from the
person, leaving a living radical nesiac. Suppose further that the person’s
mental life were transcribed into another radically nesiac body. Has the person
survived, and if so, as whom? PERSONAL
IDENTITY, SOUL. W.E.M. sustaining cause.CAUSATION. sutra (from Sanskrit sutra,
‘thread’, ‘precept’), a single verse or aphorism of Hindu or Buddhist teaching,
or a collection of them. Written to be memorized, they provide a means of
encoding and transmitting laws and rules of grmar, ritual, poetic meter, and
philosophical disputation. Typically using technical terms and written so as to
be mnemonic, they serve well for passing on information in an oral tradition.
What makes them serviceable for this purpose also makes them largely
unintelligible without commentary. The sutra style is typical in philosophical
traditions. The Brahma-Sutras of Badharana are an exple of a set of sutras
regarded as authoritative by Vedanta but interpreted in vastly different ways
by Shankara, Ranuja, and Madhva. The sutras associated with Buddhism typically
are more expansive than those associated with Hinduism, and thus more
intelligible on their own. The Tripitaka (“Basket of the Teachings”) is a
collection of sutras that Buddhist tradition ascribes to Ananda, who is said to
have recited them from memory at the first Buddhist council; each sutra is
introduced by the words ‘Thus have I heard’. Sutras are associated with
Theravada as well as Mahayana Buddhism and deal with both religious and
philosophical topics. K.E.Y. Swedenborgianism, the theosophy professed by a
worldwide movement established as the New Jerusalem Church in London in 1788 by
the followers of Emanuel Swedenborg (1688–1772), a Swedish natural philosopher,
visionary, and biblical exegete. Author of geological and cosmological works,
he fused the rationalist (Cartesian) and empiricist (Lockean) legacies into a
natural philosophy (Principia Rerum Naturalium, 1734) that propounded the
harmony of the mechanistic universe with biblical revelation. Inspired by
Liebniz, Malebranche, Platonism, and Neoplatonism, he unfolded a doctrine of
correspondence (A Hieroglyphic Key, 1741) to account for the relation between
body and soul and between the natural and spiritual worlds, and applied it to
biblical exegesis. What attracted the wide following of the “Spirit-Seer” were
his theosophic speculations in the line of Boehme and the mystical, prophetic
tradition in which he excelled (Heavenly Arcana, 1749–56). J.-L.S. Swinburne,
Richard (b.1934), British philosopher of religion and of science. In philosophy
of science, he has contributed to confirmation theory and to the philosophy of
space and time. His work in philosophy of religion is the most bitious project
in philosophical theology undertaken by a British philosopher in the twentieth
century. Its first part is a trilogy on the coherence and justification of
theistic belief and the rationality of living by that belief: The Coherence of
Theism (1977), The Existence of God (1979), and Faith and Reason (1981). Since
1985, when Swinburne bece Nolloth Professor of the Philosophy of the Christian
Religion at the University of Oxford, he has written a tetralogy about some of
the most central of the distinctively Christian religious doctrines:
Responsibility and Atonement (1989), Revelation (1992), The Christian God
(1994), and Providence and the Problem of Evil (1998). The most interesting
feature of the trilogy is its contribution to natural theology. Using Bayesian
reasoning, Swinburne builds a cumulative case for theism by arguing that its
probability is raised sustaining cause Swinburne, Richard 893 893 by such things as the existence of the
universe, its order, the existence of consciousness, human opportunities to do
good, the pattern of history, evidence of miracles, and religious experience.
The existence of evil does not count against the existence of God. On our total
evidence theism is more probable than not. In the tetralogy he explicates and
defends such Christian doctrines as original sin, the Atonement, Heaven, Hell,
the Trinity, the Incarnation, and Providence. He also analyzes the grounds for
supposing that some Christian doctrines are revealed truths, and argues for a
Christian theodicy in response to the problem of evil.
syllogism, in Aristotle’s
words, “a discourse in which, a certain thing being stated, something other
than what is stated follows of necessity from being so” (Prior Analytics, 24b
18). Three types of syllogism were usually distinguished: categorical,
hypothetical, and disjunctive. Each will be treated in that order. The
categorical syllogism. This is an argument consisting of three categorical
propositions, two serving as premises and one serving as conclusion. E.g.,
‘Some college students are happy; all college students are high school
graduates; therefore, some high school graduates are happy’. If a syllogism is
valid, the premises must be so related to the conclusion that it is impossible
for both premises to be true and the conclusion false. There are four types of
categorical propositions: universal affirmative or A-propositions – ‘All S are
P’, or ‘SaP’; universal negative or E-propositions – ‘No S are P’, or ‘SeP’; particular
affirmative or I-propositions – ‘Some S are P’, or ‘SiP’; and particular
negative or O-propositions: ‘Some S are not P’, or ‘SoP’. The mediate basic
components of categorical syllogism are terms serving as subjects or predicates
in the premises and the conclusion. There must be three and only three terms in
any categorical syllogism, the major term, the minor term, and the middle term.
Violation of this basic rule of structure is called the fallacy of four terms
(quaternio terminorum); e.g., ‘Whatever is right is useful; only one of my
hands is right; therefore only one of my hands is useful’. Here ‘right’ does
not have the se meaning in its two occurrences; we therefore have more than
three terms and hence no genuine categorical syllogism. The syllogistic terms
are identifiable and definable with reference to the position they have in a
given syllogism. The predicate of the conclusion is the major term; the subject
of the conclusion is the minor term; the term that appears once in each premise
but not in the conclusion is the middle term. As it is used in various types of
categorical propositions, a term is either distributed (stands for each and
every member of its extension) or undistributed. There is a simple rule
regarding the distribution: universal propositions (SaP and SeP) distribute
their subject terms; negative propositions (SeP and SoP) distribute their
predicate terms. No terms are distributed in an I-proposition. Various sets of
rules governing validity of categorical syllogisms have been offered. The
following is a “traditional” set from the popular Port-Royal Logic (1662). R1:
The middle term must be distributed at least once. Violation: ‘All cats are
animals; some animals do not eat liver; therefore some cats do not eat liver’.
The middle term ‘animals’ is not distributed either in the first or minor
premise, being the predicate of an affirmative proposition, nor in the second
or major premise, being the subject of a particular proposition; hence, the
fallacy of undistributed middle. R2: A term cannot be distributed in the
conclusion if it is undistributed in the premises. Violation: ‘All dogs are
carnivorous; no flowers are dogs; therefore, no flowers are carnivorous’. Here
the major, ‘carnivorous’, is distributed in the conclusion, being the predicate
of a negative proposition, but not in the premise, serving there as predicate
of an affirmative proposition; hence, the fallacy of illicit major term.
Another violation of R2: ‘All students are happy individuals; no criminals are
students; therefore, no happy individuals are criminals’. Here the minor,
‘happy individuals’, is distributed in the conclusion, but not distributed in
the minor premise; hence the fallacy of illicit minor term. R3: No conclusion
may be drawn from two negative premises. Violation: ‘No dogs are cats; some
dogs do not like liver; therefore, some cats do not like liver’. Here R1 is
satisfied, since the middle term ‘dogs’ is distributed in the minor premise; R2
is satisfied, since both the minor term ‘cats’ as well as the major term
‘things that like liver’ are distributed in the premises and thus no violation
of distribution of terms occurs. It is only by virtue of R3 that we can
proclaim this syllogism to be invalid. R4: A negative conclusion cannot be
drawn where both premises are affirmative. Violation: ‘All educated people take
good care of their children; all syllogism syllogism 894 894 who take good care of their children are
poor; therefore, some poor people are not educated’. Here, it is only by virtue
of the rule of quality, R4, that we can proclaim this syllogism invalid. R5:
The conclusion must follow the weaker premise; i.e., if one of the premises is
negative, the conclusion must be negative, and if one of them is particular,
the conclusion must be particular. R6: From two particular premises nothing
follows. Let us offer an indirect proof for this rule. If both particular
premises are affirmative, no term is distributed and therefore the fallacy of
undistributed middle is inevitable. To avoid it, we have to make one of the
premises negative, which will result in a distributed predicate as middle term.
But by R5, the conclusion must then be negative; thus, the major term will be
distributed in the conclusion. To avoid violating R2, we must distribute that
term in the major premise. It could not be in the position of subject term,
since only universal propositions distribute their subject term and, by
hypothesis, both premises are particular. But we could not use the se negative
premise used to distribute the middle term; we must make the other particular
premise negative. But then we violate R3. Thus, any attempt to make a syllogism
with two particular premises valid will violate one or more basic rules of
syllogism. (This set of rules assumes that A- and Epropositions have
existential import and hence that an I- or an O-proposition may legitimately be
drawn from a set of exclusively universal premises.) Categorical syllogisms are
classified according to figure and mood. The figure of a categorical syllogism
refers to the schema determined by the possible position of the middle term in
relation to the major and minor terms. In “modern logic,” four syllogistic
figures are recognized. Using ‘M’ for middle term, ‘P’ for major term, and ‘S’
for minor term, they can be depicted as follows: Aristotle recognized only
three syllogistic figures. He seems to have taken into account just the two
premises and the extension of the three terms occurring in them, and then asked
what conclusion, if any, can be derived from those premises. It turns out,
then, that his procedure leaves room for three figures only: one in which the M
term is the subject of one and predicate of the other premise; another in which
the M term is predicated in both premises; and a third one in which the M term
is the subject in both premises. Medievals followed him, although all
considered the so-called inverted first (i.e., moods of the first figure with
their conclusion converted either simply or per accidens) to be legitimate
also. Some medievals (e.g., Albalag) and most moderns since Leibniz recognize a
fourth figure as a distinct figure, considering syllogistic terms on the basis
not of their extension but of their position in the conclusion, the S term of
the conclusion being defined as the minor term and the P term being defined as
the major term. The mood of a categorical syllogism refers to the configuration
of types of categorical propositions determined on the basis of the quality and
quantity of the propositions serving as premises and conclusion of any given
syllogism; e.g., ‘No animals are plants; all cats are animals; therefore no
cats are plants’, ‘(MeP, S /, SeP)’, is a syllogism in the mood EAE in the
first figure. ‘All metals conduct electricity; no stones conduct electricity;
therefore no stones are metals’, ‘(P, SeM /, SeP)’, is the mood AEE in the
second figure. In the four syllogistic figures there are 256 possible moods,
but only 24 are valid (only 19 in modern logic, on the ground of a
non-existential treatment of A- and E-propositions). As a mnemonic device and
to facilitate reference, nes have been assigned to the valid moods, with each
vowel representing the type of categorical proposition. Willi Sherwood and
Peter of Spain offered the fous list designed to help students to remember which
moods in any given figure are valid and how the “inevident” moods in the second
and third figures are provable by reduction to those in the first figure:
barbara, celarent, darii, ferio (direct Fig. 1); baralipton, celantes, dabitis,
fapesmo, frisesomorum (indirect Fig. 1); cesare, cestres, festino, baroco (Fig.
2); darapti, felapton, disis, datisi, bocardo, ferison (Fig. 3). The
hypothetical syllogism. The pure hypothetical syllogism is an argument in which
both the premises and the conclusion are hypothetical, i.e. conditional,
propositions; e.g., ‘If the sun is shining, it is warm; if it is warm, the
plants will grow; therefore if the sun is shining, the plants will grow’.
Symbolically, this argument form can be represented by ‘A P B, B P C /, A P C’.
It was not recognized as such by Aristotle, but Aristotle’s pupil Theophrastus
foreshadowed it, even syllogism syllogism 895
895 though it is not clear from his exple of it – ‘If man is, animal is;
if animal is, then substance is; if therefore man is, substance is’ – whether
this was seen to be a principle of term logic or a principle of propositional
logic. It was the MegaricStoic philosophers and Boethius who fully recognized
hypothetical propositions and syllogisms as principles of the most general theory
of deduction. Mixed hypothetical syllogisms are arguments consisting of a
hypothetical premise and a categorical premise, and inferring a categorical
proposition; e.g., ‘If the sun is shining, the plants will grow; the sun is
shining; therefore the plants will grow’. Symbolically, this is represented by
‘P P Q, P /, Q’. This argument form was explicitly formulated in ancient times
by the Stoics as one of the “indemonstrables” and is now known as modus ponens.
Another equally basic form of mixed hypothetical syllogism is ‘P P Q, -Q /,
~P’, known as modus tollens. The disjunctive syllogism. This is an argument in
which the leading premise is a disjunction, the other premise being a denial of
one of the alternatives, concluding to the remaining alternative; e.g., ‘It is
raining or I will go for a walk; but it is not raining; therefore I will go for
a walk’. It is not always clear whether the ‘or’ of the disjunctive premise is
inclusive or exclusive. Symbolic logic removes the biguity by using two different
symbols and thus clearly distinguishes between inclusive or weak disjunction,
‘P 7 Q’, which is true provided not both alternatives are false, and exclusive
or strong disjunction, ‘P W Q’, which is true provided exactly one alternative
is true and exactly one false. The definition of ‘disjunctive syllogism’
presupposes that the lead premise is an inclusive or weak disjunction, on the
basis of which two forms are valid: ‘P 7 Q, -P /, Q’ and ‘P 7 Q, -Q /, P’. If
the disjunctive premise is exclusive, we have four valid argument forms, and we
should speak here of an exclusive disjunctive syllogism. This is defined as an
argument in which either from an exclusive disjunction and the denial of one of
its disjuncts we infer the remaining disjunct – ’P W Q, -P /,Q’, and ‘P W Q, -Q
/, P’ (modus tollendo ponens); or else, from an exclusive disjunction and one
of its disjuncts we infer the denial of the remaining disjunct – ’P W Q, P /,
-Q’, and ‘P W Q, Q /,-P’ (modus ponendo tollens).
synaesthesia, a conscious
experience in which qualities normally associated with one sensory modality are
or seem to be sensed in another. Exples include auditory and tactile visions
such as “loud sunlight” and “soft moonlight” as well as visual bodily
sensations such as “dark thoughts” and “bright smiles.” Two features of
synaesthesia are of philosophic interest. First, the experience may be used to
judge the appropriateness of sensory metaphors and similes, such as
Baudelaire’s “sweet as oboes.” The metaphor is appropriate just when oboes
sound sweet. Second, synaesthesia challenges the manner in which common sense
distinguishes ong the external senses. It is commonly acknowledged that taste,
e.g., is not only unlike hearing, smell, or any other sense, but differs from
them because taste involves gustatory rather than auditory experiences. In
synaesthesia, however, one might taste sounds (sweet-sounding oboes). G.A.G.
syncategoremata, (1) in grmar, words that cannot serve by themselves as
subjects or predicates of categorical propositions. The opposite is
categoremata, words that can do this. For exple, ‘and’, ‘if’, ‘every’,
‘because’, ‘insofar’, and ‘under’ are syncategorematic terms, whereas ‘dog’,
‘smooth’, and ‘sings’ are categorematic ones. This usage comes from the
fifth-century Latin grmarian Priscian. It seems to have been the original way
of drawing the distinction, and to have persisted through later periods along
syllogism, demonstrative syncategoremata 896
896 with other usages described below. (2) In medieval logic from the twelfth
century on, the distinction was drawn semantically. Categoremata are words that
have a (definite) independent signification. Syncategoremata do not have any
independent signification (or, according to some authors, not a definite one
anyway), but acquire a signification only when used in a proposition together
with categoremata. The exples used above work here as well. (3) Medieval logic
distinguished not only categorematic and syncategorematic words, but also
categorematic and syncategorematic uses of a single word. The most important is
the word ‘is’, which can be used both categorematically to make an existence
claim (‘Socrates is’ in the sense ‘Socrates exists’) or syncategorematically as
a copula (‘Socrates is a philosopher’). But other words were treated this way
too. Thus ‘whole’ was said to be used syncategorematically as a kind of
quantifier in ‘The whole surface is white’ (from which it follows that each
part of the surface is white), but categorematically in ‘The whole surface is
two square feet in area’ (from which it does not follow that each part of the
surface is two square feet in area). (4) In medieval logic, again,
syncategoremata were sometimes taken to include words that can serve by
themselves as subjects or predicates of categorical propositions, but may
interfere with standard logical inference patterns when they do. The most
notorious exple is the word ‘nothing’. If nothing is better than eternal bliss
and tepid tea is better than nothing, still it does not follow (by the transitivity
of ‘better than’) that tepid tea is better than eternal bliss. Again, consider
the verb ‘begins’. Everything red is colored, but not everything that begins to
be red begins to be colored (it might have been some other color earlier). Such
words were classified as syncategorematic because an analysis (called an
expositio) of propositions containing them reveals implicit syncategoremata in
sense (1) or perhaps (2). Thus an analysis of ‘The apple begins to be red’
would include the claim that it was not red earlier, and ‘not’ is
syncategorematic in both senses (1) and (2). (5) In modern logic, sense (2) is
extended to apply to all logical symbols, not just to words in natural
languages. In this usage, categoremata are also called “proper symbols” or “complete
symbols,” while syncategoremata are called “improper symbols” or “incomplete
symbols.” In the terminology of modern formal semantics, the meaning of
categoremata is fixed by the models for the language, whereas the meaning of
syncategoremata is fixed by specifying truth conditions for the various
formulas of the language in terms of the models.
synderesis, in medieval
moral theology, conscience. St. Jerome used the term, and it bece a fixture
because of Peter Lombard’s inclusion of it in his Sentences. Despite this
origin, ‘synderesis’ is distinguished from ‘conscience’ by Aquinas, for whom
synderesis is the quasi-habitual grasp of the most common principles of the
moral order (i.e., natural law), whereas conscience is the application of such
knowledge to fleeting and unrepeatable circumstances. ’Conscience’ is biguous
in the way in which ‘knowledge’ is: knowledge can be the mental state of the
knower or what the knower knows. But ‘conscience’, like ‘synderesis’, is
typically used for the mental state. Sometimes, however, conscience is taken to
include general moral knowledge as well as its application here and now; but
the content of synderesis is the most general precepts, whereas the content of
conscience, if general knowledge, will be less general precepts. Since
conscience can be erroneous, the question arises as to whether synderesis and
its object, natural law precepts, can be obscured and forgotten because of bad
behavior or upbringing. Aquinas held that while great attrition can take place,
such common moral knowledge cannot be wholly expunged from the human mind. This
is a version of the Aristotelian doctrine that there are starting points of
knowledge so easily grasped that the grasping of them is a defining mark of the
human being. However perversely the human agent behaves there will remain not
only the comprehensive realization that good is to be done and evil avoided,
but also the recognition of some substantive human goods. AQUINAS, ARISTOTLE, ETHICS. R.M.
syndicalism.SOREL. synechism.PEIRCE, TYCHISM. synergism, in Christian
soteriology, the cooperation within human consciousness of free will and divine
grace in the processes of conversion and regeneration. Synergism bece an issue
in sixteenth-century Lutheranism during a controversy prompted by Philip
Melanchthon (1497– syncategorematic synergism 897 897 1569). Under the influence of Erasmus,
Melanchthon mentioned, in the 1533 edition of his Common Places, three causes
of good actions: “the Word, the Holy Spirit, and the will.” Advocated by
Pfeffinger, a Philipist, synergism was attacked by the orthodox,
predestinarian, and monergist party, sdorf and Flacius, who retorted with
Gnesio-Lutheranism. The ensuing Formula of Concord (1577) officialized
monergism. Synergism occupies a middle position between uncritical trust in
human noetic and salvific capacity (Pelagianism and deism) and exclusive trust
in divine agency (Calvinist and Lutheran fideism). Catholicism, Arminianism,
Anglicanism, Methodism, and nineteenth- and twentieth-century liberal
Protestantism have professed versions of synergism.
systems theory, the
transdisciplinary study of the abstract organization of phenomena, independent
of their substance, type, or spatial or temporal scale of existence. It
investigates both the principles common to all complex entities and the
(usually mathematical) models that can be used to describe them. Systems theory
was proposed in the 1940s by the biologist Ludwig von Bertalanffy and furthered
by Ross Ashby (Introduction to Cybernetics, 1956). Von Bertalanffy was both
reacting against reductionism and attempting to revive the unity of science. He
emphasized that real systems are open to, and interact with, their
environments, and that they can acquire qualitatively new properties through
emergence, resulting in continual evolution. Rather than reduce an entity (e.g.
the human body) to the properties of its parts or elements (e.g. organs or
cells), systems theory focuses on the arrangement of and relations ong the
parts that connect them into a whole (cf. holism). This particular organization
determines a system, which is independent of the concrete substance of the
elements (e.g. particles, cells, transistors, people). Thus, the se concepts
and principles of organization underlie the different disciplines (physics,
biology, technology, sociology, etc.), providing a basis for their unification.
Systems concepts include: system– environment boundary, input, output, process,
state, hierarchy, goal-directedness, and information. The developments of systems
theory are diverse (Klir, Facets of Systems Science, 1991), including
conceptual foundations and philosophy (e.g. the philosophies of Bunge, Bahm,
and Laszlo); mathematical modeling and information theory (e.g. the work of
Mesarovic and Klir); and practical applications. Mathematical systems theory
arose from the development of isomorphies between the models of electrical
circuits and other systems. Applications include engineering, computing,
ecology, management, and fily psychotherapy. Systems analysis, developed
independently of systems theory, applies systems principles to aid a decision
maker with problems of identifying, reconstructing, optimizing, and controlling
a system (usually a socio-technical organization), while taking into account
multiple objectives, constraints, and resources. It aims to specify possible
courses of action, together with their risks, costs, and benefits. Systems
theory is closely connected to cybernetics, and also to system dynics, which
models changes in a network of synergy systems theory 898 898 coupled variables (e.g. the “world
dynics” models of Jay Forrester and the Club of Rome). Related ideas are used
in the emerging “sciences of complexity,” studying self-organization and
heterogeneous networks of interacting actors, and associated domains such as
far-from-equilibrium thermodynics, chaotic dynics, artificial life, artificial
intelligence, neural networks, and computer modeling and simulation.
T
Ta-hsüeh, a part of the
Chinese Confucian classic Book of Rites whose title is standardly translated as
Great Learning. Chu Hsi significantly ended the text (composed in the third or
second century B.C.) and elevated it to the status of an independent classic as
one of the Four Books. He regarded it as a quotation from Confucius and a
commentary by Confucius’s disciple Tseng-tzu, but neither his emendations nor
his interpretation of the text is beyond dispute. The Ta-hsüeh instructs a
ruler in how to bring order to his state by self-cultivation. Much discussion
of the text revolves around the phrase ko wu, which describes the first step in
self-cultivation but is left undefined. The Ta-hsüeh claims that one’s
virtuousness or viciousness is necessarily evident to others, and that virtue
manifests itself first in one’s filial relationships, which then serve as an
exemplar of order in both filies and the state.
CONFUCIANISM. B.W.V.N.
Tai Chen (1724–77),
Chinese philologist, philosopher, mathematician, and astronomer. A prominent
member of the K’ao-cheng (evidential research) School, Tai attacked the
Neo-Confucian dualism of li (pattern) and ch’i (ether), insisting that li is
simply the orderly structure of ch’i. In terms of ethics, li consists of
“feelings that do not err.” In his Meng-tzu tzu-yi shu-cheng (“Meanings of Terms
in the Mencius Explained and Attested”), Tai argues for the need to move from
mere yi-chien (opinions) to pu-te chih-yi (undeviating standards) by applying
the Confucian golden rule – not as a formal principle determining right action
but as a winnowing procedure that culls out improper desires and allows only
proper ones to inform one’s actions. Beginning with tzu jan (natural) desires,
one tests their universalizability with the golden rule, thereby identifying
those that accord with what is pi-jan (necessary). One spontaneously k’o
(approves of) the “necessary,” and Tai claims this is what Mencius describes as
the “joy” of moral action. MENCIUS.
P.J.I. t’ai-chi, Chinese term meaning ‘Great Ultimate’, an idea first developed
in the “Appended Remarks” of the I-Ching, where it is said that in the system
of Change there is the Great Ultimate. It generates the Two Modes (yin and
yang); the Two Modes generate the Four Forms (major and minor yin and yang);
and the Four Forms generate the Eight Trigrs. In his “Explanation of the Diagr
of the Great Ultimate,” Chou Tunyi (1017–73) spoke of “Non-ultimate (wu-chi)
and also the Great Ultimate!” He generated controversies. Chu Hsi (1130–1200)
approved Chou’s formulation and interpreted t’ai-chi as li (principle), which
is formless on the one hand and has principle on the other hand. CH’IEN, K’UN; CHOU TUN-YI; CHU HSI. S.-h.L.
T’ang Chün-i (1909–78),
Chinese philosopher, a leading contemporary New Confucian and cofounder, with
Ch’ien Mu, of New Asia College in Hong Kong in 1949. He acknowledged that it
was through the influence of Hsiung Shih-li that he could see the true insights
in Chinese philosophy. He drafted a manifesto published in 1958 and signed by
Carsun Chang (1887–1969), Hsü Fu-kuan, and Mou Tsung-san. They criticized
current sinological studies as superficial and inadequate, and maintained that
China must learn science and democracy from the West, but the West must also
learn human-heartedness and love of harmony and peace from Chinese culture. CH’IEN MU, CHINESE PHILOSOPHY, HSIUNG
SHIH-LI, HSÜ FU-KUAN. S.-h.L. T’an Ssu-t’ung (1864–98), Chinese philosopher of
the late Ching dynasty, a close associate of K’ang Yu-wei and Liang Ch’i-ch’ao.
He was a syncretist who lumped together Confucianism, Mohism, Taoism, Buddhism,
Christianity, and Western science. His book on Jen-hsüeh (philosophy of
humanity) identified humanity with ether, a cosmic force, and gave a new
interpreta900 T 900 tion to the unity
between nature and humanity. Jen for him is the source of all existence and
creatures; it is none other than reality itself. He participated in the Hundred
Days Reform in 1898 and died a martyr. His personal exple inspired many
revolutionaries afterward.
KANG YU-WEI, LIANG
CH’I-CH’AO. S.-h.L. tao, Chinese term meaning ‘path’, ‘way’, ‘account’. From
the sense of a literal path, road, or way, the term comes to mean a way of
doing something (e.g., living one’s life or organizing society), especially the
way advocated by a particular individual or school of thought (“the way of the
Master,” “the way of the Mohists,” etc.). Frequently, it refers to the way of
doing something, the right way (e.g., “The Way has not been put into practice
for a long time”). Tao also ce to refer to the linguistic account that embodies
or describes a way. Finally, in some texts the tao is a metaphysical entity.
For exple, in Neo-Confucianism, tao is identified with li (principle). In some
contexts it is difficult to tell what sense is intended. LI1, NEO-CONFUCIANISM. B.W.V.N. tao-hsin,
jen-hsin, Chinese terms used by NeoConfucian philosophers to contrast the mind
according to the Way (tao-hsin) and the mind according to man’s artificial,
selfish desires (jenhsin). When one responds spontaneously without making
discrimination, one is acting according to the Way. One is naturally happy,
sad, angry, and joyful as circumstances require. But when one’s self is
alienated from the Way, one works only for self-interest, and the emotions and
desires are excessive and deviate from the Mean. In the Confucian tradition
sages and worthies take Heaven as their model, while common people are urged to
take chün-tzu (the superior men) as their model.
Taoism, a Chinese philosophy identified with
the Tao-chia (School of the Way), represented by Chuang Tzu and Lao Tzu. The
term may also refer to the Huang–Lao School; Neo-Taoists, such as Wang Pi and
Kuo Hsiang; and Tao-chiao, a diverse religious movement. Only the Tao-chia is
discussed here. The school derives its ne from the word tao (Way), a term used
by Chinese thinkers of almost every persuasion. Taoists were the first to use
the term to describe the comprehensive structure and dynic of the cosmos.
Taoists believe that (1) there is a way the world should be, a way that, in
some deep sense, it is; (2) human beings can understand this and need to have
and follow such knowledge if they and the world are to exist in harmony; and
(3) the world was once in such a state. Most early Chinese thinkers shared
similar beliefs, but Taoists are distinct in claiming that the Way is not
codifiable, indeed is ineffable. Taoists thus are metaphysical and ethical
realists, but epistemological skeptics of an unusual sort, being language
skeptics. Taoists further deny that one can strive successfully to attain the
Way; Taoist self-cultivation is a process not of accumulation but of paring
away. One must unweave the social fabric, forsake one’s cultural conditioning,
and abandon rational thought, to be led instead by one’s tzu jan (spontaneous)
inclinations. With a hsü (tenuous) mind, one then will perceive the li
(pattern) of the cosmos and live by wu wei (non-action). Though sharing a
strong fily resemblance, the Taoisms of Lao Tzu and Chuang Tzu are distinct.
Lao Tzu advocates a primitive utopianism in which people enjoy the simple life
of small agrarian communities, indifferent to what is happening in the
neighboring village. Having abandoned cultural achievements such as writing,
they keep accounts by knotting cords. Lao Tzu bles human “cleverness,” which
imposes the “human” on the “Heavenly,” for most of what is bad in the world.
For him, a notion like beauty gives rise to its opposite and only serves to
increase anxiety and dissatisfaction; extolling a virtue, such as benevolence,
only encourages people to affect it hypocritically. Lao Tzu advocates “turning
back” to the time when intellect was young and still obedient to intuition and
instinct. To accomplish this, the Taoist sage must rule and enforce this view
upon the clever, if they should “dare to act.” Chuang Tzu emphasizes changing
oneself more than changing society. He too is a kind of anti-rationalist and
sees wisdom as a “knowing how” rather than a “knowing that.” He invokes a
repertoire of skillful individuals as exemplars of the Way. Such individuals
engage the world through a knack that eludes definitive description and display
all the Taoist virtues. Their minds are hsü (empty) of preconceptions, and so
they perceive the li (pattern) in each situation. They respond spontaneously
and so are tzu jan; they don’t force things and so practice wu wei. In accord
with the tao, they lead a frictionless existence; they “walk without touching
the ground.” NEO-TAOISM, TAO. P.J.I. tao
Taoism 901 901 Tao Te Ching.LAO TZU.
tao-t’ung, Chinese term meaning ‘the orthodox line of transmission of the Way’.
According to Chu Hsi (1130–1200), the first to use this term, the line of
transmission can be traced back to ancient sage-emperors, Confucius and
Mencius. The line was broken since Mencius and was only revived by the Ch’eng
brothers in the Sung dynasty. The interesting feature is that the line has
excluded important Confucian scholars such as Hsün Tzu (fl. 298–238 B.C.) and
Tung Chungshu (c.179–c.104 B.C.). The idea of tao-t’ung can be traced back to
Han Yü (768–824) and Mencius.
CHU HSI, CONFUCIANISM, CONFUCIUS, HAN YÜ, HSÜN
TZU, MENCIUS, NEOCONFUCIANISM, TUNG CHUNG-SHU. S.-h.L. Tarski, Alfred
(1901–83), Polish-born erican mathematician, logician, and philosopher of logic
fous for his investigations of the concepts of truth and consequence conducted
in the 1930s. His analysis of the concept of truth in syntactically precise,
fully interpreted languages resulted in a definition of truth and an articulate
defense of the correspondence theory of truth. Sentences of the following kind
are now known as Tarskian biconditionals: ‘The sentence “Every perfect number
is even” is true if and only if every perfect number is even.’ One of Tarski’s
major philosophical insights is that each Tarskian biconditional is, in his
words, a partial definition of truth and, consequently, all Tarskian
biconditionals whose right-hand sides exhaust the sentences of a given formal
language together constitute an implicit definition of ‘true’ as applicable to
sentences of that given formal language. This insight, because of its
penetrating depth and disarming simplicity, has become a staple of modern
analytic philosophy. Moreover, it in effect reduced the philosophical problem
of defining truth to the logical problem of constructing a single sentence
having the form of a definition and having as consequences each of the Tarskian
biconditionals. Tarski’s solution to this problem is the fous Tarski truth
definition, versions of which appear in virtually every mathematical logic
text. Tarski’s second most widely recognized philosophical achievement was his
analysis and explication of the concept of consequence. Consequence is
interdefinable with validity as applied to arguments: a given conclusion is a
consequence of a given premise-set if and only if the argument composed of the
given conclusion and the given premise-set is valid; conversely, a given
argument is valid if and only if its conclusion is a consequence of its
premise-set. Shortly after discovering the truth definition, Tarski presented
his “no-countermodels” definition of consequence: a given sentence is a
consequence of a given set of sentences if and only if every model of the set
is a model of the sentence (in other words, if and only if there is no way to
reinterpret the non-logical terms in such a way as to render the sentence false
while rendering all sentences in the set true). As Quine has emphasized, this
definition reduces the modal notion of logical necessity to a combination of
syntactic and semantic concepts, thus avoiding reference to modalities and/or
to “possible worlds.” After Tarski’s definitive work on truth and on
consequence he devoted his energies largely to more purely mathematical work.
For exple, in answer to Gödel’s proof that arithmetic is incomplete and
undecidable, Tarski showed that algebra and geometry are both complete and
decidable. Tarski’s truth definition and his consequence definition are found
in his 1956 collection Logic, Semantics, Metathematics (2d ed., 1983): article
VIII, pp. 152–278, contains the truth definition; article XVI, pp. 409–20,
contains the consequence definition. His published articles, nearly 3,000 s in
all, have been available together since 1986 in the four-volume Alfred Tarski,
Collected Papers, edited by S. Givant and R. McKenzie.
tautology, a proposition
whose negation is inconsistent, or (self-) contradictory, e.g. ‘Socrates is
Socrates’, ‘Every human is either male or nonmale’, ‘No human is both male and
non-male’, ‘Every human is identical to itself’, ‘If Socrates is human then
Socrates is human’. A proposition that is (or is logically equivalent to) the
negation of a tautology is called a (self-)contradiction. According to
classical logic, the property of being Tao Te Ching tautology 902 902 implied by its own negation is a
necessary and sufficient condition for being a tautology and the property of
implying its own negation is a necessary and sufficient condition for being a
contradiction. Tautologies are logically necessary and contradictions are
logically impossible. Epistemically, every proposition that can be known to be
true by purely logical reasoning is a tautology and every proposition that can
be known to be false by purely logical reasoning is a contradiction. The
converses of these two statements are both controversial ong classical logicians.
Every proposition in the se logical form as a tautology is a tautology and
every proposition in the se logical form as a contradiction is a contradiction.
For this reason sometimes a tautology is said to be true in virtue of form and
a contradiction is said to be false in virtue of form; being a tautology and
being a contradiction (tautologousness and contradictoriness) are formal
properties. Since the logical form of a proposition is determined by its
logical terms (‘every’, ‘some’, ‘is’, etc.), a tautology is sometimes said to
be true in virtue of its logical terms and likewise mutatis mutandis for a
contradiction. Since tautologies do not exclude any logical possibilities they
are sometimes said to be “empty” or “uninformative”; and there is a tendency
even to deny that they are genuine propositions and that knowledge of them is
genuine knowledge. Since each contradiction “includes” (implies) all logical
possibilities (which of course are jointly inconsistent), contradictions are
sometimes said to be “overinformative.” Tautologies and contradictions are
sometimes said to be “useless,” but for opposite reasons. More precisely,
according to classical logic, being implied by each and every proposition is
necessary and sufficient for being a tautology and, coordinately, implying each
and every proposition is necessary and sufficient for being a contradiction.
Certain developments in mathematical logic, especially model theory and modal
logic, seem to support use of Leibniz’s expression ‘true in all possible
worlds’ in connection with tautologies. There is a special subclass of
tautologies called truth-functional tautologies that are true in virtue of a
special subclass of logical terms called truthfunctional connectives (‘and’,
‘or’, ‘not’, ‘if’, etc.). Some logical writings use ‘tautology’ exclusively for
truth-functional tautologies and thus replace “tautology” in its broad sense by
another expression, e.g. ‘logical truth’. Tarski, Gödel, Russell, and many
other logicians have used the word in its broad sense, but use of it in its
narrow sense is widespread and entirely acceptable. Propositions known to be
tautologies are often given as exples of a priori knowledge. In philosophy of
mathematics, the logistic hypothesis of logicism is the proposition that every
true proposition of pure mathematics is a tautology. Some writers make a sharp
distinction between the formal property of being a tautology and the non-formal
metalogical property of being a law of logic. For exple, ‘One is one’ is not
metalogical but it is a tautology, whereas ‘No tautology is a contradiction’ is
metalogical but is not a tautology.
Taylor, Charles (b.1931),
Canadian philosopher and historian of modernity. Taylor was educated at McGill
and Oxford and has taught primarily at these universities. His work has a
broadly analytic character, although he has consistently opposed the
naturalistic and reductionist tendencies that were associated with the
positivist domination of analytic philosophy during the 1950s and 1960s. He
was, for exple, a strong opponent of behaviorism and defended the essentially
interpretive nature of the social sciences against efforts to reduce their
methodology to that of the natural sciences. Taylor has also done important
work on the histiory of philosophy, particularly on Hegel, and has connected
his work with that of Continental philosophers such as Heidegger and
Merleau-Ponty. He has contributed to political theory and written on
contemporary political issues such as multiculturalism (in, e.g., The Ethics of
Authenticity, 1991), often with specific reference to Canadian politics. He has
also taken an active political role in Quebec. Taylor’s most important work,
Sources of the Self (1989), is a historical and critical study of the emergence
of the modern concept of the self. Like many other critics of modernity, Taylor
rejects modern tendencies to construe personal identity in entirely scientific
or naturalistic terms, arguing that these construals lead to a view of the self
that can make no sense of our undeniable experience of ourselves as moral
agents. He develops this critique in a historical mode through discussion of
the radical Enlightenment’s (e.g., Locke’s) reduction of the self to an atomic
individual, essentially disengaged from everything except its own ideas and
desires. But unlike many critics, Taylor also finds in modernity other, richer
sources for a conception of the self. These include the idea of the self’s
inwardness, traceable as far back as Augustine Taylor, Charles Taylor, Charles
903 903 but developed in a
distinctively modern way by Montaigne and Descartes; the affirmation of
ordinary life (and of ourselves as participants in it), particularly associated
with the Reformation; and the expressivism (of, e.g., the Romantics) for which
the self fulfills itself by embracing and articulating the voice of nature
present in its depths. Taylor thinks that these sources constitute a modern
self that, unlike the “punctual self” of the radical Enlightenment, is a
meaningful ethical agent. He suggests, nonetheless, that an adequate conception
of the modern self will further require a relation of human inwardness to God.
This suggestion so far remains undeveloped.
Taylor, Harriet
(1807–58), English feminist and writer. She was the wife of J. S. Mill, who called
her the “most admirable person” he had ever met; but according to her critics,
Taylor was “a stupid woman” with “a knack for repeating prettily what J.S.M.
said.” Although Mill may have exaggerated her moral and intellectual virtues,
her writings on marriage, the enfranchisement of women, and toleration did
influence his Subjection of Women and On Liberty. In The Enfranchisement of
Women, Taylor rejected the reigning “angel in the house” ideal of woman. She
argued that confining women to the house impeded both sexes’ development.
Taylor was a feminist philosopher in her own right, who argued even more
strongly than Mill that women are entitled to the se educational, legal, and
economic opportunities that men enjoy. R.T. te, Chinese term meaning ‘moral
charisma’ or ‘virtue’. In its earliest use, te is the quality bestowed on a
ruler by Heaven (t’ien) which makes his subjects willingly follow him. Rule by
te is traditionally thought to be not just ethically preferable to rule by
force but also more effective instrumentally. It is a necessary condition for
having te that one be ethically exemplary, but traditional thinkers differ over
whether being virtuous is also sufficient for the bestowal of te, and whether
the bestowal of te makes one even more virtuous. Te soon ce also to refer to
virtue, in the sense of either a disposition that contributes to human
flourishing (benevolence, courage, etc.) or the specific excellence of any kind
of thing. B.W.V.N. techne (Greek, ‘art’, ‘craft’), a human skill based on
general principles and capable of being taught. In this sense, a manual craft
such as carpentry is a techne, but so are sciences such as medicine and
arithmetic. According to Plato (Gorgias 501a), a genuine techne understands its
subject matter and can give a rational account of its activity. Aristotle
(Metaphysics I.1) distinguishes technefrom experience on the grounds that
techne involves knowledge of universals and causes, and can be taught.
Sometimes ‘techne’ is restricted to the productive (as opposed to theoretical
and practical) arts, as at Nicomachean Ethics VI.4. Techne and its products are
often contrasted with physis, nature (Physics II.1).
Teichmüller, Gustav
(1832–88), German philosopher who contributed to the history of philosophy and
developed a theory of knowledge and a metaphysical conception based on these
historical studies. Born in Braunschweig, he taught at Göttingen and Basel and
was influenced by Lotze and Leibniz. His major works are Aristotelische
Forschungen (Aristotelian Investigations, 1867–73) and Die wirkliche und
scheinbar Welt (The Actual and the Apparent World, 1882). His other works are
Ueber die Unsterblichkeit der Seele (1874), Studien zur Geschichte der Begriffe
(1874), Darwinismus und Philosophie (1877), Ueber das Wesen der Liebe (1879),
Religionsphilosophie (1886), and the posthumously published Neue Grundlegung
der Psychologie und Logik (1889). Teichmüller maintained that the self of
immediate experience, the “I,” is the most fundental reality and that the
conceptual world is a projection of its constituting activity. On the basis of
his studies in the history of metaphysics and his sympathies with Leibniz’s
monadology, he held that each metaphysical system contained partial truths and
construed each metaphysical standpoint as a perspective on a complex reality.
Thinking of both metaphysical interpretations of reality and the subjectivity
of individual immediate experience, Teichmüller christened his own
philosophical position “perspectivism.” His work influenced later European
thought through its impact on the philosophical reflections of Nietzsche, who
was probably influenced by him in the development of his perspectival theory of
knowledge.
Teilhard de Chardin,
Pierre (1881–1955), French paleontologist, Jesuit priest, and philosopher. His
Taylor, Harriet Teilhard de Chardin, Pierre 904 904 philosophical work, while published only
posthumously, was vigorously discussed throughout his career. His writings
generated considerable controversy within the church, since one of his
principal concerns was to bring about a forceful yet generous reconciliation
between the traditional Christian dogma and the dratic advances yielded by
modern science. His philosophy consisted of systematic reflections on
cosmology, biology, physics, anthropology, social theory, and theology –
reflections guided, he maintained, by his fascination with the nature of life,
energy, and matter, and by his profound respect for human spirituality.
Teilhard was educated in philosophy and mathematics at the Jesuit college of
Mongré, near Lyons. He entered the Jesuit order at the age of eighteen and was
ordained a priest in 1911. He went on to study at Aix-en-Provence, Laval, and
Caen, as well as on the Isle of Jersey and at Hastings, England. Returning to Paris
after the war, he studied biology, geology, and paleontology at the Museum of
Natural History and at the Institut Catholique, receiving a doctoral degree in
geology in 1922. In 1923, shortly after appointment to the faculty of geology
at the Institut Catholique, he took leave to pursue field research in China.
His research resulted in the discovery, in 1929, of Peking man (Sinanthropus
pekinensis) – which he saw as “perhaps the next to the last step traceable
between the anthropoids and man.” It was during this period that Teilhard began
to compose one of his major theoretical works, The Phenomenon of Man (1955), in
which he stressed the deep continuity of evolutionary development and the
emergence of humanity from the animal realm. He argued that received
evolutionary theory was fully compatible with Christian doctrine. Indeed, it is
the synthesis of evolutionary theory with his own Christian theology that
perhaps best characterizes the broad tenor of his thought. Starting with the
very inception of the evolutionary trajectory, i.e., with what he termed the
“Alpha point” of creation, Teilhard’s general theory resists any absolute
disjunction between the inorganic and organic. Indeed, matter and spirit are
two “stages” or “aspects” of the se cosmic stuff. These transitions from one
state to another may be said to correspond to those between the somatic and
psychic, the exterior and interior, according to the state of relative
development, organization, and complexity. Hence, for Teilhard, much as for
Bergson (whose work greatly influenced him), evolutionary development is
characterized by a progression from the simplest components of matter and
energy (what he termed the lithosphere), through the organization of flora and
fauna (the biosphere), to the complex formations of sentient and cognitive
human life (the noosphere). In this sense, evolution is a “progressive
spiritualization of matter.” He held this to be an orthogenetic process, one of
“directed evolution” or “Genesis,” by which matter would irreversibly
metorphose itself, in a process of involution and complexification, toward the
psychic. Specifically, Teilhard’s account sought to overcome what he saw as a
prescientific worldview, one based on a largely antiquated and indefensible
metaphysical dualism. By accomplishing this, he hoped to realize a productive
convergence of science and religion. The end of evolution, what he termed “the
Omega point,” would be the full presence of Christ, embodied in a universal
human society. Many have tended to see a Christian pantheism expressed in such
views. Teilhard himself stressed a profoundly personalist, spiritual
perspective, drawn not only from the theological tradition of Thomism, but from
that of Pauline Neoplatonism and Christian mysticism as well – especially that
tradition extending from Meister Eckhart through Cardinal Bérulle and
Malebranche. D.Al. telekinesis.PARAPSYCHOLOGY. teleofunctionalism.FODOR.
teleological argument.PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. teleological ethics.ETHICS.
teleological explanation.TELEOLOGY. teleological law.CAUSAL LAW. teleological
suspension of the ethical
.KIERKEGAARD. teleology,
the philosophical doctrine that all of nature, or at least intentional agents,
are goaldirected or functionally organized. Plato first suggested that the organization
of the natural world can be understood by comparing it to the behavior of an
intentional agent – external teleology. For exple, human beings can anticipate
the future and behave in ways calculated to realize their telekinesis teleology
905 905 intentions. Aristotle invested
nature itself with goals – internal teleology. Each kind has its own final
cause, and entities are so constructed that they tend to realize this goal.
Heavenly bodies travel as nearly as they are able in perfect circles because
that is their nature, while horses give rise to other horses because that is
their nature. Natural theologians combined these two teleological perspectives
to explain all phenomena by reference to the intentions of a beneficent,
omniscient, all-powerful God. God so constructed the world that each entity is
invested with the tendency to fulfill its own God-given nature. Darwin
explained the teleological character of the living world non-teleologically.
The evolutionary process is not itself teleological, but it gives rise to
functionally organized systems and intentional agents. Present-day philosophers
acknowledge intentional behavior and functional organization but attempt to
explain both without reference to a supernatural agent or internal natures of the
more metaphysical sort. Instead, they define ‘function’ cybernetically, in
terms of persistence toward a goal state under varying conditions, or
etiologically, in terms of the contribution that a structure or action makes to
the realization of a goal state. These definitions confront a battery of
counterexples designed to show that the condition mentioned is either not
necessary, not sufficient, or both; e.g., missing goal objects, too many goals,
or functional equivalents. The trend has been to decrease the scope of
teleological explanations from all of nature, to the organization of those
entities that arise through natural selection, to their final refuge in the
behavior of human beings. Behaviorists have attempted to eliminate this last
vestige of teleology. Just as natural selection makes the attribution of goals
for biological species redundant, the selection of behavior in terms of its
consequences is designed to make any reference to intentions on the part of
human beings unnecessary. MECHANISTIC
EXPLANATION. D.L.H. telepathy.PARAPSYCHOLOGY.
Telesio, Bernardino
(1509–88), Italian philosopher whose early scientific empiricism influenced
Francis Bacon and Galileo. He studied in Padua, where he completed his
doctorate in 1535, and practiced philosophy in Naples and Cosenza without
holding any academic position. His major work, the nine volumes of De rerum
natura iuxta propria principia (“On the Nature of Things According to Their
Principles,” 1586), contains an attempt to interpret nature on the basis of its
own principles, which Telesio identifies with the two incorporeal active forces
of heat and cold, and the corporeal and passive physical substratum. As the two
active forces permeate all of nature and are endowed with sensation, Telesio
argues that all of nature possesses some degree of sensation. Human beings
share with animals a material substance produced by heat and coming into
existence with the body, called spirit. They are also given a mind by God.
Telesio knew both the Averroistic and the Alexandrist interpretations of
Aristotle. However, he broke with both, criticizing Aristotle’s Physics and
claiming that nature is investigated better by the senses than by the
intellect. P.Gar. telishment, punishment of one suspected of wrongdoing, but whom
the authorities know to be innocent, imposed as a deterrent to future
wrongdoers. Telishment is thus not punishment insofar as punishment requires
that the recipient’s harsh treatment be deserved. Telishment is classically
given as one of the thought experiments challenging utilitarianism (and more
broadly, consequentialism) as a theory of ethics, for such a theory seems to
justify telishment on some occasions.
PUNISHMENT. M.S.M. telos, ancient Greek term meaning ‘end’ or ‘purpose’.
Telos is a key concept not only in Greek ethics but also in Greek science. The
purpose of a human being is a good life, and human activities are evaluated
according to whether they lead to or manifest this telos. Plants, animals, and
even inanimate objects were also thought to have a telos through which their
activities and relations could be understood and evaluated. Though a telos
could be something that transcends human activities and sensible things, as
Plato thought, it need not be anything apart from nature. Aristotle, e.g.,
identified the telos of a sensible thing with its immanent form. It follows
that the purpose of the thing is simply to be what it is and that, in general,
a thing pursues its purpose when it endeavors to preserve itself. Aristotle’s
view shows that ‘purpose in nature’ need not mean a higher purpose beyond
nature. Yet, his immanent purpose does not exclude “higher” purposes, and
Aristotelian teleology was pressed into service by medieval thinkers as a
frework for understanding God’s agency through nature. Thinkers in the modern
period argued against the prominent role accorded to telos by ancient telepathy
telos 906 906 and medieval thinkers,
and they replaced it with analyses in terms of mechanism and law.
IDENTITY. tense logic, an
extension of classical logic introduced by Arthur Prior (Past, Present, and
Future, 1967), involving operators P and F for the past and future tenses, or
‘it was the case that . . .’ and ‘it will be the case that . . .’. Classical or
mathematical logic was developed as a logic of unchanging mathematical truth,
and can be applied to tensed discourse only by artificial regimentation
inspired by mathematical physics, introducing quantification over “times” or
“instants.” Thus ‘It will have been the case that p,’ which Prior represents
simply as FPp, classical logic represents as ‘There [exists] an instant t and
there [exists] an instant tH such that t [is] later than the present and tH
[is] earlier than t, and at tH it [is] the case that pH, or DtDtH (t o‹t8tH
‹t8p(tH)), where the brackets indicate that the verbs are to be understood as
tenseless. Prior’s motives were in part linguistic (to produce a formalization
less removed from natural language than the classical) and in part metaphysical
(to avoid ontological commitment to such entities as instants). Much effort was
devoted to finding tense-logical principles equivalent to various classical
assertions about the structure of the earlier–later order ong instants; e.g.,
‘Between any two instants there is another instant’ corresponds to the validity
of the axioms Pp P PPp and Fp P FFp. Less is expressible using P and F than is
expressible with explicit quantification over instants, and further operators
for ‘since’ and ‘until’ or ‘now’ and ‘then’ have been introduced by Hans Kp and
others. These are especially important in combination with quantification, as
in ‘When he was in power, all who now condemn him then praised him.’ As tense
is closely related to mood, so tense logic is closely related to modal logic.
(As Kripke models for modal logic consist each of a set X of “worlds” and a
relation R of ‘x is an alternative to y’, so for tense logic they consist each
of a set X of “instants” and a relation R of ‘x is earlier than y’: Thus
instants, banished from the syntax or proof theory, reappear in the semantics
or model theory.) Modality and tense are both involved in the issue of future
contingents, and one of Prior’s motives was a desire to produce a formalism in
which the views on this topic of ancient, medieval, and early modern logicians
(from Aristotle with his “sea fight tomorrow” and Diodorus Cronos with his
“Master Argument” through Ockh to Peirce) could be represented. The most
important precursor to Prior’s work on tense logic was that on many-valued
logics by Lukasiewicz, which was motivated largely by the problem of future
contingents. Also related to tense and mood is aspect, and modifications to
represent this grmatical category (evaluating formulas at periods rather than
instants of time) have also been introduced. Like modal logic, tense logic has
been the object of intensive study in theoretical computer science, especially
in connection with attempts to develop languages in which properties of progrs
can be expressed and proved; variants of tense logic (under such labels as
“dynic logic” or “process logic”) have thus been extensively developed for
technological rather than philosophical motives.
Teresa of Ávila, Saint
(1515–82), Spanish religious, mystic, and author of spiritual treatises. Having
entered the Carmelite order at Ávila at twenty-two, Teresa spent the next
twenty-five years seeking guidance in the practice of prayer. Despite variously
inept spiritual advisers, she seems to have undergone a number of mystical
experiences and to have made increasingly important discoveries about interior
life. After 1560 Teresa took on a public role by attaching herself to the
reforming party within the Spanish Carmelites. Her remaining years were
occupied with the reform, in which she was associated most fously with John of the
Cross. She also composed several works, including a spiritual autobiography
(the Vida) and two masterpieces of spirituality, the Way of Perfection and the
Interior Castle. The latter two, but especially the Castle, offer philosophical
suggestions about the soul’s passions, activities, faculties, and ground. Their
principal motive is to teach the reader how to progress, by successive
surrender, toward the divine Trinity dwelling at the soul’s center. M.D.J.
term.RELATION, RUSSELL, SYLLOGISM. term, major.SYLLOGISM. temperance term,
major 907 907 term, minor.SYLLOGISM.
term, observation.PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. term, transcendental.TRANSCENDENTALS.
terminist logic, a school of logic originating in twelfth-century Europe and
dominant in the universities until its demise in the humanistic reforms. Its
chief goal was the elucidation of the logical form (the “exposition”) of
propositions advanced in the context of Scholastic disputation. Its central
theory concerned the properties of terms, especially supposition, and did the
work of modern quantification theory. Important logicians in the school include
Peter of Spain, Willi Sherwood, Walter Burley, Willi Heytesbury, and Paul of
Venice. BURLEY, HEYTESBURY, PAUL OF
VENICE, PETER OF SPAIN, SHERWOOD. J.Lo. terminus ad quem.TERMINUS A QUO.
terminus a quo (Latin, ‘term from which’), the
starting point of some process. The terminus ad quem is the ending point. For
exple, change is a process that begins from some state (the terminus a quo) and
proceeds to some state at which it ends (the terminus ad quem). In particular,
in the ripening of an apple, the green apple is the terminus a quo and the red
apple is the terminus ad quem. A.P.M. tertiary qualities.QUALITIES. Tertullian
(A.D. c.155–c.240), Latin theologian, an early father of the Christian church.
A layman from Carthage, he laid the conceptual and linguistic basis for the
doctrine of the Trinity. Though appearing hostile to philosophy (“What has
Athens to do with Jerusalem?”) and to rationality (“It is certain because it is
impossible”), Tertullian was steeped in Stoicism. He denounced all eclecticism
not governed by the normative tradition of Christian doctrine, yet commonly
used philosophical argument and Stoic concepts (e.g., the corporeality of God
and the soul). Despite insisting on the sole authority of the New Testent
apostles, he joined with Montanism, which taught that the Holy Spirit was still
inspiring prophecy concerning moral discipline. Reflecting this interest in the
Spirit, Tertullian pondered the distinctions (to which he gave the neologism
trinitas) within God. God is one “substance” but three “persons”: a plurality
without division. The Father, Son, and Spirit are distinct, but share equally
in the one Godhead. This threeness is manifest only in the “economy” of God’s
temporal action toward the world; later orthodoxy (e.g. Athanasius, Basil the
Great, Augustine), would postulate a Triunity that is eternal and “immanent,”
i.e., internal to God’s being.
MONTANISM, STOICISM,
TRINITARIANISM. A.E.L. testability, in the sciences, capacity of a theory to
undergo experimental testing. Theories in the natural sciences are regularly
subjected to experimental tests involving detailed and rigorous control of
variable factors. Not naive observation of the workings of nature, but
disciplined, designed intervention in such workings, is the hallmark of
testability. Logically regarded, testing takes the form of seeking confirmation
of theories by obtaining positive test results. We can represent a theory as a
conjunction of a hypothesis and a statement of initial conditions, (H • A).
This conjunction deductively entails testable or observational consequences O.
Hence, (H • A) P O. If O obtains, (H • A) is said to be confirmed, or rendered
probable. But such confirmation is not decisive; O may be entailed by, and
hence explained by, many other theories. For this reason, Popper insisted that
the testability of theories should seek disconfirmations or falsifications. The
logical schema (H • A) P O not-O not-(H • A) is deductively valid, hence
apparently decisive. On this view, science progresses, not by finding the
truth, but by discarding the false. Testability becomes falsifiability. This
deductive schema (modus tollens) is also employed in the analysis of crucial
tests. Consider two hypotheses H1 and H2, both introduced to explain some
phenomenon. H1 predicts that for some test condition C, we have the test result
‘if C then e1’, and H2, the result ‘if C then e2’, where e1 and e2 are
logically incompatible. If experiment falsifies ‘if C then e1’ (e1 does not
actually occur as a test result), the hypothesis H1 is false, which implies
that H2 is true. It was originally supposed that the experiments of J. B. L.
Foucault constituted a decisive falsification of the corpuscular theory of the
nature of light, and thus provided a decisive establishment of the truth of its
rival, the wave theory of light. This account of crucial experiments neglects
certain points in logic and also the role of auxiliary hypotheses in science.
As Duhem pointed term, minor testability 908
908 out, rarely, if ever, does a hypothesis face the facts in isolation
from other supporting assumptions. Furthermore, it is a fact of logic that the
falsification of a conjunction of a hypothesis and its auxiliary assumptions
and initial conditions (not-(H • A)) is logically equivalent to (not-H or
not-A), and the test result itself provides no warrant for choosing which
alternative to reject. Duhem further suggested that rejection of any component
part of a complex theory is based on extra-evidential considerations (factors
like simplicity and fruitfulness) and cannot be forced by negative test
results. Acceptance of Duhem’s view led Quine to suggest that a theory must
face the tribunal of experience en bloc; no single hypothesis can be tested in
isolation. Original conceptions of testability and falsifiability construed
scientific method as hypothetico-deductive. Difficulties with these
reconstructions of the logic of experiment have led philosophers of science to
favor an explication of empirical support based on the logic of
probability. CRUCIAL EXPERIMENT, DUHEM,
HYPOTHETICO-DEDUCTIVE METHOD, PROBABILITY. R.E.B.
testimony, an act of
telling, including all assertions apparently intended to impart information, regardless
of social setting. In an extended sense personal letters and messages, books,
and other published material purporting to contain factual information also
constitute testimony. Testimony may be sincere or insincere, and may express
knowledge or baseless prejudice. When it expresses knowledge, and it is rightly
believed, this knowledge is disseminated to its recipients, near or remote.
Secondhand knowledge can be passed on further, producing long chains of
testimony; but these chains always begin with the report of an eyewitness or
expert. In any social group with a common language there is potential for the
sharing, through testimony, of the fruits of individuals’ idiosyncratic
acquisition of knowledge through perception and inference. In advanced societies
specialization in the gathering and production of knowledge and its wider
dissemination through spoken and written testimony is a fundental
socioepistemic fact, and a very large part of each person’s body of knowledge
and belief stems from testimony. Thus the question when a person may properly
believe what another tells her, and what grounds her epistemic entitlement to
do so, is a crucial one in epistemology. Reductionists about testimony insist
that this entitlement must derive from our entitlement to believe what we
perceive to be so, and to draw inferences from this according to filiar general
principles. (See e.g., Hume’s classic discussion, in his Enquiry into Human
Understanding, section X.) On this view, I can perceive that someone has told
me that p, but can thereby come to know that p only by means of an inference –
one that goes via additional, empirically grounded knowledge of the
trustworthiness of that person. Anti-reductionists insist, by contrast, that
there is a general entitlement to believe what one is told just as such –
defeated by knowledge of one’s informant’s lack of trustworthiness (her
mendacity or incompetence), but not needing to be bolstered positively by
empirically based knowledge of her trustworthiness. Anti-reductionists thus see
testimony as an autonomous source of knowledge on a par with perception,
inference, and memory. One argument adduced for anti-reductionism is
transcendental: We have many beliefs acquired from testimony, and these beliefs
are knowledge; their status as knowledge cannot be accounted for in the way
required by the reductionist – that is, the reliability of testimony cannot be
independently confirmed; therefore the reductionist’s insistence on this is
mistaken. However, while it is perhaps true that the reliability of all the
beliefs one has that depend on past testimony cannot be simultaneously
confirmed, one can certainly sometimes ascertain, without circularity, that a
specific assertion by a particular person is likely to be correct – if, e.g.,one’s
own experience has established that that person has a good track record of
reliability about that kind of thing.
EPISTEMOLOGY, HUME, INFERENTIAL KNOWLEDGE. E.F. Tetens, Johann Nicolas
(1736–1807), German philosopher and psychologist, sometimes called the German
Locke. After his studies in Rostock and Copenhagen, he taught at Bützow and
Kiel (until 1789). He had a second successful career as a public servant in
Denmark (1790–1807) that did not leave him time for philosophical work. Tetens
was one of the most important German philosophers between Wolff and Kant. Like
Kant, whom he significantly influenced, Tetens attempted to find a middle way
between empiricism and rationalism. His most important work, the Philosophische
Versuche über die menschliche Natur und ihre Entwicklung (“Philosophical Essays
on Human Nature and its Development,” 1777), is indicative of the state of
philosophical discustestimony Tetens, Johann Nicolas 909 909 sion in Germany before Kant’s Critique
of Pure Reason. Tetens, who followed the “psychological method” of Locke,
tended toward a naturalism, like that of Hume. However, Tetens made a more
radical distinction between reason and sensation than Hume allowed and
attempted to show how basic rational principles guarantee the objectivity of
human knowledge. M.K. Tetractys.
PYTHAGORAS. Thales of
Miletus (fl. c.585 B.C.), Greek philosopher who was regarded as one of the
Seven Sages of Greece. He was also considered the first philosopher, founder of
the Milesians. Thales is also reputed to have been an engineer, astronomer,
mathematician, and statesman. His doctrines even early Greek sources know only
by hearsay: he said that water is the arche, and that the earth floats on water
like a raft. The magnet has a soul, and all things are full of the gods.
Thales’ attempt to explain natural phenomena in natural rather than exclusively
supernatural terms bore fruit in his follower Anaximander. PRE-SOCRATICS. D.W.G. thema (plural:
themata), in Stoic logic, a ground rule used to reduce argument forms to basic
forms. The Stoics analyzed arguments by their form (schema, or tropos). They
represented forms using numbers to represent claims; for exple, ‘if the first,
the second; but the first; therefore the second’. Some forms were
undemonstrable; others were reduced to the undemonstrable argument forms by
ground rules (themata); e.g., if R follows from P & Q, -Q follows from P
& -R. The five undemonstrable arguments are: (1) modus ponens; (2) modus
tollens; (3) not both (P and Q), P, so not-Q; (4) P or Q but not both, P, so
not-Q; and (5) disjunctive syllogism. The evidence about the four ground rules
is incomplete, but a sound and consistent system for propositional logic can be
developed that is consistent with the evidence we have. (See Diogenes Laertius,
Lives of the Philosophers, 776–81, for an introduction to the Stoic theory of
arguments; other evidence is more scattered.)
DOXOGRAPHERS, FORMAL LOGIC, LOGICAL FORM,
STOICISM. H.A.I. Themistius.COMMENTARIES ON ARISTOTLE. theodicy (from Greek theos,
‘God’, and dike, ‘justice’), a defense of the justice or goodness of God in the
face of doubts or objections arising from the phenomena of evil in the world
(‘evil’ refers here to bad states of affairs of any sort). Many types of
theodicy have been proposed and vigorously debated; only a few can be sketched
here. (1) It has been argued that evils are logically necessary for greater
goods (e.g., hardships for the full exemplification of certain virtues), so
that even an omnipotent being (roughly, one whose power has no logically
contingent limits) would have a morally sufficient reason to cause or permit
the evils in order to obtain the goods. Leibniz, in his Theodicy (1710),
proposed a particularly comprehensive theodicy of this type. On his view, God had
adequate reason to bring into existence the actual world, despite all its
evils, because it is the best of all possible worlds, and all actual evils are
essential ingredients in it, so that omitting any of them would spoil the
design of the whole. Aside from issues about whether actual evils are in fact
necessary for greater goods, this approach faces the question whether it
assumes wrongly that the end justifies the means. (2) An important type of
theodicy traces some or all evils to sinful free actions of humans or other
beings (such as angels) created by God. Proponents of this approach assume that
free action in creatures is of great value and is logically incompatible with
divine causal control of the creatures’ actions. It follows that God’s not intervening
to prevent sins is necessary, though the sins themselves are not, to the good
of created freedom. This is proposed as a morally sufficient reason for God’s
not preventing them. It is a major task for this type of theodicy to explain
why God would permit those evils that are not themselves free choices of
creatures but are at most consequences of such choices. (3) Another type of
theodicy, both ancient and currently influential ong theologians, though less
congenial to orthodox traditions in the major theistic religions, proposes to
defend God’s goodness by abandoning the doctrine that God is omnipotent. On
this view, God is causally, rather than logically, unable to prevent many evils
while pursuing sufficiently great goods. A principal sponsor of this approach
at present is the movement known as process theology, inspired by Whitehead; it
depends on a complex metaphysical theory about the nature of causal
relationships. (4) Other theodicies focus more on outcomes than on origins.
Some religious beliefs suggest that God will turn out to have been very good to
created persons by virtue of gifts (especially religious gifts, such as
communion with God as supreme Good) that may be bestowed in a life Tetractys
theodicy 910 910 after death or in
religious experience in the present life. This approach may be combined with
one of the other types of theodicy, or adopted by people who think that God’s
reasons for permitting evils are beyond our finding out.
DIVINE ATTRIBUTES, FREE
WILL PROBLEM, PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION, PROCESS THEOLOGY. R.M.A.
Theodorus.CYRENAICS. theologia naturalis (Latin, ‘natural theology’), theology
that uses the methods of investigation and standards of rationality of any
other area of philosophy. Traditionally, the central problems of natural
theology are proofs for the existence of God and the problem of evil. In
contrast with natural theology, supernatural theology uses methods that are
supposedly revealed by God and accepts as fact beliefs that are similarly
outside the realm of rational acceptability. Relying on a prophet or a pope to
settle factual questions would be acceptable to supernatural, but not to
natural, theology. Nothing prevents a natural theologian from analyzing
concepts that can be used sanguinely by supernatural theologians, e.g.,
revelation, miracles, infallibility, and the doctrine of the Trinity.
Theologians often work in both areas, as did, e.g., Anselm and Aquinas. For his
brilliant critiques of traditional theology, Hume deserves the title of
“natural anti-theologian.”
PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION.
A.P.M. theological creationism.PREEXISTENCE. theological naturalism, the
attempt to develop a naturalistic conception of God. As a philosophical
position, naturalism holds (1) that the only reliable methods of knowing what there
is are methods continuous with those of the developed sciences, and (2) that
the application of those methods supports the view that the constituents of
reality are either physical or are causally dependent on physical things and
their modifications. Since supernaturalism affirms that God is purely spiritual
and causally independent of physical things, naturalists hold that either
belief in God must be abandoned as rationally unsupported or the concept of God
must be reconstituted consistently with naturalism. Earlier attempts to do the
latter include the work of Feuerbach and Comte. In twentieth-century erican
naturalism the most significant attempts to develop a naturalistic conception
of God are due to Dewey and Henry Nelson Wieman (1884–1975). In A Common Faith
Dewey proposed a view of God as the unity of ideal ends resulting from human
imagination, ends arousing us to desire and action. Supernaturalism, he argued,
was the product of a primitive need to convert the objects of desire, the
greatest ideals, into an already existing reality. In contrast to Dewey, Wieman
insisted on viewing God as a process in the natural world that leads to the
best that humans can achieve if they but submit to its working in their lives.
In his earlier work he viewed God as a cosmic process that not only works for
human good but is what actually produced human life. Later he identified God
with creative interchange, a process that occurs only within already existing
human communities. While Wieman’s God is not a human creation, as are Dewey’s
ideal ends, it is difficult to see how love and devotion are appropriate to a
natural process that works as it does without thought or purpose. Thus, while
Dewey’s God (ideal ends) lacks creative power but may well qualify as an object
of love and devotion, Wieman’s God (a process in nature) is capable of creative
power but, while worthy of our care and attention, does not seem to qualify as
an object of love and devotion. Neither view, then, satisfies the two fundental
features associated with the traditional idea of God: possessing creative power
and being an appropriate object of supreme love and devotion.
theoretical reason, in
its traditional sense, a faculty or capacity whose province is theoretical
knowledge or inquiry; more broadly, the faculty concerned with ascertaining
truth of any kind (also sometimes called speculative reason). In Book 6 of his
Metaphysics, Aristotle identifies mathematics, physics, and theology as the
subject matter of theoretical reason. Theoretical reason is traditionally
distinguished from practical reason, a faculty exercised in determining guides
to good conduct and in deliberating about proper courses of action. Aristotle
contrasts it, as well, with productive reason, which is concerned with “making”:
shipbuilding, sculpting, healing, and the like. Kant distinguishes theoretical
reason not only from practical reason but also (sometimes) from the faculty of
understanding, in which the categories originate. Theoretical reason, possessed
of its own a priori concepts (“ideas of reason”), regulates the activities of
the understanding. It presupposes a systematic unity in nature, sets the goal
for scientific inquiry, and determines the “criterion of empirical truth”
(Critique of Pure Reason). Theoretical reason, on Kant’s conception, seeks an
explanatory “completeness” and an “unconditionedness” of being that transcend
what is possible in experience. Reason, as a faculty or capacity, may be
regarded as a hybrid composed of theoretical and practical reason (broadly
construed) or as a unity having both theoretical and practical functions. Some
commentators take Aristotle to embrace the former conception and Kant the
latter. Reason is contrasted sometimes with experience, sometimes with emotion
and desire, sometimes with faith. Its presence in human beings has often been
regarded as constituting the primary difference between human and non-human
animals; and reason is sometimes represented as a divine element in human
nature. Socrates, in Plato’s Philebus, portrays reason as “the king of heaven
and earth.” Hobbes, in his Leviathan, paints a more sobering picture,
contending that reason, “when we reckon it ong the faculties of the mind, . . .
is nothing but reckoning – that is, adding and subtracting – of the consequences
of general nes agreed upon for the marking and signifying of our
thoughts.”
PRACTICAL REASON,
RATIONALITY. A.R.M. theoretical reasoning.PRACTICAL REASONING. theoretical
term, a term occurring in a scientific theory that purports to make reference
to an unobservable entity (e.g., ‘electron’), property (e.g., ‘the monatomicity
of a molecule’), or relation (‘greater electrical resistance’). The
qualification ‘purports to’ is required because instrumentalists deny that any
such unobservables exist; nevertheless, they acknowledge that a scientific
theory, such as the atomic theory of matter, may be a useful tool for
organizing our knowledge of observables and predicting future experiences.
Scientific realists, in contrast, maintain that at least some of the
theoretical terms (e.g., ‘quark’ or ‘neutrino’) actually denote entities that
are not directly observable – they hold, i.e., that such things exist. For
either group, theoretical terms are contrasted with such observational terms as
‘rope’, ‘smooth’, and ‘louder than’, which refer to observable entities,
properties, or relations. Much philosophical controversy has centered on how to
draw the distinction between the observable and the unobservable. Did Galileo
observe the moons of Jupiter with his telescope? Do we observe bacteria under a
microscope? Do physicists observe electrons in bubble chbers? Do astronomers
observe the supernova explosions with neutrino counters? Do we observe ordinary
material objects, or are sense-data the only observables? Are there any
observational terms at all, or are all terms theory-laden? Another important
meaning of ‘theoretical term’ occurs if one regards a scientific theory as a
semiformal axiomatic system. It is then natural to think of its vocabulary as
divided into three parts, (i) terms of logic and mathematics, (ii) terms drawn
from ordinary language or from other theories, and (iii) theoretical terms that
constitute the special vocabulary of that particular theory. Thermodynics,
e.g., employs (i) terms for numbers and mathematical operations, (ii) such
terms as ‘pressure’ and ‘volume’ that are common to many branches of physics,
and (iii) such special thermodynical terms as ‘temperature’, ‘heat’, and
‘entropy’. In this second sense, a theoretical term need not even purport to
refer to unobservables. For exple, although special equipment is necessary for
its precise quantitatheoretical entity theoretical term 912 912 tive measurement, temperature is an
observable property. Even if theories are not regarded as axiomatic systems,
their technical terms can be considered theoretical. Such terms need not
purport to refer to unobservables, nor be the exclusive property of one
particular theory. In some cases, e.g., ‘work’ in physics, an ordinary word is
used in the theory with a meaning that departs significantly from its ordinary
use. Serious questions have been raised about the meaning of theoretical terms.
Some philosophers have insisted that, to be meaningful, they must be given
operational definitions. Others have appealed to coordinative definitions to
secure at least partial interpretation of axiomatic theories. The verifiability
criterion has been invoked to secure the meaningfulness of scientific theories
containing such terms. A theoretical concept (or construct) is a concept
expressed by a theoretical term in any of the foregoing senses. The term
‘theoretical entity’ has often been used to refer to unobservables, but this
usage is confusing, in part because, without introducing any special
vocabulary, we can talk about objects too small to be perceived directly –
e.g., spheres of gboge (a yellow resin) less than 10–6 meters in dieter, which
figured in a historically important experiment by Jean Perrin.
theory-laden, dependent
on theory; specifically, involving a theoretical interpretation of what is
perceived or recorded. In the heyday of logical empiricism it was thought, by
Carnap and others, that a rigid distinction could be drawn between
observational and theoretical terms. Later, N. R. Hanson, Paul Feyerabend, and
others questioned this distinction, arguing that perhaps all observations are
theory-laden either because our perception of the world is colored by
perceptual, linguistic, and cultural differences or because no attempt to
distinguish sharply between observation and theory has been successful. This
shift brings a host of philosophical problems. If we accept the idea of radical
theoryladenness, relativism of theory choice becomes possible, for, given rival
theories each of which conditions its own observational evidence, the choice
between them would seem to have to be made on extra-evidential grounds, since
no theory-neutral observations are available. In its most perplexing form,
relativism holds that, theory-ladenness being granted, one theory is as good as
any other, so far as the relationship of theory to evidence is concerned.
Relativists couple the thesis of theory-ladenness with the alleged fact of the
underdetermination of a theory by its observational evidence, which yields the
idea that any number of alternative theories can be supported by the se
evidence. The question becomes one of what it is that constrains choices
between theories. If theory-laden observations cannot constrain such choices,
the individual subjective preferences of scientists, or rules of fraternal
behavior agreed upon by groups of scientists, become the operative constraints.
The logic of confirmation seems to be intrinsically continated by both
idiosyncratic and social factors, posing a threat to the very idea of scientific
rationality.
theory of appearing, the theory that to
perceive an object is simply for that object to appear (present itself) to one
as being a certain way, e.g., looking round or like a rock, smelling vinegary,
sounding raucous, or tasting bitter. Nearly everyone would accept this
formulation on some interpretation. But the theory takes this to be a
rock-bottom characterization of perception, and not further analyzable. It
takes “appearing to subject S as so-and-so” as a basic, irreducible relation, one
readily identifiable in experience but not subject to definition in other
terms. The theory preserves the idea that in normal perception we are directly
aware of objects in the physical environment, not aware of them through
non-physical sense-data, sensory impressions, or other intermediaries. When a
tree looks to me a certain way, it is the tree and nothing else of which I directly aware. That involves “having” a
sensory experience, but that experience just consists of the tree’s looking a
certain way to me. After enjoying a certain currency early in this century the
theory was largely abandoned under the impact of criticisms by Price, Broad,
and Chisholm. The most widely advertised difficulty theoretical
underdetermination theory of appearing 913
913 is this. What is it that appears to the subject in completely
hallucinatory experience? Perhaps the greatest strength of the theory is its
fidelity to what perceptual experience seems to be.
theory of descriptions,
an analysis, initially developed by Peano and Russell, of sentences containing
descriptions. Descriptions include indefinite descriptions such as ‘an
elephant’ and definite descriptions such as ‘the positive square root of four’.
On Russell’s analysis, descriptions are “incomplete symbols” that are
meaningful only in the context of other symbols, i.e., only in the context of
the sentences containing them. Although the words ‘the first president of the
United States’ appear to constitute a singular term that picks out a particular
individual, much as the ne ‘George Washington’ does, Russell held that
descriptions are not referring expressions, and that they are “analyzed out” in
a proper specification of the logical form of the sentences in which they
occur. The grmatical form of ‘The first president of the United States is tall’
is simply misleading as to its logical form. According to Russell’s analysis of
indefinite descriptions, the sentence ‘I saw a man’ asserts that there is at
least one thing that is a man, and I saw that thing – symbolically, (Ex) (Mx
& Sx). The role of the apparent singular term ‘a man’ is taken over by the
existential quantifier ‘(Ex)’ and the variables it binds, and the apparent
singular term disappears on analysis. A sentence containing a definite
description, such as ‘The present king of France is bald’, is taken to make
three claims: that at least one thing is a present king of France, that at most
one thing is a present king of France, and that that thing is bald –
symbolically, (Ex) {[Fx & (y) (Fy / y % x)] & Bx}. Again, the apparent
referring expression ‘the present king of France’ is analyzed away, with its
role carried out by the quantifiers and variables in the symbolic
representation of the logical form of the sentence in which it occurs. No
element in that representation is a singular referring expression. Russell held
that this analysis solves at least three difficult puzzles posed by
descriptions. The first is how it could be true that George IV wished to know
whether Scott was the author of Waverly, but false that George IV wished to
know whether Scott was Scott. Since Scott is the author of Waverly, we should
apparently be able to substitute ‘Scott’ for ‘the author of Waverly’ and infer
the second sentence from the first, but we cannot. On Russell’s analysis,
‘George IV wished to know whether Scott was the author of Waverly’ does not,
when properly understood, contain an expression ‘the author of Waverly’ for
which the ne ‘Scott’ can be substituted. The second puzzle concerns the law of
excluded middle, which rules that either ‘The present king of France is bald’
or ‘The present king of France is not bald’ must be true; the problem is that
neither the list of bald men nor that of non-bald men contains an entry for the
present king of France. Russell’s solution is that ‘The present king of France
is not bald’ is indeed true if it is understood as ‘It is not the case that
there is exactly one thing that is now King of France and is bald’, i.e., as
-(Ex) {Fx & (y) {[Fy / y % x)] & Bx}. The final puzzle is how ‘There is
no present king of France’ or ‘The present king of France does not exist’ can
be true – if ‘the present king of France’ is a referring expression that picks
out something, how can we truly deny that that thing exists? Since descriptions
are not referring expressions on Russell’s theory, it is easy for him to show
that the negation of the claim that there is at least and at most (i.e.,
exactly) one present king of France, -(Ex) [Fx & (y) (Fy / y % x)], is
true. Strawson offered the first real challenge to Russell’s theory, arguing
that ‘The present king of France is bald’ does not entail but instead
presupposes ‘There is a present king of France’, so that the former is not
falsified by the falsity of the latter, but is instead deprived of a truth-value.
Strawson argued for the natural view that definite descriptions are indeed
referring expressions, used to single something out for predication. More
recently, Keith Donnellan argued that both Russell and Strawson ignored the
fact that definite descriptions have two uses. Used attributively, a definite
description is intended to say something about whatever it is true of, and when
a sentence is so used it conforms to Russell’s analysis. Used referentially, a
definite description is intended to single something out, but may not correctly
describe it. For exple, seeing an inebriated man in a policeman’s uniform, one
might say, “The cop on the corner is drunk!” Donnellan would say that even if
the person were a drunken actor dressed as a policeman, the speaker would have
referred to him and truly said of him that he was drunk. If it is for some
reason crucial that the description be correct, as it might be if one said,
“The cop on the corner has the authority to issue speeding tickets,” the use is
attributive; and because ‘the cop on the corner’ does not describe anyone
correctly, no one has been said to have the authority to issue speeding
tickets. Donnellan criticized Russell for overlooking referential uses of
theory of descriptions theory of descriptions 914 914 descriptions, and Strawson for both
failing to acknowledge attributive uses and maintaining that with referential
uses one can refer to something with a definite description only if the
description is true of it. Discussion of Strawson’s and Donnellan’s criticisms
is ongoing, and has provoked very useful work in both semantics and speech act
theory, and on the distinctions between semantics and pragmatics and between
semantic reference and speaker’s reference, ong others.
CAUSAL THEORY OF PROPER
NES, PRESUPPOSITION, RUSSELL. R.B. theory of effluxes.DEMOCRITUS. theory of
Forms.PLATO. theory of frequency.PROBABILITY. theory of relativity.RELATIVITY.
theory of signs, the philosophical and scientific theory of
information-carrying entities, communication, and information transmission. The
term ‘semiotic’ was introduced by Locke for the science of signs and
signification. The term bece more widely used as a result of the influential
work of Peirce and Charles Morris. With regard to linguistic signs, three areas
of semiotic were distinguished: pragmatics – the study of the way people,
animals, or machines such as computers use signs; semantics – the study of the
relations between signs and their meanings, abstracting from their use; and
syntax – the study of the relations ong signs themselves, abstracting both from
use and from meaning. In Europe, the near-equivalent term ‘semiology’ was
introduced by Ferdinand de Saussure, the Swiss linguist. Broadly, a sign is any
information-carrying entity, including linguistic and animal signaling tokens,
maps, road signs, diagrs, pictures, models, etc. Exples include smoke as a sign
of fire, and a red light at a highway intersection as a sign to stop.
Linguistically, vocal aspects of speech such as prosodic features (intonation,
stress) and paralinguistic features (loudness and tone, gestures, facial
expressions, etc.), as well as words and sentences, are signs in the most
general sense. Peirce defined a sign as “something that stands for something in
some respect or capacity.” ong signs, he distinguished symbols, icons, and
indices. A symbol, or conventional sign, is a sign, typical of natural language
forms, that lacks any significant relevant physical correspondence with or
resemblance to the entities to which the form refers (manifested by the fact
that quite different forms may refer to the se class of objects), and for which
there is no correlation between the occurrence of the sign and its referent. An
index, or natural sign, is a sign whose occurrence is causally or statistically
correlated with occurrences of its referent, and whose production is not
intentional. Thus, yawning is a natural sign of sleepiness; a bird call may be
a natural sign of alarm. Linguistically, loudness with a rising pitch is a sign
of anger. An icon is a sign whose form corresponds to or resembles its referent
or a characteristic of its referent. For instance, a tailor’s swatch is an icon
by being a sign that resembles a fabric in color, pattern, and texture. A
linguistic exple is onomatopoeia – as with ‘buzz’. In general, there are
conventional and cultural aspects to a sign being an icon.
GRMAR, MEANING,
PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE, SEMIOSIS. W.K.W. theory of types.TYPE THEORY. theory
theory.SIMULATION THEORY. theosophy, any philosophical mysticism, especially
those that purport to be mathematically or scientifically based, such as
Pythagoreanism, Neoplatonism, or gnosticism. Vedic Hinduism, and certain
aspects of Buddhism, Taoism, and Islic Sufism, can also be considered
theosophical. In narrower senses, ‘theosophy’ may refer to the philosophy of
Swedenborg, Steiner, or Made Helena Petrovna Blavatsky (1831–91). Swedenborg’s
theosophy originally consisted of a rationalistic cosmology, inspired by
certain elements of Cartesian and Leibnizian philosophy, and a Christian
mysticism. Swedenborg labored to explain the interconnections between soul and
body. Steiner’s theosophy is a reaction to standard scientific theory. It
purports to be as rigorous as ordinary science, but superior to it by incorporating
spiritual truths about reality. According to his theosophy, reality is organic
and evolving by its own resource. Genuine knowledge is intuitive, not
discursive. Made Blavatsky founded the Theosophical Society in 1875. Her views
were eclectic, but were strongly influenced by mystical elements of Indian
philosophy. MYSTICISM, STEINER,
SWEDENBORGIANISM. A.P.M. theory of effluxes theosophy 915 915 Theravada Buddhism.BUDDHISM.
thermodynics, first law of.ENTROPY. thermodynics, second law of.ENTROPY. thesis.HEGEL.
theurgy.NEOPLATONISM. thing.METAPHYSICS. thing-in-itself.KANT. Third Man
argument.PLATO. thirdness.PEIRCE. thisness.HAECCEITY. Thomas Aquinas.AQUINAS.
Thomism, the theology and
philosophy of Thomas Aquinas. The term is applied broadly to various thinkers
from different periods who were heavily influenced by Aquinas’s thought in
their own philosophizing and theologizing. Here three different eras and three
different groups of thinkers will be distinguished: those who supported
Aquinas’s thought in the fifty years or so following his death in 1274; certain
highly skilled interpreters and commentators who flourished during the period
of “Second Thomism” (sixteenth–seventeenth centuries); and various late
nineteenth- and twentieth-century thinkers who have been deeply influenced in
their own work by Aquinas. Thirteenth- and fourteenth-century Thomism. Although
Aquinas’s genius was recognized by many during his own lifetime, a number of
his views were immediately contested by other Scholastic thinkers. Controversies
ranged, e.g., over his defense of only one substantial form in human beings;
his claim that prime matter is purely potential and cannot, therefore, be kept
in existence without some substantial form, even by divine power; his emphasis
on the role of the human intellect in the act of choice; his espousal of a real
distinction betweeen the soul and its powers; and his defense of some kind of
objective or “real” rather than a merely mind-dependent composition of essence
and act of existing (esse) in creatures. Some of Aquinas’s positions were
included directly or indirectly in the 219 propositions condemned by Bishop
Stephen Tempier of Paris in 1277, and his defense of one single substantial
form in man was condemned by Archbishop Robert Kilwardby at Oxford in 1277,
with renewed prohibitions by his successor as archbishop of Canterbury, John
Peckh, in 1284 and 1286. Only after Aquinas’s canonization in 1323 were the
Paris prohibitions revoked insofar as they touched on his teaching (in 1325).
Even within his own Dominican order, disagreement about some of his views
developed within the first decades after his death, notwithstanding the order’s
highly sympathetic espousal of his cause. Early English Dominican defenders of
his general views included Willi Hothum (d.1298), Richard Knapwell (d.c.1288),
Robert Orford (b. after 1250, fl.1290–95), Thomas Sutton (d. c.1315?), and
Willi Macclesfield (d.1303). French Dominican Thomists included Bernard of
Trilia (d.1292), Giles of Lessines in present-day Belgium (d.c.1304?), John
Quidort of Paris (d. 1306), Bernard of Auvergne (d. after 1307), Hervé Nédélec
(d.1323), Armand of Bellevue (fl. 1316–34), and Willi Peter Godin (d.1336). The
secular master at Paris, Peter of Auvergne (d. 1304), while remaining very independent
in his own views, knew Aquinas’s thought well and completed some of his
commentaries on Aristotle. Sixteenth- and seventeenth-century Thomism.
Sometimes known as the period of Second Thomism, this revival gained impetus
from the early fifteenth-century writer John Capreolus (1380–1444) in his
Defenses of Thomas’s Theology (Defensiones theologiae Divi Thomae), a
commentary on the Sentences. A number of fifteenth-century Dominican and
secular teachers in German universities also contributed: Kaspar Grunwald
(Freiburg); Cornelius Sneek and John Stoppe (in Rostock); Leonard of Brixental
(Vienna); Gerard of Heerenberg, Lbert of Heerenberg, and John Versor (all at
Cologne); Gerhard of Elten; and in Belgium Denis the Carthusian. Outstanding
ong various sixteenth-century commentators on Thomas were Tommaso de Vio
(Cardinal) Cajetan, Francis Sylvester of Ferrara, Francisco de Vitoria
(Salanca), and Francisco’s disciples Domingo de Soto and Melchior Cano. Most
important ong early seventeenth-century Thomists was John of St. Thomas, who
lectured at Piacenza, Madrid, and Alcalá, and is best known for his Cursus
philosophicus and his Cursus theologicus. Theravada Buddhism Thomism 916 916 The nineteenth- and twentieth-century
revival. By the early to mid-nineteenth century the study of Aquinas had been
largely abandoned outside Dominican circles, and in most Roman Catholic
colleges and seminaries a kind of Cartesian and Suarezian Scholasticism was
taught. Long before he bece Pope Leo XIII, Joachim Pecci and his brother Joseph
had taken steps to introduce the teaching of Thomistic philosophy at the
diocesan seminary at Perugia in 1846. Earlier efforts in this direction had
been made by Vincenzo Buzzetti (1778–1824), by Buzzetti’s students Serafino and
Domenico Sordi, and by Taparelli d’Aglezio, who bece director of the Collegio
Romano (Gregorian University) in 1824. Leo’s encyclical Aeterni Patris(1879)
marked an official effort on the part of the Roman Catholic church to foster
the study of the philosophy and theology of Thomas Aquinas. The intent was to
draw upon Aquinas’s original writings in order to prepare students of
philosophy and theology to deal with problems raised by contemporary thought.
The Leonine Commission was established to publish a critical edition of all of
Aquinas’s writings; this effort continues today. Important centers of Thomistic
studies developed, such as the Higher Institute of Philosophy at Louvain
(founded by Cardinal Mercier), the Dominican School of Saulchoir in France, and
the Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies in Toronto. Different groups of
Roman, Belgian, and French Jesuits acknowledged a deep indebtedness to Aquinas
for their personal philosophical reflections. There was also a concentration of
effort in the United States at universities such as The Catholic University of
erica, St. Louis University, Notre De, Fordh, Marquette, and Boston College, to
mention but a few, and by the Dominicans at River Forest. A great weakness of
many of the nineteenthand twentieth-century Latin manuals produced during this
effort was a lack of historical sensitivity and expertise, which resulted in an
unreal and highly abstract presentation of an “Aristotelian-Thomistic”
philosophy. This weakness was largely offset by the development of solid historical
research both in the thought of Aquinas and in medieval philosophy and theology
in general, chpioned by scholars such as H. Denifle, M. De Wulf, M. Grabmann,
P. Mandonnet, F. Van Steenberghen, E. Gilson and many of his students at
Toronto, and by a host of more recent and contemporary scholars. Much of this
historical work continues today both within and without Catholic scholarly
circles. At the se time, remarkable diversity in interpreting Aquinas’s thought
has emerged on the part of many twentieth-century scholars. Witness, e.g., the
heavy influence of Cajetan and John of St. Thomas on the Thomism of Maritain;
the much more historically grounded approaches developed in quite different
ways by Gilson and F. Van Steenberghen; the emphasis on the metaphysics of
participation in Aquinas in the very different presentations by L. Geiger and
C. Fabro; the emphasis on existence (esse) promoted by Gilson and many others
but resisted by still other interpreters; the movement known as Transcendental
Thomism, originally inspired by P. Rousselot and by J. Marechal (in dialogue
with Kant); and the long controversy about the appropriateness of describing
Thomas’s philosophy (and that of other medievals) as a Christian philosophy. An
increasing number of non-Catholic thinkers are currently directing considerable
attention to Aquinas, and the varying backgrounds they bring to his texts will
undoubtedly result in still other interesting interpretations and applications
of his thought to contemporary concerns.
AQUINAS,
GILSON, JOHN OF SAINT
THOMAS, MARITAIN, NEO-THOMISM. J.F.W. Thomson, Judith Jarvis (b.1929), erican
analytic philosopher best known for her contribution to moral philosophy and
for her paper “A Defense of Abortion” (1971). Thomson has taught at M.I.T.
since 1964. Her work is centrally concerned with issues in moral philosophy,
most notably questions regarding rights, and with issues in metaphysics such as
the identity across time of people and the ontology of events. Her Acts and
Other Events (1977) is a study of human action and provides an analysis of the
part– whole relation ong events. “A Defense of Abortion” has not only
influenced much later work on this topic but is one of the most widely
discussed papers in contemporary philosophy. By appeal to imaginative scenarios
analogous to pregnancy, Thomson argues that even if the fetus is assumed to be
a person, its rights are in many circumstances outweighed by the rights of the
pregnant woman. Thus the paper advances an argument for a right to abortion
that does not turn upon the question of whether the fetus is a person. Several
of Thomson’s essays, including “Preferential Hiring” (1973), “The Right to
Privacy” (1975), and “Killing, Letting Die, and the Trolley Problem” (1976),
address the questions of what constitutes Thomson, Judith Jarvis Thomson,
Judith Jarvis 917 917 an infringement
of rights and when it is morally permissible to infringe a right. These are
collected in Rights, Restitution, and Risk: Essays in Moral Theory (1986).
Thomson’s The Realm of Rights (1990) offers a systematic account of human
rights, addressing first what it is to have a right and second which rights we
have. Thomson’s work is distinguished by its exceptionally lucid style and its
reliance on highly inventive exples. The centrality of exples to her work
reflects a methodological conviction that our views about actual and imagined
cases provide the data for moral theorizing.
ACTION THEORY, ETHICS, RIGHTS. A.E.B.
Thoreau, Henry David
(1817–62), erican naturalist and writer. Born in Concord, Massachusetts, he
attended Harvard (1833–37) and then returned to Concord to study nature and
write, making a frugal living as a schoolteacher, land surveyor, and pencil
maker. Commentators have emphasized three aspects of his life: his love and
penetrating study of the flora and fauna of the Concord area, recorded with
philosophical reflections in Walden (1854); his continuous pursuit of
simplicity in the externals of life, thus avoiding a life of “quiet
desperation”; and his acts of civil disobedience. The last item has been
somewhat overemphasized; not paying a poll tax by way of protest was not
original with Thoreau. However, his essay “Resistance to Civil Government”
immortalized his protest and influenced people like Gandhi and Martin Luther
King, Jr., in later years. Thoreau eventually helped runaway slaves at
considerable risk; still, he considered himself a student of nature and not a
reformer.
TRANSCENDENTALISM. E.H.M.
thought, language of.MEANING, MENTALESE, PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE. thought
experiment, a technique for testing a hypothesis by imagining a situation and
what would be said about it (or more rarely, happen in it). This technique is
often used by philosophers to argue for (or against) a hypothesis about the
meaning or applicability of a concept. For exple, Locke imagined a switch of
minds between a prince and a cobbler as a way to argue that personal identity
is based on continuity of memory, not continuity of the body. To argue for the
relativity of simultaneity, Einstein imagined two observers – one on a train,
the other beside it – who observed lightning bolts. And according to some
scholars, Galileo only imagined the experiment of tying two five-pound weights
together with a fine string in order to argue that heavier bodies do not fall
faster. Thought experiments of this last type are rare because they can be used
only when one is thoroughly filiar with the outcome of the imagined situation.
J.A.K. Thrasymachus (fl. 427 B.C.), Greek Sophist from Bithynia who is known
mainly as a character in Book I of Plato’s Republic. He traveled and taught
extensively throughout the Greek world, and was well known in Athens as a
teacher and as the author of treatises on rhetoric. Innovative in his style, he
was credited with inventing the “middle style” of rhetoric. The only surviving
fragment of a speech by Thrasymachus was written for delivery by an Athenian
citizen in the assembly, at a time when Athens was not faring well in the
Peloponnesian War; it shows him concerned with the efficiency of government,
pleading with the Athenians to recognize their common interests and give up
their factionalism. Our only other source for his views on political matters is
Plato’s Republic, which most scholars accept as presenting at least a half-truth
about Thrasymachus. There, Thrasymachus is represented as a foil to Socrates,
claiming that justice is only what benefits the stronger, i.e., the rulers.
From the point of view of those who are ruled, then, justice always serves the
interest of someone else, and rulers who seek their own advantage are
unjust.
three-valued
logic.MANY-VALUED LOGIC. Three Ways.BONAVENTURE. threshold, absolute.FECHNER.
threshold, relative.FECHNER. t’i, yung, Chinese terms often rendered into
English as ‘substance’ and ‘function’, respectively. Ch’eng Yi (1033–1107), in
the preface to his Commentary to the Book of Changes, says: “Substance (t’i)
and function (yung) come from the se source, and there is no gap between the
manifest and the hidden.” Such thought is characteristic of the Chinese way of
thinking. Chu Hsi (1130–1200) applied the pair of concepts to his theory of
human nature; he maintained that jen (humanity) is nature, substance, while
love is Thoreau, Henry David t’i, yung 918
918 feeling, function. In the late Ch’ing dynasty (1644–1912) Chang
Chih-tung (1837–1909) advocated Chinese learning for t’i and Western learning
for yung. CHINESE PHILOSOPHY, CHU HSI.
S.-h.L. t’ien, Chinese term meaning ‘heaven’, ‘sky’. T’ien has a range of uses
running from the most to the least anthropomorphic. At one extreme, t’ien is
identified with shang ti. T’ien can be spoken of as having desires and engaging
in purposive actions, such as bestowing the Mandate of Heaven (t’ien ming).
T’ien ming has a political and an ethical use. It can be the mandate to rule
given to a virtuous individual. It can also be the moral requirements that
apply to each individual, especially as these are embodied in one’s nature. At
the other extreme, thinkers such as Hsün-Tzu identify t’ien with the natural
order. Even in texts where t’ien is sometimes used anthropomorphically, it can
also be used as synonymous with ming (in the sense of fate), or simply refer to
the sky. After the introduction of Buddhism into China, the phrase ‘Hall of
Heaven’ (t’ien t’ang) is used to refer to the paradise awaiting some souls
after death.
CHUNG-YUNG, HSING, MING, SHANG TI. B.W.V.N.
t’ien-jen ho-i, Chinese term for the relationship between t’ien (Heaven) and
human beings. Most ancient Chinese philosophers agreed on the ideal t’ien-jen
ho-i: the unity and harmony of Heaven or the natural order of events and human
affairs. They differed on the means of achieving this ideal vision. The
Taoists, Lao Tzu and Chuang Tzu, focused on adaptability to all natural
occurrences without human intervention. The Confucians stressed the cultivation
of virtues such as jen (benevolence), i (rightness), and li (propriety), both
in the rulers and the people. Some later Confucians, along with Mo Tzu,
emphasized the mutual influence and response or interaction of Heaven and
humans. Perhaps the most distinctive Confucian conception is Hsün Tzu’s thesis
that Heaven provides resources for completion by human efforts. A.S.C. t’ien
li, jen-yü, Chinese terms literally meaning ‘heavenly principles’ and ‘human
desires’, respectively. Sung–Ming Neo-Confucian philosophers believed that
Heaven enables us to understand principles and to act according to them.
Therefore we must try our best to preserve heavenly principles and eliminate
human desires. When hungry, one must eat; this is acting according to t’ien li.
But when one craves gourmet food, the only thing one cares about is
gratification of desire; this is jen-yü. Neo-Confucian philosophers were not
teaching asceticism; they only urged us not to be slaves of our excessive,
unnatural, artificial, “human” desires.
t’ien ming.MING. Tillers.HSü HSING. Tillich,
Paul (1886–1965), German-born erican philosopher and theologian. Born in
Starzeddel, eastern Germany, he was educated in philosophy and theology and
ordained in the Prussian Evangelical Church in 1912. He served as an army
chaplain during World War I and later taught at Berlin, Marburg, Dresden,
Leipzig, and Frankfurt. In November 1933, following suspension from his
teaching post by the Nazis, he emigrated to the United States, where he taught
at Columbia and Union Theological Seminary until 1955, and then at Harvard and
Chicago until his death. A popular preacher and speaker, he developed a wide
audience in the United States through such writings as The Protestant Era
(1948), Systematic Theology (three volumes: 1951, 1957, 1963), The Courage to
Be (1952), and Dynics of Faith (1957). His sometimes unconventional lifestyle,
as well as his syncretic yet original thought, moved “on the boundary” between
theology and other elements of culture – especially art, literature, political
thought, and depth psychology – in the belief that religion should relate to
the whole extent, and the very depths, of human existence. Tillich’s thought,
despite its distinctive “ontological” vocabulary, was greatly influenced by the
voluntaristic tradition from Augustine through Schelling, Schopenhauer, Marx,
Nietzsche, and Freud. It was a systematic theology that sought to state fresh
Christian answers to deep existential questions raised by individuals and
cultures – his method of correlation. Every age has its distinctive kairos,
“crisis” or “fullness of time,” the right time for creative thought and action.
In Weimar Germany, Tillich found the times ripe for religious socialism. In
post–World War II erica, he focused more on psychological themes: in the midst
of anxiety over death, meaninglessness, and guilt, everyone seeks the courage
to be, which comes only by avoiding the abyss of non-being (welling up in the
demonic) and by placing one’s unconditional faith – ultit’ien Tillich, Paul
919 919 mate concern – not in any
particular being (e.g. God) but in Being-Itself (“the God above God,” the
ground of being). This is essentially the Protestant principle, which prohibits
lodging ultimate concern in any finite and limited reality (including state,
race, and religious institutions and symbols). Tillich was especially
influential after World War II. He represented for many a welcome critical
openness to the spiritual depths of modern culture, opposing both demonic
idolatry of this world (as in National Socialism) and sectarian denial of
cultural resources for faith (as in Barthian neo-orthodoxy).
time, “a moving image of
eternity” (Plato); “the number of movements in respect of the before and after”
(Aristotle); “the Life of the Soul in movement as it passes from one stage of
act or experience to another” (Plotinus); “a present of things past, memory, a
present of things present, sight, and a present of things future, expectation”
(Augustine). These definitions, like all attempts to encapsulate the essence of
time in some neat formula, are unhelpfully circular because they employ
temporal notions. Although time might be too basic to admit of definition,
there still are many questions about time that philosophers have made some
progress in answering by analysis both of how we ordinarily experience and talk
about time, and of the deliverances of science, thereby clarifying and
deepening our understanding of what time is. What follows gives a sple of some
of the more important of these issues. Temporal becoming and the A- and
B-theories of time. According to the B-theory, time consists in nothing but a
fixed “B-series” of events running from earlier to later. The A-theory requires
that these events also form an “A-series” going from the future through the
present into the past and, moreover, shift in respect to these determinations.
The latter sort of change, commonly referred to as “temporal becoming,” gives
rise to well-known perplexities concerning both what does the shifting and the
sort of shift involved. Often it is said that it is the present or now that
shifts to ever-later times. This quickly leads to absurdity. ‘The present’ and
‘now’, like ‘this time’, are used to refer to a moment of time. Thus, to say
that the present shifts to later times entails that this very moment of time –
the present – will become some other moment of time and thus cease to be
identical with itself! Sometimes the entity that shifts is the property of
nowness or presentness. The problem is that every event has this property at
some time, nely when it occurs. Thus, what must qualify some event as being now
simpliciter is its having the property of nowness now; and this is the start of
an infinite regress that is vicious because at each stage we are left with an
unexpurgated use of ‘now’, the very term that was supposed to be analyzed in
terms of the property of nowness. If events are to change from being future to
present and from present to past, as is required by temporal becoming, they
must do so in relation to some mysterious transcendent entity, since temporal
relations between events and/or times cannot change. The nature of the shift is
equally perplexing, for it must occur at a particular rate; but a rate of
change involves a comparison between one kind of change and a change of time.
Herein, it is change of time that is compared to change of time, resulting in
the seeming tautology that time passes or shifts at the rate of one second per
second, surely an absurdity since this is not a rate of change at all. Broad
attempted to skirt these perplexities by saying that becoming is sui generis
and thereby defies analysis, which puts him on the side of the mystically
inclined Bergson who thought that it could be known only through an act of
ineffable intuition. To escape the clutches of both perplexity and mysticism,
as well as to satisfy the demand of science to view the world
non-perspectivally, the B-theory attempted to reduce the A-series to the B-series
via a linguistic reduction in which a temporal indexical proposition reporting
an event as past, present, or future is shown to be identical with a
non-indexical proposition reporting a relation of precedence or simultaneity
between it and another event or time. It is generally conceded that such a
reduction fails, since, in general, no indexical proposition is identical with
any non-indexical one, this being due to the fact that one can have a
propositional attitude toward one of them that is not had to the other; e.g., I
can believe that it is now raining without believing that it rains
(tenselessly) at t 7. The friends of becoming have drawn the wrong moral from
this failure – that there is a mysterious Mr. X out there doing “The Shift.”
They have overlooked the fact that two sentences can express different
propositions and yet report one and the se event or state of affairs; e.g.,
‘This time time 920 920 is water’ and
‘this is a collection of H2O molecules’, though differing in sense, report the
se state of affairs – this being water is nothing but this being a collection
of H2O molecules. It could be claimed that the se holds for the appropriate use
of indexical and non-indexical sentences; the tokening at t 7 of ‘Georgie flies
at this time (at present)’ is coreporting with the non-synonymous ‘Georgie
flies (tenselessly) at t 7’, since Georgie’s flying at this time is the se
event as Georgie’s flying at t 7, given that this time is t 7. This effects the
se ontological reduction of the becoming of events to their bearing temporal
relations to each other as does the linguistic reduction. The “coreporting
reduction” also shows the absurdity of the “psychological reduction” according
to which an event’s being present, etc., requires a relation to a perceiver,
whereas an event’s having a temporal relation to another event or time does not
require a relation to a perceiver. Given that Georgie’s flying at this time is
identical with Georgie’s flying at t 7, it follows that one and the se event
both does and does not have the property of requiring relation to a perceiver,
thereby violating Leibniz’s law that identicals are indiscernible. Continuous
versus discrete time. Assume that the instants of time are linearly ordered by
the relation R of ‘earlier than’. To say that this order is continuous is,
first, to imply the property of density or infinite divisibility: for any
instants i 1 and i 2 such that Ri1i 2, there is a third instant i 3, such that
Ri1i 3 and Ri3i 2. But continuity implies something more since density allows
for “gaps” between the instants, as with the rational numbers. (Think of R as
the ‘less than’ relation and the i n as rationals.) To rule out gaps and
thereby assure genuine continuity it is necessary to require in addition to
density that every convergent sequence of instants has a limit. To make this
precise one needs a distance measure d( , ) on pairs of instants, where d(i m,
i n) is interpreted as the lapse of time between i m and i n. The requirement
of continuity proper is then that for any sequence i l , i 2, i 3, . . . , of
instants, if d(i m i n) P 0 as m, n P C, there is a limit instant i ø such that
d(i n, iø ) P 0 as n P C. The analogous property obviously fails for the
rationals. But taking the completion of the rationals by adding in the limit
points of convergent sequences yields the real number line, a genuine
continuum. Numerous objections have been raised to the idea of time as a
continuum and to the very notion of the continuum itself. Thus, it was objected
that time cannot be composed of durationless instants since a stack of such
instants cannot produce a non-zero duration. Modern measure theory resolves
this objection. Leibniz held that a continuum cannot be composed of points
since the points in any (finite closed) interval can be put in one-to-one
correspondence with a smaller subinterval, contradicting the axiom that the
whole is greater than any proper part. What Leibniz took to be a contradictory
feature is now taken to be a defining feature of infinite collections or
totalities. Modern-day Zenoians, while granting the viability of the
mathematical doctrine of the continuum and even the usefulness of its
employment in physical theory, will deny the possibility of its applying to
real-life changes. Whitehead gave an analogue of Zeno’s paradox of the
dichotomy to show that a thing cannot endure in a continuous manner. For if (i
1, i 2) is the interval over which the thing is supposed to endure, then the
thing would first have to endure until the instant i 3, halfway between i 1 and
i 2; but before it can endure until i 3, it must first endure until the instant
i 4 halfway between i 1 and i 3, etc. The seductiveness of this paradox rests
upon an implicit anthropomorphic demand that the operations of nature must be
understood in terms of concepts of human agency. Herein it is the demand that
the physicist’s description of a continuous change, such as a runner traversing
a unit spatial distance by performing an infinity of runs of ever-decreasing
distance, could be used as an action-guiding recipe for performing this feat,
which, of course, is impossible since it does not specify any initial or final
doing, as recipes that guide human actions must. But to make this
anthropomorphic demand explicit renders this deployment of the dichotomy, as
well as the arguments against the possibility of performing a “supertask,”
dubious. Anti-realists might deny that we are committed to real-life change
being continuous by our acceptance of a physical theory that employs principles
of mathematical continuity, but this is quite different from the Zenoian claim
that it is impossible for such change to be continuous. To maintain that time
is discrete would require not only abandoning the continuum but also the
density property as well. Giving up either conflicts with the intuition that
time is one-dimensional. (For an explanation of how the topological analysis of
dimensionality entails that the dimension of a discrete space is 0, see W.
Hurewicz, Dimension Theory, 1941.) The philotime time 921 921 sophical and physics literatures contain
speculations about a discrete time built of “chronons” or temporal atoms, but
thus far such hypothetical entities have not been incorporated into a
satisfactory theory. Absolute versus relative and relational time. In a
scholium to the Principia, Newton declared that “Absolute, true and
mathematical time, of itself and from its own nature, flows equably without
relation to anything external.” There are at least five interrelated senses in
which time was absolute for Newton. First, he thought that there was a
fre-independent relation of simultaneity for events. Second, he thought that
there was a fre-independent measure of duration for non-simultaneous events. He
used ‘flows equably’ not to refer to the above sort of mysterious “temporal
becoming,” but instead to connote the second sense of absoluteness and partly
to indicate two further kinds of absoluteness. To appreciate the latter, note
that ‘flows equably’ is modified by ‘without relation to anything external’.
Here Newton was asserting (third sense of ‘absolute’) that the lapse of time
between two events would be what it is even if the distribution and motions of
material bodies were different. He was also presupposing a related form of
absoluteness (fourth sense) according to which the metric of time is intrinsic
to the temporal interval. Leibniz’s philosophy of time placed him in agreement
with Newton as regards the first two senses of ‘absolute’, which assert the
non-relative or fre-independent nature of time. However, Leibniz was very much
opposed to Newton on the fourth sense of ‘absolute’. According to Leibniz’s
relational conception of time, any talk about the length of a temporal interval
must be unpacked in terms of talk about the relation of the interval to an
extrinsic metric standard. Furthermore, Leibniz used his principles of
sufficient reason and identity of indiscernibles to argue against a fifth sense
of ‘absolute’, implicit in Newton’s philosophy of time, according to which time
is a substratum in which physical events are situated. On the contrary, the
relational view holds that time is nothing over and above the structure of
relations of events. Einstein’s special and general theories of relativity have
direct bearing on parts of these controversies. The special theory necessitates
the abandonment of fre-independent notions of simultaneity and duration. For
any pair of spacelike related events in Minkowski space-time there is an
inertial fre in which the events are simultaneous, another fre in which the
first event is temporally prior, and still a third in which the second event is
temporally prior. And the temporal interval between two timelike related events
depends on the worldline connecting them. In fact, for any e ( 0, no matter how
small, there is a worldline connecting the events whose proper length is less
than e. (This is the essence of the so-called twin paradox.) The general theory
of relativity abandons the third sense of absoluteness since it entails that
the metrical structure of space-time covaries with the distribution of
mass-energy in a manner specified by Einstein’s field equations. But the heart
of the absolute–relational controversy – as focused by the fourth and fifth
senses of ‘absolute’ – is not settled by relativistic considerations. Indeed,
opponents from both sides of the debate claim to find support for their
positions in the special and general theories.
time slice, a temporal
part or stage of any concrete particular that exists for some interval of time;
a three-dimensional cross section of a fourdimensional object. To think of an
object as consisting of time slices or temporal stages is to think of it as
related to time in much the way that it is related to space: as extending
through time as well as space, rather than as enduring through it. Just as an
object made up of spatial parts is thought of as a whole made up of parts that
exist at different locations, so an object made up of time slices is thought of
as a whole made up of parts or stages that exist at successive times; hence,
just as a spatial whole is only partly present in any space that does not
include all its spatial parts, so a whole made up of time slices is only partly
present in any stretch of time that does not include all its temporal parts. A
continuant, by contrast, is most commonly understood to be a particular that
endures through time, i.e., that is wholly present at each moment at which it
exists. To conceive of an object as a continuant is to conceive of it as
related to time in a very different way from that in which it is related to
space. A continuant does not extend through time as well as space; it does not
exist at different times by virtue of the existence of successive parts of it
at those times; it is the continuant itself that is wholly present at each such
time. To conceive an object as a continuant, therefore, is to conceive it as
not made time lag argument time slice 922
922 up of temporal stages, or time slices, at all. There is another, less
common, use of ‘continuant’ in which a continuant is understood to be any
particular that exists for some stretch of time, regardless of whether it is
the whole of the particular or only some part of it that is present at each
moment of the particular’s existence. According to this usage, an entity that
is made up of time slices would be a kind of continuant rather than some other
kind of particular. Philosophers have disputed whether ordinary objects such as
cabbages and kings endure through time (are continuants) or only extend through
time (are sequences of time slices). Some argue that to understand the
possibility of change one must think of such objects as sequences of time
slices; others argue that for the se reason one must think of such objects as
continuants. If an object changes, it comes to be different from itself. Some
argue that this would be possible only if an object consisted of distinct,
successive stages; so that change would simply consist in the differences ong
the successive temporal parts of an object. Others argue that this view would
make change impossible; that differences ong the successive temporal parts of a
thing would no more imply the thing had changed than differences ong its
spatial parts would.
token-reflexive, an expression that refers to
itself in an act of speech or writing, such as ‘this token’. The term was
coined by Reichenbach, who conjectured that all indexicals, all expressions
whose semantic value depends partly on features of the context of utterance,
are tokenreflexive and definable in terms of the phrase ‘this token’. He
suggested that ‘I’ means the se as ‘the person who utters this token’, ‘now’
means the se as ‘the time at which this token is uttered’, ‘this table’ means
the se as ‘the table pointed to by a gesture accompanying this token’, and so
forth. (Russell made a somewhat similar suggestion in his discussion of
egocentric particulars.) Reichenbach’s conjecture is widely regarded as false;
although ‘I’ does pick out the person using it, it is not synonymous with ‘the
person who utters this token’. If it were, as David Kaplan observes, ‘If no one
were to utter this token, I would not exist’ would be true. EGOCENTRIC PARTICULAR, INDEXICAL. R.B.
token-token
identity.PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. Toletus, Francisco (1532–96), Spanish Jesuit
theologian and philosopher. Born in Córdoba, he studied at Valencia, Salanca,
and Rome, and bece the first Jesuit cardinal in 1594. He composed commentaries
on several of Aristotle’s works and a commentary on Aquinas’s Summa theologiae.
Toletus followed a Thomistic line, but departed from Thomism in some details.
He held that individuals are directly apprehended by the intellect and that the
agent intellect is the se power as the possible intellect. He rejected the
Thomistic doctrines of the real distinction between essence and existence and
of individuation by designated matter; for Toletus individuation results from
form. AQUINAS. J.J.E.G. tonk, a
sentential connective whose meaning and logic are completely characterized by
the two rules (or axioms) (1) [P P (P tonk Q)] and (2) [(P tonk Q) P Q]. If (1)
and (2) are added to any normal system, then every Q can be derived from any P.
Arthur Prior invented ‘tonk’ to show that deductive validity must not be
conceived as depending solely on arbitrary syntactically defined rules or
axioms. We may prohibit ‘tonk’ on the ground that it is not a natural,
independently meaningful notion, but we may also prohibit it on purely
syntactical grounds. E.g., we may require that, for every connective C, the
C-introduction rule [(xxx) P (. . . C . . .)] and the C-elimination rule [( - -
- C - - -) P (yyy)] be such that the (yyy) is part of (xxx) or is related to
(xxx) in some other syntactical way. .
topic-neutral,
noncommittal between two or more ontological interpretations of a term. J. J.
C. Smart (in 1959) suggested that introspective reports can be taken as
topic-neutral: composed of terms neutral between “dualistic metaphysics” and
“materialistic metaphysics.” When one asserts, e.g., that one has a
yellowish-orange afterimage, this is tantount to saying ‘There is something
going on that is like what is going on when I have my eyes open, awake, and there is an orange illuminated in
good light in front of me, i.e., when I really see an orange’. The italicized
phrase is, in Smart’s terms, topic-neutral; it refers to an event, while
remaining noncommittal about whether it is material or immaterial. The term has
not always been restricted to neutrality regarding dualism and materialism.
Smart suggests that topic-neutral descriptions are composed of “quasi-logical”
words, and hence would be suitable for any occasion where a relatively
noncommittal expression of a view is required.
PHILOSOPHY OF MIND.
D.C.D. topics, the analysis of common strategies of argumentation, later a
genre of literature analyzing syllogistic reasoning. Aristotle considered the
analysis of types of argument, or “topics,” the best means of describing the
art of dialectical reasoning; he also used the term to refer to the principle
underlying the strategy’s production of an argument. Later classical
commentators on Aristotle, particularly Latin rhetoricians like Cicero,
developed Aristotle’s discussions of the theory of dialectical reasoning into a
philosophical form. Boethius’s work on topics exemplifies the later classical
expansion of the scope of topics literature. For him, a topic is either a
self-evidently true universal generalization, also called a “maximal
proposition,” or a differentia, a member of the set of a maximal proposition’s
characteristics that determine its genus and species. Man is a rational animal
is a maximal proposition, and like from genus, the differentia that
characterizes the maximal proposition as concerning genera, it is a topic.
Because he believed dialectical reasoning leads to categorical, not
conditional, conclusions, Boethius felt that the discovery of an argument
entailed discovering a middle term uniting the two, previously unjoined terms
of the conclusion. Differentiae are the genera of these middle terms, and one
constructs arguments by choosing differentiae, thereby determining the middle
term leading to the conclusion. In the eleventh century, Boethius’s logical
structure of maximal propositions and differentiae was used to study
hypothetical syllogisms, while twelfth-century theorists like Abelard extended
the applicability of topics structure to the categorical syllogism. By the
thirteenth century, Peter of Spain, Robert Kilwardby, and Boethius of Dacia
applied topics structure exclusively to the categorical syllogism, principally
those with non-necessary, probable premises. Within a century, discussion of
topics structure to evaluate syllogistic reasoning was subsumed by consequences
literature, which described implication, entailment, and inference relations
between propositions. While the theory of consequences as an approach to
understanding relations between propositions is grounded in Boethian, and
perhaps Stoic, logic, it bece prominent only in the later thirteenth century
with Burley’s recognition of the logical significance of propositional
logic.
toxin puzzle, a puzzle
about intention and practical rationality posed by Gregory Kavka. A trustworthy
billionaire offers you a million dollars for intending tonight to drink a
certain toxin tomorrow. You are convinced that he can tell what you intend
independently of what you do. The toxin would make you painfully ill for a day,
but you need to drink it to get the money. Constraints on the formation of a
prize-winning intention include prohibitions against “gimmicks,” “external incentives,”
and forgetting relevant details. For exple, you will not receive the money if
you have a hypnotist “implant the intention” or hire a hit man to kill you
should you not drink the toxin. If, by midnight tonight, without violating any
rules, you form an intention to drink the toxin tomorrow, you will find a
million dollars in your bank account when you awake tomorrow morning. You
probably would drink the toxin for a million dollars. But can you, without
violating the rules, intend tonight to drink it tomorrow? Apparently, you have
no reason to drink it and an excellent reason not to drink it. Seemingly, you
will infer from this that you will eschew drinking the toxin, and believing
that you will top-down toxin puzzle 924
924 eschew drinking it seems inconsistent with intending to drink it.
Even so, there are several reports in the philosophical literature of
(possible) people who struck it rich when offered the toxin deal!
transcendence, broadly,
the property of rising out of or above other things (virtually always
understood figuratively); in philosophy, the property of being, in some way, of
a higher order. A being, such as God, may be said to be transcendent in the
sense of being not merely superior, but incomparably superior, to other things,
in any sort of perfection. God’s transcendence, or being outside or beyond the
world, is also contrasted, and by some thinkers combined, with God’s immanence,
or existence within the world. In medieval philosophy of logic, terms such as
‘being’ and ‘one’, which did not belong uniquely to any one of the Aristotelian
categories or types of predication (such as substance, quality, and relation),
but could be predicated of things belonging to any (or to none) of them, were
called transcendental. In Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, principles that
profess (wrongly) to take us beyond the limits of any possible experience are
called transcendent; whereas anything belonging to non-empirical thought that
establishes, and draws consequences from, the possibility and limits of
experience may be called transcendental. Thus a transcendental argument (in a
sense still current) is one that proceeds from premises about the way in which
experience is possible to conclusions about what must be true of any
experienced world. Transcendentalism was a philosophical or religious movement
in mid-nineteenth-century New England, characterized, in the thought of its
leading representative, Ralph Waldo Emerson, by belief in a transcendent
(spiritual and divine) principle in human nature.
transcendental argument,
an argument that elucidates the conditions for the possibility of some
fundental phenomenon whose existence is unchallenged or uncontroversial in the
philosophical context in which the argument is propounded. Such an argument proceeds
deductively, from a premise asserting the existence of some basic phenomenon
(such as meaningful discourse, conceptualization of objective states of
affairs, or the practice of making promises), to a conclusion asserting the
existence of some interesting, substantive enabling conditions for that
phenomenon. The term derives from Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, which gives
several such arguments. The paradigmatic Kantian transcendental argument is the
“Transcendental Deduction of the Pure Concepts of Understanding.” Kant argued
there that the objective validity of certain pure, or a priori, concepts (the
“categories”) is a condition for the possibility of experience. ong the
concepts allegedly required for having experience are those of substance and cause.
Their apriority consists in the fact that instances of these concepts are not
directly given in sense experience in the manner of instances of empirical
concepts such as red. This fact gave rise to the skepticism of Hume concerning
the very coherence of such alleged a priori concepts. Now if these concepts do
have objective validity, as Kant endeavored to prove in opposition to Hume,
then the world contains genuine instances of the concepts. In a transcendental
argument concerning the conditions for the possibility of experience, it is
crucial that some feature entailed by the having of experience is identified.
Then it is argued that experience could not have this feature without
satisfying some substantive conditions. In the Transcendental Deduction, the
feature of experience on which Kant concentrates is the ability of a subject of
experience to be aware of several distinct inner states as all belonging to a
single consciousness. There is no general agreement on how Kant’s argument
actually unfolded, though it seems clear to most that he focused on the role of
the categories in the synthesis or combination of one’s inner states in
judgments, where such synthesis is said to be required for one’s awareness of
the states as being all equally one’s own states. Another fous Kantian
transcendental argument – the “Refutation of Idealism” in the CriToynbee,
Arnold transcendental argument 925 925
tique of Pure Reason – shares a noteworthy trait with the Transcendental Deduction.
The Refutation proceeds from the premise that one is conscious of one’s own
existence as determined in time, i.e., knows the temporal order of some of
one’s inner states. According to the Refutation, a condition for the
possibility of such knowledge is one’s consciousness of the existence of
objects located outside oneself in space. If one is indeed so conscious, that
would refute the skeptical view, formulated by Descartes, that one lacks
knowledge of the existence of a spatial world distinct from one’s mind and its
inner states. Both of the Kantian transcendental arguments we have considered,
then, conclude that the falsity of some skeptical view is a condition for the
possibility of some phenomenon whose existence is acknowledged even by the
skeptic (the having of experience; knowledge of temporal facts about one’s own
inner states). Thus, we can isolate an interesting subclass of transcendental
arguments: those which are anti-skeptical in nature. Barry Stroud has raised
the question whether such arguments depend on some sort of suppressed
verificationism according to which the existence of language or
conceptualization requires the availability of the knowledge that the skeptic
questions (since verificationism has it that meaningful sentences expressing
coherent concepts, e.g., ‘There are tables’, must be verifiable by what is
given in sense experience). Dependence on a highly controversial premise is
undesirable in itself. Further, Stroud argued, such a dependence would render
superfluous whatever other content the anti-skeptical transcendental argument
might embody (since the suppressed premise alone would refute the skeptic).
There is no general agreement on whether Stroud’s doubts about anti-skeptical
transcendental arguments are well founded. It is not obvious whether the doubts
apply to arguments that do not proceed from a premise asserting the existence
of language or conceptualization, but instead conform more closely to the
Kantian model. Even so, no anti-skeptical transcendental argument has been
widely accepted. This is evidently due to the difficulty of uncovering
substantive enabling conditions for phenomena that even a skeptic will
countenance. KANT, SKEPTICISM. A.B.
transcendental deduction.KANT. transcendental dialectic.DIALECTIC. transcendental
ego.KANT. transcendentalia.TRANSCENDENTALS. transcendental idealism.KANT.
transcendentalism, a
religious-philosophical viewpoint held by a group of New England intellectuals,
of whom Emerson, Thoreau, and Theodore Parker were the most important. A
distinction taken over from Suel Taylor Coleridge was the only bond that
universally united the members of the Transcendental Club, founded in 1836: the
distinction between the understanding and reason, the former providing
uncertain knowledge of appearances, the latter a priori knowledge of necessary
truths gained through intuition. The transcendentalists insisted that
philosophical truth could be reached only by reason, a capacity common to all
people unless destroyed by living a life of externals and accepting as true
only secondhand traditional beliefs. On almost every other point there were
disagreements. Emerson was an idealist, while Parker was a natural realist –
they simply had conflicting a priori intuitions. Emerson, Thoreau, and Parker
rejected the supernatural aspects of Christianity, pointing out its
unmistakable parochial nature and sociological development; while Jes Marsh,
Frederick Henry Hedge, and Caleb Henry remained in the Christian fold. The
influences on the transcendentalists differed widely and explain the diversity
of opinion. For exple, Emerson was influenced by the Platonic tradition, German
Romanticism, Eastern religions, and nature poets, while Parker was influenced
by modern science, the Scottish realism of Reid and Cousin (which also
emphasized a priori intuitions), and the German Higher Critics. Emerson,
Thoreau, and Parker were also bonded by negative beliefs. They not only
rejected Calvinism but Unitarianism as well; they rejected the ordinary concept
of material success and put in its place an Aristotelian type of
selfrealization that emphasized the rational and moral self as the essence of
humanity and decried idiosyncratic self-realization that admires what is unique
in people as constituting their real value.
EMERSON, THOREAU. E.H.M. transcendental number.
MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS.
transcendentals, also called transcendentalia, terms or concepts that apply to
all things regardless of the things’ ontological kind or category.
transcendental deduction transcendentals 926
926 Terms or concepts of this sort are transcendental in the sense that
they transcend or are superordinate to all classificatory categories. The
classical doctrine of the transcendentals, developed in detail in the later
Middle Ages, presupposes an Aristotelian ontology according to which all beings
are substances or accidents classifiable within one of the ten highest genera,
the ten Aristotelian categories. In this scheme being (Greek on, Latin ens) is
not itself one of the categories since all categories mark out kinds of being.
But neither is it a category above the ten categories of substance and
accidents, an ultimate genus of which the ten categories are species. This is
because being is homonymous or equivocal, i.e., there is no single generic
property or nature shared by members of each category in virtue of which they
are beings. The ten categories identify ten irreducible, most basic ways of
being. Being, then, transcends the categorial structure of the world: anything
at all that is ontologically classifiable is a being, and to say of anything
that it is a being is not to identify it as a member of some kind distinct from
other kinds of things. According to this classical doctrine, being is the
primary transcendental, but there are other terms or concepts that transcend
the categories in a similar way. The most commonly recognized transcendentals
other than being are one (unum), true (verum), and good (bonum), though some
medieval philosophers also recognized thing (res), something (aliquid), and
beautiful (pulchrum). These other terms or concepts are transcendental because
the ontological ground of their application to a given thing is precisely the
se as the ontological ground in virtue of which that thing can be called a
being. For exple, for a thing with a certain nature to be good is for it to
perform well the activity that specifies it as a thing of that nature, and to
perform this activity well is to have actualized that nature to a certain
extent. But for a thing to have actualized its nature to some extent is just
what it is for the thing to have being. So the actualities or properties in
virtue of which a thing is good are precisely those in virtue of which it has
being. Given this account, medieval philosophers held that transcendental terms
are convertible (convertuntur) or extensionally equivalent (idem secundum
supposita). They are not synonymous, however, since they are intensionally
distinct (differunt secundum rationem). These secondary transcendentals are
sometimes characterized as attributes (passiones) of being that are necessarily
concomitant with it. In the modern period, the notion of the transcendental is
associated primarily with Kant, who made ‘transcendental’ a central technical
term in his philosophy. For Kant the term no longer signifies that which
transcends categorial classification but that which transcends our experience
in the sense of providing its ground or structure. Kant allows, e.g., that the
pure forms of intuition (space and time) and the pure concepts of understanding
(categories such as substance and cause) are transcendental in this sense.
Forms and concepts of this sort constitute the conditions of the possibility of
experience.
transfinite number, in
set theory, an infinite cardinal or ordinal number.
transformational
grmar.GRMAR. transformation rule, an axiom-schema or rule of inference. A
transformation rule is thus a rule for transforming a (possibly empty) set of
wellformed formulas into a formula, where that rule operates only upon
syntactic information. It was this conception of an axiom-schema and rule of
inference that was one of the keys to creating a genuinely rigorous science of
deductive reasoning. In the 1950s, the idea was imported into linguistics,
giving rise to the notion of a transformational rule. Such a rule transforms
tree structures into tree structures, taking one from the deep structure of a
sentence, which determines its semantic interpretation, to the surface
structure of that sentence, which determines its phonetic interpretation. GRMAR, LOGISTIC SYSTEM. G.F.S. transitive.RELATION.
transitive closure.ANCESTRAL. translation, radical
.INDETERMINACY OF
TRANSLATION. transcendental subjectivity translation, radical 927 927 transparent.REFERENTIALLY TRANSPARENT.
transparent context.REFERENTIALLY TRANSPARENT. transubstantiation, change of
one substance into another. Aristotelian metaphysics distinguishes between
substances and the accidents that inhere in them; thus, Socrates is a substance
and being snub-nosed is one of his accidents. The Roman Catholic and Eastern
Orthodox churches appeal to transubstantiation to explain how Jesus Christ
becomes really present in the Eucharist when the consecration takes place: the
whole substances of the bread and wine are transformed into the body and blood
of Christ, but the accidents of the bread and wine such as their shape, color,
and taste persist after the transformation. This seems to commit its adherents
to holding that these persisting accidents subsequently either inhere in Christ
or do not inhere in any substance. Luther proposed an alternative explanation
in terms of consubstantiation that avoids this hard choice: the substances of
the bread and wine coexist in the Eucharist with the body and blood of Christ
after the consecration; they are united but each remains unchanged. P.L.Q. transvaluation
of values.NIETZSCHE.
transversality,
transcendence of the sovereignty of identity or self-seness by recognizing the
alterity of the Other as Unterschied – to use Heidegger’s term – which
signifies the sense of relatedness by way of difference. An innovative idea
employed and appropriated by such diverse philosophers as Merleau-Ponty,
Sartre, Gilles Deleuze, and Félix Guattari, transversality is meant to replace
the Eurocentric formulation of truth as universal in an age when the world is said
to be rushing toward the global village. Universality has been a Eurocentric
idea because what is particular in the West is universalized, whereas what is
particular elsewhere remains particularized. Since its center is everywhere and
its circumference nowhere, truth is polycentric and correlative. Particularly
noteworthy is the erican phenomenologist Calvin O. Schrag’s attempt to
appropriate transversality by splitting the difference between the two extremes
of absolutism and relativism on the one hand and modernity’s totalizing
practices and postmodernity’s fragmentary tendencies on the other. HEIDEGGER, MERLEAU-PONTY, PHENOMENOLOGY,
SARTRE. H.Y.J. tree of Porphyry, a structure generated from the logical and
metaphysical apparatus of Aristotle’s Categories, as systematized by Porphyry
and later writers. A tree in the category of substance begins with substance as
its highest genus and divides that genus into mutually exclusive and
collectively exhaustive subordinate genera by means of a pair of opposites,
called differentiae, yielding, e.g., corporeal substance and incorporeal
substance. The process of division by differentiae continues until a lowest
species is reached, a species that cannot be divided further. The species
“human being” is said to be a lowest species whose derivation can be recaptured
from the formula “mortal, rational, sensitive, animate, corporeal
substance.” ARISTOTLE, INFIMA SPECIES,
PORPHYRY. W.E.M. trichotomous.RELATION. trichotomy, law of.CHOICE SEQUENCE,
RELATION. Trinitarianism, the theological doctrine that God consists of three
persons. The persons who constitute the Holy Trinity are the Father; the Son,
who is Jesus Christ; and the Holy Spirit (or Holy Ghost). The doctrine states
that each of these three persons is God and yet they are not three Gods but one
God. According to a traditional formulation, the three persons are but one
substance. In the opinion of Aquinas, the existence of God can be proved by
human reason, but the existence of the three persons cannot be proved and is
known only by revelation. According to Christian tradition, revelation contains
information about the relations ong the three persons, and these relations
ground proper attributes of each that distinguish them from one another. Thus,
since the Father begets the Son, a proper attribute of the Father is paternity
and a proper attribute of the Son is filiation. Procession transparent
Trinitarianism 928 928 (or spiration)
is a proper attribute of the Holy Spirit. A disagreement about procession has
contributed to dividing Eastern and Western Christianity. The Eastern Orthodox
church teaches that the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Father through the Son. A
theory of double procession according to which the Holy Spirit proceeds from
the Father and the Son has been widely accepted in the West. This disagreement
is known as the filioque (‘and the Son’) controversy because it arose from the
fact that adding this Latin phrase to the Nicene Creed bece acceptable in the
West but not in the East. Unitarianism denies that God consists of three
persons and so is committed to denying the divinity of Jesus. The monotheistic
faiths of Judaism and Isl are unitarian, but there are unitarians who consider
themselves Christians. PHILOSOPHY OF
RELIGION. P.L.Q. Trinity.TRINITARIANISM.
Troeltsch, Ernst
(1865–1923), German philosopher and historian whose primary aim was to provide
a scientific foundation for theology. Educated at Erlangen, Göttingen (under
Ritschl and Lagarde), and Berlin, he initially taught theology at Heidelberg
and later philosophy in Berlin. He launched the school of history of religion
with his epoch-making “On Historical and Dogmatical Method in Theology” (1896).
His contributions to theology (The Religious Apriori, 1904), philosophy,
sociology, and history (Historicism and Its Problems, 1922) were vastly
influential. Troeltsch claimed that only a philosophy of religion drawn from
the history and development of religious consciousness could strengthen the
standing of the science of religion ong the sciences and advance the Christian
strategy against materialism, naturalism, skepticism, aestheticism, and
pantheism. His historical masterpiece, Protestantism and Progress (1906),
argues that early Protestantism was a modified medieval Catholicism that
delayed the development of modern culture. As a sociologist, he addressed, in
The Social Teachings of the Christian Churches (1912), the twofold issue of
whether religious beliefs and movements are conditioned by external factors and
whether, in turn, they affect society and culture. From Christian social
history he inferred three types of “sociological self-formation of the
Christian idea”: the church, the sect, and the mystic. J.-L.S.
trope, in recent
philosophical usage, an “abstract particular”; an instance of a property
occurring at a particular place and time, such as the color of the cover of
this book or this . The whiteness of this
and the whiteness of the previous
are two distinct tropes, identical neither with the universal whiteness
that is instantiated in both s, nor with the
itself; although the whiteness of this
cannot exist independently of this , this could be dyed some other color. A number of
writers, perhaps beginning with D. C. Willis, have argued that tropes must be
included in our ontology if we are to achieve an adequate metaphysics. More
generally, a trope is a figure of speech, or the use of an expression in a
figurative or nonliteral sense. Metaphor and irony, e.g., fall under the
category of tropes. If you are helping someone move a glass table but drop your
end, and your companion says, “Well, you’ve certainly been a big help,” her
utterance is probably ironical, with the intended meaning that you have been no
help. One important question is whether, in order to account for the ironical
use of this sentence, we must suppose that it has an ironical meaning in
addition to its literal meaning. Quite generally, does a sentence usable to
express two different metaphors have, in addition to its literal meaning, two
metaphorical meanings – and another if it can be hyperbolic, and so forth? Many
philosophers and other theorists from Aristotle on have answered yes, and
postulated such figurative meanings in addition to literal sentence meaning.
Recently, philosophers loath to multiply sentence meanings have denied that
sentences have any non-literal meanings.Their burden is to explain how, e.g., a
sentence can be used ironically if it does not have an ironical sense or
meaning. Such philosophers disagree on whether tropes are to be explained
semantically or pragmatically. A semantic account might hypothesize that tropes
are generated by violations of semantical rules. An important pragmatic
approach is Grice’s suggestion that tropes can be subsumed under the more
general phenomenon of conversational implicature.
truth, the quality of
those propositions that accord with reality, specifying what is in fact the
case. Whereas the aim of a science is to discover which of the propositions in
its domain are true i.e., which propositions possess the property of Trinity
truth 929 929 truth – the central
philosophical concern with truth is to discover the nature of that property.
Thus the philosophical question is not What is true? but rather, What is truth?
– What is one saying about a proposition in saying that it is true? The
importance of this question stems from the variety and depth of the principles
in which the concept of truth is deployed. We are tempted to think, e.g., that
truth is the proper aim and natural result of scientific inquiry, that true beliefs
are useful, that the meaning of a sentence is given by the conditions that
would render it true, and that valid reasoning preserves truth. Therefore
insofar as we wish to understand, assess, and refine these epistemological,
ethical, semantic, and logical views, some account of the nature of truth would
seem to be required. Such a thing, however, has been notoriously elusive. The
belief that snow is white owes its truth to a certain feature of the external
world: the fact that snow is white. Similarly, the belief that dogs bark is
true because of the fact that dogs bark. Such trivial observations lead to what
is perhaps the most natural and widely held account of truth, the
correspondence theory, according to which a belief (statement, sentence, proposition,
etc.) is true provided there exists a fact corresponding to it. This
Aristotelian thesis is unexceptionable in itself. However, if it is to provide
a complete theory of truth – and if it is to be more than merely a picturesque
way of asserting all instances of ‘the belief that p is true if and only if p’
– then it must be supplemented with accounts of what facts are, and what it is
for a belief to correspond to a fact; and these are the problems on which the
correspondence theory of truth has foundered. A popular alternative to the
correspondence theory has been to identify truth with verifiability. This idea
can take on various forms. One version involves the further assumption that
verification is holistic – i.e., that a belief is verified when it is part of
an entire system of beliefs that is consistent and “harmonious.” This is known
as the coherence theory of truth and was developed by Bradley and Brand
Blanchard. Another version, due to Dummett and Putn, involves the assumption
that there is, for each proposition, some specific procedure for finding out
whether one should believe it or not. On this account, to say that a
proposition is true is to say that it would be verified by the appropriate
procedure. In mathematics this ounts to the identification of truth with
provability and is sometimes referred to as intuitionistic truth. Such theories
aim to avoid obscure metaphysical notions and explain the close relation
between knowability and truth. They appear, however, to overstate the intimacy of
that link: for we can easily imagine a statement that, though true, is beyond
our power to establish as true. A third major account of truth is Jes’s
pragmatic theory. As we have just seen, the verificationist selects a prominent
property of truth and considers it to be the essence of truth. Similarly the
pragmatist focuses on another important characteristic – nely, that true
beliefs are a good basis for action – and takes this to be the very nature of
truth. True assumptions are said to be, by definition, those that provoke
actions with desirable results. Again we have an account with a single
attractive explanatory feature. But again the central objection is that the
relationship it postulates between truth and its alleged analysans – in this
case, utility – is implausibly close. Granted, true beliefs tend to foster
success. But often actions based on true beliefs lead to disaster, while false
assumptions, by pure chance, produce wonderful results. One of the few fairly
uncontroversial facts about truth is that the proposition that snow is white is
true if and only if snow is white, the proposition that lying is wrong is true
if and only if lying is wrong, and so on. Traditional theories of truth
acknowledge this fact but regard it as insufficient and, as we have seen,
inflate it with some further principle of the form ‘X is true if and only if X
has property P’ (such as corresponding to reality, verifiability, or being
suitable as a basis for action), which is supposed to specify what truth is. A
collection of radical alternatives to the traditional theories results from
denying the need for any such further specification. For exple, one might
suppose (with Rsey, Ayer, and Strawson) that the basic theory of truth contains
nothing more than equivalences of the form, ‘The proposition that p is true if
and only if p’ (excluding instantiation by sentences such as ‘This proposition
is not true’ that generate contradiction). This so-called deflationary theory
is best presented (following Quine) in conjunction with an account of the
raison d’être of our notion of truth: nely, that its function is not to
describe propositions, as one might naively infer from its syntactic form, but
rather to enable us to construct a certain type of generalization. For exple,
‘What Einstein said is true’ is intuitively equivalent to the infinite
conjunction ‘If Einstein said that nothing goes faster than light, then nothing
goes faster than light; and if Einstein said truth truth 930 930 that nuclear weapons should never be
built, then nuclear weapons should never be built; . . . and so on.’ But
without a truth predicate we could not capture this statement. The deflationist
argues, moreover, that all legitimate uses of the truth predicate – including
those in science, logic, semantics, and metaphysics – are simply displays of
this generalizing function, and that the equivalence schema is just what is
needed to explain that function. Within the deflationary cp there are various
competing proposals. According to Frege’s socalled redundancy theory,
corresponding instances of ‘It is true that p’ and ‘p’ have exactly the se
meaning, whereas the minimalist theory assumes merely that such propositions
are necessarily equivalent. Other deflationists are skeptical about the
existence of propositions and therefore take sentences to be the basic vehicles
of truth. Thus the disquotation theory supposes that truth is captured by the
disquotation principle, ‘p’ is true if and only if p’. More bitiously, Tarski
does not regard the disquotation principle, also known as Tarski’s (T) schema,
as an adequate theory in itself, but as a specification of what any adequate
definition must imply. His own account shows how to give an explicit definition
of truth for all the sentences of certain formal languages in terms of the
referents of their primitive nes and predicates. This is known as the semantic
theory of truth. .
truthlikeness, a term
introduced by Karl Popper in 1960 to explicate the idea that one theory may
have a better correspondence with reality, or be closer to the truth, or have
more verisimilitude, than another theory. Truthlikeness, which combines truth
with information content, has to be distinguished from probability, which
increases with lack of content. Let T and F be the classes of all true and
false sentences, respectively, and A and B deductively closed sets of
sentences. According to Popper’s qualitative definition, A is more truthlike
than B if and only if B 3 T 0 A 3 T and A 3 F 0 B 3 F, where one of these
setinclusions is strict. In particular, when A and B are non-equivalent and
both true, A is more truthlike than B if and only if A logically entails B.
David Miller and Pavel Tichý proved in 1974 that Popper’s definition is not
applicable to the comparison of false theories: if A is more truthlike than B,
then A must be true. Since the mid-1970s, a new approach to truthlikeness has
been based upon the concept of similarity: the degree of truthlikeness of a
statement A depends on the distances from the states of affairs allowed by A to
the true state. In Grah Oddie’s Likeness to Truth (1986), this dependence is
expressed by the average function; in Ilkka Niiniluoto’s Truthlikeness (1987),
by the weighted average of the minimum distance and the sum of all distances.
The concept of verisimilitude is also used in the epistemic sense to express a
rational evaluation of how close to the truth a theory appears to be on
available evidence. CONFIRMATION,
INFORMATION THEORY, INSTRUMENTALISM, PROBABILITY. I.N. truthmaker
principle.ARMSTRONG. truth predicate.
SEMANTIC PARADOXES. truth
table, a tabular display of one or more truth-functions, truth-functional
operators, or representatives of truth-functions or truth-functional operators
(such as well-formed formulas of propositional logic). In the tabular display,
each row displays a possible assignment of truthvalues to the arguments of the
truth-functions or truth-functional operators. Thus, the collection of all rows
in the table displays all possible assignments of truth-values to these
arguments. The following simple truth table represents the truth-functional
operators negation and conjunction: truth, coherence theory of truth table
931 931 Because a truth table displays
all possible assignments of truth-values to the arguments of a truth-function,
truth tables are useful devices for quickly ascertaining logical properties of
propositions. If, e.g., all entries in the column of a truth table representing
a proposition are T, then the proposition is true for all possible assignments
of truth-values to its ultimate constituent propositions; in this sort of case,
the proposition is said to be logically or tautologically true: a tautology. If
all entries in the column of a truth table representing a proposition are F,
then the proposition is false for all possible assignments of truth-values to
its ultimate constituent propositions, and the proposition is said to be
logically or tautologically false: a contradiction. If a proposition is neither
a tautology nor a contradiction, then it is said to be a contingency. The truth
table above shows that both Not-P and Pand-Q are contingencies. For the se
reason that truth tables are useful devices for ascertaining the logical
qualities of single propositions, truth tables are also useful for ascertaining
whether arguments are valid or invalid. A valid argument is one such that there
is no possibility (no row in the relevant truth table) in which all its
premises are true and its conclusion false. Thus the above truth table shows
that the argument ‘P-and-Q; therefore, P’ is valid.
truth-value, most
narrowly, one of the values T (for ‘true’) or F (for ‘false’) that a
proposition may be considered to have or take on when it is regarded as true or
false, respectively. More broadly, a truth-value is any one of a range of
values that a proposition may be considered to have when taken to have one of a
range of different cognitive or epistemic statuses. For exple, some
philosophers speak of the truth-value I (for ‘indeterminate’) and regard a
proposition as having the value I when it is indeterminate whether the
proposition is true or false. Logical systems employing a specific number n of
truthvalues are said to be n-valued logical systems; the simplest sort of
useful logical system has two truth-values, T and F, and accordingly is said to
be two-valued. Truth-functions are functions that take truth-values as
arguments and that yield truth-values as resultant values. The truthtable
method in propositional logic exploits the idea of truth-functions by using
tabular displays.
TRUTH TABLE. R.W.B.
truth-value gaps.MANY-VALUED LOGIC, PRESUPPOSITION. truth-value semantics,
interpretations of formal systems in which the truth-value of a formula rests
ultimately only on truth-values that are assigned to its atomic subformulas (where
‘subformula’ is suitably defined). The label is due to Hugues Leblanc. On a
truth-value interpretation for first-order predicate logic, for exple, the
formula atomic ExFx is true in a model if and only if all its instances Fm, Fn,
. . . are true, where the truth-value of these formulas is simply assigned by
the model. On the standard Tarskian or objectual interpretation, by contrast,
ExFx is true in a model if and only if every object in the domain of the model
is an element of the set that interprets F in the model. Thus a truth-value
semantics for predicate logic comprises a substitutional interpretation of the
quantifiers and a “non-denotational” interpretation of terms and predicates. If
t 1, t 2, . . . are all the terms of some first-order language, then there are
objectual models that satisfy the set {Dx-Fx, Ft1, Ft2 . . . .}, but no
truth-value interpretations that do. One can ensure that truth-value semantics
delivers the standard logic, however, by suitable modifications in the
definitions of consistency and consequence. A set G of formulas of language L
is said to be consistent, for exple, if there is some G' obtained from G by
relettering terms such that G' is satisfied by some truth-value assignment, or,
alternatively, if there is some language L+ obtained by adding terms to L such
that G is satisfied by some truth-value assignment to the atoms of L+.
Truth-value semantics is of both technical and philosophical interest.
Technically, it allows the completeness of first-order predicate logic and a
variety of other formal systems to be obtained in a natural way from that of
propositional logic. Philosophically, it dratizes the fact that the formulas in
one’s theories about the world do not, in themselves, determine one’s
ontological commitments. It is at least possible to interpret first-order
formulas without reference to special truth-table method truth-value semantics
932 932 domains of objects, and
higher-order formulas without reference to special domains of relations and
properties. The idea of truth-value semantics dates at least to the writings of
E. W. Beth on first-order predicate logic in 1959 and of K. Schütte on simple
type theory in 1960. In more recent years similar semantics have been suggested
for secondorder logics, modal and tense logics, intuitionistic logic, and set
theory.
Tsou Yen (350?–270?
B.C.), Chinese cosmologist, a member of the Chi-hsia Academy and influential
political figure who applied yin–yang fivephases thinking to dynastic cycles.
Tsou Yen believed that the natural order, the human order, and the relation
between the two were all governed and made intelligible by the dynic interplay
ong yin–yang and the five phases (wu-hsing: earth, wood, metal, fire, and
water). He gained political fe for his idea that the rise and fall of dynasties
are correlated with the five phases and accord with the se cyclical pattern:
earth, wood, metal, fire, and water. Thus, the reign of the Yellow Emperor,
correlated with the earth phase, was followed by the Hsia (wood), the Shang (metal),
and the Chou (fire) dynasties. Tsou Yen predicted that the ascendancy of the
water phase would signal the end of the Chou and the beginning of a new
dynasty.
CHINESE PHILOSOPHY.
R.P.P. & R.T.A. Tung Chung-shu (c.179–c.104 B.C.), Chinese philosopher, a
Han scholar fous for his answers to questions by Emperor Wu, which were
instrumental in making Confucianism the state doctrine in 136 B.C. He wrote
Ch’un-ch’iu fan-lu (“Luxuriant Gems of the Spring and Autumn Annals”), in which
he read moral messages from historical events recorded in the classic in such a
way that they could be applied to future history. Tung’s teachings were
actually quite different from those of Confucius and Mencius. He believed that
Heaven and the Way do not change, and he taught the so-called Three Bonds,
according to which the ruler, the father, and the husband are to be the
standards of the ruled, the son, and the wife. These added a conservative ring
to Confucianism, so that the rulers were happy to use it in combination with Legalist
practice to create a state Confucianism. He also incorporated many ideas from
the yin–yang school in his philosophy. He believed that history goes in cycles,
the five powers (wood, fire, earth, metal, water) succeed each other, and there
is a strict correlation between natural affairs and human affairs. He saw
natural disasters as warning signs for the rulers to cultivate virtues and not
to abuse their powers. CONFUCIANISM,
CONFUCIUS, MENCIUS. S.-h.L. tu quoque.INFORMAL FALLACY. Turing degree.DEGREE OF
UNSOLVABILITY. Turing machine, an abstract automaton or imagined computer
consisting of a finite automaton operating an indefinitely long storage tape.
The finite automaton provides the computing power of the machine. The tape is
used for input, output, and calculation workspace; in the case of the universal
Turing machine, it also specifies another Turing machine. Initially, only a
finite number of squares of the tape are marked with symbols, while the rest
are blank. The finite automaton part of the machine has a finite number of
internal states and operates discretely, at times t % 0, 1, 2, . . . . At each
time-step the automaton exines the tape square under its tape head, possibly
changes what is there, moves the tape left or right, and then changes its
internal state. The law governing this sequence of actions is deterministic and
is defined in a state table. For each internal state and each tape symbol (or
blank) under the tape head, the state table describes the tape action performed
by the machine and gives the next internal state of the machine. Since a
machine has only a finite number of internal states and of tape symbols, the
state table of a machine is finite in length and can be stored on a tape. There
is a universal Turing machine Mu that can simulate every Turing machine
(including itself): when the state table of any machine M is written on the
tape of Mu, the universal machine Mu will perform the se input-output
computation that M performs. Mu does this by using the state table of M to calculate
M’s complete history for any given input. Turing machines may be thought of as
conceptual devices for enumerating the elements of an infinite set (e.g., the
theorems of a formal language), or as decision machines (e.g., deciding of any
truth-functional formula whether it is a tautology). A. M. Turing showed that
there are welldefined logical tasks that cannot be carried out by any machine;
in particular, no machine can solve the halting problem. Tsou Yen Turing
machine 933 933 Turing’s definition of a
machine was theoretical; it was not a practical specification for a machine.
After the modern electronic computer was invented, he proposed a test for
judging whether there is a computer that is behaviorally equivalent to a human
in reasoning and intellectual creative power. The Turing test is a “black box”
type of experiment that Turing proposed as a way of deciding whether a computer
can think. Two rooms are fitted with the se input-output equipment going to an
outside experimenter. A person is placed in one room and a progrmed electronic
computer in the other, each in communication with the experimenter. By issuing
instructions and asking questions, the experimenter tries to decide which room
has the computer and which the human. If the experimenter cannot tell, that
outcome is strong evidence that the computer can think as well as the person.
More directly, it shows that the computer and the human are equivalent for all
the behaviors tested. Since the computer is a finite automaton, perhaps the
most significant test task is that of doing creative mathematics about the
non-enumerable infinite.
Turnbull, George
(1698–1748), Scottish moral sense philosopher and educational theorist. He was
briefly a philosophy regent at Aberdeen (1721–27) and a teacher of Reid. His
Principles of Moral and Christian Philosophy (1740) and Discourse upon the
Nature and Origin of Moral and Civil Laws (1741) show him as the most
systematic of those who aimed to recast moral philosophy on a Newtonian model,
deriving moral laws “experimentally” from human psychology. In A Treatise on
Ancient Painting (1740), Observations Upon Liberal Education (1742), and some
smaller works, he extolled history and the arts as propaedeutic to the teaching
of virtue and natural religion. MORAL SENSE
THEORY. M.A.St. Twardowski.ACT-OBJECT PSYCHOLOGY, POLISH LOGIC. Twin-Earth, a
fictitious planet first visited by Hilary Putn in a thought experiment designed
to show, ong other things, that “ ‘meanings’ just ain’t in the head” (“The
Meaning of ‘Meaning’,” 1975). Twin-Earth is exactly like Earth with one notable
exception: ponds, rivers, and ice trays on Twin-Earth contain, not H2O, but
XYZ, a liquid superficially indistinguishable from water but with a different
chemical constitution. According to Putn, although some inhabitants of
Twin-Earth closely resemble inhabitants of Earth, ‘water’, when uttered by a
Twin-Earthling, does not mean water. Water is H2O, and, on Twin-Earth, the word
‘water’ designates a different substance, XYZ, Twin-water. The moral drawn by
Putn is that the meanings of at least some of our words, and the significance
of some of our thoughts, depend, in part, on how things stand outside our
heads. Two “molecular duplicates,” two agents with qualitatively similar mental
lives, might mean very different things by their utterances and think very
different thoughts. Although Twin-Earth has become a popular stopping-off place
for philosophers en route to theories of meaning and mental content, others
regard Twin-Earth as hopelessly remote, doubting that useful conclusions can be
drawn about our Earthly circumstances from research conducted there.
tychism (from Greek
tyche, ‘chance’), Peirce’s doctrine that there is absolute chance in the
universe and its fundental laws are probabilistic and inexact. Peirce’s tychism
is part of his evolutionary cosmology, according to which all regularities of
nature are products of growth and development, i.e., results of evolution. The
laws of nature develop over time and become increasingly rigid and exact; the
apparently deterministic laws of physics are limiting cases of the basic,
probabilistic laws. Underlying all other laws is “the tendency of all things to
take habits”; Peirce calls this the Law of Habit. In his cosmology his tychism
is associated with synechism, the doctrine of the continuity of nature. His
synechism involves the doctrine of the continuity of mind and matter; Peirce
sometimes expressed this view by saying that “matter is effete mind.” R.Hi.
type.ACTION THEORY,
type theory, broadly, any
theory according to which the things that exist fall into natural, perhaps
mutually exclusive, categories or types. In most modern discussions, ‘type
theory’ refers to the theory of logical types first sketched by Russell in The
Principles of Mathematics (1903). It is a theory of logical types insofar as it
purports only to classify things into the most general categories that must be
presupposed by an adequate logical theory. Russell proposed his theory in
response to his discovery of the now-fous paradox that bears his ne. The
paradox is this. Common sense suggests that some classes are members of
themselves (e.g., the class of all classes), while others are not (e.g., the
class of philosophers). Let R be the class whose membership consists of exactly
those classes of the latter sort, i.e., those that are not members of
themselves. Is R a member of itself? If so, then it is a member of the class of
all classes that are not members of themselves, and hence is not a member of
itself. If, on the other hand, it is not a member of itself, then it satisfies
its own membership conditions, and hence is a member of itself after all.
Either way there is a contradiction. The source of the paradox, Russell
suggested, is the assumption that classes and their members form a single,
homogeneous logical type. To the contrary, he proposed that the logical
universe is stratified into a regimented hierarchy of types. Individuals
constitute the lowest type in the hierarchy, type 0. (For purposes of
exposition, individuals can be taken to be ordinary objects like chairs and
persons.) Type 1 consists of classes of individuals, type 2 of classes of
classes of individuals, type 3 classes of classes of classes of individuals,
and so on. Unlike the homogeneous universe, then, in the type hierarchy the
members of a given class must all be drawn from a single logical type n, and
the class itself must reside in the next higher type n ! 1. (Russell’s sketch
in the Principles differs from this account in certain details.) Russell’s paradox
cannot arise in this conception of the universe of classes. Because the members
of a class must all be of the se logical type, there is no such class as R,
whose definition cuts across all types. Rather, there is only, for each type n,
the class Rn of all non-self-membered classes of that type. Since Rn itself is
of type n ! 1, the paradox breaks down: from the assumption that Rn is not a
member of itself (as in fact it is not in the type hierarchy), it no longer
follows that it satisfies its own membership conditions, since those conditions
apply only to objects of type n. Most formal type theories, including Russell’s
own, enforce the class membership restrictions of simple type theory
syntactically such that a can be asserted to be a member of b only if b is of
the next higher type than a. In such theories, the definition of R, hence the
paradox itself, cannot even be expressed. Numerous paradoxes remain unscathed
by the simple type hierarchy. Of these, the most prominent are the semantic
paradoxes, so called because they explicitly involve semantic notions like
truth, as in the following version of the liar paradox. Suppose Epimenides
asserts that all the propositions he asserts today are false; suppose also that
that is the only proposition he asserts today. It follows immediately that,
under those conditions, the proposition he asserts is true if and only if it is
false. To address such paradoxes, Russell was led to the more refined and
substantially more complicated system known as rified type theory, developed in
detail in his 1908 paper “Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of Types.”
In the rified theory, propositions and properties (or propositional functions,
in Russell’s jargon) come to play the central roles in the type-theoretic
universe. Propositions are best construed as the metaphysical and semantical
counterparts of sentences – what sentences express – and properties as the
counterparts of “open sentences” like ‘x is a philosopher’ that contain a
variable ‘x’ in place of a noun phrase. To distinguish linguistic expressions
from their semantic counterparts, the property expressed by, say, ‘x is a
philosopher’, will be denoted by ‘x ^ is a philosopher’, and the proposition
expressed by ‘Aristotle is a philosopher’ will be denoted by ‘Aristotle is a
philosopher’. A property . . .x ^ . . . is said to be true of an individual a
if . . . a . . . is a true proposition, and false of a if . . . a . . . is a
false proposition (where ‘. . . a . . .’ is the result of replacing ‘x ^ ’ with
‘a’ in ‘. . . x ^ . . .’). So, e.g., x ^ is a philosopher is true of Aristotle.
The range of significance of a property P is the collection of objects of which
P is true or false. a is a possible argument for P if it is in P’s range of
significance. In the rified theory, the hierarchy of classes is supplanted by a
hierarchy of properties: first, properties of individuals (i.e., properties
whose range of significance is restricted to individuals), then properties of
properties of individuals, and so on. Parallel to the simple theory, then, the
type of a property must exceed the type of its possible arguments by one. Thus,
Russell’s paradox with R now in the guise of the property x ^ is a property
that is not true of itself – is avoided along analogous lines. Following the
French mathematician Henri Poincaré, Russell traced the type theory type theory
935 935 source of the semantic
paradoxes to a kind of illicit self-reference. So, for exple, in the liar
paradox, Epimenides ostensibly asserts a proposition p about all propositions,
p itself ong them, nely that they are false if asserted by him today. p thus
refers to itself in the sense that it – or more exactly, the sentence that
expresses it – quantifies over (i.e., refers generally to all or some of the
elements of) a collection of entities ong which p itself is included. The
source of semantic paradox thus isolated, Russell formulated the vicious circle
principle (VCP), which proscribes all such self-reference in properties and
propositions generally. The liar proposition p and its ilk were thus
effectively banished from the realm of legitimate propositions and so the
semantic paradoxes could not arise. Wedded to the restrictions of simple type
theory, the VCP generates a rified hierarchy based on a more complicated form
of typing. The key notion is that of an object’s order. The order of an
individual, like its type, is 0. However, the order of a property must exceed
the order not only of its possible arguments, as in simple type theory, but
also the orders of the things it quantifies over. Thus, type 1 properties like
x ^ is a philosopher and x ^ is as wise as all other philosophers are
first-order properties, since they are true of and, in the second instance,
quantify over, individuals only. Properties like these whose order exceeds the
order of their possible arguments by one are called predicative, and are of the
lowest possible order relative to their range of significance. Consider, by
contrast, the property (call it Q) x ^ has all the (first-order) properties of
a great philosopher. Like those above, Q also is a property of individuals.
However, since Q quantifies over first-order properties, by the VDP, it cannot
be counted ong them. Accordingly, in the rified hierarchy, Q is a second-order
property of individuals, and hence non-predicative (or impredicative). Like Q,
the property x ^ is a (first-order) property of all great philosophers is also
second-order, since its range of significance consists of objects of order 1
(and it quantifies only over objects of order 0); but since it is a property of
first-order properties, it is predicative. In like manner it is possible to
define third-order properties of individuals, third-order properties of
first-order properties, third-order properties of second-order properties of
individuals, third-order properties of secondorder properties of first-order
properties, and then, in the se fashion, fourth-order properties, fifth-order
properties, and so on ad infinitum. A serious shortcoming of rified type
theory, from Russell’s perspective, is that it is an inadequate foundation for
classical mathematics. The most prominent difficulty is that many classical
theorems appeal to definitions that, though consistent, violate the VCP. For
instance, a wellknown theorem of real analysis asserts that every bounded set
of real numbers has a least upper bound. In the rified theory, real numbers are
identified with certain predicative properties of rationals. Under such an
identification, the usual procedure is to define the least upper bound of a
bounded set S of reals to be the property (call it b) some real number in S is
true of x ^ , and then prove that this property is itself a real number with
the requisite characteristics. However, b quantifies over the real numbers.
Hence, by the VCP, b cannot itself be taken to be a real number: although of
the se type as the reals, and although true of the right things, b must be
assigned a higher order than the reals. So, contrary to the classical theorem,
S fails to have a least upper bound. Russell introduced a special axiom to
obviate this difficulty: the axiom of reducibility. Reducibility says, in
effect, that for any property P, there is a predicative property Q that is true
of exactly the se things as P. Reducibility thus assures that there is a
predicative property bH true of the se rational numbers as b. Since the reals
are predicative, hence of the se order as bH, it turns out that bH is a real
number, and hence that S has a least upper bound after all, as required by the
classical theorem. The general role of reducibility is thus to undo the
draconian mathematical effects of rification without undermining its capacity
to fend off the semantic paradoxes.
type–token distinction,
as drawn by Peirce, the contrast between a category and a member of that
category. An individual or token is said to exemplify a type; it possesses the
property that characterizes that type. In philosophy this distinction is often
applied to linguistic expressions and to mental states, but it can be applied
also to objects, events, properties, and states of affairs. Related to it are
the distinctions between type and token individuation and between qualitative
and numerical identity. Distinct tokens of the se type, such as two ants, may
be qualitatively identical but cannot be numerically identical. Irrespective of
the controversial metaphysical view that every individual has an essence, a
type type theory, rified type–token distinction 936 936 to which it belongs essentially, every
individual belongs to many types, although for a certain theoretical or
practical purpose it may belong to one particularly salient type (e.g., the
entomologist’s Formicidae or the picnicker’s buttinsky). The type–token
distinction as applied in the philosophy of language marks the difference
between linguistic expressions, such as words and sentences, which are the
subject of linguistics, and the products of acts of writing or speaking (the
subject of speech act theory). Confusing the two can lead to conflating matters
of speaker meaning withmatters of word or sentence meaning (as noted by Grice).
An expression is a linguistic type and can be used over and over, whereas a
token of a type can be produced only once, though of course it may be
reproduced (copied). A writer composes an essay (a type) and produces a
manuscript (a token), of which there might be many copies (more tokens). A
token of a type is not the se as an occurrence of a type. In the previous
sentence there are two occurrences of the word ‘type’; in each inscription of
that sentence, there are two tokens of that word. In philosophy of mind the
type–token distinction underlies the contrast between two forms of physicalism,
the type–type identity theory or type physicalism and the token–token identity
theory or token physicalism. ACTION
THEORY, PEIRCE, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. K.B. type-type identity.PHILOSOPHY OF MIND.
tzu jan, Chinese term meaning ‘naturally’, ‘spontaneity’, or ‘so-of-itself’. It
is a Taoist term of art describing the ideal state of agents and quality of
actions. A coordinate concept is wu wei (nonaction), particularly in the Tao Te
Ching. Taoists seek to eliminate the rational “human” perspective and return to
spontaneous “Heavenly” inclinations. Actions then will be unself-conscious, and
we and what we do will be tzu jan (spontaneous). Wang Ch’ung presents an early
critique of this Taoist notion in chapter 54 of his Lun Heng. Later thinkers
appropriate the term to support their own positions. For exple, Neo-Confucians
regard particular filial and social obligations as tzu jan, as are certain
virtuous inclinations. NEO-TAOISM,
TAOISM. P.J.I.
Ununo, Miguel de
(1864–1936), Spanish philosopher, scholar, and writer. Born in Bilbao, he
studied in Bilbao and Madrid and taught Greek and philosophy in Salanca. His
open criticism of the Spanish government led to dismissal from the university
and exile (1924–30) and, again, to dismissal from the rectorship in 1936. Ununo
is an important figure in Spanish letters. Like Ortega y Gasset, his aim was to
capture life in its complex emotional and intellectual dimensions rather than
to describe the world scientifically. Thus, he favored fiction as a medium for
his ideas and may be considered a precursor of existentialism. He wrote several
philosophically significant novels, a commentary on Don Quijote (1905), and
some poetry and dra; his philosophical ideas are most explicitly stated in Del
sentimiento trágico de la vida (“The Tragic Sense of Life,” 1913). Ununo
perceived a tragic sense permeating human life, a sense arising from our desire
for immortality and from the certainty of death. In this predicent man must
abandon all pretense of rationalism and embrace faith. Faith characterizes the
authentic life, while reason leads to despair, but faith can never completely
displace reason. Torn between the two, we can find hope only in faith; for
reason deals only with abstractions, while we are “flesh and bones” and can
find fulfillment only through commitment to an ideal. J.J.E.G. unary
quantifier.
unexpected exination
paradox, a paradox about belief and prediction. One version is as follows: It
seems that a teacher could both make, and act on, the following announcement to
his class: “Sometime during the next week I will set you an exination, but at
breakfast time on the day it will occur, you will have no good reason to expect
that it will occur on that day.” If he announces this on Friday, could he not
do what he said he would by, say, setting the exination on the following
Wednesday? The paradox is that there is an argument purporting to show that
there could not be an unexpected exination of this kind. For let us suppose
that the teacher will carry out his threat, in both its parts; i.e., he will
set an exination, and it will be unexpected. Then he cannot set the exination
on Friday (assuming this to be the last possible day of the week). For, by the
time Friday breakfast arrives, and we know that all the previous days have been
exination-free, we would have every reason to expect the exination to occur on
Friday. So leaving the exination until Friday is inconsistent with setting an
unexpected exination. For similar reasons, the exination cannot be held on
Thursday. Given our previous conclusion that it cannot be delayed until Friday,
we would know, when Thursday morning ce, and the previous days had been
exination-free, that it would have to be held on Thursday. So if it were held
on Thursday it would not be unexpected. So it cannot be held on Thursday.
Similar reasoning sup938 U 938 posedly
shows that there is no day of the week on which it can be held, and so
supposedly shows that the supposition that the teacher can carry out his threat
must be rejected. This is paradoxical, for it seems plain that the teacher can
carry out his threat. PARADOX. R.M.S.
unified science.UNITY OF SCIENCE.
uniformity of nature, a
state of affairs thought to be required if induction is to be justified. For
exple, inductively strong arguments, such as ‘The sun has risen every day in
the past; therefore, the sun will rise tomorrow’, are thought to presuppose
that nature is uniform in the sense that the future will resemble the past, in
this case with respect to the diurnal cycle. The Scottish empiricist Hume was
the first to make explicit that the uniformity of nature is a substantial
assumption in inductive reasoning. Hume argued that, because the belief that
the future will resemble the past cannot be grounded in experience – for the
future is as yet unobserved – induction cannot be rationally justified; appeal
to it in defense of induction is either question-begging or illicitly
metaphysical. Francis Bacon’s “induction by enumeration” and J. S. Mill’s “five
methods of experimental inquiry” presuppose that nature is uniform. Whewell
appealed to the uniformity of nature in order to account for the “consilience
of inductions,” the tendency of a hypothesis to explain data different from
those it was originally introduced to explain. For reasons similar to Hume’s,
Popper holds that our belief in the uniformity of nature is a matter of faith.
Reichenbach held that although this belief cannot be justified in advance of
any instance of inductive reasoning, its presupposition is vindicated by
successful inductions. It has proved difficult to formulate a philosophical
statement of the uniformity of nature that is both coherent and informative. It
appears contradictory to say that nature is uniform in all respects, because
inductive inferences always mark differences of some sort (e.g., from present
to future, from observed to unobserved, etc.), and it seems trivial to say that
nature is uniform in some respects, because any two states of nature, no matter
how different, will be similar in some respect. Not all observed regularities
in the world (or in data) are taken to support successful inductive reasoning;
not all uniformities are, to use Goodman’s term, “projectible.” Philosophers of
science have therefore proposed various rules of projectibility, involving such
notions as simplicity and explanatory power, in an attempt to distinguish those
observed patterns that support successful inductions (and thus are taken to
represent genuine causal relations) from those that are accidental or
spurious.
unity in diversity, in
aesthetics, the principle that the parts of the aesthetic object must cohere or
hang together while at the se time being different enough to allow for the
object to be complex. This principle defines an important formal requirement
used in judging aesthetic objects. If an object has insufficient unity (e.g., a
collection of color patches with no recognizable patterns of any sort), it is
chaotic or lacks harmony; it is more a collection than one object. But if it
has insufficient diversity (e.g., a canvas consisting entirely of one color
with no internal differentiations), it is monotonous. Thus, the formal pattern
desired in an aesthetic object is that of complex parts that differ
significantly from each other but fit together to form one interdependent whole
such that the character or meaning of the whole would be changed by the change
of any part.
AESTHETICS, ORGANIC.
J.A.K. unity of science, a situation in which all branches of empirical science
form a coherent system called unified science. Unified science is sometimes
extended to include formal sciences (e.g., branches of logic and mathematics).
‘Unity of science’ is also used to refer to a research progr aimed at unified
science. Interest in the unity of science has a long history with many roots,
including ancient atomism and the work of the French Encyclopedists. In the
twentieth century this interest was prominent in logical empiricism (see Otto
Neurath et al., International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, vol. I, 1938).
Logical empiricists originally conceived of unified science in terms of a
unified language of science, in particular, a universal observation language.
All laws and theoretical statements in any branch of science were to be
translatable into such an observation language, or else be appropriately
related to sentences of this language. In unified science unity of science 939 939 addition to encountering technical
difficulties with the observational–theoretical distinction, this conception of
unified science also leaves open the possibility that phenomena of one branch
may require special concepts and hypotheses that are explanatorily independent
of other branches. Another concept of unity of science requires that all
branches of science be combined by the intertheoretic reduction of the theories
of all non-basic branches to one basic theory (usually assumed to be some
future physics). These reductions may proceed stepwise; an oversimplified exple
would be reduction of psychology to biology, together with reductions of
biology to chemistry and chemistry to physics. The conditions for reducing
theory T2 to theory T1 are complex, but include identification of the ontology
of T2 with that of T1, along with explanation of the laws of T2 by laws of T1
together with appropriate connecting sentences. These conditions for reduction
can be supplemented with conditions for the unity of the basic theory, to
produce a general research progr for the unification of science (see Robert L.
Causey, Unity of Science, 1977). Adopting this research progr does not commit
one to the proposition that complete unification will ever be achieved; the
latter is primarily an empirical proposition. This progr has been criticized,
and some have argued that reductions are impossible for particular pairs of
theories, or that some branches of science are autonomous. For exple, some
writers have defended a view of autonomous biology, according to which
biological science is not reducible to the physical sciences. Vitalism
postulated non-physical attributes or vital forces that were supposed to be
present in living organisms. More recent neovitalistic positions avoid these postulates,
but attempt to give empirical reasons against the feasibility of reducing
biology. Other, sometimes a priori, arguments have been given against the
reducibility of psychology to physiology and of the social sciences to
psychology. These disputes indicate the continuing intellectual significance of
the idea of unity of science and the broad range of issues it encompasses.
universal instantiation,
also called universal quantifier elimination. (1) The argument form ‘Everything
is f; therefore a is f’, and arguments of this form. (2) The rule of inference
that permits one to infer that any given thing is f from the premise that
everything is f. In classical logic, where all terms are taken to denote things
in the domain of discourse, the rule says simply that from (v)A[v] one may
infer A[t], the result of replacing all free occurrences of v in A[v] by the
term t. If non-denoting terms are allowed, however, as in free logic, then the
rule would require an auxiliary premise of the form (Du)u % t to ensure that t
denotes something in the range of the variable v. Likewise in modal logic,
which is sometimes held to contain terms that do not denote “genuine
individuals” (the things over which variables range), an auxiliary premise may
be required. (3) In higher-order logic, the rule of inference that says that
from (X)A[X] one may infer A[F], where F is any expression of the grmatical
category (e.g., n-ary predicate) appropriate to that of X (e.g., n-ary
predicate variable).
universalizability. (1)
Since the 1920s, the moral criterion implicit in Kant’s first formulation of
the categorical imperative: “Act only on that maxim that you can at the se time
will to be a universal law,” often called the principle of universality. A
maxim or principle of action that satisfies this test is said to be
universalizable, hence morally acceptable; one that does not is said to be not
universalizable, hence contrary to duty. (2) A second sense developed in
connection with the work of Hare in the 1950s. For Hare, universalizability is
“common to all judgments which carry descriptive meaning”; so not only
normative claims (moral and evaluative judgments) but also empirical statements
are universalizable. Although Hare describes how such universalizuniversal
universalizability 940 940 ability can
figure in moral argument, for Hare “offenses against . . . universalizability
are logical, not moral.” Consequently, whereas for Kant not all maxims are
universalizable, on Hare’s view they all are, since they all have descriptive
meaning. (3) In a third sense, one that also appears in Hare,
‘universalizability’ refers to the principle of universalizability: “What is
right (or wrong) for one person is right (or wrong) for any similar person in
similar circumstances.” This principle is identical with what Sidgwick (The
Methods of Ethics) called the Principle of Justice. In Generalization in Ethics
(1961) by M. G. Singer (b.1926), it is called the Generalization Principle and
is said to be the formal principle presupposed in all moral reasoning and
consequently the explanation for the feature alleged to hold of all moral
judgments, that of being generalizable. A particular judgment of the form ‘A is
right in doing x’ is said to imply that anyone relevantly similar to A would be
right in doing any act of the kind x in relevantly similar circumstances. The
characteristic of generalizability, of presupposing a general rule, was said to
be true of normative claims, but not of all empirical or descriptive
statements. The Generalization Principle (GP) was said to be involved in the
Generalization Argument (GA): “If the consequences of everyone’s doing x would
be undesirable, while the consequences of no one’s doing x would not be, then
no one ought to do x without a justifying reason,” a form of moral reasoning
resembling, though not identical with, the categorical imperative (CI). One
alleged resemblance is that if the GP is involved in the GP, then it is
involved in the CI, and this would help explain the moral relevance of Kant’s
universalizability test. (4) A further extension of the term
‘universalizability’ appears in Alan Gewirth’s Reason and Morality (1978).
Gewirth formulates “the logical principle of universalizability”: “if some
predicate P belongs to some subject S because S has the property Q . . . then P
must also belong to all other subjects S1, S2, . . . , Sn that have Q.” The
principle of universalizability “in its moral application” is then deduced from
the logical principle of universalizability, and is presupposed in Gewirth’s
Principle of Generic Consistency, “Act in accord with the generic rights of
your recipients as well as yourself,” which is taken to provide an a priori
determinate way of determining relevant similarities and differences, hence of
applying the principle of universalizability. The principle of
universalizability is a formal principle; universalizability in sense (1),
however, is intended to be a substantive principle of morality.
universe of discourse,
the usually limited class of individuals under discussion, whose existence is
presupposed by the discussants, and which in some sense constitutes the
ultimate subject matter of the discussion. Once the universe of a discourse has
been established, expressions such as ‘every object’ and ‘some object’ refer
respectively to every object or to some object in the universe of discourse.
The concept of universe of discourse is due to De Morgan in 1846, but the
expression was coined by Boole eight years later. When a discussion is
formalized in an interpreted standard first-order language, the universe of
discourse is taken as the “universe” of the interpretation, i.e., as the range
of values of the variables. Quine and others have emphasized that the universe
of discourse represents an ontological commitment of the discussants. In a
discussion in a particular science, the universe of discourse is often wider
than the domain of the science, although economies of expression can be
achieved by limiting the universe of discourse to the domain.
Upanishads, a group of
ancient Hindu philosophical texts, or the esoteric sacred doctrines contained
in them. ‘Upanishad’ includes the notion of the student “sitting near” the
guru. In the eighth century A.D., Shankara identified certain Upanishads as the
official source of Vedanta teachings: Aitreya, Brhadaranyaka, Chandogya, Isa,
Katha, Kaufitaki, Kena, Maitri, Mupdaka, Prasna, Svetasvatara, and Taittiriya.
These are the classic universalizability, principle of Upanishads 941 941 Upanishads; together with the Vedanta
Sutras, they constitute the doctrinally authoritative sources for Vedanta. The
Vedanta Sutras are a series of aphorisms, composed somewhere between 200 B.C.
and A.D. 200, attributed to Badarayana. Practically unintelligible without
commentary, these sutras are interpreted in one way by Shankara, in another by
Ranuja, and in a third way by Madhva (though Madhva’s reading is closer to
Ranuja’s than to Shankara’s). For Vedanta, the Upanishads are “the end of the
Vedas,” both in the sense of completing the transcript of the immutable source
of truth and articulating the foundational wisdom that the Vedas presuppose.
While the Upanishads agree on the importance of religious knowledge, on the
priority of religious over other sorts of wellbeing, and on the necessity of
religious discipline, they contain radically disparate cosmologies that differ
regarding agent, modality, and product of the creative process and offer
various notions of Brahman and Atman.
use–mention distinction,
two ways in which terms enter into discourse – used when they refer to or
assert something, mentioned when they are exhibited for consideration of their
properties as terms. If I say, “Mary is sad,” I use the ne ‘Mary’ to refer to
Mary so that I can predicate of her the property of being sad. But if I say, “
‘Mary’ contains four letters,” I
mentioning Mary’s ne, exhibiting it in writing or speech to predicate of
that term the property of being spelled with four letters. In the first case,
the sentence occurs in what Carnap refers to as the material mode; in the
second, it occurs in the formal mode, and hence in a metalanguage (a language
used to talk about another language). Single quotation marks or similar
orthographic devices are conventionally used to disbiguate mentioned from used
terms. The distinction is important because there are fallacies of reasoning
based on use–mention confusions in the failure to observe the use– mention
distinction, especially when the referents of terms are themselves linguistic
entities. Consider the inference: (1) Some sentences are written in English.
(2) Some sentences are written in English. Here it looks as though the argument
offers a counterexple to the claim that all arguments of the form ‘P, therefore
P’ are circular. But either (1) asserts that some sentences are written in
English, or it provides evidence in support of the conclusion in (2) by
exhibiting a sentence written in English. In the first case, the sentence is
used to assert the se truth in the premise as expressed in the conclusion, so
that the argument remains circular. In the second case, the sentence is
mentioned, and although the argument so interpreted is not circular, it is no
longer strictly of the form ‘P, therefore P’, but has the significantly
different form, ‘ “P” is a sentence written in English, therefore P’.
utilitarianism, the moral theory that an
action is morally right if and only if it produces at least as much good
(utility) for all people affected by the action as any alternative action the
person could do instead. Its best-known proponent is J. S. Mill, who formulated
the greatest happiness principle (also called the principle of utility): always
act so as to produce the greatest happiness. Two kinds of issues have been
central in debates about whether utilitarianism is an adequate or true moral
theory: first, whether and how utilitarianism can be clearly and precisely
formulated and applied; second, whether the moral implications of
utilitarianism in particular cases are acceptable, or instead constitute
objections to it. Issues of formulation. A central issue of formulation is how
utility is to be defined and whether it can be measured in the way
utilitarianism requires. Early utilitarians often held some form of hedonism,
according to which only pleasure and the absence of pain have utility or
intrinsic value. For something to have intrinsic value is for it to be valuable
for its own sake and apart from its consequences or its relations to other
things. Something has instrumental value, on the other hand, provided it brings
about what has intrinsic value. Most utilitarians have held that hedonism is
too narrow an account of utility because there are many things that people
value intrinsically besides pleasure. Some nonhedonists define utility as
happiness, and ong them there is considerable debate about the proper account
of happiness. Happiness has also been criticized as too narrow to exhaust
utility or intrinsic value; e.g., many people value accomplishments, not just
the happiness that may use–mention distinction utilitarianism 942 942 accompany them. Sometimes utilitarianism
is understood as the view that either pleasure or happiness has utility, while
consequentialism is understood as the broader view that morally right action is
action that maximizes the good, however the good is understood. Here, we take
utilitarianism in this broader interpretation that some philosophers reserve
for consequentialism. Most utilitarians who believe hedonism gives too narrow
an account of utility have held that utility is the satisfaction of people’s
informed preferences or desires. This view is neutral about what people desire,
and so can account for the full variety of things and experiences that
different people in fact desire or value. Finally, ideal utilitarians have held
that some things or experiences, e.g. knowledge or being autonomous, are
intrinsically valuable or good whether or not people value or prefer them or
are happier with them. Whatever account of utility a utilitarian adopts, it
must be possible to quantify or measure the good effects or consequences of
actions in order to apply the utilitarian standard of moral rightness.
Happiness utilitarianism, e.g., must calculate whether a particular action, or
instead some possible alternative, would produce more happiness for a given person;
this is called the intrapersonal utility comparison. The method of measurement
may allow cardinal utility measurements, in which numerical units of happiness
may be assigned to different actions (e.g., 30 units for Jones expected from
action a, 25 units for Jones from alternative action b), or only ordinal
utility measurements may be possible, in which actions are ranked only as
producing more or less happiness than alternative actions. Since nearly all
interesting and difficult moral problems involve the happiness of more than one
person, utilitarianism requires calculating which ong alternative actions
produces the greatest happiness for all people affected; this is called the
interpersonal utility comparison. Many ordinary judgments about personal action
or public policy implicitly rely on interpersonal utility comparisons; e.g.,
would a fily whose members disagree be happiest overall taking its vacation at
the seashore or in the mountains? Some critics of utilitarianism doubt that it
is possible to make interpersonal utility comparisons. Another issue of
formulation is whether the utilitarian principle should be applied to
individual actions or to some form of moral rule. According to act
utilitarianism, each action’s rightness or wrongness depends on the utility it
produces in comparison with possible alternatives. Even act utilitarians agree,
however, that rules of thumb like ‘keep your promises’ can be used for the most
part in practice because following them tends to maximize utility. According to
rule utilitarianism, on the other hand, individual actions are evaluated, in
theory not just in practice, by whether they conform to a justified moral rule,
and the utilitarian standard is applied only to general rules. Some rule
utilitarians hold that actions are right provided they are permitted by rules
the general acceptance of which would maximize utility in the agent’s society,
and wrong only if they would be prohibited by such rules. There are a number of
forms of rule utilitarianism, and utilitarians disagree about whether act or
rule utilitarianism is correct. Moral implications. Most debate about
utilitarianism has focused on its moral implications. Critics have argued that
its implications sharply conflict with most people’s considered moral judgments,
and that this is a strong reason to reject utilitarianism. Proponents have
argued both that many of these conflicts disappear on a proper understanding of
utilitarianism and that the remaining conflicts should throw the particular
judgments, not utilitarianism, into doubt. One important controversy concerns
utilitarianism’s implications for distributive justice. Utilitarianism
requires, in individual actions and in public policy, maximizing utility
without regard to its distribution between different persons. Thus, it seems to
ignore individual rights, whether specific individuals morally deserve
particular benefits or burdens, and potentially to endorse great inequalities
between persons; e.g., some critics have charged that according to utilitarianism
slavery would be morally justified if its benefits to the slaveowners
sufficiently outweighed the burdens to the slaves and if it produced more
overall utility than alternative practices possible in that society. Defenders
of utilitarianism typically argue that in the real world there is virtually
always a better alternative than the action or practice that the critic charges
utilitarianism wrongly supports; e.g., no system of slavery that has ever
existed is plausibly thought to have maximized utility for the society in
question. Defenders of utilitarianism also typically try to show that it does
take account of the moral consideration the critic claims it wrongly ignores;
for instance, utilitarians commonly appeal to the declining marginal utility of
money – equal marginal increments of money tend to produce less utility (e.g.
happiness) for persons, the more money they already utilitarianism
utilitarianism have – as giving some support to equality in income
distribution. Another source of controversy concerns whether moral principles
should be agent-neutral or, in at least some cases, agent-relative.
Utilitarianism is agent-neutral in that it gives all people the se moral aim –
act so as to maximize utility for everyone – whereas agent-relative principles
give different moral aims to different individuals. Defenders of agent-relative
principles note that a commonly accepted moral rule like the prohibition of
killing the innocent is understood as telling each agent that he or she must
not kill, even if doing so is the only way to prevent a still greater number of
killings by others. In this way, a non-utilitarian, agent-relative prohibition
reflects the common moral view that each person bears special moral
responsibility for what he or she does, which is greater than his or her
responsibility to prevent similar wrong actions by others. Common moral beliefs
also permit people to give special weight to their own projects and commitments
and, e.g., to favor to some extent their own children at the expense of other
children in greater need; agent-relative responsibilities to one’s own fily
reflect these moral views in a way that agent-neutral utilitarian
responsibilities apparently do not. The debate over neutrality and relativity
is related to a final area of controversy about utilitarianism. Critics charge
that utilitarianism makes morality far too demanding by requiring that one
always act to maximize utility. If, e.g., one reads a book or goes to a movie,
one could nearly always be using one’s time and resources to do more good by
aiding fine relief. The critics believe that this wrongly makes morally
required what should be only supererogatory – action that is good, but goes
beyond “the call of duty” and is not morally required. Here, utilitarians have
often argued that ordinary moral views are seriously mistaken and that morality
can demand greater sacrifices of one’s own interests for the benefit of others
than is commonly believed. There is little doubt that here, and in many other
cases, utilitarianism’s moral implications significantly conflict with
commonsense moral beliefs – the dispute is whether this should count against
commonsense moral beliefs or against utilitarianism.
vagueness, a property of
an expression in virtue of which it can give rise to a “borderline case.” A
borderline case is a situation in which the application of a particular
expression to a (ne of) a particular object does not generate an expression
with a definite truth-value; i.e., the piece of language in question neither
unequivocally applies to the object nor fails to apply. Although such a
formulation leaves it open what the pieces of language might be (whole
sentences, individual words, nes or singular terms, predicates or general
terms), most discussions have focused on vague general terms and have
considered other types of terms to be nonvague. (Exceptions to this have called
attention to the possibility of vague objects, thereby rendering vague the
designation relation for singular terms.) The formulation also leaves open the possible
causes for the expression’s lacking a definite truth-value. If this
indeterminacy is due to there being insufficient information available to
determine applicability or non-applicability of the term (i.e., we are
convinced the term either does or does not apply, but we just do not have
enough information to determine which), then this is sometimes called epistemic
vagueness. It is somewhat misleading to call this vagueness, for unlike true
vagueness, this epistemic vagueness disappears if more information is brought
into the situation. (‘There are between 1.89 $ 106 and 1.9 $ 106 stars in the
sky’ is epistemically vague but is not vague in the generally accepted sense of
the term.) ’Vagueness’ may also be used to characterize non-linguistic items such
as concepts, memories, and objects, as well as such semilinguistic items as
statements and propositions. Many of the issues involved in discussing the
topic of vagueness impinge upon other philosophical topics, such as the
existence of truth-value gaps – (declarative sentences that are neither true
nor false) – and the plausibility of many-valued logic. There are other related
issues such as the nature of propositions and whether they must be either true
or false. We focus here on linguistic vagueness, as it manifests itself with
general terms; for it is this sort of indeterminacy that defines what most
researchers call vagueness, and which has led the push in some schools of
thought to “eliminate vagueness” or to construct languages that do not manifest
vagueness. Linguistic vagueness is sometimes confused with other linguistic
phenomena: generality, biguity, and open texture. Statements can be general
(‘Some wheelbarrows are red’, ‘All insects have antennae’) and if there is no
other vagueness infecting them, they are true or false – and not borderline or
vague. Terms can be general (‘person’, ‘dog’) without being vague. Those
general terms apply to many different objects but are not therefore vague; and
furthermore, the fact that they apply to different kinds of objects (‘person’
applies to both men and women) also does not show them to be vague or biguous.
A vague term admits of borderline cases – a completely determinate situation in
which there just is no correct answer as to whether the term applies to a
certain object or not – and this is not the case with generality. biguous
linguistic items, including structurally biguous sentences, also do not have
this feature (unless they also contain vague terms). Rather, an biguous
sentence allows there to be a completely determinate situation in which one can
simultaneously correctly affirm the sentence and also deny the sentence,
depending on which of the claims allowed by the biguities is being affirmed or
denied. Terms are considered open-textured if they are precise along some
dimensions of their meaning but where other possible dimensions simply have not
been considered. It would therefore not be clear what the applicability of the
term would be were objects to vary along these other dimensions. Although related
to vagueness, open texture is a different notion. Friedrich Waismann, who
coined the term, put it this way: “Open texture . . . is something like the
possibility of vagueness.” Vagueness has long been an irritant to philosophers
of logic and language. ong the oldest of the puzzles associated with vagueness
is the sorites (‘heap’) paradox reported by Cicero (Academica 93): One grain of
sand does not make a heap, and adding a grain of sand to something that is not
a heap will not create a heap; there945 V
945 fore there are no heaps. This type of paradox is traditionally
attributed to Zeno of Elea, who said that a single millet seed makes no sound
when it falls, so a basket of millet seeds cannot make a sound when it is
dumped. The term ‘sorites’ is also applied to the entire series of paradoxes
that have this form, such as the falakros (‘bald man’, Diogenes Laertius,
Grmatica II, 1, 45): A man with no hairs is bald, and adding one hair to a bald
man results in a bald man; therefore all men are bald. The original version of
these sorites paradoxes is attributed to Eubulides (Diogenes Laertius II, 108):
“Isn’t it true that two are few? and also three, and also four, and so on until
ten? But since two are few, ten are also few.” The linchpin in all these paradoxes
is the analysis of vagueness in terms of some underlying continuum along which
an imperceptible or unimportant change occurs. Almost all modern accounts of
the logic of vagueness have assumed this to be the correct analysis of
vagueness, and have geared their logics to deal with such vagueness. But we
will see below that there are other kinds of vagueness too. The search for a
solution to the sorites-type paradoxes has been the stimulus for much research
into alternative semantics. Some philosophers, e.g. Frege, view vagueness as a
pervasive defect of natural language and urge the adoption of an artificial
language in which each predicate is completely precise, without borderline
cases. Russell too thought vagueness thoroughly infected natural language, but
thought it unavoidable – and indeed beneficial – for ordinary usage and
discourse. Despite the occasional argument that vagueness is pragmatic rather
than a semantic phenomenon, the attitude that vagueness is inextricably bound
to natural language (together with the philosophical logician’s self-ascribed
task of formalizing natural language semantics) has led modern writers to the
exploration of alternative logics that might adequately characterize vagueness
– i.e., that would account for our pretheoretic beliefs concerning truth,
falsity, necessary truth, validity, etc., of sentences containing vague
predicates. Some recent writers have also argued that vague language undermines
realism, and that it shows our concepts to be “incoherent.” Long ago it was
seen that the attempt to introduce a third truth-value, indeterminate, solved
nothing – replacing, as it were, the sharp cutoff between a predicate’s
applying and not applying with two sharp cutoffs. Similar remarks could be made
against the adoption of any finitely manyvalued logic as a characterization of
vagueness. In the late 1960s and early 1970s, fuzzy logic was introduced into
the philosophic world. Actually a restatement of the Tarski-Lukasiewicz
infinitevalued logics of the 1930s, one of the side benefits of fuzzy logics
was claimed to be an adequate logic for vagueness. In contrast to classical
logic, in which there are two truth-values (true and false), in fuzzy logic a
sentence is allowed to take any real number between 0 and 1 as a truthvalue.
Intuitively, the closer to 1 the value is, the “more true” the sentence is. The
value of a negated sentence is 1 minus the value of the unnegated sentence;
conjuction is viewed as a minimum function and disjunction as a maximum
function. (Thus, a conjunction takes the value of the “least true” conjunct,
while a disjunction takes the value of the “most true” disjunct.) Since vague
sentences are maximally neither true nor false, they will be valued at
approximately 0.5. It follows that if F is maximally vague, so is the negation
-F; and so are the conjunction (F & -F) and the disjunction (~F 7 -F). Some
theorists object to these results, but defenders of fuzzy logic have argued in
favor of them. Other theorists have attempted to capture the elusive logic of
vagueness by employing modal logic, having the operators AF (meaning ‘F is
definite’) and B F (meaning ‘F is vague’). The logic generated in this way is
peculiar in that A (F & Y)P(AF & AY) is not a theorem. E.g., (p &
-p) is definitely false, hence definite; hence A (p & -p). Yet neither p
nor -p need be definite. (Technically, it is a non-Kripke-normal modal logic.)
Some other peculiarities are that (AF Q A -F) is a theorem, and that (AFPBF) is
not. There are also puzzles about whether ((B FP ABF) should be a theorem, and
about iterated modalities in general. Modal logic treatments of vagueness have
not attracted many advocates, except as a portion of a general epistemic logic
(i.e., modal logics might be seen as an account of so-called epistemic vagueness).
A third direction that has been advocated as a logical account of vagueness has
been the method of supervaluations (sometimes called “supertruth”). The
underlying idea here is to allow the vague predicate in a sentence to be
“precisified” in an arbitrary manner. Thus, for the sentence ‘Friar Tuck is
bald’, we arbitrarily choose a precise number of hairs on the head that will
demarcate the bald/not-bald border. In this valuation Friar Tuck is either
definitely bald or definitely not bald, and the sentence either is true or is
false. Next, we alter the valuation so that there is some other bald/not-bald
bordervagueness vagueness 946 946 line,
etc. A sentence true in all such valuations is deemed “really true” or “supertrue”;
one false in all such valuations is “really false” or “superfalse.” All others
are vague. Note that, in this conception of vagueness, if F is vague, so is -F.
However, unlike fuzzy logic ‘F & -F’ is not evaluated as vague – it is
false in every valuation and hence is superfalse. And ‘F 7 -F’ is supertrue.
These are seen by some as positive features of the method of supervaluations,
and as an argument against the whole fuzzy logic enterprise. In fact there seem
to be at least two distinct types of (linguistic) vagueness, and it is not at
all clear that any of the previously mentioned logic approaches can deal with
both. Without going into the details, we can just point out that the “sorites
vagueness” discussed above presumes an ordering on a continuous underlying
scale; and it is the indistinguishability of adjacent points on this scale that
gives rise to borderline cases. But there are exples of vague terms for which
there is no such scale. A classic exple is ‘religion’: there are a number of
factors relevant to determining whether a social practice is a religion. Having
none of these properties guarantees failing to be a religion, and having all of
them guarantees being one. However, there is no continuum of the sorites
variety here; for exple, it is easy to distinguish possessing four from
possessing five of the properties, unlike the sorites case where such a change
is imperceptible. In the present type of vagueness, although we can tell these
different cases apart, we just do not know whether to call the practice a
religion or not. Furthermore, some of the properties (or combinations of
properties) are more important or salient in determining whether the practice
is a religion than are other properties or combinations. We might call this
fily resemblance vagueness: there are a number of clearly distinguishable
conditions of varying degrees of importance, and fily resemblance vagueness is
attributed to there being no definite answer to the question, How many of which
conditions are necessary for the term to apply? Other exples of fily resemblance
vagueness are ‘schizophrenia sufferer’, ‘sexual perversion’, and the venerable
‘ge’. A special subclass of fily resemblance vagueness occurs when there are
pairs of underlying properties that normally co-occur, but occasionally apply
to different objects. Consider, e.g., ‘tributary’. When two rivers meet, one is
usually considered a tributary of the other. ong the properties relevant to
being a tributary rather than the main river are: relative volume of water and
relative length. Normally, the shorter of the two rivers has a lesser volume,
and in that case it is the tributary of the other. But occasionally the two
properties do not co-occur and then there is a conflict, giving rise to a kind
of vagueness we might call conflict vagueness. The term ‘tributary’ is vague
because its background conditions admit of such conflicts: there are borderline
cases when these two properties apply to different objects. To conclude: the
fundental philosophical problems involving vagueness are (1) to give an adequate
characterization of what the phenomenon is, and (2) to characterize our ability
to reason with these terms. These were the problems for the ancient
philosophers, and they remain the problems for modern philosophers.
Vaihinger, philosopher
best known for Die Philosophie des Als Ob (1911; translated by C. K. Ogden as
The Philosophy of “As If” in 1924). A neo-Kantian, he was also influenced by
Schopenhauer and Nietzsche. His commentary on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason (2
vols., 1881) is still a standard work. Vaihinger was a cofounder of both the
Kant Society and Kant-Studien. The “philosophy of the as if” involves the claim
that values and ideals ount only to “fictions” that serve “life” even if they
are irrational. We must act “as if” they were true because they have biological
utility. M.K. Vair, Guillaume du.DU VAIR.
Valentinianism, a form of
Christian gnosticism of Alexandrian origin, founded by Valentinus in the second
century and propagated by Theodotus in Eastern, and Heracleon in Western, Christianity.
To every gnostic, pagan or Christian, knowledge leads to salvation from the
perishable, material world. Valentinianism therefore prompted fous refutations
by Tertullian (Adversus Valentinianos) and Irenaeus (Adversus haereses). The
latter accused the Valentinians of maintaining “creatio ex nihilo.” Valentinus
is believed to have authored the Peri trion phuseon, the Evangelium veritatis,
and the Treatise on the Resurrection. Since only a few fragments of these
remain, his Neoplatonic cosmogony is accessible mainly through his opponents
and critics (Hippolytus, Clement of Alexandria) and in the Nag Hmadi codices.
To explain the origins of creation and of evil, Valentinus separated God
(primal Father) from the Creator (Demiurge) and attributed the cruVaihinger,
Hans Valentinianism 947 947 cial role
in the processes of emanation and redemption to Sophia.
Valentinus (A.D. 100–65),
Christian gnostic teacher. He was born in Alexandria, where he taught until he
moved to Rome in 135. A dualist, he constructed an elaborate cosmology in which
God the Father (Bythos, or Deep Unknown) unites the the feminine Silence (Sige)
and in the overflow of love produces thirty successive divine emanations (or
aeons) constituting the Pleroma (fullness of the Godhead). Each emanation is
arranged hierarchically with a graded existence, becoming progressively further
removed from the Father and hence less divine. The lowest emanation, Sophia
(wisdom), yields to passion and seeks to reach, beyond her ability, to the
Father, which causes her fall. In the process, she causes the creation of the
material universe (wherein resides evil) and the loss of divine sparks from the
Pleroma. The divine elements are embodied in those humans who are the elect.
Jesus Christ is an aeon close to the Father and is sent to retrieve the souls
into the heavenly Pleroma. Valentinus wrote a gospel. His sect stood out in the
early church for ordaining women priests and prophetesses.
valid, having the
property that a well-formed formula, argument, argument form, or rule of
inference has when it is logically correct in a certain respect. A well-formed
formula is valid if it is true under every admissible reinterpretation of its
non-logical symbols. (If truth-value gaps or multiple truth-values are allowed,
‘true’ here might be replaced by ‘non-false’ or takes a “designated”
truth-value.) An argument is valid if it is impossible for the premises all to
be true and, at the se time, the conclusion false. An argument form (schema) is
valid if every argument of that form is valid. A rule of inference is valid if
it cannot lead from all true premises to a false conclusion.
Valla, Lorenzo
(c.1407–57), Italian humanist and historian who taught rhetoric in Pavia and
was later secretary of King Alfonso I of Aragona in Naples, and apostolic
secretary in Rome under Pope Nicholas V. In his dialogue On Pleasure or On the
True Good (1431–34), Stoic and Epicurean interlocutors present their ethical
views, which Valla proceeds to criticize from a Christian point of view. This
work is often regarded as a defense of Epicurean hedonism, because Valla
equates the good with pleasure; but he claims that Christians can find pleasure
only in heaven. His description of the Christian pleasures reflects the
contemporary Renaissance attitude toward the joys of life and might have
contributed to Valla’s reputation for hedonism. In the later work, On Free Will
(between 1435 and 1448), Valla discusses the conflict between divine
foreknowledge and human freedom and rejects Boethius’s then predominantly
accepted solution. Valla distinguishes between God’s knowledge and God’s will,
but denies that there is a rational solution of the apparent conflict between
God’s will and human freedom. As a historian, he is fous for The Donation of
Constantine (1440), which denounces as spurious the fous document on which
medieval jurists and theologians based the papal rights to secular power.
value, the worth of
something. Philosophers have discerned these main forms: intrinsic,
instrumental, inherent, and relational value. Intrinsic value may be taken as
basic and many of the others defined in terms of it. ong the many attempts to
explicate the concept of intrinsic value, some deal primarily with the source
of value, while others employ the concept of the “fittingness” or
“appropriateness” to it of certain kinds of emotions and desires. The first is
favored by Moore and the second by Brentano. Proponents of the first view hold
that the intrinsic value of X is the value that X has solely in virtue of its intrinsic
nature. Thus, the state of affairs, Smith’s experiencing pleasure, has
intrinsic value provided it has value solely in virtue of its intrinsic nature.
Followers of the second approach explicate intrinsic value in terms of the
sorts of emotions and desires appropriate to a thing “in and for itself” (or
“for its own sake”). Thus, one might say X has intrinsic value (or is
intrinsically good) if and only if X is worthy of desire in and for itself, or,
alternatively, it is fitting or appropriate for anyone to favor X in and for
itself. Thus, the state of affairs of Smith’s experiencing pleasure is
intrinsically valuable provided that state of affairs is worthy of desire for
its own sake, or it is fitting for anyone to favor that state of affairs in and
for itself. Concerning the other forms of value, we may say that X has
instrumental value if and only if it is a means to, or causally contributes to,
something that is intrinsically valuable. If Smith’s experiencing pleasure is
intrinsically valuable and his taking a warm bath is a means to, or Valentinus
value 948 948 causally contributes to,
his being pleased, then his taking a warm bath is instrumentally valuable or
“valuable as a means.” Similarly, if health is intrinsically valuable and
exercise is a means to health, then exercise is instrumentally valuable. X has
inherent value if and only if the experience, awareness, or contemplation of X
is intrinsically valuable. If the experience of a beautiful sunset is
intrinsically valuable, then the beautiful sunset has inherent value. X has
contributory value if and only if X contributes to the value of some whole, W,
of which it is a part. If W is a whole that consists of the facts that Smith is
pleased and Brown is pleased, then the fact that Smith is pleased contributes
to the value of W, and Smith’s being pleased has contributory value. Our exple
illustrates that something can have contributory value without having
instrumental value, for the fact that Smith is pleased is not a means to W and,
strictly speaking, it does not bring about or causally contribute to W. Given
the distinction between instrumental and contributory value, we may say that
certain sorts of experiences and activities can have contributory value if they
are part of an intrinsically valuable life and contribute to its value, even
though they are not means to it. Finally, we may say that X has relational
value if and only if X has value in virtue of bearing some relation to
something else. Instrumental, inherent, and contributory value may be construed
as forms of relational value. But there are other forms of relational value one
might accept, e.g. one might hold that X is valuable for S in virtue of being
desired by S or being such that S would desire X were S “fully informed” and
“rational.” Some philosophers defend the organicity of intrinsic value. Moore,
for exple, held that the intrinsic value of a whole is not necessarily equal to
the sum of the intrinsic values of its parts. According to this view, the
presence of an intrinsically good part might lower the intrinsic value of a
whole of which it is a part and the presence of an intrinsically bad part might
raise the intrinsic value of a whole to which it belongs. Defenders of
organicity sometimes point to exples of Mitfreude (taking joy or pleasure in
another’s joy) and Schadenfreude (taking joy or pleasure in another’s
suffering) to illustrate their view. Suppose Jones believes incorrectly that
Smith is happy and Brown believes incorrectly that Gray is suffering, but Jones
is pleased that Smith is happy and Brown is pleased that Gray is suffering. The
former instance of Mitfreude seems intrinsically better than the latter
instance of Schadenfreude even though they are both instances of pleasure and
neither whole has an intrinsically bad part. The value of each whole is not a
“mere sum” of the values of its parts.
ETHICS, HEDONISM, MOORE, PROPERTY, UTILITARIANISM, VALUE THEORY. N.M.L.
value, cognitive.FREGE. value, contributive.VALUE. value, inherent.VALUE.
value theory, also called
axiology, the branch of philosophy concerned with the nature of value and with
what kinds of things have value. Construed very broadly, value theory is
concerned with all forms of value, such as the aesthetic values of beauty and
ugliness, the ethical values of right, wrong, obligation, virtue, and vice, and
the epistemic values of justification and lack of justification. Understood
more narrowly, value theory is concerned with what is intrinsically valuable or
ultimately worthwhile and desirable for its own sake and with the related
concepts of instrumental, inherent, and contributive value. When construed very
broadly, the study of ethics may be taken as a branch of value theory, but
understood more narrowly value theory may be taken as a branch of ethics. In
its more narrow form, one of the chief questions of the theory of value is,
What is desirable for its own sake? One traditional sort of answer is hedonism.
Hedonism is roughly the view that (i) the only intrinsically good experiences
or states of affairs are those containing pleasure, and the only instrinsically
bad experiences or states of affairs are those containing pain; (ii) all
experiences or states of affairs that contain more pleasure than pain are
intrinsically good and all experiences or states of affairs that contain more
pain than pleasure are intrinsically bad; and (iii) any experience or state of
affairs that is intrinsically good is so in virtue of being pleasant or
containing pleasure and any experience or state of affairs that is intrinsically
bad is so in virtue of being painful or involving pain. Hedonism has value,
cognitive value theory 949 949 been
defended by philosophers such as Epicurus, Benth, Sidgwick, and, with
significant qualifications, J. S. Mill. Other philosophers, such as C. I.
Lewis, and, perhaps, Brand Blanshard, have held that what is intrinsically or
ultimately desirable are experiences that exhibit “satisfactoriness,” where
being pleasant is but one form of being satisfying. Other philosophers have
recognized a plurality of things other than pleasure or satisfaction as having
intrinsic value. ong the value pluralists are Moore, Rashdall, Ross, Brentano,
Hartmann, and Scheler. In addition to certain kinds of pleasures, these
thinkers count some or all of the following as intrinsically good:
consciousness and the flourishing of life, knowledge and insight, moral virtue
and virtuous actions, friendship and mutual affection, beauty and aesthetic
experience, a just distribution of goods, and self-expression. Many, if not all,
of the philosophers mentioned above distinguish between what has value or is
desirable for its own sake and what is instrumentally valuable. Furthermore,
they hold that what is desirable for its own sake or intrinsically good has a
value not dependent on anyone’s having an interest in it. Both of these claims
have been challenged by other value theorists. Dewey, for exple, criticizes any
sharp distinction between what is intrinsically good or good as an end and what
is good as a means on the ground that we adopt and abandon ends to the extent
that they serve as means to the resolution of conflicting impulses and desires.
Perry denies that anything can have value without being an object of interest.
Indeed, Perry claims that ‘X is valuable’ means ‘Interest is taken in X’ and
that it is a subject’s interest in a thing that confers value on it. Insofar as
he holds that the value of a thing is dependent upon a subject’s interest in
that thing, Perry’s value theory is a subjective theory and contrasts sharply with
objective theories holding that some things have value not dependent on a
subject’s interests or attitudes. Some philosophers, dissatisfied with the view
that value depends on a subject’s actual interests and theories, have proposed
various alternatives, including theories holding that the value of a thing
depends on what a subject would desire or have an interest in if he were fully
rational or if desires were based on full information. Such theories may be
called “counterfactual” desire theories since they take value to be dependent,
not upon a subject’s actual interests, but upon what a subject would desire if
certain conditions, which do not obtain, were to obtain. Value theory is also
concerned with the nature of value. Some philosophers have denied that
sentences of the forms ‘X is good’ or ‘X is intrinsically good’ are, strictly
speaking, either true or false. As with other forms of ethical discourse, they
claim that anyone who utters these sentences is either expressing his emotional
attitudes or else prescribing or commending something. Other philosophers hold
that such sentences can express what is true or false, but disagree about the
nature of value and the meaning of value terms like ‘good’, ‘bad’, and
‘better’. Some philosophers, such as Moore, hold that in a truth of the form ‘X
is intrinsically good’, ‘good’ refers to a simple, unanalyzable, non-natural
property, a property not identical with or analyzable by any “natural” property
such as being pleasant or being desired. Moore’s view is one form of
non-naturalism. Other philosophers, such as Brentano, hold that ‘good’ is a
syncategorematic expression; as such it does not refer to a property or
relation at all, though it contributes to the meaning of the sentence. Still
other philosophers have held that ‘X is good’ and ‘X is intrinsically good’ can
be analyzed in natural or non-ethical terms. This sort of naturalism about
value is illustrated by Perry, who holds that ‘X is valuable’ means ‘X is an
object of interest’. The history of value theory is full of other attempted
naturalistic analyses, some of which identify or analyze ‘good’ in terms of
pleasure or being the object of rational desire. Many philosophers argue that
naturalism is preferable on epistemic grounds. If, e.g., ‘X is valuable’ just
means ‘X is an object of interest’, then in order to know whether something is
valuable, one need only know whether it is the object of someone’s interest.
Our knowledge of value is fundentally no different in kind from our knowledge
of any other empirical fact. This argument, however, is not decisive against
non-naturalism, since it is not obvious that there is no synthetic a priori
knowledge of the sort Moore takes as the fundental value cognition.
Furthermore, it is not clear that one cannot combine non-naturalism about value
with a broadly empirical epistemology, one that takes certain kinds of
experience as epistemic grounds for beliefs about value.
Vanini, philosopher, a
Renaissance Aristotelian who studied law and theology. He bece a monk and
traveled all over Europe. After abjuring, he taught and practiced medicine. He
was burned at the stake by the Inquisition. His major work is four volumes of
dialogues, De admirandis naturae reginae deaeque mortalium arcanis (“On the
Secrets of Nature, Queen and Goddess of Mortal Beings,” 1616). He was
influenced by Averroes and Pietro Pomponazzi, whom he regarded as his teacher.
Vanini rejects revealed religion and claims that God is immanent in nature. The
world is ruled by a necessary natural order and is eternal. Like Averroes, he
denies the immortality and the immateriality of the human soul. Like
Pomponazzi, he denies the existence of miracles and claims that all apparently
extraordinary phenomena can be shown to have natural causes and to be predetermined.
Despite the absence of any original contribution, from the second half of the
seventeenth century Vanini was popular as a symbol of free and atheist thought.
variable, in logic and
mathematics, a symbol interpreted so as to be associated with a range of
values, a set of entities any one of which may be temporarily assigned as a
value of the variable. An occurrence of a variable in a mathematical or logical
expression is a free occurrence if assigning a value is necessary in order for
the containing expression to acquire a semantic value – a denotation,
truth-value, or other meaning. Suppose a semantic value is assigned to a
variable and the se value is attached to a constant as meaning of the se kind;
if an expression contains free occurrences of just that variable, the value of
the expression for that assignment of value to the variable is standardly taken
to be the se as the value of the expression obtained by substituting the
constant for all the free occurrences of the variable. A bound occurrence of a
variable is one that is not free.
FORMAL LOGIC, LOGICAL
SYNTAX, QUANTIFICATION, WELLFORMED FORMULA. C.A.A. variable, bound.ONTOLOGICAL
COMMITMENT, VARIABLE. variable, free.VARIABLE. variable, regressor.REGRESSION
ANALYSIS. variable, response.REGRESSION ANALYSIS. variable, state.STATE.
variable, value of.ONTOLOGICAL COMMITMENT, VARIABLE. variable sum ge.GE THEORY.
vasana, Buddhist philosophical term meaning ‘tendency’. It is an explanatory
category, designed to show how it is possible to talk of tendencies or
capacities in persons on the basis of a metaphysic that denies that there are
any enduring existents in the continua of events conventionally called
“persons.” According to this metaphysic, when we speak of the tendency of
persons understood in this way to do this or that – to be jealous, lustful,
angry – we are speaking of the presence of karmic seeds in continua of events,
seeds that may mature at different times and so produce tendencies to engage in
this or that action. ALAYA-VIJÑANA.
P.J.G. Vasubandhu (fourth–fifth century A.D.), Indian philosopher, a Mahayana
Buddhist of the Yogacara or Sarvastivada school. He wrote the Abhidharmakosá
(“Treasure Chber of the Abhidharma,” the Abhidharma being a compilation of
Buddhist philosophy and psychology) and the Vimcatika (“Proof in Twenty Verses
That Everything Is Only Conception”). He held that the mind is only a stre of
ideas and that there is nothing non-mental. In contrast to Buddhist direct and
representational realists, he argued that dre experience seems to be of objects
located in space and existing independent of the dreer without their actually
doing so.
Vauvenargues, Luc de
Clapiers de (1715–47), French army officer and secular moralist. Discovering
Plutarch at an early age, he critically adopted Stoic idealism.
Poverty-stricken, obscure, and solitary, he was bitious for glory. Though
eventful, his military career brought little reward. In poor health, he
resigned in 1744 to write. In 1747, he published Introduction to the Knowledge
of the Human Mind, followed by Reflections and Maxims. Voltaire and Mirabeau
praised his vigorous and eclectic thought, which aimed at teaching people how
to live. Vauvenargues was a deist and an optimist who equally rejected
Bossuet’s Christian pessimism and La Rochefoucauld’s secular pessimism. He
asserted human freedom and natural goodness, but denied social and political
equality. A lover of martial virtues and noble passions, Vauvenargues crafted
memVardhana Jnatrputra Vauvenargues, Luc de Clapiers de 951 951 orable maxims and excelled in character
depiction. His complete works were published in 1862.
Vázquez, Gabriel
(1549–1604), Spanish Jesuit theologian and philosopher. Born in Villaescusa de
Haro, he studied at Alcalá de Henares and taught at Ocaña, Madrid, Alcalá, and
Rome. He was a prolific writer; his philosophically most important work is a
commentary on Aquinas’s Summa theologiae. Vázquez was strongly influenced by
Aquinas, but he differed from him in important ways and showed marked leanings
toward Augustine. He rejected the Thomistic doctrine of the real distinction
between essence and existence and the position that matter designated by
quantity (materia signata quantitate) is the principle of individuation.
Instead of Aquinas’s five ways for proving the existence of God, he favored a
version of the moral argument similar to the one later used by Kant and also
favored the teleological argument. Following Augustine, he described the union
of body and soul as a union of two parts. Finally, Vázquez modified the
doctrine of formal and objective concepts present in Toletus and Suárez in a
way that facilitated the development of idealism in early modern philosophy. He
accomplished this by identifying the actual being (esse) of the thing that is
known (conceptus objectivus) with the act (conceptus formalis) whereby it is
known.
Vedanta, also called
Uttara Mimsa (‘the end of the Vedas’), the most influential of the six orthodox
schools of Hinduism. Much of the philosophical content of other schools has been
taken up into it. It claims to present the correct interpretation of the Vedas
and Upanishads, along with the Bhagavad Gita, sacred texts within Indian
culture. Much of the dispute over these texts is religious as well as
philosophical in nature; it concerns whether or not they are best read
theistically or monistically. To read these texts theistically is to see them
as teaching the existence of an omnipotent and omniscient personal Brahman, who
in sport (not out of need, but not without moral seriousness) everlastingly
sustains the material world and conscious selves in existence; the ultimate
good of the conscious selves then consists in being rightly related to Brahman.
To read these texts monistically is to see them as teaching the existence of a
qualityless ineffable Brahman who appears to the unenlightened to be manifested
in a multiplicity of bodies and minds and in a personal deity; critics
naturally ask to whom such an appearance appears. Two great thinkers in the
theistic Vedantic tradition are Ranuja (traditional dates: 1017– 1137) and
Madhva (b.1238). Shankara (788– 820?) represents Advaita Vedanta (‘Advaita’
meaning ‘non-dual’) and defends the view that the sacred texts ought to be read
monistically; his view is often compared to the absolute idealism embraced by
Bradley; for Shankara what appears as a pluralistic world is really a seless
unity. Madhva is a leading proponent of Dvaita Vedanta, an uncompromisingly
theistic reading of the se texts; for him, what appears as a pluralistic world
is a pluralistic world that exists distinct from, though dependent on, Brahman.
Ranuja is a leading exponent of Visistadvaita Vedanta, often called “qualified
non-dualism” because Ranuja, in contrast to Madhva, views the pluralistic world
that appears as the body of Brahman but, in contrast to Shankara, views that
body as real and distinct from Brahman conceived as an omnicompetent
person.
Vedas, the earliest Hindu
sacred texts. ‘Veda’ literally means a text that contains knowledge, in
particular sacred knowledge concerning the nature of ultimate reality and the
proper human ways of relating thereto. Passed down orally and then composed
over a millennium beginning around 1400 B.C., there are four collections of
Vedas: the Rg Veda (1,028 sacred songs of praise with some cosmological
speculations), the Sa Veda (chants to accompany sacrifices), Yajur Veda
(sacrificial formulas and mantras), and Atharva Veda (magical formulas, myths,
and legends). The term ‘Veda’ also applies to the Brahmanas (ritual and
theological commentaries on the prior Vedas); the Aranyakas(mainly composed by
men who have passed through their householder stage of life and retired to the
forest to meditate), and the Upanishads, which more fully reflect the idea of
theoretical sacred knowledge, while the early Vedas are more practice-oriented,
concerned with ritual and sacrifice. All these texts are regarded as scripture
(sruti), “heard” in an oral tradition believed to be handed down by sages by
whom their content was “seen.” The content is held to express a timeless and
uncreated wisdom produced by neither God nor human. It contains material
ranging from instructions concerning the proper sacriVázquez, Gabriel Vedas
952 952 fices to make and how to make them
properly, through hymns and mantras, to accounts of the nature of Brahman,
humankind, and the cosmos. Sruti contrasts with smrti (tradition), which is
humanly produced commentary on scripture. The Bhagavad Gita, perhaps strictly
smrti, typically has the de facto status of sruti. K.E.Y. veil of
ignorance.RAWLS. velleity.VOLITION. Venn diagr, a logic diagr invented by the
logician John Venn in which standard form statements (the four kinds listed
below) are represented by two appropriately marked overlapping circles, as
follows: Syllogisms are represented by three overlapping circles, as in the
exples below. If a few simple rules are followed, e.g. “diagr universal
premises first,” then in a valid syllogism diagrming the premises automatically
gives a diagr in which the conclusion is represented. In an invalid syllogism
diagrming the premises does not automatically give a diagr in which the
conclusion is represented, as below. Venn diagrs are less perspicuous for the
beginner than Euler diagrs. EULER DIAGR,
SYLLOGISM. R.P.
verificationism, a metaphysical
theory about what determines meaning: the meaning of a statement consists in
its method(s) of verification. Verificationism thus differs radically from the
account that identifies meaning with truth conditions, as is implicit in
Frege’s work and explicit in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus and throughout the
writings of Davidson. On Davidson’s theory, e.g., the crucial notions for a
theory of meaning are truth and falsity. Contemporary verificationists, under
the influence of the Oxford philosopher Michael Dummett, propose what they see
as a constraint on the concept of truth rather than a criterion of
meaningfulness. No foundational place is generally assigned in modern
verificationist semantics to corroboration by observation statements; and
modern verificationism is not reductionist. Thus, many philosophers read
Quine’s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” as rejecting verificationism. This is
because they fail to notice an important distinction. What Quine rejects is not
verificationism but “reductionism,” nely, the theory that there is, for each
statement, a corresponding range of verifying conditions determinable a priori.
Reductionism is inherently localist with regard to verification; whereas
verificationism, as such, is neutral on whether verification is holistic. And,
lastly, modern verificationism is, veil of ignorance verificationism 953 953 whereas traditional verificationism
never was, connected with revisionism in the philosophy of logic and
mathematics (e.g., rejecting the principle of bivalence). LOGICAL POSITIVISM, MEANING, PRINCIPLE OF
VERIFIABILITY, VIENNA CIRCLE. E.L.
Verstehen (German,
‘understanding’, ‘interpretation’), a method in the human sciences that aims at
reconstructing meanings from the “agent’s point of view.” Such a method makes primary
how agents understand themselves, as, e.g., when cultural anthropologists try
to understand symbols and practices from the “native’s point of view.”
Understanding in this sense is often contrasted with explanation, or Erklärung.
Whereas explanations discover causes in light of general laws and take an
external perspective, understanding aims at explicating the meaning that, from
an internal perspective, an action or expression has for the actor. This
distinction often is the basis for a further methodological and ontological
distinction between the natural and the human sciences, the Natur- and the
Geisteswissenschaften. Whereas the data of the natural sciences may be
theory-dependent and in that sense interpretive, the human sciences are
“doubly” interpretive; they try to interpret the interpretations that human
subjects give to their actions and practices. The human sciences do not aim at
explaining events but at understanding meanings, texts, and text analogues.
Actions, artifacts, and social relations are all like texts in that they have a
significance for and by human subjects. The method of Verstehen thus denies the
“unity of science” thesis typical of accounts of explanation given by
empiricists and positivists. However, other philosophers such as Weber argue
against such a dichotomy and assert that the social sciences in particular must
incorporate features of both explanation and understanding, and psychoanalysis
and theories of ideology unify both approaches. Even ong proponents of this
method, the precise nature of interpretation remains controversial. While
Dilthey and other neo-Kantians proposed that Verstehen is the imaginative
reexperiencing of the subjective point of view of the actor, Wittgenstein and
his following propose a sharp distinction between reasons and causes and
understand reasons in terms of relating an action to the relevant rules or
norms that it follows. In both cases, the aim of the human sciences is to
understand what the text or text analogue really means for the agent. Following
Heidegger, recent German hermeneutics argues that Verstehen does not refer to
special disciplinary techniques nor to merely cognitive and theoretical
achievements, but to the practical mode of all human existence, its
situatedness in a world that projects various possibilities. All understanding
then becomes interpretation, itself a universal feature of all human activity,
including the natural sciences. The criteria of success in Verstehen also
remain disputed, particularly since many philosophers deny that it constitutes
a method. If all understanding is interpretation, then there are no
presuppositionless, neutral data that can put them to an empirical test.
Verstehen is therefore not a method but an event, in which there is a “fusion
of horizons” between text and interpreter. Whether criteria such as coherence,
the capacity to engage in a tradition, or increasing dialogue apply depends on
the type, purpose, and context of various interpretations. DILTHEY, EXPLANATION, HEIDEGGER,
HERMENEUTICS, UNITY OF SCIENCE. J.Bo. verum.Appendix of Special Symbols.
vicious regress, regress
that is in some way unacceptable, where a regress is an infinite series of
items each of which is in some sense dependent on a prior item of a similar
sort, e.g. an infinite series of events each of which is caused by the next
prior event in the series. Reasons for holding a regress to be vicious might be
that it is either impossible or that its existence is inconsistent with things
known to be true. The claim that something would lead to a vicious regress is
often made as part of a reductio ad absurdum argument strategy. An exple of
this can be found in Aquinas’s argument for the existence of an uncaused cause
on the ground that an infinite regress of causes is vicious. Those responding
to the argument have sometimes contended that this regress is not in fact
vicious and hence that the argument fails. A more convincing exple of a regress
is generated by the principle that one’s coming to know the meaning of a word
must always be based on a prior understanding of other words. If this principle
is correct, then one can know the meaning of a word w1 only on the basis of
previously understanding the meanings of other words (w2 and w3). But a further
application of the principle yields the result that one can understand these
words (w2 and w3) only on the basis of understanding still other words. This
leads to an infinite regress. Since no one understands any words at birth, the
regress implies that no one ever comes to understand any words. But this is
clearly false. Since the existence of this regress is inconsistent with an
obvious truth, we may conclude that the regress is vicious and consequently
that the principle that generates it is false.
EPISTEMIC REGRESS ARGUMENT, REDUCTIO AD ABSURDUM.
Vico, Philosopher who
founded modern philosophy of history, philosophy of culture, and philosophy of
mythology. He was born and lived all his life in or near Naples, where he
taught eloquence. The Inquisition was a force in Naples throughout Vico’s
lifetime. A turning point in his career was his loss of the concourse for a
chair of civil law (1723). Although a disappointment and an injustice, it
enabled him to produce his major philosophical work. He was appointed royal
historiographer by Charles of Bourbon. Vico’s major work is “La scienza nuova” completely revised in a second, definitive
version in 1730. In the 1720s, he published three connected works in Latin on
jurisprudence, under the title Universal Law; one contains a sketch of his conception
of a “new science” of the historical life of nations. Vico’s principal works
preceding this are On the Study Methods of Our Time (1709), comparing the
ancients with the moderns regarding human education, and On the Most Ancient
Wisdom of the Italians (1710), attacking the Cartesian conception of metaphysics.
His Autobiography inaugurates the conception of modern intellectual
autobiography. Basic to Vico’s philosophy is his principle that “the true is
the made” (“verum ipsum factum”), that what is true is convertible with what is
made. This principle is central in his conception of “science” (scientia,
scienza). A science is possible only for those subjects in which such a
conversion is possible. There can be a science of mathematics, since mathematical
truths are such because we make them. Analogously, there can be a science of
the civil world of the historical life of nations. Since we make the things of
the civil world, it is possible for us to have a science of them. As the makers
of our own world, like God as the maker who makes by knowing and knows by
making, we can have knowledge per caussas (through causes, from within). In the
natural sciences we can have only conscientia (a kind of “consciousness”), not
scientia, because things in nature are not made by the knower. Vico’s “new
science” is a science of the principles whereby “men make history”; it is also
a demonstration of “what providence has wrought in history.” All nations rise
and fall in cycles within history (corsi e ricorsi) in a pattern governed by
providence. The world of nations or, in the Augustinian phrase Vico uses, “the
great city of the human race,” exhibits a pattern of three ages of “ideal
eternal history” (storia ideale eterna). Every nation passes through an age of
gods (when people think in terms of gods), an age of heroes (when all virtues
and institutions are formed through the personalities of heroes), and an age of
humans (when all sense of the divine is lost, life becomes luxurious and false,
and thought becomes abstract and ineffective); then the cycle must begin again.
In the first two ages all life and thought are governed by the primordial power
of “imagination” (fantasia) and the world is ordered through the power of
humans to form experience in terms of “imaginative universals” (universali
fantastici). These two ages are governed by “poetic wisdom” (sapienza poetica).
At the basis of Vico’s conception of history, society, and knowledge is a
conception of mythical thought as the origin of the human world. Fantasia is the
original power of the human mind through which the true and the made are
converted to create the myths and gods that are at the basis of any cycle of
history. Michelet was the primary supporter of Vico’s ideas in the nineteenth
century; he made them the basis of his own philosophy of history. Coleridge is
the principal disseminator of Vico’s views in England. Jes Joyce used the New
Science as a substructure for Finnegans Wake, making plays on Vico’s ne,
beginning with one in Latin in the first sentence: “by a commodius vicus of
recirculation.” Croce revives Vico’s philosophical thought, wishing to conceive
Vico as the Italian Hegel. Vico’s ideas have been the subject of analysis by
such prominent philosophical thinkers as Horkheimer and Berlin, by anthropologists
such as Edmund Leach, and by literary critics such as René Wellek and Herbert
Read.
Vienna Circle – vide
ayerism -- a group of philosophers and scientists who met periodically for
discussions in Vienna from 1922 to 1938 and who proposed a self-consciously
revolutionary conception of scientific knowledge. The Circle was initiated by
the mathematician Hans Hahn to continue a prewar forum with the physicist
Philip Frank and the social scientist Otto Neurath after the arrival in Vienna
of Moritz Schlick, a philosopher who had studied with Max Planck. Carnap joined
in 1926 (from 1931 in Prague); other members included Herbert Feigl (from 1930
in Iowa), Friedrich Waismann, Bergmann, Viktor Kraft, and Bela von Juhos.
Viennese associates of the Circle included Kurt Gödel, Karl Menger, Felix
Kaufmann, and Edgar Zilsel. (Popper was not a member or associate.) During its
formative period the Circle’s activities were confined to discussion meetings
(many on Wittgenstein’s Tractatus). In 1929 the Circle entered its public
period with the formation of the Verein Ernst Mach, the publication of its
manifesto Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung: Der Wiener Kreis by Carnap, Hahn,
and Neurath (translated in Neurath, Empiricism and Sociology, 1973), and the
first of a series of philosophical monographs edited by Frank and Schlick. It
also began collaboration with the independent but broadly like-minded Berlin
“Society of Empirical Philosophy,” including Reichenbach, Kurt Grelling, Kurt
Lewin, Friedrich Kraus, Walter Dubislav, Hempel, and Richard von Mises: the
groups together organized their first public conferences in Prague and
Königsberg, acquired editorship of a philosophical journal rened Erkenntnis,
and later organized the international Unity of Science congresses. The death
and dispersion of key members from 1934 onward (Hahn died in 1934, Neurath left
for Holland in 1934, Carnap left for the United States in 1935, Schlick died in
1936) did not mean the extinction of Vienna Circle philosophy. Through the
subsequent work of earlier visitors (Ayer, Ernest Nagel, Quine) and members and
collaborators who emigrated to the United States (Carnap, Feigl, Frank, Hempel,
and Reichenbach), the logical positivism of the Circle (Reichenbach and Neurath
independently preferred “logical empiricism”) strongly influenced the
development of analytic philosophy. The Circle’s discussions concerned the
philosophy of formal and physical science, and even though their individual
publications ranged much wider, it is the attitude toward science that defines
the Circle within the philosophical movements of central Europe at the time.
The Circle rejected the need for a specifically philosophical epistemology that
bestowed justification on knowledge claims from beyond science itself. In this,
the Circle may also have drawn on a distinct Austrian tradition (a thesis of
its historian Neurath): in most of Germany, science and philosophy had parted
ways during the nineteenth century. Starting with Helmholtz, of course, there
also arose a movement that sought to distinguish the scientific respectability
of the Kantian tradition from the speculations of German idealism, yet after
1880 neo-Kantians insisted on the autonomy of epistemology, disparaging earlier
fellow travelers as “positivist.” Yet the progr of reducing the knowledge claim
of science and providing legitimations to what’s left found wide favor with the
more empirical-minded like Mach. Comprehensive description, not explanation, of
natural phenomena bece the task for theorists who no longer looked to
philosophy for foundations, but found them in the utility of their preferred
empirical procedures. Along with the positivists, the Vienna Circle thought
uneconomical the Kantian answer to the question of the possibility of
objectivity, the synthetic a priori. Moreover, the Vienna Circle and its
conventionalist precursors Poincaré and Duhem saw them contradicted by the
results of formal science. Riemann’s geometries showed that questions about the
geometry of physical space were open to more than one answer: Was physical
space Euclidean or non-Euclidean? It fell to Einstein and the pre-Circle
Schlick (Space and Time in Contemporary Physics, 1917) to argue that relativity
theory showed the untenability of Kant’s conception of space and time as forever
fixed synthetic a priori forms of intuition. Yet Frege’s anti-psychologistic
critique had also shown empiricism unable to account for knowledge of
arithmetic and the conventionalists had ended the positivist dre of a theory of
experiential elements that bridged the gap between descriptions of fact and
general principles of science. How, then, could the Vienna Circle defend the
claim – under attack as just one worldview ong others – that science provides
knowledge? The Circle confronted the problem of constitutive conventions. As
befitted their self-image beyond Kant and Mach, they found their paraVienna
Circle Vienna Circle 956 956 digmatic
answer in the theory of relativity: they thought that irreducible conventions
of measurement with wide-ranging implications were sharply separable from pure
facts like point coincidences. Empirical theories were viewed as logical
structures of statements freely created, yet accountable to experiential input
via their predictive consequences identifiable by observation. The Vienna
Circle defended empiricism by the reconceptualization of the relation between a
priori and a posteriori inquiries. First, in a manner sympathetic to Frege’s
and Russell’s doctrine of logicism and guided by Wittgenstein’s notion of
tautology, arithmetic was considered a part of logic and treated as entirely
analytical, without any empirical content; its truth was held to be exhausted
by what is provable from the premises and rules of a formal symbolic system.
(Carnap’s Logical Syntax of Language, 1934, assimilated Gödel’s incompleteness
result by claiming that not every such proof could be demonstrated in those
systems themselves which are powerful enough to represent classical
arithmetic.) The synthetic a priori was not needed for formal science because
all of its results were non-synthetic. Second, the Circle adopted
verificationism: supposedly empirical concepts whose applicability was
indiscernible were excluded from science. The terms for unobservables were to
be reconstructed by logical operations from the observational terms. Only if
such reconstructions were provided did the more theoretical parts of science
retain their empirical character. (Just what kind of reduction was aimed for
was not always clear and earlier radical positions were gradually weakened;
Reichenbach instead considered the relation between observational and
theoretical statements to be probabilistic.) Empirical science needed no
synthetic a priori either; all of its statements were a posteriori. Combined
with the view that the analysis of the logical form of expressions allowed for
the exact determination of their combinatorial value, verificationism was to
exhibit the knowledge claims of science and eliminate metaphysics. Whatever
meaning did not survive identification with the scientific was deemed
irrelevant to knowledge claims (Reichenbach did not share this view either).
Since the Circle also observed the then long-discussed ban on issuing
unconditional value statements in science, its metaethical positions may be
broadly characterized as endorsing noncognitivism. Its members were not simply
emotivists, however, holding that value judgments were mere expressions of
feeling, but sought to distinguish the factual and evaluative contents of value
judgments. Those who, like Schlick (Questions of Ethics, 1930), engaged in
metaethics, distinguished the expressive component (x desires y) of value
judgments from their implied descriptive component (doing zfurthers aim y) and
held that the demand inherent in moral principles possessed validity if the
implied description was true and the expressed desire was endorsed. This
analysis of normative concepts did not render them meaningless but allowed for
psychological and sociological studies of ethical systems; Menger’s formal
variant (Morality, Decision and Social Organization, 1934) proved influential
for decision theory. The semiotic view that knowledge required structured
representations was developed in close contact with foundational research in
mathematics and depended on the “new” logic of Frege, Russell, and
Wittgenstein, out of which quantification theory was emerging. Major new
results were quickly integrated (albeit controversially) and Carnap’s works
reflect the development of the conception of logic itself. In his Logical Syntax
he adopted the “Principle of Tolerance” vis-à-vis the question of the
foundation of the formal sciences: the choice of logics (and languages) was
conventional and constrained, apart from the demand for consistency, only by
pragmatic considerations. The proposed language form and its difference from
alternatives simply had to be stated as exactly as possible: whether a
logico-linguistic frework as a whole correctly represented reality was a
cognitively meaningless question. Yet what was the status of the verifiability
principle? Carnap’s suggestion that it represents not a discovery but a
proposal for future scientific language use deserves to be taken seriously, for
it not only characterizes his own conventionalism, but also plifies the
Circle’s linguistic turn, according to which all philosophy concerned ways of
representing, rather than the nature of the represented. What the Vienna Circle
“discovered” was how much of science was conventional: its verificationism was
a proposal for accommodating the creativity of scientific theorizing without
accommodating idealism. Whether an empirical claim in order to be meaningful
needed to be actually verified or only potentially verifiable, or fallible or
only potentially testable, and whether so by current or only by future means,
bece matters of discussion during the 1930s. Equally important for the question
whether the Circle’s conventionalism avoided idealism and metaphysics were the
issues of the status of theoretical discourse about Vienna Circle Vienna Circle
957 957 unobservables and the nature of
science’s empirical foundation. The view suggested in Schlick’s early General
Theory of Knowledge (1918, 2d. ed. 1925) and Frank’s The Causal Law and its
Limitations (1932) and elaborated in Carnap’s “Logical Foundations of the Unity
of Science” (in Foundations of the Unity of Science I.1, 1938) characterized
the theoretical language as an uninterpreted calculus that is related to the
fully interpreted observational language only by partial definitions. Did such an
instrumentalism require for its empirical anchor the sharp separation of
observational from theoretical terms? Could such a separation even be
maintained? Consider the unity of science thesis. According to the
methodological version, endorsed by all members, all of science abides by the
se criteria: no basic methodological differences separate the natural from the
social or cultural sciences (Geisteswissenschaften) as claimed by those who
distinguish between ‘explanation’ and ‘understanding’. According to the
metalinguistic version, all objects of scientific knowledge could in principle
be comprehended by the se “universal” language. Physicalism asserts that this
is the language that speaks of physical objects. While everybody in the Circle
endorsed physicalism in this sense, the understanding of its importance varied,
as bece clear in the socalled protocol sentence debate. (The nomological
version of the unity thesis was only later clearly distinguished: whether all
scientific laws could be reduced to those of physics was another matter on
which Neurath ce to differ.) Ostensively, this debate concerned the question of
the form, content, and epistemological status of scientific evidence
statements. Schlick’s unrevisable “affirmations” talked about phenomenal states
in statements not themselves part of the language of science (“The Foundation
of Knowledge,” 1934, translated in Ayer, ed., Logical Positivism). Carnap’s
preference changed from unrevisable statements in a primitive methodologically
solipsistic protocol language that were fallibly translatable into the
physicalistic system language (1931; see Unity of Science, 1934), via arbitrary
revisable statements of that system language that are taken as temporary
resting points in testing (1932), to revisable statements in the scientific
observation language (1935; see “Testability and Meaning,” Philosophy of
Science, 1936–37). These changes were partly prompted by Neurath, whose own
revisable “protocol statements” spoke, ongst other matters, of the relation between
observers and the observed in a “universal slang” that mixed expressions of the
physicalistically cleansed colloquial and the high scientific languages
(“Protocol Statements,” 1932, translated in Ayer, ed., Logical Positivism).
Ultimately, these proposals answered to different projects. Since all agreed
that all statements of science were hypothetical, the questions of their
“foundation” concerned rather the very nature of Vienna Circle philosophy. For
Schlick philosophy bece the activity of meaning determination (inspired by
Wittgenstein); Carnap pursued it as the rational reconstruction of knowledge
claims concerned only with what Reichenbach called the “context of
justification” (its logical aspects, not the “context of discovery”); and
Neurath replaced philosophy altogether with a naturalistic, interdisciplinary,
empirical inquiry into science as a distinctive discursive practice, precluding
the orthodox conception of the unity of science. The Vienna Circle was neither
a monolithic nor a necessarily reductionist philosophical movement, and quick
assimilation to the tradition of British empiricism mistakes its struggles with
the form–content dichotomy for foundationalism, when instead sophisticated
responses to the question of the presuppositions of their own theories of
knowledge were being developed. In its time and place, the Circle was a
minority voice; the sociopolitical dimension of its theories – stressed more by
some (Neurath) than others (Schlick) – as a renewal of Enlightenment thought,
ultimately against the rising tide of Blutund-Boden metaphysics, is gaining
recognition. After the celebrated “death” of reductionist logical positivism in
the 1960s the historical Vienna Circle is reemerging as a multifaceted object
of the history of analytical philosophy itself, revealing in nuce different
strands of reasoning still significant for postpositivist theory of
science. MEANING, OPERATIONALISM,
PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, REDUCTION, UNITY OF SCIENCE. T.U.
Vijñanavada, an idealist
school of Buddhist thought in India in the fourth century A.D. It engaged in
lively debates on important epistemological and metaphysical issues with the
Buddhist Madhyika school (known for its relativistic and nihilistic views),
with Buddhist realist schools, and with various Hindu philosophical systems of
its time. Madhyika philosophy used effective dialectic to show the
contradictions in our everyday philosophical notions such as cause, substance,
self, etc., but the Vijñanavada school, while agreeing with the Madhyikas on this
point, went further and Vijñanavada Vijñanavada 958 958 gave innovative explanations regarding
the origin and the status of our mental constructions and of the mind itself.
Unlike the Madhyikas, who held that reality is “emptiness” (sunyata), the Vijñanavadins
held that the reality is consciousness or the mind (vijñana). The Vijñanavada
school is also known as Yogacara. Its idealism is remarkably similar to the
subjective idealism of Berkeley. Consistent with the process ontology of all
the Buddhist schools in India, Vijñanavadins held that consciousness or the
mind is not a substance but an ever-changing stre of ideas or impressions. BUDDHISM. D.K.C. vijñapti, Indian Buddhist
term meaning ‘representation’, used by some philosophers as a label for a mental
event that appears, phenomenally, to have an intentional object and to
represent or communicate to its possessor some information about extrental
reality. The term was used mostly by Buddhists with idealist tendencies who
claimed that there is nothing but representation, nothing but communicative
mental events, and that a complete account of human experience can be given
without postulating the existence of anything extrental. This view was not
uncontroversial, and in defending it Indian Buddhists developed arguments that
are in important ways analogous to those constructed by Western idealists.
violence, (1) the use of
force to cause physical harm, death, or destruction (physical violence); (2)
the causing of severe mental or emotional harm, as through humiliation,
deprivation, or brainwashing, whether using force or not (psychological
violence); (3) more broadly, profaning, desecrating, defiling, or showing
disrespect for (i.e., “doing violence” to) something valued, sacred, or
cherished; (4) extreme physical force in the natural world, as in tornados,
hurricanes, and earthquakes. Physical violence may be directed against persons,
animals, or property. In the first two cases, harm, pain, suffering, and death
figure prominently; in the third, illegality or illegitimacy (the forceful
destruction of property is typically considered violence when it lacks
authorization). Psychological violence applies principally to persons. It may
be understood as the violation of beings worthy of respect. But it can apply to
higher animals as well (as in the daging mental effects of some
experimentation, e.g., involving isolation and deprivation). Environmentalists
sometimes speak of violence against the environment, implying both destruction
and disrespect for the natural world. Sometimes the concept of violence is used
to characterize acts or practices of which one morally disapproves. To this
extent it has a normative force. But this prejudges whether violence is wrong.
One may, on the other hand, regard inflicting harm or death as only prima facie
wrong (i.e., wrong all other things being equal). This gives violence a
normative character, establishing its prima facie wrongness. But it leaves open
the ultimate moral justifiability of its use. Established practices of physical
or psychological violence – e.g., war, capital punishment – constitute
institutionalized violence. So do illegal or extralegal practices like
vigilantism, torture, and state terrorism (e.g., death squads). Anarchists
sometimes regard the courts, prisons, and police essential to maintaining the
state as violence. Racism and sexism may be considered institutional violence
owing to their associated psychological as well as physical violence. NONVIOLENCE. R.L.H. vipassana (Pali,
‘insight’, ‘discernment’), Indian Buddhist term used to describe both a
particular kind of meditational practice and the states of consciousness
produced by it. The meditational practice is aimed at getting the practitioner
to perceive and cognize in accord with the major categories of Buddhist
metaphysics. Since that metaphysics is constitutively deconstructive, being
concerned with parts rather than wholes, the method too is analytic and
deconstructive. The practitioner is encouraged to analyze the perceived
solidities and continuities of her everyday experience into transitory events,
and so to cultivate the perception of such events until she experiences the
world no longer in terms of medium-sized physical objects that endure through
time, but solely in terms of transitory events. Arriving at such a condition is
called the attainment of vipassana. P.J.G. virtù.CLASSICAL REPUBLICANISM,
MACHIAVELLI. virtue, epistemic.VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY.
virtue epistemology, the
subfield of epistemology that takes epistemic virtue to be central to
understanding justification or knowledge or both. An epistemic virtue is a
personal quality conducive to the discovery of truth, the avoidance of error,
or some other intellectually valuable goal. Following Aristotle, we should
distinguish these virtues from such qualities as wisdom or good judgment, which
are the intellectual basis of practical – but not necessarily intellectual –
success. The importance, and to an extent, the very definition, of this notion
depends, however, on larger issues of epistemology. For those who favor a
naturalist conception of knowledge (say, as belief formed in a “reliable” way),
there is reason to call any truth-conducive quality or properly working
cognitive mechanism an epistemic virtue. There is no particular reason to limit
the epistemic virtues to recognizable personal qualities: a high mathematical
aptitude may count as an epistemic virtue. For those who favor a more
“normative” conception of knowledge, the corresponding notion of an epistemic
virtue (or vice) will be narrower: it will be tied to personal qualities (like
impartiality or carelessness) whose exercise one would associate with an ethics
of belief. RELIABILISM, VIRTUE ETHICS.
virtue ethics, also
called virtue-based ethics and agent-based ethics, conceptions or theories of
morality in which virtues play a central or independent role. Thus, it is more
than simply the account of the virtues offered by a given theory. Some take the
principal claim of virtue ethics to be about the moral subject – that, in
living her life, she should focus her attention on the cultivation of her (or
others’) virtues. Others take the principal claim to be about the moral
theorist – that, in mapping the structure of our moral thought, she should
concentrate on the virtues. This latter view can be construed weakly as holding
that the moral virtues are no less basic than other moral concepts. In this
type of virtue ethics, virtues are independent of other moral concepts in that
claims about morally virtuous character or action are, in the main, neither
reducible to nor justified on the basis of underlying claims about moral duty
or rights, or about what is impersonally valuable. It can also be construed
strongly as holding that the moral virtues are more basic than other moral
concepts. In such a virtue ethics, virtues are fundental, i.e., claims about
other moral concepts are either reducible to underlying claims about moral
virtues or justified on their basis. Forms of virtue ethics predominated in
Western philosophy before the Renaissance, most notably in Aristotle, but also
in Plato and Aquinas. Several ancient and medieval philosophers endorsed strong
versions of virtue ethics. These views focused on character rather than on
discrete behavior, identifying illicit behavior with vicious behavior, i.e.,
conduct that would be seriously out of character for a virtuous person. A
virtuous person, in turn, was defined as one with dispositions relevantly
linked to human flourishing. On these views, while a person of good character,
or someone who carefully observes her, may be able to articulate certain
principles or rules by which she guides her conduct (or to which, at least, it
outwardly conforms), the principles are not an ultimate source of moral
justification. On the contrary, they are justified only insofar as the conduct
they endorse would be in character for a virtuous person. For Aristotle, the
connection between flourishing and virtue seems conceptual. (He conceived moral
virtues as dispositions to choose under the proper guidance of reason, and
defined a flourishing life as one lived in accordance with these virtues.)
While most accounts of the virtues link them to the flourishing of the virtuous
person, there are other possibilities. In principle, the flourishing to which
virtue is tied (whether causally or conceptually) may be either that of the
virtuous subject herself, or that of some patient who is a recipient of her
virtuous behavior, or that of some larger affected group – the agent’s
community, perhaps, or all humanity, or even sentient life in general. For the
philosophers of ancient Greece, it was human nature, usually conceived
teleologically, that fixed the content of this flourishing. Medieval Christian
writers reinterpreted this, stipulating both that the flourishing life to which
the virtues lead extends past death, and that human flourishing is not merely
the fulfillment of capacities and tendencies inherent in human nature, but is
the realization of a divine plan. In late twentieth-century versions of virtue
ethics, some theorists have suggested that it is neither to a teleology
inherent in human nature nor to the divine will that we should look in
determining the content of that flourishing to which the virtues lead. They
understand flourishing more as a matter of a person’s living a life that meets
the standards of her cultural, historical tradition. In his most general
characterization, Aristotle called a thing’s virtues those features of it that
made it and its operation good. The moral virtues were what made people live
well. This use of ‘making’ is biguous. Where he and other premodern thinkers
thought the connection between virtues and living well to be conceptual, moral
theorists of the modernist era have usually virtue ethics virtue ethics understood
it causally. They commonly maintain that a virtue is a character trait that
disposes a person to do what can be independently identified as morally
required or to effect what is best (best for herself, according to some
theories; best for others, according to different ones). Benjin Franklin, e.g.,
deemed it virtuous for a person to be frugal, because he thought frugality was
likely to result in her having a less troubled life. On views of this sort, a
lively concern for the welfare of others has moral importance only inasmuch as
it tends to motivate people actually to perform helpful actions. In short,
benevolence is a virtue because it conduces to beneficent conduct; veracity,
because it conduces to truth telling; fidelity, because it conduces to promise
keeping; and so on. Reacting to this aspect of modernist philosophy, recent
proponents of virtue ethics deny that moral virtues derive from prior
determinations of what actions are right or of what states of affairs are best.
Some, especially certain theorists of liberalism, assign virtues to what they
see as one compartment of moral thought and duties to a separate, and only
loosely connected compartment. For them, the life (and theory) of virtue is
autonomous. They hold that virtues and duties have independent sources of justification,
with virtues chiefly concerned with the individual’s personal “ideals,”
self-image, or conception of her life goals, while duties and rights are
thought to derive from social rules regulating interpersonal dealings.
Proponents of virtue ethics maintain that it has certain advantages over more
modern alternatives. They argue that virtue ethics is properly concrete,
because it grounds morality in facts about human nature or about the concrete
development of particular cultural traditions, in contrast with modernist
attempts to ground morality in subjective preference or in abstract principles
of reason. They also claim that virtue ethics is truer to human psychology in
concentrating on the less conscious aspects of motivation – on relatively stable
dispositions, habits, and long-term goals, for exple – where modern ethics
focuses on decision making directed by principles and rules. Virtue ethics,
some say, offers a more unified and comprehensive conception of moral life, one
that extends beyond actions to comprise wants, goals, likes and dislikes, and,
in general, what sort of person one is and aims to be. Proponents of virtue
ethics also contend that, without the sensitivity and appreciation of their
situation and its opportunities that only virtues consistently make available,
agents cannot properly apply the rules that modernist ethical theories offer to
guide their actions. Nor, in their view, will the agent follow those rules
unless her virtues offer her sufficient clarity of purpose and perseverance
against temptation. Several objections have been raised against virtue ethics
in its most recent forms. Critics contend that it is antiquarian, because it
relies on conceptions of human nature whose teleology renders them obsolete;
circular, because it allegedly defines right action in terms of virtues while
defining virtues in terms of right action; arbitrary and irrelevant to modern
society, since there is today no accepted standard either of what constitutes
human flourishing or of which dispositions lead to it; of no practical use,
because it offers no guidance when virtues seem to conflict; egoistic, in that
it ultimately directs the subject’s moral attention to herself rather than to
others; and fatalistic, in allowing the morality of one’s behavior to hinge
finally on luck in one’s constitution, upbringing, and opportunities. There may
be versions of virtue ethics that escape the force of all or most of the
objections, but not every form of virtue ethics can claim for itself all the
advantages mentioned above. AQUINAS,
ARISTOTLE, ETHICS, PLATO. J.L.A.G. virtues, cardinal.CARDINAL VIRTUES. virtues,
theological.AQUINAS.
Vishnu (from Sanskrit
Vifpu), major Hindu god and Supreme Lord for his devotees, the Vaishpavites.
Vaishpavite philosophers regard Vishnu as the referent of the term ‘Brahman’ in
the Vedic texts. Later texts attempt a synthesis of Vishnu with two other
deities into a trimurti (‘three forms’ of the Absolute), with Brahma as
Creator, Vishnu as Preserver, and Siva as Destroyer. This relatively unpopular
idea is used by modern thinkers to speak of these gods as three forms of the
formless Absolute. Madhva and Ranuja regard Vishnu as the Highest Lord,
possessed of infinite good qualities and superior to the qualityless Absolute
of the nondualist thinkers. Vaishpavite thinkers identify Vishnu with the
Purusa, the primeval, cosmic person, and Prajapati, Creator god, of the Vedas,
and give him epithets that identify Vishnu with other representatives of a
Supreme Being. He is Creator, Preserver, and Destroyer of the Universe. Vishnu
is best known for the doctrine of avatar, his “descents” into the world in
various virtues, cardinal forms to promote righteousness. Through this and the
concept of vyuhas, aspects or fragments, Vaishpavites incorporated other
deities, hero cults, and savior myths into their fold. He was a minor deity in
the early Vedic literature, known for his “three strides” across the universe,
which indicate that he pervades all. During the epic period (400 B.C.–A.D.
400), Vishnu bece one of the most popular gods in India, represented
iconographically as dark-complexioned and holding a conch and discus. His
consort is usually Laksmi and his vehicle the bird Garuda.
Visistadvaita Vedanta, a
form of Hinduism for which Brahman is an independently existing, omnipotent,
omniscient personal deity. In creative, morally serious sport, Brahman
everlastingly sustains in existence a world of both minds and physical things,
these together being the body of Brahman in the sense that Brahman can act on
any part of the world without first acting on some other part and that the
world manifests (though in some ways it also hides) Brahman’s nature. In
response to repentance and trust, Brahman will forgive one’s sins and bring one
into a gracious relationship that ends the cycle of rebirths. HINDUISM.
vitalism.PHILOSOPHY OF
BIOLOGY. vital lie, (1) an instance of self-deception (or lying to oneself)
when it fosters hope, confidence, self-esteem, mental health, or creativity;
(2) any false belief or unjustified attitude that helps people cope with
difficulties; (3) a lie to other people designed to promote their wellbeing.
For exple, self-deceiving optimism about one’s prospects for success in work or
personal relationships may generate hope, mobilize energy, enrich life’s
meaning, and increase chances for success. Henrik Ibsen dratized “life-lies” as
essential for happiness (The Wild Duck, 1884), and Eugene O’Neill portrayed
“pipe dres” as necessary crutches (The Iceman Cometh, 1939). Nietzsche endorsed
“pious illusions” or “holy fictions” about the past that liberate individuals
and societies from she and guilt (On the Advantage and Disadvantage of History
for Life, 1874). Schiller praised normal degrees of vanity and self-conceit
because they support selfesteem (Problems of Belief, 1924). BAD FAITH, FALSE CONSCIOUSNESS.
Vitoria, Dominican
jurist, political philosopher, and theologian who is regarded as the founder of
modern international law. Born in Vitoria or Burgos, he studied and taught at the
College of SaintJacques in Paris, where he met Erasmus and Vives. He also
taught at the College of San Gregorio in Valladolid and at Salanca. His most
fous works are the notes (relectiones) for twelve public addresses he delivered
at Salanca, published posthumously in 1557. Two relectiones stand out: De Indis
and De jure belli. They were responses to the legal and political issues raised
by the discovery and colonization of erica. In contrast with Mariana’s contract
Arianism, Vitoria held that political society is our natural state. The aim of
the state is to promote the common good and preserve the rights of citizens.
Citizenship is the result of birthplace (jus solis) rather than blood (jus
sanguini). The authority of the state resides in the body politic but is
transferred to rulers for its proper exercise. The best form of government is
monarchy because it preserves the unity necessary for social action while
safeguarding individual freedoms. Apart from the societies of individual
states, humans belong to an international society. This society has its own
authority and laws that establish the rights and duties of the states. These
laws constitute the law of nations (jus gentium). J.J.E.G. Vives, Juan Luis
(1492?–1540), Spanish humanist and teacher. Born in Valencia, he attended the
University of Paris (1509–14) and lived most of his life in Flanders. With his
friend Erasmus he prepared a widely used commentary (1522) of Augustine’s De
civitate Dei. From 1523 to 1528 Vives visited England, taught at Oxford,
befriended More, and bece Catherine of Aragon’s confidant. While in Paris,
Vives repudiated medieval logic as useless (Adversus pseudodialecticos, 1520)
and proposed instead a dialectic emphasizing resourceful reasoning and clear
and persuasive exposition (De tradendis disciplinis, 1532). His method was
partially inspired by Rudolph Agricola and probably influential upon Peter Rus.
Less interested in theology than Erasmus or More, he surpassed both in
philosophical depth. As one of the great pedagogues of his age, Vives proposed
a plan of education that substituted the Aristotelian ideal of speculative
certainty for a pragmatic probability capable of guiding action. Vives enlarged
the scope of women’s education (De institutione feminae Christianae, 1524) and
contributed to the teaching of classical Latin (Exercitatio linguae latinae,
1538). A chpion of EuroVisistadvaita Vedanta Vives, Juan Luis 962 962 pean unity against the Turks, he
professed the belief that international order (De concordia, 1526) depended
upon the control of passion (De anima et vita, 1538). As a social reformer,
Vives pioneered the secularization of welfare (De subventione pauperum, 1526)
and opposed the abuse of legal jargon (Aedes legum, 1520). Although his Jewish
parents were victimized by the Inquisition, Vives remained a Catholic and
managed to write an apology of Christianity without taking sides in
controversial theological matters (De veritate fidei, 1543). C.G.Nore.
volition, cf.
desideratum. a mental event involved with the initiation of action. ‘To will’
is sometimes taken to be the corresponding verb form of ‘volition’. The concept
of volition is rooted in modern philosophy; contemporary philosophers have
transformed it by identifying volitions with ordinary mental events, such as
intentions, or beliefs plus desires. Volitions, especially in contemporary
guises, are often taken to be complex mental events consisting of cognitive,
affective, and conative elements. The conative element is the impetus – the
underlying motivation – for the action. A velleity is a conative element
insufficient by itself to initiate action. The will is a faculty, or set of
abilities, that yields the mental events involved in initiating action. There
are three primary theories about the role of volitions in action. The first is
a reductive account in which action is identified with the entire causal
sequence of the mental event (the volition) causing the bodily behavior. J. S.
Mill, for exple, says: “Now what is action? Not one thing, but a series of two
things: the state of mind called a volition, followed by an effect. . . . [T]he
two together constitute the action” (Logic). Mary’s raising her arm is Mary’s
mental state causing her arm to rise. Neither Mary’s volitional state nor her
arm’s rising are themselves actions; rather, the entire causal sequence (the
“causing”) is the action. The primary difficulty for this account is
maintaining its reductive status. There is no way to delineate volition and the
resultant bodily behavior without referring to action. There are two
non-reductive accounts, one that identifies the action with the initiating
volition and another that identifies the action with the effect of the
volition. In the former, a volition is the action, and bodily movements are
mere causal consequences. Berkeley advocates this view: “The Mind . . . is to
be accounted active in . . . so far forth as volition is included. . . . In
plucking this flower I active, because I
do it by the motion of my hand, which was consequent upon my volition” (Three
Dialogues). In this century, Prichard is associated with this theory: “to act
is really to will something” (Moral Obligation, 1949), where willing is sui
generis (though at other places Prichard equates willing with the action of
mentally setting oneself to do something). In this sense, a volition is an act
of will. This account has come under attack by Ryle (Concept of Mind, 1949).
Ryle argues that it leads to a vicious regress, in that to will to do
something, one must will to will to do it, and so on. It has been countered
that the regress collapses; there is nothing beyond willing that one must do in
order to will. Another criticism of Ryle’s, which is more telling, is that
‘volition’ is an obscurantic term of art; “[volition] is an artificial concept.
We have to study certain specialist theories in order to find out how it is to
be manipulated. . . . [It is like] ‘phlogiston’ and ‘animal spirits’ . . .
[which] have now no utility” (Concept of Mind). Another approach, the causal
theory of action, identifies an action with the causal consequences of
volition. Locke, e.g., says: “Volition or willing is an act of the mind
directing its thought to the production of any action, and thereby exerting its
power to produce it. . . . [V]olition is nothing but that particular
determination of the mind, whereby . . . the mind endeavors to give rise,
continuation, or stop, to any action which it takes to be in its power” (Essay
concerning Human Understanding). This is a functional account, since an event
is an action in virtue of its causal role. Mary’s arm rising is Mary’s action
of raising her arm in virtue of being caused by her willing to raise it. If her
arm’s rising had been caused by a nervous twitch, it would not be action, even
if the bodily movements were photographically the se. In response to Ryle’s
charge of obscurantism, contemporary causal theorists tend to identify
volitions with ordinary mental events. For exple, Davidson takes the cause of
actions to be beliefs plus desires and Wilfrid Sellars takes volitions to be
intentions to do something here and now. Despite its plausibility, however, the
causal theory faces two difficult problems: the first is purported
counterexples based on wayward causal chains connecting the antecedent mental
event and the bodily movements; the second is provision of an enlightening
account of these mental events, e.g. intending, that does justice to the
conative element. ACTION THEORY, FREE
WILL PROBLEM, PRACTICAL REASONING, WAYWARD CAUSAL CHAIN. M.B. volition volition
Voltaire, pen ne of
François-Marie Arouet (1694–1778), French philosopher and writer who won early
fe as a playwright and poet and later was an influential popularizer of
Newtonian natural philosophy. His enduring reputation rests on his acerbically
witty essays on religious and moral topics (especially the Philosophical
Letters, 1734, and the Philosophical Dictionary, 1764), his brilliant stories,
and his passionate polemics against the injustices of the ancien régime. In
Whitehead’s phrase, he was more “a philosophe than a philosopher” in the
current specialized disciplinary sense. He borrowed most of his views on
metaphysics and epistemology from Locke, whose work, along with Newton’s, he ce
to know and extravagantly admire during his stay (1726–28) in England. His is
best placed in the line of great French literary moralists that includes
Montaigne, Pascal, Diderot, and Cus. Voltaire’s position is skeptical,
empirical, and humanistic. His skepticism is not of the radical sort that
concerned Descartes. But he denies that we can find adequate support for the
grand metaphysical claims of systematic philosophers, such as Leibniz, or for
the dogmatic theology of institutional religions. Voltaire’s empiricism urges
us to be content with the limited and fallible knowledge of our everyday
experience and its development through the methods of empirical science. His
humanism makes a plea, based on his empiricist skepticism, for religious and
social tolerance: none of us can know enough to be justified in persecuting
those who disagree with us on fundental philosophical and theological matters.
Voltaire’s positive view is that our human condition, for all its flaws and
perils, is meaningful and livable strictly in its own terms, quite apart from
any connection to the threats and promises of dubious transcendental realms.
Voltaire’s position is well illustrated by his views on religion. Although
complex doctrines about the Trinity or the Incarnation strike him as gratuitous
nonsense, he nonetheless is firmly convinced of the reality of a good God who
enjoins us through our moral sense to love one another as brothers and sisters.
Indeed, it is precisely this moral sense that he finds outraged by the
intolerance of institutional Christianity. His deepest religious thinking
concerns the problem of evil, which he treated in his “Poem of the Lisbon
Earthquake” and the classic tales Zadig (1747) and Candide (1759). He rejects
the Panglossian view (held by Candide’s Dr. Pangloss, a caricature of Leibniz)
that we can see the hand of providence in our daily life but is prepared to
acknowledge that an all-good God does not (as an extreme deism would hold) let
his universe just blindly run. Whatever metaphysical truth there may be in the
thought that “all is for the best in the best of all possible worlds,” Voltaire
insists that this idea is ludicrous as a practical response to evil and
recommends instead concrete action to solve specific local problems: “We must
cultivate our garden.” Voltaire was and remains an immensely controversial
figure. Will Durant regarded him as “the greatest man who ever lived,” while
Joseph de Maistre maintained that “admiration for Voltaire is an infallible
sign of a corrupt soul.” Perhaps it is enough to say that he wrote with
unequaled charm and wit and stood for values that are essential to, if perhaps
not the very core of, our humanity.
voluntarism, any
philosophical view that makes our ability to control the phenomena in question
an essential part of the correct understanding of those phenomena. Thus,
ethical voluntarism is the doctrine that the standards that define right and
wrong conduct are in some sense chosen by us. Doxastic voluntarism is the
doctrine that we have extensive control over what we believe; we choose what to
believe. A special case of doxastic voluntarism is theological voluntarism,
which implies that religious belief requires a substantial element of choice;
the evidence alone cannot decide the issue. This is a view that is closely
associated with Pascal, Kierkegaard, and Jes. Historical voluntarism is the
doctrine that the human will is a major factor in history. Such views contrast
with Marxist views of history. Metaphysical voluntarism is the doctrine, linked
with Schopenhauer, that the fundental organizing principle of the world is not
the incarnation of a rational or a moral order but rather the will, which for
Schopenhauer is an ultimately meaningless striving for survival, to be found in
all of nature. EPISTEMOLOGY. R.Fo.
voluntarism, doxastic.VOLUNTARISM. voluntarism, ethical.NATURAL LAW.
voluntarism, metaphysical.VOLUNTARISM. voluntarism, theological.VOLUNTARISM.
voluntary act.ACTION THEORY. voluntary euthanasia.EUTHANASIA. Voltaire
voluntary euthanasia 964 964
von Neumann, John
(1903–57), Hungarian-born erican mathematician, physicist, logician, economist,
engineer, and computer scientist. Born in Budapest and trained in Hungary,
Switzerland, and Germany, he visited Princeton University in 1930 and bece a
professor at the Institute for Advanced Study at Princeton in 1933. His most
outstanding work in pure mathematics was on rings of operators in Hilbert
spaces. In quantum mechanics he showed the equivalence of matrix mechanics to
wave mechanics, and argued that quantum mechanics could not be embedded in an
underlying deterministic system. He established important results in set theory
and mathematical logic, and worked on Hilbert’s Progr to prove the consistency
of mathematics within mathematics until he was shocked by Gödel’s
incompleteness theorems. He established the mathematical theory of ges and
later showed its application to economics. In these many different areas, von
Neumann demonstrated a remarkable ability to analyze a subject matter and
develop a mathematical formalism that answered basic questions about that subject
matter; formalization in logic is the special case of this process where the
subject matter is language and reasoning. With the advent of World War II von
Neumann turned his great analytical ability to more applied areas of
hydrodynics, ballistics, and nuclear explosives. In 1945 he began to work on
the design, use, and theory of electronic computers. He later bece a leading
scientist in government. Von Neumann contributed to the hardware architecture
of the modern electronic computer, and he invented the first modern progr
language. A progr in this language could change the addresses of its own
instructions, so that it bece possible to use the se subroutine on different
data structures and to write progrs to process progrs. Von Neumann proposed to use
a computer as a research tool for exploring very complex phenomena, such as the
discontinuous nature of shock waves. He began the development of a theory of
automata that would cover computing, communication, and control systems, as
well as natural organisms, biological evolution, and societies. To this end, he
initiated the study of probabilistic automata and of selfreproducing and
cellular automata. COGNITIVE SCIENCE,
COMPUTER THEORY, CYBERNETICS, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND, SELF-REPRODUCING AUTOMATON.
A.W.B.
von Wright, G. H., Finnish
philosopher, one of the most influential analytic philosophers of the twentieth
century. His early work, influenced by logical empiricism, is on logic,
probability, and induction, including contributions in modal and deontic logic,
the logic of norms and action, preference logic, tense logic, causality, and
determinism. In the 1970s his ideas about the explanation of action helped to
link the analytic tradition to Continental hermeneutics. His most important
contribution is A Treatise on Induction and Probability (1951), which develops
a system of eliminative induction using the concepts of necessary and
sufficient condition. In 1939 von Wright went to Cbridge to meet Broad, and he
attended Wittgenstein’s lectures. Regular discussions with Moore also had an
impact on him. In 1948 von Wright succeeded Wittgenstein as professor at
Cbridge University. After Wittgenstein’s death in 1951, von Wright returned to
Helsinki. Together with Anscombe and Rush Rhees, he bece executor and editor of
Wittgenstein’s Nachlass. The study, organization, systematization, and
publication of this exceptionally rich work bece a lifelong task for him. In
his Cbridge years von Wright bece interested in the logical properties of
various modalities: alethic, deontic, epistemic. An Essay in Modal Logic (1951)
studies, syntactically, various deductive systems of modal logic. That year he
published his fous article “Deontic Logic” in Mind. It made him the founder of
modern deontic logic. These logical works profoundly influenced analytic
philosophy, especially action theory. Von Wright distinguishes technical oughts
(means-ends relationships) from norms issued by a norm-authority. His Norm and
Action (1963) discusses philosophical problems concerning the existence of
norms and the truth of normative statements. His main work on metaethics is The
Varieties of Goodness (1963). In Explanation and Understanding (1971) he turned
to philosophical problems concerning the human sciences. He defends a
manipulation view of causality, where the concept of action is basic for that
of cause: human action cannot be explained causally by laws, but must be
understood intentionally. The basic model of intentionality is the practical
syllogism, which explains action by a logical connection with wants and
beliefs. This work, sometimes characterized as anti-positivist analytical
hermeneutics, bridges analytic and Continental philosophy. His studies in
truth, knowledge, modality, lawlikeness, causality, determinism, norms, and
practical inference were published in 1983–84 in his Philosophical Papers. von
Neumann, John von Wright, G. H. 965 965
In 1961 von Wright bece a member of the Academy of Finland, the highest honor
Finland gives to its scientists. Over many years he has written, in Swedish and
Finnish, eloquent essays in the history of ideas and the philosophy of culture.
He has become increasingly critical of the modern scientific-technological
civilization, its narrowly instrumental concept of rationality, and its myth of
progress. His public pleas for peace, human rights, and a more harmonious
coexistence of human beings and nature have made him the most esteemed
intellectual in the Scandinavian countries.
ACTION THEORY, DEONTIC LOGIC, EPISTEMIC LOGIC, PRACTICAL REASONING.
voting paradox, the
possibility that if there are three candidates, A, B, and C, for democratic
choice, with at least three choosers, and the choosers are asked to make
sequential choices ong pairs of candidates, A could defeat B by a majority
vote, B could defeat C, and C could defeat A. (This would be the outcome if the
choosers’ preferences were ABC, BCA, and CAB.) Hence, although each individual
voter may have a clear preference ordering over the candidates, the collective
may have cyclic preferences, so that individual and majoritarian collective
preference orderings are not analogous. While this fact is not a logical
paradox, it is perplexing to many analysts of social choice. It may also be
morally perplexing in that it suggests majority rule can be quite capricious.
For exple, suppose we vote sequentially over various pairs of candidates, with
the winner at each step facing a new candidate. If the candidates are favored
by cyclic majorities, the last candidate to enter the fray will win the final
vote. Hence, control over the sequence of votes may determine the outcome. It
is easy to find cyclic preferences over such candidates as movies and other
matters of taste. Hence, the problem of the voting paradox is clearly real and
not merely a logical contrivance. But is it important? Institutions may block
the generation of evidence for cyclic majorities by making choices pairwise and
sequentially, as above. And some issues over which we vote provoke preference
patterns that cannot produce cycles. For exple, if our issue is one of
unidimensional liberalism versus conservatism on some major political issue
such as welfare progrs, there may be no one who would prefer to spend both more
and less money than what is spent in the status quo. Hence, everyone may
display single-peaked preferences with preferences falling as we move in either
direction (toward more money or toward less) from the peak. If all important
issues and combinations of issues had this preference structure, the voting
paradox would be unimportant. It is widely supposed by many public choice
scholars that collective preferences are not single-peaked for many issues or,
therefore, for combinations of issues. Hence, collective choices may be quite
chaotic. What order they display may result from institutional manipulation. If
this is correct, we may wonder whether democracy in the sense of the
sovereignty of the electorate is a coherent notion. ARROW’S PARADOX, DECISION THEORY, SOCIAL
CHOICE THEORY.
Vorstellung voting
paradox 966 966 wang, pa, Chinese
political titles meaning ‘king’ and ‘hegemon’, respectively. A true wang has
the Mandate of Heaven and rules by te rather than by force. The institution of
the pa developed during a period in which the kings of China lacked any real
power. In order to bring an end to political chaos, the most powerful of the
nobles was appointed pa, and effectively ruled while the wang reigned. During
the Warring States period in China (403–221 B.C.), rulers began to assume the
title of wang regardless of whether they had either the power of a pa or the
right to rule of a wang. After this period, the title of Emperor (ti or huang-ti)
replaced wang.
Wang Ch’ung (A.D.
27–100?), Chinese philosopher, commonly regarded as the most independent-minded
thinker in the Later Han period (25–220). He wrote the Lun-heng (“Balanced
Inquiries”). Since Tung Chung-shu, Confucian doctrine of the unity of man and
nature had degenerated into one of mutual influence, with talk of strange
phenomena and calities abounding. Wang Ch’ung cast serious doubts on such
superstitions. He even dared to challenge the authority of Confucius and
Mencius. His outlook was naturalistic. According to him, things in the world
are produced by the interaction of material forces (ch’i). He rejected the
teleological point of view and was fatalistic.
Wang Fu-chih (1619–92), Chinese philosopher and innovative Confucian
thinker. Wang attacked the Neo-Confucian dualism of li (pattern) and ch’i
(ether), arguing that li is the orderly structure of individual ch’i (implements/things
and events), which are composed of ch’i (ether). Wang rejected all
transcendental ontology and believed society evolves and improves over time. He
is touted as a “materialist” by Marxist thinkers in contemporary China, though
the term is hardly applicable, as is clear from his criticisms of Shao Yung.
Wang attacked Shao’s overly “objective” account of the world, arguing that all
such formal descriptions fail because they disregard intuition, our only access
to the lively, shen (spiritual) nature of the universe.
Wang Pi (A.D. 226–49),
Chinese philosopher of the Hsüan hsüeh (Mysterious Learning) School. He is
described, along with thinkers like Kuo Hsiang, as a Neo-Taoist. Unlike Kuo,
who believed the world to be self-generated, Wang claimed it arose from a
mysterious unified state called wu (non-being). But like Kuo, Wang regarded
Confucius as the one true sage, arguing that Lao Tzu and Chuang Tzu only
“talked about” non-being, whereas Confucius embodied it. Wang is important for
his development of the notion li (pattern) and his pioneering use of the paired
concepts t’i (substance) and yung (function). His commentary on the Tao Te
Ching, the oldest known, has had a profound and persistent influence on later
Chinese thought. Wang Yang-ming (1472–1529),
Chinese philosopher known for his doctrines of the unity of knowledge and
action (chih-hsing ho-i) and liangchih (innate knowledge of the good). Wang was
also known as a sort of metaphysical idealist, anticipated by Lu Hsiang-shan,
for his insistence on the quasi-identity of mind and li (principle, reason).
The basic concern of Wang’s philosophy is the question, How can one become a
Confucian sage (sheng)? This is a question intelligible only in the light of
understanding and commitment to the Confucian vision of jen or ideal of the
universe as a moral community. Wang reminded his students that the concrete
significance of such a vision in human life cannot be exhausted with any claim
to finality. He stressed that one must get rid of any selfish desires in the
pursuit of jen. Unlike Chu Hsi, Wang showed little interest in empirical
inquiry concerning the rationales of existing things. For him, “things” are the
objectives of moral will. To investigate things is to rectify one’s mind, to
get rid of evil thoughts and to do good. Rectification of the mind involves, in
particular, an acknowledgment of the unity of moral knowledge and action
(chihhsing ho-i), an enlargement of the scope of moral concern in the light of
the vision of jen, rather than extensive acquisition of factual knowledge.
Ward, Jes (1843–1925),
English philosopher and psychologist. Influenced by Lotze, Herbart, and
Brentano, Ward sharply criticized Bain’s associationism and its allied
nineteenth-century reductive naturalism. His psychology rejected the
associationists’ sensationism, which regarded mind as passive, capable only of
sensory receptivity and composed solely of cognitive presentations. Ward
emphasized the mind’s inherent activity, asserting, like Kant, the prior
existence of an inferred but necessarily existing ego or subject capable of
feeling and, most importantly, of conation, shaping both experience and
behavior by the willful exercise of attention. Ward’s psychology stresses
attention and will. In his metaphysics, Ward resisted the naturalists’
mechanistic materialism, proposing instead a teleological spiritualistic
monism. While his criticisms of associationism and naturalism were telling,
Ward was a transitional figure whose positive influence is limited, if we
except H. P. Grice who follows him to a T. Although sympathetic to scientific
psychology – he founded scientific psychology in Britain by establishing a
psychology laboratory – he, with his
student Stout, represented the beginning of armchair psychology at Oxford, which
Grice adored. Through Stout he influenced the hormic psychology of McDougall,
and Grice who calls himself a Stoutian (“until Prichard converted me”). Ward’s
major work is “Psychology” (Encyclopedia Britannica, 9th ed., 1886), reworked
as Psychological Principles (1918).
wayward causal chain, a
causal chain, referred to in a proposed causal analysis of a key concept, that
goes awry. Causal analyses have been proposed for key concepts – e.g.,
reference, action, explanation, knowledge, artwork. There are two main cases of
wayward (or deviant) causal chains that defeat a causal analysis: (1) those in
which the prescribed causal route is followed, but the expected event does not
occur; and (2) those in which the expected event occurs, but the prescribed causal
route is not followed. Consider action. One proposed analysis is that a
person’s doing something is an action if and only if what he does is caused by
his beliefs and desires. The possibility of wayward causal chains defeats this
analysis. For case (1), suppose, while climbing, John finds he is supporting
another man on a rope. John wants to rid himself of this danger, and he
believes that he can do so by loosening his grip. His belief and desire unnerve
him, causing him to loosen his hold. The prescribed causal route was followed,
but the ensuing event, his grip loosening, is not an action. For case (2),
suppose Harry wants to kill his rich uncle, and he believes that he can find
him at home. His beliefs and desires so agitate him that he drives recklessly.
He hits and kills a pedestrian, who, by chance, is his uncle. The killing
occurs, but without following the prescribed causal route; the killing was an
accidental consequence of what Harry did.
ACTION THEORY.
Weber, Max (1864–1920),
German social theorist and sociologist. Born in Berlin in a liberal and
intellectual household, he taught economics in Heidelberg, where his circle
included leading sociologists and philosophers such as Simmel and Lukacs.
Although Weber gave up his professorship after a nervous breakdown in 1889, he
remained important in public life, an adviser to the commissions that drafted
the peace treaty at Versailles and the Weimar constitution. Weber’s social
theory was influenced philosophically by both neo-Kantianism and Nietzsche,
creating tensions in a theorist who focused much of his attention on Occidental
rationalism and yet was a noncognitivist in ethics. He wrote many comparative
studies on topics such as law and urbanization and a celebrated study of the
cultural factors responsible for the rise of capitalism, The Protestant Ethic
and the Spirit of Capitalism (1904). But his major, synthetic work in social
theory is Economy and Society (1914); it includes a methodological introduction
to the basic concepts of sociology that has been treated by many philosophers
of social science. One of the main theoretical goals of Weber’s work is to
understand how social processes become “rationalized,” taking up certain themes
want-belief model Weber, Max 968 of the
German philosophy of history since Hegel as part of social theory. Culture,
e.g., bece rationalized in the process of the “disenchantment of worldviews” in
the West, a process that Weber thought had “universal significance.” But because
of his goal-oriented theory of action and his noncognitivism in ethics, Weber
saw rationalization exclusively in terms of the spread of purposive, or
means–ends rationality (Zweckrationalität). Rational action means choosing the
most effective means of achieving one’s goals and implies judging the
consequences of one’s actions and choices. In contrast, value rationality
(Wertrationalität) consists of actions oriented to ultimate ends, where
considerations of consequences are irrelevant. Although such action is rational
insofar as it directs and organizes human conduct, the choice of such ends or
values themselves cannot be a matter for rational or scientific judgment.
Indeed, for Weber this meant that politics was the sphere for the struggle
between irreducibly competing ultimate ends, where “gods and demons fight it
out” and charismatic leaders invent new gods and values. Professional
politicians, however, should act according to an “ethics of responsibility”
(Verantwortungsethik) aimed at consequences, and not an “ethics of conviction”
(Gesinnungsethik) aimed at abstract principles or ultimate ends. Weber also
believed that rationalization brought the separation of “value spheres” that
can never again be unified by reason: art, science, and morality have their own
“logics.” Weber’s influential methodological writings reject positivist
philosophy of science, yet call for “value neutrality.” He accepts the
neo-Kantian distinction, common in his day under the influence of Rickert,
between the natural and the human sciences, between the Natur- and the Geisteswissenschaften.
Because human social action is purposive and meaningful, the explanations of
social sciences must be related to the values (Wertbezogen) and ideals of the
actors it studies. Against positivism, Weber saw an ineliminable element of Verstehen,
or understanding of meanings, in the methodology of the human sciences. For
exple, he criticized the legal positivist notion of behavioral conformity for
failing to refer to actors’ beliefs in legitimacy. But for Weber Verstehen is
not intuition or empathy and does not exclude causal analysis; reasons can be
causes. Thus, explanations in social science must have both causal and
subjective adequacy. Weber also thought that adequate explanations of
large-scale, macrosocial phenomena require the construction of ideal types,
which abstract and summarize the common features of complex, empirical
phenomena such as “sects,” “authority,” or even “the Protestant ethic.”
Weberian ideal types are neither merely descriptive nor simply heuristic, but
come at the end of inquiry through the successful theoretical analysis of
diverse phenomena in various historical and cultural contexts. Weber’s analysis
of rationality as the disenchantment of the world and the spread of purposive
reason led him to argue that reason and progress could turn into their
opposites, a notion that enormously influenced critical theory. Weber had a
critical “diagnosis of the times” and a pessimistic philosophy of history. At
the end of The Protestant Ethic Weber warns that rationalism is desiccating
sources of value and constructing an “iron cage” of increasing
bureaucratization, resulting in a loss of meaning and freedom in social life.
According to Weber, these basic tensions of modern rationality cannot be
resolved.
Weil, Simone (1909–43),
French religious philosopher and writer. Born in Paris, Weil was one of the
first women to graduate from the École Normale Supérieure, having earlier
studied under the philosopher Alain. While teaching in various French lycées
Weil bece involved in radical leftist politics, and her early works concern
social problems and labor. They also show an attempt to work out a theory of
action as fundental to human knowing. This is seen first in her diploma essay,
“Science and Perception in Descartes,” and later in her critique of Marx,
capitalism, and technocracy in “Reflections concerning the Causes of Social
Oppression and Liberty.” Believing that humans cannot escape certain basic
harsh necessities of embodied life, Weil sought to find a way by which freedom
and dignity could be achieved by organizing labor in such a way that the mind
could understand that necessity and thereby come to consent to it. After a year
of testing her theories by working in three factories in 1934–35, Weil’s early
optimism was shattered by the discovery of what she called “affliction”
(malheur), a destruction of the human person to which one cannot consent. Three
important religious experiences, however, caused her to attempt to put the
problem into a Weber’s law Weil, Simone 969
969 larger context. By arguing that necessity obeys a transcendent
goodness and then by using a kenotic model of Christ’s incarnation and
crucifixion, she tried to show that affliction can have a purpose and be
morally enlightening. The key is the renunciation of any ultimate possession of
power as well as the social personality constituted by that power. This is a
process of “attention” and “decreation” by which one sheds the veil that
otherwise separates one from appreciating goodness in anything but oneself, but
most especially from God. She understands God as a goodness that is revealed in
self-emptying and in incarnation, and creation as an act of renunciation and
not power. During her last months, while working for the Free French in London,
Weil’s social and religious interests ce together, especially in The Need for
Roots. Beginning with a critique of social rights and replacing it with
obligations, Weil sought to show, on the one hand, how modern societies had
illegitimately become the focus of value, and on the other hand, how cultures
could be reconstructed so that they would root humans in something more
ultimate than themselves. Returning to her earlier themes, Weil argued that in
order for this rootedness to occur, physical labor must become the spiritual
core of culture. Weil died of tuberculosis while this book was in progress.
Often regarded as mystical and syncretistic, Weil’s philosophy owes much to an
original reading of Plato (e.g., in Intimations of Christianity ong the Ancient
Greeks) as well as to Marx, Alain, and Christianity. Recent studies, however,
have also seen her as significantly contributing to social, moral, and
religious philosophy. Her concern with problems of action and persons is not
dissimilar to Wittgenstein’s. MARX,
PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION.
well-formed formula, a
grmatically wellformed sentence or (structured) predicate of an artificial
language of the sort studied by logicians. A well-formed formula is sometimes
known as a wff (pronounced ‘woof’) or simply a formula. Delineating the
formulas of a language involves providing it with a syntax or grmar, composed
of both a vocabulary (a specification of the symbols from which the language is
to be built, sorted into grmatical categories) and formation rules (a purely
formal or syntactical specification of which strings of symbols are grmatically
well-formed and which are not). Formulas are classified as either open or
closed, depending on whether or not they contain free variables (variables not
bound by quantifiers). Closed formulas, such as (x) (Fx / Gx), are sentences,
the potential bearers of truth-values. Open formulas, such as Fx / Gx, are
handled in any of three ways. On some accounts, these formulas are on a par
with closed ones, the free variables being treated as nes. On others, open
formulas are (structured) predicates, the free variables being treated as place
holders for terms. And on still other accounts, the free variables are regarded
as implicitly bound by universal quantifiers, again making open formulas
sentences. FORMAL LOGIC, LOGICAL
CONSTANT, LOGICAL SYNTAX, QUANTIFICATION.
Westermarck: philosopher
who spent his life studying the mores and morals of cultures. His main works,
The Origin and Development of Moral Ideas and Ethical Relativity, attack the
idea that moral principles express objective value. In defending ethical
relativism, he argued that moral judgments are based not on intellectual but on
emotional grounds. He admitted that cultural variability in itself does not
prove ethical relativism, but contended that the fundental differences are so
comprehensive and deep as to constitute a strong presumption in favor of
relativism. ETHICAL OBJECTIVISM,
RELATIVISM.
wheel of
rebirth.BUDDHISM, SSARA. Whewell, Willi (1794–1866), English historian,
astronomer, and philosopher of science. He was a master of Trinity College,
Cbridge (1841–66). Francis Bacon’s early work on induction was furthered by
Whewell, J. F. W. Herschel, and J. S. Mill, who attempted to create a logic of
welfare economics Whewell, Willi 970 970 induction, a methodology that can both
discover generalizations about experience and prove them to be necessary.
Whewell’s theory of scientific method is based on his reading of the history of
the inductive sciences. He thought that induction began with a non-inferential
act, the superimposition of an idea on data, a “colligation,” a way of seeing
facts in a “new light.” Colligations generalize over data, and must satisfy
three “tests of truth.” First, colligations must be empirically adequate; they
must account for the given data. Any number of ideas may be adequate to explain
given data, so a more severe test is required. Second, because colligations
introduce generalizations, they must apply to events or properties of objects
not yet given: they must provide successful predictions, thereby enlarging the
evidence in favor of the colligation. Third, the best inductions are those
where evidence for various hypotheses originally thought to cover unrelated
kinds of data “jumps together,” providing a consilience of inductions.
Consilience characterizes those theories achieving large measures of
simplicity, generality, unification, and deductive strength. Furthermore,
consilience is a test of the necessary truth of theories, which implies that
what many regard as merely pragmatic virtues of theories like simplicity and
unifying force have an epistemic status. Whewell thus provides a strong
argument for scientific realism. Whewell’s exples of consilient theories are
Newton’s theory of universal gravitation, which covers phenomena as seemingly
diverse as the motions of the heavenly bodies and the motions of the tides, and
the undulatory theory of light, which explains both the polarization of light
by crystals and the colors of fringes. There is evidence that Whewell’s
methodology was employed by Maxwell, who designed the influential Cavendish
Laboratories at Cbridge. Peirce and Mach favored Whewell’s account of method
over Mill’s empiricist theory of induction.
EXPLANATION, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. R.E.B. Whichcote, Benjin.CBRIDGE
PLATONISTS.
Whitehead, A. N.
(1861–1947), English mathematician, logician, philosopher of science, and
metaphysician. Educated first at the Sherborne School in Dorsetshire and then
at Trinity College, Cbridge, Whitehead emerged as a first-class mathematician
with a rich general background. In 1885 he bece a fellow of Trinity College and
remained there in a teaching role until 1910. In the early 1890s Bertrand
Russell entered Trinity College as a student in mathematics; by the beginning of
the new century Russell had become not only a student and friend but a
colleague of Whitehead’s at Trinity College. Each had written a first book on
algebra (Whitehead’s A Treatise on Universal Algebra won him election to the
Royal Society in 1903). When they discovered that their projected second books
largely overlapped, they undertook a collaboration on a volume that they
estimated would take about a year to write; in fact, it was a decade later that
the three volumes of their ground-breaking Principia Mathematica appeared,
launching symbolic logic in its modern form. In the second decade of this
century Whitehead and Russell drifted apart; their responses to World War I
differed radically, and their intellectual interests and orientations diverged.
Whitehead’s London period (1910–24) is often viewed as the second phase of a
three-phase career. His association with the University of London involved him
in practical issues affecting the character of working-class education. For a
decade (1914–24) Whitehead held a professorship at the Imperial College of
Science and Technology and also served as dean of the Faculty of Science in the
University, chair of the Academic Council (which managed educational affairs in
London), and chair of the council that managed Goldsmith’s College. His book
The Aims of Education (1928) is a collection of essays largely growing out of
reflections on the experiences of these years. Intellectually, Whitehead’s
interests were moving toward issues in the philosophy of science. In the years
1919–22 he published An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge,
The Concept of Nature, and The Principle of Relativity – the third led to his
later (1931) election as a fellow of the British Academy. In 1924, at the age
of sixty-three, Whitehead made a dratic move, both geographically and
intellectually, to launch phase three of his career: never having formally
studied philosophy in his life, he agreed to become professor of philosophy at
Harvard University, a position he held until retirement in 1937. The
accompanying intellectual shift was a move from philosophy of science to
metaphysics. The earlier investigations had assumed the self-containedness of
nature: “nature is closed to mind.” The philosophy of nature exined nature at the
level of abstraction entailed by this assumption. Whitehead had come to regard
philosophy as “the critic of abstractions,” a notion introduced in Science and
the Modern World (1925). This book traced the intertwined emergence of
Newtonian science and its philosophical presuppositions. It noted that with the
development of the theory of relativity in the twentieth century, scientific
understanding had left behind the Newtonian conceptuality that had generated
the still-dominant philosophical assumptions, and that those philosophical
assumptions considered in themselves had become inadequate to explicate our
full concrete experience. Philosophy as the critic of abstractions must
recognize the limitations of a stance that assumes that nature is closed to mind,
and must push deeper, beyond such an abstraction, to create a scheme of ideas
more in harmony with scientific developments and able to do justice to human
beings as part of nature. Science and the Modern World merely outlines what
such a philosophy might be; in 1929 Whitehead published his magnum opus, titled
Process and Reality. In this volume, subtitled “An Essay in Cosmology,” his
metaphysical understanding is given its final form. It is customary to regard
this book as the central document of what has become known as process
philosophy, though Whitehead himself frequently spoke of his system of ideas as
the philosophy of organism. Process and Reality begins with a sentence that
sheds a great deal of light upon Whitehead’s metaphysical orientation: “These
lectures are based upon a recurrence to that phase of philosophic thought which
began with Descartes and ended with Hume.” Descartes, adapting the classical
notion of substance to his own purposes, begins a “phase of philosophic
thought” by assuming there are two distinct, utterly different kinds of
substance, mind and matter, each requiring nothing but itself in order to
exist. This assumption launches the reign of epistemology within philosophy: if
knowing begins with the experiencing of a mental substance capable of existing
by itself and cut off from everything external to it, then the philosophical
challenge is to try to justify the claim to establish contact with a reality
external to it. The phrase “and ended with Hume” expresses Whitehead’s conviction
that Hume (and more elegantly, he notes, Santayana) showed that if one begins
with Descartes’s metaphysical assumptions, skepticism is inevitable.
Contemporary philosophers have talked about the end of philosophy. From
Whitehead’s perspective such talk presupposes a far too narrow view of the
nature of philosophy. It is true that a phase of philosophy has ended, a phase
dominated by epistemology. Whitehead’s response is to offer the dictum that all
epistemological difficulties are at bottom only couflaged metaphysical
difficulties. One must return to that moment of Cartesian beginning and replace
the substance metaphysics with an orientation that avoids the epistemological
trap, meshes harmoniously with the scientific understandings that have
displaced the much simpler physics of Descartes’s day, and is consonant with
the facts of evolution. These are the considerations that generate Whitehead’s
fundental metaphysical category, the category of an actual occasion. An actual
occasion is not an enduring, substantial entity. Rather, it is a process of
becoming, a process of weaving together the “prehensions” (a primitive form of
‘apprehension’ meant to indicate a “taking account of,” or “feeling,” devoid of
conscious awareness) of the actual occasions that are in the immediate past.
Whitehead calls this process of weaving together the inheritances of the past
“concrescence.” An actual entity is its process of concrescence, its process of
growing together into a unified perspective on its immediate past. (The seeds
of Whitehead’s epistemological realism are planted in these fundental first
moves: “The philosophy of organism is the inversion of Kant’s philosophy. . . .
For Kant, the world emerges from the subject; for the philosophy of organism,
the subject emerges from the world.”) It is customary to compare an actual
occasion with a Leibnizian monad, with the caveat that whereas a monad is
windowless, an actual occasion is “all window.” It is as though one were to
take Aristotle’s system of categories and ask what would result if the category
of substance were displaced from its position of preeminence by the category of
relation – the result would, mutatis mutandis, be an understanding of being
somewhat on the model of a Whiteheadian actual occasion. In moving from
Descartes’s dualism of mental substance and material substance to his own
notion of an actual entity, Whitehead has been doing philosophy conceived of as
the critique of abstractions. He holds that both mind and matter are
abstractions from the concretely real. They are important abstractions,
necessary for everyday thought and, of supreme importance, absolutely essential
in enabling the seventeenth through nineteenth centuries to accomplish their
magnificent advances in scientific thinking. Indeed, Whitehead, in his
philosophy of science phase, by proceeding as though “nature is closed to
mind,” was operating with those selfse abstractions. He ce to see that while
these abstractions were indispensable for certain kinds of investigations, they
were, at the philosophical level, as Hume had demonstrated, a disaster. In
considering mind and matter to be ontological ultimates, Descartes had
committed what Whitehead termed the fallacy of misplaced concreteness. The
category of an actual occasion designates the fully real, the fully concrete.
The challenge for such an orientation, the challenge that Process and Reality
is designed to meet, is so to describe actual occasions that it is intelligible
how collections of actual occasions, termed “nexus” or societies, emerge,
exhibiting the characteristics we find associated with “minds” and “material
structures.” Perhaps most significantly, if this challenge is met successfully,
biology will be placed, in the eyes of philosophy, on an even footing with
physics; metaphysics will do justice both to human beings and to human beings
as a part of nature; and such vexing contemporary problem areas as animal
rights and environmental ethics will appear in a new light. Whitehead’s last
two books, Adventures of Ideas (1933) and Modes of Thought (1938), are less
technical and more lyrical than is Process and Reality. Adventures of Ideas is
clearly the more significant of these two. It presents a philosophical study of
the notion of civilization. It holds that the social changes in a civilization
are driven by two sorts of forces: brute, senseless agencies of compulsion on
the one hand, and formulated aspirations and articulated beliefs on the other.
(These two sorts of forces are epitomized by barbarians and Christianity in the
ancient Roman world and by ste and democracy in the world of the industrial
revolution.) Whitehead’s focal point in Adventures of Ideas is aspirations,
beliefs, and ideals as instruments of change. In particular, he is concerned to
articulate the ideals and aspirations appropriate to our own era. The character
of such ideals and aspirations at any moment is limited by the philosophical
understandings available at that moment, because in their struggle for release
and efficacy such ideals and aspirations can appear only in the forms permitted
by the available philosophical discourse. In the final section of Adventures of
Ideas Whitehead presents a statement of ideals and aspirations fit for our era
as his own philosophy of organism allows them to take shape and be articulated.
The notions of beauty, truth, adventure, zest, Eros, and peace are given a
content drawn from the technical understandings elaborated in Process and
Reality. But in Adventures of Ideas a less technical language is used, a
language reminiscent of the poetic imagery found in the style of Plato’s
Republic, a language making the ideas accessible to readers who have not
mastered Process and Reality, but at the se time far richer and more meaningful
to those who have. Whitehead notes in Adventures of Ideas that Plato’s later
thought “circles round the interweaving of seven main notions, nely, The Ideas,
The Physical Elements, The Psyche, The Eros, The Harmony, The Mathematical
Relations, The Receptacle. These notions are as important for us now, as they
were then at the dawn of the modern world, when civilizations of the old type
were dying.” Whitehead uses these notions in quite novel and modern ways; one
who is unfiliar with his metaphysics can get something of what he means as he
speaks of the Eros of the Universe, but if one is filiar from Process and
Reality with the notions of the Primordial Nature of God and the Consequent
Nature of God then one sees much deeper into the meanings present in Adventures
of Ideas. Whitehead was not religious in any narrow, doctrinal, sectarian
sense. He explicitly likened his stance to that of Aristotle, dispassionately
considering the requirements of his metaphysical system as they refer to the
question of the existence and nature of God. Whitehead’s thoughts on these
matters are most fully developed in Chapter 11 of Science and the Modern World,
in the final chapter of Process and Reality, and in Religion in the Making
(1926). These thoughts are expressed at a high level of generality. Perhaps
because of this, a large part of the interest generated by Whitehead’s thought
has been within the community of theologians. His ideas fairly beg for
elaboration and development in the context of particular modes of religious
understanding. It is as though many modern theologians, recalling the relation
between the theology of Aquinas and the metaphysics of Aristotle, cannot resist
the temptation to play Aquinas to Whitehead’s Aristotle. Process theology, or
Neo-Classical Theology as it is referred to by Hartshorne, one of its leading
practitioners, has been the arena within which a great deal of clarification
and development of Whitehead’s ideas has occurred. Whitehead was a gentle man,
soft-spoken, never overbearing or threatening. He constantly encouraged
students to step out on their own, to develop their creative capacities. His
concern not to inhibit students made him a notoriously easy grader; it was said
that an A-minus in one of his courses was equivalent to failure. Lucien Price’s
Dialogues of Alfred North Whitehead chronicles many evenings of discussion in
the Whitehead household. He there described Whitehead as follows: Whitehead,
Alfred North Whitehead, Alfred North 973
973 his face, serene, luminous, often smiling, the complexion pink and
white, the eyes brilliant blue, clear and candid as a child’s yet with the
depth of the sage, often laughing or twinkling with humour. And there was his
figure, slender, frail, and bent with its lifetime of a scholar’s toil. Always
benign, there was not a grain of ill will anywhere in him; for all his
formidable arment, never a wounding word.
LEIBNIZ, METAPHYSICS, PROCESS THEOLOGY, RUSSELL.
Alnwick -- (d. 1333),
English Franciscan theologian. Willi studied under Duns Scotus at Paris, and
wrote the Reportatio Parisiensia, a central source for Duns Scotus’s teaching.
In his own works, Willi opposed Scotus on the univocity of being and
haecceitas. Some of his views were attacked by Ockh. DUNS SCOTUS, HAECCEITY.
Willi of Auvergne
(c.1190–1249), French philosopher who was born in Aurillac, taught at Paris,
and bece bishop of Paris in 1228. Critical of the new Aristotelianism of his
time, he insisted that the soul is an individual, immortal form of intellectual
activity alone, so that a second form was needed for the body and sensation.
Though he rejected the notion of an agent intellect, he described the soul as a
mirror that reflects both exemplary ideas in God’s mind and sensible singulars.
He conceived being as something common to everything that is, after the manner
of Duns Scotus, but rejected the Avicennan doctrine that God necessarily
produces the universe, arguing that His creative activity is free of all
determination. He is the first exple of the complex of ideas we call
Augustinianism, which would pass on through Alexander of Hales to Bonaventure
and other Franciscans, forming a point of departure for the philosophy of Duns
Scotus. AUGUSTINE, DUNS SCOTUS.
Willi of Auxerre
(c.1140–1231), French theologian and renowned teacher of grmar, arts, and
theology at the University of Paris. In 1231 he was appointed by Pope Gregory
IX to a commission charged with editing Aristotle’s writings for doctrinal
purity. The commission never submitted a report, perhaps partly due to Willi’s
death later that se year. Willi’s major work, the Summa aurea (1215–20),
represents one of the earliest systematic attempts to reconcile the Augustinian
and Aristotelian traditions in medieval philosophy. Willi tempers, e.g., the
Aristotelian concession that human cognition begins with the reception in the material
intellect of a species or sensible representation from a corporeal thing, with
the Augustinian idea that it is not possible to understand the principles of
any discipline without an interior, supernatural illumination. He also
originated the theological distinction between perfect happiness, which is
uncreated and proper to God, and imperfect happiness, which pertains to human
beings. Willi was also one of the first to express what bece, in later
centuries, the important distinction between God’s absolute and ordained
powers, taking, with Gilbert of Poitiers, the view that God could, absolutely
speaking, change the past. The Summa aurea helped shape the thought of several
important philosophers and theologians who were active later in the century, including
Albertus Magnus, Bonaventure, and Aquinas. Willi remained an authority in
theological discussions throughout the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries. ARISTOTLE, AUGUSTINE.
Willi of Moerbeke
(c.1215–1286), French scholar who was the most important thirteenth century
translator from Greek into Latin of works in philosophy and natural science.
Having joined the Dominicans and spent some time in Greek-speaking territories,
Willi served at the papal court and then as (Catholic) archbishop of Corinth
(1278–c.1286). But he worked from the 1260s on as a careful and literal-minded
translator. Willi was the first to render into Latin white horse paradox Willi
of Moerbeke 974 974 some of the most
important works by Aristotle, including the Politics, Poetics, and History of
Animals. He retranslated or revised earlier translations of several other
Aristotelian works. Willi also provided the first Latin versions of
commentaries on Aristotle by Alexander of Aphrodisias, Themistius, monius, John
Philoponus, and Simplicius, not to mention his efforts on behalf of Greek
optics, mathematics, and medicine. When Willi provided the first Latin
translation of Proclus’s Elements of Theology, Western readers could at last
recognize the Liber de causis as an Arabic compilation from Proclus rather than
as a work by Aristotle.
Willis: B. A. O.
London-born Welsh philosopher who has made major contributions to many fields
but is primarily known as a moral philosopher. His approach to ethics, set out
in Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (1985), is characterized by a
wide-ranging skepticism, directed mainly at the capacity of academic moral
philosophy to further the aim of reflectively living an ethical life. One line
of skeptical argument attacks the very idea of practical reason. Attributions
of practical reasons to a particular agent must, in Willis’s view, be
attributions of states that can potentially explain the agent’s action.
Therefore such reasons must be either within the agent’s existing set of
motivations or within the revised set of motivations that the agent would
acquire upon sound reasoning. Willis argues from these minimal assumptions that
this view of reasons as internal reasons undermines the idea of reason itself
being a source of authority over practice. Willis’s connected skepticism about
the claims of moral realism is based both on his general stance toward realism
and on his view of the nature of modern societies. In opposition to internal
realism, Willis has consistently argued that reflection on our conception of
the world allows one to develop a conception of the world maximally independent
of our peculiar ways of conceptualizing reality – an absolute conception of the
world. Such absoluteness is, he argues, an inappropriate aspiration for ethical
thought. Our ethical thinking is better viewed as one way of structuring a form
of ethical life than as the ethical truth about how life is best lived. The
pervasive reflectiveness and radical pluralism of modern societies makes them
inhospitable contexts for viewing ethical concepts as making knowledge
available to groups of concept users. Modernity has produced at the level of
theory a distortion of our ethical practice, nely a conception of the morality
system. This view is reductionist, is focused centrally on obligations, and
rests on various fictions about responsibility and ble that Willis challenges
in such works as She and Necessity (1993). Much academic moral philosophy, in
his view, is shaped by the covert influence of the morality system, and such
distinctively modern outlooks as Kantianism and utilitarianism monopolize the
terms of contemporary debate with insufficient attention to their origin in a
distorted view of the ethical. Willis’s views are not skeptical through and
through; he retains a commitment to the values of truth, truthfulness in a
life, and individualism. His most recent work, which thematizes the
long-implicit influence of Nietzsche on his ethical philosophy, explicitly
offers a vindicatory “genealogical” narrative for these ideals. EXTERNALISM, MORALITY, MORAL REALISM, NIETZSCHE,
PRACTICAL REASON.
Wilson, J. C. Oxonian
philosopher, like Grice. Cook Wilson studied with T. H. Green before becoming
Wykeh Professor of Logic at Oxford and leading the Oxford reaction against the
then entrenched absolute idealism. More influential as a tutor than as a
writer, his major oeuvre, Statement and Inference, was posthumously
reconstructed from drafts of papers, philosophical correspondence, and an
extensive set of often inconsistent lectures for his logic courses. A staunch
critic of Whitehead’s mathematical logic, Wilson conceived of logic as the
study of thinking, an activity unified by the fact that thinking either is
knowledge or depends on knowledge (“What we know we kow”). Wilson claims that
knowledge involves apprehending an object that in most cases is independent of
the act of apprehension and that knowledge is indefinable without circularity,
views he defended by appealing to common usage. Many of Wilson’s ideas are
disseminated by H. W. B. Joseph, especially in his “Logic.” Rejecting “symbolic
logic,” Joseph attempts to reinvigorate traditional logic conceived along
Wilsonian lines. To do so Joseph combined a careful exposition of Aristotle
with insights drawn from idealistic logicians. Besides Joseph, Wilson
decisively influenced a generation of Oxford philosophers including Prichard
and Ross, and Grice who explores the ‘interrogative subordination’ in the
account of ‘if.’ (“Who killed Cock Robin”).
Windelband, Wilhelm
(1848–1915), German philosopher and originator of Baden neoKantianism. He
studied under Kuno Fischer (1824–1907) and Lotze, and was professor at Zürich,
Freiburg, Strasbourg, and Heidelberg. Windelband gave Baden neo-Kantianism its
distinctive mark of Kantian axiology as the core of critical philosophy. He is
widely recognized for innovative work in the history of philosophy, in which
problems rather than individual philosophers are the focus and organizing
principle of exposition. He is also known for his distinction, first drawn in
“Geschichte und Naturwissenschaft” (“History and Natural Science,” 1894),
between the nomothetic knowledge that most natural sciences seek (the discovery
of general laws in order to master nature) and the idiographic knowledge that
the historical sciences pursue (description of individual and unique aspects of
reality with the aim of self-affirmation). His most important student, and
successor at Heidelberg, was Heinrich Rickert (1863– 1936), who made lasting
contributions to the methodology of the historical sciences. NEO-KANTIANISM. H.v.d.L. wisdom, an
understanding of the highest principles of things that functions as a guide for
living a truly exemplary human life. From the preSocratics through Plato this
was a unified notion. But Aristotle introduced a distinction between
theoretical wisdom (sophia) and practical wisdom (phronesis), the former being
the intellectual virtue that disposed one to grasp the nature of reality in
terms of its ultimate causes (metaphysics), the latter being the ultimate practical
virtue that disposed one to make sound judgments bearing on the conduct of
life. The former invoked a contrast between deep understanding versus wide
information, whereas the latter invoked a contrast between sound judgment and
mere technical facility. This distinction between theoretical and practical
wisdom persisted through the Middle Ages and continues to our own day, as is
evident in our use of the term ‘wisdom’ to designate both knowledge of the
highest kind and the capacity for sound judgment in matters of conduct. ARISTOTLE, PRACTICAL REASON, THEORETICAL
REASON.
Vitters, Ludwig
(1889–1951), Vienna-born philosopher (trained as an enginner at Manchester),
one of the most original and challenging philosophical writers of the twentieth
century. Born in Vienna into an assimilated fily of Jewish extraction, he went
to England as a student and eventually bece a protégé of Russell’s at Cbridge.
He returned to Austria at the beginning of The Great War I, but went back to
Cbridge in 1928 and taught there as a fellow and professor. Despite spending
much of his professional life in England, Wittgenstein never lost contact with
his Austrian background, and his writings combine in a unique way ideas derived
from both the insular and the continental European tradition. His thought is
strongly marked by a deep skepticism about philosophy, but he retained the
conviction that there was something important to be rescued from the
traditional enterprise. In his Blue Book (1958) he referred to his own work as
“one of the heirs of the subject that used to be called philosophy.” What
strikes readers first when they look at Wittgenstein’s writings is the peculiar
form of their composition. They are generally made up of short individual notes
that are most often numbered in sequence and, in the more finished writings,
evidently selected and arranged with the greatest care. Those notes range from
fairly technical discussions on matters of logic, the mind, meaning,
understanding, acting, seeing, mathematics, and knowledge, to aphoristic
observations about ethics, culture, art, and the meaning of life. Because of
their wide-ranging character, their unusual perspective on things, and their
often intriguing style, Wittgenstein’s writings have proved to appeal to both
professional philosophers and those interested in philosophy in a more general
way. The writings as well as his unusual life and personality have already
produced a large body of interpretive literature. But given his uncompromising
stand, it is questionable whether his thought will ever be fully integrated
into academic philosophy. It is more likely that, like Pascal and Nietzsche, he
will remain an uneasy presence in philosophy. From an early date onward
Wittgenstein was greatly influenced by the idea that philosophical problems can
be resolved by paying attention to the working of language – a thought he may
have gained from Fritz Mauthner’s Beiträge zu einer Kritik der Sprache
(1901–02). Wittgenstein’s affinity to Mauthner is, indeed, evident in all
phases of his philosophical development, though it is particularly noticeable
in his later thinking.Until recently it has been common to divide
Wittgenstein’s work into two sharply distinct phases, separated by a prolonged
period of dormancy. According to this schema the early (“Tractarian”) period is
that of the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (1921), which Wittgenstein wrote in
the trenches of World War I, and the later period that of the Philosophical
Investigations (1953), which he composed between 1936 and 1948. But the
division of his work into these two periods has proved misleading. First, in
spite of obvious changes in his thinking, Wittgenstein remained throughout
skeptical toward traditional philosophy and persisted in channeling
philosophical questioning in a new direction. Second, the common view fails to
account for the fact that even between 1920 and 1928, when Wittgenstein
abstained from actual work in philosophy, he read widely in philosophical and
semiphilosophical authors, and between 1928 and 1936 he renewed his interest in
philosophical work and wrote copiously on philosophical matters. The posthumous
publication of texts such as The Blue and Brown Books, Philosophical Grmar,
Philosophical Remarks, and Conversations with the Vienna Circle has led to acknowledgment
of a middle period in Wittgenstein’s development, in which he explored a large
number of philosophical issues and viewpoints – a period that served as a
transition between the early and the late work. Early period. As the son of a
greatly successful industrialist and engineer, Wittgenstein first studied
engineering in Berlin and Manchester, and traces of that early training are
evident throughout his writing. But his interest shifted soon to pure
mathematics and the foundations of mathematics, and in pursuing questions about
them he bece acquainted with Russell and Frege and their work. The two men had
a profound and lasting effect on Wittgenstein even when he later ce to
criticize and reject their ideas. That influence is particularly noticeable in
the Tractatus, which can be read as an attempt to reconcile Russell’s atomism
with Frege’s apriorism. But the book is at the se time moved by quite different
and non-technical concerns. For even before turning to systematic philosophy
Wittgenstein had been profoundly moved by Schopenhauer’s thought as it is
spelled out in The World as Will and Representation, and while he was serving
as a soldier in World War I, he renewed his interest in Schopenhauer’s
metaphysical, ethical, aesthetic, and mystical outlook. The resulting
confluence of ideas is evident in the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus and gives
the book its peculiar character. Composed in a dauntingly severe and compressed
style, the book attempts to show that traditional philosophy rests entirely on
a misunderstanding of “the logic of our language.” Following in Frege’s and
Russell’s footsteps, Wittgenstein argued that every meaningful sentence must
have a precise logical structure. That structure may, however, be hidden
beneath the clothing of the grmatical appearance of the sentence and may
therefore require the most detailed analysis in order to be made evident. Such
analysis, Wittgenstein was convinced, would establish that every meaningful
sentence is either a truth-functional composite of another simpler sentence or
an atomic sentence consisting of a concatenation of simple nes. He argued
further that every atomic sentence is a logical picture of a possible state of
affairs, which must, as a result, have exactly the se formal structure as the atomic
sentence that depicts it. He employed this “picture theory of meaning” – as it
is usually called – to derive conclusions about the nature of the world from
his observations about the structure of the atomic sentences. He postulated, in
particular, that the world must itself have a precise logical structure, even
though we may not be able to determine it completely. He also held that the
world consists primarily of facts, corresponding to the true atomic sentences,
rather than of things, and that those facts, in turn, are concatenations of
simple objects, corresponding to the simple nes of which the atomic sentences
are composed. Because he derived these metaphysical conclusions from his view
of the nature of language, Wittgenstein did not consider it essential to
describe what those simple objects, their concatenations, and the facts
consisting of them are actually like. As a result, there has been a great deal
of uncertainty and disagreement ong interpreters about their character. The
propositions of the Tractatus are for the most part concerned with spelling out
Wittgenstein’s account of the logical structure of language and the world and
these parts of the book have understandably been of most interest to
philosophers who are primarily concerned with questions of symbolic logic and
its applications. But for Wittgenstein himself the most important part of the
book consisted of the negative conclusions about philosophy that he reaches at
the end of his text: in particular, that all sentences that are not atomic
pictures of concatenations of objects or truth-functional composites of such are
strictly speaking meaningless. ong these he included all the propositions of
ethics and aesthetics, all propositions dealing with the meaning of life, all
propositions of logic, indeed all philosophical propositions, and finally all
the propositions of the Tractatus itself. These are all strictly meaningless;
they aim at saying something important, but what they try to express in words
can only show itself. As a result Wittgenstein concluded that anyone who
understood what the Tractatus was saying would finally discard its propositions
as senseless, that she would throw away the ladder after climbing up on it.
Someone who reached such a state would have no more temptation to pronounce
philosophical propositions. She would see the world rightly and would then also
recognize that the only strictly meaningful propositions are those of natural
science; but those could never touch what was really important in human life,
the mystical. That would have to be contemplated in silence. For “whereof one
cannot speak, thereof one must be silent,” as the last proposition of the
Tractatus declared. Middle period. It was only natural that Wittgenstein should
not embark on an academic career after he had completed that work. Instead he
trained to be a school teacher and taught primary school for a number of years
in the mountains of lower Austria. In the mid-1920s he also built a house for
his sister; this can be seen as an attempt to give visual expression to the
logical, aesthetic, and ethical ideas of the Tractatus. In those years he
developed a number of interests seminal for his later development. His school
experience drew his attention to the way in which children learn language and to
the whole process of enculturation. He also developed an interest in psychology
and read Freud and others. Though he remained hostile to Freud’s theoretical
explanations of his psychoanalytic work, he was fascinated with the analytic
practice itself and later ce to speak of his own work as therapeutic in
character. In this period of dormancy Wittgenstein also bece acquainted with
the members of the Vienna Circle, who had adopted his Tractatus as one of their
key texts. For a while he even accepted the positivist principle of meaning
advocated by the members of that Circle, according to which the meaning of a
sentence is the method of its verification. This he would later modify into the
more generous claim that the meaning of a sentence is its use. Wittgenstein’s
most decisive step in his middle period was to abandon the belief of the
Tractatus that meaningful sentences must have a precise (hidden) logical
structure and the accompanying belief that this structure corresponds to the
logical structure of the facts depicted by those sentences. The Tractatus had,
indeed, proceeded on the assumption that all the different symbolic devices
that can describe the world must be constructed according to the se underlying
logic. In a sense, there was then only one meaningful language in the
Tractatus, and from it one was supposed to be able to read off the logical
structure of the world. In the middle period Wittgenstein concluded that this
doctrine constituted a piece of unwarranted metaphysics and that the Tractatus
was itself flawed by what it had tried to combat, i.e., the misunderstanding of
the logic of language. Where he had previously held it possible to ground
metaphysics on logic, he now argued that metaphysics leads the philosopher into
complete darkness. Turning his attention back to language he concluded that
almost everything he had said about it in the Tractatus had been in error.
There were, in fact, many different languages with many different structures
that could meet quite different specific needs. Language was not strictly held
together by logical structure, but consisted, in fact, of a multiplicity of
simpler substructures or language ges. Sentences could not be taken to be
logical pictures of facts and the simple components of sentences did not all function
as nes of simple objects. These new reflections on language served
Wittgenstein, in the first place, as an aid to thinking about the nature of the
human mind, and specifically about the relation between private experience and
the physical world. Against the existence of a Cartesian mental substance, he
argued that the word ‘I’ did not serve as a ne of anything, but occurred in
expressions meant to draw attention to a particular body. For a while, at
least, he also thought he could explain the difference between private
experience and the physical world in terms of the existence of two languages, a
primary language of experience and a secondary language of physics. This
duallanguage view, which is evident in both the Philosophical Remarks and The
Blue Book, Wittgenstein was to give up later in favor of the assumption that
our grasp of inner phenomena is dependent on the existence of outer criteria.
From the mid-1930s onward he also renewed his interest in the philosophy of
mathematics. In contrast to Frege and Russell, he argued strenuously that no
part of mathematics is reducible purely to logic. Instead he set out to
describe mathematics as part of our natural history and as consisting of a
number of diverse language ges. He also insisted that the meaning of those ges
depended on the uses to which the mathematical formulas were put. Applying the
principle of verification to mathematics, he held that the meaning of a
mathematical formula lies in its proof. These remarks on the philosophy of
mathematics have remained ong Wittgenstein’s most controversial and least
explored writings. Later period. Wittgenstein’s middle period was characterized
by intensive philosophical work on a broad but quickly changing front. By 1936,
however, his thinking was finally ready to settle down once again into a
steadier pattern, and he now began to elaborate the views for which he bece
most fous. Where he had constructed his earlier work around the logic devised
by Frege and Russell, he now concerned himself mainly with the actual working
of ordinary language. This brought him close to the tradition of British common
sense philosophy that Moore had revived and made him one of the godfathers of
the ordinary language philosophy that was to flourish in Oxford in the 1950s.
In the Philosophical Investigations Wittgenstein emphasized that there are
countless different uses of what we call “symbols,” “words,” and “sentences.”
The task of philosophy is to gain a perspicuous view of those multiple uses and
thereby to dissolve philosophical and metaphysical puzzles. These puzzles were
the result of insufficient attention to the working of language and could be
resolved only by carefully retracing the linguistic steps by which they had
been reached. Wittgenstein thus ce to think of philosophy as a descriptive,
analytic, and ultimately therapeutic practice. In the Investigations he set out
to show how common philosophical views about meaning (including the logical
atomism of the Tractatus), about the nature of concepts, about logical necessity,
about rule-following, and about the mind–body problem were all the product of
an insufficient grasp of how language works. In one of the most influential
passages of the book he argued that concept words do not denote sharply
circumscribed concepts, but are meant to mark fily resemblances between the
things labeled with the concept. He also held that logical necessity results
from linguistic convention and that rules cannot determine their own
applications, that rule-following presupposes the existence of regular
practices. Furthermore, the words of our language have meaning only insofar as
there exist public criteria for their correct application. As a consequence, he
argued, there cannot be a completely private language, i.e., a language that in
principle can be used only to speak about one’s own inner experience. This
private language argument has caused much discussion. Interpreters have
disagreed not only over the structure of the argument and where it occurs in
Wittgenstein’s text, but also over the question whether he meant to say that
language is necessarily social. Because he said that to speak of inner
experiences there must be external and publicly available criteria, he has
often been taken to be advocating a logical behaviorism, but nowhere does he,
in fact, deny the existence of inner states. What he says is merely that our
understanding of someone’s pain is connected to the existence of natural and
linguistic expressions of pain. In the Philosophical Investigations
Wittgenstein repeatedly draws attention to the fact that language must be
learned. This learning, he says, is fundentally a process of inculcation and
drill. In learning a language the child is initiated in a form of life. In
Wittgenstein’s later work the notion of form of life serves to identify the
whole complex of natural and cultural circumstances presupposed by our language
and by a particular understanding of the world. He elaborated those ideas in
notes on which he worked between 1948 and his death in 1951 and which are now published
under the title On Certainty. He insisted in them that every belief is always
part of a system of beliefs that together constitute a worldview. All
confirmation and disconfirmation of a belief presuppose such a system and are
internal to the system. For all this he was not advocating a relativism, but a
naturalism that assumes that the world ultimately determines which language ges
can be played. Wittgenstein’s final notes vividly illustrate the continuity of
his basic concerns throughout all the changes his thinking went through. For
they reveal once more how he remained skeptical about all philosophical
theories and how he understood his own undertaking as the attempt to undermine
the need for any such theorizing. The considerations of On Certainty are
evidently directed against both philosophical skeptics and those philosophers
who want to refute skepticism. Against the philosophical skeptics Wittgenstein
insisted that there is real knowledge, but this knowledge is always dispersed
and not necessarily reliable; it consists of things we have heard and read, of
what has been drilled into us, and of our modifications of this inheritance. We
have no general reason to doubt this inherited Wittgenstein, Ludwig
Wittgenstein, Ludwig 979 979 body of
knowledge, we do not generally doubt it, and we are, in fact, not in a position
to do so. But On Certainty also argues that it is impossible to refute
skepticism by pointing to propositions that are absolutely certain, as
Descartes did when he declared ‘I think, therefore I ’ indubitable, or as Moore
did when he said, “I know for certain that this is a hand here.” The fact that
such propositions are considered certain, Wittgenstein argued, indicates only
that they play an indispensable, normative role in our language ge; they are
the riverbed through which the thought of our language ge flows. Such
propositions cannot be taken to express metaphysical truths. Here, too, the
conclusion is that all philosophical argumentation must come to an end, but
that the end of such argumentation is not an absolute, self-evident truth, but
a certain kind of natural human practice.
wodeh: Oxonian
philosopher, like Grice. Ad de (c. 1295–1358), English Franciscan
philosopher-theologian who lectured on Peter Lombard’s Sentences at London,
Norwich, and Oxford. His published works include the Tractatus de
indivisibilibus; his Lectura secunda (Norwich lectures); and an abbreviation of
his Oxford lectures by Henry Totting of Oyta, published by John Major in 1512.
Wodeh’s main work, the Oxford lectures, themselves remain unpublished. A
brilliant interpreter of Duns Scotus, whose original manuscripts he consulted,
Wodeh deemed Duns Scotus the greatest Franciscan doctor. Willi Ockh, Wodeh’s
teacher, was the other great influence on Wodeh’s philosophical theology. Wodeh
defended Ockh’s views against attacks mounted by Walter Chatton; he also wrote
the prologue to Ockh’s Summa logicae. Wodeh’s own influence rivaled that of
Ockh. ong the authors he strongly influenced are Gregory of Rimini, John of
Mirecourt, Nicholas of Autrecourt, Pierre d’Ailly, Peter Ceffons, Alfonso
Vargas, Peter of Candia (Alexander V), Henry Totting of Oyta, and John Major.
Wodeh’s theological works were written for an audience with a very
sophisticated understanding of current issues in semantics, logic, and medieval
mathematical physics. Contrary to Duns Scotus and Ockh, Wodeh argued that the
sensitive and intellective souls were not distinct. He further develops the
theory of intuitive cognition, distinguishing intellectual intuition of our own
acts of intellect, will, and memory from sensory intuition of external objects.
Scientific knowledge based on experience can be based on intuition, according
to Wodeh. He distinguishes different grades of evidence, and allows that
sensory perceptions may be mistaken. Nonetheless, they can form the basis for
scientific knowledge, since they are reliable; mistakes can be corrected by
reason and experience. In semantic theory, Wodeh defends the view that the
immediate object of scientific knowledge is the complexe significabile, that
which the conclusion is designed to signify.
wolff, Christian
(1679–1754), German philosopher and the most powerful advocate for secular
rationalism in early eighteenth-century Germany. Although he was a Lutheran,
his early education in Catholic Breslau made him filiar with both the
Scholasticism of Aquinas and Suárez and more modern sources. His later studies
at Leipzig were completed with a dissertation on the application of
mathematical methods to ethics (1703), which brought him to the attention of
Leibniz. He remained in correspondence with Leibniz until the latter’s death
(1716), and bece known as the popularizer of Leibniz’s philosophy, although his
views did not derive from that source alone. Appointed to teach mathematics in
Halle in 1706 (he published mathematical textbooks and compendia that dominated
German universities for decades), Wolff began lecturing on philosophy as well
by 1709. His rectoral address On the Practical Philosophy of the Chinese (1721)
argued that revelation and even belief in God were unnecessary for arriving at
sound principles of moral and political reasoning; this brought his uneasy
relations with the Halle Pietists to a head, and in 1723 they secured his
dismissal and indeed banishment. Wolff was immediately welcomed in Marburg,
where he bece a hero for freedom of thought, and did not return to Prussia
until the ascension of Frederick the Great in 1740, when he resumed his post at
Halle. Wolff published an immense series of texts on logic, metaphysics,
ethics, politics, natural theology, and teleology (1713–24), in which he
created the philosophical terminology of modern German; he then published an
even more extensive series of works in Latin for the rest of his life, expanding
and modifying his German works but also adding works on natural and positive
law and economics (1723–55). He accepted the traWodeh, Ad de Wolff, Christian
980 980 ditional division of logic into
the doctrines of concepts, judgment, and inference, which influenced the
organization of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason (1781–87) and even Hegel’s
Science of Logic(1816). In metaphysics, he included general ontology and then
the special disciplines of rational cosmology, rational psychology, and
rational theology (Kant replaced Wolff’s general ontology with his
transcendental aesthetic and analytic, and then demolished Wolff’s special
metaphysics in his transcendental dialectic). Wolff’s metaphysics drew heavily
on Leibniz, but also on Descartes and even empiricists like Locke.
Methodologically, he attempted to derive the principle of sufficient reason
from the logical law of identity (like the unpublished Leibniz of the 1680s
rather than the published Leibniz of the 1700s); substantively, he began his
German metaphysics with a reconstruction of Descartes’s cogito argument, then
argued for a simple, immaterial soul, all of its faculties reducible to forms
of representation and related to body by preestablished harmony. Although
rejected by Crusius and then Kant, Wolff’s attempt to found philosophy on a
single principle continued to influence German idealism as late as Reinhold,
Fichte, and Hegel, and his exple of beginning metaphysics from the unique
representative power of the soul continued to influence not only later writers
such as Reinhold and Fichte but also Kant’s own conception of the
transcendental unity of apperception. In spite of the academic influence of his
metaphysics, Wolff’s importance for German culture lay in his rationalist
rather than theological ethics. He argued that moral worth lies in the
perfection of the objective essence of mankind; as the essence of a human is to
be an intellect and a will (with the latter dependent on the former), which are
physically embodied and dependent for their well-being on the well-being of
their physical body, morality requires perfection of the intellect and will,
physical body, and external conditions for the well-being of that combination.
Each person is obliged to perfect all instantiations of this essence, but in
practice does so most effectively in his own case; duties to oneself therefore
precede duties to others and to God. Because pleasure is the sensible sign of
perfection, Wolff’s perfectionism resembles contemporary utilitarianism. Since
he held that human perfection can be understood by human reason independently
of any revelation, Wolff joined contemporary British enlighteners such as
Shaftesbury and Hutcheson in arguing that morality does not depend on divine
commands, indeed the recognition of divine commands depends on an antecedent
comprehension of morality (although morality does require respect for God, and
thus the atheistic morality of the Chinese, even though sound as far as it
went, was not complete). This was the doctrine that put Wolff’s life in danger,
but it had tremendous repercussions for the remainder of his century, and
certainly in Kant.
wollaston, Willi
(1659–1724), English moralist notorious for arguing that the immorality of
actions lies in their implying false propositions. An assistant headmaster who
later took priestly orders, Wollaston maintains in his one published work, The
Religion of Nature Delineated (1722), that the foundations of religion and
morality are mutually dependent. God has preestablished a harmony between
reason (or truth) and happiness, so that actions that contradict truth through
misrepresentation thereby frustrate human happiness and are thus evil. For
instance, if a person steals another’s watch, her falsely representing the
watch as her own makes the act wrong. Wollaston’s views, particularly his
taking morality to consist in universal and necessary truths, were influenced
by the rationalists Ralph Cudworth and Clarke. ong his many critics the most
fous was Hume, who contends that Wollaston’s theory implies an absurdity: any
action concealed from public view (e.g., adultery) conveys no false proposition
and therefore is not immoral.
Wollstonecraft, Mary
(1759–97), English author and feminist whose A Vindication of the Rights of
Women (1792) is a central text of feminist philosophy. Her chief target is
Rousseau: her goal is to argue against the separate and different education
Rousseau provided for girls and to extend his recommendations to girls as well
as boys. Wollstonecraft saw such an improved education for women as necessary
to their asserting their right as “human creatures” to develop their faculties
in a way conducive to human virtue. She also wrote A Vindication of the Rights
of Men (1790), an attack on Edmund Burke’s pphlet on the French Revolution, as
well as novels, essays, an account of her travels, and books for children.
wright, C: philosopher. His
philosophical discussions are stimulating and attracted many, including Peirce,
Jes, and Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., who thinks of him as their “intellectual
boxing master.” Wright eventually accepted empiricism, especially that of J. S.
Mill, though under Darwinian influence he modified Mill’s view considerably by
rejecting the empiricist claim that general propositions merely summarize particulars.
Wright claims instead that scientific theories are hypotheses to be further
developed, and insisted that a moral rule is irreducible and needs no
utilitarian “proof.” Though he denied the “summary” view of universals, he is
not strictly a pragmatist, since for him a low-level empirical proposition like
Peirce’s ‘this diond is hard’ is not a hypothesis but a self-contained
irreducible statement. PEIRCE,
PRAGMATISM.
wu.YU, WU. wu-hsing,
Chinese term meaning ‘five phases, processes, or elements’. The five phases –
earth, wood, metal, fire, and water – along with yin and yang, were the basis
of Chinese correlative cosmologies developed in the Warring States period
(403–221 B.C.) and early Han dynasty (206 B.C.– A.D. 220). These cosmologies
posited a relation between the human world and the natural order. Thus the five
phases were correlated to patterns in human history such as the cyclical rise
and fall of dynasties, to sociopolitical order and the monthly rituals of
rulers, to musical notes and tastes, even to organs of the body. Whereas the
goal of early cosmologists such as Tsou Yen was to bring the human order into
harmony with the natural order via the five phases, Han dynasty cosmologists
and immortality seekers sought to control nature and prolong life by
manipulating the five phases, particularly within the body. R.P.P. & R.T.A.
Wundt: Wilhelm Maximilien
(1832–1920), German philosopher and psychologist, a founder of scientific
psychology. Although trained as a physician, he turned to philosophy and in
1879, at the University of Leipzig, established the first recognized psychology
laboratory. For Wundt, psychology was the science of conscious experience, a
definition soon overtaken by behaviorism. Wundt’s psychology had two
departments: the so-called physiological psychology (Grundzuge der
physiologischen Psychologie, 3 vols., 1873– 74; only vol. 1 of the fifth
edition, 1910, was translated into English), primarily the experimental study
of immediate experience broadly modeled on Fechner’s psychophysics; and the
Volkerpsychologie (Volkerpsychologie, 10 vols., 1900–20; fragment translated as
The Language of Gestures, 1973), the non-experimental study of the higher
mental processes via their products, language, myth, and custom. Although Wundt
was a prodigious investigator and author, and was revered as psychology’s
founder, his theories, unlike his methods, exerted little influence. A typical
German scholar of his time, he also wrote across the whole of philosophy, including
logic and ethics. .
wu wei, Chinese
philosophical term often translated as ‘non-action’ and associated with Taoism.
It is actually used in both Taoist and non-Taoist texts to describe an ideal
state of existence or ideal form of government, interpreted differently in
different texts. In the Chuang Tzu, it describes a state of existence in which
one is not guided by preconceived goals or projects, including moral ideals; in
the Lao Tzu, it refers to the absence of striving toward worldly goals, and
also describes the ideal form of government, which does not teach or impose on
the people standards of behavior, including those of conventional morality. In
other texts, it is sometimes used to describe the effortlessness of moral
action, and sometimes used to refer to the absence of any need for active
participation in government by the ruler, resulting either from the appointment
of worthy and able officials inspired by the moral exple of the ruler, or from
the establishment of an effective machinery of government presided over by a ruler
with prestige. TAOISM. K.-l.S. Wyclif,
John (c.1330–84), English theologian and religious reformer. He worked for most
of his life in Oxford as a secular clerk, teaching philosophy and later
theology and writing extensively in both fields. The mode of thought expressed
in his surviving works is one of extreme realism, and in this his thought
fostered the split of Bohemian, later Hussite, philosophy from that of the
German masters teaching in Prague. His worldline Wyclif, John 982 982 philosophical summa was most influential
for his teaching on universals, but also dealt extensively with the question of
determinism; these issues underlay his later handling of the questions of the
Eucharist and of the identity of the church respectively. His influence on English
philosophy was severely curtailed by the growing hostility of the church to his
ideas, the condemnation of many of his tenets, the persecution of his
followers, and the destruction of his writings. A.Hu. Wyclif, John Wyclif, John
983 983 Xenocrates.ACADEMY. Xenophanes
(c.570–c.475 B.C.), Greek philosopher, a proponent of an idealized conception
of the divine, and the first of the pre-Socratics to propound epistemological
views. Born in Colophon, an Ionian Greek city on the coast of Asia Minor, he emigrated
as a young man to the Greek West (Sicily and southern Italy). The formative
influence of the Milesians is evident in his rationalism. He is the first of
the pre-Socratics for whom we have not only ancient reports but also quite a
few verbatim quotations – fragments from his “Lpoons” (Silloi) and from other
didactic poetry. Xenophanes attacks the worldview of Homer, Hesiod, and
traditional Greek piety: it is an outrage that the poets attribute moral
failings to the gods. Traditional religion reflects regional biases (blond gods
for the Northerners; black gods for the Africans). Indeed, anthropomorphic gods
reflect the ultimate bias, that of the human viewpoint (“If cattle, or horses,
or lions . . . could draw pictures of the gods . . . ,” frg. 15). There is a
single “greatest” god, who is not at all like a human being, either in body or
in mind; he perceives without the aid of organs, he effects changes without
“moving,” through the sheer power of his thought. The rainbow is no sign from
Zeus; it is simply a special cloud formation. Nor are the sun or the moon gods.
All phenomena in the skies, from the elusive “Twin Sons of Zeus” (St. Elmo’s
fire) to sun, moon, and stars, are varieties of cloud formation. There are no
mysterious infernal regions; the filiar strata of earth stretch down ad
infinitum. The only cosmic limit is the one visible at our feet: the horizontal
border between earth and air. Remarkably, Xenophanes tempers his theological
and cosmological pronouncements with an epistemological caveat: what he offers
is only a “conjecture.” In later antiquity Xenophanes ce to be regarded as the
founder of the Eleatic School, and his teachings were assimilated to those of
Parmenides and Melissus. This appears to be based on nothing more than Xenophanes’
emphasis on the oneness and utter immobility of God.
Xenophon (c.430–c.350
B.C.), Greek soldier and historian, author of several Socratic dialogues, along
with important works on history, education, political theory, and other topics.
He was interested in philosophy, and he was a penetrating and intelligent
“social thinker” whose views on morality and society have been influential over
many centuries. His perspective on Socrates’ character and moral significance
provides a valuable supplement and corrective to the better-known views of
Plato. Xenophon’s Socratic dialogues, the only ones besides Plato’s to survive
intact, help us obtain a broader picture of the Socratic dialogue as a literary
genre. They also provide precious evidence concerning the thoughts and
personalities of other followers of Socrates, such as Antisthenes and
Alcibiades. Xenophon’s longest and richest Socratic work is the Memorabilia, or
“Memoirs of Socrates,” which stresses Socrates’ self-sufficiency and his
beneficial effect on his companions. Xenophon’s Apology of Socrates and his
Symposium were probably intended as responses to Plato’s Apology and Symposium.
Xenophon’s Socratic dialogue on estate management, the Oeconomicus, is valuable
for its underlying social theory and its evidence concerning the role and
status of women in classical Athens.
SOCRATES. D.R.M. 984 X 984
yang.YIN, YANG. Yang Chu,
also called Yang Tzu (c.370–319 B.C.), Chinese philosopher most fous for the
assertion, attributed to him by Mencius, that one ought not sacrifice even a
single hair to save the whole world. Widely criticized as a selfish egotist and
hedonist, Yang Chu was a private person who valued bodily integrity, health,
and longevity over fe, fortune, and power. He believed that because one’s body
and lifespan were bestowed by Heaven (t’ien), one has a duty (and natural
inclination) to maintain bodily health and live out one’s years. Far from
sanctioning hedonistic indulgence, this Heavenimposed duty requires discipline.
R.P.P. & R.T.A. Yang Hsiung (53 B.C.–A.D. 18), Chinese philosopher who
wrote two books: Tai-hsüan ching (“Classic of the Supremely Profound
Principle”), an imitation of the I-Ching, and Fa-yen (“Model Sayings”), an
imitation of the Analects. The former was ignored by his contemporaries, but
the latter was quite popular in his time. His thoughts were eclectic. He was
the first in the history of Chinese thought to advance the doctrine of human
nature as a mixture of good and evil in order to avoid the extremes of Mencius
and Hsün Tzu. HSÜN TZU, MENCIUS. S.-h.L.
Yen Yuan (1635–1704),
Chinese traditionalist and social critic. Like Wang Fu-chih, he attacked
Neo-Confucian metaphysical dualism, regarding the Neo-Confucians’ views as wild
speculations obscuring the true nature of Confucianism. Chu Hsi interpreted ko
wu (investigating things) as discovering some transcendent “thing” called li
(pattern), and Wang Yang-ming understood ko wu as rectifying one’s thoughts,
but Yen argued it meant a kind of knowledge by acquaintance: the “hands-on”
practice of traditional rituals and disciplines. As “proof” that Sung–Ming
Confucians were wrong, Yen pointed to their social and political failures. Like
many, he believed Confucianism was not only true but efficacious as well;
failure to reform the world could be understood only as a personal failure to
grasp and implement the Way. CONFUCIANISM,
WANG FUCHIH.
yi, Chinese term probably
with an earlier meaning of ‘sense of honor’, subsequently used to refer to the
fitting or right way of conducting oneself (when so used, it is often
translated as ‘rightness’ or ‘duty’), as well as to a commitment to doing what
is fitting or right (when so used, it is often translated as ‘righteousness’ or
‘dutifulness’). For Mohists, yi is determined by what benefits (li) the public,
where benefit is understood in terms of such things as order and increased
resources in society. For Confucians, while yi behavior is often behavior in
accordance with traditional norms, it may also call for departure from such
norms. Yi is determined not by specific rules of conduct, but by the proper
weighing (chüan) of relevant considerations in a given context of action. Yi in
the sense of a firm commitment to doing what is fitting or right, even in
adverse circumstances, is an important component of the Confucian ethical
ideal. CONFUCIANISM, MO TZU. K.-l.S. Yi
Ching.I-CHING.
yin, yang, metaphors used
in the classical tradition of Chinese philosophy to express contrast and
difference. Originally they designated the shady side and the sunny side of a
hill, and gradually ce to suggest the way in which one thing “overshadows”
another in some particular aspect of their relationship. Yin and yang are not
“principles” or “essences” that help classify things; rather, they are ad hoc
explanatory categories that report on relationships and interactions ong
immediate concrete things of the world. Yin and yang always describe the
relationships that are constitutive of unique particulars, and provide a
vocabulary for “reading” the distinctions that obtain ong them. The
complementary nature of the opposition captured in this pairing expresses the
mutuality, interdependence, diversity, and creative efficacy of the dynic
relationships that are deemed immanent in and valorize the world. The full
range of difference in the world is deemed explicable 985 Y 985 through this pairing.
yü, Chinese term meaning
‘desire’. One can feel yü toward sex objects or food, but one can also yü to be
a more virtuous person. Yü is paired contrastively with wu (aversion), which
has a similarly broad range of objects. After the introduction of Buddhism into
China, some thinkers contended that the absence of yü and wu was the goal of
self-cultivation. Generally, however, the presence of at least some yü and wu
has been thought to be essential to moral perfection. B.W.V.N. yu, wu, Chinese
terms literally meaning ‘having’ and ‘nothing’, respectively; they are often
rendered into English as ‘being’ and ‘non-being’. But the Chinese never
developed the mutually contradictory concepts of Being and Non-Being in
Parmenides’ sense. In chapter 2 of Tao Te Ching, Lao Tzu says that “being (yu)
and non-being (wu) produce each other.” They appear to be a pair of
interdependent concepts. But in chapter 40 Lao Tzu also says that “being comes
from non-being.” It seems that for Taoism non-being is more fundental than
being, while for Confucianism the opposite is true. The two traditions were
seen to be complementary by later scholars.
yung, Chinese term usually translated as
‘courage’ or ‘bravery’. Different forms of yung are described in Chinese
philosophical texts, such as a readiness to avenge an insult or to compete with
others, or an absence of fear. Confucians advocate an ideal form of yung guided
by rightness (yi). A person with yung of the ideal kind is fully committed to
rightness, and will abide by rightness even at the risk of death. Also,
realizing upon self-exination that there is no fault in oneself, the person
will be without fear or uncertainty.
Zabarella, Jacopo
(1532–89), Italian Aristotelian philosopher who taught at the University of
Padua. He wrote extensive commentaries on Aristotle’s Physics and On the Soul
and also discussed other interpreters such as Averroes. However, his most
original contribution was his work in logic, Opera logica (1578). Zabarella
regards logic as a preliminary study that provides the tools necessary for
philosophical analysis. Two such tools are order and method: order teaches us
how to organize the content of a discipline to apprehend it more easily; method
teaches us how to draw syllogistic inferences. Zabarella reduces the varieties
of orders and methods classified by other interpreters to compositive and
resolutive orders and methods. The compositive order from first principles to
their consequences applies to theoretical disciplines. The resolutive order
from a desired end to means appropriate to its achievement applies to practical
disciplines. This much was already in Aristotle. Zabarella offers an original
analysis of method. The compositive method infers particular consequences from
general principles. The resolutive method infers originating principles from
particular consequences, as in inductive reasoning or in reasoning from effect
to cause. It has been suggested that Zabarella’s terminology might have influenced
Galileo’s mechanics.
Zeigarnik effect, the
selective recall of uncompleted tasks in comparison to completed tasks. The
effect was ned for Bluma Zeigarnik, a student of K. Lewin, who discovered it
and described it in a paper published in the Psychologische Forschung in 1927.
Subjects received an array of short tasks, such as counting backward and
stringing beads, for rapid completion. Performance on half of these was
interrupted. Subsequent recall for the tasks favored the interrupted tasks.
Zeigarnik concluded that recall is influenced by motivation and not merely
associational strength. The effect was thought relevant to Freud’s claim that
unfulfilled wishes are persistent. Lewin attempted to derive the effect from
field theory, suggesting that an attempt to reach a goal creates a tension
released only when that goal is reached; interruption of the attempt produces a
tension favoring recall. Conditions affecting the Zeigarnik effect are
incompletely understood, as is its significance.
Zeno’s paradoxes, four
paradoxes relating to space and motion attributed to Zeno of Elea (fifth
century B.C.): the racetrack, Achilles and the tortoise, the stadium, and the
arrow. Zeno’s work is known to us through secondary sources, in particular
Aristotle. The racetrack paradox. If a runner is to reach the end of the track,
he must first complete an infinite number of different journeys: getting to the
midpoint, then to the point midway between the midpoint and the end, then to
the point midway between this one and the end, and so on. But it is logically
impossible for someone to complete an infinite series of journeys. Therefore
the runner cannot reach the end of the track. Since it is irrelevant to the
argument how far the end of the track is – it could be a foot or an inch or a
micron away – this argument, if sound, shows that all motion is impossible.
Moving to any point will involve an infinite number of journeys, and an
infinite number of journeys cannot be completed. The paradox of Achilles and the
tortoise. Achilles can run much faster than the tortoise, so when a race is
arranged between them the tortoise is given a lead. Zeno argued that Achilles
can never catch up with the tortoise no matter how fast he runs and no matter
how long the race goes on. For the first thing Achilles has to do is to get to
the place from which the tortoise started. But the tortoise, though slow, is
unflag987 Z 987 ging: while Achilles
was occupied in making up his handicap, the tortoise has advanced a little
farther. So the next thing Achilles has to do is to get to the new place the
tortoise occupies. While he is doing this, the tortoise will have gone a little
farther still. However small the gap that remains, it will take Achilles some
time to cross it, and in that time the tortoise will have created another gap.
So however fast Achilles runs, all that the tortoise has to do, in order not to
be beaten, is not to stop. The stadium paradox. Imagine three equal cubes, A,
B, and C, with sides all of length l, arranged in a line stretching away from
one. A is moved perpendicularly out of line to the right by a distance equal to
l. At the se time, and at the se rate, C is moved perpendicularly out of line
to the left by a distance equal to l. The time it takes A to travel l/2
(relative to B) equals the time it takes A to travel to l (relative to C). So,
in Aristotle’s words, “it follows, he [Zeno] thinks, that half the time equals
its double” (Physics 259b35). The arrow paradox. At any instant of time, the
flying arrow “occupies a space equal to itself.” That is, the arrow at an
instant cannot be moving, for motion takes a period of time, and a temporal
instant is conceived as a point, not itself having duration. It follows that
the arrow is at rest at every instant, and so does not move. What goes for
arrows goes for everything: nothing moves. Scholars disagree about what Zeno
himself took his paradoxes to show. There is no evidence that he offered any
“solutions” to them. One view is that they were part of a progr to establish
that multiplicity is an illusion, and that reality is a seless whole. The
argument could be reconstructed like this: if you allow that reality can be
successively divided into parts, you find yourself with these insupportable
paradoxes; so you must think of reality as a single indivisible One.
Zoroastrianism, the
national religion of ancient Iran. Zoroastrianism suffered a steep decline
after the seventh century A.D. because of conversion to Isl. Of a remnant of
roughly 100,000 adherents today, three-fourths are Parsis (“Persians)” in or
from western India; the others are Iranian Zoroastrians. The tradition is
identified with its prophet; his ne in Persian, Zarathushtra, is preserved in
German, but the ancient Greek rendering of that ne, Zoroaster, is the form used
in most other modern European languages. Zoroaster’s hymns to Ahura Mazda (“the
Wise Lord”), called the Gathas, are interspersed ong ritual hymns to other
divine powers in the collection known as the Avesta. In them, Zoroaster seeks
reassurance that good will ultimately triumph over evil and that Ahura Mazda
will be a protector to him in his prophetic mission. The Gathas expect that
humans, by aligning themselves with the force of righteousness and against
evil, will receive bliss and benefit in the next existence. The dating of the
texts and of the prophet himself is an elusive matter for scholars, but it is
clear that Zoroaster lived somewhere in Iran sometime prior to the emergence of
the Achaemenid empire in the sixth century B.C. His own faith in Ahura Mazda,
reflected in the Gathas, ce to be integrated with other strains of old
Indo-Iranian religion. We see these in the Avesta’s hymns and the religion’s
ritual practices. They venerate an array of Iranian divine powers that resemble
in function the deities found in the Vedas of India. A common Indo-Iranian
heritage is indicated conclusively by similarities of language and of content
between the Avesta and the Vedas. Classical Zoroastrian orthodoxy does not
replace the Indo-Iranian divinities with Ahura Mazda, but instead incorporates
them into its thinking more or less as Ahura Mazda’s agents. The Achaemenid
kings from the sixth through the fourth centuries B.C. mention Ahura Mazda in
their inscriptions, but not Zoroaster. The Parthians, from the third century
B.C. to the third century A.D., highlighted Mithra ong the Indo-Iranian pantheon.
But it was under the Sasanians, who ruled Iran from the third to the seventh
centuries, that Zoroastrianism bece the established religion. A salient doctrine
is the teaching concerning the struggle between good and evil. The time fre
from the world’s creation to the final resolution or judgment finds the Wise
Lord, Ahura Mazda (or Ohrmazd, in the Pahlavi language of Sasanian times),
locked in a struggle with the evil spirit, Angra Mainyu (in Pahlavi, Ahriman).
The teaching expands on an implication in the text of the Gathas, particularly
Yasna 30, that the good and evil spirits, coming together in the beginning and
establishing the living and inanimate realms, determined that at the end
benefit would accrue to the righteous but not the wicked. In Sasanian times,
there was speculative concern to assert Ahura Mazda’s infinity, omnipotence,
and omniscience, qualities that may indicate an impact of Mediterranean philosophy.
For exple, the Bundahishn, a Pahlavi cosmological and eschatological narrative,
portrays Ahura Mazda as infinite in all four compass directions but the evil
spirit as limited in one and therefore doomed to ultimate defeat. Such doctrine
has been termed by some dualistic, in that it has (at least in Sasanian times)
seen the power of God rivaled by that of an evil spirit. Zoroastrians today
assert that they are monotheists, and do not worship the evil spirit. But to
the extent that the characterization may hold historically, Zoroastrianism has
manifested an “ethical” dualism, of good and evil forces. Although capable of
ritual pollution through waste products and decay, the physical world, God’s
creation, remains potentially morally good. Contrast “ontological” dualism, as
in gnostic and Manichaean teaching, where the physical world itself is the
result of the fall or entrapment of spirit in matter. In the nineteenth
century, Zoroastrian texts newly accessible to Europe produced an awareness of
the prophet’s concern for ethical matters. Nietzsche’s values in his work Thus
Spake Zarathustra, however, are his own, not those of the ancient prophet. The
title is arresting, but the connection of Nietzsche with historical Zoroastrianism
is a connection in theme only, in that the work advances ideas about good and
evil in an oracular style.
No comments:
Post a Comment