Hegel, Georg Wilhelm
Friedrich (1770–1831), one of the most influential and systematic of the German
idealists, also well known for his philosophy of history and philosophy of
religion. Life and works. Hegel, the eldest of three children, was born in
Stuttgart, the son of a minor financial official in the court of the Duchy of
Württemberg. His mother died when he was eleven. At eighteen, he began attending
the theology seminary or Stift attached to the University at Tübingen; he
studied theology and classical languages and literature and bece friendly with
his future colleague and adversary, Schelling, as well as the great genius of
German Romantic poetry, Hölderlin. In 1793, upon graduation, he accepted a job
as a tutor for a fily in Bern, and moved to Frankfurt in 1797 for a similar
post. In 1799 his father bequeathed him a modest income and the freedom to
resign his tutoring job, pursue his own work, and attempt to establish himself
in a university position. In 1801, with the help of Schelling, he moved to the
university town of Jena, already widely known as the home of Schiller, Fichte,
and the Schlegel brothers. After lecturing for a few years, he bece a professor
in 1805. Prior to the move to Jena, Hegel’s essays had been chiefly concerned
with problems in morality, the theory of culture, and the philosophy of
religion. Hegel shared with Rousseau and the German Romantics many doubts about
the political and moral implications of the European Enlightenment and modern
philosophy in general, even while he still enthusiastically chpioned what he
termed the principle of modernity, “absolute freedom.” Like many, he feared
that the modern attack on feudal political and religious authority would merely
issue in the reformulation of new internalized and still repressive forms of
authority. And he was ong that legion of German intellectuals infatuated with
ancient Greece and the superiority of their supposedly harmonious social life,
compared with the authoritarian and legalistic character of the Jewish and
later Christian religions. At Jena, however, he coedited a journal with
Schelling, The Critical Journal of Philosophy, and ce to work much more on the
philosophic issues created by the critical philosophy or “transcendental
idealism” of Kant, and its legacy in the work of Rheinhold, Fichte, and
Schelling. His written work bece much more influenced by these theoretical
projects and their attempt to extend Kant’s search for the basic categories
necessary for experience to be discriminated and evaluated, and for a theory of
the subject that, in some non-empirical way, was responsible for such
categories. Problems concerning the completeness, interrelation, and ontological
status of such a categorial structure were quite prominent, along with a
continuing interest in the relation between a free, self-determining agent and
the supposed constraints of moral principles and other agents. In his early
years at Jena (especially before Schelling left in 1803), he was particularly
preoccupied with this problem of a systematic philosophy, a way of accounting
for the basic categories of the natural world and for human practical activity
that would ground all such categories on commonly presupposed and logically
interrelated, even interdeducible, principles. (In Hegel’s terms, this was the
problem of the relation between a “Logic” and a “Philosophy of Nature” and
“Philosophy of Spirit.”) After 1803, however, while he was preparing his own
systematic philosophy for publication, what had been planned as a short
introduction to this system took on a life of its own and grew into one of
Hegel’s most provocative and influential books. Working at a furious pace, he
finished hedonistic paradox Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 365 4065h-l.qxd 365 what would be eventually called The
Phenomenology of Spirit in a period of great personal and political turmoil.
During the final writing of the book, he had learned that Christina Burkhard
would give birth to his illegitimate son. (Ludwig was born in February 1807.)
And he is supposed to have completed the text on October 13, 1807, the day
Napoleon’s armies captured Jena. It was certainly an unprecedented work. In
conception, it is about the human race itself as a developing, progressively
more self-conscious subject, but its content seems to take in a vast,
heterogeneous range of topics, from technical issues in empiricist epistemology
to the significance of burial rituals. Its range is so heterogeneous that there
is controversy to this day about whether it has any overall unity, or whether
it was pieced together at the last minute. Adding to the interpretive problem,
Hegel often invented his own striking language of “inverted worlds,” “struggles
to the death for recognition,” “unhappy consciousness,” “spiritual animal
kingdoms,” and “beautiful souls.” Continuing his university career at Jena in
those times looked out of the question, so Hegel accepted a job at Bberg
editing a newspaper, and in the following year began an eight-year stint
(1808–16) as headmaster and philosophy teacher at a Gymnasium (or secondary
school) at Nürnberg. During this period, at forty-one, he married the
twenty-year-old Marie von Tucher. He also wrote what is easily his most
difficult work, and the one he often referred to as his most important, a
magisterial two-volume Science of Logic, which attempts to be a philosophical
account of the concepts necessary in all possible kinds of account-givings.
Finally, in 1816, Hegel was offered a chair in philosophy at the University of
Heidelberg, where he published the first of several versions of his
Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences, his own systematic account of the
relation between the “logic” of human thought and the “real” expression of such
interrelated categories in our understanding of the natural world and in our
understanding and evaluation of our own activities. In 1818, he accepted the
much more prestigious post in philosophy at Berlin, where he remained until his
death in 1831. Soon after his arrival in Berlin, he began to exert a powerful
influence over German letters and intellectual life. In 1821, in the midst of a
growing political and nationalist crisis in Prussia, he published his
controversial book on political philosophy, The Philosophy of Right. His
lectures at the university were later published as his philosophy of history,
of aesthetics, and of religion, and as his history of philosophy. Philosophy.
Hegel’s most important ideas were formed gradually, in response to a number of
issues in philosophy and often in response to historical events. Moreover, his
language and approach were so heterodox that he has inspired as much
controversy about the meaning of his position as about its adequacy. Hence any
summary will be as much a summary of the controversies as of the basic
position. His dissatisfactions with the absence of a public realm, or any forms
of genuine social solidarity in the German states and in modernity generally,
and his distaste with what he called the “positivity” of the orthodox religions
of the day (their reliance on law, scripture, and abstract claims to
authority), led him to various attempts to make use of the Greek polis and
classical art, as well as the early Christian understanding of love and a
renewed “folk religion,” as critical foils to such tendencies. For some time,
he also regarded much traditional and modern philosophy as itself a kind of
lifeless classifying that only contributed to contemporary fragmentation,
myopia, and confusion. These concerns remained with him throughout his life,
and he is thus rightly known as one of the first modern thinkers to argue that
what had come to be accepted as the central problem of modern social and
political life, the legitimacy of state power, had been too narrowly conceived.
There are now all sorts of circumstances, he argued, in which people might
satisfy the modern criterion of legitimacy and “consent” to the use of some
power, but not fully understand the terms within which such issues are posed,
or assent in an attenuated, resentful, manipulated, or confused way. In such
cases they would experience no connection between their individual will and the
actual content of the institutions they are supposed to have sanctioned. The
modern problem is as much alienation (Entfremdung) as sovereignty, an exercise
of will in which the product of one’s will appears “strange” or “alien,”
“other,” and which results in much of modern life, however chosen or willed,
being fundentally unsatisfying. However, during the Jena years, his views on
this issue changed. Most importantly, philosophical issues moved closer to
center stage in the Hegelian dra. He no longer regarded philosophy as some sort
of self-undermining activity that merely prepared one for some leap into
genuine “speculation” (roughly Schelling’s position) and began to chpion a
unique kind of comprehensive, very determinate reflection on the interrelations
ong all the various classical alternatives in philosophy. Much more
controversially, he also attempted to understand the way in which such
relations and transitions were also reflected in the history of the art,
politics, and religions of various historical communities. He thus ce to think
that philosophy should be some sort of recollection of its past history, a
realization of the mere partiality, rather than falsity, of its past attempts
at a comprehensive teaching, and an account of the centrality of these
continuously developing attempts in the development of other human practices.
Through understanding the “logic” of such a development, a reconciliation of
sorts with the implications of such a rational process in contemporary life, or
at least with the potentialities inherent in contemporary life, would be
possible. In all such influences and developments, one revolutionary aspect of
Hegel’s position bece clearer. For while Hegel still frequently argued that the
subject matter of philosophy was “reason,” or “the Absolute,” the unconditioned
presupposition of all human account-giving and evaluation, and thereby an
understanding of the “whole” within which the natural world and human deeds
were “parts,” he also always construed this claim to mean that the subject
matter of philosophy was the history of human experience itself. Philosophy was
about the real world of human change and development, understood by Hegel to be
the collective self-education of the human species about itself. It could be
this, and satisfy the more traditional ideals because, in one of his most fous
phrases, “what is actual is rational,” or because some full account could be
given of the logic or teleological order, even the necessity, for the great
conceptual and political changes in human history. We could thereby finally
reassure ourselves that the way our species had come to conceptualize and
evaluate is not finite or contingent, but is “identical” with “what there is,
in truth.” This identity theory or Absolute Knowledgemeans that we will then be
able to be “at home” in the world and so will have understood what philosophers
have always tried to understand, “how things in the broadest possible sense of
the term hang together in the broadest possible sense of the term.” The way it
all hangs together is, finally, “due to us,” in some collective and historical
and “logical” sense. (In a much disputed passage in his Philosophy of Religion
lectures, Hegel even suggested that with such an understanding, history itself
would be over.) Several elements in this general position have inspired a good
deal of excitement and controversy. To advance claims such as these Hegel had
to argue against a powerful, deeply influential assumption in modern thought:
the priority of the individual, self-conscious subject. Such an assumption
means, for exple, that almost all social relations, almost all our bonds to
other human beings, exist because and only because they are made, willed into
existence by individuals otherwise naturally unattached to each other. With
respect to knowledge claims, while there may be many beliefs in a common
tradition that we unreflectively share with others, such shared beliefs are
also taken primarily to be the result of individuals continuously affirming
such beliefs, however implicitly or unreflectively. Their being shared is
simply a consequence of their being simultaneously affirmed or assented to by
individuals. Hegel’s account requires a different picture, an insistence on the
priority of some kind of collective subject, which he called human “spirit” or
Geist. His general theory of conceptual and historical change requires the
assumption of such a collective subject, one that even can be said to be
“coming to self-consciousness” about itself, and this required that he argue
against the view that so much could be understood as the result of individual
will and reflection. Rather, he tried in many different ways to show that the
formation of what might appear to an individual to be his or her own particular
intention or desire or belief already reflected a complex social inheritance
that could itself be said to be evolving, even evolving progressively, with a
“logic” of its own. The completion of such collective attempts at
self-knowledge resulted in what Hegel called the realization of Absolute
Spirit, by which he either meant the absolute completion of the human attempt
to know itself, or the realization in human affairs of some sort of extrahuman
transcendence, or full expression of an infinite God. Hegel tried to advance
all such claims about social subjectivity without in some way hypostatizing or
reifying such a subject, as if it existed independently of the actions and
thoughts of individuals. This claim about the deep dependence of individuals on
one another (even for their very identity), even while they maintain their
independence, is one of the best-known exples of Hegel’s attempt at a
dialectical resolution of many of the traditional oppositions and antinomies of
past thought. Hegel often argued that what appeared to be contraries in
philosophy, such as mind/body, freedom/determinism, Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 367 4065h-l.qxd 367 idealism/materialism,
universal/particular, the state/the individual, or even God/man, appeared such
incompatible alternatives only because of the undeveloped and so incomplete
perspective within which the oppositions were formulated. So, in one of his
more fous attacks on such dualisms, human freedom according to Hegel could not
be understood coherently as some purely rational self-determination,
independent of heteronomous impulses, nor the human being as a perpetual
opposition between reason and sensibility. In his moral theory, Kant had argued
for the latter view and Hegel regularly returned to such Kantian claims about
the opposition of duty and inclination as deeply typical of modern dualism.
Hegel claimed that Kant’s version of a rational principle, the “categorical
imperative,” was so formal and devoid of content as not to be action-guiding
(it could not coherently rule in or rule out the appropriate actions), and that
the “moral point of view” rigoristically demanded a pure or dutiful motivation
to which no human agent could conform. By contrast, Hegel claimed that the
dualisms of morality could be overcome in ethical life (Sittlichkeit), those
modern social institutions which, it was claimed, provided the content or true
“objects” of a rational will. These institutions, the fily, civil society, and
the state, did not require duties in potential conflict with our own
substantive ends, but were rather experienced as the “realization” of our individual
free will. It has remained controversial what for Hegel a truly free, rational
self-determination, continuous with, rather than constraining, our desire for
happiness and self-actualization, ounted to. Many commentators have noted that,
ong modern philosophers, only Spinoza, whom Hegel greatly admired, was as
insistent on such a thoroughgoing compatibilism, and on a refusal to adopt the
Christian view of human beings as permanently divided against themselves. In
his most bitious analysis of such oppositions Hegel went so far as to claim
that, not only could alternatives be shown to be ultimately compatible when
thought together within some higher-order “Notion” (Begriff) that resolved or
“sublated” the opposition, but that one term in such opposition could actually
be said to imply or require its contrary, that a “positing” of such a notion
would, to maintain consistency, require its own “negating,” and that it was
this sort of dialectical opposition that could be shown to require a sublation,
or Aufhebung (a term of art in Hegel that simultaneously means in German ‘to
cancel’, ‘to preserve’, and ‘to raise up’). This claim for a dialectical
development of our fundental notions has been the most severely criticized in
Hegel’s philosophy. Many critics have doubted that so much basic conceptual
change can be accounted for by an internal critique, one that merely develops
the presuppositions inherent in the affirmation of some notion or position or
related practice. This issue has especially attracted critics of Hegel’s
Science of Logic, where he tries first to show that the attempt to categorize
anything that is, simply and immediately, as “Being,” is an attempt that both
“negates itself,” or ends up categorizing everything as “Nothing,” and then
that this self-negation requires a resolution in the higher-order category of
“Becoming.” This analysis continues into an extended argument that purports to
show that any attempt to categorize anything at all must ultimately make use of
the distinctions of “essence” and “appearance,” and elements of syllogistic and
finally Hegel’s own dialectical logic, and both the details and the grand
design of that project have been the subject of a good deal of controversy.
(Unfortunately, much of this controversy has been greatly confused by the
popular association of the terms “thesis,” “antithesis,” and “synthesis” with
Hegel’s theory of dialectic. These crude, mechanical notions were invented in
1837 by a less-than-sensitive Hegel expositor, Heinrich Moritz Chalybäus, and were
never used as terms of art by Hegel.) Others have argued that the tensions
Hegel does identify in various positions and practices require a much broader
analysis of the historical, especially economic, context within which positions
are formulated and become important, or some more detailed attention to the
empirical discoveries or paradoxes that, at the very least, contribute to basic
conceptual change. Those worried about the latter problem have also raised
questions about the logical relation between universal and particular implied
in Hegel’s account. Hegel, following Fichte, radicalizes a Kantian claim about
the inaccessibility of pure particularity in sensations (Kant had written that
“intuitions without concepts are blind”). Hegel charges that Kant did not draw
sufficiently radical conclusions from such an antiempiricist claim, that he
should have completely rethought the traditional distinction between “what was
given to the mind” and “what the mind did with the given.” By contrast Hegel is
confident that he has a theory of a “concrete universal,” concepts that cannot
be understood as pale generalizations or abstract representations of given
particulars, because they are required for particulars to Hegel, Georg Wilhelm
Friedrich Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 368 4065h-l.qxd 368 be apprehended in the first place.
They are not originally dependent on an immediate acquaintance with
particulars; there is no such acquaintance. Critics wonder if Hegel has much of
a theory of particularity left, if he does not claim rather that particulars,
or whatever now corresponds to them, are only interrelations of concepts, and
in which the actual details of the organization of the natural world and human
history are deduced as conceptual necessities in Hegel’s Encyclopedia. (This
interpretation of Hegel, that he believes all entities are really the thoughts,
expressions, or modes of a single underlying mental substance, and that this
mind develops and posits itself with some sort of conceptual necessity, has been
termed a panlogicism, a term of art coined by Hermann Glockner, a Hegel
commentator in the first half of the twentieth century. It is a much-disputed
reading.) Such critics are especially concerned with the implications of this
issue in Hegel’s political theory, where the great modern opposition between
the state and the individual seems subjected to this se logic, and the
individual’s true individuality is said to reside in and only in the political
universal, the State. Thus, on the one hand, Hegel’s political philosophy is
often praised for its early identification and analysis of a fundental, new
aspect of contemporary life – the categorically distinct realm of political
life in modernity, or the independence of the “State” from the social world of
private individuals engaged in competition and private association (“civil
society”). But, on the other hand, his attempt to argue for a completion of
these domains in the State, or that individuals could only be said to be free
in allegiance to a State, has been, at least since Marx, one of the most
criticized aspects of his philosophy. Finally, criticisms also frequently
target the underlying intention behind such claims: Hegel’s career-long
insistence on finding some basic unity ong the many fragmented spheres of
modern thought and existence, and his demand that this unity be articulated in
a discursive account, that it not be merely felt, or gestured at, or celebrated
in edifying speculation. PostHegelian thinkers have tended to be suspicious of
any such intimations of a whole for modern experience, and have argued that,
with the destruction of the premodern world, we simply have to content
ourselves with the disconnected, autonomous spheres of modern interests. In his
lecture courses these basic themes are treated in wide-ranging accounts of the
basic institutions of cultural history. History itself is treated as
fundentally political history, and, in typically Hegelian fashion, the major
epochs of political history are claimed to be as they were because of the
internal inadequacies of past epochs, all until some final political
semiconsciousness is achieved and realized. Art is treated equally
developmentally, evolving from symbolic, through “classical,” to the most
intensely self-conscious form of aesthetic subjectivity, romantic art. The
Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion embody these themes in some of the most
controversial ways, since Hegel often treats religion and its development as a
kind of picture or accessible “representation” of his own views about the
relation of thought to being, the proper understanding of human finitude and
“infinity,” and the essentially social or communal nature of religious life.
This has inspired a characteristic debate ong Hegel scholars, with some arguing
that Hegel’s appropriation of religion shows that his own themes are
essentially religious (if an odd, pantheistic version of Christianity), while
others argue that he has so Hegelianized religious issues that there is little
distinctively religious left. Influence. This last debate is typical of that
prominent in the post-Hegelian tradition. Although, in the decades following
his death, there was a great deal of work by self-described Hegelians on the
history of law, on political philosophy, and on aesthetics, most of the
prominent academic defenders of Hegel were interested in theology, and many of
these were interested in defending an interpretation of Hegel consistent with
traditional Christian views of a personal God and personal immortality. This
began to change with the work of “young Hegelians” such as D. F. Strauss
(1808–74), Feuerbach (1804–72), Bruno Bauer (1809–82), and Arnold Ruge
(1803–80), who emphasized the humanistic and historical dimensions of Hegel’s
account of religion, rejected the Old Hegelian tendencies toward a
reconciliation with contemporary political life, and began to reinterpret and
expand Hegel’s account of the productive activity of human spirit (eventually
focusing on labor rather than intellectual and cultural life). Strauss himself
characterized the fight as between “left,” “center,” and “right” Hegelians,
depending on whether one was critical or conservative politically, or had a
theistic or a humanistic view of Hegelian Geist. The most fous young or left
Hegelian was Marx, especially during his days in Paris as coeditor, with Ruge,
of the Deutsch-französischen Jahrbücher (1844). Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 369 4065h-l.qxd 369 In Great Britain, with its long skeptical,
empiricist, and utilitarian tradition, Hegel’s work had little influence until
the latter part of the nineteenth century, when philosophers such as Green and
Caird took up some of the holistic themes in Hegel and developed a neo-Hegelian
reading of issues in politics and religion that began to have influence in the
academy. The most prominent of the British neo-Hegelians of the next generation
were Bosanquet, McTaggart, and especially Bradley, all of whom were interested
in many of the metaphysical implications of Hegel’s idealism, what they took to
be a Hegelian claim for the “internally related” interconnection of all
particulars within one single, ideal or mental, substance. Moore and Russell
waged a hugely successful counterattack in the ne of traditional empiricism and
what would be called “analytic philosophy” against such an enterprise and in
this tradition largely finished off the influence of Hegel (or what was left of
the historical Hegel in these neo-Hegelian versions). In Germany, Hegel has
continued to influence a number of different schools of neo-Marxism, sometimes
itself simply called “Hegelian Marxism,” especially the Frankfurt School, or
“critical theory” group (especially Adorno, Horkheimer, and Marcuse). And he
has been extremely influential in France, particularly thanks to the lectures
of a brilliant if idiosyncratic Russian émigré, Alexander Kojève, who taught
Hegel in the 1930s at the École Pratique des Hautes Études to the likes of
Merleau-Ponty and Lacan. Kojève was as much influenced by Marx and Heidegger as
Hegel, but his lectures inspired many thinkers to turn again to Hegel’s account
of human selfdefinition in time and to the historicity of all institutions and
practices and so forged an unusual link between Hegel and postwar
existentialism. Hegelian themes continue to resurface in contemporary
hermeneutics, in “communitarianism” in ethics, and in the increasing attention
given to conceptual change and history in the philosophy of science. This has
meant for many that Hegel should now be regarded not only as the origin of a
distinctive tradition in European philosophy that emphasizes the historical and
social nature of human existence, but as a potential contributor to many new
and often interdisciplinary approaches to philosophy.
Heidegger, Martin
(1889–1976), German philosopher whose early works contributed to phenomenology
and existentialism (e.g., Sartre) and whose later works paved the way to
hermeneutics (Gader) and post-structuralism (Derrida and Foucault). Born in
Messkirch in the Black Forest region, Heidegger first trained to be a Jesuit,
but switched to mathematics and philosophy in 1911. As an instructor at
Freiburg University, he worked with the founder of phenomenology, Husserl. His
masterwork, Sein und Zeit (Being and Time, 1927), was published while he was
teaching at Marburg University. This work, in opposition to the preoccupation
with epistemology dominant at the time, focused on the traditional question of
metaphysics: What is the being of entities in general? Rejecting abstract
theoretical approaches to this question, Heidegger drew on Kierkegaard’s
religious individualism and the influential movement called life-philosophy –
Lebensphilosophie, then identified with Nietzsche, Bergson, and Dilthey – to
develop a highly original account of humans as embedded in concrete situations
of action. Heidegger accepted Husserl’s chair at Freiburg in 1928; in 1933,
having been elected rector of the University, he joined the Nazi party.
Although he stepped down as rector one year later, new evidence suggests complicity
with the Nazis until the end of the war. Starting in the late thirties, his
writings started to shift toward the “antihumanist” and “poetic” form of
thinking referred to as “later Heidegger.” Heidegger’s lifelong project was to
answer the “question of being” (Seinsfrage). This question asks, concerning
things in general (rocks, tools, people, etc.), what is it to be an entity of
these sorts? It is the question of ontology first posed by ancient Greek
philosophers from Anaximander to Aristotle. Heidegger holds, however, that
philosophers starting with Plato have gone astray in trying to answer this
question because they have tended to think of being as a property or essence
enduringly present in things. In other words, they have fallen into the “metaphysics
of presence,” which thinks of being as substance. What is overlooked in
traditional metaphysics is the background conditions that enable entities to
show up as counting or mattering in some specific way in the first place. In
his early works, Heidegger tries to bring this concealed dimension of things to
light by recasting the question of being: What is the meaning of being? Or, put
differently, how do entities come to show up as intelligible to Hegelians,
Young Heidegger, Martin 370 4065h-l.qxd
370 us in some determinate way? And this question calls for an analysis
of the entity that has some prior understanding of things: human existence or
Dasein (the German word for “existence” or “being-there,” used to refer to the
structures of humans that make possible an understanding of being). Heidegger’s
claim is that Dasein’s pretheoretical (or “preontological”) understanding of
being, embodied in its everyday practices, opens a “clearing” in which entities
can show up as, say, tools, protons, numbers, mental events, and so on. This
historically unfolding clearing is what the metaphysical tradition has
overlooked. In order to clarify the conditions that make possible an
understanding of being, then, Being and Time begins with an analytic of Dasein.
But Heidegger notes that traditional interpretations of human existence have
been one-sided to the extent that they concentrate on our ways of existing when
we are engaged in theorizing and detached reflection. It is this narrow focus
on the spectator attitude that leads to the picture, found in Descartes, of the
self as a mind or subject representing material objects – the so-called
subjectobject model. In order to bypass this traditional picture, Heidegger
sets out to describe Dasein’s “average everydayness,” i.e., our ordinary,
prereflective agency when we are caught up in the midst of practical affairs.
The “phenomenology of everydayness” is supposed to lead us to see the totality
of human existence, including our moods, our capacity for authentic individuality,
and our full range of involvements with the world and with others. The analytic
of Dasein is also an ontological hermeneutics to the extent that it provides an
account of how understanding in general is possible. The result of the analytic
is a portrayal of human existence that is in accord with what Heidegger regards
as the earliest Greek experience of being as an emerging-into-presence
(physis): to be human is to be a temporal event of self-manifestation that lets
other sorts of entities first come to “emerge and abide” in the world. From the
standpoint of this description, the traditional concept of substance – whether
mental or physical – simply has no role to play in grasping humans. Heidegger’s
brilliant diagnoses or “de-structurings” of the tradition suggest that the idea
of substance arises only when the conditions making entities possible are
forgotten or concealed. Heidegger holds that there is no pregiven human
essence. Instead, humans, as self-interpreting beings, just are what they make
of themselves in the course of their active lives. Thus, as everyday agency,
Dasein is not an object with properties, but is rather the “happening” of a
life course “stretched out between birth and death.” Understood as the
“historicity” of a temporal movement or “becoming,” Dasein is found to have
three main “existentials” or basic structures shared by every “existentiell”
(i.e., specific and local) way of living. First, Dasein finds itself thrown
into a world not of its choosing, already delivered over to the task of living
out its life in a concrete context. This “facticity” of our lives is revealed
in the moods that let things matter to us in some way or other – e.g., the
burdensome feelings of concern that accompany being a parent in our culture.
Second, as projection, Dasein is always already taking some stand on its life
by acting in the world. Understood as agency, human existence is “ahead of
itself” in two senses: (1) our competent dealings with filiar situations sketch
out a range of possibilities for how things may turn out in the future, and (2)
each of our actions is contributing to shaping our lives as people of specific
sorts. Dasein is futuredirected in the sense that the ongoing fulfillment of
possibilities in the course of one’s active life constitutes one’s identity (or
being). To say that Dasein is “being-toward-death” is to say that the stands we
take (our “understanding”) define our being as a totality. Thus, my actual ways
of treating my children throughout my life define my being as a parent in the
end, regardless of what good intentions I might have. Finally, Dasein is
discourse in the sense that we are always articulating – or “addressing and
discussing” – the entities that show up in our concernful absorption in current
situations. These three existentials define human existence as a temporal
unfolding. The unity of these dimensions – being already in a world, ahead of
itself, and engaged with things – Heidegger calls care. This is what it means
to say that humans are the entities whose being is at issue for them. Taking a
stand on our own being, we constitute our identity through what we do. The
formal structure of Dasein as temporality is made concrete through one’s
specific involvements in the world (where ‘world’ is used in the life-world sense
in which we talk about the business world or the world of academia). Dasein is
the unitary phenomenon of being-in-the-world. A core component of Heidegger’s
early works is his description of how Dasein’s practical dealings with
equipment define the being of the entities that show up in the world. In
hmering in a workshop, e.g., what ordinarily shows up for us is not a
hmer-thing with properties, but rather a web of significance relations shaped
by Heidegger, Martin Heidegger, Martin 371 4065h-l.qxd 371
our projects. Hmering is “in order to” join boards, which is “for” building a
bookcase, which is “for the sake of” being a person with a neat study. The hmer
is encountered in terms of its place in this holistic context of functionality
– the “ready-to-hand.” In other words, the being of the equipment – its
“ontological definition” – consists of its relations to other equipment and its
actual use within the entire practical context. Seen from this standpoint, the
brute, meaningless objects assumed to be basic by the metaphysical tradition –
the “present-at-hand” – can show up only when there is a breakdown in our
ordinary dealings with things, e.g., when the hmer breaks or is missing. In
this sense, the ready-to-hand is said to be more primordial than the material
objects treated as basic by the natural sciences. It follows, then, that the
being of entities in the world is constituted by the frework of intelligibility
or “disclosedness” opened by Dasein’s practices. This clearing is truth in the
original meaning of the Greek word aletheia, which Heidegger renders as
‘un-concealment’. But it would be wrong to think that what is claimed here is
that humans are initially just given, and that they then go on to create a
clearing. For, in Heidegger’s view, our own being as agents of specific types
is defined by the world into which we are thrown: in my workshop, I can be a
craftsman or an ateur, but not a surai paying court to a daimyo. Our identity
as agents is made possible by the context of shared forms of life and
linguistic practices of a public life-world. For the most part, we exist as the
“they” (das Man), participants in the historically constituted “cohappening of
a people” (Volk). The embeddedness of our existence in a cultural context
explains our inveterate tendency toward inauthenticity. As we become initiated
into the practices of our community, we are inclined to drift along with the
crowd, doing what “one” does, enacting stereotyped roles, and thereby losing
our ability to seize on and define our own lives. Such falling into public
preoccupations Heidegger sees as a sign that we are fleeing from the fact that
we are finite beings who stand before death (understood as the culmination of
our possibilities). When, through anxiety and hearing the call of conscience,
we face up to our being-toward-death, our lives can be transformed. To be
authentic is to clear-sightedly face up to one’s responsibility for what one’s
life is adding up to as a whole. And because our lives are inseparable from our
community’s existence, authenticity involves seizing on the possibilities
circulating in our shared “heritage” in order to realize a communal “destiny.”
Heidegger’s ideal of resolute “taking action” in the current historical
situation no doubt contributed to his leap into politics in the 1930s.
According to his writings of that period, the ancient Greeks inaugurated a
“first beginning” for Western civilization, but centuries of forgetfulness
(beginning with the Latinization of Greek words) have torn us away from the
primal experience of being rooted in that initial setting. Heidegger hoped
that, guided by the insights embodied in great works of art (especially
Hölderlin’s poetry), National Socialism would help bring about a
world-rejuvenating “new beginning” comparable to the first beginning in ancient
Greece. Heidegger’s later writings attempt to fully escape the subjectivism he
sees dominating Western thought from its inception up to Nietzsche. “The Origin
of the Work of Art” (1935), for exple, shows how a great work of art such as a
Greek temple, by shaping the world in which a people live, constitutes the
kinds of people that can live in that world. An Introduction to Metaphysics
(1935) tries to recover the Greek experience of humans as beings whose
activities of gathering and ning (logos) are above all a response to what is
more than human. The later writings emphasize that which resists all human
mastery and comprehension. Such terms as ‘nothingness’, ‘earth’, and ‘mystery’
suggest that what shows itself to us always depends on a background of what
does not show itself, what remains concealed. Language comes to be understood
as the medium through which anything, including the human, first becomes
accessible and intelligible. Because language is the source of all
intelligibility, Heidegger says that humans do not speak, but rather language
speaks us – an idea that bece central to poststructuralist theories. In his
writings after the war, Heidegger replaces the notions of resoluteness and
political activism with a new ideal of letting-be or releasement
(Gelassenheit), a stance characterized by meditative thinking, thankfulness for
the “gift” of being, and openness to the silent “call” of language. The
technological “enfring” (Gestell) of our age – encountering everything as a
standing reserve on hand for our use – is treated not as something humans do,
but instead as a manifestation of being itself. The “anti-humanism” of these
later works is seen in the description of technology (the mobilization of
everything for the sole purpose of greater efficiency) as an Heidegger, Martin
Heidegger, Martin 372 4065h-l.qxd 372
epochal event in the “history of being,” a way things have come-into-their-own
(Ereignis) rather than as a human accomplishment. The history or “sending”
(Geschick) of being consists of epochs that have all gone increasingly astray
from the original beginning inaugurated by the pre-Socratics. Since human
willpower alone cannot bring about a new epoch, technology cannot be ended by
our efforts. But a non-technological way of encountering things is hinted at in
a description of a jug as a fourfold of earth, sky, mortals, and gods, and
Heidegger reflects on forms of poetry that point to a new, non-metaphysical way
of experiencing being. Through a transformed relation to language and art, and
by abandoning “onto-theology” (the attempt to ground all entities in one
supreme entity), we might prepare ourselves for a transformed way of
understanding being.
Hellenistic philosophy,
the philosophical systems of the Hellenistic age (323–30 B.C., although 311–87
B.C. better defines it as a philosophical era), notably Epicureanism, Stoicism,
and Skepticism. These all emerged in the generation after Aristotle’s death
(322 B.C.), and dominated philosophical debate until the first century B.C.,
during which there were revivals of traditional Platonism and of
Aristotelianism. The age was one in which much of the eastern Mediterranean
world absorbed Greek culture (was “Hellenized,” hence “Hellenistic”), and
recruits to philosophy flocked from this region to Athens, which remained the
center of philosophical activity until 87 B.C. Then the Roman sack of Athens
drove many philosophers into exile, and neither the schools nor the styles of
philosophy that had grown up there ever fully recovered. Very few philosophical
writings survive intact from the period. Our knowledge of Hellenistic
philosophers depends mainly on later doxography, on the Roman writers Lucretius
and Cicero (both mid-first century B.C.), and on what we learn from the
schools’ critics in later centuries, e.g. Sextus Empiricus and Plutarch.
’Skeptic’, a term not actually current before the very end of the Hellenistic
age, serves as a convenient label to characterize two philosophical movements.
The first is the New Academy: the school founded by Plato, the Academy, bece in
this period a largely dialectical one, conducting searching critiques of other
schools’ doctrines without declaring any of its own, beyond perhaps the
assertion (however guarded) that nothing could be known and the accompanying
recommendation of “suspension of judgment” (epoche). The nature and vivacity of
Stoicism owed much to its prolonged debates with the New Academy. The founder
of this Academic phase was Arcesilaus (school head c.268– c.241); its most
revered and influential protagonist was Carneades (school head in the
mid-second century); and its most prestigious voice was that of Cicero (106–43
B.C.), whose highly influential philosophical works were written mainly from a
New Academic stance. But by the early first century B.C. the Academy was
drifting back to a more doctrinal stance, and in the later part of the century
it was largely eclipsed by a second “skeptic” movement, Pyrrhonism. This was
founded by Aenesidemus, a pioneering skeptic despite his claim to be merely
reviving the philosophy of Pyrrho, a philosophical guru of the early
Hellenistic period. His neo-Pyrrhonism survives today mainly through the
writings of Sextus Empiricus (second century A.D.), an adherent of the school
who, strictly speaking, represents its post-Hellenistic phase. The Peripatos,
Aristotle’s school, officially survived throughout the era, but it is not
regarded as a distinctively “Hellenistic” movement. Despite the eminence of
Aristotle’s first successor, Theophrastus (school head 322–287), it thereafter
fell from prominence, its fortunes only reviving around the mid-first century
B.C. It is disputed how far the other Hellenistic philosophers were even aware
of Aristotle’s treatises, which should not in any case be regarded as a primary
influence on them. Each school had a location in Athens to which it could draw
pupils. The Epicurean school was a relatively private institution, its “Garden”
outside the city walls housing a close-knit philosophical community. The Stoics
took their ne from the Stoa Poikile, the “Painted Colonnade” in central Athens
where they gathered. The Academics were based in the Academy, a public grove
just outside the city. Philosophers were public figures, a filiar sight around
town. Each school’s philosophical identity was further clarified by its
absolute loyalty to the ne of its Heidelberg School Hellenistic philosophy 373
4065h-l.qxd 373 founder –
respectively Epicurus, Zeno of Citium, and Plato – and by the polarities that
developed in interschool debates. Epicureanism is dietrically opposed on most
issues to Stoicism. Academic Skepticism provides another antithesis to
Stoicism, not through any positions of its own (it had none), but through its
unflagging critical cpaign against every Stoic thesis. It is often said that in
this age the old Greek political institution of the city-state had broken down,
and that the Hellenistic philosophies were an answer to the resulting crisis of
values. Whether or not there is any truth in this, it remains clear that moral
concerns were now much less confined to the individual city-state than
previously, and that at an extreme the boundaries had been pushed back to
include all mankind within the scope of an individual’s moral obligations. Our
“affinity” (oikeiosis) to all mankind is an originally Stoic doctrine that
acquired increasing currency with other schools. This attitude partly reflects
the weakening of national and cultural boundaries in the Hellenistic period, as
also in the Roman imperial period that followed it. The three recognized
divisions of philosophy were ethics, logic, and physics. In ethics, the central
objective was to state and defend an account of the “end” (telos), the moral
goal to which all activity was subordinated: the Epicureans ned pleasure, the
Stoics conformity with nature. Much debate centered on the semimythical figure
of the wise man, whose conduct in every conceivable circumstance was debated by
all schools. Logic in its modern sense was primarily a Stoic concern, rejected
as irrelevant by the Epicureans. But Hellenistic logic included epistemology,
where the primary focus of interest was the “criterion of truth,” the ultimate
yardstick against which all judgments could be reliably tested. Empiricism was
a surprisingly uncontroversial feature of Hellenistic theories: there was
little interest in the Platonic-Aristotelian idea that knowledge in the strict
sense is non-sensory, and the debate between dogmatists and Skeptics was more
concerned with the question whether any proposed sensory criterion was
adequate. Both Stoics and Epicureans attached especial importance to prolepsis,
the generic notion of a thing, held to be either innate or naturally acquired
in a way that gave it a guaranteed veridical status. Physics saw an opposition
between Epicurean atomism, with its denial of divine providence, and the Stoic
world-continuum, imbued with divine rationality. The issue of determinism was
also placed on the philosophical map: Epicurean morality depends on the denial
of (both physical and logical) determinism, whereas Stoic morality is
compatible with, indeed actually requires, the deterministic causal nexus
through which providence operates.
DOXOGRAPHERS,
EPICUREANISM, SKEPTICS, STOICISM. D.N.S. Helmholtz, Hermann von (1821–94),
German physiologist and physicist known for groundbreaking work in physics,
physiological optics, perceptual psychology, and the philosophy of geometry.
Formally trained as a physician, he distinguished himself in physics in 1848 as
a codiscoverer of the law of conservation of energy, and by the end of his life
was perhaps the most influential figure in German physical research.
Philosophically, his most important influence was on the study of space.
Intuitionist psychologists held that the geometrical structure of
three-dimensional space was given directly in sensation by innate physiological
mechanisms; Helmholtz brought this theory to severe empirical trials and
argued, on the contrary, that our knowledge of space consists of inferences
from accumulated experience. On the mathematical side, he attacked Kant’s view
that Euclidean geometry is the a priori form of outer intuition by showing that
it is possible to have visual experience of non-Euclidean space (“On the
Origins and Meaning of Geometrical Axioms,” 1870). His crucial insight was that
empirical geometry depends on physical assumptions about the behavior of
measuring instruments. This inspired the view of Poincaré and logical
empiricism that the empirical content of geometry is fixed by physical
definitions, and made possible Einstein’s use of non-Euclidean geometry in
physics.
PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS, POINCARÉ. R.D.
Helvétius, Claude Adrien (1715–71), French philosopher prominent in the
formative phases of eighteenth-century materialism in France. His De l’esprit
(1758) was widely discussed internationally, but condemned by the University of
Paris and burned by the government. Helvétius attempted to clarify his doctrine
in his posthumously published De l’homme. Following Locke’s criticism of the
innate ideas, Helvétius stressed the function of experience in our acquisition
of knowledge. In accord with the doctrines of d’Holbach, Condillac, and La
Mettrie, the materialist Helvétius regarded the sensations as the basis of all
our knowledge. Only by Helmholtz, Hermann von Helvétius, Claude Adrien 374
4065h-l.qxd 374 comparison,
abstraction, and combination of sensations do we reach the level of concepts.
Peculiar to Helvétius, however, is the stress on the social determinations of
our knowledge. Specific interests and passions are the starting point of all
our striving for knowledge. Egoism is the spring of our desires and actions.
The civil laws of the enlightened state enabled egoism to be transformed into
social competition and thereby diverted toward public benefits. Like his
materialist contemporary d’Holbach and later Condorcet, Helvétius sharply
criticized the social function of the church. Priests, he claimed, provided
society with wrong moral ideas. He demanded a thorough reform of the
educational system for the purpose of individual and social emancipation. In
contrast to the teachings of Rousseau, Helvétius praised the further
development of science, art, and industry as instruments for the historical
progress of mankind. The ideal society consists of enlightened because
well-educated citizens living in comfortable and even moderately luxurious
circumstances. All people should participate in the search for truth, by means
of public debates and discussions. Truth is equated with the moral good.
Helvétius had some influence on Marxist historical materialism. H.P. Hempel,
Carl G(ustav) (1905–97), eminent philosopher of science associated with the
Vienna Circle of logical empiricist philosophers in the early 1930s, before his
emigration to the United States; thereafter he bece one of the most influential
philosophers of science of his time, largely through groundbreaking work on the
logical analysis of the concepts of confirmation and scientific explanation.
Hempel received his doctorate under Reichenbach at the University of Berlin in
1934 with a dissertation on the logical analysis of probability. He studied
with Carnap at the University of Vienna in 1929–30, where he participated in
the “protocol-sentence debate” concerning the observational basis of scientific
knowledge raging within the Vienna Circle between Moritz Schlick (1882–1936)
and Otto Neurath (1882–1945). Hempel was attracted to the “radical physicalism”
articulated by Neurath and Carnap, which denied the foundational role of immediate
experience and asserted that all statements of the total language of science
(including observation reports or protocol-sentences) can be revised as science
progresses. This led to Hempel’s first major publication, “On the Logical
Positivists’ Theory of Truth” (1935). He moved to the United States to work
with Carnap at the University of Chicago in 1937–38. He also taught at Queens
College and Yale before his long career at Princeton (1955–1975). In the 1940s
he collaborated with his friends Olaf Helmer and Paul Oppenheim on a celebrated
series of papers, the most influential of which are “Studies in the Logic of
Confirmation” (1945) and “Studies in the Logic of Explanation” (1948,
coauthored with Oppenheim). The latter paper articulated the deductive-nomological
model, which characterizes scientific explanations as deductively valid
arguments proceeding from general laws and initial conditions to the fact to be
explained, and served as the basis for all future work on the subject. Hempel’s
papers on explanation and confirmation (and also related topics such as concept
formation, criteria of meaningfulness, and scientific theories) were collected
together in Aspects of Scientific Explanation (1965), one of the most important
works in postwar philosophy of science. He also published a more popular, but
extremely influential introduction to the field, Philosophy of Natural Science
(1966). Hempel and Kuhn bece colleagues at Princeton in the 1960s. Another
fruitful collaboration ensued, as a result of which Hempel moved away from the
Carnapian tradition of logical analysis toward a more naturalistic and
pragmatic conception of science in his later work. As he himself explains,
however, this later turn can also be seen as a return to a similarly
naturalistic conception Neurath had earlier defended within the Vienna
Circle.
henotheism, allegiance to
one supreme deity while conceding existence to others; also described as
monolatry, incipient monotheism, or practical monotheism. It occupies a middle
ground between polytheism and radical monotheism, which denies reality to all
gods save one. It has been claimed that early Judaism passed through a
henotheistic phase, acknowledging other Middle Eastern deities (albeit
condemning their worship), en route to exclusive recognition of Yahweh. But the
concept of progress from polytheism through henotheism Hempel, Carl G(ustav)
henotheism 375 4065h-l.qxd 375 to
monotheism is a rationalizing construct, and cannot be supposed to capture the
complex development of any historical religion, including that of ancient
Israel. A.E.L. Henry of Ghent (c.1217–93), Belgian theologian and philosopher.
After serving as a church official at Tournai and Brugge, he taught theology at
Paris from 1276. His major writings were Summa quaestionum ordinariarum (Summa
of Ordinary Questions) and Quodlibeta (Quodlibetal Questions). He was the
leading representative of the neoAugustinian movement at Paris in the final
quarter of the thirteenth century. His theory of knowledge combines Aristotelian
elements with Augustinian illuminationism. Heavily dependent on Avicenna for
his view of the reality enjoyed by essences of creatures (esse essentiae) from
eternity, he rejected both real distinction and real identity of essence and
existence in creatures, and defended their intentional distinction. He also
rejected a real distinction between the soul and its powers and rejected the
purely potential character of prime matter. He defended the duality of
substantial form in man, the unicity of form in other material substances, and
the primacy of will in the act of choice. J.F.W. Hentisberi,
Hentisberus.HEYTESBURY. Heraclitus (fl. c.500 B.C.), Greek philosopher. A
transition figure between the Milesian philosophers and the later pluralists,
Heraclitus stressed unity in the world of change. He follows the Milesians in
positing a series of cyclical transformations of basic stuffs of the world; for
instance, he holds that fire changes to water and earth in turn. Moreover, he
seems to endorse a single source or arche of natural substances, nely fire. But
he also observes that natural transformations necessarily involve contraries
such as hot and cold, wet and dry. Indeed, without the one contrary the other
would not exist, and without contraries the cosmos would not exist. Hence
strife is justice, and war is the father and king of all. In the conflict of
opposites there is a hidden harmony that sustains the world, symbolized by the
tension of a bow or the attunement of a lyre. Scholars disagree about whether
Heraclitus’s chief view is that there is a one in the many or that process is
reality. Clearly the underlying unity of phenomena is important for him. But he
also stresses the transience of physical substances and the importance of
processes and qualities. Moreover, his underlying source of unity seems to be a
law of process and opposition; thus he seems to affirm both the unity of
phenomena and the reality of process. Criticizing his predecessors such as
Pythagoras and Xenophanes for doing research without insight, Heraclitus claims
that we should listen to the logos, which teaches that all things are one. The
logos, a principle of order and knowledge, is common to all, but the many
remain ignorant of it, like sleepwalkers unaware of the reality around them. All
things come to pass according to the logos; hence it is the law of change, or
at least its expression. Heraclitus wrote a single book, perhaps organized into
sections on cosmology, politics and ethics, and theology. Apparently, however,
he did not provide a continuous argument but a series of epigrmatic remarks
meant to reveal the nature of reality through oracular and riddling language.
Although he seems to have been a recluse without immediate disciples, he may
have stirred Parmenides to his reaction against contraries. In the late fifth
century B.C. Cratylus of Athens preached a radical Heraclitean doctrine
according to which everything is in flux and there is accordingly no knowledge
of the world. This version of Heracliteanism influenced Plato’s view of the
sensible world and caused Plato and Aristotle to attribute a radical doctrine
of flux to Heraclitus. Democritus imitated Heraclitus’s ethical sayings, and in
Hellenistic times the Stoics appealed to him for their basic principles.
Herbart, Johann Friedrich
(1776–1841), German philosopher who significantly contributed to psychology and
the theory of education. Rejecting the idealism of Fichte and Hegel, he
attempted to establish a form of psychology founded on experience. The task of
philosophy is the analysis of concepts given in ordinary experience. Logic must
clarify these concepts, Metaphysics should correct them, while Aesthetics and
Ethics are to complement them by an analysis of values. Herbart advocated a
form of determinism in psychology and ethics. The laws that govern
psychological processes are identical with those that govern the heavens. He
subordinated ethics to aesthetics, arguing that our moral values originate from
certain immediate and involuntary judgments of like and dislike. The five basic
ideas of morality are inner freedom, perfection, benevolence, law, and justice
or equity. Herbart’s view of education – that it should aim at producing
individuals who possess inner freedom and strength of character – was highly
influential in nineteenth-century Germany. M.K. Henry of Ghent Herbart, Johann
Friedrich 376 4065h-l.qxd 376 Herder,
Johann Gottfried von (1744–1803), German philosopher, an intellectual and
literary figure central to the transition from the German Enlightenment to Romanticism.
He was born in East Prussia and received an early classical education. About
1762, while studying theology at the University of Königsberg, he ce under the
influence of Kant. He also began a lifelong friendship with Hann, who
especially stimulated his interests in the interrelations ong language,
culture, and history. After ordination as a Lutheran minister in 1765, he began
his association with the Berlin Academy, earning its prestigious “prize” for
his “Essay on the Origin of Language” (1772). In 1776 he was appointed
Generalsuperintendent of the Lutheran clergy at Weimar through the intercession
of Goethe. He was then able to focus his intellectual and literary powers on
most of the major issues of his time. Of particular note are his contributions
to psychology in Of the Cognition and Sensation of the Human Soul (1778); to
the philosophy of history and culture in Ideas for the Philosophy of the
History of Mankind (1784–91), perhaps his most influential work; and to
philosophy in Understanding and Experience (1799), which contains his extensive
Metakritik of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. Herder was an intellectual
maverick and provocateur, writing when the Enlightenment conception of reason
was in decline but before its limited defense by Kant or its total rejection by
Romanticism had become entrenched in the German-speaking world. Rejecting any
rational system, Herder’s thought is best viewed as a mosaic of certain ideas
that reemerge in various guises throughout his writings. Because of these features,
Herder’s thought has been compared with that of Rousseau. Herder’s philosophy
can be described as involving elements of naturalism, organicism, and vitalism.
He rejected philosophical explanations, appealing to the supernatural or
divine, such as the concept of the “immortal soul” in psychology, a “divine
origin” of language, or “providence” in history. He sought to discern an
underlying primordial force to account for the psychological unity of the
various “faculties.” He viewed this natural tendency toward “organic formation”
as also operative in language and culture, and as ultimately manifested in the
dynic development of the various cultures in the form of a universal history.
Finally, he often wrote in a way that suggested the dynic process of life
itself as the basic metaphor undergirding his thought. His influence can be
traced through Humboldt into later linguistics and through Schelling and Hegel
in the philosophy of history and later German historicism. He anticipated
elements of vitalism in Schopenhauer and Bergson.
hermeneutics, the art or
theory of interpretation, as well as a type of philosophy that starts with
questions of interpretation. Originally concerned more narrowly with
interpreting sacred texts, the term acquired a much broader significance in its
historical development and finally bece a philosophical position in
twentieth-century German philosophy. There are two competing positions in
hermeneutics: whereas the first follows Dilthey and sees interpretation or
Verstehen as a method for the historical and human sciences, the second follows
Heidegger and sees it as an “ontological event,” an interaction between
interpreter and text that is part of the history of what is understood.
Providing rules or criteria for understanding what an author or native “really”
meant is a typical problem for the first approach. The interpretation of the
law provides an exple for the second view, since the process of applying the
law inevitably transforms it. In general, hermeneutics is the analysis of this
process and its conditions of possibility. It has typically focused on the
interpretation of ancient texts and distant peoples, cases where the
unproblematic everyday understanding and communication cannot be assumed.
Schleiermacher’s analysis of understanding and expression related to texts and
speech marks the beginning of hermeneutics in the modern sense of a scientific
methodology. This emphasis on methodology continues in nineteenth-century
historicism and culminates in Dilthey’s attempt to ground the human sciences in
a theory of interpretation, understood as the imaginative but publicly
verifiable reenactment of the subjective experiences of others. Such a method
of interpretation reveals the possibility of an objective knowledge of human beings
not accessible to empiricist inquiry and thus of a distinct methodology for the
human sciences. One result of the analysis of interpretation in the nineteenth
century was the recognition of “the hermeneutic circle,” first developed by
SchleierHerder, Johann Gottfried von hermeneutics 377 4065h-l.qxd 377 macher. The circularity of
interpretation concerns the relation of parts to the whole: the interpretation
of each part is dependent on the interpretation of the whole. But
interpretation is circular in a stronger sense: if every interpretation is
itself based on interpretation, then the circle of interpretation, even if it
is not vicious, cannot be escaped. Twentieth-century hermeneutics advanced by
Heidegger and Gader radicalize this notion of the hermeneutic circle, seeing it
as a feature of all knowledge and activity. Hermeneutics is then no longer the
method of the human sciences but “universal,” and interpretation is part of the
finite and situated character of all human knowing. “Philosophical
hermeneutics” therefore criticizes Cartesian foundationalism in epistemology
and Enlightenment universalism in ethics, seeing science as a cultural practice
and prejudices (or prejudgments) as ineliminable in all judgments. Positively,
it emphasizes understanding as continuing a historical tradition, as well as
dialogical openness, in which prejudices are challenged and horizons
broadened.
GADER, HEIDEGGER,
HISTORICISM, SCHLEIERMACHER, VERSTEHEN. J.Bo. hermeticism.HERMETISM. hermetism,
also hermeticism, a philosophical theology whose basic impulse was the gnostic
conviction that human salvation depends on revealed knowledge (gnosis) of God
and of the human and natural creations. Texts ascribed to Hermes Trismegistus,
a Greco-Egyptian version of the Egyptian god Thoth, may have appeared as early
as the fourth century B.C., but the surviving Corpus Hermeticum in Greek and
Latin is a product of the second and third centuries A.D. Fragments of the se
literature exist in Greek, Armenian, and Coptic as well; the Coptic versions
are part of a discovery made at Nag Hmadi after World War II. All these
Hermetica record hermetism as just described. Other Hermetica traceable to the
se period but surviving in later Arabic or Latin versions deal with astrology,
alchemy, magic, and other kinds of occultism. Lactantius, Augustine, and other
early Christians cited Hermes but disagreed on his value; before Iblichus,
pagan philosophers showed little interest. Muslims connected Hermes with a
Koranic figure, Idris, and thereby enlarged the medieval hermetic tradition,
which had its first large effects in the Latin West ong the twelfth-century
Platonists of Chartres. The only ancient hermetic text then available in the
West was the Latin Asclepius, but in 1463 Ficino interrupted his epochal
translation of Plato to Latinize fourteen of the seventeen Greek discourses in
the main body of the Corpus Hermeticum (as distinct from the many Greek
fragments preserved by Stobaeus but unknown to Ficino). Ficino was willing to
move so quickly to Hermes because he believed that this Egyptian deity stood at
the head of the “ancient theology” (prisca theologia), a tradition of pagan
revelation that ran parallel to Christian scripture, culminated with Plato, and
continued through Plotinus and the later Neoplatonists. Ficino’s Hermes
translation, which he called the Pimander, shows no interest in the magic and
astrology about which he theorized later in his career. Trinitarian theology
was his original motivation. The Pimander was enormously influential in the
later Renaissance, when Giovanni Pico della Mirandola, Lodovico Lazzarelli,
Jacques Lefèvre d’Etaples, Symphorien Chpier, Francesco Giorgi, Agostino
Steuco, Francesco Patrizi, and others enriched Western appreciation of Hermes.
The first printed Greek Hermetica was the 1554 edition of Adrien Turnebus. The
last before the nineteenth century appeared in 1630, a textual hiatus that
reflected a decline in the reputation of Hermes after Isaac Casaubon proved
philologically in 1614 that the Greek Hermetica had to be post-Christian, not
the remains of primeval Egyptian wisdom. After Casaubon, hermetic ideas fell
out of fashion with most Western philosophers of the current canon, but the
historiography of the ancient theology remained influential for Newton and for
lesser figures even later. The content of the Hermetica was out of tune with
the new science, so Casaubon’s redating left Hermes to the theosophical heirs
of Robert Fludd, whose opponents (Kepler, Mersenne, Gassendi) turned away from
the Hermetica and similar fascinations of Renaissance humanist culture. By the
nineteenth century, only theosophists took Hermes seriously as a prophet of
pagan wisdom, but he was then rediscovered by German students of Christianity
and Hellenistic religions, especially Richard Reitzenstein, who published his
Poimandres in 1904. The ancient Hermetica are now read in the 1946–54 edition
of A. D. Nock and A. J. Festugière.
FICINO. B.P.C. Herzen, Alexander (1812–70), Russian editor, memoirist,
and social philosopher, in exile in Western Europe from 1847. Herzen moved in
his philosophy of history from an early Hegelian hermeticism Herzen, Alexander
378 4065h-l.qxd 378 rationalism to a
“philosophy of contingency,” stressing the “whirlwind of chances” in nature and
in human life and the “tousled improvisation” of the historical process. He
rejected determinism, emphasizing the “phenomenological fact” of the
experienced “sense of freedom.” Anticipating the Dostoevsky of the “Legend of
the Grand Inquisitor,” he offered an original analysis of the “escape from
freedom” and the cleaving to moral and political authority, and sketched a
curiously contemporary-sounding “emotivist” ethical theory. After 1848,
disillusioned with “bourgeois” Europe and its “selfenclosed individualism,” but
equally disillusioned with what he had come to see as the bourgeois ideal of
many European socialists, Herzen turned to the Russian peasant and the peasant
village commune as offering the best hope for a humane development of society.
In this “Russian socialism” he anticipated a central doctrine of the Russian
populists of the 1870s. Herzen stood alone in resisting the common tendency of
such otherwise different thinkers as Feuerbach, Marx, and J. S. Mill to
undervalue the historical present, to overvalue the historical future, and to
treat actual persons as means in the service of remote, merely possible
historical ends. Herzen’s own central emphasis fell powerfully and consistently
on the freedom, independence, and non-instrumentalizable value of living
persons. And he saw more clearly than any of his contemporaries that there are
no future persons, that it is only in the present that free human individuals
live and move and have their being.
RUSSIAN
PHILOSOPHY. G.L.K.
heterological.SET-THEORETIC PARADOXES. heteronomy.KANT. heuristics, a rule or
solution adopted to reduce the complexity of computational tasks, thereby
reducing demands on resources such as time, memory, and attention. If an
algorithm is a procedure yielding a correct solution to a problem, then a
heuristic procedure may not reach a solution even if there is one, or may
provide an incorrect answer. The reliability of heuristics varies between
domains; the resulting biases are predictable, and provide information about
system design. Chess, for exple, is a finite ge with a finite number of
possible positions, but there is no known algorithm for finding the optimal
move. Computers and humans both employ heuristics in evaluating intermediate
moves, relying on a few significant cues to ge quality, such as safety of the
king, material balance, and center control. The use of these criteria
simplifies the problem, making it computationally tractable. They are heuristic
guides, reliable but limited in success. There is no guarantee that the result
will be the best move or even good. They are nonetheless satisfactory for
competent chess. Work on human judgment indicates a similar moral. Exples of
judgmental infelicities support the view that human reasoning systematically
violates standards for statistical reasoning, ignoring base rates, sple size,
and correlations. Experimental results suggest that humans utilize judgmental
heuristics in gauging probabilities, such as representativeness, or the degree
to which an individual or event resembles a prototypical member of a category.
Such heuristics produce reasonable judgments in many cases, but are of limited
validity when measured by a Bayesian standard. Judgmental heuristics are biased
and subject to systemic errors. Experimental support for the importance of
these heuristics depends on cases in which subjects deviate from the normative
standard. BAYESIAN RATIONALITY,
EMPIRICAL DECISION THEORY. R.C.R. hexis (Greek, from hexo, ‘to have’, ‘to be
disposed’), a (good or bad) condition, disposition, or state. The traditional
rendering, ‘habit’ (Latin habitus), is misleading, for it tends to suggest the
idea of an involuntary and merely repetitious pattern of behavior. A hexis is
rather a state of character or of mind that disposes us to deliberately choose
to act or to think in a certain way. The term acquired a quasi-technical status
after Aristotle advanced the view that hexis is the genus of virtue, both moral
and intellectual. In the Nicomachean Ethics he distinguishes hexeis from
passions (pathe) and faculties (dunis) of the soul. If a man fighting in the
front ranks feels afraid when he sees the enemy approaching, he is undergoing
an involuntary passion. His capacity to be affected by fear on this or other
occasions is part of his makeup, one of his faculties. If he chooses to stay
where his commanders placed him, this is due to the hexis or state of character
we call courage. Likewise, one who is consistently good at identifying what is
best for oneself can be said to possess a hexis called prudence. Not all states
and dispositions are commendable. Cowardice and stupidity are also hexeis. Both
in the sense of ‘state’ and of ‘possession’ hexis plays a role in Aristotle’s
Categories.
Heytesbury, Willi, also
called Hentisberus, Hentisberi, Tisberi (before 1313–c.1372), English
philosopher and chancellor of Oxford University. He wrote Sophismata
(“Sophisms”), Regulae solvendi sophismata (“Rules for Solving Sophisms”), and
De sensu composito et diviso (“On the Composite and Divided Sense”). Other works
are doubtfully attributed to him. Heytesbury belonged to the generation
immediately after Thomas Bradwardine and Kilvington, and was ong the most
significant members of the Oxford Calculators, important in the early
developemnt of physics. Unlike Kilvington but like Bradwardine, he appealed to
mathematical calculations in addition to logical and conceptual analysis in the
treatment of change, motion, acceleration, and other physical notions. His
Regulae includes perhaps the most influential treatment of the liar paradox in
the Middle Ages. Heytesbury’s work makes widespread use of “imaginary” thought
experiments assuming physical impossibilities that are yet logically
consistent. His influence was especially strong in Italy in the fifteenth
century, where his works were studied widely and commented on many times.
PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE,
QUANTUM MECHANICS. hierarchical system.COMPUTER THEORY. hierarchy, a division
of mathematical objects into subclasses in accordance with an ordering that
reflects their complexity. Around the turn of the century, analysts interested
in the “descriptive set theory” of the real numbers defined and studied two
systems of classification for sets of reals, the Borel (due to Emil Borel) and
the G hierarchies. In the 1940s, logicians interested in recursion and
definability (most importantly, Stephen Kleene) introduced and studied other
hierarchies (the arithmetic, the hyperarithmetic, and the analytical
hierarchies) of reals (identified with sets of natural numbers) and of sets of
reals; the relations between this work and the earlier work were made explicit
in the 1950s by J. Addison. Other sorts of hierarchies have been introduced in
other corners of logic. All these so-called hierarchies have at least this in
common: they divide a class of mathematical objects into subclasses subject to
a natural well-founded ordering (e.g., by subsethood) that reflects the
complexity (in a sense specific to the hierarchy under consideration) of the
objects they contain. What follows describes several hierarchies from the study
of definability. (For more historical and mathematical information see
Descriptive Set Theory by Y. Moschovakis, North-Holland Publishing Co., 1980.)
(1) Hierarchies of formulas. Consider a formal language L with quantifiers ‘E’
and ‘D’. Given a set B of formulas in L, we inductively define a hierarchy that
treats the members of B as “basic.” Set P0 % S0 % B. Suppose sets Pn and Sn of
formulas have been defined. Let Pn!1 % the set of all formulas of the form Q1u1
. . . Qmumw when u1, . . . , um are distinct variables, Q1, . . . , Qm are all
‘E’, m M 1, and w 1 Sn. Let Sn+1 % the set of all formulas of that form for Q1,
. . . , Qm all ‘D’, and w 1 Pn. Here are two such hierarchies for languages of
arithmetic. Take the logical constants to be truthfunctions, ‘E’ and ‘D’. (i)
Let L0 % the first-order language of arithmetic, based on ‘%’, a two-place
predicate-constant ‘‹’, an individual-constant for 0, functionconstants for
successor, addition, and multiplication; ‘first-order’ means that bound
variables are all first-order (ranging over individuals); we’ll allow free
second-order variables (ranging over properties or sets of individuals). Let B
% the set of bounded formulas, i.e. those formed from atomic formulas using
connectives and bounded quantification: if w is bounded so are Eu(u ‹ t / w)
and Du(u ‹ t & w). (ii) Let L1 % the second-order language of arithmetic
(formed from L0 by allowing bound second-order variables); let B % the set of
formulas in which no second-order variable is bound, and take all u1, . . . ,
um as above to be second-order variables. (2) Hierarchies of definable sets.
(i) The Arithmetic Hierarchy. For a set of natural numbers (call such a thing
‘a real’) A : A 1 P0 n [ or S0 n ] if and only if A is defined over the
standard model of arithmetic (i.e., with the constant for 0 assigned to 0,
etc., and with the first-order variables ranging over the natural numbers) by a
formula of L0 in Pn [respectively Sn] as described in (1.i). Set D0 n % P0 n
Thus: In fact, all these inclusions are proper. This hierarchy classifies the
reals simple enough to be defined by arithmetic formulas. Exple: ‘Dy x % y ! y’
defines the set even of even natural numHeytesbury, Willi hierarchy 380
4065h-l.qxd 380 bers; the formula 1 S1,
so even 1 S0 1; even is also defined by a formula in P1; so even 1 P0 1, giving
even 1 D0 1. In fact, S0 1 % the class of recursively enumerable reals, and D0
1 % the class of recursive reals. The classification of reals under the
arithmetic hierarchy reflects complexity of defining formulas; it differs from
classification in terms of a notion of degree of unsolvability, that reflecting
a notion of comparative computational complexity; but there are connections
between these classifications. The Arithmetic Hierarchy extends to sets of
reals (using a free second-order variable in defining sentences). Exple: ‘Dx
(Xx & Dy y % x ! x)’ 1 S1 and defines the set of those reals with an even
number; so that set 1 S0 1. (ii) The Analytical Hierarchy. Given a real A : A 1
P1 n [S1 1] if and only if A is defined (over the standard model of arithmetic
with second-order variables ranging over all sets of natural numbers) by a
formula of L1 in Pn (respectively Sn) as described in (1.ii); D1 n % P1 n 3 S1
n. Similarly for a set of reals. The inclusions pictured above carry over,
replacing superscripted 0’s by 1’s. This classifies all reals and sets of reals
simple enough to have analytical (i.e., second-order arithmetic) definitions.
The subscripted ‘n’ in ‘P0 n’, etc., ranged over natural numbers. But the
Arithmetic Hierarchy is extended “upward” into the transfinite by the
rified-analytical hierarchy. Let R0 % the class of all arithmetical reals. For
an ordinal a let Ra!1 % the class of all sets of reals definable by formulas of
L1 in which second-order variables range only over reals in Ra – this
constraint imposes rification. For a limit-ordinal l, let Rl % Ua where n % m !
1. So to determine relative possibility in a model, we identify R with a
collection of pairs of the form where each of u and v is in W. If a pair is in
R, v is possible relative to u, and if is not in R, v is impossible relative to
u. The relative possibility relation then enters into the rules for evaluating
modal operators. For exple, we do not want to say that at the actual world, it
is possible for me to originate from a different sperm and egg, since the only
worlds where this takes place are impossible relative to the actual world. So
we have the rule that B f is true at a world u if f is true at some world v
such that v is possible relative to u. Similarly, Af is true at a world u if f
is true at every world v which is possible relative to u. R may have simple
first-order properties such as reflexivity, (Ex)Rxx, symmetry, (Ex)(Ey)(Rxy P
Ryx), and transitivity, (Ex)(Ey)(Ez)((Rxy & Ryz) P Rxz), and different
modal systems can be modal logic modal logic 575 575 obtained by imposing different
combinations of these on R (other systems can be obtained from higher-order
constraints). The least constrained system is the system K, in which no
structural properties are put on R. In K we have B (B & C) X B B, since if
B (B & C) holds at w* then (B & C) holds at some world w possible
relative to w*, and thus by the truth-function for &, B holds at w as well,
so B B holds at w*. Hence any interpretation that makes B (B & C) true (%
true at w*) also makes B B true. Since there are no restrictions on R in K, we
can expect B (B & C) X B B in every system of modal logic generated by
constraining R. However, for K we also have C Z B C. For suppose C holds at w*.
B C holds at w* only if there is some world possible relative to w* where C
holds. But there need be no such world. In particular, since R need not be
reflexive, w* itself need not be possible relative to w*. Concomitantly, in any
system for which we stipulate a reflexive R, we will have C X B C. The simplest
such system is known as T, which has the se semantics as K except that R is
stipulated to be reflexive in every interpretation. In other systems, further
or different constraints are put on R. For exple, in the system B, each
interpretation must have an R that is reflexive and symmetric, and in the
system S4, each interpretation must have an R that is reflexive and transitive.
In B we have B C Z B B C, as can be shown by an interpretation with
nontransitive R, while in S4 we have B AC Z C, as can be shown by an
interpretation with non-symmetric R. Correspondingly, in S4, B C X B B C, and
in B, B AC X C. The system in which R is reflexive, transitive, and symmetric
is called S5, and in this system, R can be omitted. For if R has all three
properties, R is an equivalence relation, i.e., it partitions W into mutually
exclusive and jointly exhaustive equivalence classes. If Cu is the equivalence
class to which u belongs, then the truthvalue of a formula at u is independent
of the truth-values of sentence letters at worlds not in Cu, so only the worlds
in Cw* are relevant to the truth-values of sentences in an S5 interpretation.
But within Cw* R is universal: every world is possible relative to every other.
Consequently, in an S5 interpretation, we need not specify a relative
possibility relation, and the evaluation rules for B and A need not mention
relative possibility; e.g., we can say that B f is true at a world u if there
is at least one world v at which f is true. Note that by the characteristics of
R, whenever 9 X s in K, T, B, or S4, then 9 X s in S5: the other systems are
contained in S5. K is contained in all the systems we have mentioned, while T
is contained in B and S4, neither of which is contained in the other.
Sentential modal logics give rise to quantified modal logics, of which
quantified S5 is the bestknown. Just as, in the sentential case, each world in
an interpretation is associated with a valuation of sentence letters as in
non-modal sentential logic, so in quantified modal logic, each world is
associated with a valuation of the sort filiar in non-modal first-order logic.
More specifically, in quantified S5, each world w is assigned a domain Dw – the
things that exist at w – such that at least one Dw is non-empty, and each
atomic n-place predicate of the language is assigned an extension Extw of
n-tuples of objects that satisfy the predicate at w. So even restricting
ourselves to just the one first-order extension of a sentential system, S5,
various degrees of freedom are already evident. We discuss the following: (a)
variability of domains, (b) interpretation of quantifiers, and (c) predication.
(a) Should all worlds have the se domain or may the domains of different worlds
be different? The latter appears to be the more natural choice; e.g., if
neither of of Dw* and Du are subsets of the other, this represents the
intuitive idea that some things that exist might not have, and that there could
have been things that do not actually exist (though formulating this latter
claim requires adding an operator for ‘actually’ to the language). So we should
distinguish two versions of S5, one with constant domains, S5C, and the other
with variable domains, S5V. (b) Should the truth of (Dn)f at a world w require
that f is true at w of some object in Dw or merely of some object in D (D is
the domain of all possible objects, 4weWDw)? The former treatment is called the
actualist reading of the quantifiers, the latter, the possibilist reading. In
S5C there is no real choice, since for any w, D % Dw, but the issue is live in
S5V. (c) Should we require that for any n-place atomic predicate F, an n-tuple
of objects satisfies F at w only if every member of the n-tuple belongs to Dw,
i.e., should we require that atomic predicates be existence-entailing? If we
abbreviate (Dy) (y % x) by Ex (for ‘x exists’), then in S5C, A(Ex)AEx is
logically valid on the actualist reading of E (%-D-) and on the possibilist. On
the former, the formula says that at each world, anything that exists at that
world exists at every world, which is true; while on the latter, using the
definition of ‘Ex’, it says that at each world, anything that exists at some
world or other is such that at every world, it exists at some world or other,
which is also true; indeed, the formula stays valid in S5C with possibilist
quantifiers even if we make E a primitive logical constant, stipulated to be
true at every w of modal logic modal logic 576 576 exactly the things that exist at w. But
in S5V with actualist quantifiers, A(Ex)AEx is invalid, as is (Ex)AEx –
consider an interpretation where for some u, Du is a proper subset of Dw*.
However, in S5V with possibilist quantifiers, the status of the formula, if ‘Ex’
is defined, depends on whether identity is existence-entailing. If it is
existenceentailing, then A(Ex)AEx is invalid, since an object in D satisfies
(Dy)(y % x) at w only if that object exists at w, while if identity is not
existence-entailing, the formula is valid. The interaction of the various
options is also evident in the evaluation of two well-known schemata: the
Barcan formula, B (Dx)fx P (Dx) B fx; and its converse, (Dx) B fx P B (Dx)fx.
In S5C with ‘Ex’ either defined or primitive, both schemata are valid, but in
S5V with actualist quantifiers, they both fail. For the latter case, if we
substitute -E for f in the converse Barcan formula we get a conditional whose
antecedent holds at w* if there is u with Du a proper subset of Dw*, but whose
consequent is logically false. The Barcan formula fails when there is a world u
with Du not a subset of Dw*, and the condition f is true of some non-actual
object at u and not of any actual object there. For then B (Dx)f holds at w*
while (Dx) B fx fails there. However, if we require atomic predicates to be
existence-entailing, then instances of the converse Barcan formula with f
atomic are valid. In S5V with possibilist quantifiers, all instances of both
schemata are valid, since the prefixes (Dx) B and B (Dx) correspond to (Dx)
(Dw) and (Dw) (Dx), which are equivalent (with actualist quantifiers, the
prefixes correspond to (Dx 1 Dw*), and (Dw) (Dx 1 Dw) which are non-equivalent
if Dw and Dw* need not be the se set). Finally in S5V with actualist
quantifiers, the standard quantifier introduction and elimination rules must be
adjusted. Suppose c is a ne for an object that does not actually exist; then -
Ec is true but (Dx) - Ex is false. The quantifier rules must be those of free
logic: we require Ec & fc before we infer (Dv)fv and Ec P fc, as well as
the usual EI restrictions, before we infer (Ev)fv.
mode (from Latin modus,
‘way’, ‘fashion’), a term used in many senses in philosophy. In Aristotelian
logic, it refers either to the arrangement of universal, particular,
affirmative, or negative propositions within a syllogism, only certain of which
are valid (this is often translated as ‘mood’ in English), or to the property a
proposition has by virtue of which it is necessary or contingent, possible or
impossible. In Scholastic metaphysics, it was often used in a not altogether
technical sense to mean that which characterizes a thing and distinguishes it
from others. Micraelius (Lexicon philosophicum, 1653) writes that “a mode does
not compose a thing, but distinguishes it and makes it determinate.” It was
also used in the context of the modal distinction in the theory of distinctions
to designate the distinction that holds between a substance and its modes or
between two modes of a single substance. The term ‘mode’ also appears in the
technical vocabulary of medieval speculative grmar in connection with the
notions of modes of signifying (modi significandi), modes of understanding
(modi intelligendi), and modes of being (modi essendi). The term ‘mode’ bece
especially important in the seventeenth century, when Descartes, Spinoza, and
Locke each took it up, giving it three somewhat different special meanings
within their respective systems. Descartes makes ‘mode’ a central notion in his
metaphysics in his Principia philosophiae. For Descartes, each substance is
characterized by a principal attribute, thought for mind and extension for
body. Modes, then, are particular ways of being extended or thinking, i.e.,
particular sizes, shapes, etc., or particular thoughts, properties (in the
broad sense) that individual things (substances) have. In this way, ‘mode’
occupies the role in Descartes’s philosophy that ‘accident’ does in
Aristotelian philosophy. But for Descartes, each mode must be connected with
the principal attribute of a substance, a way of being extended or a way of
thinking, whereas for the Aristotelian, accidents may or may not be connected
with the essence of the substance in which they inhere. Like Descartes, Spinoza
recognizes three basic metaphysical terms, ‘substance,’ ‘attribute’, and
‘mode’. Recalling Descartes, he defines ‘mode’ as “the affections of a
substance, or that which is in another, and which is also conceived through
another” (Ethics I). But for Spinoza, there is only one substance, which has all
possible attributes. This makes it somewhat difficult to determine exactly what
Spinoza means by ‘modes’, whether they are to be construed as being in some
sense “properties” of God, the one infinite modal logic of progrs mode 577 577 substance, or whether they are to be
construed more broadly as simply individual things that depend for their
existence on God, just as Cartesian modes depend on Cartesian substance.
Spinoza also introduces somewhat obscure distinctions between infinite and
finite modes, and between immediate and mediate infinite modes. Locke uses
‘mode’ in a way that evidently derives from Descartes’s usage, but that also
differs from it. For Locke, modes are “such complex Ideas, which however
compounded, contain not in them the supposition of subsisting by themselves,
but are considered as Dependences on, or Affections of Substances” (Essay II).
Modes are thus ideas that represent to us the complex properties of things,
ideas derived from what Locke calls the simple ideas that come to us from
experience. Locke distinguishes between simple modes like number, space, and
infinity, which are supposed to be constructed by compounding the se idea many
times, and mixed modes like obligation or theft, which are supposed to be
compounded of many simple ideas of different sorts.
model theory, a branch of
mathematical logic that deals with the connection between a language and its
interpretations or structures. Basic to it is the characterization of the
conditions under which a sentence is true in structure. It is confusing that
the term ‘model’ itself is used slightly differently: a model for a sentence is
a structure for the language of the sentence in which it is true. Model theory
was originally developed for explicitly constructed, formal languages, with the
purpose of studying foundational questions of mathematics, but was later
applied to the semantical analysis of empirical theories, a development
initiated by the Dutch philosopher Evert Beth, and of natural languages, as in
Montague grmar. More recently, in situation theory, we find a theory of
semantics in which not the concept of truth in a structure, but that of
information carried by a statement about a situation, is central. The term
‘model theory’ ce into use in the 1930s, with the work on first-order model
theory by Tarski, but some of the most central results of the field date from
before that time. The history of the field is complicated by the fact that in
the 1910s and 1920s, when the first model-theoretic findings were obtained, the
separation between first-order logic and its extensions was not yet completed.
Thus, in 1915, there appeared an article by Leopold Löwenheim, containing the
first version of what is now called the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem. Löwenheim
proved that every satisfiable sentence has a countable model, but he did not
yet work in firstorder logic as we now understand it. One of the first who did
so was the Norwegian logician Thoralf Skolem, who showed in 1920 that a set of
first-order sentences that has a model, has a countable model, one form of the
LöwenheimSkolem theorem. Skolem argued that logic was first-order logic and
that first-order logic was the proper basis for metathematical investigations,
fully accepting the relativity of set-theoretic notions in first-order logic.
Within philosophy this thesis is still dominant, but in the end it has not
prevailed in mathematical logic. In 1930 Kurt Gödel solved an open problem of
Hilbert-Ackermann and proved a completeness theorem for first-order logic. This
immediately led to another important model-theoretic result, the compactness
theorem: if every finite subset of a set of sentences has a model then the set
has a model. A good source for information about the model theory of
first-order logic, or classical model theory, is still Model Theory by C. C.
Chang and H. J. Keisler (1973). When the separation between first-order logic
and stronger logics had been completed and the model theory of first-order
logic had become a mature field, logicians undertook in the late 1950s the
study of extended model theory, the model theory of extensions of first-order
logic: first of cardinality quantifiers, later of infinitary languages and of
fragments of second-order logic. With so many exples of logics around – where
sometimes classical theorems did generalize, sometimes not – Per Lindström
showed in 1969 what sets first-order logic apart from its extensions: it is the
strongest logic that is both compact and satisfies the LöwenheimSkolem theorem.
This work has been the beginning of a study of the relations between various
properties logics may possess, the so-called abstract model.
modularity, the
commitment to functionally independent and specialized cognitive systems in
psychological organization, or, more generally, in the organization of any
complex system. Modularity entails that behavior is the product of components
with subordinate functions, that these functions are realized in discrete
physical systems, and that the subsystems are minimally interactive. Modular
organization varies from simple decomposability to what Herbert Simon calls
near decomposability. In the former, component systems are independent,
operating according to intrinsically determined principles; system behavior is
an additive or aggregative function of these independent contributions. In the
latter, the short-run behavior of components is independent of the behavior of
other components; the system behavior is a relatively simple function of
component contributions. In the early nineteenth century, Franz Joseph Gall
(1758–1828) defended a modular organization for the mind/brain, holding that
the cerebral hemispheres consist of a variety of organs, or centers, each
subserving specific intellectual and moral functions. This picture of the brain
as a collection of relatively independent organs contrasts sharply with the
traditional view that intellectual activity involves the exercise of a general
faculty in a variety of domains, a view that was common to Descartes and Hume
as well as Gall’s major opponents such as Pierre Flourens (1794–1867). By the
middle of the nineteenth century, the French physicians Jean-Baptiste Bouillaud
(1796–1881) and Pierre-Paul Broca (1824–80) defended the view that language is
controlled by localized structures in the left hemisphere and is relatively
independent of other cognitive activities. It was later discovered by Karl
Wernicke (1848–1905) that there are at least two centers for the control of
language, one more posterior and one more anterior. On these views, there are
discrete physical structures responsible for language, which are largely
independent of one another and of structures responsible for other
psychological functions. This is therefore a modular organization. This view of
the neurophysiological organization of language continues to have advocates
into the late twentieth century, though the precise characterization of the
functions these two centers serve is controversial. Many more recent views have
tended to limit modularity to more peripheral functions such as vision,
hearing, and motor control and speech, but have excluded so-called higher
cognitive processes.
modus ponens, in full,
modus ponendo ponens (Latin, ‘proposing method’), (1) the argument form ‘If A
then B; A; therefore, B’, and arguments of this form (compare fallacy of
affirming the consequent); (2) the rule of inference that permits one to infer
the consequent of a conditional from that conditional and its antecedent. This
is also known as the rule of /-elimination or rule of /- detachment. COUNTERFACTUALS, FORMAL FALLACY. G.F.S. modus
tollendo ponens.SYLLOGISM. modus tollens, in full, modus tollendo tollens
(Latin, ‘removing method’), (1) the argument form ‘If A then B; not-B;
therefore, not-A’, and arguments of this form (compare fallacy of denying the
antecedent); (2) the rule of inference that permits one to infer the negation
of the antecedent of a conditional from that conditional and the negation of
its consequent.
Mohism, a school of
classical Chinese thought founded by Mo Tzu (fl. 479–438 B.C.). Mo Tzu was the
first major philosopher to challenge Confucius. Whereas Confucius believed a
moral life was an end in itself, Mo Tzu advocated a form of utilitarianism
wherein the test of moral rightness (yi) was the ount of benefit (li) to the
gods, state, and people. Accordingly, Mo Tzu condemned war as harmful,
criticized Confucians for their elaborate funerals and wasteful indulgence in
music, and promoted a hierarchical meritocracy dominated by a powerful ruler as
the most efficient way to unify the conflicting moral views and interests of
the people, and thereby achieve social order. Mo Tzu also attacked fatalism,
and unlike the agnostic Confucius, firmly believed in spirits and an
anthropomorphic Heaven (t’ien) that rewarded those who benefited others and
punished those who did not. He is most fous for his doctrine of chien ai or
impartial concern (often translated as universal love). Whereas Confucius
espoused a relational morality in which one’s obligations modernism Mohism 579 579 varied depending on the status of the
parties and the degree of closeness, Mo Tzu insisted that each person be
treated equally as an object of moral concern. During the Warring States period
(403–221 B.C.), the Mohists split into three factions. The Later Mohist Canons,
most of which were written as late as the third century B.C., are characterized
by analytical reasoning and logical sophistication. Later Mohists sought to
provide a rational rather than a religious basis for Mo Tzu’s utilitarianism
based upon logical (and causal) necessity (pi). Treating a wide variety of
subjects from politics to optics to economics, the Canons are organized around
four topics: discourse, or knowledge of the relation between nes and objects;
ethics, or knowledge of how to act; sciences, or knowledge of objects; and
argumentation, or knowledge of nes. As Confucianism emerged to become the state
ideology, the Mohists disappeared sometime in the early Han dynasty (206
B.C.–A.D. 220), having been in important measure co-opted by the leading
interpreter of Confucianism of the period, Hsün Tzu (c.298–238 B.C.). CONFUCIANISM, LI3, MO TZU, YI. R.P.P. &
R.T.A. Mohist School.MOHISM, MO TZU. moksha.MAYA. Molina, Luis de (1535–1600),
Spanish Jesuit theologian and philosopher. He studied and taught at Coimbra and
Évora and also taught in Lisbon and Madrid. His most important works are the
Concordia liberi arbitrii cum gratiae donis(“Free Will and Grace,” 1588),
Commentaria in prim divi Thomae partem (“Commentary on the First Part of
Thomas’s Summa,” 1592), and De justitia et jure (“On Justice and Law,”
1592–1613). Molina is best known for his doctrine of middle knowledge (scientia
media). Its aim was to preserve free will while maintaining the Christian
doctrine of the efficacy of divine grace. It was opposed by Thomists such as
Bañez, who maintained that God exercises physical predetermination over
secondary causes of human action and, thus, that grace is intrinsically
efficacious and independent of human will and merits. For Molina, although God
has foreknowledge of what human beings will choose to do, neither that
knowledge nor God’s grace determine human will; the cooperation (concursus) of
divine grace with human will does not determine the will to a particular
action. This is made possible by God’s middle knowledge, which is a knowledge
in between the knowledge God has of what existed, exists, and will exist, and
the knowledge God has of what has not existed, does not exist, and will not
exist. Middle knowledge is God’s knowledge of conditional future contingent
events, nely, of what persons would do under any possible set of circumstances.
Thanks to this knowledge, God can arrange for certain human acts to occur by
prearranging the circumstances surrounding the choice without determining the human
will. Thus, God’s grace is concurrent with the act of the will and does not
predetermine it, rendering the Thomistic distinction between sufficient and
efficacious grace superfluous. AQUINAS,
FREE WILL PROBLEM, FUTURE CONTINGENTS, MIDDLE KNOWLEDGE. J.J.E.G. Molyneux
question, also called Molyneux’s problem, the question that, in correspondence
with Locke, Willi Molyneux (or Molineux, 1656– 98), a Dublin lawyer and member
of the Irish Parlient, posed and Locke inserted in the second edition of his
Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1694; book 2, chap. 9, section 8):
Suppose a Man born blind, and now adult, and taught by his touch to distinguish
a Cube, and a Sphere of the se metal, and nighly of the se bigness, so as to
tell, when he felt one and t’other, which is the Cube, which the Sphere.
Suppose then the Cube and Sphere placed on a Table, and the Blind Man to be
made to see. Quære, Whether by his sight, before he touch’d them, he could now
distinguish, and tell, which is the Globe, which the Cube. Although it is
tempting to regard Molyneux’s question as straightforwardly empirical, attempts
to gauge the abilities of newly sighted adults have yielded disappointing and
biguous results. More interesting, perhaps, is the way in which different
theories of perception answer the question. Thus, according to Locke, sensory
modalities constitute discrete perceptual channels, the contents of which
perceivers must learn to correlate. Such a theory answers the question in the
negative (as did Molyneux himself). Other theories encourage different
responses.
NON-MONOTONIC LOGIC.
Montague grmar.GRMAR. Montaigne, Michel de (1533–92), French essayist and
philosopher who set forth the Renaissance version of Greek skepticism. Born and
raised in Bordeaux, he bece its mayor, and was an adviser to leaders of the
Reformation and Counter-Reformation. In 1568 he translated the work of the
Spanish rationalist theologian Raimund Sebond on natural theology. Shortly
thereafter he began writing essais, attempts, as the author said, to paint
himself. These, the first in this genre, are rbling, curious discussions of
various topics, suggesting tolerance and an undogmatic Stoic morality. The
longest essai, the “Apology for Raimund Sebond,” “defends” Sebond’s rationalism
by arguing that since no adequate reasons or evidence could be given to support
any point of view in theology, philosophy, or science, one should not ble
Sebond for his views. Montaigne then presents and develops the skeptical
arguments found in Sextus Empiricus and Cicero. Montaigne related skeptical
points to thencurrent findings and problems. Data of explorers, he argues,
reinforce the cultural and ethical relativism of the ancient Skeptics.
Disagreements between Scholastics, Platonists, and Renaissance naturalists on
almost everything cast doubt on whether any theory is correct. Scientists like
Copernicus and Paracelsus contradict previous scientists, and will probably be
contradicted by future ones. Montaigne then offers the more theoretical
objections of the Skeptics, about the unreliability of sense experience and
reasoning and our inability to find an unquestionable criterion of true
knowledge. Trying to know reality is like trying to clutch water. What should
we then do? Montaigne advocates suspending judgment on all theories that go
beyond experience, accepting experience undogmatically, living according to the
dictates of nature, and following the rules and customs of one’s society.
Therefore one should remain in the religion in which one was born, and accept only
those principles that God chooses to reveal to us. Montaigne’s skepticism
greatly influenced European thinkers in undermining confidence in previous
theories and forcing them to seek new ways of grounding knowledge. His
acceptance of religion on custom and faith provided a way of living with total
skepticism. His presentation of skepticism in a modern language shaped the
vocabulary and the problems of philosophy in modern times.
SKEPTICISM, SKEPTICS. R.H.P. Montanism, a
charismatic, schismatic movement in early Christianity, originating in Phrygia
in the late second century. It rebuked the mainstre church for laxity and
apathy, and taught moral purity, new, i.e. postbiblical, revelation, and the
imminent end of the world. Traditional accounts, deriving from critics of the
movement, contain exaggerations and probably some fabrications. Montanus
himself, abetted by the prophetesses Maximilla and Prisca, announced in
ecstatic speech a new, final age of prophecy. This fulfilled the biblical
promises that in the last days the Holy Spirit would be poured out universally
(Joel 2: 28ff.; Acts 2: 16ff.) and would teach “the whole truth” (Jon. 14:26;
16:13). It also empowered the Montanists to enjoin more rigorous discipline
than that required by Jesus. The sect denied that forgiveness through baptism
covered serious subsequent sin; forbade remarriage for widows and widowers;
practiced fasting; and condemned believers who evaded persecution. Some later
followers may have identified Montanus with the Holy Spirit itself, though he
claimed only to be the Spirit’s mouthpiece. The “new prophecy” flourished for a
generation, especially in North Africa, gaining a fous convert in Tertullian.
But the church’s bishops repudiated the movement’s criticisms and innovations,
and turned more resolutely against postapostolic revelation, apocalyptic
expectation, and ascetic extremes. A.E.L. Montanus.MONTANISM. Monte Carlo
fallacy.GBLER’s FALLACY. Montesquieu, Baron de La Brède et de, title of
Charles-Louis de Secondat (1689–1755), French political philosopher, the
political philosophe of the Enlightenment. He was born at La Brède, educated at
the Oratorian Collège de Juilly (1700–05), and received law degrees from the
University of Bordeaux (1708). From his uncle he inherited the barony of
Montesquieu (1716) and the office of Président à Mortier at the Parlient of
Guyenne at Bordeaux. Fe, national monism Montesquieu 581 581 and international, ce suddenly (1721)
with the Lettres persanes (“The Persian Letters”), published in Holland and
France, a landmark of the Enlightenment. His Réflexions sur la monarchie
universelle en Europe, written and printed (1734) to remind the authorities of
his qualifications and availability, delivered the wrong message at the wrong
time (anti-militarism, pacifism, free trade, while France supported Poland’s
King Stanislas, dethroned by Russia and Austria). Montesquieu withdrew the
Réflexions before publication and substituted the Considerations on the Romans:
the se thesis is expounded here, but in the exclusively classical context of
ancient history. The stratagem succeeded: the sterd edition was freely
imported; the Paris edition appeared with a royal privilège (1734). A few
months after the appearance of the Considerations, he undertook L’Esprit des lois,
the outline of a modern political science, conceived as the foundation of an
effective governmental policy. His optimism was shaken by the disasters of the
War of Austrian Succession (1740–48); the Esprit des lois underwent hurried
changes that upset its original plan. During the very printing process, the
author was discovering the true essence of his philosophie pratique: it would
never culminate in a final, invariable progr, but in an orientation,
continuously, intelligently adapting to the unpredictable circumstances of
historical time in the light of permanent values. According to L’Esprit des
lois, governments are either republics, monarchies, or despotisms. The
principles, or motivational forces, of these types of government are,
respectively, political virtue, honor, and fear. The type of government a
people has depends on its character, history, and geographical situation. Only
a constitutional government that separates its executive, legislative, and
judicial powers preserves political liberty, taken as the power to do what one
ought to will. A constitutional monarchy with separation of powers is the best
form of government. Montesquieu influenced the authors of the U.S. Constitution
and the political philosophers Burke and Rousseau.
Moore, G(eorge) E(dward)
(1873–1958), English philosopher who spearheaded the attack on idealism and was
a major supporter of realism in all its forms: metaphysical, epistemological,
and axiological. He was born in Upper Norwood, a suburb of London; did his
undergraduate work at Cbridge University; spent 1898–1904 as a fellow of
Trinity College; returned to Cbridge in 1911 as a lecturer; and was granted a
professorship there in 1925. He also served as editor of Mind. The bulk of his
work falls into four categories: metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, and
philosophical methodology. Metaphysics. In this area, Moore is mainly known for
his attempted refutation of idealism and his defense thereby of realism. In his
“The Refutation of Idealism” (1903), he argued that there is a crucial premise
that is essential to all possible arguments for the idealistic conclusion that
“All reality is mental (spiritual).” This premise is: “To be is to be
perceived” (in the broad sense of ‘perceive’). Moore argued that, under every
possible interpretation of it, that premise is either a tautology or false;
hence no significant conclusion can ever be inferred from it. His positive
defense of realism had several prongs. One was to show that there are certain
claims held by non-realist philosophers, both idealist ones and skeptical ones.
Moore argued, in “A Defense of Common Sense” (1925), that these claims are
either factually false or self-contradictory, or that in some cases there is no
good reason to believe them. ong the claims that Moore attacked are these:
“Propositions about (purported) material facts are false”; “No one has ever
known any such propositions to be true”; “Every (purported) physical fact is
logically dependent on some mental fact”; and “Every physical fact is causally
dependent on some mental fact.” Another major prong of Moore’s defense of
realism was to argue for the existence of an external world and later to give a
“Proof of an External World” (1933). Epistemology. Most of Moore’s work in this
area dealt with the various kinds of knowledge we have, why they must be
distinguished, and the problem of perception and our knowledge of an external
world. Because he had already argued for the existence of an external world in
his metaphysics, he here focused on how we know it. In many papers and chapters
(e.g., “The Nature and Reality of Objects of Perception,” 1906) he exined and
at times supported three main positions: naive or direct realism,
representative or indirect realism, and phenomenalism. Although he seemed to
favor direct realism at first, in the majority of his papers he found
representative realism to be the most supportable position despite its
problems. It should also be noted that, in connection with his leanings mood
toward representative realism, Moore maintained the existence of sense-data and
argued at length for an account of just how they are related to physical
objects. That there are sense-data Moore never doubted. The question was, What
is their (ontological) status? With regard to the various kinds of knowledge
(or ways of knowing), Moore made a distinction between dispositional (or
non-actualized) and actualized knowledge. Within the latter Moore made
distinctions between direct apprehension (often known as knowledge by
acquaintance), indirect apprehension, and knowledge proper (or propositional
knowledge). He devoted much of his work to finding the conditions for knowledge
proper. Ethics. In his major work in ethics, Principia Ethica (1903), Moore
maintained that the central problem of ethics is, What is good? – meaning by
this, not what things are good, but how ‘good’ is to be defined. He argued that
there can be only one answer, one that may seem disappointing, nely: good is
good, or, alternatively, ‘good’ is indefinable. Thus ‘good’ denotes a “unique, simple
object of thought” that is indefinable and unanalyzable. His first argument on
behalf of that claim consisted in showing that to identify good with some other
object (i.e., to define ‘good’) is to commit the naturalistic fallacy. To
commit this fallacy is to reduce ethical propositions to either psychological
propositions or reportive definitions as to how people use words. In other
words, what was meant to be an ethical proposition, that X is good, becomes a
factual proposition about people’s desires or their usage of words. Moore’s
second argument ran like this: Suppose ‘good’ were definable. Then the result
would be even worse than that of reducing ethical propositions to non-ethical
propositions – ethical propositions would be tautologies! For exple, suppose
you defined ‘good’ as ‘pleasure’. Then suppose you maintained that pleasure is
good. All you would be asserting is that pleasure is pleasure, a tautology. To
avoid this conclusion ‘good’ must mean something other than ‘pleasure’. Why is
this the naturalistic fallacy? Because good is a non-natural property. But even
if it were a natural one, there would still be a fallacy. Hence some have
proposed calling it the definist fallacy – the fallacy of attempting to define
‘good’ by any means. This argument is often known as the open question argument
because whatever purported definition of ‘good’ anyone offers, it would always
be an open question whether whatever satisfies the definition really is good.
In the last part of Principia Ethica Moore turned to a discussion of what sorts
of things are the greatest goods with which we are acquainted. He argued for
the view that they are personal affection and aesthetic enjoyments.
Philosophical methodology. Moore’s methodology in philosophy had many
components, but two stand out: his appeal to and defense of common sense and
his utilization of various methods of (philosophical/conceptual) analysis. “A
Defense of Common Sense” argued for his claim that the commonsense view of the
world is wholly true, and for the claim that any view which opposed that view
is either factually false or self-contradictory. Throughout his writings Moore
distinguished several kinds of analysis and made use of them extensively in
dealing with philosophical problems. All of these may be found in the works
cited above and other essays gathered into Moore’s Philosophical Studies(1922)
and Philosophical Papers (1959). These have been referred to as refutational
analysis, with two subforms, showing contradictions and “translation into the concrete”;
distinctional analysis; decompositional analysis (either definitional or
divisional); and reductional analysis. Moore was greatly revered as a teacher.
Many of his students and colleagues have paid high tribute to him in very warm
and grateful terms.
ANALYSIS, DEFINITION,
EPISTEMOLOGY, ETHICS, MALCOLM, NATURALISM. E.D.K.
Moore’s paradox, as first
discussed by G. E. Moore, the perplexity involving assertion of what is
expressed by conjunctions such as ‘It’s raining, but I believe it isn’t’ and
‘It’s raining, but I don’t believe it is’. The oddity of such presenttense
first-person uses of ‘to believe’ seems peculiar to those conjunctions just
because it is assumed both that, when asserting – roughly, representing as true
– a conjunction, one also asserts its conjuncts, and that, as a rule, the
assertor believes the asserted proposition. Thus, no perplexity arises from
assertions of, for instance, ‘It’s raining today, but I (falsely) believed it
wasn’t until I ce out to the porch’ and ‘If it’s raining but I believe it
isn’t, I have been misled by the weather report’. However, there are reasons to
think that, if we rely only on these assumptions and exples, our
characterization of the problem is unduly narrow. First, assertion seems
relevant only because we are interested in what the assertor believes.
Secondly, those conjunctions are disturbing only insofar as they show that
Moore’s paradox Moore’s paradox 583
583 some of the assertor’s beliefs, though contingent, can only be
irrationally held. Thirdly, autobiographical reports that may justifiably be
used to charge the reporter with irrationality need be neither about his belief
system, nor conjunctive, nor true (e.g., ‘I don’t exist’, ‘I have no beliefs’),
nor false (e.g., ‘It’s raining, but I have no evidence that it is’). So,
Moore’s paradox is best seen as the problem posed by contingent propositions
that cannot be justifiably believed. Arguably, in forming a belief of those
propositions, the believer acquires non-overridable evidence against believing
them. A successful analysis of the problem along these lines may have important
epistemological consequences.
CONTINGENT, EPISTEMOLOGY,
EVIDENCE, JUSTIFICATION, MOORE, PARADOX, PROPOSITION, RATIONALITY, REASONS FOR
BELIEF. C.d.A. moral argument for God’s existence.PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. moral
certainty.
moral dilemma. (1) Any
problem where morality is relevant. This broad use includes not only conflicts
ong moral reasons but also conflicts between moral reasons and reasons of law,
religion, or self-interest. In this sense, Abrah is in a moral dilemma when God
commands him to sacrifice his son, even if he has no moral reason to obey.
Similarly, I in a moral dilemma if I
cannot help a friend in trouble without forgoing a lucrative but morally
neutral business opportunity. ’Moral dilemma’ also often refers to (2) any
topic area where it is not known what, if anything, is morally good or right.
For exple, when one asks whether abortion is immoral in any way, one could call
the topic “the moral dilemma of abortion.” This epistemic use does not imply
that anything really is immoral at all. Recently, moral philosophers have
discussed a much narrower set of situations as “moral dilemmas.” They usually
define ‘moral dilemma’ as (3) a situation where an agent morally ought to do
each of two acts but cannot do both. The bestknown exple is Sartre’s student
who morally ought to care for his mother in Paris but at the se time morally
ought to go to England to join the Free French and fight the Nazis. However,
‘ought’ covers ideal actions that are not morally required, such as when
someone ought to give to a certain charity but is not required to do so. Since
most common exples of moral dilemmas include moral obligations or duties, or
other requirements, it is more accurate to define ‘moral dilemma’ more narrowly
as (4) a situation where an agent has a moral requirement to do each of two
acts but cannot do both. Some philosophers also refuse to call a situation a
moral dilemma when one of the conflicting requirements is clearly overridden,
such as when I must break a trivial promise in order to save a life. To exclude
such resolvable conflicts, ‘moral dilemma’ can be defined as (5) a situation
where an agent has a moral requirement to adopt each of two alternatives, and
neither requirement is overridden, but the agent cannot fulfill both. Another
common move is to define ‘moral dilemma’ as (6) a situation where every
alternative is morally wrong. This is equivalent to (4) or (5), respectively,
if an act is morally wrong whenever it violates any moral requirement or any
non-overridden moral requirement. However, we usually do not call an act wrong
unless it violates an overriding moral requirement, and then (6) rules out
moral dilemmas by definition, since overriding moral requirements clearly
cannot conflict. Although (5) thus seems preferable, some would object that (5)
includes trivial requirements and conflicts, such as conflicts between trivial
promises. To include only tragic situations, we could define ‘moral dilemma’ as
(7) a situation where an agent has a strong moral obligation or requirement to
adopt each of two alternatives, and neither is overridden, but the agent cannot
adopt both alternatives. This definition is strong enough to raise the
important controversies about moral dilemmas without being so strong as to rule
out their possibility by definition.
moral epistemology, the
discipline, at the intersection of ethics and epistemology, that studies the
epistemic status and relations of moral judgments and principles. It has
developed out of an interest, common to both ethics and epistemology, in
questions of justification and justifiability – in epistemology, of statements
or beliefs, and in ethics, of actions as well as judgments of actions and also
general principles of judgment. Its most prominent questions include the
following. Can normative claims be true or false? If so, how can they be known
to be true or false? If not, what status do they have, and are they capable of
justification? If they are capable of moral argument for God’s existence moral
epistemology 584 584 justification,
how can they be justified? Does the justification of normative claims differ
with respect to particular claims and with respect to general principles? In
epistemology recent years have seen a tendency to accept as valid an account of
knowledge as entailing justified true belief, a conception that requires an
account not just of truth but also of justification and of justified belief.
Thus, under what conditions is someone justified, epistemically, in believing
something? Justification, of actions, of judgments, and of principles, has long
been a central element in ethics. It is only recently that justification in
ethics ce to be thought of as an epistemological problem, hence ‘moral
epistemology’, as an expression, is a fairly recent coinage, although its
problems have a long lineage. One long-standing linkage is provided by the
challenge of skepticism. Skepticism in ethics can be about the existence of any
genuine distinction between right and wrong, or it can focus on the possibility
of attaining any knowledge of right and wrong, good or bad. Is there a right
answer? is a question in the metaphysics of ethics. Can we know what the right
answer is, and if so how? is one of moral epistemology. Problems of perception
and observation and ones about observation statements or sense-data play an
important role in epistemology. There is not any obvious parallel in moral
epistemology, unless it is the role of prereflective moral judgments, or
commonsense moral judgments – moral judgments unguided by any overt moral
theory – which can be taken to provide the data of moral theory, and which need
to be explained, systematized, coordinated, or revised to attain an appropriate
relation between theory and data. This would be analogous to taking the data of
epistemology to be provided, not by sense-data or observations but by judgments
of perception or observation statements. Once this step is taken the parallel
is very close. One source of moral skepticism is the apparent lack of any
observational counterpart for moral predicates, which generates the question
how moral judgments can be true if there is nothing for them to correspond to.
Another source of moral skepticism is apparently constant disagreement and
uncertainty, which would appear to be explained by the skeptical hypothesis
denying the reality of moral distinctions. Noncognitivism in ethics maintains
that moral judgments are not objects of knowledge, that they make no statements
capable of truth or falsity, but are or are akin to expressions of attitudes.
Some other major differences ong ethical theories are largely epistemological
in character. Intuitionism maintains that basic moral propositions are knowable
by intuition. Empiricism in ethics maintains that moral propositions can be
established by empirical means or are complex forms of empirical statements.
Ethical rationalism maintains that the fundental principle(s) of morality can
be established a priori as holding of necessity. This is exemplified by Kant’s
moral philosophy, in which the categorical imperative is regarded as synthetic
a priori; more recently by what Alan Gewirth (b.1912) calls the “principle of
generic consistency,” which he claims it is selfcontradictory to deny. Ethical
empiricism is exemplified by classical utilitarianism, such as that of Benth,
which aspires to develop ethics as an empirical science. If the consequences of
actions can be scientifically predicted and their utilities calculated, then
ethics can be a science. Situationism is equivalent to concrete case
intuitionism in maintaining that we can know immediately what ought to be done
in specific cases, but most ethical theories maintain that what ought to be
done is, in J. S. Mill’s words, determined by “the application of a law to an
individual case.” Different theories differ on the epistemic status of these
laws and on the process of application. Deductivists, either empiricistic or
rationalistic, hold that the law is essentially unchanged in the application;
non-deductivists hold that the law is modified in the process of application.
(This distinction is explained in F. L. Will [1909–98], Beyond Deduction,
1988.) There is similar variation about what if anything is selfevident,
Sidgwick maintaining that only certain highly abstract principles are
self-evident, Ross that only general rules are, and Prichard that only concrete
judgments are, “by an act of moral thinking.” Other problems in moral
epistemology are provided by the fact–value distinction – and controversies
about whether there is any such distinction – and the is–ought question, the
question how a moral judgment can be derived from statements of fact alone.
Naturalists affirm the possibility, non-naturalists deny it. Prescriptivists
claim that moral judgments are prescriptions and cannot be deduced from
descriptive statements alone. This question ultimately leads to the question
how an ultimate principle can be justified. If it cannot be deduced from
statements of fact, that route is out; if it must be deduced from some other
moral principle, then the principle deduced cannot be ultimate and in any case
this process is either circular or leads to an infimoral epistemology moral
epistemology 585 585 nite regress. If
the ultimate principle is self-evident, then the problem may have an answer.
But if it is not it would appear to be arbitrary. The problem of the
justification of an ultimate principle continues to be a leading one in moral
epistemology. Recently there has been much interest in the status and existence
of “moral facts.” Are there any, what are they, and how are they established as
“facts”? This relates to questions about moral realism. Moral realism maintains
that moral predicates are real and can be known to be so; anti-realists deny
this. This denial links with the view that moral properties supervene on
natural ones, and the problem of supervenience is another recent link between
ethics and epistemology. Pragmatism in ethics maintains that a moral problem is
like any problem in that it is the occasion for inquiry and moral judgments are
to be regarded as hypotheses to be tested by how well they resolve the problem.
This ounts to an attempt to bypass the is–ought problem and all such
“dualisms.” So is constructivism, a development owing much to the work of
Rawls, which contrasts with moral realism. Constructivism maintains that moral
ideas are human constructs and the task is not epistemological or metaphysical
but practical and theoretical – that of attaining reflective equilibrium
between considered moral judgments and the principles that coordinate and
explain them. On this view there are no moral facts. Opponents maintain that
this only replaces a foundationalist view of ethics with a coherence
conception. The question whether questions of moral epistemology can in this
way be bypassed can be regarded as itself a question of moral epistemology. And
the question of the foundations of morality, and whether there are foundations,
can still be regarded as a question of moral epistemology, as distinct from a
question of the most convenient and efficient arrangement of our moral
ideas.
ETHICAL CONSTRUCTIVISM,
ETHICS, INTUITION, MORAL REALISM, REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM. M.G.S. moral
evil.PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. morality, an informal public system applying to
all rational persons, governing behavior that affects others, having the
lessening of evil or harm as its goal, and including what are commonly known as
the moral rules, moral ideals, and moral virtues. To say that it is a public
system means that all those to whom it applies must understand it and that it
must not be irrational for them to use it in deciding what to do and in judging
others to whom the system applies. Ges are the paradigm cases of public
systems; all ges have a point and the rules of a ge apply to all who play it.
All players know the point of the ge and its rules, and it is not irrational
for them to be guided by the point and rules and to judge the behavior of other
players by them. To say that morality is informal means that there is no
decision procedure or authority that can settle all its controversial
questions. Morality thus resembles a backyard ge of basketball more than a
professional ge. Although there is overwhelming agreement on most moral
matters, certain controversial questions must be settled in an ad hoc fashion
or not settled at all. For exple, when, if ever, abortion is acceptable is an
unresolvable moral matter, but each society and religion can adopt its own
position. That morality has no one in a position of authority is one of the
most important respects in which it differs from law and religion. Although
morality must include the commonly accepted moral rules such as those
prohibiting killing and deceiving, different societies can interpret these rules
somewhat differently. They can also differ in their views about the scope of
morality, i.e., about whether morality protects newborns, fetuses, or non-human
animals. Thus different societies can have somewhat different moralities,
although this difference has limits. Also within each society, a person may
have his own view about when it is justified to break one of the rules, e.g.,
about how much harm would have to be prevented in order to justify deceiving
someone. Thus one person’s morality may differ somewhat from another’s, but
both will agree on the overwhelming number of non-controversial cases. A moral
theory is an attempt to describe, explain, and if possible justify, morality.
Unfortunately, most moral theories attempt to generate some simplified moral
code, rather than to describe the complex moral system that is already in use.
Morality does not resolve all disputes. Morality does not require one always to
act so as to produce the best consequences or to act only in those ways that
one would will everyone to act. Rather morality includes both moral rules that
no one should transgress and moral ideals that all are encouraged to follow,
but much of what one does will not be governed by morality. moral evil morality
586 586
APPLIED ETHICS, ETHICS,
JUSTICE, MORALITY, UTILITARIANISM. B.Ge. morality, slave.NIETZSCHE. moral
patient.MORAL STATUS. moral point of view.ETHICS. moral psychology, (1) the
subfield of psychology that traces the development over time of moral reasoning
and opinions in the lives of individuals (this subdiscipline includes work of
Jean Piaget, Lawrence Kohlberg, and Carol Gilligan); (2) the part of philosophy
where philosophy of mind and ethics overlap, which concerns all the
psychological issues relevant to morality. There are many different
psychological matters relevant to ethics, and each may be relevant in more than
one way. Different ethical theories imply different sorts of connections. So
moral psychology includes work of many and diverse kinds. But several
traditional clusters of concern are evident. Some elements of moral psychology
consider the psychological matters relevant to metaethical issues, i.e., to
issues about the general nature of moral truth, judgment, and knowledge.
Different metaethical theories invoke mental phenomena in different ways:
noncognitivism maintains that sentences expressing moral judgments do not
function to report truths or falsehoods, but rather, e.g., to express certain
emotions or to prescribe certain actions. So some forms of noncognitivism imply
that an understanding of certain sorts of emotions, or of special activities
like prescribing that may involve particular psychological elements, is crucial
to a full understanding of how ethical sentences are meaningful. Certain forms
of cognitivism, the view that moral (declarative) sentences do express truths
or falsehoods, imply that moral facts consist of psychological facts, that for
instance moral judgments consist of expressions of positive psychological
attitudes of some particular kind toward the objects of those judgments. And an
understanding of psychological phenomena like sentiment is crucial according to
certain sorts of projectivism, which hold that the supposed moral properties of
things are mere misleading projections of our sentiments onto the objects of
those sentiments. Certain traditional moral sense theories and certain
traditional forms of intuitionism have held that special psychological
faculties are crucial for our epistemic access to moral truth. Particular views
in normative ethics, particular views about the moral status of acts, persons,
and other targets of normative evaluation, also often suggest that an
understanding of certain psychological matters is crucial to ethics. Actions,
intentions, and character are some of the targets of evaluation of normative
ethics, and their proper understanding involves many issues in philosophy of
mind. Also, many normative theorists have maintained that there is a close
connection between pleasure, happiness, or desiresatisfaction and a person’s
good, and these things are also a concern of philosophy of mind. In addition,
the rightness of actions is often held to be closely connected to the motives,
beliefs, and other psychological phenomena that lie behind those actions.
Various other traditional philosophical concerns link ethical and psychological
issues: the nature of the patterns in the long-term development in individuals
of moral opinions and reasoning, the appropriate form for moral education and
punishment, the connections between obligation and motivation, i.e., between
moral reasons and psychological causes, and the notion of free will and its
relation to moral responsibility and autonomy. Some work in philosophy of mind
also suggests that moral phenomena, or at least normative phenomena of some
kind, play a crucial role in illuminating or constituting psychological
phenomena of various kinds, but the traditional concern of moral psychology has
been with the articulation of the sort of philosophy of mind that can be useful
to ethics.
AKRASIA, ETHICS,
PRACTICAL REASONING, SELF-DECEPTION. J.R.M. moral rationalism, the view that
the substance of morality, usually in the form of general moral principles, can
be known a priori. The view is defended by Kant in Groundwork of the Metaphysic
of Morals, but it goes back at least to Plato. Both Plato and Kant thought that
a priori moral knowledge could have an impact on what we do quite independently
of any desire that we happen to have. This motivational view is also ordinarily
associated with moral rationalism. It comes in two quite different forms. The
first is that a priori moral knowledge consists in a sui generis mental state
that is both belief-like and desire-like. This seems to have been Plato’s view,
for he held that the belief that something is good is itself a disposition to
promote that thing. The second is that a priori moral knowledge consists in a
belief that is capable of rationally producing a distinct desire. morality,
slave moral rationalism 587 587
Rationalists who make the first claim have had trouble accommodating the
possibility of someone’s believing that something is good but, through weakness
of will, not mustering the desire to do it. Accordingly, they have been forced
to assimilate weakness of will to ignorance of the good. Rationalists who make
the second claim about reason’s action-producing capacity face no such problem.
For this reason, their view is often preferred. The best-known anti-rationalist
about morality is Hume. His Treatise of Human Nature denies both that
morality’s substance can be known by reason alone and that reason alone is
capable of producing action. AKRASIA,
ETHICS, HUME, KANT, MORAL SENSE THEORY, MOTIVATIONAL INTERNALISM, RATIONALISM.
M.Sm. moral realism, a metaethical view committed to the objectivity of ethics.
It has (1) metaphysical, (2) semantic, and (3) epistemological components. (1)
Its metaphysical component is the claim that there are moral facts and moral
properties whose existence and nature are independent of people’s beliefs and
attitudes about what is right or wrong. In this claim, moral realism contrasts
with an error theory and with other forms of nihilism that deny the existence
of moral facts and properties. It contrasts as well with various versions of
moral relativism and other forms of ethical constructivism that make moral
facts consist in facts about people’s moral beliefs and attitudes. (2) Its
semantic component is primarily cognitivist. Cognitivism holds that moral
judgments should be construed as assertions about the moral properties of
actions, persons, policies, and other objects of moral assessment, that moral
predicates purport to refer to properties of such objects, that moral judgments
(or the propositions that they express) can be true or false, and that cognizers
can have the cognitive attitude of belief toward the propositions that moral
judgments express. These cognitivist claims contrast with the noncognitive
claims of emotivism and prescriptivism, according to which the primary purpose
of moral judgments is to express the appraiser’s attitudes or commitments,
rather than to state facts or ascribe properties. Moral realism also holds that
truth for moral judgments is non-epistemic; in this way it contrasts with moral
relativism and other forms of ethical constructivism that make the truth of a
moral judgment epistemic. The metaphysical and semantic theses imply that there
are some true moral propositions. An error theory accepts the cognitivist
semantic claims but denies the realist metaphysical thesis. It holds that moral
judgments should be construed as containing referring expressions and having
truth-values, but insists that these referring expressions are empty, because
there are no moral facts, and that no moral claims are true. Also on this theory,
commonsense moral thought presupposes the existence of moral facts and
properties, but is systematically in error. In this way, the error theory
stands to moral realism much as atheism stands to theism in a world of theists.
(J. L. Mackie introduced and defended the error theory in his Ethics: Inventing
Right and Wrong, 1977.) (3) Finally, if moral realism is to avoid skepticism it
must claim that some moral beliefs are true, that there are methods for
justifying moral beliefs, and that moral knowledge is possible. While making
these metaphysical, semantic, and epistemological claims, moral realism is
compatible with a wide variety of other metaphysical, semantic, and
epistemological principles and so can take many different forms. The moral
realists in the early part of the twentieth century were generally
intuitionists. Intuitionism combined a commitment to moral realism with a
foundationalist moral epistemology according to which moral knowledge must rest
on self-evident moral truths and with the nonnaturalist claim that moral facts
and properties are sui generis and not reducible to any natural facts or
properties. Friends of noncognitivism found the metaphysical and
epistemological commitments of intuitionism extravagant and so rejected moral
realism. Later moral realists have generally sought to defend moral realism
without the metaphysical and epistemological trappings of intuitionism. One
such version of moral realism takes a naturalistic form. This form of ethical
naturalism claims that our moral beliefs are justified when they form part of
an explanatorily coherent system of beliefs with one another and with various
non-moral beliefs, and insists that moral properties are just natural
properties of the people, actions, and policies that instantiate them. Debate
between realists and anti-realists and within the realist cp centers on such
issues as the relation between moral judgment and action, the rational
authority of morality, moral epistemology and methodology, the relation between
moral and non-moral natural properties, the place of ethics in a naturalismoral
realism moral realism 588 588 tic
worldview, and the parity of ethics and the sciences. EMOTIVISM, ETHICAL CONSTRUCTIVISM, ETHICAL
OBJECTIVISM, ETHICS, NATURALISM. D.O.B. Moral Rearment Movement.BUCHMANISM.
moral sense theory, an ethical theory, developed by eighteenth-century British
philosophers – notably Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, and Hume – according to which
the pleasure or pain a person feels upon thinking about (or “observing”)
certain character traits is indicative of the virtue or vice, respectively, of
those features. It is a theory of “moral perception,” offered in response to
moral rationalism, the view that moral distinctions are derived by reason
alone, and combines Locke’s empiricist doctrine that all ideas begin in
experience with the belief, widely shared at the time, that feelings play a
central role in moral evaluation and motivation. On this theory, our emotional
responses to persons’ characters are often “perceptions” of their morality,
just as our experiences of an apple’s redness and sweetness are perceptions of
its color and taste. These ideas of morality are seen as products of an
“internal” sense, because they are produced in the “observer” only after she
forms a concept of the conduct or trait being observed (or contemplated) – as
when a person realizes that she is seeing someone intentionally harm another
and reacts with displeasure at what she sees. The moral sense is conceived as
being analogous to, or possibly an aspect of, our capacity to recognize varying
degrees of beauty in things, which modern writers call “the sense of beauty.”
Rejecting the popular view that morality is based on the will of God,
Shaftesbury maintains rather that morality depends on human nature, and he
introduces the notion of a sense of right and wrong, possessed uniquely by
human beings, who alone are capable of reflection. Hutcheson argues that to
approve of a character is to regard it as virtuous. For him, reason, which
discovers relations of inanimate objects to rational agents, is unable to
arouse our approval in the absence of a moral sense. Ultimately, we can explain
why, for exple, we approve of someone’s temperate character only by appealing
to our natural tendency to feel pleasure (sometimes identified with approval)
at the thought of characters that exhibit benevolence, the trait to which all
other virtues can be traced. This disposition to feel approval (and
disapproval) is what Hutcheson identifies as the moral sense. Hume emphasizes that
typical human beings make moral distinctions on the basis of their feelings
only when those sentiments are experienced from a disinterested or “general”
point of view. In other words, we turn our initial sentiments into moral
judgments by compensating for the fact that we feel more strongly about those
to whom we are emotionally close than those from whom we are more distant. On a
widely held interpretation of Hume, the moral sense provides not only
judgments, but also motives to act according to those judgments, since its
feelings may be motivating passions or arouse such passions. Roderick Firth’s
(1917–87) twentieth-century ideal observer theory, according to which moral
good is designated by the projected reactions of a hypothetically omniscient, disinterested
observer possessing other ideal traits, as well as Brandt’s contemporary moral
spectator theory, are direct descendants of the moral sense theory.
BUTLER, HUME, HUTCHESON,
SHAFTESBURY. E.S.R. moral skepticism, any metaethical view that raises
fundental doubts about morality as a whole. Different kinds of doubts lead to
different kinds of moral skepticism. The primary kinds of moral skepticism are
epistemological. Moral justification skepticism is the claim that nobody ever
has (any or adequate) justification for believing any substantive moral claim.
Moral knowledge skepticism is the claim that nobody ever knows that any
substantive moral claim is true. If knowledge implies justification, as is
often assumed, then moral justification skepticism implies moral knowledge
skepticism. But even if knowledge requires justification, it requires more, so
moral knowledge skepticism does not imply moral justification skepticism.
Another kind of skeptical view in metaethics rests on linguistic analysis. Some
emotivists, expressivists, and prescriptivists argue that moral claims (like
“Cheating is morally wrong”) resemble expressions of emotion or desire (like
“Boo, cheating”) or prescriptions for action (like “Don’t cheat”), which are
neither true nor false, so moral claims themselves are neither true nor false.
This linguistic moral skepticism, which is sometimes called noncognitivism,
implies moral knowledge skepticism if knowledge implies truth. Even if such
linguistic analyses are rejected, Moral Rearment Movement moral skepticism
589 589 one can still hold that no
moral properties or facts really exist. This ontological moral skepticism can
be combined with the linguistic view that moral claims assert moral properties
and facts to yield an error theory that all positive moral claims are false. A
different kind of doubt about morality is often raised by asking, “Why should I
be moral?” Practical moral skepticism answers that there is not always any
reason or any adequate reason to be moral or to do what is morally required.
This view concerns reasons to act rather than reasons to believe. Moral
skepticism of all these kinds is often seen as immoral, but moral skeptics can
act and be motivated and even hold moral beliefs in much the se way as
non-skeptics. Moral skeptics just deny that their or anyone else’s moral
beliefs are justified or known or true, or that they have adequate reason to be
moral. EMOTIVISM, ETHICS, JUSTIFICATION,
MORAL EPISTEMOLOGY, PRESCRIPTIVISM, SKEPTICISM. W.S.-A. moral status, the suitability
of a being to be viewed as an appropriate object of direct moral concern; the
nature or degree of a being’s ability to count as a ground of claims against
moral agents; the moral standing, rank, or importance of a (kind of) being; the
condition of being a moral patient; moral considerability. Ordinary moral
reflection involves considering others. But which others ought to be
considered? And how are the various objects of moral consideration to be
weighed against one another? Anything might be the topic of moral discussion,
but not everything is thought to be an appropriate object of direct moral
concern. If there are any ethical constraints on how we may treat a ceric
plate, these seem to derive from considerations about other beings, not from the
interests or good or nature of the plate. The se applies, presumably, to a clod
of earth. Many philosophers view a living but insentient being, such as a
dandelion, in the se way; others have doubts. According to some, even sentient
animal life is little more deserving of moral consideration than the clod or
the dandelion. This tradition, which restricts significant moral status to
humans, has come under vigorous and varied attack by defenders of animal
liberation. This attack criticizes speciesism, and argues that “humanism” is
analogous to theories that illegitimately base moral status on race, gender, or
social class. Some philosophers have referred to beings that are appropriate
objects of direct moral concern as “moral patients.” Moral agents are those
beings whose actions are subject to moral evaluation; analogously, moral
patients would be those beings whose suffering (in the sense of being the
objects of the actions of moral agents) permits or demands moral evaluation.
Others apply the label ‘moral patients’ more narrowly, just to those beings
that are appropriate objects of direct moral concern but are not (also) moral
agents. The issue of moral status concerns not only whether beings count at all
morally, but also to what degree they count. After all, beings who are moral
patients might still have their claims outweighed by the preferred claims of
other beings who possess some special moral status. We might, with Nozick,
propose “utilitarianism for animals, Kantianism for people.” Similarly, the bodily
autonomy argument in defense of abortion, made fous by Thomson, does not deny
that the fetus is a moral patient, but insists that her/his/its claims are
limited by the pregnant woman’s prior claim to control her bodily destiny. It
has often been thought that moral status should be tied to the condition of
“personhood.” The idea has been either that only persons are moral patients, or
that persons possess a special moral status that makes them (morally) more
important than nonpersons. Personhood, on such theories, is a minimal condition
for moral patiency. Why? Moral patiency is said to be “correlative” with moral
agency: a creature has both or neither. Alternatively, persons have been viewed
not as the only moral patients, but as a specially privileged elite ong moral
patients, possessing rights as well as interests. ETHICS, KANT, PERSONAL IDENTITY, PERSONHOOD,
RIGHTS. E.J. moral subjectivism.ETHICS. More, Henry (1614–87), English
philosopher, theologian, and poet, the most prolific of the Cbridge Platonists.
In 1631 he entered Christ’s College, where he spent the rest of his life after
becoming Fellow in 1641. He was primarily an apologist of anti-Calvinist,
latitudinarian stp whose inalienable philosophico- theological purpose was to
demonstrate the existence and immortality of the soul and to cure “two enormous
distempers of the mind,” atheism and “enthusiasm.” He described himself as “a
Fisher for Philosophers, desirous to draw them to or retain them in the
Christian Faith.” His eclectic method deployed Neoplatonism (notably Plotinus
and Ficino), mystical theologies, caboral status More, Henry 590 590 listic doctrines (as More misconceived
them), empirical findings (including reports of witchcraft and ghosts), the new
science, and the new philosophy, notably the philosophy of Descartes. Yet he
rejected Descartes’s beast-machine doctrine, his version of dualism, and the
pretensions of Cartesian mechanical philosophy to explain all physical
phenomena. Animals have souls; the universe is alive with souls. Body and
spirit are spatially extended, the former being essentially impenetrable,
inert, and discerpible (divisible into parts), the latter essentially
penetrable, indiscerpible, active, and capable of a spiritual density, which
More called essential spissitude, “the redoubling or contracting of substance
into less space than it does sometimes occupy.” Physical processes are
activated and ordered by the spirit of nature, a hylarchic principle and “the
vicarious power of God upon this great automaton, the world.” More’s writings
on natural philosophy, especially his doctrine of infinite space, are thought
to have influenced Newton. More attacked Hobbes’s materialism and, in the 1660s
and 1670s, the impieties of Dutch Cartesianism, including the perceived atheism
of Spinoza and his circle. He regretted the “enthusiasm” for and conversion to
Quakerism of Anne Conway, his “extrural” tutee and assiduous correspondent.
More had a partiality for coinages and linguistic exotica. We owe to him
‘Cartesianism’ (1662), coined a few years before the first appearance of the
French equivalent, and the substantive ‘materialist’ (1668).
BOYLE, CBRIDGE
PLATONISTS, DESCARTES, NEOPLATONISM. A.G. More, Sir Thomas (1477 or 1478–1535),
English humanist, statesman, martyr, and saint. A lawyer by profession, he
entered royal service in 1517 and bece lord chancellor in 1529. After refusing
to swear to the Act of Supremacy, which ned Henry VIII the head of the English
church, More was beheaded as a traitor. Although his writings include
biography, poetry, letters, and anti-heretical tracts, his only philosophical
work, Utopia (published in Latin, 1516), is his masterpiece. Covering a wide
variety of subjects including government, education, punishment, religion, fily
life, and euthanasia, Utopia contrasts European social institutions with their
counterparts on the imaginary island of Utopia. Inspired in part by Plato’s
Republic, the Utopian communal system is designed to teach virtue and reward it
with happiness. The absence of money, private property, and most social
distinctions allows Utopians the leisure to develop the faculties in which
happiness consists. Because of More’s love of irony, Utopia has been subject to
quite different interpretations. J.W.A. Mosca, Gaetano (1858–1941), Italian
political scientist who made pioneering contributions to the theory of
democratic elitism. Combining the life of a university professor with that of a
politician, he taught such subjects as constitutional law, public law,
political science, and history of political theory; at various times he was
also an editor of the Parlientary proceedings, an elected member of the Chber
of Deputies, an under-secretary for colonial affairs, a newspaper columnist,
and a member of the Senate. For Mosca ‘elitism’ refers to the empirical
generalization that every society is ruled by an organized minority. His
democratic commitment is embodied in what he calls juridical defense: the
normative principle that political developments are to be judged by whether and
how they prevent any one person, class, force, or institution from dominating
the others. His third main contribution is a frework consisting of two
intersecting distinctions that yield four possible ideal types, defined as
follows: in autocracy, authority flows from the rulers to the ruled; in
liberalism, from the ruled to the rulers; in democracy, the ruling class is
open to renewal by members of other classes; in aristocracy it is not. He was
influenced by, and in turn influenced, positivism, for the elitist thesis
presumably constitutes the fundental “law” of political “science.” Even deeper
is his connection with the tradition of Machiavelli’s political realism. There
is also no question that he practiced an empirical approach. In the tradition
of elitism, he may be compared and contrasted with Pareto, Michels, and
Schumpeter; and in the tradition of Italian political philosophy, to Croce,
Gentile, and Grsci. CROCE, GENTILE,
GRSCI, MACHIAVELLI, WEBER. M.A.F. Moses ben Maimon.MAIMONIDES. Mo Ti.MO TZU.
motion.NEWTON. motivation, a property central in motivational explanations of
intentional conduct. To assert that Ann is driving to Boston today because she
wants to see the Red Sox play and believes that they are playing today in
Boston is to offer a More, Sir Thomas motivation 591 591 motivational explanation of this
action. On a popular interpretation, the assertion mentions a pair of
attitudes: a desire and a belief. Ann’s desire is a paradigmatic motivational
attitude in that it inclines her to bring about the satisfaction of that very
attitude. The primary function of motivational attitudes is to bring about
their own satisfaction by inducing the agent to undertake a suitable course of
action, and, arguably, any attitude that has that function is, ipso facto, a
motivational one. The related thesis that only attitudes having this function
are motivational – or, more precisely, motivation-constituting – is
implausible. Ann hopes that the Sox won yesterday. Plainly, her hope cannot
bring about its own satisfaction, since Ann has no control over the past. Even
so, the hope seemingly may motivate action (e.g., Ann’s searching for sports
news on her car radio), in which case the hope is motivation-constituting. Some
philosophers have claimed that our beliefs that we are morally required to take
a particular course of action are motivation-constituting, and such beliefs
obviously do not have the function of bringing about their own satisfaction
(i.e., their truth). However, the claim is controversial, as is the related
claim that beliefs of this kind are “besires” – that is, not merely beliefs but
desires as well.
ACCIDIE, ACTION THEORY,
MOTIVATIONAL EXPLANATION, MOTIVATIONAL INTERNALISM. A.R.M. motivational
explanation, a type of explanation of goal-directed behavior where the
explanans appeals to the motives of the agent. The explanation usually is in
the following form: Smith sw hard in order to win the race. Here the
description of what Smith did identifies the behavior to be explained, and the
phrase that follows ‘in order to’ identifies the goal or the state of affairs
the obtaining of which was the moving force behind the behavior. The general
presumption is that the agent whose behavior is being explained is capable of
deliberating and acting on the decisions reached as a result of the
deliberation. Thus, it is dubious whether the explanation contained in ‘The
plant turned toward the sun in order to receive more light’ is a motivational
explanation. Two problems are thought to surround motivational explanations.
First, since the state of affairs set as the goal is, at the time of the
action, non-existent, it can only act as the “moving force” by appearing as the
intentional object of an inner psychological state of the agent. Thus, motives
are generally desires for specific objects or states of affairs on which the
agent acts. So motivational explanation is basically the type of explanation
provided in folk psychology, and as such it inherits all the alleged problems
of the latter. And second, what counts as a motive for an action under one
description usually fails to be a motive for the se action under a different
description. My motive for saying “hello” may have been my desire to answer the
phone, but my motive for saying “hello” loudly was to express my irritation at
the person calling me so late at night.
ACTION THEORY, EXPLANATION, FOLK PSYCHOLOGY, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. B.E.
motivational internalism, the view that moral motivation is internal to moral
duty (or the sense of duty). The view represents the contemporary understanding
of Hume’s thesis that morality is essentially practical. Hume went on to point
out the apparent logical gap between statements of fact, which express
theoretical judgments, and statements about what ought to be done, which
express practical judgments. Motivational internalism offers one explanation
for this gap. No motivation is internal to the recognition of facts. The
specific internal relation the view affirms is that of necessity. Thus,
motivational internalists hold that if one sees that one has a duty to do a
certain action or that it would be right to do it, then necessarily one has a
motive to do it. For exple, if one sees that it is one’s duty to donate blood,
then necessarily one has a motive to donate blood. Motivational externalism,
the opposing view, denies this relation. Its adherents hold that it is possible
for one to see that one has a duty to do a certain action or that it would be
right to do it yet have no motive to do it. Motivational externalists
typically, though not universally, deny any real gap between theoretical and
practical judgments. Motivational internalism takes either of two forms,
rationalist and anti-rationalist. Rationalists, such as Plato and Kant, hold
that the content or truth of a moral requirement guarantees in those who
understand it a motive of compliance. Anti-rationalists, such as Hume, hold
that moral judgment necessarily has some affective or volitional component that
supplies a motive for the relevant action but that renders morality less a matter
of reason and truth than of feeling or commitment. It is also possible in the
abstract to motivational explanation motivational internalism 592 592 Mo Tzu mysticism 593 draw an analogous
distinction between two forms of motivational externalism, cognitivist and
noncognitivist, but because the view springs from an interest in assimilating
practical judgment to theoretical judgment, its only influential form has been
cognitivist.
EMOTIVISM, ETHICS, HUME.
J.D. Mo Tzu, also known as Master Mo, Mo Ti (fifth century B.C.), Chinese
philosopher and founder of the Mohist school of thought, which was a major
rival to Confucianism in ancient China. The text Mo Tzu contains different
versions of his teachings as well as subsequent developments of his thought. Mo
Tzu regarded rightness (yi) as determined by what benefits (li) the public,
where benefit is understood in terms of such things as order and increased
resources in society. He opposed the musical activities and ritual practices of
the Confucians on the ground that such practices are detrimental to the public
good. He is probably best known for advocating the ideal of an equal concern to
benefit and avoid harm to every human being. Practicing this ideal is to the
public good, since strife and disorder stem from partiality toward oneself or
one’s fily or social group. Also, it being the will of Heaven (t’ien) that
people have equal concern for all, one will be rewarded or punished by Heaven
according to whether one practices this ideal. In response to worries about the
practicability of the ideal, Mo Tzu insisted that it was simple and easy to put
the ideal into practice, leaving himself open to the charge that he neglected
the complexities of emotional management.
CONFUCIANISM, MOHISM. K.-l.S. Mou Tsung-san (1909–95), Chinese
philosopher, perhaps the most original thinker ong contemporary Neo-Confucians.
Educated at Peking University, he first studied Western philosophy but was
converted to Chinese philosophy under the influence of Hsiung Shih-li. He made
a great breakthrough in his study of Sung–Ming NeoConfucian philosophy, arguing
that Chu Hsi was really a side branch that took the position of the orthodoxy.
He maintained that all three major Chinese traditions, Confucian, Taoist, and
Buddhist, assert that humans have the endowment for intellectual intuition,
meaning personal participation in tao (the Way).
CHINESE PHILOSOPHY,
HSIUNG SHIH-LI, HSÜ FU-KUAN, NEO-CONFUCIANISM, T’ANG CHÜN-I. S.-h.L. moving
rows paradox.ZENO’s PARADOXES. multiple realizability.FUNCTIONALISM.
multiple-relation theory.PERCEPTION. mystical experience, an experience alleged
to reveal some aspect of reality not normally accessible to sensory experience
or cognition. The experience – typically characterized by its profound emotional
impact on the one who experiences it, its transcendence of spatial and temporal
distinctions, its transitoriness, and its ineffability – is often but not
always associated with some religious tradition. In theistic religions,
mystical experiences are claimed to be brought about by God or by some other
superhuman agent. Theistic mystical experiences evoke feelings of worshipful
awe. Their content can vary from something no more articulate than a feeling of
closeness to God to something as specific as an item of revealed theology, such
as, for a Christian mystic, a vision of the Trinity. Non-theistic mystical
experiences are usually claimed to reveal the metaphysical unity of all things
and to provide those who experience them with a sense of inner peace or bliss. MYSTICISM. W.E.M. mysticism, a doctrine or
discipline maintaining that one can gain knowledge of reality that is not
accessible to sense perception or to rational, conceptual thought. Generally
associated with a religious tradition, mysticism can take a theistic form, as
it has in Jewish, Christian, and Islic traditions, or a non-theistic form, as
it has in Buddhism and some varieties of Hinduism. Mystics claim that the
mystical experience, the vehicle of mystical knowledge, is usually the result of
spiritual training, involving some combination of prayer, meditation, fasting,
bodily discipline, and renunciation of worldly concerns. Theistic varieties of
mysticism describe the mystical experience as granted by God and thus not
subject to the control of the mystic. Although theists claim to feel closeness
to God during the mystical experience, they regard assertions of identity of
the self with God as heretical. Non-theistic varieties are more apt to describe
the experience as one that can be induced and controlled by the mystic and in
which distinctions between the self and reality, or subject and object, are
revealed to be illusory. Mystics claim that, although veridical, their
experiences cannot be adequately described in language, because ordinary communication
is based on sense experience and conceptual differentiation: mystical writings
are thus characterized by metaphor and simile. It is con 593 troversial whether all mystical
experiences are basically the se, and whether the apparent diversity ong them
is the result of interpretations influenced by different cultural
traditions. MYSTICAL EXPERIENCE,
PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. W.E.M. myth of Er, a tale at the end of Plato’s
Republic dratizing the rewards of justice and philosophy by depicting the process
of reincarnation. Complementing the main argument of the work, that it is
intrinsically better to be just than unjust, this longest of Plato’s myths
blends traditional lore with speculative cosmology to show that justice also
pays, usually in life and certainly in the afterlife. Er, a warrior who revived
shortly after death, reports how judges assign the souls of the just to heaven
but others to punishment in the underworld, and how most return after a
thousand years to behold the celestial order, to choose their next lives, and
to be born anew. PLATO. S.A.W. myth of
the given.SELLARS, WILFRID. myth of Er myth of the given 594 594 Nagarjuna (fl. early second century
A.D.), Indian Mahayana Buddhist philosopher, founder of the Madhyika view. The
Mulanadhyakarika Prajña (“The Fundental Verses on the Middle Way”) and the
Sunyatasaptati (“The Septuagint on Emptiness”) are perhaps his major works. He
distinguishes between “two truths”: a conditional truth, which is provisional
and reflects the sort of distinctions we make in everyday speech and find in
ordinary experience; and a final truth, which is that there exists only an
ineffable independent reality. Overcoming acceptance of the conventional,
conditional truth is requisite for seeing the final truth in
enlightenment. MADHYIKA. K.E.Y. Nagel,
Ernest (1901–85), Czech-born erican philosopher, the preeminent erican
philosopher of science in the period from the mid-1930s to the 1960s. Arriving
in New York as a ten-yearold immigrant, he earned his B.S. degree from the
College of the City of New York and his Ph.D. from Columbia University in 1931.
He was a member of the Philosophy Department at Columbia from 1930 to 1970. He
coauthored the influential An Introduction to Logic and Scientific Method with
his former teacher, M. R. Cohen. His many publications include two well-known
classics: Principles of the Theory of Probability (1939) and Structure of
Science (1960). Nagel was sensitive to developments in logic, foundations of
mathematics, and probability theory, and he shared with Russell and with
members of the Vienna Circle like Carnap and Phillip Frank a respect for the
relevance of scientific inquiry for philosophical reflection. But his writing
also reveals the influences of M. R. Cohen and that strand in the thinking of
the pragmatism of Peirce and Dewey which Nagel himself called “contextualist
naturalism.” He was a persuasive critic of Russell’s views of the data of
sensation as a source of non-inferential premises for knowledge and of cognate
views expressed by some members of the Vienna Circle. Unlike Frege, Russell,
Carnap, Popper, and others, he rejected the view that taking account of context
in characterizing method threatened to taint philosophical reflection with an
unacceptable psychologism. This stance subsequently allowed him to oppose
historicist and sociologist approaches to the philosophy of science. Nagel’s
contextualism is reflected in his contention that ideas of determinism,
probability, explanation, and reduction “can be significantly discussed only if
they are directed to the theories or formulations of a science and not its
subject matter” (Principles of the Theory of Probability, 1939). This attitude
infused his influential discussions of covering law explanation, statistical
explanation, functional explanation, and reduction of one theory to another, in
both natural and social science. Similarly, his contention that participants in
the debate between realism and instrumentalism should clarify the import of
their differences for (context-sensitive) scientific methodology served as the
core of his argument casting doubt on the significance of the dispute. In
addition to his extensive writings on scientific knowledge methodology, Nagel
wrote influential essays on measurement, the history of mathematics, and the
philosophy of law.
COVERING LAW MODEL,
PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, REDUCTION, VIENNA CIRCLE. I.L. Nagel, Thomas (b.1937),
erican professor of philosophy and of law at New York University, known for his
important contributions in the fields of metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, and
political philosophy. Nagel’s work in these areas is unified by a particular
vision of perennial philosophical problems, according to which they emerge from
a clash between two perspectives from which human beings can view themselves
and the world. From an impersonal perspective, which results from detaching
ourselves from our particular viewpoints, we strive to achieve an objective
view of the world, whereas from a personal perspective, we see the world from
our particular point of view. According to Nagel, dominance of the impersonal
perspective in trying to understand reality leads to implausible philosophical
views because it fails to accommodate facts about the self, minds, agency, and
values that are revealed through engaged personal perspectives. In the
philosophy of mind, for instance, Nagel criticizes various reductive accounts
of mentality 595 N 595 resulting from
taking an exclusively impersonal standpoint because they inevitably fail to
account for the irreducibly subjective character of consciousness. In ethics,
consequentialist moral theories (like utilitarianism), which feature strong
impartialist demands that stem from taking a detached, impersonal perspective,
find resistance from the personal perspective within which individual goals and
motives are accorded an importance not found in strongly impartialist moral
theories. An exination of such problems in metaphysics, epistemology, and
ethics is found in his Moral Questions (1979) and The View from Nowhere (1986).
In Equality and Partiality (1990) Nagel argues that the impersonal standpoint
gives rise to an egalitarian form of impartial regard for all people that often
clashes with the goals, concerns, and affections that individuals experience
from a personal perspective. Quite generally, then, as Nagel sees it, one
important philosophical task is to explore ways in which these two standpoints
on both theoretical and practical matters might be integrated. Nagel has also
made important contributions regarding the nature and possibility of reason or
rationality in both its theoretical and its practical uses. The Possibility of
Altruism (1970) is an exploration of the structure of practical reason in which
Nagel defends the rationality of prudence and altruism, arguing that the
possibility of such behavior is connected with our capacities to view ourselves
respectively persisting through time and recognizing the reality of other
persons. The Last Word (1998) is a defense of reason against skeptical views,
according to which reason is a merely contingent, locally conditioned feature
of particular cultures and hence relative.
naturalism, the twofold
view that (1) everything is composed of natural entities – those studied in the
sciences (on some versions, the natural sciences) – whose properties determine
all the properties of things, persons included (abstracta like possibilia and
mathematical objects, if they exist, being constructed of such abstract
entities as the sciences allow); and (2) acceptable methods of justification
and explanation are continuous, in some sense, with those in science. Clause
(1) is metaphysical or ontological, clause (2) methodological and/or
epistemological. Often naturalism is formulated only for a specific subject
matter or domain. Thus ethical naturalism holds that moral properties are
equivalent to or at least determined by certain natural properties, so that
moral judgments either form a subclass of, or are (non-reductively) determined
by the factual or descriptive judgments, and the appropriate methods of moral
justification and explanation are continuous with those in science. Aristotle
and Spinoza sometimes are counted ong the ancestors of naturalism, as are
Democritus, Epicurus, Lucretius, and Hobbes. But the major impetus to
naturalism in the last two centuries comes from advances in science and the
growing explanatory power they signify. By the 1850s, the synthesis of urea,
reflections on the conservation of energy, work on “animal electricity,” and
discoveries in physiology suggested to Feuerbach, L. Buchner, and others that
all aspects of human beings are explainable in purely natural terms. Darwin’s
theory had even greater impact, and by the end of the nineteenth century
naturalist philosophies were making inroads where idealism once reigned
unchallenged. Naturalism’s ranks now included H. Spencer, J. Tyndall, T. H.
Huxley, W. K. Clifford, and E. Haeckel. Early in the twentieth century,
Santayana’s naturalism strongly influenced a number of erican philosophers, as
did Dewey’s. Still other versions of naturalism flourished in erica in the
1930s and 1940s, including those of R. W. Sellars and M. Cohen. Today most
erican and other philosophers of mind naive realism naturalism 596 596 are naturalists of some stripe, largely
because of what they see as the lessons of continuing scientific advances, some
of them spectacular, particularly in the brain sciences. Nonetheless,
twentieth-century philosophy has been largely anti-naturalist. Both
phenomenology in the Husserlian tradition and analytic philosophy in the
Fregean tradition, together with their descendants, have been united in
rejecting psychologism, a species of naturalism according to which empirical
discoveries about mental processes are crucial for understanding the nature of
knowledge, language, and logic. In order to defend the autonomy of philosophy
against inroads from descriptive science, many philosophers have tried to turn
the tables by arguing for the priority of philosophy over science, hence over
any of its alleged naturalist implications. Many continue to do so, often on
the ground that philosophy alone can illuminate the normativity and
intentionality involved in knowledge, language, and logic; or on the ground
that philosophy can evaluate the normative and regulative presuppositions of
scientific practice which science itself is either blind to or unequipped to
analyze; or on the ground that phi- losophy understands how the language of
science can no more be used to get outside itself than any other, hence can no
more be known to be in touch with the world and ourselves than any other; or on
the ground that would-be justifications of fundental method, naturalist method
certainly included, are necessarily circular because they must employ the very
method at issue. Naturalists may reply by arguing that naturalism’s
methodological clause (2) entails the opposite of dogmatism, requiring as it
does an uncompromising fallibilism about philosophical matters that is
continuous with the open, selfcritical spirit of science. If evidence were to
accumulate against naturalism’s metaphysical clause (1), (1) would have to be
revised or rejected, and there is no a priori reason such evidence could in
principle never be found; indeed many naturalists reject the a priori
altogether. Likewise, (2) itself might have to be revised or even rejected in
light of adverse argument, so that in this respect (2) is self-referentially
consistent. Until then, (2)’s having survived rigorous criticism to date is
justification enough, as is the case with hypotheses in science, which often
are deployed without circularity in the course of their own evaluation, whether
positive or negative (H. I. Brown, “Circular Justifications,” 1994). So too can
language be used without circularity in expressing hypotheses about the
relations between language and the prelinguistic world (as illustrated by R.
Millikan’s Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories, 1984; cf. Post,
“Epistemology,” 1996). As for normativity and intentionality, naturalism does
not entail materialism or physicalism, according to which everything is
composed of the entities or processes studied in physics, and the properties of
these basic physical affairs determine all the properties of things (as in
Quine). Some naturalists deny this, holding that more things than are dret of
in physics are required to account for normativity and intentionality – and
consciousness. Nor need naturalism be reductive, in the sense of equating every
property with some natural property. Indeed many physicalists themselves
explain how the physical, hence natural, properties of things might determine
other, non-natural properties without being equivalent to them (G. Hellman, T.
Horgan, D. Lewis; see J. Post, The Faces of Existence, 1987). Often the
determining physical properties are not all properties of the thing x that has
the non-natural properties, but include properties of items separated from x in
space and time or in some cases bearing no physical relation to x that does any
work in determining x’s properties (Post, “ ‘Global’ Supervenient
Determination: Too Permissive?” 1995). Thus naturalism allows a high degree of
holism and historicity, which opens the way for a non-reductive naturalist
account of intentionality and normativity, such as Millikan’s, that is immune
to the usual objections, which are mostly objections to reduction. The
alternative psychosemantic theories of Dretske and Fodor, being largely
reductive, remain vulnerable to such objections. In these and other ways
non-reductive naturalism attempts to combine a monism of entities – the natural
ones of which everything is composed – with a pluralism of properties, many of
them irreducible or emergent. Not everything is nothing but a natural thing,
nor need naturalism accord totalizing primacy to the natural face of existence.
Indeed, some naturalists regard the universe as having religious and moral
dimensions that enjoy a crucial kind of primacy; and some offer theologies that
are more traditionally theist (as do H. N. Wieman, C. Hardwick, J. Post). So
far from exhibiting “reptilian indifference” to humans and their fate, the
universe can be an enchanted place of belonging.
naturalistic
epistemology, an approach to epistemology that views the human subject as a
natural phenomenon and uses empirical science to study epistemic activity. The
phrase was introduced by Quine (“Epistemology Naturalized,” in Ontological
Relativity and Other Essays, 1969), who proposed that epistemology should be a
chapter of psychology. Quine construed classical epistemology as Cartesian
epistemology, an attempt to ground all knowledge in a firmly logical way on
immediate experience. In its twentieth-century embodiment, it hoped to give a
translation of all discourse and a deductive validation of all science in terms
of sense experience, logic, and set theory. Repudiating this dre as forlorn,
Quine urged that epistemology be abandoned and replaced by psychology. It would
be a scientific study of how the subject takes sensory stimulations as input
and delivers as output a theory of the three-dimensional world. This
formulation appears to eliminate the normative mission of epistemology. In
later writing, however, Quine has suggested that normative epistemology can be
naturalized as a chapter of engineering: the technology of predicting
experience, or sensory stimulations. Some theories of knowledge are
naturalistic in their depiction of knowers as physical systems in causal
interaction with the environment. One such theory is the causal theory of
knowing, which says that a person knows that p provided his belief that p has a
suitable causal connection with a corresponding state of affairs. Another exple
is the information-theoretic approach developed by Dretske (Knowledge and the
Flow of Information, 1981). This says that a person knows that p only if some
signal “carries” this information (that p) to him, where information is
construed as an objective commodity that can be processed and transmitted via
instruments, gauges, neurons, and the like. Information is “carried” from one
site to another when events located at those sites are connected by a suitable
lawful dependence. The normative concept of justification has also been the
subject of naturalistic construals. Whereas many theories of justified belief
focus on logical or probabilistic relations between evidence and hypothesis,
naturalistic theories focus on the psychological processes causally responsible
for the belief. The logical status of a belief does not fix its justificational
status. Belief in a tautology, for instance, is not justified if it is formed
by blind trust in an ignorant guru. According to Goldman (Epistemology and
Cognition, 1986), a belief qualifies as justified only if it is produced by
reliable belief-forming processes, i.e., processes that generally have a high
truth ratio. Goldman’s larger progr for naturalistic epistemology is called
“epistemics,” an interdisciplinary enterprise in which cognitive science would
play a major role. Epistemics would seek to identify the subset of cognitive
operations available to the human cognizer that are best from a truth-bearing
standpoint. Relevant truth-linked properties include problem-solving power and
speed, i.e., the abilities to obtain correct answers to questions of interest
and to do so quickly. Close connections between epistemology and artificial
intelligence have been proposed by Clark Glymour, Gilbert Harman, John Pollock,
and Paul Thagard. Harman stresses that principles of good reasoning are not
directly given by rules of logic. Modus ponens, e.g., does not tell you to
infer q if you already believe p and ‘if p then q’. In some cases it is better
to subtract a belief in one of the premises rather than add a belief in q.
Belief revision also requires attention to the storage and computational
limitations of the mind. Limits of memory capacity, e.g., suggest a principle
of clutter avoidance: not filling one’s mind with vast numbers of useless
beliefs (Harman, Change in View, 1986). Other conceptions of naturalistic
epistemology focus on the history of science. Larry Laudan conceives of
naturalistic epistemology as a scientific inquiry that gathers empirical
evidence concerning the past track records of various scientific methodologies,
with the aim of determining which of these methodologies can best advance the
chosen cognitive ends. Naturalistic epistemology need not confine its attention
to individual epistemic agents; it can also study communities of agents. This
perspective invites contributions from sciences that address the social side of
the knowledge-seeking enterprise. If naturalistic epistemology is a normative
inquiry, however, it must not simply naturalism, biological naturalistic
epistemology 598 598 describe social
practices or social influences; it must analyze the impact of these factors on
the attainment of cognitive ends. Philosophers such as David Hull, Nicholas
Rescher, Philip Kitcher, and Alvin Goldman have sketched models inspired by
population biology and economics to explore the epistemic consequences of
alternative distributions of research activity and different ways that
professional rewards might influence the course of research. ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE, EPISTEMOLOGY,
NATURALISM, RELIABILISM.
A.I.G. naturalistic fallacy.MOORE. natural kind, a category of entities
classically conceived as having modal implications; e.g., if Socrates is a
member of the natural kind human being, then he is necessarily a human being.
The idea that nature fixes certain sortals, such as ‘water’ and ‘human being’,
as correct classifications that appear to designate kinds of entities has roots
going back at least to Plato and Aristotle. Anil Gupta has argued that sortals
are to be distinguished from properties designated by such predicates as ‘red’
by including criteria for individuating the particulars (bits or ounts for mass
nouns) that fall under them as well as criteria for sorting those particulars
into the class. Quine is salient ong those who find the modal implications of
natural kinds objectionable. He has argued that the idea of natural kinds is
rooted in prescientific intuitive judgments of comparative similarity, and he
has suggested that as these intuitive classifications are replaced by
classifications based on scientific theories these modal implications drop
away. Kripke and Putn have argued that science in fact uses natural kind terms
having the modal implications Quine finds so objectionable. They see an
important role in scientific methodology for the capacity to refer
demonstratively to such natural kinds by pointing out particulars that fall
under them. Certain inferences within science – such as the inference to the
charge for electrons generally from the measurement of the charge on one or a
few electrons – seem to be additional aspects of a role for natural kind terms in
scientific practice. Other roles in the methodology of science for natural kind
concepts have been discussed in recent work by Ian Hacking and Thomas
Kuhn. COUNT NOUN, ESSENTIALISM,
PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, QUALITATIVE PREDICATE. W.Har. natural language.FORMAL
LANGUAGE, PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE. natural law, also called law of nature, in
moral and political philosophy, an objective norm or set of objective norms
governing human behavior, similar to the positive laws of a human ruler, but
binding on all people alike and usually understood as involving a superhuman
legislator. Ancient Greek and Roman thought, particularly Stoicism, introduced
ideas of eternal laws directing the actions of all rational beings and built
into the very structure of the universe. Roman lawyers developed a doctrine of
a law that all civilized peoples would recognize, and made some effort to
explain it in terms of a natural law common to animals and humans. The most
influential forms of natural law theory, however, arose from later efforts to
use Stoic and legal language to work out a Christian theory of morality and
politics. The aim was to show that the principles of morals could be known by
reason alone, without revelation, so that the whole human race could know how
to live properly. The law of nature applies, on this understanding, only to
rational beings, who can obey or disobey it deliberately and freely. It is thus
different in kind from the laws God laid down for the inanimate and irrational
parts of creation. Natural law theorists often saw continuities and analogies
between natural laws for humans and those for the rest of creation but did not
confuse them. The most enduringly influential natural law writer was Aquinas.
On his view God’s eternal reason ordains laws directing all things to act for
the good of the community of the universe, the declaration of His own glory.
Human reason can participate sufficiently in God’s eternal reason to show us
the good of the human community. The natural law is thus our sharing in the eternal
law in a way appropriate to our human nature. God lays down certain other laws
through revelation; these divine laws point us toward our eternal goal. The
natural law concerns our earthly good, and needs to be supplemented by human
laws. Such laws can vary from community to community, but to be binding they
must always stay within the limits of the law of nature. God engraved the most
basic principles of the natural law in the minds of all people alike, but their
detailed application takes reasoning powers that not everyone may have.
Opponents of Aquinas – called voluntarists – argued that God’s will, not his
intellect, is the source of law, and that God could have laid down different
natural laws for us. Hugo Grotius naturalistic fallacy natural law 599 599 rejected their position, but unlike
Aquinas he conceived of natural law as meant not to direct us to bring about
some definite common good but to set the limits on the ways in which each of us
could properly pursue our own personal aims. This Grotian outlook was developed
by Hobbes, Pufendorf, and Locke along voluntarist lines. Thomistic views
continued to be expounded by Protestant as well as Roman Catholic writers until
the end of the seventeenth century. Thereafter, while natural law theory remained
central to Catholic teaching, it ceased to attract major new non-Catholic
proponents. Natural law doctrine in both Thomistic and Grotian versions treats
morality as basically a matter of compliance with law. Obligation and duty,
obedience and disobedience, merit and guilt, reward and punishment, are central
notions. Virtues are simply habits of following laws. Though the law is suited
to our distinctive human nature and can be discovered by the proper use of
reason, it is not a self-imposed law. In following it we are obeying God. Since
the early eighteenth century, philosophical discussions of whether or not there
is an objective morality have largely ceased to center on natural law. The idea
remains alive, however, in jurisprudence. Natural law theories are opposed to
legal positivism, the view that the only binding laws are those imposed by
human sovereigns, who cannot be subject to higher legal constraints. Legal
theorists arguing that there are rational objective limits to the legislative
power of rulers often think of these limits in terms of natural law, even when
their theories do not invoke or imply any of the religious aspects of earlier
natural law positions.
AQUINAS, GROTIUS, HOBBES,
PHILOSOPHY OF LAW, PUFENDORF. J.B.S. natural light.DESCARTES. natural
meaning.MEANING. naturalness.JUAN CHI. natural number.MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS,
MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION. natural philosophy, the study of nature or of the
spatiotemporal world. This was regarded as a task for philosophy before the
emergence of modern science, especially physics and astronomy, and the term is
now only used with reference to premodern times. Philosophical questions about
nature still remain, e.g., whether materialism is true, but they would usually
be placed in metaphysics or in a branch of it that may be called philosophy of
nature. Natural philosophy is not to be confused with metaphysical naturalism,
which is the metaphysical view (no part of science itself) that all that there
is is the spatiotemporal world and that the only way to study it is that of the
empirical sciences. It is also not to be confused with natural theology, which
also may be considered part of metaphysics.
METAPHYSICS. P.Bu. natural religion, a term first occurring in the second
half of the seventeenth century, used in three related senses, the most common
being (1) a body of truths about God and our duty that can be discovered by
natural reason. These truths are sufficient for salvation or (according to some
orthodox Christians) would have been sufficient if Ad had not sinned. Natural
religion in this sense should be distinguished from natural theology, which
does not imply this. A natural religion may also be (2) one that has a human,
as distinct from a divine, origin. It may also be (3) a religion of human nature
as such, as distinguished from religious beliefs and practices that have been
determined by local circumstances. Natural religion in the third sense is
identified with humanity’s original religion. In all three senses, natural
religion includes a belief in God’s existence, justice, benevolence, and
providential government; in immortality; and in the dictates of common
morality. While the concept is associated with deism, it is also
sympathetically treated by Christian writers like Clarke, who argues that revealed
religion simply restores natural religion to its original purity and adds
inducements to compliance.
necessitarianism, the
doctrine that necessity is an objective feature of the world. Natural language
permits speakers to express modalities: a state of affairs can be actual
(Paris’s being in France), merely possible (chlorophyll’s making things blue),
or necessary (2 ! 2 % 4). Anti-necessitarians believe that these distinctions
are not grounded in the nature of the world. Some of them claim that the
distinctions are merely verbal. Others, e.g., Hume, believed that psychological
facts, like our expectations of future events, explain the idea of necessity.
Yet others contend that the modalities reflect epistemic considerations;
necessity reflects the highest level of an inquirer’s commitment. Some
necessitarians believe there are different modes of metaphysical necessity,
e.g., causal and logical necessity. Certain proponents of idealism believe that
each fact is necessarily connected with every other fact so that the ultimate
goal of scientific inquiry is the discovery of a completely rigorous
mathematical system of the world.
DETERMINISM, FREE WILL PROBLEM. B.B. necessity, a modal property
attributable to a whole proposition (dictum) just when it is not possible that
the proposition be false (the proposition being de dicto necessary). Narrowly
construed, a proposition P is logically necessary provided P satisfies certain
syntactic conditions, nely, that P’s denial is formally self-contradictory. More
broadly, P is logically necessary just when P satisfies certain semantic
conditions, nely, that P’s denial is false, and P true, in all possible worlds.
These semantic conditions were first suggested by Leibniz, refined by
Wittgenstein and Carnap, and fully developed as the possible worlds semantics
of Kripke, Hintikka, et al., in the 1960s. Previously, philosophers had to rely
largely on intuition to determine the acceptability or otherwise of formulas
involving the necessity operator, A, and were at a loss as to which of various
axiomatic systems for modal logic, as developed in the 1930s by C. I. Lewis,
best captured the notion of logical necessity. There was much debate, for
instance, over the characteristic (NN) thesis of Lewis’s system S4, nely, AP /
A AP (if P is necessary then it is necessarily necessary). But given a
Leibnizian account of the truth conditions for a statement of the form Aa nely
(R1) that Aa is true provided a is true in all possible worlds, and (R2) that
Aa is false provided there is at least one possible world in which a is false,
a proof can be constructed by reductio ad absurdum. For suppose that AP / AAP
is false in some arbitrarily chosen world W. Then its antecedent will be true
in W, and hence (by R1) it follows (a) that P will be true in all possible
worlds. But equally its consequent will be false in W, and hence (by R2) AP
will be false in at least one possible world, from which (again by R2) it
follows (b) that P will be false in at least one possible world, thus contradicting
(a). A similar proof can be constructed for the characteristic thesis of S5,
nely, -A-P / A-A-P (if P is possibly true then it is necessarily possible).
Necessity is also attributable to a property F of an object O provided it is
not possible that (there is no possible world in which) O exists and lacks F –
F being de re necessary, internal or essential to O. For instance, the
non-repeatable (haecceitist) property of being identical to O is de re
necessary (essential) to O, and arguably the repeatable property of being
extended is de re necessary to all colored objects. CONTINGENT, ESSENTIALISM, HAECCEITY, MODAL
LOGIC, POSSIBLE WORLDS. R.D.B. necessity, metaphysical
.NECESSITY, PHILOSOPHY OF
MIND. necessity, nomic.LAWLIKE GENERALIZATION. negation, the logical operation
on propositions that is indicated, e.g., by the prefatory clause ‘It is not the
case that . . .’. Negation is standardly distinguished sharply from the
operation on predicates that is called complementation and that is indicated by
the prefix ‘non-’. Because negation can also be indicated by the adverb ‘not’,
a distinction is often drawn between external negation, which is indicated by
attaching the prefatory ‘It is not the case that . . .’ to an assertion, and
internal negation, which is indicated by inserting the adverb ‘not’ (along
with, perhaps, nature, right of negation 601
601 grmatically necessary words like ‘do’ or ‘does’) into the assertion
in such a way as to indicate that the adverb ‘not’ modifies the verb. In a
number of cases, the question arises as to whether external and internal
negation yield logically equivalent results. For exple, ‘It is not the case
that Santa Claus exists’ would seem obviously to be true, whereas ‘Santa Claus
does not exist’ seems to some philosophers to presuppose what it denies, on the
ground that nothing could be truly asserted of Santa Claus unless he
existed.
Nemesius of Emesa (fl.
c.390–400), Greek Christian philosopher. His treatise on the soul, On the
Nature of Man, translated from Greek into Latin by Alphanus of Salerno and
Burgundio of Pisa (c.1160), was attributed to Gregory of Nyssa in the Middle
Ages, and enjoyed some authority; the treatise rejects Plato for underplaying
the unity of soul and body, and Aristotle for making the soul essentially
corporeal. The soul is selfsubsistent, incorporeal, and by nature immortal, but
naturally suited for union with the body. Nemesius draws on monius Saccas and
Porphyry, as well as analogy to the union of divine and human nature in Christ,
to explain the incorruptible soul’s perfect union with the corruptible body.
His review of the powers of the soul draws especially on Galen on the brain.
His view that rational creatures possess free will in virtue of their
rationality influenced Maximus the Confessor and John of Dascus. J.Lo.
Neo-Confucianism, Confucianism as revived in China during the late tenth to
mid-seventeenth centuries. It has also been called Tao-hsüeh (learning of the
Way) or Li-hsüeh (learning of principles) in the broader sense. It is without
any doubt Confucianism, since Sung–Ming Confucianists also found their ultimate
commitment in jen (humanity or human-heartedness) and regulated their behavior
by li (propriety). But it acquired new features, since it was a movement in
response to the challenges from Buddhism and Neo-Taoism. Therefore it developed
sophisticated theories of human mind and nature and also cosmology and
metaphysics far beyond the scope of Pre-Ch’in Confucianism. If the Confucian
ideal may be characterized by nei-sheng-waiwang (inward sageliness and outward
kingliness), then the Neo-Confucianists certainly made greater contributions to
the nei-sheng side, as they considered wei-chi-chih-hsüeh (learning for one’s
self) as their primary concern, and developed sophisticated discipline of the
mind comparable to the kind of transcendental meditation practiced by Buddhists
and Taoists. They put emphasis on finding resources within the self. Hence they
moved away from the Han tradition of writing extensive commentaries on the Five
Classics. Instead, they looked for guidance to the so-called Four Books: the
Analects, the Mencius, The Great Learning, and The Doctrine of the Mean. They
also believed that they should put what they had learned from the words of the
sages and worthies into practice in order to make themselves better. This was
to start a new trend in sharp contrast to the earlier Five Dynasties period
(907–60), when moral standards had fallen to a new low. According to Chu Hsi,
the movement started with Chou Tun-yi (1017–73), who, along with Chang Tsai
(1020–77), gave new interpretations to the I-Ching (the Book of Changes) and
The Doctrine of the Mean in combination with the Analects and the Mencius so as
to develop new cosmologies and metaphysics in response to the challenges from
Buddhism and Taoism. The ne of Shao Yung (1011–77), an expert on the I-Ching,
was excluded, as his views were considered too Taoistic. But the true founders
and leaders of the movement were the two Ch’eng brothers – Ch’eng Hao (1032–85)
and Ch’eng Yi (1033– 1107). Onetime pupils of Chou, they developed li
(principle) into a philosophical concept. Even though Hua-yen Buddhism had used
the term first, the Ch’eng brothers gave it a totally new interpretation from a
Confucian perspective. Later scholars find that the thoughts of the two
brothers differed both in style and in substance. Ch’eng Hao believed in i-pen
(one foundation), while Ch’eng Yi developed a dualistic metaphysics of li
(principle) and ch’i (material force). On the surface Chu Hsi was the follower
of the Ch’eng brothers, but in fact he was only following the lead of Ch’eng
Yi, and promoted the socalled Li-hsüeh (learning of principles) in the narrower
sense. His younger contemporary negation-complete Neo-Confucianism 602 602 Lu Hsiang-shan (1139–93) objected to
Chu’s method of looking for principles ong things. He urged us to realize
principle within one’s own mind, went back to Mencius’s teaching to establish
the greater part of the self first, and promoted the so-called hsin-hsüeh (learning
of the mind). But Chu Hsi’s commentaries on the Four Books were adopted as the
basis of civil service exinations in the Yüan dynasty; Lu’s views were largely
ignored until there were revived in the Ming dynasty (1368–1644) by Wang
Yang-ming (1472–1529), who identified the mind with principle and advocated
that knowledge and action are one. Since Lu–Wang’s thoughts were closer to
Mencius, who was honored to have represented the orthodox line of transmission
of the Way, Mou Tsung-san advanced the theory that Chu Hsi was the side branch
taking over the orthodoxy; he also believed that Hu Hung (1100–55) and Liu
Tsung-chou (1578–1645) developed a third branch of Neo-Confucianism in addition
to that of Ch’eng and Chu and that of Lu and Wang. His views have generated
many controversies. Sung–Ming Neo-Confucianism was hailed as creating the
second golden period of Chinese philosophy since the late Chou. Huang Tsung-hsi
(1610–95), a pupil of Liu Tsung-chou and the last important figure in Sung–Ming
Neo-Confucianism, extensively studied the movement and wrote essential works on
it.
neo-Kantianism, the
diverse Kantian movement that emerged within German philosophy in the 1860s,
gained a strong academic foothold in the 1870s, reached its height during the
three decades prior to World War I, and disappeared with the rise of Nazism.
The movement was initially focused on renewed study and elaboration of Kant’s
epistemology in response to the growing epistemic authority of the natural
sciences and as an alternative to both Hegelian and speculative idealism and
the emerging materialism of, ong others, Ludwig Büchner (1824–99). Later
neo-Kantianism explored Kant’s whole philosophy, applied his critical method to
disciplines other than the natural sciences, and developed its own
philosophical systems. Some originators and/or early contributors were Kuno
Fischer (1824–1907), Hermann von Helmholtz (1821–94), Friedrich Albert Lange
(1828–75), Eduard Zeller (1814–1908), and Otto Liebmann (1840–1912), whose Kant
und die Epigonen (1865) repeatedly stated what bece a neoKantian motto, “Back
to Kant!” Several forms of neo-Kantianism are to be distinguished. T. K.
Oesterreich (1880–1949), in Friedrich Ueberwegs Grundriss der Geschichte der
Philosophie (“F.U.’s Compendium of the History of Philosophy,” 1923), developed
the standard, somewhat chronological, classification: (1) The physiological
neo-Kantianism of Helmholtz and Lange, who claimed that physiology is
“developed or corrected Kantianism.” (2) The metaphysical neo-Kantianism of the
later Liebmann, who argued for a Kantian “critical metaphysics” (beyond
epistemology) in the form of “hypotheses” about the essence of things. (3) The
realist neo-Kantianism of Alois Riehl (1844–1924), who emphasized the real
existence of Kant’s thing-in-itself. (4) The logistic-methodological
neo-Kantianism of the Marburg School of Hermann Cohen (1842–1918) and Paul
Natorp (1854–1924). (5) The axiological neo-Kantianism of the Baden or
Southwest German School of Windelband (1848–1915) and Heinrich Rickert
(1863–1936). (6) The relativistic neo-Kantianism of Georg Simmel (1858–1918),
who argued for Kantian categories relative to individuals and cultures. (7) The
psychological neo-Kantianism of Leonard Nelson (1882–1927), originator of the
Göttingen School; also known as the neo-Friesian School, after Jakob Friedrich
Fries (1773–1843), Nelson’s self-proclaimed precursor. Like Fries, Nelson held
that Kantian a priori principles cannot be transcendentally justified, but can
be discovered only through introspection. Oesterreich’s classification has been
narrowed or modified, partly because of conflicting views on how distinctly
“Kantian” a philosopher must have been to be called “neo-Kantian.” The very
term ‘neo-Kantianism’ has even been called into question, as suggesting real
intellectual commonality where little or none is to be found. There is,
however, growing consensus that Marneo-Euclidean geometry neo-Kantianism
603 603 burg and Baden neo-Kantianism
were the most important and influential. Marburg School. Its founder, Cohen,
developed its characteristic Kantian idealism of the natural sciences by
arguing that physical objects are truly known only through the laws of these
sciences and that these laws presuppose the application of Kantian a priori principles
and concepts. Cohen elaborated this idealism by eliminating Kant’s dualism of
sensibility and understanding, claiming that space and time are construction
methods of “pure thought” rather than a priori forms of perception and that the
notion of any “given” (perceptual data) prior to the “activity” of “pure
thought” is meaningless. Accordingly, Cohen reformulated Kant’s thing-in-itself
as the regulative idea that the mathematical description of the world can
always be improved. Cohen also emphasized that “pure thought” refers not to
individual consciousess – on his account Kant had not yet sufficiently left
behind a “subject–object” epistemology – but rather to the content of his own
system of a priori principles, which he saw as subject to change with the
progress of science. Just as Cohen held that epistemology must be based on the
“fact of science,” he argued, in a decisive step beyond Kant, that ethics must
transcendentally deduce both the moral law and the ideal moral subject from a
humanistic science – more specifically, from jurisprudence’s notion of the
legal person. This analysis led to the view that the moral law demands that all
institutions, including economic enterprises, become democratic – so that they
display unified wills and intentions as transcendental conditions of the legal
person – and that all individuals become colegislators. Thus Cohen arrived at
his frequently cited claim that Kant “is the true and real originator of German
socialism.” Other important Marburg Kantians were Cohen’s colleague Natorp,
best known for his studies on Plato and philosophy of education, and their
students Karl Vorländer (1860–1928), who focused on Kantian socialist ethics as
a corrective of orthodox Marxism, and Ernst Cassirer (1874–1945). Baden School.
The basic task of philosophy and its transcendental method is seen as
identifying universal values that make possible culture in its varied
expressions. This focus is evident in Windelband’s influential insight that the
natural sciences seek to formulate general laws – nomothetic knowledge – while
the historical sciences seek to describe unique events – idiographic knowledge.
This distinction is based on the values (interests) of mastery of nature and
understanding and reliving the unique past in order to affirm our
individuality. Windelband’s view of the historical sciences as idiographic
raised the problem of selection central to his successor Rickert’s writings:
How can historians objectively determine which individual events are
historically significant? Rickert argued that this selection must be based on
the values that are generally recognized within the cultures under
investigation, not on the values of historians themselves. Rickert also
developed the transcendental argument that the objectivity of the historical
sciences necessitates the assumption that the generally recognized values of
different cultures approximate in various degrees universally valid values.
This argument was rejected by Weber, whose methodological work was greatly
indebted to Rickert.
Neoplatonism, that period
of Platonism following on the new impetus provided by the philosophical
speculations of Plotinus (A.D. 204–69). It extends, as a minimum, to the
closing of the Platonic School in Athens by Justinian in 529, but maximally
through Byzantium, with such figures as Michael Psellus (1018–78) and Pletho
(c.1360–1452), the Renaissance (Ficino, Pico, and the Florentine Academy), and
the early modern period (the Cbridge Platonists, Thomas Taylor), to the advent
of the “scientific” study of the works of Plato with Schleiermacher (1768–1834)
at the beginning of the nineteenth century. The term was formerly also used to
characterize the whole period from the Old Academy of Plato’s immediate
successors, Speusippus and Xenocrates, through what is now termed Middle
Platonism (c.80 B.C.–A.D. 220), down to Plotinus. This account confines itself
to the “minimum” interpretation. Neoplatonism proper may be divided into three
main periods: that of Plotinus and his immediate followers (third century); the
“Syrian” School of Iblichus and his followers (fourth century); and the
“Athenian” School begun by Plutarch of Athens, and including Syrianus, Proclus,
and their successors, down to Dascius (fifth–sixth centuries). Plotinus and his
school. Plotinus’s innovations in Platonism (developed in his essays, the
Enneads, collected and edited by his pupil Porphyry after his death), are
mainly two: (a) above Neoplatonism Neoplatonism 604 604 the traditional supreme principle of
earlier Platonism (and Aristotelianism), a self-thinking intellect, which was
also regarded as true being, he postulated a principle superior to intellect
and being, totally unitary and simple (“the One”); (b) he saw reality as a
series of levels (One, Intelligence, Soul), each higher one outflowing or
radiating into the next lower, while still remaining unaffected in itself, and
the lower ones fixing themselves in being by somehow “reflecting back” upon
their priors. This eternal process gives the universe its existence and character.
Intelligence operates in a state of non-temporal simultaneity, holding within
itself the “forms” of all things. Soul, in turn, generates time, and receives
the forms into itself as “reason principles” (logoi). Our physical
three-dimensional world is the result of the lower aspect of Soul (nature)
projecting itself upon a kind of negative field of force, which Plotinus calls
“matter.” Matter has no positive existence, but is simply the receptacle for
the unfolding of Soul in its lowest aspect, which projects the forms in
three-dimensional space. Plotinus often speaks of matter as “evil” (e.g.
Enneads II.8), and of the Soul as suffering a “fall” (e.g. Enneads V.1, 1), but
in fact he sees the whole cosmic process as an inevitable result of the
superabundant productivity of the One, and thus “the best of all possible
worlds.” Plotinus was himself a mystic, but he arrived at his philosophical
conclusions by perfectly logical means, and he had not much use for either
traditional religion or any of the more recent superstitions. His immediate
pupils, elius (c.225–90) and Porphyry (234–c.305), while somewhat more
hospitable to these, remained largely true to his philosophy (though elius had
a weakness for triadic elaborations in metaphysics). Porphyry was to have wide
influence, both in the Latin West (through such men as Marius Victorinus,
Augustine, and Boethius), and in the Greek East (and even, through
translations, on medieval Isl), as the founder of the Neoplatonic tradition of
commentary on both Plato and Aristotle, but it is mainly as an expounder of
Plotinus’s philosophy that he is known. He added little that is distinctive,
though that little is currently becoming better appreciated. Iblichus and the
Syrian School. Iblichus (c.245–325), descendant of an old Syrian noble fily,
was a pupil of Porphyry’s, but dissented from him on various important issues.
He set up his own school in Apea in Syria, and attracted many pupils. One chief
point of dissent was the role of theurgy (really just magic, with philosophical
underpinnings, but not unlike Christian sacrental theology). Iblichus claimed,
as against Porphyry, that philosophical reasoning alone could not attain the
highest degree of enlightenment, without the aid of theurgic rites, and his
view on this was followed by all later Platonists. He also produced a
metaphysical scheme far more elaborate than Plotinus’s, by a Scholastic filling
in, normally with systems of triads, of gaps in the “chain of being” left by
Plotinus’s more fluid and dynic approach to philosophy. For instance, he
postulated two Ones, one completely transcendent, the other the source of all
creation, thus “resolving” a tension in Plotinus’s metaphysics. Iblichus was
also concerned to fit as many of the traditional gods as possible into his system,
which later attracted the attention of the Emperor Julian, who based himself on
Iblichus when attempting to set up a Hellenic religion to rival Christianity, a
project which, however, died with him in 363. The Athenian School. The precise
links between the pupils of Iblichus and Plutarch (d.432), founder of the
Athenian School, remain obscure, but the Athenians always retained a great
respect for the Syrian. Plutarch himself is a dim figure, but Syrianus
(c.370–437), though little of his writings survives, can be seen from constant
references to him by his pupil Proclus (412– 85) to be a major figure, and the
source of most of Proclus’s metaphysical elaborations. The Athenians
essentially developed and systematized further the doctrines of Iblichus, creating
new levels of divinity (e.g. intelligibleintellectual gods, and “henads” in the
realm of the One – though they rejected the two Ones), this process reaching
its culmination in the thought of the last head of the Athenian Academy,
Dascius (c.456–540). The drive to systematize reality and to objectivize
concepts, exhibited most dratically in Proclus’s Elements of Theology, is a
lasting legacy of the later Neoplatonists, and had a significant influence on
the thought, ong others, of Hegel.
neo-Scholasticism, the
movement given impetus Neoplatonism, Islic neo-Scholasticism 605 605 by Pope Leo XIII’s encyclical Aeterni
Patris (1879), which, while stressing Aquinas, was a general recommendation of
the study of medieval Scholasticism as a source for the solution of vexing
modern problems. Leo assumed that there was a doctrine common to Aquinas,
Bonaventure, Albertus Magnus, and Duns Scotus, and that Aquinas was a
preeminent spokesman of the common view. Maurice De Wulf employed the phrase
‘perennial philosophy’ to designate this common medieval core as well as what
of Scholasticism is relevant to later times. Historians like Mandonnet,
Grabmann, and Gilson soon contested the idea that there was a single medieval
doctrine and drew attention to the profound differences between the great
medieval masters. The discussion of Christian philosophy precipitated by
Brehier in 1931 generated a variety of suggestions as to what medieval thinkers
and later Christian philosophers have in common, but this was quite different
from the assumption of Aeterni Patris. The pedagogical directives of this and
later encyclicals brought about a revival of Thomism rather than of
Scholasticism, generally in seminaries, ecclesiastical colleges, and Catholic
universities. Louvain’s Higher Institute of Philosophy under the direction of
Cardinal Mercier and its Revue de Philosophie Néoscolastique were ong the first
fruits of the Thomistic revival. The studia generalia of the Dominican order
continued at a new pace, the Saulchoir publishing the Revue thomiste. In
graduate centers in Milan, Madrid, Latin erica, Paris, and Rome, men were
trained for the task of teaching in colleges and seminaries, and scholarly
research began to flourish as well. The Leonine edition of the writings of Aquinas
was soon joined by new critical editions of Bonaventure, Duns Scotus, and Ockh,
as well as Albertus Magnus. Medieval studies in the broader sense gained from
the quest for manuscripts and the growth of paleography and codicology. Besides
the historians mentioned above, Jacques Maritain (1882–1973), a layman and
convert to Catholicism, did much both in his native France and in the United
States to promote the study of Aquinas. The Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval
Studies at Toronto, with Gilson regularly and Maritain frequently in residence,
bece a source of college and university teachers in Canada and the United
States, as Louvain and, in Rome, the Jesuit Gregorianum and the Dominican
Angelicum already were. In the 1940s ericans took doctorates in theology and
philosophy at Laval in Quebec and soon the influence of Charles De Koninck was
felt. Jesuits at St. Louis University began to publish The Modern Schoolman,
Dominicans in Washington The Thomist, and the erican Catholic Philosophical
Association The New Scholasticism. The School of Philosophy at Catholic
University, long the primary domestic source of professors and scholars, was
complemented by graduate progrs at St. Louis, Georgetown, Notre De, Fordh, and
Marquette. In the golden period of the Thomistic revival in the United States,
from the 1930s until the end of the Vatican Council II in 1965, there were
varieties of Thomism based on the variety of views on the relation between
philosophy and science. By the 1960s Thomistic philosophy was a prominent part
of the curriculum of all Catholic colleges and universities. By 1970, it had
all but disappeared under the mistaken notion that this was the intent of
Vatican II. This had the effect of releasing Aquinas into the wider
philosophical world.
Neo-Taoism, in Chinese,
hsüan-hsüeh (‘Profound Learning’, ‘Mysterious Learning’, or ‘Dark Learning’), a
broad, multifaceted revival of Taoist learning that dominated Chinese
philosophy from the third to the sixth century A.D. Literally ‘dark red’, hsüan
is used in the Lao Tzu (Tao Te Ching) to describe the sublime mystery of the
tao. Historically, hsüan-hsüeh formed a major topic of “Pure Conversation”
(ch’ing-t’an), where scholars in a time of political upheaval sought to arrest
the perceived decline of the tao. When the Wei dynasty replaced the Han in A.D.
220, a first wave of Neo-Taoist philosophers represented by Ho Yen (c.190–249)
and Wang Pi (226–49) radically reinterpreted the classical heritage to bring to
light its profound meaning. The Confucian orthodoxy – as distinguished from the
original teachings of Confucius – was deemed ineffectual and an obstacle to
renewal. One of the most important debates in Profound Learning – the debate on
“words and meaning” – criticizes Han scholarship for its literal imagination
and confronts the question of interpretation. Words are necessary but not
sufficient for understanding. The ancient sages had a unified view of the Tao,
articulated most clearly in the I-Ching, Lao Tzu, and Chuang Tzu, but distorted
by Han scholars. Most Neo-Taoists concentrated on these “Three Profound
Treatises” (san-hsüan). Wang Pi is best known for his commentaries on the
I-Ching and the Lao Tzu; and Kuo Hsiang (d.312), another Neo-Taoism Neo-Taoism
606 606 leading Neo-Taoist, is
arguably the most important Chuang Tzu commentator in Chinese history. The tao
is the source of all being, but against identifying the tao with a creator
“heaven” or an original “vital energy” (ch’i), Wang Pi argues that being
originates from “non-being” (wu). The concept of non-being, taken from the Lao
Tzu, brings out the transcendence of the tao. Neless and without form, the tao
as such can be described only negatively as wu, literally “not having” any
characteristics. In contrast, for Kuo Hsiang, non-being does not explain the
origin of being because, as entirely conceptual, it cannot create anything. If
non-being cannot bring forth being, and if the idea of a creator remains
problematic, the only alternative is to regard the created order as coming into
existence spontaneously. This implies that being is eternal. Particular beings
can be traced to contingent causes, but ultimately the origin of being can be
understood only in terms of a process of “selftransformation.” Chinese sources
often contrast Wang Pi’s “valuing non-being” (kuei-wu) with Kuo Hsiang’s
“exaltation of being” (ch’ung-yu). In ethics and politics, Wang stresses that
the tao is manifest in nature as constant principles (li). This is what the
classics mean by tzu-jan, naturalness or literally what is of itself so. The
hierarchical structure of sociopolitical relations also has a basis in the
order of nature. While Wang emphasizes unity, Kuo Hsiang chpions diversity. The
principle of nature dictates that everyone has a particular “share” of vital
energy, the creative power of the tao that determines one’s physical,
intellectual, and moral capacity. Individual differences ought to be accepted,
but do not warrant value discrimination. Each individual is in principle
complete in his/her own way, and constitutes an indispensable part in a larger
whole. Taoist ethics thus consists in being true to oneself, and nourishing
one’s nature. In government, naturalness finds expression in non-action
(wu-wei), which may be contrasted with Legalist policies emphasizing punishment
and control. For Wang Pi, wu-wei aims at preserving the natural order so that
the myriad things can flourish. Practically, it involves the elimination of
willful intervention and a return to “emptiness and quiescence”; i.e., freedom
from the dictates of desire and a life of guileless simplicity. Not to be
confused with total inaction, according to Kuo Hsiang, wu-weisignifies a mode
of being that fully uses one’s natural endowment. When one is guided by
inherent moral principles, there is no place for artificiality or
self-deception in the Taoist way of life. Ethical purity does not entail
renunciation. Though the sage finds himself along the corridors of power, he
safeguards his nature and remains empty of desire. In government, the sage
ruler naturally reduces arbitrary restrictions, adjusts policies to suit
changing needs, identifies the right people for office, and generally creates
an environment in which all under heaven can dwell in peace and realize their
potential. Ho Yen died a victim of political intrigue, at the close of the
Cheng-shih reign period (240–49) of the Wei dynasty. Wang Pi died later in the
se year. Historians refer to “Cheng-shih hsüanhsüeh” to mark the first phase of
Neo-Taoism. Later, political power was controlled by the Ssuma fily, who
eventually founded the Chin dynasty in A.D. 265. During the Wei–Chin
transition, a group of intellectuals, the “Seven Worthies of the Bboo Grove,”
ce to represent the voice of Profound Learning. ong them, Hsi K’ang (223–62),
Juan Chi (210–63), and Hsiang Hsiu (c.227–80) are of particular interest to
philosophy. In different ways, they look to naturalness as a basis for renewal.
Debates in Profound Learning often revolve around the relationship between
“orthodox teachings” (ming-chiao) and tzu-jan. For Wang Pi and Kuo Hsiang,
government and society should ideally conform to nature. Both Hsi K’ang and
Juan Chi found ming-chiao impinging on naturalness. This also gave impetus to
the development of a counterculture. Central to this is the place of emotion in
the ethical life. Ho Yen is credited with the view that sages are without
emotions (ch’ing), whose exceptional ch’i-endowment translates into a purity of
being that excludes emotional disturbance. Hsi K’ang also values dispassion,
and Hsiang Hsiu urges putting passion under the rule of ritual; but many
appreciated strong emotion as a sign of authenticity, which often contravened
orthodox teachings. As Pure Conversation gained currency, it bece fashionable
to give free rein to one’s impulses; and many hoped to establish a reputation
by opposing orthodoxy. The debate on naturalness raises the further question of
talent or capacity (ts’ai) and its relationship to human nature (hsing). In
Profound Learning, four distinct positions have been proposed: that talent and
nature are identical (t’ung); different (i); harmonious (ho); and separate
(li). This is important because the right talent must be identified to serve
political ends. In the early fourth century, the Chin dynasty had to flee its
capital and rebuild in south China. As the literati resettled, they looked back
to the Neo-Taoism Neo-Taoism 607 607
time of Ho Yen and Wang Pi as the golden age of Profound Learning. Although
Pure Conversation continued with undiminished vigor, it did not introduce many
new ideas. As it entered its last phase, another Taoist work, the Lieh-tzu, ce
to rival the “Three Profound Treatises.” Chang Chan (c.330–400) wrote an
important commentary on the work, which not only recapitulated many of the
ideas that spanned the spectrum of Neo-Taoist philosophy but also borrowed
Buddhist ideas. From the fourth century onward, Buddhist masters frequently
engaged in Pure Conversation and challenged hsüan-hsüeh scholars at their own
ge.
BUDDHISM, CHINESE
LEGALISM, CHINESE PHILOSOPHY. A.K.L.C. Neo-Thomism, a philosophical-theological
movement in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries manifesting a revival of
interest in Aquinas. It was stimulated by Pope Leo XIII’s encyclical Aeterni
Patris (1879) calling for a renewed emphasis on the teaching of Thomistic
principles to meet the intellectual and social challenges of modernity. The
movement reached its peak in the 1950s, though its influence continues to be
seen in organizations such as the erican Catholic Philosophical Association.
ong its major figures are Joseph Kleutgen, Désiré Mercier, Joseph Maréchal,
Pierre Rousselot, Réginald Garrigou-LaGrange, Martin Grabmann, M.-D. Chenu,
Jacques Maritain, Étienne Gilson, Yves R. Simon, Josef Pieper, Karl Rahner,
Cornelio Fabro, Emerich Coreth, Bernard Lonergan, and W. Norris Clarke. Few, if
any, of these figures have described themselves as NeoThomists; some explicitly
rejected the designation. Neo-Thomists have little in common except their
commitment to Aquinas and his relevance to the contemporary world. Their
interest produced a more historically accurate understanding of Aquinas and his
contribution to medieval thought (Grabmann, Gilson, Chenu), including a
previously ignored use of the Platonic metaphysics of participation (Fabro). This
richer understanding of Aquinas, as forging a creative synthesis in the midst
of competing traditions, has made arguing for his relevance easier. Those
Neo-Thomists who were suspicious of modernity produced fresh readings of
Aquinas’s texts applied to contemporary problems (Pieper, Gilson). Their
influence can be seen in the revival of virtue theory and the work of Alasdair
MacIntyre. Others sought to develop Aquinas’s thought with the aid of later
Thomists (Maritain, Simon) and incorporated the interpretations of
Counter-Reformation Thomists, such as Cajetan and Jean Poinsot, to produce more
sophisticated, and controversial, accounts of the intelligence, intentionality,
semiotics, and practical knowledge. Those Neo-Thomists willing to engage modern
thought on its own terms interpreted modern philosophy sympathetically using
the principles of Aquinas (Maréchal, Lonergan, Clarke), seeking dialogue rather
than confrontation. However, some readings of Aquinas are so thoroughly
integrated into modern philosophy that they can seem assimilated (Rahner,
Coreth); their highly individualized metaphysics inspired as much by other
philosophical influences, especially Heidegger, as Aquinas. Some of the labels
currently used ong Neo-Thomists suggest a division in the movement over
critical, postKantian methodology. ‘Existential Thomism’ is used for those who
emphasize both the real distinction between essence and existence and the role
of the sensible in the mind’s first grasp of being. ‘Transcendental Thomism’
applies to figures like Maréchal, Rousselot, Rahner, and Coreth who rely upon
the inherent dynism of the mind toward the real, rooted in Aquinas’s theory of
the active intellect, from which to deduce their metaphysics of being. AQUINAS, GILSON, MARITAIN, MERCIER, THOMISM.
D.W.H. Neumann, John von.VON NEUMANN. neural net.CONNECTIONISM. neural network
modeling.CONNECTIONISM. Neurath, Otto.VIENNA CIRCLE.
neurophilosophy.CHURCHLAND, PATRICIA. neuroscience.COGNITIVE SCIENCE. neustic.
PRESCRIPTIVISM.
neutrality.LIBERALISM. neutral monism.PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. New Academy, the ne
given the Academy, the school founded by Plato in Athens, during the time it
was controlled by Academic Skeptics after about 265 B.C. Its principal leaders
in this period were Arcesilaus (315–242) and Carneades (219– 129); our most
accessible source for the New Academy is Cicero’s Academica. A master of
logical techniques such as sorites Neo-Thomism New Academy 608 608 (which he learned from Diodorus), Arcesilaus
attempted to revive the dialectic of Plato, using it to achieve the suspension
of belief he learned to value from Pyrrho. Later, and especially under the
leadership of Carneades, the New Academy developed a special relationship with
Stoicism: as the Stoics found new ways to defend their doctrine of the
criterion, Carneades found new ways to refute it in the Stoics’ own terms.
Carneades’ visit to Rome in 155 B.C. with a Stoic and a Peripatetic marks the
beginning of Rome’s interest in Greek philosophy. His anti-Stoic arguments were
recorded by his successor Clitomachus (d. c.110 B.C.), whose work is known to
us through summaries in Cicero. Clitomachus was succeeded by Philo of Larisa
(c.160–79 B.C.), who was the teacher of Antiochus of Ascalon (c.130–c.67 B.C.).
Philo later attempted to reconcile the Old and the New Academy by softening the
Skepticism of the New and by fostering a Skeptical reading of Plato. Angered by
this, Antiochus broke away in about 87 B.C. to found what he called the Old
Academy, which is now considered to be the beginning of Middle Platonism.
Probably about the se time, Aenesidemus (dates unknown) revived the strict
Skepticism of Pyrrho and founded the school that is known to us through the
work of Sextus Empiricus. Academic Skepticism differed from Pyrrhonism in its sharp
focus on Stoic positions, and possibly in allowing for a weak assent (as
opposed to belief, which they suspended) in what is probable; and Pyrrhonians
accused Academic Skeptics of being dogmatic in their rejection of the
possibility of knowledge. The New Academy had a major influence on the
development of modern philosophy, most conspicuously through Hume, who
considered that his brand of mitigated skepticism belonged to this school. ACADEMY, ISLIC NEOPLATONISM, SKEPTICS. P.Wo.
Newcomb’s paradox, a conflict between two widely accepted principles of
rational decision, arising in the following decision problem, known as
Newcomb’s problem. Two boxes are before you. The first contains either
$1,000,000 or nothing. The second contains $1,000. You may take the first box
alone or both boxes. Someone with uncanny foresight has predicted your choice
and fixed the content of the first box according to his prediction. If he has
predicted that you will take only the first box, he has put $1,000,000 in that
box; and if he has predicted that you will take both boxes, he has left the
first box empty. The expected utility of an option is commonly obtained by
multiplying the utility of its possible outcomes by their probabilities given
the option, and then adding the products. Because the predictor is reliable,
the probability that you receive $1,000,000 given that you take only the first
box is high, whereas the probability that you receive $1,001,000 given that you
take both boxes is low. Accordingly, the expected utility of taking only the
first box is greater than the expected utility of taking both boxes. Therefore
the principle of maximizing expected utility says to take only the first box.
However, the principle of dominance says that if the states determining the outcomes
of options are causally independent of the options, and there is one option
that is better than the others in each state, then you should adopt it. Since
your choice does not causally influence the contents of the first box, and
since choosing both boxes yields $1,000 in addition to the contents of the
first box whatever they are, the principle says to take both boxes. Newcomb’s
paradox is ned after its formulator, Willi Newcomb. Nozick publicized it in
“Newcomb’s Problem and Two Principles of Choice” (1969). Many theorists have
responded to the paradox by changing the definition of the expected utility of
an option so that it is sensitive to the causal influence of the option on the
states that determine its outcome, but is insensitive to the evidential bearing
of the option on those states.
Newman, John Henry
(1801–90), English prelate and philosopher of religion. As fellow at Oriel
College, Oxford, he was a prominent member of the Anglican Oxford Movement. He
bece a Roman Catholic in 1845, took holy orders in 1847, and was made a
cardinal in 1879. His most important philosophical work is the Grmar of Assent
(1870). Here Newman explored the difference between formal reasoning and the
informal or natural movement of the mind in discerning the truth about the
concrete and historical. Concrete reasoning in the mode of natural inference is
implicit and unreflective; it deals not with general principles as such but
with their employment in particular circumstances. Thus a scientist must judge
whether the phenomenon he confronts is a novel significant datum, a
coincidence, or merely an insignificant variation in the data. The acquired
capacity to make judgments of Newcomb’s paradox Newman, John Henry 609 609 this sort Newman called the illative
sense, an intellectual skill shaped by experience and personal insight and
generally limited for individuals to particular fields of endeavor. The
illative sense makes possible a judgment of certitude about the matter
considered, even though the formal argument that partially outlines the process
possesses only objective probability for the novice. Hence probability is not
necessarily opposed to certitude. In becoming aware of its tacit dimension,
Newman spoke of recognizing a mode of informal inference. He distinguished such
reasoning, which, by virtue of the illative sense, culminates in a judgment of
certitude about the way things are (real assent), from formal reasoning
conditioned by the certainty or probability of the premises, which assents to
the conclusion thus conditioned (notional assent). In real assent, the
proposition functions to “image” the reality, to make its reality present. In
the Development of Christian Doctrine (1845), Newman analyzed the ways in which
some ideas unfold themselves only through historical development, within a
tradition of inquiry. He sought to delineate the common pattern of such
development in politics, science, philosophy, and religion. Although his focal
interest was in how religious doctrines develop, he emphasizes the general
character of such a pattern of progressive articulation. F.J.C. New Realism, an
early twentieth-century revival, both in England and in the United States, of
various forms of realism in reaction to the dominant idealisms inherited from
the nineteenth century. In erica this revival took a cooperative form when six
philosophers (Ralph Barton Perry, Edwin Holt, Willi Pepperell Montague, Walter
Pitkin, Edward Spaulding, and Walter Marvin) published “A Progr and First
Platform of Six Realists” (1910), followed two years later by the cooperative
volume The New Realism, in which each authored an essay. This volume gave rise
to the designation ‘New Realists’ for these six philosophers. Although they
clearly disagreed on many particulars, they concurred on several matters of
philosophical style and epistemological substance. Procedurally they endorsed a
cooperative and piecemeal approach to philosophical problems, and they were
constitutionally inclined to a closeness of analysis that would prepare the way
for later philosophical tendencies. Substantively they agreed on several
epistemological stances central to the refutation of idealism. ong the
doctrines in the New Realist platform were the rejection of the fundental
character of epistemology; the view that the entities investigated in logic,
mathematics, and science are not “mental” in any ordinary sense; the view that
the things known are not the products of the knowing relation nor in any
fundental sense conditioned by their being known; and the view that the objects
known are immediately and directly present to consciousness while being
independent of that relation. New Realism was a version of direct realism,
which viewed the notions of mediation and representation in knowledge as
opening gbits on the slippery slope to idealism. Their refutation of idealism
focused on pointing out the fallacy of moving from the truism that every object
of knowledge is known to the claim that its being consists in its being known.
That we are obviously at the center of what we know entails nothing about the
nature of what we know. Perry dubbed this fact “the egocentric predicent,” and
supplemented this observation with arguments to the effect that the objects of
knowledge are in fact independent of the knowing relation. New Realism as a
version of direct realism had as its primary conceptual obstacle “the facts of
relativity,” i.e., error, illusion, perceptual variation, and valuation.
Dealing with these phenomena without invoking “mental intermediaries” proved to
be the stumbling block, and New Realism soon gave way to a second cooperative
venture by another group of erican philosophers that ce to be known as Critical
Realism. The term ‘new realism’ is also occasionally used with regard to those
British philosophers (principal ong them Moore and Russell) similarly involved
in refuting idealism. Although individually more significant than the erican
group, theirs was not a cooperative effort, so the group term ce to have
primarily an erican referent. CRITICAL
REALISM, IDEALISM, PERCEPTION. C.F.D. new riddle of induction.GRUE PARADOX. new
theory of reference.
Newton, Sir Isaac
(1642–1727), English physicist and mathematician, one of the greatest
scientists of all time. Born in Woolsthorpe, Lincolnshire, he attended Cbridge
University, receiving the B.A. in 1665; he bece a fellow of Trinity in New
Realism Newton, Sir Isaac 610 610 1667
and Lucasian Professor of Mathematics in 1669. He was elected fellow of the
Royal Society in 1671 and served as its president from 1703 until his death. In
1696 he was appointed warden of the mint. In his later years he was involved in
political and governmental affairs rather than in active scientific work. A
sensitive, secretive person, he was prone to irascibility – most notably in a
dispute with Leibniz over priority of invention of the calculus. His
unparalleled scientific accomplishments overshadow a deep and sustained
interest in ancient chronology, biblical study, theology, and alchemy. In his
early twenties Newton’s genius asserted itself in an astonishing period of
mathematical and experimental creativity. In the years 1664– 67, he discovered
the binomial theorem; the “method of fluxions” (calculus); the principle of the
composition of light; and fundentals of his theory of universal gravitation.
Newton’s masterpiece, Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (“The
Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy”), appeared in 1687. This work
sets forth the mathematical laws of physics and “the system of the world.” Its
exposition is modeled on Euclidean geometry: propositions are demonstrated
mathematically from definitions and mathematical axioms. The world system
consists of material bodies (masses composed of hard particles) at rest or in
motion and interacting according to three axioms or laws of motion: (1) Every
body continues in its state of rest or of uniform motion in a straight line
unless it is compelled to change that state by forces impressed upon it. (2)
The change of motion is proportional to the motive force impressed and is made in
the direction of the straight line in which that force is impressed. [Here, the
impressed force equals mass times the rate of change of velocity, i.e.,
acceleration. Hence the filiar formula, F % ma.] (3) To every action there is
always opposed an equal reaction; or, the mutual action of two bodies upon each
other is always equal and directed to contrary parts. Newton’s general law of
gravitation (in modern restatement) is: Every particle of matter attracts every
other particle with a force varying directly as the product of their masses and
inversely as the square of the distance between them. The statement of the laws
of motion is preceded by an equally fous scholium in which Newton enunciates
the ultimate conditions of his universal system: absolute time, space, place,
and motion. He speaks of these as independently existing “quantities” according
to which true measurements of bodies and motions can be made as distinct from
relative “sensible measures” and apparent observations. Newton seems to have thought
that his system of mathematical principles presupposed and is validated by the
absolute frework. The scholium has been the subject of much critical
discussion. The main problem concerns the justification of the absolute
frework. Newton commends adherence to experimental observation and induction
for advancing scientific knowledge, and he rejects speculative hypotheses. But
absolute time and space are not observable. (In the scholium Newton did offer a
renowned experiment using a rotating pail of water as evidence for
distinguishing true and apparent motions and proof of absolute motion.) It has
been remarked that conflicting strains of a rationalism (anticipating Kant) and
empiricism (anticipating Hume) are present in Newton’s conception of science. Some
of these issues are also evident in Newton’s Optics (1704, especially the
fourth edition, 1730), which includes a series of suggestive “Queries” on the
nature of light, gravity, matter, scientific method, and God. The triumphant
reception given to Newton’s Principia in England and on the Continent led to
idealization of the man and his work. Thus Alexander Pope’s fous epitaph:
Nature and Nature’s laws lay hid in night; God said, “Let Newton be!” and all
was light. The term ‘Newtonian’, then, denoted the view of nature as a
universal system of mathematical reason and order divinely created and
administered. The metaphor of a “universal machine” was frequently applied. The
view is central in the eighteenth-century Enlightenment, inspiring a religion
of reason and the scientific study of society and the human mind. More
narrowly, ‘Newtonian’ suggests a reduction of any subject matter to an ontology
of individual particles and the laws and basic terms of mechanics: mass,
length, and time. FIELD THEORY, PHILOSOPHY
OF SCIENCE, QUANTUM MECHANICS, SPACE, TIME. H.S.T. Newtonian.NEWTON. Newton,
Sir Isaac Newtonian 611 611 Nicholas
Kryfts.NICHOLAS OF CUSA. Nicholas of Autrecourt (c.1300–after 1350), French
philosopher and theologian. Born in Autrecourt, he was educated at Paris and
earned bachelor’s degrees in theology and law and a master’s degree in arts.
After a list of propositions from his writings was condemned in 1346, he was
sentenced to burn his works publicly and recant, which he did in Paris the
following year. He was appointed dean of Metz cathedral in 1350. Nicholas’s
ecclesiastical troubles arose partly from nine letters (two of which survive)
which reduce to absurdity the view that appearances provide a sufficient basis
for certain and evident knowledge. On the contrary, except for “certitude of
the faith,” we can be certain only of what is equivalent or reducible to the
principle of noncontradiction. He accepts as a consequence of this that we can
never validly infer the existence of one distinct thing from another, including
the existence of substances from qualities, or causes from effects. Indeed, he
finds that “in the whole of his natural philosophy and metaphysics, Aristotle
had such [evident] certainty of scarcely two conclusions, and perhaps not even
of one.” Nicholas devotes another work, the Exigit ordo executionis (also known
as The Universal Treatise), to an extended critique of Aristotelianism. It
attacks what seemed to him the blind adherence given by his contemporaries to
Aristotle and Averroes, showing that the opposite of many conclusions alleged
to have been demonstrated by the Philosopher – e.g., on the divisibility of
continua, the reality of motion, and the truth of appearances – are just as
evident or apparent as those conclusions themselves. Because so few of his
writings are extant, however, it is difficult to ascertain just what Nicholas’s
own views were. Likewise, the reasons for his condemnation are not well
understood, although recent studies have suggested that his troubles might have
been due to a reaction to certain ideas that he appropriated from English
theologians, such as Ad de Wodeh. Nicholas’s views elicited comment not only
from church authorities, but also from other philosophers, including Buridan,
Marsilius of Inghen, Albert of Saxony, and Nicholas of Oresme. Despite a few
surface similarities, however, there is no evidence that his teachings on
certainty or causality had any influence on modern philosophers, such as
Descartes or Hume. .
Nicholas of Cusa, also
called Nicolaus Cusanus, Nicholas Kryfts (1401–64), German philosopher, an
important Renaissance Platonist. Born in Kues on the Moselle, he earned a
doctorate in canon law in 1423. He bece known for his De concordantia
catholica, written at the Council of Basel in 1432, a work defending the
conciliarist position against the pope. Later, he decided that only the pope
could provide unity for the church in its negotiations with the East, and
allied himself with the papacy. In 1437–38, returning from a papal legation to
Constantinople, he had his fous insight into the coincidence of opposites
(coincidentia oppositorum) in the infinite, upon which his On Learned Ignorance
is based. His unceasing labor was chiefly responsible for the Vienna Concordat
with the Eastern church in 1448. He was made cardinal in 1449 as a reward for
his efforts, and bishop of Brixen (Bressanone) in 1450. He traveled widely in
Germany as a papal legate (1450–52) before settling down in his see. Cusa’s
central insight was that all oppositions are united in their infinite measure,
so that what would be logical contradictions for finite things coexist without
contradiction in God, who is the measure of (i.e., is the form or essence of)
all things, and identical to them inasmuch as he is identical with their
reality, quiddity, or essence. Considered as it is contracted to the
individual, a thing is only an image of its measure, not a reality in itself.
His position drew on mathematical models, arguing, for instance, that an
infinite straight line tangent to a circle is the measure of the curved
circumference, since a circle of infinite dieter, containing all the being
possible in a circle, would coincide with the tangent. In general, the measure
of a thing must contain all the possible being of that sort of thing, and so is
infinite, or unlimited, in its being. Cusa attacked Aristotelians for their
unwillingness to give up the principle of non-contradiction. His epistemology
is a form of Platonic skepticism. Our knowledge is never of reality, the infinite
measure of things that is their essence, but only of finite images of reality
corresponding to the finite copies with which we must deal. These images are
constructed by our own minds, and do not represent an immediate grasp of any
reality. Their highest form is found in mathematics, and it is only through
mathematics that reason can understand the world. In relation to the infinite
real, these images and the contracted realities they enable us to know have
only an infinitesimal reality. Our knowledge is only a mass of conjectures,
i.e., assertions that are true insofar as Nicholas Kryfts Nicholas of Cusa
612 612 they capture some part of the
truth, but never the whole truth, the infinite measure, as it really is in
itself. Cusa was much read in the Renaissance, and is somethimes said to have
had significant influence on German thought of the eighteenth century, in
particular on Leibniz, and German idealism, but it is uncertain, despite the
considerable intrinsic merit of his thought, if this is true.
Nietzsche, Friedrich
Wilhelm (1844–1900), German philosopher and cultural critic. Born in a small
town in the Prussian province of Saxony, Nietzsche’s early education emphasized
religion and classical languages and literature. After a year at the university
at Bonn he transferred to Leipzig, where he pursued classical studies. There he
happened upon Schopenhauer’s The World as Will and Representation, which
profoundly influenced his subsequent concerns and early philosophical thinking.
It was as a classical philologist, however, that he was appointed professor at
the Swiss university at Basel, before he had even received his doctorate, at
the astonishingly early age of twenty-four. A mere twenty years of productive
life remained to him, ending with a mental and physical collapse in January
1889, from which he never recovered. He held his position at Basel for a
decade, resigning in 1879 owing to the deterioration of his health from
illnesses he had contracted in 1870 as a volunteer medical orderly in the Franco-Prussian
war. At Basel he lectured on a variety of subjects chiefly relating to
classical studies, including Greek and Roman philosophy as well as literature.
During his early years there he also bece intensely involved with the composer
Richard Wagner; and his fascination with Wagner was reflected in several of his
early works – most notably his first book, The Birth of Tragedy (1872), and his
subsequent essay Richard Wagner in Bayreuth (1876). His later break with
Wagner, culminating in his polemic The Case of Wagner(1888), was both profound
and painful to him. While at first regarding Wagner as a creative genius
showing the way to a cultural and spiritual renewal, Nietzsche ce to see him
and his art as epitomizing and exacerbating the fundental problem with which he
bece increasingly concerned. This problem was the pervasive intellectual and
cultural crisis Nietzsche later characterized in terms of the “death of God”
and the advent of “nihilism.” Traditional religious and metaphysical ways of
thinking were on the wane, leaving a void that modern science could not fill,
and endangering the health of civilization. The discovery of some
life-affirming alternative to Schopenhauer’s radically pessimistic response to
this disillusionment bece Nietzsche’s primary concern. In The Birth of Tragedy
he looked to the Greeks for clues and to Wagner for inspiration, believing that
their art held the key to renewed human flourishing for a humanity bereft both
of the consolations of religious faith and of confidence in reason and science
as substitutes for it. In his subsequent series of Untimely Meditations
(1873–76) he expanded upon his theme of the need to reorient human thought and
endeavor to this end, and criticized a variety of tendencies detrimental to it
that he discerned ong his contemporaries. Both the deterioration of Nietzsche’s
health and the shift of his interest away from his original discipline
prevented retention of his position at Basel. In the first years after his
retirement, he completed his transition from philologist to philosopher and
published the several parts of Human, All-Too-Human (1878–90), Daybreak (1881),
and the first four parts of The Gay Science (1882). These aphoristic writings
sharpened and extended his analytical and critical assessment of various human
tendencies and social, cultural, and intellectual phenomena. During this period
his thinking bece much more sophisticated; and he developed the philosophical
styles and concerns that found mature expression in the writings of the final
years of his brief active life, following the publication of the four parts of
Thus Spoke Zarathustra (1883–85). These last remarkably productive years saw
the appearance of Beyond Good and Evil (1886), a fifth part of The Gay Science,
On the Genealogy of Morals (1887), The Case of Wagner (1888), and a series of
prefaces to his earlier works (1886–87), as well as the completion of several
books published after his collapse – Twilight of the Idols (1889), The
Antichrist (1895), and Ecce Homo (1908). He was also assing a great deal of
material in notebooks, of which a selection was later published under the title
The Will to Power. (The status and significance of this mass of Nachlass
material are matters of continuing controversy.) In the early 1880s, when he
wrote Thus Spoke Zarathustra, Nietzsche arrived at a conception of human life
and possibility – and with it, of value and meaning – that he believed could
overcome the Schopenhauerian pessimism and nihilism that he saw as outcomes of
the collapse of traditional modes of religious and philosophical
interNietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm 613 613 pretation. He prophesied a period of
nihilism in the aftermath of their decline and fall; but this prospect deeply
distressed him. He was convinced of the untenability of the “God hypothesis,”
and indeed of all religious and metaphysical interpretations of the world and
ourselves; and yet he was well aware that the very possibility of the
affirmation of life was at stake, and required more than the mere abandonment
of all such “lies” and “fictions.” He took the basic challenge of philosophy
now to be to reinterpret life and the world along more tenable lines that would
also overcome nihilism. What Nietzsche called “the death of God” was both a
cultural event – the waning and impending demise of the “Christian-moral”
interpretation of life and the world – and also a philosophical development:
the abandonment of anything like the God-hypothesis (all demidivine absolutes
included). As a cultural event it was a phenomenon to be reckoned with, and a
source of profound concern; for he feared a “nihilistic rebound” in its wake,
and worried about the consequences for human life and culture if no
countermovement to it were forthcoming. As a philosophical development, on the
other hand, it was his point of departure, which he took to call for a radical
reconsideration of everything from life and the world and human existence and
knowledge to value and morality. The “de-deification of nature,” the “translation
of man back into nature,” the “revaluation of values,” the tracing of the
“genealogy of morals” and their critique, and the elaboration of “naturalistic”
accounts of knowledge, value, morality, and our entire “spiritual” nature thus
ce to be his main tasks. His published and unpublished writings contain a
wealth of remarks, observations, and suggestions contributing importantly to
them. It is a matter of controversy, even ong those with a high regard for
Nietzsche, whether he tried to work out positions on issues bearing any
resemblance to those occupying other philosophers before and after him in the
mainstre of the history of philosophy. He was harshly critical of most of his
predecessors and contemporaries; and he broke fundentally with them and their
basic ideas and procedures. His own writings, moreover, bear little resemblance
to those of most other philosophers. Those he himself published (as well as his
reflections in his notebooks) do not systematically set out and develop views.
Rather, they consist for the most part in collections of short paragraphs and
sets of aphorisms, often only loosely if at all connected. Many deal with
philosophical topics, but in very unconventional ways; and because his remarks
about these topics are scattered through many different works, they are all too
easily taken in isolation and misunderstood. On some topics, moreover, much of
what he wrote is found only in his very rough notebooks, which he filled with
thoughts without indicating the extent of his reflected commitment to them. His
language, furthermore, is by turns coolly analytical, heatedly polemical,
sharply critical, and highly metaphorical; and he seldom indicates clearly the
scope of his claims and what he means by his terms. It is not surprising, therefore,
that many philosophers have found it difficult to know what to make of him and
to take him seriously – and that some have taken him to repudiate altogether
the traditional philosophical enterprise of seeking reasoned conclusions with
respect to questions of the kind with which philosophers have long been
concerned, heralding the “death” not only of religious and metaphysical
thinking, but also of philosophy itself. Others read him very differently, as
having sought to effect a fundental reorientation of philosophical thinking,
and to indicate by both precept and exple how philosophical inquiry might
better be pursued. Those who regard Nietzsche in the former way take his
criticisms of his philosophical predecessors and contemporaries to apply to any
attempt to address such matters. They seize upon and construe some of his more
sweeping negative pronouncements on truth and knowledge as indicating that he
believed we can only produce fictions and merely expedient (or possibly
creative) perspectival expressions of our needs and desires, as groups or as
individuals. They thus take him as a radical nihilist, concerned to subvert the
entire philosophical enterprise and replace it with a kind of thinking more
akin to the literary exploration of human possibilities in the service of life
– a kind of artistic play liberated from concern with truth and knowledge.
Those who view him in the latter way, on the other hand, take seriously his
concern to find a way of overcoming the nihilism he believed to result from traditional
ways of thinking; his retention of recast notions of truth and knowledge; and
his evident concern – especially in his later writings – to contribute to the
comprehension of a broad range of phenomena. This way of understanding him,
like the former, remains controversial; but it permits an interpretation of his
writings that is philosophically more fruitful. Nietzsche indisputably insisted
upon the inter pretive character of all human thought; and he called for “new
philosophers” who would follow him in engaging in more self-conscious and
intellectually responsible attempts to assess and improve upon prevailing
interpretations of human life. He also was deeply concerned with how these
matters might better be evaluated, and with the values by which human beings
live and might better do so. Thus he made much of the need for a revaluation of
all received values, and for attention to the problems of the nature, status,
and standards of value and evaluation. One form of inquiry he took to be of
great utility in connection with both of these tasks is genealogical inquiry
into the conditions under which various modes of interpretation and evaluation
have arisen. It is only one of the kinds of inquiry he considered necessary in
both cases, however, serving merely to prepare for others that must be brought
to bear before any conclusions are warranted. Nietzsche further emphasized the
perspectival character of all thinking and the merely provisional character of
all knowing, rejecting the idea of the very possibility of absolute knowledge
transcending all perspectives. However, because he also rejected the idea that
things (and values) have absolute existence “in themselves” apart from the
relations in which he supposes their reality to consist, he held that, if viewed
in the multiplicity of perspectives from which various of these relations come
to light, they admit of a significant measure of comprehension. This
perspectivism thus does not exclude the possibility of any sort of knowledge
deserving of the ne, but rather indicates how it is to be conceived and
achieved. His kind of philosophy, which he characterizes as fröhliche
Wissenschaft (cheerful science), proceeds by way of a variety of such
“perspectival” approaches to the various matters with which he deals. Thus for
Nietzsche there is no “truth” in the sense of the correspondence of anything we
might think or say to “being,” and indeed no “true world of being” to which it
may even be imagined to fail to correspond; no “knowledge” conceived in terms
of any such truth and reality; and, further, no knowledge at all – even of
ourselves and the world of which we are a part – that is absolute,
non-perspectival, and certain. But that is not the end of the matter. There
are, e.g., ways of thinking that may be more or less well warranted in relation
to differing sorts of interest and practice, not only within the context of
social life but also in our dealings with our environing world. Nietzsche’s
reflections on the reconceptualization of truth and knowledge thus point in the
direction of a naturalistic epistemology that he would have replace the
conceptions of truth and knowledge of his predecessors, and fill the nihilistic
void seemingly left by their bankruptcy. There is, moreover, a good deal about
ourselves and our world that he bece convinced we can comprehend. Our
comprehension may be restricted to what life and the world show themselves to
be and involve in our experience; but if they are the only kind of reality,
there is no longer any reason to divorce the notions of truth, knowledge, and
value from them. The question then becomes how best to interpret and assess
what we find as we proceed to explore them. It is to these tasks of
interpretation and “revaluation” that Nietzsche devoted his main efforts in his
later writings. In speaking of the death of God, Nietzsche had in mind not only
the abandonment of the Godhypothesis (which he considered to be utterly
“unworthy of belief,” owing its invention and appeal entirely to naïveté,
error, all-too-human need, and ulterior motivation), but also the demise of all
metaphysical substitutes for it. He likewise criticized and rejected the
related postulations of substantial “souls” and self-contained “things,” taking
both notions to be ontological fictions merely reflecting our artificial
(though convenient) linguistic-conceptual shorthand for functionally unitary
products, processes, and sets of relations. In place of this cluster of
traditional ontological categories and interpretations, he conceived the world
in terms of an interplay of forces without any inherent structure or final end.
It ceaselessly organizes and reorganizes itself, as the fundental disposition
he called will to power gives rise to successive arrays of power relationships.
“This world is the will to power – and nothing besides,” he wrote; “and you
yourselves are also this will to power – and nothing besides!” Nietzsche’s idea
of the eternal return (or eternal recurrence) underscores this conception of a
world without beginning or end, in which things happen repeatedly in the way
they always have. He first introduced this idea as a test of one’s ability to
affirm one’s own life and the general character of life in this world as they
are, without reservation, qualification, or appeal to anything transcending
them. He later entertained the thought that all events might actually recur
eternally in exactly the se sequence, and experimented in his unpublished
writings with arguments to this effect. For the most part, however, he
restricted himself to less problematic
615 Neitzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm 616 uses
of the idea that do not presuppose its literal truth in this radical form. His
rhetorical embellishments and experimental elaborations of the idea may have
been intended to make it more vivid and compelling; but he employed it chiefly
to depict his conception of the radically non-linear character of events in
this world and their fundental homogeneity, and to provide a way of testing our
ability to live with it. If we are sufficiently strong and well disposed to
life to affirm it even on the supposition that it will only be the se sequence
of events repeated eternally, we have what it takes to endure and flourish in
the kind of world in which Nietzsche believed we find ourselves in the
aftermath of disillusionment. Nietzsche construed human nature and existence
naturalistically, in terms of the will to power and its rifications in the
establishment and expression of the kinds of complex systems of dynic quanta in
which human beings consist. “The soul is only a word for something about the
body,” he has Zarathustra say; and the body is fundentally a configuration of
natural forces and processes. At the se time, he insisted on the importance of
social arrangements and interactions in the development of human forms of
awareness and activity. He also emphasized the possibility of the emergence of
exceptional human beings capable of an independence and creativity elevating
them above the level of the general human rule. So he stressed the difference
between “higher men” and “the herd,” and through Zarathustra proclaimed the
Übermensch (‘overman’ or ‘superman’) to be “the meaning of the earth,”
employing this image to convey the ideal of the overcoming of the
“all-too-human” and the fullest possible creative “enhancement of life.” Far
from seeking to diminish our humanity by stressing our animality, he sought to
direct our efforts to the emergence of a “higher humanity” capable of endowing
existence with a human redemption and justification, above all through the
enrichment of cultural life. Notwithstanding his frequent characterization as a
nihilist, therefore, Nietzsche in fact sought to counter and overcome the
nihilism he expected to prevail in the aftermath of the collapse and abandonment
of traditional religious and metaphysical modes of interpretation and
evaluation. While he was highly critical of the latter, it was not his
intention merely to oppose them; for he further attempted to make out the
possibility of forms of truth and knowledge to which philosophical interpreters
of life and the world might aspire, and espoused a “Dionysian value-standard”
in place of all non-naturalistic modes of valuation. In keeping with his
interpretation of life and the world in terms of his conception of will to
power, Nietzsche fred this standard in terms of his interpretation of them. The
only tenable alternative to nihilism must be based upon a recognition and
affirmation of the world’s fundental character. This meant positing as a
general standard of value the attainment of a kind of life in which the will to
power as the creative transformation of existence is raised to its highest
possible intensity and qualitative expression. This in turn led him to take the
“enhancement of life” and creativity to be the guiding ideas of his revaluation
of values and development of a naturalistic value theory. This way of thinking
carried over into Nietzsche’s thinking about morality. Insisting that
moralities as well as other traditional modes of valuation ought to be assessed
“in the perspective of life,” he argued that most of them were contrary to the
enhancement of life, reflecting the all-too-human needs and weaknesses and
fears of less favored human groups and types. Distinguishing between “master”
and “slave” moralities, he found the latter to have become the dominant type of
morality in the modern world. He regarded present-day morality as a
“herd-animal morality,” well suited to the requirements and vulnerabilities of
the mediocre who are the human rule, but stultifying and detrimental to the
development of potential exceptions to that rule. Accordingly, he drew
attention to the origins and functions of this type of morality (as a
social-control mechanism and device by which the weak defend and avenge and assert
themselves against the actually or potentially stronger). He further suggested
the desirability of a “higher morality” for the exceptions, in which the
contrast of the basic “slave/herd morality” categories of “good and evil” would
be replaced by categories more akin to the “good and bad” contrast
characteristic of “master morality,” with a revised (and variable) content
better attuned to the conditions and attainable qualities of the enhanced forms
of life such exceptional human beings can achieve. The strongly creative flavor
of Nietzsche’s notions of such a “higher humanity” and associated “higher
morality” reflects his linkage of both to his conception of art, to which he
attached great importance. Art, for Nietzsche, is fundentally creative (rather
than cognitive), serving to prepare for the emergence of a sensi 616 bility and manner of life reflecting the
highest potentiality of human beings. Art, as the creative transformation of
the world as we find it (and of ourselves thereby) on a small scale and in
particular media, affords a glimpse of a kind of life that would be lived more
fully in this manner, and constitutes a step toward emergence. In this way,
Nietzsche’s mature thought thus expands upon the idea of the basic connection
between art and the justification of life that was his general theme in his
first major work, The Birth of Tragedy.
EXISTENTIALISM, HEGEL,
KANT, SCHOPENHAUER. R.Sc. Nihil est in intellectu quod non prius fuerit in
sensu (Latin, ‘Nothing is in the understanding that had not previously been in
the senses’), a principal tenet of empiricism. A weak interpretation of the
principle maintains that all concepts are acquired from sensory experience; no
concepts are innate or a priori. A stronger interpretation adds that all propositional
knowledge is derived from sense experience. The weak interpretation was held by
Aquinas and Locke, who thought nevertheless that we can know some propositions
to be true in virtue of the relations between the concepts involved. The
stronger interpretation was endorsed by J. S. Mill, who argued that even the
truths of mathematics are inductively based on experience. EMPIRICISM. W.E.M. Nihil ex nihilo fit
(Latin, ‘Nothing arises from nothing’), an intuitive metaphysical principle
first enunciated in the West by Parmenides, often held equivalent to the
proposition that nothing arises without a cause. Creation ex nihilo is God’s
production of the world without any natural or material cause, but involves a
supernatural cause, and so it would not violate the principle. J.Lo. nihilism,
ethical.RELATIVISM. nihilism, philosophical.NIETZSCHE, RUSSIAN NIHILISM.
nihilism, Russian.RUSSIAN NIHILISM. nihilism, semantic.SEMANTIC HOLISM.
nirodha-sapatti, also known as sjnavedayita-nirodha (Sanskrit, ‘attainment of
cessation’), a term used by Indian Buddhists to denote a state produced by
meditation in which no mental events of any kind occur. What ceases in
nirodha-sapatti is all the operations of the mind; all that remains is the
mindless body. Some Buddhists took this state to have salvific significance,
and so likened it to Nirvana. But its principal philosophical interest lies in
the puzzle it produced for Buddhist theorists: What causal account can be given
that will make sense of the reemergence of mental events from a continuum in
which none exist, given the pan-Buddhist assumption that all existents are
momentary? P.J.G. NN thesis.NECESSITY. noema.HUSSERL, NOETIC. noemata
moralia.MORE, THOMAS. noematic analysis.HUSSERL. noesis.DIVIDED LINE, HUSSERL.
noetic (from Greek noetikos, from noetos, ‘perceiving’), of or relating to
apprehension by the intellect. In a strict sense the term refers to nonsensuous
data given to the cognitive faculty, which discloses their intelligible meaning
as distinguished from their sensible apprehension. We hear a sentence spoken,
but it becomes intelligible for us only when the sounds function as a
foundation for noetic apprehension. For Plato, the objects of such apprehension
(noetá) are the Forms (eide) with respect to which the sensible phenomena are
only occasions of manifestation: the Forms in themselves transcend the sensible
and have their being in a realm apart. For empiricist thinkers, e.g., Locke,
there is strictly speaking no distinct noetic aspect, since “ideas” are only
faint sense impressions. In a looser sense, however, one may speak of ideas as
independent of reference to particular sense impressions, i.e. independent of
their origin, and then an idea can be taken to signify a class of objects.
Husserl uses the term to describe the intentionality or dyadic character of
consciousness in general, i.e. including both eidetic or categorial and
perceptual knowing. He speaks of the correlation of noesis or intending and
noema or the intended object of awareness. The categorial or eidetic is the
perceptual object as intellectually cognized; it is not a realm apart, but
rather what is disclosed or made present (“constituted”) Nihil est in
intellectu quod non prius fuerit in sensu noetic 617 617 when the mode of appearance of the
perceptual object is intended by a categorial noesis. HUSSERL, NOÛS. F.J.C. noetic
analysis.HUSSERL. noise.INFORMATION THEORY. nomic.LAWLIKE GENERALIZATION. nomic
necessity.LAWLIKE GENERALIZATION. nominal definition.DEFINITION. nominal
essence.ESSENTIALISM. nominalism.METAPHYSICAL REALISM, PROPERTY.
nominalization.STATE OF AFFAIRS. nominatum.OBLIQUE CONTEXT. nomological.LAWLIKE
GENERALIZATION.
nomothetic.WINDELBAND. non-action.WU WEI. non causa pro causa.INFORMAL FALLACY.
noncognitivism.EMOTIVISM, ETHICS. non-contradiction, principle of.PRINCIPLE OF
CONTRADICTION. non-duplication principle.PHILOSOPHY OF MIND.
non-embodiment.DISEMBODIMENT. non-epistemic.PERCEPTION. non-Euclidean geometry,
those axiomatized versions of geometry in which the parallel axiom of Euclidean
geometry is rejected, after so many unsuccessful attempts to prove it. As in so
many branches of mathematics, C. F. Gauss had thought out much of the matter
first, but he kept most of his ideas to himself. As a result, credit is given
to J. Bolyai and N. Lobachevsky, who worked independently from the late 1820s.
Instead of assuming that just one line passes through a point in a plane
parallel to a non-coincident coplanar line, they offered a geometry in which a
line admits more than one parallel, and the sum of the “angles” between the
“sides” of a “triangle” lies below 180°. Then in mid-century G. F. B. Riemann
conceived of a geometry in which lines always meet (so no parallels), and the
sum of the “angles” exceeds 180°. In this connection he distinguished between
the unboundedness of space as a property of its extent, and the special case of
the infinite measure over which distance might be taken (which is dependent
upon the curvature of that space). Pursuing the (published) insight of Gauss,
that the curvature of a surface could be defined in terms only of properties
dependent solely on the surface itself (and later called “intrinsic”), Riemann
also defined the metric on a surface in a very general and intrinsic way, in
terms of the differential arc length. Thereby he clarified the ideas of
“distance” that his non-Euclidean precursors had introduced (drawing on
trigonometric and hyperbolic functions); arc length was now understood
geodesically as the shortest “distance” between two “points” on a surface, and
was specified independent of any assumptions of a geometry within which the
surface was embedded. Further properties, such as that pertaining to the
“volume” of a three-“dimensional” solid, were also studied. The two main types
of non-Euclidean geometry, and its Euclidean parent, may be summarized as
follows: Reaction to these geometries was slow to develop, but their impact
gradually emerged. As mathematics, their legitimacy was doubted; but in 1868 E.
Beltri produced a model of a Bolyai-type two-dimensional space inside a planar
circle. The importance of this model was to show that the consistency of this
geometry depended upon that of the Euclidean version, thereby dispelling the
fear that it was an inconsistent flash of the imagination. During the last
thirty years of the nineteenth century a variety of variant geometries were
proposed, and the relationships between them were studied, together with
consequences for projective geometry. On the empirical side, these geometries,
and especially Riemann’s approach, affected the understanding of the
relationship between geometry and space; in particular, it posed the question
whether space is curved or not (the latnoetic analysis non-Euclidean geometry
618 618 non-monotonic logic
nonviolence 619 ter being the Euclidean answer). The geometries thus played a
role in the emergence and articulation of relativity theory, especially the
differential geometry and tensorial calculus within which its mathematical
properties could be expressed. Philosophically the new geometries stressed the
hypothetical nature of axiomatizing, in contrast to the customary view of
mathematical theories as true in some (usually) unclear sense. This feature led
to the ne ‘metageometry’ for them; it was intended (as an ironical proposal of
opponents) to be in line with the hypothetical character of metaphysics in
philosophy. They also helped to encourage conventionalist philosophy of science
(with Poincaré, e.g.), and put fresh light on the age-old question of the
(im)possibility of a priori knowledge.
EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY, PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS. I.G.-G. non-monotonic
logic, a logic that fails to be monotonic, i.e., in proof-theoretic terms,
fails to meet the condition that for all statements u1, . . . un,f,y, if ‘u1, .
. . un Yf’, then, for any y, ‘u1 , . . . un, y Y f’. (Equivalently, let Γ
represent a collection of statements, u1 . . . un, and say that in monotonic
logic, if ‘Γ Y f’, then, for any y, ‘Γ, y Y f’ and similarly in other cases.) A
non-monotonic logic is any logic with the following property: For some Γ, f,
and y, ‘ΓNML f’ but ‘Γ, y K!NML f’. This is a weak non-monotonic logic. In a
strong non-monotonic logic, we might have, again for some Γ, f, y, where Γ is
consistent and Γ 8 f is consistent: ‘Γ, y YNML > f’. A primary motivation
(ong AI researchers) for non-monotonic logic or defeasible reasoning, which is
so evident in commonsense reasoning, is to produce a machine representation for
default reasoning or defeasible reasoning. The interest in defeasible reasoning
readily spreads to epistemology, logic, and ethics. The exigencies of practical
affairs requires leaping to conclusions, going beyond available evidence,
making assumptions. In doing so, we often err and must leap back from our
conclusions, undo our assumptions, revise our beliefs. In the literature’s
standard exple, Tweety is a bird and all birds fly, except penguins and
ostriches. Does Tweety fly? If pressed, we may need to form a belief about this
matter. Upon discovering that Tweety is a penguin, we may have to retract our
conclusion. Any representation of defeasible reasoning must capture the
nonmonotonicity of this reasoning. Non-monotonic logic is an attempt to do this
within logic itself – by adding rules of inference that do not preserve monotonicity.
Although practical affairs require us to reason defeasibly, the best way to
achieve non-monotonicity may not be to add non-monotonic rules of inference to
standard logic. What one gives up in such systems may well not be worth the
cost: loss of the deduction theorem and of a coherent notion of consistency.
Therefore, the challenge of non-monotonic logic (or defeasible reasoning,
generally) is to develop a rigorous way to represent the structure of
non-monotonic reasoning without losing or abandoning the historically hard-won
properties of monotonic (standard) logic.
ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE, DEFAULT LOGIC, DEFEASIBILITY. F.A. non-natural
properties.MOORE. non-predicative property.
TYPE THEORY.
non-propositional knowledge.EPISTEMOLOGY. non-reductive materialism.PHILOSOPHY
OF MIND. non-reductive physicalism.KIM. non-reflexive.RELATION. non-standard
analysis.MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS. non-standard interpretation.FORMAL SEMANTICS.
non-standard model.STANDARD MODEL. non-standard semantics.SECOND-ORDER LOGIC.
non-symmetric.RELATION. non-transitive.RELATION. nonviolence, the renunciation
of violence in personal, social, or international affairs. It often includes a
commitment (called active nonviolence or nonviolent direct action) actively to
oppose violence (and usually evil or injustice as well) by nonviolent means.
Nonviolence may renounce physical violence alone or both physical and
psychological violence. It may represent a purely personal commitment or be
intended to be normative for others as well. When unconditional – absolute 619 norm normative relativism 620
nonviolence – it renounces violence in all actual and hypothetical
circumstances. When conditional – conditional nonviolence – it concedes the
justifiability of violence in hypothetical circumstances but denies it in
practice. Held on moral grounds (principled nonviolence), the commitment
belongs to an ethics of conduct or an ethics of virtue. If the former, it will
likely be expressed as a moral rule or principle (e.g., One ought always to act
nonviolently) to guide action. If the latter, it will urge cultivating the
traits and dispositions of a nonviolent character (which presumably then will
be expressed in nonviolent action). As a principle, nonviolence may be
considered either basic or derivative. Either way, its justification will be
either utilitarian or deontological. Held on non-moral grounds (pragmatic
nonviolence), nonviolence is a means to specific social, political, economic,
or other ends, themselves held on non-moral grounds. Its justification lies in
its effectiveness for these limited purposes rather than as a way of life or a
guide to conduct in general. An alternative source of power, it may then be
used in the service of evil as well as good. Nonviolent social action, whether
of a principled or pragmatic sort, may include noncooperation, mass
demonstrations, marches, strikes, boycotts, and civil disobedience – techniques
explored extensively in the writings of Gene Sharp. Undertaken in defense of an
entire nation or state, nonviolence provides an alternative to war. It seeks to
deny an invading or occupying force the capacity to attain its objectives by
withholding the cooperation of the populace needed for effective rule and by
nonviolent direct action, including civil disobedience. It may also be used
against oppressive domestic rule or on behalf of social justice. Gandhi’s
cpaign against British rule in India, Scandinavian resistance to Nazi
occupation during World War II, and Martin Luther King, Jr.’s actions on behalf
of civil rights in the United States are illustrative. Nonviolence has origins
in Far Eastern thought, particularly Taoism and Jainism. It has strands in the
Jewish Talmud, and many find it implied by the New Testent’s Sermon on the
Mount. CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE, GANDHI,
PACIFISM. R.L.H. norm.BASIC NORM. normal form, a formula equivalent to a given
logical formula, but having special properties. The main varieties follow.
Conjunctive normal form. If D1 . . . Dn are disjunctions of sentential
variables or their negations, such as (p 7 -q 7 r), then a formula F is in
conjunctive normal form provided F % D1 & D2 & . . & Dn. The
following are in conjunctive normal form: (-p 7 q); (p 7 q 7 r) & (-p 7 -q
7 -r) & (-q 7 r). Every formula of sentential logic has an equivalent conjunctive
normal form; this fact can be used to prove the completeness of sentential
logic. Disjunctive normal form. If C1 . . . Cn are conjunctions of sentential
variables or their negations, such as p & -q & -r, then a formula F is
in disjunctive normal form provided F % C1 7 C27 . . Cn. The following are thus
in disjunctive normal form: (p & -q) 7 (-p & q); (p & q & -r) 7
(-p & -q & -r). Every formula of sentential logic has an equivalent
disjunctive normal form. Prenex normal form. A formula of predicate logic is in
prenex normal form if (1) all quantifiers occur at the beginning of the
formula, (2) the scope of the quantifiers extends to the end of the formula,
and (3) what follows the quantifiers contains at least one occurrence of every
variable that appears in the set of quantifiers. Thus, (Dx)(Dy)(Fx / Gy) and
(x)(Dy)(z)((Fxy 7 Gyz) / Dxyz) are in prenex normal form. The formula may
contain free variables; thus, (Dx)(y) (Fxyz / Gwyx) is also in prenex normal
form. The following, however, are not in prenex normal form: (x)(Dy) (Fx / Gx);
(x)(y) Fxy / Gxy. Every formula of predicate logic has an equivalent formula in
prenex normal form. Skolem normal form. A formula F in predicate logic is in
Skolem normal form provided (1) F is in prenex normal form, (2) every
existential quantifier precedes any universal quantifier, (3) F contains at
least one existential quantifier, and (4) F contains no free variables. Thus,
(Dx)(Dy) (z)(Fxy / Gyz) and (Dx)(Dy)(Dz)(w)(Fxy 7 Fyz 7 Fzw) are in Skolem
normal form; however, (Dx) (y) Fxyz and (x) (y) (Fxy 7 Gyx) are not. Any
formula has an equivalent Skolem normal form; this has implications for the
completeness of predicate logic.
COMPLETENESS. V.K. normative.DEFINIST. normative ethics.ETHICS.
normative reason.REASONS FOR ACTION, REASONS FOR BELIEF. normative
relativism.RELATIVISM. 620 notation,
logical Nozick, Robert 621 notation, logical.LOGICAL NOTATION. notion.BERKELEY.
notional assent.NEWMAN. notum per se (Latin, ‘known through itself’),
self-evident. This term corresponds roughly to the term ‘analytic’. In
Thomistic theology, there are two ways for a thing to be self-evident, secundum
se (in itself) and quoad nos (to us). The proposition that God exists is
self-evident in itself, because God’s existence is identical with his essence;
but it is not self-evident to us (humans), because humans are not directly
acquainted with God’s essence.Aquinas’s Summa theologiae I, q.2,a.1,c.
noûs, Greek term for mind
or the faculty of reason. Noûs is the highest type of thinking, the kind a god
would do. Sometimes called the faculty of intellectual intuition, it is at work
when someone understands definitions, concepts, and anything else that is
grasped all at once. Noûs stands in contrast with another intellectual faculty,
dianoia. When we work through the steps of an argument, we exercise dianoia; to
be certain the conclusion is true without argument – to just “see” it, as,
perhaps, a god might – is to exercise noûs. Just which objects could be
apprehended by noûs was controversial. E.C.H. Novalis, pseudonym of Friedrich
von Hardenberg (1772–1801), German poet and philosopher of early German
Romanticism. His starting point was Fichte’s reflective type of transcendental
philosophy; he attempted to complement Fichte’s focus on philosophical
speculation by including other forms of intellectual experience such as faith,
love, poetry, and religion, and exhibit their equally autonomous status of
existence. Of special importance in this regard is his analysis of the
imagination in contrast to reason, of the poetic power in distinction from the
reasonable faculties. Novalis insists on a complementary interaction between
these two spheres, on a union of philosophy and poetry. Another important
aspect of his speculation concerns the relation between the inner and the outer
world, subject and object, the human being and nature. Novalis attempted to
reveal the correspondence, even unity between these two realms and to present
the world as a “universal trope” or a “symbolic image” of the human mind and
vice versa. He expressed his philosophical thought mostly in fragments. FICHTE. E.Beh. Nozick, Robert (b.1938),
erican philosopher currently at Harvard University, best known for Anarchy,
State, and Utopia (1974), which defends the libertarian position that only a
minimal state (limited to protecting rights) is just. Nozick argues that a
minimal state, but not a more extensive state, could arise without violating
rights. Drawing on Kant’s dictum that people may not be used as mere means,
Nozick says that people’s rights are inviolable, no matter how useful
violations might be to the state. He criticizes principles of redistributive
justice on which theorists base defenses of extensive states, such as the
principle of utility, and Rawls’s principle that goods should be distributed in
favor of the least well-off. Enforcing these principles requires eliminating
the cumulative effects of free exchanges, which violates (permanent,
bequeathable) property rights. Nozick’s own entitlement theory says that a
distribution of holdings is just if people under that distribution are entitled
to what they hold. Entitlements, in turn, would be clarified using principles
of justice in acquisition, transfer, and rectification. Nozick’s other works
include Philosophical Explanations (1981), The Exined Life (1989), The Nature
of Rationality (1993), and Socratic Puzzles (1997). These are contributions to
rational choice theory, epistemology, metaphysics, philosophy of mind,
philosophy of religion, and ethics. Philosophical Explanations features two
especially important contributions. The first is Nozick’s (reliabilist, causal)
view that beliefs that constitute knowledge must track the truth. My belief
that (say) a cat is on the mat tracks the truth only if (a) I would not believe
this if a cat were not on the mat, and (b) I would believe this if a cat were
there. The tracking account positions Nozick to reject the principle that
people know all of the things they believe via deductions from things they
know, and to reject versions of skepticism based on this principle of closure.
The second is Nozick’s closest continuer theory of identity, according to which
A’s identity at a later time can depend on facts about other existing things,
for it depends on (1) what continues A closely enough to be A and (2) what 621 n-tuple Nussbaum, Martha C(raven) 622
continues A more closely than any other existing thing. Nozick’s 1969 essay
“Newcomb’s Problem and Two Principles of Choice” is another important
contribution. It is the first discussion of Newcomb’s problem, a problem in
decision theory, and presents many positions prominent in subsequent
debate.
null class.SET THEORY.
null relation.RELATION. number.MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS, PHILOSOPHY OF
MATHEMATICS, QUALITIES. number, natural.MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS, MATHEMATICAL
INDUCTION. number, rational.MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS. number, real.MATHEMATICAL
ANALYSIS. number, transcendental.MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS. numbers, law of
large.BERNOULLI’s THEOREM. number theory.PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS. Numenius of
Apea (fl. mid-second century A.D.), Greek Platonist philosopher of
neoPythagorean tendencies. Very little is known of his life apart from his
residence in Apea, Syria, but his philosophical importance is considerable. His
system of three levels of spiritual reality – a primal god (the Good, the
Father), who is almost supra-intellectual; a secondary, creator god (the
demiurge of Plato’s Timaeus); and a world soul – largely anticipates that of
Plotinus in the next century, though he was more strongly dualist than Plotinus
in his attitude to the physical world and matter. He was much interested in the
wisdom of the East, and in comparative religion. His most important work,
fragments of which are preserved by Eusebius, is a dialogue On the Good, but he
also wrote a polemic work On the Divergence of the Academics from Plato, which
shows him to be a lively controversialist. J.M.D. numerical identity.
IDENTITY. nung chia.HSÜ
HSING. Nussbaum, Martha C(raven) (b.1947), erican philosopher, classicist, and
public intellectual with influential views on the human good, the emotions and
their place in practical reasoning, and the rights of women and homosexuals.
After training at Harvard in classical philology, she published a critical
edition, with translation and commentary, of Aristotle’s Motion of Animals
(1978). Its essays formulated ideas that she has continued to articulate: that
perception is trainable, imagination interpretive, and desire a reaching out
for the good. Via provocative readings of Plato, Aristotle, Aeschylus,
Sophocles, and Euripides, The Fragility of Goodness (1986) argues that many
true goods succumb to fortune, lack any common measure, and demand finetuned
discernment. The essays in Love’s Knowledge (1990) – on Proust, Dickens,
Beckett, Henry Jes, and others – explore the emotional implications of our
fragility and the particularism of practical reasoning. They also undertake a
brief against Plato’s ancient criticism of the poets, an argument that Nussbaum
carried on years later in debates with Judge Richard Posner. The Therapy of
Desire (1994) dissects the Stoics’ conviction that our vulnerability calls for
philosophical therapy to extirpate the emotions. While Nussbaum holds that the
Stoics were mistaken about the good, she has adopted and strengthened their
view that emotions embody judgments – most notably in her Gifford Lectures of
1993, Upheavals of Thought. A turning point in Nussbaum’s career ce in 1987,
when she bece a part-time research adviser at the United Nations–sponsored World
Institute for Development Economics Research. She there adapted her
Aristotelian account of the human good to help ground the “capabilities
approach” that the economist and philosopher artya Sen was developing for
policymakers to use in assessing individuals’ well-being. Nussbaum spells out
the human capabilities essential to leading a good life, integrating them
within a nuanced liberalism of universalist appeal. This view has rified:
Poetic Justice (1996) argues that its legal realization must avoid the oversimplifications
that utilitarianism and economics encourage and instead balance generality with
emotionally sensitive imagination. Sex and Social Justice (1998) explores her
view’s implications for problems of sexual inequality, gay rights, and sexual objectification.
Feminist Internationalism, her 1998 Seeley Lec
622 tures, argues that an effective international feminism must chpion
rights, eschew relativism, and study local traditions sufficiently closely to see
their diversity.
Nyaya-Vaishesika, one of
the orthodox schools of Hinduism. It holds that earth, air, fire, and water are
the four types of atoms. Space is a substance and a container of atoms. The
atoms are everlasting and eternal, though their combinations are neither.
Properties of complexes are explained in terms of the properties of their
components. There are emergent properties the causation of which does not
require that something come from nothing; one need only grant brute causal
connections. Nyaya is a monotheistic perspective and Nyaya philosopher Udana
wrote a text – Kusmañjali (“The Handful of Flowers”) – in natural theology;
this tenth-century work is an Indian classic on the subject. In addition to
material things composed of atoms, there are immaterial persons. Each person is
an enduring, substantial self whose nature is to be conscious and who is
capable of love and aversion, of feeling pleasure and pain, and of making
choices; selves differ from one another even when not embodied by virtue of
being different centers of consciousness, not merely in terms of having had
diverse transmigratory biographies. Nyaya-Vaishesika is the Hindu school most
like Anglo-erican philosophy, as evidenced in its studies of inference and
perception. HINDUISM. K.E.Y.
Nyaya-Vaishesika Nyaya-Vaishesika 623
623 Oakeshott, Michael (1900–91), British philosopher and political
theorist trained at Cbridge and in Germany. He taught first at Cbridge and
Oxford; from 1951 he was professor of political science at the London School of
Economics and Political Science. His works include Experience and Its Modes
(1933), Rationalism in Politics (1962), On Human Conduct (1975), and On History
(1983). Oakeshott’s misleading general reputation, based on Rationalism in
Politics, is as a conservative political thinker. Experience and Its Modes is a
systematic work in the tradition of Hegel. Human experience is exclusively of a
world of ideas intelligible insofar as it is coherent. This world divides into
modes (historical, scientific, practical, and poetic experience), each being
partly coherent and categorially distinct from all others. Philosophy is the
never entirely successful attempt to articulate the coherence of the world of
ideas and the place of modally specific experience within that whole. His later
works exine the postulates of historical and practical experience, particularly
those of religion, morality, and politics. All conduct in the practical mode
postulates freedom and is an “exhibition of intelligence” by agents who
appropriate inherited languages and ideas to the generic activity of
self-enactment. Some conduct pursues specific purposes and occurs in
“enterprise associations” identified by goals shared ong those who participate
in them. The most estimable forms of conduct, exemplified by “conversation,”
have no such purpose and occur in “civil societies” under the purely
“adverbial” considerations of morality and law. “Rationalists” illicitly use
philosophy to dictate to practical experience and subordinate human conduct to
some master purpose. Oakeshott’s distinctive achievement is to have melded
holistic idealism with a morality and politics radical in their affirmation of
individuality.
POLITICAL THEORY. R.E.F.
obiectum quo (Latin, ‘object by which’), in medieval and Scholastic
epistemology, the object by which an object is known. It should be understood
in contrast with obiectum quod, which refers to the object that is known. For
exple, when a person knows what an apple is, the apple is the obiectum quod and
his concept of the apple is the obiectum quo. That is, the concept is
instrumental to knowing the apple, but is not itself what is known. Human
beings need concepts in order to have knowledge, because their knowledge is
receptive, in contrast with God’s which is productive. (God creates what he
knows.) Human knowledge is mediated; divine knowledge is immediate. Scholastic
philosophers believe that the distinction between obiectum quod and obiectum
quo exposes the crucial mistake of idealism. According to idealists, the object
of knowledge, i.e., what a person knows, is an idea. In contrast, the
Scholastics maintain that idealists conflate the object of knowledge with the
means by which human knowledge is made possible. Humans must be connected to
the object of knowledge by something (obiectum quo), but what connects them is
not that to which they are connected. A.P.M. object, intentional.BRENTANO.
object, propositional.PROPOSITION. objective body.EMBODIMENT. objective
probability.PROBABILITY. objective reality.DESCARTES, REALITY. objective reason.REASONS
FOR ACTION. objective rightness. In ethics, an action is objectively right for
a person to perform (on some occasion) if the agent’s performing it (on that
occasion) really is right, whether or not the agent, or anyone else, believes
it is. An action is subjectively right for a person to perform (on some
occasion) if the agent believes, or perhaps justifiably believes, of that
action that it is (objectively) right. For exple, according to a version of
utilitarianism, an action is objectively right provided the action is optimific
in the sense that the consequences that would result from its per624 O 624 formance are at least as good as those
that would result from any alternative action the agent could instead perform.
Were this theory correct, then an action would be an objectively right action
for an agent to perform (on some occasion) if and only if that action is in
fact optimific. An action can be both objectively and subjectively right or
neither. But an action can also be subjectively right, but fail to be
objectively right, as where the action fails to be optimific (again assuming
that a utilitarian theory is correct), yet the agent believes the action is
objectively right. And an action can be objectively right but not subjectively
right, where, despite the objective rightness of the action, the agent has no
beliefs about its rightness or believes falsely that it is not objectively
right. This distinction is important in our moral assessments of agents and
their actions. In cases where we judge a person’s action to be objectively
wrong, we often mitigate our judgment of the agent when we judge that the
action was, for the agent, subjectively right. This se objective–subjective
distinction applies to other ethical categories such as wrongness and
obligatoriness, and some philosophers extend it to items other than actions,
e.g., emotions.
obligationes, the study
of inferentially inescapable, yet logically odd arguments, used by late
medieval logicians in analyzing inferential reasoning. In Topics VIII.3
Aristotle describes a respondent’s task in a philosophical argument as
providing answers so that, if they must defend the impossible, the
impossibility lies in the nature of the position, and not in its logical
defense. In Prior Analytics I.13 Aristotle argues that nothing impossible
follows from the possible. Burley, whose logic exemplifies early
fourteenth-century obligationes literature, described the resulting logical
exercise as a contest between interlocutor and respondent. The interlocutor must
force the respondent into maintaining contradictory statements in defending a
position, and the respondent must avoid this while avoiding maintaining the
impossible, which can be either a position logically incompatible with the
position defended or something impossible in itself. Especially interesting to
Scholastic logicians were the paradoxes of disputation inherent in such
disputes. Assuming that a respondent has successfully defended his position,
the interlocutor may be able to propose a commonplace position that the
respondent can neither accept nor reject, given the truth of the first,
successfully defended position. Roger Swineshead introduced a controversial
innovation to obligationes reasoning, later rejected by Paul of Venice. In the
traditional style of obligation, a premise was relevant to the argument only if
it followed from or was inconsistent with either (a) the proposition defended
or (b) all the premises consequent to the former and prior to the premise in
question. By admitting any premise that was either consequent to or
inconsistent with the proposition defended alone, without regard to
intermediate premises, Swineshead eliminated concern with the order of
sentences proposed by the interlocutor, making the respondent’s task harder.
oblique context. As
explained by Frege in “Über Sinn und Bedeutung” (1892), a linguistic context is
oblique (ungerade) if and only if an expression (e.g., proper ne, dependent
clause, or sentence) in that context does not express its direct (customary) sense.
For Frege, the sense of an expression is the mode of presentation of its
nominatum, if any. Thus in direct speech, the direct (customary) sense of an
expression designates its direct (customary) nominatum. For exple, the context
of the proper ne ‘Kepler’ in (1) Kepler died in misery. is non-oblique (i.e.,
direct) since the proper ne expresses its direct (customary) sense, say, the
sense of ‘the man who discovered the elliptical planetary orbits’, thereby
designating its direct (customary) nominatum, Kepler himself. Moreover, the
entire sentence expresses its direct sense, nely, the proposition that Kepler
died in misery, thereby designating its direct nominatum, a truth-value, nely,
the true. By contrast, objectivism oblique context 625 625 in indirect speech an expression
neither expresses its direct sense nor, therefore, designates its direct
nominatum. One such sort of oblique context is direct quotation, as in (2)
‘Kepler’ has six letters. The word appearing within the quotation marks neither
expresses its direct (customary) sense nor, therefore, designates its direct
(customary) nominatum, Kepler. Rather, it designates a word, a proper ne.
Another sort of oblique context is engendered by the verbs of propositional
attitude. Thus, the context of the proper ne ‘Kepler’ in (3) Frege believed
Kepler died in misery. is oblique, since the proper ne expresses its indirect
sense, say, the sense of the words ‘the man widely known as Kepler’, thereby
designating its indirect nominatum, nely, the sense of ‘the man who discovered
the elliptical planetary orbits’. Note that the indirect nominatum of ‘Kepler’
in (3) is the se as the direct sense of ‘Kepler’ in (1). Thus, while ‘Kepler’
in (1) designates the man Kepler, ‘Kepler’ in (3) designates the direct (customary)
sense of the word ‘Kepler’ in (1). Similarly, in (3) the context of the
dependent clause ‘Kepler died in misery’ is oblique since the dependent clause
expresses its indirect sense, nely, the sense of the words ‘the proposition
that Kepler died in misery’, thereby designating its indirect nominatum, nely,
the proposition that Kepler died in misery. Note that the indirect nominatum of
‘Kepler died in misery’ in (3) is the se as the direct sense of ‘Kepler died in
misery’ in (1). Thus, while ‘Kepler died in misery’ in (1) designates a
truthvalue, ‘Kepler died in misery’ in (3) designates a proposition, the direct
(customary) sense of the words ‘Kepler died in misery’ in (1). INDIRECT DISCOURSE, MEANING, QUANTIFYING IN.
R.F.G. oblique intention.INTENTION. observation.PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE.
observation language.
obversion, a sort of
immediate inference that allows a transformation of affirmative categorical
A-propositions and I-propositions into the corresponding negative
E-propositions and O-propositions, and of E- and O-propositions into the
corresponding A- and I-propositions, keeping in each case the order of the
subject and predicate terms, but changing the original predicate into its
complement, i.e., into a negated term. For exple, ‘Every man is mortal’ – ’No
man is non-mortal’; ‘Some students are happy’ – ‘Some students are not
non-happy’; ‘No dogs are jealous’ – ‘All dogs are non-jealous’; and ‘Some
bankers are not rich’ – ‘Some bankers are not non-rich’. SQUARE OF OPPOSITION, SYLLOGISM. I.Bo. obviousness.SELF-EVIDENCE.
Occ, Willi.OCKH. occasionalism, a theory of causation held by a number of
important seventeenth-century Cartesian philosophers, including Johannes
Clauberg (1622–65), Géraud de Cordemoy (1626– 84), Arnold Geulincx (1624–69),
Louis de la Forge (1632–66), and Nicolas Malebranche (1638–1715). In its most
extreme version, occasionalism is the doctrine that all finite created entities
are devoid of causal efficacy, and that God is the only true causal agent.
Bodies do not cause effects in other bodies nor in minds; and minds do not
cause effects in bodies nor even within themselves. God is directly,
immediately, and solely responsible for bringing about all phenomena. When a
needle pricks the skin, the physical event is merely an occasion for God to
cause the relevant mental state (pain); a volition in the soul to raise an arm
or to think of something is only an occasion for God to cause the arm to rise
or the ideas to be present to the mind; and the impact of one billiard ball
upon another is an occasion for God to move the second ball. In all three
contexts – mind–body, body–body, and mind alone – God’s ubiquitous causal
activity proceeds in accordance with certain general laws, and (except for
miracles) he acts only when the requisite material or psychic conditions
obtain. Less thoroughgoing forms of occasionalism limit divine causation (e.g.,
to mind–body or body–body alone). Far from being an ad hoc solution to a
Cartesian mind–body problem, as it is often considered, occasionalism is argued
for from general philosophical considerations regarding the nature of causal
relations (considerations that later appear, modified, in Hume), from an
analysis of the Cartesian concept of matoblique intention occasionalism 626 626 ter and of the necessary impotence of
finite substance, and, perhaps most importantly, from theological premises
about the essential ontological relation between an omnipotent God and the
created world that he sustains in existence. Occasionalism can also be regarded
as a way of providing a metaphysical foundation for explanations in mechanistic
natural philosophy. Occasionalists are arguing that motion must ultimately be
grounded in something higher than the passive, inert extension of Cartesian
bodies (emptied of the substantial forms of the Scholastics); it needs a causal
ground in an active power. But if a body consists in extension alone, motive
force cannot be an inherent property of bodies. Occasionalists thus identify
force with the will of God. In this way, they are simply drawing out the
implications of Descartes’s own metaphysics of matter and motion.
Ockh, Willi
(c.1285–1347), also written Willi Occ, known as the More than Subtle Doctor,
English Scholastic philosopher known equally as the father of nominalism and
for his role in the Franciscan dispute with Pope John XXII over poverty. Born
probably in the village of Ockh near London, Willi Ockh entered the Franciscan
order at an early age and studied at Oxford, attaining the rank of baccalarius
formatus. His brilliant but controversial career was cut short when John
Lutterell, former chancellor of Oxford University, presented the pope with a
list of fifty-six allegedly heretical theses extracted from Ockh’s writings.
The papal commission studied them for two years and found fifty-one open to
censure, but none was formally condemned. While in Avignon, Ockh researched
previous papal concessions to the Franciscans regarding collective poverty,
eventually concluding that John XXII contradicted his predecessors and hence
was “no true pope.” After committing these charges to writing, Ockh fled with
Michael of Cesena, then minister general of the order, first to Pisa and
ultimately to Munich, where he lived until his death, writing many treatises
about church–state relations. Although departures from his eminent predecessors
have combined with ecclesiastical difficulties to make Ockh unjustly notorious,
his thought remains, by current lights, philosophically and theologically
conservative. On most metaphysical issues, Ockh fancied himself the true
interpreter of Aristotle. Rejecting the doctrine that universals are real
things other than nes or concepts as “the worst error of philosophy,” Ockh
dismissed not only Platonism, but also “modern realist” doctrines according to which
natures enjoy a double mode of existence and are universal in the intellect but
numerically multiplied in particulars. He argues that everything real is
individual and particular, while universality is a property pertaining only to
nes and that by virtue of their signification relations. Because Ockh
understands the primary nes to be mental (i.e., naturally significant
concepts), his own theory of universals is best classified as a form of
conceptualism. Ockh rejects atomism, and defends Aristotelian hylomorphism in
physics and metaphysics, complete with its distinction between substantial and
accidental forms. Yet, he opposes the reifying tendency of the “moderns” (unned
contemporary opponents), who posited a distinct kind of thing (res) for each of
Aristotle’s ten categories; he argues that – from a purely philosophical point
of view – it is indefensible to posit anything besides particular substances
and qualities. Ockh followed the Franciscan school in recognizing a plurality
of substantial forms in living things (in humans, the forms of corporeity,
sensory soul, and intellectual soul), but diverged from Duns Scotus in
asserting a real, not a formal, distinction ong them. Aristotle had reached
behind regular correlations in nature to posit substance-things and
accident-things as primitive explanatory entities that essentially are or give
rise to powers (virtus) that produce the regularities; similarly, Ockh
distinguishes efficient causality properly speaking from sine qua non
causality, depending on whether the correlation between A’s and B’s is produced
by the power of A or by the will of another, and explicitly denies the
existence of any sine qua non causation in nature. Further, Ockh insists, in
Aristotelian fashion, that created substance- and accident-natures are
essentially the causal powers they are in and of themselves and hence
independently of their relations to anything else; so that not even God can
make heat naturally a coolant. Yet, if God cannot change, He shares with
created things the occurrent ability to obstruct such “Aristotelian” productive
powers and prevent their normal operation. Ockh’s nominalistic conceptualism
about universals does not keep him from endorsing the uniformity of nature
principle, because he holds that individual natures are powers and hence that
co-specific things are maximally similar powers. Likewise, he is conventional
in appealing to several other a priori causal principles: “Everything that is
in motion is moved by something,” “Being cannot come from non-being,” “Whatever
is produced by something is really conserved by something as long as it
exists.” He even recognizes a kind of necessary connection between created
causes and effects – e.g., while God could act alone to produce any created
effect, a particular created effect could not have had another created cause of
the se species instead. Ockh’s main innovation on the topic of causality is his
attack on Duns Scotus’s distinction between “essential” and “accidental” orders
and contrary contention that every genuine efficient cause is an immediate
cause of its effects. Ockh is an Aristotelian reliabilist in epistemology,
taking for granted as he does that human cognitive faculties (the senses and
intellect) work always or for the most part. Ockh infers that since we have
certain knowledge both of material things and of our own mental acts, there
must be some distinctive species of acts of awareness (intuitive cognitions)
that are the power to produce such evident judgments. Ockh is matter-of-fact
both about the disruption of human cognitive functions by created obstacles (as
in sensory illusion) and about divine power to intervene in many ways. Such
facts carry no skeptical consequences for Ockh, because he defines certainty in
terms of freedom from actual doubt and error, not from the logical,
metaphysical, or natural possibility of error. In action theory, Ockh defends
the liberty of indifference or contingency for all rational beings, created or
divine. Ockh shares Duns Scotus’s understanding of the will as a self-determining
power for opposites, but not his distaste for causal models. Thus, Ockh allows
that (1) unfree acts of will may be necessitated, either by the agent’s own
nature, by its other acts, or by an external cause; and that (2) the efficient
causes of free acts may include the agent’s intellectual and sensory cognitions
as well as the will itself. While recognizing innate motivational tendencies in
the human agent – e.g., the inclination to seek sensory pleasure and avoid
pain, the affectio commodi (tendency to seek its own advantage), and the
affectio iustitiae (inclination to love things for their own intrinsic worth) –
he denies that these limit the will’s scope. Thus, Ockh goes beyond Duns Scotus
in assigning the will the power, with respect to any option, to will for it
(velle), to will against it (nolle), or not to act at all. In particular, Ockh
concludes that the will can will against (nolle) the good, whether ignorantly
or perversely – by hating God or by willing against its own happiness, the
good-in-general, the enjoyment of a clear vision of God, or its own ultimate
end. The will can also will (velle) evils – the opposite of what right reason
dictates, unjust deeds qua unjust, dishonest, and contrary to right reason, and
evil under the aspect of evil. Ockh enforces the traditional division of moral
science into non-positive morality or ethics, which directs acts apart from any
precept of a superior authority and draws its principles from reason and
experience; and positive morality, which deals with laws that oblige us to
pursue or avoid things, not because they are good or evil in themselves, but
because some legitimate superior commands them. The notion that Ockh sponsors
an unmodified divine command theory of ethics rests on conflation and
confusion. Rather, in the area of non-positive morality, Ockh advances what we
might label a “modified right reason theory,” which begins with the
Aristotelian ideal of rational self-government, according to which morally
virtuous action involves the agent’s free coordination of choice with right
reason. He then observes that suitably informed right reason would dictate that
God, as the infinite good, ought to be loved above all and for his own sake,
and that such love ought to be expressed by the effort to please him in every
way (ong other things, by obeying all his commands). Thus, if right reason is
the primary norm in ethics, divine commands are a secondary, derivative norm.
Once again, Ockh is utterly unconcerned about the logical possibility opened by
divine liberty of indifference, that these twin norms might conflict (say, if
God commanded us to act contrary to right reason); for him, their de facto
congruence suffices for the moral life. In the area of soteriological merit and
demerit (a branch of positive morality), things are the other way around:
divine will is the primary norm; yet because God includes following the
dictates of right reason ong the criteria for divine acceptance (thereby giving
the moral life eternal significance), right reason becomes a secondary and
derivative norm there.
Ockh’s razor, also called
the principle of parsimony, a methodological principle commending a bias toward
simplicity in the construction of theories. The pareters whose simplicity is
singled out for attention have varied considerably, from kinds of entities to
the number of presupposed axioms to the nature of the curve drawn between data
points. Found already in Aristotle, the tag “entities should not be multiplied
beyond necessity” bece associated with Willi Ockh (although he never states
that version, and even if non-contradiction rather than parsimony is his
favorite weapon in metaphysical disputes), perhaps because it characterized the
spirit of his philosophical conclusions. Opponents, who thought parsimony was
being carried too far, formulated an “anti-razor”: where fewer entities do not
suffice, posit more!
Olivi, Peter John
(c.1247–98), French philosopher-theologian whose views on the theory and
practice of Franciscan poverty led to a long series of investigations of his
orthodoxy. Olivi’s preference for humility, as well as the suspicion with which
he was regarded, prevented his becoming a master of theology at Paris. After
1285, he was effectively vindicated and permitted to teach at Florence and Montpellier.
But after his death, probably in part because his remains were venerated and
his views were chpioned by the Franciscan Spirituals, his orthodoxy was again
exined. The Council of Vienne (1311–12) condemned three unrelated tenets
associated with Olivi. Finally, in 1326, Pope John XXII condemned a series of
statements based on Olivi’s Apocalypse commentary. Olivi thought of himself
chiefly as a theologian, writing copious biblical commentaries; his philosophy
of history was influenced by Joachim of Fiore. His views on poverty inspired
the leader of the Franciscan Observant reform movement, St. Bernardino of
Siena. Apart from his views on poverty, Olivi is best known for his
philosophical independence from Aristotle, whom he condemned as a materialist.
Contrary to Aristotle’s theory of projectile motion, Olivi advocated a theory
of impetus. He undermined orthodox views on Aristotelian categories. His attack
on the category of relation was thought to have dangerous implications in
Trinitarian theology. Ockh’s theory of quantity is in part a defense of views
presented by Olivi. Olivi was critical of Augustinian as well as Aristotelian
views; he abandoned the theories of seminal reason and divine illumination. He
also argued against positing impressed sensible and intelligible species,
claiming that only the soul, not perceptual objects, played an active role in
perception. Bold as his philosophical views were, he presented them
tentatively. A voluntarist, he emphasized the importance of will. He claimed that
an act of understanding was not possible in the absence of an act of will. He
provided an important experiential argument for the freedom of the will. His
treatises on contracts revealed a sophisticated understanding of economics. His
treatise on evangelical poverty includes the first defense of a theory of papal
infallibility. R.W. Olympiodorus.NEOPLATONISM. omega, the last letter of the
Greek alphabet (w). Following Cantor (1845–1911), it is used in lowercase as a
proper ne for the first infinite ordinal number, which is the ordinal of the
natural ordering of the set of finite ordinals. By extension it is also used as
a proper ne for the set of finite ordinals itself or even for the set of
natural numbers. Following Gödel (1906–78), it is used as a prefix in nes of
various logical properties of sets of sentences, most notably
omega-completeness and omega-consistency. Omega-completeness, in the original
sense due to Tarski, is a syntactical property of sets of sentences in a formal
arithmetic language involving a symbol ‘0’ for the number zero and a symbol ‘s’
for the so-called successor function, resulting in each natural number being
ned by an expression, called a numeral, in the following series: ‘0’, ‘s0’,
‘ss0’, and so on. For exple, five is denoted by ‘sssss0’. A set of sentences is
said to be omegacomplete if it (deductively) yields every universal sentence
all of whose singular instances it yields. In this frework, as usual, every
universal sentence, ‘for every n, n has P’ yields each and every one of its
singular instances, ‘0 has P’, ‘s0 has P’, ‘ss0 has P’, etc. However, as had
been known by logicians at least since the Middle Ages, the converse is not
true, i.e., it is not in general the case that a universal sentence is
deducible from the set of its singular instances. Thus one should not expect to
find omega-completeness except in exceptional sets. The set of all true
sentences of arithmetic is such an exceptional set; the reason is the semantic
fact that every universal sentence (whether or not in arithmetic) is materially
equivalent to the set of all its singular instances. A set of sentences that is
not omega-complete is Ockh’s razor omega 629
629 said to be omega-incomplete. The existence of omega-incomplete sets
of sentences is a phenomenon at the core of the 1931 Gödel incompleteness
result, which shows that every “effective” axiom set for arithmetic is
omega-incomplete and thus has as theorems all singular instances of a universal
sentence that is not one of its theorems. Although this is a remarkable fact,
the existence of omega-incomplete sets per se is far from remarkable, as
suggested above. In fact, the empty set and equivalently the set of all
tautologies are omega-incomplete because each yields all singular instances of
the non-tautological formal sentence, here called FS, that expresses the
proposition that every number is either zero or a successor. Omega-consistency
belongs to a set that does not yield the negation of any universal sentence all
of whose singular instances it yields. A set that is not omega-consistent is
said to be omega-inconsistent. Omega-inconsistency of course implies
consistency in the ordinary sense; but it is easy to find consistent sets that
are not omega-consistent, e.g., the set whose only member is the negation of
the formal sentence FS mentioned above. Corresponding to the syntactical
properties just mentioned there are analogous semantic properties whose
definitions are obtained by substituting ‘(semantically) implies’ for
‘(deductively) yields’. The Greek letter omega and its English ne have many
other uses in modern logic. Carnap introduced a non-effective, non-logical
rule, called the omega rule, for “inferring” a universal sentence from its
singular instances; adding the omega rule to a standard axiomatization of
arithmetic produces a complete but non-effective axiomatization. An
omega-valued logic is a many-valued logic whose set of truth-values is or is
the se size as the set of natural numbers.
.
one–many problem, also
called one-and-many problem, the question whether all things are one or many.
According to both Plato and Aristotle this was the central question for
pre-Socratic philosophers. Those who answered “one,” the monists, ascribed to
all things a single nature such as water, air, or oneness itself. They appear
not to have been troubled by the notion that numerically many things would have
this one nature. The pluralists, on the other hand, distinguished many
principles or many types of principles, though they also maintained the unity
of each principle. Some monists understood the unity of all things as a denial
of motion, and some pluralists advanced their view as a way of refuting this
denial. To judge from our sources, early Greek metaphysics revolved around the
problem of the one and the many. In the modern period the dispute between
monists and pluralists centered on the question whether mind and matter
constitute one or two substances and, if one, what its nature is. PRE-SOCRATICS, SPINOZA. E.C.H. one over many,
a universal; especially, a Platonic Form. According to Plato, if there are,
e.g., many large things, there must be some one largeness itself in respect of
which they are large; this “one over many” (hen epi pollon) is an intelligible
entity, a Form, in contrast with the sensible many. Plato himself recognizes
difficulties explaining how the one character can be present to the many and
why the one and the many do not together constitute still another many (e.g.,
Parmenides 131a–133b). Aristotle’s sustained critique of Plato’s Forms
(Metaphysics A 9, Z 13–15) includes these and other problems, and it is he,
more than Plato, who regularly uses ‘one over many’ to refer to Platonic
Forms. ARISTOTLE, ONE–MANY PROBLEM,
PLATO. E.C.H. omega, order type one over many 630 630 one-way reduction sentence.REDUCTION
SENTENCE. ontological argument.
ontological commitment,
the object or objects common to the ontology fulfilling some (regimented)
theory (a term fashioned by Quine). The ontology of a (regimented) theory
consists in the objects the theory assumes there to be. In order to show that a
theory assumes a given object, or objects of a given class, we must show that
the theory would be true only if that object existed, or if that class is not
empty. This can be shown in two different but equivalent ways: if the notation
of the theory contains the existential quantifier ‘(Ex)’ of first-order
predicate logic, then the theory is shown to assume a given object, or objects
of a given class, provided that object is required ong the values of the bound
variables, or (additionally) is required ong the values of the domain of a
given predicate, in order for the theory to be true. Thus, if the theory
entails the sentence ‘(Ex)(x is a dog)’, then the values over which the bound
variable ‘x’ ranges must include at least one dog, in order for the theory to
be true. Alternatively, if the notation of the theory contains for each
predicate a complementary predicate, then the theory assumes a given object, or
objects of a given class, provided some predicate is required to be true of
that object, in order for the theory to be true. Thus, if the theory contains
the predicate ‘is a dog’, then the extension of ‘is a dog’ cannot be empty, if
the theory is to be true. However, it is possible for different, even mutually
exclusive, ontologies to fulfill a theory equally well. Thus, an ontology
containing collies to the exclusion of spaniels and one containing spaniels to
the exclusion of collies might each fulfill a theory that entails ‘(Ex) (x is a
dog)’. It follows that some of the objects a theory assumes (in its ontology)
may not be ong those to which the theory is ontologically committed. A theory
is ontologically committed to a given object only if that object is common to
all of the ontologies fulfilling the theory. And the theory is ontologically
committed to objects of a given class provided that class is not empty
according to each of the ontologies fulfilling the theory.
open formula, also called
open sentence, a sentence with a free occurrence of a variable. A closed
sentence, sometimes called a statement, has no free occurrences of variables.
In a language whose only variable-binding operators are quantifiers, an
occurrence of a variable in a formula is bound provided that occurrence either
is within the scope of a quantifier employing that variable or is the
occurrence in that quantifier. An occurrence of a variable in a formula is free
provided it is not bound. The formula ‘xy ( O’ is open because both ‘x’ and ‘y’
occur as free variables. In ‘For some real number y, xy ( O’, no occurrence of
‘y’ is free; but the occurrence of ‘x’ is free, so the formula is open. The
sentence ‘For every real number x, for some real number y, xy ( O’ is closed,
since none of the variables occur free. Semantically, an open formula such as
‘xy ( 0’ is neither true nor false but rather true of or false of each
assignment of values to its free-occurring variables. For exple, ‘xy ( 0’ is
true of each assignment of two positive or two negative real numbers to ‘x’ and
to ‘y’ and it is false of each assignment of 0 to either and false at each
assignment of a positive real to one of the variables and a negative to the
other. QUANTIFICATION, SCOPE. C.S. open
loop.CYBERNETICS. open question argument.MOORE. open sentence.OPEN FORMULA.
open society.POPPER. open texture, the possibility of vagueness. Frieone-way
reduction sentence open texture 631
631 drich Waismann (“Verifiability,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society, 1945) introduced the concept, claiming that open texture is a
universal property of empirical terms. Waismann claimed that an inexhaustible
source of vagueness remains even after measures are taken to make an expression
precise. His grounds were, first, that there are an indefinite number of
possibilities for which it is indeterminate whether the expression applies
(i.e., for which the expression is vague). There is, e.g., no definite answer
whether a catlike creature that repeatedly vanishes into thin air, then
reappears, is a cat. Waismann’s explanation is that when we define an empirical
term, we fre criteria of its applicability only for foreseeable circumstances.
Not all possible situations in which we may use the term, however, can be
foreseen. Thus, in unanticipated circumstances, real or merely possible, a term’s
criteria of applicability may yield no definite answer to whether it applies.
Second, even for terms such as ‘gold’, for which there are several precise
criteria of application (specific gravity, X-ray spectrograph, solubility in
aqua regia), applying different criteria can yield divergent verdicts, the
result being vagueness. Waismann uses the concept of open texture to explain
why experiential statements are not conclusively verifiable, and why
phenomenalist attempts to translate material object statements fail.
operationalism, a progr
in philosophy of science that aims to interpret scientific concepts via
experimental procedures and observational outcomes. P. W. Bridgman introduced
the terminology when he required that theoretical concepts be identified with
the operations used to measure them. Logical positivism’s criteria of cognitive
significance incorporated the notion: Bridgman’s operationalism was assimilated
to the positivistic requirement that theoretical terms T be explicitly defined
via (logically equivalent to) directly observable conditions O. Explicit
definitions failed to accommodate alternative measurement procedures for the se
concept, and so were replaced by reduction sentences that partially defined
individual concepts in observational terms via sentences such as ‘Under
observable circumstances C, x is T if and only if O’. Later this was weakened
to allow ensembles of theoretical concepts to be partially defined via
interpretative systems specifying collective observable effects of the concepts
rather than effects peculiar to single concepts. These cognitive significance
notions were incorporated into various behaviorisms, although the term
‘operational definition’ is rarely used by scientists in Bridgman’s or the
explicit definition senses: intervening variables are theoretical concepts
defined via reduction sentences and hypothetical constructs are definable by
interpretative systems but not reduction sentences. In scientific contexts
observable terms often are called dependent or independent variables. When, as
in science, the concepts in theoretical assertions are only partially defined,
observational consequences do not exhaust their content, and so observational
data underdetermines the truth of such assertions in the sense that more than
one theoretical assertion will be compatible with maximal observational
data.
BEHAVIORISM, REDUCTION,
REDUCTION SENTENCE, THEORETICAL TERM. F.S. operator, a one-place sentential
connective; i.e., an expression that may be prefixed to an open or closed
sentence to produce, respectively, a new open or closed sentence. Thus ‘it is
not the case that’ is a (truth-functional) operator. The most thoroughly
investigated operators are the intensional ones; an intensional operator O,
when prefixed to an open or closed sentence E, produces an open or closed
sentence OE, whose extension is determined not by the extension of E but by
some other property of E, which varies with the choice of O. For exple, the
extension of a closed sentence is its truth-value A, but if the modal operator
‘it is necessary that’ is prefixed to A, the extension of the result depends on
whether A’s extension belongs to it necessarily or contingently. This property
of A is usually modeled by assigning to A a subset X of a domain of possible
worlds W. If X % W then ‘it is necessary that A’ is true, but if X is a proper
subset of W, it is false. Another exple involves the epistemic operator ‘it is
plausible that’. Since a true sentence may be either plausible or implausible,
the truth-value of ‘it is plausible that A’ is not fixed by the truth-value of
A, but rather by the body of evidence that supports A relative to a thinker in
a given context. This may also be modeled in a possible worlds frework, by
operant conditioning operator 632 632
stipulating, for each world, which worlds, if any, are plausible relative to
it. The topic of intensional operators is controversial, and it is even
disputable whether standard exples really are operators at the correct level of
logical form. For instance, it can be argued that ‘it is necessary that’, upon
analysis, turns out to be a universal quantifier over possible worlds, or a
predicate of expressions. On the former view, instead of ‘it is necessary that
A’ we should write ‘for every possible world w, A(w)’, and, on the latter, ‘A
is necessarily true’.
operator theory of
adverbs, a theory that treats adverbs and other predicate modifiers as
predicate-forming operators on predicates. The theory expands the syntax of
first-order logic by adding operators of various degrees, and makes
corresponding additions to the semantics. Romane Clark, Terence Parsons, and
Richard Montague (with Hans Kp) developed the theory independently in the early
1970s. For exple: ‘John runs quickly through the kitchen’ contains a simple
one-place predicate, ‘runs’ (applied to John); a zero-place operator,
‘quickly’, and a one-place operator, ‘through ()’ (with ‘the kitchen’ filling
its place). The logical form of the sentence becomes [O1 1(a) [O2 0 [P(b)]]],
which can be read: [through (the kitchen) [quickly [runs (John)]]].
Semantically ‘quickly’ will be associated with an operation that takes us from
the extension of ‘runs’ to a subset of that extension. ‘John runs quickly’ will
imply ‘John runs’. ‘Through (the kitchen)’ and other operators are handled
similarly. The wide variety of predicate modifiers complicates the inferential
conditions and semantics of the operators. ‘John is finally done’ implies ‘John
is done’. ‘John is nearly done’ implies ‘John is not done’. Clark tries to
distinguish various types of predicate modifiers and provides a different
semantic analysis for operators of different sorts. The theory can easily
characterize syntactic aspects of predicate modifier iteration. In addition,
after being modified the original predicates remain as predicates, and maintain
their original degree. Further, there is no need to force John’s running into
subject position as might be the case if we try to make ‘quickly’ an ordinary
predicate. T.J.D. O-proposition.SYLLOGISM. oratio obliqua.INDIRECT DISCOURSE.
order, the level of a logic as determined by the type of entity over which the
free variables of that logic range. Entities of the lowest type, usually called
type O, are known as individuals, and entities of higher type are constructed
from entities of lower type. For exple, type 1 entities are (i) functions from
individuals or n-tuples of individuals to individuals, and (ii) n-place
relations on individuals. First-order logic is that logic whose variables range
over individuals, and a model for first-order logic includes a domain of
individuals. The other logics are known as higher-order logics, and the first
of these is second-order logic, in which there are variables that range over
type 1 entities. In a model for second-order logic, the first-order domain
determines the second-order domain. For every sentence to have a definite
truth-value, only totally defined functions are allowed in the range of
second-order function variables, so these variables range over the collection
of total functions from n-tuples of individuals to individuals, for every value
of n. The second-order predicate variables range over all subsets of n-tuples
of individuals. Thus if D is the domain of individuals of a model, the type 1
entities are the union of the two sets {X: Dn: X 0 Dn$D}, {X: Dn: X 0 Dn}.
Quantifiers may bind second-order variables and are subject to introduction and
elimination rules. Thus whereas in first-order logic one may infer ‘Someone is
wise, ‘(Dx)Wx’, from ‘Socrates is wise’, ‘Ws’, in second-order logic one may
also infer ‘there is something that Socrates is’, ‘(DX)Xs’. The step from
first- to second-order logic iterates: in general, type n entities are the
domain of n ! 1th–order variables in n ! 1th– order logic, and the whole
hierarchy is known as the theory of types.
TYPE THEORY. G.Fo. ordered n-tuple.SET THEORY. ordered pair.
SET THEORY. operator,
deontic ordered pair 633 633 ordering,
an arrangement of the elements of a set so that some of them come before others.
If X is a set, it is useful to identify an ordering R of X with a subset R of
X$X, the set of all ordered pairs with members in X. If ‹ x,y ( 1 R then x
comes before y in the ordering of X by R, and if ‹ x,y ( 2 R and ‹ y,x ( 2 R,
then x and y are incomparable. Orders on X are therefore relations on X, since
a relation on a set X is any subset of X $ X. Some minimal conditions a
relation must meet to be an ordering are (i) reflexivity: (Ex)Rxx; (ii)
antisymmetry: (Ex)(Ey)((Rxy & Ryx) / x % y); and (iii) transitivity:
(Ex)(Ey)(Ez)((Rxy & Ryz) / Rxz). A relation meeting these three conditions
is known as a partial order (also less commonly called a semi-order), and if
reflexivity is replaced by irreflexivity, (Ex)-Rxx, as a strict partial order.
Other orders are strengthenings of these. Thus a tree-ordering of X is a
partial order with a distinguished root element a, i.e. (Ex)Rax, and that
satisfies the backward linearity condition that from any element there is a
unique path back to a: (Ex)(Ey)(Ez)((Ryx & Rzx) / (Ryz 7 Rzy). A total
order on X is a partial order satisfying the connectedness requirement:
(Ex)(Ey)(Rxy 7 Ryx). Total orderings are sometimes known as strict linear
orderings, contrasting with weak linear orderings, in which the requirement of
antisymmetry is dropped. The natural number line in its usual order is a strict
linear order; a weak linear ordering of a set X is a strict linear order of
levels on which various members of X may be found, while adding antisymmetry
means that each level contains only one member. Two other important orders are
dense (partial or total) orders, in which, between any two elements, there is a
third; and well-orders. A set X is said to be well-ordered by R if R is total
and every non-empty subset of Y of X has an R-least member: (EY 0 X)[Y & /
/ (Dz 1 Y)(Ew 1 Y)Rzw]. Well-ordering rules out infinite descending sequences,
while a strict well-ordering, which is irreflexive rather than reflexive, rules
out loops. The best-known exple is the membership relation of axiomatic set
theory, in which there are no loops such as x 1 y 1 x or x 1 x, and no infinite
descending chains . . . x2 1 x1 1 x0.
order type omega, in
mathematics, the order type of the infinite set of natural numbers. The last
letter of the Greek alphabet, w, is used to denote this order type; w is thus
the first infinite ordinal number. It can be defined as the set of all finite
ordinal numbers ordered by magnitude; that is, w % {0,1,2,3 . . . }. A set has
order type w provided it is denumerably infinite, has a first element but not a
last element, has for each element a unique successor, and has just one element
with no immediate predecessor. The set of even numbers ordered by magnitude,
{2,4,6,8 . . . }, is of order type w. The set of natural numbers listing first
all even numbers and then all odd numbers, {2,4,6,8 . . .; 1,3,5,7 . . . }, is
not of order type w, since it has two elements, 1 and 2, with no immediate
predecessor. The set of negative integers ordered by magnitude, { . . .
–3,–2,–1}, is also not of order type w, since it has no first element. V.K.
ordinal logic, any means of associating effectively and uniformly a logic (in
the sense of a formal axiomatic system) Sa with each constructive ordinal
notation a. This notion and term for it was introduced by Alan Turing in his
paper “Systems of Logic Based on Ordinals” (1939). Turing’s aim was to try to
overcome the incompleteness of formal systems discovered by Gödel in 1931, by
means of the transfinitely iterated, successive adjunction of unprovable but
correct principles. For exple, according to Gödel’s second incompleteness
theorem, for each effectively presented formal system S containing a modicum of
elementary number theory, if S is consistent then S does not prove the purely
universal arithmetical proposition Cons expressing the consistency of S (via
the Gödelnumbering of symbolic expressions), even though Cons is correct.
However, it may be that the result S’ of adjoining Cons to S is inconsistent.
This will not happen if every purely existential statement provable in S is
correct; call this condition (E-C). Then if S satisfies (E-C), so also does S;
% S ! Cons ; now S; is still incomplete by Gödel’s theorem, though it is more
complete than S. Clearly the passage from S to S; can be iterated any finite
number of times, beginning with any S0 satisfying (E-C), to form S1 % S; 0, S2
% S; 1, etc. But this procedure can also be extended into the transfinite, by
taking Sw to be the union of the systems Sn for n % 0,1, 2 . . . and then Sw!1
% S;w, Sw!2 % S;w!1, etc.; condition (EC) is preserved throughout. To see how
far this and other effective extension procedures of any effectively presented
system S to another S; can be iterated into the transfinite, one needs the
notion of the set O of constructive ordinal notations, due to Alonzo Church and
Stephen C. Kleene in 1936. O is a set ordering ordinal logic 634 634 of natural numbers, and each a in O
denotes an ordinal a, written as KaK. There is in O a notation for 0, and with
each a in O is associated a notation sc(a) in O with Ksc(a)K % KaK ! 1;
finally, if f is a number of an effective function {f} such that for each n,
{f}(n) % an is in O and KanK < Kan!1K, then we have a notation ø(f) in O
with Kø(f)K % limnKanK. For quite general effective extension procedures of S
to S; and for any given S0, one can associate with each a in O a formal system
Sa satisfying Ssc(a) % S;a and Sø(f) % the union of the S{f}(n) for n % 0,1, 2.
. . . However, as there might be many notations for each constructive ordinal,
this ordinal logic need not be invariant, in the sense that one need not have:
if KaK % KbK then Sa and Sb have the se consequences. Turing proved that an
ordinal logic cannot be both complete for true purely universal statements and
invariant. Using an extension procedure by certain proof-theoretic reflection
principles, he constructed an ordinal logic that is complete for true purely
universal statements, hence not invariant. (The history of this and later work
on ordinal logics is traced by the undersigned in “Turing in the Land of O(z),”
in The Universal Turing Machine: A Half Century Survey, edited by Rolf Herken
[1988].)
ordinary language
philosophy, a loosely structured philosophical movement holding that the
significance of concepts, including those central to traditional philosophy –
e.g., the concepts of truth and knowledge – is fixed by linguistic practice.
Philosophers, then, must be attuned to the actual uses of words associated with
these concepts. The movement enjoyed considerable prominence chiefly ong
English-speaking philosophers between the mid-1940s and the early 1960s. It was
initially inspired by the work of Wittgenstein, and later by John Wisdom,
Gilbert Ryle, Norman Malcolm, and J. L. Austin, though its roots go back at
least to Moore and arguably to Socrates. Ordinary language philosophers do not
mean to suggest that, to discover what truth is, we are to poll our fellow
speakers or consult dictionaries. Rather, we are to ask how the word ‘truth’
functions in everyday, nonphilosophical settings. A philosopher whose theory of
truth is at odds with ordinary usage has simply misidentified the concept.
Philosophical error, ironically, was thought by Wittgenstein to arise from our
“bewitchment” by language. When engaging in philosophy, we may easily be misled
by superficial linguistic similarities. We suppose minds to be special sorts of
entity, for instance, in part because of grmatical parallels between ‘mind’ and
‘body’. When we fail to discover any entity that might plausibly count as a
mind, we conclude that minds must be nonphysical entities. The cure requires
that we remind ourselves how ‘mind’ and its cognates are actually used by
ordinary speakers.
organic, having parts
that are organized and interrelated in a way that is the se as, or analogous
to, the way in which the parts of a living animal or other biological organism
are organized and interrelated. Thus, an organic unity or organic whole is a
whole that is organic in the above sense. These terms are primarily used of
entities that are not literally organisms but are supposedly analogous to them.
ong the applications of the concept of an organic unity are: to works of art,
to the state (e.g., by Hegel), and to the universe as a whole (e.g., in
absolute idealism). The principal element in the concept is perhaps the notion
of an entity whose parts cannot be understood except by reference to their
contribution to the whole entity. Thus to describe something as an organic
unity is typically to imply that its properties cannot be given a reductive
explanation in terms of those of its parts; rather, at least some of the
properties of the parts must themselves be explained by reference to the
properties of the whole. Hence it usually involves a form of holism. Other
features sometimes attributed to organic unities include a mutual dependence
between the existence of the parts and that of the whole and the need for a
teleological explanation of properties of the parts in terms of some end or
purpose associated with the whole. To what extent these characteristics belong
to genuine biological organisms is disputed.
ORGANICISM, ORGANISM. P.Mac. organicism, a theory that applies the
notion of an organic unity, especially to things that are not literally
organisms. G. E. Moore, in Principia Ethica, proposed a principle of organic
unities, concerning intrinsic value: the (intrinsic) value of a whole need not
be equivalent to the sum of the (intrinsic) values of its parts. Moore applies
the principle in arguing that there is no systematic relation between ordinal
utility organicism 635 635 the
intrinsic value of an element of a complex whole and the difference that the
presence of that element makes to the value of the whole. E.g., he holds that
although a situation in which someone experiences pleasure in the contemplation
of a beautiful object has far greater intrinsic goodness than a situation in
which the person contemplates the se object without feeling pleasure, this does
not mean that the pleasure itself has much intrinsic value.
HOLISM, REDUCTION, VALUE.
P.Mac. organic unity.ORGANIC. organism, a carbon-based living thing or
substance, e.g., a parecium, a tree, or an ant. Alternatively, ‘organism’ can
mean a hypothetical living thing of another natural kind, e.g., a silicon-based
living thing. Defining conditions of a carbon-based living thing, x, are as
follows. (1) x has a layer made of m-molecules, i.e., carbonbased
macromolecules of repeated units that have a high capacity for selective
reactions with other similar molecules. x can absorb and excrete through this
layer. (2) x can metabolize m-molecules. (3) x can synthesize m-molecular parts
of x by means of activities of a proper part of x that is a nuclear molecule,
i.e., an m-molecule that can copy itself. (4) x can exercise the foregoing
capacities in such a way that the corresponding activities are causally
interrelated as follows: x’s absorption and excretion causally contribute to
x’s metabolism; these processes jointly causally contribute to x’s
synthesizing; and x’s synthesizing causally contributes to x’s absorption,
excretion, and metabolism. (5) x belongs to a natural kind of compound physical
substance that can have a member, y, such that: y has a proper part, z; z is a
nuclear molecule; and y reproduces by means of z’s copying itself. (6) x is not
possibly a proper part of something that satisfies (1)–(6). The last condition
expresses the independence and autonomy of an organism. For exple, a part of an
organism, e.g., a heart cell, is not an organism. It also follows that a colony
of organisms, e.g., a colony of ants, is not an organism. LIFE, ORGANIC, ORGANICISM. J.Ho. & G.Ro.
Organon.ARISTOTLE. Origen (A.D. 185–253), Christian theologian and biblical
scholar in the Alexandrian church. Born in Egypt, he bece head of the catechetical
school in Alexandria. Like his mentor, Clement of Alexandria, he was influenced
by Middle Platonism. His principal works were Hexapla, On First Principles, and
Contra Celsum. The Hexapla, little of which survives, consisted of six Hebrew
and two Greek versions of the Old Testent with Origen’s commentary. On First
Principles sets forth the most systematic Christian theology of the early
church, including some doctrines subsequently declared heretical, such as the
subordination of the Son (“a secondary god”) and Spirit to the Father,
preexisting human souls (but not their transmigration), and a premundane fall
from grace of each human soul. The most fous of his views was the notion of
apocatastasis, universal salvation, the universal restoration of all creation
to God in which evil is defeated and the devil and his minions repent of their
sins. He interpreted hell as a temporary purgatory in which impure souls were
purified and made ready for heaven. His notion of subordination of the Son of
God to the Father was condemned by the church in 533. Origen’s Contra Celsum is
the first sustained work in Christian apologetics. It defends Christianity
before the pagan world. Origen was a leading exponent of the allegorical
interpretation of the Scriptures, holding that the text had three levels of
meaning corresponding to the three parts of human nature: body, soul, and
spirit. The first was the historical sense, sufficient for simple people; the
second was the moral sense; and the third was the mystical sense, open only to
the deepest souls. L.P.P. original position.LIBERALISM, RAWLS. Orpheus.ORPHISM.
Orphism, a religious movement in ancient Greece that may have influenced Plato
and some of the pre-Socratics. Neither the nature of the movement nor the scope
of its influence is adequately understood: ancient sources and modern scholars
tend to confuse Orphism with Pythagoreanism and with ancient mystery cults,
especially the Bacchic or Dionysiac mysteries. “Orphic poems,” i.e., poems
attributed to Orpheus (a mythic figure), circulated as early as the mid-sixth
century B.C. We have only indirect evidence of the early Orphic poems; but we
do have a sizable body of fragments from poems composed in later antiquity.
Central to both early and later versions is a theogonic-cosmogonic narrative
that posits Night as the primal entity – ostensibly a revision of the account
offered by Hesiod – and gives major emphasis to organic unity Orphism 636 636 Ortega y Gasset, José outer converse
637 the birth, death through dismemberment, and rebirth of the god Dionysus.
Plato gives us clear evidence of the existence in his time of itinerant
religious teachers who, drawing on the “books of Orpheus,” performed and taught
rituals of initiation and purification intended to procure divine favor either
in this life or in an afterlife. The extreme skepticism of such scholars as
Ulrich von Wilowitz-Moellendorff and I. M. Linforth concerning the importance
of early Orphism for Greek religion and Greek philosophy has been undermined by
archaeological findings in recent decades: the Derveni papyrus, which is a
fragment of a philosophical commentary on an Orphic theogony; and inscriptions
with Orphic instructions for the dead, from funerary sites in southern Italy,
mainland Greece, and the Crimea. A.P.D.M. Ortega y Gasset, José (1883–1955),
Spanish philosopher and essayist. Born in Madrid, he studied there and in
Leipzig, Berlin, and Marburg. In 1910 he was ned professor of metaphysics at
the University of Madrid and taught there until 1936, when he was forced to
leave because of his political involvement in and support for the Spanish
Republic. He returned to Spain in 1945. Ortega was a prolific writer whose
works fill nine thick volumes. ong his most influential books are Meditaciones
del Quijote (“Meditations on the Quixote,” 1914), El tema de nuestro tiempo
(“The Modern Theme,” 1923), La revolución de las masas (“The Revolt of the
Masses,” 1932), La deshumanización del arte (“The Dehumanization of Art,”
1925), Historia como sistema (“History as a System,” 1941), and the
posthumously published El hombre y la gente (“Man and People,” 1957) and La
idea de principio en Leibniz(“The Idea of Principle in Leibniz,” 1958). His
influence in Spain and Latin erica was enormous, in part because of his brilliant
style of writing and lecturing. He avoided jargon and rejected systematization;
most of his works were first written as articles for newspapers and magazines.
In 1923 he founded the Revista de Occidente, a cultural magazine that helped
spread his ideas and introduced German thought into Spain and Latin erica.
Ortega ventured into nearly every branch of philosophy, but the kernel of his
views is his metaphysics of vital reason (rasón vital) and his perspectival
epistemology. For Ortega, reality is identified with “my life”; something is
real only insofar as it is rooted and appears in “my life.” “My life” is
further unpacked as “myself” and “my circumstances” (“yo soy yo y mi
circumstancia“). The self is not an entity separate from what surrounds it; there
is a dynic interaction and interdependence of self and things. These and the
self together constitute reality. Because every life is the result of an
interaction between self and circumstances, every self has a unique
perspective. Truth, then, is perspectival, depending on the unique point of
view from which it is determined, and no perspective is false except one that
claims exclusivity. This doctrine is known as Ortega’s perspectivism. J.J.E.G.
ostensive definition.DEFINITION. Ostwald, Wilhelm.ENERGETICISM. other minds,
problem of.PROBLEM OF OTHER MINDS. ought–is problem.
FACT–VALUE DISTINCTION.
ousia, ancient Greek term traditionally translated as ‘substance’. Formed from
the participle for ‘being’, the term ousia refers to the character of being, beingness,
as if this were itself an entity. Just as redness is the character that red
things have, so ousia is the character that beings have. Thus, the ousia of
something is the character that makes it be, its nature. But ousia also refers
to an entity that possesses being in its own right; for consider a case where
the ousia of something is just the thing itself. Such a thing possesses being
by virtue of itself; because its being depends on nothing else, it is
self-subsistent and has a higher degree of being than things whose being
depends on something else. Such a thing would be an ousia. Just which entities
meet the criteria for ousia is a question addressed by Aristotle. Something
such as redness that exists only as an attribute would not have being in its
own right. An individual person is an ousia, but Aristotle also argues that his
form is more properly an ousia; and an unmoved mover is the highest type of
ousia. The traditional rendering of the term into Latin as substantia and
English as ‘substance’ is appropriate only in contexts like Aristotle’s
Categories where an ousia “stands under” attributes. In his Metaphysics, where
Aristotle argues that being a substrate does not characterize ousia, and in
other Greek writers, ‘substance’ is often not an apt translation. SUBSTANCE. E.C.H. outer converse.CONVERSE,
OUTER AND INNER. 637 outer domain
semantics.FREE LOGIC. overdetermination.CAUSATION. overman.NIETZSCHE.
overriding reason.REASONS FOR ACTION. Oxford Calculators, a group of natural
philosophers, mathematicians, and logicians who flourished at Oxford University
in the second quarter of the fourteenth century. The ne derives from the Liber
calculationum (Book of Calculations), written some time before 1350. The author
of this work, often called “Calculator” by later Continental authors, was
probably ned Richard Swineshead. The Book of Calculations discussed a number of
issues related to the quantification or measurement of local motion,
alteration, and augmentation (for a fuller description, see John Murdoch and
Edith Sylla, “Swineshead, Richard,” in Dictionary of Scientific Biography, Vol.
13, 1976). The Book of Calculations has been studied mainly by historians of
science and grouped together with a number of other works discussing natural
philosophical topics by such authors as Thomas Bradwardine, Willi Heytesbury,
and John Dumbleton. In earlier histories many of the authors now referred to as
Oxford Calculators are referred to as the Merton School, since many of them
were fellows of Merton College. But since some authors whose work appears to
fit into the se intellectual tradition (e.g., Richard Kilvington, whose
Sophismata represents an earlier stage of the tradition later epitomized by
Willi Heytesbury’s Sophismata) have no known connection with Merton College,
the ne ‘Oxford Calculators’ would appear to be a more accurate appellation. The
works of the Oxford Calculators were produced in the context of education in
the Oxford arts faculty (see Edith Sylla, “The Oxford Calculators,” in Norman
Kretzmann, Anthony Kenny, and Jan Pinborg, eds., The Cbridge History of Later
Medieval Philosophy, 1982). In Oxford at this time logic was the centerpiece of
the early years of undergraduate education. After logic, Oxford ce to be known
for its work in mathematics, astronomy, and natural philosophy. Students
studying under the Oxford faculty of arts not only heard lectures on the
liberal arts and on natural philosophy, moral philosophy, and metaphysics; they
were also required to take part in disputations. Willi Heytesbury’s Regule
solvendi sophismatum (Rules for Solving Sophismata) explicitly and Swineshead’s
Book of Calculations implicitly are written to prepare students for these
disputations. The three influences most formative on the work of the Oxford Calculators
were (1) the tradition of commentaries on the works of Aristotle; (2) the
developments in logical theory, particularly the theories of categorematic and
syncategorematic terms and the theory of logical supposition; and (3)
developments in mathematics, particularly the theory of ratios as developed in
Thomas Bradwardine’s De proportionibus velocitatum in motibus (On the Ratios of
Velocities in Motions). In addition to Richard Swineshead, Heytesbury,
Bradwardine, Dumbleton, and Kilvington, other authors and works related to the
work of the Oxford Calculators are Walter Burley, De primo et ultimo instanti,
Tractatus Primus (De formis accidentalibus), Tractatus Secundus (De intensione
et remissione formarum); Roger Swineshead, Descriptiones motuum; and John Bode,
A est unum calidum. These and other works had a considerable later influence on
the Continent.
pacifism, (1) opposition
to war, usually on moral or religious grounds, but sometimes on the practical
ground (pragmatic pacifism) that it is wasteful and ineffective; (2) opposition
to all killing and violence; (3) opposition only to war of a specified kind
(e.g., nuclear pacifism). Not to be confused with passivism, pacifism usually
involves actively promoting peace, understood to imply cooperation and justice
ong peoples and not merely absence of war. But some (usually religious)
pacifists accept military service so long as they do not carry weapons. Many
pacifists subscribe to nonviolence. But some consider violence and/or killing
permissible, say, in personal self-defense, law enforcement, abortion, or
euthanasia. Absolute pacifism rejects war in all circumstances, hypothetical
and actual. Conditional pacifism concedes war’s permissibility in some
hypothetical circumstances but maintains its wrongness in practice. If at least
some hypothetical wars have better consequences than their alternative,
absolute pacifism will almost inevitably be deontological in character, holding
war intrinsically wrong or unexceptionably prohibited by moral principle or divine
commandment. Conditional pacifism may be held on either deontological or
utilitarian (teleological or sometimes consequentialist) grounds. If
deontological, it may hold war at most prima facie wrong intrinsically but
nonetheless virtually always impermissible in practice because of the absence
of counterbalancing right-making features. If utilitarian, it will hold war
wrong, not intrinsically, but solely because of its consequences. It may say
either that every particular war has worse consequences than its avoidance (act
utilitarianism) or that general acceptance of (or following or compliance with)
a rule prohibiting war will have best consequences even if occasional
particular wars have best consequences (rule utilitarianism). NONVIOLENCE. R.L.H.
Paine, Thomas
(1737–1809), erican political philosopher, revolutionary defender of democracy
and human rights, and chpion of popular radicalism in three countries. Born in
Thetford, England, he emigrated to the erican colonies in 1774; he later moved
to France, where he was made a French citizen in 1792. In 1802 he returned to
the United States, where he was rebuffed by the public because of his support
for the French Revolution. Paine was the bestknown polemicist for the erican
Revolution. In many incendiary pphlets, he called for a new, more democratic
republicanism. His direct style and uncompromising egalitarianism had wide
popular appeal. In Common Sense (1776) Paine asserted that commoners were the
equal of the landed aristocracy, thus helping to spur colonial resentments
sufficiently to support independence from Britain. The sole basis of political
legitimacy is universal, active consent; taxation without representation is
unjust; and people have the right to resist when the contract between governor
and governed is broken. He defended the French Revolution in The Rights of Man
(1791–92), arguing against concentrating power in any one individual and
against a property qualification for suffrage. Since natural law and right
reason as conformity to nature are accessible to all rational persons,
sovereignty resides in human beings and is not bestowed by membership in class
or nation. Opposed to the extremist Jacobins, he helped write, with Condorcet,
a constitution to secure the Revolution. The Age of Reason (1794), Paine’s most
misunderstood work, sought to secure the social cohesion necessary to a
well-ordered society by grounding it in belief in a divinity. But in supporting
deism and attacking established religion as a tool of enslavement, he alienated
the very laboring classes he sought to enlighten. A lifelong adversary of
slavery and supporter of universal male suffrage, Paine argued for
redistributing property in Agrarian Justice (1797).
Paley, Willi,
(1743–1805), English moral philosopher and theologian. He was born in
Peterborough and educated at Cbridge, 639 P
639 where he lectured in moral philosophy, divinity, and Greek New
Testent before assuming a series of posts in the Church of England, the last as
archdeacon of Carlisle. The Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy (1785)
first introduced utilitarianism to a wide public. Moral obligation is created
by a divine command “coupled” with the expectation of everlasting rewards or
punishments. While God’s commands can be ascertained “from Scripture and the
light of nature,” Paley emphasizes the latter. Since God wills human welfare,
the rightness or wrongness of actions is determined by their “tendency to
promote or diminish the general happiness.” Horae Pauline: Or the Truth of the
Scripture History of St Paul Evinced appeared in 1790, A View of the Evidences
of Christianity in 1794. The latter defends the authenticity of the Christian
miracles against Hume. Natural Theology (1802) provides a design argument for
God’s existence and a demonstration of his attributes. Nature exhibits abundant
contrivances whose “several parts are fred and put together for a purpose.”
These contrivances establish the existence of a powerful, wise, benevolent
designer. They cannot show that its power and wisdom are unlimited, however,
and “omnipotence” and “omniscience” are mere “superlatives.” Paley’s Principles
and Evidences served as textbooks in England and erica well into the nineteenth
century.
panpsychism, the doctrine
that the physical world is pervasively psychical, sentient or conscious
(understood as equivalent). The idea, usually, is that it is articulated into
certain ultimate units or particles, momentary or enduring, each with its own
distinct charge of sentience or consciousness, and that some more complex
physical units possess a sentience emergent from the interaction between the
charges of sentience pertaining to their parts, sometimes down through a series
of levels of articulation into sentient units. Animal consciousness is the
overall sentience pertaining to some substantial part or aspect of the brain,
while each neuron may have its own individual charge of sentience, as may each
included atom and subatomic particle. Elsewhere the only sentient units may be
at the atomic and subatomic level. Two differently motivated versions of the
doctrine should be distinguished. The first implies no particular view about
the nature of matter, and regards the sentience pertaining to each unit as an
extra to its physical nature. Its point is to explain animal and human
consciousness as emerging from the interaction and perhaps fusion of more
pervasive sentient units. The better motivated, second version holds that the
inner essence of matter is unknown. We know only structural facts about the
physical or facts about its effects on sentience like our own. Panpsychists
hypothesize that the otherwise unknown inner essence of matter consists in
sentience or consciousness articulated into the units we identify externally as
fundental particles, or as a supervening character pertaining to complexes of
such or complexes of complexes, etc. Panpsychists can thus uniquely combine the
idealist claim that there can be no reality without consciousness with
rejection of any subjectivist reduction of the physical world to human
experience of it. Modern versions of panpsychism (e.g. of Whitehead,
Hartshorne, and Sprigge) are only partly akin to hylozoism as it occurred in
ancient thought. Note that neither version need claim that every physical
object possesses consciousness; no one supposes that a te of conscious
cricketers must itself be conscious.
HYLOZOISM, WHITEHEAD.
T.L.S.S. pantheism, the view that God is identical with everything. It may be
seen as the result of two tendencies: an intense religious spirit and the belief
that all reality is in some way united. Pantheism should be distinguished from
panentheism, the view that God is in all things. Just as water might saturate a
sponge and in that way be in the entire sponge, but not be identical with the
sponge, God might be in everything without being identical with everything.
Spinoza is the most distinguished pantheist in Western philosophy. He argued
that since substance is completely self-sufficient, and only God is
self-sufficient, God is the only substance. In other words, God is everything.
Hegel is also sometimes considered a pantheist since he identifies God with the
totality of being. Many people think that pantheism is tantount to atheism,
because they believe that theism requires that God transcend ordinary, sensible
reality at least to some degree. It is not obvious that theism requires a
transcendent or Panaetius pantheism 640
640 personal notion of God; and one might claim that the belief that it
does is the result of an anthropomorphic view of God. In Eastern philosophy,
especially the Vedic tradition of Indian philosophy, pantheism is part of a
rejection of polytheism. The apparent multiplicity of reality is illusion. What
is ultimately real or divine is Brahman.
Pantheismusstreit
(German, ‘dispute over pantheism’), a debate primarily between the German
philosophers Jacobi and Mendelssohn, although it also included Lessing, Kant,
and Goethe. The basic issue concerned what pantheism is and whether all
pantheists are atheists. In particular, it concerned whether Spinoza was a
pantheist, and if so, whether he was an atheist; and how close Lessing’s
thought was to Spinoza’s. The standard view, propounded by Bayle and Leibniz,
was that Spinoza’s pantheism was a thin veil for his atheism. Lessing and Goethe
did not accept this harsh interpretation of him. They believed that his
pantheism avoided the alienating transcendence of the standard Judeo-Christian
concept of God. It was debated whether Lessing was a Spinozist or some form of
theistic pantheist. Lessing was critical of dogmatic religions and denied that
there was any revelation given to all people for rational acceptance. He may
have told Jacobi that he was a Spinozist; but he may also have been speaking
ironically or hypothetically.
SPINOZA. A.P.M.
Paracelsus, pseudonym of Theophrastus Bombastus von Hohenheim (1493–1541),
Swiss chemist, physician, and natural philosopher. He pursued medical studies
at various German and Austrian universities, probably completing them at
Ferrara (1513–16). Thereafter he had little to do with the academic world,
apart from a brief and stormy period as professor of medicine at Basle
(1527–28). Instead, he worked first as a military surgeon and later as an
itinerant physician in Germany, Austria, and Switzerland. His works were mainly
in German rather than Latin, and only a few were published during his lifetime.
His importance for medical practice lay in his insistence on observation and
experiment, and his use of chemical methods for preparing drugs. The success of
Paracelsian medicine and chemistry in the later sixteenth and seventeenth
centuries was, however, largely due to the theoretical background he provided.
He firmly rejected the classical medical inheritance, particularly Galen’s
explanation of disease as an imbalance of humors; he drew on a combination of
biblical sources, German mysticism, alchemy, and Neoplatonic magic as found in
Ficino to present a unified view of humankind and the universe. He saw man as a
microcosm, reflecting the nature of the divine world through his immortal soul,
the sidereal world through his astral body or vital principle, and the
terrestrial world through his visible body. Knowledge requires union with the
object, but because elements of all the worlds are found in man, he can acquire
knowledge of the universe and of God, as partially revealed in nature. The
physician needs knowledge of vital principles (called astra) in order to heal.
Disease is caused by external agents that can affect the human vital principle
as well as the visible body. Chemical methods are employed to isolate the
appropriate vital principles in minerals and herbs, and these are used as
antidotes. Paracelsus further held that matter contains three principles,
sulfur, mercury, and salt. As a result, he thought it was possible to transform
one metal into another by varying the proportions of the fundental principles;
and that such transformations could also be used in the production of
drugs. ALCHEMY, MYSTICISM. E.J.A.
paraconsistency, the property of a logic in which one cannot derive all
statements from a contradiction. What is objectionable about contradictions,
from the standpoint of classical logic, is not just that they are false but
that they imply any statement whatsoever: one who accepts a contradiction is thereby
committed to accepting everything. In paraconsistent logics, however, such as
relevance logics, contradictions are isolated inferentially and thus rendered
relatively harmless. The interest in such logics stems from the fact that
people sometimes continue to work in inconsistent theories even after the
inconsistency has been exposed, and do so without inferring everything. Whether
this phenomenon can be explained satisfactorily by the classical logician or
shows instead that the underlying logic of, e.g., science and mathematics is
some non-classical paraconsistent logic, is disputed.
paradigm, as used by Thomas Kuhn (The
Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 1962), a set of scientific and
metaphysical beliefs that make up a theoretical frework within which scientific
theories Pantheismusstreit paradigm 641
641 can be tested, evaluated, and if necessary revised. Kuhn’s principal
thesis, in which the notion of a paradigm plays a central role, is structured
around an argument against the logical empiricist view of scientific theory
change. Empiricists viewed theory change as an ongoing smooth and cumulative
process in which empirical facts, discovered through observation or
experimentation, forced revisions in our theories and thus added to our ever-increasing
knowledge of the world. It was claimed that, combined with this process of
revision, there existed a process of intertheoretic reduction that enabled us
to understand the macro in terms of the micro, and that ultimately aimed at a
unity of science. Kuhn maintains that this view is incompatible with what
actually happens in case after case in the history of science. Scientific
change occurs by “revolutions” in which an older paradigm is overthrown and is
replaced by a frework incompatible or even incommensurate with it. Thus the
alleged empirical “facts,” which were adduced to support the older theory,
become irrelevant to the new; the questions asked and answered in the new
frework cut across those of the old; indeed the vocabularies of the two freworks
make up different languages, not easily intertranslatable. These episodes of
revolution are separated by long periods of “normal science,” during which the
theories of a given paradigm are honed, refined, and elaborated. These periods
are sometimes referred to as periods of “puzzle solving,” because the changes
are to be understood more as fiddling with the details of the theories to “save
the phenomena” than as steps taking us closer to the truth. A number of
philosophers have complained that Kuhn’s conception of a paradigm is too
imprecise to do the work he intended for it. In fact, Kuhn, fifteen years
later, admitted that at least two distinct ideas were exploited by the term:
(i) the “shared elements [that] account for the relatively unproblematic
character of professional communication and for the relative unanimity of
professional judgment,” and (ii) “concrete problem solutions, accepted by the
group [of scientists] as, in a quite usual sense, paradigmatic” (Kuhn, “Second
Thoughts on Paradigms,” 1977). Kuhn offers the terms ‘disciplinary matrix’ and
‘exemplar’, respectively, for these two ideas.
paradigm case argument,
an argument designed to yield an affirmative answer to the following general
type of skeptically motivated question: Are A’s really B? E.g., Do material
objects really exist? Are any of our actions really free? Does induction really
provide reasonable grounds for one’s beliefs? The structure of the argument is
simple: in situations that are “typical,” “exemplary,” or “paradigmatic,”
standards for which are supplied by common sense, or ordinary language, part of
what it is to be B essentially involves A. Hence it is absurd to doubt if A’s
are ever B, or to doubt if in general A’s are B. (More commonly, the argument
is encountered in the linguistic mode: part of what it means for something to
be B is that, in paradigm cases, it be an A. Hence the question whether A’s are
ever B is meaningless.) An exple may be found in the application of the
argument to the problem of induction. (See Strawson, Introduction to Logical
Theory, 1952.) When one believes a generalization of the form ‘All F’s are G’
on the basis of good inductive evidence, i.e., evidence constituted by
innumerable and varied instances of F all of which are G, one would thereby
have good reasons for holding this belief. The argument for this claim is based
on the content of the concepts of reasonableness and of strength of evidence.
Thus according to Strawson, the following two propositions are analytic: (1) It
is reasonable to have a degree of belief in a proposition that is proportional
to the strength of the evidence in its favor. (2) The evidence for a
generalization is strong in proportion as the number of instances, and the
variety of circumstances in which they have been found, is great. Hence,
Strawson concludes, “to ask whether it is reasonable to place reliance on
inductive procedures is like asking whether it is reasonable to proportion the
degree of one’s convictions to the strength of the evidence. Doing this is what
‘being reasonable’ means in such a context” (p. 257). In such arguments the
role played by the appeal to paradigm cases is crucial. In Strawson’s version,
paradigm cases are constituted by “innumerable and varied instances.” Without
such an appeal the argument would fail completely, for it is clear that not all
uses of induction are reasonable. Even when this appeal is made clear though,
the argument remains questionable, for it fails to confront adequately the
force of the word ‘really’ in the skeptical challenges.
paradox, a seemingly
sound piece of reasoning based on seemingly true assumptions that leads to a
contradiction (or other obviously false conclusion). A paradox reveals that
either the principles of reasoning or the assumptions on which it is based are
faulty. It is said to be solved when the mistaken principles or assumptions are
clearly identified and rejected. The philosophical interest in paradoxes arises
from the fact that they sometimes reveal fundentally mistaken assumptions or
erroneous reasoning techniques. Two groups of paradoxes have received a great
deal of attention in modern philosophy. Known as the semantic paradoxes and the
logical or settheoretic paradoxes, they reveal serious difficulties in our
intuitive understanding of the basic notions of semantics and set theory. Other
well-known paradoxes include the barber paradox and the prediction (or hangman
or unexpected exination) paradox. The barber paradox is mainly useful as an
exple of a paradox that is easily resolved. Suppose we are told that there is
an Oxford barber who shaves all and only the Oxford men who do not shave
themselves. Using this description, we can apparently derive the contradiction
that this barber both shaves and does not shave himself. (If he does not shave
himself, then according to the description he must be one of the people he
shaves; if he does shave himself, then according to the description he is one
of the people he does not shave.) This paradox can be resolved in two ways.
First, the original claim that such a barber exists can simply be rejected:
perhaps no one satisfies the alleged description. Second, the described barber
may exist, but not fall into the class of Oxford men: a woman barber, e.g.,
could shave all and only the Oxford men who do not shave themselves. The
prediction paradox takes a variety of forms. Suppose a teacher tells her
students on Friday that the following week she will give a single quiz. But it
will be a surprise: the students will not know the evening before that the quiz
will take place the following day. They reason that she cannot give such a
quiz. After all, she cannot wait until Friday to give it, since then they would
know Thursday evening. That leaves Monday through Thursday as the only possible
days for it. But then Thursday can be ruled out for the se reason: they would
know on Wednesday evening. Wednesday, Tuesday, and Monday can be ruled out by
similar reasoning. Convinced by this seemingly correct reasoning, the students
do not study for the quiz. On Wednesday morning, they are taken by surprise
when the teacher distributes it. It has been pointed out that the students’
reasoning has this peculiar feature: in order to rule out any of the days, they
must assume that the quiz will be given and that it will be a surprise. But
their alleged conclusion is that it cannot be given or else will not be a
surprise, undermining that very assumption. Kaplan and Montague have argued (in
“A Paradox Regained,” Notre De Journal of Formal Logic, 1960) that at the core
of this puzzle is what they call the knower paradox – a paradox that arises
when intuitively plausible principles about knowledge (and its relation to
logical consequence) are used in conjunction with knowledge claims whose
content is, or entails, a denial of those very claims.
paradoxes of omnipotence,
a series of paradoxes in philosophical theology that maintain that God could
not be omnipotent because the concept is inconsistent, alleged to result from
the intuitive idea that if God is omnipotent, then God must be able to do
anything. (1) Can God perform logically contradictory tasks? If God can, then
God should be able to make himself simultaneously omnipotent and not
omnipotent, which is absurd. If God cannot, then it appears that there is
something God cannot do. Many philosophers have sought to avoid this
consequence by claiming that the notion of performing a logically contradictory
task is empty, and that question (1) specifies no task that God can perform or
fail to perform. (2) Can God cease to be omnipotent? If God can and were to do
so, then at any time thereparadox paradoxes of omnipotence 643 643 after, God would no longer be
completely sovereign over all things. If God cannot, then God cannot do
something that others can do, nely, impose limitations on one’s own powers. A
popular response to question (2) is to say that omnipotence is an essential
attribute of a necessarily existing being. According to this response, although
God cannot cease to be omnipotent any more than God can cease to exist, these
features are not liabilities but rather the lack of liabilities in God. (3) Can
God create another being who is omnipotent? Is it logically possible for two
beings to be omnipotent? It might seem that there could be, if they never
disagreed in fact with each other. If, however, omnipotence requires control
over all possible but counterfactual situations, there could be two omnipotent
beings only if it were impossible for them to disagree. (4) Can God create a
stone too heavy for God to move? If God can, then there is something that God
cannot do – move such a stone – and if God cannot, then there is something God
cannot do – create such a stone. One reply is to maintain that ‘God cannot
create a stone too heavy for God to move’ is a harmless consequence of ‘God can
create stones of any weight and God can move stones of any weight.’
paradox of analysis, an
argument that it is impossible for an analysis of a meaning to be informative
for one who already understands the meaning. Consider: ‘An F is a G’ (e.g., ‘A
circle is a line all points on which are equidistant from some one point’)
gives a correct analysis of the meaning of ‘F’ only if ‘G’ means the se as ‘F’;
but then anyone who already understands both meanings must already know what
the sentence says. Indeed, that will be the se as what the trivial ‘An F is an
F’ says, since replacing one expression by another with the se meaning should
preserve what the sentence says. The conclusion that ‘An F is a G’ cannot be
informative (for one who already understands all its terms) is paradoxical only
for cases where ‘G’ is not only synonymous with but more complex than ‘F’, in
such a way as to give an analysis of ‘F’. (‘A first cousin is an offspring of a
parent’s sibling’ gives an analysis, but ‘A dad is a father’ does not and in
fact could not be informative for one who already knows the meaning of all its
words.) The paradox appears to fail to distinguish between different sorts of
knowledge. Encountering for the first time (and understanding) a correct
analysis of a meaning one already grasps brings one from merely tacit to
explicit knowledge of its truth. One sees that it does capture the meaning and
thereby sees a way of articulating the meaning one had not thought of
before. ANALYSIS, DEFINITION, MEANING.
C.G. paradox of omniscience, an objection to the possibility of omniscience,
developed by Patrick Grim, that appeals to an application of Cantor’s power set
theorem. Omniscience requires knowing all truths; according to Grim, that means
knowing every truth in the set of all truths. But there is no set of all
truths. Suppose that there were a set T of all truths. Consider all the subsets
of T, that is, all members of the power set 3T. Take some truth T1. For each
member of 3T either T1 is a member of that set or T1 is not a member of that
set. There will thus correspond to each member of 3T a further truth specifying
whether T1 is or is not a member of that set. Therefore there are at least as
many truths as there are members of 3T. By the power set theorem, there are
more members of 3T than there are of T. So T is not the set of all truths. By a
parallel argument, no other set is, either. So there is no set of all truths,
after all, and therefore no one who knows every member of that set. The
objection may be countered by denying that the claim ‘for every proposition p,
if p is true God knows that p’ requires that there be a set of all true
propositions.
parapsychology, the study
of certain anomalous phenomena and ostensible causal connections neither
recognized nor clearly rejected by traditional science. Parapsychology’s
principal areas of investigation are extrasensory perception (ESP),
psychokinesis (PK), and cases suggesting the survival of mental functioning
following bodily death. The study of ESP has traditionally focused on two sorts
of ostensible phenomena, telepathy (the apparent anomalous influence of one
person’s mental states on those of another, commonly identified with apparent
communication between two minds by extrasensory means) and clairvoyance (the
apparent anomalous influence of a physical state of affairs on a person’s
mental states, commonly identified with the supposed ability to perceive or
know of objects or events not present to the senses). The forms of ESP may be
viewed either as types of cognition (e.g., the anomalous knowledge of another
person’s mental states) or as merely a form of anomalous causal influence
(e.g., a distant burning house causing one to have – possibly incongruous –
thoughts about fire). The study of PK covers the apparent ability to produce
various physical effects independently of filiar or recognized intermediate
sorts of causal links. These effects include the ostensible movement of remote
objects, materializations (the apparently instantaneous production of matter), apports
(the apparently instantaneous relocation of an object), and (in laboratory
experiments) statistically significant non-random behavior of normally random
microscopic processes (such as radioactive decay). Survival research focuses on
cases of ostensible reincarnation and mental mediumship (i.e., “channeling” of
information from an apparently deceased communicator). Cases of ostensible
precognition may be viewed as types of telepathy and clairvoyance, and suggest
the causal influence of some state of affairs on an earlier event (an agent’s
ostensible precognitive experience). However, those opposed to backward
causation may interpret ostensible precognition either as a form of unconscious
inference based on contemporaneous information acquired by ESP, or else as a
form of PK (possibly in conjunction with telepathic influence) by which the
precognizer brings about the events apparently precognized. The data of
parapsychology raise two particularly deep issues. The evidence suggesting
survival poses a direct challenge to materialist theories of the mental. And
the evidence for ESP and PK suggests the viability of a “magical” worldview
associated usually with so-called primitive societies, according to which we
have direct and intimate access to and influence on the thoughts and bodily
states of others.
Pareto efficiency, also
called Pareto optimality, a state of affairs in which no one can be made better
off without making someone worse off. The Italian economist Vilfredo Pareto
(1848–1923) referred to optimality rather than efficiency, but usage has
drifted toward the less normative term. Pareto supposed that utilitarian
addition of welfare across individuals is meaningless. He concluded that the
only useful aggregate measures of welfare must be ordinal. One state of affairs
is Pareto-superior to another if we cannot move to the second state without
making someone worse off. Although the Pareto criteria are generally thought to
be positive rather than normative, they are often used as normative principles for
justifying particular changes or refusals to make changes. For exple, some
economists and philosophers take the Pareto criteria as moral constraints and
therefore oppose certain government policies. In market and voluntary exchange
contexts, it makes sense to suppose every exchange will be Pareto-improving, at
least for the direct parties to the exchange. If, however, we fail to account
for external effects of our exchange on other people, it may not be
Pareto-improving. Moreover, we may fail to provide collective benefits that
require the cooperation or coordination of many individuals’ efforts. Hence,
even in markets, we cannot expect to achieve Pareto efficiency. We might
therefore suppose we should invite government intervention to help us. But in typical
social contexts, it is often hard to believe that significant policy changes
can be Paretoimproving: there are sure to be losers from any change. PERFECT COMPETITION, SOCIAL CHOICE THEORY,
UTILITARIANISM. R.Har. Pareto optimality.PARETO EFFICIENCY. Pareto-superior.PARETO
EFFICIENCY. parallel distributed processing Pareto-superior 645 645 Parfit, Derek (b.1942), British
philosopher internationally known for his major contributions to the
metaphysics of persons, moral theory, and practical reasoning. Parfit first
rose to prominence by challenging the prevalent view that personal identity is
a “deep fact” that must be all or nothing and that matters greatly in rational
and moral deliberations. Exploring puzzle cases involving fission and fusion,
Parfit propounded a reductionist account of personal identity, arguing that
what matters in survival are physical and psychological continuities. These are
a matter of degree, and sometimes there may be no answer as to whether some
future person would be me. Parfit’s magnum opus, Reasons and Persons (1984), is
a strikingly original book brimming with startling conclusions that have
significantly reshaped the philosophical agenda. Part One treats different
theories of morality, rationality, and the good; bleless wrongdoing; moral
immorality; rational irrationality; imperceptible harms and benefits; harmless
torturers; and the self-defeatingness of certain theories. Part Two introduces
a critical present-aim theory of individual rationality, and attacks the standard
selfinterest theory. It also discusses the rationality of different attitudes
to time, such as caring more about the future than the past, and more about the
near than the remote. Addressing the age-old conflict between self-interest and
morality, Parfit illustrates that contrary to what the self-interest theory
demands, it can be rational to care about certain other aims as much as, or
more than, about our own future well-being. In addition, Parfit notes that the
self-interest theory is a hybrid position, neutral with respect to time but
partial with respect to persons. Thus, it can be challenged from one direction
by morality, which is neutral with respect to both persons and time, and from
the other by a present-aim theory, which is partial with respect to both
persons and time. Part Three refines Parfit’s views regarding personal identity
and further criticizes the self-interest theory: personal identity is not what
matters, hence reasons to be specially concerned about our future are not
provided by the fact that it will be our future. Part Four presents puzzles
regarding future generations and argues that the moral principles we need when
considering future people must take an impersonal form. Parfit’s arguments
deeply challenge our understanding of moral ideals and, some believe, the
possibility of comparing outcomes. Parfit has three forthcoming manuscripts,
tentatively titled Rediscovering Reasons, The Metaphysics of the Self, and On
What Matters. His current focus is the normativity of reasons. A reductionist
about persons, he is a non-reductionist about reasons. He believes in
irreducibily normative beliefs that are in a strong sense true. A realist about
reasons for acting and caring, he challenges the views of naturalists,
noncognitivists, and constructivists. Parfit contends that internalists
conflate normativity with motivating force, that contrary to the prevalent view
that all reasons are provided by desires, no reasons are, and that Kant poses a
greater threat to rationalism than Hume. Parfit is Senior Research Fellow of
All Souls College, Oxford, and a regular visiting professor at both Harvard and
New York University. Legendary for monograph-length criticisms of book
manuscripts, he is editor of the Oxford Ethics Series, whose goal is to make
definite moral progress, a goal Parfit himself is widely believed to have
attained.
Parmenides (early fifth
century B.C.), Greek philosopher, the most influential of the preSocratics,
active in Elea (Roman and modern Velia), an Ionian Greek colony in southern
Italy. He was the first Greek thinker who can properly be called an ontologist
or metaphysician. Plato refers to him as “venerable and awesome,” as “having
magnificent depth” (Theaetetus 183e– 184a), and presents him in the dialogue
Parmenides as a searching critic – in a fictional and dialectical transposition
– of Plato’s own theory of Forms. Nearly 150 lines of a didactic poem by
Parmenides have been preserved, assembled into about twenty fragments. The
first part, “Truth,” provides the earliest specimen in Greek intellectual
history of a sustained deductive argument. Drawing on intuitions concerning
thinking, knowing, and language, Parmenides argues that “the real” or “what-is”
or “being” (to eon) must be ungenerable and imperishable, indivisible, and
unchanging. According to a Plato-inspired tradition, Parmenides held that “all
is one.” But the phrase does not occur in the fragments; Parmenides does not
even speak of “the One”; and it is possible that either a holistic One or a
plurality of absolute monads might conform to Parmenides’ deduction.
Nonetheless, it is difficult to resist the impression that the argument
converges on a unique entity, which may indifferParfit, Derek Parmenides
646 646 ently be referred to as Being,
or the All, or the One. Parmenides embraces fully the paradoxical consequence
that the world of ordinary experience fails to qualify as “what-is.”
Nonetheless, in “Opinions,” the second part of the poem, he expounds a dualist
cosmology. It is unclear whether this is intended as candid phenomenology – a
doctrine of appearances – or as an ironic foil to “Truth.” It is noteworthy
that Parmenides was probably a physician by profession. Ancient reports to this
effect are borne out by fragments (from “Opinions”) with embryological themes,
as well as by archaeological findings at Velia that link the memory of
Parmenides with Romanperiod remains of a medical school at that site.
Parmenides’ own attitude notwithstanding, “Opinions” recorded four major
scientific breakthroughs, some of which, doubtless, were Parmenides’ own
discoveries: that the earth is a sphere; that the two tropics and the Arctic
and Antarctic circles divide the earth into five zones; that the moon gets its
light from the sun; and that the morning star and the evening star are the se
planet. The term Eleatic School is misleading when it is used to suggest a
common doctrine supposedly held by Parmenides, Zeno of Elea, Melissus of Sos,
and (anticipating Parmenides) Xenophanes of Colophon. The fact is, many
philosophical groups and movements, from the middle of the fifth century
onward, were influenced, in different ways, by Parmenides, including the
“pluralists,” Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and Democritus. Parmenides’ deductions,
transformed by Zeno into a repertoire of full-blown paradoxes, provided the
model both for the eristic of the Sophists and for Socrates’ elenchus.
Moreover, the Parmenidean criteria for “whatis” lie unmistakably in the
background not only of Plato’s theory of Forms but also of salient features of
Aristotle’s system, notably, the priority of actuality over potentiality, the
unmoved mover, and the man-begets-man principle. Indeed, all philosophical and
scientific systems that posit principles of conservation (of substance, of
matter, of matter-energy) are inalienably the heirs to Parmenides’
deduction. ELEATIC SCHOOL, MELISSUS OF
SOS, PRE-SOCRATICS. A.P.D.M. parousia.PLATO. parse tree.PARSING. parsimony,
principle of.OCKH’S RAZOR.
parsing, the process of
determining the syntactic structure of a sentence according to the rules of a
given grmar. This is to be distinguished from the generally simpler task of
recognition, which is merely the determination of whether or not a given string
is well-formed (grmatical). In general, many different parsing strategies can
be employed for grmars of a particular type, and a great deal of attention has
been given to the relative efficiencies of these techniques. The most
thoroughly studied cases center on the contextfree phrase structure grmars,
which assign syntactic structures in the form of singly-rooted trees with a
left-to-right ordering of “sister” nodes. Parsing procedures can then be
broadly classified according to the sequence of steps by which the parse tree
is constructed: top-down versus bottom-up; depth-first versus breadthfirst;
etc. In addition, there are various strategies for exploring alternatives
(agendas, backtracking, parallel processing) and there are devices such as
“charts” that eliminate needless repetitions of previous steps. Efficient
parsing is of course important when language, whether natural or artificial
(e.g., a progrming language), is being processed by computer. Human beings also
parse rapidly and with apparently little effort when they comprehend sentences
of a natural language. Although little is known about the details of this
process, psycholinguists hope that study of mechanical parsing techniques might
provide insights. GRMAR. R.E.W. partial
belief.PROBABILITY. partial function.MATHEMATICAL FUNCTION. partial
order.RELATION. partial ordering.ORDERING. participation.PLATO.
particular.CONCEPTUALISM, INDIVIDUATION, METAPHYSICS. particular,
bare.METAPHYSICS. particular, basic.STRAWSON. particularism.PROBLEM OF THE
CRITERION.
particular
proposition.SYLLOGISM. partition, division of a set into mutually exclusive and
jointly exhaustive subsets. Derivatively, parousia partition 647 647 ‘partition’ can mean any set P whose
members are mutually exclusive and jointly exhaustive subsets of set S. Each subset
of a partition P is called a partition class of S with respect to P. Partitions
are intimately associated with equivalence relations, i.e. with relations that
are transitive, symmetric, and reflexive. Given an equivalence relation R
defined on a set S, R induces a partition P of S in the following natural way:
members s1 and s2 belong to the se partition class of P if and only if s1 has
the relation R to s2. Conversely, given a partition P of a set S, P induces an
equivalence relation R defined on S in the following natural way: members s1 and
s2 are such that s1 has the relation R to s2 if and only if s1 and s2 belong to
the se partition class of P. For obvious reasons, then, partition classes are
also known as equivalence classes.
RELATION, SET THEORY. R.W.B. Parva naturalia.
ARISTOTLE. Pascal, Blaise
(1623–62), French philosopher known for his brilliance as a mathematician,
physicist, inventor, theologian, polemicist, and French prose stylist. Born at
Clermont-Ferrand in the Auvergne, he was educated by his father, Étienne, and
first gained note for his contribution to mathematics when at sixteen he
produced, under the influence of Desargues, a work on the projective geometry
of the cone. This was published in 1640 under the title Essai pour les coniques
and includes what has since become known as Pascal’s theorem. Pascal’s other
mathematical accomplishments include the original development of probability
theory, worked out in correspondence with Fermat, and a method of infinitesimal
analysis to which Leibniz gave credit for inspiring his own development of the
calculus. Pascal’s early scientific fe rests also on his work in physics, which
includes a treatise on hydrostatics (Traités de l’équilibre des liqueurs et de
la pesanteur de la masse de l’air) and his experiments with the barometer, which
attempted to establish the possibility of a vacuum and the weight of air as the
cause of the mercury’s suspension. Pascal’s fe as a stylist rests primarily on
his Lettres provinciales (1656–57), which were an anonymous contribution to a
dispute between the Jansenists, headed by Arnauld, and the Jesuits. Jansenism
was a Catholic religious movement that emphasized an Augustinian position on
questions of grace and free will. Pascal, who was not himself a Jansenist,
wrote a series of scathing satirical letters ridiculing both Jesuit casuistry
and the persecution of the Jansenists for their purported adherence to five
propositions in Jansen’s Augustinus. Pascal’s philosophical contributions are
found throughout his work, but primarily in his Pensées (1670), an intended
apology for Christianity left incomplete and fragmentary at his death. The
influence of the Pensées on religious thought and later existentialism has been
profound because of their extraordinary insight, passion, and depth. At the
time of Pascal’s death some of the fragments were sewn together in clusters;
many others were left unorganized, but recent scholarship has recovered much of
the original plan of organization. The Pensées raise skeptical arguments that
had become part of philosophical parlance since Montaigne. While these
arguments were originally raised in order to deny the possibility of knowledge,
Pascal, like Descartes in the Meditations, tries to utilize them toward a
positive end. He argues that what skepticism shows us is not that knowledge is
impossible, but that there is a certain paradox about human nature: we possess
knowledge yet recognize that this knowledge cannot be rationally justified and
that rational arguments can even be directed against it (fragments 109, 131,
and 110). This peculiarity can be explained only through the Christian doctrine
of the fall (e.g., fragment 117). Pascal extends his skeptical considerations
by undermining the possibility of demonstrative proof of God’s existence. Such
knowledge is impossible on philosophical grounds because such a proof could be
successful only if an absurdity followed from denying God’s existence, and
nature furnishes us with no knowledge incompatible with unbelief (fragments 429
and 781). Furthermore, demonstrative proof of God’s existence is incompatible
with the epistemological claims of Christianity, which make God’s personal
agency essential to religious knowledge (fragments 460, 449). Pascal’s use of
skepticism and his refusal to admit proofs of God’s existence have led some
commentators, like Richard Popkin (“Fideism,” 1967) and Terence Penelhum
(“Skepticism and Fideism,” 1983) to interpret Pascal as a fideist, i.e., one
who denies that religious belief can be based on anything other than pragmatic
reasons. But such an interpretation disregards Pascal’s attempts to show that
Christian belief is rational because of the explanatory power of its doctrines,
particularly its doctrine of the fall (e.g., fragments 131, 137, 149, 431, 449,
and 482). These purported demonstrations of the explanatory superiority of
Christianity prepare Parva naturalia Pascal, Blaise 648 648 the way for Pascal’s fous “wager”
(fragment 418). The wager is ong the fragments that Pascal had not classified
at the time of his death, but textual evidence shows that it would have been
included in Section 12, entitled “Commencement,” after the demonstrations of
the superior explanatory power of Christianity. The wager is a direct
application of the principles developed in Pascal’s earlier work on probability,
where he discovered a calculus that could be used to determine the most
rational action when faced with uncertainty about future events, or what is now
known as decision theory. In this case the uncertainty is the truth of
Christianity and its claims about afterlife; and the actions under
consideration are whether to believe or not. The choice of the most rational
action depends on what would now be called its “expected value.” The expected
value of an action is determined by (1) assigning a value, s, to each possible
outcome of the action, (2) subtracting the cost of the action, c, from this
value, and (3) multiplying the difference by the probability of the respective
outcomes and adding these products together. Pascal invites the reader to
consider Christian faith and unbelief as if they were acts of wagering on the
truth of Christianity. If one believes, then there are two possible outcomes –
either God exists or not. If God does exist, the stake to be gained is infinite
life. If God does not exist, there are no winnings. Because the potential
winnings are infinite, religious belief is more rational than unbelief because
of its greater expected value. The wager has been subjected to numerous
criticisms. Willi Jes argued that it is indecisive, because it would apply with
equal validity to any religion that offers a promise of infinite rewards (The
Will to Believe, 1897). But this ignores Pascal’s careful attempt to show that
only Christianity has adequate explanatory power, so that the choice is
intended to be between Christianity and unbelief. A stronger objection to the
wager arises from contemporary work in decision theory that prohibits the
introduction of infinite values because they have the counterintuitive result
of making even the slightest risk irrational. But while these objections are
valid, they do not refute Pascal’s strategy in the Pensées, in which the proofs
of Christianity’s explanatory power and the wager have only the preliminary
role of inducing the reader to seek the religious certainty that comes only
from a saving religious experience which he calls “inspiration” (fragments 110,
381, 382, 588, 808).
paternalism, interference
with the liberty or autonomy of another person, with justifications referring
to the promotion of the person’s good or the prevention of harm to the person.
More precisely, P acts paternalistically toward Q if and only if (a) P acts
with the intent of averting some harm or promoting some benefit for Q; (b) P
acts contrary to (or is indifferent to) the current preferences, desires or
values of Q; and (c) P’s act is a limitation on Q’s autonomy or liberty. The
presence of both autonomy and liberty in clause (c) is to allow for the fact
that lying to someone is not clearly an interference with liberty. Notice that
one can act paternalistically by telling people the truth (as when a doctor
insists that a patient know the exact nature of her illness, contrary to her
wishes). Note also that the definition does not settle any questions about the
legitimacy or illegitimacy of paternalistic interventions. Typical exples of
paternalistic actions are (1) laws requiring motorcyclists to wear helmets; (2)
court orders allowing physicians to transfuse Jehovah’s Witnesses against their
wishes; (3) deception of a patient by physicians to avoid upsetting the
patient; (4) civil commitment of persons judged dangerous to themselves; and
(5) laws forbidding swimming while lifeguards are not on duty. Soft (weak)
paternalism is the view that paternalism is justified only when a person is acting
non-voluntarily or one needs time to determine whether the person is acting
voluntarily or not. Hard (strong) paternalism is the view that paternalism is
sometimes justified even when the person being interfered with is acting
voluntarily. The analysis of the term is relative to some set of problems. If
one were interested in the orgaPascal’s wager paternalism 649 649 nizational behavior of large
corporations, one might adopt a different definition than if one were concerned
with limits on the state’s right to exercise coercion. The typical normative
problems about paternalistic actions are whether, and to what extent, the
welfare of individuals may outweigh the need to respect their desire to lead
their own lives and make their own decisions (even when mistaken). J. S. Mill
is the best exple of a virtually absolute antipaternalism, at least with
respect to the right of the state to act paternalistically. He argued that
unless we have reason to believe that a person is not acting voluntarily, as in
the case of a man walking across a bridge that, unknown to him, is about to
collapse, we ought to allow adults the freedom to act even if their acts are
harmful to themselves.
patristic authors, also
called church fathers, a group of early Christian authors originally so ned
because they were considered the “fathers” (patres) of the orthodox Christian
churches. The term is now used more broadly to designate the Christian writers,
orthodox or heterodox, who were active in the first six centuries or so of the Christian
era. The chronological division is quite flexible, and it is regularly moved
several centuries later for particular purposes. Moreover, the study of these
writers has traditionally been divided by languages, of which the principal
ones are Greek, Latin, and Syriac. The often sharp divisions ong patristic
scholarships in the different languages are partly a reflection of the
different histories of the regional churches, partly a reflection of the
sociology of modern scholarship. Greeks. The patristic period in Greek is
usually taken as extending from the first writers after the New Testent to such
figures as Maximus the Confessor (579/580–662) or John of Dascus (c.650–c.750).
The period is traditionally divided around the Council of Nicea (325). PreNicean
Greek authors of importance to the history of philosophy include Irenaeus
(130/140– after 198?), Clement of Alexandria (c.150–after 215), and Origen
(c.180–c.254). Important Nicean and post-Nicean authors include Athanasius
(c.295–373); the Cappadocians, i.e., Gregory of Nazianzus (c.330–90), Basil of
Cesarea (c.330–79), and his brother, Gregory of Nyssa (335/340–c.394); and John
Chrysostom (c.350– 407). Philosophical topics and practices are constantly
engaged by these Greek authors. Justin Martyr (second century), e.g., describes
his conversion to Christianity quite explicitly as a transit through lower
forms of philosophy into the true philosophy. Clement of Alexandria, again,
uses the philosophic genre of the protreptic and a host of ancient texts to
persuade his pagan readers that they ought to come to Christianity as to the
true wisdom. Origen devotes his Against Celsus to the detailed rebuttal of one
pagan philosopher’s attack on Christianity. More importantly, if more subtly,
the major works of the Cappadocians appropriate and transform the teachings of
any number of philosophic authors – Plato and the Neoplatonists in first place,
but also Aristotle, the Stoics, and Galen. Latins. The Latin churches ce to
count four post-Nicean authors as its chief teachers: brose (337/339–97),
Jerome (c.347–419), Augustine (354–430), and Gregory the Great (c.540–604).
Other Latin authors of philosophical interest include Tertullian (fl.
c.195–c.220), Lactantius (c.260–c.330), Marius Victorinus (280/285–before 386),
and Hilary of Poitiers (fl. 356–64). The Latin patristic period is typically
counted from the second century to the fifth or sixth, i.e., roughly from
Tertullian to Boethius. The Latin authors share with their Greek contemporaries
a range of relations to the pagan philosophic schools, both as rival
institutions and as sources of useful teaching. Tertullian’s Against the
Nations and Apology, for exple, take up pagan accusations against Christianity
and then counterattack a number of pagan beliefs, including philosophical ones.
By contrast, the writings of Marius Victorinus, brose, and Augustine enact
transformations of philosophic teachings, especially from the Neoplatonists.
Because philosophical erudition was generally not as great ong the Latins as ong
the Greeks, they were both more eager to accept philosophical doctrines and
freer in improvising variations on them.
Paul of Venice
(c.1368–1429), Italian philosopher and theologian. A Hermit of Saint Augustine
(O.E.S.A.), he spent three years as a student patriarchalism Paul of Venice
650 650 in Oxford (1390–93) and taught
at the University of Padua, where he bece a doctor of arts and theology in
1408. He also held appointments at the universities of Parma, Siena, and
Bologna. He was active in the administration of his order, holding various high
offices. Paul of Venice wrote commentaries on several logical, ethical, and
physical works of Aristotle, but his ne is connected especially with an
extremely popular textbook, Logica parva (over 150 manuscripts survive, and
more than forty printed editions of it were made), and with a huge Logica
magna. These Oxford-influenced works contributed to the favorable climate
enjoyed by the English logic in northern Italian universities from the late
fourteenth century through the fifteenth century.
Peano postulates, also
called Peano axioms, a list of assumptions from which the integers can be
defined from some initial integer, equality, and successorship, and usually
seen as defining progressions. The Peano postulates for arithmetic were
produced by G. Peano in 1889. He took the set N of integers with a first term 1
and an equality relation between them, and assumed these nine axioms: 1 belongs
to N; N has more than one member; equality is reflexive, symmetric, and
associative, and closed over N; the successor of any integer in N also belongs
to N, and is unique; and a principle of mathematical induction applying across
the members of N, in that if 1 belongs to some subset M of N and so does the
successor of any of its members, then in fact M % N. In some ways Peano’s
formulation was not clear. He had no explicit rules of inference, nor any
guarantee of the legitimacy of inductive definitions (which Dedekind
established shortly before him). Further, the four properties attached to
equality were seen to belong to the underlying “logic” rather than to
arithmetic itself; they are now detached. It was realized (by Peano himself)
that the postulates specified progressions rather than integers (e.g., 1, ½, ¼,
1 /8, . . . , would satisfy them, with suitable interpretations of the
properties). But his work was significant in the axiomatization of arithmetic;
still deeper foundations would lead with Russell and others to a major role for
general set theory in the foundations of mathematics. In addition, with O.
Veblen, T. Skolem, and others, this insight led in the early twentieth century
to “non-standard” models of the postulates being developed in set theory and
mathematical analysis; one could go beyond the ‘. . .’ in the sequence above
and admit “further” objects, to produce valuable alternative models of the
postulates. These procedures were of great significance also to model theory,
in highlighting the property of the non-categoricity of an axiom system. A
notable case was the “non-standard analysis” of A. Robinson, where
infinitesimals were defined as arithmetical inverses of transfinite numbers
without incurring the usual perils of rigor associated with them.
Peirce, Charles S(anders)
(1839–1914), erican philosopher, scientist, and mathematician, the founder of
the philosophical movement called pragmatism. Peirce was born in Cbridge,
Massachusetts, the second son of Benjin Peirce, who was professor of
mathematics and astronomy at Harvard and one of erica’s leading mathematicians.
Charles Peirce studied at Harvard University and in 1863 received a degree in
chemistry. In 1861 he began work with the U.S. Coast and Geodetic Survey, and
remained in this service for thirty years. Simultaneously with his professional
career as a scientist, Peirce worked in logic and philosophy. He lectured on
philosophy and logic at various universities and institutes, but was never able
to obtain a permanent academic position as a teacher of philosophy. In 1887 he
retired to Milford, Pennsylvania, and devoted the rest of his life to
philosophical work. He earned a meager income from occasional lectures and by
writing articles for periodicals and dictionaries. He spent his last years in
extreme poverty and ill health. Pragmatism. Peirce formulated the basic
principles of pragmatism in two articles, “The Fixation of Belief” and “How to
Make Our Ideas Clear” (1877–78). The title of the latter paper refers to
Descartes’s doctrine of clear and distinct ideas. According to Peirce, the
criteria of clarity and distinctness must be supplemented by a third condition
of meaningfulness, which states that the meaning of a proposition or an
“intellectual conception” lies in its “practical consequences.” In his paper
“Pragmatism” (1905) he formulated the “Principle of Pragmatism” or the
“Pragmatic Maxim” as follows: In order to ascertain the meaning of an
intellectual conception we should consider what Peano, Giuseppe Peirce, Charles
S(anders) 651 651 practical consequences
might conceivably result by necessity from the truth of that conception; and
the sum of these consequences will constitute the entire meaning of the
conception. By “practical consequences” Peirce means conditional propositions
of the form ‘if p, then q’, where the antecedent describes some action or
experimental condition, and the consequent describes an observable phenomenon
or a “sensible effect.” According to the Pragmatic Maxim, the meaning of a
proposition (or of an “intellectual conception”) can be expressed as a
conjunction of such “practical conditionals.” The Pragmatic Maxim might be
criticized on the ground that many meaningful sentences (e.g., theoretical
hypotheses) do not entail any “practical consequences” in themselves, but only
in conjunction with other hypotheses. Peirce anticipated this objection by
observing that “the maxim of pragmatism is that a conception can have no
logical effect or import differing from that of a second conception except so
far as, taken in connection with other conceptions and intentions, it might conceivably
modify our practical conduct differently from that of the second conception”
(“Pragmatism and Abduction,” 1903). Theory of inquiry and philosophy of
science. Peirce adopted Bain’s definition of belief as “that which a man is
prepared to act upon.” Belief guides action, and as a content of belief a
proposition can be regarded as a maxim of conduct. According to Peirce, belief
is a satisfactory and desirable state, whereas the opposite of belief, the
state of doubt, is an unsatisfactory state. The starting point of inquiry is
usually some surprising phenomenon that is inconsistent with one’s previously
accepted beliefs, and that therefore creates a state of doubt. The purpose of
inquiry is the replacement of this state by that of belief: “the sole aim of
inquiry is the settlement of opinion.” A successful inquiry leads to stable
opinion, a state of belief that need not later be given up. Peirce regarded the
ultimate stability of opinion as a criterion of truth and reality: “the real .
. . is that which, sooner or later, information and reasoning would finally
result in, and which is therefore independent of the vagaries of you and me.”
He accepted, however, an objectivist conception of truth and reality: the
defining characteristic of reality is its independence of the opinions of
individual persons. In “The Fixation of Belief” Peirce argued that the
scientific method, a method in which we let our beliefs be determined by
external reality, “by something upon which our thinking has no effect,” is the
best way of settling opinion. Much of his philosophical work was devoted to the
analysis of the various forms of inference and argument employed in science. He
studied the concept of probability and probabilistic reasoning in science,
criticized the subjectivist view of probability, and adopted an objectivist
conception, according to which probability can be defined as a relative
frequency in the long run. Peirce distinguished between three main types of
inference, which correspond to three stages of inquiry: (i) abduction, a
tentative acceptance of an explanatory hypothesis which, if true, would make
the phenomenon under investigation intelligible; (ii) deduction, the derivation
of testable consequences from the explanatory hypothesis; and (iii) induction,
the evaluation of the hypothesis in the light of these consequences. He called
this method of inquiry the inductive method; in the contemporary philosophy of
science it is usually called the hypothetico-deductive method. According to
Peirce, the scientific method can be viewed as an application of the pragmatic
maxim: the testable consequences derived from an explanatory hypothesis
constitute its concrete “meaning” in the sense of the Pragmatic Maxim. Thus the
Maxim determines the admissibility of a hypothesis as a possible (meaningful)
explanation. According to Pierce, inquiry is always dependent on beliefs that
are not subject to doubt at the time of the inquiry, but such beliefs might be
questioned on some other occasion. Our knowledge does not rest on indubitable
“first premises,” but all beliefs are dependent on other beliefs. According to
Peirce’s doctrine of fallibilism, the conclusions of science are always
tentative. The rationality of the scientific method does not depend on the
certainty of its conclusions, but on its self-corrective character: by
continued application of the method science can detect and correct its own
mistakes, and thus eventually lead to the discovery of truth. Logic, the theory
of signs, and the philosophy of language. In “The Logic of Relatives,”
published in 1883 in a collection of papers by himself and his students at the
Johns Hopkins University (Studies in Logic by Members of the Johns Hopkins
University), Peirce formalized relational statements by using subscript indices
for individuals (individual variables), and construed the quantifiers ‘some’
and ‘every’ as variable binding operators; thus Peirce can be regarded
(together Peirce, Charles S(anders) Peirce, Charles S(anders) 652 652 with the German logician Frege) as one
of the founders of quantification theory (predicate logic). In his paper “On
the Algebra of Logic – A Contribution to the Philosophy of Notation” (1885) he
interpreted propositional logic as a calculus of truth-values, and defined
(logically) necessary truth (in propositional logic) as truth for all
truth-value assignments to sentential letters. He studied the logic of
modalities and in the 1890s he invented a system of logical graphs (called
“existential graphs”), based on a diagrmatic representation of propositions, in
which he anticipated some basic ideas of the possible worlds semantics of modal
logic. Peirce’s letters and notebooks contain significant logical and
philosophical insights. For exple, he exined three-valued truth tables
(“Triadic Logic”), and discovered (in 1886) the possibility of representing the
truth-functional connectives of propositional logic by electrical switching
circuits. Peirce regarded logic as a part of a more general area of inquiry,
the theory of signs, which he also called semeiotic (nowadays usually spelled
‘semiotic(s)’). According to Peirce, sign relations are triadic, involving the
sign itself, its object (or what the sign stands for), and an interpretant
which determines how the sign represents the object; the interpretant can be
regarded as the meaning of the sign. The interpretant of a sign is another sign
which in turn has its own interpretant (or interpretants); such a sequence of
interpretants ends in an “ultimate logical interpretant,” which is “a change of
habit of conduct.” On the basis of the triadic character of the sign relation
Peirce distinguished three divisions of signs. These divisions were based on
(i) the character of the sign itself, (ii) the relation between the sign and
its object, and (iii) the way in which the interpretant represents the object.
These divisions reflect Peirce’s system of three fundental ontological
categories, which he termed Quality or Firstness, Relation or Secondness, and
Representation or Thirdness. Thus, according to the first division, a sign can
be (a) a qualisign, a mere quality or appearance (a First); (b) a sinsign or
token, an individual object, or event (a Second); or (c) a legisign or a
general type (a Third). Secondly, signs can be divided into icons, indices, and
symbols on the basis of their relations to their objects: an icon refers to an
object on the basis of its similarity to the object (in some respect); an index
stands in a dynic or causal relation to its object; whereas a symbol functions
as a sign of an object by virtue of a rule or habit of interpretation. Peirce’s
third division divides signs into rhemes (predicative signs), propositional
signs (propositions), and arguments. Some of the concepts and distinctions
introduced by Peirce, e.g., the distinction between “types” and “tokens” and
the division of signs into “icons,” “indices,” and “symbols,” have become part
of the standard conceptual repertoire of philosophy and semiotics. In his
philosophy of language Peirce made a distinction between a proposition and an assertion,
and studied the logical character of assertive speech acts. Metaphysics. In
spite of his critical attitude toward traditional metaphysics, Peirce believed
that metaphysical questions can be discussed in a meaningful way. According to
Peirce, metaphysics studies the most general traits of reality, and “kinds of
phenomena with which every man’s experience is so saturated that he usually
pays no particular attention to them.” The basic categories of Firstness,
Secondness, and Thirdness mentioned above occupy a central position in Peirce’s
metaphysics. Especially in his later writings he emphasized the reality and
metaphysical irreducibility of Thirdness, and defended the view that general
phenomena (for exple, general laws) cannot be regarded as mere conjunctions of
their actual individual instances. This view was associated with Peirce’s
synechism, the doctrine that the world contains genuinely continuous phenomena.
He regarded synechism as a new form of Scholastic realism. In the area of
modalities Peirce’s basic categories appear as possibility, actuality, and
necessity. Here he argued that reality cannot be identified with existence (or
actuality), but comprises real (objective) possibilities. This view was partly
based on his realization that many conditional statements, for instance the
“practical” conditionals expressing the empirical import of a proposition (in
the sense of the Pragmatic Maxim), cannot be construed as material or
truth-functional conditionals, but must be regarded as modal (subjunctive)
conditionals. In his cosmology Peirce propounded the doctrine of tychism,
according to which there is absolute chance in the universe, and the basic laws
of nature are probabilistic and inexact. Peirce’s position in contemporary
philosophy. Peirce had few disciples, but some of his students and colleagues
bece influential figures in erican philosophy and science, e.g., the
philosophers Jes, Royce, and Dewey and the economist Thorstein Veblen. Peirce’s
pragmatism Peirce, Charles S(anders) Peirce, Charles S(anders) 653 653 bece widely known through Jes’s
lectures and writings, but Peirce was dissatisfied with Jes’s version of
pragmatism, and rened his own form of it ‘pragmaticism’, which term he
considered to be “ugly enough to keep it safe from kidnappers.” Pragmatism bece
an influential philosophical movement during the twentieth century through
Dewey (philosophy of science and philosophy of education), C. I. Lewis (theory
of knowledge), Rsey, Ernest Nagel, and Quine (philosophy of science). Peirce’s
work in logic influenced, mainly through his contacts with the German logician
Ernst Schröder, the model-theoretic tradition in twentieth-century logic. There
are three comprehensive collections of Peirce’s papers: Collected Papers of
Charles Sanders Peirce (1931–58), vols. 1–6 edited by Charles Hartshorne and
Paul Weiss, vols. 7–8 edited by Arthur Burks; The New Elements of Mathematics
by Charles S. Peirce (1976), edited by Carolyn Eisele; and Writings of Charles
S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition (1982–).
DEWEY, JES, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, PRAGMATISM, TRUTH, TYCHISM. R.Hi.
Peirce’s law, the
principle ‘((A P B) P A) P A’, which holds in classical logic but fails in the
eyes of relevance logicians when ‘ P’ is read as ‘entails’.
Pelagianism, the doctrine
in Christian theology that, through the exercise of free will, human beings can
attain moral perfection. A broad movement devoted to this proposition was only
loosely associated with its eponymous leader. Pelagius (c.354–c.425), a lay
theologian from Britain or Ireland, taught in Rome prior to its sacking in 410.
He and his disciple Celestius found a forceful adversary in Augustine, whom
they provoked to stiffen his stance on original sin, the bondage of the will,
and humanity’s total reliance upon God’s grace and predestination for
salvation. To Pelagius, this constituted fatalism and encouraged moral apathy.
God would not demand perfection, as the Bible sometimes suggested, were that
impossible to attain. Rather grace made the struggle easier for a sanctity that
would not be unreachable even in its absence. Though in the habit of sinning,
in consequence of the fall, we have not forfeited the capacity to overcome that
habit nor been released from the imperative to do so. For all its moral
earnestness this teaching seems to be in conflict with much of the New Testent,
especially as interpreted by Augustine, and it was condemned as heresy in 418.
The bondage of the will has often been reaffirmed, perhaps most notably by
Luther in dispute with Erasmus. Yet Christian theology and practice have always
had their sympathizers with Pelagianism and with its reluctance to attest the
loss of free will, the inevitability of sin, and the utter necessity of God’s
grace. A.E.L. Pelagius.
per accidens (Latin, ‘by
accident’), by, as, or being an accident or non-essential feature. A per
accidens predication is one in which an accident is predicated of a substance.
(The terminology is medieval. Note that the accident and substance themselves,
not words standing for them, are the terms of the predication relation.) An ens
(entity) per accidens is either an accident or the “accidental unity” of a
substance and an accident (Descartes, e.g., insists that a person is not a per
accidens union of body and mind.)
perception, the extraction
and use of information about one’s environment (exteroception) and one’s own
body (interoception). The various external senses – sight, hearing, touch,
smell, and taste – though they overlap to some extent, are distinguished by the
kind of information (e.g., about light, sound, temperature, pressure) they
deliver. Proprioception, perception of the self, concerns stimuli arising
within, and carrying information about, one’s own body – e.g., acceleration,
position, and orientation of the limbs. There are distinguishable stages in the
extraction and use of sensory information, one (an earlier stage) corresponding
to our perception of objects (and events), the other, a later stage, to the
perception of facts about these objects. We see, e.g., both the cat on the sofa
(an object) and that the cat is on the sofa (a fact). Seeing an object (or
event) – a cat on the sofa, a person on the street, or a vehicle’s movement –
does not require that the object (event) be identified or recognized in any
particular way (perhaps, though this is controversial, in any way whatsoever).
One can, e.g., see a cat on the sofa and mistake it for a rumpled sweater.
Airplane lights are often misidentified as stars, and one can see the movement
of an object either as the movement of oneself or (under some viewing
conditions) as Peirce’s law perception 654
654 expansion (or contraction). Seeing objects and events is, in this
sense, non-epistemic: one can see O without knowing (or believing) that it is O
that one is seeing. Seeing facts, on the other hand, is epistemic; one cannot
see that there is a cat on the sofa without, thereby, coming to know that there
is a cat on the sofa. Seeing a fact is coming to know the fact in some visual
way. One can see objects – the fly in one’s soup, e.g., – without realizing
that there is a fly in one’s soup (thinking, perhaps, it is a bean or a
crouton); but to see a fact, the fact that there is a fly in one’s soup is,
necessarily, to know it is a fly. This distinction applies to the other sense modalities
as well. One can hear the telephone ringing without realizing that it is the
telephone (perhaps it’s the TV or the doorbell), but to hear a fact, that it is
the telephone (that is ringing), is, of necessity, to know that it is the
telephone that is ringing. The other ways we have of describing what we
perceive are primarily variations on these two fundental themes. In seeing
where (he went), when (he left), who (went with him), and how he was dressed,
e.g., we are describing the perception of some fact of a certain sort without
revealing exactly which fact it is. If Martha saw where he went, then Martha
saw (hence, ce to know) some fact having to do with where he went, some fact of
the form ‘he went there’. In speaking of states and conditions (the condition
of his room, her injury), and properties (the color of his tie, the height of
the building), we sometimes, as in the case of objects, mean to be describing a
non-epistemic perceptual act, one that carries no implications for what (if
anything) is known. In other cases, as with facts, we mean to be describing the
acquisition of some piece of knowledge. One can see or hear a word without
recognizing it as a word (it might be in a foreign language), but can one see a
misprint and not know it is a misprint? It obviously depends on what one uses
‘misprint’ to refer to: an object (a word that is misprinted) or a fact (the
fact that it is misprinted). In exining and evaluating theories (whether
philosophical or psychological) of perception it is essential to distinguish
fact perception from object perception. For a theory might be a plausible
theory about the perception of objects (e.g., psychological theories of “early
vision”) but not at all plausible about our perception of facts. Fact
perception, involving, as it does, knowledge (and, hence, belief) brings into
play the entire cognitive system (memory, concepts, etc.) in a way the former
does not. Perceptual relativity – e.g., the idea that what we perceive is
relative to our language, our conceptual scheme, or the scientific theories we
have available to “interpret” phenomena – is quite implausible as a theory
about our perception of objects. A person lacking a word for, say, kumquats,
lacking this concept, lacking a scientific way of classifying these objects
(are they a fruit? a vegetable? an animal?), can still see, touch, smell, and
taste kumquats. Perception of objects does not depend on, and is therefore not
relative to, the observer’s linguistic, conceptual, cognitive, and scientific
assets or shortcomings. Fact perception, however, is another matter. Clearly
one cannot see that there are kumquats in the basket (as opposed to seeing the
objects, the kumquats, in the basket) if one has no idea of, no concept of,
what a kumquat is. Seeing facts is much more sensitive (and, hence, relative)
to the conceptual resources, the background knowledge and scientific theories,
of the observer, and this difference must be kept in mind in evaluating claims
about perceptual relativity. Though it does not make objects invisible,
ignorance does tend to make facts perceptually inaccessible. There are
characteristic experiences associated with the different senses. Tasting a
kumquat is not at all like seeing a kumquat although the se object is perceived
(indeed, the se fact – that it is a kumquat – may be perceived). The
difference, of course, is in the subjective experience one has in perceiving
the kumquat. A causal theory of perception (of objects) holds that the
perceptual object, what it is we see, taste, smell, or whatever, is that object
that causes us to have this subjective experience. Perceiving an object is that
object’s causing (in the right way) one to have an experience of the
appropriate sort. I see a bean in my soup if it is, in fact (whether I know it or
not is irrelevant), a bean in my soup that is causing me to have this visual
experience. I taste a bean if, in point of fact, it is a bean that is causing
me to have the kind of taste experience I
now having. If it is (unknown to me) a bug, not a bean, that is causing
these experiences, then I (unwittingly)
seeing and tasting a bug – perhaps a bug that looks and tastes like a bean.
What object we see (taste, smell, etc.) is determined by the causal facts in
question. What we know and believe, how we interpret the experience, is
irrelevant, although it will, of course, determine what we say we see and
taste. The se is to be said, with appropriate changes, for our perception of
facts (the most significant change being the replacement of belief for experience).
I see that there is a bug in my soup if the fact that there is a bug in my soup
causes me to perception perception 655
655 believe that there is a bug in my soup. I can taste that there is a
bug in my soup when this fact causes me to have this belief via some taste
sensation. A causal theory of perception is more than the claim that the
physical objects we perceive cause us to have experiences and beliefs. This
much is fairly obvious. It is the claim that this causal relation is
constitutive of perception, that necessarily, if S sees O, then O causes a
certain sort of experience in S. It is, according to this theory, impossible,
on conceptual grounds, to perceive something with which one has no causal
contact. If, e.g., future events do not cause present events, if there is no
backward causation, then we cannot perceive future events and objects. Whether
or not future facts can be perceived (or known) depends on how liberally the
causal condition on knowledge is interpreted. Though conceding that there is a
world of mind-independent objects (trees, stars, people) that cause us to have
experiences, some philosophers – traditionally called representative realists –
argue that we nonetheless do not directly perceive these external objects. What
we directly perceive are the effects these objects have on us – an internal
image, idea, or impression, a more or less (depending on conditions of
observation) accurate representation of the external reality that helps produce
it. This subjective, directly apprehended object has been called by various
nes: a sensation, percept, sensedatum, sensum, and sometimes, to emphasize its
representational aspect, Vorstellung (German, ‘representation’). Just as the
images appearing on a television screen represent their remote causes (the
events occurring at some distant concert hall or playing field), the images
(visual, auditory, etc.) that occur in the mind, the sensedata of which we are
directly aware in normal perception, represent (or sometimes, when things are
not working right, misrepresent) their external physical causes. The
representative realist typically invokes arguments from illusion, facts about
hallucination, and temporal considerations to support his view. Hallucinations
are supposed to illustrate the way we can have the se kind of experience we
have when (as we commonly say) we see a real bug without there being a real bug
(in our soup or anywhere else) causing us to have the experience. When we
hallucinate, the bug we “see” is, in fact, a figment of our own imagination, an
image (i.e., sense-datum) in the mind that, because it shares some of the
properties of a real bug (shape, color, etc.), we might mistake for a real bug.
Since the subjective experiences can be indistinguishable from that which we
have when (as we commonly say) we really see a bug, it is reasonable to infer
(the representative realist argues) that in normal perception, when we take
ourselves to be seeing a real bug, we are also directly aware of a buglike
image in the mind. A hallucination differs from a normal perception, not in
what we are aware of (in both cases it is a sense-datum) but in the cause of
these experiences. In normal perception it is an actual bug; in hallucination
it is, say, drugs in the bloodstre. In both cases, though, we are caused to
have the se thing: an awareness of a buglike sense-datum, an object that, in
normal perception, we naively take to be a real bug (thus saying, and
encouraging our children to say, that we see a bug). The argument from illusion
points to the fact that our experience of an object changes even when the
object that we perceive (or say we perceive) remains unchanged. Though the
physical object (the bug or whatever) remains the se color, size, and shape,
what we experience (according to this argument) changes color, shape, and size
as we change the lighting, our viewing angle, and distance. Hence, it is
concluded, what we experience cannot really be the physical object itself.
Since it varies with changes in both object and viewing conditions, what we
experience must be a causal result, an effect, of both the object we commonly
say we see (the bug) and the conditions in which we view it. This internal
effect, it is concluded, is a sense-datum. Representative realists have also
appealed to the fact that perceiving a physical object is a causal process that
takes time. This temporal lag is most dratic in the case of distant objects
(e.g., stars), but it exists for every physical object (it takes time for a
neural signal to be transmitted from receptor surfaces to the brain).
Consequently, at the moment (a short time after light leaves the object’s
surface) we see a physical object, the object could no longer exist. It could
have ceased to exist during the time light was being transmitted to the eye or
during the time it takes the eye to communicate with the brain. Yet, even if
the object ceases to exist before we become aware of anything (before a visual
experience occurs), we are, or so it seems, aware of something when the causal
process reaches its climax in the brain. This something of which we are aware,
since it cannot be the physical object (it no longer exists), must be a
sense-datum. The representationalist concludes in this “time-lag argument,”
therefore, that even when the physperception perception 656 656 ical object does not cease to exist
(this, of course, is the normal situation), we are directly aware, not of it,
but of its (slightly later-occurring) representation. Representative realists
differ ong themselves about the question of how much (if at all) the sense-data
of which we are aware resemble the external objects (of which we are not
aware). Some take the external cause to have some of the properties (the
so-called primary properties) of the datum (e.g., extension) and not others (the
so-called secondary properties – e.g., color). Direct (or naive) realism shares
with representative realism a commitment to a world of independently existing
objects. Both theories are forms of perceptual realism. It differs, however, in
its view of how we are related to these objects in ordinary perception. Direct
realists deny that we are aware of mental intermediaries (sensedata) when, as
we ordinarily say, we see a tree or hear the telephone ring. Though direct
realists differ in their degree of naïveté about how (and in what respect)
perception is supposed to be direct, they need not be so naive (as sometimes
depicted) as to deny the scientific facts about the causal processes underlying
perception. Direct realists can easily admit, e.g., that physical objects cause
us to have experiences of a particular kind, and that these experiences are
private, subjective, or mental. They can even admit that it is this causal
relationship (between object and experience) that constitutes our seeing and
hearing physical objects. They need not, in other words, deny a causal theory
of perception. What they must deny, if they are to remain direct realists,
however, is an analysis of the subjective experience (that objects cause us to
have) into an awareness of some object. For to understand this experience as an
awareness of some object is, given the wholly subjective (mental) character of
the experience itself, to interpose a mental entity (what the experience is an
awareness of) between the perceiver and the physical object that causes him to
have this experience, the physical object that is supposed to be directly
perceived. Direct realists, therefore, avoid analyzing a perceptual experience
into an act (sensing, being aware of, being acquainted with) and an object (the
sensum, sense-datum, sensation, mental representation). The experience we are
caused to have when we perceive a physical object or event is, instead, to be
understood in some other way. The adverbial theory is one such possibility. As
the ne suggests, this theory takes its cue from the way nouns and adjectives
can sometimes be converted into adverbs without loss of descriptive content.
So, for instance, it comes to pretty much the se thing whether we describe a
conversation as animated (adjective) or say that we conversed animatedly (an
adverb). So, also, according to an adverbialist, when, as we commonly say, we
see a red ball, the red ball causes in us (a moment later) an experience, yes,
but not (as the representative realist says) an awareness (mental act) of a
sense-datum (mental object) that is red and circular (adjectives). The
experience is better understood as one in which there is no object at all, as
sensing redly and circularly (adverbs). The adverbial theorist insists that one
can experience circularly and redly without there being, in the mind or
anywhere else, red circles (this, in fact, is what the adverbialist thinks
occurs in dres and hallucinations of red circles). To experience redly is not
to have a red experience; nor is it to experience redness (in the mind). It is,
says the adverbialist, a way or a manner of perceiving ordinary objects
(especially red ones seen in normal light). Just as dancing gracefully is not a
thing we dance, so perceiving redly is not a thing – and certainly not a red
thing in the mind – that we experience. The adverbial theory is only one option
the direct realist has of acknowledging the causal basis of perception while,
at the se time, maintaining the directness of our perceptual relation with
independently existing objects. What is important is not that the experience be
construed adverbially, but that it not be interpreted, as representative
realists interpret it, as awareness of some internal object. For a direct
realist, the appearances, though they are subjective (mind-dependent) are not
objects that interpose themselves between the conscious mind and the external
world. As classically understood, both naive and representative realism are
theories about object perception. They differ about whether it is the external
object or an internal object (an idea in the mind) that we (most directly)
apprehend in ordinary sense perception. But they need not (although they
usually do) differ in their analysis of our knowledge of the world around us,
in their account of fact perception. A direct realist about object perception
may, e.g., be an indirect realist about the facts that we know about these
objects. To see, not only a red ball in front of one, but that there is a red
ball in front of one, it may be necessary, even on a direct theory of (object)
perception, to infer (or in some way derive) this fact from facts that are
known more directly perception perception about one’s experiences of the ball.
Since, e.g., a direct theorist may be a causal theorist, may think that seeing
a red ball is (in part) constituted by the having of certain sorts of
experience, she may insist that knowledge of the cause of these experiences
must be derived from knowledge of the experience itself. If one is an
adverbialist, e.g., one might insist that knowledge of physical objects is
derived from knowledge of how (redly? bluely? circularly? squarely?) one
experiences these objects. By the se token, a representative realist could
adopt a direct theory of fact perception. Though the objects we directly see
are mental, the facts we come to know by experiencing these subjective entities
are facts about ordinary physical objects. We do not infer (at least at no
conscious level) that there is a bug in our soup from facts (known more
directly) about our own conscious experiences (from facts about the sensations
the bug causes in us). Rather, our sensations cause us, directly, to have
beliefs about our soup. There is no intermediate belief; hence, there is no
intermediate knowledge; hence, no intermediate fact perception. Fact perception
is, in this sense, direct. Or so a representative realist can maintain even
though committed to the indirect perception of the objects (bug and soup)
involved in this fact. This merely illustrates, once again, the necessity of
distinguishing object perception from fact perception. DIRECT REALISM, EPISTEMOLOGY, METAPHYSICAL
REALISM, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND, SKEPTICISM,
Percival, Thomas
(1740–1804), English physician and author of Medical Ethics (1803). He was
central in bringing the Western traditions of medical ethics from prayers and
oaths (e.g., the Hippocratic oath) toward more detailed, modern codes of proper
professional conduct. His writing on the normative aspects of medical practice
was part ethics, part prudential advice, part professional etiquette, and part
jurisprudence. Medical Ethics treated standards for the professional conduct of
physicians relative to surgeons and apothecaries (pharmacists and general
practitioners), as well as hospitals, private practice, and the law. The issues
Percival addressed include privacy, truth telling, rules for professional
consultation, human experimentation, public and private trust, compassion,
sanity, suicide, abortion, capital punishment, and environmental nuisances.
Percival had his greatest influence in England and erica. At its founding in
1847, the erican Medical Association used Medical Ethics to guide its own first
code of medical ethics.
perdurance, in one common
philosophical use, the property of being temporally continuous and having
temporal parts. There are at least two conflicting theories about temporally
continuous substances. According to the first, temporally continuous substances
have temporal parts (they perdure), while according to the second, they do not.
In one ordinary philosophical use, endurance is the property of being
temporally continuous and not having temporal parts. There are modal versions
of the aforementioned two theories: for exple, one version of the first theory
is that necessarily, temporally continuous substances have temporal parts,
while another version implies that possibly, they do not. Some versions of the
first theory hold that a temporally continuous substance is composed of
instantaneous temporal parts or “object-stages,” while on other versions these
object-stages are not parts but boundaries.
IDENTITY, METAPHYSICS, PERSONAL
perfect competition, the
state of an ideal market under the following conditions: (a) every consumer in
the market is a perfectly rational maximizer of utility; (b) every producer is
a perfect maximizer of profit; (c) there is a very large (ideally infinite)
number of producers of the good in question, which ensures that no producer can
set the price for its output (otherwise, an imperfect competitive state of oligopoly
or monopoly obtains); and (d) every producer provides a product perfectly
indistinguishable from that of other producers (if consumers could distinguish
products to the point that there was no longer a very large number of producers
for each distinguishable good, competition would again be imperfect). Under
these conditions, the market price is equal to the marginal cost of producing
the last unit. This in turn determines the market supply of the good, since
each producer will gain by increasing production when price exceeds marginal
cost and will generally cut losses by decreasing production when marginal cost
exceeds price. Perfect competition is sometimes perceptual realism perfect
competition 658 658 thought to have
normative implications for political philosophy, since it results in Pareto
optimality. The concept of perfect competition becomes extremely complicated
when a market’s evolution is considered. Producers who cannot equate marginal
cost with the market price will have negative profit and must drop out of the
market. If this happens very often, then the number of producers will no longer
be large enough to sustain perfect competition, so new producers will need to
enter the market. PHILOSOPHY OF
ECONOMICS, PRODUCTION
perfectionism, an ethical
view according to which individuals and their actions are judged by a maximal
standard of achievement – specifically, the degree to which they approach
ideals of aesthetic, intellectual, emotional, or physical “perfection.”
Perfectionism, then, may depart from, or even dispense with, standards of
conventional morality in favor of standards based on what appear to be
non-moral values. These standards reflect an admiration for certain very rare
levels of human achievement. Perhaps the most characteristic of these standards
are artistic and other forms of creativity; but they prominently include a
variety of other activities and emotional states deemed “noble” – e.g., heroic
endurance in the face of great suffering. The perfectionist, then, would also tend
toward a rather non-egalitarian – even aristocratic – view of humankind. The
rare genius, the inspired few, the suffering but courageous artist – these
exples of human perfection are genuinely worthy of our estimation, according to
this view. Although no fully worked-out system of “perfectionist philosophy”
has been attempted, aspects of all of these doctrines may be found in such
philosophers as Nietzsche. Aristotle, as well, appears to endorse a
perfectionist idea in his characterization of the human good. Just as the good
lyre player not only exhibits the characteristic activities of this profession
but achieves standards of excellence with respect to these, the good human
being, for Aristotle, must achieve standards of excellence with respect to the virtue
or virtues distinctive of human life in general.
Peripatetic School, also
called Peripatos, the philosophical community founded by Aristotle at a public
gymnasium (the Lyceum) after his return to Athens in c.335 B.C. The derivation
of ‘Peripatetic’ from the alleged Aristotelian custom of “walking about”
(peripatein) is probably wrong. The ne should be explained by reference to a
“covered walking hall” (peripatos) ong the school facilities. A scholarch or
headmaster presided over roughly two classes of members: the presbyteroi or
seniors, who probably had some teaching duties, and the neaniskoi or juniors.
No evidence of female philosophers in the Lyceum has survived. During
Aristotle’s lifetime his own lectures, whether for the inner circle of the school
or for the city at large, were probably the key attraction and core activity;
but given Aristotle’s knack for organizing group research projects, we may
assume that young and old Peripatetics spent much of their time working on
their own specific assignments either at the library, where they could consult
works of earlier writers, or at some kind of repository for specimens used in
zoological and botanical investigations. As a resident alien, Aristotle could
not own property in Athens and hence was not the legal owner of the school.
Upon his final departure from Athens in 322, his longtime collaborator
Theophrastus of Eresus in Lesbos (c.370–287) succeeded him as scholarch.
Theophrastus was an able Aristotelian who wrote extensively on metaphysics, psychology,
physiology, botany, ethics, politics, and the history of philosophy. With the
help of the Peripatetic dictator Demetrius of Phaleron, he was able to secure
property rights over the physical facilities of the school. Under Theophrastus,
the Peripatos continued to flourish and is said to have had 2,000 students,
surely not all at the se time. His successor, Strato of Lpsakos (c.335–269),
had narrower interests and abandoned key Aristotelian tenets. With him a
progressive decline set in, to which the early loss of Aristotle’s personal
library, taken to Asia Minor perfect duty Peripatetic School 659 659 by Neleus of Skepsis, certainly
contributed. By the first century B.C. the Peripatos had ceased to exist. Philosophers
of later periods sympathetic to Aristotle’s views have also been called
Peripatetics.
Perry, Ralph Barton
(1876–1957), erican philosopher who taught at Harvard University and wrote
extensively in ethics, social philosophy, and the theory of knowledge. He
received a Pulitzer Prize in 1936 for The Thought and Character of Willi Jes, a
biography of his teacher and colleague. Perry’s other major works include: The
Moral Economy (1909), General Theory of Value (1926), Puritanism and Democracy
(1944), and Realms of Value (1954). He is perhaps best known for his views on
value. He writes in General Theory of Value, “Any object, whatever it be,
acquires value when any interest, whatever it be, is taken in it; just as
anything whatsoever becomes a target when anyone whosoever aims at it.” Something’s
having value is nothing but its being the object of some interest, and to know
whether it has value one need only know whether it is the object of someone’s
interest. Morality aims at the promotion of the moral good, which he defines as
“harmonious happiness.” This consists in the reconciliation, harmonizing, and
fulfillment of all interests. Perry’s epistemological and metaphysical views
were part of a revolt against idealism and dualism. Along with five other
philosophers, he wrote The New Realism (1912). The “New Realists” held that the
objects of perception and memory are directly presented to consciousness and
are just what they appear to be; nothing intervenes between the knower and the
external world. The view that the objects of perception and memory are
presented by means of ideas leads, they argued, to idealism, skepticism, and
absurdity. Perry is also known for having developed, along with E. B. Holt, the
“specific response” theory, which is an attempt to construe belief and
perception in terms of bodily adjustment and behavior.
personal identity, the
(numerical) identity over time of persons. The question of what personal
identity consists in is the question of what it is (what the necessary and
sufficient conditions are) for a person existing at one time and a person
existing at another time to be one and the se person. Here there is no question
of there being any entity that is the “identity” of a person; to say that a
person’s identity consists in such and such is just shorthand for saying that
facts about personal identity, i.e., facts to the effect that someone existing
at one time is the se as someone existing at another time, consist in such and
such. (This should not be confused with the usage, common in ordinary speech
and in psychology, in which persons are said to have identities, and,
sometimes, to seek, lose, or regain their identities, where one’s “identity”
intimately involves a set of values and goals that structure one’s life.) The
words ‘identical’ and ‘se’ mean nothing different in judgments about persons
than in judgments about other things. The problem of personal identity is
therefore not one of defining a special sense of ‘identical,’ and it is at
least misleading to characterize it as defining a particular kind of identity.
Applying Quine’s slogan “no entity without identity,” one might say that
characterizing any sort of entity involves indicating what the identity
conditions for entities of that sort are (so, e.g., part of the explanation of
the concept of a set is that sets having the se members are identical), and
that asking what the identity of persons consists in is just a way of asking
what sorts of things persons are. But the main focus in traditional discussions
of the topic has been on one kind of identity judgment about persons, nely
those asserting “identity over time”; the question has been about what the
persistence of persons over time consists in. What has made the identity
(persistence) of persons of special philosophical interest is partly its
epistemology and partly its connections with moral and evaluative matters. The
crucial epistemological fact is that persons have, in memory, an access to
their own past histories that is unlike the access they have to the histories
of other things (including other persons); when one remembers doing or
experiencing something, one normally has no need to employ any criterion of
identity in order to know that the subject of the remembered action or
experience is (i.e., is identical with) oneself. The moral and evaluative
matters include moral responsibility (someone can be held responsible for a
past action only Peripatos personal identity if he or she is identical to the
person who did it) and our concern for our own survival and future well-being
(since it seems, although this has been questioned, that what one wants in
wanting to survive is that there should exist in the future someone who is
identical to oneself). The modern history of the topic of personal identity
begins with Locke, who held that the identity of a person consists neither in
the identity of an immaterial substance (as dualists might be expected to hold)
nor in the identity of a material substance or “animal body” (as materialists
might be expected to hold), and that it consists instead in “se consciousness.”
His view appears to have been that the persistence of a person through time
consists in the fact that certain actions, thoughts, experiences, etc.,
occurring at different times, are somehow united in memory. Modern theories
descended from Locke’s take memory continuity to be a special case of something
more general, psychological continuity, and hold that personal identity
consists in this. This is sometimes put in terms of the notion of a
“person-stage,” i.e., a momentary “time slice” of the history of a person. A
series of person-stages will be psychologically continuous if the psychological
states (including memories) occurring in later members of the series grow out
of, in certain characteristic ways, those occurring in earlier members of it; and
according to the psychological continuity view of personal identity,
person-stages occurring at different times are stages of the se person provided
they belong to a single, non-branching, psychologically continuous series of
person-stages. Opponents of the Lockean and neo-Lockean (psychological
continuity) view tend to fall into two cps. Some, following Butler and Reid,
hold that personal identity is indefinable, and that nothing informative can be
said about what it consists in. Others hold that the identity of a person
consists in some sort of physical continuity – perhaps the identity of a living
human organism, or the identity of a human brain. In the actual cases we know
about (putting aside issues about non-bodily survival of death), psychological continuity
and physical continuity go together. Much of the debate between psychological
continuity theories and physical continuity theories has centered on the
interpretation of thought experiments involving brain transplants, brain-state
transfers, etc., in which these come apart. Such exples make vivid the question
of whether our fundental criteria of personal identity are psychological,
physical, or both. Recently philosophical attention has shifted somewhat from
the question of what personal identity consists in to questions about its
importance. The consideration of hypothetical cases of “fission” (in which two
persons at a later time are psychologically continuous with one person at an
earlier time) has suggested to some that we can have survival – or at any rate
what matters in survival – without personal identity, and that our
self-interested concern for the future is really a concern for whatever future
persons are psychologically continuous with us.
personalism, a version of
personal idealism that flourished in the United States (principally at Boston
University) from the late nineteenth century to the mid-twentieth century. Its
principal proponents were Borden Parker Bowne (1847– 1910) and three of his
students: Albert Knudson (1873–1953); Ralph Flewelling (1871–1960), who founded
The Personalist; and, most importantly, Edgar Sheffield Brightman (1884–1953).
Their personalism was both idealistic and theistic and was influential in
philosophy and in theology. Personalism traced its philosophical lineage to
Berkeley and Leibniz, and had as its foundational insight the view that all
reality is ultimately personal. God is the transcendent person and the ground
or creator of all other persons; nature is a system of objects either for or in
the minds of persons. Both Bowne and Brightman considered themselves
empiricists in the tradition of Berkeley. Immediate experience is the starting
point, but this experience involves a fundental knowledge of the self as a
personal being with changing states. Given this pluralism, the coherence,
order, and intelligibility of the universe are seen to derive from God, the
uncreated person. Bowne’s God is the eternal and omnipotent being of classical
theism, but Brightman argued that if God is a real person he must be construed
as both temporal and finite. Given the fact of evil, God is seen as gradually
gaining control over his created world, with regard to which his will is
intrinsically limited. Another version of personalism developed in France out
of the neo-Scholastic tradition. E. Mounier (1905–50), Maritain, and Gilson
identified themselves as personalists, inasmuch as they viewed the infinite
person (God) and finite persons as the source and locus of intrinsic value.
They did not, however, view the natural order as intrinsically personal.
personhood, the condition
or property of being a person, especially when this is considered to entail
moral and/or metaphysical importance. Personhood has been thought to involve
various traits, including (moral) agency; reason or rationality; language, or
the cognitive skills language may support (such as intentionality and
self-consciousness); and ability to enter into suitable relations with other
persons (viewed as members of a self-defining group). Buber emphasized the
difference between the I-It relationship holding between oneself and an object,
and the IThou relationship, which holds between oneself and another person (who
can be addressed). Dennett has construed persons in terms of the “intentional
stance,” which involves explaining another’s behavior in terms of beliefs,
desires, intentions, etc. Questions about when personhood begins and when it
ends have been central to debates about abortion, infanticide, and euthanasia,
since personhood has often been viewed as the mark, if not the basis, of a
being’s possession of special moral status.
Peter Lombard
(c.1095–1160), Italian theologian and author of the Book of Sentences (Liber
sententiarum), a renowned theological sourcebook in the later Middle Ages.
Peter was educated at Bologna, Reims, and Paris before teaching in the school
of Notre De in Paris. He bece a canon at Notre De in 1144–45 and was elected
bishop of Paris in 1159. His extant works include commentaries on the Psalms
(written in the mid-1130s) and on the epistles of Paul (c.1139–41); a
collection of sermons; and his one-volume summary of Christian doctrine, the
Sentences (completed by 1158). The Sentences consists of four books: Book I, On
the Trinity; Book II, On the Creation of Things; Book III, On the Incarnation;
and Book IV, On the Doctrine of Signs (or Sacrents). His discussion is
organized around particular questions or issues e.g., “On Knowledge,
Foreknowledge, and Providence” (Book I), “Is God the Cause of Evil and Sin?”
(Book II). For a given issue Peter typically presents a brief summary,
accompanied by short quotations, of main positions found in Scripture and in
the writings of the church fathers and doctors, followed by his own
determination or adjudication of the matter. Himself a theological conservative,
Peter seems to have intended this sort of compilation of scriptural and ancient
doctrinal teaching as a counter to the popularity, fueled by the recent
recovery of important parts of Aristotle’s logic, of the application of
dialectic to theological matters. The Sentences enjoyed wide circulation and
admiration from the beginning, and within a century of its composition it bece
a standard text in the theology curriculum. From the midthirteenth through the
mid-fourteenth century every student of theology was required, as the last
stage in obtaining the highest academic degree, to lecture and comment on
Peter’s text. Later medieval thinkers often referred to Peter as “the Master”
(magister), thereby testifying to the Sentences’ preeminence in theological
training. In lectures and commentaries, the greatest minds of this period used
Peter’s text as a frework in which to develop their own original positions and
debate with their contemporaries. As a result the Sentences-commentary
tradition is an extraordinarily rich repository of later medieval philosophical
and theological thought. S.Ma. Peter of Spain. It is now thought that there
were two Peters of Spain. The Spanish prelate and philosopher (c.1205–77) was
born in Lisbon, studied at Paris, and taught medicine at Siena (1248–50). He
served in various ecclesiastical posts in Portugal and Italy (1250–73) before
being elected pope as John XXI in 1276. He wrote several books on philosophical
psychology and compiled the fous medical work Thesaurus pauperum. The second
Peter of Spain was a Spanish Dominican who lived during the first half of the
thirteenth century. His Tractatus, later called Summulae logicales, received
over 166 printings during subsequent centuries. The Tractatus presents the
essentials of Aristotelian logic (propositions, universals, categories,
syllogism, dialectical topics, and the sophistical fallacies) and improves on
the mnemonic verses of Willi Sherwood; he then introduces the subjects of the
so-called parva logicalia (supposition, relatives, pliation, personality Peter
of Spain 662 662 appellation,
restriction, distribution), all of which were extensively developed in the
later Middle Ages. There is not sufficient evidence to claim that Peter wrote a
special treatise on consequences, but his understanding of conditionals as
assertions of necessary connection undoubtedly played an important role in the
rules of simple, as opposed to as-of-now, consequences. I.Bo. petitio
principii.
phantasia (Greek,
‘appearance’, ‘imagination’), (1) the state we are in when something appears to
us to be the case; (2) the capacity in virtue of which things appear to us.
Although frequently used of conscious and imagistic experiences, ‘phantasia’ is
not limited to such states; in particular, it can be applied to any
propositional attitude where something is taken to be the case. But just as the
English ‘appears’ connotes that one has epistemic reservations about what is
actually the case, so ‘phantasia’ suggests the possibility of being misled by
appearances and is thus often a subject of criticism. According to Plato,
phantasia is a “mixture” of sensation and belief; in Aristotle, it is a
distinct faculty that makes truth and falsehood possible. The Stoics take a
phantasia to constitute one of the most basic mental states, in terms of which
other mental states are to be explained, and in rational animals it bears the
propositional content expressed in language. This last use becomes prominent in
ancient literary and rhetorical theory to designate the ability of language to
move us and convey subjects vividly as well as to range beyond the bounds of
our immediate experience. Here lie the origins of the modern concept of
imagination (although not the Romantic distinction between fancy and
imagination). Later Neoplatonists, such as Proclus, take phantasia to be
necessary for abstract studies such as geometry, by enabling us to envision
spatial relations.
IMAGINATION. V.C. phase
space.STATE. phenomena.KANT. phenomenal body.EMBODIMENT. phenomenalism, the
view that propositions asserting the existence of physical objects are
equivalent in meaning to propositions asserting that subjects would have
certain sequences of sensations were they to have certain others. The basic
idea behind phenomenalism is compatible with a number of different analyses of
the self or conscious subject. A phenomenalist might understand the self as a
substance, a particular, or a construct out of actual and possible experience.
The view also is compatible with any number of different analyses of the
visual, tactile, auditory, olfactory, gustatory, and kinesthetic sensations
described in the antecedents and consequents of the subjunctive conditionals
that the phenomenalist uses to analyze physical object propositions (as
illustrated in the last paragraph). Probably the most common analysis of
sensations adopted by traditional phenomenalists is a sense-datum theory, with
the sense-data construed as mind-dependent entities. But there is nothing to
prevent a phenomenalist from accepting an adverbial theory or theory of
appearing instead. The origins of phenomenalism are difficult to trace, in part
because early statements of the view were usually not careful. In his
Dialogues, Berkeley hinted at phenomenalism when he had Philonous explain how
he could reconcile an ontology containing only minds and ideas with the story
of a creation that took place before the existence of people. Philonous
imagines that if he had been present at the creation he should have seen
things, i.e., had sensations, in the order described in the Bible. It can also
be argued, however, that J. S. Mill in An Exination of Sir Willi Hilton’s
Philosophy was the first to put forth a clearly phenomenalistic analysis when
he identified matter with the “permanent possibility of sensation.” When Mill
explained what these permanent possibilities are, he typically used
conditionals that describe the sensations one would have if one were placed in
certain conditions. The attraction of classical phenomenalism grew with the
rise of logical positivism and its acceptance of the verifiability criterion of
meaning. Phenomenalists were usually foundationalists who were convinced that
justified belief in the physical world rested ultimately on our
noninferentially justified beliefs about our sensations. Implicitly committed
to the view that only deductive and inductive inferences are legitimate, and
further assuming that to be justified in believing one proposition P on the
basis of another E, one must be justified in believing both E and that E makes
P probable, the phenomenalist saw an insuperable difficulty in justifying
belief in ordinary statements about the physical world given prevalent
conceptions of physical petitio principii phenomenalism 663 663 objects. If all we ultimately have as
our evidence for believing in physical objects is what we know about the
occurrence of sensation, how can we establish sensation as evidence for the
existence of physical objects? We obviously cannot deduce the existence of
physical objects from any finite sequence of sensations. The sensations could,
e.g., be hallucinatory. Nor, it seems, can we observe a correlation between
sensation and something else in order to generate the premises of an inductive
argument for the conclusion that sensations are reliable indicators of physical
objects. The key to solving this problem, the phenomenalist argues, is to
reduce assertions about the physical world to complicated assertions about the
sequences of sensations a subject would have were he to have certain others. The
truth of such conditionals, e.g., that if I have the clear visual impression of
a cat, then there is one before me, might be mind-independent in the way in
which one wants the truth of assertions about the physical world to be
mind-independent. And to the phenomenalist’s great relief, it would seem that
we could justify our belief in such conditional statements without having to
correlate anything but sensations. Many philosophers today reject some of the
epistemological, ontological, and metaphilosophical presuppositions with which
phenomenalists approached the problem of understanding our relation to the
physical world through sensation. But the argument that was historically most
decisive in convincing many philosophers to abandon phenomenalism was the argument
from perceptual relativity first advanced by Chisholm in “The Problem of
Perception.” Chisholm offers a strategy for attacking any phenomenalistic
analysis. The first move is to force the phenomenalist to state a conditional
describing only sensations that is an alleged consequence of a physical object
proposition. C. I. Lewis, e.g., in An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation,
claims that the assertion (P) that there is a doorknob before me and to the
left entails (C) that if I were to seem to see a doorknob and seem to reach out
and touch it then I would seem to feel it. Chisholm argues that if P really did
entail C then there could be no assertion R that when conjoined with P did not
entail C. There is, however, such an assertion: I unable to move my limbs and my hands but subject to delusions such that I think I moving them; I often seem to be initiating a
grasping motion but with no feeling of contacting anything. Chisholm argues, in
effect, that what sensations one would have if one were to have certain others
always depends in part on the internal and external physical conditions of
perception and that this fact dooms any attempt to find necessary and
sufficient conditions for the truth of a physical object proposition couched in
terms that describe only connections between sensations.
phenomenology, in the
twentieth century, the philosophy developed by Husserl and some of his
followers. The term has been used since the mideighteenth century and received
a carefully defined technical meaning in the works of both Kant and Hegel, but
it is not now used to refer to a homogeneous and systematically developed
philosophical position. The question of what phenomenology is may suggest that
phenomenology is one ong the many contemporary philosophical conceptions that
have a clearly delineated body of doctrines and whose essential characteristics
can be expressed by a set of wellchosen statements. This notion is not correct,
however. In contemporary philosophy there is no system or school called
“phenomenology,” characterized by a clearly defined body of teachings.
Phenomenology is neither a school nor a trend in contemporary philosophy. It is
rather a movement whose proponents, for various reasons, have propelled it in
many distinct directions, with the result that today it means different things
to different people. While within the phenomenological movement as a whole
there are several related currents, they, too, are by no means homogeneous.
Though these currents have a common point of departure, they do not project
toward the se destination. The thinking of most phenomenologists has changed so
greatly that their respective views can be presented adequately only by showing
them in their gradual development. This is true not only for Husserl, founder
of the phenomenological movement, but also for such later phenomenologists as
Scheler, N. Hartmann, Heidegger, Sartre, and Merleau-Ponty. To anyone who
studies the phenomenological movement without prejudice the differences ong its
many currents are obvious. It has been phenomenal property phenomenology
664 664 said that phenomenology
consists in an analysis and description of consciousness; it has been claimed
also that phenomenology simply blends with existentialism. Phenomenology is
indeed the study of essences, but it also attempts to place essences back into
existence. It is a transcendental philosophy interested only in what is “left
behind” after the phenomenological reduction is performed, but it also
considers the world to be already there before reflection begins. For some
philosophers phenomenology is speculation on transcendental subjectivity,
whereas for others it is a method for approaching concrete existence. Some use
phenomenology as a search for a philosophy that accounts for space, time, and the
world, just as we experience and “live” them. Finally, it has been said that
phenomenology is an attempt to give a direct description of our experience as
it is in itself without taking into account its psychological origin and its
causal explanation; but Husserl speaks of a “genetic” as well as a
“constitutive” phenomenology. To some people, finding such an abundance of
ideas about one and the se subject constitutes a strange situation; for others
it is annoying to contemplate the “confusion”; and there will be those who
conclude that a philosophy that cannot define its own scope does not deserve
the discussion that has been carried on in its regard. In the opinion of many,
not only is this latter attitude not justified, but precisely the opposite view
defended by Thevenaz should be adopted. As the term ‘phenomenology’ signifies
first and foremost a methodical conception, Thevenaz argues that because this
method, originally developed for a very particular and limited end, has been
able to branch out in so many varying forms, it manifests a latent truth and
power of renewal that implies an exceptional fecundity. Speaking of the great
variety of conceptions within the phenomenological movement, Merleau-Ponty
remarked that the responsible philosopher must recognize that phenomenology may
be practiced and identified as a manner or a style of thinking, and that it
existed as a movement before arriving at a complete awareness of itself as a
philosophy. Rather than force a living movement into a system, then, it seems
more in keeping with the ideal of the historian as well as the philosopher to
follow the movement in its development, and attempt to describe and evaluate
the many branches in and through which it has unfolded itself. In reality the
picture is not as dark as it may seem at first sight. Notwithstanding the
obvious differences, most phenomenologists share certain insights that are very
important for their mutual philosophical conception as a whole. In this
connection the following must be mentioned: (1) Most phenomenologists admit a
radical difference between the “natural” and the “philosophical” attitude. This
leads necessarily to an equally radical difference between philosophy and
science. In characterizing this difference some phenomenologists, in agreement
with Husserl, stress only epistemological issues, whereas others, in agreement
with Heidegger, focus their attention exclusively on ontological topics. (2)
Notwithstanding this radical difference, there is a complicated set of
relationships between philosophy and science. Within the context of these
relationships philosophy has in some sense a foundational task with respect to
the sciences, whereas science offers to philosophy at least a substantial part
of its philosophical problematic. (3) To achieve its task philosophy must
perform a certain reduction, or epoche, a radical change of attitude by which
the philosopher turns from things to their meanings, from the ontic to the
ontological, from the realm of the objectified meaning as found in the sciences
to the realm of meaning as immediately experienced in the “life-world.” In
other words, although it remains true that the various phenomenologists differ
in characterizing the reduction, no one seriously doubts its necessity. (4) All
phenomenologists subscribe to the doctrine of intentionality, though most
elaborate this doctrine in their own way. For Husserl intentionality is a
characteristic of conscious phenomena or acts; in a deeper sense, it is the
characteristic of a finite consciousness that originally finds itself without a
world. For Heidegger and most existentialists it is the human reality itself
that is intentional; as Being-in-the-world its essence consists in its
ek-sistence, i.e., in its standing out toward the world. (5) All phenomenologists
agree on the fundental idea that the basic concern of philosophy is to answer
the question concerning the “meaning and Being” of beings. All agree in
addition that in trying to materialize this goal the philosopher should be
primarily interested not in the ultimate cause of all finite beings, but in how
the Being of beings and the Being of the world are to be constituted. Finally,
all agree that in answering the question concerning the meaning of Being a
privileged position is to be attributed to subjectivity, i.e., to that being
which questions the Being of beings. Phenomenologists differ, phenomenology
phenomenology 665 665 however, the
moment they have to specify what is meant by subjectivity. As noted above,
whereas Husserl conceives it as a worldless monad, Heidegger and most later
phenomenologists conceive it as being-in-the-world. Referring to Heidegger’s
reinterpretation of his phenomenology, Husserl writes: one misinterprets my
phenomenology backwards from a level which it was its very purpose to overcome,
in other words, one has failed to understand the fundental novelty of the
phenomenological reduction and hence the progress from mundane subjectivity
(i.e., man) to transcendental subjectivity; consequently one has remained stuck
in an anthropology . . . which according to my doctrine has not yet reached the
genuine philosophical level, and whose interpretation as philosophy means a
lapse into “transcendental anthropologism,” that is, “psychologism.” (6) All
phenomenologists defend a certain form of intuitionism and subscribe to what
Husserl calls the “principle of all principles”: “whatever presents itself in
‘intuition’ in primordial form (as it were in its bodily reality), is simply to
be accepted as it gives itself out to be, though only within the limits in
which it then presents itself.” Here again, however, each phenomenologist
interprets this principle in keeping with his general conception of
phenomenology as a whole. Thus, while phenomenologists do share certain
insights, the development of the movement has nevertheless been such that it is
not possible to give a simple definition of what phenomenology is. The fact
remains that there are many phenomenologists and many phenomenologies.
Therefore, one can only faithfully report what one has experienced of
phenomenology by reading the phenomenologists.
Philo Judaeus (c.20
B.C.–A.D. 40), Jewish Hellenistic philosopher of Alexandria who composed the
bulk of his work in the form of commentaries and discourses on Scripture. He
made the first known sustained attempt to synthesize its revealed teachings
with the doctrines of classical philosophy. Although he was not the first to
apply the methods of allegorical interpretation to Scripture, the number and
variety of his interpretations make Philo unique. With this interpretive tool,
he transformed biblical narratives into Platonic accounts of the soul’s quest
for God and its struggle against passion, and the Mosaic commandments into
specific manifestations of general laws of nature. Philo’s most influential
idea was his conception of God, which combines the personal, ethical deity of
the Bible with the abstract, transcendentalist theology of Platonism and
Pythagoreanism. The Philonic deity is both the loving, just God of the Hebrew
Patriarchs and the eternal One whose essence is absolutely unknowable and who
creates the material world by will from primordial matter which He creates ex
nihilo. Besides the intelligible realm of ideas, which Philo is the earliest
known philosopher to identify as God’s thoughts, he posited an intermediate
divine being which he called, adopting scriptural language, the logos. Although
the exact nature of the logos is hard to pin down – Philo variously and,
without any concern for consistency, called it the “first-begotten Son of the
uncreated Father,” “Second God,” “idea of ideas,” “archetype of human reason,”
and “pattern of creation” – its main functions are clear: to bridge the huge
gulf between the transcendent deity and the lower world and to serve as the
unifying law of the universe, the ground of its order and rationality. A
philosophical eclectic, Philo was unknown to medieval Jewish philosophers but,
beyond his anticipations of Neoplatonism, he had a lasting impact on
Christianity through Clement of Alexandria, Origen, and brose.
HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY.
J.Ste. Philolaus (470?–390? B.C.), pre-Socratic Greek philosopher from Croton
in southern Italy, the first Pythagorean to write a book. The surviving
fragments of it are the earliest primary texts for Pythagoreanism, but numerous
spurious fragments have also been preserved. Philolaus’s book begins with a
cosmogony and includes astronomical, medical, and psychological doctrines. His
major innovation was to argue that the cosmos and everything in it is a
combination not just of unlimiteds (what is structured and ordered, e.g.
material elements) but also of limiters (structural and ordering elements, e.g.
shapes). These elements are held together in a harmonia (fitting together),
which comes to be in accord with perspicuous mathematical relationships, such
as the whole number ratios that correspond to the harmonic intervals (e.g.
octave % phenotext Philolaus 666 666 1
: 2). He argued that secure knowledge is possible insofar as we grasp the
number in accordance with which things are put together. His astronomical
system is fous as the first to make the earth a planet. Along with the sun,
moon, fixed stars, five planets, and counter-earth (thus making the perfect
number ten), the earth circles the central fire (a combination of the limiter
“center” and the unlimited “fire”). Philolaus’s influence is seen in Plato’s
Philebus; he is the primary source for Aristotle’s account of
Pythagoreanism. PYTHAGORAS. C.A.H. Philo
of Larisa.ACADEMY. Philoponus, John.JOHANNES PHILOPONUS. philosopher’s stone.
philosophia perennis, a
supposed body of truths that appear in the writings of the great philosophers,
or the truths common to opposed philosophical viewpoints. The term is derived
from the title of a book (De perenni philosophia) published by Agostino Steuco
of Gubbio in 1540. It suggests that the differences between philosophers are
inessential and superficial and that the common essential truth emerges,
however partially, in the major philosophical schools. Aldous Huxley employed
it as a title. L. Lavelle, N. Hartmann, and K. Jaspers also employ the phrase.
M. De Wulf and many others use the phrase to characterize Neo-Thomism as the
chosen vehicle of essential philosophical truths. R.M. philosophical
anthropology, philosophical inquiry concerning human nature, often starting
with the question of what generally characterizes human beings in contrast to
other kinds of creatures and things. Thus broadly conceived, it is a kind of
inquiry as old as philosophy itself, occupying philosophers from Socrates to
Sartre; and it embraces philosophical psychology, the philosophy of mind,
philosophy of action, and existentialism. Such inquiry presupposes no immutable
“essence of man,” but only the meaningfulness of distinguishing between what is
“human” and what is not, and the possibility that philosophy as well as other
disciplines may contribute to our self-comprehension. It leaves open the
question of whether other kinds of naturally occurring or artificially produced
entity may possess the hallmarks of our humanity, and countenances the
possibility of the biologically evolved, historically developed, and socially
and individually variable character of everything about our attained humanity.
More narrowly conceived, philosophical anthropology is a specific movement in
recent European philosophy associated initially with Scheler and Helmuth
Plessner, and subsequently with such figures as Arnold Gehlen, Cassirer, and
the later Sartre. It initially emerged in the late 1920s in Germany, simultaneously
with the existential philosophy of Heidegger and the critical social theory of
the Frankfurt School, with which it competed as German philosophers turned
their attention to the comprehension of human life. This movement was
distinguished from the outset by its attempt to integrate the insights of
phenomenological analysis with the perspectives attainable through attention to
human and comparative biology, and subsequently to social inquiry as well. This
turn to a more naturalistic approach to the understanding of ourselves, as a
particular kind of living creature ong others, is reflected in the titles of
the two works published in 1928 that inaugurated the movement: Scheler’s Man’s
Place in Nature and Plessner’s The Levels of the Organic and Man. For both
Scheler and Plessner, however, as for those who followed them, our nature must
be understood by taking further account of the social, cultural, and
intellectual dimensions of human life. Even those like Gehlen, whose Der Mensch
(1940) exhibits a strongly biological orientation, devoted much attention to
these dimensions, which our biological nature both constrains and makes
possible. For all of them, the relation between the biological and the social
and cultural dimensions of human life is a central concern and a key to
comprehending our human nature. One of the common themes of the later
philosophical-anthropological literature – e.g., Cassirer’s An Essay on Man
(1945) and Sartre’s Critique of Dialectical Reason (1960) as well as Plessner’s
Contitio Humana (1965) and Gehlen’s Early Man and Late Culture (1963) – is the
plasticity of human nature, made possible by our biological constitution, and
the resulting great differences in the ways human beings live. Yet this is not
taken to preclude saying anything meaningful about human nature generally;
rather, it merely requires attention to the kinds of general features involved
and reflected in human diversity and variability. Critics of the very idea and
possibility of a philosophical anthropology (e.g., Althusser and Foucault)
typically either deny that there are any Philo of Larisa philosophical
anthropology 667 667 such general
features or maintain that there are none outside the province of the biological
sciences (to which philosophy can contribute nothing substantive). Both claims,
however, are open to dispute; and the enterprise of a philosophical
anthropology remains a viable and potentially significant one.
philosophy of biology,
the philosophy of science applied to biology. On a conservative view of the
philosophy of science, the se principles apply throughout science. Biology
supplies additional exples but does not provide any special problems or require
new principles. For exple, the reduction of Mendelian genetics to molecular
biology exemplifies the se sort of relation as the reduction of thermodynics to
statistical mechanics, and the se general analysis of reduction applies equally
to both. More radical philosophers argue that the subject matter of biology has
certain unique features; hence, the philosophy of biology is itself unique. The
three features of biology most often cited by those who maintain that
philosophy of biology is unique are functional organization, embryological
development, and the nature of selection. Organisms are functionally organized.
They are capable of maintaining their overall organization in the face of
fairly extensive variation in their envisonments. Organisms also undergo
ontogenetic development resulting from extremely complex interactions between
the genetic makeup of the organism and its successive environments. At each
step, the course that an organism takes is determined by an interplay between
its genetic makeup, its current state of development, and the environment it
happens to confront. The complexity of these interactions produces the
nature–nurture problem. Except for human artifacts, similar organization does
not occur in the non-living world. The species problem is another classic issue
in the philosophy of biology. Biological species have been a paradigm exple of
natural kinds since Aristotle. According to nearly all pre-Darwinian
philosophers, species are part of the basic makeup of the universe, like
gravity and gold. They were held to be as eternal, immutable, and discrete as
these other exples of natural kinds. If Darwin was right, species are not
eternal. They come and go, and once gone can no more reemerge than Aristotle
can once again walk the streets of Athens. Nor are species immutable. A sple of
lead can be transmuted into a sple of gold, but these elements as elements
remain immutable in the face of such changes. However, Darwin insisted that
species themselves, not merely their instances, evolved. Finally, because
Darwin thought that species evolved gradually, the boundaries between species are
not sharp, casting doubt on the essentialist doctrines so common in his day. In
short, if species evolve, they have none of the traditional characteristics of
species. Philosophers and biologists to this day are working out the
consequences of this radical change in our worldview. The topic that has
received the greatest attention by philosophers of biology in the recent
literature is the nature of evolutionary theory, in particular selection,
adaptation, fitness, and the population structure of species. In order for
selection to operate, variation is necessary, successive generations must be
organized genealogically, and individuals must interact differentially with
their environments. In the simplest case, genes pass on their structure largely
intact. In addition, they provide the information necessary to produce
organisms. Certain of these organisms are better able to cope with their
environments and reproduce than are other organisms. As a result, genes are
perpetuated differentially through successive generations. Those
characteristics that help an organism cope with its environments are termed
adaptations. In a more restricted sense, only those characteristics that arose
through past selective advantage count as adaptations. Just as the notion of IQ
was devised as a single measure for a combination of the factors that influence
our mental abilities, fitness is a measure of relative reproductive success.
Claims about the tautological character of the principle philosophical
behaviorism philosophy of biology of the survival of the fittest stem from the
blunt assertion that fitness just is relative reproductive success, as if
intelligence just is what IQ tests measure. Philosophers of biology have
collaborated with biologists to analyze the notion of fitness. This literature
has concentrated on the role that causation plays in selection and, hence, must
play in any adequate explication of fitness. One important distinction that has
emerged is between replication and differential interaction with the environment.
Selection is a function of the interplay between these two processes. Because
of the essential role of variation in selection, all the organisms that belong
to the se species either at any one time or through time cannot possibly be
essentially the se. Nor can species be treated adequately in terms of the
statistical covariance of either characters or genes. The populational
structure of species is crucial. For exple, species that form numerous,
partially isolated demes are much more likely to speciate than those that do
not. One especially controversial question is whether species themselves can
function in the evolutionary process rather than simply resulting from it.
Although philosophers of biology have played an increasingly important role in
biology itself, they have also addressed more traditional philosophical
questions, especially in connection with evolutionary epistemology and ethics.
Advocates of evolutionary epistemology argue that knowledge can be understood
in terms of the adaptive character of accurate knowledge. Those organisms that
hold false beliefs about their environment, including other organisms, are less
likely to reproduce themselves than those with more accurate beliefs. To the
extent that this argument has any force at all, it applies only to humansized
entities and events. One common response to evolutionary epistemology is that
sometimes people who hold manifestly false beliefs flourish at the expense of
those who hold more realistic views of the world in which we live. On another
version of evolutionary epistemology, knowledge acquisition is viewed as just
one more instance of a selection process. The issue is not to justify our
beliefs but to understand how they are generated and proliferated. Advocates of
evolutionary ethics attempt to justify certain ethical principles in terms of
their survival value. Any behavior that increases the likelihood of survival
and reproduction is “good,” and anything that detracts from these ends is
“bad.” The main objection to evolutionary ethics is that it violates the
is–ought distinction. According to most ethical systems, we are asked to
sacrifice ourselves for the good of others. If these others were limited to our
biological relatives, then the biological notion of inclusive fitness might be
adequate to account for such altruistic behavior, but the scope of ethical
systems extends past one’s biological relatives. Advocates of evolutionary
ethics are hard pressed to explain the full range of behavior that is
traditionally considered as virtuous. Either biological evolution cannot
provide an adequate justification for ethical behavior or else ethical systems
must be drastically reduced in their scope.
. philosophy of
economics, the study of methodological issues facing positive economic theory
and normative problems on the intersection of welfare economics and political
philosophy. Methodological issues. Applying approaches and questions in the
philosophy of science specifically to economics, the philosophy of economics
explores epistemological and conceptual problems raised by the explanatory aims
and strategy of economic theory: Do its assumptions about individual choice
constitute laws, and do they explain its derived generalizations about markets
and economies? Are these generalizations laws, and if so, how are they tested
by observation of economic processes, and how are theories in the various
compartments of economics – microeconomics, macroeconomics – related to one
another and to econometrics? How are the various schools – neoclassical, institutional,
Marxian, etc. – related to one another, and what sorts of tests might enable us
to choose between their theories? Historically, the chief issue of interest in
the development of the philosophy of economics has been the empirical adequacy
of the assumptions of rational “economic man”: that all agents have complete
and transitive cardinal or ordinal utility rankings or preference orders and
that they always choose that available option which maximizes their utility or
preferences. Since the actual behavior of agents appears to disconfirm these
assumptions, the claim that they constitute causal laws governing economic
behavior is difficult to sustain. On the other hand, the assumption of
preference-maximizing behavior is indispensable to twentieth-century economics.
These two considerations jointly undermine the claim that economic theory
honors criteria on explanatory power and evidential probity drawn philosophy of
economics philosophy of economics 669 669
from physical science. Much work by economists and philosophers has been
devoted therefore to disputing the claim that the assumptions of rational
choice theory are false or to disputing the inference from this claim to the
conclusion that the cognitive status of economic theory as empirical science is
thereby undermined. Most frequently it has been held that the assumptions of
rational choice are as harmless and as indispensable as idealizations are
elsewhere in science. This view must deal with the allegation that unlike
theories embodying idealization elsewhere in science, economic theory gains
little more in predictive power from these assumptions about agents’
calculations than it would secure without any assumptions about individual
choice. Normative issues. Both economists and political philosophers are
concerned with identifying principles that will ensure just, fair, or equitable
distributions of scarce goods. For this reason neoclassical economic theory
shares a history with utilitarianism in moral philosophy. Contemporary welfare
economics continues to explore the limits of utilitarian prescriptions that
optimal economic and political arrangements should maximize and/or equalize
utility, welfare, or some surrogate. It also exines the adequacy of
alternatives to such utilitarian principles. Thus, economics shares an agenda
of interests with political and moral philosophy. Utilitarianism in economics
and philosophy has been constrained by an early realization that utilities are
neither cardinally measurable nor interpersonally comparable. Therefore the
prescription to maximize and/or equalize utility cannot be determinatively
obeyed. Welfare theorists have nevertheless attempted to establish principles
that will enable us to determine the equity, fairness, or justice of various
economic arrangements, and that do not rely on interpersonal comparisons
required to measure whether a distribution is maximal or equal in the utility
it accords all agents. Inspired by philosophers who have surrendered
utilitarianism for other principles of equality, fairness, or justice in
distribution, welfare economists have explored Kantian, social contractarian,
and communitarian alternatives in a research progr that cuts clearly across
both disciplines. Political philosophy has also profited as much from innovations
in economic theory as welfare economics has benefited from moral philosophy.
Theorems from welfare economics that establish the efficiency of markets in
securing distributions that meet minimal conditions of optimality and fairness
have led moral philosophers to reexine the moral status of free-market
exchange. Moreover, philosophers have come to appreciate that coercive social
institutions are sometimes best understood as devices for securing public goods
– goods like police protection that cannot be provided to those who pay for
them without also providing them to free riders who decline to do so. The
recognition that everyone would be worse off, including free riders, were the
coercion required to pay for these goods not imposed, is due to welfare economics
and has led to a significant revival of interest in the work of Hobbes, who
appears to have prefigured such arguments.
. philosophy of
education, a branch of philosophy concerned with virtually every aspect of the
educational enterprise. It significantly overlaps other, more mainstre branches
(especially epistemology and ethics, but even logic and metaphysics). The field
might almost be construed as a “series of footnotes” to Plato’s Meno, wherein
are raised such fundental issues as whether virtue can be taught; what virtue
is; what knowledge is; what the relation between knowledge of virtue and being
virtuous is; what the relation between knowledge and teaching is; and how and
whether teaching is possible. While few people would subscribe to Plato’s
doctrine (or convenient fiction, perhaps) in Meno that learning by being taught
is a process of recollection, the paradox of inquiry that prompts this doctrine
is at once the root text of the perennial debate between rationalism and
empiricism and a profoundly unsettling indication that teaching passeth
understanding. Mainstre philosophical topics considered within an educational
context tend to take on a decidedly genetic cast. So, e.g., epistemology, which
analytic philosophy has tended to view as a justificatory enterprise, becomes
concerned if not with the historical origins of knowledge claims then with
their genesis within the mental economy of persons generally – in consequence
of their educations. And even when philosophers of education come to endorse
something akin to Plato’s classic account of knowledge as justified true
belief, they are inclined to suggest, then, that the conveyance of knowledge
via instruction must somehow provide the student with the justification along
with the true philosophy of education philosophy of education 670 670 belief – thereby reintroducing a
genetic dimension to a topic long lacking one. Perhaps, indeed, analytic
philosophy’s general (though not universal) neglect of philosophy of education
is traceable in some measure to the latter’s almost inevitably genetic
perspective, which the former tended to decry as armchair science and as a
threat to the autonomy and integrity of proper philosophical inquiry. If this
has been a basis for neglect, then philosophy’s more recent, postanalytic turn
toward naturalized inquiries that reject any dichotomy between empirical and
philosophical investigations may make philosophy of education a more inviting
area. Alfred North Whitehead, himself a leading light in the philosophy of
education, once remarked that we are living in the period of educational
thought subject to the influence of Dewey, and there is still no denying the
observation. Dewey’s instrumentalism, his special brand of pragmatism, informs
his extraordinarily comprehensive progressive philosophy of education; and he
once went so far as to define all of philosophy as the general theory of
education. He identifies the educative process with the growth of experience,
with growing as developing – where experience is to be understood more in
active terms, as involving doing things that change one’s objective environment
and internal conditions, than in the passive terms, say, of Locke’s
“impression” model of experience. Even traditionalistic philosophers of
education, most notably Maritain, have acknowledged the wisdom of Deweyan
educational means, and have, in the face of Dewey’s commanding philosophical
presence, refred the debate with progressivists as one about appropriate
educational ends – thereby insufficiently acknowledging Dewey’s trenchant
critique of the means–end distinction. And even some recent analytic
philosophers of education, such as R. S. Peters, can be read as if translating
Deweyan insights (e.g., about the aim of education) into an analytic idiom. Analytic
philosophy of education, as charted by Peters, Israel Scheffler, and others in
the Anglo-erican philosophical tradition, has used the tools of linguistic
analysis on a wide variety of educational concepts (learning, teaching,
training, conditioning, indoctrinating, etc.) and investigated their
interconnections: Does teaching entail learning? Does teaching inevitably
involve indoctrinating? etc. This careful, subtle, and philosophically
sophisticated work has made possible a much-needed conceptual precision in
educational debates, though the debaters who most influence public opinion and
policy have rarely availed themselves of that precisification. Recent work in
philosophy of education, however, has taken up some major educational
objectives – moral and other values, critical and creative thinking – in a way
that promises to have an impact on the actual conduct of education. Philosophy
of education, long isolated (in schools of education) from the rest of the
academic philosophical community, has also been somewhat estranged from the
professional educational mainstre. Dewey would surely have approved of a change
in this status quo.
philosophy of history,
the philosophical study of human history and of attempts to record and
interpret it. ‘History’ in English (and its equivalent in most modern European
languages) has two primary senses: (1) the temporal progression of large-scale
human events and actions, primarily but not exclusively in the past; and (2)
the discipline or inquiry in which knowledge of the human past is acquired or
sought. This has led to two senses of ‘philosophy of history’, depending on
which “history” has been the object of philosophers’ attentions. Philosophy of
history in the first sense is often called substantive (or speculative), and
placed under metaphysics. Philosophy of history in the second sense is called
critical (or analytic) and can be placed in epistemology. Substantive
philosophy of history. In the West, substantive philosophy of history is
thought to begin only in the Christian era. In the City of God, Augustine
wonders why Rome flourished while pagan, yet fell into disgrace after its
conversion to Christiantity. Divine reward and punishment should apply to whole
peoples, not just to individuals. The unfolding of events in history should
exhibit a plan that is intelligible rationally, morally, and (for Augustine)
theologically. As a believer Augustine is convinced that there is such a plan,
though it may not always be evident. In the modern period, philosophers such as
Vico and Herder also sought such intelligibility in history. They also believed
in a long-term direction or purpose of history that is often opposed to and
makes use of the purposes of individuals. The most elaborate and best-known
exple of this approach is found in Hegel, who thought that the gradual
realization of human freedom could be discerned in history even if much
slavery, tyranny, and suffering are necessary in the philosophy of history
philosophy of history 671 671 process.
Marx, too, claimed to know the laws – in his case economic – according to which
history unfolds. Similar searches for overall “meaning” in human history have
been undertaken in the twentieth century, notably by Arnold Toynbee
(1889–1975), author of the twelve-volume Study of History, and Oswald Spengler
(1880–1936), author of Decline of the West. But the whole enterprise was
denounced by the positivists and neo-Kantians of the late nineteenth century as
irresponsible metaphysical speculation. This attitude was shared by twentieth-century
neopositivists and some of their heirs in the analytic tradition. There is some
irony in this, since positivism, explicitly in thinkers like Comte and
implicitly in others, involves belief in progressively enlightened stages of
human history crowned by the modern age of science. Critical philosophy of
history. The critical philosophy of history, i.e., the epistemology of
historical knowledge, can be traced to the late nineteenth century and has been
dominated by the paradigm of the natural sciences. Those in the positivist,
neopositivist, and postpositivist tradition, in keeping with the idea of the
unity of science, believe that to know the historical past is to explain events
causally, and all causal explanation is ultimately of the se sort. To explain
human events is to derive them from laws, which may be social, psychological,
and perhaps ultimately biological and physical. Against this reductionism, the
neo-Kantians and Dilthey argued that history, like other humanistic disciplines
(Geisteswissenschaften), follows irreducible rules of its own. It is concerned
with particular events or developments for their own sake, not as instances of
general laws, and its aim is to understand, rather than explain, human actions.
This debate was resurrected in the twentieth century in the English-speaking
world. Philosophers like Hempel and Morton White (b.1917) elaborated on the
notion of causal explanation in history, while Collingwood and Willi Dray
(b.1921) described the “understanding” of historical agents as grasping the
thought behind an action or discovering its reasons rather than its causes. The
comparison with natural science, and the debate between reductionists and
antireductionists, dominated other questions as well: Can or should history be
objective and valuefree, as science purportedly is? What is the significance of
the fact that historians can never perceive the events that interest them,
since they are in the past? Are they not limited by their point of view, their
place in history, in a way scientists are not? Some positivists were inclined
to exclude history from science, rather than make it into one, relegating it to
“literature” because it could never meet the standards of objectivity and
genuine explanation; it was often the anti-positivists who defended the
cognitive legitimacy of our knowledge of the past. In the non-reductionist
tradition, philosophers have increasingly stressed the narrative character of
history: to understand human actions generally, and past actions in particular,
is to tell a coherent story about them. History, according to W. B. Gallie
(b.1912), is a species of the genus Story. History does not thereby become
fiction: narrative remains a “cognitive instrument” (Louis Mink, 1921–83) just
as appropriate to its domain as theory construction is to science.
Nevertheless, concepts previously associated with fictional narratives, such as
plot structure and beginning-middle-end, are seen as applying to historical
narratives as well. This tradition is carried further by Hayden White (b.1928),
who analyzes classical nineteenth-century histories (and even substantive
philosophies of history such as Hegel’s) as instances of romance, comedy,
tragedy, and satire. In White’s work this mode of analysis leads him to some
skepticism about history’s capacity to “represent” the reality of the past:
narratives seem to be imposed upon the data, often for ideological reasons,
rather than drawn from them. To some extent White’s view joins that of some
positivists who believe that history’s literary character excludes it from the
realm of science. But for White this is hardly a defect. Some philosophers have
criticized the emphasis on narrative in discussions of history, since it
neglects search and discovery, deciphering and evaluating sources, etc., which
is more important to historians than the way they “write up” their results.
Furthermore, not all history is presented in narrative form. The debate between
pro- and anti-narrativists ong philosophers of history has its parallel in a
similar debate ong historians themselves. Academic history in recent times has
seen a strong turn away from traditional political history toward social,
cultural, and economic analyses of the human past. Narrative is associated with
the supposedly outmoded focus on the doings of kings, popes, and generals.
These are considered (e.g. by the French historian Fernand Braudel, 1902–85)
merely surface ripples compared to the deeper-lying and slower-moving currents
of social and economic change. It is the methods and concepts of the social
sciences, not philosophy of history philosophy of history 672 672 the art of the storyteller, on which
the historian must draw. This debate has now lost some of its ste and narrative
history has made something of a comeback ong historians. ong philosophers Paul
Ricoeur has tried to show that even ostensibly non-narrative history retains
narrative features. Historicity. Historicity (or historicality:
Geschichtlichkeit) is a term used in the phenomenological and hermeneutic
tradition (from Dilthey and Husserl through Heidegger and Gader) to indicate an
essential feature of human existence. Persons are not merely in history; their
past, including their social past, figures in their conception of themselves
and their future possibilities. Some awareness of the past is thus constitutive
of the self, prior to being formed into a cognitive discipine. Modernism and
the postmodern. It is possible to view some of the debates over the modern and
postmodern in recent Continental philosophy as a new kind of philosophy of
history. Philosophers like Lyotard and Foucault see the modern as the period
from the Enlightenment and Romanticism to the present, characterized chiefly by
belief in “grand narratives” of historical progress, whether capitalist, Marxist,
or positivist, with “man” as the triumphant hero of the story. Such belief is
now being (or should be) abandoned, bringing modernism to an end. In one sense
this is like earlier attacks on the substantive philosophy of history, since it
unmasks as unjustified moralizing certain beliefs about large-scale patterns in
history. It goes even further than the earlier attack, since it finds these
beliefs at work even where they are not explicitly expressed. In another sense
this is a continuation of the substantive philosophy of history, since it makes
its own grand claims about largescale historical patterns. In this it joins
hands with other philosophers of our day in a general historicization of
knowledge (e.g., the philosophy of science merges with the history of science)
and even of philosophy itself. Thus the later Heidegger – and more recently
Richard Rorty – view philosophy itself as a large-scale episode in Western
history that is nearing or has reached its end. Philosophy thus merges with the
history of philosophy, but only thanks to a philosophical reflection on this
history as part of history as a whole.
philosophy of language,
the philosophical study of natural language and its workings, particularly of
linguistic meaning and the use of language. A natural language is any one of
the thousands of various tongues that have developed historically ong
populations of human beings and have been used for everyday purposes –
including English, Italian, Swahili, and Latin – as opposed to the formal and
other artificial “languages” invented by mathematicians, logicians, and
computer scientists, such as arithmetic, the predicate calculus, and LISP or
COBOL. There are intermediate cases, e.g., Esperanto, Pig Latin, and the sort
of “philosophese” that mixes English words with logical symbols. Contemporary
philosophy of language centers on the theory of meaning, but also includes the
theory of reference, the theory of truth, philosophical pragmatics, and the
philosophy of linguistics. The main question addressed by the theory of meaning
is: In virtue of what are certain physical marks or noises meaningful
linguistic expressions, and in virtue of what does any particular set of marks
or noises have the distinctive meaning it does? A theory of meaning should also
give a comprehensive account of the “meaning phenomena,” or general semantic
properties of sentences: synonymy, biguity, entailment, and the like. Some
theorists have thought to express these questions and issues in terms of
languageneutral items called propositions: ‘In virtue of what does a particular
set of marks or noises express the proposition it does?’; cf. ‘ “La neige est
blanche” expresses the proposition that snow is white’, and ‘Synonymous
sentences express the se proposition’. On this view, to understand a sentence
is to “grasp” the proposition expressed by that sentence. But the explanatory
role and even the existence of such entities are disputed. It has often been
maintained that certain special sentences are true solely in virtue of their
meanings and/or the meanings of their component expressions, without regard to
what the nonlinguistic world is like (‘No bachelor is married’; ‘If a thing is
blue it is colored’). Such vacuously true sentences are called analytic.
However, Quine and others have disputed whether there really is such a thing as
analyticity. Philosophers have offered a number of sharply competing hypotheses
as to the nature of meaning, including: (1) the referential view that words
mean by standing for things, and that a sentence means what it does because its
parts correspond referentially to the elements of an actual or possible state
of affairs in the world; (2) ideational or mentalist theories, according to
philosophy of language philosophy of language 673 673 which meanings are ideas or other
psychological phenomena in people’s minds; (3) “use” theories, inspired by
Wittgenstein and to a lesser extent by J. L. Austin: a linguistic expression’s
“meaning” is its conventionally assigned role as a ge-piece-like token used in
one or more existing social practices; (4) Grice’s hypothesis that a sentence’s
or word’s meaning is a function of what audience response a typical utterer
would intend to elicit in uttering it.(5) inferential role theories, as
developed by Wilfrid Sellars out of Carnap’s and Wittgenstein’s views: a
sentence’s meaning is specified by the set of sentences from which it can
correctly be inferred and the set of those which can be inferred from it
(Sellars himself provided for “language-entry” and “language-exit” moves as
partly constitutive of meaning, in addition to inferences); (6)
verificationism, the view that a sentence’s meaning is the set of possible
experiences that would confirm it or provide evidence for its truth; (7) the
truth-conditional theory: a sentence’s meaning is the distinctive condition
under which it is true, the situation or state of affairs that, if it obtained,
would make the sentence true; (8) the null hypothesis, or eliminativist view,
that “meaning” is a myth and there is no such thing – a radical claim that can
stem either from Quine’s doctrine of the indeterminacy of translation or from
eliminative materialism in the philosophy of mind. Following the original work
of Carnap, Alonzo Church, Hintikka, and Richard Montague in the 1950s, the theory
of meaning has made increasing use of “possible worlds”–based intensional logic
as an analytical apparatus. Propositions (sentence meanings considered as
entities), and truth conditions as in (7) above, are now commonly taken to be
structured sets of possible worlds – e.g., the set of worlds in which
Aristotle’s maternal grandmother hates broccoli. And the structure imposed on
such a set, corresponding to the intuitive constituent structure of a
proposition (as the concepts ‘grandmother’ and ‘hate’ are constituents of the
foregoing proposition), accounts for the meaning-properties of sentences that
express the proposition. Theories of meaning can also be called semantics, as
in “Gricean semantics” or “Verificationist semantics,” though the term is sometimes
restricted to referential and/or truth-conditional theories, which posit
meaning-constitutive relations between words and the nonlinguistic world.
Semantics is often contrasted with syntax, the structure of grmatically
permissible ordering relations between words and other words in well-formed
sentences, and with pragmatics, the rules governing the use of meaningful
expressions in particular speech contexts; but linguists have found that
semantic phenomena cannot be kept purely separate either from syntactic or from
pragmatic phenomena. In a still more specialized usage, linguistic semantics is
the detailed study (typically within the truth-conditional format) of
particular types of construction in particular natural languages, e.g.,
belief-clauses in English or adverbial phrases in Kwakiutl. Linguistic
semantics in that sense is practiced by some philosophers of language, by some
linguists, and occasionally by both working together. Montague grmar and
situation semantics are common formats for such work, both based on intensional
logic. The theory of referenceis pursued whether or not one accepts either the
referential or the truthconditional theory of meaning. Its main question is: In
virtue of what does a linguistic expression designate one or more things in the
world? (Prior to theorizing and defining of technical uses, ‘designate’,
‘denote’, and ‘refer’ are used interchangeably.) Denoting expressions are
divided into singular terms, which purport to designate particular individual
things, and general terms, which can apply to more than one thing at once.
Singular terms include proper nes (‘Cindy’, ‘Bangladesh’), definite
descriptions (‘my brother’, ‘the first baby born in the New World’), and
singular pronouns of various types (‘this’, ‘you’, ‘she’). General terms
include common nouns (‘horse’, ‘trash can’), mass terms (‘water’, ‘graphite’),
and plural pronouns (‘they’, ‘those’). The twentieth century’s dominant theory
of reference has been the description theory, the view that linguistic terms
refer by expressing descriptive features or properties, the referent being the
item or items that in fact possess those properties. For exple, a definite
description does that directly: ‘My brother’ denotes whatever person does have
the property of being my brother. According to the description theory of proper
nes, defended most articulately by Russell, such nes express identifying
properties indirectly by abbreviating definite descriptions. A general term
such as ‘horse’ was thought of as expressing a cluster of properties
distinctive of horses; and so forth. But the description theory ce under heavy
attack in the late 1960s, from Keith Donnellan, Kripke, and Putn, and was
generally abandoned on each of several grounds, in favor of the
causal-historical theory of reference. The causal-historical idea is that a
particular use of a linguistic expression denotes by being etiologically
grounded in the thing or philosophy of language philosophy of language 674 674 group that is its referent; a
historical causal chain of a certain shape leads backward in time from the act
of referring to the referent(s). More recently, problems with the
causal-historical theory as originally formulated have led researchers to
backpedal somewhat and incorporate some features of the description theory.
Other views of reference have been advocated as well, particularly analogues of
some of the theories of meaning listed above – chiefly (2)–(6) and (8). Modal
and propositional-attitude contexts create special problems in the theory of reference,
for referring expressions seem to alter their normal semantic behavior when
they occur within such contexts. Much ink has been spilled over the question of
why and how the substitution of a term for another term having exactly the se
referent can change the truth-value of a containing modal or
propositional-attitude sentence. Interestingly, the theory of truth
historically predates articulate study of meaning or of reference, for
philosophers have always sought the nature of truth. It has often been thought
that a sentence is true in virtue of expressing a true belief, truth being
primarily a property of beliefs rather than of linguistic entities; but the
main theories of truth have also been applied to sentences directly. The
correspondence theory maintains that a sentence is true in virtue of its
elements’ mirroring a fact or actual state of affairs. The coherence theory
instead identifies truth as a relation of the true sentence to other sentences,
usually an epistemic relation. Pragmatic theories have it that truth is a
matter either of practical utility or of idealized epistemic warrant.
Deflationary views, such as the traditional redundancy theory and D. Grover, J.
Cp, and N. D. Belnap’s prosentential theory, deny that truth comes to anything
more important or substantive than what is already codified in a recursive
Tarskian truth-definition for a language. Pragmatics studies the use of
language in context, and the context-dependence of various aspects of
linguistic interpretation. First, one and the se sentence can express different
meanings or propositions from context to context, owing to biguity or to
indexicality or both. An biguous sentence has more than one meaning, either
because one of its component words has more than one meaning (as ‘bank’ has) or
because the sentence admits of more than one possible syntactic analysis
(‘Visiting doctors can be tedious’, ‘The mouse tore up the street’). An
indexical sentence can change in truth-value from context to context owing to
the presence of an element whose reference fluctuates, such as a demonstrative
pronoun (‘She told him off yesterday’, ‘It’s time for that meeting now’). One
branch of pragmatics investigates how context determines a single propositional
meaning for a sentence on a particular occasion of that sentence’s use. Speech
act theory is a second branch of pragmatics that presumes the propositional or
“locutionary” meanings of utterances and studies what J. L. Austin called the
illocutionary forces of those utterances, the distinctive types of linguistic
act that are performed by the speaker in making them. (E.g., in uttering ‘I
will be there tonight’, a speaker might be issuing a warning, uttering a
threat, making a promise, or merely offering a prediction, depending on
conventional and other social features of the situation. A crude test of
illocutionary force is the “hereby” criterion: one’s utterance has the force
of, say, a warning, if it could fairly have been paraphrased by the
corresponding “explicitly performative” sentence beginning ‘I hereby warn you
that . . .’.).Speech act theory interacts to some extent with semantics,
especially in the case of explicit performatives, and it has some fairly dratic
syntactic effects as well. A third branch of pragmatics (not altogether
separate from the second) is the theory of conversation or theory of implicature,
founded by Grice. Grice notes that sentences, when uttered in particular
contexts, often generate “implications” that are not logical consequences of
those sentences (‘Is Jones a good philosopher?’ – ’He has very neat
handwriting’). Such implications can usually be identified as what the speaker
meant in uttering her sentence; thus (for that reason and others), what Grice
calls utterer’s meaning can diverge sharply from sentence-meaning or “timeless”
meaning. To explain those non-logical implications, Grice offered a now widely
accepted theory of conversational implicature. Conversational implicatures
arise from the interaction of the sentence uttered with mutually shared
background assumptions and certain principles of efficient and cooperative
conversation. The philosophy of linguistics studies the academic discipline of
linguistics, particularly theoretical linguistics considered as a science or
purported science; it exines methodology and fundental assumptions, and also
tries to incorporate linguists’ findings into the rest of philosophy of
language. Theoretical linguistics concentrates on syntax, and took its
contempophilosophy of language philosophy of language 675 675 rary form in the 1950s under Zellig
Harris and Chomsky: it seeks to describe each natural language in terms of a
generative grmar for that language, i.e., a set of recursive rules for
combining words that will generate all and only the “well-formed strings” or
grmatical sentences of that language. The set must be finite and the rules
recursive because, while our informationprocessing resources for recognizing
grmatical strings as such are necessarily finite (being subagencies of our
brains), there is no limit in any natural language either to the length of a
single grmatical sentence or to the number of grmatical sentences; a small
device must have infinite generative and parsing capacity. Many grmars work by
generating simple “deep structures” (a kind of tree diagr), and then producing
multiple “surface structures” as variants of those deep structures, by means of
rules that rearrange their parts. The surface structures are syntactic parsings
of natural-language sentences, and the deep structures from which they derive
encode both basic grmatical relations between the sentences’ major constituents
and, on some theories, the sentences’ main semantic properties as well; thus,
sentences that share a deep structure will share some fundental grmatical
properties and all or most of their semantics. As Paul Ziff and Davidson saw in
the 1960s, the foregoing syntactic problem and its solution had semantic
analogues. From small resources, human speakers understand – compute the
meanings of – arbitrarily long and novel sentences without limit, and almost
instantaneously. This ability seems to require semantic compositionality, the
thesis that the meaning of a sentence is a function of the meanings of its
semantic primitives or smallest meaningful parts, built up by way of syntactic
compounding. Compositionality also seems to be required by learnability, since
a normal child can learn an infinitely complex dialect in at most two years,
but must learn semantic primitives one at a time. A grmar for a natural
language is commonly taken to be a piece of psychology, part of an explanation
of speakers’ verbal abilities and behavior. As such, however, it is a
considerable idealization: it is a theory of speakers’ linguistic “competence”
rather than of their actual verbal performance. The latter distinction is
required by the fact that speakers’ considered, reflective judgments of
grmatical correctness do not line up very well with the class of expressions
that actually are uttered and understood unreflectively by those se speakers.
Some grmatical sentences are too hard for speakers to parse quickly; some are
too long to finish parsing at all; speakers commonly utter what they know to be
formally ungrmatical strings; and real speech is usually fragmentary,
interspersed with vocalizations, false starts, and the like. Actual departures
from formal grmaticality are ascribed by linguists to “performance
limitations,” i.e., psychological factors such as memory failure, weak
computational capacity, or heedlessness; thus, actual verbal behavior is to be
explained as resulting from the perturbation of competence by performance
limitations.
philosophy of law, also
called general jurisprudence, the study of conceptual and theoretical problems
concerning the nature of law as such, or common to any legal system. Problems
in the philosophy of law fall roughly into two groups. The first contains
problems internal to law and legal systems as such. These include (a) the
nature of legal rules; the conditions under which they can be said to exist and
to influence practice; their normative character, as mandatory or advisory; and
the (in)determinacy of their language; (b) the structure and logical character
of legal norms; the analysis of legal principles as a class of legal norms; and
the relation between the normative force of law and coercion; (c) the identity
conditions for legal systems; when a legal system exists; and when one legal
system ends and another begins; (d) the nature of the reasoning used by courts
in adjudicating cases; (e) the justification of legal decisions; whether legal
justification is through a chain of inferences or by the coherence of norms and
decisions; and the relation between intralegal and extralegal justification;
(f) the nature of legal validity and of what makes a norm a valid law; the
relation between validity and efficacy, the fact that the norms of a legal
system are obeyed by the norm-subjects; (g) properties of legal systems,
including comprehensiveness (the claim to regulate any behavior) and
completeness (the absence of gaps in the law); (h) legal rights; under what
conditions citizens possess them; and their analytical structure as protected
normative positions; (i) legal interpretation; whether it is a pervasive
feature of law or is found only in certain kinds of adjudication; its
rationality or otherwise; and its essentially ideological character or
otherwise. The second group of problems concerns the philosophy of law
philosophy of law 676 676 relation
between law as one particular social institution in a society and the wider
political and moral life of that society: (a) the nature of legal obligation;
whether there is an obligation, prima facie or final, to obey the law as such;
whether there is an obligation to obey the law only when certain standards are
met, and if so, what those standards might be; (b) the authority of law; and
the conditions under which a legal system has political or moral authority or
legitimacy; (c) the functions of law; whether there are functions performed by
a legal system in a society that are internal to the design of law; and
analyses from the perspective of political morality of the functioning of legal
systems; (d) the legal concept of responsibility; its analysis and its relation
to moral and political concepts of responsibility; in particular, the place of
mental elements and causal elements in the assignment of responsibility, and
the analysis of those elements; (e) the analysis and justification of legal
punishment; (f) legal liberty, and the proper limits or otherwise of the
intrusion of the legal system into individual liberty; the plausibility of
legal moralism; (g) the relation between law and justice, and the role of a
legal system in the maintenance of social justice; (h) the relation between
legal rights and political or moral rights; (i) the status of legal reasoning
as a species of practical reasoning; and the relation between law and practical
reason; (j) law and economics; whether legal decision making in fact tracks, or
otherwise ought to track, economic efficiency; (k) legal systems as sources of
and embodiments of political power; and law as essentially gendered, or imbued
with race or class biases, or otherwise. Theoretical positions in the
philosophy of law tend to group into three large kinds – legal positivism,
natural law, and legal realism. Legal positivism concentrates on the first set
of problems, and typically gives formal or content-independent solutions to
such problems. For exple, legal positivism tends to regard legal validity as a
property of a legal rule that the rule derives merely from its formal relation
to other legal rules; a morally iniquitous law is still for legal positivism a
valid legal rule if it satisfies the required formal existence conditions.
Legal rights exist as normative consequences of valid legal rules; no questions
of the status of the right from the point of view of political morality arise.
Legal positivism does not deny the importance of the second set of problems,
but assigns the task of treating them to other disciplines – political philosophy,
moral philosophy, sociology, psychology, and so forth. Questions of how society
should design its legal institutions, for legal positivism, are not technically
speaking problems in the philosophy of law, although many legal positivists
have presented their theories about such questions. Natural law theory and
legal realism, by contrast, regard the sharp distinction between the two kinds
of problem as an artifact of legal positivism itself. Their answers to the
first set of problems tend to be substantive or content-dependent. Natural law
theory, for exple, would regard the question of whether a law was consonant
with practical reason, or whether a legal system was morally and politically
legitimate, as in whole or in part determinative of the issue of legal
validity, or of whether a legal norm granted a legal right. The theory would
regard the relation between a legal system and liberty or justice as in whole
or in part determinative of the normative force and the justification for that
system and its laws. Legal realism, especially in its contemporary politicized
form, sees the claimed role of the law in legitimizing certain gender, race, or
class interests as the prime salient property of law for theoretical analysis,
and questions of the determinacy of legal rules or of legal interpretation or
legal right as of value only in the service of the project of explaining the
political power of law and legal systems.
philosophy of literature,
literary theory. However, while the literary theorist, who is often a literary
critic, is primarily interested in the conceptual foundations of practical
criticism, philosophy of literature, usually done by philosophers, is more
often concerned to place literature in the context of a philosophical system.
Plato’s dialogues have much to say about poetry, mostly by way of aligning it
with Plato’s metaphysical, epistemological, and ethico-political views.
Aristotle’s Poetics, the earliest exple of literary theory in the West, is also
an attempt to accommodate the practice of Greek poets to Aristotle’s
philosophical system as a whole. Drawing on the thought of philosophers like
Kant and Schelling, Suel Taylor Coleridge offers in his Biographia philosophy
of liberation philosophy of literature 677
677 Literaria a philosophy of literature that is to Romantic poetics
what Aristotle’s treatise is to classical poetics: a literary theory that is
confirmed both by the poets whose work it legitimates and by the metaphysics
that recommends it. Many philosophers, ong them Hume, Schopenhauer, Heidegger,
and Sartre, have tried to make room for literature in their philosophical
edifices. Some philosophers, e.g., the German Romantics, have made literature
(and the other arts) the cornerstone of philosophy itself. (See Philippe
Lacoue-Labarthe and Jean-Luc Nancy, The Literary Absolute, 1988.) Sometimes
‘philosophy of literature’ is understood in a second sense: philosophy and
literature; i.e., philosophy and literature taken to be distinct and
essentially autonomous activities that may nonetheless sustain determinate
relations to each other. Philosophy of literature, understood in this way, is
the attempt to identify the differentiae that distinguish philosophy from
literature and to specify their relationships to each other. Sometimes the two
are distinguished by their subject matter (e.g., philosophy deals with
objective structures, literature with subjectivity), sometimes by their methods
(philosophy is an act of reason, literature the product of imagination,
inspiration, or the unconscious), sometimes by their effects (philosophy
produces knowledge, literature produces emotional fulfillment or release), etc.
Their relationships then tend to occupy the area(s) in which they are not
essentially distinct. If their subject matters are distinct, their effects may
be the se (philosophy and literature both produce understanding, the one of
fact and the other of feeling); if their methods are distinct, they may be
approaching the se subject matter in different ways; and so on. For Aquinas,
e.g., philosophy and poetry may deal with the se objects, the one communicating
truth about the object in syllogistic form, the other inspiring feelings about
it through figurative language. For Heidegger, the philosopher investigates the
meaning of being while the poet nes the holy, but their preoccupations tend to
converge at the deepest levels of thinking. For Sartre, literature is
philosophy engagé, existential-political activity in the service of freedom.
’Philosophy of literature’ may also be taken in a third sense: philosophy in
literature, the attempt to discover matters of philosophical interest and value
in literary texts. The philosopher may undertake to identify, exine, and
evaluate the philosophical content of literary texts that contain expressions of
philosophical ideas and discussions of philosophical problems – e.g., the
debates on free will and theodicy in Fyodor Dostoevsky’s The Brothers Karazov.
Many if not most college courses on philosophy of literature are taught from
this point of view. Much interesting and important work has been done in this
vein; e.g., Santayana’s Three Philosophical Poets (1910), Cavell’s essays on
Emerson and Thoreau, and Nussbaum’s Love’s Knowledge (1989). It should be
noted, however, that to approach the matter in this way presupposes that
literature and philosophy are simply different forms of the se content: what
philosophy expresses in the form of argument literature expresses in lyric,
dratic, or narrative form. The philosopher’s treatment of literature implies that
he is uniquely positioned to explicate the subject matter treated in both
literary and philosophical texts, and that the language of philosophy gives
optimal expression to a content less adequately expressed in the language of
literature. The model for this approach may well be Hegel’s Phenomenology of
Spirit, which treats art (along with religion) as imperfect adumbrations of a
truth that is fully and properly articulated only in the conceptual mode of
philosophical dialectic. Dissatisfaction with this presupposition (and its
implicit privileging of philosophy over literature) has led to a different view
of the relation between philosophy and literature and so to a different progr
for philosophy of literature. The self-consciously literary form of Kierkegaard’s
writing is an integral part of his polemic against the philosophical
imperialism of the Hegelians. In this century, the work of philosophers like
Derrida and the philosophers and critics who follow his lead suggests that it
is mistaken to regard philosophy and literature as alternative expressions of
an identical content, and seriously mistaken to think of philosophy as the
master discourse, the “proper” expression of a content “improperly” expressed
in literature. All texts, on this view, have a “literary” form, the texts of
philosophers as well as the texts of novelists and poets, and their content is
internally determined by their “means of expression.” There is just as much
“literature in philosophy” as there is “philosophy in literature.” Consequently,
the philosopher of literature may no longer be able simply to extract
philosophical matter from literary form. Rather, the modes of literary
expression confront the philosopher with problems that bear on the
presuppositions of his own enterprise. E.g., fictional mimesis (especially in
the works of postmodern writers) raises questions about the possibility and the
prephilosophy of literature philosophy of literature 678 678 philosophy of logic philosophy of logic
679 sumed normativeness of factual representation, and in so doing tends to
undermine the traditional hierarchy that elevates “fact” over “fiction.”
Philosophers’ perplexity over the truth-value of fictional statements is an
exple of the kind of problems the study of literature can create for the
practice of philosophy (see Rorty, Consequences of Pragmatism, 1982, ch. 7). Or
again, the self-reflexivity of contemporary literary texts can lead
philosophers to reflect critically on their own undertaking and may seriously
unsettle traditional notions of self-referentiality. When it is not regarded as
another, attractive but perhaps inferior source of philosophical ideas,
literature presents the philosopher with epistemological, metaphysical, and
methodological problems not encountered in the course of “normal”
philosophizing. AESTHETICS, LITERARY
THEORY, POSTMODERN. L.H.M. philosophy of logic, the arena of philosophy devoted
to exining the scope and nature of logic. Aristotle considered logic an
organon, or foundation, of knowledge. Certainly, inference is the source of
much human knowledge. Logic judges inferences good or bad and tries to justify
those that are good. One need not agree with Aristotle, therefore, to see logic
as essential to epistemology. Philosophers such as Wittgenstein, additionally,
have held that the structure of language reflects the structure of the world.
Because inferences have elements that are themselves linguistic or are at least
expressible in language, logic reveals general features of the structure of
language. This makes it essential to linguistics, and, on a Wittgensteinian
view, to metaphysics. Moreover, many philosophical battles have been fought
with logical weaponry. For all these reasons, philosophers have tried to
understand what logic is, what justifies it, and what it tells us about reason,
language, and the world. The nature of logic. Logic might be defined as the
science of inference; inference, in turn, as the drawing of a conclusion from
premises. A simple argument is a sequence, one element of which, the conclusion,
the others are thought to support. A complex argument is a series of simple
arguments. Logic, then, is primarily concerned with arguments. Already,
however, several questions arise. (1) Who thinks that the premises support the
conclusion? The speaker? The audience? Any competent speaker of the language?
(2) What are the elements of arguments? Thoughts? Propositions? Philosophers
following Quine have found these answers unappealing for lack of clear identity
criteria. Sentences are more concrete and more sharply individuated. But should
we consider sentence tokens or sentence types? Context often affects
interpretation, so it appears that we must consider tokens or types-in-context.
Moreover, many sentences, even with contextual information supplied, are
biguous. Is a sequence with an biguous sentence one argument (which may be good
on some readings and bad on others) or several? For reasons that will become
clear, the elements of arguments should be the primary bearers of truth and
falsehood in one’s general theory of language. (3) Finally, and perhaps most
importantly, what does ‘support’ mean? Logic evaluates inferences by
distinguishing good from bad arguments. This raises issues about the status of
logic, for many of its pronouncements are explicitly normative. The philosophy
of logic thus includes problems of the nature and justification of norms akin
to those arising in metaethics. The solutions, moreover, may vary with the
logical system at hand. Some logicians attempt to characterize reasoning in
natural language; others try to systematize reasoning in mathematics or other
sciences. Still others try to devise an ideal system of reasoning that does not
fully correspond to any of these. Logicians concerned with inference in
natural, mathematical, or scientific languages tend to justify their norms by
describing inferential practices in that language as actually used by those
competent in it. These descriptions justify norms partly because the practices
they describe include evaluations of inferences as well as inferences
themselves. The scope of logic. Logical systems meant to account for natural
language inference raise issues of the scope of logic. How does logic differ
from semantics, the science of meaning in general? Logicians have often treated
only inferences turning on certain commonly used words, such as ‘not’, ‘if’,
‘and’, ‘or’, ‘all’, and ‘some’, taking them, or items in a symbolic language
that correspond to them, as logical constants. They have neglected inferences
that do not turn on them, such as My brother is married. Therefore, I have a
sister-in-law. Increasingly, however, semanticists have used ‘logic’ more
broadly, speaking of the logic of belief, perception, abstraction, or even
kinship. Such uses seem to treat logic
and semantics as coextensive. Philosophers who have sought to maintain a
distinction between the semantics and logic of natural language have tried to
develop non-arbitrary criteria of logical constancy. An argument is valid
provided the truth of its premises guarantees the truth of its conclusion. This
definition relies on the notion of truth, which raises philosophical puzzles of
its own. Furthermore, it is natural to ask what kind of connection must hold
between the premises and conclusion. One answer specifies that an argument is
valid provided replacing its simple constituents with items of similar
categories while leaving logical constants intact could never produce true
premises and a false conclusion. On this view, validity is a matter of form: an
argument is valid if it instantiates a valid form. Logic thus becomes the
theory of logical form. On another view, an argument is valid if its conclusion
is true in every possible world or model in which its premises are true. This
conception need not rely on the notion of a logical constant and so is
compatible with the view that logic and semantics are coextensive. Many issues
in the philosophy of logic arise from the plethora of systems logicians have
devised. Some of these are deviant logics, i.e., logics that differ from
classical or standard logic while seeming to treat the se subject matter.
Intuitionistic logic, for exple, which interprets the connectives and
quantifiers non-classically, rejecting the law of excluded middle and the
interdefinability of the quantifiers, has been supported with both semantic and
ontological arguments. Brouwer, Heyting, and others have defended it as the
proper logic of the infinite; Dummett has defended it as the correct logic of
natural language. Free logic allows non-denoting referring expressions but
interprets the quantifiers as ranging only over existing objects. Many-valued
logics use at least three truthvalues, rejecting the classical assumption of
bivalence – that every formula is either true or false. Many logical systems attempt
to extend classical logic to incorporate tense, modality, abstraction,
higher-order quantification, propositional quantification, complement
constructions, or the truth predicate. These projects raise important
philosophical questions. Modal and tense logics. Tense is a pervasive feature
of natural language, and has become important to computer scientists interested
in concurrent progrs. Modalities of several sorts – alethic (possibility,
necessity) and deontic (obligation, permission), for exple – appear in natural
language in various grmatical guises. Provability, treated as a modality,
allows for revealing formalizations of metathematics. Logicians have usually
treated modalities and tenses as sentential operators. C. I. Lewis and Langford
pioneered such approaches for alethic modalities; von Wright, for deontic
modalities; and Prior, for tense. In each area, many competing systems
developed; by the late 1970s, there were over two hundred axiom systems in the
literature for propositional alethic modal logic alone. How might competing
systems be evaluated? Kripke’s semantics for modal logic has proved very
helpful. Kripke semantics in effect treats modal operators as quantifiers over
possible worlds. Necessarily A, e.g., is true at a world if and only if A is
true in all worlds accessible from that world. Kripke showed that certain
popular axiom systems result from imposing simple conditions on the
accessibility relation. His work spawned a field, known as correspondence
theory, devoted to studying the relations between modal axioms and conditions
on models. It has helped philosophers and logicians to understand the issues at
stake in choosing a modal logic and has raised the question of whether there is
one true modal logic. Modal idioms may be biguous or indeterminate with respect
to some properties of the accessibility relation. Possible worlds raise
additional ontological and epistemological questions. Modalities and tenses
seem to be linked in natural language, but attempts to bring tense and modal
logic together remain young. The sensitivity of tense to intra- and
extralinguistic context has cast doubt on the project of using operators to
represent tenses. Kp, e.g., has represented tense and aspect in terms of event
structure, building on earlier work by Reichenbach. Truth. Tarski’s theory of
truth shows that it is possible to define truth recursively for certain
languages. Languages that can refer to their own sentences, however, permit no
such definition given Tarski’s assumptions – for they allow the formulation of
the liar and similar paradoxes. Tarski concluded that, in giving the semantics
for such a language, we must ascend to a more powerful metalanguage. Kripke and
others, however, have shown that it is possible for a language permitting self-reference
to contain its own truth 680 predicate
by surrendering bivalence or taking the truth predicate indexically.
Higher-order logic. First-order predicate logic allows quantification only over
individuals. Higher-order logics also permit quantification over predicate
positions. Natural language seems to permit such quantification: ‘Mary has
every quality that John admires’. Mathematics, moreover, may be expressed
elegantly in higher-order logic. Peano arithmetic and Zermelo-Fraenkel set
theory, e.g., require infinite axiom sets in firstorder logic but are finitely
axiomatizable – and categorical, determining their models up to isomorphism –
in second-order logic. Because they quantify over properties and relations,
higher-order logics seem committed to Platonism. Mathematics reduces to
higher-order logic; Quine concludes that the latter is not logic. Its most
natural semantics seems to presuppose a prior understanding of properties and
relations. Also, on this semantics, it differs greatly from first-order logic.
Like set theory, it is incomplete; it is not compact. This raises questions
about the boundaries of logic. Must logic be axiomatizable? Must it be
possible, i.e., to develop a logical system powerful enough to prove every
valid argument valid? Could there be valid arguments with infinitely many
premises, any finite fragment of which would be invalid? With an operator for
forming abstract terms from predicates, higher-order logics easily allow the
formulation of paradoxes. Russell and Whitehead for this reason adopted type
theory, which, like Tarski’s theory of truth, uses an infinite hierarchy and
corresponding syntactic restrictions to avoid paradox. Type-free theories avoid
both the restrictions and the paradoxes, as with truth, by rejecting bivalence
or by understanding abstraction indexically.
philosophy of
mathematics, the study of ontological and epistemological problems raised by
the content and practice of mathematics. The present agenda in this field
evolved from critical developments, notably the collapse of Pythagoreanism, the
development of modern calculus, and an early twentieth-century foundational
crisis, which forced mathematicians and philosophers to exine mathematical
methods and presuppositions. Greek mathematics. The Pythagoreans, who
represented the height of early demonstrative Greek mathematics, believed that
all scientific relations were measureable by natural numbers (1, 2, 3, etc.) or
ratios of natural numbers, and thus they assumed discrete, atomic units for the
measurement of space, time, and motion. The discovery of irrational magnitudes
scotched the first of these beliefs. Zeno’s paradoxes showed that the second
was incompatible with the natural assumption that space and time are infinitely
divisible. The Greek reaction, ultimately codified in Euclid’s Elements,
included Plato’s separation of mathematics from empirical science and, within
mathematics, distinguished number theory – a study of discretely ordered
entities – from geometry, which concerns continua. Following Aristotle (and
employing methods perfected by Eudoxus), Euclid’s proofs used only “potentially
infinite” geometric and arithmetic procedures. The Elements’ axiomatic form and
its constructive proofs set a standard for future mathematics. Moreover, its
dependence on visual intuition (whose consequent deductive gaps were already
noted by Archimedes), together with the challenge of Euclid’s infous fifth
postulate (about parallel lines), and the fous unsolved problems of compass and
straightedge construction, established an agenda for generations of
mathematicians. The calculus. The two millennia following Euclid saw new
analytical tools (e.g., Descartes’s geometry) that wedded arithmetic and
geometric considerations and toyed with infinitesimally small quantities.
These, together with the demands of physical application, tempted
mathematicians to abandon the pristine Greek dichotomies. Matters ce to a head
with Newton’s and Leibniz’s (almost simultaneous) discovery of the powerful
computational techniques of the calculus. While these unified physical science
in an unprecedented way, their dependence on unclear notions of infinitesimal
spatial and temporal increments emphasized their shaky philosophical
foundation. Berkeley, for instance, condemned the calculus for its
unintuitability. However, this time the power of the new methods inspired a
decidedly conservative response. Kant, in particular, tried to anchor the new
mathematics in intuition. Mathematicians, he claimed, construct their objects
in the “pure intuitions” of space and time. And these mathematical objects are
the a priori forms of transcendentally ideal empirical objects. For Kant this
combination of epistemic empiricism and ontological idealism explained the
physical philosophy of mathematics philosophy of mathematics 681 681 applicability of mathematics and thus
granted “objective validity” (i.e., scientific legitimacy) to mathematical
procedures. Two nineteenth-century developments undercut this Kantian
constructivism in favor of a more abstract conceptual picture of mathematics.
First, Jànos Bolyai, Carl F. Gauss, Bernhard Riemann, Nikolai Lobachevsky, and
others produced consistent non-Euclidean geometries, which undid the Kantian
picture of a single a priori science of space, and once again opened a rift
between pure mathematics and its physical applications. Second, Cantor and
Dedekind defined the real numbers (i.e., the elements of the continuum) as
infinite sets of rational (and ultimately natural) numbers. Thus they founded
mathematics on the concepts of infinite set and natural number. Cantor’s set
theory made the first concept rigorously mathematical; while Peano and Frege
(both of whom advocated securing rigor by using formal languages) did that for
the second. Peano axiomatized number theory, and Frege ontologically reduced
the natural numbers to sets (indeed sets that are the extensions of purely
logical concepts). Frege’s Platonistic conception of numbers as unintuitable
objects and his claim that mathematical truths follow analytically from purely
logical definitions – the thesis of logicism – are both highly anti-Kantian.
Foundational crisis and movements. But antiKantianism had its own problems. For
one thing, Leopold Kronecker, who (following Peter Dirichlet) wanted mathematics
reduced to arithmetic and no further, attacked Cantor’s abstract set theory on
doctrinal grounds. Worse yet, the discovery of internal antinomies challenged
the very consistency of abstract foundations. The most fous of these, Russell’s
paradox (the set of all sets that are not members of themselves both is and
isn’t a member of itself), undermined Frege’s basic assumption that every
well-formed concept has an extension. This was a full-scale crisis. To be sure,
Russell himself (together with Whitehead) preserved the logicist foundational
approach by organizing the universe of sets into a hierarchy of levels so that
no set can be a member of itself. (This is type theory.) However, the crisis
encouraged two explicitly Kantian foundational projects. The first, Hilbert’s
Progr, attempted to secure the “ideal” (i.e., infinitary) parts of mathematics
by formalizing them and then proving the resultant formal systems to be
conservative (and hence consistent) extensions of finitary theories. Since the
proof itself was to use no reasoning more complicated than simple numerical
calculations – finitary reasoning – the whole metathematical project belonged
to the untainted (“contentual”) part of mathematics. Finitary reasoning was
supposed to update Kant’s intuition-based epistemology, and Hilbert’s
consistency proofs mimic Kant’s notion of objective validity. The second
project, Brouwer’s intuitionism, rejected formalization, and was not only
epistemologically Kantian (resting mathematical reasoning on the a priori intuition
of time), but ontologically Kantian as well. For intuitionism generated both
the natural and the real numbers by temporally ordered conscious acts. The
reals, in particular, stem from choice sequences, which exploit Brouwer’s
epistemic assumptions about the open future. These foundational movements
ultimately failed. Type theory required ad hoc axioms to express the real
numbers; Hilbert’s Progr foundered on Gödel’s theorems; and intuitionism
remained on the fringes because it rejected classical logic and standard
mathematics. Nevertheless the legacy of these movements – their formal methods,
indeed their philosophical agenda – still characterizes modern research on the
ontology and epistemology of mathematics. Set theory, e.g. (despite recent
challenges from category theory), is the lingua franca of modern mathematics.
And formal languages with their precise semantics are ubiquitous in technical
and philosophical discussions. Indeed, even intuitionistic mathematics has been
formalized, and Michael Dummett has recast its ontological idealism as a
semantic antirealism that defines truth as warranted assertability. In a
similar semantic vein, Paul Benacerraf proposed that the philosophical problem
with Hilbert’s approach is inability to provide a uniform realistic (i.e.,
referential, non-epistemic) semantics for the allegedly ideal and contentual
parts of mathematics; and the problem with Platonism is that its semantics
makes its objects unknowable. Ontological issues. From this modern perspective,
the simplest realism is the outright Platonism that attributes a standard model
consisting of “independent” objects to classical theories expressed in a
first-order language (i.e., a language whose quantifiers range over objects but
not properties). But in fact realism admits variations on each aspect. For one
thing, the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem shows that formalized theories can have
non-standard models. There are expansive non-standard models: Abrah Robinson,
e.g., used infinitary non-stanphilosophy of mathematics philosophy of
mathematics 682 682 dard models of
Peano’s axioms to rigorously reintroduce infinitesimals. (Roughly, an
infinitesimal is the reciprocal of an infinite element in such a model.) And
there are also “constructive” models, whose objects must be explicitly
definable. Predicative theories (inspired by Poincaré and Hermann Weyl), whose
stage-by-stage definitions refer only to previously defined objects, produce
one variety of such models. Gödel’s constructive universe, which uses less
restricted definitions to model apparently non-constructive axioms like the
axiom of choice, exemplifies another variety. But there are also views (various
forms of structuralism) which deny that formal theories have unique standard
models at all. These views – inspired by the fact, already sensed by Dedekind,
that there are multiple equivalid realizations of formal arithmetic – allow a
mathematical theory to characterize only a broad fily of models and deny unique
reference to mathematical terms. Finally, some realistic approaches advocate
formalization in secondorder languages, and some eschew ordinary semantics
altogether in favor of substitutional quantification. (These latter are still
realistic, for they still distinguish truth from knowledge.) Strict finitists –
inspired by Wittgenstein’s more stringent epistemic constraints – reject even
the open-futured objects admitted by Brouwer, and countenance only finite (or
even only “feasible”) objects. In the other direction, A. A. Markov and his
school in Russia introduced a syntactic notion of algorithm from which they
developed the field of “constructive analysis.” And the erican mathematician
Errett Bishop, starting from a Brouwer-like disenchantment with mathematical
realism and with strictly formal approaches, recovered large parts of classical
analysis within a non-formal constructive frework. All of these approaches
assume abstract (i.e., causally isolated) mathematical objects, and thus they
have difficulty explaining the wide applicability of mathematics (constructive
or otherwise) within empirical science. One response, Quine’s
“indispensability” view, integrates mathematical theories into the general
network of empirical science. For Quine, mathematical objects – just like
ordinary physical objects – exist simply in virtue of being referents for terms
in our best scientific theory. By contrast Hartry Field, who denies that any
abstract objects exist, also denies that any purely mathematical assertions are
literally true. Field attempts to recast physical science in a relational
language without mathematical terms and then use Hilbert-style conservative
extension results to explain the evident utility of abstract mathematics.
Hilary Putn and Charles Parsons have each suggested views according to which
mathematics has no objects proper to itself, but rather concerns only the
possibilities of physical constructions. Recently, Geoffrey Hellman has
combined this modal approach with structuralism. Epistemological issues. The
equivalence (proved in the 1930s) of several different representations of
computability to the reasoning representable in elementary formalized
arithmetic led Alonzo Church to suggest that the notion of finitary reasoning
had been precisely defined. Church’s thesis (so ned by Stephen Kleene) inspired
Georg Kreisel’s investigations (in the 1960s and 70s) of the general conditions
for rigorously analyzing other informal philosophical notions like semantic
consequence, Brouwerian choice sequences, and the very notion of a set. Solomon
Feferman has suggested more recently that this sort of piecemeal conceptual
analysis is already present in mathematics; and that this rather than any
global foundation is the true role of foundational research. In this spirit,
the relative consistency arguments of modern proof theory (a continuation of
Hilbert’s Progr) provide information about the epistemic grounds of various
mathematical theories. Thus, on the one hand, proofs that a seemingly
problematic mathematical theory is a conservative extension of a more secure theory
provide some epistemic support for the former. In the other direction, the fact
that classical number theory is consistent relative to intuitionistic number
theory shows (contra Hilbert) that his view of constructive reasoning must
differ from that of the intuitionists. Gödel, who did not believe that
mathematics required any ties to empirical perception, suggested nevertheless
that we have a special nonsensory faculty of mathematical intuition that, when
properly cultivated, can help us decide ong formally independent propositions
of set theory and other branches of mathematics. Charles Parsons, in contrast,
has exined the place of perception-like intuition in mathematical reasoning.
Parsons himself has investigated models of arithmetic and of set theory
composed of quasi-concrete objects (e.g., numerals and other signs). Others
(consistent with some of Parsons’s observations) have given a Husserlstyle
phenomenological analysis of mathematical intuition. Frege’s influence
encouraged the logical positivists and other philosophers to view mathematical
knowledge as analytic or conventional. philosophy of mathematics philosophy of
mathematics 683 683 Poincaré responded
that the principle of mathematical induction could not be analytic, and
Wittgenstein also attacked this conventionalism. In recent years, various
formal independence results and Quine’s attack on analyticity have encouraged
philosophers and historians of mathematics to focus on cases of mathematical
knowledge that do not stem from conceptual analysis or strict formal
provability. Some writers (notably Mark Steiner and Philip Kitcher) emphasize
the analogies between empirical and mathematical discovery. They stress such
things as conceptual evolution in mathematics and instances of mathematical generalizations
supported by individual cases. Kitcher, in particular, discusses the analogy
between axiomatization in mathematics and theoretical unification. Penelope
Maddy has investigated the intrathematical grounds underlying the acceptance of
various axioms of set theory. More generally, Imre Lakatos argued that most
mathematical progress stems from a concept-stretching process of conjecture,
refutation, and proof. This view has spawned a historical debate about whether
critical developments such as those mentioned above represent Kuhn-style
revolutions or even crises, or whether they are natural conceptual advances in
a uniformly growing science.
.
philosophy of mind, the
branch of philosophy that includes the philosophy of psychology, philosophical
psychology, and the area of metaphysics concerned with the nature of mental
phenomena and how they fit into the causal structure of reality. Philosophy of
psychology, a branch of the philosophy of science, exines what psychology says
about the nature of psychological phenomena; exines aspects of psychological
theorizing such as the models used, explanations offered, and laws invoked; and
exines how psychology fits with the social sciences and natural sciences.
Philosophical psychology investigates folk psychology, a body of
commonsensical, protoscientific views about mental phenomena. Such
investigations attempt to articulate and refine views found in folk psychology
about conceptualization, memory, perception, sensation, consciousness, belief,
desire, intention, reasoning, action, and so on. The mind–body problem, a
central metaphysical one in the philosophy of mind, is the problem of whether
mental phenomena are physical and, if not, how they are related to physical
phenomena. Other metaphysical problems in the philosophy of mind include the
free will problem, the problem of personal identity, and the problem of how, if
at all, irrational phenomena such as akrasia and self-deception are possible.
Mind–body dualism Cartesian dualism. The doctrine that the soul is distinct
from the body is found in Plato and discussed throughout the history of
philosophy, but Descartes is considered the father of the modern mind–body
problem. He maintained that the essence of the physical is extension in space.
Minds are unextended substances and thus are distinct from any physical
substances. The essence of a mental substance is to think. This twofold view is
called Cartesian dualism. Descartes was well aware of an intimate relationship
between mind and the brain. (There is no a priori reason to think that the mind
is intimately related to the brain; Aristotle, e.g., did not associate them.)
Descartes (mistakenly) thought the seat of the relationship was in the pineal
gland. He maintained, however, that our minds are not our brains, lack spatial
location, and can continue to exist after the death and destruction of our
bodies. Cartesian dualism invites the question: What connects the mind and
brain? Causation is Descartes’s answer: states of our minds causally interact
with states of our brains. When bodily sensations such as aches, pains, itches,
and tickles cause us to moan, wince, scratch, or laugh, they do so by causing
brain states (events, processes), which in turn cause bodily movements. In
deliberate action, we act on our desires, motives, and intentions to carry out
our purposes; and acting on these mental states involves their causing brain
states, which in turn cause our bodies to move, thereby causally influencing
the physical world. The physical world, in turn, influences our minds through
its influence on our brains. Perception of the physical world with five senses
– sight, hearing, smell, taste, and touch – involves causal transactions from
the physical to the mental: what we perceive (i.e., see, hear, etc.) causes a
sense experience (i.e., a visual experience, aural experience, etc.). Thus,
Descartes held that there is two-way psychophysical causal interaction: from
the mental to the physical (as in action) and from the physical to the mental
(as in perception). The conjunction of Cartesian dualism and the doctrine of
two-way psychophysical causal interaction is called Cartesian interactionism.
philosophy of mind philosophy of mind 684
684 Perhaps the most widely discussed difficulty for this view is how
states of a non-spatial substance (a mind) can causally interact with states of
a substance that is in space (a brain). Such interactions have seemed utterly
mysterious to many philosophers. Mystery would remain even if an unextended
mind is locatable at a point in space (say, the center of the pineal gland).
For Cartesian interactionism would still have to maintain that causal
transactions between mental states and brain states are fundental, i.e.,
unmediated by any underlying mechanism. Brain states causally interact with
mental states, but there is no answer to the question of how they do so. The
interactions are brute facts. Many philosophers, including many of Descartes’s
contemporaries, have found that difficult to accept. Parallelism. Malebranche
and Leibniz, ong others, rejected the possibility of psychophysical causal
interaction. They espoused versions of parallelism: the view that the mental
and physical realms run in parallel, in that types of mental phenomena co-occur
with certain types of physical phenomena, but these co-occurrences never
involve causal interactions. On all extant versions, the parallels hold because
of God’s creation. Leibniz’s parallelism is preestablished harmony: the
explanation of why mental types and certain physical types co-occur is that in
the possible world God actualized (i.e., this world) they co-occur. In
discussing the relation between the mental and physical realms, Leibniz used
the analogy of two synchronized but unconnected clocks. The analogy is,
however, somewhat misleading; suggesting causal mechanisms internal to each
clock and intrental and intraphysical (causal) transactions. But Leibniz’s
monadology doctrine excludes the possibility of such transactions: mental and
physical phenomena have no effects even within their own realms. Malebranche is
associated with occasionalism, according to which only God, through his
continuous activities, causes things to happen: non-divine phenomena never
cause anything. Occasionalism differs from preestablished harmony in holding that
God is continually engaged in acts of creation; each moment creating the world
anew, in such a way that the correlations hold. Both brands of parallelism face
formidable difficulties. First, both rest on highly contentious, obscure
theological hypotheses. The contention that God exists and the creation stories
in question require extensive defense and explanation. God’s relationship to
the world can seem at least as mysterious as the relationship Descartes posits
between minds and brains. Second, since parallelism denies the possibility of
psychophysical interaction, its proponents must offer alternatives to the
causal theory of perception and the causal theory of action or else deny that
we can perceive and that we can act intentionally. Third, since parallelism
rejects intrental causation, it must either deny that reasoning is possible or
explain how it is possible without causal connections between thoughts. Fourth,
since parallelism rejects physical transactions, it is hard to see how it can
allow, e.g., that one physical thing ever moves another; for that would require
causing a change in location. Perhaps none of these weighty difficulties is
ultimately insuperable; in any case, parallelism has been abandoned.
Epiphenomenalism. Empirical research gives every indication that the occurrence
of any brain state can, in principle, be causally explained by appeal solely to
other physical states. To accommodate this, some philosophers espoused
epiphenomenalism, the doctrine that physical states cause mental states, but
mental states do not cause anything. (This thesis was discussed under the ne
‘conscious automatism’ by Huxley and Hogeson in the late nineteenth century.
Willi Jes was the first to use the term ‘epiphenomena’ to mean phenomena that
lack causal efficacy. And Jes Ward coined the term ‘epiphenomenalism’ in 1903.)
Epiphenomenalism implies that there is only one-way psychophysical action –
from the physical to the mental. Since epiphenomenalism allows such causal
action, it can embrace the causal theory of perception. However, when combined
with Cartesian dualism, epiphenomenalism, like Cartesian interactionism,
implies the problematic thesis that states of an extended substance can affect
states of an unextended substance. An epiphenomenalist can avoid this problem
by rejecting the view that the mind is an unextended substance while
maintaining that mental states and events are nonetheless distinct from
physical states and events. Still, formidable problems would remain. It is hard
to see how epiphenomenalism can allow that we are ever intentional agents. For
intentional agency requires acting on reasons, which, according to the causal
theory of action, requires a causal connection between reasons and actions.
Since epiphenomenalism denies that such causal connections are possible, it
must either maintain that our sense of agency is illusory or offer an
alternative to the causal theory of action. Similarly, it must explain how
thinking is possible philosophy of mind philosophy of mind 685 685 given that there are no causal
connections between thoughts. Monism The dual-aspect theory. Many philosophers
reject Descartes’s bifurcation of reality into mental and physical substances.
Spinoza held a dualattribute theory – also called the dual-aspect theory – according
to which the mental and the physical are distinct modes of a single substance,
God. The mental and the physical are only two of infinitely many modes of this
one substance. Many philosophers opted for a thoroughgoing monism, according to
which all of reality is really of one kind. Materialism, idealism, and neutral
monism are three brands of monism. Hobbes, a contemporary of Descartes,
espoused materialism, the brand of monism according to which everything is
material or physical. Berkeley is associated with idealism, the brand of monism
according to which everything is mental. He held that both mental and physical
phenomena are perceptions in the mind of God. For Hegel’s idealism, everything
is part of the World Spirit. The early twentieth-century British philosophers
Bradley and McTaggart also held a version of idealism. Neutral monism is the
doctrine that all of reality is ultimately of one kind, which is neither mental
nor physical. Hume was a neutral monist, maintaining that mental and physical substances
are really just bundles of the neutral entities. Versions of neutral monism
were later held by Mach and, for a short time, Russell. Russell called his
neutral entities sensibilia and claimed that minds and physical objects are
logical constructions out of them. Phenomenalism. This view, espoused in the
twentieth century by, ong others, Ayer, argues that all empirical statements
are synonymous with statements solely about phenomenal appearances. While the
doctrine is about statements, phenomenalism is either a neutral monism or an
idealism, depending on whether phenomenal appearances are claimed to be neither
mental nor physical or, instead, mental. The required translations of physical
statements into phenomenal ones proved not to be forthcoming, however. Chisholm
offered a reason why they would not be: what appearances a physical state of
affairs (e.g., objects arrayed in a room) has depends both on physical
conditions of observation (e.g., lighting) and physical conditions of the
perceiver (e.g., of the nervous system). At best, a statement solely about
phenomenal appearances is equivalent to one about a physical state of affairs,
only when certain physical conditions of observation and certain physical
conditions of the perceiver obtain. Materialism. Two problems face any monism:
it must characterize the phenomena it takes as basic, and it must explain how
the fundental phenomena make up non-basic phenomena. The idealist and neutral
monist theories proposed thus far have faltered on one or both counts. Largely
because of scientific successes of the twentieth century, such as the rebirth
of the atomic theory of matter, and the successes of quantum mechanics in
explaining chemistry and of chemistry in turn in explaining much of biology,
many philosophers today hold that materialism will ultimately succeed where
idealism and neutral monism apparently failed. Materialism, however, comes in
many different varieties and each faces formidable difficulties. Logical
behaviorism. Ryle ridiculed Cartesianism as the view that there is a ghost in
the machine (the body). He claimed that the view that the mind is a substance
rests on a category mistake: ‘mind’ is a noun, but does not ne an object.
Cartesianism confuses the logic of discourse about minds with the logic of
discourse about bodies. To have a mind is not to possess a special sort of
entity; it is simply to have certain capacities and dispositions. (Compare the
thesis that to be alive is to possess not a certain entity, an entelechy or
élan vital, but rather certain capacities and dispositions.) Ryle maintained,
moreover, that it was a mistake to regard mental states such as belief, desire,
and intention as internal causes of behavior. These states, he claimed, are
dispositions to behave in overt ways. In part in response to the dualist point
that one can understand our ordinary psychological vocabulary (‘belief’,
‘desire’, ‘pain’, etc.) and know nothing about the physical states and events
in the brain, logical behaviorism has been proposed as a materialist doctrine
that explains this fact. On this view, talk of mental phenomena is shorthand
for talk of actual and potential overt bodily behavior (i.e., dispositions to
overt bodily behavior). Logical behaviorism was much discussed from roughly the
1930s until the early 1960s. (While Ryle is sometimes counted as a logical
behaviorist, he was not committed to the thesis that all mental talk can be
translated into behavioral talk.) The translations promised by logical
behaviorism appear unachievable. As Putn and others pointed out, one can fake
being in pain and one can be in pain and yet not behave or be disposed to
behave as if one were in pain (e.g., one might philosophy of mind philosophy of
mind 686 686 be paralyzed or might be
a “super-spartan”). Logical behaviorism faces similar difficulties in
translating sentences about (what Russell called) propositional attitudes
(i.e., beliefs that p, desires that p, hopes that p, intentions that p, and the
like). Consider the following sple proposal (similar to one offered by Carnap):
one believes that the cat is on the mat if and only if one is disposed to
assent to ‘The cat is on the mat’. First, the proposed translation meets the
condition of being purely behavioral only if assenting is understandable in
purely behavioral terms. That is doubtful. The proposal also fails to provide a
sufficient or a necessary condition: someone may assent to ‘The cat is on the
mat’ and yet not believe the cat is on the mat (for the person may be trying to
deceive); and a belief that the cat is on the mat will dispose one to assent to
‘The cat is on the mat’ only if one understands what is being asked, wants to
indicate that one believes the cat is on the mat, and so on. But none of these
conditions is required for believing that the cat is on the mat. Moreover, to
invoke any of these mentalistic conditions defeats the attempt to provide a
purely behavioral translation of the belief sentence. Although the project of
translation has been abandoned, in recent years Dennett has defended a view in
the spirit of logical behaviorism, intentional systems theory: belief-desire
talk functions to characterize overall patterns of dispositions to overt
behavior (in an environmental context) for the purposes of predicting overt
behavior. The theory is sometimes characterized as supervenient behaviorism
since it implies that whether an individual has beliefs, desires, intentions
and the like supervenes on his dispositions to overt behavior: if two
individuals are exactly alike in respect of their dispositions to overt
behavior, the one has intentional states if and only if the other does. (This
view allows, however, that the contents of an individual’s intentional states –
what the individual believes, desires, etc. – may depend on environmental factors.
So it is not committed to the supervenience of the contents of intentional
states on dispositions to overt behavior.the discussion of content externalism
below.) One objection to this view, due to Ned Block, is that it would
mistakenly count as an intentional agent a giant look-up table – “a Blockhead”
– that has the se dispositions to peripheral behavior as a genuine intentional
agent. (A look-up table is a simple mechanical device that looks up preprogrmed
responses.) Identity theories. In the early 1950s, Herbert Feigl claimed that
mental states are brain states. He pointed out that if mental properties or
state types are merely nomologically correlated with physical properties or
state types, the connecting laws would be “nomological danglers”: irreducible
to physical laws, and thus additional fundental laws. According to the identity
theory, the connecting laws are not fundental laws (and so not nomological
danglers) since they can be explained by identifying the mental and physical
properties in question. In the late 1950s and the early 1960s, the philosopher
Smart and the psychologist U. T. Place defended the materialist view that
sensations are identical with brain processes. Smart claimed that while mental
terms differ in meaning from physical terms, scientific investigation reveals
that they have the se referents as certain physical terms. (Compare the fact
that while ‘the Morning Star’ and ‘the Evening Star’ differ in meaning
empirical investigation reveals the se referent: Venus.) Smart and Place
claimed that feeling pain, e.g., is some brain process, exactly which one to be
determined by scientific investigation. Smart claimed that sensation talk is
paraphraseable in topic-neutral terms; i.e., in terms that leave open whether
sensational properties are mental or physical. ‘I have an orange afterimage’ is
paraphraseable (roughly) as: ‘There is something going on like what is going on
when I have my eyes open, awake, and
there is an orange illuminated in good light in front of me, i.e., when I really
see an orange’. The description is topic-neutral since it leaves open whether
what is going on is mental or physical. Smart maintained that scientific
investigation reveals that what in fact meets the topic-neutral description is
a brain process. He held that psychophysical identity statements such as ‘Pain
is C-fiber firing’ are contingent, likening these to, e.g., ‘Lightning is
electrical discharge’, which is contingent and knowable only through empirical
investigation. Central state materialism. This brand of materialism was
defended in the late 1960s and the early 1970s by Armstrong and others. On this
view, mental states are states that are apt to produce a certain range of
behavior. Central state materialists maintain that scientific investigation reveals
that such states are states of the central nervous system, and thus that mental
states are contingently identical with states of the central nervous system.
Unlike logical behaviorism, central state materialism does not imply that
mental sentences can be translated into physical sentences. Unlike both logical
behaviorism and philosophy of mind philosophy of mind 687 687 intentional systems theory, central
state materialism implies that mental states are actual internal states with
causal effects. And unlike Cartesian interactionism, it holds that
psychophysical interaction is just physical causal interaction. Some central
state materialists held in addition that the mind is the brain. However, if the
mind were the brain, every change in the brain would be a change in the mind;
and that seems false: not every little brain change ounts to a change of mind.
Indeed, the mind ceases to exist when brain death occurs, while the brain
continues to exist. The moral that most materialists nowadays draw from such
considerations is that the mind is not any physical substance, since it is not
a substance of any sort. To have a mind is not to possess a special substance,
but rather to have certain capacities – to think, feel, etc. To that extent,
Ryle was right. However, central state materialists insist that the properly
functioning brain is the material seat of mental capacities, that the exercise
of mental capacities consists of brain processes, and that mental states are
brain states that can produce behavior. Epistemological objections have been
raised to identity theories. As self-conscious beings, we have a kind of
privileged access to our own mental states. The exact avenue of privileged
access, whether it is introspection or not, is controversial. But it has seemed
to many philosophers that our access to our own mental states is privileged in
being open only to us, whereas we lack any privileged access to the states of
our central nervous systems. We come to know about central nervous system
states in the se way we come to know about the central nervous system states of
others. So, against central state materialism and the identity theory, it is
claimed that mental states cannot be states of our central nervous systems.
Taking privileged access to imply that we have incorrigible knowledge of our
conscious mental states, and despairing of squaring privileged access so
understood with materialism, Rorty advocated eliminative materialism, the
thesis that there actually are no mental phenomena. A more common materialist
response, however, is to deny that privileged access entails incorrigibility
and to maintain that privileged access is compatible with materialism. Some
materialists maintain that while certain types of mental states (e.g.,
sensations) are types of neurological states, it will be knowable only by
empirical investigation that they are. Suppose pain is a neural state N. It
will be only a posteriori knowable that pain is N. Via the avenue of privileged
access, one comes to believe that one is in a pain state, but not that one is
in an N-state. One can believe one is in a pain state without believing that
one is in an N-state because the concept of pain is different from the concept
of N. Nevertheless, pain is N. (Compare the fact that while water is H2O, the
concept of water is different from that of H2O. Thus, while water is H2O, one
can believe there is water in the glass without believing that there is H2O in
it. The avenue of privileged access presents N conceptualized as pain, but
never as neurological state N. The avenue of privileged access involves the
exercise of mental, but not neurophysiological, concepts. However, our mental
concepts answer to – apply in virtue of – the se properties (state types) as do
certain of our neurophysiological concepts. The identity theory and central
state materialism both hold that there are contingent psychophysical property
and type identities. Some theorists in this tradition tried to distinguish a
notion of theoretical identity from the notion of strict identity. They held
that mental states are theoretically, but not strictly, identical with brain
states. Against any such distinction, Kripke argued that identities are
metaphysically necessary, i.e., hold in every possible world. If A % B, then
necessarily A % B. Kripke acknowledged that there can be contingent statements
of identity. But such statements, he argued, will employ at least one term that
is not a rigid designator, i.e., a term that designates the se thing in every
world in which it designates anything. Thus, since ‘the inventor of bifocals’
is a non-rigid designator, ‘Benjin Franklin is the inventor of bifocals’ is
contingent. While Franklin is the inventor of bifocals, he might not have been.
However, statements of identity in which the identity sign is flanked by rigid
designators are, if true, metaphysically necessary. Kripke held that proper nes
are rigid designators, and hence, the true identity statement ‘Cicero is Tully’
is metaphysically necessary. Nonetheless, a metaphysically necessary identity
statement can be knowable only a posteriori. Indeed, ‘Cicero is Tully’ is
knowable only a posteriori. Both ‘water’ and ‘H2O’, he maintained, are rigid
designators: each designates the se kind of stuff in every possible world. And
he thus maintained that it is metaphysically necessary that water is H2O,
despite its not being a priori knowable that water is H2O. On Kripke’s view,
any psychophysical identity statement that employs mental terms and physical
terms that are rigid designators will also be metaphysically necessary, if
true. philosophy of mind philosophy of mind 688 688 Central state materialists maintain
that mental concepts are equivalent to concepts whose descriptive content is
the state that is apt to produce such-and-such behavior in such-and-such
circumstances. These defining descriptions for mental concepts are intended to
be meaning-giving, not contingent reference-fixing descriptions; they are,
moreover, not rigid designators. Thus, the central state materialists can
concede that all identities are necessary, but maintain that psychophysical
claims of identity are contingent claims of identity since the mental terms
that figure in those statements are not rigid designators. However, Kripke
maintained that our concepts of sensations and other qualitative states are not
equivalent to the sorts of descriptions in question. The term ‘pain’, he
maintained, is a rigid designator. This position might be refuted by a
successful functional analysis of the concept of pain in physical and/or topic-neutral
terms. However, no successful analysis of this sort has yet been produced. (See
the section on consciousness below.) A materialist can grant Kripke that ‘pain’
is a rigid designator and claim that a statement such as ‘Pain is C-fiber
firing’ will be metaphysically necessary if true, but only a posteriori
knowable. However, Kripke raised a formidable problem for this materialism. He
pointed out that if a statement is metaphysically necessary but only a
posteriori knowable, its appearance of contingency calls for explanation.
Despite being metaphysically necessary, ‘Water is H2O’ appears contingent.
According to Kripke, we explain this appearance by noting that one can
coherently imagine a world in which something has all the phenomenal properties
of water, and so is an “epistemic counterpart” of it, yet is not H2O. The fact
that we can coherently imagine such epistemic counterparts explains why ‘Water
is H2O’ appears contingent. But no such explanation is available for (e.g.)
‘Pain is C-fiber firing’. For an epistemic counterpart of pain, something with
the phenomenal properties of pain – the feel of pain – is pain. Something can
look, smell, taste, and feel like water yet not be water. But whatever feels
like pain is pain: pain is a feeling. In contrast, we can explain the apparent
contingency of claims like ‘Water is H2O’ because water is not constituted by
its phenomenal properties; our concept of water allows that it may have a
“hidden essence,” i.e., an essential microstructure. If Kripke is right, then
anyone who maintains that a statement of identity concerning a type of bodily
sensation and a type of physical state is metaphysically necessary yet a
posteriori, must explain the appearance of contingency in a way that differs
from the way Kripke explains the appearance of contingency of ‘Water is H2O’.
This is a formidable challenge. (The final section, on consciousness, sketches
some materialist responses to it.) The general issue of property and state type
identity is controversial. The claim that water is H2O despite the fact that
the concept of water is distinct from the concept of H2O seems plausible.
However, property or state type identity is more controversial than the
identity of types of substances. For properties or state types, there are no generally
accepted “non-duplication principles” – to use a phrase of David Lewis’s. (A
nonduplication principle for A’s will say that no two A’s can be exactly alike
in a certain respect; e.g., no two sets can have exactly the se members.) It is
widely denied, for instance, that no two properties can be possessed by exactly
the se things. Two properties, it is claimed, can be possessed by the se
things; likewise, two state types can occur in the se space-time regions. Even
assuming that mental concepts are distinct from physical concepts, the issue of
whether mental state types are physical state types raises the controversial
issue of the non-duplication principle for state types. Token and type
physicalisms. Token physicalism is the thesis that every particular is
physical. Type physicalism is the thesis that every type or kind of entity is
physical; thus, the identity thesis and central state materialism are type
physicalist theses since they imply that types of mental states are types of
physical states. Type physicalism implies token physicalism: given the former,
every token falls under some physical type, and therefore is token-token
identical with some token of a physical type. But token physicalism does not
imply type physicalism; the former leaves open whether physical tokens fall
under non-physical types. Some doctrines billed as materialist or physicalist
embrace token epiphenomenalism, but reject type physicalism. Non-reductive
materialism. This form of materialism implies token physicalism, but denies
type physicalism and, as well, that mental types (properties, etc.) are
reducible to physical types. This doctrine has been discussed since at least
the late nineteenth century and was widely discussed in the first third of the
twentieth century. The British philosophers George Henry Lewes, Suel Alexander,
Lloyd Morgan, and C. D. Broad all held or thought plausible a certain version
of non-reductive materialism. They held or sympathized with the view that every
substance philosophy of mind philosophy of mind 689 689 either is or is wholly made up of
physical particles, that the well-functioning brain is the material seat of
mental capacities, and that token mental states (events, processes, etc.) are
token neurophysiological states (events, processes, etc.). However, they either
held or thought plausible the view that mental capacities, properties, etc.,
emerge from, and thus do not reduce to, physical capacities, properties, etc.
Lewes coined the term ‘emergence’; and Broad later labeled the doctrine
emergent materialism. Emergent materialists maintain that laws correlating
mental and physical properties are irreducible. (These laws would be what Feigl
called nomological danglers.) Emergentists maintain that, despite their
untidiness, such laws must be accepted with natural piety. Davidson’s doctrine
of anomalous monism is a current brand of non-reductive materialism. He
explicitly formulates this materialist thesis for events; and his
irreducibility thesis is restricted to intentional mental types – e.g.,
believings, desirings, and intendings. Anomalous monism says that every event
token is physical, but that intentional mental predicates and concepts (ones
expressing propositional attitudes) do not reduce, by law or definition, to
physical predicates or concepts. Davidson offers an original argument for this
irreducibility thesis. Mental predicates and concepts are, he claims, governed
by constitutive principles of rationality, but physical predicates and concepts
are not. This difference, he contends, excludes the possibility of reduction of
mental predicates and concepts to physical ones. Davidson denies, moreover,
that there are strict psychological or psychophysical laws. He calls the
conjunction of this thesis and his irreducibility thesis the principle of the
anomalism of the mental. His argument for token physicalism (for events)
appeals to the principle of the anomalism of the mental and to the principle of
the nomological character of causality: when two events are causally related,
they are subsumed by a strict law. He maintains that all strict laws are
physical. Given that claim, and given the principle of the nomological
character of causality, it follows that every event that is a cause or effect
is a physical event. On this view, psychophysical causation is just causation
between physical events. Stephen Schiffer has also maintained a non-reductive
materialism, one he calls ontological physicalism and sentential dualism: every
particular is physical, but mental truths are irreducible to physical truths.
Non-reductive materialism presupposes that mental state (event) tokens can fall
under physical state types and, thereby, count as physical state tokens. This
presupposition is controversial; no uncontroversial non-duplication principle
for state tokens settles the issue. Suppose, however, that mental state tokens
are physical state tokens, despite mental state types not being physical state
types. The issue of how mental state types and physical state types are related
remains. Suppose that some physical token x is of a mental type M (say, a
belief that the cat is on the mat) and some other physical token y is not of
type M. There must, it seems, be some difference between x and y in virtue of
which x is, and y is not, of type M. Otherwise, it is simply a brute fact that
x is and y is not of type M. That, however, seems implausible. The claim that
certain physical state tokens fall under mental state types simply as a matter
of brute fact would leave the difference in question utterly mysterious. But if
it is not a brute fact, then there is some explanation of why a certain
physical state is a mental state of a certain sort. The non-reductive
materialist owes us an explanation that does not imply psychophysical
reduction. Moreover, even though the non-reductive materialist can claim that
mental states are causes because they are physical states with physical
effects, there is some question whether mental state types are relevant to
causal relations. Suppose every state is a physical state. Given that physical
states causally interact in virtue of falling under physical types, it follows
that whenever states causally interact they do so in virtue of falling under
physical types. That raises the issue of whether states are ever causes in
virtue of falling under mental types. Type epiphenomenalism is the thesis that
no state can cause anything in virtue of falling under a mental type. Token
epiphenomenalism, the thesis that no mental state can cause anything, implies
type epiphenomenalism, but not conversely. Nonreductive materialists are not
committed to token physicalism. However, token epiphenomenalism may be false
but type epiphenomenalism true since mental states may be causes only in virtue
of falling under physical types, never in virtue of falling under mental types.
Broad raised the issue of type epiphenomenalism and discussed whether emergent
materialism is committed to it. Ted Honderich, Jaegwon Kim, Ernest Sosa, and
others have in recent years raised the issue of whether non-reductive materialism
is committed to type epiphenomenalism. Brian McLaughlin has argued that the
claim that an event acts as a cause in virtue of falling under a certain
physical type is consistent with the philosophy of mind philosophy of mind 690 690 claim that it also acts as a cause in
virtue of falling under a certain mental type, even when the mental type is not
identical with the physical type. But even if this is so, the relationship
between mental types and physical types must be addressed. Ernest LePore and Barry
Loewer, Frank Jackson and Philip Pettit, Stephen Yablo, and others have
attempted to characterize a relation between mental types and physical types
that allows for the causal relevance of mental types. But whether there is a
relation between mental and physical properties that is both adequate to secure
the causal relevance of mental properties and available to non-reductive
materialists remains an open question. Davidson’s anomalous monism may appear
to be a kind of dual-aspect theory: there are events and they can have two
sorts of autonomous aspects, mental and physical. However, while Davidson holds
that mental properties (or types) do not reduce to physical ones, he also holds
that the mental properties of an event depend on its physical properties in
that the former supervene on the latter in this sense: no two events can be
exactly alike in every physical respect and yet differ in some mental respect.
This proposal introduced the notion of supervenience into contem- porary
philosophy of mind. Often nonreductive materialists argue that mental
properties (types) supervene on physical properties (types). Kim, however, has
distinguished various supervenience relations, and argues that some are too
weak to count as versions of materialism (as opposed to, say, dual-aspect
theory), while other supervenience relations are too strong to use to formulate
non-reductive materialism since they imply reducibility. According to Kim,
non-reductive materialism is an unstable position. Materialism as a
supervenience thesis. Several philosophers have in recent years attempted to
define the thesis of materialism using a global supervenience thesis. Their aim
is not to formulate a brand of non-reductive materialism; they maintain that
their supervenience thesis may well imply reducibility. Their aim is, rather,
to formulate a thesis to which anyone who counts as a genuine materialist must
subscribe. David Lewis has maintained that materialism is true if and only if
any non-alien possible worlds that are physically indiscernible are mentally
indiscernible as well. Non-alien possible worlds are worlds that have exactly
the se perfectly natural properties as the actual world. Frank Jackson has
offered this proposal: materialism is true if and only if any minimal physical
duplicate of the actual world is a duplicate simpliciter of the actual world. A
world is a physical duplicate of the actual world if and only if it is exactly
like the actual world in every physical respect (physical particular for
physical particular, physical property for physical property, physical relation
for physical relation, etc.); and a world is a duplicate simpliciter of the
actual world if and only if it is exactly like the actual world in every
respect. A minimal physical duplicate of the actual world is a physical
duplicate that contains nothing else (by way of particulars, kinds, properties,
etc.) than it must in order to be a physical duplicate of the actual world. Two
questions arise for any formulation of the thesis of materialism. Is it adequate
to materialism? And, if it is, is it true? Functionalism. The
nineteenth-century British philosopher George Henry Lewes maintained that while
not every neurological event is mental, every mental event is neurological. He
claimed that what makes certain neurological events mental events is their
causal role in the organism. This is a very early version of functionalism,
nowadays a leading approach to the mind–body problem. Functionalism implies an
answer to the question of what makes a state token a mental state of a certain
kind M: nely, that it is an instance of some functional state type identical
with M. There are two versions of this proposal. On one, a mental state type M
of a system will be identical with the state type that plays a certain causal
role R in the system. The description ‘the state type that plays R in the
system’ will be a nonrigid designator; moreover, different state types may play
R in different organisms, in which case the mental state is multiply
realizable. On the second version, a mental state type M is identical with a
second-order state type, the state of being in some first-order state that
plays causal role R. More than one first-order state may play role R, and thus
M may be multiply realizable. On either version, if the relevant causal roles
are specifiable in physical or topic-neutral terms, then the functional
definitions of mental state types will be, in principle, physically reductive.
Since the roles would be specified partly in topic-neutral terms, there may
well be possible worlds in which the mental states are realized by non-physical
states; thus, functionalism does not imply token physicalism. However,
functionalists typically maintain that, on the empirical evidence, mental
states are realized (in our world) only by physical states. Functionalism comes
in many varieties. philosophy of mind philosophy of mind 691 691 Smart’s topic-neutral analysis of our
talk of sensations is in the spirit of functionalism. And Armstrong’s central
state materialism counts as a kind of functionalism since it maintains that
mental states are states apt to produce a certain range of behavior, and thus
identifies states as mental states by their performing this causal role.
However, functionalists today typically hold that the defining causal roles
include causal roles vis-à-vis input state types, as well as output state
types, and also vis-à-vis other internal state types of the system in question.
In the 1960s David Lewis proposed a functionalist theory, analytical
functionalism, according to which definitions of mental predicates such as
‘belief’, ‘desire’, and the like (though not predicates such as ‘believes that
p’ or ‘desires that q’) can be obtained by conjoining the platitudes of
commonsense psychology and formulating the Rsey sentence for the conjunction.
The relevant Rsey sentence is a second-order quantificational sentence that
quantifies over the mental predicates in the conjunction of commonsense
psychological platitudes, and from it one can derive definitions of the mental
predicates. On this view, it will be analytic that a certain mental state
(e.g., belief) is the state that plays a certain causal role vis-à-vis other
states; and it is a matter of empirical investigation what state plays the
role. Lewis claimed that such investigation reveals that the state types that
play the roles in question are physical states. In the early 1960s, Putn
proposed a version of scientific functionalism, machine state functionalism:
according to this view, mental states are types of Turing machine table states.
Turing machines are mechanical devices consisting of a tape with squares on it
that either are blank or contain symbols, and an executive that can move one
square to the left, or one square to the right, or stay where it is. And it can
either write a symbol on a square, erase a symbol on a square, or leave the
square as it is. (According to the Church-Turing thesis, every computable
function can be computed by a Turing machine.) Now there are two functions
specifying such a machine: one from input states to output states, the other
from input states to input states. And these functions are expressible by
counterfactuals (e.g., ‘If the machine is in state s 1 and receives input I, it
will emit output O and enter state s2’). Machine tables are specified by the
counterfactuals that express the functions in question. So the main idea of
machine state functionalism is that any given mental type is definable as the
state type that participates in certain counterfactual relationships specified
in terms of purely formal, and so not semantically interpreted, state types.
Any system whose inputs, outputs, and internal states are counterfactually
related in the way characterized by a machine table is a realization of that
table. This version of machine state functionalism has been abandoned: no one
maintains that the mind has the architecture of a Turing machine. However,
computational psychology, a branch of cognitive psychology, presupposes a
scientific functionalist view of cognitive states: it takes the mind to have a
computational architecture. (See the section on cognitive psychology below.)
Functionalism – the view that what makes a state a realization of a mental
state is its playing a certain causal role – remains a leading theory of mind.
But functionalism faces formidable difficulties. Block has pinpointed one. On
the one hand, if the input and output states that figure in the causal role
alleged to define a certain mental state are specified in insufficient detail,
the functional definition will be too liberal: it will mistakenly classify
certain states as of that mental type. On the other hand, if the input and
output states are specified in too much detail, the functional definition will
be chauvinistic: it will fail to count certain states as instances of the
mental state that are in fact such instances. Moreover, it has also been argued
that functionalism cannot capture conscious states since types of conscious
states do not admit of functional definitions. Cognitive psychology, content, and
consciousness Cognitive psychology. Many claim that one aim of cognitive
psychology is to provide explanations of intentional capacities, capacities to
be in intentional states (e.g., believing) and to engage in intentional
activities (e.g., reasoning). Fodor has argued that classical cognitive
psychology postulates a cognitive architecture that includes a language of
thought: a system of mental representation with a combinatorial syntax and
semantics, and computational processes defined over these mental representations
in virtue of their syntactic structures. On this view, cognition is
rule-governed symbol manipulation. Mental symbols have meanings, but they
participate in computational processes solely in virtue of their syntactic or
formal properties. The mind is, so to speak, a syntactic engine. The view
implies a kind of content parallelism: syntaxsensitive causal transitions
between symbols will preserve semantic coherence. Fodor has mainphilosophy of
mind philosophy of mind 692 692 tained
that, on this language-of-thought view of cognition (the classical view), being
in a beliefthat-p state can be understood as consisting in bearing a
computational relation (one that is constitutive of belief) to a sentence in
the language of thought that means that p; and similarly for desire, intention,
and the like. The explanation of intentional capacities will be provided by a
computational theory for mental sentences in conjunction with a psychosemantic
theory, a theory of meaning for mental sentences. A research progr in cognitive
science called connectionism postulates networks of neuron-like units. The
units can be either on or off, or can have continuous levels of activation.
Units are connected, the connections have various degrees of strength, and the
connections can be either inhibitory or excitatory. Connectionism has provided
fruitful models for studying how neural networks compute information. Moreover,
connectionists have had much success in modeling pattern recognition tasks
(e.g., facial recognition) and tasks consisting of learning categories from
exples. Some connectionists maintain that connectionism will yield an
alternative to the classical language-of-thought account of intentional states
and capacities. However, some favor a mixed-models approach to cognition: some
cognitive capacities are symbolic, some connectionist. And some hold that
connectionism will yield an implementational architecture for a symbolic
cognitive architecture, one that will help explain how a symbolic cognitive
architecture is realized in the nervous system. Content externalism. Many today
hold that Twin-Earth thought experiments by Putn and Tyler Burge show that the
contents of a subject’s mental states do not supervene on intrinsic properties
of the subject: two individuals can be exactly alike in every intrinsic
respect, yet be in mental states with different contents. (In response to
Twin-Earth thought experiments, some philosophers have, however, attempted to
characterize a notion of narrow content, a kind of content that supervenes on
intrinsic properties of thinkers.) Content, externalists claim, depends on
extrinsic-contextual factors. If externalism is correct, then a psychosemantic
theory must exine the relation between mental symbols and the extrinsic,
contextual factors that determine contents. Stephen Stich has argued that
psychology should eschew psychosemantics and concern itself only with the
syntactic properties of mental sentences. Such a psychology could not explain
intentional capacities. But Stich urges that computational psychology also
eschew that explanatory goal. If, however, psychology is to explain intentional
capacities, a psychosemantic theory is needed. Dretske, Fodor, Ruth Millikan,
and David Papineau have each independently attempted to provide, in
physicalistically respectable terms, foundations for a naturalized externalist
theory of the content of mental sentences or internal physical states. Perhaps
the leading problem for these theories of content is to explain how the
physical and functional facts about a state determine a unique content for it.
Appealing to work by Quine and by Kripke, some philosophers argue that such
facts will not determine unique contents. Both causal and epistemic concerns
have been raised about externalist theories of content. Such theories invite
the question whether the property of having a certain content is ever causally
relevant. If content is a contextual property of a state that has it, can
states have effects in virtue of their having a certain content? This is an
important issue because intentional states figure in explanations not only in
virtue of their intentional mode (whether they are beliefs, or desires, etc.)
but also in virtue of their contents. Consider an everyday belief-desire
explanation. The fact that the subject’s belief was that there was milk in the
refrigerator and the fact that the subject’s desire was for milk are both
essential to the belief and desire explaining why the subject went to the
refrigerator. Dretske, who maintains that content depends on a
causal-historical context, has attempted to explain how the property of having
a certain content can be causally relevant even though the possession of the
property depends on causal-historical factors. And various other philosophers
have attempted to explain how the causal relevance of content can be squared
with the fact that it fails to supervene on intrinsic properties of the
subject. A further controversial question is whether externalism is consistent
with our having privileged access to what we are thinking. Consciousness.
Conscious states such as pain states, visual experiences, and so on, are such
that it is “like” something for the subject of the state to be in them. Such
states have a qualitative aspect, a phenomenological character. The
what-it-is-like aspects of experiences are called qualia. Qualia pose a serious
difficulty for physicalism. Broad argued that one can know all the physical
properties of a chemical and how it causally interacts with other physical
phenomena and yet not know what it is like to smell it. He concluded that the
smell of the chemical is philosophy of mind philosophy of mind 693 693 not itself a physical property, but
rather an irreducible emergent property. Frank Jackson has recently defended a
version of the argument, which has been dubbed the knowledge argument. Jackson
argues that a super-scientist, Mary, who knows all the physical and functional
facts about color vision, light, and matter, but has never experienced redness
since she has spent her entire life in a black and white room, would not know
what it is like to visually experience red. He concludes that the physical and
functional (topic-neutral) facts do not entail all the facts, and thus
materialism is false. In response, Lawrence Nemirow, David Lewis, and others
have argued that knowing what it is like to be in a certain conscious state is,
in part, a matter of know-how (e.g., to be able to imagine oneself in the
state) rather than factual knowledge, and that the failure of knowledge of the
physical and functional facts to yield such know-how does not imply the falsity
of materialism. Functionalism seems unable to solve the problem of qualia since
qualia seem not to be functionally definable. In the 1970s, Fodor and Ned Block
argued that two states can have the se causal role, thereby realizing the se
functional state, yet the qualia associated with each can be inverted. This is
called the problem of inverted qualia. The color spectrum, e.g., might be
inverted for two individuals (a possibility raised by Locke), despite their
being in the se functional states. They further argued that two states might
realize the se functional state, yet the one might have qualia associated with
it and the other not. This is called the problem of absent qualia. Sydney
Shoemaker has argued that the possibility of absent qualia can be ruled out on
functionalist grounds. However, he has also refined the inverted qualia
scenario and further articulated the problem it poses for functionalism.
Whether functionalism or physicalism can avoid the problems of absent and
inverted qualia remains an open question. Thomas Nagel claims that conscious
states are subjective: to fully understand them, one must understand what it is
like to be in them, but one can do that only by taking up the experiential
point of view of a subject in them. Physical states, in contrast, are
objective. Physical science attempts to characterize the world in abstraction
from the experiential point of view of any subject. According to Nagel, whether
phenomenal mental states reduce to physical states turns on whether subjective
states reduce to objective states; and, at present, he claims, we have no
understanding of how they could. Nagel has suggested that consciousness may be
explainable only by appeal to as yet undiscovered basic nonmental, non-physical
properties – “proto-mental properties” – the idea being that experiential
points of view might be constituted by protomental properties together with
physical properties. He thus claims that panphysicism is worthy of serious
consideration. Frank Jackson, Jes Van Cleve, and David Chalmers have argued
that conscious properties are emergent, i.e., fundental, irreducible
macro-properties; and Chalmers sympathizes with a brand of panphysicism. Colin
McGinn claims that while conscious properties are likely reductively
explainable by brain properties, our minds seem conceptually closed to the
explaining properties: we are unable to conceptualize them, just as a cat is
unable to conceptualize a square root. Dennett attempts to explain
consciousness in supervenient behaviorist terms. David Rosenthal argues that
consciousness is a special case of intentionality – more specifically, that
conscious states are just states we can come in a certain direct way to believe
we are in. Dretske, Willi Lycan, and Michael Tye argue that conscious
properties are intentional properties and physicalistically reducible. Patricia
Churchland argues that conscious phenomena are reducible to neurological
phenomena. Brian Loar contends that qualia are identical with either functional
or neurological states of the brain; and Christopher Hill argues specifically
that qualia are identical with neurological states. Loar and Hill attempt to
explain away the appearance of contingency of psychophysical identity claims,
but in a way different from the way Kripke attempts to explain the appearance
of contingency of ‘Water is H2O’, since they concede that that mode of
explanation is unavailable. They appeal to differences in the conceptual roles
of neurological and functional concepts by contrast with phenomenal concepts.
They argue that while such concepts are different, they answer to the se
properties. The nature of consciousness thus remains a matter of dispute.
philosophy of psychology,
the philosophical study of psychology. Psychology began to separate from
philosophy with the work of the ninephilosophy of organism philosophy of
psychology 694 694 teenth-century
German experimentalists, especially Fechner (1801–87), Helmholtz (1821– 94),
and Wundt (1832–1920). In the first half of the twentieth century, the
separation was completed in this country insofar as separate psychology
departments were set up in most universities, psychologists established their
own journals and professional associations, and experimental methods were
widely employed, although not in every area of psychology (the first
experimental study of the effectiveness of a psychological therapy did not
occur until 1963). Despite this achievement of autonomy, however, issues have remained
about the nature of the connections, if any, that should continue between
psychology and philosophy. One radical view, that virtually all such
connections should be severed, was defended by the behaviorist John Watson in
his seminal 1913 paper “Psychology as the Behaviorist Views It.” Watson
criticizes psychologists, even the experimentalists, for relying on
introspective methods and for making consciousness the subject matter of their
discipline. He recommends that psychology be a purely objective experimental
branch of natural science, that its theoretical goal be to predict and control
behavior, and that it discard all reference to consciousness. In making
behavior the sole subject of psychological inquiry, we avoid taking sides on
“those time-honored relics of philosophical speculation,” nely competing
theories about the mind–body problem, such as interactionism and parallelism.
In a later work, published in 1925, Watson claimed that the success of
behaviorism threatened the very existence of philosophy: “With the
behavioristic point of view now becoming dominant, it is hard to find a place
for what has been called philosophy. Philosophy is passing – has all but
passed, and unless new issues arise which will give a foundation for a new
philosophy, the world has seen its last great philosopher.” One new issue was
the credibility of behaviorism. Watson gave no argument for his view that
prediction and control of behavior should be the only theoretical goals of
psychology. If the attempt to explain behavior is also legitimate, as some
anti-behaviorists argue, then it would seem to be an empirical question whether
that goal can be met without appealing to mentalistic causes. Watson and his
successors, such as B. F. Skinner, cited no credible empirical evidence that it
could, but instead relied primarily on philosophical arguments for banning
postulation of mentalistic causes. As a consequence, behaviorists virtually
guaranteed that philosophers of psychology would have at least one additional
task beyond wrestling with traditional mind– body issues: the analysis and
criticism of behaviorism itself. Although behaviorism and the mind–body problem
were never the sole subjects of philosophy of psychology, a much richer set of
topics developed after 1950 when the so-called cognitive revolution occurred in
erican psychology. These topics include innate knowledge and the acquisition of
transformational grmars, intentionality, the nature of mental representation,
functionalism, mental imagery, the language of thought, and, more recently,
connectionism. Such topics are of interest to many cognitive psychologists and
those in other disciplines, such as linguistics and artificial intelligence,
who contributed to the emerging discipline known as cognitive science. Thus, after
the decline of various forms of behaviorism and the consequent rise of
cognitivism, many philosophers of psychology collaborated more closely with
psychologists. This increased cooperation was probably due not only to a
broadening of the issues, but also to a methodological change in philosophy. In
the period roughly between 1945 and 1975, conceptual analysis dominated both
erican and English philosophy of psychology and the closely related discipline,
the philosophy of mind. Many philosophers took the position that philosophy was
essentially an a priori discipline. These philosophers rarely cited the
empirical studies of psychologists. In recent decades, however, philosophy of
psychology has become more empirical, at least in the sense that more attention
is being paid to the details of the empirical studies of psychologists. The
result is more interchanges between philosophers and psychologists. Although
interest in cognitive psychology appears to predominate in recent erican
philosophy of psychology, the new emphasis on empirical studies is also
reflected in philosophic work on topics not directly related to cognitive
psychology. For exple, philosophers of psychology have written books in recent
years on the clinical foundations of psychoanalysis, the foundations of
behavior therapy and behavior modification, and self-deception. The emphasis on
empirical data has been taken one step further by naturalists, who argue that
in epistemology, at least, and perhaps in all areas of philosophy,
philosophical questions should either be replaced by questions from empirical
psychology or be answered by appeal to empirical studies in psychology and
related disciplines. It is philosophy of psychology philosophy of psychology
695 695 still too early to predict the
fruitfulness of the naturalist approach, but this new trend might well have
pleased Watson. Taken to an extreme, naturalism would make philosophy dependent
on psychology instead of the reverse and thus would further enhance the
autonomy of psychology that Watson desired.
philosophy of religion,
the subfield of philosophy devoted to the study of religious phenomena.
Although religions are typically complex systems of theory and practice,
including both myths and rituals, philosophers tend to concentrate on
evaluating religious truth claims. In the major theistic traditions, Judaism,
Christianity, and Isl, the most important of these claims concern the
existence, nature, and activities of God. Such traditions commonly understand
God to be something like a person who is disembodied, eternal, free,
all-powerful, all-knowing, the creator and sustainer of the universe, and the
proper object of human obedience and worship. One important question is whether
this conception of the object of human religious activity is coherent; another
is whether such a being actually exists. Philosophers of religion have sought
rational answers to both questions. The major theistic traditions draw a
distinction between religious truths that can be discovered and even known by
unaided human reason and those to which humans have access only through a
special divine disclosure or revelation. According to Aquinas, e.g., the
existence of God and some things about the divine nature can be proved by
unaided human reason, but such distinctively Christian doctrines as the Trinity
and Incarnation cannot be thus proved and are known to humans only because God
has revealed them. Theists disagree about how such divine disclosures occur;
the main candidates for vehicles of revelation include religious experience,
the teachings of an inspired religious leader, the sacred scriptures of a
religious community, and the traditions of a particular church. The religious
doctrines Christian traditions take to be the content of revelation are often
described as matters of faith. To be sure, such traditions typically affirm
that faith goes beyond mere doctrinal belief to include an attitude of profound
trust in God. On most accounts, however, faith involves doctrinal belief, and
so there is a contrast within the religious domain itself between faith and
reason. One way to spell out the contrast – though not the only way – is to
imagine that the content of revelation is divided into two parts. On the one
hand, there are those doctrines, if any, that can be known by human reason but
are also part of revelation; the existence of God is such a doctrine if it can
be proved by human reason alone. Such doctrines might be accepted by some
people on the basis of rational argument, while others, who lack rational
proof, accept them on the authority of revelation. On the other hand, there are
those doctrines that cannot be known by human reason and for which the
authority of revelation is the sole basis. They are objects of faith rather
than reason and are often described as mysteries of faith. Theists disagree
about how such exclusive objects of faith are related to reason. One prominent
view is that, although they go beyond reason, they are in harmony with it;
another is that they are contrary to reason. Those who urge that such doctrines
should be accepted despite the fact that, or even precisely because, they are
contrary to reason are known as fideists; the fous slogan credo quia absurdum
(‘I believe because it is absurd’) captures the flavor of extreme fideism. Many
scholars regard Kierkegaard as a fideist on account of his emphasis on the
paradoxical nature of the Christian doctrine that Jesus of Nazareth is God
incarnate. Modern philosophers of religion have, for the most part, confined
their attention to topics treatable without presupposing the truth of any
particular tradition’s claims about revelation and have left the exploration of
mysteries of faith to the theologians of various traditions. A great deal of
philosophical work clarifying the concept of God has been prompted by puzzles
that suggest some incoherence in the traditional concept. One kind of puzzle
concerns the coherence of individual claims about the nature of God. Consider
the traditional affirmation that God is allpowerful (omnipotent). Reflection on
this doctrine raises a fous question: Can God make a stone so heavy that even
God cannot lift it? No matter how this is answered, it seems that there is at
least one thing that even God cannot do, i.e., make such a stone or lift such a
stone, and so it appears that even God cannot be all-powerful. Such puzzles
stimulate attempts by philosophers to analyze the concept of omnipotence in a
way that specifies more precisely the scope of the powers coherently
attributable to an omnipotent being. To the extent that such attempts succeed,
they foster a deeper understanding of the concept of God and, if God exists, of
the divine nature. Another sort of puzzle concerns the consistency of
attributing two or more properties to philosophy of religion philosophy of religion
696 696 God. Consider the claim that
God is both immutable and omniscient. An immutable being is one that cannot
undergo internal change, and an omniscient being knows all truths, and believes
no falsehoods. If God is omniscient, it seems that God must first know and
hence believe that it is now Tuesday and not believe that it is now Wednesday
and later know and hence believe that it is now Wednesday and not believe that
it is now Tuesday. If so, God’s beliefs change, and since change of belief is an
internal change, God is not immutable. So it appears that God is not immutable
if God is omniscient. A resolution of this puzzle would further contribute to
enriching the philosophical understanding of the concept of God. It is, of
course, one thing to elaborate a coherent concept of God; it is quite another
to know, apart from revelation, that such a being actually exists. A proof of
the existence of God would yield such knowledge, and it is the task of natural
theology to evaluate arguments that purport to be such proofs. As opposed to
revealed theology, natural theology restricts the assumptions fit to serve as
premises in its arguments to things naturally knowable by humans, i.e.,
knowable without special revelation from supernatural sources. Many people have
hoped that such natural religious knowledge could be universally communicated
and would justify a form of religious practice that would appeal to all
humankind because of its rationality. Such a religion would be a natural
religion. The history of natural theology has produced a bewildering variety of
arguments for the existence of God. The four main types are these: ontological
arguments, cosmological arguments, teleological arguments, and moral arguments.
The earliest and most fous version of the ontological argument was set forth by
Anselm of Canterbury in chapter 2 of his Proslogion. It is a bold attempt to
deduce the existence of God from the concept of God: we understand God to be a
perfect being, something than which nothing greater can be conceived. Because
we have this concept, God at least exists in our minds as an object of the
understanding. Either God exists in the mind alone, or God exists both in the
mind and as an extrental reality. But if God existed in the mind alone, then we
could conceive of a being greater than that than which nothing greater can be
conceived, nely, one that also existed in extrental reality. Since the concept
of a being greater than that than which nothing greater can be conceived is
incoherent, God cannot exist in the mind alone. Hence God exists not only in
the mind but also in extrental reality. The most celebrated criticism of this
form of the argument was Kant’s, who claimed that existence is not a real
predicate. For Kant, a real predicate contributes to determining the content of
a concept and so serves as a part of its definition. But to say that something
falling under a concept exists does not add to the content of a concept; there
is, Kant said, no difference in conceptual content between a hundred real dollars
and a hundred imaginary dollars. Hence whether or not there exists something
that corresponds to a concept cannot be settled by definition. The existence of
God cannot be deduced from the concept of a perfect being because existence is
not contained in the concept or the definition of a perfect being. Contemporary
philosophical discussion has focused on a slightly different version of the
ontological argument. In chapter 3 of Proslogion Anselm suggested that
something than which nothing greater can be conceived cannot be conceived not
to exist and so exists necessarily. Following this lead, such philosophers as
Charles Hartshorne, Norman Malcolm, and Alvin Plantinga have contended that God
cannot be a contingent being who exists in some possible worlds but not in
others. The existence of a perfect being is either necessary, in which case God
exists in every possible world, or impossible, in which case God exists in no
possible worlds. On this view, if it is so much as possible that a perfect
being exists, God exists in every possible world and hence in the actual world.
The crucial premise in this form of the argument is the assumption that the
existence of a perfect being is possible; it is not obviously true and could be
rejected without irrationality. For this reason, Plantinga concedes that the
argument does not prove or establish its conclusion, but maintains that it does
make it rational to accept the existence of God. The key premises of various
cosmological arguments are statements of obvious facts of a general sort about
the world. Thus, the argument to a first cause begins with the observation that
there are now things undergoing change and things causing change. If something
is a cause of such change only if it is itself caused to change by something
else, then there is an infinitely long chain of causes of change. But, it is
alleged, there cannot be a causal chain of infinite length. Therefore there is
something that causes change, but is not caused to change by anything else,
i.e., a first cause. Many critics of this form of the arguphilosophy of
religion philosophy of religion 697
697 ment deny its assumption that there cannot be an infinite causal
regress or chain of causes. This argument also fails to show that there is only
one first cause and does not prove that a first cause must have such divine
attributes as omniscience, omnipotence, and perfect goodness. A version of the
cosmological argument that has attracted more attention from contemporary
philosophers is the argument from contingency to necessity. It starts with the
observation that there are contingent beings – beings that could have failed to
exist. Since contingent beings do not exist of logical necessity, a contingent
being must be caused to exist by some other being, for otherwise there would be
no explanation of why it exists rather than not doing so. Either the causal
chain of contingent beings has a first member, a contingent being not caused by
another contingent being, or it is infinitely long. If, on the one hand, the chain
has a first member, then a necessary being exists and causes it. After all,
being contingent, the first member must have a cause, but its cause cannot be
another contingent being. Hence its cause has to be non-contingent, i.e., a
being that could not fail to exist and so is necessary. If, on the other hand,
the chain is infinitely long, then a necessary being exists and causes the
chain as a whole. This is because the chain as a whole, being itself
contingent, requires a cause that must be noncontingent since it is not part of
the chain. In either case, if there are contingent beings, a necessary being
exists. So, since contingent beings do exist, there is a necessary being that
causes their existence. Critics of this argument attack its assumption that there
must be an explanation for the existence of every contingent being. Rejecting
the principle that there is a sufficient reason for the existence of each
contingent thing, they argue that the existence of at least some contingent
beings is an inexplicable brute fact. And even if the principle of sufficient
reason is true, its truth is not obvious and so it would not be irrational to
deny it. Accordingly, Willi Rowe (b.1931) concludes that this version of the
cosmological argument does not prove the existence of God, but he leaves open
the question of whether it shows that theistic belief is reasonable. The
starting point of teleological arguments is the phenomenon of goal-directedness
in nature. Aquinas, e.g., begins with the claim that we see that things which
lack intelligence act for an end so as to achieve the best result. Modern
science has discredited this universal metaphysical teleology, but many
biological systems do seem to display remarkable adaptations of means to ends.
Thus, as Willi Paley (1743–1805) insisted, the eye is adapted to seeing and its
parts cooperate in complex ways to produce sight. This suggests an analogy
between such biological systems and human artifacts, which are known to be
products of intelligent design. Spelled out in mechanical terms, the analogy
grounds the claim that the world as a whole is like a vast machine composed of
many smaller machines. Machines are contrived by intelligent human designers.
Since like effects have like causes, the world as a whole and many of its parts
are therefore probably products of design by an intelligence resembling the
human but greater in proportion to the magnitude of its effects. Because this
form of the argument rests on an analogy, it is known as the analogical
argument for the existence of God; it is also known as the design argument
since it concludes the existence of an intelligent designer of the world. Hume
subjected the design argument to sustained criticism in his Dialogues
Concerning Natural Religion. If, as most scholars suppose, the character Philo
speaks for Hume, Hume does not actually reject the argument. He does, however,
think that it warrants only the very weak conclusion that the cause or causes
of order in the universe probably bear some remote analogy to human intelligence.
As this way of putting it indicates, the argument does not rule out polytheism;
perhaps different minor deities designed lions and tigers. Moreover, the
analogy with human artificers suggests that the designer or designers of the
universe did not create it from nothing but merely imposed order on already
existing matter. And on account of the mixture of good and evil in the
universe, the argument does not show that the designer or designers are morally
admirable enough to deserve obedience or worship. Since the time of Hume, the
design argument has been further undermined by the emergence of Darwinian
explanations of biological adaptations in terms of natural selection that give
explanations of such adaptations in terms of intelligent design stiff competition.
Some moral arguments for the existence of God conform to the pattern of
inference to the best explanation. It has been argued that the hypothesis that
morality depends upon the will of God provides the best explanation of the
objectivity of moral obligations. Kant’s moral argument, which is probably the
best-known specimen of this type, takes a different tack. According to Kant,
the complete good consists of perfect virtue rewarded with perfect happiness,
and philosophy of religion philosophy of religion 698 698 virtue deserves to be rewarded with
proportional happiness because it makes one worthy to be happy. If morality is
to command the allegiance of reason, the complete good must be a real
possibility, and so practical reason is entitled to postulate that the
conditions necessary to guarantee its possibility obtain. As far as anyone can
tell, nature and its laws do not furnish such a guarantee; in this world,
apparently, the virtuous often suffer while the vicious flourish. And even if
the operation of natural laws were to produce happiness in proportion to
virtue, this would be merely coincidental, and hence finite moral agents would
not have been made happy just because they had by their virtue made themselves
worthy of happiness. So practical reason is justified in postulating a
supernatural agent with sufficient goodness, knowledge, and power to ensure
that finite agents receive the happiness they deserve as a reward for their
virtue, though theoretical reason can know nothing of such a being. Critics of
this argument have denied that we must postulate a systematic connection
between virtue and happiness in order to have good reasons to be moral. Indeed,
making such an assumption might actually tempt one to cultivate virtue for the
sake of securing happiness rather than for its own sake. It seems therefore
that none of these arguments by itself conclusively proves the existence of
God. However, some of them might contribute to a cumulative case for the
existence of God. According to Richard Swinburne, cosmological, teleological,
and moral arguments individually increase the probability of God’s existence
even though none of them makes it more probable than not. But when other
evidence such as that deriving from providential occurrences and religious
experiences is added to the balance, Swinburne concludes that theism becomes
more probable than its negation. Whether or not he is right, it does appear to
be entirely correct to judge the rationality of theistic belief in the light of
our total evidence. But there is a case to be made against theism too.
Philosophers of religion are interested in arguments against the existence of
God, and fairness does seem to require admitting that our total evidence
contains much that bears negatively on the rationality of belief in God. The
problem of evil is generally regarded as the strongest objection to theism. Two
kinds of evil can be distinguished. Moral evil inheres in the wicked actions of
moral agents and the bad consequences they produce. An exple is torturing the
innocent. When evil actions are considered theologically as offenses against
God, they are regarded as sins. Natural evils are bad consequences that
apparently derive entirely from the operations of impersonal natural forces,
e.g. the human and animal suffering produced by natural catastrophes such as
earthquakes and epidemics. Both kinds of evil raise the question of what
reasons an omniscient, omnipotent, and perfectly good being could have for
permitting or allowing their existence. Theodicy is the enterprise of trying to
answer this question and thereby to justify the ways of God to humans. It is,
of course, possible to deny the presuppositions of the question. Some thinkers
have held that evil is unreal; others have maintained that the deity is limited
and so lacks the power or knowledge to prevent the evils that occur. If one
accepts the presuppositions of the question, the most promising strategy for
theodicy seems to be to claim that each evil God permits is necessary for some
greater good or to avoid some alternative to it that is at least as bad if not
worse. The strongest form of this doctrine is the claim made by Leibniz that
this is the best of all possible worlds. It is unlikely that humans, with their
cognitive limitations, could ever understand all the details of the greater
goods for which evils are necessary, assuming that such goods exist; however,
we can understand how some evils contribute to achieving goods. According to
the soul-making theodicy of John Hick (b.1922), which is rooted in a tradition
going back to Irenaeus, admirable human qualities such as compassion could not
exist except as responses to suffering, and so evil plays a necessary part in
the formation of moral character. But this line of thought does not seem to provide
a complete theodicy because much animal suffering occurs unnoticed by humans
and child abuse often destroys rather than strengthens the moral character of
its victims. Recent philosophical discussion has often focused on the claim
that the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent, and perfectly good being is
logically inconsistent with the existence of evil or of a certain quantity of
evil. This is the logical problem of evil, and the most successful response to
it has been the free will defense. Unlike a theodicy, this defense does not
speculate about God’s reasons for permitting evil but merely argues that God’s
existence is consistent with the existence of evil. Its key idea is that moral
good cannot exist apart from libertarian free actions that are not causally
determined. If God aims to produce moral good, God must create free creatures
upon whose cooperation he must depend, philosophy of religion philosophy of
religion 699 699 and so divine
omnipotence is limited by the freedom God confers on creatures. Since such
creatures are also free to do evil, it is possible that God could not have
created a world containing moral good but no moral evil. Plantinga extends the
defense from moral to natural evil by suggesting that it is also possible that
all natural evil is due to the free actions of non-human persons such as Satan
and his cohorts. Plantinga and Swinburne have also addressed the probabilistic
problem of evil, which is the claim that the existence of evil disconfirms or
renders improbable the hypothesis that God exists. Both of them argue for the
conclusion that this is not the case. Finally, it is worth mentioning three
other topics on which contemporary philosophers of religion have worked to good
effect. Important studies of the meaning and use of religious language were
stimulated by the challenge of logical positivism’s claim that theological
language is cognitively meaningless. Defenses of such Christian doctrines as
the Trinity, Incarnation, and Atonement against various philosophical objections
have recently been offered by people committed to elaborating an explicitly
Christian philosophy. And a growing appreciation of religious pluralism has
both sharpened interest in questions about the cultural relativity of religious
rationality and begun to encourage progress toward a comparative philosophy of
religions. Such work helps to make philosophy of religion a lively and diverse
field of inquiry.
philosophy of science,
the branch of philosophy that is centered on a critical exination of the
sciences: their methods and their results. One branch of the philosophy of
science, methodology, is closely related to the theory of knowledge. It
explores the methods by which science arrives at its posited truths concerning
the world and critically explores alleged rationales for these methods. Issues
concerning the sense in which theories are accepted in science, the nature of
the confirmation relation between evidence and hypothesis, the degree to which
scientific claims can be falsified by observational data, and the like, are the
concern of methodology. Other branches of the philosophy of science are
concerned with the meaning and content of the posited scientific results and
are closely related to metaphysics and the philosophy of language. Typical
problems exined are the nature of scientific laws, the cognitive content of
scientific theories referring to unobservables, and the structure of scientific
explanations. Finally, philosophy of science explores specific foundational
questions arising out of the specific results of the sciences. Typical
questions explored might be metaphysical presuppositions of space-time
theories, the role of probability in statistical physics, the interpretation of
measurement in quantum theory, the structure of explanations in evolutionary
biology, and the like. Concepts of the credibility of hypotheses. Some crucial
concepts that arise when issues of the credibility of scientific hypotheses are
in question are the following: Inductivism is the view that hypotheses can receive
evidential support from their predictive success with respect to particular
cases falling under them. If one takes the principle of inductive inference to
be that the future will be like the past, one is subject to the skeptical
objection that this rule is empty of content, and even self-contradictory, if
any kind of “similarity” of cases is permitted. To restore content and
consistency to the rule, and for other methodological purposes as well, it is
frequently alleged that only natural kinds, a delimited set of “genuine”
properties, should be allowed in the formulation of scientific hypotheses. The
view that theories are first arrived at as creative hypotheses of the
scientist’s imagination and only then confronted, for justificatory purposes,
with the observational predictions deduced from them, is called the
hypotheticodeductive model of science. This model is contrasted with the view
that the very discovery of hypotheses is somehow “generated” out of accumulated
observational data. The view that hypotheses are confirmed to the degree that
they provide the “best explanatory account” of the data is often called
abduction and sometimes called inference to the best explanation. The alleged
relation that evidence bears to hypothesis, warranting its truth but not,
generally, guaranteeing that truth, is called confirmation. Methodological
accounts such as inductivism countenance such evidential warrant, frequently
speaking of evidence as making a hypothesis probable but not establishing it
with certainty. Probability in the confirmational context is supposed to be a
relationship holding between propositions that is quantitative and is described
philosophy of science philosophy of science 700 700 by the formal theory of probability. It
is supposed to measure the “degree of support” that one proposition gives to
another, e.g. the degree of support evidential statements give to a hypothesis
allegedly supported by them. Scientific methodologists often claim that science
is characterized by convergence. This is the claim that scientific theories in
their historical order are converging to an ultimate, final, and ideal theory.
Sometimes this final theory is said to be true because it corresponds to the
“real world,” as in realist accounts of convergence. In pragmatist versions
this ultimate theory is the defining standard of truth. It is sometimes alleged
that one ground for choosing the most plausible theory, over and above
conformity of the theory with the observational data, is the simplicity of the
theory. Many versions of this thesis exist, some emphasizing formal elements of
the theory and others, e.g., emphasizing paucity of ontological commitment by
the theory as the measure of simplicity. It is sometimes alleged that in
choosing which theory to believe, the scientific community opts for theories
compatible with the data that make minimal changes in scientific belief
necessary from those demanded by previously held theory. The believer in
methodological conservatism may also try to defend such epistemic conservatism
as normatively rational. An experiment that can decisively show a scientific
hypothesis to be false is called a crucial experiment for the hypothesis. It is
a thesis of many philosophers that for hypotheses that function in theories and
can only confront observational data when conjoined with other theoretical
hypotheses, no absolutely decisive crucial experiment can exist. Concepts of
the structure of hypotheses. Here are some of the essential concepts
encountered when it is the structure of scientific hypotheses that is being
explored: In its explanatory account of the world, science posits novel
entities and properties. Frequently these are alleged to be not accessible to
direct observation. A theory is a set of hypotheses positing such entities and
properties. Some philosophers of science divide the logical consequences of a
theory into those referring only to observable things and features and those
referring to the unobservables as well. Various reductionist, eliminationist,
and instrumentalist approaches to theory agree that the full cognitive content
of a theory is exhausted by its observational consequences reported by its
observation sentences, a claim denied by those who espouse realist accounts of
theories. The view that the parts of a theory that do not directly relate
observational consequences ought not to be taken as genuinely referential at
all, but, rather, as a “mere linguistic instrument” allowing one to derive
observational results from observationally specifiable posits, is called
instrumentalism. From this point of view terms putatively referring to
unobservables fail to have genuine reference and individual non-observational
sentences containing such terms are not individually genuinely true or false.
Verificationism is the general ne for the doctrine that, in one way or another,
the semantic content of an assertion is exhausted by the conditions that count
as warranting the acceptance or rejection of the assertion. There are many
versions of verificationist doctrines that try to do justice both to the
empiricist claim that the content of an assertion is its totality of empirical
consequences and also to a wide variety of anti-reductionist intuitions about
meaning. The doctrine that theoretical sentences must be strictly translatable
into sentences expressed solely in observational terms in order that the
theoretical assertions have genuine cognitive content is sometimes called
operationalism. The “operation” by which a magnitude is determined to have a
specified value, characterized observationally, is taken to give the very
meaning of attributing that magnitude to an object. The doctrine that the
meanings of terms in theories are fixed by the role the terms play in the
theory as a whole is often called semantic holism. According to the semantic
holist, definitions of theoretical terms by appeal to observational terms
cannot be given, but all of the theoretical terms have their meaning given “as
a group” by the structure of the theory as a whole. A related doctrine in
confirmation theory is that confirmation accrues to whole theories, and not to
their individual assertions one at a time. This is confirmational holism. To
see another conception of cognitive content, conjoin all the sentences of a
theory together. Then replace each theoretical term in the sentence so obtained
with a predicate variable and existentially quantify over all the predicate
variables so introduced. This is the Rsey sentence for a (finitely axiomatized)
theory. This sentence has the se logical consequences frable in the
observational vocabulary alone as did the original theory. It is often claimed
that the Rsey sentence for a theory exhausts the cognitive content of the
theory. The Rsey senphilosophy of science philosophy of science 701 701 tence is supposed to “define” the
meaning of the theoretical terms of the original theory as well as have
empirical consequences; yet by asserting the existence of the theoretical
properties, it is sometimes alleged to remain a realist construal of the
theory. The latter claim is made doubtful, however, by the existence of “merely
representational” interpretations of the Rsey sentence. Theories are often said
to be so related that one theory is reducible to another. The study of the
relation theories bear to one another in this context is said to be the study
of intertheoretic reduction. Such reductive claims can have philosophical
origins, as in the alleged reduction of material objects to sense-data or of
spatiotemporal relations to causal relations, or they can be scientific
discoveries, as in the reduction of the theory of light waves to the theory of
electromagnetic radiation. Numerous “models” of the reductive relation exist,
appropriate for distinct kinds and cases of reduction. The term scientific
realism has many and varied uses. ong other things that have been asserted by
those who describe themselves as scientific realists are the claims that
“mature” scientific theories typically refer to real features of the world,
that the history of past falsifications of accepted scientific theories does
not provide good reason for persistent skepticism as to the truth claims of
contemporary theories, and that the terms of theories that putatively refer to
unobservables ought to be taken at their referential face value and not reinterpreted
in some instrumentalistic manner. Internal realism denies irrealist claims
founded on the past falsification of accepted theories. Internal realists are,
however, skeptical of “metaphysical” claims of “correspondence of true theories
to the real world” or of any notion of truth that can be construed in radically
non-epistemic terms. While theories may converge to some ultimate “true”
theory, the notion of truth here must be understood in some version of a
Peircian idea of truth as “ultimate warranted assertability.” The claim that
any theory that makes reference to posited unobservable features of the world
in its explanatory apparatus will always encounter rival theories incompatible
with the original theory but equally compatible with all possible observational
data that might be taken as confirmatory of the original theory is the claim of
the underdetermination thesis. A generalization taken to have “lawlike force”
is called a law of nature. Some suggested criteria for generalizations having lawlike
force are the ability of the generalization to back up the truth of claims
expressed as counterfactual conditions; the ability of the generalization to be
confirmed inductively on the basis of evidence that is only a proper subset of
all the particular instances falling under the generality; and the
generalization having an appropriate place in the simple, systematic hierarchy
of generalizations important for fundental scientific theories of the world.
The application of a scientific law to a given actual situation is usually
hedged with the proviso that for the law’s predictions to hold, “all other,
unspecified, features of the situation are normal.” Such a qualifying clause is
called a ceteris paribus clause. Such “everything else being normal” claims
cannot usually be “filled out,” revealing important problems concerning the
“open texture” of scientific claims. The claim that the full specification of
the state of the world at one time is sufficient, along with the laws of
nature, to fix the full state of the world at any other time, is the claim of
determinism. This is not to be confused with claims of total predictability,
since even if determinism were true the full state of the world at a time might
be, in principle, unavailable for knowledge. Concepts of the foundations of
physical theories. Here, finally, are a few concepts that are crucial in
discussing the foundations of physical theories, in particular theories of
space and time and quantum theory: The doctrine that space and time must be thought
of as a fily of spatial and temporal relations holding ong the material
constituents of the universe is called relationism. Relationists deny that
“space itself” should be considered an additional constituent of the world over
and above the world’s material contents. The doctrine that “space itself” must
be posited as an additional constituent of the world over and above ordinary
material things of the world is substantivalism. Mach’s principle is the demand
that all physical phenomena, including the existence of inertial forces used by
Newton to argue for a substantivalist position, be explainable in purely
relationist terms. Mach speculated that Newton’s explanation for the forces in
terms of acceleration with respect to “space itself” could be replaced with an
explanation resorting to the acceleration of the test object with respect to
the remaining matter of the universe (the “fixed stars”). In quantum theory the
claim that certain philosophy of science philosophy of science 702 702 “conjugate” quantities, such as
position and momentum, cannot be simultaneously “determined” to arbitrary
degrees of accuracy is the uncertainty principle. The issue of whether such a
lack of simultaneous exact “determination” is merely a limitation on our
knowledge of the system or is, instead, a limitation on the system’s having
simultaneous exact values of the conjugate quantities, is a fundental one in
the interpretation of quantum mechanics. Bell’s theorem is a mathematical
result aimed at showing that the explanation of the statistical correlations
that hold between causally noninteractive systems cannot always rely on the
positing that when the systems did causally interact in the past independent
values were fixed for some feature of each of the two systems that determined
their future observational behavior. The existence of such “local hidden
variables” would contradict the correlational predictions of quantum mechanics.
The result shows that quantum mechanics has a profoundly “non-local” nature.
Can quantum probabilities and correlations be obtained as averages over
variables at some deeper level than those specifying the quantum state of a
system? If such quantities exist they are called hidden variables. Many
different types of hidden variables have been proposed: deterministic,
stochastic, local, non-local, etc. A number of proofs exist to the effect that
positing certain types of hidden variables would force probabilistic results at
the quantum level that contradict the predictions of quantum theory. Complementarity
was the term used by Niels Bohr to describe what he took to be a fundental
structure of the world revealed by quantum theory. Sometimes it is used to
indicate the fact that magnitudes occur in conjugate pairs subject to the
uncertainty relations. Sometimes it is used more broadly to describe such
aspects as the ability to encompass some phenomena in a wave picture of the
world and other phenomena in a particle picture, but implying that no one
picture will do justice to all the experimental results. The orthodox
formalization of quantum theory posits two distinct ways in which the quantum
state can evolve. When the system is “unobserved,” the state evolves according
to the deterministic Schrödinger equation. When “measured,” however, the system
suffers a discontinuous “collapse of the wave packet” into a new quantum state
determined by the outcome of the measurement process. Understanding how to
reconcile the measurement process with the laws of dynic evolution of the
system is the measurement problem. Conservation and symmetry. A number of
important physical principles stipulate that some physical quantity is
conserved, i.e. that the quantity of it remains invariant over time. Early
conservation principles were those of matter (mass), of energy, and of momentum.
These bece assimilated together in the relativistic principle of the
conservation of momentum-energy. Other conservation laws (such as the
conservation of baryon number) arose in the theory of elementary particles. A
symmetry in physical theory expressed the invariance of some structural feature
of the world under some transformation. Exples are translation and rotation
invariance in space and the invariance under transformation from one uniformly
moving reference fre to another. Such symmetries express the fact that systems
related by symmetry transformations behave alike in their physical evolution.
Some symmetries are connected with space-time, such as those noted above,
whereas others (such as the symmetry of electromagnetism under socalled gauge
transformations) are not. A very important result of the mathematician Emma
Noether shows that each conservation law is derivable from the existence of an
associated underlying symmetry. Chaos theory and chaotic systems. In the
history of the scientific study of deterministic systems, the paradigm of
explanation has been the prediction of the future states of a system from a
specification of its initial state. In order for such a prediction to be
useful, however, nearby initial states must lead to future states that are
close to one another. This is now known to hold only in exceptional cases. In
general deterministic systems are chaotic systems, i.e., even initial states
very close to one another will lead in short intervals of time to future states
that diverge quickly from one another. Chaos theory has been developed to
provide a wide range of concepts useful for describing the structure of the
dynics of such chaotic systems. The theory studies the features of a system
that will determine if its evolution is chaotic or non-chaotic and provides the
necessary descriptive categories for characterizing types of chaotic motion.
Randomness. The intuitive distinction between a sequence that is random and one
that is orderly plays a role in the foundations of probability theory and in
the scientific study of philosophy of science philosophy of science 703 703 dynical systems. But what is a random
sequence? Subjectivist definitions of randomness focus on the inability of an
agent to determine, on the basis of his knowledge, the future occurrences in
the sequence. Objectivist definitions of randomness seek to characterize it
without reference to the knowledge of any agent. Some approaches to defining
objective randomness are those that require probability to be the se in the
original sequence and in subsequences “mechanically” selectable from it, and
those that define a sequence as random if it passes every “effectively
constructible” statistical test for randomness. Another important attempt to
characterize objective randomness compares the length of a sequence to the
length of a computer progr used to generate the sequence. The basic idea is
that a sequence is random if the computer progrs needed to generate the
sequence are as long as the sequence itself.
philosophy of the social
sciences, the study of the logic and methods of the social sciences. Central
questions include: What are the criteria of a good social explanation? How (if
at all) are the social sciences distinct from the natural sciences? Is there a distinctive
method for social research? Through what empirical procedures are social
science assertions to be evaluated? Are there irreducible social laws? Are
there causal relations ong social phenomena? Do social facts and regularities
require some form of reduction to facts about individuals? What is the role of
theory in social explanation? The philosophy of social science aims to provide
an interpretation of the social sciences that answers these questions. The
philosophy of social science, like that of natural science, has both a
descriptive and a prescriptive side. On the one hand, the field is about the
social sciences – the explanations, methods, empirical arguments, theories,
hypotheses, etc., that actually occur in the social science literature. This
means that the philosopher needs extensive knowledge of several areas of social
science research in order to be able to formulate an analysis of the social
sciences that corresponds appropriately to scientists’ practice. On the other
hand, the field is epistemic: it is concerned with the idea that scientific
theories and hypotheses are put forward as true or probable, and are justified
on rational grounds (empirical and theoretical). The philosopher aims to
provide a critical evaluation of existing social science methods and practices
insofar as these methods are found to be less truth-enhancing than they might
be. These two aspects of the philosophical enterprise suggest that philosophy
of social science should be construed as a rational reconstruction of existing
social science practice – a reconstruction guided by existing practice but
extending beyond that practice by identifying faulty assumptions, forms of
reasoning, and explanatory freworks. Philosophers have disagreed over the
relation between the social and natural sciences. One position is naturalism,
according to which the methods of the social sciences should correspond closely
to those of the natural sciences. This position is closely related to
physicalism, the doctrine that all higher-level phenomena and regularities –
including social phenomena – are ultimately reducible to physical entities and
the laws that govern them. On the other side is the view that the social
sciences are inherently distinct from the natural sciences. This perspective
holds that social phenomena are metaphysically distinguishable from natural
phenomena because they are intentional – they depend on the meaningful actions
of individuals. On this view, natural phenomena admit of causal explanation,
whereas social phenomena require intentional explanation. The anti-naturalist
position also maintains that there is a corresponding difference between the
methods appropriate to natural and social science. Advocates of the Verstehen
method hold that there is a method of intuitive interpretation of human action
that is radically distinct from methods of inquiry in the natural sciences. One
important school within the philosophy of social science takes its origin in
this fact of the meaningfulness of human action. Interpretive sociology
maintains that the goal of social inquiry is to provide interpretations of
human conduct within the context of culturally specific meaningful
arrangements. This approach draws an analogy between literary texts and social
phenomena: both are complex systems of meaningful elements, and the goal of the
interpreter is to provide an interpretation of the elements that makes sense of
them. In this respect social science involves a hermeneutic inquiry: it
requires that the interpreter should tease out the meanings underlying a
particular complex of social behavior, much as a literary critic pieces
together an interpretation of the meaning of a complex philosophy of the social
sciences philosophy of the social sciences 704 704 literary text. An exple of this
approach is Weber’s treatment of the relation between capitalism and the
Protestant ethic. Weber attempts to identify the elements of western European
culture that shaped human action in this environment in such a way as to
produce capitalism. On this account, both Calvinism and capitalism are
historically specific complexes of values and meanings, and we can better
understand the emergence of capitalism by seeing how it corresponds to the
meaningful structures of Calvinism. Interpretive sociologists often take the
meaningfulness of social phenomena to imply that social phenomena do not admit
of causal explanation. However, it is possible to accept the idea that social
phenomena derive from the purposive actions of individuals without
relinquishing the goal of providing causal explanations of social phenomena.
For it is necessary to distinguish between the general idea of a causal
relation between two events or conditions and the more specific idea of “causal
determination through strict laws of nature.” It is true that social phenomena
rarely derive from strict laws of nature; wars do not result from antecedent
political tensions in the way that earthquakes result from antecedent
conditions in plate tectonics. However, since non-deterministic causal relations
can derive from the choices of individual persons, it is evident that social
phenomena admit of causal explanation, and in fact much social explanation
depends on asserting causal relations between social events and processes –
e.g., the claim that the administrative competence of the state is a crucial
causal factor in determining the success or failure of a revolutionary
movement. A central goal of causal explanation is to discover the conditions
existing prior to the event that, given the law-governed regularities ong
phenomena of this sort, were sufficient to produce this event. To say that C is
a cause of E is to assert that the occurrence of C, in the context of a field
of social processes and mechanisms F, brought about E (or increased the likelihood
of the occurrence of E). Central to causal arguments in the social sciences is
the idea of a causal mechanism – a series of events or actions leading from
cause to effect. Suppose it is held that the extension of a trolley line from
the central city to the periphery caused the deterioration of public schools in
the central city. In order to make out such a claim it is necessary to provide
some account of the social and political mechanisms that join the antecedent
condition to the consequent. An important variety of causal explanation in
social science is materialist explanation. This type of explanation attempts to
explain a social feature in terms of features of the material environment in
the context of which the social phenomenon occurs. Features of the environment
that often appear in materialist explanations include topography and climate;
thus it is sometimes maintained that banditry thrives in remote regions because
the rugged terrain makes it more difficult for the state to repress bandits.
But materialist explanations may also refer to the material needs of society –
e.g., the need to produce food and other consumption goods to support the
population. Thus Marx holds that it is the development of the “productive
forces” (technology) that drives the development of property relations and
political systems. In each case the materialist explanation must refer to the
fact of human agency – the fact that human beings are capable of making
deliberative choices on the basis of their wants and beliefs – in order to
carry out the explanation; in the banditry exple, the explanation depends on
the fact that bandits are prudent enough to realize that their prospects for
survival are better in the periphery than in the core. So materialist
explanations too accept the point that social phenomena depend on the purposive
actions of individuals. A central issue in the philosophy of social science
involves the relation between social regularities and facts about individuals.
Methodological individualism is the position that asserts the primacy of facts
about individuals over facts about social entities. This doctrine takes three
forms: a claim about social entities, a claim about social concepts, and a
claim about social regularities. The first version maintains that social
entities are reducible to ensembles of individuals – as an insurance company
might be reduced to the ensemble of employees, supervisors, managers, and
owners whose actions constitute the company. Likewise, it is sometimes held
that social concepts must be reducible to concepts involving only individuals –
e.g., the concept of a social class might be defined in terms of concepts
pertaining only to individuals and their behavior. Finally, it is sometimes
held that social regularities must be derivable from regularities of individual
behavior. There are several positions opposed to methodological individualism.
At the extreme there is methodological holism – the doctrine that social
entities, facts, and laws are autonomous and irreducible; for exple, that
social structures such as the state have dynic properties independent of the
beliefs and purphilosophy of the social sciences philosophy of the social
sciences poses of the particular persons who occupy positions within the
structure. A third position intermediate between these two holds that every
social explanation requires microfoundations – an account of the circumstances
at the individual level that led individuals to behave in such ways as to bring
about the observed social regularities. If we observe that an industrial strike
is successful over an extended period of time, it is not sufficient to explain
this circumstance by referring to the common interest that members of the union
have in winning their demands. Rather, we need information about the circumstances
of the individual union member that induce him or her to contribute to this
public good. The microfoundations dictum does not require, however, that social
explanations be couched in non-social concepts; instead, the circumstances of
individual agents may be characterized in social terms. Central to most
theories of explanation is the idea that explanation depends on general laws
governing the phenomena in question. Thus the discovery of the laws of
electrodynics permitted the explanation of a variety of electromagnetic
phenomena. But social phenomena derive from the actions of purposive men and
women; so what kinds of regularities are available on the basis of which to
provide social explanations? A fruitful research frework in the social sciences
is the idea that men and women are rational, so it is possible to explain their
behavior as the outcome of a deliberation about means of achieving their
individual ends. This fact in turn gives rise to a set of regularities about
individual behavior that may be used as a ground for social explanation. We may
explain some complex social phenomenon as the aggregate result of the actions
of a large number of individual agents with a hypothesized set of goals within
a structured environment of choice. Social scientists have often been inclined
to offer functional explanations of social phenomena. A functional explanation
of a social feature is one that explains the presence and persistence of the
feature in terms of the beneficial consequences the feature has for the ongoing
working of the social system as a whole. It might be held, e.g., that sports
clubs in working-class Britain exist because they give working-class people a
way of expending energy that would otherwise go into struggles against an
exploitative system, thus undermining social stability. Sports clubs are
explained, then, in terms of their contribution to social stability. This type
of explanation is based on an analogy between biology and sociology. Biologists
explain species traits in terms of their contribution to reproductive fitness,
and sociologists sometimes explain social traits in terms of their contribution
to “social” fitness. However, the analogy is misleading, because there is a
general mechanism establishing functionality in the biological realm that is
not present in the social realm. This is the mechanism of natural selection,
through which a species arrives at a set of traits that are locally optimal.
There is no analogous process at work in the social realm, however; so it is groundless
to suppose that social traits exist because of their beneficial consequences
for the good of society as a whole (or important subsystems within society). So
functional explanations of social phenomena must be buttressed by specific
accounts of the causal processes that underlie the postulated functional
relationships.
physicalism, in the
widest sense of the term, materialism applied to the question of the nature of
mind. So construed, physicalism is the thesis – call it ontological physicalism
– that whatever exists or occurs is ultimately constituted out of physical
entities. But sometimes ‘physicalism’ is used to refer to the thesis that
whatever exists or occurs can be completely described in the vocabulary of
physics. Such a view goes with either reductionism or eliminativism about the
mental. Here reductionism is the view that psychological explanations,
including explanations in terms of “folk-psychological” concepts such as those
of belief and desire, are reducible to explanations formulable in a physical
vocabulary, which in turn would imply that entities referred to in
psychological explanations can be fully described in physical terms; and
elminativism is the view that nothing corresponds to the terms in psychological
explanations, and that the only correct explanations are in physical terms. The
term ‘physicalism’ appears to have originated in the Vienna Circle, and the
reductionist Philo the Megarian physicalism 706 706 physical realization pi 707 version
initially favored there was a version of behaviorism: psychological statements
were held to be translatable into behavioral statements, mainly hypothetical
conditionals, expressible in a physical vocabulary. The psychophysical identity
theory held by Herbert Feigl, Smart, and others, sometimes called type
physicalism, is reductionist in a somewhat different sense. This holds that
mental states and events are identical with neurophysiological states and
events. While it denies that there can be analytic, meaning-preserving
translations of mental statements into physicalistic ones, it holds that by
means of synthetic “bridge laws,” identifying mental types with physical ones,
mental statements can in principle be translated into physicalistic ones with
which they are at least nomologically equivalent (if the terms in the bridge
laws are rigid designators, the equivalence will be necessary). The possibility
of such a translation is typically denied by functionalist accounts of mind, on
the grounds that the se mental state may have indefinitely many different
physical realizations, and sometimes on the grounds that it is logically
possible, even if it never happens, that mental states should be realized
non-physically. In his classic paper “The ‘mental’ and the ‘physical’ “ (1958),
Feigl distinguishes two senses of ‘physical’: ‘physical1’ and ‘physical2’.
‘Physical1’ is practically synonymous with ‘scientific’, applying to whatever
is “an essential part of the coherent and adequate descriptive and explanatory
account of the spatiotemporal world.” ‘Physical2’ refers to “the type of
concepts and laws which suffice in principle for the explanation and prediction
of inorganic processes.” (It would seem that if Cartesian dualism were true,
supposing that possible, then once an integrated science of the interaction of
immaterial souls and material bodies had been developed, concepts for
describing the former would count as physical1.) Construed as an ontological
doctrine, physicalism says that whatever exists or occurs is entirely
constituted out of those entities that constitute inorganic things and
processes. Construed as a reductionist or elminativist thesis about description
and explanation, it is the claim that a vocabulary adequate for describing and
explaining inorganic things and processes is adequate for describing and
explaining whatever exists. While the second of these theses seems to imply the
first, the first does not imply the second. It can be questioned whether the
notion of a “full” description of what exists makes sense. And many ontological
physicalists (materialists) hold that a reduction to explanations couched in
the terminology of physics is impossible, not only in the case of psychological
explanations but also in the case of explanations couched in the terminology of
such special sciences as biology. Their objection to such reduction is not
merely that a purely physical description of (e.g.) biological or psychological
phenomena would be unwieldy; it is that such descriptions necessarily miss
important laws and generalizations, ones that can only be formulated in terms
of biological, psychological, etc., concepts. If ontological physicalists
(materialists) are not committed to the reducibility of psychology to physics,
neither are they committed to any sort of identity theory claiming that
entities picked out by mental or psychological descriptions are identical to
entities fully characterizable by physical descriptions. As already noted,
materialists who are functionalists deny that there are typetype identities
between mental entities and physical ones. And some deny that materialists are
even committed to token-token identities, claiming that any psychological event
could have had a different physical composition and so is not identical to any
event individuated in terms of a purely physical taxonomy.
physis, Greek term for
nature, primarily used to refer to the nature or essence of a living thing
(Aristotle, Metaphysics V.4). Physis is defined by Aristotle in Physics II.1 as
a source of movement and rest that belongs to something in virtue of itself,
and identified by him primarily with the form, rather than the matter, of the
thing. The term is also used to refer to the natural world as a whole. Physis
is often contrasted with techne, art; in ethics it is also contrasted with nomos,
convention, e.g. by Callicles in Plato’s Gorgias (482e ff.), who distinguishes
natural from conventional justice.
ARISTOTLE, PLATO, TECHNE. W.J.P. pi, Chinese term meaning ‘screen’,
‘shelter’, or ‘cover’. Pi is Hsün Tzu’s metaphor for an obscuration or
blindness of mind. In this condition the mind is obstructed in its proper
functioning, e.g., thinking, remembering, imagining, and judging. In short, a
pi is anything that obstructs the mind’s
707 Piaget, Jean Plantinga, Alvin 708 cognitive task. When the mind is
in the state of pi, reason is, so to speak, not operating properly. The
opposite of pi is clarity of mind, a precondition for the pursuit of knowledge.
A.S.C. Piaget, Jean (1896–1980), Swiss psychologist and epistemologist who
profoundly influenced questions, theories, and methods in the study of
cognitive development. The philosophical interpretation and implications of his
work, however, remain controversial. Piaget regarded himself as engaged in
genetic epistemology, the study of what knowledge is through an empirical
investigation of how our epistemic relations to objects are improved. Piaget
hypothesized that our epistemic relations are constructed through the
progressive organization of increasingly complex behavioral interactions with physical
objects. The cognitive system of the adult is neither learned, in the
Skinnerian sense, nor genetically preprogrmed. Rather, it results from the
organization of specific interactions whose character is shaped both by the
features of the objects interacted with (a process called accommodation) and by
the current cognitive system of the child (a process called assimilation). The
tendency toward equilibrium results in a change in the nature of the
interaction as well as in the cognitive system. Of particular importance for
the field of cognitive development were Piaget’s detailed descriptions and
categorizations of changes in the organization of the cognitive system from
birth through adolescence. That work focused on changes in the child’s
understanding of such things as space, time, cause, number, length, weight, and
morality. ong his major works are The Child’s Conception of Number (1941),
Biology and Knowledge (1967), Genetic Epistemology (1970), and Psychology and
Epistemology (1970).
Pico della Mirandola,
Giovanni (1463–94), Italian philosopher who, in 1486, wrote a series of 900
theses which he hoped to dispute publicly in Rome. Thirteen of these were
criticized by a papal commission. When Pico defended himself in his Apology,
the pope condemned all 900 theses. Pico fled to France, but was briefly
imprisoned there in 1488. On his release, he returned to Florence and devoted
himself to private study. He hoped to write a Concord of Plato and Aristotle,
but the only part he was able to complete was On Being and the One (1492), in
which he uses Aquinas and Christianity to reconcile Plato’s and Aristotle’s
views about God’s being and unity. He is often described as a syncretist, but
in fact he made it clear that the truth of Christianity has priority over the
prisca theologia or ancient wisdom found in the hermetic corpus and the cabala.
Though he was interested in magic and astrology, he adopts a guarded attitude
toward them in his Heptaplus (1489), which contains a mystical interpretation
of Genesis; and in his Disputations Against Astrology, published posthumously,
he rejects them both. The treatise is largely technical, and the question of
human freedom is set aside as not directly relevant. This fact casts some doubt
on the popular thesis that Pico’s philosophy was a celebration of man’s freedom
and dignity. Great weight has been placed on Pico’s most fous work, On the
Dignity of Man (1486). This is a short oration intended as an introduction to
the disputation of his 900 theses, and the title was invented after his death.
Pico has been interpreted as saying that man is set apart from the rest of
creation, and is completely free to form his own nature. In fact, as the
Heptaplus shows, Pico saw man as a microcosm containing elements of the
angelic, celestial, and elemental worlds. Man is thus firmly within the
hierarchy of nature, and is a bond and link between the worlds. In the oration,
the emphasis on freedom is a moral one: man is free to choose between good and
evil.
pien, Chinese Mohist
technical term for disputation, defined as ‘contending over converse claims’.
It involves discrimination between what does and does not “fit the facts.” In
Hsün Tzu, pien as discrimination pertains especially to the ability to
distinguish mental states (such as anger, grief, love, hate, and desires) as
well as proper objects of different senses. Pien is significantly used in the
context of justification as a phase in ethical argumentation. ong other things,
pien as justification pertains to projection of the significance of comparable
past ethical experiences to present “hard cases” of human life
Plantinga, Alvin
(b.1932), one of the most important twentieth-century erican philosophers 708 of religion. His ideas have determined
the direction of debate in many aspects of the discipline. He has also
contributed substantially to analytic epistemology and the metaphysics of
modality. Plantinga is currently director of the Center for Philosophy of
Religion and John O’Brien Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre
De. Plantinga’s philosophy of religion has centered on the epistemology of
religious belief. His God and Other Minds (1967) introduced a defining claim of
his career – that belief in God may be rational even if it is not supported by
successful arguments from natural theology. This claim was fully developed in a
series of articles published in the 1980s, in which he argued for the position
he calls “Reformed Epistemology.” Borrowing from the work of theologians such
as Calvin, Bavinck, and Barth, Plantinga reasoned that theistic belief is
“properly basic,” justified not by other beliefs but by immediate experience.
This position was most thoroughly treated in his article “Reason and Belief in
God” (Plantinga and Wolterstorff, eds., Faith and Rationality, 1983). In early
work Plantinga assumed an internalist view of epistemic justification. Later he
moved to externalism, arguing that basic theistic belief would count as
knowledge if true and appropriately produced. He developed this approach in
“Justification and Theism” (Faith and Philosophy, 1987). These ideas led to the
development of a full-scale externalist epistemological theory, first presented
in his 1989 Gifford Lectures and later published in the two-volume set Warrant:
The Current Debate and Warrant and Proper Function (1993). This theory has
become the focal point of much contemporary debate in analytic epistemology.
Plantinga is also a leading theorist in the metaphysics of modality. The Nature
of Necessity (1974) developed a possible worlds semantics that has become
standard in the literature. His analysis of possible worlds as maximally
consistent states of affairs offers a realist compromise between nominalist and
extreme reificationist conceptions. In the last two chapters, Plantinga brings
his modal metaphysics to bear on two classical topics in the philosophy of
religion. He presented what many consider the definitive version of the free
will defense against the argument from evil and a modal version of the
ontological argument that may have produced more response than any version
since Anselm’s original offering.
No comments:
Post a Comment