Filmer, Robert 15881653,
English political writer who produced, most importantly, the posthumous
Patriarcha 1680. It is remembered because Locke attacked it in the first of his
Two Treatises of Government 1690. Filmer argued that God gave complete
authority over the world to Adam, and that from him it descended to his eldest
son when he became the head of the family. Thereafter only fathers directly
descended from Adam could properly be rulers. Just as Adam’s rule was not
derived from the consent of his family, so the king’s inherited authority is
not dependent on popular consent. He rightly makes laws and imposes taxes at
his own good pleasure, though like a good father he has the welfare of his
subjects in view. Filmer’s patriarchalism, intended to bolster the absolute
power of the king, is the classic English statement of the doctrine.
find
play
– where Grice’s implicature finds play Strawson Wiggins p. 523
Fludd, Robert 15741637,
English physician and writer. Influenced by Paracelsus, hermetism, and the
cabala, Fludd defended a Neoplatonic worldview on the eve of its supersession
by the new mechanistic philosophy. He produced improvements in the manufacture
of steel and invented a thermometer, though he also used magnets to cure
disease and devised a salve to be applied to a weapon to cure the wound it had
inflicted. He held that science got its ideas from Scripture allegorically
interpreted, when they were of any value. His works combine theology with an
occult, Neoplatonic reading of the Bible, and contain numerous fine diagrams
illustrating the mutual sympathy of human beings, the natural world, and the
supernatural world, each reflecting the others in parallel harmonic structures.
In controversy with Kepler, Fludd claimed to uncover essential natural
processes rooted in natural sympathies and the operation of God’s light, rather
than merely describing the external movements of the heavens. Creation is the
extension of divine light into matter. Evil arises from a darkness in God, his
failure to will. Matter is uncreated, but this poses no problem for orthodoxy,
since matter is nothing, a mere possibility without the least actuality, not
something Filmer, Robert Fludd, Robert 311
311 coeternal with the Creator.
Fodor, Jerry A. --
influential contemporary philosopher of
psychology, known for his energetic and often witty defense of intensional
realism, a computationalrepresentational model of thought, and an atomistic,
externalist theory of content determination for mental states. Fodor’s
philosophical writings fall under three headings. First, he has defended the
theory of mind implicit in contemporary cognitive psychology, that the
cognitive mind-brain is both a representational/computational device and,
ultimately, physical. He has taken on behaviorists Ryle, psychologists in the
tradition of J. J. Gibson, and eliminative materialists P. A. Churchland.
Second, he has engaged in various theoretical disputes within cognitive
psychology, arguing for the modularity of the perceptual and language systems
roughly, the view that they are domain-specific, mandatory, limited-access,
innately specified, hardwired, and informationally encapsulated The Modularity
of Mind, 3; for a strong form of nativism that virtually all of our concepts
are innate; and for the existence of a “language of thought” The Language of
Thought, 5. The latter has led him to argue against connectionism as a
psychological theory as opposed to an implementation theory. Finally, he has
defended the views of ordinary propositional attitude psychology that our
mental states 1 are semantically evaluable intentional, 2 have causal powers,
and 3 are such that the implicit generalizations of folk psychology are largely
true of them. His defense is twofold. Folk psychology is unsurpassed in
explanatory power; furthermore, it is vindicated by contemporary cognitive
psychology insofar as ordinary propositional attitude states can be identified
with information-processing states, those that consist in a computational
relation to a representation. The representational component of such states
allows us to explain the semantic evaluability of the attitudes; the
computational component, their causal efficacy. Both sorts of accounts raise
difficulties. The first is satisfactory only if supplemented by a naturalistic
account of representational content. Here Fodor has argued for an atomistic,
externalist causal theory Psychosemantics, 7 and against holism the view that no
mental representation has content unless many other non-synonymous mental
representations also have content Holism: A Shopper’s Guide, 2, against
conceptual role theories the view that the content of a representation is
determined by its conceptual role Ned Block, Brian Loar, and against
teleofunctional theories teleofunctionalism is the view that the content of a
representation is determined, at least in part, by the biological functions of
the representations themselves or systems that produce or use those
representations Ruth Millikan, David Papineau. The second sort is satisfactory
only if it does not imply epiphenomenalism with respect to content properties.
To avoid such epiphenomenalism, Fodor has argued that not only strict laws but
also ceteris paribus laws can be causal. In addition, he has sought to
reconcile his externalism vis-à-vis content with the view that causal efficacy
requires an individualistic individuation of states. Two solutions have been
explored: the supplementation of broad externally determined content with
narrow content, where the latter supervenes on what is “in the head”
Psychosemantics, 7, and its supplementation with modes of presentation
identical to sentences of the language of thought The Elm and the Expert, 5.
folk psychology, in one
sense, a putative network of principles constituting a commonsense theory that
allegedly underlies everyday explanations of human behavior; the theory assigns
a central role to mental states like belief, desire, and intention. Consider an
example of an everyday commonsense psychological explanation: Jane went to the
refrigerator because she wanted a beer and she believed there was beer in the
refrigerator. Like many such explanations, this adverts to a so-called
propositional attitude a mental state,
expressed by a verb ‘believe’ plus a that-clause, whose intentional content is
propositional. It also adverts to a mental state, expressed by a verb ‘want’
plus a direct-object phrase, whose intentional content appears not to be
propositional. In another, related sense, folk psychology is a network of
social practices that includes ascribing such mental states to ourselves and
others, and proffering explanations of human behavior that advert to these
states. The two senses need fluxion folk psychology 312 312 distinguishing because some philosophers
who acknowledge the existence of folk psychology in the second sense hold that
commonsense psychological explanations do not employ empirical generalizations,
and hence that there is no such theory as folk psychology. Henceforth, ‘FP’
will abbreviate ‘folk psychology’ in the first sense; the unabbreviated phrase
will be used in the second sense. Eliminativism in philosophy of mind asserts
that FP is an empirical theory; that FP is therefore subject to potential
scientific falsification; and that mature science very probably will establish
that FP is so radically false that humans simply do not undergo mental states
like beliefs, desires, and intentions. One kind of eliminativist argument first
sets forth certain methodological strictures about how FP would have to
integrate with mature science in order to be true e.g., being smoothly
reducible to neuroscience, or being absorbed into mature cognitive science, and
then contends that these strictures are unlikely to be met. Another kind of
argument first claims that FP embodies certain strong empirical commitments
e.g., to mental representations with languagelike syntactic structure, and then
contends that such empirical presuppositions are likely to turn out false. One
influential version of folk psychological realism largely agrees with
eliminativism about what is required to vindicate folk psychology, but also
holds that mature science is likely to provide such vindication. Realists of
this persuasion typically argue, for instance, that mature cognitive science
will very likely incorporate FP, and also will very likely treat beliefs,
desires, and other propositional attitudes as states with languagelike
syntactic structure. Other versions of folkpsychological realism take issue, in
one way or another, with either i the eliminativists’ claims about FP’s
empirical commitments, or ii the eliminativists’ strictures about how FP must
mesh with mature science in order to be true, or both. Concerning i, for instance,
some philosophers maintain that FP per se is not committed to the existence of
languagelike mental representations. If mature cognitive science turns out not
to posit a “language of thought,” they contend, this would not necessarily show
that FP is radically false; instead it might only show that propositional
attitudes are subserved in some other way than via languagelike
representational structures. Concerning ii, some philosophers hold that FP can
be true without being as tightly connected to mature scientific theories as the
eliminativists require. For instance, the demand that the special sciences be
smoothly reducible to the fundamental natural sciences is widely considered an
excessively stringent criterion of intertheoretic compatibility; so perhaps FP
could be true without being smoothly reducible to neuroscience. Similarly, the
demand that FP be directly absorbable into empirical cognitive science is
sometimes considered too stringent as a criterion either of FP’s truth, or of
the soundness of its ontology of beliefs, desires, and other propositional
attitudes, or of the legitimacy of FP-based explanations of behavior. Perhaps
FP is a true theory, and explanatorily legitimate, even if it is not destined
to become a part of science. Even if FP’s ontological categories are not
scientific natural kinds, perhaps its generalizations are like generalizations
about clothing: true, explanatorily usable, and ontologically sound. No one
doubts the existence of hats, coats, or scarves. No one doubts the truth or
explanatory utility of generalizations like ‘Coats made of heavy material tend
to keep the body warm in cold weather’, even though these generalizations are
not laws of any science. Yet another approach to folk psychology, often wedded
to realism about beliefs and desires although sometimes wedded to
instrumentalism, maintains that folk psychology does not employ empirical
generalizations, and hence is not a theory at all. One variant denies that folk
psychology employs any generalizations, empirical or otherwise. Another variant
concedes that there are folk-psychological generalizations, but denies that
they are empirical; instead they are held to be analytic truths, or norms of
rationality, or both at once. Advocates of non-theory views typically regard
folk psychology as a hermeneutic, or interpretive, enterprise. They often claim
too that the attribution of propositional attitudes, and also the proffering
and grasping of folk-psychological explanations, is a matter of imaginatively
projecting oneself into another person’s situation, and then experiencing a
kind of empathic understanding, or Verstehen, of the person’s actions and the
motives behind them. A more recent, hi-tech, formulation of this idea is that
the interpreter “runs a cognitive simulation” of the person whose actions are
to be explained. Philosophers who defend folk-psychological realism, in one or
another of the ways just canvassed, also sometimes employ arguments based on
the allegedly self-stultifying nature of eliminativism. One such argument
begins from the premise that the notion of action is folk-psychological that a behavioral event counts as an action
only if it is caused by propositional attitudes that rationalize it under some
suitable actdescription. If so, and if humans never really undergo
propositional attitudes, then they never really act either. In particular, they
never really assert anything, or argue for anything since asserting and arguing
are species of action. So if eliminativism is true, the argument concludes, then
eliminativists can neither assert it nor argue for it an allegedly intolerable pragmatic paradox.
Eliminativists generally react to such arguments with breathtaking equanimity.
A typical reply is that although our present concept of action might well be
folk-psychological, this does not preclude the possibility of a future
successor concept, purged of any commitment to beliefs and desires, that could
inherit much of the role of our current, folk-psychologically tainted, concept
of action.
Fonseca, Pedro da, philosopher and logician. He entered the
Jesuit order in 1548. Apart from a period in Rome, he lived in Portugal,
teaching philosophy and theology at the universities of Evora and Coimbra and
performing various administrative duties for his order. He was responsible for
the idea of a published course on Aristotelian philosophy, and the resulting
series of Coimbra commentaries, the Cursus Conimbricensis, was widely used in
the seventeenth century. His own logic text, the Institutes of Dialectic 1564,
went into many editions. It is a good example of Renaissance Aristotelianism,
with its emphasis on Aristotle’s syllogistic, but it retains some material on
medieval developments, notably consequences, exponibles, and supposition
theory. Fonseca also wrote a commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics published in
parts from 1577 on, which contains the Grecian text, a corrected Latin
translation, comments on textual matters, and an extensive exploration of
selected philosophical problems. He cites a wide range of medieval
philosophers, both Christian and Arab, as well as the newly published Grecian
commentators on Aristotle. His own position is sympathetic to Aquinas, but
generally independent. Fonseca is important not so much for any particular
doctrines, though he did hold original views on such matters as analogy, but
for his provision of fully documented, carefully written and carefully argued
books that, along with others in the same tradition, were read at universities,
both Catholic and Protestant, well into the seventeenth century. He represents
what is often called the Second Scholasticism.
Fontenelle, Bernard Le
Bovier de 16571757, writer who heralded
the age of the philosophes. A product of Jesuit education, he was a versatile
freethinker with skeptical inclinations. Dialogues of the Dead 1683 showed off
his analytical mind and elegant style. In 1699, he was appointed secretary of
the Academy of Sciences. He composed famous eulogies of scientists; defended
the superiority of modern science over tradition in Digression on Ancients and
Moderns 1688; popularized Copernican astronomy in Conversations on the
Plurality of Worlds 1686 famous for
postulating the inhabitation of planets; stigmatized superstition and credulity
in History of Oracles 1687 and The Origin of Fables 1724; promoted Cartesian
physics in The Theory of Cartesian Vortices 1752; and wrote Elements of
Infinitesimal Calculus 1727 in the wake of Newton and Leibniz. J.-L.S. Foot,
Philippa b.0, British philosopher who exerted a lasting influence on the
development of moral philosophy in the second half of the twentieth century.
Her persisting, intertwined themes are opposition to all forms of subjectivism
in ethics, the significance of the virtues and vices, and the connection
between morality and rationality. In her earlier papers, particularly “Moral
Beliefs” 8 and “Goodness and Choice” 1, reprinted in Virtues and Vices 8, she
undermines the subjectivist accounts of moral “judgment” derived from C. L.
Stevenson and Hare by arguing for many logical or conceptual connections
between evaluations and the factual statements on which they must be based.
Lately she has developed this kind of thought into the naturalistic claim that
moral evaluations are determined by facts about our life and our nature, as
evaluations of features of plants and animals as good or defective specimens of
their kind are determined by facts about their nature and their life. Foot’s
opposition to subjectivism has remained constant, but her views on the virtues
in relation to rationality have undergone several changes. In “Moral Beliefs”
she relates them to self-interest, maintaining that a virtue must benefit its
possessor; in the subsequently repudiated “Morality as a System of Hypothetical
Imperatives” 2 she went as far as to deny that there was necessarily anything
contrary to reason in being uncharitable or unjust. In “Does Moral Subjectivism
Rest on a Mistake?” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 5 the virtues themselves
appear as forms of practical rationality. Her most recent work, soon to be
published as The Grammar of Goodness, preserves and develops the latter claim
and reinstates ancient connections between virtue, rationality, and
happiness.
forcing, a method
introduced by Paul J. Cohen see his Set
Theory and the Continuum Hypothesis 6 to
prove independence results in Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory ZF. Cohen proved the
independence of the axiom of choice AC from ZF, and of the continuum hypothesis
CH from ZF ! AC. The consistency of AC with ZF and of CH with ZF ! AC had previously
been proved by Gödel by the method of constructible sets. A model of ZF
consists of layers, with the elements of a set at one layer always belonging to
lower layers. Starting with a model M, Cohen’s method produces an “outer model”
N with no more levels but with more sets at each level whereas Gödel’s method
produces an ‘inner model’ L: much of what will become true in N can be “forced”
from within M. The method is applicable only to hypotheses in the more
“abstract” branches of mathematics infinitary combinatorics, general topology,
measure theory, universal algebra, model theory, etc.; but there it is
ubiquitous. Applications include the proof by Robert M. Solovay of the
consistency of the measurability of all sets of all projective sets with ZF with
ZF ! AC; also the proof by Solovay and Donald A. Martin of the consistency of
Martin’s axiom MA plus the negation of the continuum hypothesis -CH with ZF !
AC. CH implies MA; and of known consequences of CH about half are implied by
MA, about half refutable by MA ! -CH. Numerous simplifications, extensions, and
variants e.g. Boolean-valued models of Cohen’s method have been
introduced.
Fordyce, D., Scottish
philosopher and educational theorist whose writings were influential in the
eighteenth century. His lectures formed the basis of his Elements of Moral
Philosophy, written originally for The Preceptor 1748, later tr. into G. and ,
and abridged for the articles on moral philosophy in the first Encylopaedia
Britannica 1771. Fordyce combines the preacher’s appeal to the heart in the
advocacy of virtue with a moral “scientist’s” appraisal of human psychology. He
claims to derive our duties experimentally from a study of the prerequisites of
human happiness. M.A.St. foreknowledge, divine.
form, in metaphysics,
especially Plato’s and Aristotle’s, the structure or essence of a thing as
contrasted with its matter. 1 Plato’s theory of Forms is a realistic ontology
of universals. In his elenchus, Socrates sought what is common to, e.g., all
chairs. Plato believed there must be an essence
or Form common to everything
falling under one concept, which makes anything what it is. A chair is a chair
because it “participates in” the Form of Chair. The Forms are ideal “patterns,”
unchanging, timeless, and perfect. They exist in a world of their own cf. the
Kantian noumenal realm. Plato speaks of them as self-predicating: the Form of
Beauty is perfectly beautiful. This led, as he realized, to the Third Man
argument that there must be an infinite number of Forms. The only true
understanding is of the Forms. This we attain through anamnesis,
“recollection.” 2 Aristotle agreed that forms are closely tied to
intelligibility, but denied their separate existence. Aristotle explains change
and generation through a distinction between the form and matter of substances.
A lump of bronze matter becomes a statue through its being molded into a
certain shape form. In his earlier metaphysics, Aristotle identified primary
substance with the composite of matter and form, e.g. Socrates. Later, he
suggests that primary substance is form
what makes Socrates what he is the form here is his soul. This notion of
forms as essences has obvious similarities with the Platonic view. They became
the “substantial forms” of Scholasticism, accepted until the seventeenth
century. 3 Kant saw form as the a priori aspect of experience. We are presented
with phenomenological “matter,” which has no meaning until the mind imposes
some form upon it.
formal fallacy, an
invalid inference pattern that is described in terms of a formal logic. There
are three main cases: 1 an invalid or otherwise unacceptable argument
identified solely by its form or structure, with no reference to the content of
the premises and conclusion such as equivocation or to other features,
generally of a pragmatic character, of the argumentative discourse such as
unsuitability of the argument for the purposes for which it is given, failure
to satisfy inductive standards for acceptable argument, etc.; the latter
conditions of argument evaluation fall into the purview of informal fallacy; 2
a formal rule of inference, or an argument form, that is not valid in the
logical system on which the evaluation is made, instances of which are
sufficiently frequent, familiar, or deceptive to merit giving a name to the
rule or form; and 3 an argument that is an instance of a fallacious rule of
inference or of a fallacious argument form and that is not itself valid. The
criterion of satisfactory argument typically taken as relevant in discussing
formal fallacies is validity. In this regard, it is important to observe that
rules of inference and argument forms that are not valid may have instances
which may be another rule or argument form, or may be a specific argument that
are valid. Thus, whereas the argument form i P, Q; therefore R a form that
every argument, including every valid argument, consisting of two premises
shares is not valid, the argument form ii, obtained from i by substituting
P&Q for R, is a valid instance of i: ii P, Q; therefore P&Q. Since ii
is not invalid, ii is not a formal fallacy though it is an instance of i. Thus,
some instances of formally fallacious rules of inference or argument-forms may
be valid and therefore not be formal fallacies. Examples of formal fallacies
follow below, presented according to the system of logic appropriate to the
level of description of the fallacy. There are no standard names for some of
the fallacies listed below. Fallacies of sentential propositional logic.
Affirming the consequent: If p then q; q / , p. ‘If Richard had his nephews
murdered, then Richard was an evil man; Richard was an evil man. Therefore,
Richard had his nephews murdered.’ Denying the antecedent: If p then q; not-p /
, not-q. ‘If North was found guilty by the courts, then North committed the
crimes charged of him; North was not found guilty by the courts. Therefore,
North did not commit the crimes charged of him.’ Commutation of conditionals:
If p then q / , If q then p. ‘If Reagan was a great leader, then so was
Thatcher. Therefore, if Thatcher was a great leader, then so was Reagan.”
Improper transposition: If p then q / , If not-p then not-q. ‘If the nations of
the Middle East disarm, there will be peace in the region. Therefore, if the
nations of the Middle East do not disarm, there will not be peace in the
region.’ Improper disjunctive syllogism affirming one disjunct: p or q; p / ,,
not-q. ‘Either John is an alderman or a ward committeeman; John is an alderman.
Therefore, John is not a ward committeeman.’ This rule of inference would be
valid if ‘or’ were interpreted exclusively, where ‘p or EXq’ is true if exactly
one constituent is true and is false otherwise. In standard systems of logic,
however, ‘or’ is interpreted inclusively. Fallacies of syllogistic logic.
Fallacies of distribution where M is the middle term, P is the major term, and
S is the minor term. Undistributed middle term: the middle term is not
distributed in either premise roughly, nothing is said of all members of the
class it designates, as in form, grammatical formal fallacy 316 316 Some P are M ‘Some politicians are
crooks. Some M are S Some crooks are thieves. ,Some S are P. ,Some politicians
are thieves.’ Illicit major undistributed major term: the major term is distributed
in the conclusion but not in the major premise, as in All M are P ‘All radicals
are communists. No S are M No socialists are radicals. ,Some S are ,Some
socialists are not not P. communists.’ Illicit minor undistributed minor term:
the minor term is distributed in the conclusion but not in the minor premise,
as in All P are M ‘All neo-Nazis are radicals. All M are S All radicals are
terrorists. ,All S are P. ,All terrorists are neoNazis.’ Fallacies of negation.
Two negative premises exclusive premises: the syllogism has two negative premises,
as in No M are P ‘No racist is just. Some M are not S Some racists are not
police. ,Some S are not P. ,Some police are not just. Illicit
negative/affirmative: the syllogism has a negative premise conclusion but no
negative conclusion premise, as in All M are P ‘All liars are deceivers. Some M
are not S Some liars are not aldermen. ,Some S are P. ,Some aldermen are
deceivers.’ and All P are M ‘All vampires are monsters. All M are S All
monsters are creatures. ,Some S are not P. ,Some creatures are not vampires.’
Fallacy of existential import: the syllogism has two universal premises and a
particular conclusion, as in All P are M ‘All horses are animals. No S are M No
unicorns are animals. ,Some S are not P. ,Some unicorns are not horses.’ A
syllogism can commit more than one fallacy. For example, the syllogism Some P
are M Some M are S ,No S are P commits the fallacies of undistributed middle,
illicit minor, illicit major, and illicit negative/affirmative. Fallacies of
predicate logic. Illicit quantifier shift: inferring from a universally
quantified existential proposition to an existentially quantified universal
proposition, as in Ex Dy Fxy / , Dy Ex Fxy ‘Everyone is irrational at some time
or other /, At some time, everyone is irrational.’ Some are/some are not
unwarranted contrast: inferring from ‘Some S are P’ that ‘Some S are not P’ or
inferring from ‘Some S are not P’ that ‘Some S are P’, as in Dx Sx & Px / ,
Dx Sx & -Px ‘Some people are left-handed / , Some people are not
left-handed.’ Illicit substitution of identicals: where f is an opaque oblique
context and a and b are singular terms, to infer from fa; a = b / , fb, as in
‘The Inspector believes Hyde is Hyde; Hyde is Jekyll / , The Inspector believes
Hyde is Jekyll.’
formalism, the view that
mathematics concerns manipulations of symbols according to prescribed
structural rules. It is cousin to nominalism, the older and more general
metaphysical view that denies the existence of all abstract objects and is
often contrasted with Platonism, which takes mathematics to be the study of a
special class of non-linguistic, non-mental objects, and intuitionism, which
takes it to be the study of certain mental constructions. In sophisticated
versions, mathematical activity can comprise the study of possible formal
manipulations within a system as well as the manipulations themselves, and the
“symbols” need not be regarded as either linguistic or concrete. Formalism is
often associated with the mathematician formalism formalism 317 317 David Hilbert. But Hilbert held that the
“finitary” part of mathematics, including, for example, simple truths of
arithmetic, describes indubitable facts about real objects and that the “ideal”
objects that feature elsewhere in mathematics are introduced to facilitate
research about the real objects. Hilbert’s formalism is the view that the
foundations of mathematics can be secured by proving the consistency of formal
systems to which mathematical theories are reduced. Gödel’s two incompleteness
theorems establish important limitations on the success of such a project.
formalization, an
abstract representation of a theory that must satisfy requirements sharper than
those imposed on the structure of theories by the axiomatic-deductive method.
That method can be traced back to Euclid’s Elements. The crucial additional
requirement is the regimentation of inferential steps in proofs: not only do
axioms have to be given in advance, but the rules representing argumentative
steps must also be taken from a predetermined list. To avoid a regress in the
definition of proof and to achieve intersubjectivity on a minimal basis, the
rules are to be “formal” or “mechanical” and must take into account only the
form of statements. Thus, to exclude any ambiguity, a precise and effectively
described language is needed to formalize particular theories. The general kind
of requirements was clear to Aristotle and explicit in Leibniz; but it was only
Frege who, in his Begriffsschrift 1879, presented, in addition to an
expressively rich language with relations and quantifiers, an adequate logical
calculus. Indeed, Frege’s calculus, when restricted to the language of
predicate logic, turned out to be semantically complete. He provided for the
first time the means to formalize mathematical proofs. Frege pursued a clear
philosophical aim, namely, to recognize the “epistemological nature” of
theorems. In the introduction to his Grundgesetze der Arithmetik 3, Frege
wrote: “By insisting that the chains of inference do not have any gaps we
succeed in bringing to light every axiom, assumption, hypothesis or whatever
else you want to call it on which a proof rests; in this way we obtain a basis
for judging the epistemological nature of the theorem.” The Fregean frame was
used in the later development of mathematical logic, in particular, in proof
theory. Gödel established through his incompleteness theorems fundamental
limits of formalizations of particular theories, like the system of Principia
Mathematica or axiomatic set theories. The general notion of formal theory
emerged from the subsequent investigations of Church and Turing clarifying the
concept of ‘mechanical procedure’ or ‘algorithm.’ Only then was it possible to
state and prove the incompleteness theorems for all formal theories satisfying
certain very basic representability and derivability conditions. Gödel
emphasized repeatedly that these results do not establish “any bounds for the
powers of human reason, but rather for the potentialities of pure formalism in
mathematics.”
Formalize: narrowly
construed, to formulate a subject as a theory in first-order predicate logic;
broadly construed, to describe the essentials of the subject in some formal
language for which a notion of consequence is defined. For Hilbert, formalizing
mathematics requires at least that there be finite means of checking purported
proofs.
formal language: H. P.
Grice, “Bergmann on ideal language versus ordinary language,” a language in
which an expression’s grammaticality and interpretation if any are determined
by precisely defined rules that appeal only to the form or shape of the symbols
that constitute it rather than, for example, to the intention of the speaker.
It is usually understood that the rules are finite and effective so that there
is an algorithm for determining whether an expression is a formula and that the
grammatical expressions are uniquely readable, i.e., they are generated by the
rules in only one way. A paradigm example is the language of firstorder
predicate logic, deriving principally from the Begriffsschrift of Frege. The
grammatical formulas of this language can be delineated by an inductive
definition: 1 a capital letter ‘F’, ‘G’, or ‘H’, with or without a numerical
subscript, folformalism, aesthetic formal language 318 318 lowed by a string of lowercase letters
‘a’, ‘b’, or ‘c’, with or without numerical subscripts, is a formula; 2 if A is
a formula, so is -A; 3 if A and B are formulas, so are A & B, A P B, and A
7 B; 4 if A is a formula and v is a lowercase letter ‘x’, ‘y’, or ‘z’, with or
without numerical subscripts, then DvA' and EvA' are formulas where A' is
obtained by replacing one or more occurrences of some lowercase letter in A
together with its subscripts if any by v; 5 nothing is a formula unless it can
be shown to be one by finitely many applications of the clauses 14. The
definition uses the device of metalinguistic variables: clauses with ‘A’ and
‘B’ are to be regarded as abbreviations of all the clauses that would result by
replacing these letters uniformly by names of expressions. It also uses several
naming conventions: a string of symbols is named by enclosing it within single
quotes and also by replacing each symbol in the string by its name; the symbols
‘7’, ‘‘,’’, ‘&’, ‘P’, ‘-’ are considered names of themselves. The
interpretation of predicate logic is spelled out by a similar inductive
definition of truth in a model. With appropriate conventions and stipulations,
alternative definitions of formulas can be given that make expressions like ‘P
7 Q’ the names of formulas rather than formulas themselves. On this approach,
formulas need not be written symbols at all and form cannot be identified with
shape in any narrow sense. For Tarski, Carnap, and others a formal language
also included rules of “transformation” specifying when one expression can be
regarded as a consequence of others. Today it is more common to view the
language and its consequence relation as distinct. Formal languages are often
contrasted with natural languages, like English or Swahili. Richard Montague,
however, has tried to show that English is itself a formal language, whose
rules of grammar and interpretation are similar to though much more complex than predicate logic.
formal learnability
theory, the study of human language learning through explicit formal models typically
employing artifical languages and simplified learning strategies. The
fundamental problem is how a learner is able to arrive at a grammar of a
language on the basis of a finite sample of presented sentences and perhaps
other kinds of information as well. The seminal work is by E. Gold 7, who
showed, roughly, that learnability of certain types of grammars from the
Chomsky hierarchy by an unbiased learner required the presentation of
ungrammatical strings, identified as such, along with grammatical strings.
Recent studies have concentrated on other types of grammar e.g., generative
transformational grammars, modes of presentation, and assumptions about
learning strategies in an attempt to approximate the actual situation more
closely.
formal logic, the science
of correct reasoning, going back to Aristotle’s Prior Analytics, based upon the
premise that the validity of an argument is a function of its structure or
logical form. The modern embodiment of formal logic is symbolic mathematical
logic. This is the study of valid inference in artificial, precisely formulated
languages, the grammatical structure of whose sentences or well-formed formulas
is intended to mirror, or be a regimentation of, the logical forms of their
natural language counterparts. These formal languages can thus be viewed as
mathematical models of fragments of natural language. Like models generally,
these models are idealizations, typically leaving out of account such phenomena
as vagueness, ambiguity, and tense. But the idea underlying symbolic logic is
that to the extent that they reflect certain structural features of natural
language arguments, the study of valid inference in formal languages can yield
insight into the workings of those arguments. The standard course of study for
anyone interested in symbolic logic begins with the classical propositional
calculus sentential calculus, or PC. Here one constructs a theory of valid
inference for a formal language built up from a stock of propositional
variables sentence letters and an expressively complete set of connectives. In
the propositional calculus, one is therefore concerned with arguments whose
validity turns upon the presence of two-valued truth-functional
sentence-forming operators on sentences such as classical negation, conjunction,
disjunction, and the like. The next step is the predicate calculus lower
functional calculus, first-order logic, elementary quantification theory, the
study of valid inference in first-order languages. These are languages built up
from an expressively complete set of connectives, first-order universal or
existential quantifiers, individual variables, names, predicates relational
symbols, and perhaps function symbols. Further, and more specialized, work in
symbolic logic might involve looking at fragments of the language of the
propositional or predicate calculus, changing the semantics that the language
is standardly given e.g., by allowing truth-value gaps or more than two
truth-values, further embellishing the language e.g., by adding modal or other
non-truth-functional connectives, or higher-order quantifiers, or liberalizing
the grammar or syntax of the language e.g., by permitting infinitely long
well-formed formulas. In some of these cases, of course, symbolic logic remains
only marginally connected with natural language arguments as the interest
shades off into one in formal languages for their own sake, a mark of the most
advanced work being done in formal logic today.
formal semantics, the
study of the interpretations of formal languages. A formal language can be
defined apart from any interpretation of it. This is done by specifying a set
of its symbols and a set of formation rules that determine which strings of
symbols are grammatical or well formed. When rules of inference transformation
rules are added and/or certain sentences are designated as axioms a logical
system also known as a logistic system is formed. An interpretation of a formal
language is roughly an assignment of meanings to its symbols and truth
conditions to its sentences. Typically a distinction is made between a standard
interpretation of a formal language and a non-standard interpretation. Consider
a formal language in which arithmetic is formulable. In addition to the symbols
of logic variables, quantifiers, brackets, and connectives, this language will
contain ‘0’, ‘!’, ‘•’, and ‘s’. A standard interpretation of it assigns the set
of natural numbers as the domain of discourse, zero to ‘0’, addition to ‘!’,
multiplication to ‘•’, and the successor function to ‘s’. Other standard
interpretations are isomorphic to the one just given. In particular, standard
interpretations are numeral-complete in that they correlate the numerals
one-to-one with the domain elements. A result due to Gödel and Rosser is that
there are universal quantifications xAx that are not deducible from the Peano
axioms if those axioms are consistent even though each An is provable. The
Peano axioms if consistent are true on each standard interpretation. Thus each
An is true on such an interpretation. Thus xAx is true on such an
interpretation since a standard interpretation is numeral-complete. However,
there are non-standard interpretations that do not correlate the numerals
one-to-one with domain elements. On some of these interpretations each An is true
but xAx is false. In constructing and interpreting a formal language we use a
language already known to us, say, English. English then becomes our
metalanguage, which we use to talk about the formal language, which is our
object language. Theorems proven within the object language must be
distinguished from those proven in the metalanguage. The latter are
metatheorems. One goal of a semantical theory of a formal language is to
characterize the consequence relation as expressed in that language and prove semantical
metatheorems about that relation. A sentence S is said to be a consequence of a
set of sentences K provided S is true on every interpretation on which each
sentence in K is true. This notion has to be kept distinct from the notion of
deduction. The latter concept can be defined only by reference to a logical
system associated with a formal language. Consequence, however, can be
characterized independently of a logical system, as was just done.
Foucault: m., philosopher
and historian of thought. Foucault’s earliest writings e.g., Maladie mentale et
personnalité [“Mental Illness and Personality”], 4 focused on psychology and
developed within the frameworks of Marxism and existential phenomenology. He
soon moved beyond these frameworks, in directions suggested by two fundamental
influences: formal mode Foucault, Michel 320
320 history and philosophy of science, as practiced by Bachelard and
especially Canguilhem, and the modernist literature of, e.g., Raymond Roussel,
Bataille, and Maurice Blanchot. In studies of psychiatry Histoire de la folie
[“History of Madness in the Classical Age”], 1, clinical medicine The Birth of
the Clinic, 3, and the social sciences The Order of Things, 6, Foucault
developed an approach to intellectual history, “the archaeology of knowledge,”
that treated systems of thought as “discursive formations” independent of the
beliefs and intentions of individual thinkers. Like Canguilhem’s history of
science and like modernist literature, Foucault’s archaeology displaced the human
subject from the central role it played in the humanism dominant in our culture
since Kant. He reflected on the historical and philosophical significance of
his archaeological method in The Archaeology of Knowledge 9. Foucault
recognized that archaeology provided no account of transitions from one system
to another. Accordingly, he introduced a “genealogical” approach, which does
not replace archaeology but goes beyond it to explain changes in systems of
discourse by connecting them to changes in the non-discursive practices of
social power structures. Foucault’s genealogy admitted the standard economic,
social, and political causes but, in a non-standard, Nietzschean vein, refused
any unified teleological explanatory scheme e.g., Whig or Marxist histories.
New systems of thought are seen as contingent products of many small, unrelated
causes, not fulfillments of grand historical designs. Foucault’s geneaological
studies emphasize the essential connection of knowledge and power. Bodies of
knowledge are not autonomous intellectual structures that happen to be employed
as Baconian instruments of power. Rather, precisely as bodies of knowledge,
they are tied but not reducible to systems of social control. This essential
connection of power and knowledge reflects Foucault’s later view that power is
not merely repressive but a creative, if always dangerous, source of positive
values. Discipline and Punish 5 showed how prisons constitute criminals as
objects of disciplinary knowledge. The first volume of the History of Sexuality
6 sketched a project for seeing how, through modern biological and
psychological sciences of sexuality, individuals are controlled by their own
knowledge as self-scrutinizing and self-forming subjects. The second volume was
projected as a study of the origins of the modern notion of a subject in
practices of Christian confession. Foucault wrote such a study The Confessions
of the Flesh but did not publish it because he decided that a proper
understanding of the Christian development required a comparison with ancient
conceptions of the ethical self. This led to two volumes 4 on Grecian and Roman
sexuality: The Use of Pleasure and The Care of the Self. These final writings
make explicit the ethical project that in fact informs all of Foucault’s work:
the liberation of human beings from contingent conceptual constraints masked as
unsurpassable a priori limits and the adumbration of alternative forms of
existence.
foundationalism, the view
that knowledge and epistemic knowledge-relevant justification have a two-tier
structure: some instances of knowledge and justification are non-inferential,
or foundational; and all other instances thereof are inferential, or
non-foundational, in that they derive ultimately from foundational knowledge or
justification. This structural view originates in Aristotle’s Posterior
Analytics at least regarding knowledge, receives an extreme formulation in
Descartes’s Meditations, and flourishes, with varying details, in the works of
such twentieth-century philosophers as Russell, C. I. Lewis, and Chisholm.
Versions of foundationalism differ on two main projects: a the precise
explanation of the nature of non-inferential, or foundational, knowledge and
justification, and b the specific explanation of how foundational knowledge and
justification can be transmitted to non-foundational beliefs. Foundationalism
allows for differences on these projects, since it is essentially a view about
the structure of knowledge and epistemic justification. The question whether
knowledge has foundations is essentially the question whether the sort of
justification pertinent to knowledge has a twotier structure. Some philosophers
have construed the former question as asking whether knowledge depends on
beliefs that are certain in some sense e.g., indubitable or infallible. This
construal bears, however, on only one species of foundationalism: radical
foundationalism. Such foundationalism, represented primarily by Descartes,
requires that foundational beliefs be certain and able to guarantee the
certainty of the non-foundational beliefs they support. Radical foundationalism
is currently unpopular for two main reasons. First, very few, if any, of our
perceptual beliefs are certain i.e., indubitable; and, second, those of our
beliefs that might be candidates for certainty e.g., the belief that I am
thinking lack sufficient substance to guarantee the certainty of our rich,
highly inferential knowledge of the external world e.g., our knowledge of
physics, chemistry, and biology. Contemporary foundationalists typically
endorse modest foundationalism, the view that non-inferentially justified,
foundational beliefs need not possess or provide certainty and need not
deductively support justified non-foundational beliefs. Foundational beliefs or
statements are often called basic beliefs or statements, but the precise
understanding of ‘basic’ here is controversial among foundationalists.
Foundationalists agree, however, in their general understanding of
non-inferentially justified, foundational beliefs as beliefs whose
justification does not derive from other beliefs, although they leave open
whether the causal basis of foundational beliefs includes other beliefs.
Epistemic justification comes in degrees, but for simplicity we can restrict
discussion to justification sufficient for satisfaction of the justification
condition for knowledge; we can also restrict discussion to what it takes for a
belief to have justification, omitting issues of what it takes to show that a
belief has it. Three prominent accounts of non-inferential justification are
available to modest foundationalists: a self-justification, b justification by
non-belief, non-propositional experiences, and c justification by a non-belief
reliable origin of a belief. Proponents of self-justification including, at one
time, Ducasse and Chisholm contend that foundational beliefs can justify
themselves, with no evidential support elsewhere. Proponents of foundational
justification by non-belief experiences shun literal self-justification; they
hold, following C. I. Lewis, that foundational perceptual beliefs can be
justified by non-belief sensory or perceptual experiences e.g., seeming to see
a dictionary that make true, are best explained by, or otherwise support, those
beliefs e.g., the belief that there is, or at least appears to be, a dictionary
here. Proponents of foundational justification by reliable origins find the
basis of non-inferential justification in belief-forming processes e.g.,
perception, memory, introspection that are truth-conducive, i.e., that tend to
produce true rather than false beliefs. This view thus appeals to the
reliability of a belief’s nonbelief origin, whereas the previous view appeals
to the particular sensory or perceptual experiences that correspond to e.g.,
make true or are best explained by a foundational belief. Despite disagreements
over the basis of foundational justification, modest foundationalists typically
agree that foundational justification is characterized by defeasibility, i.e.,
can be defeated, undermined, or overridden by a certain sort of expansion of
one’s evidence or justified beliefs. For instance, your belief that there is a
blue dictionary before you could lose its justification e.g., the justification
from your current perceptual experiences if you acquired new evidence that
there is a blue light shining on the dictionary before you. Foundational
justification, therefore, can vary over time if accompanied by relevant changes
in one’s perceptual evidence. It does not follow, however, that foundational justification
positively depends, i.e., is based, on grounds for denying that there are
defeaters. The relevant dependence can be regarded as negative in that there
need only be an absence of genuine defeaters. Critics of foundationalism
sometimes neglect that latter distinction regarding epistemic dependence. The
second big task for foundationalists is to explain how justification transmits
from foundational beliefs to inferentially justified, non-foundational beliefs.
Radical foundationalists insist, for such transmission, on entailment relations
that guarantee the truth or the certainty of nonfoundational beliefs. Modest
foundationalists are more flexible, allowing for merely probabilistic
inferential connections that transmit justification. For instance, a modest
foundationalist can appeal to explanatory inferential connections, as when a
foundational belief e.g., I seem to feel wet is best explained for a person by
a particular physical-object belief e.g., the belief that the air conditioner
overhead is leaking on me. Various other forms of probabilistic inference are
available to modest foundationalists; and nothing in principle requires that
they restrict foundational beliefs to what one “seems” to sense or to perceive.
The traditional motivation for foundationalism comes largely from an
eliminative regress argument, outlined originally regarding knowledge in
Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics. The argument, in shortest form, is that
foundationalism is a correct account of the structure of justification since
the alternative accounts all fail. Inferential justification is justification
wherein one belief, B1, is justified on the basis of another belief, B2. How,
if at all, is B2, the supporting belief, itself justified? Obviously, Aristotle
suggests, we cannot have a circle here, where B2 is justified by B1; nor can we
allow the chain of support to extend endlessly, with no ultimate basis for
justification. We cannot, moreover, allow B2 to remain unjustified,
foundationalism foundationalism 322 322
lest it lack what it takes to support B1. If this is right, the structure of
justification does not involve circles, endless regresses, or unjustified
starter-beliefs. That is, this structure is evidently foundationalist. This is,
in skeletal form, the regress argument for foundationalism. Given appropriate
flesh, and due attention to skepticism about justification, this argument poses
a serious challenge to non-foundationalist accounts of the structure of
epistemic justification, such as epistemic coherentism. More significantly,
foundationalism will then show forth as one of the most compelling accounts of
the structure of knowledge and justification. This explains, at least in part,
why foundationalism has been very prominent historically and is still widely
held in contemporary epistemology.
Fourier,
François-Marie-Charles 17721837, social
theorist and radical critic, often called a utopian socialist. His main works
were The Theory of Universal Unity 1822 and The New Industrial and Societal
World 1829. He argued that since each person has, not an integral soul but only
a partial one, personal integrity is possible only in unity with others.
Fourier thought that all existing societies were antagonistic. Following
Edenism, he believed societies developed through stages of savagery,
patriarchalism, barbarianism, and civilization. He believed this antagonism
could be transcended only in Harmony. It would be based on twelve kinds of
passions. Five were sensual, four affective, and three distributive; and these
in turn encouraged the passion for unity. The basic social unit would be a
phalanx containing 300 400 families about 1,6001,800 people of scientifically
blended characters. As a place of production but also of maximal satisfaction
of the passions of every member, Harmony should make labor attractive and
pleasurable. The main occupations of its members should be gastronomy, opera,
and horticulture. It should also establish a new world of love a form of
polygamy where men and women would be equal in rights. Fourier believed that
phalanxes would attract members of all other social systems, even the less
civilized, and bring about this new world system. Fourier’s vision of
cooperation both in theory and experimental practice influenced some
anarchists, syndicalists, and the cooperationist movement. His radical social
critique was important for the development of political and social thought in
France, Europe, and North America.
Frankena, William K.
894, moral philosopher who wrote a
series of influential articles and a text, Ethics 3, which was tr. into eight
languages and remains in use today. Frankena taught at the of Michigan 778, where he and his colleagues
Charles Stevenson 879, a leading noncognitivist, and Richard Brandt, an
important ethical naturalist, formed for many years one of the most formidable
faculties in moral philosophy in the world. Frankena was known for analytical
rigor and sharp insight, qualities already evident in his first essay, “The
Naturalistic Fallacy” 9, which refuted Moore’s influential claim that ethical
naturalism or any other reductionist ethical theory could be convicted of
logical error. At best, Frankena showed, reductionists could be said to
conflate or misidentify ethical properties with properties of some other kind.
Even put this way, such assertions were question-begging, Frankena argued.
Where Moore claimed to see propfoundation axiom Frankena, William K. 323 323 erties of two different kinds,
naturalists and other reductionists claimed to be able to see only one. Many of
Frankena’s most important papers concerned similarly fundamental issues about
value and normative judgment. “Obligation and Motivation in Recent Moral
Philosophy” 8, for example, is a classic treatment of the debate between
internalism, which holds that motivation is essential to obligation or to the
belief or perception that one is obligated, and externalism, which holds that
motivation is only contingently related to these. In addition to metaethics,
Frankena’s published works ranged broadly over normative ethical theory, virtue
ethics, moral psychology, religious ethics, moral education, and the philosophy
of education. Although relatively few of his works were devoted exclusively to
the area, Frankena was also known as the preeminent historian of ethics of his
day. More usually, Frankena used the history of ethics as a framework within
which to discuss issues of perennial interest. It was, however, for Ethics, one
of the most widely used and frequently cited philosophical ethics textbooks of
the twentieth century, that Frankena was perhaps best known. Ethics continues
to provide an unparalleled introduction to the subject, as useful in a first
undergraduate course as it is to graduate students and professional
philosophers looking for perspicuous ways to frame issues and categorize
alternative solutions. For example, when in the 0s philosophers came to
systematically investigate normative ethical theories, it was Frankena’s
distinction in Ethics between deontological and teleological theories to which
they referred.
Frankfurt School, a group
of philosophers, cultural critics, and social scientists associated with the
Institute for Social Research, which was founded in Frankfurt in 9. Its
prominent members included, among others, the philosophers Horkheimer, Adorno,
and Marcuse, as well as the psychoanalyst Erich Fromm 080 and the literary
critic Walter Benjamin 2 0. Habermas is the leading representative of its
second generation. The Frankfurt School is less known for particular theories
or doctrines than for its program of a “critical theory of society.” Critical
theory represents a sophisticated effort to continue Marx’s transformation of
moral philosophy into social and political critique, while rejecting orthodox
Marxism as a dogma. Critical theory is primarily a way of doing philosophy,
integrating the normative aspects of philosophical reflection with the
explanatory achievements of the social sciences. The ultimate goal of its
program is to link theory and practice, to provide insight, and to empower subjects
to change their oppressive circumstances and achieve human emancipation, a
rational society that satisfies human needs and powers. The first generation of
the Frankfurt School went through three phases of development. The first,
lasting from the beginning of the Institute until the end of the 0s, can be
called “interdisciplinary historical materialism” and is best represented in
Horkheimer’s programmatic writings. Horkheimer argued that a revised version of
historical materialism could organize the results of social research and give
it a critical perspective. The second, “critical theory” phase saw the
abandonment of Marxism for a more generalized notion of critique. However, with
the near-victory of the Nazis in the early 0s, Horkheimer and Adorno entered
the third phase of the School, “the critique of instrumental reason.” In their
Dialectic of Enlightenment 1 as well as in Marcuse’s One Dimensional Man 4, the
process of instrumentally dominating nature leads to dehumanization and the
domination of human beings. In their writings after World War II, Adorno and
Horkheimer became increasingly pessimistic, seeing around them a “totally
administered society” and a manipulated, commodity culture. Horkheimer’s most
important essays are from the first phase and focus on the relation of
philosophy and social science. Besides providing a clear definition and program
for critical social science, he proposes that the normative orientation of
philosophy should be combined with the empirical research in the social sciences.
This metaphilosophical orientation distinguishes a “critical,” as opposed to
“traditional,” theory. For example, such a program demands rethinking the
relation of epistemology to the sociology of science. A critical theory seeks
to show how the norm of truth is historical and practical, without falling into
the skepticism or relativism of traditional sociologies of knowledge such as
Mannheim’s. Adorno’s major writings belong primarily to the second and third
phases of the development of the Frankfurt School. As the possibilities for
criticism appeared to him increasingly narrow, Adorno sought to discover them
in aesthetic experience and the mimetic relation to nature. Adorno’s approach
was motivated by his view Frankfurt School Frankfurt School 324 324 that modern society is a “false
totality.” His diagnosis of the causes traced this trend back to the spread of
a one-sided, instrumental reason, based on the domination of nature and other
human beings. For this reason, he sought a noninstrumental and non-dominating
relation to nature and to others, and found it in diverse and fragmentary
experiences. Primarily, it is art that preserves this possibility in
contemporary society, since in art there is a possibility of mimesis, or the
“non-identical” relation to the object. Adorno’s influential attempt to avoid
“the logic of identity” gives his posthumous Aesthetic Theory 0 and other later
works a paradoxical character. It was in reaction to the third phase that the
second generation of the Frankfurt School recast the idea of a critical theory.
Habermas argued for a new emphasis on normative foundations as well as a return
to an interdisciplinary research program in the social sciences. After first
developing such a foundation in a theory of cognitive interests technical,
practical, and emancipatory, Habermas turned to a theory of the unavoidable
presuppositions of communicative action and an ethics of discourse. The
potential for emancipatory change lies in communicative, or discursive,
rationality and practices that embody it, such as the democratic public sphere.
Habermas’s analysis of communication seeks to provide norms for non-dominating
relations to others and a broader notion of reason.
free logic, a system of
quantification theory, with or without identity, that allows for non-denoting
singular terms. In classical quantification theory, all singular terms free
variables and individual constants are assigned a denotation in all models. But
this condition appears counterintuitive when such systems are applied to
natural language, where many singular terms seem to be non-denoting ‘Pegasus’,
‘Sherlock Holmes’, and the like. Various solutions of this problem have been
proposed, ranging from Frege’s chosen object theory assign an arbitrary
denotation to each non-denoting singular term to Russell’s description theory
deny singular term status to most expressions used as such in natural language,
and eliminate them from the “logical form” of that language to a weakening of
the quantifiers’ “existential import,” which allows for denotations to be
possible, but not necessarily actual, objects. All these solutions preserve the
structure of classical quantification theory and make adjustments at the level
of application. Free logic is a more radical solution: it allows for legitimate
singular terms to be denotationless, maintains the quantifiers’ existential
import, but modifies both the proof theory and the semantics of first-order
logic. Within proof theory, the main modification consists of eliminating the rule
of existential generalization, which allows one to infer ‘There exists a flying
horse’ from ‘Pegasus is a flying horse’. Within semantics, the main problem is
giving truth conditions for sentences containing non-denoting singular terms,
and there are various ways of accomplishing this. Conventional semantics
assigns truth-values to atomic sentences containing non-denoting singular terms
by convention, and then determines the truth-values of complex sentences as
usual. Outer domain semantics divides the domain of interpretation into an
inner and an outer part, using the inner part as the range of quantifiers and
the outer part to provide for “denotations” for non-denoting singular terms
which are then not literally denotationless, but rather left without an
existing denotation. Supervaluational semantics, when considering a sentence A,
assigns all possible combinations of truth-values to the atomic components of A
containing non-denoting singular terms, evaluates A on the basis of each of
those combinations, and then assigns to A the logical product of all such
evaluations. Thus both ‘Pegasus flies’ and ‘Pegasus does not fly’ turn out
truth-valueless, but ‘Pegasus flies or Pegasus does not fly’ turns out true
since whatever truth-value is assigned to its atomic component ‘Pegasus flies’
the truth-value for the whole sentence is true. A free logic is inclusive if it
allows for the possibility that the range of quantifiers be empty that there
exists nothing at all; it is exclusive otherwise.
free rider, a person who
benefits from a social arrangement without bearing an appropriate share of the
burdens of maintaining that arrangement, e.g. one who benefits from government
services without paying one’s taxes that support them. The arrangements from
which a free rider benefits may be either formal or informal. Cooperative
arrangements that permit free riders are likely to be unstable; parties to the
arrangement are unlikely to continue to bear the burdens of maintaining it if
others are able to benefit without doing their part. As a result, it is common
for cooperative arrangements to include mechanisms to discourage free riders,
e.g. legal punishment, or in cases of informal conventions the mere disapproval
of one’s peers. It is a matter of some controversy as to whether it is always
morally wrong to benefit from an arrangement without contributing to its
maintenance.
free will problem, the
problem of the nature of free agency and its relation to the origins and
conditions of responsible behavior. For those who contrast ‘free’ with
‘determined’, a central question is whether humans are free in what they do or
determined by external events beyond their control. A related concern is
whether an agent’s responsibility for an action requires that the agent, the
act, or the relevant decision be free. This, in turn, directs attention to
action, motivation, deliberation, choice, and intention, and to the exact
sense, if any, in which our actions are under our control. Use of ‘free will’
is a matter of traditional nomenclature; it is debated whether freedom is
properly ascribed to the will or the agent, or to actions, choices,
deliberations, etc. Controversy over conditions of responsible behavior forms
the predominant historical and conceptual background of the free will problem.
Most who ascribe moral responsibility acknowledge some sense in which agents
must be free in acting as they do; we are not responsible for what we were
forced to do or were unable to avoid no matter how hard we tried. But there are
differing accounts of moral responsibility and disagreements about the nature
and extent of such practical freedom a notion also important in Kant.
Accordingly, the free will problem centers on these questions: Does moral
responsibility require any sort of practical freedom? If so, what sort? Are
people practically free? Is practical freedom consistent with the antecedent
determination of actions, thoughts, and character? There is vivid debate about
this last question. Consider a woman deliberating about whom to vote for. From
her first-person perspective, she feels free to vote for any candidate and is
convinced that the selection is up to her regardless of prior influences. But
viewing her eventual behavior as a segment of larger natural and historical
processes, many would argue that there are underlying causes determining her
choice. With this contrast of intuitions, any attempt to decide whether the
voter is free depends on the precise meanings associated with terms like
‘free’, ‘determine’, and ‘up to her’. One thing event, situation determines
another if the latter is a consequence of it, or necessitated by it, e.g., the
voter’s hand movements by her intention. As usually understood, determinism
holds that whatever happens is determined by antecedent conditions, where determination
is standardly conceived as causation by antecedent events and circumstances. So
construed, determinism implies that at any time the future is already fixed and
unique, with no possibility of alternative development. Logical versions of
determinism declare each future event to be determined by what is already true,
specifically, by the truth that it will occur then. Typical theological
variants accept the predestination of all circumstances and events inasmuch as
a divine being knows in advance or even from eternity that they will obtain.
Two elements are common to most interpretations of ‘free’. First, freedom
requires an absence of determination or certain sorts of determination, and
second, one acts and chooses freely only if these endeavors are, properly
speaking, one’s own. From here, accounts diverge. Some take freedom liberty of
indifference or the contingency of alternative courses of action to be
critical. Thus, for the woman deliberating about which candidate to select,
each choice is an open alternative inasmuch as it is possible but not yet
necessitated. Indifference is also construed as motivational equilibrium, a
condition some find essential to the idea that a free choice must be rational.
Others focus on freedom liberty of spontaneity, where the voter is free if she
votes as she chooses or desires, a reading that reflects the popular equation
of freedom with “doing what you want.” Associated with both analyses is a third
by which the woman acts freely if she exercises her control, implying
responsiveness to free rider free will problem 326 326 intent as well as both abilities to
perform an act and to refrain. A fourth view identifies freedom with autonomy,
the voter being autonomous to the extent that her selection is self-determined,
e.g., by her character, deeper self, higher values, or informed reason. Though
distinct, these conceptions are not incompatible, and many accounts of
practical freedom include elements of each. Determinism poses problems if
practical freedom requires contingency alternate possibilities of action.
Incompatibilism maintains that determinism precludes freedom, though
incompatibilists differ whether everything is determined. Those who accept
determinism thereby endorse hard determinism associated with eighteenthcentury
thinkers like d’Holbach and, recently, certain behaviorists, according to which
freedom is an illusion since behavior is brought about by environmental and
genetic factors. Some hard determinists also deny the existence of moral
responsibility. At the opposite extreme, metaphysical libertarianism asserts
that people are free and responsible and, a fortiori, that the past does not
determine a unique future a position
some find enhanced by developments in quantum physics. Among adherents of this
sort of incompatibilism are those who advocate a freedom of indifference by
describing responsible choices as those that are undetermined by antecedent
circumstances Epicureans. To rebut the charge that choices, so construed, are
random and not really one’s “own,” it has been suggested that several elements,
including an agent’s reasons, delimit the range of possibilities and influence
choices without necessitating them a view held by Leibniz and, recently, by
Robert Kane. Libertarians who espouse agency causation, on the other hand,
blend contingency with autonomy in characterizing a free choice as one that is
determined by the agent who, in turn, is not caused to make it a view found in
Carneades and Reid. Unwilling to abandon practical freedom yet unable to
understand how a lack of determination could be either necessary or desirable
for responsibility, many philosophers take practical freedom and responsibility
to be consistent with determinism, thereby endorsing compatibilism. Those who
also accept determinism advocate what James called soft determinism. Its
supporters include some who identify freedom with autonomy the Stoics, Spinoza
and others who champion freedom of spontaneity Hobbes, Locke, Hume. The latter
speak of liberty as the power of doing or refraining from an action according
to what one wills, so that by choosing otherwise one would have done otherwise.
An agent fails to have liberty when constrained, that is, when either prevented
from acting as one chooses or compelled to act in a manner contrary to what one
wills. Extending this model, liberty is also diminished when one is caused to
act in a way one would not otherwise prefer, either to avoid a greater danger
coercion or because there is deliberate interference with the envisioning of alternatives
manipulation. Compatibilists have shown considerable ingenuity in responding to
criticisms that they have ignored freedom of choice or the need for open
alternatives. Some apply the spontaneity, control, or autonomy models to
decisions, so that the voter chooses freely if her decision accords with her
desires, is under her control, or conforms to her higher values, deeper
character, or informed reason. Others challenge the idea that responsibility
requires alternative possibilities of action. The so-called Frankfurt-style
cases developed by Harry G. Frankfurt are situations where an agent acts in
accord with his desires and choices, but because of the presence of a
counterfactual intervener a mechanism
that would have prevented the agent from doing any alternative action had he
shown signs of acting differently the
agent could not have done otherwise. Frankfurt’s intuition is that the agent is
as responsible as he would have been if there were no intervener, and thus that
responsible action does not require alternative possibilities. Critics have
challenged the details of the Frankfurt-style cases in attempting to undermine
the appeal of the intuition. A different compatibilist tactic recognizes the
need for open alternatives and employs versions of the indifference model in
describing practical freedom. Choices are free if they are contingent relative
to certain subsets of circumstances, e.g. those the agent is or claims to be
cognizant of, with the openness of alternatives grounded in what one can choose
“for all one knows.” Opponents of compatibilism charge that since these
refinements leave agents subject to external determination, even by hidden
controllers, compatibilism continues to face an insurmountable challenge. Their
objections are sometimes summarized by the consequence argument so called by
Peter van Inwagen, who has prominently defended it: if everything were
determined by factors beyond one’s control, then one’s acts, choices, and
character would also be beyond one’s control, and consequently, agents would
never be free and there would be nothing free will problem free will problem
327 327 for which they are responsible.
Such reasoning usually employs principles asserting the closure of the practical
modalities ability, control, avoidability, inevitability, etc. under
consequence relations. However, there is a reason to suppose that the sort of
ability and control required by responsibility involve the agent’s sense of
what can be accomplished. Since cognitive states are typically not closed under
consequence, the closure principles underlying the consequence argument are
disputable.
Freges
Sättigung:
Frege’s original Sinn. Fregeian saturation. Grice was once at the Bodleian
assisting Austin in his translation of Frege’s Grundlegung – and browsing
through the old-style library fiches, Grice exclaims: “All these essays in
German journals about Fregeian saturation can surely saturate one!’ Austin was
not amused. Neben mathematischen und physikalischen Vorlesungen sowie einer in
Philosophie hat Frege in Jena Vorlesungen in Chemie besucht und in diesem Fach
auch an einem einsemestrigen Praktikum teilgenommen. In seiner wohlbekannten
Rede über Bindung und Sättigung von Ausdrücken klingt davon noch etwas
nach.Betrachten wir nun die Konsequenzen der Fregeschen Auffassung der
prädikativen Natur der Begriffe. Hierfür ist es zunächst erforderlich,
abschließend einige Besonderheiten anzumerken, die daraus folgen, daß auch
Begriffsausdrücke bedeutungsvoll sein sollen. Zunächst hatten wir ja mit Hilfe
der Analogie festgestellt, daß in einem Satz dasjenige, was Begriffsausdrücke
bedeuten, denselben ontologischen Status haben muß wie das, was Eigennamen
bedeuten. Insofern scheinen sowohl Eigennamen als auch Begriffsausdrücke
jeweils bestimmte (wenn auch hinsichtlich ihrer Sättigung oder
Bindungsfähigkeit unterschiedene) Entitäten als Bedeutung zu haben. Und Frege
erklärt auch explizit „Begriff ist Bedeutung eines Prädikates“ [BG, 198]. Frege’s distinction between saturated
expressions and unsaturated expressions corresponds to the distinction between
objects and concepts. A saturated expression refers to an object or argument
and has a complete sense in itself, while an unsaturated expression refers to a
concept or function and does not have a complete sense. For example, in the
sentence “Socrates is the teacher of Plato,” “Socrates” and “Plato” are proper
names and are saturated, while “. . . is the teacher of . . .” is unsaturated,
for it has empty spaces that must be filled with saturated expressions before it
gains a complete sense. “Statements in general . . . can be imagined to be
split up into two parts; one complete in itself, and the other in need of
supplementation, or ‘unsaturated’.” Frege, “Function and Concept,”
Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege.
Frege, G., philosopher. A
founder of modern mathematical logic, an advocate of logicism, and a major
source of twentieth-century analytic philosophy, he directly influenced
Russell, Vitters, and Carnap. Frege’s distinction between the sense and the
reference of linguistic expressions continues to be debated. His first
publication in logic was his strikingly original 1879 Begriffsschrift
Concept-notation. Here he devised a formal language whose central innovation is
the quantifier-variable notation to express generality; he set forth in this
language a version of second-order quantificational logic that he used to
develop a logical definition of the ancestral of a relation. Frege invented his
Begriffsschrift in order to circumvent drawbacks of the use of colloquial
language to state proofs. Colloquial language is irregular, unperspicuous, and
ambiguous in its expression of logical relationships. Moreover, logically
crucial features of the content of statements may remain tacit and unspoken. It
is thus impossible to determine exhaustively the premises on which the
conclusion of any proof conducted within ordinary language depends. Frege’s
Begriffsschrift is to force the explicit statement of the logically relevant
features of any assertion. Proofs in the system are limited to what can be
obtained from a body of evidently true logical axioms by means of a small
number of truth-preserving notational manipulations inference rules. Here is
the first hallmark of Frege’s view of logic: his formulation of logic as a
formal system and the ideal of explicitness and rigor that this presentation
subserves. Although the formal exactitude with which he formulates logic makes
possible the metamathematical investigation of formalized theories, he showed
almost no interest in metamathematical questions. He intended the
Begriffsschrift to be used. How though does Frege conceive of the subject
matter of logic? His orientation in logic is shaped by his anti-psychologism,
his conviction that psychology has nothing to do with logic. He took his
notation to be a full-fledged language in its own right. The logical axioms do
not mention objects or properties whose investigation pertains to some special
science; and Frege’s quantifiers are unrestricted. Laws of logic are, as he says,
the laws of truth, and these are the most general truths. He envisioned the
supplementation of the logical vocabulary of the Begriffsschrift with the basic
vocabulary of the special sciences. In this way the Begriffsschrift affords a
framework for the completely rigorous deductive development of any science
whatsoever. This resolutely nonpsychological universalist view of logic as the
most general science is the second hallmark of Frege’s view of logic. This
universalist view distinguishes his approach sharply from the coeval algebra of
logic approach of George Boole and Ernst Schröder. Vitters, both in the
Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus 1 and in later writings, is very critical of
Frege’s universalist view. Logical positivism
most notably Carnap in The Logical Syntax of Language 4 rejected it as well. Frege’s universalist
view is also distinct from more contemporary views. With his view of
quantifiers as intrinsically unrestricted, he saw little point in talking of
varying interpretations of a language, believing that such talk is a confused
way of getting at what is properly said by means of second-order
generalizations. In particular, the semantical conception of logical
consequences that becomes prominent in logic after Kurt Gödel’s and Tarski’s work
is foreign to Frege. Frege’s work in logic was prompted by an inquiry after the
ultimate foundation for arithmetic truths. He criticized J. S. Mill’s
empiricist attempt to ground knowledge of the arithmetic of the positive
integers inductively in our manipulations of small collections of things. He
also rejected crudely formalist views that take pure mathematics to be a sort
of notational game. In contrast to these views and Kant’s, he hoped to use his
Begriffsschrift to define explicitly the basic notions of arithmetic in logical
terms and to deduce the basic principles of arithmetic from logical axioms and
these definitions. The explicitness and rigor of his formulation of logic will
guarantee that there are no implicit extralogical premises on which the
arithmetical conclusions depend. Such proofs, he believed, would show
arithmetic to be analytic, not synthetic as Kant had claimed. However, Frege
redefined ‘analytic’ to mean ‘provable from
logical laws’ in his rather un-Kantian sense of ‘logic’ and definitions.
Frege’s strategy for these proofs rests on an analysis of the concept of
cardinal number that he presented in his nontechnical 4 book, The Foundations
of Arithmetic. Frege, attending to the use of numerals in statements like ‘Mars
has two moons’, argued that it contains an assertion about a concept, that it
asserts that there are exactly two things falling under the concept ‘Martian
moon’. He also noted that both numerals in these statements and those of pure
arithmetic play the logical role of singular terms, his proper names. He
concluded that numbers are objects so that a definition of the concept of
number must then specify what objects numbers are. He observed that 1 the
number of F % the number of G just in case there is a one-to-one correspondence
between the objects that are F and those that are G. The right-hand side of 1
is statable in purely logical terms. As Frege recognized, thanks to the
definition of the ancestral of a relation, 1 suffices in the second-order
setting of the Begriffsschrift for the derivation of elementary arithmetic. The
vindication of his logicism requires, however, the logical definition of the
expression ‘the number of’. He sharply criticized the use in mathematics of any
notion of set or collection that views a set as built up from its elements.
However, he assumed that, corresponding to each concept, there is an object,
the extension of the concept. He took the notion of an extension to be a
logical one, although one to which the notion of a concept is prior. He adopted
as a fundamental logical principle the ill-fated biconditional: the extension
of F % the extension of G just in case every F is G, and vice versa. If this
principle were valid, he could exploit the equivalence relation over concepts
that figures in the right-hand side of 1 to identify the number of F with a
certain extension and thus obtain 1 as a theorem. In The Basic Laws of
Arithmetic vol. 1, 3; vol. 2, 3 he formalized putative proofs of basic
arithmetical laws within a modified version of the Begriffsschrift that
included a generalization of the law of extensions. However, Frege’s law of
extensions, in the context of his logic, is inconsistent, leading to Russell’s
paradox, as Russell communicated to Frege in 2. Frege’s attempt to establish
logicism was thus, on its own terms, unsuccessful. In Begriffsschrift Frege
rejected the thesis that every uncompound sentence is logically segmented into
a subject and a predicate. Subsequently, he said that his approach in logic was
distinctive in starting not from the synthesis of concepts into judgments, but
with the notion of truth and that to which this notion is applicable, the
judgeable contents or thoughts that are expressed by statements. Although he
said that truth is the goal of logic, he did not think that we have a grasp of
the notion of truth that is independent of logic. He eschewed a correspondence
theory of truth, embracing instead a redundancy view of the truth-predicate.
For Frege, to call truth the goal of logic points toward logic’s concern with
inference, with the recognition-of-thetruth judging of one thought on the basis
of the recognition-of-the-truth of another. This recognition-of-the-truth-of is
not verbally expressed by a predicate, but rather in the assertive force with
which a sentence is uttered. The starting point for logic is then reflection on
elementary inference patterns that analyze thoughts and reveal a logical
segmentation in language. This starting point, and the fusion of logical and
ontological categories it engenders, is arguably what Frege is pointing toward
by his enigmatic context principle in Foundations: only in the context of a
sentence does a word have a meaning. He views sentences as having a
function-argument segmentation like that manifest in the terms of arithmetic,
e.g., 3 $ 4 ! 2. Truth-functional inference patterns, like modus ponens,
isolate sentences as logical units in compound sentences. Leibniz’s law the substitution of one name for another in a
sentence on the basis of an equation
isolates proper names. Proper names designate objects. Predicates,
obtainable by removing proper names from sentences, designate concepts. The
removal of a predicate from a sentence leaves a higher level predicate that
signifies a second-level concept under which first-level concepts fall. An
example is the universal quantifier over objects: it designates a second-level
concept under which a first-level concept falls, if every object falls under
it. Frege takes each first-level concept to be determinately true or false of
each object. Vague predicates, like ‘is bald’, thus fail to signify concepts.
This requirement of concept determinacy is a product of Frege’s construal of
quantification over objects as intrinsically unrestricted. Thus, concept
determinacy is simply a form of the law of the excluded middle: for any concept
F and any object x, either x is F or x is not F. Frege elaborates and modifies
his basic logical ideas in three seminal papers from , “Function and Concept,”
“On Concept and Frege, Gottlob Frege, Gottlob 329 329 Object,” and “On Sense and Meaning.” In
“Function and Concept,” Frege sharpens his conception of the function-argument
structure of language. He introduces the two truth-values, the True and the
False, and maintains that sentences are proper names of these objects. Concepts
become functions that map objects to either the True or the False. The
course-of-values of a function is introduced as a generalization of the notion
of an extension. Generally then, an object is anything that might be designated
by a proper name. There is nothing more basic to be said by way of elucidating
what an object is. Similarly, first-level functions are what are designated by
the expressions that result from removing names from compound proper names.
Frege calls functions unsaturated or incomplete, in contrast to objects, which
are saturated. Proper names and function names are not intersubstitutable so
that the distinction between objects and functions is a type-theoretic,
categorial distinction. No function is an object; no function name designates
an object; there are no quantifiers that simultaneously generalize over both
functions and concepts. Just here Frege’s exposition of his views, if not the
views themselves, encounter a difficulty. In explaining his views, he uses proper
names of the form ‘the concept F’ to talk about concepts; and in contrasting
unsaturated functions with saturated objects, apepars to generalize over both
with a single quantifier. Benno Kerry, a contemporary of Frege, charged Frege’s
views with inconsistency. Since the phrase ‘the concept horse’ is a proper
name, it must designate an object. On Frege’s view, it follows that the concept
‘horse’ is not a concept, but an object, an apparent inconsistency. Frege
responded to Kerry’s criticism in “On Concept and Object.” He embraced Kerry’s
paradox, denying that it represents a genuine inconsistency, while admitting
that his remarks about the functionobject distinction are, as the result of an
unavoidable awkwardness of language, misleading. Frege maintained that the
distinction between function and object is logically simple and so cannot be
properly defined. His remarks on the distinction are informal handwaving
designed to elucidate what is captured within the Begriffsschrift by the
difference between proper names and function names together with their
associated distinct quantifiers. Frege’s handling of the function object
distinction is a likely source for Vitters’s sayshow distinction in the
Tractatus. At the beginning of “On Sense and Meaning,” Frege distinguishes
between the reference or meaning Bedeutung of a proper name and its sense Sinn.
He observes that the sentence ‘The Morning Star is identical with the Morning
Star’ is a trivial instance of the principle of identity. In contrast, the
sentence ‘The Morning Star is identical with the Evening Star’ expresses a
substantive astronomical discovery. The two sentences thus differ in what Frege
called their cognitive value: someone who understood both might believe the
first and doubt the second. This difference cannot be explained in terms of any
difference in reference between names in these sentences. Frege explained it in
terms of a difference between the senses expressed by ‘the Morning Star’ and
‘the Evening Star’. In posthumously published writings, he indicated that the
sensereference distinction extends to function names as well. In this
distinction, Frege extends to names the notion of the judgeable content
expressed by a sentence: the sense of a name is the contribution that the name
makes to the thought expressed by sentences in which it occurs. Simultaneously,
in classifying sentences as proper names of truth-values, he applies to
sentences the notion of a name’s referring to something. Frege’s
function-argument view of logical segmentation constrains his view of both the
meaning and the sense of compound names: the substitution for any name
occurring in a compound expression of a name with the same reference sense
yields a new compound expression with the same reference sense as the original.
Frege advances several theses about sense that individually and collectively
have been a source of debate in philosophy of language. First, the sense of an
expression is what is grasped by anyone who understands it. Despite the
connection between understanding and sense, Frege provides no account of
synonymy, no identity criteria for senses. Second, the sense of an expression
is not something psychological. Senses are objective. They exist independently
of anyone’s grasping them; their availability to different thinkers is a
presupposition for communication in science. Third, the sense expressed by a
name is a mode of presentation of the name’s reference. Here Frege’s views
contrast with Russell’s. Corresponding to Frege’s thoughts are Russell’s
propositions. In The Principles of Mathematics 3, Russell maintained that the
meaningful words in a sentence designate things, properties, and relations that
are themselves constituents of the proposition expressed by the sentence. For
Frege, our access through judgment to objects and functions is via Frege,
Gottlob Frege, Gottlob 330 330 the
senses that are expressed by names that mean these items. These senses, not the
items they present, occur in thoughts. Names expressing different senses may
refer to the same item; and some names, while expressing a sense, refer to
nothing. Any compound name containing a name that has a sense, but lacks a
reference, itself lacks a meaning. A person may fully understand an expression
without knowing whether it means anything and without knowing whether it
designates what another understood name does. Fourth, the sense ordinarily
expressed by a name is the reference of the name, when the name occurs in
indirect discourse. Although the Morning Star is identical with the Evening Star,
the inference from the sentence ‘Smith believes that the Morning Star is a
planet’ to ‘Smith believes that the Evening Star is a planet’ is not sound.
Frege, however, accepts Leibniz’s law without restriction. He accordingly takes
such seeming failures of Leibniz’s law to expose a pervasive ambiguity in
colloquial language: names in indirect discourse do not designate what they
designate outside of indirect discourse. The fourth thesis is offered as an
explanation of this ambiguity.
liberatum – liberum arbitrium – vide ‘arbitrium’ How can arbitrium
not be free? Oddly this concerns rationality. For Grice, as for almost
everyone, a rational agent is an autonomous agent. Freewill is proved
grammatically. The Romans had a ‘modus deliberativus’, and even a ‘modus
optativus’ (ortike ktesis) “in imitationem Graecis.”If you utter “Close the
door!” you rely on free will. It would be otiose for a language or system of
communication to have as its goal to inform/get informed, and influence/being
influenced if determinism and fatalism were true. freedom: Like identity, crucial in philosophy
in covering everything. E cannot communicate that p, unless E is FREE. An
amoeba cannot communicate thatp. End setting, unweighed rationality,
rationality about the ends, autonomy. Grice was especially concerned with Kants
having brought back the old Greek idea of eleutheria for philosophical
discussion. Refs.: the obvious keywords are “freedom” and “free,” but most of
the material is in “Actions and events,” in PPQ, and below under ‘kantianism’ –
The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC.Bratman, of Stanford, much influenced by Grice (at
Berkeley then) thanks to their Hands-Across-the-Bay programme, helps us to
understand this Pological progression towards the idea of strong autonomy or
freedom. Recall that Grices Ps combine Lockes very intelligent parrots with
Russells and Carnaps nonsensical Ps of which nothing we are told other than
they karulise elatically. Grices purpose is to give a little thought to a
question. What are the general principles exemplified, in
creature-construction, in progressing from one type of P to a higher type? What
kinds of steps are being made? The kinds of step with which Grice deals are
those which culminate in a licence to include, within the specification of the
content of the psychological state of this or that type of P, a range of
expressions which would be inappropriate with respect to this lower-type P.
Such expressions include this or that connective, this or that quantifier, this
or that temporal modifier, this or that mode indicator, this or that modal
operator, and (importantly) this or that expression to refer to this or that
souly state like … judges that … and …
will that … This or that expression, that is, the availability of which leads
to the structural enrichment of the specification of content. In general, these
steps will be ones by which this or that item or idea which has, initially, a
legitimate place outside the scope of this or that souly instantiable (or, if
you will, the expressions for which occur legitimately outside the scope of
this or that souly predicate) come to have a legitimate place within the scope
of such an instantiable, a step by which, one might say, this or that item or
ideas comes to be internalised. Grice is disposed to regard as prototypical the
sort of natural disposition or propension which Hume attributes to a person,
and which is very important to Hume, viz. the tendency of the soul to spread
itself upon objects, i.e. to project into the world items which, properly or primitively
considered, is a feature of this or that souly state. Grice sets out in stages
the application of aspects of the genitorial programme. We then start with a
zero-order, with a P equipped to satisfy unnested, or logically amorphous,
judging and willing, i.e. whose contents do not involve judging or willing. We
soon reach our first P, G1. It would be advantageous to a P0 if
it could have this or that judging and this or that willing, which relate to
its own judging or willing. Such G1 could be equipped to
control or regulate its own judgings and willings. It will presumably be
already constituted so as to conform to the law that, cæteris paribus, if it
wills that p and judge that ~p, if it can, it makes it the case that p in its
soul To give it some control over its judgings and willings, we need only
extend the application of this law to the Ps judging and willing. We equip the
P so that, cæteris paribus, if it wills that it is not the case that it wills
that p and it judges that they do will that p, if it can, it makes it the case
that it does not will that p. And we somehow ensure that sometimes it can do
this. It may be that the installation of this kind of control would go hand in
had with the installation of the capacity for evaluation. Now, unlike it is the
case with a G1, a G2s intentional effort depends on the motivational strength
of its considered desire at the time of action. There is a process by which
this or that conflicting considered desire motivates action as a broadly causal
process, a process that reveals motivational strength. But a G2 might itself
try to weigh considerations provided by such a conflicting desire B1 and B2 in
deliberation about this or that pro and this or that con of various
alternatives. In the simplest case, such weighing treats each of the things
desired as a prima facie justifying end. In the face of conflict, it weighs
this and that desired end, where the weights correspond to the motivational
strength of the associated considered desire. The outcome of such deliberation,
Aristotle’s prohairesis, matches the outcome of the causal motivational process
envisioned in the description of G2. But, since the weights it
invokes in such deliberation correspond to the motivational strength of this or
that relevant considered desire (though perhaps not to the motivational
strength of this or that relevant considered desire), the resultant activitiy
matches those of a corresponding G2 (each of whose desires, we
are assuming, are considered). To be more realistic, we might limit ourselves
to saying that a P2 has the capacity to make the transition
from this or that unconsidered desire to this or that considered desire, but
does not always do this. But it will keep the discussion more manageable to
simplify and to suppose that each desire is considered. We shall not want this
G2 to depend, in each will and act in ways that reveal the motivational
strength of this or that considered desire at the time of action, but for a G3 it
will also be the case that in this or that, though not each) case, it acts on
the basis of how it weights this or that end favoured by this or that
conflicting considered desire. This or that considered desire will concern
matters that cannot be achieved simply by action at a single time. E. g. G3 may
want to nurture a vegetable garden, or build a house. Such matters will require
organized and coordinated action that extends over time. What the G3 does now
will depend not only on what it now desires but also on what it now expects it
will do later given what it does now. It needs a way of settling now what it
will do later given what it does now. The point is even clearer when we remind
ourselves that G3 is not alone. It is, we may assume, one of some number of G3;
and in many cases it needs to coordinate what it does with what other G3 do so
as to achieve ends desired by all participants, itself included. These
costs are magnified for G4 whose various plans are interwoven so that a change
in one element can have significant ripple effects that will need to be
considered. Let us suppose that the general strategies G4 has for responding to
new information about its circumstances are sensitive to these kinds of costs.
Promoting in the long run the satisfaction of its considered desires and
preferences. G4 is a somewhat sophisticated planning agent but
it has a problem. It can expect that its desires and preferences may well
change over time and undermine its efforts at organizing and coordinating its
activities over time. Perhaps in many cases this is due to the kind of temporal
discounting. So for example G4 may have a plan to exercise every day but may
tend to prefer a sequence of not exercising on the present day but exercising
all days in the future, to a uniform sequence the present day included. At the
end of the day it returns to its earlier considered preference in favour of
exercising on each and every day. Though G4, unlike G3, has the
capacity to settle on prior plans or plaices concerning exercise, this capacity
does not yet help in such a case. A creature whose plans were stable in ways in
part shaped by such a no-regret principle would be more likely than G4 to
resist temporary temptations. So let us build such a principle into the
stability of the plans of a G5, whose plans and policies are not derived solely
from facts about its limits of time, attention, and the like. It is also
grounded in the central concerns of a planning agent with its own future,
concerns that lend special significance to anticipated future regret. So let us
add to G5 the capacity and disposition to arrive at such hierarchies of
higher-order desires concerning its will. This gives us creature G6. There
is a problem with G6, one that has been much discussed. It is not clear why a
higher-order desire ‒ even a higher-order desire that a certain
desire be ones will ‒ is not simply one more desire in the pool of
desires (Berkeley Gods will problem). Why does it have the authority to
constitute or ensure the agents (i. e. the creatures) endorsement or rejection
of a first-order desire? Applied to G6 this is the question of whether, by
virtue solely of its hierarchies of desires, it really does succeed in taking
its own stand of endorsement or rejection of various first-order desires. Since
it was the ability to take its own stand that we are trying to provide in the
move to P6, we need some response to this challenge. The basic point
is that G6 is not merely a time-slice agent. It is, rather, and
understands itself to be, a temporally persisting planning agent, one who
begins, and continues, and completes temporally extended projects. On a broadly
Lockean view, its persistence over time consists in relevant psychological
continuities (e.g., the persistence of attitudes of belief and intention) and
connections (e.g., memory of a past event, or the later intentional execution
of an intention formed earlier). Certain attitudes have as a primary role the
constitution and support of such Lockean continuities and connections. In
particular, policies that favour or reject various desires have it as their
role to constitute and support various continuities both of ordinary desires
and of the politicos themselves. For this reason such policies are not merely
additional wiggles in the psychic stew. Instead, these policies have a claim to
help determine where the agent ‒ i.e., the temporally persisting agent ‒
stands with respect to its desires, or so it seems to me reasonable to say. The
psychology of G7 continues to have the hierarchical structure of pro-attitudes
introduced with G6. The difference is that the higher-order pro-attitudes of G6
were simply characterized as desires in a broad, generic sense, and no appeal
was made to the distinctive species of pro-attitude constituted by plan-like
attitudes. That is the sense in which the psychology of G7 is an extension of
the psychology of G6. Let us then give G7 such higher-order policies with the
capacity to take a stand with respect to its desires by arriving at relevant
higher-order policies concerning the functioning of those desires over time. G7 exhibits
a merger of hierarchical and planning structures. Appealing to planning theory
and ground in connection to the temporally extended structure of agency to be
ones will. G7 has higher-order policies that favour or challenge motivational
roles of its considered desires. When G7 engages in deliberative weighing of
conflicting, desired ends it seems that the assigned weights should reflect the
policies that determine where it stands with respect to relevant desires. But
the policies we have so far appealed to ‒ policies concerning what desires are
to be ones will ‒ do not quite address this concern. The problem is that one
can in certain cases have policies concerning which desires are to motivate and
yet these not be policies that accord what those desires are for a
corresponding justifying role in deliberation. G8. A solution is to give our
creature, G8, the capacity to arrive at policies that express
its commitment to be motivated by a desire by way of its treatment of that
desire as providing, in deliberation, a justifying end for action. G8 has
policies for treating (or not treating) certain desires as providing justifying
ends, as, in this way, reason-providing, in motivationally effective
deliberation. Let us call such policies self-governing policies. We will
suppose that these policies are mutually compatible and do not challenge each
other. In this way G8 involves an extension of structures already present in
G7. The grounds on which G8 arrives at (and on occasion revises) such
self-governing policies will be many and varied. We can see these policies as
crystallizing complex pressures and concerns, some of which are grounded in
other policies or desires. These self-governing policies may be tentative and
will normally not be immune to change. If we ask what G8 values in this case,
the answer seems to be: what it values is constituted in part by its
higher-order self-governing policies. In particular, it values exercise over
nonexercise even right now, and even given that it has a considered, though
temporary, preference to the contrary. Unlike lower Ps, what P8 now
values is not simply a matter of its present, considered desires and
preferences. Now this model of P8 seems in relevant aspects to be a partial)
model of us, in our better moments, of course. So we arrive at the conjecture
that one important kind of valuing of which we are capable involves, in the
cited ways, both our first-order desires and our higher order self-governing
policies. In an important sub-class of cases our valuing involves reflexive
polices that are both first-order policies of action and higher-order policies
to treat the first-order policy as reason providing in motivationally effective
deliberation. This may seem odd. Valuing seems normally to be a first-order
attitude. One values honesty, say. The proposal is that an important kind of
valuing involves higher-order policies. Does this mean that, strictly speaking,
what one values (in this sense) is itself a desire ‒ not honesty, say, but a
desire for honesty? No, it does not. What I value in the present case is
honesty; but, on the theory, my valuing honesty in art consists in certain
higher-order self-governing policies. An agents reflective valuing involves a
kind of higher-order willing. Freud challenged the power structure of the soul
in Plato: it is the libido that takes control, not the logos. Grice takes up
this polemic. Aristotle takes up Platos challenge, each type of soul is united
to the next by the idea of life. The animal soul, between the vegetative and
the rational, is not detachable.
Freud, S., Austrian
neurologist and psychologist, the founder of psychoanalysis. Starting with the
study of hysteria in late nineteenth-century Vienna, Freud developed a theory
of the mind that has come to dominate modern thought. His notions of the
unconscious, of a mind divided against itself, of the meaningfulness of
apparently meaningless activity, of the displacement and transference of
feelings, of stages of psychosexual development, of the pervasiveness and
importance of sexual motivation, as well as of much else, have helped shape
modern consciousness. His language and that of his translators, whether
specifying divisions of the mind e.g. id, ego, and superego, types of disorder
e.g. obsessional neurosis, or the structure of experience e.g. Oedipus complex,
narcissism, has become the language in which we describe and understand
ourselves and others. As the poet W. H. Auden wrote on the occasion of Freud’s
death, “if often he was wrong and, at times, absurd, / to us he is no more a
person / now but a whole climate of opinion / under whom we conduct our
different lives. . . .” Hysteria is a disorder involving organic symptoms with
no apparent organic cause. Following early work in neurophysiology, Freud in
collaboration with Josef Breuer came to the view that “hysterics suffer mainly
from reminiscences,” in particular buried memories of traumatic experiences,
the strangulated affect of which emerged in conversion hysteria in the
distorted form of physical symptoms. Treatment involved the recovery of the
repressed memories to allow the cathartic discharge or abreaction of the
previously displaced and strangulated affect. This provided the background for
Freud’s seduction theory, which traced hysterical symptoms to traumatic prepubertal
sexual assaults typically by fathers. But Freud later abandoned the seduction
theory because the energy assumptions were problematic e.g., if the only energy
involved was strangulated affect from long-past external trauma, why didn’t the
symptom successfully use up that energy and so clear itself up? and because he
came to see that fantasy could have the same effects as memory of actual
events: “psychical reality was of more importance than material reality.” What
was repressed was not memories, but desires. He came to see the repetition of
symptoms as fueled by internal, in particular sexual, energy. While it is
certainly true that Freud saw the Frege-Geach point Freud, Sigmund 331 331 working of sexuality almost everywhere,
it is not true that he explained everything in terms of sexuality alone.
Psychoanalysis is a theory of internal psychic conflict, and conflict requires
at least two parties. Despite developments and changes, Freud’s instinct theory
was determinedly dualistic from beginning to end at the beginning, libido versus ego or
self-preservative instincts, and at the end Eros versus Thanatos, life against
death. Freud’s instinct theory not to be confused with standard biological
notions of hereditary behavior patterns in animals places instincts on the
borderland between the mental and physical and insists that they are internally
complex. In particular, the sexual instinct must be understood as made up of
components that vary along a number of dimensions source, aim, and object.
Otherwise, as Freud argues in his Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality 5, it
would be difficult to understand how the various perversions are recognized as
“sexual” despite their distance from the “normal” conception of sexuality
heterosexual genital intercourse between adults. His broadened concept of
sexuality makes intelligible sexual preferences emphasizing different sources
erotogenic zones or bodily centers of arousal, aims acts, such as intercourse
and looking, designed to achieve pleasure and satisfaction, and objects whether
of the same or different gender, or even other than whole living persons. It
also allows for the recognition of infantile sexuality. Phenomena that might
not on the surface appear sexual e.g. childhood thumbsucking share essential characteristics
with obviously sexual activity infantile sensual sucking involves pleasurable
stimulation of the same erotogenic zone, the mouth, stimulated in adult sexual
activities such as kissing, and can be understood as earlier stages in the
development of the same underlying instinct that expresses itself in such
various forms in adult sexuality. The standard developmental stages are oral,
anal, phallic, and genital. Neuroses, which Freud saw as “the negative of
perversions” i.e., the same desires that might in some lead to perverse
activity, when repressed, result in neurosis, could often be traced to
struggles with the Oedipus complex: the “nucleus of the neuroses.” The Oedipus
complex, which in its positive form postulates sexual feelings toward the parent
of the opposite sex and ambivalently hostile feelings toward the parent of the
same sex, suggests that the universal shape of the human condition is a
triangle. The conflict reaches its peak between the ages of three and five,
during the phallic stage of psychosexual development. The fundamental
structuring of emotions has its roots in the prolonged dependency of the human
infant, leading to attachment a primary
form of love to the primary caregiver,
who partly for biological reasons such as lactation is most often the mother,
and the experience of others as rivals for the time, attention, and concern of
the primary caregiver. Freud’s views of the Oedipus complex should not be
oversimplified. The sexual desires involved, e.g., are typically unconscious
and necessarily infantile, and infantile sexuality and its associated desires
are not expressed in the same form as mature genital sexuality. His efforts to
explain the distinctive features of female psychosexual development in
particular led to some of his most controversial views, including the
postulation of penis envy to explain why girls but not boys standardly
experience a shift in gender of their primary love object both starting with
the mother as the object. Later love objects, including psychoanalysts as the
objects of transference feelings in the analytic setting, the analyst functions
as a blank screen onto which the patient projects feelings, are the results of
displacement or transference from earlier objects: “The finding of an object is
in fact a refinding of it.” Freud used the same structure of explanation for
symptoms and for more normal phenomena, such as dreams, jokes, and slips of the
tongue. All can be seen as compromise formations between forces pressing for
expression localized by Freud’s structural theory in the id, understood as a
reservoir of unconscious instinct and forces of repression some also
unconscious, seeking to meet the constraints of morality and reality. On
Freud’s underlying model, the fundamental process of psychic functioning, the
primary process, leads to the uninhibited discharge of psychic energy. Such
discharge is experienced as pleasurable, hence the governing principle of the
fundamental process is called the pleasure principle. Increase of tension is
experienced as unpleasure, and the psychic apparatus aims at a state of
equilibrium or constancy sometimes Freud writes as if the state aimed at is one
of zero tension, hence the Nirvana principle associated with the death instinct
in Freud’s Beyond the Pleasure Principle [0]. But since pleasure can in fact
only be achieved under specific conditions, which sometimes require
arrangement, planning, and delay, individuals must learn to inhibit discharge,
and this secondary process thinking is governed by what Freud came to call the
reality principle. The aim is still satisfaction, but the “exigencies of life”
require attention, reasoning, and judgment to avoid falling into the fantasy
wishfulfillment of the primary process. Sometimes defense mechanisms designed
to avoid increased tension or unpleasure can fail, leading to neurosis in
general, under the theory, a neurosis is a psychological disorder rooted in
unconscious conflict particular neuroses
being correlated with particular phases of development and particular mechanisms
of defense. Repression, involving the confining of psychic representations to
the unconscious, is the most important of the defense mechanisms. It should be
understood that unlike preconscious ideas, which are merely descriptively
unconscious though one may not be aware of them at the moment, they are readily
accessible to consciousness, unconscious ideas in the strict sense are kept
from awareness by forces of repression, they are dynamically unconscious as evidenced by the resistance to making the
unconscious conscious in therapy. Freud’s deep division of the mind between
unconscious and conscious goes beyond neurotic symptoms to help make sense of
familiar forms of irrationality such as selfdeception, ambivalence, and
weakness of the will that are highly problematical on Cartesian models of an
indivisible unitary consciousness. Perhaps the best example of the primary
process thinking that characterizes the unconscious unconstrained by the
realities of time, contradiction, causation, etc. can be found in dreaming.
Freud regarded dreams as “the royal road to a knowledge of the unconscious.”
Dreams are the disguised fulfillment of unconscious wishes. In extracting the
meaning of dreams through a process of interpretation, Freud relied on a
central distinction between the manifest content the dream as dreamt or as
remembered on waking and the latent content the unconscious dreamthoughts.
Freud held that interpretation via association to particular elements of the
manifest content reversed the process of dream construction, the dream-work in
which various mechanisms of distortion operated on the day’s residues
perceptions and thoughts stemming from the day before the dream was dreamt and
the latent dream-thoughts to produce the manifest dream. Prominent among the
mechanisms are the condensation in which many meanings are represented by a
single idea and displacement in which there is a shift of affect from a
significant and intense idea to an associated but otherwise insignificant one
also typical of neurotic symptoms, as well as considerations of
representability and secondary revision more specific to dream formation.
Symbolism is less prominent in Freud’s theory of dreams than is often thought;
indeed, the section on symbols appeared only as a later addition to The
Interpretation of Dreams 0. Freud explicitly rejected the ancient “dream book”
mode of interpretation in terms of fixed symbols, and believed one had to
recover the hidden meaning of a dream through the dreamer’s not the
interpreter’s associations to particular elements. Such associations are a part
of the process of free association, in which a patient is obliged to report to
the analyst all thoughts without censorship of any kind. The process is crucial
to psychoanalysis, which is both a technique of psychotherapy and a method of
investigation of the workings of the mind. Freud used the results of his
investigations to speculate about the origins of morality, religion, and
political authority. He tended to find their historical and psychological roots
in early stages of the development of the individual. Morality in particular he
traced to the internalization as one part of the resolution of the Oedpius
complex of parental prohibitions and demands, producing a conscience or
superego which is also the locus of self-observation and the ego-ideal. Such
identification by incorporation
introjection plays an important
role in character formation in general. The instinctual renunciation demanded
by morality and often achieved by repression Freud regarded as essential to the
order society needs to conduct its business. Civilization gets the energy for
the achievements of art and science by sublimation of the same instinctual
drives. But the costs of society and civilization to the individual in frustration,
unhappiness, and neurosis can be too high. Freud’s individual therapy was meant
to lead to the liberation of repressed energies which would not by itself
guarantee happiness; he hoped it might also provide energy to transform the
world and moderate its excess demands for restraint. But just as his individual
psychology was founded on the inevitability of internal conflict, in his social
thought he saw some limits especially on aggression the death instinct turned outward as
necessary and he remained pessimistic about the apparently endless struggle
reason must wage Civilization and Its Discontents, 0.
FUNCTIONALISM -- Grice’s
functionalism: a response to the dualist challenge -- dualism, the view that
reality consists of two disparate parts. The crux of dualism is an apparently
unbridgeable gap between two incommensurable orders of being that must be
reconciled if our assumption that there is a comprehensible universe is to be
justified. Dualism is exhibited in the pre-Socratic division between appearance
and reality; Plato’s realm of being containing eternal Ideas and realm of
becoming containing changing things; the medieval division between finite man
and infinite God; Descartes’s substance dualism of thinking mind and extended
matter; Hume’s separation of fact from value; Kant’s division between empirical
phenomena and transcendental noumena; the epistemological double-aspect theory
of James and Russell, who postulate a neutral substance that can be understood
in separate ways either as mind or brain; and Heidegger’s separation of being
and time that inspired Sartre’s contrast of being and nothingness. The doctrine
of two truths, the sacred and the profane or the religious and the secular, is
a dualistic response to the conflict between religion and science. Descartes’s
dualism is taken to be the source of the mindbody problem. If the mind is
active unextended thinking and the body is passive unthinking extension, how
can these essentially unlike and independently existing substances interact
causally, and how can mental ideas represent material things? How, in other
words, can the mind know and influence the body, and how can the body affect
the mind? Descartes said mind and body interact and that ideas represent
material things without resembling them, but dream argument dualism 244 244 could not explain how, and concluded
merely that God makes these things happen. Proposed dualist solutions to the
mindbody problem are Malebranche’s occasionalism mind and body do not interact
but God makes them appear to; Leibniz’s preestablished harmony among
noninteracting monads; and Spinoza’s property dualism of mutually exclusive but
parallel attributes expressing the one substance God. Recent mindbody dualists
are Popper and John C. Eccles. Monistic alternatives to dualism include
Hobbes’s view that the mental is merely the epiphenomena of the material;
Berkeley’s view that material things are collections of mental ideas; and the
contemporary materialist view of Smart, Armstrong, and Paul and Patricia Churchland
that the mind is the brain. A classic treatment of these matters is Arthur O.
Lovejoy’s The Revolt Against Dualism. Dualism is related to binary thinking,
i.e., to systems of thought that are two-valued, such as logic in which
theorems are valid or invalid, epistemology in which knowledge claims are true
or false, and ethics in which individuals are good or bad and their actions are
right or wrong. In The Quest for Certainty, Dewey finds that all modern
problems of philosophy derive from dualistic oppositions, particularly between
spirit and nature. Like Hegel, he proposes a synthesis of oppositions seen as
theses versus antitheses. Recent attacks on the view that dualistic divisions
can be explicitly described or maintained have been made by Vitters, who offers
instead a classification scheme based on overlapping family resemblances; by
Quine, who casts doubt on the division between analytic or formal truths based
on meanings and synthetic or empirical truths based on facts; and by Derrida,
who challenges our ability to distinguish between the subjective and the
objective. But despite the extremely difficult problems posed by ontological
dualism, and despite the cogency of many arguments against dualistic thinking,
Western philosophy continues to be predominantly dualistic, as witnessed by the
indispensable use of two-valued matrixes in logic and ethics and by the
intractable problem of rendering mental intentions in terms of material
mechanisms or vice versa. functional
dependence, a relationship between variable magnitudes especially physical
magnitudes and certain properties or processes. In modern physical science
there are two types of laws stating such relationships. 1 There are numerical
laws stating concomitant variation of certain quantities, where a variation in
any one is accompanied by variations in the others. An example is the law for
ideal gases: pV % aT, where p is the pressure of the gas, V its volume, T its
absolute temperature, and a a constant derived from the mass and the nature of
the gas. Such laws say nothing about the temporal order of the variations, and
tests of the laws can involve variation of any of the relevant magnitudes.
Concomitant variation, not causal sequence, is what is tested for. 2 Other
numerical laws state variations of physical magnitudes correlated with times.
Galileo’s law of free fall asserts that the change in the unit time of a freely
falling body in a vacuum in the direction of the earth is equal to gt, where g
is a constant and t is the time of the fall, and where the rate of time changes
of g is correlative with the temporal interval t. The law is true of any body
in a state of free fall and for any duration. Such laws are also called
“dynamical” because they refer to temporal processes usually explained by the
postulation of forces acting on the objects in question. functionalism, the
view that mental states are defined by their causes and effects. As a
metaphysical thesis about the nature of mental states, functionalism holds that
what makes an inner state mental is not an intrinsic property of the state, but
rather its relations to sensory stimulation input, to other inner states, and
to behavior output. For example, what makes an inner state a pain is its being
a type of state typically caused by pinpricks, sunburns, and so on, a type that
causes other mental states e.g., worry, and a type that causes behavior e.g.,
saying “ouch”. Propositional attitudes also are identified with functional
states: an inner state is a desire for water partly in virtue of its causing a
person to pick up a glass and drink its contents when the person believes that
the glass contains water. The basic distinction needed for functionalism is
that between role in terms of which a type of mental state is defined and
occupant the particular thing that occupies a role. Functional states exhibit
multiple realizability: in different kinds of beings humans, computers,
Martians, a particular kind of causal role may have different occupants e.g., the causal role definitive of a belief
that p, say, may be occupied by a neural state in a human, but occupied perhaps
by a hydraulic state in a Martian. Functionalism, like behaviorism, thus
entails that mental states may be shared by physically dissimilar systems.
Although functionalism does not automatically rule out the existence of
immaterial souls, its motivation has been to provide a materialistic account of
mentality. The advent of the computer gave impetus to functionalism. First, the
distinction between software and hardware suggested the distinction between
role function and occupant structure. Second, since computers are automated,
they demonstrate how inner states can be causes of output in the absence of a
homunculus i.e., a “little person” intelligently directing output. Third, the
Turing machine provided a model for one of the earliest versions of
functionalism. A Turing machine is defined by a table that specifies
transitions from current state and input to next state or to output. According
to Turing machine functionalism, any being with pscychological states has a
unique best description, and each psychological state is identical to a machine
table state relative to that description. To be in mental state type M is to
instantiate or realize Turing machine T in state S. Turing machine functionalism,
developed largely by Putnam, has been criticized by Putnam, Ned Block, and
Fodor. To cite just one serious problem: two machine table states and hence, according to Turing machine
functionalism, two psychological states
are distinct if they are followed by different states or by different
outputs. So, if a pinprick causes A to say “Ouch” and causes B to say “Oh,”
then, if Turing machine functionalism were true, A’s and B’s states of pain
would be different psychological states. But we do not individuate
psychological states so finely, nor should we: such fine-grained individuation
would be unsuitable for psychology. Moreover, if we assume that there is a path
from any state to any other state, Turing machine functionalism has the
unacceptable consequence that no two systems have any of their states in common
unless they have all their states in common. Perhaps the most prominent version
of functionalism is the causal theory of mind. Whereas Turing machine
functionalism is based on a technical computational or psychological theory,
the causal theory of mind relies on commonsense understanding: according to the
causal theory of mind, the concept of a mental state is the concept of a state
apt for bringing about certain kinds of behavior Armstrong. Mental state terms
are defined by the commonsense platitudes in which they appear David Lewis.
Philosophers can determine a priori what mental states are by conceptual
analysis or by definition. Then scientists determine what physical states
occupy the causal roles definitive of mental states. If it turned out that
there was no physical state that occupied the causal role of, say, pain i.e.,
was caused by pinpricks, etc., and caused worry, etc., it would follow, on the
causal theory, that pain does not exist. To be in mental state type M is to be
in a physical state N that occupies causal role R. A third version is
teleological or “homuncular” functionalism, associated with William G. Lycan
and early Dennett. According to homuncular functionalism, a human being is
analogous to a large corporation, made up of cooperating departments, each with
its own job to perform; these departments interpret stimuli and produce
behavioral responses. Each department at the highest subpersonal level is in
turn constituted by further units at a sub-subpersonal level and so on down
until the neurological level is reached. The roleoccupant distinction is thus
relativized to level: an occupant at one level is a role at the next level
down. On this view, to be in a mental state type M is to have a sub- . . .
subpersonal f-er that is in its characteristic state Sf. All versions of
functionalism face problems about the qualitative nature of mental states. The
difficulty is that functionalism individuates states in purely relational terms,
but the acrid odor of, say, a paper mill seems to have a non-relational,
qualitative character that functionalism misses altogether. If two people, on
seeing a ripe banana, are in states with the same causes and effects, then, by
functionalist definition, they are in the same mental state say, having a sensation of yellow. But it
seems possible that one has an “inverted spectrum” relative to the other, and
hence that their states are qualitatively different. Imagine that, on seeing
the banana, one of the two is in a state qualitatively indistinguishable from
the state that the other would be in on seeing a ripe tomato. Despite
widespread intuitions that such inverted spectra are possible, according to
functionalism, they are not. A related problem is that of “absent qualia.” The
population of China, or even the economy of Bolivia, could be functionally
equivalent to a human brain i.e., there
could be a function that mapped the relations between inputs, outputs, and
internal states of the population of China onto those of a human brain; yet the
population of China, no matter how its members interact with one another and
with other nations, intuitively does not have mental states. The status of
these arguments remains controversial.
fundamentum divisionis
Latin, ‘foundation of a division’, term in Scholastic logic and ontology
meaning ‘grounds for a distinction’. Some distinctions categorize separately
existing things, such as men and beasts. This is a real distinction, and the
fundamentum divisionis exists in reality. Some distinctions categorize things
that cannot exist separately but can be distinguished mentally, such as the
difference between being a human being and having a sense of humor, or the
difference between a soul and one of its powers, say, the power of thinking. A
mental distinction is also called a formal distinction. Duns Scotus is well
known for the idea of formalis distinctio cum fundamento ex parte rei a formal
distinction with a foundation in the thing, primarily in order to handle logical
problems with functionalism, analytical fundamentum divisionis 335 335 the Christian concept of God. God is
supposed to be absolutely simple; i.e., there can be no multiplicity of
composition in him. Yet, according to traditional theology, many properties can
be truly attributed to him. He is wise, good, and powerful. In order to
preserve the simplicity of God, Duns Scotus claimed that the difference between
wisdom, goodness, and power was only formal but still had some foundation in
God’s own being.
Futurum continens. –
Grice knew that his obsession with action was an obsession with the uncertainty
of a contingent future, alla Aristotle. Futurum -- future contingents, singular
events or states of affairs that may come to pass, and also may not come to
pass, in the future. There are three traditional problems involving future
contingents: the question of universal validity of the principle of bivalence,
the question of free will and determinism, and the question of foreknowledge.
The debate about future contingents in modern philosophical logic was revived
by Lukasiewicz’s work on three-valued logic. He thought that in order to avoid
fatalistic consequences, we must admit that the principle of bivalence for any
proposition, p, either p is true or not-p is true does not hold good for
propositions about future contingents. Many authors have considered this view
confused. According to von Wright, e.g., when propositions are said to be true
or false and ‘is’ in ‘it is true that’ is tenseless or atemporal, the illusion
of determinism does not arise. It has its roots in a tacit oscillation between
a temporal and an atemporal reading of the phrase ‘it is true’. In a
temporalized reading, or in its tensed variants such as ‘it was/will be/is
already true’, one can substitute, for ‘true’, other words like ‘certain’,
‘fixed’, or ‘necessary’. Applying this diachronic necessity to atemporal
predications of truth yields the idea of logical determinism. In contemporary
discussions of tense and modality, future contingents are often treated with
the help of a model of time as a line that breaks up into branches as it moves
from left to right i.e., from past to future. Although the conception of truth
at a moment has been found philosophically problematic, the model of historical
modalities and branching time as such is much used in works on freedom and
determination. Aristotle’s On Interpretation IX contains a classic discussion
of future contingents with the famous example of tomorrow’s sea battle. Because
of various ambiguities in the text and in Aristotle’s modal conceptions in
general, the meaning of the passage is in dispute. In the Metaphysics VI.3 and
in the Niocmachean Ethics III.5, Aristotle tries to show that not all things
are predetermined. The Stoics represented a causally deterministic worldview;
an ancient example of logical determinism is Diodorus Cronus’s famous master
argument against contingency. Boethius thought that Aristotle’s view can be
formulated as follows: the principle of bivalence is universally valid, but
propositions about future contingents, unlike those about past and present
things, do not obey the stronger principle according to which each proposition
is either determinately true or determinately false. A proposition is
indeterminately true as long as the conditions that make it true are not yet
fixed. This was the standard Latin doctrine from Abelard to Aquinas. Similar
discussions occurred in Arabic commentaries on On Interpretation. In the
fourteenth century, many thinkers held that Aristotle abandoned bivalence for
future contingent propositions. This restriction was usually refuted, but it
found some adherents like Peter Aureoli. Duns Scotus and Ockham heavily
criticized the Boethian-Thomistic view that God can know future contingents only
because the flux of time is present to divine eternity. According to them, God
contingently foreknows free acts. Explaining this proved to be a very
cumbersome task. Luis de Molina 15351600 suggested that God knows what possible
creatures would do in any possible situation. This “middle knowledge” theory
about counterfactuals of freedom has remained a living theme in philosophy of
religion; analogous questions are treated in theories of subjunctive
reasoning.
futurum
indicativum: The Grecians called it just ‘horistike klesis.’ The
Romans transliterated as modus definitivus, inclination anima affectations
demonstrans.’ But they had other terms, indicativus, finitus, finitivus, and
pronuntiativus. f. H. P. Grice and D. F. Pears, “Predicting and deciding.” The
future is essentially involved in “E communicates that p,” i. e. E, the
emissor, intends that his addressee, in a time later than t, will come to
believe this or that. Grice is
especially concerned with the future for his analysis of the communicatum.
“Close the door!” By uttering “Close the door!,” U means that A is to close the
door – in the future. So Grice spends HOURS exploring how one can have
justification to have an intention about a future event. Grice is aware of the
‘shall.’ Grice uses ‘shall’ in the first person to mean wha the calls ‘futurum
indicativum.’ (He considers the case of the ‘shall’ in the second and third
persons in his analysis of mode). What are the conditions for the use of
“shall” in the first person. “I shall close the door” may be predictable. It is
in the indicative mode. “Thou shalt close the door,” and “He shall close the
door” are in the imperative mode, or rather they correspond to the ‘futurum
intentionale.’ Since Grice is an analytic
philosopher, he specifies the analysis in the third person (“U means that…”)
one has to be careful. For ‘futurum indicativum’ we have ‘shall’ in the first
person, and ‘will’ in the second and third persons. So for the first group, U
means that he will go. In the second group, U means that his addressee or a
third party shall go. Grice adopts a subscript variant, stick with ‘will,’ but
add the mode afterwards: so will-ind. will be ‘futurum indicativum,’ and
will-int. will be futurum intentionale. The OED has it as “shall,”
and defines as a Germanic preterite-present strong verb. In Old English,
it is “sceal,” and which the OED renders as “to owe (money,” 1425 Hoccleve Min.
Poems, The leeste ferthyng þat y men shal. To owe (allegiance); 1649 And by
that feyth I shal to god and yow; followed by an infinitive, without to. Except
for a few instances of shall will, shall may (mowe), "shall conne" in
the 15th c., the infinitive after shall is always either that of a principal
verb or of have or be; The present tense shall; in general statements of what
is right or becoming, = ought, superseded by the past subjunctive should; in
OE. the subjunctive present sometimes occurs in this use; 1460 Fortescue Abs.
and Lim. Mon. The king shall often times send his judges to punish rioters and
risers. 1562 Legh Armory; Whether are Roundells of all suche coloures, as ye
haue spoken of here before? or shall they be Namesd Roundelles of those
coloures? In OE. and occas. in Middle English used to express necessity of
various kinds. For the many shades of meaning in Old English see Bosworth and
Toller), = must, "must needs", "have to", "am
compelled to", etc.; in stating a necessary condition: = `will have to,
`must (if something else is to happen). 1596 Shaks. Merch. V. i. i. 116 You
shall seeke all day ere you finde them, & when you haue them they are
not worth the search. 1605 Shaks. Lear. He that parts vs, shall bring a Brand
from Heauen. c In hypothetical clause, accompanying the statement of a
necessary condition: = `is to. 1612 Bacon Ess., Greatn. Kingd., Neither must
they be too much broken of it, if they shall be preserued in vigor; ndicating
what is appointed or settled to take place = the mod. `is to, `am to, etc. 1600
Shaks. A.Y.L. What is he that shall buy his flocke and pasture? 1625 in Ellis
Orig. Lett. Ser. "Tomorrow His Majesty will be present to begin the Parliament which is thought
shall be removed to Oxford; in commands or instructions; n the second person,
“shall” is equivalent to an imperative. Chiefly in Biblical language, of divine
commandments, rendering the jussive future of the Hebrew and Vulgate. In Old
English the imperative mode is used in the ten commandments. 1382 Wyclif Exod.
Thow shalt not tak the Names of the Lord thi God in veyn. So Coverdale, etc. b)
In expositions: you shall understand, etc. (that). c) In the formula you shall
excuse (pardon) me. (now "must"). 1595 Shaks. John. Your Grace shall
pardon me, I will not backe. 1630 R. Johnsons Kingd. and Commw. 191 You shall
excuse me, for I eat no flesh on Fridayes; n the *third* person. 1744 in Atkyns
Chanc. Cases (1782) III. 166 The words shall and may in general acts of
parliament, or in private constitutions, are to be construed imperatively, they
must remove them; in the second and third persons, expressing the determination
by the Griceian utterer to bring about some action, event, or state of things
in the future, or (occasionally) to refrain from hindering what is otherwise
certain to take place, or is intended by another person; n the second person.
1891 J. S. Winter Lumley. If you would rather not stay then, you shall go down
to South Kensington Square then; in third person. 1591 Shaks. Two Gent. Verona
shall not hold thee. 1604 Shaks. Oth. If there be any cunning Crueltie, That
can torment him much, It shall be his. 1891 J. S. Winter Lumley xiv, `Oh, yes,
sir, she shall come back, said the nurse. `Ill take care of that. `I will come
back, said Vere; in special interrogative uses, a) in the *first* person, used
in questions to which the expected answer is a command, direction, or counsel,
or a resolve on the speakers own part. a) in questions introduced by an
interrogative pronoun (in oblique case), adverb, or adverbial phrase. 1600
Fairfax Tasso. What shall we doe? shall we be gouernd still, By this false
hand? 1865 Kingsley Herew. Where shall we stow the mare? b) in categorical
questions, often expressing indignant reprobation of a suggested course of
action, the implication (or implicature, or entailment) being that only a
negative (or, with negative question an affirmative) answer is conceivable.
1611 Shaks. Wint. T. Shall I draw the Curtaine? 1802 Wordsw. To the Cuckoo i, O
Cuckoo! shall I call thee Bird, Or but a wandering Voice? 1891 J. S. Winter
Lumley `Are you driving, or shall I call you a cab? `Oh, no; Im driving, thanks.
c) In *ironical* affirmative in exclamatory sentence, equivalent to the above
interrogative use, cf. Ger. soll. 1741 Richardson Pamela, A pretty thing truly!
Here I, a poor helpless Girl, raised from Poverty and Distress, shall put on
Lady-airs to a Gentlewoman born. d) to stand shall I, shall I (later shill I,
shall I: v. shilly-shally), to be at shall I, shall I (not): to be vacillating,
to shilly-shally. 1674 R. Godfrey Inj. and Ab. Physic Such Medicines. that will
not stand shall I? shall I? but will fall to work on the Disease presently. b
Similarly in the *third* person, where the Subjects represents or includes the
utterer, or when the utterer is placing himself at anothers point of view. 1610
Shaks. Temp., Hast thou (which art but aire) a touch, a feeling Of their
afflictions, and shall not my selfe, One of their kinde be kindlier moud then
thou art? In the second and third person, where the expected answer is a
decision on the part of the utterer or of some person OTHER than the Subjects.
The question often serves as an impassioned repudiation of a suggestion (or
implicature) that something shall be permitted. 1450 Merlin `What shal be his
Names? `I will, quod she, `that it haue Names after my fader. 1600 Shaks.
A.Y.L.; What shall he haue that kild the Deare? 1737 Alexander Pope,
translating Horaces Epistle, And say, to which shall our applause belong, this
new court jargon, or the good old song? 1812 Crabbe Tales, Shall a wife
complain? In indirect question. 1865 Kingsley Herew, Let her say what shall be
done with it; as a mere auxiliary, forming, with present infinitive, the
future, and (with perfect infinitive) the future perfect tense. In Old English,
the notion of the future tense is ordinarily expressed by the present tense. To
prevent ambiguity, wile (will) is not unfrequently used as a future auxiliary,
sometimes retaining no trace of its initial usage, connected with the faculty
of volition, and cognate indeed with volition. On the other hand, sceal
(shall), even when rendering a Latin future, can hardly be said to have been
ever a mere future tense-sign in Old English. It always expressed something of
its original notion of obligation or necessity, so Hampshire is wrong in saying
I shall climb Mt. Everest is predictable. In Middle English, the present early
ceases to be commonly employed in futural usage, and the future is expressed by
shall or will, the former being much more common. The usage as to the
choice between the two auxiliaries, shall and will, has varied from time to
time. Since the middle of the seventeenth century, with Wallis, mere
predictable futurity is expressed in the *first* person by shall, in the second
and third by will, and vice versa. In oratio obliqua, usage allows either the
retention of the auxiliary actually used by the original utterer, or the
substitution of that which is appropriate to the point of view of the uttering
reporting; in Old English, ‘sceal,; while retaining its primary usage, serves
as a tense-sign in announcing a future event as fated or divinely decreed, cf.
Those spots mean measle. Hence shall has always been the auxiliary used, in all
persons, for prophetic or oracular announcements of the future, and for solemn
assertions of the certainty of a future event. 1577 in Allen Martyrdom Campion;
The queene neither ever was, nor is, nor ever shall be the head of the Church
of England. 1601 Shaks. Jul. C. Now do I Prophesie. A Curse shall light vpon
the limbes of men. b In the first person, "shall" has, from the early
ME. period, been the normal auxiliary for expressing mere futurity, without any
adventitious notion. (a) Of events conceived as independent of the volition of
the utterer. To use will in these cases is now a mark of, not
public-school-educated Oxonian, but Scottish, Irish, provincial, or extra-British
idiom. 1595 in Cath. Rec. Soc. Publ. V. 357 My frend, yow and I shall play no
more at Tables now. 1605 Shaks. Macb. When shall we three meet againe? 1613
Shaks. Hen. VIII, Then wee shall haue em, Talke vs to silence. 1852 Mrs. Stowe
Uncle Toms C.; `But what if you dont hit? `I shall hit, said George coolly; of
voluntary action or its intended result. Here I shall or we shall is always
admissible except where the notion of a present, as distinguished from a
previous, decision or consent is to be expressed, in which case ‘will’ shall be
used. Further, I shall often expresses a determination insisted on in spite of
opposition. In the 16th c. and earlier, I shall often occurs where I will would
now be used. 1559 W. Cunningham Cosmogr. Glasse, This now shall I alway kepe
surely in memorye. 1601 Shaks. Alls Well; Informe him so tis our will he
should.-I shall my liege. 1885 Ruskin On Old Road, note: Henceforward I shall
continue to spell `Ryme without our wrongly added h. c In the *second* person,
shall as a mere future auxiliary appears never to have been usual, but in
categorical questions it is normal, e.g. Shall you miss your train? I am afraid
you will. d In the *third* person, superseded by will, except when anothers
statement or expectation respecting himself is reported in the third person,
e.g. He conveys that he shall not have time to write. Even in this case will is
still not uncommon, but in some contexts leads to serious ambiguity. It might
be therefore preferable, to some, to use ‘he shall’ as the indirect rendering
of ‘I shall.’ 1489 Caxton Sonnes of Aymon ii. 64 Yf your fader come agayn from
the courte, he shall wyll yelde you to the kynge Charlemayne. 1799 J. Robertson
Agric. Perth, The effect of the statute labour
has always been, now is, and probably shall continue to be, less
productive than it might. Down to the eighteenth century, shall, the auxiliary
appropriate to the first person, is sometimes used when the utterer refers to
himself in the third person. Cf. the formula: `And your petitioner shall ever
pray. 1798 Kemble Let. in Pearsons Catal. Mr. Kemble presents his respectful
compliments to the Proprietors of the `Monthly Mirror, and shall have great
pleasure at being at all able to aid them; in negative, or virtually negative,
and interrogative use, shall often = will be able to. 1600 Shaks. Sonn. lxv:
How with this rage shall beautie hold a plea. g) Used after a hypothetical
clause or an imperative sentence in a statementsof a result to be expected from
some action or occurrence. Now (exc. in the *first* person) usually replaced by
will. But shall survives in literary use. 1851 Dasent Jest and Earnest, Visit
Rome and you shall find him [the Pope] mere carrion. h) In clause expressing
the object of a promise, or of an expectation accompanied by hope or fear, now
only where shall is the ordinary future auxiliary, but down to the nineteenth
century shall is often preferred to will in the second and third persons. 1628
in Ellis Orig. Lett. Ser., He is confident that the blood of Christ shall wash
away his sins. 1654 E. Nicholas in N. Papers, I hope neither your Cosen Wat.
Montagu nor Walsingham shall be
permitted to discourse with the D. of Gloucester; in impersonal phrases,
"it shall be well, needful", etc. (to do so and so). (now "will").
j) shall be, added to a future date in clauses measuring time. 1617 Sir T.
Wentworth in Fortescue Papers. To which purpose my late Lord Chancelour gave
his direction about the 3. of Decembre shallbe-two-yeares; in the idiomatic use
of the future to denote what ordinarily or occasionally occurs under specified
conditions, shall was formerly the usual auxiliary. In the *second* and *third*
persons, this is now somewhat formal or rhetorical. Ordinary language
substitutes will or may. Often in antithetic statements coupled by an
adversative conjunction or by and with adversative force. a in the first
person. 1712 Steele Spect. In spite of all my Care, I shall every now and then
have a saucy Rascal ride by reconnoitring
under my Windows. b) in the *second* person. 1852 Spencer Ess. After
knowing him for years, you shall suddenly discover that your friends nose is
slightly awry. c) in the *third* person. 1793 W. Roberts Looker-On, One man
shall approve the same thing that another man shall condemn. 1870 M. Arnold St.
Paul and Prot. It may well happen that a man who lives and thrives under a
monarchy shall yet theoretically disapprove the principle of monarchy. Usage
No. 10: in hypothetical, relative, and temporal clauses denoting a future
contingency, the future auxiliary is shall for all persons alike. Where no
ambiguity results, however, the present tense is commonly used for the future,
and the perfect for the future-perfect. The use of shall, when not required for
clearness, is, Grice grants, apt to sound pedantic by non Oxonians. Formerly
sometimes used to express the sense of a present subjunctive. a) in
hypothetical clauses. (shall I = if I shall) 1680 New Hampsh. Prov. Papers, If
any Christian shall speak contempteously of the Holy Scriptures, such person shall be punished. b) in relative clauses,
where the antecedent denotes an as yet undetermined person or thing: 1811
Southey Let., The minister who shall first become a believer in that book will obtain a higher reputation than ever
statesman did before him. 1874 R. Congreve Ess. We extend our sympathies to the
unborn generations which shall follow us on this earth; in temporal clauses:
1830 Laws of Cricket in Nyren Yng. Cricketers Tutor, If in striking, or at any
other time, while the ball shall be in play, both his feet be over the
popping-crease; in clauses expressing the purposed result of some action, or
the object of a desire, intention, command, or request, often admitting of
being replaced by may. In Old English, and occasionally as late as the seventeenth
century, the present subjunctive was used exactly as in Latin. a) in final
clause usually introduced by that. In this use modern idiom prefers should (22
a): see quot. 1611 below, and the appended remarks. 1879 M. Pattison Milton At
the age of nine and twenty, Milton has already determined that this lifework
shall be an epic poem; in relative clause: 1599 Shaks. Hen. V, ii. iv. 40: As
Gardeners doe with Ordure hide those Roots that shall first spring. The choice
between should and would follows the same as shall and will as future
auxiliaries, except that should must sometimes be avoided on account of
liability to be misinterpreted as = `ought to. In present usage, should occurs
mainly in the first person. In the other persons it follows the use of shall.
III Elliptical and quasi-elliptical uses. Usage No. 24: with ellipsis of verb
of motion: = `shall go; he use is common in OHG. and OS., and in later HG.,
LG., and Du. In the Scandinavian languages it is also common, and instances
occur in MSw.] 1596 Shaks. 1 Hen. IV, That with our small coniunction we should
on. 1598 Shaks. Merry W. If the bottome were as deepe as hell, I shold down; n
questions, what shall = `what shall (it) profit, `what good shall (I) do. Usage
No. 26: with the sense `is due, `is proper, `is to be given or applied. Cf. G.
soll. Usage No. 27: a) with ellipsis of active infinitive to be supplied from
the context. 1892 Mrs. H. Ward David Grieve, `No, indeed, I havnt got all I
want, said Lucy `I never shall, neither; if I shall. Now dial. 1390 Gower Conf.
II. 96: Doun knelende on mi kne I take leve, and if I schal, I kisse hire. 1390
Gower Conf., II. 96: I wolde kisse hire eftsones if I scholde. 1871 Earle
Philol. Engl. Tongue 203: The familiar proposal to carry a basket, I will if I
shall, that is, I am willing if you will command me; I will if so required.
1886 W. Somerset Word-bk. Ill warn our Tomll do it vor ee, nif he shall-i.e. if
you wish. c) with generalized ellipsis in proverbial phrase: needs must that
needs shall = `he must whom fate compels. Usage No. 28: a) with ellipsis of do
(not occurring in the context). 1477 Norton Ord. Alch., O King that shall These
Workes! b) the place of the inf. is sometimes supplied by that or so placed at
the beginning of the sentence. The construction may be regarded as an ellipsis
of "do". It is distinct from the use (belonging to 27) in which so
has the sense of `thus, `likewise, or `also. In the latter there is usually
inversion, as so shall I. 1888 J. S. Winter Bootles Childr. iv: I should like
to see her now shes grown up. `So you shall. Usage No. 29: with ellipsis of be
or passive inf., or with so in place of this (where the preceding context has
is, was, etc.). 1615 J. Chamberlain in Crt. And Times Jas.; He is not yet
executed, nor I hear not when he shall. Surely he may not will that he be
executed.
futurum intentionale: Surely intention has nothing to do with predictable truth.
If Smith promises Jones a job – he intends that Jones get a job. Then the world
explodes, so Jones does not get the job. Kant, Austin, or Grice, don’t care. A
philosopher is not a scientist. He is into ‘conceptual matters,’ about what is
to have a good intention, not whether the intention, in a future scenario, is
realised or not. If they are interested in ‘tense,’ as Prior was as Grice was
with his time-relative identity, it’s still because in the PRESENT, the emissor
emits a future-tense utterance. The future figures more prominently than
anything because in “Emissor communicates that p” there is the FUTURE ESSENTIAL.
The emissor intends that his addressee in a time later than the present will do
this or that. While Grice is always looking to cross the
credibility/desirability divide, there is a feature that is difficult to cross
in the bridge of asses. This is the shall vs. will. Grice is aware that ‘will,’
in the FIRST person, is not a matter of prediction. When Grice says “I will go
to Harborne,” that’s not a prediction. He firmly contrasts it with “I shall go
to Harborne” which is a perfect prediction in the indicative mode. “I will go
to Harborne” is in the ‘futurum intentionale.’ Grice is also aware that in the
SECOND and THIRD persons, ‘will’ reports something that the utterer must judge
unpredictable. An utterance like “Thou wilt go to London” and “He will go to
London” is in the ‘futurum indicativus.’ This is one nuance that Prichard
forgets in the analysis of ‘willing’ that Grice eventually adopts. Prichard
uses ‘will’ derivatively, and followed by a ‘that’-clause. Prichard quotes from
the New-World, where the dialect is slightly different. For William James had
said, “I will that the distant table slides over the floor toward me. And it
does not.” Since James is using ‘will’ in the first person, the utterance is
indeed NOT in the indicative, but the ‘intentional’ mode. In the case of the
‘communicatum,’ things get complicated, since U intends that A will believe
that… In which case, U’s intention (and thus will) is directed towards the
‘will’ of his addressee, too, even if it is merely to adopt a ‘belief.’ So what
would be the primary uses of the ‘will.’ In the first person, “I will go to
Harborne” is in the futurum intentionale. It is used to report the utterer’s
will. In the second and third person – “Thou will go to Harborne” and “He will
go to Harborne,” the utterer uses the futurum indicativum and utters a statement
which is predictable. Since analytic
philosophers specify the analysis in the third person (“U means that…”) one has
to be careful. For ‘futurum intentionale’ we have ‘will’ in the first person,
and ‘shall’ in the second and third persons. So for the first group, U means
that he SHALL go. In the second group, U means that his addressee or a third
party WILL go. Grice adopts a subscript variant, stick with ‘will,’ but add the
mode afterwards: so will-ind. will be ‘futurum indicativum,’ and will-int. will
be futurum intentionale. Grice distinguishes the ‘futurum imperativum.’ This
may be seen as a sub-class of the ‘futurum intentionale,’ as applied to the
second and third persons, to avoid the idea that one can issue a
‘self-command.’ Grice has a futurum imperativum, in Latin ending in -tō(te),
used to request someone to do something, or if something else happens first.
“Sī quid acciderit, scrībitō. If anything happens, write to me' (Cicero). ‘Ubi nōs
lāverimus, lavātō.’ 'When*we* have finished washing, *you* get washed.’
(Terence). ‘Crūdam si edēs, in acētum intinguitō.’ ‘If you eat cabbage raw, dip
it in vinegar.’ (Cato). ‘Rīdētō multum quī tē, Sextille, cinaedum dīxerit et
digitum porrigitō medium.’ 'Laugh loudly at anyone who calls you camp,
Sextillus, and stick up your middle finger at him.' (Martial). In Latin, some verbs have only a futurum
imperativum, e. g., scītō 'know', mementō 'remember'. In Latin, there is also a
third person imperative also ending in -tō, plural -ntō exists. It is used in
very formal contexts such as laws. ‘Iūsta imperia suntō, īsque cīvēs pārentō.’
'Orders must be just, and citizens must obey them' (Cicero). Other ways of
expressing a command or request are made with expressions such as cūrā ut 'take
care to...', fac ut 'see to it that...' or cavē nē 'be careful that you
don't...' Cūrā ut valeās. 'Make sure you keep well' (Cicero). Oddly, in Roman,
the futurum indicativum can be used for a polite commands. ‘Pīliae salūtem dīcēs
et Atticae.’ 'Will you please give my
regards to Pilia and Attica?' (Cicero. The OED has will, would. It is traced to
Old English willan, pres.t. wille, willaþ, pa. t. wolde. Grice was especially
interested to check Jamess and Prichards use of willing that, Prichards shall
will and the will/shall distinction; the present tense will; transitive uses,
with simple obj. or obj. clause; occas. intr. 1 trans. with simple obj.:
desire, wish for, have a mind to, `want (something); sometimes implying also `intend,
purpose. 1601 Shaks. (title) Twelfe Night, Or what you will. 1654 Whitlock
Zootomia 44 Will what befalleth, and befall what will. 1734 tr. Rollins Anc.
Hist. V. 31 He that can do what ever he will is in great danger of willing what
he ought not. b intr. with well or ill, or trans. with sbs. of similar meaning
(e.g. good, health), usually with dat. of person: Wish (or intend) well or ill
(to some one), feel or cherish good-will or ill-will. Obs. (cf. will v.2 1 b).
See also well-willing; to will well that: to be willing that. 1483 Caxton Gold.
Leg. I wyl wel that thou say, and yf thou say ony good, thou shalt be pesybly
herde. Usage No. 2: trans. with obj. clause (with vb. in pres. subj., or in
periphrastic form with should), or acc. and inf.: Desire, wish; sometimes
implying also `intend, purpose (that something be done or happen). 1548 Hutten
Sum of Diuinitie K viij, God wylle all men to be saued; enoting expression
(usually authoritative) of a wish or intention: Determine, decree, ordain,
enjoin, give order (that something be done). 1528 Cromwell in Merriman Life and
Lett. (1902) I. 320 His grace then wille that thellection of a new Dean shalbe
emonges them of the colledge; spec. in a direction or instruction in ones will
or testament; hence, to direct by will (that something be done). 1820 Giffords
Compl. Engl. Lawyer. I do hereby will and direct that my executrix..do excuse
and release the said sum of 100l. to him;
figurative usage. of an abstract thing (e.g. reason, law): Demands,
requires. 1597 Shaks. 2 Hen. IV, Our Battaile is more full of Namess then yours
Then Reason will, our hearts should be as good. Usage No. 4 transf. (from 2).
Intends to express, means; affirms, maintains. 1602 Dolman La Primaud. Fr.
Acad. Hee will that this authority should be for a principle of demonstration.
2 With dependent infinitive (normally without "to"); desire to, wish
to, have a mind to (do something); often also implying intention. 1697 Ctess
DAunoys Trav. I will not write to you often, because I will always have a stock
of News to tell you, which..is pretty long in picking up. 1704 Locke Hum.
Und. The great Encomiasts of the
Chineses, do all to a man agree and will convince us that the Sect of the
Literati are Atheists. 6 In relation to anothers desire or requirement, or to
an obligation of some kind: Am (is, are) disposed or willing to, consent to;
†in early use sometimes = deign or condescend to.With the (rare and obs.)
imper. use, as in quot. 1490, cf. b and the corresponding negative use in 12 b.
1921 Times Lit. Suppl. 10 Feb. 88/3 Literature thrives where people will read
what they do not agree with, if it is good. b In 2nd person, interrog., or in a
dependent clause after beg or the like, expressing a request (usually
courteous; with emphasis, impatient). 1599 Shaks. Hen. V, ii. i. 47 Will you
shogge off? 1605 1878 Hardy Ret. Native v. iii, O, O, O,..O, will you have
done! Usage No. 7 Expressing voluntary action, or conscious intention directed
to the doing of what is expressed by the principal verb (without temporal
reference as in 11, and without emphasis as in 10): = choose to (choose v. B. 3
a). The proper word for this idea, which cannot be so precisely expressed by
any other. 1685 Baxter Paraphr., When God will tell us we shall know. Usage No.
8 Expressing natural disposition to do something, and hence habitual action:
Has the habit, or `a way, of --ing; is addicted or accustomed to --ing;
habitually does; sometimes connoting `may be expected to (cf. 15). 1865 Ruskin
Sesame, Men, by their nature, are prone to fight; they will fight for any
cause, or for none; expressing potentiality, capacity, or sufficiency: Can,
may, is able to, is capable of --ing; is (large) enough or sufficient to.†it
will not be: it cannot be done or brought to pass; it is all in vain. So, †will
it not be? 1833 N. Arnott Physics, The heart will beat after removal from the
body. Usage No. 10 As a strengthening of sense 7, expressing determination,
persistence, and the like (without temporal reference as in 11); purposes to,
is determined to. 1539 Bible (Great) Isa. lxvi. 6, I heare ye voyce of the
Lorde, that wyll rewarde, etc; recompence his enemyes; emphatically. Is fully
determined to; insists on or persists in --ing: sometimes with mixture of sense
8. (In 1st pers. with implication of futurity, as a strengthening of sense 11
a. Also fig. = must inevitably, is sure to. 1892 E. Reeves Homeward Bound viii.
239, I have spent 6,000 francs to come here..and I will see it! c In phr. of
ironical or critical force referring to anothers assertion or opinion. Now
arch. exc. in will have it; 1591 Shaks. 1 Hen. VI, This is a Riddling Merchant
for the nonce, He will be here, and yet he is not here. 1728 Chambers Cycl.,
Honey, Some naturalists will have honey to be of a different quality, according
to the difference of the flowers..the bees suck it from. Also, as auxiliary of
the future tense with implication (entailment rather than cancellable
implicatum) of intention, thus distinguished from ‘shall,’ v. B. 8, where see
note); in 1st person: sometimes in slightly stronger sense = intend to, mean
to. 1600 Shaks. A.Y.L., To morrow will we be married. 1607 Shaks. Cor., Ile run
away Till I am bigger, but then Ile fight. 1777 Clara Reeve Champion of Virtue,
Never fear it..I will speak to Joseph about it. b In 2nd and 3rd pers., in
questions or indirect statements. 1839 Lane Arab. Nts., I will cure thee without giving thee to drink
any potion When King Yoonán heard his words, he..said.., How wilt thou do this?
c will do (with omission of "I"): an expression of willingness to
carry out a request. Cf. wilco. colloq. 1967 L. White Crimshaw Memorandum, `And
find out where the bastard was `Will do, Jim said. 13 In 1st pers., expressing
immediate intention: "I will" = `I am now going to, `I proceed at
once to. 1885 Mrs. Alexander At Bay, Very well; I will wish you good-evening. b
In 1st pers. pl., expressing a proposal: we will (†wule we) = `let us. 1798
Coleridge Nightingale 4 Come, we will rest on this old mossy bridge!, c
figurative, as in It will rain, (in 3rd pers.) of a thing: Is ready to, is on
the point of --ing. 1225 Ancr. R. A treou þet wule uallen, me underset hit mid
on oðer treou. 14 In 2nd and 3rd pers., as auxiliary expressing mere futurity,
forming (with pres. inf.) the future, and (with pf. inf.) the future pf. tense:
corresponding to "shall" in the 1st pers. (see note s.v. shall v. B.
8). 1847 Tennyson Princess iii. 12 Rest, rest, on mothers breast, Father will
come to thee soon. b As auxiliary of future substituted for the imper. in mild
injunctions or requests. 1876 Ruskin St. Marks Rest. That they should use their
own balances, weights, and measures; (not by any means false ones, you will
please to observe). 15 As auxiliary of future expressing a contingent event, or
a result to be expected, in a supposed case or under particular conditions
(with the condition expressed by a conditional, temporal, or imper. clause, or
otherwise implied). 1861 M. Pattison Ess.
The lover of the Elizabethan drama will readily recal many such
allusions; b with pers.sSubjects (usually 1st pers. sing.), expressing a
voluntary act or choice in a supposed case, or a conditional promise or
undertaking: esp. in asseverations, e.g. I will die sooner than, I’ll be hanged
if, etc.). 1898 H. S. Merriman Rodens Corner. But I will be hanged if I see
what it all means, now; xpressing a determinate or necessary consequence
(without the notion of futurity). 1887 Fowler Deductive Logic, From what has
been said it will be seen that I do not agree with Mr. Mill. Mod. If, in a
syllogism, the middle term be not distributed in either premiss, there will be
no conclusion; ith the notion of futurity obscured or lost: = will prove or
turn out to, will be found on inquiry to; may be supposed to, presumably does.
Hence (chiefly Sc. and north. dial.) in estimates of amount, or in uncertain or
approximate statements, the future becoming equivalent to a present with
qualification: e.g. it will be = `I think it is or `it is about; what will that
be? = `what do you think that is? 1584 Hornby Priory in Craven Gloss. Where on
40 Acres there will be xiij.s. iv.d. per acre yerely for rent. 1791 Grose Olio
(1792) 106, I believe he will be an Irishman. 1791 Grose Olio. C. How far is it
to Dumfries? W. It will be twenty miles. 1812 Brackenridge Views Louisiana, The
agriculture of this territory will be very similar to that of Kentucky. 1876
Whitby Gloss. sThis word we have only once heard, and that will be twenty years
ago. 16 Used where "shall" is now the normal auxiliary, chiefly in
expressing mere futurity: since 17th c. almost exclusively in Scottish, Irish,
provincial, or extra-British use (see shall. 1602 Shaks. Ham. I will win for
him if I can: if not, Ile gaine nothing but my shame, and the odde hits. 1825
Scott in Lockhart Ballantyne-humbug. I expect we will have some good singing.
1875 E. H. Dering Sherborne. `Will I start, sir? asked the Irish groom. Usage
No. 3 Elliptical and quasi-elliptical uses; n absol. use, or with ellipsis of
obj. clause as in 2: in meaning corresponding to senses 5-7.if you will is
sometimes used parenthetically to qualify a word or phrase: = `if you wish it
to be so called, `if you choose or prefer to call it so. 1696 Whiston The.
Earth. Gravity depends entirely on the constant and efficacious, and, if you
will, the supernatural and miraculous Influence of Almighty God. 1876 Ruskin
St. Marks Rest. Very savage! monstrous! if you will. b In parenthetic phr. if
God will (†also will God, rarely God will), God willing: if it be the will of
God, `D.V.In OE. Gode willi&asg.ende (will v.2) = L. Deo volente. 1716
Strype in Thoresbys Lett. Next week, God willing, I take my journey to my
Rectory in Sussex; fig. Demands, requires (absol. or ellipt. use of 3 c). 1511
Reg. Privy Seal Scot. That na seculare personis have intrometting with thaim
uther wais than law will; I will well: I assent, `I should think so indeed.
(Cf. F. je veux bien.) Usage No. 18: with ellipsis of a vb. of motion. 1885
Bridges Eros and Psyche Aug. I will to thee oer the stream afloat. Usage No.
19: with ellipsis of active inf. to be supplied from the context. 1836 Dickens
Sk. Boz, Steam Excurs., `Will you go on deck? `No, I will not. This was said
with a most determined air. 1853 Dickens Bleak Ho. lii, I cant believe it. Its
not that I dont or I wont. I cant! 1885 Mrs. Alexander Valeries Fate vi, `Do
you know that all the people in the house will think it very shocking of me to
walk with you?.. `The deuce they will!; With generalized ellipsis, esp. in
proverbial saying (now usually as in quot. 1562, with will for would). 1639 J.
Clarke Paroem. 237 He that may and will not, when he would he shall not. c With
so or that substituted for the omitted inf. phr.: now usually placed at the
beginning of the sentence. 1596 Shaks. Tam. Shr. Hor. I promist we would beare
his charge of wooing Gremio. And so we wil. d Idiomatically used in a
qualifying phr. with relative, equivalent to a phr. with indef. relative in
-ever; often with a thing as subj., becoming a mere synonym of may: e.g. shout
as loud as you will = `however loud you (choose to) shout; come what will =
`whatever may come; be that as it will = `however that may be. 1732 Pope Mor.
Ess. The ruling Passion, be it what it will, The ruling Passion conquers Reason
still. 20 With ellipsis of pass. inf. A. 1774 Goldsm. Surv. Exp. Philos. The
airs force is compounded of its swiftness and density, and as these are
encreased, so will the force of the wind; in const. where the ellipsis may be
either of an obj. clause or of an inf. a In a disjunctive qualifying clause or
phr. usually parenthetic, as whether he will or no, will he or not, (with pron.
omitted) will or no, (with or omitted) will he will he not, will he nill he
(see VI. below and willy-nilly), etc.In quot. 1592 vaguely = `one way or
another, `in any case. For the distinction between should and would, v. note
s.v. shall; in a noun-clause expressing the object of desire, advice, or
request, usually with a person as subj., implying voluntary action as the
desired end: thus distinguished from should, which may be used when the persons
will is not in view. Also (almost always after wish) with a thing as Subjects,
in which case should can never be substituted because it would suggest the idea
of command or compulsion instead of mere desire. Cf. shall; will; willest;
willeth; wills; willed (wIld); also: willian, willi, wyll, wille, wil, will,
willode, will, wyllede, wylled, willyd, ied, -it, -id, willed; wijld, wilde,
wild, willid, -yd, wylled,willet, willed; willd(e, wild., OE. willian wk. vb. =
German “willen.” f. will sb.1, 1 trans. to wish, desire; sometimes with
implication of intention: = will. 1400 Lat. and Eng. Prov. He þt a lytul me
3euyth to me wyllyth optat longe lyffe. 1548 Udall, etc. Erasm. Par. Matt. v.
21-24 Who so euer hath gotten to hymselfe the charitie of the gospell, whyche
wylleth wel to them that wylleth yll. 1581 A. Hall Iliad, By Mineruas helpe,
who willes you all the ill she may. A. 1875 Tennyson Q. Mary i. iv, A great
party in the state Wills me to wed her; To assert, affirm: = will v.1 B. 4.
1614 Selden Titles Hon. None of this excludes Vnction before, but only wils him
the first annointed by the Pope. 2 a to direct by ones will or testament (that
something be done, or something to be done); to dispose of by will; to bequeath
or devise; to determine by the will; to attempt to cause, aim at effecting by
exercise of will; to set the mind with conscious intention to the performance
or occurrence of something; to choose or decide to do something, or that
something shall be done or happen. Const. with simple obj., acc. and inf.,
simple inf. (now always with to), or obj. clause; also absol. or intr. (with as
or so). Nearly coinciding in meaning with will v.1 7, but with more explicit
reference to the mental process of volition. 1630 Prynne Anti-Armin. 119 He had
onely a power, not to fall into sinne vnlesse he willed it. 1667 Milton P.L. So
absolute she seems..that what she wills to do or say, Seems wisest. 1710 J.
Clarke tr. Rohaults Nat. Philos. If I will to move my Arm, it is presently
moved. 1712 Berkeley Pass. Obed. He that willeth the end, doth will the
necessary means conducive to that end. 1837 Carlyle Fr. Rev. All shall be as
God wills. 1880 Meredith Tragic Com. So great, heroical, giant-like, that what
he wills must be. 1896 Housman Shropsh. Lad xxx, Others, I am not the first,
Have willed more mischief than they durst; intr. to exercise the will; to
perform the mental act of volition. 1594 Hooker Eccl. Pol. To will, is to bend
our soules to the hauing or doing of that which they see to be good. 1830 Mackintosh
Eth. Philos. Wks.. But what could induce such a being to will or to act? 1867
A. P. Forbes Explan. Is this infinitely powerful and intelligent Being free?
wills He? loves He? c trans. To bring or get (into, out of, etc.) by exercise
of will. 1850 L. Hunt Table-t. (1882) 184 Victims of opium have been known to
be unable to will themselves out of the chair in which they were sitting. d To
control (another person), or induce (another) to do something, by the mere
exercise of ones will, as in hypnotism. 1882 Proc. Soc. Psych. Research I. The
one to be `willed would go to the other end of the house, if desired, whilst we
agreed upon the thing to be done. 1886 19th Cent. They are what is called
`willed to do certain things desired by the ladies or gentlemen who have hold
of them. 1897 A. Lang Dreams & Ghosts iii. 59 A young lady, who
believed that she could play the `willing game successfully without touching
the person `willed; to express or communicate ones will or wish with regard to
something, with various shades of meaning, cf. will, v.1 3., specifically: a to
enjoin, order; to decree, ordain, a) with personal obj., usually with inf. or
clause. 1481 Cov. Leet Bk. 496 We desire and also will you that vnto oure seid
seruaunt ye yeue your aid. 1547 Edw. VI in Rymer Foedera, We Wyll and Commaunde
yowe to Procede in the seid Matters. 1568 Grafton Chron., Their sute was smally
regarded, and shortly after they were willed to silence. 1588 Lambarde Eiren.
If a man do lie in awaite to rob me, and (drawing his sword upon me) he willeth
me to deliver my money. 1591 Shaks. 1 Hen. VI We doe no otherwise then wee are
willd. 1596 Nashe Saffron Walden P 4, Vp he was had and.willed to deliuer vp
his weapon. 1656 Hales Gold. Rem. The King in the Gospel, that made a Feast,
and..willed his servants to go out to the high-ways side. 1799 Nelson in
Nicolas Disp., Willing and requiring all Officers and men to obey you; 1565
Cooper Thesaurus s.v. Classicum, By sounde of trumpet to will scilence. 1612
Bacon Ess., Of Empire. It is common with Princes (saith Tacitus) to will
contradictories. 1697 Dryden Æneis i. 112 Tis yours, O Queen! to will The Work,
which Duty binds me to fulfil. 1877 Tennyson Harold vi. i, Get thou into thy
cloister as the king Willd it.; to pray, request, entreat; = desire v. 6. 1454
Paston Lett. Suppl. As for the questyon that ye wylled me to aske my lord, I
fond hym yet at no good leyser. 1564 Haward tr. Eutropius. The Romaines sent
ambassadoures to him, to wyll him to cease from battayle. 1581 A. Hall Iliad,
His errand done, as he was willde, he toke his flight from thence. 1631 [Mabbe]
Celestina. Did I not will you I should not be wakened? 1690 Dryden Amphitryon
i. i, He has sent me to will and require you to make a swinging long Night for
him; fig. of a thing, to require, demand; also, to induce, persuade a person to
do something. 1445 in Anglia. Constaunce willeth also that thou doo noughte
with weyke corage. Cable and Baugh note that one important s. of prescriptions
that now form part of all our grammars -- that governing the use of will and
shall -- has its origin in this period. Previous to 1622 no grammar recognized
any distinction between will and shall. In 1653 Wallis in his Grammatica
Linguae Anglicanae states in Latin and for the benefit of Europeans that
Subjectsive intention is expressed by will in the first person, by shall in the
second and third, while simple factual indicative predictable futurity is
expressed by shall in the first person, by will in the second and third. It is
not until the second half of the eighteenth century that the use in questions
and subordinate clauses is explicitly defined. In 1755 Johnson, in his
Dictionary, states the rule for questions, and in 1765 William Ward, in his
Grammar, draws up for the first time the full set of prescriptions that
underlies, with individual variations, the rules found in later tracts. Wards
pronouncements are not followed generally by other grammarians until Lindley
Murray gives them greater currency in 1795. Since about 1825 they have often
been repeated in grammars, v. Fries, The periphrastic future with will and
shall. Will qua modal auxiliary never had an s. The absence of conjugation is a
very old common Germanic phenomenon. OE 3rd person present indicative of willan
(and of the preterite-present verbs) is not distinct from the 1st person
present indicative. That dates back at least to CGmc, or further if one looks
just as the forms and ignore tense and/or mood). Re: Prichard: "Prichard
wills that he go to London. This is Prichards example, admired by Grice
("but I expect not pleasing to Maucaulays ears"). The -s is
introduced to indicate a difference between the modal and main verb use (as in
Prichard and Grice) of will. In fact, will, qua modal, has never been used with
a to-infinitive. OE uses present-tense forms to refer to future events as well
as willan and sculan. willan would give a volitional nuance; sculan, an
obligational nuance. Its difficult to find an example of weorthan used to
express the future, but that doesnt mean it didnt happen. In insensitive
utterers, will has very little of volition about it, unless one follows Walliss
observation for for I will vs. I shall. Most probably use ll, or be going
to for the future.
Fuzzy
implicatum. Grice loved ‘fuzzy,’ “if only because it’s one of the few
non-Graeco-Roman philosophical terms!” -- fuzzy set, a set in which membership is a
matter of degree. In classical set theory, for every set S and thing x, either
x is a member of S or x is not. In fuzzy set theory, things x can be members of
sets S to any degree between 0 and 1, inclusive. Degree 1 corresponds to ‘is a
member of’ and 0 corresponds to ‘is not’; the intermediate degrees are degrees
of vagueness or uncertainty. Example: Let S be the set of men who are bald at
age forty. L. A. Zadeh developed a logic of fuzzy sets as the basis for a logic
of vague predicates. A fuzzy set can be represented mathematically as a
function from a given universe into the interval [0, 1]. Zadeh tried to interpret Grice alla fuzzy in
“Pragmatics”
Gadamer, Hans-Georg b.0,
G. philosopher, the leading proponent of hermeneutics in the second half of the
twentieth century. He studied at Marburg in the 0s with Natorp and Heidegger.
His first book, Plato’s Dialectical Ethics 1, bears their imprint and reflects
his abiding interest in Grecian philosophy. Truth and Method 0 established
Gadamer as an original thinker and had an impact on a variety of disciplines
outside philosophy, including theology, legal theory, and literary criticism.
The three parts of Truth and Method combine to displace the scientific
conceptions of truth and method as the model for understanding in the human
sciences. In the first part, which presents itself as a critique of the
abstraction inherent in aesthetic consciousness, Gadamer argues that artworks
make a claim to truth. Later Gadamer draws on the play of art in the experience
of the beautiful to offer an analogy to how a text draws its readers into the
event of truth by making a claim on them. In the central portion of the book
Gadamer presents tradition as a condition of understanding. Tradition is not
for him an object of historical knowledge, but part of one’s very being. The
final section of Truth and Method is concerned with language as the site of
tradition. Gadamer sought to shift the focus of hermeneutics from the problems
of obscurity and misunderstanding to the community of understanding that the
participants in a dialogue share through language. Gadamer was involved in
three debates that define his philosophical contribution. The first was an
ongoing debate with Heidegger reflected throughout Gadamer’s corpus. Gadamer
did not accept all of the innovations that Heidegger introduced into his
thinking in the 0s, particularly his reconstruction of the history of philosophy
as the history of being. Gadamer also rejected Heidegger’s elevation of
Hölderlin to the status of an authority. Gadamer’s greater accessibility led
Habermas to characterize Gadamer’s contribution as that of having “urbanized
the Heideggerian province.” The second debate was with Habermas himself.
Habermas criticized Gadamer’s rejection of the Enlightenment’s “prejudice
against prejudice.” Whereas Habermas objected to the conservatism inherent in
Gadamer’s rehabilitation of prejudice, Gadamer explained that he was only
setting out the conditions for understanding, conditions that did not exclude
the possibility of radical change. The third debate, which formed the basis of
Dialogue and Deconstruction 9, was with Derrida. Derridean deconstruction is
indebted to Heidegger’s later philosophy and so this debate was in part about
the direction philosophy should take after Heidegger. However, many observers
concluded that there was no real engagement between Gadamer and Derrida. To
some it seemed that Derrida, by refusing to accept the terms on which Gadamer
insisted dialogue should take place, had exposed the limits imposed by
hermeneutics. To others it was confirmation that any attempt to circumvent the
conditions of dialogue specified by Gadamerian hermeneutics is selfdefeating.
Galen A.D. 129c.215, physician and philosopher
from Grecian Asia Minor. He traveled extensively in the Greco-Roman world
before settling in Rome and becoming court physician to Marcus Aurelius. His
philosophical interests lay mainly in the philosophy of science On the
Therapeutic Method and nature On the Function of Parts, and in logic
Introduction to Logic, in which he develops a crude but pioneering treatment of
the logic of relations. Galen espoused an extreme form of directed teleology in
natural explanation, and sought to develop a syncretist picture of cause and
explanation drawing on Plato, Aristotle, the Stoics, and preceding medical
writers, notably Hippocrates, whose views he attempted to harmonize with those
of Plato On the Doctrines of Hippocrates and Plato. He wrote on philosophical
psychology On the Passions and Errors of the Soul; his materialist account of
mind Mental Characteristics Are Caused by Bodily Conditions is notable for its
caution in approaching issues such as the actual nature of the substance of the
soul and the age and structure of the universe that he regarded as undecidable.
In physiology, he adopted a version of the four-humor theory, that health
consists in an appropriate balance of four basic bodily constituents blood,
black bile, yellow bile, and phlegm, and disease in a corresponding imbalance a
view owed ultimately to Hippocrates. He sided with the rationalist physicians
against the empiricists, holding that it was possible to elaborate and to
support theories concerning the fundamentals of the human body; but he stressed
the importance of observation and experiment, in particular in anatomy he
discovered the function of the recurrent laryngeal nerve by dissection and
ligation. Via the Arabic tradition, Galen became the most influential doctor of
the ancient world; his influence persisted, in spite of the discoveries of the
seventeenth century, until the end of the nineteenth century. He also wrote
extensively on semantics, but these texts are lost.
Galileo Galilei
15641642, astronomer, natural
philosopher, and physicist. His Dialogue concerning the Two Chief World Systems
1632 defended Copernicus by arguing against the major tenets of the
Aristotelian cosmology. On his view, one kind of motion replaces the multiple
distinct celestial and terrestrial motions of Aristotle; mathematics is
applicable to the real world; and explanation of natural events appeals to
efficient causes alone, not to hypothesized natural ends. Galileo was called
before the Inquisition, was made to recant his Copernican views, and spent the
last years of his life under house arrest. Discourse concerning Two New
Sciences 1638 created the modern science of mechanics: it proved the laws of
free fall, thus making it possible to study accelerated motions; asserted the
principle of the independence of forces; and proposed a theory of parabolic
ballistics. His work was developed by Huygens and Newton. Galileo’s scientific
and technological achievements were prodigious. He invented an air thermoscope,
a device for raising water, and a computer for calculating quantities in
geometry and ballistics. His discoveries in pure science included the
isochronism of the pendulum and the hydrostatic balance. His telescopic
observations led to the discovery of four of Jupiter’s satellites the Medicean
Stars, the moon’s mountains, sunspots, the moon’s libration, and the nature of
the Milky Way. In methodology Galileo accepted the ancient Grecian ideal of
demonstrative science, and employed the method of retroductive inference,
whereby the phenomena under investigation are attributed to remote causes. Much
of his work utilizes the hypothetico-deductive method. R.E.B. gambler’s
fallacy, also called Monte Carlo fallacy, the fallacy of supposing, of a
sequence of independent events, that the probabilities of later outcomes must
increase or decrease to “compensate” for earlier outcomes. For example, since
by Bernoulli’s theorem in a long run of tosses of a fair coin it is very
probable that the coin will come up heads roughly half the time, one might
think that a coin that has not come up heads recently must be “due” to come up
heads must have a probability greater
than one-half of doing so. But this is a misunderstanding of the law of large
numbers, which requires no such compensating tendencies of the coin. The
probability of heads remains one-half for each toss despite the preponderance,
so far, of tails. In the sufficiently long run what “compensates” for the
presence of improbably long subsequences in which, say, tails strongly
predominate, is simply that such subsequences occur rarely and therefore have
only a slight effect on the statistical character of the whole.
game theory: J. Hintikka,
“Grice and game theory.” the theory of the structure of, and the rational
strategies for performing in, games or gamelike human interactions. Although
there were forerunners, game theory was virtually invented by the mathematician
John von Neumann and the economist Oskar Morgenstern in the early 0s. Its most
striking feature is its compact representation of interactions of two or more
choosers, or players. For example, two players may face two choices each, and
in combination these choices produce four possible outcomes. Actual choices are
of strategies, not of outcomes, although it is assessments of outcomes that
recommend strategies. To do well in a game, even for all choosers to do well,
as is often possible, generally requires taking all other players’ positions
and interests into account. Hence, to evaluate strategies directly, without
reference to the outcomes they might produce in interaction with others, is
conspicuously perverse. It is not surprising, therefore, that in ethics, game
theory has been preeminently applied to utilitarian moral theory. As the
numbers of players and strategies rise, the complexity of games increases
geometrically. If two players have two strategies each and each ranks the four
possible outcomes without ties, there are already seventy-eight strategically
distinct games. Even minor real-life interactions may have astronomically
greater complexity. One might complain that this makes game theory useless.
Alternatively, one can note that this makes it realistic and helps us
understand why real-life choices are at least as complex as they sometimes
seem. To complicate matters further, players can choose over probabilistic
combinations of their “pure” strategies. Hence, the original four outcomes in a
simple 2 $ 2 game define a continuum of potential outcomes. After noting the
structure of games, one might then be struck by an immediate implication of
this mere description. A rational individual may be supposed to attempt to
maximize her potential or expected outcome in a game. But if there are two or
more choosers in a game, in general they cannot all maximize simultaneously
over their expected outcomes while assuming that all others are doing likewise.
This is a mathematical principle: in general, we cannot maximize over two
functions simultaneously. For example, the general notion of the greatest good
of the greatest number is incoherent. Hence, in interactive choice contexts,
the simple notion of economic rationality is incoherent. Virtually all of early
game theory was dedicated to finding an alternative principle for resolving
game interactions. There are now many so-called solution theories, most of
which are about outcomes rather than strategies they stipulate which outcomes
or range of outcomes is game-theoretically rational. There is little consensus
on how to generalize from the ordinary rationality of merely choosing more
rather than less and of displaying consistent preferences to the general choice
of strategies in games. Payoffs in early game theory were almost always
represented in cardinal, transferable utilities. Transferable utility is an odd
notion that was evidently introduced to avoid the disdain with which economists
then treated interpersonal comparisons of utility. It seems to be analogous to
money. In the language of contemporary law and economics, one could say the
theory is one of wealth maximization. In the early theory, the rationality
conditions were as follows. 1 In general, if the sums of the payoffs to all
players in various outcomes differ, it is assumed that rational players will
manage to divide the largest possible payoff among themselves. 2 No individual
will accept a payoff below the “security level” obtainable even if all the
other players form a coalition against the individual. 3 Finally, sometimes it
is also assumed that no group of players will rationally accept less than it
could get as its group security level
but in some games, no outcome can meet this condition. This is an odd
combination of individual and collective elements. The collective elements are
plausibly thought of as merely predictive: if we individually wish to do well,
we should combine efforts to help us do best as a group. But what we want is a
theory that converts individual preferences into collective results.
Unfortunately, to put a move doing just this in the foundations of the theory
is questionbegging. Our fundamental burden is to determine whether a theory of
individual rationality can produce collectively good results, not to stipulate
that it must. In the theory with cardinal, additive payoffs, we can divide
games into constant sum games, in which the sum of all players’ payoffs in each
outcome is a constant, and variable sum games. Zero-sum games are a special
case of constant sum games. Two-person constant sum games are games of pure
conflict, because each player’s gain is the other’s loss. In constant sum games
with more than two players and in all variable sum games, there is generally
reason for coalition formation to improve payoffs to members of the coalition
hence, the appeal of assumptions 1 and 3 above. Games without transferable utility,
such as games in which players have only ordinal preferences, may be
characterized as games of pure conflict or of pure coordination when players’
preference orderings over outcomes are opposite or identical, respectively, or
as games of mixed motive when their orderings are partly the same and partly
reversed. Mathematical analysis of such games is evidently less tractable than
that of games with cardinal, additive utility, and their theory is only
beginning to be extensively developed. Despite the apparent circularity of the
rationality assumptions of early game theory, it is the game theorists’
prisoner’s dilemma that makes clear that compelling individual principles of
choice can produce collectively deficient outcomes. This game was discovered about
0 and later given its catchy but inapt name. If they play it in isolation from
any other interaction between them, two players in this game can each do what
seems individually best and reach an outcome that both consider inferior to the
outcome that results from making opposite strategy choices. Even with the
knowledge that this is the problem they face, the players still have incentive
to choose the strategies that jointly produce the inferior outcome. Prisoner’s
dilemma involves both coordination and conflict. It has played a central role
in contemporary discusgame theory game theory 340 340 sions of moral and political philosophy.
Games that predominantly involve coordination, such as when we coordinate in all
driving on the right or all on the left, have a similarly central role. The
understanding of both classes of games has been read into the political
philosophies of Hobbes and Hume and into mutual advantage theories of
justice.
Gassendi, Pierre
15921655, philosopher and scientist who
advocated a via media to scientific knowledge about the empirically observable
material world that avoids both the dogmatism of Cartesians, who claimed to
have certain knowledge, and the skepticism of Montaigne and Charron, who
doubted that we have knowledge about anything. Gassendi presented Epicurean
atomism as a model for explaining how bodies are structured and interact. He
advanced a hypothetico-deductive method by proposing that experiments should be
used to test mechanistic hypotheses. Like the ancient Pyrrhonian Skeptics, he
did not challenge the immediate reports of our senses; but unlike them he
argued that while we cannot have knowledge of the inner essences of things, we
can develop a reliable science of the world of appearances. In this he
exemplified the mitigated skepticism of modern science that is always open to
revision on the basis of empirical evidence. Gassendi’s first book,
Exercitationes Paradoxicae Adversis Aristoteleos 1624, is an attack on
Aristotle. He is best known as the author of the fifth set of objections to
Descartes’s Meditations1641, in which Gassendi proposed that even clear and
distinct ideas may represent no objects outside our minds, a possibility that
Descartes called the objection of objections, but dismissed as destructive of
all reason. Gassendi’s Syntagma Philosophiae Epicuri 1649 contains his
development of Epicurean philosophy and science. His elaboration of the
mechanistic atomic model and his advocacy of experimental testing of hypotheses
were crucially important in the rise of modern science. Gassendi’s career as a
Catholic priest, Epicurean atomist, mitigated skeptic, and mechanistic
scientist presents a puzzle as do the
careers of several other philosopher-priests in the seventeenth century concerning his true beliefs. On the one hand,
he professed faith and set aside Christian doctrine as not open to challenge.
On the other hand, he utilized an arsenal of skeptical arguments that was
beginning to undermine and would eventually destroy the rational foundations of
the church. Gassendi thus appears to be of a type almost unknown today, a
thinker indifferent to the apparent discrepancy between his belief in Christian
doctrine and his advocacy of materialist science.
Gay, John 16991745,
British moralist who tried to reconcile divine command theory and
utilitarianism. The son of a minister, Gay was Gandhi, Mohandas Karamchand Gay,
John 341 341 elected a fellow of Sidney
Sussex , Cambridge, where he taught church history, Hebrew, and Grecian. His
one philosophical essay, “Dissertation Concerning the Fundamental Principle of
Virtue or Morality” 1731, argues that obligation is founded on the will of God,
which, because people are destined to be happy, directs us to act to promote
the general happiness. Gay offers an associationist psychology according to
which we pursue objects that have come to be associated with happiness e.g.
money, regardless of whether they now make us happy, and argues, contra
Hutcheson, that our moral sense is conditioned rather than natural. Gay’s blend
of utilitarianism with associationist psychology gave David Hartley the basis
for his moral psychology, which later influenced Bentham in his formulation of
classical utilitarianism.
Geach, Peter b.6, English
philosopher and logician whose main work has been in logic and philosophy of
language. A great admirer of McTaggart, he has published a sympathetic
exposition of the latter’s work Truth, Love and Immortality, 9, and has always
aimed to emulate what he sees as the clarity and rigor of the Scottish
idealist’s thought. Greatly influenced by Frege and Vitters, Geach is
particularly noted for his powerful use of what he calls “the Frege point,”
better called “the Frege-Geach point,” that the same thought may occur as
asserted or unasserted and yet retain the same truth-value. The point has been
used by Geach to refute ascriptivist theories of responsibility, and can be
employed against noncognitivist theories of ethics, which are said to face the
Frege-Geach problem of accounting for the sense of moral ascriptions in
contexts like ‘If he did wrong, he will be punished’. He is also noted for
helping to bring Frege to the English-speaking world, through co-translations
with Max Black 9 88. In logic he is known for proving, independently of Quine,
a contradiction in Frege’s way out of Russell’s paradox Mind, 6, and for his
defense of modern Fregean-Russellian logic against traditional
Aristotelian-Scholastic logic. He also has a deep admiration for the Polish
logicians. In metaphysics, Geach is known for his defense of relative identity,
the thesis that an object a can be the same F where F is a kind-term as an
object b while not being the same G, even though a and b are both G’s. His
spirited defense of the thesis has been met by equally vigorous attacks, and it
has not received wide acceptance. An obvious application of the thesis is to
the defense of the doctrine of the Trinity e.g., the Father is the same god as
the Son but not the same person, which has caught the attention of some
philosophers of religion. Geach’s main works include Mental Acts 8, which
attacks dispositional theories of mind, Reference and Generality 2, which
contains much important work on logic, and the collection Logic Matters 2. A
notable defender of Catholicism despite his animadversions against Scholastic
logic, his religious views find their greatest exposure in God and the Soul 9,
Providence and Evil 7, and The Virtues 7. He is married to the philosopher
Elizabeth Anscombe.
Grice’s genitorial
programme -- demiurge from Grecian demiourgos, ‘artisan’, ‘craftsman’, a deity
who shapes the material world from the preexisting chaos. Plato introduces the
demiurge in his Timaeus. Because he is perfectly good, the demiurge wishes to
communicate his own goodness. Using the Forms as a model, he shapes the initial
chaos into the best possible image of these eternal and immutable archetypes.
The visible world is the result. Although the demiurge is the highest god and
the best of causes, he should not be identified with the God of theism. His ontological
and axiological status is lower than that of the Forms, especially the Form of
the Good. He is also limited. The material he employs is not created by him.
Furthermore, it is disorderly and indeterminate, and thus partially resists his
rational ordering. In gnosticism, the demiurge is the ignorant, weak, and evil
or else morally limited cause of the cosmos. In the modern era the term has
occasionally been used for a deity who is limited in power or knowledge. Its
first occurrence in this sense appears to be in J. S. Mill’s Theism 1874.
Gentile, Giovanni
18754, idealist philosopher and
educational reformer. He taught at the universities of Palermo, Pisa, and Rome,
and became minister of education in the first years of Mussolini’s government
224. He was the most influential intellectual of the Fascist regime and
promoted a radical transformation of the
school system, most of which did not survive that era. Gentile rejected
Hegel’s dialectics as the process of an objectified thought. His actualism or
actual idealism claims that only the pure act of thinking or the Transcendental
Subject can undergo a dialectical process. All reality, such as nature, God,
good, and evil, is immanent in the dialectics of the Transcendental Subject,
which is distinct from Empirical Subjects. Among his major works are La teoria
generale dello spirito come atto puro 6; tr. as The Theory of Mind as Pure Act,
2 and Sistema di logica come teoria del conoscere “System of Logic as a Theory
of Knowledge,” 7. Gentile’s pedagogical views were also influenced by
actualism. Education is an act that overcomes the difficulties of
intersubjective communication and realizes the unity of the pupil and the
teacher within the Transcendental Subject Sommario di pedagogia come scienza
filosofica, “Summary of Pedagogy as a Philosophical Science,” 314. Actualism
was influential in Italy during Gentile’s life. With Croce’s historicism, it
influenced British idealists like Bosanquet and Collingwood.
Genus – gender -- Gender
implicatum – Most languages have three genders: masculine, feminine, and neuter
(or epicene, or common). feminist epistemology, epistemology from a feminist
perspective. It investigates the relevance that the gender of the
inquirer/knower has to epistemic practices, including the theoretical practice
of epistemology. It is typified both by themes that are exclusively feminist in
that they could arise only from a critical attention to gender, and by themes
that are non-exclusively feminist in that they might arise from other politicizing
theoretical perspectives besides feminism. A central, exclusively feminist
theme is the relation between philosophical conceptions of reason and cultural
conceptions of masculinity. Here a historicist stance must be adopted, so that
philosophy is conceived as the product of historically and culturally situated
hence gendered authors. This stance brings certain patterns of intellectual
association into view patterns, perhaps,
of alignment between philosophical conceptions of reason as contrasted with
emotion or intuition, and cultural conceptions of masculinity as contrasted
with femininity. A central, non-exclusively feminist theme might be called
“social-ism” in epistemology. It has two main tributaries: political
philosophy, in the form of Marx’s historical materialism; and philosophy of
science, in the form of either Quinean naturalism or Kuhnian historicism. The
first has resulted in feminist standpoint theory, which adapts and develops the
Marxian idea that different social groups have different epistemic standpoints,
where the material positioning of one of the groups is said to bestow an
epistemic privilege. The second has resulted in feminist work in philosophy of
science which tries to show that not only epistemic values but also non-epistemic
e.g. gendered values are of necessity sometimes an influence in the generation
of scientific theories. If this can be shown, then an important feminist
project suggests itself: to work out a rationale for regulating the influence
of these values so that science may be more self-transparent and more
responsible. By attempting to reveal the epistemological implications of the
fact that knowers are diversely situated in social relations of identity and
power, feminist epistemology represents a radicalizing innovation in the
analytic tradition, which has typically assumed an asocial conception of the
epistemic subject, and of the philosopher. -- feminist philosophy, a discussion
of philosophical concerns that refuses to identify the human experience with the
male experience. Writing from a variety of perspectives, feminist philosophers
challenge several areas of traditional philosophy on the grounds that they fail
1 to take seriously women’s interests, identities, and issues; and 2 to
recognize women’s ways of being, thinking, and doing as valuable as those of
men. Feminist philosophers fault traditional metaphysics for splitting the self
from the other and the mind from the body; for wondering whether “other minds”
exist and whether personal identity depends more on memories or on physical
characteristics. Because feminist philosophers reject all forms of ontological
dualism, they stress the ways in which individuals interpenetrate each other’s
psyches through empathy, and the ways in which the mind and body coconstitute
each other. Because Western culture has associated rationality with
“masculinity” and emotionality with “femininity,” traditional epistemologists
have often concluded that women are less human than men. For this reason,
feminist philosophers argue that reason and emotion are symbiotically related,
coequal sources of knowledge. Feminist philosophers also argue that Cartesian
knowledge, for all its certainty and clarity, is very limFechner’s law feminist
philosophy 305 305 ited. People want to
know more than that they exist; they want to know what other people are
thinking and feeling. Feminist philosophers also observe that traditional
philosophy of science is not as objective as it claims to be. Whereas
traditional philosophers of science often associate scientific success with
scientists’ ability to control, rule, and otherwise dominate nature, feminist
philosophers of science associate scientific success with scientists’ ability
to listen to nature’s self-revelations. Since it willingly yields abstract
theory to the testimony of concrete fact, a science that listens to what nature
says is probably more objective than one that does not. Feminist philosophers
also criticize traditional ethics and traditional social and political
philosophy. Rules and principles have dominated traditional ethics. Whether
agents seek to maximize utility for the aggregate or do their duty for the sake
of duty, they measure their conduct against a set of universal, abstract, and
impersonal norms. Feminist philosophers often call this traditional view of
ethics a “justice” perspective, contrasting it with a “care” perspective that
stresses responsibilities and relationships rather than rights and rules, and
that attends more to a moral situation’s particular features than to its
general implications. Feminist social and political philosophy focus on the
political institutions and social practices that perpetuate women’s
subordination. The goals of feminist social and political philosophy are 1 to
explain why women are suppressed, repressed, and/or oppressed in ways that men
are not; and 2 to suggest morally desirable and politically feasible ways to
give women the same justice, freedom, and equality that men have. Liberal
feminists believe that because women have the same rights as men do, society
must provide women with the same educational and occupational opportunities
that men have. Marxist feminists believe that women cannot be men’s equals
until women enter the work force en masse and domestic work and child care are
socialized. Radical feminists believe that the fundamental causes of women’s
oppression are sexual. It is women’s reproductive role and/or their sexual role
that causes their subordination. Unless women set their own reproductive goals
childlessness is a legitimate alternative to motherhood and their own sexual
agendas lesbianism, autoeroticism, and celibacy are alternatives to
heterosexuality, women will remain less than free. Psychoanalytic feminists
believe that women’s subordination is the result of earlychildhood experiences
that cause them to overdevelop their abilities to relate to other people on the
one hand and to underdevelop their abilities to assert themselves as autonomous
agents on the other. Women’s greatest strength, a capacity for deep relationships,
may also be their greatest weakness: a tendency to be controlled by the needs
and wants of others. Finally, existentialist feminists claim that the ultimate
cause of women’s subordination is ontological. Women are the Other; men are the
Self. Until women define themselves in terms of themselves, they will continue
to be defined in terms of what they are not: men. Recently, socialist feminists
have attempted to weave these distinctive strands of feminist social and
political thought into a theoretical whole. They argue that women’s condition
is overdetermined by the structures of production, reproduction and sexuality,
and the socialization of children. Women’s status and function in all of these
structures must change if they are to achieve full liberation. Furthermore,
women’s psyches must also be transformed. Only then will women be liberated
from the kind of patriarchal thoughts that undermine their self-concept and
make them always the Other. Interestingly, the socialist feminist effort to establish
a specifically feminist standpoint that represents how women see the world has
not gone without challenge. Postmodern feminists regard this effort as an
instantiation of the kind of typically male thinking that tells only one story
about reality, truth, knowledge, ethics, and politics. For postmodern
feminists, such a story is neither feasible nor desirable. It is not feasible
because women’s experiences differ across class, racial, and cultural lines. It
is not desirable because the “One” and the “True” are philosophical myths that
traditional philosophy uses to silence the voices of the many. Feminist
philosophy must be many and not One because women are many and not One. The
more feminist thoughts, the better. By refusing to center, congeal, and cement
separate thoughts into a unified and inflexible truth, feminist philosophers
can avoid the pitfalls of traditional philosophy. As attractive as the
postmodern feminist approach to philosophy may be, some feminist philosophers
worry that an overemphasis on difference and a rejection of unity may lead to
intellectual as well as political disintegration. If feminist philosophy is to
be without any standpoint whatsoever, it becomes difficult to ground claims
about what is good for women in particufeminist philosophy feminist philosophy
306 306 lar and for human beings in
general. It is a major challenge to contemporary feminist philosophy,
therefore, to reconcile the pressures for diversity and difference with those
for integration and commonality.
genus generalissimum: a
genus that is not a species of some higher genus; a broadest natural kind. One
of the ten Aristotelian categories, it is also called summum genus highest
genus. For Aristotle and many of his followers, the ten categories are not species
of some higher all-inclusive genus say,
being. Otherwise, that all-inclusive genus would wholly include its
differences, and would be universally predicable of them. But no genus is
predicable of its differences in this manner. Few authors explained this
reasoning clearly, but some pointed out that if the difference ‘rational’ just
meant ‘rational animal’, then to define ‘man’ as ‘rational animal’ would be to
define him as ‘rational animal animal’, which is ill formed. So too generally:
no genus can include its differences in this way. Thus there is no
all-inclusive genus; the ten categories are the most general genera.
Gerson, Jean de, original
name, Jean Charlier 13631429,
theologian, philosopher, and ecclesiastic. He studied in Paris, and
succeeded the nominalist Pierre d’Ailly as chancellor of the in 1395. Both d’Ailly and Gerson played a
prominent part in the work of the Council of Constance 141418. Much of Gerson’s
influence on later thinkers arose from his conciliarism, the view that the
church is a political society and that a general council, acting on behalf of
the church, has the power to depose a pope who fails to promote the church’s
welfare, for it seemed that similar arguments could apply to other forms of
political society. Gerson’s conciliarism was not constitutionalism in the
modern sense, for he appealed to corporate and hierarchical ideas of church
government, and did not rest his case on any principle of individual rights.
His main writings dealt with mystical theology, which, he thought, brings the
believer closer to the beatific vision of God than do other forms of theology.
He was influenced by St. Bonaventure and Albertus Magnus, but especially by
Pseudo-Dionysius, whom he saw as a disciple of St. Paul and not as a Platonist.
He was thus able to adopt an anti-Platonic position in his attacks on the
mystic Ruysbroeck and on contemporary followers of Duns Scotus, such as Jean de
Ripa. In dismissing Scotist realism, he made use of nominalist positions,
particularly those that emphasized divine freedom. He warned theologians
against being misled by pride into supposing that natural reason alone could
solve metaphysical problems; and he emphasized the importance of a priest’s
pastoral duties. Despite his early prominence, he spent the last years of his
life in relative obscurity.
Gersonides, also called
Levi ben Gershom 12881344, Jewish
philosopher and mathematician, the leading Jewish Aristotelian after
Maimonides. Gersonides was also a distinguished Talmudist, Bible commentator,
and astronomer. His philosophical writings include supercommentaries on most of
Averroes’ commentaries on Aristotle 134; On the Correct Syllogism 1319, a
treatise on the modal syllogism; and a major Scholastic treatise, The Wars of
the Lord 131729. In addition, his biblical commentaries rank among the best
examples of philosophical scriptural exegesis; especially noteworthy is his
interpretation of the Song of Songs as an allegory describing the ascent of the
human intellect to the agent intellect. Gersonides’ mentors in the Aristotelian
tradition were Maimonides and Averroes. However, more than either of them,
Gersonides held philosophical truth and revealed truth to be coextensive: he
acknowledged neither the conflict that Averroes saw between reason and revelation
nor Maimonides’ critical view of the limitations of the human intellect.
Furthermore, while remaining within the Aristotelian framework, Gersonides was
not uncritical of it; his independence can be illustrated by two of his most
distinctive positions. First, against Maimonides, Gersonides claimed that it is
possible to demonstrate both the falsity of the Aristotelian theory of the
eternity of the world Averroes’ position and the absurdity of creation ex
nihilo, the traditional rabbinic view that Maimonides adopted, though for
nondemonstrative reasons. Instead Gersonides advocated the Platonic theory of
temporal creation from primordial matter. Second, unlike Maimonides and
Averroes, who both held that the alleged contradiction between divine foreknowledge
of future contingent particulars and human freedom is spurious, Gersonides took
the dilemma to be real. In defense of human freedom, he then argued that it is
logically impossible even for God to have knowledge of particulars as
particulars, since his knowledge is only of general laws. At the same time, by
redefining ‘omniscience’ as knowing everything that is knowable, he showed that
this impossibility is no deficiency in God’s knowledge. Although Gersonides’
biblical commentaries received wide immediate acceptance, subsequent medieval
Jewish philosophers, e.g., Hasdai Crescas, by and large reacted negatively to
his rigorously rationalistic positions. Especially with the decline of
Aristotelianism within the philosophical world, both Jewish and Christian, he
was either criticized sharply or simply ignored.
Get
across – used by Grice in Causal: Surely the truth or falsity of Strawson
having a beautiful handwriting has no bearing on the truth or falsity of his
being hopeless at philosophy (“provided that is what I intended to get
across.”). This is the Austinian in Grice. Austin suggested that Grice analysed
or consult with Holdcroft for all ‘forms of indirect communication.’ Grice
lists: mean, indicate, suggest, imply, insinuate, hint – ‘get across’.
Geulincx, Arnold 162469,
Dutch philosopher. Born in Antwerp, he was educated at Louvain and there became
professor of philosophy 1646 and dean 1654. In 1657 he was forced out of
Louvain, perhaps for his Jansenist or Cartesian tendencies, and in 1658 he moved
to Leyden and became a Protestant. Though he taught there until his death, he
never attained a regular professorship at the . His main philosophical work is
his Ethica 1675, only Part I of which appeared during his lifetime as De
virtute et primis ejus proprietatibus 1665. Also published during his lifetime
were the Questiones quodlibeticae 1652; later editions published as Saturnalia,
a Logica 1661, and a Methodus inveniendi argumenta 1665. His most important
works, though, were published posthumously; in addition to the Ethica, there is
the Physica vera 1688, the Physica peripatetica 1690, the Metaphysica vera
1691, and the Metaphysica ad mentem peripateticam 1691. There are also two
posthumous commentaries on Descartes’s Principia Philosophiae 1690 and 1691.
Geulincx was deeply influenced by Descartes, and had many ideas that closely
resemble those Gersonides Geulincx, Arnold 344
344 of the later Cartesians as well as those of more independent
thinkers like Spinoza and Leibniz. Though his grounds were original, like many
later Cartesians, Geulincx upheld a version of occasionalism; he argued that
someone or something can only do what it knows how to do, inferring from that
that we cannot be the genuine causes of our own bodily movements. In discussing
the mindbody relation, Geulincx used a clock analogy similar to one Leibniz
used in connection with his preestablished harmony. Geulincx also held a view
of mental and material substance reminiscent of that of Spinoza. Finally, he
proposed a system of ethics grounded in the idea of a virtuous will. Despite
the evident similarities between Geulincx’s views and the views of his more
renowned contemporaries, it is very difficult to determine exactly what
influence Geulincx may have had on them, and they may have had on him.
Giles of Rome, original
name, Egidio Colonna c.12431316,
theologian and ecclesiastic. A member of the order of the Hermits of St.
Augustine, he studied arts at Augustinian house and theology at the in Paris 1260 72 but was censured by the
theology faculty 1277 and denied a license to teach as master. Owing to the
intervention of Pope Honorius IV, he later returned from Italy to Paris to
teach theology 128591, was appointed general of his order 1292, and became
archbishop of Bourges 1295. Giles both defended and criticized views of
Aquinas. He held that essence and existence are really distinct in creatures,
but described them as “things”; that prime matter cannot exist without some
substantial form; and, early in his career, that an eternally created world is
possible. He defended only one substantial form in composites, including man.
He supported Pope Boniface VIII in his quarrel with Philip IV of France.
Gilson, Étienne 48, Catholic philosopher, historian, cofounder of
the Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies in Toronto, and a major figure in
Neo-Thomism. Gilson discovered medieval philosophy through his pioneering work
on Descartes’s Scholastic background. As a historian, he argued that early
modern philosophy was incomprehensible without medieval thought, and that
medieval philosophy itself did not represent the unified theory of reality that
some Thomists had supposed. His studies of Duns Scotus, Augustine, Bernard,
Aquinas, Bonaventure, Dante, and Abelard and Héloïse explore this diversity.
But in his Gifford lectures 132, The Spirit of Medieval Philosophy, Gilson
attempted a broad synthesis of medieval teaching on philosophy, metaphysics,
ethics, and epistemology, and employed it in his critique of modern philosophy,
The Unity of Philosophical Experience 7. Most of all, Gilson attempted to
reestablish Aquinas’s distinction between essence and existence in created
being, as in Being and Some Philosophers 9.
Gioberti, Vincenzo
180152, philosopher and statesman. He
was an ordained priest, was imprisoned and exiled for advocating unification, and became a central political
figure during the Risorgimento. His major political work, Del primato morale e
civile degli i “On the Moral and Civil Primacy of s,” 1843, argues for a
federation of the states with the pope
as its leader. Gioberti’s philosophical theory, ontologism, in contrast to
Hegel’s idealism, identifies the dialectics of Being with God’s creation. He
condensed his theory in the formula: “Being creates the existent.” The dialectics
of Being, which is the only necessary substance, is a palingenesis, or a return
to its origin, in which the existent first departs from and imitates its
creator mimesis, and then returns to its creator methexis. By intuition, the
human mind comes in contact with God and discovers truth by retracing the
dialectics of Being. However, knowledge of supernatural truths is given only by
God’s revelation Teorica del soprannaturale [“Theory of the Supernatural,”
1838] and Introduzione allo studio della filosofia [“Introduction to the Study
of Philosophy,” 1841]. Gioberti criticized modern philosophers such as
Descartes for their psychologism seeking
truth from the human subject instead of from Being itself and its revelation.
His thought is still influential in Italy, especially in Christian
spiritualism. P.Gar. given, in epistemology, the “brute fact” element to be
found or postulated as a component of perceptual experience. Some theorists who
endorse the existence of a given element in experience think that we can find
this element by careful introspection of what we experience Moore, H. H. Price.
Such theorists generally distinguish between those components of ordinary
perceptual awareness that constitute what we believe or know about the objects
we perceive and those components that we strictly perceive. For example, if we
analyze introspectively what we are aware of when we see an apple we find that
what we believe of the apple is that it is a three-dimensional object with a
soft, white interior; what we see of it, strictly speaking, is just a
red-shaped expanse of one of its facing sides. This latter is what is “given”
in the intended sense. Other theorists treat the given as postulated rather
than introspectively found. For example, some theorists treat cognition as an
activity imposing form on some material given in conscious experience. On this
view, often attributed to Kant, the given and the conceptual are interdefined
and logically inseparable. Sometimes this interdependence is seen as rendering
a description of the given as impossible; in this case the given is said to be
ineffable C. I. Lewis, Mind and the World Order, 9. On some theories of
knowledge foundationalism the first variant of the given that which is “found” rather than
“postulated” provides the empirical
foundations of what we might know or justifiably believe. Thus, if I believe on
good evidence that there is a red apple in front of me, the evidence is the
non-cognitive part of my perceptual awareness of the red appleshaped expanse.
Epistemologies postulating the first kind of givenness thus require a single
entity-type to explain the sensorial nature of perception and to provide
immediate epistemic foundations for empirical knowledge. This requirement is
now widely regarded as impossible to satisfy; hence Wilfred Sellars describes
the discredited view as the myth of the given.
Glanvill, Joseph 163680,
English philosopher and Anglican minister who defended the Royal Society
against Scholasticism. Glanvill believed that certainty was possible in
mathematics and theology, but not in empirical knowledge. In his most important
philosophical work, The Vanity of Dogmatizing 1661, he claimed that the human
corruption that resulted from Adam’s fall precludes dogmatic knowledge of
nature. Using traditional skeptical arguments as well as an analysis of
causality that partially anticipated Hume, Glanvill argued that all empirical
knowledge is the probabilistic variety acquired by piecemeal investigation.
Despite his skepticism he argued for the existence of witches in Witches and
Witchcraft 1668.
gnosticism, a dualistic
religious and philosophical movement in the early centuries of the Christian
church, especially important in the second century under the leadership of
Valentinus and Basilides. They taught that matter was evil, the result of a
cosmic disruption in which an evil archon often associated with the god of the
Old Testament, Yahweh rebelled against the heavenly pleroma the complete
spiritual world. In the process divine sparks were unleashed from the pleroma
and lodged in material human bodies. Jesus was a high-ranking archon Logos sent
to restore those souls with divine sparks to the pleroma by imparting esoteric
knowledge gnosis to them. Gnosticism influenced and threatened the orthodox
church from within and without. NonChristian gnostic sects rivaled
Christianity, and Christian gnostics threatened orthodoxy by emphasizing
salvation by knowledge rather than by faith. Theologians like Clement of
Alexandria and his pupil Origen held that there were two roads to salvation,
the way of faith for the masses and the way of esoteric or mystical knowledge
for the philosophers. Gnosticism profoundly influenced the early church,
causing it to define its scriptural canon and to develop a set of creeds and an
episcopal organization.
Goclenius, Rudolphus, in
G.y, Rudolf Göckel 15471628, G. philosopher. After holding some minor posts
elsewhere, Goclenius became professor at the
of Marburg in 1581, where he remained until his death, teaching physics,
logic, mathematics, and ethics. Though he was well read and knowledgeable of
later trends in these disciplines, his basic sympathies were Aristotelian.
Goclenius was very well given, myth of the Goclenius, Rudolphus 346 346 regarded by his contemporaries, who
called him the Plato of Marburg, the Christian Aristotle, and the Light of
Europe, among other things. He published an unusually large number of books,
including the Psychologia, hoc est de hominis perfectione . . . 1590, the
Conciliator philosophicus 1609, the Controversiae logicae et philosophicae
1609, and numerous other works on logic, rhetoric, physics, metaphysics, and
the Latin language. But his most lasting work was his Lexicon Philosophicum
1613, together with its companion, the Lexicon Philosophicum Graecum 1615.
These lexicons provide clear definitions of the philosophical terminology of
late Scholastic philosophy, and are still useful as reference works for
sixteenth- and early seventeenth-century thought. D.Garb. God
Gödel’s incompleteness
theorems, two theorems formulated and proved by the Austrian logician Kurt
Gödel 678 in his famous 1 paper “Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der
Principia Mathematica und vervandter Systeme I,” probably the most celebrated
results in the whole of logic. They are aptly referred to as “incompleteness”
theorems since each shows, for any member of a certain class of formal systems,
that there is a sentence formulable in its language that it cannot prove, but
that it would be desirable for it to prove. In the case of the first theorem
G1, what cannot be proved is a true sentence of the language of the given
theory. G1 is thus a disappointment to any theory constructor who wants his
theory to tell the whole truth about its subject. In the case of the second theorem
G2, what cannot be proved is a sentence of the theory that “expresses” its
consistency. G2 is thus a disappointment to those who desire a straightforward
execution of Hilbert’s Program. The proofs of the incompleteness theorems can
be seen as based on three main ideas. The first is that of a Gödel numbering,
i.e., an assignment of natural numbers to each of the various objects i.e., the
terms, formulas, axioms, proofs, etc. belonging to the various syntactical
categories of the given formal system T referred to here as the “represented
theory” whose metamathematics is under consideration. The second is that of a
representational scheme. This includes i the use of the Gödel numbering to
develop number-theoretic codifications of various of the metamathematical
properties pertaining to the represented theory, and ii the selection of a
theory S hereafter, the “representing theory” and a family of formulas from
that theory the “representing formulas” in terms of which to register as
theorems various of the facts concerning the metamathematical properties of the
represented theory thus encoded. The basic result of this representational
scheme is the weak representation of the set of Gödel numbers of theorems of T,
where a set L of numbers is said to be weakly represented in S by a formula
‘Lx’ of S just in case for every number n, n1 L if and only if ‘L[n]’ is a
theorem of S, where ‘[n]’ is the standard term of S that, under the intended
interpretation of S, designates the number n. Since the set of Gödel numbers of
theorems of the represented theory T will typically be recursively enumerable,
and the representing theory S must be capable of weakly representing this set,
the basic strength requirement on S is that it be capable of weakly
representing the recursively enumerable sets of natural numbers. Because basic
systems of arithmetic e.g. Robinson’s arithmetic and Peano arithmetic all have
this capacity, Gödel’s theorems are often stated using containment of a
fragment of arithmetic as the basic strength requirement governing the
capacities of the representing theory which, of course, is also often the
represented theory. More on this point below. The third main idea behind the
incompleteness theorems is that of a diagonal or fixed point construction
within S for the notion of unprovability-in-T; i.e., the formulation of a
sentence Gödel of S which, under the given Gödel numbering of T, the given
representation of T’s metamathematical notions in S, and the intended
interpretation of the language of S, says of itself that it is not
provable-in-T. Gödel is thus false if provable and unprovable if true. More
specifically, if ‘ProvTx’ is a formula of S that weakly represents the set of
Gödel numbers of theorems of T in S, then Gödel can be any formula of S that is
provably equivalent in S to the formula ‘- ProvT [Gödel]’. Given this
background, G1 can be stated as follows: If a the representing theory S is any
subtheory of the represented theory T up to and God Gödel’s incompleteness
theorems 347 347 including the represented
theory itself, b the representing theory S is consistent, c the formula ‘ProvT
x’ weakly represents the set of Gödel numbers of theorems of the represented
theory T in the representing theory S, and d Gödel is any sentence provably
equivalent in the representing theory S to ‘ProvT [Gödel]’, then neither Gödel
nor -Gödel is a theorem of the representing theory S. The proof proceeds in two
parts. In the first part it is shown that, for any representing theory S up to
and including the case where S % T , if S is consistent, then -Gödel is not a
theorem of S. To obtain this in its strongest form, we pick the strongest
subtheory S of T possible, namely S % T, and construct a reductio. Thus,
suppose that 1 -Gödel is a theorem of T. From 1 and d it follows that 2
‘ProvT[Gödel]’ is a theorem of T. And from 2 and c in the “if” direction it
follows that 3 Gödel is a theorem of T. But 1 and 3 together imply that the
representing theory T is inconsistent. Hence, if T is consistent, -Gödel cannot
be a theorem of T. In the second part of the proof it is argued that if the
representing theory S is consistent, then Gödel is not a theorem of it. Again,
to obtain the strongest result, we let S be the strongest subtheory of T
possible namely T itself and, as before, argue by reductio. Thus we suppose
that A Gödel is a theorem of S % T . From this assumption and condition d it
follows that B ‘-Provr [Gödel]’ is a theorem of S % T . By A and c in the “only
if” direction it follows that C ‘ProvT [Gödel]’ is a theorem of S % T . But
from B and C it follows that S % T is
inconsistent. Hence, Gödel is not provable in any consistent representing
theory S up to and including T itself. The above statement of G1 is, of course,
not the usual one. The usual statement suppresses the distinction stressed
above between the representing and represented theories and collaterally
replaces our condition c with a clause to the effect that T is a recursively
axiomatizable extension of some suitably weak system of arithmetic e.g.
Robinson’s arithmetic, primitive recursive arithmetic, or Peano arithmetic.
This puts into a single clause what, metamathematically speaking, are two
separate conditions one pertaining to
the representing theory, the other to the represented theory. The requirement that
T be an extension of the selected weak arithmetic addresses the question of T’s
adequacy as a representing theory, since the crucial fact about extensions of
the weak arithmetic chosen is that they are capable of weakly representing all
recursively enumerable sets. This constraint on T’s capabilities as a
representing theory is in partnership with the usual requirement that, in its
capacity as a represented theory, T be recursively axiomatizable. For T’s
recursive axiomatizability ensures under ordinary choices of logic for T that its set of theorems will be recursively
enumerable and hence weakly
representable in the kind of representing theory that it itself by virtue of its
being an extension of the weak arithmetic specified is. G1 can, however, be
extended to certain theories whose sets of Gödel numbers of theorems are not
recursively enumerable. When this is done, the basic capacity required of the
representing theory is no longer merely that the recursively enumerable sets of
natural numbers be representable in it, but that it also be capable of
representing various non-recursively enumerable sets, and hence that it go
beyond the weak arithmetics mentioned earlier. G2 is a more demanding result
that G1 in that it puts significantly stronger demands on the formula ‘ProvT x’
used to express the notion of provability for the represented theory T. In
proving G1 all that is required of ‘ProvT x’ is that it weakly represent θ %
the set of Gödel numbers of theorems of T; i.e., that it yield an extensionally
accurate registry of the theorems of the represented theory in the representing
theory. G2 places additional conditions on ‘ProvT x’; conditions which result
from the fact that, to prove G2, we must codify the second part of the proof of
G1 in T itself. To do this, ‘ProvT x’ must be a provability predicate for T.
That is, it must satisfy the following constraints, commonly referred to as the
Derivability Conditions for ‘ProvT x’: I If A is a theorem of the represented
theory, then ‘ProvT [A]’ must be a theorem of the representing theory. II Every
instance of the formula ‘ProvT [A P B] P ProvT [A] P ProvT [B]’ must be a
theorem of T. III Every instance of the formula ‘ProvT [A] P ProvT [ProvT [A]]’
must be a theorem of T. I, of course, is just part of the requirement that
‘ProvT [A]’ weakly represent T’s theoremset in T. So it does not go beyond what
is required for the proof of G1. II and III, however, do. They make it possible
to “formalize” the second part of the proof of G1 in T itself. II captures, in terms
of ‘ProvT X’, the modus ponens inference by which B is derived from A, and III
codiGödel’s incompleteness theorems Gödel’s incompleteness theorems 348 348 fies in T the appeal to c used in
deriving C from A. The result of this “formalization” process is a proof within
T of the formula ‘ConT P Gödel’ where ConT is a formula of the form ‘- ProvT
[#]’, with ‘ProvT x’ a provability predicate for T and ‘[#]’ the standard
numeral denoting the Gödel number # of some formula refutable in T . From this,
and the proof of the second part of G1 itself in which the first Derivability
Condition, which is just the “only if” direction of c, figures prominently, we
arrive at the following result, which is a generalized form of G2: If S is any
consistent representing theory up to and including the represented theory T
itself, ‘ProvT x’ any provability predicate for T, and ConT any formula of T of
the form ‘- ProvT [#]’, then ConT is not a theorem of S. To the extent that, in
being a provability predicate for T, ‘ProvT x’ “expresses” the notion of
provability of the represented theory T, it seems fair to say that ConT
expresses its consistency. And to the extent that this is true, it is sensible
to read G2 as saying that for any representing theory S and any represented theory
T extending S, if S is consistent, then the consistency of T is not provable in
S.
Godfrey of Fontaines
probably before 1250 1306 or 1309,
philosopher. He taught theology at Paris 1285c.1299; 130304. Among his
major writings are fifteen Quodlibetal Questions and other disputations. He was
strongly Aristotelian in philosophy, with Neoplatonic influences in
metaphysics. He defended identity of essence and existence in creatures against
theories of their real or intentional distinction, and argued for the
possibility of demonstrating God’s existence and of some quidditative knowledge
of God. He admitted divine ideas for species but not for individuals within
species. He made wide applications of Aristotelian actpotency theory e.g., to the distinction between the soul and
its powers, to the explanation of intellection and volition, to the general
theory of substance and accident, and in unusual fashion to essence-existence
“composition” of creatures.
Godwin, William 17561836,
English philosopher, novelist, and political writer. Godwin’s main
philosophical treatise, Enquiry concerning Political Justice 1793, aroused
heated debate. He argued for radical forms of determinism, anarchism, and
utilitarianism. Government corrupts everyone by encouraging stereotyped
thinking that prevents us from seeing each other as unique individuals.
Godwin’s novel Caleb Williams 1794 portrays a good man corrupted by prejudice.
Once we remove prejudice and artificial inequality we will see that our acts
are wholly determined. This makes punishment pointless. Only in small, anarchic
societies can people see others as they really are and thus come to feel
sympathetic concern for their wellbeing. Only so can we be virtuous, because
virtue is acting from sympathetic feelings to bring the greatest happiness to
all affected. Godwin took this principle quite literally, and accepted all its
consequences. Truthfulness has no claim on us other than the happiness it
brings. If keeping a promise causes less good than breaking it, there is no
reason at all to keep it. If one must choose between saving the life either of
a major human benefactor or of one’s mother, one must choose the benefactor.
Ideally we would need no rules in morals at all. They prevent us from seeing
others properly, thereby impairing the sympathetic feelings that constitute
virtue. Rights are pointless since sympathetic people will act to help others.
Later utilitarians like Bentham had difficulty in separating their positions
from Godwin’s notorious views.
Goethe, Johann Wolfgang
von 17491832, G. writer often considered the leading cultural figure of his
age. He wrote lyric poetry, dramas, and fictional, essayistic, and aphoristic
prose as well as works in various natural sciences, including anatomy, botany,
and optics. A lawyer by training, for most of his life Goethe was a government
official at the provincial court of Saxony-Weimar. In his numerous
contributions to world literature, such as the novels The Sorrows of Young
Werther 1774, Wilhelm Meister’s Years of Apprenticeship 1795/96, Elective
Affinities 1809, and Wilhelm Meister’s Years of Pilgrimage 1821/29, and the
two-part tragedy Faust 1808/32, Goethe represented the tensions between
individual and society as well as between culture and nature, with increased recognition
of their tragic opposition and the need to cultivate a resigned self-discipline
in artistic and social matters. In his poetic and scientific treatment of
nature he was influenced by Spinoza’s pantheist identification of nature and
God and maintained that everything in nature is animate and expressive of
divine presence. In his theory and practice of science he opposed the
quantitative and experimental method and Godfrey of Fontaines Goethe, Johann
Wolfgang von 349 349 insisted on a
description of the phenomena that was to include the intuitive grasp of the
archetypal forms or shapes underlying all development in nature.
Goldman, Alvin Ira
b.8, philosopher who has made notable
contributions to action theory, naturalistic and social epistemology,
philosophy of mind, and cognitive science. He has persistently urged the
relevance of cognitive and social science to problems in epistemology,
metaphysics, the philosophy of mind, and ethics. A Theory of Human Action 0
proposes a causal theory of action, describes the generative structure of basic
and non-basic action, and argues for the compatibility of free will and
determinism. In “Epistemics: The Regulative Theory of Cognition” 8, he argued
that traditional epistemology should be replaced by ‘epistemics’, which differs
from traditional epistemology in characterizing knowledge, justified belief,
and rational belief in light of empirical cognitive science. Traditional
epistemology has used a coarse-grained notion of belief, taken too restrictive
a view of cognitive methods, offered advice for ideal cognizers rather than for
human beings with limited cognitive resources, and ignored flaws in our
cognitive system that must be recognized if cognition is to be improved.
Epistemologists must attend to the results of cognitive science if they are to
remedy these deficiencies in traditional epistemology. Goldman later developed
epistemics in Epistemology and Cognition 6, in which he developed a historical,
reliabilist theory of knowledge and epistemic justification and employed
empirical cognitive science to characterize knowledge, evaluate skepticism, and
assess human cognitive resources. In Liaisons: Philosophy Meets the Cognitive
and Social Sciences 2 and in Knowledge in a Social World 9, he defended and elaborated
a veritistic i.e., truth-oriented evaluation of communal beliefprofiles, social
institutions, and social practices e.g., the practice of restricting evidence
admissible in a jury trial. He has opposed the widely accepted view that mental
states are functional states “The Psychology of Folk Psychology,” Behavioral
and Brain Sciences, 3 and defended a simulation theory of mental state
attribution, on which one attributes mental states to another by imagining what
mental state one would be in if one were in the other’s situation “In Defense
of the Simulation Theory,” 2. He has also argued that cognitive science bears
on ethics by providing information relevant to the nature of moral evaluation,
moral choice, and hedonic states associated with the good e.g., happiness
“Ethics and Cognitive Science,” 3.
good-making
characteristic, a characteristic that makes whatever is intrinsically or
inherently good, good. Hedonists hold that pleasure and conducing to pleasure
are the sole good-making characteristics. Pluralists hold that those
characteristics are only some among many other goodmaking characteristics,
which include, for instance, knowledge, friendship, beauty, and acting from a
sense of duty.
Goodman, Nelson 698, philosopher who made seminal contributions to
metaphysics, epistemology, and aesthetics. Like Quine, Goodman repudiates
analyticity and kindred notions. Goodman’s work can be read as a series of
investigations into how to do philosophy without them. A central concern is how
symbols structure facts and our understanding of them. The Structure of
Appearance 2 presents Goodman’s constructionalism. Pretheoretical beliefs are
vague and mutually inconsistent. By devising an interpreted formal system that
derives them from or explicates them in terms of suitable primitives, we bring
them into logical contact, eliminate inconsistencies, and disclose
unanticipated logical and theoretical connections. Multiple, divergent systems
do justice to the same pretheoretical beliefs. All systems satisfying our criteria
of adequacy are equally acceptable. Nothing favors any one of them over the
others. Ways of Worldmaking 8 provides a less formal treatment of the same
themes. Category schemes dictate criteria of identity for their objects. So
mutually irreducible category schemes do not treat of the same things. Since a
world consists of the things it comprises, irreducible schemes mark out
different worlds. There are, Goodman concludes, many worlds if any. Inasmuch as
the categories that define identity Goldbach’s conjecture Goodman, Nelson
350 350 conditions on objects are human
constructs, we make worlds. Languages of Art 8 argues that art, like science,
makes and reveals worlds. Aesthetics is the branch of epistemology that
investigates art’s cognitive functions. Goodman analyzes the syntactic and
semantic structures of symbol systems, both literal and figurative, and shows
how they advance understanding in art and elsewhere. Fact, Fiction, and
Forecast4 poses the new riddle of induction. An item is grue if and only if it
is examined before future time t and found to be green or is not so examined
and is blue. All hitherto examined emeralds are both green and grue. What
justifies our expecting future emeralds to be green, not grue? Inductive
validity, the riddle demonstrates, depends on the characterization as well as
the classification of the evidence class. ‘Green’ is preferable, Goodman
maintains, because it is entrenched in inductive practice. This does not
guarantee that inferences using ‘green’ will yield truths. Nothing guarantees
that. But entrenched predicates are pragmatically advantageous, because they
mesh with our habits of thought and other cognitive resources. Goodman’s other
works include Problems and Projects 2, Of Mind and Other Matters 4, and Reconceptions
8, written with Catherine Z. Elgin.
Gorgias c.483c.376 B.C.,
Grecian Sophist. A teacher of rhetoric from Leontini in Syracuse, Gorgias came
to Athens in 427 B.C. as an ambassador from his city and caused a sensation
with his artful oratory. He is known through references and short quotations in
later writers, and through a few surviving texts two speeches and a philosophical treatise. He
taught a rhetorical style much imitated in antiquity, by delivering model
speeches to paying audiences. Unlike other Sophists he did not give formal
instruction in other topics, nor prepare a formal rhetorical manual. He was
known to have had views on language, on the nature of reality, and on virtue.
Gorgias’s style was remarkable for its use of poetic devices such as rhyme,
meter, and elegant words, as well as for its dependence on artificial
parallelism and balanced antithesis. His surviving speeches, defenses of Helen
and Palamedes, display a range of arguments that rely heavily on what the
ancients called eikos ‘likelihood’ or ‘probability’. Gorgias maintained in his
“Helen” that a speech can compel its audience to action; elsewhere he remarked
that in the theater it is wiser to be deceived than not. Gorgias’s short book
On Nature or On What Is Not survives in two paraphrases, one by Sextus
Empiricus and the other now considered more reliable in an Aristotelian work,
On Melissus, Xenophanes, and Gorgias. Gorgias argued for three theses: that
nothing exists; that even if it did, it could not be known; and that even if it
could be known, it could not be communicated. Although this may be in part a
parody, most scholars now take it to be a serious philosophical argument in its
own right. In ethics, Plato reports that Gorgias thought there were different
virtues for men and for women, a thesis Aristotle defends in the Politics.
Gracián y Morales,
Baltasar 160158, writer, moralist, and a
leading literary theorist of the
baroque. Born in Belmonte, he entered the Jesuit order in 1619 and
became rector of the Jesuit at Tarragona
and a favorite of King Philip III. Gracián’s most important works are Agudeza y
arte de ingenio “The Art of Worldly Wisdom,” 164248 and El criticón “The
Critic,” 165157. The first provides philosophical support for conceptismo,
a literary movement that sought to
create new concepts through the development of an elaborate style,
characterized by subtlety agudeza and ingenious literary artifices. El
criticón, written in the conceptist style, is a philosophical novel that
pessimistically criticizes the evils of civilization. Gracián anticipates
Rousseau’s noble savage in claiming that, although human beings are
fundamentally good in the state of nature, they are corrupted by civilization.
Echoing a common theme of thought at the
time, he attributes the nefarious influence of civilization to the confusion it
creates between appearance and reality. But Gracián’s pessimism is tempered by
faith: man has hope in the afterlife, when reality is finally revealed. Gracián
wrote several other influential books. In El héroe “The Hero,” 1637 and El
político “The Politician,” 1640, he follows Machiavelli in discussing the
attributes of the ideal prince; El discreto “The Man of Discretion,” 1646
explores the ideal gentleman, as judged by
society. Most of Gracián’s books were published under pseudonyms to
avoid censure by his order. Gorgias Gracián y Morales, Baltasar 351 351 Among authors outside Spain who used his
ideas are Nietzsche, Schopenhauer, Voltaire, and Rousseau.
grammar: Sometimes geography, sometimes
botany – “Grammatica” the Romans never cared to translate. Although
‘literature’ is the cognate. – For some reasons, the Greeks were obsessed with
the alphabet – It was a trivial ‘art’. Like ‘logic,’ and philosophy is NOT an
art or ‘techne.’ A philosopher is not a technician – and hardly an artist like
William Morris (his ‘arts and crafts’ is a joke since it translates in Latin to
‘ars et ars,’ and ‘techne kai techne’). The sad thing is that at MIT, as Grice
knew, Chomsky is appointed professor of philosophy, and he mainly writes about
‘grammar’! Later, Chomsky tries to get more philosophical, but chooses the
wrong paradigm – Cartesianism, the ghost in the machine, in Ryle’s parlance. Odly,
Oxonians, who rarely go to grammar schools, see ‘grammar’ as a divinity, and
talk of the logical grammar of a Ryleian agitation, say. It sounds high class
because there is the irony that an Oxonian philosopher is surely not a
common-or-garden grammarian, involved in the grammar of, say, “Die Deutsche
Sprache.” The Oxonian is into the logical grammar. It is more of a ‘linguistic
turn’ expression than the duller ‘conceptual analysis,’ or ‘linguistic
philosophy.’ cf. logical form, and Russell, “grammar is a pretty good guide to
logical form.” while philosophers would use grammar jocularly, Chomsky didnt.
The problem, as Grice notes, is that Chomsky never tells us where grammar ends
(“or begins for that matter.”) “Consider the P, karulising elatically.” When
Carnap introduces the P, he talks syntax, not grammar. But philosophers always
took semiotics more seriously than others. So Carnap is well aware of Morriss
triad of the syntactics, the semantics, and the pragmatics. Philosophers always
disliked grammar, because back in the days of Aelfric, philosophia was supposed
to embrace dialectica and grammatica, and rhetorica. “It is all part of
philosophy.” Truth-conditional semantics and implicata. grammar,
a system of rules specifying a language. The term has often been used
synonymously with ‘syntax’, the principles governing the construction of
sentences from words perhaps also including the systems of word derivation and
inflection case markings, verbal tense
markers, and the like. In modern linguistic usage the term more often encompasses
other components of the language system such as phonology and semantics as well
as syntax. Traditional grammars that we may have encountered in our school
days, e.g., the grammars of Latin or English, were typically fragmentary and
often prescriptive basically a selective
catalog of forms and sentence patterns, together with constructions to be
avoided. Contemporary linguistic grammars, on the other hand, aim to be
descriptive, and even explanatory, i.e., embedded within a general theory that
offers principled reasons for why natural languages are the way they are. This
is in accord with the generally accepted view of linguistics as a science that
regards human language as a natural phenomenon to be understood, just as
physicists attempt to make sense of the world of physical objects. Since the
publication of Syntactic Structures 7 and Aspects of the Theory of Syntax 5 by
Noam Chomsky, grammars have been almost universally conceived of as generative
devices, i.e., precisely formulated deductive systems commonly called generative grammars specifying all and only the well-formed
sentences of a language together with a specification of their relevant
structural properties. On this view, a grammar of English has the character of
a theory of the English language, with the grammatical sentences and their
structures as its theorems and the grammar rules playing the role of the rules
of inference. Like any empirical theory, it is subject to disconfirmation if
its predictions do not agree with the facts
if, e.g., the grammar implies that ‘white or snow the is’ is a
wellformed sentence or that ‘The snow is white’ is not. The object of this
theory construction is to model the system of knowledge possessed by those who
are able to speak and understand an unlimited number of novel sentences of the
language specified. Thus, a grammar in this sense is a psychological
entity a component of the human
mind and the task of linguistics
avowedly a mentalistic discipline is to determine exactly of what this
knowledge consists. Like other mental phenomena, it is not observable directly
but only through its effects. Thus, underlying linguistic competence is to be
distinguished from actual linguistic performance, which forms part of the
evidence for the former but is not necessarily an accurate reflection of it, containing,
as it does, errors, false starts, etc. A central problem is how this competence
arises in the individual, i.e., how a grammar is inferred by a child on the
basis of a finite, variable, and imperfect sample of utterances encountered in
the course of normal development. Many sorts of observations strongly suggest
that grammars are not constructed de novo entirely on the basis of experience,
and the view is widely held that the child brings to the task a significant,
genetically determined predisposition to construct grammars according to a
well-defined pattern. If this is so, and since apparently no one language has
an advantage over any other in the learning process, this inborn component of
linguistic competence can be correctly termed a universal grammar. It
represents whatever the grammars of all natural languages, actual or potential,
necessarily have in common because of the innate linguistic competence of human
beings. The apparent diversity of natural languages has often led to a serious
underestimation of the scope of universal grammar. One of the most influential
proposals concerning the nature of universal grammar was Chomsky’s theory of
transformational grammar. In this framework the syntactic structure of a
sentence is given not by a single object e.g., a parse tree, as in phrase
structure grammar, but rather by a sequence of trees connected by operations
called transformations. The initial tree in such a sequence is specified
generated by a phrase structure grammar, together with a lexicon, and is known
as the deep structure. The final tree in the sequence, the surface structure,
contains the morphemes meaningful units of the sentence in the order in which
they are written or pronounced. For example, the English sentences ‘John hit
the ball’ and its passive counterpart ‘The ball was hit by John’ might be
derived from the same deep structure in this case a tree looking very much like
the surface structure for the active sentence except that the optional
transformational rule of passivization has been applied in the derivation of
the latter sentence. This rule rearranges the constituents of the tree in such
a way that, among other changes, the direct object ‘the ball’ in deep structure
becomes the surface-structure subject of the passive sentence. It is thus an
important feature of this theory that grammatical grammar grammar 352 352 relations such as subject, object, etc.,
of a sentence are not absolute but are relative to the level of structure. This
accounts for the fact that many sentences that appear superficially similar in
structure e.g., ‘John is easy to please’, ‘John is eager to please’ are
nonetheless perceived as having different underlying deep-structure grammatical
relations. Indeed, it was argued that any theory of grammar that failed to make
a deep-structure/surface-structure distinction could not be adequate.
Contemporary linguistic theories have, nonetheless, tended toward minimizing
the importance of the transformational rules with corresponding elaboration of
the role of the lexicon and the principles that govern the operation of
grammars generally. Theories such as generalized phrase-structure grammar and
lexical function grammar postulate no transformational rules at all and capture
the relatedness of pairs such as active and passive sentences in other ways.
Chomsky’s principles and parameters approach 1 reduces the transformational
component to a single general movement operation that is controlled by the
simultaneous interaction of a number of principles or subtheories: binding,
government, control, etc. The universal component of the grammar is thus
enlarged and the contribution of languagespecific rules is correspondingly
diminished. Proponents point to the advantages this would allow in language
acquisition. Presumably a considerable portion of the task of grammar
construction would consist merely in setting the values of a small number of
parameters that could be readily determined on the basis of a small number of
instances of grammatical sentences. A rather different approach that has been
influential has arisen from the work of Richard Montague, who applied to
natural languages the same techniques of model theory developed for logical
languages such as the predicate calculus. This so-called Montague grammar uses
a categorial grammar as its syntactic component. In this form of grammar,
complex lexical and phrasal categories can be of the form A/B. Typically such
categories combine by a kind of “cancellation” rule: A/B ! B P A something of
category A/B combines with something of category B to yield something of
category A. In addition, there is a close correspondence between the syntactic
category of an expression and its semantic type; e.g., common nouns such as
‘book’ and ‘girl’ are of type e/t, and their semantic values are functions from
individuals entities, or e-type things to truth-values T-type things, or
equivalently, sets of individuals. The result is an explicit, interlocking
syntax and semantics specifying not only the syntactic structure of grammatical
sentences but also their truth conditions. Montague’s work was embedded in his
own view of universal grammar, which has not, by and large, proven persuasive
to linguists. A great deal of attention has been given in recent years to
merging the undoubted virtues of Montague grammar with a linguistically more
palatable view of universal grammar. Refs.: One source is an essay on
‘grammar’ in the H. P. Grice Papers, BANC.
Gramsci, Antonio 17, political leader whose imprisonment by the
Fascists for his involvement with the
Communist Party had the ironical result of sparing him from Stalinism
and enabling him to better articulate his distinctive political philosophy. In
7 he welcomed the Bolshevik Revolution as a “revolution against Capital” rather
than against capitalism: as a revolution refuting the deterministic Marxism
according to which socialism could arise only by the gradual evolution of
capitalism, and confirming the possibility of the radical transformation of
social institutions. In 1 he supported creation of the Communist Party; as its general secretary
from 4, he tried to reorganize it along more democratic lines. In 6 the
Fascists outlawed all opposition parties. Gramsci spent the rest of his life in
various prisons, where he wrote more than a thousand s of notes ranging from a
few lines to chapterlength essays. These Prison Notebooks pose a major
interpretive challenge, but they reveal a keen, insightful, and open mind
grappling with important social and political problems. The most common
interpretation stems from Palmiro Togliatti, Gramsci’s successor as leader of
grammar, categorial Gramsci, Antonio 353
353 the Communists. After the
fall of Fascism and the end of World War II, Togliatti read into Gramsci the
so-called road to socialism: a strategy
for attaining the traditional Marxist goals of the classless society and the
nationalization of the means of production by cultural means, such as education
and persuasion. In contrast to Bolshevism, one had to first conquer social
institutions, and then their control would yield the desired economic and
political changes. This democratic theory of Marxist revolution was long
regarded by many as especially relevant to Western industrial societies, and so
for this and other reasons Gramsci is a key figure of Western Marxism. The same
theory is often called Gramsci’s theory of hegemony, referring to a
relationship between two political units where one dominates the other with the
consent of that other. This interpretation was a political reconstruction,
based primarily on Gramsci’s Communist involvement and on highly selective
passages from the Notebooks. It was also based on exaggerating the influence on
Gramsci of Marx, Engels, Lenin, and Gentile, and minimizing influences like
Croce, Mosca, Machiavelli, and Hegel. No new consensus has emerged yet; it
would have to be based on analytical and historical spadework barely begun. One
main interpretive issue is whether Gramsci, besides questioning the means, was
also led to question the ends of traditional Marxism. In one view, his
commitment to rational persuasion, political realism, methodological
fallibilism, democracy, and pluralism is much deeper than his inclinations
toward the classless society, the abolition of private property, the
bureaucratically centralized party, and the like; in particular, his pluralism
is an aspect of his commitment to the dialectic as a way of thinking, a concept
he adapted from Hegel through Croce.
Green, Thomas Hill
183682, British absolute idealist and social philosopher. The son of a
clergyman, Green studied and taught at Oxford. His central concern was to
resolve what he saw as the spiritual crisis of his age by analyzing knowledge
and morality in ways inspired by Kant and Hegel. In his lengthy introduction to
Hume’s Treatise, he argued that Hume had shown knowledge and morality to be
impossible on empiricist principles. In his major work, Prolegomena to Ethics
3, Green contended that thought imposed relations on sensory feelings and
impulses whose source was an eternal consciousness to constitute objects of
knowledge and of desire. Furthermore, in acting on desires, rational agents
seek the satisfaction of a self that is realized through their own actions.
This requires rational agents to live in harmony among themselves and hence to
act morally. In Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation 5 Green
transformed classical liberalism by arguing that even though the state has no
intrinsic value, its intervention in society is necessary to provide the
conditions that enable rational beings to achieve self-satisfaction.
Gregory I, Saint, called
Gregory the Great c.540604, a pope and Roman political leader. Born a
patrician, he was educated for public office and became prefect of Rome in 570.
In 579, he was appointed papal representative in Constantinople, returning to
Rome as counselor to Pope Pelagius II in 586. He was elected Pope Gregory I in
590. When the Lombards attacked Rome in 594, Gregory bought them off.
Constantinople would neither cede nor defend Italy, and Gregory stepped in as
secular ruler of what became the Papal States. He asserted the universal
jurisdiction of the bishop of Rome, and claimed patriarchy of the West. His
writings include important letters; the Moralia, an exposition of the Book of
Job summarizing Christian theology; Pastoral Care, which defined the duties of
the clergy for the Middle Ages; and Dialogues, which deals chiefly with the
immortality of the soul, holding it could enter heaven immediately without
awaiting the Last Judgment. His thought, largely Augustinian, is unoriginal,
but was much quoted in the Middle Ages.
Gregory of Nyssa, Saint
33598, Grecian theologian and mystic who tried to reconcile Platonism with
Christianity. As bishop of Cappadocia in eastern Asia Minor, he championed
orthodoxy and was prominent at the First Council of Constantinople. He related
the doctrine of the Trinity to Plato’s ideas of the One and the Many. He
followed Origen in believing that man’s material great chain of being Gregory
of Nyssa 354 354 nature was due to the
fall and in believing in the Apocatastasis, the universal restoration of all
souls, including Satan’s, in the kingdom of God.
Gregory of Rimini
c.130058, philosopher and monk. He
studied in Italy, England, and France, and taught at the universities of
Bologna, Padua, Perugia, and Paris before becoming prior general of the Hermits
of St. Augustine in his native city of Rimini, about eighteen months before he
died. Gregory earned the honorific title “the Authentic Doctor” because he was
considered by many of his contemporaries to be a faithful interpreter of
Augustine, and thus a defender of tradition, in the midst of the skepticism of
Ockham and his disciples regarding what could be known in natural philosophy
and theology. Thus, in his commentary on Books I and II of Peter Lombard’s
Sentences, Gregory rejected the view that because of God’s omnipotence he can
do anything and is therefore unknowable in his nature and his ways. Gregory
also maintained that after Adam’s fall from righteousness, men need, in
conjunction with their free will, God’s help grace to perform morally good
actions. In non-religious matters Gregory is usually associated with the theory
of the complexe significabile, according to which the object of knowledge
acquired by scientific proof is neither an object existing outside the mind,
nor a word simplex or a proposition complexum, but rather the complexe
significabile, that which is totally and adequately signified by the
proposition expressed in the conclusion of the proof in question.
“grice” as a count noun –
“Lots of grice in the fields.” – One Scots to another -- count noun, a noun
that can occur syntactically a with quantifiers ‘each’, ‘every’, ‘many’, ‘few’,
‘several’, and numerals; b with the indefinite article, ‘an’; and c in the
plural form. The following are examples of count nouns CNs, paired with
semantically similar mass nouns MNs: ‘each dollar / silver’, ‘one composition /
music’, ‘a bed / furniture’, ‘instructions / advice’. MNs but not CNs can occur
with the quantifiers ‘much’ and ‘little’: ‘much poetry / poems’, ‘little bread
/ loaf’. Both CNs and MNs may occur with ‘all’, ‘most’, and ‘some’.
Semantically, CNs but not MNs refer distributively, providing a counting
criterion. It makes sense to ask how many CNs?: ‘How many coins / gold?’ MNs
but not CNs refer collectively. It makes sense to ask how much MN?: ‘How much
gold / coins?’ One problem is that these syntactic and semantic criteria yield
different classifications; another problem is to provide logical forms and
truth conditions for sentences containing mass nouns.
Grice: English
philosopher, born in Harborne, “in the middle of nowhere,” as Strawson put it –
(“He was from London, Strawson was”) -- whose work concerns perception and
philosophy of language, and whose most influential contribution is the concept
of a conversational implicature and the associated theoretical machinery of
conversational ‘postulates.’ The concept of a conversational implicature is
first used in his ‘presentation’ on the causal theory of perception and
reference. Grice distinguishes between the ‘meaning’ of the words used in a
sentence and what is implied by the utterer’s choice of words. If someone says
“It looks as if there is a red pillar box in front of me,” the choice of words
implies that there is some doubt about the pillar box being red. But, Grice
argues, that is a matter of word choice and the sentence itself does not
‘impl’ that there is doubt. The term
‘conversational implicature’ was introduced in Grice’s William James lectures
published in 8 and used to defend the use of the material implication as a
logical translation of ‘if’. With Strawson “In Defence of Dogma”, Grice gives a
spirited defense of the analyticsynthetic distinction against Quine’s
criticisms. In subsequent systematic papers Grice attempts, among other things,
to give a theoretical grounding of the distinction. Grice’s oeuvre is part of
the Oxford ordinary language tradition, if formal and theoretical. He also
explores metaphysics, especially the concept of absolute value. .
gricese: english,
being English or the genius of the ordinary. H. P. Grice refers to “The English
tongue.” A refusal to rise above the facts of ordinary life is characteristic
of classical Eng. Phil. from
Ireland-born Berkeley to Scotland-born Hume, Scotland-born Reid, and very
English Jeremy Bentham and New-World Phil. , whether in transcendentalism
Emerson, Thoreau or in pragmatism from James to Rorty. But this orientation did
not become truly explicit until after the linguistic turn carried out by
Vienna-born Witters, translated by C. K. Ogden, very English Brighton-born
Ryle, and especially J. L. Austin and his best companion at the Play Group, H.
P. Grice, when it was radicalized and systematized under the name of a phrase
Grice lauged at: “‘ordinary’-language philosophy.” This preponderant recourse
to the ordinary seems inseparable from certain peculiar characteristics of the
English Midlanders such as H. P. Grice, such as the gerund that often make it
difficult if not impossible to translate. It is all the more important to
emphasize this paradox because English Midlander philosopher, such as H. P.
Grice, claims to be as simple as it is universal, and it established itself as
an important philosophical language in the second half of the twentieth
century, due mainly to the efforts of H. P. Grice. English, but especially
Oxonian Phil. has a specific
relationship to ‘ordinary’ language (even though for Grice, “Greek and Latin
were always more ordinary to me – and people who came to read Eng. at Oxford
were laughed at!”), as well as to the requirements of everyday life, that is
not limited to the theories of the Phil.
of language, in which an Eng. philosopher such as H. P. Grice appears as
a pioneer. It rejects the artificial linguistic constructions of philosophical
speculation that is, Met. and always prefers to return to its original home, as
Witters puts it: the natural environment of everyday words Philosophical
Investigations. Thus we can discern a continuity between the recourse to the
ordinary in Scots Hume, Irish Berkeley, Scots Reid, and very English Jeremy
Bentham and what will become in Irish London-born G. E. Moore and Witters after
he started using English, at least orally and then J. L. Austin’s and H. P.
Grice’s ‘ordinary’-language philosophy. This continuity can be seen in several
areas. First, in the exploitation of all the resources of the language, which
is considered as a source of information and is valid in itself. Second, in the
attention given to the specificities—and even the defects, or ‘implicata,’ as
Grice calls them —of the vernacular --
which become so many philosophical characteristics from which one can
learn. Finally, in the affirmation of the naturalness of the distinctions made
in and by ordinary language, seeking to challenge the superiority of the
technical language of Philosophy —the former being the object of an agreement
deeper than the latter. Then there’s The Variety of Modes of Action. The
passive. There are several modes of agency, and these constitute both part of
the genius of the language and a main source of its problems in tr.. Agency is
a strange intersection of points of view that makes it possible to designate
the person who is acting while at the same time concealing the actor behind the
act—and thus locating agency in the passive subject itself v. AGENCY. A classic
difficulty is illustrated by the following sentence from J. Stuart Mill’s To
gauge the naturalness of the passive construction in English, it suffices to
examine a couple of newspaper headlines. “Killer’s Car Found” On a retrouvé la
voiture du tueur, “Kennedy Jr. Feared Dead.” On craint la mort du fils Kennedy;
or the titles of a philosophical essay, “Epistemology Naturalized,”
L’Épistémologie naturalisée; Tr. J.
Largeault as L’Épistémologie devenue naturelle; a famous article by Quine that
was the origin of the naturalistic turn in American Phil. and “Consciousness Explained” La conscience
expliquée by Daniel Dennett. We might then better understand why this PASSIVE
VOICE kind of construction—which seems so awkward in Fr. compared with the active voice— is perceived
by its Eng. users as a more direct and effective way of speaking. More
generally, the ellipsis of the agent seems to be a tendency of Eng. so profound
that one can maintain that the phenomenon Lucien Tesnière called diathèse
récessive the loss of the agent has become a characteristic of the Eng.
language itself, and not only of the passive. Thus, e. g. , a Fr. reader irresistibly gains the impression that
a reflexive pronoun is lacking in the following expressions. “This book reads
well.” ce livre se lit agréablement. “His poems do not translate well.” ses
poèmes se traduisent difficilement. “The door opens.” la porte s’ouvre. “The
man will hang.” l’homme sera pendu. In reality, here again, Eng. simply does
not need to mark by means of the reflexive pronoun se the presence of an active
agent. Do, make, have Eng. has several terms to translate the single Fr. word faire, which it can render by to do, to
make, or to have, depending on the type of agency required by the context.
Because of its attenuation of the meaning of action, its value as emphasis and
repetition, the verb “to do” has become omnipresent in English, and it plays a
particularly important role in philosophical texts. We can find a couple of
examples of tr. problems in the Oxonian seminars by J. L. Austin. In Sense and
Considerations on Representative Government: “I must not be understood to say
that” p. To translate such a passive construction, Fr. is forced to resort to the impersonal pronoun
on and to put it in the position of an observer of the “I” je as if it were
considered from the outside: On ne doit pas comprendre que je dis que p. But at
the same time, the network of relations internal to the sentence is modified,
and the meaning transformed. Necessity is no longer associated with the subject
of the sentence and the author; it is made impersonal. Philosophical language
also makes frequent use of the diverse characteristics of the passive. Here we can
mention the crucial turning point in the history of linguistics represented by
Chomsky’s discovery Syntactic Structures,
of the paradigm of the active/ passive relation, which proves the
necessity of the transformational component in grammar. A passive utterance is
not always a reversal of the active and only rarely describes an undergoing, as
is shown by the example She was offered a bunch of flowers. In particular,
language makes use of the fact that this kind of construction authorizes the
ellipsis of the agent as is shown by the common expression Eng. spoken. For a
philosopher, the passive is thus the privileged form of an action when its
agent is unknown, indeterminate, unimportant, or, inversely, too obvious. Thus
without making his prose too turgid, in Sense and Sensibilia Austin can use
five passives in less than a page, and these can be translated in Fr. only by on, an indeterminate subject defined
as differentiated from moi. “It is clearly implied, that “Now this, at least if
it is taken to mean The expression is here put forward We are given, as
examples, familiar objects The expression is not further defined On sous-entend
clairement que Quant à cela, du moins si on l’entend au sens de On avance ici
l’expression On nous donne, comme exemples, des objets familiers On
n’approfondit pas la définition de l’expression . . . 1 Langage, langue,
parole: A virtual distinction. Contrary to what is too often believed, the Eng.
language does not conflate under the term language what Fr. distinguishes following Saussure with the
terms langage, langue, and parole. In reality, Eng. also has a series of three
terms whose semantic distribution makes possible exactly the same trichotomy as
Fr. : First there’s Grice’s “tongue,”which serves to designate a specific
language by opposition to another; speech, which refers more specifically to
parole but which is often translated in Fr.
by discours; and language in the sense of faculté de langage.
Nonetheless, Fr. ’s set of systematic distinctions can only remain fundamentally
virtual in English, notably because the latter refuses to radically detach
langue from parole. Thus in Chrestomathia, Bentham uses “tongue” (Bentham’s
tongue – in Chrestomathia) and language interchangeably and sometimes uses
language in the sense of langue: “Of all known languages the Grecian [Griceian]
is assuredly, in its structure, the most plastic and most manageable. Bentham
even uses speech and language as equivalents, since he speaks of parts of
speech. But on the contrary, he sometimes emphasizes differences that he
ignores here. And he proceeds exactly like Hume in his essay Of the Standard of
Taste, where we find, e. g. , But it must also be allowed, that some part of
the seeming harmony in morals may be accounted for from the very nature of
language. The word, virtue, with its equivalent in every tongue, implies
praise; as that of vice does blame. REFS.: Bentham, Jeremy.
ChrestomathiEd. by M. J. Smith and W. H.
Burston. Oxford: Clarendon, . Hume, D. . Of the Standard of Taste. In Four Dissertations.
London: Thoemmes Continuum, . First published in 175 Saussure, F. de. Course in
General Linguistics. Ed. by Bally and
Sechehaye. Tr. R. Harris. LaSalle, IL:
Open Court, . First published in circulation among these forms. This formal
continuity promotes a great methodological inventiveness through the interplay
among the various grammatical entities that it enables. The gerund: The form of -ing that is the most
difficult to translate Eng. is a nominalizing language. Any verb can be
nominalized, and this ability gives the Eng. philosophical language great
creative power. “Nominalization,” as Grice calls it, is in fact a
substantivization without substantivization: the verb is not substantivized in
order to refer to action, to make it an object of discourse which is possible
in any language, notably in philosophical Fr.
and G. , but rather to nominalize the verb while at the same time
preserving its quality as a verb, and even to nominalize whole clauses.
Fr. can, of course, nominalize faire,
toucher, and sentir le faire, le toucher, even le sentir, and one can do the
same, in a still more systematic manner, in G. . However, these forms will not
have the naturalness of the Eng. expressions: the making and unmaking the doing
and undoing, the feeling, the feeling Byzantine, the meaning. Above all, in
these languages it is hard to construct expressions parallel to, e. g. , the
making of, the making use of, my doing wrongly, “my meaning this,”
(SIGNIFICATUM, COMMUNICATUM), his feeling pain, etc., that is, mixtures of noun
and verb having—and this is the grammatical characteristic of the gerund — the
external distribution of a nominal expression and the internal distribution of
a verbal expression. These forms are so common that they characterize, in
addition to a large proportion of book titles e. g. , The Making of the Eng.
Working Class, by E. P. Thomson; or, in Phil. , The Taming of Chance, or The
taming of the true, by I. Hacking, the language of classical Eng. Phil. . The
gerund functions as a sort of general equivalent or exchanger between
grammatical forms. In that way, it not only makes the language dynamic by
introducing into it a permanent temporal flux, but also helps create, in the
language itself, a kind of indeterminacy in the way it is parsed, which the
translator finds awkward when he understands the message without being able to
retain its lightness. Thus, in A Treatise of Human Nature, Hume speaks,
regarding the idea, of the manner of its being conceived, which a Fr. translator might render as sa façon d’être
conçue or perhaps, la façon dont il lui appartient d’être conçue, which is not
quite the same thing. And we v. agency and the gerund connected in a language
like that of Bentham, who minimizes the gaps between subject and object, verb
and noun: much regret has been suggested at the thoughts of its never having
yet been brought within the reach of the Eng. reader ChrestomathiTranslators
often feel obliged to render the act expressed by a gerund by the expression le
fait de, but this has a meaning almost contrary to the English. With its
gerund, Eng. avoids the discourse of fact by retaining only the event and
arguing only on that basis. The inevitable confusion suggested by Fr. when it translates the Eng. gerund is all the
more unfortunate in this case because it becomes impossible to distinguish when
Eng. uses the fact or the case from when it uses the gerund. The importance of
the event, along with the distinction between trial, case, and event, on the
one hand and happening on the other, is Sensibilia, he has criticized the claim
that we never perceive objects directly and is preparing to criticize its
negation as well: I am not going to maintain that we ought to embrace the
doctrine that we do perceive material things. Je ne vais pas soutenir que nous
devons embrasser la doctrine selon laquelle nous percevons vraiment les choses
matérielles. Finally, let us recall Austin’s first example of the performative,
which plays simultaneously on the anaphoric value of do and on its sense of
action, a duality that v.ms to be at the origin of the theory of the
performative, I do take this woman to be my lawful wedded wife—as uttered in
the course of the marriage ceremony Oui à savoir: je prends cette femme pour
épouse’énoncé lors d’une cérémonie de mariage; How to Do Things with Words. On
the other hand, whereas faire is colored by a causative sense, Eng. uses to
make and to have—He made Mary open her bags il lui fit ouvrir sa valise; He had
Mary pour him a drink il se fit verser un verre—with this difference: that make
can indicate, as we v., coercion, whereas have presupposes that there is no
resistance, a difference that Fr. can
only leave implicit or explain by awkward periphrases. Twentieth-century Eng.
philosophers from Austin to Geach and Anscombe have examined these differences
and their philosophical implications very closely. Thus, in A Plea for Excuses,
Austin emphasizes the elusive meaning of the expression doing something, and
the correlative difficulty of determining the limits of the concept of
action—Is to sneeze to do an action? There is indeed a vague and comforting
idea that doing an action must come down to the making of physical movements.
Further, we need to ask what is the detail of the complicated internal
machinery we use in acting. Philosophical Papers No matter how partial they may
be, these opening remarks show that there is a specific, intimate relation
between ordinary language and philosophical language in English language Phil.
. This enables us to better understand why the most Oxonian philosophers are so
comfortable resorting to idiomatic expressions cf. H. Putnam and even to
clearly popular usage: “Meanings ain’t in the head.” It ain’t necessarily so.As
for the title of Manx-ancestry Quine’s famous book From a Logical Point of
View, which at first seems austere, it is taken from a calypso song: “From a
logical point of view, Always marry women uglier than you. The Operator -ing:
Properties and Antimetaphysical Consequences -ing: A multifunctional operator
Although grammarians think it important to distinguish among the forms of
-ing—present participles, adjectives, the progressive, and the gerund—what
strikes the reader of scientific and philosophical texts is first of all the
free in Phil. , You are v.ing something Austin, Sense and Sensibilia, regarding
a stick in water; I really am perceiving the familiar objects Ayer, Foundations
of Empirical Knowledge. The passage to the form be + verb + -ing indicates,
then, not the progressiveness of the action but rather the transition into the
metalanguage peculiar to the philosophical description of phenomena of
perception. The sole exception is, curiously, to know, which is practically
never used in the progressive: even if we explore the philosophical and
epistemological literature, we do not find “I am knowing” or he was knowing, as
if knowledge could not be conceived as a process. In English, there is a great
variety of what are customarily called aspects, through which the status of the
action is marked and differentiated in a more systematic way than in Fr. or G. , once again because of the -ing
ending: he is working / he works / he worked / he has been working. Unlike what
happens in Slavic languages, aspect is marked at the outset not by a duality of
verbal forms but instead by the use of the verb to be with a verb ending in
-ing imperfect or progressive, by opposition to the simple present or past
perfect. Moreover, Grice mixes several aspects in a single expression:
iterativity, progressivity, completion, as in it cannot fail to have been
noticed Austin, How to Do Things. These are nuances, or implicate, as Labov and
then Pinker recently observed, that are not peculiar to classical or written
Eng. but also exist in certain vernaculars that appear to be familiar or allegedly
ungrammatical. The vernacular seems particularly sophisticated on this point,
distinguishing “he be working” from “he working” —that is, between having a
regular job and being engaged in working at a particular moment, standard usage
being limited to “he is working” Pinker, Language Instinct. Whether or not the
notion of aspect is used, it seems clear that in Eng. there is a particularly
subtle distinction between the different degrees of completion, of the
iterativity or development of an action, that leads Oxonian philosophers to pay
more attention to these questions and even to surprising inventions, such as
that of ‘implicatum,’ or ‘visum,’ or ‘disimplicatum.’ The linguistic
dissolution of the idea of substance
Fictive entities Thus the verb + -ing operation simply gives the verb
the temporary status of a noun while at the same time preserving some of its
syntactic and semantic properties as a verb, that is, by avoiding
substantivization. It is no accident that the substantiality of the I think asserted
by Descartes was opposed by virtually all the Eng. philosophers of the
seventeenth century. If a personal identity can be constituted by the making
our distant perceptions influence each other, and by giving us a present
concern for our past or future pains or pleasures Hume, Treatise of Human
Nature, it does not require positing a substance: the substantivization of
making and giving meets the need. We can also consider the way in which Russell
Analysis of Matter, ch.27 makes his reader understand far more easily than does
Bachelard, and without having to resort to the category of an epistemological
obstacle, that one can perfectly well posit an atom as a series of events
without according it the status of a substance. crucial in discussions of probability.
The very definition of probability with which Bayes operates in An Essay
towards Solving a Problem, the first great treatise on subjective probability,
is based on this status of the happening, the event conceived not in terms of
its realization or accomplishment but in terms of its expectation: The
probability of any event is the ratio between the value at which an expectation
depending on the happening of the event ought to be computed, and the value of
the thing expected upon its happening.
The progressive: Tense and aspect If we now pass from the gerund to the
progressive, another construction that uses -ing, a new kind of problem
appears: that of the aspect and temporality of actions. An interesting case of
tr. difficulty is, e. g. , the one posed by Austin precisely when he attempts,
in his presentation of performatives, to distinguish between the sentence and
the act of saying it, between statement and utterance: there are utterances,
such as the uttering of the sentence is, or is part of, the doing of an action
How to Do Things. The tr. difficulty here is caused by the combination in the
construction in -ing of the syntactical flexibility of the gerund and a
progressive meaning. Does the -ing construction indicate the act, or the
progressiveness of the act? Similarly, it is hard to choose to translate “On
Referring” P. F. Strawson as De la référence rather than as De l’action de
référer. Should one translate On Denoting Russell as De la dénotation the usual
tr. or as Du dénoter? The progressive in the strict sense—be + verb + -ing—
indicates an action at a specific moment, when it has already begun but is not
yet finished. A little farther on, Austin allows us to gauge the ease of Eng.
in the whole of these operations. “To utter the sentence is not to describe my
doing of what I should be said in so uttering to be doing. The Fr. tr. gives, correctly: Énoncer la phrase, ce
n’est pas décrire ce qu’il faut bien reconnaître que je suis en train de faire
en parlant ainsi, but this remains unsatisfying at best, because of the
awkwardness of en train de. Moreover, in many cases, en train de is simply not
suitable insofar as the -ing does not indicate duration: e. g. , in At last I
am v.ing . It is interesting to examine from this point of view the famous
category of verbs of perception, verbum percipiendi. It is remarkable that
these verbs v., hear can be in some cases used with the construction be + verb
+ -ing, since it is generally said even in grammar books that they can be used
only in the present or simple past and not in the progressive. This rule
probably is thought to be connected with something like the immediacy of
perception, and it can be compared with the fact that the verbs to know and to
understand are also almost always in the present or the simple past, as if the
operations of the understanding could not be presented in the progressive form
and were by definition instantaneous; or as if, on the contrary, they
transcended the course of time. In reality, there are counterexamples. “I don’t
know if I’m understanding you correctly”; You are hearing voices; and often
Oxonian Phil. , which makes their tr. particularly indigestible, especially in
Fr. , where -ismes gives a very Scholastic feel to the classifications
translated. In addition to the famous term realism, which has been the object
of so many contradictory definitions and so many debates over past decades that
it has been almost emptied of meaning, we may mention some common but
particularly obscure for anyone not familiar with the theoretical context
terms: “cognitivism,” noncognitivism, coherentism, eliminativism,
consequentialism, connectionism, etSuch terms in which moral Phil. is particularly fertile are in general
transposed into Fr. without change in a
sort of new, international philosophical language that has almost forgone tr..
More generally, in Eng. as in G. , words can be composed by joining two other
words far more easily than in Fr. —without specifying the logical connections
between the terms: toothbrush, pickpocket, lowlife, knownothing; or, for more
philosophical terms: aspect-blind, language-dependent, rule-following,
meaning-holism, observer-relative, which are translatable, of course, but not
without considerable awkwardness. Oxonian
philosophese. Oxonian Phil. seems to establish a language that is
stylistically neutral and appears to be transparently translatable. Certain
specific problems—the tr. of compound words and constructions that are more
flexible in Eng. and omnipresent in current philosophical discourse, such as
the thesis that la thèse selon laquelle, the question whether la question de
savoir si, and my saying that le fait que je dise que—make Fr. tr.s of contemporary Eng. philosophical texts
very awkward, even when the author writes in a neutral, commonplace style.
Instead, these difficulties, along with the ease of construction peculiar to
English, tend to encourage non-Oxonian analytical philosophers to write
directly in Gricese, following the example of many of their European
colleagues, or else to make use of a technical vernacular we have noted the
-isms and compounds that is frequently heavy going and not very inventive when
transRomang terms which are usually transliterated. This situation is certainly
attributable to the paradoxical character of Gricese, which established itself
as a philosophical language in the second half of the twentieth century: it is
a language that is apparently simple and accessible and that thus claims a kind
of universality but that is structured, both linguistically and
philosophically, around major stumbling blocks to do, -ing, etthat often make
it untranslatable. It is paradoxically this untranslatability, and not its
pseudo-transparency, that plays a crucial role in the process of
universalization. . IThe Austinian Paradigm: Ordinary Language and Phil. The proximity of ordinary language and
philosophical language, which is rooted in classical English-language Phil. ,
was theorized in the twentieth century by Austin and can be summed up in the
expression “‘ordinary’-language philosophy”. Ordinary language Phil. is interested This sort of overall
preeminence in Eng. of the verbal and the subjective over the nominal and the
objective is clear in the difference in the logic that governs the discourse of
affectivity in Fr. and in English. How
would something that one is correspond to something that one has, as in the
case of fear in Fr. avoir peur? It
follows that a Fr. man—who takes it for granted that fear is something that one
feels or senses—cannot feel at home with the difference that Eng. naturally
makes between something that has no objective correlative because it concerns
only feeling like fear; and what is available to sensation, implying that what
is felt through it has the status of an object. Thus in Eng. something is
immediately grasped that in Fr. v.ms a
strange paradox, viz. that passion, as Bentham notes in Deontology, is a
fictive entity. Thus what sounds in Fr.
like a nominalist provocation is implicated in the folds of the Eng.
language. A symbolic theory of affectivity is thus more easily undertaken in
Eng. than in Fr. , and if an ontological conception of affectivity had to be
formulated in English, symmetrical difficulties would be encountered. Reversible derivations Another particularity
of English, which is not without consequences in Phil. , is that its poverty
from the point of view of inflectional morphology is compensated for by the
freedom and facility it offers for the construction of all sorts of
derivatives. Nominal derivatives based on adjectives and using suffixes such as
-ity, -hood, -ness, -y. The resulting compounds are very difficult to
differentiate in Fr. and to translate in
general, which has led, in contemporary Fr.
tr.s, to various incoherent makeshifts. To list the most common
stumbling blocks: privacy privé-ité, innerness intériorité, not in the same
sense as interiority, vagueness caractère vague, goodness bonté, in the sense
of caractère bon, rightness justesse, “sameness,” similarité, in the sense of
mêmeté, ordinariness, “appropriateness,” caractère ordinaire, approprié,
unaccountability caractère de ce dont il est impossible de rendre compte.
Adjectival derivatives based on nouns, using numerous suffixes: -ful, -ous, -y,
-ic, -ish, -al e.g., meaningful, realistic, holistic, attitudinal, behavioral.
Verbal derivatives based on nouns or adjectives, with the suffixes -ize, -ify,
-ate naturalize, mentalize, falsify, and even without suffixes when possible
e.g., the title of an article “How Not to Russell Carnap’s Aufbau,” i.e., how
not to Russell Carnap’s Aufbau. d. Polycategorial derivatives based on verbs,
using suffixes such as -able, -er, -age, -ismrefutable, truthmaker. The
reversibility of these nominalizations and verbalizations has the essential
result of preventing the reification of qualities or acts. The latter is more
difficult to avoid in Fr. and G. , where
nominalization hardens and freezes notions compare intériorité and innerness,
which designates more a quality, or even, paradoxically, an effect, than an
entity or a domain. But this kind of ease in making compounds has its flip
side: the proliferation of -isms in liberties with the natural uses of the
language. The philosophers ask, e. g. , how they can know that there is a real
object there, but the question How do I know? can be asked in ordinary language
only in certain contexts, that is, where it is always possible, at least in
theory, to eliminate doubt. The doubt or question But is it a real one? has
always must have a special basis, there must be some reason for suggesting that
it isn’t real, in the sense of some specific way in which it is suggested that
this experience or item may be phoney. The wile of the metaphysician consists
in asking Is it a real table? a kind of object which has no obvious way of being
phoney and not specifying or limiting what may be wrong with it, so that I feel
at a loss how to prove it is a real one. It is the use of the word real in this
manner that leads us on to the supposition that real has a single meaning the
real world, material objects, and that a highly profound and puzzling one.
Austin, Philosophical Papers This analysis of real is taken up again in Sense
and Sensibilia, where Austin criticizes the notion of a sense datum and also a
certain way of raising problems supposedly on the basis of common opinion e. g.
, the common opinion that we really perceive things—but in reality on the basis
of a pure construction. To state the case in this way, Austin says, is simply
to soften up the plain man’s alleged views for the subsequent treatment; it is
preparing the way for, by practically attributing to him, the so-called
philosophers’ view. Phil. ’s frequent recourse to the ordinary is characterized
by a certain condescension toward the common man. The error or deception consists
in arguing the philosopher’s position against the ordinary position, because if
the in what we should say when. It is, in other words, a Phil. of language, but on the condition that we
never forget that we are looking not merely at words or ‘meanings,’ whatever
they may be but also at the realities we use the words to talk about, as Austin
emphasizes A Plea for Excuses, in Philosophical Papers. During the twentieth
century or more precisely, between the 1940s and the s, there was a division of
the paradigms of the Phil. of language
between the logical clarification of ordinary language, on the one hand, and
the immanent examination of ordinary language, on the other. The question of
ordinary language and the type of treatment that it should be given—a normative
clarification or an internal examination—is present in and even constitutive of
the legacy of logical positivism. Wittgenstein’s work testifies to this through
the movement that it manifests and performs, from the first task of the Phil. of language the creation of an ideal or
formal language to clarify everyday language to the second the concern to
examine the multiplicity of ordinary language’s uses. The break thus
accomplished is such that one can only agree with Rorty’s statement in his
preface to The Linguistic Turn that the only difference between Ideal Language
Philosophers and Ordinary Language Philosophers is a disagreement about which
language is ideal. In the renunciation of the idea of an ideal language, or a
norm outside language, there is a radical change in perspective that consists
in abandoning the idea of something beyond language: an idea that is
omnipresent in the whole philosophical tradition, and even in current
analytical Phil. . Critique of language and Phil. More generally, Austin criticizes traditional
Phil. for its perverse use of ordinary
language. He constantly denounces Phil. ’s abuse of ordinary language—not so
much that it forgets it, but rather that it exploits it by taking 2 A defect in
the Eng. language? Between according to Bentham Eng. philosophers are not very
inclined toward etymology—no doubt because it is often less traceable than it
is in G. or even in Fr. and discourages a certain kind of commentary.
There are, however, certain exceptions, like Jeremy Bentham’s analysis of the
words “in,” “or,” “between,” “and,” etc., -- cf. Grice on “to” and “or” – “Does
it make sense to speak of the ‘sense’ of ‘to’?” -- through which Eng.
constructs the kinds of space that belong to a very specific topiLet us take
the case of between, which Fr. can
render only by the word entre. Both the semantics and the etymology of entre
imply the number three in Fr. , since what is entre intervenes as a third term
between two others which it separates or brings closer in Lat., in-ter; in Fr.,
en tiers; as a third. This is not the case in English, which constructs between
in accord with the number two in conformity with the etymology of this word, by
tween, in pairs, to the point that it can imagine an ordering, even when it
involves three or more classes, only in the binary mode: comon between three?
relation between three?—the hue of selfcontradictoriness presents itself on the
very face of the phrase. By one of the words in it, the number of objects is
asserted to be three: by another, it is asserted to be no more than two. To the
use thus exclusively made of the word between, what could have given rise, but
a sort of general, howsoever indistinct, perception, that it is only one to one
that objects can, in any continued manner, be commodiously and effectually
compared. The Eng. language labours under a defect, which, when it is compared
in this particular with other European langues, may perhaps be found peculiar
to it. By the derivation, and thence by the inexcludible import, of the word
between i.e., by twain, the number of the objects, to which this operation is
represented as capable of being applied, is confined to two. By the Roman
inter—by its Fr. derivation entre—no
such limitation v.ms to be expressed. Chrestomathia REFS.: Bentham, Jeremy.
ChrestomathiEd. by M. J. Smith and W. H.
Burston. Oxford: Clarendon, To my mind, experience proves amply that we do come
to an agreement on what we should say when such and such a thing, though I
grant you it is often long and difficult. I should add that too often this is
what is missing in Phil. : a preliminary datum on which one might agree at the
outset. We do not claim in this way to discover all the truth that exists
regarding everything. We discover simply the facts that those who have been
using our language for centuries have taken the trouble to notice.
Performatif-Constatif Austinian agreement is possible for two reasons: Ordinary language cannot claim to have the
last word. Only remember, it is the first word Philosophical Papers. The
exploration of language is also an exploration of the inherited experience and
acumen of many generations of men ibid..
Ordinary language is a rich treasury of differences and embodies all the
distinctions men have found worth drawing, and the connections they have found
worth marking, in the lifetimes of many generations. These are certainly more
subtle and solid than any that you or I are likely to think up in our
arm-chairs of an afternoon ibid.. It is this ability to indicate differences
that makes language a common instrument adequate for speaking things in the
world. Who is we? Cavell’s question It is clear that analytical Phil. ,
especially as it has developed in the United States since the 1940s, has moved
away from the Austinian paradigm and has at the same time abandoned a certain
kind of philosophical writing and linguistic subtlety. But that only makes all
the more powerful and surprising the return to Austin advocated by Stanley
Cavell and the new sense of ordinary language Phil. that is emerging in his work and in
contemporary American Phil. . What right do we have to refer to our uses? And
who is this we so crucial for Austin that it constantly recurs in his work? All
we have, as we have said, is what we say and our linguistic agreements. We
determine the meaning of a given word by its uses, and for Austin, it is
nonsensical to ask the question of meaning for instance, in a general way or
looking for an entity; v. NONSENSE. The quest for agreement is founded on
something quite different from signification or the determination of the common
meaning. The agreement Austin is talking about has nothing to do with an
intersubjective consensus; it is not founded on a convention or on actual
agreements. It is an agreement that is as objective as possible and that bears
as much on language as on reality. But what is the precise nature of this
agreement? Where does it come from, and why should so much importance be
accorded to it? That is the question Cavell asks, first in Must We Mean What We
Say? and then in The Claim of Reason: what is it that allows Austin and Witters
to say what they say about what we say? A claim is certainly involved here.
That is what Witters means by our agreement in judgments, and in language it is
based only on itself, on the latter exists, it is not on the same level. The
philosopher introduces into the opinion of the common man particular entities,
in order then to reject, amend, or explain it. The method of ordinary language:
Be your size. Small Men. Austin’s immanent method comes down to examining our
ordinary use of ordinary words that have been confiscated by Phil. , such as
‘true’ and ‘real,’ in order to raise the question of truth: Fact that is a
phrase designed for use in situations where the distinction between a true
statement and the state of affairs about which it is a truth is neglected; as
it often is with advantage in ordinary life, though seldom in Phil. . So
speaking about the fact that is a compendious way of speaking about a situation
involving both words and world. Philosophical Papers We can, of course,
maintain along with a whole trend in analytical Phil. from Frege to Quine that these are
considerations too small and too trivial from which to draw any conclusions at
all. But it is this notion of fact that Austin relies on to determine the
nature of truth and thus to indicate the pertinence of ordinary language as a
relationship to the world. This is the nature of Austin’s approach: the foot of
the letter is the foot of the ladder ibid.. For Austin, ordinary words are part
of the world: we use words, and what makes words useful objects is their
complexity, their refinement as tools ibid.: We use words to inform ourselves
about the things we talk about when we use these words. Or, if that v.ms too
naïve: we use words as a way of better understanding the situation in which we
find ourselves led to make use of words. What makes this claim possible is the
proximity of dimension, of size, between words and ordinary objects. Thus
philosophers should, instead of asking whether truth is a substance, a quality,
or a relation, take something more nearly their own size to strain at ibid..
The Fr. translators render size by
mesure, which v.ms excessively theoretical; the reference is to size in the
material, ordinary sense. One cannot know everything, so why not try something
else? Advantages of slowness and cooperation. Be your size. Small Men.
Conversation cited by Urmson in A Symposium Austin emphasizes that this
technique of examining words which he ended up calling linguistic phenomenology
(and Grice linguistic botany) is not new and that it has existed since
Socrates, producing its slow successes. But Grice is the first to make a
systematic application of such a method, which is based, on the one hand, on
the manageability and familiarity of the objects concerned and, on the other
hand, on the common agreement at which it arrives in each of its stages. The
problem is how to agree on a starting point, that is, on a given. This given or
datum, for Grice, is Gricese, not as a corpus consisting of utterances or
words, but as the site of agreement about what we should say when. Austin
regards language as an empirical datum or experimental dat -- Bayes, T. . An
Essay towards Solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chances, with Richard
Price’s Foreword and Discussion. In Facsimiles of Two Papers by Bayes. :
Hafner, . First published in 176 Bentham, Jeremy. ChrestomathiEd. by M. J. Smith and W. H. Burston. Oxford:
Clarendon, . . Deontology. Ed. by
Goldworth. Oxford: Clarendon, . . Essay on Language. In The Works of Jeremy
Bentham, ed. by J. Bowring. Edinburgh:
W. Tait, 18384 Berkeley, George. Of Infinities. In vol. 2 of The Works,
ed. by Luce and T. E. Jessop, 4081
London: Nelson, 19485 Reprint, : Kraus, . . A Treatise concerning the
Principles of Human Knowledge. Ed. by J.
Dancy. Oxford: Oxford , . Cavell, Stanley. The Claim of Reason. : Oxford , . .
In Quest of the Ordinary. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, . . Must We
Mean What We Say? Cambridge: Cambridge , . . This New Yet Unapproachable
AmericAlbuquerque: Living Batch Press, . Chomsky, Noam. Syntactic Structures.
The Hague: Mouton, . Emerson, Ralph Waldo. Essays, First and Second Series. :
Library of America, . Hacking, Jan. Why Does Language Matter to Phil. ? Cambridge:
Cambridge , . Hume, D. . Dialogues concerning Natural Religion. Ed. by D. Coleman. Cambridge: Cambridge , . .
Essays, Moral, Political and Literary Ed.
by E. F. Miller. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Classics, . . A Treatise of
Human Nature. Ed. by L. Selby-Bigge.
Oxford: Oxford . 197 Laugier, SandrDu réel à l’ordinaire. : Vrin, . .
Recommencer la philosophie. : Presses Universitaires de France, . Locke, J.. An
Essay concerning Human Understanding. Oxford: Oxford , . Mill, J. Stuart.
Considerations on Representative Government. In Essays on Pol. and Society,
vol. 19 of Collected Works, ed. by J. M.
Robson. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, . . Essays on Ethics, Religion
and Society. Vol. 10 of Collected Works, ed.
by J. M. Robson. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, . . A System of
Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, .
Nedeljkovic, Maryvonne. D. Hume,
approche phénoménologique de l’action et théorie linguistique. : Presses
Universitaires de France, . Pinker, Steven. The Language Instinct: The New
Science of Language and Mind. London: Penguin, . Putnam, Hilary. Mind, Language
and Reality. Vol. 2 of Philosophical Papers. Cambridge: Cambridge , . . Realism
with a Human Face. Ed. by J.
Conant. , . Quine, Willard V. From a
Logical Point of View. , 195 . Word and
Object. , . Ricœur, Paul. Memory, History, Forgetting. Tr. K. Blamey and D. Pellauer. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, . Rorty, Richard, ed. The Linguistic Turn.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, . First published . Russell, Bertrand.
The Analysis of Matter. London: Allen and Unwin, 195 . An Inquiry into Meaning
and Truth. : Routledge, . First published in 1950. Tesnière, Lucien. Éléments
de syntaxe structural. : Klincksieck, . Urmson, J. O., W.V.O. Quine, and S.
Hampshire. A Symposium on Austin’s Method. In Symposium on J. L. Austin,
ed. by K. T. Fann. London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul, . Wittgenstein, Ludwig. The Blue and the Brown Books. Ed. by R. Rhees. Oxford: Blackwell, . First
published in 195 . Philosophical Investigations. Tr. G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell, 195 we,
as Cavell says in a passage that illustrates many of the difficulties of tr. we
have discussed up to this point: We learn and teach words in certain contexts,
and then we are expected, and expect others, to be able to project them into
further contexts. Nothing ensures that this projection will take place in
particular, not the grasping of universals nor the grasping of books of rules,
just as nothing ensures that we will make, and understand, the same
projections. That we do, on the whole, is a matter of our sharing routes of
interest and feeling, modes of response, senses of humor and ‑of significance
and of fulfillment, of what is outrageous, of what is similar to what else,
what a rebuke, what forgiveness, of when an utterance is an assertion, when an
appeal, when an explanation—all the whirl of organism Witterscalls forms of
life. Human speech and activity, sanity and community, rest upon nothing more,
but nothing less, than this. It is a vision as simple as it is and because it
is terrifying. Must We Mean What We Say?
The fact that our ordinary language is based only on itself is not only a
reason for concern regarding the validity of what we do and say, but also the
revelation of a truth about ourselves that we do not always want to recognize:
the fact that I am the only possible source of such a validity. That is a new
understanding of the fact that language is our form of life, precisely its
ordinary form. Cavell’s originality lies in his reinvention of the nature of
ordinary language in American thought and in the connection he
establishes—notably through his reference to Emerson and Thoreau, American
thinkers of the ordinary—between this nature of language and human nature,
finitude. It is also in this sense that the question of linguistic agreements
reformulates that of the ordinary human condition and that the acceptance of
the latter goes hand in hand with the recognition of the former. In Cavell’s
Americanization of ordinary language Phil.
there thus emerges a radical form of the return to the ordinary. But
isn’t this ordinary, e. g. , that of Emerson in his Essays, precisely the one
that the whole of Eng. Phil. has been
trying to find, or rather to feel or taste, since its origins? Thus we can
compare the writing of Emerson or James, in texts like Experience or Essays in
Radical Empiricism, with that of the British empiricists when they discuss
experience, the given, and the sensible. This is no doubt one of the principal
dimensions of philosophical writing in English: always to make the meaning more
available to the senses. J.-Pierre Cléro Sandra Laugier REFS.: Austin, J. L.
How to Do Things with Words. Oxford: Clarendon, . . Performatif-Constatif. In
La philosophie analytique, ed. by J.
Wahl and L. Beck. : Editions du Minuit, . Tr. in Performative-Constative. In
Phil. and Ordinary Language, ed. by E. Caton. Urbana: University of Illinois
Press, . . Philosophical Papers. Ed. by
J. O. Urmson and G. J. Warnock. Oxford: Clarendon, . . Sense and
SensibiliOxford: Clarendon, . Ayer, J. The Foundations of Empirical Knowledge.
London: Macmillan, 1940. ENTREPRENEUR 265 form the basis of the kingdom by
means of calculated plans; to the legal domain: someone who contravenes the
hierarchical order of the professions and subverts their rules; finally, to the
economic domain: someone who agrees, on the basis of a prior contract an
established price to execute a project collection of taxes, supply of an army,
a merchant expedition, construction, production, transaction, assuming the
hazards related to exchange and time. This last usage corresponds to practices
that became more and more socially prominent starting in the sixteenth century.
Let us focus on the term in economics. The engagement of the entrepreneur in
his project may be understood in various ways, and the noun entrepreneur
translated in various ways into English: by contractor if the stress is placed
on the engagement with regard to the client to execute the task according to
conditions negotiated in advance a certain time, a fixed price, firm price,
tenant farming; by undertaker now rare in this sense when we focus on the
engagement in the activity, taking charge of the project, its practical
realization, the setting in motion of the transaction; and by adventurer,
enterpriser, and projector, to emphasize the risks related to speculation. At
the end of the eighteenth century, the Fr.
word entreprise acquired the new meaning of an industrial establishment.
Entrepreneur accordingly acquired the sense of the head or direction of a
business of production superintendent, employer, manager. In France, at the
beginning of the eighteenth century, the noun entrepreneur had strong political
connotations, in particular in the abundant pamphlets containing mazarinades
denouncing the entrepreneurs of tax farming. The economist Pierre de
Boisguilbert wrote the Factum de la France, the largest trial ever conducted by
pen against the big financiers, entrepreneurs of the wealth of the kingdom, who
take advantage of its good administration its political economy in the name of
the entrepreneurs of commerce and industry, who contribute to the increase in
its wealth. Boisguilbert failed in his project of reforming the tax farm, or
tax business, and it was left to a clever financier, Richard Cantillon, to
create the economic concept of the entrepreneur. Chance in Business: Risk and
Uncertainty There is no trace of Boisguilbert’s moral indignation in
Cantillon’s Essai sur la nature du commerce en générale Essay on the nature of
commerce in general. Having shown that all the classes and all the men of a
State live or acquire wealth at the expense of the owners of the land bk. 1,
ch.12, he suggests that the circulation and barter of goods and merchandise,
like their production, are conducted in Europe by entrepreneurs and haphazardly
bk. 1, of ch.1 He then describes in detail what composes the uncertain aspect
of the action of an entrepreneur, in which he acts according to his ideas and
without being able to predict, in which he conceives and executes his plans
surrounded by the hazard of events. The uncertainty related to business profits
turns especially on the fact that it is dependent on the forms of consumption
of the owners, the only members of society who are independent—naturally
independent, Cantillon specified. Entrepreneurs are those who are capable of
breaking ÉNONCÉ Énoncé, from the Roman enuntiare to express, divulge; from ex
out and nuntiare to make known; a nuntius is a messenger, a nuncio, ranges over
the same type of entity as do proposition and phrase: it is a basic unit of
syntax, the relevant question being whether or not it is the bearer of truth
values. An examination of the differences among these entities, and the
networks they constitute in different languages especially in English:
sentence, statement, utterance, appears under PROPOSITION. V. also DICTUM and
LOGOS, both of which may be acceptably Tr.
énoncé. Cf. PRINCIPLE, SACHVERHALT, TRUTH, WORD especially WORD,
Box The essential feature of an énoncé
is that it is considered to be a singular occurrence and thus is paired with
its énonciation: v. SPEECH ACT; cf. ENGLISH, LANGUAGE, SENSE, SIGN,
SIGNIFIER/SIGNIFIED, WITTICISM. v. DISCOURSE
ENTREPRENEUR FR. ENG. adventurer,
contractor, employer, enterpriser, entrepreneur, manager, projector,
undertaker, superintendent v. ACT,
AGENCY, BERUF, ECONOMY, LIBERAL, OIKONOMIA, PRAXIS, UTILITY. Refs.: G. J.
Warnock, “English philosophy,” H. P. Grice, “Gricese,” BANC.
Grice’s handwave. A sort of handwave can mean in a one-off act of
communication something. It’s the example he uses. By a sort of handwave, the
emissor communicates either that he knows the route or that he is about to
leave the addressee. Handwave signals. Code. Cfr. the Beatles’s HELP.
Explicatum: We need some body – Implicatum: Not just Any Body. Why does this
matter to the philosopher? The thing is as follows. Grice was provoked by
Austin. To defeat Austin, Grice needs a ‘theory of communication.’ This theory
applies his early reflections on the intentional side to an act of
communication. This allows him to explain the explicatum versus the implicatum.
By analysing each, Grice notes that there is no need to refer to linguistic
entities. So, the centrality of the handwave is an offshoot of his theory
designed to defeat Austin.
Grice’s myth. Or Griceian myths – The Handbook of Griceian mythology. At
one point Grice suggests that his ‘genitorial programme’ a kind of
ideal-observer theory is meant as ‘didactic,’ and for expository purposes. It
seems easier, as , as Grice and Plato would agree, to answer a question
about the genitorial programme rather than use a first-person approach and
appeal to introspection. Grice refers to the social
contract as a ‘myth,’ which may still explain, as ‘meaning’ does. G. R. Grice
built his career on this myth. This is G. R. Grice, of the social-contract
fame. Cf. Strawson and Wiggins comparing Grice’s myth with Plato’s, and they
know what they are talking about.
Grice’s predicament. S draws a pic- "one-off predicament"). ...
Clarendon, 1976); and Simon
Blackburn, Spreading the Word (Oxford: Clarendon, 1984) ... But
there is an obvious way of emending the account. Grice points out. ... Blackburn helpfully
suggests that we can cut through much of this complexity by ... The above
account is intended to capture the notion of one-off meaning. Walking in a
forest, having gone some way ahead of the rest of the party, I draw an arrow at
a fork of a path, meaning that those who are following me should go straight
on. Gricean considerations
may be safely ignored. Only when trying to communicate by nonconventional means
("one-off predicament," Blackburn,
1984, chap. Blackburn's mission
is to promote the philosophy of language as a pivotal enquiry ... and
dismissed; the Gricean model
might be suitable to explain one-off acts. The Gricean mechanism
with its complex communicative intentions has a clear point in what Blackburn calls
“a one-off predicament”
- a situation in which an ...
Grice’s shaggy-dog story: While Grice would like to say that it should be in the
range of a rational creature to refer and to predicate, what about the hand
wave? By his handwave, the emissor means that _HE_ (subject) is a knower of the
road (or roate), the predicate after the copula or that he, the emissor,
subject, is (the copula) about to leave his emissee – but there is nothing IN
THE MATTER (the handwave) that can be ‘de-composed’ like that. The FORM
attaches to the communicatum directly. This is strange, but not impossible, and
shows Grice’s programme. Because his idea is that a communicatum need not a
vehicile which is syntactically structured (as “Fido is shaggy”). This is the
story that Grice tells in his lecture. He uses a ‘shaggy-dog’ story to explain
TWO main notions: that of ‘reference’ or denotatio, and that of predicatio. He
had explored that earlier when discussing, giving an illustration “Smith is
happy”, the idea of ‘value,’ as correspondence, where he adds the terms for
‘denote’ and ‘predicatio,’ or actually, ‘designatio’ and ‘indicatio’, need to
be “explained within the theory.” In the utterance ‘Smith is happy,’ the
utterer DESIGNATES an item, Smith. The utterer also INDICATES some class,
‘being happy.’ Grice introduces a shorthand, ‘assign’, or ‘assignatio,’
previous to the value-satisfaction, to involve both the ‘designatio’ and the
‘indicatio’. U assigns the item Smith to the class ‘being happy.’ U’s intention
involves A’s belief that U believes that “the item belongs to the class, or
that he ASSIGNS the item to the class. A predicate, such as
'shaggy,' in my shaggy-dog story, is a part of a bottom-up, or top-bottom, as I
prefer, analysis of this or that sentences, and a predicate, such as 'shaggy,'
is the only indispensable 'part,' or 'element,' as I prefer, since a
predicate is the only 'pars orationis,' to use the old phrase, that must
appear in every sentence. In a later lecture he ventures with ‘reference.’ Lewis
and Short have “rĕferre,” rendered as “to bear, carry, bring, draw, or give
back,” in a “transf.” usage, they render as “to make a reference, to refer
(class.),” asa in “de rebus et obscuris et incertis ad Apollinem censeo
referendum; “ad quem etiam Athenienses publice de majoribus rebus semper
rettulerunt,” Cic. Div. 1, 54, 122.” While Grice uses ‘Fido,’ he could have
used ‘Pegasus’ (Martin’s cat, as it happens) and apply Quine’s adage: we could
have appealed to the ex hypothesi unanalyzable, irreducible attribute of being
Pegasus, adopting, for its expression, the verb 'is-Pegasus', or 'pegasizes'.
And Grice could have played with ‘predicatio’ and ‘subjectio.’ Grice on
subject. Lewis and Short have “sūbĭcĭo,” (less correctly subjĭcĭo ;
post-Aug. sometimes sŭb- ), jēci, jectum, 3, v. a. sub-jacio. which they render as “to throw, lay, place,
or bring under or near (cf. subdo),” and in philosophy, “subjectum , i, n. (sc.
verbum), as “that which is spoken of, the foundation or subject of a
proposition;” “omne quicquid dicimus aut
subjectum est aut de subjecto aut in subjecto est. Subjectum est prima substantia,
quod ipsum nulli accidit alii inseparabiliter, etc.,” Mart. Cap. 4, § 361; App.
Dogm. Plat. 3, p. 34, 4 et saep.—.” Note that for Mart. Cap. the ‘subject,’
unlike the ‘predicate’ is not a ‘syntactical category.’ “Subjectum est prima
substantia,” The subject is a prote ousia. As for correlation, Grice ends up
with a reductive analysis. By uttering utterance-token V, the utterer U
correlates predicate P1 with (and only with) each member of P2 ≡ (∃R)(∃R') (1) U effects that (∀x)(R P1x ≡
x ∈ P1) and (2) U
intends (1), and (3) U intends that (∀y)(R'
P1y ≡ y ∈
P1), where R' P1 is an expression-type such that utterance-token V is a
sequence consisting of an expression-token p1 of expression-type P1 and an
expression-token p2 of expression-type P2, the R-co-relatum of which is a
set of which y is a member. And he is back with ‘denotare. Lewis and Short have
“dēnŏtare,” which they render as “to mark, set a mark on, with chalk, color,
etc.: “pedes venalium creta,”
It is interesting to trace Grice’s earliest investigations on this. Grice and
Strawson stage a number of joint seminars on topics related to the notions of
meaning, categories, and logical form. Grice and Strawson engage in systematic
and unsystematic philosophical exploration. From these discussions springs work
on predication and categories, one or two reflections of which are acknowledge
at two places (re: the reductive analysis of a ‘particular,’ “the tallest man
that did, does, or will exist” --) in Strawson’s “Particular and general” for
The Aristotelian Society – and “visible” as Grice puts it, but not
acknowledged, in Strawson’s “Individuals: an essay in descriptive
metaphysics.””
Grice’s
theory-theory: “I am perhaps not too happy with
the word ‘theory,’ as applied to this, but that’s Ramsey for you” (WoW: 285). Grice’s theory-theory: A theory of mind concerning
how we come to know about the propositional attitudes of others. It tries to
explain the nature of ascribing certain thoughts, beliefs, or intentions to
other persons in order to explain their actions. The theory-theory holds that
in ascribing beliefs to others we are tacitly applying a theory that enables us
to make inferences about the beliefs behind the actions of others. The theory
that is applied is a set of rules embedded in folk psychology. Hence, to
anticipate and predict the behavior of others, one engages in an intellectual
process moving by inference from one set of
beliefs to another. This position contrasts with another theory of mind, the
simulation theory, which holds that we need to make use of our own motivational
and emotional resources and capacities for practical reasoning in explaining
actions of others. “So called ‘theory-theorists’ maintain that the ability to
explain and predict behaviour is underpinned by a folk-psychological theory of
the structure and functioning of the mind – where the theory in question may be
innate and modularised, learned individually, or acquired through a process of
enculturation.” Carruthers and Smith (eds.), Theories of Theories of Mind. Grice
needs a theory. For those into implicata and conversation as rational
cooperation, when introducing the implicatum he mentions ‘pre-theoretical
adequacy’ of the model. So he is thinking of the conversational theory as a
theory in the strict sense, with ‘explanatory’ and not merely taxonomical
power. So one task is to examine in which way the conversational theory is a
theory that explains, rather than merely ad hoc ex post facto commentary. Not so much for his approach to mean. He
polemises with Rountree, of Somerville, that you dont need a thory to analyse
mean. Indeed, you cannot have a theory to analyse mean, because mean is a
matter of intuition, not a theoretical concept. But Grice appeals to theory,
when dealing with willing. He knows what willing means because he relies on a
concept of folk-science. In this folk-science, willing is a theoretical
concept. Grice arrived at this conclusion by avoiding the adjective souly, and
seeing that there is no word to describe willing other than by saying it is a
psychoLOGICAL concept, i.e. part of a law within that theory of folk-science.
That law will include, by way of ramsified naming or describing willing as a
predicate-constant. Now, this is related to metaphysics. His liberal or
ecunmenical metaphysics is best developed in terms of his ontological marxism
presented just after he has expanded on this idea of willing as a theoretical
concept, within a law involving willing (say, Grices Optimism-cum-Pesimism
law), within the folk-science of psychology that explains his behaviour. For
Aristotle, a theoria, was quite a different animal, but it had to do with
contemplatio, hence the theoretical (vita contemplativa) versus the practical
(vita activa). Grices sticking to Aristotle’srare use of theory inspires him to
develop his fascinating theory of the theory-theory. Grice realised that there is no way to refer
to things like intending except with psychological, which he takes to mean,
belonging to a pscyhological theory. Grice was keen to theorise on theorising. He
thought that Aristotle’s first philosophy (prote philosophia) is best rendered
as Theory-theory. Grice kept using Oxonian English spelling, theorising, except
when he did not! Grice calls himself folksy: his theories, even if
Subjects to various types of Ramseyfication, are popular in kind! And
ceteris paribus! Metaphysical construction is disciplined and the best
theorising the philosopher can hope for! The way Grice conceives of his
theory-theory is interesting to revisit. A route by which Grice hopes to show
the centrality of metaphysics (as prote philosophia) involves taking seriously
a few ideas. If any region of enquiry is to be successful as
a rational enterprise, its deliverance must be expressable in the
shape of one or another of the possibly different types of theory. A
characterisation of the nature and range of a possible kind of
theory θ is needed. Such a body of characterisation must itself
be the outcome of rational enquiry, and so must itself exemplify whatever
requirement it lays down for any theory θ in general. The
characterisation must itself be expressible as a
theory θ, to be called, if you like, Grice politely puts it,
theory-theory, or meta-theory, θ2. Now, the specification and justification
of the ideas and material presupposed by any theory θ, whether
such account falls within the bounds of Theory-theory, θ2 would be
properly called prote philosophia (first philosophy) and may turn out to relate
to what is generally accepted as belonging to the Subjects matter of
metaphysics. It might, for example, turn out to be establishable that any
theory θ has to relate to a certain range of this or that Subjects
item, has to attribute to each item this or that predicate or attribute, which
in turn has to fall within one or another of the range of types or
categories. In this way, the enquiry might lead to recognised metaphysical
topics, such as the nature of being, its range of application, the nature of
predication and a systematic account of categories. Met. , philosophical
eschatology, and Platos Republic, Thrasymachus, social justice, Socrates, along
with notes on Zeno, and topics for pursuit, repr.in Part II, Explorations in
semantics and metaphysics to WOW , metaphysics, philosophical
eschatology, Platos Republic, Socrates, Thrasymachus, justice, moral right,
legal right, Athenian dialectic. Philosophical eschatology is a sub-discipline
of metaphysics concerned with what Grice calls a category shift. Grice, having
applied such a technique to Aristotle’s aporia on philos (friend) as alter ego,
uses it now to tackle Socratess view, against Thrasymachus, that right applies
primarily to morality, and secondarily to legality. Grice has a specific reason
to include this in his WOW Grices exegesis of Plato on justice displays Grices
take on the fact that metaphysics needs to be subdivided into ontology proper
and what he calls philosophical eschatology, for the study of things like
category shift and other construction routines. The exploration of Platos
Politeia thus becomes an application of Grices philosophically eschatological
approach to the item just, as used by Socrates (morally just) and Thrasymachus
(legally just). Grice has one specific essay on Aristotle in PPQ. So he thought
Plato merited his own essay, too! Grices focus is on Plato’s exploration of
dike. Grice is concerned with a neo-Socratic (versus neo-Thrasymachean) account
of moral justice as conceptually (or axiologically) prior to legal justice. In
the proceeding, he creates philosophical eschatology as the other branch to metaphysics,
along with good ol ontology. To say that just crosses a categorial barrier
(from the moral to the legal) is to make a metaphysical, strictly
eschatological, pronouncement. The Grice Papers locate the Plato essay in s. II, the Socrates essay in s. III, and the Thrasymachus essay, under social
justice, in s. V. Grice is well aware that in his account of fairness, Rawls
makes use of his ideas on personal identity. The philosophical elucidation of
fairness is of great concern for Grice. He had been in touch with such
explorations as Nozicks and Nagels along anti-Rawlsian lines. Grices ideas on
rationality guide his exploration of social justice. Grice keeps revising the
Socrates notes. The Plato essay he actually dates. As it happens, Grices most
extensive published account of Socrates is in this commentary on Platos
Republic: an eschatological commentary, as he puts it. In an entertaining
fashion, Grice has Socrates, and neo-Socrates, exploring the logic and grammar
of just against the attack by Thrasymachus and neo-Thrasymachus. Grices point
is that, while the legal just may be conceptually prior to the moral just, the
moral just is evaluationally or axiologically prior. Refs.: There is a specific
essay on ‘theorising’ in the Grice Papers, but there are scattered sources
elsewhere, such as “Method” (repr. in “Conception”), BANC.
Grice’s three-year-old’s guide to Russell’s theory of types, with an
advice to parents by Strawson: Grice put forward the empirical hypothesis that a
three-year old CAN understand Russell’s theory of types. “In more than one
way.” This brought confusion in the household, with some members saying they
could not – “And I trust few of your tutees do!” Russell’s influential solution
to the problem of logical paradoxes. The theory was developed in particular to
overcome Russell’s paradox, which seemed to destroy the possibility of Frege’s
logicist program of deriving mathematics from logic. Suppose we ask whether the
set of all sets which are not members of themselves is a member of itself. If
it is, then it is not, but if it is not, then it is. The theory of types
suggests classifying objects, properties, relations, and sets into a hierarchy
of types. For example, a class of type 0 has members that are ordinary objects;
type 1 has members that are properties of objects of type 0; type 2 has members
that are properties of the properties in type 1; and so on. What can be true or
false of items of one type can not significantly be said about those of another
type and is simply nonsense. If we observe the prohibitions against classes
containing members of different types, Russell’s paradox and similar paradoxes
can be avoided. The theory of types has two variants. The simple theory of
types classifies different objects and properties, while the ramified theory of
types further sorts types into levels and adds a hierarchy of levels to that of
types. By restricting predicates to those that relate to items of lower types
or lower levels within their own type, predicates giving rise to paradox are
excluded. The simple theory of types is sufficient for solving logical
paradoxes, while the ramified theory of type is introduced to solve semantic
paradoxes, that is, paradoxes depending on notions such as reference and truth.
“Any expression containing an apparent variable is of higher type than that
variable. This is the fundamental principles of the doctrines of types.”
Russell, Logic and Knowledge. Grice’s
commentary in “In defense of a dogma,” The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC.
villa grice: While Grice loved Academia, he also loved non-Academia. He
would socialize at the Flag and Lamb, at the Bird and Baby, and the cricket
club, at the bridge club, etc. In this way, he goes back to Plato’s idea of an
‘academy,’ established
by Plato at his villa outside Athens near the public park and gymnasium known
by that name. Although it may not have maintained a continuous tradition, the
many and varied philosophers of the Academy all considered themselves Plato’s
successors, and all of them celebrated and studied his work. The school
survived in some form until A.D. 529, when it was dissolved, along with the
other pagan schools, by the Eastern Roman emperor Justinian I. The history of
the Academy is divided by some authorities into that of the Old Academy Plato,
Speusippus, Xenocrates, and their followers and the New Academy the Skeptical
Academy of the third and second centuries B.C.. Others speak of five phases in
its history: Old as before, Middle Arcesilaus, New Carneades, Fourth Philo of
Larisa, and Fifth Antiochus of Ascalon. For most of its history the Academy was
devoted to elucidating doctrines associated with Plato that were not entirely
explicit in the dialogues. These “unwritten doctrines” were apparently passed
down to his immediate successors and are known to us mainly through the work of
Aristotle: there are two opposed first principles, the One and the Indefinite
Dyad Great and Small; these generate Forms or Ideas which may be identified
with numbers, from which in turn come intermediate mathematicals and, at the
lowest level, perceptible things Aristotle, Metaphysics I.6. After Plato’s
death, the Academy passed to his nephew Speusippus, who led the school until
his death. Although his written works have perished, his views on certain main
points, along with some quotations, were recorded by surviving authors. Under
the influence of late Pythagoreans, Speusippus anticipated Plotinus by holding
that the One transcends being, goodness, and even Intellect, and that the Dyad
which he identifies with matter is the cause of all beings. To explain the
gradations of beings, he posited gradations of matter, and this gave rise to
Aristotle’s charge that Speusippus saw the universe as a series of disjointed
episodes. Speusippus abandoned the theory of Forms as ideal numbers, and gave
heavier emphasis than other Platonists to the mathematicals. Xenocrates who
once went with Plato to Sicily, succeeded Speusippus and led the Academy till
his own death. Although he was a prolific author, Xenocrates’ works have not
survived, and he is known only through the work of other authors. He was
induced by Aristotle’s objections to reject Speusippus’s views on some points,
and he developed theories that were a major influence on Middle Platonism, as
well as on Stoicism. In Xenocrates’ theory the One is Intellect, and the Forms
are ideas in the mind of this divine principle; the One is not transcendent,
but it resides in an intellectual space above the heavens. While the One is
good, the Dyad is evil, and the sublunary world is identified with Hades.
Having taken Forms to be mathematical entities, he had no use for intermediate
mathematicals. Forms he defined further as paradigmatic causes of regular
natural phenomena, and soul as self-moving number. Polemon led the Academy, and
was chiefly known for his fine character, which set an example of self-control
for his students. The Stoics probably derived their concept of oikeiosis an
accommodation to nature from his teaching. After Polemon’s death, his colleague
Crates led the Academy until the accession of Arcesilaus. The New Academy arose
when Arcesilaus became the leader of the school and turned the dialectical
tradition of Plato to the Skeptical aim of suspending belief. The debate
between the New Academy and Stoicism dominated philosophical discussion for the
next century and a half. On the Academic side the most prominent spokesman was
Carneades. In the early years of the first century B.C., Philo of Larisa
attempted to reconcile the Old and the New Academy. His pupil, the former Skeptic
Antiochus of Ascalon, was enraged by this and broke away to refound the Old
Academy. This was the beginning of Middle Platonism. Antiochus’s school was
eclectic in combining elements of Platonism, Stoicism, and Aristotelian
philosophy, and is known to us mainly through Cicero’s Academica. Middle
Platonism revived the main themes of Speusippus and Xenocrates, but often used
Stoic or neo-Pythagorean concepts to explain them. The influence of the Stoic
Posidonius was strongly felt on the Academy in this period, and Platonism
flourished at centers other than the Academy in Athens, most notably in
Alexandria, with Eudorus and Philo of Alexandria. After the death of Philo, the
center of interest returned to Athens, where Plutarch of Chaeronia studied with
Ammonius at the Academy, although Plutarch spent most of his career at his home
in nearby Boeotia. His many philosophical treatises, which are rich sources for
the history of philosophy, are gathered under the title Moralia; his interest
in ethics and moral education led him to write the Parallel Lives paired
biographies of famous Romans and Athenians, for which he is best known. After
this period, the Academy ceased to be the name for a species of Platonic
philosophy, although the school remained a center for Platonism, and was
especially prominent under the leadership of the Neoplatonist Proclus.
griceism. Gricese. At Oxford, it was usual to refer to Austin’s
idiolect as Austinese. In analogy with Grecism, we have a Gricism, a Griceian
cliché. Cf. a ‘grice’ and ‘griceful’ in ‘philosopher’s lexicon.’ Gricese is a
Latinism, from -ese, word-forming element, from Old French -eis (Modern French -ois, -ais), from Vulgar Latin, from Latin -ensem, -ensis "belonging
to" or "originating in."
grecianism: why was Grice obsessed with Socrates’s convesations? He
does not say. But he implicates it. For the Athenian dialecticians, it is all a
matter of ta legomena. Ditto for the Oxonian dialecticians. Ta legomena becomes
ordinary language. And the task of the philosopher is to provide reductive
analysis of this or that concept in terms of necessary and sufficient
conditions. Cf. Hospers. Grices review of the history of philosophy (Philosophy
is but footnotes to Zeno.). Grice enjoyed Zenos answer, What is a friend? Alter
ego, Allego. ("Only it was the other Zeno." Grice tried to apply the
Socratic method during his tutorials. "Nothing like a heartfelt dedication
to the Socratic art of mid-wifery, seeking to bring forth error and to strangle
it at birth.” μαιεύομαι (A.“μαῖα”), ‘to serve as a midwife, act a; “ἡ
Ἄρτεμις μ.” Luc. D Deor.26.2. 2. cause delivery to take place, “ἱκανὴ ἔκπληξις
μαιεύσασθαι πρὸ τῆς ὥρας” Philostr. VA1.5. 3. c. acc., bring to the birth,
Marin.Procl.6; ὄρνιθας μ. hatch chickens, Anon. ap. Suid.; αἰετὸν κάνθαρος
μαιεύσομαι, prov. of taking vengeance on a powerful enemy, Ar. Lys.695 (cf.
Sch.). 4. deliver a woman, esp. metaph. in Pl. of the Socratic method, Tht.
149b. II. Act., Poll. 4.208, Sch. OH.4.506. Pass., τὰ ὑπ᾽ ἐμοῦ μαιευθέντα
brought into the world by me, Pl. Tht. 150e, cf. Philostr.VA5.13. Refs.: the
obvious references are Grice’s allusions to Aristotle, Plato, Socrates, Zeno,
The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC.
No comments:
Post a Comment