Agitation. A Byzantine
feeling is a Ryleian agitation. . If Grice
were to advance the not wholly plausible thesis that “to feel Byzantine” is
just to have a an anti-rylean agitation which is caused by the thought that
Grice is or might *be* Byzantine, it would surely be ridiculous to criticize
Grice on the grounds that Grice saddles himself with an ontological commitment
to feelings, or to modes of feeling. And why? Well, because, alla Parsons, if a
quantifier is covertly involved at all, it will only be a universal quantifier which
in such a case as this is more than adequately handled by a substitutional
account of quantification. Grice’s situation vis-a-vis the ‘proposition’ is in
no way different. The word ‘emotion’
is used to designate at least three or four different kinds of things, which I
shall call ‘inclinations’ (or ‘motives’), ‘moods’, ‘agitations’ (or ‘commotions’)
and ‘feelings’. Inclinations and moods, including agitations, are not
occurrences and do not therefore take place either publicly or privately. They
are propensities, not acts or states. They are, however, propensities of
different kinds, and their differences are important. Feelings, on the other
hand, are occurrences, but the place that mention of them should take in
descriptions of human behaviour is very different from that which the standard
theories accord to it. susceptibilities to specific agitations are on the same
general footing with inclinations, namely that both are general propensities
and not occurrences. Agitations are not motives. But agitations presuppose
motives, or rather they presuppose behaviour trends of which motives are for us
the most interesting sort. There
is however a linguistic matter which is the source of some confusion. There are
some words which signify both inclinations and agitations, besides some which
never signify anything but agitations, and others again which never signify
anything but inclinations. Words like ‘uneasy’, ‘anxious’, ‘distressed’,
‘excited’, ‘startled’ always signify agitations. Phrases like ‘fond of
fishing’, ‘keen on gardening’, ‘bent on becoming a bishop’ never signify
agitations. But words like ‘love’, ‘want’, ‘desire’, ‘proud’, ‘eager’ and many
others stand sometimes for simple inclinations and sometimes for agitations
which are resultant upon those inclinations and interferences with the exercise
of them. Thus ‘hungry’ in the sense of ‘having a good appetite’ means roughly
‘is eating or would eat heartily and without sauces, etc.’; but this is
different from the sense in which a person might be said to be ‘too hungry to
concentrate on his work’. Hunger in this second sense is a distress, and
requires for its existence the conjunction of an appetite with the inability to
eat. Similarly the sense in which a boy is proud of his school is different
from the sense in which he is speechless with pride on being unexpectedly given
a place in a school team. To remove a possible misapprehension, it must be
pointed out that not all agitations are disagreeable. People voluntarily
subject themselves to suspense, fatigue, uncertainty, perplexity, fear and
surprise in such practices as angling, rowing, travelling, crossword puzzles,
rock-climbing and joking. That thrills, raptures, surprise, amusement and
relief are agitations is shown by the fact that we can say that someone is too
much thrilled, amused or relieved to act, think or talk coherently. It is helpful to
notice that, anyhow commonly, the word which completes the phrase ‘pang of . .
.’ or ‘chill of . . .’ is the name of an agitation. I shall now argue that
feelings are intrinsically connected with agitations and are not intrinsically
connected with inclinations, save in so far as inclinations are factors in
agitations. But I am not trying to establish a novel psychological hypothesis;
I am trying to show only that it is part of the logic of our descriptions of
feelings that they are signs of agitations and are not exercises of
inclinations. Feelings are not among the sorts of things of which it makes
sense to ask from what motives they issue. The same is true, for the same
reasons, of other signs of agitations. Feelings, in other words, are not among
the sorts of things of which it makes sense to ask from what motives they
issue. The same is true, for the same reasons, of the other signs of
agitations. This point shows why we were right to suggest above that feelings
do not belong directly to simple inclinations. An inclination is a certain sort
of proneness or readiness to do certain sorts of things on purpose. These
things are therefore describable as being done from that motive. They are the
exercises of the disposition that we call ‘a motive’. Feelings are not from
motives and are therefore not among the possible exercises of such
propensities. The widespread theory that a motive such as vanity, or affection,
is in the first instance a disposition to experience certain specific feelings
is therefore absurd. There are, of course, tendencies to have feelings; being
vertiginous and rheumatic are such tendencies. But we do not try to modify
tendencies of these kinds by sermons. What feelings do causally belong to are
agitations; they are signs of agitations in the same sort of way as
stomach-aches are signs of indigestion. Roughly, we do not, as the prevalent
theory holds, act purposively because we experience feelings; we experience
feelings, as we wince and shudder, because we are inhibited from acting
purposively. Sentimentalists
are people who indulge in induced feelings without acknowledging the
fictitiousness of their agitations.
Friday, May 1, 2020
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment