The Grice Club

Welcome

The Grice Club

The club for all those whose members have no (other) club.

Is Grice the greatest philosopher that ever lived?

Search This Blog

Monday, February 28, 2011

Griceian arguments against compositionality

Adapted from Szabo, Stanford Encyclopedia, online, essay on 'compositionality'. Later fragments.

Szabo entitles the section, "Arguments against compositionality."

Szabo offers an example from Chess, which Grice played well, and notes:

"We CAN have productive and systematic understanding of representations even if we do NOT understand complex representations merely by understanding their simple components and the way those components are combined."

Szabo presents a similar sub-argument to the same effect.

The next section is entitled,

"How compositionality allegedly fails"

(a) Conditionals

Consider the following minimal pair:

(1) Everyone will succeed if he works hard.
(2) No one will succeed if he goofs off.

"A good translation of (1) into a first-order language is (1′)."

"But the analogous translation of (2) would yield (2′), which is inadequate."

A good translation for (2) would be (2″) but it is unclear why. We might convert

¬∃

to the equivalent ∀¬

but then we must also inexplicably push the negation into the consequent of the embedded conditional."

(1′)

∀x(x works hard → x will succeed)

(2′)

¬∃x (x goofs off → x will succeed)

(2″)

∀x (x goofs off → ¬(x will succeed))

"This gives rise to a problem for the compositionality of English, since is seems rather plausible that the syntactic structure of (1) and (2) is the same and that ‘if’ contributes some sort of conditional connective—not necessarily a material conditional!—to the meaning of (1)."

"But it seems that it cannot contribute just that to the meaning of (2)."

"More precisely, the interpretation of an embedded conditional clause appears to be sensitive to the nature of the quantifier in the embedding sentence—a violation of compositionality.[16]"

"One response might be to claim that ‘if’ does not contribute a conditional connective to the meaning of either (1) or (2)—rather, it marks a restriction on the domain of the quantifier, as the paraphrases under (1″) and (2″) suggest:[17]."

(1″) Everyone who works hard will succeed.

(2″) No one who goofs off will succeed.

"But this simple proposal (however it may be implemented) runs into trouble when it comes to quantifiers like ‘most’. Unlike (3′), (3) says that those students (in the contextually given domain) who succeed if they work hard are most of the students (in the contextually relevant domain)."

(3) Most students will succeed if they work hard.

(3′) Most students who work hard will succeed.

"The debate whether a good semantic analysis of if-clauses under quantifiers can obey compositionality is lively and open.[18]"

SECOND suspect-case:

Cross-sentential anaphora

Consider the following minimal pair from Barbara Partee:

(4)

I dropped 10 marbles and found all but 1 of them. It is probably under the sofa.

(5)

I dropped 10 marbles and found 9 of them. It is probably under the sofa.

"There is a clear difference between (4) and (5)—the first one is unproblematic, the second markedly odd."

"This difference is plausibly a matter of meaning, and so (4) and (5) cannot be synonyms."

"Nonetheless, the first sentences are at least truth-conditionally equivalent."

"If we adopt a conception of meaning where truth-conditional equivalence is sufficient for synonymy, we have an apparent counterexample to compositionality."

"Few would insist that the first sentences of (4) and (5) are really synonymous."

"What is interesting about this example is that even if we conclude that we should opt for a more fine grained conception of meaning, it is not immediately clear how that will account for the contrast between these sentences."

"The difference is obviously due to the fact that ‘1’ occurs in the first sentence of (4), which is available as a proper antecedent for ‘it’ and that there is nothing in the first sentence of (5) that could play a similar role."

"Some authors have suggested that the right way to approach this problem is to opt for a dynamic conception of meaning, one that can encode anaphoric possibilities for subsequent sentences.[19]"

"Interesting though these cases might be, it is not at all clear that we are faced with a genuine challenge to compositionality, even if we want to stick with the idea that meanings are just truth-conditions."

"For it is not clear that (5) lacks the normal reading of (4)—on reflection it seems better to say that the reading is available even though it is considerably harder to get."

"Contrast this with an example due to—I think—Irene Heim:

They got married. She is beautiful.

"This is like (5) because the first sentence lacks an explicit antecedent for the pronoun in the second."

"Nonetheless, it is clear that the bride is said to be beautiful."

"If the difference between (4) and (5) is only this, it is no longer clear that we must accept the idea that they must differ in meaning."

THIRD SUSPECT-CASE: Adjectives -- Grice on 'shaggy' and 'French poem' (in Aristotle and the multiplicity of being" PPQ)

"Suppose a Japanese maple leaf, turned brown, has been painted green. Consider someone pointing at this leaf uttering (6)."

(6) This leaf is green.

"The utterance could be true on one occasion (say, when the speaker is sorting leaves for decoration) and false on another (say, when the speaker is trying to identify the species of tree the leaf belongs to)."

"The meanings of the words are the same on both occasions and so is their syntactic composition."

"But the meaning of (6) on these two occasions—what (6) says when uttered in these occasions—is different."

"As Travis, the inventor of this example puts it:

“…words may have all the stipulated features while saying something true, but also while saying something false.”[[20]

"At least three responses offer themselves. One is to deny the relevant intuition. Perhaps the leaf really is green if it is painted green and (6) is uttered truly in both situations."

"Nonetheless, we might be sometimes reluctant to make such a true utterance for fear of being misleading. We might be taken to falsely suggest that the leaf is green under the paint or that it is not painted at all.[21] The second option is to point out that the fact that a sentence can say one thing on one occasion and something else on another is not in conflict with its meaning remaining the same. Do we have then a challenge to compositionality of reference, or perhaps to compositionality of content? Not clear, for the reference or content of ‘green’ may also change between the two situations. This could happen, for example, if the lexical representation of this word contains an indexical element.[22] If this seems ad hoc, we can say instead that although (6) can be used to make both true and false assertions, the truth-value of the sentence itself is determined compositionally.[23]"

FOURTH CASE: Propositional attitudes

"Perhaps the most widely known objection to compositionality comes from the observation that even if e and e′ are synonyms, the truth-values of sentences where they occur embedded within the clausal complement of a mental attitude verb may well differ."

"So, despite the fact that ‘eye-doctor’ and ‘ophthalmologist’ are synonyms (7) may be true and (8) false if Carla is ignorant of this fact:

(7)

Carla believes that eye doctors are rich.

(8)

Carla believes that ophthalmologists are rich.

"So, we have a case of apparent violation of compositionality; cf. Pelletier (1994)."

"There is a sizable literature on the semantics of propositional attitude reports."

"Some think that considerations like this show that there are no genuine synonyms in natural languages. If so, compositionality (at least the language-bound version) is of course vacuously true. Some deny the intuition that (7) and (8) may differ in truth-conditions and seek explanations for the contrary appearance in terms of implicature.[24] Some give up the letter of compositionality but still provide recursive semantic clauses.[25] And some preserve compositionality by postulating a hidden indexical associated with ‘believe’.[26]"

And the debate ensues...

REFERENCES

Barker, S. (1997) ‘Material implication and general indicative conditionals.’ The Philosophical Quarterly 47: 195–211.
Berg J. (2002) ‘Is semantics still possible?’ Journal of Pragmatics 34: 349–359.
Cappelen, H. and E. Lepore (2004) ‘Radical and moderate pragmatics: does meaning determine truth-conditions?’ In Z. G. Szabó ed., Semantics vs. Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Carnap, R. (1947) Meaning and Necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Chierchia, G. (1995) The Dynamics of Meaning: Anaphora, Presupposition, and the Theory of Grammar. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Cresswell, M. (1986) Structured Meanings. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Davidson, D. (1965) ‘Theories of meaning and learnable languages.’ Reprinted in D. Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001: 3–16.
-----. (1970) ‘Semantics for natural languages.’ Reprinted in D. Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001: 55–64.
Davies, M. (1981) Meaning, Quantification, Necessity. London: Routledge.
Davis, W. (2003) Meaning, Expression, and Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dever, J. (1999) ‘Compositionality as methodology.’ Linguistics and Philosophy 22: 311–326.
Dummett, M. (1973) Frege: Philosophy of Language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Evans, G. (1982) The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
von Fintel, K. (1998) ‘Quantifiers and if-clauses.’ The Philosophical Quarterly 48: 209–214.
Fischer, E. (2000) Linguistic Creativity: Exercises in ‘Philosophical Therapy’. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Fodor, J. (1991) ‘Why meaning (probably) isn't conceptual role.’ Mind and Language 6: 329–343.
-----. (1996) ‘The pet fish and the red herring: why concepts aren't prototypes’ Cognition 58: 243–276.
-----. (1998a) ‘There are no recognitional concepts — not even RED.’ In In Critical Condition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 35–47.
-----. (1998b) ‘There are no recognitional concepts — not even RED, Part 2: The plot thickens.’ In In Critical Condition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 49–62.
-----. (2001a) ‘Language, thought and compositionality.’ Mind and Language 16: 1–15.
-----. (2001b) ‘Why compositionality won't go away: Reflections on Horwich's “Deflationary” Theory.’ Ratio 14: 350–368.
Fodor, J. and E. Lepore (1992) Holism: A Shopper's Guide. Oxford: Blackwell.
-----. (2002) The Compositionality Papers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fodor, J., and Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). ‘Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critique.’ Cognition 28: 3–71.
Frege, G. (1884) The Foundations of Arithmetic. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1980.
-----. (1891) ‘On the law of inertia.’ Reprinted in B. McGuiness, ed., Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell, 1984: 123–138.
-----. (1892) ‘On concept and object.’ Reprinted in B. McGuiness, ed., Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell, 1984: 182–194.
-----. (1906a) ‘Foundations of geometry/II.’ Reprinted in B. McGuiness, ed., Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell, 1984: 293–340.
-----. (1906b) ‘Introduction to logic.’ In Hermes et al. eds., Posthumous Writings. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1979: 185–196.
-----. (1914) ‘Logic in mathematics.’ In Hermes et al. eds., Posthumous Writings. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1979: 201–250.
-----. (1914?) ‘Letter to Jourdain.’ In G. Gabriel et al. eds., Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1980: 78–80.
-----. (1923) ‘Compound thoughts.’ Reprinted in B. McGuiness, ed., Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell, 1984: 390–406.
Gazdar, G., Klein E., Pullum G., and Sag I. (1985) Generalized Phrase Structure Grammar. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Grandy, R. (1990) ‘Understanding and compositionality.’ In J. A. Tomberlin ed., Philosophical Perspectives, 4: Action Theory and Philosophy of Mind. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Co.: 557 – 572.
Groenendijk J. and M. Stokhof (1990) ‘Dynamic Montague Grammar.’ In L. Kálmán et al. Proceedings of the 2nd Symposium on Logic and Language. Budapest: Akadémiai Kiadó, 3–48.
-----. (1991) ‘Dynamic Predicate Logic.’ Linguistics and Philosophy, 14: 39–100.
Heim , I. (1982) The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases. PhD. Dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst. Garland Publishing Inc., 1988.
Hendrix, H. (2001) ‘Compositionality and model-theoretic interpretation.’ Journal of Logic, Language, and Information 10: 29–48.
Higginbotham, J. (1985) ‘On semantics.’ Linguistic Inquiry 16: 547–593.
-----. (1986) ‘Linguistic theory and Davidson's program in semantics.’ In E. Lepore ed., Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Oxford: Blackwell: 29–48.
-----. (2003) ‘Conditionals and compositionality.’ In J. Hawthorne ed., Philosophical Perspectives 17: 181–194.
Hintikka, J. (1981) ‘Theories of truth and learnable languages.’ In S. Kanger and S. Öhman eds., Philosophy and Grammar. Dordrecht: Reidel: 37–58.
Hintikka, J. and G. Sandu (1997) ‘Game-theoretical semantics.’ In J. van Benthem and A. ter Meulen eds., Handbook of Logic and Language. Amsterdam: Elsevier. 361–410.
Hodges, W. (1998) ‘Compositionality is not the problem.’ Logic and Logical Philosophy 6: 7–33.
-----. (2001) ‘Formal features of compositionality.’ Journal of Logic, Language, and Information 10: 7–28.
Horwich, P. (1997) ‘The composition of meanings.’ Philosophical Review 106: 503–533.
Husserl, E. (1913) Logische Untersuchungen II/1. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.
Janssen, T. M. V. (1983) Foundations and Applications of Montague Grammar. Amsterdam: Mathematisch Centrum.
-----. (1997) ‘Compositionality.’ In J. van Benthem and A. ter Meulen eds., Handbook of Logic and Language. Amsterdam: Elsevier. 417–473.
-----. (2001) ‘Frege, contextuality and compositionality.’ Journal of Logic, Language, and Information 10: 115–136.
Geach, P. (1965) ‘Logical procedures and the identity of expressions.’ Reprinted in Logic Matters Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1980, pp. 108–115.
Johnson, K. (2004) ‘On the systematicity of language and thought.’ Journal of Philosophy 101: 111–139.
Johnson, K. (2006) ‘On the nature of reverse compositionality.’ Erkenntnis 64: 37–60.
Kamp, H. (1981) ‘A theory of truth and semantic representation.’ In J. Groenendijk and M. Stokhof eds., Formal Methods in the Study of Natural Language. Amsterdam: Amsterdam Centre: 277–322.
Kamp, H. and B. Partee (1995) ‘Prototype theory and compositionality.’ Cognition 57: 129–191.
Kazmi, A. and F. J. Pelletier (1998) ‘Is compositionality formally vacuous?’ Linguistics and Philosophy 21: 629–633.
Kratzer, A. (1986) ‘Conditionals.’ Chicago Linguistic Society 22: 1–15.
Lahav, R. (1989) ‘Against compositionality: the case of adjectives.’ Philosophical Studies 57: 261–279.
Larson, R. and G. Segal (1995) Knowledge of Meaning: An Introduction to Semantic Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Leitgeb, H. (2005) ‘Hodges' theorem does not account for determinacy of translation: A reply to Werning.’ Erkenntnis, 62: 411–425.
Lewis, D. (1970) ‘General semantics.’ Reprinted in Philosophical Papers. Vol. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 189–229.
-----. (1975) ‘Adverbs of quantification.’ Reprinted in Papers in Philosophical Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 5–20.
-----. (1980) ‘Index, context, and content.’ Reprinted in Papers in Philosophical Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 21–44.
Martin R. L. (1994) The Meaning of Language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Montague, R. (1970) ‘Universal Grammar.’ Reprinted in R. Thomason ed., Formal Philosophy. New Haven : Yale University Press, 1974: 222–246.
Nunberg G., I. A. Sag and T. Wasow (1994) ‘Idioms.’ Language, 70: 491–538.
Pagin, P. (2003) ‘Communication and strong compositionality.’ Journal of Philosophical Logic 32: 287–322.
Partee, B. (1984) ‘Compositionality.’ In F. Landman and F. Veltman eds., Varieties of Formal Semantics. Dordrecht: Foris: 281–312.
-----. (1995) ‘Lexical semantics and compositionality.’ D. Osherson ed., An Invitation to Cognitive Science. Vol. 1. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press: 311–360.
Patterson, D. (2005) ‘Learnability and compositionality.’ Mind and Language, 20: 326–352.
Pelletier, F. J. (1994) ‘The principle of semantic compositionality.’ Topoi, 13: 11–24.
-----. (2001) ‘Did Frege believe in Frege's Principle?’ Journal of Logic, Language, and Information 10: 87–114.
-----. (2003) ‘Context-dependence and compositionality.’ Mind and Language 18: 148–161.
Pietroski, P. (2005) Events and semantic architecture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Platts, M. (1979) Ways of Meaning. London: Routledge.
Robbins, P. (2001) ‘What compositionality still can do.’ Philosophical Quarterly, 51: 328–336.
Robbins, P. (2005) ‘The myth of reverse compositionality’ Philosophical Studies, 125: 251–275.
Sainsbury, M. (2001) ‘Two ways to smoke a cigarette’ Ratio 14: 386–406.
Salmon, N. (1986) Frege's Puzzle. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Schiffer, S. (1987) The Remnants of Meaning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
-----. (1991) ‘Does Mentalese have a compositional semantics?’ In B. Loewer and G. Rey eds., Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics. Oxford: Blackwell.
Stainton, R. (2003) Words and Thoughts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stanley, J. and Z. G. Szabó (2000) ‘On quantifier domain restriction.’ Mind and Language 15: 219–261.
Szabó, Z. G. (2000a) Problems of Compositionality. New York: Garland.
-----. (2000b) ‘Compositionality as supervenience.’ Linguistics and Philosophy 23: 475–505.
-----. (2000c) ‘Adjectives in context.’ In I. Kenesei and R., Harnish eds., Perspectives on Semantics, Pragmatics, and Discourse. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, pp. 119–146.
-----. (2004) ‘Review of J. Fodor and E. Lepore The Compositionality Papers.’ Mind 113: 340–344.
Werning, M. (2004) ‘Compositionality, context, categories and the indeterminacy of translation.’ Erkenntnis, 60: 145–178.
Werning, M. (2005) ‘Right and wrong reasons for compositionality.’ M. Werning ed., The compositionality of meaning and content. Volume 1: Foundational Issues. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag: 285–309.
Westerståhl, D. (1998) ‘On mathematical proofs of the vacuity of compositionality.’ Linguistics and Philosophy 21: 635–643.
Zadrozny, W. (1994) ‘From compositional to systematic semantics.’ Linguistics and Philosophy 17: 329–342.
Zeevat, H. (1989) ‘A compositional approach to Discourse Representation Theory.’ Linguistics and Philosophy, 12: 95–131.

2 comments:

  1. seems to be more a problem of ...confirming premises (and translating them into symbolic language) than about the conditional per se.

    first off, a claim such as ∀x (x goofs off → ¬(x will succeed)) could hardly be confirmed. Many people do goof off and succeed--it's not a necessary argument that the class of non-successful is only goof offs. There are successful goofs. And unsuccessful non-goofs. The conditional merely indicates that antecedent included inside the consequent (IMHE)

    Macro point: many logicians or philosophers of language often seem to conflate the empirical aspects of confirming premises with the logical/formal aspects of arguments, IMHE. Or perhaps its the translation issue. Griceans seem to think the natural language can be adequately translated into formal logic. Im not convinced of that (ie, the problem of verb tense, various other grammatical issues, connotation, etc).IM not anti-logic per se. Run the premises through the olde Quine Bot, and hit the V button, JLS !(valid or not). But once like the ...world enters, it's not really strictly logical but evidentiary.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Yes. Good points. I should rephrase any comment from me in a separate blog post. But meanwhile.

    Yes, Grice is never clear. I mean, it's pretty depressing to reach the middle of that essay by him, "Indicative conditionals" (WoW:IV) to read that he says that the truth-functionality of 'if' and the 'horseshoe' won't do for 'subjunctive conditionals'. He even grants that just adding, 'then', to the conditional,

    "if p, THEN q"

    turns it non-truth-functional. Some grand scheme! So, I have learned to read Grice with pinches of salt!

    I am amused by his clever attempt to refute Strawson. At least Strawson did learn a lesson from Grice. He got so confused that he HAD to modify his naive views on 'if' in "Introduction to logical theory". His best reply is still in PGRICE, ed. Grandy and Warner, "If and )".

    ReplyDelete