Speranza
In "Vacuous Names", the Oxonian philosopher H. P. Grice refers to the famous essay by K. S. Donnellan (of Cornell, etc.), "Reference &
Definite Descriptions, Philosophical Review, 75.
Grice is not sure that he is "wholly sympathetic towards the conclusions" which Donnellan
draws from the existence of the distinction" [between what Donnellan had
dubbed an
"attributive" and a "referential" use of a definite description
(Grice, op.cit. p.145).
The implicature is that Grice thinks the conclusion is implicatural, and Donnellan seems to implicate it's semantical, rather.
Grice's two corresponding usages of definite descritpions he calls in "Vacuous Names
are
"non-identificatory" (symbolised by italics)
and"identificatory" (symbolised by capitals):
viz (p.141):
1. Jones's
butler will be seeking a new position.
*The F* is G.
2. Jones's
butler got the hats and coats mixed up.
THE F is G
Grice wants to refer to
these different 'usages' of definite descriptions' as pertaining
to pragmatics
(utterer's intentions and conversational implicature), rather
than semantics
(logical form):
Grice writes:
"It is important to bear in mind that I am NOT
suggesting that the difference between these devices represents a difference in the MEANING or SENSE which a descriptive phrase may have on
different occasions; on the contrary, I am suggesting that descriptive
phrases have no relevant systematic duplicity of meaning: their meaning is
given by a Russellian account" --
(p.143) -- referring to Donnellan's arch-enemy: Lord Bertie Russell -- Grice is again robbing Peter (Strawson) to pay Paul (Grice) himself.
Grice is here concerned with what
we may regard as 'knowledge by acquaintance', or to use G Evans's phrase (in
The Varieties of Reference), 'recognition-based identification'.
For this,
Grice provides a linguistic device or test, namely, the appropriateness or not of the addition, to any definite
description, of the phrase, 'whoever he [it/she] may be" (or 's/h/it', as Geary prefers)
Grice notes that
only the attributive (or non-identificatory) usage allows for the addition of
the phrase:
Jones's butler, whoever he may be, will be seeking a new
position.
The utterance of
*Jones's butler, whoever he may be, got the hats and coats mixed
up.
sounds odd and triggers the wrong implicature, ALWAYS.
Grice writes:
"We may say with respect to [the referential or
identificatory
use] that some particular individual has been 'described
as'
[or 'MISdescribed as', as the case may be. Speranza], 'REFERRED to as',
or 'called' Jones's butler by the [utterer]. No such comments are
in place with respect to [attributive or non-identificatory
usages]"
(p.141).
It is in this context that Grice introduces the notion of a
"dossier" associated to a definite description.
In this he is, as Evans
notes, more or less following Strawson in 'Identifying Reference & Truth
Values' (now repr. in Strawson's Logico-Linguistic Papers, Methuen), although not explicitly using the
notion of 'information'.
Grice defines a dossier as follows:
Let us say
that utterer U has a dossier for a definite description
D if there is a
set of definite descriptions which includes D, all
the members of which U
supposes to be satisfied by one and the same
item. In [the
non-identificatory usages], unlike [the identificatory
ones], the
[utterer] intends the audience to think (via the recognition
that he is so
intended)
1. that U has a dossier for the definite description D
which he has used,
and
2. that U has selected D from
this dossier at least partly IN THE HOPE
THAT THE HEARER HAS A DOSSIER
FOR D WHICH 'OVERLAPS' the utterer's
dossier for D. p.142.
This
is labelled a 'tremendously important feature of referring expressions' by
Evans, and given a kind of cognitive background:
[An] organism must have
more than the simple capacity to
find previously encountered objects
familiar; a recognitional
capacity must be associated with (i.e. enable the
subject
to recall) the appropriate dossier of information. Under
these
circumstances, selection pressures would strongly
favour organisms which
possessed, or were capable to
developing, this capacity. G Evans, "The
Varieties of Reference",
Oxford University Press, p.276.
(Grice also
cited on pages 50 and 306).
Grice proposes a method having to do with semantic
interpretation (rather
than the syntactical one involving the 'whoever he may
be' idiom) when
stressing the fact that the existence of BOTH these two
non-identificatory
and identificatory uses conform to truth-conditional
semantics.
The apparent difference is explained in terms of the distinction
between what the utterer
EXPLICITLY communicates, or SAYS - rendered by means of the logical form - and
what he generally MEANS (rendered by the communicative intentions):
the
truth-conditions for a statement [of the identificatory type]
no less than
for a statement [of the non-identificatory type],
can be thought of as
being given by a Russellian account of definite
descriptions. Though what
a [utterer] has SAID may be FALSE [in
the identificatory use] what he
MEANT may be true (for example,
that a certain particular individual (who
is in fact Jones's gardener)
mixed up the hats and coats. p.142.
A
third device, of the linguistic type, that Grice introduces to
distinguish
between these two uses is the effects of the replacement of the
definite
description by a [proper] name, yielding:
*Jones's butler* (let
us call him Bill) will be seeking a new position.
JONES'S BUTLER (let us
call him Bill) got our coats and hats mixed up.
Here, there is an apparent
asymmetry between which Grice analyses,
precisely, in terms of the
distinction between a truth-value associated to
WHAT IS EXPLICITLY COMMUNICATED or SAID (for the
non-identificatory use), as opposed to WHAT IS MEANT (for the identificatory
use):
A subsequent remark [to a non-identificatory use] containing
[the newly introduced proper name] 'Bill' will have THE SAME
TRUTH-VALUE
as would have a corresponding remark in which
*Jones's butler* replaces
'Bill'. If Jones has no butler,
and if in consequence it is FALSE that
*Jones's butler*
will be seeking a new position, then it will be [also]
false
that Bill will be seeking a new position ... [However, in the
case of an identificatory use], it will NOT be true that a a
subsequent
remark containing [a newly introduced proper name such
as] 'Bill' will have
the same truth-value as would have a
corresponding remark in which 'Bill'
is replaced by 'Jones's butler'.
For the person whom the [utterer]
proposes to call 'Bill' will be
the person whom he MEANT when he said,
'Let us call JONES'S BUTLER
[sic in capitals. JLS] Bill', viz. the person
who looked after the
hats and coats, [...] and if this person turns out
to have been
Jones's gardener and not Jones's butler, then it may be TRUE
that
Bill mixed up the hats and coats and FALSE that Jones's butler
mixed
up the hats and coats.
The distinction between the
non-identificatory and the identificatory use is
based thus on the way in
which they react to the replacement of the definite
description by a proper
name:
[In the identificatory use] remarks of the form 'Bill is
such-and-
such' will be INFLEXIBLY TIED, as regards truth-value, not to
possible remarks of the form 'Jones's butler is such-and-such", but
to possible remarks of the form 'The person whom U meant when he
said
'Let us call Jones's Butler 'Bill' is such-and-such'.
p.143.
Grice
further considers the issue of "vacuous" descriptions, in connection
the concerns of Strawson -- Donnellan's second arch-enemy after Russell.
Grice writes of the different uses of 'vacuous
definite
descriptions', even when used in an identificatory way - including
what he
calls 'parasitic' uses:
"It is important to note that, for a definite
description used
in explanation of a name to be employed in an
IDENTIFICATORY way,
it is NOT required that the item which the explainer
MEANS
(is referring to) when he uses the description should ACTUALLY
EXIST.
A person may establish or explain a use for a name A by saying
'Let us call THE F A' or 'THE F is called A' even though every definite
description in his dossier for 'the F' is vacuous. He may mistakenly
think, or merely deceitfully intend his hearer to think, that the
elements
in the dossier are non-vacuous and satisfied by a single item;
and in
secondary or 'parasitic' types of case, as in the narration of
or
commentary upon fiction, that this is so may be something which
the
speaker non-deceitfully pretends or 'feigns'".
Grice, p.144.
Incidentally, when
Donnellan replied to criticisms by A. Mckay] to his
'Reference & Definite
Descriptions' (which we have seen is cited by Grice in
'Vacuous Names'), as
e.g. 'Putting Humpty Dumpty Together Again'
(Philosophical Review 1967) he
relies on Grice's intentional stance.
Donnellan is concerned with A. Mckay's
allegation of 'linguistic anarchism'
(as when an utterer can mean what he
wishes, as Humpty Dumpty does in Alice
in Wonderland). Donnellan then explicitly refers to the Oxonian philosopher H. P. Grice:
In the analysis of meaning given by Grice [In Meaning, reprinted
in
Studies in the Way of Words], a speaker means something by an utterance
when he has a certain complex kind of intention involving recognition
on the part of his audience of his intention ... It does not follow from
this analysis that speakers might, out of the blue, mean anything at all
by any utterance.
Donnellan, p.212.
Donnellan's example is using 'the book' to
mean a rock:
"Suppose there is a rock on my shelf that has been
carefully
carved to resemble a book and that I know the person I am
speaking to cannot recognise it for what it is. I say to him
'Bring me the
book with the blue binding'.
It seems at least plausible to say that I
referred to a rock.
When a speaker uses a definite description
referentially
[or as Grice would have it, in an identificatory way.
Speranza]
he intends his audience to take the descritption as
characterising what it is he want s to talk about."
Donellan, p.214.
An
interdisciplinary note: the linguistic-philosophical literature on
definite
descriptions is also dealt with, from a cognitive linguistic point
of view,
by P N Johnson-Laird and A Garnham, of the Centre for Research on
Perception
& Cognition at the University of Sussex, in their essay,
'Descriptions
& Discourse Models' (Linguistics & Philosophy, 3, 371-393).
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment