Speranza
Why Donnellan chose to refute Strawson (and Russell) -- in their "On
referring" and "On denoting" respectively -- is an interesting step in the
history of analytic philosophy alla Grice.
Indeed, for Grice, the
debate around what Whitehead and Russell call 'the
iota operator' and which
roughly translates as "the", runs along the lines
of his 'Logic &
Conversation'.
It is solved by posing, precisely,a distinction between
utterer's meaning
- the conversational implicature-level (what a
neo-traditionalist like
Strawson, an 'informalist' or 'neo-traditionalist'
is attempting elucidate, but
failing ) - and the truth-conditional semantic
component (the Russellian
component of the 'modernist' or 'formalist'). We
cannot speak of
truth-functionality here since the iota operator is NOT a
truth-functional operator.
Indeed, in the second William James Lecture,
among the formal devices
mentioned by Grice is the 'iota operator' ('(iota
x)') and its natural-language
counterpart, 'the'.
He goes into
detail on these matters, not so much in the William James
lectures, but in
his "'Presupposition & Conversational Implicature" (where he
refutes
Strawson's solution involving a truth-value gap), "Vacuous Names"
and
"Definite descriptions in Russell and in the vernacular".
Grice develops
a conversational-pragmatic treatment of
i. The king of France is
bald.
in terms, not of truth-value gaps as Strawson would have it, but
standard
truth-conditional semantics (the Russellian tripartite analysis of
the
above) PLUS conversational implicature - notably by appeal to the
conversational maxim falling under the category of Manner (or Perspicuity):
"Frame
whatever you say in the form most suitable for any repl that would
be regarded
as appropriate".
As if a conversation would
proceed:
ii. A: The king of France is bald.
B: He is not!
A: Well, he doesn't have any hair!
B: That's not the king of France. He
is the PRESIDENT of France: De
Gaulle.
Strawson's original example
was
iii. The king (or president) of France is _wise_.
but Grice
preferred to stick with Russell's original example, since it was
trickier.
Russell played with
iv. The king of France is bald,
but he wears a wig.
This inspired Dummett, who expanded on the
scenario.
v. For that matter, we might just as well claim that the Queen
of England,
Elizabeth I, was bald, and wore a wig. (I mean, how can we
verify the
past?)
Grice's treatment, which also avails of the notion
of "common ground
status" something like "mutual knowledge" -- only that it
can be false -- as
discussed by philosophers more in connection with
'presupposition' (notably
the ontological commitment of existential
presupposition) rather than
'definite description,' though.
But
surely Grice is trying to show that Strawson's 'presupposition' does
not
exist, and it's a mere conversational implicature (Indeed, Strawson used
'imply' instead of 'presuppose' in "On referring").
In "Vacuous
Names", an irreverent tribute to Quine repr. in "Words and
Objections",
Grice considers the
issue, developing a formal system for the treatment of
conversational
pragmatics, which he calls system Q (later re-labelled
system G by Grice's
disciple, George Myro).
Grice makes some
interesting remarks re: the pragmatics of descriptions,
as they may trigger
the use of names.
This he does in the tenth section, entitled, 'Names
& Definite
Descriptions'.
In 'Definite Descriptions in Russell
& in The Vernacular' he goes on to
defend Russell explicitly. Grice
implicates Russell did not speak the
vernacular as well as HE
did!
Bealer, who went to Reed, has dwelt on these matters in his "Quality
and
Concept". Bealer relies on the notion of a pragmatically complete vs
semantically incomplete symbol:
Bealer writes:
"On the
picture that emerges [from Grice's work], although definite
descriptions
usually DO HAVE A REFERENCE, REFERRING, unlike NAMING, is a
PRAGMATIC
relation, not a semantic relation. Thus, definite descriptions, while
pragmatically complete symbols (they typically refer in conversational
contexts), are semantically INCOMPLETE: their being co-referential in
conversational context does not make them alike in any kind of genuine
semantic
meaning. Even if definite descriptions were taken as semantically
COMPLETE
symbols, one would intuitively not want to say that they NAME
anything (only
names name). They would be more like predicates and
sentences: they would
express something, and what they MEAN would be what
they express. But what
about REFERRING? True enough, if definite
descriptions were semantically
COMPLETE symbols, referring would seem to be
a semantic relation. But it would be
only a DERIVED relation, defined as
follows. E refers to x iff
1. If E is a definite description, x = whatever E
EXPRESSES.
2. If E is a name, x = whatever E NAMES.
This would be all
there is to the commonsense theory of REFERENCE since
predicates and
sentences intuitively do NOT refer. On this account, then,
there is still
only one fundamental kind of meaning, and it partitions into
naming and
expressing. ... [In this account] Our model structures would need
to be
enriched with a PRIMITIVE DEFINITE DESCRIPTION OPERATION and
appropriate
predication and relativised predication operations.
From a historical
point of view, we should add further keywords here: not
just GRICE and
DONNELLAN, but KRIPKE and BARCAN MARCUS, since the whole
picture should
provide a detailed historical development of these
views.
Cheers,
Speranza
Tuesday, February 24, 2015
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment