Speranza
Geach was a prominent Catholic philosopher admired for his mastery
of logic and work on ethics. Grice wasn't (implicature: Catholic; the rest he shared with Geach).
There have been several notable Catholic philosophers in the last half
century, among them M. A. E. Dummett, but probably none whose Catholicism was so
integral to their philosophy as it was for Peter Thomas Geach.
The professor of logic at Leeds, and subsequently professor
emeritus, he was admired by philosophers for his mastery of that discipline, and
his contributions to the philosophy of language and ethics, while also acclaimed
by Cahal Daly, the archbishop of Armagh, for his fidelity to divine
revelation, and awarded the papal medal Pro Ecclesia et Pontifice.
For
Geach, faith neither conflicted with reason nor trumped it.
Rather, the two
nicely dovetailed.
He was never a unitary, system-building philosopher, but
produced sharp gems of analytical argument that brilliantly lacerated
orthodoxies current in philosophy, while often simultaneously bolstering those
of Catholicism.
Defending the reality of time against JME McTaggart's theories
in "Truth, Love and Immortality" was an excellent opportunity for
reasserting the truth of God's interventions in time and reconciling
difficulties in divine foreknowledge.
Repudiating Locke's memory criterion for
personal identity (that Grice had adopted and adapted in "Personal Identity", Mind, 1941), Geach gave scope to rehabilitate the archaic doctrine of bodily
resurrection.
Geach's marriage to fellow Catholic philosopher G. E. M.
Anscombe was a fertile philosophical coupling like that of Jean-Paul Sartre and
Simone de Beauvoir, only in the Geaches' case, LITERALLY so, since they had four
daughters and three sons -- one of them, Mary Geach, a philosopher (literally).
They were a daunting duo in philosophical debate, and
collaborated in translating Descartes, and in the movement (later called
Analytical Thomism) to connect analytic philosophy with the thought of the Italian philosopher Thomas
Aquinas.
If anything, though, G. E. M. Anscombe was supposed to be the more renowned philosopher of the
two. Not for me!
Geach was born in Lower Chelsea, London.
His father, Cardiff-born George Hender Geach taught at Cambridge -- a fellow of Trinity -- in "the great Trinity days of Moore, Russell, McTaggart and Keynes", the son will later recall -- but Geach spent much of his childhood in
Cardiff with his maternal grandparents, who were Polish immigrants.
At the
age of eight Geach became a boarder at Llandaff Cathedral school.
Geach studied
classics at Balliol, and converted to Catholicism while a
student.
In 1938, the year Geach graduated, he met Anscombe at a Corpus Christi
procession and they married in 1941, after he had ensured that she was reliably
Catholic.
He refused to fight in the second world war, since, although he
thought there was a satisfactory jus ad bellum – in line with the Catholic
doctrine of the just war – he suspected there would not be jus in bello – right
conduct within war.
On the other hand, usually the right, Grice served in the Navy and retired as Captain.
After doing philosophical research at Cambridge -- with Witters and von Wright, no less --, Geach
became assistant lecturer in philosophy at Birmingham in 1951, later
senior lecturer, then reader in logic there.
His and Max Black's translation of
works by the German mathematician and logician Gottlob Frege appeared in
1952.
Geach's own first book, "Mental Acts" (1957), now a classic in the
philosophy of psychology, argued that "acquiring a concept is a process of
becoming able to do something" – not, as many philosophers since Descartes had
held, a matter of having internal representations of external things, or
undergoing inner experiences.
Geach criticised what he called abstractionism,
the view that we acquire the concept of red, say, from repeated experiences of
red. It would, he said, fail to account for many of our concepts.
"Nowhere in
the sensible world could you find anything, nor could you draw any picture, that
could suitably be labelled 'or' or 'not'."
On the other hand, Grice's first paper ever, "Negation", argued for an empiricist account of and approach to 'not'.
"Mental Acts" was much indebted to
Wittgenstein.
More original and in line with his distinctive technique of using
hard logic to crack problems in metaphysics and ethics was his essay "Ascriptivism", reprinted in "Logic matters".
In "Ascriptivism", Geach shows by means of "if" sentences the inadequacy of
ethical theories which claim that to call a person, act or principle good or bad
is just a matter of commending or expressing disapproval of the person, act or
principle, without any possibility of referring to a real quality they have, or
of being accurate about that quality.
Geach makes what he called "the Frege point",
and later came to be called the Frege-Geach point, commenting that the word
"wrong" in the sentence
"If Bill did wrong, he will be punished,"
has the same
meaning whether or not the person saying this believes that Bill did
wrong.
Grice discusses this in terms of implicature in "Retrospective Epilogue", 1987.
"Good" and "bad" are anyway, Geach had argued in an article of 1956,
nearly always attributive: adjectives integrally related to the terms they
qualify.
"X is good" is an incomplete assertion – the relevant criteria for
saying Bill, or this horse, or this pen, is good depend on what sort of thing
each is. It only makes sense to, say "X is a good F" (at least implicitly), and
then the truth or falsity of saying so can be ascertained by finding out the
function and nature of F.
A pen, a horse, a man are good if they fulfil certain
criteria. Bill might be a good engineer and a good thief, but a bad man. A man,
however, unlike a horse, is not purely biological. We (properly) call him good
not on behalf of our own preferences or purposes but of his own.
Geach was a
great influence on Philippa Foot, who borrowed Geach's thought experiment of
whether a fat man stuck at the mouth of a pothole should be killed in order to
save the people inside. Inevitably, Geach himself thought not, and used this
example when arguing that, where a mother's life is at stake unless her unborn
child is killed, no intervention should occur, since their lives are of equal
importance.
He and Anscombe were very traditional on matters of sexual
morality, and in 1968 they toasted the Humanae Vitae encyclical, which forbade
Catholics' use of contraception, with champagne. They were fairly liberal with
their children, however, and dismissive of cleanliness or supervision.
On
opening the door to a policeman and a lost child, Geach shouted into the house:
"Elizabeth, is it one of ours?" It was.
From 1971 to 1974 Geach gave the
Stanton Lectures at Cambridge on the philosophy of religion. His theory of
relative identity, elaborated in Logic Matters (1972), argued that it makes no
sense to say that one thing is the same as something else unless you say what
sort of category the two things which are putatively one thing belong to. They
may be the same in some respects but not others – a clue, Geach thought, to the
baffling doctrine of the Holy Trinity, according to which God the Father, God
the Son and God the Holy Ghost are all different persons yet the same
god.
Geach was a wonderful lecturer and great stylist.
He wrote in a direct,
pointed, elegant, almost Johnsonian way, and had a capacity to produce crisp
epigrammatic terms that entered the philosophical lexicon, such as "pronouns of
laziness" for pronouns that only commonsensically, not grammatically, refer to
something. Also "Shakespearean context", "donkey pronoun" and so on.
He tended to look over people's shoulders when talking to them, as
if at some impersonal truth, was famously irascible and failed to suffer gladly
anything he considered to conflict with Catholic doctrine, even if uttered by
respected clerics.
He once stood up during a sermon, shouting "This is heresy",
and marched his family out of the church.
In Who's Who he listed his recreations
as "Reading stories of detection, mystery and horror; collecting and annotating
old bad logic texts".
Elizabeth died in 2001. He is survived by his
children.
Peter Thomas Geach, philosopher, born 29 March 1916; died 21
December 2013.
.
Saturday, December 28, 2013
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment