Speranza
Are there implicatures connected with ignorance?
Grice discusses Strawson's treatment of 'or':
"My wife is in the kitchen OR in the garden".
Implicature: Heaven knows where.
In "On The Sources Of Knowledge and IGNORANCE", Sir Karl Raimund Popper, as he delivered the
Annual Philosophical Lecture read before the British Academy on January 20th,
1960, dealt more or less with the same topic. More less than more.
Oddly, Grice's Annual Philosophical Lecture at Cumberland House
(as some like to refer to this) came out slightly later, in
1971.
Popper's essay was first published in the Proceedings of the
British Academy, 46, 1960, and separately by Oxford University Press,
1961.
Ditto with Grice: 1971 and 1971.
Some running commentary
Popper starts his lecture with
three epigraphs:
It follows, therefore, that truth manifests
itself.
Benedetto di Spinoza.
John Locke writes:
"Every man carries about him a
touchstone to distinguish truth from appearances."
David Home writes:
"It is
impossible for us to think of any thing, which we have not antecedently felt,
either by ourexternal or internal senses."
Popper starts:
"The title of this lecture is likely, I fear, to offend some critical
ears."
Titles, in general, should be ignored. Alice was well aware of
this:
The name of the song is called 'Haddocks' Eyes.''
'Oh,
that's the name of the song, is it?' Alice said, trying to feel
interested.
'No, you don't understand,' the Knight said, looking a little
vexed. 'That's what the name
is called. The name really is 'The Aged, Aged
Man.''
'Then I ought to have said 'That's what the song is called'?' Alice
corrected herself.
'No you oughtn't: that's another thing. The song is called
'Ways and Means' but that's only
what it's called, you know!'
'Well, what
is the song then?' said Alice, who was by this time completely bewildered.
'I
was coming to that,' the Knight said. 'The song really is 'A-sitting On a Gate':
and the
tune's my own invention.'
As Gardner notes ("The Annotated
Alice"), "A-Sitting On a Gate" is not yet _the song_ but another of its
titles.
Popper continues:
"For although ‘Sources of Knowledge’ is
in order, and ‘Sources of Error’ would have been in order too, the phrase
‘Sources of Ignorance’ is another matter."
"‘Ignorance is something
negative: it is the absence of knowledge. But how on earth can the absence of
anything have sources?"
Descartes and Spinoza went even further, and
asserted that not only ignorance but also error is 'something negative'-a
'privation' of knowledge, and even of the proper use of our freedom.
See:
Descartes' Principles, Part r, 33-42.
Descartes, The Third and Fourth Meditations.
Also:
Spinoza's Ethics, Part II, propos. 35 and schol.
Spinoza, Principles of
Descartes' Philosophy, Part r, propos. 15 and schol.
Nevertheless, Descartes and Spinoza speak
(e.g. Ethics, Part II, propos. 41) also of the 'cause' of falsity (or error), as
does Aristotle in "Metaphysica" 1046a30-35.
See also:
Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1008b35; 1009a6; 1 052al
Aristotle, Topica 147b29
Aristotle,
Analytica Posteriora, 79b23; and Grice's favourite Aristotle: Categoriae, l2a26-l3a35.
Popper confesses:
"This
question [that something negative may have a source] was put to me by a "friend"
when I confided to him the title I had chosen for this [distinguished] lecture."
"Hard pressed for a reply I found myself improvising a rationalization,
and explaining to my friend that the curious linguistic effect of the title was
actually intended."
I told him that I hoped to direct attention,
through the phrasing of this title, to a number of unrecorded philosophical
doctrines and among them (apart from the doctrine that truth is manifest)
especially to the conspiracy theory of ignorance which interprets ignorance not
as a mere lack of knowledge but as the work of some sinister power, the source
of impure and evil influences which pervert and poison our minds and instill in
us the habit of resistance to knowledge.
I am not quite sure whether this
explanation allayed my friend’s misgivings, but it did silence him. Your case is
different since you are silenced by the rules of the present transactions.
So I
can only hope that I have allayed your misgivings sufficiently, for the time
being, to allow me to begin my story at the other end-with the sources of
knowledge rather than with the sources of ignorance. However, I shall presently
come back to the sources of ignorance, and also to the conspiracy theory of
these sources.
The problem which I wish to examine afresh in this
lecture, and which I hope not only to examine but to solve, may perhaps be
described as an aspect of the old quarrel between the British and the
Continental schools of philosophy-the quarrel between the classical empiricism
of Bacon, Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and Mill, and the classical rationalism or
intellectualism of Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz. In this quarrel the British
school insisted that the ultimate source of all knowledge was observation, while
the Continental school insisted that it was the intellectual intuition of clear
and distinct ideas.
Most of these issues are still very much alive. Not only
has empiricism, still the ruling doctrine in England, conquered the United
States, but it is now widely accepted even on the European Continent as the true
theory of scientific knowledge.
Cartesian intellectualism, alas, has been only
too often distorted into one or another of the various forms of modern
irrationalism.
In the Popper tries to show of the two schools of
empiricism and rationalism that their differences are much smaller than their
similarities, and that both are mistaken. I hold that they are mistaken
although I am myself an empiricist and a rationalist of sorts. But I believe
that, though observation and reason have each an important role to play, these
roles hardly resemble those which their classical defenders attributed to them.
More especially, Popper tries to show that neither observation nor reason can be
described as a source of knowledge, in the sense in which they have been
claimed to be sources of knowledge, down to the present day.
Popper's problem belongs to the theory of knowledge, or to epistemology, reputed to be
the most abstract and remote and altogether irrelevant region of pure
philosophy. Hume, for example, one of the greatest thinkers in the field,
predicted that, because of the remoteness and abstractness and practical
irrelevance of some of his results, none of his readers would believe in them
for more than an hour.
Kant’s attitude was different.
He thought that the
problem
‘What can I know?’
-- as opposed to
'What can I ignore?'
-- was one of the three most important questions a man
could ask.
Lord Russell, in spite of being closer to Hume in philosophic
temperament, seems to side in this matter with Kant. And I think Russell is
right when he attributes to epistemology practical consequences for science,
ethics, and even politics. For he says that episemological relativism, or the
idea that there is no such thing as objective truth, and epistemological
pragmatism, or the idea that truth is the same as usefulness, are closely linked
with authoritarian and totalitarian ideas.
Cf. Russell, Let The People Think.
Russell’s views are of course disputed. Some recent philosophers have
developed a doctrine of the essential impotence and practical irrelevance of all
genuine philosophy, and thus, one can assume, of epistemology. Philosophy, they
say, cannot by its very nature have any significant consequences, and so it can
influence neither science nor politics. But I think that ideas are dangerous and
powerful things, and that even philosophers have sometimes produced ideas.
Indeed, I do not doubt that this new doctrine of the impotence of all philosophy
is amply refuted by the facts.
The situation is really very simple.
The
belief of a liberal-the belief in the possibility of a rule of law, of equal
justice, of fundamental rights, and a free Society can easily survive the
recognition that judges are not omniscient and may make mistakes about facts and
that, in practice, absolute justice is never fully realized in any particular
legal case. But the belief in the possibility of a rule of law, of justice, and
of freedom, can hardly survive the acceptance of an epistemology which teaches
that there are no objective facts; not merely in this particular case, but in
any other case; and that the judge cannot have made a factual mistake because he
can no more be wrong about the facts than he can be right.
The great
movement of liberation which started in the Renaissance and led through the many
vicissitudes of the reformation and the religious and revolutionary wars to the
free societies in which the English speaking peoples are privileged to live,
this movement was inspired throughout by an unparalleled epistemological
optimism: by a most optimistic view of man’s power to discern truth and to
acquire knowledge.
At the heart of this new optimistic view of the
possibility of knowledge lies the doctrine that truth is manifest. Truth may
perhaps be veiled.
But it may reveal itself [2. See my mottoes: Spinoza, of God,
Man, and Human Happiness, ch. 15 (parallel passages are:
Ethics, ii, scholium
to propos. 4-3:
'Indeed, as light manifests itself and darkness, so with truth:
it is its own standard, and that offalsity.' De intel!. em., 35, 36; letter 76
[74-J, end of para. 5 [7]);
Locke, Condo Underst., 3.
Cp. also Romans, i, 19,
and see ch. 17, below.) ]
And if it does not reveal itself, it may be revealed
by us.
Removing the veil may not be easy.
But once the naked truth stands
revealed before our eyes, we have the power to see it, to distinguish it from
falsehood, and to know that it is truth.
The birth of modern science and
modern technology was inspired by this optimistic epistemology whose main
spokesmen were Bacon and Descartes.
They taught that there was no need for any
man to appeal to authority in matters of truth because each man carried the
sources of knowledge in himself; either in his power of sense perception which
he may use for the careful observation of nature, or in his power of
intellectual intuition which he may use to distinguish truth from falsehood by
refusing to accept any idea which is not clearly and distinctly perceived by the
intellect.
Man can know: thus he can be free.
This is the formula which
explains the link between epistemological optimism and the ideas of
liberalism.
This link is paralleled by the opposite link. Disbelief in the
power of human reason, in man’s power to discern the truth, is almost invariably
linked with distrust of man. Thus epistemological pessimism is linked,
historically, with a doctrine of human depravity, and it tends to lead to the
demand for the establishment of powerful traditions and the entrenchment of a
powerful authority which would save man from his folly and his wickedness.
There is a striking sketch of this theory of authoritarianism, and a picture of
the burden carried by those in authority, in the story of The Grand Inquisitor
in Dostoievsky’s The Brothers Karamazov.
The contrast between
epistemological pessimism and optimism may be said to be fundamentally the same
as that between epistemological traditionalism and rationalism.
Popper uses the
latter term in its wider sense in which it is opposed to irrationalism, and in
which it covers not only Cartesian intellectualism but empiricism also.)
For we
can interpret traditionalism as the belief that, in the absence of an objective
and discernible truth, we are faced with the choice between accepting the
authority of tradition, and chaos; while rationalism has, of course, always
claimed the right of reason and of empirical science to criticize, and to
reject, any tradition, and any authority, as being based on sheer unreason or
prejudice or accident.
It is a disturbing fact that even an abstract
study like pure epistemology is not as pure as one might think (and as Aristotle
believed) but that its ideas may, to a large extent, be motivated and
unconsciously inspired by political hopes and by Utopian dreams.
This should be
a warning to the epistemologist.
What can he do about it? As an epistemologist I
have only one interest-to find out the truth about the problems of epistemology,
whether or not this truth fits in with my political ideas. But am I not liable
to be influenced, unconsciously, by my political hopes and beliefs?
It so
happens that I am not only an empiricist and a rationalist of sorts but also a
liberal (in the English sense of this term); but just because I am a liberal, I
feel that few things are more important for a liberal than to submit the various
theories of liberalism to a searching critical examination.
While I was
engaged in a critical examination of this kind I discovered the part played by
certain epistemological theories in the development of liberal ideas; and
especially by the various forms of epistemological optimism.
And I found that,
as an epistemologist, I had to reject these epistemological theories as
untenable. This experience of mine may illustrate the point that our dreams and
our hopes need not necessarily control our results, and that, in searching for
the truth, it may be our best plan to start by criticizing our most cherished
beliefs. This may seem to some a perverse plan. But it will not seem so to those
who want to find the truth and are not afraid of it.
In examining the
optimistic epistemology inherent in certain ideas of liberalism, I found a
cluster of doctrines which, although often accepted implicitly, have not, to my
knowledge, been explicitly discussed or even noticed by philosophers or
historians.
The most fundamental of them is one which I have already
mentioned-the doctrine that truth is manifest. The strangest of them is the
conspiracy theory of ignorance, which is a curious outgrowth from the doctrine
of manifest truth.
By the doctrine that truth is manifest I mean, you will
recall, the optimistic view that truth, if put before us naked, is always
recognizable as truth. Thus truth, if it does not reveal itself, has only to be
unveiled, or dis-covered. Once this is done, there is no need for further
argument. We have been given eyes to see the truth, and the ‘natural light’ of
reason to see it by.
This doctrine is at the heart of the teaching of both
Descartes and Bacon. Descartes based his optimistic epistemology on the
important theory of the "veracitas dei".
What we clearly and distinctly see to
be true must indeed be true; for otherwise God would be deceiving us.
Thus the
truthfulness of God must make truth manifest.
In Bacon we have a similar
doctrine. It might be described as the doctrine of the veracitas naturae, the
truthfulness of Nature. Nature is an open book. He who reads it with a pure mind
cannot misread it. Only if his mind is poisoned by prejudice can he fall into
error.
This last remark shows that the doctrine that truth is manifest
creates the need to explain falsehood. Knowledge, the possession of truth, need
not be explained. But how can we ever fall into error if truth is manifest? The
answer is: through our own sinful refusal to see the manifest truth; or because
our minds harbour prejudices inculcated by education and tradition, or other
evil influences which have perverted our originally pure and innocent minds.
Ignorance may be the work of powers conspiring to keep us in ignorance, to
poison our minds by filling them with falsehood, and to blind our eyes so that
they cannot see the manifest truth. Such prejudices and such powers, then, are
sources of ignorance.
The conspiracy theory of ignorance is fairly well known
in its Marxian form as the conspiracy of a capitalist press that perverts and
suppresses truth and fills the workers’ minds with false ideologies. Prominent
among these, of course, are the doctrines of religion. It is surprising to find
how unoriginal this Marxist theory is.
The wicked and fraudulent priest who
keeps the people in ignorance was a stock figure of the eighteenth century and,
I am afraid, one of the inspirations of liberalism. It can be traced back to
the protestant belief in the conspiracy of the Roman Church, and also to the
beliefs of those dissenters who held similar views about the Established Church.
Elsewhere Popper traces the pre-history of this belief back to Plato’s uncle
Critias; see chapter 8, section ii, of my Open Society.
This curious belief
in a conspiracy is the almost inevitable consequence of the optimistic belief
that truth, and therefore goodness, must prevail if only truth is given a fair
chance. ‘Let her and falsehood grapple; who ever knew Truth put to the worse, in
a free and open encounter?’ (Areopagitica. Compare the French proverb, La verite
triomphe toujours.)
So when Milton’s Truth was put to the worse, the necessary
inference was that the encounter had not been free and open: if the manifest
truth does not prevail, it must have been maliciously suppressed. One can see
that an attitude of tolerance which is based upon an optimistic faith in the
victory of truth may easily be shaken.
See ]. W N. Watkins on Milton in The
Listener, Und January 1959.
For it is liable to turn into a conspiracy theory
which would be hard to reconcile with an attitude of tolerance.
I do not
assert that there was never a grain of truth in this conspiracy theory. But in
the main it was a myth, just as the theory of manifest truth from which it grew
was a myth.
For the simple truth is that truth is often hard to come by, and
that once found it may easily be lost again. Erroneous beliefs may have an
astonishing power to survive, for thousands of years, in defiance of experience,
with or without the aid of any conspiracy.
The history of science, and
especially of medicine, could furnish us with a number of good examples. One
example is, indeed, the general conspiracy theory itself I mean the erroneous
view that whenever something evil happens it must be due to the evil will of an
evil power. Various forms of this view have survived down to our own
day.
Thus the optimistic epistemology of Bacon and of Descartes cannot be
true.
Yet perhaps the strangest thing in this story is that this false
epistemology was the major inspiration of an intellectual and moral revolution
without parallel in history. It encouraged men to think for themselves. It gave
them hope that through knowledge they might free themselves and others from
servitude and misery. It made modern science possible. It became the basis of
the fight against censorship and the suppression of free thought. It became the
basis of the nonconformist conscience, of individualism, and of a new sense of
man’s dignity; of a demand for universal education, and of a new dream of a free
society. It made men feel responsible for themselves and for others, and eager
to improve not only their own condition but also that of their fellow men. It
is a case of a bad idea inspiring many good ones.
This false
epistemology, however, has also led to disastrous consequences.
The theory that
truth is manifest-that it is there for everyone to see, if only he wants to see
it-this theory is the basis of almost every kind of fanaticism. For only the
most depraved wickedness can refuse to see the manifest truth; only those who
have reason to fear truth conspire to suppress it.
Yet the theory that truth
is manifest not only breeds fanatics-men possessed by the conviction that all
those who do not see the manifest truth must be possessed by the devil-but it
may also lead, though perhaps less directly than does a pessimistic
epistemology, to authoritarianism. This is so, simply, because truth is not
manifest, as a rule.
The allegedly manifest truth is therefore in constant need,
not only of interpretation and affirmation, but also of re- interpretation and
reaffirmation. An authority is required to pronounce upon, and lay down, almost
from day to day, what is to be the manifest truth, and it may learn to do so
arbitrarily and cynically. And many disappointed epistemologists will turn away
from their own former optimism and erect a resplendent authoritarian theory on
the basis of a pessimistic epistemology. It seems to me that the greatest
epistemologist of all, Plato, exemplifies this tragic
development.
Plato plays a decisive part in the pre-history of
Descartes’ doctrine of the veracitas dei-the doctrine that our intellectual
intuition does not deceive us because God is truthful and will not deceive us;
or in other words, the doctrine that our intellect is a source of knowledge
because God is a source of knowledge. This doctrine has a long history which can
easily be traced back at least to Homer and Hesiod.
To us, the habit of
referring to one’s sources would seem natural in a scholar or an historian, and
it is perhaps a little surprising to find that this habit stems from the poets;
but it does.
The Greek poets refer to the sources of their knowledge.
The
sources are divine. They are the Muses. ‘ … the Greek bards’, Gilbert Murray
observes (The Rise of the Greek Epic, 3rd edn., 1924, p. 96), ‘always owe, not
only what we should call their inspiration, but their actual knowledge of facts
to the Muses. The Muses “are present and know all things” … Hesiod … always
explains that he is dependent on the Muses for his knowledge. Other sources of
knowledge are indeed recognized …. But most often he consults the Muses …. So
does Homer for such subjects as the Catalogue of the Greek army.’
As this
quotation shows, the poets were in the habit of claiming not only divine sources
of inspiration, but also divine sources of knowledge-divine guarantors of the
truth of their stories.
Precisely the same two claims were raised by the
philosophers Eraclito and Parmenide.
ERACLITO, it seems, sees himself as a
prophet who ‘talks with raving mouth, … possessed by the god’-by Zeus, the
source of all wisdom (DK [3. DK = Diels-Kranz, Fmgmente der Vorsokmtiker.],3 B
92, 32; cf. 93, 41,64,50).
And Parmenide, one could almost say, forms the
missing link between Homer or Hesiod on the one side and Descartes on the
other. His guiding star and inspiration is the goddess Dike, described by
Heraclitus (DK, B 28) as the guardian of truth. Parmenides describes her as the
guardian and keeper of the keys of truth, and as the source of all his
knowledge.
But Parmenides and Descartes have more in common than the doctrine
of divine veracity. For example, Parmenides is told by his divine guarantor of
truth that in order to distinguish between truth and falsehood, he must rely
upon the intellect alone, to the exclusion of the senses of sight, hearing, and
taste. (Cf. Heraclitus, B 54, 123; 88 and 126 hint at unobservable changes
yielding observable opposites.) And even the principle of his physical theory
which, like Descartes, he founds upon his intellectualist theory of knowledge,
is the same as that adopted by Descartes: it is the impossibility of a void, the
necessary fullness of the world.
In Plato’s Ion a sharp distinction is made
between divine inspiration-the divine frenzy of the poet-and the divine sources
or origins of true knowledge. (The topic is further developed in the Phaedrus,
especially from 25ge on; and in 275b-c Plato even insists, as Harold Cherniss
pointed out to me, on the distinction between questions of origin and of
truth.) Plato grants that the poets are inspired, but he denies to them any
divine authority for their alleged knowledge of facts. Nevertheless, the
doctrine of the divine source of our knowledge plays a decisive part in Plato’s
famous theory of anamnesis which in some measure grants to each man the
possession of divine sources of knowledge. (The knowledge considered in this
theory is knowledge of the essence or nature of a thing rather than of a
particular historical fact.) According to Plato’s Meno (81 b-d) there is nothing
which our immortal soul does not know, prior to our birth. For as all natures
are kindred and akin, our soul must be akin to all natures. Accordingly it knows
them all: it knows all things. (On kinship and knowledge see also Phaedo, 79d;
Republic, 611 d; Laws, 899d.)
In being born we forget; but we may recover our
memory and our knowledge, though only partially: only if we see the truth again
shall we recognize it. All knowledge is therefore re-cognition-recalling or
remembering the essence or true nature that we once knew. (Cp. Phaedo, 72e ff.;
75e.)
This theory implies that our soul is in a divine state of omniscience
as long as it dwells, and participates, in a divine world of ideas or essences
or natures, prior to being born. The birth of a man is his fall from grace; it
is his fall from a natural or divine state of knowledge; and it is thus the
origin and cause of his ignorance. (Here may be the seed of the idea that
ignorance is sin, or at least related to sin; cpo Phaedo, 7 6d.)
It is clear
that there is a close link between this theory of anamnesis and the doctrine of
the divine origin or source of our knowledge. At the same time, there is also a
close link between the theory of anamnesis and the doctrine of manifest truth:
if, even in our depraved state of forgetfulness, we see the truth, we cannot
but recognize it as the truth. So, as the result of anamnesis, truth is restored
to the status of that which is not forgotten and not concealed (alerhes): it is
that which is manifest.
Socrates demonstrates this in a beautiful passage of
the Meno by helping an uneducated young slave to ‘recall’ the proof of a
special case of the theorem of Pythagoras. Here indeed is an optimistic
epistemology, and the root of Cartesianism. It seems that, in the Meno, Plato
was conscious of the highly optimistic character of his theory, for he describes
it as a doctrine which makes men eager to learn, to search, and to
discover.
Yet disappointment must have come to Plato.
For in the Republica
(and also in the "Fedro") we find the beginnings of a pessimistic epistemology.
In the famous story of the prisoners in the cave (5 14 ff.) he shows that the
world of our experience is only a shadow, a reflection, of the real world.
And
he shows that even if one of the prisoners should escape from the cave and face
the real world, he would have almost insuperable difficulties in seeing and
understanding it-to say nothing of his difficulties in trying to make those
understand who stayed behind. The difficulties in the way of an understanding of
the real world are all but super-human, and only the very few, if anybody at
all, can attain to the divine state of understanding the real world-the divine
state of true knowledge, of episteme.
This is a pessimistic theory with
regard to almost all men, though not with regard to all. (For it teaches that
truth may be attained by a few-the elect. With regard to these it is, one might
say, more wildly optimistic than even the doctrine that truth is manifest.) The
authoritarian and traditionalist consequences of this pessimistic theory are
fully elaborated in the Laws.
Thus we find in Plato the first transition from
an optimistic to a pessimistic epistemology. Each of these forms a basis for one
of two diametrically opposed philosophies of the state and of society: on the
one hand an anti-traditionalist, anti-authoritarian, revolutionary and Utopian
rationalism of the Cartesian kind, and on the other hand an authoritarian
traditionalism.
This development may well be connected with the fact that the
idea of an epistemological fall of man can be interpreted not only in the sense
of the optimistic doctrine of anamnesis, but also in a pessimistic sense.
In
this latter interpretation, the fall of man condemns all mortalsor almost
all-to ignorance. I think one can discern in the story of the cave (and perhaps
also in the story of the fall of the city, when the Muses and their divine
teaching are neglected; see Republic, 546d) an echo of an interesting older form
of this idea. I have in mind Parmenides’ doctrine that the opinions of mortals
are delusions, and the result of a misguided convention.
This may stem from
Xenophanes’ doctrine that all human knowledge is guesswork, and that his own
theories are, at best, merely similar to the truth!)[4. Xenophanes' fragment
here alluded to is DK. B 35, quoted here in ch. 5, section xii, below. For the
idea of truthlikeness---of a doctrine that partly corresponds to the facts (and
so may be 'taken for real', as Parmenides has it here)---see especially pp. 320
f, below, where verisimilitude is contrasted with probability, and the Addenda
3, 4, 6, and 7.
The misguided convention is a linguistic one: it consists
in giving names to what is non-existent. The idea of an epistemological fall of
man can perhaps be found, as Karl Reinhardt suggested, in those words of the
goddess that mark the transition from the way of truth to the way of delusive
opinion.[5. See Karl Reinhardt, Parmenides, 2nd ed., p. 26; see also pp. 5-11
for the text of Parmenides, DK, B I: 31-32, which are the first two lines here
quoted. My third line is Parmenides, DK, B 8: 60, cf Xenophanes, B 35.
Popper's fourth
line is Parmenides, DK, B 8: 61. ]
"But you also shall learn how it was that
delusive opinion,
Bound to be taken for real, was forcing its way through all
things …
Now of this world thus arranged to seem wholly like truth I shall
tell
you;
Then you will be nevermore led astray by the notions of mortals.
Thus though the fall affects all men, the truth may be revealed to the elect
by an act of grace-even the truth about the unreal world of the delusions,
opinions, conventional notions and decisions, of mortals: the unreal world of
appearance, destined to be accepted, and to be approved of, as real. 6 It is
interesting to contrast this pessimistic view of the necessity of error with the
optimism of Descartes, or of Spinoza who scorns (letter 76[74], paragraph 5[7])
those ‘who dream of an impure spirit inspiring us with false ideas which are
similar to true ones (veris similes)’: see also ch. 10, section xiv, and Mdendum
6, below.
The revelation received by Parmenides, and his conviction that a
few may reach certainty about both the unchanging world of eternal reality and
the unreal and changing world of verisimilitude and deception, were two of the
main inspirations of plato’s philosophy. It was a theme to which he was for ever
returning, oscillating between hope, despair, and resignation.
Yet
what interests us here is Plato’s optimistic epistemology, the theory of
anamnesis in the Meno. It contains, I believe, not only the germs of Descartes’
intellectualism, but also the germs of Aristotle’s and especially of Bacon’s
theories of induction.
For Meno’s slave is helped by Socrates’ judicious
questions to remember or recapture’the forgotten knowledge which his soul
possessed in its pre-natal state of omniscience.
It is, I belieye, this famous
Socratic method, called in the Theaetetus the art of midwifery or maieutic, to
which Aristotle alluded when he said (Metaphysics, 1 078b 17-33; see also 98 7b
1) that Socrates was the inventor of the method of induction.
Aristotle, and
also Bacon, I “wish to suggest, meant by ‘induction’ not so much the inferring
of universal laws from particular observed instances as a method by which we are
guided to the point whence we can intuit or perceive the essence or the true
nature of a thing. [7. Aristotle meant by 'induction' (epagoge) at least two
different things which he sometimes links together. One is a method by which we
are 'led to intuit the general principle' (Anal. Pro 67a 22 f., on anamnesis in
the Meno; An. Post., 71a 7). The other (Topics 105a 13, 156a 4; 157a 34; Anal.
Posteriam 78a 35; 81b 5 ff.) is a method of adducing (particular)
evidence-positive evidence rather than critical evidence or counter-examples.
The first method seems to me the older one, and the one which can be better
connected with Socrates and his maieutic method of criticism and
counter-examples.
The second method seems to originate in the attempt to
systematize induction logically or, as Aristotle (Anal. Priam, 68b 15 ff.) puts
it, to construct a valid 'syllogism which springs out of induction'; this, to be
valid, must of course be a syllogism of perfect or complete induction (complete
enumeration of instances); and ordinary induction in the sense of the second
method here mentioned is just a weakened (and invalid) form of this valid
syllogism. (Cp. my Open Society, note 33 to ch. 11.)]
But this, as we have seen,
is precisely the aim of Socrates’ maieutic: its aim is to help or lead us to
anamnesis; and anamnesis is the power of seeing the true nature or essence of a
thing, the nature or essence with which we were acquainted before birth, before
our fall from grace. Thus the aims of the two, maieutic and induction, are the
same.
Incidentally, Aristotle taught that the result of an induction-the
intuition of the essence was to be expressed by a definition of that
essence.
Now let us look more closely at the two procedures.
The maieutic
art of Socrates consists, essentially, in asking questions designed to destroy
prejudices.
False beliefs which are often traditional or fashionable beliefs.
False answers, given in the spirit of ignorant cocksureness. Socrates himself
does not pretend to know. His attitude is described by Aristotle in the words,
‘Socrates raised questions but gave no answers; for he confessed that he did not
know.’ (Sophist. El., 183b7; cpo Theaetetus, IS0c-d, IS7c, 16Ib.)
Thus Socrates’
maieutic is not an art that aims at teaching any belief, but one that aims at
purging or cleansing (cf. the allusion to the Amphidromia in Theaetetus 160e;
cpo Phaedo 67b, 69b/ c) the soul of its false beliefs, its seeming knowledge,
its prejudices. It achieves this by teaching us to doubt our own
convictions.
Fundamentally the same procedure is part of Bacon’s
induction.
The framework of Bacon’s theory of induction is this.
He
distinguishes in the Norum Organum between a true method and a false method. His
name for the true method, ‘interpretatio naturae’ , is ordinarily translated by
the phrase ‘interpretation of nature’, and his name for the false method,
‘anticipatio mentis’, by ‘anticipation of the mind’. Obvious as these
translations may seem, they are misleading.
What Bacon means by ‘interpretatio
naturae’ is, I suggest, the reading of, or better still, the spelling out of,
the book of Nature. (Galileo, in a famous passage of his II saggiatore, section
6, of which Mario Bunge has kindly reminded me, speaks of ‘that great book which
lies before our eyes-I mean the universe’; cf. Descartes’ Discourse, section
1.)
The term ‘interpretation’ has in modern English a decidedly
subjectivistic or relativistic tinge. When we speak of Rudolf Serkin’s
interpretation of the Emperor Concerto, we imply that there are different
interpretations, but that this one is Serkin’s. We do not of course wish to
imply that Serkin’s is not the best, the truest, the nearest to Beethoven’s
intentions. But although we may be unable to imagine that there is a better one,
by using the term ‘interpretation’ we imply that there are other interpretations
or readings, leaving the question open whether some of these other readings may,
or may not, be equally true.
I have here used the word ‘reading’ as a synonym
for ‘interpretation’, not only because the two meanings are so similar but also
because ‘reading’ and ‘to read’ have suffered a modification analogous to that
of ‘interpretation’ and ‘to interpret’; except that in the case of ‘reading’
both meanings are still in full use. In the phrase ‘I have read John’s letter’,
we have the ordinary, non-subjectivist meaning. But ‘I read this passage of
John’s letter quite differently’ or perhaps ‘My reading of this passage is very
different’ may illustrate a later, a subjectivistic or relativistic, meaning of
the word ‘reading’.
I assert that the meaning of ‘interpret’ (though not in
the sense of ‘translate’) has changed in exactly the same way, except that the
original meaning-perhaps ‘reading aloud for those who cannot read
themselves’-has been practically lost.
Today even the phrase ‘the judge must
interpret the law’ means that he has a certain latitude in interpreting it;
while in Bacon’s time it would have meant that the judge had the duty to read
the law as it stood, and to expound it and to apply it in the one and only right
way. Interpretatio juris (or legis) means either this or else the expounding of
the law to the layman. (Cp. Bacon, De Augmentis VI, xlvi; and 1. Manley, The
Interpreter: … Obscure Words and Terms used in the Lawes of this Realm, 1672.)
It leaves the legal interpreter no latitude; at any rate no more than would be
allowed to a sworn interpreter translating a legal document.
Thus the
translation ‘the interpretation of nature’ is misleading; it should be replaced
by something like ‘the (true) reading of nature’; analogous to ‘the (true)
reading of the law’. And I suggest that ‘reading the book of Nature as it is’ or
better still ‘spelling out the book of Nature’ is what Bacon meant.
The point is
that the phrase should suggest the avoidance of all interpretation in the modern
sense, and that it should not contain, more especially, any suggestion of an
attempt to interpret what is manifest in nature in the light of non-manifest
causes or of hypotheses; for all this would be an anticipatio mentis, in Bacon’s
sense. (It is a mistake, I think, to ascribe to Bacon the teaching that
hypotheses-or conjectures-may result from his method of induction; for Baconian
induction results in certain knowledge rather than in conjecture.)
As to the
meaning of ‘anticipatio mentis’ we have only to quote Locke: ‘men give
themselves up to the first anticipations of their minds’ (Conduct Underst.,
26). This is, practically, a translation from Bacon; and it makes it amply clear
that ‘anticipatio’ means ‘prejudice’ or even ‘superstition’. We can also refer
to the phrase’ anticipatio deorwn’ which means harbouring nalve or primitive or
superstitious views about the gods. But to make matters still more obvious:
‘prejudice’ (cp. Descartes, Princ. I, 50) derives from a legal term, and
according to the Oxford English Dictionary it was Bacon who introduced the verb
‘to prejudge’ into the English language, in the sense of ‘to judge adversely in
advance’-that is, in violation of the judge’s duty.
Thus the two methods are
(1) ‘the spelling out of the open book of Nature’, leading to knowledge or
episteme, and (2) ‘the prejudice of the mind that wrongly prejudges, and perhaps
misjudges, Nature’, leading to doxa, or mere guesswork, and to the misreading of
the book of Nature. This latter method, rejected by Bacon, is in fact a method
of interpretation, in the modern sense of the word. It is the method of
conjecture or hypothesis (a method of which, incidentally, I happen to be a
convinced advocate).
How can we prepare ourselves to read the book of Nature
properly or truly?
Bacon’s answer is: by purging our minds of all anticipations
or conjectures or guesses or prejudices (Nov.Org. i, 68, 69 end). There are
various things to be done in order so to purge our minds. We have to get rid of
all sorts of ‘idols’, or generally held false beliefs; for these distort our
observations (Nov. Org. i, 97). But we have also, like Socrates, to look out for
all sorts of counter-instances by which to destroy our prejudices concerning the
kind of thing whose true essence or nature we wish to ascertain. Like Socrates,
we must, by purifying our intellects, prepare our souls to face the eternal
light of essences or natures (cf. St Augustine, Civ. Dei, VIII, 3): our impure
prejudices must be exorcized by the invocation of counter-instances (Nov.Org.
ii, 16 ff.).
Only after our souls have been cleansed in this way may we begin
the work of spelling out diligently the open book of Nature, the manifest
truth.
In view of all this I suggest that Baconian (and also Aristotelian)
induction is the same, fundamentally, as Socratic maieutic; that is to say, the
preparation of the mind by cleansing it of prejudices, in order to enable it to
recognize the manifest truth, or to read the open book of Nature.
Descartes’
method of systematic doubt is also fundamentally the same: it is a method of
destroying all false prejudices of the mind, in order to arrive at the
unshakeable basis of self-evident truth.
We can now see more clearly how, in
this optimistic epistemology, the state of knowledge is the natural or the pure
state of man, the state of the innocent eye which can see the truth, while the
state of ignorance has its source in the injury suffered by the innocent eye in
man’s fall from grace; an injury which can be partially healed by a course of
purification. And we can see more clearly why this epistemology, not only in
Descartes’ but also in Bacon’s form, remains essentially a religious doctrine in
which the source of all knowledge is divine authority.
One might say that,
encouraged by the divine ‘essences’ or divine ‘natures’ of Plato, and by the
traditional Greek opposition between the truthfulness of nature and the
deceitfulness of man-made convention, Bacon substitutes, in his epistemology,
‘Nature’ for ‘God’. This may be the reason why we have to purify ourselves
before we may approach the goddess Natura: when we have purified our minds, even
our sometimes unreliable senses (held by Plato to be hopelessly impure) will be
pure.
The sources of knowledge must be kept pure, because any impurity may
become a source of IGNORANCE.
In spite of the religious character of
their epistemologies, Bacon’s and Descartes’ attacks upon prejudice, and upon
traditional beliefs which we carelessly or recklessly harbour, are clearly
anti-authoritarian and anti-traditionalist.
For they require us to shed all
beliefs except those whose truth we have perceived ourselves.
And their attacks
were certainly intended to be attacks upon authority and tradition. They were
part of the war against authority which it was the fashion of the time to wage,
the war against the authority of Aristotle and the tradition of the schools. Men
do not need such authorities if they can perceive the truth themselves.
But I
do not think that Bacon and Descartes succeeded in freeing their epistemologies
from authority; not so much because they appealed to religious authority-to
Nature or to God-but for an even deeper reason.
In spite of their
individualistic tendencies, they did not dare to appeal to our critical
judgment-to your judgment, or to mine; perhaps because they felt that this might
lead to subjectivism and to arbitrariness. Yet whatever the reason may have
been, they certainly were unable to give up thinking in terms of authority, much
as they wanted to do so. They could only replace one authority-that of Aristotle
and the Bible-by another. Each of them appealed to a new authority; the one to
the authority of the senses, and the other to the authority of the
intellect.
This means that they failed to solve the great problem: How can we
admit that our knowledge is a human-an all too human-affair, without at the same
time implying that it is all individual whim and arbitrariness?
Yet this
problem had been seen and solved long before.
First, it appears, by Xenophanes,
and then by Democritus, and by Socrates (the Socrates of the Apology rather than
of the Meno). The solution lies in the realization that all of us may and often
do err, singly and collectively, but that this very idea of error and human
fallibility involves another one-the idea of objective truth: the standard which
we may fall short of. Thus the doctrine of fallibility should not be regarded as
part of a pessimistic epistemology. This doctrine implies that we may seek for
truth, for objective truth, though more often than not we may miss it by a wide
margin. And it implies that if we respect truth, we must search for it by
persistently searching for our errors: by indefatigable rational criticism, and
self-criticism.
Erasmo of Rotterdam attempted to revive this Socratic
doctrine, the important though unobtrusive doctrine,
‘Know thyself, and thus
admit to thyself how little thou knowest!’
Yet Erasmo's doctrine was swept away by
the belief that truth is manifest, and by the new self-assurance exemplified and
taught in different ways by Luther and Calvin, by Bacon and Descartes.
It is
important to realize, in this connection, the difference between Cartesian doubt
and the doubt of Socrates, or Erasmo, or Montaigne.
While Socrates doubts human
knowledge or wisdom, and remains firm in his rejection of any pretension to
knowledge or wisdom, Descartes doubts everything-but only to end up with the
possession of absolutely certain knowledge; for he finds that his universal
doubt would lead him to doubt the truthfulness of God, which is absurd.
Having
proved that universal doubt is absurd, he concludes that we can know securely,
that we can be wise-by distinguishing, in the natural light of reason, between
clear and distinct ideas whose source is God, and all other ideas whose source
is our own impure imagination.
Cartesian doubt, we see, is merely a maieutic
instrument for establishing a criterion of truth and, with it, a way to secure
knowledge and wisdom.
Yet for the Socrates of the Apology, wisdom consisted in
the awareness of our limitations; in knowing how little we know, everyone of
us.
It was this doctrine of an essential human fallibility which Nicola di
Cusa and Erasmo of Rotterdam (who refers to Socrates) revived.
And it was this
‘humanist’ doctrine (in contradistinction to the optimistic doctrine on which
Milton relied, the doctrine that truth will prevail) which Nicola and Erasmo,
Montaigne and Locke and Voltaire, followed by Mill and Bertrand
Russell, made the basis of the doctrine of tolerance.
‘What is tolerance?’ asks
Voltaire in his Philosophical Dictionary; and he answers: ‘It is a necessary
consequence of our humanity. We are all fallible, and prone to error; let us
then pardon each other’s follies.
This is the first principle of natural right.
More recently the doctrine of fallibility has been made the basis of a theory
of political freedom; that is, freedom from coercion.
See F. A. Hayek, The
Constitution of Liberty, especially pp. 22 and 29.
Bacon and Descartes
set up observation and reason as new authorities, and they set them up within
each individual man. But in doing so they split man into two parts, into a
higher part which had authority with respect to truth-Bacon’s observations,
Descartes’ intellect-and a lower part. It is this lower part which constitutes
our ordinary selves, the old Adam in us. For it is always ‘we ourselves’ who are
alone responsible for error, if truth is manifest.
It is we, with our
prejudices, our negligence, our pigheadedness, who are to blame; it is we
ourselves who are the sources of our ignorance.
Thus we are split into a
human part, we ourselves, the part which is the source of our fallible opinions
(doxa), of our errors, and of our ignorance; and a super-human part, such as the
senses or the intellect, the· sources of real knowledge (episteme), whose
authority over us is almost divine.
But this will not do. For we know that
Descartes’ physics, admirable as it was in many ways, was mistaken; yet it was
based only upon ideas which, he thought, were clear and distinct, and which
therefore should have been true.
And as to the authority of the senses as
sources of knowledge, the fact that the senses are not reliable was known to the
ancients even before Parmenides, for example to Xenophanes and Heraclitus; and
of course to Democritus and to Plato. (Cp. pp. 222 f, below.)
It is strange
that this teaching of antiquity could be almost ignored by modern empiricists,
including phenomenalists and positivists; yet it is ignored in most of the
problems posed by positivists and phenomenalists, and in the solutions they
offer.
The reason is this: they believe that it is not our senses that err, but
that it is always ‘we ourselves’ who err in our interpretation of what is
‘given’ to us by our senses. Our senses tell the truth, but we may err, for
example, when we try to put into language–conventional, man-made, imperfect
language-what they tell us. It is our linguistic description which is faulty
because it may be tinged with prejudice.
So our man-made language was at
fault.
But then it was discovered that our language too was ‘given’ to us, in an
important sense: that it embodied the wisdom and experience of many generations,
and that it should not be blamed if we misused it. So language too became a
truthful authority that could never deceive us.
If we fall into temptation and
use language in vain, then it is we who are to blame for the trouble that
ensues.
For Language is a jealous God and will not hold him guiltless that
taketh His words in vain, but will throw him into darkness and confusion.
By
blaming us, and our language (or misuse of Language), it is possible to uphold
the divine authority of the senses (and even of Language).
But it is possible
only at the cost of widening the gap between this authority and ourselves:
between the pure sources from which we can obtain an authoritative knowledge of
the truthful goddess Nature, and our impure and guilty selves: between God and
man.
As indicated before, this idea of the truthfulness of Nature which, I
believe, can be discerned in Bacon, derives from the Greeks; for it is part of
the classical opposition between nature and human convention which, according to
Plato, is due to Pindar; which may be discerned in Parmenides; and which is
identified by him, and by some Sophists (for example, by Hippias) and partly
also by Plato himself, with the opposition between divine truth and human
error, or even falsehood. After Bacon, and under his influence, the idea that
nature is divine and truthful, and that all error or falsehood is due to the
deceitfulness of our own human conventions, continued to playa major role not
only in the history of philosophy, of science, and of politics, but also in that
of the visual arts.
This may be seen, for example, from Constable’s most
interesting theories on nature, veracity, prejudice, and convention, quoted in
E. H. Gombrich’s Art and Illusion. It also played a role in the history of
literature, and even in that of music.
Can the strange view that the
truth of a statement may be decided upon by inquiring into its sources-that is
to say its origin-be explained as due to some logical mistake which might be
cleared up?
Or can we do no better than explain it in terms of religious
beliefs, or in psychological terms-referring perhaps to parental authority? I
think that it is indeed possible to discern here a logical mistake which is
connected with the close analogy between the meaning of our words, or terms, or
concepts, and the truth of our statements or propositions.
It is easy to see that the meaning of our words does have some
connection with their history or their origin.
A word is, logically considered,
a conventional sign; psychologically considered, it is a sign whose meaning is
established by usage or custom or association.
Logically considered, its meaning
is indeed established by an initial decision-something like a primary definition
or convention, a kind of original social contract; and psychologically
considered, its meaning was established when we originally learned to use it,
when we first formed our linguistic habits and associations.
Thus there is a
point in the complaint of the schoolboy about the unnecessary artificiality of
French in which ‘pain’ means bread, while English, he feels, is so much more
natural and straightforward in calling pain ‘pain’ and bread ‘bread’.
He may
understand the conventionality of the usage perfectly well, but he gives
expression to the feeling that there is no reason why the original
conventions-original for him-should not be binding. So his mistake may consist
merely in forgetting that there can be several equally binding original
conventions. But who has not made, implicitly, the same mistake?
Most of us have
caught ourselves in a feeling of surprise when we find that in France even
little children speak French fluently.
Of course, we smile about our own
naivety; but we do not smile about the policeman who discovers that the real
name of the man called ‘Samuel Jones’ was ‘John Smith’-though here is, no doubt,
a last vestige of the magical belief that we gain power over a man or a god or a
spirit by gaining knowledge of his real name: by pronouncing it we can summon or
cite him.
Thus there is indeed a familiar as well as a logically defensible
sense in which the ‘true’ or ‘proper’ meaning of a term is its original
meaning; so that if we understand it, we do so because we learned it
correctly-from a true authority, from one who knew the
language.
Ideas
That is
DESIGNATIONS OF TERMS OR CONCEPTSSTATEMENTS OF
PROPOSITIONS OR THEORIES
may be formulated in
Words
Assertions
which
may be
meaningfultrue
and their
meaningtruth
may be reduced, by way
of
definitionsderivations
to that of
undefined conceptsprimitive
propositions
The attempt to establish (rather than reduce) by these
means their meaning/truth leads to infinite regress
This shows that
the problem of the meaning of a word is indeed linked to the problem of the
authoritative source, or the origin, of our usage.
It is different with the
problem of the truth of a statement of fact, a proposition.
For anybody can make
a factual mistake – even in matters on which he should be an authority, such as
his own age or the colour of a thing which he has just this moment clearly and
distinctly perceived.
And as to origins, a statement may easily have been false
when it was first made, and first properly understood. A word, on the other
hand, must have had a proper meaning as soon as it was ever understood.
If we
thus reflect upon the difference between the ways in which the meaning of words
and the truth of statements is related to their origins, we are hardly tempted
to think that the question of origin can have much bearing on the question of
knowledge or of truth.
There is, however, a deep analogy between meaning and
truth; and there is a philosophical view -- I have called it ‘essentialism’-- which
tries to link meaning and truth so closely that the temptation to treat both in
the same way becomes almost irresistible.
In order to explain this briefly,
we may once more contemplate our table of Ideas, noting the relation between its
two sides.
How are the two sides of this table connected?
A definition
is a kind of statement or theory or proposition, and therefore one of those
things which stand on the right side of our table.
This fact, incidentally,
does not spoil the symmetry of our table ofIdeas; for derivations also
transcend the kind of thing-statements, etc.-which stand on the side where the
word ‘derivation’ occurs: just as a definition is formulated by a special kind
of sequence of words rather than by a word, so a derivation is formulated by a
special kind of sequence of statements rather than by a statement.)
The fact
that definitions, which occur on the left side of our table, are nevertheless
statements suggests that somehow they may form a link between the left and the
right side of the table.
That they do this is, indeed, part of that
philosophic doctrine to which I have given the name’ essentialism’.
According to
essentialism (especially Aristotle’s version of it) a definition is a statement
of the inherent essence or nature of a thing. At the same time, it states the
meaning of a word-of the name that designates the essence. (For example,
Descartes, and also Kant, hold that the word ‘body’ designates something that
is, essentially, extended.)
Moreover, Aristotle and all other essentialists
held that definitions are ‘principles’; that is to say, they yield primitive
propositions (example: ‘All bodies are extended’) which cannot be derived from
other propositions, and which form the basis, or are part of the basis, of
every demonstration. They thus form the basis of every science. (Cf. my Open
Society, especially notes 27 to 33 to chapter 11.)
It should be noted that this
particular tenet, though an important part of the essentialist creed, is free of
any reference to ‘essences’. This explains why it was accepted by some
nominalistic opponents of essentialism such as Hobbes or, say, Schlick. (See the
latter’s Erkenntnislehre, 2nd edition, 1925, p. 62.)
I think we have now the
means at our disposal by which we can explain the logic of the view that
questions of origin may decide questions of factual truth. For if origins can
determine the true meaning of a term or word, then they can determine the true
definition of an important idea, and therefore some at least of the basic
‘principles’ which are descriptions of the essences or natures of things and
which underlie our demonstrations and consequently our scientific knowledge. So
it will then appear that there are authoritative sources of our
knowledge.
Yet we must realize that essentialism is mistaken in suggesting
that definitions can add to our knowledge of facts (although qua decisions about
conventions they may be influenced by our knowledge of facts, and although they
create instruments which may in their turn influence the formation of our
theories and thereby the evolution of our knowledge of facts).
Once we see that
definitions never give any factual knowledge about ‘nature’, or about ‘the
nature of things’, we also see the break in the logical link between the problem
of origin and that of factual truth which some essentialist philosophers tried
to forge.
Popper then goes on to leave all these largely historical reflections
aside, and turn to the problems themselves, and to their solution.
This part
of my lecture might be described as an attack on empiricism, as formulated for
example in the following classical statement of Hume’s: ‘IfI ask you why you
believe any particular matter off act … , you must tell me some reason; and this
reason will be some other fact, connected with it. But as you cannot proceed
after this manner, ad infinitum, you must at last terminate in some fact, which
is present to your memory or senses; or must allow that your belief is entirely
without foundation.’ (Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Section v, Part I;
SelbyBigge, p. 46; see also my motto, taken from Section vii, Part I; p.
62.)
The problem of the validity of empiricism may be roughly put as follows:
is observation the ultimate source of our knowledge of nature? And if not, what
are the sources of our knowledge?
These questions remain, whatever I may have
said about Bacon, and even ifI should have managed to make those parts of his
philosophy on which I have commented somewhat unattractive for Baconians and for
other empiricists.
The problem of the source of our knowledge has recently
been restated as follows.
If we make an assertion, we must justify it; but this
means that we must be able to answer the following questions.
‘How do you
know? What are the sources of your assertion?’
This, the empiricist holds,
amounts in its turn to the question, ‘What observations (or memories of
observations) underlie your assertion?’ I find this string of questions quite
unsatisfactory.
First of all, most of our assertions are not based upon
observations, but upon all kinds of other sources. ‘I read it in The Times’ or
perhaps ‘I read it in the Encyclopaedia Britannica’ is a more likely and a more
definite answer to the question ‘How do you know?’ than ‘I have observed it’
or’I know it from an observation I made last year’.
‘But’, the empiricist
will reply, ‘how do you think that The Times or the Encyclopaedia Britannica got
their information? Surely, if you only carry on your inquiry long enough, you
will end up with reports of the observations of eyewitnesses (sometimes called
“protocol sentences” or-by yourself-Hbasic statements”). Admittedly’, the
empiricist will continue, ‘books are largely made from other books.
Admittedly,
a historian, for example, will work from documents. But ultimately, in the last
analysis, these other books, or these documents, must have been based upon
observations. Otherwise they would have to be described as poetry, or invention,
or lies, but not as testimony. It is in this sense that we empiricists assert
that observation must be the ultimate source of our knowledge.’
Here we have
the empiricist’s case, as it is still put by some of my positivist friends.
I
shall try to show that this case is as little valid as Bacon’s; that the answer
to the question of the sources of knowledge goes against the empiricist; and,
finally, that this whole question of ultimate sourcessources to which one may
appeal, as one might to a higher court or a higher authority-must be rejected as
based upon a mistake.
First, Popper wants to show that if you actually went on
questioning "The Times" and its correspondents about the sources of their
knowledge, you would in fact never arrive at all those observations by
eyewitnesses in the existence of which the empiricist believes.
You would find,
rather, that with every single step you take, the need for further steps
increases in snowball-like fashion.
Take as an example the sort of assertion
for which reasonable people might simply accept as sufficient the answer
‘I read
it in The Times’.
Lt us say the assertion
i. The Prime Minister has decided to
return to London several days ahead of schedule.
Now assume for a moment that
somebody doubts this assertion, or feels the need to investigate its truth.
What
shall he do?
If he has a friend in the Prime Minister’s office, the simplest and
most direct way would be to ring him up.
And if this friend corroborates the
message, then that is that.
In other words, the investigator will, if
possible, try to check, or to examine, the asserted fact itself, rather than
trace the source of the information.
But according to the empiricist theory,
the assertion
‘I have read it in The Times’
is merely a first step in a
justification procedure consisting in tracing the ultimate source.
What is the
next step?
There are at least two next steps.
One would be to reflect that
i. I
have read it in The Tim
is also an assertion, and that we might ask
‘What is
the source of your knowledge that you read it in The Times and not, say, in a
paper looking very similar to The Times?’
The other is to ask The Times for the
sources of its knowledge.
The answer to the first question may be"
‘But we have
only The Times on order and we always get it in the morning’ which gives rise
to a host of further questions about sources which we shall not pursue.
The
second question may elicit from the editor of The Times the answer:
‘We had a
telephone call from the Prime Minister’s Office.’
Now according to the
empiricist procedure, we should at this stage ask next:
‘Who is the gentleman
who received the telephone call?’
and then get his observation report; but we
should also have to ask that gentleman:
‘What is the source of your knowledge
that the voice you heard came from an official in the Prime Minister’s office’,
and so on.
---
There is a simple reason why this tedious sequence of questions
never comes to a satisfactory conclusion.
It is this.
Every witness must always
make ample use, in his report, of his knowledge of persons, places, things,
linguistic usages, social conventions, and so on.
He cannot rely merely upon
his eyes or ears, especially if his report is to be of use in justifying any
assertion worth justifying. But this fact must of course always raise new
questions as to the sources of those elements of his knowledge which are not
immediately observational.
This is why the programme of tracing back all
knowledge to its ultimate source in observation is logically impossible to carry
through.
It leads to an infinite regress.
The doctrine that truth is manifest
cuts off the regress.
This is interesting because it may help to explain the
attractiveness of that doctrine.
Popper wishes to mention that
this argument is closely related to another-that all observation involves
interpretation in the light of our theoretical knowledge, [8. See my Logic of
Scientific Discovery, last paragraph of section 25, and new appendix *x, (2).
For an anticipation by Mark Twain of my Times argument, see p. 557 below.] or
that pure observational knowledge, unadulterated by theory, would, if at all
possible, be utterly barren and futile.
The most striking thing about the
observationalist programme of asking for sources-apart from its tediousness-is
its stark violation of common sense.
For if we are doubtful about an assertion,
then the normal procedure is to test it, rather than to ask for its sources; and
if we find independent corroboration, then we shall often accept the assertion
without bothering at all about sources.
Of course there are cases in which
the situation is different.
Testing an historical assertion always means going
back to sources; but not, as a rule, to the reports of eyewitnesses.
Clearly,
no historian will accept the evidence of documents uncritically.
There are
problems of genuineness, there are problems of bias, and there are also such
problems as the reconstruction of earlier sources.
There are, of course, also
problems such as: was the writer present when these events happened?
But this is
not one of the characteristic problems of the historian.
He may worry about the
reliability of a report, but he will rarely worry about whether or not the
writer of a document was an eyewitness of the event in question, even assuming
that this event was of the nature of an observable event.
A letter saying:
i. I
changed my mind yesterday on this question.
may be most valuable historical
evidence, even though changes of mind are unobservable -- and even though we may
conjecture, in view of other evidence, that the writer was lying.
As to
eyewitnesses, they are important almost exclusively in a court of law where they
can be cross-examined.
As most lawyers know, eyewitnesses often err.
This has
been experimentally investigated, with the most striking results.
Witnesses most
anxious to describe an event as it happened are liable to make scores of
mistakes, especially if some exciting things happen in a hurry; and if an event
suggests some tempting interpretation, then this interpretation, more often
than not, is allowed to distort what has actually been seen.
Hume’s view of
historical knowledge was different.
We believe’, Home writes in the Treatise
(Book T, Part III, Section iv; Selby-Bigge, p. 83), that
ii. Caesar was killed in
the Senate House on the ides of March.
because this fact is established on the
unanimous testimony of historians, who agree to assign this precise time and
place to that event.
Here are certain characters and letters present either to
our memory or senses; which characters we likewise remember to have been us’d as
the signs of certain ideas; and these ideas were either in the minds of such as
were immediately present at that action, and receiv’d the ideas directly from
its existence; or they were deriv’d from the testimony of others, and that again
from another testimony … ’till we arrive at those who were eye-witnesses and
spectators of the event.’ (See also Enquiry, Section x; Selby-Bigge, pp. 111
ff.)
It seems to me that this view must lead to the infinite regress
described above.
For the problem is, of course, whether ‘the unanimous
testimony of historians’ is to be accepted, or whether it is, perhaps, to be
rejected as the result of their reliance on a common yet spurious source. The
appeal to ‘letters present to our memory or our senses’ cannot have any bearing
on this or on any other relevant pro blem of historiography.
But what,
then, are the sources of our knowledge?
The answer, I think, is this.
There
are all kinds of sources of our knowledge; but none has authority.
We may say
that "The Times" can be a source of knowledge, or the "Encyclopaedia Britannica".
We
may say that certain papers in "The Physical Review" about a problem in physics
have more authority, and are more of the character of a source, than an article
about the same problem in The Times or the Encyclopaedia.
But it would be quite
wrong to say that the source of the article in the Physical Review must have
been wholly, or even partly, observation.
The source may well be the discovery
of an inconsistency in another paper or, say, the discovery of the fact that a
hypothesis proposed in another paper could be tested by such and such an
experiment; all these non-observational discoveries are ‘sources’ in the sense
that they all add to our knowledge.
Popper does not, of course, deny that an
experiment may also add to our knowledge, and in a most important manner.
But it
is not a source in any ultimate sense. It has always to be checked: as in the
example of the news in The Times we do not, as a rule, question the eyewitness
of an experiment, but, if we doubt the result, we may repeat the experiment, or
ask somebody else to repeat it.
The fundamental mistake made by the
philosophical theory of the ultimate sources of our knowledge is that it does
not distinguish clearly enough between questions of origin and questions of
validity.
Admittedly’ in the case of historiography, these two questions may
sometimes coincide.
The question of the validity of an historical assertion may
be testable only, or mainly, in the light of the origin of certain sources. But
in general the two questions are different; and in general we do not test the
validity of an assertion or information by tracing its sources or its origin,
but we test it, much more directly, by a critical examination of what has been
asserted-of the asserted facts themselves.
Thus the empiricist’s questions
‘How do you know? What is the source of your assertion?’ are wrongly put.
They
are not formulated in an inexact or slovenly manner, but they are entirely
misconceived: they are questions that beg for an authoritarian
answer.
The traditional systems of epistemology may be said to result
from yes answers or no-answers to questions about the sources of our knowledge.
They never challenge these questions, or dispute their legitimacy; the questions
are taken as perfectly natural, and nobody seems to see any harm in
them.
This is quite interesting, for these questions are clearly
authoritarian in spirit. They can be compared with that traditional question of
political theory, ‘Who should rule?’, which begs for an authoritarian answer
such as ‘the best’, or ‘the wisest’, or ‘the people’, or ‘the majority’. (It
suggests, incidentally, such silly alternatives as ‘Who should be our rulers:
the capitalists or the workers?’, analogous to ‘What is the ultimate source of
knowledge: the intellect or the senses?’) This political question is wrongly put
and the answers which it elicits are paradoxical (as I have tried to show in
chapter 7 of my Open Society).
It should be replaced by a completely
different question such as ‘How can we organize our political institutions so
that bad or incompetent rulers (whom we should try not to get, but whom we so
easily might get all the same) cannot do too much damage?’ I believe that only
by changing our question in this way can we hope to proceed towards a reasonable
theory of political institutions.
The question about the sources of our
knowledge can be replaced in a similar way.
It has always been asked in the
spirit of: ‘What are the best sources of our knowledge-the most reliable ones,
those which will not lead us into error, and those to which we can and must
turn, in case of doubt, as the last court of appeal?’
I propose to assume,
instead, that no such ideal sources exist-no more than ideal rulers-and that all
‘sources’ are liable to lead us into error at times.
And I propose to replace,
therefore, the question of the sources of our knowledge by the entirely
different question: ‘How can we hope to detect and eliminate error?’
The
question of the sources of our knowledge like so many authoritarian questions,
is a genetic one.
It asks for the origin of our knowledge, in the belief that
knowledge may legitimize itself by its pedigree.
The nobility of the racially
pure knowledge, the untainted knowledge, the knowledge which derives from the
highest authority, if possible from God: these are the (often unconscious)
metaphysical ideas behind the question.
My modified question, ‘How can we hope
to detect error?’ may be said to derive from the view that such pure, untainted
and certain sources do not exist, and that questions of origin or of purity
should not be confounded with questions of validity, or of truth.
This view may
be said to be as old as Xenophanes. Xenophanes knew that our knowledge is
guesswork, opinion—–cloxa rather than episteme-as shown by his verses (DK, B, 18
and 34):
The gods did not reveal, from the beginning, all things to us; but
in the course of time.
Through seeking we may learn, and know things
better.
But as for certain truth, no man has known it.
Nor will he know it;
neither of the gods,
Nor yet of all the things of which I speak.
And even
if by chance he were to utter the perfect truth, he would himself not know
it.
For all is but a woven web of guesses.
Yet the traditional question of
the authoritative sources of knowledge is repeated even today-and very often by
positivists and by other philosophers who believe themselves to be in revolt
against authority.
The proper answer to my question ‘How can we hope to
detect and eliminate error?’ is, I believe, ‘By criticizing the theories or
guesses of others and-if we can train ourselves to do so-by criticizing our own
theories or guesses.’
The latter point is highly desirable, but not
indispensable; for if we fail to criticize our own theories, there may be others
to do it for us.
This answer sums up a position which I propose to call
‘critical rationalism’.
It is a view, an attitude, and a tradition, which we owe
to the Greeks.
It is very different from the ‘rationalism’ or ‘intellectualism’
of Descartes andJ1is school, and very different even from the epistemology of
Kant. Yet in the field of ethics, of moral knowledge, it was approached by Kant
with his principle of autonomy. This principle expresses his realization that we
must not accept the command of an authority, however exalted, as the basis of
ethics. For whenever we are faced with a command by an authority, it is for us
to judge, critically, whether it is moral or immoral to obey.
The authority may
have power to enforce its commands, and we may be powerless to resist. But if we
have the physical power of choice, then the ultimate responsibility remains with
us. It is our own critical decision whether to obey a command; whether to submit
to an authority.
Kant boldly carried this idea into the field of religion: ‘
… in whatever way’, he writes, ‘the Deity should be made known to you, and even
… if He should reveal Himself to you: it is you … who must judge whether you are
permitted to believe in Him, and to worship Him. ‘ [9. See Immanuel Kant,
Religion Within the Limits of Pure Reoson, 2nd edition (1794), Fourth Chapter,
Part II, § I, the first footnote. The passage (not in the 1st edition, 1793) is
quoted more fully in ch. 7 of the present volume, text to note 22.]
In view
of this bold statement, it seems strange that in his philosophy of science Kant
did not adopt the same attitude of critical rationalism, of the critical search
for error. I feel certain that it was only his acceptance of the authority of
Newton’s cosmology-a result of its almost unbelievable success in passing the
most severe tests-which prevented Kant from doing so. If this interpretation of
Kant is correct, then the critical rationalism (and also the critical
empiricism) which I advocate merely puts the finishing touch to Kant’s own
critical philosophy. And this was made possible by Einstein, who taught us that
Newton’s theory may well be mistaken in spite of its overwhelming success.
So
my answer to the questions ‘How do you know? What is the source or the basis of
your assertion? What observations have led you to it?’ would be:
I do not know:
my assertion was merely a guess.
Never mind the source, or the sources, from
which it may spring-there are many possible sources, and I may not be aware of
half of them; and origins or pedigrees have in any case little bearing upon
truth.
But if you are interested in the problem which I tried to solve by my
tentative assertion, you may help me by criticizing it as severely as you can;
and if you can design some experimental test which you think might refute my
assertion, I shall gladly, and to the best of my powers, help you to refute
it.’
This answer
This answer, and almost the whole of the contents of the
present section xv, are taken with only minor changes from a paper of mine which
was first published in The Indian Journal of Philosophy, 1, NO.1, 1959.]
applies, strictly speaking, only if the question is asked about some scientific
assertion as distinct from an historical one. If my conjecture was an historical
one, sources (in the non-ultimate sense) will of course come into the critical
discussion of its validity.
Yet fundamentally, my answer will be the same, as we
have seen.
It is high time now, I think, to formulate the
epistemological results of this discussion.
I will put them in the form of
theses.
There are no ultimate sources of knowledge.
Every source, every
suggestion, is welcome; and every source, every suggestion, is open to critical
examination. Except in history, we usually examine the facts themselves rather
than the sources of our information.
The proper epistemological question
is not one about sources; rather, we ask whether the assertion made is true-that
is to say, whether it agrees with the facts. (That we may operate, without
getting involved in antinomies, with the idea of objective truth in the sense of
correspondence to the facts, has been shown by the work of Alfred Tarski.)
And
we try to find this out, as well as we can, by examining or testing the
assertion itself; either in a direct way, or by examining or testing its
consequences.
In connection with this examination, all kinds of arguments
may be relevant.
A typical procedure is to examine whether our theories are
consistent with our observations. But we may also examine, for example, whether
our historical sources are mutually and internally consistent.
Quantitatively and qualitatively by far the most important source of our
knowledge-apart from inborn knowledge-is tradition. Most things we know we have
learnt by example, by being told, by reading books, by learning how to
criticize, how to take and to accept criticism, how to respect truth.
The
fact that most of the sources of our knowledge are traditional condemns
anti-traditionalism as futile. But this fact must not be held to support a
traditionalist attitude: every bit of our traditional knowledge (and even our
inborn knowledge) is open to critical examination and may be overthrown.
Nevertheless, without tradition, knowledge would be impossible.
Knowledge
cannot start from nothing-from a tabula rasa-nor yet from observation.
The
advance of knowledge consists, mainly, in the modification of earlier knowledge.
Although we may sometimes, for example in archaeology, advance through a chance
observation, the significance of the discovery will usually depend upon its
power to modify our earlier theories.
Pessimistic and optimistic
epistemologies are about equally mistaken.
The pessimistic cave story of Plato
is the true one, and not his optimistic story of anamnesis (even though we
should admit that all men, like all other animals, and even all plants, possess
inborn knowledge). But although the world of appearances is indeed a world of
mere shadows on the walls of our cave, we all constantly reach out beyond it;
and although, as Democritus said, the truth is hidden in the deep, we can probe
into the deep. There is no criterion of truth at our disposal, and this fact
supports pessimism. But we do possess criteria which, if we are lucky, may allow
us to recognize error and falsity. Clarity and distinctness are not criteria of
truth, but such things as obscurity or confusion may indicate error. Similarly
coherence cannot establish truth, but incoherence and inconsistency do establish
falsehood. And, when they are recognized, our own errors provide the dim red
lights which help us in groping our way out of the darkness of our cave.
Neither observation nor reason is an authority.
Intellectual intuition and
imagination are most important, but they are not reliable: they may show us
things very clearly, and yet they may mislead us.
They are indispensable as the
main sources of our theories; but most of our theories are false anyway.
The
most important function of observation and reasoning, and even of intuition and
imagination, is to help us in the critical examination of those bold conjectures
which are the means by which we probe into the unknown.
Although clarity
is valuable in itself, exactness or precision is not: there can be no point in
trying to be more precise than our problem demands.
Linguistic precision is a
phantom, and problems connected with the meaning or definition of words are
unimportant.
Thus our table of Ideas in spite of its symmetry, has an
important and an unimportant side.
While the left-hand side (words and their
meanings) is unimportant, the right-hand side (theories and the problems
connected with their truth) is all-important.
Words are significant only as
instruments for the formulation of theories, and verbal problems are tiresome.
They should be avoided at all cost.
Every solution of a problem raises
new unsolved problems.
The more so the deeper the original problem and the
bolder its solution.
The more we learn about the world, and the deeper our
learning, the more conscious, specific, and articulate will be our knowledge of
what we do not know, our knowledge of our IGNORANCE.
For this, indeed, is the
main source of our IGNORANCE: the fact that our knowledge can be only finite,
while our IGNORANCE must necessarily be infinite.
We may get a glimpse of the
vastness of our IGNORANCE when we contemplate the vastness of the heavens.
Though the mere size of the universe is not the deepest cause of our ignorance,
it is one of its causes.
Ramsey writes in "Foundations of Mathematics"
"Where I seem to differ from some of my friends is in attaching little importance to physical size, I don’t feel in the
least humble before the vastness of the heavens.
The stars may be large but they
cannot think or love.
And these are qualities which impress me far more than
size does.
I take no credit for weighing nearly seventeen stone.
Popper suspects that
Ramsey’s friends would have agreed with him about the insignificance of sheer
physical size; and he suspects that if they felt humble before the vastness of the
heavens, this was because they saw in it a symbol of their IGNORANCE.
Popper holds that it would be worth trying to learn something about the world even if
in trying to do so we should merely learn that we do not know much.
This state
oflearned IGNORANCE might be a help in many of our troubles.
It might be well
for all of us to remember that, while differing widely in the various little
bits we know, in our infinite ignorance we are all equal.
There is a
last question I wish to raise.
If only we look for it we can often find a
true idea, worthy of being preserved, in a philosophical theory which must be
rejected as false. Can we find an idea like this in one of the theories of the
ultimate sources of our knowledge?
I believe we can; and I suggest that it is
one of the two main ideas which underlie the doctrine that the source of all our
knowledge is super-natural.
The first of these ideas is false, I believe, while
the second is true.
The first, the false idea, is that we must justify our
knowledge, or our theories, by positive reasons, that is, by reasons capable of
establishing them, or at least of making them highly probable; at any rate, by
better reasons than that they have so far withstood criticism.
This idea
implies, I suggest, that we must appeal to some ultimate or authoritative
source of true knowledge; which still leaves open the character of that
authority-whether it is human, like observation or reason, or super-human (and
therefore super-natural).
The second idea-whose vital importance has been
stressed by Russell-is that no man’s authority can establish truth by decree;
that we should submit to truth; that truth is above human authority.
Taken
together these two ideas almost immediately yield the conclusion that the
sources from which our knowledge derives must be super-human; a conclusion which
tends to encourage selfrighteousness and the use of force against those who
refuse to see the divine truth.
Some who rightly reject this conclusion do
not, unhappily, reject the first idea-the belief in the existence of ultimate
sources of knowledge. Instead they reject the second idea-the thesis that truth
is above human authority.
They thereby endanger the idea of the objectivity of
knowledge, and of common standards of criticism or rationality.
What we
should do, I suggest, is to give up the idea of ultimate sources of knowledge,
and admit that all knowledge is human; that it is mixed with our errors, our
prejudices, our dreams, and our hopes; that all we can do is to grope for truth
even though it be beyond our reach. We may admit that our groping is often
inspired, but we must be on our guard against the belief, however deeply felt,
that our inspiration carries any authority, divine or otherwise.
If we thus admit
that there is no authority beyond the reach of criticism to be found within the
whole province of our knowledge, however far it may have penetrated into the
unknown, then we can retain, without danger, the idea that truth is beyond human
authority.
And we must retain it. For without this idea there can be no
objective standards of inquiry; no criticism of our conjectures; no groping for
the unknown; no quest for knowledge.
Sunday, December 29, 2013
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment