ring of Gyges, a ring that gives its wearer
invisibility, discussed in Plato’s Republic II, 359b 360d. Glaucon tells the
story of a man who discovered the ring and used it to usurp the throne to
defend the claim that those who behave justly do so only because they lack the
power to act unjustly. If they could avoid paying the penalty of injustice,
Glaucon argues, everyone would be unjust.
Roman philosophy. Grice loved it. AENESIDEMUS: Academic philosopher, founder of a Pyrrhonist
revival in Rome. ANAXAGORAS. pre-Socratic
enquirer into the origin of the cosmos
-- ANDRONICUS. mid-first cent., Peripatetic; editor of Aristotle’s works. -- ANTIOCHUS.
early 1st. cent., Academic who reverted to Plato’s dogmatism -- ANTIPATER, 1st. cent., Stoic,
tutor to Cato Uticensis. -- APOLLONIDES, mid-1st. cent., Stoic, adviser to Cato Uticensis -- APOLLONIUS, 1st. cent. CE,
Neo-pythagorean. -- APULEIUS. ca.125–180 CE,
Platonic, author of "Metamorphoses". -- ARCESILAUS. mid-3rd.cent., Academic sceptic, head of the
New Academy --- ARISTIPPUS. late-5th. cent., member of Socrates’s circle --
ARISTON. 3rd. cent., Peripatetic and
head of the Lyceum -- ARISTOTLE. 384–322, founder of the Peripatetic school -- ARISTUS. early
1st. cent., head of the Academy and
teacher of Brutus -- ARIUS. 1st. cent., adviser to Augustus -- ARTEMIDORUS.
1st. cent. CE, Stoic, friend of Pliny the Younger and son-in-law of Musonius --
ATHENODORUS. mid-1st. cent., Stoic and adviser
to Cato Uticensis, in whose house he lived -- ATHENODORUS.
mid-first cent., Stoic and friend of
Cicero -- ATTALUS. 1st. cent. CE, Stoic,
teacher of Seneca -- AUGUSTINE. 354–430 CE, Neo-platonist -- BION. ca. 335–245, Cynic, popular teacher -- BOETHIUS
ca. 480–524 CE, philosopher with Stoic
and Neoplatonist views, author of "The Consolation of Philosophy" -- CARNEADES mid-2nd. cent.,
head of the New Academy, Sceptic and
star of the Athenian embassy to Rome in 155 -- CHAEREMON. mid-lst. cent., CE, Stoic, tutor to Nero --
CHRYSIPPUS. ca. 280–206, head of the
Stoic school from 232 -- CICERO. 106–43, leading transmitter of Hellenistic philosophy to Rome and
Renaissance Europe, follower of the New
Academy and pupil of Philo of Larissa -- CLEANTHES. 331–232, Zeno’s successor as head of the Stoic school from
262 -- CLITOMACHUS. late-2nd. cent., Sceptic and pupil of Carneades, head
of the New Academy from 127 -- CORNUTUS.
1st. cent. CE, Stoic, teacher and friend
of Persius and Lucan -- CRANTOR ca. 335–275, Academic, the first commentator on Plato -- CRATES. ca.365–285,
Cynic, follower of Diogenes of Sinope
and teacher of Zeno of Citium -- CRATIPPUS. mid-lst. cent., Peripatetic, friend of Cicero and Nigidius
and teacher of Cicero’s son. -- CRITOLAUS.
first half of 2nd. cent., head of the Peripatetic school and member of the Athenian embassy to Rome in 155 --
DEMETRIUS. 1st. cent. CE, friend of
Seneca -- DEMETRIUS. mid-1st.cent., adviser of Cato Uticensis -- DEMOCRITUS. second half of 5th.
cent., pre-Socratic, founder of atomism
-- DICHAEARCHUS. late 4th. cent., Peripatetic, pupil of Aristotle -- DIODOTUS. first of 1st.cent.,
Stoic, teacher and friend of Cicero, in
whose house he lived -- DIOGENES LAERTIUS. first half of 3rd. cent. CE, author of "The Lives of the
Philosophers" -- DIOGENES OF
APOLLONIA. 2nd half of 5th. cent., pre-Socratic philosopher and
enquirer into the natural world; a
source for Seneca’s "Naturates Quaestiones" -- DIOGENES OF BABYLON.
mid-2nd. cent., head of the Stoic school and member of the Athenian embassy to Rome in 155, tutor to
Panaetius -- DIOGENES OF OENOANDA late
2nd. cent. CE, Epicurean and part-author of the inscription on the stoa which he caused to be set up in Oenoanda
-- DIOGENES OF SINOPE. mid-4th.cent., founder of Cynicism -- EPICTETUS. ca. 50–120 CE, Stoic, pupil of Musonius -- EPICURUS 341–271,
principal source for Lucretius’s poem --
EUPHRATES late-lst. cent. CE, Stoic, student of Musonius and friend of Pliny the Younger -- FAVORINUS. ca.
85–155 CE, philosopher of the Second
Sophistic, friend of Plutarch and teacher of Fronto -- GALEN. late-second cent. CE, physician to Marcus
Aurelius, Platonist -- HECATO. early
1st. cent., Stoic, pupil of Panaetius and member of circle of Posidonius -- HERMARCHUS. 1st half of 3rd.
cent., pupil of Epicurus and his
successor as head of the Epicurean school from 271, with Epicurus, Metrodorus and Polyaenus, one of “The Four
Men”, founders of the Epicurean school
-- HIEROCLES early 2nd. cent. CE, Stoic --
LAELIUS. ca. 190–125, consul in
140, friend of Scipio Aemilianus and Panaetius and called by Cicero "the first Roman
philosopher." -- LEUCIPPUS. second half
of 5th. cent., co-founder with
Democritus of atomism -- LUCRETIUS. first half of 1st. cent., Epicurean, author of "De
Rerum Natura" -- MANILIUS. ate-lst.
cent. BCE and early-lst. cent CE, Stoic author of
"Astronomica" -- MARCUS
AURELIUS. 121–180 CE, Roman emperor (161–180) and Stoic, author of
"To Himself", a private diary
-- MENIPPUS. first half of 3rd. cent., Cynic and satirical author in prose and verse on
philosophical subjects -- METRODORUS. ca. 331–278, friend of Epicurus and one
“The Four Men”, founders of Epicureanism
-- MODERATUS. second half of 1st. cent. CE,
Neo-pythagorean -- MUSONIUS. second half of 1st. cent. CE, Roman of Etruscan descent, Stoic, teacher of Epictetus
-- NIGIDIUS. 1st. cent., Neo-pythagorean
-- PANAETIUS. ca. 185–109, Stoic, head of the Stoic school from 129, influential at Rome, friend
of Scipio Aemilianus and major source
for Cicero’s "De Officiis" -- PARMENIDES. first half of 5th. cent.,
pre-Socratic, pioneer enquirer into the
nature of “what is” -- PATRON. first half of 1st. cent., friend of Cicero and successor of Phaedrus as
head of the Epicurean school -- PHAEDRUS.
ca. 140–70, Epicurean, admired by Cicero. head of the Epicurean school in the
last years of his life -- PHILO OF ALEXANDRIA.
first half of 1st. cent. CE, philosopher, sympathetic to Stoic ethics
and influential in the later development
of Neo-platonism -- PHILO OF LARISSA
ca.159–84, head of the New Academy, 110–88, the most influential of
Cicero’s tutors -- PHILODEMUS. ca.
110–40, Epicurean philosopher, protegé of Piso Caesoninus and an influence on
Virgil and Horace, many of his fragmentary
writings are preserved in the Herculaneum papyri -- PLATO ca.
429–347, founder of the Academy and
disciple and interpreter of Socrates -- PLOTINUS. 205–270 CE, Neo-platonist,
resident in Rome and Campania -- PLUTARCH. ca. 50–120 CE, Platonist -- POLEMO.
died 270, Platonist and head of the
Academy from 314. -- POLYAENUS. died before
271, friend of Epicurus and one of “The
Four Men,” founders of Epicureanism -- POSIDONIUS. ca. 135–50, Stoic, student
of Panaetius and head of his own school
in Rhodes, where Cicero heard him. The dominant figure in middle
Stoicism, whose works encompassed the
whole range of intellectual enquiry.-- PYRRHO. ca.
365–270, the founder of Scepticism, whose doctrines were revived in Rome
by Aenesidemus -- PYTHAGORAS OF SAMOS
6th. cent., head of a community at
Croton in S. Italy, emphasized the importance of number and proportion,
his doctrines included vegetarianism and
the transmigration of souls, influenced
Plato, his philosophy was revived at Rome by Nigidius and the Sextii.
-- RUSTICUS. consul in 133 and 162 CE, Stoic, friend
and teacher of Marcus Aurelius --
SENECA. 4 BCE–65 CE, Stoic, tutor, adviser and victim of Nero, author of philosophical treatises,
including "Dialogi" and "Epistulae Morales" -- SEVERUS. consul in 146 CE,
Stoic friend and teacher of Marcus
Aurelius, whose son married his daughter. -- SEXTIUS. mid-1st. cent.,
Neo-pythagorean, founder of the only genuinely Roman school of
philosophy; admired by Seneca for his
disciplined Roman ethos -- SEXTUS EMPIRICUS.
late-2nd. cent. CE, Sceptic, author of philosophical and medical works
and critic of Stoicism, principal source
for Pyrrhonism -- SIRO. 1st. cent.,
Epicurean, teacher in Campania of Virgil -- SOCRATES. 469–399,
iconic Athenian philosopher and one of
the most influential figures in Greek
philosophy; he wrote nothing but is the central figure in Plato’s
dialogues, admired by non-Academics,
including the Stoic Marcus Aurelius nearly six hundred years after his death -- SOTION. 1st. cent.
CE, Neopythagorean, teacher of Seneca --
SPEUSIPPUS. ca. 407–339, Plato’s successor as head of the Academy -- TELES. second half of 3rd. cent.,
Cynic, author of diatribes on ethical
subjects -- THEOPHRASTUS. 372–287, Peripatetic, successor to Aristotle as head of the Lyceum from 322 --
VARRO, 116–27, Academic, Roman polymath,
author of works on language, agriculture, history and philosophy, as well as satires, and principal
speaker in the later version of Cicero’s
"Academica" -- XENOCRATES. died 314, head of the Academy from 339 --
ZENO OF CITIUM. 335–263, founder of Stoicism, originally a follower of the Cynic Crates, taught at
Athens in the Stoa Poikile, which gave
its name to his school -- ZENO OF SIDON. ca. 155–75, head of the Epicurean school at Athens, where he taught
Philodemus and was heard by Cicero.
Rorty, R. philosopher, notable for the breadth of his
philosophical and cultural interests. He was educated at the of Chicago and Yale and has taught at
Wellesley, Princeton, Virginia, and Stanford. His early work was primarily in
standard areas of analytic philosophy such as the philosophy of mind, where,
for example, he developed an important defense of eliminative materialism. In
9, however, he published Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, which was both
hailed and denounced as a fundamental critique of analytic philosophy. Both the
praise and the abuse were often based on misconceptions, but there is no doubt
that Rorty questioned fundamental presuppositions of many Anglo- philosophers
and showed affinities for Continental alternatives to analytic philosophy. At
root, however, Rorty’s position is neither analytic except in its stylistic
clarity nor Continental except in its cultural breadth. His view is, rather,
pragmatic, a contemporary incarnation of the distinctively philosophizing of James, Peirce, and Dewey.
On Rorty’s reading, pragmatism involves a rejection of the representationalism
that has dominated modern philosophy from Descartes through logical positivism.
According to representationalism, we have direct access only to ideas that
represent the world, not to the world itself. Philosophy has the privileged
role of determining the criteria for judging that our representations are
adequate to reality. A main thrust of Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature is to
discredit representationalism, first by showing how it has functioned as an
unjustified presupposition in classical modern philosophers such as Descartes,
Locke, and Kant, and second by showing how analytic philosophers such as Wilfrid
Sellars and Quine have revealed the incoherence of representationalist
assumptions in contemporary epistemology. Since, on Rorty’s view,
representationalism defines the epistemological project of modern philosophy,
its failure requires that we abandon this project and, with it, traditional
pretensions to a privileged cognitive role for philosophy. Rorty sees no point
in seeking a non-representationalist basis for the justification or the truth
of our knowledge claims. It is enough to accept as justified beliefs those on
which our epistemic community agrees and to use ‘true’ as an honorific term for
beliefs that we see as “justified to the hilt.” Rorty characterizes his
positive position as “liberal ironism.” His liberalism is of a standard sort,
taking as its basic value the freedom of all individuals: first, their freedom
from suffering, but then also freedom to form their lives with whatever values
they find most compelling. Rorty distinguishes the “public sphere” in which we
all share the liberal commitment to universal freedom from the “private
spheres” in which we all work out our own specific conception of the good. His
ironism reflects his realization that there is no grounding for public or
private values other than our deep but contingent commitment to them and his
appreciation of the multitude of private values that he does not himself happen
to share. Rorty has emphasized the importance of literature and literary
criticism as opposed to traditional
philosophy for providing the citizens of
a liberal society with appropriate sensitivities to the needs and values of
others.
Roscelin de Compiègne, philosopher and logician who
became embroiled in theological controversy when he applied his logical
teachings to the doctrine of the Trinity. Since almost nothing survives of his
written work, we must rely on hostile accounts of his views by Anselm of
Canterbury and Peter Abelard, both of whom openly opposed his positions.
Perhaps the most notorious view Roscelin is said to have held is that
universals are merely the puffs of air produced when a word is pronounced. On
this point he opposed views current among many theologians that a universal has
an existence independent of language, and somehow is what many different
particulars are. Roscelin’s aversion to any proposal that different things can
be some one thing is probably what led him in his thinking about the three
persons of God to a position that sounded suspiciously like the heresy of
tritheism. Roscelin also evidently held that the qualities of things are not
entities distinct from the subjects that possess them. This indicates that
Roscelin probably denied that terms in the Aristotelian categories other than
substance signified anything distinct from substances. Abelard, the foremost
logician of the twelfth century, studied under Roscelin around 1095 and was
undoubtedly influenced by him on the question of universals. Roscelin’s view
that universals are linguistic entities remained an important option in
medieval thought. Otherwise his positions do not appear to have had much
currency in the ensuing decades.
Rosenzweig, F. G. philosopher and Jewish theologian
known as one of the founders of religious existentialism. His early relation to
Judaism was tenuous, and at one point he came close to converting to
Christianity. A religious experience in a synagogue made him change his mind
and return to Judaism. His chief philosophic works are a two-volume study,
Hegel and the State 0, and his masterpiece, The Star of Redemption 1.
Rosenzweig’s experience in World War I caused him to reject absolute idealism
on the ground that it cannot account for the privacy and finality of death.
Instead of looking for a unifying principle behind existence, Rosenzweig starts
with three independent realities “given” in experience: God, the self, and the
world. Calling his method “radical empiricism,” he explains how God, the self,
and the world are connected by three primary relations: creation, revelation,
and redemption. In revelation, God does not communicate verbal statements but
merely a presence that calls for love and devotion from worshipers.
Rosmini-Serbati, Antonio, philosopher, Catholic priest,
counselor to Pope Pius IX, and supporter of the supremacy of the church over
civil government Neo-Guelphism. Rosmini had two major concerns: the objectivity
of human knowledge and the synthesis of philosophical thought within the
tradition of Catholic thought. In his Nuovo saggio sull’origine delle idee “New
Essay on the Origin of Ideas,” 1830, he identifies the universal a priori
intuitive component of all human knowledge with the idea of being that gives us
the notion of a possible or ideal being. Everything in the world is known by
intellectual perception, which is the synthesis of sensation and the idea of
being. Except for the idea of being, which is directly given by God, all ideas
derive from abstraction. The objectivity of human knowledge rests on its
universal origin in the idea of being. The harmony between philosophy and
religion comes from the fact that all human knowledge is the result of divine
revelation. Rosmini’s thought was influenced by Augustine and Aquinas, and
stimulated by the attempt to find a solution to the contrasting needs of
rationalism and empiricism.
Ross: w. d. Aristotelian scholar and moral philosopher.
Born in Edinburgh and educated at the of
Edinburgh and at Balliol , Oxford, he became a fellow of Merton , then a
fellow, tutor, and eventually provost at Oriel . He was vice-chancellor of
Oxford 144 and president of the British
Academy 640. He was knighted in 8 in view of national service. Ross was a
distinguished classical scholar: he edited the Oxford translations of Aristotle
831 and tr. the Metaphysics and the Ethics himself. His Aristotle 3 is a
judicious exposition of Aristotle’s work as a whole. Kant’s Ethical Theory 4 is
a commentary on Kant’s The Groundwork of Ethics. His major contribution to
philosophy was in ethics: The Right and the Good 0 and Foundations of Ethics9.
The view he expressed there was controversial in English-speaking countries for
ten years or so. He held that ‘right’ and ‘good’ are empirically indefinable
terms that name objective properties the presence of which is known intuitively
by persons who are mature and educated. We first cognize them in particular
instances, then arrive at general principles involving them by “intuitive
induction.” He thought every ethical theory must admit at least one intuition.
The knowledge of moral principles is thus rather like knowledge of the
principles of geometry. ‘Right’ ‘dutiful’ applies to acts, in the sense of what
an agent brings about and there is no duty to act from a good motive, and a
right act can have a bad motive; ‘morally good’ applies primarily to the
desires that bring about action. He castigated utilitarianism as absorbing all
duties into enhancing the wellbeing of everyone affected, whereas in fact we
have strong special obligations to keep promises, make reparation for injuries,
repay services done, distribute happiness in accord with merit, benefit
individuals generally and he concedes this is a weighty matter and ourselves
only in respect of knowledge and virtue, and not injure others normally a
stronger obligation than that to benefit. That we have these “prima facie”
duties is self-evident, but they are only prima facie in the sense that they
are actual duties only if there is no stronger conflicting prima facie duty;
and when prima facie duties conflict, what one ought to do is what satisfies
all of them best although which this is
is a matter of judgment, not self-evidence. He conceded, however, in contrast
to his general critique of utilitarianism, that public support of these prima
facie principles with their intuitive strength can be justified on utilitarian
grounds. To meet various counterexamples Ross introduced complications, such as
that a promise is not binding if discharge of it will not benefit the promisee
providing this was an implicit understanding, and it is less binding if made
long ago or in a casual manner. Only four states of affairs are good in
themselves: desire to do one’s duty virtue, knowledge, pleasure, and the
distribution of happiness in accordance with desert. Of these, virtue is more
valuable than any amount of knowledge or pleasure. In Foundations of Ethics he
held that virtue and pleasure are not good in the same sense: virtue is
“admirable” but pleasure only a “worthy object of satisfaction” so ‘good’ does
not name just one property.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, philosopher, essayist,
novelist, and musician, best known for his theories on social freedom and
societal rights, education, and religion. Born in Geneva, he was largely
self-educated and moved to France as a teenager. Throughout much of his life he
moved between Paris and the provinces with several trips abroad including a Scottish
stay with Hume and a return visit to Geneva, where he reconverted to
Protestantism from his earlier conversion to Catholicism. For a time he was a
friend of Diderot and other philosophes and was asked to contribute articles on
music for the Encyclopedia. Rousseau’s work can be seen from at least three
perspectives. As social contract theorist, he attempts to construct a
hypothetical state of nature to explain the current human situation. This
evolves a form of philosophical anthropology that gives us both a theory of
human nature and a series of pragmatic claims concerning social organization.
As a social commentator, he speaks of both practical and ideal forms of
education and social organization. As a moralist, he continually attempts to
unite the individual and the citizen through some form of universal political
action or consent. In Discourse on the Origin and Foundation of Inequality
Among Mankind 1755, Rousseau presents us with an almost idyllic view of
humanity. In nature humans are first seen as little more than animals except
for their special species sympathy. Later, through an explanation of the
development of reason and language, he is able to suggest how humans, while
retaining this sympathy, can, by distancing themselves from nature, understand
their individual selves. This leads to natural community and the closest thing
to what Rousseau considers humanity’s perfect moment. Private property quickly
follows on the division of labor, and humans find themselves alienated from
each other by the class divisions engendered by private property. Thus man, who
was born in freedom, now finds himself in chains. The Social Contract or
Principles of Political Right 1762 has a more ambitious goal. With an account
of the practical role of the legislator and the introduction of the concept of
the general will, Rousseau attempts to give us a foundation for good government
by presenting a solution to the conflicts between the particular and the
universal, the individual and the citizen, and the actual and the moral.
Individuals, freely agreeing to a social pact and giving up their rights to the
community, are assured of the liberties and equality of political citizenship
found in the contract. It is only through being a citizen that the individual
can fully realize his freedom and exercise his moral rights and duties. While
the individual is naturally good, he must always guard against being dominated
or dominating. Rousseau finds a solution to the problems of individual freedoms
and interests in a superior form of moral/political action that he calls the
general will. The individual as citizen substitutes “I must” for “I will,”
which is also an “I shall” when it expresses assent to the general will. The
general will is a universal force or statement and thus is more noble than any
particular will. In willing his own interest, the citizen is at the same time
willing what is communally good. The particular and the universal are united.
The individual human participant realizes himself in realizing the good of all.
As a practical political commentator Rousseau knew that the universal and the
particular do not always coincide. For this he introduced the idea of the
legislator, which allows the individual citizen to realize his fulfillment as
social being and to exercise his individual rights through universal consent.
In moments of difference between the majority will and the general will the
legislator will instill the correct moral/political understanding. This will be
represented in the laws. While sovereignty rests with the citizens, Rousseau
does not require that political action be direct. Although all government
should be democratic, various forms of government from representative democracy
preferable in small societies to strong monarchies preferable in large nation-states
may be acceptable. To shore up the unity and stability of individual societies,
Rousseau suggests a sort of civic religion to which all citizens subscribe and
in which all members participate. His earlier writings on education and his
later practical treatises on the governments of Poland and Corsica reflect
related concerns with natural and moral development and with historical and
geographical considerations.
Royce, J. philosopher best known for his pragmatic
idealism, his ethics of loyalty, and his theory of community. Educated at
Berkeley, at Johns Hopkins, and in G.y, he taught philosophy at Harvard from 2.
Royce held that a concept of the absolute or eternal was needed to account for
truth, ultimate meaning, and reality in the face of very real evil in human
experience. Seeking to reconcile individuals with the Absolute, he postulated,
in The World and the Individual 9,1, Absolute Will and Thought as an expression
of the concrete and differentiated individuality of the world. Royce saw the
individual self as both moral and sinful, developing through social
interaction, community experience, and communal and self-interpretation. Self
is constituted by a life plan, by loyalty to an ultimate goal. Yet
selflimitation and egoism, two human sins, work against achievement of
individual goals, perhaps rendering life a senseless failure. The self needs
saving and this is the message of religion, argues Royce The Religious Aspects
of Philosophy, 5; The Sources of Religious Insight, 2. For Royce, the instrument
of salvation is the community. In The Philosophy of Loyalty 8, he develops an
ethics of loyalty to loyalty, i.e., the extension of loyalty throughout the
human community. In The Problem of Christianity 3, Royce presents a doctrine of
community that overcomes the individualismcollectivism dilemma and allows a
genuine blending of individual and social will. Community is built through
interpretation, a mediative process that reconciles two ideas, goals, and
persons, bringing common meaning and understanding. Interpretation involves
respect for selves as dynamos of ideas and purposes, the will to interpret,
dissatisfaction with partial meanings and narrowness of view,
reciprocity, and mutuality. In this work, the Absolute
is a “Community of Interpretation and Hope,” in which there is an endlessly
accumulating series of interpretations and significant deeds. An individual
contribution thus is not lost but becomes an indispensable element in the
divine life. Among Royce’s influential students were C. I. Lewis, William
Ernest Hocking, Norbert Wiener, Santayana, and T. S. Eliot.
rule of law, the largely formal or procedural
properties of a well-ordered legal system. Commonly, these properties are
thought to include: a prohibition of arbitrary power the lawgiver is also
subject to the laws; laws that are general, prospective, clear, and consistent
capable of guiding conduct; and tribunals courts that are reasonably accessible
and fairly structured to hear and determine legal claims. Contemporary
discussions of the rule of law focus on two major questions: 1 to what extent
is conformity to the rule of law essential to the very idea of a legal system;
and 2 what is the connection between the rule of law and the substantive moral
value of a legal system?
Russell, Bertrand Arthur William, philosopher,
logician, social reformer, and man of letters, one of the founders of analytic
philosophy. Born of Celtic Highland stock into an aristocratic family in Wales
(then part of England), Russell always divided his interests between politics,
philosophy, and the ladies (he married six times). Orphaned at four, he was
brought up by his grandmother, who educated him at home with the help of “rather
dull” tutors. He studied mathematics at Cambridge and then, as his grandmother
says, ‘out of the blue,’ he turned to philosophy. At home he had absorbed J. S.
Mill’s liberalism, but not his empiricism. At Cambridge he came under the
influence of neo-Hegelianism, especially the idealism of McTaggart, Ward his
tutor, and Bradley. His earliest logical views were influenced most by Bradley,
especially Bradley’s rejection of psychologism. But, like Ward and McTaggart,
he rejected Bradley’s metaphysical monism in favor of pluralism or monadism.
Even as an idealist, he held that scientific knowledge was the best available
and that philosophy should be built around it. Through many subsequent changes,
this belief about science, his pluralism, and his anti-psychologism remained
constant. In 5, he conceived the idea of an idealist encyclopedia of the
sciences to be developed by the use of transcendental arguments to establish
the conditions under which the special sciences are possible. Russell’s first
philosophical book, An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry 7, was part of this
project, as were other mostly unfinished and unpublished pieces on physics and
arithmetic written at this time see his Collected Papers, vols. 12. Russell
claimed, in contrast to Kant, to use transcendental arguments in a purely
logical way compatible with his anti-psychologism. In this case, however, it
should be both possible and preferable to replace them by purely deductive
arguments. Another problem arose in connection with asymmetrical relations,
which led to contradictions if treated as internal relations, but which were
essential for any treatment of mathematics. Russell resolved both problems in 8
by abandoning idealism including internal relations and his Kantian
methodology. He called this the one real revolution in his philosophy. With his
Cambridge contemporary Moore, he adopted an extreme Platonic realism, fully
stated in The Principles of Mathematics 3 though anticipated in A Critical
Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz 0. Russell’s work on the sciences was
by then concentrated on pure mathematics, but the new philosophy yielded little
progress until, in 0, he discovered Peano’s symbolic logic, which offered hope
that pure mathematics could be treated without Kantian intuitions or
transcendental arguments. On this basis Russell propounded logicism, the claim
that the whole of pure mathematics could be derived deductively from logical
principles, a position he came to independently of Frege, who held a similar
but more restricted view but whose work Russell discovered only later. Logicism
was announced in The Principles of Mathematics; its development occupied
Russell, in collaboration with Whitehead, for the next ten years. Their results
were published in Principia Mathematica 013, 3 vols., in which detailed
derivations were given for Cantor’s set theory, finite and transfinite
arithmetic, and elementary parts of measure theory. As a demonstration of
Russell’s logicism, Principia depends upon much prior arithmetization of
mathematics, e.g. of analysis, which is not explicitly treated. Even with these
allowances much is still left out: e.g., abstract algebra and statistics.
Russell’s unpublished papers Papers, vols. 45, however, contain logical
innovations not included in Principia, e.g., anticipations of Church’s
lambda-calculus. On Russell’s extreme realism, everything that can be referred
to is a term that has being though not necessarily existence. The combination
of terms by means of a relation results in a complex term, which is a
proposition. Terms are neither linguistic nor psychological. The first task of
philosophy is the theoretical analysis of propositions into their constituents.
The propositions of logic are unique in that they remain true when any of their
terms apart from logical constants are replaced by any other terms. In 1
Russell discovered that this position fell prey to self-referential paradoxes.
For example, if the combination of any number of terms is a new term, the
combination of all terms is a term distinct from any term. The most famous such
paradox is called Russell’s paradox. Russell’s solution was the theory of
types, which banned self-reference by stratifying terms and expressions into
complex hierarchies of disjoint subclasses. The expression ‘all terms’, e.g.,
is then meaningless unless restricted to terms of specified types, and the
combination of terms of a given type is a term of different type. A simple
version of the theory appeared in Principles of Mathematics appendix A, but did
not eliminate all the paradoxes. Russell developed a more elaborate version
that did, in “Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of Types” 8 and in
Principia. From 3 to 8 Russell sought to preserve his earlier account of logic
by finding other ways to avoid the paradoxes
including a well-developed substitutional theory of classes and relations
posthumously published in Essays in Analysis, 4, and Papers, vol. 5. Other
costs of type theory for Russell’s logicism included the vastly increased
complexity of the resulting sysRussell, Bertrand Arthur William Russell,
Bertrand Arthur William 802 802 tem
and the admission of the problematic axiom of reducibility. Two other
difficulties with Russell’s extreme realism had important consequences: 1 ‘I
met Quine’ and ‘I met a man’ are different propositions, even when Quine is the
man I met. In the Principles, the first proposition contains a man, while the
second contains a denoting concept that denotes the man. Denoting concepts are
like Fregean senses; they are meanings and have denotations. When one occurs in
a proposition the proposition is not about the concept but its denotation. This
theory requires that there be some way in which a denoting concept, rather than
its denotation, can be denoted. After much effort, Russell concluded in “On
Denoting” 5 that this was impossible and eliminated denoting concepts as
intermediaries between denoting phrases and their denotations by means of his
theory of descriptions. Using firstorder predicate logic, Russell showed in a
broad, though not comprehensive range of cases how denoting phrases could be
eliminated in favor of predicates and quantified variables, for which logically
proper names could be substituted. These were names of objects of
acquaintance represented in ordinary
language by ‘this’ and ‘that’. Most names, he thought, were disguised definite
descriptions. Similar techniques were applied elsewhere to other kinds of
expression e.g. class names resulting in the more general theory of incomplete
symbols. One important consequence of this was that the ontological commitments
of a theory could be reduced by reformulating the theory to remove expressions
that apparently denoted problematic entities. 2 The theory of incomplete
symbols also helped solve extreme realism’s epistemic problems, namely how to
account for knowledge of terms that do not exist, and for the distinction
between true and false propositions. First, the theory explained how knowledge
of a wide range of items could be achieved by knowledge by acquaintance of a
much narrower range. Second, propositional expressions were treated as incomplete
symbols and eliminated in favor of their constituents and a propositional
attitude by Russell’s multiple relation theory of judgment. These innovations
marked the end of Russell’s extreme realism, though he remained a Platonist in
that he included universals among the objects of acquaintance. Russell referred
to all his philosophy after 8 as logical atomism, indicating thereby that
certain categories of items were taken as basic and items in other categories
were constructed from them by rigorous logical means. It depends therefore upon
reduction, which became a key concept in early analytic philosophy. Logical
atomism changed as Russell’s logic developed and as more philosophical
consequences were drawn from its application, but the label is now most often
applied to the modified realism Russell held from 5 to 9. Logic was central to
Russell’s philosophy from 0 onward, and much of his fertility and importance as
a philosopher came from his application of the new logic to old problems. In 0
Russell became a lecturer at Cambridge. There his interests turned to
epistemology. In writing a popular book, Problems of Philosophy 2, he first
came to appreciate the work of the British empiricists, especially Hume and
Berkeley. He held that empirical knowledge is based on direct acquaintance with
sense-data, and that matter itself, of which we have only knowledge by
description, is postulated as the best explanation of sense-data. He soon
became dissatisfied with this idea and proposed instead that matter be logically
constructed out of sensedata and unsensed sensibilia, thereby obviating dubious
inferences to material objects as the causes of sensations. This proposal was
inspired by the successful constructions of mathematical concepts in Principia.
He planned a large work, “Theory of Knowledge,” which was to use the multiple
relation theory to extend his account from acquaintance to belief and inference
Papers, vol. 7. However, the project was abandoned as incomplete in the face of
Vitters’s attacks on the multiple relation theory, and Russell published only
those portions dealing with acquaintance. The construction of matter, however,
went ahead, at least in outline, in Our Knowledge of the External World 4,
though the only detailed constructions were undertaken later by Carnap. On
Russell’s account, material objects are those series of sensibilia that obey
the laws of physics. Sensibilia of which a mind is aware sense-data provide the
experiential basis for that mind’s knowledge of the physical world. This theory
is similar, though not identical, to phenomenalism. Russell saw the theory as
an application of Ockham’s razor, by which postulated entities were replaced by
logical constructions. He devoted much time to understanding modern physics,
including relativity and quantum theory, and in The Analysis of Matter 7 he
incorporated the fundamental ideas of those theories into his construction of
the physical world. In this book he abandoned sensibilia as fundamental
constituents of the world in favor Russell, Bertrand Arthur William Russell,
Bertrand Arthur William 803 803 of
events, which were “neutral” because intrinsically neither physical nor mental.
In 6 Russell was dismissed from Cambridge on political grounds and from that
time on had to earn his living by writing and public lecturing. His popular
lectures, “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism” 8, were a result of this. These
lectures form an interim work, looking back on the logical achievements of 510
and emphasizing their importance for philosophy, while taking stock of the
problems raised by Vitters’s criticisms of the multiple relation theory. In 9
Russell’s philosophy of mind underwent substantial changes, partly in response
to those criticisms. The changes appeared in “On Propositions: What They Are
and How They Mean” 9 and The Analysis of Mind 1, where the influence of
contemporary trends in psychology, especially behaviorism, is evident. Russell
gave up the view that minds are among the fundamental constituents of the
world, and adopted neutral monism, already advocated by Mach, James, and
the New Realists. On Russell’s neutral
monism, a mind is constituted by a set of events related by subjective temporal
relations simultaneity, successiveness and by certain special “mnemic” causal
laws. In this way he was able to explain the apparent fact that “Hume’s
inability to perceive himself was not peculiar.” In place of the multiple
relation theory Russell identified the contents of beliefs with images
“imagepropositions” and words “word-propositions”, understood as certain sorts
of events, and analyzed truth qua correspondence in terms of resemblance and
causal relations. From 8 to 4 Russell lived in the United States, where he
wrote An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth 0 and his popular A History of Western
Philosophy 5. His philosophical attention turned from metaphysics to
epistemology and he continued to work in this field after he returned in 4 to
Cambridge, where he completed his last major philosophical work, Human
Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits 8. The framework of Russell’s early
epistemology consisted of an analysis of knowledge in terms of justified true
belief though it has been suggested that he unintentionally anticipated Edmund
Gettier’s objection to this analysis, and an analysis of epistemic justification
that combined fallibilism with a weak empiricism and with a foundationalism
that made room for coherence. This framework was retained in An Inquiry and
Human Knowledge, but there were two sorts of changes that attenuated the
foundationalist and empiricist elements and accentuated the fallibilist
element. First, the scope of human knowledge was reduced. Russell had already
replaced his earlier Moorean consequentialism about values with subjectivism.
Contrast “The Elements of Ethics,” 0, with, e.g., Religion and Science, 5, or
Human Society in Ethics and Politics, 4. Consequently, what had been construed
as self-evident judgments of intrinsic value came to be regarded as
non-cognitive expressions of desire. In addition, Russell now reversed his
earlier belief that deductive inference can yield new knowledge. Second, the
degree of justification attainable in human knowledge was reduced at all
levels. Regarding the foundation of perceptual beliefs, Russell came to admit
that the object-knowledge “acquaintance with a sensedatum” was replaced by
“noticing a perceptive occurrence” in An Inquiry that provides the
non-inferential justification for a perceptual belief is buried under layers of
“interpretation” and unconscious inference in even the earliest stages of perceptual
processes. Regarding the superstructure of inferentially justified beliefs,
Russell concluded in Human Knowledge that unrestricted induction is not
generally truthpreserving anticipating Goodman’s “new riddle of induction”.
Consideration of the work of Reichenbach and Keynes on probability led him to
the conclusion that certain “postulates” are needed “to provide the antecedent
probabilities required to justify inductions,” and that the only possible
justification for believing these postulates lies, not in their self-evidence,
but in the resultant increase in the overall coherence of one’s total belief
system. In the end, Russell’s desire for certainty went unsatisfied, as he felt
himself forced to the conclusion that “all human knowledge is uncertain,
inexact, and partial. To this doctrine we have not found any limitation
whatever.” Russell’s strictly philosophical writings of 9 and later have
generally been less influential than his earlier writings. His influence was
eclipsed by that of logical positivism and ordinary language philosophy. He
approved of the logical positivists’ respect for logic and science, though he
disagreed with their metaphysical agnosticism. But his dislike of ordinary
language philosophy was visceral. In My Philosophical Development 9, he accused
its practitioners of abandoning the attempt to understand the world, “that
grave and important task which philosophy throughout the ages has hitherto
pursued.”
Russian nihilism, a form of nihilism, a phenomenon
mainly of Russia in the 1860s, which, in contrast to the general cultural
nihilism that Nietzsche later criticized in the 0s as a “dead-end” devaluing of
all values, was futureoriented and “instrumental,” exalting possibility over
actuality. Russian nihilists urged the “annihilation” figurative and literal of the past and present, i.e., of realized
social and cultural values and of such values in process of realization, in the
name of the future, i.e., for the sake of social and cultural values yet to be
realized. Bakunin, as early as 1842, had stated the basic nihilist theme: “the
negation of what exists . . . for the benefit of the future which does not yet
exist.” The bestknown literary exemplar of nihilism in Russia is the character
Bazarov in Turgenev’s novel Fathers and Sons 1862. Its most articulate
spokesman was Dmitri Pisarev 184068, who shared Bazarov’s cultural
anti-Romanticism, philosophical anti-idealism, and unquestioned trust in the
power of natural science to solve social and moral problems. Pisarev proclaimed,
“It is precisely in the [spread-eagled, laboratory] frog that the salvation . .
. of the Russian people is to be found.” And he formulated what may serve as
the manifesto of Russian nihilism: “What can be broken should be broken; what
will stand the blow is fit to live; what breaks into smithereens is rubbish; in
any case, strike right and left, it will not and cannot do any harm.”
Russian philosophy, the philosophy produced by Russian
thinkers, both in Russia and in the countries to which they emigrated, from the
mideighteenth century to the present. There was no Renaissance in Russia, but
in the early eighteenth century Peter the Great, in opening a “window to the
West,” opened Russia up to Western philosophical influences. The beginnings of
Russian speculation date from that period, in the dialogues, fables, and poems
of the anti-Enlightenment thinker Gregory Skovoroda 172294 and in the social
tracts, metaphysical treatises, and poems of the Enlightenment thinker
Alexander Radishchev 17491802. Until the last quarter of the nineteenth century
the most original and forceful Russian thinkers stood outside the academy.
Since then, both in Russia and in Western exile, a number of the most important
Russian philosophers including Berdyaev
and Lev Shestov 1866 8 have been professors. The nineteenth-century thinkers,
though educated, lacked advanced degrees. The only professor among them, Peter Lavrov 18230,
taught mathematics and science rather than philosophy during the 1850s. If we
compare Russian philosophy to G. philosophy of this period, with its galaxy
of professors Wolff, Kant, Fichte, Schelling, Hegel,
Dilthey the contrast is sharp. However,
if we compare Russian philosophy to English or
philosophy, the contrast fades. No professors of philosophy appear in
the line from Francis Bacon through Hobbes, Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Bentham, and
J. S. Mill, to Spencer. And in France Montaigne, Descartes, Pascal, Rousseau,
and Comte were all non-professors. True to their non-professional, even
“amateur” status, Russian philosophers until the late nineteenth century paid
little attention to the more technical disciplines: logic, epistemology,
philosophy of language, and philosophy of science. They focused instead on
philosophical anthropology, ethics, social and political philosophy, philosophy
of history, and philosophy of religion. In Russia, more than in any other
Western cultural tradition, speculation, fiction, and poetry have been linked.
On the one hand, major novelists such as Tolstoy and Dostoevsky, and major
poets such as Pasternak and Brodsky, have engaged in wide-ranging philosophical
reflection. On the other hand, philosophers such as Skovoroda, Alexei Khomyakov
180460, and Vladimir Solovyov 18530 were gifted poets, while thinkers such as
Herzen, Konstantin Leontyev 183, and the anti-Leninist Marxist Alexander
Bogdanov 18738 made their literary mark with novels, short stories, and
memoirs. Such Russian thinkers as Vasily Rozanov 18569 and Shestov, although
they wrote no belles lettres, were celebrated in literary circles for their
sparkling essayistic and aphoristic styles. Certain preoccupations of
nineteenth-century Russian thinkers
especially Pyotr Chaadaev 17941856 during the 1820s and 1830s, the
Slavophiles and Westernizers during the 1840s and 1850s, and the Populists
during the 1860s and 1870s might appear
to be distinctive but in fact were not. The controversial questions of Russia’s
relation to Western Europe and of Russell’s paradox Russian philosophy 805 805 Russia’s “special path” to modernity
have their counterparts in the reflections of thinkers in Spain “Spain and
Europe”, G.y the Sonderweg a term of
which the Russian osobyi put’ is a translation, and Poland “the Polish
Question”. The content of Russian philosophy may be characterized in general
terms as tending toward utopianism, maximalism, moralism, and soteriology. To
take the last point first: Hegelianism was received in Russia in the 1830s not
only as an allembracing philosophical system but also as a vehicle of secular
salvation. In the 1860s Darwinism was similarly received, as was Marxism in the
0s. Utopianism appears at the historical and sociopolitical level in two of
Solovyov’s characteristic doctrines: his early “free theocracy,” in which the
spiritual authority of the Roman pope was to be united with the secular
authority of the Russian tsar; and his later ecumenical project of reuniting
the Eastern Russian Orthodox and Western Roman Catholic churches in a single
“universal [vselenskaia] church” that would also incorporate the “Protestant
principle” of free philosophical and theological inquiry. Maximalism appears at
the individual and religious level in Shestov’s claim that God, for whom alone
“all things are possible,” can cause what has happened not to have happened and,
in particular, can restore irrecoverable human loss, such as that associated
with disease, deformity, madness, and death. Maximalism and moralism are united
at the cosmic and “scientific-technological” level in Nikolai Fyodorov’s 18293
insistence on the overriding moral obligation of all men “the sons” to join the
common cause of restoring life to “the fathers,” those who gave them life
rather than, as sanctioned by the “theory of progress,” pushing them,
figuratively if not literally, into the grave. Certain doctrinal emphases and
assumptions link Russian thinkers from widely separated points on the political
and ideological spectrum: 1 Russian philosophers were nearly unanimous in
dismissing the notorious CartesianHumean “problem of other minds” as a nonproblem.
Their convictions about human community and conciliarity sobornost’, whether
religious or secular, were too powerful to permit Russian thinkers to raise
serious doubts as to whether their moaning and bleeding neighbor was “really”
in pain. 2 Most Russian thinkers the
Westernizers were a partial exception
viewed key Western philosophical positions and formulations, from the
Socratic “know thyself” to the Cartesian cogito, as overly individualistic and
overly intellectualistic, as failing to take into account the wholeness of the
human person. 3 Both such anti-Marxists as Herzen with his “philosophy of the
act” and Fyodorov with his “projective” common task and the early Russian
Marxists were in agreement about the unacceptability of the “Western” dichotomy
between thought and action. But when they stressed the unity of theory and
practice, a key question remained: Who is to shape this unity? And what is its
form? The threadbare MarxistLeninist “philosophy” of the Stalin years paid lip
service to the freedom involved in forging such a unity. Stalin in fact imposed
crushing restraints upon both thought and action. Since 2, works by and about
the previously abused or neglected religious and speculative thinkers of
Russia’s past have been widely republished and eagerly discussed. This applies
to Fyodorov, Solovyov, Leontyev, Rozanov, Berdyaev, Shestov, and the Husserlian
Shpet, among others.
Ryle, Gilbert, English analytic philosopher known
especially for his contributions to the philosophy of mind and his attacks on
Cartesianism. His best-known work is the masterpiece The Concept of Mind 9, an
attack on what he calls “Cartesian dualism” and a defense of a type of logical
behaviorism. This dualism he dubs “the dogma of the Ghost in the Machine,” the Machine
being the body, which is physical and publicly observable, and the Ghost being
the mind conceived as a private or secret arena in which episodes of sense
perception, consciousness, and inner perception take place. A person, then, is
a combination of such a mind and a body, with the mind operating the body
through exercises of will called “volitions.” Ryle’s attack on this doctrine is
both sharply focused and multifarious. He finds that it rests on a category
mistake, namely, assimilating statements about mental processes to the same
category as statements about physical processes. This is a mistake in the logic
of mental statements and mental concepts and leads to the mistaken metaphysical
theory that a person is composed of two separate and distinct though somehow
related entities, a mind and a body. It is true that statements about the
physical are statements about things and their changes. But statements about
the mental are not, and in particular are not about a thing called “the mind.”
These two types of statements do not belong to the same category. To show this,
Ryle deploys a variety of arguments, including arguments alleging the
impossibility of causal relations between mind and body and arguments alleging
vicious infinite regresses. To develop his positive view on the nature of mind,
Ryle studies the uses and hence the logic of mental terms and finds that mental
statements tell us that the person performs observable actions in certain ways
and has a disposition to perform other observable actions in specifiable
circumstances. For example, to do something intelligently is to do something
physical in a certain way and to adjust one’s behavior to the circumstances,
not, as the dogma of the Ghost in the Machine would have it, to perform two
actions, one of which is a mental action of thinking that eventually causes a
separate physical action. Ryle buttresses this position with many acute and
subtle analyses of the uses of mental terms. Much of Ryle’s other work concerns
philosophical methodology, sustaining the thesis which is the backbone of The
Concept of Mind that philosophical problems and doctrines often arise from
conceptual confusion, i.e., from mistakes about the logic of language.
Important writings in this vein include the influential article “Systematically
Misleading Expressions” and the book Dilemmas 4. Ryle was also interested in
Grecian philosophy throughout his life, and his last major work, Plato’s
Progress, puts forward novel hypotheses about changes in Plato’s views, the
role of the Academy, the purposes and uses of Plato’s dialogues, and Plato’s
relations with the rulers of Syracuse.
Saadiah Gaon 882942, Jewish exegete, philosopher,
liturgist, grammarian, and lexicographer. Born in the Fayyum in Egypt, Saadiah
wrote his first Hebrew dictionary by age twenty. He removed to Tiberias,
probably fleeing the backlash of his polemic against the Karaite biblicist,
anti-Talmudic sect. There he mastered the inductive techniques of semantic
analysis pioneered by Muslim MuÅtazilites in defending their rationalistic
monotheism and voluntaristic theodicy. He learned philologically from the
Masoretes and liturgical poets, and philosophically from the
MuÅtazilite-influenced Jewish metaphysician Daud al-Muqammif of Raqqa in Iraq,
and Isaac Israeli of Qayrawan in Tunisia, a Neoplatonizing physician, with whom
the young philosopher attempted a correspondence. But his sense of system,
evidenced in his pioneering chronology, prayerbook, and scheme of tropes, and
nurtured by Arabic versions of Plato but seemingly not much Aristotle, allowed
him to outgrow and outshine his mentors. He came to prominence by successfully
defending the traditional Hebrew calendar, using astronomical, mathematical,
and rabbinic arguments. Called to Baghdad, he became Gaon Hebrew, ‘Eminence’ or
head of the ancient Talmudic academy of Pumpedita, then nearly defunct. His
commentaries on rabbinic property law and his letters to Jewish communities as
far away as Spain refurbished the authority of the academy, but a controversy
with the Exilarch, secular head of Mesopotamian Jewry, led to his deposition
and six years in limbo, deprived of his judicial authority. He delved into
scientific cosmology, tr. many biblical books into Arabic with philosophic
commentaries and thematic introductions, and around 933 completed The Book of
Critically Chosen Beliefs and Convictions, the first Jewish philosophical
summa. Unusual among medieval works for a lengthy epistemological introduction,
its ten Arabic treatises defend and define creation, monotheism, human
obligation and virtue, theodicy, natural retribution, resurrection, immortality
and recompense, Israel’s redemption, and the good life. Saadiah argues that no
single good suffices for human happiness; each in isolation is destructive. The
Torah prepares the optimal blend of the appetitive and erotic, procreative,
civilizational, ascetic, political, intellectual, pious, and tranquil.
Following al-Rhazi d. 925 or 932, Saadiah argues that since destruction always
overcomes organization in this world, sufferings will always outweigh
pleasures; therefore as in rabbinic and MuÅtazilite theodicy God must be
assumed to right the balances in the hereafter. Indeed, justice is the object
of creation not simply that the
righteous be rewarded but that all should earn their deserved requital: the
very light that is sown for the righteous is the fire that torments the wicked.
But if requital and even recompense must be earned, this life is much more than
an anteroom. Authenticity becomes a value in itself: the innocent are not told
directly that their sufferings are a trial, or their testing would be invalid.
Only by enduring their sufferings without interference can they demonstrate the
qualities that make them worthy of the highest reward. Movingly reconciled with
the Exilarch, Saadiah ended his life as Gaon. His voluntarism, naturalism, and
rationalism laid philosophical foundations for Maimonides, and his inductive
exegesis became a cornerstone of critical hermeneutics.
Saint Petersburg paradox, a puzzle about gambling that
motivated the distinction between expected return and expected utility. Daniel
Bernoulli published it in a St. Petersburg journal in 1738. It concerns a
gamble like this: it pays $2 if heads appears on the first toss of a coin, $4
if heads does not appear until the second toss, $8 if heads does not appear
until the third toss, and so on. The expected return from the gamble is ½2 ! ¼4
! 1 /88 ! . . . , or 1 ! 1 ! 1 ! ..., i.e., it is infinite. But no one would
pay much for the gamble. So it seems that expected returns do not govern
rational preferences. Bernoulli argued that expected utilities govern rational
preferences. He also held that the utility of wealth is proportional to the log
of the amount of wealth. Given his assumptions, the gamble has finite 808
S 808 expected utility, and should not
be preferred to large sums of money. However, a twentieth-century version of
the paradox, attributed to Karl Menger, reconstructs the gamble, putting utility
payoffs in place of monetary payoffs, so that the new gamble has infinite
expected utility. Since no one would trade much utility for the new gamble, it
also seems that expected utilities do not govern rational preferences. The
resolution of the paradox is under debate.
Saint-Simon, Comte de, title of Claude-Henri de Rouvroy
17601825, social reformer. An aristocrat
by birth, he initially joined the ranks of the enlightened and liberal
bourgeoisie. His Newtonian Letters to an Inhabitant of Geneva 1803 and
Introduction to Scientific Works of the Nineteenth Century 1808 championed
Condorcet’s vision of scientific and technological progress. With Auguste
Comte, he shared a positivistic philosophy of history: the triumph of science
over metaphysics. Written in wartime, The Reorganization of European Society
1814 urged the creation of a European parliamentary system to secure peace and
unity. Having moved from scientism to pacifism, Saint-Simon moved further to
industrialism. In 1817, under the influence of two theocratic thinkers, de
Maistre and Bonald, Saint-Simon turned away from classical economic liberalism
and repudiated laissez-faire capitalism. The Industrial System 1820 drafts the
program for a hierarchical state, a technocratic society, and a planned
economy. The industrial society of the future is based on the principles of
productivity and cooperation and led by a rational and efficient class, the
industrialists artists, scientists, and technicians. He argued that the
association of positivism with unselfishness, of techniques of rational
production with social solidarity and interdependency, would remedy the plight
of the poor. Industrialism prefigures socialism, and socialism paves the way
for the rule of the law of love, the eschatological age of The New Christianity
1825. This utopian treatise, which reveals Saint-Simon’s alternative to
reactionary Catholicism and Protestant individualism, became the Bible of the
Saint-Simonians, a sectarian school of utopian socialists.
Same -- Sameness -- Griceian – One of Grice’s favourite
essays ever was Wiggins’s “Sameness and substance” -- Griceian différance,
a coinage deployed by Derrida in De la
Grammatologie 7, where he defines it as “an economic concept designating the
production of differing/deferring.” Différance is polysemic, but its key
function is to name the prime condition for the functioning of all language and
thought: differing, the differentiation of signs from each other that allows us
to differentiate things from each other. Deferring is the process by which
signs refer to each other, thus constituting the self-reference essential to
language, without ever capturing the being or presence that is the transcendent
entity toward which it is aimed. Without the concepts or idealities generated
by the iteration of signs, we could never identify a dog as a dog, could not
perceive a dog or any other thing as such. Perception presupposes language,
which, in turn, presupposes the ideality generated by the repetition of signs.
Thus there can be no perceptual origin for language; language depends upon an
“original repetition,” a deliberate oxymoron that Derrida employs to signal the
impossibility of conceiving an origin of language from within the linguistic
framework in which we find ourselves. Différance is the condition for language,
and language is the condition for experience: whatever meaning we may find in
the world is attributed to the differing/ deferring play of signifiers. The
notion of différance and the correlative thesis that meaning is
language-dependent have been appropriated by radical thinkers in the attempt to
demonstrate that political inequalities are grounded in nothing other than the
conventions of sign systems governing differing cultures.
Sanches, F. c.15511623, Portuguese born philosopher and
physician. Raised in southern France, he took his medical degree at the of Montpellier. After a decade of medical
practice he was professor of philosophy at the
of Toulouse and later professor of medicine there. His most important
work, Quod nihil sciturThat Nothing Is Known, 1581, is a classic of skeptical
argumentation. Written at the same time that his cousin, Montaigne, wrote the
“Apology for Raimund Sebond,” it devastatingly criticized the Aristotelian
theory of knowledge. He began by declaring that he did not even know if he knew
nothing. Then he examined the Aristotelian view that science consists of
certain knowledge gained by demonstrations from true definitions. First of all,
we do not possess such definitions, since all our definitions are just
arbitrary names of things. The Aristotelian theory of demonstration is useless,
since in syllogistic reasoning the conclusion has to be part of the evidence
for the premises. E.g., how can one know that all men are mortal unless one
knows that Socrates is mortal? Also, anything can be proven by syllogistic
reasoning if one chooses the right premises. This does not produce real
knowledge. Further we cannot know anything through its causes, since one would
have to know the causes of the causes, and the causes of these, ad infinitum.
Sanches also attacked the Platonic theory of knowledge, since mathematical
knowledge is about ideal rather than real objects. Mathematics is only
hypothetical. Its relevance to experience is not known. True science would
consist of perfect knowledge of a thing. Each particular would be understood in
and by itself. Such knowledge can be attained only by God. We cannot study
objects one by one, since they are all interrelated and interconnected. Our
faculties are also not reliable enough. Hence genuine knowledge cannot be
attained by humans. What we can do, using “scientific method” a term first used
by Sanches, is gather careful empirical information and make cautious judgments
about it. His views were well known in the seventeenth century, and may have
inspired the “mitigated skepticism” of Gassendi and others.
sanction, anything whose function is to penalize or
reward. It is useful to distinguish between social sanctions, legal sanctions,
internal sanctions, and religious sanctions. Social sanctions are extralegal
pressures exerted upon the agent by others. For example, others might distrust
us, ostracize us, or even physically attack us, if we behave in certain ways.
Legal sanctions include corporal punishment, imprisonment, fines, withdrawal of
the legal rights to run a business or to leave the area, and other penalties.
Internal sanctions may include not only guilt feelings but also the sympathetic
pleasures of helping others or the gratified conscience of doing right. Divine
sanctions, if there are any, are rewards or punishments given to us by a god
while we are alive or after we die. There are important philosophical questions
concerning sanctions. Should law be defined as the rules the breaking of which
elicits punishment by the state? Could there be a moral duty to behave in a
given way if there were no social sanctions concerning such behavior? If not,
then a conventionalist account of moral duty seems unavoidable. And, to what
extent does the combined effect of external and internal sanctions make
rational egoism or prudence or self-interest coincide with morality?
Santayana, G., philosopher and writer. Born in Spain,
he arrived in the United States as a child, received his education at Harvard,
and rose to professor of philosophy there. He first came to prominence for his
view, developed in The Sense of Beauty 6, that beauty is objectified pleasure.
His The Life of Reason 5 vols., 5, a celebrated expression of his naturalistic
vision, traces human creativity in ordinary life, society, art, religion, and
science. He denied that his philosophy ever changed, but the mature expression
of his thought, in Skepticism and Animal Faith 3 and The Realms of Being 4
vols., 740, is deliberately ontological and lacks the phenomenological emphasis
of the earlier work. Human beings, according to Santayana, are animals in a
material world contingent to the core. Reflection must take as its primary
datum human action aimed at eating and fleeing. The philosophy of animal faith
consists of disentangling the beliefs tacit in such actions and yields a
realism concerning both the objects of immediate consciousness and the objects
of belief. Knowledge is true belief rendered in symbolic terms. As symbolism,
it constitutes the hauntingly beautiful worlds of the senses, poetry, and
religion; as knowledge, it guides and is tested by successful action. Santayana
had been taught by William James, and his insistence on the primacy of action
suggests a close similarity to the views of Dewey. He is, nevertheless, not a
pragmatist in any ordinary sense: he views nature as the fully formed arena of
human activity and experience as a flow of isolated, private sentience in this
alien world. His deepest sympathy is with Aristotle, though he agrees with
Plato about the mind-independent existence of Forms and with Schopenhauer about
the dimness of human prospects. His mature four-realm ontology turns on the
distinction between essence and matter. Essences are forms of definiteness.
They are infinite in number and encompass everything possible. Their eternity
makes them causally inefficacious: as possibilities, they cannot accomplish
their own actualization. Matter, a surd and formless force, generates the
physical universe by selecting essences for embodiment. Truth is the realm of
being created by the intersection of matter and form: it is the eternal record
of essences that have been, are being, and will be given actuality in the
history of the world. Spirit or consciousness cannot be reduced to the motions
of the physical organism that give rise to it. It is constituted by a sequence
of acts or intuitions whose objects are essences but whose time-spanning,
synthetic nature renders them impotent. Organic selectivity is the source of
values. Accordingly, the good of each organism is a function of its nature.
Santayana simply accepts the fact that some of these goods are incommensurable
and the tragic reality that they may be incompatible, as well. Under favorable
circumstances, a life of reason or of maximal harmonized satisfactions is possible
for a while. The finest achievement of human beings, however, is the spiritual
life in which we overcome animal partiality and thus all valuation in order to
enjoy the intuition of eternal essences. Santayana identifies such spirituality
with the best that religion and sound philosophy can offer. It does not help us
escape finitude and death, but enables us in this short life to transcend care
and to intuit the eternal. Santayana’s exquisite vision has gained him many
admirers but few followers. His system is a self-consistent and sophisticated
synthesis of elements, such as materialism and Platonism, that have hitherto
been thought impossible to reconcile. His masterful writing makes his books
instructive and pleasurable, even if many of his characteristic views engender
resistance among philosophers.
Sapir-Whorf hypothesis, broadly, the claim that one’s
perception, thought, and behavior are influenced by one’s language. The
hypothesis was named after Benjamin Lee Whorf 7 1 and his teacher Edward Sapir
4 9. We may discern different versions of this claim by distinguishing degrees
of linguistic influence, the highest of which is complete and unalterable
determination of the fundamental structures of perception, thought, and
behavior. In the most radical form, the hypothesis says that one’s reality is
constructed by one’s language and that differently structured languages give
rise to different realities, which are incommensurable.
Sartre, J.-P. philosopher and writer, the leading
advocate of existentialism during the years following World War II. The heart
of his philosophy was the precious notion of freedom and its concomitant sense
of personal responsibility. He insisted, in an interview a few years before his
death, that he never ceased to believe that “in the end one is always
responsible for what is made of one,” only a slight revision of his earlier,
bolder slogan, “man makes himself.” To be sure, as a student of Hegel, Marx,
Husserl, and Heidegger and because of
his own physical frailty and the tragedies of the war Sartre had to be well aware of the many
constraints and obstacles to human freedom, but as a Cartesian, he never
deviated from Descartes’s classical portrait of human consciousness as free and
distinct from the physical universe it inhabits. One is never free of one’s
“situation,” Sartre tells us, though one is always free to deny “negate” that
situation and to try to change it. To be human, to be conscious, is to be free
to imagine, free to choose, and responsible for one’s lot in life. As a
student, Sartre was fascinated by Husserl’s new philosophical method,
phenomenology. His first essays were direct responses to Husserl and
applications of the phenomenological method. His essay on The Imagination in 6
established the groundwork for much of what was to follow: the celebration of
our remarkable freedom to imagine the world other than it is and following Kant
the way that this ability informs all of our experience. In The Transcendence
of the Ego 7 he reconsidered Husserl’s central idea of a “phenomenological
reduction” the idea of examining the essential structures of consciousness as
such and argued following Heidegger that one cannot examine consciousness
without at the same time recognizing the reality of actual objects in the world.
In other words, there can be no such “reduction.” In his novel Nausea 8, Sartre
made this point in a protracted example: his bored and often nauseated narrator
confronts a gnarled chestnut tree in the park and recognizes with a visceral
shock that its presence is simply given and utterly irreducible. In The
Transcendence of the Ego Sartre also reconsiders the notion of the self, which
Husserl and so many earlier philosophers had identified with consciousness. But
the self, Sartre argues, is not “in” consciousness, much less identical to it.
The self is out there “in the world, like the self of another.” In other words,
the self is an ongoing project in the world with other people; it is not simply
self-awareness or self-consciousness as such “I think, therefore I am”. This
separation of self and consciousness and the rejection of the self as simply
self-consciousness provide the framework for Sartre’s greatest philosophical
treatise, L’être et le néant Being and Nothingness, 3. Its structure is
unabashedly Cartesian, consciousness “being-for-itself” or pour soi on the one
side, the existence of mere things “being-in-itself” or en soi on the other.
The phraseology comes from Hegel. But Sartre does not fall into the Cartesian
trap of designating these two types of being as separate “substances.” Instead,
Sartre describes consciousness as “nothing’
“not a thing” but an activity, “a wind blowing from nowhere toward the
world.” Sartre often resorts to visceral metaphors when developing this theme
e.g., “a worm coiled in the heart of being”, but much of what he is arguing is
familiar to philosophical readers in the more metaphor-free work of Kant, who
also warned against the follies “paralogisms” of understanding consciousness as
itself a possible object of consciousness rather than as the activity of
constituting the objects of consciousness. As the lens of a camera can never
see itself and in a mirror only sees a
reflection of itself consciousness can
never view itself as consciousness and is only aware of itself “for itself”
through its experience of objects. Ontologically, one might think of
“nothingness” as “no-thing-ness,” a much less outrageous suggestion than those
that would make it an odd sort of a thing. It is through the nothingness of
consciousness and its activities that negation comes into the world, our
ability to imagine the world other than it is and the inescapable necessity of
imagining ourselves other than we seem to be. And because consciousness is
nothingness, it is not subject to the rules of causality. Central to the
argument of L’être et le néant and Sartre’s insistence on the primacy of human
freedom is his insistence that consciousness cannot be understood in causal
terms. It is always self-determining and, as such, “it always is what it is
not, and is not what it is” a playful
paradox that refers to the fact that we are always in the process of choosing.
Consciousness is “nothing,” but the self is always on its way to being
something. Throughout our lives we accumulate a body of facts that are true of
us our “facticity” but during our lives we remain free to
envision new possibilities, to reform ourselves and to reinterpret our
facticity in the light of new projects and ambitions our “transcendence.” This indeterminacy means
that we can never be anything, and when we try to establish ourselves as
something particular whether a social
role policeman, waiter or a certain character shy, intellectual, cowardly we are in “bad faith.” Bad faith is
erroneously viewing ourselves as something fixed and settled Sartre utterly
rejects Freud and his theory of the unconscious determination of our
personalities and behavior, but it is also bad faith to view oneself as a being
of infinite possibilities and ignore the always restrictive facts and circumstances
within which all choices must be made. On the one hand, we are always trying to
define ourselves; on the other hand we are always free to break away from what
we are, and always responsible for what we have made of ourselves. But there is
no easy resolution or “balance” between facticity and freedom, rather a kind of
dialectic or tension. The result is our frustrated desire to be God, to be both
in-itself and for-itself. But this is not so much blasphemy as an expression of
despair, a form of ontological original sin, the impossibility of being both
free and what we want to be. Life for Sartre is yet more complicated. There is
a third basic ontological category, on a par with the being-in-itself and
being-for-itself and not derivative of them. He calls it “being-for-others.” To
say that it is not derivative is to insist that our knowledge of others is not
inferred, e.g. by some argument by analogy, from the behavior of others, and we
ourselves are not wholly constituted by our self-determinations and the facts
about us. Sartre gives us a brutal but familiar everyday example of our
experience of being-for-others in what he calls “the look” le regard. Someone
catches us “in the act” of doing something humiliating, and we find ourselves
defining ourselves probably also resisting that definition in their terms. In
his Saint Genet 3, Sartre describes such a conversion of the ten-year-old Jean
Genet into a thief. So, too, we tend to “catch” one another in the judgments we
make and define one another in terms that are often unflattering. But these
judgments become an essential and ineluctible ingredient in our sense of
ourselves, and they too lead to conflicts indeed, conflicts so basic and so
frustrating that in his play Huis clos No Exit, 3 Sartre has one of his
characters utter the famous line, “Hell is other people.” In his later works,
notably his Critique of Dialectical Reason 859, Sartre turned increasingly to
politics and, in particular, toward a defense of Marxism on existentialist
principles. This entailed rejecting materialist determinism, but it also
required a new sense of solidarity or what Sartre had wistfully called,
following Heidegger, Mitsein or “being with others”. Thus in his later work he
struggled to find a way of overcoming the conflict and insularity or the rather
“bourgeois” consciousness he had described in Being and Nothingness. Not
surprisingly given his constant political activities he found it in
revolutionary engagement. Consonant with his rejection of bourgeois selfhood,
Sartre turned down the 4 Nobel prize for literature.
Satisfactoriness-condition, a state of affairs or “way
things are,” most commonly referred to in relation to something that implies or
is implied by it. Let p, q, and r be schematic letters for declarative sentences;
and let P, Q, and R be corresponding nominalizations; e.g., if p is ‘snow is
white’, then P would be ‘snow’s being white’. P can be a necessary or
sufficient condition of Q in any of several senses. In the weakest sense P is a
sufficient condition of Q iff if and only if: if p then q or if P is actual
then Q is actual where the conditional
is to be read as “material,” as amounting merely to not-p & not-q. At the
same time Q is a necessary condition of P iff: if not-q then not-p. It follows
that P is a sufficient condition of Q iff Q is a necessary condition of P.
Stronger senses of sufficiency and of necessity are definable, in terms of this
basic sense, as follows: P is nomologically sufficient necessary for Q iff it
follows from the laws of nature, but not without them, that if p then q that if
q then p. P is alethically or metaphysically sufficient necessary for Q iff it
is alethically or metaphysically necessary that if p then q that if q then p.
However, it is perhaps most common of all to interpret conditions in terms of
subjunctive conditionals, in such a way that P is a sufficient condition of Q
iff P would not occur unless Q occurred, or: if P should occur, Q would; and P
is a necessary condition of Q iff Q would not occur unless P occurred, or: if Q
should occur, P would. -- satisfaction,
an auxiliary semantic notion introduced by Tarski in order to give a recursive
definition of truth for languages containing quantifiers. Intuitively, the
satisfaction relation holds between formulas containing free variables such as
‘Buildingx & Tallx’ and objects or sequences of objects such as the Empire
State Building if and only if the formula “holds of” or “applies to” the
objects. Thus, ‘Buildingx & Tallx’, is satisfied by all and only tall
buildings, and ‘-Tallx1 & Tallerx1, x2’ is satisfied by any pair of objects
in which the first object corresponding to ‘x1’ is not tall, but nonetheless
taller than the second corresponding to ‘x2’. Satisfaction is needed when
defining truth for languages with sentences built from formulas containing free
variables, because the notions of truth and falsity do not apply to these
“open” formulas. Thus, we cannot characterize the truth of the sentences ‘Dx
Buildingx & Tallx’ ‘Some building is tall’ in terms of the truth or falsity
of the open formula ‘Buildingx & Tallx’, since the latter is neither true
nor false. But note that the sentence is true if and only if the formula is
satisfied by some object. Since we can give a recursive definition of the
notion of satisfaction for possibly open formulas, this enables us to use this
auxiliary notion in defining truth. -- satisfiable,
having a common model, a structure in which all the sentences in the set are
true; said of a set of sentences. In modern logic, satisfiability is the
semantic analogue of the syntactic, proof-theoretic notion of consistency, the
unprovability of any explicit contradiction. The completeness theorem for
first-order logic, that all valid sentences are provable, can be formulated in
terms of satisfiability: syntactic consistency implies satisfiability. This
theorem does not necessarily hold for extensions of first-order logic. For any
sound proof system for secondorder logic there will be an unsatisfiable set of
sentences without there being a formal derivation of a contradiction from the
set. This follows from Gödel’s incompleteness theorem. One of the central
results of model theory for first-order logic concerns satisfiability: the
compactness theorem, due to Gödel in 6, says that if every finite subset of a
set of sentences is satisfiable the set itself is satisfiable. It follows
immediately from his completeness theorem for first-order logic, and gives a
powerful method to prove the consistency of a set of sentences.
satisfice, to choose or do the good enough rather than
the most or the best. ‘Satisfice’, an obsolete variant of ‘satisfy’, has been
adopted by economist Herbert Simon and others to designate nonoptimizing choice
or action. According to some economists, limitations of time or information may
make it impossible or inadvisable for an individual, firm, or state body to
attempt to maximize pleasure, profits, market share, revenues, or some other
desired result, and satisficing with respect to such results is then said to be
rational, albeit less than ideally rational. Although many orthodox economists
think that choice can and always should be conceived in maximizing or
optimizing terms, satisficing models have been proposed in economics,
evolutionary biology, and philosophy. Biologists have sometimes conceived
evolutionary change as largely consisting of “good enough” or satisficing
adaptations to environmental pressures rather than as proceeding through
optimal adjustments to such pressures, but in philosophy, the most frequent
recent use of the idea of satisficing has been in ethics and rational choice
theory. Economists typically regard satisficing as acceptable only where there
are unwanted constraints on decision making; but it is also possible to see
satisficing as entirely acceptable in itself, and in the field of ethics, it
has recently been argued that there may be nothing remiss about moral
satisficing, e.g., giving a good amount to charity, but less than one could
give. It is possible to formulate satisficing forms of utilitarianism on which
actions are morally right even if they contribute merely positively and/or in
some large way, rather than maximally, to overall net human happiness.
Bentham’s original formulation of the principle of utility and Popper’s
negative utilitarianism are both examples of satisficing utilitarianism in this
sense and it should be noted that
satisficing utilitarianism has the putative advantage over optimizing forms of
allowing for supererogatory degrees of moral excellence. Moreover, any moral
view that treats moral satisficing as permissible makes room for moral
supererogation in cases where one optimally goes beyond the merely acceptable.
But since moral satisficing is less than optimal moral behavior, but may be
more meritorious than certain behavior that in the same circumstances would be
merely permissible, some moral satisficing may actually count as
supererogatory. In recent work on rational individual choice, some philosophers
have argued that satisficing may often be acceptable in itself, rather than
merely second-best. Even Simon allows that an entrepreneur may simply seek a
satisfactory return on investment or share of the market, rather than a maximum
under one of these headings. But a number of philosophers have made the further
claim that we may sometimes, without irrationality, turn down the readily
available better in the light of the goodness and sufficiency of what we
already have or are enjoying. Independently of the costs of taking a second
dessert, a person may be entirely satisfied with what she has eaten and, though
willing to admit she would enjoy that extra dessert, turn it down, saying “I’m
just fine as I am.” Whether such examples really involve an acceptable
rejection of the momentarily better for the good enough has been disputed.
However, some philosophers have gone on to say, even more strongly, that
satisficing can sometimes be rationally required and optimizing rationally
unacceptable. To keep on seeking pleasure from food or sex without ever being
thoroughly satisfied with what one has enjoyed can seem compulsive and as such
less than rational. If one is truly rational about such goods, one isn’t
insatiable: at some point one has had enough and doesn’t want more, even though
one could obtain further pleasure. The idea that satisficing is sometimes a
requirement of practical reason is reminiscent of Aristotle’s view that
moderation is inherently reasonable
rather than just a necessary means to later enjoyments and the avoidance
of later pain or illness, which is the way the Epicureans conceived moderation.
But perhaps the greatest advocate of satisficing is Plato, who argues in the
Philebus that there must be measure or limit to our desire for pleasure in
order for pleasure to count as a good thing for us. Insatiably to seek and
obtain pleasure from a given source is to gain nothing good from it. And
according to such a view, satisficing moderation is a necessary precondition of
human good and flourishing, rather than merely being a rational restraint on
the accumulation of independently conceived personal good or well-being.
Saussure, Ferdinand de, founder of structuralism. His
work in semiotics is a major influence on the later development of structuralist philosophy, as well as
structural anthropology, structuralist literary criticism, and modern
semiology. He pursued studies in linguistics largely under Georg Curtius at
the of Leipzig, along with such future
Junggrammatiker neogrammarians as Leskien and Brugmann. Following the publication
of his important Mémoire sur le système primitif des voyelles dans les langues
indo-européenes 1879, Saussure left for Paris, where he associated himself with
the Société Linguistique and taught comparative grammar. In 1, he returned to
Switzerland to teach Sanskrit, comparative grammar, and general linguistics at
the of Geneva. His major work, the
Course in General Linguistics 6, was assembled from students’ notes and his
original lecture outlines after his death. The Course in General Linguistics argued
against the prevalent historical and comparative philological approaches to
language by advancing what Saussure termed a scientific model for linguistics,
one borrowed in part from Durkheim. Such a model would take the “social fact”
of language la langue as its object, and distinguish this from the variety of
individual speech events la parole, as well as from the collectivity of speech
events and grammatical rules that form the general historical body of language
as such le langage. Thus, by separating out the unique and accidental elements
of practiced speech, Saussure distinguished language la langue as the objective
set of linguistic elements and rules that, taken as a system, governs the
language use specific to a given community. It was the systematic coherency and
generality of language, so conceived, that inclined Saussure to approach
linguistics principally in terms of its static or synchronic dimension, rather
than its historical or diachronic dimension. For Saussure, the system of
language is a “treasury” or “depository” of signs, and the basic unit of the
linguistic sign is itself two-sided, having both a phonemic component “the
signifier” and a semantic component “the signified”. He terms the former the
“acoustical” or “sound” image which may,
in turn, be represented graphically, in writing
and the latter the “concept” or “meaning.” Saussure construes the
signifier to be a representation of linguistic sounds in the imagination or
memory, i.e., a “psychological phenomenon,” one that corresponds to a
specifiable range of material phonetic sounds. Its distinctive property
consists in its being readily differentiated from other signifiers in the
particular language. It is the function of each signifier, as a distinct
entity, to convey a particular meaning
or “signified” concept and this
is fixed purely by conventional association. While the relation between the
signifier and signified results in what Saussure terms the “positive” fact of
the sign, the sign ultimately derives its linguistic value its precise
descriptive determination from its position in the system of language as a
whole, i.e., within the paradigmatic and syntagmatic relations that
structurally and functionally differentiate it. Signifiers are differentially
identified; signifiers are arbitrarily associated with their respective
signified concepts; and signs assume the determination they do only through
their configuration within the system of language as a whole: these facts
enabled Saussure to claim that language is largely to be understood as a closed
formal system of differences, and that the study of language would be
principally governed by its autonomous structural determinations. So conceived,
linguistics would be but a part of the study of social sign systems in general,
namely, the broader science of what Saussure termed semiology. Saussure’s
insights would be taken up by the subsequent Geneva, Prague, and Copenhagen
schools of linguistics and by the Russian formalists, and would be further
developed by the structuralists in France and elsewhere, as well as by recent
semiological approaches to literary criticism, social anthropology, and
psychoanalysis.
scepticism: For some reason, Grice was irritated by
Wood’s sobriquet of Russell as a “passionate sceptic”: ‘an oxymoron.” The most
specific essay by Grice on this is an essay he kept after many years, that he
delivered back in the day at Oxford, entitled, “Scepticism and common sense.”
Both were traditional topics at Oxford at the time. Typically, as in the
Oxonian manner, he chose two authors, New-World’s Malcolm’s treatment of
Old-World Moore, and brings in Austin’s ‘ordinary-language’ into the bargain.
He also brings in his own obsession with what an emissor communicates. In this
case, the “p” is the philosopher’s sceptical proposition, such as “That pillar box
is red.” Grice thinks ‘dogmatic’ is the opposite of ‘sceptic,’ and he is right!
Liddell and Scott have “δόγμα,” from “δοκέω,” and which they render as “that
which seems to one, opinion or belief;” Pl.R.538c; “δ. πόλεως κοινόν;” esp. of
philosophical doctrines, Epicur.Nat.14.7; “notion,” Pl.Tht.158d; “decision,
judgement,” Pl. Lg.926d; (pl.); public decree,
ordinance, esp. of Roman Senatus-consulta,
“δ. συγκλήτου” “δ. τῆς βουλῆς” So note
that there is nothing ‘dogmatic’ about ‘dogma,’ as it derives from ‘dokeo,’ and
is rendered as ‘that which seems to one.’ So the keyword should be later
Grecian, and in the adjectival ‘dogmatic.’ Liddell and Scott have “δογματικός,”
which they render as “of or for doctrines, didactic, [διάλογοι]
Quint.Inst.2.15.26, and “of persons, δ. ἰατροί,” “physicians who go by general
principles,” opp. “ἐμπειρικοί and μεθοδικοί,” Dsc.Ther.Praef., Gal.1.65; in
Philosophy, S.E.M.7.1, D.L.9.70, etc.; “δ. ὑπολήψεις” Id.9.83; “δ. φιλοσοφία”
S.E. P.1.4. Adv. “-κῶς” D.L.9.74, S.E.P.1.197: Comp. “-κώτερον” Id.M. 6.4. Why
is Grice interested in scepticism. His initial concern, the one that Austin
would authorize, relates to ‘ordinary language.’ What if ‘ordinary language’
embraces scepticism? What if it doesn’t? Strawso notes that the world of
ordinary language is a world of things, causes, and stuff. None of the good
stuff for the sceptic. what is Grice’s answer to the sceptic’s implicaturum?
The sceptic’s implicaturum is a topic that always fascinated Girce. While Grice
groups two essays as dealing with one single theme, strictly, only this or that
philosopher’s paradox (not all) may count as sceptical. This or that
philosopher’s paradox may well not be sceptical at all but rather dogmatic. In
fact, Grice defines philosophers paradox as anything repugnant to common sense,
shocking, or extravagant ‒ to Malcolms ears, that is! While it is,
strictly, slightly odd to quote this as a given date just because, by a stroke
of the pen, Grice writes that date in the Harvard volume, we will follow
his charming practice. This is vintage Grice. Grice always takes the
sceptics challenge seriously, as any serious philosopher should. Grices
takes both the sceptics explicatum and the scepticss implicaturum as
self-defeating, as a very affront to our idea of rationality, conversational or
other. V: Conversations with a sceptic: Can he be slightly more conversational
helpful? Hume’ sceptical attack is partial, and targeted only towards
practical reason, though. Yet, for Grice, reason is one. You cannot
really attack practical or buletic reason without attacking theoretical or
doxastic reason. There is such thing as a general rational acceptance, to use Grice’s
term, that the sceptic is getting at. Grice likes to play with the idea that
ultimately every syllogism is buletic or practical. If, say, a syllogism by
Eddington looks doxastic, that is because Eddington cares to omit the practical
tail, as Grice puts it. And Eddington is not even a philosopher, they say.
Grice is here concerned with a Cantabrigian topic popularised by
Moore. As Grice recollects, Some like Witters, but
Moore’s my man. Unlike Cambridge analysts such as Moore, Grice sees
himself as a linguistic-turn Oxonian analyst. So it is only natural that Grice
would connect time-honoured scepticism of Pyrrhos vintage, and common sense
with ordinary language, so mis-called, the elephant in Grices room. Lewis
and Short have “σκέψις,” f. σκέπτομαι, which they render as “viewing,
perception by the senses, ἡ διὰ τῶν ὀμμάτων ςκέψις, Pl. Phd. 83a;
observation of auguries; also as examination, speculation, consideration, τὸ
εὕρημα πολλῆς σκέψιος; βραχείας ςκέψις; ϝέμειν ςκέψις take thought of a
thing; ἐνθεὶς τῇ τέχνῃ ςκέψις; ςκέψις ποιεῖσθαι; ςκέψις προβέβληκας;
ςκέψις λόγων; ςκέψις περί τινος inquiry into, speculation on a thing;
περί τι Id. Lg. 636d;ἐπὶ σκέψιν τινὸς ἐλθεῖν; speculation, inquiry,ταῦτα
ἐξωτερικωτέρας ἐστὶ σκέψεως; ἔξω τῆς νῦν ςκέψεως; οὐκ οἰκεῖα τῆς παρούσης
ςκέψις; also hesitation, doubt, esp. of the Sceptic or Pyrthonic philosophers,
AP 7. 576 (Jul.); the Sceptic philosophy, S. E. P. 1.5; οἱ ἀπὸ τῆς
ςκέψεως, the Sceptics, ib. 229. in politics, resolution, decree, συνεδρίον
Hdn. 4.3.9, cf. Poll. 6.178. If scepticism attacks common sense and fails,
Grice seems to be implicating, that ordinary language philosophy is a good
antidote to scepticism. Since what language other than ordinary language does
common sense speak? Well, strictly, common sense doesnt speak. The man in the
street does. Grice addresses this topic in a Mooreian way in a later essay,
also repr. in Studies, Moore and philosophers paradoxes, repr. in Studies.
As with his earlier Common sense and scepticism, Grice tackles Moores and
Malcolms claim that ordinary language, so-called, solves a few of philosophers
paradoxes. Philosopher is Grices witty way to generalise over your
common-or-garden, any, philosopher, especially of the type he found eccentric,
the sceptic included. Grice finds this or that problem in this overarching
Cantabrigian manoeuvre, as over-simplifying a pretty convoluted
terrain. While he cherishes Austins Some like Witters, but Moores MY man!
Grice finds Moore too Cantabrigian to his taste. While an Oxonian thoroughbred,
Grice is a bit like Austin, Some like Witters, but Moores my man, with this or
that caveat. Again, as with his treatment of Descartes or Locke, Grice is
hardly interested in finding out what Moore really means. He is a philosopher,
not a historian of philosophy, and he knows it. While Grice agrees with Austins
implicaturum that Moore goes well above Witters, if that is the expression
(even if some like him), we should find the Oxonian equivalent to Moore. Grice
would not Names Ryle, since he sees him, and his followers, almost every day.
There is something apostolic about Moore that Grice enjoys, which is just as
well, seeing that Moore is one of the twelve. Grice found it amusing that
the members of The Conversazione Society would still be nickNamesd apostles
when their number exceeded the initial 12. Grice spends some time exploring
what Malcolm, a follower of Witters, which does not help, as it were, has to
say about Moore in connection with that particularly Oxonian turn of phrase,
such as ordinary language is. For Malcolms Moore, a paradox by philosopher
[sic], including the sceptic, arises when philosopher [sic], including the
sceptic, fails to abide by the dictates of ordinary language. It might merit
some exploration if Moore’s defence of common sense is against: the sceptic may
be one, but also the idealist. Moore the realist, armed with ordinary language
attacks the idealists claim. The idealist is sceptical of the realists claim.
But empiricist idealism (Bradley) has at Oxford as good pedigree as empiricist
realism (Cook Wilson). Malcolm’s simplifications infuriate Grice, and ordinary
language has little to offer in the defense of common sense realism against
sceptical empiricist idealism. Surely the ordinary man says ridiculous, or
silly, as Russell prefers, things, such as Smith is lucky, Departed spirits
walk along this road on their way to Paradise, I know there are infinite stars,
and I wish I were Napoleon, or I wish that I had
been Napoleon, which does not mean that the utterer wishes that
he were like Napoleon, but that he wishes that he had lived
not in the his century but in the XVIIIth century. Grice is being specific
about this. It is true that an ordinary use of language, as Malcolm
suggests, cannot be self-contradictory unless the ordinary use of language is
defined by stipulation as not self-contradictory, in which case an appeal to
ordinary language becomes useless against this or that paradox by Philosopher.
I wish that I had been Napoleon seems to involve nothing but an ordinary use of
language by any standard but that of freedom from absurdity. I wish
that I had been Napoleon is not, as far as Grice can see, philosophical, but
something which may have been said and meant by numbers of ordinary
people. Yet, I wish that I had been Napoleon is open to the suspicion of
self-contradictoriness, absurdity, or some other kind of
meaninglessness. And in this context suspicion is all Grice needs. By
uttering I wish that I had been Napoleon U hardly means the same as he
would if he uttered I wish I were like Napoleon. I wish that I had been
Napoleon is suspiciously self-contradictory, absurd, or meaningless, if, as
uttered by an utterer in a century other than the XVIIIth century, say, the
utterer is understood as expressing the proposition that the utterer wishes
that he had lived in the XVIIIth century, and not in his century, in which case
he-1 wishes that he had not been him-1? But blame it on the
buletic. That Moore himself is not too happy with Malcolms criticism can
be witnessed by a cursory glimpse at hi reply to Malcolm. Grice is totally
against this view that Malcolm ascribes to Moore as a view that is too broad to
even claim to be true. Grices implicaturum is that Malcolm is appealing to
Oxonian turns of phrase, such as ordinary language, but not taking proper
Oxonian care in clarifying the nuances and stuff in dealing with, admittedly, a
non-Oxonian philosopher such as Moore. When dealing with Moore, Grice is not
necessarily concerned with scepticism. Time is unreal, e.g. is hardly a sceptic
utterance. Yet Grice lists it as one of Philosophers paradoxes. So, there are
various to consider here. Grice would start with common sense. That is what he
does when he reprints this essay in WOW, with his attending note in both the
preface and the Retrospective epilogue on how he organizes the themes and
strands. Common sense is one keyword there, with its attending realism.
Scepticism is another, with its attending empiricist idealism. It is intriguing
that in the first two essays opening Grices explorations in semantics and
metaphysics it seems its Malcolm, rather than the dryer Moore, who interests
Grice most. While he would provide exegeses of this or that dictum by Moore,
and indeed, Moore’s response to Malcolm, Grice seems to be more concerned with
applications of his own views. Notably in Philosophers paradoxes. The fatal
objection Grice finds for the paradox propounder (not necessarily a sceptic,
although a sceptic may be one of the paradox propounders) significantly rests
on Grices reductive analysis of meaning that
as ascribed to this or that utterer U. Grice elaborates on circumstances
that hell later take up in the Retrospective epilogue. I find myself not
understanding what I mean is dubiously acceptable. If meaning, Grice claims, is
about an utterer U intending to get his addressee A to believe that U ψ-s that
p, U must think there is a good chance that A will recognise what he is
supposed to believe, by, perhaps, being aware of the Us practice or by a supplementary
explanation which might come from U. In which case, U should not be meaning
what Malcolm claims U might mean. No utterer should intend his addressee to
believe what is conceptually impossible, or incoherent, or blatantly false
(Charles Is decapitation willed Charles Is death.), unless you are Queen in
Through the Looking Glass. I believe five impossible things before breakfast,
and I hope youll soon get the proper training to follow suit. Cf. Tertulian,
Credo, quia absurdum est. Admittedly, Grice edits the Philosophers paradoxes
essay. It is only Grices final objection which is repr. in WOW, even if he
provides a good detailed summary of the previous sections. Grice appeals to
Moore on later occasions. In Causal theory, Grice lists, as a third philosophical
mistake, the opinion by Malcolm that Moore did not know how to use knowin a
sentence. Grice brings up the same example again in Prolegomena. The use of
factive know of Moore may well be a misuse. While at Madison, Wisconsin, Moore
lectures at a hall eccentrically-built with indirect lighting simulating sun
rays, Moore infamously utters, I know that there is a window behind that
curtain, when there is not. But it is not the factiveness Grice is aiming at,
but the otiosity Malcolm misdescribes in the true, if baffling, I know that I
have two hands. In Retrospective epilogue, Grice uses M to abbreviate Moore’s
fairy godmother – along with G (Grice), A (Austin), R (Ryle) and Q (Quine)! One
simple way to approach Grices quandary with Malcolm’s quandary with Moore is
then to focus on know. How can Malcolm claim that Moore is guilty of misusing
know? The most extensive exploration by Grice on know is in Grices third James
lecture (but cf. his seminar on Knowledge and belief, and his remarks on some
of our beliefs needing to be true, in Meaning revisited. The examinee
knows that the battle of Waterloo was fought in 1815. Nothing odd about that,
nor about Moores uttering I know that these are my hands. Grice is perhaps the
only one of the Oxonian philosophers of Austins play group who took common
sense realsim so seriously, if only to crticise Malcoms zeal with it. For
Grice, common-sense realism = ordinary language, whereas for the typical
Austinian, ordinary language = the language of the man in the street. Back at
Oxford, Grice uses Malcolm to contest the usual criticism that Oxford
ordinary-language philosophers defend common-sense realist assumptions just
because the way non-common-sense realist philosopher’s talk is not ordinary
language, and even at Oxford. Cf. Flews reference to Joness philosophical
verbal rubbish in using self as a noun. Grice is infuriated by all this unclear
chatter, and chooses Malcolms mistreatment of Moore as an example. Grice is
possibly fearful to consider Austins claims directly! In later essays, such as
‘the learned’ and ‘the lay,’ Grice goes back to the topic criticising now the
scientists jargon as an affront to the ordinary language of the layman that
Grice qua philosopher defends. scepticism, in the most common sense, the refusal
to grant that there is any knowledge or justification. Skepticism can be either
partial or total, either practical or theoretical, and, if theoretical, either
moderate or radical, and either of knowledge or of justification. Skepticism is
partial iff if and only if it is restricted to particular fields of beliefs or
propositions, and total iff not thus restricted. And if partial, it may be
highly restricted, as is the skepticism for which religion is only opium, or
much more general, as when not only is religion called opium, but also history
bunk and metaphysics meaningless. Skepticism is practical iff it is an attitude
of deliberately withholding both belief and disbelief, accompanied perhaps but
not necessarily by commitment to a recommendation for people generally, that
they do likewise. Practical skepticism can of course be either total or
partial, and if partial it can be more or less general. Skepticism is
theoretical iff it is a commitment to the belief that there is no knowledge
justified belief of a certain kind or of certain kinds. Such theoretical
skepticism comes in several varieties. It is moderate and total iff it holds
that there is no certain superknowledge superjustified belief whatsoever, not
even in logic or mathematics, nor through introspection of one’s present
experience. It is radical and total iff it holds that there isn’t even any
ordinary knowledge justified belief at all. It is moderate and partial, on the
other hand, iff it holds that there is no certain superknowledge superjustified
belief of a certain specific kind K or of certain specific kinds K1, . . . , Kn
less than the totality of such kinds. It is radical and partial, finally, iff
it holds that there isn’t even any ordinary knowledge justified belief at all
of that kind K or of those kinds K1, . . . , Kn. Grecian skepticism can be
traced back to Socrates’ epistemic modesty. Suppressed by the prolific
theoretical virtuosity of Plato and Aristotle, such modesty reasserted itself
in the skepticism of the Academy led by Arcesilaus and later by Carneades. In
this period began a long controversy pitting Academic Skeptics against the
Stoics Zeno and later Chrysippus, and their followers. Prolonged controversy,
sometimes heated, softened the competing views, but before agreement congealed
Anesidemus broke with the Academy and reclaimed the arguments and tradition of
Pyrrho, who wrote nothing, but whose Skeptic teachings had been preserved by a
student, Timon in the third century B.C.. After enduring more than two
centuries, neoPyrrhonism was summarized, c.200 A.D., by Sextus Empiricus
Outlines of Pyrrhonism and Adversus mathematicos. Skepticism thus ended as a
school, but as a philosophical tradition it has been influential long after
that, and is so even now. It has influenced strongly not only Cicero Academica
and De natura deorum, St. Augustine Contra academicos, and Montaigne “Apology
for Raimund Sebond”, but also the great historical philosophers of the Western
tradition, from Descartes through Hegel. Both on the Continent and in the
Anglophone sphere a new wave of skepticism has built for decades, with logical
positivism, deconstructionism, historicism, neopragmatism, and relativism, and
the writings of Foucault knowledge as a mask of power, Derrida deconstruction,
Quine indeterminacy and eliminativism, Kuhn incommensurability, and Rorty
solidarity over objectivity, edification over inquiry. At the same time a
rising tide of books and articles continues other philosophical traditions in
metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, etc. It is interesting to compare the
cognitive disengagement recommended by practical skepticism with the affective
disengagement dear to stoicism especially in light of the epistemological
controversies that long divided Academic Skepticism from the Stoa, giving rise
to a rivalry dominant in Hellenistic philosophy. If believing and favoring are
positive, with disbelieving and disfavoring their respective negative
counterparts, then the magnitude of our happiness positive or unhappiness
negative over a given matter is determined by the product of our
belief/disbelief and our favoring/disfavoring with regard to that same matter.
The fear of unhappiness may lead one stoically to disengage from affective
engagement, on either side of any matter that escapes one’s total control. And
this is a kind of practical affective “skepticism.” Similarly, if believing and
truth are positive, with disbelieving and falsity their respective negative
counterparts, then the magnitude of our correctness positive or error negative
over a given matter is determined by the product of our belief/disbelief and
the truth/falsity with regard to that same matter where the positive or
negative magnitude of the truth or falsity at issue may be determined by some
measure of “theoretical importance,” though alternatively one could just assign
all truths a value of !1 and all falsehoods a value of †1. The fear of error
may lead one skeptically to disengage from cognitive engagement, on either side
of any matter that involves risk of error. And this is “practical cognitive
skepticism.” We wish to attain happiness and avoid unhappiness. This leads to
the disengagement of the stoic. We wish to attain the truth and avoid error.
This leads to the disengagement of the skeptic, the practical skeptic. Each opts
for a conservative policy, but one that is surely optional, given just the
reasoning indicated. For in avoiding unhappiness the stoic also forfeits a
corresponding possibility of happiness. And in avoiding error the skeptic also
forfeits a corresponding possibility to grasp a truth. These twin policies
appeal to conservatism in our nature, and will reasonably prevail in the lives
of those committed to avoiding risk as a paramount objective. For this very
desire must then be given its due, if we judge it rational. Skepticism is
instrumental in the birth of modern epistemology, and modern philosophy, at the
hands of Descartes, whose skepticism is methodological but sophisticated and
well informed by that of the ancients. Skepticism is also a main force, perhaps
the main force, in the broad sweep of Western philosophy from Descartes through
Hegel. Though preeminent in the history of our subject, skepticism since then
has suffered decades of neglect, and only in recent years has reclaimed much
attention and even applause. Some recent influential discussions go so far as
to grant that we do not know we are not dreaming. But they also insist one can
still know when there is a fire before one. The key is to analyze knowledge as
a kind of appropriate responsiveness to its object truth: what is required is
that the subject “track” through his belief the truth of what he believes. S
tracks the truth of P iff: S would not believe P if P were false. Such an
analysis of tracking, when conjoined with the view of knowledge as tracking,
enables one to explain how one can know about the fire even if for all one
knows it is just a dream. The crucial fact here is that even if P logically
entails Q, one may still be able to track the truth of P though unable to track
the truth of Q. Nozick, Philosophical Explanations, 1. Many problems arise in
the literature on this approach. One that seems especially troubling is that
though it enables us to understand how contingent knowledge of our surroundings
is possible, the tracking account falls short of enabling an explanation of how
such knowledge on our part is actual. To explain how one knows that there is a
fire before one F, according to the tracking account one presumably would
invoke one’s tracking the truth of F. But this leads deductively almost
immediately to the claim that one is not dreaming: Not D. And this is not
something one can know, according to the tracking account. So how is one to
explain one’s justification for making that claim? Most troubling of all here
is the fact that one is now cornered by the tracking account into making
combinations of claims of the following form: I am quite sure that p, but I
have no knowledge at all as to whether p. And this seems incoherent. A
Cartesian dream argument that has had much play in recent discussions of
skepticism is made explicit by Barry Stroud, The Significance of Philosophical
Scepticism, 4 as follows. One knows that if one knows F then one is not
dreaming, in which case if one really knows F then one must know one is not dreaming.
However, one does not know one is not dreaming. So one does not know F. Q.E.D.
And why does one fail to know one is not dreaming? Because in order to know it
one would need to know that one has passed some test, some empirical procedure
to determine whether one is dreaming. But any such supposed test say, pinching oneself could just be part of a dream, and dreaming
one passes the test would not suffice to show one was not dreaming. However,
might one not actually be witnessing the fire, and passing the test and be doing this in wakeful life, not in a
dream and would that not be compatible
with one’s knowing of the fire and of one’s wakefulness? Not so, according to
the argument, since in order to know of the fire one needs prior knowledge of
one’s wakefulness. But in order to know of one’s wakefulness one needs prior
knowledge of the results of the test procedure. But this in turn requires prior
knowledge that one is awake and not dreaming. And we have a vicious circle. We
might well hold that it is possible to know one is not dreaming even in the
absence of any positive test result, or at most in conjunction with coordinate
not prior knowledge of such a positive indication. How in that case would one
know of one’s wakefulness? Perhaps one would know it by believing it through
the exercise of a reliable faculty. Perhaps one would know it through its
coherence with the rest of one’s comprehensive and coherent body of beliefs.
Perhaps both. But, it may be urged, if these are the ways one might know of one’s
wakefulness, does not this answer commit us to a theory of the form of A below?
A The proposition that p is something one knows believes justifiably if and
only if one satisfies conditions C with respect to it. And if so, are we not
caught in a vicious circle by the question as to how we know what justifies us in believing A itself? This is far from obvious, since the
requirement that we must submit to some test procedure for wakefulness and know
ourselves to test positively, before we can know ourselves to be awake, is
itself a requirement that seems to lead equally to a principle such as A. At
least it is not evident why the proposal of the externalist or of the
coherentist as to how we know we are awake should be any more closely related
to a general principle like A than is the foundationalist? notion that in order
to know we are awake we need epistemically prior knowledge that we test
positive in a way that does not presuppose already acquired knowledge of the
external world. The problem of how to justify the likes of A is a descendant of
the infamous “problem of the criterion,” reclaimed in the sixteenth century and
again in this century by Chisholm, Theory of Knowledge, 6, 7, and 8 but much
used already by the Skeptics of antiquity under the title of the diallelus.
About explanations of our knowledge or justification in general of the form
indicated by A, we are told that they are inadequate in a way revealed by
examples like the following. Suppose we want to know how we know anything at
all about the external world, and part of the answer is that we know the
location of our neighbor by knowing the location of her car in her driveway.
Surely this would be at best the beginning of an answer that might be
satisfactory in the end if recursive, e.g., but as it stands it cannot be
satisfactory without supplementation. The objection here is based on a
comparison between two appeals: the appeal of a theorist of knowledge to a
principle like A in the course of explaining our knowledge or justification in
general, on one side; and the appeal to the car’s location in explaining our
knowledge of facts about the external world, on the other side. This comparison
is said to be fatal to the ambition to explain our knowledge or justification
in general. But are the appeals relevantly analogous? One important difference
is this. In the example of the car, we explain the presence, in some subject S,
of a piece of knowledge of a certain kind of the external world by appeal to
the presence in S of some other piece of knowledge of the very same kind. So
there is an immediate problem if it is our aim to explain how any knowledge of
the sort in question ever comes to be unless the explication is just beginning,
and is to turn recursive in due course. Now of course A is theoretically
ambitious, and in that respect the theorist who gives an answer of the form of
A is doing something similar to what must be done by the protagonist in our car
example, someone who is attempting to provide a general explanation of how any
knowledge of a certain kind comes about. Nevertheless, there is also an
important difference, namely that the theorist whose aim it is to give a
general account of the form of A need not attribute any knowledge whatsoever to
a subject S in explaining how that subject comes to have a piece of knowledge
or justified belief. For there is no need to require that the conditions C
appealed to by principle A must be conditions that include attribution of any
knowledge at all to the subject in question. It is true that in claiming that A
itself meets conditions C, and that it is this which explains how one knows A,
we do perhaps take ourselves to know A or at least to be justified in believing
it. But if so, this is the inevitable lot of anyone who seriously puts forward
any explanation of anything. And it is quite different from a proposal that
part of what explains how something is known or justifiably believed includes a
claim to knowledge or justified belief of the very same sort. In sum, as in the
case of one’s belief that one is awake, the belief in something of the form of
A may be said to be known, and in so saying one does not commit oneself to
adducing an ulterior reason in favor of A, or even to having such a reason in
reserve. One is of course committed to being justified in believing A, perhaps
even to having knowledge that A. But it is not at all clear that the only way
to be justified in believing A is by way of adduced reasons in favor of A, or
that one knows A only if one adduces strong enough reasons in its favor. For we
often know things in the absence of such adduced reasons. Thus consider one’s
knowledge through memory of which door one used to come into a room that has
more than one open door. Returning finally to A, in its case the explanation of
how one knows it may, once again, take the form of an appeal to the justifying
power of intellectual virtues or of coherence
or both. Recent accounts of the nature of thought and representation
undermine a tradition of wholesale doubt about nature, whose momentum is hard
to stop, and threatens to leave the subject alone and restricted to a solipsism
of the present moment. But there may be a way to stop skepticism early by questioning the possibility of its being
sensibly held, given what is required for meaningful language and thought.
Consider our grasp of observable shape and color properties that objects around
us might have. Such grasp seems partly constituted by our discriminatory
abilities. When we discern a shape or a color we do so presumably in terms of a
distinctive impact that such a shape or color has on us. We are put
systematically into a certain distinctive state X when we are appropriately
related, in good light, with our eyes open, etc., to the presence in our
environment of that shape or color. What makes one’s distinctive state one of
thinking of sphericity rather than something else, is said to be that it is a
state tied by systematic causal relations to skepticism skepticism 849 849 the presence of sphericity in one’s
normal environment. A light now flickers at the end of the skeptic’s tunnel. In
doubt now is the coherence of traditional skeptical reflection. Indeed, our
predecessors in earlier centuries may have moved in the wrong direction when
they attempted a reduction of nature to the mind. For there is no way to make
sense of one’s mind without its contents, and there is no way to make sense of
how one’s mind can have such contents except by appeal to how one is causally
related to one’s environment. If the very existence of that environment is put
in doubt, that cuts the ground from under one’s ability reasonably to
characterize one’s own mind, or to feel any confidence about its contents.
Perhaps, then, one could not be a “brain in a vat.” Much contemporary thought
about language and the requirements for meaningful language thus suggests that
a lot of knowledge must already be in place for us to be able to think
meaningfully about a surrounding reality, so as to be able to question its very
existence. If so, then radical skepticism answers itself. For if we can so much
as understand a radical skepticism about the existence of our surrounding
reality, then we must already know a great deal about that reality. Sceptics, those ancient thinkers who developed
sets of arguments to show either that no knowledge is possible Academic
Skepticism or that there is not sufficient or adequate evidence to tell if any
knowledge is possible. If the latter is the case then these thinkers advocated
suspending judgment on all question concerning knowledge Pyrrhonian Skepticism.
Academic Skepticism gets its name from the fact that it was formulated in
Plato’s Academy in the third century B.C., starting from Socrates’ statement,
“All I know is that I know nothing.” It was developed by Arcesilaus c.268241
and Carneades c.213129, into a series of arguments, directed principally
against the Stoics, purporting to show that nothing can be known. The Academics
posed a series of problems to show that what we think we know by our senses may
be unreliable, and that we cannot be sure about the reliability of our
reasoning. We do not possess a guaranteed standard or criterion for
ascertaining which of our judgments is true or false. Any purported knowledge
claim contains some element that goes beyond immediate experience. If this
claim constituted knowledge we would have to know something that could not
possibly be false. The evidence for the claim would have to be based on our
senses and our reason, both of which are to some degree unreliable. So the
knowledge claim may be false or doubtful, and hence cannot constitute genuine
knowledge. So, the Academics said that nothing is certain. The best we can
attain is probable information. Carneades is supposed to have developed a form
of verification theory and a kind of probabilism, similar in some ways to that
of modern pragmatists and positivists. Academic Skepticism dominated the
philosophizing of Plato’s Academy until the first century B.C. While Cicero was
a student there, the Academy turned from Skepticism to a kind of eclectic philosophy.
Its Skeptical arguments have been preserved in Cicero’s works, Academia and De
natura deorum, in Augustine’s refutation in his Contra academicos, as well as
in the summary presented by Diogenes Laertius in his lives of the Grecian
philosophers. Skeptical thinking found another home in the school of the
Pyrrhonian Skeptics, probably connected with the Methodic school of medicine in
Alexandria. The Pyrrhonian movement traces its origins to Pyrrho of Elis
c.360275 B.C. and his student Timon c.315225 B.C.. The stories about Pyrrho
indicate that he was not a theoretician but a practical doubter who would not
make any judgments that went beyond immediate experience. He is supposed to
have refused to judge if what appeared to be chariots might strike him, and he
was often rescued by his students because he would not make any commitments.
His concerns were apparently ethical. He sought to avoid unhappiness that might
result from accepting any value theory. If the theory was at all doubtful,
accepting it might lead to mental anguish. The theoretical formulation of
Pyrrhonian Skepticism is attributed to Aenesidemus c.100 40 B.C.. Pyrrhonists
regarded dogmatic philosophers and Academic Skeptics as asserting too much, the
former saying that something can be known and the latter that nothing can be
known. The Pyrrhonists suspended judgments on all questions on which there was
any conflicting evidence, including whether or not anything could be known. The
Pyrrhonists used some of the same kinds of arguments developed by Arcesilaus
and Carneades. Aenesidemus and those who followed after him organized the
arguments into sets of “tropes” or ways of leading to suspense of judgment on
various questions. Sets of ten, eight, five, and two tropes appear in the only
surviving writing of the Pyrrhonists, the works of Sextus Empiricus, a
third-century A.D. teacher of Pyrrhonism. Each set of tropes offers suggestions
for suspending judgment about any knowledge claims that go beyond appearances.
The tropes seek to show that for any claim, evidence for and evidence against
it can be offered. The disagreements among human beings, the variety of human
experiences, the fluctuation of human judgments under differing conditions,
illness, drunkenness, etc., all point to the opposition of evidence for and
against each knowledge claim. Any criterion we employ to sift and weigh the
evidence can also be opposed by countercriterion claims. Given this situation,
the Pyrrhonian Skeptics sought to avoid committing themselves concerning any kind
of question. They would not even commit themselves as to whether the arguments
they put forth were sound or not. For them Skepticism was not a statable
theory, but rather an ability or mental attitude for opposing evidence for and
against any knowledge claim that went beyond what was apparent, that dealt with
the non-evident. This opposing produced an equipollence, a balancing of the
opposing evidences, that would lead to suspending judgment on any question.
Suspending judgment led to a state of mind called “ataraxia,” quietude, peace
of mind, or unperturbedness. In such a state the Skeptic was no longer
concerned or worried or disturbed about matters beyond appearances. The
Pyrrhonians averred that Skepticism was a cure for a disease called “dogmatism”
or rashness. The dogmatists made assertions about the non-evident, and then
became disturbed about whether these assertions were true. The disturbance
became a mental disease or disorder. The Pyrrhonians, who apparently were
medical doctors, offered relief by showing the patient how and why he should
suspend judgment instead of dogmatizing. Then the disease would disappear and
the patient would be in a state of tranquillity, the peace of mind sought by
Hellenistic dogmatic philosophers. The Pyrrhonists, unlike the Academic
Skeptics, were not negative dogmatists. The Pyrrhonists said neither that
knowledge is possible nor that it is impossible. They remained seekers, while
allowing the Skeptical arguments and the equipollence of evidences to act as a
purge of dogmatic assertions. The purge eliminates all dogmas as well as
itself. After this the Pyrrhonist lives undogmatically, following natural
inclinations, immediate experience, and the laws and customs of his society,
without ever judging or committing himself to any view about them. In this
state the Pyrrhonist would have no worries, and yet be able to function
naturally and according to law and custom. The Pyrrhonian movement disappeared
during the third century A.D., possibly because it was not considered an alternative
to the powerful religious movements of the time. Only scant traces of it appear
before the Renaissance, when the texts of Sextus and Cicero were rediscovered
and used to formulate a modern skeptical view by such thinkers as Montaigne and
Charron. Refs.: The obvious source is
the essay on scepticism in WoW, but there are allusions in “Prejudices and
predilections, and elsewhere, in The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC
Scheler, M.: G. phenomenologist, social philosopher,
and sociologist of knowledge. Born in Munich, he studied in Jena; when he
returned to Munich in 7 he came in contact with phenomenology, especially the
realist version of the early Husserl and his Munich School followers. Scheler’s
first works were phenomenological studies in ethics leading to his ultimate
theory of value: he described the moral feelings of sympathy and resentment and
wrote a criticism of Kantian formalism and rationalism, Formalism in Ethics and
a Non-Formal Ethics of Value 3. During the war, he was an ardent nationalist
and wrote essays in support of the war that were also philosophical criticisms
of modern culture, opposed to “Anglo-Saxon” naturalism and rational
calculation. Although he later embraced a broader notion of community, such
criticisms of modernity remained constant themes of his writings. His
conversion to Catholicism after the war led him to apply phenomenological
description to religious phenomena and feelings, and he later turned to themes
of anthropology and natural science. The core of Scheler’s phenomenological
method is his conception of the objectivity of essences, which, though
contained in experience, are a priori and independent of the knower. For
Scheler, values are such objective, though non-Platonic, essences. Their
objectivity is intuitively accessible in immediate experience and feelings, as
when we experience beauty in music and do not merely hear certain sounds.
Scheler distinguished between valuations or value perspectives on the one hand,
which are historically relative and variable, and values on the other, which
are independent and invariant. There are four such values, the hierarchical
organization of which could be both immediately intuited and established by
various public criteria like duration and independence: pleasure, vitality, spirit,
and religion. Corresponding to these values are various personalities who are
not creators of value but their discoverers, historical disclosers, and
exemplars: the “artist of consumption,” the hero, the genius, and the saint. A
similar hierarchy of values applies to forms of society, the highest of which
is the church, or a Christian community of solidarity and love. Scheler
criticizes the leveling tendencies of liberalism for violating this hierarchy,
leading to forms of resentment, individualism, and nationalism, all of which
represent the false ordering of values.
Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph, philosopher whose
metamorscalar implicaturum Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph 816 816 phoses encompass the entire history of
G. idealism. A Schwabian, Schelling first studied at Tübingen, where he
befriended Hölderlin and Hegel. The young Schelling was an enthusiastic
exponent of Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre and devoted several early essays to its
exposition. After studying science and mathematics at Leipzig, he joined Fichte
at Jena in 1798. Meanwhile, in such writings as Philosophische Briefe über
Dogmatismus und Kritizismus “Philosophical Letters on Dogmatism and Criticism,”
1795, Schelling betrayed growing doubts concerning Fichte’s philosophy above
all, its treatment of nature and a lively interest in Spinoza. He then turned
to constructing a systematic Naturphilosophie philosophy of nature within the
context of which nature would be treated more holistically than by either
Newtonian science or transcendental idealism. Of his many publications on this
topic, two of the more important are Ideen zu einer Philosophie der Natur
“Ideas concerning a Philosophy of Nature,” 1797 and Von der Weltseele “On the
World-Soul,” 1798. Whereas transcendental idealism attempts to derive objective
experience from an initial act of free self-positing, Schelling’s philosophy of
nature attempts to derive consciousness from objects. Beginning with “pure
objectivity,” the Naturphilosophie purports to show how nature undergoes a
process of unconscious self-development, culminating in the conditions for its
own self-representation. The method of Naturphilosophie is fundamentally a
priori: it begins with the concept of the unity of nature and accounts for its
diversity by interpreting nature as a system of opposed forces or “polarities,”
which manifest themselves in ever more complex levels of organization Potenzen.
At Jena, Schelling came into contact with Tieck, Novalis, and the Schlegel
brothers and became interested in art. This new interest is evident in his
System des transzendentalen Idealismus 1800, which describes the path from pure
subjectivity self-consciousness to objectivity the necessary positing of the
Not-I, or of nature. The most innovative and influential portion of this
treatise, which is otherwise closely modeled on Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre, is
its conclusion, which presents art as the concrete accomplishment of the
philosophical task. In aesthetic experience the identity between the subjective
and the objective, the ideal and the real, becomes an object to the
experiencing I itself. For Schelling, transcendental idealism and
Naturphilosophie are two complementary sides or subdivisions of a larger, more
encompassing system, which he dubbed the System of Identity or Absolute
Idealism and expounded in a series of publications, including the Darstellung
meines Systems der Philosophie “Presentation of My System of Philosophy,” 1801,
Bruno 1802, and Vorlesungen über die Methode des akademischen Studiums “Lectures
on the Method of Academic Study,” 1803. The most distinctive feature of this
system is that it begins with a bald assertion of the unity of thought and
being, i.e., with the bare idea of the self-identical “Absolute,” which is
described as the first presupposition of all knowledge. Since the identity with
which this system commences transcends every conceivable difference, it is also
described as the “point of indifference.” From this undifferentiated or
“indifferent” starting point, Schelling proceeds to a description of reality as
a whole, considered as a differentiated system within which unity is maintained
by various synthetic relationships, such as substance and attribute, cause and
effect, attraction and repulsion. Like his philosophy of nature, Schelling’s
System of Identity utilizes the notion of various hierarchically related
Potenzen as its basic organizing principle. The obvious question concerns the
precise relationship between the “indifferent” Absolute and the real system of
differentiated elements, a question that may be said to have set the agenda for
Schelling’s subsequent philosophizing. From 1803 to 1841 Schelling was in
Bavaria, where he continued to expound his System of Identity and to explore
the philosophies of art and nature. The most distinctive feature of his thought
during this period, however, was a new interest in religion and in the
theosophical writings of Boehme, whose influence is prominent in the
Philosophische Untersuchungen über das Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit “Philosophical
Investigations concerning the Nature of Human Freedom,” 1809, a work often
interpreted as anticipating existentialism. He also worked on a speculative
interpretation of human history, Die Weltalter, which remained unpublished, and
lectured regularly on the history of philosophy. In 1841 Schelling moved to
Berlin, where he lectured on his new philosophy of revelation and mythology,
which he now characterized as “positive philosophy,” in contradistinction to
the purely “negative” philosophy of Kant, Fichte, and Hegel. Some scholars have
interpreted these posthumously published lectures as representing the
culmination both of Schelling’s own protracted philosophical development and of
G. idealism as a whole.
Schema (Latin ‘figura,’ as in Grice, ‘figure of
speech’), also schema plural: schemata, a metalinguistic frame or template used
to specify an infinite set of sentences, its instances, by finite means, often
taken with a side condition on how its blanks or placeholders are to be filled.
The sentence ‘Either Abe argues or it is not the case that Abe argues’ is an
instance of the excluded middle scheme for English: ‘Either . . . or it is not
the case that . . .’, where the two blanks are to be filled with one and the
same well-formed declarative English sentence. Since first-order number theory
cannot be finitely axiomatized, the mathematical induction scheme is used to
effectively specify an infinite set of axioms: ‘If zero is such that . . . and
the successor of every number such that . . . is also such that . . . , then
every number is such that . . .’, where the four blanks are to be filled with
one and the same arithmetic open sentence, such as ‘it precedes its own
successor’ or ‘it is finite’. Among the best-known is Tarski’s scheme T: ‘. . .
is a true sentence if and only if . . .’, where the second blank is filled with
a sentence and the first blank by a name of the sentence.
Schiller, Johann Christoph Friedrich von, G. poet,
dramatist, and philosopher. Along with his colleagues Reinhold and Fichte, he
participated in systematically revising Kant’s transcendental idealism. Though
Schiller’s bestknown theoretical contributions were to aesthetics, his
philosophical ambitions were more general, and he proposed a novel solution to
the problem of the systematic unity, not merely of the critical philosophy, but
of human nature. His most substantial philosophical work, Briefe über die
äesthetische Erziehung des Menschen “Letters on the Aesthetic Education of
Man,” 1794/95, examines the relationship between natural necessity and
practical freedom and addresses two problems raised by Kant: How can a creature
governed by natural necessity and desire ever become aware of its own freedom
and thus capable of autonomous moral action? And how can these two sides of
human nature the natural, sensuous side
and the rational, supersensuous one be
reconciled? In contradistinction both to those who subordinate principles to
feelings “savages” and to those who insist that one should strive to
subordinate feelings to principles “barbarians”, Schiller posited an
intermediary realm between the sphere of nature and that of freedom, as well as
a third basic human drive capable of mediating between sensuous and rational
impulses. This third impulse is dubbed the “play impulse,” and the intermediary
sphere to which it pertains is that of art and beauty. By cultivating the play
impulse i.e., via “aesthetic education” one is not only freed from bondage to
sensuality and granted a first glimpse of one’s practical freedom, but one also
becomes capable of reconciling the rational and sensuous sides of one’s own
nature. This idea of a condition in which opposites are simultaneously
cancelled and preserved, as well as the specific project of reconciling freedom
and necessity, profoundly influenced subsequent thinkers such as Schelling and
Hegel and contributed to the development of G. idealism.
Schlegel, Friedrich von, G. literary critic and
philosopher, one of the principal representatives of G. Romanticism. In On the
Study of Grecian Poetry 1795, Schlegel laid the foundations for the distinction
of classical and Romantic literature and a pronounced consciousness of literary
modernity. Together with his brother August Wilhelm, he edited the Athenaeum
17981800, the main theoretical organ of G. Romanticism, famous for its
collection of fragments as a new means of critical communication. Schlegel is
the originator of the Romantic theory of irony, a non-dialectical form of
philosophizing and literary writing that takes its inspiration from Socratic
irony and combines it with Fichte’s thought process of affirmation and
negation, “self-creation” and “self-annihilation.” Closely connected wih
Schlegel’s theory of irony is his theory of language and understanding
hermeneutics. Critical reflection on language promotes an ironic awareness of
the “necessity and impossibility of complete communication” Critical Fragments,
No. 108; critical reflection on understanding reveals the amount of
incomprehensibility, of “positive not-understanding” involved in every act of
understanding On Incomprehensibility, 1800. Schlegel’s writings were essential
for the rise of historical consciousness in G. Romanticism. His On Ancient and
Modern Literature 1812 is reputed to represent the first literary history in a
modern and broadly comparative fashion. His Philosophy of History 1828,
together with his Philosophy of Life 1828 schema Schlegel, Friedrich von
818 818 and Philosophy of Language
1829, confront Hegel’s philosophy from the point of view of a Christian and
personalistic type of philosophizing. Schlegel converted to Catholicism in
1808.
Schleiermacher, F. G. philosopher, a “critical realist”
working among post-Kantian idealists. In philosophy and science he presupposed
transcendental features, noted in his dialectic lectures, and advocated
integrative but historically contingent, empirical functions. Both develop,
but, contra Hegel, not logically. Schleiermacher was a creator of modern
general hermeneutics; a father of modern theological and religious studies; an
advocate of women’s rights; the cofounder, with Humboldt, of the at Berlin 180810, where he taught until 1834;
and the classic translator of Plato into G.. Schleiermacher has had an
undeservedly minor place in histories of philosophy. Appointed chiefly to
theology, he published less philosophy, though he regularly lectured, in
tightly argued discourse, in Grecian philosophy, history of philosophy,
dialectic, hermeneutics and criticism, philosophy of mind “psychology”, ethics,
politics, aesthetics, and philosophy of education. From the 0s, his collected
writings and large correspondence began to appear in a forty-volume critical
edition and in the larger Schleiermacher Studies and Translations series.
Brilliant, newly available pieces from his twenties on freedom, the highest
good, and values, previously known only in fragments but essential for
understanding his views fully, were among the first to appear. Much of his
outlook was formed before he became prominent in the early Romantic circle 17961806,
distinguishable by his markedly religious, consistently liberal views.
Scholasticism, a set of scholarly and instructional
techniques developed in Western European schools of the late medieval period,
including the use of commentary and disputed question. ‘Scholasticism’ is
derived from Latin scholasticus, which in the twelfth century meant the master
of a school. The Scholastic method is usually presented as beginning in the law
schools notably at Bologna and as being then transported into theology
and philosophy by a series of masters including Abelard and Peter Lombard.
Within the new universities of the thirteenth century the standardization of
the curriculum and the enormous prestige of Aristotle’s work despite the
suspicion with which it was initially greeted contributed to the entrenchment
of the method and it was not until the educational reforms of the beginning of
the sixteenth century that it ceased to be dominant. There is, strictly
speaking, no such thing as Scholasticism. As the term was originally used it
presupposed that a single philosophy was taught in the universities of late
medieval Europe, but there was no such philosophy. The philosophical movements
working outside the universities in the late sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries
and the “neo-Scholastics” of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries
all found such a presupposition useful, and their influence led scholars to
assume it. At first this generated efforts to find a common core in the
philosophies taught in the late medieval schools. More recently it has led to
efforts to find methods characteristic of their teaching, and to an extension
of the term to the schools of late antiquity and of Byzantium. Both among the
opponents of the schools in the seventeenth century and among the
“neoScholastics,” ‘Scholasticism’ was supposed to designate a doctrine whose
core was the doctrine of substance and accidents. As portrayed by Descartes and
Locke, the Scholastics accepted the view that among the components of a thing
were a substantial form and a number of real accidental forms, many of which
corresponded to perceptible properties of the thing its color, shape, temperature. They were also
supposed to have accepted a sharp distinction between natural and unnatural motion.
Schopenhauer, Arthur, G. philosopher. Born in Danzig
and schooled in G.y, France, and England during a welltraveled childhood, he
became acquainted through his novelist mother with Goethe, Schlegel, and the
brothers Grimm. He studied medicine at the
of Göttingen and philosophy at the
of Berlin; received the doctorate from the of Jena in 1813; and lived much of his adult
life in Frankfurt, where he died. Schopenhauer’s dissertation, On the Fourfold
Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason 1813, lays the groundwork for all of
his later philosophical work. The world of representation equivalent to Kant’s
phenomenal world is governed by “the principle of sufficient reason”: “every
possible object . . . stands in a necessary relation to other objects, on the
one hand as determined, on the other as determining” The World as Will and
Representation. Thus, each object of consciousness can be explained in terms of
its relations with other objects. The systematic statement of Schopenhauer’s
philosophy appeared in The World as Will and Representation 1818. His other
works are On Vision and Colors 1815, “On the Will in Nature” 1836, conjoined
with “On the Foundation of Morality” in The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics
1841; the second edition of The World as Will and Representation, which
included a second volume of essays 1844; an enlarged and revised edition of On
the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason 1847; and Parerga and
Paralipomena, a series of essays 1851. These are all consistent with the
principal statement of his thought in The World as Will and Representation. The
central postulate of Schopenhauer’s system is that the fundamental reality is
will, which he equates with the Kantian thing-in-itself. Unlike Kant,
Schopenhauer contends that one can immediately know the thing-in-itself through
the experience of an inner, volitional reality within one’s own body. Every
phenomenon, according to Schopenhauer, has a comparable inner reality.
Consequently, the term ‘will’ can extend to the inner nature of all things.
Moreover, because number pertains exclusively to the phenomenal world, the
will, as thing-initself, is one. Nevertheless, different types of things
manifest the will to different degrees. Schopenhauer accounts for these differences
by invoking Plato’s Ideas or Forms. The Ideas are the universal prototypes for
the various kinds of objects in the phenomenal world. Taken collectively, the
Ideas constitute a hierarchy. We usually overlook them in everyday experience,
focusing instead on particulars and their practical relationships to us.
However, during aesthetic experience, we recognize the universal Idea within
the particular; simultaneously, as aesthetic beholders, we become “the
universal subject of knowledge.” Aesthetic experience also quiets the will
within us. The complete silencing of the will is, for Schopenhauer, the ideal
for human beings, though it is rarely attained. Because will is the fundamental
metaphysical principle, our lives are dominated by willing and, consequently, filled with struggle,
conflict, and dissatisfaction. Inspired by Buddhism, Schopenhauer contends that
all of life is suffering, which only an end to desire can permanently eliminate
as opposed to the respite of aesthetic experience. This is achieved only by the
saint, who rejects desire in an inner act termed “denial of the will to live.”
The saint fully grasps that the same will motivates all phenomena and,
recognizing that nothing is gained through struggle and competition, achieves
“resignation.” Such a person achieves the ethical ideal of all religions compassion toward all beings, resulting from
the insight that all are, fundamentally, one.
Schröder-Bernstein theorem, the theorem that mutually
dominant sets are equinumerous. A set A is said to be dominated by a set B if
and only if each element of A can be mapped to a unique element of B in such a
way that no two elements of A are mapped to the same element of B possibly with
some elements of B left over. Intuitively, if A is dominated by B, then B has
at least as many members as A. Given this intuition, one would expect that if A
is dominated by B and B is dominated by A, then A and B are equinumerous i.e.,
A can be mapped to B as described above with no elements of B left over. This
is the Schröder-Bernstein theorem. Stated in terms of cardinal numbers, the
theorem says that if k m l and l m k, then k % l. Despite the simplicity of the
theorem’s statement, its proof is non-trivial.
Schrödinger, Erwin, Austrian physicist best known for
five papers published in 6, in which he discovered the Schrödinger wave
equation and created modern wave mechanics. For this achievement, he was
awarded the Nobel prize in physics shared with Paul Dirac in 3. Like Einstein,
Schrödinger was a resolute but ultimately unsuccessful critic of the Copenhagen
interpretation of quantum mechanics. Schrödinger defended the view which he
derived from Boltzmann that theories should give a picture, continuous in space
and time, of the real processes that produce observable phenomena.
Schrödinger’s realistic philosophy of science played an important role in his
discovery of wave mechanics. Although his physical interpretation of the psi
function was soon abandoned, his approach to quantum mechanics survives in the
theories of Louis de Broglie and David Bohm.
Schulze, Gottlob Ernst, G. philosopher today known
mainly as an acute and influential early critic of Kant and Reinhold. He taught
at Wittenberg, Helmstedt, and Göttingen; one of his most important students was
Schopenhauer, whose view of Kant was definitely influenced by Schulze’s
interpretation. Schulze’s most important work was his Aenesidemus, or “On the
Elementary Philosophy Put Forward by Mr. Reinhold in Jena. Together with a
Defense of Skepticism” 1792. It fundamentally changed the discussion of Kantian
philosophy. Kant’s earliest critics had accused him of being a skeptic like
Hume. Kantians, like Reinhold, had argued that critical philosophy was not only
opposed to skepticism, but also contained the only possible refutation of
skepticism. Schulze tried to show that Kantianism could not refute skepticism,
construed as the doctrine that doubts the possibility of any knowledge
concerning the existence or non-existence of “things-in-themselves,” and he
argued that Kant and his followers begged the skeptic’s question by
presupposing that such things exist and causally interact with us. Schulze’s
Aenesidemus had a great impact on Fichte and Hegel, and it also influenced
neoKantianism.
realism, the view that the subject matter of common
sense or scientific research and scientific theories exists independently of
our knowledge of it, and that the goal of science is the description and
explanation of both observable and unobservable aspects of the world.
Scientific realism is contrasted with logical empiricism and social
constructivism. Early arguments for scientific realism simply stated that, in
light of the impressive products and methods of science, realism is the only
philosophy that does not make the success of science a miracle. Formulations of
scientific realism focus on the objects of theoretical knowledge: theories,
laws, and entities. One especially robust argument for scientific realism due
to Putnam and Richard Boyd is that the instrumental reliability of scientific
methodology in the mature sciences such as physics, chemistry, and some areas
of biology can be explained adequately only if we suppose that theories in the
mature sciences are at least approximately true and their central theoretical
terms are at least partially referential Putnam no longer holds this view. More
timid versions of scientific realism do not infer approximate truth of mature
theories. For example, Ian Hacking’s “entity realism” 3 asserts that the
instrumental manipulation of postulated entities to produce further effects
gives us legitimate grounds for ontological commitment to theoretical entities,
but not to laws or theories. Paul Humphreys’s “austere realism” 9 states that
only theoretical commitment to unobserved structures or dispositions could
explain the stability of observed outcomes of scientific inquiry. Distinctive
versions of scientific realism can be found in works by Richard Boyd 3, Philip
Kitcher 3, Richard Miller 7, William Newton-Smith 1, and J. D. Trout 8. Despite
their differences, all of these versions of realism are distinguished against logical empiricism by their commitment that knowledge of
unobservable phenomena is not only possible but actual. As well, all of the
arguments for scientific realism are abductive; they argue that either the
approximate truth of background theories or the existence of theoretical
entities and laws provides the best explanation for some significant fact about
the scientific theory or practice. Scientific realists address the difference between
real entities and merely useful constructs, arguing that realism offers a
better explanation for the success of science. In addition, scientific realism
recruits evidence from the history and practice of science, and offers
explanations for the success of science that are designed to honor the dynamic
and uneven character of that evidence. Most arguments for scientific realism
cohabit with versions of naturalism. Anti-realist opponents argue that the
realist move from instrumental reliability to truth is question-begging.
However, realists reply that such formal criticisms are irrelevant; the
structure of explanationist arguments is inductive and their principles are a
posteriori.
scope, the “part” of the sentence or proposition to
which a given term “applies” under a given interpretation of the sentence. If
the sentence ‘Abe does not believe Ben died’ is interpreted as expressing the
proposition that Abe believes that it is not the case that Ben died, the scope
of ‘not’ is ‘Ben died’; interpreted as “It is not the case that Abe believes
that Ben died,” the scope is the rest of the sentence, i.e., ‘Abe believes Ben
died’. In the first case we have narrow scope, in the second wide scope. If
‘Every number is not even’ is interpreted with narrow scope, it expresses the
false proposition that every number is non-even, which is logically equivalent
to the proposition that no number is even. Taken with wide scope it expresses
the truth that not every number is even, which is equivalent to the truth that
some number is non-even. Under normal interpretations of the sentences,
‘hardened’ has narrow scope in ‘Carl is a hardened recidivist’, whereas
‘alleged’ has wide scope in ‘Dan is an alleged criminal’. Accordingly, ‘Carl is
a hardened recidivist’ logically implies ‘Carl is a recidivist’, whereas ‘Dan
is an alleged criminal’, being equivalent to ‘Allegedly, Dan is a criminal’,
does not imply ‘Dan is a criminal’. Scope considerations are useful in
analyzing structural ambiguity and in understanding the difference between the
grammatical form of a sentence and the logical form of a proposition it
expresses. In a logically perfect language grammatical form mirrors logical
form, there is no scope ambiguity, and the scope of a given term is uniquely
determined by its context.
Scottish common sense philosophy, a comprehensive
philosophical position developed by Reid in the latter part of the eighteenth
century. Reid’s views were propagated by a succession of Scottish popularizers,
of whom the most successful was Dugald Stewart. Through them common sense
doctrine became nearly a philosophical orthodoxy in Great Britain during the
first half of the nineteenth century. Brought to the United States through the
s in Princeton and Philadelphia, common sensism continued to be widely taught
until the later nineteenth century. The early Reidians Beattie and Oswald were,
like Reid himself, read in G.y by Kant and others; and Reid’s views were widely
taught in post-Napoleonic France. The archenemy for the common sense theorists was
Hume. Reid saw in his skepticism the inevitable outcome of Descartes’s thesis,
accepted by Locke, that we do not perceive external objects directly, but that
the immediate object of perception is something in the mind. Against this he
argued that perception involves both sensation and certain intuitively known
general truths or principles that together yield knowledge of external objects.
He also argued that there are many other intuitively known general principles,
including moral principles, available to all normal humans. As a result he
thought that whenever philosophical argument results in conclusions that run
counter to common sense, the philosophy must be wrong. Stewart made some
changes in Reid’s acute and original theory, but his main achievement was to
propagate it through eloquent classes and widely used textbooks. Common
sensism, defending the considered views of the ordinary man, was taken by many
to provide a defense of the Christian religious and moral status quo. Reid had
argued for free will, and presented a long list of self-evident moral axioms.
If this might be plausibly presented as part of the common sense of his time,
the same could not be said for some of the religious doctrines that Oswald
thought equally self-evident. Reid had not given any rigorous tests for what
might count as selfevident. The easy intuitionism of later common sensists was
a natural target for those who, like J. S. Mill, thought that any appeal to
self-evidence was simply a way of justifying vested interest. Whewell, in both
his philosophy of science and his ethics, and Sidgwick, in his moral theory,
acknowledged debts to Reid and tried to eliminate the abuses to which his
method was open. But in doing so they transformed common sensism beyond the
limits within which Reid and those shaped by him operated.
Searle, John R. b.2,
philosopher of language and mind D. Phil., Oxford influenced by Frege,
Vitters, and J. L. Austin; a founder of speech act theory and an important
contributor to debates on intentionality, consciousness, and institutional
facts. Language. In Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language 9,
Searle brings together modified versions of Frege’s distinctions between the
force F and content P of a sentence, and between singular reference and predication,
Austin’s analysis of speech acts, and Grice’s analysis of speaker meaning.
Searle explores the hypothesis that the semantics of a natural language can be
regarded as a conventional realization of underlying constitutive rules and
that illocutionary acts are acts performed in accordance with these rules.
Expression and Meaning 9 extends this analysis to non-literal and indirect
illocutionary acts, and attempts to explain Donnellan’s referential-attributive
distinction in these terms and proposes an influential taxonomy of five basic
types of illocutionary acts based on the illocutionary point or purpose of the
act, and word-to-world versus world-toword direction of fit. Language and mind.
Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind 3 forms the foundation for
the earlier work on speech acts. Now the semantics of a natural language is
seen as the result of the mind intrinsic intentionality imposing conditions of
satisfaction or aboutness on objects expressions in a language, which have
intentionality only derivatively. Perception and action rather than belief are
taken as fundamental. Satisfaction conditions are essentially Fregean i.e.
general versus singular and internal
meaning is in the head, relative to a background of non-intentional states,
and relative to a network of other intentional states. The philosophy of
language becomes a branch of the philosophy of mind. Mind. “Minds, Brains and
Programs” 0 introduced the famous “Chin. room” argument against strong
artificial intelligence the view that
appropriately programming a machine is sufficient for giving it intentional
states. Suppose a monolingual English-speaker is working in a room producing
Chin. answers to Chin. questions well enough to mimic a Chin.speaker, but by
following an algorithm written in English. Such a person does not understand
Chin. nor would a computer computing the same algorithm. This is true for any
such algorithms because they are syntactically individuated and intentional
states are semantically individuated. The Rediscovery of the Mind 2 continues
the attack on the thesis that the brain is a digital computer, and develops a
non-reductive “biological naturalism” on which intentionality, like the
liquidity of water, is a high-level feature, which is caused by and realized in
the brain. Society. The Construction of Social Reality 5 develops his realistic
worldview, starting with an independent world of particles and forces, up
through evolutionary biological systems capable of consciousness and
intentionality, to institutions and social facts, which are created when
persons impose status-features on things, which are collectively recognized and
accepted.
First-order predicate calculus with time-relative
identity -- second-order logic, the logic of languages that contain, in
addition to variables ranging over objects, variables ranging over properties,
relations, functions, or classes of those objects. A model, or interpretation,
of a formal language usually contains a domain of discourse. This domain is
what the language is about, in the model in question. Variables that range over
this domain are called first-order variables. If the language contains only
first-order variables, it is called a first-order language, and it is within
the purview of first-order logic. Some languages also contain variables that
range over properties, relations, functions, or classes of members of the
domain of discourse. These are second-order variables. A language that contains
first-order and second-order variables, and no others, is a secondorder
language. The sentence ‘There is a property shared by all and only prime
numbers’ is straightforwardly rendered in a second-order language, because of
the bound variable ranging over properties. There are also properties of
properties, relations of properties, and the like. Consider, e.g., the property
of properties expressed by ‘P has an infinite extension’ or the relation
expressed by ‘P has a smaller extension than Q’. A language with variables
ranging over such items is called thirdorder. This construction can be
continued, producing fourth-order languages, etc. A language is called
higher-order if it is at least second-order. Deductive systems for second-order
languages are obtained from those for first-order languages by adding
straightforward extensions of the axioms and rules concerning quantifiers that
bind first-order variables. There may also be an axiom scheme of comprehension:
DPExPx S Fx, one instance for each formula F that does not contain P free. The
scheme “asserts” that every formula determines the extension of a property. If
the language has variables ranging over functions, there may also be a version
of the axiom of choice: ERExDyRxy P DfExRxfx. In standard semantics for
second-order logic, a model of a given language is the same as a model for the
corresponding first-order language. The relation variables range over every
relation over the domain-of-discourse, the function variables range over every
function from the domain to the domain, etc. In non-standard, or Henkin semantics,
each model consists of a domain-ofdiscourse and a specified collection of
relations, functions, etc., on the domain. The latter may not include every
relation or function. The specified collections are the range of the
second-order variables in the model in question. In effect, Henkin semantics
regards second-order languages as multi-sorted, first-order languages.
secundum quid, in a certain respect, or with a
qualification. Fallacies can arise from confusing what is true only secundum
quid with what is true simpliciter ‘without qualification’, ‘absolutely’, ‘on
the whole’, or conversely. Thus a strawberry is red simpliciter on the whole.
But it is black, not red, with respect to its seeds, secundum quid. By ignoring
the distinction, one might mistakenly infer that the strawberry is both red and
not red. Again, a certain thief is a good cook, secundum quid; but it does not
follow that he is good simpliciter without qualification. Aristotle was the
first to recognize the fallacy secundum quid et simpliciter explicitly, in his
Sophistical Refutations. On the basis of some exceptionally enigmatic remarks
in the same work, the liar paradox was often regarded in the Middle Ages as an
instance of this fallacy.
Auto-deception – D. F. Pears -- self-deception, 1
purposeful action to avoid unpleasant truths and painful topics about oneself
or the world; 2 unintentional processes of denial, avoidance, or biased
perception; 3 mental states resulting from such action or processes, such as
ignorance, false belief, wishful thinking, unjustified opinions, or lack of
clear awareness. Thus, parents tend to exaggerate the virtues of their
children; lovers disregard clear signs of unreciprocated affection; overeaters
rationalize away the need to diet; patients dying of cancer pretend to
themselves that their health is improving. In some contexts ‘self-deception’ is
neutral and implies no criticism. Deceiving oneself can even be desirable,
generating a vital lie that promotes happiness or the ability to cope with
difficulties. In other contexts ‘self-deception’ has negative connotations,
suggesting bad faith, false consciousness, or what Joseph Butler called “inner
hypocrisy” the refusal to acknowledge
our wrongdoing, character flaws, or onerous responsibilities. Existentialist
philosophers, like Kierkegaard, Heidegger, and most notably Sartre Being and
Nothingness, 3, denounced self-deception as an inauthentic dishonest, cowardly
refusal to confront painful though significant truths, especially about
freedom, responsibility, and death. Herbert Fingarette, however, argued that
self-deception is morally ambiguous
neither clearly blameworthy nor clearly faultless because of how it erodes capacities for
acting rationally Self-Deception, 9. The idea of intentionally deceiving oneself
seems paradoxical. In deceiving other people I usually know a truth that guides
me as I state the opposite falsehood, intending thereby to mislead them into
believing the falsehood. Five difficulties seem to prevent me from doing
anything like that to myself. 1 With interpersonal deception, one person knows
something that another person does not. Yet self-deceivers know the truth all
along, and so it seems they cannot use it to make themselves ignorant. One
solution is that self-deception occurs over time, with the initial knowledge
becoming gradually eroded. Or perhaps selfdeceivers only suspect rather than
know the truth, and then disregard relevant evidence. 2 If consciousness
implies awareness of one’s own conscious acts, then a conscious intention to
deceive myself would be self-defeating, for I would remain conscious of the
truth I wish to flee. Sartre’s solution was to view self-deception as
spontaneous and not explicitly reflected upon. Freud’s solution was to conceive
of self-deception as unconscious repression. 3 It seems that self-deceivers
believe a truth that they simultaneously get themselves not to believe, but how
is that possible? Perhaps they keep one of two conflicting beliefs unconscious
or not fully conscious. 4 Self-deception suggests willfully creating beliefs,
but that seems impossible since beliefs cannot voluntarily be chosen. Perhaps
beliefs can be indirectly manipulated by selectively ignoring and attending to
evidence. 5 It seems that one part of a person the deceiver manipulates another
part the victim, but such extreme splits suggest multiple personality disorders
rather than self-deception. Perhaps we are composed of “subselves” relatively unified clusters of elements in
the personality. Or perhaps at this point we should jettison interpersonal
deception as a model for understanding self-deception. .
auto-determination -- self-determination, the autonomy
possessed by a community when it is politically independent; in a strict sense,
territorial sovereignty. Within international law, the principle of
self-determination appears to grant every people a right to be
self-determining, but there is controversy over its interpretation. Applied to
established states, the principle calls for recognition of state sovereignty
and non-intervention in internal affairs. By providing for the
self-determination of subordinate communities, however, it can generate demands
for secession that conflict with existing claims of sovereignty. Also, what
non-self-governing groups qualify as beneficiaries? The national interpretation
of the principle treats cultural or national units as the proper claimants,
whereas the regional interpretation confers the right of self-determination
upon the populations of well-defined regions regardless of cultural or national
affiliations. This difference reflects the roots of the principle in the
doctrines of nationalism and popular sovereignty, respectively, but complicates
its application.
self-evidence, the property of being self-evident. Only
true propositions or truths are self-evident, though false propositions can
appear to be self-evident. It is widely held that a true proposition is
self-evident if and only if one would be justified in believing it if one
adequately understood it. Some would also require that self-evident
propositions are known if believed on the basis of such an understanding. Some
self-evident propositions are obvious, such as the proposition that all stags
are male, but others are not, since it may take considerable reflection to achieve
an adequate understanding of them. That slavery is wrong and that there is no
knowledge of falsehoods are perhaps examples of the latter. Not all obvious
propositions are self-evident, e.g., it is obvious that a stone will fall if
dropped, but adequate understanding of that claim does not by itself justify
one in believing it. An obvious proposition is one that immediately seems true
for anyone who adequately understands it, but its obviousness may rest on
wellknown and commonly accepted empirical facts, not on understanding. All
analytic propositions are self-evident but not all self-evident propositions
are analytic. The propositions that if A is older than B, then B is younger
than A, and that no object can be red and green all over at the same time and
in the same respects, are arguably self-evident but not analytic. All
self-evident propositions are necessary, for one could not be justified in
believing a contingent proposition simply in virtue of understanding it.
However, not all necessary propositions are self-evident, e.g., that water is
H2O and that temperature is the measure of the molecular activity in substances
are necessary but not self-evident. A proposition can appear to be selfevident
even though it is not. For instance, the proposition that all unmarried adult
males are bachelors will appear self-evident to many until they consider that
the pope is such a male. A proposition may appear self-evident to some but not
to others, even though it must either have or lack the property of being self-evident.
Self-evident propositions are knowable non-empirically, or a priori, but some
propositions knowable a priori are not self-evident, e.g., certain conclusions
of long and difficult chains of mathematical reasoning.
self-presenting, in the philosophy of Meinong, having
the ability common to all mental
states to be immediately present to our
thought. In Meinong’s view, no mental state can be presented to our thought in
any other way e.g., indirectly, via a
Lockean “idea of reflection.” The only way to apprehend a mental state is to
experience or “live through” it. The experience involved in the apprehension of
an external object has thus a double presentational function: 1 via its
“content” it presents the object to our thought; 2 as its own “quasi-content”
it presents itself immediately to our thought. In the contemporary era,
Roderick Chisholm has based his account of empirical knowledge in part on a
related concept of the self-presenting. In Chisholm’s sense the definition of which we omit here all self-presenting states are mental, but
not conversely; for instance, being depressed because of the death of one’s
spouse would not be self-presenting. In Chisholm’s epistemology,
self-presenting states are a source of certainty in the following way: if F is
a self-presenting state, then to be certain that one is in state F it is
sufficient that one is, and believes oneself to be in state F.
auto-phoric -- self-referential incoherence, an
internal defect of an assertion or theory, which it possesses provided that a
it establishes some requirement that must be met by assertions or theories, b
it is itself subject to this requirement, and c it fails to meet the
requirement. The most famous example is logical positivism’s meaning criterion,
which requires that all meaningful assertions be either tautological or
empirically verifiable, yet is itself neither. A possible early example is
found in Hume, whose own writings might have been consigned to the flames had
librarians followed his counsel to do so with volumes that contain neither
“abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number” nor “experimental reasoning
concerning matter of fact and existence.” Bold defiance was shown by Vitters,
who, realizing that the propositions of the Tractatus did not “picture” the
world, advised the reader to “throw away the ladder after he has climbed up
it.” An epistemological example is furnished by any foundationalist theory that
establishes criteria for rational acceptability that the theory itself cannot
meet.
self-reproducing automaton, a formal model of
self-reproduction of a kind introduced by von Neumann. He worked with an
intuitive robot model and then with a well-defined cellular automaton model.
Imagine a class of robotic automata made of robot parts and operating in an
environment of such parts. There are computer parts switches, memory elements,
wires, input-output parts sensing elements, display elements, action parts
grasping and moving elements, joining and cutting elements, and straight bars
to maintain structure and to employ in a storage tape. There are also energy
sources that enable the robots to operate and move around. These five
categories of parts are sufficient for the construction of robots that can make
objects of various kinds, including other robots. These parts also clearly
suffice for making a robot version of any finite automaton. Sensing and acting
parts can then be added to this robot so that it can make an indefinitely
expandable storage tape from straight bars. A “blank tape” consists of bars
joined in sequence, and the robot stores information on this tape by attaching
bars or not at the junctions. If its finite automaton part can execute programs
and is sufficiently powerful, such a robot is a universal computing robot cf. a
universal Turing machine. A universal computing robot can be augmented to form
a universal constructing robot a robot
that can construct any robot, given its description. Let r be any robot with an
indefinitely expandable tape, let Fr be the description of its finite part, and
let Tr be the information on its tape. Now take a universal computing robot and
augment it with sensing and acting devices and with programs so that when Fr
followed by Tr is written on its tape, this augmented universal computer
performs as follows. First, it reads the description Fr, finds the needed
parts, and constructs the finite part of r. Second, it makes a blank tape,
attaches it to the finite part of r, and then copies the information Tr from
its own tape onto the new tape. This augmentation of a universal computing
robot is a universal constructor. For when it starts with the information Fr,Tr
written on its tape, it will construct a copy of r with Tr on its tape. Robot
self-reproduction results from applying the universal constructor to itself.
Modify the universal constructor slightly so that when only a description Fr is
written on its tape, it constructs the finite part of r and then attaches a
tape with Fr written on it. Call this version of the universal constructor Cu.
Now place Cu’s description FCu on its own tape and start it up. Cu first reads
this description and constructs a copy of the finite part of itself in an empty
region of the cellular space. Then it adds a blank tape to the new construction
and copies FCu onto it. Hence Cu with FCu on its tape has produced another copy
of Cu with FCu on its tape. This is automaton self-reproduction. This robot
model of self-reproduction is very general. To develop the logic of
self-reproduction further, von Neumann first extended the concept of a finite
automaton to that of an infinite cellular automaton consisting of an array or
“space” of cells, each cell containing the same finite automaton. He chose an
infinite checkerboard array for modeling self-reproduction, and he specified a
particular twenty-nine-state automaton for each square cell. Each automaton is
connected directly to its four contiguous neighbors, and communication between
neighbors takes one or two time-steps. The twenty-nine states of a cell fall
into three categories. There is a blank state to represent the passivity of an
empty area. There are twelve states for switching, storage, and communication,
from which any finite automaton can be constructed in a sufficiently large
region of cells. And there are sixteen states for simulating the activities of
construction and destruction. Von Neumann chose these twenty-nine states in
such a way that an area of non-blank cells could compute and grow, i.e.,
activate a path of cells out to a blank region and convert the cells of that
region into a cellular automaton. A specific cellular automaton is embedded in
this space by the selection of the initial states of a finite area of cells,
all other cells being left blank. A universal computer consists of a
sufficiently powerful finite automaton with a tape. The tape is an indefinitely
long row of cells in which bits are represented by two different cell states.
The finite automaton accesses these cells by means of a construction arm that
it extends back and forth in rows of cells contiguous to the tape. When
activated, this finite automaton will execute programs stored on its tape. A
universal constructor results from augmenting the universal computer cf. the
robot model. Another construction arm is added, together with a finite automaton
controller to operate it. The controller sends signals into the arm to extend
it out to a blank region of the cellular space, to move around that region, and
to change the states of cells in that region. After the universal constructor
has converted the region into a cellular automaton, it directs the construction
arm to activate the new automaton and then withdraw from it. Cellular automaton
selfreproduction results from applying the universal constructor to itself, as
in the robot model. Cellular automata are now studied extensively by humans
working interactively with computers as abstract models of both physical and
organic systems. See Arthur W. Burks, “Von Neumann’s Self-Reproducing
Automata,” in Papers of John von Neumann on Computers and Computer Theory,
edited by William Aspray and Arthur Burks, 7. The study of artificial life is
an outgrowth of computer simulations of cellular automata and related automata.
Cellular automata organizations are sometimes used in highly parallel
computers.
sellars: philosopher, son of Roy Wood Sellars, and one of the
great systematic philosophers of the century. His most influential and
representative works are “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind” 6 and
“Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man” 0. The Sellarsian system may be
outlined as follows. The myth of the given. Thesis 1: Classical empiricism
foundationalism maintains that our belief in the commonsense, objective world
of physical objects is ultimately justified only by the way that world presents
itself in sense experience. Thesis 2: It also typically maintains that sense
experience a is not part of that world and b is not a form of conceptual
cognition like thinking or believing. Thesis 3: From 1 and 2a classical
empiricism concludes that our knowledge of the physical world is inferred from
sense experience. Thesis 4: Since inferences derive knowledge from knowledge,
sense experience itself must be a form of knowledge. Theses 14 collectively are
the doctrine of the given. Each thesis taken individually is plausible.
However, Sellars argues that 2b and 4 are incompatible if, as he thinks,
knowledge is a kind of conceptual cognition. Concluding that the doctrine of
the given is false, he maintains that classical empiricism is a myth. The
positive system. From an analysis of theoretical explanation in the physical
sciences, Sellars concludes that postulating theoretical entities is justified
only if theoretical laws nomological
generalizations referring to theoretical entities are needed to explain particular observable
phenomena for which explanation in terms of exceptionless observation laws is
unavailable. While rejecting any classical empiricist interpretation of
observation, Sellars agrees that some account of non-inferential knowledge is
required to make sense of theoretical explanation thus conceived. He thinks
that utterances made in direct response to sensory stimuli observational
reports count as non-inferential knowledge when a they possess authority, i.e.,
occur in conditions ensuring that they reliably indicate some physical property
say, shape in the environment and are accepted by the linguistic community as
possessing this quality; and b the utterer has justified belief that they
possess this authority. Sellars claims that some perceptual conditions induce
ordinary people to make observation reports inconsistent with established
explanatory principles of the commonsense framework. We thus might tend to
report spontaneously that an object is green seen in daylight and blue seen
indoors, and yet think it has not undergone any process that could change its
color. Sellars sees in such conflicting tendencies vestiges of a primitive
conceptual framework whose tensions have been partially resolved by introducing
the concept of sense experiences. These experiences count as theoretical
entities, since they are postulated to account for observational phenomena for
which no exceptionless observation laws exist. This example may serve as a
paradigm for a process of theoretical explanation occurring in the framework of
commonsense beliefs that Sellars calls the manifest image, a process that
itself is a model for his theory of the rational dynamics of conceptual change
in both the manifest image and in science
the scientific image. Because the actual process of conceptual evolution
in Homo sapiens may not fit this pattern of rational dynamics, Sellars treats
these dynamics as occurring within certain hypothetical ideal histories myths
of the way in which, from certain conceptually primitive beginnings, one might
have come to postulate the requisite theoretical explanations. The manifest
image, like the proto-theories from which it arose, is itself subject to
various tensions ultimately resolved in the scientific image. Because this
latter image contains a metaphysical theory of material objects and persons
that is inconsistent with that of its predecessor framework, Sellars regards
the manifest image as replaced by its successor. In terms of the Peircean
conception of truth that Sellars endorses, the scientific image is the only
true image. In this sense Sellars is a scientific realist. There is, however,
also an important sense in which Sellars is not a scientific realist: despite
discrediting classical empiricism, he thinks that the intrinsic nature of sense
experience gives to conceptualization more than simply sensory stimulus yet
less than the content of knowledge claims. Inspired by Kant, Sellars treats the
manifest image as a Kantian phenomenal world, a world that exists as a
cognitive construction which, though lacking ideal factual truth, is guided in
part by intrinsic features of sense experience. This is not analytic
phenomenalism, which Sellars rejects. Moreover, the special methodological role
for sense experience has effects even within the scientific image itself.
Theories of mind, perception, and semantics. Mind: In the manifest image
thoughts are private episodes endowed with intentionality. Called inner speech,
they are theoretical entities whose causal and intentional properties are modeled,
respectively, on inferential and semantic properties of overt speech. They are
introduced within a behaviorist proto-theory, the Rylean framework, to provide
a theoretical explanation for behavior normally accompanied by linguistically
overt reasons. Perception: In the manifest image sense experiences are sense
impressions states of persons modeled on
two-dimensional, colored physical replicas and introduced in the theoretical
language of the adverbial theory of perception to explain why it can look as if
some perceptible quality is present when it is not. Semantics: The meaning of a
simple predicate p in a language L is the role played in L by p defined in
terms of three sets of linguistic rules: language entry rules, intralinguistic
rules, and language departure rules. This account also supports a nominalist
treatment of abstract entities. Identification of a role for a token of p in L
can be effected demonstratively in the speaker’s language by saying that p in L
is a member of the class of predicates playing the same role as a demonstrated
predicate. Thus a speaker of English might say that ‘rot’ in G. plays the
semantic role ‘red’ has in English. Sellars sees science and metaphysics as
autonomous strands in a single web of philosophical inquiry. Sellarsianism thus
presents an important alternative to the view that what is fundamentally real
is determined by the logical structure of scientific language alone. Sellars
also sees ordinary language as expressing a commonsense framework of beliefs
constituting a kind of proto-theory with its own methods, metaphysics, and
theoretical entities. Thus, he also presents an important alternative to the
view that philosophy concerns not what is ultimately real, but what words like
‘real’ ultimately mean in ordinary language.
semantic: Grice was careful with what he felt was an abuse of
‘semantic’ – v. Evans: “Meaning and truth: essayis in semantics.” “Well, that’s
what ‘meaning’ means, right?” The semantics is more reated to the signatum than
to the significatum. The Grecians did not have anything remotely similar to the
significatum, which is all about the making (facere) of a sign (as in Grice’s
example of the handwave). This is the meaning Grice gives to ‘semantics.’ There
is no need for the handwave to be part of a system of communication, or have
syntactic structure, or be ‘arbitrary.’ Still, one thing is communicated from
the emissor to his recipient, and that is all count. “I know the route” is the
message, or “I will leave you soon.” The handwave may be ambiguous. Grice is
aware that formalists like Hilbert and Gentzen think that they can do without
semantics – but as long as there is something ‘transmitted,’ or ‘messaged,’ it
cannot. In the one-off predicament, Emissor E emits x and communicates that p.
Since an intention with a content involving a psychological state is involved
and attached, even in a one-off, to ‘x,’ we can legitimately say the scenario
may be said to describe a ‘semantic’ phenomenon. Grice would freely use
‘semantic,’ and the root for ‘semantics,’ that Grice does use, involves the
richest root of all Grecian roots: the ‘semion.’ Liddell and Scott have “τό
σημεῖον,” Ion. σημήϊον , Dor. σα_μήϊον IG12(3).452 (Thera, iv B.C.), σα_μεῖον
IPE12.352.25 (Chersonesus, ii B.C.), IG5(1).1390.16 (Andania, i B.C.), σα_μᾶον
CIG5168 (Cyrene); = σῆμα in all senses, and more common in Prose, but never in
Hom. or Hes.; and which they render as “mark by which a thing is known,”
Hdt.2.38;” they also have “τό σῆμα,” Dor. σᾶμα Berl.Sitzb.1927.161 (Cyrene),
etc.; which they render as “sign, mark, token,” “ Il.10.466, 23.326, Od.19.250,
etc.” Grice lectured not only on Cat. But the next, De Int. As Arsitotle puts
it, an expression is a symbol (symbolon) or sign (semeion) of an affections or
impression (pathematon) of the soul (psyche). An affection of the soul, of
which a word is primarily a sign, are
the same for the whole of mankind, as is also objects (pragmaton) of which the
affections is a representation or likenes, image, or copiy (homoiomaton). [De Int., 1.16a4] while Grice is NOT concerned about the
semantics of utterers meaning (how could he, when he analyses means
in terms of intends , he is about
the semantics of expression-meaning. Grices
second stage (expression meaing) of his programme about meaning begins with
specifications of means as applied to x, a token of X. He is having Tarski and
Davidson in their elaborations of schemata like ‘p’ ‘means’ that p. ‘Snow
is white’ ‘means’ that snow is white, and stuff! Grice was especially concerned
with combinatories, for both unary and dyadic operators, and with multiple
quantifications within a first-order predicate calculus with identity. Since in
Grice’s initial elaboration on meaning he relies on Stevenson, it is worth
exploring how ‘semantics’ and ‘semiotics’ were interpreted by Peirce and the
emotivists. Stevenson’s main source is however in the other place, though,
under Stevenson. Semantics – communication – H. P. Grice, “Implicaturum and
Explicature: The basis of communication” – “Communication and Intention” --
philosophy of language, the philosophical study of natural language and its workings,
particularly of linguistic meaning and the use of language. A natural language
is any one of the thousands of various tongues that have developed historically
among populations of human beings and have been used for everyday purposes including English, , Swahili, and Latin as opposed to the formal and other artificial
“languages” invented by mathematicians, logicians, and computer scientists,
such as arithmetic, the predicate calculus, and LISP or COBOL. There are
intermediate cases, e.g., Esperanto, Pig Latin, and the sort of “philosophese”
that mixes English words with logical symbols. Contemporary philosophy of
language centers on the theory of meaning, but also includes the theory of
reference, the theory of truth, philosophical pragmatics, and the philosophy of
linguistics. The main question addressed by the theory of meaning is: In virtue
of what are certain physical marks or noises meaningful linguistic expressions,
and in virtue of what does any particular set of marks or noises have the distinctive
meaning it does? A theory of meaning should also give a comprehensive account
of the “meaning phenomena,” or general semantic properties of sentences:
synonymy, ambiguity, entailment, and the like. Some theorists have thought to
express these questions and issues in terms of languageneutral items called
propositions: ‘In virtue of what does a particular set of marks or noises
express the proposition it does?’; cf. ‘ “La neige est blanche” expresses the
proposition that snow is white’, and ‘Synonymous sentences express the same
proposition’. On this view, to understand a sentence is to “grasp” the
proposition expressed by that sentence. But the explanatory role and even the
existence of such entities are disputed. It has often been maintained that certain
special sentences are true solely in virtue of their meanings and/or the
meanings of their component expressions, without regard to what the
nonlinguistic world is like ‘No bachelor is married’; ‘If a thing is blue it is
colored’. Such vacuously true sentences are called analytic. However, Quine and
others have disputed whether there really is such a thing as analyticity.
Philosophers have offered a number of sharply competing hypotheses as to the
nature of meaning, including: 1 the referential view that words mean by
standing for things, and that a sentence means what it does because its parts
correspond referentially to the elements of an actual or possible state of
affairs in the world; 2 ideational or mentalist theories, according to which
meanings are ideas or other psychological phenomena in people’s minds; 3 “use”
theories, inspired by Vitters and to a lesser extent by J. L. Austin: a
linguistic expression’s “meaning” is its conventionally assigned role as a
game-piece-like token used in one or more existing social practices; 4 H. P.
Grice’s hypothesis that a sentence’s or word’s meaning is a function of what
audience response a typical utterer would intend to elicit in uttering it. 5
inferential role theories, as developed by Wilfrid Sellars out of Carnap’s and
Vitters’s views: a sentence’s meaning is specified by the set of sentences from
which it can correctly be inferred and the set of those which can be inferred
from it Sellars himself provided for “language-entry” and “language-exit” moves
as partly constitutive of meaning, in addition to inferences; 6
verificationism, the view that a sentence’s meaning is the set of possible
experiences that would confirm it or provide evidence for its truth; 7 the
truth-conditional theory: a sentence’s meaning is the distinctive condition
under which it is true, the situation or state of affairs that, if it obtained,
would make the sentence true; 8 the null hypothesis, or eliminativist view,
that “meaning” is a myth and there is no such thing a radical claim that can stem either from
Quine’s doctrine of the indeterminacy of translation or from eliminative
materialism in the philosophy of mind. Following the original work of Carnap,
Alonzo Church, Hintikka, and Richard Montague in the 0s, the theory of meaning has
made increasing use of “possible worlds”based intensional logic as an
analytical apparatus. Propositions sentence meanings considered as entities,
and truth conditions as in 7 above, are now commonly taken to be structured
sets of possible worlds e.g., the set of
worlds in which Aristotle’s maternal grandmother hates broccoli. And the
structure imposed on such a set, corresponding to the intuitive constituent
structure of a proposition as the concepts ‘grandmother’ and ‘hate’ are
constituents of the foregoing proposition, accounts for the meaning-properties
of sentences that express the proposition. Theories of meaning can also be
called semantics, as in “Gricean semantics” or “Verificationist semantics,”
though the term is sometimes restricted to referential and/or truth-conditional
theories, which posit meaning-constitutive relations between words and the
nonlinguistic world. Semantics is often contrasted with syntax, the structure
of grammatically permissible ordering relations between words and other words
in well-formed sentences, and with pragmatics, the rules governing the use of
meaningful expressions in particular speech contexts; but linguists have found
that semantic phenomena cannot be kept purely separate either from syntactic or
from pragmatic phenomena. In a still more specialized usage, linguistic
semantics is the detailed study typically within the truth-conditional format
of particular types of construction in particular natural languages, e.g.,
belief-clauses in English or adverbial phrases in Kwakiutl. Linguistic
semantics in that sense is practiced by some philosophers of language, by some
linguists, and occasionally by both working together. Montague grammar and
situation semantics are common formats for such work, both based on intensional
logic. The theory of referenceis pursued whether or not one accepts either the
referential or the truthconditional theory of meaning. Its main question is: In
virtue of what does a linguistic expression designate one or more things in the
world? Prior to theorizing and defining of technical uses, ‘designate’,
‘denote’, and ‘refer’ are used interchangeably. Denoting expressions are
divided into singular terms, which purport to designate particular individual
things, and general terms, which can apply to more than one thing at once.
Singular terms include proper names ‘Cindy’, ‘Bangladesh’, definite
descriptions ‘my brother’, ‘the first baby born in the New World’, and singular
pronouns of various types ‘this’, ‘you’, ‘she’. General terms include common nouns
‘horse’, ‘trash can’, mass terms ‘water’, ‘graphite’, and plural pronouns
‘they’, ‘those’. The twentieth century’s dominant theory of reference has been
the description theory, the view that linguistic terms refer by expressing
descriptive features or properties, the referent being the item or items that
in fact possess those properties. For example, a definite description does that
directly: ‘My brother’ denotes whatever person does have the property of being
my brother. According to the description theory of proper names, defended most
articulately by Russell, such names express identifying properties indirectly
by abbreviating definite descriptions. A general term such as ‘horse’ was
thought of as expressing a cluster of properties distinctive of horses; and so
forth. But the description theory came under heavy attack in the late 0s, from
Keith Donnellan, Kripke, and Putnam, and was generally abandoned on each of
several grounds, in favor of the causal-historical theory of reference. The
causal-historical idea is that a particular use of a linguistic expression
denotes by being etiologically grounded in the thing or group that is its
referent; a historical causal chain of a certain shape leads backward in time
from the act of referring to the referents. More recently, problems with the
causal-historical theory as originally formulated have led researchers to
backpedal somewhat and incorporate some features of the description theory.
Other views of reference have been advocated as well, particularly analogues of
some of the theories of meaning listed above
chiefly 26 and 8. Modal and propositional-attitude contexts create
special problems in the theory of reference, for referring expressions seem to
alter their normal semantic behavior when they occur within such contexts. Much
ink has been spilled over the question of why and how the substitution of a
term for another term having exactly the same referent can change the
truth-value of a containing modal or propositional-attitude sentence.
Interestingly, the theory of truth historically predates articulate study of
meaning or of reference, for philosophers have always sought the nature of
truth. It has often been thought that a sentence is true in virtue of
expressing a true belief, truth being primarily a property of beliefs rather
than of linguistic entities; but the main theories of truth have also been
applied to sentences directly. The correspondence theory maintains that a
sentence is true in virtue of its elements’ mirroring a fact or actual state of
affairs. The coherence theory instead identifies truth as a relation of the
true sentence to other sentences, usually an epistemic relation. Pragmatic
theories have it that truth is a matter either of practical utility or of
idealized epistemic warrant. Deflationary views, such as the traditional
redundancy theory and D. Grover, J. Camp, and N. D. Belnap’s prosentential
theory, deny that truth comes to anything more important or substantive than
what is already codified in a recursive Tarskian truth-definition for a
language. Pragmatics studies the use of language in context, and the
context-dependence of various aspects of linguistic interpretation. First, one
and the same sentence can express different meanings or propositions from
context to context, owing to ambiguity or to indexicality or both. An ambiguous
sentence has more than one meaning, either because one of its component words
has more than one meaning as ‘bank’ has or because the sentence admits of more
than one possible syntactic analysis ‘Visiting doctors can be tedious’, ‘The
mouse tore up the street’. An indexical sentence can change in truth-value from
context to context owing to the presence of an element whose reference
fluctuates, such as a demonstrative pronoun ‘She told him off yesterday’, ‘It’s
time for that meeting now’. One branch of pragmatics investigates how context
determines a single propositional meaning for a sentence on a particular
occasion of that sentence’s use. Speech act theory is a second branch of
pragmatics that presumes the propositional or “locutionary” meanings of
utterances and studies what J. L. Austin called the illocutionary forces of
those utterances, the distinctive types of linguistic act that are performed by
the speaker in making them. E.g., in uttering ‘I will be there tonight’, a
speaker might be issuing a warning, uttering a threat, making a promise, or
merely offering a prediction, depending on conventional and other social
features of the situation. A crude test of illocutionary force is the “hereby” criterion:
one’s utterance has the force of, say, a warning, if it could fairly have been
paraphrased by the corresponding “explicitly performative” sentence beginning
‘I hereby warn you that . . .’..Speech act theory interacts to some extent with
semantics, especially in the case of explicit performatives, and it has some
fairly dramatic syntactic effects as well. A third branch of pragmatics not
altogether separate from the second is the theory of conversation or theory of implicaturum,
founded by H. P. Grice. Grice notes that sentences, when uttered in particular
contexts, often generate “implications” that are not logical consequences of
those sentences ‘Is Jones a good philosopher?’
’He has very neat handwriting’. Such implications can usually be identified
as what the speaker meant in uttering her sentence; thus for that reason and
others, what Grice calls utterer’s meaning can diverge sharply from
sentence-meaning or “timeless” meaning. To explain those non-logical
implications, Grice offered a now widely accepted theory of conversational implicaturum.
Conversational implicaturums arise from the interaction of the sentence uttered
with mutually shared background assumptions and certain principles of efficient
and cooperative conversation. The philosophy of linguistics studies the
academic discipline of linguistics, particularly theoretical linguistics
considered as a science or purported science; it examines methodology and
fundamental assumptions, and also tries to incorporate linguists’ findings into
the rest of philosophy of language. Theoretical linguistics concentrates on
syntax, and took its contemporary form in the 0s under Zellig Harris and
Chomsky: it seeks to describe each natural language in terms of a generative
grammar for that language, i.e., a set of recursive rules for combining words
that will generate all and only the “well-formed strings” or grammatical
sentences of that language. The set must be finite and the rules recursive
because, while our informationprocessing resources for recognizing grammatical
strings as such are necessarily finite being subagencies of our brains, there
is no limit in any natural language either to the length of a single
grammatical sentence or to the number of grammatical sentences; a small device
must have infinite generative and parsing capacity. Many grammars work by
generating simple “deep structures” a kind of tree diagram, and then producing
multiple “surface structures” as variants of those deep structures, by means of
rules that rearrange their parts. The surface structures are syntactic parsings
of natural-language sentences, and the deep structures from which they derive
encode both basic grammatical relations between the sentences’ major
constituents and, on some theories, the sentences’ main semantic properties as
well; thus, sentences that share a deep structure will share some fundamental
grammatical properties and all or most of their semantics. As Paul Ziff and
Davidson saw in the 0s, the foregoing syntactic problem and its solution had
semantic analogues. From small resources, human speakers understand compute the meanings of arbitrarily long and novel sentences without
limit, and almost instantaneously. This ability seems to require semantic
compositionality, the thesis that the meaning of a sentence is a function of
the meanings of its semantic primitives or smallest meaningful parts, built up
by way of syntactic compounding. Compositionality also seems to be required by
learnability, since a normal child can learn an infinitely complex dialect in
at most two years, but must learn semantic primitives one at a time. A grammar
for a natural language is commonly taken to be a piece of psychology, part of
an explanation of speakers’ verbal abilities and behavior. As such, however, it
is a considerable idealization: it is a theory of speakers’ linguistic
“competence” rather than of their actual verbal performance. The latter
distinction is required by the fact that speakers’ considered, reflective
judgments of grammatical correctness do not line up very well with the class of
expressions that actually are uttered and understood unreflectively by those
same speakers. Some grammatical sentences are too hard for speakers to parse
quickly; some are too long to finish parsing at all; speakers commonly utter what
they know to be formally ungrammatical strings; and real speech is usually
fragmentary, interspersed with vocalizations, false starts, and the like.
Actual departures from formal grammaticality are ascribed by linguists to
“performance limitations,” i.e., psychological factors such as memory failure,
weak computational capacity, or heedlessness; thus, actual verbal behavior is
to be explained as resulting from the perturbation of competence by performance
limitations. Refs.: The main sources are
his lectures on language and reality – part of them repr. in WOW. The keywords
under ‘communication,’ and ‘signification,’ that Grice occasionally uses ‘the
total signification’ of a remark, above, BANC. -- semantic holism, a
metaphysical thesis about the nature of representation on which the meaning of
a symbol is relative to the entire system of representations containing it.
Thus, a linguistic expression can have meaning only in the context of a
language; a hypothesis can have significance only in the context of a theory; a
concept can have intentionality only in the context of the belief system.
Holism about content has profoundly influenced virtually every aspect of
contemporary theorizing about language and mind, not only in philosophy, but in
linguistics, literary theory, artificial intelligence, psychology, and
cognitive science. Contemporary semantic holists include Davidson, Quine,
Gilbert Harman, Hartry Field, and Searle. Because semantic holism is a
metaphysical and not a semantic thesis, two theorists might agree about the
semantic facts but disagree about semantic holism. So, e.g., nothing in
Tarski’s writings determines whether the semantic facts expressed by the
theorems of an absolute truth semantic atomism semantic holism 829 829 theory are holistic or not. Yet
Davidson, a semantic holist, argued that the correct form for a semantic theory
for a natural language L is an absolute truth theory for L. Semantic theories,
like other theories, need not wear their metaphysical commitments on their sleeves.
Holism has some startling consequences. Consider this. Franklin D. Roosevelt
who died when the United States still had just forty-eight states did not
believe there were fifty states, but I do; semantic holism says that what
‘state’ means in our mouths depends on the totality of our beliefs about
states, including, therefore, our beliefs about how many states there are. It
seems to follow that he and I must mean different things by ‘state’; hence, if
he says “Alaska is not a state” and I say “Alaska is a state” we are not
disagreeing. This line of argument leads to such surprising declarations as
that natural langauges are not, in general, intertranslatable Quine, Saussure;
that there may be no fact of the matter about the meanings of texts Putnam, Derrida;
and that scientific theories that differ in their basic postulates are
“empirically incommensurable” Paul Feyerabend, Kuhn. For those who find these
consequences of semantic holism unpalatable, there are three mutually exclusive
responses: semantic atomism, semantic molecularism, or semantic nihilism.
Semantic atomists hold that the meaning of any representation linguistic,
mental, or otherwise is not determined by the meaning of any other
representation. Historically, Anglo- philosophers in the eighteenth and
nineteenth centuries thought that an idea of an X was about X’s in virtue of
this idea’s physically resembling X’s. Resemblance theories are no longer
thought viable, but a number of contemporary semantic atomists still believe
that the basic semantic relation is between a concept and the things to which
it applies, and not one among concepts themselves. These philosophers include
Dretske, Dennis Stampe, Fodor, and Ruth Millikan. Semantic molecularism, like
semantic holism, holds that the meaning of a representation in a language L is
determined by its relationships to the meanings of other expressions in L, but,
unlike holism, not by its relationships to every other expression in L.
Semantic molecularists are committed to the view, contrary to Quine, that for
any expression e in a language L there is an in-principle way of distinguishing
between those representations in L the meanings of which determine the meaning
of e and those representations in L the meanings of which do not determine the
meaning of e. Traditionally, this inprinciple delimitation is supported by an
analytic/synthetic distinction. Those representations in L that are
meaning-constituting of e are analytically connected to e and those that are
not meaning-constituting are synthetically connected to e. Meaning molecularism
seems to be the most common position among those philosophers who reject
holism. Contemporary meaning molecularists include Michael Devitt, Dummett, Ned
Block, and John Perry. Semantic nihilism is perhaps the most radical response
to the consequences of holism. It is the view that, strictly speaking, there
are no semantic properties. Strictly speaking, there are no mental states;
words lack meanings. At least for scientific purposes and perhaps for other
purposes as well we must abandon the notion that people are moral or rational
agents and that they act out of their beliefs and desires. Semantic nihilists
include among their ranks Patricia and Paul Churchland, Stephen Stich, Dennett,
and, sometimes, Quine. -- semantic
paradoxes, a collection of paradoxes involving the semantic notions of truth,
predication, and definability. The liar paradox is the oldest and most widely
known of these, having been formulated by Eubulides as an objection to
Aristotle’s correspondence theory of truth. In its simplest form, the liar
paradox arises when we try to assess the truth of a sentence or proposition
that asserts its own falsity, e.g.: A Sentence A is not true. It would seem
that sentence A cannot be true, since it can be true only if what it says is
the case, i.e., if it is not true. Thus sentence A is not true. But then, since
this is precisely what it claims, it would seem to be true. Several alternative
forms of the liar paradox have been given their own names. The postcard paradox,
also known as a liar cycle, envisions a postcard with sentence B on one side
and sentence C on the other: B The sentence on the other side of this card is
true. semantic molecularism semantic paradoxes 830 830 C The sentence on the other side of
this card is false. Here, no consistent assignment of truth-values to the pair
of sentences is possible. In the preface paradox, it is imagined that a book
begins with the claim that at least one sentence in the book is false. This
claim is unproblematically true if some later sentence is false, but if the
remainder of the book contains only truths, the initial sentence appears to be
true if and only if false. The preface paradox is one of many examples of
contingent liars, claims that can either have an unproblematic truth-value or
be paradoxical, depending on the truth-values of various other claims in this
case, the remaining sentences in the book. Related to the preface paradox is
Epimenedes’ paradox: Epimenedes, himself from Crete, is said to have claimed
that all Cretans are liars. This claim is paradoxical if interpreted to mean
that Cretans always lie, or if interpreted to mean they sometimes lie and if no
other claim made by Epimenedes was a lie. On the former interpretation, this is
a simple variation of the liar paradox; on the latter, it is a form of
contingent liar. Other semantic paradoxes include Berry’s paradox, Richard’s
paradox, and Grelling’s paradox. The first two involve the notion of
definability of numbers. Berry’s paradox begins by noting that names or
descriptions of integers consist of finite sequences of syllables. Thus the
three-syllable sequence ‘twenty-five’ names 25, and the seven-syllable sequence
‘the sum of three and seven’ names ten. Now consider the collection of all
sequences of English syllables that are less than nineteen syllables long. Of
these, many are nonsensical ‘bababa’ and some make sense but do not name
integers ‘artichoke’, but some do ‘the sum of three and seven’. Since there are
only finitely many English syllables, there are only finitely many of these
sequences, and only finitely many integers named by them. Berry’s paradox
arises when we consider the eighteen-syllable sequence ‘the smallest integer
not nameable in less than nineteen syllables’. This phrase appears to be a
perfectly well-defined description of an integer. But if the phrase names an
integer n, then n is nameable in less than nineteen syllables, and hence is not
described by the phrase. Richard’s paradox constructs a similarly paradoxical
description using what is known as a diagonal construction. Imagine a list of
all finite sequences of letters of the alphabet plus spaces and punctuation,
ordered as in a dictionary. Prune this list so that it contains only English
definitions of real numbers between 0 and 1. Then consider the definition: “Let
r be the real number between 0 and 1 whose kth decimal place is if the kth decimal place of the number named
by the kth member of this list is 1, and 0 otherwise’. This description seems
to define a real number that must be different from any number defined on the
list. For example, r cannot be defined by the 237th member of the list, because
r will differ from that number in at least its 237th decimal place. But if it
indeed defines a real number between 0 and 1, then this description should
itself be on the list. Yet clearly, it cannot define a number different from
the number defined by itself. Apparently, the definition defines a real number
between 0 and 1 if and only if it does not appear on the list of such
definitions. Grelling’s paradox, also known as the paradox of heterologicality,
involves two predicates defined as follows. Say that a predicate is
“autological” if it applies to itself. Thus ‘polysyllabic’ and ‘short’ are
autological, since ‘polysyllabic’ is polysyllabic, and ‘short’ is short. In
contrast, a predicate is “heterological” if and only if it is not autological.
The question is whether the predicate ‘heterological’ is heterological. If our
answer is yes, then ‘heterological’ applies to itself and so is autological, not heterological. But
if our answer is no, then it does not apply to itself and so is heterological, once again
contradicting our answer. The semantic paradoxes have led to important work in
both logic and the philosophy of language, most notably by Russell and Tarski.
Russell developed the ramified theory of types as a unified treatment of all
the semantic paradoxes. Russell’s theory of types avoids the paradoxes by
introducing complex syntactic conditions on formulas and on the definition of
new predicates. In the resulting language, definitions like those used in
formulating Berry’s and Richard’s paradoxes turn out to be ill-formed, since
they quantify over collections of expressions that include themselves,
violating what Russell called the vicious circle principle. The theory of types
also rules out, on syntactic grounds, predicates that apply to themselves, or
to larger expressions containing those very same predicates. In this way, the
liar paradox and Grelling’s paradox cannot be constructed within a language
conforming to the theory of types. Tarski’s attention to the liar paradox made
two fundamental contributions to logic: his development of semantic techniques
for defining the truth predicate for formalized languages and his proof of
Tarski’s theorem. Tarskian semantics avoids the liar paradox by starting with a
formal language, call it L, in which no semantic notions are expressible, and
hence in which the liar paradox cannot be formulated. Then using another language,
known as the metalanguage, Tarski applies recursive techniques to define the
predicate true-in-L, which applies to exactly the true sentences of the
original language L. The liar paradox does not arise in the metalanguage,
because the sentence D Sentence D is not true-in-L. is, if expressible in the
metalanguage, simply true. It is true because D is not a sentence of L, and so
a fortiori not a true sentence of L. A truth predicate for the metalanguage can
then be defined in yet another language, the metametalanguage, and so forth,
resulting in a sequence of consistent truth predicates. Tarski’s theorem uses
the liar paradox to prove a significant result in logic. The theorem states
that the truth predicate for the first-order language of arithmetic is not definable
in arithmetic. That is, if we devise a systematic way of representing sentences
of arithmetic by numbers, then it is impossible to define an arithmetical
predicate that applies to all and only those numbers that represent true
sentences of arithmetic. The theorem is proven by showing that if such a
predicate were definable, we could construct a sentence of arithmetic that is
true if and only if it is not true: an arithmetical version of sentence A, the
liar paradox. Both Russell’s and Tarski’s solutions to the semantic paradoxes
have left many philosophers dissatisfied, since the solutions are basically
prescriptions for constructing languages in which the paradoxes do not arise.
But the fact that paradoxes can be avoided in artificially constructed
languages does not itself give a satisfying explanation of what is going wrong
when the paradoxes are encountered in natural language, or in an artificial
language in which they can be formulated. Most recent work on the liar paradox,
following Kripke’s “Outline of a Theory of Truth” 5, looks at languages in
which the paradox can be formulated, and tries to provide a consistent account
of truth that preserves as much as possible of the intuitive notion.
semeiotics: semiological: or is it semiotics? Cf. semiological,
semotic. Since Grice uses ‘philosophical psychology’ and ‘philosopical
biology,’ it may do to use ‘semiology,’ indeed ‘philosophical semiology,’ here.
Oxonian semiotics is unique. Holloway
published his “Language and Intelligence” and everyone was excited. It is best
to see this as Grices psychologism. Grice would rarely use ‘intelligent,’ less
so the more pretentious, ‘intelligence,’ as a keyword. If he is doing it, it is
because what he saw as the misuse of it by Ryle and Holloway. Holloway, a PPE,
is a tutorial fellow in philosophy at All Souls. He acknowledges Ryle as his
mentor. (Holloway also quotes from Austin). Grice was amused that J. N.
Findlay, in his review of Holloway’s essay in “Mind,” compares Holloway to C.
W. Morris, and cares to cite the two relevant essay by Morris: The Foundation
in the theory of signs, and Signs, Language, and Behaviour. Enough for Grice to
feel warmly justified in having chosen another New-World author, Peirce, for
his earlier Oxford seminar. Morris studied under G. H. Mead. But is
‘intelligence’ part of The Griceian Lexicon?Well, Lewis and Short have
‘interlegere,’ to chose between. Lewis and Short have ‘interlĕgo , lēgi, lectum,
3, v. a., I’.which they render it as “to cull or pluck off here and there
(poet. and postclass.).in tmesi) uncis Carpendae manibus frondes, interque
legendae, Verg. G. 2, 366: “poma,” Pall. Febr. 25, 16; id. Jun. 5, 1.intellĕgo (less
correctly intellĭgo), exi, ectum (intellexti for intellexisti, Ter. Eun. 4, 6,
30; Cic. Att. 13, 32, 3: I.“intellexes for intellexisses,” Plaut. Cist. 2, 3,
81; subj. perf.: “intellegerint,” Sall. H. Fragm. 1, 41, 23 Dietsch);
“inter-lego,” “to see into, perceive, understand.” I. Lit. A. Lewis and Short
render as “to perceive, understand, comprehend.” Cf. Grice on his handwriting
being legible to few. And The child is an adult as being UNintelligible until
the creature is produced. In “Aspects,” he mentions flat rationality, and
certain other talents that are more difficult for the philosopher to
conceptualise, such as nose (i.e. intuitiveness), acumen, tenacity, and
such. Grices approach is Pological. If Locke had used intelligent to refer
to Prince Maurices parrot, Grice wants to find criteria for intelligent as
applied to his favourite type of P, rather (intelligent, indeed rational.). semiosis
from Grecian semeiosis, ‘observation of signs’, the relation of signification
involving the three relata of sign, object, and mind. Semiotic is the science
or study of semiosis. The semiotic of John of Saint Thomas and of Peirce
includes two distinct components: the relation of signification and the
classification of signs. The relation of signification is genuinely triadic and
cannot be reduced to the sum of its three subordinate dyads: sign-object,
sign-mind, object-mind. A sign represents an object to a mind just as A gives a
gift to B. Semiosis is not, as it is often taken to be, a mere compound of a
sign-object dyad and a sign-mind dyad because these dyads lack the essential
intentionality that unites mind with object; similarly, the gift relation
involves not just A giving and B receiving but, crucially, the intention
uniting A and B. In the Scholastic logic of John of Saint Thomas, the
sign-object dyad is a categorial relation secundum esse, that is, an essential
relation, falling in Aristotle’s category of relation, while the sign-mind dyad
is a transcendental relation secundum dici, that is, a relation only in an
analogical sense, in a manner of speaking; thus the formal rationale of
semiosis is constituted by the sign-object dyad. By contrast, in Peirce’s
logic, the sign-object dyad and the sign-mind dyad are each only potential
semiosis: thus, the hieroglyphs of ancient Egypt were merely potential signs
until the discovery of the Rosetta Stone, just as a road-marking was a merely
potential sign to the driver who overlooked it. Classifications of signs
typically follow from the logic of semiosis. Thus John of Saint Thomas divides
signs according to their relations to their objects into natural signs smoke as
a sign of fire, customary signs napkins on the table as a sign that dinner is
imminent, and stipulated signs as when a neologism is coined; he also divides
signs according to their relations to a mind. An instrumental sign must first
be cognized as an object before it can signify e.g., a written word or a
symptom; a formal sign, by contrast, directs the mind to its object without
having first been cognized e.g., percepts and concepts. Formal signs are not
that which we cognize but that by which we cognize. All instrumental signs
presuppose the action of formal signs in the semiosis of cognition. Peirce
similarly classified signs into three trichotomies according to their relations
with 1 themselves, 2 their objects, and 3 their interpretants usually minds;
and Charles Morris, who followed Peirce closely, called the relationship of
signs to one another the syntactical dimension of semiosis, the relationship of
signs to their objects the semantical dimension of semiosis, and the
relationship of signs to their interpreters the pragmatic dimension of
semiosis. Refs.: The most specific essay
is his lecture on Peirce, listed under ‘communication, above. A reference to
‘criteria of intelligence relates. The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC.
sensus: sensationalism, the belief that all mental
states particularly cognitive
states are derived, by composition or
association, from sensation. It is often joined to the view that sensations
provide the only evidence for our beliefs, or more rarely to the view that
statements about the world can be reduced, without loss, to statements about
sensation. Hobbes was the first important sensationalist in modern times.
“There is no conception in man’s mind,” he wrote, “which hath not at first,
totally, or by parts, been begotten upon the organs of sense. The rest are
derived from that original.” But the belief gained prominence in the eighteenth
century, due largely to the influence of Locke. Locke himself was not a
sensationalist, because he took the mind’s reflection on its own operations to
be an independent source of ideas. But his distinction between simple and
complex ideas was used by eighteenthcentury sensationalists such as Condillac
and Hartley to explain how conceptions that seem distant from sense might
nonetheless be derived from it. And to account for the particular ways in which
simple ideas are in fact combined, Condillac and Hartley appealed to a second
device described by Locke: the association of ideas. “Elementary”
sensations the building blocks of our
mental life were held by the
sensationalists to be non-voluntary, independent of judgment, free of
interpretation, discrete or atomic, and infallibly known. Nineteenth-century
sensationalists tried to account for perception in terms of such building
blocks; they struggled particularly with the perception of space and time. Late
nineteenth-century critics such as Ward and James advanced powerful arguments
against the reduction of perception to sensation. Perception, they claimed,
involves more than the passive reception or recombination and association of
discrete pellets of incorrigible information. They urged a change in
perspective to a functionalist viewpoint
more closely allied with prevailing trends in biology from which sensationalism never fully
recovered. sensibile: Austin, “Sense and
sensibile,” as used by Russell, those entities that no one is at the moment
perceptually aware of, but that are, in every other respect, just like the
objects of perceptual awareness. If one is a direct realist and believes that
the objects one is aware of in sense perception are ordinary physical objects,
then sensibilia are, of course, just physical objects of which no one is at the
moment aware. Assuming with common sense that ordinary objects continue to
exist when no one is aware of them, it follows that sensibilia exist. If,
however, one believes as Russell did that what one is aware of in ordinary
sense perception is some kind of idea in the mind, a so-called sense-datum,
then sensibilia have a problematic status. A sensibile then turns out to be an
unsensed sense-datum. On some the usual conceptions of sense-data, this is like
an unfelt pain, since a sense-datum’s existence not as a sense-datum, but as
anything at all depends on our someone’s perception of it. To exist for such
things is to be perceived see Berkeley’s “esse est percipii“. If, however, one
extends the notion of sense-datum as Moore was inclined to do to whatever it is
of which one is directly aware in sense perception, then sensibilia may or may
not exist. It depends on what physical
objects or ideas in the mind we are
directly aware of in sense perception and, of course, on the empirical facts
about whether objects continue to exist when they are not being perceived. If
direct realists are right, horses and trees, when unobserved, are sensibilia.
So are the front surfaces of horses and trees things Moore once considered to
be sensedata. If the direct realists are wrong, and what we are perceptually
aware of are “ideas in the mind,” then whether or not sensibilia exist depends
on whether or not such ideas can exist apart from any mind. sensorium, the seat and cause of sensation in
the brain of humans and other animals. The term is not part of contemporary
psychological parlance; it belongs to prebehavioral, prescientific psychology,
especially of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. Only creatures
possessed of a sensorium were thought capable of bodily and perceptual
sensations. Some thinkers believed that the sensorium, when excited, also
produced muscular activity and motion. sensus communis, a cognitive faculty to
which the five senses report. It was first argued for in Aristotle’s On the
Soul II.12, though the term ‘common sense’ was first introduced in Scholastic
thought. Aristotle refers to properties such as magnitude that are perceived by
more than one sense as common sensibles. To recognize common sensibles, he
claims, we must possess a single cognitive power to compare such qualities,
received from the different senses, to one another. Augustine says the “inner
sense” judges whether the senses are working properly, and perceives whether
the animal perceives De libero arbitrio II.35. Aquinas In De anima II, 13.370
held that it is also by the common sense that we perceive we live. He says the
common sense uses the external senses to know sensible forms, preparing the
sensible species it receives for the operation of the cognitive power, which
recognizes the real thing causing the sensible species. sentential connective, also called sentential
operator, propositional connective, propositional operator, a word or phrase,
such as ‘and’, ‘or’, or ‘if . . . then’, that is used to construct compound
sentences from atomic i.e.,
non-compound sentences. A sentential
connective can be defined formally as an expression containing blanks, such
that when the blanks are replaced with sentences the result is a compound
sentence. Thus, ‘if ——— then ———’ and ‘——— or ———’ are sentential connectives,
since we can replace the blanks with sentences to get the compound sentences
‘If the sky is clear then we can go swimming’ and ‘We can go swimming or we can
stay home’. Classical logic makes use of truth-functional connectives only, for
which the truth-value of the compound sentence can be determined uniquely by
the truth-value of the sentences that replace the blanks. The standard
truth-functional sensibilia sentential connective 834 834 connectives are ‘and’, ‘or’, ‘not’, ‘if
. . . then’, and ‘if and only if’. There are many non-truth-functional
connectives as well, such as ‘it is possible that ———’ and ‘——— because
———’. sentimentalism, the theory,
prominent in the eighteenth century, that epistemological or moral relations
are derived from feelings. Although sentimentalism and sensationalism are both
empiricist positions, the latter view has all knowledge built up from
sensations, experiences impinging on the senses. Sentimentalists may allow that
ideas derive from sensations, but hold that some relations between them are
derived internally, that is, from sentiments arising upon reflection. Moral
sentimentalists, such as Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, and Hume, argued that the
virtue or vice of a character trait is established by approving or disapproving
sentiments. Hume, the most thoroughgoing sentimentalist, also argued that all
beliefs about the world depend on sentiments. On his analysis, when we form a
belief, we rely on the mind’s causally connecting two experiences, e.g., fire
and heat. But, he notes, such causal connections depend on the notion of
necessity that the two perceptions will
always be so conjoined and there is
nothing in the perceptions themselves that supplies that notion. The idea of
necessary connection is instead derived from a sentiment: our feeling of
expectation of the one experience upon the other. Likewise, our notions of
substance the unity of experiences in an object and of self the unity of
experiences in a subject are sentimentbased. But whereas moral sentiments do
not purport to represent the external world, these metaphysical notions of
necessity, substance, and self are “fictions,” creations of the imagination
purporting to represent something in the outside world.
sententia: For some reason, perhaps of his eccentricity, J. L.
Austin was in love with Chomsky. He would read “Syntactic Structures” aloud to
the Play Group. And Grice was listening. This stuck with Grice, who started to
use ‘sentence,’ even in Polish, when translating Tarski. Hardie had taught him
that ‘sententia’ was a Roman transliteration of ‘dia-noia,’ which helped. Since
“Not when the the of dog” is NOT a sentence, not even an ‘ill-formed sentence,’
Grice concludes that like ‘reason,’ and ‘cabbage,’ sentence is a value-paradeigmatic
concept. His favourite sentence was “Fido is shaggy,” uttered to communicate
that Smith’s dog is hairy coated. One of Grice’s favourite sentences was
Carnap’s “Pirots karulise elatically,” which Carnap borrowed from (but never
returned to) Baron Russell. (“I later found out a ‘pirot’ is an extinct fish,
which destroyed my whole implicaturum – talk of ichthyological necessity!” (Carnap
contrasted, “Pirots karulise elatically,” with “The not not if not the dog
the.”
shaggy-dog story, v. Grice’s shaggy-dog story.
shared experience: WoW: 286.
set-theoretic paradoxes, a collection of paradoxes that
reveal difficulties in certain central notions of set theory. The best-known of
these are Russell’s paradox, Burali-Forti’s paradox, and Cantor’s paradox. Russell’s
paradox, discovered in 1 by Bertrand Russell, is the simplest and so most
problematic of the set-theoretic paradoxes. Using it, we can derive a
contradiction directly from Cantor’s unrestricted comprehension schema. This
schema asserts that for any formula Px containing x as a free variable, there
is a set {x _ Px} whose members are exactly those objects that satisfy Px. To
derive the contradiction, take Px to be the formula x 1 x, and let z be the set
{x _ x 2 x} whose existence is guaranteed by the comprehension schema. Thus z
is the set whose members are exactly those objects that are not members of
themselves. We now ask whether z is, itself, a member of z. If the answer is
yes, then we can conclude that z must satisfy the criterion of membership in z,
i.e., z must not be a member of z. But if the answer is no, then since z is not
a member of itself, it satisfies the criterion for membership in z, and so z is
a member of z. All modern axiomatizations of set theory avoid Russell’s paradox
by restricting the principles that assert the existence of sets. The simplest
restriction replaces unrestricted comprehension with the separation schema.
Separation asserts that, given any set A and formula Px, there is a set {x 1 A
_ Px}, whose members are exactly those members of A that satisfy Px. If we now
take Px to be the formula x 2 x, then separation guarantees the existence of a
set zA % {x 1 A _ x 2 x}. We can then use Russell’s reasoning to prove the
result that zA cannot be a member of the original set A. If it were a member of
A, then we could prove that it is a member of itself if and only if it is not a
member of itself. Hence it is not a member of A. But this result is not
problematic, and so the paradox is avoided. The Burali-Forte paradox and Cantor’s
paradox are sometimes known as paradoxes of size, since they show that some
collections are too large to be considered sets. The Burali-Forte paradox,
discovered by Cesare Burali-Forte, is concerned with the set of all ordinal
numbers. In Cantor’s set theory, an ordinal number can be assigned to any
well-ordered set. A set is wellordered if every subset of the set has a least
element. But Cantor’s set theory also guarantees the existence of the set of
all ordinals, again due to the unrestricted comprehension schema. This set of
ordinals is well-ordered, and so can be associated with an ordinal number. But
it can be shown that the associated ordinal is greater than any ordinal in the
set, hence greater than any ordinal number. Cantor’s paradox involves the
cardinality of the set of all sets. Cardinality is another notion of size used
in set theory: a set A is said to have greater cardinality than a set B if and
only if B can be mapped one-to-one onto a subset of A but A cannot be so mapped
onto B or any of its subsets. One of Cantor’s fundamental results was that the
set of all subsets of a set A known as the power set of A has greater
cardinality than the set A. Applying this result to the set V of all sets, we
can conclude that the power set of V has greater cardinality than V. But every
set in the power set of V is also in V since V contains all sets, and so the
power set of V cannot have greater cardinality than V. We thus have a
contradiction. Like Russell’s paradox, both of these paradoxes result from the
unrestricted comprehension schema, and are avoided by replacing it with weaker
set-existence principles. Various principles stronger than the separation
schema are needed to get a reasonable set theory, and many alternative
axiomatizations have been proposed. But the lesson of these paradoxes is that
no setexistence principle can entail the existence of the Russell set, the set
of all ordinals, or the set of all sets, on pain of contradiction.
set theory – “I distinguish between a class and a set,
but Strawson does not.” – Grice -- the
study of collections, ranging from familiar examples like a set of
encyclopedias or a deck of cards to mathematical examples like the set of
natural numbers or the set of points on a line or the set of functions from a
set A to another set B. Sets can be specified in two basic ways: by a list
e.g., {0, 2, 4, 6, 8} and as the extension of a property e.g., {x _ x is an
even natural number less than 10}, where this is read ‘the set of all x such
that x is an even natural number less than 10’. The most fundamental relation
in set theory is membership, as in ‘2 is a member of the set of even natural
numbers’ in symbols: 2 1 {x _ x is an even natural number}. Membership is
determinate, i.e., any candidate for membership in a given set is either in the
set or not in the set, with no room for vagueness or ambiguity. A set’s
identity is completely determined by its members or elements i.e., sets are
extensional rather than intensional. Thus {x _ x is human} is the same set as {x
_ x is a featherless biped} because they have the same members. The smallest
set possible is the empty or null set, the set with no members. There cannot be
more than one empty set, by extensionality. It can be specified, e.g., as {x _
x & x}, but it is most often symbolized as / or { }. A set A is called a
subset of a set B and B a superset of A if every member of A is also a member
of B; in symbols, A 0 B. So, the set of even natural numbers is a subset of the
set of all natural numbers, and any set is a superset of the empty set. The
union of two sets A and B is the set whose members are the members of A and the
members of B in symbols, A 4 B % {x _ x
1 A or x 1 B} so the union of the set of
even natural numbers and the set of odd natural numbers is the set of all
natural numbers. The intersection of two sets A and B is the set whose members
are common to both A and B in symbols, A
3 B % {x _ x 1 A and x 1 B} so the
intersection of the set of even natural numbers and the set of prime natural
numbers is the singleton set {2}, whose only member is the number 2. Two sets
whose intersection is empty are called disjoint, e.g., the set of even natural
numbers and the set of odd natural numbers. Finally, the difference between a
set A and a set B is the set whose members are members of A but not members of
B in symbols, A B % {x _ x 1 A and x 2 B} so the set of odd numbers between 5 and 20
minus the set of prime natural numbers is {9, 15}. By extensionality, the order
in which the members of a set are listed is unimportant, i.e., {1, 2, 3} % {2,
3, 1}. To introduce the concept of ordering, we need the notion of the ordered
pair of a and b in symbols, a, b or .
All that is essential to ordered pairs is that two of them are equal only when
their first entries are equal and their second entries are equal. Various sets
can be used to simulate this behavior, but the version most commonly used is
the Kuratowski ordered pair: a, b is defined to be {{a}, {a, b}}. On this
definition, it can indeed be proved that a, b % c, d if and only if a % c and b
% d. The Cartesian product of two sets A and B is the set of all ordered pairs
whose first entry is in A and whose second entry is B in symbols, A $ B % {x _ x % a, b for some a
1 A and some b 1 B}. This set-theoretic reflection principles set theory
836 836 same technique can be used to
form ordered triples a, b, c % a, b, c;
ordered fourtuples a, b, c, d % a, b, c,
d; and by extension, ordered n-tuples for all finite n. Using only these simple
building blocks, substitutes for all the objects of classical mathematics can
be constructed inside set theory. For example, a relation is defined as a set
of ordered pairs so the successor
relation among natural numbers becomes {0, 1, 1, 2, 2, 3 . . . } and a function is a relation containing no
distinct ordered pairs of the form a, b and a, c so the successor relation is a function. The
natural numbers themselves can be identified with various sequences of sets,
the most common of which are finite von Neumann ordinal numbers: /, {/}, {/,
{/}, {/}, {/}, {/, {/}}}, . . . . On this definition, 0 % /, 1 % {/}, 2 % {/,
{/}}, etc., each number n has n members, the successor of n is n 4 {n}, and n ‹
m if and only if n 1 m. Addition and multiplication can be defined for these
numbers, and the Peano axioms proved from the axioms of set theory; see below.
Negative, rational, real, and complex numbers, geometric spaces, and more
esoteric mathematical objects can all be identified with sets, and the standard
theorems about them proved. In this sense, set theory provides a foundation for
mathematics. Historically, the theory of sets arose in the late nineteenth
century. In his work on the foundations of arithmetic, Frege identified the
natural numbers with the extensions of certain concepts; e.g., the number two
is the set of all concepts C under which two things fall in symbols, 2 % {x _ x is a concept, and
there are distinct things a and b which fall under x, and anything that falls
under x is either a or b}. Cantor was led to consider complex sets of points in
the pursuit of a question in the theory of trigonometric series. To describe
the properties of these sets, Cantor introduced infinite ordinal numbers after
the finite ordinals described above. The first of these, w, is {0, 1, 2, . .
.}, now understood in von Neumann’s terms as the set of all finite ordinals.
After w, the successor function yields w ! 1 % w 4 {w} % {0, 1, 2, . . . n, n +
1, . . . , w}, then w ! 2 % w ! 1 ! 1 % {0, 1, 2, . . . , w , w ! 1}, w ! 3 % w
! 2 ! 1 % {0, 1, 2, . . . , w, w ! 1, w ! 2}, and so on; after all these comes
w ! w % {0, 1, 2, . . . , w, w ! 1, w ! 2, . . . , w ! n, w ! n ! 1, . . .},
and the process begins again. The ordinal numbers are designed to label the
positions in an ordering. Consider, e.g., a reordering of the natural numbers
in which the odd numbers are placed after the evens: 0, 2, 4, 6, . . . 1, 3, 5,
7, . . . . The number 4 is in the third position of this sequence, and the
number 5 is in the w + 2nd. But finite numbers also perform a cardinal
function; they tell us how many so-andso’s there are. Here the infinite
ordinals are less effective. The natural numbers in their usual order have the
same structure as w, but when they are ordered as above, with the evens before
the odds, they take on the structure of a much larger ordinal, w ! w. But the
answer to the question, How many natural numbers are there? should be the same
no matter how they are arranged. Thus, the transfinite ordinals do not provide
a stable measure of the size of an infinite set. When are two infinite sets of
the same size? On the one hand, the infinite set of even natural numbers seems
clearly smaller than the set of all natural numbers; on the other hand, these
two sets can be brought into one-to-one correspondence via the mapping that
matches 0 to 0, 1 to 2, 2 to 4, 3 to 6, and in general, n to 2n. This puzzle
had troubled mathematicians as far back as Galileo, but Cantor took the
existence of a oneto-one correspondence between two sets A and B as the
definition of ‘A is the same size as B’. This coincides with our usual
understanding for finite sets, and it implies that the set of even natural
numbers and the set of all natural numbers and w ! 1 and w! 2 and w ! w and w !
w and many more all have the same size. Such infinite sets are called
countable, and the number of their elements, the first infinite cardinal
number, is F0. Cantor also showed that the set of all subsets of a set A has a
size larger than A itself, so there are infinite cardinals greater than F0,
namely F1, F2, and so on. Unfortunately, the early set theories were prone to
paradoxes. The most famous of these, Russell’s paradox, arises from
consideration of the set R of all sets that are not members of themselves: is R
1 R? If it is, it isn’t, and if it isn’t, it is. The Burali-Forti paradox
involves the set W of all ordinals: W itself qualifies as an ordinal, so W 1 W,
i.e., W ‹ W. Similar difficulties surface with the set of all cardinal numbers
and the set of all sets. At fault in all these cases is a seemingly innocuous
principle of unlimited comprehension: for any property P, there is a set {x _ x
has P}. Just after the turn of the century, Zermelo undertook to systematize
set theory by codifying its practice in a series of axioms from which the known
derivations of the paradoxes could not be carried out. He proposed the axioms
of extensionality two sets with the same members are the same; pairing for any
a and b, there is a set {a, b}; separation for any set A and property P, there
is a set {x _ x 1 A and x has P}; power set for any set A, there is a set {x _
x0 A}; union for any set of sets F, there is a set {x _ x 1 A for some A 1
F} this yields A 4 B, when F % {A, B}
and {A, B} comes from A and B by pairing; infinity w exists; and choice for any
set of non-empty sets, there is a set that contains exactly one member from
each. The axiom of choice has a vast number of equivalents, including the
well-ordering theorem every set can be
well-ordered and Zorn’s lemma if every chain in a partially ordered set has
an upper bound, then the set has a maximal element. The axiom of separation
limits that of unlimited comprehension by requiring a previously given set A
from which members are separated by the property P; thus troublesome sets like
Russell’s that attempt to collect absolutely all things with P cannot be
formed. The most controversial of Zermelo’s axioms at the time was that of
choice, because it posits the existence of a choice set a set that “chooses” one from each of
possibly infinitely many non-empty sets
without giving any rule for making the choices. For various
philosophical and practical reasons, it is now accepted without much debate.
Fraenkel and Skolem later formalized the axiom of replacement if A is a set,
and every member a of A is replaced by some b, then there is a set containing
all the b’s, and Skolem made both replacement and separation more precise by
expressing them as schemata of first-order logic. The final axiom of the
contemporary theory is foundation, which guarantees that sets are formed in a
series of stages called the iterative hierarchy begin with some non-sets, then
form all possible sets of these, then form all possible sets of the things
formed so far, then form all possible sets of these, and so on. This iterative picture
of sets built up in stages contrasts with the older notion of the extension of
a concept; these are sometimes called the mathematical and the logical notions
of collection, respectively. The early controversy over the paradoxes and the
axiom of choice can be traced to the lack of a clear distinction between these
at the time. Zermelo’s first five axioms all but choice plus foundation form a
system usually called Z; ZC is Z with choice added. Z plus replacement is ZF,
for Zermelo-Fraenkel, and adding choice makes ZFC, the theory of sets in most
widespread use today. The consistency of ZFC cannot be proved by standard
mathematical means, but decades of experience with the system and the strong
intuitive picture provided by the iterative conception suggest that it is.
Though ZFC is strong enough for all standard mathematics, it is not enough to
answer some natural set-theoretic questions e.g., the continuum problem. This
has led to a search for new axioms, such as large cardinal assumptions, but no
consensus on these additional principles has yet been reached.
Sextus Empiricus, the sixth son of Empiricus the Elder
– “My five brothers were not philosophers” -- Grecian Skeptic philosopher whose
writings are the chief source of our knowledge about the extreme Skeptic view,
Pyrrhonism. Practically nothing is known about him as a person. He was
apparently a medical doctor and a teacher in a Skeptical school, probably in
Alexandria. What has survived are his Hypotoposes, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, and
a series of Skeptical critiques, Against the Dogmatists, questioning the
premises and conclusions in many disciplines, such as physics, mathematics,
rhetoric, and ethics. In these works, Sextus summarized and organized the views
of Skeptical arguers before him. The Outlines starts with an attempt to
indicate what Skepticism is, to explain the terminology employed by the
Skeptics, how Pyrrhonian Skepticism differs from other so-called Skeptical
views, and how the usual answers to Skepticism are rebutted. Sextus points out
that the main Hellenistic philosophies, Stoicism, Epicureanism, and Academic
Skepticism which is presented as a negative dogmatism, claimed that they would
bring the adherent peace of mind, ataraxia. Unfortunately the dogmatic adherent
would only become more perturbed by seeing the Skeptical objections that could
be brought against his or her view. Then, by suspending judgment, epoche, one
would find the tranquillity being sought. Pyrrhonian Skepticism is a kind of
mental hygiene or therapy that cures one of dogmatism or rashness. It is like a
purge that cleans out foul matter as well as itself. To bring about this state
of affairs there are sets of Skeptical arguments that should bring one to
suspense of judgment. The first set are the ten tropes of the earlier Skeptic,
Anesidemus. The next are the five tropes about causality. And lastly are the
tropes about the criterion of knowledge. The ten tropes stress the variability
of sense experience among men and animals, among men, and within one
individual. The varying and conflicting experiences present conflicts about
what the perceived object is like. Any attempt to judge beyond appearances, to
ascertain that which is non-evident, requires some way of choosing what data to
accept. This requires a criterion. Since there is disagreement about what
criterion to employ, we need a criterion of a criterion, and so on. Either we
accept an arbitrary criterion or we get into an infinite regress. Similarly if
we try to prove anything, we need a criterion of what constitutes a proof. If
we offer a proof of a theory of proof, this will be circular reasoning, or end
up in another infinite regress. Sextus devotes most of his discussion to
challenging Stoic logic, which claimed that evident signs could reveal what is
non-evident. There might be signs that suggested what is temporarily
non-evident, such as smoke indicating that there is a fire, but any supposed
linkage between evident signs and what is non-evident can be challenged and
questioned. Sextus then applies the groups of Skeptical arguments to various
specific subjects physics, mathematics,
music, grammar, ethics showing that one
should suspend judgment on any knowledge claims in these areas. Sextus denies
that he is saying any of this dogmatically: he is just stating how he feels at
given moments. He hopes that dogmatists sick with a disease, rashness, will be
cured and led to tranquillity no matter how good or bad the Skeptical arguments
might be.
Shaftesbury, Lord, in full, Third Earl of Shaftesbury,
title of Anthony Ashley Cooper, English philosopher and politician who
originated the moral sense theory. He was born at Wimborne St. Giles,
Dorsetshire. As a Country Whig he served in the House of Commons for three
years and later, as earl, monitored meetings of the House of Lords. Shaftesbury
introduced into British moral philosophy the notion of a moral sense, a mental
faculty unique to human beings, involving reflection and feeling and
constituting their ability to discern right and wrong. He sometimes represents
the moral sense as analogous to a purported aesthetic sense, a special capacity
by which we perceive, through our emotions, the proportions and harmonies of
which, on his Platonic view, beauty is composed. For Shaftesbury, every
creature has a “private good or interest,” an end to which it is naturally
disposed by its constitution. But there are other goods as well notably, the public good and the good without
qualification of a sentient being. An individual creature’s goodness is defined
by the tendency of its “natural affections” to contribute to the “universal
system” of nature of which it is a part
i.e., their tendency to promote the public good. Because human beings
can reflect on actions and affections, including their own and others’, they
experience emotional responses not only to physical stimuli but to these mental
objects as well e.g., to the thought of one’s compassion or kindness. Thus,
they are capable of perceiving and
acquiring through their actions a
particular species of goodness, namely, virtue. In the virtuous person, the
person of integrity, natural appetites and affections are in harmony with each
other wherein lies her private good and in harmony with the public interest.
Shaftesbury’s attempted reconciliation of selflove and benevolence is in part a
response to the egoism of Hobbes, who argued that everyone is in fact motivated
by self-interest. His defining morality in terms of psychological and public
harmony is also a reaction to the divine voluntarism of his former tutor, Locke,
who held that the laws of nature and morality issue from the will of God. On
Shaftesbury’s view, morality exists independently of religion, but belief in
God serves to produce the highest degree of virtue by nurturing a love for the
universal system. Shaftesbury’s theory led to a general refinement of
eighteenth-century ideas about moral feelings; a theory of the moral sense
emerged, whereby sentiments are under
certain conditions perceptions of, or
constitutive of, right and wrong. In addition to several essays collected in
three volumes under the title Characteristics of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times
second edition, 1714, Shaftesbury also wrote stoical moral and religious
meditations reminiscent of Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius. His ideas on moral
sentiments exercised considerable influence on the ethical theories of
Hutcheson and Hume, who later worked out in detail their own accounts of the
moral sense. H. P. Grice, “My favourite
Cooper.”
Sheffer stroke – see abdicatum, Grice, “Negation and
privation” and “Lectures on negation” -- also called alternative denial, a
binary truth-functor represented by the symbol ‘_’, the logical force of which
can be expressed contextually in terms of ‘-’ and ‘&’ by the following
definition: p_q % Df -p & q. The importance of the Sheffer stroke lies in the
fact that it by itself can express any well-formed expression of
truth-functional logic. Thus, since {-,7} forms an expressively complete set,
defining -p as p_p and p 7 q as p_p _q_q provides for the possibility of a
further reduction of primitive functors to one. This system of symbols is
commonly called the stroke notation.
Shyreswood -- Sherwood, William, also called William
Shyreswood, English logician who taught logic at Oxford and at Paris between
1235 and 1250. He was the earliest of the three great “summulist” writers, the
other two whom he influenced strongly being Peter of Spain and Lambert of
Auxerre. His main works are “Introductiones in Logicam,” “Syncategoremata,” “De
insolubilibus,” and “Obligationes.” Some serious doubts have recently arisen
about the authorship of the latter work. Since M. Grabmann published Sherwood’s
Introductiones, philosophers have paid considerable attention to this seminal
Griceian. While the first part of Introductiones offer the basic ideas of
Aristotle’s Organon, and the latter part neatly lays out the Sophistical
Refutations, the final tract expounds the doctrine of the four properties of a
term. First, signification. Second, supposition. Third, conjunction, Fourth, appellation
-- hence the label ‘terminist’ for this sort of logic. These logico-semantic
discussions, together with the discussions of syncategorematic words,
constitute the “logica moderna,” (Grice’s ‘mdoernism’) as opposed to the more
strictly Aristotelian contents of the earlier logica vetus (Grice’s
neo-traditionalism) and logica nova (“It took me quite a while to explain to
Strawson the distinction between ‘logica nova’ and ‘logica moderna,’ only to
have him tell me, “worry not, Grice – I’ll be into ‘logica vetus’ anyways!””. The
doctrine of properties of terms and the analysis of syncategorematic terms,
especially those of ‘all’ (or every) ‘no’ (or not or it is not the case) and
‘nothing’, ‘only’, ‘not’, ‘begins’ and ‘ceases (to eat iron) ‘necessarily’,
‘if’ (Latin ‘si,’ Grecian ‘ei’), ‘and’ (Latin ‘et’, Grecian ‘kai’) and ‘or’
(Latin ‘vel’) may be said to constitute Sherwood’s
or Shyrewood’s philosophy of logic. Shyrewood not only distinguishes
categorematic descriptive and syncategorematic logical words but also shows how
some terms are used categorematically in some contexts and syncategorematically
in others – “he doesn’t explain which, and that’s one big map in his opus.”–
Grice. He recognizes the importance of the order of words (hence Grice, ‘be
orderly’) and of the scope of logical functors; he also anticipates the variety
of composite and divided senses of propositions. Obligationes, if indeed his,
attempts to state conditions under which a formal disputation may take place.
De Insolubilibus deals with paradoxes of self-reference and with ways of
solving them. Understanding Sherwood’s logic is important for understanding the
later medieval developments of logica moderna down to Occam whom Grice laughed
at (“modified Occam’s razor.”).
ship of Theseus, the ship of the Grecian hero Theseus,
which, according to Plutarch “Life of Theseus,” 23, the Athenians preserved by
gradually replacing its timbers. A classic debate ensued concerning identity
over time. Suppose a ship’s timbers are replaced one by one over a period of
time; at what point, if any, does it cease to be the same ship? What if the
ship’s timbers, on removal, are used to build a new ship, identical in
structure with the first: which ship has the best claim to be the original
ship?
shpet: phenomenologist and highly regarded friend of
Husserl. Shpet plays a major role in the development of phenomenology. Graduating
from Kiev in 6, Shpet accompanied his mentor
Chelpanov to Moscow, ommencing graduate studies at Moscow M.A., 0; Ph.D., 6. He attends Husserl’s
seminars at Göttingen during 213, out of which developed a continuing
friendship between the two, recorded in correspondence extending through 8. In
4 Shpet published a meditation, “Iavlenie i smysl,” nspired by Husserl’s
Logical Investigations and, especially, Ideas I, which had appeared in 3.
Between 4 and 7 he published six additional books on such disparate topics as
the concept of history, Herzen, philosophy, aesthetics, ethnic psychology, and
language. He founds and edited the philosophical yearbook Mysl’ i slovo Thought
and Word between 8 and 1, publishing an important article on skepticism in it.
He was arrested and sentenced to internal exile. Under these conditions he made
a running commentary of Hegel’s Phenomenology. He was executed.
sidgwick: h. English philosopher. Best known for “The Methods
of Ethics,” he also wrote “Outlines of the History of Ethics.” In the “Methods,”
Sidgwick tries to assess the rationality of the main ways in which ordinary
people go about making this or that moral decision. Sidgwick thinks that our
common “methods of ethics” fall into three main patterns. The first pattern is
articulated by the philosophical theory known as intuitionism. This is the view
that we can just see straight off either what particular act is right or what
binding rule or general principle we ought to follow. A second pattern is
spelled out by what self-love or egoism, the view that we ought in each act to
get as much good as we can for ourselves. – vide: H. P. Grice, “The principle
of conversational self-love and the principle of conversational benevolence,”
H. P. Grice, “Conversational
benevolence, not conversational self-love.” The third widely used method is
represented by utilitarianism, the view that we ought in each case to bring
about as much good as possible for everyone affected. Can any or all of the
methods prescribed by these views be rationally defended? And how are they
related to one another? By framing his philosophical questions in these terms,
Sidgwick makes it centrally important to examine the chief philosophical
theories of morality in the light of the common-sense morals of his time.
Sidgwick thinks that no theory wildly at odds with common-sense morality would
be acceptable. Intuitionism, a theory originating with Butler (of ‘self-love
and benevolence’ fame), transmitted by Reid, and most systematically expounded
during the Victorian era by Whewell, is widely held to be the best available
defense of Christian morals. Egoism (Self-love) was thought by many to be the
clearest pattern of practical (or means-end) rationality and is frequently said
to be compatible with Christianity. And J. S. Mill had argues that
utilitarianism is both rational and in accord with common sense. But whatever
their relation to ordinary morality, the three methods or patterns seem to be
seriously at odds with one another. Examining all the chief commonsense
precepts and rules of morality, such as that promises ought to be kept,
Sidgwick argues that none is truly self-evident or intuitively certain. Each
fails to guide us at certain points where we expect it to answer our practical
questions. Utilitarianism, he found, could provide a complicated method for
filling these gaps. But what ultimately justifies utilitarianism is certain
very general axioms seen intuitively to be true. Among them are the principles
that what is right in one case must be right in any similar case, and that we
ought to aim at good generally, not just at some particular part of it. Thus
intuitionism and utilitarianism can be reconciled. When taken together they
yield a complete and justifiable method of ethics that is in accord with common
sense. What then of egoism and self-love? Self love and egoirm can provide as
complete a method as utilitarianism, and it also involves a self-evident axiom.
But the results of egoism and self-love often
contradict those of utilitarianism. Hence there is a serious problem. The
method that instructs us to act always for the good generally and the method
that tells one to act solely for one’s own good are equally rational. Since the
two methods give contradictory directions, while each method rests on
self-evident axioms, it seems that practical reason is fundamentally
incoherent. Sidgwick could see no way to solve the problem. Sidgwick’s bleak
conclusion is not generally accepted (especially at Oxford), but his Methods is
widely viewed as one of the best works of moral philosophy ever written in what
Grice calls ‘insular’ philosophy (as opposed to mainland philosophy). Sidgwick’s account of classical utilitarianism
is unsurpassed. Sidwick’s discussions of the general status of morality and of
particular moral concepts are enduring models of clarity and acumen. His
insights about the relations between egoism (self-love) and utilitarianism have
stimulated much valuable research. And his way of framing moral problems, by
asking about the relations between commonsense beliefs and the best available
theories, has set much of the agenda for ethics.
siger of Brabant: Grice: “Sigier is mentioned in Dante;
I’m not!” -- philosopher, an activist in the philosophical struggles within the
arts faculty at Paris. Siger ie is usually regarded as a leader of a “radical
Aristotelianism” Siger holds that everything originates through a series of
emanations from a first cause. The world and each species including the human
species are eternal. Human beings share a single active intellect. There is no
good reason to think that Siger advances the view that there was a double
truth, one in theology and another in natural philosophy. It is difficult to
distinguish Siger’s own views from those he attributes to “the Philosophers”
and thus to know the extent to which he held the heterodox views he taught as
the best interpretation of the prescribed texts in the arts curriculum. In any
case, Siger is summoned before the
Inquisition, but wisefully flees Paris and settles in Orvieto. Siger is never convicted of heresy, but it seems that
the condemnations at Paris are partially directed at his teaching. He was suspiciously
and criminally stabbed to death by his own clerk in Orvieto -- the papal sea.
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Implicatura in Dante.”
signatum: Cf. “to sign” as a verb – from French. Grice uses
designatum, too – but more specifically within the ‘propositio’ as a compound
of a subjectum and a predicatum. The subject-item indicates a thing; and the
predicate-item designates a property. As Grice notes, there is a distinction
between Aristotle’s use, in De Int., of ‘sumbolon,’ for which Aristotle
sometimes means ‘semeion,’ and their Roman counterparts, ‘signum’ sounds otiose
enough. But ‘significo’ does not. There is this –fico thing that sounds
obtrusive. The Romans, however, were able to distinguish between ‘make a sign,’
and just ‘signal.’ The point is important when Grice tries to apply the
Graeco-Roman philosophical terminology to a lexeme which does not belong in
there: “mean.” His example is someone in pain, uttering “Oh.” If he later gains
voluntary control, by uttering “Oh” he means that he is in pain, and even at a
later stage, provided he learns ‘lupe,’ he may utter the expression which is
somewhat correlated in a non-iconic fashion with something which iconically is
a vehicle for U to mean that he is in pain. In this way, in a communication-system,
a communication-device, such as “Oh” does for the state of affairs something
that the state of affairs cannot do for itself, govern the addresee’s thoughts
and behaviour (very much as the Oxfordshire cricket team does for Oxfordshire
what Oxfordshire cannot do for herself, viz. to engage in a game of cricket.
There’s rae-presentatum, for you! Short and Lewis have ‘signare,’ from
‘signum,’ and which they render as ‘to set a mark upon, to mark, mark out, designate
(syn.: noto, designo),’ Lit. A. In gen. (mostly poet. and in post-Aug. prose):
discrimen non facit neque signat linea alba, Lucil. ap. Non. 405, 17: “signata
sanguine pluma est,” Ov. M. 6, 670: “ne signare quidem aut partiri limite
campum Fas erat,” Verg. G. 1, 126: “humum limite mensor,” Ov. M. 1, 136; id.
Am. 3, 8, 42: “moenia aratro,” id. F. 4, 819: “pede certo humum,” to print,
press, Hor. A. P. 159; cf.: “vestigia summo pulvere,” to mark, imprint, Verg.
G. 3, 171: auratā cyclade humum, Prop. 4 (5), 7, 40. “haec nostro signabitur
area curru,” Ov. A. A. 1, 39: “locum, ubi ea (cistella) excidit,” Plaut. Cist.
4, 2, 28: “caeli regionem in cortice signant,” mark, cut, Verg. G. 2, 269:
“nomina saxo,” Ov. M. 8, 539: “rem stilo,” Vell. 1, 16, 1: “rem carmine,” Verg.
A. 3, 287; “for which: carmine saxum,” Ov. M. 2, 326: “cubitum longis
litteris,” Plaut. Rud. 5, 2, 7: “ceram figuris,” to imprint, Ov. M. 15, 169:
“cruor signaverat herbam,” had stained, id. ib. 10, 210; cf. id. ib. 12, 125:
“signatum sanguine pectus,” id. A. A. 2, 384: “dubiā lanugine malas,” id. M.
13, 754: “signata in stirpe cicatrix,” Verg. G. 2, 379: “manibus Procne pectus
signata cruentis,” id. ib. 4, 15: “vocis infinitios sonos paucis notis,” Cic.
Rep. 3, 2, 3: “visum objectum imprimet et quasi signabit in animo suam
speciem,” id. Fat. 19, 43.— B. In partic. 1. To mark with a seal; to seal, seal
up, affix a seal to a thing (usually obsignare): “accepi a te signatum
libellum,” Cic. Att. 11, 1, 1: “volumina,” Hor. Ep. 1, 13, 2: locellum tibi
signatum remisi, Caes. ap. Charis. p. 60 P.: “epistula,” Nep. Pel. 3, 2:
“arcanas tabellas,” Ov. Am. 2, 15, 15: “signatis quicquam mandare tabellis,”
Tib. 4, 7, 7: “lagenam (anulus),” Mart. 9, 88, 7: “testamentum,” Plin. Ep. 2,
20, 8 sq.; cf. Mart. 5, 39, 2: “nec nisi signata venumdabatur (terra),” Plin.
35, 4, 14, § 33.—Absol., Mart. 10, 70, 7; Quint. 5, 7, 32; Suet. Ner. 17.— 2.
To mark with a stamp; hence, a. Of money, to stamp, to coin: “aes argentum aurumve
publice signanto,” Cic. Leg. 3, 3, 6; cf.: “qui primus ex auro denarium
signavit ... Servius rex primus signavit aes ... Signatum est nota pecudum,
unde et pecunia appellata ... Argentum signatum est anno, etc.,” Plin. 33, 3,
13, § 44: “argentum signatum,” Cic. Verr. 2, 5, 25, § 63; Quint. 5, 10, 62; 5,
14, 26: “pecunia signata Illyriorum signo,” Liv. 44, 27, 9: “denarius signatus
Victoriā,” Plin. 33, 3, 13, § 46: “sed cur navalis in aere Altera signata est,”
Ov. F. 1, 230: “milia talentūm argenti non signati formā, sed rudi pondere,”
Curt. 5, 2, 11.— Hence, b. Poet.: “signatum memori pectore nomen habe,”
imprinted, impressed, Ov. H. 13, 66: “(filia) quae patriā signatur imagine
vultus,” i. e. closely resembles her father, Mart. 6, 27, 3.— c. To stamp, i. e.
to license, invest with official authority (late Lat.): “quidam per ampla
spatia urbis ... equos velut publicos signatis, quod dicitur, calceis agitant,”
Amm. 14, 6, 16.— 3. Pregn., to distinguish, adorn, decorate (poet.): “pater
ipse suo superūm jam signat honore,” Verg. A. 6, 781 Heyne: caelum corona,
Claud. Nupt. Hon. et Mar. 273. to point out, signify, indicate, designate,
express (rare; more usually significo, designo; in Cic. only Or. 19, 64, where
dignata is given by Non. 281, 10; “v. Meyer ad loc.): translatio plerumque
signandis rebus ac sub oculos subiciendis reperta est,” Quint. 8, 6, 19:
“quotiens suis verbis signare nostra voluerunt (Graeci),” id. 2, 14, 1; cf.:
“appellatione signare,” id. 4, 1, 2: “utrius differentiam,” id. 6, 2, 20; cf. id.
9, 1, 4; 12, 10, 16: “nomen (Caieta) ossa signat,” Verg. A. 7, 4: “fama signata
loco est,” Ov. M. 14, 433: “miratrixque sui signavit nomine terras,”
designated, Luc. 4, 655; cf.: “(Earinus) Nomine qui signat tempora verna suo,”
Mart. 9, 17, 4: “Turnus ut videt ... So signari oculis,” singled out, looked
to, Verg. A. 12, 3: signare responsum, to give a definite or distinct answer,
Sen. Ben. 7, 16, 1.—With rel.-clause: “memoria signat in quā regione quali
adjutore legatoque fratre meo usus sit,” Vell. 2, 115.— B. To distinguish,
recognize: “primi clipeos mentitaque tela Adgnoscunt, atque ora sono discordia
signant,” Verg. A. 2, 423; cf.: “sonis homines dignoscere,” Quint. 11, 3, 31:
“animo signa quodcumque in corpore mendum est,” Ov. R. Am. 417.— C. To seal, settle,
establish, confirm, prescribe (mostly poet.): “signanda sunt jura,” Prop. 3
(4), 20, 15. “signata jura,” Luc. 3, 302: jura Suevis, Claud. ap. Eutr. 1, 380;
cf.: “precati deos ut velint ea (vota) semper solvi semperque signari,” Plin.
Ep. 10, 35 (44). To close, end: “qui prima novo signat quinquennia lustro,”
Mart. 4, 45, 3.—Hence, A. signan-ter , adv. (acc. to II. A.), expressly,
clearly, distinctly (late Lat. for the class. significanter): “signanter et
breviter omnia indicare,” Aus. Grat. Act. 4: “signanter et proprie dixerat,” Hier.
adv. Jovin. 1, 13 fin. signātus, a, um, P. a. 1. (Acc. to I. B. 1. sealed;
hence) Shut up, guarded, preserved (mostly ante- and post-class.): signata
sacra, Varr. ap. Non. 397, 32: limina. Prop. 4 (5), 1, 145. Chrysidem negat
signatam reddere, i. e. unharmed, intact, pure, Lucil. ap. Non. 171, 6; cf.:
“assume de viduis fide pulchram, aetate signatam,” Tert. Exhort. 12.— 2. (Acc.
to II. A.) Plain, clear, manifest (post-class. for “significans” – a back
formation!): “quid expressius atque signatius in hanc causam?” Tert. Res. Carn.Adv.:
signātē , clearly, distinctly (post-class.): “qui (veteres) proprie atque
signate locuti sunt,” Gell. 2, 6, 6; Macr. S. 6, 7 Comp.: “signatius explicare
aliquid,” Amm. 23, 6, 1. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Sign and sign-making – the Roman
signi-ficare, and beyond.”
significatum: or better ‘signatum.’ Grice knew that in old Roman,
signatum was intransitive, as originally ‘significatum’ was – “He is
signifying,” i. e. making signs. In the Middle Ages it was applied to ‘utens’
of this or that expression, as was an actum, ‘agitur,’ Thus an expression was
not said to ‘signify’ in the same way. Grice plays with the
expression-communication distinction. When dealing with a lexeme that does NOT
belong in the Graeco-Roman tradition, that of “mean,” he is never sure. His
doubts were hightlighted in essays on “Grice without an audience.” While Grice
explicitly says that a ‘word’ is not a sign, he would use ‘signify’ at a later
stage, including the implicaturum as part of the significatum. There is indeed
an entry for signĭfĭcātĭo, f. significare. L and S render it, unhelpfully,
as “a pointing out, indicating, denoting, signifying; an
expression, indication, mark, sign, token, = indicium,
signum, ἐπισημασία, etc., freq. and class. As with Stevenson’s ‘communico,’
Grice goes sraight to ‘signĭfĭco,’ also dep. “signĭfĭcor,” f.
‘significare,’ from signum-facere, to make sign, signum-facio, I make sign,
which L and S render as to signify, which is perhaps not too helpful. Grice, if
not the Grecians, knew that. Strictly, L and S render significare as to show by
signs; to show, point out, express, publish, make known, indicate; to intimate,
notify, signify, etc. Note that the cognate signify almost comes last, but not
least, if not first. Enough to want to coin a word to do duty for them all.
Which is what Grice (and the Grecians) can, but the old Romans cannot, with
mean. If that above were not enough, L and S go on, also, to betoken,
prognosticate, foreshow, portend, mean (syn. praedico), as in to betoken a
change of weather (post-Aug.): “ventus Africus tempestatem significat,
etc.,”cf. Grice on those dark clouds mean a storm is coming. Short
and Lewis go on, to say that significare may be rendered as to call, name; to
mean, import, signify. Hence, ‘signĭfĭcans,’ in rhet. lang., of
speech, full of meaning, expressive, significant; graphic, distinct,
clear: adv.: signĭfĭcanter, clearly, distinctly, expressly, significantly,
graphically: “breviter ac significanter ordinem rei protulisse;” “rem indicare
(with proprie),” “dicere (with
ornate),” “apertius, significantius
dignitatem alicujus defendere,” “narrare,”“disponere,” “appellare aliquid (with
consignatius);” “dicere (with probabilius).” -- signifier, a vocal sound or a
written symbol. The concept owes its modern formulation to the Swiss linguist
Saussure. Rather than using the older conception of sign and referent, he
divided the sign itself into two interrelated parts, a signifier and a
signified. The signified is the concept and the signifier is either a vocal
sound or writing. The relation between the two, according to Saussure, is
entirely arbitrary, in that signifiers tend to vary with different languages.
We can utter or write ‘vache’, ‘cow’, or ‘vaca’, depending on our native
language, and still come up with the same signified i.e., concept. H. P. Grice,
“Significatum and English ‘meaning.’”
simmel: Grice, “As Simmel would say, information is like
money – the giver hardly knows to what use the recipient is going to to put
it.” philosopher and one of the founders of sociology as a distinct discipline.
Born and educated in Berlin, he was a popular lecturer at its university. But
the unorthodoxy of his interests and unprofessional writing style probably kept
him from being offered a regular professorship until late in his career, and then
only at ‘provincial’ Strasbourg. He died four years later.Simmel’s writings range from conventional
philosophical topics with essays on
ethics, philosophy of history, education, religion, and the philosophers Kant,
Schopenhauer, and Nietzsche to essays on
Rembrandt, Goethe, and the philosophy of money. He wrote numerous essays on
various artists and poets, on different cities, and on such themes as love,
adventure, shame, and on being a stranger, as well as on many specifically
sociological topics. Simmel is regarded as a Kulturphilosoph who meditates on
his themes in an insightful and digressive rather than scholarly and systematic
style. Though late in life he sketches a unifying Lebensphilosophie that
considers all works and structures of culture as products of different forms of
human experience, Simmel has remained of interest primarily for a multiplicity
of insights into specific topics. Anyone who uses a
sentence of the form X is meeting a woman this evening would normally implicate
that the person to be met was someone other than X' s wife, mother, sister, or
perhaps even close platonic friend. Similarly, if I were to say X went into a
house yesterday and found a tortoise inside the front door, my hearer would
normally be surprised if some time later I revealed that the house was X's own.
I could produce similar linguistic phenomena involving the expressions a
garden, a car, a college, and so on. Sometimes, however, there would normally
be no such implicature ('I have been sitting in a car all morning'), and
sometimes a reverse implicature ('I broke a finger yesterday'). I am inclined
to think that one would not lend a sympathetic ear to a philosopher who
suggested that there are three senses of the form of expression an X: one in
which it means roughly 'something that satisfies the conditions defining the
word X,' another in which it means approximately 'an X (in the first sense)
that is only remotely related in a certain way to some person indicated by the
context,' and yet another in which it means 'an X (in the first sense) that is
closely related in a certain way to some person indicated by the context.'
Would we not much prefer an account on the following lines (which, of course,
may be incorrect in detail): I I ; .. ' Logic and Conversation 57 When someone,
by using the form of expression an X, implicates that the X does not belong to
or is not otherwise closely connected with some identifiable person, the
implicature is present l >ecause the speaker has failed to be specific in a
way in which he might have been expected to be specific, with the consequence
that it is likely to be assumed that he is not in a position to be specific.
This is a familiar implicature situation and is classifiable as a failure, for
one reason or another, to fulfill the first maxim of Quantity. The only
difficult question is why it should, in certain cases, be presumed,
independently of information about particular contexts of utterance, that
specification of the closeness or remoteness of the connection between a
particular person or object and a further person who is mentioned or indicated
by the utterance should be likely to be of interest. The answer must lie in the
following region: Transactions between a person and other persons or things
closely connected witl1 him are liable to be very different as regards their
concomitants and results from the same sort of transactions involving only
remotely connected persons or things; the concomitants and results, for
instance, of my finding a hole in MY roof are likely to be very different from
the concomitants and results of my finding a hole in someone else's roof.
Information, like money, is often given without the giver's knowing to just
what use the recipient will want to put it. If someone to whom a transaction is
mentioned gives it further consideration, he is likely to find himself wanting
the answers to further questions that the speaker may not be able to identify
in advance; if the appropriate specification will be likely to enable the
hearer to answer a considerable variety of such questions for himself, then
there is a presumption that the speaker should include it in his remark; if
not, then there is no such presumption.
simplicius: Grecian Neoplatonist philosopher. His
surviving works are extensive commentaries on Aristotle’s On the Heavens,
Physics, and Categories, and on the Encheiridion of Epictetus. The authenticity
of the commentary on Aristotle’s On the Soul attributed to Simplicius has been
disputed. He studied with Ammonius in Alexandria, and with Damascius, the last
known head of the Platonist school in Athens. Justinian closed the school in
529. Two or three years later a group of philosophers, including Damascius and
Simplicius, visited the court of the Sassanian king Khosrow I Chosroes but soon
returned to the Byzantine Empire under a guarantee of their right to maintain
their own beliefs. It is generally agreed that most, if not all, of
Simplicius’s extant works date from the period after his stay with Khosrow. But
there is no consensus about where Simplicius spent his last years both Athens
and Harran have been proposed recently, or whether he resumed teaching
philosophy; his commentaries, unlike most of the others that survive from that
period, are scholarly treatises rather than classroom expositions. Simplicius’s
Aristotle commentaries are the most valuable extant works in the genre. He is
our source for many of the fragments of the preSocratic philosophers, and he
frequently invokes material from now-lost commentaries and philosophical works.
He is a deeply committed Neoplatonist, convinced that there is no serious
conflict between the philosophies of Plato and Aristotle. The view of earlier
scholars that his Encheiridion commentary embodies a more moderate Platonism
associated with Alexandria is now generally rejected. Simplicius’s virulent
defense of the eternity of the world in response to the attack of the Christian
John Philoponus illustrates the intellectual vitality of paganism at a time
when the Mediterranean world had been officially Christian for about three
centuries. H. P. Grice, “Why we should
study Simplicius.”
simulation theory: Grice: “How does one simulate an
implicature? I challenge AI, so-called, to do it!” -- the view that one represents the mental
activities and processes of others by mentally simulating them, i.e.,
generating similar activities and processes in oneself. By simulating them, one
can anticipate their product or outcome; or, where this is already known, test
hypotheses about their starting point. For example, one anticipates the product
of another’s theoretical or practical inferences from given premises by making
inferences from the same premises oneself; or, knowing what the product is, one
retroduces the premises. In the case of practical reasoning, to reason from the
same premises would typically require indexical adjustments, such as shifts in
spatial, temporal, and personal “point of view,” to place oneself in the
other’s physical and epistemic situation insofar as it differs from one’s own.
One may also compensate for the other’s reasoning capacity and level of
expertise, if possible, or modify one’s character and outlook as an actor
might, to fit the other’s background. Such adjustments, even when insufficient
for making decisions in the role of the other, allow one to discriminate
between action options likely to be attractive or unattractive to the agent.
One would be prepared for the former actions and surprised by the latter. The
simulation theory is usually considered an alternative to an assumption
sometimes called the “theory theory” that underlies much recent philosophy of
mind: that our commonsense understanding of people rests on a speculative
theory, a “folk psychology” that posits mental states, events, and processes as
unobservables that explain behavior. Some hold that the simulation theory
undercuts the debate between philosophers who consider folk psychology a
respectable theory and those the eliminative materialists who reject it. Unlike
earlier writing on empathic understanding and historical reenactment,
discussions of the simulation theory often appeal to empirical findings,
particularly experimental results in developmental psychology. They also
theorize about the mechanism that would accomplish simulation: presumably one
that calls up computational resources ordinarily used for engagement with the
world, but runs them off-line, so that their output is not “endorsed” or acted
upon and their inputs are not limited to those that would regulate one’s own
behavior. Although simulation theorists agree that the ascription of mental
states to others relies chiefly on simulation, they differ on the nature of
selfascription. Some especially Robert Gordon and simple supposition simulation
theory 845 845 Jane Heal, who
independently proposed the theory give a non-introspectionist account, while
others especially Goldman lean toward a more traditional introspectionist
account. The simulation theory has affected developmental psychology as well as
branches of philosophy outside the philosophy of mind, especially aesthetics
and philosophy of the social sciences. Some philosophers believe it sheds light
on traditional topics such as the problem of other minds, referential opacity,
broad and narrow content, and the peculiarities of self-knowledge.
singulare: singular term -- singŭlāris
, e, adj. singuli. I. Lit. A. In gen., one by one, one at a time, alone,
single, solitary; alone of its kind, singular (class.; “syn.: unus, unicus):
non singulare nec solivagum genus (sc. homines),” i. e. solitary, Cic. Rep. 1,
25, 39: “hostes ubi ex litore aliquos singulares ex navi egredientes
conspexerant,” Caes. B. G. 4, 26: “homo,” id. ib. 7, 8, 3; so, “homo (with
privatus, and opp. isti conquisiti coloni),” Cic. Agr. 2, 35, 97: “singularis
mundus atque unigena,” id. Univ. 4 med.: “praeconium Dei singularis facere,”
Lact. 4, 4, 8; cf. Cic. Ac. 1, 7, 26: “natus,” Plin. 28, 10, 42, § 153: “herba
(opp. fruticosa),” id. 27, 9, 55, § 78: singularis ferus, a wild boar (hence,
Fr. sanglier), Vulg. Psa. 79, 14: “hominem dominandi cupidum aut imperii singularis,”
sole command, exclusive dominion, Cic. Rep. 1, 33, 50; so, “singulare imperium
et potestas regia,” id. ib. 2, 9, 15: “sunt quaedam in te singularia ...
quaedam tibi cum multis communia,” Cic. Verr. 2, 3, 88, § 206: “singulare
beneficium (opp. commune officium civium),” id. Fam. 1, 9, 4: “odium (opp.
communis invidia),” id. Sull. 1, 1: “quam invisa sit singularis potentia et
miseranda vita,” Nep. Dion, 9, 5: “pugna,” Macr. S. 5, 2: “si quando quid
secreto agere proposuisset, erat illi locus in edito singularis,” particular,
separate, Suet. Aug. 72.— B. In partic. 1. In gram., of or belonging to unity,
singular: “singularis casus,” Varr. L. L. 7, § 33 Müll.; “10, § 54 ib.:
numerus,” Quint. 1, 5, 42; 1, 6, 25; 8, 3, 20; Gell. 19, 8, 13: “nominativus,”
Quint. 1, 6, 14: “genitivus,” id. 1, 6, 26 et saep. —Also absol., the singular
number: “alii dicunt in singulari hac ovi et avi, alii hac ove et ave,” Varr.
L. L. 8, § 66 Müll.; Quint. 8, 6, 28; 4, 5, 25 al.— 2. In milit lang., subst.:
singŭlāris , is, m. a. In gen., an orderly man (ordonance), assigned to
officers of all kinds and ranks for executing their orders (called apparitor,
Lampr. Alex. Sev. 52): “SINGVLARIS COS (consulis),” Inscr. Orell. 2003; cf. ib.
3529 sq.; 3591; 6771 al.— b. Esp., under the emperors, equites singulares
Augusti, or only equites singulares, a select horse body-guard (selected from
barbarous nations, as Bessi, Thraces, Bæti, etc.), Tac. H. 4, 70; Hyg. m. c. §§
23 and 30; Inscr. Grut. 1041, 12 al.; cf. on the Singulares, Henzen, Sugli
Equiti Singolari, Roma, 1850; Becker, Antiq. tom. 3, pass. 2, p. 387 sq.— 3. In
the time of the later emperors, singulares, a kind of imperial clerks, sent
into the provinces, Cod. Just. 1, 27, 1, § 8; cf. Lyd. Meg. 3, 7.— II. Trop.,
singular, unique, matchless, unparalleled, extraordinary, remarkable (syn.:
unicus, eximius, praestans; “very freq. both in a good and in a bad sense):
Aristoteles meo judicio in philosophiā prope singularis,” Cic. Ac. 2, 43, 132:
“Cato, summus et singularis vir,” id. Brut. 85, 293: “vir ingenii naturā
praestans, singularis perfectusque undique,” Quint. 12, 1, 25; so, “homines
ingenio atque animo,” Cic. Div. 2, 47, 97: “adulescens,” Plin. Ep. 7, 24, 2.—Of
things: “Antonii incredibilis quaedam et prope singularis et divina vis ingenii
videtur,” Cic. de Or. 1, 38, 172: “singularis eximiaque virtus,” id. Imp. Pomp.
1, 3; so, “singularis et incredibilis virtus,” id. Att. 14, 15, 3; cf. id. Fam.
1, 9, 4: “integritas atque innocentia singularis,” id. Div. in Caecil. 9, 27: “Treviri,
quorum inter Gallos virtutis opinio est singularis,” Caes. B. G. 2, 24:
“Pompeius gratias tibi agit singulares,” Cic. Fam. 13, 41, 1; cf.: “mihi
gratias egistis singularibus verbis,” id. Cat. 4, 3: “fides,” Nep. Att. 4:
“singulare omnium saeculorum exemplum,” Just. 2, 4, 6.—In a bad sense:
“nequitia ac turpitudo singularis,” Cic. Verr. 2, 3, 44, § 106; so, “nequitia,”
id. ib. 2, 2, 54, § 134; id. Fin. 5, 20, 56: “impudentia,” Cic. Verr. 2, 2, 7,
§ 18: audacia (with scelus incredibile), id. Fragm. ap. Quint. 4, 2, 105:
“singularis et nefaria crudelitas,” Caes. B. G. 7, 77.— Hence, adv.:
singŭlārĭter (singlā-rĭter , Lucr. 6, 1067). 1. One by one, singly, separately.
a. In gen. (ante- and post-class.): “quae memorare queam inter se singlariter
apta, Lucr. l. l. Munro (Lachm. singillariter): a juventā singulariter sedens,”
apart, separately, Paul. Nol. Carm. 21, 727.— b. In partic. (acc. to I. B. 1.),
in the singular number: “quod pluralia singulariter et singularia pluraliter
efferuntur,” Quint. 1, 5, 16; 1, 7, 18; 9, 3, 20: “dici,” Gell. 19, 8, 12; Dig.
27, 6, 1 al.— 2. (Acc. to II.) Particularly, exceedingly: “aliquem diligere,”
Cic. Verr. 2, 2, 47, § 117: “et miror et diligo,” Plin. Ep. 1, 22, 1: “amo,”
id. ib. 4, 15, 1. Grice: “I would define a ‘singular implicaturum’ as
any vehicle of communicatum such as an expression, like ‘Zeus’, ‘Pegasus,’ ‘the
President’, ‘Strawson’s dog,’ ‘Fido,’ or ‘my favorite chair’, that can be the
grammatical subject of what is semantically a subject-predicate sentence.” Grice:
“By contrast, what one might call a ‘general,’ or ‘non-singular term, such as ‘horse,’
‘dog,’‘table’ or ‘swam’ is one that can serve in predicative position.” It is
also often said that a singular term (‘nomen singularis,’ ‘expressio
singularis’) is a word or phrase that could refer or ostensibly refer, on a
given occasion of use, only to a single (or ‘singular’) object – unless you
show me a ‘general’ object --, whereas a general term is predicable of *more
than one* singular object, if not a ‘general’ object, which does not exist. A
singular term is thus the expression that replace, or are replaced by, an individual
variable (x, y, z, …) in applications of such quantifier rules as universal
instantiation and existential generalization or flank ‘%’ in identity
statements.” H. P. Grice, “System G: the rudiments.”
situation ethics, a kind of anti-theoretical,
caseby-case applied ethics in vogue largely in some European and religious circles for twenty years or so
following World War II. It is characterized by the insistence that each moral
choice must be determined by one’s particular context or situation i.e., by a consideration of the outcomes that
various possible courses of action might have, given one’s situation. To that
degree, situation ethics has affinities to both act utilitarianism and
traditional casuistry. But in contrast to utilitarianism, situation ethics
rejects the idea that there are universal or even fixed moral principles beyond
various indeterminate commitments or ideals e.g., to Christian love or
humanism. In contrast to traditional casuistry, it rejects the effort to
construct general guidelines from a case or to classify the salient features of
a case so that it can be used as a precedent. The anti-theoretical stance of
situation ethics is so thoroughgoing that writers identified with the position
have not carefully described its connections to consequentialism,
existentialism, intuitionism, personalism, pragmatism, relativism, or any other
developed philosophical view to which it appears to have some affinity.
st. john’s: st. john’s keeps a record of all of H. P. Grice’s
tutees. It is fascinating that Strawson’s closest collaboration, as Plato with
Socrates, and Aristotle with Plato, was with his tutee Strawson – whom Grice
calls a ‘pupil,’ finding ‘tutee’ too French to his taste. G. J. Warnock recalls
that, of all the venues that the play group held, their favourite one was the
room overlooking the garden at st. john’s. “It’s one of the best gardens in
England, you know. Very peripathetic.” In alphabetical order, some of his
English ‘gentlemanly’ tutees include: London-born J. L. Ackrill, London-born
David Bostock, London-born A. G. N. Flew, Leeds-born T. C. Potts, London-born
P. F. Strawson. They were happy to have Grice as a tutorial fellow, since he,
unlike Mabbot, was English, and did not instill on the tutees a vernacular
furrin to the area.
skolem: semanticist, he made fundamental contributions to
recursion theory (Grice: “which I need for my account of communication”), set
theory in particular, the proposal and formulation of the axiom of replacement,
and model theory. The first work devoted exclusively
to recursive definability was Skolem’s (1923) paper The foundations of
elementary arithmetic established by the recursive mode of thought, without the
use of apparent variables ranging over infinite domains. This work is
significant with respect to the subsequent development of computability theory
for at least three reasons. First, it contains a informal description of what
we now call the primitive recursive functions. Second, it can be regarded as
the first place where recursive definability is linked to effective
computability (see also Skolem 1946). And third, it demonstrates that a wide
range of functions and relations are primitive recursive in a manner which
anticipates Gödel’s (1931) use of primitive recursion for the arithmetization
of syntax. One of Skolem’s stated goals was to present a logical
foundation for number theory which avoids the use of unrestricted quantifiers.
He was inspired in this regard by the observation that it is possible to
develop much of elementary arithmetic without the use of the expressions
“always” (i.e. for all) and “sometimes” (i.e. there exists) which figure in the
formalization of number theory given by Russell and Whitehead in Principia
Mathematica (1910–1913). This was to be accomplished by formulating
arithmetical theorems as what he referred to as functional assertions. These
took the form of identities between terms defined by primitive recursive
operations which Skolem referred to as descriptive functions. For instance, the
commutativity of addition is expressed in this form by an equation with free
variables x+y=y+x In cases where such statements are provable in
the system Skolem describes, the intended interpretation is that the claim
holds universally for all natural numbers—e.g., ∀x∀y(x+y=y+x).
But in Skolem’s system there is no means of negating such a statement to express
a bare existential assertion without producing a witness. Statements like
(5) would later be referred to by Hilbert & Bernays (1934) (who provided
the first textbook treatment of recursion) as verifiable in the sense that
their individual instances can be verified computationally by replacing
variables with concrete numerals. This is accomplished by what Skolem referred
to as the “recursive mode of thought”. The sense of this phrase is clarified by
the following properties of the system he describes: the natural numbers
are taken as basic objects together with the successor function x+1; it is
assumed that descriptive functions proven to be equal may be substituted for
one another in other expressions; all definitions of functions and relations on
natural numbers are given by recursion; functional assertions such as (5) must
be proven by induction. Taking these principles as a foundation, Skolem showed
how to obtain recursive definitions of the predecessor and subtraction
functions, the less than, divisibility, and primality relations, greatest
common divisors, least common multiples, and bounded sums and products which
are similar to those given in Section 2.1.2 below. Overall Skolem
considered instances of what we would now refer to as primitive recursion,
course of values recursion, double recursion, and recursion on functions of
type N→N. He did not, however, introduce general schemas so as to systematically
distinguish these modes of definition. Nonetheless, properties i–iv of Skolem’s
treatment provide a means of assimilating calculations like (2) to derivations
in quantifier-free first-order logic. It is thus not difficult to discern in
(Skolem 1923) the kernel of the system we now know as Primitive Recursive
Arithmetic (as later formally introduced by Hilbert & Bernays 1934, ch. 7). Skolem’s most important results for philosophical
semantics are the Downward Löwenheim-Skolem theorem, whose first proof involved
putting formulas into Skolem normal form; and a demonstration of the existence
of models of first-order arithmetic not isomorphic to the standard model. Both
results exhibit the extreme non-categoricity that can occur with formulations
of mathematical theories in first-order logic, and causes Skolem to be sceptical
about the use of a formal systems such as System G (after Grice), particularly
for set theory, as a foundation for semantics. The existence of non-standard
models is actually a consequence of the completeness and first incompleteness
theorems by Gödel, for these together show that there must be sentences of
arithmetic if consistent that are true in the standard model, but false in some
other, nonisomorphic model. However, Skolem’s result describes a general
technique for constructing such models. Skolem’s theorem is now more easily
proved using the compactness theorem, an easy consequence of the completeness
theorem. The Löwenheim-Skolem theorem produces a similar problem of
characterization, Skolem’s paradox. Roughly, Skolem’s paradox says that if
first-order set theory has a model, it must also have a countable model whose
continuum is a countable set, and thus apparently non-standard. This does not
contradict Cantor’s theorem, which merely demands that the countable model
contain as an element no function that maps its natural numbers one-toone onto
its continuum, although there must be such a function outside the model.
Although usually seen as limiting first-order logic, this result is extremely
fruitful technically, providing one basis of the proof of the independence of
the continuum hypothesis from the usual axioms of set theory given by Gödel and
Cohen. This connection between independence results and the existence of
countable models was partially foreseen by Skolem. Refs.: H. P. Grice,
“Skolem’s recursive implicatura.” Skolem, Thoralf,
1923, “Begründung Der Elementaren Arithmetik Durch Die Rekurrierende Denkweise
Ohne Anwendung Scheinbarer Veranderlichen Mit Unendlichem Ausdehnungsbereich”,
Videnskapsselskapets Skrifter, I. Matematisk-Naturvidenskabelig Klasse, 6:
1–38. –––, 1946, “The development of recursive arithmetic” In Dixíeme Congrés
des Mathimaticiens Scandinaves, Copenhagen, 1–16. Reprinted in Skolem 1970, pp.
499–415. –––, 1970, Selected Works in Logic Olso: Universitetsforlaget. Edited
by J.E. Fenstad.
Recursum: Grice, ‘anti-sneak.”
Grice, “philosophical semanticist.”
slippery slope argument, an argument that an action
apparently unobjectionable in itself would set in motion a train of events
leading ultimately to an undesirable outcome. The metaphor portrays one on the
edge of a slippery slope, where taking the first step down will inevitably
cause sliding to the bottom. For example, it is sometimes argued that voluntary
euthanasia should not be legalized because this will lead to killing unwanted
people, e.g. the handicapped or elderly, against their will. In some versions
the argument aims to show that one should intervene to stop an ongoing train of
events; e.g., it has been argued that suppressing a Communist revolution in one
country was necessary to prevent the spread of Communism throughout a whole
region via the so-called domino effect. Slippery slope arguments with dubious
causal assumptions are often classed as fallacies under the general heading of
the fallacy of the false cause. This argument is also sometimes called the
wedge argument. There is some disagreement concerning the breadth of the
category of slippery slope arguments. Some would restrict the term to arguments
with evaluative conclusions, while others construe it more broadly so as to
include other sorites arguments.
smart and place: Cambridge-born Australian philosopher
whose name is associated with three very non-Oxonian doctrines in particular:
the mind-body identity theory, scientific realism, and utilitarianism. A
student of Ryle’s at Oxford, from the other place, he rejected logical
behaviorism in favor of what came to be known as Australian or ‘colonial’ or
“Dominion” materialism. This is the view that mental processes and, as, -- “the other colonial,” – Grice -- Armstrong
brought Smart to see, mental states
cannot be explained simply in terms of behavioristic dispositions. In
order to make good sense of how the ordinary person talks of them we have to
see them as brain processes and
states under other names. Smart
developed this identity theory of mind and brain, under the stimulus of his
colleague, Yorkshire-born, Rugby and Corpus-Christi (via Open Scholarship),
tutee of Ryle, U. T. Place, in “Sensations and Brain Processes” Philosophical
Review. It became a mainstay of twentieth-century philosophy. Smart endorsed
the materialist analysis of mind on the grounds that it gave a simple picture
that was consistent with the findings of science. He took a realist view of the
claims of science, rejecting phenomenalism, instrumentalism, and the like, and
he argued that commonsense beliefs should be maintained only so far as they are
plausible in the light of total science. Philosophy and Scientific Realism 3
gave forceful expression to this physicalist picture of the world, as did some
later works. He attracted attention in particular for his argument that if we
take science seriously then we have to endorse the four-dimensional picture of
the universe and recognize as an illusion the experience of the passing of
time. He published a number of defenses of utilitarianism, the best known being
his contribution to J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism, For
and Against 3. He gave new life to act utilitarianism at a time when
utilitarians were few and most were attached to rule utilitarianism or other
restricted forms of the doctrine. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Ryle and the devil of
scientism,” H. P. Grice, “What Smart learned from Ryle.”
smith: Scots philosopher, a founder of modern political
economy and a major contributor to ethics and the psychology of morals. His
first published work is “The Theory of Moral Sentiments.” This book immediately
made him famous, and earned the praise of thinkers of the stature of Hume,
Burke, and Kant. It sought to answer two questions: Wherein does virtue
consist, and by means of what psychological principles do we determine this or
that to be virtuous or the contrary? His answer to the first combined ancient
Stoic and Aristotelian views of virtue with modern views derived from Hutcheson
and others. His answer to the second built on Hume’s theory of sympathy our ability to put ourselves imaginatively in
the situation of another as well as on
the notion of the “impartial spectator.” Smith throughout is skeptical about
metaphysical and theological views of virtue and of the psychology of morals.
The self-understanding of reasonable moral actors ought to serve as the moral
philosopher’s guide. Smith’s discussion ranges from the motivation of wealth to
the psychological causes of religious and political fanaticism. Smith’s second
published work, the immensely influential An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes
of the Wealth of Nations 1776, attempts to explain why free economic,
political, and religious markets are not only more efficient, when properly
regulated, but also more in keeping with nature, more likely to win the
approval of an impartial spectator, than monopolistic alternatives. Taken
together, Smith’s two books attempt to show how virtue and liberty can
complement each other. He shows full awareness of the potentially dehumanizing
force of what was later called “capitalism,” and sought remedies in schemes for
liberal education and properly organized religion. Smith did not live to
complete his system, which was to include an analysis of “natural
jurisprudence.” We possess student notes of his lectures on jurisprudence and
on rhetoric, as well as several impressive essays on the evolution of the
history of science and on the fine arts.
co-agency: social action: Grice: “My principle of
co-operation you can call the ‘conversational contract.’ In this respect, I
agree with Grice: Grice: “When I speak of conversation, I mean of a social
action – where one agent’s expectations influence his co-agent’s” -- a subclass
of human action involving the interaction among agents and their mutual
orientation, or the action of groups. While all intelligible actions are in
some sense social, social actions must be directed to others. Talcott Parsons
279 captured what is distinctive about social action in his concept of “double
contingency,” and similar concepts have been developed by other philosophers
and sociologists, including Weber, Mead, and Vitters. Whereas in monological
action the agents’ fulfilling their purposes depends only on contingent facts
about the world, the success of social action is also contingent on how other
agents react to what the agent does and how that agent reacts to other agents,
and so on. An agent successfully communicates, e.g., not merely by finding some
appropriate expression in an existing symbol system, but also by understanding
how other agents will understand him. Game theory describes and explains
another type of double contingency in its analysis of the interdependency of
choices and strategies among rational agents. Games are also significant in two
other respects. First, they exemplify the cognitive requirements for social
interaction, as in Mead’s analysis of agents’ perspective taking: as a subject
“I”, I am an object for others “me”, and can take a third-person perspective
along with others on the interaction itself “the generalized other”. Second,
games are regulated by shared rules and mediated through symbolic meanings;
Vitters’s private language argument establishes that rules cannot be followed
“privately.” Some philosophers, such as Peter Winch, conclude from this
argument that rule-following is a basic feature of distinctively social action.
Some actions are social in the sense that they can only be done in groups.
Individualists such as Weber, Jon Elster, and Raimo Tuomela believe that these
can be analyzed as the sum of the actions of each individual. But holists such
as Marx, Durkheim, and Margaret Gilbert reject this reduction and argue that in
social actions agents must see themselves as members of a collective agent.
Holism has stronger or weaker versions: strong holists, such as Durkheim and
Hegel, see the collective subject as singular, the collective consciousness of
a society. Weak holists, such as Gilbert and Habermas, believe that social
actions have plural, rather than singular, collective subjects. Holists
generally establish the plausibility of their view by referring to larger
contexts and sequences of action, such as shared symbol systems or social
institutions. Explanations of social actions thus refer not only to the mutual
expectations of agents, but also to these larger causal contexts, shared
meanings, and mechanisms of coordination. Theories of social action must then explain
the emergence of social order, and proposals range from Hobbes’s coercive
authority to Talcott Parsons’s value consensus about shared goals among the
members of groups. -- social biology,
the understanding of social behavior, especially human social behavior, from a
biological perspective; often connected with the political philosophy of social
Darwinism. Charles Darwin’s Origin of Species highlighted the significance of
social behavior in organic evolution, and in the Descent of Man, he showed how
significant such behavior is for humans. He argued that it is a product of
natural selection; but it was not until 4 that the English biologist William
Hamilton showed precisely how such behavior could evolve, namely through “kin
selection” as an aid to the biological wellbeing of close relatives. Since
then, other models of explanation have been proposed, extending the theory to
non-relatives. Best known is the self-describing “reciprocal altruism.” Social
biology became notorious in 5 when Edward O. Wilson published a major treatise
on the subject: Sociobiology: The New Synthesis. Accusations of sexism and
racism were leveled because Wilson suggested that Western social systems are
biologically innate, and that in some respects males are stronger, more aggressive,
more naturally promiscuous than females. Critics argued that all social biology
is in fact a manifestation of social Darwinism, a nineteenthcentury philosophy
owing more to Herbert Spencer than to Charles Darwin, supposedly legitimating
extreme laissez-faire economics and an unbridled societal struggle for
existence. Such a charge is extremely serious, for as Moore pointed out in his
Principia Ethica 3, Spencer surely commits the naturalistic fallacy, inasmuch
as he is attempting to derive the way that the world ought to be from the way
that it is. Naturally enough, defenders of social biology, or “sociobiology” as
it is now better known, denied vehemently that their science is mere right-wing
ideology by another name. They pointed to many who have drawn very different
social conclusions on the basis of biology. Best known is the Russian anarchist
Kropotkin, who argued that societies are properly based on a biological
propensity to mutual aid. With respect to contemporary debate, it is perhaps
fairest to say that sociobiology, particularly that pertaining to humans, did
not always show sufficient sensitivity toward all societal groups although certainly there was never the crude
racism of the fascist regimes of the 0s. However, recent work is far more
careful in these respects. Now, indeed, the study of social behavior from a
biological perspective is one of the most exciting and forward-moving branches
of the life sciences. -- social choice
theory, the theory of the rational action of a group of agents. Important
social choices are typically made over alternative means of collectively
providing goods. These might be goods for individual members of the group, or
more characteristically, public goods, goods such that no one can be excluded
from enjoying their benefits once they are available. Perhaps the most central
aspect of social choice theory concerns rational individual choice in a social
context. Since what is rational for one agent to do will often depend on what
is rational for another to do and vice versa, these choices take on a strategic
dimension. The prisoner’s dilemma illustrates how it can be very difficult to
reconcile individual and collectively rational decisions, especially in
non-dynamic contexts. There are many situations, particularly in the provision
of public goods, however, where simple prisoner’s dilemmas can be avoided and
more manageable coordination problems remain. In these cases, individuals may
find it rational to contractually or conventionally bind themselves to courses
of action that lead to the greater good of all even though they are not
straightforwardly utility-maximizing for particular individuals. Establishing
the rationality of these contracts or conventions is one of the leading
problems of social choice theory, because coordination can collapse if a
rational agent first agrees to cooperate and then reneges and becomes a free
rider on the collective efforts of others. Other forms of uncooperative
behaviors such as violating rules established by society or being deceptive
about one’s preferences pose similar difficulties. Hobbes attempted to solve
these problems by proposing that people would agree to submit to the authority
of a sovereign whose punitive powers would make uncooperative behavior an
unattractive option. It has also been argued that cooperation is rational if
the concept of rationality is extended beyond utility-maximizing in the right
way. Other arguments stress benefits beyond selfinterest that accrue to
cooperators. Another major aspect of social choice theory concerns the rational
action of a powerful central authority, or social planner, whose mission is to
optimize the social good. Although the central planner may be instituted by
rational individual choice, this part of the theory simply assumes the
institution. The planner’s task of making a onetime allocation of resources to
the production of various commodities is tractable if social good or social
utility is known as a function of various commodities. When the planner must
take into account dynamical considerations, the technical problems are more
difficult. This economic growth theory raises important ethical questions about
intergenerational conflict. The assumption of a social analogue of the
individual utility functions is particularly worrisome. It can be shown
formally that taking the results of majority votes can lead to intransitive
social orderings of possible choices and it is, therefore, a generally
unsuitable procedure for the planner to follow. Moreover, under very general
conditions there is no way of aggregating individual preferences into a
consistent social choice function of the kind needed by the planner. -- social constructivism, also called social
constructionism, any of a variety of views which claim that knowledge in some
area is the product of our social practices and institutions, or of the
interactions and negotiations between relevant social groups. Mild versions
hold that social factors shape interpretations of the world. Stronger versions
maintain that the world, or some significant portion of it, is somehow
constituted by theories, practices, and institutions. Defenders often move from
mild to stronger versions by insisting that the world is accessible to us only
through our interpretations, and that the idea of an independent reality is at
best an irrelevant abstraction and at worst incoherent. This philosophical
position is distinct from, though distantly related to, a view of the same name
in social and developmental psychology, associated with such figures as Piaget and
Lev Vygotsky, which sees learning as a process in which subjects actively
construct knowledge. Social constructivism has roots in Kant’s idealism, which
claims that we cannot know things in themselves and that knowledge of the world
is possible only by imposing pre-given categories of thought on otherwise
inchoate experience. But where Kant believed that the categories with which we
interpret and thus construct the world are given a priori, contemporary
constructivists believe that the relevant concepts and associated practices
vary from one group or historical period to another. Since there are no
independent standards for evaluating conceptual schemes, social constructivism
leads naturally to relativism. These views are generally thought to be present in
Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, which argues that observation
and methods in science are deeply theory-dependent and that scientists with
fundamentally different assumptions or paradigms effectively live in different
worlds. Kuhn thus offers a view of science in opposition to both scientific
realism which holds that theory-dependent methods can give us knowledge of a
theory-independent world and empiricism which draws a sharp line between theory
and observation. Kuhn was reluctant to accept the apparently radical
consequences of his views, but his work has influenced recent social studies of
science, whose proponents frequently embrace both relativism and strong
constructivism. Another influence is the principle of symmetry advocated by David
Bloor and Barry Barnes, which holds that sociologists should explain the
acceptance of scientific views in the same way whether they believe those views
to be true or to be false. This approach is elaborated in the work of Harry
Collins, Steve Woolgar, and others. Constructivist themes are also prominent in
the work of feminist critics of science such as Sandra Harding and Donna
Haraway, and in the complex views of Bruno Latour. Critics, such as Richard
Boyd and Philip Kitcher, while applauding the detailed case studies produced by
constructivists, claim that the positive arguments for constructivism are
fallacious, that it fails to account satisfactorily for actual scientific
practice, and that like other versions of idealism and relativism it is only dubiously
coherent. Then there’s the idea of a
‘contract,’ or social contract, an agreement either between the people and
their ruler, or among the people in a community. The idea of a social contract
has been used in arguments that differ in what they aim to justify or explain
e.g., the state, conceptions of justice, morality, what they take the problem
of justification to be, and whether or not they presuppose a moral theory or
purport to be a moral theory. Traditionally the term has been used in arguments
that attempt to explain the nature of political obligation and/or the kind of
responsibility that rulers have to their subjects. Philosophers such as Plato,
Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, and Kant argue that human beings would find life in a
prepolitical “state of nature” a state that some argue is also presocietal so
difficult that they would agree either
with one another or with a prospective ruler
to the creation of political institutions that each believes would
improve his or her lot. Note that because the argument explains political or
social cohesion as the product of an agreement among individuals, it makes
these individuals conceptually prior to political or social units. Marx and
other socialist and communitarian thinkers have argued against conceptualizing
an individual’s relationship to her political and social community in this way.
Have social contracts in political societies actually taken place? Hume
ridicules the idea that they are real, and questions what value makebelieve
agreements can have as explanations of actual political obligations. Although
many social contract theorists admit that there is almost never an explicit act
of agreement in a community, nonetheless they maintain that such an agreement
is implicitly made when members of the society engage in certain acts through
which they give their tacit consent to the ruling regime. It is controversial
what actions constitute giving tacit consent: Plato and Locke maintain that the
acceptance of benefits is sufficient to give such consent, but some have argued
that it is wrong to feel obliged to those who foist upon us benefits for which
we have not asked. It is also unclear how much of an obligation a person can be
under if he gives only tacit consent to a regime. How are we to understand the
terms of a social contract establishing a state? When the people agree to obey
the ruler, do they surrender their own power to him, as Hobbes tried to argue?
Or do they merely lend him that power, reserving the right to take it from him
if and when they see fit, as Locke maintained? If power is merely on loan to
the ruler, rebellion against him could be condoned if he violates the
conditions of that loan. But if the people’s grant of power is a surrender,
there are no such conditions, and the people could never be justified in taking
back that power via revolution. Despite controversies surrounding their
interpretation, social contract arguments have been important to the
development of modern democratic states: the idea of the government as the
creation of the people, which they can and should judge and which they have the
right to overthrow if they find it wanting, contributed to the development of
democratic forms of polity in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. and
revolutionaries explicitly acknowledged their debts to social contract
theorists such as Locke and Rousseau. In the twentieth century, the social
contract idea has been used as a device for defining various moral conceptions
e.g. theories of justice by those who find its focus on individuals useful in
the development of theories that argue against views e.g. utilitarianism that
allow individuals to be sacrificed for the benefit of the group -- social
epistemology, the study of the social dimensions or determinants of knowledge,
or the ways in which social factors promote or perturb the quest for knowledge.
Some writers use the term ‘knowledge’ loosely, as designating mere belief. On
their view social epistemology should simply describe how social factors
influence beliefs, without concern for the rationality or truth of these
beliefs. Many historians and sociologists of science, e.g., study scientific
practices in the same spirit that anthropologists study native cultures,
remaining neutral about the referential status of scientists’ constructs or the
truth-values of their beliefs. Others try to show that social factors like
political or professional interests are causally operative, and take such
findings to debunk any objectivist pretensions of science. Still other writers
retain a normative, critical dimension in social epistemology, but do not
presume that social practices necessarily undermine objectivity. Even if
knowledge is construed as true or rational belief, social practices might
enhance knowledge acquisition. One social practice is trusting the opinions of
authorities, a practice that can produce truth if the trusted authorities are
genuinely authoritative. Such trust may also be perfectly rational in a complex
world, where division of epistemic labor is required. Even a scientist’s
pursuit of extra-epistemic interests such as professional rewards may not be
antithetical to truth in favorable circumstances. Institutional provisions,
e.g., judicial rules of evidence, provide another example of social factors.
Exclusionary rules might actually serve the cause of truth or accuracy in
judgment if the excluded evidence would tend to mislead or prejudice
jurors. -- social philosophy, broadly
the philosophy of socisocial Darwinism social philosophy 856 856 ety, including the philosophy of social
science and many of its components, e.g., economics and history, political
philosophy, most of what we now think of as ethics, and philosophy of law. But
we may distinguish two narrower senses. In one, it is the conceptual theory of
society, including the theory of the study of society the common part of all the philosophical
studies mentioned. In the other, it is a normative study, the part of moral
philosophy that concerns social action and individual involvement with society
in general. The central job of social philosophy in the first of these narrower
senses is to articulate the correct notion or concept of society. This would
include formulating a suitable definition of ‘society’; the question is then
which concepts are better for which purposes, and how they are related. Thus we
may distinguish “thin” and “thick” conceptions of society. The former would
identify the least that can be said before we cease talking about society at
all say, a number of people who
interact, whose actions affect the behavior of their fellows. Thicker
conceptions would then add such things as community rules, goals, customs, and
ideals. An important empirical question is whether any interacting groups ever
do lack such things and what if anything is common to the rules, etc., that
actual societies have. Descriptive social philosophy will obviously border on,
if not merge into, social science itself, e.g. into sociology, social
psychology, or economics. And some outlooks in social philosophy will tend to
ally with one social science as more distinctively typical than others e.g., the individualist view looks to
economics, the holist to sociology. A major methodological controversy concerns
holism versus individualism. Holism maintains that at least some social groups
must be studied as units, irreducible to their members: we cannot understand a
society merely by understanding the actions and motivations of its members.
Individualism denies that societies are “organisms,” and holds that we can
understand society only in that way. Classic G. sociologists e.g., Weber
distinguished between Gesellschaft, whose paradigm is the voluntary
association, such as a chess club, whose activities are the coordinated actions
of a number of people who intentionally join that group in order to pursue the
purposes that identify it; and Gemeinschaft, whose members find their
identities in that group. Thus, the are
not a group whose members teamed up with like-minded people to form society. They were before they had separate individual purposes.
The holist views society as essentially a Gemeinschaft. Individualists agree
that there are such groupings but deny that they require a separate kind of
irreducibly collective explanation: to understand the we must understand how typical individuals behave compared, say, with the G.s, and so on. The
methods of Western economics typify the analytical tendencies of methodological
individualism, showing how we can understand large-scale economic phenomena in
terms of the rational actions of particular economic agents. Cf. Adam Smith’s
invisible hand thesis: each economic agent seeks only his own good, yet the
result is the macrophenomenal good of the whole. Another pervasive issue
concerns the role of intentional characterizations and explanations in these
fields. Ordinary people explain behavior by reference to its purposes, and they
formulate these in terms that rely on public rules of language and doubtless
many other rules. To understand society, we must hook onto the
selfunderstanding of the people in that society this view is termed Verstehen.
Recent work in philosophy of science raises the question whether intentional
concepts can really be fundamental in explaining anything, and whether we must
ultimately conceive people as in some sense material systems, e.g. as
computer-like. Major questions for the program of replicating human
intelligence in data-processing terms cf. artificial intelligence are raised by
the symbolic aspects of interaction. Additionally, we should note the emergence
of sociobiology as a potent source of explanations of social phenomena.
Normative social philosophy, in turn, tends inevitably to merge into either
politics or ethics, especially the part of ethics dealing with how people ought
to treat others, especially in large groups, in relation to social institutions
or social structures. This contrasts with ethics in the sense concerned with
how individual people may attain the good life for themselves. All such
theories allot major importance to social relations; but if one’s theory leaves
the individual wide freedom of choice, then a theory of individually chosen
goods will still have a distinctive subject matter. The normative involvements
of social philosophy have paralleled the foregoing in important ways. Individualists
have held that the good of a society must be analyzed in terms of the goods of
its individual members. Of special importance has been the view that society
must respect indisocial philosophy social philosophy 857 857 vidual rights, blocking certain actions
alleged to promote social good as a whole. Organicist philosophers such as
Hegel hold that it is the other way around: the state or nation is higher than
the individual, who is rightly subordinated to it, and individuals have
fundamental duties toward the groups of which they are members. Outrightly
fascist versions of such views are unpopular today, but more benign versions
continue in modified form, notably by communitarians. Socialism and especially
communism, though focused originally on economic aspects of society, have
characteristically been identified with the organicist outlook. Their extreme
opposite is to be found in the libertarians, who hold that the right to
individual liberty is fundamental in society, and that no institutions may override
that right. Libertarians hold that society ought to be treated strictly as an
association, a Gesellschaft, even though they might not deny that it is
ontogenetically Gemeinschaft. They might agree that religious groups, e.g.,
cannot be wholly understood as separate individuals. Nevertheless, the
libertarian holds that religious and cultural practices may not be interfered
with or even supported by society. Libertarians are strong supporters of
free-market economic methods, and opponents of any sort of state intervention
into the affairs of individuals. Social Darwinism, advocating the “survival of
the socially fittest,” has sometimes been associated with the libertarian view.
Insofar as there is any kind of standard view on these matters, it combines elements
of both individualism and holism. Typical social philosophers today accept that
society has duties, not voluntary for individual members, to support education,
health, and some degree of welfare for all. But they also agree that individual
rights are to be respected, especially civil rights, such as freedom of speech
and religion. How to combine these two apparently disparate sets of ideas into
a coherent whole is the problem. John Rawls’s celebrated Theory of Justice, 1,
is a contemporary classic that attempts to do just that. Refs.: H. P. Grice,
“Grice and Grice on the conversational contract.”
sozzini: -- Socinianism, NELLA PRIMA METÀ DEL SEDICESIMO SECOLO NACQUERO IN QUESTA CASA LELIO E
FAUSTO SOZZINI LETTERATI INSIGNI FILOSOFI SOMMI DELLA LIBERTÀ DI PENSIERO
STRENUI PROPUGNATORI ______ CONTRO IL SOPRANNATURALE VINDICI DELLA UMANA
RAGIONE FONDARONO LA CELEBRE SCUOLA SOCINIANA PRECORRENDO DI TRE SECOLI LE
DOTTRINE DEL MODERNO RAZIONALISMO ______
I LIBERALI SENESI AMMIRATORI REVERENTI QUESTA MEMORIA POSERO 1879
a movement originating in the sixteenth century from the work of reformer Laelius Socinus “Sozzini” and his
nephew Faustus Socinus. Born in Siena of
a patrician family, Sozzini is widely read. Influenced by the evangelical
movement, Sozzini makes contact with noted Protestant reformers, including
Calvin and Melanchthon, some of whom questioned his orthodoxy. In response,
Sozzini writes a confession of faith, one of a small number of his writings to
have survived. After his death, Sozzini’s oeuvre was carried on by his nephew,
Faustus, whose writings including “On the Authority of Scripture,” “On the
Savior Jesus Christ,” and “On
Predestination,” expressed heterodox views. Sozzini believed that Christ’s
nature is entirely human, that the souls does not possess immortality by nature
though there is selective resurrection for believers, that invocation of Christ
in prayer is permissible but not required, and he argues, like Grice, Pears,
and Thomson, against predestination. After publication of his writings, Sozzini is invited to Transylvania
and Poland to engage in a dispute within the Reformed churches there. He
decides to make his permanent residence in Poland, which, through his tireless
efforts, became the center of the Socinian movement. The most important
document of this movement was the Racovian Catechism, published shortly after
Faustus’s death. The Minor church of Poland, centered at Racov, became the
focal point of the movement. Its academy attracted hundreds of students and its
publishing house produced books in many languages defending Socinian ideas.
Socinianism, as represented by the Racovian Catechism and other writings
collected by Faustus’s disciples, involves the views of Laelius and especially
Faustus Socinus, aligned with the anti-Trinitarian views of the Polish Minor
church.. It accepts Christ’s message as the definitive revelation of God, but
regards Christ as human, not divine; rejects the natural immortality of the
soul, but argues for the selective resurrection of the faithful; rejects the
doctrine of the Trinity; emphasizes human free will against predestinationism;
defends pacifism and the separation of church and state; and argues that
reason not creeds, dogmatic tradition,
or church authority must be the final
interpreter of Scripture. Its view of God is temporalistic: God’s eternity is
existence at all times, not timelessness, and God knows future free actions
only when they occur. In these respects, the Socinian view of God anticipates
aspects of modern process theology. Socinianism was suppressed in Poland in
1658, but it had already spread to other European countries, including Holland
where it appealed to followers of Arminius and England, where it influenced the
Cambridge Platonists, Locke, and other philosophers, as well as scientists like
Newton. In England, it also influenced and was closely associated with the
development of Unitarianism. H. P.
Grice, “Sozzini, rationalism, and moi.”
athenian
dialectic – Socrates, Grecian
philosopher, the exemplar of the examined life, best known for his dictum that
only such a life is worth living. Although he wrote nothing, his thoughts and
way of life had a profound impact on many of his contemporaries, and, through
Plato’s portrayal of him in his early writings, he became a major source of
inspiration and ideas for later generations of philosophers. His daily
occupation was adversarial public conversation with anyone willing to argue
with him. A man of great intellectual brilliance, moral integrity, personal
magnetism, and physical self-command, he challenged the moral complacency of
his fellow citizens, and embarrassed them with their inability to answer such
questions as What is virtue? questions
that he thought we must answer, if we are to know how best to live our lives.
His ideas and personality won him a devoted following among the young, but he
was far from universally admired. Formal charges were made against him for
refusing to recognize the gods of the city, introducing other new divinities,
and corrupting the youth. Tried on a single day before a large jury 500 was a
typical size, he was found guilty by a small margin: had thirty jurors voted
differently, he would have been acquitted. The punishment selected by the jury
was death and was administered by means of poison, probably hemlock. Why was he
brought to trial and convicted? Part of the answer lies in Plato’s Apology,
which purports to be the defense Socrates gave at his trial. Here he says that
he has for many years been falsely portrayed as someone whose scientific
theories dethrone the traditional gods and put natural forces in their place,
and as someone who charges a fee for offering private instruction on how to
make a weak argument seem strong in the courtroom. This is the picture of
Socrates drawn in a play of Aristophanes, the Clouds, first presented in 423.
It is unlikely that Aristophanes intended his play as an accurate depiction of
Socrates, and the unscrupulous buffoon found in the Clouds would never have won
the devotion of so serious a moralist as Plato. Aristophanes drew together the
assorted characteristics of various fifth-century thinkers and named this
amalgam “Socrates” because the real Socrates was one of several controversial
intellectuals of the period. Nonetheless, it is unlikely that the charges
against Socrates or Aristophanes’ caricature were entirely without foundation.
Both Xenophon’s Memorabilia and Plato’s Euthyphro say that Socrates aroused
suspicion because he thought a certain divine sign or voice appeared to him and
gave him useful instruction about how to act. By claiming a unique and private
source of divine inspiration, Socrates may have been thought to challenge the
city’s exclusive control over religious matters. His willingness to disobey the
city is admitted in Plato’s Apology, where he says that he would have to
disobey a hypothetical order to stop asking his philosophical questions, since
he regards them as serving a religious purpose. In the Euthyphro he seeks a
rational basis for making sacrifices and performing other services to the gods;
but he finds none, and implies that no one else has one. Such a challenge to
traditional religious practice could easily have aroused a suspicion of atheism
and lent credibility to the formal charges against him. Furthermore, Socrates
makes statements in Plato’s early dialogues and in Xenophon’s Memorabilia that
could easily have offended the political sensibilities of his contemporaries.
He holds that only those who have given special study to political matters
should make decisions. For politics is a kind of craft, and in all other crafts
only those who have shown their mastery are entrusted with public
responsibilities. Athens was a democracy in which each citizen had an equal
legal right to shape policy, and Socrates’ analogy between the role of an
expert in politics and in other crafts may have been seen as a threat to this
egalitarianism. Doubts about his political allegiance, though not mentioned in
the formal charges against him, could easily have swayed some jurors to vote
against him. Socrates is the subject not only of Plato’s early dialogues but
also of Xenophon’s Memorabilia, Socinus, Faustus Socrates 859 859 and in many respects their portraits are
consistent with each other. But there are also some important differences. In
the Memorabilia, Socrates teaches whatever a gentleman needs to know for civic
purposes. He is filled with platitudinous advice, and is never perplexed by the
questions he raises; e.g., he knows what the virtues are, equating them with
obedience to the law. His views are not threatening or controversial, and
always receive the assent of his interlocutors. By contrast, Plato’s Socrates
presents himself as a perplexed inquirer who knows only that he knows nothing
about moral matters. His interlocutors are sometimes annoyed by his questions
and threatened by their inability to answer them. And he is sometimes led by
force of argument to controversial conclusions. Such a Socrates could easily
have made enemies, whereas Xenophon’s Socrates is sometimes too “good” to be
true. But it is important to bear in mind that it is only the early works of
Plato that should be read as an accurate depiction of the historical Socrates.
Plato’s own theories, as presented in his middle and late dialogues, enter into
philosophical terrain that had not been explored by the historical
Socrates even though in the middle and
some of the late dialogues a figure called Socrates remains the principal
speaker. We are told by Aristotle that Socrates confined himself to ethical
questions, and that he did not postulate a separate realm of imperceptible and
eternal abstract objects called “Forms” or “Ideas.” Although the figure called
Socrates affirms the existence of these objects in such Platonic dialogues as
the Phaedo and the Republic, Aristotle takes this interlocutor to be a vehicle
for Platonic philosophy, and attributes to Socrates only those positions that
we find in Plato’s earlier writing, e.g. in the Apology, Charmides, Crito,
Euthyphro, Hippias Minor, Hippias Major, Ion, Laches, Lysis, and Protagoras.
Socrates focused on moral philosophy almost exclusively; Plato’s attention was
also devoted to the study of metaphysics, epistemology, physical theory,
mathematics, language, and political philosophy. When we distinguish the philosophies
of Socrates and Plato in this way, we find continuities in their thought for instance, the questions posed in the
early dialogues receive answers in the Republic
but there are important differences. For Socrates, being virtuous is a
purely intellectual matter: it simply involves knowing what is good for human
beings; once we master this subject, we will act as we should. Because he
equates virtue with knowledge, Socrates frequently draws analogies between
being virtuous and having mastered any ordinary subject cooking, building, or geometry, e.g. For
mastery of these subjects does not involve a training of the emotions. By
contrast, Plato affirms the existence of powerful emotional drives that can
deflect us from our own good, if they are not disciplined by reason. He denies
Socrates’ assumption that the emotions will not resist reason, once one comes
to understand where one’s own good lies. Socrates says in Plato’s Apology that
the only knowledge he has is that he knows nothing, but it would be a mistake
to infer that he has no convictions about moral matters convictions arrived at through a difficult
process of reasoning. He holds that the unexamined life is not worth living,
that it is better to be treated unjustly than to do injustice, that understanding
of moral matters is the only unconditional good, that the virtues are all forms
of knowledge and cannot be separated from each other, that death is not an
evil, that a good person cannot be harmed, that the gods possess the wisdom
human beings lack and never act immorally, and so on. He does not accept these
propositions as articles of faith, but is prepared to defend any of them; for
he can show his interlocutors that their beliefs ought to lead them to accept
these conclusions, paradoxical though they may be. Since Socrates can defend
his beliefs and has subjected them to intellectual scrutiny, why does he
present himself as someone who has no knowledge
excepting the knowledge of his own ignorance? The answer lies in his
assumption that it is only a fully accomplished expert in any field who can
claim knowledge or wisdom of that field; someone has knowledge of navigational
matters, e.g., only if he has mastered the art of sailing, can answer all
inquiries about this subject, and can train others to do the same. Judged by
this high epistemic standard, Socrates can hardly claim to be a moral expert,
for he lacks answers to the questions he raises, and cannot teach others to be
virtuous. Though he has examined his moral beliefs and can offer reasons for
them an accomplishment that gives him an
overbearing sense of superiority to his contemporaries he takes himself to be quite distant from the
ideal of moral perfection, which would involve a thorough understanding of all
moral matters. This keen sense of the moral and intellectual deficiency of all
human beings accounts for a great deal of Socrates’ appeal, just as his
arrogant disdain for his fellow citizens no doubt contributed to his demise.
Socrates Socrates 860 860 -- Socratic intellectualism, the claim that
moral goodness or virtue consists exclusively in a kind of knowledge, with the
implication that if one knows what is good and evil, one cannot fail to be a
good person and to act in a morally upright way. The claim and the term derive
from Socrates; a corollary is another claim of Socrates: there is no moral
weakness or akrasia all wrong action is
due to the agent’s ignorance. Socrates defends this view in Plato’s dialogue
Protagoras. There are two ways to understand Socrates’ view that knowledge of
the good is sufficient for right action. 1 All desires are rational, being
focused on what is believed to be good; thus, an agent who knows what is good
will have no desire to act contrary to that knowledge. 2 There are non-rational
desires, but knowledge of the good has sufficient motivational power to
overcome them. Socratic intellectualism was abandoned by Plato and Aristotle,
both of whom held that emotional makeup is an essential part of moral
character. However, they retained the Socratic idea that there is a kind of
knowledge or wisdom that ensures right action
but this knowledge presupposes antecedent training and molding of the
passions. Socratic intellectualism was later revived and enjoyed a long life as
a key doctrine of the Stoics. -- Socratic
irony, a form of indirect communication frequently employed by Socrates in
Plato’s early dialogues, chiefly to praise insincerely the abilities of his
interlocutors while revealing their ignorance; or, to disparage his own
abilities, e.g. by denying that he has knowledge. Interpreters disagree whether
Socrates’ self-disparagement is insincere.
-- Socratic paradoxes, a collection of theses associated with Socrates
that contradict opinions about moral or practical matters shared by most
people. Although there is no consensus on the precise number of Socratic
paradoxes, each of the following theses has been identified as one. 1 Because
no one desires evil things, anyone who pursues evil things does so
involuntarily. 2 Because virtue is knowledge, anyone who does something morally
wrong does so involuntarily. 3 It is better to be unjustly treated than to do
what is unjust. The first two theses are associated with weakness of will or
akrasia. It is sometimes claimed that the topic of the first thesis is
prudential weakness, whereas that of the second is moral weakness; the
reference to “evil things” in 1 is not limited to things that are morally evil.
Naturally, various competing interpretations of these theses have been offered.
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Oxonian dialectic; or, Athenian dialetic, revisited.”
solus ipse, solipsism: Grice: “If my theory of
conversation has any value, is the refutation of solipsism!” -- the doctrine
that there exists a firstperson perspective possessing privileged and
irreducible characteristics, in virtue of which we stand in various kinds of
isolation from any other persons or external things that may exist. This
doctrine is associated with but distinct from egocentricism. On one variant of
solipsism Thomas Nagel’s we are isolated from other sentient beings because we
can never adequately understand their experience empathic solipsism. Another
variant depends on the thesis that the meanings or referents of all words are
mental entities uniquely accessible only to the language user semantic
solipsism. A restricted variant, due to Vitters, asserts that first-person
ascriptions of psychological states have a meaning fundamentally different from
that of second- or thirdperson ascriptions psychological solipsism. In extreme
forms semantic solipsism can lead to the view that the only things that can be
meaningfully said to exist are ourselves or our mental states ontological
solipsism. Skepticism about the existence of the world external to our minds is
sometimes considered a form of epistemological solipsism, since it asserts that
we stand in epistemological isolation from that world, partly as a result of
the epistemic priority possessed by firstperson access to mental states. In
addition to these substantive versions of solipsism, several variants go under
the rubric methodological solipsism. The idea is that when we seek to explain
why sentient beings behave in certain ways by looking to what they believe,
desire, hope, and fear, we should identify these psychological states only with
events that occur inside the mind or brain, not with external events, since the
former alone are the proximate and sufficient causal explanations of bodily
behavior.
Solovyov: philosopher, author of major treatises and
dialogues in speculative philosophy, The
mystical image of the “Divine Sophia,” which Solovyov articulated in
theoretical concepts as well as poetic symbols, powerfully influenced the
Russian symbolist poets of the early twentieth century. His stress on the human
role in the “divine-human process” that creates both cosmic and historical
being led to charges of heresy from Russian Orthodox traditionalists.
Solovyov’s rationalistic “justification of the good” in history, society, and
individual life was inspired by Plato, Spinoza, and especially Hegel. However,
at the end of his life Solovyov offered in Three Conversations on War,
Progress, and the End of History, 0 a contrasting apocalyptic vision of
historical and cosmic disaster, including the appearance, in the twenty-first
century, of the Antichrist. In ethics, social philosophy, philosophy of
history, and theory of culture, Solovyov was both a vigorous ecumenist and a
“good European” who affirmed the intrinsic value of both the “individual human
person” Russian lichnost’ and the “individual nation or people” narodnost’, but
he decisively repudiated the perversions of these values in egoism and
nationalism, respectively. He contrasted the fruits of English narodnost’ the works of Shakespeare and Byron, Berkeley
and Newton with the fruits of English
nationalism the repressive and
destructive expansion of the British Empire. In opposing ethnic, national, and
religious exclusiveness and self-centeredness, Solovyov also, and quite
consistently, opposed the growing xenophobia and antiSemitism of his own time.
Since 8 long-suppressed works by and about Solovyov have been widely
republished in Russia, and fresh interpretations of his philosophy and theology
have begun to appear.
sophisma, a sentenca illustrating a semantic or logical
issue associated with the analysis of a syncategorematic term, or a term
lacking independent signification. Typically a sophisma was used from the
thirteenth century into the sixteenth century to analyze relations holding
between logic or semantics and broader philosophical issues. For example, the
syncategorematic term ‘besides’ praeter in ‘Socrates twice sees every man
besides Plato’ is ambiguous, because it could mean ‘On two occasions Socrates
sees every-man-but-Plato’ and also ‘Except for overlooking Plato once, on two
occasions Socrates sees every man’. Roger Bacon used this sophisma to discuss
the ambiguity of distribution, in this case, of the scope of the reference of
‘twice’ and ‘besides’. Sherwood used the sophisma to illustrate the
applicability of his rule of the distribution of ambiguous syncategoremata,
while Pseudo-Peter of Spain uses it to establish the truth of the rule, ‘If a
proposition is in part false, it can be made true by means of an exception, but
not if it is completely false’. In each case, the philosopher uses the
ambiguous signification of the syncategorematic term to analyze broader logical
problems. The sophisma ‘Every man is of necessity an animal’ has ambiguity
through the syncategorematic ‘every’ that leads to broader philosophical problems.
In the 1270s, Boethius of Dacia analyzed this sophisma in terms of its
applicability when no man exists. Is the knowledge derived from understanding
the proposition destroyed when the object known is destroyed? Does ‘man’
signify anything when there are no men? If we can correctly predicate a genus
of a species, is the nature of the genus in that species something other than,
or distinct from, what finally differentiates the species? In this case, the
sophisma proves a useful approach to addressing metaphysical and
epistemological problems central to Scholastic discourse. sophisma: Grice: “Literally, a
wisecrack.” “’Sophisma’ is a very Griceian and Grecian pun on ‘sophos,’ the
wise men of Gotham -- any of a number of ancient Grecians, roughly contemporaneous
with Socrates, who professed to teach, for a fee, rhetoric, philosophy, and how
to succeed in life. They typically were itinerants, visiting much of the
Grecian world, and gave public exhibitions at Olympia and Delphi. They were
part of the general expansion of Grecian learning and of the changing culture
in which the previous informal educational methods were inadequate. For
example, the growing litigiousness of Athenian society demanded Solovyov,
Vladimir Sophists 862 862 instruction
in the art of speaking well, which the Sophists helped fulfill. The Sophists
have been portrayed as intellectual charlatans hence the pejorative use of
‘sophism’, teaching their sophistical reasoning for money, and at the other
extreme as Victorian moralists and educators. The truth is more complex. They
were not a school, and shared no body of opinions. They were typically
concerned with ethics unlike many earlier philosophers, who emphasized physical
inquiries and about the relationship between laws and customs nomos and nature
phusis. Protagoras of Abdera c.490c.420 B.C. was the most famous and perhaps
the first Sophist. He visited Athens frequently, and became a friend of its
leader, Pericles; he therefore was invited to draw up a legal code for the
colony of Thurii 444. According to some late reports, he died in a shipwreck as
he was leaving Athens, having been tried for and found guilty of impiety. He
claimed that he knew nothing about the gods, because of human limitations and
the difficulty of the question. We have only a few short quotations from his
works. His “Truth” also known as the “Throws,” i.e., how to overthrow an
opponent’s arguments begins with his most famous claim: “Humans are the measure
of all things of things that are, that
they are, of things that are not, that they are not.” That is, there is no
objective truth; the world is for each person as it appears to that person. Of
what use, then, are skills? Skilled people can change others’ perceptions in
useful ways. For example, a doctor can change a sick person’s perceptions so
that she is healthy. Protagoras taught his students to “make the weaker
argument the stronger,” i.e., to alter people’s perceptions about the value of
arguments. Aristophanes satirizes Protagoras as one who would make unjust
arguments defeat just arguments. This is true for ethical judgments, too: laws
and customs are simply products of human agreement. But because laws and
customs result from experiences of what is most useful, they should be followed
rather than nature. No perception or judgment is more true than another, but
some are more useful, and those that are more useful should be followed.
Gorgias c.483376 was a student of Empedocles. His town, Leontini in Sicily,
sent him as an ambassador to Athens in 427; his visit was a great success, and
the Athenians were amazed at his rhetorical ability. Like other Sophists, he
charged for instruction and gave speeches at religious festivals. Gorgias
denied that he taught virtue; instead, he produced clever speakers. He insisted
that different people have different virtues: for example, women’s virtue
differs from men’s. Since there is no truth and if there were we couldn’t know
it, we must rely on opinion, and so speakers who can change people’s opinions
have great power greater than the power
produced by any other skill. In his “Encomium on Helen” he argues that if she
left Menelaus and went with Paris because she was convinced by speech, she
wasn’t responsible for her actions. Two paraphrases of Gorgias’s “About What
Doesn’t Exist” survive; in this he argues that nothing exists, that even if
something did, we couldn’t know it, and that even if we could know anything we
couldn’t explain it to anyone. We can’t know anything, because some things we
think of do not exist, and so we have no way of judging whether the things we
think of exist. And we can’t express any knowledge we may have, because no two
people can think of the same thing, since the same thing can’t be in two
places, and because we use words in speech, not colors or shapes or objects.
This may be merely a parody of Parmenides’ argument that only one thing exists.
Antiphon the Sophist fifth century is probably although not certainly to be
distinguished from Antiphon the orator d. 411, some of whose speeches we possess.
We know nothing about his life if he is distinct from the orator. In addition
to brief quotations in later authors, we have two papyrus fragments of his “On
Truth.” In these he argues that we should follow laws and customs only if there
are witnesses and so our action will affect our reputation; otherwise, we
should follow nature, which is often inconsistent with following custom. Custom
is established by human agreement, and so disobeying it is detrimental only if
others know it is disobeyed, whereas nature’s demands unlike those of custom
can’t be ignored with impunity. Antiphon assumes that rational actions are
selfinterested, and that justice demands actions contrary to self-interest a position Plato attacks in the Republic.
Antiphon was also a materialist: the nature of a bed is wood, since if a buried
bed could grow it would grow wood, not a bed. His view is one of Aristotle’s
main concerns in the Physics, since Aristotle admits in the Categories that
persistence through change is the best test for substance, but won’t admit that
matter is substance. Hippias fifth century was from Elis, in the Peloponnesus,
which used him as an ambasSophists Sophists 863 863 sador. He competed at the festival of
Olympus with both prepared and extemporaneous speeches. He had a phenomenal
memory. Since Plato repeatedly makes fun of him in the two dialogues that bear
his name, he probably was selfimportant and serious. He was a polymath who
claimed he could do anything, including making speeches and clothes; he wrote a
work collecting what he regarded as the best things said by others. According
to one report, he made a mathematical discovery the quadratrix, the first curve
other than the circle known to the Grecians. In the Protagoras, Plato has
Hippias contrast nature and custom, which often does violence to nature.
Prodicus fifth century was from Ceos, in the Cyclades, which frequently
employed him on diplomatic missions. He apparently demanded high fees, but had
two versions of his lecture one cost
fifty drachmas, the other one drachma. Socrates jokes that if he could have
afforded the fifty-drachma lecture, he would have learned the truth about the
correctness of words, and Aristotle says that when Prodicus added something
exciting to keep his audience’s attention he called it “slipping in the
fifty-drachma lecture for them.” We have at least the content of one lecture of
his, the “Choice of Heracles,” which consists of banal moralizing. Prodicus was
praised by Socrates for his emphasis on the right use of words and on
distinguishing between synonyms. He also had a naturalistic view of the origin
of theology: useful things were regarded as gods.
sorel: sphilosopher best known for his “Reflections on
Violence,” which develops the notion of revolutionary syndicalism as seen
through proletarian violence and the interpretation of myth. An early proponent
of the quasiMarxist position of gradual democratic reformism, Sorel eventually
developed a highly subjective interpretation of historical materialism that,
while retaining a conception of proletarian revolution, now understood it
through myth rather than reason. He was in large part reacting to the
empiricism of the Enlightenment and the
statistical structuring of sociological studies. In contrast to Marx and
Engels, who held that revolution would occur when the proletariat attained its
own class consciousness through an understanding of its true relationship to
the means of production in capitalist society, Sorel introduced myth rather
than reason as the correct way to interpret social totality. Myth allows for
the necessary reaction to bourgeois rationalism and permits the social theorist
to negate the status quo through the authenticity of revolutionary violence. By
acknowledging the irrationality of the status quo, myth permits the possibility
of social understanding and its necessary reaction, human emancipation through
proletarian revolution. Marxism is myth because it juxtaposes the
irreducibility of capitalist organization to its negation violent proletarian revolution. The
intermediary stage in this development is radical syndicalism, which organizes
workers into groups opposed to bourgeois authority, instills the myth of
proletarian revolution in the workers, and allows them in postrevolutionary
times to work toward a social arrangement of worker and peasant governance and
collaboration. The vehicle through which all this is accomplished is the
general strike, whose aim, through the justified violence of its ends, is to
facilitate the downfall and ultimate elimination of the bourgeoisie. In doing
so the proletariat will lead society to a classless and harmonious stage in
history. By stressing the notion of spontaneity Sorel thought he had solved the
vexing problems of party and future bureaucracy found in much of the
revolutionary literature of his day. In his later years he was interested in
the writings of both Lenin and Mussolini.
sorites, an argument consisting of categorical
propositions that can be represented as or decomposed into a sequence of
categorical syllogisms such that the conclusion of each syllogism except the
last one in the sequence is a premise of the next syllogism in the sequence. An
example is ‘All cats are felines; all felines are mammals; all mammals are
warm-blooded animals; therefore, all cats are warm-blooded animals’. This
sorites may be viewed as composed of the two syllogisms ‘All cats are felines;
all felines are mammals; therefore, all cats are mammals’ and ‘All cats are
mammals; all mammals are warm-blooded animals; therefore, all cats are
warm-blooded animals’. A sorites is valid if and only if each categorical
syllogism into which it decomposes is valid. In the example, the sorites
decomposes into two syllogisms in the mood Barbara; since any syllogism in
Barbara is valid, the sorites is valid.
sorites paradox from Grecian soros, ‘heap’, any of a
number of paradoxes about heaps and their Sorel, Georges sorites paradox
864 864 elements, and more broadly
about gradations. A single grain of sand cannot be arranged so as to form a heap.
Moreover, it seems that given a number of grains insufficient to form a heap,
adding just one more grain still does not make a heap. If a heap cannot be
formed with one grain, it cannot be formed with two; if a heap cannot be formed
with two, it cannot be formed with three; and so on. But this seems to lead to
the absurdity that however large the number of grains, it is not large enough
to form a heap. A similar paradox can be developed in the opposite direction. A
million grains of sand can certainly be arranged so as to form a heap, and it
is always possible to remove a grain from a heap in such a way that what is
left is also a heap. This seems to lead to the absurdity that a heap can be
formed even from just a single grain. These paradoxes about heaps were known in
antiquity they are associated with Eubulides of Miletus, fourth century B.C.,
and have since given their name to a number of similar paradoxes. The loss of a
single hair does not make a man bald, and a man with a million hairs is certainly
not bald. This seems to lead to the absurd conclusion that even a man with no
hairs at all is not bald. Or consider a long painted wall hundreds of yards or
hundreds of miles long. The left-hand region is clearly painted red, but there
is a subtle gradation of shades and the right-hand region is clearly yellow. A
small double window exposes a small section of the wall at any one time. It is
moved progressively rightward, in such a way that at each move after the
initial position the left-hand segment of the window exposes just the area that
was in the previous position exposed by the right-hand segment. The window is
so small relative to the wall that in no position can you tell any difference
in color between the exposed areas. When the window is at the extreme left,
both exposed areas are certainly red. But as the window moves to the right, the
area in the right segment looks just the same color as the area in the left,
which you have already pronounced to be red. So it seems that one must call it
red too. But then one is led to the absurdity of calling a clearly yellow area
red. As some of these cases suggest, there is a connection with dynamic
processes. A tadpole turns gradually into a frog. Yet if you analyze a motion
picture of the process, it seems that there are no two adjacent frames of which
you can say the earlier shows a tadpole, the later a frog. So it seems that you
could argue: if something is a tadpole at a given moment, it must also be a
tadpole and not a frog a millionth of a second later, and this seems to lead to
the absurd conclusion that a tadpole can never turn into a frog. Most responses
to this paradox attempt to deny the “major premise,” the one corresponding to
the claim that if you cannot make a heap with n grains of sand then you cannot
make a heap with n ! 1. The difficulty is that the negation of this premise is
equivalent, in classical logic, to the proposition that there is a sharp
cutoff: that, e.g., there is some number n of grains that are not enough to
make a heap, where n ! 1 are enough to make a heap. The claim of a sharp cutoff
may not be so very implausible for heaps perhaps for things like grains of
sand, four is the smallest number which can be formed into a heap but is very
implausible for colors and tadpoles. There are two main kinds of response to
sorites paradoxes. One is to accept that there is in every such case a sharp
cutoff, though typically we do not, and perhaps cannot, know where it is.
Another kind of response is to evolve a non-classical logic within which one
can refuse to accept the major premise without being committed to a sharp
cutoff. At present, no such non-classical logic is entirely free of
difficulties. So sorites paradoxes are still taken very seriously by
contemporary philosophers.
sort: Grice, “One of the few technicisms introduced by
an English philosopher, in this case Locke.” – a sortal predicate, roughly, a
predicate whose application to an object says what kind of object it is and
implies conditions for objects of that kind to be identical. Person, green
apple, regular hexagon, and pile of coal would generally be regarded as sortal
predicates, whereas tall, green thing, and coal would generally be regarded as
non-sortal predicates. An explicit and precise definition of the distinction is
hard to come by. Sortal predicates are sometimes said to be distinguished by
the fact that they provide a criterion of counting or that they do not apply to
the parts of the objects to which they apply, but there are difficulties with
each of these characterizations. The notion figures in recent philosophical
discussions on various topics. Robert Ackermann and others have suggested that
any scientific law confirmable by observation might require the use of sortal
predicates. Thus ‘all non-black things are non-ravens’, while logically
equivalent to the putative scientific law ‘all ravens are black’, is not itself
confirmable by observation because ‘non-black’ is not a sortal predicate. David
Wiggins and others have discussed the sortal sortal predicate 865 865 idea that all identity claims are
sortal-relative in the sense that an appropriate response to the claim a % b is
always “the same what as b?” John Wallace has argued that there would be
advantages in relativizing the quantifiers of predicate logic to sortals. ‘All
humans are mortal’ would be rendered Ex[m]Dx, rather than ExMxPDx. Crispin
Wright has suggested that the view that natural number is a sortal concept is
central to Frege’s or any other number-theoretic platonism. The word ‘sortal’
as a technical term in philosophy apparently first occurs in Locke’s Essay
Concerning Human Understanding. Locke argues that the so-called essence of a
genus or sort unlike the real essence of a thing is merely the abstract idea
that the general or sortal name stands for. But ‘sortal’ has only one
occurrence in Locke’s Essay. Its currency in contemporary philosophical idiom
probably should be credited to P. F. Strawson’s Individuals. The general idea
may be traced at least to the notion of second substance in Aristotle’s
Categories.
Soto, Domingo de -- Dominican theologian and
philosopher. Born in Segovia, he studied in Paris, taught at Segovia and
Salamanca, and was named official representative of the Holy Roman Empire at
the Council of Trent by Charles V. Among Soto’s many works, his commentaries on
Aristotle’s Physics and On the Soul stand out. He also wrote a book on the
nature of grace and an important treatise on law. Soto was one of the early
members of the school of Thomism, but he
did not always follow Aquinas. He rejected the doctrine of the real distinction
between essence and existence and adopted Duns Scotus’s position that the
primary object of human understanding is indeterminate being in general. Apart
from metaphysics and theology, Soto’s philosophy of law and political theory
are historically important. He maintained, contrary to his teacher Vitoria,
that law originates in the understanding rather than in the will of the
legislator. He also distinguished natural from positive law: the latter arises from
the decision of legislators, whereas the former is based on nature. Soto was a
founder of the general theory of international law.
soul: -- cf. Grice on “soul-to-soul transfer” -- also
called spirit, an entity supposed to be present only in living things,
corresponding to the Grecian psyche and Latin anima. Since there seems to be no
material difference between an organism in the last moments of its life and the
organism’s newly dead body, many philosophers since the time of Plato have
claimed that the soul is an immaterial component of an organism. Because only
material things are observed to be subject to dissolution, Plato took the
soul’s immateriality as grounds for its immortality. Neither Plato nor
Aristotle thought that only persons had souls: Aristotle ascribed souls to
animals and plants since they all exhibited some living functions. Unlike
Plato, Aristotle denied the transmigration of souls from one species to another
or from one body to another after death; he was also more skeptical about the
soul’s capacity for disembodiment
roughly, survival and functioning without a body. Descartes argued that
only persons had souls and that the soul’s immaterial nature made freedom
possible even if the human body is subject to deterministic physical laws. As
the subject of thought, memory, emotion, desire, and action, the soul has been
supposed to be an entity that makes self-consciousness possible, that
differentiates simultaneous experiences into experiences either of the same
person or of different persons, and that accounts for personal identity or a
person’s continued identity through time. Dualists argue that soul and body
must be distinct in order to explain consciousness and the possibility of
immortality. Materialists argue that consciousness is entirely the result of
complex physical processes.
soundness: Grice: “The etymology if fascinating.” The English
Grice. "Most of the terms I use are
Latinate." "I implicate: a few are not." "I say that System
G should be sound." "free from special defect or injury," c.
1200, from Old English gesund "sound, safe, having the organs and
faculties complete and in perfect action," from Proto-Germanic *sunda-,
from Germanic root *swen-to- "healthy, strong" (source also of Old
Saxon gisund, Old Frisian sund, Dutch gezond, Old High German gisunt, German
gesund "healthy," as in the post-sneezing interjection gesundheit;
also Old English swið "strong," Gothic swinþs "strong,"
German geschwind "fast, quick"), with connections in Indo-Iranian and
Balto-Slavic. Meaning "right, correct, free from error" is from
mid-15c. Meaning "financially solid or safe" is attested from c.
1600; of sleep, "undisturbed," from 1540s. Sense of "holding
accepted opinions" is from 1520s Grice: “’sound’ is not polysemous,
but it has different usages: of an argument the property of being valid and
having all true premises; of a system, like Sytem G, the property of being not too strong in a
certain respect. A System G has weak
soundness provided every theorem of G is
valid. And G has strong soundness if for every set S of sentences, every
sentence deducible from S using system G is a logical consequence of S.
spatium: space, an extended manifold of several dimensions,
where the number of dimensions corresponds to the number of variable magnitudes
Soto, Domingo de space 866 866 needed
to specify a location in the manifold; in particular, the three-dimensional
manifold in which physical objects are situated and with respect to which their
mutual positions and distances are defined. Ancient Grecian atomism defined
space as the infinite void in which atoms move; but whether space is finite or
infinite, and whether void spaces exist, have remained in question. Aristotle
described the universe as a finite plenum and reduced space to the aggregate of
all places of physical things. His view was preeminent until Renaissance
Neoplatonism, the Copernican revolution, and the revival of atomism
reintroduced infinite, homogeneous space as a fundamental cosmological
assumption. Further controversy concerned whether the space assumed by early
modern astronomy should be thought of as an independently existing thing or as
an abstraction from the spatial relations of physical bodies. Interest in the
relativity of motion encouraged the latter view, but Newton pointed out that
mechanics presupposes absolute distinctions among motions, and he concluded
that absolute space must be postulated along with the basic laws of motion
Principia, 1687. Leibniz argued for the relational view from the identity of
indiscernibles: the parts of space are indistinguishable from one another and
therefore cannot be independently existing things. Relativistic physics has
defused the original controversy by revealing both space and spatial relations
as merely observer-dependent manifestations of the structure of spacetime.
Meanwhile, Kant shifted the metaphysical controversy to epistemological grounds
by claiming that space, with its Euclidean structure, is neither a
“thing-in-itself” nor a relation of thingsin-themselves, but the a priori form
of outer intuition. His view was challenged by the elaboration of non-Euclidean
geometries in the nineteenth century, by Helmholtz’s arguments that both
intuitive and physical space are known through empirical investigation, and
finally by the use of non-Euclidean geometry in the theory of relativity.
Precisely what geometrical presuppositions are inherent in human spatial
perception, and what must be learned from experience, remain subjects of
psychological investigation.
space-time, a four-dimensional continuum combining the
three dimensions of space with time in order to represent motion geometrically.
Each point is the location of an event, all of which together represent “the
world” through time; paths in the continuum worldlines represent the dynamical
histories of moving particles, so that straight worldlines correspond to
uniform motions; three-dimensional sections of constant time value “spacelike
hypersurfaces” or “simultaneity slices” represent all of space at a given time.
The idea was foreshadowed when Kant represented “the phenomenal world” as a
plane defined by space and time as perpendicular axes Inaugural Dissertation,
1770, and when Joseph Louis Lagrange 17361814 referred to mechanics as “the
analytic geometry of four dimensions.” But classical mechanics assumes a
universal standard of simultaneity, and so it can treat space and time
separately. The concept of space-time was explicitly developed only when
Einstein criticized absolute simultaneity and made the velocity of light a
universal constant. The mathematician Hermann Minkowski showed in 8 that the
observer-independent structure of special relativity could be represented by a
metric space of four dimensions: observers in relative motion would disagree on
intervals of length and time, but agree on a fourdimensional interval combining
spatial and temporal measurements. Minkowski’s model then made possible the
general theory of relativity, which describes gravity as a curvature of
spacetime in the presence of mass and the paths of falling bodies as the
straightest worldlines in curved space-time.
spatio-temporal continuity, a property of the careers,
or space-time paths, of well-behaved objects. Let a space-time path be a series
of possible spatiotemporal positions, each represented in a selected coordinate
system by an ordered pair consisting of a time its temporal component and a
volume of space its spatial component. Such a path will be spatiotemporally
continuous provided it is such that, relative to any inertial frame selected as
coordinate system, space, absolute spatiotemporal continuity 867 867 1 for every segment of the series, the
temporal components of the members of that segment form a continuous temporal
interval; and 2 for any two members ‹ti, Vi and ‹tj, Vj of the series that
differ in their temporal components ti and tj, if Vi and Vj the spatial
components differ in either shape, size, or location, then between these
members of the series there will be a member whose spatial component is more
similar to Vi and Vj in these respects than these are to each other. This
notion is of philosophical interest partly because of its connections with the
notions of identity over time and causality. Putting aside such qualifications
as quantum considerations may require, material objects at least macroscopic
objects of familiar kinds apparently cannot undergo discontinuous change of
place, and cannot have temporal gaps in their histories, and therefore the path
through space-time traced by such an object must apparently be spatiotemporally
continuous. More controversial is the claim that spatiotemporal continuity,
together with some continuity with respect to other properties, is sufficient
as well as necessary for the identity of such objects e.g., that if a spatiotemporally continuous
path is such that the spatial component of each member of the series is
occupied by a table of a certain description at the time that is the temporal
component of that member, then there is a single table of that description that
traces that path. Those who deny this claim sometimes maintain that it is
further required for the identity of material objects that there be causal and
counterfactual dependence of later states on earlier ones ceteris paribus, if
the table had been different yesterday, it would be correspondingly different
now. Since it appears that chains of causality must trace spatiotemporally
continuous paths, it may be that insofar as spatiotemporal continuity is
required for transtemporal identity, this is because it is required for
transtemporal causality. Refs.: H. P. Grice and P. F. Strawson, “Categories,”
in The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC MSS 90/135c, The Bancroft Library, The
University of California, Berkeley.
specious present: the supposed time between past and
future. The phrase was first offered by Clay in “The Alternative: A Study in
Psychology,” and is cited by James in his
Principles of Psychology Clay challenges
the assumption that the “present” as a “datum” is given as “present” to us in
our experience. “The present to which the datum refers is really a part of the *past*,
a recent past delusively given as benign
time that intervenes between the past and the future. Let it be named ‘the
specious present,’ and let the past that is given as being the past be known as
‘the obvious past.’” For James, this position is supportive of his contention
that consciousness (conscientia) is a stream and can be divided into parts only
by conceptual addition, i.e., only by our ascribing past, present, and future
to what is, in our actual experience, a seamless flow. James holds that the
“practically cognized present is no knife-edge but a saddleback,” a sort of
“ducatum” which we experience as a whole, and only upon reflective attention do
we “distinguish its beginning from its end.” Whereas Clay refers to the datum
of the present as “delusive,” one might rather say that it is perpetually *elusive*,
for as we have our experience, now, it is always bathed retrospectively and
prospectively. Contrary to common wisdom, no single experience ever is had by
our consciousness utterly alone, single and without relations, fore and aft.
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The logical-construction theory of personal identity.”
speculatum: Grice: “Philosophy may broadly be divided
into ‘philosophia speculativa” and “philosophia practica.”” -- speculative
philosophy, a form of theorizing that goes beyond verifiable observation;
specifically, a philosophical approach informed by the impulse to construct a
grand narrative of a worldview that encompasses the whole of reality.
Speculative philosophy purports to bind together reflections on the existence
and nature of the cosmos, the psyche, and God. It sets for its goal a unifying
matrix and an overarching system whereswith to comprehend the considered
judgments of cosmology, psychology, and theology. Hegel’s absolute idealism,
particularly as developed in his later thought, paradigmatically illustrates
the requirements for speculative philosophizing. His system of idealism offered
a vision of the unity of the categories of human thought as they come to
realization in and through their opposition to each other. Speculative thought
tends to place a premium on universality, totality, and unity; and it tends to
marginalize the concrete particularities of the natural and social world. In
its aggressive use of the systematic principle, geared to a unification of
human experience, speculative philosophy aspires to a comprehensive
understanding and explanation of the structural interrelations of the culture
spheres of science, morality, art, and religion. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Practical
and doxastic attitudes: why I need exhibitive clauses.”
austinianism: speech act theory, the theory of language use,
sometimes called pragmatics, as opposed to the theory of meaning, or semantics.
Based on the meaninguse distinction, it categorizes systematically the sorts of
things that can be done with words and explicates the ways these are
determined, underdetermined, or undetermined by the meanings of the words used.
Relying further on the distinction between speaker meaning and linguistic
meaning, it aims to characterize the nature of communicative intentions and how
they are expressed and recognized. Speech acts are a species of intentional
action. In general, one and the same utterance may comprise a number of
distinct though related acts, each corresponding to a different intention on
the part of the speaker. Beyond intending to produce a certain sequence of
sounds forming a sentence in English, a person who utters the sentence ‘The
door is open’, e.g., is likely to be intending to perform, in the terminology
of J. L. Austin How to Do Things with Words, 2, 1 the locutionary act of saying
expressing the proposition that a certain door is open, 2 the illocutionary act
of making the statement expressing the belief that it is open, and 3 the
perlocutionary act of getting his listener to believe that it is open. In so
doing, he may be performing the indirect speech act of requesting illocutionary
the listener to close the door and of getting perlocutionary the hearer to
close the door. The primary focus of speech act theory is on illocutionary
acts, which may be classified in a variety of ways. Statements, predictions,
and answers exemplify constatives; requests, commands and permissions are directives;
promises, offers, and bets are commissives; greetings, apologies, and
congratulations are acknowledgments. These are all communicative illocutionary
acts, each distinguished by the type of psychological state expressed by the
speaker. Successful communication consists in the audience’s recognition of the
speaker’s intention to be expressing a certain psychological state with a
certain content. Conventional illocutionary acts, on the other hand, effect or
officially affect institutional states of affairs. Examples of the former are
appointing, resigning, sentencing, and adjourning; examples of the latter are
assessing, acquitting, certifying, and grading. See Kent Bach and Robert M.
Harnish, Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts, 9. The type of act an
utterance exemplifies determines its illocutionary force. In the example ‘The
door is open’, the utterance has the force of both a statement and a request.
The illocutionary force potential of a sentence is the force or forces with
which it can be used literally, e.g., in the case of the sentence ‘The door is
open’, as a statement but not as a request. The felicity conditions on an
illocutionary act pertain not only to its communicative or institutional
success but also to its sincerity, appropriateness, and effectiveness. An
explicit performative utterance is an illocutionary act performed by uttering
an indicative sentence in the simple present tense with a verb naming the type
of act being performed, e.g., ‘I apologize for everything I did’ and ‘You are
requested not to smoke’. The adverb ‘hereby’ may be used before the
performative verb ‘apologize’ and ‘request’ in these examples to indicate that
the very utterance being made is the vehicle of the performance of the
illocutionary act in question. A good test for distinguishing illocutionary
from perlocutionary acts is to determine whether a verb naming the act can be
used performatively. Austin exploited the phenomenon of performative utterances
to expose the common philosophical error of assuming that the primary use of
language is to make statements.
spencer: English philosopher, social reformer, and editor of
The Economist. In epistemology, Spencer adopted the ninespeculative reason
Spencer, Herbert 869 869 teenth-century
trend toward positivism: the only reliable knowledge of the universe is to be
found in the sciences. His ethics were utilitarian, following Bentham and J. S.
Mill: pleasure and pain are the criteria of value as signs of happiness or
unhappiness in the individual. His Synthetic Philosophy, expounded in books
written over many years, assumed both in biology and psychology the existence
of Lamarckian evolution: given a characteristic environment, every animal
possesses a disposition to make itself into what it will, failing maladaptive
interventions, eventually become. The dispositions gain expression as inherited
acquired habits. Spencer could not accept that species originate by chance
variations and natural selection alone: direct adaptation to environmental
constraints is mainly responsible for biological changes. Evolution also
includes the progression of societies in the direction of a dynamical
equilibrium of individuals: the human condition is perfectible because human
faculties are completely adapted to life in society, implying that evil and
immorality will eventually disappear. His ideas on evolution predated
publication of the major works of Darwin; A. R. Wallace was influenced by his
writings. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Evolutionary pirotology,” in “Method in
philosophical psychology: from the banal to the bizarre.”
speranza: luigi della --. Italian philosopher, attracted, for
some reason, to H. P. Grice. Speranza knows St. John’s very well. He is the
author of “Dorothea Oxoniensis.” He is a member of a number of cultivated Anglo-Italian
societies, like H. P. Grice’s Playgroup. He is the custodian of Villa Grice,
not far from Villa Speranza. He works at the Swimming-Pool Library. Cuisine is
one of his hobbies – grisottoa alla ligure, his specialty. He can be reached
via H. P. Grice. Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Vita ed opinion di Luigi Speranza,”
par Luigi Speranza. The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC MSS 90/135c, The Bancroft
Library, The University of California, Berkeley.
spinoza: Jewish metaphysician, born in the Netherlanads -- epistemologist,
psychologist, moral philosopher, political theorist, and philosopher of
religion, generally regarded as one of the most important figures of
seventeenth-century rationalism. Life and works. Born and educated in the
Jewish ‘community’ of Amsterdam, he forsook his given name ‘Baruch’ in favor of
the Latin ‘Benedict’ at the age of twenty-two. Between 1652 and 1656 he studied
the philosophy of Descartes in the school of Francis van den Enden. Having
developed unorthodox views of the divine nature and having ceased to be fully
observant of Jewish practice, he was excommunicated by the Jewish community in
1656. He spent his entire life in Holland; after leaving Amsterdam in 1660, he
resided successively in Rijnsburg, Voorburg, and the Hague. He supported himself
at least partly through grinding lenses, and his knowledge of optics involved
him in an area of inquiry of great importance to seventeenth-century science.
Acquainted with such leading intellectual figures as Leibniz, Huygens, and
Henry Oldenberg, he declined a professorship at the of Heidelberg partly on the grounds that it
might interfere with his intellectual freedom. His premature death at the age
of fortyfour was due to consumption. The only work published under Spinoza’s
name during his lifetime was his Principles of Descartes’s Philosophy Renati
Des Cartes Principiorum Philosophiae, Pars I et II, 1663, an attempt to recast
and present Parts I and II of Descartes’s Principles of Philosophy in the
manner that Spinoza called geometrical order or geometrical method. Modeled on
the Elements of Euclid and on what Descartes called the method of synthesis,
Spinoza’s “geometrical order” involves an initial set of definitions and
axioms, from which various propositions are demonstrated, with notes or scholia
attached where necessary. This work, which established his credentials as an
expositor of Cartesian philosophy, had its origins in his endeavor to teach
Descartes’s Principles of Philosophy to a private student. Spinoza’s
TheologicalPolitical Treatise Tractatus Theologico-Politicus was published
anonymously in 1670. After his death, his close circle of friends published his
Posthumous Works Opera Postuma, 1677, which included his masterpieces, Ethic,
Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Ethica, Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata. The
Posthumous Works also included his early unfinished Treatise on the Emendation
of the Intellect Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione, his later unfinished
Political Treatise Tractatus Politicus, a Hebrew Grammar, and Correspondence.
An unpublished early work entitled Short Treatise on God, Man, and His
Well-Being Korte Vorhandelung van God, de Mensch en deszelvs Welstand, in many
ways a forerunner of the Ethics, was rediscovered in copied manuscript and
published in the nineteenth century. Spinoza’s authorship of two brief
scientific treatises, On the Rainbow and On the Calculation of Chances, is
still disputed. Metaphysics. Spinoza often uses the term ‘God, or Nature’
“Deus, sive Natura“, and this identification of God with Nature is at the heart
of his metaphysics. Because of this identification, his philosophy is often
regarded as a version of pantheism and/or naturalism. But although philosophy
begins with metaphysics for Spinoza, his metaphysics is ultimately in the
service of his ethics. Because his naturalized God has no desires or purposes,
human ethics cannot properly be derived from divine command. Rather,
Spinozistic ethics seeks to demonstrate, from an adequate understanding of the
divine nature and its expression in human nature, the way in which human beings
can maximize their advantage. Central to the successful pursuit of this advantage
is adequate knowledge, which leads to increasing control of the passions and to
cooperative action. Spinoza’s ontology, like that of Descartes, consists of
substances, their attributes which Descartes called principal attributes, and
their modes. In the Ethics, Spinoza defines ‘substance’ as what is “in itself,
and is conceived through itself”; ‘attribute’ as that which “the intellect perceives
of a substance as constituting its essence”; and ‘mode’ as “the affections of a
substance, or that which is in another through which also it is conceived.”
While Descartes had recognized a strict sense in which only God is a substance,
he also recognized a second sense in which there are two kinds of created
substances, each with its own principal attribute: extended substances, whose
only principal attribute is extension; and minds, whose only principal
attribute is thought. Spinoza, in contrast, consistently maintains that there
is only one substance. His metaphysics is thus a form of substantial monism.
This one substance is God, which Spinoza defines as “a being absolutely
infinite, i.e., a substance consisting of an infinity of attributes, of which
each expresses an eternal and infinite essence.” Thus, whereas Descartes
limited each created substance to one principal attribute, Spinoza claims that
the one substance has infinite attributes, each expressing the divine nature
without limitation in its own way. Of these infinite attributes, however,
humans can comprehend only two: extension and thought. Within each attribute,
the modes of God are of two kinds: infinite modes, which are pervasive features
of each attribute, such as the laws of nature; and finite modes, which are
local and limited modifications of substance. There is an infinite sequence of
finite modes. Descartes regarded a human being as a substantial union of two
different substances, the thinking soul and the extended body, in causal interaction
with each other. Spinoza, in contrast, regards a human being as a finite mode
of God, existing simultaneously in God as a mode of thought and as a mode of
extension. He holds that every mode of extension is literally identical with
the mode of thought that is the “idea of” that mode of extension. Since the
human mind is the idea of the human body, it follows that the human mind and
the human body are literally the same thing, conceived under two different
attributes. Because they are actually identical, there is no causal interaction
between the mind and the body; but there is a complete parallelism between what
occurs in the mind and what occurs in the body. Since every mode of extension
has a corresponding and identical mode of thought however rudimentary that
might be, Spinoza allows that every mode of extension is “animated to some
degree”; his view is thus a form of panpsychism. Another central feature of
Spinoza’s metaphysics is his necessitarianism, expressed in his claim that
“things could have been produced . . . in no other way, and in no other order”
than that in which they have been produced. He derives this necessitarianism
from his doctrine that God exists necessarily for which he offers several
arguments, including a version of the ontological argument and his doctrine
that everything that can follow from the divine nature must necessarily do so.
Thus, although he does not use the term, he accepts a very strong version of
the principle of sufficient reason. At the outset of the Ethics, he defines a
thing as free when its actions are determined by its own nature alone. Only
God whose actions are determined
entirely by the necessity of his own nature, and for whom nothing is external is completely free in this sense.
Nevertheless, human beings can achieve a relative freedom to the extent that
they live the kind of life described in the later parts of the Ethics. Hence,
Spinoza is a compatibilist concerning the relation between freedom and
determinism. “Freedom of the will” in any sense that implies a lack of causal
determination, however, is simply an illusion based on ignorance of the true
causes of a being’s actions. The recognition that all occurrences are causally
determined, Spinoza holds, has a positive consolatory power that aids one in
controlling the passions. Epistemology and psychology. Like other rationalists,
Spinoza distinguishes two representational faculties: the imagination and the
intellect. The imagination is a faculty of forming imagistic representations of
things, derived ultimately from the mechanisms of the senses; the intellect is
a faculty of forming adequate, nonimagistic conceptions of things. He also
distinguishes three “kinds of knowledge.” The first or lowest kind he calls
opinion or imagination opinio, imaginatio. It includes “random or indeterminate
experience” experientia vaga and also “hearsay, or knowledge from mere signs”;
it thus depends on the confused and mutilated deliverances of the senses, and
is inadequate. The second kind of knowledge he calls reason ratio; it depends
on common notions i.e., features of things that are “common to all, and equally
in the part and in the whole” or on adequate knowledge of the properties as
opposed to the essences of things. The third kind of knowledge he calls intuitive
knowledge scientia intuitiva; it proceeds from adequate knowledge of the
essence or attributes of God to knowledge of the essence of things, and hence
proceeds in the proper order, from causes to effects. Both the second and third
kinds of knowledge are adequate. The third kind is preferable, however, as
involving not only certain knowledge that something is so, but also knowledge
of how and why it is so. Because there is only one substance God
the individual things of the world are not distinguished from one
another by any difference of substance. Rather, among the internal qualitative
modifications and differentiations of each divine attribute, there are patterns
that have a tendency to endure; these constitute individual things. As they
occur within the attribute of extension, Spinoza calls these patterns fixed
proportions of motion and rest. Although these individual things are thus modes
of the one substance, rather than substances in their own right, each has a
nature or essence describable in terms of the thing’s particular pattern and
its mechanisms for the preservation of its own being. This tendency toward
self-preservation Spinoza calls conatus sometimes tr. as ‘endeavor’. Every
individual thing has some conatus. An individual thing acts, or is active, to
the extent that what occurs can be explained or understood through its own
nature i.e., its selfpreservatory mechanism alone; it is passive to the extent
that what happens must be explained through the nature of other forces
impinging on it. Thus, every thing, to whatever extent it can, actively strives
to persevere in its existence; and whatever aids this self-preservation
constitutes that individual’s advantage. Spinoza’s specifically human
psychology is an application of this more general doctrine of conatus. That
application is made through appeal to several specific characteristics of human
beings: they form imagistic representations of other individuals by means of
their senses; they are sufficiently complex to undergo increases and decreases
in their capacity for action; and they are capable of engaging in reason. The
fundamental concepts of his psychology are desire, which is conatus itself,
especially as one is conscious of it as directed toward attaining a particular
object; pleasure, which is an increase in capacity for action; and pain, which
is a decrease in capacity for action. He defines other emotions in terms of
these basic emotions, as they occur in particular combinations, in particular
kinds of circumstances, with particular kinds of causes, and/or with particular
kinds of objects. When a person is the adequate cause of his or her own
emotions, these emotions are active emotions; otherwise, they are passions.
Desire and pleasure can be either active emotions or passions, depending on the
circumstances; pain, however, can only be a passion. Spinoza does not deny the
phenomenon of altruism: one’s self-preservatory mechanism, and hence one’s
desire, can become focused on a wide variety of objects, including the
well-being of a loved person or object
even to one’s own detriment. However, because he reduces all human
motivation, including altruistic motivation, to permutations of the endeavor to
seek one’s own advantage, his theory is arguably a form of psychological
egoism. Ethics. Spinoza’s ethical theory does not take the form of a set of
moral commands. Rather, he seeks to demonstrate, by considering human actions
and appetites objectively “just as if it
were a Question of lines, planes, and bodies”
wherein a person’s true advantage lies. Readers who genuinely grasp the
demonstrated truths will, he holds, ipso facto be motivated, to at least some
extent, to live their lives accordingly. Thus, Spinozistic ethics seeks to show
how a person acts when “guided by reason“; to act in this way is at the same
time to act with virtue, or power. All actions that result from
understanding i.e., all virtuous
actions may be attributed to strength of
character fortitudo. Such virtuous actions may be further divided into two
classes: those due to tenacity animositas, or “the Desire by which each one
strives, solely from the dictate of reason, to preserve his being”; and those
due to nobility generositas, or “the Desire by which each one strives, solely
from the dictate of reason, to aid other men and join them to him in
friendship.” Thus, the virtuous person does not merely pursue private
advantage, but seeks to cooperate with others; returns love for hatred; always
acts honestly, not deceptively; and seeks to join himself with others in a
political state. Nevertheless, the ultimate reason for aiding others and
joining them to oneself in friendship is that “nothing is more useful to man
than man” i.e., because doing so is
conducive to one’s own advantage, and particularly to one’s pursuit of knowledge,
which is a good that can be shared without loss. Although Spinoza holds that we
generally use the terms ‘good’ and ‘evil’ simply to report subjective
appearances so that we call “good”
whatever we desire, and “evil” whatever we seek to avoid he proposes that we define ‘good’
philosophically as ‘what we certainly know to be useful to us’, and ‘evil’ as
‘what we certainly know prevents us from being masters of some good’. Since God
is perfect and has no needs, it follows that nothing is either good or evil for
God. Spinoza’s ultimate appeal to the agent’s advantage arguably renders his
ethical theory a form of ethical egoism, even though he emphasizes the
existence of common shareable goods and the instrumental ethical importance of
cooperation with others. However, it is not a form of hedonism; for despite the
prominence he gives to pleasure, the ultimate aim of human action is a higher
state of perfection or capacity for action, of whose increasing attainment
pleasure is only an indicator. A human being whose self-preservatory mechanism
is driven or distorted by external forces is said to be in bondage to the
passions; in contrast, one who successfully pursues only what is truly
advantageous, in consequence of genuine understanding of where that advantage
properly lies, is free. Accordingly, Spinoza also expresses his conception of a
virtuous life guided by reason in terms of an ideal “free man.” Above all, the
free man seeks understanding of himself and of Nature. Adequate knowledge, and
particularly knowledge of the third kind, leads to blessedness, to peace of
mind, and to the intellectual love of God. Blessedness is not a reward for
virtue, however, but rather an integral aspect of the virtuous life. The human
mind is itself a part of the infinite intellect of God, and adequate knowledge
is an eternal aspect of that infinite intellect. Hence, as one gains knowledge,
a greater part of one’s own mind comes to be identified with something that is
eternal, and one becomes less dependent on
and less disturbed by the local
forces of one’s immediate environment. Accordingly, the free man “thinks of
nothing less than of death, and his wisdom is a meditation on life, not on
death.” Moreover, just as one’s adequate knowledge is literally an eternal part
of the infinite intellect of God, the resulting blessedness, peace of mind, and
intellectual love are literally aspects of what might be considered God’s own
eternal “emotional” life. Although this endows the free man with a kind of
blessed immortality, it is not a personal immortality, since the sensation and
memory that are essential to personal individuality are not eternal. Rather,
the free man achieves during his lifetime an increasing participation in a body
of adequate knowledge that has itself always been eternal, so that, at death, a
large part of the free man’s mind has become identified with the eternal. It is
thus a kind of “immortality” in which one can participate while one lives, not
merely when one dies. Politics and philosophical theology. Spinoza’s political
theory, like that of Hobbes, treats rights and power as equivalent. Citizens
give up rights to the state for the sake of the protection that the state can
provide. Hobbes, however, regards this social contract as nearly absolute, one
in which citizens give up all of their rights except the right to resist death.
Spinoza, in contrast, emphasizes that citizens cannot give up the right to
pursue their own advantage as they see it, in its full generality; and hence
that the power, and right, of any actual state is always limited by the state’s
practical ability to enforce its dictates so as to alter the citizens’
continuing perception of their own advantage. Furthermore, he has a more
extensive conception of the nature of an individual’s own advantage than
Hobbes, since for him one’s own true advantage lies not merely in fending off
death and pursuing pleasure, but in achieving the adequate knowledge that
brings blessedness and allows one to participate in that which is eternal. In
consequence, Spinoza, unlike Hobbes, recommends a limited, constitutional state
that encourages freedom of expression and religious toleration. Such a
state itself a kind of individual best preserves its own being, and provides
both the most stable and the most beneficial form of government for its
citizens. In his Theological-Political Treatise, Spinoza also takes up popular
religion, the interpretation of Scripture, and their bearing on the well-being
of the state. He characterizes the Old Testament prophets as individuals whose
vivid imaginations produced messages of political value for the ancient Hebrew
state. Using a naturalistic outlook and historical hermeneutic methods that
anticipate the later “higher criticism” of the Bible, he seeks to show that
Scriptural writers themselves consistently treat only justice and charity as
essential to salvation, and hence that dogmatic doxastic requirements are not
justified by Scripture. Popular religion should thus propound only these two
requirements, which it may imaginatively represent, to the minds of the many,
as the requirements for rewards granted by a divine Lawgiver. The few, who are
more philosophical, and who thus rely on intellect, will recognize that the
natural laws of human psychology require charity and justice as conditions of
happiness, and that what the vulgar construe as rewards granted by personal
divine intervention are in fact the natural consequences of a virtuous life.
Because of his identificaton of God with Nature and his treatment of popular
religion, Spinoza’s contemporaries often regarded his philosophy as a thinly
disguised atheism. Paradoxically, however, nineteenth-century Romanticism
embraced him for his pantheism; Novalis, e.g., famously characterized him as
“the God-intoxicated man.” In fact, Spinoza ascribes to Nature most of the
characteristics that Western theologians have ascribed to God: Spinozistic
Nature is infinite, eternal, necessarily existing, the object of an ontological
argument, the first cause of all things, all-knowing, and the being whose
contemplation produces blessedness, intellectual love, and participation in a
kind of immortality or eternal life. Spinoza’s claim to affirm the existence of
God is therefore no mere evasion. However, he emphatically denies that God is a
person or acts for purposes; that anything is good or evil from the divine
perspective; or that there is a personal immortality involving memory. In
addition to his influence on the history of biblical criticism and on
literature including not only Novalis but such writers as Wordsworth,
Coleridge, Heine, Shelley, George Eliot, George Sand, Somerset Maugham, Jorge
Luis Borges, and Bernard Malamud, Spinoza has affected the philosophical
outlooks of such diverse twentieth-century thinkers as Freud and Einstein. Contemporary
physicists have seen in his monistic metaphysics an anticipation of
twentieth-century field metaphysics. More generally, he is a leading
intellectual forebear of twentieth-century determinism and naturalism, and of
the mindbody identity theory. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Hampshire’s Spinoza.”
spir: philosopher. He served in the Crimean War as a
Russian officer. His major works are “Forschung nach der Gewissheit in der
Erkenntnis der Wirklichkeit,” and “Denken und Wirklichkeit: Versuch einer
Erneuerung der kritischen Philosophie..” The latter essay presents a
metaphysics based on the radical separation of the apparent world and an
absolute reality. All we can know about the “unconditioned” is that it must
conform with the principle of identity. While retaining the unknowable thing-in-itself
of Kant, Spir argues for the empirical reality of time, which is given to us in
immediate experience and depends on our experience of a succession of
differential states (cf. Grice, “Personal identity”). The aim of philosophy is
to reach fundamental and immediate certainties. Of the works included in his “Gesammelte
Schriften,” the essay “Right and Wrong,” was tr.There are a number of
references to Spir in the writings of Nietzsche, which indicate that some of
Nietzsche’s central notions were influenced, both positively and negatively, by
Spir’s analyses of becoming and temporality, as well as by his concept of the
separation of the world of appearance and the “true world.” Refs.: H. P. Grice,
“Bradley’s absolute: a relative account.”
split brain effects, a wide array of behavioral effects
consequent upon the severing of the cerebral commisures, and generally
interpreted as indicating asymmetry in cerebral functions. The human brain has
considerable leftright functional differentiation, or asymmetry, that affects
behavior. The most obvious example is handedness. By the 1860s Bouillaud, Dax,
and Broca had observed that the effects of unilateral damage indicated that the
left hemisphere was preferentially involved in language. Since the 0s, this
commitment to functional asymmetry has been reinforced by studies of patients
in whom communication between the hemispheres has been surgically disrupted.
Split brain effects depend on severing the cerebral commisures, and especially
the corpus callosum, which are neural structures mediating communication
between the cerebral hemispheres. Commisurotomies have been performed since the
0s to control severe epilepsy. This is intended to leave both hemispheres
intact and functioning independently. Beginning in the 0s, J. E. Bogen, M. S.
Gazzaniga, and R. W. Sperry conducted an array of psychological tests to
evaluate the distinctive abilities of the different hemispheres. Ascertaining
the degree of cerebral asymmetry depends on a carefully controlled experimental
design in which access of the disassociated hemispheres to peripheral cues is
limited. The result has been a wide array of striking results. For example,
patients are unable to match an object such as a key felt in one hand with a similar
object felt in the other; patients are unable to name an object Spir, Afrikan
split brain effects 874 874 held in the
left hand, though they can name an object held in the right. Researchers have
concluded that these results confirm a clear lateralization of speech, writing,
and calculation in the left hemisphere for righthanded patients, leaving the
right hemisphere largely unable to respond in speech or writing, and typically
unable to perform even simple calculations. It is often concluded that the left
hemisphere is specialized for verbal and analytic modes of thinking, while the
right hemisphere is specialized for more spatial and synthetic modes of
thinking. The precise character and extent of these differences in normal
subjects are less clear.
square of opposition – figura quadrata – Grice: “It is
clear that the apparatus of Modernism does not give a faithful account of the
character of semantic phenomena. One such less than faithful account, indeed,
deviant account, appears in the treatment of the square of opposition.” cited
by Grice in “Retrospective epilogue.” Since tutoring Strawson on this for
Strawson’s ‘logic paper,’ Grice kept an interest, if only to witness Strwson’s
playing with the square – and ‘uselessly trying to circle it’ -- a graphic
representation of various logical relations among categorical propositions.
Relations among modal and even among hypothetical propositions have also been
represented on the square. Two propositions are said to be each other’s 1
contradictories if exactly one of them must be true and exactly one false; 2
contraries if they could not both be true although they could both be false;
and 3 subcontraries if at least one of them must be true although both of them
may be true. There is a relation of 4 subalternation of one proposition, called
subaltern, to another called superaltern, if the truth of the latter implies
the truth of the former, but not conversely. Applying these definitions to the
four types of categorical propositions, we find that SaP and SoP are
contradictories, and so are SeP and SiP. SaP and SeP are contraries. SiP and
SoP are subcontraries. SiP is subaltern to SaP, and SoP is subaltern to SeP.
These relations can be represented graphically in a square of opposition: The
four relations on the traditional square are expressed in the following theses:
Contradictories: SaP S -SoP, SeP S -SiP Contraries: -SaP & SeP or SaP P
-SeP Subcontraries: SiP 7 SoP Subalterns: SaP P SiP, SeP P SoP For these
relations to hold, an underlying existential assumption must be satisfied: the
terms serving as subjects of propositions must be satisfied, not empty e.g.,
‘man’ is satisfied and ‘elf’ empty. Only the contradictory opposition remains
without that assumption. Modern interpretations of categorical propositions
exclude the existential assumption; thus, only the contradictory opposition
remains in the square. Refs.: H. P.
Grice, “Apuleius on the square of opposition,” H. P. Grice, “Boethius and the
square of opposition.”
standard: Grice:
“People, philosophers included, misuse ‘standard’ – in Italian, it just means
‘flag’!” -- model, a term that, like ‘non-standard model’, is used with regard
to theories that systematize part of our knowledge of some mathematical
structure, for instance the structure of natural numbers with addition,
multiplication, and the successor function, or the structure of real numbers
with ordering, addition, and multiplication. Models isomorphic to this intended
mathematical structure are the “standard models” of the theory, while any
other, non-isomorphic, model of the theory is a ‘non-standard’ model. Since
Peano arithmetic is incomplete, it has consistent extensions that have no
standard model. But there are also non-standard, countable models of complete
number theory, the set of all true first-order sentences about natural numbers,
as was first shown by Skolem in 4. Categorical theories do not have a
non-standard model. It is less clear whether there is a standard model of set
theory, although a countable model would certainly count as non-standard. The
Skolem paradox is that any first-order formulation of set theory, like ZF, due
to Zermelo and Fraenkel, has a countable model, while it seems to assert the
existence of non-countable sets. Many other important mathematical structures
cannot be characterized by a categorical set of first-order axioms, and thus
allow non-standard models. The
philosopher Putnam has argued that this fact has important implications
for the debate about realism in the philosophy of language. If axioms cannot
capture the spontaneity, liberty of standard model 875 875 “intuitive” notion of a set, what could?
Some of his detractors have pointed out that within second-order logic
categorical characterizations are often possible. But Putnam has objected that
the intended interpretation of second-order logic itself is not fixed by the
use of the formalism of second-order logic, where “use” is determined by the
rules of inference for second-order logic we know about. Moreover, categorical
theories are sometimes uninformative.
state, Grice: “I will use the phrase ‘state of the soul’ –
This may sound pedantic, and it is!” – “I will use ‘psychological state,’ where
the more correct phrase would be ‘state’ of the ‘soul,’ since theory – as in
‘-logical,’ has nothing to do with it. Now you’ll wonder if the soul has
states. A state of the soul – or a ‘frame of mind,’ as Strawson wrongly puts it
– is a physical state on which a ‘state’ of the soul supervenes, alla
Funcionalism” – “Note that a ’state’ of the soul may be quite specific and
involving other states, like the belief that Strawson’s dog is shaggy.” – “A
state is anything that follows a ‘that’-clause; the way an object or system
basically is; the fundamental, intrinsic properties of an object or system, and
the basis of its other properties. An instantaneous state is a state at a given
time. State variables are constituents of a state whose values may vary with
time. In classical or Newtonian mechanics the instantaneous state of an
n-particle system consists of the positions and momenta masses multiplied by
velocities of the n particles at a given time. Other mechanical properties are
functions of those in states. Fundamental and derived properties are often,
though possibly misleadingly, called observables. The set of a system’s
possible states can be represented as an abstract phase space or state space,
with dimensions or coordinates for the components of each state variable. In
quantum theory, states do not fix the particular values of observables, only
the probabilities of observables assuming particular values in particular
measurement situations. For positivism or instrumentalism, specifying a quantum
state does nothing more than provide a means for calculating such
probabilities. For realism, it does more e.g., it refers to the basis of a quantum
system’s probabilistic dispositions or propensities. Vectors in Hilbert spaces
represent possible states, and Hermitian operators on vectors represent
observables.
state of affairs. Grice: “My poor friend D. F. Pears
got himself into a lot of trouble by offering to correct C. K. Ogden’s passe
translation of Vitters’s Tractatus!” a possibility, actuality, or impossibility
of the kind expressed by a nominalization of a declarative sentence. The
declarative sentence ‘This die comes up six’ can be nominalized either through
the construction ‘that this die comes up six’ or through the likes of ‘this
die’s coming up six’. The resulting nominalizations might be interpreted as
naming corresponding propositions or states of affairs. States of affairs come
in several varieties. Some are possible states of affairs, or possibilities.
Consider the possibility of a certain die coming up six when rolled next. This
possibility is a state of affairs, as is its “complement” the die’s not coming up six when rolled next.
There is in addition the state of affairs which conjoins that die’s coming up
six with its not coming up six. And this contradictory state of affairs is of
course not a possibility, not a possible state of affairs. Moreover, for every
actual state of affairs there is a non-actual one, its complement. For every
proposition there is hence a state of affairs: possible or impossible, actual
or not. Indeed some consider propositions to be states of affairs. Some take
facts to be actual states of affairs, while others prefer to define them as
true propositions. If propositions are states of affairs, then facts are of
course both actual states of affairs and true propositions. In a very broad
sense, events are just possible states of affairs; in a narrower sense they are
contingent states of affairs; and in a still narrower sense they are contingent
and particular states of affairs, involving just the exemplification of an
nadic property by a sequence of individuals of length n. In a yet narrower
sense events are only those particular and contingent states of affairs that
entail change. A baseball’s remaining round throughout a certain period does
not count as an event in this narrower sense but only as a state of that baseball,
unlike the event of its being hit by a certain bat.
statistics – Grice: “I shall use the singular,
‘statistic’” -- statistical explanation.
Grice: “Jill says, “Jack is an Englishman; he is, therefore, brave.” Is the
validty of her reasoning based on statistics?” -- an explanation expressed in
an explanatory argument containing premises and conclusions making claims about
statistical probabilities. These arguments include deductions of less general
from more general laws and differ from other such explanations only insofar as
the contents of the laws imply claims about statistical probability. Most
philosophical discussion in the latter half of the twentieth century has
focused on statistical explanation of events rather than laws. This type of
argument was discussed by Ernest Nagel The Structure of Science, 1 under the
rubric “probabilistic explanation,” and by Hempel Aspects of Scientific
Explanation, 5 as “inductive statistical” explanation. The explanans contains a
statement asserting that a given system responds in one of several ways
specified by a sample space of possible outcomes on a trial or experiment of
some type, and that the statistical probability of an event represented by a
set of points in the sample space on the given kind of trial is also given for
each such event. Thus, the statement might assert that the statistical
probability is near 1 of the relative frequency r/n of heads in n tosses being
close to the statistical probability p of heads on a single toss, where the
sample space consists of the 2n possible sequences of heads and tails in n
tosses. Nagel and Hempel understood such statistical probability statements to
be covering laws, so that inductive-statistical explanation and
deductivenomological explanation of events are two species of covering law
explanation. The explanans also contains a claim that an experiment of the kind
mentioned in the statistical assumption has taken place e.g., the coin has been
tossed n times. The explanandum asserts that an event of some kind has occurred
e.g., the coin has landed heads approximately r times in the n tosses. In many
cases, the kind of experiment can be described equivalently as an n-fold
repetition of some other kind of experiment as a thousandfold repetition of the
tossing of a given coin or as the implementation of the kind of trial
thousand-fold tossing of the coin one time. Hence, statistical explanation of
events can always be construed as deriving conclusions about “single cases”
from assumptions about statistical probabilities even when the concern is to
explain mass phenomena. Yet, many authors controversially contrast statistical
explanation in quantum mechanics, which is alleged to require a singlecase
propensity interpretation of statistical probability, with statistical explanation
in statistical mechanics, genetics, and the social sciences, which allegedly
calls for a frequency interpretation. The structure of the explanatory argument
of such statistical explanation has the form of a direct inference from
assumptions about statistical probabilities and the kind of experiment trial
which has taken place to the outcome. One controversial aspect of direct
inference is the problem of the reference class. Since the early nineteenth
century, statistical probability has been understood to be relative to the way
the experiment or trial is described. Authors like J. Venn, Peirce, R. A.
Fisher, and Reichenbach, among many others, have been concerned with how to
decide on which kind of trial to base a direct inference when the trial under
investigation is correctly describable in several ways and the statistical
probabilities of possible outcomes may differ relative to the different sorts
of descriptions. The most comprehensive discussion of this problem of the
reference class is found in the work of H. E. Kyburg e.g., Probability and the
Logic of Rational Belief, 1. Hempel acknowledged its importance as an
“epistemic ambiguity” in inductive statistical explanation. Controversy also
arises concerning inductive acceptance. May the conclusion of an explanatory
direct inference be a judgment as to the subjective probability that the
outcome event occurred? May a judgment that the outcome event occurred is
inductively “accepted” be made? Is some other mode of assessing the claim about
the outcome appropriate? Hempel’s discussion of the “nonconjunctiveness of
inductivestatistical” explanation derives from Kyburg’s earlier account of
direct inference where high probability is assumed to be sufficient for
acceptance. Non-conjunctiveness has been avoided by abandoning the sufficiency
of high probability I. Levi, Gambling with Truth, 7 or by denying that direct
inference in inductive-statistical explanation involves inductive acceptance at
all R. C. Jeffrey, “Statistical Explanation vs. Statistical Inference,” in Essays
in Honor of C. G. Hempel. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Jack and Jill.”
steiner: Austrian spiritualist and founder of anthroposophy.
Trained as a scientist, he edited Goethe’s scientific writings and prepared the
standard edition of his complete works from 9 to 6. Steiner’s major work, Die
Philosophie der Freiheit, was published in 4. His Friedrich Nietzsche: Ein
Kämpfer gegen seine Zeit 5 was tr. in 0 by Margaret deRis as Friedrich
Nietzsche: Fighter for Freedom. Steiner taught at a workingmen’s and edited a literary journal, Magazin für
Literatur, in Berlin. In 1 he embraced a spiritualism which emphasized a form
of knowledge that transcended sensory experience and was attained by the
“higher self.” He held that man had previously been attuned to spiritual
processes by virtue of a dreamlike state of consciousness, but was diverted
from this consciousness by preoccupation with material entities. Through
training, individuals could retrieve their innate capacity to perceive a
spiritual realm. Steiner’s writings on this theme are The Philosophy of
Spiritual Activity 4, Occult Science: An Outline 3, On the Riddle of Man 6, and
On the Riddles of the Soul 7. His last work was his autobiography 4. To advance
his teachings, he founded the Anthroposophical Society 2 and a school of
“spiritual science” called the Goetheanum near Basel, Switzerland. His work
inspired the Waldorf School movement, which comprises some eighty schools for
children. The anthroposophy movement he established remains active in Europe
and the United States. G.J.S. Stephen, Sir Leslie 18324, English literary
critic, editor, intellectual historian, and philosopher. He was the first chief
editor of the great Dictionary of National Biography, writing hundreds of the
entries himself. Brought up in an intensely religious household, he lost his
faith and spent much of his time trying to construct a moral and intellectual
outlook to replace it. His main works in intellectual history, the two-volume
History of English Thought in the Eighteenth Century 1876 and the three-volume
English Utilitarians 0, were undertaken as part of this project. So was his one
purely philosophical work, the Science of Ethics 2, in which he tried to
develop an evolutionary theory of morality. Stephen was impatient of
philosophical technicalities. Hence his treatise on ethics does very little to
resolve the problems some of them
pointed out to him by his friend Henry Sidgwick
with evolutionary ethics, and does not get beyond the several other
works on the subject published during this period. His histories of thought are
sometimes superficial, and their focus of interest is not ours; but they are
still useful because of their scope and the massive scholarship they put to
use. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Steiner and
moi.”
Stillingfleet: e.
English divine and controversialist who first made his name with “Irenicum,”
using natural-law doctrines to oppose religious sectarianism. His “Origines
Sacrae” ostensibly on the superiority of the Scriptural record over other forms
of ancient history, was for its day a learned study in the moral certainty of
historical evidence, the authority of testimony, and the credibility of
miracles. In drawing eclectically on philosophy from antiquity to the Cambridge
Platonists, he was much influenced by the Cartesian theory of ideas, but later
repudiated Cartesianism for its mechanist tendency. For three decades he
pamphleteered on behalf of the moral certainty of orthodox Protestant belief
against what he considered the beliefs “contrary to reason” of Roman
Catholicism. This led to controversy with Unitarian and deist writers who
argued that mysteries like the Trinity were equally contrary to “clear and
distinct” ideas. He was alarmed at the use made of Locke’s “new,” i.e.
nonCartesian, way of ideas by John Toland in Christianity not Mysterious, and
devoted his last years to challenging Locke to prove his orthodoxy. The debate
was largely over the concepts of substance, essence, and person, and of faith
and certainty. Locke gave no quarter in the public controversy, but in the fourth
edition of his Essay he silently amended some passages that had provoked
Stillingfleet.
Schmidt: -- Stirner, Max, pseudonym of Kasper Schmidt, philosopher
who proposed a theory of radical individualism. Born in Bayreuth, he taught in
Gymnasiums and later at a Berlin academy for women. He tr. what became a
standard G. version of Smith’s Wealth of Nations and contributed articles to
the Rhenische Zeitung. His most important work was statistical probability, “Der
Einzige und sein Eigenthum,” tr. by Steven T. Byington as The Ego and His Own,
and Grice as “The idiot and his idiocy.” -- His second book was “Die Geschichte
der Reaktion.” Schmidt is in reaction to Hegel and was for a time associated
with the left Hegelians. He stressed the priority of will and instinct over
reason and proposed a radical anarchic individualism. Each individual is
unique, and the independent ego is the fundamental value and reality. Stirner
attacks the state, religious ideas, and abstractions such as “humanity” as
“spectres” that are deceptive illusions, remnants of erroneous
hypostatizations. His defense of egoism is such that the individual is
considered to have no obligations or duties, and especially not to the state.
Encouraging an individual “rebellion” against state domination and control,
Stirner attracted a following among nineteenthand twentieth-century anarchists.
The sole goal of life is the cultivation of “uniqueness” or “ownness.” Engels
and Marx attack his ideas at length under the rubric “Saint Marx” in The G.
Ideology. Insofar as his theory of radical individualism offers no clearly
stated ethical requirements, it has been characterized as a form of nihilistic
egoism. Refs.: H. P. Grice: “Schmidt, or the idiot and his idiocy.”
stochastic process – 1660s,
"pertaining to conjecture," from Greek stokhastikos "able to
guess, conjecturing," from stokhazesthai "to guess, aim at,
conjecture," from stokhos "a guess, aim, fixed target, erected pillar
for archers to shoot at," perhaps from PIE *stogh-, variant of root
*stegh- "to stick, prick, sting." The sense of "randomly
determined" is from 1934, from German stochastik (1917). a process
that evolves, as time goes by, according to a probabilistic principle rather
than a deterministic principle. Such processes are also called random
processes, but ‘stochastic’ does not imply complete disorderliness. The
principle of evolution governing a stochastic or random process is precise,
though probabilistic, in form. For example, suppose some process unfolds in
discrete successive stages. And suppose that given any initial sequence of
stages, S1, S2, . . . , Sn, there is a precise probability that the next stage
Sn+1 will be state S, a precise probability that it will be SH, and so on for
all possible continuations of the sequence of states. These probabilities are
called transition probabilities. An evolving sequence of this kind is called a
discrete-time stochastic process, or discrete-time random process. A
theoretically important special case occurs when transition probabilities
depend only on the latest stage in the sequence of stages. When an evolving
process has this property it is called a discrete-time Markov process. A simple
example of a discrete-time Markov process is the behavior of a person who keeps
taking either a step forward or a step back according to whether a coin falls
heads or tails; the probabilistic principle of movement is always applied to the
person’s most recent position. The successive stages of a stochastic process
need not be discrete. If they are continuous, they constitute a
“continuous-time” stochastic or random process. The mathematical theory of
stochastic processes has many applications in science and technology. The
evolution of epidemics, the process of soil erosion, and the spread of cracks
in metals have all been given plausible models as stochastic processes, to
mention just a few areas of research. H.
P. Grice, “Stochastic implicatum.”
stoa – H. P. Grice: “The Stoa and Athenian dialectic.” -- stoicism,
one of the three leading movements constituting Hellenistic philosophy. Its
founder was Zeno of Citium, who was succeeded as school head by Cleanthes. But
the third head, Chrysippus, was its greatest exponent and most voluminous
writer. These three are the leading representatives of Early Stoicism. No work
by any early Stoic survives intact, except Cleanthes’ short “Hymn to Zeus.”
Otherwise we are dependent on doxography, on isolated quotations, and on
secondary sources, most of them hostile. Nevertheless, a remarkably coherent
account of the system can be assembled. The Stoic world is an ideally good
organism, all of whose parts interact for the benefit of the whole. It is
imbued with divine reason logos, its entire development providentially ordained
by fate and repeated identically from one world phase to the next in a
never-ending cycle, each phase ending with a conflagration ekpyrosis. Only
bodies strictly “exist” and can interact. Body is infinitely divisible, and
contains no void. At the lowest level, the world is analyzed into an active
principle, god, and a passive principle, matter, both probably corporeal. Out
of these are generated, at a higher level, the four elements air, fire, earth,
and water, whose own interaction is analogous to that of god and matter: air
and fire, severally or conjointly, are an active rational force called breath
Grecian pneuma, Latin spiritus, while earth and water constitute the passive
substrate on which these act, totally interpenetrating each other thanks to the
non-particulate structure of body and its capacity to be mixed “through and
through.” Most physical analysis is conducted at this higher level, and pneuma
becomes a key concept in physics and biology. A thing’s qualities are
constituted by its pneuma, which has the additional role of giving it
cohestochastic process Stoicism 879 879
sion and thus an essential identity. In inanimate objects this unifying pneuma
is called a hexis state; in plants it is called physis nature; and in animals
“soul.” Even qualities of soul, e.g. justice, are portions of pneuma, and they
too are therefore bodies: only thus could they have their evident causal
efficacy. Four incorporeals are admitted: place, void which surrounds the
world, time, and lekta see below; these do not strictly “exist” they lack the corporeal power of
interaction but as items with some
objective standing in the world they are, at least, “somethings.” Universals,
identified with Plato’s Forms, are treated as concepts ennoemata, convenient
fictions that do not even earn the status of “somethings.” Stoic ethics is
founded on the principle that only virtue is good, only vice bad. Other things
conventionally assigned a value are “indifferent” adiaphora, although some,
e.g., health, wealth, and honor, are naturally “preferred” proegmena, while
their opposites are “dispreferred” apoproegmena. Even though their possession
is irrelevant to happiness, from birth these indifferents serve as the
appropriate subject matter of our choices, each correct choice being a “proper
function” kathekon not yet a morally
good act, but a step toward our eventual end telos of “living in accordance
with nature.” As we develop our rationality, the appropriate choices become
more complex, less intuitive. For example, it may sometimes be more in accordance
with nature’s plan to sacrifice your wealth or health, in which case it becomes
your “proper function” to do so. You have a specific role to play in the world
plan, and moral progress prokope consists in learning it. This progress
involves widening your natural “affinity” oikeiosis: an initial concern for
yourself and your parts is later extended to those close to you, and eventually
to all mankind. That is the Stoic route toward justice. However, justice and
the other virtues are actually found only in the sage, an idealized perfectly
rational person totally in tune with the divine cosmic plan. The Stoics doubted
whether any sages existed, although there was a tendency to treat at least
Socrates as having been one. The sage is totally good, everyone else totally
bad, on the paradoxical Stoic principle that all sins are equal. The sage’s
actions, however similar externally to mere “proper functions,” have an
entirely distinct character: they are renamed ‘right actions’ katorthomata.
Acting purely from “right reason,” he is distinguished by his “freedom from
passion” apatheia: morally wrong impulses, or passions, are at root
intellectual errors of mistaking what is indifferent for good or bad, whereas
the sage’s evaluations are always correct. The sage alone is happy and truly
free, living in perfect harmony with the divine plan. All human lives are
predetermined by the providentially designed, all-embracing causal nexus of
fate; yet being the principal causes of their actions, the good and the bad
alike are responsible for them: determinism and morality are fully compatible.
Stoic epistemology defends the existence of cognitive certainty against the
attacks of the New Academy. Belief is described as assent synkatathesis to an
impression phantasia, i.e. taking as true the propositional content of some
perceptual or reflective impression. Certainty comes through the “cognitive
impression” phantasia kataleptike, a self-certifying perceptual representation
of external fact, claimed to be commonplace. Out of sets of such impressions we
acquire generic conceptions prolepseis and become rational. The highest
intellectual state, knowledge episteme, in which all cognitions become mutually
supporting and hence “unshakable by reason,” is the prerogative of the wise. Everyone
else is in a state of mere opinion doxa or of ignorance. Nevertheless, the
cognitive impression serves as a “criterion of truth” for all. A further
important criterion is prolepseis, also called common conceptions and common
notions koinai ennoiai, often appealed to in philosophical argument. Although
officially dependent on experience, they often sound more like innate
intuitions, purportedly indubitable. Stoic logic is propositional, by contrast
with Aristotle’s logic of terms. The basic unit is the simple proposition
axioma, the primary bearer of truth and falsehood. Syllogistic also employs
complex propositions conditional,
conjunctive, and disjunctive and rests
on five “indemonstrable” inference schemata to which others can be reduced with
the aid of four rules called themata. All these items belong to the class of
lekta “sayables” or “expressibles.”
Words are bodies vibrating portions of air, as are external objects, but
predicates like that expressed by ‘ . . . walks’, and the meanings of whole
sentences, e.g., ‘Socrates walks’, are incorporeal lekta. The structure and
content of both thoughts and sentences are analyzed by mapping them onto lekta,
but the lekta are themselves causally inert. Conventionally, a second phase of
the school is distinguished as Middle Stoicism. It developed largely at Rhodes
under Panaetius and Posidonius, both of whom influenced the presentation of
Stoicism in Cicero’s influential philosophical treatises mid-first century
B.C.. Panaetius Stoicism Stoicism 880
880 c.185c.110 softened some classical Stoic positions, his ethics being
more pragmatic and less concerned with the idealized sage. Posidonius c.135c.50
made Stoicism more open to Platonic and Aristotelian ideas, reviving Plato’s
inclusion of irrational components in the soul. A third phase, Roman Stoicism,
is the only Stoic era whose writings have survived in quantity. It is
represented especially by the younger Seneca A.D. c.165, Epictetus A.D.
c.55c.135, and Marcus Aurelius A.D. 12180. It continued the trend set by
Panaetius, with a strong primary focus on practical and personal ethics. Many
prominent Roman political figures were Stoics. After the second century A.D.
Stoicism as a system fell from prominence, but its terminology and concepts had
by then become an ineradicable part of ancient thought. Through the writings of
Cicero and Seneca, its impact on the moral and political thought of the
Renaissance was immense.
stoutianism: g. f., philosophical psychologist, astudent
of Ward, he was influenced by Herbart and especially Brentano. He influenced
Grice to the point that Grice called himself “a true Stoutian.” He was editor of Mind 20. He followed Ward in
rejecting associationism and sensationism, and proposing analysis of mind as
activity rather than passivity, consisting of acts of cognition, feeling, and
conation. Stout stressed attention as the essential function of mind, and
argued for the goal-directedness of all mental activity and behavior, greatly
influencing McDougall’s hormic psychology. He reinterpreted traditional
associationist ideas to emphasize primacy of mental activity; e.g., association
by contiguity a passive mechanical
process imposed on mind became association
by continuity of attentional interest. With Brentano, he argued that mental
representation involves “thought reference” to a real object known through the
representation that is itself the object of thought, like Locke’s “idea.” In
philosophy he was influenced by Moore and Russell. His major works are Analytic
Psychology 6 and Manual of Psychology 9.
Strato: Grecian philosopher and polymath nicknamed “the
Physicist” for his innovative ideas in natural science. He succeeded
Theophrastus as head of the Lyceum. Earlier he served as royal tutor in
Alexandria, where his students included Aristarchus, who devised the first
heliocentric model. Of Strato’s many writings only fragments and summaries
survive. These show him criticizing the abstract conceptual analysis of earlier
theorists and paying closer attention to empirical evidence. Among his targets
were atomist arguments that motion is impossible unless there is void, and also
Aristotle’s thesis that matter is fully continuous. Strato argued that no large
void occurs in nature, but that matter is naturally porous, laced with tiny
pockets of void. His investigations of compression and suction were influential
in ancient physiology. In dynamics, he proposed that bodies have no property of
lightness but only more or less weight.
strawsonise: verb invented by A. M. Kemmerling. To adopt
Strawson’s manoever in the analysis of ‘meaning.’ “A form of ‘disgricing,’” –
Kemmerling adds.
Strawsonism – Grice’s favourite Strawsonisms were too
many to count. His first was Strawson on ‘true’ for ‘Analysis.’ Grice was
amazed by the rate of publishing in Strawson’s case. Strawson kept publishing
and Grice kept criticizing. In “Analysis,’ Strawson gives Grice his first
‘strawsonism’ “To say ‘true’ is ditto.’ The second strawsonism is that there is
such a thing as ‘ordinary language’ which is not Russellian. As Grice shows,
ordinary language IS Russellian. Strawson said that composing “In defence of a
dogma” was torture and that it is up to Strawson to finish the thing off. So there are a few strawonisms there, too. Strawson
had the courtesy never to reprint ‘In defence’ in any of his compilations, and
of course to have Grice as fist author. There are ‘strawsonisms’ in Grice’s
second collaboration with Strawson – that Grice intentionally ignores in “Life
and opinions.” This is a transcript of the talk of the dynamic trio: Grice,
Pears, and Strawson, published three years later by Pears in “The nature of
metaphysics.” Strawson collaborated with “If and the horseshoe” to PGRICE, but
did not really write it for the occasion. It was an essay he had drafted ages
ago, and now saw fit to publish. He expands on this in his note on Grice for
the British Academy, and in his review of Grice’s compilation. Grice makes an
explicit mention of Strawson in a footnote in “Presupposition and
conversational implicaturum,” the euphemism he uses is ‘tribute’: the
refutation of Strawson’s truth-value gap as a metaphysical excrescence and
unnecessary is called a ‘tribute,’ coming from the tutor – “in this and other
fields,” implicating, “there may be mistakes all over the place.” Kemmerling
somewhat ignores Urmson when he says, “Don’t disgrice if you can grice.” To
strawsonise, for Kemmerling is to avoid Grice’s direct approach and ask for a
higher-level intention. To strawsonise is the first level of disgrice. But
Grice first quotes Urmson and refers to Stampe’s briddge example before he does
to Strawson’s rat-infested house example.
strawson’s
rat-infested house. Few in Grice’s
playgroup had Grice’s analytic skills. Only a few cared to join him in his
analysis of ‘mean.’ The first was Urmson with the ‘bribe.’ The second was
Strawson, with his rat-infested house. Grice re-writes Strawson’s alleged
counterexample. To deal with his own rat-infested house example, Strawson
proposes that the analysans of "U means that p" might be restricted
by the addition of a further condition, namely that the utterer U should utter
x not only, as already provided, with the intention that his addressee should
think that U intends to obtain a certain response from his addressee, but also
with the intention that his addressee should think (recognize) that U has the
intention just mentioned. In Strawson's example, in The Philosohical
Review (that Grice cites on WOW:x) repr. in his "Logico-Linguistic
Papers," the potential home buyer is intended to think that the realtor
wants him to think that the house is rat-infested. However, the potential
house-buyer is not intended by the realtor to think that he is intended to
think that the realtor wants him to think that the house is rat infested. The
addressee is intended to think that it is only as a result of being too
clever for the realtor that he has learned that the potential home
buyer wants him to think that the house is rat-infested; the
potential home-buyer is to think that he is supposed to take the artificially
displayed dead rat as a evidence that the house is rat infested. U
wants to get A to believe that the house A is thinking of buying is
rat-infested. S decides to· bring about this belief in A by taking into the
house and letting loose a big fat sewer rat. For S has the following
scheme. He knows that A is watching him and knows that A believes that S
is unaware that he, A, is watching him. It isS's intention that A should
(wrongly) infer from the fact that S let the rat loose that S did so with the
intention that A should arrive at the house, see the rat, and, taking the rat
as "natural evidence", infer therefrom that the house is
rat-infested. S further intends A to realize that given the nature of the rat's
arrival, the existence of the rat cannot be taken as genuine or natural
evidence that the house is rat-infested; but S kilows that A will believe that
S would not so contrive to get A to believe the house is rat-infested unless
Shad very good reasons for thinking that it was, and so S expects and intends A
to infer that the house is rat-infested from the fact that Sis letting the rat
loose with the intention of getting A to believe that the house is
rat-infested. Thus S satisfies the conditions purported to be necessary and
sufficient for his meaning something by letting the rat loose: S lets the rat
loose intending (4) A to think that the house is rat-infested, intending
(1)-(3) A to infer from the fact that S let the rat loose that S did so
intending A to think that the house is rat-infested, and intending (5) A's
recognition of S's . intention (4) to function as his reason for thinking that
the house is rat-infested. But even though S's action meets these
conditions, Strawson feels that his scenario fits Grice's conditions in
Grice's reductive analysis and not yet Strawson's intuition about his own use
of 'communicate.' To minimise Strawson's discomfort, Grice brings an
anti-sneaky clause. ("Although I never shared Strawson's intuition about
his use of 'communicate;' in fact, I very rarely use 'communicate that...' To
exterminate the rats in Strawson's rat-infested house, Grice uses, as he
should, a general "anti-deception" clause. It may be that
the use of this exterminating procedure is possible. It may be that any 'backward-looking'
clauses can be exterminated, and replaced by a general prohibitive, or closure
clause, forbidding an intention by the utterer to be sneaky. It is a conceptual
point that if you intend your addressee NOT TO REALISE that p, you are not
COMMUNICATING that p. (3A) (if) (3r) (ic): (a) U utters x
intending (I) A to think x possesses f (2) A to thinkf correlated in
way c with the type to which r belongs (3) A to think, on the basis of the
fulfillment of (I) and (3) that U intends A to produce r (4) A, on the basis of
the fulfillment of (3) to produce r, and (b) There is no
inference-element E such that U intends both (I') A in his determination of r
to rely on E (2') A to think Uto intend (I') to be false. In the final version
Grice reaches after considering alleged counterexamples to the NECESSITY of
some of the conditions in the analysans, Grice reformulates. It is not the case
that, for some inference element E, U intends x to be such
that anyone who has φ both rely on E in coming to ψ, or think that U ψ-s, that p and think that (Ǝφ) U intends x to be
such that anyone who has φ come to ψ (or think that U ψ-s) that
p without relying on E. Embedded in the general definition. By uttering x,
U means that-ψb-dp ≡ (Ǝφ)(Ǝf)(Ǝc) U
utters x intending x to be such that anyone who
has φ think that x has f, f is correlated in way c
with ψ-ing that p, and (Ǝφ') U intends x to be such
that anyone who has φ' think, via thinking that x has
f and that f is correlated in way c with ψ-ing that p, that U ψ-s that
p, and in view of (Ǝφ') U intending x to be such
that anyone who has φ' think, via thinking that x has
f, and f is correlated in way c with ψ-ing that p, that U ψ-s that
p, U ψ-s that p, and, for some
substituends of ψb-d, U utters x
intending that, should there actually be anyone who
has φ, he will, via thinking in view of (Ǝφ') U
intending x to be such that anyone who has φ' think, via
thinking that x has f, and f is correlated in way c
with ψ-ing that p, that U ψ-s that p, U ψ-s that
p himself ψ that p, and it is not
the case that, for some inference element E, U intends x to be such
that anyone who has φ both rely on E in coming to ψ, or think that U ψ-s, that p and think that (Ǝφ) U intends x to be
such that anyone who has φ come to ψ (or think that U ψ-s) that
p without relying on E,
strawson: p. f. – Grice’s tutee. b.9, London-born,
Oxford-educated philosopher who has made major contributions to logic,
metaphysics, and the study of Kant. His career has been mainly at Oxford (he
spent a term in Wales and visited the New World a lot), where he was the
leading philosopher of his generation, due to that famous tutor he had for his
‘logic paper’: H. P. Grice, at St. John’s. His first important work, “On
Referring” argues that Baron Russell’s theory of descriptions fails to deal
properly with the role of descriptions as “referring expressions” because
Russell assumed the “bogus trichotomy” that sentences are true, false, or
meaningless: for Strawson, sentences with empty descriptions are meaningful but
“neither true nor false” because the general presuppositions governing the use
of referring expressions are not fulfilled. One aspect of this argument was
Russell’s alleged insensitivity to the ordinary use of definite descriptions.
The contrast between the abstract schemata of formal logic and the manifold
richness of the inferences inherent in ordinary language is the central theme
of Strawson’s “ Introduction to Logical Theory,” where he credits H. P. Grice
for making him aware of ‘pragmatic rules’ of conversation – Grice was amused
that Baron Russell cared to respond to Strawson in “Mind” – where Russell’s
original “On denoting” had been published. Together, after a joint seminar with
Quine, Strawson submitted “In defense of a dogma,” co-written with Grice – A
year later Strawson submitted on Grice’s behalf “Meaning” to the same journal –
They participated with Pears in a Third programme lecture, published by Pears
in “The nature of metaphysics” (London, Macmillan”). In Individuals,
provocatively entitled “an essay in DESCRIPTIVE (never revisionary)
metaphysics,” Strawson, drawing “without crediting” on joint seminars with Grice
on Categories and De Interpretatione, Strawson reintroduced metaphysics as a respectable
philosophical discipline after decades of positivist rhetoric. But his project
is only “descriptive” metaphysics
elucidation of the basic features of our own conceptual scheme and his arguments are based on the philosophy
of language: “basic” particulars are those like “Grice” or his “cricket bat”,
which are basic objects of reference, and it is the spatiotemporal and sortal
conditions for their identification and reidentification by speakers that
constitute the basic categories. Three arguments are especially famous. First, even
in a purely auditory world objective reference on the basis of experience
requires at least an analogue of space. Second, because self-reference
presupposes reference to others, persons, conceived as bearers of both physical
and psychological properties, are a type of basic particular – cfr. Grice on
“Personal identity.” Third, “feature-placing” discourse, such as ‘it is snowing
here now’, is “the ultimate propositional level” through which reference to
particulars enters discourse. Strawson’s next book, The Bounds of Sense 6,
provides a critical reading of Kant’s theoretical philosophy. His aim is to
extricate what he sees as the profound truths concerning the presuppositions of
objective experience and judgment that Kant’s transcendental arguments
establish from the mysterious metaphysics of Kant’s transcendental idealism.
Strawson’s critics have argued, however, that the resulting position is
unstable: transcendental arguments can tell us only what we must suppose to be
the case. So if Kant’s idealism, which restricts such suppositions to things as
they appear to us, is abandoned, we can draw conclusions concerning the way the
world itself must be only if we add the verificationist thesis that ability to
make sense of such suppositions requires ability to verify them. In his next
book, Skepticism and Naturalism: Some Varieties 5, Strawson conceded this:
transcendental arguments belong within descriptive metaphysics and should not
be regarded as attempts to provide an external justification of our conceptual
scheme. In truth no such external justification is either possible or needed:
instead and here Strawson invokes Hume
rather than Kant our reasonings come to
an end in natural propensities for belief that are beyond question because they
alone make it possible to raise questions. In a famous earlier paper Strawson
had urged much the same point concerning the free will debate: defenders of our
ordinary attitudes of reproach and gratitude should not seek to ground them in
the “panicky metaphysics” of a supra-causal free will; instead they can and
need do no more than point to our unshakable commitment to these “reactive”
attitudes through which we manifest our attachment to that fundamental category
of our conceptual scheme persons.
structuratum: mid-15c.,
"action or process of building or construction;" 1610s, "that
which is constructed, a building or edifice;" from Latin structura "a
fitting together, adjustment; a building, mode of building;" figuratively,
"arrangement, order," from structus, past participle of struere
"to pile, place together, heap up; build, assemble, arrange, make by
joining together," related to strues "heap," from PIE *streu-,
extended form of root *stere- "to spread.” structuralism, a
distinctive yet extremely wide range of productive research conducted in the
social and human sciences from the 0s through the 0s, principally in France. It
is difficult to describe structuralism as a movement, because of the
methodological constraints exercised by the various disciplines that came to be
influenced by structuralism e.g.,
anthropology, philosophy, literary theory, psychoanalysis, political theory,
even mathematics. Nonetheless, structuralism is generally held to derive its
organizing principles from the early twentieth-century work of Saussure, the
founder of structural linguistics. Arguing against the prevailing historicist
and philological approaches to linguistics, he proposed a “scientific” model of
language, one understood as a closed system of elements and rules that account
for the production and the social communication of meaning. Inspired by
Durkheim’s notion of a “social fact”
that domain of objectivity wherein the psychological and the social
orders converge Saussure viewed language
as the repository of discursive signs shared by a given linguistic community.
The particular sign is composed of two elements, a phonemic signifier, or
distinctive sound element, and a corresponding meaning, or signified element.
The defining relation between the sign’s sound and meaning components is held
to be arbitrary, i.e., based on conventional association, and not due to any
function of the speaking subject’s personal inclination, or to any external
consideration of reference. What lends specificity or identity to each
particular signifier is its differential relation to the other signifiers in
the greater set; hence, each basic unit of language is itself the product of differences
between other elements within the system. This principle of differential and structural relation was extended by Troubetzkoy to the
order of phonemes, whereby a defining set of vocalic differences underlies the
constitution of all linguistic phonemes. Finally, for Saussure, the closed set
of signs is governed by a system of grammatical, phonemic, and syntactic rules.
Language thus derives its significance from its own autonomous organization,
and this serves to guarantee its communicative function. Since language is the
foremost instance of social sign systems in general, the structural account
might serve as an exemplary model for understanding the very intelligibility of
social systems as such hence, its
obvious relevance to the broader concerns of the social and human sciences.
This implication was raised by Saussure himself, in his Course on General
Linguistics6, but it was advanced dramatically by the anthropologist Claude Lévi-Strauss who is generally acknowledged to be the
founder of modern structuralism in his
extensive analyses in the area of social anthropology, beginning with his
Elementary Structures of Kinship 9. Lévi-Strauss argued that society is itself
organized according to one form or another of significant communication and exchange whether this be of information, knowledge, or
myths, or even of its members themselves. The organization of social phenomena
could thus be clarified through a detailed elaboration of their subtending
structures, which, collectively, testify to a deeper and all-inclusive, social
rationality. As with the analysis of language, these social structures would be
disclosed, not by direct observation, but by inference and deduction from the
observed empirical data. Furthermore, since these structures are models of
specific relations, which in turn express the differential properties of the
component elements under investigation, the structural analysis is both readily
formalizable and susceptible to a broad variety of applications. In Britain,
e.g., Edmund Leach pursued these analyses in the domain of social anthropology;
in the United States, Chomsky applied insights of structuralism to linguistic
theory and philosophy of mind; in Italy, Eco conducted extensive structuralist
analyses in the fields of social and literary semiotics. With its
acknowledgment that language is a rule-governed social system of signs, and
that effective communication depends on the resources available to the speaker
from within the codes of language itself, the structuralist approach tends to
be less preoccupied with the more traditional considerations of “subjectivity”
and “history” in its treatment of meaningful discourse. In the
post-structuralism that grew out of this approach, the philosopher Foucault, e.g., focused on the
generation of the “subject” by the various epistemic discourses of imitation
and representation, as well as on the institutional roles of knowledge and
power in producing and conserving particular “disciplines” in the natural and
social sciences. These disciplines, Foucault suggested, in turn govern our
theoretical and practical notions of madness, criminality, punishment,
sexuality, etc., notions that collectively serve to “normalize” the individual
subject to their determinations. Likewise, in the domain of psychoanalysis,
Lacan drew on the work of Saussure and Lévi-Strauss to emphasize Freud’s
concern with language and to argue that, as a set of determining codes,
language serves to structure the subject’s very unconscious. Problematically,
however, it is the very dynamism of language, including metaphor, metonymy,
condensation, displacement, etc., that introduces the social symbolic into the
constitution of the subject. Althusser applied the principles of structuralist
methodology to his analysis of Marxism, especially the role played by
contradiction in understanding infrastructural and superstructural formation,
i.e., for the constitution of the historical dialectic. His account followed
Marx’s rejection of Feuerbach, at once denying the role of traditional subjectivity
and humanism, and presenting a “scientific” analysis of “historical
materialism,” one that would be anti-historicist in principle but attentive to
the actual political state of affairs. For Althusser, such a philosophical
analysis helped provide an “objective” discernment to the historical
transformation of social reality. The restraint the structuralists extended
toward the traditional views of subjectivity and history dramatically colored
their treatment both of the individuals who are agents of meaningful discourse
and of the linguistically articulable object field in general. This redirection
of research interests particularly in France, due to the influential work of
Barthes and Michel Serres in the fields of poetics, cultural semiotics, and
communication theory has resulted in a series of original analyses and also
provoked lively debates between the adherents of structuralist methodology and
the more conventionally oriented schools of thought e.g., phenomenology,
existentialism, Marxism, and empiricist and positivist philosophies of science.
These debates served as an agency to open up subsequent discussions on
deconstruction and postmodernist theory for the philosophical generation of the
0s and later. These post-structuralist thinkers were perhaps less concerned
with the organization of social phenomena than with their initial constitution
and subsequent dynamics. Hence, the problematics of the subject and
history or, in broader terms,
temporality itself were again engaged.
The new discussions were abetted by a more critical appraisal of language and
tended to be antiHegelian in their rejection of the totalizing tendency of
systematic metaphysics. Heidegger’s critique of traditional metaphysics was one
of the major influences in the discussions following structuralism, as was the
reexamination of Nietzsche’s earlier accounts of “genealogy,” his
antiessentialism, and his teaching of a dynamic “will to power.” Additionally,
many poststructuralist philosophers stressed the Freudian notions of the libido
and the unconscious as determining factors in understanding not only the
subject, but the deep rhetorical and affective components of language use. An
astonishing variety of philosophers and critics engaged in the debates
initially framed by the structuralist thinkers of the period, and their
extended responses and critical reappraisals formed the vibrant,
poststructuralist period of intellectual
life. Such figures as Ricoeur, Emmanuel Levinas, Kristeva, Maurice Blanchot,
Derrida, Gilles Deleuze, Félix Guattari, Lyotard, Jean Baudrillard, Philippe
LacoueLabarthe, Jean-Luc Nancy, and Irigaray inaugurated a series of
contemporary reflections that have become international in scope. Refs.: H. P.
Grice, “The structure of structure.”
Suarez, also known as Doctor Eximius, Jesuit philosopher and theologian. Born in
Granada, he studied at Salamanca and taught there and at Rome, Coimbra, and
other leading universities. Suárez’s most important works are De legibus “On
Law,” 1612, De Deo uno et trino “On the Trinity,” 1606, De anima “On the Soul,”
1621, and the monumental Disputationes metaphysicae “Metaphysical
Disputations,” 1597. The Disputationes has a unique place in philosophy, being
the first systematic and comprehensive work of metaphysics written in the West
that is not a commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Divided into fifty-four
disputations, it discusses every metaphysical issue known at the time. Its
influence was immediate and lasting and can be seen in the work of Scholastics
in both Europe and Latin America, and of modern philosophers such as Descartes,
Leibniz, Wolff, and Schopenhauer. Suárez’s main contributions to philosophy
occurred in metaphysics, epistemology, and the philosophy of law. In all three
areas he was influenced by Aristotle and Aquinas, although he also drew
inspiration from Ockham, Duns Scotus, and others. In metaphysics, Suárez is
known for his views on the nature of metaphysics, being, and individuation.
Metaphysics is the science of “being insofar as it is real being” ens in
quantum ens reale, and its proper object of study is the object concept of
being. This understanding of the object of metaphysics is often seen as paving
the way for early modern metaphysical theory, in which the object of
metaphysics is mental. For Suárez the concept of being is derived by analogy
from the similarity existing among things. Existing reality for Suárez is
composed of individuals: everything that exists is individual, including
substances and their properties, accidents, principles, and components. He
understands individuality as incommunicability, namely, the inability of
individuals to be divided into entities of the same specific kind as
themselves. The principle of individuation is “entity,” which he identifies
with “essence as it exists.” This principle applies both to substances and
their properties, accidents, principles, and components. In epistemology, two
of Suárez’s views stand out: that the intellect knows the individual through a
proper and separate concept without structuralism, mathematical Suárez,
Francisco 884 884 having to turn to
reflection, a position that supports an empiricist epistemology in which,
contrary to Thomism, knowledge of the individual is not mediated through universals;
and 2 his view of middle knowledge scientia media, the knowledge God has of
what every free creature would freely do in every possible situation. This
notion was used by Suárez and Molina to explain how God can control human
actions without violating free will. In philosophy of law, Suárez was an
innovative thinker whose ideas influenced Grotius. For him law is fundamentally
an act of the will rather than a result of an ordinance of reason, as Aquinas
held. Law is divided into eternal, divine, natural, and human. Human law is
based on natural or divine law and is not the result of human creation.
Sub-perceptual -- subdoxastic, pertaining to states of
mind postulated to account for the production and character of certain
apparently non-inferential beliefs. These were first discussed by Stephen P.
Stich in “Beliefs and Subdoxastic States” 8. I may form the belief that you are
depressed, e.g., on the basis of subtle cues that I am unable to articulate.
The psychological mechanism responsible for this belief might be thought to
harbor information concerning these cues subdoxastically. Although subdoxastic
states resemble beliefs in certain respects
they incorporate intentional content, they guide behavior, they can
bestow justification on beliefs they
differ from fullyfledged doxastic states or beliefs in at least two respects.
First, as noted above, subdoxastic states may be largely inaccessible to
introspection; I may be unable to describe, even on reflection, the basis of my
belief that you are depressed. Second, subdoxastic states seem cut off
inferentially from an agent’s corpus of beliefs; my subdoxastic appreciation
that your forehead is creased may contribute to my believing that you are
depressed, but, unlike the belief that your forehead is creased, it need not,
in the presence of other beliefs, lead to further beliefs about your visage.
Sub-iectum – sub-iectificatio -- subjectification: Grice
is right in distinguishing this from nominalization, because not all
nominalization takes the subject position. Grice plays with this. It is a
derivation of the ‘subjectum,’ which Grice knows it is Aristotelian. Liddell
and Scott have the verb first, and the neuter singular later. “τὸ ὑποκείμενον,”
Liddell and Scott note “has three main applications.” The first is “to the
matter (hyle) which underlies the form (eidos), as opp. To both “εἶδος” and
“ἐντελέχεια” Met. 983a30; second, to the substantia (hyle + morphe) which
underlies the accidents, and as opposed to “πάθη,” and “συμβεβηκότα,” as in
Cat. 1a20,27 and Met.1037b16, 983b16; third, and this is the use that
‘linguistic’ turn Grice and Strawson are interested in, “to the logical subject
to which attributes are ascribed,” and here opp. “τὸ κατηγορούμενον,” (which
would be the ‘praedicatum’), as per Cat.1b10,21, Ph.189a31. If Grice uses Kiparsky’s
factive, he is also using ‘nominalisation’ as grammarians use it. Refs.: Grice,
“Reply to Richards,” in PGRICE, also BANC.
sub-iectum -- subjectivism: When Grice speaks of the
subjective condition on intention, he is using ‘subject,’ in a way a philosophical
psychologist would. He does not mean Kant’s transcendental subject or ego.
Grice means the simpler empiricist subject, personal identity, or self. The
choice is unfelicitious in that ‘subject’ contrasts with ‘object.’ So when he
speaks of a ‘subjective’ person he means an ‘ego-centric’ condition, or a
self-oriented condition, or an agent-oriented condition, or an
‘utterer-oriented’ or ‘utterer-relative’ condition. But this is tricky. His
example: “Nixon should get that chair of theology.” The utterer may have to put
into Nixon’s shoes. He has to perceive Nixon as a PERSON, a rational agent,
with views of his own. So, the philosophical psychologist that Grice is has to
think of a conception of the self by the self, and the conception of the other
by the self. Wisdom used to talk of ‘other minds;’ Grice might speak of other
souls. Grice was concerned with intending folloed by a that-clause. Jeffrey
defines desirability as doxastically modified. It is entirely possible for
someone to desire the love that he already has. It is what he thinks that
matters. Cf. his dispositional account to intending. A Subjectsive
condition takes into account the intenders, rather than the ascribers, point of
view: Marmaduke Bloggs intends to climb Mt. Everest on hands and knees.
Bloggs might reason: Given my present state, I should do what is
fun. Given my present state, the best thing for me to do would be to do
what is fun. For me in my present state it would make for my well-being,
to have fun. Having fun is good, or, a good. Climbing a mountain would be
fun. Climbing the Everest would be/make for climbing fun. So, I shall
climb the Everest. Even if a critic insisted that a practical syllogism is
the way to represent Bloggs finding something to be appealing, and that it
should be regarded as a respectable evaluation, the assembled propositions dont
do the work of a standard argument. The premises do not support or yield the
conclusion as in a standard argument. The premises may be said to yield the
conclusion, or directive, for the particular agent whose reasoning process it
is, only on the basis of a Subjectsive condition: that the agent is in a
certain Subjectsive state, e.g. feels like going out for dinner-fun. Rational
beings (the agent at some other time, or other individuals) who do not have
that feeling, will not accept the conclusion. They may well accept as true. It
is fun to climb Everest, but will not accept it as a directive unless they feel
like it now. Someone wondering what to do for the summer might think that if he
were to climb Everest he would find it fun or pleasant, but right now she does
not feel like it. That is in general the end of the matter. The alleged
argument lacks normativity. It is not authoritative or directive unless there
is a supportive argument that he needs/ought to do something diverting/pleasant
in the summer. A practical argument is different. Even if an agent did not feel
like going to the doctor, an agent would think I ought to have a medical check
up yearly, now is the time, so I should see my doctor to be a directive with
some force. It articulates a practical argument. Perhaps the strongest
attempt to reconstruct an (acceptable or rational) thought
transition as a standard arguments is to treat the Subjectsive
condition, I feel like having climbing fun in the summer, as a premise, for
then the premises would support the conclusion. But the individual, whose
thought transition we are examining, does not regard a description of his
psychological state as a consideration that supports the conclusion. It
will be useful to look more closely at a variant of the example to note when it
is appropriate to reconstruct thinking in the form of argument. Bloggs,
now hiking with a friend in the Everest, comes to a difficult spot and says:
I dont like the look of that, I am frightened. I am going back. That is
usually enough for Bloggs to return, and for the friend to turn back with him.
Bloggss action of turning back, admittedly motivated by fear, is, while not
acting on reasons, nonetheless rational unless we judge his fear to be
irrational. Bloggss Subjectsive condition can serve as a
premise, but only in a very different situation. Bloggs resorts to reasons.
Suppose that, while his friend does not think Bloggss fear irrational, the
friend still attempts to dissuade Bloggs from going back. After listening and
reflecting, Bloggs may say I am so frightened it is not worth it. I am not
enjoying this climbing anymore. Or I am too frightened to be able to safely go
on. Or I often climb the Everest and dont usually get frightened. The fact that
I am now is a good indication that this is a dangerous trail and I should turn
back. These are reasons, considerations implicitly backed by principles, and
they could be the initial motivations of someone. But in Bloggss case they
emerged when he was challenged by his friend. They do not express his initial
practical reasoning. Bloggs was frightened by the trail ahead, wanted to go
back, and didnt have any reason not to. Note that there is no general
rational requirement to always act on reasons, and no general truth that a
rational individual would be better off the more often he acted on
reasons. Faced with his friends objections, however, Bloggs needed
justification for acting on his fear. He reflected and found reason(s) to act
on his fear. Grice plays with Subjectsivity already in Prolegomena. Consider
the use of carefully. Surely we must include the agents own idea of this. Or
consider the use of phi and phi – surely we dont want the addressee to regard
himself under the same guise with which the utterer regards him. Or consider “Aspects”:
Nixon must be appointed professor of theology at Oxford. Does he feel the need?
Grice raises the topic of Subjectsivity again in the Kant lectures just after
his discussion of mode, in a sub-section entitled, Modalities: relative and
absolute. He finds the topic central for his æqui-vocality thesis: Subjectsive
conditions seem necessary to both practical and alethic considerations. Refs.:
The source is his essay on intentions and the subjective condition, The H. P. Grice
Papers, BANC.
sub-iectum, subject: hypokeimenon -- When Frege turned
from ‘term logic’ to ‘predicate logic’ “he didn’t know what he was doing.” Cf.
Oxonian nominalization. Grice plays a lot on that. His presentation at the
Oxford Philosophical Society he entitled, in a very English way, as “Meaning”
(echoing Ogden and Richards). With his “Meaning, Revisited,” it seems more
clearly that he is nominalizing. Unless he means, “The essay “Meaning,”
revisited,” – alla Putnam making a bad joke on Ogden: “The meaning of
‘meaning’” – “ ‘Meaning,’ revisited” -- Grice is very familiar with this since it’s
the literal transliteration of Aristotle’s hypokeimenon, opp. in a specific
context, to the ‘prae-dicatum,’ or categoroumenon. And with the same sort of
‘ambiguity,’ qua opposite a category of expression, thought, or reality. In
philosophical circles, one has to be especially aware of the subject-object
distinction (which belong in philosophical psychology) and the thing which
belongs in ontology. Of course there’s the substance (hypousia, substantia),
the essence, and the sumbebekon, accidens. So one has to be careful. Grice
expands on Strawson’s explorations here. Philosophy, to underlie, as the
foundation in which something else inheres, to be implied or presupposed by
something else, “ἑκάστῳ τῶν ὀνομάτων . . ὑ. τις ἴδιος οὐσία” Pl.Prt.349b, cf.
Cra.422d, R.581c, Ti.Locr.97e: τὸ ὑποκείμενον has three main applications: (1)
to the matter which underlies the form, opp. εἶδος, ἐντελέχεια,
Arist.Metaph.983a30; (2) to the substance (matter + form) which underlies the
accidents, opp. πάθη, συμβεβηκότα, Id.Cat.1a20,27, Metaph.1037b16, 983b16; (3)
to the logical subject to which attributes are ascribed, opp. τὸ
κατηγορούμενον, Id.Cat.1b10,21, Ph.189a31: applications (1) and (2) are
distinguished in Id.Metaph.1038b5, 1029a1-5, 1042a26-31: τὸ ὑ. is occasionally
used of what underlies or is presupposed in some other way, e. g. of the
positive termini presupposed by change, Id.Ph.225a3-7. b. exist, τὸ ἐκτὸς
ὑποκείμενον the external reality, Stoic.2.48, cf. Epicur.Ep.1pp.12,24 U.; “φῶς
εἶναι τὸ χρῶμα τοῖς ὑ. ἐπιπῖπτον” Aristarch. Sam. ap. Placit.1.15.5; “τὸ κρῖνον
τί τε φαίνεται μόνον καὶ τί σὺν τῷ φαίνεσθαι ἔτι καὶ κατ᾽ ἀλήθειαν ὑπόκειται”
S.E.M.7.143, cf. 83,90,91, 10.240; = ὑπάρχω, τὰ ὑποκείμενα πράγματα the
existing state of affairs, Plb.11.28.2, cf. 11.29.1, 15.8.11,13, 3.31.6,
Eun.VSp.474 B.; “Τίτος ἐξ ὑποκειμένων ἐνίκα, χρώμενος ὁπλις μοῖς καὶ τάξεσιν
αἷς παρέλαβε” Plu.Comp.Phil.Flam.2; “τῆς αὐτῆς δυνάμεως ὑποκειμένης” Id.2.336b;
“ἐχομένου τοῦ προσιόντος λόγου ὡς πρὸς τὸν ὑποκείμενον” A.D.Synt.122.17. c. ὁ
ὑ. ἐνιαυτός the year in question, D.S.11.75; οἱ ὑ. καιροί the time in question,
Id.16.40, Plb.2.63.6, cf. Plu.Comp.Sol.Publ.4; τοῦ ὑ. μηνός the current month,
PTeb.14.14 (ii B. C.), al.; ἐκ τοῦ ὑ. φόρου in return for a reduction from the
said rent, PCair.Zen.649.18 (iii B. C.); πρὸς τὸ ὑ. νόει according to the
context, Gp.6.11.7. Note that both Grice and Strawson oppose Quine’s Humeian
dogma that, since the subjectum is beyond comprehension, we can do with a
‘predicate’ calculus, only. Vide Strawson, “Subject and predicate in logic and
grammar.” Refs: H. P. Grice, Work on the categories with P. F. Strawson, The H.
P. Grice Papers, BANC MSS 90/135c.
sub-ordination. Grice must be the only Oxonian
philosopher in postwar Oxford that realised the relevance of subordination.
Following J. C. Wilson, Grice notes that ‘if’ is a subordinating connective,
and the only one of the connectives which is not commutative. This gives Grice
the idea to consult Cook Wilson and develop his view of ‘interrogative
subordination.’ Who killed Cock Robin. If it was not the Hawk, it was the
Sparrow. It was not the Hawk. It was the Sparrow. What Grecian idiom is
Romanesque sub-ordinatio translating. The opposite is co-ordination. “And” and
“or” are coordinative particles. Interrogative coordination is provided by
‘or,’ but it relates to yes/no questions. Interrogative subordination involves
x-question. WHO killed Cock Robin. The Grecians were syntactic and hypotactic.
Varro uses jungendi. is the same and wherefrom it is different, in relation to
what &c." It may well be doubted whether he has thus improved upon his
predecessors. Surely the discernment of sameness and difference is a function
necessarily belonging to soul and necessarily included in the catalogue of her
functions : yet Stallbaum's rendering excludes it from that catalogue. The fact
that we have ory hv $, not orcp ecri, does not really favour his view—"
with whatsoever a thing may be the same, she declares it the same.' I coincide
then with the other interpreters in regarding the whole sentence from orw t' hv
as indirect INTERROGATION SUBORDINATE interrogation subordinateto \iyeiThis
mistake in logic carries with it serious mistakes in trans lation. The clause
otw t av ti tovtov rj kcu otov hv erepov is made an indirect INTERROGATIVE
COORDINATE with itpbs o tC re pu£Aio-ra xai ottt? [ 39 ] k.t.\., which is
impossible. Stallbaum rightly makes the clause a substantive clause and subject
of elvai or £vp.f}aivei elvai. (3) eKao-ra is of course predicate with elvai to
this sthe question, ‘How many sugars would Tom like in his tea?’ is not
‘satisfied’ by the answer ‘Tom loves sugar’. It may well be true that Tom loves
sugar, but the question is not satisfied by that form of answer. Conversely the
answer ‘one spoonful’ satisfies the question, even though it might be the wrong
answer and leave the tea insufficiently sugary for the satisfaction of Tom’s
sweet tooth.
sub-perceptum: This relates to Stich and his sub-doxastic. For
Aristotle, “De An.,” the anima leads to the desideratum. Unlike in ‘phuta,’ or
vegetables, which are still ‘alive,’ (‘zoa’ – he had a problem with ‘sponges’
which were IN-animate, to him, most likely) In WoW:139, Grice refers to “the
pillar box seems red” as “SUB-PERCEPTUAL,” the first of a trio. The second is
the perceptual, “A perceives that the pillar box is red,” and the third, “The
pillar box is red.” He wishes to explore the truth-conditons of the
subperceptum, and although first in the list, is last in the analsysis. Grice
proposes: ‘The pillar box seems red” iff (1) the pillar box is red; (2) A
perceives that the pillar box is red; and (3) (1) causes (2). In this there is
a parallelism with his quasi-causal account of ‘know’ (and his caveat that
‘literally,’ we may just know that 2 + 2 = 4 (and such) (“Meaning Revisited). In
what he calls ‘accented sub-perceptum,’ the idea is that the U is choosing the
superceptum (“seems”) as opposed to his other obvious choices (“The pillar box
IS red,”) and the passive-voice version of the ‘perceptum’: “The pillar box IS
PERCEIVED red.” The ‘accent’ generates the D-or-D implicaturum: By uttering
“The pillar box seems red,” U IMPLICATES that it is denied that or doubted that
the pillar box is perceived red by U or that the pillar box is red. In this,
the accented version contrasts with the unaccented version where the implicaturum
is NOT generated, and the U remains uncommitted re: this doubt or denial implicaturum.
It is this uncommitment that will allow to disimplicate or cancel the implicaturum
should occasion arise. The reference Grice makes between the sub-perceptum and
the perceptum is grammatical, not psychological. Or else he may be meaning that
in uttering, “I perceive that the pillar box is red,” one needs to appeal to
Kant’s apperception of the ego. Refs.: Pecocke, Sense and content, Grice, BANC.
subscriptum: Quine thought that Grice’s subscript device was
otiose, and that he would rather use brackets, or nothing, any day. Grice plays with various roots of ‘scriptum.’
He was bound to. Moore had showed that ‘good’ was not ‘descriptive.’ Grice
thinks it’s pseudo-descriptive. So here we have the first, ‘descriptum,’ where
what is meant is Griceian: By uttering the “The cat is on the mat” U means, by
his act of describing, that the cat is on the mat. Then there’s the
‘prae-scriptum.’ Oddly, Grice, when criticizing the ‘descriptive’ fallacy,
seldom mentions the co-relative ‘prescriptum.’ “Good” would be understood in
terms of a ‘prae-scriptum’ that appeals to his utterer’s intentions. Then
there’s the subscriptum. This may have various use, both in Grice. “I
subscribe,” and in the case of “Pegasus flies.” Where the utterer subscribes to
his ontological commitment. subscript device. Why does Grice think we NEED a
subscript device? Obviously, his wife would not use it. I mean, you cannot
pronounce a subscript device or a square-bracket device. So his point is
ironic. “Ordinary” language does not need it. But if Strawson and Quine are
going to be picky about stuff – ontological commitment, ‘existential
presupposition,’ let’s subscribe and bracket! Note that Quine’s response to
Grice is perfunctory: “Brackets would have done!” Grice considers a quartet of
utterances: Jack wants someone to marry him; Jack wants someone or
other to marry him; Jack wants a particular person to marry him,
and There is someone whom Jack wants to marry him.Grice notes that
there are clearly at least two possible readings of an utterance
like our (i): a first reading in which, as Grice puts it, (i) might be
paraphrased by (ii). A second reading is one in which it might be
paraphrased by (iii) or by (iv). Grice goes on to symbolize the
phenomenon in his own version of a first-order predicate calculus. Ja wants
that p becomes Wjap where ja stands for the individual constant Jack
as a super-script attached to the predicate standing for Jacks psychological
state or attitude. Grice writes: Using the apparatus of classical predicate logic,
we might hope to represent, respectively, the external reading and the internal
reading (involving an intentio secunda or intentio obliqua)
as (Ǝx)WjaFxja and Wja(Ǝx)Fxja. Grice then goes on
to discuss a slightly more complex, or oblique, scenario involving this second
internal reading, which is the one that interests us, as it involves an
intentio seconda.Grice notes: But suppose that Jack wants a specific
individual, Jill, to marry him, and this because Jack has been deceived
into thinking that his friend Joe has a highly delectable sister called Jill,
though in fact Joe is an only child. The Jill Jack eventually goes up the hill
with is, coincidentally, another Jill, possibly existent. Let us
recall that Grices main focus of the whole essay is, as the title goes,
emptiness! In these circumstances, one is inclined to say that (i)
is true only on reading (vii), where the existential quantifier
occurs within the scope of the psychological-state or -attitude verb,
but we cannot now represent (ii) or (iii), with Jill being vacuous,
by (vi), where the existential quantifier (Ǝx) occurs outside the
scope of the psychological-attitude verb, want, since [well,] Jill does
not really exist, except as a figment of Jacks imagination. In a manoeuver that
I interpret as purely intentionalist, and thus favouring by far Suppess over
Chomskys characterisation of Grice as a mere behaviourist, Grice hopes that
we should be provided with distinct representations
for two familiar readings of, now: Jack wants Jill to marry him and
Jack wants Jill to marry him. It is at this point that Grice applies a
syntactic scope notation involving sub-scripted numerals, (ix) and (x),
where the numeric values merely indicate the order of introduction of the
symbol to which it is attached in a deductive schema for the predicate calculus
in question. Only the first formulation represents the internal reading (where
ji stands for Jill): W2ja4F1ji3ja4 and
W3ja4F2ji1ja4. Note
that in the second formulation, the individual constant for Jill, ji, is
introduced prior to want, – jis sub-script is 1, while Ws sub-script is the
higher numerical value 3. Grice notes: Given that Jill does not exist, only the
internal reading can be true, or alethically satisfactory. Grice sums up
his reflections on the representation of the opaqueness of a verb standing for
a psychological state or attitude like that expressed by wanting with one
observation that further marks him as an intentionalist, almost of a Meinongian
type. He is willing to allow for existential phrases in cases of vacuous
designata, provided they occur within opaque psychological-state or attitude
verbs, and he thinks that by doing this, he is being faithful to the richness
and exuberance of ordinary discourse, while keeping Quine happy. As Grice
puts it, we should also have available to us also three neutral, yet distinct,
(Ǝx)-quantificational forms (together with their isomorphs), as a philosopher
who thinks that Wittgenstein denies a distinction, craves for a generality!
Jill now becomes x. W4ja5Ǝx3F1x2ja5, Ǝx5W2ja5F1x4ja3, Ǝx5W3ja4F1x2ja4. As Grice
notes, since in (xii) the individual variable x (ranging over Jill) does not
dominate the segment following the (Ǝx) quantifier, the formulation does not
display any existential or de re, force, and is suitable therefore for
representing the internal readings (ii) or (iii), if we have to allow, as we do
have, if we want to faithfully represent ordinary discourse, for the
possibility of expressing the fact that a particular person, Jill, does not
actually exist.
more grice to
the mill: sous-entendu: used by, of
all people, Mill. An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's
Philosophybooks.google.com › books ... and speak with any approach to
precision, and adopting into [the necessary sufficient clauses of a piece of
philosophical conceptual analysis] a mere sous-entendu of common conversation
in its most unprecise form. If I say to any one, Cf. understatement, as opposed
to overstatement. The ‘statement’ thing complicates things,
‘underunderstanding’ seems better, or ‘sub-understanding,’ strictly. Trust
Grice to bring more Grice to the Mill and provide a full essay, indeed theory,
and base his own philosophy, on the sous-tentendu! Cf. Pears, Pears
Cyclopaedia. “The English love meiosis, litotes, and understatement. The French
don’t.” Note all the figures of rhetoric cited by Grice, and why they have
philosophical import. Many entries here: hyperbole, meiosis, litotes, etc. Grice
took ‘sous-entendu’ etymologically serious. It is UNDERSTOOD. Nobody taught
you, but it understood. It is understood is like It is known. So “The pillar
box seems red” is understood to mean, “It may not be.” Now a sous-entendu may
be cancellable, in which case it was MIS-understood, or the emissor has changed
his mind. Grice considers the paradoxes the understanding under ‘uptake,’ just to
make fun of Austin’s informalism. The ‘endendu’ is what the French understand
by ‘understand,’ the root being Latin intellectus, or intendo.
stoicus --- stoicism -- Neo-stoicism -- du Vair,
Guillaume, philosopher, bishop, and political figure. Du Vair and Justus
Lipsius were the two most influential propagators of neo-Stoicism in early
modern Europe. Du Vair’s Sainte Philosophie “Holy Philosophy,” 1584 and his
shorter Philosophie morale des Stoïques “Moral Philosophy of the Stoics,” 1585,
were tr. and frequently reprinted. The latter presents Epictetus in a form
usable by ordinary people in troubled times. We are to follow nature and live
according to reason; we are not to be upset by what we cannot control; virtue
is the good. Du Vair inserts, moreover, a distinctly religious note. We must be
pious, accept our lot as God’s will, and consider morality obedience to his
command. Du Vair thus Christianized Stoicism, making it widely acceptable. By
teaching that reason alone enables us to know how we ought to live, he became a
founder of modern rationalism in ethics. Stōĭcus , a,
um, adj., = Στωϊκός, I.of or belonging to the Stoic philosophy or to the
Stoics, Stoic: “schola,” Cic. Fam. 9, 22 fin.: “secta,” Sen. Ep. 123, 14:
“sententia,” id. ib. 22, 7: “libelli,” Hor. Epod. 8, 15: “turba,” Mart. 7, 69,
4: “dogmata,” Juv. 13, 121: “disciplina,” Gell. 19, 1, 1: “Stoicum est,” it is
a saying of the Stoics, Cic. Ac. 2, 26, 85: “non loquor tecum Stoicā linguā,
sed hac submissiore,” Sen. Ep. 13, 4: “est aliquid in illo Stoici dei: nec cor
nec caput habet,” Sen. Apoc. 8.— Subst.: Stōĭcus , i, m., a Stoic philosopher,
a Stoic, Cic. Par. praef. § 2; Hor. S. 2, 3, 160; 2, 3, 300; plur., Cic. Mur.
29, 61; and in philosophical writings saepissime.— 2. Stōĭca , ōrum, n. plur.,
the Stoic philosophy, Cic. N. D. 1, 6, 15.—Adv.: Stōĭcē , like a Stoic,
Stoically: “agere austere et Stoice,” Cic. Mur. 35, 74: dicere, id. Par. praef.
§ 3.H. P. Grice, “The Stoa: from Athenian to Oxonian dialectic,” H. P.
Grice, “The Stoa and Athenian dialectic.”
stupid. Grice loved Plato. They are considering
‘horseness.’ “I cannot see horeseness; I can see horses.” “You are the epitome
of stupidity.” “I cannot see stupidity. I see stupid.”
No comments:
Post a Comment