tempus: cited by Grice and Myro in the Grice-Myro theory of
identity. tense logic, an extension of classical logic introduced by Arthur
Prior Past, Present, and Future, 7, involving operators P and F for the past
and future tenses, or ‘it was the case that . . .’ and ‘it will be the case
that . . .’. Classical or mathematical logic was developed as a logic of
unchanging mathematical truth, and can be applied to tensed discourse only by
artificial regimentation inspired by mathematical physics, introducing
quantification over “times” or “instants.” Thus ‘It will have been the case
that p,’ which Prior represents simply as FPp, classical logic represents as
‘There [exists] an instant t and there [exists] an instant tH such that t [is]
later than the present and tH [is] earlier than t, and at tH it [is] the case
that pH, or DtDtH t o‹t8tH ‹t8ptH, where the brackets indicate that the verbs
are to be understood as tenseless. Prior’s motives were in part linguistic to
produce a formalization less removed from natural language than the classical
and in part metaphysical to avoid ontological commitment to such entities as
instants. Much effort was devoted to finding tense-logical principles
equivalent to various classical assertions about the structure of the
earlierlater order among instants; e.g., ‘Between any two instants there is
another instant’ corresponds to the validity of the axioms Pp P PPp and Fp P
FFp. Less is expressible using P and F than is expressible with explicit
quantification over instants, and further operators for ‘since’ and ‘until’ or
‘now’ and ‘then’ have been introduced by Hans Kamp and others. These are
especially important in combination with quantification, as in ‘When he was in
power, all who now condemn him then praised him.’ As tense is closely related
to mood, so tense logic is closely related to modal logic. As Kripke models for
modal logic consist each of a set X of “worlds” and a relation R of ‘x is an
alternative to y’, so for tense logic they consist each of a set X of
“instants” and a relation R of ‘x is earlier than y’: Thus instants, banished
from the syntax or proof theory, reappear in the semantics or model theory.
Modality and tense are both involved in the issue of future contingents, and
one of Prior’s motives was a desire to produce a formalism in which the views
on this topic of ancient, medieval, and early modern logicians from Aristotle
with his “sea fight tomorrow” and Diodorus Cronos with his “Master Argument”
through Ockham to Peirce could be represented. The most important precursor to
Prior’s work on tense logic was that on many-valued logics by Lukasiewicz,
which was motivated largely by the problem of future contingents. Also related
to tense and mood is aspect, and modifications to represent this grammatical
category evaluating formulas at periods rather than instants of time have also
been introduced. Like modal logic, tense logic has been the object of intensive
study in theoretical computer science, especially in connection with attempts to
develop languages in which properties of programs can be expressed and proved;
variants of tense logic under such labels as “dynamic logic” or “process logic”
have thus been extensively developed for technological rather than
philosophical motives. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “D. H. Mellor on real and irreal
time.”
terminus – horos – Cicero’s transliteration of the Greianism
--. terminist logic, a school of semantics until its demise in the humanistic
reforms. The chief goal of ‘terminisim’ – or terministic semantics -- is the
elucidation (or conceptual analysis) of the
form, the “exposition,” of a proposition advanced in the context of
Scholastic disputation. The cntral theory of terminisitc semantics concerns
this or that property of this or that term, especially the suppositum.
Terminisic semantics does the work of modern quantification theory. Important
semanticists in the school include Peter of Spain, Sherwood, Burleigh
(Burlaeus), Heytesbury, and Paolo Veneto.
the terminus
a quo-terminus a quem distinction:
used by Grice for the starting point of some process, as opposed to the
terminus ad quem, the ending point. E. g., change is a process that begins from
some state, the terminus a quo, and proceeds to some state at which it ends,
the terminus ad quem. In particular, in the ripening of an apple, the green
apple is the terminus a quo and the red apple is the terminus ad quem.
tertullian Roman – Grice says that ‘you’re the cream in my
coffee’ is absurd – “Can you believe it?” -- Adored by Grice because he believed
what he thought was absurd. theologian,
an early father of the Christian church. A layman from Carthage, he laid the
conceptual and linguistic basis for the doctrine of the Trinity. Though
appearing hostile to philosophy “What has Athens to do with Jerusalem?” and to
rationality “It is certain because it is impossible”, Tertullian was steeped in
Stoicism. He denounced all eclecticism not governed by the normative tradition
of Christian doctrine, yet commonly used philosophical argument and Stoic concepts
e.g., the corporeality of God and the soul. Despite insisting on the sole
authority of the New Testament apostles, he joined with Montanism, which taught
that the Holy Spirit was still inspiring prophecy concerning moral discipline.
Reflecting this interest in the Spirit, Tertullian pondered the distinctions to
which he gave the neologism trinitas within God. God is one “substance” but
three “persons”: a plurality without division. The Father, Son, and Spirit are
distinct, but share equally in the one Godhead. This threeness is manifest only
in the “economy” of God’s temporal action toward the world; later orthodoxy
e.g. Athanasius, Basil the Great, Augustine, would postulate a Triunity that is
eternal and “immanent,” i.e., internal to God’s being.
testing: Grice: “A token proving testability.” Grice: “We need
a meta-test: a test for a test for implicatura.” late
14c., "small vessel used in assaying precious metals," from Old
French test, from Latin testum "earthen pot," related to testa
"piece of burned clay, earthen pot, shell" (see tete). Sense of
"trial or examination to determine the correctness of something" is
recorded from 1590s. The connecting notion is "ascertaining the quality of
a metal by melting it in a pot." Test Act was the name given to various
laws in English history meant to exclude Catholics and Nonconformists from
office, especially that of 1673, repealed 1828. Test drive (v.) is first
recorded 1954. In the sciences, capacity of a theory to undergo
experimental testing. Theories in the natural sciences are regularly subjected
to experimental tests involving detailed and rigorous control of variable
factors. Not naive observation of the workings of nature, but disciplined,
designed intervention in such workings, is the hallmark of testability.
Logically regarded, testing takes the form of seeking confirmation of theories
by obtaining positive test results. We can represent a theory as a conjunction
of a hypothesis and a statement of initial conditions, H • A. This conjunction
deductively entails testable or observational consequences O. Hence, H • A P O.
If O obtains, H • A is said to be confirmed, or rendered probable. But such
confirmation is not decisive; O may be entailed by, and hence explained by,
many other theories. For this reason, Popper insisted that the testability of
theories should seek disconfirmations or falsifications. The logical schema H •
A P O not-O not-H • A is deductively valid, hence apparently decisive. On this
view, science progresses, not by finding the truth, but by discarding the
false. Testability becomes falsifiability. This deductive schema modus tollens
is also employed in the analysis of crucial tests. Consider two hypotheses H1
and H2, both introduced to explain some phenomenon. H1 predicts that for some
test condition C, we have the test result ‘if C then e1’, and H2, the result
‘if C then e2’, where e1 and e2 are logically incompatible. If experiment
falsifies ‘if C then e1’ e1 does not actually occur as a test result, the
hypothesis H1 is false, which implies that H2 is true. It was originally
supposed that the experiments of J. B. L. Foucault constituted a decisive
falsifcation of the corpuscular theory of the nature of light, and thus
provided a decisive establishment of the truth of its rival, the wave theory of
light. This account of crucial experiments neglects certain points in logic and
also the role of auxiliary hypotheses in science. As Duhem pointed term, minor
testability 908 908 out, rarely, if
ever, does a hypothesis face the facts in isolation from other supporting
assumptions. Furthermore, it is a fact of logic that the falsification of a
conjunction of a hypothesis and its auxiliary assumptions and initial
conditions not-H • A is logically equivalent to not-H or not-A, and the test result
itself provides no warrant for choosing which alternative to reject. Duhem
further suggested that rejection of any component part of a complex theory is
based on extra-evidential considerations factors like simplicity and
fruitfulness and cannot be forced by negative test results. Acceptance of
Duhem’s view led Quine to suggest that a theory must face the tribunal of
experience en bloc; no single hypothesis can be tested in isolation. Original
conceptions of testability and falsifiability construed scientific method as
hypothetico-deductive. Difficulties with these reconstructions of the logic of
experiment have led philosophers of science to favor an explication of
empirical support based on the logic of probability. Grice: “Linguists never
take ‘testability’ too conceptually, as one can witness in Saddock’s hasty
proofs!” – Refs: H. P. Grice, “On testing for testing for conversational
implicatura.”
testis
(n.). (plural testes), Latin
testis "testicle," usually regarded as a special application of
testis "witness" (see testament), presumably because it "bears
witness to male virility" [Barnhart]. Stories that trace the use of the
Latin word to some supposed swearing-in ceremony are modern and
groundless. Compare Greek parastatai "testicles," from parastates
"one that stands by;" and French slang témoins, literally
"witnesses." But Buck thinks Greek parastatai "testicles"
has been wrongly associated with the legal sense of parastates "supporter,
defender" and suggests instead parastatai in the sense of twin
"supporting pillars, props of a mast," etc. Or it might be a
euphemistic use of the word in the sense "comrades." OED, meanwhile,
points to Walde's suggestion of a connection between testis and testa
"pot, shell, etc." (see tete). testis "witness," from PIE *tri-st-i- "third
person standing by," from root *tris- "three" (see three) on the
notion of "third person, disinterested witness." -- as Grice
notes, “it is etymologically -- or
etymythologically -- related to ‘testicles,’” -- Grice proposes an analysis of ‘testify’ in
terms of necessary and sufficient conditions, “t is a testimony iff t is an act
of telling, including any assertion apparently intended to impart information,
regardless of social setting.” In an extended use, personal letters and messages,
books, and other published material purporting to contain factual information
also constitute testimony. As Grice notes, “testimony may be sincere or
insincere” -- and may express knowledge or baseless prejudice. When it
expresses knowledge, and it is rightly believed, this knowledge is disseminated
to its recipient, near or remote. Second-hand knowledge can be passed on
further, producing long chains of testimony; but these chains always begin with
the report of an eye-witness or expert. In any social group with a common
language there is potential for the sharing, through testimony, of the fruits
of individuals’ idiosyncratic acquisition of knowledge through perception and
inference. In advanced societies specialization in the gathering and production
of knowledge and its wider dissemination through spoken and written testimony
is a fundamental socio-epistemic fact, and a very large part of each person’s
body of knowledge and belief stems from testimony. Thus, the question when a
person may properly believe what another tells her, and what grounds her
epistemic entitlement to do so, is a crucial one in epistemology. Reductionists
about testimony insist that this entitlement must derive from our entitlement
to believe what we perceive to be so, and to draw inferences from this
according to familiar general principles. See e.g., Hume’s classic discussion,
in his “Enquiry into Human Understanding,” section X. On this view, I can
perceive that someone has told me that p, but can thereby come to know that p only
by means of an inference one that goes
via additional, empirically grounded knowledge of the trustworthiness of that
person. Anti-reductionists insist, by contrast, that there is a general
entitlement to believe what one is told just as such defeated by knowledge of
one’s informant’s lack of trustworthiness her mendacity or incompetence, but
not needing to be bolstered positively by empirically based knowledge of her
trustworthiness. Anti-reductionists thus see testimony as an autonomous source
of knowledge on a par with perception, inference, and memory. One argument
adduced for anti-reductionism is transcendental: We have many beliefs acquired
from testimony, and these beliefs are knowledge; their status as knowledge
cannot be accounted for in the way required by the reductionist, i. e., the
reliability of testimony cannot be independently confirmed; therefore, the
reductionist’s insistence on this is mistaken. However, while it is perhaps
true that the reliability of all the beliefs one has that depend on past
testimony cannot be simultaneously confirmed, one can certainly sometimes
ascertain, without circularity, that a specific assertion by a particular
person is likely to be correct if,
e.g.,one’s own experience has established that that person has a good track
record of reliability about that kind of thing. Grice: “Sometimes I use
testimonium.” Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Trust and rationality.”
tetens: philosopher, referred to by Grice as “Dutch Locke.” After
his studies in Rostock and Copenhagen, Tetens teaches at Bützow and Kiel. He
had a second successful career as a public servant in Denmark that did not leave him time for philosophical
explorations. Tetens is one of the most important mainland philosophers between
Wolff and Kant. Like Kant, whom he significantly influenced, Tetens attempts to
find a middle way between Descartes’s rationalism and Locke’s empiricism.
Tetens’s most important work, the “Philosophische Versuche über die menschliche
Natur und ihre Entwicklung,” is indicative of the state of philosophical
discussion before Kant’s Critique of Pure
Reason. Tetens, who follows the “psychological method” of Locke, tends toward a
naturalism. Tetens makes a more radical distinction between sensation and
reason than Hume allows and attempts to show how this or that basic rational
principle – a prequel to Grice’s principle of conversational cooperation --
guarantee the objectivity of human knowledge.
thales: called by
Grice the first Grecian philosopher (“Oddly, we call him a Ionian, but the Ionian
is quite a way from where he was born!”) – who poisted a ‘philosophical’
why-explanation. Grecian philosopher who
was regarded as one of the Seven Sages of Greece. He was also considered the
first philosopher, founder of the Milesians. Thales is also reputed to have
been an engineer, astronomer, mathematician, and statesman. His doctrines even
early Grecian sources know only by hearsay: he said that water is the arche,
and that the earth floats on water like a raft. The magnet has a soul, and all
things are full of the gods. Thales’ attempt to explain natural phenomena in
natural rather than exclusively supernatural terms bore fruit in his follower
Anaximander.
thema: a term Grice borrows from Stoic logic, after
attending a seminar on the topic by Benson Mates – a ‘thema’ is a ground rule
used to reduce argument forms to basic forms. The Stoics analyzed arguments by
their form schema, or tropos. They represented forms using numbers to represent
claims; for example, ‘if the first, the second; but the first; therefore the
second’. Grice uses “so-and-so” for ‘the first’ and ‘such and such’ for the
‘second’. “If so and so, such and such, but so and so; therefore, such and
such.” Some forms were undemonstrable; others were reduced to the
undemonstrable argument forms by ground rules themata; e.g., if R follows from
P & Q, -Q follows from P & -R. The five undemonstrable arguments are: 1
modus ponendo ponens; 2 modus tollendo tollens; 3 not both P and Q, P, so
not-Q; 4 P or Q but not both, P, so not-Q; and 5 disjunctive syllogism. The
evidence about the four ground rules is incomplete, but a sound and consistent
system for propositional logic can be developed that is consistent with the
evidence we have. See Diogenes Laertius, Lives of the Philosophers, for an
introduction to the Stoic theory of arguments; other evidence is more
scattered.
θ: Grice’s symbol for a theory. Grice uses small-case
theta for a token of a theory, and capital theta for a type of theory.– Grice
couldn’t quite stand some type of attitude he found in people like J. M.
Rountree – Rountree was claiming that one needs a ‘theory’ of meaning. Grice
responded: “ Rountree is wrong: if meaning is a matter of theory, it cannot be
a matter of intuition; and I’m sure it should be a matter of intuition for
Rountree!” theoretical term – Grice was once attracted to Ramsey’s essay on “Theories,”
but later came to see it as ‘pretentious’. “Surely the way *I* use ‘theory’ is
not Ramsey’s!” – If something is an object of an intuition by Grice, it cannot
be a theoretical term – theory and intuition don’t go together. They repel each
other! a term occurring in a scientific theory that purports to make reference
to an unobservable entity e.g., ‘electron’, property e.g., ‘the monatomicity of
a molecule’, or relation ‘greater electrical resistance’. The qualification
‘purports to’ is required because instrumentalists deny that any such
unobservables exist; nevertheless, they acknowledge that a scientific theory,
such as the atomic theory of matter, may be a useful tool for organizing our
knowledge of observables and predicting future experiences. Scientific
realists, in contrast, maintain that at least some of the theoretical terms
e.g., ‘quark’ or ‘neutrino’ actually denote entities that are not directly
observable they hold, i.e., that such
things exist. For either group, theoretical terms are contrasted with such
observational terms as ‘rope’, ‘smooth’, and ‘louder than’, which refer to
observable entities, properties, or relations. Much philosophical controversy
has centered on how to draw the distinction between the observable and the unobservable.
Did Galileo observe the moons of Jupiter with his telescope? Do we observe
bacteria under a microscope? Do physicists observe electrons in bubble
chambers? Do astronomers observe the supernova explosions with neutrino
counters? Do we observe ordinary material objects, or are sense-data the only
observables? Are there any observational terms at all, or are all terms
theory-laden? Another important meaning of ‘theoretical term’ occurs if one
regards a scientific theory as a semiformal axiomatic system. It is then
natural to think of its vocabulary as divided into three parts, i terms of
logic and mathematics, ii terms drawn from ordinary language or from other
theories, and iii theoretical terms that constitute the special vocabulary of
that particular theory. Thermodynamics, e.g., employs i terms for numbers and
mathematical operations, ii such terms as ‘pressure’ and ‘volume’ that are
common to many branches of physics, and iii such special thermodynamical terms
as ‘temperature’, ‘heat’, and ‘entropy’. In this second sense, a theoretical
term need not even purport to refer to unobservables. For example, although
special equipment is necessary for its precise quantitatheoretical entity
theoretical term 912 912 tive
measurement, temperature is an observable property. Even if theories are not
regarded as axiomatic systems, their technical terms can be considered
theoretical. Such terms need not purport to refer to unobservables, nor be the
exclusive property of one particular theory. In some cases, e.g., ‘work’ in
physics, an ordinary word is used in the theory with a meaning that departs
significantly from its ordinary use. Serious questions have been raised about
the meaning of theoretical terms. Some philosophers have insisted that, to be
meaningful, they must be given operational definitions. Others have appealed to
coordinative definitions to secure at least partial interpretation of axiomatic
theories. The verifiability criterion has been invoked to secure the
meaningfulness of scientific theories containing such terms. A theoretical
concept or construct is a concept expressed by a theoretical term in any of the
foregoing senses. The term ‘theoretical entity’ has often been used to refer to
unobservables, but this usage is confusing, in part because, without
introducing any special vocabulary, we can talk about objects too small to be
perceived directly e.g., spheres of
gamboge a yellow resin less than 106 meters in diameter, which figured in a
historically important experiment by Jean Perrin. Grice uses Ramsey’s concept of ‘theory’ –
“granting that Ramsey overrated theory, as all Cambridge men do!” -- theory-laden,
dependent on theory; specifically, involving a theoretical interpretation of
what is perceived or recorded. In the heyday of logical empiricism it was
thought, by Carnap and others, that a rigid distinction could be drawn between
observational and theoretical terms. Later, N. R. Hanson, Paul Feyerabend, and
others questioned this distinction, arguing that perhaps all observations are
theory-laden either because our perception of the world is colored by
perceptual, linguistic, and cultural differences or because no attempt to
distinguish sharply between observation and theory has been successful. This
shift brings a host of philosophical problems. If we accept the idea of radical
theoryladenness, relativism of theory choice becomes possible, for, given rival
theories each of which conditions its own observational evidence, the choice
between them would seem to have to be made on extra-evidential grounds, since
no theory-neutral observations are available. In its most perplexing form,
relativism holds that, theory-ladenness being granted, one theory is as good as
any other, so far as the relationship of theory to evidence is concerned.
Relativists couple the thesis of theory-ladenness with the alleged fact of the
underdetermination of a theory by its observational evidence, which yields the
idea that any number of alternative theories can be supported by the same
evidence. The question becomes one of what it is that constrains choices
between theories. If theory-laden observations cannot constrain such choices,
the individual subjective preferences of scientists, or rules of fraternal
behavior agreed upon by groups of scientists, become the operative constraints.
The logic of confirmation seems to be intrinsically contaminated by both
idiosyncratic and social factors, posing a threat to the very idea of
scientific rationality.
signum – Grice: “I prefer token, so Anglo-Saxon! Plus
I’m a ‘teacher’ – “to teach philosophy” --” whose explorations on the
Nicomachean Ethics, in one of their earlier incarnations, as a set of lecture
notes, sees me through terms of teaching Aristotle's moral theory.” “My own
philosophical life in this period involves two especially important aspects.” ROBBING
PETER TO PAY PAUL.. “The first is my prolonged collaboration with my tutee at St.
John’s, P. F. Strawson.”“Strawson’s and my efforts are partly directed towards the
giving of joint seminars.”“Strawson and I stage a number of joint seminars on
topics related to the notions of meaning, categories, and logical form.” “But
my association with P. F. Strawson is much more than an alliance for the
purpose of teaching.” -- theory of signs, the philosophical and scientific theory
of information-carrying entities, communication, and information transmission.
The term ‘semiotic’ was introduced by Locke for the science of signs and
signification. The term became more widely used as a result of the influential
work of Peirce and Charles Morris. With regard to linguistic signs, three areas
of semiotic were distinguished: pragmatics
the study of the way people, animals, or machines such as computers use
signs; semantics the study of the
relations between signs and their meanings, abstracting from their use; and
syntax the study of the relations among
signs themselves, abstracting both from use and from meaning. In Europe, the
near-equivalent term ‘semiology’ was introduced by Ferdinand de Saussure, the
Swiss linguist. Broadly, a sign is any information-carrying entity, including
linguistic and animal signaling tokens, maps, road signs, diagrams, pictures,
models, etc. Examples include smoke as a sign of fire, and a red light at a
highway intersection as a sign to stop. Linguistically, vocal aspects of speech
such as prosodic features intonation, stress and paralinguistic features
loudness and tone, gestures, facial expressions, etc., as well as words and
sentences, are signs in the most general sense. Peirce defined a sign as
“something that stands for something in some respect or capacity.” Among signs,
he distinguished symbols, icons, and indices. A symbol, or conventional sign,
is a sign, typical of natural language forms, that lacks any significant
relevant physical correspondence with or resemblance to the entities to which
the form refers manifested by the fact that quite different forms may refer to
the same class of objects, and for which there is no correlation between the
occurrence of the sign and its referent. An index, or natural sign, is a sign
whose occurrence is causally or statistically correlated with occurrences of
its referent, and whose production is not intentional. Thus, yawning is a
natural sign of sleepiness; a bird call may be a natural sign of alarm.
Linguistically, loudness with a rising pitch is a sign of anger. An icon is a
sign whose form corresponds to or resembles its referent or a characteristic of
its referent. For instance, a tailor’s swatch is an icon by being a sign that
resembles a fabric in color, pattern, and texture. A linguistic example is
onomatopoeia as with ‘buzz’. In general,
there are conventional and cultural aspects to a sign being an icon.
theosophy, any philosophical mysticism, especially
those that purport to be mathematically or scientifically based, such as
Pythagoreanism, Neoplatonism, or gnosticism. Vedic Hinduism, and certain
aspects of Buddhism, Taoism, and Islamic Sufism, can also be considered
theosophical. In narrower senses, ‘theosophy’ may refer to the philosophy of
Swedenborg, Steiner, or Madame Helena Petrovna Blavatsky 183. Swedenborg’s
theosophy originally consisted of a rationalistic cosmology, inspired by
certain elements of Cartesian and Leibnizian philosophy, and a Christian
mysticism. Swedenborg labored to explain the interconnections between soul and
body. Steiner’s theosophy is a reaction to standard scientific theory. It
purports to be as rigorous as ordinary science, but superior to it by
incorporating spiritual truths about reality. According to his theosophy, reality
is organic and evolving by its own resource. Genuine knowledge is intuitive,
not discursive. Madame Blavatsky founded the Theosophical Society in 1875. Her
views were eclectic, but were strongly influenced by mystical elements of philosophy.
thomism, the theology and philosophy of Thomas Aquinas.
The term is applied broadly to various thinkers from different periods who were
heavily influenced by Aquinas’s thought in their own philosophizing and
theologizing. Here three different eras and three different groups of thinkers
will be distinguished: those who supported Aquinas’s thought in the fifty years
or so following his death in 1274; certain highly skilled interpreters and
commentators who flourished during the period of “Second Thomism” sixteenthseventeenth
centuries; and various late nineteenth- and twentieth-century thinkers who have
been deeply influenced in their own work by Aquinas. Thirteenth- and
fourteenth-century Thomism. Although Aquinas’s genius was recognized by many
during his own lifetime, a number of his views were immediately contested by
other Scholastic thinkers. Controversies ranged, e.g., over his defense of only
one substantial form in human beings; his claim that prime matter is purely
potential and cannot, therefore, be kept in existence without some substantial
form, even by divine power; his emphasis on the role of the human intellect in
the act of choice; his espousal of a real distinction betweeen the soul and its
powers; and his defense of some kind of objective or “real” rather than a
merely mind-dependent composition of essence and act of existing esse in
creatures. Some of Aquinas’s positions were included directly or indirectly in
the 219 propositions condemned by Bishop Stephen Tempier of Paris in 1277, and
his defense of one single substantial form in man was condemned by Archbishop
Robert Kilwardby at Oxford in 1277, with renewed prohibitions by his successor
as archbishop of Canterbury, John Peckham, in 1284 and 1286. Only after
Aquinas’s canonization in 1323 were the Paris prohibitions revoked insofar as
they touched on his teaching in 1325. Even within his own Dominican order,
disagreement about some of his views developed within the first decades after
his death, notwithstanding the order’s highly sympathetic espousal of his
cause. Early English Dominican defenders of his general views included William
Hothum d.1298, Richard Knapwell d.c.1288, Robert Orford b. after 1250,
fl.129095, Thomas Sutton d. c.1315?, and William Macclesfield d.1303. Dominican Thomists included Bernard of Trilia
d.1292, Giles of Lessines in present-day Belgium d.c.1304?, John Quidort of
Paris d. 1306, Bernard of Auvergne d. after 1307, Hervé Nédélec d.1323, Armand
of Bellevue fl. 131634, and William Peter Godin d.1336. The secular master at
Paris, Peter of Auvergne d. 1304, while remaining very independent in his own
views, knew Aquinas’s thought well and completed some of his commentaries on
Aristotle. Sixteenth- and seventeenth-century Thomism. Sometimes known as the
period of Second Thomism, this revival gained impetus from the early
fifteenth-century writer John Capreolus 13801444 in his Defenses of Thomas’s
Theology Defensiones theologiae Divi Thomae, a commentary on the Sentences. A
number of fifteenth-century Dominican and secular teachers in G. universities
also contributed: Kaspar Grunwald Freiburg; Cornelius Sneek and John Stoppe in
Rostock; Leonard of Brixental Vienna; Gerard of Heerenberg, Lambert of
Heerenberg, and John Versor all at Cologne; Gerhard of Elten; and in Belgium
Denis the Carthusian. Outstanding among various sixteenth-century commentators
on Thomas were Tommaso de Vio Cardinal Cajetan, Francis Sylvester of Ferrara,
Francisco de Vitoria Salamanca, and Francisco’s disciples Domingo de Soto and
Melchior Cano. Most important among early seventeenth-century Thomists was John
of St. Thomas, who lectured at Piacenza, Madrid, and Alcalá, and is best known
for his Cursus philosophicus and his Cursus theologicus. Theravada Buddhism
Thomism 916 916 The nineteenth- and
twentieth-century revival. By the early to mid-nineteenth century the study of
Aquinas had been largely abandoned outside Dominican circles, and in most Roman
Catholic s and seminaries a kind of Cartesian and Suarezian Scholasticism was
taught. Long before he became Pope Leo XIII, Joachim Pecci and his brother
Joseph had taken steps to introduce the teaching of Thomistic philosophy at the
diocesan seminary at Perugia in 1846. Earlier efforts in this direction had
been made by Vincenzo Buzzetti, by Buzzetti’s students Serafino and Domenico
Sordi, and by Taparelli d’Aglezio, who became director of the Collegio Romano
Gregorian in 1824. Leo’s encyclical
Aeterni Patris1879 marked an official effort on the part of the Roman Catholic
church to foster the study of the philosophy and theology of Thomas Aquinas.
The intent was to draw upon Aquinas’s original writings in order to prepare
students of philosophy and theology to deal with problems raised by
contemporary thought. The Leonine Commission was established to publish a
critical edition of all of Aquinas’s writings; this effort continues today.
Important centers of Thomistic studies developed, such as the Higher Institute
of Philosophy at Louvain founded by Cardinal Mercier, the Dominican School of
Saulchoir in France, and the Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies in
Toronto. Different groups of Roman, Belgian, and Jesuits acknowledged a deep indebtedness to
Aquinas for their personal philosophical reflections. There was also a
concentration of effort in the United States at universities such as The
Catholic of America, St. Louis , Notre
Dame, Fordham, Marquette, and Boston , to mention but a few, and by the
Dominicans at River Forest. A great weakness of many of the nineteenthand
twentieth-century Latin manuals produced during this effort was a lack of
historical sensitivity and expertise, which resulted in an unreal and highly
abstract presentation of an “Aristotelian-Thomistic” philosophy. This weakness
was largely offset by the development of solid historical research both in the
thought of Aquinas and in medieval philosophy and theology in general,
championed by scholars such as H. Denifle, M. De Wulf, M. Grabmann, P.
Mandonnet, F. Van Steenberghen, E. Gilson and many of his students at Toronto,
and by a host of more recent and contemporary scholars. Much of this historical
work continues today both within and without Catholic scholarly circles. At the
same time, remarkable diversity in interpreting Aquinas’s thought has emerged
on the part of many twentieth-century scholars. Witness, e.g., the heavy
influence of Cajetan and John of St. Thomas on the Thomism of Maritain; the
much more historically grounded approaches developed in quite different ways by
Gilson and F. Van Steenberghen; the emphasis on the metaphysics of
participation in Aquinas in the very different presentations by L. Geiger and
C. Fabro; the emphasis on existence esse promoted by Gilson and many others but
resisted by still other interpreters; the movement known as Transcendental
Thomism, originally inspired by P. Rousselot and by J. Marechal in dialogue
with Kant; and the long controversy about the appropriateness of describing
Thomas’s philosophy and that of other medievals as a Christian philosophy. An
increasing number of non-Catholic thinkers are currently directing considerable
attention to Aquinas, and the varying backgrounds they bring to his texts will
undoubtedly result in still other interesting interpretations and applications
of his thought to contemporary concerns.
jarvis, j. Grice collaborated with Jarvis’s husband at
Oxford. analytic philosopher best known for her contribution to moral
philosophy and for her paper “A Defense of Abortion” 1. Thomson has taught at
M.I.T. since 4. Her work is centrally concerned with issues in moral philosophy,
most notably questions regarding rights, and with issues in metaphysics such as
the identity across time of people and the ontology of events. Her Acts and
Other Events 7 is a study of human action and provides an analysis of the part
whole relation among events. “A Defense of Abortion” has not only influenced
much later work on this topic but is one of the most widely discussed papers in
contemporary philosophy. By appeal to imaginative scenarios analogous to
pregnancy, Thomson argues that even if the fetus is assumed to be a person, its
rights are in many circumstances outweighed by the rights of the pregnant
woman. Thus the paper advances an argument for a right to abortion that does
not turn upon the question of whether the fetus is a person. Several of
Thomson’s essays, including “Preferential Hiring” 3, “The Right to Privacy” 5,
and “Killing, Letting Die, and the Trolley Problem” 6, address the questions of
what constitutes Thomson, Judith Jarvis Thomson, Judith Jarvis 917 917 an infringement of rights and when it is
morally permissible to infringe a right. These are collected in Rights,
Restitution, and Risk: Essays in Moral Theory 6. Thomson’s The Realm of Rights
0 offers a systematic account of human rights, addressing first what it is to
have a right and second which rights we have. Thomson’s work is distinguished
by its exceptionally lucid style and its reliance on highly inventive examples.
The centrality of examples to her work reflects a methodological conviction
that our views about actual and imagined cases provide the data for moral
theorizing. Refs.: H. P. Grice and J. F. Thomson, ‘The philosophy of action and
free will.’
thoreau: h. d. born in Concord, Massachusetts, New
England, he attended Harvard, and, rather than the usual Rhodes scholarship to
Oxford, he returns to Concord to study nature and write, making a frugal living
as a schoolteacher, land surveyor, and pencil maker. Commentators have
emphasized three aspects of his life: his love and penetrating study of the
flora and fauna of the Concord area, recorded with philosophical reflections in
Walden 1854; his continuous pursuit of simplicity in the externals of life,
thus avoiding a life of “quiet desperation”; and his acts of civil
disobedience. The last item has been somewhat overemphasized; not paying a poll
tax by way of protest was not original with Thoreau. However, his essay
“Resistance to Civil Government” immortalized his protest and influenced people
like Gandhi and Martin Luther King, Jr., in later years. Thoreau eventually
helped runaway slaves at considerable risk; still, he considered himself a
student of nature and not a reformer. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “What Thoreau missed
at Oxford.”
Gedanke experiment – Grice: “Oddly, Turing’s Gedanke
experiment’ is about the meaning of ‘gedanke’!” -- used by Grice, first, in his
“Some remarks about the senses.” His Gedanke experiment involves a Martian who
comes and conquers the earth. He has four eyes in his face, with two of them he
x-s, with the other tow he y-s. Tthought experiment, a technique for testing a
hypothesis by imagining a situation and what would be said about it or more
rarely, happen in it. This technique is often used by philosophers to argue for
or against a hypothesis about the meaning or applicability of a concept. For
example, Locke imagined a switch of minds between a prince and a cobbler as a
way to argue that personal identity is based on continuity of memory, not
continuity of the body. To argue for the relativity of simultaneity, Einstein
imagined two observers one on a train,
the other beside it who observed
lightning bolts. And according to some scholars, Galileo only imagined the
experiment of tying two five-pound weights together with a fine string in order
to argue that heavier bodies do not fall faster. Thought experiments of this
last type are rare because they can be used only when one is thoroughly
familiar with the outcome of the imagined situation. J.A.K. Thrasymachus fl.
427 B.C., Grecian Sophist from Bithynia who is known mainly as a character in
Book I of Plato’s Republic. He traveled and taught extensively throughout the
Grecian world, and was well known in Athens as a teacher and as the author of
treatises on rhetoric. Innovative in his style, he was credited with inventing
the “middle style” of rhetoric. The only surviving fragment of a speech by
Thrasymachus was written for delivery by an Athenian citizen in the assembly,
at a time when Athens was not faring well in the Peloponnesian War; it shows
him concerned with the efficiency of government, pleading with the Athenians to
recognize their common interests and give up their factionalism. Our only other
source for his views on political matters is Plato’s Republic, which most
scholars accept as presenting at least a half-truth about Thrasymachus. There,
Thrasymachus is represented as a foil to Socrates, claiming that justice is
only what benefits the stronger, i.e., the rulers. From the point of view of
those who are ruled, then, justice always serves the interest of someone else,
and rulers who seek their own advantage are unjust. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Some
remarks about the senses,” in WoW – Coady, “The senses of the Martians.”
tillich: p. philosopher, born in Starzeddel, eastern
Germany, he was educated in philosophy and theology and ordained in the
Prussian Evangelical Church in 2. He served as an army chaplain during World
War I and later taught at Berlin, Marburg, Dresden, Leipzig, and Frankfurt. In
November 3, following suspension from his teaching post by the Nazis, he
emigrated to the United States, where he taught at Columbia and Union
Theological Seminary until 5, and then at Harvard and Chicago until his death.
A popular preacher and speaker, he developed a wide audience in the United
States through such writings as The Protestant Era 8, Systematic Theology three
volumes: 1, 7, 3, The Courage to Be 2, and Dynamics of Faith 7. His sometimes
unconventional lifestyle, as well as his syncretic yet original thought, moved
“on the boundary” between theology and other elements of culture especially art, literature, political
thought, and depth psychology in the
belief that religion should relate to the whole extent, and the very depths, of
human existence. Tillich’s thought, despite its distinctive “ontological”
vocabulary, was greatly influenced by the voluntaristic tradition from
Augustine through Schelling, Schopenhauer, Marx, Nietzsche, and Freud. It was a
systematic theology that sought to state fresh Christian answers to deep
existential questions raised by individuals and cultures his method of correlation. Every age has its
distinctive kairos, “crisis” or “fullness of time,” the right time for creative
thought and action. In Weimar G.y, Tillich found the times ripe for religious
socialism. In postWorld War II America, he focused more on psychological
themes: in the midst of anxiety over death, meaninglessness, and guilt,
everyone seeks the courage to be, which comes only by avoiding the abyss of
non-being welling up in the demonic and by placing one’s unconditional faith ultit’ien Tillich, Paul 919 919 mate concern not in any particular being e.g. God but in
Being-Itself “the God above God,” the ground of being. This is essentially the
Protestant principle, which prohibits lodging ultimate concern in any finite
and limited reality including state, race, and religious institutions and
symbols. Tillich was especially influential after World War II. He represented
for many a welcome critical openness to the spiritual depths of modern culture,
opposing both demonic idolatry of this world as in National Socialism and
sectarian denial of cultural resources for faith as in Barthian
neo-orthodoxy.
tempus – applied by H. P. Grice and G. Myro in the
so-called “Grice-Myro theory of identity,” a time-relative identity, drawing
from A. N. Prior, of Oxford, D. Wiggins, Wykeham professor of logic at Oxford,
and Geach (married to an Oxonian donna),
time, “a moving image of eternity” Plato; “the number of movements in
respect of the before and after” Aristotle; “the Life of the Soul in movement
as it passes from one stage of act or experience to another” Plotinus; “a
present of things past, memory, a present of things present, sight, and a
present of things future, expectation” Augustine. These definitions, like all
attempts to encapsulate the essence of time in some neat formula, are
unhelpfully circular because they employ temporal notions. Although time might
be too basic to admit of definition, there still are many questions about time
that philosophers have made some progress in answering by analysis both of how
we ordinarily experience and talk about time, and of the deliverances of
science, thereby clarifying and deepening our understanding of what time is.
What follows gives a sample of some of the more important of these issues. Temporal
becoming and the A- and B-theories of time. According to the B-theory, time
consists in nothing but a fixed “B-series” of events running from earlier to
later. The A-theory requires that these events also form an “A-series” going
from the future through the present into the past and, moreover, shift in
respect to these determinations. The latter sort of change, commonly referred
to as “temporal becoming,” gives rise to well-known perplexities concerning
both what does the shifting and the sort of shift involved. Often it is said
that it is the present or now that shifts to ever-later times. This quickly
leads to absurdity. ‘The present’ and ‘now’, like ‘this time’, are used to
refer to a moment of time. Thus, to say that the present shifts to later times
entails that this very moment of time
the present will become some
other moment of time and thus cease to be identical with itself! Sometimes the
entity that shifts is the property of nowness or presentness. The problem is
that every event has this property at some time, namely when it occurs. Thus,
what must qualify some event as being now simpliciter is its having the
property of nowness now; and this is the start of an infinite regress that is
vicious because at each stage we are left with an unexpurgated use of ‘now’,
the very term that was supposed to be analyzed in terms of the property of
nowness. If events are to change from being future to present and from present
to past, as is required by temporal becoming, they must do so in relation to
some mysterious transcendent entity, since temporal relations between events
and/or times cannot change. The nature of the shift is equally perplexing, for
it must occur at a particular rate; but a rate of change involves a comparison
between one kind of change and a change of time. Herein, it is change of time
that is compared to change of time, resulting in the seeming tautology that
time passes or shifts at the rate of one second per second, surely an absurdity
since this is not a rate of change at all. Broad attempted to skirt these
perplexities by saying that becoming is sui generis and thereby defies
analysis, which puts him on the side of the mystically inclined Bergson who
thought that it could be known only through an act of ineffable intuition. To
escape the clutches of both perplexity and mysticism, as well as to satisfy the
demand of science to view the world non-perspectivally, the B-theory attempted
to reduce the A-series to the B-series via a linguistic reduction in which a
temporal indexical proposition reporting an event as past, present, or future
is shown to be identical with a non-indexical proposition reporting a relation
of precedence or simultaneity between it and another event or time. It is
generally conceded that such a reduction fails, since, in general, no indexical
proposition is identical with any non-indexical one, this being due to the fact
that one can have a propositional attitude toward one of them that is not had
to the other; e.g., I can believe that it is now raining without believing that
it rains tenselessly at t 7. The friends of becoming have drawn the wrong moral
from this failure that there is a
mysterious Mr. X out there doing “The Shift.” They have overlooked the fact
that two sentences can express different propositions and yet report one and
the same event or state of affairs; e.g., ‘This is water’ and ‘this is a
collection of H2O molecules’, though differing in sense, report the same state
of affairs this being water is nothing but
this being a collection of H2O molecules. It could be claimed that the same
holds for the appropriate use of indexical and non-indexical sentences; the
tokening at t 7 of ‘Georgie flies at this time at present’ is coreporting with
the non-synonymous ‘Georgie flies tenselessly at t 7’, since Georgie’s flying
at this time is the same event as Georgie’s flying at t 7, given that this time
is t 7. This effects the same ontological reduction of the becoming of events
to their bearing temporal relations to each other as does the linguistic reduction.
The “coreporting reduction” also shows the absurdity of the “psychological
reduction” according to which an event’s being present, etc., requires a
relation to a perceiver, whereas an event’s having a temporal relation to
another event or time does not require a relation to a perceiver. Given that
Georgie’s flying at this time is identical with Georgie’s flying at t 7, it
follows that one and the same event both does and does not have the property of
requiring relation to a perceiver, thereby violating Leibniz’s law that
identicals are indiscernible. Continuous versus discrete time. Assume that the
instants of time are linearly ordered by the relation R of ‘earlier than’. To
say that this order is continuous is, first, to imply the property of density or
infinite divisibility: for any instants i 1 and i 2 such that Ri1i 2, there is
a third instant i 3, such that Ri1i 3 and Ri3i 2. But continuity implies
something more since density allows for “gaps” between the instants, as with
the rational numbers. Think of R as the ‘less than’ relation and the i n as
rationals. To rule out gaps and thereby assure genuine continuity it is
necessary to require in addition to density that every convergent sequence of
instants has a limit. To make this precise one needs a distance measure d
, on pairs of instants, where di m, i n
is interpreted as the lapse of time between i m and i n. The requirement of
continuity proper is then that for any sequence i l , i 2, i 3, . . . , of
instants, if di m i n P 0 as m, n P C, there is a limit instant i ø such that
di n, iø P 0 as n P C. The analogous
property obviously fails for the rationals. But taking the completion of the
rationals by adding in the limit points of convergent sequences yields the real
number line, a genuine continuum. Numerous objections have been raised to the
idea of time as a continuum and to the very notion of the continuum itself.
Thus, it was objected that time cannot be composed of durationless instants
since a stack of such instants cannot produce a non-zero duration. Modern
measure theory resolves this objection. Leibniz held that a continuum cannot be
composed of points since the points in any finite closed interval can be put in
one-to-one correspondence with a smaller subinterval, contradicting the axiom that
the whole is greater than any proper part. What Leibniz took to be a
contradictory feature is now taken to be a defining feature of infinite
collections or totalities. Modern-day Zenoians, while granting the viability of
the mathematical doctrine of the continuum and even the usefulness of its
employment in physical theory, will deny the possibility of its applying to
real-life changes. Whitehead gave an analogue of Zeno’s paradox of the
dichotomy to show that a thing cannot endure in a continuous manner. For if i
1, i 2 is the interval over which the thing is supposed to endure, then the
thing would first have to endure until the instant i 3, halfway between i 1 and
i 2; but before it can endure until i 3, it must first endure until the instant
i 4 halfway between i 1 and i 3, etc. The seductiveness of this paradox rests
upon an implicit anthropomorphic demand that the operations of nature must be
understood in terms of concepts of human agency. Herein it is the demand that
the physicist’s description of a continuous change, such as a runner traversing
a unit spatial distance by performing an infinity of runs of ever-decreasing
distance, could be used as an action-guiding recipe for performing this feat,
which, of course, is impossible since it does not specify any initial or final
doing, as recipes that guide human actions must. But to make this
anthropomorphic demand explicit renders this deployment of the dichotomy, as
well as the arguments against the possibility of performing a “supertask,”
dubious. Anti-realists might deny that we are committed to real-life change
being continuous by our acceptance of a physical theory that employs principles
of mathematical continuity, but this is quite different from the Zenoian claim
that it is impossible for such change to be continuous. To maintain that time
is discrete would require not only abandoning the continuum but also the
density property as well. Giving up either conflicts with the intuition that
time is one-dimensional. For an explanation of how the topological analysis of
dimensionality entails that the dimension of a discrete space is 0, see W.
Hurewicz, Dimension Theory, 1. The philosophical and physics literatures
contain speculations about a discrete time built of “chronons” or temporal
atoms, but thus far such hypothetical entities have not been incorporated into
a satisfactory theory. Absolute versus relative and relational time. In a
scholium to the Principia, Newton declared that “Absolute, true and
mathematical time, of itself and from its own nature, flows equably without
relation to anything external.” There are at least five interrelated senses in
which time was absolute for Newton. First, he thought that there was a
frame-independent relation of simultaneity for events. Second, he thought that
there was a frame-independent measure of duration for non-simultaneous events.
He used ‘flows equably’ not to refer to the above sort of mysterious “temporal
becoming,” but instead to connote the second sense of absoluteness and partly
to indicate two further kinds of absoluteness. To appreciate the latter, note
that ‘flows equably’ is modified by ‘without relation to anything external’.
Here Newton was asserting third sense of ‘absolute’ that the lapse of time
between two events would be what it is even if the distribution and motions of
material bodies were different. He was also presupposing a related form of
absoluteness fourth sense according to which the metric of time is intrinsic to
the temporal interval. Leibniz’s philosophy of time placed him in agreement
with Newton as regards the first two senses of ‘absolute’, which assert the
non-relative or frame-independent nature of time. However, Leibniz was very
much opposed to Newton on the fourth sense of ‘absolute’. According to
Leibniz’s relational conception of time, any talk about the length of a
temporal interval must be unpacked in terms of talk about the relation of the
interval to an extrinsic metric standard. Furthermore, Leibniz used his
principles of sufficient reason and identity of indiscernibles to argue against
a fifth sense of ‘absolute’, implicit in Newton’s philosophy of time, according
to which time is a substratum in which physical events are situated. On the
contrary, the relational view holds that time is nothing over and above the structure
of relations of events. Einstein’s special and general theories of relativity
have direct bearing on parts of these controversies. The special theory
necessitates the abandonment of frame-independent notions of simultaneity and
duration. For any pair of spacelike related events in Minkowski space-time
there is an inertial frame in which the events are simultaneous, another frame
in which the first event is temporally prior, and still a third in which the
second event is temporally prior. And the temporal interval between two
timelike related events depends on the worldline connecting them. In fact, for
any e 0, no matter how small, there is a
worldline connecting the events whose proper length is less than e. This is the
essence of the so-called twin paradox. The general theory of relativity
abandons the third sense of absoluteness since it entails that the metrical
structure of space-time covaries with the distribution of mass-energy in a
manner specified by Einstein’s field equations. But the heart of the
absoluterelational controversy as
focused by the fourth and fifth senses of ‘absolute’ is not settled by relativistic
considerations. Indeed, opponents from both sides of the debate claim to find
support for their positions in the special and general theories. H. P. Grice,
“D. H. Mellor on real and irreal time.”
tempus -- time slice: used by Grice in two different
contexts: personal identity, and identity in general. In identity in general,
Grice draws from Geach and Wiggins, and with the formal aid of Myro, construct
a system of a first-order predicate calculus with time-relative identity -- a
temporal part or stage of any concrete particular that exists for some interval
of time; a three-dimensional cross section of a fourdimensional object. To
think of an object as consisting of time slices or temporal stages is to think
of it as related to time in much the way that it is related to space: as
extending through time as well as space, rather than as enduring through it.
Just as an object made up of spatial parts is thought of as a whole made up of
parts that exist at different locations, so an object made up of time slices is
thought of as a whole made up of parts or stages that exist at successive
times; hence, just as a spatial whole is only partly present in any space that
does not include all its spatial parts, so a whole made up of time slices is
only partly present in any stretch of time that does not include all its
temporal parts. A continuant, by contrast, is most commonly understood to be a
particular that endures through time, i.e., that is wholly present at each
moment at which it exists. To conceive of an object as a continuant is to
conceive of it as related to time in a very different way from that in which it
is related to space. A continuant does not extend through time as well as
space; it does not exist at different times by virtue of the existence of
successive parts of it at those times; it is the continuant itself that is
wholly present at each such time. To conceive an object as a continuant,
therefore, is to conceive it as not made up of temporal stages, or time slices,
at all. There is another, less common, use of ‘continuant’ in which a
continuant is understood to be any particular that exists for some stretch of
time, regardless of whether it is the whole of the particular or only some part
of it that is present at each moment of the particular’s existence. According
to this usage, an entity that is made up of time slices would be a kind of
continuant rather than some other kind of particular. Philosophers have
disputed whether ordinary objects such as cabbages and kings endure through
time are continuants or only extend through time are sequences of time slices.
Some argue that to understand the possibility of change one must think of such
objects as sequences of time slices; others argue that for the same reason one
must think of such objects as continuants. If an object changes, it comes to be
different from itself. Some argue that this would be possible only if an object
consisted of distinct, successive stages; so that change would simply consist
in the differences among the successive temporal parts of an object. Others
argue that this view would make change impossible; that differences among the
successive temporal parts of a thing would no more imply the thing had changed
than differences among its spatial parts would.
H. P. Grice, “D. H. Mellor on real and irreal time.”
token-reflexive, an expression that refers to itself in
an act of speech or writing, such as ‘this token’. The term was coined by
Reichenbach, who conjectured that all indexicals, all expressions whose
semantic value depends partly on features of the context of utterance, are
tokenreflexive and definable in terms of the phrase ‘this token’. He suggested that
‘I’ means the same as ‘the person who utters this token’, ‘now’ means the same
as ‘the time at which this token is uttered’, ‘this table’ means the same as
‘the table pointed to by a gesture accompanying this token’, and so forth.
Russell made a somewhat similar suggestion in his discussion of egocentric
particulars. Reichenbach’s conjecture is widely regarded as false; although ‘I’
does pick out the person using it, it is not synonymous with ‘the person who
utters this token’. If it were, as David Kaplan observes, ‘If no one were to
utter this token, I would not exist’ would be true.
toletus, F. Jesuit theologian and philosopher. Born in
Córdoba, he studied at Valencia, Salamanca, and Rome, and became the first
Jesuit cardinal in 1594. He composed commentaries on several of Aristotle’s
works and a commentary on Aquinas’s Summa theologiae. Toletus followed a
Thomistic line, but departed from Thomism in some details. He held that
individuals are directly apprehended by the intellect and that the agent intellect
is the same power as the possible intellect. He rejected the Thomistic
doctrines of the real distinction between essence and existence and of
individuation by designated matter; for Toletus individuation results from
form.
tonk, a sentential connective whose meaning and logic
are completely characterized by the two rules or axioms 1 [P P P tonk Q] and 2
[P tonk Q P Q]. If 1 and 2 are added to any normal system, then every Q can be
derived from any P. A. N. Prior invented ‘tonk’ to show that deductive validity
must not be conceived as depending solely on arbitrary syntactically defined
rules or axioms. We may prohibit ‘tonk’ on the ground that it is not a natural,
independently meaningful notion, but we may also prohibit it on purely
syntactical grounds. E.g., we may require that, for every connective C, the
C-introduction rule [xxx P . . . C . . .] and the C-elimination rule [ - - - C
- - - P yyy] be such that the yyy is part of xxx or is related to xxx in some
other syntactical way.
topic-neutral, noncommittal between two or more
ontological interpretations of a term. J. J. C. Smart suggested that
introspective reports can be taken as topic-neutral: composed of terms neutral
between “dualistic metaphysics” and “materialistic metaphysics.” When one
asserts, e.g., that one has a yellowish-orange afterimage, this is tantamount
to saying ‘There is something going on that is like what is going on when I
have my eyes open, am awake, and there is an orange illuminated in good light
in front of me, i.e., when I really see an orange’. The italicized phrase is,
in Smart’s terms, topic-neutral; it refers to an event, while remaining
noncommittal about whether it is material or immaterial. The term has not
always been restricted to neutrality regarding dualism and materialism. Smart
suggests that topic-neutral descriptions are composed of “quasi-logical” words,
and hence would be suitable for any occasion where a relatively noncommittal
expression of a view is required.
topos – Grice: “I will use the Latinate ‘commonplace’” –
‘locus communis’-- topic, the analysis of common strategies of argumentation,
later a genre of literature analyzing syllogistic reasoning. Aristotle
considered the analysis of types of argument, or “topics,” the best means of
describing the art of dialectical reasoning; he also used the term to refer to
the principle underlying the strategy’s production of an argument. Later
classical commentators on Aristotle, particularly Latin rhetoricians like
Cicero, developed Aristotle’s discussions of the theory of dialectical
reasoning into a philosophical form. Boethius’s work on topics exemplifies the
later classical expansion of the scope of topics literature. For him, a topic
is either a self-evidently true universal generalization, also called a
“maximal proposition,” or a differentia, a member of the set of a maximal
proposition’s characteristics that determine its genus and species. Man is a
rational animal is a maximal proposition, and like from genus, the differentia
that characterizes the maximal proposition as concerning genera, it is a topic.
Because he believed dialectical reasoning leads to categorical, not
conditional, conclusions, Boethius felt that the discovery of an argument
entailed discovering a middle term uniting the two, previously unjoined terms
of the conclusion. Differentiae are the genera of these middle terms, and one
constructs arguments by choosing differentiae, thereby determining the middle
term leading to the conclusion. In the eleventh century, Boethius’s logical structure
of maximal propositions and differentiae was used to study hypothetical
syllogisms, while twelfth-century theorists like Abelard extended the
applicability of topics structure to the categorical syllogism. By the
thirteenth century, Peter of Spain, Robert Kilwardby, and Boethius of Dacia
applied topics structure exclusively to the categorical syllogism, principally
those with non-necessary, probable premises. Within a century, discussion of
topics structure to evaluate syllogistic reasoning was subsumed by consequences
literature, which described implication, entailment, and inference relations
between propositions. While the theory of consequences as an approach to
understanding relations between propositions is grounded in Boethian, and
perhaps Stoic, logic, it became prominent only in the later thirteenth century
with Burley’s recognition of the logical significance of propositional
logic.
toxin puzzle, a puzzle about intention and practical
rationality: trustworthy billionaire, call him Paul, offers you, Peter, a
million pounds for intending tonight to drink a certain toxin tomorrow. Peter
is convinced that Paul can tell what Peter intends independently of what Peter
does. The toxin would make Peter painfully ill for a day. But Peter needs to drink
it to get the money. Constraints on the formation of a prize-winning intention
include prohibitions against “gimmicks,” “external incentives,” and forgetting
relevant details; e. g. Peter will not receive the money if Peter has a
hypnotist “implant the intention” or hire a hit man to kill Peter should Peter not
drink the toxin. If, by midnight tonight, without violating any rules, Peter
forms an intention to drink the toxin tomorrow, Peter will find a million
pounds in his bank account when he awakes tomorrow morning. Peter probably
would drink the toxin for a million dollars. But can you, without violating the
rules, intend tonight to drink it tomorrow? Apparently, you have no reason to
drink it and an excellent reason not to drink it. Seemingly, you will infer
from this that you will eschew drinking the toxin, and believing that you will top-down
eschew drinking it seems inconsistent with intending to drink it. Even so,
there are several reports in the philosophical literature of possible people
who struck it rich when offered the toxin deal! Refs: H. P. Grice, “Grice’s
book of paradoxes, with puzzling illustrations to match!”
transcendentale: Grice: “Trust Cicero to look for the
abstract!” -- transcendentia, broadly, the property of rising out of or above
other things virtually always understood figuratively; in philosophy, the
property of being, in some way, of a higher order. A being, such as God, may be
said to be transcendent in the sense of being not merely superior, but
incomparably superior, to other things, in any sort of perfection. God’s
transcendence, or being outside or beyond the world, is also contrasted, and by
some thinkers combined, with God’s immanence, or existence within the world. In
medieval philosophy of logic, terms such as ‘being’ and ‘one’, which did not
belong uniquely to any one of the Aristotelian categories or types of
predication such as substance, quality, and relation, but could be predicated
of things belonging to any or to none of them, were called transcendental. In
Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, principles that profess wrongly to take us
beyond the limits of any possible experience are called transcendent; whereas
anything belonging to non-empirical thought that establishes, and draws
consequences from, the possibility and limits of experience may be called
transcendental. Thus a transcendental argument in a sense still current is one
that proceeds from premises about the way in which experience is possible to
conclusions about what must be true of any experienced world. Transcendentalism
was a philosophical or religious movement in mid-nineteenth-century New
England, characterized, in the thought of its leading representative, Ralph
Waldo Emerson, by belief in a transcendent spiritual and divine principle in
human nature.
transcendental argument: Grice: “I prefer metaphysical
argument.’ -- an argument that elucidates the conditions for the possibility of
some fundamental phenomenon whose existence is unchallenged or uncontroversial
in the philosophical context in which the argument is propounded. Such an
argument proceeds deductively, from a premise asserting the existence of some
basic phenomenon such as meaningful discourse, conceptualization of objective
states of affairs, or the practice of making promises, to a conclusion
asserting the existence of some interesting, substantive enabling conditions
for that phenomenon. The term derives from Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason,
which gives several such arguments. The paradigmatic Kantian transcendental
argument is the “Transcendental Deduction of the Pure Concepts of
Understanding.” Kant argued there that the objective validity of certain pure,
or a priori, concepts the “categories” is a condition for the possibility of
experience. Among the concepts allegedly required for having experience are
those of substance and cause. Their apriority consists in the fact that
instances of these concepts are not directly given in sense experience in the
manner of instances of empirical concepts such as red. This fact gave rise to
the skepticism of Hume concerning the very coherence of such alleged a priori
concepts. Now if these concepts do have objective validity, as Kant endeavored
to prove in opposition to Hume, then the world contains genuine instances of
the concepts. In a transcendental argument concerning the conditions for the
possibility of experience, it is crucial that some feature entailed by the
having of experience is identified. Then it is argued that experience could not
have this feature without satisfying some substantive conditions. In the
Transcendental Deduction, the feature of experience on which Kant concentrates
is the ability of a subject of experience to be aware of several distinct inner
states as all belonging to a single consciousness. There is no general
agreement on how Kant’s argument actually unfolded, though it seems clear to
most that he focused on the role of the categories in the synthesis or
combination of one’s inner states in judgments, where such synthesis is said to
be required for one’s awareness of the states as being all equally one’s own
states. Another famous Kantian transcendental argument the “Refutation of Idealism” in the
CriToynbee, Arnold transcendental argument 925
925 tique of Pure Reason shares a
noteworthy trait with the Transcendental Deduction. The Refutation proceeds
from the premise that one is conscious of one’s own existence as determined in
time, i.e., knows the temporal order of some of one’s inner states. According
to the Refutation, a condition for the possibility of such knowledge is one’s
consciousness of the existence of objects located outside oneself in space. If
one is indeed so conscious, that would refute the skeptical view, formulated by
Descartes, that one lacks knowledge of the existence of a spatial world
distinct from one’s mind and its inner states. Both of the Kantian
transcendental arguments we have considered, then, conclude that the falsity of
some skeptical view is a condition for the possibility of some phenomenon whose
existence is acknowledged even by the skeptic the having of experience;
knowledge of temporal facts about one’s own inner states. Thus, we can isolate
an interesting subclass of transcendental arguments: those which are
anti-skeptical in nature. Barry Stroud has raised the question whether such
arguments depend on some sort of suppressed verificationism according to which
the existence of language or conceptualization requires the availability of the
knowledge that the skeptic questions since verificationism has it that
meaningful sentences expressing coherent concepts, e.g., ‘There are tables’,
must be verifiable by what is given in sense experience. Dependence on a highly
controversial premise is undesirable in itself. Further, Stroud argued, such a
dependence would render superfluous whatever other content the anti-skeptical
transcendental argument might embody since the suppressed premise alone would
refute the skeptic. There is no general agreement on whether Stroud’s doubts
about anti-skeptical transcendental arguments are well founded. It is not
obvious whether the doubts apply to arguments that do not proceed from a
premise asserting the existence of language or conceptualization, but instead
conform more closely to the Kantian model. Even so, no anti-skeptical
transcendental argument has been widely accepted. This is evidently due to the
difficulty of uncovering substantive enabling conditions for phenomena that
even a skeptic will countenance.
transcendentalism, a religious-philosophical viewpoint
held by a group of New England intellectuals, of whom Emerson, Thoreau, and
Theodore Parker were the most important. A distinction taken over from Samuel
Taylor Coleridge was the only bond that universally united the members of the
Transcendental Club, founded in 1836: the distinction between the understanding
and reason, the former providing uncertain knowledge of appearances, the latter
a priori knowledge of necessary truths gained through intuition. The
transcendentalists insisted that philosophical truth could be reached only by reason,
a capacity common to all people unless destroyed by living a life of externals
and accepting as true only secondhand traditional beliefs. On almost every
other point there were disagreements. Emerson was an idealist, while Parker was
a natural realist they simply had
conflicting a priori intuitions. Emerson, Thoreau, and Parker rejected the
supernatural aspects of Christianity, pointing out its unmistakable parochial
nature and sociological development; while James Marsh, Frederick Henry Hedge,
and Caleb Henry remained in the Christian fold. The influences on the
transcendentalists differed widely and explain the diversity of opinion. For
example, Emerson was influenced by the Platonic tradition, G. Romanticism,
Eastern religions, and nature poets, while Parker was influenced by modern
science, the Scottish realism of Reid and Cousin which also emphasized a priori
intuitions, and the G. Higher Critics. Emerson, Thoreau, and Parker were also
bonded by negative beliefs. They not only rejected Calvinism but Unitarianism
as well; they rejected the ordinary concept of material success and put in its
place an Aristotelian type of selfrealization that emphasized the rational and
moral self as the essence of humanity and decried idiosyncratic self-realization
that admires what is unique in people as constituting their real value.
transcendentale: Grice: “The formation of this
Ciceronian expression is fascinating. There’s the descent of the lark, and the
transcend of the lark!” -- transcendentals, also called transcendentalia, terms
or concepts that apply to all things regardless of the things’ ontological kind
or category. transcendental deduction transcendentals 926 926 Terms or concepts of this sort are
transcendental in the sense that they transcend or are superordinate to all
classificatory categories. The classical doctrine of the transcendentals,
developed in detail in the later Middle Ages, presupposes an Aristotelian
ontology according to which all beings are substances or accidents classifiable
within one of the ten highest genera, the ten Aristotelian categories. In this
scheme being Grecian on, Latin ens is not itself one of the categories since
all categories mark out kinds of being. But neither is it a category above the
ten categories of substance and accidents, an ultimate genus of which the ten
categories are species. This is because being is homonymous or equivocal, i.e.,
there is no single generic property or nature shared by members of each
category in virtue of which they are beings. The ten categories identify ten
irreducible, most basic ways of being. Being, then, transcends the categorial
structure of the world: anything at all that is ontologically classifiable is a
being, and to say of anything that it is a being is not to identify it as a
member of some kind distinct from other kinds of things. According to this
classical doctrine, being is the primary transcendental, but there are other
terms or concepts that transcend the categories in a similar way. The most
commonly recognized transcendentals other than being are one unum, true verum,
and good bonum, though some medieval philosophers also recognized thing res,
something aliquid, and beautiful pulchrum. These other terms or concepts are
transcendental because the ontological ground of their application to a given
thing is precisely the same as the ontological ground in virtue of which that
thing can be called a being. For example, for a thing with a certain nature to
be good is for it to perform well the activity that specifies it as a thing of
that nature, and to perform this activity well is to have actualized that
nature to a certain extent. But for a thing to have actualized its nature to
some extent is just what it is for the thing to have being. So the actualities
or properties in virtue of which a thing is good are precisely those in virtue
of which it has being. Given this account, medieval philosophers held that
transcendental terms are convertible convertuntur or extensionally equivalent
idem secundum supposita. They are not synonymous, however, since they are
intensionally distinct differunt secundum rationem. These secondary
transcendentals are sometimes characterized as attributes passiones of being
that are necessarily concomitant with it. In the modern period, the notion of
the transcendental is associated primarily with Kant, who made ‘transcendental’
a central technical term in his philosophy. For Kant the term no longer
signifies that which transcends categorial classification but that which
transcends our experience in the sense of providing its ground or structure.
Kant allows, e.g., that the pure forms of intuition space and time and the pure
concepts of understanding categories such as substance and cause are
transcendental in this sense. Forms and concepts of this sort constitute the
conditions of the possibility of experience.
Trans-finitum, definitum, infinitum: Trans-finite
number, in set theory, an infinite cardinal or ordinal number.
transformation – Grice: “My system G makes minimal use
of transformations” -- minimal transformation rule: an axiom-schema or rule of
inference. Grice: “Strictly, an Ovidian metamorphose!” -- A transformation rule
is thus a rule for transforming a possibly empty set of wellformed formulas
into a formula, where that rule operates only upon syntactic information. It
was this conception of an axiom-schema and rule of inference that was one of
the keys to creating a genuinely rigorous science of deductive reasoning. In
the 0s, the idea was imported into linguistics, giving rise to the notion of a
transformational rule. Such a rule transforms tree structures into tree
structures, taking one from the deep structure of a sentence, which determines
its semantic interpretation, to the surface structure of that sentence, which
determines its phonetic interpretation. Grice: “Chomsky misuses
‘transformation.’” --
metaosiosis – cited by Grice, one of his metaphysical
routines. transubstantiation, change of one substance into another.
Aristotelian metaphysics distinguishes between substances and the accidents
that inhere in them; thus, Socrates is a substance and being snub-nosed is one
of his accidents. The Roman Catholic and Eastern Orthodox churches appeal to
transubstantiation to explain how Jesus Christ becomes really present in the
Eucharist when the consecration takes place: the whole substances of the bread
and wine are transformed into the body and blood of Christ, but the accidents
of the bread and wine such as their shape, color, and taste persist after the
transformation. This seems to commit its adherents to holding that these
persisting accidents subsequently either inhere in Christ or do not inhere in
any substance. Luther proposed an alternative explanation in terms of
consubstantiation that avoids this hard choice: the substances of the bread and
wine coexist in the Eucharist with the body and blood of Christ after the
consecration; they are united but each remains unchanged. P.L.Q. transvaluation
of values.
transversum -- Transversality – a term Grice borrowed from
Heidegger – ‘the greatest philosopher that ever lived.” -- transcendence of the sovereignty of identity
or self-sameness by recognizing the alterity of the Other as Unterschied to use Heidegger’s term which signifies the sense of relatedness by
way of difference. An innovative idea employed and appropriated by such diverse
philosophers as Merleau-Ponty, Sartre, Gilles Deleuze, and Félix Guattari,
transversality is meant to replace the Eurocentric formulation of truth as
universal in an age when the world is said to be rushing toward the global
village. Universality has been a Eurocentric idea because what is particular in
the West is universalized, whereas what is particular elsewhere remains
particularized. Since its center is everywhere and its circumference nowhere, truth
is polycentric and correlative. Particularly noteworthy is the phenomenologist Calvin O. Schrag’s attempt to
appropriate transversality by splitting the difference between the two extremes
of absolutism and relativism on the one hand and modernity’s totalizing
practices and postmodernity’s fragmentary tendencies on the other.
arbor
griceiana, arbor porphyriana: a structure generated from the logical and
metaphysical apparatus of Aristotle’s Categories, as systematized by Porphyry
and later writers. A tree in the category of substance begins with substance as
its highest genus and divides that genus into mutually exclusive and
collectively exhaustive subordinate genera by means of a pair of opposites,
called differentiae, yielding, e.g., corporeal substance and incorporeal
substance. The process of division by differentiae continues until a lowest
species is reached, a species that cannot be divided further. The species
“human being” is said to be a lowest species whose derivation can be recaptured
from the formula “mortal, rational, sensitive, animate, corporeal
substance.”
trinitarianism, -- “Raining, raining, raining.” -- the
theological doctrine that God consists of three persons, “in Strawson’s usage
of the expression” – Vide Grice, “Personal identity,” -- The persons who
constitute the Holy Trinity are the Father; the Son, who is Jesus Christ; and
the Holy Spirit or Holy Ghost. The doctrine states that each of these three
persons is God and yet they are not three Gods but one God. According to a
traditional formulation, the three persons are but one substance. In the
opinion of Aquinas, the existence of God can be proved by human reason, but the
existence of the three persons cannot be proved and is known only by
revelation. According to Christian tradition, revelation contains information
about the relations among the three persons, and these relations ground proper
attributes of each that distinguish them from one another. Thus, since the
Father begets the Son, a proper attribute of the Father is paternity and a
proper attribute of the Son is filiation. Procession transparent Trinitarianism
928 928 or spiration is a proper
attribute of the Holy Spirit. A disagreement about procession has contributed
to dividing Eastern and Western Christianity. The Eastern Orthodox church
teaches that the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Father through the Son. A theory
of double procession according to which the Holy Spirit proceeds from the
Father and the Son has been widely accepted in the West. This disagreement is
known as the filioque ‘and the Son’ controversy because it arose from the fact
that adding this Latin phrase to the Nicene Creed became acceptable in the West
but not in the East. Unitarianism denies that God consists of three persons and
so is committed to denying the divinity of Jesus. The monotheistic faiths of
Judaism and Islam are unitarian, but there are unitarians who consider
themselves Christians. H. P. Grice, “Raining, raining, raining – my mother and
the Trinitarians.”
troeltsch: philosopher whose primary aim was to provide a
scientific foundation for theology. Educated at Erlangen, Göttingen under
Ritschl and Lagarde, and Berlin, he initially taught theology at Heidelberg and
later philosophy in Berlin. He launched the school of history of religion with
his epoch-making “On Historical and Dogmatical Method in Theology” 6. His
contributions to theology The Religious Apriori, 4, philosophy, sociology, and
history Historicism and Its Problems, 2 were vastly influential. Troeltsch
claimed that only a philosophy of religion drawn from the history and
development of religious consciousness could strengthen the standing of the
science of religion among the sciences and advance the Christian strategy
against materialism, naturalism, skepticism, aestheticism, and pantheism. His
historical masterpiece, Protestantism and Progress 6, argues that early
Protestantism was a modified medieval Catholicism that delayed the development
of modern culture. As a sociologist, he addressed, in The Social Teachings of
the Christian Churches 2, the twofold issue of whether religious beliefs and
movements are conditioned by external factors and whether, in turn, they affect
society and culture. From Christian social history he inferred three types of
“sociological self-formation of the Christian idea”: the church, the sect, and
the mystic
tropic: Grice: “Cf. Cicero, ‘Tropicus, and
sub-tropicus’ –“ used by R. M. Hare and H. P. Grice – Hare introduced the
‘tropic’ to contrast with the ‘phrastic,’ the ‘neustic,’ and the ‘clistic’ – “I
often wondered if Hare was not distinguishing too narrowly” – H. P. Grice --trope,
in recent philosophical usage, an “abstract particular”; an instance of a
property occurring at a particular place and time, such as the color of the
cover of this book or this . The whiteness of this and the whiteness of the previous are two distinct tropes, identical neither
with the universal whiteness that is instantiated in both s, nor with the itself; although the whiteness of this cannot exist independently of this ,
this could be dyed some other color. A
number of writers, perhaps beginning with D. C. Williams, have argued that
tropes must be included in our ontology if we are to achieve an adequate
metaphysics. More generally, a trope is a figure of speech, or the use of an
expression in a figurative or nonliteral sense. Metaphor and irony, e.g., fall
under the category of tropes. If you are helping someone move a glass table but
drop your end, and your companion says, “Well, you’ve certainly been a big
help,” her utterance is probably ironical, with the intended meaning that you
have been no help. One important question is whether, in order to account for
the ironical use of this sentence, we must suppose that it has an ironical
meaning in addition to its literal meaning. Quite generally, does a sentence
usable to express two different metaphors have, in addition to its literal
meaning, two metaphorical meanings and
another if it can be hyperbolic, and so forth? Many philosophers and other
theorists from Aristotle on have answered yes, and postulated such figurative
meanings in addition to literal sentence meaning. Recently, philosophers loath
to multiply sentence meanings have denied that sentences have any non-literal
meanings.Their burden is to explain how, e.g., a sentence can be used
ironically if it does not have an ironical sense or meaning. Such philosophers
disagree on whether tropes are to be explained semantically or pragmatically. A
semantic account might hypothesize that tropes are generated by violations of
semantical rules. An important pragmatic approach is Grice’s suggestion that
tropes can be subsumed under the more general phenomenon of conversational implicaturum.
verisimilitude -- truthlikeness, a term introduced by
Karl Popper to explicate the idea that one theory may have a better
correspondence with reality, or be closer to the truth, or have more
verisimilitude, than another theory. Truthlikeness, which combines truth with
information content, has to be distinguished from probability, which increases
with lack of content. Let T and F be the classes of all true and false
sentences, respectively, and A and B deductively closed sets of sentences.
According to Popper’s qualitative definition, A is more truthlike than B if and
only if B 3 T 0 A 3 T and A 3 F 0 B 3 F, where one of these setinclusions is
strict. In particular, when A and B are non-equivalent and both true, A is more
truthlike than B if and only if A logically entails B. David Miller and Pavel
Tichý proved in 4 that Popper’s definition is not applicable to the comparison
of false theories: if A is more truthlike than B, then A must be true. Since
the mid-0s, a new approach to truthlikeness has been based upon the concept of
similarity: the degree of truthlikeness of a statement A depends on the
distances from the states of affairs allowed by A to the true state. In Graham
Oddie’s Likeness to Truth 6, this dependence is expressed by the average
function; in Ilkka Niiniluoto’s Truthlikeness 7, by the weighted average of the
minimum distance and the sum of all distances. The concept of verisimilitude is
also used in the epistemic sense to express a rational evaluation of how close
to the truth a theory appears to be on available evidence.
verum – Grice: “Cognate with German ‘wahr’” -- there’s
the ‘truth table’ and the ‘truth’ -- truth table, a tabular display of one or
more truth-functions, truth-functional operators, or representatives of
truth-functions or truth-functional operators such as well-formed formulas of
propositional logic. In the tabular display, each row displays a possible
assignment of truthvalues to the arguments of the truth-functions or
truth-functional operators. Thus, the collection of all rows in the table
displays all possible assignments of truth-values to these arguments. The
following simple truth table represents the truth-functional operators negation
and conjunction: truth, coherence theory of truth table 931 931 Because a truth table displays all
possible assignments of truth-values to the arguments of a truth-function,
truth tables are useful devices for quickly ascertaining logical properties of
propositions. If, e.g., all entries in the column of a truth table representing
a proposition are T, then the proposition is true for all possible assignments
of truth-values to its ultimate constituent propositions; in this sort of case,
the proposition is said to be logically or tautologically true: a tautology. If
all entries in the column of a truth table representing a proposition are F,
then the proposition is false for all possible assignments of truth-values to
its ultimate constituent propositions, and the proposition is said to be
logically or tautologically false: a contradiction. If a proposition is neither
a tautology nor a contradiction, then it is said to be a contingency. The truth
table above shows that both Not-P and Pand-Q are contingencies. For the same
reason that truth tables are useful devices for ascertaining the logical
qualities of single propositions, truth tables are also useful for ascertaining
whether arguments are valid or invalid. A valid argument is one such that there
is no possibility no row in the relevant truth table in which all its premises
are true and its conclusion false. Thus the above truth table shows that the argument
‘P-and-Q; therefore, P’ is valid. Verum
-- truth-value, most narrowly, one of the values T for ‘true’ or F for ‘false’
that a proposition may be considered to have or take on when it is regarded as
true or false, respectively. More broadly, a truth-value is any one of a range
of values that a proposition may be considered to have when taken to have one
of a range of different cognitive or epistemic statuses. For example, some
philosophers speak of the truth-value I for ‘indeterminate’ and regard a proposition
as having the value I when it is indeterminate whether the proposition is true
or false. Logical systems employing a specific number n of truthvalues are said
to be n-valued logical systems; the simplest sort of useful logical system has
two truth-values, T and F, and accordingly is said to be two-valued.
Truth-functions are functions that take truth-values as arguments and that
yield truth-values as resultant values. The truthtable method in propositional
logic exploits the idea of truth-functions by using tabular displays. Verum -- truth-value
semantics, interpretations of formal systems in which the truth-value of a
formula rests ultimately only on truth-values that are assigned to its atomic
subformulas where ‘subformula’ is suitably defined. The label is due to Hugues
Leblanc. On a truth-value interpretation for first-order predicate logic, for
example, the formula atomic ExFx is true in a model if and only if all its
instances Fm, Fn, . . . are true, where the truth-value of these formulas is
simply assigned by the model. On the standard Tarskian or objectual
interpretation, by contrast, ExFx is true in a model if and only if every
object in the domain of the model is an element of the set that interprets F in
the model. Thus a truth-value semantics for predicate logic comprises a
substitutional interpretation of the quantifiers and a “non-denotational”
interpretation of terms and predicates. If t 1, t 2, . . . are all the terms of
some first-order language, then there are objectual models that satisfy the set
{Dx-Fx, Ft1, Ft2 . . . .}, but no truth-value interpretations that do. One can
ensure that truth-value semantics delivers the standard logic, however, by
suitable modifications in the definitions of consistency and consequence. A set
G of formulas of language L is said to be consistent, for example, if there is
some G' obtained from G by relettering terms such that G' is satisfied by some
truth-value assignment, or, alternatively, if there is some language L+
obtained by adding terms to L such that G is satisfied by some truth-value
assignment to the atoms of L+. Truth-value semantics is of both technical and
philosophical interest. Technically, it allows the completeness of first-order
predicate logic and a variety of other formal systems to be obtained in a
natural way from that of propositional logic. Philosophically, it dramatizes
the fact that the formulas in one’s theories about the world do not, in
themselves, determine one’s ontological commitments. It is at least possible to
interpret first-order formulas without reference to special truth-table method
truth-value semantics 932 932 domains
of objects, and higher-order formulas without reference to special domains of
relations and properties. The idea of truth-value semantics dates at least to
the writings of E. W. Beth on first-order predicate logic in 9 and of K.
Schütte on simple type theory in 0. In more recent years similar semantics have
been suggested for secondorder logics, modal and tense logics, intuitionistic
logic, and set theory. Truth, the quality of those propositions that accord
with reality, specifying what is in fact the case. Whereas the aim of a science
is to discover which of the propositions in its domain are true i.e., which
propositions possess the property of Trinity truth 929 929 truth
the central philosophical concern with truth is to discover the nature
of that property. Thus the philosophical question is not What is true? but rather,
What is truth? What is one saying about
a proposition in saying that it is true? The importance of this question stems
from the variety and depth of the principles in which the concept of truth is
deployed. We are tempted to think, e.g., that truth is the proper aim and
natural result of scientific inquiry, that true beliefs are useful, that the
meaning of a sentence is given by the conditions that would render it true, and
that valid reasoning preserves truth. Therefore insofar as we wish to
understand, assess, and refine these epistemological, ethical, semantic, and
logical views, some account of the nature of truth would seem to be required.
Such a thing, however, has been notoriously elusive. The belief that snow is
white owes its truth to a certain feature of the external world: the fact that
snow is white. Similarly, the belief that dogs bark is true because of the fact
that dogs bark. Such trivial observations lead to what is perhaps the most
natural and widely held account of truth, the correspondence theory, according
to which a belief statement, sentence, proposition, etc. is true provided there
exists a fact corresponding to it. This Aristotelian thesis is unexceptionable
in itself. However, if it is to provide a complete theory of truth and if it is to be more than merely a picturesque
way of asserting all instances of ‘the belief that p is true if and only if
p’ then it must be supplemented with
accounts of what facts are, and what it is for a belief to correspond to a
fact; and these are the problems on which the correspondence theory of truth
has foundered. A popular alternative to the correspondence theory has been to
identify truth with verifiability. This idea can take on various forms. One
version involves the further assumption that verification is holistic i.e., that a belief is verified when it is
part of an entire system of beliefs that is consistent and “harmonious.” This
is known as the coherence theory of truth and was developed by Bradley and
Brand Blanchard. Another version, due to Dummett and Putnam, involves the
assumption that there is, for each proposition, some specific procedure for
finding out whether one should believe it or not. On this account, to say that
a proposition is true is to say that it would be verified by the appropriate
procedure. In mathematics this amounts to the identification of truth with
provability and is sometimes referred to as intuitionistic truth. Such theories
aim to avoid obscure metaphysical notions and explain the close relation
between knowability and truth. They appear, however, to overstate the intimacy
of that link: for we can easily imagine a statement that, though true, is
beyond our power to establish as true. A third major account of truth is
James’s pragmatic theory. As we have just seen, the verificationist selects a
prominent property of truth and considers it to be the essence of truth.
Similarly the pragmatist focuses on another important characteristic namely, that true beliefs are a good basis
for action and takes this to be the very
nature of truth. True assumptions are said to be, by definition, those that
provoke actions with desirable results. Again we have an account with a single
attractive explanatory feature. But again the central objection is that the
relationship it postulates between truth and its alleged analysans in this case, utility is implausibly close. Granted, true beliefs
tend to foster success. But often actions based on true beliefs lead to
disaster, while false assumptions, by pure chance, produce wonderful results.
One of the few fairly uncontroversial facts about truth is that the proposition
that snow is white is true if and only if snow is white, the proposition that
lying is wrong is true if and only if lying is wrong, and so on. Traditional
theories of truth acknowledge this fact but regard it as insufficient and, as
we have seen, inflate it with some further principle of the form ‘X is true if
and only if X has property P’ such as corresponding to reality, verifiability,
or being suitable as a basis for action, which is supposed to specify what
truth is. A collection of radical alternatives to the traditional theories
results from denying the need for any such further specification. For example,
one might suppose with Ramsey, Ayer, and Strawson that the basic theory of
truth contains nothing more than equivalences of the form, ‘The proposition
that p is true if and only if p’ excluding instantiation by sentences such as
‘This proposition is not true’ that generate contradiction. This so-called
deflationary theory is best presented following Quine in conjunction with an
account of the raison d’être of our notion of truth: namely, that its function
is not to describe propositions, as one might naively infer from its syntactic
form, but rather to enable us to construct a certain type of generalization.
For example, ‘What Einstein said is true’ is intuitively equivalent to the
infinite conjunction ‘If Einstein said that nothing goes faster than light,
then nothing goes faster than light; and if Einstein said truth truth 930 930 that nuclear weapons should never be
built, then nuclear weapons should never be built; . . . and so on.’ But
without a truth predicate we could not capture this statement. The deflationist
argues, moreover, that all legitimate uses of the truth predicate including those in science, logic, semantics,
and metaphysics are simply displays of
this generalizing function, and that the equivalence schema is just what is
needed to explain that function. Within the deflationary camp there are various
competing proposals. According to Frege’s socalled redundancy theory,
corresponding instances of ‘It is true that p’ and ‘p’ have exactly the same
meaning, whereas the minimalist theory assumes merely that such propositions
are necessarily equivalent. Other deflationists are skeptical about the
existence of propositions and therefore take sentences to be the basic vehicles
of truth. Thus the disquotation theory supposes that truth is captured by the
disquotation principle, ‘p’ is true if and only if p’. More ambitiously, Tarski
does not regard the disquotation principle, also known as Tarski’s T schema, as
an adequate theory in itself, but as a specification of what any adequate
definition must imply. His own account shows how to give an explicit definition
of truth for all the sentences of certain formal languages in terms of the
referents of their primitive names and predicates. This is known as the
semantic theory of truth. .
Turing: Grice: “While not a philosopher, Turing’s thought
experiment is about the ‘conceptual analysis’ of ‘thought’” --similar to a
Griceian machine -- a machine, an
abstract automaton or imagined computer consisting of a finite automaton
operating an indefinitely long storage tape. The finite automaton provides the
computing power of the machine. The tape is used for input, output, and
calculation workspace; in the case of the universal Turing machine, it also
specifies another Turing machine. Initially, only a finite number of squares of
the tape are marked with symbols, while the rest are blank. The finite
automaton part of the machine has a finite number of internal states and
operates discretely, at times t % 0, 1, 2, . . . . At each time-step the
automaton examines the tape square under its tape head, possibly changes what
is there, moves the tape left or right, and then changes its internal state.
The law governing this sequence of actions is deterministic and is defined in a
state table. For each internal state and each tape symbol or blank under the
tape head, the state table describes the tape action performed by the machine
and gives the next internal state of the machine. Since a machine has only a
finite number of internal states and of tape symbols, the state table of a
machine is finite in length and can be stored on a tape. There is a universal
Turing machine Mu that can simulate every Turing machine including itself: when
the state table of any machine M is written on the tape of Mu, the universal
machine Mu will perform the same input-output computation that M performs. Mu
does this by using the state table of M to calculate M’s complete history for
any given input. Turing machines may be thought of as conceptual devices for
enumerating the elements of an infinite set e.g., the theorems of a formal
language, or as decision machines e.g., deciding of any truth-functional
formula whether it is a tautology. A. M. Turing showed that there are
welldefined logical tasks that cannot be carried out by any machine; in
particular, no machine can solve the halting problem. Turing’s definition of a
machine was theoretical; it was not a practical specification for a machine.
After the modern electronic computer was invented, he proposed a test for
judging whether there is a computer that is behaviorally equivalent to a human
in reasoning and intellectual creative power. The Turing test is a “black box”
type of experiment that Turing proposed as a way of deciding whether a computer
can think. Two rooms are fitted with the same input-output equipment going to
an outside experimenter. A person is placed in one room and a programmed
electronic computer in the other, each in communication with the experimenter.
By issuing instructions and asking questions, the experimenter tries to decide
which room has the computer and which the human. If the experimenter cannot
tell, that outcome is strong evidence that the computer can think as well as
the person. More directly, it shows that the computer and the human are
equivalent for all the behaviors tested. Since the computer is a finite
automaton, perhaps the most significant test task is that of doing creative mathematics
about the non-enumerable infinite.
turnbull, G.: moral sense philosopher and educational theorist.
He was briefly a philosophy regent at Aberdeen and a teacher of Reid. His
Principles of Moral and Christian Philosophy 1740 and Discourse upon the Nature
and Origin of Moral and Civil Laws 1741 show him as the most systematic of
those who aimed to recast moral philosophy on a Newtonian model, deriving moral
laws “experimentally” from human psychology. In A Treatise on Ancient Painting
1740, Observations Upon Liberal Education 1742, and some smaller works, he
extolled history and the arts as propaedeutic to the teaching of virtue and
natural religion.
Grice’s
Martian Chronicles -- Twin-Earth – as
opposed to Mars -- a fictitious planet first visited by Hilary Putnam in a
thought experiment inspired by H. P. Grice in “Some remarks about the senses”
-- designed to show, among other things, that “ ‘meanings’ just ain’t in the
head” “The Meaning of ‘Meaning’,” 5. Twin-Earth is exactly like Earth with one
notable exception: ponds, rivers, and ice trays on Twin-Earth contain, not H2O,
but XYZ, a liquid superficially indistinguishable from water but with a
different chemical constitution. According to Putnam, although some inhabitants
of Twin-Earth closely resemble inhabitants of Earth, ‘water’, when uttered by a
Twin-Earthling, does not mean water. Water is H2O, and, on Twin-Earth, the word
‘water’ designates a different substance, XYZ, Twin-water. The moral drawn by
Putnam is that the meanings of at least some of our words, and the significance
of some of our thoughts, depend, in part, on how things stand outside our
heads. Two “molecular duplicates,” two agents with qualitatively similar mental
lives, might mean very different things by their utterances and think very
different thoughts. Although Twin-Earth has become a popular stopping-off place
for philosophers en route to theories of meaning and mental content, others
regard Twin-Earth as hopelessly remote, doubting that useful conclusions can be
drawn about our Earthly circumstances from research conducted there. Suppose that long-awaited invasion of the
Martians takes place, that they turn out to be friendly creatures and teach us
their language. We get on all right, except that we find no verb in their
language which unquestionably corresponds to our verb “see.” Instead we find
two verbs which we decide to render as “x” and “y”: we find that (in their
tongue) they speak of themselves as x-ing, and also as y-ing, things to be of
this and that color, size, and shape. Further, in physical appearance they are
more or less like ourselves, except that in their heads they have, one above
the other, two pairs of organs, not perhaps exactly like one another, but each
pair more or less like our eyes: each pair of organs is found to be sensitive
to light waves. It turns out that for them x-ing is dependent on the operation
of the upper organs, and y-ing on that of the lower organs. The question which
it seems natural to ask is this: Are x-ing and y-ing both cases of seeing, the
difference between them being that x-ing is seeing with the upper organs, and
y-ing is seeing with the lower organs? Or alternatively, do one or both of
these accomplishments constitute the exercise of a new sense, other than that
of sight? If we adopt, to distinguish the senses, a combination of suggestion
(I) with one or both of suggestions (III) or (IV), the answer seems clear: both
x-ing and y-ing are seeing, with different pairs of organs. But is the question
really to be settled so easily? Would we not in fact want to ask whether x-ing
something to be round was like y-ing it to be round, or whether when something
x-ed blue to them this was like or unlike its y-ing blue to them? If in answer
to such questions as these they said, “Oh no, there’s all the difference in the
world!” then I think we should be inclined to say that either x-ing or y-ing
(if not both) must be something other than seeing: we might of course be quite
unable to decide which (if either) was seeing. (I am aware that here those
whose approach is more Wittgensteinian than my own might complain that unless
something more can be said about how the difference between x-ing and y-ing
might “come out” or show itself in publicly observable phenomena, then the
claim by the supposed Martians that x-ing and y-ing are different would be one
of which nothing could be made, which would leave one at a loss how to
understand it. First, I am not convinced of the need for “introspectible”
differences to show themselves in the way this approach demands (I shall not
discuss this point further); second, I think that if I have to meet this
demand, I can. One can suppose that one or more of these Martians acquired the
use of the lower y-ing organs at some comparatively late date in their careers,
and that at the same time (perhaps for experimental purposes) the operation of
the upper x-ing organs was inhibited. One might now be ready to allow that a
difference between Some Remarks about the Senses 47 x-ing and y-ing would have
shown itself if in such a situation the creatures using their y-ing organs for
the first time were unable straightaway, without any learning process, to use
their “color”-words fluently and correctly to describe what they detected
through the use of those organs.) It might be argued at this point that we have
not yet disposed of the idea that the senses can be distinguished by an amalgam
of suggestions (I), (III), and (IV); for it is not clear that in the example of
the Martians the condition imposed by suggestion (I) is fulfilled. The thesis,
it might be said, is only upset if x-ing and y-ing are accepted as being the
exercise of different senses; and if they are, then the Martians’ color-words
could be said to have a concealed ambiguity. Much as “sweet” in English may
mean “sweet-smelling” or “sweet-tasting,” so “blue” in Martian may mean
“blue-x-ing” or “blue-y-ing.” But if this is so, then the Martians after all do
not detect by x-ing just those properties of things which they detect by y-ing.
To this line of argument there are two replies: (1) The defender of the thesis
is in no position to use this argument; for he cannot start by making the
question whether x-ing and y-ing are exercises of the same sense turn on the
question (inter alia) whether or not a single group of characteristics is
detected by both, and then make the question of individuation of the group turn
on the question whether putative members of the group are detected by one, or
by more than one, sense. He would be saying in effect, “Whether, in x-ing and
y-ing, different senses are exercised depends (inter alia) on whether the same
properties are detected by x-ing as by y-ing; but whether a certain x-ed
property is the same as a certain y-ed property depends on whether x-ing and
y-ing are or are not the exercise of a single sense.” This reply seems fatal.
For the circularity could only be avoided by making the question whether “blue”
in Martian names a single property depend either on whether the kinds of
experience involved in x-ing and y-ing are different, which would be to
reintroduce suggestion (II), or on whether the mechanisms involved in x-ing and
y-ing are different (in this case whether the upper organs are importantly
unlike the lower organs): and to adopt this alternative would, I think, lead to
treating the differentiation of the senses as being solely a matter of their
mechanisms, thereby making suggestion (I) otiose. (2) Independently of its
legitimacy or illegitimacy in the present context, we must reject the idea that
if it is accepted that in x-ing and y-ing different senses are being exercised,
then Martian color-words will be ambiguous. For ex hypothesi there will be a
very close correlation between things x-ing blue and their y-ing blue, far
closer 48 H. P. Grice than that between things smelling sweet and their tasting
sweet. This being so, it is only to be expected that x-ing and y-ing should
share the position of arbiters concerning the color of things: that is, “blue”
would be the name of a single property, determinable equally by x-ing and y-ing.
After all, is this not just like the actual position with regard to shape,
which is doubly determinable, by sight and by touch? While I would not wish to
quarrel with the main terms of this second reply, I should like briefly to
indicate why I think that this final quite natural comparison with the case of
shape will not do. It is quite conceivable that the correlation between x-ing
and y-ing , in the case supposed, might be close enough to ensure that Martian
color-words designated doubly determinable properties, and yet that this
correlation should break down in a limited class of cases: for instance, owing
to some differences between the two pairs of organs, objects which transmitted
light of a particular wavelength might (in standard conditions) x blue but y
black. I suggest, then, that given the existence of an object which, for the
Martians, standardly x-ed blue but y-ed black (its real color being
undecidable), no conclusion could be drawn to the effect that other objects do,
or could as a matter of practiSome Remarks about the Senses 51 cal possibility
be made to, x one way and y another way either in respect of color or in
respect of some other feature within the joint province of x-ing and y-ing.
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Some remarks about the senses,” in WoW --. Coady, “The
senses of the Martians.”
tychism: from Grecian tyche, ‘chance’, Peirce’s doctrine that
there is absolute chance in the universe and its fundamental laws are
probabilistic and inexact. Peirce’s tychism is part of his evolutionary
cosmology, according to which all regularities of nature are products of growth
and development, i.e., results of evolution. The laws of nature develop over
time and become increasingly rigid and exact; the apparently deterministic laws
of physics are limiting cases of the basic, probabilistic laws. Underlying all
other laws is “the tendency of all things to take habits”; Peirce calls this
the Law of Habit. In his cosmology his tychism is associated with synechism,
the doctrine of the continuity of nature. His synechism involves the doctrine
of the continuity of mind and matter; Peirce sometimes expressed this view by
saying that “matter is effete mind.”
Grice’s “The
Three-Year-Old’s Guide to Russell’s Theory of Types,” with an advice to parents
by P. F. Starwson -- type theory,
broadly, any theory according to which the things that exist fall into natural,
perhaps mutually exclusive, categories or types. In most modern discussions,
‘type theory’ refers to the theory of logical types first sketched by Russell
in The Principles of Mathematics 3. It is a theory of logical types insofar as
it purports only to classify things into the most general categories that must
be presupposed by an adequate logical theory. Russell proposed his theory in
response to his discovery of the now-famous paradox that bears his name. The
paradox is this. Common sense suggests that some classes are members of
themselves e.g., the class of all classes, while others are not e.g., the class
of philosophers. Let R be the class whose membership consists of exactly those
classes of the latter sort, i.e., those that are not members of themselves. Is
R a member of itself? If so, then it is a member of the class of all classes
that are not members of themselves, and hence is not a member of itself. If, on
the other hand, it is not a member of itself, then it satisfies its own
membership conditions, and hence is a member of itself after all. Either way
there is a contradiction. The source of the paradox, Russell suggested, is the
assumption that classes and their members form a single, homogeneous logical
type. To the contrary, he proposed that the logical universe is stratified into
a regimented hierarchy of types. Individuals constitute the lowest type in the
hierarchy, type 0. For purposes of exposition, individuals can be taken to be
ordinary objects like chairs and persons. Type 1 consists of classes of
individuals, type 2 of classes of classes of individuals, type 3 classes of
classes of classes of individuals, and so on. Unlike the homogeneous universe,
then, in the type hierarchy the members of a given class must all be drawn from
a single logical type n, and the class itself must reside in the next higher
type n ! 1. Russell’s sketch in the Principles differs from this account in certain
details. Russell’s paradox cannot arise in this conception of the universe of
classes. Because the members of a class must all be of the same logical type,
there is no such class as R, whose definition cuts across all types. Rather,
there is only, for each type n, the class Rn of all non-self-membered classes
of that type. Since Rn itself is of type n ! 1, the paradox breaks down: from
the assumption that Rn is not a member of itself as in fact it is not in the
type hierarchy, it no longer follows that it satisfies its own membership
conditions, since those conditions apply only to objects of type n. Most formal
type theories, including Russell’s own, enforce the class membership
restrictions of simple type theory syntactically such that a can be asserted to
be a member of b only if b is of the next higher type than a. In such theories,
the definition of R, hence the paradox itself, cannot even be expressed.
Numerous paradoxes remain unscathed by the simple type hierarchy. Of these, the
most prominent are the semantic paradoxes, so called because they explicitly
involve semantic notions like truth, as in the following version of the liar
paradox. Suppose Epimenides asserts that all the propositions he asserts today
are false; suppose also that that is the only proposition he asserts today. It
follows immediately that, under those conditions, the proposition he asserts is
true if and only if it is false. To address such paradoxes, Russell was led to
the more refined and substantially more complicated system known as ramified
type theory, developed in detail in his 8 paper “Mathematical Logic as Based on
the Theory of Types.” In the ramified theory, propositions and properties or
propositional functions, in Russell’s jargon come to play the central roles in the
type-theoretic universe. Propositions are best construed as the metaphysical
and semantical counterparts of sentences
what sentences express and
properties as the counterparts of “open sentences” like ‘x is a philosopher’
that contain a variable ‘x’ in place of a noun phrase. To distinguish
linguistic expressions from their semantic counterparts, the property expressed
by, say, ‘x is a philosopher’, will be denoted by ‘x ^ is a philosopher’, and
the proposition expressed by ‘Aristotle is a philosopher’ will be denoted by
‘Aristotle is a philosopher’. A property . . .x ^ . . . is said to be true of
an individual a if . . . a . . . is a true proposition, and false of a if . . .
a . . . is a false proposition where ‘. . . a . . .’ is the result of replacing
‘x ^ ’ with ‘a’ in ‘. . . x ^ . . .’. So, e.g., x ^ is a philosopher is true of
Aristotle. The range of significance of a property P is the collection of
objects of which P is true or false. a is a possible argument for P if it is in
P’s range of significance. In the ramified theory, the hierarchy of classes is
supplanted by a hierarchy of properties: first, properties of individuals i.e.,
properties whose range of significance is restricted to individuals, then
properties of properties of individuals, and so on. Parallel to the simple
theory, then, the type of a property must exceed the type of its possible
arguments by one. Thus, Russell’s paradox with R now in the guise of the
property x ^ is a property that is not true of itself is avoided along analogous lines. Following
the mathematician Henri Poincaré,
Russell traced the type theory type theory 935
935 source of the semantic paradoxes to a kind of illicit
self-reference. So, for example, in the liar paradox, Epimenides ostensibly
asserts a proposition p about all propositions, p itself among them, namely
that they are false if asserted by him today. p thus refers to itself in the
sense that it or more exactly, the
sentence that expresses it quantifies
over i.e., refers generally to all or some of the elements of a collection of
entities among which p itself is included. The source of semantic paradox thus
isolated, Russell formulated the vicious circle principle VCP, which proscribes
all such self-reference in properties and propositions generally. The liar
proposition p and its ilk were thus effectively banished from the realm of
legitimate propositions and so the semantic paradoxes could not arise. Wedded
to the restrictions of simple type theory, the VCP generates a ramified
hierarchy based on a more complicated form of typing. The key notion is that of
an object’s order. The order of an individual, like its type, is 0. However,
the order of a property must exceed the order not only of its possible
arguments, as in simple type theory, but also the orders of the things it
quantifies over. Thus, type 1 properties like x ^ is a philosopher and x ^ is
as wise as all other philosophers are first-order properties, since they are
true of and, in the second instance, quantify over, individuals only. Properties
like these whose order exceeds the order of their possible arguments by one are
called predicative, and are of the lowest possible order relative to their
range of significance. Consider, by contrast, the property call it Q x ^ has
all the first-order properties of a great philosopher. Like those above, Q also
is a property of individuals. However, since Q quantifies over first-order
properties, by the VDP, it cannot be counted among them. Accordingly, in the
ramified hierarchy, Q is a second-order property of individuals, and hence
non-predicative or impredicative. Like Q, the property x ^ is a first-order
property of all great philosophers is also second-order, since its range of
significance consists of objects of order 1 and it quantifies only over objects
of order 0; but since it is a property of first-order properties, it is
predicative. In like manner it is possible to define third-order properties of
individuals, third-order properties of first-order properties, third-order
properties of second-order properties of individuals, third-order properties of
secondorder properties of first-order properties, and then, in the same
fashion, fourth-order properties, fifth-order properties, and so on ad
infinitum. A serious shortcoming of ramified type theory, from Russell’s
perspective, is that it is an inadequate foundation for classical mathematics.
The most prominent difficulty is that many classical theorems appeal to
definitions that, though consistent, violate the VCP. For instance, a wellknown
theorem of real analysis asserts that every bounded set of real numbers has a
least upper bound. In the ramified theory, real numbers are identified with
certain predicative properties of rationals. Under such an identification, the
usual procedure is to define the least upper bound of a bounded set S of reals
to be the property call it b some real number in S is true of x ^ , and then
prove that this property is itself a real number with the requisite
characteristics. However, b quantifies over the real numbers. Hence, by the
VCP, b cannot itself be taken to be a real number: although of the same type as
the reals, and although true of the right things, b must be assigned a higher
order than the reals. So, contrary to the classical theorem, S fails to have a
least upper bound. Russell introduced a special axiom to obviate this
difficulty: the axiom of reducibility. Reducibility says, in effect, that for
any property P, there is a predicative property Q that is true of exactly the
same things as P. Reducibility thus assures that there is a predicative
property bH true of the same rational numbers as b. Since the reals are
predicative, hence of the same order as bH, it turns out that bH is a real
number, and hence that S has a least upper bound after all, as required by the
classical theorem. The general role of reducibility is thus to undo the
draconian mathematical effects of ramification without undermining its capacity
to fend off the semantic paradoxes.
token-type
distinction – Grice: “Strictly, they
are not antonyms – and token is too English!” Grice: “Token is cognate with
‘teach,’ a Graeco-Roman thing, cfr. insignum – insignare – to teach is to show,
almost, with an m-intention behind.” -- first the token, then the type – if
necessary; “After all a type is a set of tokens” -- used by Grice: there’s a
type of an utterer, but there’s the individual utterer: In symbols, “u” is an
individual utterer, say, Grice. “U” is a type of utterer, say Oxonian
philosophy dons. Aas drawn by Peirce, the contrast between a category and a
member of that category. An individual or token is said to exemplify a type; it
possesses the property that characterizes that type. In philosophy this
distinction is often applied to linguistic expressions and to mental states,
but it can be applied also to objects, events, properties, and states of
affairs. Related to it are the distinctions between type and token
individuation and between qualitative and numerical identity. Distinct tokens
of the same type, such as two ants, may be qualitatively identical but cannot
be numerically identical. Irrespective of the controversial metaphysical view
that every individual has an essence, a type to which it belongs essentially,
every individual belongs to many types, although for a certain theoretical or
practical purpose it may belong to one particularly salient type e.g., the
entomologist’s Formicidae or the picnicker’s buttinsky. The typetoken
distinction as applied in the philosophy of language marks the difference
between linguistic expressions, such as words and sentences, which are the
subject of linguistics, and the products of acts of writing or speaking the
subject of speech act theory. Confusing the two can lead to conflating matters
of speaker meaning withmatters of word or sentence meaning as noted by Grice.
An expression is a linguistic type and can be used over and over, whereas a
token of a type can be produced only once, though of course it may be
reproduced copied. A writer composes an essay a type and produces a manuscript
a token, of which there might be many copies more tokens. A token of a type is
not the same as an occurrence of a type. In the previous sentence there are two
occurrences of the word ‘type’; in each inscription of that sentence, there are
two tokens of that word. In philosophy of mind the typetoken distinction
underlies the contrast between two forms of physicalism, the typetype identity
theory or type physicalism and the tokentoken identity theory or token
physicalism.
uncertainty: one of those negativisims by Grice – cfr.
‘non-certainty’ -- v. certum. It may be held that ‘uncertain’ is wrong. Grice
is certain that p. It is not the case that Grice is certain that p.
universale: Grice: “Very Ciceronian – not found in Aristotle.” --
Like ‘qualia,’ which is the plural for ‘quale,’ ‘universalia’ is the plural for
‘universale.’ The totum for Grice on “all” -- This is a Gricism. It all started
with arbor porphyriana. It is supposed to translate Aristotle’s “to kath’olou”
(which happens to be one of the categories in Kant, “alleheit,” and which
Aristotle contrasts with “to kath’ekastou,” (which Kant has as a category,
SINGULARITAS. For a nominalist, any predicate is a ‘name,’ hence ‘nominalism.’
Opposite ‘realism.’ “Nominalism” is actually a misnomer. The opposite of realism
is anti-realism. We need something like ‘universalism,’ (he who believes in the
existence, not necessary ‘reality’ of a universal) and a ‘particularist,’ or
‘singularist,’ who does not. Note that the opposite of ‘particularism,’ is
‘totalism.’ (Totum et pars). Grice holds a set-theoretical approach to the
universalium. Grice is willing to provide always a set-theoretical
extensionalist (in terms of predicate) and an intensionalist variant in terms
of property and category. Grice explicitly uses ‘X’ for utterance-type
(WOW:118), implying a distinction with the utterance-token. Grice gets engaged
in a metabolical debate concerning the reductive analysis of what an
utterance-type means in terms of a claim to the effect that, by uttering
x, an utterance-token of utterance-type X, the utterer means that p. The implicaturum
is x (utterance-token). Grice is not enamoured with the type/token or
token/type distinction. His thoughts on logical form are provocative. f
you cannot put it in logical form, it is not worth saying. Strawson
infamously reacted with a smile. Oh, no: if you CAN put it in logical form, it
is not worth saying. Grice refers to the type-token distinction when he uses x
for token and X for type. Since Bennett cares to call Grice a
meaning-nominalist we should not care about the type X anyway. He expands on
this in Retrospective Epilogue. Grice should have payed more attention to the
distinction seeing that it was Ogdenian. A common mode of estimating the
amount of matter in a printed book is to count the number of words. There will
ordinarily be about twenty thes on a page, and, of course, they count as twenty
words. In another use of the word word, however, there is but one word the in
the English language; and it is impossible that this word should lie visibly on
a page, or be heard in any voice. Such a Form, Peirce, as cited by Ogden and
Richards, proposes to term a type. A single object such as this or that word on
a single line of a single page of a single copy of a book, Peirce ventures to
call a token. In order that a type may be used, it has to be embodied in a
token which shall be a sign of the type, and thereby of the object the type
signifies, and Grice followed suit. Refs.: Some of the sources are given under
‘abstractum.’ Also under ‘grecianism,’ since Grice was keen on exploring what
Aristotle has to say about this in Categoriae, due to his joint research with Austin,
Code, Friedman, and Strawson. Grice also has a specific Peirceian essay on the
type-token distinction. BANC.
universalis: Grice – “A Ciceronian technicism, not found in
Aristotle. -- (‘the altogether nice girl’) dictum de omni et nullo, also dici
de omni et nullo Latin, ‘said of all and none’, two principles that were
supposed by medieval logicians to underlie all valid syllogisms. Dictum de omni
applies most naturally to universal affirmative propositions, maintaining that
in such a proposition, whatever falls under the subject term also falls under
the predicate term. Thus, in ‘Every whale is a mammal’, whatever is included under
‘whale’ is included under ‘mammal’. Dictum de nullo applies to universal
negative propositions, such as ‘No whale is a lizard’, maintaining that
whatever falls under the subject term does not fall under the predicate term. SYLLOGISM. W.E.M. Diderot, Denis 171384, philosopher, Encyclopedist, dramatist,
novelist, and art critic, a champion of Enlightenment values. He is known
primarily as general editor of the Encyclopedia 174773, an analytical and
interpretive compendium of eighteenth-century science and technology. A friend
of Rousseau and Condillac, Diderot tr. Shaftesbury’s Inquiry Concerning Virtue
1745 into . Revealing Lucretian affinities Philosophical Thoughts, 1746, he
assailed Christianity in The Skeptics’ Walk 1747 and argued for a materialistic
and evolutionary universe Letter on the Blind, 1749; this led to a short
imprisonment. Diderot wrote mediocre bourgeois comedies; some bleak fiction The
Nun, 1760; and two satirical dialogues, Rameau’s Nephew 1767 and Jacques the
Fatalist 176584, his masterpieces. He innovatively theorized on drama Discourse
on Dramatic Poetry, 1758 and elevated art criticism to a literary genre Salons
in Grimm’s Literary Correspondence. At Catherine II’s invitation, Diderot
visited Saint Petersburg in 1773 and planned the creation of a Russian .
Promoting science, especially biology and chemistry, Diderot unfolded a
philosophy of nature inclined toward monism. His works include physiological
investigations, Letter on the Deaf and Dumb 1751 and Elements of Physiology 177480;
a sensationalistic epistemology, On the Interpretation of Nature 1745; an
aesthetic, Essays on Painting 1765; a materialistic philosophy of science,
D’Alembert’s Dream 1769; an anthropology, Supplement to the Voyage of
Bougainville 1772; and an anti-behavioristic Refutation of Helvétius’ Work “On
Man” 177380.
universalisierung:
Grice: “Ironically, the Dutch so careful with
their lingo, this is vague, in that the universe is not a pluriverse.” -- While
Grice uses ‘universal,’ he means like Russell, the unnecessary implication of
‘every.’ Oddly, Kant does not relate this –ung with the first of his three
categories under ‘quantitas,’ the universal. But surely they are related.
Problem is that Kant wasn’t aware because he kept moving from the Graeco-Roman
classical vocabulary to the Hun. Thus, Kant has “Allheit,” which he renders in
Latinate as “Universitas,” and “Totalität,” gehört in der Kategorienlehre des
Philosophen Immanuel Kant zu den reinen Verstandesbegriffen, d. h. zu den
Elementen des Verstandes, welche dem Menschen bereits a priori, also unabhängig
von der sinnlichen Erfahrung gegeben sind. “Allheit” wird wie Einheit und
Vielheit den Kategorien der “Quantität” zugeordnet und entspricht den Einzelnen
Urteilen (Urteil hier im Sinn von 'Aussage über die Wirklichkeit') in der Form
„Ein S ist P“, also z. B. „Immanuel Kant ist ein Philosoph“. Sie wird von Kant
definiert als „die Vielheit als Einheit betrachtet“ (KrV, B 497 f.)[3]. Siehe
auch Transzendentale Analytik Weblinks. Allheit – Bedeutungserklärungen,
Wortherkunft, Synonyme, Übersetzungen Einzelnachweise Immanuel Kant: Kritik der reinen Vernunft.
Reclam, Stuttgart 1966, ISBN 3-15-006461-9.
Peter Kunzmann, Franz-Peter Burkard, Franz Wiedmann: dtv-Atlas zur
Philosophie. dtv, München 1991, ISBN 3-423-03229-4, S. 136 ff. Zitiert nach Arnim Regenbogen, Uwe Meyer
(Hrsg.): Wörterbuch der Philosophischen Begriffe. Meiner, Hamburg 2005, ISBN
3-7873-1738-4: Allheit Kategorie: Ontologie. Referred to by Grice in his
“Method,” – “A requisite for a maxim to enter my manual, which I call the
Immanuel, is that it should be universalizable. Die Untersuchung zur
»Universalisierung in der Ethik« greift eine Problematik auf, die für eine
Reihe der prominentesten Ethikentwürfe der Gegenwart sowohl des deutschsprachigen
wie des angelsächsischen Raumes zentral ist, nämlich ob der normative
Rationalitätsanspruch, den ethische Argumentationen erheben, auf eine dem
wissenschaftlichen Anspruch der deskriptiven Gesetzeswissenschaften
vergleichbare Weise eingelöst werden kann, nämlich durch Verallgemeinerungs-
oder Universalisierungsprinzipien. universalizability
Ethics The idea that moral judgments should be universalizable can be traced to
the Golden Rule and Kant’s ethics. In the twentieth century it was elaborated
by Hare and became a major thesis of his prescriptivism. The principle states
that all moral judgments are universalizable in the sense that if it is right
for a particular person A to do an action X, then it must likewise be right to
do X for any person exactly like A, or like A in the relevant respects.
Furthermore, if A is right in doing X in this situation, then it must be right
for A to do X in other relevantly similar situations. Hare takes this feature
to be an essential feature of moral judgments. An ethical statement is the
issuance of a universal prescription. Universalizability is not the same as
generality, for a moral judgment can be highly specific and detailed and need
not be general or simple. The universalizability principle enables Hare to avoid
the charge of irrationality that is usually lodged against non-cognitivism, to
which his prescriptivism belongs, and his theory is thus a great improvement on
emotivism. “I have been maintaining that the meaning of the word ‘ought’ and
other moral words is such that a person who uses them commits himself thereby
to a universal rule. This is the thesis of universalizability.” Hare, Freedom
and Reason.
unstructured:
Grice: “Paget was able to structure compositionality with his hands!” -- one of
those negativisms of Grice (cfr. ‘non-structured’). Surely Grice cared a hoot
for French anthropological structuralism! So he has the ‘unstructured’ followed
by the structured. A handwave is unstructured, meaning syntactically
unstructured, and in it you have all the enigma of reason resolved. By waving
his hand, U means that SUBJECT: the emissor, copula IS, predicate: A KNOWER OF
THE ROUTE, or ABOUT TO LEAVE the emissor.There is a lot of structure in the
soul of the emissor. So apply this to what Grice calls a ‘soul-to-soul
transfer’ to which he rightly reduces communication. Even if it is n
unstructured communication device, and maybe a ‘one-off’ one, to use
Blackburn’s vulgarism, we would have the three types of correspondence of
Grice’s Semantic Triangle obtaining. First, the psychophysical. The emissor
knows the route, and he shows it. And he wants the emissee to ‘catch’ or get
the emissor’s drift. It is THAT route which he knows. So the TWO psychophysical
correspondences obtain. Then there are the two psychosemiotic correspondences.
The emissor intends that the emissor will recognise the handwave as a signal
that he, the emissor, knows the route. As for the emissee’s psychosemiotic
correspondence: he better realise it is THAT route – to Banbury, surely, with
bells in his shoes, as Grice’s mother would sing to him. And then we have the
two semio-physical correspondences. If the emissor DOES know the route (and he
is not lying, or rather, he is not mistaken about it), then that’s okay. Many
people say or signal that they know because they feel ashamed to admit their
ignorance. So it is very expectable, outside Oxford, to have someone waving
meaning that he knows the route, when he doesn’t. This is surely non-natural,
because it’s Kiparsky-non-factive. Waving the hand thereby communicating that
he knows the route does not entail that he knows the route (as ‘spots’ do
entail measles). From the emissee’s point of view, provided the emissor knows
the route and shows it, the emissee will understand, hopefully, and feel assured
that the emissor will hopefully reach the destination, Banbury, surely, safely
enough.
uptake: used
by Grice slightly different from Austin. Austin: “The performance of an
illocutionary act involves the securing of uptake.” “I distinguish some senses of
consequences and effects, especially three senses in which effects can come in
even with illocutionary acts, viz. securing uptake, taking effect, and inviting
a response.” “Comparing
stating to what we have said about the illocu- tionary act, it is an act
to which, just as much as to other illocutionary acts, it is essential to
‘secure uptake’ : the doubt about whether I stated something if it was
not heard or understood is just the same as the doubt about whether
I warned sotto voce or protested if someone did not take it as a protest,
&c. And statements do ‘take effect’ just as much as ‘namings’, say:
if I have stated something, then that commits me to other
statements: other statements made by me will be in order or out of
order.” Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Verstehen and uptake.”
urmsonianism.
Who other than Urmson would come up with a counter-example to the sufficiency
of Grice’s analysis of an act of communication. In a case of bribery, the
response or effect in the emittee is NOT meant to be recognised. So we need a
further restriction unless we want to say that the briber means that his
emittee recognise the ‘gift’ as a meta-bribe. Refs.: Urmson, “Introduction” to
Austin’s Philosophical Papers, cited by Grice. Urmson, Introduction to Austin’s
How to do things with words, cited by Grice. Urmson on Grice, “The
Independent.” Urmson on pragmatics.
urmson’s
bribe: Urmson’s use of the bribe is
‘accidental.’ What Urmson is getting at is that if the briber intends the bribe
acts as a cause to effect a response, even a cognitive one, in the bribe, the
propositional complexum, “This is a bribe,” should not necessarily be
communicated. It is amazing how Grice changed the example into one about
physical action. They seem different. On the other hand, Grice would not have
cared to credit Urmson had it not believed it worth knowing that the criticism
arose within the Play Group (Grice admired Urmson). In his earlier “Meaning,”
Grice presents his own self-criticisms to arrive at a more refined analysis.
But in “Utterer’s meaning and intention,” when it comes to the SUFFICIENCY,
it’s all about other people: notably Urmson and Strawson. Grice cites Stampe
before Strawson, but many ignore Stampe on the basis that Strawson does not
credit him, and there is no reason why he should have been aware of it. But
Stampe was at Oxford at the time so this is worth noting. It has to be
emphasised that the author list is under ‘sufficiency.’ Under necessity, Grice
does not credit the source of the objections, so we can assume it is Grice
himself, as he had presented criticisms to his own view within the same
‘Meaning.’ It is curious that Grice loved Stampe. Grice CHANGED Urmon’s
example, and was unable to provide a specific scenario to Strawson’s alleged
counterexample, because Strawson is vague himself. But Stampe’s, Grice left
unchanged. It seems few Oxonian philosohpers of Grice’s playgroup had his
analytic acumen. Consider his sophisticated account of ‘meaning.’ It’s
different if you are a graduate student from the New World, and you have to
prove yourself intelligent. But for Grice’s playgroup companion, only three or
four joined in the analysis. The first is Urmson. The second is Strawson. The
case by Urmson involved a tutee offering to buy Gardiner an expensive dinner,
hoping that Gardiner will give him permission for an over-night visit to
London. Gardiner knows that his tutee wants his permission. The
appropriate analysans for "By offering to buy Gardiner an expensive
dinner, the tuttee means that Gardiner should give him permission for an
overnight stay in London" are fulfilled: (1) The tutee offers to buy
Gardiner an expensive dinner with the intention of producing a certain response
on the part of Gardiner (2) The tutee intends that Gardiner should recognize
(know, think) that the tutee is offering to buy him an expensive dinner with
the intention of producing this response; (3) The tutee intends that Gardiners
recognition (thought) that the tutee has the intention mentioned in (2) should
be at least part of Gardiners reason for producing the response mentioned. If
in general to specify in (i) the nature of an intended response is to specify
what was meant, it should be correct not only to say that by offering to buy
Gardiner an expensive dinner, the tutee means that Gardiner is to give him
permission for an overnight stay in London, but also to say that he meas that
Gardiner should (is to) give him permission for an over-night visit to London.
But in fact one would not wish to say either of these things; only that the tutee
meant Gardiner to give him permission. A restriction seems to be required, and
one which might serve to eliminate this range of counterexamples can be
identified from a comparison of two scenarios. Grice goes into a tobacconists
shop, ask for a packet of my favorite cigarettes, and when the unusually
suspicious tobacconist shows that he wants to see the color of my money before
he hands over the goods, I put down the price of the cigarettes on the counter.
Here nothing has been meant. Alternatively, Grice goes to his regular
tobacconist (from whom I also purchase other goods) for a packet of my regular
brand of Players Navy Cuts, the price of which is distinctive, say 43p. Grice
says nothing, but puts down 43p. The tobacconist recognizes my need, and hands
over the packet. Here, I think, by putting down 43p I meant something-Namesly,
that I wanted a packet of Players Navy Cuts. I have at the same time provided
an inducement. The distinguishing feature of the second example seems to be
that here the tobacconist recognized, and was intended to recognize, what he
was intended to do from my "utterance" (my putting down the money),
whereas in the first example this was not the case. Nor is it the case with
respect to Urmson’s case of the tutees attempt to bribe Gardiner. So one might
propose that the analysis of meaning be amended accordingly. U means something
by uttering x is true if: (i) U intends, by uttering x, to induce a certain
response in A (2) U intends A to recognize, at least in part from the utterance
of x, that U intends to produce that response (3) U intends the fulfillment of
the intention mentioned in (2) to be at least in part As reason for fulfilling
the intention mentioned in (i). This copes with Urmsons counterexample to
Grices proposal in the Oxford Philosophical Society talk involving the tutee
attempting to bribe Gardiner.
use: Grice: “I
would rephrase Vitter’s adage, ‘Don’t ask for the expression meaning, as for
the UTTERER’s meaning, if you have to axe at all!” -- while Grice uses ‘use,’ as
Ryle once told him, ‘you should use ‘usage, too.’ Parkinson was nearby. When
Warnock commissioned Parkinson to compile a couple of Oxonian essays on meaning
and communication, Parkinson unearthed the old symposium by Ryle and Findlay on
the matter. Typically, when Ryle reprinted it, he left Findlay out!
sender: Grice:
“Surely, if there is a ‘recipient,’ there must be a ‘sender.’” Grice: “I prefer
‘sender’ as correlative for ‘recipient,’ since there is an embedded
intentionality about it.” Cf. Sting, “Message in a bottle – sending out an S.
O. S.” – Grice: “Addresser and addressee sound otiose.” – Grice: “Then there’s
this jargon of the ‘target’ addressee’ – while we are in the metaphorical
mode!” -- emissor: utterer: cf.
emissum, emissor. Usually Homo sapiens sapiens – and usually Oxonian, the Homo
sapiens sapiens Grice interactes with. Sometimes tutees, sometimes tutor. There
is something dualistic about the ‘utterer.’ It is a vernacularism from English
‘out.’ So the French impressionists were into IM-pressing, out to in; the
German expressionists were into EX-pressing, in to out. Or ‘man’. The important
thing is for Grice to avoid ‘speaker.’ He notes that ‘utterance’ has a nice
fuzziness about it. He still notes that he is using ‘utter’ in a ‘perhaps artificial’
way. He was already wedded to ‘utter’ in
his talk for the Oxford Philosopical Society. Grice does not elaborate
much on general gestures or signals. His main example is a sort of handwave by
which the emissor communicates that either he knows the route or that he is
about to leave the addressee. Even this is complex. Let’s try to apply his
final version of communication to the hand-wave. The question of “Homo sapiens
sapiens” is an interesting one. Grice is all for ascribing predicates regarding
the soul to what he calls the ‘lower animals’. He is not ready to ascribe
emissor’s meaning to them. Why? Because of Schiffer! I mean, when it comes to
the conditions of necessity of the reductive analysis, he seems okay. When it
comes to the sufficiency, there are two types of objection. One by Urmson,
easily dismissed. The second, first by Stampe and Strawson, not so easily. But
Grice agrees to add a clause limiting intentions to be ‘in the open.’ Those who
do not have a philosophical background usually wonder about this. So for their
sake, it may be worth considering Grice’s synthetic a posteriori argument to
refuse an emissor other than a Homo sapiens sapiens to be able to ‘mean,’ if not
‘communicate,’ or ‘signify.’ There is an
objection which is not mentioned by his editors, which seems to Grice to be one
to which Grice must respond. The objection may be stated thus. One of the
leading strands in Grice’s reductive analysis of an emissor communicating that
p is that communication is not to be regarded exclusively, or even primarily,
as a ‘feature’ of emissors who use what philosophers of language call
‘language’ (Sprache, Taal, Langage, Linguaggio – to restrict to the
philosophical lexicon, cf. Plato’s Cratylus), and a fortiori of an emissor who
emits this or that “linguistic” ‘utterance.’ There are many instances of
NOTABLY NON-“linguistic” vehicles or devices of communication, within a
communication-system, which fulfil this or that communication-function; these
vehicles or devices are mostly syntactically un-structured or amorphous.
Sometimes, a device may exhibit at least some rudimentary syntactic structure,
in that we may distinguish a totum from a pars and identify a ‘simplex’ within
a ‘complexum.’ Grice’s intention-based reductive analysis of a communicatum,
based on Aristotle, Locke, and Peirce, is designed to allow for the possibility
that a non-“linguistic,” and, further, indeed a non-“conventional” 'utterance'
token, perhaps even manifesting some degree of syntactic structure, and not
just a block of an amorphous signal, may be within the ‘repertoire’ of
‘procedures’ of this or that organism, or creature, or agent, which, even if
not relying on any apparatus for communication of the kind that that we may
label ‘linguistic’ or otherwise ‘conventional,’
‘do’ this or that ‘thing’ thereby ‘communicating’ that p, or q. To
provide for this possibility, it is plainly necessary that the key ingredient in
any representation of ‘communicating,’ viz. intending that p, should be a ‘state’
of the emissor’s soul the capacity for which does not require what we may label
the ‘possession’ of, shall we say, a ‘faculty,’ of what philosophers call ‘a’
‘language’ (Sprache, Taal, langue, lingua – note that in German we do not
distinguish between ‘die Deutsche Sprache’ and ‘Sprache’ as ‘ein Facultat.’).
Now a philosopher, relying on this or that neo-Prichardian reductive analysis
of ‘intending that p,’ may not be willing to allow the possibility of such,
shall we call it, pre-linguistic intending that p, or non-linguistic intending
that p. Surely if the emissor realizes that his addressee does not share what
the Germans call ‘die Deutsche Sprache,” the emissor may still communicate with
his addresse this or that by doing this or that. E. g. he may simulate that he
wants to smoke a cigarette and wonders if his addressee has one to spare.
Against that objection, Grice surely wins the day. But Grice grants that
winning the day on THAT front may not be enough. And that is because, as far as
Grice’s Oxonian explorations on communication go, in a succession of
increasingly elaborate moves – ending with a ‘closure’ clause which cut this
succession of increasingly elaborate moves -- designed to thwart this or that
scenario, later deemed illegitimate, involving two rational agents where the
emissor relies on an ‘inference-element’ that it is not the case that he
intends his addressee will recogise – Grice is led to restrict the ‘intending’
which is to constitute a case of an emissor communicating that p to
C-intending. Grice suspects that whatever may be the case in general with
regard to ‘intending,’ C-intending seems for some reason to Grice to be
unsophisticatedly, viz. plainly, too sophisticated a ‘state’ of a soul to be
found in an organism, ‘pirot,’ creature, that we may not want to deem ‘rational,’
or as the Germans would say, a creature that is destitute of “Die Deutsche
Sprache.” We need the pirot to be “very intelligent, indeed rational.”Grice
regrets that some may think that what he thought were unavoidable rear-guard
actions (ending with a complex reductive analysis of C-intending) seem to have
undermined the raison d'etre of the Griciean campaign.”Unfortunately, Grice
provides what he admittedly labels “a brief reply” which “will have to
suffice.” Why? Because “a full treatment would require delving deep into
crucial problems concerning the boundaries between vicious and virtuous
circularity.” Which is promising. It is not something totally UNATTAINABLE. It
reduces to the philosopher being virtuously circular, only! Why is the
‘virtuous circle’ so crucial – vide ‘circulus virtuosus.’ virtŭōsus , a, um, adj. virtus, I.virtuous, good (late Lat.), Aug. c. Sec.
Man. 10. A circle is virtuous if it is not that bad. In this case, we need the
‘virtuous circle’ because we are dealing with ‘a loop.’ This is exactly
Schiffer’s way of putting it in his ‘Introduction’ to Meaning (second edition).
There is a ‘conceptual loop.’ Schiffer is not interested in ‘communicating;’
only ‘meaning.’ But his point can be transferred. He is saying that ‘U means
that p,’ may rely on ‘U intends that p,’ where ‘U intends that p’ relies on ‘U
means that p.’ There is a loop. In more generic terms:We have a creature, call
it a pirot P1 that, by doing thing T, communicates that p. Are we talking of
the OBSERVER? I hope so, because Grice’s favourite pirot is the parrot. So we
have Prince Maurice’s Parrot. Locke: Since I think I may be confident, that,
whoever should see a CREATURE of his own shape or make, though it had no more
reason all its life than a cat or a PARROT, would call him still A MAN; or
whoever should hear a cat or a parrot discourse, reason, and philosophize,
would call or think it nothing but a cat or a PARROT; and say, the one was A
DULL IRRATIONAL MAN, and the other A VERY INTELLIGENT RATIONAL PARROT. A
relation we have in an author of great note, is sufficient to countenance the
supposition of A RATIONAL PARROT. The author’s words are: I had a mind to know,
from Prince Maurice's own mouth, the account of a common, but much credited
story, that I had heard so often from many others, of an old parrot he has,
that speaks, and asks, and answers common questions, like A REASONABLE
CREATURE. So that those of his train there generally conclude it to be witchery
or possession; and one of his chaplains, would never from that time endure A
PARROT, but says all PARROTS have a devil in them. I had heard many particulars
of this story, and as severed by people hard to be discredited, which made me
ask Prince Maurice what there is of it. Prince Maurice says, with his usual
plainness and dryness in talk, there is something true, but a great deal false
of what is reported. I desired to know of him what there was of the first.
Prince Maurice tells me short and coldly, that he had HEARD of such A PARROT;
and though he believes nothing of it, and it was a good way off, yet he had so much
curiosity as to send for the parrot: that it was a very great parrot; and when
the parrot comes first into the room where Prince Maurice is, with a great many
men about him, the parrot says presently, What a nice company is here. One of
the men asks the parrot, ‘What thinkest thou that man is?,’ ostending his
finger, and pointing to Prince Maurice. The parrot answers, ‘Some general -- or
other.’ When the man brings the parrot close to Prince Maurice, Prince Maurice
asks the parrot., “D'ou venez-vous?” The parrot answers, “De Marinnan.” Then
Prince Maurice goes on, and poses a second question to the parrot. “A qui
estes-vous?” The Parrot answers: “A un Portugais.” Prince Maurice asks a third
question. “Que fais-tu la?” The parrot answers: “Je garde les poulles.”Prince Maurice
smiles, which pleases the Parrot. Prince Maurice, violating a Griceian maxim,
and being just informed that p, asks whether p. This is his fourth question.
“Vous gardez les poulles?” The Parrot answers, “Oui, moi; et je scai bien
faire.” The Parrott appeals to Peirce’s iconic system and makes the chuck four
or five times that a man uses to make to chickens when a man calls them. I set
down the words of this worthy dialogue in French, just as Prince Maurice said
them to me. I ask Prince Maurice in what ‘language’ the parrot speaks. Prince
Maurice says that the parrot speaks in Brazilian. I ask Prince William whether
he understands the Brazilian language. Prince Maurice says: No, but he has
taken care to have TWO interpreters by him, the one a Dutchman that spoke
Brazilian, and the other a Brazilian that spoke Dutch; that Prince Maurice asked
them separatelyand privately, and both of them AGREED in telling Prince Maurice
just the same thing that the parrot had said. I could not but tell this ODD
story, because it is so much out of the way, and from the first hand, and what
may pass for a good one; for I dare say Prince Maurice at least believed
himself in all he told me, having ever passed for a very honest and pious man. I
leave it to naturalists to reason, and to other men to believe, as they please
upon it. However, it is not, perhaps, amiss to relieve or enliven a busy scene
sometimes with such digressions, whether to the purpose or no.Locke takes care that
the reader should have the story at large in the author's own words, because he
seems to me not to have thought it incredible.For it cannot be imagined that so
able a man as he, who had sufficiency enough to warrant all the testimonies he
gives of himself, should take so much pains, in a place where it had nothing to
do, to pin so close, not only on a man whom he mentions as his friend, but on a
prince in whom he acknowledges very great honesty and piety, a story which, if
he himself thought incredible, he could not but also think RIDICULOUS. Prince
Maurice, it is plain, who vouches this story, and our author, who relates it
from him, both of them call this talker A PARROT. And Locke asks any one else
who thinks such a story fit to be told, whether, if this PARROT, and all of its
kind, had always talked, as we have a prince's word for it this one did,-
whether, I say, they would not have passed for a race of RATIONAL ANIMALS; but
yet, whether, for all that, they would have been allowed to be MEN, and not
PARROTS? For I presume it is not the idea of A THINKING OR RATIONAL BEING alone
that makes the idea of A MAN in most people's sense: but of A BODY, so and so
shaped, joined to it: and if that be the idea of a MAN, the same successive
body not shifted all at once, must, as well as THE SAME IMMATERIAL SPIRIT, go to the
making of the same MAN. So back to
Grice’s pirotology.But first a precis of the conversation, or
languaging:PARROT: What a nice company is here.MAN (pointing to Prince
Maurice): What thinkest thou that man is?PARROT: Some general -- or other. (i.
e. the parrot displays what Grice calls ‘up-take.’ The parrot recognizes the
man’s c-intention. So far is ability to display uptake.PRINCE MAURICE: D'ou
venez-vous?PARROT: De Marinnan.PRINCE MAURICE: A qui estes-vous?PARROT: A un
Portugais.PRINCE MAURICE: Que fais-tu la?PARROT: Je garde les poulles.PRINCE
MAURICE SMILES and flouts a Griceian maxim: Vous gardez les poulles?PARROT
(losing patience, and grasping the Prince’s implicaturum that he doubts it):
Oui, moi. Et je scai bien faire.(The Parrott then appeals to Peirce’s iconic
system and makes the chuck five times that a man uses to make to chickens when
a man calls them.)So back to Grice:“According to my most recent speculations
about communication, one should distinguish between what I call the ‘factual’
or ‘de facto’ character of behind the state of affairs that one might describe
as ‘rational agent A communicates that p,’ for those communication-relevant
features which obtain or are present in the circumstances) the ‘titular’ or ‘de
jure’ character, viz. the nested C-intending which is only deemed to be
present. And the reason Grice calls it ‘nested’ is that it involves three
sub-intentions:(C) Emissor E communicates that (psi*) p iff Emissor E c-intends
that A recognises that E psi-s that p iffC1: Emissor E intends A to recognise
that A psi-s that p.C2: Emissor intends that A recognise C1 by A recognising C2C3:
There is no inference-element which is C-constitutive such that Emissor relies
on it and yet does not intend A to recognise.Grice:“The titular or de jure character
of the state of affairs that is described as “Emissor communicates that p,”
involves self-reference in the closure clause regarding the third intention,
C3, may be thought as being ‘regressive,’ or involving what mathematicians mean
when they use “, …;” and the translators of Aristotle, ‘eis apeiron,’
translated as ‘ad infinitum.’There may be ways of UNDEEMING this, i. e. of
stating that self-reference and closure are meant to BLOCK an infinite regress.
Hence the circle, if there is one – one feature of a virtuous circle is that it
doesn’t look like a circle simpliciter --
would be virtuous. The ‘de jure’ character stands for a situation which,
in Grice’s words, is “infinitely complex,” and so cannot be actually present in
toto – only DEEMED to be.”“In which case,” Grice concludes pointing to the
otiosity or rendering inoperative, “to point out that THE INCONCEIVABLE actual
presence of the ‘de jure’ character of ‘Emissor communicates that p’ WOULD,
still, be possible, or would be detectable, only via the ‘use’ of something
like ‘die Deutsche Sprache’ seem to serve little, if any, purpose.”“At its most
meagre, the factual or ‘de facto’ character consists merely in the pre-rational
‘counterpart’ of the state of affairs describable by “Emissor E communicates
that p,” which might amount to no more than making a certain sort of utterance
in order thereby to get some creature to think or want some particular
thing.This meagre condition does not involve a reference to any expertise
regarding anything like ‘die Deutsche Sprache.’Let’s reformulate the
condition.It’s just a pirot, at a ‘pre-rational’ level. The pirot does a thing
T IN ORDER THEREBY to get some other pirot to think or do some particular
thing. To echo Hare,Die Tur ist geschlossen, ja.Die Tur ist geschlossen, bitte.Grice
continues as a corollary: “Maybe in a less straightforward instance of “Emissor
E communicates that p” there is actually present the C-intention whose
feasibility as an ‘intention’ suggests some ability to use ‘die Deutsche
Sprache.’But vide “non-verbal communication,” pre-verbal communication,
languaging, pre-conventional communication, gestural communication – as in What
Grice has as “a gesture (a signal).” Not necessary ‘conventional,’ and MAYBE
‘established’ – is one-off sufficient for ‘established’? I think so. By waving
his hand in a particular way (“a particular sort of hand wave”), the emissor
communicates that he knows the route (or is about to leave the addressee). Grice concludes about the less straightforward
instances, that there can be no advance guarantee when this will be so, i. e.
that there is actually present the C-intention whose feasibility as an
intention points to some capacity to use ‘die Deutsche Sprache.’Grice adds: “It
is in any case arguable that the use of ‘die Deutsche Sprache’ would here be an
indispensable aid to philosophising about communication, rather than it being an
element in the PHILOSOPHISING about communication! Philosophers
of Grice’s generation use ‘man’ on purpose to mean ‘mankind’. What a man means.
What a man utters. The utterer is the man. In semiotics one can use something
more Latinate, like gesturer, or emitter – or profferer. The distinction is
between what an utterer means and what the logical and necessary implication.
He doesn’t need to say this since ‘imply’ in the logical usage does not take
utterer as subject. It’s what the utterer SAYS that implies this or that. (Strawson
and Wiggins, p. 519). The utterer is possibly the ‘expresser.’
unamuno: m. d. b. Born in Bilbao, he studied in Bilbao and
Madrid and taught Grecian and philosophy in Salamanca. His open criticism of
the government led to dismissal from
the and exile 430 and, again, to
dismissal from the rectorship in 6. Unamuno is an important figure in letters. Like Ortega y Gasset, his aim was to
capture life in its complex emotional and intellectual dimensions rather than
to describe the world scientifically. Thus, he favored fiction as a medium for
his ideas and may be considered a precursor of existentialism. He wrote several
philosophically significant novels, a commentary on Don Quijote 5, and some
poetry and drama; his philosophical ideas are most explicitly stated in Del
sentimiento trágico de la vida “The Tragic Sense of Life,” 3. Unamuno perceived
a tragic sense permeating human life, a sense arising from our desire for
immortality and from the certainty of death. In this predicament man must
abandon all pretense of rationalism and embrace faith. Faith characterizes the
authentic life, while reason leads to despair, but faith can never completely
displace reason. Torn between the two, we can find hope only in faith; for
reason deals only with abstractions, while we are “flesh and bones” and can
find fulfillment only through commitment to an ideal.
unexpected
examination paradox, a paradox about
belief and prediction. One version is as follows: It seems that a teacher could
both make, and act on, the following announcement to his class: “Sometime
during the next week I will set you an examination, but at breakfast time on
the day it will occur, you will have no good reason to expect that it will
occur on that day.” If he announces this on Friday, could he not do what he
said he would by, say, setting the examination on the following Wednesday? The
paradox is that there is an argument purporting to show that there could not be
an unexpected examination of this kind. For let us suppose that the teacher
will carry out his threat, in both its parts; i.e., he will set an examination,
and it will be unexpected. Then he cannot set the examination on Friday
assuming this to be the last possible day of the week. For, by the time Friday
breakfast arrives, and we know that all the previous days have been
examination-free, we would have every reason to expect the examination to occur
on Friday. So leaving the examination until Friday is inconsistent with setting
an unexpected examination. For similar reasons, the examination cannot be held
on Thursday. Given our previous conclusion that it cannot be delayed until
Friday, we would know, when Thursday morning came, and the previous days had
been examination-free, that it would have to be held on Thursday. So if it were
held on Thursday it would not be unexpected. So it cannot be held on Thursday.
Similar reasoning sup938 U 938 posedly
shows that there is no day of the week on which it can be held, and so
supposedly shows that the supposition that the teacher can carry out his threat
must be rejected. This is paradoxical, for it seems plain that the teacher can
carry out his threat. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Grice’s book of paradoxes, with
pictures and illustrations to confuse you.”
uniformity of
nature – Grice: “’uniformity’ has
nothing to do with ‘form’ here!” – Grice: “I once used the phrase in a tutorial
with Hardie: “What do you mean by ‘of’?’ he asked” -- a state of affairs thought to be required if
induction is to be justified. For example, inductively strong arguments, such
as ‘The sun has risen every day in the past; therefore, the sun will rise
tomorrow’, are thought to presuppose that nature is uniform in the sense that
the future will resemble the past, in this case with respect to the diurnal
cycle. The Scottish empiricist Hume was the first to make explicit that the
uniformity of nature is a substantial assumption in inductive reasoning. Hume
argued that, because the belief that the future will resemble the past cannot
be grounded in experience for the future
is as yet unobserved induction cannot be
rationally justified; appeal to it in defense of induction is either
question-begging or illicitly metaphysical. Francis Bacon’s “induction by
enumeration” and J. S. Mill’s “five methods of experimental inquiry” presuppose
that nature is uniform. Whewell appealed to the uniformity of nature in order
to account for the “consilience of inductions,” the tendency of a hypothesis to
explain data different from those it was originally introduced to explain. For
reasons similar to Hume’s, Popper holds that our belief in the uniformity of
nature is a matter of faith. Reichenbach held that although this belief cannot
be justified in advance of any instance of inductive reasoning, its
presupposition is vindicated by successful inductions. It has proved difficult
to formulate a philosophical statement of the uniformity of nature that is both
coherent and informative. It appears contradictory to say that nature is
uniform in all respects, because inductive inferences always mark differences
of some sort e.g., from present to future, from observed to unobserved, etc.,
and it seems trivial to say that nature is uniform in some respects, because
any two states of nature, no matter how different, will be similar in some
respect. Not all observed regularities in the world or in data are taken to
support successful inductive reasoning; not all uniformities are, to use
Goodman’s term, “projectible.” Philosophers of science have therefore proposed
various rules of projectibility, involving such notions as simplicity and
explanatory power, in an attempt to distinguish those observed patterns that
support successful inductions and thus are taken to represent genuine causal
relations from those that are accidental or spurious.
unity in
diversity, in aesthetics, the
principle that the parts of the aesthetic object must cohere or hang together
while at the same time being different enough to allow for the object to be
complex. This principle defines an important formal requirement used in judging
aesthetic objects. If an object has insufficient unity e.g., a collection of
color patches with no recognizable patterns of any sort, it is chaotic or lacks
harmony; it is more a collection than one object. But if it has insufficient
diversity e.g., a canvas consisting entirely of one color with no internal
differentiations, it is monotonous. Thus, the formal pattern desired in an
aesthetic object is that of complex parts that differ significantly from each
other but fit together to form one interdependent whole such that the character
or meaning of the whole would be changed by the change of any part.
einheit – H. P. Grice, “Unity of science and teleology.” unity
of science, a situation in which all branches of empirical science form a
coherent system called unified science. Unified science is sometimes extended
to include formal sciences e.g., branches of logic and mathematics. ‘Unity of
science’ is also used to refer to a research program aimed at unified science.
Interest in the unity of science has a long history with many roots, including
ancient atomism and the work of the
Encyclopedists. In the twentieth century this interest was prominent in
logical empiricism see Otto Neurath et al., International Encyclopedia of
Unified Science, vol. I, 8. Logical empiricists originally conceived of unified
science in terms of a unified language of science, in particular, a universal
observation language. All laws and theoretical statements in any branch of
science were to be translatable into such an observation language, or else be
appropriately related to sentences of this language. In unified science unity
of science 939 939 addition to
encountering technical difficulties with the observationaltheoretical
distinction, this conception of unified science also leaves open the
possibility that phenomena of one branch may require special concepts and
hypotheses that are explanatorily independent of other branches. Another
concept of unity of science requires that all branches of science be combined
by the intertheoretic reduction of the theories of all non-basic branches to
one basic theory usually assumed to be some future physics. These reductions
may proceed stepwise; an oversimplified example would be reduction of
psychology to biology, together with reductions of biology to chemistry and
chemistry to physics. The conditions for reducing theory T2 to theory T1 are
complex, but include identification of the ontology of T2 with that of T1,
along with explanation of the laws of T2 by laws of T1 together with
appropriate connecting sentences. These conditions for reduction can be supplemented
with conditions for the unity of the basic theory, to produce a general
research program for the unification of science see Robert L. Causey, Unity of
Science, 7. Adopting this research program does not commit one to the
proposition that complete unification will ever be achieved; the latter is
primarily an empirical proposition. This program has been criticized, and some
have argued that reductions are impossible for particular pairs of theories, or
that some branches of science are autonomous. For example, some writers have
defended a view of autonomous biology, according to which biological science is
not reducible to the physical sciences. Vitalism postulated non-physical
attributes or vital forces that were supposed to be present in living organisms.
More recent neovitalistic positions avoid these postulates, but attempt to give
empirical reasons against the feasibility of reducing biology. Other, sometimes
a priori, arguments have been given against the reducibility of psychology to
physiology and of the social sciences to psychology. These disputes indicate
the continuing intellectual significance of the idea of unity of science and
the broad range of issues it encompasses.
universal
instantiation: Grice: “Slightly
confusing in that the universe is not a pluri-verse.” -- discussed by Grice in
his System G -- also called universal quantifier elimination. 1 The argument
form ‘Everything is f; therefore a is f’, and arguments of this form. 2 The
rule of inference that permits one to infer that any given thing is f from the
premise that everything is f. In classical logic, where all terms are taken to
denote things in the domain of discourse, the rule says simply that from vA[v]
one may infer A[t], the result of replacing all free occurrences of v in A[v]
by the term t. If non-denoting terms are allowed, however, as in free logic,
then the rule would require an auxiliary premise of the form Duu % t to ensure
that t denotes something in the range of the variable v. Likewise in modal
logic, which is sometimes held to contain terms that do not denote “genuine
individuals” the things over which variables range, an auxiliary premise may be
required. 3 In higher-order logic, the rule of inference that says that from
XA[X] one may infer A[F], where F is any expression of the grammatical category
e.g., n-ary predicate appropriate to that of X e.g., n-ary predicate variable.
G.F.S.
universalisability: -- Grice: ‘Slightly confusing, in that the universe
is not a pluri-verse” -- discussed along three dimension by Grice:
applicational conceptual, and formal. -- 1 Since the 0s, the moral criterion
implicit in Kant’s first formulation of the categorical imperative: “Act only
on that maxim that you can at the same time will to be a universal law,” often
called the principle of universality. A maxim or principle of action that
satisfies this test is said to be universalizable, hence morally acceptable;
one that does not is said to be not universalizable, hence contrary to duty. 2
A second sense developed in connection with the work of Hare in the 0s. For
Hare, universalizability is “common to all judgments which carry descriptive
meaning”; so not only normative claims moral and evaluative judgments but also
empirical statements are universalizable. Although Hare describes how such
universalizuniversal universalizability 940
940 ability can figure in moral argument, for Hare “offenses against . .
. universalizability are logical, not moral.” Consequently, whereas for Kant
not all maxims are universalizable, on Hare’s view they all are, since they all
have descriptive meaning. 3 In a third sense, one that also appears in Hare,
‘universalizability’ refers to the principle of universalizability: “What is
right or wrong for one person is right or wrong for any similar person in
similar circumstances.” This principle is identical with what Sidgwick The
Methods of Ethics called the Principle of Justice. In Generalization in Ethics
1 by M. G. Singer b.6, it is called the Generalization Principle and is said to
be the formal principle presupposed in all moral reasoning and consequently the
explanation for the feature alleged to hold of all moral judgments, that of
being generalizable. A particular judgment of the form ‘A is right in doing x’
is said to imply that anyone relevantly similar to A would be right in doing
any act of the kind x in relevantly similar circumstances. The characteristic
of generalizability, of presupposing a general rule, was said to be true of
normative claims, but not of all empirical or descriptive statements. The
Generalization Principle GP was said to be involved in the Generalization
Argument GA: “If the consequences of everyone’s doing x would be undesirable,
while the consequences of no one’s doing x would not be, then no one ought to
do x without a justifying reason,” a form of moral reasoning resembling, though
not identical with, the categorical imperative CI. One alleged resemblance is
that if the GP is involved in the GP, then it is involved in the CI, and this
would help explain the moral relevance of Kant’s universalizability test. 4 A
further extension of the term ‘universalizability’ appears in Alan Gewirth’s
Reason and Morality 8. Gewirth formulates “the logical principle of
universalizability”: “if some predicate P belongs to some subject S because S
has the property Q . . . then P must also belong to all other subjects S1, S2,
. . . , Sn that have Q.” The principle of universalizability “in its moral
application” is then deduced from the logical principle of universalizability,
and is presupposed in Gewirth’s Principle of Generic Consistency, “Act in
accord with the generic rights of your recipients as well as yourself,” which
is taken to provide an a priori determinate way of determining relevant
similarities and differences, hence of applying the principle of
universalizability. The principle of universalizability is a formal principle;
universalizability in sense 1, however, is intended to be a substantive
principle of morality.
universe of
discourse: Grice: “The phrase is
confusing, seeing the uni-verse, is not a pluri-verse.” Tthe usually limited
class of individuals under discussion, whose existence is presupposed by the
discussants, and which in some sense constitutes the ultimate subject matter of
the discussion. Once the universe of a discourse has been established,
expressions such as ‘every object’ and ‘some object’ refer respectively to
every object or to some object in the universe of discourse. The concept of
universe of discourse is due to De Morgan in 1846, but the expression was coined
by Boole eight years later. When a discussion is formalized in an interpreted
standard first-order language, the universe of discourse is taken as the
“universe” of the interpretation, i.e., as the range of values of the
variables. Quine and others have emphasized that the universe of discourse
represents an ontological commitment of the discussants. In a discussion in a
particular science, the universe of discourse is often wider than the domain of
the science, although economies of expression can be achieved by limiting the
universe of discourse to the domain.
use-mention
distinction: Grice: “I once used
Jevons’s coinage in a tutorial with Hardie; he said, ‘What do you mean by
‘of’?’” -- Grice: “Strictly, if you mention, you are using!” -- discussed by
Grice in “Retrospective epilogue” – the only use of a vehicle of communication
is to communicate. two ways in which terms enter into discourse used when they refer to or assert something,
mentioned when they are exhibited for consideration of their properties as
terms. If I say, “Mary is sad,” I use the name ‘Mary’ to refer to Mary so that
I can predicate of her the property of being sad. But if I say, “ ‘Mary’
contains four letters,” I am mentioning Mary’s name, exhibiting it in writing
or speech to predicate of that term the property of being spelled with four
letters. In the first case, the sentence occurs in what Carnap refers to as the
material mode; in the second, it occurs in the formal mode, and hence in a
metalanguage a language used to talk about another language. Single quotation
marks or similar orthographic devices are conventionally used to disambiguate
mentioned from used terms. The distinction is important because there are
fallacies of reasoning based on usemention confusions in the failure to observe
the use mention distinction, especially when the referents of terms are
themselves linguistic entities. Consider the inference: 1 Some sentences are
written in English. 2 Some sentences are written in English. Here it looks as
though the argument offers a counterexample to the claim that all arguments of
the form ‘P, therefore P’ are circular. But either 1 asserts that some
sentences are written in English, or it provides evidence in support of the
conclusion in 2 by exhibiting a sentence written in English. In the first case,
the sentence is used to assert the same truth in the premise as expressed in
the conclusion, so that the argument remains circular. In the second case, the
sentence is mentioned, and although the argument so interpreted is not
circular, it is no longer strictly of the form ‘P, therefore P’, but has the
significantly different form, ‘ “P” is a sentence written in English, therefore
P’.
English
futilitarians: utilitarianism, the
moral theory that an action is morally right if and only if it produces at
least as much good utility for all people affected by the action as any
alternative action the person could do instead. Its best-known proponent is J.
S. Mill, who formulated the greatest happiness principle also called the
principle of utility: always act so as to produce the greatest happiness. Two
kinds of issues have been central in debates about whether utilitarianism is an
adequate or true moral theory: first, whether and how utilitarianism can be
clearly and precisely formulated and applied; second, whether the moral
implications of utilitarianism in particular cases are acceptable, or instead
constitute objections to it. Issues of formulation. A central issue of
formulation is how utility is to be defined and whether it can be measured in
the way utilitarianism requires. Early utilitarians often held some form of
hedonism, according to which only pleasure and the absence of pain have utility
or intrinsic value. For something to have intrinsic value is for it to be
valuable for its own sake and apart from its consequences or its relations to
other things. Something has instrumental value, on the other hand, provided it
brings about what has intrinsic value. Most utilitarians have held that
hedonism is too narrow an account of utility because there are many things that
people value intrinsically besides pleasure. Some nonhedonists define utility
as happiness, and among them there is considerable debate about the proper
account of happiness. Happiness has also been criticized as too narrow to
exhaust utility or intrinsic value; e.g., many people value accomplishments,
not just the happiness that may accompany them. Sometimes utilitarianism is
understood as the view that either pleasure or happiness has utility, while
consequentialism is understood as the broader view that morally right action is
action that maximizes the good, however the good is understood. Here, we take
utilitarianism in this broader interpretation that some philosophers reserve
for consequentialism. Most utilitarians who believe hedonism gives too narrow
an account of utility have held that utility is the satisfaction of people’s
informed preferences or desires. This view is neutral about what people desire,
and so can account for the full variety of things and experiences that
different people in fact desire or value. Finally, ideal utilitarians have held
that some things or experiences, e.g. knowledge or being autonomous, are intrinsically
valuable or good whether or not people value or prefer them or are happier with
them. Whatever account of utility a utilitarian adopts, it must be possible to
quantify or measure the good effects or consequences of actions in order to
apply the utilitarian standard of moral rightness. Happiness utilitarianism,
e.g., must calculate whether a particular action, or instead some possible
alternative, would produce more happiness for a given person; this is called
the intrapersonal utility comparison. The method of measurement may allow
cardinal utility measurements, in which numerical units of happiness may be
assigned to different actions e.g., 30 units for Jones expected from action a,
25 units for Jones from alternative action b, or only ordinal utility
measurements may be possible, in which actions are ranked only as producing
more or less happiness than alternative actions. Since nearly all interesting
and difficult moral problems involve the happiness of more than one person,
utilitarianism requires calculating which among alternative actions produces
the greatest happiness for all people affected; this is called the
interpersonal utility comparison. Many ordinary judgments about personal action
or public policy implicitly rely on interpersonal utility comparisons; e.g.,
would a family whose members disagree be happiest overall taking its vacation
at the seashore or in the mountains? Some critics of utilitarianism doubt that
it is possible to make interpersonal utility comparisons. Another issue of formulation
is whether the utilitarian principle should be applied to individual actions or
to some form of moral rule. According to act utilitarianism, each action’s
rightness or wrongness depends on the utility it produces in comparison with
possible alternatives. Even act utilitarians agree, however, that rules of
thumb like ‘keep your promises’ can be used for the most part in practice
because following them tends to maximize utility. According to rule
utilitarianism, on the other hand, individual actions are evaluated, in theory
not just in practice, by whether they conform to a justified moral rule, and
the utilitarian standard is applied only to general rules. Some rule
utilitarians hold that actions are right provided they are permitted by rules
the general acceptance of which would maximize utility in the agent’s society,
and wrong only if they would be prohibited by such rules. There are a number of
forms of rule utilitarianism, and utilitarians disagree about whether act or
rule utilitarianism is correct. Moral implications. Most debate about
utilitarianism has focused on its moral implications. Critics have argued that
its implications sharply conflict with most people’s considered moral
judgments, and that this is a strong reason to reject utilitarianism.
Proponents have argued both that many of these conflicts disappear on a proper
understanding of utilitarianism and that the remaining conflicts should throw
the particular judgments, not utilitarianism, into doubt. One important
controversy concerns utilitarianism’s implications for distributive justice.
Utilitarianism requires, in individual actions and in public policy, maximizing
utility without regard to its distribution between different persons. Thus, it
seems to ignore individual rights, whether specific individuals morally deserve
particular benefits or burdens, and potentially to endorse great inequalities
between persons; e.g., some critics have charged that according to
utilitarianism slavery would be morally justified if its benefits to the
slaveowners sufficiently outweighed the burdens to the slaves and if it
produced more overall utility than alternative practices possible in that
society. Defenders of utilitarianism typically argue that in the real world
there is virtually always a better alternative than the action or practice that
the critic charges utilitarianism wrongly supports; e.g., no system of slavery
that has ever existed is plausibly thought to have maximized utility for the
society in question. Defenders of utilitarianism also typically try to show
that it does take account of the moral consideration the critic claims it
wrongly ignores; for instance, utilitarians commonly appeal to the declining
marginal utility of money equal marginal
increments of money tend to produce less utility e.g. happiness for persons,
the more money they already utilitarianism utilitarianism have as giving some support to equality in income
distribution. Another source of controversy concerns whether moral principles
should be agent-neutral or, in at least some cases, agent-relative.
Utilitarianism is agent-neutral in that it gives all people the same moral
aim act so as to maximize utility for
everyone whereas agent-relative
principles give different moral aims to different individuals. Defenders of
agent-relative principles note that a commonly accepted moral rule like the
prohibition of killing the innocent is understood as telling each agent that he
or she must not kill, even if doing so is the only way to prevent a still
greater number of killings by others. In this way, a non-utilitarian,
agent-relative prohibition reflects the common moral view that each person
bears special moral responsibility for what he or she does, which is greater
than his or her responsibility to prevent similar wrong actions by others.
Common moral beliefs also permit people to give special weight to their own
projects and commitments and, e.g., to favor to some extent their own children
at the expense of other children in greater need; agent-relative responsibilities
to one’s own family reflect these moral views in a way that agent-neutral
utilitarian responsibilities apparently do not. The debate over neutrality and
relativity is related to a final area of controversy about utilitarianism.
Critics charge that utilitarianism makes morality far too demanding by
requiring that one always act to maximize utility. If, e.g., one reads a book
or goes to a movie, one could nearly always be using one’s time and resources
to do more good by aiding famine relief. The critics believe that this wrongly
makes morally required what should be only supererogatory action that is good, but goes beyond “the
call of duty” and is not morally required. Here, utilitarians have often argued
that ordinary moral views are seriously mistaken and that morality can demand
greater sacrifices of one’s own interests for the benefit of others than is
commonly believed. There is little doubt that here, and in many other cases,
utilitarianism’s moral implications significantly conflict with commonsense moral
beliefs the dispute is whether this
should count against commonsense moral beliefs or against utilitarianism.
Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Bergmann on Stephen
and the English utilitarians.”
vagum: Oddly,
A. C. Ewing has a very early thing on ‘vagueness.’ Grice liked Ewing. There is
an essay on “Clarity” which relates. Cf. Price, “Clarity is not enough” Which
implicates it IS a necessity, though. Cf. “Clarity – who cares?” Some days,
Grice did not feel ‘Grecian,’ and would use very vernacular expressions. He
thought that what Cicero calls ‘vagum’ is best rendered in Oxfordshire dialect
as ‘fuzzy.’ It is not clear which of Grice’s maxim controls this. The opposite
of ‘vague’ is ‘specific.’ Grice was more concerned about this in the earlier
lectures where he has under the desideratum of conversational candour and the
principle of conversational benevolence, and the desideratum of conversational
clarity that one should be explicit, and make one’s point explicit. But under
the submaxims of the conversational category of modus (‘be perspicuous [sic]),
none seem to prohibit ‘vagueness’ as such: Avoid
obscurity of expression.Avoid ambiguity.Be brief (avoid unnecessary prolixity).Be orderly The one he later calls a ‘tailoring
principle’ ‘frame your contribution in way that facilitates a reply’, the
‘vagueness’ avoidance seems implicit. Cf. fuzzy. The
indeterminacy of the field of application of an expression, in contrast to
precision. For instance, the expression “young man” is vague since the point at
which its appropriate application to a person begins and ends cannot be
precisely defined. Vagueness should be distinguished from ambiguity, by which
a term has more than one meaning. The
vagueness of an expression is due to a semantic feature of the term itself,
rather than to the subjective condition of its user. Vagueness gives rise to
borderline cases, and propositions with vague terms lack a definite
truth-value. For this reason, Frege rejected the possibility of vague concepts,
although they are tolerated in recent work in vague or fuzzy logic. Various
paradoxes arise due to the vagueness of words, including the ancient sorites
paradox. It is because of its intrinsic vagueness that some philosophers seek
to replace ordinary language with an ideal language. But ordinary language
philosophers hold that this proposal creates a false promise of eliminating
vagueness. Wittgenstein’s notion of family resemblance in part is a model of
meaning that tolerates vagueness. As a property of expressions, vagueness
extends to all sorts of cognitive representations. Some philosophers hold that
there can be vagueness in things as well as in the representation of things. “A
representation is vague when the relation of the representing system to the
represented system is not one–one, but one–many.” Russell, Collected Papers of
Bertrand Russell, vol. IX. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Fuzzy impicatures, and
how to unfuzz them;” H. P. Grice, “The conversational maxim of vagueness avoidance.”
valitum: Oddly Vitters has a couple of lectures on ‘value,’
that Grice ‘ignored.’ Valitum should be contrasted from‘validum.’ ‘Valid,’
which is cognate with ‘value,’ a noun Grice loved, is used by logicians. In
Grice’s generalised alethic-cum-deontic logic, ‘valid’ applies, too. ‘Valid’ is
contrasted to the ‘satisfactoriness’ value that attaches directly to the
utterance. ‘Valid’ applies to the reasoning, i.e. the sequence of psychological
states from the premise to the conclusion. How common and insidious was the
talk of a realm of ‘values’ at Oxford in the early 1930s to have Barnes attack
it, and Grice defend it? ‘The realm of values’ sounds like an ordinary man’s
expression, and surely Oxford never had a Wilson Chair of Metaphysical Axiology.
validum is the correct form out of Roman
‘valeor.’ Grice finds the need for the English equivalent, and plays with
constructing the ‘concept’ “to be of value”! There’s also the axiologicum. The
root for ‘value’ as ‘axis’ is found in Grice’s favourite book of the Republic,
the First! Grice sometimes enjoys sounding pretentious and uses the definite
article ‘the’ indiscriminately, just to tease Flew, his tutee, who said that
talking of ‘the self’ is just ‘rubbish’. It is different with Grice’s ‘the
good’ (to agathon), ‘the rational,’ (to logikon), ‘the valuable’ (valitum), and
‘the axiological’. Of course, whilesticking with ‘value,’ Grice plays with
Grecian “τιμή.”
Lewis and Short have ‘vălor,’ f. ‘valeo,’ which they render as
‘value,’ adding that it is supposed to translate in Gloss. Lab, Grecian ‘τιμή.’ ‘valor, τιμή, Gloss. Lab.’
‘Valere,’ which of course algo gives English ‘valid,’ that Grice overuses, is said
by Lewis and Short to be cognate with “vis,” “robur,” “fortissimus,” cf.
debilis” and they render as “to be strong.” So one has to be careful here.
“Axiology” is a German thing, and not used at Clifton or Oxford, where they
stick with ‘virtus’ or ‘arete.’ This or that Graeco-Roman philosopher may have
explored a generic approach to ‘value.’ Grice somewhat dismisses Hare who in
Language of Morals very clearly distinguishes between deontic ‘ought’ and
teleological, value-judgemental ‘good.’ For ‘good’ may have an aesthetic use:
‘that painting is good,’ the food is good). The sexist ‘virtus’ of the Romans
perhaps did a disservice to Grecian ‘arete,’ but Grice hardly uses ‘arete,’
himself. It is etymologically unrelated to ‘agathon,’ yet rumour has it that ‘arete,’
qua ‘excellence,’ is ‘aristos,’ the superlative of ‘agathon.’ Since Aristotle
is into the ‘mesotes,’ Grice worries not. Liddell and Scott have “ἀρετή” and
render it simpliciter as “goodness, excellence, of any kind,” adding that “in
Hom. esp. of manly qualities”: “ποδῶν ἀρετὴν ἀναφαίνων;” “ἀμείνων παντοίας
ἀρετὰς ἠμὲν πόδας ἠδὲ μάχεσθαι καὶ νόον;” so of the gods, “τῶν περ καὶ μείζων
ἀ. τιμή τε βίη τε;” also of women, “ἀ. εἵνεκα for valour,” “ἀ. ἀπεδείκνυντο,”
“displayed brave deeds.” But when Liddell
and Scott give the philosophical references (Plathegel and Ariskant), they do
render “ἀρετή,” as ‘value,’ generally,
excellence, “ἡ ἀ. τελείωσίς τις” Arist. Met. 1021b20, cf. EN1106a15, etc.; of
persons, “ἄνδρα πὺξ ἀρετὰν εὑρόντα,” “τὸ φρονεῖν ἀ. μεγίστη,” “forms of
excellence, “μυρίαι ἀνδρῶν ἀ.;” “δικαστοῦ αὕτη ἀ.;” esp. moral virtue, opp.
“κακία,” good nature, kindness, etc. We should not be so concerned about this,
were not for the fact that Grice explored Foot, not just on meta-ethics as a
‘suppositional’ imperratives, but on
‘virtue’ and ‘vice,’ by Foot, who had edited a reader in meta-ethics for the
series of Grice’s friend, Warnock. Grice knows that when he hears the phrases
value system, or belief system, he is conversing with a relativist. So he plays
jocular here. If a value is not a concept, a value system at least is not what
Davidson calls a conceptual scheme. However, in “The conception of value”
(henceforth, “Conception”) Grice does argue that value IS a concept, and thus
part of the conceptual scheme by Quine. Hilary Putnam congratulates Grice on
this in “Fact and value,” crediting Baker – i. e. Judy – into the bargain.
While utilitarianism, as exemplified by Bentham, denies that a moral intuition
need be taken literally, Bentham assumes the axiological conceptual scheme of
hedonistic eudaemonism, with eudaemonia as the maximal value (summum bonum)
understood as hedone. The idea
of a system of values (cf. system of ends) is meant to unify the goals of the
agent in terms of the pursuit of eudæmonia. Grice wants to disgress from
naturalism, and the distinction between a
description and anything else. Consider the use of ‘rational’ as applied to
‘value.’ A naturalist holds that ‘rational’ can be legitimately
apply to the ‘doxastic’ realm, not to the ‘buletic’ realm. A desire (or a
‘value’) a naturalist would say is not something of which ‘rational’ is
predicable. Suppose, Grice says, I meet a philosopher who is in the habit of
pushing pins into other philosophers. Grice asks the philosopher why he does
this. The philosopher says that it gives him pleasure. Grice asks him whether
it is the fact that he causes pain that gives him pleasure. The philosopher
replies that he does not mind whether he causes pain. What gives him pleasure
is the physical sensation of driving a pin into a philosopher’s body. Grice
asks him whether he is aware that his actions cause pain. The philosopher says
that he is. Grice asks him whether he would not feel pain if others did this to
him. The philosopher agrees that he would. I ask him whether he would allow
this to happen. He says that he guesses he would seek to prevent it. Grice asks
him whether he does not think that others must feel pain when he drives pins
into them, and whether he should not do to others what he would try to prevent
them from doing to him. The philosopher says that pins driven into him cause
him pain and he wishes to prevent this. Pins driven by him into others do not
cause him pain, but pleasure, and he therefore wishes to do it. Grice asks him
whether the fact that he causes pain to other philosophers does not seem to him
to be relevant to the issue of whether it is rationally undesirable to drive
pins into people. He says that he does not see what possible difference can
pain caused to others, or the absence of it, make to the desirability of
deriving pleasure in the way that he does. Grice asks him what it is that
gives him pleasure in this particular activity. The philosopher replies that he
likes driving pins into a philosopher’s resilient body. Grice asks whether he
would derive equal pleasure from driving pins into a tennis ball. The
philosopher says that he would derive equal pleasure, that into what he drives
his pins, a philosopher or a tennis ball, makes no difference to him – the
pleasure is similar, and he is quite prepared to have a tennis ball
substituted, but what possible difference can it make whether his pins
perforate living men or tennis balls? At this point, Grice begins to suspect
that the philosopher is evil. Grice does not feel like agreeing with a
naturalist, who reasons that the pin-pushing philosopher is a philosopher with
a very different scale of moral values from Grice, that a value not being
susceptible to argument, Grice may disagree but not reason with the pin-pushing
philosopher. Grice rather sees the pin-pushing philosopher beyond the reach of
communication from the world occupied by him. Communication is as unattainable
as it is with a philosopher who that he is a doorknob, as in the story by
Hoffman. A value enters into the essence of what constitutes a person. The
pursuit of a rational end is part of the essence of a person. Grice does not
claim any originality for his position (which much to Ariskant), only validity.
The implicaturum by Grice is that rationalism and axiology are incompatible,
and he wants to cancel that. So the keyword here is rationalistic axiology, in
the neo-Kantian continental vein, with a vengeance. Grice arrives at value
(validitum, optimum, deeming) via Peirce on meaning. And then there is the truth
“value,” a German loan-translation (as value judgment, Werturteil). The sorry
story of deontic logic, Grice says, faces Jørgensens dilemma. The
dilemma by Jørgensens is best seen as a trilemma, Grice says; viz. Reasoning
requires that premise and conclusion have what Boole, Peirce, and Frege call a
“truth” value. An imperative dos not have a “truth” value. There may be a
reasoning with an imperative as premise or conclusion. A philosopher can reject
the first horn and provide an inference mechanism on elements – the input of
the premise and the output of the conclusion -- which are not presupposed to
have a “truth” value. A philosopher can reject the second horn and restrict
‘satisfactory’ value to a doxastic embedding a buletic (“He judges he wills…”).
A philosopher can reject the third horn, and refuse to explore the desideratum.
Grice generalizes over value as the mode-neutral ‘satisfactory.’ Both ‘p’ and
“!p” may be satisfactory. ‘.p’ has doxastic value (0/1); ‘!p’ has buletic
value (0/1). The mode marker of the
utterance guides the addresse you as to how to read ‘satisfactory.’ Grice’s
‘satisfactory’ is a variation on a theme by Hofstadter and McKinsey, who
elaborate a syntax for the imperative mode, using satisfaction. They refer to
what they call the ‘satisfaction-function’ of a fiat. A fiat is ‘satisfied’ (as
The door is closed may also be said to be satisfied iff the door is closed) iff
what is commanded is the case. The fiat ‘Let the door be closed’ is satisfied
if the door is closed. An unary or dyadic operator becomes a
satisfaction-functor. As Grice puts it,
an inferential rule, which flat rationality is the capacity to apply,
is not arbitrary. The inferential rule picks out a transition of
acceptance in which transmission of ‘satisfactory’ is guaranteed or
expected. As Grice notes, since mode marker indicate the species ‘satisfactory’
does. He imports into the object-language ‘It is satisfactory-d/p that’ just
in case psi-d/b-p is satisfactory. Alla Tarski, Grice introduces ‘It is
acceptable that’: It is acceptable that psi-d/b-p is satisfactory-b/d just in
case ‘psi-d/b-p is satisfactory-d/b’ is satisfactory-b/d. Grice goes
on to provide a generic value-assignment for satisfactoriness-functors. For
coordinators: “φ Λ ψ” is 1-b/d just in case φ is 1-b/d and
ψ is 1-b/d. “φ ν ψ” is 1-b/d
just in case one of the pair, φ and ψ, is 1-b/d. For subordinator: “φ⊃ψ” is
1-b/d just in case either φ is 0-b/d or ψ is 0-b/d. There are,
however, a number of points to be made. It is not fully clear to Grice just how
strong the motivation is for assigning a value to a mode-neutral, generic
functor. Also he is assuming symmetry, leaving room for a functor is introduced
if a restriction is imposed. Consider a bi-modal utterance. “The beast is
filthy and do not touch it” and “The beast is filthy and I shall not touch it”
seem all right. The commutated “Do not touch the beast and it is filthy” is
dubious. “Touch the beast and it will bite you,” while idiomatic is hardly an
imperative, since ‘and’ is hardly a conjunction. “Smith is taking a bath or
leave the bath-room door open” is intelligible. The commutated “Leave the
bath-room door open or Smith is taking a bath” is less so. In a bi-modal
utterance, Grice makes a case for the buletic to be dominant over the doxastic.
The crunch comes, however, with one of the four possible unary
satisfactoriness-functors, especially with regard to the equivalence of “~psi-b/d-p” and “psi-b/d-~p). Consider “Let
it be that I now put my hand on my head” or
“Let it be that my bicycle faces north” in which neither seems to be
either satisfactory or unsatisfactory. And it is a trick to assign a
satisfactory value to “~psi-b/d-p” and “~psi-b/d~p.” Do we proscribe this or
that form altogether, for every cases? But that would seem to be a pity, since
~!~p seems to be quite promising as a representation for you may (permissive)
do alpha that satisfies p; i.e., the utterer explicitly conveys his refusal to
prohibit his addressee A doing alpha. Do we disallow embedding of (or
iterating) this or that form? But that (again if we use ~!p and ~!~p to
represent may) seems too restrictive. Again, if !p is neither buletically
satisfactory nor buletically unsatisfactory (U could care less) do we assign a
value other than 1 or 0 to !p (desideratively neuter, 0.5). Or do we say,
echoing Quine, that we have a buletically satisfactoriness value gap? These and
other such problems would require careful consideration. Yet Grice cannot see
that those problems would prove insoluble, any more than this or that analogous
problem connected with Strawsons presupposition (Dont arrest the intruder!) are
insoluble. In Strawsons case, the difficulty is not so much to find a solution
as to select the best solution from those which present themselves. Grice takes
up the topic of a calculus in connection with the introduction rule and the
elimination rule of a modal such as must. We might hope to find, for each
member of a certain family of modalities, an introduction rule and an
elimination rule which would be analogous to the rules available for classical
logical constants. Suggestions are not hard to come by. Let us suppose that we
are seeking to provide such a pair of rules for the particular modality of
necessity □. For (□,+) Grice considers the following (Grice thinks equivalent)
forms: if φ is demonstrable, □φ is
demonstrable. Provided φ is dependent on no assumptions, derive φ from □φ. For (□,-), Grice considers From □φ derive φ. It is to be understood, of course, that the
values of the syntactical variable φ would contain either a buletic or a
doxastic mode markers. Both !p and .p would be proper substitutes for φ but p
would not. Grice wonders: [W]hat should be said of Takeuti’s conjecture
(roughly) that the nature of the introduction rule determines the character of
the elimination rule? There seems to be no particular problem about
allowing an introduction rule which tells us that, if it is established in P’s
personalised system that φ, it is necessary, with respect to P, that φ is
doxastically satisfactory/establishable. The accompanying elimination rule is,
however, slightly less promising. If we suppose such a rule to tell us that, if
one is committed to the idea that it is necessary, with respect to P, that φ,
one is also committed to whatever is expressed by φ, we shall be in trouble.
For such a rule is not acceptable. φ will be a buletic expression such as Let
it be that Smith eats his hat. And my commitment to the idea that Smiths system
requires him to eat his hat does not ipso facto involve me in accepting volitively
Let Smith eat his hat. But if we take the elimination rule rather as telling us
that, if it is necessary, with respect to X, that let X eat his hat, then let X
eat his hat possesses satisfactoriness-with-respect-to-X, the situation is
easier. For this person-relativised version of the rule seems inoffensive, even
for Takeuti, we hope. Grice, following Mackie, uses absolutism, as opposed to relativism, which denies
the rational basis to attitude ascriptions (but cf. Hare on Subjectsivism).
Grice is concerned with the absence of a thorough discussion of value by
English philosophers, other than Hare (and he is only responding to Mackie!).
Continental philosophers, by comparison, have a special discipline, axiology,
for it! Similarly, a continental-oriented tradition Grice finds in The New
World in philosophers of a pragmatist bent, such as Carus. Grice wants to
say that rationality is a value, because it is a faculty that a creature
(human) displays to adapt and survive to his changing environments. The implicaturum
of the title is that values have been considered in the English philosophical
tradition, almost alla Nietzsche, to belong to the realm irrational. Grice
grants that axiological implicaturum rests on a PRE-rational propension. While Grice could play with “the good” in the New
World, as a Lit. Hum. he knew he had to be slightly more serious. The good is
one of the values, but what is valuing? Would the New Worlders understand
valuing unattached to the pragmatism that defines them? Grice starts by
invoking Hume on his bright side: the concept of value, versus the conception
of value. Or rather, how the concept of value derives from the conception of
value. A distinction that would even please Aquinas (conceptum/conceptio), and
the Humeian routine. Some background for his third Carus lecture. He tries to
find out what Mackie means when he says that a value is ultimately Subjectsive.
What about inter-Subjectsive, and constructively objective? Grice constructs
absolute value out of relative value. But once a rational pirot P (henceforth,
P – Grice liked how it sounded like Locke’s parrot) constructs value, the P
assigns absolute status to rationality qua value. The P cannot then choose not
to be rational at the risk of ceasing to exist (qua person, or essentially
rationally human agent). A human, as opposed to a person, assigns relative
value to his rationality. A human is accidentally rational. A person is
necessarily so. A distinction seldom made by Aristotle and some of his dumbest
followers obsessed with the modal-free adage, Homo rationale animal. Short
and Lewis have “hūmānus” (old form: hemona humana et hemonem hominem dicebant,
Paul. ex Fest. p. 100 Müll.; cf. homo I.init.), adj., f. “homo,” and which they
render as “of or belonging to man, human.” Grice also considers the etymology
of ‘person.’ Lewis and Short have ‘persōna,’
according to Gabius Bassus ap. Gell. 5, 7, 1 sq., f. ‘persŏno,’ “to
sound through, with the second syllable lengthened.’ Falsa est (finitio), si
dicas, Equus est animal rationale: nam est equus animal, sed irrationale,
Quint.7,3,24:homo est animal rationale; “nec si mutis finis voluptas,
rationalibus quoque: quin immo ex contrario, quia mutis, ideo non
rationalibus;” “a rationali ad rationale;” “τὸ λογικόν ζῷον,” ChrysiStoic.3.95;
ἀρεταὶ λ., = διανοητικαί, oἠθικαί, Arist. EN1108b9; “λογικός, ή, όν, (λόγος),
ζῶον λόγον ἔχον NE, 1098a3-5. λόγον δὲ μόνον ἄνθρωπος ἔχει τῶν ζῴων, man alone
of all animals possesses speech, from the Politics. Grice takes the
stratification of values by Hartmann much more seriously than Barnes. Grice
plays with rational motivation. He means it seriously. The motivation is the
psychological bite, but since it is qualified by rational, it corresponds to
the higher more powerful bit of the soul, the rational soul. There are, for
Grice, the Grecians, Kantotle and Plathegel, three souls: the vegetal, the
animal, and the rational. As a matter of history, Grice reaches value (in its
guises of optimum and deeming) via his analysis of meaning by Peirce. Many
notions are value-paradeigmatic. The most important of all philosophical
notions that of rationality, presupposes objective value as one of its
motivations. For Grice, ratio can be understood cognoscendi but also
essendi, indeed volendi and fiendi, too. Rational motivation involves a ratio
cognoscendi and a ratio volendi; objective, “objectum,” and “objectus,” ūs, m.
f. “obicio,” rendered as “a casting before, a putting against, in the way, or
opposite, an opposing; or, neutr., a lying before or opposite (mostly poet. and
in postAug. prose): dare objectum parmaï, the opposing of the shield” “vestis;”
“insula portum efficit objectu laterum,” “by the opposition,” “cum terga
flumine, latera objectu paludis tegerentur;” “molis;” “regiones, quæ Tauri
montis objectu separantur;” “solem interventu lunæ occultari, lunamque terræ
objectu, the interposition,” “eademque terra objectu suo umbram noctemque
efficiat;” “al. objecta soli: hi molium objectus (i. e. moles objectas)
scandere, the projection,” transf., that which presents itself to the sight, an
object, appearance, sight, spectacle;” al. objecto; and if not categoric. This is analogous to
the overuse by Grice of psychoLOGICAL when he just means souly. It is
perhaps his use of psychological for souly that leads to take any souly concept
as a theoretical concept within a folksy psychoLOGICAL theory. Grice
considered the stratification of values, alla Hartmann, unlike Barnes, who
dismissed him in five minutes. “Some like Philippa Foot, but Hare is MY man,” Grice
would say. “Virtue” ethics was becoming all the fashion, especially around
Somerville. Hare was getting irritated by the worse offender, his Anglo-Welsh
tutee, originally with a degree from the other place, Williams. Enough for
Grice to want to lecture on value, and using Carus as an excuse! Mackie was
what Oxonians called a colonial, and a clever one! In fact, Grice quotes from
Hares contribution to a volume on Mackie. Hares and Mackies backgrounds could
not be more different. Like Grice, Hare was a Lit. Hum., and like Grice, Hare
loves the Grundlegung. But unlike Grice and Barnes, Hare would have nothing to
say about Stevenson. Philosophers in the play group of Grice never took the
critique by Ayer of emotivism seriously. Stevenson is the thing. V. Urmson on
the emotive theory of ethics, tracing it to English philosphers like Ogden,
Barnes, and Duncan-Jones. Barnes was opposing both Prichard (who was the Whites
professor of moral philosophy – and more of an interest than Moore is, seeing
that Prichard is Barness tutor at Corpus) and Hartmann. Ryle would have nothing
to do with Hartmann, but these were the days before Ryle took over Oxford, and
forbade any reference to a continental philosopher, even worse if a “Hun.”
Grice reaches the notion of value through that of meaning. If Peirce is
simplistic, Grice is not. But his ultra-sophisticated analysis ends up being
deemed to hold in this or that utterer. And deeming is valuing, as is optimum.
While Grice rarely used axiology, he should! A set of three lectures, which
are individually identified below. I love Carus! Grice was undecided as to
what his Carus lectures were be on. Grice explores meaning under its value
optimality guise in Meaning revisited. Grice thinks that a
value-paradeigmatic notion allows him to respond in a more apt way to what some
critics were raising as a possible vicious circle in his approach to semantic
and psychological notions. The Carus lectures are then dedicated to the
construction, alla Hume, of a value-paradeigmatic notion in general, and value
itself. Grice starts by quoting Austin, Hare, and Mackie, of
Oxford. The lectures are intended to a general audience, provided it is a
philosophical general audience. Most of the second lecture is a subtle
exploration by Grice of the categorical imperative of Kant, with which he had
struggled in the last Locke lecture in “Aspects,” notably the reduction of the
categorical imperative to this or that counsel of prudence with an implicated
protasis to the effect that the agent is aiming at eudæmonia. The Carus
Lectures are three: on objectivity and value, on relative and absolute value,
and on metaphysics and value. The first lecture, on objectivity and value,
is a review Inventing right and wrong by Mackie, quoting Hare’s
antipathy for a value being ‘objective’. The second lecture, on relative and
absolute value, is an exploration on the categorical imperative, and its
connection with a prior hypothetical or suppositional imperative. The
third lecture, on metaphycis and value, is an eschatological defence of
absolute value. The collective citation should be identified by each lecture
separately. This is a metaphysical defence by Grice of absolute value. The
topic fascinates Grice, and he invents a few routines to cope with it.
Humeian projection rationally reconstructs the intuitive concept being of
value. Category shift allows to put a value such as the disinterestedness
by Smith in grammatical subject position, thus avoiding to answer that the
disinterestedness of Smith is in the next room, since it is not the
spatio-temporal continuan prote ousia that Smith is. But the
most important routine is that of trans-substantatio, or metousiosis. A
human reconstructs as a rational personal being, and alla Kantotle,
whatever he judges is therefore of absolute value. The issue involves for
Grice the introduction of a telos qua aition, causa finalis (final cause),
role, or métier. The final cause of a tiger is to tigerise, the
final cause of a reasoner is to reason, the final cause of a person is to
personise. And this entails absolute value, now metaphysically defended. The
justification involves the ideas of end-setting, unweighed rationality,
autonomy, and freedom. In something like a shopping list that Grice
provides for issues on free. Attention to freedom calls for formidably
difficult undertakings including the search for a justification for the
adoption or abandonment of an ultimate end. The point is to secure that freedom
does not dissolve into compulsion or chance. Grice proposes four items for this
shopping list. A first point is that full action calls for strong freedom. Here
one has to be careful that since Grice abides by what he calls the Modified
Occams Razor in the third James lecture on Some remarks about logic and
conversation, he would not like to think of this two (strong freedom and weak
freedom) as being different senses of free. Again, his calls for is best
understood as presupposes. It may connect with, say, Kanes full-blown examples
of decisions in practical settings that call for or presuppose
libertarianism. A second point is that the buletic-doxastic justification
of action has to accomodate for the fact that we need freedom which is strong.
Strong or serious autonomy or freedom ensures that this or that action is
represented as directed to this or that end E which are is not merely the
agents, but which is also freely or autonomously adopted or pursued by the
agent. Grice discusses the case of the gym instructor commanding, Raise your
left arm! The serious point then involves this free adoption or free pursuit.
Note Grices use of this or that personal-identity pronoun: not merely mine,
i.e. not merely the agents, but in privileged-access position. This connects
with what Aristotle says of action as being up to me, and Kant’s idea of the transcendental
ego. An end is the agents in that the agent adopts it with liberum
arbitrium. This or that ground-level desire may be circumstantial. A weak
autonomy or freedom satisfactorily accounts for this or that action as directed
to an end which is mine. However, a strong autonomy or freedom, and a strong
autonomy or freedom only, accounts for this or that action as directed to an
end which is mine, but, unlike, say, some ground-level circumstantial desire
which may have sprung out of some circumstantial adaptability to a given
scenario, is, first, autonomously or freely adopted by the agent, and, second,
autonomously or freely pursued by the agent. The use of the disjunctive
particle or in the above is of some interest. An agent may autonomously or freely
adopt an end, yet not care to pursue it autonomously or freely, even in this
strong connotation that autonomous or free sometimes has. A further point
relates to causal indeterminacy. Any attempt to remedy this situation by
resorting to causal indeterminacy or chance will only infuriate the scientist
without aiding the philosopher. This remark by Grice has to be understood
casually. For, as it can be shown, this or that scientist may well have
resorted to precisely that introduction and in any case have not
self-infuriated. The professional tag that is connoted by philosopher should
also be seen as best implicated than entailed. A scientist who does resort to
the introduction of causal indeterminacy may be eo ipso be putting forward a
serious consideration regarding ethics or meta-ethics. In other words, a
cursory examination of the views of a scientist like Eddington, beloved by
Grice, or this or that moral philosopher like Kane should be born in mind when
considering this third point by Grice. The reference by Grice to chance,
random, and causal indeterminacy, should best be understood vis-à-vis
Aristotles emphasis on tykhe, fatum, to the effect that this or that event may
just happen just by accident, which may well open a can of worms for the naive
Griceian, but surely not the sophisticated one (cf. his remarks on
accidentally, in Prolegomena). A further item in Grices shopping list involves
the idea of autonomous or free as a value, or optimum. The specific character
of what Grice has as strong autonomy or freedom may well turn out to
consist, Grice hopes, in the idea of this or that action as the outcome of a
certain kind of strong valuation ‒ where this would include the
rational selection, as per e.g. rational-decision theory, of this or that
ultimate end. What Grice elsewhere calls out-weighed or extrinsically weighed
rationality, where rational includes the buletic, of the end and not the means
to it. This or that full human action calls for the presence of this or that
reason, which require that this or that full human action for which this or
that reason accounts should be the outcome of a strong rational valuation. Like
a more constructivist approach, this line suggests that this or that action may
require, besides strong autonomy or freedom, now also strong valuation. Grice
sets to consider how to adapt the buletic-doxastic soul progression to reach
these goals. In the case of this or that ultimate end E, justification should
be thought of as lying, directly, at least, in this or that outcome, not on the
actual phenomenal fulfilment of this or that end, but rather of the, perhaps
noumenal, presence qua end. Grice relates to Kants views on the benevolentia or
goodwill and malevolentia, or evil will, or illwill. Considers Smiths action of
giving Jones a job. Smith may be deemed to have given Jones a job, whether or
not Jones actually gets the job. It is Smiths benevolentia, or goodwill, not
his beneficentia, that matters. Hence in Short and Lewis, we have
“bĕnĕfĭcentĭa,” f. “beneficus,” like “magnificentia” f. magnificus, and
“munificentia” f. munificus; Cicero, Off. 1, 7, 20, and which they thus render
as “the quality of beneficus, kindness, beneficence, an honorable and kind
treatment of others” (omaleficentia, Lact. Ira Dei, 1, 1; several times in the
philos. writings of Cicero. Elsewhere rare: quid praestantius bonitate et
beneficentiā?” “beneficentia, quam eandem vel benignitatem vel liberalitatem
appellari licet,” “comitas ac beneficentia,” “uti beneficentiā adversus
supplices,”“beneficentia augebat ornabatque subjectsos.” In a more general
fashion then, it is the mere presence of an end qua end of a given action that
provides the justification of the end, and not its phenomenal satisfaction or
fulfilment. Furthermore, the agents having such and such an end, E1, or
such and such a combination of ends, E1 and E2, would be justified by showing
that the agents having this end exhibits some desirable feature, such as this
or that combo being harmonious. For how can one combine ones desire to smoke
with ones desire to lead a healthy life? Harmony is one of the six requirements
by Grice for an application of happy to the life of Smith. The buletic-doxastic
souly ascription is back in business at a higher level. The suggestion would
involve an appeal, in the justification of this or that end, to this or that
higher-order end which would be realised by having this or that lower, or
first-order end of a certain sort. Such valuation of this or that lower-order
end lies within reach of a buletic-doxastic souly ascription. Grice has an
important caveat at this point. This or that higher-order end involved in the
defense would itself stand in need of justification, and the regress might well
turn out to be vicious. One is reminded of Watson’s requirement for a thing
like freedom or personal identity to overcome this or that alleged
counterexample to freewill provided by H. Frankfurt. It is after the
laying of a shopping list, as it were, and considerations such as those above
that Grice concludes his reflection with a defense of a noumenon, complete with
the inner conflict that it brings. Attention to the idea of autonomous and free
leads the philosopher to the need to resolve if not dissolve the most important
unsolved problem of philosophy, viz. how an agent can be, at the same time, a
member of both the phenomenal world and the noumenal world, or, to settle the
internal conflict between one part of our rational nature, the doxastic, even
scientific, part which seems to call for the universal reign of a deterministic
law and the other buletic part which insists that not merely moral
responsibility but every variety of rational belief demands exemption from just
such a reign. In this lecture, Grice explores freedom and value from a
privileged-access incorrigible perspective rather than the creature
construction genitorial justification. Axiology – v. axiological. Valitum
-- Fact-value distinction, the apparently fundamental difference between how
things are and how they should be. That people obey the law or act honestly or
desire money is one thing; that they should is quite another. The first is a
matter of fact, the second a matter of value. Hume is usually credited with
drawing the distinction when he noticed that one cannot uncontroversially infer
an ‘ought’ from an ‘is’ the isought gap. From the fact, say, that an action
would maximize overall happiness, we cannot legitimately infer that it ought to
be done without the introduction of some
so far suppressed evaluative premise. We could secure the inference by assuming
that one ought always to do what maximizes overall happiness. But that
assumption is evidently evaluative. And any other premise that might link the
non-evaluative premises to an evaluative conclusion would look equally
evaluative. No matter how detailed and extensive the non-evaluative premises,
it seems no evaluative conclusion follows directly and as a matter of logic.
Some have replied that at least a few non-evaluative claims do entail
evaluative ones. To take one popular example, from the fact that some promise
was made, we might it appears legitimately infer that it ought to be kept,
other things equal and this without the
introduction of an evaluative premise. Yet many argue that the inference fails,
or that the premise is actually evaluative, or that the conclusion is not. Hume
himself was both bold and brief about the gap’s significance, claiming simply
that paying attention to it “wou’d subvert all the vulgar systems of morality,
and let us see, that the distinction of vice and virtue is not founded merely
on the relations of objects, nor is perceiv’d by reason” Treatise of Human
Nature. Others have been more expansive. Moore, for instance, in effect relied
upon the gap to establish via the open question argument that any attempt to
define evaluative terms using non-evaluative ones would commit the naturalistic
fallacy. Moore’s main target was the suggestion that ‘good’ means “pleasant”
and the fallacy, in this context, is supposed to be misidentifying an
evaluative property, being good, with a natural property, being pleasant.
Assuming that evaluative terms have meaning, Moore held that some could be
defined using others he thought, e.g., that ‘right’ could be defined as
“productive of the greatest possible good” and that the rest, though meaningful,
must be indefinable terms denoting simple, non-natural, properties. Accepting
Moore’s use of the open question argument but rejecting both his non-naturalism
and his assumption that evaluative terms must have descriptive meaning,
emotivists and prescriptivists e.g. Ayer, C. L. Stevenson, and Hare argued that
evaluative terms have a role in language other than to denote properties.
According to them, the primary role of evaluative language is not to describe,
but to prescribe. The logical gap between ‘is’ and ‘ought’, they argue,
establishes both the difference between fact and value and the difference
between describing how things are and recommending how they might be. Some
naturalists, though, acknowledge the gap and yet maintain that the evaluative
claims nonetheless do refer to natural properties. In the process they deny the
ontological force of the open question argument and 302 F 302 treat evaluative claims as describing a
special class of facts. Refs.: The main
source is The construction of value, the Carus lectures, Clarendon. But there
are scattered essays on value and valuing in the Grice Papers. H. P. Grice,
“Objectivity and value,” s. V, c. 8-f. 18, “The rational motivation for
objective value,” s. V, c. 8-f. 19, “Value,” s. V, c. 9-f. 20; “Value,
metaphysics, and teleology,” s. V, c. 9-f. 23, “Values, morals, absolutes, and
the metaphysical,” s. V., c. 9-f. 24;
“Value sub-systems and the Kantian problem,” s. V. c. 9-ff. 25-27; “Values and
rationalism,” s. V, c. 9-f. 28; while the Carus are in the second series, in
five folders, s. II, c-2, ff. 12-16, the H. P. Grice Papers, BANC.
velia -- Velia -- Grice as Eleatic -- School, strictly, two
fifth-century B.C. Grecian philosophers, Parmenides and Zeno of Elea. The
Ionian Grecian colony of Elea or Hyele in southern Italy became Velia in Roman
times and retains that name today. A playful remark by Plato in Sophist 242d
gave rise to the notion that Xenophanes of Colophon, who was active in southern
Italy and Sicily, was Parmenides’ teacher, had anticipated Parmenides’ views,
and founded the Eleatic School. Moreover, Melissus of Samos and according to
some ancient sources even the atomist philosopher Leucippus of Abdera came to
be regarded as “Eleatics,” in the sense of sharing fundamental views with
Parmenides and Zeno. In the broad and traditional use of the term, the Eleatic
School characteristically holds that “all is one” and that change and plurality
are unreal. So stated, the School’s position is represented best by Melissus.
Grice: “Crotone and Velia are the origins of western philosophy, since Greece
is eastern!” – Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Grice a Velia,” Villa Grice.
verificatum:
Grice: “Strictly, what is ‘verified’ is therefore ‘made true,’ analytically.”
-- see ayerism. Grice would possibly NOT be interested in verificationism had
not been for Ayer ‘breaking tradition’ “and other things” with it --. Oppoiste
Christian virtuous –ism: falsificationism. Verificationism is one of the twelve
temptations Grice finds on his way to the City of Eternal Truth. (Each one has
its own entry). Oddly, Boethius was the first verificationist. He use
‘verifico’ performatively. “When I say, ‘verifico’, I verify that what I say is
true.” He didn’t mean it as a sophisma (or Griceisma, but it was (mis-)understood
as such! “When I was listing the temptations, I thought of calling this
‘Ayerism,’ but then I changed my mind. verification theory of meaning The
theory of meaning advocated by the logical positivists and associated with the
criterion of verifiability. The latter provides a criterion of meaningfulness
for sentences, while the verification theory of meaning specifies the nature of
meaning. According to the criterion, a sentence is cognitively meaningful if
and only if it is logically possible for it to be verified. The meaning of a
sentence is its method of verification, that is, the way in which it can be
verified or falsified, particularly by experience. The theory has been
challenged because the best formulations still exclude meaningful sentences and
allow meaningless sentences. Critics also claim that the theory is a test for
meaningfulness rather than a theory of meaning proper. Further, they claim that
it fails to recognize that the interconnectedness of language might allow a
sentence that cannot itself be verified to be meaningful. “The verification
theory of meaning, which dominated the Vienna Circle, was concerned with the
meaning and meaningfulness of sentences rather than words.” Quine, Theories and
Things verificationism Philosophical method, philosophy of science, philosophy
of language A position fundamental to logical positivism, claiming that the
meaning of a statement is its method of verification. Accordingly, apparent
statements lacking a method of verification, such as those of religion and
metaphysics, are meaningless. Theoretical expressions can be defined in terms
of the experiences by means of which assertions employing them can be verified.
In the philosophy of mind, behaviorism, which tries to reduce unobserved inner
states to patterns of behavior, turns out to be a version of verificationism.
Some philosophers require conclusive verification for a statement to be
meaningful, while others allow any positive evidence to confer meaning. There
are disputes whether every statement must be verified separately or theories
can be verified as a whole even if some of their statements cannot be
individually verified. Attempts to offer a rigorous account of verification
have run into difficulties because statements that should be excluded as
meaningless nevertheless pass the test of verification and statements that should be allowed
as meaningful are excluded. “For over a hundred years, one of the dominant
tendencies in the philosophy of science has been verificationism, that is, the
doctrine that to know the meaning of a scientific proposition . . . is to know
what would be evidence for that proposition.” Putnam, Mind, Language and
Reality verisimilitude Philosophy of science [from Latin verisimilar, like the
truth] The degree of approximation or closeness to truth of a statement or a
theory. Popper defined it in terms of the difference resulting from
truth-content minus falsity-content. The truthcontent of a statement is all of
its true consequences, while the falsity-content of a statement is all of its
false consequences. The aim of science is to find better verisimilitude. One
theory has a better verisimilitude than competing theories if it can explain
the success of competing theories and can also explain cases where the other
theories fail. Popper emphasized that verisimilitude is different from
probability. Probability is the degree of logical certainty abstracted from
content, while verisimilitude is degree of likeness to truth and combines truth
and content. “This suggests that we combine here the ideas of truth and content
into one – the idea of a degree of better (or worse) correspondence to truth or
of greater (or less) likeness or similarity to truth; or to use a term already
mentioned above (in contradistinction to probability) the idea of (degrees of )
verisimilitude.” Popper, Conjectures and Refutations.
verum: Porphyry called the verum one of the four
transcendental, along with unum, pulchrum and bonum – Grice agreed. Grice’s
concern with the ‘verum’ is serious. If Quine is right, and logical truth
should go, so truth should go. Grice needs ‘true’ to correct a few
philosophical mistakes. It is true that Grice sees a horse as a horse, for
example. The nuances of the implicaturum are of a lesser concern for Grice than
the taming of the true. The root of
Latin ‘vero’ is cognate with an idea Grice loved: that of ‘sincerity.’ The
point is more obviously realised lexically in the negative: the fallax versus
the mendax. But ‘verum’ had to do with candidum – and thus very much cognate
with the English that Grice avoided, ‘truth,’ cognate with ‘trust.’ quod non
possit ab honestate sejungi The true and simple Good which cannot be separated
from honesty, Cicero, Academica, I, 2, but also for the ontological which one
can find in Cicero’s tr. Topica, 35 of etumologia ἐτυμολογία by veriloquium. Most
contemporary hypotheses propose that verus —and the words signifying true,
vrai, vérité, G. wahr, G. Wahrheit — derive from an Indo-European root, *wer,
which would retain meanings of to please, pleasing, manifesting benevolence,
gifts, services rendered, fidelity, pact. Chantraine Dictionnaire étymologique
de la langue grecque links it to the Homeric expression êra pherein ἦϱα φέϱειν,
to please, as well as to ἐπίηϱα, ἐπίηϱος, and ἐπιήϱανος, agreeable Odyssey, 19,
343, just like the Roman verus cf. se-vere, without benevolence, the G. war, and the Russian vera, faith, or verit’
верить, to believe. Pokorny adds to this same theme the Grecian ἑοϱτή,
religious feast, cult. And from the same basis have come terms signifying
guarantee, protect: Fr. garir and later
garant, G. Gewähren, Eng. warrant, to
grant. According to Chantraine, this root *wer should be distinguished from another
root ver-, whence eirô εἴϱω in Grecian , verbum in Roman word in English, etc.,
and words from the family of vereor, revereor, to fear, to respect, verecundia
respectful fear. According to Chantraine, this root *wer should be
distinguished from another root ver-, whence eirô εἴϱω in Grecian , verbum in
Roman word in English, etc., and words from the family of vereor, revereor, to
fear, to respect, verecundia respectful fear. Alfred Ernout does not support
this separation. We should recall that plays on the words verum and verbum were
common, as Augustine mentions verbum = verum boare, proclaiming the truth,
Dialectics 1. P. Florensky, following G. Curtius, “Grundzüge der griechischen
Etymologie,” also claims a single root for the ensemble of these derivations,
including the Sanskrit vratum, sacred act, vow, promise, the Grecian bretas
βϱέτας, cult object, wooden idol Aeschylus, Eumenides, v. 258, and the Roman
“ver-bum.” The signification of verus must be considered as belonging first to
the field of religious ritual and subsequently of juridical formulas: strictly
speaking, verus means protected or grounded in the sense of that which is the
object of a taboo or consecration Pillar and Ground. Then there’s from the
juridical to the philosophical. “Verum” implies a rectification of an
adversarial allegation considered to be fraudulent, as is indicated by the
original opposition verax/fallax-mendax. It thus signifies the properly founded
in fact or in the rules of law: crimen verissimum a well-founded accusation
Cicero, In Verrem, 5, 15. In texts of grammar and rhetoric, but also in juridical
texts as well, verus and veritas signify the veracity of the rule, inasmuch as
it can be distinguished from usage. “Quid verum sit intellego; sed alias ita
loquor ut concessum est I know what is correct, but sometimes I avail myself of
the variation in usage, Cicero, De oratore, Loeb Classical Library; Consule
veritatem: reprehendet; refer ad auris: probabunt If you consult the strict
rule of analogy, it will say this practice is wrong, but if you consult the
ear, it will approve 1586. The juridical connotation of the word verus and thus
of veritas is retained and subsequently reinforced. In the glosses of the
Middle Ages, verus signifies legitimate and the Roman sense of the word, legal
and authentic or conforming to existing law. One normally finds “verum est” in
legal texts to certify that a new rule conforms to preexisting ones Digest, 8,
4, 1. It is this juridical dimension that produces the meaning of verus as
authenticated, authentic in contrast to false, imitative, deceiving and thus
real as in real cream or a genuine Rolex watch.
The juridical here provides a foundation not only for the moral Verum et
simplex bonum. The paradigm of “verum” is not easy to separate from any
epistemological dimensions, as is evident in the varied fates of the Indo-European
root *wer, from which derives, in addition to vera in Russian, belief, the old
Fr. garir, in the sense of certifying as
true, designating as true, whence the participle garant. The evolution of these
derived words inscribes G. “wahr,” and “Wahrheit” in a semantic network from
which emerge two directions, belief and salvation. Belief. “Wahr” is often
linked back, in composite words, to the idea of belief, in the sense of true
belief, to take as true. “Wahrsagen,” to predict, “wahr haben,” to admit, agree
upon, “für wahr halten,” to hold as true, to believe. This is the term that
Kant employs in the Critique of Pure Reason, Transcendental theory of method,
ch.2, 3 On Opinion, Science, and Belief: “das Fürwahrhalten” is a belief, as a
modality of subjectivity, that can be divided into conviction Überzeugung or
persuasion Überredung and that is capable of three degrees: opinion Meinung,
belief Glaube, and science Wissenschaft. Safeguarding, conservation. Similarly “wahren,”
“bewahren” in the sense of to guard, to conserve is linked to “Wahrung” in the
sense of defending one’s interests or safeguarding. One might refer to
Heidegger’s use of this etymological and semantic relation in reference to
Nietzsche. It remains to be said that many common or colloquial expressions, in
Fr. as well as in English, play on the
semantic slippages of vrai and real, between the ontological sense and
linguistic meanings. Thus in Fr. , c’est pas vrai! does not mean it is false,
but rather that it is not reality. In English, the opposite is the case: get
real! means come back down to earth, accept the truth. Grice’s main manoeuvre
may be seen as intended to crack the crib of reality. For he wants to say some
philosophers engaged in conceptual analysis are misled if they think an
inappropriate usage reveals a truth-condition. By coining ‘implicaturum,’ his
point is to give room for “Emissor E communicates that p,” as opposed to
‘emissum x ‘means’ ‘p.’ Therefore, Grice can claim that an utterance may very
well totally baffling and misleading YET TRUE (or otherwise ‘good’), and that
in no way that reveals anything about the emissum itself. This is due to the
fact that ‘Emissor E communicates that p’ is diaphanous. And one can conjoin
what the emissor E communicates to what he explicitly conveys and NOT HAVE the
emissor contradicting himself or uttering a falsehood. And that is what in
philosophy should count. H. P. Grice was always happy with a ‘correspondence’
theory of truth. It was what Aristotle thought. So why change? The fact that
Austin agreed helped. The fact that Strawson applied Austin’s shining new tool
of the performatory had him fashion a new shining skid, and that helped,
because, once Grice has identified a philosophical mistake, that justifies his
role as methodologist in trying to ‘correct’ the mistake. The Old Romans did
not have an article. For them it is the unum, the verum, the bonum, and the
pulchrum. They were trying to translate the very articled Grecian ‘to alethes,’
‘to agathon,’ and ‘to kallon.’ Grecian Grice is able to restore the articles.
He would use ‘the alethic’ for the ‘verum,’ after von Wright. But occasionally
uses the ‘verum’ root. E. g. when his account of ‘personal identity’ was seen
to fail to distinguish between a ‘veridical’ memory and a non-veridical one. If
it had not been for Strawson’s ‘ditto’ theory to the ‘verum,’ Grice would not
have minded much. Like Austin, his inclination was for a ‘correspondence’
theory of truth alla Aristotle and Tarski, applied to the utterance, or
‘expressum.’ So, while we cannot say that an utterer is TRUE, we can say that
he is TRUTHFUL, and trustworthy (Anglo-Saxon ‘trust,’ being cognate with
‘true,’ and covering both the credibility and desirability realms. Grice
approaches the ‘verum’ in terms of predicate calculus. So we need at least an
utterance of the form, ‘the dog is shaggy.’ An utterance of ‘The dog is shaggy’
is true iff the denotatum of ‘the dog’ is a member of the class ‘shaggy.’ So,
when it comes to ‘verum,’ Grice feels like ‘solving’ a problem rather than
looking for new ones. He thought that Strawson’s controversial ‘ditto’ was
enough of a problem ‘to get rid of.’ VERUM. Along with verum, comes the falsum.
fallibilism, the doctrine, relative to some significant class of beliefs or
propositions, that they are inherently uncertain and possibly mistaken. The
most extreme form of the doctrine attributes uncertainty to every belief; more
restricted forms attribute it to all empirical beliefs or to beliefs concerning
the past, the future, other minds, or the external world. Most contemporary
philosophers reject the doctrine in its extreme form, holding that beliefs
about such things as elementary logical principles and the character of one’s
current feelings cannot possibly be mistaken. Philosophers who reject
fallibilism in some form generally insist that certain beliefs are analytically
true, self-evident, or intuitively obvious. These means of supporting the
infallibility of faculty psychology fallibilism 303 303 some beliefs are now generally discredited.
W. V. Quine has cast serious doubt on the very notion of analytic truth, and
the appeal to self-evidence or intuitive obviousness is open to the charge that
those who officially accept it do not always agree on what is thus evident or
obvious there is no objective way of identifying it, and that beliefs said to
be self-evident have sometimes been proved false, the causal principle and the
axiom of abstraction in set theory being striking examples. In addition to
emphasizing the evolution of logical and mathematical principles, fallibilists
have supported their position mainly by arguing that the existence and nature
of mind-independent objects can legitimately be ascertained only be
experimental methods and that such methods can yield conclusions that are, at
best, probable rather than certain. false consciousness, 1 lack of clear
awareness of the source and significance of one’s beliefs and attitudes
concerning society, religion, or values; 2 objectionable forms of ignorance and
false belief; 3 dishonest forms of self-deception. Marxists if not Marx use the
expression to explain and condemn illusions generated by unfair economic
relationships. Thus, workers who are unaware of their alienation, and “happy
homemakers” who only dimly sense their dependency and quiet desperation, are
molded in their attitudes by economic power relationships that make the status
quo seem natural, thereby eclipsing their long-term best interests. Again,
religion is construed as an economically driven ideology that functions as an
“opiate” blocking clear awareness of human needs. Collingwood interprets false
consciousness as self-corrupting untruthfulness in disowning one’s emotions and
ideas The Principles of Art, 8. . false
pleasure, pleasure taken in something false. If it is false that Jones is
honest, but Smith believes Jones is honest and is pleased that Jones is honest,
then Smith’s pleasure is false. If pleasure is construed as an intentional
attitude, then the truth or falsity of a pleasure is a function of whether its
intentional object obtains. On this view, S’s being pleased that p is a true
pleasure if an only if S is pleased that p and p is true. S’s being pleased
that p is a false pleasure if and only if S is pleased that p and p is false.
Alternatively, Plato uses the expression ‘false pleasure’ to refer to things
such as the cessation of pain or neutral states that are neither pleasant nor
painful that a subject confuses with genuine or true pleasures. Thus, being
released from tight shackles might mistakenly be thought pleasant when it is
merely the cessation of a pain. Refs: Grice, “Rationality and Trust,” Grice,
“The alethic.” “P. F. Strawson and the performatory account of ‘true’”, The
Grice Papers.
vico -- Danesi, Marcel. Vico, Metaphor, and the Origin of Language. Bloomington:
Indiana. Serious scholars of Vico as
well as glottogeneticists will find much of value in this excellent monograph. Vico
Studies. A provocative, well-researched argument which might find reapplication
in philosophy." —Theological Book Review. Danesi returns to Vico to
create a persuasive, original account of the evolution and development of
language, one of the deep mysteries of human existence. The Vico’s reconstruction
of the origin of language is described at length, then evaluated in light of Grice’s
philosophical conversational pragmatics. Glottogenesis Vico’s Reconstruction. The
New Science Basic Notions. Language and the Imagination: Vito’s Glottogenetic
Scenario Vico’s Approach Reconstructing the Primal Scene After the Primal
Scence. The Dawn of Communication: Iconicity and Mimesis Hypotheses The Nature
of Iconicity. Imagery, Iconicity, and Gesture. Iconic Representation. Osmosis Hypothesis
Ontogenesis From Percepts to Concepts The Metaphoricity Metaphor Metaphor and
Concept-Formation Mentation, Narrativity, and Myth The Sociobiological-Computationist Viewpoint:A
Vichian Critique The Vichian Scenario Revisited Revisting the Genetic
Perspective computationism. Refs.: Luigi
Speranza, “Vico e Grice,” Villa Grice.
vis: When in a Latinate mood, Grice would refer to a ‘vis’
of an expression. Apparently, ‘vis’ is cognate with ‘validum,’ transf., of abstr. things, force, notion, meaning, sense, import, nature, essence (cf. significatio): “id, in quo est omnis vis amicitiae,” Cic. Lael. 4, 15: “eloquentiae vis et natura,” id. Or. 31, 112: “vis honesti (with natura),” id. Off. 1, 6, 18; cf. id. Fin. 1, 16, 50: “virtutis,” id. Fam. 9, 16, 5: “quae est alia vis legis?” id. Dom. 20, 53: “vis, natura, genera verborum et simplicium et copulatorum,” i.e. the sense, signification, id. Or. 32, 115: “vis verbi,” id. Inv. 1, 13, 17; id. Balb. 8, 21: “quae vis insit in his paucis verbis, si attendes, si attendes, intelleges,” id. Fam. 6, 2, 3: “quae vis subjecta sit vocibus,” id. Fin. 2, 2, 6: “nominis,” id. Top. 8, 35: μετωνυμία, cujus vis est, pro eo, quod dicitur, causam, propter
quam dicitur, ponere, Quint. 8, 6, 23.
vagum – Oddly, Grice does not have a conversational, ‘be
precise,’; but he did. In his earlier desideratum of conversational clarity,
the point was to make your point precise – rather than fuzzy -- vagueness, a
property of an expression in virtue of which it can give rise to a “borderline
case.” A borderline case is a situation in which the application of a
particular expression to a name of a particular object does not generate an
expression with a definite truth-value; i.e., the piece of language in question
neither unequivocally applies to the object nor fails to apply. Although such a
formulation leaves it open what the pieces of language might be whole
sentences, individual words, names or singular terms, predicates or general
terms, most discussions have focused on vague general terms and have considered
other types of terms to be nonvague. Exceptions to this have called attention
to the possibility of vague objects, thereby rendering vague the designation
relation for singular terms. The formulation also leaves open the possible
causes for the expression’s lacking a definite truth-value. If this
indeterminacy is due to there being insufficient information available to
determine applicability or non-applicability of the term i.e., we are convinced
the term either does or does not apply, but we just do not have enough
information to determine which, then this is sometimes called epistemic
vagueness. It is somewhat misleading to call this vagueness, for unlike true
vagueness, this epistemic vagueness disappears if more information is brought
into the situation. ‘There are between 1.89 $ 106 and 1.9 $ 106 stars in the
sky’ is epistemically vague but is not vague in the generally accepted sense of
the term. ’Vagueness’ may also be used to characterize non-linguistic items
such as concepts, memories, and objects, as well as such semilinguistic items
as statements and propositions. Many of the issues involved in discussing the
topic of vagueness impinge upon other philosophical topics, such as the
existence of truth-value gaps
declarative sentences that are neither true nor false and the plausibility of many-valued logic.
There are other related issues such as the nature of propositions and whether
they must be either true or false. We focus here on linguistic vagueness, as it
manifests itself with general terms; for it is this sort of indeterminacy that
defines what most researchers call vagueness, and which has led the push in
some schools of thought to “eliminate vagueness” or to construct languages that
do not manifest vagueness. Linguistic vagueness is sometimes confused with
other linguistic phenomena: generality, ambiguity, and open texture. Statements
can be general ‘Some wheelbarrows are red’, ‘All insects have antennae’ and if
there is no other vagueness infecting them, they are true or false and not borderline or vague. Terms can be
general ‘person’, ‘dog’ without being vague. Those general terms apply to many
different objects but are not therefore vague; and furthermore, the fact that
they apply to different kinds of objects ‘person’ applies to both men and women
also does not show them to be vague or ambiguous. A vague term admits of
borderline cases a completely
determinate situation in which there just is no correct answer as to whether
the term applies to a certain object or not
and this is not the case with generality. Ambiguous linguistic items,
including structurally ambiguous sentences, also do not have this feature
unless they also contain vague terms. Rather, an ambiguous sentence allows
there to be a completely determinate situation in which one can simultaneously
correctly affirm the sentence and also deny the sentence, depending on which of
the claims allowed by the ambiguities is being affirmed or denied. Terms are
considered open-textured if they are precise along some dimensions of their
meaning but where other possible dimensions simply have not been considered. It
would therefore not be clear what the applicability of the term would be were
objects to vary along these other dimensions. Although related to vagueness,
open texture is a different notion. Friedrich Waismann, who coined the term,
put it this way: “Open texture . . . is something like the possibility of
vagueness.” Vagueness has long been an irritant to philosophers of logic and
language. Among the oldest of the puzzles associated with vagueness is the
sorites ‘heap’ paradox reported by Cicero Academica 93: One grain of sand does
not make a heap, and adding a grain of sand to something that is not a heap
will not create a heap; there945 V 945
fore there are no heaps. This type of paradox is traditionally attributed to
Zeno of Elea, who said that a single millet seed makes no sound when it falls,
so a basket of millet seeds cannot make a sound when it is dumped. The term
‘sorites’ is also applied to the entire series of paradoxes that have this
form, such as the falakros ‘bald man’, Diogenes Laertius, Grammatica II, 1, 45:
A man with no hairs is bald, and adding one hair to a bald man results in a
bald man; therefore all men are bald. The original version of these sorites
paradoxes is attributed to Eubulides Diogenes Laertius II, 108: “Isn’t it true
that two are few? and also three, and also four, and so on until ten? But since
two are few, ten are also few.” The linchpin in all these paradoxes is the
analysis of vagueness in terms of some underlying continuum along which an
imperceptible or unimportant change occurs. Almost all modern accounts of the
logic of vagueness have assumed this to be the correct analysis of vagueness,
and have geared their logics to deal with such vagueness. But we will see below
that there are other kinds of vagueness too. The search for a solution to the
sorites-type paradoxes has been the stimulus for much research into alternative
semantics. Some philosophers, e.g. Frege, view vagueness as a pervasive defect
of natural language and urge the adoption of an artificial language in which
each predicate is completely precise, without borderline cases. Russell too
thought vagueness thoroughly infected natural language, but thought it
unavoidable and indeed beneficial for ordinary usage and discourse. Despite the
occasional argument that vagueness is pragmatic rather than a semantic
phenomenon, the attitude that vagueness is inextricably bound to natural language
together with the philosophical logician’s self-ascribed task of formalizing
natural language semantics has led modern writers to the exploration of
alternative logics that might adequately characterize vagueness i.e., that would account for our pretheoretic
beliefs concerning truth, falsity, necessary truth, validity, etc., of
sentences containing vague predicates. Some recent writers have also argued
that vague language undermines realism, and that it shows our concepts to be
“incoherent.” Long ago it was seen that the attempt to introduce a third
truth-value, indeterminate, solved nothing
replacing, as it were, the sharp cutoff between a predicate’s applying
and not applying with two sharp cutoffs. Similar remarks could be made against
the adoption of any finitely manyvalued logic as a characterization of
vagueness. In the late 0s and early 0s, fuzzy logic was introduced into the
philosophic world. Actually a restatement of the Tarski-Lukasiewicz
infinitevalued logics of the 0s, one of the side benefits of fuzzy logics was
claimed to be an adequate logic for vagueness. In contrast to classical logic,
in which there are two truth-values true and false, in fuzzy logic a sentence
is allowed to take any real number between 0 and 1 as a truthvalue.
Intuitively, the closer to 1 the value is, the “more true” the sentence is. The
value of a negated sentence is 1 minus the value of the unnegated sentence;
conjuction is viewed as a minimum function and disjunction as a maximum
function. Thus, a conjunction takes the value of the “least true” conjunct,
while a disjunction takes the value of the “most true” disjunct. Since vague
sentences are maximally neither true nor false, they will be valued at
approximately 0.5. It follows that if F is maximally vague, so is the negation
-F; and so are the conjunction F & -F and the disjunction ~F 7 -F. Some
theorists object to these results, but defenders of fuzzy logic have argued in
favor of them. Other theorists have attempted to capture the elusive logic of
vagueness by employing modal logic, having the operators AF meaning ‘F is
definite’ and B F meaning ‘F is vague’. The logic generated in this way is
peculiar in that A F & YPAF & AY is not a theorem. E.g., p & -p is
definitely false, hence definite; hence A p & -p. Yet neither p nor -p need
be definite. Technically, it is a non-Kripke-normal modal logic. Some other
peculiarities are that AF Q A -F is a theorem, and that AFPBF is not. There are
also puzzles about whether B FP ABF should be a theorem, and about iterated
modalities in general. Modal logic treatments of vagueness have not attracted
many advocates, except as a portion of a general epistemic logic i.e., modal
logics might be seen as an account of so-called epistemic vagueness. A third
direction that has been advocated as a logical account of vagueness has been
the method of supervaluations sometimes called “supertruth”. The underlying
idea here is to allow the vague predicate in a sentence to be “precisified” in
an arbitrary manner. Thus, for the sentence ‘Friar Tuck is bald’, we
arbitrarily choose a precise number of hairs on the head that will demarcate
the bald/not-bald border. In this valuation Friar Tuck is either definitely
bald or definitely not bald, and the sentence either is true or is false. Next,
we alter the valuation so that there is some other bald/not-bald
bordervagueness vagueness 946 946 line,
etc. A sentence true in all such valuations is deemed “really true” or
“supertrue”; one false in all such valuations is “really false” or
“superfalse.” All others are vague. Note that, in this conception of vagueness,
if F is vague, so is -F. However, unlike fuzzy logic ‘F & -F’ is not
evaluated as vague it is false in every
valuation and hence is superfalse. And ‘F 7 -F’ is supertrue. These are seen by
some as positive features of the method of supervaluations, and as an argument
against the whole fuzzy logic enterprise. In fact there seem to be at least two
distinct types of linguistic vagueness, and it is not at all clear that any of
the previously mentioned logic approaches can deal with both. Without going
into the details, we can just point out that the “sorites vagueness” discussed
above presumes an ordering on a continuous underlying scale; and it is the
indistinguishability of adjacent points on this scale that gives rise to
borderline cases. But there are examples of vague terms for which there is no
such scale. A classic example is ‘religion’: there are a number of factors
relevant to determining whether a social practice is a religion. Having none of
these properties guarantees failing to be a religion, and having all of them
guarantees being one. However, there is no continuum of the sorites variety
here; for example, it is easy to distinguish possessing four from possessing
five of the properties, unlike the sorites case where such a change is
imperceptible. In the present type of vagueness, although we can tell these
different cases apart, we just do not know whether to call the practice a
religion or not. Furthermore, some of the properties or combinations of
properties are more important or salient in determining whether the practice is
a religion than are other properties or combinations. We might call this family
resemblance vagueness: there are a number of clearly distinguishable conditions
of varying degrees of importance, and family resemblance vagueness is
attributed to there being no definite answer to the question, How many of which
conditions are necessary for the term to apply? Other examples of family
resemblance vagueness are ‘schizophrenia sufferer’, ‘sexual perversion’, and
the venerable ‘game’. A special subclass of family resemblance vagueness occurs
when there are pairs of underlying properties that normally co-occur, but
occasionally apply to different objects. Consider, e.g., ‘tributary’. When two
rivers meet, one is usually considered a tributary of the other. Among the
properties relevant to being a tributary rather than the main river are:
relative volume of water and relative length. Normally, the shorter of the two
rivers has a lesser volume, and in that case it is the tributary of the other.
But occasionally the two properties do not co-occur and then there is a
conflict, giving rise to a kind of vagueness we might call conflict vagueness.
The term ‘tributary’ is vague because its background conditions admit of such
conflicts: there are borderline cases when these two properties apply to
different objects. To conclude: the fundamental philosophical problems
involving vagueness are 1 to give an adequate characterization of what the
phenomenon is, and 2 to characterize our ability to reason with these terms.
These were the problems for the ancient philosophers, and they remain the
problems for modern philosophers. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “The conversational maxim
for vagueness avoidance.”
vaihinger: Grice once gave a seminar on Vaihinger – “but
thinking it would not attract that many, I titled it ‘As if.’” – H. P. Grice. philosopher
best known for Die Philosophie des Als Ob; tr. by C. K. Ogden as The Philosophy
of “As If” in 4. A neo-Kantian, he was also influenced by Schopenhauer and
Nietzsche. His commentary on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason 2 vols., 1 is still
a standard work. Vaihinger was a cofounder of both the Kant Society and
Kant-Studien. The “philosophy of the as if” involves the claim that values and
ideals amount only to “fictions” that serve “life” even if they are irrational.
We must act “as if” they were true because they have biological utility.
valentinianism: a form of Christian gnosticism of Alexandrian origin,
founded by Valentinus in the second century and propagated by Theodotus in
Eastern, and Heracleon in Western, Christianity. To every gnostic, pagan or
Christian, knowledge leads to salvation from the perishable, material world.
Valentinianism therefore prompted famous refutations by Tertullian Adversus
Valentinianos and Irenaeus Adversus haereses. The latter accused the
Valentinians of maintaining “creatio ex nihilo.” Valentinus is believed to have
authored the Peri trion phuseon, the Evangelium veritatis, and the Treatise on
the Resurrection. Since only a few fragments of these remain, his Neoplatonic
cosmogony is accessible mainly through his opponents and critics Hippolytus,
Clement of Alexandria and in the Nag Hammadi codices. To explain the origins of
creation and of evil, Valentinus separated God primal Father from the Creator
Demiurge and attributed the cruVaihinger, Hans Valentinianism 947 947 cial role in the processes of emanation
and redemption to Sophia.
valentinus: gnostic teacher, born in Alexandria, where he taught
until he moved to Rome. A dualist, he constructed an elaborate cosmology in
which God the Father Bythos, or Deep Unknown unites the the feminine Silence
Sige and in the overflow of love produces thirty successive divine emanations
or aeons constituting the Pleroma fullness of the Godhead. Each emanation is
arranged hierarchically with a graded existence, becoming progressively further
removed from the Father and hence less divine. The lowest emanation, Sophia
wisdom, yields to passion and seeks to reach, beyond her ability, to the
Father, which causes her fall. In the process, she causes the creation of the
material universe wherein resides evil and the loss of divine sparks from the
Pleroma. The divine elements are embodied in those humans who are the elect.
Jesus Christ is an aeon close to the Father and is sent to retrieve the souls
into the heavenly Pleroma. Valentinus wrote a gospel. His sect stood out in the
early church for ordaining women priests and prophetesses. Grice: “Since he
lived in Rome, he was almost a Roman.” – Refs.: Luigi Speranza, “Valentinus e
Grice,” Villa Grice.
valla: l. humanist and historian who taught rhetoric in
Pavia and was later secretary of King Alfonso I of Aragona in Naples, and
apostolic secretary in Rome under Pope Nicholas V. In his dialogue On Pleasure
or On the True Good 143134, Stoic and Epicurean interlocutors present their
ethical views, which Valla proceeds to criticize from a Christian point of
view. This work is often regarded as a defense of Epicurean hedonism, because
Valla equates the good with pleasure; but he claims that Christians can find
pleasure only in heaven. His description of the Christian pleasures reflects
the contemporary Renaissance attitude toward the joys of life and might have
contributed to Valla’s reputation for hedonism. In the later work, On Free Will
between 1435 and 1448, Valla discusses the conflict between divine
foreknowledge and human freedom and rejects Boethius’s then predominantly
accepted solution. Valla distinguishes between God’s knowledge and God’s will,
but denies that there is a rational solution of the apparent conflict between
God’s will and human freedom. As a historian, he is famous for The Donation of
Constantine 1440, which denounces as spurious the famous document on which
medieval jurists and theologians based the papal rights to secular power. Refs.:
Luigi Speranza, “Valla e Grice,” Villa Grice.
No comments:
Post a Comment