sub-gestum -- suggestio falsi – suggest. To suggest is
like to ‘insinuate,’ only different. The root involves a favourite with Grice,
‘a gesture.’ That gesture is very suggesture. Grice explores hint versus
suggest in Retrospective epilogue. Also cited by Strawson and Wiggins. The
emissor’s implication is exactly this suggestio, for which suggestum. To suggest, advise, prompt, offer, bring to mind: “quoties aequitas restitutionem suggerit,” Dig. 4, 6, 26 fin.;
cf.: “quae (res) suggerit, ut Italicarum rerum esse credantur eae res,” reminds, admonishes, ib. 28, 5, 35 fin.: “quaedam de republicā,” Aur. Vict. Vir. Ill. 66, 2. — Absol.: “suggerente conjuge,” at the instigation of, Aur. Vict. Epit. 41, 11; cf.: “suggerente irā,” id. ib. 12, 10 suggestio falsi. Pl. suggestiones
falsi. [mod.L., = suggestion of what is false.] A misrepresentation
of the truth whereby something incorrect is implied to be true; an indirect
lie. Often in contexts with suppressio veri. QUOTES: 1815 H.
Maddock Princ. & Pract. Chancery I. 208 Whenever Suppressio veri or
Suggestio falsi occur..they afford a sufficient ground for setting aside any
Release or Conveyance. 1855 Newspaper & Gen. Reader's Pocket
Compan. i.4 He was bound to say that the suppressio veri on that occasion
approached very nearly to a positive suggestio falsi. 1898 Kipling
Stalky & Co. (1899) 36 It seems..that they had held back material
facts; that they were guilty both of suppressio veri and suggestio falsi.
1907 W. de Morgan Alice-for-Short xxxvi. 389 That's suppressio veri
and suggestio falsi! Besides, it's fibs! 1962 J. Wilson Public
Schools & Private Practice i. 19 It is rare to find a positively
verifiable untruth in a school brochure: but it is equally rare not to find a
great many suggestiones falsi, particularly as regards the material comfort and
facilities available. 1980 D. Newsome On Edge of Paradise 7
There are undoubted cases of suppressio veri; on the other hand, he appears to
eschew suggestio falsi. --- Fibs indeed. Suppress, suggest.
Write: "Griceland, Inc." "Yes, I agree to
become a Doctor in Gricean Studies" EXAM QUESTION: 1.
Discuss suggestio falsi in terms of detachability. 2. Compare suppresio
veri and suggestion falsi in connection with "The king of France is
bald" uttered during Napoleon's time. 3. Invent things for
'suppressio falsi' and 'suggestio veri'. 4. No. You cannot go to the
bathroom.
sub-gestum --
suggestum: not necesarilyy ‘falsi.’
The verb is ‘to suggest that…’ which is diaphanous. Note that the ‘su-‘ stands
for ‘sub-‘ which conveys the implicitness or covertness of the impicatum.
Indirectness. It’s ‘under,’ not ‘above’ board.’ To suggest, advise, prompt,
offer, bring to mind: “quoties aequitas restitutionem suggerit,” Dig. 4, 6, 26
fin.; cf.: “quae (res) suggerit, ut Italicarum rerum esse credantur eae res,”
reminds, admonishes, ib. 28, 5, 35 fin.: “quaedam de republicā,” Aur. Vict.
Vir. Ill. 66, 2. — Absol.: “suggerente conjuge,” at the instigation of, Aur.
Vict. Epit. 41, 11; cf.: “suggerente irā,” id. ib. 12, 10.— The implicaturum is
a suggestum – ALWAYS cancellable. Or not? Sometimes not, if ‘reasonable,’ but
not ‘rational.’ Jill suggests that Jack is brave when she says, “He is an
Englishman, he is; therefore, brave.” The tommy suggests that her povery
contrasts with her honesty (“’Tis the same the whole world over.”) So the
‘suggestum’ is like the implicaturum. A particular suggesta are ‘conversational
suggestum.’ For Grice this is philosophically important, because many
philosophical adages cover ‘suggesta’ which are not part of the philosopher’s
import! Vide Holdcroft, “Some forms of indirect communication.”
sub-pressum
-- suppresum veri: This is a bit like
an act of omission – about which Urmson once asked, “Is that ‘to do,’ Grice?” –
Strictly, it is implicatural. “Smith has a beautiful handwriting.” Grice’s
abductum: “He must be suppressing some ‘veri,’ but surely the ‘suggestio falsi’
is cancellable. On the other hand, my abent-minded uncle, who ‘suppresses,’ is
not ‘implicating.’ The ‘suppressio’ has to be ‘intentional,’ as an ‘omission’
is. Since for the Romans, the ‘verum’ applied to a unity (alethic/practical)
this was good. No multiplication, but unity – cf. untranslatable (think) –
modality ‘the ‘must’, neutral – desideratum-doxa – think – Yes, when
Untranslatable discuss ‘vero’ they do say it applies to ‘factual’ and
sincerity, I think. At Collections, the expectation is that Grice gives a
report on the philosopher’s ability – not on
his handwriting. It is different when Grice applied to St. John’s. “He
doesn’t return library books.” G. Richardson. Why did he use this on two
occasions? In “Prolegomena,” he uses it for his desideratum of conversational
fortitude (“make a strong conversational move”). To suppress. suggestio falsi.
Pl. suggestiones falsi. [mod.L., = suggestion of what is false.] A
misrepresentation of the truth whereby something incorrect is implied to be
true; an indirect lie. Often in contexts with suppressio veri. QUOTES:
1815 H. Maddock Princ. & Pract. Chancery I. 208 Whenever Suppressio
veri or Suggestio falsi occur..they afford a sufficient ground for setting
aside any Release or Conveyance. 1855 Newspaper & Gen. Reader's
Pocket Compan. i.4 He was bound to say that the suppressio veri on that
occasion approached very nearly to a positive suggestio falsi. 1898
Kipling Stalky & Co. (1899) 36 It seems..that they had held back
material facts; that they were guilty both of suppressio veri and suggestio
falsi. 1907 W. de Morgan Alice-for-Short xxxvi. 389 That's
suppressio veri and suggestio falsi! Besides, it's fibs! 1962 J.
Wilson Public Schools & Private Practice i. 19 It is rare to find a
positively verifiable untruth in a school brochure: but it is equally rare not
to find a great many suggestiones falsi, particularly as regards the material
comfort and facilities available. 1980 D. Newsome On Edge of
Paradise 7 There are undoubted cases of suppressio veri; on the other
hand, he appears to eschew suggestio falsi. --- Fibs indeed. Suppress,
suggest. Write: "Griceland, Inc." "Yes,
I agree to become a Doctor in Gricean Studies" EXAM
QUESTION: 1. Discuss suggestio falsi in terms of detachability. 2.
Compare suppresio veri and suggestion falsi in connection with "The king
of France is bald" uttered during Napoleon's time. 3. Invent things
for 'suppressio falsi' and 'suggestio veri'. 4. No. You cannot go to the
bathroom.
summum genus. What adjective is the ‘sumum’ translating, Grice
wondered. And he soon found out. We know that the Romans were unoriginally
enough with their ‘genus’ (cf. ‘gens’) translating Grecian ‘genos.’ The highest
category in the ‘arbor griceiana’ -- The categories. There is infimum genus, or
sub-summum. Talk of categories becomes informal in Grice when he ‘echoes’ Kant
in the mention of four ‘functions’ that generate for Kant twelve categories.
Grice however uses the functions themselves, echoing Ariskant, rather, as
‘caegory’. We have then a category of conversational quantity (involved in a
principle of maximization of conversational informativeness). We have a
category of conversational quality (or a desideratum of conversational
candour). We have a category of conversational relation (cf. Strawson’s
principle of relevance along with Strawson’s principles of the presumption of
knowledge and the presumption of ignorance). Lastly, we have a category of
conversational mode. For some reason, Grice uses ‘manner’ sometimes in lieu of
Meiklejohn’s apt translation of Kant’s modality into the shorter ‘mode.’ The
four have Aristotelian pedigree, indeed Grecian and Graeco-Roman: The quantity
is Kant’s quantitat which is Aristotle’s posotes (sic abstract) rendered in
Roman as ‘quantitas.’ Of course, Aristotle derives ‘posotes,’ from ‘poson,’ the
quantum. No quantity without quantum. The quality is Kant’s qualitat, which
again has Grecian and Graeco-Roman pediegree. It is Aristotel’s poiotes (sic in
abstract), rendered in Roman as qualitas. Again, derived from the more basic
‘poion,’ or ‘quale.’ Aristotle was unable to find a ‘-tes’ ending form for what
Kant has as ‘relation.’ ‘pros it’ is used, and first translated into Roman as
‘relatio.’ We see here that we are talking of a ‘summum genus.’ For who other
but a philosopher is going to lecture on the ‘pros it’? What Aristotle means is
that Socrates is to the right of Plato. Finally, for Grice’s mode, there is
Kant’s wrong ‘modalitat,’ since this refers to Aristotle ‘te’ and translated in
Roman as ‘modus,’ which Meiklejohn, being a better classicist than Kant,
renders as ‘mode,’ and not the pretentious sounding ‘modality.’ Now for Kant,
12 categories are involved here. Why? Because he subdivides each summum genus
into three sub-summum or ‘inferiore’ genus. This is complex. Kant would
DISAGREE with Grice’s idea that a subject can JUDGE in generic terms, say,
about the quantum. The subject has THREE scenarios. It’s best to reverse the
order, for surely unity comes before totality. One scenario, he utters a
SINGULAR or individual utterance (Grice on ‘the’). The CATEGORY is the first
category, THE UNUM or UNITAS. The one. The unity. Second scenario, he utters a
PARTICULAR utterance (Grice’s “some (at least one). Here we encounter the
SECOND category, that of PLURALITAS, the plurum, plurality. It’s a good thing Kant
forgot that the Greeks had a dual number, and that Urquhart has fourth number,
a re-dual. A third scenario: the nirvana. He utters a UNIVERSAL (totum)
utterance (Grice on “all”). The category is that of TOTUM, TOTALITAS, totality.
Kant does not deign to specify if he means substitutional or
non-substitutional. For the quale, there are again three scenarios for Kant,
and he would deny that the subject is confronted with the FUNCTION quale and be
able to formulate a judgement. The first scenario involves the subject uttering
a PROPOSITIO DEDICATIVA (Grice elaborates on this before introducing ‘not’ in
“Indicative conditionals” – “Let’s start with some unstructured amorophous
proposition.” Here the category is NOT AFFIRMATION, but the nirvana “REALITAS,”
Reality, reale.Second scenario, subject utters a PROPOSITIO ABDICATIVA (Grice
on ‘not’). While Kant does not consider affirmatio a category (why should he?),
he does consider NEGATIO a category. Negation. See abdicatum. Third scenario,
subject utters an PROPOSITIO INFINITA. Here the category is that of LIMITATION,
which is quite like NEGATIO (cf. privatio, stelesis, versus habitus or hexis),
but not quite. Possibly LIMITATUM. Regarding the ‘pros ti.’ The first scenario
involves a categorema, PROPOSITIO CATEGORICA. Here Kant seems to think that
there is ONE category called “INHERENCE AND SUBSTISTENCE or substance and
accident. There seem rather two. He will go to this ‘pair’ formulation in one
more case in the relation, and for the three under modus. If we count the
‘categorical pairs’ as being two categories. The total would not be 12
categories but 17, which is a rather ugly number for a list of categories,
unles it is not. Kant is being VERY serious here, because if he has
SUBSTISTENCE or SUBSTANCE as a category, this is SECUNDA SUBSTANTIA or
‘deutero-ousia.’ It is a no-no to count the prote ousia or PRIMA SUBSTANTIA as
a category. It is defined as THE THING which cannot be predicated of anything!
“SUMBEBEKOS” is a trick of Kant, for surely EVERYTHING BUT THE SUBSTANCE can be
seen as an ‘accidens’ (In fact, those who deny categories, reduce them to
‘attribute’, or ‘property.’ The second scenario involves an ‘if’ Grice on ‘if’
– PROPOSITIO CONDITIONALIS – hypothetike protasis -- this involves for the
first time a MOLECULAR proposition. As in the previous case, we have a
‘category pair’, which is formulated either as CAUSALITY (CAUSALITAS) and
DEPENDENCE (Dependentia), or “cause’ (CAUSA) and ‘effect’ (Effectum). Kant is
having in mind Strawson’s account of ‘if’ (The influence of P. F. Strawson on
Kant). For since this is the hypothetical, Kant is suggeseting that in ‘if p,
q’ q depends on p, or q is an effect of its cause, p. As in “If it rains, the
boots are in the closet.” (J). The third scenario also involves a molectural proposition, A
DISJUNCTUM. PROPOSITIO DISJUNCTIVA. Note that in Kant, ‘if’ before ‘or’! His implicaturum:
subordination before coordination, which makes sense. Grice on ‘or.’ FOR SOME
REASON, the category here for Kant is that of COMMUNITAS (community) or
RECIPROCITAS, reciprocity. He seems to be suggesting that if you turn to the
right or to the left, you are reciprocally forbidden to keep on going straight.
For the modus, similar. Here Kant is into modality. Again, it is best to
re-order the scenarios in terms of priority. Here it’s the middle which is
basic. The first scenario, subject utters an ASSERTORIC. The category is a
pair: EXISTENCE (how is this different from REALITY) and NON-EXISTENCE (how is
this different from negation?). He has in mind: ‘the cat is in the room,’ ‘the
room is empty.’ Second scenario, the subject doubts. subject utters a
problematical. (“The pillar box may be red”). Here we have a category pair:
POSSIBILITIAS (possibility) and, yes, IMPOSSIBILITAS – IMPOSSIBILITY. This is
odd, because ‘impossibility’ goes rather with the negation of necessity. The
third and last scenario, subject utters an APODEICTIC. Here again there is a
category pair – yielding 17 as the final number --: NECESSITAS, necessity, and
guess what, CONTINGENTIA, or contingency. Surely, possibilitas and contingentia
are almost the same thing. It may be what Grice has in mind when he blames a
philosopher to state that ‘what is actual is not also possible.’ Or not. Refs.:
H. P. Grice, “Gilbert Ryle’s criticism of Ariskant’s categories,” Ryle,
“Categories.” “The nisnamed categories.” Ryle notes that when it comes to
‘relatio,’ Kant just murders Aristotle’s idea of a ‘relation’ as in higher
than, or smaller than. – “His idea of the molecular propositions has nothing to
do with Aristotle’s ‘relation’ or ‘pros ti.’”
super-knowing. In WoW. A notion Grice detested. Grice,
“I detest superknowing.” “For that reason, I propose a closure clause – for a
communicatum to count as one, there should not be any sneaky intention.” The
use of ‘super’ is Plotinian. If God is super-good, he is not good. If someobody
superknows, he doesn’t know. This is an implicaturum. Surely it is cancellable:
“God is supergood; therefore, He is good.” “Smith superknows that p; therefore,
Smith, as per a semantic entailment, knows that p.” Grice: “The implicature
arise out of the postulate of conversational fortitude: why stop at knowing if
you can claim that Smith superknows? Why say that God is love, when He is
super-love?”
subjectum – Grecian hypokeimenon – Grice’s ‘implying,’
qua nominalization, is a category shift, a subjectification, or
objectificiation. – We have ‘employ,’ ‘imply,’ and then ‘implication,’
‘implicature, and ‘implying’ Using the participles, we have the active voice
present implicans, the active voice future, implicaturum, and the passive
perfect ‘impicatum.’ subjectivism, any philosophical view that attempts to
understand in a subjective manner what at first glance would seem to be a class
of judgments that are objectively either true or false i.e., true or false independently of what we
believe, want, or hope. There are two ways of being a subjectivist. In the
first way, one can say that the judgments in question, despite first appearances,
are really judgments about our own attitudes, beliefs, emotions, etc. In the
second way, one can deny that the judgments are true or false at all, arguing
instead that they are disguised commands or expressions of attitudes. In
ethics, for example, a subjective view of the second sort is that moral
judgments are simply expressions of our positive and negative attitudes. This
is emotivism. Prescriptivism is also a subjective view of the second sort; it
is the view that moral judgments are really commands to say “X is good” is to say, details aside,
“Do X.” Views that make morality ultimately a matter of conventions or what we
or most people agree to can also be construed as subjective theories, albeit of
the first type. Subjectivism is not limited to ethics, however. According to a
subjective view of epistemic rationality, the standards of rational belief are
the standards that the individual or perhaps most members in the individual’s
community would approve of insofar as they are interested in believing those
propositions that are true and not believing those propositions that are false.
Similarly, phenomenalists can be regarded as proposing a subjective account of
material object statements, since according to them, such statements are best
understood as complex statements about the course of our experiences.
the subiectum-obiectum-abiectumm-exiectum quartet:
Grice: subject-object dichotomy, the distinction between thinkers and what they
think about. The distinction is not exclusive, since subjects can also be
objects, as in reflexive self-conscious thought, which takes the subject as its
intended object. The dichotomy also need not be an exhaustive distinction in
the strong sense that everything is either a subject or an object, since in a
logically possible world in which there are no thinkers, there may yet be
mind-independent things that are neither subjects nor objects. Whether there
are non-thinking things that are not objects of thought in the actual world
depends on whether or not it is sufficient in logic to intend every individual
thing by such thoughts and expressions as ‘We can think of everything that
exists’. The dichotomy is an interimplicative distinction between thinkers and
what they think about, in which each presupposes the other. If there are no
subjects, then neither are there objects in the true sense, and conversely. A
subjectobject dichotomy is acknowledged in most Western philosophical
traditions, but emphasized especially in Continental philosophy, beginning with
Kant, and carrying through idealist thought in Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, and
Schopenhauer. It is also prominent in intentionalist philosophy, in the
empirical psychology of Brentano, the object theory of Meinong, Ernst Mally, and
Twardowski, and the transcendental phenomenology of Husserl. Subjectobject dichotomy
is denied by certain mysticisms, renounced as the philosophical fiction of
duality, of which Cartesian mindbody dualism is a particular instance, and
criticized by mystics as a confusion that prevents mind from recognizing its
essential oneness with the world, thereby contributing to unnecessary intellectual
and moral dilemmas.
sub-lime, neuter. sublīmie (collat.
form sublīmus , a, um: ex sublimo vertice, Cic. poët. Tusc. 2, 7, 19; Enn. ap.
Non. 169; Att. and Sall. ib. 489, 8 sq.; Lucr. 1, 340), adj. etym. dub.; perh.
sub-limen, up to the lintel; cf. sublimen (sublimem est in altitudinem elatum,
Fest. p. 306 Müll.), I.uplifted, high, lofty, exalted, elevated (mostly poet.
and in postAug. prose; not in Cic. or Cæs.; syn.: editus, arduus, celsus, altus).
I. Lit. A. In gen., high, lofty: “hic vertex nobis semper sublimis,” Verg. G.
1, 242; cf. Hor. C. 1, 1, 36: “montis cacumen,” Ov. M. 1, 666: “tectum,” id.
ib. 14, 752: “columna,” id. ib. 2, 1: “atrium,” Hor. C. 3, 1, 46: “arcus
(Iridis),” Plin. 2, 59, 60, § 151: “portae,” Verg. A. 12, 133: “nemus,” Luc. 3,
86 et saep.: os, directed upwards (opp. to pronus), Ov. M. 1, 85; cf. id. ib.
15, 673; Hor. A. P. 457: “flagellum,” uplifted, id. C. 3, 26, 11: “armenta,”
Col. 3, 8: “currus,” Liv. 28, 9.—Comp.: “quanto sublimior Atlas Omnibus in
Libyā sit montibus,” Juv. 11, 24.—Sup.: “triumphans in illo sublimissimo
curru,” Tert. Apol. 33.— B. Esp., borne aloft, uplifted, elevated, raised:
“rapite sublimem foras,” Plaut. Mil. 5, 1: “sublimem aliquem rapere (arripere,
auferre, ferre),” id. As. 5, 2, 18; id. Men. 5, 7, 3; 5, 7, 6; 5, 7, 13; 5, 8,
3; Ter. And. 5, 2, 20; id. Ad. 3, 2, 18; Verg. A. 5, 255; 11, 722 (in all these
passages others read sublimen, q. v.); Ov. M 4, 363 al.: “campi armis
sublimibus ardent,” borne aloft, lofty, Verg. A. 11, 602: sublimes in equis
redeunt, id. ib. 7, 285: “apparet liquido sublimis in aëre Nisus,” id. G. 1,
404; cf.: “ipsa (Venus) Paphum sublimis abit,” on high through the air, id. A.
1, 415: “sublimis abit,” Liv. 1, 16; 1, 34: “vehitur,” Ov. M. 5, 648 al.— C. On
high, lofty, in a high position: “tenuem texens sublimis aranea telum,” Cat.
68, 49: “juvenem sublimem stramine ponunt,” Verg. A. 11, 67: “sedens solio
sublimis avito,” Ov. M. 6, 650: “Tyrio jaceat sublimis in ostro,” id. H. 12,
179.— D. Subst.: sublīme , is, n., height; sometimes to be rendered the air:
“piro per lusum in sublime jactato,” Suet. Claud. 27; so, in sublime, Auct. B.
Afr. 84, 1; Plin. 10, 38, 54, § 112; 31, 6, 31, § 57: “per sublime volantes
grues,” id. 18, 35, 87, § 362: “in sublimi posita facies Dianae,” id. 36, 5, 4,
§ 13: “ex sublimi devoluti,” id. 27, 12, 105, § 129.—Plur.: “antiquique memor
metuit sublimia casus,” Ov. M. 8, 259: “per maria ac terras sublimaque caeli,”
Lucr. 1, 340.— II. Trop., lofty, exalted, eminent, distinguished. A. In gen.:
“antiqui reges ac sublimes viri,” Varr. R. R. 2, 4, 9; cf. Luc. 10, 378:
“mens,” Ov. P. 3, 3, 103: “pectora,” id. F. 1, 301: “nomen,” id. Tr. 4, 10,
121: “sublimis, cupidusque et amata relinquere pernix,” aspiring, Hor. A. P.
165; cf.: “nil parvum sapias et adhuc sublimia cures,” id. Ep. 1, 12,
15.—Comp.: “quā claritate nihil in rebus humanis sublimius duco,” Plin. 22, 5,
5, § 10; Juv. 8, 232.—Sup.: “sancimus supponi duos sublimissimos judices,” Cod.
Just. 7, 62, 39.— B. In partic., of language, lofty, elevated, sublime (freq.
in Quint.): “sublimia carmina,” Juv. 7, 28: “verbum,” Quint. 8, 3, 18: “clara
et sublimia verba,” id. ib.: “oratio,” id. 8, 3, 74: “genus dicendi,” id. 11,
1, 3: “actio (opp. causae summissae),” id. 11, 3, 153: “si quis sublimia
humilibus misceat,” id. 8, 3, 60 et saep.—Transf., of orators, poets, etc.:
“natura sublimis et acer,” Hor. Ep. 2, 1, 165: “sublimis et gravis et
grandiloquus (Aeschylus),” Quint. 10, 1, 66: “Trachalus plerumque sublimis,” id.
10, 1, 119.—Comp.: “sublimior gravitas Sophoclis,” Quint. 10, 1, 68: “sublimius
aliquid,” id. 8, 3, 14: “jam sublimius illud pro Archiā, Saxa atque solitudines
voci respondent,” id. 8, 3, 75.—Hence, advv. 1. Lit., aloft, loftily, on high.
(α). Form sub-līmĭter (rare ): “stare,” upright, Cato, R. R. 70, 2; so id. ib.
71: “volitare,” Col. 8, 11, 1: “munitur locus,” id. 8, 15, 1.— (β). Form
sub-līme (class. ): “Theodori nihil interest, humine an sublime putescat,” Cic.
Tusc. 1, 43, 102; cf.: “scuta, quae fuerant sublime fixa, sunt humi inventa,”
id. Div. 2, 31, 67: “volare,” Lucr. 2, 206; 6, 97: “ferri,” Cic. Tusc. 1, 17,
40; id. N. D. 2, 39, 101; 2, 56, 141 Orell. N. cr.: “elati,” Liv. 21, 30:
“expulsa,” Verg. G. 1, 320 et saep.— b. Comp.: “sublimius altum Attollit
caput,” Ov. Hal. 69.— 2. Trop., of speech, in a lofty manner, loftily (very
rare): “alia sublimius, alia gravius esse dicenda,” Quint. 9, 4, 130.
Grice’s favoured translation of Grecian ‘hypsos’ -- a
feeling brought about by objects that are infinitely large or vast such as the
heavens or the ocean or overwhelmingly powerful such as a raging torrent, huge
mountains, or precipices. The former in Kant’s terminology is the
mathematically sublime and the latter the dynamically sublime. Though the experience
of the sublime is to an important extent unpleasant, it is also accompanied by
a certain pleasure: we enjoy the feeling of being overwhelmed. On Kant’s view,
this pleasure results from an awareness that we have powers of reason that are
not dependent on sensation, but that legislate over sense. The sublime thus
displays both the limitations of sense experience and hence our feeling of
displeasure and the power of our own mind and hence the feeling of pleasure.
The sublime was an especially important concept in the aesthetic theory of the
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. Reflection on it was stimulated by the
appearance of a translation of Longinus’s Peri hypsous On the Sublime in 1674.
The “postmodern sublime” has in addition emerged in late twentieth century
thought as a basis for raising questions about art. Whereas beauty is
associated with that whose form can be apprehended, the sublime is associated
with the formless, that which is “unpresentable” in sensation. Thus, it is
connected with critiques of “the aesthetic”
understood as that which is sensuously present as a way of understanding what is important
about art. It has also been given a political reading, where the sublime
connects with resistance to rule, and beauty connects with conservative
acceptance of existing forms or structures of society.
sub-sidiarium -- subsidiarity, a basic principle of
social order and the common good governing the relations between the higher and
lower associations in a political community. Positively, the principle of
subsidiarity holds that the common good, i.e., the ensemble of social resources
and institutions that facilitate human self-realization, depends on fostering
the free, creative initiatives of individuals and of their voluntary
associations; thus, the state, in addition to its direct role in maintaining
public good which comprises justice, public peace, and public morality also has
an indirect role in promoting other aspects of the common good by rendering
assistance subsidium to those individuals and associations whose activities
facilitate cooperative human self-realization in work, play, the arts,
sciences, and religion. Negatively, the principle of subsidiarity holds that
higher-level i.e., more comprehensive associations while they must monitor, regulate, and
coordinate ought not to absorb, replace,
or undermine the free initiatives and activities of lower-level associations
and individuals insofar as these are not contrary to the common good. This presumption
favoring free individual and social initiative has been defended on various
grounds, such as the inefficiency of burdening the state with myriad local
concerns, as well as the corresponding efficiency of unleashing the free,
creative potential of subordinate groups and individuals who build up the
shared economic, scientific, and artistic resources of society. But the deeper
ground for this presumption is the view subjunctive conditional subsidiarity
886 886 that human flourishing depends
crucially on freedom for individual self-direction and for the self-government
of voluntary associations and that human beings flourish best through their own
personal and cooperative initiatives rather than as the passive consumers or
beneficiaries of the initiatives of others.
sub-sistum -- subsistence translation of G. Bestand, in current
philosophy, especially Meinong’s system, the kind of being that belongs to
“ideal” objects such as mathematical objects, states of affairs, and
abstractions like similarity and difference. By contrast, the kind of being
that belongs to “real” wirklich objects, things of the sorts investigated by
the sciences other than psychology and pure mathematics, is called existence
Existenz. Existence and subsistence together exhaust the realm of being Sein.
So, e.g., the subsistent ideal figures whose properties are investigated by
geometers do not exist they are nowhere
to be found in the real world but it is
no less true of them that they have being than it is of an existent physical
object: there are such figures. Being does not, however, exhaust the realm of
objects or things. The psychological phenomenon of intentionality shows that
there are in some sense of ‘there are’ objects that neither exist nor subsist.
Every intentional state is directed toward an object. Although one may covet
the Hope Diamond or desire the unification of Europe, one may also covet a
non-existent material object or desire a non-subsistent state of affairs. If
one covets a non-existent diamond, there is in some sense of ‘there is’
something that one covets one’s state of
mind has an object and it has certain
properties: it is, e.g., a diamond. It may therefore be said to inhabit the
realm of Sosein ‘being thus’ or ‘predication’ or ‘having properties’, which is
the category comprising the totality of objects. Objects that do not have any
sort of being, either existence or subsistence, belong to non-being Nichtsein.
In general, the properties of an object do not determine whether it has being
or non-being. But there are special cases: the round square, by its very
nature, cannot subsist. Meinong thus maintains that objecthood is ausserseiend,
i.e., independent of both existence and subsistence.
sub-statum: hypoeinai, hypostasis, hypokemeinon -- substantia – Grice:
“The Romans never felt the need for the word ‘substantia’ but trust Cicero to
force them to use it!” -- Grice lectured on this with J. L. Austin and P. F.
Strawson. hypousia -- as defined by Aristotle in the Categories, that which is
neither predicable “sayable” of anything nor present in anything as an aspect
or property of it. The examples he gives are an individual man and an
individual horse. We can predicate being a horse of something but not a horse;
nor is a horse in something else. He also held that only substances can remain
self-identical through change. All other things are accidents of substances and
exist only as aspects, properties, or relations of substances, or kinds of
substances, which Aristotle called secondary substances. An example of an
accident would be the color of an individual man, and an example of a secondary
substance would be his being a man. For Locke, a substance is that part of an
individual thing in which its properties inhere. Since we can observe, indeed
know, only a thing’s properties, its substance is unknowable. Locke’s sense is
obviously rooted in Aristotle’s but the latter carries no skeptical
implications. In fact, Locke’s sense is closer in meaning to what Aristotle
calls matter, and would be better regarded as a synonym of ‘substratum’, as indeed
it is by Locke. Substance may also be conceived as that which is capable of
existing independently of anything else. This sense is also rooted in
Aristotle’s, but, understood quite strictly, leads to Spinoza’s view that there
can be only one substance, namely, the totality of reality or God. A fourth
sense of ‘substance’ is the common, ordinary sense, ‘what a thing is made of’.
This sense is related to Locke’s, but lacks the latter’s skeptical
implications. It also corresponds to what Aristotle meant by matter, at least
proximate matter, e.g., the bronze of a bronze statue Aristotle analyzes
individual things as composites of matter and form. This notion of matter, or
stuff, has great philosophical importance, because it expresses an idea crucial
to both our ordinary and our scientific understandings of the world.
Philosophers such as Hume who deny the existence of substances hold that
individual things are mere bundles of properties, namely, the properties
ordinarily attributed to them, and usually hold that they are incapable of
change; they are series of momentary events, rather than things enduring
through time.
substantialism, the view that the primary, most
fundamental entities are substances, everything else being dependent for its
existence on them, either as a property of them or a relation between them.
Different versions of the view would correspond to the different senses of the
word ‘substance’.
Potts: English philosopher, tutee of H. P. Grice.
Semanticist of the best order! Structures and Categories
for the Representation of Meaning T.C. Potts. Potts, alla Grice, addresses the
representation problem ... how best to represent the meanings of linguistic
expressions... One might call this the 'semantic form' of expressions (p. xi,
italics in the original). The book begins with "three chapters in which I
survey the contributions made by linguistics, logic and computer science
respectively to the representation of meaning" (p. xii). These three
chapters are not easy to understand, principally because of Potts's obtuse
style, an example of which is that instead of saying "'either P or Q' is
false if 'P' and 'Q' are both false; otherwise, it is true," he says,
"we lay down that a proposition having the structure represented by 'either
P or Q' is to be accounted false if a false proposition is substituted for 'P'
and a false proposition for 'Q', but is otherwise to be accounted true"
(p. 53). These chapters are also outdated. In particular, the chapter on
computer science, discussing the work of researchers whose goals are the
closest to Potts's own stated goals, is mainly a review of work as of the
seventies. There are citations to several of the papers in Findler (1979), but
only three to more recent research publications: Hayes (1980), Sowa (1984), and
Hobbs and Shieber (1987). Perhaps the most valuable aspect of these three
chapters is Potts's criticisms of some of the work he surveys. Of course, some
of the problems noted have been corrected in literature that Potts hasn't yet
got around to reading. By the end of the three survey chapters, Potts has
introduced two techniques that he 427 Computational Linguistics Volume
21, Number 3 then develops into his own representation-- categorial grammars
and graphs as representation formalisms. He takes the categorial analysis to be
the prior of the two, with his graphs, which he calls categorialgraphs, being
the clearer representation of sentence meaning. Unfortunately,
"formalism" and "clearer" must be taken with a grain of
salt. Potts never formally defines his categorial graphs, let alone gives a
formal semantics for them. Although I have had extensive experience reading,
interpreting, and devising graphical representations of meaning, I could not
understand the details of Potts's graphs. But then, neither, apparently, can
he: "The relationship between semantic and syntactic structures has not
been spelled out, so that it is not fully determinate what our semantic
representations represent at the syntactic level" (p. 168). The four
substantive chapters are useful for the linguistic issues that they address,
even if they are not useful for the representation scheme that they develop.
These issues, which must eventually be faced by all knowledge representation
formalisms that aspire to complete coverage of natural language include:
quantifier scope; pronouns; relative clauses; count nouns, substance nouns, and
proper names; generic propositions; deictic terms; plurals; identity; and
adverbs. Appropriately, the book does not end on a note of claimed accomplishment,
but on a note of work yet to do: "The purpose of a philosophical book is
to stimulate thought, not to put it to rest with solutions to every problem ...
It is still premature to formulate a graph grammar for semantic representation
of everyday language... The representation problem is commonly not accorded the
respect which it deserves" (p. 288). Many people agree, and have,
accordingly, produced a vast literature that Potts is apparently not familiar
with. (Some relevant collections are Cercone and McCalla 1987, Sowa 1991, and
Lehmann 1992.) Nevertheless, Potts is still correct when he suggests that there
is much work left to do.--Stuart C. Shapiro, State University of New York at
Buffalo References Cercone, Nick and McCalla, Gordon (editors) (1987). The
Knowledge Frontier: Essays in the Representation of Knowledge. Springer-Verlag.
Findler, Nicholas V. (editor) (1979). Associative Networks: The Representation
and Use of Knowledge in Computers. Academic Press. Hayes, Patrick J. (1980).
"The logic of frames." In Frame Conceptions and Text Understanding,
edited by Dieter Metzing, 46-61. de Gruyter, 1980. Also in Readings in
Knowledge Representation, edited by Ronald J. Brachman and Hector J. Levesque,
287-295. Morgan Kaufmann. 1985. Hobbs, Jerry R., and Shieber, Stuart M. (1987).
"An algorithm for generating quantifier scopings." Computational
Linguistics, 13(1-2), 47-63. Lehmann, Fritz (editor) (1992). Semantic Networks
in Artificial Intelligence. Pergamon Press. Sowa, John E (1984). Conceptual Structures.
Addison-Wesley. Sowa, John F. (editor) (1991). Principles of Semantic Networks:
Explorations in the Representation of Knowledge. Morgan Kaufmann. Refs.: Luigi
Speranza, “Potts at Villa Grice.”
The salva-veritate/salva-congruitate distinction: The phrase occurs
in two fragments from Gottfried Leibniz's General Science.
Characteristics: In Chapter 19, Definition 1, Leibniz writes: "Two
terms are the same (eadem) if one can be substituted for the other without
altering the truth of any statement (salva veritate)." In Chapter 20,
Definition 1, Leibniz writes: "Terms which can be substituted for one
another wherever we please without altering the truth of any statement (salva
veritate), are the same (eadem) or coincident (coincidentia). For example,
'triangle' and 'trilateral', for in every proposition demonstrated by Euclid
concerning 'triangle', 'trilateral' can be substituted without loss of truth
(salva veritate)." ubstitutivity salva veritate: Grice: “The phrase
‘salva veritate’ has been used at Oxford for years, Kneale tells me!” -- a
condition met by two expressions when one is substitutable for the other at a
certain occurrence in a sentence and the truth-value truth or falsity of the
sentence is necessarily unchanged when the substitution is made. In such a case
the two expressions are said to exhibit substitutivity or substitutability
salva veritate literally, ‘with truth saved’ with respect to one another in
that context. The expressions are also said to be interchangeable or
intersubstitutable salva veritate in that context. Where it is obvious from a
given discussion that it is the truth-value that is to be preserved, it may be
said that the one expression is substitutable for the other or exhibits
substitutability with respect to the other at that place. Leibniz proposed to
use the universal interchangeability salva veritate of two terms in every
“proposition” in which they occur as a necessary and sufficient condition for
identity presumably for the identity of
the things denoted by the terms. There are apparent exceptions to this
criterion, as Leibniz himself noted. If a sentence occurs in a context governed
by a psychological verb such as ‘believe’ or ‘desire’, by an expression
conveying modality e.g., ‘necessarily’, ‘possibly’, or by certain temporal
expressions such as ‘it will soon be the case that’, then two terms may denote
the same thing but not be interchangeable within such a sentence. Occurrences
of expressions within quotation marks or where the expressions are both
mentioned and used cf. Quine’s example, “Giorgione was so-called because of his
size” also exhibit failure of substitutivity. Frege urged that such failures
are to be explained by the fact that within such contexts an expression does
not have its ordinary denotation but denotes instead either its usual sense or
the expression itself. Salva congruitate From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Jump to navigationJump to search Salva congruitate[1] is a Latin scholastic
term in logic, which means "without becoming ill-formed",[2] salva
meaning rescue, salvation, welfare and congruitate meaning combine, coincide,
agree. Salva Congruitate is used in logic to mean that two terms may be
substituted for each other while preserving grammaticality in all
contexts.[3][4] Contents 1 Remarks on
salva congruitate 1.1 Timothy C. Potts 1.2 Bob Hale 2See also 3References
Remarks on salva congruitate Timothy C. Potts Timothy C. Potts describes salva
congruitate as a form of replacement in the context of meaning. It is a
replacement which preserves semantic coherence and should be distinguished from
a replacement which preserves syntactic coherence but may yield an expression
to which no meaning has been given. This means that supposing an original
expression is meaningful, the new expression obtained by the replacement will
also be meaningful, though it will not necessarily have the same meaning as the
original one, nor, if the expression in question happens to be a proposition,
will the replacement necessarily preserve the truth value of the original.[5] Bob Hale Bob Hale explains salva congruitate,
as applied to singular terms, as substantival expressions in natural language,
which are able to replace singular terms without destructive effect on the
grammar of a sentence.[6] Thus the singular term 'Bob' may be replaced by the
definite description 'the first man to swim the English Channel' salva
congruitate. Such replacement may shift both meaning and reference, and so, if
made in the context of a sentence, may cause a change in truth-value. Thus terms
which may be interchanged salva congruitate may not be interchangeable salva
veritate (preserving truth). More generally, expressions of any type are
interchangeable salva congruitate if and only if they can replace one another
preserving grammaticality or well-formedness.
See also Salva veritate Reference principle Referential opacity Crispin
Wright Peter Geach References W.V.O.
Quine, Philosophy of logic Dr. Benjamin
Schnieder, Canonical Property Designators, P9
W.V.O. Quine, Quiddities, P204
W.V.O. Quine, Philosophy of Logic, P18
Timothy C. Potts, Structures and categories for the representation of
meaning, p57 Bob Hale, Singular Terms,
P34 Categories: Concepts in logicPhilosophical logicPhilosophy of languageLatin
logical phrases. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Implicaturum salva veritate,” H. P.
Grice, “What I learned from T. C. Potts.” – T. C. Potts, “My tutorials with
Grice at St. John’s.”
summum bonum: Grice: “that in relation to which all
other things have at most instrumental value value only insofar as they are
productive of what is the highest good. Philosophical conceptions of the summum
bonum have for the most part been teleological in character. That is, they have
identified the highest good in terms of some goal or goals that human beings, it
is supposed, pursue by their very nature. These natural goals or ends have
differed considerably. For the theist, this end is God; for the rationalist, it
is the rational comprehension of what is real; for hedonism, it is pleasure;
etc. The highest good, however, need not be teleologically construed. It may
simply be posited, or supposed, that it is known, through some intuitive
process, that a certain type of thing is “intrinsically good.” On such a view,
the relevant contrast is not so much between what is good as an end and what is
good as a means to this end, as between what is good purely in itself and what
is good only in combination with certain other elements the “extrinsically
good”. Perhaps the best example of such a view of the highest good would be the
position of Moore. Must the summum bonum be just one thing, or one kind of
thing? Yes, to this extent: although one could certainly combine pluralism the
view that there are many, irreducibly different goods with an assertion that
the summum bonum is “complex,” the notion of the highest good has typically
been the province of monists believers in a single good, not pluralists.
Urmson’s super-erogation: ‘super-erogatum --. 1520s, "performance of more than duty requires,"
in Catholic theology, from Late Latin supererogationem (nominative
supererogatio) "a payment in addition," noun of action from past
participle stem of supererogare "pay or do additionally," from Latin
super "above, over" (see super-) + erogare "pay out," from
ex "out" (see ex-) + rogare "ask, request," apparently a
figurative use of a PIE verb meaning literally "to stretch out (the
hand)," from root *reg- "move in a straight line." Grice
got interested in this thanks to J. O. Urmson who discussed his ‘saints and
heroes’ with the Saturday morning kindergarten held by Austin -- the property
of going beyond the call of duty. Supererogatory actions are sometimes equated
with actions that are morally good in the sense that they are encouraged by
morality but not required by it. Sometimes they are equated with morally
commendable actions, i.e., actions that indicate a superior moral character. It
is quite common for morally good actions to be morally commendable and vice
versa, so that it is not surprising that these two kinds of supererogatory
actions are not clearly distinguished even though they are quite distinct.
Certain kinds of actions are not normally considered to be morally required,
e.g., giving to charity, though morality certainly encourages doing them.
However, if one is wealthy and gives only a small amount to charity, then,
although one’s act is supererogatory in the sense of being morally good, it is
not supererogatory in the sense of being morally commendable, for it does not
indicate a superior moral character. Certain kinds of actions are normally
morally required, e.g., keeping one’s promises. However, when the harm or risk
of harm of keeping one’s promise is sufficiently great compared to the harm
caused by breaking the promise to excuse breaking the promise, then keeping one’s
promise counts as a supererogatory act in the sense of being morally
commendable. Some versions of consequentialism claim that everyone is always
morally required to act so as to bring about the best consequences. On such a
theory there are no actions that are morally encouraged but not required; thus,
for those holding such theories, if there are supererogatory acts, they must be
morally commendable. Many versions of non-consequentialism also fail to provide
for acts that are morally encouraged but not morally required; thus, if they
allow for supererogatory acts, they must regard them as morally required acts
done at such significant personal cost that one might be excused for not doing
them. The view that all actions are either morally required, morally
prohibited, or morally indifferent makes it impossible to secure a place for
supererogatory acts in the sense of morally good acts. This view that there are
no acts that are morally encouraged but not morally required may be the result
of misleading terminology. Both Kant and Mill distinguish between duties of
perfect obligation and duties of imperfect obligation, acknowledging that a
duty of imperfect obligation does not specify any particular act that one is
morally required to do. However, since they use the term ‘duty’ it is very easy
to view all acts falling under these “duties” as being morally required. One
way of avoiding the view that all morally encouraged acts are morally required
is to avoid the common philosophical misuse of the term ‘duty’. One can replace
‘duties of perfect obligation’ with ‘actions required by moral rules’ and
‘duties of imperfect obligation’ with ‘actions encouraged by moral ideals’.
However, a theory that includes the kinds of acts that are supererogatory in
the sense of being morally good has to distinguish between that sense of
‘supererogatory’ and the sense meaning ‘morally commendable’, i.e., indicating
a superior moral character in the agent. For as pointed out above, not all
morally good acts are morally commendable, nor are all morally commendable acts
morally good, even though a particular act may be supererogatory in both
senses. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Urmson’s supererogation,” H. P. Grice, “Urmson no
saint, hero perhaps –.” H. P. Grice, “Urmson, my hero.”
Hareian supervenience: a dependence relation between
properties or facts of one type, and properties or facts of another type. In
the other place, G. E. Moore, for instance, holds that the property intrinsic
value is dependent in the relevant way on certain non-moral properties. Moore
did not employ the expression ‘supervenience’. As Moore puts it, “if a given
thing possesses any kind of intrinsic value in a certain degree, not only must that same thing possess it,
under all circumstances, in the same degree, but also anything exactly like it,
must, under all circumstances, possess it in exactly the same degree” (Philosophical
Studies, 2). The concept of supervenience, as a relation between properties, is
essentially this: A poperties of type A is supervenient (or better, as Grice
prefesrs, supervenes) on a property of type B if and only if two objects cannot
differ with respect to their A-properties without also differing with respect
to their B-properties. Properties that allegedly are supervenient on others are
often called consequential properties, especially in ethics; the idea is that
if something instantiates a moral property, then it does so in virtue of, i.e.,
as a non-causal consequence of, instantiating some lower-level property on
which the moral property supervenes. In another, related sense, supervenience
is a feature of discourse of one type, vis-à-vis discourse of another type.
‘Supervenience’ is so used by Hare. “First, let us take that characteristic of
“good” which has been called its ‘supervenience.’” Grice: “Hare has a good ear
for the neologism: he loved my ‘implicature,’ and used in an essay he submitted
to “Mind,” way before I ventured to publish the thing!” – “Suppose that we say,
“St. Francis is a good man.” It is logically impossible to say this and to
maintain at the same time that there might have been another man placed exactly
in the same circumstances as St. Francis, and who behaved in exactly the same
way, but who differed from St. Francis in this respect only, that it is NOT the
case that this man is a good man.” (“The Language of Morals”). Here the idea is
that it would be a misuse of moral language, a violation of the “logic of moral
discourse,” to apply ‘good’ to one thing but not to something else exactly
similar in all pertinent non-moral respects. Hare is a meta-ethical irrealist.
He denies that there are moral properties or facts. So for him, supervenience
is a ‘category of expression,’ a feature of discourse and judgment, not a
relation between properties or facts of two types. The notion of supervenience
has come to be used quite widely in metaphysics and philosophical philosophy, usually
in the way explained above. This use is heralded by Davidson in articulating a
position about the relation between a physical property and a property of the
‘soul,’ or statet-ypes, that eschews the reducibility of mental properties to
physical ones. “Although the position I describe denies there are psycho-physical
laws, it is consistent with the view that mental characteristics are in some
sense dependent, or supervenient, or plainly supervene on physical
characteristics. Such supervenience might be taken to mean that there cannot be
two events alike in all physical respects but differing in some mental
respects, or that an object cannot alter in some mental respects without
altering in some physical respects. Dependence or supervenience of this kind
does not entail reducibility through law or definition. “Mental Events.” A
variety of supervenience theses have been propounded in metaphysics and philosophical
psychology, usually although not always in conjunction with attempts to
formulate metaphysical positions that are naturalistic, in some way, without
being strongly reductionistic, if reductive. E. g. it is often asserted that
mental properties and facts are supervenient on neurobiological properties,
and/or on physicochemical properties and facts. And it is often claimed, more
generally, that all properties and facts are supervenient on the properties and
facts of the kind described by physics. Much attention has been directed at how
to formulate the desired supervenience theses, and thus how to characterize
supervenience itself. A distinction has been drawn between weak supervenience,
asserting that in any single possible world w, any two individuals in w that
differ in their A-properties also differ in their B-properties; and strong
supervenience, asserting that for any two individuals i and j, either within a
single possible world or in two distinct ones, if i and j differ in
A-properties then they also differ in Bproperties. It is sometimes alleged that
traditional formulations of supervenience, like Moore’s or Hare’s, articulate
only weak supervenience, whereas strong supervenience is needed to express the
relevant kind of determination or dependence. It is sometimes replied, however,
that the traditional natural-language formulations do in fact express strong
supervenience and that formalizations
expressing mere weak supervenience are mistranslations. Questions about how
best to formulate supervenience theses also arise in connection with intrinsic
and non-intrinsic properties. For instance, the property being a bank,
instantiated by the brick building on Main Street, is not supervenient on
intrinsic physical properties of the building itself; rather, the building’s
having this social-institutional property depends on a considerably broader
range of facts and features, some of which are involved in subserving the
social practice of banking. The term ‘supervenience base’ is frequently used to
denote the range of entities and happenings whose lowerlevel properties and
relations jointly underlie the instantiation of some higher-level property like
being a bank by some individual like the brick building on Main Street.
Supervenience theses are sometimes formulated so as to smoothly accommodate
properties and facts with broad supervenience bases. For instance, the idea
that the physical facts determine all the facts is sometimes expressed as
global supervenience, which asserts that any two physically possible worlds
differing in some respect also differ in some physical respect. Or, sometimes
this idea is expressed as the stronger thesis of regional supervenience, which
asserts that for any two spatiotemporal regions r and s, either within a single
physically possible world or in two distinct ones, if r and s differ in some
intrinsic respect then they also differ in some intrinsic physical respect. H.
P. Grice, “Hare on supervenience.” H. P. Grice, “Supervenience in my method in
philosophical psychology: from the banal to the bizarre.” H. P. Grice,
“Supervenience and the devil of scientism.”
sub-positum, suppositum – (literally, ‘sub-positum,’) -- cf.
presuppositum -- in the Middle Ages, reference. The theory of supposition, the
central notion in the theory of proprietates terminorum, was developed in the
twelfth century, and was refined and discussed into early modern times. It has
two parts their names are a modern convenience. 1 The theory of supposition
proper. This typically divided suppositio into “personal” reference to
individuals not necessarily to persons, despite the name, “simple” reference to
species or genera, and “material” reference to spoken or written expressions.
Thus ‘man’ in ‘Every man is an animal’ has personal supposition, in ‘Man is a
species’ simple supposition, and in ‘Man is a monosyllable’ material
supposition. The theory also included an account of how the range of a term’s
reference is affected by tense and by modal factors. 2 The theory of “modes” of
personal supposition. This part of supposition theory divided personal
supposition typically into “discrete” ‘Socrates’ in ‘Socrates is a man’,
“determinate” ‘man’ in ‘Some man is a Grecian’, “confused and distributive”
‘man’ in ‘Every man is an animal’, and “merely confused” ‘animal’ in ‘Every man
is an animal’. The purpose of this second part of the theory is a matter of
some dispute. By the late fourteenth century, it had in some authors become a
theory of quantification. The term ‘suppositio’ was also used in the Middle
Ages in the ordinary sense, to mean ‘assumption’, ‘hypothesis’. H. P. Grice,
“Implicaturum, implicatum, positum, subpositum;” H. P. Grice: “A
communicational analogy: explicatum/expositum:implicatum/impositum,” H. P.
Grice, “The positum: between the sub-positum and the supra-positum,” H. P.
Grice, “The implicaturum, the sous-entendu, and the sub-positum.”
more grice to
the mill: SOUS-ENTENDU,
-UE, part. passé, adj. et subst. masc. I. − Part. passé de sous-entendre*. A. −
Empl. impers. Il est sous-entendu que + complét. à l'ind. Il est inutile de
préciser que. Synon. il va sans dire que.Elle lui écrivit (...) que (...) elle
aurait enfin, après avoir été si souvent reçue chez eux, le plaisir de les
inviter à son tour. De lui, elle ne disait pas un mot, il était sous-entendu
que leur présence excluait la sienne (Proust,Swann,1913, p. 301). B. − Empl.
ell. à valeur de prop. part. Sous-entendu (inv., le locuteur suppléant ce qui
n'est pas exprimé mais suggéré). Ce qui signifie par là (que). Mon cher Ami,
Encore une! sous-entendu: demande de croix d'honneur (Flaub.,Corresp.,1871, p.
287). II. − Adjectif A. − Synon. implicite, tacite; anton. avoué, explicite,
formulé. 1. Qu'on laisse entendre sans l'exprimer. Le lendemain, à table, mon
mari me dit (je me demandai d'abord s'il n'y avait pas là quelque dessein
sous-entendu): − Sais-tu ce que m'a annoncé Brassy? Gurgine a essayé de se tuer
(Daniel-Rops,Mort,1934, p. 291). 2. Qui reste implicite. Je me rappelle (...)
d'avoir lu dans la déclaration des droits de l'homme cette maxime sous-entendue
dans tous les codes qu'on nous a donnés depuis: « Tout ce qui n'est pas défendu
par la loi ne peut être empêché, et nul ne peut être contraint à faire ce
qu'elle n'ordonne pas » (Bonald,Législ. primit.,t. 1, 1802, p. 152).Toute
mélodie commence par une anacrouse exprimée ou sous-entendue (D'Indy,Compos.
mus.,t. 1, 1897-1900, p. 35). B. − GRAMM. Qui n'est pas exprimé, mais que le
sens ou la syntaxe pourrait suppléer aisément. Observez qu'ainsi est tantôt
adverbe, tantôt conjonction. (...) Il est encore adverbe dans celle-ci [cette
phrase], ainsi que la vertu, le crime a ses degrés; il signifie de la même
manière. C'est que, qui est la conjonction qui lie ensemble la phrase exprimée,
le crime a ses degrés, avec la phrase sous-entendue, la vertu a ses degrés
(Destutt de Tr.,Idéol. 2,1803, p. 140).L'intelligence fait donc naturellement
usage des rapports d'équivalent à équivalent, de contenu à contenant, de cause
à effet, etc., qu'implique toute phrase, où il y a un sujet, un attribut, un
verbe, exprimé ou sous-entendu (Bergson,Évol. créatr.,1907, p. 149). III. −
Subst. masc. A. − Au sing. Comportement de celui qui sous-entend les choses
sans les exprimer explicitement. C'est la plus immense personnalité que je
connaisse [Zola], mais elle est toute dans le sous-entendu: l'homme ne parle
pas de lui, mais toutes les théories, toutes les idées, toutes les logomachies
qu'il émet combattent uniquement, à propos de tout et de n'importe quoi, en
faveur de sa littérature et de son talent (Goncourt, Journal, 1883, p. 251). B.
− P. méton. 1. Parfois péj. Ce qui est sous-entendu, insinué dans des propos ou
dans un texte, ou p. ext., par un comportement. Synon. allusion,
insinuation.Plus libre que ses confrères, il ne craignait pas, − bien
timidement encore, avec des clignements d'yeux et des sous-entendus, − de
fronder les gens en place (Rolland,J.-Chr.,Adolesc., 1905, p. 365). − Au sing.
à valeur de neutre. Henry Céard a passé avec moi toute la journée, causant du
roman qu'il fait, − et qu'il veut faire dans le gris, le voilé, le sous-entendu
(Goncourt,, Journal1878, p. 1276). − En partic. Allusion grivoise. Les
conversations fourmillaient d'allusions et de sous-entendus dont la grivoiserie
me choquait (Beauvoir,Mém. j. fille,1958, p. 165). 2. Ce qui n'est pas exprimé
explicitement. Synon. restriction, réticence.Personne ne dit: « Je suis », si
ce n'est dans une certaine attitude très instable et généralement apprise, et
on ne le dit alors qu'avec quantité de sous-entendus: il y faut parfois un long
commentaire (Valéry, Variété IV,1938, p. 228). REM. Sous-entente, subst.
fém.,vx. a) Action de sous-entendre par artifice; p. méton., ce qui est ainsi
sous-entendu. Il ne parle jamais qu'il n'y ait quelque sous-entente à ce qu'il
dit. Il y a quelque sous-entente à cela (Ac. 1798-1878). b) Gramm. Synon. de
sous-entendu. (Ds Bally 1951). Prononc. et Orth.: [suzɑ ̃tɑ ̃dy]. Ac. 1694:
sousentendu, -ue, 1718: sousentendu, -üe, dep. 1740: sous-entendu, -ue. Fréq.
abs. littér.: 249. Fréq. rel. littér.: xixes.: a) 189, b) 230; xxes.: a) 480,
b) 484. Bbg. Ducrot (O.). Le Dire et le dit. Paris, 1984, pp. 13-31. −
Kerbrat-Orecchioni (C.). L'Énonciation. De la subjectivité ds le lang. Paris,
1980, 290 p., passim.
survival: discussed by Grice in what he calls the ‘genoritorial
programme, where the philosopher posits himself as a creature-constructor. It’s
an expository device that allows to ask questions in the third person, “seeing
that we can thus avoid the so-called ‘first-person bias’” -- continued
existence after one’s biological death. So understood, survival can pertain
only to beings that are organisms at some time or other, not to beings that are
disembodied at all times as angels are said to be or to beings that are
embodied but never as organisms as might be said of computers. Theories that
maintain that one’s individual consciousness is absorbed into a universal
consciousness after death or that one continues to exist only through one’s
descendants, insofar as they deny one’s own continued existence as an
individual, are not theories of survival. Although survival does not entail
immortality or anything about reward or punishment in an afterlife, many
theories of survival incorporate these features. Theories about survival have
expressed differing attitudes about the importance of the body. supervenient
behaviorism survival 892 892 Some
philosophers have maintained that persons cannot survive without their own
bodies, typically espousing a doctrine of resurrection; such a view was held by
Aquinas. Others, including the Pythagoreans, have believed that one can survive
in other bodies, allowing for reincarnation into a body of the same species or
even for transmigration into a body of another species. Some, including Plato
and perhaps the Pythagoreans, have claimed that no body is necessary, and that
survival is fully achieved by one’s escaping embodiment. There is a similar
spectrum of opinion about the importance of one’s mental life. Some, such as
Locke, have supposed that survival of the same person would require memory of
one’s having experienced specific past events. Plato’s doctrine of
recollection, in contrast, supposes that one can survive without any
experiential memory; all that one typically is capable of recollecting are
impersonal necessary truths. Philosophers have tested the relative importance
of bodily versus mental factors by means of various thought experiments, of
which the following is typical. Suppose that a person’s whole mental life memories, skills, and character traits were somehow duplicated into a data bank and
erased from the person, leaving a living radical amnesiac. Suppose further that
the person’s mental life were transcribed into another radically amnesiac body.
Has the person survived, and if so, as whom?
swedenborgianism: the theosophy professed by a worldwide movement
established as the New Jerusalem Church in London by the followers of the
philosopher Emanuel Swedenborg. Swedenborg fuses the rationalist Cartesian and
empiricist Lockean legacies into a natural philosophy “Principia Rerum
Naturalium,” that propounds the harmony of the mechanistic universe with
biblical revelation. Inspired by Liebniz, Malebranche, Platonism, and
Neoplatonism, Swedenborg unfolds a doctrine of correspondence, “A Hieroglyphic
Key,” to account for the relation between body and soul and between the natural
and spiritual worlds, and applied it to biblical exegesis. What attracts the
wide following of the “Spirit-Seer” are his speculations in the line of Boehme
and the mystical, prophetic tradition in which he excelled, as in Heavenly
Arcana. Grice’s great uncle was a Swedenborgian.
swinburne: Grice: “Those Savoyards among us should never confuse
Swinburne, parodied in “Patience,” and the Oxonian theologian – hardly an
aesthete!” -- English philosopher of religion and of science. In philosophy of
science, he has contributed to confirmation theory and to the philosophy of
space and time. His work in philosophy of religion is the most ambitious
project in philosophical theology undertaken by a British philosopher in the
twentieth century. Its first part is a trilogy on the coherence and
justification of theistic belief and the rationality of living by that belief:
TheCoherence of Theism 7, The Existence of God 9, and Faith and Reason 1. Since
5, when Swinburne became Nolloth Professor of the Philosophy of the Christian
Religion at the of Oxford, he has
written a tetralogy about some of the most central of the distinctively
Christian religious doctrines: Responsibility and Atonement 9, Revelation 2,
The Christian God 4, and Providence and the Problem of Evil 8. The most
interesting feature of the trilogy is its contribution to natural theology.
Using Bayesian reasoning, Swinburne builds a cumulative case for theism by
arguing that its probability is raised sustaining cause Swinburne, Richard
893 893 by such things as the existence
of the universe, its order, the existence of consciousness, human opportunities
to do good, the pattern of history, evidence of miracles, and religious
experience. The existence of evil does not count against the existence of God.
On our total evidence theism is more probable than not. In the tetralogy he
explicates and defends such Christian doctrines as original sin, the Atonement,
Heaven, Hell, the Trinity, the Incarnation, and Providence. He also analyzes
the grounds for supposing that some Christian doctrines are revealed truths,
and argues for a Christian theodicy in response to the problem of evil. Refs.:
H. P. Grice, “Swinburne et moi.”
synaesthesia: cum-perceptum: co-sensibile – cum-sensibile –
co-sensatio, co-sensation -- a conscious experience in which qualities normally
associated with one sensory modality are or seem to be sensed in another.
Examples include auditory and tactile visions such as “loud sunlight” and “soft
moonlight” as well as visual bodily sensations such as “dark thoughts” and
“bright smiles.” Two features of synaesthesia are of philosophic interest.
First, the experience may be used to judge the appropriateness of sensory
metaphors and similes, such as Baudelaire’s “sweet as oboes.” The metaphor is
appropriate just when oboes sound sweet. Second, synaesthesia challenges the
manner in which common sense distinguishes among the external senses. It is
commonly acknowledged that taste, e.g., is not only unlike hearing, smell, or
any other sense, but differs from them because taste involves gustatory rather
than auditory experiences. In synaesthesia, however, one might taste sounds
sweet-sounding oboes. G.A.G. syncategoremata, 1 in grammar, words that cannot
serve by themselves as subjects or predicates of categorical propositions. The
opposite is categoremata, words that can do this. For example, ‘and’, ‘if’,
‘every’, ‘because’, ‘insofar’, and ‘under’ are syncategorematic terms, whereas
‘dog’, ‘smooth’, and ‘sings’ are categorematic ones. This usage comes from the
fifth-century Latin grammarian Priscian. It seems to have been the original way
of drawing the distinction, and to have persisted through later periods along
syllogism, demonstrative syncategoremata 896
896 with other usages described below. 2 In medieval logic from the
twelfth century on, the distinction was drawn semantically. Categoremata are
words that have a definite independent signification. Syncategoremata do not
have any independent signification or, according to some authors, not a
definite one anyway, but acquire a signification only when used in a
proposition together with categoremata. The examples used above work here as
well. 3 Medieval logic distinguished not only categorematic and syncategorematic
words, but also categorematic and syncategorematic uses of a single word. The
most important is the word ‘is’, which can be used both categorematically to
make an existence claim ‘Socrates is’ in the sense ‘Socrates exists’ or
syncategorematically as a copula ‘Socrates is a philosopher’. But other words
were treated this way too. Thus ‘whole’ was said to be used
syncategorematically as a kind of quantifier in ‘The whole surface is white’
from which it follows that each part of the surface is white, but categorematically
in ‘The whole surface is two square feet in area’ from which it does not follow
that each part of the surface is two square feet in area. 4 In medieval logic,
again, syncategoremata were sometimes taken to include words that can serve by themselves
as subjects or predicates of categorical propositions, but may interfere with
standard logical inference patterns when they do. The most notorious example is
the word ‘nothing’. If nothing is better than eternal bliss and tepid tea is
better than nothing, still it does not follow by the transitivity of ‘better
than’ that tepid tea is better than eternal bliss. Again, consider the verb
‘begins’. Everything red is colored, but not everything that begins to be red
begins to be colored it might have been some other color earlier. Such words
were classified as syncategorematic because an analysis called an expositio of
propositions containing them reveals implicit syncategoremata in sense 1 or
perhaps 2. Thus an analysis of ‘The apple begins to be red’ would include the
claim that it was not red earlier, and ‘not’ is syncategorematic in both senses
1 and 2. 5 In modern logic, sense 2 is extended to apply to all logical
symbols, not just to words in natural languages. In this usage, categoremata
are also called “proper symbols” or “complete symbols,” while syncategoremata
are called “improper symbols” or “incomplete symbols.” In the terminology of
modern formal semantics, the meaning of categoremata is fixed by the models for
the language, whereas the meaning of syncategoremata is fixed by specifying
truth conditions for the various formulas of the language in terms of the
models. H. P. Grice, “Implicatures of synaesthesia,” “Some remarks about the
senses.”
syneidesis,
conscientia -- synderesis: Grice disliked
the word as a ‘barbarism.’ Grice: “synderesis was
by most of us at the Playgroup reckoned to be a corruption of the Greician “συνείδησις” shared
knowledge, literally ‘co-ideatio,’ formed from ‘syn’ and ‘eidesis,’
‘co-vision,’ or conscience, the corruption appearing in the medieval
manuscripts of what Austin called ‘that ignorant saint,’ Jerome in his Commentary.”
Douglas Kries in Traditio vol.
57: Origen, Plato, and Conscience (Synderesis) in Jerome's Ezekiel
Commentary, p. 67. συνείδησις , εως, ἡ, A.
Liddell and Scott render as “knowledge shared with another,” -- τῶν ἀλγημάτων
(in a midwife) Sor.1.4. 2. communication, information, εὑρήσεις ς. PPar. p.422
(ii A.D.); “ς. εἰσήνεγκαν τοῖς κολλήγαις αὐτῶν” POxy. 123.13 (iii/iv A.D.). 3.
knowledge, λῦε ταῦτα πάντα μὴ διαλείψας ἀγαθῇ ς. (v.l. ἀγαθῇ τύχῃ) Hp.Ep.1. 4.
consciousness, awareness, [τῆς αὑτοῦ συστάσεως] Chrysipp.Stoic.3.43, cf.
Phld.Rh.2.140 S., 2 Ep.Cor.4.2, 5.11, 1 Ep.Pet.2.19; “τῆς κακοπραγμοσύνης”
Democr.297, cf. D.S.4.65, Ep.Hebr.10.2; “κατὰ συνείδησιν ἀτάραχοι διαμενοῦσι”
Hero Bel.73; inner consciousness, “ἐν ς. σου βασιλέα μὴ καταράσῃ” LXX Ec.
10.20; in 1 Ep.Cor.8.7 συνειδήσει is f.l. for συνηθείᾳ. 5. consciousness of
right or wrong doing, conscience, Periander and Bias ap. Stob.3.24.11,12, Luc.Am.49;
ἐὰν ἐγκλήματός τινος ἔχῃ ς. Anon. Oxy.218 (a) ii 19; “βροτοῖς ἅπασιν ἡ ς. θεός” Men.Mon.654, cf. LXX
Wi.17.11, D.H.Th.8 (but perh. interpol.); “ς. ἀγαθή” Act.Ap.23.1; ἀπρόσκοπος
πρὸς τὸν θεόν ib.24.16; “καθαρά” 1 Ep.Ti.3.9, POsl.17.10 (ii A.D.); “κολαζομένους
κατὰ συνείδησιν” Vett.Val.210.1; “θλειβομένη τῇ ς. περὶ ὧν ἐνοσφίσατο”
PRyl.116.9 (ii A.D.); τὸν . . θεὸν κεχολωμένον ἔχοιτο καὶ τὴν ἰδίαν ς.
Ath.Mitt.24.237 (Thyatira); conscientiousness, Arch.Pap.3.418.13 (vi
A.D.).--Senses 4 and 5 sts. run one into the other, v. 1 Ep.Cor.8.7, 10.27 sq.
6. complicity, guilt, crime, “περὶ τοῦ πεφημίσθαι αὐτὴν ἐν ς. τοιαύτῃ”
Supp.Epigr.4.648.13 (Lydia, ii A.D.). Grice: “The rough Romans could not do
with the ‘cum-‘ of the ‘syn-‘ but few of us at Oxford think of Laurel and Hardy
or Grice and Strawson when they say ‘conscientia’!” con-scĭo , īre, v. a. * I.
To be conscious of wrong: nil sibi, * Hor. Ep. 1, 1, 61.— II. To know well
(late Lat.): “consciens Christus, quid esset,” Tert. Carn. Chr. 3. moral theology, conscience. Jerome used ‘synderesis.’
‘Synderesis’ becomes a fixture because of Peter Lombard’s inclusion of it in
his Sentences. Despite this origin, Grecian ‘synderesis’ is distinguished from Roman
‘conscience’ (from cum-scire) -- by
Aquinas. For Aquinas, Grecian ‘synderesis’ is the quasi-habitual grasp of the
most common principles of the moral order i.e., natural law, whereas ‘conscienntia’
is the *application* of such knowledge to fleeting and unrepeatable
circumstances. ’Conscientia,’ Aquinas misleadingly claims, is allegedly ambiguous
in the way in which ‘knowledge’ is. Knowledge (Scientia) can be the mental
state of the knower or what the knower knows (scitum, cognitum) – Grice: “In
fact, Roman has four participles, active present, sciens, passive perfect,
sctium, future active, sciendus, future passive, sciturus -- But ‘conscientia’ like ‘synderesis’, is typically used for the
state of the soul. Sometimes, however, conscientia is taken to include general
moral knowledge as well as its application here and now; but the content of
synderesis is the most general precepts, whereas the content of conscience, if
general knowledge, will be less general precepts. Since conscience can be
erroneous, the question arises as to whether synderesis and its object, natural
law precepts, can be obscured and forgotten because of bad behavior or
upbringing. Aquinas holds that while great attrition can take place, such
common moral knowledge cannot be wholly expunged from the soul. This is a
version of the Aristotelian doctrine that there are starting points of
knowledge so easily grasped that the grasping of them is a defining mark of the
human being. However perversely the human agent behaves there will remain not
only the comprehensive realization that good (bonum) is to be done and evil (malum)
avoided, but also the recognition of some substantive human goods. Refs.: Luigi
Speranza, “Grice ad Aquino,” Villa Grice --. H. P. Grice, “Kenny on Aquinas,”
“Kenny uses barbaric Griceian and Grecian.”
Implicaturum: Grice fought with this. It’s a term of
art, and he mainly wants to avoid, fastidiously, equivocation. “I say
fastidiously because at Oxford, few – Hare is one of them – followed suit --.
Most stuck with ‘implicatio.’ “So, if we
stick with Roman, we have ‘implicatio.’ This gives English ‘implication,’
because the Anglo-Norman nominative proceeded via the Roman accusative, i. e.
‘implicationem.’ The use of –ure is also Anglo-Norman, for Roman ‘-ura.’ So we
have ‘implicatura,’ and in Anglo-Norman, ‘implicature.’ ‘Implicatio’ is a
feminine noun, and so is ‘implicatura.’ ‘Implicatio’ is a ‘active voice’ noun;
so is ‘implicatura.’ The Roman allows for a correlative neuter to the past
participle, ‘implicatum,’ or ‘implicitum’ (there are vowel alternation here).
So, the two neuter correlative active forms for the two neuter passive perfect
forms, ‘implicatum’ and ‘implicitum’ are ‘implicaturum’ and ‘impliciturum.’
Kneale has expanded on the use of ‘implicans.’ If ‘implicans’ is the active
PRESENT participle for ‘implicare,’ ‘implicaturum’ is the active FUTURE
participle. There is no need to specify the vehicle, as per Kneale, ‘propositio
implicans,’ ‘propositio implicata’ – Since ‘implicatura’ is definitely
constructed out of the active-voice future participle, we should have in fact a
trio, where the two second items get two variants, each: the implicans, the
implicaturum/impliciturum, and the implicatum/implicitum. Note that in the
present participle, the vowel alternation does not apply: there’s ‘implicans’
(masculine, feminine, and neuter) only, which then yields, in the neuter forms,
the future, ‘implicaturum’/’impliciturum,’ and the perfect,
‘implicatum’/’implicitum.’ The same for ‘explicare’: explicatio, explicatura,
-- explicans, yielding explicaturum/expliciturm, explicatum/explciitum. Note
that when I speak of what is seen, ‘see’ being diaphanous, I refer to ‘visum,’
what is seen. – There is no need, and in fact it is best not to, spceficy the
vehicle. The Romans used the neuter, singular, for each case --.” “If I were serious about ‘implicature’ being
feminine, I would speak of the ‘implicata’ as a singular form, but I do not. I
use ‘implicatum,’ what is implied – and use ‘implicata’ as plural neuter. Since
an implicatum is usually indeterminate, it’s best to refer to the plural,
‘implicata’ – Ditto for the ‘implicaturum,’ which becomes, in the plural,
‘implicatura.’ – the vehicles are various in that stress, emphasis, context,
all change the vehicle, somehow --. Implicatio then is like ‘conceptio,’ it is
an abstract form (strictly feminine) that has a process-producti ambiguity that
the neuter family: implicans, implicaturum/impliciturm, implicatum/implicitum
avoids. Note that while –ure form in Anglo-Norman does not derive from the
accusative, as ‘implication,’ does hence no accusative nasal ‘n’ (of
‘implicatioN,’ but not ‘implicatio’) in ‘implicature.’ The fact that the
Anglo-Normans confused it all by turning this into ‘employ,’ and ‘imply’ should
not deter the Oxonian for his delightful coinages!” Active
Nominal Forms Infinitive: implicā́re Present participle: implicāns;
implicántis Future participle: implicītúrus; implicātúrus Gerund:
implicándum Gerundive: implicándus Passive Nominal Forms Infinitive:
implicā́re Perfect participle: implicī́tum; implicā́tum. implicitura (Latin
Dictionary) lemma part voice mood tense
gender number case implicare verb active participle future feminine singularnominative
ablative vocative lemma part voice mood tense gender number case implicare verb
active participle future neuter plural nominative accusative vocative
INFLECTION Temporal inflection present – masculine implicans future – masculine
impliciturus / implicaturus present – feminine implicans future – feminine implicitura
/ implicatura present – neuter implicans future – neuter impliciturum /
implicaturum. De camptgii , vel eampacis dicemus inlra in vita Galheni apud
TtebeUtum Pollionem, ratdeiorum cajcci ISc imperatotum ita vocabantur , non
"gamba," vel "campa," qua pro crure pofteriores
wfuipatunt, quod crure tenus calcea xeniui: id k corrigiarum flexuris, &
implicaturis , quibus circumligabantur. lologiae et Mercurii di Marziano Capella
(I 68), e avanza una nuova ipotesi di ... naculis implicaturis in retia sua
praecipites implagabuntur, syllogismis tuae pro- ... miliae suae longo ordine
ac multis stemmatum inligata flexuris in
parte prima. It may be argued that when Grice compares ‘impicature’ to “the
‘implying,’ that’s a feminine form, cognate with German/Dutch, -ung. Cf. Grice,
“The conception of value” – The conceiving of value,” the concept of value, the
conceptus of value, the conceptum of value. Active
Nominal Forms Present participle: cōncipiēns; cōncipiéntis Future participle:
cōnceptúrus Passive Nominal Forms Perfect participle: cōnceptum. Since Grice
plays with this in “Conception of value,” let’s compare. “Grice: “It is worth
comparing ‘to conceive’ with ‘to employ’.” Active present participle: implicans
– concipiens, concipientis --. Active future participle:
implicaturum/impliciturm, concepturus --. Passive perfect participle:
implicatum/implicitum – conceptum. Hardie would ask, “what do you mean ‘of’?” –
The implication of implication. The conception of value. In an objective
(passive) interpretation: it’s the conceptum of ‘value’. In a subjective
(active) interpretion, it’s the ‘conceiving’ of ‘value.’ Cfr. “the love of
god,” “the fear of the enemy.” “The implication of implication.” For Grice,
it’s the SENDER who implicates, a rational agent – although he may allow for an
expression to ‘imply’ – via connotation --, and provided the sender does, or
would occasionally do. In terms of the subjective/active, and objective/passive
distinction, we would have, ‘implication,’ as in Strawson’s implication,
meaning Strawson’s ‘implying’ (originally a feminine noun), i. e. Strawson’s
‘implicatio’ and Strawson’s ‘implicatura’, and Strawson’s ‘implicature,’ and
Strawson’s ‘implicaturum’/’impliciturm.’ In terms of the passive/objective
realm, what is implied by Strawson – the implicatum, and the implicitum. There
passive interpretation allows for only one form (with two vowel alternates):
implicatum and implicitum. The active forms can be present: ‘implicans’ and
‘implicaturum’. If it’s Strawson the ‘implier’ – implicans is ‘masculine.’ If
it’s Strawson the one about to imply, it’s “Strawson implicaturus” --. By use
of the genitive – “Ciceronis” we would have, “implicatura Ciceronis” – Cicero’s
implicature --, Cicero the implier, Cicero implicans --. Surely Cicero did
something to imply. This ‘something’ is best conceived in the neuter,
‘implicans,’ as applied, say, to sententia, or propositio – ‘propositio
implicans – ‘sententia implicans’ – ‘implicatura’ would refer to the act of
implying – as the conceiving of value --. Since ‘implicatura’ is formed out of
the future participle, its corresponding form in the neuter would be
‘implicaturum.’ By his handwave (implicaturum/implicitum – qua vehicle of
Cicero’s implicature – or implicatura – his act of implying), Cicero
(implicans) implies (implicat) this or that ‘implicatum’ or ‘implicitum.’
synergism: in
soteriology, the cooperation within human consciousness of free will and divine
grace in the processes of conversion and regeneration. Synergism became an
issue in sixteenth-century Lutheranism during a controversy prompted by Philip
Melanchthon 1497 syncategorematic synergism 897 897 1569. Under the influence of Erasmus,
Melanchthon mentioned, in the 1533 edition of his Common Places, three causes
of good actions: “the Word, the Holy Spirit, and the will.” Advocated by Pfeffinger,
a Philipist, synergism was attacked by the orthodox, predestinarian, and
monergist party, Amsdorf and Flacius, who retorted with Gnesio-Lutheranism. The
ensuing Formula of Concord 1577 officialized monergism. Synergism occupies a
middle position between uncritical trust in human noetic and salvific capacity
Pelagianism and deism and exclusive trust in divine agency Calvinist and
Lutheran fideism. Catholicism, Arminianism, Anglicanism, Methodism, and
nineteenth- and twentieth-century liberal Protestantism have professed versions
of synergism.
systems
theory: the transdisciplinary study of
the abstract organization of phenomena, independent of their substance, type,
or spatial or temporal scale of existence. It investigates both the principles
common to all complex entities and the usually mathematical models that can be
used to describe them. Systems theory was proposed in the 0s by the biologist
Ludwig von Bertalanffy and furthered by Ross Ashby Introduction to Cybernetics,
6. Von Bertalanffy was both reacting against reductionism and attempting to
revive the unity of science. He emphasized that real systems are open to, and
interact with, their environments, and that they can acquire qualitatively new
properties through emergence, resulting in continual evolution. Rather than
reduce an entity e.g. the human body to the properties of its parts or elements
e.g. organs or cells, systems theory focuses on the arrangement of and
relations among the parts that connect them into a whole cf. holism. This particular
organization determines a system, which is independent of the concrete
substance of the elements e.g. particles, cells, transistors, people. Thus, the
same concepts and principles of organization underlie the different disciplines
physics, biology, technology, sociology, etc., providing a basis for their
unification. Systems concepts include: system environment boundary, input,
output, process, state, hierarchy, goal-directedness, and information. The
developments of systems theory are diverse Klir, Facets of Systems Science, 1,
including conceptual foundations and philosophy e.g. the philosophies of Bunge,
Bahm, and Laszlo; mathematical modeling and information theory e.g. the work of
Mesarovic and Klir; and practical applications. Mathematical systems theory
arose from the development of isomorphies between the models of electrical
circuits and other systems. Applications include engineering, computing,
ecology, management, and family psychotherapy. Systems analysis, developed
independently of systems theory, applies systems principles to aid a decision
maker with problems of identifying, reconstructing, optimizing, and controlling
a system usually a socio-technical organization, while taking into account
multiple objectives, constraints, and resources. It aims to specify possible
courses of action, together with their risks, costs, and benefits. Systems
theory is closely connected to cybernetics, and also to system dynamics, which
models changes in a network of synergy systems theory 898 898 coupled variables e.g. the “world
dynamics” models of Jay Forrester and the Club of Rome. Related ideas are used
in the emerging “sciences of complexity,” studying self-organization and
heterogeneous networks of interacting actors, and associated domains such as
far-from-equilibrium thermodynamics, chaotic dynamics, artificial life,
artificial intelligence, neural networks, and computer modeling and simulation.
tautologum: The difference between a truth and a tautological
truth is part of the dogma Grice defends. “A three-year old cannot understand
Russell’s theory of types” is possibly true. “It is not the case that a
three-year old is an adult” is TAUTOLOGICALLY true. As Strawson and Wiggins
note, by coining implicaturum Grice is mainly interested in having the MAN
implying this or that, as opposed to what the man implies implying this or
that. So, in Strawson and Wiggins’s rephrasing, the implicaturum is to be
distinguished with the logical and necessary implication, i. e., the
‘tautological’ implication. Grice uses ‘tautological’ variously. It is
tautological that we smell smells, for example. This is an extension of
‘paradigm-case,’ re: analyticity. Without ‘analytic’ there is no
‘tautologicum.’ tautŏlŏgĭa , ae, f., = ταυτολογία,I.a repetition of the same meaning in different words, tautology, Mart. Cap. 5, § 535; Charis,
p. 242 P. ταὐτολογ-έω ,A.repeat what has been said,
“περί τινος” Plb.1.1.3; “ὑπέρ τινος” Id.1.79.7; “τ. τὸν λόγον” Str.12.3.27:—abs., Plb.36.12.2, Phld. Po.Herc.994.30, Hermog.Inv.3.15.
Oddly why Witters restricts tautology to truth-table propositional logic,
Grice’s two examples are predicate calculus: Women are women and war is war.
4.46 GER [→OGD | →P/M] Unter den möglichen Gruppen von Wahrheitsbedingungen
gibt es zwei extreme Fälle. In dem einen Fall ist der Satz für sämtliche
Wahrheitsmöglichkeiten der Elementarsätze wahr. Wir sagen, die
Wahrheitsbedingungen sind t a u t o l o g i s c h. Im zweiten Fall ist der Satz
für sämtliche Wahrheitsmöglichkeiten falsch: Die Wahrheitsbedingungen sind k o
n t r a d i k t o r i s c h. Im ersten Fall nennen wir den Satz eine
Tautologie, im zweiten Fall eine Kontradiktion. 4.461 GER [→OGD | →P/M] Der
Satz zeigt was er sagt, die Tautologie und die Kontradiktion, dass sie nichts
sagen. Die Tautologie hat keine Wahrheitsbedingungen, denn sie ist
bedingungslos wahr; und die Kontradiktion ist unter keiner Bedingung wahr.
Tautologie und Kontradiktion sind sinnlos. (Wie der Punkt, von dem zwei Pfeile
in entgegengesetzter Richtung auseinandergehen.) (Ich weiß z. B. nichts über
das Wetter, wenn ich weiß, dass es regnet oder nicht regnet.) 4.4611 GER [→OGD
| →P/M] Tautologie und Kontradiktion sind aber nicht unsinnig; sie gehören zum
Symbolismus, und zwar ähnlich wie die „0“ zum Symbolismus der Arithmetik. 4.462
GER [→OGD | →P/M] Tautologie und Kontradiktion sind nicht Bilder der
Wirklichkeit. Sie stellen keine mögliche Sachlage dar. Denn jene lässt j e d e
mögliche Sachlage zu, diese k e i n e. In der Tautologie heben die Bedingungen
der Übereinstimmung mit der Welt—die darstellenden Beziehungen—einander auf, so
dass sie in keiner darstellenden Beziehung zur Wirklichkeit steht. 4.463 GER
[→OGD | →P/M] Die Wahrheitsbedingungen bestimmen den Spielraum, der den
Tatsachen durch den Satz gelassen wird. (Der Satz, das Bild, das Modell, sind
im negativen Sinne wie ein fester Körper, der die Bewegungsfreiheit der anderen
beschränkt; im positiven Sinne, wie der von fester Substanz begrenzte Raum,
worin ein Körper Platz hat.) Die Tautologie lässt der Wirklichkeit den
ganzen—unendlichen—logischen Raum; die Kontradiktion erfüllt den ganzen
logischen Raum und lässt der Wirklichkeit keinen Punkt. Keine von beiden kann daher
die Wirklichkeit irgendwie bestimmen. 4.464 GER [→OGD | →P/M] Die Wahrheit der
Tautologie ist gewiss, des Satzes möglich, der Kontradiktion unmöglich.
(Gewiss, möglich, unmöglich: Hier haben wir das Anzeichen jener Gradation, die
wir in der Wahrscheinlichkeitslehre brauchen.) 4.465 GER [→OGD | →P/M] Das
logische Produkt einer Tautologie und eines Satzes sagt dasselbe, wie der Satz.
Also ist jenes Produkt identisch mit dem Satz. Denn man kann das Wesentliche
des Symbols nicht ändern, ohne seinen Sinn zu ändern. 4.466 GER [→OGD | →P/M]
Einer bestimmten logischen Verbindung von Zeichen entspricht eine bestimmte
logische Verbindung ihrer Bedeutungen; j e d e b e l i e - b i g e Verbindung
entspricht nur den unverbundenen Zeichen. Das heißt, Sätze, die für jede
Sachlage wahr sind, können überhaupt keine Zeichenverbindungen sein, denn sonst
könnten ihnen nur bestimmte Verbindungen von Gegenständen entsprechen. (Und
keiner logischen Verbindung entspricht k e i n e Verbindung der Gegenstände.)
Tautologie und Kontradiktion sind die Grenzfälle der Zeichenverbindung, nämlich
ihre Auflösung. 4.4661 GER [→OGD | →P/M] Freilich sind auch in der Tautologie
und Kontradiktion die Zeichen noch mit einander verbunden, d. h. sie stehen in
Beziehungen zu einander, aber diese Beziehungen sind bedeu- tungslos, dem S y m
b o l unwesentlich. 4.46 OGD [→GER | →P/M] Among the possible groups of
truthconditions there are two extreme cases. In the one case the proposition is
true for all the truth-possibilities of the elementary propositions. We say
that the truth-conditions are tautological. In the second case the proposition
is false for all the truth-possibilities. The truth-conditions are
self-contradictory. In the first case we call the proposition a tautology, in
the second case a contradiction. 4.461 OGD [→GER | →P/M] The proposition shows
what it says, the tautology and the contradiction that they say nothing. The
tautology has no truth-conditions, for it is unconditionally true; and the
contradiction is on no condition true. Tautology and contradiction are without
sense. (Like the point from which two arrows go out in opposite directions.) (I
know, e.g. nothing about the weather, when I know that it rains or does not
rain.) 4.4611 OGD [→GER | →P/M] Tautology and contradiction are, however, not
nonsensical; they are part of the symbol- ism, in the same way that “0” is part
of the symbolism of Arithmetic. 4.462 OGD [→GER | →P/M] Tautology and
contradiction are not pictures of the reality. They present no possible state
of affairs. For the one allows every possible state of affairs, the other none.
In the tautology the conditions of agreement with the world—the presenting
relations— cancel one another, so that it stands in no presenting relation to
reality. 4.463 OGD [→GER | →P/M] The truth-conditions determine the range,
which is left to the facts by the proposition. (The proposition, the picture,
the model, are in a negative sense like a solid body, which restricts the free
movement of another: in a positive sense, like the space limited by solid
substance, in which a body may be placed.) Tautology leaves to reality the
whole infinite logical space; contradiction fills the whole logi- cal space and
leaves no point to reality. Neither of them, therefore, can in any way
determine reality. 4.464 OGD [→GER | →P/M] The truth of tautology is certain,
of propositions possible, of contradiction impossible. (Certain, possible,
impossible: here we have an indication of that gradation which we need in the
theory of probability.) 4.465 OGD [→GER | →P/M] The logical product of a
tautology and a proposition says the same as the proposition. Therefore that
product is identical with the proposition. For the essence of the symbol cannot
be altered without altering its sense. 4.466 OGD [→GER | →P/M] To a definite
logical combination of signs corresponds a definite logical combination of
their meanings; every arbitrary combination only corresponds to the unconnected
signs. That is, propositions which are true for ev- ery state of affairs cannot
be combinations of signs at all, for otherwise there could only correspond to
them definite combinations of objects. (And to no logical combination
corresponds no combination of the objects.) Tautology and contradiction are the
limiting cases of the combination of symbols, namely their dissolution. 4.4661
OGD [→GER | →P/M] Of course the signs are also combined with one another in the
tautology and contradiction, i.e. they stand in relations to one another, but
these relations are meaningless, unessential to the symbol. 4.46 P/M [→GER |
→OGD] Among the possible groups of truthconditions there are two extreme cases.
In one of these cases the proposition is true for all the truth-possibilities
of the elementary propositions. We say that the truth-conditions are tautological.
In the second case the proposition is false for all the truth-possibilities:
the truth-conditions are contradictory. In the first case we call the
proposition a tautology; in the second, a contradiction. 4.461 P/M [→GER |
→OGD] Propositions show what they say: tautolo- gies and contradictions show
that they say nothing. A tautology has no truth-conditions, since it is
unconditionally true: and a contradiction is true on no condition. Tautologies
and contradictions lack sense. (Like a point from which two arrows go out in
opposite directions to one another.) (For example, I know nothing about the
weather when I know that it is either raining or not raining.) 4.4611 P/M [→GER
| →OGD] Tautologies and contradictions are not, however, nonsensical. They are part
of the symbolism, much as ‘0’ is part of the symbolism of arithmetic. 4.462 P/M
[→GER | →OGD] Tautologies and contradictions are not pictures of reality. They
do not represent any possible situations. For the former admit all possible
situations, and latter none. In a tautology the conditions of agreement with
the world—the representational relations—cancel one another, so that it does
not stand in any representational relation to reality. 4.463 P/M [→GER | →OGD]
The truth-conditions of a proposition determine the range that it leaves open
to the facts. (A proposition, a picture, or a model is, in the negative sense,
like a solid body that restricts the freedom of movement of others, and, in the
positive sense, like a space bounded by solid substance in which there is room
for a body.) A tautology leaves open to reality the whole—the infinite whole—of
logical space: a contradiction fills the whole of logical space leaving no
point of it for reality. Thus neither of them can determine reality in any way.
4.464 P/M [→GER | →OGD] A tautology’s truth is certain, a proposition’s
possible, a contradiction’s impossible. (Certain, possible, impossible: here we
have the first indication of the scale that we need in the theory of
probability.) 4.465 P/M [→GER | →OGD] The logical product of a tautology and a
proposition says the same thing as the proposition. This product, therefore, is
identical with the proposition. For it is impossible to alter what is essential
to a symbol without altering its sense. 4.466 P/M [→GER | →OGD] What
corresponds to a determinate logical combination of signs is a determinate
logical combination of their meanings. It is only to the uncombined signs that
absolutely any combination corresponds. In other words, propositions that are
true for every situation cannot be combinations of signs at all, since, if they
were, only determinate combinations of objects could correspond to them. (And
what is not a logical combination has no combination of objects corresponding
to it.) Tautology and contradiction are the limiting cases—indeed the
disintegration—of the combination of signs. 4.4661 P/M [→GER | →OGD] Admittedly
the signs are still combined with one another even in tautologies and
contradictions—i.e. they stand in certain relations to one another: but these
relations have no meaning, they are not essential to the symbol. Grice would
often use ‘tautological,’ and ‘self-contradiction’ presupposes ‘analyticity,’
or rather the analytic-synthetic distinction. Is it contradictory, or a
self-contradiction, to say that one’s neighbour’s three-year-old child is an
adult? Is there an implicaturum for ‘War is not war’? Grice refers to Bayes in
WOW re Grices paradox, and to crazy Bayesy, as Peter Achinstein does (Newton
was crazy, but not Bayesy). We can now, in principle, characterize
the desirability of the action a 1 , relative to each end (E1 and E2), and to
each combination of ends (here just E1 and E2), as a function of the
desirability of the end and the probability that the action a 1 will realize that
end, or combination of ends. If we envisage a range of possible actions, which
includes a 1 together with other actions, we can imagine that each such action
has a certain degree of desirability relative to each end (E1 and (or) E2) and
to their combination. If we suppose that, for each possible action, these
desirabilities can be compounded (perhaps added), then we can suppose that one
particular possible action scored higher (in actiondesirability relative to
these ends) than any alternative possible action; and that this is the action
which wins out; that is, is the action which is, or at least should, end p.105
be performed. (The computation would in fact be more complex than I have
described, once account is taken of the fact that the ends involved are often
not definite (determinate) states of affairs (like becoming President),
but are variable in respect of the degree to which they might be realized (if
ones end is to make a profit from a deal, that profit might be of a varying
magnitude); so one would have to consider not merely the likelihood of a
particular actions realizing the end of making a profit, but also the
likelihood of its realizing that end to this or that degree; and this would
considerably complicate the computational problem.) No doubt most readers are
far too sensible ever to have entertained any picture even remotely resembling
the "Crazy-Bayesy" one I have just described. Grice was
fascinated by the fact that paradox translates the Grecian neuter paradoxon.
Some of the paradoxes of entailment, entailment and paradoxes. This is not the
first time Grice uses paradox. As a classicist, he was aware of the nuances
between paradox (or paradoxon, as he preferred, via Latin paradoxum, and
aporia, for example. He was interested in Strawsons treatment of this or that
paradox of entailment. He even called his own paradox involving if and
probablility Grices paradox.
telementationalism: see psi-transmission. The coinage is interesting.
Since Grice has an essay on ‘modest mentalism,’ and would often use ‘mental’
for ‘psychological,’ it does make sense. ‘Ideationalism’ is analogous. this is
a special note, or rather, a very moving proem, on Grices occasion of
delivering his lectures on ‘Aspects of reason and reasoning’ at Oxford as the
Locke Lectures at Merton. Particularly apt in mentioning, with humility, his
having failed, *thrice* [sic] to obtain the Locke lectureship, Strawson did, at
once, but feeling safe under the ægis of that great English philosopher (viz.
Locke! always implicated, never explicited) now. Grice starts the proem in a
very moving, shall we say, emotional, way: I find it difficult to convey to you
just how happy I am, and how honoured I feel, in being invited to give these
lectures. Difficult, but not impossible. I think of this university and this
city, it has a cathedral, which were my home for thirty-six years, as my
spiritual and intellectual parents. The almost majestic plural is Grices implicaturum
to the town and gown! Whatever I am was originally fashioned here; I never left
Oxford, Oxford made me, and I find it a moving experience to be, within these
splendid and none too ancient walls, once more engaged in my old occupation of
rendering what is clear obscure, by flouting the desideratum of conversational
clarity and the conversational maxim, avoid obscurity of expression, under be
perspicuous [sic]!. Grices implicaturum on none too ancient seems to be
addressed to the truly ancient walls that saw Athenian dialectic! On the other
hand, Grices funny variant on the obscurum per obscurius ‒ what Baker found as
Grices skill in rendering an orthodoxy into a heterodoxy! Almost! By clear
Grice implicates Lewis and his clarity is not enough! I am, at the same time,
proud of my mid-Atlantic [two-world] status, and am, therefore, delighted that
the Old World should have called me in, or rather recalled me, to redress, for
once, the balance of my having left her for the New. His implicaturum seems to
be: Strictly, I never left? Grice concludes his proem: I am, finally, greatly
heartened by my consciousness of the fact that that great English philosopher,
under whose ægis I am now speaking, has in the late afternoon of my days
extended to me his Lectureship as a gracious consolation for a record threefold
denied to me, in my early morning, of his Prize. I pray that my present
offerings may find greater favour in his sight than did those of long ago. They
did! Even if Locke surely might have found favour to Grices former offerings,
too, Im sure. Refs.: The allusions to Locke are in “Aspects.” Good references
under ‘ideationalism,’ above, especially in connection with Myro’s ‘modest
mentalism,’ The H. P. Grice Papers, BANC.
‘that’: a demonstrative. Since Grice would make so many
references to the ‘that’-clause, he is aware that ‘that’ is etymologically a
demonstrative, that has lost its efficacy there. But the important etymological
lesson is that what follows a ‘that’-clause (cf. the classical languages Grice
learned at Clifton, Greek and Latin) is a ‘propositio’ just because the ‘that’
POINTS at the proposition. Sometimes he refers to ‘obliquus casus,’ and ‘oratio
obliqua,’ but he is more at home with things like ‘verba percipienda,’ verba
volendi, etc.
‘that’-clause: Grice’s priority for the ‘that’-clause is multiple.
He dislikes what he calls an ‘amorphous’ propositional complex. His idea is to
have at least ‘The S is P,’ one act involving a subjectum or denotatum, and one
involving the praedicatum. There is also what he calls sub-perceptual
utterances. They do look like structured (“That red pillar seems red”) but they
are not perceptual reports like “I perceive that the pillar box is red.” At
points he wanst to restrict utterer’s communucatum to a ‘that’-clause; but
ignoring Austin’s remark that to wonder about what a ‘word’ ‘means’ is
senseless, Grice sometimes allows for things like ‘The cat sat on the mat’ to
‘mean’ that the cat sat on the mat. Grice thinks that his account of ‘the
red-seeming pillar box’ succeeded, and that it was this success that prompted
him to apply the thing to other areas, notably Strawson, but one hopes, all the
theses he presents in “Causal” and “Prolegomena.” But he does not go back to
the is/seems example, other than perhaps the tie is/seems blue. The reason is
that the sense-datum theory is very complex. Note “seems.” “It seems to me
that…” but the ‘that’-clause not as a content of a state of the agent. If the
pillar box seems red to Grice because it is red, what ‘that’-clause are we
talking about to involve in the implicaturum? And what generates the implicaturum.
“By uttering “The pillar box seems red,” U conversationally implicates that
there is a denial or doubt, somewhere as to whether the pillar box IS red.” Grice
thought of Staal as particularly good at this type of formalistic philosophy,
which was still adequate to reflect the subtleties of ordinary
language. How do we define a Griceian action? How do we define a
Griceian event? This is Grices examination and criticism of Davidson, as a
scientific realist, followed by a Kantian approach to freedom and causation.
Grice is especially interested in the logical form, or explicitum, so that he
can play with the implicaturum. One of his favourite examples: He fell on his
sword, having tripped as he crossed the Galliæ. Grice manages to quote from
many and varied authors (some of which you would not expect him to quote) such
as Reichenbach, but also Robinson, of Oriel, of You Names it fame (for any x,
if you can Names it, x exists). Robinson has a brilliant essay on parts of Cook
Wilsons Statement and inference, so he certainly knows what he is talking
about. Grice also quotes from von Wright and Eddington. Grice offers a
linguistic botanic survey of autonomy and free (sugar-free, free fall, implicaturum-free)
which some have found inspirational. His favourite is Finnegans alcohol-free.
Finnegans obvious implicaturum is that everything is alcohol-laden. Grice kept
a copy of Davidsons The logical form of action sentences, since surely
Davidson, Grice thought, is making a primary philosophical point. Horses run
fast; therefore, horses run. A Davidsonian problem, and there are more to come!
Smith went fishing. Grices category shift allows us to take Smiths fishing
as the grammatical Subjects of an action sentence. Cf. indeed the way to cope
with entailment in The horse runs fast; therefore, the horse runs. Grices
Actions and events is Davidsonian in motivation, but Kantian in method, one of
those actions by Grice to promote a Griceian event! Davidson had published,
Grice thought, some pretty influential (and provocative, anti-Quineian) stuff
on actions and events, or events and actions, actually, and, worse, he was
being discussed at Oxford, too, over which Grice always keeps an eye! Davidsons
point, tersely put, is that while p.q (e.g. It is raining, and it is pouring)
denotes a concatenation of events. Smith is fishing denotes an action, which is
a kind of event, if you are following him (Davidson, not Smith). However,
Davidson is fighting against the intuition, if you are a follower of Whitehead
and Russell, to symbolise the Smith is fishing as Fs, where s stands for Smith
and F for fishing. The logical form of a report of an event or an action seems
to be slightly more complicated. Davidsons point specifically involves adverbs,
or adverbial modifiers, and how to play with them in terms of entailment. The
horse runs fast; therefore, the horse runs. Symbolise that! as Davidson told
Benson Mates! But Mates had gone to the restroom. Grice explores all these and
other topics and submits the thing for publication. Grice quotes, as isnt his
wont, from many and various philosophers, not just Davidson, whom he saw every
Wednesday, but others he didnt, like Reichenbach, Robinson, Kant, and, again
even a physicist like Eddington. Grice remarks that Davidson is into hypothesis,
suppositio, while he is, as he should, into hypostasis, substantia. Grice then
expands on the apparent otiosity of uttering, It is a fact that grass is green.
Grice goes on to summarise what he ironically dubs an ingenious argument.
Let σ abbreviate the operator
consists in the fact that , which, when prefixed to a sentence,
produces a predicate or epithet. Let S abbreviate Snow is white,
and let G abbreviate Grass is green. In that case, xσS is 1 just
in case xσ(y(y=y and S) = y(y=y) is 1, since the first part of the
sub-sentence which follows σ in the main sentence is logically equivalent
logically equivalent to the second part. And xσ(y(y=y and S) =
y(y=y) is 1 just in case xσ(y(if y=y, G) = y(y=y) is 1,
since y(if y=y, S) and y(if y=y, G) are each a singular term, which, if
S and G are both true, each refers to y(y=y), and are therefore
co-referential and inter-substitutable. And xσ(y(if y=y, G) =
y(y=y) is true just in case xσG is 1, since G is logically equivalent
to the sub-sentence which follows σ. So, this fallacy goes, provided that
S and G are both 1, regardless of what an utterer explicitly conveys by
uttering a token of it, any event which consists of the otiose fact that S also
consists of the otiose fact that G, and vice versa, i. e. this randomly
chosen event is identical to any other randomly chosen event. Grice hastens to
criticise this slingshot fallacy licensing the inter-substitution of this or
that co-referential singular term and this or that logically equivalent
sub-sentence as officially demanded because it is needed to license a
patently valid, if baffling, inference. But, if in addition to providing
this benefit, the fallacy saddles the philosopher with a commitment to a
hideous consequence, the rational course is to endeavour to find a way of
retaining the benefit while eliminating the disastrous accompaniment, much
as in set theory it seems rational to seek as generous a comprehension
axiom as the need to escape this or that paradox permits. Grice proposes
to retain the principle of co-reference, but prohibit is
use after the principle of logical equivalence has been
used. Grice finds such a measure to have some intuitive appeal. In
the fallacy, the initial deployment of the principle of logical equivalence seems
tailored to the production of a sentence which provides opportunity for
trouble-raising application of the principle of
co-referentiality. And if that is what the game is, why not stop
it? On the assumption that this or that problem which originally prompts
this or that analysis is at least on their way towards independent
solution, Grice turns his attention to the possibility of providing a
constructivist treatment of things which might perhaps have more intuitive
appeal than a naïve realist approach. Grice begins with a class of
happenstance attributions, which is divided into this or that basic
happenstance attribution, i.e. ascriptions to a Subjects-item of an
attribute which is metabolically expressible, and this or that non-basic
resultant happenstance attribution, in which the attribute ascribed,
though not itself metabolically expressible, is such that its possession
by a Subjects item is suitably related to the possession by that or by some
other Subjects item, of this or that attribute which is metabolically
expressible. Any member of the class of happenstance attributions may be
used to say what happens, or happens to be the case, without talking about
any special entity belonging to a class of a happening or a happenstance. A
next stage involves the introduction of the operator consists of the fact that This
operator, when prefixed to a sentence S that makes a happen-stance
attribution to a Subjects-item, yields a predicate which is satisfied by an
entity which is a happenstance, provided that sentence S is doxastically
satisfactory, i. e., 1, and that some further metaphysical condition obtains,
which ensures the metaphysical necessity of the introduction into reality of
the category of a happenstance, thereby ensuring that this new category is
not just a class of this or that fiction. As far as the slingshot fallacy,
and the hideous consequence that all facts become identical to one Great Big
Fact, in the light of a defence of Reichenbach against the realist attack,
Grice is reasonably confident that a metaphysical extension of reality will not
saddle him with an intolerable paradox, pace the caveat that, to some, the
slingshot is not contradictory in the way a paradox is, but merely an
unexpected consequence ‒ not seriously hideous, at that. What this metaphysical
condition would be which would justify the metaphysical extension remains,
alas, to be determined. It is tempting to think that the metaphysical
condition is connected with a theoretical need to have this or that
happenstance as this or that item in, say, a causal relation. Grice goes on to
provide a progression of linguistic botanising including free. Grice
distinguishes four elements or stages in the step-by-step development of
freedom. A first stage is the transeunt causation one finds in
inanimate objects, as when we experience a stone in free fall. This is Hume’s
realm, the atomistss realm. This is external or transeunt casuation, when an
object is affected by processes in other objects. A second stage is internal or
immanent causation, where a process in an object is the outcome of previous
stages in that process, as in a freely moving body. A third stage is the
internal causation of a living being, in which changes are generated in a
creature by internal features of the creature which are not earlier stages of
the same change, but independent items, the function or finality of which is to
provide for the good of the creature in question. A fourth stage is a
culminating stage at which the conception of a certain mode by a human of
something as being for that creatures good is sufficient to initiate the doing
of that thing. Grice expands on this interesting last stage. At this stage, it
is the case that the creature is liberated from every factive cause. There is
also a discussion of von Wrights table of adverbial modifiers, or Grices
pentagram. Also an exploration of specificity: Jack buttering a parsnip in the
bathroom in the presence of Jill. Grice revisits some of his earlier concerns,
and these are discussed in the appropriate places, such as his exploration on
the Grecian etymology of aition. “That”-clause should be preferred to ‘oratio
obliqua,’ since the latter is a misnomer when you ascribe a psychological state
rather than an utterance. Refs.: The main sources are given under ‘oratio
obliqua’ above, The BANC.
theism: as an
Aristotelian scholar, H. P. Grice is aware of the centrality of God, nous
nouseos, in Aristotle’s philosophy -- atheism from Grecian a-, ‘not’, and
theos, ‘god’, the view that there are no gods. A widely used sense denotes
merely not believing in God and is consistent with agnosticism. A stricter
sense denotes a belief that there is no God; this use has become the standard
one. In the Apology Socrates is accused of atheism for not believing in the
official Athenian gods. Some distinguish between theoretical atheism and
practical atheism. A theoretical atheist is one who self-consciously denies the
existence of a supreme being, whereas a practical atheist may believe that a
supreme being exists but lives as though there were no god.
theology -- Grice’s philosophical theology -- concursus
dei, God’s concurrence. The notion derives from a theory from medieval
philosophical theology, according to which any case of causation involving
created substances requires both the exercise of genuine causal powers inherent
in creatures and the exercise of God’s causal activity. In particular, a
person’s actions are the result of the person’s causal powers, often including
the powers of deliberation and choice, and God’s causal endorsement. Divine
concurrence maintains that the nature of God’s activity is more determinate
than simply conserving the created world in existence. Although divine
concurrence agrees with occasionalism in holding God’s power to be necessary
for any event to occur, it diverges from occasionalism insofar as it regards
creatures as causally active.
theory-theory, v. Grice’s theory-theory.
theseus’s
ship. Grice sails on Theseus’s ship. Theseus’ ship: Example used by Grice to relativise
‘identity.’ After the hero Theseus accomplished his mission to sail to Crete to
kill the Minotaur, his ship (Ship 1) was put on display in Athens. As the time
went by, its original planks and other parts were replaced one by one with new
materials until one day all of its parts were new, with none of its original
parts remaining. Do we want to say that the completely rebuilt ship (Ship 2) is
the same as the original or that it is
a different ship? The case is further complicated. If all the original
materials were kept and eventually used to construct a ship (Ship 3), would
this ship be the same as the original? This example has inspired much
discussion concerning the problems of identity and individuation. “To be
something later is to be its closest continuer. Let us apply this view to one traditional
puzzle about identity over time: the puzzle of the ship of Theseus.” Nozick,
Philosophical Explanation. Grice basically formalized this with G. Myro. Refs.:
Collingwood, translation of Benedetto Croce, “Il paradosso della nave di
Teseo,” H. P. Grice, “Relative identity,” The Grice Papers, BANC.
thomson: Grice did not collaborate with that many friends. He
did with his tutee Strawson. He later did it with G. J. Warnock only on the
theory of perception (notably the ‘visum’). He collaborated with two more
Oxonian philosophers, and with both on the philosophy of action: D. F. Pears
and J. F. Thomson. J. F. Scots London-born
philosopher who would often give seminars with H. P. Grice. They also explored
‘philosophy of action.’ Thomson presented his views on public occasons on the
topic, usually under the guidance of D. F. Pears – on topics such as ‘freedom
of the will.’ Thomson has assocations with University, and is a Fellow of
Corpus, Grice’s alma.
thomsonianism: Grice explored philosophy of action with J. F.
Thomson. Thomson would socialize mainly with Grice and D. F. Pears. Oddly,
Thomson was also interested in ‘if’ and reached more or less the same Philonian
consequences that Grice does.
three-year-old’s
guide to Russell’s theory of types, the
– by H. P. Grice, with an appendix by P. F. Strawson, “Advice to parents,” v.
Grice’s three-year-old’s guide.
transcendens -- transcendental argument: Transcendental
argument -- Davidson, D.: H. P. Grice, “Reply to Davidson,” philosopher of mind
and language. His views on the relationship between our conceptions of
ourselves as persons and as complex physical objects have had an enormous
impact on contemporary philosophy. Davidson regards the mindbody problem as the
problem of the relation between mental and physical events; his discussions of
explanation assume that the entities explained are events; causation is a
relation between events; and action is a species of events, so that events are
the very subject matter of action theory. His central claim concerning events
is that they are concrete particulars
unrepeatable entities located in space and time. He does not take for
granted that events exist, but argues for their existence and for specific
claims as to their nature. In “The Individuation of Events” in Essays on
Actions and Events, 0, Davidson argues that a satisfactory theory of action
must recognize that we talk of the same action under different descriptions. We
must therefore assume the existence of actions. His strongest argument for the
existence of events derives from his most original contribution to metaphysics,
the semantic method of truth Essays on Actions and Events, pp. 10580; Essays on
Truth and Interpretation, 4, pp. 214. The argument is based on a distinctive
trait of the English language one not obviously shared by signal systems in
lower animals, namely, its productivity of combinations. We learn modes of
composition as well as words and are thus prepared to produce and respond to
complex expressions never before encountered. Davidson argues, from such
considerations, that our very understanding of English requires assuming the
existence of events. To understand Davidson’s rather complicated views about
the relationships between mind and body, consider the following claims: 1 The mental
and the physical are distinct. 2 The mental and the physical causally interact.
3 The physical is causally closed. Darwinism, social Davidson, Donald 206 206 1 says that no mental event is a
physical event; 2, that some mental events cause physical events and vice
versa; and 3, that all the causes of physical events are physical events. If
mental events are distinct from physical events and sometimes cause them, then
the physical is not causally closed. The dilemma posed by the plausibility of
each of these claims and by their apparent incompatibility just is the
traditional mind body problem. Davidson’s resolution consists of three theses:
4 There are no strict psychological or psychophysical laws; in fact, all strict
laws are expressible in purely physical vocabulary. 5 Mental events causally
interact with physical events. 6 Event c causes event e only if some strict
causal law subsumes c and e. It is commonly held that a property expressed by M
is reducible to a property expressed by P where M and P are not logically
connected only if some exceptionless law links them. So, given 4, mental and
physical properties are distinct. 6 says that c causes e only if there are
singular descriptions, D of c and DH of e, and a “strict” causal law, L, such
that L and ‘D occurred’ entail ‘D caused D'’. 6 and the second part of 4 entail
that physical events have only physical causes and that all event causation is
physically grounded. Given the parallel between 13 and 4 6, it may seem that
the latter, too, are incompatible. But Davidson shows that they all can be true
if and only if mental events are identical to physical events. Let us say that
an event e is a physical event if and only if e satisfies a basic physical
predicate that is, a physical predicate appearing in a “strict” law. Since only
physical predicates or predicates expressing properties reducible to basic
physical properties appear in “strict” laws, every event that enters into
causal relations satisfies a basic physical predicate. So, those mental events
which enter into causal relations are also physical events. Still, the
anomalous monist is committed only to a partial endorsement of 1. The mental
and physical are distinct insofar as they are not linked by strict law but they are not distinct insofar as mental
events are in fact physical events.
transcendental
club. “A club I created to discuss
what I call a ‘metaphysical argument,’ but Kant calls ‘transcendental.’
Strawson objected to my calling it “The Metaphysical Club.” transcendentalism: Also called “New England
transcendentalism,” an early nineteenth-century spiritual and philosophical
movement in the United States, represented by Ralph Waldo Emerson and Henry
David Thoreau. It was centered in the so-called The Transcendental Club in
Boston, and published a quarterly journal The Dial. Influenced by German
idealism and Romanticism, it claimed that there is a spirit of the whole, the
over-soul, which is beyond the space and time of the everyday world but at the
same time immanent in it, and which forms a higher spiritual reality. It
advocated an ascetic lifestyle, emphasized selfreliance and communal living,
and rejected contemporary civilization. The eventual goal of life is to achieve
a mystical unity with this spiritual reality, that is, with nature.
Transcendentalism is viewed as a mixture of speculative philosophy and
semi-religious faith. This philosophical movement had a deep influence upon
existentialism, James’s pragmatism, and contemporary environmental philosophy.
In a broad sense, transcendentalism is any doctrine that emphasizes the
transcendental, and is taken as a synonym of transcendental philosophy. In this
sense, all types of absolute philosophy, especially those idealist systems that
emphasize the transcendence of the Absolute over the finite world, are
considered examples of transcendentalism. Thus, transcendentalists had aims
differing from those of Kant’s transcendental philosophy, which criticized
those who wished to extend knowledge beyond experience and instead sought to
use a transcendental argument to establish the conditions for the possibility
of experience. “The transcendentalists believed in man’s ability to apprehend
absolute Truth, absolute Justice, absolute Rectitude, absolute goodness. They
spoke of the Right, the True, the Beautiful as eternal realities which man can
discover in the world and which he can incorporate into his life. And they were
convinced of the unlimited perfectibility of man.” Werkmeister, A History of
Philosophical Ideas in America.
triangulus -- Grice’s triangle. He uses the word in “Meaning
Revisited,” (WoW: 286). It’s the semiotic triange between what he calls the
‘communication device,’ the denotatum, and the soul. While
often referred to as H. P. Grice’s triangle, or H. P. Grice’s semiotic triangle,
or "Ogden/Richards triangle" the idea is also expressed in 1810, by
Bernard Bolzano, in his rather obscure, Grice grants, “Beiträge zu einer
begründeteren Darstellung der Mathematik.” However, the triangle can be traced
back to the 4th century BC, in Aristotle's Peri Hermeneias (often referred to
in its Latin translation De Interpretatione, second book of his Organon, on
which Grice gave seminars as University Lecturer at Oxford with J. L. Austin).
H. P. Grice’s semiotic Triangle relates to the problem of universals, a
philosophical debate which split ancient and medieval philosophers (mainly
realists and nominalists). The triangle describes a simplified form of
relationship between the emissor as subject, a concept as object or referent or
denotatum, and its designation (sign, signans, or as Grice prefers
‘communication device’). For more elaborated research see Semiotics.
Ogden semiotic triangle.png Contents 1Interlocutory applications 1.1Other
triangles 1.2The communicative stand 1.3Direction of fit 2See also 3References
4External links Interlocutory applications Other triangles The relations
between the triangular corners may be phrased more precisely in causal terms as
follows[citation needed][original research?]. The matter evokes the emissor's
soul. The emissor refers the matter to the symbol. The symbol evokes the
emissee’s soul. The emissee refers the symbol back to the matter. The
communicative stand Such a triangle represents ONE agent, the emissor, whereas
communication takes place between TWO (objects, not necessarily agents). So
imagine another triangle and consider that for the two to understand each
other, the content that the "triangles" represent must fit or be
aligned. Clearly, this calls for synchronisation and an interface as well as
scale among other things. Notice also, that we perceive the world mostly
through our eyes and in alternative phases of seeing and not seeing with change
in the environment as the most important information to look for. Our eyes are
lenses and we see a surface (2D) in ONE direction (focusing) if we are
stationary and the object is not moving either. This is why you may position
yourself in one corner of the triangle and by replicating (mirroring) it, you
will be able to see the whole picture, your cognitive epistemological and the
ontological existential or physical model of life, the universe, existence,
etc. combined.[citation needed][original research?] Direction of fit Main
article: Direction of fit This section has multiple issues. Please help
improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page. (Learn how and when to
remove these template messages) This section does not cite any sources.
(December 2012) This section is written like a personal reflection, personal
essay, or argumentative essay that states a Wikipedia editor's personal
feelings or presents an original argument about a topic. (December 2012) Grice
uses the notion of "direction of fit" (in “Intention and
Uncertainty”) to create a taxonomy of acts. [3] [4] This table
possibly contains original research. Please improve it by verifying the claims
made and adding inline citations. Statements consisting only of original
research should be removed. (December 2012) (Learn how and when to remove this
template message) World or Referentintended →Writer's Thought
decoded ↑ ↓ encoded Thought Emissee's← extendedSymbol or
Word Emissor's THOUGHT retrieves SYMBOL suited to REFERENT, Word
suited to World. Reader's THOUGHT retrieves REFERENT suited to SYMBOL,
World suited to Word. Actually the arrows indicate that there is something
exchanged between the two parties and it is a feedback cycle. Especially, if
you imagine that the world is represented in the soul of both the emissor and
the emissee and used for reality check. If you look at the triangle above
again, remember that reality check is not what is indicated there between the
sign and the referent and marked as "true', because a term or a sign is
allocated "arbitrarily'. What you check for is the observance of the law
of identity which requires you and your partner to sort out that you are on the
same page, that the emissor is communicating and the emissee is understanding
about the same thing. So the chunk of reality and the term are
replaceable/interchangeable within limits and your concepts in the soul as
presented in some appropriate way are all related and mean the same thing.
Usually the check does not stop there, your ideas must also be tested for
feasibility and doability to make sure that they are "real" and not
"phantasy". Reality check comes from consolidating your experience
with other people's experience to avoid solipsism and/or by putting your ideas
(projection) in practice (production) and see the reaction. Notice, however how
vague the verbs used and how the concept of a fit itself is left unexplained in
details.[editorializing] See also The Delta Factor De dicto De se De re
References Colin Cherry (1957) On Human Communication C. K. Ogden
and I. A. Richards (1923) The Meaning of Meaning John Searle (1975)
"A Taxonomy of Illocutionary Acts", in: Gunderson, K. (ed.),
Language, Mind, and Knowledge (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press) pp.
344-369. John Searle (1976) "A Classification of Illocutionary
Acts", Language in Society, Vol.5, pp. 1-24. External links Jessica Erickstad
(1998) Richards' Meaning of Meaning Theory. University of Colorado at Boulder.
Allie Cahill (1998) "Proper Meaning Superstition" (I. A. Richards).
University of Colorado at Boulder. Categories:
SemioticsSemanticsPragmaticsPhilosophy of languagePhilosophy of mind. Semiotisches
Dreieck Zur Navigation springen. Zur Suche springen. Das semiotische Dreieck
stellt die Relation zwischen dem Symbol, dem dadurch hervorgerufenen Begriff
und dem damit gemeinten realen Ding dar. Das semiotische Dreieck ist ein in der
Sprachwissenschaft und Semiotik verwendetes Modell. Es soll veranschaulichen,
dass ein Zeichenträger (Graphem, Syntagma, Symbol) sich nicht direkt und
unmittelbar auf einen außersprachlichen Gegenstand bezieht, sondern dieser
Bezug nur mittelbar durch eine Vorstellung/einen Begriff erfolgt. Das
semiotische Dreieck publizierten erstmals Charles Kay Ogden und Ivor Armstrong
Richards in dem Werk The Meaning of Meaning. Das semiotische Dreieck in
vereinfachter Beschreibung. Die Welt besteht aus Gegenständen, Sachverhalten,
Ereignissen und Ähnlichem. Diese sind wirklich und bestimmen alles, was
geschieht. Das Symbol für ein Einzelnes davon steht in den folgenden Dreiecken
rechts und bedeutet vereinfacht: Ding oder „was Sache ist“. Wenn der Mensch ein
Ding bemerkt oder sich vorstellt, macht er sich ein gedachtes Bild davon. Das
Symbol dafür steht in den folgenden Dreiecken oben und bedeutet: Begriff oder
„was man meint“. Wenn Menschen mit diesen Begriffen von Dingen reden, so
verwenden sie Zeichen (meist hörbar, gelegentlich auch sichtbar oder anders
wahrnehmbar). Das sind Wörter (auch Bezeichnungen, Benennungen, Symbole oder
Ähnliches). Das Symbol dafür steht in den folgenden DREIECKEN links und
bedeutet: Wort oder „was man dazu sagt“. Ding, Begriff und Wort sollen
eindeutig zusammengehören. Das gelingt nicht immer, vielmehr muss man immerzu
aufpassen, ob der eben verwendete Begriff das betrachtete Ding richtig erfasst,
ob das eben verwendete Wort den gemeinten Begriff trifft, und sogar ob das eben
betrachtete Ding überhaupt eins ist und nicht etwa einige oder gar keins. Passen
die drei Ecken nicht zueinander, „So entstehen leicht die fundamentalsten
Verwechslungen (deren die ganze Philosophie voll ist).“ Vitters:
Tractatus 3.324. Das semiotische Dreieck als bildliche Darstellung der
Mehrdimensionalität der Zeichen Begriff /\ / \ / \ /
\ / \ Zeichen ......
Gegenstand (Wort) (Ding). Das semiotische Dreieck ist zunächst nur
ein bildliches Hilfsmittel, um sich Beziehungen „im“ bzw. „des“ Zeichens zu
veranschaulichen. Seine Interpretation und nähere Ausgestaltung hängt daher von
der zugrunde gelegten Erkenntnistheorie ab. In entscheidender Weise wird
durch das semiotische Dreieck veranschaulicht, dass zwischen dem Wort (der
Zeichenform, d. h. dem Schriftbild oder dem Lautbild) und dem Bezeichneten
(Ding, Gegenstand) keine direkte Beziehung, sondern nur durch (mindestens) eine
hier so genannte Vermittlungsinstanz vermittelte Beziehung besteht. Graphisch
wird dies durch eine unterschiedliche Linie dargestellt. Gebräuchlich ist
ein Dreieck. Entscheidend ist die nicht-direkte Beziehung zwischen Zeichen
(Wort) und Gegenstand (Ding). Je nach Anzahl der zu veranschaulichenden (nicht
auszublendenden) Bezugspunkte und Vermittlungsinstanzen und der Art der
betonten Beziehungen kann man auch ein Quadrat, ein sonstiges Vieleck bzw.
einen mehrdimensionalen Körper benutzen. Darauf hinzuweisen ist, dass die
Vermittlungsinstanz – hier mit dem mehrdeutigen Ausdruck „Begriff“ bezeichnet –
sehr unterschiedlich gesehen wird, was aus dem Terminologiebefund unten
deutlich wird. Das semiotische Dreieck ist Veranschaulichung eines
Zeichenverständnisses, das dem Zeichenbegriff von Ferdinand de Saussure, wonach
ein Zeichen eine „psychische Einheit“ zwischen einem „akustischen Bild“
(Signifikanten) und einem „Begriff“ (Signifikat) (bei ihm im Sinne einer
psychischen Vorstellung)[2] sein soll, widersprechen dürfte:[3] statt der
„Papierblattmetapher“ für das Verhältnis von Signifikant/Signifikat (von de
Saussure) wird im semiotischen Dreieck eine optische Trennung und Distanzierung
von Zeichenkörper und Begriff (Sinn) vorgenommen. Das semiotische Dreieck
blendet auch pragmatische Bedingungen und Bezüge aus bzw. reduziert sie auf die
semantische Dimension und wird daher von pragmatischen Bedeutungstheorien
kritisiert (vgl. Semiotik). Das Fehlen einer unmittelbaren Beziehung
zwischen Zeichen und Gegenstand wird zugleich als Ausdruck der (von de Saussure
betonten) Arbitrarität und Konventionalität von Zeichen interpretiert.
Geschichte Man muss unterscheiden zwischen dem semiotischen Dreieck als Bild
und einem dreiseitigen (triadischen) Zeichenbegriff, dessen Veranschaulichung
es dient. Verbreitet wird die sprachwissenschaftliche Entwicklung so
dargestellt, als gäbe es ein semiotisches Dreieck erst seit Ogden/Richards, die
damit einen nur zweigliedrigen Zeichenbegriff von de Saussure
modifiziert/überwunden hätten.[4] Es heißt, bis ins 19. Jahrhundert sei der
Zeichenbegriff im Wesentlichen hinsichtlich seines Sachbezugs als „zweistellige
Relation“ diskutiert worden.[5] Andere betonen den zugrunde liegenden
dreiseitigen („triadischen“) Zeichenbegriff, der meist bei Aristoteles,
mitunter auch schon bei Platon angesetzt wird. Schon bei Platon findet
sich ein gedankliches Wort-Gegenstand-Modell zwischen Namen (Zeichen) – Idee
(Begriff) und Ding. Bei Aristoteles ist ein Zeichen (semeion, damit meint er
ein Wort) ein Symptom für eine Seelenregung, d. h. für etwas, das der Sprecher
sich vorstellt. Diese Vorstellung des Sprechers ist dann ein Ikon für ein Ding.
Dies sind für ihn die primären Zeichenrelationen (rot in der untenstehenden
Figur). Davon abgeleitet ist die sekundäre Zeichenrelation (schwarz in der Figur).
Das Semiotische Dreieck bei Aristoteles Seit Aristoteles wird vertreten,
dass Zeichen Dinge der Welt nicht unvermittelt, sondern vermittelt über einen
„Begriff“, „Vorstellung“ etc. bezeichnen. Dies bedeutet eine Differenzierung
gegenüber der einfachen aliquid-stat-pro-aliquo-Konzeption und ist „für die
ganze Geschichte der Semiotik entscheidend“. Bei Aristoteles stehen „Zeichen
[…] für Sachen, welche von den Bewußtseinsinhalten abgebildet worden sind“. „Die
Sachen werden von den Zeichen nicht präsentiert, sondern repräsentiert.“. Die
Interpretation von De interpretatione ist dabei seit Jahrtausenden kontrovers.
Die oben wiedergegebene Interpretation entspricht einer psychologischen
Deutung, die einen Psychologismus nahelegt. Dies erscheint fraglich, da
Aristoteles eher einen erkenntnistheoretischen Realismus vertreten haben
dürfte. Scholastik In der Sprachphilosophie der Scholastik finden sich
Überlegungen zum Dreierschema res (Sache, Ding), intellectus (Verstand,
Gedanken, Begriff), vox (Wortzeichen). Logik von Port-Royal. In der
Grammatik von Port-Royal (Mitte des 17. Jh.) soll das semiotische Dreieck
eingeführt worden sein.[10] In der Logik von Port-Royal sind die Gegenstände
und die Sprachzeichen nicht unmittelbar, sondern über Universalien miteinander
verknüpft. Nach KANT ist das zwischen Begrifflichkeit und Sinnlichkeit bzw.
Gegenstand vermittelnde Element das Schema als ein bildhaftes und anschauliches
Zeichen. Das Verfahren des Verstandes, mit Hilfe der ‚Einbildungskraft‘ die
reinen Verstandesbegriffe zu versinnlichen, heißt Schematismus. Auch Arthur
Schopenhauer, ein deutscher Philosoph des 19. Jahrhunderts, unterscheidet in
seinem Hauptwerk Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung strikt zwischen Wort,
Begriff und Anschauung. Ausblendung des Referenzbezugs im Zeichenmodell von de
Saussure Nach verbreiteter Auffassung haben die moderne Sprachwissenschaft und
der moderne Zeichenbegriff erst mit de Saussure eingesetzt. Nach de Saussure
ist ein Zeichen die Verbindung eines Ausdrucks (signifiant) mit einem Inhalt
(signifié), wobei das Zeichen als „psychische Einheit mit zwei Seiten“[14]
aufgefasst wurde. In diesem zweigliedrigen (dyadischen) Zeichenmodell „hat die
reale Welt keine Bedeutung“:[15] „Hier Bezeichnetes als geistige Vorstellung,
dort Bezeichnendes als dessen Materialisation in der Sprache, aber kein Platz
für das Objekt selbst“. Triadisches Zeichenmodells bei Peirce. Charles S.
Peirce entwickelte eine pragmatische Semiotik[16] und die Pragmatik soll auf
dem triadischen Zeichenmodell von Peirce beruhen.[17] Statt eines dyadischen
entwickelte Peirce ein kommunikativ-pragmatisches, triadisches Zeichenmodell:
das Zeichen ist eine „triadische Relation (semiotisches Dreieck)“. Dies, indem
er zu Zeichenmittel und Objekt den „Interpretanten“ ergänzte, d. h. die
Bedeutung, die durch Interpretation der Zeichenbenutzer (Sprecher bzw. Hörer)
in einem Handlungszusammenhang zustande kommt. „Das, was als
Bewusstseinsinhalt erscheint, der Interpretant, ist der individuell erkannte
Sinn, der seinerseits kulturell vor- oder mitgeprägt sein kann. Daher wird in
diesem Konzept die Zeichenbedeutung (…) auch als „kulturelle Einheit“ (Eco,
1972) postuliert.“Peirce-Interpreten wie Floyd Merrell oder Gerhard Schönrich
wenden sich gegen die Dreiecksdarstellung peircescher Zeichentriaden, da sie
suggerieren könnte, dass sich die irreduzible triadische Relation zerlegen
lasse in einzelne zweistellige Relationen. Stattdessen schlagen sie eine
Y-förmige Darstellung vor, bei der die drei Relate jeweils durch eine Linie mit
dem Mittelpunkt verbunden sind, aber entlang der Seiten des „Dreiecks“ keine
Linien verlaufen. Charles Kay Ogden / Ivor Armstrong Richards Als „die“
Vertreter eines dreiseitigen Zeichenmodells bzw. eines semiotischen Dreiecks
(unter Ausblendung ihrer Vorläufer) werden verbreitet Charles Kay Ogden und
Ivor Armstrong Richards angeführt. Diese erkannten eine Welt außerhalb des
menschlichen Bewusstseins ausdrücklich an und wandten sich gegen „idealistische
Konzepte“. Nach Charles Kay Ogden und Ivor Armstrong Richards symbolisiert das
Zeichen (symbol) etwas und ruft einen entsprechenden Bewusstseinsinhalt
(reference) hervor, der sich auf das Objekt (referent) bezieht.[6] Das
semiotische Dreieck wird wie folgt erklärt: „Umweltsachverhalte werden im
Gedächtnis begrifflich bzw. konzeptuell repräsentiert und mit Sprachzeichen
assoziiert. So ist z. B. das Wort „Baum“ ein Sprachzeichen, das mit dem Begriff
bzw. Konzept von „BAUM“ assoziiert ist und über diesen auf reale Bäume (Buchen,
Birken, Eichen usw.) verweisen kann.“. Siehe auch Organon-Modell (von Karl
Bühler) Literatur Metamorphosen des semiotischen Dreieck. In: Zeitschrift für
Semiotik. Band 10, (darin 8 einzelne Artikel). Umberto Eco: Semiotik – Entwurf
einer Theorie der Zeichen. 2. Auflage. Wilhelm Fink Verlag, München 1991, ISBN
3-7705-2323-7. Umberto Eco: Einführung in die Semiotik. Wilhelm Fink Verlag,
München 1994, ISBN 3-7705-0633-2. Einzelnachweise C. K. Ogden, I. A.
Richards: The Meaning of Meaning. 1923 Kassai: Sinn. In: Martinet
(Hrsg.): Linguistik. Ohne Problematisierung trotz der Nähe zu Saussure hingegen
bei Kassai: Sinn. In: Martinet (Hrsg.): Linguistik. 1973, S. 251 (S. 254 f.)
referiert So wohl Fischer Kolleg Abiturwissen, Deutsch (2002), S.
27 So z. B. Schülerduden, Philosophie (2002), Semiotik Triadische
Zeichenrelation. In: Homberger: Sachwörterbuch zur Sprachwissenschaft.
2000 Trabant: Semiotik. Trabant: Semiotik. So auch Triadische
Zeichenrelation. In: Homberger: Sachwörterbuch zur Sprachwissenschaft. 2000,
wonach Aristoteles das Platonische Modell „psychologisiert“ haben soll So
Schülerduden, Philosophie (2002), Sprachphilosophie Schülerduden,
Philosophie (2002), Sprachphilosophie Baumgartner: Kants „Kritik der
reinen Vernunft“, Anleitung zur Lektüre. [1988], neu ersch. 5. Auflage. ALBER,
Freiburg Hierzu vor allem das Kapitel: „Zur Lehre von der abstrakten, oder Vernunft-Erkenntnis“
(Zweiter Band) Fischer Kolleg Abiturwissen, Deutsch (2002), S. 26
Ernst: Pragmalinguistik. 2002, S. 66 Schülerduden, Philosophie (2002),
Peirce So Pelz: Linguistik. 1996, S. 242 Zeichenprozess. In: Homberger:
Sachwörterbuch zur Sprachwissenschaft. 2000 Bedeutung. In: Homberger:
Sachwörterbuch zur Sprachwissenschaft. 2000 Kategorien: SemiotikSemantik. For
Grice, the triangle represents the three correspondences. First,
psychophysical, second psychosemiotic, and third semio-physical.
tukey’s bit: from binary digit, a unit or measure of information.
Suggested by John W. Tukey, a bit is both an amount of information a reduction
of eight equally likely possibilities to one generates three bits [% log2 8] of
information and a system of representing that quantity. The binary system uses
1’s and 0’s.
type: v.
Grice’s three-year-old’s guide to Russell’s theory of type
tarski: a., cited by Grice. Grice liked Tarski because unlike
Strawson, he was an Aristotelian correspondenntist at heart, philosopher of
logic famous for his investigations of the concepts of truth and consequence
conducted in the 0s. His analysis of the concept of truth in syntactically
precise, fully interpreted languages resulted in a definition of truth and an
articulate defense of the correspondence theory of truth. Sentences of the
following kind are now known as Tarskian biconditionals: ‘The sentence “Every
perfect number is even” is true if and only if every perfect number is even.’
One of Tarski’s major philosophical insights is that each Tarskian
biconditional is, in his words, a partial definition of truth and,
consequently, all Tarskian biconditionals whose right-hand sides exhaust the
sentences of a given formal language together constitute an implicit definition
of ‘true’ as applicable to sentences of that given formal language. This
insight, because of its penetrating depth and disarming simplicity, has become
a staple of modern analytic philosophy. Moreover, it in effect reduced the
philosophical problem of defining truth to the logical problem of constructing
a single sentence having the form of a definition and having as consequences
each of the Tarskian biconditionals. Tarski’s solution to this problem is the
famous Tarski truth definition, versions of which appear in virtually every
mathematical logic text. Tarski’s second most widely recognized philosophical
achievement was his analysis and explication of the concept of consequence.
Consequence is interdefinable with validity as applied to arguments: a given
conclusion is a consequence of a given premise-set if and only if the argument
composed of the given conclusion and the given premise-set is valid;
conversely, a given argument is valid if and only if its conclusion is a
consequence of its premise-set. Shortly after discovering the truth definition,
Tarski presented his “no-countermodels” definition of consequence: a given
sentence is a consequence of a given set of sentences if and only if every
model of the set is a model of the sentence in other words, if and only if
there is no way to reinterpret the non-logical terms in such a way as to render
the sentence false while rendering all sentences in the set true. As Quine has
emphasized, this definition reduces the modal notion of logical necessity to a combination
of syntactic and semantic concepts, thus avoiding reference to modalities
and/or to “possible worlds.” After Tarski’s definitive work on truth and on
consequence he devoted his energies largely to more purely mathematical work.
For example, in answer to Gödel’s proof that arithmetic is incomplete and
undecidable, Tarski showed that algebra and geometry are both complete and
decidable. Tarski’s truth definition and his consequence definition are found
in his 6 collection Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics 2d ed., 3: article VIII,
pp. 152278, contains the truth definition; article XVI, pp. 40920, contains the
consequence definition. His published articles, nearly 3,000 s in all, have
been available together since 6 in the four-volume Alfred Tarski, Collected
Papers, edited by S. Givant and R. McKenzie.
tautologicum – Grice gives two examples: War is war, and Women are
women – “Note that “Men are men” sounds contingent.” tautology, a proposition
whose negation is inconsistent, or self- contradictory, e.g. ‘Socrates is
Socrates’, ‘Every human is either male or nonmale’, ‘No human is both male and
non-male’, ‘Every human is identical to itself’, ‘If Socrates is human then
Socrates is human’. A proposition that is or is logically equivalent to the
negation of a tautology is called a self-contradiction. According to classical
logic, the property of being Tao Te Ching tautology 902 902 implied by its own negation is a
necessary and sufficient condition for being a tautology and the property of
implying its own negation is a necessary and sufficient condition for being a
contradiction. Tautologies are logically necessary and contradictions are
logically impossible. Epistemically, every proposition that can be known to be
true by purely logical reasoning is a tautology and every proposition that can
be known to be false by purely logical reasoning is a contradiction. The
converses of these two statements are both controversial among classical
logicians. Every proposition in the same logical form as a tautology is a
tautology and every proposition in the same logical form as a contradiction is
a contradiction. For this reason sometimes a tautology is said to be true in
virtue of form and a contradiction is said to be false in virtue of form; being
a tautology and being a contradiction tautologousness and contradictoriness are
formal properties. Since the logical form of a proposition is determined by its
logical terms ‘every’, ‘some’, ‘is’, etc., a tautology is sometimes said to be
true in virtue of its logical terms and likewise mutatis mutandis for a
contradiction. Since tautologies do not exclude any logical possibilities they
are sometimes said to be “empty” or “uninformative”; and there is a tendency
even to deny that they are genuine propositions and that knowledge of them is
genuine knowledge. Since each contradiction “includes” implies all logical
possibilities which of course are jointly inconsistent, contradictions are
sometimes said to be “overinformative.” Tautologies and contradictions are
sometimes said to be “useless,” but for opposite reasons. More precisely,
according to classical logic, being implied by each and every proposition is
necessary and sufficient for being a tautology and, coordinately, implying each
and every proposition is necessary and sufficient for being a contradiction.
Certain developments in mathematical logic, especially model theory and modal
logic, seem to support use of Leibniz’s expression ‘true in all possible
worlds’ in connection with tautologies. There is a special subclass of
tautologies called truth-functional tautologies that are true in virtue of a
special subclass of logical terms called truthfunctional connectives ‘and’,
‘or’, ‘not’, ‘if’, etc.. Some logical writings use ‘tautology’ exclusively for
truth-functional tautologies and thus replace “tautology” in its broad sense by
another expression, e.g. ‘logical truth’. Tarski, Gödel, Russell, and many
other logicians have used the word in its broad sense, but use of it in its
narrow sense is widespread and entirely acceptable. Propositions known to be
tautologies are often given as examples of a priori knowledge. In philosophy of
mathematics, the logistic hypothesis of logicism is the proposition that every
true proposition of pure mathematics is a tautology. Some writers make a sharp
distinction between the formal property of being a tautology and the non-formal
metalogical property of being a law of logic. For example, ‘One is one’ is not
metalogical but it is a tautology, whereas ‘No tautology is a contradiction’ is
metalogical but is not a tautology.
taylor, philosopher, educated at Oxford where he
taught. Taylor’s oeuvre has a broadly analytic character, although he has
consistently opposed the naturalistic and reductionist tendencies that were
associated with the positivist domination of analytic philosophy during the 0s
and 0s. He was, for example, a strong opponent of behaviorism and defended the
essentially interpretive nature of the social sciences against efforts to
reduce their methodology to that of the natural sciences. Taylor has also done
important work on the histiory of philosophy, particularly on Hegel, and has
connected his work with that of Continental philosophers such as Heidegger and
Merleau-Ponty. He has contributed to political theory and written on
contemporary political issues such as multiculturalism in, e.g., The Ethics of
Authenticity, 1, often with specific reference to politics. He has also taken an active
political role in Quebec. Taylor’s most important work, Sources of the Self 9,
is a historical and critical study of the emergence of the modern concept of
the self. Like many other critics of modernity, Taylor rejects modern
tendencies to construe personal identity in entirely scientific or naturalistic
terms, arguing that these construals lead to a view of the self that can make
no sense of our undeniable experience of ourselves as moral agents. He develops
this critique in a historical mode through discussion of the radical
Enlightenment’s e.g., Locke’s reduction of the self to an atomic individual,
essentially disengaged from everything except its own ideas and desires. But
unlike many critics, Taylor also finds in modernity other, richer sources for a
conception of the self. These include the idea of the self’s inwardness,
traceable as far back as Augustine but developed in a distinctively modern way
by Montaigne and Descartes; the affirmation of ordinary life and of ourselves
as participants in it, particularly associated with the Reformation; and the
expressivism of, e.g., the Romantics for which the self fulfills itself by
embracing and articulating the voice of nature present in its depths. Taylor
thinks that these sources constitute a modern self that, unlike the “punctual
self” of the radical Enlightenment, is a meaningful ethical agent. He suggests,
nonetheless, that an adequate conception of the modern self will further
require a relation of human inwardness to God. This suggestion so far remains
undeveloped. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Taylor
et moi.”
teichmüller: philosopher who contributes to the history of
philosophy and develops a theory of knowledge and a metaphysical conception
based on these historical studies. Born in Braunschweig, Teichmüller teaches at
Göttingen and Basel and is influenced by Lotze and Leibniz. Teichmüller’s major
works are “Aristotelische Forschungen” and “Die wirkliche und scheinbar Welt.” His
other works are “Ueber die Unsterblichkeit der Seele,” vide H. P. Grice, “The immortality of
Shropshire’s soul” Old English steorfan "to
die" (past tense stearf, past participle storfen), literally "become
stiff," from Proto-Germanic *sterbanan "be stiff, starve"
(source also of Old Frisian sterva, Old Saxon sterban, Dutch sterven, Old High
German sterban "to die," Old Norse stjarfi "tetanus"), from
extended form of PIE root *ster- (1) "stiff." The conjugation
became weak in English by 16c. The sense narrowed to "die of cold"
(14c.); transitive meaning "to kill with hunger" is first recorded
1520s (earlier to starve of hunger, early 12c.). Intransitive sense of "to
die of hunger" dates from 1570s. German cognate sterben retains the
original sense of the word, but the English has come so far from its origins
that starve to death (1910) is now common. “Studien zur Geschichte der
Begriffe,” “Darwinismus und Philosophie,” “Ueber das Wesen der Liebe,” “
Religionsphilosophie,” and “Neue Grundlegung der Psychologie und Logik.”
Teichmüller maintains that the self of immediate experience, the “I,” is the
most fundamental reality and that the conceptual world is a projection of its
constituting activity. On the basis of his studies in the history of
metaphysics and his sympathies with Leibniz’s monadology, he held that each
metaphysical system contained partial truths and construed each metaphysical
standpoint as a perspective on a complex reality. Thinking of both metaphysical
interpretations of reality and the subjectivity of individual immediate
experience, Teichmüller christened his own philosophical position
“perspectivism.” His work influenced later thought through its impact on the
philosophical reflections of Nietzsche, who was probably influenced by him in
the development of his perspectival theory of knowledge.
teilhard: philosopher whose oeuvre is vigorously discussed
throughout his career. Teilhard de Chardin’s philosophy generates considerable
controversy within the church, since one of his principal concerns is to bring
about a forceful yet generous reconciliation between the traditional Christian
dogma and the dramatic advances yielded by modern science. His philosophy
consisted of systematic reflections on cosmology, biology, physics,
anthropology, social theory, and theology
reflections guided, he maintains, by his fascination with the nature of
life, energy, and matter, and by his profound respect for human spirituality.
Teilhard is educated in philosophy at Mongré. He entered the Jesuit order at
the age of eighteen and was ordained a priest.He went on to study at
Aix-en-Provence, Laval, and Caen, as well as on the Isle of Jersey and at
Hastings, England. Returning to Paris after the war, he studies biology,
geology, and paleontology at the Museum of Natural History and at the Institut
Catholique, receiving a doctoral degree in geology. Shortly after appointment
to the faculty of geology at the Institut Catholique, he takes leave to pursue
field research. His research resulted in the discovery of “Sinanthropus
pekinensis,” which he saw as “perhaps the next to the last step traceable
between the anthropoids and man.” It was during this period that Teilhard
begins to compose one of his major theoretical works, “Le phenomene de
l’homme,” in which he stressed the deep continuity of evolutionary development
and the emergence of humanity from the animal realm. He argues that received
evolutionary theory is fully compatible with Christian doctrine. Indeed, it is
the synthesis of evolutionary theory with his own Christian theology that
perhaps best characterizes the broad tenor of his thought. Starting with the
very inception of the evolutionary trajectory, i.e., with what he termed the “alpha
point” of creation, Teilhard’s general theory resists any absolute disjunction
between the inorganic and organic. Indeed, matter and spirit are two “stages”
or “aspects” of the same cosmic stuff. These transitions from one state to
another may be said to correspond to those between the somatic and psychic, the
exterior and interior, according to the state of relative development,
organization, and complexity. Hence, for Teilhard, much as for Bergson whose
work greatly influenced him, evolutionary development is characterized by a
progression from the simplest components of matter and energy what he termed
the lithosphere, through the organization of flora and fauna the biosphere, to
the complex formations of sentient and cognitive human life the noosphere. In
this sense, evolution is a “progressive spiritualization of matter.” He held
this to be an orthogenetic process, one of “directed evolution” or “Genesis,”
by which matter would irreversibly metamorphose itself, in a process of involution
and complexification, toward the psychic. Specifically, Teilhard’s account
sought to overcome what he saw as a prescientific worldview, one based on a
largely antiquated and indefensible metaphysical dualism. By accomplishing
this, he hoped to realize a productive convergence of science and religion. The
end of evolution, what he termed “the Omega point,” would be the full presence
of Christ, embodied in a universal human society. Many have tended to see a
Christian pantheism expressed in such views. Teilhard himself stressed a
profoundly personalist, spiritual perspective, drawn not only from the
theological tradition of Thomism, but from that of Pauline Neoplatonism and
Christian mysticism as well especially
that tradition extending from Meister Eckhart through Cardinal Bérulle and
Malebranche. Refs.: H. P. Grice, “Teilhard et moi,” – “Method in philosophical
psychology: from the banal to the bizarre.”
telesio: philosopher whose empiricism influences Francis Bacon
and Galileo. Telesio studies in Padova, where he completed his doctorate, and practiced philosophy in Naples and Cosenza
without holding any academic position. His major oeuvre, “De rerum natura iuxta
propria principia,” contains an attempt to interpret nature on the basis of its
own principles, which Telesio identifies with the two incorporeal active forces
of heat and cold, and the corporeal and passive physical substratum. As the two
active forces permeate all of nature and are endowed with sensation, Telesio
argues that all of nature possesses some degree of sensation. Human beings
share with animals a material substance produced by heat and coming into
existence with the body, called spirit. They are also given a mind by God.
Telesio knew various interpretations of Aristotle. However, Telesio broke with foreign exegeses, criticizing
Aristotle’s Physics and claiming that nature is investigated better by the
senses than by the intellect.
telishment: punishment of one suspected of wrongdoing,
but whom the authorities know to be innocent, imposed as a deterrent to future
wrongdoers. Telishment is thus not punishment insofar as punishment requires
that the recipient’s harsh treatment be deserved. Telishment is classically
given as one of the thought experiments challenging utilitarianism and more
broadly, consequentialism as a theory of ethics, for such a theory seems to
justify telishment on some occasions. Grice considers the sophisma that only
the condemnable is supposed to be responsible – as a disregard for the
implicaturum.
finis: H. P. Grice, "Cum finis est licitus, etiam media
sunt licita" -- "Der Zweck und die Mittel.” Grice: “means-end
rationality is a must” -- finitum -- telos, ancient Grecian term meaning ‘end’
or ‘purpose’. Telos is a key concept not only in Grecian ethics but also in
Grecian science. The purpose of a human being is a good life, and human
activities are evaluated according to whether they lead to or manifest this
telos. Plants, animals, and even inanimate objects were also thought to have a
telos through which their activities and relations could be understood and
evaluated. Though a telos could be something that transcends human activities
and sensible things, as Plato thought, it need not be anything apart from
nature. Aristotle, e.g., identified the telos of a sensible thing with its
immanent form. It follows that the purpose of the thing is simply to be what it
is and that, in general, a thing pursues its purpose when it endeavors to
preserve itself. Aristotle’s view shows that ‘purpose in nature’ need not mean a
higher purpose beyond nature. Yet, his immanent purpose does not exclude
“higher” purposes, and Aristotelian teleology was pressed into service by
medieval thinkers as a framework for understanding God’s agency through nature.
Thinkers in the modern period argued against the prominent role accorded to
telos by ancient telepathy telos 906
906 and medieval thinkers, and they replaced it with analyses in terms
of mechanism and law. teleology, the philosophical doctrine that all of nature,
or at least intentional agents, are goaldirected or functionally organized.
Plato first suggested that the organization of the natural world can be
understood by comparing it to the behavior of an intentional agent external teleology. For example, human beings
can anticipate the future and behave in ways calculated to realize their
telekinesis teleology 905 905
intentions. Aristotle invested nature itself with goals internal teleology. Each kind has its own
final cause, and entities are so constructed that they tend to realize this
goal. Heavenly bodies travel as nearly as they are able in perfect circles
because that is their nature, while horses give rise to other horses because
that is their nature. Natural theologians combined these two teleological
perspectives to explain all phenomena by reference to the intentions of a
beneficent, omniscient, all-powerful God. God so constructed the world that
each entity is invested with the tendency to fulfill its own God-given nature.
Darwin explained the teleological character of the living world
non-teleologically. The evolutionary process is not itself teleological, but it
gives rise to functionally organized systems and intentional agents.
Present-day philosophers acknowledge intentional behavior and functional
organization but attempt to explain both without reference to a supernatural
agent or internal natures of the more metaphysical sort. Instead, they define
‘function’ cybernetically, in terms of persistence toward a goal state under
varying conditions, or etiologically, in terms of the contribution that a
structure or action makes to the realization of a goal state. These definitions
confront a battery of counterexamples designed to show that the condition
mentioned is either not necessary, not sufficient, or both; e.g., missing goal
objects, too many goals, or functional equivalents. The trend has been to
decrease the scope of teleological explanations from all of nature, to the
organization of those entities that arise through natural selection, to their
final refuge in the behavior of human beings. Behaviorists have attempted to
eliminate this last vestige of teleology. Just as natural selection makes the
attribution of goals for biological species redundant, the selection of
behavior in terms of its consequences is designed to make any reference to
intentions on the part of human beings unnecessary. Kant, in
fact, for reasons not unlike these, sought to show the validity of a different
but fairly closely related Technical Imperative by just such a method. The form
which he selects is one which, in my terms, would be represented by "It is
fully acceptable, given let it be that B, that let it be that A" or
"It is necessary, given let it be that B, that let it be that A".
Applying this to the one fully stated technical imperative given in
Grundlegung, we get "It is necessary, given let it be that one bisect a
line on an unerring principle, that let it be that I draw from its extremities
two intersecting arcs". Call this statement, (α). Though he does not
express himself very clearly, I am certain that his claim is that this
imperative is validated in virtue of the fact that it is, analytically, a
consequence of an indicative statement which is true and, in the present
context, unproblematic, namely, the statement vouched for by geometry, that if
one bisects a line on an unerring principle, then one does so only as a result
of having drawn from its extremities two intersecting arcs. Call this
statement, (β). His argument seems to be expressible as follows. (1) It is
analytic that he who wills the end (so far as reason decides his conduct),
wills the indispensable means thereto. (2) So it is analytic that (so far as
one is rational) if one wills that A, and judges that if A, then A as a result
of B, then one wills that B. end p.93 (3) So it is analytic that (so far as one
is rational) if one judges that if A, then A as a result of B, then if one
wills that A then one wills that B. (4) So it is analytic that, if it is true
that if A, then A as a result of B, then if let it be that A, then it must be
that let it be that B. From which, by substitution, we derive (5): it is
analytic that if β then α. Now it seems to me to be meritorious, on Kant's
part, first that he saw a need to justify hypothetical imperatives of this
sort, which it is only too easy to take for granted, and second that he invoked
the principle that "he who wills the end, wills the means"; intuitively,
this invocation seems right. Unfortunately, however, the step from (3) to (4)
seems open to dispute on two different counts. (1) It looks as if an
unwarranted 'must' has appeared in the consequent of the conditional which is
claimed, in (4), as analytic; the most that, to all appearances, could be
claimed as being true of the antecedent is that 'if let it be that A then let
it be that B'. (2) (Perhaps more serious.) It is by no means clear by what
right the psychological verbs 'judge' and 'will', which appear in (3), are
omitted in (4); how does an (alleged) analytic connection between (i) judging
that if A, A as a result of B and (ii) its being the case that if one wills
that A then one wills that B yield an analytic connection between (i) it's
being the case that if A, A as a result of B and (ii) the 'proposition' that if
let it be that A then let it be that B? Can the presence in (3) of the phrase
"in so far as one is rational" legitimize this step? I do not know
what remedy to propose for the first of these two difficulties; but I will
attempt a reconstruction of Kant's line of argument which might provide relief
from the second. It might, indeed, even
be an expansion of Kant's actual thinking; but whether or not this is so, I am
a very long way from being confident in its adequacy. (1) Let us suppose it to
be a fundamental psychological law that, ceteris paribus, for any creature x
(of a sufficiently developed kind), no matter what A and B are, if x wills A
and judges that if A, A only as a result of B, then x wills B. This I take to
be a proper representation of "he who wills the end, wills the
indispensable means"; and in calling it a fundamental law I mean that it
is the end p.94 law, or one of the laws, from which 'willing' and 'judging'
derive their sense as names of concepts which explain behaviour. So, I assume,
to reject it would be to deprive these words of their sense. If x is a rational
creature, since in this case his attitudes of acceptance are at least to some
degree under his control (volitive or judicative assent can be withheld or
refused), this law will hold for him only if the following is true: (2) x wills
(it is x's will) that (for any A, B) if x wills that A and judges that if A, A
only as a result of B, then x is to will that B. In so far as x proceeds
rationally, x should will as specified in (2) only if x judges that if it is
satisfactory to will that A and also satisfactory to judge that if A, A only as
a result of B, then it is satisfactory to will that B; otherwise, in willing as
specified in (2), he will be willing to run the risk of passing from
satisfactory attitudes to unsatisfactory ones. So, given that x wills as
specified in (2): (3) x should (qua rational) judge that (for any A, B) if it
is satisfactory to will that A and also satisfactory to judge that if A, A only
as a result of B, then it is satisfactory to will that B. Since the
satisfactoriness of attitudes of acceptance resolves itself into the
satisfactoriness (in the sense distinguished in the previous chapter) of the contents
of those attitudes (marked by the appropriate mode-markers), if x judges as
specified in (3) then: (4) x should (qua rational) judge that (for any A, B) if
it is satisfactory that ! A and also satisfactory that if it is the case that
A, A only as a result of B, then it is satisfactory that ! B. And, if x judges
as in (4), then (because (A & B → C) yields A → (B → C)): (5) x should
judge that (for any A, B) if it is satisfactory that if A, A only because B,
then it is satisfactory that, if let it be that A, then let it be that B. But
if x judges that satisfactoriness is, for any A, B, transmitted in this
particular way, then: (6) x should judge that (for any A, B) if A, A only
because B, yields if let it be that A, then let it be that B. end p.95 But if
any rational being should (qua rational) judge that (for any A, B) the first
'propositional' form yields the second, then the first propositional form does
yield the second; so: (7) (For any A, B) if A, A only because B yields if let
it be that A, then let it be that B. (A special apology for the particularly
violent disregard of 'use and mention'; my usual reason is offered.) Fig. 4
summarizes the steps of the argument. I. Kant's Steps α = It is necessary,
given let it be that one bisect a line on an unerring principle, that let it be
that I draw from its extremities two intersecting arcs. β = If one bisects a
line on an unerring principle, then one does so only as a result of having
drawn from its extremities two intersecting arcs. (1) It is analytic that (so
far as he is rational) he who wills the end wills the means. (2) It is analytic
that (so far as one is rational) if one wills that A, and judges that if A,
then A only as a result of B, then one wills that B. (3) It is analytic that
(so far as one is rational) if one judges that if A, A as a result of B, then
if one wills that A one wills that B. (4) It is analytic that if, if A, then A
as a result of B, then, if let it be that A, then it must be that let it be
that B. (5) It is analytic that if β, then α. Grice goes on to provide
some Reconstruction Steps (1) Fundamental law
that (ceteris paribus) for any creature x (for any A, B), if x wills A and
judges that if A, then A as a result of B; then x wills B. (2) x wills that
(for any A, B) if x wills A and judges that if A, A as a result of B, then x is
to will that B. (3) x should (qua rational) judge that (for any A, B) if it is
satisfactory to will that A and also satisfactory to judge that if A, A only as
a result of B, then it is satisfactory to will that B. (4) x should (qua
rational) judge that (for any A, B) if it is satisfactory that ! A and also
satisfactory that if ⊢A, then ⊢A only as a result of B, then it is satisfactory that ! B.
(5) x should (q.r.) judge that (for any A, B) if it is satisfactory that if ⊢A, ⊢A only because B, then it is
satisfactory that, if let it be that A, then let it be that B. (6) x should (q.r.)
judge that (for any A, B) if A, A only because B, yields if let it be that A,
then let it be that B. (7) (For any A, B) if A, A only because B yields if let
it be that A, then let it be that B. Fig. 4. Validation of Technical
Acceptabilities end p.96 Prudential Acceptability It will be convenient to
initiate the discussion of this topic by again referring to Kant. Kant thought
that there is a special sub-class of Hypothetical Imperatives (which he called
"counsels of prudence") which were like his class of Technical
Imperatives, except in that the end specified in a full statement of the
imperative is the special end of Happiness (one's happiness). To translate into
my terminology, this seems to amount to the thesis that there is a special
subclass of, for example, singular practical acceptability conditionals which
exemplifies the structure "it is acceptable, given that let a (an
individual) be happy, that let a be (do) G"; an additional indicative
sub-antecedent ("that it is the case that a is F") might be sometimes
needed, and could be added without difficulty. There would, presumably, be a
corresponding special subclass of acceptability generalizations. The main
characteristics which Kant would attribute to such prudential acceptability
conditionals would, I think, be the following. (1) The foundation for such
conditionals is exactly the same as that for technical imperatives; they would
be treated as being, in principle, analytically consequences of indicative
statements to the effect that so-and-so is a (the) means to such-and-such. The
relation between my doing philosophy now and my being happy would be a causal
relation not significantly different from the relation between my taking an
aspirin and my being relieved of my headache. (2) However, though the relation
would be the same, the question whether in fact my doing philosophy now will
promote my happiness is insoluble; to solve it, I should have to be omniscient,
since I should have to determine that my doing philosophy now would lead to "a
maximum of welfare in my present and all future circumstances". (3) The
special end (happiness) of specific prudential acceptability conditionals is
one which we know that, as a matter of "natural necessity", every
human being has; so, unlike technical imperatives, their applicability to
himself cannot be disclaimed by any human being. end p.97 (4) Before we bring
in the demands of morality (which will prescribe concern for our own happiness
as a derivative duty), the only positive evaluation of a desire for one's
happiness is an alethic evaluation; one ought to, or must, desire one's own
happiness only in the sense that, whoever one may be, it is acceptable that it
is the case that one desire one's own happiness; the 'ought' or 'must' is
non-practical. (This position seems to me akin to a Humean appeal to 'natural
dispositions', in place of justification.) I would wish to disagree with Kant
in two, or possibly three, ways.(1) Kant, I think, did not devote a great deal
of thought to the nature of happiness, no doubt because he regarded it as being
of little importance to the philosophical foundations of morality. So it is not
clear whether he regarded happiness as a distinct end from the variety of ends
which one might pursue with a view to happiness, rather than as a complex end
which includes (in some sense of 'include') some of such ends. If he did regard
it as a distinct end, then I think he was wrong. (2) I think he was certainly
wrong in thinking of something's being conducive to happiness as being on all fours
with, say, something's being conducive to the relief of a headache; as,
perhaps, a matter (in both cases) of causal relationship. (3) I would like to
think him wrong in thinking that (morality apart) there is no practical
interpretation of 'ought' in which one ought to pursue (desire, aim at) one's
own happiness. We have, then, three not unconnected questions which demand some
attention. (A) What is the nature of happiness? (B) In what sense (if any) (and
why) should I desire, or aim at, my own happiness? (C) What is the nature of
the connection between things which are conducive to happiness and happiness?
(What, specifically, is implied by 'conducive'?) Though it is fiendishly
difficult, I shall take up question (C) first. I trust that I will be forgiven
if I do not present a full and coherent answer. Let us take a brief look at
Aristotle. Aristotle was, I think, more sophisticated in this area. end p.98
(1) Though it is by no means beyond dispute, I am disposed to think that he did
regard Happiness (eudaemonia) as a complex end 'containing' (in some sense) the
ends which are constitutive of happiness; to use the jargon of recent
commentators, I suspect he regarded it as an 'inclusive' and not a 'dominant'
end. (2) He certainly thought that one should (practical 'should') aim at one's
own happiness. (3) (The matter directly relevant to my present purpose.) I
strongly suspect that he did not think that the relationship between, say, my
doing philosophy and my happiness was a straightforward causal relationship.
The passage which I have in mind is Nicomachean Ethics VI. 12, 13, where he
distinguishes between wisdom ("practical wisdom") and cleverness (or,
one might say, resourcefulness). He there makes the following statements: (a)
that wisdom is not the same as cleverness, though like it, (b) that wisdom does
not exist without cleverness, (c) that wisdom is always laudable (to be wise
one must be virtuous), but cleverness is not always laudable, for example, in
rogues, (d) that the relation between wisdom and cleverness is analogous to the
relation between 'natural' virtue and virtue proper (he says this in the same
place as he says (a)). Faced with these not exactly voluminous remarks, some
commentators have been led (not I think without reluctance) to interpret
Aristotle as holding that the only difference between wisdom and cleverness is
that the former does, and the latter does not, require the presence of virtue;
to be wise is simply to be clever in good causes. Apart from the fact that
additional difficulties are generated thereby, with respect to the
interpretation of Nicomachean Ethics VI, to attribute this view to Aristotle
does not seem to indicate a very high respect for his wisdom, particularly as
the text does not seem to demand such an interpretation. Following an idea once
given me, long ago, by Austin, I would prefer to think of Aristotle as
distinguishing between the characteristic manifestation of wisdom, namely, the
ability to determine what one should do (what should be done), and the characteristic
manifestation of cleverness, which is the ability to determine how to do what
it is that should be done. On this interpretation cleverness would plainly be
in a certain sense subordinate to wisdom, since opportunity for cleverness (and
associated qualities) will only end p.99 arise after there has been some
determination of what it is that is to be done. It may also be helpful
(suggestive) to think of wisdom as being (or being assimilable to)
administrative ability, with cleverness being comparable with executive
ability. I would also like to connect cleverness, initially, with the ability
to recognize (devise) technical acceptabilities (though its scope might be
larger than this), while wisdom is shown primarily in other directions. On such
assumptions, expansion of the still obscureAristotelian distinction is plainly
a way of pursuing question (C), or questions closely related to it; for we will
be asking what other kinds of acceptabilities (beyond 'technical'
acceptabilities) we need in order to engage (or engage effectively) in
practical reasoning. I fear my contribution here will be sketchy and not very
systematic. We might start by exploring a little further the 'administrative/
executive' distinction, a distinction which, I must admit, is extremely hazy
and also not at all hard and fast (lines might be drawn, in different cases, in
quite different places). A boss tells his secretary that he will be travelling
on business to suchand-such places, next week, and asks her to arrange travel
and accommodation for him. I suspect that there is nothing peculiar about that.
But suppose, instead of giving her those instructions, he had said to her that
he wanted to travel on business somewhere or other, next week, and asked her to
arrange destinations, matters to be negotiated, firms to negotiate with, and
brief him about what to say to those whom he would visit. That would be a
little more unusual, and the secretary might reply angrily, "I am paid to
be your secretary, not to run your business for you, let alone run you."
What (philosophically) differentiates the two cases? Let us call a desire or
intention D which a man has at t "terminal for him at t" if there is
no desire or intention which he has at t, which is more specific than D; if, for
example, a man wanted at t a car, but it was also true of him that he wanted a
Mercedes, then his desire for a car would not be terminal. Now I think we can
(roughly) distinguish (at least) three ways in which a terminal desire may be
non-specific. (1) D may be finitely non-specific; for example, a man may want a
large, fierce dog (to guard his house) and not care at all what kind of large,
fierce dog he acquired; any kind will do (at least within end p.100 some normal
range). Furthermore, he does not envisage his attitude, that any kind will do,
being changed when action-time comes; he will of course get some particular
kind of dog, but what kind will simply depend on such things as availability.
(2) D may be indeterminately non-specific: that is to say the desirer may recognize,
and intend, that before he acts the desire or intention D should be made more
specific than it is; he has decided, say, that he wants a large, fierce dog,
but has not yet decided what kind he wants. It seems to me that an
indeterminately non-specific desire or intention differs from a finitely
non-specific desire in a way which is relevant to the application of the
concept of 'meanstaking'. If the man with the finitely non-specific desire for
a large, fierce dog decides on a mastiff, that would be (or at least could be)
a case of choosing a mastiff as a means to having a large, fierce dog, but not
something of which getting a large, fierce dog would be an effect. But, if the
man with the indeterminate desire for a large, fierce dog decides that he wants
a mastiff (as a further determination of that indeterminate desire), that is
not a case of meanspicking at all. (3) There is a further kind of
non-specificity which I mention only with a view to completeness: a desire D
may be vaguely, or indefinitely, non-specific; a man may have decided that he
wants a large, fierce dog, but it may not be very well defined what could count
as a large, fierce dog; a mastiff would count, and a Pekinese would not, but
what about a red setter? In such cases the desire or intention needs to be
interpreted, but not to be further specified. With regard to the first two
kinds of non-specificity, there are some remarks to be made. (1) We do not
usually (if we are sensible) make our desires more determinate than the
occasion demands; if getting a dog is not a present prospect, a man who decides
exactly what kind of dog he would like is engaging in fantasy. (2) The final
stage of determination may be left to the occasion of action; if I want to buy
some fancy curtains, I may leave the full determination of the kind until I see
them in the store. (3) Circumstances may change the status of a desire; a man
may have a finitely non-specific desire for a dog until he talks to end p.101
his wife, who changes things for him (making his desire indeterminately
non-specific). (4) Indeterminately non-specific desires may of course be
founded (and well founded) on reasons, and so may be not merely desires one
does have but also desires which one should have.We may now return to the boss
and his secretary. It seems to me that what the 'normally' behaved boss does
(assuming that he has a very new and inexperienced secretary) is to reach a
finitely non-specific desire or intention (or a set of such), communicate these
to his secretary, and leave to her the implementation of this (these)
intention(s); he presumes that nothing which she will do, and no problem which
she will encounter, will disturb his intention (for, within reasonable limits,
he does not care what she does), even though her execution of her tasks may
well involve considerable skill and diplomacy (deinotes). If she is more
senior, then he may well not himself reach a finitely, but only an
indeterminately, non-specific intention, leaving it to her to complete the
determination and trusting her to do so more or less as he would himself. If
she reaches a position in which she is empowered to make determinate his
intentions not as she thinks he would think best, but as she thinks best, then
I would say that she has ceased to be a secretary and has become an
administrative assistant. This might be a convenient place to refer briefly to
a distinction which is of some importance in practical thinking which is not
just a matter of finding a means, of one sort or another, to an already fixed
goal, and which is fairly closely related to the process of determination which
I have been describing. This is the distinction between non-propositional ends,
like power, wealth, skill at chess, gardening; and propositional or objective
ends, like to get the Dean to agree with my proposal, or that my uncle should
go to jail for his peculations of the family money. Non-propositional ends are
in my view universals, the kind of items to be named by mass-terms or abstract
nouns. I should like to regard their non-propositional appearance as genuine; I
would like them to be not only things which we can be said to pursue, but also
things which we can be said to care about; and I would not want to reduce
'caring about' to 'caring that', though of course there is an intimate end
p.102 connection between these kinds of caring. I would like to make the
following points. (1) Non-propositional ends enter into the most primitive
kinds of psychological explanation; the behaviour of lower animals is to be
explained in terms of their wanting food, not of their wanting (say) to eat an
apple. (2) Non-propositional ends are characteristically variable in degree,
and the degrees are valuationally ordered; for one who wants wealth, a greater
degree of wealth is (normally) preferable to a lesser degree. (3) They are the
type, I think, to which ultimate ends which are constitutive of happiness
belong; and not without reason, since their non-propositional, and often
non-temporal, character renders them fit members of an enduring system which is
designed to guide conduct in particular cases. (4) The process of determination
applies to them, indeed, starts with them; desire for power is (say) rendered
more determinate as desire for political power; and objectives (to get the
position of Prime Minister) may be reached by determination applied to
non-propositional ends. (5) Though it is clear to me that the distinction
exists, and that a number of particular items can be placed on one side or
another of the barrier, there is a host of uncertain examples, and the
distinction is not easy to apply. Let us now look at things from her (the
secretary's) angle. First, many (indeed most) of the things she does, though
perhaps cases of means-finding, will not be cases of finding means of the kind
which philosophers usually focus on, namely, causal means. She gets him an
air-ticket, which enables, but does not cause, him to travel to Kalamazoo,
Michigan; she arranges by telephone for him to stay at the Hotel Goosepimple;
his being booked in there is not an effect but an intended outcome of her
conversation on the telephone; and his being booked in at that hotel is not a
cause of his being booked at a hotel, but a way in which that situation or
circumstance is realized. Second, if during her operations she discovers that
there is an epidemic of yellow fever at Kalamazoo, she does not (unless she
wishes to be fired) go blindly ahead and book him in; she consults him, because
something has now happened end p.103 which will (if he knows of it) disturb his
finitely non-specific intention; indeed may confront the boss with a plurality
of conflicting (or apparently conflicting) ends or desiderata; a situation
which is next in line for consideration. Before turning to it, however, I think
I should remark that the kind of featureswhich have shown up in this
interpersonal transaction are also characteristic of solitary deliberation,
when the deliberator executes his own decisions. We are now, we suppose, at a
stage at which the secretary has come back to the boss to announce that if she
executes the task given her (implements the decision about what to do which he
has reached), there is such-and-such a snag; that is, the decision can be
implemented only at the cost of a consequence which will (or which she suspects
may) dispromote some further end which he wants to promote, or promote some
"counter-end" which he wants to dispromote. (1) We may remark that
this kind of problem is not something which only arises after a finitely
non-specific intention has been formed; exactly parallel problems are
frequently, though not invariably, encountered on the way towards a finitely
non-specific intention or desire. This prompts a further comment on Aristotle's
remark that, though wisdom is not identical with cleverness, wisdom does not
exist without cleverness. This dictum covers two distinct truths; first, that
if a man were good at deciding what to do, but terrible at executing it (he
makes a hash of working out train times, he is tactless with customs officials,
he irritates hotel clerks into non-cooperation), one might hesitate to confer
upon him the title 'wise'; at least a modicum of cleverness is required.
Second, and more interestingly, cleverness is liable to be manifested at all
stages of deliberation; every time a snag arises in connection with a tentative
determination of one's will, provided that the snag is not blatantly obvious,
some degree of cleverness is manifested in seeing that, if one does
such-and-such (as one contemplates doing), then there will be the undesirable
result that so-and-so. (2) The boss may now have to determine how 'deep' the
snag is, how radically his plan will have to be altered to surmount it. To lay
things out a bit, the boss might (in some sense of 'might'), in his
deliberation, have formed successively a series of indeterminately non-specific
intentions (I i , I ii , I iii , . . . I n ), where each end p.104 member is a
more specific determination of its predecessor, and I n represents the final
decision which he imparted to the secretary. He now (the idea is) goes back to
this sequence to find the most general (least specific) member which is such
that if he has that intention, then he is saddled with the unwanted
consequences. He then knows where modification is required. Of course, in
practice he may very well not have constructed such a convenient sequence; if
he has not, then he has partially to construct one on receipt of the bad news
from the secretary, to construct one (that is) which is just sufficiently well
filled in to enable him to be confident that a particular element in it is the
most generic intention of those he has, which generates the undesirable
consequence. Having now decided which desire or intention to remove, how does
he decide what to put in its place? How, in effect, does he 'compound' his
surviving end or ends with the new desideratum, the attainment of the end (or
the avoidance of the counter-end) which has been brought to light by the snag?
Now I have to confess that in connection with this kind of problem, I used to entertain
a certain kind of picture. Let us label (for simplicity) initially just two
ends E1 and E2, with degrees of "objective desirability" d 1 and d 2
. For any action a 1 which might realize E1, or E2, there will be a certain
probability p 1 that it will realize E1, a certain probability p 2 that it will
realize E2, and a probability p 12 (a function of p 1 and p 2 ) that it will
realize both. If E1 and E2 are inconsistent (again, for simplicity, let us
suppose they are) p 12 will be zero. We can now, in principle, characterize the
desirability of the action a 1 , relative to each end (E1 and E2), and to each
combination of ends (here just E1 and E2), as a function of the desirability of
the end and the probability that the action a 1 will realize that end, or
combination of ends. If we envisage a range of possible actions, which includes
a 1 together with other actions, we can imagine that each such action has a
certain degree of desirability relative to each end (E1 and (or) E2) and to
their combination. If we suppose that, for each possible action, these
desirabilities can be compounded (perhaps added), then we can suppose that one
particular possible action scored higher (in actiondesirability relative to
these ends) than any alternative possible action; and that this is the action
which wins out; that is, is the action which is, or at least should, end p.105
be performed. (The computation would in fact be more complex than I have
described, once account is taken of the fact that the ends involved are often
not definite (determinate) states of affairs(like becoming President), but are
variable in respect of the degree to which they might be realized (if one's end
is to make a profit from a deal, that profit might be of a varying magnitude);
so one would have to consider not merely the likelihood of a particular
action's realizing the end of making a profit, but also the likelihood of its
realizing that end to this or that degree; and this would considerably
complicate the computational problem.) No doubt most readers are far too
sensible ever to have entertained any picture even remotely resembling the
"Crazy-Bayesy" one I have just described. I was not, of course, so
foolish as to suppose that such a picture represents the manner in which anybody
actually decides what to do, though I did (at one point) consider the
possibility that it might mirror, or reflect, a process actually taking place
in the physiological underpinnings of psychological states (desires and
beliefs), a process in the 'animal spirits', so to speak. I rather thought that
it might represent an ideal, a procedure which is certainly unrealized in fact,
and quite possibly one which is in principle unrealizable in fact, but still
something to which the procedures we actually use might be thought of as
approximations, something for which they are substitutes; with the additional
thought that the closer the approximation the better the procedure. The
inspirational source of such pictures as this seems to me to be the very
pervasive conception of a mechanical model for the operations of the soul;
desires are like forces to which we are subject; and their influence on us, in
combination, is like the vectoring of forces. I am not at all sure that I
regard this as a good model; the strength of its appeal may depend considerably
on the fact that some model is needed, and that, if this one is not chosen, it
is not clear what alternative model is available. If we are not to make use of
any variant of my one-time picture, how are we to give a general representation
of the treatment of conflicting or competing ends? It seems to me that, for
example, the accountant with the injured wife in Boise might, in the first
instance, try to keep everything, to fulfil all relevant ends; he might think
of telephoning Redwood City to see if his firm could postpone for a week the
preparation of their accounts. If this is end p.106 ineffective, then he would
operate on some system of priorities. Looking after his wife plainly takes
precedence over attention to his firm's accounting, and over visiting his
mother. But having settled on measures which provide adequately for his wife's
needs, he then makes whatever adjustments he can to provide for the ends which
have lost the day. What he does not do, as a rule, is to compromise; even with
regard to his previous decision involving the conflict between the claims of
his firm and his mother, substantially he adopted a plan which would satisfy
the claims of the firm, incorporating therein a weekend with mother as a way of
doing what he could for her, having given priority to the claims of the firm.
Such systems of priorities seem to me to have, among their significant
features, the following. (1) They may be quite complex, and involve sub-systems
of priorities within a single main level of priority. It may be that, for me,
family concerns have priority over business concerns; and also that, within the
area of family concerns, matters affecting my children have priority over
matters concerning Aunt Jemima, whs been living with us all these years. (2)
There is a distinction between a standing, relatively long-term system of
priorities, and its application to particular occasions, with what might be
thought of as divergences between the two. Even though my relations with my
children have, in general, priority over my relations with Aunt Jemima, on a
particular occasion I may accord priority to spending time with Aunt Jemima to
get her out of one of her tantrums over taking my son to the zoo to see the
hippopotami. It seems to me that a further important feature of practical
thinking, which plays its part in simplifying the handling of problems with
which such thinking is concerned, is what I might call its 'revisionist'
character (in a non-practical sense of that term). Our desires, and ascriptions
of desirability, may be relative in more than one way. They may be
'desire-relative' in that my desiring A, or my regarding A as desirable, may be
dependent on my desiring, or regarding as desirable, B; the desire for, or the
desirability of, A may be parasitic on a desire for, or the desirability of, B.
This is the familiar case of A's being desired, or desirable for the sake of B.
But desires and desirabilities may be relative in another slightly less banal
way, which end p.107 (initially) one might think of as 'fact-relativity'. They
may be relative to some actual or supposed prevailing situation; and, relative
to such prevailing situations, things may be desired or thought desirablewhich
would not normally be so regarded. A man who has been sentenced to be hanged,
drawn, and quartered may be relieved and even delighted when he hears that the
sentence has been changed to beheading; and a man whose wealth runs into
hundreds of millions may be considerably upset if he loses a million or so on a
particular transaction. Indeed, sometimes, one is led to suspect that the
richer one is, the more one is liable to mind such decrements; witness the
story, no doubt apocryphal, that Paul Getty had pay-telephones installed in his
house for the use of his guests. The phenomenon of 'fact-relativity' seems to
reach at least to some extent into the area of moral desirabilities. It can be
used, I think, to provide a natural way of disposing of the Good Samaritan
paradox; and if one recalls the parable of the Prodigal Son, one may reflect
that what incensed the for so long blameless son was that there should be all
that junketing about a fact-relative desirability manifested by his errant
brother; why should one get a party for that? It perhaps fits in very well with
these reflections that our practical thinking, or a great part of it, should be
revisionist or incremental in character; that what very frequently happens is
that we find something in the prevailing situation (or the situation
anticipated as prevailing) which could do with improvement or remove a blemish.
We do not, normally, set to work to construct a minor Utopia. It is notable
that aversions play a particularly important role in incremental deliberations;
and it is perhaps just that (up to a point) the removal of objects of aversion
should take precedence over the installation of objects of desire. If I have to
do without something which I desire, the desired object is not (unless the
desire is extreme) constantly present in imagination to remind me that I am
doing without it; but if I have to do or have something which I dislike, the
object of aversion is present in reality, and so difficult to escape. This
revisionist kind of thinking seems to me to extend from the loftiest problems
(how to plan my life, which becomes how to improve on the pattern which
prevails) to the smallest (how to arrange the furniture); and it extends also,
at the next move so to speak, to the projected improvements which I entertain
in thought; I seek to improve on them; a master chess-player, end p.108 it is
said, sees at once what would be a good move for him to make; all his thought
is devoted to trying to find a better one. When one looks at the matter a
little more closely, one sees that 'fact-relative' desirability is really desirability
relative to an anticipated, expected, or feared temporal extension of the
actual state of affairs which prevails (an extension which is not necessarily
identical with what prevails, but which will come about unless something is
done about it). And looked at a little more closely still, such desires or
desirabilities are seen to be essentially comparative; what we try for is
thought of as better than the anticipated state which prompts us to try for it.
This raises the large and difficult question, how far is desirability of its
nature comparative? Is it just that the pundits have not yet given us a
non-comparative concept of desirability, or is there something in the nature of
desire, or in the use we want to make of the concept of desirability, which is
a good reason why we cannot have, or should not have, a noncomparative concept?
Or, perhaps, we do have one, which operates only in limited regions? Certainly
we do not have to think in narrowly incremental ways, as is attested by those
who seek to comfort us (or discomfort us) by getting us to count our blessings
(or the reverse); by, for example, pointing out that being beheaded is not
really so hot, or that, if you have 200 million left after a bad deal, you are
not doing so badly. Are such comforters abandoning comparative desirability, or
are they merely shifting the term of comparison? Do we find non-comparative
desirability (perhaps among other regions) in moral regions? If we say that a
man is honest, we are likely to mean that he is at least not less honest than
the average; but we do not expect a man, who wants or tries to be honest, just
to want or try to be averagely honest. Nor do we expect him to aspire to
supreme or perfect honesty (that might be a trifle presumptuous). We do expect,
perhaps, that he try to be as honest as he can, which may mean that we don't
expect him to form aspirations with regard to a lifetime record of any sort for
honesty, but we do expect him to try on each occasion, or limited bunch of
occasions, to be impeccably honest on those occasions, even though we know (and
he knows) that on some occasions at some times there will or may be lapses. If
something like this interpretation be correct, it may correspond to a general
feature of universals (non-propositional ends) of which one cannot have end
p.109 too much, a type of which certain moral universals are specimens;
desirabilities in the case of such universals are, perhaps, not comparative.
But these are unworked-out speculations.To summarize briefly this rambling,
hopefully somewhat diagnostic, and certainly unsystematic discussion. I have
suggested, in a preliminary enquiry into practical acceptability which is other
than technical acceptability: (1) that practical thinking, which is not just
means-end thinking, includes the determination or sharpening of antecedently
indeterminate desires and intentions; (2) that means-end thinking is involved
in the process of such determination; (3) that a certain sort of computational
model may not be suitable; (4) that systems of priorities, both general and
tailored to occasions, are central; (5) that much, though not perhaps all, of
practical thinking is revisionist and comparative in character. I turn now to a
brief consideration of questions (A) and (B) which I distinguished earlier, and
left on one side. These questions are: (A) What is the nature of happiness? (B)
In what sense, and why, should I desire or aim at my own happiness? I shall
take them together. First, question (B) seems to me to divide, on closer
examination, into three further questions. (1) Is there justification for the
supposition that one should, other things being equal, voluntarily continue
one's existence, rather than end it? (2) (Given that the answer to (1) is
'yes'.) Is there justification for the idea that one should desire or seek to
be happy? (3) (Given that the answer to (2) is 'yes'.) Is there a way of
justifying (evaluating favourably) the acceptance of some particular set of
ends (as distinct from all other such sets) as constitutive of happiness (or of
my happiness)? end p.110 The second and third questions, particularly the
third, are closely related to, and likely to be dependent on, the account of
happiness provided in answer to question (A); indeed, such an account might
wholly or partly provide an answer to question (3), since "happiness"
might turn out to be a valueparadigmatic term, the meaning of which dictates
that to be happy is to have a combination of ends which (the combination) is
valuable with respect to some particular purpose or point of view. I shall say
nothing about the first two questions; one or both of these would, I suspect,
require a careful treatment of the idea of Final Causes, which so far I have
not even mentioned. I will discuss the third question and question (A) in the
next chapter. end p.111 5 Some Reflections About Ends and Happiness I The topic
which I have chosen is one which eminently deserves a thorough, systematic, and
fully theoretical treatment; such an approach would involve, I suspect, a
careful analysis of the often subtly different kinds of state which may be
denoted by the word 'want', together with a comprehensive examination of the
role which different sorts of wanting play in the psychological equipment of
rational (and non-rational) creatures. While I hope to touch on matters of this
sort, I do not feel myself to be quite in a position to attempt an analysis of
this kind, which would in any case be a very lengthy undertaking. So, to give
direction to my discussion, and to keep it within tolerable limits, I shall
relate it to some questions arising out of Aristotle's handling of this topic
in the Nicomachean Ethics; such a procedure on my part may have the additional
advantage of emphasizing the idea, in which I believe, that the proper habitat
for such great works of the past as the Nicomachean Ethics is not the museums
but the marketplaces of philosophy. My initial Aristotelian question concerns
two conditions which Aristotle supposes to have to be satisfied by whatever is
to be recognized as being the good for man. At the beginning of Nicomachean
Ethics I. 4, Aristotle notes that there is general agreement that the good for
man is to be identified with eudaemonia (which may or may not be well rendered
as 'happiness'), and that this in turn is to be identified with living well and
with doing well; but remarks that there is large-scale disagreement with
respect to any further and more informative specification of eudaemonia. In I.
7 he seeksend p.112 to confirm the identification of the good for man with
eudaemonia by specifying two features, maximal finality (unqualified finality)
and self-sufficiency, which, supposedly, both are required of anything which is
to qualify as the good for man, and are also satisfied by eudaemonia. 'Maximal
finality' is defined as follows: "Now we call that which is in itself
worthy of pursuit more final than that which is worthy of pursuit for the sake
of something else, and that which is never desirable for the sake of something
else more final than the things which are desirable both in themselves and for
the sake of that other thing, and therefore we call final without qualification
that which is always desirable in itself and never for the sake of something
else." Eudaemonia seems (intuitively) to satisfy this condition; such
things as honour, pleasure, reason, and virtue (the most popular candidates for
identification with the good for man and with eudaemonia) are chosen indeed for
themselves (they would be worthy of choice even if nothing resulted from them);
but they are also chosen for the sake of eudaemonia, since "we judge that
by means of them we shall be happy". Eudaemonia, however, is never chosen
for the sake of anything other than itself. After some preliminaries, the
relevant sense of 'self-sufficiency' is defined thus: "The selfsufficient
we now define as that which when isolated makes life desirable and lacking in
nothing." Eudaemonia, again, appears to satisfy this condition too; and
Aristotle adds the possibly important comment that eudaemonia is thought to be
"the most desirable of all things, without being counted as one good thing
among others". This remark might be taken to suggest that, in Aristotle's
view, it is not merely true that the possession of eudaemonia cannot be
improved upon by the addition of any other good, but it is true because
eudaemonia is a special kind of good, one which it would be inappropriate to
rank alongside other goods. This passage in Nicomachean Ethics raises in my
mindseveral queries: (1) It is, I suspect, normally assumed by commentators
that Aristotle thinks of eudaemonia as being the only item which satisfies the
condition of maximal finality. This uniqueness claim is not, however,
explicitly made in the passage (nor, so far as I can recollect, elsewhere); nor
is it clear to me that if it were made it end p.113 would be correct. Might it
not be that, for example, lazing in the sun is desired, and is desirable, for
its own sake, and yet is not something which is also desirable for the sake of
something else, not even for the sake of happiness? If it should turn out that
there is a distinction, within the class of things desirable for their own sake
(I-desirables), between those which are also desirable for the sake of
eudaemonia (H-desirables) and those which are not, then the further question
arises whether there is any common feature which distinguishes items which are
(directly) H-desirable, and, if so, what it is. This question will reappear
later. (2) Aristotle claims that honour, reason, pleasure, and virtue are all
both I-desirable and Hdesirable. But, at this stage in the Nicomachean Ethics,
these are uneliminated candidates for identification with eudaemonia; and,
indeed, Aristotle himself later identifies, at least in a sort of way, a
special version of one of them (metaphysical contemplation) with eudaemonia.
Suppose that it were to be established that one of these candidates (say,
honour) is successful. Would not Aristotle then be committed to holding that
honour is both desirable for its own sake, and also desirable for the sake of
something other than honour, namely, eudaemonia, that is, honour? It is not
clear, moreover, that this prima facie inconsistency can be eliminated by an
appeal to the non-extensionality of the context "——is desirable". For
while the argument-pattern 'α is desirable for the sake of β, β is identical
with γ; so, α is desirable for the sake of γ' may be invalid, it is by no means
clear that the argument-pattern 'α is desirable for the sake of β, necessarily
β is identical with γ; so, α is desirable for the sake of γ' is invalid. And,
if it were true that eudaemonia is to be identified with honour, this would
presumably be a non-contingent truth. (3) Suppose the following: (a) playing
golf and playing tennis are each I-desirables, (b) each is conducive to
physical fitness, which is itself I-desirable, (c) that a daily round of golf
and a daily couple of hours of tennis are each sufficient for peak physical
fitness, and (if you like, for simplicity), (d) that there is no third route to
physical fitness. Now, X and Y accept all these suppositions; X plays golf
daily, and Y plays both golf and tennis daily. It seems difficult to deny,
first, that it is quite conceivable that allof the sporting activities of these
gentlemen are undertaken both for their own sake and also for the sake of
physical fitness, and, second, that (pro end p.114 tanto) the life of Y is more
desirable than the life of X, since Y has the value of playing tennis while X
does not. The fact that in Y's life physical fitness is overdetermined does not
seem to be a ground for denying that he pursues both golf and tennis for the
sake of physical fitness; if we wished to deny this, it looks as if we could,
in certain circumstances, be faced with the unanswerable question, "If he
doesn't pursue each for the sake of physical fitness, then which one does he
pursue for physical fitness?" Let us now consider how close an analogy to
this example we can construct if we search for one which replaces references to
physical fitness by references to eudaemonia. We might suppose that X and Y
have it in common that they have distinguished academic lives, satisfying
family situations, and are healthy and prosperous; that they value, and rightly
value, these aspects of their existences for their own sakes and also regard
them as contributing to their eudaemonia. Each regards himself as a thoroughly
happy man. But Y, unlike X, also composes poetry, an activity which he cares
about and which he also thinks of as something which contributes to his
eudaemonia; the time which Y devotes to poetic endeavour is spent by X
pottering about the house doing nothing in particular. We now raise the
question whether or not Y's life is more desirable than X's, on the grounds
that it contains an I-desirable element, poetic composition, which X's life
does not contain, and that there is no counterbalancing element present in X's
life but absent in Y's. One conceivable answer would be that Y's life is indeed
more desirable than X's, since it contains an additional value, but that this
fact is consistent with their being equal in respect of eudaemonia, in line
with the supposition that each regards himself as thoroughly happy. If we give
this answer we, in effect, reject the Aristotelian idea that eudaemonia is, in
the appropriate sense, self-sufficient. There seems to me, however, to be good
reason not to give this answer. Commentators have disagreed about the precise
interpretation of the word "eudaemonia", but none, so far as I know,
has suggested what I think of as much the most plausible conjecture; namely,
that "eudaemonia" is to be understood as the name for that state or
condition which one's good daemon would (if he could) ensure for one; and my
good daemon is a being motivated, with respect to me, solely by concern for my
well-being or happiness. end p.115 To change the idiom, "eudaemonia"
is the general characterization of what a full-time and unhampered fairy
godmother would secure for you. The identifications regarded by Aristotle as
unexcitingly correct, of eudaemonia with doing well and with living well, now
begin to look like necessary truths. If this interpretation of
"eudaemonia" is correct (as I shall brazenly assume) then it would be
quite impossible for Y's life to be more desirable than X's, though X and Y are
equal in respect of eudaemonia; for this would amount to Y's being better off
than X, though both are equally well-off. Various other possible answers
remain. It might be held that not only is Y's life more desirable than X's, but
Y is more eudaemon (better off) than X. This idea preserves the proposed
conceptual connection between eudaemonia and being well-off, and relies on the
not wholly implausible principle that the addition of a value to a life
enhances the value of that life (whatever, perhaps, the liver may think). One
might think of such a principle, when more fully stated, as laying down or
implying that any increase in the combined value of the H-desirable elements
realized in a particular life is reflected, in a constant proportion, in an
increase in the degree of happiness or well-being exemplified by that life; or,
more cautiously, that the increase in happiness is not determined by a constant
proportion, but rather in some manner analogous to the phenomenon of
diminishing marginal utility. I am inclined to see the argument of this chapter
as leading towards a discreet erosion of the idea that the degree of a
particular person's happiness is the value of a function the arguments of which
are measures of the particular Hdesirables realized in that person's life, no
matter what function is suggested; but at the present moment it will be
sufficient to cast doubt on the acceptability of any of the crudest versions of
this idea. To revert to the case of X and Y: it seems to me that when we speak
of the desirability of X's life or of Y's life, the desirability of which we
are speaking is the desirability of that life from the point of view of the
person whose life it is; and that it is therefore counterintuitive to suppose
that, for example, X who thinks of himself as "perfectly happy" and
so not to be made either better off or more happy (though perhaps more
accomplished) by an injection of poetry composition, should be making a
misassessment of what his stateof well-being would be if the composition of poetry
were added to his occupation. Furthermore, if the pursuit end p.116 of
happiness is to be the proper end, or even a proper end, of living, to suppose
that the added realization of a further H-desirable to a life automatically
increases the happiness or well-being of the possessor of that life will
involve a commitment to an ethical position which I, for one, find somewhat
unattractive; one would be committed to advocating too unbridled an eudaemonic
expansionism. A more attractive position would be to suppose that we should
invoke, with respect to the example under consideration, an analogue not of
diminishing marginal utility, but of what might be called vanishing marginal
utility; to suppose, that is, that X and Y are, or at least may be, equally well-off
and equally happy even though Y's life contains an H-desirable element which is
lacking in X's life; that at a certain point, so to speak, the bucket of
happiness is filled, and no further inpouring of realized Hdesirables has any
effect on its contents. This position would be analogous to the view I adopted
earlier with respect to the possible overdetermination of physical fitness.
Even should this position be correct, it must be recognized that the really
interesting work still remains to be done; that would consist in the
characterization of the conditions which determine whether the realization of a
particular set of Hdesirables is sufficient to fill the bucket. The main
result, then, of the discussion has been to raise two matters for exploration;
first, the possibility of a distinction between items which are merely
I-desirable and items which are not only Idesirable but also H-desirable; and,
second, the possibility that the degree of happiness exemplified by a life may
be overdetermined by the set of H-desirables realized in that life, together
with the need to characterize the conditions which govern such
overdetermination. (4) Let us move in a different direction. I have already
remarked that, with respect to the desirability-status of happiness and of the
means thereto, Aristotle subscribed to two theses, with which I have no quarrel
(or, at least, shall voice no quarrel). (A) That some things are both
I-desirable and H-desirable (are both ends in themselves and also means to
happiness). (B) That happiness, while desirable in itself, is not desirable for
the sake of any further end. end p.117 I have suggested the possibility that a
further thesis might be true (though I have not claimed that it is true),
namely: (C) That some things are I-desirable without being H-desirable (and,
one might add, perhaps without being desirable for the sake of any further end,
in which case happiness will not be the only item which is not desirable for
the sake of any further end). But there are two further as yet unmentioned
theses which I am inclined to regard as being not only true, but also
important: first, (D) Any item which is directly H-desirable must be
I-desirable. And second, (E) Happiness is attainable only via the realization
of items which are I-desirable (and also of course H-desirable). Thesis (D)
would allow that an item could be indirectly H-desirable without being
I-desirable; engaging in morning press-ups could be such an item, but only if
it were desirable for the sake of (let us say) playing cricket well, which
would plainly be itself an item which was both I-desirable and Hdesirable. A
thesis related to (D), namely, (D′). (An item can be directly conducive to the
happiness of an individual x only if it is regarded by x as being I-desirable)
seems to me very likely to be true; the question whether not only (D′) but (D)
are true would depend on whether a man who misconceives (if that be possible)
certain items as being I-desirable could properly be said to achieve happiness
through the realization of those items. To take an extreme case, could a wicked
man who pervertedly regards cheating others in an ingenious way as being
I-desirable, and who delights in so doing, properly be said to be (pro tanto)
achieving happiness? I think Aristotle would answer negatively, and I am rather
inclined to side with him; but I recognize that there is much to debate. A
consequence of thesis (D), if true, would be that there cannot be a
happiness-pill (a pill the taking of which leads directly tohappiness); there
could be (and maybe there is) a pill which leads directly to "feeling
good" or to euphoria; but these states would have to be distinguishable
from happiness. Thesis (E) would imply that happiness is essentially a
dependent state; happiness cannot just happen; its realization is conditional
end p.118 upon the realization of one or more items which give rise to it.
Happiness should be thought of adverbially; to be happy is, for some x, to x
happily or with happiness. And reflection on the interchangeability or near-interchangeability
of the ideas of happiness and of well-being would suggest that the adverbial in
question is an evaluation adverbial. The importance, for present purposes, of
the two latest theses is to my mind that questions are now engendered about the
idea that items which are chosen (or desirable) for the sake of happiness can
be thought of as items which are chosen (or desirable) as means to happiness,
at least if the means-end relation is conceived as it seems very frequently to
be conceived in contemporary philosophy; if, that is, x is a means to y just in
case the doing or producing of x designedly causes (generates, has as an
effect) the occurrence of y. For, if items the realization of which give rise
to happiness were items which could be, in the above sense, means to happiness,
(a) it should be conceptually possible for happiness to arise otherwise than as
a consequence of the occurrence of any such items, and (b) it seems too
difficult to suppose that so non-scientific a condition as the possession of
intrinsic desirability should be a necessary condition of an item's giving rise
to happiness. In other words, theses (D) and (E) seem to preclude the idea that
what directly gives rise to happiness can be, in the currently favoured sense,
a means to happiness. The issue which I have just raised is closely related to
a scholarly issue which has recently divided Aristotelian commentators; battles
have raged over the question whether Aristotle conceived of eudaemonia as a
'dominant' or as an 'inclusive' end. The terminology derives, I believe, from
W. F. R. Hardie; but I cite a definition of the question which is given by
Ackrill in a recent paper: "By 'an inclusive end' might be meant any end
combining or including two or more values or activities or goods . . . By 'a
dominant end' might be meant a monolithic end, an end consisting of just one
valued activity or good."1 One's initial reaction to this formulation may
fall short of overwhelming enlightenment, among other things, perhaps, because
the verb 'include' appears within end p.119 the characterization of an
inclusive end. I suspect, however, that this deficiency could be properly
remedied only by a logicometaphysical enquiry into the nature of the 'inclusion
relation' (or, rather, the family of inclusion relations), which would go far
beyond the limits of my present undertaking. But, to be less ambitious, let us,
initially and provisionally, think of an inclusive end as being a set of ends.
If happiness is in this sense an inclusive end, then we can account for some of
the features displayed in the previous section. Happiness will be dependent on
the realization of subordinate ends, provided that the set of ends constituting
happiness may not be the empty set (a reasonable, if optimistic, assumption).
Since the "happiness set" has as its elements I-desirables, what is
desirable directly for the sake of happiness must be I-desirable. And if it
should turn out to be the case, contrary perhaps to the direction of my
argument in the last section, that the happiness set includes all I-desirables,
then we should have difficulty in finding any end for the sake of which
happiness would be desirable. So far so good, perhaps; but so far may not
really be very far at all. Some reservation about the treatment of eudaemonia
as an inclusive end is hinted at by Ackrill: It is not necessary to claim that
Aristotle has made quite clear how there may be 'components' in the best life
or how they may be interrelated. The very idea of constructing a compound end
out of two or more independent ends may arouse suspicion. Is the compound to be
thought of as a mere aggregate or as an organized system? If the former, the
move to eudaemonia seems trivial—nor is it obvious that goods can be just added
together. If the latter, if there is supposed to be a unifying plan, what is
it?2 From these very pertinent questions, Ackrill detaches himself, on the
grounds that his primary concern is with the exposition and not with the
justification of Aristotle's thought. But we cannot avail ourselves of this
rain check, and so the difficulties which Ackrill touches on must receive
further exposure.Let us suppose a next-to-impossible world W, in which there
are just three I-desirables, which are also H-desirables, A, B, and C. If you
like, you may think of these as being identical, respectively, with honour,
wealth, and virtue. If, in general, happiness is end p.120 to be an inclusive
end, happiness-in-W will have as its components A, B, and C, and no others. Now
one might be tempted to suppose that, since it is difficult or impossible to
deny that to achieve happiness-in-W it is necessary and also sufficient to
realize A, to realize B, and to realize C, anyone who wanted to realize A,
wanted to realize B, and wanted to realize C would ipso facto be someone who
wanted to achieve happiness-in-W. But there seems to me to be a good case for
regarding such an inference as invalid. To want to achieve happiness-in-W might
be equivalent to wanting to realize A and to realize B and to realize C, or indeed
to wanting A and B and C; but there are relatively familiar reasons for
allowing that, with respect to a considerable range of psychological verbs
(represented by 'ψ'), one cannot derive from a statement of the form 'x ψ's
(that) A and x ψ's (that) B' a statement of the form 'x ψ's (that) A and B'.
For instance, it seems to me a plausible thesis that there are circumstances in
which we should want to say of someone that he believed that p and that he
believed that q, without being willing to allow that he believed that both p
and q. The most obvious cases for the application of the distinction would
perhaps be cases in which p and q are inconsistent; we can perhaps imagine
someone of whom we should wish to say that he believed that he was a
grotesquely incompetent creature, and that he also believed that he was a
world-beater, without wishing to say of him that he believed that he was both
grotesquely incompetent and a world-beater. Inconsistent beliefs are not, or
are not necessarily, beliefs in inconsistencies. Whatever reasons there may be
for allowing that a man may believe that p and believe that q without believing
that p and q would, I suspect, be mirrored in reasons for allowing that a man
may want A and want B without wanting both A and B; if I want a holiday in
Rome, and also want some headache pills, it does not seem to me that ipso facto
I want a holiday in Rome and some headache pills. Moreover, even if we were to
sanction the disputed inference, it would not, I think, be correct to make the
further supposition that a man who wants A and B (simply as a consequence of
wanting A and wanting B) would, or even could, want A (or want B) for the sake
of, or with a view to, realizing A and B. So even if, in world W, a man could
be said to want A and B and C, on the strength of wanting each one of them,
some further condition would end p.121 have to be fulfilled before we could say
of him that he wanted each of them for the sake of realizing A and B and C,
that is, for the sake of achieving happiness-in-W. In an attempt to do justice
to the idea that happiness should be treated as being an 'inclusive' end, let
me put forward a modest proposal; not, perhaps, the only possible proposal, but
one which may seem reasonably intuitive. Let us categorize, for present
purposes, the I-desirables in world W as 'universals'. I propose that to want,
severally, each of these I-desirables should be regarded as equivalent to
wanting the set whose members are just those I-desirables, with the
understanding that a set of universals is not itself a universal. So to want A,
want B, and want C is equivalent to wanting the set whose members are A, B, and
C ('the happinessin-W set'). To want happiness-in-W requires satisfaction of
the stronger condition of wanting A and B and C, which in turn is equivalent to
wanting something which is a universal, namely, a compound universal in which
are included just those universals which are elements of the happiness-inW set.
I shall not attempt to present a necessary and sufficient condition for the
fulfilment of the stronger rather than merely of the weaker condition; but I
shall suggest an important sufficient condition for this state of affairs. The
condition is the following: for x to want the conjunction of the members of a
set, rather than merely for him to want, severally, each member of the set, it
is sufficient that his wanting, severally, each member of the set should be
explained by (have as one of its explanations) the fact that there is an 'open'
feature F which is believed by x to be exemplified by the set, and the
realization of which is desired by x. By an open feature I mean a feature the
specification of which does not require the complete enumeration of the items
which exemplify it. To illustrate, a certain Oxford don at one time desired to
secure for himself the teaching, in his subject, at the colleges of Somerville,
St Hugh's, St Hilda's, Lady Margaret Hall, and St Anne's. (He failed, by two
colleges.) This compound desire was based on the fact that the named colleges
constituted the totality of women's colleges in Oxford, and he desired the
realization of the open feature consisting in his teaching, in his subject, at
all the women's colleges in Oxford. This sufficient condition is important in that it
is, I think, fulfilled with respect to all compound desires which are rational,
as distinct from end p.122 arbitrary or crazy. There can be, of course,
genuinely compound desires which are non-rational, and I shall not attempt to
specify the condition which distinguishes them; but perhaps I do not need to,
since I think we may take it as a postulate that, if a desire for happiness is
a compound desire, it is a rational compound desire. The proposal which I have
made does, I think, conform to acceptable general principles for metaphysical
construction. For it provides for the addition to an initially given category
of items ('universals') of a special sub-category ('compound universals') which
are counterparts of certain items which are not universals but rather sets of
universals. It involves, so to speak, the conversion of certain non-universals
into 'new' universals, and it seems reasonable to suppose that the purpose of
this conversion is to bring these non-universals, in a simple and relatively
elegant way, within the scope of laws which apply to universals. It must be
understood that by 'laws' I am referring to theoretical generalities which
belong to any of a variety of kinds of theory, including psychological,
practical, and moral theories; so among such laws will be laws of various kinds
relating to desires for ends and for means to ends. If happiness is an
inclusive end, and if, for it to be an inclusive end the desire for which is
rational, there must be an open feature which is exemplified by the set of
components of happiness, our next task is plainly to attempt to identify this
feature. To further this venture I shall now examine, within the varieties of
means-end relation, what is to my mind a particularly suggestive kind of case.
II At the start of this section I shall offer a brief sketch of the varieties,
or of some of the varieties, of means-end relation; this is a matter which is
interesting in itself, which is largely neglected in contemporary philosophy,
and which I am inclined to regard as an important bit of background in the
present enquiry. I shall then consider a particular class of cases in our
ordinary thinking about means and ends, which might be called cases of
'end-fixing', and which might provide an important modification to our
consideration of the idea that happiness is an inclusive end. end p.123 I shall
introduce the term 'is contributive to' as a general expression for what I have
been calling 'means-end' relation, and I shall use the phrase 'is contributive
in way w to' to refer, in a general way, to this or that particular specific
form of the contributiveness relation. I shall, for convenience, assume that
anyone who thinks of some state of affairs or action as being contributive to
the realization of a certain universal would have in mind that specific form of
contributiveness which would be appropriate to the particular case. We may now
say, quite unstartlingly, that x wants to do A for the sake of B just in case x
wants to do A because (1) x regards his doing A as something which would be
contributive in way w to the realization of B, and (2) x wants B. That leaves
us the only interesting task, namely, that of giving the range of specific
relations one element in which will be picked out by the phrase 'contributive
in way w', once A and B are specified. The most obvious mode of
contributiveness, indeed one which has too often been attended to to the
exclusion of all others, is that of causal antecedence; x's contributing to y
here consists in x's being the (or a) causal origin of y. But even within this
mode there may be more complexity than meets the eye. The causal origin may be
an initiating cause, which triggers the effect in the way in which flipping a
switch sets off illumination in a light bulb; or it may be a sustaining cause,
the continuation of which is required in order to maintain the effect in being.
In either case, the effect may be either positive or negative; I may initiate a
period of non-talking in Jones by knocking him cold, or sustain one by keeping
my hand over his mouth. A further dimension, in respect of which examples of
each variety of causal contributiveness may vary, is that of conditionality.
Doing A may be desired as something which will, given the circumstances which
obtain, unconditionally originate the realization of B, or as something which
will do so provided that a certain possibility is fulfilled. A specially
important subclass of cases of conditional causal contributiveness is the class
of cases in which the relevant possibility consists in the desire or will of some
agent, either the means-taker or someone else, that B should be realized; these
arecases in which x wants to do A in order to enable, or to make it possible
for, himself (or someone else) to achieve the realization of B; as when, for
example, x puts a corkscrew in his pocket to enable him later, should be wish
to do so, to open a bottle of wine. end p.124 But, for present purposes, the
more interesting modes of contributiveness may well be those other than that of
causal contributiveness. These include the following types. (1) Specificatory
contributiveness. To do A would, in the prevailing circumstances, be a
specification of, or a way of, realizing B; it being understood that, for this
mode of contributiveness, B is not to be a causal property, a property
consisting in being such as to cause the realization of C, where C is some
further property. A host's seating someone at his right-hand side at dinner may
be a specification of treating him with respect; waving a Union Jack might be a
way of showing loyalty to the Crown. In these cases, the particular action
which exemplifies A is the same as the item which exemplifies B. Two further
modes involve relations of inclusion, of one or another of the types to which
such relations may belong. (2) To do A may contribute to the realization of B
by including an item which realizes B. I may want to take a certain advertised
cruise because it includes a visit to Naples. (3) To do A may contribute to the
realization of B by being included in an item which realizes B. Here we may
distinguish more than one kind of case. A and B may be identical; I may, for
example, be hospitable to someone today because I want to be hospitable to him
throughout his visit to my town. In such a case the exemplification of B
(hospitality) by the whole (my behaviour to him during the week) will depend on
a certain distribution of exemplifications of B among the parts, such as my
behaviour on particular days. We might call this kind of dependence
"componentdependence". In other cases A and B are distinct, and in
some of these (perhaps all) B cannot, if it is exemplified by the whole, also
be exemplified by any part. These further cases subdivide in ways which are
interesting but not germane to the present enquiry. We are now in a position to
handle, not quite as Aristotle did, a 'paradox' about happiness raised by
Aristotle, which involves Solon's dictum "Call no man happy till he is
dead". I give a simplified, but I hope not distorted, version of the
'paradoxical' line of argument. If we start by suggesting that happiness is the
end for man, we shall have to modify this suggestion, replacing
"happiness" by "happiness in a complete life". (Aristotle
himself end p.125 applies the qualification "in a complete life" not
to happiness, but to what he gives as constituted of happiness, namely,
activity of soul in accordance with excellence). For, plainly, a life which as
a whole exemplifies happiness is preferable to one which does not. But since
lifelong happiness can only be exemplified by a whole life, non-predictive
knowledge that the end for man is realized with respect to a particular person
is attainable only at the end of the person's life, and so not (except possibly
at the time of his dying gasp) by the person himself. But this is paradoxical,
since the end for man should be such that non-predictive knowledge of its
realization is available to those who achieve its realization. I suggest that
we need to distinguish non-propositional, attributive ends, such as happiness,
and propositional ends or objectives, such as that my life, as a whole, should
be happy. Now it is not in fact clear that people do, or even should, desire
lifelong happiness; it may be quite in order not to think about this as an
objective. And, even if one should desire lifelong happiness, it is not clear
that one should aim at it, that one should desire, and do, things for the sake
of it. But let us waive these objections. The attainment of lifelong happiness,
an objective, consists in the realization, in a whole life, of the attributive
end happiness. This realization is component-dependent; it depends on a certain
distribution of realizations of that same end in episodes or phases of that
life. But these realizations are certainly nonpredictively knowable by the
person whose life it is. So, if we insist that to specify the end for man is to
specify an attributive end and not an objective, then the 'paradox' disappears.
The special class of cases to which one might be tempted to apply the term
'end-fixing' may be approached in the following way. For any given mode of
contributiveness, say causal contributiveness, the same final position, that x
wants (intends, does) A as contributive to the realization of B, may be reached
through more than one process of thought. In line with the canonical
Aristotelian model, x maydesire to realize B, then enquire what would lead to
B, decide that doing A would lead to B, and so come to want, and to do, A.
Alternatively, the possibility of doing A may come to his mind, he then
enquires what doing A would lead to, sees that it would lead to B, which he
wants, and so he comes to want, and perhaps do, A. I now ask whether there are
cases in which the following end p.126 conditions are met: (1) doing A is fixed
or decided, not merely entertained as a possibility, in advance of the
recognition of it as desirable with a view to B, and (2) that B is selected as
an end, or as an end to be pursued on this occasion, at least partly because it
is something which doing A will help to realize. A variety of candidates, not
necessarily good ones, come to mind. (1) A man who is wrecked on a desert
island decides to use his stay there to pursue what is a new end for him,
namely, the study of the local flora and fauna. Here doing A (spending time on
the island) is fixed but not chosen; and the specific performances, which some
might think were more properly regarded as means to the pursuit of this study,
are not fixed in advance of the adoption of the end. (2) A man wants (without
having a reason for so wanting) to move to a certain town; he is uncomfortable
with irrational desires (or at least with this irrational desire), and so comes
to want to make this move because the town has a specially salubrious climate.
Here, it seems, the movement of thought cannot be fully conscious; we might say
that the reason why he wants to move to a specially good climate is that such a
desire would justify the desire or intention, which he already has, to move to
the town in question; but one would baulk at describing this as being his reason
for wanting to move to a good climate. The example which interests me is the
following. A tyrant has become severely displeased with one of his ministers,
and to humiliate him assigns him to the task of organizing the disposal of the
palace garbage, making clear that only a high degree of efficiency will save
him from a more savage fate. The minister at first strives for efficiency
merely in order to escape disaster; but later, seeing that thereby he can
preserve his self-respect and frustrate the tyrant's plan to humiliate him, he
begins to take pride in the efficient discharge of his duties, and so to be
concerned about it for its own sake. Even so, when the tyrant is overthrown and
the minister is relieved of his menial duties, he leaves them without regret in
spite of having been intrinsically concerned about their discharge. One might
say of the minister that he efficiently discharged his office for its own sake
in order to frustrate the tyrant; and this is clearly inadequately represented
as his being interested in the efficient discharge of his office both for its
own sake and for the end p.127 sake of frustrating the tyrant, since he hoped
to achieve the latter goal by an intrinsic concern with his office. It seems
clear that higher-order desires are involved; the minister wants, for its own
sake, to discharge his office efficiently, and he wants to want this because he
wants, by so wanting, to frustrate the tyrant. Indeed, wanting to do A for the
sake of B can plausibly be represented as having two interpretations. The first
interpretation is invoked if we say that a man who does A for the sake of B (1)
does A because he wants to do A and (2) wants to do A for the sake of B. Here
wanting A for the sake of B involves thinking that A will lead to B. But we can
conceive of wanting A for the sake of B (analogously with doing A for the sake
of B) as something which is accounted for by wanting to want A for the sake of
B; if so, we have the second interpretation, one which implies not thinking
that A will help to realize B, but rather thinking that wanting A will help to
realize B. The impact of this discussion, on the question of the kind of end
which happiness should be taken to be, will be that, if happiness is to be
regarded as an inclusive end, the components may be not the realizations of
certain ends, but rather the desires for those realizations. Wanting A for the
sake of happiness should be given the second mode of interpretation specified
above, one which involves thinking that wanting A is one of a set of items
which collectively exhibit the open feature associated with happiness. III My
enquiry has, I hope, so far given some grounds for the favourable consideration
of three theses: (1) happiness is an end for the sake of which certain I-desirables
are desirable, but is to beregarded as an inclusive rather than a dominant end;
(2) for happiness to be a rational inclusive end, the set of its components
must exemplify some particular open feature, yet to be determined; and (3) the
components of happiness may well be not universals or states of affairs the
realization of which is desired for its own sake, end p.128 but rather the
desires for such universals or states of affairs, in which case a desire for
happiness will be a higher-order desire, a desire to have, and satisfy, a set
of desires which exemplifies the relevant open feature. At this point, we might
be faced with a radical assault, which would run as follows. "Your whole
line of enquiry consists in assuming that, when some item is desired, or
desirable, for the sake of happiness, it is desired, or desirable, as a means
to happiness, and in then raising, as the crucial question, what kind of an end
happiness is, or what kind of means-end relation is involved. But the initial
assumption is a mistake. To say of an item that it is desired for the sake of
happiness should not be understood as implying that that item is desired as any
kind of a means to anything. It should be understood rather as claiming that
the item is desired (for its own sake) in a certain sort of way: 'for the sake
of happiness' should be treated as a unitary adverbial, better heard, perhaps,
as 'happinesswise'. To desire something happiness-wise is to take the desire
for it seriously in a certain sort of way, in particular to take the desire
seriously as a guide for living, to have incorporated it in one's overall plan
or system for the conduct of life. If one looks at the matter this way, one can
see at once that it is conceivable that these should be I-desirables which are
not H-desirables; for the question whether something which is desirable is
intrinsically desirable, or whether its desirability derives from the
desirability of something else, is plainly a different question from the
question whether or not the desire for it is to be taken seriously in the
planning and direction of one's life, that is, whether the item is H-desirable.
One can, moreover, do justice to two further considerations which you have, so
far, been ignoring: first, that what goes to make up happiness is relative to
the individual whose happiness it is, a truth which is easily seen when it is
recognized that what x desires (or should desire) happiness-wise may be quite
different from what y so desires; and, second, that intuition is sympathetic to
the admittedly vague idea that the decision that certain items are constitutive
of one's happiness is not so much a matter of judgement or belief as a matter
of will. One's happiness consists in what one makes it consist in, an idea
which will be easily accommodated if 'for the sake of happiness' is understood
in the way which I propose." end p.129 There is much in this (spirited yet
thoughtful) oration towards which I am sympathetic and which I am prepared to
regard as important; in particular, the idea of linking H-desirability with
desires or concerns which enter into a system for the direction of one's life,
and the suggestion that the acceptance of a system of ends as constituting
happiness, or one's own happiness, is less a matter of belief or judgement than
of will. But, despite these attractive features, and despite its air of
simplifying iconoclasm, the position which is propounded can hardly be regarded
as tenable. When looked at more closely, it can be seen to be just another form
of subjectivism: what are ostensibly beliefs that particular items are
conducive to happiness are represented as being in fact psychological states or
attitudes, other than beliefs, with regard to these items; and it is vulnerable
to variants of stock objections to subjectivist manœuvres. That in common
speech and thought we have application for, and so need a philosophical account
of, not only the idea of desiring things for the sake of happiness but, also,
that of being happy (or well-off), is passed over; and should it turn out that
the position under consideration has no account to offer of the latter idea,
that would be not only paradoxical but also, quite likely, theoretically
disastrous. For it would seem to be the case that the construction or adoption
of a system of ends for the direction of life is something which can be done
well or badly, or better or less well; that being so, there will be a demand
for the specification of the criteria governing this area of evaluation; and it
will be difficult to avoid the idea that the conditions characteristic of a
good system of ends will be determined by the fact that the adoption of a
system conforming to those conditions will lead, or is likely to lead, or other
things being equal will lead, to the realization of happiness; to something,
that is, which the approach under consideration might well not be able to
accommodate. So it begins to look as if we may be back where we were before the
start of this latest discussion. But perhaps not quite; for, perhaps, something
can be done with the notion of a set or system of endswhich is suitable for the
direction of life. The leading idea would be of a system which is maximally
stable, one whose employment for the direction of life would be maximally
conducive end p.130 to its continued employment for that purpose, which would
be maximally self-perpetuating. To put the matter another way, a system of ends
would be stable to the extent to which, though not constitutionally immune from
modification, it could accommodate changes of circumstances or vicissitudes
which would impose modification upon other less stable systems. We might need
to supplement the idea of stability by the idea of flexibility; a system will
be flexible in so far as, should modifications be demanded, they are achievable
by easy adjustment and evolution; flounderings, crises, and revolutions will be
excluded or at a minimum. A succession of systems of ends within a person's
consciousness could then be regarded as stages in the development of a single
life-scheme, rather than as the replacement of one life-scheme by another. We
might find it desirable also to incorporate into the working-out of these ideas
a distinction, already foreshadowed, between happiness-in-general and
happiness-for-an-individual. We might hope that it would be possible to present
happiness-in-general as a system of possible ends which would be specified in
highly general terms (since the specification must be arrived at in abstraction
from the idiosyncrasies of particular persons and their circumstances), a
system which would be determined either by its stability relative to stock
vicissitudes in the human condition, or (as I suspect) in some other way; and
we might further hope that happiness for an individual might lie in the
possession, and operation for the guidance of life, of a system of ends which
(a) would be a specific and personalized derivative, determined by that
individual's character, abilities, and situations in the world, of the system
constitutive of happiness in general; and (b) the adoption of which would be
stable for that individual in his circumstances. The idea that happiness might
be fully, or at least partially, characterized in something like this kind of
way would receive some support if we could show reason to suppose that features
which could plausibly be regarded, or which indeed actually have been regarded,
as characteristic of happiness, or at least of a satisfactory system for the
guidance of life, are also features which are conducive to stability. Refs.: H.
P. Grice, “Means-end rationality.”
No comments:
Post a Comment